SYSTEMS OF STATES
SYSTEMS OF STATES
Martin Wight Edited with an introduction hy Hedley Bull
LEICESTER UNIVERSITY PRE...
72 downloads
943 Views
9MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
SYSTEMS OF STATES
SYSTEMS OF STATES
Martin Wight Edited with an introduction hy Hedley Bull
LEICESTER UNIVERSITY PRESS IN ASSOCIATION WITH THE LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL SCIENCE
1977
First published in 1977 by Leicester University Press Distributed in North America by Humanities Press Inc., New Jersey Copyright
© Gabriele Ingaborg Wight and Leonard Keith Purkiss 1977
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the Leicester University Press. Designed by Douglas Martin Set in Linotype Granjon Printed in Great Britain by Western Printing Services Ltd, Bristol Bound by Remploy Ltd, Swansea ISBN 0
7185 1153
0
CONTENTS
Introduction: Martin Wight and the srudy of international relations, by Hedley Bull
I
I
De systematibus civitatum
2I
2
The states-system of Hellas
46
3
Hellas and Persia
73
4
The origins of our states-system :
5
geographical limits
IIO
The origins of our states-system: chronological limits
I29
6
International legitimacy
I 53
7
Triangles and duels
I74
Martin Wight: publications
20I
Notes
203
Index
223
Introduction: Martin Wight and the study of international relations
1 The papers collected in this volume, all of which relate to the theme of systems of states, were written by Martin Wight in the last eight years of his life for meetings of the British Committee on the Theory
of International Politics. Apart from the paper on 'International Legitimacy ', which appeared in slightly different form in the May
1972 issue of International Relations, and is reprinted here by kind permission of the editor, they have not previously been published. The British Committee on the Theory of International Politics has met
regularly since 1958 with the generous support of the Rocke
feller Foundation. At the time of his death in July 1972 Martin Wight was Convenor of the Committee, having succeeded Sir
Herbert Butterfield in this role after the latter's retirement in 1967 from the Mastership of Peterhouse. When these papers were written the other members of the Committe� were Sir Herbert Butterfield,
Adam Watson, the late Geoffrey Hudson, the late Donald Mac Lachlan, Michael Howard, Coral Bell, Desmond Williams, Donald MacKinnon, Robert Wade-Gery, Maurice Keens-Soper and the editor of this volume. While they have no common view of the Theory of International Politics, their general approach to it is illustrated in Diplomatic Investigations, a sample of the papers written for the Committee, edited by Herbert Butterfield and Martin Wight, and published by Allen and Unwin in 1966. As the editors of that volume note in their Introduction, the Committee - by contrast with students of the Theory of International Politics in the United States of America - 'have probably been more concerned with the historical than the contemporary, with the normative than the scientific, with the philosophical than the methodological, with principles than policy' .1 The present papers represent Martin Wight's contribution to a collective exploration, by members of the
Systems of States Committee, of the concept of states-systems, the workings of the modern or Western states-system and of other historical states-systems.
2 Martin Wight was born in I9 I3, the son of a Brighton doctor, and educated at Bradfield and Hertford College, Oxford, where he took a first in Modern History in 1935 (Herbert Butterfield being one of his examiners). After a year in research at Oxford he joined the staff of the Royal Institute of International Aff airs, Chatham House, with which he had a lifelong association. He stayed at Chatham House from I936 until 1938, returned to it after the war from I 946 until I949, and was a member of the Council for the 20 years from 1952 until his death. His early period at Chatham House brought him into close contact with Arnold Toynbee, with whom he worked both on successive volumes of the Institute's Survey of International Affairs and on A Study of History, to Volume VII of which he contributed comments and notes.2 The young Martin Wight was profoundly influenced by Toynbee, and while he cannot be considered a disciple of the latter (his disagreement with his mentor on both historical and theological issues is evident in the notes to A Study of History,
and deepened with the passing of the years), he shared Toynbee,s
commitment to the study of universal history and his interests in the relationship of secular history and sacred history or divine provi dence. This commitment placed Wight, as it placed Toynbee, outside the mainstream of professional, academic historiography, even though he both taught and wrote history of a quite secular or technical kind. From 1938 to 1941 Wight was a schoolmaster at Haileybury, where the range and power of his mind, brought to bear both on historical questions and on the issues of the day, made a deep impression on his colleagues and pupils. One of his former pupils writes as follows: Martin came to Haileybury in succession to J. Hampden Jackson, who had followed C. E. Carrington. There was, therefore, a strong tradition on the history side and the subject attracted the
Introduction
3
more intellectually inclined boy.Martin moved into this situation without teaching experience .and at once established a reputation as a remarkable and brilliant teacher. His skills lay in a combina tion of a first rate intellect with a complete commitment to things of the mind. To be his pupil meant something much more than attending his classes. He expected, and got, from the small group who made up the History Vlth, working for Oxford and Cam bridge scholarships, an attention to history not merely as know ledge of the past but as a way of life in which all things were to be seen as having a moral content, all decisions as moral decisions. He was intensely serious minded, though with no solemnity and with a highly developed sense of the human and the ridiculous .... Martin . saw history as prophetic drama, 'philosophy teaching by examples,' and he taught it against a conceptual background
'
which was strongly T oynbeean.... This involved his pupils in elaborate and, I think, often preten tious debate on internal and external proletariats, on ' routs' and rallies' of civilisations, on yin' and 'yang' and on where we had •
•
then arrived in the great scheme of things.I am not now sure of its value as history but as intellectual stimulus it was immensely powerful.•
Martin Wight was at this time a Christian pacifist. His contem poraries at Oxford remember him as a passionate supporter of the League of Nations, much as it was later interpreted in Viscount Cecil's A Great Experiment; the Abyssinian crisis, which for Martin Wight was the formative international experience (as for later generations of students the Suez crisis or the Vietnam War was such an experience) brought disillusion with the League and a turn to pacifism, which he proclaimed in severe and uncompromising terms in an article in Theology in July 1936. In that year he got to know Dick Sheppard, the former Vicar of StMartin's in the Fields and Dean of Canterbury who at that time was residential Canon of St Paul's Cathedral, and was a founder of the Peace Pledge Union and the best-known spokesman for pacifism in England. Wight was strongly influenced by Sheppard, and for a period managed a pacifist bookshop for him on Ludgate Hill. The pacifism which the young Martin Wight expounded in the article in Theology was based upon the doctrine that it was contrary
4
Systems of States
to Christ's teaching to take hU:man life - whether in war, capital punishment, abortion or euthanasia. He did not advocate quietism or withdrawal, but saw pacifism as a long-range policy that would not triumph until one nation, at least, had offered itself as a sacrifice in the cause of peace.• His pacifism, however, was more doctrinal rather than practical: it derived less from the belief that pacifism would pro
vide a viable technique for achieving results in this world than from the conviction that Christian principles allowed him no alternative.
The approach and outbreak of the Second World War brought him great moral anguish, not only because he felt the force of the argument that the struggle against Nazi Germany was a just one, but also because he had difficulty in convincing himself that he was wor thy to undertake what he saw as the high responsibility of being a pacifist. The application he lodged with the local tribunal on I 1 May I940 gave the following as the reasons that led him finally to declare himself a conscientious objector: I. That the War is the convulsion of a civilization that has forsaken its Christian origins, and become increasingly enslaved to secularism and materialism. It is a divine judgment upon Euro pean civilization for the corporate Sin (in which all share without distinction of religion or nation) which is the cause of the War: a judgment which is the consequence and punishment of past sin, itself taking the form of a more violent abandonment thereto. 2. That the method of the War can do nothing towards solving this fundamental problem of spiritual apostasy: it is one of the worst symptoms of that apostasy, and is utterly opposed to the Kingdom of God as shown in the life of Christ. The only method that can finally overcome the irrational and demonic forces of evil that have their fullest expression in Nazi Germany, is that of Calvary and the catacombs. 3· That the Christian who believes this, cannot avoid a refusal to take part in war, and must seek by other means to prepare the foundations of a new civilization that will be less in conflict with the Kingdom of God. While he felt that he as a Christian could not fight, the young Martin Wight had no illusions that pacifism could bring about the defeat of Hider, nor was he in any doubt as to which side he wanted to win. Nor did he hold that those Christians who chose to fight, in
Introduction
5
(he belief that the war was the struggle of sinful but free men against
. dae Prince of Darkness, were doing wrong. He followed the course of
the· war eagerly, and was a great admirer of Churchill; those who lis aened to Churchill's great radio speeches with Wight (who always had
the capacity
to make those with him feel in the presence of history)
ranember it as a powerful experience. As Wight grew older his
pacifism appears
to have dropped away; those who met him in later
·f H e found no inkling of it in his views, and learnt only with surprise .that this had been part of his background. What did, perhaps,
remain permanent in his outlook on the world was the combination ·of a stark! y realistic perception of the nature of international politics and a sense of personal moral revulsion from it. In I 94 I Wight returned to Oxford to join the distinguished team
.working under Margery Perham on colonial constitutions, and :remained there until 1 9 46. The fruits of this wartime work at Oxford were his three books on colonial questions:
·ment of the Legislative Council 16o6-1945
The D�v�lop
(Faber and Faber,
1946), The Gold Coast Legislative Council (Faber and Faber, 194 7), and British Colonial Constitutions 1947 (Oxford at the Clarendon Press, 1 95 2). It was this experience also which led later to his co authoring (with W. Arthur Lewis, Michael Scott, and Colin Legum)
of Attitude to Africa (Penguin, 19 5 1), a popular work calling on Britain to adjust to the tide of nationalism in the African colonies. His work in the colonial field, however, while it was his most substantial contribution to technical or professional history, and
contributed
to
his moving away from the Toynbeean conceptual
framework of his early years, was not of his own choice, and does not express his central intdlectual and moral concerns. These concerns did find partial expression in
Power Politics ,
published by Chatham House in 1946. This slender pamphlet, now 'for many years out of print (dog-eared copies of it, annotated by successive generations of students, are to be found in libraries wher ever International Relations are studied), established him as a thinker and scholar of great distinction, and is still his best-known work. His second period at Chatham House, interrupted by a spell as the
Observer's
United Nations correspondent covering the sessions at
Lake Success in
1 946- 7,
Charles Manning, of
an
led to his acceptance, at the urging of
invitation to join the Department of Inter
national Relations at the London School of Economics.
6
Systems of States
At the L.S.E. Martin Wight, while he enjoyed many wann friendships and commanded immense authority, verging on rever ence, among colleagues and students alike, was a somewhat aloof figure. Intellectually, his commitment to history, and more especially to the search for pattern or design in the grand sweep of universal history, tended to isolate him in a department which was concerned, in Manning's view, however tentatively, with the development of International Relations as a social science. Viewing education, as he did, as a process of being initiated into a great intellectual tradition, Wight saw the study of the present - the main concern of those around him- as an impoverishment of the mind. He was not, of course, uninterested in the present, but on the contrary devoted much of his own life to the study of it; he did, however, always see contemporary events against the background panorama of universal history. Fortified by his complete commitment to intellectual values and intellectual endeavour he was always reluctant to be drawn into the world of journalistic comment on current affairs and knowing pronouncements as to how they should be conducted, which beckoned him often enough. Wight at first lectured ·on International Institutions, which is usually taken to connote chiefly the League of Nations and the United Nations. Characteristically, he began with the Conciliar
Movement of 1409-49, and after dealing with seventeenth- and
eighteenth-century ideas of perpetual peace, presented the Congress System and the United Nations as the embodiment of the political ideas of Hobbes and the League as embodying the ideas of Locke. The subject, however, did not greatly interest him, and his mature assessment of International Institutions was stated in a seminar paper with this title, in which he argued that the League and the United Nations were merely pseudo-institutions; that the real in stitutions of international society were alliances, diplomacy and war; and that these were the institutions with which he proposed to deal. He later developed a course of lectures on what he called Inter national Theory and it was this subject which, more than any other, he made his own.a He saw it not as the attempt to develop a 'general theory, of International Relations that would serve to explain the present and predict the future - the enterprise that was then getting under way in universities in the United States - but rather as an account of the main traditions of thought about International Rela-
Introduction
7
tions in the past. These traditions he saw as three - the Realist, ·
Rationalist and Revolutionist traditions (alternatively, Machiavellian, Grotian, and Kantian) - and it was in terms of the perennial debate among successive representatives of these traditions that he presented the great issues, intellectual and moral, of world politics to a 1pellbound student audience. Some of the material from these lectures later found its way into his single most important paper, �Western Values in International Relations ', which was published in Diplomatic lnv�stigations in 1 966. : Wight remained at the L.S.E. from 1 949 unti1 1 96 1, spending one year teaching, at Hans Morgenthau's invitation, at the University of Chicago. When in 196 1 he went to the new University of Sussex as Professor of History and Dean of the School of European Studies 10me of his colleagues in London were surpri�d, but he was greatly excited by Lord Fulton's invitation to p�rticipate in the planning of a new university. Through the European Studies course he helped to devise at Sussex he sought ' to satisfy the educational needs of students as persons, to enable them to make sense of their lives, and to find a creative order in the knowledge they acquired and in their own experience. '8 The School of European Studies at Sussex was the first of its kind in a British university. From the stan Wight committed it firmly to the study of European civilization from the time of the Greeks onwards, and he became closely involved with its characteristic Courses on ' the European Tradition ' and ' the Modern European Mind '. He regularly gave tutorials himself in courses on Ancient History, on Dante, on Burckhardt, on various problems and periods in modern European history, and in his own field of International Relations. He was keenly alert to the needs, the talents, and the commitments of his younger colleagues, and in a system in which particular care was taken over the progress of individual students, he was unsurpassed in the combination of firmness and compassion he provided, and not only to those in particular difficulties. He was sometimes sceptical of some of the enthusiasms of a new university, and he could be openly hostile to anything he regarded as a lapse in integrity. But he had his own enthusiasms - Religious Studies, the History of Art, the University Library, and the 'Year Abroad ' for the students in his School - and he used to say that he enjoyed nothing more at Sussex than to participate in the meeting of deans
8
Systems of States
when imagination - more usually other people's than his own - had to be tied to practicalities. Wight 's own contributions were all the more resonant for their peculiar mix of restraint with a sense of purpose. These were at once happy and academically creative years. His School won the allegiance of large numbers of able students ; and once he had become persuaded that it should pay more attention to contemporary Europe than he had originally planned, its range was immense (it even included Russian Studies, both Orthodox and Communist). But given the breadth of his own mind, it remained a coherent whole, and many of his younger professorial colleagues testify to the singular influence that his profound and single-minded devotion to his School, and to the intellectual and educational en deavour it involved, h�d upon both their own thinking and upon the University more widely . During his I I years at Sussex much of his energy was taken up by academic planning and administration, not only for the University of Sussex but also for the University of Kent, of whose Academic Planning Board he was a member. But his research and writing continued to be directed towards International Theory, to which he still hoped to make a major contribution, and indeed it was during his period at Sussex that the papers collected in the present volume were written. Both at the L.S.E. and at Sussex Wight displayed a great gift for teaching simply person to person, and it was through the tutorial system that he most influenced his students, with many of whom he formed lasting friendships and corresponded in later life. While he was fundamentally a serious person, and his view of the world could be said to be stern and even severe, this was balanced by his humour and wit, including his ability to poke fun at himself : with a turn of phrase he could bring a discussion that had become too abstract or too heated down to earth, bringing relief and laughter.
3 The view of International Relations which Martin Wight pre sented in Power Politics was, in a loose sense, a ' realist ' one. This
Introduction
9
.,... not a term which he ever 'used to describe his own position, and it would be a mistake to confuse that position with others to which 1he· term is sometimes applied. He did not, of course, contend that all international politics was· about power or force: the term 'Power Politics' for him signified not Machtpolitik but simply the politics of Powers or states in their external aspect, and while he based his aposition on Stubbs' view that what distinguishes modern history
from medieval is the predominance of the idea of power over the idea Df right, he recognized that statesmen are moved by considerations of right, law, and justice.7 His was not the polemical or iconoclastic
tzealism, (developed in opposition to 'utopianism') of E. H. Carr's The Twenty Years' Crisis (19 3 9)- a book, however, which greatly influenced him. Nor did he seek to present a systematic theory of 1he goals of all states, such as Hans J. Morgenthau put forward in
Politics Among Nations (1 948).
Nor yet did he have the purpose of pointing the way ahead to policymakers, after the fashion of such didactic 'realist ' works as George F. Kennan's American Diplomacy
(19 5 2).
What Wight does have in common with these other 'realist' thinkers is his pessimism: his rejection of the view that progress, away from power politics (in the sense of Machtpolitik) and towards more peaceful and just international order, has taken place or may be ·expected to take place. If Sir Thomas More or Henry IV, he a
wrote in
1 96o,
were to return to contemporary England or France
they might admit that their countries had moved domestically to wards goals of which they could approve. 'But if they contemplated the international scene it is more likely that they would be struck by resemblances to what they remembered . . . The stage would have become much wider, the actors fewer, their weapons more alarming, but the play would be the same old melodrama. International politics is the realm of recurrence and repetition; it is the field in which political action is most regularly necessitous. '8 This disposition to interpret international politics in terms of recurrent patterns led Wight always to suspect claims that some new or apparently new development (nuclear weapons, scientific advance, world public opinion, the growth of communications) was about to transform the international system. It led him also to seek out the historical precedents to which international events might be expected to conform: to view the polarization of power between America and
IO
Systems of States
Russia as a return to the polarization between France and the Habs burgs, or the ideological conflict between the West and Communism as a replay of the schism of Western and Eastern Christendom;' to see in Mussolini's invasion of France in the wake of Hitler's victories the same role of the jackal Power that had been played by Prussia before the battle of Jena, or in President Wilson's moral objections, as he sent American troops to intervene in the Russian Civil War, the equivalent of the tears shed by Maria Theresa as she despatched Austrian troops to take part in the partition of Poland.10 He saw Marxism as in essence a perversion of the New Testament, a secular ized debasement of the Messianic story, and National Socialism as a perversion of the Old Testament, the self-appointment of a new Chosen People.11 As between the view of International Relations Wight took at the age of 33, when Power Politics was published, and the view he developed in later life there is a difference of emphasis, if not of basic content. In Power Politics the emphasis is on the elements of conflict and anarchy in International Relations, even though it is conceded that this conflict and anarchy is restrained by a sense of common interest and common obligation: 'Powers will continue to seek security without reference to justice, and to pursue their vital interests irrespective of common interests, but in the fraction that they may be deflected lies the difference between the jungle and the traditions of Europe ,. 12 In his later writings it is these elements of common interest and co.trunon obligation that came to comman d his attention, most notably in the article on 'Western Values in Inter national Relations, (an account of the Grotian or Rationalist tradi tion) to which reference has been made, and in the papers assembled in the present volume. There is sometimes a note of moral revulsion, a hint of ohne mich, in Wight's clear-sighted descriptions of the cycle of power politics: most notably in his invocation of the 'occult and terrible law ' of the violent destruction of human species propounded by de Maistre- a law which, he thought, provided a more accurate account of the historical record than progressivist theory.u This helps to account for Martin Wight's attitude of Olympian detachment from public controversy about international affairs. He was not without strong fedings about matters of foreign policy: the contempt he felt as an undergraduate for Mussolini and for the policy of appeasement did
Introduction
II
not leave him; he felt strongly against Britain's invasion of Egypt,
and in favour of her entry into the European Economic Community.
Nor do his writings display any coy reluctance to call evil and ltupidity by their proper names. Nor yet again did he display any general unwillingness to stand up and be counted on public issues:
he was, for example, a co--founder of 'The Responsible Society ', a
body set up
in I 97'
to combat the commercialization and exploita�
tion of sex. u But in his attitude to international affairs he was remarkably
free of the impulse that drives so many students of the
subject to advocate policies or canvass solutions to the problems of the day. Wight emphatically did not stand for an attitude of what today is called political commitment, and this was because his
commitment, while it was very powerful, was not political in nature, but intellectual and moral - and, most fundamental! y of all, reli
gious.
4 If Martin Wight's view of International Relations has as its central characteristic his pessimism, the sources of this view lie in his religious faith. Wight was, judged by the fashions of today, a very orthodox Christian- a devout Anglican- and was much impressed by the efforts of Herbert Butterfield and Reinhold Niebuhr to recall Christianity 'to the Old Testament or prophetic interpretation of history, with its belief in the sinfulness of human nature, in cataclysm and tragic conflict, in judgement and providence. 'U In the Christian's attitude towards the march of history, he thought, two attitudes should go hand in hand: on the one hand, the rejection of secular optimism; on the other hand, the acceptance of theological hope. 'Hope', as he once put it, 'is not a political virtue: it is a theological virtue' .18 In his 1 948 article in the Ecumenical Review he attacks the Pelagian belief that 'we are on the whole wdl-meaning people doing our best, who will somehow muddle through', together with secular optimism, 'the belief that because we are wdl-meaning and doing our best, things will therefore tend to come right; or (for optimism sidesteps subtly in fatalism) that what does happen will be for the best anyway.' Neither of these beliefs, he says, is Christian.
12
Systems of States
We are not well-meaning people doing our best; we are miserable sinners, living under judgement, with a heritage of sin to expiate. We are doing our best like Caiaphas, for our idolatrous loyalties; we are well-meaning like Pilate, every day crucifying Christ afresh. We will not somehow muddle through; if we repent and cast ourselves upon God's mercy we have the promise that we shall be saved - a totally different thing, which carries no assurance of muddling through in this world.11 The belief in progress, which had infected Christian historical thinking since the seventeenth century, he thought, had produced 'a kind of welfare state, standard of living, United Nations Christian ity' .18 The secular hope upon which, above all, it focused, was the avoidance of war. This hope Martin Wight did not flinch from rejecting. War is inevitable, he proclaimed on the Third Programme
in 1 953, even though particular wars are avoidable.19 This is a point
of view that at least permits us to go on working to avoid the particular war that is threatening, even while recognizing, as a matter of statistical probability, that over a period wars will break out. In the early years of the cold war, however, Wight appears to have felt that the Third World War was one particular war that was
not avoidable. In a letter written from New York in 1 946 , after a day spent watching the Security Council debate, and feeling that 'it seemed like Geneva all over again only that the rules of the game are now a good deal less civilised', he wrote that: the Third World War is as certain as the return of Halley's Comet .... There is a great temptation for us all to think that though the League collapsed we have learnt our lesson, and the United Nations is in some sense an improvement on the League, and that if we worry enough about it it will work, and we shall be
enabled to live happily ever after. I am convinced that these are dangerous fallacies. Nor indeed do I know that Christians have any warrant for entertaining such secula . r hopes. And I do feel that it is time that the discussion of these matters among Christians proceeded from the realisation that the level on which a Christian political philosophy has to be worked out is ultimately that, not of the White House and Downing Street, but of the catacombs.2 0 He appears to have felt that even to pray for peace can involve a kind of impiety. 'Perhaps there is a sense today', he said in a broad-
Introduction cast in 1 94 8, 'in which we will have to say that the preservation of civilization and the averting of war are not important, before we can recover our balance and find again the way in which they are important. For what matters is not whether there is going to he another war or not, but that it should be recognised, if it comes, as an
act of God's
In his
I
fustice and if it is averted, as an act of God's Mercy.'21
95 I Cambridge sermon 'God in History', Wight called
upon Christians to return to the doctrine of Antichrist, the decline of which in Christian thought had gone
pari passu
with the growth of
the belief in progress. The Christian era had made possible what was
not possible before, but what Christ himself had foretold: a succession of false Christs and false Prophets. If I suggest that the doctrine of Antichrist is part of their theologi cal equipment which Christians might do well to refurbish, it is not to encourage the notion that the Book of Daniel or the Apocalypse of StJohn can be tortured into throwing light upon the current policies of Washington and Moscow, nor to revive the use of the word 'Antichrist', as a term of denunciation for Stalin or General MacArthur or Aneurin Bevan; for in this sense the word had by the seventeeth century become as depreciated by overuse as the word 'Fascist' has become with us today 22 .
Antichrist should be seen not as a person- as the Church of their day had seen Nero, or Julian the Apostate, or Cesare Borgia- but rather as a recurrent situation marked by apostasy, persecution, and demonic possession. By recognizing that theirs is an age of Antichrist, he held, Christians would find a safeguard against secular optimism, and at the same time a source of Christian hope. For as history moves towards a final concentration of Satanic evil, it moves also towards the divine act of judgment that will bring history to an end. 'What is the Reign of Antichrist but the prologue to the Second Coming, the sign that the forces of evil in history have come to a head and worked themselves out? '23
In the last 20 years of his life these views were less in the fore
ground of his thought. They do not, for example, obtrude in the essays in the present volume. There is no reason to think that he abandoned or qualified his religious views, but having wrestled for many years with the moral and intellectual implications of being a Christian, and having come to a kind of truce, rather than an
Systems of States ultimate conclusion, he became more detached about these theo logical themes. His later writings, coming as they did after a very happy marriage, express a more mellow view of the world and reflect a lessening preoccupation with his own inner problems and tensions. But he does not seem ever to have wavered in his faith in funda mental Christian tenets; indeed, this unshakability of his most fundamental beliefs helps to account for the great solidity of his contributions to International Relations and the other subjects in which he was interested; in an age of doubt, in which others were uncertain of their bearings, he always spoke from a point of reference.
5 If Martin Wight was something of an odd man out both as an historian and as a student of International Relations this was because the questions which concerned him most were ethical and theologi cal; at a time when, in both subjects, this was unfashionable he saw the study of history and of International Relations as a means through which these questions could be probed. In his mature years, when the papers in this volume were written, the predominant influence upon the study of International Relations
in Western
coun
tries was that of what may loosely be called the 'social scientific' school, which sought through techniques such as systems analysis, game theory, simulation, content analysis, communications theory and bargaining theory, to arrive at a general explanation of inter national phenomena. Wight's attitude towards the 'social scientific ' school - characterized as the school was by the undervaluing of purely historical understanding, by disdain of inquiry into the moral presuppositions of international behaviour, and by an under lying utilitarianism of purpose and motivation - was wholly un sympathetic. He made no serious effort to come to grips with it, or to set out the basis of his rejection of it, and his critics used to complain of his failure to do so. The truth is, however, that as be tween Martin Wighes view of the subject and that embraced by what I have called the 'social scientific' school there was simply no point of contact at all: the idea that an approach to the subject as
Introduction
secular, as anti-historical and as anti-philosophical as this might provide some guidance as to man's dilemmas in world politics is one that he would have found impossible to comprehend. While Wight's work is less well known than that of some of his more publicized contemporaries he had a profound impact on those ·who came into contact with him through his striking clarity of mind, his awe-inspiring erudition, his modesty and the sense he conveyed of being above the battle, his integrity and gravitas, and above all the very high standards, intellectual and moral, that he set himself. Partly at least because of the sense he always had of the inadequacy of his own work, judged by these standards, he never completed the great work on International Relations which he hoped to write, and of which his friends thought him capable. This was a revised and expanded Power Politics, over which he laboured for many years, ·and about which he wrote in I 97 I in a letter to a friend: I analyse with painful interest the perfectionism which seems to prevent me from being satisfied with anything. There is also that final act of will power which will seize a number of endless! y worked, disjointed, disparate chapters, and fuse them together into a whole in a blaze of creative integration. This is what I have been waiting for over Power Politics. Meanwhile the months flow by, and Nixon decides to go to China, and Japan enters the Great Power dance, and Britain joins the Common Market, and so many sentences have to be revised that one wonders whether a new chapter is necessary, and so on.24 It is hoped that an edited version of Martin Wight's unfinished revision and expansion of Pow" Politics will soon be published. The essays collected in the present volume were not intended by their author for inclusion in Power Politics, but stand on their own. Because they were written for a Committee of specialists, they assume a good deal of knowledge of the history and philosophy of Inter national Relations. Because they are part of a collective enquiry they ·occasional!y make reference to previous discussions of the Committee and papers by others of its members; the reader coming fresh to these essays will occasionally have the impression that he is eaves dropping on a conversation. Wight did not conceive these papers as chapters in a single book, but they do possess a unity of theme, all of them forming part of an enquiry into systems of states.
Systems of States 6
The concept of systems of states lies at the heart of the contem porary study of International Relations, and owes its vogue to the attempt of social scientists (principally but not exclusively American) to view the international political field as a whole as a particular kind of 'system of action'. 2� However, the idea that European states form a system was first given wide currency by early-nineteenth century historians such as Heeren and Ancillon, and is traced hy Wight to an essay of Pufendorf's published in 1675· Wight's ap proach to the subject may be said to have three distinguishing features. First, by contrast with those studies that derive from theoretical models of states-systems, actual and possible, Wight's approach is based on the comparative study of states-systems, that have actually existed. In these essays he deals comprehensively only with the modern or Western states-system and with the classical Greek or Greco-Persian system. However, he draws upon papers written by other members of the Committee on the fonns of universal political organization that existed in ancient India, in China during the Period of Warring States, in Imperial China, in Islam, in the Europe of the Dark Ages, and in Western Christendom. Wight takes a states-system to be simply a group of states that are sovereign, in the sense that they recognize no political superior, and have more or less permanent relations with one another, expressed in four institutions: messengers, conferences and congresses, a diplo matic language, and trade. On this definition there are only three reasonably unambiguous examples of states-systems. There is first the modern or Western states-system which (Wight argues) arose in Europe in the fifteenth century, and is now world-wide, and has six essential features or 'internal signs': sovereign states, their mutual recognition, great powers, a means of regular communication, inter national law and the defence of its common interests through maintenance of a balance of power. There is second!y the Hellenic Hellenistic or Greco-Roman system, which in Wight's treatment comprises not only the Greek or Greco-Persian states-system before the Macedonian conquest, with which he deals in the chapters on 'Bellas' and 'Bellas and Persia', but also the system of Hellenistic kingdoms between the death of Alexander and the Roman conquest,
Introduction
17
with which he proposed also to deal in a later paper that was never written. The Classical Greek city-state system, Wight argues, was unlike the modern Western states-system not only in that it was based on a common language and did not derive from a previously existing political unity, but also in that it operated without some of the most vital of the modern states-system's institutions: international law, resident embassies, great powers and the attempt to preserve a balance of power. And there is thirdly the states-system that existed in China during the Period of Warring States. The attempt to take account of those forms of universal political organization that cannot be treated as states-systems leads Wight to make a number of important distinctions. One is between inter national states-systems, or systems strictly of states that are sovereign, and suzerain state-systems, or systems in which one political unit asserts suzerainty or paramountcy over the rest: examples are the systems centring upon Imperial China, Byzantium, the Ahbasid Caliphate and (in relation to the principalities of the Indian sub continent) the British Raj. Another important distinction he draws is between primary states-systems, or systems whose members are states, and secondary states-systems, whose members are systems of states: examples are the relations of Rome and Persia, the relations of Egypt, the Hittites and Babylon, and the relations of Eastern Chris tendom, Western Christendom and Islam. Wight also makes a vital distinction between open and closed states-systems - between states systems that are impinged upon by outside forces (as the Hellenic system was by Persia and Carthage, or the European system by Tur· key) and those systems that are free of outside pressures, the contem porary global system being the first in history that is completely closed. A second distinguishing feature of Wight's approach is that by contrast with those studies of states-systems which view them as determined purely by mechanical factors such as the number of states in the system, their relative size, the political configuration in which they stand, the state of military technology, he places emphasis on the norms and values that animate the system, and the institutions in which they are expressed. A states-system, in Wight's view, pre supposes·� common culture. The Greco-Roman system, the ancient Chinese· ... system, and the· modern, Western system - his staple examples - were all founded upon such a common culture. The
t8
Systems of States
absence of any such culture in the rdations between the Hellenic states and barbarian powers such as Persia and Carthage, or in the relations between modern European states and Turkey before the nineteenth century, provide part of the case for doubting that the states concerned belong to any common states-system. Wight raises but does not answer the question whether the culrural unity that is a necessary presupposition of states-systems consists simply in a common morality and code, leading to agreement about the basic rules of coexistence among states, or whether it requires common assumptions of a deeper kind - religious or ideological such
as
he explores
in relation to the Western states-system in the
chapter on 'International Legitimacy'. He also places on the agenda of a comparative study of states-systems the question whether there is a wide variation between the common code of one system and another, or whether all such codes 'belong to the great pool of practices and platitudes, supposedly common to the human race, where men seek for Natural Law. ' 2 6 Wight notes that a characteristic tendency of the Western states system has been that its cultural unity is subject to recurrent fracture, as in the religious wars, the wars of the French Revolution and Napoleon, and the ideological conflicts of our own times. He also notes that all states-systems before the Western system in its current phase have had a sense of cultural differentiation from what lay outside: from this sense there has arisen the designation of outsiders as barbarians, and the distinction between just wars, or wars fought against members of the system to enforce its rules, and holy wars, or wars fought to defend the system
as
a whole against outsiders. The
central question about the global states-system of our own times is perhaps whether - given the international fracture to which it is at present subject, the disappearance of the sense of cultural differentia tion from what lay outside, and the expansion of the system of states beyond its original, European confines- any sense of cultural unity can still be said to exist. This is a question which Wight does not,
unfortunately, discuss systematically, although what he writes will help others to seek answers to it.
A
third feature that distinguishes Wight's approach is that by con
trast with those studies that seek to expound the nature and dynamics of states-systems
as
if a rigid line could be drawn between this parti
cular form of universal political organization and others, Wight
Introduction recognizes and explores the uncertain boundaries between what is a states-system and what is not. In the study of world politics at the present time there is legitimate suspicion of attempts to explain inter national conduct - or to justify it - exclusively in terms of the states 1ystcm. Much of the history of modern world politics, particularly of JlOll-European peoples and states, lay outside the confines of any states tystem. Much of the present practice of world politics cannot be comprehended in terms simply of the relations of states, but requires us instead to recognize the role played on the world stage by groups JUch as international organizations, transnational associations, multi national corporations and world revolutionary and counter-revolu tionary movements. Whether or not the structure of the states system is in decline in world politics at the present time, many would argue that it has become an obstacle to the achievement of human goals such as peace, or economic justice, or the control of the environment. It is one of the strengths of Wight's work in this field that much of it is concerned with forms of world political experience that lie beyond the states system in any strict sense. Mention has already been made of his elaboration of the concepts of a suzerain state system, and of a secondary states system. His two chapters on ' The Origins of Our States-System ' explore, successively, its geographical boundaries and its chronological boundaries. In his paper on ' Hellas and Persia' he remarks : 'A historic states-system may seem a tolerably clear and distinct kind of community, or set of relationships and practices, when we study its internal structure and organic life. But when we examine its penumbra, look at its connections with what lies beyond it, explore the scaredy definable gradations by which it shades into its cultural and diplomatic background, it begins to lose its coherence and identity, and doubts may arise about the validity of the concept itself of a states-system. '2 7 Some would say that the study of world politics stands in need of liberation from the domina ting concept of the states system. Certainly it is the case that alternative forms of universal political organization have not received the attention that their historical importance warrants. Wight's essays contain some valuable hints as to how this vast territory might be explored. 'De Systematibus Civitatum ' was written for the Committee meeting of April 196 7 . 'The States-System of Hellas ' and 'Hellas and Persia ', which were written for the meetings of October I 964
20
Systems of States
and September 19 65 respectively, were envisaged as the first two parts of a four-part study of The States System of Greece and Rome which, had it been finished, would have dealt also with the Hellenis tic states-system and the changes following upon the intrusion of Rome. 'The Origins of Our States-System : Geographical Limits' was written for the meeting of July 197 1, 'The Origins of our States System : Chronological Limits ' for that of September I 97 I , ' Inter national Legitimacy ' for that of April 1 9 7 1 , and ' Triangles and Duels' for that of January I 972. Where references have been given for quotations in the text these have been checked and corrected, but there are a number of quota tions for which no references are given, and these have been left as they stand. No substantial alterations have been made to the text, apart from the deletion of some references to previous discussions of the Committee. I must thank Nicola Feakes for her work on the footnores, and Hester Gascoigne for her help with the proofs and index. I am particularly grateful to Gabriele Wight and Harry Pitt for their help and encouragement.
I
De systematihus civitatum
The title is Pufendorfs : a tract published in his Dissertationes llcademicae selectiores at Lund in I 675 . He was trying to make sense of the German constitution after the Peace of Westphalia. Effective sovereignty had been surrendered or lost by the emperor, but its passing to the princes was obstructed by the emperor's residual authority. ' There is nothing for it but to say that Germany is an irregular body, similar to a monster, if it is measured by the rules of civil science. ' But the conception of a states-system provided a new category of explanation, transferring the problem from the domain of constitutional law to that of international relations. His definition of a states-system is : ' several states that are so connected as to seem to constitute one body but whose members retain sovereignty ' .1 The term thus passed into juristic literature. States-systems were subdivided by later writers into ' unions ' (such as that effected in 1 6 88 between England and the United Provinces, Saxony-Poland, and Britain-Hanover) and ' confederations ' (the Empire, the Dutch, the Swiss). I have not been able to trace how ' states-system ' acquired the inclusive meaning it has for us of ' the family of nations '. Gierke's notes show that Thomasius in 1 6 87 distinguished a systema citJita tum from a confederation as ' perpetua unio inddinitae gratiae causa', . and that Nettelbladt in 1 748 described the society of peoples as ·systema gentium.2 Rousseau wrote in 1 756 that ' routes les Puissances de l'Europe forment entre elles une sorte de systeme '.• The French Revolutionary upheaval confirmed the need for a general term to describe the European condition that the French Revolution had upset ; Staatensystem appears in this sense in Gentz's Fragmente in I 8o6 ; and by the time Heeren published his Handbuch der Ges chichte des europaischen Staatensystems und seiner Colonien in 1 809 the transformation may be taken as complete. The O.E.D. gives the first appearance of the word ' states-system ' in English with the translation of Heeren's book in I 8 34· It might be added that it defines ' states-system ' as ' the federation of a number of states with
22
Systems of States
the object of preserving the actual balance of power ' - a definition that reveals the difficulties of the subject by magnificently begging two of the principal questions�. My aim in the present paper is to offer some notes towards clarifying the idea of a states-system, and to formulate some of the questions or propositions which a comparative study of states-systems would examine. Some of them may be beyond the limits of our enquiry ; many may be wrongly formulated. But they illustrate the kind of issue which I believe we should discuss systematically.
1 . DEFINITIONS AND DELIMITATIONS It is worth reminding ourselves that if we were to define the kind of states-system we are concerned with by enumeration, we have perhaps three clear examples : the Western, the Hellenic-Hellen istic or Graeco-Roman, and the Chinese between the collapse of the Chou empire in 771 B .C. and the establishment of the Ts'in Empire in 2 2 1 A.D. As I read Adam Watson's account of what he calls the Southern Indian sub-system I was wondering if this indeed was another example,4 for the states-system of which this sub-system is assumed to be a part remains unclear, and when the sub-system is described with such clarity it is easy to suppose that it may itself be the states-system which emerged after the collapse of the Satavahana Empire. One way of pursuing our enquiry is to ask what these systems have in common and extend the list. An alternative way of pursuing the enquiry would be to take a definition of a states-system and refine it. Montague Bernard offered this definition : a group of states having relations more or less permanent with one another '. Heeren's was more precise : the union of several contiguous states, resembling each other in their manners, religion, and degree of social improve ment, and cemented together by a reciprocity of interests '. 5 I shall try to combine the two procedures, and to examine, first, the states or political units which may be supposed to form the kind of group we have in mind - the members of the states-system ; and secondly, the kinds of communication or intercourse, arising from relations more or less permanent, which we consider ' systematic '. •
•
De systematibus civitatum
23
A . STATES, SUZERAINS, AND SYSTEMS OP STATES
Who are the members of a states-system? By 'states' we normally mean 'sovereign states', political authorities which recognize no superior. But for them to form a system we must mean something more : not only must each claim independence of any political superior for itself, but each must recognize the validity of the same claim by all the others. In modern Europe this has been formulated in the doctrine of the legal equality of states. The ancient Greek poleis and the Hellenistic Kingdoms, in a similar way, both claimed sovereignty and recognized one another's. The kind of states-system described in Geoffrey Hudson's paper on the Chinese is different from this.6 Here there is indeed a group of states having relations more or less permanent with one another, but one ruru>ng them asserts unique claims which the others formally or tacidy accept. This is the suzerain, the sole source of legitimate authority, conferring status on the rest and exacting tribute or other marks of deference. The conception of a presiding monarch seems deeply engrained in Chinese history, for it appears that even . before the internal unification of China by the Ts'in Empire, during the Period of Warring States, the independent Chinese principalities continued to recognize the shadowy authority of the Chou dynasty down to about 335 B.C. Perhaps the closest parallel to China is Byzantium. The Byzantine Basileus was in constitutional theory the overlord of the universe, combining the universal claims of the Roman Emperor with the duty of protecting and disseminating . the universal religion of Christianity. All other Christian princes were his representatives, and all lands that had formerly belonged to the Empire but were now lost would in due time return to their lawful sovereign. The theory of the Abbasid Caliphate was similar. As the Islamic empire decayed and its provinces became independent, self made sultans and emirs as far afield as the Slave Kings of. Delhi continued to apply to a titular caliph for a diploma of investiture. The most recent instance of this kind of system is the British Raj in India. The Blitish Indian Government did not claim to rule the world but within its narrower range it asserted an authority over the 6oo-odd native princes which was so effective that the Raj appears an extreme example of what we are discussing. And it was compelled to translate the position into modern juridical terms, when in I 8 9 I it officially declared that the principles of international law have no ·
•
Syst�ms of Stat�s bearing upon the rdations between the government of India as representing the queen-empress on the one hand, and the native states under the suzerainty of Her Majesty on the other. The paramount supremacy of the former presupposes and implies the subordination of the latter. ' 1 We might distinguish these from inter national states..systems by calling them
first
suzerain
state-systems (in the
phrase the word ' state ' should be in the plural, but in the
second in the singular). And we may note that, while the funda mental political principle of the first will be to maintain a balance of power, for the second it will be
divide �t imp�ra.
Can suzerain powers, or suzerain state-systems, themselves form a secondary states-system ? There have not been many of them together in the world at any one time, and we have at once the question, what is the minimum number of units we think of as constituting a states system ? The rdations between the Roman Empire and the Persian empire in its successive manifestations (Parthian, Sassanian, Abbasid Caliphate) might provide a test-case. These two world-empires had closer rdations with one another than either had with the contem· porary empires in India and China. Their cultural interdependence was notable, and in the intervals of mortal struggle there were periods
of high mutual esteem. In the years following 1945 these Roman Persian rdations were hopefully adduced by journalists and radio
commentators who wanted a historical precedent for peaceful co existence between world-dividing giants. None of them,
so
far as I
remember, found the text for their purpose in the Histories of Theophylact of Simocatta. He records a letter of the Great King Chosroes II to the Emperor Maurice : ' There are two eyes to which Divinity confided the task of illuminating the world : these are the powerful monarchy of the Romans and the wisely governed Commonwealth of the Persians. By these two great empires the barbarous and war-loving nations are kept in check, and mankind given better and safer government throughout. ' The occasion was unusual, because Chosroes was a fugitive at Maurice's court, seeking aid to recover his throne from rebels, and when he had been restored with Maurice's assistance, the two powers joined forces to suppress a
national revolt in Armenia which they had partitioned between
them. But if the letter had been typical of the relationship between the two empires, would their rdationship have amounted to a states system ? Wesdake gave an answer to the cognate question concerning
De syst�matibus civitatum the conditions for international law. In the time of the Roman jurists, he said, ' there was hardly an international society. The Roman and Parthian empires divided the world within which international relations on anything like an equal footing were possible. But the society which is to give birth to law must contain a sufficient number of members for the questions which arise among them to be viewed in
a
general light. Between two or three individuals particular
interests determine and general rules do not arise. ' At the other end of this scale is the case of the Near East in the latter half of the second millennium B.C. Here the revolution in communications due to the introduction of the horse and the in vention of cuneiform writing seems to have produced a states-system with Babylonian as the tem,
lingua franca,
a rudimentary diplomatic sys
io.Yiolability of heralds and ambassadors, treaties of commerce
and marriage, dynastic alliances, and a rudimentary ideology of fraternity and peace. Egypt and the Hittites were the protagonists, with Babylonia and Crete holding the balance. Each of these was an empire, ' federation ,, or suzerain state-system. Of the Hittite royal
tide, Great King, Gurney says ' the title " Great King " belongs to the language of diplomacy and denotes the Hittite King's claim to be one of the great powers of the time, with dominion over lesser kings. '8 If we had a paper on this states-system, we should want to know how many were the powers between whom these relations existed, according to the evidence of the Tell el-Amarna and Boghaz koy documents (the minor powers, Elam, Assyria, Cyprus, the
Aramaean tribes, are mentioned by the historians but do not come
dearly into focus); and also the extent to which the powers accepted doctrine of equality among themselves. In the famous treaty between Egypt and the H ittite Empire of 1 272 B.C., Hogarth finds a
possible traces of a recognition of subordination by the Hittites. 9 For all that, the Armana age seems to be a virtually unique example of what I have called a secondary states-system, that is to say, one whose members are themselves not unitary sovereign states but complex empires or suzerain state-systems. The nearest analogue would perhaps be provided by international relations in the
Medi
terranean in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries A.D. Here there was a triangular relationship between Eastern Christendom, Western Christendom and Islam. But none of them was a single power-bloc. In the central act of the drama, the Fourth Crusade, Venice finally
Systems of St4tes established her own sovereign independence of the Byzantine Empire by placing it under Venetian management. The Second Bulgarian Empire played off the Crusaders against declining Byzantium, and defeated and captured the first Latin Emperor of Constantinople within a y�r of his accession. The West consisted of at least two powers, the Empire, with its ambitions and resources transformed by Henry VI 's marriage to the heiress of the Kingdom of Sicily, and the papacy. The Frankish Kingdom of Jerusalem was the most distant fief of the Holy See, but the Eastern Emperor asserted suzerainty over the Frankish principality of Antioch. Islam was the most fragmented of the three. The vestigal Abbasid Caliphate in Baghdad was eclipsed by the rival Fatimid Caliphate in Egypt ; and when Saladin suppressed the Fatimids he restored the titular supremacy of the Abbasids in order that his own Syrian-Egyptian empire should be able to function more effectively as an independent power. Equally independent was the Selj ug Great Sultanate of Rum, with which the title sultan came to replace that of caliph as the designa tion for the holder of supreme secular power. The relationships between these and the minor powers formed an animated drama of power politics and cultural interchange ; but whether they were sufficient! y organized to compose a states-system, in the sense in which we have been using the term, might be a matter for discussion. What seems to have been most lacking was a common ethos or ideology. Even the chivalric practices and feudal assumptions of the West were only partially reproduced in the social disintegration of Islam, and still less in the Byzantine Empire. Nevertheless, if we are seeking a medieval states-system, it is perhaps only in these external relations that we shall find it. I agree with the conclusion of Desmond Williams' paper that in the Middle Ages there was not a states-system of the kind we are concerned with.10 If I might supplement his arguments, I would say that the i(!ternal arrangements of Western Christendom seem to be marked
y
b the following characteristics :
1.
!.h..�
. .
existence of a single undivided
societas christiana,
which
was the framework of all relationship and all roriflkt. There was a persistent theoretical emphasis on unity rather than separateness, and on hierarchy rather than equality. Consequently it is im possible to use the word ' international ' in speaking of medieval
De systematibus civitatum politics without serious anachronism and distortion. There was also, one might add, a persistent emphasis on questions of right · 'rather than questions of interest : one recalls Stubbs' distinction between the natures of medieval and modern wars. 2. A distribution and parcelling of power among an innumerable multitude of governmental units. Their interdependence and the restraints upon them followed, so to speak, pyramidal not hori zontal lines. A few of them slowly grew into the-ritlitates et regna to whom Aquinas in the later thirteenth century could apply the Aristotelian category of a ' perfect community '. These developed the internal organization and external claims which in due course gave birth to the conceptions of ' sovereignty ' and ' the state '. 3 · The claim of the Empire to universal j urisdiction in tempora
libus.
This was never effective in fact, and the traditional excep
tions slowly gained recognition, as the French king's claim to have no political superior was recognized by Innocent· III's decretal Per Venerabilem in 1 202. But the claim persisted, and characteris tically grew clearer and more defined after the Empire as a political institution had fallen to pieces. It was only in the fourteenth century that the maxim rex imperator in regno suo became current. Where Burckhardt emphasized the illegitimacy of the Renaissance despots, more recently historians have tended to emphasize the survival of imperial investiture in Italy : ' power came from below, from the peopl� : sovereignty came from above, from the emperor'. And as late as 1 4 1 6, Sigismund, when visiting the capitals of Europe, was incautious enough while attending a meeting of the Parlement ·of Paris to dub a French knight, and was consequently refused admission at Dover until he had formally declared that he had no intention of infringing the king's authority
in the realm of England. (The new mediatory role that Sigismund
had discovered for the imperial office has obvious resemblances to that of the Secretary-General of the United Nations. Sigismund stood at the end of the long hittory of the international power of
the Holy Roman Emperor; many people see the Secretary-General of the United Nations standing on the further side of the centuries of international anarchy which we call a states-system, and hope that his office will grow in power. Perhaps it will re-enact the history of the imperial dignity' backwards.) 4 · The claim of the papacy to universal jurisdiction in spiritualibus.
Systems of States This, unlike the imperial claim, was made effective, through a massive international bureaucracy, which was the chief limitation on the rudimentary sovereignty of the civitates et regna, and prompted Figgis's dictum that ' the real state of the Middle Ages in the modern sense if the words are not a paradox - is the Church '. One might add that the real diplomatic system of the Middle Ages was the system of papal legates, who ' carry out direct papal goverrunent through the length and breadth of the societas' .11 The universal government of the papacy was dismanded only after the Council of Constance, with the development of national churches. The change was symbolized by the invention at Constance of the concordat, a new kind of diplomatic agreement on an equal basis between the papacy and the 'nations ', who were afterwards replaced by the kings . -
5 . The conflict between Empire and papacy for supremacy within the societas christiana. It was always essentially a conflict between two officers of the same undivided society, but degenerated into a struggle between two great powers, one territorially based on Germany, to which the Hohenstaufen were able to add Sicily, the other territorially based on the Patrimony of St Peter with effec tive! y organized backing throughout the societas. Both sides, in di.flerent ways, pursued the struggle by soliciting the support of the third world ' of the civitates et regna. In the course of the struggle the papacy was led to claim a supreme rulership, transcending its universal jurisdiction in spiritualihus, which prompted Hobbes's epigram that it was the true successor of the Empire of the Caesars. Ullmann has set the same development in a light which connects it with our concerns : •
This papal world monarchy was also the bridge builder between Roman and modern times. All the characteristic Roman features had impressed themselves upon the physiognomy of the papacy, the Roman Church. Not onl y the law ; also the conception of the universality of government. It was as universal monarchs that the popes pard y applied Roman principles, partly developed them, and partly created new ones, which have since gained universal recognition in international law . The protection of legates ; safe conduct of ambassadors ; secrecy in diplomatic nego tiations ; insistence on the adherence to treaties made between
De systematibus civitatum secular rulers ; condemnation of treaty violations ; papal annul ment and rescission of treaties and compacts ; fixation of treaty conditions ; excommunication and deposition of rulers ; orders for the release of prisoners, for their humane treatment and that . of hostages ; protection of exiles, aliens and Jews ; condemnation . � 'unjust' wars and piracy ; confirmation of peace treaties ; orders for the free passage of troops engaged in a 'just' campaign ; orders to rulers to enter into alliances ; ascription of occupied territories to a victorious belligerent party, and so forth . 1 2
1>oes
this suggest an alternative historical model for the develop ment of the Secretary-Generalship of the United Nations ? 6. The claim of the heads of the societas christiana, first the Em peror and then the pope, to � lords of all mankind. This was �parently first developed during the Investiture Contest by imperialist writers, and was a new facet of the old political ideal of renovatio Romani imperii. The success of the First Crusade in �propriating the pagans · and the revival of Roman Law produced eonditions in which Barbarossa could claim universal lordship explicitly : ' super omnes mortales constituti sumus' . About the same time St Bernard was arguing that Christ had left the govern� ment of the whole human race to Peter, and the canonists quickly took over the imperialist claim to world dominion. The doctrine oi the pope as dominus mundi influenced the geographical ex pansion of Christendom and underlay Alexander VI's arbitral division of the New World between Spain and Portugal, the first great territorial settlement of the modern states-system.
If medieval society provides an example of a states-system at all, which I am inclined to deny, it is a uniquely complicated dualistic or double-headed suzerain state-system . B. A SYSTEM : COMMUNICATION AND INTERCOURSE
'Having relations more or less perltlanent with one another '. How do they have relations ? What is the nature of the relations they have ? Most fundamental and difficult to answer, why do they have relations ?
i. Messengers. Having relations means first of all a system of com munications, which means messengers. It may be worth reviewing
Systems of States the kinds of diplomatic and military messenger we have so far come across. The basic messenger is the herald, an official ad hoc who carries a message from one power or prince to another, and especial! y pro claims war and peace. To establish the inviolability of the herald's person is the beginning of international law. No states·system, pre sumably, could work with heralds alone, because the herald does not negotiate. But the herald constantly reappears in the person of the special envoy. When Goering sent the Swede Dahlerns to London in August
1 939
with an appeal, when Wilson sent Sir Morrice James to
Salisbury with messages, one perhaps saw the herald supplementing more regular methods of communication. The Greeks distinguished the herald,
keryx, who only carried a message, from the ambassador or envoy, presbys, who was empowered to negotiate. They sent ambassadors ad hoc, and it was through ambassadors that their states system worked. (Was this the case with the Chinese ?) The
reciprocally recognized, is the unique
resident ambassador,
invention which has allowed the Western states--system to develop a suppleness and complexity hitherto unknown. The
proxenos
or resident agent was a Greek institution which,
Adam Watson reminds us, has parallels in Latin America.11 My paper on the Graeco-Roman States-System inclined to over emphasize the importance of the oddness.14 The
proxenos
because of its very
was not a negotiator (unless perhaps in
commercial matters), and
proxenoi alone. The spy deserves
proxenos,
a
states·system could not be
run
on
not to be forgotten. He is primarily a means of
information, but sometimes of communication. In the modern West, the world of intelligence, counter-espionage and double agents pro vides a reverse image of the states-system : the dark underside of mutual interdependence. In the early days of Western diplomacy, the ambassador and the spy were not fully distinguished. In totalitarian diplomatic practice, they become reassimilated. And it is interesting to note that Soviet diplomacy has consistently repudiated proposals for international inspection to verify disarmament (which from a Western viewpoint might seem a legitimate and organic development in the institutions of international government which themselves have grown out of diplomacy) as amounting to ' espionage \ Is the intelligence and espionage system complementary to and
De systematibus civitatum
31
iJII!peodent upon the dip�omatic system ? Has it been developed in any
_ l*cr states-system ? Ne1ther Greek nor Latln seems to have a word i.Jm quite the meaning of our international spy. Kataskopos and ,.,tor mean primarily a military scout, like Dolon in the Rhesus, *-)..cbe three men whom the Panhellenic Congress sent to Sardis to
· ·• what they could of Xerxes' preparations for the invasion, and omcerning whom Xerxes gave orders that they should be given full . fldlitics to see everything they wanted, and sent away unharmed. 1 1 ·�k spies, like Greek ambassadors, were not professionals follow
:-lilg a career but individuals entrusted with a commission ad hoc. The principal kind of spy that figures in classical literature is the internal ·;py of an imperial system, the ' king's eye ' in the Persian Empire, the
·*��#or of the Roman. The two spies whom Joshua sent into Jericho .ae engaged on military reconnaissance. The Arthashastra is prob
. .Yy unique among books on international relations in containing oaly one chapter on envoys and much more about spies. Was the early Hindu states-system run on espionage rather than diplomacy ? . · A slightly different institution of a states-system may be mentioned
here: the hostage. The hostage is not a messenger, but an instrument
« coercion against those from whom he has been taken without their
cao�ent, and a pledge by those who have given him willingly. The hutitution antedated the development of the states--system, and, one 181mes, was at its zenith in conditions of feudal warfare; but it sur.. Yived to coexist with diplomacy. Its fully developed form was a mu
tual exchange of hostages, and this was a kind of communication : a aolcmn confirmation of readiness to observe pledges given. Mter Pavia Charles V extorted the surrender of Francis' Is two sons as security for 1he French king's fulfilling the Treaty of Madrid ; Spain and France
exchanged hostages after the Treaty of Cateav.-Cambresis (the Span
ish hostages who went briefly to Paris being William of Orange and Egmont). The last surrender of hostages to ensure the performance of an agreement other than a military convention was apparendy at the Treaty of Aix-la-Chapelle in
1 748,
when ' the King of England
undertook to send to the King of France two persons of rank and consideration, to remain as hostages, until a certain and authentic acount should be" received of the restitution of Cape Breton and of all .the conquests made by his anns or subjects in the East and West Indies ' •1 6 But hostages continued to be taken in war, to secure legiti mate warfare, the prompt payment of contributions, compliance with
32
Syst�ms of Stat�s
requisitions, etc'., and the practice is regulated by international law, where it easily merges into the law of reprisals. The conception of the hostage has been rediscovered by the strategic analysts. The balance of terror, Schelling has said, is ' a massive modern version of an ancient institution, equivalent to a total exchange of all conceivable hostages '. Schelling has also suggested that the function of the
American troops stationed in Europe is that of hostages : they are
pledges that the United States will not evade her obligation to support her European allies in the event of conflict. In this
case,
one may
observe, the hostage is given by the stronger party to the weaker ; is it the same with the British hostages in I 74 8 ? It has been suggested, moreover, that when Harold Wilson met Ian Smith on the
Tiger in
November I 966, the Governor of Rhodesia was brought along in the role of a negative hostage : the representative of legitimate authority would not be allowed to return to the colony unless the rebel ruler returned too. ii.
Confer�nc�s and international institutions.
ferences have been the
set
Congress and con
pieces punctuating the history of the
European states-system, moments of maximum communication. Are they an essential of a states-system ? They existed in ancient Greece, hut
seem
paradoxically to have been both less prominent and epoch
making, and possibly more effective, than in Europe. In Greece the ambassador ad
hoc coming to a conference was the consummation of
the diplomatic process. In the modern world, the foreign minister or head of government coming to a conference (since I S I S) has only supplemented ' the usual diplomatic channels ', and often not con structively. What part did conferences play in other states-systems ? In China there appears to have been a disarmament conference attended by 1 4 states in 546 B.C. Was this unique ? We must also ask whether any states-system other than the Wes tern has attempted to erect constitutional machinery in the shape of a permanent conference. Almost certainly the Greeks did not. In the seventh and sixth centuries B.C. there seems to have been a Chinese Central Confederacy with a permanent constitution and regular assemblies of the heads of state. But its aim seems to have been defensive against other Chinese powers, and not inclusive. The enquiry would need carefully to disentangle confederacies and federations from inclusive international institutions.
De systematihus cit1itatum
33
iii . .A diplomatic language. Is a common language, in addition to W:maculars, essential to communication between members of a states
·if*m ?
The modern world has had first Latin, then French, now
English. The Hell�nic and Hellenistic �orld had A c :�k, supplemented by Lattn. I t may be worth nottng that effective
�ps
�
' tub-systems have grown up, in the modern world, almost exclusively
:ladong
states with a common language : as the German states, the
Italian, the Arab, the Latin American. Has any states-system oper ata! multilingually ? lY·. Trr:�de. The Western states-system grew up round the coalescence ff 'the two commercial worlds of the Mediterranean and of the Baltic ad .North Seas, and it seems that throughout its development the -omic horizon has stretched beyond the limits of diplomacy.
COmmerce has cast a nimbus of activity and connexions round the .fditical system, prefiguring as it were the next stage of its outward
powth,
whether that came about through colonial expansion
or
the
idmission of peripheral states to membership. The Greek states lfltem has similarities, though it never extended to embrace the
range of Hellenistic trade with Parthia, Arabia and India. Are the Western and Greek systems different from others in this respect, by rason of their common geographical configuration - proximity to
the
sea
and great varieties of natural advantage within a small area,
favouring a progressive extension of the market ? Or is it true of most states-systems that economic interdependence precedes diplomatic organization ?
2. CULTURAL QUESTIONS Are we going to concern ourselves with what might be called the sociology of states-systems ?
A . CUL'nJRAL UNITY
We must assume that a states-system will not come into being without a degree of cultural unity among its members. The three states·systems that we have taken as paradigms, the Greek, the Western, and the early Chinese, each arose within a single culture.
SystemJ of States
34
What I have called secondary states-systems (like those of the Annana age and of the medieval Mediterranean world) might also be called ' inter-cultural '. Yet presumably there must have been sufficient community between these cultures - Egypt, the Hittites, and Babylon ; the West, Byzantium, and Islam - for a states--system between them to have been approximated to. How
we describe this cultural community ? Does it consist essentially in a common morality and a common code, leading to can
agreed rules about warfare, hostages, diplomatic immunity, the right of asylum and so on ? Does it require common assumptions of a deeper kind, religious or ideological ? Is there wide variation between the common code of one states-system and of another ? Or do they all belong to the great pool of practices and platitudes, supposed! y common to the human race, where men seek for Natural Law ? These questions are topical, because it may be thought that in the history of the development of the Westero states-system, diplomatic and technological interdependence have today outrun cultural and moral community. The states-system organized in the United Nations is qualitatively different from that of the Concert of Europe, as well as geographically wider. B. CULTURAL DIFFERENTIATION : EXTERNAL
The greater the cultural unity of a states-system, the greater its sense
of distinctness from the surrounding world is likely to be. The
Western states-system in the twentieth century is the first that has had no external relations except such as may arise from space dis covery. All other states-systems, including the Western in its earlier chapters, have expanded or had to defend themselves against alien pressures. Hence the designation of those outside the states-system as ' barbarians '. Hence also the idea of the ' Hoi y War • . The institution of the Hoi y War seems to have originated with the Jews, and to have reached its highest development in the Islamic
jihad,
whence it passed (though the matter is controversial) to the
West as the crusade. It is distinct, in theory and practice, from other kinds of war. One is tempted to say that the Just War is the norm within the states-system, the Hoi y War the norm between states systems. In the notion of the Just War, the premise is that all parties have their due rights, and war is the means of penalizing violation of right and ensuring restoration and restitution. It is
a
juridical con-
v� systematibus dvitatum
35
·;
.
·tiption, of war as the instrument of law. In the notion of the Holy war, the premise is that the true believers ar� right, and that infidels lie to be converted or extenninated. ' Paien unt tort e chrestiens unt &;tit '. It is a religious conception, of war as the instrument of God's .W, or of history. ,. But two questions follow. First, have all states-systems entertained jOIDe notion of Holy War in their external relations ? Or is it a uct of the Judae<>-Christian-Islamic tradition ? The evidence does � seem clear. In Greek thinking there is a strain of belief that Hdlenes and barbarians were by nature in a state of war with one
prod
another; and !socrates described the Panhellenic war that he advo-4 cated against Persia as ' more like a sacred mission than a military expedition '. On the other hand, Byzantium, whose raison d'etr� almost was to champion Christianity against the barbarians, had an attitude towards warfare · that was unmilitaristic, cautious and ttaoderate. ' To the realist outlook of East Rome the Crusades were llrgely incomprehensible.' : - Secondly, can we say that the institution of the Holy War is typical of a states-system, but precisely of those systems which we hetitate to classify as states-systems ? The jihad flourished under the
•ot
Caliphate, which was a world empire, a universal state, or in its decline a suzerain state-system. The crusade flourished in the medi eval West, which was an anomalous suzerain state-system, or an embryo states--system. Would it be possible to show that the tradition of the Hoi y War loses its strength as the states-system of modern ·Europe matures ? There seems to be much evidence against such a comforting conclusion, mainly by reason of the steady expansion of the European states-system at the expense of the world's barbarians and natives. The evidence ranges from the English conduct of war against the mere Irish, and the maxim 'The only good Indian is a dead Indian ', in the seventeenth century, to the French conquest of Algeria and the Anglo-Chinese Wars in the nineteenth. c. CULTURAL DI FFERENTIATION : INTERNAL
A characteristic feature of the European states-system has been its tendency to internal fracture. If we take the three conventional dates of the French invasion of Italy in 1494, Luther at Wittenburg in 1 5 1 7, and the Turkish siege of Vienna in 1 529, we may say that the first generation of the European states-system saw both the greatest
Systems of Sl4tes external pressure that the state�system has ever suffered, and its most fundamental internal schism. The connection between these three developments has never so far as I know been fully explored, in the way in which Braudel has explored the next chapter of the story in the second half of the century. It might perhaps be sym bolized by Sir Thomas More, imprisoned in the Tower of London before execution, writing the Dialogue of Comfort against Tribula
tion,
with its pervading sombre theme, not of his own predicament,
but of the Turkish threat to Christendom. The Religious Wars marked the first fracture in the states-system ; the French Revolutionary Wars marked a second ; the totalitarian revolutions and wars of the twentieth century have marked a third. The effect in each case, as Burke put it, ' was to introduce other interests into all countries than those which arose from their locality and natural circumstances.
.
•
.
The warm parties in each state were
more affectionately attached to those of their own doctrinal interest in some other country, than to their fellow-citizens, or to their natural government, when they or either of them happened to be of 11 a different persuasion ' .
But there have been further effects. A doctrinal fracture or schism in the states-system undermines the tacit understanding that every member of the states-system in claiming sovereignty and political independence for himself acknowledges the same claim by every other member. To a militant Catholic or Jacobin or Communist state, its opponents do not have an intrinsic right to exist : they have a right only to be restored to the true faith or liberated or, as Khrush chev said, 'buried ' . In these circumstances the regular working of the states-system is deranged. And there are thus introduced within the states-system the assumptions and attitudes of the Holy War, and heretics or political opponents are assimilated to barbarians. One view in the controversy about the source of the idea of the crusade traces it back to the Augustinian idea of the bellum justum against the enemies of God, rather than to an Islamic source, and sees the Christian jihad as having been from its origins primarily inward turning and directed against heretics. Internal Holy War, originally of Christian inspiration but later of the secular ideologies deriving from Christianity in this respect if in no other, has certainly been a recrudescent feature of the Western states-system. Is it peculiar to Western Europe ? Burke found a precedent in the
r
De systematibus civitatum
,,
37
';,'Jirilion
of the Hellenic states-system between the democratic and ic ' factions ' - ' full as powerful and full as mischievous as ::. .... spirit of religious system had ever been ' .18 Our main evidence � J* these factions is scattered about in Thucydides, and summed up the passage where he says that the savageries of the Corcyraean ·
ftUprch
·,
.·
16
�nolution seemed the more atrocious because it was the first revolu .tkm that had occurred.
'.:· But
•.
afterwards practically the whole Hellenic world was con
: · vulsed, in every state the democratic leaders trying to bring in the
. Athenians, and the oligarchs trying to bring in the Spartans. In .. ·,time of peace there would have been no pretext and no inclination · to ask for their intervention. But in war-time, allies were available
to either side to get the better of its opponents and strengthen its
. . own position, and those who wanted a change of government had ·
plenty of occasions to call in outside help.19
}d the Peloponnesian War swung against Athens, the leaders of the oligarchic revolution of 4 I I in Athens set about replacing democra . ci.es by oligarchies in the subject cities, but ' found that most of the business had
(lletairot)' .20
already been accomplished by the local
parties
Three years later Lysander, the new Spartan comman
·der in the Aegean, organized the various oligarchical clubs (laetairiot) in the Ionian states, ' promising that if his undertakings were success ful he would put each group in control of its city' .21 Xenophon refers
to
these as ' Lysander's friends', who intrigued against Lysander's
successor in the command.22 When Lysander had been reappointed and Athens defeated, ' he introduced governments in all the cities under the Spartans in accordance with the policy of the Spartan government, establishing dekarchies, the rule of ten men, in some and oligarchies in others ' .2 8 All these arrangements collapsed within half a generation. It is difficult on such slight evidence to draw a comparison between international stasis in the Greek world and Holy War in the modern. But four comments are possible. I . The Hellenic factions, so far as we know, were not united by an ideology, a fanatically held philo soph y of life or doctrine of politics. They simply recognized common political interests across state frontiers. 2 . The inspiration of the Hellenic factions seems to have been spontaneously local. Their Greek name, hetairia, is usually translated ' club ', and the word
Systems of States denotes a religious or craft guild more often than a political asso ciation. There seems to be no evidence of inter-state organization about them, no element of international ' Church ' or ' Party '. We do not hear of any groups of political missionaries resembling the Jesuits and the Calvinist preachers, the Jacobin societies and the Communist Party. 3· The great power on either side seems to have been corresponding} y more detached from the interests of its poten tial partisans abroad than perhaps has been the case in modern Europe. De Romilly points out that Thucydides never presents the international democratic leaning towards Athens : as being anything more for Athens than an instrument which she uses to facilitate her conquests, but which in no way explains the principles which lead her to act. (For instance, the Athenians are sorry that they attacked Syracuse, a democratic city like Athens, for they are unable to spread discontent and make friends there). It is the natural tendency for democracies to unite which will help to bring about the predominance of Athens, not this predominance which will foster an ideal union of democracies. 24 Lysander tried to organize the oligarchic clubs of the liberated states, but as much in the interest of his personal aggrandisement as in that of Sparta herself, and with only the most temporary effect. 4 · The international stasis that was produced by the strains of the Pelo ponnesian War on the states-system died away, and was not repeated in any later chapter of the story. It was not a recurrent feature of the Graeco-Roman states-system. To the extent that these comments are sound, Burke's comparison loses its force. Has any other states-system shown an internal cultural differentia tion leading to ideological schism and crusading attitudes ? A familiar aspect of the intellectual history of the modem Euro pean states-system has been the way in which its theory has fallen into three main traditions. Those whose outlook has been missionary and messianic have emphasized the ideal unity of international society as the standard for condemning the empirical divisions within the society and believing them to be transitory. They implicitly repudiate the validity of the states-system. The repudiation has usual} y taken the militant and crusading form discussed above ; less often it has taken a liberal idealist, pacifist and Tolstoy an form ; they
De systematibus civitatum
39
are two versions of a common international theory. On the other side are the children of Machiavelli and Hobbes, who regard the existing states--system as an expression of the state of nature, and see all in terms of raison d'etat, of survival in a situation that is
,_,ncy
eSsentially one of anarchy. In between are those who accept the statewystem as constituting a valid society of mutual right and ons; of these Grotius is usually taken as the great exemplar.
lwigati
There are
many intermediate positions, but the three traditions are
diltinct. tr.r. Can a comparison be made with the schools of thought in ancient .
(;bina, which arose during the Period of Warring States ? The &cbool of Law, the Legalists, are commonly compared to Machiavelli; ludiur Waley describes them under the name ' Realists ' ; and
The Jook of the Lord Shang has been compared to Kautilya's Arthasha fJIW· The Legalists grew up against the conservative tradition of Confucious, Mencius and the Mohists, who, with many variations
�
inconsistencies, seem to represent a moralist and natural-law
.pproach to politics. ' Like the Confucians ', says Waley, and one may idd like Grotius, ' Mo Tzu believed in the Righteous War, in which a · good King, at the command of Heaven, punishes a bad one '. 2 5 (This in European terms is the conception of the Just War, not the Holy War). What seems most difficult to find in China is a counter
part to the messianic and missionary strand in European thought. The nearest is provided by the Taoists, who were (translated into
European terms) anarchist and pacifist in their outlook, looked back to a golden age, dreamed of the ideal state, and asserted the harmony
of · interests. What is lacking in the comparison is the crusading or militant impulse. Indeed, the Taoists seem to have been the objects rather than the inspirers of violence. Soothill says, ' Whilst wars of extermination have been prosecuted by the state against the Moslems
in China, as also against the Taoists - chiefly on political grounds religious wars between the three religions, or the horrors of the Inquisition on account of religion, have been unknown, for intensity of religious feeling has never been sufficient! y strong to produce extremities of so virulent a character '.2 8 Did the Chinese schools of thought contain sufficient! y coherent theories of the nature and obligations of the states-system for a parallel with Europe to be sought ? Is there anything similar in other cultures?
Systems of States 3.
POLITICAL QUESTIONS
Even more insistent than the cultural questions, if we are attempting a general study of states-systems, are certain political questions. A. THE NUMBER OF MEMBERS OF THE STATES-SYSTEM
One of the prime questions about any society for a historian or social scientist is the size of its population. Is there an analogous question about the size of membership of a states-system ? The membership of the modern European states-system was drastically lowered in number by the Revolutionary Wars and the Vienna Settlement; it was then reduced to its minimum by the unification of Italy and Germany, though the liberation of the Balkan states was beginning a counter-tendency which became dominant with the Versailles Settlement. (Between 1 8 7 I and I 905, when Norway seceded from Sweden, there seem to have been only twenty sovereign states in Europe. This excludes the American states, which only assumed a formal role in the states-system at the Hague Conferences.) To what extent, if any, can the characteristics which distinguish the nineteeth-century states-system from that of the eighteenth or twentieth centuries be attributed to this ? The number of poleis in the Hellenic states-system before Alexan der seems to have been at the other extreme : perhaps I soo. How was this number related, whether as cause or effect, to the inveterate factiousness and parochialism of the Greek states ? Ancient China seems to have resembled modern Europe rather than Greece . According to Elbert D. Thomas, it was divided into so odd kingdoms, not counting the peripheral tribes. 27 Needham lists 25 'feudal states of the Chou period ' which were eventualI y unified in the Ts'in Empire.28 Is a smaller membership likd y to make for greater stability, mutual understanding and cooperativeness in a states-system ? Under what conditions is the multiplication of states likely, on the one hand, to increase the occasions of conflict, and on the other hand, to enrich and lubricate the working of the balance of power? B. KINDS OF MEMBER AND HOMOGENEITY OF MEMBERSH I P
What is the effect on a states-system of variety or similarity among its members ? Here we must distinguish the structure of the state
I � .
De systematibus civ;tatum
: (e.g. city-state, feudal kingdom, nation-state, federation) from the ··cture of government (e.g. democracy, dictatorship). ·:�� · The states-system of ancient Greece seems to have had a high ·:lt;gree of homogeneity as regards the kind of state it embraced. The vast majority of its members were poleis. The exceptions, like pre . �Jkilitical Arcadia, or the tribal kingdom of Macedon, were so few :that their very membership of the system is uncertain. The post Alexandrian states-system was more varied, with the great Hellenistic monarchies overshadowing the city-states. The modern European states-system has had a heterogeneous membership. Before 1 789, when international legitimacy was based on prescription, the system included multi-national monarchies like Austria and Britain, national monarchies like France and Sweden, provincial monarchies like the German electorates, overgrown dty-states like Venice and Tuscany, a confederation of overgrown city-states in the United Provinces, a confederation of cantons in Switzerland. Since 1 789, national self-determination has replaced prescription as the doctrine of international legitimacy, and between 1 9 1 9 and 1 939 the states-system achieved a degree of transient homogeneity on this basis. Since then, with national self-determina 'tion being applied in conditions so different from those in which it originated that the word ' nation' has lost any distinct meaning, heterogeneity has returned. The states represented at the United Nations are more various in origin, size and structure than were the states represented at the Congress of Westphalia. It is not possible to distinguish state-structure complete! y from government-structure. Both have been made matters of ideology in the modern West, by apostles of homogeneity within the states system. Mazzini held that the states-system would not be just or effective until all its members were nationally free, and assumed that nationality meant democracy. Wilson wanted to make democracy a qualification for membership of the League. The Western states system has come nearer than any other to erecting the structure of government into a principle of international legitimacy. Does homogeneity of membership make for the stability of a states system and cooperation between its members ? Are there characteristic differences between a states-system of city-states and one of nation states ? Or are the internal political arrangements of the members of a states-system for the most part irrelevant to its working? ,
·
Systems of States C. HIUAit.CHY
The modern European states-system, while formulating the principle of the equality of states, has modified it by establishing the class of great powers. Since 1907, if not since I 8 1 5, their responsibilities and privileges have been recognized in international law. Do other states-systems have this natural aristocracy ? If so, has it been institutionalized anywhere besides Europe ? Has the modern states-system gone further than others in trying to put their great powers under some kinds of restraint, and in encouraging their transformation (as Zimmern once said) from great powers into ' great responsibles ' ? D. DYNAMICS
If we take the European states-system as our example, we the following questions :
can
ask
Do other states--systems show a succession of hegemonies, in which one great power after another tries to transform the states-system, or even to abolish it, by reducing it to unity ? Do other states-systems embody a system of the balance of power ? Does the balance of power system arise only in response to the threat of a hegemony ? Has there been any states-system that was innocent of the idea or practice of the balance ? Do other states-systems colonize or conquer their peripheral regions and afterwards admit these regions to membership ? Do other states-systems develop sub-systems, and under what conditions ? E. PHASES
The Western states-system may be seen as having gone through four phases or periods. In each phase, there has been a highly organized geographical core, with a periphery of powers or regions more loosely connected with the system. To 1 500
core, Italy ; periphery, Transalpine Europe
1 500-1 763
core, Western Europe ; periphery, Eastern Europe
1 763- 1 94 1
core, Europe ; periphery, the Americas and the traditional states of Asia
De systematihus civitatum .Since 1 94 1
43
core, roughly the states which helped to found or were members of the League of Nations ; periphery, the ex-colonial states, especially in Africa
· . The
Graeco-Roman states-system had three clear phases. Before
Alezander came the Hellenic states�system of city-states ; after Alex ander, the Hellenistic states-system in which the great powers were
tbe successor-states of his own Empire, large half-orientalized monarchies towering above the surviving city-states. Alexander in
Greek history combined the roles of Christopher Colombus, George tWashington, and Napoleon. But a third phase must be distin�
guished.
When Rome conquered and destroyed the Macedonian
kingdom at the battle of Pydna in
168
B.C., she transformed the
ltatcs-system into a suzerain state-system. Its international relations thenceforward were subordinate to the domestic politics of the
Roman Republic itself. Nothing like this has happened in the
Western states-system.
Have other states-systems passed through a sequence of marked phases ? What varieties of pattern do they show ? F.
TERMINUS AD QUEM ?
Most states�syst�s have ended in a universal empire, which has swallowed all the states of the system. It has been particularly clear
in the case of the primary states-systems, those that are the political
expression of a single culture. The Chinese was unified by the Ts'in Empire, the Hellenistic by the Roman, the Indian by the Moghul. It seems
also the case with our clearest example of a secondary stat�
system, that of the Amarna age. This ended in the Assyrian Empire, the first of the ancient empires to unite both Mesopotamia, Syria and Egypt, and the militaristic forerunner of the more benign and civilized Persian Empire. In a similar way, the medieval Mediter ranean states-system (if such existed) ended with the Ottoman Em pire, which absorbed the Islamic and Byzantine sections of the states-system and threatened to absorb the Frankish (Bayezid I declared his intention of feeding his horse at the altar of St Peter's, and Mehmed II planned the conquest of Italy to confirm his capture of Constantinople). These examples surely suggest the two most important questions that we can ask about states-systems. The first is factual, a matter of
Systems of States
44
history or political science. Is there any states-system which has not led fairly directly to the establishment of a world empire ? Does the evidence rather suggest that we should expect a states-system to culminate in this way ? If so, what can be said about the possible causal connections? It might be argued that every states-system can only maintain its existence on the principle of the balance of power, that the balance of power is inherently unstable, and that sooner or later its tensions and conflicts will be resolved into a monopoly of power. The second question is a matter of theory, or of judgment, and goes deeper; indeed, it underlies our choice of states-systems as a subject of study. For what reasons are we inclined (as I think we probably are) to judge a states-system as per se a more desirable way of arranging the affairs of a great number of men than the alterna tives, whatever these may be ? For what reasons, or should we say, under what conditions ? George Orwell imagined, for I 984, a divi sion of the world between three totalitarian great powers, locked together in interdependent hatred, like the characters in Huis Clos, or Ugolino and Archbishop Roger on their sea of ice in the Inferno. This too is a picture of a states-system. It may he worth remembering that some of the historic generations which have experienced the end of a states-system have done so with relief and rejoicing. St Augustine expressed a preference for a world of small nations over the Roman Empire. But he qualified the statement in a highly characteristic manner, which makes it both instructive and relevant. He is asking whether it is appropriate for good men to rejoice in extension of empire. The implied answer is no, for the world would be a better place without empires. 'Human affairs being thus more happy, all kingdoms would have been small, rejoicing in neighbourly concord (concordi vicinitate laetantia : the ideal of a states-system) ; and thus there would have been very many nation-states (regna gentium) in the world, as there are very many houses of citizens in a city '. 29 Why then has this state of affairs not come about? Because 'the iniquity of those, against whom just wars are waged, favours the expansion of a state'. Here, as in another passage, Augustine takes the view that the wars by which the Roman Empire was created were on the whole just. 'Therefore, to carry on war and to extend dominion over subjugated peoples seems to bad men to be felicity, but to good men necessity . Moreover, since it would be worse that the more 10
De systematihus civitatum
45
criminal should rule over the more righteous (injuriosi justioribus), it is not incongruous after all to describe empire as felicity. (But beyond question', he adds, 'it is greater felicity to have a good DCighbour at peace, than to subjugate a bad one by war). ' 11
2
The states-system of Hellas
A states-system presupposes a common culture. The classic descrip tion of the community of Hellas is in Herodotus, in a speech the Athenians make to reassure the Spartans that Athens will not accept the Persian overtures for a separate peace : There are many great reasons why we should not do this, even if we so desired. First and foremost, the burning and destruction of the statues and temples of our gods, whom we are bound to avenge to the uttermost rather than make terms with the perpetrator. And next, because the Hellenes are related in blood and language, and
have shrines of the gods and sacrifices in common, and a simi lar way of life. It would ill become the Athenians to betray all this.1
Blood, the belief in a common descent, was systematized by inventing the eponymous ancester Hellen from whose three sons were sprung the tribes of the Aeolians, Ionians and Dorians.
was the obj ective test of being a Hellene, as to speak a language other than
Language
Greek was the test of being a barbarian. In both these respects Greek civilization made an assumption of its own unity and homogeneity that contrasts with the Romano-German culture of medieval Chris tendom, amalgamating two strains at least. A states-system whose members are bound together by having a common language - this is one contrast with the modern Western states-system that Hell as offers. It led nineteenth-century historians to write of the ancient Greeks as a ' nation ', and to think of their states-system in terms of the linguistically homogeneous modern sub-systems such
as
Italy and
Germany, whose manifest destiny was a union or federation which the ancient Greeks unaccountably missed.
Religion,
by contrast
again, had more variety of cult and was less organized than Western Catholicism in the early Middle Ages. But it had some common shrines and important common oracles, of which Delphi was the
The states-system of Hellas
47
foremost. Way of life is illustrated by the Panhellenic games, those at Olympia above all. .i
Perhaps the most important difference between the Hellenic states
lystem and the Western is that the Western states-system developed out of the theoretical institutional unity of the Respublica Christiana,
With its diarchic structure of Sacerdotium and Regnum, while the Hdlenic states-system had no historical background of this kind. In Bellas the state seems to have existed well before the states-system . The Greeks invented the
polis
as the normal unit of social cohesion
.lomewhere after 1 000 B.C. Behind it lie only the shadowy Mycen aean monarchies of Homer,s Achaean kings, which are the equiva
lent perhaps of the Ostrogothic kingdom of Theodoric. The polis is Cfevdoped in the Greek Middle Ages, and is the historical counterpart
'of the feudal principality of the European Middle Ages as well as,
perhaps even more than, of the modern European nation-state. · The states-system which the pokis formed may be considered
· ..
'nnder five heads : Panhellenic institutions, international law, a diplo matic system , a balance of power, and international public opinion.
The first three correspond roughly to an order of historical evolution. I . PANHELLENIC INSTITUTIONS These were religious in origin, the common shrines and festivals of the Hellenes. The two most famous are the quadrennial festival of ·
the Olympian Zeus whose chief feature was the Games, and the oracle of Apollo at Delphi. Both were geographically central. Olym pia is on the western edge of the Peloponnese, remote from the
Aegean and Ionia ; but it was correspondingI y more accessible to the Greeks of Sicily and Italy, and its rise may be connected with the rise of the Western colonies. Del phi was more central still, and its position enabled it to replace the older oracular shrine of Zeus at Dodona, in the highlands of Epirus. The sanctuary of Olympia was in the territory of Pisa, and its control was coveted by Elis, which succeeded in usurping the presidency of the festival. Elis was backed by Sparta ; Argos, the hereditary enemy of Sparta, therefore backed Pisa. The Eleans were in control from the beginning of the sixth century. In 420, during the Peace of Nicias that punctuated the Peloponnesian War, they
Systems of States were even strong enough to exclude Sparta herself from the sanc tuary and the Games, for failing to pay a fine imposed for breach of the Olympic law.2 In 364, when Thebes had replaced Sparta as the dominant power, an attempt was made to restore the rights of Pisa by Argos and the Arcadian league. There was fighting in the sanc tuary, and the victorious Arcadians plundered the sacred treasures to pay the Allied army. The general moral condemnation of this sacrilege was sufficient! y strong to do lasting damage to the Arcadian league. a During the celebration of the festival a sacred truce was observed, and the Eleans claimed that for this period their territory was inviolable ; they themselves violated the sanctuary in 3 64, however, when the Pisatans were once more in control. The festival had political importance as a forum and a sounding�board. The texts of important treaties were inscribed on pillars set up at Olympia as well as at Delphi:' When Mytilene revolted from the Athenian Empire in 428, the Spartans instructed the Mytilenaeans to come and state their case at the 01 ympian festival, which they did at length. 5 At the
festival of 408 Gorgias protested against the alliance between Sparta
and Persia ; in 3 8 8 Lysias used the festival to denounce Persia and Dionysius the tyrant of Syracuse as twin dangers to Greek liberty ;6 and the
Panegyricus
of !socrates, his greatest political tract, was
composed in the form of an oration to be delivered perhaps at the
following 01 ympiad.
The Oracle at Delphi had greater political importance than the Olympian festival : it was the nearest equivalent in Hellas to the papacy in Christendom. From the eighth century it enjoyed universal prestige as the supreme shrine. It acquired a political role as the adviser of the Greek states during the great period of colonization, when it was regularly consulted in advance on choice of site. Later it was resorted to as arbitrator of international disputes. 1 The Delphic priesthood became a repository of geographical and political know� ledge. But the dissimilarities from the papacy are more striking than the resemblance. The Oracle had no doctrinal authority ; it did not censor morals ; it did not exercise political rule through an ecu menical legal and fiscal system. Even its political advice was largely rigged. ' Greek states did not ask Apollo to originate or direct their policy, ' said Bury ; ' they onl y sought his authority for what they had already determined '. 8
49
The states-system of Hellas
In general the priesthood leaned to conservatism and had aristo
:tratic sympathies. The Oracle usually gave its support to the power
that was on the upgrade, like The Times newspaper in British
politics,
and unlike the papacy in international politics. The rise of
.Jbe Oracle is associated with Spartan predominance. At the begin iiing of the fifth century the Oracle accepted the Persian invasion
and discouraged Greek
resistance ; it is remarkable that it recovered
ia political influence after this blunder. It supported Sparta in the �oponnesian War, and Athenian resentment has been traced in
Euripides' jibes at Apollo and Aristophanes' satirical treatment of .oracles. During the war both Delphi and Olympia were in the aritorial control of the Peloponnesian league, and the Corinthians proposed using the treasuries of the two temples to finance the allied war-effort ;9 but there is no evidence that this was done. A hundred years later Delphi backed Philip of Macedon : ' the Pythia is philip pizing', said Demosthenes.10 . Like other international institutions, the Oracle was manipulable
by the dominant power of the time. A valued privilege was the
promanteia,
or right of first consultation with the prophetess. The
Delphians (themselves forming a small
polis)
usually claimed it for
themselves, and accorded the right of coming next to different states at different times. Thus the
promanteia
was an index of political
influence, as the choice of a papal conclave has sometimes been. When Croesus was at the height of his power and loading the Oracle with rich gifts, the Del phians granted the
promanteia
to the
Lydians.11 In 44 9, after the end of the First Peloponnesian War, Sparta intervened to support the Delphians in their conflict with Phocis. In return, the Spartans were granted
promanteia,
and had
the decree inscribed on the forehead of the bronze wolf that stood in the sanctuary. Pericles promptly counter-intervened and restored Phocian control of Delphi; he secured the grant of
promanteia
for
the Athenians, and had it chiselled along the right flank of the same wolf.1 2 Was this simply a dispute about diplomatic precedence ? It is not clear whether Sparta had not previously enjoyed the
promanteia;
nor whether the Athenian action restored the balance by asserting an equal right to the privilege, or deprived Sparta of it. Athens seems to have retained her precedence in consulting the oracle until she lost it to Philip - here it is clearly a privilege that only one power holds.11
Systems of St4tes
so
2. INTERNATIONAL LAW AND ORGANIZATION Delphi was the centre of the best-known and most important Amphictyony, or religious league. Originally it had been organized round the temple of Demeter at Anthela near Thermopylae, but the upkeep and administration of the Delphian temple became its main purpose. The league consisted of I 2 tribes, mainly in central
and northern Greece. At the beginning of the sixth century Delphi was dominated and the shrine was exploited by the neighbouring
polis
of Kirrha. The
Amphictyony invoked the penalties of sacrilege against Kirrha, de clared a holy war, and duly annihilated her.u It was the first of the Sacred Wars, fought by the Amphictyony against one or more of its members on behalf of the Pythian Apollo. The Sacred Wars are not comparable to the Crusades. They were punitive wars within a religious league instead of a religious war against an alien civiliza tion, and their circumstances were parochial rather than ecumenical. The Second Sacred War was begun by the Phocian seizure of Delphi in about 449, which prompted the intervention of Sparta and Athens already mentioned. But the Third (355-46) gave Philip of Macedon the opportunity to intervene in Central Greece, and the Fourth (34o-3 6) provided the occasion for his conquest of Thebes and Athens, the remaining great powers. The members of the Amphictyony were bound by an oath, not to destroy any
polis of the Amphictyons,
nor starve it out, nor
cut off its running water in war or in peace; and if anyone should violate this oath, to march against him and call up [ ? ] the
poleis;
and if anyone plunders the shrine of the god, or abets plunder, or has any designs against the sanctuary, to punish him with hand and foot and voice and all one's power•13 This oath was the foundation and almost the summary of what international law the Greeks possessed. Modern pacifist writers have praised the moral sense of the Greeks for declaring that their water-supplies should be mutually inviolable. But it seems that the oath was practically ineffective, since its imputed violation by one party released the others from its obligations. The First Sacred War is said to have been brought to an end by a stratagem suggested by Solon : first he diverted the river that supplied water to Kirrha, and
r
The states-system of Hellas
(
when this was not decisive, he allowed it to resume its course and
. pMsoned it with hellebore, which disabled the defenders.18 It might almost be said that Thucydides' history of the greatest of · - Greek wars is intended to show that the customs of war were minimal and that they were generally disregarded, at least by Athens . The only restraints on savagery were not accepted custom nor agreed · law, but a dim fear of committing impiety on the part of the con - lel'Vatives, and prudential calculations on the part of the progressives . . It was considerations of the latter sort that made the Athenians JJCVe:rse their original decision to destroy Mytilene by killing the men and selling the women and children into slavery ; considerations of the former sort, urged by the Melians, failed to deter the Athenians from inflicting this fate on Melos. There is a famous passage in the Republic which has been re prded as one of the earliest pleas for the rule of Jaw in international relations. The discussion turns to ' how our soldiers will deal with enemies '. It is agreed that the enslavement of Greeks by Greeks, the stripping of corpses on the battlefield, the ravaging of land and the burning of houses, ought to be abolished. A distinction is made between war (polemos) 'when Greeks fight with barbarians, whom we may call their natural enemies ', and civil strife or stasis as the appropriate term for dissension within Hellas. ' Is not the city that you are planning to be a Hellenic city ? and won't the inhabitants be philhellenes, lovers of Hellas, and won't they regard all Hellas as their fatherland, where they share in one common religion with the rest ? '17 But this part of the discussion occupies three pages out of 300 a fair reflection of the proportion of Greek writing about political theory that is given to international relations. For the Greeks, the object of systematic social thought was the polis itself, not classes within the polis nor the states-system of which it was a part. Moreover, what is under discussion is the ideal state, which may or may not be capable of realization. A cardinal difference between the Hellenic and modern Western states-systems is that the Hellenic system had no notion of interna tional law. The Greeks did not conceive of the polis as possessing rights, and being subject to obligations. Partly this was because of the early development of the polis as the final term of human organi zation already alluded to. Partly it was because they did not have the enormous inheritance of legal codes, legal thinking and legal practice .
-
SyJtems of States
which modern Europe derived from the Civilians and Canonists, and out of which the rules of nascent international society were educed. There was no Greek Vitoria or Grotius. The general absence of legal norms from the Greek conception of their states-system rna y be illustrated from their procedures for the peaceful settlement of disputes. This practice apparent! y became common from the seventh century onwards, and we have fairly complete evidence (mainly epigraphic) of 8 I such transactions. Thucydides makes it clear that the Thirty Years Peace of 446 be tween Athens and Sparta provided for the conciliation of disputes, and that Pericles gained a moral advantage in the diplomatic nega. tiations preceding the Peloponnesian War by emphasizing the Spartans' refusal to honour the treaty in this respect.18 Thucydides gives the texts of the armistice of 4 2 3 and of the Peace of N icias of 421, both of which contained a conciliation clause ;19 he also records Argos in 4 1 8 as offering ' a fair and impartial arbitration of any complaint which the Lacedaemonians had against the Argives '. Modern internationalist writers are accustomed to treat these provi sions as examples of ' arbitration ' in the proper sense, but generally this seems a mistranslation of the key-word dike, which means only the determining of right by appropriate proceedings. For example, the clause in the armistice of 42 3 runs : 'You shall go to law (dike) with us, and we with you, in accordance with ancestral custom, settling our disputes by peaceful means (dike) instead of war '. Most of these instances were of conciliation rather than arbitration. When impartial third parties were appealed to - another city or the Delphic Oracle - they were expected to exercise wide discretion, to think in terms of equity rather than law, to make a moral rather than a legal decision, to re-establish friendship between the disputing states rather than to achieve a technically satisfactory settlement of the dispute itself. The only body of international law the Greeks developed was the Rhodian maritime law, but this was in Hellenistic times. The Delphic Amphictyony was one among a number of amphic tyonies or leagues connected with temples and the maintenance of cults. But as the Temple of the Pythian Apollo was the most impor tant shrine in Hellas, so the Delphic Amphictyony became the most important league. Transcending its local origins, it acquired a Panhellenic character, and became the only international organiza20
53
tion which had a claim to be co-extensive with the states-system. Yet its primary function remained religious ; Freeman compares it to an
Ecclesiastical Synod in rdation to Western Christendom. 2 1 The Reformation prevented modern Europe from having any counterpart to the long and continuous history of the Delphic Amphictyony.
Originally it was composed of 1 2 tribes, having arisen before the full development of the polis. Each had two votes in the assembly
which took place twice a year. The constitution of the Amphictyony seems to have endured unchanged, when most of the members had
sunk into petty tribes some of which were not even independent
political communities, while the Dorian and Ionic tribes had fathered great powers like Sparta and Athens. It had small political impor tance, or the archaic constitution would not have survived. Thessal y dominated it in the sixth century, Sparta thereafter. After the defeat
·of the Persian invasion, Sparta proposed that the Amphictyony
should expel from membership all cities which had collaborated with the Persians (this was aimed at Thebes and Thessal y) and even
those which had remained neutral (this was aimed at Argos). This
attempt to capture the Amphictyony was prevented by the diplomacy of Themistocles.32 It may be characteristic of the difference between the sluggish defensiveness of Sparta's foreign policy and the resource
ful aggressiveness of Philip's, that Sparta apparently made no diplomatic use of the Amphictyonic League in the Peloponnesian War, while Philip employed it as a means for subverting Greece. At
the end of the Third Sacred War in 3 4 6 the votes of the Phocians were transferred to Philip and his descendants, 28 the first recorded change in the ancient constitution, a monarch replacing a tribe. But the 24 votes remained until Augustus, after founding Nicopolis to commemorate his victory at Actium, enlarged the Amphictyon y to include Nicopolis with six votes.
3. DIPLOMATIC SYSTEM The master-institution of the modern Western states-system is the diplomatic network of resident embassies, reciprocally exchanged. This Italian invention seems to be unique, and found in no other civilization. The Greeks did not know it. Their counterpart was proxeny. The traditional translations of
Systems of States
54
proxmos are consul ', agent', or ' resident ', none of which is ade quate. The ess ence of the modern diplomatic system is that a government sends one of its own countrymen abroad to represent its interests, and that he is accorded certain agreed immunities and privileges by the government to whom he is accredited. The essence of the proxeny was that a polis conferred guest-friendship on a citizen of another polis, on condition that he would help and protect the citizens of the first polis when they visited the other. In the modern system, the diplomatic representative is the subj ect and servant of the government that sends him, and diplomatic privileges are accorded, in conformity with international law and custom, by the state that receives him. In the ancient system, the proxenos is a citizen of the polis with which links are sought, and has to be wooed; diplomatic privileges are conferred by the foreign polis which see ks his services. We know something of the privileges which Athenian proxenoi en joyed when they visited Athens: they included equality with citizens in taxation (instead of being subject like other foreigners to higher taxes), and a front seat at the public games. Proxeny is found as early as the beginning of the sixth cenrury. Probably the office was originally self-chosen: Thucydides mentions an example of a volunteer-proxmos of the Athenians in Corcyra, who combined the role with leadership of the popular party.2• But the office became formalized, and a matter of appointment. At Athens and most Greek states, every other state chose its own proxenos. At totalitarian Sparta, the proxmoi were appointed by the Spartan authorities themselves.2 11 The most celebrated Athenian proxenos was the poet Pindar in Thebes. The most celebrated proxenoi of another state in Athens were Kimon and Alcibiades, who in their generation were diplomatic agents for Sparta. The function of proxeny was sometimes exercised by whole families and became hereditary. 2 8 In the Laws Plato says ' I t is probably the universal experience of boys anywhere that when they are told they are proxenoi for a certain state, they conceive an affection for that state from earliest youth, and each regards it as a second fatherland, next only to his own '.2 1 It is not easy to assess the difference between proxeny and the modern diplomatic system. The following comments may be offered. First, proxeny by itself was never enough. The chief duty of the proxenos was to entertain and help the citizens of the polis for which •
•
The states-system of Helkls
55
he acted when they visited the polis of which he was a citizen and where he lived. ' You are their proxenos, and their foremost citizens are always being entertained at your house '. 28 He could not con tinuous!y represent the interests of the polis for which he was proxenos, in the manner of a modern diplomatist, since he was not in the confidence of that polis and did not receive instructions from it. Second, it was a consequence of this that when major issues of policy had to be argued between one polis and another, an envoy or ambassador (angelos, presbys) was sent. These seem to have been the agents of diplomatic negotiation in the political sense. Thucydides is full of examples of the representative of one state arriving in another, and often stating his own state's case before the assembly of the state he visits. This was the equivalent of a modern ambassador's being received by a foreign minister, not of an honorific address by an admired foreigner to a joint session of Congress. The proxenos in such circumstances had the special duty of giving hospitality to the ambassador. Third, an influential proxenos might neverthdess count for much in improving commercial relations between two states. 29 Fourth, the proxenos of a great power was likd y to be the local representative of that power's ideological interests, the local leader of its potential fifth column. The Spartan proxenoi in Athens were the leading laconizers. The Athenian proxenoi were the leaders of the democratic faction, as in the case of the Athenian proxenos in Corcyra mentioned above. 80 This is a function for which modern international politics has often had to supplement the diplomatic system. Fifth, the logical culmination of proxeny was the grant of citizenship to the proxenos by the state in whose interests he acted. •When, as was frequently the case from the fourth century on, proxeny was conferred together with the citizenship, and when it became possible to hold more than one citizenship at the same time, the end was reached, and the true meaning of the institution was lost. Beside it, and replacing it, came the honour of a golden wreath or a statue '.81 Thus Churchill (a hereditary half-American) has been a kind of United States proxenos in Britain. What is the correspon ding logical culmination of the modern diplomatic system ? Is it the position achieved by a Stratford Canning at Constantinople, and by a Soviet ambassador at Warsaw and Bucharest ? Should we regard proxeny as a more primitive system of
Systems of States international intercourse than modern diplomatic representation,. and say that as proxeny required to be supplemented by the sending of embassies
ad hoc,
so
modern diplomatic representation has required
to be supplemented by conferences of foreign ministers or heads of states ? Or should we say, rather, that the Hellenic states--system was not built upon the same theory of representation as the modern states-system . The modern ambassador government, as the prince or
represents his prince or his government represents its subjects or
citizens in the international community ; conceptions unknown in ancient Greece. The modern system is weak in giving expression to the sympathy of individuals for foreign peoples, exemplified by the concern of many Victorian Englishmen for United Italy, of R. W. Seton-Watson for the Central European and Balkan nations, of
C. A. Macartney for Hungary, of T. E. Lawrence for the Arabs, of Denis Brogan (honorary citizen of La Roche Blanche, Puy-de-Dome) for France as well as the United States. Such sympathies in the modern world are eccentric, slightly suspect, and mainly confined to scholars. It was precisely these sympathies that the Hellenic system of proxeny institutionalized.
4. HEGEMONIES AND THE BALANCE OF POWER The Greek Middle Ages show the dim oudines of a succession of political hegemonies. Argos was supreme in the Peloponnese in the seventh century. Thucydides traces the sequence of thalassocracies since Agamemnon of Mycenae, with Corinth the most important. But from the sixth century Sparta was the leading state, with a recognized primacy as ' president of Greece ',
prostates tes Hellados. 32
This was based on her military supremacy, and on the awe or admiration felt for her Prussian constitution. She intervened freely in other states to overthrow tyrants and restore conservative aristo cracies. And in the sixth century she organized her predominance in a
Hellas-wide coalition. This was the alliance usually called ' the Peloponnesian league ' -
misleading! y, since it extended beyond the limits of the Peloponnese. Its contemporary description was ' the Lacedaemonians and their Allies ' . It was a complex of bilateral defensive military alliances contracted between Sparta and other states; the military command
The states-system of Helias
57
-s to have been automatically in the hands of Sparta. In modern Bwopean terms, a predominant power organizing its hegemony through an alliance appears odd : the predominant powers of the modern states-system have in general been lone wolves, and alliances have been the instruments of the supporters of a balance of power. Against whom was the Spartan alliance, and what interests did it .erve ? The answer seems threefold. First, it was against the serf majority of conquered Helots and Messenians within the Spartan state itself. Sparta affords perhaps the clearest example in history of the primacy of domestic policy, since her domestic policy was nothing but the conduct of a permanent war by the Spartiates against the subjugated majority of the population ; and this preoccupation governed every other aspect of policy. The earliest of her recorded alliances, with Tegea, bound the Tegeans to expel Messenians from their territory. Second, it was against Argos, Sparta's inveterate enemy, the only state in the Peloponnese that could sometimes play the part of a military rival. Third, it expressed the international oligarchic interest, threatened everywhere by the appearance of tyrants who promoted the interests of the rising hoplite middle class. The alliance only became operative in time of war, but its existence was bound to influence politics generally, and to have what the Spartans regarded as a ' stabilizing' effect. Thus in 5 1 o Sparta intervened by force in Athens to ' liberate ' the city from her tyrants; the nobles proceeded to reorganize the government, and Athens probably joined the Spartan alliance. Immediately after this, proposing to intervene again in Athens, Sparta summoned a conference of her allies, and found them unani mous against her." Henceforward the congress of the allies appar ently became a regular feature of the alliance. In the debates recorded by Thucydides before the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War, one finds the Peloponnesian league arriving at its decision by a double process : a debate in the Lacedaemonian assembly, which decides policy for Sparta, the head of the league; and a concurrent debate in a congress of the allies held at Sparta, where each ally (Sparta in cluded) has a single vote. Thus, at the moment of the Persian invasion, which was the decisive historical experience of the Greeks, the Hellenic states system has two organs. One is the Delphic Amphictyony, which is nearly Panhdlenic but not political, and so irre_levant to the crisis. as
ss
Systems of States
The other is the Spartan alliance, which is political but not Pan hellenic. And the decisive circumstance is that the Hellenic states system has split wide open. Most of the states of northern Greece have offered submission to Xerxes, and half the remainder are sitting on the fence. Now there emerges a new and distinct coalition. It is described as ' the Greeks who declared war on the barbarian ', 38 and ' the Greeks who had chosen the better part for Hellas '.56 These states send delegates to a Panhellen.ic congress at the Isthmus, i.e. Corinth . Most historians have assumed that there was only one congress that coordinated Greek resistance. N. G. L. Hanunond suggests that there were two. 57 First, a meeting in Sparta at Hellenium. 88 Here ' the Greeks that had the better purpose for Hellas ' pledged them selves to resist the Persians jointly, agreed on post-war measures against the Greeks who had voluntarily submitted to Persia, and ' resolved in debate to make an end of all their feuds and their wars against each other, from whatever cause arising '." They also sent envoys to Argos, Syracuse, Corcyra and Crete, asking for military support, ' for they hoped that since the danger threatened all Hellenes alike, all Hellenes might cooperate for one common end ', 4 0 and they agreed on a joint command, in the hands of Sparta . There was a move to give the naval command to Athens, but the allies (Sparta's allies, or the other states in the new coalition ?) said that if Sparta were not their leader they would rather break up the fleet that was preparing than be led by the Athenians ; and the Athenians waived their claim. 41 These measures having been taken at the preliminary congress, if indeed it was a separate gathering, a congress assembled at the Isthmus 'of delegates from all the Greek states that were loyal to the common cause of Hellas '." 2 Several questions can now be asked. First, how distinct was the new coalition from the Spartan alliance ? If there was a preliminary congress at Sparta, it was presumably summoned on Sparta's initia tive. Moreover, the envoys to Syracuse come in the name of ' Sparta and her allies ',45 just as later, when the crisis is nearly over, ' Sparta and her allies ' offer refuge to Athenian non-combatants as an inducement to Athens not to sign a separate peace."" Two things may be set against this. From the first mention of the Greeks who decide to stake everything on resisting the Persians, Herodotus describes them consistently by a different form of words.u If ' Sparta
59
The states-system of Hellas and
her allies ' is a technical term, then its replacement by another term must be given equal weight. Moreover (and Herodotus em
phasizes that what he says will be unpopular), it was the Athenian
decision to resist that was decisive. ' By choosing that Hellas should
remain free they and none others roused all the rest of the Greeks
who had not gone over to the Persians, and did under heaven beat the King o£1 '."8 This may be a little unfair to Sparta ; at least it is not a
description of the Spartan alliance in action. Second, what was the Panhdlenic character of the new coalition ?
It is described henceforward as ' the Hellenes '
tout court
-
as if the
states--system had become fused into a united nation. This is the coalition (acting through its Congress ?) which wins the war. It decides strategy, appoints to the command, levies taxes on its mem
bers.47 It culminates after victory in a general assembly of the Hellenes, which decides on an annual commemorative meeting at Plataea of delegates from the whole of Hellas, and institutes festival games of deliverance for every fourth year. "8 Third, what qualifications of its Panhellenic character have to be made ? It must be admitted that it was something of a fiction. Only potentially did the coalition represent all Hellas. One of its pre occupations was suitable penalties against states which were not
supporting the common cause."9 Only 3 I states took part in the war :
their names were inscribed, after the crowning victory of Plataea, on the bronze pedestal of three intertwined snakes which was dedicated at Delphi as first fruits of the spoils won from the enemy, and which
still stands in the Hippodrome in Istanbul .Go So these 3 I must have been a very small proportion of the total membership of the Hellenic states-system, and Themistocles himself used their fewness as an argument against the Spartan proposal in the Amphictyonic league to disenfranchise the rest. If the coalition became inclusive, it was because the majority of states climbed on the bandwaggon when victory was in sight. Nevertheless, in Hellenic tradition the league against the Persians marked the highest point of unity and cooperation ever achieved by the Hellenic states-system. And thenceforward the configuration of the states-system was altogether different from what had gone before. The Persians had been driven back beyond the Hellespont, but the war went on - until the Peace of Kallias in
44 9 ·
Athens took over
the leadership from Sparta, and reorganized the Panhellenic alliance
6o
Systems of States
on a permanent basis as the Confederacy of Delos. The two alliances, the Spartan and the Panhellenic, had largely overlapped ; now they became disentangled from one another. The traditional Spartan hegemony was replaced by a diarchy ; Sparta retained her continental supremacy, but conceded Athenian supremacy at sea ; the parmership of the two great powers which had defeated the Persian invasion was institutionalized. The conservative party in Athens, led by Kimon, hdd to this tradition. It was summed up in the only frag ment of Kim on's oratory which has survived, when he persuaded the Athenian assembly to respond to an appeal from Sparta for military assistance against her subject population : ' you should not allow Hellas to be crippled, nor our own Polis to be robbed of its yoke fellow '. 81 But several years before this speech was made, Spartan policy had already been prompted by dislike and fear of the way Athens was transforming the Delian Confederacy into an empire. Thasos had revolted from Athens and tried to secede from the Confederacy, and Sparta had secretly promised the Thasians the help for which they appealed, though circumstances prevented its being given. 5 2 When the final breach between Athens and Sparta occurred in 461, the Athenians ' abrogated the alliance which they had made with Sparta against the Persians, and entered into an alliance with her enemy Argos'.58 This was the end of even the pretence of Hellenic unity. It had lasted 40 years. There followed the classic example of what from the standpoint of the states-system as a whole is an unstable diarch y, or from the stand point of the competitors is a rivalry of hegemonies. Athens played the role of Prussia within the Germanic Body, of the Soviet Union within the United Nations. The latter parallel has been noticed with misgiving by contemporary American writers. For Athens versus Sparta is also the classic instance in history of a rivalry where our sympathies are on the side of the restless, aggressive, imperialist power, and against the quiescent, law-abiding, status quo power. Political leadership in Athens had passed from Kimon to his young rival Pericles, who aimed at Athens' becoming in Hellas what Sparta used to be before the Persian Invasion. In the First Peloponnesia.11 War (459-445 ) Athens put forth her greatest strength. She con tinued to wage the Persian War, in Cyprus, Phoenicia and Egypt. At the same time, challenging Sparta at Sparta's own game, she con quered a land empire in Central Greece. The gigantic effort of war
The states-system of Hellas f.��? . · lli.i �twa fronts wa� too much for her.. She made . peace with Persi� in lt9, and then, cnppled �y a revolt tn the empue, made the T�trty �� Truce with Sparta tn 445· But before the war ended, Pencles ... . . I
' ' .
�ed
a project for reorganizing the states-system which showed jl·more than Napoleonic grandeu r.
; · : By way of inciting the Athenians to cherish yet loftier thoughts aod to think themselves worthy of great achievements, he intro duccd a decree in the assembly, that all Hellenes wheresoever ·
·,.
·
.
resident in Europe or Asia, small and large poleis alike, should be ' . invited to send delegates to a Congress at Athens. The agenda was to be : (a) the Hellenic sanctuaries which the Barbarians had burnt down [primarily those on the Acropolis, still unrestored ] ; (b) the sacrifices due to the gods in the name of Hellas, in fulfilment of vows made during the war with the Barbarians ; (c) maritime security, that all might sail the sea fearlessly and keep the peace.11'
Commissioners were sent all over mainland Greece, the Aegean
islands and Ionia, from Byzantium to the Peloponnese. But Sparta
.�aged to wreck the plan, and the congress did not meet. It was the boldest attempt Athens made to institutionalize her hegemony. With its failure, she fell back on other measures. The organization of her empire was tightened up ; the Parthenon was built from the tribute of her allies instead of from Panhellenic contributions ; the uneasy diarchy with Sparta was provisionally accepted. 'The dualism had now to be accepted until it could be smashed ' .115 It was smashed in the second, or great, Peloponnesian War ; but by the defeat of Athens herself instead of Sparta. Athens was defeated
for two reasons : because she failed· in her grandiose attempt to
conquer the Greater Hellas of Sicily, to call in the new world of the West to redress the balance of the old ; and because Sparta called in the ancient enemy of the East, Persia. As a result, Sparta emerged once more as hegemon of Hellas. She was the dominant power from the Athenian surrender in 404 down to her own defeat of Leuctra in 37 I by Thebes. But the great wars of the fifth century had brought changes to the states-system which were reflected in the more squalid conflicts of the fourth century. All the poleis had become coarsened and weakened, bereft of broad policies and grand conceptions, and incapable of carrying them out had they had them . The Pelopon nesian War had left Sparta victorious, but depopulated, impoverished
Systems of States and corrupted. Her restored hegemony was a different matter frorn the traditional leadership of the sixth century. It was brutal, oppres sive and clumsily Machiavellian, and its disappearance left no regrets. After their victory at Leuctra the Thebans liberated Messenia, which destroyed the economic basis of the Spartan state, and ended its role as a great power. The states-system had now become more flexible ; the weights moved more £reel y. The dominant power did not have the towering ascendancy over its fellows that Athens and Sparta had both had in the days of the diarchy. A multiple balance of power had come into being, and Sparta, Athens, Thebes, Argos and Corinth combine and recombine against one another with an even greater absence of continuity or principle than the Italian and Transalpine powers in the time of Charles VIII and Louis XII . But it is · now that the idea of collective security can, for the first and last time, be detected. The Theban supremacy lasted for half a generation after Leuctra, and was punctuated by another great but indecisive battle against an alliance of Sparta, Athens and minor powers at Mantinea in 362. After it, the exhausted states made a general peace and alliance. It seems that the new league was styled ' the Hellenes ', like the Pan hellenic League of 4 So, and that it embodied the principle that an attack on one was an attack on all. 56 Is it significant that the principle of collective security is recognized at the very beginning of the modern European states-system, in the Most Holy League that
accompanied the Peace of Lodi in 1454, while it does not appear in Greek international politics until the Hellenic states--system is ex hausted and near its end ? The new league was entirely ineffective, as every system of collec tive security has been. The inheritor and transformer of the states
system was already at hand : a vigorous outsider, a new national monarchy instead of an effete polis, and she swept the board. Philip took the opportunity of the Third Sacred War to intervene in Hellenic politics in 3 5 3 · He exploited the procrastinations and feuds of the Greek powers so skilfully that in 33 8, ' at that dishonest victory, at Chaeronea, fatal to liberty ', the Macedonian conquest of Greece was complete. He now summoned a congress of the Greek States at Corinth. All attended except Sparta, still resentfully sulking. A new league was formed, the Hellenic league. It embodied a general mutual guarantee of the independence and constitution of each
The states-system of He/las i
.ber, and the principle of collective security. It had a council, =�ding by a majority, on which members had unequal representa 'lt)n according to their importance. The council was a federal itrhority with unlimited competence in organizing war, finance, and
i;bitrating disputes. So much to restore peace and security within the ..Cttts-system. Hut Philip had wider ends in view. At its first meeting 6e league entered into a perpetual offensive and defensive alliance trith the Macedonian kingdom, declared war on Persia, and elected
·�p
commander-in-chief. To this position, this instrument and thctc aims Alexander succeeded. · Historians make two kinds of judgment on Philip. Some em the Hellenic league, as showing a broad-minded international
phasize
ttatesmanship of a quality that the Hellenic world had not seen since Pericles, and a recognition of the needs and susceptibilities of the
Greek states which Pericles had not shown. Others emphasize the hegemony, and see the Hellenic league as resembling the Bismarck ian constitution of Germany more than the Panhellenic league of 4�0. But two conclusions seem to stand out. One is, that the Hellenic States-system was only redeemed from anarchy by forcible conquest from without. The second is, that the immediate aim of the union once achieved was war against an external enemy. Another aspect of the states-system after the Peloponnesian War must be mentioned : it had a wider geographical range . Commercial activity was more widely diffused throughout the Mediterranean region and economic interdependence increased. There are growing evidences of commercial treaties, trading privileges, international banking, arbitration, etc. All this has its political counterpart. On the one side, Persia had been brought into the balance again; now she was playing the part of a great power in the Hellenic states-system. On the other side, the states of Greater Hellas, in Sicily and Italy, wete being drawn more closely into the system. Here �ere was a great power, in Syracuse. Herodotus says of Gelon, despot of Syra cuse at the time of the Persian Invasion, ' Now the power of Gelon was said to be very great, far greater than that of any Hellenic people ,, 151 and he makes Gelon himself say that his military and naval resources greatly exceed Sparta's.118 Gelon at that time had a simultaneous Carthaginian invasion of Sicily on his hands, and for the next 6o years Syracuse was occupied in extending its power in Sicily and along the Italian coast as far north as Cumae.119 The
Systems of States invitations to Pericles's Panhellenic congress did not include the Western Greeks, but Pericles had a policy of western expansion for Athens. Perhaps one of its aims was to impede the unification of Sicily by Syracuse, which was a Dorian state and sympathetic to Sparta. When the Peloponnesian War began the Dorian states of Sicily, with the one exception of Camarina, joined the Spartan alliance, but took no active part. eo AI though nominal, this seems to be the first recorded involvement of the Western Greeks in the international politics of the Old Greek World. Thucydides does not mention it as a justification for Athenian intervention in Sicily ; indeed, he makes Hermocrates say that the Athenians rightly despise the Syracusans for not having helped Sparta to destroy them.11 Athens sent her first expedition to Sicily in 4 2 7 , and a stronger one the next year. The Sicilian states reacted by convening a conference at Gela and sinking their own differences. Here the Syracusan states man Hermocrates made an appeal for continental solidarity : We are neighbours, and dwell together in a single land encircled by the sea, and are called by a single name - Sicilians. We shall have our wars, no doubt, whenever occasion arises, and we shall make peace again by agreement among ourselves. But when foreigners invade us, we shall if we are wise always act in concert, and repel them, since an injury to one of us endangers us all. And let us never hencefotward invite their intervention, whether as allies or mediators. If we can agree on this, we shall not deprive Sicily of two things that are immediate! y essential - getting rid of the Athenians and our civil wars. And for the future we shall inhabit a land that is free and in less danger from abroad. 82 It was perhaps the last occasion for a century on which the doctrine of Greater Hellas as an alter orbis could carry conviction. When Nicias appealed to it in the Athenian assembly as an argument against the Sicilian Expedition8 8 he was voted down. Thucydides does not offer an estimate of the strength of Syracuse compared with that of the two great powers. But he emphasizes that Syracuse as a polis was as large as Athens, u and that Athens was now attacking a power, not only of her own size, but of her own kind: a resourceful democracy with a great navy, the opposite of the sluggish, cautious Sparta. The Sicilian Expedition brought Syracuse fully into the war. If a
The states-system of Hellas
pt power is a power which can protect its interests and make its ttrength felt throughout the whole extent of a states-system, the
Athenian disaster in Sicily made Syracuse a Hellenic great power, more definitely than the defeat of the Spanish Armada made England one. Hennocrates urged the Sicilians to take part in finishing Athens olf,18 and in 4 1 2 led a Syracusan fleet into the Aegean to support the new Peloponnesian navy ;68 henceforward they are prominent in the war.17 A Syracusan wrote up the story of the Anabasis before Xenophon's account was published.68 In the same year that Athens surrendered, Dionysius the Great made himself tyrant of Syracuse, and he maintained the alliance with Sparta, sending an expeditionary force to Sparta's aid against Thebes in the Boeotian War.69 Diony· sius's pursuit of prestige at the Olympic festival and in the tragic contests at Athens became as celebrated as the unhappy intervention of Plato in Syracusan domestic politics under Dionysius II. But as Macedon rose to power in the Aegean basin, Greater Hellas sank into isolation again, weakened by social and international conflict. It is only when Alexander has established his world empire and is receiving congratulatory embassies in Babylon that Sicily and Italy reappear in the states--system, and then they are already overshadowed by the rising name of Rome. 70 It might be argued that the Greeks seem to have had a funda mentally hegemonial theory of the states-system. From the sixth century they seem to have thought of it as having a natural leader or president', and they had several terms for this concept prostates tes Hellados , hegemon. It was only under the unparalleled stress of the Persian Invasion that a more collective conception appeared. The outcome was a transient diarchy of Sparta and Athens which quickly resolved itself into a struggle for primacy, leading within 1 50 years to acquiescence in the decisive hegemony of a power which outclassed the rest. And the hegemonial theory was linked with a generally egalitarian assumption about the members of the states-system. This showed itself in the survival of the archaic Am phictyonic constitution. It showed itself, moreover, in a notable contrast with the modern European states-system - the absence of a hierarchic conception of international society. The Greeks do not seem to have had any term corresponding to 'great power ', and the use of the modem phrase in writing about Hellenic politics (as it has been used in this paper) may lead to serious distortions. In modern •
-
66
Systems of States
Europe the idea of a great power is as old as the states-system itself. Was it derived from the aristocratic society in which the states-system grew up ? Again, the Hellenic states-system does not show any developed idea of the balance of power. One or two random examples of the use of the metaphor may illustrate this. Herodotus says that at the moment of the Persian invasion Athenian policy was decisive : ' for whichever side they chose, that way the balance would incline', or ' that would preponderate '. 71 Diodorus says of the Theban-Spartan alliance at the beginning of the First Peloponnesian War, that the Spartans believed ' that if Thebes were strengthened she would be a kind of counterweight, antipalon, to the increasing power of Athens '. 72 (Does the phrase reflect the late Hellenistic ideas of Diodorus's own time, or did he find it in his sources ?) Thucydides, as has often been noticed, is full of comparisons of power in different situations, but never formulates a theory of the balance. When Corcyra sought the alliance of Athens against Corinth, her envoys to Athens clinched their argument thus : The Hellenes have only three navies worth mentioning - yours, ours, and the Corinthian fleet. If now you let two of them be united, by Corinth getting control of ours first, you will have to fight at sea against both Corcyra and the Peloponnesians [whose main naval Power Corinth was] ; but if you ally with us, you will be able to maintain the struggle with your Beet and ours together. 7 3 Here also is the advice that Alcibiades gives to Tissaphernes, which has sometimes been seen as the earliest expression of a policy of ' holding the balance of power ' : he argued that Persia's interest was ' to wear the Hellenes out upon one another. . . . He therefore urged him, first to wear out both sides, then to curtail the power of the
Athenians as much as possible, and finally to get the Peloponnesians out of his country. ' H There is nothing much here for a theory of the balance of power. If Thucydides does not provide one, it is because the Greeks did not possess one. Just as they had no diplomatic system and no public international law, so they had no sense of an equilibrium of power being the foundation and as it were the constitution of international society. In modern Western international relations the three have been interdependent. It is in the subsequent Hellenistic chapter of the
The sttJtes·system of Hellas ._ucient states.system that the first glimmerings of the doctrine of the balance of power appear, in Polybius' description of the policy of Hicro of Syracuse during the Punic Wars : He was convinced that it was in his own interests, both for the security of his Sicilian possessions and for his friendship with Rome, that Carthage should be preserved, and that the stronger Power should not be able to attain its ultimate object entirely without effort. His policy was very wise and sensible. This aspect of affairs should never be neglected, and we should never contri bute to a Power becoming so preponderant that none dare dispute with it even for acknowledged rights.13 But still this is only a glimmering - the starting-point of modern doctrine and practice.
5. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC OPINION It might be a matter for discussion whether a states-system can exist without an international public opinion. If there is no sense of cultural interdependence or common interest between states that come into contact with one another, can they be said to form a system ? If their contacts are continuous and regular, will they not give rise to a sense of interdependence and so to an international public opinion ? Modern history has several instances that raise these questions : for example, the slow extension of the Western diplomatic system to include the Ottoman Empire and the Russian Empire, and the maintenance of international relations across an ideological gulf,
as
with Soviet Russia and Communist China. There was certainly an international public opinion in Hellas. The
international festivals and competitions, the 01 ympic Games and their more frequent lesser counterparts, the Pythian, Isthmian and Nemean Games, the Delphic Amphictyony and the lesser amphic tyonies, were evidence for it. At the same time they revealed how little effect international public opinion had on the actions of states. When we talk about public opinion we usually mean a kind of consensus or collective judgment, a prevalent sentiment of approval or (more likely) disapproval crystallized by current debate. Thus
68
Sysums of States
public opinion, we say, condemned Turkish misrule in the Balkans, or aggressive war after I 9 I 9 ; that it demands (an inverted condem nation) great power negotiations, or disarmament, or the ending of colonial rule. The Greeks had a similar conception of a collective political judgment. The word Thucydides uses for it, with some degree of precision, is eunoia. It means goodwill, approval, sympathy, readiness to help. Thucydides describes the condition of international public opinion at the beginning of the Peloponnesian War in these words : All the rest of Hdlas was in anxious suspense as its two Great Powers came into conflict with each other. . . . International public opinion,
eunoia, .
however, inclined decidedly to the side of the
Spartans, especially since they proclaimed that they were liberating Hellas. Every individual and every
polis was
deeply committed to
helping them in every possible way, whether by word or deed, and each man thought that unless he took a personal share in things the whole effort was being handicapped. So bitter was the general feeling against Athens, some wishing to be delivered from her rule, others afraid of falling under it. 76 Gomme in his
Commentary 71
observes that this sweeping and cate
gorical statement is not borne out by Thucydides' narrative of the war; there is little other evidence of a general enthusiasm for the Spartan cause, though Thucydides repeats the generalization when he describes how, after the Sicilian disaster, neutrals and Pelopon nesians and subject states of Athens ' were more than ever animated by a common eagerness ' to finish off the tyrant city. 7 8 But the statement establishes one pole, so to speak, of the Thucydidean interpretation. The other pole is represented by Pericles' extra ordinary valedictory disquisition on the logic of imperial power. ' Hatred and abhorrence for the moment have always bee n the lot of
those who have aspired to rule over others. But if one has a great aim
in view, this burden of envy must be accepted, and it is wise to accept it. Hatred does not last for long ; but the splendour of the present is the glory of the future stored up in everlasting remem brance. '79 And though on the one hand this defiance of eunoia, of international public opinion, is for Thucydides a mark of the h uhris that brings Athens to ruin, on the other hand he suggests that eunoia is ineffective unless it produces a superiority of power, 80 and that the
The states-system of Hellas
Spartans are interested in conciliating world opinion only in so far as it promotes their own hegemony. 8 1
· . But Thucydides's conception of eunoia has another dimension. The term is used to describe what we should call ideological loyalties, which cut through the states-system horizontally, and attract classes factions in one polis to their counterparts in others. In the Mytilen8Ca.D debate, Diodotus tells the Athenian assembly : ' At present the broad masses, the demos, in every city are well-disposed (eunous, the or
adjective of eunoia) to you. Either they do not support the upper classes in revolting against you, or if compelled to do so they remain
all the time hostile to the rebellion, so that when you use force against the rebels you will have the masses as your allies '. 82 Thucydides repeats it in his famous description of stasis : Practically the whole Hellenic world was convulsed, since in each state the leaders of the democratic factions were at variance with the oligarchs, the former seeking to bring in the Athenians, the latter the Spartans. And while in time of peace they would have had no pretext for asking the intervention of these Powers, nor any inclination to do so, yet now that war had broken out each faction, if it wanted to overthrow the government, found it easy to call in allies, for the discomfiture of its opponents and the promotion of its own cause. And so revolutions brought many calamities in the various states - as happens and always will happen while human nature remains the same, though there may be different degrees of savagery and so on according to circumstances.83 This is one of the great themes of the History, and one of the shock ing characteristics of the war. It also provides perhaps the most striking parallel between the Hellenic states-system and the modern European. Burke saw it as the closest precedertt for the ideological division of Europe by the French Revolution, since unlike the international factions introduced by the Reformation, it was free from the special motive of religion. But Burke also acutely pointed out a contrast between the Hellenic and modern factions. ' Secret cabals and publick alliances were carried on and made, not upon a conformity of general political interests, but for the support and aggrandisement of the two leading states which headed the aristocratick and democratick factions ,. 8 • He implies that the international factions in modern history have had
Systems of States more detachment from the power struggle - that it was only after a hundred years that the Protestant interest in Europe found in Sweden a great power to give it leadership, as Spain was already leader of the Catholic interest. Thucydides, too, sees stasis as a product of inter national war, and ideological loyalties as always subordinate to ' the fundamental motives which inspire the two sides : for Athens, the desire to rule, for the others, the desire to be independent'. &G Brasidas, recognizing that the class-war on the whole worked to the interna tional advantage of Athens, repudiated it when he liberated the cities 88 of Thrace. The Athenians realized that one of their miscalculations in attacking Syracuse was that Syracuse's being a democracy deprived 87 them of the ability to promote a fifth column there. And when Athens was beaten to her knees, 20 years after Brasidas's campaign in Thrace, the triumphant Lysander could sail through the Aegean installing oligarchic governments as agents of Spartan hegemony. In the fourth century there is no writer about international politics with Thucydides's analytical power and intellectual precision. When Xenophon describes the apogee and decline of Sparta's hegemony, he does not use Thucydidean terms, and say that Sparta had flouted the world opinion which had previously helped her to defeat Athens, though his own evidence makes it clear that this had happened. He uses instead the old-fashioned concept of divine retribution. 'One could mention many other incidents, both among Greeks and bar barians, to prove that the gods do not fail to notice wicked and unrighteous actions. Here I will speak of the case under considera tion . Sparta had pledged herself to respect the independence of other states, and then had committed aggression against Thebes by seizing the citadel there. And although Sparta had never before been de feated by any Power, she now was punished by the very Thebans, 88 unaided, who had been thus wronged ' . But as Professor de Romill y has argued, the writers of the fourth century are all engaged in discussing and digesting the experience of
the fifth century : why it is that the Athenian Empire failed, the 89 relation between might and right. The kind of international public opinion that contributes to ideological cleavage grows fainter ; stasis is no longer a feature of international life. But eunoia is constantly discussed. For !socrates the cultivating of eunoia is the true aim of foreign policy. For Demosthenes eunoia is something Athens should attract and organize to arrest the steady advance of Philip's aggres-
The states-system of Helias lion. And at the same time, the meaning of the word eirene was devdoping from simply the opposite of war, a state of peace, into a treaty of peace. The new idea of a common or general peace among all Greek states was appearing, and nine such multilateral pacifica tions have been distinguished .90 Nevertheless, what stands out is the tDta1 inability of international public opinion to affect the march of events. In practical tenns, !socrates failed to influence policy as defin itely as did the post-Kantian peace movements of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The new general peace-treaties were all concerned to guarantee the independence of states ; they did nothing to end the feuds, mitigate the particularism, or promote cooperation. They had the novel feature that they were concluded without time-limit; but they proved more evanescent than the solid ' truces ' of the previous tentury. In circumstances and in character alike Demosthenes was a Churchill manque, who ran away at the battle of Chaeronea, spent another I 5 years in futile opposition to Alexander the Great, and after staging a last unsuccessful revolt sucked poison concealed in the end of his pen and so died. It is with the notion of international public opinion that the study of international relations comes closest to the general culture of the society of states. At this point we become most aware of the prevailing
ideas of the ' world ' whose collective opinion we postulate . In ancient Greece, the notion of international public opinion was expressed by a word, eunoia, importing an emotional and moral disposition to wards some
polis or Nicomachean Ethics,
person. Eunoia, as Aristotle observes in the is the beginning of friendship.91 It is, so to speak, a bilateral impulse ; it does not seem to attain any meaning of the love of mankind in general. The opposite of eunoia is fear. The Mytilenaean delegation which visits Sparta to ask for assistance against Athens describes the relations between their city and Athens in these words : ' They courted us in time of war only because they were afraid of us, while we acted in the same manner towards them in time of peace. Good faith, which in most cases is made steadfast by good will, eunoia, was in our case made secure by fear '. 92 Or the opposite of eunoia is hatred. ' In place of the eunoia which was accorded us by our allies ', wrote I socrates, ' and of the good repute in which we had been hdd by the rest of Hellas, our empire brought us so much hatred that our country scarcely escaped being enslaved '. 98 I have wondered if it would be accurate to exemplify the greater
Systems of States richness and complexity of modern international thought by saying that, in the modern states·system, the notion of international public opinion comes dose to meaning the spirit and purpose of mankind. Its connotation is multilateral ; its objects are general and universal. And it implies, not simply benevolence towards some agent in international society, but adherence to some standard of action. We often use the phrase with the suggestion of a moralistic or revolution ary condemnation of a practice on the ground that it violates a principle or falls short of an ideal. World opinion condemns apart heid, we like to say, or demands an end to American bombing in Vietnam. The antithesis of world opinion, therefore, is no longer simply a primary emotion like hate or fear. It is the condition of moral obtuseness or delinquency which public opinion seeks to correct. The chief mark of this condition is absence of knowledge and information, whether through sloth or secrecy ; for it is the theory of public opinion that all it needs for its health and growth is a free flow of information. Hence Kant's transcendental formula of public law, that all actions relating to the rights of other men are unjust unless their principle is consistent with publicity. u Hence Wilson's speech about the draft Covenant at the Peace Conference in 1 9 1 9 : ' throughout this instrument we are depending primarily and chiefly upon one great force, and that is the moral force of the public opinion of the world, the cleansing and clarifying and com pelling influences of publicity, so that intrigues can no longer have their coverts, so that designs that are sinister can at any time be drawn into the open, so that those things that are destroyed by the light may be promptly destroyed by the overwhelming light of the universal expression of the condemnation of the world' . This is a statement that would have puzzled, but in different ways, Thucy dides and Plato, !socrates and Demosthenes.
3 Hellas and Persia
When w� contemplate the Hellenic states-system we are likely to be �truck by two features of it. First, it was the most complex and highly organized of which history seems to have record before our
own. This makes for comparison with the modern European states
system. Second, it was to an unparalleled extent dominated by a neighbouring world-empire. This makes for contrast. At the begin ning of fully historic times, the Persian Empire made a deliberate attempt to conquer Hellas. Five generations later, a Hellenic power, ·which had unified the Hellenic states-system by force, conquered and transformed the Persian Empire. It seems to be the story of a unique symbiosis. We have to ask, were Bellas and Persia members
of a common states-system ? Or was Hellas a states-system with an
external suzerain power ? The memory of Marathon and Salamis, and the Herodotean interpretation of the Persian Wars, suggest at once the answer no to
both questions.
The flying Mede, his shaftless broken bow; The fiery Greek, his red pursuing spear This is the classic picture of the triumph of Europe over Asia, of freedom over despotism, of civilization over barbarism. There was a great deal of mutual incomprehension between Greeks and Persians. They were at the opposite extremes of political experience. After their military victories the Greeks came to enter
tain
more contemptuous opinions about the Persian Empire, but a
basic feeling about it was wonder at its mere extent. It may be illustrated from Xenophon's Cyropa�dia, a puzzling book, a roman tic ·biography of Cyrus the Great and a philosophical case-study in the art of ruling, suffused with a sense of the magnitude of the Empire. Cyrus, says Xenophon, was unlike all other kings. They are well content if they can maintain themselves in power over their own subjects. Thus the peoples of Europe - Scythians, Thracians,
74
Systems of States
Illyrians - as well as the Greeks have always been free and inde pendent. But Cyrus by art and conquest acquired dominion over ' very many nations of which one could not even tell the names '. He ruled over these nations, even though they did not speak the same language as he, nor the same as one another. And he was able to cover so vast a region with the fear which he inspired, that he astonished all men and no one tried to withstand him. And he was able to inspire in all men so great a desire to please him, that they always wanted to be governed by his judgment. Moreover, the peoples he made dependent upon himself were so many that it is a difficult matter to travel to them all, in whatever direction one begins one's journey from the palace - whether towards the east or the west, the north or the south.1 This is the antithesis of the Aristotelian optimum size of the polis. And on the other hand, Persian contempt for the agora-centred commercially-inspired Kleinstaaterei of the Greeks is suggested by a famous story in Herodotus. Sparta had sent a diplomatic mission to Cyrus at Sardis, warning him to abstain from any hostile act against the Ionian Greek states, since Sparta would not tolerate it. The story goes on that when the envoy had made this d�marche, Cyrus asked the Greeks in his entourage, 'Who are the Spartans ? How many divisions do they have ? ' While he was making the inquiry, he remarked to the Spartan envoy, ' I have never yet felt afraid of people who have a place reserved in the middle of their towns for meeting together and cheating each other on oath. These folk, unless there is something wrong with me, will soon have not merely the Ionians' troubles to chatter about, but their own '. These words of Cyrus's were a hit at the Hellenes in general, because they have market-places for buying and selling. The Persians never buy in the open market, and indeed do not have a single agora in the empire. 2 It was out of such elements as these that Herodotus wove his theme of an eternal conflict between East and West going back to the Troj an War, a struggle between the vast numbers, indefinite terri torial extent, and political shapelessness of Oriental despotism, and the compact, limited, maritime, free communities of Europe. It is a theme that seems to explain recurring features of European history,
Hellas and Persia
75
when Christendom has been threatened by the Abbasid Caliphate and the Mongol Empire, the West by the Ottoman Turks and the Soviet Union ; and it has influenced historians down to Karl Witt
fogd
and Northcote Parkinson. But the period of the Persian Wars
itself is capable of a less heroic interpretation than Herodotus gives
it, and events after Herodotus' time show a more complicated picture. It is necessary to consider the extent to which the Greek states
accepted Persian suzerainty, the phenomenon of medizing, the Greek attitude to the Persians even after the Persian Wars, the sub sequent role of the Persian Empire in the international affairs of Hdlas, and the final Greek conquest of Persia. It is also necessary to
glance at the cognate question of Carthage.
1 . PERSIA AS SUZERAIN POWER The political ambiguity of the Hellenic states-system is the conse quence of its geographical extension sprawling on both sides of the Aegean (not to mention the Greater Hellas in the western Mediter ranean). The Ionian Greeks along the Anatolian seaboard were likely to be dominated by a great power with continental resources in the hinterland, unless they joined forces in a federation or union, which they sometimes talked of but conspicuously failed to do any thing about. (In exacd y the same way the peninsular Greeks, given their own failure to unite, were in the long run due to be dominated by a great power in the Balkan hinterland.) The Persian Wars arose because a large part of the Hellenic states-system, having been tribu tary to Persia for some so years, revolted. Herodotus says that all Greek states had been free and independent
until the time of Croesus, king of Lydia. He it was who first made the Ionian coastal cities dependent, though he failed to subdue the island states. s Lydia was a familiar neighbour to the Greeks, com mercial! y dependent on them and partial! y Hellenized, with a tradition of devotion to the Delphic Oracle, and herself almost a member of the Hellenic states-system. Croesus was remembered afterwards, at any rate in contrast with the Persians who succeeded him, as a mild and good ruler : ' the kindly generosity of Croesus
fadeth not ', says Pindar So years later.• Croesus had friendly rela tions with Sparta, and when the Persian threat developed took the
Systems of States initiative in making a Spartan alliance.8 Cyrus, on his side, in his diplomatic preparations for the Lydian war, invited the Ionian states to revolt against Croesus. They refused. After the defeat of Lydia, they offered to become Cyrus's subjects on the same terms as those which they had had under Croesus. It was Cyrus's turn to refuse : now
he
would make the conditions. The Ionian states called a
hurried conference at the Panionium, their international centre, and sent to Sparta for help. 6 In this way the Greeks became the Persian Empire's north-west frontier problem. Cyrus remained in Sardis long enough to reject the diplomatic representations of Sparta ; then he marched east again. ' At first he gave the lonians no high priority, ' says Herodotus. ' He had Babylon to think about, and Bactria, and the Sacae on the north-east frontier, and Egypt. He intended to conduct campaigns against them in person and to leave the Ionians to one of his generals ' . 7 At this juncture two of the Seven Sages of antiquity gave advice which showed that political sagacity was not among their qualities. Thales of Miletus, the philosopher, proposed federal union for Ionia. Bias of Priene proposed collective migration to Sardinia followed by political union : ' thus they would escape subjugation for themselves and gain prosperity, possessing the biggest island in the world, and ruling others. But if they stayed in Ionia, he said, he could sec no prospect of independence for them ' .8 Bias's advice was a practical precursor of Gibbon 's speculation that, if a savage conqueror, issuing from the deserts of Tartary, should ' carry slavery and desolation as far as the Atlantic ocean, ten thousand vessels would transport beyond their pursuit the remains of civilized society ; and Europe would revive and flourish in the American world, which is already filled with her colonies and instirutions '. 9 These suggestions of Thales and Bias were as ineffective as those of the Cruces and St Pierres, the Coudenhove-Kalergis and Clarence Streits of every age. Nothing seems to be a more constant feature in the history of the Hellenic as of the Western states-systems than the inability of independent states to make an effective voluntary union so
as to avert an imposed unification by force. The more highly
developed the states-system, the more obstinate the parochialism· of its members. ' Take away the independence of those city-states ', Barraclough has said, ' and it is difficult, if not impossible, to see how what was of enduring value in Greek civilisation could have been
Hellas and Persia
77
secured. In other words, the independence of the city-states had the same roots as Greek civilisation itself; it was ineradicable so long as that civilisation lasted ' .1 0 The Ionians were duly subjugated. The inhabitants of two states migrated
en masse
to avoid the inevitable fate, the Phokaians to
Corsica and the Teians to Thrace. The rest ' were for the second time enslaved : and when Harpagus, the Persian commander, had conquered the Ionians of the mainland, the Ionians of the islands, fearing the same fate, surrendered themselves to Cyrus ' .11 The Persians learned how to take advantage, not only of the lack of unity among the Greek states, but also of class divisions within them. As a rule they supported tyrants, who might represent commercial in terests or the many or the poor, but would owe their position largely to Persian backing.1 2 For nearly
30
years the Persian government was employed on
other frontiers, and the Greek question was quiet. In this interval Samos, under the pirate-tyrant Polycrates, became the greatest power
in
the Aegean.18 Then Darius resumed the Persian advance. He
sent a small naval squadron to make a reconnaissance throughout the Hellenic world. Leaving from Sidon, ' they set sail for Hell as, where they explored and took notes on the coasts to which they came; until having surveyed the greater and more famous parts they reached Tarentum in Italy '. Here they ran into political diffi culties, used threats of Persian intervention, ' and sailed back for Asia, abandoning any attempt to reconnoitre the further parts of Hellas . . . . These Persians were the first who came from Asia into Hell as '. u Soon afterwards Darius conquered Samos, u and Lesbos and Chios accepted Persian suzerainty. With these resources he undertook his first invasion of Europe. A Samian engineer bridged the Bosphorus for the army to advance, and the Ionian fleets sailed in support through the Black Sea and up the delta of the Danube to meet the expedition.16 Darius aimed to establish Persian power on
the north side of the Black Sea, and crossing the Danube advanced some way into the Ukraine. Among his vassals on this campaign was the Athenian Miltiades, now general and tyrant of the Cher sonites of the Hellespont, later to be the victor of Marathon.17 At the end of the campaign Darius left his general Megabazus with a directive to subjugate all the Hellespontine states which had not supported Persia, and then to conquer Thrace. Macedonia also gave
Systems of Staks the symbolic ' earth and water' in token of submission.18 In the years immediately following, Darius reorganized the satrapies of the Empire. In inscriptions at Persepolis and Susa, two new administra tive districts appear. Besides Ionia and ' Those on the Sea ' (i.e. the Aegean island states) there are now ' Those beyond the Sea ' (i.e. roughly what is now European Turkey and Bulgaria) and Skudra (i.e. Thrace and Macedonia).19 Persian power was now established on the north as well as the east of the Aegean. The first offer of submission from the peninsular Greeks in the west came, by an irony, from Athens herself. She had expellee the tyrant Hippias, and was going through a democratic revolution. Sparta threatened to intervene in the interests of oli garchy. The revolutionary government under Cleisthenes sent a delegation to Sardis to ask for Persian hdp. The viceroy made the
usual condition : the giving of earth and water in recognition of Persian suzerainty ; and the envoys consented. But Athenian vassal age to the Persian Empire lasted a shorter time than King John's fealty and homage to the Holy See. When the embassy returned from Sardis the emergency had passed, and the Athenian govern ment could reap the popular advantage of repudiating what it had done, or silently falsify the record later.20 Eight years later the great Ionian Revolt against Persia broke out, and Athens accepted a plea to intervene on the side of the rebels. Perhaps the main cause of the Revolt was hatred of the tyrannies, and Persian statesmanship was never better shown than after the Revolt had been stamped out, when all the Ionian despots were deposed and democracies were set up instead. 2 1 But it was now Darius' policy to end the Greek Question for good and all by bringing peninsular Greece under control ; prestige also required the chastisement of Athens. 22 He controlled the Hellenic states up to and including Macedonia. 2 1 He now sent envoys to every independent state in Hellas demanding submission. All the island states, including Aegina, and many of the mainland states complied. u Herodotus names only Athens and Sparta as refusing the demand. 'The Persian envoys were thrown into the pit for condemned criminals in one city, and into a well in the other, and told to take from there the required earth and water to the King '.25 And the second Persian invasion of Europe was launched, which ended at Marathon. The third Persian invasion of Europe, the Great Invasion, was the
·
79
Hellas and Persia most elaborate!y prepared, and came nearest
to
absorbing what re
mained of the Hellenic states-system. The Greek states under Persian suzerainty furnished their part of the expedition. 2 6 Throughout the campaign the Macedonian king acted as a satrap.27 From Sardis, Xerxes had sent envoys demanding submission from every indepen dent Greek state, excepting only Athens and Sparta because of the fate of Darius's envoys ten years before ; the returning envoys met him when he had reached Thessal y. ' Among those who gave
earth and water were the Thessalians, Dolopes, Erienes, Perrhae
bians, Locrians, Magnesians, Malians, the Achaeans of Phthiotis, Thebes, and all the other states of B�otia except Thespiae and Plataea. These were the peoples about whom the Allies against Persia swore their oath : that if they should be victorious, they would confiscate the possessions of all the Greeks who had voluntarily submitted to Persia, and dedicate them to the god of Delphi '. 28 The majority of the states of the Peloponnese, Herodotus writes, ' sat apart from the war, and if I may speak frankly, were neutral on the side of Persia '. 2 8 The most important of these was Argos, Sparta's hereditary enemy, which had recendy undergone a crushing defeat at Sparta's hands, and now had an understanding with Xerxes, if indeed she had not encouraged Persian intervention. 80 Corcyra sat on the fence; the Cretans refused to help the resistance.81 Gelon the tyrant of Syracuse, who was preoccupied with an imminent Cartha ginian war in Sicily, offered help on condition that he himself should be commander-in-chief. When the Allies refused the condition, Gelon reinsured and sent a squadron, with an appropriate sum of money and a stock of diplomatic phrases, to watch the event of the war from Delphi. If the Persians won, the money was to be offered to them, together with earth and water on behalf of Gelon's dominions. If the Greeks won, the money was to be brought home again.3 2 The power of Persia seemed so inexorable that perhaps half the membership of the Hellenic states-system had submitted to it and half of the remainder were ready to follow suit. This unedifying and perhaps discreditable picture was later blurred by the legend of an eagerness for freedom which ' animated the mass of Greeks ' against Persia ; Demosthenes employed the legend in order to assert the decline of Greek morale in his own day. 38 The truth was told by
the Plataeans when, in the fifth year of the Peloponnesian War, they had to remind Sparta of their services to the common cause
50 years
So
Systems of States
before : ' at that time it was a rare thing for Hellenes
to
oppose their
courage to the might of Xerxes '. 84 Herodotus, writing about the same time, when Hellenic opinion now strongly favoured Sparta against Athens, was constrained to record the conclusion to which his researches had led him, although ' most people will find it invidi ous '. If Athens had given up the struggle, he said, the whole of the Hellenic resistance would have collapsed. Sparta might have fortified the Isthmus and tried with her remaining allies to defend a Fortress Peloponnesus ; her allies would inevitably have been worn down by Persian
sea
power, and Sparta would at last have stood alone, to
come to terms or perish heroically. 815
2. MED ISM The Greek verb ' to medize ' meant to collaborate with the Persians. If used of states, it meant submitting to Persian overlordship. This was the subject of the previous section. If used of individuals, it meant defecting to the Persians. This as a phenomenon of political psychology deserves separate mention. Bury pointed out that the very word ' medism ' shows the antiquity of the practice, going back to the time when the Medes were still a separate power from the Persians, and the Ionian Greeks played the Medes off against their suzerain Croesus of Lydia. ' For if such intriguing had first come into fashion after the rise of Persia and the fall of Lydia, the name chosen to designate it would naturally have been
persism '
.
88 The Greeks recognized their proneness to treachery
and faction. Pausanias, the traveller and geographer of the second century A.D., in his
prodosia,
Description of Gr�ec� has a long invective upon
treason, as the besetting sin of Greek politics, and begins
with the examples in the Persian Wars. 87 The individual who medized most flagrandy and influentially was Apollo. His oracles at Branchidae near Miletus in Ionia, and more particularly at Delphi, consistendy recommended submission to Persia. It looks as if consulting the oracle, for states which wanted . an excuse for temporizing or inaction, played a similar role to that which referring a problem to the League or the United Nations has had in recent history. The shrine of Apollo at Magnesia on the Maeander was under Darius' especial protection. 88 Xerxes on his
Hellas and Persia advance did not occupy Delphi, probably by prior agreement ; Hero dotus has an edifying story of a supernatural occurrence which discouraged him, recalling the way in which Pope Leo the Great warded off Attila the Hun from Rome in A.D. 452.89 ' And such was the prestige of Delphi that no extant literary source questions
this story '. �0
No doubt the priesthood of the oracles was venal . Perhaps the Persians found how to bribe them. 41 Perhaps the priesthood made an honest political calculation that an imperial peace would be for the common good and also their own. The defeat of the Persians did not discredit the oracles. The mutually jealous states of Greece competed for the favour of Delphi, and the oracle, in an age of dawning scepticism, kept its prestige remarkably, not least in the •
circle of Socrates. Like many undoubted facts in history, it is very odd, and not at all what one might have expected '.4 2 The history of the papacy has parallels. A generation after the incorporation of the Ionian Greek states in the Persian Empire, we have the first records of Persia being used as a factor in the politics of independent Greek states. Was she so used by Greek politicians, or did the Persian government take the initiative ? It is difficult to tell. The preceding section tried to review the evidence for the progressive Persian conquest of Greece. But how far this policy of expansion was based on knowledge of Hellenic affairs and preceded by calculated intervention in Hellenic domestic politics is unclear. When the embassy went from revolutionary Athens to Sardis to solicit a Persian alliance, and had stated their case according to their instructions, the Persian viceroy said, ' Who are you, and where do you come from, that you want a Persian alliance ? '41 Herodotus gives it the same contemptuous inflection as Cyrus's question about the Spartans ; hut the implication surely is not that the viceroy did not know, but that he was putting the Athenians in their place. Again, when Darius was told that Athens had given assistance to the Ionian Revolt and even taken part in the burning of Sardis, the story goes that he did not give a thought to the Ion ians, knowing perfectly well that they would get their punishment, but he asked " who are the Athenians ? " '44 But this was ten years or so after both the Persian expedition to reconnoitre the Mediterranean and Darius' first invasion of the Balkan peninsula. How and Wells describe it as ' a characteristically oriental ignorance of Greece on •
Systems of States the part of the Persians ', n but the advance of historical knowledge has given us a less patronizing view of the Persian Empire since they wrote, and one wonders if it may not be part of Herodotus' dramatic art to exaggerate the insignificance of David in the eyes of Goliath. But the evidence we have suggests that it was Greek politicians who took the initiative, to borrow the expression of Representative
G. Ford, in playing footsie with the power�mad Persian leaders. The Peisistratid tyrants of Athens in their decline began it. When Hippias was feeling his position insecure, he married his daughter to the son of the tyrant of Lampsacus, ' perceiving that this family had great influence with King Darius '. On being deposed and banished, he retired first to Sigeium in the Troad, then to Lam psacus, then to the court of Darius.•6 It became the regular itinerary of discomfited Greek politicians. Walker was a little unfair therefore to say that ' the first chapter of the long and squalid history of medism had been written ' with Cleisthenes' subsequent request for a Persian alliance.4 1 It is clear that during the revolution in Athens two parties were prepared to solicit Persian intervention - not only the Peisistratid faction, but also the great ' Whig ' family of the Alcmaeonidae, led by Cleisthenes, which organized the popular forces. The role of Darius resembled that of Louis XIV in English politics in the later seventeenth century. Hippias in exile, like James II, ' did all he could to bring Athens into subjection to himself and Darius ' . The Athen ians according! y sent a second embassy to Sardis, to deprecate the political activities of exiles. ' Artaphrenes [ the viceroy] replied with an ultimatum demanding the restoration of Hippias. Athens rej ected this ultimatum when it was reported back, and decided to accept the consequences of open war with Persia ' .48 Herodotus emphasizes that this was the moment when Athens received a request from Miletus to intervene in the Ionian Revolt; which she accepted ; and so it is difficult to accept Cary's judgment that ' in this round the Greeks were the aggressors '. 49 But there were medizing tendencies in Athenian politics throughout the Ionian Revolt and the first Persian Invasion of Greece. The Persian expedition was accompanied and guided by Hippias, now aged nearly S o, and the Alcmaeonid party sent the heliograph signal to the Persians from unprotected Athens on the day of Marathon.30 It was only that resounding victory which united the Athenians for the greater struggle that followed.
Hellas and Persia
After this, medizing appears as the expedient of individuals rather than the policy of parties. Damaratus, king of Sparta, when he was deposed took refuge in Persia. A nobler version of Hippias, he accompanied Xerxes in the great invasion, and gave him much good advice about the Greeks ; no doubt if Persia had won he would have been restored as vassal king. According to Plutarch, Aristides was recalled from exile by the Athenians at that crisis for fear he should go over to the Persians : a significant fear, though a misjudgment of the man. The defeat of the great invasion and the withdrawal of the Persians from Europe left the Persian Empire intact as the greatest power on the eastern side of the Aegean, and as a continuing dement in Greek political consciousness. In the very aftermath of victory, the arrogant and ambitious Spartan commander Pausanias began intriguing with the Persians, with some plan in mind of making himself master of Hellas : he lived in Persian style, wore Persian clothes, and travelled with a Persian bodyguard.62 His down fall involved Themistocles, the greatest and most famous of all Greeks who medized. Perhaps he is also the most excusable. He was the object of jealousy in Athenian politics because of both his genius and his arrogance, and his aristocratic enemies manufactured stories about his having intrigued with Persia during the war. At the same time he made himself unpopular with Sparta by resisting the restora tion of her hegemony in Greece and asserting the independent status of Athens as a great power. When the Athenians ostracized him, both his own city and Sparta made Greece too hot to hold him, and in a sense he had nowhere else but Persia to take refuge. So having been both William III and Marlborough to Athens during the war, he ended as Bolingbroke - a Bolingbroke who never returned. After him there is no important medizer in Greek international politics until Alcibiades at the end of the Peloponnesian War. 81
3.
BASILEUS AND BARBAROS
Much of the psychological development of the Hellenic states-system would be recovered if we could write a history of the two concepts hasileus and harharos. Basileus is the Greek word for king; the Greeks used it for the king of Persia in a peculiar way, without the definite article. There were plenty of kings in Greek experience.
Systems of States
They survived from earlier times in the constitutions of many poleis : Sparta had a double kingship ; in Athens the basileus had become an annual magistrate with certain religious and judicial functions. On the fringe of the Hellenic states-system there were kings, as in Macedonia and Epirus and Cyprus; and within the Persian Empire there were vassal kings. But the word basileus without the definite article was reserved for the king of Persia. Less frequently he was called ho megas basileus, the Great King.u !socrates, the panhellenic publicist of the fourth century, makes indignant reference to this usage : the Greeks should feel it a disgrace to see the descendants of Cyrus, ' who as a child was cast out by his mother on the public highway ', addressed by this more exalted title than the kings of Sparta, who are descended from the deified Heracles.1" But I do not know of any surviving Greek comment upon the usage of basileus without the article. This usage seems to have had the connotation, in the Hellenic states-system, of the word ' emperor ' in the early Western states system. By a paradox, it was abandoned in the later part of the Graeco-Roman story, when the states-system was evolving into an imperial world-state. If Alexander was in one aspect the successor of the Great King, he was other things as well, and possibly aimed at some even more transcendent role. ' It became clear to all men that there was present!y to be neither King of Macedon nor Captain General of Hellas, nor Great King of Persia, but an Emperor of Europe and Asia ' .n It is possible that the dramatic burning of the great palace of Persepolis, which announced that the Hellenic crusade against Persia was accomplished and that Xerxes' burning of the temples at Athens was avenged, symbolically marked the ending of the Persian basileia.116 After this Alexander assumed the new style of Kyrios tes Asies, Lord of Asia, and the word basileus in its original form, with the definite article, came in informal! y to describe him and his successors.u Thus Menander refers to them in language different from that which Aeschylus used of Xerxes. This was the usage that became current, popularly and unofficially, for the Roman Emperors, when the official Greek word to translate Imperator was A utokrator. 11 8
The word barbaros was onomatopoeic in origin, describing the jabber of those who did not speak Greek. (fhus it differs from the Hebrew counterpart goyim, which means 'nations '. What is the
Helias and Persia Qllnese word ? Herodotus, in a curious parenthesis,8' says that the Egyptians call all men barbarians who do not speak the same lan guage as themselves.) The Greeks did not develop a terminology to enable them to distinguish between civilized peoples, in the sense in which we would apply that term not only to the Greeks but to Egyptians, Babylonians and Persians as well, and the simpler indi genous tribal or nomadic peoples of the Balkans, the Ukraine, Sicily and Italy. Their cultural arrogance was similar to that of nineteenth century Europeans, for whom ' European ' was apt to be synonymous with ' civilized '. Plato remarks in the Politicus, 26 2D, on the logical fallacy of giving the countless unrdated non-Greek peoples of the world a single name ' barbarian ', and then thinking of ' barbarians ' as a single species. And though this passage seems to confl.ict with the more famous statement in the Republic, 4 7oC, that Hellenes and barbarians are by nature in a state of war with one another, there is ample evidence in Plato, as in Herodotus and Xenophon, of an awareness of the Greeks' cultural debt to the great civilizations of the Middle East. The linguistic difference carried a sense of cultural difference, and barbarians were prima fade outside the Hellenic states-system . The subjugation of the Ionian Greeks by the Persian Empire made the Persians, in Greek writing, the ' barbarians ' par excellence. The Greeks' astonishing victory in the Persian Wars not only gave them self-confidence ; it made them overweening, and produced attitudes of racial superiority. The word ' barbarian ', from having been neutral, now acquired a derogatory flavour; it became the equivalent of ' Oriental ', or even ' wog'. The view became prevalent which Euripides puts in the mouth of Iphigeneia, that it is proper for Greeks to rule barbarians, but not the other way round, because barbarians are slaves by nature but Greeks free.60 In the fourth century the supposed decadence of the Persians was canvassed, es pecially by !socrates, as a compensation for the manifest confusion and decline of Hellenic affairs. Isocrates drew the conclusion that the proper way to solve the problem of international anarchy in the Hellenic states-system was to rediscover the lost unity against the external enemy. ' It is not possible for us to cement an enduring peace unless we join together in a war against the barbarians, nor for the Hellenes to attain to concord until we wrest our material advantages from one and the same source and wage our wars against
86
Systems of States
one and the same enemy '.81 He describes his project by a word for which the appropriate translation would be ' crusade ' . ' For this war is the only war which is better than peace ; it will be more like a sacred mission, theoria, than a military expedition ' •8 2 This line of thought, contrasting Greek valour and freedom with barbarian
degeneracy and servility, culminated in Aristotles advice to Alexan der - ' to treat the Greeks as a leader, but the barbarians as a master; to cultivate the former as friends and kindred, but to manage the latter as if they were animals or plants ' .81 But there were at the same time two other strands of thought about the antithesis of Hellene and barbarian. There is evidence that the
sophists in the fifth century were already beginning to deny the
antithesis and to assert, in some sense, the unity of mankind. a. Such a view appears in Euripides and in the early Cynics. More important, the Greeks were coming
to
recognize that the cultural frontier
between Hellene and barbarian was not rigid, that the Greek language and Hellenic culture were inherently expansive, that by force of circumstances or by desire barbarians might be
converted
into Hellenes. The most illustrious proselyte was Macedonia. It seems
that admission to the states-system, or diplomatic recognition, took
the form of admission to the Olympic Games, after scrutiny of the applicant's Hellenic lineage. It was Alexander I (c.
498-54)
who
first brought Macedonia into the Hellenic community. He colla borated unwilling! y with the Persians during the Great Invasion, was afterwards an ally of Athens, and pursued a systematic policy of hellenization of his country. He dedicated a golden statue at Delphi. 8� Herodotus says that when Alexander entered the fidd at Olympia, the Greek competitors tried to bar him, saying that the contest should be for Greeks and not barbarians. Alexander there upon went before the presiding committee, the Hellenodikai, and proved his descent from the Heraclid dynasty of Argos. They ac cording! y judged him to be a Greek ; ' so he contended in the furlong race and ran a dead heat for the first place ' . 68 This genealogy of the royal family thus became an important element in Macedonian nationalism. 87 But it was !socrates who saw the general process at work a century later. Athens, he said, ' has brought it about that the name of Hellene suggests no longer a race but an intelligence, and that the word Hellene is applied rather to those who share our culture than to those who share a common blood '. 88 Again, in his
Hellas and Persia eulogy of Evagoras the despot of Salamis in Cyprus, he says that •citizens of barbarian birth he transformed into Hellenes, cowards
into warriors, and obscure individuals into men of note '. 69 The
Hellenic states-system was the framework of a proselytizing culture. Not less important than the theory of relations between Greek and barbarian states was their actual inextricable involvement in a com mon political and economic system. The role of Persia in inter national affairs in the fourth century is the great example ; this is described in the next section. But the Second Athenian Confederacy,
whose charter was promulgated in 377, was in theory open to bar
barian as well as Greek states (provided they did not owe allegiance to
the king), an astonishing contrast with the Delian Confederacy. In
fact the barbarian kingdom of the Molossi, in the highlands of Epirus, under Alketas and his son Neoptolemus, were members and they were not qualified for admission to the Olympic Games. 70 Of these attitudes and beliefs about the relations of Greek and barbarian, Philip and Alexander provided a Marxian synthesis. For reasons about which no evidence survives, Philip adopted the Iso cratean policy of uniting Hellas in an anti-Persian crusade : 'for it was coming to be his ambition to be designated generalissimo of Hellas and to wage the war against the Persians'. 1 1 Alexander inherited the policy and transformed it into a campaign of hellenization through out Asia. And he rose to a conception of the unity of mankind. Eratosthenes, the third-century scholar, recorded Aristotle's aston ishing advice to Alexander quoted above, but added that Alexan der disregarded it, thinking it better to distinguish men according to their virtues and vices, ' since among the Greeks there are many worthless characters, and many highly civilized are to be found amongst the barbarians ' . 1 2 ' Since he believed that he had a mission from God to harmonize men generally and to be the reconciler of the world, those whom he could not unite by reason he coerced by force of arms, bringing men from everywhere into a unity and mixing their lives and customs, their marriages and social ways, as in a loving-cup. He enjoined them all to consider the whole inhabited earth as d1eir fatherland, his camp as their citadel and guard-post, good men in general as their kindred, bad men only as aliens. For the distinction between Greek and barbarian should not be a matter of clothes and weapons [ N.B. language has now become an obsolete test] , but the mark of the Greek should be seen in virtue, and the
88
Systems of States
mark of the barbarian in an evil character '. 71 This lofty conception temporarily dissolved the Hellenic states-system in a wider unity, and illustrated, perhaps for the first time in history, the incompatibility of the cosmopolitan ideal with the existence of any states-system.
4. PERSIA AS PRIMUS INTER PARES One of the most striking events in Greek history is the Persian come back. Beween 480 and 4 7 5 Persia is defeated on land and sea and driven out of Europe. Within a century, the Great King ' sends down peace ' to the warring Greek powers and is recognized as arbiter of the Hellenic states-system. The crowning mercies of Salamis and Plataea, like the defeat of the Spanish Annada, came at the beginning, not as the conclusion, of a long-drawn-out war. The war went on until the generation · of Xerxes and Themistodes and Aristides was dead and the new generation of Pericles was already in middle age. Athens organized her allies, liberated even more Greek states and added them to her Confederacy, pushed Persian power back and back, beyond the eastern shore of the Mediterranean, lost an expeditionary force in supporting an Egyptian revolt against the king, and at last made peace in 449, the peace known from the Athenian diplomatist who negotiated it as the Peace of Kallias. 74 At this point, if at all, Persia was decisively thrust out of the Hellenic states-system, and the new configuration of that system as an Atheno-Spartan diarchy was confirmed. The Peace of Kallias was an incident in the First Peloponnesian War (4 5 9-44 5) Pericles ended the war with Persia because he had learned that Athens was not strong enough to fight Persia and Sparta simultaneously. Thucy dides, concentrating on the breakdown of the diarchy, does not mention the Peace of Kallias at all. In his account of the First Pelo ponnesian War his only mention of Persia is of her failure to secure Spartan intervention against Athens when the Athenian expedition ary force was in Egypt (i. 1 09). It might be made a criticism of his whole History that he virtually ignores the strength of Persia, waiting in the wings. Wade-Gery has elucidated the Peace of Kallias and its conse quences in a classic essay, which will be followed here . 73 The Peace .
Hellas and Persia of Kallias was a negotiated, not a dictated, peace. Athens after her
Egyptian disaster could not impose terms ; each side made conces sions ; hence a stable and lasting settlement. 7 8 Athens recognized Per sian sovereignty over Cyprus, Egypt and Libya. Persia recognized the Ionian Greek states as autonomous, but they continued to pay a modest tribute to the king. 77 To the east of them, a demilitarized zone was established, both on land and at sea off the southern coast
of Asia Minor. ' By covenanting this, the Persian Empire was con verted from an offensive power, treating the world as its prey, into a defensive power, living on terms with its neighbours '. 78 A compari
son might be drawn with the Peace of Zsitva-Torok of I 6o6, the first in which the Ottomon Sultan recognized the Habsburg Emperor as a political and diplomatic equal. The settlement lasted for a generation. Even when the great war
between Athens and Sparta broke out, Persia prudent! y refrained from taking part, despite attempts by Sparta to involve her. She accepted an Athenian initiative and renewed the Treaty of Kallias in
424. No doubt the ministers of Artaxerxes I and Darius II were able
to formulate for themselves the advice that was later given them by Alcibiades, that it was in Persia's interest to see the two Hellenic great powers grind down each other's strength . It was not until the Athenian disaster in Sicily had shifted the balance of power through out the Hellenic world that Persia intervened. Even then she only did so under Athenian provocation. By an act of folly eclipsing the decision to send the Syracusan expedition, Athens herself repudiated the renewed Treaty of Kallias, by officially supporting the revolt of the satrap of Lydia. ' We threw away the king's power, as if it were no use to us, and chose instead Amorges's friendship, thinking it more in our interest. Whereupon the king, in his resentment against us, allied with the Spartans, and subsidized them with s,ooo talents for the war, until he had overthrown our empire '. 79 It was the combination of Persia and Sparta that defeated Athens
in the Peloponnesian War. Sparta could not defeat Athens without a navy ; Persia supplied her with the means to build one, and even subsidized the naval pay . But Persia had her own interests to secure. The Treaty of Kallias was now dead, and she reoccupied the de militarized zones. Moreover, in the first treaty of alliance between Persia and Sparta in 4 1 2 (Thucydides gives its text, viii. 1 8) the first clause was ' Whatsoever territory and cities the king holds or the
go forefathers of the king held, shall belong to the king '. A Spartan diplomatist, Lichas, pointed out that this was a monstrous claim : its effect would be to restore Persian sovereignty over the island states and central Greece as far as Boeotia, and instead of liberating Hellas, Sparta would be reimposing the Persian yoke.8 0 Accordingly the third Persian-Spartan treaty, in 4 1 1, contained a vaguer formula, which dominated the diplomacy of the next s o years : ' The king's country, as much of it as is in Asia, shall be the king's ; and con cerning his own country the king shall determine as he pleases '. 8 1 But when the Spartans were at last triumphant, and with great enthusiasm began to tear down the walls of Athens to the music of flute-girls, thinking that this day was the beginning of freedom for Hdlas,8 2 it was at the price of revising the settlement of the Persian Wars. But there was now a balance of power as different from the Persian ascendancy of the end of the sixth century as it was from the Atheno Spartan diarchy that had followed. The Great King no longer ex tended his suzerain claims diplomatic intercourse ; the heard again, even in Asia, Wars had reduced Persian
to Europe. He accepted the forms of
old demand for earth and water is not after the Peace of Kallias. The Persian pretensions, as the Peloponnesian War
had reduced Athenian pretensions, and there was now a system of great powers of comparable strength : Sparta, Athens, Thebes, Corinth, Syracuse - and Persia. Persia was both within the Hellenic states-system and outside it. The greater part of the Empire Iay beyond the system, but the only deadly external threat to the Empire came from the Greek powers. The Empire had internal weaknesses : the irremediable disaffection of Egypt and Babylon, the two more ancient cultures reluctantly incapsulated within the Persian structure, and the tendency of so vast and complex a commonwealth to split up
through the independence or disloyalty of the satraps and vassal rulers. Moreover, the hellenization of the Empire was proceeding steadily, and itself had a disintegrating effect, above all in the mili tary field : the Persian authorities, both central and local, increasingly
liked to recruit Greek mercenaries. But against the Greek powers, Persia had great sources of strength . She had enormous man-power ; . and though no Persian infantry was a match for Greek hoplites, Persian cavalry remained superior to anything the Greeks possessed. She had inexhaustible finances, and became the paymaster of the
Helias and Persia Hdlenic states-system. ' I t was the belief of the Persian King that by
possessing himself of colossal wealth, he would put all things in subjection to himself. In this belief he tried to engross all the gold,
all the silver and all the most costly things in the world '. 88 Above all,
Persia had superior diplomatic skill, and taking every advantage of
the incurable dissensions of the Greek powers she learned how to divide and rule.u But her application of the maxim was now defen sive; ' rule ' did not mean ' conquer ' ; her vital interest was to prevent any single Greek power from dominating the Aegean. Historians usually describe the
30
years following the Peloponnes
ian War as a Spartan hegemony. So it was, if Sparta's dependence on
Persia be remembered. 811 Of course the two powers quarrelled, as soon as their common enemy had been crushed. Sparta was embar
rassed by the Persian alliance, which spoiled her claim to be liberator of Hdlas. She gave unofficial assistance to the putsch against the Great King by the younger Cyrus, which is the subj ect of Xenophon's most famous work. Then the Asiatic Greeks appealed to Sparta,
although she had acknowledged Persian suzerainty over them. Ac cordingly Agesilaus, the lame king of Sparta
(3 99-60),
Xenophon's
friend and hero, who dominates the international politics of the time,
invaded Asia Minor with a romantic aim of ' paying back the Persian in his own coin for the former invasion of Greece ' . 8 8 This was the
first post-Athenian attempt at the anti-Persian crusade, which !so
crates tireless! y preached and Alexander afterwards carried to success.
Agesilaus's expedition quickly ended. Sparta's continental ex-al lies, Thebes, Corinth and Argos, formed with Athens a coalition against Sparta behind her back, which was financed by Persia, 87 and the
Spartan government recalled Agesilaus to Europe. Plutarch records
several examples of Agesilaus' s political wit. ' It was at this time, as we are told, and as he was evacuating, that Agesilaus said to his
friends, " The King has driven me out of Asia with
3o,ooo archers " ;
for the Persian coin has the figure of an archer stamped upon it '. 88
The war, which goes by the name of the Corinthian War, lasted another six or seven years, and came to an end when Persia switched sides from Athens back to Sparta. Athens had recovered her strength, begun to re-establish her empire, and supported Evagoras of Cyprus,
a rebellious vassal, against the king.89 Modern historians differ in
assigning the diplomatic credit for negotiating the peace to Sparta or Persia. Olmstead, the Chicago historian, who retold the whole story
Systems of States as
champion of the undervalued Persians, and T. T. B. Ryder, in his recent study Koine Eirme, might be taken as contrasted representa tives. But the ancient authorities agree in regarding the peace as a Persian triumph, and therefore as a Greek disgrace. Sometimes the Greeks refer to it as the Peace of Antalkidas, after the chief Spartan plenipotentiary ; more commonly they call it simply the King's Peace. Our surviving accounts of it show the king being accepted as the president or arbiter of the Hellenic states-system. As early as 393 Sparta had sent Antalkidas to Sardis to discuss terms with the satrap Tiribazus. These bilateral negotiations had been enlarged, against Sparta's will, into an abortive conference of all the belligerents, over which Tiribazus presided.90 In 388 Antalkidas was sent up to Susa for a second try. The following year, therefore, Tiribazus presided again over a conference of ambassadors from the belligerent states. He 'summoned those to he present who wanted to listen to the terms of peace that the king had sent down. And when they had assembled, Tiribazus showed them the king's seal and read the document. It ran as follows : " Artaxerxes the king thinks it just that [specific terms follow] . And whichever of the two sides refuses to accept this peace, upon them will I impose military sanctions (in concert with those who approve the peace), by land and by sea, both naval and financial ''. '91 The terms which the king thus guaranteed were simple and funda mental. First, the Greek states in Asia, including Cyprus, were recognized as his possessions. SecondIy, all other Greek states, small and great, were assured their independence. An exception was made of Lemnos, Imbros and Scyros, which were to belong to Athens as of old (they had anyway been inhabited by Athenians for generations). The sacrifice of Asia to the king was the point most attacked after wards by philhellenes, as a betrayal of the cause of Hellas and an abandonment of all that had been won since the Ionian Revolt in 499· It was, however, for diplomatists an acceptance of the existing facts of power, like the recognition of Soviet ascendancy in Eastern Europe in 1 945. And in the view of philhellene enthusiasts, this disgrace was almost offset and compensated for by the principle of the autonomy of other Greek states. This principle was skilfully designed to appeal to the inextinguishable passion of the polis for parochial sovereignty, and to keep the states-system atomized and incapable of common action. ' Autonomy ' was left conveniently un defined. It was generally understood to mean at least freedom from
H�llas and Pn-sia
93
foreign garrisons and from payment of tribute to another power; also that a state ' should possess its-own territory ', however this might be understood . 92 And it was bound up with two unprecedented features. The King's Peace was a common or general peace, k.oin� eirme, applicable to all states whether or not they had fought in the Corinthian War ; and it was cond uded without a time-limit, and so marked a growing belie£ that war should be the exception, peace the
rule, and that peace·treaties should therefore aim at a permanent settlement.98 This doctrine was given expression by Xenophon in a
pamphlet he published in his old age. 96
The King's Peace reflected the interests of Sparta as much as of
Persia. The principle of autonomy weakened Sparta's potential
rivals. It dismanded the reviving Athenian confederacy ; it deprived
Thebes of her hegemony over the other states of Boeotia ; it compelled Argos to renounce her recent
Anschluss
with Corinth. With regard
.to lesser states, Sparta interpreted the principle to suit herself. She
was the executor and policeman of the peace; Persia did not inter vene in Hellenic politics, did not need to, for a good many years
afterwards. 98 When someone deplored the King's Peace to Agesilaus, saying ' Alas for Hdlas, now that the Spartans are medizing ', he replied, ' Isn't it rather the case that the Medes are laconizing r s e The King's Peace of 38 7 was the fundamental Hellenic peace
settlement of the fourth century. It recorded the lasting dements of the balance of power more accurately than the peace which Sparta
and her allies had imposed on Athens at the end of the great war in 404 . In the next 30 years there were several more pacifications
which were popularly called ' the King's Peace ', and which in the surviving literary sources, tend to be confused one with another. They reaffirmed or modified the original peace, but all had the characteristics of accepting the Icing's sovereignty over the Asiatic
Greeks, and of being common to all the other Greek states of the mainland (the Western Greeks were never included, as the states of the American continent were never included in the affairs of the Concert of Europe in the nineteenth century). In most of them the king seeins to have taken the initiative, and to have been accorded
the presidential role. 9 7 When one surveys the whole history of Persia's role in the Hel lenic states-system after the failure of her attempt to incorporate the system within her Empire, it seems that Persia developed a policy of
94
Systems of States
collaborating with each successive power that exercised a hegemony. Her motive was now defensive, and it was through the dominant power that she found �erself able to divide and rule - or divide and deter. The policy was worked out in the time of Athenian hegemony. Because the Peace of Kallias of 449 was a negotiated settlement arrived at by compromise, Persia was able to accept it, and loyally observed it until Athens herself tore it up. Persia then transferred her support to Sparta, and backed Sparta (so long as Sparta was coopera tive) down to Sparta's catastrophic defeat by Thebes at the battle of Leuctra in 3 7 1 . Leuctra destroyed Spartan prestige
in
Asia, and
when the Theban statesman Pelopidas went up to Susa in 3 6 7 on a diplomatic mission, Artaxerxes readily transferred to him the con fidence he had hitherto reposed in Antalkidas. 98 Thebes could now cash in on her long tradition of medism. Pelopidas was able to remind Artaxerxes ' that his people were the only ones among the Greeks who had fought on the side of the king at Plataea [in 4 79 ] , that they had never afterwards undertaken a campaign against the king and that Sparta had gone to war with them for the very reason that they had refused to take part in Agesilaus's expedition '. The Persian-Theban alliance remained fairly stable. Artaxerxes III readily gave Thebes financial assistance during the Third Sacred War, in
3 50, and Thebes responded by sending him a force of x ,ooo hoplites to help reconquer Egypt in 343.99 Of all the successive dominant powers in Greece, Thebes offered least potential danger to Persia. By contrast the growth of Macedonian power, in Thrace and
in the
Hellespont, alarmed the king, and he intervened against Philip even before Philip had conquered Central Greece.1 00 Thebes' medizing policy gave Philip's relations with her a tinge of suspicion . and hostility lacking in his relations with Athens or Sparta ; and a dread ful logic of power brought it about that the crowning act of violence by which Macedon consolidated her hegemony of the Hellenic states system in preparation for the crusade against Persia, was Alexander's destruction of Thebes.
5. CARTHAGE Was Carthage a member of the Hellenic states-system ? Her position had resemblances to Persia's. They were kindred powers. Carthage
Hellas and Persia
95
lay on the flank of the Western Greeks as Persia lay on the flank of
the Asiatic Greeks. They were to the Greeks the two principal bar barian powers, and at times they cooperated. Carthage was a colony of Tyre. It was founded, with the name of
' the New Town ', at the end of the ninth century. There were other Phoenician trading settlements as well in the western Mediterra
but Carthage became the most prosperous. Though indepen dent, she remained united with Tyre by the ties of filial friendship
nean,
seen also in the relations of Greek colonies with their mother-cities. Tyre herself, which half a century earlier had resisted conquest by Nebuchadnezzar through a 1 3 years' siege, and her fellow Phoeni cian city-states, submitted to the beneficent imperialism of Cyrus the Great with such prudent conunercial promptitude that it is virtually unrecorded.1 0 1 Thenceforward these Phoenician states provided the backbone of the Persian navy. But when the son of Cyrus, Cambyses, who conquered Egypt, planned also to extend Persian rule along the North African coast to include Carthage, ' the Phoenicians would not consent. For they said they were bound by a strict treaty, and could not justly attack their own sons. And the Phoenicians being un willing, the rest were of no account as fighters . Thus Carthage
escaped being subjugated by Persia. For Cambyses would not coerce the Phoenicians, seeing that they had willingly accepted Persian suzerainty and that the whole fleet depended upon them ' . 1 0 2 Phoenician colonization almost certainly antedated Greek in the western Mediterranean. For several centuries the expansion of Carthaginian interests was commercial, confined to establishing trading-posts or factories along the coasts, without any aim of territorial dominion.1 0 8 The first armed clash with the Greeks was in the year 6oo, when the Phokaians in order to found their colony of Marseilles had first to beat the Carthaginians at sea.1 04 Carthage ' knew the intruders on her ancient home, the young light-hearted masters of the waves ' - of whom historians are far more ready to use such words as ' aggressors ' and ' pirates ' than they were a genera tion or two ago. In the next century the Greeks were challenging the Western Phoenicians along the coasts of North Africa and Spain, in Sardinia and Corsica, and above all in Sicily. In the eastern Mediter ranean the greatest of barbarian powers was pressing upon the Greeks ; in the western Mediterranean it was the Greeks who were pressing upon the barbarian powers. The Persian conquest of Ionia
Systems of States seems to have had its repercussions in the west, by sending across a wave of displaced Greeks, which in n�rn provoked Carthage into
defensive alliances and counter-attack. There is evidence also of
concerted policy between Carthage and Persia. The whole Mediter ranean for the first time fell into a single pattern of organized power, and danced to a common measure. Carthage entered upon a policy of territorial expansion in Sicily ' in the time of Cyrus ', according to a late and bad authority ;10 5
modern historians date it between 5 5 0 and 540. She then apparently
first developed a large army, assumed the hegemony of the other
Phoenician cities in Sicily, and gained control of the western corner
of the island. There is no evidence as to whether her aims were
aggressive or preventive. But her army was transferred from Sicily to Sardinia at about the time that Bias proposed that the inhabitants of
the Ionian Greek states should migrate collectively to Sardinia to escape the Persians. 1 00 Bias's advice was not taken ; but in the same crisis half the population of Phokaia (the mother-city of Marseilles)
migrated to Corsica. There they harried and plundered their neigh
bours. The consequence was an alliance against them between Car
thage and the Etruscans, who drove them out of Corsica at the battle of Alalia in 5 3 5 . 1 0 1 The alliance between Carthaginians and Etrus cans became so constant a feature of the international scene that
Aristotle, more than a century later, could take it as an example of a union for mutual defence or economic intercourse that just fell short of fonning a single state. 108 A little later we have our earliest diplo matic document in the western Mediterranean, the first treaty be
tween Carthage and Rome, which Pol ybius had difficulty in transcribing out of the archaic Latin. Its date is 5 09, ' 28 years before
the crossing of Xerxes into Greece ', the first year after Rome threw off the Etruscan yoke and expelled her kings. It is an agreement
to
delimit spheres of influence. It does not mention the Greeks, but
perhaps it shows that Carthage was intent on mending her political
and strategical fences and thought it valuable to come to terms with the new republic.1 09 Meanwhile a regular balance of power had developed in Sicily,
cutting across the distinction between Greek and barbarian, and
producing the phenomenon of Greeks who ' phoenicized ' (a word that does not seem to have been used in the political sense). Syracuse,
under its able despot Gelon, had rapidly become predominant, and
Hellas and Persia
97
by far the largest state in Sicily.1 10 Syracuse allied with Akragas,
and
counter-alliance was made by Selinus, and the tyrants of Rhegium and Himera, with Carthage. Akragas retaliated by intervening in a
Himera and expelling its tyrant, who then appealed for Carthaginian aid . 111 This was the local situation when Syracuse was invited by the Hellenic congress to send help against Xerxes' invasion of Greece,112 and helped to explain her temporizing response. It adds to the picture
of Helleno-Carthaginian involvement that Hamilcar, the suffete of
Carthage at this juncture, was the son of a Carthaginian father and a Syracusan mother. 11 3
The relations between Carthage and Persia when Xerxes was
preparing to invade Greece, and Carthage to invade Sicily, provide
the most important unsolved problem in the history of the Hellenic states-system . In the
5 20s
Cambyses had entertained his project for annexing Carthage to the Persian Empire . In about 5 1 8 Darius at the begin
ning of his reign had sent his naval expedition to reconnoitre the Mediterranean. 1 u In the 4 9 0s he had accepted a proposal for making Sardinia tributary to Persia ; 11 1S not only was it ' the greatest of is
lands ,, it was the only island in the western Mediterranean that had not been occupied by either Carthage, the Etruscans or the Greeks.
But it was Xerxes, according to one account, who replaced plans for
direct Persian intervention in the west by establishing what might be called a Persia-Carthage Axis. When he had resolved upon his in
vasion of Hellas, he ' sent an embassy to Carthage to urge her to join
him in the undertaking, and made an agreement with them, that he
would wage war upon the Greeks who lived in Greece, while Car thage should at the same time gather great armaments and subdue
the Greeks living in Sicily and Italy. In fulfilment of the agreement,
therefore, the Carthaginians accumulated a large war-chest, and
enlisted mercenaries from Italy and Liguria, and from Gaul and Spain as well. In addition to these, they mobilized the citizen forces
of the whole of Libya and Carthage. At last, after three years of
assiduous preparation, they collected more than and 200 warships , . 11 8
3oo,ooo
infantry,
The joint Persian-Carthaginian plan has been doubted because Herodotus, writing a century earlier than Ephorus, does not mention it. 11 7 Herodotus suggests that Syracuse was concerned like the rest of the Greek world with the threat from the east, and was taken by
Systems of States surprise when the deposed tyrant of Himera called in the Carthagin ians.118 Whether or not the two invasions were concerted, they were simultaneous, and were defeated at about the same time. The Car thaginian expedition was totally destroyed by Gelon of Syracuse at the battle of Himera. Selinus was on the Carthaginian side.119 Hero dotus records the tradition that the victory of Himera fell on the very same day as the victory of Salamis ;12 0 Diodorus makes it the same day as Thermopylae. 1 2 1 Pindar, writing his first Pythian Ode to celebrate the winning of the chariot-race of 4 7 0 by Gelon's brother and successor, commemorates the triple victory against the barbarians of Salamis, Plataea and Himera. Carthage immediately sued for peace, fearing that Gelon might invade Africa, and Gelon granted
generous terms, not only to Carthage but also to the Sicilian Greek
states and rulers who had been on the wrong side.122 His moderation ensured for more than two generations Syracusan predominance in Sicily, with Carthage still entrenched in the western end of the
island.
The affairs of the western and eastern halves of the Hellenic states
system continued to show parallels after the great crisis of 4 8 o. The barbarian power having been pushed back and successfully con tained, there was a long period of peaceful coexistence, which
enabled the victorious Hellenic great power, Athens in the one case
and Syracuse in the other, to develop its empire. In 445 a general pacification of the world was achieved : Athens had made the Thirty
Years' Truce with Sparta to conclude the First Peloponnesian War,
and Syracuse had defeated Akragas and definitely established her
hegemony in Sicily.128 From this date there is increasing evidence of Athens' strengthening her diplomatic connections with the Sicilian
states opposed to Syracuse ; Syracuse herself traditionally leaned
towards her mother-city Corinth, which was Athens's chief commer cial rival, and towards Corinth's ally Sparta. When the clash of
interests between the Greek powers led to the Peloponnesian War,
and its subsidiary international conflicts in Sicily, Carth age like Persia refrained from intervening. Thus she refused an appeal from Segesta for help against Selinus in 4 1 6 .124 But Athens, having already
sent an inconclusive expedition to Sicily to support her anti-Syracusan allies in 42 7-5, answered a similar appeal from Segesta, and launched her great expedition in 4 1 5. In 4 8 o the two halves of the Hellenic
states-system had been brought close together by external violence, a
Hdlas and Persia
99
conj oint barbarian attack from the east and the west. Now the two halves momentarily coalesced through internal violence, a wanton
aggression by Athens, the dominant power in the one, against
Syracuse, the dominant power in the other. Athens was responding to a request for help from an ally, as an
excuse for embarking upon a plan of conquest that would establish
her supremacy throughout the western Mediterranean. A hostile · critic might have said that she was uniting the ambitions of Hamilcar
against Sicily and of Cambyses against Carthage herself, in order to fulfil the ambitions of Darius and Xerxes against the whole Hellenic
states-system. Alcibiades, who led the expansionist party, aimed to conquer Carthage as well as Sicily.12 5 In public he spoke of acquiring ' empire over all Hellas ' .12 8 Popular enthusiasm supported him. The young men in their sports-grounds and the old men in their
workshops and places of entertainment would sit in clusters draw ing maps of Sicily [in the sand] , and charts of the surrounding
seas
and of the harbours and coastal districts opposite Africa. For
they did not regard Sicily itself as the object of the war, but rather as a mere base of operations, from which they would extend the conflict to Carthage and conquer both North Africa and the seas as
far as the Pillars of Hercules.127
When Alcibiades had defected to Sparta he described his strategic plans freely :
we .sailed to Sicily to conquer first, if we could, the Sicilian
Hellenes, and after them the Hellenes of Italy as well, and then to
attack the Carthaginian empire and Carthage herself. If these
objectives were gained, or the greater part of them, we intended to make our assault on the Peloponnese, bringing with us all the
additional Hellenic forces which we should have acquired in the
west, and engaging large numbers of barbarian troops, Spaniards
and others who are now recognized as the best barbarian fighting
material. We should have constructed many more triremes in addition to our existing Reet, as Italy has timber in abundance.
Thus we should have established a total maritime blockade of the
Peloponnese. At the same time we should have mounted an in
vasion by land, and taken some cities by storm and the rest by siege. We hoped in this way to bring the war to a successful con clusion and after that to be masters of the whole Hellenic world
I OO
Systems of States
[ of the whole Hellenic states·system, arxein ] .1 28
tou xympantos Hellenikou
When the Syracusan assembly debated defence measures against the impending invasion, Hennocrates surveyed the possible allies. It seems to me that we ought to make a diplomatic approach to Carthage too [ he said] . They would not be unprepared for it; indeed they live in a perpetual apprehension of Athenian attack.
They will very likely think that if they pursue a policy of non intervention now, they will soon find themselves in danger, and
so they may be inclined to help us in one way or another, secredy
if not openly. They could give us more assistance than any other existing power, if they chose. They have the greatest reserves of gold and silver, which are the sinews of war and of everything else.1 2 9 This is the only surviving piece of evidence, indirect and biased, of what Carthaginian attitudes may have been in this crisis. So far as we know she sent no aid to Syracuse. Some months later, when the Athenian expeditionary force was passing its first winter in Sicily without having achieved any military successes, the Athenians them selves cast about for allies. They it was (the leaders of the expedition, not the people at home) who now ' sent a trireme to Carthage on a goodwill mission, to see if any help might be got from there ; and they also sent one to Etruria, where some of the cities had offered of their own accord to join them in the war'. The Etruscans sent three pentekonters with some troops who did stout service in the final struggle. 1 8° Carthage preserved her neutrality. (Thucydides' careful enumeration of the belligerents on either side191 is decisive.) Carthage was probably content to see Syracuse and Athens fight it out. Like Persia, she entered the general struggle after the Athenian disaster in Sicily, though her occasions and motives were different. In
4 t o the frontier dispute between Segesta and Selinus flared up again, and Segesta, whose appeal for help to Athens had been the occasion of the Athenian expedition to Sicily, and whom the defeat of Athens had left in a state of great anxiety, now appealed for help to Carthage and offered themselves to Carthage as a protectorate. ' When the envoys arrived and laid their instructions before the Senate, the Carthaginians were presented with no small problem. On the one hand they were eager to acquire such a strategically attractive city ; on
Hellas and Persia
IOI
the other, they had considerable fear of Syracuse, having only re
..
cendy witnessed her defeat of the Athenian annada ' . On the advice of Hannibal, suffete for that year and grandson of the Hamilcar defeated and killed at Himera in 480, they decided to intervene. First they artfully invited Syracuse to arbitrate the Segestan-Selinun
tian dispute, being confident that Selinus would reject arbitration
and
so
lose the moral support of Syracuse. The negotiations took the
expected course, and at the end Syracuse decided to sit on the fence, ' maintaining her alliance with Selinus, and her good relations with Carthage '. The dispute between Segesta and Selinus now had to be fought out, and Carthage supplied troops to Segesta, including 8oo Italian native mercenaries who had been hired for the Athenians in the war against Syracuse, and had since been without an empl oyer.112 These antecedents of the second Carthaginian invasion of Sicily fonn the most elaborate passage of diplomacy between Carthage and the Sicilian states that Diodorus records. The attempt to neutralize Syracuse was a failure ; within a year the two great powers were openly involved on opposite sides of the conflict between Segesta and Selinus. Carthage invaded Sicily in 409 with a great force, and
conquered and sacked first Selinus, and then Himera, in revenge for the defeat of 480.19 8 Three years later she resumed her offensive with a still greater armament, aiming now at the subjugation of the whole island, and having sought diplomatic support as far afield as Athens.18t The main result of the ensuing war, in which Carthage increased her conquests, was the seizure of power in Syracuse by Dionysius the Great, who dominates the politics of the Western world for the next 40 years. He came to terms with Carthage, recog nizing her conquests and virtually partitioning Sicily with her, on the tacit understanding that she supported his despotism. This was in 405, a year before the end of the Peloponnesian War: Diodorus takes the double pacification as marking an era.185 Dionysius was, in one aspect, the greatest of phoenicizers. Men attributed to him the policy of ' exploiting the fear of Carthage in order to dominate securely the remaining Sicilian states ' .1 8 8 His opponents said that to be tributary to Carthage was preferable to submitting to Dionysius ' lawless tyranny .157 He later waged three wars against Carthage, and reduced the extent of her dominion. But ' we must recognize that it was a fixed principle in the policy of Dionysius not to press the Carthaginians too hard and that he never
1 02
Systems of States
aimed at making Sicily a Greek island. He seemed to have considered
it more expedient for Syracuse and himself to suffer the Phoenicians as neighbours, hoping by their menace to protect his own despotic rule , .1 8 8 His detached realism and freedom from Hellenic sentiment illustrates the transformation of Greek international ideas in the
fourth century no less than the incipient cosmopolitanism of the sophists. When Alexander was conquering the Persian Empire he met desperate resistance from Tyre, which had been the most loyal and contented member of the Persian commonwealth. There were reli gious envoys from Carthage in Tyre at the time, and the Tyrians hoped for help from Carthage ; but there is no evidence that they had grounds for expecting an intervention which would have been far
beyond Carthage's sphere of interest. All she did was to give asylum to non-combatants from the doomed city .139 But the design was attributed to Alexander, after his return from India, of a 'campaign against the Carthaginians, and the others who live along the coast of North Africa and Spain and the adj oining coastal region as far as Sicil y ' .140 It was also said that embassies came to him in Babylon, to congratulate him and solicit his favour, from all the nations of the known world, including Carthage and the Etruscans, and even
Rome.141 Both these stories - of the embassies to Babylon and the plan of conquering the western Mediteranean - are subjected to destructive criticism by Tam and reduced for the most part to later fabrications. u2 Whatever the decision on this, it is manifest that the
career and conquests of Alexander did not draw Carthage into the general movement of the H ellenic states�system as did the great crises of 48o and 4 1 5-13. Nevertheless, the survey we have made shows that Carthage was a constant factor in the western Mediterranean balance of power. She was in regular diplomatic contact with Syracuse, intermittent contact with Athens. She had allies among the Greek states of Sicily, as well as individual supporters (Empedion of Selinus, for example). us Was she, then, a member of the Hellenic states-system ? Was she ' ac cepted ' ? There are two oddly concurrent scraps of evidence about early Greek attitudes to Carthage and the Etruscans. Herodotus has a famous description of Carthaginian methods of silent barter with the natives on the coast of West Africa.1u What he emphasizes is that
Hellas and Persia
1 03
neither party defrauds the other,. The Carthaginians were trust worthy; one might almost say, the Carthaginian's word was his bond. The hostile Roman tradition of ' Punic faith ' is not found until the second century .1 411 And the geographer Strabo, writing at the time of Augustus, says of the Etruscan city-state Caere that it ' enjoyed a high reputation with the Greeks for bravery and justice; for it abstained &om piracy, despite being very powerful, and set up at Delphi the building called the Treasury of the Agyllaians - for the state was formerly called Agylla, though now it is Caere '.148 In the age of colonial expansion some Greeks, it may seem, could recognize some barbarians as having political and commercial standards higher than their own. The passage from Strabo shows a connection between the Etrus cans and Delphi. Carthage had no connection with Delphi ; like the Jews, the Carthaginians were cut off from the Hellenic world by their religion. Pausanias the traveller, writing 1 5 0 years later than Strabo, describes a Treasury of the Carthaginians at Olympia which contained spoils won from them in battle.147 It is possible that the Treasury of the Agyllaians at Delphi was likewise not the offerings of barbarian piety but war-booty won at their expense.us But Hero dotus too describes a mission from Agylla to Delphi.149 The helleni zation of the Etruscans was deeper and more pervasive than that of Carthage. Agylla had sent to Delphi for advice about lifting a curse occa sioned by an act of sacrilege. After the battle of Alalia the Carthagin ians and Etruscans had drawn lots for their Greek prisoners; the Etruscans had got the bigger share, and massacred them; a blight then fell upon them and attested their bloodguiltiness. This has more resemblance to the character that Carthage had among the Greeks. It was a reputation for savagery and cruelty, unmitigated by any recourse to Del phi in atonement. Eratosthenes describes ' repelling strangers ' as ' a practice common to all barbarians', and illustrates it by the Carthaginians' habit of drowning strangers who sailed past on their voyage to Sardinia off the Pillars of Hercules. 'This is the reason ' he adds, ' why geogr�phical information about the west is unreliable' .1"0 The implication seems to be that the Greeks asserted not so much the freedom of the seas, as respect for human life except in time of war, and Carthage regarded herself as in a state of per petual war. Diodorus's account of the Carthaginian sack of Selinus •
Systems of States
in 409 rises into unaccustomed eloquence when he describes the Greeks' horror at barbarian practices in war. 'They mutilated even the dead, according to their national custom, some carrying dis membered hands in bunches about their bodies, and others heads which they had spitted on their javelins and spears , .11J1 The Greeks could be as indignant about the continued practice of human sacri fice, which with them had become obsolete, as twentieth-century Englishmen about the survival of slave-trading. Plutarch has a story that in the peace-terms imposed on Carthage after the defeat of Himera in 480, Gelon included a prohibition of the practice of sacrificing children to Moloch.u2 If this is true, it is an interesting case of an ' unequal treaty ,, intervening in the domestic affairs of a defeated state to suppress practices that offend the civilized standards of the victor Whether true or a later edifying invention, it suggests that Greeks would have regarded Carthage as belonging to their states-system, if at all, only in the dubious and marginal way in which Europeans regarded China in the nineteenth century as be longing to the family of nations. And the Greeks did not fail to note occasions when Carthage reverted to human sacrifice, such as Hamil car,s propitiation of his dead grandfather, the sacrifice of a boy at the siege of Akragas, and of 200 children at Carthage.1 u For the Greeks, there were three contrasts between Carthage and Persia. First, Carthage did not have ecumenical claims and imperial status. Or to put it in terms of power and not of authority, Carthage was never in a position of threatening to subjugate the entire Hel lenic states-system, as Persia was. Second, Carthage was a city-state, not a despotic empire. This was the single point of affinity between Carthage and the Greeks. She was a power of a kind they could appreciate from their own political experience, and admire as a particularly stable and effective specimen of the polis. It is remarkable that the three constitutions which Aristotle examines as approximat ing to the ideal are those of Sparta, Crete, and Carthage. Carthage had a mixed constitution, blending the advantages of aristocracy (merit), oligarchy (wealth) and democracy (numbers); it was un usually free from civil dissensions and from attempts at tyranny.155 Plato, with a similar admiration for political effectiveness, commends the Carthaginian law that forbade soldiers on active service from drinking liquor.158 Third, however, Carthage did not represent, as Persia did, a high .us
Hellas and Persia
1 05
culture. The political sphere apart, no Greek could write about Car thage as Herodotus or Xenophon wrote about Persia. Persia herself, her chivalry, her system of training the young, her imperial genius, claimed the admiration of philosophical Greeks ; and she had united in her commonwealth more ancient cultures from which the Greeks knew their own civilization was largely derived. This perhaps was the deepest reason why the Greeks felt themselves bound up with Persia in a way they were not with the barbarian great power of the West. In due course they transformed their states-system by the incorporation and hellenization of the Persian Empire. But perhaps it was not only due to the logic of power that in the second part of the story Rome, the successor of Alexander, completed his work by the destruction of Carthage as something utterly alien. 6. CONCLUSION
historic states-system may seem a tolerably clear and distinct kind of community, or set of relationships and practices, when we study its internal structure and organic life. But when we examine its penumbra, look at its connections with what lies beyond it, explore the scarcely definable gradations by which it shades into its cultural and diplomatic background, it begins to lose its coherence and iden tity, and doubts may arise about the validity of the concept itself of a states-system. This sketch of the relations between Greece and Persia suggests that the conventional picture of a system of Hellenic states, separated from the outer barbarian world by the possession of the Greek language, is in important respects inaccurate. Two reflections may be added about the Hellenic states-system in the wider sense in which it may be said to embrace Persia. The first concerns ideological conflict, and the second imperial authority, within this wider system. When two cultures and systems of power are as closely interdepen dent as the Hellenic states-system and the Persian Empire, their relations often appear, not as a conflict of civilized with barbarians, nor as a clash of civilizations, but as an ideological struggle within a single community. Thus the Hellenic states-system knew two kinds of ideological tension and ideological drive. One was that for which Thucydides used the word stasis151 in the sense of class-war, civil
A
1 06
Systems of States
war, revolutionary dissension cutting across the boundaries of states
and dividing the states--system horizontally as international war
divides it vertical}y. Plato proposed a different
use
of the word
stasis
when he said it ought to be employed for conflict within the core of the Hellenic states-system, and the word for war,
polemos,
reserved
for war between Greeks and barbarians ; as if wars between Greek
states would be transformed from the condition of inter-state war into the condition of civil war by exhorting philhellenes to think of
all Hellas as their homeland.us Demosthenes described something similar to Thucydides'
stasis
when ·he said that democracies could
never have lasting good relations with oligarchies, because oligarchies
by their very nature threatened the constitutions and liberties of democracies ; but he described the resulting conflicts by the word
polemos.159
But in addition to the conflict of democracy and oligarchy there was the conflict between hellenism and medism . The acuteness of
this second tension was in direct relation to the political and military pressure of Persia upon the states-system . It was at its greatest during the period of the Persian Wars, when it produced many medizing
individuals as well as states ; then it diminished, and reappeared in a milder form in the age of the King's Peace, with more hellenizing in Persia now than medizing in Greece. And the second conflict,
though distinct in its origin, had an inherent tendency to combine with and reinforce the first. Persia was the natural enemy of demo cracy, the natural supporter of tyrants at the end of the sixth century
and of oligarchies in the fourth.
The pressure of a barbarian Greek power upon a states-system will
tend to produce strains resembling ideological conflict, and rein forcing existing ideological conflicts . The ambiguities of Persia's
relations with the Hellenic states-system have resemblances to those of the Ottoman and Russian Empires with the Western family of
nations. Darius and Xerxes claimed and exercised more authority in Hellas than the Ottoman Sultan claimed or exerted in sixteenth century Europe, when nevertheless there were individuals as well as
provinces who turned Turk. And fourth-century Persia's role in the Hellenic states--system was as important as Russia's in the European system in the time since Catherine the Great, when there has been nevertheless a recurrent assertion of the view that, whether Tsarist or Soviet, she is a despotic barbarian outsider. To illustrate this assimila-
Hellas and Persia
ti.on of cultural to ideological conflict, I append a pleasant recon struction of the Persian Invasion of Greece in terms of Soviet radio bulletins during the Russo-Finnish War, which appeared in Punch in January 1 940, over initials one guesses to be those of Sir John Squire. The Persian Empire marks a historical watershed, Jaspers' Ach senzeit, scarcely less notable in the development of the West than the Roman Empire. When Cyrus the Great conquered Babylon, the decisive victory in the founding of the Empire, he ' heaped up the ancient titles ', stretching his hand back to the imperial figures of the past, Ur-Nammu and Hammurabi, Ashurbanipal and Nebuchad nezzar : ' I am Cyrus, the King of the universe, the Great King, the King of Babylon, the King of the land of Sumer and Akkad, the King of the four quarters of the world . . . ' (The Cyrus Cylinder in the British Museum). When two centuries later the pupil of Aristotle took over Cyrus's empire, his titles were more complex, varied and restrained. They were essentially three, and he kept them distinct, each requiring its own legal and constitutional procedure. He was hereditary king of Macedon ; he was nominally elected hegemon or generalissimo of the League of Corinth, the organization of the core of the Hellenic states-system ; and he was king of Asia by right of conquest.160 He seems to foreshadow the complexities of the political position of an Augustus, a Charles V, even perhaps a President of the United States in the age of NATO. This was the effect of the fusion of the most politically sophisticated of cultures with the greatest world-empire that had yet arisen. APPENDIX RADIO PERSIA CALLING,
480-479
B.C.
§ Propagandists of the capitalist aggressors of Athens and Sparta are
informing neutrals that we are at war with them. This is one more characteristic and propagandist lie. No war has been declared and the Greek incident is progressing towards a natural solution, namdy, the extermination of the Greek aggressors. § It is announced from the Greek Front that our Hero-Father
Xerxes has dug a canal through the Athos isthmus. This should be a
1 08
Systems of States
strong line of defence against the Greek Imperialists, who hate our Persian freedom and democracy. § Our beloved Xerxes, with the devoted help of our noble army, has thrown bridges across the Hellespont. This will thwart the criminal
Greek scheme of invading Persia by way of the Caucasus. The Athenian White Guards are in retreat, and everywhere the liberated populations are giving our men a frenzied welcome. § Yesterday happened the greatest incident in the Greek Incident.
A regiment of our Persian heroes advancing across the Plain of Ther mopylae encountered an immense army of Spartan capitalists under the command of the notorious aristocrat and White Guard Leonidas. As our men approached, it was seen that these effete Imperialists were too busy combing their hair to notice them. The effects of their surprise were overwhelming. The Greek aggressors offered only the slightest and most ineffective resistance and were slaughtered to a man. § To-day, in honour of the victory of our gallant Persian comrades
against overwhelming odds on the vast open plain at Thermopylae, our Beloved Hero-Father Xerxes has awarded himself the Highest Order of the Empire, which has never been earned by anybody else. § Last night our Beloved Xerxes received a cordial message from
the President of Carthage congratulating him on his glorious victory over the Spartan capitalist exploiters. § Messages from the Greek Incident Front report that Athens has
been captured without a blow. Our noble troops were received with immense enthusiasm by the population, with whom they shared their rations. § The Greek Incident may now be regarded as almost closed, and it
is probable that the workers of Greece will now unanimously vote for union with our democratic Persia, under our Hero-Brother, Father, and Uncle, Xerxes. A few Greek ships are still somewhere in hiding under the notorious liar and aristocrat Themistocles, but it is likely that our brave Persian sailors will shortly clear them out of their holes, after which the Greek Incident will be closed and the Athenian and Spartan oppressors, aggressors, reptiles and Egypto philes will have been cleared from the face of the earth.
Hellas and Persia
1 09
§ Messages from Salamis report that one of our brave Persian ships
has had a skirmish with the remaining Greek trawlers under the aiminal-pirate·traitor Thermistocles. The capitalist exploiters were driven off; a few of our beloved sailors were killed by Hellenophile Egyptologist treachery. Our dear Father Xerxes announces that the Greek Incident may now be regarded as almost closed, so that the greater part of our small reconnoitring expedition may now be withdrawn. § There is little to add to our last bulletin except that almost the
whole of our reconnoitring force in Greece is now in the process of withdrawal. A very small garrison has been left in Greece under the command of our Beloved Hero--Comrade Mardonius. § Our gallant Comrade Mardonius yesterday encountered a wan
dering band of Greek-capitalist-Imperialist-aristocrat-White-Guard exploiter reptiles at Plataea. The engagement was only a brush but entire! y successful, our noble comrades pushing on to another position. Our Beloved Hero-Leader Xerxes has consequently decided to with draw the last of the reconnaissance garrison platoons from Hellas, and states that the Greek Incident may now be regarded as entire! y closed. Medals have been distributed to all the troops, and our Beloved Xerxes has bestowed upon himself the Order of Xerxes (First Class). Indefatigable as ever, our Hero-Comrade will now devote himself to the suppression of the Hellenophile-Egyptologist sabotage by reptiles in Babylonia, where some remains of the aristo cratic exploiters whom we too mercifully failed to exterminate en tirely are endeavouring, though utterly in vain, to spread discontent by diabolical and rep_tilian lies amongst the liberated Babylonian workers . § P.S. - Fifteen Years Later. The abominable tyrant, reptile, White
Guard and Egyptologist Xerxes was jusdy executed to-day by our Hero-Brother Artabanus. Punch, January 1 940.
4
The origins of our states-system: geographical limits
The simplest speculation about the origins of the Western states system is about the question as to when it can be deemed to have come into existence. This is bound up with the question as to when modern history began. Guicciardini gave the answer which his authority made classic, in the opening words of the Storia d'ltalia ' lo ho deliberato di scrivere le cose accadute alla memoria nostra in Italia, dappoi che rarmi de' Franzesi, chiamate da' nostri Principi medesimi, cominciorono con grandissimo movimento a perturharla '. This embodied the widespread belief in Italy that 1494 had been a turning-point, a belief first expressed by two contemporary writers, the Florentine diplomatist Bernardo Rucellai, who had himself played a part in affairs, in his De Bello ltalico Commentarius, and the Milanese historiographer Bernardino Corio, in his Storia di :
Milano.
But the houses of Valois and Habsburg had an older cause of quarrel than Italy : Burgundy. Callieres observes that since the dis putes of France and Austria took their origin in the relations and treaties existing between the King Louis XI and Charles, the last Duke of Burgundy, from whom the House of Burgundy descends, it is vital that the negotiator of our time should be well acquainted with all the treaties made at that period and since '. It is said that when Louis XV visited the tomb of Mary of Burgundy at Bruges, he remarked, Here is the origin of all our wars '. But there seems to have been little contemporary recognition of the international signifi cance of Mary's marriage to Maximilian in 1 477· French writers were more concerned to record the national consolidation through the recovery of those parts of the Burgundian inheritance that Louis XI successfully seized. Commynes's stock of ideas, when he is moved to reflect, allow no more than a censure upon Louis's handling of the •
1
•
The origins of our states-system : geographical limits
r
11
Burgundian succession on the grounds that his military movements were oppressive to the French Kingdom.2 In his
Letters on the Study of History,
Bolingbroke seeks to dis
tinguish the point in time up to which a gentleman after which, if he is attached to the service of his
reads history, but country, he studies
it. He says that the chain of connexion between events sometimes seems to become broken, not only by extraordinary and violent occurrences, but also by slow and imperceptible changes. ' When such changes as these happen in several states about the same time, and consequently affect other states by their vicinity, and by many differ ent relations which they frequently bear to one another ; then is one of those periods formed, at which the chain spoken of is so broken as to have little or no real or visible connexion with that which we see continue.
A new situation,
different from the former, begets new
interests in the same proportion of difference ; not in this or that particular state alone, but in all those that are concerned by vicinity or other relations, as I said just now, in one general system of policy
.
.
•
The end of the fifteenth century seems to be just such a
period as I have been describing, for those who li�e in the eighteenth, and who inhabit the western parts of Europe'. 8 When he particular izes, he finds the beginning of modern history in the reign of Louis
XI, but the beginning of a states-system, recognizable by the balance
of power, in the rivalry of Charles V and Francis I . This is the classic doctrine, that the states-system originated about the end of the fifteenth century. It is an interpretation that attributes an impetus to Valois aggrandisement, seen both in the Burgundian succession and the invasion of Italy - to the assertiveness of those whom Polydore Vergil called ' Franci super omnes mortales, ampli andi imperii avidi ' ! From the conventional date of 1 4 94, rudimen� and premonitions of the states-system can be sought further back, and confirmations further forward. The Congress of Mantua pan-European gathering to
be
in
1 4 5 7-60 was the first
frustrated by the national egoism of
the powers. The Peace of Lodi and the Most Hoi y League of Venice in 1 4 54 founded the Italian Concert and the first system of collective security. The Turkish conquest of Constantinople confirmed the re-erection on the Bosphorus of an Eastern Empire which, expanding or declining, conditioned international relations for four and a half centuries to come. The Council of Constance was the last parade of
1 12
Systems of States
Latin Christendom presided over by an Emperor, as well as the first Council of the Church to be organized by ' nations '. In his introductory note to the first volume of the Cambridge Modern History, in 1 902, Creighton found the criterion of modern
times in a sense of familiarity : ' the period in which the problems that still occupy us came into conscious recognition, and were dealt with in ways intelligible to us as resembling our own . . . On the hither side of this line men speak a language which we can readily under stand ; they are animated by ideas and aspirations which resemble those animating ourselves ; the forms in which they express their thoughts and the records of their activity are the same as those still prevailing among us'. The Times Literary Supplemmt recendy reviewed the new reprint of the Cambridge Modern History, and described this ' classic vision ' as a ' breathtaking unreality Does a .
•
•
.
Luther, a Cromwell, a Louis XIV " speak a language we
can
readily understand " ? '6 But Mattingly uses the same argument in a more pointed form in 1 954· ' One may date the beginning of the
new time from the battle of Nicopolis, or of Agincourt, from the fall of Ceuta, or of Constantinople, from the Council of Constance or of Basle, from the martyrdom of John H uss or of Joan of Arc, but somewhere within the lifetime of Bernard du Rosier [ fl. 1 4 3 5 ] the forces which were to make the modern world began decisive! y to over-balance the old. Chief among these forces was the new territorial •
state with, as a notable weapon in its arsenal, the new diplomacy '. 8 In an earlier article, avowedly influenced by the events of the 1 930s, Mattingly placed the decisive break after 1 4 94, at the Failure of the Universal Peace of London of 1 5 1 8, which had concluded the first chapter of the Italian Wars. In June 1 5 22, as a result of Charles V's visit to England, the Emperor and Henry VIII joindy declared war upon France. ' And so ended . the last hope of Wolsey-s great scheme of European peace, the first European nonaggression pact, by which the powers sought to ward off the dangerous consequences of their own new strength . So ended, too, the last public expression of
•
the unity of Catholic Christendom. Before the guns were silent again, the Turks had overrun Hungary ; and England and half of the Teutonic North were no longer Catholic ' . 1 Another American writer, in a book about the Humanists, has marked the same point : ' As nearly as I
•
can
fix the moment, it was during these French
wars of 1 5 2 2-23 that the once grand medieval concept of a common
The origins of our statcs-syj·tem : geographical limits
1 13
Christendom finally expired and assumed the practical status of a myth. Perhaps few or no men then living were or could have been aware of it, but events speak with a clarion voice. To the Pope's anguished appeals the great Christian princes were not only indiffer ent, they were. . . now even incredulous. . . . From this moment on ward to our own day, broadly speaking, the Christian humanist concept of a good life based on reason and common justice (as in Utopia) has been submerged by a radically different and, internation ally speaking, frankly anarchic form of "reason" raison d'etat, which was progressively substituted for the ideal of justice common to and a right of all humanity. From 1 5 22 onward, all peaces would be, as Frederick Duval says, of iron, and the '' natural " relation of states would be chronic war'. 8 There is, however, an alternative conventional starting-point to 1494 : the Peace of Westphalia in 1 648. Westphalia became the legal basis of the states-system. Subsequent peace treaties, down at least to Teschen in 1 779, expressly confirmed Westphalia and were codicils thereto. Similarly, Italian peace treaties down to 1494 confirmed the Peace of Lodi. Satow says that the preambles of the treaties of Osnabrii ck and Munster introduced the Latin word 'con gressus' into international language. 9 In retrospect, Westphalia was believed to mark the transition from religious to secular politics, from ' Christendom ' to ' Europe', the exclusion from international politics of the Holy See, the effective end of the Holy Roman Empire by the virtual recognition of the sovereignty of its members, the formal admission of the United Provinces and the Swiss Confedera tion to the family of independent nations, and the beginning of the system of the balance of power. The prestige of Westphalia was buttressed by that of Grotius, whose reputation as father of inter national law was due to a work prompted by the same general war that Westphalia ended. It seems to have been Grotius, incidentally, who brought the word ' system ' into the vocabulary of international politics, though not yet in the sense of the whole diplomatic com munity.10 The Westphalian interpretation of the history of the states-system fits in with the doctrine that the Scientific Revolution marks a more important epoch in the general history of Europe than does the Renaissance. There has been much historical writing in the past generation to emphasize the international changes in the period -
1 14
Systems of States
following Westphalia, the 'emergence of the great powers ', the Military Revolution of 1 5 6o-1 66o, the rise of standing armies and the beginnings of conscription, the professionalization of diplomacy, the organization of foreign offices and of war finance. If it is seen as beginning after 1 648 rather than after 1494, the states-system wears a different aspect. Secularized politics, raison d'etat or national interest, and a multiple balance of power become the norm, and the ideological strife of the French Revolutionary period and the twentieth century an aberration. If we go back to 1494, though Machiavelli writes the foreword to the story, it quickly moves into a chapter he neither foresaw nor was capable of under standing, and we watch the states-system being shaped by the strains of four generations of doctrinal conflict, and of a bipolar balance of power. At the same time the Westphalian starting-point is itself eroded by the historiographical desire to establish continuity and the tendency for 'origins' to slide ever backwards in time. The turning-point may be found, for instance, in Richelieu's committing Louis XIII to war against the Habsburgs in 1 629 instead of to domestic reform and to extirpating heresy. Or Koenigsberger can say that ' the European state system was beginning to crystallize ' at the point where the Dutch abandon their search for a foreign sovereign and are accepted as equal partners in alliance by France and England.11 2
What eludes the grasp in these speculations is a criterion by which to identify the states-system. There are two theoretical questions, one concerned with chronological, one with geographical limits : 1 . What are the internal marks by which we will tell the states-system ? We can expect them to develop slowly, but we must have an idea of what we are looking for. 2. What are the boundaries of the field of en quiry ? What are the frontiers within which we expect to find the states-system ? Let us consider the second question first. h will serve to remind us that there is yet another conventional date besides 1494 and 1 648 for the beginning of modern international history : 1492. Whether or not we agree with Adam Smith that ' the discovery of America and
The origins of our states-system : geographical limits
1 15
that of a passage to the East Indies by the Cape of Good Hope, are
the two greatest and most important events recorded in the history of mankind ', those events largely governed the development of inter national society. If we lean towards the classic interpretation, we shall remember that these events occurred during the lifetime of Machiavelli, that in the preface to his greatest work he compared his own intdlectual adventure to the Great Discoveries, and that the pope who had to handle King Charles VIII when he entered Rome at the head of his armies on the last day of 1494 was the same pope who had already apportioned the new found lands between Portugal and Spain. If we lean towards the Westphalian interpretation, we shall say that the Nine Years War, because of its commercial aspects, was the first European conflict that extended to the rest of the world.12 Was the states-system, therefore, world-wide from the beginning ? Did it include all mankind ? Was Prester John (if he could be found)
a member of the society of princes ? Was the Grand Turk ? Was the Sultan of Bijapur, from whom the Portuguese wrested Goa ? Were Montezuma and Atahualpa ? Or if we descend to the lower date,
was the Great Moghul Aurungzeb ? Was the Emperor K'ang-hsi, who entertained the Jesuits ? Were the Six Nations of the Iroquois ? More to the point, was Alexis Michailovich,
tsar
of Muscovy ?
The orthodox answer to these questions is one that was worked out mainly in retrospect. It is the answer of the positivist phase of international law, which flowered in the nineteenth century, and its motive was
ad Europae maiorem gloriam.
' It is scarcely necessary to
point out ', pronounces W. E. Hall magisterially, ' that as interna tional law is a product of the special civilisation of modern Europe, and forms a highly artificial system of which the principles cannot be supposed to be understood or recognised by countries differently civilised, such states only can be presumed to be subject to it as are inheritors of that civilisation. They have lived, and are living, under law, and a positive act of withdrawal would be required to free them from its restraints. But states outside European civilisation must formal!y enter into the circle of law-governed countries. They must do something with the acquiescence of the latter, or of some of them, which amounts to an acceptance of the law in its entirety beyond
all
possibility of misconstruction . It is not enough consequently that they shall enter into arrangements by treaty identical with arrangements made by law-governed powers, nor that they shall do acts, like
1 16
Systems of States
sending and receiving permanent embassies, which are compatible with ignorance or rejection of law ' 1 8 Such a belief in the necessity of formal admission to the states-system lay behind article vii of the Treaty of Paris 1 8 56, in which the signatory powers 'declare the Sublime Porte admitted to participate in the advantages of the Public Law and System (Concert) of Europe , . Such reasoning equally underlay the spread of capitulations, those unequal treaties imposed .
by European powers, to exempt their subjects from local jurisdiction
in a non-European country. What I have called the orthodox answer was not confined to inter national lawyers stricti y of the positivist school. The great opposite
of W. E. Hall in his generation was James Lorimer, Regius Profes sor at Edinburgh of Public Law and of the Law of Nature and Nations, a splendid title, revived for him after the chair had been untenanted for 30 years.u H e distinguished his tenure by a deter
mined attempt, in the teeth of prevailing doctr:ID& south of the Border, to revive the principles of natural law. And it is he who gives the most lucid, comprehensive and philosophical statement of the orthodox answer : As a political phenomenon, humanity, in its present condition,
divides itself into three concentric zones or spheres - that of civil ised humanity, that of barbarous humanity, and that of savage humanity. To these, whether arising from peculiarities of race or
from various stages of development in the same race, belong, of right, at the hands of civilised nations, three stages of recognition plenary political recognition, partial political recognition, and natural or mere human recognition. I ntensively, the first of these forms of recognition embraces the two latter ; extensive! y, the third embraces the two former. The sphere of plenary political recognition extends to all the existing States of Europe, with their colonial dependencies, in so far as these are peopled by persons of European birth or descent ; and to the States of North and South America which have vindi cated their independence of the European States of which they were colonies. The sphere of partial political recognition extends to Turkey in Europe and in Asia, and to the old historical States of Asia which have not become European dependencies - viz. to Persia and the
The origins of our states-system : geographical limits
1 17
other separate States of Central Asia, to China, Siam, and Japan. The sphere of natural or mere human recognition, extends to
the residue of mankind; though here we ought, perhaps, to dis tinguish between the progressive and non-progressive races .
It is with the first of these spheres alone that the international jurist has directly to deal ; but inasmuch as jural progress consists not
merely
in
perfecting the
relations which
arise within
the sphere of political recognition, but in its gradual expansion, he
is
brought into continual contact with the external spheres, and
must take cognisance of the relations in which civilised communi ties are placed to the partially civilised communities which sur
round them. He is not bound to apply the positive law of nations
to savages, or even to barbarians, as such ; but he is bound to
ascertain the points at which, and the directions in which, bar
barians or savages come within the scope of partial recognition. In the case of the Turks we have had bitter experience of the conse
quences of extending the rights of civilisation to barbarians who
have proved to be incapable of performing its duties, and who
possibly do not even belong to the progressive races of mankind.
Should the Japanese, on the other hand, continue their present
rate of progress for another twenty years, the question whether
they are not entitled to plenary political recognition may have to be determined. 1 15
The orthodox answer, then, to the question about the limits of the
states-system, is that it was originally confined to Western Christen dom out of which it grew; that the European colonies in North and
South America became peripheral members of it when they attained independence ; that the first non-European state to be admitted was the Ottoman Empire in 1 85 6 ; that Persia, Siam, China and Japan (but not yet Ethiopia or Liberia) were admitted with different degrees of grudging patronage in the later part of the nineteenth century;
that this extension of the system beyond Europe and America first
received legal recognition in the Hague Conferences of 1 899 and 1 907 ;18 and that the transformation of the Western European system
into a world system was finally performed through the League of Nations and the United Nations.
This interpretation of international history was roundly attacked in 1 967 by C. H . Alexandrowicz.1 1 From a study of the treaty
1 18
Systems of States
relations between Christian and non-Christian powers, as well as of the classic controversy over the East Indies and the freedom of the seas between Grotius and the Portuguese publicist Seraphim de Freitas, Alexandrowicz concludes that the expanding European powers were compelled by the facts of the case to treat with the non-European powers in regular diplomatic relations, whose princi ples were derived as much from non-European practice as from European. Accordingly he emphasizes those European publicists who assert a legal community of the whole of mankind (including Burke's defence of the status of the Rajah of Benares !n the trial of Warren Hastings), and who argue that unequal treaties - veaties of protection, tribute or va ssalage - are not necessarily prej udicial to the sovereignty of the weaker party. ' The ideas of natural law and the universality of the family of nations had been inseparable compan ions ,, he says.18 They waned together as Europe grew powerful and arrogant, and yielded to the positivist doctrine that there is no inter national law save what states have ' posited ' in their recognized customs and express treaties, and the constitutive doctrine that new states derive their legal existence from the will of states already established, through the act of recognition. The argument has topical interest, with certain important legal consequences. Are the ' emergent ' states which have been emanci pated from colonial rule since 1 94 5 new creations, or recovering an ancient sovereignty ? Is Ceylon the legal successor of the Kingdom of Kandy ? Is the Republic of India the legal successor of the Maratha Confederacy, or of the Moghul Empire ? Is Algeria the successor of the Bey of Algiers, the Malagasy Republic of the Hova queens of lmerina, Indonesia of Sri Vijaya and Majapahit, Ghana of Ghana ? (Was Poland of 1 9 1 9 the legal successor of Poland of 1795 ? Was Portugal of 1 640 the legal successor of Portugal of 1 5 8 0 ?)19 Alexandrowicz 's thesis deserves careful and sympathetic scrutiny. All I offer here is an impression and some comments. The impression is that, in order to correct an interpretation of the history of the states-system that was exaggerated (as well as being today politically unfashionable), he exaggerates upon the other side. I believe that a proper view of the nascent states-system will be stereoscopic, seeing in the states-system a dual nature, two concentric circles, European and universal . The following reflections aim to describe aspects of this view, and to qualify Alexandrowicz's argument.
The origins of our states-system: geographical limits
1 rg
A. THE UNIVERSALISM OF WESTERN CHRISTENDOM
Obviously the states-system developed out of Western Christendom But the Western Christendom it developed out of was itself a peculiar culture. It combined universalist claims with a missionary dynamic. Perhaps China, or Byzantium, may be considered as having had universal claims also, since they considered the rest of the world to be actually or formally in a tributary status ; but they lacked the energy to give the claims effect. The Roman emperors had asserted in a general way that they were lords of the world, and the claim was formulated in the Digest. It descended to the Western Emperors as well as to their Byzantine rivals. It was asserted by the Hohenstau fen.20 But the Papacy trumped the imperial ace by playing the universality promised to the Christian religion. In the end it was the Vicar of Christ, not the emperor, who had the dominium mundi. ' I psius vox', said St Bernard, ' est hodie per universum mundum '. The earth is the Lord's, and the fullness thereof; 'ergo ', wrote a later papalist, ' er papae est terra et plenitudo ejus '.21 ' The papalist claim to world monarchy ', says Ulmann, ' was the direct result of the stimulus afforded by the crusades. '22 It is interest ing that the claim reached its full development under Innocent IV, in the mid-thirteenth century, when the expansionism of Western Christendom was temporarily exhausted, the Crusades had failed and the Latin kingdom of Jerusalem was lost, and the Mongols had conquered Poland and Hungary, defeated the duke of Silesia at Liebnitz and almost reached the Adriatic at Fiume. But as the tide of Mongol conquest ebbed, their Empire became a mission field. The Franciscans penetrated to Karakorum, and provided the first archbishop of Peking. The papal claims were the earliest version of the European assertion of superiority in the nineteenth century, and the missionaries were the forerunners of the conquistadors and the gunboats. And the most far-reaching exercise of papal world sovereignty was the four bulls of 1493 by which Alexander VI, in the plenitude of his apostolic authority, conferred on Ferdi nand and Isabella the dominion over lands discovered or to be discovered at one hundred leagues to the west and to the south of the Azores and the Cape Verde Islands. 2s Alexandrowicz mentions, but discounts, the ambiguity of this medieval universalism. The pope, according to the canonists, had rightful jurisdiction over all men, faithful and infidel alike. He had
1 20
Systems of States
the right of peaceful penetration into the infidel world, the right of unrestricted (and unreciprocable) missionary activity that Nehru afterwards complained about. He had a right of direct interference in non-Christian countries, to protect Christians there, to c�rrect misgovernment, and even in extreme cases to depose their rulers. The lofty language of the Roosevelt Corollary to the Monroe doc trine, 'Chronic wrongdoing, or an impotence which results in a general loosening of the ties of civilized society, may in America, as elsewhere, ultimately require intervention by some civilized nation ', is a secularized adaptation of the lofty language of the canonists. The final question was whether infidels had rightful dominion over their lands at all, and whether Christians might make conquests of them. It was debated theoretically in the thirteenth century, and with immediate practical bearing in the sixteenth, when Las Casas con fronted Sepulveda in the disputation at Valladolid. The canonists conceded, on the whole, that infidels were capable of acquiring rulership by prescription, and that it was wrong to use force against them, except to redress an injury received. But when the Christians were driven by greed of gain, and enjoyed technological superiority, it was easy for worse theory to prevail over better. B . THE UNRECI PROCATING WILL OF TH;E UNSPEAKABLE TURK
The doctrine of the universality of human society found its greatest obstacle, in the sixteenth century, in the peculiar relationship between Christendom and the Turk. Had Christendom been contiguous only with mild Hindoos, polished Chinese, and noble savages, it is possible that the two concentric circles would have blended into a homo geneous society with fewer convulsions; though the attitude of the Spaniards towards the repulsive civilization of the Aztecs, or of the Dutch and English colonists towards the Red Man, of whom it was being said already in the seventeenth century that the only good one was a dead one, give litde grounds for confidence. But the principal external society with which Christendom had to do, in the centuries when it was transformed into the states-system, was regarded by it as a historical, even an eschatological, embodiment of evil. Perhaps the deepest reason for this is the very similarity between the two cultures, both of them combining a universal faith with proselytizing zeal and energy, the very origin of Islam as the greatest and most successful of all Christian heresies. During the Middle
The origins of our states-system : geographical limits
121
Ages the Saracens were by many standards more civilized than the Frankish Crusaders, and there was fruitful cultural exchange be tween them in Spain and in the Levant. But by the sixteenth century the Saracens had given place to the Ottomans, who were both more primitive, and incomparably more powerful and dangerous to Western Christendom. Not only did they lead Islam ; they re·erected and enlarged the Greek Empire. But no Saracen ruler, and no Eastern Emperor, had threatened, like Bajazid, to feed his horse on the altar of St Peter's, and that he would come to France after he had finished with Austria. The Ottoman power in the second half of the fifteenth century was a threat to Christendom of a kind and scale that had never been known before. It is a commonplace that the Western powers quickly learnt to do business with the Grand Signior, and included him in their diplo matic machinations. Alexandrowicz quotes the remarkable letter of
Francis I to Paul III, in which he j ustifies the Franco--Oto t man alliance of I 535 by arguing that the Turks were not outside human society, that if nations were divided it was not by nature but by tradition and usages, and that diversity of cult and custom cannot destroy the natural association of humanity. ' Paroles glorieuses ', says Nys, ' qui ouvrent dignement l'epoque moderne '.24 All the same, they are typical of neither Western Christian nor Western European opinion. The generation of Pol ydore Vergil and Thomas More was very frightened of the Turk. More's
lation,
Dialogue of Comfort against Tribu
written in the Tower in I 5 34, takes the Turkish conquest of
Hungary as the great example of contemporary misfortune and misery. The simplest explanation of the Turkish danger, and one that had a long history behind it, was to identify the Turkish power as anti christ. This had much currency in Germany, which was in the front line. Luther had persuaded himself that the pope was antichrist, but the Turk could not be omitted. ' Antichrist is the pope and the Turk together ', he said, with a fine power of synthesis ; ' a beast full of life must have a body and soul ; the spirit or soul of antichrist, is the pope, his flesh or body the Turk ' . This was the reasoning of a beleaguered and fragmented Christen dom, not of the belief in human society. In the language of diplo macy Francis I, before he had found the advantage of a Turkish alliance, wrote to Leo X in I 5 I 6 about a crusade as communis
omnium Christianorum causa.
The notion of this common cause
1 22
Systems of Stotes
survived Lepanto. Grotius came off his naturalistic fence and asserted the obligation of all Christians to join an alliance against the enemies of Christianity, ' an impious enemy raging in arms . . . All Christians ought to contribute men or money, according to their capa�ity, ad
causam hanc commu n em '. 2 5
The common cause flickered into life
again in the Holy League of
1 6 84-99·
In his last speech in the
House of Commons, Burke used language that looks back to More and forwards to Gladstone, and is far more characteristic of the tradition of Western Christendom (be it said without any implication
of approval or blame) than Francis l's letter to Paul II I :
He had never before heard it held forth, that the Turkish empire was ever considered as any part of the balance of power in Europe. They had nothing to do with European power ; they considered themselves as wholly Asiatic. Where was the Turkish resident at our court, the court of Prussia, or of Holland ? They despised and condemned all christian princes, as infidels, and only wished to subdue and exterminate them and their people. What had these worse than savages to do with the powers of Europe, but to spread war, destruction, and pestilence amongst them ? 26
Burke here pointed to a curiosity of the international position of the Ottomans. Though Turkey had been in a sense part of the diplomatic community ever since the Venetians and the pope first intrigued with it in the fifteenth century a generation before the French alliance, it had never yet entered upon that regular exchange of diplomatic representatives that was the test of full membership. But this revealed a deeper disharmony. Turkey professed an in tolerant creed, preventing it from accepting what Lorimer called ' the postulate of coexistence ', and excluding ' the presumption of a reciprocating will '. During the great Eastern Crisis, at the beginning of the academic session of I 8 77-8, Lorimer regaled his class of public law with an introductory lecture entitled ' Does the Coran supply an Ethical Basis on which a Political Superstructure can be Raised ? ' The answer was a resounding no, because ' the premises from which a Mussulman deduces his rules of conduct towards an unbeliever are precisely the converse of those from which he deduces his rules of conduct towards a believer '. This was the reason for ' what we often talk of as the inconceivable obstinacy and bad faith of the Turks ' . 27
The origins of our states-system: geographical limits C.
1 23
Tll!.ATIES OP CESSION
For all the treaties that Alexandrowicz examines, it seems that Christian Europeans approached the non-Christian world with a c:lliierent set of assumptions from th�se with which they approached one another. Here is one piece of negative evidence, one question that Alexandrowicz fails to ask. It seems to have become established within Europe, by the end of the fifteenth century, that a conquest needed to be sealed, and given . legal effect, by an act of cession, normally embodied in the peace treaty concluding the war. Under the Treaty of Bretigny, 1 360, for example, which marked the high point of Edward III's conquests in France, the king of France ceded to the king of England Guyenne, Gascony, Poitou, etc., in full sovereignty, together with Pontheiu, Calais and Guines. Under the Treaty of Bagnolo, 1484, which ended the War of Ferrara, the duke of Ferrara ceded Rovigo and the Polesina to Venice. But when Albuquerque seized Goa from the Sultan of Bijapur in I 502, no treaty of cession followed. Let me assert the negative to invite cor rection. Alexandrowicz cites the standard collection of Portuguese treaties, but no treaty conferring legal possession of Goa is to be found there. The Portuguese viceroy at Goa was later in treaty relations on behalf of his sovereign with the Sultan of Bijapur, as with other Indian powers, and this might be taken (and perhaps was by the Portuguese) as signifying tacit acquiescence in his presence. But it seems that a state of affairs which within Christendom would have been regularized, in partibus infidelium was not considered by the Christians to require regularizing. The Republic of India does not appear to have made use of this argument in the debate concern ing its seizure or recovery of Goa in I 96 I . D. PA.IX MARITIMES AND PA.IX CONTINENTALES
Diplomatic practice recognized the dual nature of international society in a more regular and important manner. A distinction was sometimes made in the eighteenth century between pair maritimes and paix continentales, since it was in the eighteenth century that the struggles for mastery in the two regions, Britain and France overseas, and Austria and Prussia in Germany, diverged most widely. Thus the Anglo-French treaties of 1 748, 1 763 and 1783 were all classified as pair maritimes.28 But the distinction went back very nearly to the classic beginning of the states-system.
1 24
Sy_stems of States
The first round of the Italian Wars, from 1 4 94 to I 5 I6, was pursued separately from the exploration and delimitation of the Eastern and Western Indies by Portugal and Spain. But in I 5 20 Cortes sent to the king of Spain the first of Montezuma's treasure, the treasure that Diirer marvelled at in Brussels; in 1 5 2 I he conquered Mexico City ; in 1 5 22 the second round of the Italian Wars began; in I 53 5 Pizarro conquered Peru. As the resources of the Indies slowly began to affect the European struggle, the European struggle began to send its repercussions through the Indies. The Peace of �brai, I 5 29, was perhaps the last peace settlement between the great powers that could ignore the trans-European penumbra of the states system. During the uneasy peace that followed, in 1 534, Jacques Cartier discovered and charted the gulf of the St Lawrence, thus breaching the Spanish monopoly of America. During the third round of the Italian Wars, which began with the French invasion of Savoy in I 536, Francis I sent Roberval on Cartier's third voyage, as viceroy of Canada, Newfoundland and Labrador, and the French seized a treasure fleet coming to Spain from Cortes. The Peace of Crepy, 1 544, was the first to be a paix maritime as well as continen tale. The French, whose fortunes were at a low ebb, undertook to abandon Canada, and to respect the rights of the Spaniards and the Portuguese in all the Indian lands. Fifteen years later, at the Peace of Cateau-Cambresis, 1 5 59, the two circles of the states-system acquired a form of diplomatic recog nition that remained lasting. Despite their momentary concession at Crepy, the French had hitherto insisted that title to overseas terri tories came not from discovery but from occupation and settlement, that the line of demarcation between Portugal and Spain under the Treaty of Tordesillas, I494, was not part of the public law of Chris tendom but a private agreement between the two crowns, and that the preceding papal bulls and subsequent papal confirmation added nothing to its force. In the negotiations at Cateau-Cambresis, where the French bargaining position was stronger than it had been at Crepy, the positions of the two great powers on this issue were irreconcilable. But they could agree to safeguard the European peace, which both sides needed, from the consequences of continued dis agreement about the Indies. In a verbal arrangement, that formed no part of the treaty, the delegates decided on the meridian of the Azores and the tropic of Cancer as a line, to the west and south of '
Th � origins of our states-sysum : geographical limits
I
25
which acts of hostility would not violate the treaty nor constitute grounds for complaint, and whoever was strongest would pass for master. Thus the papal ' lines of demarcation ', which in theory or legend was an arbitral award to preserve peace, gave way to the 'amity lines ', which divided the zone of peace from the zone of war. Other powers besides France, especially England, appealed to the arrange ment. Its original meaning was negative and concessive; it acquired a new interpretation, positive and permissive. ' No peace beyond the line ' became almost a rule of international law, giving freedom to plunder, attack and settle without upsetting the peace of Europe. Its original application, moreover, was to the West Indies, the realm of those whom Lorimer was to designate as savages; but it was soon extended to the East Indies, where the great European companies circled round the kingdoms of the barbarians. No better conventional date for the appearance of the dual states-system could be found than Cateau-Cambresis, I 55 9. In the twentieth-century states-system, divided still concentrically between the world city and the world rural district, the amity lines have reappeared. One of the unwritten understandings of the Cold War has been that the peace of Europe shall be warily preserved while the struggle is pursued for influence and position throughout the Third World. E. niE DUAL STATES-5YSTEM IN GllOTIUS
The dual aspect of the states-system is at last formulated, like so many other things, though clumsily, by Grotius. On the one side there had been the Respublica Christiana. Every body knew what this was. Though its legal unity was broken by the Reformation, it was a historical and cultural unity; the religious wars were its internal wars; Poland-Lithuania belonged to it but Muscovy did not. It was appealed to in the Treaty of Vervins ; it did not appear, perhaps significantly, in the Treaties of Westphalia ; it last appeared in the Treaty of Utrecht. On the other side were the visionary asserters of natural law and the unity of the human race. ' Totus orbis, qui aliquo modo est una republica ', said Vitoria. ' The human race ', said Suarez, ' though divided into no matter how many different peoples and nations, has for all that a certain unity, a unity not merdy physical, but also in a
Sysums of States sense political and moral. This is shown by the natural precept of mutual love and mercy, which extends to all men, including foreign ers of every way of thinking. Wherefore, though any one state, republic or kingdom be in itself a perfect community and constant in its members, nevertheless each of the states is also a member, in a certain manner, of the world, as far as the human race is concerned '. Similarly Fenelon : ' Toutes les nations de la terre ne sont que les differentes families d'une meme republique dont Dieu est le pere commun ' . 29
Grotius puts the two together. He asserts a common interest of the human race, and a law of nature that binds it. ' If other ties are wanting, sufficit humanae naturae communio '.so The last and widest reason for taking up arms, is
hominum inter se conjunctio, ' the
connexion of men with men as such, which alone is often sufficient to induce them to give their aid'. 8 1 Thus treaty relations with infidels were lawful, and even encouraged by the Gospel, 82 and conquest of infidels on the grounds that their lands are
terra nullius, that they
are immoral, or have wrong notions of God and dull intellects, or are natural enemies, is unlawful . ss There is a mutua gentium inter se societas," a communis societas generis humani.35
But within human society, there is a particular bond uniting Christian states. ' All Christians are members of one body, who are bidden to bear each other's sufferings and sorrows. Just as this principle applies to individuals, so it applies to peoples qua peoples, and to kings
kings. For every man ought to serve Christ not only personally, but also with the power entrusted to him ' .18 Among Christians in general it has been established that captives of war are not to be enslaved.87 Again, it is the duty of Christians to abstain
qua
from such violence as storming cities : ' The tie of Christians among each other is closer than that of the ancient Greeks, and yet there was an Amphyctionic decree that in their wars no Greek city should be destroyed '. 88 But the most important reference to the Christian community (which Grotius does not call the Respublica Christiana) is this : Especiall y are Christian kings and princes bound to try this way of avoiding war [viz. arbitration] . For if both Jews and Christians appointed arbiters for themselves, in order to avoid judgment by judges not of the true faith, and Paul prescribes the practice, how
The origins of out' statespsystem : geographical limits
1 27
much more should this be done to avoid a much greater disadvan tage, namely, war . . . For this and other reasons it would be useful, indeed it is almost necessary, to hold certain congresses (conventus) of Christian Powers, in which disputes may be settled by those who do not have an interest in them, where in fact measures may be taken to compel the disputants to accept peace on equitable tenns.89 Trying to pick a path once again through the baroque thickets of Grotius's work, where profound and potent principles lurk in the shade of forgotten arguments and obsolete examples like violets beneath overgrown gigantic rhododendrons, I find that he does not say what I thought he said. Inaccurate memory suggested that he described the possibility, within the universal society of the human race, of subordinate societies of states bound by regional variants of the jus gentium : a multi-cultural or multipcivilizational international society. He does not say quite this. When he distinguishes between narural law and jus gentium, he says that scarcely any law apart from natural law is common to all nations. ' Indeed ', he adds, ' often in one part of the world there prevails a jus gentium that is not found in another '. But he does not relate this variety of law that he glimpse& to difference of culture. He has just defined jus gentium as ' law which has received an obligatory force from the will of all nations, or of many ' .40 The only regional or civilizational systems of law whose possibility he recognizes are versions of divine law. 'There is one nation in particular to whom God has given his laws, the Jews'.41 And there is the law of Christ, the last of the three sets of law given by God to the human race.42 Being of divine origin, Christianity has a special status, and Christians have the benefit of the doubt in their relations with infidels. 'No right whatever is sufficient to warrant what may be considered harmful, directly or indirectly, to religion. For we must seek in the first place the kingdom of God, that is, the propagation of the Gospel ' .u In several places Grotius describes limited grouping of states. ' The association (consociatio) of several peoples, either by themselves or by their heads, is a league (fedus) '. 44 'Between contracting parties there is a closer society than the common society of mankind '. 4� He is thinking of what we would call alliances, though giving much
Systems of States weight to semi-permanent alliances like the Peloponnesian League and the Achaean Confederacy; it is for these that he borrows the word systema. ' Again it can happen, that several peoples have the same head, though each of these peoples constitutes a perfect com munity. For though in a natural body there cannot be one head for several bodies, there may be in a moral body '. 46 Here he is thinking of a cluster of sovereignties held by a single Habsburg, or of the British Commonwealth. These descriptions do not apply to Christendom or any similar cul� tural grouping. It is true that he himself goes on, a little later, to speak of Christendom as a league. He says that Christian princes need to help one another against infidel aggression, ' which cannot conveniently be done, unless a fedus is made for that purpose ; such a fedus was made a long time ago, and the leader of it was created by common consent, Roman Emperor ' .47 But here, using a faulty historical argument, he momentarily degrades Christendom to make it fit one of his political categories. He does not conceive categories to fit Christendom and its rivals. To conclude : Grotius presents the dual or concentric conception of international society. There is an outer circle that embraces all man kind, under natural law, and an inner circle, the corpus Christian arum, bound by the law of Christ. The inner circle is unique. Grotius still accepts implicit! y the traditional Christian view . of history, and does not have sufficient knowledge qf the non-European world to develop a more complex picture.
5 The origins of our states-system: chronological limits
The first part of this paper [i.e. Chapter questions :
1.
above - Ed. ] put two
4
What are the internal marks by which we would be
able to recognize our states-system, when we scan the past for its first appearance ?
2.
What are the geographical limits within which
we look for such marks ? On the latter question, the first part of this paper then made some disconnected observations. Here answer the former question. We must remember that when we
' scan
I
shall try to
the past ' we are not
scanning a void, expecting a new object to swim into it. We are scanning a society, that of Western Europe, in slow but constant change. By the time of the Congress of Utrecht,
1 7 1 2-I 3,
the
international articulation of Western Europe had become manifestly different from what it had been at the time of the Council of Con stance,
I 4 14- I 8 ;
the states-system is there.
I
suggest that its internal
marks, which have become progressive! y dearer during those three centuries, are first, sovereign states ; second, their mutual recognition ; third, their accepted hierarchy ; fourth, their means of regular com munication ; fifth, their framework of law ; sixth, their means of defending their common interests.
I . SOVEREIGN STATES The nununum condition of a states-system is the presence of a multitude of sovereign states. Historians of political thought have been traditionally interested mainly in the notion of political obligation, the authority of the ruler and the rights of subjects. They have traced the development of internal sovereignty, of a supreme law-making authority in each
1 30
Systems of States
community. Marsiglio of Padua marks an important stage on this road. We are more concerned with the development of external sove- . reignty, the claim to be politically and juridically independent of any superior. On this road, a similar place to that of Marsiglio is marked by his slighdy younger contemporary, Bartolus of Sassoferrato ( 1 3 1 3-5 7), the prince of civilians. A doctor of Roman Law, deeply respecting his text, he was concerned also to adapt its truths to a historical situation in which the Holy Roman Empire was in full decay. He recognized that a city-state that did not acknowledge the emperor as overlord, and whose citizens were free people, was itself its own emperor, ipsamet civitas sihi princeps est.1 In his time the formula rex in regno suo est imperator regni sui became current. It used to be thought to have originated in Italy, but it has now been pushed back to French origin, in the conflict between the papacy and Philip the Fair at the beginning of the century. Bartolus also made a famous assertion, that it is probably a heresy to deny that the emperor is the lord of the world. Grotius thought it worth dismissing as ' stultum ', 2 and it has sometimes been taken as evidence of the doctrinaire nature of fourteenth-century imperialist lawyers. It has been left for a very recent writer to make the observa tion that this ' is not a quibble to save the face of the imperial laws : it is a reminder that political thought implies the consideration of problems not only of national but also of international government'.8 However, to assert their independence of the Empire was not necessary for the more important of the emergent states of Europe, and particularly the great national monarchies of Western Europe, which had never acknowledged the Empire's overlordship. Though probably a majority of the ' states ' of Europe were nominally within the Empire, they were smaller and less powerful. Those in Italy did not find it difficult to reduce imperial suzerainty to nothing. Only those in Germany had to traverse the Wars of Religion and the Thirty Years War before arriving at the same end. The international framework of the system that preceded the states-system was provided, not by the fictitious Empire, but by the Church . The sentence needs to be modified in two respects which show how our vocabulary for discussing these things itself presup poses the states-system within which it has grown up. The word ' international ' is anachronistic when applied to the Middle Ages :
The origtns of our states-system: chronological limits
"
(
I3I
we need another word, perhaps ' ecumenical ' would serve. And what the Church provided was more than a framework . ' The real State of the Middle Ages in the modern sense - if the words are not a paradox - is the Church ', said Figgis. ' There was no doubt that the canonists meant by the [pope's] plenitudo potestatis everything that the modern means by sovereignty '. 4 The modern secular sovereign states-system arose from the ruins of the medieval international papal monarchy. The dividing line between the two is clearly marked by the Council of Constance, which is as far hack as one need go in the search for the origins of the states-system. The chief aim of the Council of Constance was to heal the Great Schism. This had divided Latin Christendom into two - and later three - obediences under rival popes. It inevitably strengthened the secular powers. They now had some freedom in choosing their pope, and could make him pay for their support. Lorenzo the Magnificent afterwards observed, ' The division of power is advantageous and, if it were possible without scandal, three or four Popes would be better than a single one '. 6 The growth of national churches and Erastian principles in due course gave his thought a fulfilment he did not foresee. Nevertheless, the public opinion of Christendom, which was perhaps the same as the interests of the Church, demanded an end to the Schism, as well as a more general reformation of the Church. At Constance, then, there was a three-cornered struggle : public opinion, led by the reforming party, the reunited papacy, and the secular powers. The first had hoped to use the last to discipline the second. What happened was that the second allied with the third to frustrate the first, and was itself soon subordinated to the third. The Council of Constance was not yet an international congress, but it was very nearly so. It was a General Council of the Church, . with the aim of reforming the Church ; at the same time it had an unprecedented amount of secular business. It was composed primar ily of bishops and abbots, but doctors, i.e. the intelligentsia from the universities, and princes also had the vote. There were interesting questions of procedure, which foreshadow much that becomes fami liar later. To counteract the preponderance of Italians, the English proposed to organize the Council according to ' nations ', a principle borrowed from the universities, and the proposal was accepted. The nations were four large regional groupings : Italy, France, Germany (which included the Scandinavian countries), and England (which
Syst�ms of Stat�s included the other British countries). When the Spaniards arrived late, they made their attendance conditional on being recognized as a fifth nation. Matters were first discussed by each nation separately, then by a general congregation formed of an equal number of deputies from each nation. After three years of the Council, when it had removed three popes and elected a new canonical pope in their stead, its capacity to put through a programme of reform had dwindled to nothing. It allowed reforms to be agreed bilateral! y between the new pope, Martin V, and each nation. To these agreements the new name of concordat was given. The content of the concordats was not very important, and the English government had already unilaterally enacted what it wanted in the statutes of Provisoes and Praemunire 50 years before. But the concordats carried an assumption of diplomatic equality between the pope and the nations, and hastened the process by which the secular princes usurped many papal rights of presenting to bene fices, controlling appeals and taxing the local clergy. Thus they forwarded the transformation of the international papal monarchy into a system of secular states. There is one other respect, possibly the most important of all, in which the Council of Constance foreshadows the experience of the states-system. It is the greatest attempt before the League of Nations to provide a legal and regular constitution for the international sys tem, a constitution on constirutionalist principles.8 Again, our politi cal vocabulary is inadequate for writing in the same sentence about the states-system and its medieval precursor. The Council of Con.6 stance does not yet inaugurate the states-system. It is the last Ecu menical Council of undivided Latin Christendom, whose failure to effect reform of the Church makes revolution inevitable. It attempts to reform the international system of Christendom, which is the papally-centralized Church. Its failure leads direcdy to the break down of the system and to rebellion within the Church. The reforming party, who dominated the early days at Constance, was composed of highly intdligent and rational academics with a powerful political doctrine. The only way to deal with the scandalous siruation of three rival popes was to appeal to the older, latent authority of a general council. A council had the right to correct and even depose a scandalous pope. Gerson, Pierre d'Ailly, and Nicholas of Cusa have a notable intellecrual resemblance to Lord Robert Cecil,
The origins of our states-system : chronological limits
I 33
Gilbert Murray, and Norman Angell, as apostles of a League of Nations that had the right and duty, as a last resort, to impose sanc tions on a lawless great power. The Council of Constance culminated in the decree Sacrosancta (14 15); ' The Council of Constance, an ecumenical council, derives its power direct from Christ, and all men, including the pope, are bound to obey it in matters of faith '. Figgis called it ' Probably the most revolutionary official document in the history of the world . . . . striving to turn into a tepid constitutionalism the Divine authority of a thousand years. The movement is the culmination of medieval constitutionalism. It forms the watershed between the medieval and modern world '. 7 Sacrosancta was followed by the decree Frequens (14 17) which laid down that general councils should henceforward be regular : the next in five years time, the next after that in seven years, by which time the reform of the Church might be completed, and thereafter every ten years. Figgis saw the Conciliar Movement as the precursor of the consti tutional principles which later triumphed in the Netherlands and in England, against the autocratic principles of the restored popes, Martin V and Eugenius IV. 'Eugenius IV is the forerunner of Louis XIV '. But the Conciliar Movement is the precursor too of the con stitutional principles which have never yet transformed international life. Frequens was so far observed that in 1423 a council was sum moned at Siena, but at once prorogued; after the prescribed seven years another met at Basle, which quick! y ran into conflict with Eugenius IV, was dissolved, resisted, elected the last of the anti popes, and protracted a futile and invalid existence for another ten years to disappear in 1 449. That was the end of the Conciliar Move ment. It left a strengthened papacy on a narrower foundation, and an international anarchy of strengthened secular powers. A subjective awareness of an international anarchy provides some evidence for the existence of a multitude of sovereign states, though not yet for a states-system. Perhaps the earliest description of inter national anarchy is one which comes immediately after the end of the Conciliar Movement, and dates appropriately from 1454, the year of the Peace of Lodi, the conventional beginning of the Concert of Italy. The fall of Constantinople the previous year had created general concern and a desire for European pacification. Nicholas V had issued a summons to a crusade. The Emperor Frederick
1 34
Systems of States
III organized a European congress at Regensburg, inviting France, England, Scotland, Denmark, Poland and Hungary, as well as the powers of Italy and Gennany. Most ignored the invitation ; some sent excuses (Christian of Denmark, for instance, that he was engaged in an expedition against Norway) ; Frederick himself found it conve nient to stay away; the only great powers, if the term may be used, who attended, were Philip of Burgundy in person, and representa tives of Casimir IV of Poland, who came, however, to prosecute the Polish dispute with the Teutonic Knights. The Congress met in May 14 54, made some fictitious schemes for joint action, and agreed to meet again in September. Aeneas Sylvius had been a member of the Imperial delegation, and a few days after the Congress had dis solved he wrote a pessimistic letter to a friend in Italy, as follows : You will say that the hope of successful action depends upon whether it is a well-attended congress (conventio grandis) or whether few Powers turn up. What do you think ? How do you see the future ? I prefer to hold my peace. I would rather my opinion were totally wrong - to be proved a false than a true prophet. All the same, I shall tell you my own presentiments. I do not hope for what I would like. I cannot persuade my own better judgment. You ask, why ? I answer, why should I entertain rosy hopes ? Christendom has no head, whom everybody is willing to obey. Neither the Pope nor the Emperor is rendered what is his due. There is no reverence, no obedience. We look on Pope and Emperor alike as names in a story or figures in some picture. Each state has its own king. There are as many rulers as there are prince! y families. How will you persuade as many leaders as there are in the Christian world to take up arms ? Let us just suppose that all these kings join together for war. How will you organise the command ? What order will there be in the army ? How are military discipline and obedience to be maintained ? How can such a host be provisioned ? Who will understand the different lan guages, and control the different national customs ? Who will reconcile the English with the French, Genoa with Naples, the Germans with the Bohemians and Hungarians ? If you lead a small army against the Turks, you will be easily defeated ; if it is a large one, you will be lost in confusion. On every side there are prob lems.8
The origins of our states-system : chronological limits
1 35
2. MUTUAL RECOGNITION
It would be impossible to have a society of sovereign states unless each state, while claiming sovereignty for itself, recognized that every other state had the right to claim and enjoy its own sovereignty as well. This reciprocity was inherent in the Western conception of sovereignty. It was confirmed by the legalism of feudal society, with its asswnption that every potentate has his rights, notwithstanding cantiWl�_l litigation vi et armis concerning conflicts of rights. Aqui nas, in a iscussing the limits of the proposition that all men are bound by law, observes as a matter of fact that ' the citizens of one city or realm are not bound by the laws of the ruler of another city or realm, just as they do not come under his dominion '. There were two com plementary principles : Chacon est maitre chez soi; personne n'est mattre hors de chez soi. 9 From the fourteenth to the eighteenth centuries it was assumed that the states of Western Christendom fell into al!_ierarch y. Feudal society was hierarchical ; the society of princes, though each claimed to acknowledge no superior, likewise ' observed degree, priority, and place, office and custom, in all line of order'. Hence the rules of the papal curia, with their tables of the rdative dignity of the monarchs and republics of Christendom.10 Hence the recurrent disputes be tween powers about precedence. The movement from a hierarchical to an egalitarian principle was probably inherent in the reciprocal recognition of sovereignty. Books have been written about the development of the doctrine of the equality of states.11 It was helped forward when Sweden entered the Thirty Years War as the enemy of the Holy Roman Emperor and the ally of the premier king of Europe, to neither of whom would she concede precedence, asserting the equality of all crowned heads. It was furthered by the confirmation of sovereign powers for the estates of the Empire at Westphalia, their acquiring the right to make their own foreign policies and, with Leibniz as their advocate, to equal diplomatic representation with other powers at the Congress of Nymwegen. It was formulated at last by Wolff, ' Natura gentes omnes inter se aequales sunt ',12 and more fully by his disciple Vartel : Puisque les hommes sont naturellement egaux, et que leurs droits et leurs obligations sont les memes, comme venant egalement de Ia
Systems of States
I
Nature, les Nations composees d'hommes, et considerees comme autant de personnes libres qui vivent ensemble dans l'etat de Nature, sont naturellement egales, et tiennent de la Nature les memes obligations et les memes droits. La puissance ou la faiblesse ne produisent, a cet egard, aucune difference. Un Nain est aussi bien un homme, qu'un Geant : Une petite Republique n'est pas moins un Etat souverain que le plus puissant Royaume.u This facile and uncritical statement conceals rather than reveals that the doctrine of the equality of states can mean no more than that all states recognize the right of all other states to equal treatment in law and in ceremony. The levelling of the international community was completed by the French Revolutionary and Napoleonic Wars. The abolition of the Holy Roman Empire removed the ancient president of the European Republic ; the defeat of Imperial France ended the pretensions of the Empire's ancient rival. The Congress of Vienna replaced the hierarchy by length of appointment between diplomatic representatives resident in each foreign post, and alphabetical order of states in the French language for signature of treaties. It is ironical that the same Congress that introduced this rational and egalitarian system, first also formal! y recognized the grading of states according to their power. 3. GREAT POWERS
The grading of powers is a matter of !heory. The managerial func tion of the great powers is a matter of practice. It is convenient to treat the two separately, since )ack of evidence prevents more than speculation about how they may have interacted upon one another. The earliest grading of powers known to me is in terms of political organization. Bartolus laid it down that there are three classes of state : 1 . Magna in primo gradu magnitudinis ; such are city-states, which ought to be direct democracies ; 2. Major, et sic in secunda gradu magnitudinis ; such are states too large by their extent of territory for direct democracy, like Venice or Florence; they are best governed by aristocracies ; 3· Maxima, et sic in tertia gradu magnitu dinis ; these are so large that it is necessary for their good government and unity to be ruled by monarchs. 14 The threefold classification of
The origins of our states�system : ch ronological limits
137
governments is commonplace. What seems not to be commonplace is the argument that each form of government can be appropriate, according to the size of state.u In thct. fifteenth century Concert of Italy the notion of a great power was fa41iar, and the phrase was taking shape. Commynes reports Lodovico il Moro, when he welcomed Charles VII I at A�ti in Sep tember 1 494, as having encouraged the French king with these words : ' En Ytalie, [il y] a trois puissances que nous tenons grandes, dont vous avez l'une, qui est Milan. L'autre ne bouge, qui sont Veniciens. Ainsi n'avez a faire que a cdle de Napples '1 8 Machiavelli speaks of ' i maggiori principi', Guicciardini of ' i maggiori Potentati '.17 I do not doubt that such phrases could be found earlier in the diplomatic documents. But the Italians were keenly aware that their classification was relative to their own little world : the true great powers lay beyond the Alps. Lodovico imme diately goes on to say to Charles VIII, sycophantically, of the Italian great powers : ' et plusieurs de vos predecesseurs nous ont batuz, quant nous estions tous ensemble '. During the period, roughly from 1 4 94 to 1 5 29, when the Italian states-system is losing its existence in a wider European system, the difference of status seems to coincide with the difference of religion : Italy is the field of the more important small powers ; France, Spain, the Emperor, England, perhaps the Swiss, are the great powers. But as the House of Habsburg and the French kingdom rear themselves ever higher above the rest, the class of great powers becomes overlaid and lost beneath these two dominant powers. Various phrases for describing them become current, and last through the seventeenth century, when circumstances are greatly changed. Burghley in his state papers generally calls them ' the two Monarchies'. Fulke Greville calls them ' these two Emperiall great nesses '. Rohan describes them as ' the two Poles, from whence des cend the influences of peace and war upon the other states '. Sir William Temple calls them ' the two Great Crowns ', Bolingbroke simply ' the two great powers '. I have not found any common dipl� matic phrase that admits to their company Elizabethan or Cromwell ian England, or the steadier greatness of the United Provinces, or the Sweden of Gustavus Adolphus.18 Diplomatic theory was conserva� tive, remaining well in the rear of the changes in relative power. The only power that was seen, by some writers, as in the same .
•
•
·
Systems of States class as Spain and France, was the Ottoman Empire. Botero begins his Ragione di Stato (1 5 89) with the ' divisions of dominion ' : per haps the first classification of states in terms of international power rather than domestic politics : Some dominions are small, others large, others medium; and these are not absolute but comparative, and with respect to their neigh bours. So a little state is one that is not able to maintain itself alone but has need of protection and of the suppon of another, as the Republic of Ragusa, and of Lucca. A medium one is that which has force and authority sufficient to maintain itself without the need of the help of another, as the Dominion of the Signory of Venice, the Kingdom of Bohemia, the Duchy of Milan, and the County of Flanders. Then we call those states great which have ' notable advantage over their neighbours, as the Turkish Empire, and that of the Catholic King .19 The examples of medium powers were obsolete at the time he wrote, and his two great powers were what today we call super-powers. Campanella described them a few years later in terms of unive���l ambitions : ' casa d' Austria e casa Ottoman aspirano alia somma delle cose umane ' .20 A more realist description was given a little later in the Discours des princeJ et estatJ de la Ch retientl of 1 623 or 1 624, which was the original for much of Rohan's De l'interet des princes et etats de la ch retiente of 1 638. ' Les grands puissances qui tiennent en contre poids Ies autres princes de Ia chrestiente sont les Maisons de France et d'Autriche : car ce sont les seuls qui peuvent sans secours d'autrui faire la guerre et l'entretenir tant qu'elles veulent, ne manquant pour cet effet ni d'hommes ni argent' .21 Thus, if we allow Campanella's criterion of universal aspiration to be the equivalent of the 'general interests' asserted by the great powers at the Par:is Peace Conference in 1 9 I g, and the independent war making capacity postulated by the Discours as a forerunner of the Raiikean ability ' to maintain itself against all others, even when they are united ', 22 we can say that the two principal modern definitions of great power status go back to the beginning of the seventeenth century. Let us return from theory to practice, and consider Hedley Bull's criterion of a managerial function. Let us notice, also, the grim way
� e originJ of our JtateJ-JyJtem : chronological limitJ
1 39
in which he describes this managerial function, in the opening sentence of his paper ' Super-Power Preponderance and International
Order ' : ' The super-powers contribute to international order in two main ways : by managing the balance of power between each other, and by exploiting their preponderance in relation to the rest of the world'. (A little later he says, ' only the super-powers are today in the full sense great powers ', so that it seems permissible to conflate the two classes, applying to the older what he says of the newer.) Nothing here about Great Responsibilities : about ' la vraie politique d'un grand etat c'est de proteger les petites nations ' (Thiers), ' the great nations rightly struggling for mastery, for supremacy of higher civilisation and higher political principles ' (L. S. Amery), ' the Great Powers must seek to serve and not to rule ' (Churchill). So much the better. It makes the managerial function of the great powers easier to look for, in the early centuries of the states�system. All the secondary accounts of the Italian Concert of the fifteenth century which are available to us show the great powers exercising the rather limited and self-interested managerial function that Hed ley Bull describes. Read for example in the eighth chapter of Matting ly, how the three great powers, Venice, Milan and Florence, make the Most Holy League between themselves in August 1454, inviting all the other powers of Italy to join them in a system of general pacification and collective security, how the fourth great power, the papacy, immediately joins, then all the smaller allies and neutral powers, lastly the fifth great power, Naples. In this, and the sequel, the managerial role of the great powers follows natural Iy from the preponderance they enjoy, just as it did in the nineteenth century . I guess that in this respect, as in most respects in international history,
reflection and formulation follow slowI y upon practice, so that the diplomatic documents would not yet have adequate analysis or description of what the great powers were manifestly doing. The quarter century from 1494 to 1 5 1 8 , when the consequences of the Franco-Spanish destruction of the Italian system are working themselves out, and Italian diplomatic practices are spreading north of the Alps, has a special flavour. The first frosts of winter for Italy are a springtime for Western Europe. There is a youthful folly and extravagance about the military expeditions of Maximilian, Charles VIII, James IV of Scotland, Henry VIII, Francis I, a clumsiness of inexperience about the diplomatic combinations of Louis XII, Julius
Syst�ms of S14t�s II, and afterwards Wolsey, as they fumble for the rules of power politics. Only Ferdinand at this time looks to us - and to Machiavelli - like a mature player, who know what he is doing and can bend his capacities to his aims. It is, moreover, a time more than any other in international history when there is a transient equality of status between the Transalpine powers. The new kingdoms seem more conscious of their equality of opportunity for adventure than of their inherent differences of strength and incipient differences of class. The League of Venice of March 1495 was the first European combination to include the powers of the old Italian system and the new Transalpine system on an equal footing : Milan plus Venice plus Spain plus the Emperor plus the pope plus Naples versus France.23 The Holy League of 1 5 1 I - I 2 was the last such combination ; only the papacy and Venice could any longer negotiate on equal terms with the Transalpine great powers. But the network of enemy-neighbours and encircle ment now spread across Europe from Valladolid and Naples to Edinburgh : Ferdinand plus Julius plus Venice plus the Swiss plus (later) Maximilian versus France versus England versus Scodand. Because the coalitions change so rapidly, because allies are picked up and discarded so easily, because there are no general congresses with the diplomatic questions that they raise, no consideration is yet given to differences of power and function. Such considerations begin to appear when Wolsey negotiates the multilateral Treaty of London in I 5 I 8, whose five principle contracting powers are an enumeration of the nominal great powers of the day : the pope, the Emperor, the three kings of France, Spain and En land. And these invite the lesser powers to adhere, as auxiliaries of one or another of the great. It is as clear an instance of great power management as one could wish. But the Austro-Spanish dynastic marriage, originally formed against French preponderance, had already encircled France terri torial! y with Habsburg power, and the election to the Empire of the Austro-Spanish instead of the French candidate, in I 5 I 9 gave French aggressiveness a defensive tinge. The 40 years' struggle that followed was to consolidate the power and clarify the raison d'etat of the two super-powers. Gradually they developed a sense of com mon interest, and the war ended with an example of great power management in the ideological sphere. The Peace of Cateau-Cam-
g
The origins of our states-system : chronological limits
14 1
bresis in I 55 9 was made possible for three reasons : Henry II of France was ready to abandon his dynasty's claims on Italy in ex change for solid aggrandisement on the Lorraine frontier, the two powers were financially exhausted, and they had found a common cause for concern in the growth of heresy and subversion. They made peace, partly, in order to extirpate Protestantism in their own territories and then throughout Christendom, as Henry II incau tiously told the young William of Orange, who was a delegate at the congress.2 4 That the two 'gret Monarchees ' are combined to enforce ' all christian Realmes to receave the Counsell of Trent', becomes the theme of Cecil's memoranda on English foreign policy. For wherof long Contynuance, France and Burgundy, and France and Spayn, wer commonly at Inmyte, and therby allweise on of them sought, for ther own Defence, to be allyed with England, and that for the most part was Burgundy, in respect that France was all yed with Scotland; now they both ar so combyned, (speci ally even in that Nature of Allyance, that is most contrariooss to the Crown of England, which is to avance the Sea of Roome,) that not only none of them doth desyre the Amyty of England, but ar rather bent to dayly Quarrells, and certenly intend the Overthrow of the Quenes Majesty of England; and this Lack of Allyance being evidendy seeme to the World, maketh many moor, both abrode and at home, more careless of hit Majesty. 2 11 The two great powers did not in fact co-operate to this end, but they were widely and reasonably feared to be exploiting their prepon derance, for ideological purposes, in relation to the rest of the world. 4. MEANS OF REGULAR COMMUNICATION
The regular means of conununication between sovereign states in our states-system have been I . Exchange of resident ambassadors, the ' diplomatic system ' par excellence; 2. Summit meetings; 3· Con gresses and conferences. The rise of the diplomatic system has been the most thoroughly explored by historians. Resident ambassadors are generally agreed to have first appeared in the fourteenth or fifteenth centuries, and to have been regularly exchanged first in Italy after the Peace of Lodi.
Systems of States There is still debate about whether Venice or Visconti Milan took the initiative. It is a matter of distinguishing a resident ambassador from the many other kinds of envoy that were commissioned for longer or shorter periods, by potentates more or less sovereign, with varying degrees of reciprocity. But something that strikes the student of the controversy is the extent to which the evidence under discussion illustrates a pan-European diplomatic system, not one confined to Italy, although it is in Italy that it first becomes coherent and regular.2 6 Summit meeting is Churchillian language for a meeting of heads of governments, with the aim of expediting the processes of regular diplomacy. In medieval diplomacy such meetings were as common as in modern. There were a number of meetings between emperors and kings of France. 2 7 But
in
the fifteenth century summit meetings
acquired a new quality, because of the growing sense that great issues of state power might depend on them. Two such meetings attracted much contemporary attention by their dramatic quality, and became famous. One was the occasion when Louis XI went to visit Charles the B
Quentin Durward. 2 8
The other was the visit paid by Lorenzo
the Magnificent to his unscrupulous enemy Ferrante of Naples, in the winter of
I
4 79-80.
It was a brilliant stroke, that confirmed
Lorenzo's reputation as a diplomatist, and ended the war between Florence on the one side and Sixtus IV and Napies on the other which had started with the Pazzi Conspiracy in
1478.
I have never
seen it discussed whether Lorenzo was conscious!y following the precedent of the French king ten years earlier; but the close ties between the Medici and the French court make it seem likely.29 The archetypal summit meeting of English history comes a little later : the Field of Cloth of Gold in
1 5 20,
where Henry VIII met
Francis I. It was archetypal in its flamboyance, its legend, and its
insincerity. Commynes had already laid down a sage principle, a pro pos the meeting of Louis XI with Charles the Bold at Peronne : Ainsi povez veoir qu'il est presque impossible que deux grans seigneurs se puissent accorder, pour les rapports et suspicions qu'ilz ont a chascune heure. Et deux grans princes qui se vouldroient
. bien entreaymer ne se devroyent jamais veoir, mais envoyer bonnes
The origins of our states·system : ch ronological limits
143
gens et sages les unes vers les autres, et ceulx·la les entretien· droient ou amanderoient les faultes. 80 The practice of summit meetings since then has found some excep tions to this rule, but on the whole has confirmed its wisdom. Congresses developed out of councils of the Church. The Church was the ubiquitous international organization of the Respublica Christiana, and its conciliar machinery provided the model for the states--system. In the Middle Ages there were gatherings of emperors and kings with their vassals, which had the character of political conferences ; but it is difficult to think of any international gathering after the eleventh century that was not under the auspices of the Church. The General or Ecumenical Councils, which assembled nominal I y all the bishops under the Roman See, with representatives usually of the principal secular powers, were the precursors of the great peace conferences. They were all concerned with political as well as doctrinal business, and perhaps the political grew larger as time went on. The first general council of the high Middle Ages, Lateran I
(1 1 23),
was convoked for the solemn confirmation of the
Concordat of Worms which ended the Investiture conflict. Lateran II condemned the supporters of Arnold of Brescia, Lateran IV dis possessed Raymond of Toulouse for sheltering the Albigensians, Lyons I was summoned to discuss inter alia the Moslem threat and the Mongol invasion, and formally deposed the emperor Frederick II, Vienne was summoned to confirm the suppression of the Tern· plars. They culminated in the Council of Constance (14 14-1 8), whose main purpose was to end the Great Schism, but which was concerned also with the Hussite revolution in Bohemia, and became involved in various degrees with other current conflicts, England against France, and Poland against the Teutonic knights. The unfinished business of the Council of Constance was taken up by the Council of Basle ( 143 1-9), and its successor of Ferrara Florence (1 438-45). It was at this time, when the Councils were petering out in insoluble problems and dubious ecumenicity, that the first secular congresses appear. Once again, the development is not at all confined to Italy, though it grows fastest there. The first such gathering was the Congress of Arras, 1435, be tween England, France and Burgundy.81 This was promoted by the Council of Basle. The Council was deadlocked in conflict with
Systems of States Pope Eugenius IV. Pope and Council each aimed at the prestige of concluding an Anglo-French peace, in order to strengthen its hand against the other. Each sent a cardinal to the congress as mediator, under whose safeguard and sanction the final treaty was placed. A feature of early ' secular congresses ' is here apparent : while they were gatherings of secular powers, not of the universal Church, 82 they sometimes had the papacy as mediator, down to and including the Congress of Miinster. They thus form the last chapter in the long history of papal mediation between the powers of Europe. But a glance at the main peace settlements of the period suggests that this old role of the papacy was already becoming obsolete, even before the Reformation withdrew half Europe from the Roman obedience : no doubt because of the narrowing and secularization of the Papacy,s own interests.88
Another feature of a congress is suggested, if we ask why there
had been no precedent for the gathering at Arras, no previous con ference at the two earlier moments of interval in the Hundred
Years'
War - the Treaty of Bretigny in I 36o, and the Treaty of
Troyes in I420 ? Each of these moments marked a transient mili tary triumph for England. In 1 360 the French king was a prisoner in London, where negotiations between victor and vanquished took place. The preliminaries at Bretigny between the Black Prince
and the Dauphin simply confirmed terms already arrived at in London.u In I42o the French bargaining position was even weaker. The English had conquered and occupied Normandy ; the Frendt
king was mad; there was no central government; the civil war between the Armagnac and Burgundian factions had just culmin ated in the murder of the duke of Burgundy on the bridge at Montereau (I 4 I 9) ; his son and successor, the most powerful vassal
in France, was determined to avenge the crime by alliance with the English. 1 15 Fifteen years later, however, France had recovered so much that she could meet England and Burgundy at Arras as one of three equal powers. Here we have, perhaps, what is to be hence forward the essence of a congress, that it should be a conference of
more than two powers, and that they should have some parity of weight. 1 8
In the next hundred years there were many international gather�
ings to which the name congress has been given. Thus Filippo Maria Visconti promoted an abortive congress, primarily between
The origins of our states-system : chronological limits
I45
Milan, Venice and Florence, in I 4 4 3. 1 7 The Peace of Lodi led to the Congress of Venice between the same three powers in I 4 54. In the same year the Congress of Regensburg met to plan a crusade, which prompted Aeneas Sylvius,s despairing description of inter national anarchy. 1 8 In I459, as Pius II, he presided over the more impressive but equally fruitless Congress of Mantua, ' the first assembly of national powers ,.&• The allies against Venice held a Congress of Cremona in 1 48 3 during the War of Ferrara.40 But perhaps the word congress should not be extended to a conference of allies in wartime . There was now a lull in multilateral diplomatic gatherings until after the French invasion of Italy. But when the Holy League defeated the French at Ravenna in I 5 I 2, the ' con querors met to divide the spoils, and in August the first peace
conference of modern times was opened at Mantua '. 41 Maximilian hdd a congress at Vienna in July I 5 I 5 for the kings of Hungary and Poland (Diirer made a drawing of it), where the dynastic
marriage was arranged that afterwards brought Hungary and Bo hemia into Habsburg possession. 42 In I 5 I 8, Wolsey turned an Anglo-French negotiation into the multilateral treaty of London, in a kind of
ad hoc
congress consisting of the papal legate, the
French special embassy, and the ambassadors of all the other powers represented in London. 48 . If the development of the congress as an international institution marked time during the next hundred years or more, it was because
of the bipolar nature of European politics, and the unreliability of
the great powers. The Peace of Cambrai, I 5 29, was bilateral. So was the Peace of Crepy, I 544, because in this case Charles V aban doned his confederates, England and Lorraine, to make a separate peace with Francis. The Peace of Cateau-Cambresis, I 559, was nominally trilateral, with England as the third. But she had been defeated ; Philip of Spain had no reason to protect her interests, and Queen Mary died during the negotiations,
so
that England's role
was secondary. The negotiations that created the grand alliance of England, France, and the Dutch against Philip II were conducted bilaterally. Even the final treaty of Greenwich, I 5 96, which bound the three powers together, was transacted between England and France, with the Dutch giving their adherence afterwards, because of Henry IV,s reluctance to treat openly with rebels. That grand all iance dissolved by stages, so that the great war against Philip II
Systems of States
did not end with a general peace settlement, but at Vervins in 1 598 for France (with Savoy as an ally of Spain), and at Westminster in I 6 o4 for England. This left the Dutch. You have the first inter national congress mentioned in modern history meeting in x 6 o8 at the Hague ', says Vollenhoven, ' to negotiate a truce affecting Spain, the Netherlands, England, France, Denmark, the Palatinate, Brandenburg and Hesse - a congress wearing " all the majesty of a true European Congress ", as M. Pirenne tdls us '. �4 It negotiated the Twelve Years Truce between Spain and the United Provinces. The other powers mentioned were represented as mediators or associates. Vollenhoven's exaggeration may be attributed to Dutch pride, not to ignorance of previous congresses : he should have written, the first Hague congress'. Some of the chief congresses before Westphalia have been thus reviewed - and these of course are only the most familiar, drawn from Western Europe and representing a fraction of the diplomatic activity of the states-system as a whole - to show that there were plenty of such assemblies, even if bilateral negotiations be excluded from the name, and indeed that by the end of the fifteenth century this international institution was familiar. Two questions may be asked, however. Did these gatherings before Westphalia have a common name ? And did they show a diplomatic tradition, a collec tive historical memory ? They are gatherings to which historians have retrospective! y applied the term congress. I do not know the contemporary term for them, nor whether contemporaries distinguished them generi cally. It is a matter notably untouched by the standard writers on the history of diplomacy, Maulde Ia Claviere, Mattingly, Queller, more recently Charles H. Carter. It may be suspected that the word congress ' became attached to these assemblies retrospectively by eighteenth-century historiography, when the classical theory of the origin of the states-system prevailed, and to this extent the use of the word congress begs the question we are concerned with. More interesting, did such conferences show the growth of an international sense o£ their usefulness ? Was a diplomatic tradition developing about when to summon and how to organize them ? The General Councils of the Church were different, in that they presupposed the existence of a permanent, highly competent, inter national bureaucracy - the Roman curia - which knew the prece•
•
•
The origins of our states�system : chronological limits
I4 7
dents, undertook the organizing, and provided continuity between councils. The states-system had nothing to compare until the be ginnings of an international secretariat under the League of Nations. W a!; there then any study of historical precedents, as when Lieut. C. K. Webster was commissioned by the Librarian of the Foreign Office in the summer of I 9 I S to write a handbook on the Congress of Vienna for assistance of delegates to the Paris Peace Conference ? 4� What precedents were followed at the Congress of Arras ? Was the Congress of Mantua, summoned by Pius II, organ ized by curial officials, on the lines of the Councils of Ferrara or Basle ? No writer known to me th rows any light on these questions, nor even formulates them. Mattingly speculates - the evidence does not allow anything more - that the French envoy to London in 15 I S may have brought with him, from the French royal archives, a copy of the draft treaty which Marini, the agent of George Podie brad, king of Bohemia, had recommended to Louis . XI in I 462, and whose resemblance to the Treaty of London of I S I S is ' so close in some respects as apparently to preclude mere coincidence' .48 As far as the substance of treaties goes, there is the beginning of the conception of a status quo, a rightful order, which later settle ments confirm. Italian treaties up to I494 confirmed the Peace of Lodi. The Treaty of Cambrai, 1 529, confirmed and modified the Treaty of Madrid, I 5 26 ; the Treaty of Crepy, I 544, confirmed and modified them both. Vervins similarly confirmed Cateau Cambresis. Westphalia in this respect is singular only as the basic diplomatic arrangement that has had the longest run in European history.
5. INTERNATIONAL LAW
Hedley Bull made the existence of a body of international law a criterion of the states-system, and argued that the absence of such a body of law before the seventeenth century supported the Westpha lian doctrine about the origin of the states-system. Two things must be said, briefly, in reply to this assertion. First, the states of Italy and Europe in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries did not consider themselves as exempt from rules of law. In all their activities they recognized the existence of norms of international
Systems of States conduct, in which for the most part they probably did not distin
guish the natural law element from the customary. (Nevertheless, in
these centuries the humanists were developing a more historical con ception of law, which itself contributed to the idea of sovereignty.)H
The two principle parts of what might be called the medieval
international law, were the feudal or dynastic law of success ion,
and the laws of war. The first regulated the main aims of foreign policy, the second the means. Both were powerful about the year
1 500.
Charles VIII invaded Italy in pursuance of a dynastic claim
to the throne of Naples. The laws of war were intertwined with
the code of chivalry. ' Grotius's principle, that only sovereign states may legitimately make war, may be traced back to its ancestry in the
droit de gue"e
of the feudal
seigneur. . . the
chivalrous con
ceptions of honour and loyalty of an age when the idea of nation
ality was not fully understood prepared the way for the notion of a law of nations '!8 But there were other elements in medieval inter
national law. The
Consolato del Mare,
a collection of Mediterra
nean maritime customs probably compiled in the thirteenth century,
but first published at Barcelona in
1494,
was the source of the
modern law of naval capture and many modern commercial regula tions. •s There was also a very widespread practice of arbitration. so
We have the task, therefore, not of explaining why a lawless
period, that of Machiavelli, was succeeded by a law-aspiring period,
that of Grotius, but of describing the change that occurred between the legalism of John of Legnano and Honore Bonet, n and th� legalism of Grotius, and the difference in the scope of their legal
doctrines. Here a crucial invention was the theory of corporate legal personality, which enabled similar rights and obligations to be
predicated of states as had hitherto been predicated of individuals. u Secondly, it seems that respect for international law has fluctuated through history, and the later fifteenth and early sixteenth century
was certainly a period when considerations of law tended to be
subordinated to considerations of power. Perhaps the last three quarters of the eighteenth century may be compared with it in this respect. This interval of political realism has contributed to the impression that Vitoria and Gentili, Suarez and Grotius, were
fashioning a tradition of international law out of nothing, rather ·
than adapting old doctrines to new circumstances. _
The origins of our states-system : ch ronological limits
149
6 . DEFENCE OF COMMON INTERESTS A states-system is the loosest of all political organizations known to us; hence in part its fa�cination. Nevertheless a states-system like other political organizations has means of defending its common interests. But because of its looseness and incoherence, such means are likely to be very imperfectly effective, and to exist in the realm
of aspiration rather than operation.
The means by which the states-system has defended its common interests is the system of the balance of power. In so far as it has worked, the balance of power has preserved against attack the liberties of states and the interests of international society as a whole. It was the Wilsonian view, which, though obsolete, probably still provides the basic popular assumptions about foreign policy in the Western world, that the deficiencies of the system of the balance of power made it necessary to move on to collective security, beyond which would lie the ultimate stage of world government.118 When we study the origins of the states-system, we
see
that the
Wilsonian view prescribes for the future a reversal of the historical development of the past. Western civilization began with an im pressive system of ' world government ' within the limits of Western Christendom, in the shape of the papal monarchy ; it moved to collective security ; at last it came to rest in the balance of power. By collective security we mean a system in which any breach of the peace is declared to be of concern to all the participating states, and an attack on one is taken as an attack on all. It is amusing and at the same time sobering to reflect that this system was written into the Covenant of the League of Nations, and endlessly discussed and refined for the next 1 5 years, without any suspicion (so far as I know) of knowledge on the pan of Woodrow Wilson, or of the League of Nations Union that it had been tried repeatedly in inter national history since the fifteenth century. The principles of collec tive security are found in the Most Holy League of Venice of 1 4 54, the Treaty of London of 1 5 1 8, the Treaty of Miinster (in respect of the Empire), 5� the Association of the Hague of 1 6 8 1-3, and the Quadruple Alliance of 1 7 1 8 . No doubt other instances could be found, and it would be interesting to compare the provisions. Collective security is the police arrangement of a rude community� Perhaps its medieval roots may be seen in the swom associations and
Systems of States peace guilds of early feudal society, which like the vigilance com mittees of the American frontier bound men together in collective self-defence.155 It reappeared spontaneously, in the relations between powers, in the
l.Andfrieden
of the Holy Roman Empire after the
Great Interregnum, leagues whose members undertook, for a speci fied period, ' not to wage war on any other, to observe certain rules in the interest of public order, and to assist, whether by money or by men, in chastising disloyal members or troublesome outsiders ' .158 Did the Italian powers who adopted a similar principle in
1454
have the German precedents in mind ? The Reichstag of Worms, in
1 495,
declared the
Ewige Landfriede,
a public peace without limita
tion of time, in which private war was forbidden to the states of the Empire under pain of imperial ban (cf. being ' branded as an aggressor '), and those dwelling within
20·
miles of a breach of the
peace were obliged to take part in vindicating it. This enactment deserves its place in a history of collective security.
7. CONCLUSION It is time to attempt a summing-up. At the outset the question was posed as to whether our states-system originated about the end of the fifteenth century, with the French invasion of Italy as the critical event, or about the middle of the seventeenth, with the Westphalian peace settlement as the critical event. Hinsley offers a third answer :.
the eighteenth century. Hinsley's argument is that : Historians are liable to antedate the completion of massive de velopments because of their preoccupation with origins . . . a new European states' system emerged in the eighteenth century, and not at an earlier date. . . It was during the eighteenth century that the actuality and the conception of a collection of great powers in Europe finally replaced an earlier framework of exis ting fact and inherited thought in which, while more than one state had always existed, it had �n natural for one Power to be rated above the rest and impossible for that Power's pretensions resisted though they had always been by other states - to stop short of the control and protection of Christendom.5�
Th� origins of our stat�s-syst�m : chronological limits
15 1
Enough has already been said to show why I disagree with this picture. Hinsley's account is
a
variant of the Westphalian inter
pretation, a variant whose fault is to misconceive the bipolar arrangement of the states-system in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, and whose virtue is to see that the multiple balance of power, the pentarchy, the Concen of Europe, is already apparent in the eighteenth. The latter theme, however, lies outside the discussion of origins, and need not be pursued here. My own conclusion may be put this way. If we say that the states system becomes apparent in the later seventeenth century or early eighteenth century, we are left with the task of providing a des cription for the European system between the Council of Constance and the Congress of Westphalia. And however we describe it, this system has a greater resemblance to the states-system that succeeds it . than it has to the medieval system that precedes it. The real break, prepared through the fourteenth century, becomes manifest in the fifteenth. In the fifteenth century the old constitution of the Respublica Christiana finally breaks down. The attempt at its constitutional reform in the Concilar Movement is a failure. The papacy is trans formed from an ecumenical theocracy into an Italian great power. The assertion of sovereignty by the secular powers, growing since the thirteenth century, becomes normal. The first lamentations about international anarchy are heard. To mitigate the anarchy, the first attempts at collective security are made. To assist them, the new invention of reciprocal resident embassies becomes general. As collective security proves itself unworkable, because demanding too much, the simpler system of a balance of power grows up. Some aspects of the change are retarded. For this there are four reasons. First, the change is first worked out in detail regionally, in Italy. It is diffused generally throughout Transalpine Europe only after the French invasion of Italy in 1494, and the diffusion is
slower in proportion as Transalpine Europe is geographically broader than Italy. Second, by an accident, the French invasion of Italy coincided in time with the discovery of the Indies, both East and West, which involved first the Hispanic powers and soon their rivals and supplanters in new relationships with non-European states. A diplomatic formulation for a states-system that had a Euro- pean core and a non-European penumbra was not arrived at until
Systems of States Cateau-Cambresis in 1559. Third, by another accident, the French invasion of Italy and the discovery of the Indies coincided (within a generation) with the formation of a Habsburg super-power whose rivalry with the previous dominant power, France, polarized inter national politics for a century and a half. This retarded or blurred the evolution of a class of great powers. Fourth, by a further acci dent, the three foregoing developments coincided with a widespread rebellion throughout Latin Christendom against what remained of the papal international system. The result was a century of religious conflicts, together with a secularization of international society and international law that came to completion about the time of the Peace of Westphalia. Grotius provides a purely rational foundation for natural law, and the Peace of Westphalia provides a purely utilitarian foundation for the states-system. At Westphalia the states system does not come into existence : it comes of age.
6 International legitimacy • For, when the people speaks loudly, it is from being sttongly possessed either by the Godhead or the Demon ; and he, who cannot discover the true spirit from the false, hath no ear for profitable communion '. Wordsworth, Contl�ntion of Cintra
In this paper I want to formulate some puzzles concerned with the notion of international legitimacy. In none of the literature on diplomatic theory or international law is it easy to find a broad discussion of the theory of legitimacy. A proper study would try to go back to first principles. It would disentangle the notion of legiti macy from that of international law on the one side, and that of ideology or international doctrine on the other. In doing so, it would give precision to the central usage of the word legitimacy, which is employed loosely and in several senses.1 By international legitimacy I mean the collective j udgment of international society about rightful membership of the family of nations ; how sovereignty may be transferred ; and how state succes sion is to be regulated, when large states break up into smaller, or several states combine into one. Until the French Revolution, the principle of international legitimacy was
dynastic,
being concerned
with the status and claims of rulers. Since then, dynasticism has been superseded by a
popular
principle, concerned with the claims and
consent of the governed. The sovereignty of the individual prince passed into the sovereignty of the nation he ruled. It will be noted that these principles of legitimacy mark the region of approximation between international and domestic politics. They are ·principles that prevail (or are at least proclaimed)
within
a majority of the
states that form international society, as well as in the relations
between
them.
The dynastic principle, in the form of hereditary monarchy, was the chief legacy that modern international society inherited from
1 54
Systems of States
medieval feudal society. Dynasticism was itself an international sys tem. The dynasties were collectively the European ruling class, and intermarried regularly to maintain their social primacy. But the dynastic principle coexisted with and indeed presupposed the prin ciple of election. As Burke said, ' At some time or other, all the beginners of dynasties were chosen by those who called them to govern '. The two supreme potentates of Christendom were elective. For the Church, this was the expression of a higher right, a means of revealing God's will. For the imperial lawyers and notaries who revived the Roman tradition (helped by the interests of German feudatories and of the papacy itself) it was not proper that the Em pire should follow the same rules of succession as a private estate. The dynastic principle gave rise to a dynastic idiom of interna tional politics. Alliances were consolidated by dynastic marriages. Reversals of alliance were marked by matrimonial disengagements. Territorial aggrandisement was justified by dynastic claims. Foreign revolutions were fomented by cultivating dynastic pretenders. Such was the mode of politics down to the 1 77os, when Joseph II launched his project to partition Bavaria under a bogus dynastic claim, and Pugachev impersonated the murdered Peter III, perhaps each the last example of its kind. (Despite Catherine the Great's misgivings, Pugachev's revolt was not instigated (rom abroad, and therefore was not an international event, but it was in part a colon ial rebellion by the non-Russian peoples of the Volga and the Urals). Dynastic marriages to cement a political alliance, however, survived into the age of nationalism, at least until the match between Prince Jerome Napoleon and the unfortunate Clotilde of Savoy in 1 859· There were two limits to the operation of dynastic legitimacy. The first took the form of traditional exceptions within Christen� dom. The second was provided by relations between Christendom and what lay beyond it. 1 . Medieval Christendom contained 'a number of powers, apart from the papacy and the Empire, which had an elective, not a here ditary constitution, and which, when they had disentangled them selves from the cobwebs of feudal suzerainty, assumed the status of sovereign republics. Pre-eminent were Venice, the Swiss Confedera tion, and the United Provinces of the Low Countries. These were sometimes classed in eighteenth-century diplomatic works as the ' Great Republics ', and received royal honours .
International legitimacy
ISS
The Dutch Revolt posed with embarrassing sharpness the issue of legitimacy and the right of admission to international society. By the Act of Abjuration of I S 8 I the States-General renounced only their allegiance to Philip, not the monarchic principle. ' A prince is constituted by God to be ruler of a people, to defend them from oppression and violence, as the shepherd his sheep '. If he oppresses them, ' then he is no longer a prince but a tyrant, and they may not only disallow his authority, but legally proceed to the choice of another prince for their defence '. The Dutch offered their allegiance
in turn to Anj ou and to Elizabeth ; and only the incompetence of Leicester as governor-general in I S 8 6-7 and the duplicity of Eng lish policy brought them to accept a formal republicanism which placed sovereignty in the States themselves. Both Elizabeth and Henry IV had
to
overcome considerable
scruples before entering into alliance with, and so tacidy conferring diplomatic recognition upon, a community whose
legal
standing
was the same as that of Ian Smith's regime in Rhodesia today. But when in I 6o i Clement VIII complained to the French ambassador that Henry IV, in spite of having made peace with Spain, con tinued to grant diplomatic recognition to the Dutch rebels, the ambassador replied : ' When princes are dealing with a considerable Power, they have not been accustomed to examine whether the potentate who sends them an ambassador is legitimate or not. Without further enquiry into title, they concern themselves only with the power and the possession' •2 He gave the familiar precedent of the Swiss, and could not refrain from remarking that the Hoi y See happened at that moment to be treating with an envoy from the Sublime Porte. Ossat's despatch recounting this conversation became a Douai's
locus classicus ; it duly found its way into Merlin of capacious Repertoire universel et raisonne de jurisprudence
at the time of the Revolution ; and it contains the core of the doc trine of recognition in modern international law. Another anomaly in the dynastic states-system was the Rzecz pospolita Polska. Here the elective principle ousted the hereditary in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, making Poland an elective monarchy sui generis. 2.
Dynastic legitimacy was limited to Christendom, in so far as
marriage between a Christian and- a non-Christian dynasty required that the infidel party should be converted to Christianity as a pre-
Systems of States condition of the marriage. Circumstances were likely to make this possible only among the pagan (and therefore culturally weaker) peoples in Eastern Europe, not among the Islamic states along Christendom's Mediterranean frontier, still less among the remoter Muslim and Hindu potentates to whom access was opened by Vasco da Gama. Probably the most important example of dynastic mar riage combined with conversion is the marriage between Jagiello of Lithuania and Jadviga of Poland in I 3 8 6, which was preceded by Jagiello's baptism as a Catholic in Cracow. There was already a controversy within Christendom about whether legitimacy could be predicated at all of non-Christian rulers. It went back to the debate about the right of war against infidels, represented in the thirteenth century by the two canonists Sinibaldo Fieschi (later Innocent I V) and Hostiensis. The first taught that infidels held rightful dominion over their territories, and that war to convert or to despoil them was unjust. The second responded that the coming of Christ had ' spoiled principalities and powers, making a show of them openly, triumphing over them ' (Col.ii. I 5), and that acceptance of Christ's claims had thenceforward been the condition of sovereignty. Aquinas lent his weight to the natural law school ; but, as N ys dolefully observes : ' L 'historien doit mal heureusement constater que !'opinion la moins liberale est celle qui reunit le plus de suffrages ,. s The controversy descended to Poland and the Teutonic Knights. The union of Poland and Lithuania marked the beginning of the downfall of the Teutonic Order. Smarting from their defeat at Tannenberg
in I 4 I o,
they instructed their ddegation to the Council
of Constance to impugn the legitimacy of the Polish alliance with a pagan people against a sovereign Christian Order. Their complaints were debated inconclusively by the Council over
three
years. Paulus
Vladimiri, rector of the University of Cracow, published the Polish case in a large treatise asserting the rightful sovereignty of non Christian princes, and incidentally denying the validity of papal and imperial privileges granted to the Teutonic Order for conquest of pagan lands in the Balticum. The Order engaged a Pomeranian Dominican, Johann is Falkinberg, to reply. He argued that the Poles themsdves had earned the hatred of all Christians and deserved to be exterminated like pagans. The Council could agree to condemn this extreme view; on the larger issue between two major orthodox
International legitimacy
157
powers it maintained a statesmanlike evasiveness. It had already, however, condemned a number of Wycliffe's heresies, including the doctrine that legitimate dominion depends upon the sovereign being in a state of grace. This decision helped the Catholic principle of legitimacy to flow in the natural law channel, on the side of Sini
baldo Fieschi, Aquinas and Paulus Vladimiri. It was confirmed in the next century by the Neo-Scholastics, in the great debate about the Indies, and became part of the inheritance of Grotius. I t might
be cautiously described as a doctrine that legitimacy rests upon prescription, tempered by consent.
2 The Wars of Religion, however, brought a final flare-up of the extreme or exclusive Catholic principle of legitimacy. Pius V in 1 5 70 deposed Elizabet!t as a heretic; Sixtus V in
I 58 5
declared
Henry of Navarre incapable on the same grounds of succeeding to the crown of France, and absolved his vassals from their allegiance. Mariana defended the assassination of Henry III on the grounds that no rightful prince can tolerate heresy, a heretic king is ipso facto a tyrant, and a tyrant may be assassinated even without formal de(X>sition. In order to restore the broken unity of Christen dom, the ancient arbiter of Christendom was turning revolutionary and substituting doctrine for prescription. The attempt broke against the growing national particularism of states. England remained Protestant; the Politiques rallied to Henry of Navarre before his conversion to Catholicism . Vervins in 1 5 98 was the last peace congress at which the Holy See played its old role of arbiter. The dispute with Venice in 1 60 7 was the last occa sion on which the Holy See used all its spiritual weapons against a state, laying it under interdict ; for the weapons were found ineffec tive. The Hoi y See sent a delegation to the Congress of Westphalia, but refusing to agree to concessions to Protestants within the Em pire, or to sanction peace with Sweden and the Dutch, it earned the impatience of the Catholic great powers, who made peace over its protests. Neither at the Pyrenees in 1 6 59 nor at any subsequent peace congress has the papacy been represented. The ligaments of international society were to be supplied, not by
Systems of States doctrinal orthodoxy, but by international law. The interwoven au thorities of the Middle Ages were dissolving and
recombining
into
sovereign states, which exercised exclusive jurisdiction over a terri tory and its inhabitants. The twin conceptions of the state and sovereignty were becoming clarified. In the Empire the coincidence of Church and state lasted longest, but by 1 648 the old ' liberties ' of the princes had finally been transformed into effective sovereignty, for which Leibniz was to provide the theoretical recognition. All this was accompanied by a tendency towards diplomatic egalitarianism. The idea of the legal equality of states became established by the
early eighteenth century. As early as 1 670 Leibniz noted in his
Securitas Publica,
written when he was in the service of the elector
of Mainz, how the princes of the Empire were insisting on up grading their resident envoys at foreign courts in the name of equal dignity - a process which may be thought to have reached its natural fulfilment in our own day. International law is a system of rules and principles that has been distilled chiefly from the practice of states, with a yiew to regulating their rdations and moderating their conflicts. Originating in the dynastic age, it incorporated at first the assumptions of dynasticism ;4 but the tendency of international lawyers was to be general and inclusive, finding rules that would be true for or acceptable to independent states of whatever complexion, Protestant as well as Catholic, republics as wdl as kingdoms. The branch of international law that is concerned with legitimacy in the sense in which the word is used in this paper, is the law concerning the recognition of states. This seeks to lay down principles to guide existing states in the matter of recognizing a new community as fulfilling the con ditions of statehood and qualifying for membership of the Society of Nations. And the tendency of international law has been to make recognition of new states depend upon ascertainable fact, namely whether the community has a government exerting effective author ity throughout the whole of its territory, and for it to be granted on considerations of expediency, not of principle. I have said that international law incorporated at first the assumptions of dynasticism. It incorporated also something more important : the principle of prescription. Nothing is more remark able about international history up to the French Revolution than the regard for prescriptive right. The extinctions of sovereignty
lnt�rnational legitimacy
159
were tnainly the result of disputed successions (e.g. Mantua, Orange), or the annexation of a state, effected by territorial ex change (e.g. Lorraine). The occasional dispossession of a rightful ruler, as when Ferdinand II in 1 628 arbitrarily transferred the two duchies of Mecklenburg to Wallenstein, caused general alarm, as a threat to the security of all princes. It was something of a key case when the son of the Elector Palatine, whose folly had occasioned the Thirty Years War and who had been deprived of his dectorate by a reluctant Diet in 1623, was restored in the Palatinate (or at least the Rhenish half of it) at the Peace of Westphalia. Until the final partition of Poland, it is difficult to think of any European sovereignty being arbitrarily extinguished by superior force or right of conquest. Prescriptive rights were sacrosanct, and power politics were con ducted in a litigious and not a doctrinal or ideological idiom. Grotius has a chapter on usucaption, the right by which a thing long used becomes · the property of the possessor against a known former owner. ' The reason for the introduction of this right', says Pufendorf, ' was partly that a man who neglected for a long time to reclaim a thing was considered to have abandoned it, . . . and partly because the interests of peace and quiet required that possessions should final! y be put beyond controversy ,. Vattel again devotes a chapter to it. '11 est impossible de determiner en Droit Nature!, le nombre d'annees requis pour fonder Ia Prescription. Cela depend de la nature de la chose, dont Ia propriete est disputee, et des circonstances. ' But immemorial prescription, founded on a posses sion ' dont l 'origine est inconnue, ou tellement chargee d'obscurite, que I' on ne �auroit prouver si le Possesseur tient veritablement son Droit du Proprietaire, ou s'il a re�u Ia possession d'un autre ', affords an inexpugnable title. 8 ·
3 A new doctrine of legitimacy, contractual instead of prescriptive, was introduced by the Glorious Revolution. The Nine Years War was a war of the British Succession, and the recognition of William III as rightful king of England was of central importance in the negotiations that brought the war to an end. Louis at length agreed,
1 60
Systems of Stat�s
in the Treaty of Ryswyck, to a preamble that referred to William as king by the grace of God (which would acknowledge divine
sanction for the parliamentary title), and the treaty implicidy ac
cepted the provision made for the Protestant succession in England by the Bill of Rights of
I68g.
The Treaty of Utrecht once again
gave international recognition to the Protestant succession in Eng land, as regulated now more fully by the Act of Settlement of
I 70 I .
The English had imposed upon Europe a principle of national sovereignty against Louis XIV 's doctrine of dynastic legitimacy.
Here international relations pointed the way for civil politics. ' Les
philosophes fran�ais allerent se mettre a son �cole [Lockes] et repand.irent ses doctrines a travers l'Europe, qui, en
1 7 13
deja, les
admettait dans son droit international. Le traite d'Utrecht fut le
point de depan de cette evolution des idees politiques et du droit
public, qui aboutit a la fin du d.ix�huitieme siecle a la ruine de la monarchie fran�aise, . 8 The floodgates were opened when in
gress declared :
1.
1 77 6
the Continental Con
that all men are created equal and endowed with
certain inalienable rights ;
2.
that governments are instituted to
secure these rights, and derive their just powers from the consent
of the governed ;
3.
that when a fonn of government becomes des
tructive of these ends, it is the right of the people to alter or abolish it;
4.
that therefore it may in the course of human events become
necessary for one people to dissolve the political bands which have connected them with another, ' and to assume among the Powers of the earth, the separate, and equal station to which the Laws of Nature and of Nature's God entitle them '. Henceforward dynastic
politics were to give way to popular politics. The imperialism of the
French Revolutionaries and Napoleon drove popular politics into the channds of nationality ; the rights of men gave way to the rights
of nations. Perhaps the earliest recognition of the new principle of legitimacy, a recognition partly inadvertent, may be found in the Convention of
7
May
France, and Russia,
nation,
I 8 3 2, whereby ' The Courts of Great Britain, duly authorised for this purpose by the Greek
offer the hereditary Sovereignty of Greece to the Prince
Frederick Otho of Bavaria ,. The new principle was formally sub
stituted for the old in the peace settlement of
of ' national self�detennination ,.
I 9 I 9,
under the name
The history of this phrase would itself be worth elucidating. The
International legitimacy earliest exampie of
•
self-determination ' in the
0 .E .D.
is 1 9 I I .
Lloyd George used and explored it in his statement of war-aims to the Trade Unions of 5 January 1 9 I 8 . ' All principles of self determination, or, as our earlier phrase goes, government by consent
of the governed . . . . we feel that government with the consent of the
governed must he the basis of any territorial settlement in this war '. But the full phrase appeared only when he came to speak of the disposition of the German colonies. ' The governing consideration, therefore, in all these cases must be that the inhabitants should be placed under the control of an administration acceptable to themselves, one of whose main purposes will be to prevent their exploitation for the benefit of European capitalists or Governments. The natives live in their various tribal organizations under chiefs and councils who are competent to consult and speak for their tribes and mem bers, and thus to represent their wishes and interests in regard to their disposal .
The general principle of national self-determination
is
therefore as applicable in their cases as in those of occupied Euro pean territories ' .7 It is ironical that this came from the lips of the prime minister of the power which was, in the short run, to add the bulk of the former German colonies to her own colonial empire, but it is equally far-sighted. Wilson's Fourteen Points speech was delivered three days later. Wilson kept on the whole to Jefferson's vocabulary, and spoke more of ' peoples ' than of ' nations '. I think that the phrase ' national self-determination ' does not occur in the great speeches of I 9 1 8 . The nearest he comes to it is in the Four Principles speech of I I February : ' National aspirations must be respected : peoples may now be dominated and governed only by their own consent. " Self determination " is not a mere phrase. It is an imperative principle of action which statesmen will henceforth ignore at their �ril '.8 He expressed concisely what he wanted to be his theory of legitimacy when, in the Big Four, the French put forward a case for annexing the Saar on grounds of strategy, history, economics and reparations : ' I recognise no principle but the consent of the governed ' .9 The difficulties in the principle of national self-determination are familiar. As lvor Jennings once said : ' On the surface it seemed reasonable : let the people decide. It was in fact ridiculous because the people cannot decide until somebody decides who are the people. '10 It is impossible to define a nation as the unit of self-
Systems of States
determination. In Europe, the consciousness of national identity preceded the political process of struggle for statehood. Outside Europe, statehood has generally been won first against foreign domination, and nationalism is created by governments or elites in order to unite the people and make them dependent upon the state. On a deeper level, self-determination is a purely formal principle, and as Berdyaev argued in the early 192os, if it ' comes to define the end towards which the people,s will should move, if it finds an object worthy of it and is provided with a positive substance, at that moment it is forced to put that end, that object, that substance above the formal principle of the expression of the people's will, and accept them as the basis of society ' .11 Thus the substance or object of self-determination has usually been not only independence but an ideological regime. In the most perfect and elaborately organized international plebiscite in history, the Saarlanders voted themselves heartily into the Third Reich. I do not want to go over this familiar ground, but shall remark on some contrasts between the new principle of international legiti macy and the old. 4
The dynastic principle of legitimacy was rooted in custom. At times it showed a tendency to develop into an ideology, an international dynasticism, which Paine pilloried as 'the common interest of courts against the common interest of man ,. This was the prototype of all such radical bogeys : the internationals of bankers, armaments manufacturers, Jewry, Eurocrats, and so on. In fact, the dynastic international had little vitality, and dynasticism was generally sub ordinated to state (or even national) interest. The popular principle of legitimacy, by contrast, is the direct product of ideology. It may be that this makes it both more power ful and more unstable. Its instability I shall return to later. Its power is illustrated by .its part in shaping two international constitu tions, the Covenant and the Charter. The League was open to any fully self-governing State, Dominion or Colony ' which could 'give effective guarantees of its sincere intention to observe its international obligations '. Wilson wished ' fully self-governing' to be stricdy •
International legitimacy construed, as a limiting qualification. The United Nations was open •
to all peace-loving States which accept the obligations contained in
the present Charter ', but declares its second purpose to be ' To develop friend! y relations among nations based on respect for the principle of equal rights and self--determination of peoples '. This double (and potentially contradictory) principle is repeated in Art.
55, which introduces the pledges of international economic and
social cooperation. The object of the trusteeship system is declared
in
Art. 76 to be ' to promote the . . . advancement of the inhabitants
of the trust territories, and their progressive development towards self-government or independence as may be appropriate '. Ian Brownlie, in the latest British book on the principles of public international law, observes that ' Until recently the majority of Western jurists assumed or asserted that the principle had no legal content, being an ill-defined concept of policy and morality '. But now, he argues, self-determination has been established as a prin ciple of the law of the United Nations, and is indeed part of the ' a peremptory norm of general international law from which no derogation is permitted ' .12 If this view prevails, the popu
ius cogens,
lar principle of international legitimacy will have taken a firmer hold in international law than its predecessor did. The instability inherent in the new principle may be seen in its effect upon prescriptive rights. Popular legitimacy tends to under mine and at length abolish prescription. It asserts a more dogmatic negative than did dynasticism : all that is not popularly based is illegitimate. Brownlie discusses the principle of prescription and concludes that there is no role for it any longer in international law.11 The principle of prescription seemed to carry within itself the principle ex injun·a jus oritur. An act of violence and injustice, by lapse of time and some degree of acceptance, could give rise to rights. Whether the acts of violence which shaped early Western history - the Norman conquests of England and Sicily, the French conquest of the Angevin dominions, the papal extirpation of the Hohenstaufen, the Turkish conquest of the Eastern Empire - had their lasting effects because they were successful assertions of right (as Stubbs's generalization about the legalism of medieval warfare might lead one to enquire in the case of the first three examples), or show rather the acquiescence of a politically unawakened society
Systems of States in circwnstances which it cannot change, we need not discuss. But the law of war, as it developed in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, emphasized the obligation of accepting the results of war. Gentili argues that the doctrine of the just war fits few empirical wars because there is usual! y justice on both sides, and that therefore the rights of war are due to both parties, even in the rare cases when one is evidendy in the wrong. And he adds, ' But if the unjust man gain the victory, neither in a contention in arms nor in the strife carried on in the garb of peace is there any help for it. Yet it is not the law which is at fault, but the execution of the law ' .u Pufendor£ insisted that if you appeal to the dice of Mars ' you must loyally abide by the ·result. Truces were distinguished from peaces : 'as a rule, every peace is perpetual, that is, it pennanend y extin guishes the controversies on account of which the war was begun '. u The extinction of Polish sovereignty in I795 was a moral turning point, not only in the crimin ality of the actors, but also in the response of the victim. Here was the first international injun·a which gained no acquiescence, from which no jus could arise. And it seems that in the nineteenth century the theoretical critique of the doctrine of prescription began among international lawyers. Hun dert Jahre Unrecht ist noch kein Tag Recht', said the learned Heffter.1 8 The second such unforgivable injuria was the German annexation of Alsace-Lorraine in I 8 7 1 . N'en parlez jamais, y pen sez toujours, was a new principle of international relations. The German attitude to the Versailkrdik,tat developed the theme fur ther. It has culminated in the unprecedented refusal of the Arab states, after three wars and 2 3 years, to make peace with Israel.17 Thus the current cliche of the politically illiterate and historically ignorant, that ' war settles nothing', has acquired a limited and temporary measure of truth. War cannot settle issues when it is conceived, not as litigation, but as an episode in a vendetta. The Indian seizure of Goa in I 96 1 was a key case in the erosion of prescriptive right. Was Portuguese rule in Goa legitimate ? Albuquer que conquered Goa from the Sultan of Bijapur in 1 5 10, who after wards recognized the conquest in various treaties. In I955, when Indian volunteers occupied the Portuguese enclaves of Dadra and Nagar-Aveli, which Portugal could not recapture without crossing Indian territory, Portugal appealed to the International Court of Justice. The Court examined at great length the treaties on which •
•
International legitimacy
165
the Portuguese right of passage between Goa and the enclaves was alleged to rest, particularly the Treaty of Poona of 1 779 between Portugal and the Marathas, and concluded
inter alia
that the treaty
did not confer upon Portugal full sovereignty over the enclaves ; but it cast no doubt on the legality of Portuguese sovereignty over Goa.1 8
But India had already sought to strip Portugal of her legitimacy through a declaration of the Colombo Powers in 1 954 that con
tinued Portuguese rule in Goa ' was a violation of fundamental hwnan rights and a threat to the peace of the world '. India sub sequendy argued that since the General Assembly had condemned colonialism, and had classified Goa as a non-self-governing territory
under Art. 73, Portugal was in breach of her United Nations obliga
tions. Crowning all, the doctrine was propounded, apparendy first by Krishna Menon, that the possession of colonies, under any name, amounts to permanent aggression.
5 There is however a paradox about the principle of national self determination : that the more passionatdy it has been asserted, the less has it led to impartial popular consultation. The instrument of the old principle had been dynastic marriage. The corresponding instrument of the new principle was the plebis cite. Invented by the French Revolution, perfected as a means of territorial acquisition by Napoleon III and Cavour, the plebiscite came as near as may be to an impartial method of self-determination in the peace settlement of 1 9 1 9-20. Earlier plebiscites had been
used to determine the wishes of historic states or provinces, like
Tuscany and Savoy, whose identity and frontiers were not substan tially in question. The post-war plebiscites tested the allegiance of ill..defined districts of heterogeneous population which were the debris of the collapsed Central Empires. They were arranged by Allied commissioners, who determined from the best available evi dence both the unit within which the vote was to be taken and the method of voting, and they were policed by Allied troops. These
plebiscites were at the limit of what is technically feasible in con sulting popular wishes. They reached their apogee, I 5 years later, in the Saar plebiscite, the first to be policed by neutral troops. It
I 66
Systems of States
marked the end of the international reign of law under the League of Nations. The settlement after the Second World War saw the abandon ment of this constitutional mode of establishing legitimacy. The partial Paris Peace Conference of I 946 to a great extent ratified the work of its predecessor by restoring the national boundaries of Europe as they had been established in I 9 I 9 . The boundaries of Germany were the exception, for Germany was not represented at the Conference. Stalin had already pushed the Polish frontier west wards, engulfing the frontier so carefully and painfully delimited in I 9 I 9-20 by the plebiscites on the boundaries of East Prussia and Upper Silesia, and the Western powers had accepted this
de facto.
Instead of plebiscites, there were two activities, which marked the difference between the age of Stalin and the age of Woodrow Wilson. One was the expulsion of minorities. The East European countries which had suffered conquest by the Germans now visited retribution on their own German minorities, and drove them out, so that ten million refugees crowded into prostrate Germany. The second was denazification. I n October I 9 I 8 President Wilson had proclaimed as a condition of making peace the destruction of arbi trary rule in Germany, by which he meant the imperial and Prussian constitutions. Now, to be legitimized, Germany needed more than this degree of self-determination. She needed to be purged of those Germans who had violated the principles of civilized society. She was occupied by the Allies with the purposes, among others, of destroying the Nazi Party, eradicating Nazi institutions, and re-educating the German people in the principles of democracy. Under the United Nations, the institution of the plebiscite lost ground, when it might have been expected to gain. The criteria of legitimacy became more arbitrary, more revolutionary, more ideo logical. The worst precedents of the Versailles Settlement became dominant. When in 1 9 1 9 the Germans complained that the resur rected Poland was being given, in the former Prussian provinces of Posen and West Prussia, large German populations as well, they got the reply : ' There is imposed upon the Allies a special obligation to use the victory which they have won in order to re-establish the Polish nation in the independence of which it was unjustly deprived more than one hundred years ago. . . . To undo this wrong is the first duty of the Allies. '18 This line of argument was afterwards
In ternational legitimacy developed by Israel, to justify her own aggrandisement as rectifying the wrongs of the past, rather than seeking to establish justice today. When in I 9 I 9 the Germans asked for a plebiscite in Alsace Lorraine, the French replied in occult and irrelevant terms : ' The question of Alsace-Lorraine is a question of right, and therefore not a
French question but a world question ' .20 It was with the same
argument of indefeasible right, not to be tested by any popular consultation, that Indonesia in I 966 tried to evade her obligation to hold a plebiscite in West Irian. There were some popular consultations. France held referenda in her Indian establishments before ceding them to India - Chanderna gore in 1 949, Pondicherry, Karikal, Mahe and Yanam in 1 9 54. In unimportant instances the U.N. supervised plebiscites to decide the future of former colonies, as in British Togoland, the British Cameroons, and Western Samoa, or elections, as in French Togo land and Ruanda-Urundi. In a more important issue, at the begin ning of the international conflict between Indonesia and Malaysia in 1 96 3, the U.N. investigated and confirmed the elections by which North Borneo and Sarawak had chosen to join the Malaysian Feder ation. These consultations were designed to make it ' as clear as possible to the electorate, covetous neighbours, and to the world at large that the principle of self-determination had been fully com plied with ' . 21 But Ethiopia managed to swallow Eritrea in 1 9 60 without the wishes of the inhabitants having been ascertained. India from I 94 7 onwards steadfastly refused to allow the plebiscite in Kashmir called for by Pakistan and the U.N. Over Goa, Nehru said in the Indian Parliament in I 9 55 that his government was not prepared to tolerate the presence of the Portuguese in Goa, even if the Goans wanted them .22 Indonesia treated with contempt the U.N. observers who tried to attend ' the act of free choice ' which in I 969 she reluctantly allowed to be staged in West lrian.28 When Gibraltar expressed its own self-determination through the referendum of
Io
September I 9 67, conducted under a team of Commonwealth ob servers, there was a 97 per cent poll, I 2, I 38 votes in favour of retaining links with the United Kingdom against 44 for passing under Spanish sovereignty. (It was suggested that it might be wise to tamper with the voting returns, to contrive a better pro-Franco poll and make the business look less like an East European plebiscite).
1 68
Systems of States
But the U.N. Special Committee on Colonialism had already declared that a referendum would violate the Charter, on the grounds that the present residents of Gibraltar were not indigenous to the territory ; and the General Assembly ignored the result of the referendum, requesting Britain to ' terminate the colonial situa tion in Gibraltar ' by 1 October 1 969.
6 It seems that international society is excogitating a new principle of legitimacy, or rather, a version of the popular principle which makes it both simpler in theory and easier to apply in practice. Much the most valuable writer known to me on this development is Professor Ali A. Mazrui, who combines the scholarship of a pu il of John Plamenatz and Margery Perham with a sensitive and percipient understanding of Mrican thought and aspiration.u The new principle appeals essentially neither to history, language or culture. Mazrui speaks of a right of ' racial sovereignty '. 215 But this needs to be broadened. The new principle of legitimacy has two elements. It asserts firstly the right of the majority within the fron tiers prevailing at the given moment, and secondly the right of territorial vicinUty. In most cases ' the frontiers prevailing at the given moment ' are the result of the historical and geographical circumstances of the decolonizing process after 1 9 4 5 · India's refusal to concede auton omy to the Nagas, the insistence of the U.N. upon maintaining the unity of the Congo during the crisis of 1 960, the suppression of Biafran independence, the claim of Indonesia as successor state to the Netherlands East Indies to annex West Irian, 28 exemplify the principle . So does the Chinese suppression of Tibetan autonomy in 1 9 50, though this was also the reassertion of a historic suzerainty. In two cases, the formula ' the frontiers prevailing at the given moment' has been modified into ' the frontiers prevailing at an obvious moment in the past '. The first is the Soviet annexation of Estonia, Latvia, and Lithuania in 1 940. The successful extinction of these independent states is a unique event in twentieth-century European history, and perhaps deserves more analysis and explana tion than it has received. Though the United States and the United
p
International legitimacy Kingdom have apparently refused to grant de jure recognition,27 the international community at large seems to have acquiesced in it. Its international legitimization rests on nothing more than the secret additional protocol to the German-Soviet Treaty of Non-Aggression of 13 August 1 939, as modified by the secret supplementary proto col to the German-Soviet Boundary and Friendship Treaty of 2 8 September 1 939. 28 It is usually explained and justified, for instance by Sumner in his Survey of Russian History, as a reversal of an unjust settlement after the First World War, a resumption of Peter the Great's heritage, and a defensive preparation which may have saved Leningrad from falling to the Germans during the next two years. Ex injuria jus oritur? As Stalin implicitly claimed for the Soviet Union the frontiers of the former Russian Empire, so Nehru claimed for the Republic of India the frontiers of ' India ' as it had been before Vasco da Gama. He had had to acquiesce in the creation of Pakistan, and perhaps this exacerbated his impatience both with the princdy statrs and with the European colonies in India. It did not matter that India before Vasco da Gama had had no political status, but been only a culture half-conquered by Islam. The Portuguese conquest of Goa was seen as an act of aggression against this culture, which the Republic now represented and could avenge. The majoritarian right to extinguish a territorially contiguous geographical absurdity was expressed by the Manchester Guardian, when it wrote in 1 954 ; ' It is impossible that a Portuguese pocket territory should exist indefin itely in the midst of India bred in the spirit of nationalism. Even if a fair plebescite showed that a majority of the Goans wished to remain under Portugal it would not be practical politics for them to deter mine their fate in this way ' . 2 9 Perhaps it was not practical politics that the Baltic states should survive as independent states either. Pakistan was founded in defiance of the Hindu majority within the prevailing frontiers of the British Raj . The massacres and move ments of population that accompanied the partition of India may have contributed to establish the new majoritarian principle, though India has sought to remain faithful to the ideal of a secular, that is a religiously heterogeneous, state. Indo-Pakistani relations have pro duced the classic case of conflicting claims between two majorities in Kashmir, where the majority of the disputed province contradicts the majority of the secular Indian Republic.
Systems of States
1 70
There are cases where the new principle still demands fulfilment. The claim of the Arabs to the Arab lands is still affronted by the existence of Israel. It is an irony that the Arabs' claim to speak as a political whole - their claim to be a ' nation ', whose only embodi ment so far has been the Arab League and the transient existence of the United Arab Republic8 0 was crucial to the origin of the Jewish National Home. In so vast and underpopulated a region as the Arab lands, it was argued, there was surely a corner where the Jews might gather about their historic memories ? And if thereby they began to displace some of the indigenous Arabs, surely the vast
Arab lands - Transjord anian Palestine, to begin with - could settle them elsewhere ? 81 Meanwhile, the Arab minority inside that part of partitioned Palestine that became Israel would remain subject to the same principle of subordination to the interests of the majority. In Southern Africa, still more conspicuously, the majoritarian principle is frustrated, and is given greater emotional force by the appeal
to
fundamental considerations of humanity. South Africa
provided the first case in which the United Nations established the limits of Art.
2,
para.
7
of the Charter, which precludes the U.N.
from intervening ' in matters which are essentially within the dome stic jurisdiction of any state '. If South Africa infringed human rights, might not the General Assembly infringe South African domestic jurisdiction ? In
1 95 2
the General Assembly began dis
cussing South Africa's policies of racial discrimination, and estab lished the U.N. Commission on the Racial Situation in the Union of South Africa, which being refused admission to South Africa itself, held public hearings in Geneva for three years, and became an open tribunal for propaganda against South Africa. This came near to denying the legitimacy of the South African regime, and in
I
95 5
the South African delegation withdrew temporarily from the General Assembly. South Africa has become a pariah state, like the Ottoman Empire in the later nineteenth century, although rich and tolerably secure externally instead of decrepit and vulnerable. The majoritarian
case
against both South Africa and Rhodesia is
clear. It is less obvious in Portuguese Africa, as it was also in Goa, but here the majoritarian principle is reinforced by its partner, that of territorial vicinity. This found its classic expression in Burke : ' There is a Law of Neighbourhood which does not leave a man perfect master on his own ground. When a neighbour sees a new
International legitimacy erection,
in the nature of a nuisance, set up at his door, he has a
right to represent it to the judge; who, on his part, has a right to order the work to be staid ; or if established, to be removed. On this head, the parent law [i.e. the Roman law of equity] is express and clear; and has made many wise provisions, which, without destroy ing, regulate and restrain the right of
vicinage '. 52
ownership,
by the right of
But Burke adduced the right of vicinage as a defence
against innovation, a bulwark of prescription.
semper hahetur.
Vetustas pro lege
It has now been turned upside down, and becomes
an engine of innovation, to undermine prescription.
In the later 1 94os, when the British were beginning to learn the
weight of the anti-colonial campaign, and had not yet acquiesced in the rapidity with which colonial independence was expected, Sir Hilton Poynton argued in the Trusteeship Committee against what he called ' the blue water fallacy ', whereby colonies across the sea were examples of wicked colonialism, while colonies held in territor ial contiguity (like Russia's) escaped censure. The blue water fallacy has become orthodoxy, in the form of the right of territorial vicinity, and this is growing into a principle of continental solidarity. By this, Angola and Mozambique belong first of all to their African majori ties ; and if the African majorities prove uncertain, they ' belong ' secondly to their African neighbours, as Goa ' belonged ' to her Indian neighbour. The legal fiction that Angola and Mozambique are integral parts of the national territory, like the legal fiction that Algeria was a part of metropolitan France, no longer has any co gency. The same principle of continental solidarity is among those used to condemn United States intervention in Vietnam - ' inter vention in Asia ' from across the ocean. In the sphere of legitimacy, if not yet in the sphere of strategy, land power has triumphed over sea
power.
It follows from the majoritarian principle that minorities have no rights, or only such rights as the majorities may care to concede. In the Third World generally, and in Africa particularly, minorities can be designated pej oratively as ' tribes ', and tribalism is con demned as subversive of nationalism. European nationalism en gendered an elaborate system to protect minority rights in the peace treaties of 1 9 19-20, which like the use of plebiscites reflected the
constitutionalism of the age. Although minorities treaties were repudiated with indignity by the great powers, especially Italy, and
Systems of States
were difficult to enforce, they were a notable attempt to refine the new principle of legitimacy and to control its operation. Such provisions did not survive into the peace settlement of 1946. Their formal place has been taken by the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which the General Assembly adopted in 1 948. But this tends to assert the rights of individuals, as the irreducible units of humanity, rather than of national groups or minorities, and there is not even the rudimentary machinery for international super vision that the League developed for the minorities treaties. The result is that the individual is left confronting the state. The consequence for the principle of self-determination is illus trated by a statement of the Kenya delegate at the Addis Ababa Conference of 1 963. He was speaking about the claims of the Somali minority : ' the principle of self-determination . . .has no relevance where the issue is territorial disintegration. . . . If they do not want to live with us in Kenya, they are perfectly free to leave us and our territory . . . . This is the only way they can legally exercise their right of self-determination. • aa Thus the principle which broke up the Central Empires of Europe in 1 9 1 8, is invoked for a con trary effect outside Europe. The principle cuius regio eius religio is restored in a secular form. The elite who hold state power decide the political allegiance of all within their frontiers ; the recusant indivi dual may (if he is fortunate) be permitted to emigrate.
7
It remains to consider the alternative contemporary principle of legitimacy, that of the Communist world. The effect of living in a system of states has not been the ' number of terrible clashes ' with the bourgeois states that Lenin expected for the U.S.S.R. but the gradual acceptance of the notions of legitimacy and international right, although these formed no part of the original vocabulary of Marxism-Leninism. The Soviet principle of legitimacy has two general aspects. On the one hand, it is a common version of the popular principle in its majoritarian form, flowing from the doctrine in the Communist Manifesto that ' the proletarian movement is the self-conscious, independent movement of the immense majority ' .
International legitimacy
1 73
Vyshinsky used to warn the U.N., in the days of its unchallengable American ascendancy, that a majority in the U.N. represented only a minority in the world, but that a minority in the U.N. represented a majority in the ·world. On the other hand, though all bourgeois governments are due to be superseded, a tactical approval, amounting to a precarious certificate of legitimacy, is conceded to those bour geois states, above all under colonial nationalist regimes, which are cooperating with the movement of history by opposing imperialism. The special test of legitimacy, for the Soviet principle, is rule by a Communist Party. The double hierarchy in Communist states, party as well as governmental, has often been compared to the double hierarchy of Church and state in Counter-Reformation Europe. But it produces an international relationship that has resemblances also to dynasticism. This is perhaps a truer paralld : for the Party resembles a dynast, and differs from a Church, in that its only function is to rule. The Communist states are linked together not only by diplomatic representation of the usual kind, but also by the network of Communist parties. It is an international, not of her editary monarchs, but of self-perpetuating oligarchies, who have their own common interest, distinct from but parallel to the interests of the states they rule. The ' Communist monolith , of the earlier Cold War looked from the outside as threatening as did the Habs burg family system in the days of Charles V. But in each case particularist interests were undermining the unity, and the Com munist parties, like the dynasties before them, have shown a ten dency to become the vehicles of national interests.
7 Triangles and duels I It may be asked a
propos
of the potential triangle of Russia, China
and the United States if historical precedents suggest any conclu sions about the pattern and development of such three-cornered relationships. Is there, to take the simplest hypothesis, a tendency for triangles (let us use the word in the sense of the phrase ' the eternal triangle ' to describe an emotional relationship) to resolve themselves into duels, and duels to end in a monopoly of power for one side ? The present paper tries to do no more than tidy the premises of such an enquiry. The potential triangle of Russia, China and the United States is a good point at which to begin an examination of such political constellations. It shows, with clarity and purity, what might be called the ideal or essential characteristics of a triangle : They are three :
1.
The existence of a states�system or diplomatic community.
2. The ascendancy within the states-system of three great powers, of
roughly comparable calibre, each of them singly
so
preponderant
over all the remaining powers in the system that, if the other two great powers did not exist, it would have unchallengeable predomin� ance and might be in a position to establish a universal monarchy.
3. A
relationship between the three great powers of unremitting
suspicion, tension, hostility, which makes it impossible for any two to combine even temporarily against the third. It will be see n at once how closely these conditions compare with the grisly picture of a self-perpetuating balance between three totali� tarian powers that divide the world in Orwell's
Four.
Nineteen Eighty
There are small differences. I n Orwell's fantasy, the states�
system seems to have virtually disappeared. There are no states left except the Big Three.
Their diplomatic relationships are not
described, but seem to be governed by the principle of the primacy of
policy : each requires the appearance of perpetual exter nal war in order to maintain its totalitarian structure at home.
domestic
Triangles and duels
1 75
Consequently, in accordance with a pattern that is only hinted at, the three combine, two against one, and switch sides to recombine. From the standpoint of international relations, Orwell's triangle is a less pure specimen than the actual rudimentary triangle which provides our starting-point. Each of the three characteristics that we have noted in a political triangle needs to be clarified. A states-system presupposes both regu larity of diplomatic intercourse and homogeneity of culture : it is the political articulation of a macro-culture. It might be said that in the twelfth century there was a kind of triangle of power between Western Christendom, represented severally by the papacy, the Hohenstaufen Emperor, and Venice ; Eastern Christendom, repre sented by the East Roman Emperor ; and Islam,
represented
severally by the Seljuk Turks, the declining Fatimid Caliphate, and Saladin's kingdom . But although the relationships of this motley triangle of powers resembled modern international relations more than did the internal relationships of Western Christendom, because they were sovereign independent powers unfettered
inter se
either by membership of a single spiritual republic and ecclesiastical organization, or by feudal obligations, it is doubtful whether these relationships were so regular, or the culture of the region they spanned so homogeneous, as to form a states-system. Moreover, we should distinguish between open and closed states systems. A closed states-system is one which has no peripheral or external powers which may later move into the system and alter its balance. It is a system that has attained its maximum extension. The present states-system, being for the first time in history world-wide, may be called closed. Certain regional sub-systems, with definite geographical or linguistic limits, such as Italy in the fifteenth cen tury, or Germany in the nineteenth, have functioned under tem porary and privileged conditions
as
closed systems. But most
states-systems, and in particular the Western states-system during most of the past five centuries, have been open, with indeterminate limits, usually expanding. It is in a closed system that a triangle or duel can be best identified and observed. In open systems, such political constellations are ragged and transient. We must note, too, that the third characteristic of an ideal triangle - mutual hostility so intense that no two parties can combine against the third - has seldom if ever been given in historical experience.
Systems of States Triangles tend to be mobile figures of shifting alliances and nego tiations. Let us turn to the members of a triangle. The best case, we suggested, is when they are three dominant powers, of roughly comparable calibre. By ' the best case' I imply the aesthetic satis faction that is provided by the triangulation of the old conundrum about an irresistible force encountering an immovable object : the straining equipoise that underlies Orwell's picture. In historical experience three comparable dominant powers are rare. The trian· gular pattern has sometimes shown itself when one or more sides of the triangle has been not a single power but a war-time coalition : the Entente Powers, the Central Powers, the Axis Powers. Such alliances, however, have usually been led and dominated by a single great power, as Germany dominated both the Central Powers and the Axis. That the three members of the triangle appear comparable is in general a necessary consequence of their being regarded in the light of a triangle at all. Men become aware of a three-cornered rivalry and conflict of interests, and doubtfully measure the strength of the competitors. If there was not parity, observers would register the circumstances as a duel, or an hegemony. Nevertheless, within the range of parity, the roles of protagonist, deuteragonist, tritagonist can sometimes be allotted, and can sometimes show surprising reversals. There are, however, two examples of what may be called a false triangle : those that employ the notions of a Third Force, and a Third World. An antagonism between two great powers, a duel, has sometimes been varied by the influence or intervention of a weaker power or powers which have described their mediatory role in terms of completing the triad. Sweden offered such a role in the Nine Years' War. The French talked about such a role between America and Russia in the 1 9 50s. To claim the rights of a third partner is a confession of weakness. It was not in these terms that the United States held the balance between the Allies and the Central Powers from 1 9 1 4 to 1 9 1 7 . Those who call themselves a Third Force are not comparable to the great powers they stand between. If a Third Force is not a great power, a Third World is not a power at all, not even a Third Force. A Third World appears when
Triangles and duels
177
a duel, a bipolar system of power is modified by the presence of a group of small and weak states with some sense of common interest against the ascendancy of the two great powers. The conception of a Third World is formulated at least as early as 1 733, by d'Argenson. On voit combien la politique etablie aujourd'hui est fautive, [he wrote in that year] , ' et que de plus en plus les grands absorbent les petits. 11 n'y a que l'augmentation du tiers parti en Europe qui puisse arreter le progres j ournalier de cet abus. On en tend par
tiers parti ce qui n'est ni maison d'Autriche, ni maison de Bour bon . Nos deux emules, maison de France et maison d'Aut .
.
.
riche, causent Ia ruine et les troubles d'Europe; elles absorbent et absorberont tout. Les autres puissances du tiers parti ne font que glaner.1 By the tiers parti d'Argenson meant the small powers, primarily of Italy, secondarily of Germany. He was conceiving a policy for France of promoting the independence of the Italian states, in their own interests and also in French interests. When he afterwards became Foreign Minister during the Austrian Succession War he tried to follow such a policy, without success, because the Italian states did not have sufficient resources of vitality to play the part he allotted to them. A Third World appears again in Germany when the Austro-Prussian rivalry has become established. It shows itself already in the second half of the eighteenth century. But it organizes itself within the German Confederation in the nineteenth century, when the German Middle Powers, Bavaria, Saxony and Wiirthem berg, were prompted by the Austro-Prussian alliance of 20 April 1 854 to seek an independent ' German ' policy. As Gerlach wrote to Bismarck at the time, it was a revival of the Confederation of the Rhine, this time seeking Russian not French patronage.2 The Third Germany disappeared for good in the Prussian victory of 1 87
Systems of States 2 Political triangles are in most cases abstractions, selections from the complexity and multiplicity of international history. Identifying tri angles can seem as arbitrary and subjective as the Marxist dialectical method of interpretation. Relationships between the great powers have frequently fallen into a three-sided pattern, or to put it differently, three great powers have frequently attained a pre dominance which makes the states-system dependent on their poli cies towards one another. But such constellations tend to dissolve as quickly as they have come into being, or to be altered by the flow of events in such a way that the triple predominance is lost and the three sink to the level of the other great powers . Between 1 8 66 and I 8 7 6 the future of Europe depended on the relationship be tween Prussia, Austria and France. Russia was still under the restraints resulting from defeat in the Crimean War; British policy was isolationist. Prussia was thus able to separate and crush first one and then the other of the two great powers that disputed with her the organizing of Germany. This transient triangle dissolved when Britain and Russia intervened during the ' war in sight , crisis in I 8 7 5, to warn Germany against further humiliation of France. A more striking example is the triangle of France, Russia and Britain at the height of the Napoleonic Empire, between the battle
of lena in I 8o6 and the retreat from Moscow in I 8 I 3. Austria and Prussia had been temporarily eliminated from the ranks of the great powers ; at Tilsit, Napoleon and Alexander partitioned Europe, so that the united strength of Europe could be rurned against British sea power. This is a truer triangle than that of Prussia, Austria and France between 1 8 66 and 1 8 7 I : the relative
ascendancy of the three powers over their political environment
was greater. But it was not a triangle in the full sense of our initial definition. In North America there was an invulnerable power of equal potential with the three, the young colossus to whom Bona parte had sold Louisiana remarking, as he signed the treaty of cession, that he was giving Britain a rival who would one day humble her ; a power which had already been drawn into the European struggle in an undeclared war with France, and was soon to be involved in it again in a formal war with Britain. And in I 8 I 3 the Tilsit triangle dissolved with the resurrecton of Prussia
Triangles and duels
1 79
and Austria as great powers, and the declining strength of France. It is possible that most examples of political triangle that we examine will reveal this transient, temporary and relative character, and that our conclusions will accordingly need to be qualified. Triangles, like duels, are relationships of conflict, and are resolved by war. The triangle of Russia, China, and the United States has not yet been so resolved, but the historical precedents permit no other generalization . Triangles can be classified on the model of a knock-out tourna ment. It is a tournament with some of the untidiness of the croquet game in Alice in Wonderland. The rounds are American doubles, two against one, as often as singles. To lose a round is not always decisive, and the defeated can reappear for a replay. Moreover, in an open states--system entirely new competitors can enter and join the contest half-way through. Nevertheless, over a long enough span of time some elimination takes place, and we can classify triangles according to the decisiveness of the conflict they lead to. Here are some classes : I . End-game, or world championship. Such a triangle is resolved by one of the powers defeating the other two powers singly, and usually in quick succession, so that it remains undis puted master of the field. 2. Semi-final. Such a triangle is resolved by two of the powers combining to defeat the third. The upshot is usually a duel, which may be of two kinds. Either the two victors quarrel between themselves, or the stronger victor is confronted by a new challenger that has just moved into the system . 3· First round. In such a triangle the three powers exhaust themselves in conclusively and are eclipsed and even conquered by an outsider. 4· Preliminary round. Such a triangle is resolved by one power entering into close partnership with a second, but the two together are unable to prosecute their conflict with the third, and the triangle dissolves to be resumed in a later generation. Let us examine them more closely. 3
The end-game triangle, or world championship, is intellectually the most satisfactory, because it is the most clear-cut and decisive. It occurs only in a closed system . The classic example of the terminal triangle is Rome, Carthage,
I SO
Systems of Stotes
and Macedon in the last decade of the third century and the opening decade of the second century B.C. In the Eastern Mediterranean there were three Hel lenistic great powers, successor-states of Alex ander's empire : Macedon, the Seleucid Empire, and Ptolemaic Egypt, fairly equally balanced. In the Western Mediterranean were two great powers : Rome, master of Italy and Sicily, and Carthage, master of North Mrica and Spain. They belonged to a common diplomatic community, which was a nascent states-system . The earliest diplomatic engagement of the Roman republic, after the expulsion of the Tarquins, is a treaty with Carthage of
509
B .C.
that delimits their spheres of influence, implicitly against the ex pansionist Greeks. And in
228
B .C., when she had just established
a protectorate over Corfu and part of the Ill yrian coast, in order to keep down the Ill yrian pirates, Rome sent embassies for the first time to Athens and Corinth. The Corinthians thereupon decreed the admission of the Roman people to the Isthmian Games, which was the traditional mode of declaring a state a member of the Hellenic community. (For all that, the Greeks continued to look on the Romans as barbarians.) The Hannibalic War against Rome began in
218.
Philip V of
Macedon, an unwise politician, watched the war with interest, and intervened on Hannibal's side. The First Macedonian War
205) was for Rome a war on a second front,
(2 1 5-
and she ceded territory
on the Ill yrian seaboard to bring it to an end, in order to deal with the greater enemy. When in 202 Carthage was at last defeated and reduced to a client state, Rome turned her attention to Macedon, delivered an ultimatum, and defeated her in her tum in the Second Macedonian War
(2o
This is not however a flawless example of a triangle, because Macedon was not the only Hellenistic great power. The Seleucid ruler Antiochus the Great, who had restored the fortunes of the Seleucid Empire, watched the Second Macedonian War as Philip
V had watched the Second Punic War, failed as Philip had failed to join forces with Rome's enemy at the right time, and took advantage of Macedon's predicament to intervene in her sphere of influence in Europe. In the year that Macedon was compelled to make peace with Rome, Hannibal himself took refuge at the court of Antioch us. The inevitable Romano-Seleucid War began in 192 when the minor Greek states, whom Rome had liberated from
Triangles and duels
181
Macedon, appealed to Antioch us to liberate them from Rome. Rome for the first time invaded Asia Minor, and Antiochus admitted defeat in 1 8 8 . Rome was now indisputably predominant in the Greek and Hellenistic world. This predominance was confirmed by the Third Macedonian War of
1 7 1-1 6 7,
which ended with the
kingdom of Macedon destroyed for ever by being partitioned into four republics. Rome did not need to fight another war against the Seleucid Empire, nor any war against Ptolemaic Egypt until Cleopatra joined forces with Antony over a hundred years later. This instance of a political triangle proves, therefore, to have been really a political quadrilateral . But the dynamics of its resolution are
still those we described as the end-game. In the 30 years between 2 1 8 B .C., when Hannibal invaded Italy, and 1 8 8 B.C., when the Peace of Apamea was imposed on Antiochus Ill, Rome defeated three rival great powers in quick succession and conclusively. Each
victory, to borrow an expression of Machiavelli's, left the addentella tion for constructing the next. It is perhaps an unparalleled example of momentum and finality in the transforming of a complex states system into an empire. It is apposite to mention here the Roman triumvirates. They are probably without historical parallel. They were not constellations within an international states-system, but attempts to revolutionize the government of a declining republic overblown with empire. Rome's victory in the Third Macedonian War had established her suzerainty, in fact though not yet in law, over the whole of the moribund Hellenistic states-system. From that moment the Roman Empire was in being, but it had not yet found appropriate institu tions. The triumvirates were the penultimate stage of the trans formation of the Republic to match her imperial responsibilities. They were arrangements of the domestic politics of an imperial state, involving the partition of its territories into spheres of in fluence on behalf of the dominant politicians of the governing class. Each triumvirate· was composed of two major politicians and one minor - the greedy Crassus and 'slight Lepidus ' . The First Trium virate was formed in
6o
B.C. when Caesar made
an
alliance with
Pompey against the senatorial oligarchy, and invited Crassus to join them. ' He made a compact with both of them, that nothing should be done in public affairs of which any one of the three disapproved ', a negative formula reflecting their mutual distrust. • When the
Systems of States triumvirate was renewed at the Conference of Luca in 5 6, Pompey obtained a command in Spain and Crassus one in Syria to balance Caesar's in Gaul . Crassus was defeated and killed by the Parthians in Mesopotamia. His death removed a potential rival to Caesar, and at the same time a bond between him and Pompey, since distrust of their third colleague was all that now held them together. The triangle became a duel, and ended quickly with Caesar's complete victory. ' He persuaded them, reconciled them, and won them both to his support, ' says Plutarch of Caesar and the other triumvirs, ' and constituted with that triumvirate an irresistible power, with which he overthrew the senate and people, not by making his partners greater, the one through the other, but by making himself greatest of all through them '. 4 The First Triumvirate is an imperfect example of the end-game triangle, since one of its members was removed by extraneous causes. The Second Triumvirate is in this respect a perfect example, the · more notable in that the ultimate victor was not the prime mover, as Caesar had been in 6o, and began the game as more definitely the tritagonist than Caesar had been. 5 But in another respect, both triumvirates differ from a triangle : they began as alliances against an external enemy who threatened the interests and security of the triumvirs, not as constellations of powers or dynasts who could be exclusively concerned with their, mutUal relations. The First Triumvirate was formed against the senatorial oligarchy. The Second Triumvirate had still more of the character of a revolutionary alliance against the old forces. After the murder of Caesar the Roman world had split territorially : Brutus and Cassius, the representatives of the senatorial oligarchy, controlled the East ; the Caesarian leaders who made the triumvirate had only the West, and shared that with the pirate-adventurer who ruled the seas, Young Pompey. At the Conference of Bononia in 43 B.C., where the triumvirate was agreed upon, Antony assumed command of Gaul, Lepidus of Spain, but Octavian got only Africa and the islands. After the defeat of Brutus and Cassius at Philippi, in 42, a battle in which Octavian played a poor second to Antony, the triumvirs monopo lized the Roman world, and redivided it. Antony took the East, which was the treasure-house and offered dreams of a Parthian campaign ; Octavian had to restore order in a distracted and im-
Triangles and duels poverished Italy; Lepidus was already being downgraded. At the Conference of Brundisium in 40 the division of the world was confirmed, and Lepidus was allotted Africa. By the time the trium virs met again at Tarentum in 37, Antony could see that he had unwittingly surrendered to Octavian control of the heartland and capital of the empire. In 36, in a single crisis, Octavian conquered Young Pompey in Sicily, unilaterally dismissed Lepidus from the triumvirate, and official I y declared the Civil War to be ended. The triangle had now become a duel. In 32 Octavian declared Antony stripped of his triumviral powers, and with consummate skill declared war according to the ancient ritual on the foreign enemy, Cleopatra. Each of the triumvirates lasted I I years ; in each case the weakest triumvir disappeared in the seventh year, Crassus by death in battle against a foreign enemy, Lepidus by relegation after the defeat of a domestic enemy. The First Triumvirate was secret and informal, and controlled the organs of government only indirectly. The Sec ond Triumvirate was public and statutory, established by a tribuni cian law, a restoration of the dictatorship in triple form. Partly for this reason, and partly because public authority had disintegrated still further between 6o and 40 B.C., the history of the Second Triumvirate is more complex than that of the First. But the Second is a purer example of the end-game political triangle, when one competitor eliminates his two partners and rivals in tum. For the modern Western states-system, coming to self-awareness at a time when the models of antiquity were venerated, the Punic Wars offered the archetypal example of a duel. ' Carthago delenda est' was pronounced by the Habsburgs against Venice in the Thirty Years War, by Shaftesbury against Holland in the English Parlia ment in . I 673, by the Dutch and the Bourbon powers in the eighteenth century against England (though French writers some times reversed the application, seeing England as the overweening Rome throttling the inoffensive French Carthage), by the Directory and afterwards by the Kaiser against England. D'Argenson in I 748 even stretched the Punic Wars into a tri angle : ' L' Angleterre et la maison d'Autriche sont nos seuls rivaux de puissance par mer et par terre, ce sont deux Carthages contre une Rome' .1 But this was an aberration of historical haruspicy. The archetypal example of a political triangle was properly found in the Roman triumvirates. Frederick the Great referred to them more
Systems of States
than once. At the outbreak of the Seven Years War he compared the three powers arrayed against him to the Second Triumvirate. The allies abandoned in the Diplomatic Revolution were compared to the victims of the proscriptions : the Empress had sacrificed the Maritime Powers to the resennnent of France, and France had sacrificed Prussia to the ambition of the Empress, ' celle-d se pro posant d'imiter la conduite d'Auguste, qui se servit du pouvoir de ses collegues pour s'agrandir et les precipiter ensuite l'un apres l' autre ' .r The historical parallel was far-fetched, but it was high class propaganda. The odd circumstance that each of the World Wars of the twentieth century ended with a Big Three of victors, dramatized by outstanding individuals - Woodrow Wilson, Lloyd George and Clemenceau ; Roosevelt, Stalin and Churchill - gave the triumvirates a new interest. The implications of the supposed historical parallel contradicted the progressive and pacifist hopes aroused by the two Big Threes ; but there was a precedent for these hopes too in the jubilation that greeted the Triumvirs' Pact of Brundisium in 40 B.C., and produced Virgil's Fourth Eclogue. However, neither of the victorious Allied coalitions proved to be an end-game triangle. The emergence of Chairman Mao to make a new triangle does not have a precedent in antiquity. Two other examples of an end-game triangle may be mentioned. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries there was a triangle first in North America, and then in India, between the English, the French and the native powers. The English defeated the French and could then subjugate the native powers. The outline of these triangles is relegated to an appendix. 4
Semi-final. We described this kind of triangle as that in which two of the powers combine to defeat the third. If the stat�system is open, the two survivors may be joined or overshadowed by another power hitherto on the periphery, and a new triangle appears. If the states-system is closed, the two survivors maintain their uneasy cooperation until it turns into a duel. At the end of the nineteenth century there was an antagonism in Europe between the Triple Alliance and the Dual Alliance, with
Triangles and duels Britain uncommitted : a shadowy triangle. Britain moved towards the Dual Alliance, which became the Triple Entente. The shadowy triangle turned into a duel, and it was for long evenly contended. The United States now stood forth as the third point of a new triangle. She moved towards the Entente, which became the Allied and Associated Powers. When the Central Powers had been defeated the United States drew apart again. This proved a false semi-final. The United States and the Allied Powers lacked the will and the circumstances to proceed to a duel , though Anglo-American naval rivalry came near to one, and House wrote to Wilson in July I 9 I 9 that ' the relations of the two countries are beginning to ass ume the same character as that of England and Germany before the war '. In the event, Germany recovered from her defeat, and danced her figure in the triangular dance a second time. Moreover, the Bolshevik Revolution detached Russia from her former partners and established her at an acute angle from them. From the later I 9 3os the semi-final was replayed. There was an antagonism in Europe between the League Powers and the Axis Powers. It was the Soviet Union that was uncommitted from Munich until the Nazi-Soviet Pact. During that year there was a true political triangle. It had a shadowy extension until I 94 I , since the Soviet Union was less committed to her German accomplice than their partition of Eastern Europe in I 9 39-40 had at first suggested, and on the other side the United States was more com mitted to the Western Powers than she had been in the former war. The German invasion of Russia, and Pearl Harbor resolved the triangle into a duel . The Western Powers and Russia together defeated the Axis Powers, and recovered to face a new duel between themselves - or, as some on both sides of the argument have seen it, the real and fundamental duel, going back to I 9 I 7, from which the rise of Fascism and the Second World War were a diversion, of marginal relevance. To justify its name a semi-final ought to precede an end-game. Mter I 945 it seemed that the states-system was effectively closed, and the Cold War looked like the middle stage of the end-game until perhaps I 964, when China became an atomic power. It is difficult to find a precedent for the enlargement of a duel between two advanced powers into a triangle through the transformation of a vast and backward people into a power of comparable potential.
t 86
Systems of SttJtes
The relation of the Ottoman Empire to the rivalry between France and the House of Habsburg has some similarities. But Ottoman ascendancy antedated the Valois-Habsburg struggle. The Ottoman Empire dominated Eastern Europe for a century before the fall of Constantinople in 1 4 53, and invaded Italy in 1480, while the fatal rivalry over the Burgundian succession had not begun until Mary's marriage to Maximilian in I 4 77. Another triangle in which two powers combined against a third, and then proceeded to conclusions between themselves, may be seen in the case of Spain, the United Provinces, and England in the seventeenth century. Spain, after the annexation of Portugal in 1 5 So, had a nominal monopoly of the overseas world. England and the Dutch, whom the English helped in their war of independence against Spain, steadily encroached upon the Spanish�Portuguese monopoly. By the beginning of the seventeenth century the Dutch had commercial domination of the East Indies ; before the middle of the century they had the world's carrying trade. As they rose, their relations with England deteriorated. These relations had be come so close that in 1 5 85 the Dutch invited Elizabeth to accept sovereignty over the United Provinces, and in 165 1 the Common wealth invited the United Provinces to enter a union. The interests of the two powers were both so close and so conflicting that unless they could unite they would fight. They failed to unite, and fought three wars against one another. An alliance came about with William Ill's accession to the British throne, when the Dutch had already passed the peak of their power. From this point they grad ually but irrevocably declined into the condition which Frederick afterwards described as coal-boat to the British man-of-war. At the end of the Spanish Succession War Britain violated her pledge to obtain equal trading privileges in the Spanish Empire for the British and Dutch, and secured for herself the monopoly of trade with Spanish America. It was the resolution of a triangle of com mercial politics that had lasted for a century and a half. 5
First round. This kind of triangle occurs in an open states-system, when three great powers wear each other down or knock each other
Triangles and duels out, and are eclipsed by another great power of previously unex pected possibilities. It might be called quartus gaudms. The classic example has as its central episode the Pdoponnesian War. The magic of Thucydides has stamped the Peloponnesian War for all time as a struggle between Athens and Sparta. A con temporary American scholar has written a book called Thucydides and the Politics of Bipolarity. Nevertheless the duel was subordinate to a triangle in which the third party was Persia. In the Persian Wars, Athens and Sparta had combined against the invader. Athens' initial success · led her to build up a great naval empire with the purpose of carrying a war of liberation against the Persian Empire itself. Sparta became alarmed, and the Atheno-Spartan alliance broke down. From 459 to 446 B.C. Athens was at war with Persia and Sparta simultaneously. The strain was too great. She made peace first with Persia, then with Sparta. Persia retired into the wings, and preserved a judicious neutrality at first when in 4 3 1 the duel between Athens and Sparta was taken up again. Of the two Greek great powers, Athens because of her thalassocracy was by far the more dangerous to Persia. After the Athenian disaster in Sicily, therefore, Persia resumed an active foreign policy, and intervened on the Spartan side. The final defeat of Athens was accomplished by a combination of Spartan military power and Persian economic resources. Persia even supplied the wages of the new Spartan fleet. But the capitulation of Athens in 404 B.C. was not the end of the story. It was the terminus ad quem o£ Thucydides' story (though his account did not reach it) and that has made it for all posterity the great divide. The generation of Thrasybulus and Konon prob ably saw it differently. They had lost a war, even an empire, but much might be recovered in the next round. The Long Walls had been pulled down ; they could be rebuilt. It is very striking that the Peloponnesian War, ' the greatest commotion the Hellenes had ever experienced ', ended with no peace settlement. Sparta resumed the hegemony she had traditionally enjoyed before 480. She quarrelled with her Persian ally and launched an invasion of Asia Minor. Persia retaliated by financing an anti-Spartan coalition in Greece, including Athens who rebuilt the Long Wails and recovered some of her insular possessions. The peace settlement, when it came at last in 3 89, was known as the King's Peace, because it was nego tiated, or even handed down, at the Persian court. It established a
1 88
Systems of Stales
balance of interests between Persia and Sparta. Athens, who had been first, was now the least of the three, and had to be content with the role of cultural capital. After an interval Sparta was struck down by Thebes, to whom Persia transferred her alliance. But then there arose Macedon, which in quick succession conquered Thebes, Athens, Sparta, and Persia itself, a culmination beyond the dreams of the great Athenian statesmen of the century before. The triangle of the Ottomans, the Habsburgs and France at the beginning of the Western states-system, to which allusion has al ready been made, has a greater similarity to the Macedonian quartus gaudens than to the present Ru�Sin�American triangle. Cam panella described that triangle in his Discorsi Politici, about 16oo : In Europe the House of Austria and the Ottoman House aspire to universal empire, and stand as it were in balance, so that neither one nor the other can advance. Today the princes of Italy do not allow Spain to grow so strong that they themselves would become a prey to her. Thus they make a counterbalance with France, and when they see the King of France having the worst of it, they seek to raise him to match Spain ; but if they were to see Spain decline and France become dominant in Italy, they would aid Spain as they have done in the past when France possessed Naples and Sicily. Some people think it is good to have the power of the Turk as a check on the forces of the House of Austria, which without such an obstacle would master the whole of Europe. I say that this kind of diplomacy is disastrous at the present time, because the Turk has so much power that he is without doubt superior to Italy, to Spain, to France and to Germany, divided and separately, though not to them all together. It has already been seen that, when Europe was all Catholic, she was not able to stem the growth of Ottoman power, but it was always allowed to grow through our disunion. 8 But in the end none of these three powers dominated the other two. The Ottomans and Habsburgs wore one another down, and disappeared from history in the same catastrophe. France declined until she could no longer support an East European policy. The quartus gaudens was Russia, which is now predominant in most of
Triangles and duels the regions fonnerl y occupied by the Habsburg and Ottoman Em pires, though not yet in Western Europe. If we go back to the Middle Ages, and permit ourselves to con sider once again the doubtful triangle of Latin Christendom, Greek Christendom, and Islam, we
can see
the same pattern of evolution.
What Russia has done in the later triangle, the Ottoman Turks themselves did in the earlier triangle, coming as late interlopers to gather up tw�thirds of the stakes occupying first the Byzantine and then the Moslem worlds (barring Persia), but failing in their assault upon the Western world. Let us go back still further. The earliest expression of the notion
of a political triangle in Western history is probably the celebrated letter that Alcuin wrote to Charlemagne in June
799·
There are
three potentates in the world, he said, who stand high above all others : ' the apostolic sublimity ', the pope at Rome; the imperial dignity, established in the Second Rome ; and thirdly �e royal dignity, entrusted by God to the king of the Franks himself. The pope's revival of the Western imperial dignity on Charlemagne's
behalf 1 8 months later confirmed the perspicacity of Alcuin's des cription. What happened to this triangle ? The legitimate imperial dignity at the Second Rome found reason to concede reluctant recognition to the upstart imperial dignity at Achea. But the gulf of suspicion and hatred between Byzantium and the West was unbridgeable. The two societies slid towards open schism and mutual anathema
in
1 054, to Alexius's anxious manipulation of his unwelcome Western allies on the First Crusade, to Manuel Comnenus's proposal in 1 1 6 8 that the pope should reunite the Roman Empire by recognizing Constantinople as its sole seat and deposing Barbarossa, to the
Western capture and sack of Constantinople in I 204 . Meanwhile, the apostolic sublimity and the imperial dignity of the West, twin authorities of a single society, had themselves become locked in a conflict that led at last to the papal crusade to extirpate the Hohen staufen brood of vipers. (The line ended with the death of Conradin on the scaffold at Naples.) In this central drama of the Middle Ages, the papacy was left the titular victor over two empires. But it was a false victory, and within 5 0 years the papacy was itself abased by the French kingdom, pioneer and paragon of the new nascent nation-states.
regna,
the
Systems of States A similar triangle is observable in the sphere of doctrinal or con fessional politics. At the Religious Peace of Augsburg in
1 55 5
the
duel between Catholicism and Lutheranism was given juridical recognition. The thrust of Calvinism immediately began to enlarge the duel into a triangle. Sully was one of the earliest observers to recommend that the new triangle should be recognized - though this, he suggested, should be the limit of tolerated versions of Chris tianity : thenceforward non-proliferation. Each of these three religions being now established in Europe in such a manner that there is not the least appearance that any of them can be destroyed, and experience having sufficiently demon strated the inutility and danger of such an enterprise, the best therefore that can be done, is to preserve, and even strengthen all of them in such a manner that indulgence may not become an encouragement to the production of new sects or opinions, which should carefully be suppressed on their first appearance.' However, as soon as the triangle had in its turn received juridical recognition at Westphalia, it ceased to describe the spiritual map of Europe. With varying speed the three forms of Christianity declined in influence, and the beneficiary of their deadlock was secularism, enlightenment, the scientific revolution. The ideological politics of Europe in the first half of the twentieth century showed a resem blance to the confessional politics of the seventeenth century, with liberal democracy as the heir (not always willingly acknowledged) of Catholicism, Fascism of Lutheranism, Communism of Calvinism. Many writers have suggested that the beneficiary of their deadlock will again be something different from the pretensions of all three : managerial technological bureaucracy.
6 In the course of putting these reflections on paper, I have become aware of the danger of confusing two distinct criteria for the at tempted classification of political triangles. One is a supposed ten dency of historical succession or development, suggested by the comparison with the stages of a knock.aut competition. That com.. parison begs the most important question.
Triangles and duels
The second criterion is provided by analysing the conflict within the triangle and the way the conflict is resolved. This deserves further examination. Let us try to reduce the different kinds of triangles to formulae. 1 . The formula for the end-game is : A versus B, A versus C (A versus D, etc.) A's monopoly, where versus signifies ' eliminates' or ' disposes of', and the equation sign points to the conclusion. 2 . The formula for the semi-final is : A + B versus C, leading to alternative conclusions : (a) A versus B (b) Enter D : D versus A + B, each of which sets the scene for an end-game. 3. The formula for the first round is : A versus B versus C versus A = X's monopoly, and X subsequendy becomes party to a semi-final triangle. The question is whether these formulae, if they have value and are accurate, can be correlated with the successive stages of a knock out process. To the extent to which the correlation can be estab lished, the knock-out process may become more credible. =
7
Historical precedents, even if they can be reduced to serviceable order, shed only an indirect light on present circumstances. To estimate the prospects of the Russo-Sino-American triangle, we must make political judgments, measuring the visible task against the visible resources. This is what Thucydides meant when he singled out, as supremely worthy of admiration in Themistocles, the grasp of ta deonta - the things necessary, the proper expedient, the decisive elements in the situation. And he linked it not with a sense of the past but with a sense of the future : a power of divination, an insight into how things would work out, ' Wisdom to foresee clearly the issue for better or worse that lay in the still dim future. ' It is possible that, as the world has gone on since those days,
Syskms of Sl4tes
politicians (and others) have increasingly acquired an historical perspective ; and if a man has an historical perspective it will of course colour his notion of the task ' or ' need' of the current genera tion. But it is not an essential of political insight. The strong histori cal consciousness of Churchill and Kennedy has led Dr Rowse and others to argue that statesmanship is founded upon sense of history. It might be easier to maintain the converse, that the majority of successful politicians and reformers have done without an historical sense. Cicero had a richer understanding of Roman history than Caesar; it was one reason why he was a less competent politician. Of French statesmen, the most copiously endowed with historical cul ture is Guizot, a sublime failure ; the least so, Richelieu, who made history. The opposition to Wilberforce over the slave trade (as to most reformers) was largely grounded upon arguments of historical stability . King Frederick William IV, if we may stoop so low, had livelier and more colourful thoughts about history than his repre sentative at the Federal Diet, Count von Bismarck. In the past century, the influ�nce of historicist ideologies on politics offers warnings of self-deception rather than examples of sagacity. To study the prospects of the Russo-Sin�American triangle, it was said, we must make political judgments, measuring the visible task against the visible resources. The task, let us argue, is the funda mental political task at all times : to provide order, or security, from which law, justice and prosperity may afterwards develop. The state provided security for five centuries : it can no longer. The task is primarily military, second!y governmental, third! y economic. His torical development produced these conditions in the reverse order. The Great Discoveries led to the economic unification of the world, and the completion of a world market in the nineteenth century. There was wide belief that political unity would follow naturally. It is surprising how often contemporary publicists compared the Victorian peace, particularly the armed peace of 1 8 7 1-19 14, to the Pax Romana, overlooking the essential contrast between a single imperium and a dubious concert of quarrelsome great powers. The First World War inculcated the lesson that political unity, like everything else, had to be worked for and paid for. The quasi confederal League was invented to supply it, without success. Political development limped behind economic, and military be hind political. Napoleon at the height of his power could not have •
Triangles and duels
1 93
unified the world militarily. In the nineteenth century sea power gave a deceptive impression of providing political stability ; economic blockade seemed the decisive weapon of the First World War; the League was built upon the expectation that economic sanctions could keep the world in order. There were two Raws in the theory of world-government through sea power. First, sea power was effective against a great continental military force only when used in conjunction with a mal great continental military force. The defeat of Germany required the positive application of Allied and As� ciated manpower and munitions as well as the negative application of economic blockade. Secondly, the 'WOrld was not yet so inter dependent economically, nor was sea power so dlcctive strategical! y, that it could bring pressure uniformly over the world's surface.. The Bolshevik RevolutiOR established itself roughly in that self-sufficient region of the Old World that was immune to Allied sea power for at least as long as the Allies were mioded to utilize their sea power. This gave MacKinder his definition of the H eW&od.10 Anyway, the twin monopolists of sea power after 1 9 1 9 were at cross purposes, and lacked the will to assert authority whether jointly or severally. The advent of atomic power in 1 945 at last produced circumstances in which the military domination of the entire states-system by a single power became possible and desirable. The two conditions for such an ascendancy were that the dominant power should have a monopoly of the new weapon, and should also possess the resolution to threaten the weapon and if need be to employ it in restraint of private war. For four years the United States had the monopoly. Once again, though now for different reasons, she lacked the will to make use of it, and her attempt to put it into commission through the Baruch Plan was a failure. But at this point it was reasonable to assert that the states-system was ripe for unification, the world ripe for world-government. The subsequent reversal of the process, from monopoly back into dud, gave rise in the next 20 years to repeated predictions of a devolution of power, a return to a multiple balance, a new Concert of World Powers. China is, in one aspect, only the most successful of many candidates for the role of enlarging the privileged circle. India, United Europe, Brazil, even Indonesia, conspicuously Japan, have in turn had their academic prophets of future greatness on the grounds of population, resources or rate of growth. For all this,
1 94
Systems of States
there are today only two powers that qualify for the SALT talks. If the first requirement of society is political order (the premise from which this argument began) then the most important aspect of the states-system at the present moment is that if the Russo--American duel could be converted into a firm diarchy or condominium, or if either could be eliminated without the other disappearing in the same process, the states-system would be reducible under a single authority. It is some such argument in terms of political need that I had in mind when speaking of 'measuring the visible task against the visible resources '. The content of the argument is undoubted! y questionable or fallacious. But it attempts to be a different kind of argument from the legerdemain of historical precedents, and the assumption of a knock-oUt tournament. 8
We may remind ourselves, in conclusion, of two pieces of proverbial wisdom. In a deadlocked triangle, Three will not be sorry to see One and Two batter each other to pieces. Alcibiades advised Tissaphernes, satrap of the Anatolian coast-lands for King Darius, not to be eager to bring the Peloponnesian War to an end, but to let the dominion be divided between the two sides, so as to wear the Hdlenes out upon one another. If either Athens or Sparta won a decisive victory, the king would have no alternative but sooner or later to ' stand up' himself, like the ephedros or third combatant in the games, who sits by to fight the victor. Thus Baldwin observed in July 1 936, ' If there is any fighting to be done, I should like to see the Bolsheviks and the Nazis doing it.' Provided it does not escalate into an out-of-control big war [said the Economist in I 969 ] , the Russian-Chinese conflict is pure gravy for the rest of us. . A continuing political rift, accom panied by border warfare on a scale short of all-out war, seems to be the Sino--Soviet relationship which best serves the interest of the non.-communist world. The west's role in this relationship is bound to be essential! y passive. It can look for such understand· ings as can be reached with either side. But it is remarkably hard •
•
Triangles and duels
1 95
to foresee a situation in which it would want to intervene even if it could. There is something to be said for being, for once, the neutral bystander; to be explicit about it, the Urtius gaudens. Conversely, in a deadlocked duel, where One can make no headway against Two, he may lash out at a third party, or sideways. There can be sound strategic reasons for it. & the Mytileneans said to the Peloponnesians, the war would not be decided in Attica, but in those countries from which Athens derived her support. The supreme example of the principle of enlarging the strategic orbit in the history of war is probably Grant's campaign that captured Vicks burg and opened the Mississippi to the Union. But the lashing out can be less reasonable or less successful, can resemble an act of political frustration, as when Napoleon and Hitler invaded Russia; and in these cases the third party lashed out against had been playing the role of Three in the triangle. APPENDIX It was suggested above that an end-game triangle can be discerned in each of the two chief regions of Anglo-French colonial rivalry during early modern times. In North America, there was a political triangle composed of the English and French colonists and the Indian tribes. In Hindustan, there was a corresponding triangle composed of the East India Company, the Compagnie des Indes Orientales, and the 'country powers ' - the English name for the successor-states of the Moghul Empire. To multiply paradigms is tedious. But to offer them as evidence one needs to provide supporting argument. An attempt is made here to give the outline of the two cases. Two preliminary questions present themselves. First, was there a stateS-system in either of these regions ? India before the Moghul Conquest seems to display less of a coherent states-system than any of the world's great macro-cultures less too than that earlier India which produced the Arthaslzastra, and was the main subject of Adam Watson's paper of 1 967. Part of the reason is that the Hindu states which might have composed the states-system were being progressively conquered from the twelfth
Systems of States
to the seventeenth century by alien and intolerant Muslim powers, of whom the greatest was the Moghul Empire. The East India Company's territorial acquisition began in I 639 with the grant of the site of Madras by the ruler of the decrepit kingdom of Vijayana gar. Its raison d'etre for three centuries had been to stay the tide of Muslim invasion on the river Kistna, and 40 years later it was at last conquered by Aurangzeb. After the death of Aurangzeb in 1 707, there developed the special kind of states-system in India that arises with the slow dissolution of a great empire. Westlake compared it to the condition of the Holy Roman Empire from I 648 to I 8o6. 11 Legitimacy was conferred primarily by a grant or firman from the Moghul Emperor, not by a treaty between independent sovereigns, though the country powers asserted a practical independence that increasing! y dis regarded the nominal ruler of Hindustan. All the European East India companies had begun their activities with Moghul grants authorizing them to trade. Sir Thomas Roe obtained the first for the English East India Company during his embassy of I 6 1 5-I 9, though he failed to conclude a treaty with Jehangir, since the Padi shah did not consider England a state with which he might treat on terms of equality. At last in 1 7 65 Clive secured from ·the Moghul Shah Alam the grant of the diwani, or civil and financial adminis tration, of Bengal, Bihar and Orissa, which have a show of legality to the irregular powers of government that the Company had as sumed. In return the Company paid a nominal tribute annually. By the treaty of Sarje Arjengaon which ended the Second Mahratta War in I So 3, the Company acquired control of Delhi, and the Moghul Emperor became its pensioner. Henceforward the Company used the imperial authority no more as basis for its actions. When Hastings formally declared the Company's paramountcy over India at the end of the Third Mahratta War in I 8 I 9, and conferred the title of king on the Nawab Wazir of Oudh, we may say that the interregna! states-system between Moghul Raj and British Raj had effective! y ceased to exist. India had a rudimentary states-system distinct from the European. North America, by contrast, was an annex of the European system, in which the status of the Indian tribes was wrapped in an ambi guity convenient to the European powers. Nevertheless, the Indians had the distinction of having their interests nominally safeguarded
Triangles and duels
1 97
in the Angl«rFrench Treaty of Whitehall of x 686, and again, 'vel subditi vel amici ', in the Treaty of Utrecht (art. I 5). The second .question is whether the country powers in India, or the tribes in North America, are not better regarded as Third Forces, or even Third Worlds, than as parties to a triangle. Neither group was united, and their military inferiority was such that they could not, after the very earliest years, have won, in the sense of expelling the European powers from their continents. But each group had greater military strength and played a more active role than any Third World; and being the parties in original possession, neither group had the posture of mediatory self�interposition in a duel of giants that marks a Third Force. The successor states of Hindustan were irremediably self-seeking and incapable of joint action ; none the less, Bengal under Alivardi Khan, M ysore under Haider Ali, or the Mahratta Confederacy were considerable powers. ' To Clive and his fellows ', as Williamson has said, ' the future was a sealed book . In their own eyes they were the weaker side, and the native powers of incalculable strength and wealth ' .12 Some of the primitive tribes of North America were able paradoxically to attain a greater cohesion and stability than the states of India. The Ir«r quois Confederation of the Five Qater six) Nations held the balance of power between English and French through the seventeenth century. There were great contrasts between Hindustan and North Amer� ica as states-systems or sub-systems. Hindustan was virtually closed, North America open. The geographical and cultural limits of the Indian system were fixed, except on the north-west where it inter fused with the Mghan empire; moreover, it was a system distinct from and subordinate to the European states�system. In North America, a moving frontier opened on an illimitable continent, moreover, North America itself formed one side of the states� system's great western quadrilateral of trade and sea power, whose other sides were Europe, Africa and the West Indies. Hindustan was ancient, politically articulated, and immense! y populous. North America was savage, and so thinly populated that it was called empty. Hindustan was impossible for European settlement, and was conquered by native troops in European service under European discipline - sepoys - a French invention. North America was pr«r pitious for European settlement, and as the colonists multiplied they
Sy.stems of States
took over their own fighting. For such reasons as these, the tri angular conRict in North America began a hundred years earlier than that in India, and was not finished until a hundred years later. In Hindustan, mutual rivalry drew the French and English into the political struggles and disputed successions of the country powers. Dupleix was the first to intervene on a large scale, and Bussy, his deputy in the Deccan, was the first of Europeans to acquire extensive territorial dominions, by grant from the French candidate for the nizamship of Hyderabad. But the British had command of the sea, and with their three bases at Bombay, Madras and Calcutta possessed a better strategic position than the French with their one base at Pondicherry. Once the British had conquered Bengal, French power with its nucleus in the Carnatic was to British power as the kingdom of Vijayanagar had formerly been to the Moghul Empire. Though the British had arrived from overseas and not overland, their rule, like that of all the previous imperial powers in Indian history, was based on the limidess wealth of the Ganges valley. When Clive and Coote had decisive( y defeated the French in the Seven Years War, the East India Company was led on to subjugate the country powers by a momentum similar to that which drove Rome to conquer the Hellenistic states, prompted by the fear that the country powers were still instigated and aided by the French. In North America, as in India, the French had the role of pro tagonist. As early as 1609, in his exploration of the St Lawrence, Champlain had made an alliance with the Hurons, and thereby become drawn into their traditional war with the Iroquois. The Dutch in the Hudson Valley allied with the Iroquois in 16 I 8, supplying arms for the Indians' furs. The English inherited the Iroquois alliance, and a treaty that New York made with them in 1 684 conferred a kind of protection upon them. The Iroquois held the watershed between New France in the St Lawrence valley and New York in the Hudson Valley. In King William's War, it was the Iroquois alliance that enabled the English to defeat Frontenac's aim of driving the English out of the Hudson valley and New York itself. The French refused to include the Indians in the Peace of Ryswick ; the English deserted them ; and the Iroquois were compelled to make their own peace with the French in I 701 . By this, they undertook to remain neutral in any future Anglo-French war.
Triangles and duels
1 99
In Queen Anne's War the English colonists acquir� the aim of conquering the French territories in North America, especially the Mississippi valley which was then Louisiana. The Iroquois main tained their neutrality, but French, Spanish and English alike used Indian auxiliaries. From this time Lecky's generalization holds, that the Indians were usually on the side of the French against the English, and afterwards of the British government against the Americans.a The enlightenment of French Indiana policy con trasted with 'the constant and atrocious outrages, the Indians endured from the Americans ; the centralized policy of New France con trast� with the particularism and independence of the English colonies ; but more decisive than either was the intensity and scale of English settlement. ' French colonization was dominated by its trading frontier; English colonization by its farming frontier'. In this sentence F. J. Turner explains not only why the English destroyed the Indians but also why they defeated the French. ' (The Frenchman] swore brotherhood with its savages, traded with them, intermarried with them, and explored the Middle West; but he left the wilderness much as he found it '.u The Seven Years War was ' the French and Indian War ' to the Americans, because the French were more successful in enlisting Indian allies. In 1 757 Montcalm's Indians massacred the garrison of Fort William Henry after they had surrendered their arms with a pledge of safe-conduct. Remembrance of this and similar atrocities hardened the demand four years later for the expulsion of the French from the continent. The cession of Canada, and the suppres sion of the great Indian rising of 1 763-4 under Pontiac by colonist volunteers rather than the forces of the Crown, produced the ironical change that made Great Britain instead of France the enemy of the Americans. In the Revolutionary War Britain hdd Canada and invaded the Hudson Valley with Indian allies, like Frontenac eighty years before. But the Indians by now had no military value except as scouts, and the employment of those whom Chatham denounced as ' these horrible hell-hounds of savage war' gave a propaganda advantage to the other side. After the war, Britain tried, despite the treaty, to maintain the Old Northwest (later the states of Ohio, Indiana, Illinois, Michigan, Wisconsin) as an Indian buffer region between the United States and Canada. In the diplomatic negotiations that followed the War
200
Systems of States
of 1 8 1 2 she was compelled to abandon this aim. The United States, lineal successor of the original deuteragonist in the triangle, was left to exterminate the Red Indians in the series of Indian Wars that accompanied the western movement of the frontier, and ended with the Sioux War of 1 890.
Martin Wight: Publications
I . ARTICLES
'Christian Pacifism ', Theology, XXXIII no. 1 63 (July 1936). 'The Tanaka Memorial ', History, xxvni no. 1 07 (March I 943)· 'The Church, Russia and the West ', Ecumenical Review, I no. 1 (Autumn I 948). ' History and Judgement : Butterfield, Niebuhr and the Technical Historian', Frontier, 1 no. 8 (August 1 950). 'What Makes a Good Historian ? ', Listmer, 1 7 February 1953. ' War and International Politics ', Listener, I3 October 1 953. ' The Power Struggle within the United Nations ', Proceedings of the Institute of World Affairs, 33rd session, I956. ' Why is There no International Theory ? ', Int""ational Relations, u no. I (April I96o). ' Brutus in Foreign Policy : the Memoirs of Sir Anthony Eden ', International Affairs, xxxvi no. 3 (July 1 960). ' The Place of Classics in a New University ', Didaskalos, I (I 963). ' International Legitimacy ', International Relations (May 1972). 2. CHAPTERS IN BOOKS
'Why is There No International Theory ? ', 'Western Values in International Relations ', and 'The Balance of Power ', in Herbert Butterfield and Martin Wight (eds.), Diplomatic Investigations (George Allen & Unwin, 1 9 66). ' European Studies', in David Daiches (ed.), Th e Idea of a New University. An Experiment in Sussex (Andre Deutsch, I964). ' Spain and Portugal ', ' Switzerland, the Low Countries and Scandinavia ', ' Eastern Europe ', ' Germany ', and 'The Balance of Power ', in Arnold Toynbee (ed.), Th e World in March 1939 (Oxford University Press, I 952). ' The Balance of Power and International Order', in A. M. James
"202
Systems of States
(ed.), The Bases of International Order. Essays in Honour of C. A . W. Manning (Oxford University Press, 1973). 3. B<X>KS
The Development of the Legislative Council i6o6-1945 (Faber & Faber, 1946). British Colonial Constitutions 1947 (Oxford at the Clarendon Press, 1 95 2). The Gold Coast Legislative Council (Faber & Faber, 1 94 7). Power Politics (Royal Institute of International Affairs, 1 946). (With W. Arthur Lewis, Michael Scott and Colin Legum), Attitude to Africa (Penguin Books, 1 95 1). (With Herbert Butterfield), eds., Diplomatic Investigations (George Allen & Unwin, 1 966).
Notes
Note Places of publication are given only for works published outside the United Kingdom.
INTRODUCTION 1. 2.
3· + 5·
6.. 7·
8. 9· 10.
I I. 12. 13.
14. 1 5. 16..
I7· I8. I9·
20.
2I.
See Herbert Butterfield and Martin
Wight (eds.), Diplomatic
I"vestigations (I¢6), I2. See especially Martin Wight's note 'The Crux for an Historian Brought up on the Christian Tradition ', in Arnold Toynbee, A Study of History, vol. VII ( I954), 737-48. Letter to the editor from a former pupil of Martin Wight's, now a historian. See 'Christian Pacificism', Theology, U%1.11 no. I93 (July I936). I have discussed this at length in ' Martin Wight and the Theory of International Relations. The Second Martin Wight Memorial Lecture'" British Journal of International Studies, 11 (I976), IOI-I6. See Martin Wight, ' European Studies'• in David Daiches (ed.), The Idea of a New University (I¢4), I04. See Power Politics (Looking Forward Pamphlet No. 8, Royal Institute of International Affairs, I946), especially pp. Io-I I and 6I-6. See ' Why Is There No International Theory ? ', in Butterfidd and Wight (eds.), op. cit., 26. The article was first published in International Rellltions, 11 no. I (April I9l)o). See 'The Church, Russia and the West', Ecumenical Review, I no. I (Autumn I948). See Power Politics; 46 and 48. See 'Germany ' in Arnold Toynbee (ed.), The World in March 1939 (I952), 323. Power Politics, 66. See ' Why Is There No International Theory ? ', supra, 33-4· See letter to The Times, I4 June I97I · See ' History and Judgment. Butterfidd, Niebuhr and the Technical Historian ', Frontier, I no. 8 (August I95o), 303· 'Christian Commentary•. talk on the BBC Home Service, 29 October I948. See 'The Church, Russia and the West', supra, 35-6. The phrase is from his unpublished I95I Cambridge sermon, 'God in History•. See ' War and International Politics ', Listener, I3 October I953· Letter to J. H. Oldham, 27 September I946. See 'Christian Commentary ', supra.
204
Systems of States
22. See ' God in History ', supra. 23. Ibid. 24· Letter to Mathew Melk.o, 1 November 1971. 25. See especially Morton A. Kaplan, System and Process in International Polities (Chicago, 1957). 26. See Chapter I, p. 34· 27. See Chapter 3, p. 105.
CHAPTER I . DE SYSTEMATIBUS CIVITATUM 1.
For the development of Pufendorf's thought see Leonard Kreiger, The
Politics of Direction : Pufendorf and the Acceptance of Natural Law (Chicago, 1¢5), 153....&). 2. Von Gierke, Natural Law and the Theory of Society: I 5DO-I8oo, trans. and introd. by E. Barker (1934), vol. II, 1�7, vol. II, 395-6. 3 · The Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, with introduction and notes by C. E. Vaughan (1962), vol. I, 366. 4 The reference is to a paper by Adam Watson on ' The Indian States System'. 5 · A. H. L. Heeren, A Manual of the History of the Political Sysum of Europe and its Colonies, trans. D. A. Talboys (1846). 6. The reference is to a paper by Geoffrey Hudson on •The Traditional Chinese Conception of International Relations '. 7· The Collected Papers of John Westlake on Public International Law, ed. L. Oppenheim (1914), 24-5 · 8. 0. R. Gurney, The Hittites (Penguin, rev. edn, 1962), 64. 9· D. G. Hogarth, ' The Hittites of Asia Minor', in Cambridge Ancient History ( 1924), vol. II, 266. 10. The reference is to a papc:r by Desmond Williams on 'The International States System in the Middle Ages'. W. Ullman, The Growth of Papal Got1ern ment in the Middk Ages n. (1955), 292. 12. Ibid., 450. 1 3· The reference here is to a talk by Adam Watson. 14. See Chapter 2, below. 15. Herodotus, History of the Persian Wars, viii, 1 46-7. 1 6. E. M. Satow, A Guide to Diplomatic Practice (2nd edn, 1922), vol. n, 52. 17. Edmund Burke, Thoughts on French Affairs. 1 8. Ibid. 19. Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, iii, 82. I. 20. Ibid., viii, 64-5. 21. Diodorus Siculus, Library of History, xiii.7; c£. Plutarch, Lysander, v.3. 22. Xenophon, Hellenica, i.vi.4. 23. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xrv. 13; Plutarch, op. cit., xiii.2-3. 24· J. de Romilly, Thucydides and AtheniAn Imperialism, trans. ·P. Thody (1963)· 25. A. Waley, Three Ways of Thought in Ancient China (1946), 195 ; • Even though the Confucian, Mohist and Taoist philosophers -were solidly
Notes
26.
27. 28. 29·
30. 31 .
ranged against recourse to belligerency, all made allowance for one type of warfare - the punitive action that Heaven might comman d to redress a great wrong. Even Mencius, the most extreme pacifist, believed that a "bad" nation or a state "badly " ruled had to be chastised. ' A. B. Bozeman, Politics and Culture in lntertlational History (Princeton, 196o), 140. W. E. Soothill, The Three Religions of China (1913), 2. His three religions arc Confucianism, Buddhism, and Taoism; Waley's 'three ways of thought' are Taoism, Confucianism and the School of Law. Elbert D. Thomas, Chinese Political Thought (New York, 1968), 12. J. Needham, Science and Civilisation in China (1954), vol. I, 94· St Augustine, De Civitate Dei, rv.15. Cf. op. t:it., iii. IO. Contrast libido dominandi, ili.14, v.12, Op. t:it., iv.15, cf. 3· CHAPTER
1. 2. 3· 4· 5· 6.
7· 8. 9· 10.
n.
12. 13. 14. 15.
205
2.
THE STATESSYSTEM OF HELLAS
Herodotus, History of the Persian Wal's, vili.144. Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesum War, v.49· Xcnophon, Hellenica, viL1.28--35· Thucydides, op. t:it., v.18. Ibid., ili.�14. Lysias, xxxiii, Olym/'ic Oration ; Diodorus Siculus, Library of History, XiV.109. Thucydidcs, op. t:it., i.28.2. J. B. Bury, Histr»y of Greece (yd edn, 1951), 161. Thucydides, op. t:it., i.121.3; 143•1. Acschines, ill. (Against Ctesiphon) 130. Herodotus, op. t:it., i.54. Plutarch, Pmdes, 21. Dcmosthencs, De falsa legatione, 327; Third Philippic, 32. Acschines, op. cit., 107-12. Aeschines, ii. (On The Embassy) 115. Cf. V. Ehrenberg, The Greek State (x¢o),
no.
x6. Pausanias, Desmption of Gl'eece, X-37·7· 17. Plato, Republic, 46cJ-71. 18. Thucydidcs, op. t:it., i.78.4; 140.2; 144.2; 145; vii.18.2. 19. Ibid., iv.u8.7; v.18.4. 20. Ibid., V.59·4· 21. E. A. Freeman, History of Federal Govern ment in Greece and Italy (•893), 98. 22. Plutarch, Themistocles, 20. 23. Diodorus Siculus, op. t:it., xiv.6o. 24· Thucydides, op. t:it., iii.70. 25. Herodotus, op. t:it., vi.57. 26. Thucydides, op. t:it., v.43; vi.89. 27. Plato, lAws, 642 B. 28. Xenophon, Symposium.
206 .29· 30. 31. 32· 33· 3+
35· 36. 37· 38. 39· 40. 41. -42-
43-
44-
45· 46. 47· 48. 49· 50. 51. 52. 53· 54· 55· 56.
57· s8. 59· 6o. 61. 62. 63. 64. 6s · 66.
6-J. 68.
6c).
Systems of States
Ehrenberg, op. cit., IO+ Thucydides, op. cit., ili.7o. Ehrenberg, op. cit., 104. Herodotus, op. cit., i.6c); Xenophon, H�llenka, ili.1.3. Plutarch, Grul{ Questions, 5· Herodotus, op. cit., v.91-3. Ibid., vii 132. Ibid., vii.145, 1 72. N. G. L. Hammond, Hutory of Gn�c� (1959), 2.24--5. Pausanias, op. cit., iii:rii.6-8. Herodotus, op. cit., �ii.132, 145. Ibid., vii.145· Ibid., vili.2-3. Ibid., vii. 172; Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xi.3. HerodotuS, op. at., �ii.157· Ibid., viii.142. Ibid., vii. l 32, 139· 5, 145· 148.1. Ibid., VU.I39. Ibid., vii. 173; Plutarch, Aristid�s, 24· Plutarch, Aristitles, 21. Herodotus, op. cit., viix32; ix.86-8; Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xi.3; Plutarch, Themistocl�s, 2.0. Plutarch, Themistodes, 2.0; Herodotus, op. cit., i%.81 ; Thucydides, op. cit., i. I 32· Ion, in Plutarch, IGmon, 16. Thucydides, op. cit., i.rox. Ibid., LI02. Plutarch, Pericles, 17, probably based on the original decree. H. T. Wade-Gery, Essays in Greek History (1958), 255· It is characteristic of the materials for the diplomatic history of Hellas that the three literary accounts of the league find its only interesting fc:ature to be that Sparta refused to join because Dessenia was admitted (Polybius, Histories, iv.33·8-9; Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xv.89; Plutarch, Agesilaus, 35), and that the most instructive source is an inscription on a marble stel�, found built into a well in a garden at Argos, and since lost (M. N. Tod, Gr��k Historiea/ Inst:riptions (1948), No. 145). Herodotus, op. cit., vii.I45· Ibid., vii.I6o. Ibid., r65-6; Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xi.I. Thucydides, op. cit, ii7;ili.86. Ibid., Vi.34· Ibid., iv.6.t. Ibid., vi.13. Ibid., vii.28.3 c£. Athenagoras, vi.37.2. Nicias in Thucydides, op. cit., vi.2o; vii.55; viii.96. Ibid., viii.26. Ibid., vili.28, 84--5, 104-6; Xenophon, Hell�nica, i. r.26-31 ; 2.8-14Xenophon, H�ll�nica, ili.1.2. Ibid., vi.2.33; vii.1.20-8, 4.12.
Notes 70. 71 .
p.. 73· 7+
Arrian,
Anabasis of Ale%antler, vii. I5·4• 19. 1 ; W. W. Tarn, Ale%ander the Great (1948), vol. II, 374--98· Herodotus, op. cit., vii.I39· Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xi.81 .3. Thucydides, op. cit., i.36. Ibid., vili.46; cf. 57; also the Athenian calculation about Corcyra and
Corinth, i·44· 75· Polybius, op. cit., i.83. 76. Thucydides, op. cit., ii.8. 77· A. W. Gomme, Historical Commentary on Thucyditles (1956), vol. 11, 9-10. 78. Thucydides, op. cit., vili.2. 79· Ibid., ii.6.t. So. Ibid., Athenians to Melians, v. 1o9; Alcibiades to Spartans, vi.92; J. de Romilly, Thucydides and Athenian Imperialism, trans. P. Thody ( x 963), 3•4 · 8x. Thucydides, op. cit., iv.87; viii. 2.4. 82. Ibid., iii.47· 83. Ibid., ili.82. 8+ Edmund Burke, Thought on French Affairs. 85· de Romilly, op. cit., 84. 86. Thucydides, op. cit., iv.86. 87. Ibid., vU-55· 88. Xenophon, Hellenica, v.iv. I. 89. J. de Romilly, ' ·Eunoia in kocrates, or The Political Importance of Creating Good Will ', Journal of Helknic Studies, 78 ( 1958), 92 ff. 90· T. T. B. Ryder, Koine Eirene: General Peace and Local Independence in 91. 92. 93·
9+
Ancient Greece (x¢5). Aristode, Nicomachean Ethics, IX.v. Thucydides, op. cit., ili. u. 15ocrates, On the Peace, j'S. Kant, Perpetual Peace, appendix ii.
CHAPTER 3. HELLAS AND PERSIA 1.
2. 3·
4· 5· 6. 7· 8. 9·
Xenophon, Cyropaedia, x.i.4-5· It was a three months• journey from the Ionian coast up to the imperial capital at Susa (Herodotus, History of the Persian Wars, v.5o-4). Darius extended the Empire to the Indus, which was for the Greeks the eastern limit of the world (ibid., iv.44; iii.98.1o6). Herodotus, op. cit., i.I53· Ibid., i.6, 26-7. Pindar, Pythian, i.94. Herodotus, op. cit., i.69-7o. Ibid., i.�, 141. Ibid., i. I53· Ibid., i. I70· Gibbon, Decline and Fall of the Roman Bmf'ire, in ' General
208
10.
n.
12. 13. I4· r s. 16. 17. 1 8. 19.
20.
21. 22. 23.
24· 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33· 34· 35· 36.
Systems of SUites observations' following chap. xxxviii. Herodotus says that Thales's proposal was made before the Persian conquest, but Bias's afur it, when the Ionians continued the practice of meeting at the Panionium. But it is difficult to see the value of the proposal after the possibility of adopting it had presumably been lost. Bias's political astuteness had already been shown in the way in which he diverted Croesus from a naval expedition against the Ionian insular states (i.27). G. Barraclough, History in a changing world (1955), 214 Herodotus, op. cit., i.r69. Ibid., iV. I37· Ibid., ii.39, 122. Ibid., ii.IJ6-8. Ibid., ii. I39ff. Ibid., iv.87-9, 97· Ibid., iv.I37· Ibid., iv. r44; v.2, r8. A. T. Olmstead, History of the Persian Empire (Chicago, 1948), 150, 157-8. There is an elaborate discussion in Toynbee, Study of History {1935-9), vol. VII, 679 n. I. See also A. R. Burn, Persia and the Greeks {r¢2), 12o-7. Herodotus, at the end of his list of sattapies or taxation districts of the Empire, says: • As time went on, Darius exacted revenue also from the Islands and from the inhabitants of Europe as far as Thessaly ' (op. cit., iii.¢). Herodotus, op. cit., v.73, as interpreted by E. M. Walker in Cambridge Ancient History, vol. IV, 1 58, and by Burn, op. cit., 187-8. Herodotus, op. cit., vi.43. Ibid., V.I05. Ibid., vi.44; vii. 1o8. That Persian interests at this time might still embrace the western Mediterranean is suggested by two slight pieces of evidence. Darius assented to a proposal to subjugate Sardinia, • the greatest of islands' (Herodotus, op. cit., v. 106}; and the Greek leader of the Revolt, when its failure became inevitable, thought of migrating to Sardinia with his fellow-rebels (ibid., v. r 24), as Bias of Priene had done before. Ibid., VLJ9· Ibid., vii.I33· Ibid., vii.94-5. Ibid. , vili.34t 126, 136. See S. Casson, Macedonia, T"race and IUyria (Westport, Conn., 1971), rj'9-8o. Ibid., vii.32, 131-3; Diodorus Siculus, Library of History, xi.3. Herodotus, op. cit., viii. 73· Ibid., vii.r4B-s2. Ibid., vii.r68-9. Ibid., vii.163. Demosthenes, Third Philippic, 36. Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, iii.56. Herodotus, op. cit., vii. 139. J. B. Bury, History of Greece to tile deat" of Alexander tile Great (3rd edn, 1951), 226.
37. 38. .39· 40. 41. 42· 43· 44· 45· 46. 47· 48. 49· 50. 51. 52. 53·
54· 55· 56.
57· 58. 59•
6o.
61. 62.
63 . 64.
Pausanias, D�st:ription of Gr��c�, vii.x. Olmst�ad, op. cit., 156. Herodotus, op. cit., viii.35-9· Burn, op. cit., 426. Olmstead, op. cit., 41-2. Burn, Qp. cit., 347· Herodotus, op. cit., v.73. Ibid., V.I05. W. W. How and J. Wells, Comm�ntary on HN"odotus (1949--50), vol. II, 61, ad loc. H�rodotus, op. cit. , v.65; amplified in Thucydides, op. cit., vi.59. E. M. Walker, 'Athens ; the r�form of Cleisthenes ', in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. IV, 158. Herodotus, op. cit., v.96. M. Cary, 'Th� r�ign of Darius ', section viii, in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. IV, 215. Herodotus, op. cit., vi. 107, 1 15, 121-4. Plutarch, Aristid�s, 8. . Thucydides, op. cit., i. 95, 12�30. 'The title .. king of kings ", which, so far as is known, was first used as a standing title by the supreme monarchs of the Persian Empire, expresses less the relation of the Great King to [his] petty vassal monarchs than the uniqueness of his kingship : to the Greeks he was Basil�us, the one and only real king in the world. ' G. B. Gray, 'The reign of Darius ', section ii� in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. IV, 185. !socrates, To Philip, 132; cf. Pan�gyricw, 121. D. G. Hogarth, Philip and Al�xand�r of Mac�don (Freepon, N.Y., 1971), 217; cf. 207-10. Arrian, History of Akxander, ili.18; Plutarch, Alexander, xxxviii; Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xvii.72. Tarn interprets it as ' a sign to Asia that E-sagila, the great temple at Babylon which Xerxes had destroyed, was aven�d and Achaemenid rule ended' : Alerand�r the Great ( 1948), vol. I, 54, and 'Alexander: the conquest of Persia ', in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. VI, 383. W. W. Tarn, Alexander the Great, vol. I, 59· Dio, History of Rom�, liii. 16 ; J. B. Bury, 'Th� Constitution of the Later Roman Empire ', in Sel�ct�d Essays, ed. H. W. V. Temperley (1930), 108-9. Herodotus, op. cit., ii 1 58 ad fin. Euripides, lphig�neia at Aulis, 14oo-1 . Isocrates, Pan�gyricw, 173. Ibid., 182. Th�oria is the word for sending a c�remonial embassy to consult an oracle or to perform some religious rit� at the games. The phras� 'sacred war ', hieros polemos, was reserved for a war to punish sacril�ge, proclaimed by th� Amphictyony (e.g. Thucydides, op. cit., i.1 12). Eratosth�nes, in Plutarch, D� Alexandri fortuna, 329 B. The �vid�nc� is open to different intepretations and is the subject of controversy. Contrasy for exampl�, W. W. Tam, 'Alcxander. t:Jte Great .
210
Systems of States and the unity of Mankind in Proceedings of the Btitish Academy, vol. XIX, 148 n.6, and Alexander the Great, vol. II, 401 (wanting to reserve all the credit for Alexander himself), with E. A. Havelock, The liberal temper in Greek politics (1957), chap. x, and J. B. Skemp, P/atQ's Statesman (1952), 131, note. Herodotus, op. cit., vili. 121 ; Demosthenes, Pltilip's Letter, 21. Herodotus, op. cit., v.22. Ibid., viii137-9; ix.44; Thucydides, op. cit., ii.99. Isocrates, Panegyticus, 50. Ibid., Evagoras, 66-7. M. N. Tod, Greek historical inscriptions ( 1948), No. 123, lines 16, IQ9-IO; cf. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xv.38, and Casson, op. cit., 206. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xvi.6o. Eratosthenes, in Strabo, Geography, i-4·9· Eratosthenes, in Plutarch, De Alexandti fortuna, 329 C-D, following the selective translation by Tarn in Alexander the Great, vol. II, 43�40. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xii.4.4; Plutarch, 1Umon, xili. H. T. Wade-Gery, 'The peace of Kallias', in Essays in Greek Histqry (1958), 201-_32. Olmstead, op. cit., 31o-1 1. Herodotus, op. cit., vi.-42. Wade-Gery, op. cit., 216. Andocides, On the peace with Sparlll, 29Thucydides, op. cit., vili.43· Ibid., viii.s8. Xenophon, Hellenica, ii.2 .23. Xenophon, Agesilaus, vili.6. 4 1 shall try to give you briefly my views about the King', said Demosthencs in his earliest speech to the Athenian assembly in 354· 'I admit that he is the common enemy of all the Hellenes; but I would not on that account advise you to undertake a war against him singlehanded. I observe that the Hellenes themselves are by no means common mends of one another, but that some of them place more confidence in the King than in their neighbours. . .If we precipitate a war while the King's policy is still obscure, I am afraid we shall be obliged to fight, not only him, but those whom we intend to protect. For he will suspend his designs (supposing he really plans aggression against Greece), and will distribute money among them, and offers of &iendship; and they, intent only upon pursuing and settling their parochial quarrels, will overlook the common safety of all .' (On the Navy-boards, 3·) Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xv.23. Xenophon, Agesilaus, i.B; cf.. vii.7. Xenophon, Hellenica, iii.5-1 ; Hellenica Ozyrhynchia (1909), ii.s; Polyaenus, Stratege11UJtum libti octo, i.48. Plutarch, Artaxerxes, :xx ; d. his Agesilaus, xv. Xenophon, Hellenica, iv.8.24; Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xiv.98 ; M. Cary, 'The ascendancy of Sparta ', in Cambridge Ancient History, vol. VI, 53· Xenophon, Hellen;ca, iv.8, 12-15; Andocides, op. eit. •,
65. 66.
&]. 68.
69. 70. 71. 72. 73 · 74· 75·
7fl. 77· 78. 79·
So. 81. 82. 83. 84.
85. 86.
87. 88. 89. 90·
NOles 9 1. 92. 93· 94· 95· ¢. 97· 98· 99·
100. IOI. 102. 103. IO+ 105. xo6. 107. 108.
109. I 10. 1 1 1. 1 12. 113. 1 14· 1 15. I 16. 117. n8. 1 19. 120. 121. 122. 123. 1 24 . 125. 126.
127. 128.
211
Xenophon, H�ll�nica, v.I, �I . T. T. B. Ryder, Koin� Eir�n�, 39-40 and appendix i. Ibid., I�. Xenophon, R�v�nues, v.2-3. Ryder, op. cit., 40-1. Plutarch, Artar�x�s, :xxii; Ag�silaus, u:ili. Ryder, op. cit., appendices ii and ill. Xenophon, H�ll�nica, vii. I.33ff; Plutarch, P�lopidas, xxx ; W. W. Tarn, 'Persia, from Xerxes to Alexander', in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. VI, 20. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xvi-40, # Ibid., xvi.75. I ; A. W. Pickard-Cambridge, " Macedonian supremacy in Greece', in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. VI, 250, 254. Olmstead, op. cit., 56; G. B. Gray, 'The foundation and extension of the Persian Empire', in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. IV, 14. Herodotus, op. cit., ili. 17, 19; cf. iv. I97· Thucydides, op. cit., vi.2. Ibid., i. I3. Orosius, History against the pagans, iv.6. Herodotus, op. cit., i. r 70. Ibid., i.165�. Politics, 128oa. The passage is obscure: was security or commerce the basis of the alliance ? For conflicting interpretations see E. Barker, Th� politics of Aristotl� (1946), n8; Aristotle, Politics (Loeb edn, 1932), 215; M. Pallotino, The Etruscans (Penguin, 1955), 82; Burn, op. cit., 165. Polybius, Histori�s, ili.22; c£. H. Last, ' Rome and her neighbours in the fifth century ', in Cambridge Anci�nt History, vol. VII, 486, 858--62. Herodotus, op. cit., vii.156. Ibid., vii165. Ibid., vii. 157· Ibid., vii.x66. Ibid., ili. l35--8. Ibid., V. Jo6-7. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xL x ; cf. xi.20, following, but not naming, Ephorus. Contrast R. Hackforth, 'Carthage and Sicily ', in Cambridg� Anci�nt History, vol. IV, 375--8, with Burn, op. cit., 3o6 n.3o. Herodotus, op. cit., vii.x6s. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xi.21. Herodotus, op. cit., vii. 166. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xi. 24 . Ibid., xi.26. Ibid., xii.26. Ibid., xii.82. Thucydides, op. cit., vi. rs. Ibid., vi.18. Plutarch, Nicias, xii; cf. Alci/Md�s, xvii ; cf. Thucydides, op. cit., vi.24. Thucydides, op. cit., vi.90 ; c£. J. de Romilly, Thucydid�s and Ath�nian imperilllism, s:z.
212
I29· I3o. I3I· IJ2. I3J. IJ4. I35· I36. I37· I38. 139· 140. I4I· I.p. I43· I44· I45·
I46. I 47· I48. I49· I SO· ISI· 152. I53· I 54· I55· I56. I57· I58. I59· 16o.
Systems of States Thucydides, op. cit., vi.34· Ibid., vi.88, Io3; vii.53-4· Ibid., Vii.57�· Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xili.43-4 Ibid., xiii.54-62. Ibid., xili.So. Ibid., xili. n4. Ibid., xiii. 1 12. Ibid., xiv.6s. J. B. Bury, 'Dionysius of Syracuse', in Cambridge Ancient History, vol. VI, I 26. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xvii.4o-I, 46; Justine Curtius, Alexander the Great, iv.3.19. Surdy some geographical confusion here ? Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xvili.4; cf. Arrian, Anabasis of Alexander, v.27; vii.I ; Tarn, Alexander the Great, vol. II. J90· Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xvii. n3; Arrian, op. cit., vii. 15. Tarn, Alexander the Great, appendices 23 and 24· Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xili.59· Herodotus, op. cit., iv.I¢. Polybius, op. cit., ili.78, Phoinikikon Stratagema. And here it is used without moral censure, to describe the rather ludicrous dodge of the great Hannibal to avoid assasis nation, by appearing in constandy changing wigs, with changing dress to match. Strabo, Geography, v.2.3. Pausanias, op. cit., vi. I9·7· A. R. Burn, The Lyric Age of Greece (x¢o), I54· Herodotus, op. cit., i. 167. Strabo, op. cit., I7. I. 19. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xili.57�; cf. I I I. Sayings, 175A. Justin, op. cit., :xix.I, attributes the same measure to Darius, as suzeraine of Carthage. Diodorus Siculus, op. cit., xili.86; xx�14. Politics, 1272h-I273b. Laws, 67¢. Op. cit., ili.82. Republic, 4j'O-I. Rhodians, I7.8. U. Wilcken, Alexander the Great (New York, 1¢7), preface and notes by E. N. Borza, 244-5· Tarn, in Alexander the Great, vol. I, 1 39, 140, says his ' Empire was even more complicated than the British. In Egypt Alexander was an autocrat and a god. In Asia he was an autocrat but not a god. In old Greece he was a god, but not an autocrat. In Macedonia he was neither autocrat nor god, but a quasi-constitutional King over against whom his people enjoyed certain customary rights Old Greece was not in his empire, but neither was she entirdy outside it, as many Greeks knew very well' .
•
.
Notes
213
CHAPTER .f. THE ORIGINS OF OUR STATES-SYSTEM : GEOGRAPHICAL LIMITS 1. F. de Callieres, The practice of diplomacy, trans. A. F. Whyte (1919), 42. 2. M!moires, book V, chap. xii. 3· Letters on the study and use of hisuny, no. vi. In the past term, having to teach a course entided ' International history since 1900 ', I found my students, in proportion as they hoped to be of service to their country, or rather the world, asserting a similar dividing line, and fixing it at I945· They almost used Bolingbroke's words : 'To be entirely ignorant about the ages that precede this aera would be shameful. Nay some indulgence may be had to a temperate curiosity in the review of them. But to be learned about them is a ridiculous affectation in any man who means to be useful to the present age. ' 4· Anglica Hutoria, book XXIV (ed. Hay, Camden Society, 1950), 28. 5· Times Literary Supplement, 19 February 1971, 197. 6. Renaissance Diplomacy (1955), 51. 7· 'An early non-aggression pact', Journal of Modern History, x (1938), 28. 8. Robert P. Adams, The better part of valor: More, Erasmus, Colet and Vives on Humanism, War and Peace, 1 496-1535 (Seattle, 1¢2), 211, citing Frederick Duval, De Ia paix de Dieu a Ia paix de fer (Paris, I92J), 98. 9· Guiccardini has 'Ia congregazione di Mantova' for the Mantuan congress of 1512, in Storia d'Italia (Bari, 1929), vol. 3, book XI, chap. 2, 220. 10. Thus it can even happen that several states are bound together by the closest treaty, and make a kind of systema, as Strabo says in more than one place, and nevertheless each of them preserves the condition of a perfect state, De Jure Belli ac Pads, book i, chap. iii, section vii, paragraph 2. Grotius gives the word systema in Greek, citing Strabo on the Amphyctionic ' system ' (Geography, ix.3.7)· Whewell translates 'ut plures civitates arctissimo inter se foedere colligentur' by ' are combined in a close federal connexion '. But the British (and French) attitudes to the E.E.C. seem to give a truer sense of what Grotius has in mind. II. 'Western Europe and the power of Spain', in New Cambridge Modern History (1 ¢8), vol. Ill, 307�. 12.. J. B. Wolf, The emergence of the Great Powers, 1685-1715 (New York, 1951), 47· 13. W. E. Hall, A Treatise on International Law (8th edn, by A. Pearce Higgins, 1924), 4r-S· The first edition of this classic work appeared in 188o. Cf. T. J. Lawrence, The Principles of International Law (various edns), section 44; L. Oppenheim, International Law (1947-52), vol. � paragraphs 26-9. 14. He held his chair &om 1862 till his death in 189o. His own sketch of its history is in his Studies National and International (1890), chap. xvii. He is dismissively contrasted with Hall by T. E. Holland, the Chichde Professor of International Law I 874-1910, in his Studies in International Law (1898), 16;-9. 15. James Lorimer, The Institutes of the Law of Nations (1883), vol. I, 101-3. 16. The power$ at the First Hague Conference were 27 : 20 European powers,
Systems of States
17.
18. 19. 20.
21. 22. 23. 24·
25. 26. 27. 28.
29. 30. 3'· 32. 33· 34· 35· 36. 37· 38. 39· 40. 41· 42. 43·
the United States, Mexico, Turkey, China, Japan, PersUJ, and Siam. The Second Conference added, at Theodore Roosevelt's suggestion, 17 Latin American states (all except Costa Rica and Honduras; it was the first international appearance of Cuba and Panama). Liberia later ceded to the Declarations and Convention of If)07. An Introduction to the History of the lAw of Nations in the East Indies: si%kenth, seventeenth and eighteenth centuries (z¢7). Page 9· Alexandrowicz discusses some of these questions in an article, 'New and Original states : the issue of Reversion to Sovereignty ', in International Affairs, LXV (1¢9), 4f>5-8o. See W. UJ.lmann, Growth of Papal Government in the Middle Ages (1955), 387-93; M. Wilks, The Problem of Sovereignty in the Later MiJdle Ages ( 1 963), 4n-12; R. Folz, The Concept of Empire in Westn'n Europe (1¢9), 1o8--1 4; R. W. and A. J. Carlyle, A History of Medilleval Political Theory in the West (1950), voL III, 170-&; von Gierke, Politietll Theories of the Middle Age, ed. Maitland (1951), notes 53-4 and 56. See Ullmann, op. cit., 430; Mediaeval Papalism (1949), n8; cf. Honore Bonet, The Tree of Battles (1493), pt � chap. ii. Mediaeval Papa/ism, 120. Following H. Vander Linden, Alexander VI and the Demarcation of the Maritime and Colonial Domains of Spain and Portugal, 1493-4 ', American Historical Review, :un (1916), 1-20. Alexandrowicz, An lntroduaion to the History of the lAw of Nations in the East Indies, 236; E. Nys, Les Origines du Droit lntenuJtional (Paris, 1814), 163. Grotius, op. cit., ii.xv. 12. 29 March 1791, Parliamenlllry History, vol. XXIX, 76-7· Studies National and lnt�rnational, ch. xi, especially 142; d. his Institutes of the lAw of Nations (1883), vol. I, Ul9-25. E.g. Malmesbury's �ce negotiations at Lille in 1797, Diaries (1844), vol. III, 36c; ff. Vitoria, ObraJ, De Poteslllte Civili, section :ui, paragraph 4; Suarez, De Legibus, book ii, chap. xix, section 9; Fenelon, Suppllment a l'e%amen de conscience, in Oeuvres (Paris, t82.J), vol. :u:n, 315. Op. cit., bk i, chap. v, section 2.2. Ibid., ii.:xxv.6. Ibid., ii.xvJ�-n . Ibid., ii.xxii.9-10. Ibid., iiviii. 12. Ibid., ii.XX.44·4· Ibid., ii.XV. I2. Ibid., iii.vii.9. 1. Ibid., iii.xii.8.4. Ibid., ii.xxiii 8.3-4 Ibid., i.i. I4I. Ibid., i.i.I6; c£. ii.XV.9·3· Ibid., i.i. t5.2 Ibid., ii.xv.u.2. It does not seem necessary to qualify this iD virtue of a •
Notes
215
glancing reference to Muslim law. When he pronounces that Christians have agreed not to enslave captives taken in their wars among themselves, he goes on : Reverence for the Christian law has accomplished this at least, small as it is. When Socrates formerly urged such an observance upon the Greeks between themselves, he achieved nothing. Moreover, he adds, • the same rule which Christians follow in this matter, the Mahometans also observe among themselves! (Op cit., ii.vii.9.) He does not stop to clear up the apparent inconsistency of Muslim observance deriving from Christian law. There is another reference to Muslim practice in ili.x.3· 44· Ibid., ii.v.25. This is a good example of a general proposition appended by Grotius to a chapter with which it has vinually no connection. For the subsequent and different definition of fedus as a public treaty, see ii.xv. •
•
2-J.
45· Ibid., ii.xii.9. 1.: predicated of individuals but applicable to states. 46. · Ibid., i.iii.7.2. 47· Ibid., ii.xv. 12. Gronovius, in a note, refers this to Frederick III, 1 46r. It is more likely to be Charlemagne. Cf. the account of the translatio imperii In U.1X.1 1 .2-4. CHAPTER 5. THE ORIGINS OF OUR STATES-SYSTEM : CHRONOLOGICAL LIMITS 1. C. N. S. Woolf, Bartol.u of Sassofemzto (1913), 155-ti, 368-9. Cf. von Gierke, Political Theories of the Middk Age, ed. Maitland (1938), n. 338. 2. De Jure &IIi ac Pat:is, ii.xxii. 13.I. Grotius omits Banolus's • probably ' . • Et forte si quis diceret dominum lmperatorem non esse dominum et monarcham totius orbis, esset haereticus ', Bartol us, De Captivis et Postliminia, vi.237, quoted in J. N. Figgis, Divine Right of Kings (2nd edn, 1914), note on p. 356. Cf. Woolf, op. cit., 24--5· 3· M. H. Keen, Trends in Metlitleval Political Thought (ed. Beryl Smalley, t¢5), 120. 4 · J. N. Figgis, Studies of Politiml Thought from Gerson to Grotius (2nd edn, 1923), 15. 5· Ludwig Pastor, History of the Popes from the Close of the Middle Ages, ed. F. I. Antrobus ( 1949), vol. IV, 300. 6. L. Sturzo, Church and State (1939), 154, notes the similarity to the League of Nations. 7· Figgis, From Gerson to Grotius, 31. Figgis gxves reasons for modifying his assertion in the note where he confesses that the decree 'only refers in terms to the Council of Constance', and • it is only by inference that it can be extended into a general assertion of conciliar omnipotence', 201 n. 1. 8. Lettu to Leonardus de Benevolentibus, 5 June 1454, Opera (Basle, 155 1), ep. 127, 656-7. It is translated with some abridgment in M. Creighton, History of the Papacy (1903), vol. Ill, 150. 9· Summa Theologia, prima secundae, qu. 96, art 5· (Sekt'kd Political Writings, ed. d'Entreves, 1959, I37-9·) Maulde la Claviere, La diplomatie au temps de Machiavel (Paris, 1892), vol. I, chap. iv.
216
Systems of Sllltes
10. The famous list of 1504 drawn up by Paris de Grassis of Bologna is given in E. M. Satow, Guid� to Diplomatic Praetic� (2nd edn, 1922, vol. I, 22-3); cf. G. Mattingly, R�naissana Diplomacy (1955), 251-2. n. E. D. Dickinson, Th� Equality of States in Inurnational lAw (Cambridge, Mass., 1920); J. Goebel, TM Equality of Staus (New York, 1923)· 12. C. Wolff, Jus G�ntium (1749), paragraph 16. 13. Vattel, Le Droit d�s G�ns (1 758), Pr�liminaires, paragraph 18. 14. Th� relevant extracts ar� printed in R. W. and A. J. Carlyle's M�diae11al Political Theory in the W�st, vol. VI, 78 n. 2. Cf. Figgis, Dillin� Right of Kings, 362-3. 15 · Bodin, comparing the three legitimate forms of commonwealth, labours to show that monarchy is the best; Montcsquieu does not make the same point as Bartolus; I do not find it again before Rousseau. Bodin, Six Bool(s, book vi, chap. 4; Rousseau, Contrat Social, book iii, chap. 3· For the middle, or aristocratic state, Rousseau uses the word • mediocre'. 16. Memoires de Philippe de Commynes, ed. B. de Mandrot (Paris, 19Cn), book vi, chap. 6 (ed. Ca.lmette, iii.45). In the previous chapter Commines describes how the death of Lorenzo had reduced the status of Florence. 17. E.g. Machiavelli, lsto1U fiorentin�, Guiccardini, Storia d'Italia. 18. Nevenhdess Rohan ends his chapter on England's interests by saying that if she follows her interests as discovered in Elizabeth's time, she will establish • a Third Puissance in Christendom'. Cf. F. Meinecke, Machia11ellism (1957), 161, on the same observation being made by the Discours tles princes �t �slats tl� la Chrestientl of 1623-4. 19. Th� Reason of Stat�, book r, 2. 20. Discorsi politit:i ai print:ipi d'ltalia (c. 169o), ed. P. Garzilli (Naples, 1848), 4· 21. Quoted in E. Nys, us Origin�s du droit international (1894), 170. On the Discours, see Meineck� op. cit., 153-62. The first edition of the Discours is reprinted in the Mercure d'estat ou R��il d� div�s discours d'�stat, published at Geneva in 1 634- from which Nys takes the above quotation. 22. The Great Powers (r833). T. H. von Laue, Leopold Ranl(e: the Formativt Y�ars (Princeton, 1950), 202-3. 23. It was in connection with this League that Ferdinand and Maximilian arranged the marriages of Philip and Margaret of Habsburg to Juana and Juan of Castile (duly performed in October 1496 and April 1497 respectively), and laid the foundations of the Austro-Spanish power. 24· More than 20 years later William recalled the incident, for propaganda purposes against Spain, in his Apology of 1581. 25. A Short Memoryall of the Stau of the Realme, in S. Haynes, Burghley Stak Papers (1 740), 582. 26. Cf. G. Mattingly, R�naissanc� Diplomaey, chap. vii, and Donald E. Queller, The Office of Ambassador in the Mitltlk Ages (Princeton, r¢7), chap. iii. 27. Goebel, op. cit., 43-4. The most diverting was the summit non-meeting between Frederick Barbarossa and Louis vn in I 162, at which Frederick had laid a diplomatic trap for Louis. Louis watchfully avoided the agreed
Notes
217
rendez-vous until Frederick departed. He then came to the meeting, washed his hands in the river to show that he had fulfilled his part of the agreement, and rode away. A good account is Peter Munz, Frederick
Barbarossa ( 1¢9), 232. 28. Op. cit., bk ii, chap. 6 et seq. Three years earlier, after the battle of Mondhery which ended the War of the Public Weal, Louis had, with similar calculation, put himself at the mercy of Charles the Bold in a personal interview (op. t:it., bk i, chap. 12). · 29 Lorenzo later risked his person on another occasion, as Florentine commissioner at the Congress of Cremona, in 1483, during the War of Ferrara. 30. Op. t:it., bk i, chap. 14, Dangers des entrevues princims. 3 1. ' Representatives of the chief states of Europe were present', Creighton, op. t:it., vol. II, 293· This is not borne out by the standard account, J. G. Dickinson, The Congress of A"as, 1435 (1955). There were, however, ambassadors, not only from the French crown, but also from Brittany, Alen�n, Anjou, both the city and the university of Paris, and other towns .:... testimony of the disintegration of France through the war. (Ibid.,
18-19.) _32.
33·
34·
35· 36.
For another hundred years after Arras the chief diplomatists of secular powers of coune continued to be clergy. Cateau-Cambr&is in 1559 was negotiatc=d between the Cardinal of Lorraine for France, and the Bishop of Arras, later Cardinal Granvelle, for Spain. Vervins in 1598 was probably the first irnpon.ant peace to be negotiated between laymen, Villemy, secretary of state, for Henry IV, and Richardot, president of the privy council of the Netherlands, for Spain. The papacy mediated at Lodi and encouraged the Most Holy League of Venice, 1454 But the papacy did not mediate between France and Spain at Noyon in 1516, at the Paix des Dames of Cambrai in 1529, at Crepy in 1 544 (where Henry VIII was mediator), nor at Cateau..Cambrais in 1559. It was ndminal mediator at Vervins in 1598, and for the last time at Miinster (between France and the Empire, but not at Osnabruck, between Sweden and the Empire) in 1 645-8. It played no part in the Franco Spanish Peace of the Pyrenees in 1659, nor in any later European peace settlement. E. Perroy, The Hundred Years War (Bloomington, 1959), 136-4o. The terms first appear as the Treaty of London, 1558; the preliminaries take place at Bretigny, and the final treaty is signed at Calais. Perroy, op. t:it., 242-4. Cf. Satow, op. t:it., vol. n, I-2: ' From the point of view of International Law there is no essential difference between Congresses and Conferences. Both are meetings of plenipotentiaries for the discussion and settlement of international affairs Congresses have usually been invoked for the negotiation of a peace between belligerent Powers and the redistribution of territory which in most cases is one of the conditions of peace. At a Congress, as a rule, more than two Powers have been represented, and for this. reason the inclusion of the Peace of the Pyrenees and the Peace of Amiens seems incorrect. • Mattingly, op. ·tit., R3 and notes. .
37·
•
.
218
Systems of States
38. Creighton, op. cit., vol. DI, 1 43--50. 39· Elliott Binns, DeclitJe t�nd Fall of Ilie Medi«val Papacy ( 1934), 220; Creighton, op. cit., vol m, chap. vi. 40. E. Armstrong, Lorenzo de' Medici (1 8¢}, 191-2; C. M. Ady, Lorenzo dei Medici (1955), 93· 1. J. S. C. Bridge, History of France (1929), vol. IV, 169-70. 4 42· Karl Brandi, Tile EmperM Cllllrles V, trans. C. V. Wedgwood (1963), 93--9. Called a congress by C. A. Macartney in New Cambridge Motl«n History, vol. I, 38o. 43· G. Mattingly, • An Early Non-Aggression Pact', in Journal of Modet11 History, x (1938), 7· 44 · C. van Vollenhoven, Tile Law of Peaee, tl'aD$. W. H. Carter (1936), 82, quoting Henri Pirenne, Historie de Belgique (Brussels, 1927), vol. IV, 240· 45· This handbook was not published until 1919. and thus the experience of
46. 47· 48. 49· 5 0. 5 1. 52. 5 354· 55·
Vienna had no influence on the plans for Paris. See Webster's chapter in H. W. V. Temperley (ed.), History of llle Pet�Ce Conference of Paris (1920), vol. I, chap. vii. President Wilson anyway impatieody rejected such historical aids. • An Early Non-Aggression Pact', 9· See C. J. Friedrich, PllilosopAy of Lllw in HisiMia:d Perspective (Chicago, 1958), chap. vii. M. H. Keen, Tile Laws of War in llle Late Middle Ages (1¢5), 246--7. T. J. Lawrence, Printipks of International lAw (1 895), 16, 22. van Vollenhoven, op. dt., 18-19, 43--5· John of Legnano (fl. 136o) wrote the Tranalw de Bello. Bonet (c. I34o c. 1 405) wrote rArlwe tles Batailles. See Tile Tree of Baltks, trans. G. W. Coopland, introduction, A. and B. 1., for the rdation between the two. Goebel, op. dt., 65 If. These three stages provide the framework of Inis Claude's book, Power and lnteNJational Relations (New York, r¢2), where the whole argument is subjected to an admirably aitical analysis. Clive Parry, Consolidated Treaty Series (New York, r969), vol. I, 1648--9· M. L. B. Bloch observes, • Incapable of creating out of nothing the good policing and sound justice without which no peace was possible, neither the councils nor the leagues ever succ.eeded in paDWlendy reprcssiDg disorder. "The human race", wrote Ralph Glaber, ••was like a dog that returns to its vomit. The promise was made; but it was not fulfilled. " ' Feudal Society, trans. L. A. Manyon (1¢1), 4 17. An epitaph on international attempts at collective security as well. W. T. Waugh in Cambridge Medieual History (1932), vol VII , no.
56. 57· Power and tile Purswl of Peace (r963), 1 53·
CHAPTER 6. INTERNATIONAL LEGITIMACY
1. Perhaps the most familiar sense of the term to historians is the doctrine of legitimacy that Talleyrand invented to justify the decisions of the Congress of Vienna. This is a special case of what is being discussed here.
Notes 2.
3· 4· 5·
6. 7·
8. 9·
to
Villeroy, 23 July 16c>I, Lettr�s de Cardinal Ossat au roi Henry le Grand (Paris, 1624), 259. E. Nys, Les origines du droit intnnational, (1 894), 144. Grotius has a chapter on the laws of hereditary succession, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, book ii, chap. vii. Grotius, op. cit., book ii, chap. iv; Pufendorf, Die officio llominis et civis juxtll legem natuf'alem, chap. u, para. 15 (Carnegie classics of International Law, no. 10, New York, 1927, vol II, 66-7); Vattel, le droit des gens (1758), book ii, chap. xi, paras. 142-3. Emile Bourgeois, Manuel Historique de Politique Etran g�r� (13th edn, Paris, 1945), vol. I, 249· War Memoirs (London, 1933-6), vol. V, 2519, 2520, 2524 (in chap. lxx, appendix ii.) A Hislory of the Peaee Conference of Paris, ed. H. W. V. Temperley (London, 1920), vol. I, 437· P. Mantoux, Paris Peace Conference, 1 9 1 9 : Proceedings of tile Council of Four (Geneva, 1¢4), 49·
Letter
10. Tile Approach to Self-Govern ment (1956), 56. 1 1. Tile End of Our Time (1935), 174. This was published first in 1923. 12. Ian Brownlie, Principles of Public International Ulw (1¢6), 483, 418. On 16 December 1952 the General Assembly recommended that • the States Members of the United Nations shall uphold the principle of self--determination of all peoples and nations '.
13. Op. tit., 143-9. 14. De Jure Belli ac Pacis, book i, chap. vi. In M. G. Forsyth, M. A. Keens-Soper and P. W. M. Savigcar (eds.), Tile Theory of International Relations (1970), 28. 15. De officio llominis et civis, chap. xvi, para. 16. 16. L. Oppenheim, International Law: A treatise, (8th edn), vol. I, 578 n. I. 17. But it is unwise to speak of anything in international history as unprecedented. After Bannockburn, England recognized Scottish independence by the Treaty of Edinburgh (or Northampton) of 1328. In I 333 Edward III renewed English aggression upon Scotland and implicitly tore up the • extorted ' treaty. The two kingdoms remained in a condition of formal war for ncarly two centuries, until the Treaties of London, on Henry VII's initiative, in 1502. 18. OLse concerning rights of passage over Indian Territory (Portugal vs. India), I.C.J. Reports (196o), 6. 19. History of tile Peace Conference of Paris, vol. II, 284.
20.
21. 22. 23. 24·
25. 26.
Ibid., 167, 2&-2. Alan James, Tile Politics of Peace·keeping (1¢9), 23. Manchester Gt���rdian, 7 September 1955· See Stewart Harris in Tile Times, 8 July 1¢9. See Towards a Pax Africana: a Study of Ideology and Ambition (1¢7); On Heroes and Ulluru-Worship: Essays on Independent Africa (1¢7); The Anglo-African Commonwealth : Polititul Friction and Cultural Fusion (1¢7). Towards a Pax Afn'cana, chap. ii, and p. 34· The Indonesian claim to West Irian only appears anomalous when seen
Systems of States
220
27. 28. 29. 30.
3I.
32. 33·
beside the concurrent Indonesian claim to Malaysia on the quite different principle of cultural affinity. See L. F. L. Oppenheim, International Law (8th edn), vol. I, I45, n. 3· Nazi-Soviet Relationships, 1939-4 1 (Washington, State Department, I948), 78, I07· Manchester Guardian, 5 August I954 (quoted in the Survry for I¢1, 443). The union of Egypt and Syria lasted &om 1958 to 1¢I . Egypt's continued use of the name United Arab Republic shows a political nostalgia that has many precedents in the dynastic age, the most familiar being the claim of the English sovereign to the French crown, not abandoned until i8oi. Palestinian Arab nationality was discovered or invented by the Palestine Liberation Organization which was established by the Cairo Summit Conference of the Arab League in January I ¢3· See Alfred Sherman, 'The Palestinians : a Case of Mistaken National Identity ? ' The World Today (March I97I), I04-I4. Regicide Peace, I. (Works, ed. Henry Rogers I842, vol. n, 300). Quoted in Mazrui, Towards a Pax Africana, I3, I2. CHAPTER
7.
TRIANGLES AND DUELS
I. Journal et M�moires du Marquis d'Argenson (ed. Rathery, Paris, I86c)), vol. I, I53-4· D'Argenson is here reflecting upon the Treaty of Vienna of 173I, by which the Maritime Powers guaranteed the Pragmatic Sanction, the Emperor in exchange recognized the succession of Don Carlos of Spain to the Italian duchies of Parma and Tuscany, and France was left isolated. 2. Gerlach calls them ' the Triad ' : Otto von Bismarck, Gedanken und Erinnerungen (Stuttgart, IB98), chap. 5, 11 7; Agatha Ramm, Germany 1789-1 9 19 (I¢7), 236. 3· Suetonius, Julius, chap. 19. Cf. M. Gelzer, Caesar, trans. P. Needham (x¢8), 68. 4· Plutarch, Crassus, chap. I+ 5· Alfred Duggan, in his novel Three's Company (I958), I32, makes Octavian speak thus to Antony at the conference of Bononia: 'You and I alone cannot rule the world. If we did not quarrel of our own accord our followers would egg us on to civil war, and when two men disagree they must fight or call in an arbiter. But in a college of three equal rulers two could outvote the third, and disagreements could be resolved peacefully. We need a third opinion to keep the balance.' He then proposes Lepidus for third ruler. There is no historical basis for this attractively rational account of the inauguration of a triangle. 6. M!moire co·ntre Ia paix d'Aiz-la-Cilapelle, 1748 quoted in E. Zevort, Le Marquis d'Argenson (Paris, I88o), 409· 7· Memoire raisonn� sur la situation presente de I'Allernagne, 28 juin 1756 (PolitiscM Co"espondenz, xii 473). 8. Campanella, Discorsi Politia, 4, 8 and 9· 9· It has to·be confessed that this degant formulation owes more to Mrs
Notes
221
Charlotte Lennox's translation of the Ab� de l'Ecluse des Loge's edition of Sully's memoirs, than it does to the monumental confusion of the original. (Memoirs of the Dul(e of Sully, 1756, vol. III, 334·) ro. To be exact, Mackindc.r had invented the notion of the Heartland, and coined its name, as early as 1904, in his seminal paper ' The Geographical Pivot of History '. See Democratic Ideals and Reality, with additional papers, edited by A. J. Pearce (New York, 1 ¢2), 255· The circumstances of 191�19 provided the strategic definition of the Heanland as " the region to which, under modern conditions, sea power can be refused access ' (ibid., I 10). On its relation to the Russian revolution, see pp. 203-4. CoUected Papers on International Law (1914), 197. u. A Short History of British Expansion (yd edn, 1947), vol. I, 379· 12. 13. W. E. H. Lccky, History of England in the eighteenth century (Cabinet edition, 1902), vol. IV, chap xi, p. 38. I+ The Frontier in Americr�n History (New York, 1948), 13-14, 130.
Index
Abbasid Caliphate, 23, 24, 26, 75 Achaean Confederacy, I 34, I45 Aeneas Sylvius, I34, 145 Aeschylus, 84 Agesilaus, 91, 93, 94 AJbuque�ue, I23, I64 AJcibiades, 83, 89, �100, I94 Alcmaeonidae, 82 Alcuin, I89 Alivardi Khan, I97 Alexander I of Russia, 178 Alexander, IV, Pope, I I9 Alexander the Great, number of pol�s before, 40; role in Greek. history, 43; succeeds Philip, 63 ; position of Italy and Sicily as he establishes world empire, 6s; opposed by Demosthenes, 7I ; position as basileus, 84; Aristotle's advice to, 86; statement of the cosmopolitan ideal, 87-8; succeeds in anti-Persian crusade, 91 ; destruction of Thebes, 94; rdations with Carthage, I02, 105 Alexandrowicz, C. H., thesis about geographical limits of states system,
1 17-28 ambassadors, safe conduct of in Middle Ages, 28; role in Hellenic states system, 30, 55�; resident ambassadors, I41-2 Amery, L. S., 139 Angell, Norman, 133 angelos, see ambassadors Antioch, Frankish principality of, 26 Antiochus the Great, 18G-1 Antony, IB2-3 Apollo, mc:dizing of his oracles, 1»-I Aquinas, application to nvillltes et regna of concept of ' perfect community ', 27; observes that
citizens of one: realm not bound by laws of another, I35; holds that infidels have rightful dominion,
156-7 Aristidc:s, 88 Aristophanc:s, 49 Aristotle, on ' perfect community ', 2I ; on eunoia, 71; on optimum size of the: polis, 74; advice to Alexander, 86-7; on alliance: of Carthaginians and Ettuscans, 96; on idc:al constitutions, I04; his pupil Alexander, 107 Armana age, 25, 34, 43 Arthashastra, 195 Atahualpa, 1 I 5 atomic power, I93 Attila, 81 Augustine:, 44-5 Augustus, 53, 107 Aurungzc:b, I I 5, x¢ Babylonia, 25 balance: of power, in Heeren's definition of states-system, 2I-2; rdationship to states-systems, 42, 44; c:mc:rgencc: of multiple: balance in Greece after battle of Lc:uctra, 62; absence in Greece of idea of balance:, 66-7; balance in Sicily, 96-7; emergence: of simple: balance in fifteenth-century Europe:, I5I Baldwin, 194-5 barbarians, as designation of those: outside: states-systems, 34-5; as seen by Grc:c:ks, 83�; balance of power cuts across distinction between barbarians and Greeks,
95�
barbaros, see barbarians Barbarossa, x89
Systems of States Barraclough, Geoffrey, 76-7 Bartolus, I3o, I36-7 Baruch Plan, I93 hasileus, 83--8 Bejazid, 12I Berdyaev, I62 Bernard, Montague, 22 Bernard, St, 1 I9 Bias of Priene, 76, 96 Bismarck, 1 77, 192 Bolingbroke, 83, I I I , 137 Bonet, Honore, I48 Braudel, 36 British Raj, 23, 24 Brogan, Denis, 56 Brownlie, Ian, I63 Brutus, I82 Bull, Hedley, I3B--9, I47 Burckhardt, 27 Burghley, I37 Burke, Edmund, on effect of doctrinal fractures on the states system, 36; on precedent of Hellas, 37, 38, &]-7o; on trial of Warren Hastings, 1 1 8; on relation of Turkey to European system, I22; on origins of dynasties, 154; on right of vicinage, I7o-I Bury, J. B., 48, 86 Byzantium, as example of suzerain state-system, 23; relations with Western Christendom and Islam, 25-6; attitude to Holy War, 35; claim to be lords of the world, I 19 Caesar, I8J-2, I92 Callieres, Fran�ois de, I IO Cambyses, 95• 97• 99 Campanella, I38, I88 Canning, Stratford, 55 Carter, Charles H., I46 Carthage and the Hellenic states. system, 94-I05 Cartier, Jacques, I24 Cary, M., 82 Chosroes II, 24 Churchill, Winston, as U.S. proxenos in Britain, 55 ; Demosthenes a
Churchill tn4nqul, 7I ; on great powers, I39; as member of triumvirate, I84 Cicero, I92 Cleisthenes, 78, 82 Clemenceau, Georges, I 84 Clement VIII, Pope, I55 Cleopatra, 183 Clive, Robert, I9&-,, I98 Clothilde, of Savoy, 154 Columbus, Christopher, 43 collective security, first manifestation of idea in Hellenic states-system, 62; examples in early modern times, I 49-50 communication, means of within a states-system, 29-33; historical emergence of these means, I4I-7 Concert of Europe, provided organization of a states-system qualitatively different from that of United Nations era, 34 ; did not include American states, 93; apparent in eighteenth century, 15I Concert of ltaly, I33, I 37 Conciliar movement, I I I , I3I-3, I 5 I Confucians, 39 congresses, as moments of maximum communication within the states system, 32-3; developed out of councils of the Church, I43-7; congress of Arras, I47; Cremona, I45; Mantua, I45, I47; Nymwegen, I35; Regensburg, I45; Utrecht, I 29; Venice, I45i Vienna, 136, I 47i Westphalia, 4I, 151, 157 Conradin, 1B9 Consolata del mare, 148 Continental Congress, 16o Corcyrean revolution, 37 Corinthian war, 9 1 Corio, Bernadino, I IO Cortes, Hernan, I 24 Council of Arras, 143-4 Council of Basle, 143 Council of Constance, dismantling of papal universal government by, 28 ; last parade presided over by
Index Emperor, 1 1 2; states-system there at the time of, I29; nearly an international congress, I3 I-3i culmination of series of councils of the Church, I43; marks origin of modern states-system, I 5 I ; considers claims of non-Christian princes to rightful sovereignty, I56-7 Crassus, I8 I-2 Creighton, I I2 Croesus, 75-6, 8o Cromwell, I I2 crusades, Fourth Crusade as central act of drama in relations of Eastern Christendom, Western Christendom and Islam, 25; success of First Crusade in expropriating pagans, 29; relation to Jewish and -Islamic institution of Holy War, 34; Byzantine attitude towards, 35 ; not comparable to Greek Sacred wars, so; stimulus to papal claim to world monarchy, I I9; First Crusade as factor in schism between Byzantium and West, IB9; see Holy Wars cultural basis of states.-system, cultural unity as presupposition of states-systems, 33-4 ; cultural differentiation between stat� systems and external societies, 3435 ; internal cultural differentiation of states-systems, 35-9; conmion culture as basis of Hellenic states system, 46-7 Cynics, 86 Cyrus the Great, Greek sense of magnitude of his empire, 73-4 ; surrender of Ionian islands to, 77; contemptuous attitude to Spartans, 74, 8I ; !socrates on Greek attitude to his descendants, 84; submission of Phoenician city states to his beneficent imperialism, 95; his titles assumed after conquest of Babylon, I97
d'Argenson, I77• I 83-4 Darius, his role in advance of Persian power, 77-9 ; protected shrine of Apollo, 8o; asks • who are the Athenians ? ' J 8I-2 j his role compared to that of Louis XIV in English politics, 82; sends naval expedition to reconnoitre Mediterranean, 97; Athens seeks to fulfil his ambitions against Hellenic states-system, 99; his authority in Hdlas greater than that of Ottoman Sultan in Europe, 106 defence of common interests of the states-system, I49-50 de Freitas, I I 8 Delian Confederacy, 6o Delphic Amphictyony, 5o-3, 57 Delphic Oracle, central geographical position of, 47; role compared with that of papacy, 48; aristocratic sympathies of, 49; manipulability by dominant power, 49; thought in terms of equity rather than law, 52; Lydia's tradition of devotion to, 75; medizing by, 8o-I Demosthenes, says • the Pythia is philippizing', 49; attitude to eunoia, 70, 7I, 72; his use of legend of Greek solidarity against Persia, 79; on conflict of democracies and oligarchies, 106 de Romilly, 38, 70 diarchy of Athens and Sparta, &r2 Diodorus, 66, 98, IOI, I03-4 Diodotus, 69 Dionysus the Great, IOI-2 diplomatic languages, 33 diplomatic system, in Hellas, 53-6; see communications, ambassadors, envoys, proxeny Dupleix, I98 Duval, Frederick, I I3 dynamics of states-systems, 42 dynastic legitimacy, I53-9
Damaratus, king o� Sparta, 83
Egmont, 3I
Systems of States Egy}>tt in Armana, 25 eiune, see peace Elizabeth I, 155, t86 end-game triangles, 1�4, 191, 195 envoys, 55 Ephorus, 97 Eratosthenes, 87-8, 103 eunoia, see international public optnton Euripides, 49, 85, 86 European-Asian conffict, Greco Persian conflict as archetype of, 73-5 Falkinberg, Johannis, 156 Fenelon, 126 Ferdinand ll, 159 Figgis, J. N., 28, 131, 133 false triangles, 1"]6-7 first-round triangles, 191 First World War, 192-3 Ford, Representative Gerald, 82 Francis I, rivalry with Charles V as beginning of modern states system, 1 1 1 ; letten to popes justifying alliance with Turks and crusade against them, 121 ; sent viceroy with Cartier, 12.4; youthful folly of his military expeditions, 139; summit meeting with Henry VIU, 142 Frederick the Great, 183-� 186 Frederick William IV, 192 Freeman, E. A., 53 French Revolutionary Wars, 36, 136 Gerlach, 177 Gentili, 164t 148 Gentz, 21-2 Gibbon, 76 Gierke, 21 Goa, Portuguese seizure of unaccompanied by treaty of cession, 123; Indian seizure erodes prescriptive right, 164-5; Indian rejection of plebiscite, I67 Gomme, 68 great powers, idea of in Hellas, 64-6;
as
internal mark of emergence of states-system, 136-41 ; modifies principle of equality, 42 Greville, Fulke, I 37 Grotius, as exemplar of tradition which accepts the states-system as a valid society of mutual right, 39; no equivalent of him in Hdlas, 52; his relationship to Peace of Westphalia, 1 1 3; his controversy with de Freitas, uS; his advocacy of Christian alliance against external enemies, I 22; dual statewystem in his thought, 125-8; on claim of Emperor to be lord of the world 130; relation of his legalism to earlier forms, 148; provides rational foundation for natural law, I52; inherited view of Council of Constance, 157; on prescription, I59 Guicciardini, no, I37 Guizot, 192 Gurney, 0. R., 25 Grant, Ulysses S., I95 Haider Ali, 197 Hastings, Warren, I96 Hall, W. E., I I5-I6 H�cat, 97' 99' I04 Hammond, N. G. L., 58 Hannibal, IOI, 18o hegemonies in Hellas, 5� heralds, 30 Herodotus, on common culture of Hellas, 46; on Greek resistance to Persia, 58-9; on Gelon, 63; on balance within Hellenic states system, 66; on triumph of Europe over Asia, 73-5; on Cyrus and the Ionians, 76; on Greek reception of Darius's envoys, 78; on neutrality of Pcloponnesian states, 79; on rale of Athens in sustaining Hellenic resistance to Persia, 8o; s�s struggle of Athens and Persia as David and Goliath, 81-2 ; on Egyptian conception of barbarians,
Index 85; on Alexander at the Olympic Games, 86; on Syracuse, 97�; on trustworthiness of Carthaginians, I02-3, I<>5 Heeren, A. J. L., 2I, 22 Hellenic League, 62-3 Henry II, I 41 Henry III, 157 Henry LV, 155 Henry VIII, 1 1 2, 1 39, 142 Henry of Navarre, I 57 heralds, ,30 Hermocrates, �' 65, 100 Mtairai, 37 hierarchy within a states-system, 42-3 Hinsley, F. H., 15o-2 Hippias, 78, 82 Hittites, 25 Hobbes, Thomas, 28, 39 Hogarth, 25 Holy League, I22, I4o, 145 Holy Roman Empire, claims to universal jurisdiction, 27, 29; conflict with papacy, 28; Westphalia settlement effectively ends, 113; Bartolus adapts Roman law to decay of, 130; its abolition, 136; collective security within, 150 Holy Wars, origins in relations of states-system with barbarians, 3435; relation to internal schisms of states-systems, 3&-8; absence of idea in Chinese thought, 39 ; declaration by Delphic Amphictyony, so; see crusades Homer, 47 homogeneity of members of a stat� system, 4o-2 hostages, 31, 32, 34 Hostiensis, I s6 House, Colonel, 185 How, W. W., and Wells, J., 8I-2 Hudson. Geoffrey, 23 Ionian Greek cities, in relation to Persia, 75� Indian states-system, 22, 3I, 195�
Innocent Ill, Pope, 27 Innocent IV, Pope, I I9 international organization in Hellas, 5o-3 international public opinion in Hellas, 67-72 international law, absence in Hellenic States-system, 5o-3; its bearing on states outside European civilization, ns-7; as internal mark of emergence of modern states-system, I47�; in relation to international legitimacy, 153, 158--9 lsocrates, on Panhellc:nic war against Persia, 35; his Panegyricus, 48; on cultivation of eunoia as the aim of foreign policy, 71, 72; on use of term ' basikus , 84; on need for unity against Persia to overcome Greek anarchy, 85-6, 87, 91 Islam, 25-6, 12o-1 '
Jadviga of Poland, 156 Jagiello of Lithuania, I s6 Jaspers, Karl, I O'J Jennings, W. lvor, 161 John of Legnano, 148 Joseph II, I54 Julius II, 140 Just Wars, contrasted with Holy Wars, 34-5; in Chinese thought, 39; in sixteenth- and seventeenth century thought, 1 � K'ang-hsi, the Emperor, 1 I5 Kant, 71, 72 Kennedy, President, 192 Kimon, 54, 59• 6o King's Peace of 387 B.C., 92-3, xo6, 18r-8 Koenigsberger, 114 Konon, 187 Lawrence, T. E., 56 Leibniz, I35, 158 League of Nations, homogeneity of membership of, 41; its members the core states of system after
228
Sys�ms of States
1941, 43 ; function compared to Delphic Oracle, So; part in transition from European to world system, 1 17; compared to Council of Constance, 132-3; its architects' lack of awareness of historical precedents, 149; qualifications for membership of, 162; Saar plebiscite and the reign of law under it, x66; its machinery for supervising minorities' treaties, 1 72; built on expectation that economic sanctions could provide world order, 192-3 League of Venice, 1 40, 147, 149 Leuctra, battle of, 94 Lodovico il Moro, 137 Lorenzo, 131 Lorimer, James, u 6-x7, 122, 125 Louis XI, uo, I I I , 142 Louis XII, 139, 147 Louis XIII, 1 14 Lou� XLV, 1 12, 133, 159, x6o Louis XV, 1 10 Luther, 35, 1 1 2, 121 Lysander, 37, 38 Macartney, C. A., 56 Macedonian Wars, z 8o, 181 Machiavelli, his children see statessystem as state of nature, 39; comparison with Chinese Legalists, 39; writes foreword to story of secularized politics, 1 1 4 ; his relation to the Great Discoveries, 1 1 5; on great powers, 137; differences between his period and that of Grotius, 148 Mackinder, Halford, 193 Mao, Chairman, 184 Marsiglia of Padua, 130 Mattingly, G., 1 12, 1 39, 146, 147 Maurice, the Emperor, 24 Mazrui, Ali, 168 Mazzini, 41 medieval states·system, �isted only in · its external relations, 2�; see Western Christendom medism, So-3, xo6
Melians, 51 Menander, 84 Menon, Krishna, z6s Merlin of Douai, 155 messengers, 29-32 Michailovitz, Tsar Alexis, 1 15 Montezuma, I 1 5, 124 More, Sir Thomas, 36, 121, 122 Most Holy League of Venice, 62, 1 1 1 , 139, 140, 145, 149 mutual recognition of states, 135-6 Murray, Gilbert, 133 Napoleon, 43, 178, 192-3 Napoleon III, 165 Napoleon, Prince Jerome, 154 national self-determination, provided homogeneity in states.system after 1919, 41 ; earliest recognition of it as principle of legitimacy, x6o; history of phrase, 16o-1 ; difficulties in the principle, 161-2; the more it is asserted the less it leads to popular consultation, x6s-8; new version of the principle embodies . rights of majority and of territorial vicinity, 168-72 natural law, possible embodiment of cultural unity of states.systems, 34; revival by Lorimer, 1 16; connection with idea of universality of the family of nations, 1 r8, 125-8 ; bearing on rights of dominion of non.Christian princes, xs6-7; in eighteenth-century doctrines of natural rights, 16o Needham, Joseph, 40 Nehru, 120, 169 Nettelbladt, 21 Nine Years' War, ns, 148, 159, 176 North American states·system, x¢--8 number of members in a states· system, 40 Nys, E., 121, 1 56 Octavian, x82-3 Olmstead, 91-2 Olympic Games, 47-8, 6-], 86
229
lnd�x open and closed states--systems, I 75 Orwell, George, 44, I74-6 Ossat, I 55 Ottoman Empire, extension of Western diplomatic system to include, 67; threat to West illustrates theme of external conflict of Europe and Asia, comparison of its relation to Western states-system to that of Persia to Hellenic, Io6; relation to Western states..system, 1 1 I, 1 1 2, 1 1 5, n6, 1 1 7, 12�2; as membu of political triangle with France and Habsburgs, 188-..9 ; ue Islam
management, I4�I ; only nominally trilateral, I45; confirmed by Treaty of Vervins, 147; provided diplomatic formula for states system with European core and non-European penumbra, I 5 I-2 Peace of Kallias, 59, 88--9, 90, 94 Peace of Lodi, 62, I I I , 1 1 3, IJJ, 1 4 I , I45· I47
Peace of Nicias, 4 7, 52 Peace of Vervins, I47 Peace of Westphalia, German constitution after, 2I ; as possible surting-point of states-system, 1 1 3-I4; furthered development of doctrine of equality of states, I 35; relation to earlier congresses, 146-7 ; marked coming of age of states system, I 52; embodied pdnciple of prescription, I 59, s�e Congress of Westphalia peaceful settlement of disputes, 52 Peisistratid tyrants, 82 Peloponnesian League, 56-7, I 28 Peloponnesian Wars, 37, 38, 47, 49t 52, 53, 57, �I, 61-2, 63, 64-5, J9-8o, 90, 9I, IOI, 194-5 Pericles, secured promanteia for Athens, 49; aimed to make Athens what Sparta had been before Persian invasion, 6o; project to reorganize states-system, 6I ; policy of western expansion, 64; on logic of imperial power, 68 ; ended war with Persia, 88 Persian empire, relations with Roman empire a test case of secondary states-systems, 24; spies in 31 ; Greek wonder at its extent, 73-4; as suzerain power, 75-8o; as object of medizing among Greeks, 8�3; its basil�us and Hellenic statessystem, 83-8 ; as primus in�r pares, 88-..94 ; compared to Carthage, I04I05; relation to Hellenic states system, IOS-7 Peter Ill, I 54 phases of statc:s..systems, 42 ·
Paine, Thomas, I 62 paix maritimes and paix continentales, I 23-4
Panhellenic Congress, 3I, 58 Panhellenic Games , 47 Panhellenic institutions, 47-9 Panhdlenic League, 57�, 62, 63 Panhellenic War, 35 papacy, as participant in secondary states-system, 26; claim to universal jurisdiction, 27-8 ; conflict with Empire, 28-..9 ; claim to be lords of all mankind, 29, I 19-20 ; compared with Delphic Oracle, 48--9, 8I ; conflict with Philip the Fair, I JO; as Italian great power, 139, I40 ; titular victor over two empires in central drama of Middle Ages, I � Parkinson, C. Northcote, 75 Paris Peace Conference of I9I9, 1 38 Paris Peace Conference of I946, 1 66 Paulus Vladimiri, I56, 1 57 Pausanias, So, 83, I OJ pea� idea of in Hellas, 71 Peace of Antalkidas 92-3, ue King's Peace Peace of Apamea, I8I Peace of Augsburg, I90 Peace of Cambrai, 1 24, 145, I47 Peace of Cateau-Cambresis, recognized amity lines ', I .24:...S ; embodied great power ideological •
230
Systems of States
Philip II, I 55 Philip of Macedon, backed by Ddphic Oracle, 49; conquest of Thebes and Athens, 50; exploitation of Greek disunity, 62; unified Greece by force and began war against Persia, 63; eunoia in Greece and his aggression, 7o--I ; adopted lsocratean policy, 87; rdation to Theban-Pcrsian alliance,
prescription, I5B-9, 163-5 Prester John, I I 5
promtJnteia, 49 proxeny, ,30, 53-6 Pufendorf, 21, 159, 164 Pugachev, 154 Punic Wars, 67, I8o, 183 Pydna, battle of, 43
94
Philip V of Macedon, 18o Pindar, 74-5, 98 Pirenne, M., 146 Pius V, Pope, I57 Plato, on rule of law in international rdations, 51 ; on proxenoi, 54; on eunoia, 72; on Greek cultural debt to Middle Eastern civilizations, 85; on drinking liquor while on active service, I04 Plutarch, 83, 91, 104, I82 polemos, contrasted with stasis, to6 plebiscites, I6s-8 poleis, number in Hellenic states- system, 40; formed vast majority of members of states-system, 41 ; existed before the states-system, 47i Delphic Amphictyony predicted fell devdopment of, 53; place in of proxenoi, 54-5; weakening of after· great wars of fifth century, 61 ; Syracuse one comparable in size to Athens, 64; kings survived in constitutions of, 83-4; Carthage a specimen of, 104 political triangles, definitions and classifications, 174-9; end-game triangles, 179-84, 195-200; semi final triangles, 1 84--6; first-round triangles, I8�; formulae for, 190-1 ; light shed by historical precedents on present triangles,
19I-5 Polybius, 67, ¢ Pompey, 181-2 popular legitimacy, 159-73 Poynton, Sir Hilton, 171
raison d'ltat, II3, n4, 140 Ranke, Leopold von, 138 resident ambassadors, see ambassadors respuhlica CAristiana, see Western Christendom Richdieu, n4, 192 right of the majority, 16S-72 right of territorial vicinity, 168-72 Roe, Sir Thomas, I96 Roman Empire, rdations with Persian empire, 24-5; spies in, 31; unification of Hellenistic states system, 43; Augustine on, 44-5; usage of • basileus' in, 84 Rousseau, 2I Rowse, A. L., 192 Rucellai, Bernadino, 1 10 Ryder, T. T. B., 92 Rzeczpospolita Polska, I 55 Sacred Wars, 50, 53, 62, 94 Saladin, 26 Satow, Sir Ernest, I I3 Schelling, Thomas, 32 Second Athenian Confederacy, 87 secondary states-systems, 24, 25 Secretary-General of the United Nations, 27, 29 Selinus, 98 Seljug, 26 Seton-Watson, R. W., 56 Seven Years War, 184, I99 Sicilian Expedition, 6I, 64-5, 98-
IOI Sigismund, 27 Sinibaldo Frieschi, 156, I57 Sixtus V, Pope, I57
Index Slave Kings of Delhi, 23 Smith, Adam, I 14 Soothill, 39 Socrates, 81 sovereign states, as internal mark of states-system, 129-34 Spartan alliance, s�e Pelopponesian League sptes,. 3o-1 Stalin, 166, 168, 184 suuis, Thucydides, on, 37, 69-70, x os--6 ; compared with doctrinal schisms in modern world, 374J; Plato on, 106 Strabo, 103 Stubbs, 27, 163 Suarez, 125--6, 148 Sublime Porte, n6, 155, s�e Ottoman Empire Sully, 190 Sultan of Bijapur, 1 15, 123, x6.t summit meetings, 142-3 Sumner, 169 Taoists, 39 Tarn, 102 Temple, Sir William, 137 terminus aJ qu�m of states-systems, 43-5
thalassocracy, 56, I S, Thales, 76 Themistocles, 53, 59, 83, 88, 91, 191 Thiers, 139 Third Worlds, x']6-7, 197 Thomas, Eiben D., 40 Thirty Years Peace, 52, 61, 98 Thirty Years War, 159, 183 Theophylact of Simocatta, 24 Thucydides, on sta.ris, 37, 6t)-7o, 105-6; on the democratic leaning as instrument of Athenian policy, 38; on customs of war, 51; on dil(e, 52; on prox�noi, 54; on envoys, 55 ; on the sequence of thalassocracies, s6; on debates in the Peloponnesian League, 57; on Syracuse, 64; does not provide theory of balance of power, 66;
23 1
attitude to eunoio, 72; his account of Peloponnesian War ignores Persia, 88--9; enumeration of belligerents in the War, 100; views on War as the struggle of Athens and Sparta, 187; on Themistocles, 191 Tiribazus, 92 treaties of cession, 123 Treaty of Aix-la-Chapelle, 31-2 Treaty of Bagnolo, 123 Treaty of Bretigny, 144 Treaty of Cambrai, 147, ue Peace of Cambrai Treaty of Cateau-Cambr�is, 147, see Peace of Cateau-Cambresis Treaty of Crepy, 147 Treaty of Kallias, 89, see Peace of Kallias Treaty of London of 1518, 140, 149 Treaty of Paris of 1856, n6 Treaty of Poona, 165 Treaty of Ryswick, 16o Treaty of Tordesillas, 124 Treaty of Utrecht, 125, 16o, 197 Treaty of Vervins, 125, see Peace of Vervins triumvirates, 181-4 Turner, F. J., 199 Tyrc, 95, 102 Ullman, W., 28, 1 19 United Nations, mediatory rale of Secretary-General compared to that of Emperor, 27; papacy an alternative historical model for, :zS29; states-system it organizes qualitatively different from that of Concen of Europe, 34; composed of states less homogeneous than those at Congress of Westphalia, 41; rale of Soviet Union compared to that of Athens in Hellenic states.. systelllt 6o; compared with Delphic Oracle, Bo; Charter expresses popular principle of legitimacy, 162-3; Ponugal•s
Systems .oJStates obligations under in Goa, 1 65 ; decline of institution of plebiscite under, 1«r7; made South Africa a pariah state, I 70 Universal Peace of London of 1 5 1 8, II l Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 172 Vasco da Gama,
I 56, I 59· I 69
Greek wonder at extent of Persian empire, 73-4 ; on Greek cultural
8B-9
debt to Middle Eastern civilizations, 85; on Sparta's dependence on Persia, 9I ; his doctrine that peace treaties should be permanent, 93; illustrates . difference between Greek attitudes
War of Ferrara, 145 Wars of Religion, I57 Washington, George, 43 Watson, Adam, 22, 30, I95 Webster, C. K., I47 Western Christendom, its internal arrangements, 2�; provided historical background to Western states-system which Hellenic system lacked, 47; its universalism, ·
I I9-20; its relations with the Turk,
Ilo--2; 125-8;
place in thought of Grotius, breakdown of its old constitution, 15I-2; triangular doctrinal conflict within, I90 Willxrforce, 192
I86 26
to Persia and to Canhage, I 05 Xerxes, attitude to Greek military observers, 31 ; attitude of northern Greek states towards, 58; understanding with Argos, 79; did not occupy Delphi, 8I ; accompanied by Damaratus
·
in
the
great invasion, 83; avenging of his burning of the temples at Athens, 84 ; position of Carthage at time of his invasion of Greece, ¢), 97; authority in Hellas greater than that of Ottoman Sultan in Europe,
Io6 Young Pompey,
Wilson, President, on qualifications �or membership of League, 4I,
Scanned by NT (12/08/2011)
1 57
Xenophon, on 'Lysander's friends ', 37; on Syracusan entry into �� war against Athens, 6s ; on divme retribution against Sparta, 70; on
Virgil, I84 Vitoria, 52, I25, I48 Vollenhoven, 146 Vyshinsky, 1 84
William III, 3I, I59, Williams, Desmond, Wilson, Harold, 32
on moral force of public opinion, 72; on deficiencies of balance of power, 149; on self determination, 16I, I66 Wittfogel, Karl, 75 Wolff, Christian, I35-6, I84, I85 Wolsey, Cardinal, 1 1 2, 140, 1 45 world government, I 49 Wycliffe ,
Vattel, 1 35-6, I 59 Vergil, Polydore, IJ J,I21
Wade-Gery, H. T., Waley, Arthur, 39 Wallenstein, 159 war, 27, 39, 44-5
I62;
1 82-3
Zimmern, Sir Alfred,
42