This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
e.g. arrive at an accommodation [with smbd] e.g. come to an accommodation with >smbd<
kindred with S + V + O accommodate smbd
(5–1–03–0–0) S/s + V/ø + PO/v
kindred with S + V + PO + PÖ agree >with smbd< [about smth] agree >with smbd< [about smth]
(5–2–01–0–0) S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v e.g. go/move into action
kindred with S + V act (‘be active’)
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of restructuring 71 (5–2–02–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/o + PÖ/v e.g. receive smbd with acclaim provide smbd with aid fill smbd with alarm provide smbd with amusement subject smth to an/sm analysis place/put smbd under arrest provide smbd with sm assistance
kindred with S + V + O acclaim smbd aid smbd alarm smbd amuse smbd analyse smth arrest smbd assist smbd
(5–2–02–0–6) S/s + V/ø + O/o + PÖ/v (+ Ø/pö) e.g. bring smth into alignment
kindred with S + V + O align smth >with smth<
(5–2–02–1–0) S/s + V-L/ø + O/o + PÖ/v e.g. put smth up for auction
kindred with S + V + O auction smth
(5–2–03–0–2) S/s + V/ø + O/io + PÖ/v (+ Ø/o) e.g. present smbd with an award
kindred with S + V + O + IO award smth (to smbd)
(5–2–04–0–0) S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v + PÖ/o e.g. lie/wait in ambush [for smbd] break/burst into applause [at smth/smbd]
kindred with S + V + O ambush smbd applaud [smth/smbd]
(5–2–05–0–0) S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v
kindred with S + V + O accommodate smbd
(5–2–06–0–0) S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v
kindred with S + V + O aid smbd assist smbd
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
72
Syntactic restructuring
(5–2–07–0–0) S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ arrange smth with smbd
(5–2–09–0–0) S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v
kindred with S + V + PÖ + PÖ accord with smbd about smth
(5–3–01–0–1) S/o + V/ø + PÖ/v (+ Ø/s) e.g. meet with sm acceptance
kindred with S + V + O accept (‘tolerate’) smth/smbd
(5–3–02–0–0) S/o + V/ø + PÖ/v + PÖ/s e.g. come under attack (from smbd)
kindred with S + V + O attack [smbd/smth]
(5–3–02–1–0) S/o + V-L/ø + PÖ/v + PÖ/s kindred with S + V + O e.g. come in for sm abuse from/ abuse smbd at-the-hands-of smbd (5–4–01–0–1) S/pö + V/ø + PÖ/v (+ Ø/s) e.g. go to arbitration
kindred with S + V + PÖ arbitrate between pple
(5–5–01–0–0) S/po + V/ø + PÖ/v
11
Types of restructuring 73 (5–6–01–0–0) S/x + V/ø + O/s + PÖ/v + PÖ/po e.g. call smbd to account (for smth)
kindred with Sx Vx + [S + V + PO] cause smbd to account for smth
(5–7–01–0–1) S/ö + V/ø + PÖ/v (Ø/s) e.g. suffer from an ailment
kindred with S + V + Ö smth ails smbd
11
11
In order to exemplify each subvariety of correspondences, we shall again give a pair of sentences, the first one a Structure 4 sentence, the second one (in parentheses) its kindred structure in a simple eventive verb structure: (36) (5–1–01–0–0) (5–1–02–0–0)
Sybil arrived at an accommodation with Peregrine. (Sybil accommodated Peregrine.)
(5–1–03–0–0)
The Socialists entered into an alliance with the Progressives. (The Socialists allied themselves with the Progressives.)
(5–1–04–0–0)
Sebastian entered into a formal agreement with Priscilla about the children. (Sebastian formally agreed with Priscilla about the children.)
(5–2–01–0–0)
The Secret Service moved into action. (The Secret Service acted.)
(5–2–02–0–0)
Sebastian filled Olga with alarm. (Sebastian alarmed Olga.)
(5–2–02–0–6)
Sybil brought the oar into alignment with the prow. (Sybil aligned the oar with the prow.)
(5–2–03–0–2)
Sybil presented Oscar with an award. (Sybil awarded a medal to Oscar.)
(5–2–04–0–0)
The audience burst into applause at the joke. (The audience applauded the joke.)
(5–2–06–0–0)
Sybil came to Gerald’s aid (= . . . the aid of Gerald). (Sybil aided Gerald.)
111
111
111
111
Sebastian indulged in some acting at college. (Sebastian acted at college.)
1
74
Syntactic restructuring (5–2–07–0–0)
Sebastian finally came to an agreement with Priscilla about the will. (Sebastian finally agreed with Priscilla about the will.)
(5–2–08–0–0)
Sybil came to an arrangement with the press about her meeting. (Sybil arranged her meeting with the press.)
(5–2–09–0–0)
Sebastian came to an accord with the Prime Minister about the succession. (Sebastian accorded with the Prime Minister about the succession.)
(5–3–01–0–1)
The scheme met with general acceptance. (People generally accepted the scheme.)
(5–3–02–0–0)
Sybil came under attack from the press. (The press attacked Sybil.)
(5–3–02–1–0)
Sebastian came in for abuse at the hands of the press. (The press abused Sebastian.)
(5–4–01–0–0)
The plan met with Grizelda’s approval (= . . . the approval of Grizelda). (Grizelda approved of the plan.)
(5–5–01–0–1)
Sebastian and Sybil went to arbitration. (The court arbitrated between Sebastian and Sybil).
(5–6–01–0–0)
The authorities called Oscar to account (for the emergency). (The authorities caused Oscar to account for the emergency.)
(5–7–01–0–1)
Sybil is suffering from an ailment at the moment. (Something ails Sybil at the moment.)
1
1
11
11
11
11
Unlike Structures 3 and 4, which consistently have the verb be, Structure 5 includes a number of different verbs, embracing different valency types. What all the verbs in this stretched structure share, however, is the potential for being complemented by a prepositional object or objoid, because this is the place where the event of the kindred simple verb is manifested. The fact that the thin verb is not be but a verb which in its literal use has an actional meaning has the result that the overall meaning of Structure 5 constructions refers more to an action than the kind of states referred to in Constructions 3 and 4. The verb enter (into) of enter into an alliance in (5–1–04–0–0), for instance, helps give its construction a dynamic value (in
11
Types of restructuring 75 this case an inchoative or inceptive value) compared with the Structure 4 phrase be in alliance. An examination of the different patterns of (5–1–01–0–0) through to (5–7–01–0–1) again reveals structural diversity. The patterns of (5–1) differ from the rest in having the event appearing as a prepositional object rather than a prepositional objoid. This means that the deverbal noun, which in the Structure 5 construction expresses the event, can become the subject noun in a corresponding passive sentence; so that (30)(i) and (ii) would be the passive correlates of (36)(5–1–03–0–0) and(5–1–04–0–0) respectively:
11
11
111
111
111
111
(37) (a) An alliance was entered into by the Socialists with the Progressives. (b) An agreement was entered into by Sebastian with Priscilla about the children. Such passive sentences cannot be formed when the event is expressed in the form of a prepositional objoid, as it does in (29) (5–2–07–0–0), for which the ungrammatical passive correlate would be: (38)
*An agreement was finally come to by Sebastian with Priscilla about the will.
The four patterns of (5–1), then, are the only ones within Structure 5 to have the kindred simplex verb appearing in a true passivizable prepositional object position, the main differences between them being the number of prepositional qualifiers they have (none in the (5–1–01–0–0) pattern, one in the (5–1–02–0–0) and (5–1–03–0–0) patterns, representing a kindred object or prepositional objoid respectively, and two in the (5–1–04–0–0) patten, representing a prepositional object and a prepositional objoid. The remaining patterns of Structure 5, from (5–2) to (5–7), all have an eventive prepositional objoid to represent the kindred simplex verb. They differ from each other in what kindred simplex element the subject represents: in (5–2) the subject corresponds to a kindred simplex subject, in (5–3) to a kindred simplex object, in (5–4) and (5–5) to a kindred simplex prepositional object or objoid respectively, in (5–6) to the subject of an external clause in which the clause containing the kindred simplex verb has been embedded, and in (5–7) to a kindred simplex objoid. This means that in (5–3), (5–4), (5–5), (5–6) and (5–7) there has been a more substantial restructuring: not only does the kindred structure’s verb appear as a prepositional objoid; its subject is also displaced, appearing as an object in (5–6), as a genitival qualifier of the eventive noun in (5–4), possibly as a prepositional objoid in (5–3), and finding no representation at all in (5–5) and (5–7). Within the various subvarieties of (5–2) there is a basic pattern (5–2–01–0–0) with the structure S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v, to cater for kindred intransitive verbs, and different expansions of it, mainly to accommodate
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
76
Syntactic restructuring
a kindred simplex object, which appears in the stretched structure as an object in (5–2–02) and (5–2–03), as a prepositional objoid in (5–2–04), as a prepositional qualifier in (5–2–05), and as a genitival qualifier in (5–2–06). The stretched pattern of (5–2–03–0–2) is unusual in that it represents the kindred simplex indirect object as an object, while suppressing the kindred simplex object itself. The (5–2–07–0–0) pattern has two prepositional qualifiers representing a kindred simplex prepositional object or objoid respectively. One pattern, (5–3–02–1–0), has a phrasal verb, a combination of verb-plus-limiter-adverb, as the thin verb, which means that it shows a sequence of relatively empty elements consisting of verb with limiter adverb and following preposition (come in for). Turning now, as we did for the other Structures, to the perspective of the kindred simplex verb patterns, we can now see that the intransitive pattern can only appear as S/s + V/ø + PO/v (= pattern 5–1–01–0–0) or as S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v (= pattern 5–2–01–0–0); this is the pattern at its most basic. Looking at kindred simplex S + V + O types of pattern, we can disregard the PO/v types (5–1–01) to (5–1–04) as relatively uncommon; pattern (5–1–02) , with its compulsorily reflexive object in the kindred simplex structure, is especially rare. This means that stretched structures corresponding to a kindred simplex transitive pattern are basically S/s + V/ø + PÖ/v, with the object then appearing in one of the positions O,
11
11
11
111
111
Types of restructuring 77
II.2.vi Structure 6 patterns: V-ejection to O/Ö (eventive) This is an extremely rich structural type with over eighty different variants, making it clearly the major syntactic type of stretched verb structure. Its distinctive characteristic compared with Structures 3, 4 and 5 (in other words, the others with an eventive deverbal noun) is that the event appears as a noun in object or objoid position. The valency of English verbs in general is such that there are substantially more valency structures that include an object than ones that include a preposition phrase. Table 2.1 had fifteen patterns with O, two with Ö, three with PD, five with PO, and eight with PÖ. This wider range of object structures, combined with the greater involvement of objects in transformational and kindred relations, results in there being a far wider range of different subvarieties for Structure 6, with frequent cases of one simple eventive verb structure appearing in two or three eventive noun structures, creating the stretched equivalent of passive and causative structures. There is a point to bear in mind concerning indirect objects (IO), which only appear in the stretched constructions of Structure 6. By definition (see above, section II.1.ii) indirect objects appear in two different patterns in active sentences, one in which the indirect object includes a preposition (to or for) and follows the (direct) object, the other in which the indirect object takes the form of a bare noun phrase and precedes the (direct) object. When an indirect object occurs as part of a stretched verb construction, it may appear in either form; but for the sake of simplicity of presentation, only one form will be listed below, namely the one with the preposition present and the indirect object following the (direct) object. (This was established in the discussion above as the unmarked version of the pattern.) Thus the example give aid to smbd (listed under 6–1–02–0–6 below) has the alternative form give smbd aid. Amongst the very rich range of possibilities for Structure 6 at the very least the following different subvarieties can be distinguished:43 (6–1–01–0–0)
111
S/s + V/ø + O/v e.g. do some acting initiate/take action make an advance gain advancement form an agglomeration
kindred with S + V act (‘perform dramatically’) act (‘be active’) advance (‘progress’) advance (‘be promoted’) agglomerate
111
43 It should constantly be borne in mind that the constructions grouped together under the same syntactic subvariety may differ substantially in other respects (such as the type of noun phrase used as object, the value of the thin verb, etc.).
1
78 Syntactic restructuring (6–1–01–0–2) S/s + V/ø + O/v (+ Ø/o) e.g. record/register an achievement make an acquisition assume an affectation cause anger practise appeasement make/perform/effect an arrest
1
(6–1–01–0–26)
1
S/s + V/ø + O/v (+ Ø/o + Ø/pö) e.g. call an alert show application
11
11
11
11
kindred with S + V + O achieve smth acquire smth affect smth anger smbd appease smbd arrest smbd
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ alert smbd [to smth] apply onslf [to smth]
(6–1–01–0–24/26) S/s + V/ø + O/v (+ Ø/o + Ø/nd, pd, pö) e.g. make an appointment 44
kindred with S + V + O + ND/PD/PÖ appoint smbd [(as) smth] appoint smbd [to smth]
冦
(6–1–01–1–0) S/s + V-L/ø + O/v e.g. put on an act
kindred with S + V act (‘perform dramatically’)
(6–1–01–1–2) S/s + V-L/ø + O/v (+ Ø/o) e.g. put on an affectation bring in an acquittal carry out an arrest
kindred with S + V + O affect smth acquit smbd arrest smbd
(6–1–02–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/o e.g. give an address [to smbd] 45 give an air to smth give an airing to smth give one’s approval [to smth] give articulation to smth
kindred with S + V + O address (‘speak to’) smbd air (‘dry in the air’) smth air (‘make public’) smth approve smth articulate smth
44 with the meaning ‘assign smbd to a post’ (and not with the meaning ‘arrange a meeting’). 45 cf. deliver an address to smbd under (6–1–12–0–0).
11
Types of restructuring 79 (6–1–02–0–4) S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/o (+ Ø/nd, pd, pö) e.g. give an appointment (‘post’) to smbd
11
111
(6–1–03–0–2)
111
冦
(6–1–02–0–6) S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/o (+ Ø/pö) e.g. give/offer sm aid (to smbd) cause sm amazement (to smbd) afford sm amusement to smbd cause sm amusement (to smbd) cause sm annoyance (to smbd) give one’s approval [to smth] give/render assistance to smbd affer (one’s) assistance to smbd
11
kindred with S + V + O + ND/PD/PÖ appoint smbd [(as) smth] appoint smbd [to smth]
S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/io (+ Ø/o) e.g. give/grant an award (to smbd)
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ aid smbd (with smth) amaze smbd [with smth] amuse smbd (with smth) amuse smbd (with smth) annoy smbd (with smth) approve smth (for smbd) assist smbd (with smth) assist smbd (with smth)
kindred with S + V + O + IO award smth (to smbd)
(6–1–04–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/po e.g. give one’s assent [to smth] give/pay sm attention [to smth/smbd]
kindred with S + V + PO assent to smth attend to (‘listen to’) [smth/smbd]
(6–1–05–0–2) S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/pö (+ Ø/o) e.g. give an assignment to smbd give an autograph to smbd
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ assign smth to smbd 46 autograph smth ( for smbd)
111
111
46 This is a difficult case to classify, because the verb assign has at least two different usages for most speakers and also differs between British and American English. The above analysis is based on the usage in which the noun phrase referring to the person to whom something is assigned is always preceded by a preposition and cannot become the subject of a related passive sentence; in other words, it is a prepositional objoid. Other usages would obviously require a different classification.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
80 Syntactic restructuring (6–1–06–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/pö + kindred with S + V + PO + PÖ PÖ/po e.g. give one’s assent (to smbd) assent [to smth] ( for smbd) [for smth] (6–1–07–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v + PO/po kindred with S + V + PO allow for smth e.g. make an/sm allowance for smth 47 (6–1–08–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/o e.g. heap/shower abuse on smbd hurl/shout sm abuse (at smbd) extend/minister aid to smbd provide aid [for smbd] arouse/cause alarm in smbd cause alienation in smbd provide sm amusement ( for smbd ) induce/produce anaesthesia in smbd make an approach [to smbd] provide assistance [for smbd] render assistance (to smbd) arouse/cause sm astonishment (in smbd)
kindred with S + V + O abuse smbd abuse smbd aid smbd aid smbd alarm smbd alienate smbd amuse smbd anaesthetize smbd approach smbd assist smbd assist smbd astonish smbd
(6–1–09–0–2) S/s + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/io (+ Ø/o) kindred with S + V + O + IO e.g. make/present an award (to smbd) award smth (to smbd) (6–1–10–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/po e.g. suffer agony (‘mental anguish’ ) [with smth] take aim [at smth] make an allusion to smth have an argue >with smbd<48
kindred with S + V + PO agonize about/over smth aim at smth allude to smth argue (‘quarrel’) >with smbd<
47 Note that make allowances [for smbd] ‘forgive smbd a minor annoyance’ cannot be regarded as kindred with allow for. 48 limited to highly informal British and Australian English, cf. Wierzbicka (1982).
Types of restructuring 81 make atonement [for smth] dance attendance on smbd devote one’s attention to smth/smbd focus one’s attention on smth/smbd
11
11
11
atone for smth attend to smbd 49 attend to smth/smbd 50 attend to smth/smbd 51
(6–1–10–0–2) S/s + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/pö kindred with S + V + O + PÖ (+ Ø/o) e.g. do/perform an abortion (on smbd) abort smth ( for smbd) induce an abortion (in smbd) abort smth ( for smbd) add an attachment [to smth] attach smth [to smth] (6–1–10–1–2) S/s + V-L/ø + O/v + PÖ/pö kindred with S + V + O + PÖ (+ Ø/o) e.g. carry out an abortion (on smbd) abort smth ( for smbd)
111
111
(6–1–11–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v + AE/ae e.g. make an appearance [smwh]
kindred with S + V + AE appear [smwh]
(6–1–11–1–0) S/s + V-L/ø + O/v + AE/ae e.g. put in an appearance [smwh]
kindred with S + V + AE appear [smwh]
(6–1–12–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O abridge smth access smth 52 accommodate smbd accompany smbd acknowledge smth
111
111
49 50 51 52
in the sense of ‘wait on smbd’. in the sense of ‘pay attention to smth/smbd’. in the sense of ‘pay attention to smth/smbd’. As already noted above, the verb access was a secondary derivation from the noun access, but its secondary nature is becoming less obvious.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
82
Syntactic restructuring do/make an adaptation of [smth] deliver an address (‘speech’) [to smbd] make an/sm adjustment [to smth] feel admiration for smbd publish/run an advertisement (for smth) make an affirmation (of smth) cause an/ aggravation 53 [of smth] do/make an alteration [to smth] make an amendment [to smth] provide sm amplification [of/for smth] do/make an analysis of smth make an annotation to smth issue/make an announcement (about smth) provide an answer [to smth] make an appraisal of smth/smbd feel sm appreciation for smth make an ascent [of smth/smwh] commit an assault (on smbd) do/make an assessment [of smth] launch/make/mount/press an attack [on smbd/smth] make an attempt [at smth] do an audit (of smth) calculate an average [of sm things]
(6–1–12–0–6) S/s + V/ø + O/v
adapt smth address (‘speak to’) smbd adjust smth admire smbd advertise (smth) affirm smth aggravate smth alter smth amend smth amplify smth analyse smth annotate smth announce smth answer [smth] appraise smth/smbd appreciate (‘be grateful for’) smth ascend smth/smwh assault smbd assess smth attack [smbd/smth] attempt smth audit smth average [sm things]
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ accuse smbd [of smth]
kindred with S + V + O accommodate smbd adapt smth amputate smth assassinate smbd
53 in the sense of ‘worsening’; ‘in the sense of ‘trouble’ aggravation cannot be related to the verb aggravate.
11
11
11
111
111
Types of restructuring 83 carry out an assesssment [of smth/smbd] carry out an attack (on smbd/smth) press home an attack (on smth) work out an average [of sm things] (6–1–13–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
assess smth/smbd attack [smbd/smth] attack [smth] average [sm things]
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ 54 allocate smth [to smbd/smth] annul smth ( for smbd) answer [smth] ( for smbd) appraise smth ( for smbd) approve smth ( for smbd) authorize smth ( for smbd) adjourn smth ( for smbd)
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ admit (‘confess’) smth [to smbd] appropriate smth (for smbd) approach smbd [about smth]
(6–1–15–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O + AE advertise (smth) (smwh)
111
111
54 Some of the preposition phrases with the kindred verbs in this subvariety (allocate, annul, answer, appraise, approve) may give the appearance of an indirect object, but in fact (with the exception of allocate for some speakers) the phrase concerned cannot normally appear without its preposition before the direct object, nor can it become the subject in a corresponding passive sentence.
1
1
1
11
11
84 Syntactic restructuring (6–1–16–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
11
11
55 This is of course an extremely rare verb. But it should be recalled that the ‘underlying’ verb is not being regarded as derivationally primary in any sense; it simply represents a kindred construction. 56 This is, as noted in the previous footnote, a rare verb. 57 where account means ‘explanation’. 58 with the meaning ‘urge to reconsider’.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of restructuring 85 make/submit an application ( for smth) [to smbd]
apply to smbd for smth
(6–1–18–1–0) S/s + V-L/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + PO + PÖ agree >with smbd< [about smth] appeal 59 [to smbd] [for/against smth] apply for smth
(6–1–19–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ absolve smbd [from smth] add smth [to smth] append smth [to smth] assume smth (about smth/smbd)
(6–1–20–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ absolve smbd [from smth] admit (‘let in’) smbd [to smwh]
59 with the meaning ‘urge to reconsider’. 60 in the sense of ‘not eat/drink/etc.’; not in the sense of ‘not vote’. 61 There might well also be a related structure (6–1–19–1–2) with a phrasal verb as the thin verb, but the only example collected so far is strike up an acquaintance with smbd/smth, which is slightly deviant in being kindred with a simplex structure with a reflexive verb, namely acquaint oneself with smbd/smth, and in limiting the use of the stretched verb construction to animate acquaintances.
1
1
1
86
Syntactic restructuring give/offer advice (on smth) (to smbd) give applause ( for smth) [to smbd] give an assurance [to smbd] (about smth)
advise smbd (about smth) applaud smbd ( for smth) assure 62 smbd [of/about smth]
(6–1–21–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + PO + PÖ apologize [to smbd] [for/(to smbd) about smth]
11
11
11
11
(6–1–23–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v +
kindred with S + V + PÖ + PÖ accord >with smbd< (about smth)
(6–1–24–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + AE act in a certain way
(6–1–25–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O anger smbd
62 in the sense of ‘promise’. 63 It could be argued that the semantic relationship between this construction and its simplex relative is not close enough, because the subject of the verb accord is not so often human (as for the stretched verb construction) but more commonly inanimate or abstract. A better example of this particular structural type would be perhaps reach a compromise >with smbd< (about smth) with its kindred simplex pattern compromise >with smbd< (about smth).
11
11
11
Types of restructuring 87 (6–1–25–1–0) S/s + V-L/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O anger smbd
(6–1–26–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + I attempt to do smth
(6–1–27–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + (S-)I arrange ( for smbd) to do smth
111
111
(6–1–28–1–0) S/s + V-L/ø + O/v <(S-)IC/i> e.g. work out an arrangement [( for smbd) to do smth] (6–1–29–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + F affirm that-Clause assert that-Clause assume that-Clause avow that-Clause
(6–1–30–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
111
111
kindred with S + V + (S-)I arrange ( for smbd) to do smth
64 in the sense of ‘promise’.
kindred with S + V + O + F assure 64 smbd that-Clause
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
88
Syntactic restructuring
(6–1–31–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + PÖ + F allege that-Clause to smbd
(6–2–01–0–1) S/o + V/ø + O/v (+ Ø/s) e.g. undergo acclimatization undergo an/sm adaptation get an airing suffer alienation undergo an/sm analysis suffer an awakening
kindred with S + V + O acclimatize smbd adapt smth air (‘make public’) smth alienate smbd analyse smth awaken/wake smbd
(6–2–02–0–0) S/o + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/s e.g. suffer sm abuse ( from/at-thehands-of smbd) take sm abuse ( from smbd) find sm acceptance from smbd suffer an affront ( from/at-thehands-of smbd) receive sm aid ( from smbd) feel sm alarm [at smth] feel sm amusement [at smth] find sm amusement [in smth] suffer annihilation (at-thehands-of smbd) feel sm annoyance [about/at smth/ with/at smbd] suffer sm annoyance [ from/ at-the-hands of smbd] feel sm astonishment [at smth] feel an attraction for smbd
kindred with S + V + O abuse smbd abuse smbd accept smbd affront smbd aid smbd alarm smbd amuse smbd amuse smbd annihilate smbd annoy smbd annoy smbd astonish smbd attract smbd
(6–2–03–0–1) S/o + V/ø + O/v
11
11
Types of restructuring 89 (6–2–04–0–0) S/o + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ absolve smbd [from smth] advise smbd [about smth]
(6–2–05–0–0) S/o + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O approve smth/smbd
11
111
111
(6–2–06–0–1) S/o + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ acquaint smbd >with smbd else< 65
(6–3–01–0–1) S/io + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/s + (+ Ø/o) e.g. receive an award ( from smbd)
kindred with S + V + O + IO award smth (to smbd)
(6–4–01–0–0) S/po + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/s e.g. incur/suffer aggression ( from/ at-the-hands-of smbd) receive attention ( from smbd)
kindred with S + V + PO aggress 66 against smbd attend to smbd 67
(6–4–02–0–0) S/po + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + PO approve of smth/smbd attend to smth 68
111
111
65 66 67 68
This is a problematic case, as noted above in the case of example (3–2–03–0–1). This is a rare verb, as already noted under type (6–4–01–0–0). in the sense of ‘treat medically’. in the sense of ‘pay attention to smth’.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
90
Syntactic restructuring
(6–5–01–0–0) S/pö + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V act (‘be active’)
(6–6–02–1–2) S/x + V-L/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O applaud [smbd]
(6–6–03–0–0) S/x + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O attack [smbd/smth]
(6–6–04–1–0) S/x + V-L/ø + O/v
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of restructuring 91 (6–6–05–0–0) S/x + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O access smth/smwh
(6–6–06–0–5) S/x + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + PO attend to smth 69
(6–6–07–0–0) S/x + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + PO attend to smth 70
(6–6–08–0–0) S/x + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + O approve smth
(6–6–09–0–0) S/x + V/ø + O/s + PÖ/v + PÖ/po e.g. call smbd to account ( for smth)
kindred with S + V + PO account for smth
(6–6–10–0–0) S/x (= o) + V/ø + O/v
1
92
Syntactic restructuring
(6–6–12–0–0) S/x (= pö) + V/ø + O/v kindred with S + V + O + PÖ
1
(6–6–13–0–0)
1
S/x (= pö) + V/ø + O/v
kindred with S + V + PO + PÖ apologize [to smbd] [ for smth]
(6–7–01–0–0) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v + PÖ/pö e.g. have an appeal ( for smbd)
kindred with S + V + PÖ appeal to (‘please’) smbd
11
11
(6–7–02–0–0) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v + AE/ae e.g. feel/have an ache (smwh)
kindred with S + V + AE 71 ache (smwh)
(6–7–03–0–0) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v
kindred with S + V + O appreciate (‘understand’) smth attempt smth
(6–7–03–0–7) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v
11
11
71 In a further kindred structure the place adverbial and the ‘possessor’ subject are merged to give a joint (semantically complex) subject: thus S/s + V/ø + Ö/v + A/a can be regarded as a stretching not just of S + V + AE but even of S + V, the latter construction appearing, for instance, as My arm aches.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of restructuring 93 (6–7–04–0–0) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v
kindred with S + V + PO + PÖ argue (‘quarrel’) >with smbd< (about smth)
(6–7–05–0–0) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v
kindred with S + V + PÖ ally onslf with smbd
(6–7–06–0–0) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v
kindred with S + V + I aspire to do/be smth
(6–7–07–0–0) S/s + V/ø + Ö/v
kindred with S + V + I aim to do smth attempt to do smth
(6–8–01–0–1) S/o + V/ø + Ö/v (+ Ø/s) e.g. have an airing have an application
kindred with S + V + O air smth apply smth
(6–8–02–0–1) S/o + V/ø + Ö/v
kindred with S + V + O + PÖ acquaint smbd with smth
Each structure will now be illustrated as before with an example sentence (followed by a kindred simplex eventive verb structure in parentheses): (39) (6–1–01–0–0) (6–1–01–0–2)
Sybil did some acting in her spare time. (Sybil acted in her spare time.) Sybil recorded some achievements last year. (Sybil achieved some successes last year.)
(6–1–01–0–24/26) Sebastian made an appointment. (Sebastian appointed John (as) his new press secretary.)
1
94
Syntactic restructuring (6–1–01–1–0)
Sybil was putting on an act. (Sybil was acting.)
(6–1–01–1–2)
The jury brought in an acquittal. (The jury acquitted the murder suspect.)
(6–1–02–0–0)
Sebastian gave the problem of taxation an airing. (Sebastian aired the problem of taxation.)
(6–1–02–0–4)
Sebastian gave the appointment to Priscilla. (Sebastian appointed Priscilla his new press secretary.)
1
1
(Cf. (6–1–01–0–24–26).) (6–1–02–0–6)
Switzerland gave aid to Peru. (Switzerland aided Peru.)
(6–1–03–0–2)
The authorities gave an award to Priscilla. (The authorities awarded a scholarship to Priscilla.)
(6–1–04–0–0)
Sebastian paid attention to the details. (Sebastian attended to the details.)
(6–1–05–0–2)
The authorities gave the assignment to an investigator. (The authorities assigned the job to an investigator.)
(6–1–06–0–0)
Sybil gave Idris her assent for the plan. (Sybil assented to the plan for Idris.)
(6–1–07–0–0)
Sybil made allowance(s) for Gerald’s exaggerations. (Sybil allowed for Gerald’s exaggerations.)
(6–1–08–0–0)
Sebastian made an approach to Priscilla. (Sebastian approached Priscilla.)
(6–1–09–0–2)
The committee made an award to Priscilla. (The committee awarded a prize to Priscilla.)
(6–1–10–0–0)
Sebastian took aim at the target. (Sebastian aimed at the target.)
(6–1–10–0–2)
The doctor performed an abortion on the patient. (The doctor aborted the foetus for the patient.)
(6–1–10–1–2)
The doctor carried out an abortion on the patient. (The doctor aborted the foetus for the patient.)
11
11
11
11
11
Types of restructuring 95 (6–1–11–0–0)
Sebastian made an appearance in the hall. (Sebastian appeared in the hall.)
(6–1–11–1–0)
Sebastian put in an appearance in the hall. (Sebastian appeared in the hall.)
(6–1–12–0–0)
Sybil made an adjustment to the volume. (Sybil adjusted the volume.)
(6–1–12–0–6)
Sebastian made an accusation against Priscilla. (Sebastian accused Priscilla of misconduct.)
(6–1–12–1–0)
The team carried out an assessment of the plan. (The team assessed the plan.)
(6–1–13–0–0)
The court granted an annulment of the marriage to Ida. (The court annulled the marriage for Ida.)
(6–1–14–0–0)
Sebastian made an admission about his misconduct to the journalist. (Sebastian admitted his misconduct to the journalist.)
(6–1–15–0–0)
Sybil put an advertisement about the jumble sale in the local paper. (Sybil advertised the jumble sale in the local paper.)
(6–1–16–0–0)
Sebastian made an allusion to the divorce. (Sebastian alluded to the divorce.)
(6–1–16–1–0)
Sybil stirred up agitation against the proposals. (Sybil agitated against the proposals.)
(6–1–17–0–0)
Sybil gave an account of her expenditure to Idris. (Sybil accounted for her expenditure to Idris.)
(6–1–18–0–0)
Sebastian reached a formal agreement with Priscilla about the children. (Sebastian formally agreed with Priscilla about the children.)
(6–1–18–1–0)
Sebastian worked out a formal agreement with Priscilla about the children. (Sebastian formally agreed with Priscilla about the children.)
(6–1–19–0–0)
Sybil practised total abstinence from drink. (Sybil totally abstained from drink.)
(6–1–19–0–2)
Sebastian made an addition to the estate. (Sebastian added a model village to the estate.)
11
11
111
111
111
111
1
1
96
Syntactic restructuring (6–1–20–0–0)
Sebastian gave advice to Ida about taxation. (Sebastian advised Ida about taxation.)
(6–1–21–0–0)
Sybil offered an apology for her behaviour to Idris. (Sybil apologized to Idris for her behaviour.)
(6–1–22–0–0)
Sebastian made his apologies to his hosts about the outburst. (Sebastian apologized to his hosts about the outburst.)
(6–1–23–0–0)
Sybil reached an accord with the press about the photographs. (Sybil accorded with the press about the photographs.)
(6–1–24–0–0)
Sebastian committed an act of stupidity. (Sebastian acted stupidly.)
(6–1–25–0–0)
Sybil aroused the anger of Gerald/Gerald’s anger. (Sybil angered Gerald.)
(6–1–25–1–0)
Sybil stirred up the anger of Gerald/Gerald’s anger. (Sybil angered Gerald.)
(6–1–26–0–0)
Sebastian made an attempt to persuade them. (Sebastian attempted to persuade them.)
(6–1–27–0–0)
Sybil gave authorization to Idris to sign the documents. (Sybil authorized Idris to sign the documents.)
(6–1–28–0–0)
Sebastian made an arrangement (for her) to cash cheques.72 (Sebastian arranged (for her) to cash cheques.)
(6–1–28–1–0)
Sebastian and Sybil worked out an arrangement to meet once a year. (Sebastian and Sybil arranged to meet once a year.)
(6–1–29–0–0)
Sybil made the assumption that he would agree. (Sybil assumed that he would agree.)
(6–1–30–0–0)
Sebastian gave an assurance to Ida that he would attend. (Sebastian assured Ida that he would attend.)
1
11
11
11
11
72 Such structures with an optional subject noun phrase before the infinitive follow the standard pattern of interpretation in having the same subject as the preceding (catenative) verb when the infinitive lacks an overt subject of its own.
11
11
Types of restructuring 97 (6–1–31–0–0)
Sybil made the allegation to a journalist that Sebastian was dishonest. (Sybil alleged to a journalist that Sebastian was dishonest.)
(6–2–01–0–1)
The data underwent analysis. (The laboratory analysed the data.)
(6–2–02–0–0)
Sebastian felt alarm at the news. (The news alarmed Sebastian.)
(6–2–03–0–1)
Sybil secured admittance to the garden party. (The turnstile operator admitted Sybil to the garden party.)
(6–2–04–0–0)
Sebastian received advice about the problem from Priscilla. (Priscilla advised Sebastian about the problem.)
(6–2–05–0–0)
The strategy received the approval of the government/the government’s approval. (The government approved the strategy.)
(6–2–06–0–1)
Sybil made Gerald’s acquaintance/the acquaintance of Gerald. (Someone acquainted Sybil with Gerald.)
(6–3–01–0–1)
Sybil received an award from the committee. (The committee awarded a prize to Sybil.)
(6–4–01–0–0)
Switzerland suffered aggression at the hands of Peru. (Peru aggressed against Switzerland.)
(6–4–02–0–0)
The plan found the approval of Gertrude/ Gertrude’s approval. (Gertrude approved of the plan.)
(6–5–01–0–0)
Sebastian did not receive an answer to the question from Priscilla. (Priscilla did not answer the question for Sebastian.)
(6–6–01–0–1)
The government stimulated activity in the currency market. (Traders acted in the currency market.)
(6–6–02–1–2)
The incident sparked off applause from the audience. (The audience applauded the acrobat.)
11
111
111
111
111
1
1
98 Syntactic restructuring (6–6–03–0–0)
Switzerland provoked an attack on Peru by Qatar. (Qatar attacked Peru.)
(6–6–03–1–0)
Switzerland sparked off an attack on Peru by Qatar. (Qatar attacked Peru.)
(6–6–04–1–0)
Sebastian brought about an agreement about the post between Priscilla and Peregrine. (Priscilla agreed about the post with Peregrine.)
(6–6–05–0–0)
The authorities granted access to the information to Peregrine. Peregrine accessed73 the information.
(6–6–06–0–5)
The speech attracted the attention of Gerald/Gerald’s attention. (Gerald attended to the speech)
(6–6–07–0–0)
The secretary drew the attention of the general (= the general’s attention) to the problem. (The general attended to the problem.)
(6–6–08–0–0)
Sybil got the approval of the authorities (= the authorities’ approval) for her plans. (The authorities approved Sybil’s plans.)
(6–6–09–0–0)
Sebastian called Olga to account for the fire. (Olga accounted for the fire.)
(6–6–10–0–0)
Sybil inspired the admiration of Gerald/Gerald’s admiration. (Gerald admired Sybil.)
(6–6–11–0–1)
Switzerland provoked aggression at the hands of Peru. (Peru aggressed against Switzerland.)
(6–6–12–0–0)
Sebastian obtained an annulment of the marriage from the court. (The court annulled the marriage for Sebastian.)
(6–6–13–0–0)
Sybil elicited an apology from Peregrine. (Peregrine apologized to Sybil.)
(6–7–01–0–0)
Sociology had a strong appeal for Priscilla. (Sociology strongly appealed to Priscilla.)
1
11
11
11
11
73 This is of course a relatively rare word that is still confined to technical language, but the existence of this and similar stretched verb constructions paved the way for its creation. See footnote 34 on p. 57.
11
Types of restructuring 99 (6–7–02–0–0)
Sebastian had an ache in his neck. (Sebastian ached in his neck.)
(6–7–03–0–0)
Sybil had an attempt at the jump. (Sybil attempted the jump.)
(6–7–03–0–7)
Sybil had a dynamic approach to politics. (Sybil approached politics in a dynamic manner.)
(6–7–04–0–0)
Sebastian had an argument about money with Priscilla. (Sebastian argued about money with Priscilla.)
(6–7–05–0–0)
Switzerland had an alliance with Peru. (Switzerland allied itself with Peru.)
(6–7–06–0–0)
Sybil had aspirations to enter politics. (Sybil aspired to enter politics.)
(6–7–07–0–0)
Sebastian had the aim of completing the book before the election. (Sebastian aimed to complete the book before the election.)
(6–8–01–0–1)
The subject had an airing at their last meeting. (They aired the subject at their last meeting.)
(6–8–02–0–1)
Sybil had an acquaintance with the procedure. (The lecturer acquainted Sybil with the procedure.)
11
11
111
111
111
111
As compared with the limited range of Structures 1 to 5, Structure 6 presents a vast array of different patterns. They all agree, however, in including an object or objoid, this being the place where the class of event is specified. The inclusion of an object or objoid means that the verb must be in the broadest sense transitive (i.e. monotransitive or ditransitive, etc.). This means that, while Structure 5, with its intransitive thin verbs (other than be) already has a dynamic meaning (see discussion at the end of section II.2.v), Structure 6 goes beyond this in having a dynamic meaning that somehow gives the impression of being goal-directed, positive, direct and/or decisive. Thus form an alliance with smbd seems more direct and positive than enter into an alliance with smbd (which in turn is more dynamic than be in alliance with smbd); similarly take action seems more decisive and complete than move into action (which is in turn more dynamic than be in action). The appearance of the eventive meaning (of the kindred simple verb) in valency object position in the stretched structure has certain syntactic implications: it becomes a candidate for subject position in a transformationally related passive sentence; it becomes a potential target for relative clause formation; etc. The following examples make these possibilities clear:
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
100 Syntactic restructuring (40) (a) (b) (b–x) (b–y)
Sebastian acted. Sebastian took action. Action was taken (by Sebastian). The action Sebastian took ( . . . ) was decisive.
The sentence (40)(a), as a simple intransitive structure, has no possibility of passivization, with the result that the valency subject, Sebastian, must be mentioned; equally, the verb is not a possible basis for relative clause formation. The sentence (40)(b), on the other hand, as a Structure 6 pattern, includes a noun phrase object action, which makes passivization and relative clause formation possible. The potential for passivization is particularly significant, because it permits suppression of subjects, as indicated by the parenthesis of (40)(b–x), thus permitting potentially undesirable information to go unmentioned. The structural diversity of Structure 6 is so wide as to make it difficult to summarize, but a primary division can be made into the subtypes suggested by the labelling system used. All of the (6–1) subvarieties can be regarded as variations on the theme of (6–1–01–0–0) S/s + V/ø + O/v (kindred with S + V), i.e. the combination of thin verb and eventive noun object, with the noun phrase of the subject of the kindred eventive verb retained in subject position, as illustrated by the examples of (39) (6–1–01–0–0) right through to (6–1–31–0–0). The differences between these forty-eight subvarieties partly represent different starting points in terms of the valency patterns of the kindred lexical verb; there seem to seventeen or eighteen different valency structures involved. But it is also a matter of different ways of coping with the problem of stretching a verb valency structure. Having a thin verb, with the specification of the class of event shifted to object position, means that there is often a surplus semantic role to accommodate in the stretched verb structure, most commonly the kindred simplex object. Consider, for instance, the restructuring involved in (39) (6–1–01–0–0), (6–1–01–0–2) and (6–1–02–0–0): the first of these is based on an intransitive verb and therefore there is no kindred simplex object to take care of; the second simply suppresses the kindred simplex object; the third, having its object position already filled by the eventive role, places the kindred simplex object (most frequently with a patient or ‘affected’ role) in indirect object position, with the result that the thin verb must be trivalent (e.g. give, cause). If, on the other hand, beside the direct object in the kindred simplex pattern, there already exists an indirect object, then this has no obvious place to go in the stretched structure. With some minor exceptions, three elaborators (the subject and two others, e.g. object and indirect object) is the normal maximum number of elaborators for lexical verbs, whether in simplex or stretched constructions. It is therefore unsurprising to find subvarieties like (6–1–03–0–2) and (6–1–05–0–2) in which the kindred simplex object is dropped, apparently because the superficial indirect object position is already occupied
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of restructuring 101 and the superficial object position already filled by the kindred simplex verb. The restructuring involved in subvarieties (6–1–12–0–0) to (6–1–25–1–0) introduces an important additional dimension, which we have already noted for Structures 3, 4 and 5, that of prepositional and genitival qualifiers. These subconstituents arise through the process of incorporation, by which otherwise independently expressed semantic roles are downgraded to become qualifiers in the noun phrase that has as its head a deverbal noun expressing the eventive role. In Structure 6 this noun phrase is the object or objoid; so we are now considering qualifiers, which in the kindred simple structure would have been independent elaborators of the verb, but which now appear inside the object (or objoid) noun phrase. In (6–1–12–0–0), for instance, the kindred simplex object, finding the object position in the stretched structure to be already occupied by the eventive role, attaches itself to the object as a prepositional qualifier. Thus in example sentence (39) (6–1–12–0–0) to the volume is not an elaborator of the (thin) verb make but has been incorporated as a qualifier of the deverbal noun adjustment in object position and is therefore a subconstituent. The same point applies to the genitival qualifiers of (6–1–25–0–0) and (6–1–25–1–0), and also of (6–2–05–0–0), (6–2–06–0–1), (6–4–02–0–0), (6–6–06–0–5), (6–6–07–0–0) and (6–6–08–0–0); and in these cases the downgrading of the preposition phrase is made even clearer by the possible ‘possessive ’s’ form (e.g. arouse smbd’s anger rather than arouse the anger of smbd). Moreover the infinitival, gerundial and finite clause complements (IC, GC and FC) of (6–1–26–0–0) to (6–1–31–0–0) as well as (6–7–06–0–0) and (6–7–07–0–0) agree in being attached to the object/objoid noun phrase as subconstituents, although they need not undergo any outward change in form. The restructurings of type (6–2) involve a more radical reassignment of functions, formulaically: v ⇒ O; o ⇒ S; s ⇒ Ø or PÖ or GQ. This means that they combine nominalization of the verb with a kind of lexical passivization, as illustrated by the examples (39) (6–2–01–0–1) to (6–2–05–0–0). As previously noted, it can be argued that such stretched structures should be linked to the passive form of the verb rather than to the active: thus feel alarm of (39) (6–2–02–0–0) could be related to be alarmed rather than to the more basic alarm (VERB). But there is no sign that feel alarm is GRAMMATICALLY passive: it has no verb be, no past participle, and it is incapable of expansion with an agentive by-phrase. Once again then it seems preferable to see the stretched verb structures of (6–2–01–0–1) to (6–2–05–0–0) as achieving a similar semantic effect to passivization, but through LEXICAL means. A similar view can be taken of the subvarieties listed under (6–3), (6–4) and (6–5): in these cases it is the indirect object or the prepositional object or objoid respectively that appears as the subject of the stretched verb construction. Again the kindred simple subject is in some cases dropped
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
102 Syntactic restructuring (i.e. realized as Ø), in some cases realized as a prepositional objoid (PÖ), and in some cases realized as a genitive qualifier (GQ). The subvarieties of (6–6) represent a still further dimension of grammatical restructuring, that of adding a further actor in the semantic role of causer of the whole activity represented by the kindred simplex complemented verb structure. Comparing the stretched construction and the simple construction of (39) (6–6–05–0–0), for instance, we find that the kindred simplex syntactic functions have been reassigned in the stretched structures as follows: v ⇒ O; o ⇒
74 I am grateful to Richard Matthews for highlighting this point for me.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of restructuring 103 As regards the range of Structure 6 constructions found with a phrasal verb, it seems largely to mimic the range of subvarieties with a simple thin verb (e.g. (6–1–01–1–0) mimics (6–1–01–0–0)), except that the rarer varieties are not found. The only other difference is that the corresponding ( . . . – . . . – . . . . . . –1– . . . ) type structure has the closely cohesive limiter adverb bound to the thin verb. This limiter adverb can nevertheless be looked at as an independent element in the elaborated verb structure as a whole. If we analyse the resultant structures of (6–1–01–1–0) etc. in this light, placing the limiter adverb (L) in its more basic position, we come up with the following list (ignoring subconstituents like prepositional qualifiers): (6–1–01–1–0) S+V+O+L
(commonly appearing as S + V-L + O)
(6–1–01–1–2) S+V+O+L
(commonly appearing as S + V-L + O)
(6–1–10–1–2) S + V + O + L + PÖ (commonly appearing as S + V-L + O) (6–1–11–1–0) S + V + O + L + AE (commonly appearing as S + V-L + O + AE) (6–1–12–1–0) S+V+O+L
(commonly appearing as S + V-L + O)
(6–1–16–1–0) S+V+O+L
(commonly appearing as S + V-L + O)
(6–1–18–1–0) S+V+O+L
(commonly appearing as S + V-L + O)
(6–1–25–1–0) S+V+O+L
(commonly appearing as S + V-L + O)
(6–1–28–1–0) S+V+O+L
(commonly appearing as S + V-L + O)
The above list shows how, even with the inclusion of a limiter adverb, the overall pattern of elaborated verb structures for stretched verb constructions remains within the usual framework demanded by normal lexical verbs (cf. the list in Table 2.1 in section II.1.ii). This compliance is partly achieved through the dropping of a kindred simplex object and partly through the ‘annexation’ of an object or a prepositional object or objoid, or, in the case of (6–1–18–1–0), through a double annexation. Finally, for Structure 6, let us consider the range of subvarieties from the perspective of how the different kindred simple structures appear in their different possible stretched forms. Beginning with the simple structure
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
104 Syntactic restructuring /s + v\, a relatively rare basic verb structure (because few totally uncomplemented verbs exist), we find unsurprisingly that this basic form of Structure 6 appears as S/s + V/ø + O/v, with S/s + V-L/ø + O/v as an occasional alternative. (The fact that our data only include four or five examples of the first type and only one of the second casts doubt on the view that is sometimes expressed that stretched verb constructions are largely used to give a simple intransitive verb more weight.) A more fertile field for study is the /s + v + o\ simplex structure, which appears to underlie no less than nineteen different stretched verb structures. These structures differ from each other in what realizations they provide for the subject and the object. The standard (‘active’) pattern is for the kindred simplex subject to retain its subject function, in which case the object, as we have just noted, has the possibilities of being dropped or of appearing as an indirect object, a prepositional objoid, or as prepositional or genitival qualifier. Of these different possibilities the kindred simplex object appears as an indirect object in five examples, as a prepositional objoid in twelve examples, and as a prepositional qualifier in thirty-six examples; so the latter is clearly the major pattern. In ‘passive’ stretched verb versions of /s + v + o\ the kindred simple object appears in subject position, which leaves roughly the same possibilities for the kindred simple subject as for the kindred simple object in ‘active’ stretched structures of this type: thus the kindred simple subject either is dropped or appears as a prepositional objoid or (in one case only) as a genitival qualifier. In the ‘causative’ versions of /s + v + o\ the superficial subject position is already taken by the external causer, and the superficial object position is (as usual) already taken by the kindred lexical verb, which leaves the kindred simple subject and object to compete for other superficial functions. In the three subvarieties attested both subject and object of the kindred simple structure appear on the surface as prepositional objoid \PÖ/, whereas only the kindred simple subject appears as indirect object \IO/ or genitival qualifier \
11
11
11
111
Types of restructuring 105 ones with the kindred simple subject retained in subject position, the kindred simplex object is dropped in both cases, a phenomenon we have come across regularly. The indirect object, on the other hand, in one case retains its position and in the other appears as a prepositional objoid. In the ‘passive’ examples it is the underlying indirect object that is ‘promoted’ to subject position in the stretched structure, while the kindred simplex object is dropped. Thus of the three elaborator functions, subject, object and indirect object, there is no doubt that it is the object that is most likely to be dropped or downgraded. This may well be because the object has the greatest chance of being non-human. The kindred simplex structure /s + v + o + pö\ appears in fifteen different stretched structures. Both its subject and its object are in some cases dropped, in some cases annexed by the eventive object, and in some cases shifted to indirect object position; moreover the prepositional objoid is sometimes retained and sometimes dropped, while only the object can be shifted to subject position in ‘passive’ stretched structures. Overall stretched structures give great flexibility to this basic pattern, although the choice of possibilities is severely limited by the lexical choice of individual kindred simple verb. Thus assign smth to smbd, allocate smth to smbd and appropriate smth for smbd all give rise to different subvarieties of stretched structure, namely \S + V + O + IO/ (give an assignment to smbd/give smbd an assignment), \S + V + O
111
II.2.vii General trends of restructuring Having surveyed the diversity of restructuring exhibited by all Structures, and contrasted each with with simplex eventive verb structures, we are entitled to ask what purpose such restructuring potential serves and why a language needs it. If we ask ourselves a similar question about a transformational restructuring like passivization, we might sum up one possible answer as follows, at least so far as it applies to examples like those of (41):
111
111
(41) (a) Sebastian kissed/liked Olga. (b) Olga was kissed/liked (by Sebastian). English passivization, in the first place, shifts the noun phrase Olga, the object in (41)(a) to subject position in (41)(b), with the result that its semantic
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
106 Syntactic restructuring role (‘goal’, more specifically ‘affected’ or ‘mental focus’ etc.) is made thematic, in the sense that it comes to represent the viewpoint from which the eventuality under examination (Sebastian’s kissing/liking of Sybil) is described; in the second place, English passivization shifts the kindred simple subject, the noun phrase Sebastian, to the position of perject,75 with the result that its semantic role (‘agent’, ‘mental processor’, etc.) is made more peripheral to the sentence and can be left unmentioned. In passivization, finally, the originally active verb retains its status as verb, although its passive form (be kissed/liked) is an indication of the shifting of roles that has taken place and can even be seen as a representing a redirecting of the action or process. Seen in such a light, the syntactic restructurings involved in stretched verb constructions have equally important effects. In all cases the most dramatic effect is on the semantic role carried by the underlying verb, i.e. the ‘(class of) event’. As we noted in II.1.ii this appears as an Adjectival Descriptor in Structure 1, as a Nominal Descriptor in Structures 2 and 3, as a Prepositional Descriptor in Structure 4, as a Prepositional Object (or Objoid) in Structure 5, and as an Object (or Objoid) in Structure 6. In all cases except Structure 1, therefore, it has the form of a noun phrase, although in Structures 4 and 5 this is incorporated into a preposition phrase. Semantically, this nominalization of the underlying verb may to some extent have the effect of ‘reifying’ (= ‘turning an event or quality into a thing’) the eventive meaning on the basis of its reassignment to the class NOUN. But it seems that grammatical function may have a greater effect on the meaning: the Nominal Descriptors of Structures 2 and 3 suggest a role, characteristic, quality or state that is being ascribed to the Subject; the Prepositional Descriptor of Structure 4 has a similar effect, but perhaps hinting at a less substantial or more temporary quality or state; the same applies to the Prepositional Object/Objoid of Structure 5, which often refers to the beginning or end of such states; finally, the Object/Objoid of Structure 6 most clearly reifies or ‘objectifies’ the event and suggests that some (secondary) activity is directed towards this event. Almost as significant as the syntactic siting of the semantic role of ‘(class of) event’ is the restructuring of the kindred simplex subjects, objects, etc. In the ‘active’ versions of Structure 3 the underlying object or prepositional object is often annexed by the eventive object (as a prepositional qualifier) and thus automatically becomes optional; this means that it is downgraded in importance, cf. abuse smbd (where the object is obligatorily present) with be an abuser (of smbd) or be an abuse of smth (where the prepositional qualifier can be dropped). In the ‘passive’ version of Structure 3, on the other hand, it is the kindred simplex subject that is converted to the status of prepositional qualifier or in some cases is not permitted 75 or ‘agent phrase’. The term ‘perject’ was introduced in section II.1.i.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of restructuring 107 to surface at all, while the kindred simplex object, prepositional objoid or adverbial elaborator is thrust into the limelight of subject position, where it achieves thematic status. The construction be an addition to smth, for instance, produces this effect for the underlying object of the verb add. It is interesting to note that three different statuses (in terms of centrality/ marginality) can be observed for the kindred simplex subject in such cases: in the simplex active it is of course obligatory, in the simplex passive (in the form of a perject, i.e. agentive by-phrase) it is optional, and in the ‘passive’ stretched Structure 3 it is prohibited. Structure 4 is similar in that its ‘active’ version requires an underlying object or prepositional objoid to be downgraded to a prepositional qualifier or dropped altogether, while its ‘passive’ version shifts the kindred simplex object to subject position and dispenses with the underlying subject (cf. the ‘active’ be of assistance (to smbd) and the ‘passive’ be under arrest). Structure 5 has an active variety in which the kindred simplex subject stays put and in some cases the object does too, but the expansion of the verb into a combination of (thin) verb and prepositional objoid can have the effect of changing the syntactic function of other elements: thus while fill smbd with alarm represents an expansion of alarm without reassignment of subject or object, burst into applause at smth has a prepositional objoid for the underlying object of applaud smth. The passive version naturally has the underlying object or prepositional object as surface subject with the original subject either appearing as a genitive qualifier, or simply being dropped (cf. meet with sm acceptance, meet with smbd’s approval/the approval of smbd). The ‘causative’ version of Structure 5, as illustrated by call smbd to account for smth, has a subject that is not present in the kindred simple structure (in this case account for smth) giving, in the chain reaction: x → S, s → O, po → PÖ; all this, in addition to v → PÖ, means a total restructuring, giving a whole new set of semantic perspectives. The most wide-ranging restructurings of all are found in Structure 6. The restructurings found in the major versions of this Structure are now summarized in Figure 2.1. In the ‘active’ version, then, the underlying subject remains in place, but, with the kindred simplex verb taking up object position, some shifts are required in the non-subject elaborators; moreover various reassignments between object, indirect object and prepositional object and objoid are found, one of the options being for the underlying object to be dropped. The alternative possibility for the object is downgrading to prepositional qualifier, an option found in many subvarieties of this pattern (e.g. make an analysis of smth beside analyse smth). In the ‘passive’ subvarieties of Structure 6, on the other hand, the kindred simplex object or prepositional object is promoted to subject position, while the kindred simplex subject has the main possibilities of either shifting to prepositional objoid position, being downgraded to genitive qualifier or simply being dropped. Finally the ‘causative’ versions of Structure 6 (which are not represented in Figure 2.1), like those
108 Syntactic restructuring
1
1
Structure 6 ‘active’ S
V
O,Ö
IO
AD, ND, PD
PO
PÖ
AE, Avl
s
v
o,ö
io
ad, nd, pd
po
pö
ae, avl
Structure 6 ‘passive’
1 S
V
O,Ö
IO
AD, ND, PD
PO
PÖ
AE, Avl
s
v
o,ö
io
ad, nd, pd
po
pö
ae, avl
11
11
11
11
Figure 2.1 Syntactic restructuring.
of Structure 5, involve a series of demotions, with the difference that the underlying subject cannot be demoted to object because that position is already filled by the verb; it therefore appears as an indirect object or as a prepositional objoid. Apart from the re-siting of syntactic semantic roles that is summarized in Figure 2.1, there is one further possible structural difference between a stretched verb construction and its kindred simplex structure that still needs to be considered, namely the obligatoriness or optionality of the constituents. If a given semantic element (such as the agent, or the recipient) is expressed by different structural elements (such as subject, perject, indirect object) in the two structures, this is bound to have repercussions for optionality, because while subjects and verbs are obligatory, objects, for instance, are often optional or even prohibited, prepositional objoids usually freely suppressible, etc. Structure (6–1–01–0–2), for instance, has the form S/s + V/ø + O/v (+ Ø/o), which means that the simplex structure has an object that in some cases is obligatory (e.g. in appease smbd), whereas the stretched structure (e.g. practise appeasement) has no possibility of mentioning the ‘affected’ person. In Structure (6–1–02–0–0), with the form S/s + V/ø + O/v + IO/o, on the other hand, the possibly obligatory object of the simplex structure (as address smbd, articulate smth) can be represented in the stretched construction by an indirect object
11
11
11
Types of restructuring 109 which is either contextually deletable (as give an address [to smbd] ) or obligatory (as in give articulation to smth). Clearly when there is a radical restructuring, as in patterns of the semantically ‘passive’ type, the optionality status of elements is bound to be affected: thus in pattern (6–2–02–0–0), of the form S/o + V/ø + O/v + PÖ/s, a simplex structure like abuse smbd, with its obligatory subject and object, contrasts with take sm abuse (from smbd), with its freely omissible prepositional objoid, meaning that the ‘abuser’ can but need not be mentioned. Each stretched verb construction thus consists of a sequence of grammatical elements characterized by obligatoriness or a type of optionality partly on the basis of grammatical rules (e.g. ‘Subjects are obligatory’) but partly specified individually for the individual construction. The optionality characteristics of such constructions may indeed be one reason for the speaker to prefer one construction over another. Summing up, amongst the diverse possibilities for syntactic restructuring in all Structures 3, 4, 5 and 6, the following general trends can be discerned: •
111
The eventive meaning of the kindred simple verb appears as an Adjectival Descriptor, a Nominal Descriptor, a Prepositional Descriptor, a Prepositional Object/Objoid or an Object/Objoid, giving a range of different semantic slants. The appearance of the eventive meaning in Object or Prepositional Object position allows passivization and consequently the possibility of leaving the agent unmentioned, a possibility not available to simple intransitive verbs. There can be substantial reassignments amongst the non-subject elaborators, such as object and prepositional objoid, often with the effect that obligatory elaborators become omissible (either contextually or in an indefinite sense, cf. II.1.iii above) or vice versa, meaning that individual elaborators can become foregrounded or backgrounded. Semantic roles like ‘agent’, ‘affected goal’, ‘recipient’, can have different grades of (non-)omissibility in their new syntactic functions. There is a general weakening of the object in ‘active’ sentences, so that it is either downgraded to a subconstituent or dropped. ‘Passive’ structures promote the object (to subject position) and give the possibilities of dropping the subject or demoting it (to prepositional objoid position) or downgrading it (to genitival qualifier position). There is the possibility in ‘causative’ subvarieties of introducing an external causer in subject position and consequently demoting all other elements.
111
All these possibilities for restructuring clearly provide one important motivation for the existence of stretched verb constructions, in that they allow the basic information of a sentence to be presented from a whole set of different perspectives.
111 •
•
111 • • • •
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
110 Syntactic restructuring Finally, let us note that stretched verb constructions are not alone in their capacity for syntactic restructuring: passivization, empty reflexives and phrasal verbs also have a part to play in this field. Consider briefly the following different ways in which the compulsorily transitive verb show can be adapted to be used without a (lexically full) object: PASSIVE EMPTY REFLEXIVE PHRASAL VERB STRETCHED VERB CONSTRUCTION
be shown show itself (etc.) show up be on show
Of these possibilities, the passive is purely syntactic and preserves all the semantic possibilities of the basic verb, but the other three all form new but related lexical items; in other words, they are grammatical patterns serving to extend the lexicon. This will be explored further in Part V.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Part III
The event phrase
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
11
III.1 Eventive and agentive noun phrases: their core
11
11
111
111
111
111
III.1.i Eventive nouns: their mode of derivation, semantic value and status Stretched verb structures all centre around a noun phrase or an adjective phrase that carries the ‘eventive’ meaning borne by the verb in a simple verb structure but ‘ejected’ from it, to use the terminology of Allerton (1982: 130–1), leaving a thin verb behind. The majority of stretched verb structures (Structures 3, 4, 5 and 6) all centre around a noun phrase that carries the ‘eventive’ meaning. In the case of Structures 4 and 5 the noun phrase that is the new home for the ‘eventive’ meaning, is, of course, embedded in a preposition phrase. Structure 2 has an agentive noun phrase, in which the event is only implicitly mentioned, and Structure 1 has an agentive adjective phrase, which is similar in this respect. It seems natural therefore to concentrate first of all on eventive noun phrases. The head noun of such noun phrases is derivationally related to the kindred simple verb, in the sense that is morphologically derived from it by suffixation or some other formal process. Thus the noun appearance of make an appearance is morphologically derived from the verb stem appear; similarly, the noun action of take action is derived from act. Since different deverbal nominalizing suffixes are used for this purpose, the question obviously arises whether the choice of suffix or other mode of derivation makes any difference to the meaning of the deverbal noun and thus presumably to the stretched verb construction as a whole. A full list of the deverbal nouns found in our sample, classified according to their mode of derivation, is given in Table 3.1. Let us now briefly consider the semantic contribution of these different suffixes, etc., paying close attention to the account given by Marchand (1969: 234–7, 248–9, 259–61, 302–4, 331–2, 350–1, 352–3, 359–89). We need to bear in mind throughout that derivational formatives like -ance and -ion have a certain semantic diffuseness, often involving polysemy, with the result that their global meanings are very unlikely to match perfectly. In Marchand’s view (1969: 214–15) nouns derived from verbs through affixation and/or compounding fall into different types according
1
1
1
11
11
114 The event phrase Table 3.1 Modes of derivation of eventive deverbal nouns Suffixation with -age
Suffixation with -ion
APPENDAGE
ABORTION ACTION ADJUDICATION ADMISSION ‘confession’ ADMISSION ‘entrance’ AFFILIATION AGGLOMERATION AGGRAVATION AGGRESSION AGITATION ALIENATION ALLOCATION ALLUSION ALTERNATION AMALGAMATION ANNIHILATION ANNOTATION APPRECIATION APPROPRIATION ARBITRATION ASSASSINATION ASSERTION ASSIMILATION ASSOCIATION ATTRACTION
Suffixation with -al ACQUITTAL APPRAISAL APPROVAL AVOWAL
Suffixation with -ance/-ence ABSTINENCE ABUNDANCE ACCEPTANCE ACQUAINTANCE ADMITTANCE ALLIANCE ALLOWANCE ANNOYANCE APPEARANCE ASSISTANCE ASSURANCE ‘promising’ ASSURANCE ‘financial protection’ ATTENDANCE ‘being present’ ATTENDANCE ‘waiting, service’
Suffixation with-ation/ -ition/-ution/-tion ABSOLUTION ACCLIMATIZATION ACCUSATION ACQUISITION ADAPTATION ADDITION AFFECTATION AFFIRMATION ALLEGATION ALTERATION APPLICATION ‘effort’ APPLICATION ‘request’ APPLICATION ‘use’ ASPIRATION/S ASSUMPTION ATTENTION ‘concentration’ AUTHORIZATION
11
11
Suffixation with -ing ACTING AIRING AWAKENING
Suffixation with -is ANALYSIS
Suffixation with -ment ABRIDGEMENT ACCOMPANIMENT ACHIEVEMENT ACKNOWLEDGEMENT ADJUSTMENT ADVERTISEMENT AGREEMENT AILMENT ALIGNMENT AMAZEMENT AMENDMENT AMUSEMENT ANNOUNCEMENT ANNULMENT APPEASEMENT APPOINTMENT ‘job’ ARGUMENT ‘quarrel’ ARGUMENT ‘rationale’ ARRANGEMENT ‘agreement’ ARRANGEMENT ‘plan’
11
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 115 Table 3.1 (continued) ARRANGEMENTS ASSESSMENT ASSIGNMENT ASTONISHMENT ATONEMENT
‘details’
Suffixation with -ure –
11
Loss of suffix –
11
Replacement of suffix with -ia
111
111
111
111
ANAESTHESIA
Replacement of suffix with -ity AUTHORITY
Replacement of suffix with -y AGONY APOLOGY
Final consonant replacement ABUSE ADVICE APPLAUSE ASCENT
Vowel change – Stress shift
Zero ACCESS ACCLAIM ACCORD ACCOUNT ACHE ACT ‘deed ACT ‘performance’ ADDRESS ‘place of abode’ ADDRESS ‘speech’ ADVANCE ADVANTAGE AFFRONT AID ‘help’1 AIM ‘direction of shooting’ AIM ‘purpose’ AIR ALARM ANGER ANSWER APPEAL ‘attraction’ APPEAL ‘plea’ APPEAL ‘request for adjudication’ APPROACH ARGUE ARREST ASSAULT ASSENT ATTACK ATTEMPT AVERAGE AWARD
Note: 1 Phonologically identical with aide ‘helper’, an agentive noun.
to which ‘aspect’ of the sentence (centring on the verb) they represent: these types would include ‘subject’ (e.g. examiner), ‘object’ (e.g. examinee), ‘adverbial complement’ (e.g. examination room) and, perhaps most importantly, ‘predication’ (e.g. examining, examination). This last type would seem to retain the purely eventive meaning of the verb and thus correspond to the traditional nomen actionis, the deverbal noun in its purest sense, and may be seen as providing a link between the other meanings. This is also the view of Magnusson and Persson (1986: 2–4, 35–8), who refer to the individual related meanings (e.g. employer and employee) as ‘facets’ and the relation between them as ‘categorial hyponymy’; denominal verbs which incorporate such a semantic role into their meaning are then said to function in a particular ‘phase’, e.g. the verb pocket (of pocket the money,
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
116 The event phrase etc.) in the Locative phase, the verb pod (of pod the peas, etc.) in the Source phase. For the suffix -age, for instance, which is added to both noun and verb stems (or ‘bases’), Marchand (1969: 234–6) gives meanings like ‘liberty to do smth, right to smth, toll for smth’ (e.g. stowage), ‘condition, state, rank, office of being smth’ (e.g. peerage), ‘abode of smbd’ (e.g. hermitage), ‘collectivity, system, material of smth’ (e.g. baggage), ‘charge, fee for smth’ (e.g. postage), ‘place of doing smth’ (e.g. anchorage), ‘item that is affected by a process’ (e.g. package), ‘item that results from a process’ (e.g. breakage) and, last but not least, ‘act, fact, mode of doing smth’ (e.g. leakage). It is true that only the last four senses are consistently related to verbs, but even they demonstrate a range of meaning that may give rise to semantic imprecision, and even ambiguity. If, however, we take the last sense, which can be called ‘eventive’, as the core meaning, we can see this as relating the other meanings (‘item affected by a process’, ‘place of a process’, etc.) to the underlying meaning of the verb. The noun shrinkage, for instance, has, as one of its meanings ‘the process of shrinking’; as a second sense, it can also mean ‘extent of the process of shrinking’. The noun wastage (cf. also the zero-derived form waste) can mean either ‘the process of wasting’ or ‘material that results from the process of wasting’. A question we shall have to ask is what kind of meaning such deverbal nouns have when they occur in stretched verb combinations like suffer shrinkage or cause wastage/waste. The only example of the suffix -age in our corpus is the word appendage, and it appears only in the combination add an appendage to smth. Considered on its own, the word appendage would seem to have a meaning that is concrete, namely ‘a thing that has been or will be appended’. The expression add an appendage to smth can therefore be understood quite literally to mean ‘add something to be appended to something’. But if we now consider the potential meaning of a non-existent stretched verb construction of the form *do an appending of smth to smth, then as far as can be judged, this would have a meaning that is barely distinguishable from add an appendage to smth. The suffix -al is represented by stretched verb constructions (such as bring in an acquittal, make an appraisal of smth) based on the deverbal nouns acquittal, appraisal, approval and avowal. There is little doubt about the ‘eventive’ sense of these nouns formed with -al (and things are no different in the case of deverbal nouns in -al in general,76 cf. betrayal, betrothal, committal, denial, dismissal, disposal, proposal, recital, removal, survival, upheaval, withdrawal); in fact, they only have a related concrete meaning in a limited number of cases, often where the underlying verb refers to a speech act and the noun refers to a document incorporating the written version of this (e.g. denial, proposal).
76 not all of which necessarily occur in stretched verb constructions.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 117 The deverbal suffix -ance/-ence also has a mainly ‘eventive’ sense in the twelve nouns in our data (abstinence, acceptance, acquaintance, admittance, etc., cf. also from Marchand’s general list: adherence, clearance, compliance, conveyance, dependence, deterrence, endurance, entrance, guidance, performance, remembrance, repentance, resemblance, resistance). Marchand describes the general meaning of the suffix as ‘state, act, fact of doing smth’, and expresses the view that ‘hardly any other senses than ‘act’ and ‘action’ occur’ (1969: 249). But amongst our group of -ance/-ence words abstinence, acceptance and annoyance can also denote a mental state induced by the act; acquaintance and alliance can (in slightly different senses) denote a person who is the goal of the act, while appearance can also refer to the manner of the act. The lists of Table 3.1 distinguish formations in -ation/-ition/-ution/-tion (namely absolution, acclimatization, accusation, acquisition, etc. with a total of fifteen nouns.) from those in -ion (namely abortion, action, adjudication, admission, etc. with a total of twenty-four nouns, one with two senses) on the basis that the first group adds the suffix /-ʃən/, usually preceded by a vowel or diphthong, whereas the second group simply adds /-jən/ (sometimes to a stem ending in /-t/, giving rise to a phonetic sequence /-ʃən/). (Cases in which the verbs ends in -ate and the derived noun ends in -ation are naturally assumed to involve the suffix -ion.) Marchand in fact treats both groups together77 giving further examples in his general list like accumulation, civilization, colonization, contemplation, education, expectation, fertilization, flirtation, formalization, glorification, identification, information, magnification, moderation, modification, neutralization, organization, pacification, restoration, starvation, taxation, temptation, translation, verification. As for the meaning of -ation/-ition/ution/-tion and -ion, Marchand declares that ‘-ation falls into the group of impersonal deverbal substantives with their various meanings (see especially -ment)’ (1969: 261). Turning then to -ment itself, we find this represented in our list by some twenty-two deverbal nouns (abridgement, accompaniment, achievement, acknowledgement, etc.), with a total of twenty-five senses, which can be compared with examples like bereavement, bewilderment, embarrassment, development, endorsement, engagement, equipment, fulfilment, involvement, management, measurement, puzzlement, retirement, settlement, statement, treatment in Marchand’s general list. In his view -ment, just like -ation/-ition/-ution/-tion and -ion can have any of the four ‘usual’ meanings of deverbal nouns, which are roughly ‘the act or fact of doing smth’ (the ‘eventive’ sense, e.g. development), ‘smth concrete or material connected with the process’ (e.g. equipment), ‘the state resulting from the process’ (e.g. embarrassment) and ‘the place connected with the process’ (e.g. settlement). But it is not simply a matter of four separate meanings. Taking the ‘eventive’ meaning again as central, we can see that
77 having first distinguished them, as well as separating off -ation after -iz- and after -ific-. But he seems to ignore the forms -ition and -ution.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
118 The event phrase although in some cases this is the only meaning of the noun (as in enactment), in most cases one of the other meanings is also present, so that embarrassment and settlement, for example, have the ‘eventive’ meaning alongside the ‘state’ and ‘place’ meanings, and development has an additional ‘product’ meaning beyond the ‘eventive’ meaning. Moreover, some words, like equipment, have only a secondary meaning; the corresponding primary meaning (in this case ‘act of equipping’) is no longer found. The minor suffixes -ia (of anaesthesia), -is (of analysis), -ity (of authority), -y (of agony, apology) and -ure (not found in our data but in examples like departure, failure) do not seem to throw up any meanings or constellations of meanings not so far discussed. In a way, the most interesting ‘lesser’ suffix is -ing, which mainly appears as the inflectional suffix used to form the gerund (or present participle) of a verb, but which is listed in Table 3.1 as a derivational suffix for the words acting, airing and awakening. The gerund is of course the classic nomen actionis, and naturally has an ‘eventive’ meaning. It is therefore remarkable that it is used so little in stretched verb constructions, the only representatives in our sample being do/indulge in sm acting, give smth an airing, get/have an airing and suffer an awakening. It seems that the simple nomen actionis meaning of ‘act, process, etc. of V-ing’ is involved in all cases, but it is worth noting that whereas acting denotes the act or process of (dramatic) acting in general, the other two nouns, airing and awakening, refer to one specific instance of the act and are therefore countable nouns. The most important remaining way of forming deverbal nouns is zeroderivation, of which twenty-six phonologically distinct examples (access, acclaim, accord, account, ache, etc.) appear in our list (with polysemy in address, act and appeal giving a total of thirty-one different senses). Marchand’s lists of deverbal nouns formed without a clear suffix (i.e. by zero-derivation, final consonant replacement or stress shift) also include the following: bark, belief, bite, burst, buy, call, challenge, chat, collapse, control, cough, delight, desire, doubt, drive, escape, fall, feel, grunt, halt, hate, hiss, hunt, increase, jump, laugh, leap, look, love, moan, nod, promise, push, retreat, ride, ring, rise, run, scream, search, smell, smile, smoke, stay, swim, talk, twist, wait, walk, yawn. With such a wide range of zero-derived deverbal nouns, it is not surprising to find a wide variety of different meanings; indeed, the lack of any overt affix (each associated with a more particular meaning) may even be an encouragement to semantic instability. There can be little doubt that the ‘eventive’ meaning is basic, but it appears in more than one variety: the general meaning ‘process of V-ing’, as represented in our sample by aid, but also to be seen in sleep, talk and work, is found only in a limited number of words referring to physical activities, most of which prefer to express this with the gerund (e.g. acting, arguing); for most zero-derived deverbal nouns with such a meaning we can agree with Marchand that ‘the sense most often implied is that of “single instance illustrative of the active process”’(1969: 374). This means that, unlike nouns in -ing, which are mostly simply (underived)
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 119 gerunds and therefore uncountable (with odd exceptions, like those mentioned in the previous paragraph), nouns taking the form simply of the bare stem of the verb are mostly countable. Of the long list cited from Marchand, for instance, only control, delight, desire, doubt and love have an ‘eventive’ sense that is uncountable, and even this has a partly mental meaning; most of them accord with Marchand’s statement, e.g. an act, an advance, an affront, an aim (or, from his list, a bite, a burst, a call, a collapse).78 Verbs referring to mental processes behave rather differently in that they generally do offer zero-derived uncountable nouns with the meaning ‘process of V-ing’ in a general sense, examples being accord, alarm and appeal (or, from Marchand’s list, belief (with final consonant replacement), desire, dislike). Most of these also have a countable use, meaning ‘particular instance of V-ing’, e.g. an accord, an appeal (or a belief, etc.); indeed some of them are limited to a countable use, e.g. an affront. It is a small step from the meaning(s) ‘(single instance of) the mental process of V-ing’ to the meaning ‘mental state resulting form V-ing or being V-ed’; and this meaning is found in zero-derived deverbal nouns like alarm, anger (cf. also shock, surprise), which are generally uncountable, needing a measure word to make them countable, cf. (show) some anger, (have) a fit of anger. Nouns formed from verbs denoting physical activities can have an equivalent meaning ‘physical (and mental) state resulting from V-ing or being V-ed’, as in arrest (also boycott, display) as used in be under arrest (or be subject to a boycott, be on display). A related meaning is found in expressions like (have) a velvety feel, (have) a nasty smell (of drains), where the noun is derived from a sensory verb (feel, smell, etc.), which would normally take an adjectival descriptor or prepositional objoid as part of its valency; the meaning of the noun is something like ‘condition V-ed’, so that have a velvety feel means ‘have a condition perceived (through the act of feeling) to be like velvet’. A further meaning that is semantically close to the one just discussed but syntactically distinct from it is that of ‘appearance of condition resulting from the manner of V-ing’, a meaning that more belongs to the field of manner adverbials than to the verb proper; it is found in Marchand’s examples cut (of a suit, etc.) and set (referring to hair). This leads us on to the pure manner adverbial meaning to be observed in Marchand’s examples bark, cough, grin and limp (meaning ‘manner of barking, etc.’) and probably in our example (have an) appeal ‘manner of appealing to smbd’. Other semantic developments of zero-derived deverbal nouns in an adverbial direction include time, place and distance/range. Marchand’s end, finish and start are ambiguous between time and place interpretations, but kick-off has only a temporal value (‘the time of kicking-off’) apart from 78 A further possibility for verbs denoting bodily activities is to have an uncountable plural used with the definite article meaning ‘nervous activity involving repetition of the acts’, e.g. (have) the jitters, (have) the shakes, etc.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
120 The event phrase its basic ‘single instance of the active process’. Words like access, approach (or bend, dump, lounge, stop, etc.), again apart from their ‘eventive’ interpretation, are in some sense locational in meaning (‘a place where V-ing takes place’). Examples like advance (also drop, overlap and sweep), however, usually seem to refer to range or distance rather than to pure location. An adverbial meaning that in a sense refers to a participant in the verbal action is that of ‘instrument for V-ing’; it is found in nouns like aid ‘thing used for aiding smbd’ (which occurs in the stretched verb construction be an aid), cf. also alarm; further examples in Marchand’s list include bait, clip, hoist, rattle and whistle. Since instruments can commonly be reinterpreted as inanimate agents, these examples could also be glossed as ‘thing that V-s’; in other words, they can be seen as occupying a subject position relative to the kindred verb (cf. Clips clip things beside People clip things with clips). Zero-derived deverbal nouns can also extend their meaning towards the valency object of the verb in question, giving a value of ‘person or thing that has been or will be V-ed’: examples offered by Marchand with a human object include convert, discard, pervert and plant, while, as examples for which the kindred verb has an inanimate object, we could cite award alongside brew, design, drink 79 and Marchand’s many other examples, with the effect that, for instance, convert means ‘person who has been or will be converted’ and award means ‘thing that has been or will be awarded’. Some of these zero-derived nouns suggest ‘affected’ objects (e.g. drink), some suggest ‘effected objects’ (e.g. design) and others are ambivalent (e.g. brew). Taking this meaning, give an award, for instance, can be interpreted literally as ‘give something to be awarded’; make an award, on the other hand, is more difficult to interpret with this ‘object-oriented’ meaning for award, and seems rather to require an ‘eventive’ interpretation ‘make/do an act of awarding’. Finally, Marchand points out that the meaning ‘person who V-s’ is found in two slightly differently types of zero-derived noun: in the first type, exemplified by coach, cook, judge, the noun refers to a person with a particular profession or occupation, who regularly carries out the activity, and the relationship to the verb is clearly that of subject, cf. A coach coaches people, etc.; in the second type the subjective or agentive meaning is less intentional and more a matter of the (usually censorious) judgement of others, as in bore, flirt, gossip, sneak, and such nouns are less likely to occur as subjects than as descriptors (i.e. predicatives or subject complements in traditional grammar), cf. Someone who is a bore bores people. Things can be a ‘bore’ just as well as people can; things that affront or delight people can also ‘be an affront’ or ‘be a delight’. In our study such agentive nouns, even though zero-derived, are placed alongside agentive nouns formed
79 Some words, e.g. catch, have a human and an inanimate object-oriented meaning (in addition to the ‘eventive’ meaning).
11
11
11
111
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 121 with the suffixes -er and -ist, and are treated under Structure 2, see section III.1.iii, below. It seems then that the range of meanings of deverbal nouns in general, whether derived by suffixation or by zero, covers a semantic range that extends from the process itself (whether generalized or a single instance) through connected time and place as far as instruments, agents and affected entities (= ‘patients’). In our data (limited as they are to words beginning with the letter A) the range of meanings seems to be slightly skewed, with some meanings apparently overrepresented. They are displayed in Table 3.2. Looking more specifically at stretched verb constructions, we find that the deverbal noun may have the basic ‘eventive’ meaning or one of these ‘facet’ meanings, but that in some cases the meaning is unclear. When the noun has only an ‘eventive’ interpretation, it seems natural for it to be partnered with a verb like perform (e.g. an abortion) or practise (e.g. abstinence) or carry out (e.g. an attack). But then how are we to understand make with an appearance, an ascent or an attack, or, for that matter, take with action? Such combinations seem to have a noun with a purely ‘eventive’ meaning but a verb that suggests the need for a noun denoting something created (in the case of make) or something that can be grasped (in the case of take); they must clearly have partly non-compositional meanings. On the other hand, nouns that really have developed a meaning ‘effected object arising from the verbal action’, e.g. make an abridgement, make an analysis, can be interpreted as having a literal compositional meaning that when taken holistically provides the required overall process meaning (cf. also the examples add an appendage to smth and give an award to smbd, discussed above). The most problematic of all deverbal nouns to interpret from the semantic (and also the grammatical) point of view are those involved in two rather special stretched verb constructions, namely:
111
111
111
(i) do some V-ing with the meaning ‘invest some time in the (useful) activity of V-ing’, e.g. do some cooking/thinking/weeding. (ii) have a V with the meaning ‘carry out a single, limited (but repeatable) act of V-ing’, e.g. have a look/shave/think. Doubts could be expressed as to whether these two structures are true stretched verb constructions on the grounds that, given the appropriate meaning in each case, they are formed with perfect regularity, removing the need to list them in a lexicon. This would mean that they were more like regular TRANSFORMED structures (like passives or cleft sentences) than the semi-irregular KINDRED structures that stretched verb structures were shown to be in Part I. But transformed structures (as defined there) do not effect changes between categories like noun and verb. So is the ‘deverbal noun’ in these cases a true noun? (See further V.1.ii below.) In the first structure (do some V-ing) the word based on the lexical
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
122 The event phrase Table 3.2 Additional semantic facets of eventive deverbal nouns Performer1 ACCOMPANIMENT
ALLOWANCE* AWARD
(‘income’)
(Mental) behaviour/attitude2
Service (for beneficiary)8
ABSTINENCE ABUSE* (‘abusing’) ACCEPTANCE* (‘accepting’) ACCORD AGITATION* (‘agitating’) AGGRESSION APPEASEMENT APPLICATION (‘effort’) APPRECIATION APPROVAL* (‘approving’) ATONEMENT
ADVANTAGE AID APPLAUSE ARBITRATION ASSISTANCE ASSURANCE (‘financial
protection’)
Mental focus (of performer)9
Mental experience3
ACQUAINTANCE AIM ‘direction of AIM ‘purpose’ ASPIRATION AVERAGE
AGONY AILMENT
Effected entity – General10
Mental effect4 ABSOLUTION ABUSE* (‘being abused’) ACCEPTANCE* (‘being accepted’) AFFRONT AGITATION* (‘being agitated’) ALIENATION AMAZEMENT AMUSEMENT ANAESTHESIA ANGER ANNOYANCE APPROVAL* (‘being approved’) ASTONISHMENT ATTRACTION* (‘being attracted’)
Physical effect5 ALTERATION* (‘altering effect’) ANNIHILATION
Affected entity (= ‘patient’)6 ACQUISITION ALTERATION* (‘altered item’) APPOINTMENT* (‘appointee’) ARREST (‘arrested person’) ATTACHMENT* (‘thing attached’)
Gift7 ADVANCE* (‘loan’) ALLOCATION ALLOTMENT* (‘share’)
shooting’
ABRIDGEMENT ACHIEVEMENT ACCORD ADAPTATION ADDITION ADVERTISEMENT AFFILIATION AGGLOMERATION AGREEMENT ALLIANCE AMENDMENT ANALYSIS ANNOTATION APPENDAGE APPOINTMENT* (‘job’) ARRANGEMENT ASSOCIATION
Effected speech act11 ACCUSATION ACKNOWLEDGEMENT ADDRESS* (‘speech’) ADJUDICATION ADMISSION* (‘confession’) ADVICE AFFIRMATION ALLEGATION ALLUSION ANNOUNCEMENT ANSWER APOLOGY APPEAL* (‘plea, complaint’)
11
11
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 123 Table 3.2 (continued) APPLICATION* (‘request’) APPRAISAL ASSENT ASSERTION ASSESSMENT ASSURANCE (‘promise’) AUTHORIZATION AVOWAL
Instrument12 ATTACHMENT*
(‘device for
111
111
111
ACCESS ADMISSION (‘admittance’) ADMITTANCE APPROACH
Degree/range16 ADJUSTMENT ADVANCE* (‘movement ALIGNMENT
forwards’)
attaching’) Location17 –
11
111
Path15
Mode/method13 APPLICATION* (‘use’) APPEAL* (‘attraction’) ATTRACTION (‘mode
Direction18 AIM* (‘targeting’) of attracting’) Reason19
Manner14
ARGUMENT*
(‘rationale’)
ACT ACTION APPEARANCE
Notes: * Noun with more than one interpretation. 1 Smbd who V-s (usually rendered by distinctive lexeme, often in -er or -ist). 2 Behaviour/attitude of smbd who V-s. 3 Experience of smbd who V-s. 4 Mental effect on smbd who is V-ed. 5 Physical effect on smbd/smth that is V-ed. 6 Smbd/smth that is V-ed (usually rendered by a distinctive lexeme, often in -ee). 7 Smth that is given. 8 Act performed for the benefit of smbd. 9 Smbd/smth towards which the mind of the performer is directed. 10 Smth other than a speech act effected, produced or created as a result of the activity of V-ing. 11 Speech act produced through the activity of V-ing. 12 Smth that is used for V-ing (usually rendered by a distinctive lexeme, often in -er). 13 Mode or method of V-ing. 14 Manner, way of V-ing. 15 Method by which or path along which V-ing is achieved. 16 Degree to which or range over which V-ing takes place. 17 Place where V-ing takes place. 18 Direction towards smth is V-ing. 19 Reason for which V-ing is carried out.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
124 The event phrase verb (cooking, etc.) seems to be a rather makeshift noun based on the gerund, which is in any case more noun-like than an infinitive, cf. Allerton (1988). The meaning of the ‘noun’ is therefore purely ‘eventive’, with no other facets of meaning. On the other hand, some is a clear determiner, and other uncountable determiners are possible, e.g. (not) much, (any) more and even the or that. It is true that adjectives are relatively rare in this construction, cf. do some (?careful) driving; do some (?deep) thinking beside the more natural drive carefully; think deeply, give smth sm deep thought, but semantically appropriate adjectives can be used, e.g. do some advanced driving, do some real thinking, do some worthwhile reading. So the V-ing word in this construction does need to be recognized as a noun. In the second structure (have a V) the case for noun status is even more evenly balanced. On the one hand, the word is by definition a pure verb stem with no formal marking of conversion to noun status, and the meaning is again purely eventive; moreover the apparently countable noun is spasmodically pluralizable (cf. have two shaves, (?)have two looks, ?have two thinks). On the other hand, further determiners are found, particularly possessive ones (e.g. I’ve had my look – you can have yours now), and ordinals can be used (e.g. have a second look), as well as appropriate adjectives (e.g. have a quick shave, have a good think). On balance, then, even these bare verb stem words have to be recognized as nouns.
III.1.ii The determiner and the grammatical subclass of eventive noun phrases The problematic status of the noun phrases in constructions like do some thinking or have a think may well prompt us to ask what the essence of a noun phrase is. In a common noun phrase, after the head noun, the second most important element is any determiner or determiners that accompany it; in fact, some grammarians nowadays regard the determiner as more basic and speak of determiner phrases (or ‘DPs’, see, for instance, Abney (1987), Culicover (1996)). Leaving this theoretical issue on one side, we can agree that both noun and determiner are vital to the noun phrase (or determiner phrase). But the deverbal noun phrase of a stretched verb construction has a noun and a determiner as constituents that have differing types of correspondence to the elements of a simplex verb construction, thus: SIMPLEX
STRETCHED VERB CONSTRUCTION
VERB STRUCTURE
Verb (Frequency adv.) Adverb Object (etc.)
corresponds corresponds corresponds corresponds
to to to to
(Deverbal) noun Determiner Adjective Prep. phrase (as noun complement)
e.g. adjust smth once quickly beside make one quick adjustment to smth.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 125 Hence, while the noun has the function of carrying the eventive meaning found in the verb in the corresponding simple construction, the function of the determiner is less clear. In early X-bar theory, e.g. Chomsky (1970), Jackendoff (1977), it was proposed that determiners were ‘Specifiers’ and corresponded in their function to auxiliary verbs (such as modals); yet semantically they often rather correspond to adverbs, e.g. frequency adverbs, as in the example just given. To understand the role of determiners in stretched verb constructions better, we need to examine the range of different syntactic types of noun phrase in our data on the basis of their determiner potential. Noun phrases are standardly divided into PROPER and COMMON subclasses, with the latter subclass being subdivided into COUNTABLE (or simply ‘count’) and MASS (also known as ‘uncountable’ or ‘non-count’). The basis for this classification is of course partly semantic, but it has important morphosyntactic implications, cf. Allerton (1987b: 63–9), in particular the possibility of a plural inflection for the noun and the restrictions on the use of determiners to precede it. Disregarding secondary uses, we can say that, whereas common nouns freely occur with the definite article (but also contrastively with other determiners and in some cases without one), proper nouns, such as Manchester, (Lake) Windermere, Tony, The Bible, either fail to occur with the definite article or have it as part of their very form, in which case they cannot occur without it; in either case they have no possibility of a contrastive definite article, and they also lack a contrastive plural form. Common nouns, then, occur not only with the definite article but also with other determiners, but the precise determiners they occur with and whether they occur in the plural is the basis for distinguishing the two subsubclasses. Countable common nouns, such as town(s), lake(s), person(s), pea(s), book(s), occur in the plural but also with the indefinite article, or alternatively with one, two, three, etc., while mass (common) nouns, such as countryside, water, wheat, humanity, literature, though failing to occur in the plural or with these determiners, occur instead with other determiners, like (not) much and unstressed some. Taking due account of complicating factors such as nouns that have more than one use (e.g. a stone beside some stone) and technical uses (e.g. a soup in ‘restaurantese’), the above account corresponds to the scheme described in most modern grammars, e.g. Quirk et al. (1985); but there at least two complications that will concern us. The first complication concerns nouns that apparently only occur in the plural, such as oats, trousers, remains, premises, cf. Allerton with French (1975). Standard mass nouns occur only in the singular, but, unlike countable nouns, they cannot occur with the indefinite article a(n) or the numeral one. Nouns like oats, on the other hand, although occurring in the plural, cannot occur with a numeral, cf. *five oats, *two trousers, *six remains. These nouns, just like normal (singular) mass nouns need a measure word (or ‘classifier’) to help them form a structure with a numeral, cf. five sacks of
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
126 The event phrase oats, two pairs of trousers, six sets of remains (which are comparable with five glasses of water, two sacks of wheat). In other words they are just as uncountable in their way, and can reasonably be referred to as PLURAL MASS NOUNS. Sometimes we meet a pair of singular mass noun and plural mass noun, which are both uncountable and which additionally have an irregular semantic relationship, e.g. ash/ashes, content/contents. Our corpus of deverbal eventive nouns contains words of a similar kind: for instance, to send one’s apologies is not simply the plural of (?)to send one’s apology: nor is it possible to use it with a numeral (*to send one’s two apologies). A second complication in the syntactic behaviour of nouns in general concerns the use of nouns without an article or other determiner in contexts in which they would be expected to have one. While mass nouns normally only occur without a determiner (or with zero article/determiner) in the singular (We need water, wheat, etc.), countable nouns normally only occur alone in the plural (We need lakes, peas, etc.). What then are we to make of the use of nouns in expressions like by accident, by car, at school, (go) to work, in which a singular countable noun or a mass noun is used only without a determiner and has no possibility of expansion with a relative clause and little possibility of expansion with an adjective phrase (cf. *by my car, *by unnecessary accident, ?by pure accident, *at school that has gone independent)? Nouns like accident, car, school, work in such constructions seem to combine almost directly with a preposition to form an adverbial, although normally it is only noun phrases that have this capacity. However sometimes an adjective may be added to the noun (e.g. by chauffeur-driven car); so it is probably simplest to regard such nouns (with any accompanying adjective) as constituting a limited kind of noun phrase which then has a preposition attached to it. Indeed some of these nouns also occur alone in noun phrase functions like subject and object (school was unbearable today; I hate school). We shall therefore treat these nouns as forming a special variety of noun phrase, one in which the noun (whether countable or mass) by definition appears alone or SOLO, i.e. without the possibility of a determiner. Such solo nouns are found frequently among stretched verb constructions, commonly in object position (e.g. gain (?legal) admittance) but also in a preposition phrase (e.g. place smbd under (?permanent) arrest). The range of adjectives that may accompany them is strictly limited. We are now in a position to examine the grammatical types of noun phrases that occur in stretched verb constructions. In Table 3.3 the eventive nouns of stretched verb constructions are classified under the heading of ‘countable’, ‘mass singular’, ‘solo’ and ‘specially restricted’; the latter category consists mainly of mass plural nouns and nouns requiring a possessive determiner, but also includes cases of nouns that require a reflexive possessive determiner and those that have a compulsory definite article.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 127 Reading the total results as they are given in Table 3.3, we can say that the approximate figures for the major subtypes of noun are as follows: Count Sing./Plur 84
Mass Sing. 32
Solo 37
Specially Restricted 13
(The number of stretched verb constructions found with each type of noun is roughly twice the figure given.) Placing a noun in the countable category is equivalent to saying that it occurs in the singular with determiners like a, any, each, every, one, that, the, this and in the plural with all, any, both, enough, many, more, the, these, those, two, etc. Semantically, such nouns refer to discrete entities that recur as separate individuals and are thus countable. Countable nouns, with this potential for number differentiation, represent about 50 per cent of the eventive nouns in the data. This certainly suggests that countability, a feature found in noun phrases but not in verb phrases or adjective phrases, might be one reason for the existence of stretched verb constructions. If, for instance, we compare accuse smbd [of smth] with make an accusation [against smbd], one thing we see is a kind of restructuring of one of the types discussed in Part II, with its consequent recategorizing of the optionality of elements; but we also see the eventive meaning ‘accusing’ made countable in the stretched construction, so that the number of accusations can and indeed partially must be specified – at least as to singular or plural. The factor of countability is thus bound to influence the speaker’s choice between the two constructions, and whenever the number of individual accusations, achievements, acquisitions, etc. is at the forefront of the speaker’s mind, the noun-based construction is likely to be preferred. But what of the other 50 per cent of constructions, where countability is not involved? Does their ‘raison d’être’ depend entirely on factors outside noun phrase structure, or can the particular subvariety of noun phrase be a positive factor in their selection? Let us now consider these other types. Nouns classified as mass singular have the capacity for occurring in the singular with the determiners all, any, enough, more, much, that, the, this. Semantically they suggest a naturally undivided substance that may be divided for specific purposes, but when it is divided, it still can be seen as samples of the same universal mass, e.g. some water, (not) much pride, or for our eventive nouns, much acclaim, some advice. In our data singular mass nouns are only one third as frequent as normal countable nouns in the function of eventive noun. Moreover, if we check their use against the ‘additional semantic facets’ of eventive nouns displayed in Table 3.2, we find that certain semantic facets never or rarely appear. (While it is true that these are additional semantic features, it can be assumed that they also colour the basic ‘eventive’ meaning found in stretched verb constructions.) Thus eventive nouns linked to an interpretation ‘physical effect’ or ‘affected entity’ of
11
11
11
11
abhor abominate abort abridge absolve abstain abound abuse accept access acclaim acclimatize accommodate accompany accord account accuse ache achieve acknowledge acquaint acquire acquit act 8 act 9 adapt add
Underlying verb
an an an an an an an an an an an an an
accord account accusation ache achievement acknowledgment acquaintance acquisition acquittal act action adaptation addition
an accommodation
an abuse
an abominaion an abortion an abridgement
Singular/plural countable noun
sm acting sm action
sm accompaniment
sm acclaim sm acclimatization
sm abuse sm acceptance
sm abstinence
sm abhorrence
Singular mass noun1
1 addition11
action10
acknowledgement6
accord4 account5
access3
abundance
absolution2
Singular solo noun
Table 3.3 Basic determiner potential of eventive nouns (in stretched verb constructions)
smbd’s acquaintance7
Specially restricted noun
1
1
111
111
advance advantage advertise advise affect affiliate affirm affront agglomerate aggravate aggress agitate agonize agreement aid ail aim air 21
an an an an an
address12 adhere adjourn adjudicate adjust admire admit13 admit14
affectation affiliation affirmation affront agglomeration aggravation
an ailment an aim an air
an agreement
an an an an an an
an advance an advantage an advertisement
an admission
address adhesive adjournment adjudication adjustment
Singular/plural countable noun
Underlying verb
Table 3.3 (continued)
sm aid
sm agitation sm agony
sm aggravation
sm advice
sm adjustment sm admiration
Singular mass noun1
aim20
agreement17 aid18
aggression16
admission, admittance15
Singular solo noun
smbd’s aid19
Specially restricted noun
11
11
11
111
111
11
11
alarm alert alienate align allege allocate allow allude ally alter alternate amalgamate amaze ambush amend amplify amputate amuse anaesthetize analyse anger annihilate annotate announce annoy annul answer
Underlying verb
Table 3.3 (continued)
allegation allocation allowance allusion alliance alteration
11
an annulment an answer
an annotation an announcement
an analysis
an amputation
sm annoyance
sm analysis sm anger
sm amusement
sm amplification
sm amazement
sm allowance
sm alienation
sm alarm
Singular mass noun1
answer32
annihilation31
anaesthesia28 analysis29
ambush
alternation26 amalgamation27
alliance25
alignment24
alarm23
Singular solo noun
1
an amendment
an an an an an an
an alert
Singular/plural countable noun
smbd’s anger30
Specially restricted noun
1
1
11
111
111
arrange42 arrange43 arrest articulate ascend aspire assassinate assault assent
an an an an
apologize appeal 34 appeal 35 appear appease append applaud apply appoint appraise appreciate approach appropriate approve arbitrate argument
application appointment appraisal appreciation approach appropriation
an an an an
ascent aspiration assassination assault
an arrest
an argue41 an argument an arrangement
an an an an an an
an appendage
apology appeal appeal appearance
Singular/plural countable noun
Underlying verb
Table 3.3 (continued)
sm appreciation
sm applause
sm appeal
Singular mass noun1
arrest44 articulation
approval38 arbitration40
applause37
appeasement36
Singular solo noun
smbd’s assent/ one’s assent46
sm aspirations45
sm arrangements
smbd’s approval39
one’s apologies33
Specially restricted noun
11
11
11
111
111
11
11
an assertion an assessment an assignment
assert assess assign assimilate assist associate assume assure astonish atone attack attempt attend 52 attend 53
an an an an
autograph average avow awake(n) award
sm attention
sm astonishment
sm assistance
Singular mass noun1
authority authorization54
auction
attendance
atonement49 attack50
assimilation47
Singular solo noun
1
average avowal awakening award
an audit an authorization
an attraction
attract auction audit authorize
an attack an attempt
an association an assumption an assurance
Singular/plural countable noun
Underlying verb
Table 3.3 (continued)
one’s autograph
smbd’s attention/ one’s attention
the attack51
smbd’s assistance48
Specially restricted noun
1
1
11
11
111
111
111
111 as in arouse smbd’s anger and also arouse the anger of smbd, but not simply *arouse the anger. 31 as in suffer annihilation. 32 as in be in answer to smth. 33 as in offer one’s apologies. 34 in the meaning ‘complain’. 35 in the meaning ‘be pleasing’. 36 as in practise appeasement. 37 as in burst into applause. 38 as in win approval from smbd for smth; be on approval. 39 as in gain smbd’s approval, give one’s approval, but not simply ?gain approval. 40 as in conduct/carry out arbitration. 41 only in informal British and Australian English. 42 in the meaning ‘agreement’ or ‘timetable’. 43 in the meaning ‘plan, timetable’; sm arrangements is a mass plural use. 44 as in be/place smbd under arrest. 45 a mass plural use 46 as in gain smbd’s assent ( for smth) or gain the assent of smbd ( for smth), but not simply *gain the assent; similarly give one’s assent ( for smth) (but not give the assent for smth). 47 as in undergo assimilation. 48 as in come/go to the assistance of smbd, where the determiner is compulsorily a definite article. 49 as in make atonement for smth. 50 as in be under attack, where no determiner is possible. 51 as in be on the attack, where the determiner is compulsorily a definite article. 52 in the sense ‘look after smbd’, only in the rare construction dance attendance on smbd. 53 in the sense ‘occupy oneself with smth’, as in pay sm attention to smth; attract smbd’s attention, give one’s attention to smth. 54 as in give/grant authority/authorization.
11
30
11
Notes: 1 It goes without saying that normal singular mass nouns (as exemplified in this column) can occur not only with other mass determiners such as (not) much, more, little but also without an overt determiner, whereas ‘solo nouns’ occur only without an overt determiner. 2 as in receive absolution. 3 as gain access to smwh. 4 as in be in accord. 5 as in call smbd to account. 6 as in be in ackowledgement of smth. 7 as in make smbd’s acquaintance, and also make the acquaintance of smbd, but not simply *make the acquaintance. 8 in the meaning ‘perform dramatically’. 9 in the meaning ‘be active’. 10 as in go into action. 11 as in be in addition. 12 in the meaning of either ‘speak to’ or ‘send’. 13 in the meaning ‘confess’. 14 in the meaning ‘allow to enter’. 15 as in gain/grant admission/admittance. 16 as in commit/suffer aggression. 17 as in be in agreement. 18 as in be in aid of smth. 19 as in come to smbd’s aid and also come to the aid of smbd, but not simply *come to the aid. 20 as in take aim. 21 in the meaning ‘complete the drying of [clothes]’. 22 in the meaning ‘make public’. 23 as in fill smbd with alarm. 24 as in bring smth into alignment. 25 as in be in alliance with smbd. 26 as in be in alternation with smbd. 27 as in undergo amalgamation. 28 as in induce anaesthesia in smbd. 29 as in undergo analysis, be under analysis.
11
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
134 The event phrase ‘gift’ or ‘mental focus’ or ‘effected speech act’ or possibly ‘instrument’ are assigned more or less exclusively to the countable category. Looking at it the other way round, we can say that mass nouns are only found with the ‘eventive’ function when they have additional semantic aspects of ‘performer’, ‘mental behaviour or attitude’, ‘mental experience’, ‘mental effect’, ‘service for beneficiary’ and ‘manner or mode’; these all seem to be meanings associated with actors, their mental experiences or their way of doing things. This suggests (on the face of it, surprisingly) a correlation between the semantic features ‘mass/uncountable’ and ‘agency’. Turning to solo eventive nouns, we find them to be slightly more numerous than mass nouns, although they occur in fewer constructions overall. The semantic range of the solo eventive nouns found in our data seems to be subject to restrictions similar to those just described for singular mass nouns. It is therefore tempting to regard solo eventive nouns as simply a special type of singular mass noun, one which limits the determiner range to zero, which is in any case a possibility for singular mass nouns. But even if this view is taken, an explanation is still needed for the fact that solo eventive nouns permit no overt determiners. The most natural explanation for this would be if the nouns concerned were not only uncountable but also unquantifiable (even in a mass sense). If we consider the eventive nouns in our data which occur only in a solo use, namely absolution, abundance, access, admission, admittance, aggression, alignment, alternation, amalgamation, anaesthesia, annihilation, appeasement, arbitration, articulation assimilation, atonement, attendance, auction, authority, authorization, we may detect a general trend towards an absolutive, ungradable type of meaning:80 certainly admittance, alternation, anaesthesia, annihilation and arbitration are scarcely a matter of degree, and although the other eventive meanings may be in some sense gradable (e.g. alignment, assimilation), they are used in an absolute sense in these stretched verb constructions. This point is also linked to the common use of solo eventive nouns after prepositions, to be precise, in prepositional object or objoid position, where their eventive meaning is often slanted in the direction of mental effect on a person (e.g. fill smbd with alarm), or of an effected entity, including speech acts (e.g. burst into applause, receive smbd with acclaim). The fourth column in Table 3.3 includes four minor types of restricted noun phrase, of which the most important is what we are calling ‘definite genitive’. Some noun phrases occur in two forms, one with a possessive determiner (e.g. my anger, the president’s anger), the other with the definite article and a postposed complementing of-phrase (e.g. the anger of the president).81 The stretched verb constructions requiring this kind of noun phrase mainly refer to the action of responding to somebody (go/come to smbd’s 80 In this connection Simatos (1997: 96–8) makes a comparison of the French locutions rendre service and rendre un service. 81 As would be expected, the of-phrase version of this structure is not permitted with pronouns, e.g. *the anger of him.
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 135
111
aid/assistance) or, more commonly, of getting a response from somebody (arouse/incur smbd’s anger, gain smbd’s approval/assent, capture smbd’s attention), or a even mutual response (make smbd’s acquaintance). Such actions presumably make it necessary to mention the person involved (other than the agentive subject) and link that person intimately with the action through being the genitive specifier or complement of the eventive noun. A few stretched verb constructions out of our set take a compulsorily reflexive possessive determiner, namely express/offer one’s apologies [about/for smth], give one’s approval [to/for smth], devote one’s attention to smth and focus one’s attention on smth. The determiner one’s is the impersonal reflexive possessive determiner82 and therefore used with a contextually unidentified infinitive; but my, your, his, etc. (depending on the identified subject) are more frequent in actual use. This means that in such constructions the person referred to by the grammatical subject receives a second mention in the determiner position preceding the eventive noun.83 One reason for this could be the personal nature of the actions involved in constructions with the kindred simple verbs apologize [for smth], approve[of smth]. The remaining specially restricted noun phrases are either mass plural or obligatorily accompanied by a definite article. The use of mass plural noun phrases (sm arrangements, sm aspirations) perhaps expresses quantity without the discreteness needed for countability (cf. mass plural words such as amends, arrears, funds, manners, oats, premises, remains). On the other hand the compulsory use of the definite article in stretched verb constructions like be on the attack, go on (to) the attack seems to have no obvious semantic basis and most probably has to be regarded as an arbitrary fixing of the grammatical pattern. In fact, it is not unreasonable to say that in general the selection of basic noun phrase patterns (of determiner and noun) in stretched verb constructions is somewhat arbitrary. But certain semantically motivated patterns have been described above, in particular countable, mass singular, solo and definite genitive noun phrases. What is perhaps a little surprising is that no clear connections seem to exist between these grammatical types of noun phrase and the suffixes used to form the deverbal event noun. If we compare the details of Tables 3.1 and 3.3, we can see correlations between types of word formation and types of determiner potential: for instance, the most common modes of word formation for countable nouns are zero and suffixation with -ment, -ion and -ation, but all of these morphological types also form mass singular nouns and solo nouns; in fact, zero and -ment are among the most common ways of forming mass singular nouns, while zero and -ion are the most common for solo nouns.
111
82 at least in British English; some American writers appear to prefer his. 83 It is worth noting that these reflexive determiners have no alternative construction with a postcomplementing of-phrase such as *offer the apologies of oneself.
11
11
11
111
111
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
136 The event phrase
III.1.iii Agentive nouns and their determiners We noted at the beginning of section III.1.i that Structure 2 patterns have an agentive noun rather than an eventive noun at their core. Agentive nouns (often known as ‘nomina agentis’) obviously have the effect of highlighting the person or other entity seen as the primary participant in the activity rather than focusing directly on the event itself: thus be a helper gives a different perspective compared with be a help, be of help, come to the help of or give help to (or for that matter the simplex verb help). But there cannot of course be an agent without an action, or more generally an event, that is performed by that agent. It might therefore be more prudent to refer to such nouns as ‘agentive-eventive’ rather than simply as ‘agentive’. The range of morphological and semantic possibilities for agentive nouns and their determiners is rather simpler than that of non-agentive eventive nouns. The full range of possibilities is listed in Table 3.4. The nouns of Table 3.4, with the exception84 of addressee, have an agentive-eventive meaning and thus refer to potential subjects of the verb from which they have been derived; but some of them have other meanings. Many have been lexicalized as names or ranks, professions or social roles, e.g. accompanist, actor, administrator, advertiser, advocate, agent, analyst, announcer, arranger, assessor, assistant, assurer, auctioneer, one of them, namely agent, also appearing as a word for a substance that acts chemically; in such uses they can of course appear in other grammatical positions, for instance, as grammatical subject, and with a verb other than a copular one. But several of the nouns of Table 3.4, such as abetter/-or, abhorrer, adorer are more or less limited to use in stretched verb constructions and when cited alone give the appearance of nonce-words artificially extracted from a phrase. Thus, while verb phrases like be an abridger of novels or be an adorer of beautiful women may seem acceptable, abridger and adorer as isolated words seem much less viable. Agentive-eventive nouns are more uniform than standard eventive nouns in their determiner potential: they are all normal countable nouns. This means that they occur in both the singular and the plural, although their number in the nominal descriptor in which they appear is automatically regulated by the subject of the sentence, cf.: (1)
(a) Sebastian was an administrator. (b) Sybil and Sebastian were administrators.
As regards definiteness, a definite determiner will of course be appropriate when the subject is unequivocally identified by the descriptor noun phrase, 84 We noted in the discussion of (33) in section II.2.iii above how addressee and other words with the -ee suffix were something of an exception.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Eventive and agentive noun phrases 137 Table 3.4 Modes of derivation of agentive-eventive nouns Suffixation with -ant/-ent
Suffixation with -ist/-yst
AGENT APPLICANT ASPIRANT ASSISTANT ATTENDANT
ACCOMPANIST ALARMIST ANALYST
Suffixation with -ive ADHESIVE2
Suffixation with -ee ‘agent’ ABSENTEE
Loss of verb-forming suffix ASSASSIN
Suffixation with -ee ‘recipient’ ADDRESSEE
Suffixation with -eer AUCTIONEER
Suffixation with -er/-or ABETTER/-OR ABHORRER ABRIDGER ABSCONDER ABSTAINER ABUSER ACCUSER ACTOR ADJUDICATOR ADMINISTRATOR ADMIRER ADORER ADVERTISER ADVISER/-OR AGGRESSOR AGITATOR ANALYSER1 ANNOUNCER APPEASER ARBITRATOR ARRANGER ASSESSOR ASSURER ATTACKER AUDITOR AVENGER
Zero (in some cases with stress difference) ADVOCATE AIDE (‘helper’) ALLY ASSOCIATE
Notes: 1 This item tends to refer to machines rather than to human beings, cf. recorder/recordist. 2 This item has an instrumental rather than an agentive meaning in the strict sense.
1
138 The event phrase as in (2)(a), but an indefinite determiner will be appropriate otherwise, as in (2)(b): (2)
(a) Sybil was the arranger of the score. (b) Sybil was an/one arranger of the score.
Interestingly, the kindred simplex structure of (2)(c) is ambiguous between these two interpretations; cf.:
1
(2)
1
whereas the cleft simplex structure of (2)(d) clearly has a definite interpretation corresponding to (2)(a).
11
11
11
11
(c) Sybil arranged the score. (d) It was Sybil that arranged the score.
11
III.2 Eventive and agentive noun phrases: modifiers and qualifiers
11
11
111
111
111
111
III.2.i Adjectival modifications We saw at the beginning of section III.1.ii that noun-based stretched verb constructions have the potential for adjectival expansion before the eventive noun to correspond to adverbial expansion of the corresponding simple eventive verb (as in make a quick adjustment to smth beside adjust smth quickly). The range of adjectives possible with a given eventive noun must therefore at least partly depend on the adverbs that could have occurred in the corresponding eventive verb construction. Adverbs are of course diverse: some of them (such as degree adverbs) are closely linked to the lexical verb and involve collocational restrictions (e.g. deeply disappoint but severely injure); others (such as place) modify the whole verb phrase or predicate, while still others operate at the sentence level. While it is true that adjectives in the noun phrase do need to be ordered relative to each other (e.g. substantial immediate direct legal action rather than, say, ??legal direct immediate substantial action), the important point is that most adjectives in the noun phrase occur simply between the determiner and the head noun. The wide variety of possible adverbs, on the other hand, differ considerably in susceptibility to collocational restrictions, in potential for occurrence in the different sentence positions (including subtle differences in medial position), in replaceability with a preposition phrase, etc. A survey of the range of English adverbials is given in Appendix 1, which largely follows the scheme of Allerton and Cruttenden (1974, 1978). What then is the range of meanings displayed by adjectives in the noun phrases, in particular in those with eventive nouns as heads, and how do these relate to their corresponding adverbs? In their discussion of the general semantics of adjectives Quirk et al. (1985: 434–6) refer to the features STATIVE/DYNAMIC, GRADABLE/UNGRADABLE, and INHERENT/NON-INHERENT. The first of these is not relevant to our study, because it concerns the predicative use of adjectives, prenominal attributive adjectives being invariably stative. The question of gradability is relevant but is alone not sufficient to describe the range of meanings to be found.
1
1
140 The event phrase The third feature, (non-)inherence, is a matter of the regularity of the kindred relationship between adjective-noun constructions and verbadverb constructions, which is a defining characteristic of our stretched verb constructions. In considering the range of meanings found in adjectives premodifying abstract nouns in general, and eventive nouns in particular, we should find it helpful to distinguish four main semantic types:85 (a) (b) (c) (d)
ASPECT/RANGE, e.g. aesthetic (appreciation), QUALITY, e.g. quick (appreciation), EXTENT, e.g. keen (appreciation), FACTUAL STATUS, e.g. actual (appreciation).
1
11
11
11
11
All these types of adjective form combinations with eventive nouns that can be used in a stretched verb construction such as have an appreciation of smth, giving sentences like She had a/an aesthetic/quick/keen/actual appreciation of the piece. The adjective usually corresponds to an adverb in -ly that could modify the corresponding eventive verb. Adjectives of ASPECT/RANGE define a subvariety of the entity denoted by the noun by specifying a particular domain within which it is valid. They are ungradable. They correspond frequently (but not exclusively) to adverbs of viewpoint or respect, in other words to Quirk et al.’s ‘viewpoint subjuncts’ (1985: 566–9) or ‘respect adjuncts’ (1985: 563–4). Thus the expression take legal action normally corresponds to act legally with legally as a viewpoint or respect adverb (‘in the legal sphere’) rather than as a manner adverb (‘in a legal manner’), although use of legally in this sense is just possible. Further combinations of aspect/range adjectives with eventive nouns, which are kindred with verb-plus-viewpoint/respect-adverb constructions, are chemical analysis, educational achievement, historical appeal, medical attention, religious affiliation, technical advice, all of which could be part of a stretched verb construction with adjectival expansion, e.g. make a chemical analysis, take technical advice. Some aspect/range adjectives correspond not to viewpoint or respect adverbs but to some other class of adverb. Thus the adjectives commercial and compulsory in the combinations (place a) commercial advertisement or (make a) compulsory acquisition are clearly aspect/range adjectives, but they correspond to the phrases advertise ( . . . ) commercially and acquire ( . . . ) compulsorily, which contain a method adverb, which refers to the means or method through which the action was carried out rather than to an aspect or the range of the action. One example in the LOB corpus of an aspect/range adjective referring to method has a past participle used as an adjective, namely written advice; such adjectives have no corresponding adverbs, and 85 Examples of collocations of adjective and eventive noun are, in the main, text examples taken from the texts of the LOB corpus. For a fuller list, see Appendix 2.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Modifiers and qualifiers
141
its meaning would have to be rendered in the eventive verb construction with an adverbial phrase, such as advise ( . . . ) in writing. Further correlates in verb-based constructions of aspect/range adjectives in noun phrases are place adverbials, goal objects and agentive subjects. In phrases like domestic aid, external assistance and frontal attack the aspect/range adjective corresponds to a place adverbial like at home, outside or at/from the front, although (not unusually) a simple adverb of place with the corresponding meaning does not exist. For phrases like bacterial analysis, musical appreciation or (to take an example from outside our corpus) personal criticism, we can say first that they have a closely related nominal construction with a complement of-phrase representing the semantic goal (analysis of bacteria, appreciation of music and criticism of the person(s)), and second that there is a kindred verb-based construction that has the adjectival meaning of the nominal construction expressed as the object of the verb (analyse bacteria, appreciate music, criticize the person(s)). Analogously, phrases like critical acclaim, divine approval, Ruritanian aggression, specialist advice are closely related to acclaim by the critic(s), approval by the deity, aggression by (the) Ruritanians and advice by one or more specialists respectively (from being a frequent alternative to by when less direct physical agency is involved); but such phrases also have a kindred structure based on an eventive verb, this time with the adjectival meaning represented by the subject of the verb (critics acclaim smth, the deity approves smth, etc.). In summary, then, aspect/range adjectives are noun modifiers corresponding in verb-based structures to adverbs of viewpoint or respect, to adverbials of method, to adverbials of place or to grammatical objects or subjects. They are thus closely associated with the core meaning of the eventive noun and thus largely to the valency of the kindred verb. It therefore comes as no surprise that these adjectives occur closest to the noun, as is clear from the example cited earlier, namely substantial immediate direct legal action, or from a phrase like the expected full meticulous bacterial analysis, in which legal and bacterial respectively are virtually certain to take up the immediate prenominal position. Adjectives of QUALITY form the major subcategory of adjectives. They add a further quality to the basic characteristic(s) of the (deverbal) noun, but it is a quality that is not quite so central as for aspect/range adjectives, but simply an additional description, most commonly of the manner of the process concerned. This quality is gradable, typically with scalar intensifiers such as very, slightly, otherwise with absolutive ones like utterly, only occasionally with telic (or ‘liminal’) ones like only just, cf. Allerton (1987a) and below, section III.3.ii. Typical examples are curious advertisement, dramatic action, excellent advice, intricate adjustment, natural application and satisfactory answer, which have a clear correspondence to the respective combinations of verb and manner adverb advertise ( . . . ) curiously, act dramatically, advise ( . . . ) excellently, adjust ( . . . ) intricately and answer ( . . . ) satisfactorily. These manner adverbs are process-oriented in the sense that the quality
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
142 The event phrase they refer to is a quality purely of the process itself. Some manner adverbs, on the other hand, are semantically subject-oriented in the sense that they comment on the way the subject carries out the action rather than on the action alone:86 examples are assert audaciously, accept eagerly, admit gracefully, applaud politely and assume tacitly, all of which have corresponding adjectivenoun combinations (audacious assertion, eager acceptance, graceful admission, polite applause and tacit assumption). Both kinds of manner adverbial, however, represent a quality of the verb’s process that is seen by the speaker as interesting or relevant, and this same meaning is carried by equivalent adjectives modifying an eventive noun. Some quality adjectives correspond to adverbials other than manner adverbials. A few seem to correspond to method adverbs (e.g. experimental (advance), pictorial (allusion)), while rather more have kindred subject adjunct adverbials,87 either of the comitative or of the statal subclass, (e.g. collective (agreement), joint (action); helpless (amazement), open-mouthed (attention)). Still more common are adjectives corresponding to time adverbials, either of relative time, e.g. early (acceptance), future (achievement), present (arrangement), previous (account)), or of duration, e.g. long (association), to which we might add frequency adverbials, e.g. annual (allowance) and serial restrictors, e.g. first (appearance). The most significant correspondence for quality adjectives apart from that with manner adverbials is, however, with sentence adverbials, particularly attitudinal message-oriented ones, which offer a speaker’s comment on the assertion made in the sentence. Consider the example: (1)
(a) (b) (c) (d) (e)
They reached an unexpected agreement. They unexpectedly reached an agreement. They unexpectedly agreed. They agreed, which was unexpected. They reached an agreement, which was unexpected.
In (1)(a) we have a stretched verb construction with an adjective (of the type under discussion) modifying the eventive noun. The sentence of (1)(b) has a message-oriented attitudinal sentence adverbial instead of an adjective, but is near-synonymous with the (a) sentence, demonstrating the kindred relationship of the two sentences. The example of (1)(c) shows that
86 This special semantic property is also manifested syntactically in that only subjectoriented manner adverbs can appear in medial (i.e. preverbal) position (and in formal narrative English even in initial position), cf. John cunningly arranged the papers, ?John neatly arranged the papers. 87 This class of adverbials describes the situation (in the broadest sense) of the subject when he/she/it/they performed the activity described by the verb, so that a sentence of the form SENTENCE CORE + SUBJECT ADJUNCT corresponds semantically to a sentence SENTENCE CORE + when he/she/it/they is/are/was/were + SUBJECT ADJUNCT.
Modifiers and qualifiers
143
111
such a sentence adverbial is also possible with a simplex sentence with an eventive verb, whereas it is clear that such sentences cannot allow adjectival expansion (e.g. with unexpected), because there is no eventive noun for the adjective to modify. Finally, sentences (1)(d) and (e) demonstrate the option of a (non-restrictive) sentential relative clause as a further kindred construction, with (d) and (e) corresponding to (c) and (b) respectively; but it is worth noting that (1)(e) is ambiguous according to whether the relative clause is a sentential one or simply a nominal one. Further examples of adjectives of quality corresponding to attitudinal message-oriented adverbials are disastrous (attack), interesting (attempt), necessary (attack), unfortunate (application ‘request for job’), welcome (addition). Some quality adjectives correspond to adverbials of the subject-oriented attitudinal type, which represents a comment on the subject’s behaviour (e.g. characteristic (entity), pathetic (attempt)). A related type of adjective corresponds to a volitional adverbial, i.e. an adverbial that describes the degree of intentionality involved in the subject’s action; adjectives of this type include intentional (action), unconscious (attempt). A further type of adjective is kindred with adverbials of result or ‘outcome’, e.g. abortive (attempt), favourable (answer), successful (application ‘request for job’), unsuccessful (attempt). The third major group of adjectives (which is subject to scalar or absolutive intensification according to the meaning) is those that designate EXTENT, in the sense that they give a quantitative specification of the property expressed by the eventive noun. This implies that they are equivalent to degree adverbs qualifying a corresponding eventive verb; and certainly there is a strong correlation with degree adverbials, as testified by examples such as complete answer, considerable agreement, full assessment, immense amusement, tremendous attraction, wide acceptance. Giving a person a complete answer seems to amount to more or less the same as answering that person completely; but that does not mean that the corresponding expressions are absolutely synonymous, and one aspect of the difference between them lies in the question of whether the completeness is seen as a matter of ‘degree’ in the act of answering or as a matter of ‘extent’ of the product, in this case, of the answer.88 A slightly less numerous set of correspondences can be found between extent adjectives and process-oriented manner adverbs. In these cases the manner adverb describes a way of doing something that will result in a degree of success in completion of the activity: thus align correctly comes to mean ‘align fully’, analyse exhaustively ‘analyse fully’, appreciate keenly ‘appreciate greatly’, and advance spectacularly ‘advance considerably’, with the effect that correct alignment, exhaustive analysis, keen appreciation and spectacular advance
111
88 A further difference between the two expressions is due to the presence of the thin verb (give); the semantic contribution of thin verbs is discussed in Part IV. Note that in the above discussion the term EXTENT is reserved for an adjectival quality, while the term DEGREE is reserved for an adverbial meaning.
11
11
11
111
111
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
144 The event phrase have become, at least partly, extent adjectives. Some subject-oriented manner adverbs, particularly those expressing strength of feelings or emotion, can correspond to extent adjectives in a similar way, e.g. bitterly (cf. bitter attack), convincingly (cf. convincing assurance), vigorously (cf. vigorous argument), the adjective in all three cases having in the collocation a meaning something like ‘big, powerful’. Adverbs of time and place, particularly those subvarieties that have a quantitative meaning, such as duration, frequency and proximity, can also have their corresponding adjectives used in an ‘extent’ function. Phrases like general acceptance, occasional aid and repeated application¸ for instance, have extent adjectives that correspond to frequency adverbs; phrases like brief appearance, constant attention and long account, have extent adjectives corresponding to duration adverbs; finally, phrases like close agreement, nearer approach and universal answer contain extent adjectives corresponding to place adverbs of proximity or density. Minor correspondences of extent adjectives are to conjunctional sentence adverbs like additionally or furthermore (cf. additional aid, further attacks with adjectives meaning ‘supplementary’), also to attitudinal sentence adverbs like remarkably or significantly (cf. remarkable achievement, significant advance, with adjectives meaning roughly ‘big’), and finally to serial restrictors like first or finally (cf. first aim, final authority, with adjectives again meaning roughly ‘main’). The fourth type of adjective assesses the FACTUAL STATUS of the verbal noun; this type thus differs radically from the three other types, because it questions whether the entity described is a genuine specimen of the class designated by the noun or alternatively whether the description covers all cases or only some. In the phrase an apparent adjustment, for instance, the adjective apparent does not so much give further details of the type or extent of the adjustment but rather casts doubt on whether it is an adjustment at all; in the same context the adjective real would have the function of allaying such doubts about membership of the class of entities concerned.89 Such adjectives are commonly related to validity adverbials like actually (cf. actual achievement), apparently (cf. apparent adjustment), implicitly (cf. implicit assumption), really (cf. real agony), ultimately (cf. ultimate aim), giving us correspondences like: (2)
(a) They made an apparent adjustment. (b) Apparently, they made an adjustment. (c) Apparently, they adjusted something.
An alternative kindred adverb for factual status adjectives is the polar restrictor type, including mainly, only, particularly, as exemplified by the 89 Such adjectives are, of course, not limited to eventive nouns and occur with everyday nouns, as in combinations like false friend, in which the adjective in effect largely nullifies the semantic effect of the noun, cf. Allerton (1984a: 24–6).
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Modifiers and qualifiers
145
adjective–noun combinations main advance, only appearance and particular attention. These adjectives indicate whether the entities referred to by the noun are unique or nearly unique, and thus correspond to the polar restrictors mainly, only, particularly, as shown by the correspondences: (3)
(a) They made their main advance in the west. (b) They made their advance mainly in the west. (c) They advanced mainly in the west.
A third significant group of factual status adjectives correspond to likelihood sentence adverbials, such as definitely, obviously, probably and possibly. They can be exemplified with constructions like definite answer, obvious assumption, probable defeat and possible error, and the correspondences are typified by the sentences: (4)
(a) They have made a possible error. (b) They have possibly made an error. (c) They have possibly erred.
In a similar way, suffer a probable defeat means ‘probably suffer a defeat’ or ‘probably be defeated’. The phrases definite answer and obvious assumption are less clear, because they would also allow interpretation of definitely and obviously respectively as manner adverbs, although, interestingly, this need not change the overall meaning of the sentence significantly. We have seen, then, that the adjectives that qualify the eventive noun in a stretched verb construction extend from adjectives of aspect/range through adjectives of quality and adjectives of extent to adjectives of factual status at the other end of the scale, in the sense that they are furthest away from simply subclassifying the noun by mentioning a secondary characteristic. Table 3.5 sums up their possible correspondences to adverbs. It goes without saying that these four semantic classes are not discrete grammatical categories but semantic types which shade into each other, with many border-line cases; there are even more marginal cases for the corresponding adverbial or verb elaborator types, particularly between viewpoint/respect and method, between agent and location, and between viewpoint/respect and subject (= agent). The difference in semantic value or perspective between adverb and adjective can appear to differ very radically: for instance long account has long with a quantitative meaning of extent, while the corresponding adverb is one of duration. Yet the meaning of duration is still present in the adjective; it is simply that its effect in this collocational context has been adapted to express quantity in a more general sense, in other words ‘extent’. It makes a considerable difference to the meaning of adjective or adverb whether they have an active or passive (or even causative) perspective with respect to the kindred verb: the combination contemptuous amusement, for
1
1
1
146 The event phrase instance, is understood as ‘contemptuously being amused’ and not as ‘amusing contemptuously’, so that it is not the ‘amuser’ that is being contemptuous, but the ‘amusee’! The classes and kindred relations we have observed for adjectives modifying eventive nouns are probably valid for adjectives found with abstract nouns in general. Thus alongside the examples we have seen above we could place combinations with abstract nouns with no kindred verb such as accident, cf. aerial accident (ASPECT/RANGE), annoying accident (QUALITY), serious accident (EXTENT), apparent accident (FACTUAL STATUS). Even with concrete nouns the same types of adjectives recur, with the only difference that quality adjectives are much more numerous and varied to cope with the different physical properties that concrete things and persons can be endowed with, such as age, colour, shape and size in different dimensions. The modifying adjectives we have discussed so far in this section modify eventive nouns. The agentive-eventive nouns that occur in Structure 2 refer to persons, and the question arises whether the adjectives that typically modify them can be accommodated under the four semantic types we set up above (and referred to in Table 3.5). Apparently they can, as the following examples show:
11
11
11
11
musical accompanist, commercial advertiser, political agitator, chemical analyst, external arbitrator. (b) QUALITY: rash accuser, passionate advocate, curious ally, unexpected applicant, cautious assessor, slow assistant, conscientious auditor. (c) EXTENT: total absentee, complete abstainer, outright accuser, great admirer, strong advocate, full associate. (d) FACTUAL STATUS: real abuser, implicit accuser, main agitator, possible ally, obvious appeaser, alleged assassin.
(a)
ASPECT/RANGE:
The personal value of agentive nouns means that they permit a wider variety of quality adjectives than eventive nouns do: they can, for instance, take adjectives denoting physical characteristics (e.g. tall, blond(e), welldressed). Sometimes interesting ambiguities of interpretation arise between an aspect/range adjective and a quality adjective, as in a combination like criminal assessor. Disregarding such minor variations, we can in general discern some differences between the way adjectives modify (standard eventive or agentive-eventive) nouns and the way adverbs modify (eventive) verbs. Adjectives modify nouns that see events as things which can be subclassified on the basis of a number of superficially clear criteria. Adverbs, on the other hand, suggest a wide range of possible background details to an event, such as time, place, manner, method, condition of the agent, viewpoint of the speaker, likelihood, etc., which can be expressed not only with single word adverbs but with preposition phrases of differing degrees of complexity.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Modifiers and qualifiers
147
Table 3.5 Correspondences between meanings of adjectives (modifying eventive nouns) and types of adverbial Semantic type of adjective Type of adverbial (etc.)
Aspect/ range
Quality
Extent
Interpretational – subject-oriented
+
+
Interpretational – message-oriented
+
+
Factual status
Interpretational – probabilistic
+
Presentational – validity-oriented
+
Presentational – viewpoint (/respect)
+
Presentational – style-oriented Presentational – honesty-oriented Conjunctional
+
Contingential – cause/result
+
Contingential – contrast Contingential – condition Subject Adjunct – vicariative Subject Adjunct – volitional
+
Subject Adjunct – comitative
+
Subject Adjunct – statal
+
Place Adverbial
+
+
Time Adverbial – timing
+
Time Adverbial – duration
+
+
Time Adverbial – frequency
+
+
Degree Adverbial
+
Aspect Adverbial Manner Adverbial – subject-oriented
+
+
+
Manner Adverbial – process-oriented
+
+
+
Method Adverbial
+
+
Restrictor – polar
+
Restrictor – serial
+
SUBJECT (Agent)
+
OBJECT (Goal)
+
+
1
148 The event phrase
III.2.ii Prepositional postqualifiers and thin prepositions It became clear in Part II that an element that appears as a verb elaborator (such as object or prepositional objoid) in a verb-based structure can surface as a preposition phrase complementing the eventive noun in the kindred stretched verb construction, as in (5) or (6) below: (5)
S/s + V/ø + O/v
(6)
S/s + V/ø + O/v
1
1
11
kindred with S + V + O abridge smth
A prepositional qualifier is thus incorporated into the noun phrase with the eventive noun at its core. But what is the semantic role (vis-à-vis the kindred verb) of elements incorporated in this way, and what prepositions are used to introduce them? Before we embark on this study, we should note that some preposition phrases remain unincorporated as prepositional objoids. Usually such prepositional objoids have the same preposition in the stretched verb construction and the kindred eventive verb pattern, as exemplified by (7): (7)
STRETCHED VERB CONSTRUCTION
KINDRED SIMPLEX CONSTRUCTION
make an admission (of smth) [to smbd] make an allegation (to smbd) that-Clause make an appropriation (of smth) (for smbd) add an attachment [to smth]
admit smth [to smbd] allege (to smbd) that-Clause appropriate smth (for smbd) attach smth [to smth]
11
11
11
In a few cases, however, there is a more radical difference between the two constructions, with a difference in preposition, cf. (8)
STRETCHED VERB CONSTRUCTION
KINDRED SIMPLEX CONSTRUCTION
do/perform/carry out an abortion (on smbd) abort smth (for smbd) induce an abortion (in smbd) abort smth (for smbd) have an appeal ( for smbd) appeal to smbd In all the examples of (7) and (8), however, the preposition phrase in the stretched verb construction remains independent of the eventive noun, so that we do not find sentences like those of (9) but rather those of (10), cf.:
11
11
11
111
Modifiers and qualifiers (9)
149
??An admission of guilt to the court was made. ??An allegation of rape to the police was made. ??An abortion on the woman was performed.
(10) An admission of guilt was made to the court. An allegation of rape was made to the police. An abortion was performed on the woman. We shall therefore count preposition phrases like to the court, to the police and on the woman in (10) as prepositional objoids, and not as prepositional (post)qualifiers of the eventive noun. Some stretched verb constructions have independent prepositional objoids that correspond to objects in simple eventive verb constructions. Consider the examples: (11)
STRETCHED VERB
KINDRED SIMPLEX
CONSTRUCTION
CONSTRUCTION
shout sm abuse [at smbd] heap sm abuse on smbd extend aid to smbd create alarm (among pple) provide amusement (for smbd) arouse sm astonishment (in smbd)
abuse smbd abuse smbd aid smbd alarm pple amuse smbd astonish smbd
The preposition phrases of (11) remain unintegrated with the eventive noun in the stretched verb construction, and remain as a prepositional objoid dependent on the thin verb, as a comparison of the theoretically possible sentences of (12) with the natural ones of (13) demonstrates:
111
111
111
(12) ??Much abuse at her was shouted. ??Alarm among the spectators was created. (13) Much abuse was shouted at her. Alarm was created among the spectators. As regards the actual choice of preposition, this naturally depends on the semantic role being played by the prepositional objoid. This seems to cover the range from ‘mental stimulus’ through ‘experiencer’, ‘mental goal’ and ‘affected goal’ to ‘recipient’. The precise choice of preposition is not unequivocally determined by the semantic role, with ‘affected goal’, for instance, being expressed by among (for plural noun phrases only), at, for, in, on/upon, to/for, although unequivocal to has the value of ‘recipient’. If anything, there is a stronger influence by the thin verb, as in combinations like shout . . . at, heap . . . on/upon, extend . . . to, provide . . . for.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
150 The event phrase A final group of unincorporated preposition phrases corresponds to the subject of the kindred eventive verb (or the agent of its passive form). They can be exemplified as follows: (14)
STRETCHED VERB
KINDRED SIMPLEX
CONSTRUCTION
CONSTRUCTION
take sm abuse [from smbd] feel sm alarm [at smth] find sm amusement in smth suffer annihilation (at the hands of smbd)
abuse smbd alarm smbd amuse smbd annihilate smth
Once again the non-integration of the preposition phrases can easily be demonstrated: (15) ??Some abuse from the crowd had to be taken. ??Some alarm at the news was felt. (16) Some abuse had to be taken from the crowd. Some alarm was felt at the news. There is some correlation between the choice of preposition and the precise semantic role of the ‘agent-phrase’: from seems to be the most generally available and thus the most neutral in meaning; at-the-hands-of implies physical action by the agent that is detrimental to the entity or entities represented by the passive subject/active object; at suggests a mental stimulus rather than an agent as the active subject. But the choice of in in find amusement in smth would appear to be determined by the choice of the thin verb find. Returning now to the larger numbers of preposition phrases that do become part of the eventive noun phrase, we can see the basic statistics of their semantic roles and choice of preposition given in Table 3.6. A survey of Table 3.6 brings out one or two points, the most obvious of which is that the prepositions used for prepositional qualifiers are not precisely the same as those used for prepositional objoids, or for that matter for indirect objoids or prepositional descriptors. It is true that some prepositions are used in either role (namely at, for, from, on, to and with). But the majority are specialized in the one role or the other: in particular, about, against, between and of are used in prepositional postqualifiers, but rarely if ever in prepositional objoids; whereas the prepositions among, at-the-handsof, in and into (and also to when it is in alternation with zero as in indirect object constructions) are found only in prepositional objoids and the like, but rarely if ever in prepositional postqualifers. The choice of preposition thus partly marks the closeness of syntactic connection between eventive noun and preposition phrase, but it also
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Modifiers and qualifiers
151
obviously says something about the semantic role of the phrase in question. The preposition about, for instance, as it occurs in combinations like make an announcement about smth, make an assumption about smbd/smth, has a fairly consistent meaning that we have given as ‘mental goal/issue’, because it refers to a topic in the subject’s mind that is in some sense the target in the speech-act of announcing, assuming, etc. and is sometimes the object of the kindred eventive verb. The prepositions against, between and of are like about in signalling integrated preposition phrases, but they each cover a wider semantic range. In the case of against the phrases concerned may relate to the issue involved (e.g. accusation/agitation/appeal against) or to an affected goal (aggression against), but in all cases the eventive noun refers to an action from which some negative consequences flow. The preposition between has been analysed as marking either a coagent (agreement between) or an experiencer (arbitration between), but in both cases the noun phrase following the preposition must be plural, and the persons referred to have a reciprocal relationship to each other (and in the latter case also a subordinate relationship to a third party agent). The most important preposition in integrated prepositional postqualifiers is undoubtedly of. Of all prepositions it is the one that is most strongly associated with an adnominal rather than an adverbial role. It is occasionally found in the prepositional objoids of either intransitive bivalent verbs (e.g. die of . . . ) or of transitive trivalent verbs (e.g. free . . . of . . . , rob . . . of . . . ), in which case it seems mainly to have the semantic role that we have termed ‘incubus’, i.e. something that is either an unpleasant aspect of the environment or something (possibly unpleasant) that is separated from a person, or both of these things together. But of is most commonly found with a genitive or associative meaning, linking a head noun with some kind of relational meaning to a noun phrase subordinated to it (e.g. father of the bride, captain of the team, back of the cooker); moreover some of these are morphologically deverbal and/or semantically eventive (e.g. arrival of the president, re-election of the president) and typically correspond to the subject or object of a kindred verb. Considering the examples of of-phrases after eventive nouns in our data, we need to distinguish between those cases where the of-postqualifier corresponds to possessive determiner (e.g. the bride’s father) and cases where it does not (e.g. ?the cooker’s back). Looking at the latter type first, we find that after eventive nouns they generally carry the meaning of ‘affected goal’ or ‘mental goal’, typical roles for a valency object, and in fact they generally correspond to the object or prepositional object of the kindred verb, cf. abridgement of smth, abuse of smth/smbd, analysis of smth, approval of smth/smbd, assassination of smbd, assessment of smth/smbd. We sometimes find this meaning also in cases where the of-phrase is kindred with a possessive determiner, as in arouse the anger of smbd, come to the aid of smbd. But the more basic value of this pattern is as the correlate of the subject of the kindred verb, with a meaning ranging through ‘agent’, ‘subagent’, ‘mental stimulus’ and ‘experiencer’, all
1
11
11
11
11 0 (+4)
at 0 (+7)
at-the-hands-of
between
related characterized entity
event
destination 0 (+3)
0 (+1)
0 (+1)
2 (+0)
2 (+0)
0 (+1)
2 (+10)
0 (+17)
from
location
1 (+0)
9 (+3)
27 (+6)
0 (+5)
1 (+2)
1 (+0)
for
3 (+0) 1 (+0)
4 (+3)
5 (+0)
1
incubus
recipient
joint affected goal
affected goal
2 (+0)
6 (+0)
mental goal/issue
mental goal
2 (+0)
experiencer/issue
experiencer
mental stimulus
2 (+0) 0 (+1)
among
2 (+0)
against
subagent
29 (+3)
about
coagent
agent
Semantic role
Table 3.6 Prepositions and semantic roles in prepositional qualifiers (and in other1 prepositional phrases)
1
111
111
0 (+8)
0 (+10)
Note: 1 i.e. indirect objects, prepositional objoids and prepositional descriptors.
1 (+0) 0 (+2)
event
8 (+6)
11 (+5)
18 (+4)
5 (+0)
1 (+4)
to
related characterized entity 0 (+1)
0 (+1)
12 (+5)
0 (+1)
on
5 (+0)
1 (+0)
5 (+0)
111
destination
location
incubus
recipient
0 (+14)
affected goal
1 (+0)
17 (+0)
mental goal
joint affected goal
3 (+0) 21 (+0)
mental goal/issue
0 (+3)
0 (+4)
experiencer
experiencer/issue
1 (+0)
mental stimulus 5 (+0)
20 (+0)
0 (+2)
subagent
2 (+0)
of/’s
coagent
of 4 (+0)
into
111
agent
in
11
Semantic role
Table 3.6 (continued)
0 (+23)
0 (+7)
0 (+4)
0 (+2)
0 (+5)
to/0
0 (+8)
0 (+4)
3 (+0)
4 (+0)
4 (+0)
1 (+0)
2 (+4)
17 (+1)
with
11
11
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
154 The event phrase typical active subject roles, as in secure the approval of smbd/ smbd’s approval (cf. smbd approves smth), attract the attention of smbd/smbd’s attention (cf. smbd attends to smth). Let us turn finally to those prepositions that introduce both noun-phraseindependent and noun-phrase-integrated preposition phrases; this group comprises at, for, from, on, to and with. In the case of from and with the question of whether the preposition phrase is integrated or not seems to depend on the semantic role of the individual phrase concerned. When from has the semantic value of ‘agent’ or ‘subagent’, as we saw above, it is not integrated as a prepositional postqualifier to the eventive noun, but when it has the meaning that we described above as ‘incubus’, as in pronounce absolution from smth, practise abstinence from smth, integration seems to take place, probably because the meaning is so closely associated with that of the event expressed either in the eventive verb in the simplex verbal construction or in the eventive noun in the stretched verb construction. With other prepositions the situation seems to be somewhat different, as the examples below show: (17) The paramedical staff made an attempt at resuscitation. An attempt at resuscitation was made (by the paramedical staff). (18) The author hurled abuse at the critics. *Abuse at the critics was hurled (by the author). (cf. Abuse was hurled at the critics (by the author).) Why is the preposition phrase with at, which in both cases corresponds to an object with the kindred verb (to attempt resuscitation, to hurl abuse), incorporated into the noun phrase based on the eventive noun in (17) but not in (18)? Presumably there is something about the nature of the phrase at the critics that gives it a basically (direction) adverbial status and links it with the ‘not-so-thin’ verb hurl. Consider now the following examples with for: (19) place an advertisement for smth make an application for smth present an argument for smth
feel an attraction for smbd provide amusement for smbd make allowance for smth
The preposition phrases of the left-hand column stick with the preceding noun when the stretched verb construction is used in the passive, as in example (17); they therefore involve prepositional postqualifiers attached to the eventive noun. The preposition phrases of the right-hand column, on the other hand, remain ‘in situ’ for passivization, suggesting they are noun-independent prepositional objoids dependent if anything on the thin verb; feel and provide certainly seem to retain a certain amount of their basic meaning in these constructions, and feel . . . for and provide . . . for seem
11
Modifiers and qualifiers
155
natural collocations, though the example make allowance for can only be explained through the kindred construction allow for. The remaining prepositions, on, to and with, seem to operate like for, in that they sometimes contract a closer link with the eventive noun and become incorporated into its noun phrase, but otherwise remain aloof as semi-independent prepositional objoids loosely connected with a thin verb, which may not be as semantically thin as some. Examples of the two types of preposition phrase with these prepositions are listed below for comparison:
11
11
111
111
111
111
STRUCTURES WITH INCORPORATED PREPOSITIONAL POSTQUALIFIERS
STRUCTURES WITH NOUNINDEPENDENT PREPOSITIONAL OBJOIDS
commit an assault on smbd carry out an attack on smbd make an adaptation to smth provide an answer to smth reach an agreement with smbd form an association with smbd
focus attention on smth carry out an abortion on smbd give an address to smbd present an award to smbd suffer agony with smth feel annoyance with/at smbd/smth
Like the for-phrases we looked at above, these preposition phrases seem to have a syntactic allegiance that reflects their semantic links: if they are semantically close to the eventive noun (assault/attack on, adaptation/answer to, agreement/association with), they form postqualifiers of the respective noun; but if they are semantically close to the meaning expressed by the thin verb, at least in its core meaning, (e.g. focus . . . on smth, present . . . to smbd, suffer . . . with smth), then they will probably keep the status of nounindependent prepositional objoids, or, in the case of give . . . to smbd, of an indirect object. In considering the question of which prepositions realize which functions in a given stretched verb construction, we have been concentrating on the major pattern, Structure 6, in which the (prepositionless) object position is filled by the event itself. A consequence is of course that object position cannot be filled by the various ‘goal’ meanings, and these have to be accommodated elsewhere, resulting in the general restructuring we saw in Part II. But subject position in the stretched verb construction is not immune to this restructuring and may accommodate something other than the ‘agent’, which in this case can appear as a prepositional objoid introduced by at-the-hands-of, from or as a genitive postqualifier marked with of/’s. Consideration needs to be given, finally, to a type of preposition phrase that cannot belong to the complementation of the eventive noun for one very simple reason: it contains the eventive noun within it! It is a question of Structure 4 patterns that have the eventive noun in a prepositional
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
156 The event phrase descriptor after the verb be (as in be of assistance to smbd) or Structure 5 patterns that have the eventive noun in a prepositional objoid after a noncopular thin verb, as in burst into applause at smbd/smth. These eventive preposition phrases, like the non-eventive ones we discussed above, vary according to how clear a semantic contribution they make and according to how close a relationship they have to the thin verb (although they cannot have a close relationship to the eventive noun, since they contain it themselves). As regards the prepositions involved, we find of and on occurring in prepositional descriptors, for, from and into occurring in prepositional objoids, and in, under and with occurring in both types of constituent. Looking more closely first at eventive preposition phrases which appear as prepositional descriptors in Structure 4, we find that constructions with in or of (e.g. be in acknowledgement of smth, be in alliance with smbd, be in answer to smth, be of assistance to smbd) seem to have a stative kind of meaning compared with the kindred simple eventive verb (cf. respectively acknowledge smth, ally onslf with smbd, answer smbd/smth, assist smbd with a more dynamic meaning). The two examples with on (namely be on approval, be on the attack), despite their difference in voice, appear to share the meaning of ‘provisional or temporary action’, a meaning that is clearly connected to the punctual meaning of on in its most basic locational sense. If the preposition on is equivocal as regards voice, the preposition under is definitively passive: the examples be under anaesthesia/analysis/arrest/attack 90 are all clearly related to kindred simple eventive verb patterns but with a passive meaning (cf. be anaesthetized, be analysed, etc.); however whereas such passives are usually ambiguous between a stative and a dynamic reading, the stretched verb constructions only have a stative interpretation. In all of these Structure 4 patterns the very thin verb be unsurprisingly seems unable to contract an especially close relationship to the preposition, which instead appears to form a close bond with any following prepositional modifier, often giving the effect that the combination [preposition + eventive noun + preposition] forms something of a lexical unit, almost a complex preposition, e.g. in aid of, in agreement with. The prepositional objoids of Structure 5 have been found to occur with the prepositions for, from, in, into, to, under and with, the first two of these having only one example each, namely come in for sm abuse from/at-the-handsof smbd, suffer from an ailment. The first of these has a passive sense, which seems to be a regular meaning of come in for in such combinations (cf. come in for criticism, come in for (close) scrutiny), although this is difficult to link to the core meaning of ‘purpose’. The second preposition from seems to have been selected to collocate with the verb suffer in its core meaning, and this is certainly present still to some degree in the stretched verb construction, with the result that the subject is interpreted as the ‘experiencer’, whereas 90 The pair of stretched verb constructions be on the attack versus be under attack shows an especially interesting contrast in the value of the prepositions.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Modifiers and qualifiers
157
this semantic role appears in objoid position with the simple verb ail (cf. I can see what ails you). The two attested examples with in, namely engage in an activity and come in addition to smth seem to be quite different in nature: the first seems to have its preposition selected by the thin verb (engage in) and to have a ‘progressive’ kind of meaning; the second would appear to have a preposition with a close connection to the eventive noun and form a complex adverb or preposition (in addition (to)). All the examples involving the preposition into (e.g. bring smth into alignment, move into action, get into an argument) have an inceptive meaning. Although some constructions containing to also have this inceptive meaning (namely come/go to the aid/assistance of smbd) two other different patterns with to are also found: the expressions subject smth to analysis and call smbd to account apparently have a semantic feature of ‘deliberateness’ compared with their simple eventive verb alternatives (analyse smth, make smbd account for smth); and the examples come to an accord/agreement/arrangement with smbd have a completive kind of meaning, suggesting the end of a process. The Structure 5 constructions with under (place/put smbd under arrest) are passive in meaning like their Structure 4 counterparts (like be under arrest), but they also seem to have the feature of ‘deliberateness’ noted for the preposition to. Finally the preposition with seems to occur with two different values: in the majority of cases it is apparently collocationally selected by the thin verb (either with an object, as in fill . . . with, present . . . with, provide . . . with, or without an object, as in meet with) and has little clear semantic value, apart from signalling the mental effect produced or service provided; but in one attested example (receive smbd with acclaim) the preposition seems to mark an accompanying manner. The only nominal pattern we have not assessed for prepositional qualifiers is Structure 2, with its agentive-eventive nouns. Here, too, the most popular preposition is of, occurring as it does with nouns like abetter/-or, abhorrer, abridger, abuser, accompanist, accuser, addressee, admirer, adorer, advocate, agent, ally, arranger, associate, avenger, and, with to as an alternative, for assistant. Other prepositions found are against (after aggressor and agitator), between (after arbitrator), for (after advocate, agent and applicant) and from (after absentee and abstainer). The choice of preposition is generally the same as for a kindred eventive noun, e.g. abhorrer/abhorrence of, absentee/absence from, abstainer/abstinence from, abuser/abuse of, aggressor/aggression against, applicant/ application for, arranger/arrangement of. But sometimes there is a change in the choice of, or at least in the preference for, prepositions, cf. admirer of/*for smbd but admiration for/?of smbd; assistant of/(?)to smbd but assistance to/?of smbd. The semantic role of these prepositional qualifiers is usually that of ‘affected entity’ (= ‘patient’) or of ‘mental focus’, the two most typical semantic roles for objects of verbs. This dovetails neatly with the fact that the agentive noun itself, thanks to its agentive suffix (-er, -ant/ent, -ist, etc.) represents the subject. Schematically we can represent this state of affairs as follows:
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
158 The event phrase kindred e.g. arrang(e)
VERB
+
-er = SUBJECT -er
+
prepositional qualifier = OBJECT of the music
This close syntactic–semantic connection between kindred verb, deverbal affix and preposition phrase perhaps explains why these preposition phrases are commonly incorporated as prepositional qualifiers of the agentiveeventive noun, and not left as prepositional objoids like some preposition phrases after standard eventive nouns, as noted at the beginning of this section. Summing up the functions of prepositions and preposition phrases in stretched verb constructions, we can say that semantically they are relatively thin, but that in many cases their core meanings are at least relevant to the interpretation of the whole construction. Lexically they seem to contract links either with the thin verb (on the basis of its semantically full interpretation) or with the eventive noun at the heart of the construction.
11
III.3 Agentive adjective phrases
11
11
111
111
111
111
III.3.i Agentive-eventive adjectives The stretched verb constructions of Structure 1, unlike all others, involve an adjective-based construction: a copular verb like be combines with an adjective that has an agentive meaning (or, more strictly, an agentiveeventive meaning, i.e. one that describes the quality taken on by a subject performing the event described by the verb). Thus be active, for instance, is a kindred structure to the simplex verb phrase act, with the adjective relying on its morphological derivation from the verb to give it its agentive-eventive meaning. Thus, although an ‘agent’, or some other semantic role associated with the grammatical subject, implies an underlying event, this event is referred to only obliquely, through the quality designated by the adjective. The range of morphological means for forming ‘subject’s role’ adjectives is given in Table 3.7. The data are in one respect untypical: as a result of our decision to concentrate on examples with orthographic initial A, the prefix a- is overrepresented. But in other respects the examples are reasonably representative. It is worth noting that the examples with suffixed -ing and -ed/-en are original present and past verb participles that have been lexicalized as adjectives derived from the verb. This can be demonstrated in two ways: the first is if they take purely adjective premodifiers like very or too; the second is if they are impossible with the object noun phrase that the kindred verb normally requires. Consider these examples: (20) (a) Sebastian fully/*very accommodated our needs. (b) *Sebastian (fully) accommodated. (c) Sebastian was very/*fully accommodating. (21) (a) (b) (c) (d) (e)
The news alarmed Sybil greatly/*very. *The news (greatly) alarmed. The news was very/*greatly alarming. Sybil was very alarmed. Sybil was greatly alarmed.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
160 The event phrase Table 3.7 Modes of derivation of agentive-eventive adjectives Prefixation with a-
Suffixation with -ist
AFLOAT AGAPE AGLEAM AGLITTER AGLOW ALIVE ASLEEP
ALARMIST
Suffixation with -able/-ible ABOMINABLE ACCEPTABLE ACCESSIBLE ACCOUNTABLE ANSWERABLE
Suffixation with -ive ABUSIVE ACQUISITIVE ACTIVE ADHESIVE AGGRESSIVE APPRECIATIVE ARGUMENTATIVE ATTENTIVE ATTRACTIVE
Suffixation with -ous ADVANTAGEOUS
Suffixation with -ant/-ent ABHORRENT ABSORBENT ABUNDANT
Suffixation with -some AWESOME
Suffixation with -y Suffixation with -ed/-en1
ANGRY
ABANDONED ACCUSTOMED ACQUAINTED ANNOYED
Replacement of suffix with -etic APOLOGETIC
Suffixation with -ic(al) ANALYTIC(AL)
Replacement of suffix with -istic
ANTAGONISTIC APOLOGETIC AUTOMATIC
ANTAGONISTIC
Suffixation with -ing 2 ABSORBING ACCOMMODATING ALARMING ALLURING AMAZING AMUSING ANNOYING APPALLING ASTONISHING ASTOUNDING
Zero (in some cases with stress shift) ABSENT ALERT ALTERNATIVE APPROXIMATE ARTICULATE
Notes: 1 when used, not simply as an inflection for the past participle, but to form a new (derived) adjective. 2 when used, not simply as an inflection to form the gerund or present participle, but to form a new (derived) adjective.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Agentive adjective phrases 161 The examples of (20) illustrate this point for an -ing adjective: thus (20)(a) exemplifies typical use of the kindred verb, which rejects very as a degree adverb to modify it; (20)(b) shows how the verb requires its object to be present;91 (20)(c) makes clear that (scalar gradable) adjectives co-occur with very but reject the appropriate verbal adverbs like fully or greatly. The examples of (21)(a) to (c) make the same point for another -ing adjective. But (21)(d) and (e) demonstrate how things are rather more complicated with -ed/-en adjectives because of the semantic closeness of the verbal and the corresponding adjectival construction: roughly, very in (21)(d) identifies an adjectival construction with the verb be in a stative meaning, while greatly in (21)(e) requires a verbal interpretation, with be + -ed/-en used as a marker of passive. The adjectives in Structure 1 are part of an adjective phrase in the syntactic position referred to in this volume as ‘descriptor’ but often described as ‘predicative’, as opposed to ‘attributive’, i.e. part of a noun phrase. It has already been noted, for instance by Quirk et al. (1985: 428–32), that some adjectives are limited to this position, particularly adjectives of aspect/range (e.g. medical) and of factual status (e.g. principal), but equally that some are limited to predicative position. Among the latter category are all those in Table 3.7 that involve the prefix a-, such as afloat. These adjectives, indeed all agentive-eventive adjectives in predicative position, belong to the semantic subcategory of adjectives of quality. Turning, then, to the semantic value of descriptor adjectives, we find that they describe different aspects or facets of the referent of the subject noun phrase. These facets are summarized in Table 3.8. Of the semantic facets shown in this Table, some are valid for a person or a thing, namely their evaluation (advantageous), their factual status or relevance (e.g. abundant, approximate), their physical nature (e.g. absorbent, automatic), their physical state (e.g. active, afloat, asleep) and their mental effect on a person (e.g. acceptable, alarming), while others only apply to persons, namely their behaviour or attitude (e.g. abusive, apologetic) and their social status or relationship (accountable). What they perhaps all share is that they tell us something about the state or condition of the subject, whereas the corresponding simplex verb pattern typically tells us about an event or situation in which the subject is involved. In most cases the adjective-based constructions of Structure 1 have a subject that corresponds to the subject of the kindred simplex pattern, but in patterns (1–2–02–0–0) to (1–2–04–0–0) there is a restructuring, involving mental effects by a stimulus on an experiencer. In pattern (1–2–02–0–0) (e.g. be acceptable to smbd) there is a mental stimulus as subject and an experiencer as a prepositional objoid, but the simplex verb pattern (e.g. accept 91 Indeed, the way adjectives leave the object of the kindred verb unmentioned is probably one reason for the existence of Structure 1: it gives speakers the option of leaving out something that they do not wish to mention.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
162 The event phrase Table 3.8 Semantic facets of subjects expressed by agentive adjectives as descriptors Social status/relationship (of person) ACCOUNTABLE ANSWERABLE
AGLITTER AGLOW ALIVE ARTICULATE ASLEEP
(Mental) behaviour/attitude1 ABUSIVE ACCOMMODATING ACCUSTOMED ACQUAINTED ACQUISITIVE AGGRESSIVE ALARMIST ALERT ANALYTIC ANGRY ANNOYED ANTAGONISTIC APOLOGETIC APPRECIATIVE ARGUMENTATIVE ATTENTIVE
Mental effect (on person)2 ABHORRENT ABOMINABLE ABSORBING ACCEPTABLE ALARMING ALLURING AMAZING AMUSING ANNOYING APPALLING ASTONISHING ASTOUNDING ATTRACTIVE AWESOME
Physical state of person or thing ACTIVE AFLOAT AGAPE AGLEAM
Notes: 1 behaviour/attitude of smbd who V-s. 2 mental effect on smbd who is V-ed.
Physical nature of person or thing ABSORBENT ADHESIVE AUTOMATIC
Evaluation of person or thing ADVANTAGEOUS
Factual status or relevance ABSENT ABUNDANT ALTERNATIVE ANTICIPATIVE/-ORY APPROXIMATIVE
Situation/location of person or thing ABANDONED ACCESSIBLE
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Agentive adjective phrases 163 smth) has the experiencer as subject, with the mental stimulus appearing as object. In pattern (1–2–03–0–0), on the other hand, the adjective-based structure (e.g. be angry about smth) has an experiencer as subject and a mental stimulus as prepositional qualifier, but the simplex verb pattern (e.g. anger smbd) has a mental stimulus as subject, with the experiencer appearing as object.
III.3.ii Agentive adjective modification and complementation We have seen that agentive adjectives are adjectives of quality. As such they may be ungradable or gradable, and if they are of the latter type, they may be scalar, absolutive or telic/‘liminal’. When considering adjectives that modify eventive nouns (see above section III.2.i), we referred briefly to these different kinds of gradability. They can be aptly illustrated with adjectives of size, as follows: (a) ungradable: (b) gradable: (i) scalar: (ii) absolutive: (iii) telic/‘liminal’:
(?very/?absolutely/?only just) jumbo/mini (very/?absolutely/?only just) large/small (?very/absolutely/?only just) huge/tiny (?very/?absolutely/only just) sufficient
Ungradables offer a yes/no choice; scalar gradables assess the distance along a scale with intensifiers like very, rather, slightly; absolutive gradables express a superlative degree and only allow a corresponding intensifier (absolutely, utterly, etc.); finally, telic or ‘liminal’ gradables implicitly refer to a target or threshold which may be reached or missed by a narrow or wide margin, allowing intensifiers like (only just, easily, not quite, nowhere near), often implying a development through time. Which kind or kinds of degree modification, if any, do the adjectives in our database permit? Non-gradable adjectives found in the database are absent, accountable, afloat, alive, alternate, answerable, anticipative/-ory, automatic. These mostly correspond to simplex verbs that designate events which take place or designate relationships which either clearly do or clearly do not hold. Intensifiers of any kind are therefore generally superfluous. The word alive is however sometimes used in a transferred sense (meaning roughly ‘lively, energetic’) with scalar intensifiers, e.g. very alive; but be (very) alive in this sense no longer corresponds to the simplex live and thus cannot qualify as a stretched verb construction. In an analogous way the meaning of automatic can be adjusted from its binary value (‘automatic’ versus ‘manual’) to mean something like ‘effortless, foolproof’, in which sense absolutely or completely could be used as modifiers. The largest group of agentive adjectives is those that are gradable in a scalar sense, i.e. that allow modification with very, etc. Adjectives in this group comprise absorbent, abundant, abusive, accessible, accommodating, active,
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
164 The event phrase adhesive, advantageous, aggressive, alarmist, amusing, analytical, angry, annoying, annoyed, antagonistic, apologetic, appreciative, approximate, articulate, attentive, attractive. They can all be queried for their degree with the construction How ADJECTIVE . . . ? This wide range means that they cover all kinds of meaning. Absolutives are rather more limited. They fall into two semantic groups: agape, agleam, aglitter and aglow refer to physical states or processes with a sensory effect, whereas abhorrent, abominable, amazing, appalling, astonishing, astounding, awesome describe a mental or attitudinal response to some person, thing or eventuality. A smaller group of adjectives allow either scalar or absolutive modification (e.g. rather/very absorbing beside absolutely/utterly absorbing); the group comprises absorbing, acceptable, accustomed, alarming, alert. Finally, one adjective, asleep, has telic modification, cf. nowhere near asleep, not quite asleep, only just asleep, well/sound asleep, but shades into scalar modification, thus fast asleep, deeply asleep, lightly asleep. Let us turn now from the intensifiers that premodify the adjectives in Structure 1 constructions to the preposition phrases that follow them as complements. These postqualifiers of adjectives may include any of the prepositions about, at, for, from, of, to, towards and with; some adjectives permit a choice between two of these prepositions. In general, though, the choice of preposition gives an indication of the semantic role of the phrase it introduces. A common semantic role for the prepositional complement is that of ‘mental goal’, i.e. the focus or target of the mind when it experiences the behaviour expressed by the adjective: in the meaning, accountable, accustomed, answerable and attentive require to; alert requires to; and acquainted requires with. The semantic role of ‘mental stimulus’, on the other hand, refers to the phenomenon that causes a particular mental reaction: for this meaning agape takes at; angry and annoyed take about, with or at; accountable takes for; and appreciative takes of. The person or persons who are subjected to the particular kind of behaviour can be described as ‘patients’ (or as ‘affected persons’): they are introduced by the preposition to or its close relative towards following the adjectives abusive, accommodating, aggressive, antagonistic and apologetic. Persons, however, who experience such a mental reaction can, with the appropriate adjective, be referred to in a prepositional complement: this meaning is expressed by to or for after the adjectives abhorrent, abominable, absorbing, acceptable, accessible, advantageous, alarming, alluring, amazing, amusing, annoying, appalling, astonishing, astounding, attractive and awesome. Finally there are some more minor prepositional complements: a location at which someone or something is not present is introduced by the preposition from in the combination absent from; a province, sphere or field is expressed by in in the combination active in; and the entity characterized is expressed also by in in the combination abundant in (e.g. abundant in oil, cf. also oil in abundance). As to the syntactic value of these preposition phrases, a few are integrated as prepositional complements of the object noun, i.e. as elaborators of the adjective, while the majority remain as outer elaborators, qualifying
11
Agentive adjective phrases 165 rather the verb or the verb–adjective-complex as a whole. Integrated adjective complements are found in patterns like be appreciative of smth or be attentive to smth, while outer verb phrase elaborators can be exemplified by be alarming to/for smbd, be acceptable to/for smbd, be analytic about smth or be antagonistic towards smbd, cf.: (22) (a) Sybil was very appreciative of Peregrine. (b) ?Of Peregrine Sybil was very appreciative. (c) Peregrine(,) Sybil was very appreciative of.
11
11
111
111
111
111
(23) (a) Sybil was very antagonistic towards Peregrine. (b) Towards Peregrine Sybil was very antagonistic. (c) ?Peregrine(,) Sybil was very antagonistic towards. As the examples of (22) and (23) show, a preposition phrase that is a complement to a descriptor adjective cannot be naturally fronted as a sentential theme or topic (although its component noun phrase can), whereas a preposition phrase that elaborates an outer verb phrase can readily be thematized, certainly more readily than its constituent noun phrase. These outer verb phrase elaborators mainly refer to persons and have semantic roles like ‘experiencer’ or ‘patient’.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Part IV
The thin verb
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
11
IV.1 The individual thin verbs, their meanings and collocations
11
11
111
111
111
111
IV.1.i Thinness and predictability of meaning Apart from the deverbal (eventive) noun phrase (including any qualifiers and modifiers it may have) the other essential constituent of a stretched verb construction is the thin verb that helps stretch the construction to verb phrase status. It is clear that such semantically lightweight elements have a syntactic role to play, and indeed they have to be selected so as to be of a suitable valency for the following noun phrase or preposition phrase: a copular verb is needed for Structures 1, 2, 3 and 4, an intransitive verb for Structure 5, and a transitive verb for Structure 6. But precisely how are the individual thin verbs selected – on a purely syntactic basis, on an arbitrary lexical basis, or on a semantic basis? The ways deverbal eventive nouns combine with thin verbs can be compared with the way such nouns combine with thin prepositions. When we considered this question in the previous section, we found there that a limited number of prepositions is used, and that they are selected partly as a lexical combination with the deverbal noun, but that this choice is in part semantically motivated. In the case of combinations of thin verb with deverbal noun, there is, however, a difference of scale: whereas we found in our corpus about fifteen prepositions combining with a total of about 130 eventive nouns (giving something over 300 combinations), we find the 130 eventive nouns combining with 110 verbs (to give about 350 combinations). It is clear that many more combinations will be found as soon as the database is extended to cover nouns beginning with letters of the alphabet other than ‘A’, and the number of nouns will increase commensurately. The number of prepositions is likely to stay the same, whereas the number of thin verbs will probably rise moderately. The verbs used in Structures 1, 2, 3 and 4 are copular and chosen regularly without any collocational restrictions. For Structures 5 and 6, on the other hand, the situation is different: the thin verb is selected specifically for use in the stretched verb construction and the choice is largely determined by the noun. The basic statistics found for Structures 5 and 6 can be roughly summarized as follows (where noun means ‘deverbal eventive noun’):
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
170 The thin verb 132 nouns (some polysemous, giving rise to 143 noun meanings) 15 prepositions 113 thin verbs92 180 or so noun + preposition 350 or so thin verb + noun combinations combinations Projecting the figures to what they might be for the whole of the English lexicon, we might assume that prepositions have virtually reached their peak and thin verbs will no more than double and thus arrive at statistics something like the following: 2,400 nouns (some polysemous, giving rise to 2,600 noun meanings) 15 prepositions 150 thin verbs93 3,000 combinations of noun 7,000 combinations of + preposition thin verb + noun On the face of it, then, the main difference between the two kinds of combination lies in the smaller number of prepositions, which is not so surprising considering their status as grammatical function words. This would suggest that thin verbs, belonging to a larger paradigm, simply have a slightly ‘thicker’ meaning than prepositions. Closer inspection of the statistics, however, reveals a slightly more complex situation. If we look at the overall frequency (combining the figures for postnominal qualifiers and other preposition phrases occurring after deverbal nouns, both eventive and agentive) we find the following figures, counting cases of free variation: to for of with to/0 from
86 56 50 48 41 39
of/’s on in at against
37 21 20 18 10
at-the-hands-of between into among
8 8 5 1
This reveals a range from the very rare among through between, at-the-handsof, into and against with low frequency and at, in and on with middle frequency to the high frequency items about, for, from, of, of/’s, to,94 to/0, and with with no very large breaks along the scale. If we now turn to combinations of thin verbs with a deverbal eventive 92 The figure is based on counting prepositional verbs as instances of the simple verb but counting phrasal verbs (with adverbs) as separate items. 93 The figure is based on counting prepositional verbs as instances of the simple verb but counting phrasal verbs (with adverbs) as separate items. 94 Evidently of and of/’s could be merged to give 87, and to and to/0 could be merged to give 127, but this would not greatly change the overall picture.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
The individual thin verbs 171 Table 4.1 Frequency of thin verbs in structures 5 and 61 (in combination with deverbal nouns in data base) make give have get carry-out feel grant provide receive suffer cause come do offer find undergo form go put-in take work-out arouse commit gain obtain perform present reach
54 29 15 13 10 10 9 9 9 9 8 7 7 7 5 5 4 4 4 4 4 3 3 3 3 3 3 3
TOTAL 360.
secure spark-off add arrive attract bring call capture catch command elicit enter file hold incur induce meet place practise press provoke put put-on render retain stir-up win afford
3 3 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 1 1
assume break bring-about bring-in burst calculate come-in conclude conduct create dance deliver devote draw drive-home effect engage experience express extend fill focus forge heap hurl indulge initiate inspire
1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
issue launch lie lodge minister mount move negotiate pay precipitate press-home produce pronounce publish put-forward put-up record register run send-in shout shower stimulate strike-up subject submit wait
1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
(Structures 1, 2, 3 and 4 all have be with a total of 109 occurrences.)
Note: 1 The figure is based on counting prepositional verbs (as in come to the aid of smbd) as instances of the simple verb (here come) but counting phrasal verbs (with adverbs) (as in come in for abuse) as separate items (here come-in).
noun, again for Structures 5 and 6, we find a rather different profile. Consider the data presented in Table 4.1. As a preliminary, it is worth noting the obvious fact that, despite the rough equality of numbers in our data between eventive nouns and thin verbs (just over a hundred of each), they are not equal partners. We have already observed that in a comprehensive database, the eventive nouns would probably rise twentyfold, while the thin verbs would no more than double. Equally importantly, the eventive nouns have a fairly even distribution, with the most prolific of them only achieving combinations with thirteen different thin verbs. The thin verbs, on the other hand, show a rather different picture, in the sense that a small group of items dominate, with the top four verbs covering nearly one third of the instances
1
1
1
11
172 The thin verb (111 out of 361), and with half of the verbs (56 out of 111) having only one occurrence each. It is natural enough that thin verbs should ultimately be fewer in number than eventive nouns, because they have a thinner, more grammatical meaning and are the ‘servants’ in a ‘master–servant’ collocation (see Part V and Allerton 1990b: 30–5) But the unevenness in the distribution of thin verbs is a different matter and is in need of explanation. Of course these verbs differ in their valency and thus in which of the different stretched verb structures they appear (this point will be considered in section III.2.ii). But over and above that we can ask the question, to what extent they need to be modified in meaning, compared with their normal use, to fit into a stretched verb construction. We also need to ask if and when they are simply selected by the eventive noun, and whether this selection is arbitrary or based on some kind of semantic congruence between the noun and the verb. In this connection it will be worth paying attention to eventive nouns that take different but apparently nondistinctive thin verbs, and asking whether thin verbs that occur with a wide variety of eventive nouns have a similar meaning in all cases. Building on an earlier discussion of thin verbs, under the label ‘general verbs’, cf. Allerton (1984a: 31–4) we can distinguish different grades according to frequency and freedom of collocation: (i) those of high frequency and freedom of collocation (including get, give, have, make, and also be for Structures 1, 2, 3 and 4); (ii) those of medium frequency and freedom of collocation (such as cause, find, offer and suffer); (iii) those of low frequency and freedom of collocation (such as add, calculate, focus, pay); and (iv) those that are unique or nearly unique to one particular deverbal noun (e.g. dance in dance attendance on smbd, lodge in lodge an appeal).95
11
11
11
Such a grouping can of course only be approximate and provisional. For one thing, it is not yet clear whether the frequencies listed in Table 4.1 for collocations with eventive nouns beginning with the letter ‘A’ are at all typical for the English lexicon as a whole. A thin verb that occurs only once in our data (which represent perhaps 5 per cent of the whole English lexicon) might occur twenty times in the whole lexicon, but it might not occur again at all. Similarly, some verbs might be over- or under-represented by the statistics given in Table 4.1: there are grounds for believing that the verb take, for instance, occurs rather more commonly than these figures (four occurrences out of 361) suggest (cf. take a bath, take a look, take a ride, take a shower, take a walk; take offence etc.). All thin verbs have a rather general meaning and are semantically more 95 In a few cases the thin verb occurs exclusively in the company of the eventive noun, e.g. curry favour with smbd; this gives the expression in question the status of an idiom.
11
11
11
111
The individual thin verbs 173 lightweight than the same verb would have been in a normal context. The difference in semantic value is obviously connected with their relationship to the eventive nouns they combine with, in that an eventive noun selects an appropriate meaning from the range of meanings available for the verb.96 This selection must presumably work out differently according to the frequency and freedom of collocation of the verb in question, since a high frequency verb like do or have, with its typically wide range of meanings to select from, is semantically more flexible than a low frequency verb like add or focus, with its typically narrow range of meaning, from which little or no semantic selection is necessary or even possible. Thus at the two extremes of frequency two radically different strategies of semantic selection seem to be operating: high frequency thin verbs are general enough to fit in with the semantics of a wide range of eventive nouns; low frequency thin verbs are semantically precise, but their very preciseness creates a niche, and their semantic congruence with an individual eventive noun forms a bond with it usually involving a degree of redundancy (as in add an appendix or ask a question).97 Let us begin by considering thin verbs of high frequency, i.e. high frequency in general use, as exhibited by a data-base like the LOB, for which we could take over 1,200 occurrences as a cut-off point for high frequency. On this basis (which corresponds fairly well to the total number of polysemous readings)98 the verbs be, come, do, get, give, go, have, make and go can be considered as belonging to this group. As the following statistics make clear, they are not all equally represented in stretched verb constructions: Thin verb
Text frequency
Submeanings overall
Submeanings in str. vb constr.
Occurrences in str. vb constr.
111
BE COME DO GET GIVE GO HAVE MAKE TAKE
41,295 1,607 4,317 1,402 1,469 2,117 13,334 2,471 1,835
18 15 16 19 10 22 14 13 19
9 4 3 4 5 4 6 2 4
109 7 7 13 29 4 15 54 4
111
96 As a result, the same verb-plus-noun combination can be found with two different meanings, according to whether the verb is occurring in a normal use or as a thin verb, e.g. take smbd’s notes compared with take notes (for smbd). 97 Such redundancy is particularly obvious in combinations involving morphologically related verbs and nouns, such as so-called ‘cognate objects’ like sing a song. See V. 1. iii. 98 The number and identity of polysemous readings proposed here has taken the lists given in the Cambridge International Dictionary of English as a starting point, but the analysis has been modified considerably and examples have been added.
111
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
174 The thin verb As we might expect, there is a general correlation between text frequency and broadness of meaning, as partly reflected in the number of polysemous readings. What is at first sight less obvious is why the verbs make and give should be rather overrepresented in thin verb use, while go and take are rather underrepresented. A closer examination of individual readings might explain this, for instance by showing that they are the most suited to being thin verbs because they are best able to carry the verbal meaning that remains once the meaning of the deverbal noun has been extracted. In considering this question, we should remember that the semantic basis for using these high frequency verbs seems to be that the verb already has a wide range of meanings, and if one of them is not suitable for combining with the eventive noun, a further related meaning can readily be developed. We should also bear in mind that the list of submeanings given for each verb represents just one attempt to distinguish and enumerate the ‘different’ meanings to be observed; clearly every observer would come up with a slightly different list. But the aim in what follows is to differentiate all meanings that do not always go together (in other languages) and to put together meanings that can be regarded as being predictable from a knowledge of the accompanying subjects (and objects). Listing these separate meanings does not imply that they are unrelated; on the contrary, we shall assume that polysemy rather than homonymy is the norm.99 Submeanings certainly can form at least a chain of linked readings and more commonly a set of meanings with multiple connections between them. It may even be possible to find a common thread running through all the polysemous readings for a given verb, as Ruhl (1989) advocates. In considering the range of meanings of each verb, analysable collocations have been included, but opaque idioms have been excluded. In the lists that follow many examples have been chosen from the Cambridge International Dictionary of English, which uses real text examples and organizes them into polysemous readings in a systematic way (though this does not correspond perfectly to the organization adopted here). The examples quoted are verb phrases, in the sense of verb elaboration structures, and they therefore appear in the (bare) infinitive form. Where ambiguity is a problem, a possible subject noun phrase has been added in square brackets before the verb phrase. Some colloquial or idiomatic expressions have been given as full sentences in quotation marks.
IV.1.ii Thin verbs of high frequency The most common verb, as measured by text frequency, is be, which occurs in Structures 1, 2, 3 and 4, but of course also in a wide range of other uses. Its total range of submeanings for all its uses, with relevant examples, 99 in so far as it is even possible or necessary to make a distinction between them, cf. Aarts and Calbert (1979: 121–3), Cruse (1986: 79–80).
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
The individual thin verbs 175 is summarized under (a) to (r) below. (Examples containing instances of the verb be have the relevant one in bold italics.) (a) ‘instantiate a type of event or situation’ (be an accident, be a difficulty, be a shame, etc.); (b) ‘equal/constitute’ ([Two and two] be four, [P. and Q.] be a married couple, etc.); (c) ‘come to be identified as’ (be John/me, be the problem, be the general feeling, etc.); (d) ‘count as a member of a class’ (be a doctor, be a mother, be a metal, etc.); (e) ‘possess the (permanent) characteristic/quality designated as . . . (-ness)’ (be rich, be afraid of the dark, be quiet by nature, be a fool, be self-assured, be able to do smth, be pure gold, be onslf, etc.); (f) ‘pass through the (temporary) state/quality designated as . . . (-ness)’ (be ill, be unhappy, be cold, be hungry, be naked, be in a panic, be being a fool, be certain/sure about smth, be angry, be in trouble again, etc.); (g) ‘behave in a manner that is’ (be (being) nice to smbd, be honest with smbd, etc.); (h) ‘have the function of, play the part of, act as’ (be the author/source of smth, be the brains behind smth/smbd, be a/the front for smbd/smth, etc.); (i) ‘have a particular emotive attitude towards smbd/smth’ (be for/against smth, be in favour of smth, be out of touch with smbd, be at odds with smbd, etc.); (j) ‘cost/measure/weigh’ (be 50p each, be six foot tall, be twenty stone, etc.); (k) ‘find oneself/be found somewhere’ (be there, be in my soup, be on the table, etc.); (l) ‘occur’ (be next Tuesday, be during the rush-hour, etc.); (m) ‘exist’ (cease to be, [There] be no room, [There] be no sound, to be or not to be, etc.); (n) ‘continue in progress’ [ = in PROGRESSIVE construction] (be eating, be being selfish, be studying, be coming back etc.); (o) ‘undergo a process’ [in PASSIVE construction] (be pushed, not be asked, be encouraged to leave, be discovered, be gone into, etc.); (p) (be to) ‘should’ (be to visit Australia in the spring, be never to see smbd again, etc.); (q) (be to) ‘must’ (be to sit in the corner, be not to play near the river, be to do what?, etc.); (r) (be to) ‘can’ (be currently to be seen at the City Gallery etc.). Of these eighteen meanings distinguished for the whole range of be only nine have been found in stretched verb constructions. Submeaning (a) (‘instantiate a type of event or situation’) is found in Structure 3 patterns like be an abuse of smth, be an agreement, be an answer to smth, be an attack on smbd, be an agreement between X and Y. Submeaning (d) (‘count as a member of a class’), by contrast, is seen in Structure 2 patterns like be an
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
176 The thin verb assistant/adviser, be an acquaintance of smbd, be an absconder. Submeaning (e) (‘possess the (permanent) quality’) occurs naturally with adjectives and thus with Structure 1 patterns like be abhorrent, be abstinent, be accountable, be acquisitive, be attractive, be authoritative; this also applies to submeaning (f) (‘pass through the (temporary) state/quality designated as . . . (-ness)’) as found in as in be active, be affected, be angry, but this meaning is also found in Structure 4 patterns like be in agreement, be on the attack, be under anaesthesia. A further adjectival submeaning is (g) (‘behave in a manner that is’) as seen in be abusive, be aggressive, be alarmist, be analytic, be apologetic, be appreciative, be argumentative, be assertive and be attentive. The submeaning (h) (‘have the function of, play the part of, act as’) regularly occurs in Structure 2 patterns, as in be an abstainer, be an accompanist, be an accuser, be an actor, be an adjudicator, be an adviser, be an appellant, be an applicant, be an arbitrator, be an assessor, be an assistant. A further source of adjectival structures is meaning (i) (‘have a particular relationship towards smbd/smth’), as seen in be alternate, be accountable to smbd, but this meaning seems to be more common in combinations with preposition phrases including Structure 4, as in be for/against smth, be in favour of smth, be in acknowledgement of smth, be in answer to smbd/smth, be in accord/agreement/alliance with smbd, be in alternation with smth, be in addition to smth. A rare pattern is Structure 3 with submeaning (j) (‘cost/measure/weigh’), as in be an average of smth and smth. Finally submeaning (o) (‘undergo a process’) is found in some Structure patterns with a preposition phrase, cf. be on offer, be under threat, be in use, be under analysis, be on approval, be under arrest, be under attack, all of which have a passive meaning. The range of meanings for the verb be is so wide, that it is not possible to find an overall meaning, however abstract, other than saying that it is a ‘linking’ or ‘connecting’ verb, but the type of connection depends partly on the kind of element with which the subject has been ‘linked’. As we have seen, some of these are adjectives (with various kinds of meaning, including permanent, temporary and actional), some are agentive nouns, but the majority are eventive nouns, and for these predicatives (or ‘descriptors’) the interpretation again depends on whether they take the form of noun phrases or preposition phrases. If we turn to the thin verb come, we again find a wide variety of submeanings, which can be presented as follows: (a) ‘move towards here or towards where the speaker was/is/will be’ (come over (to me), have come (a long way) to this exhibition, come (back (to London)), come (along/away/down/out/over/through) here (from smwh) etc.); (b) ‘reach its/their destination’ ([The post] come at ten, [A train/A report/Money/Produce/The tide] come in, come on (stage), [The time] come, [Results/A visa] come through/in, etc.); (c) ‘achieve, accomplish’ (come to an agreement/arrangement, etc.);
11
The individual thin verbs 177 (d) (e) (f) (g) (h) (i)
11
(j)
11
(k) (l) (m) (n) (o)
‘reach a climax’ (come to fruition, come to a climax); ‘happen’ (come to be here, [An occasion] come round often, come about); ‘receive’ (come into money); ‘be affected by, experience, suffer’ (come up for renewal, come in for abuse, come under attack, etc.); ‘appear on the scene’ (come to smbd’s attention/notice, come to the rescue, come in addition to smth, etc.); ‘change state to be, become’ (come on, come open, come good, come right, come out, come into fashion, come into flower, come (in)to prominence, etc.); ‘start, originate an action’ (come out on strike, come up with an idea, come to smbd’s aid/assistance, etc.); ‘originate from’ (come from smwh/smbd, come out of smwh, etc.); ‘change position from smwh’ (come apart/down/loose/off, etc.); ‘appear in sequence’ (come first/last/nowhere, come before/after smbd/smth, etc.); ‘can be found in context’ (come in three sizes/another colour/all shapes, come in a pink box/with its own wrapping, not come cheap); ‘act like’ (come the innocent, come the anxious parent, come the old soldier, etc.).
111
111
111
111
Of these fifteen meanings only four seem to appear in stretched verb constructions. Because of the basic valency of come the only syntactic pattern to occur is Structure 5, which always involves a preposition. Submeaning (c) (‘achieve, accomplish’) is found in combination with the preposition to and the nouns accord, agreement and arrangement; submeaning (g) (‘be affected by, experience, suffer’) occurs with the nouns abuse and attack preceded by (in) for and under respectively; submeaning (h) (‘appear on the scene’) turns up with phrases like in addition and to smbd’s attention, (in)to prominence; finally, submeaning (j) (‘start, originate an action’) is found before the preposition to and the nouns aid and assistance in a possessive construction. Considering now the thin verb do, we again find a great reduction of submeanings compared with the overall meanings available for the verb, roughly as follows: (a) ‘CODE’ [i.e. use as a pro-auxiliary] (‘Do you want to go?’, ‘Where do you work?’, ‘They don’t like beer’, etc.); (b) ‘perform it’ [= ‘pro-VP’] (‘I could do, but I won’t’, ‘Will you do it for me?’, ‘Do so’, ‘I already have done’, etc.); (c) ‘happen’ (‘There’s nothing/something doing’); (d) ‘be acceptable’ ([This room] do, [This behaviour] not do, never do, do smbd very well, etc.); (e) ‘manage’ (do fine/all right in one’s new job, do very well/badly, do well for onslf, etc.);
1
1
1
11
11
178 The thin verb (f) ‘act/behave’ (do as one is told, do as smbd else does, do right/the right thing, do well to . . . , etc.); (g) ‘perform on stage, etc.’ (do a play, have done all the important roles, do James Bond, do a brilliant impression, etc.); (h) ‘perform/carry out’ (be doing smth, do a stupid thing, do smbd harm, do damage to smth, do everything possible, do one’s best, do business with smbd, do smth about smth, do smth for/to smbd, do smth for a living, do one’s homework/a job, etc.); (i) ‘offer service’ (do three for the price of one, do travel insurance as well as flights, do repairs, do food at lunch-time, do smbd good, do smbd a good turn, etc.); (j) ‘treat suitably’ (do the film reviews/the talking, do the dishes/the carrots/the catering, do the garden wall, do the living room, do my shoes, do one’s nails/teeth, do the flowers (beautifully), get one’s hair done, do for smbd, etc.); (k) ‘treat badly, harm’ (do smbd (good and proper), do a house (while the owners are away), have been done, do smbd out of a thousand quid, etc.); (l) ‘study’ (do Chapter 4, do sm Chinese, do History at London University etc.); (m) ‘complete, finish’ (do a puzzle, do a sum, do crosswords, do me twenty photocopies, do a history essay/paper, have done with the scissors, have not done with smbd/talking to smbd, ‘Have you done?’ etc.); (n) ‘achieve time/rate’ (do 200 km an hour, do 50 miles to the gallon/20 km. to a litre, do Paris to Bordeaux in five hours etc.); (o) ‘tour’ (do India, do Nice/Oslo (in a day), do the British Museum etc.); (p) ‘serve sentence’ (do three years, do time, etc.). Of these sixteen meanings only three have been found to occur in stretched verb constructions, although these have a fairly broad meaning, with a relatively wide range of collocants. Submeaning (h) (‘perform/carry out’) can be found with a range of deverbal nouns denoting practical everyday activities, such as the cleaning/cooking/shopping/washing as well as some pastimes, such as sm painting/drawing/exercises, and words denoting damage, e.g. harm/damage/injury. Submeaning (i) (‘offer service’) appears in constructions like do smbd a favour, do smbd the honour of . . . , where the meaning ‘offer a service’ is appropriate. Finally, although the typical object nouns for submeaning (j) (‘treat suitably’) are concrete in meaning, some of them nevertheless are directly formed from verbs and can thus be seen as stretched verb constructions, e.g. do the publicity. Turning to the thin verb get, we find at least the following submeanings (excluding one or two slang uses):
11
11
(a) (b) (c) (d) (e)
‘take possession of’ ( get a new job, get the missing prisoner, etc.); ‘come to experience’ ( get a radio station, get smbd to onslf, etc.); ‘fetch, buy’ ( get sm milk, get sm new curtains, get an electrician in, etc.); ‘make ready’ ( get (the) lunch, etc.); ‘deal with’ ( get it ‘answer the doorbell/telephone; pay the bill’);
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
The individual thin verbs 179 (f) ‘cause an action or state’ ( get smbd into trouble, get smth ready, get an idea across, get smbd to do smth, etc.); (g) ‘use transport’ ( get a taxi, get the bus, etc.); (h) ‘move/go in particular direction or to a destination’ ( get up/down, get on/off the train, get together, get around, get as far as London, get back to base, get through an exam, etc.); (i) ‘cause smbd/smth to move/go in a particular direction or to a destination’ ( get smbd up the stairs, get smth through the door, get smth down off the shelf, etc.); (j) ‘begin to, come to’ ( get to like smbd, get moving, be getting to be like one’s mother); (k) ‘become’ ( get suspicious, get better, be getting a big boy, etc.); (l) ‘undergo a process’ ( get killed, get shouted at, get married, etc.) [ = PSEUDOPASSIVE]; (m) ‘experience’ ( get a lot of snow, get pleasure from smth, get a bad mark in an exam, etc.); (n) ‘contrive to experience’ ( get good results, get a good job, etc.); (o) ‘receive goods or services’ ( get a good salary, get smth for one’s birthday, get the news, etc.); (p) ‘have available’ ( get time off, get good holidays); (q) ‘understand’ ( get the message/joke, get smth wrong); (r) ‘hit’ ( get smbd (in the leg) ); (s) ‘annoy, confuse, arouse’ ( get smbd [slang uses]). At least four of these meanings are found in stretched verb constructions: submeaning (f) occurs in transitive constructions like get smbd access, get smbd into bother (with a causative meaning), whereas submeaning (l) can be exemplified by corresponding intransitive constructions like get access, get into an argument; submeaning (m) appears in expressions like get an airing with an inanimate subject, while patterns like get an answer, get smbd’s approval are strictly vague as far as the (m)/(n) distinction is concerned. The range of nouns found with the thin verb get could be said to fall into three groups: the largest group are nouns referring to treatment or a service given to a person or to a thing on behalf of a person, such as abortion, absolution, abuse, acclaim, acquittal, advice, aid, airing, answer, apology, applause, approval, assent, assistance, assurance, attention, awakening; a second group refer to an office or power bestowed on a person, such as access, admittance, appointment, authority, award; and a small group refer to a process being begun, such as (get an) ache, (get into an) argument. Overall, the meaning of the thin verb get can be summed up as ‘experiencing something, contriving to experience something or beginning to experience something’. The verb give has a rather narrower range of submeanings, with roughly the following values:
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
180 The thin verb (a) ‘pass goods to new owner’ (give smbd a present, give generously to charity, give up one’s seat, etc.); (b) ‘perform a service for others’ (give a concert, give a party, give smbd a hand, etc.); (c) ‘perform an action on a thing or person’ (give the car a push, give the child a wash, etc.); (d) ‘propose a toast to others’ ([I] give [you] the Queen); (e) ‘allow/permit/grant freedom to act’ (give smbd a chance, give smbd three weeks to do smth, etc.); (f) ‘cause others to experience smth’ (give smbd an idea, give smbd an appetite, give (smbd) to understand that . . . , etc.); (g) ‘emit (= cause others to smell/hear)’ (give a snort, give off a smell, give out a noise, etc.); (h) ‘decree (= cause others to suffer a verdict)’ (give smbd three years, give the batsman out); (i) ‘yield’ (give in/way, give ground); (j) ‘stretch, weaken’ (give under the weight of a load, give out, etc.). About half of these meanings are found in stretched verb constructions: the core meaning (a) is rare in this use, appearing in give smbd an award; meaning (b) is probably the most common, as exemplified by give smbd advice, give smbd aid, give smbd an answer, give smbd applause, give smbd an appointment (= ‘appoint smbd’), give smbd an assurance; a close relative of (b) is (c), and this is found exclusively in stretched verb constructions, as in the examples cited or in give the clothes an air, give the subject an airing, give the computer a kick, etc.; the permissive meaning of (e), as in give smbd access, give smbd admission, give smbd authority, is rather less common; meaning (f) ‘cause others to experience smth’ is seen in give smbd one’s attention, give smbd a beating (experiences which are not necessarily of benefit to the ‘patient’; finally, a close relative of the latter meaning, namely (g) ‘emit’ is found in give a bellow, etc. In most cases, though, give as a thin verb suggests action that is beneficial in the sense of facilitating action by other people, informing other people or performing a service for them. Thus whereas make emphasizes the change or product associated with an act, give stresses rather the benefit for other people or the effect on them.100 The range of eventive nouns that collocate with give is in line with the range of submeanings: what is ‘given’ is commonly a right or permission to act (in the form of nouns like absolution, access, admission, approval, assent and authority); alternatively the thing ‘given’ can be information (as evidenced by the nouns account, address (= ‘speech’), answer, appraisal or assurance) or a different kind of service, either a general one (rendered by mass 100 This may explain why we ‘make a statement’ but ‘give an order’; but the meanings are close enough to permit overlap and arbitrary selection between the two thin verbs.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
The individual thin verbs 181 nouns like advice, aid, applause, assistance or attention) or a particular one (rendered by nouns like appointment, bath or blow-wave). The verb go, although not so common as, for instance, come as a thin verb, nevertheless has to be placed in the ranks of verbs of high frequency, as the following suggested list of submeanings demonstrates: (a) ‘move elsewhere’ (go closer, go shopping, go and have a look, go back there again, go to school, go down/up, go for a walk, go into a tunnel, go into a tree, go round to Bill’s, go on ahead, go out to Austria, go to bed, go off at a tangent, etc.); (b) ‘be given/sold to smbd’ ([Notices] go out, [Money] be going to smbd, be going cheap, etc.); (c) ‘lead elsewhere’ ([A road/path] go to Birmingham/through the wood, [Records] go up to 1930, etc.); (d) ‘move, be in motion’ ([The bus, etc.] be going, get the car going, go along at 50 mph, go around (telling people), go around/about together, go around in smbd’s head, [A bug, etc.] be going around, etc.); (e) ‘change to opposite state’ ([The clocks] go back/forward, go down (in smbd’s opinion), [The sun] go in, [Lights] go off/on); (f) ‘become’ (go red, go bald, go senile/blind/deaf, go mad/beserk, go bad/off, go wrong, go bankrupt/out of business, go Tory, [A swelling] go down, go into effect/ service, go into a trance, etc.); (g) ‘become weak/ineffective’ (be starting to go, go at the elbows, ‘The bulb’s gone’, etc.); (h) ‘remain (in a bad state)’ (go hungry, go unreported, etc.); (i) ‘develop, happen, elapse’ (go on, [Time] go (by), go off (well), go well/badly, go and lose one’s watch, etc.); (j) ‘fit, belong’ ([An article of furniture] go against the wall, go nicely into the corner, . . . where everything goes, go together, go with smth, go hand in hand with smth); (k) ‘be acceptable, give advantage’ (go well in the lounge, go with the blue dress, go together, have everything going for one, ‘Anything goes’, etc.); (l) ‘operate’ (‘The watch won’t go’, have been going for 50 years, go it alone, go slow); (m) ‘make physical movement’ (go backwards and forwards (with one’s foot), go [like this] with your hand, go like so, etc.); (n) ‘make noise’ ( ‘go “beep” ’, ‘The door bell went’, ‘The alarm went off ’, ‘go quack’, etc.); (o) ‘sound, run, read, be expressed’ (‘How does that song go?’, ‘It goes smth like this’, ‘The story goes that . . .’, ‘The rumour is going around that . . .’, etc.); (p) ‘take up, start’ (go back to the original plan, go back to one’s old ways, go into journalism, go over to cigars/unleaded fuel, go to war, get going with the proposals, go to smbd’s assistance/help, etc.); (q) ‘take on, accept’ (go to a lot of trouble, go on a diet, ‘I could just go a hotpot!’ (North of England));
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
182 The thin verb (r) ‘experience’ (go through a crisis, go off smth/smbd, etc.); (s) ‘behave, respond’ (go with the crowd, go by the name of X, ‘Don’t go telling Dad’); (t) ‘judge’ (go by smth, go on smth, not have much to go on/by); (u) ‘target’ (go at smth/smbd, go after smbd/smth); (v) ‘can be divided’ (go into 12, ‘5 into 11 won’t go’). Of these many different submeanings for the verb go in general, only a few are found in thin verb use: the meaning (f) ‘become’ or perhaps better ‘assume a new state’ is found in expressions like go missing, go into production, the meaning (h) ‘remain (in a bad state)’ can be seen in adjectival patterns of Structure 1 like go hungry, go unreported; the meaning (p) ‘take up, start’ appears in go into action, go to smbd’s aid; finally, the meaning (q) ‘take on, accept’ turns up in go to a lot of trouble, go on a diet. But go is relatively rare in stretched verb constructions, only appearing with four eventive nouns from our limited corpus (action, aid, arbitration, assistance), in all cases with an ‘inceptive’ meaning. In the analysis presented here have, in its overall use, has about a dozen submeanings: (a) ‘hold, possess, own’ (have a dog, have a new car, have no money, etc.); (b) ‘include as a part’ (have black hair, have a new roof, have no entry for a particular word, etc.); (c) ‘be related to smbd who has the role of’ (have two brothers, have a Swiss mother, have a new boss, etc.); (d) ‘be in (a relationship to smbd)’ (have a friendship/pact/etc. with smbd); (e) ‘be characterized by’ (have good qualities, have many advantages, etc.); (f) ‘produce the mental effect on smbd (of V-ing), be the mental goal of smbd’s emotion’ (have an effect on smbd, have an appeal for smbd, have smbd’s approval, have a fascination for smbd [one sense]); (g) ‘intuit, feel, be mentally driven by’ (have a motive for doing smth, have a terror of smth, have the wrong attitude, have an admiration for smbd, have a fascination for/with smbd/smth, etc.); (h) ‘experience (the effects of)’ (have a cold, have a pain, have difficulties, have a marvellous time, etc.); (i) ‘perform the (relevant) action or function involving’ (have a game, have a party, have dinner, have a baby, etc.); (j) ‘receive, accept, consume’ (have letters/news from smbd, have smbd staying, have some more coffee, etc.); (k) ‘suffer the effects of action by others’ (have one’s car stolen, have a request refused, etc.); (l) ‘cause action’ (have the house painted, have (got) smth working, have a tooth out, etc.);
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
The individual thin verbs 183 (m) ‘be responsible for completed action’ (have the report ready, have the problem solved, have solved the problem [ = PERFECT]); (n) ‘must’ [in combination with to] (have to go to Manchester, have to be there by six, etc.). Of these meanings rather less than half (six out of fourteen) are found in stretched verb constructions: expressions like have an alliance/association with smbd may be thought of as a variant of (a); constructions like have an appeal could have been placed under (e), but we have placed them under a separate but adjacent submeaning (f); constructions like have an aim, have aspirations can be accommodated under the (g) submeaning; submeaning (h) (‘experience (the effects of)’) occurs in constructions like have an ache, and something very close to it in ‘passive’ stretched verb constructions like have an abortion, have an airing, have an application; a common pattern (at least in British English) is a variety of submeaning (i) with the value ‘perform a single but not necessarily complete action’, as in have an argument, have an attempt, have a bath, have a chat.101 It is difficult to suggest a single general meaning for the thin verb have, because the range of meanings is so broad. In fact, some cases of ambiguity are found, at least in interaction with polysemy in the eventive noun: for instance, have an approach, in addition to the meaning given under (g) ‘intuit, feel, be mentally driven by’ (where approach means roughly ‘attitude’) also appears with the submeaning (k) ‘suffer the effects of action by others’, in uses such as have an unwelcome approach from an unpleasant man (where approach means roughly ‘personal contact’). This fairly wide range of meanings has the consequence that a wide variety of eventive nouns is found with have, about which, it seems, no worthwhile generalization can be made, although particular submeanings obviously restrict the choice. Considering the relative concreteness of its meaning, the thin verb make has an unexpectedly wide range of submeanings, which can be summarized as follows: (a) ‘produce, create, cause to exist’ (make bread, make clothes, make aircraft, make a mess, etc.); (b) ‘transform, produce out of smth/smbd else’ (make an athlete out of smbd, make old paper into cardboard, etc.); (c) ‘free up, cause to be free’ (make time, make a day of it); (d) ‘tidy up’ (make the bed); (e) ‘perfect’ (make smbd’s day, really make the party/event etc.);
101 Constructions with have in meaning (i) ‘perform the (relevant) action or function involving’ will be given a special discussion below (section V.1.iii).
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
184 The thin verb (f) ‘cause an individual event, force smbd to do smth’ (make the dog bark, make smbd’s eyes water, make people laugh); (g) ‘perform/cause a type of event’ (make a sound, make an effort, make difficulties); (h) ‘prove, turn out to be’ (make a good teacher, make fascinating reading, etc.); (i) ‘calculate to be’ (make the answer 12, make it 2.37 p.m., etc.); (j) ‘constitute, be’ ([2 + 2] make 4, make a (good) pair, etc.); (k) ‘reach, succeed in arriving in time for’ (make the early train, make the last bus, etc.); (l) ‘go’ (make off, make for the seaside, make a beeline for . . . ); (m) ‘earn, produce money’ (make a profit, make £50,000 a year, etc.). One meaning found in stretched verb constructions is the core meaning (a), as in make an adaptation, make an arrangement; but the more common meaning is (g), as in make an accusation, make an acknowledgement, make an advance, make an agreement, make an allusion, make an approach and many other examples. This meaning (‘perform/cause a type of event’) is clearly related to the core meaning (‘produce, create, cause to exist’) and is at the same time general enough to be compatible with a wide range of eventive noun meanings. The range of eventive nouns found with make seems wide (as a result of the verb’s frequency) but still seems to fall into a small number of groups: in very many cases what is ‘made’ is a legal or official speech act (an accusation, admission, affirmation, agreement, appeal, application, appointment, arrest, assertion or award); in a second, smaller group a personal speech act (an acknowledgement, allusion, annotation, answer or approach) is involved; a third group of eventive nouns are mental judgements (analysis, appraisal, assessment and assumption); the nouns of the fourth group (abridgement, adaptation, adjustment, alteration, amendment) describe a modification made to a thing; in a related group the nouns (acquisition, addition, advance) denote increases of some kind. There are also some nouns that seem semantically isolated, as the range of near-synonymous alternative verbs shows (make (cf. put in) an appearance, make (cf. carry out) an attack, make (cf. do) atonement), but they may all involve an element of physical display. In general, however, make can be said to have a meaning something like ‘carry out a social, linguistic or cognitive act, usually involving a significant change in an object or the situation or the speaker’s view of it’. We come, finally amongst the thin verbs of relatively high general frequency, to the verb take, which in its overall use, has at least the following submeanings: (a) ‘accommodate’ ([A container] take six litres, [A car] take five people, [A camera] take two batteries, etc.); (b) ‘consume’ (take sugar and milk in one’s tea, take the medicine/tablets, etc.);
11
11
11
111
111
The individual thin verbs 185 (c) ‘need, use’ (take (a lot of ) nerve/courage, take size five shoes, take some believing, take ten minutes (to do smth), take smbd all day, take time, take one’s time, take time off work, etc.); (d) ‘receive, agree to accept’ (take a free gift, take £50,000 in the first week, take credit cards, [A school] take boys, take a newspaper, take a cottage in France, take responsibility, take a joke, [A shop] take smth back, take it or leave it, etc.); (e) ‘experience, suffer’ (take a blow to the head, take offence, (sit there and) take it, take it lying down, not be able to take it, ‘Take it as it comes’, etc.); (f) ‘consider/attend to’ (take smth seriously, take the/smbd’s point, ‘Take last week’, take smbd to be smbd, take smbd for smth, take it all back, take it that . . . , take my word for it that . . . , etc.); (g) ‘grasp (hold of)’ (take smbd’s hand/arm, take one egg, take this bag (while . . . ), take (up) a pen, take hold of smth, take smbd unawares, etc.); (h) ‘seize possession of ’ (take smth without paying, take a/smbd else’s baby, take (several) prisoners, take smbd prisoner, take the city, take smbd’s bishop, take the seat from the government, take power, take (up) office, take first prize, etc.); (i) ‘remove, extract’ (take smbd’s clothes/notes/pen, take smth away from smbd, take an idea/plot from a source, take off one’s clothes/the covers, take smth off the shelf, take the seeds out of the fruit, take a lot/it out of smbd, take smbd out of themselves, take smth apart/to pieces, etc.); (j) ‘move to new position’ (take smth smwh, take the book over/down to Mary, take smth with you, take smth back to the shop, take down the curtains, take down/up the hem, etc.); (k) ‘travel by’ (take the train, take the 10.30 flight, take the road on the left, take the bend too fast, etc.); (l) ‘accompany’ (take smbd to do smth, take smbd swimming, take smbd out (to the cinema/for a meal), etc.); (m) ‘teach, lead, select for learning’ (take (smbd for) physics, take the service of thanksgiving, take economics as a main/major subject, etc.); (n) ‘write’ (take notes, take a letter, take down every word, etc.); (o) ‘photograph’ (take sm pictures/snapshots, take smbd performing at the opera, etc.); (p) ‘do item on programme’ (take lunch, take a break, take a holiday/trip, take one thing at a time, etc.); (q) ‘perform/do action’ (take one thing at a time, take it slowly, etc.); (r) ‘react to smth with a particular emotion’ (take it badly, take the failure in one’s stride, etc.); (s) ‘become well attached’ ([Plants] take (in soil), [A skin-graft] take, [The dye] take, etc.).
111
111
Only a limited number of these meanings are found in stretched verb constructions. Submeaning (d) ‘receive, agree to accept’ is found in take advice, with its essentially passive meaning ‘(allow oneself to) be advised’; the closely related submeaning (e) ‘experience, suffer’ can be observed in take abuse, take criticism; examples like take a rest, take a walk probably repre-
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
186 The thin verb sent submeaning (q) ‘perform/do action’ is a reading that is especially common with stretched verb constructions, as witnessed by take action/a decision, take a chance/risk, take a bath/shower, take a look/breath, take exercise/a walk, take a seat, take photographs/pictures, have one’s photograph taken; finally, submeaning (r) ‘react to smth with a particular emotion’ is to be seen in examples like take an interest in smth/smbd, take (sm) notice of smth/smbd, take offence, take pity on smbd, take a (critical) view of smth/smbd, take the view that . . . This relatively short but heterogeneous list of meanings has the effect of producing a very broad selection of eventive nouns, as the above examples illustrate.
IV.1.iii Thin verbs of medium frequency We can turn now from our nine high frequency thin verbs to those of medium frequency and freedom of collocation. Although this group has no clear demarcation, we can regard verbs that have between fifty and 1,200 occurrences in the LOB database as falling into this category, which means that the group contains fifty-four verbs. If we limit ourselves to verbs that occur in at least four stretched verb constructions (the minimum we found for our high frequency verbs), we shall need to consider here the verbs cause, feel, find, form, grant, offer, provide, receive and suffer. These verbs have a rather less general meaning, with the result that the degree of polysemy is lower. Let us consider them briefly in alphabetical order. The first verb cause is something of a special case, in that it does not seem to require any semantic adaptation to be used as a thin verb: in its standard use it means ‘bring about’ and is used with object nouns such as accident or problem, which already refer to events or states of affairs; its use with deverbal eventive nouns like aggravation, alarm, alienation, amazement, amusement, anger, annoyance and astonishment is thus a matter of course. On the other hand, the verb feel has relatively many submeanings in relation to its frequency. At least six different polysemous readings may be distinguished: (a) ‘touch, check the tactile sensation of’ (feel a carpet for softness, feel how cold smth is, feel smwh for smth, etc.); (b) ‘seem, give a tactile sensation of’ ([A thing/body part] feel sore, feel cold, feel heavy, etc.); (c) ‘perceive, receive a tactile sensation of’ ([A person] feel smbd’s hot breath, feel sweat on one’s neck, feel the heat/cold, etc.); (d) ‘experience a bodily or mental event’ ([A person] feel fit, feel one’s age, feel for smbd, feel an ache, feel alarm, etc.); (e) ‘be in a particular mood’ ([A person] feel lucky, feel sad, feel weak, etc.); (f) ‘be of the opinion’ (feel the time is right, feel that one is in the way, feel onslf to be inferior, etc.).
11
The individual thin verbs 187 The total list of eventive nouns collocating with feel in our data is agony, ache, annoyance, alarm, astonishment, attraction, appreciation, amusement; they thus cover a range from pain through unpleasant emotions to pleasant emotions. They all fit clearly into submeaning (d), and this meaning, in its turn, is well integrated into the polysemy of feel, being close to meanings (c) and (e). Overall the different submeanings of the verb feel means something like ‘have sensory, especially tactile, experience of aspects of the world and react emotionally and intellectually to them’. The eventive nouns listed simply pick out the most appropriate submeaning for their needs.
11 The medium frequency verb find has at least five different submeanings in its overall use:
11
111
111
111
111
(a) ‘successfully seek’ ( find a replacement, find smwh to live, find smbd a flat, find smth smwh, find one’s way, find a way of doing smth, find the/enough money to do smth, find a solution to a crisis, etc.); (b) ‘come across’ ( find a ten-pound note, find a body, find smbd reading/ unconscious, find people doing smth, find onslf smwh, be nowhere to be found, etc.); (c) ‘come to have’ ( find one’s/its own level, find the time/courage to do smth, find one’s feet, find it in onslf/one’s heart to do smth, etc.); (d) ‘experience’ (be found only in the rainforests, find acceptance/application/use, find smbd’s approval, find amusement in smth, find onslf without friends, find onslf, etc.); (e) ‘judge’ ( find smbd (not) guilty, [a jury] find for/against smbd, be found to do smth, find smbd difficult, find smth fascinating, find that . . . , find fault with smbd/smth, etc.). This chain of meaning probably has (b) and (c) at its heart, with the core meaning something like ‘come into physical or mental contact with’. The deverbal nouns that occur with find are the examples acceptance, amusement, approval and application, listed under meaning (d). The combination of find with one of these nouns gives a meaning corresponding roughly to a passive verb, e.g. be accepted. Turning next to form, we see within its uses three rather different meanings, each associated with a different valency pattern: (a) ‘come into existence’ ([A coral reef] formed in the ocean, [A crowd] form around an accident, [A solution] form in one’s mind, etc.); (b) ‘come to have (an idea)’ ( form the impression/opinion/view, form an affiliation with smbd/smth, etc.); (c) ‘(come to) constitute/be’ ( form a normal diet, form the next government, form part of a network, form the basis for smth, form (up) into a square, form a barricade, etc.).
1
1
1
11
11
188 The thin verb Meaning (a) is found with form in an intransitive use, corresponding roughly to a verb like appear; meaning (b) involves a transitive use, roughly equivalent to something like produce; meaning (c) appears in copular uses comparable to be or become. It is nevertheless clear that the core meaning of ‘existence’ runs through all uses. In stretched verb constructions, it is the transitive use, (b), that is involved, with one of the eventive nouns affiliation, agglomeration, alliance and association occurring in object position. The thin verb grant seems in normal use to be limited to the following three submeanings: (a) ‘formally give’ (grant funds to buy machinery, grant smbd travelling expenses, grant smbd an entry visa, etc.); (b) ‘allow, give permission for’ (grant smbd access, grant smbd a favour, grant smbd an audience, etc.); (c) ‘accept another’s opinion, give way in argument’ (grant that smth is the case, take smth for granted, etc.). The appropriate meaning for stretched verb constructions is clearly submeaning (b), which is found with eventive nouns such as absolution, access, admission, annulment, authority, award, all of which refer to official acts or rights. Submeaning (a) is probably the core one, and (b) apparently has a close relationship to it, involving a metaphorical kind of giving. The verb offer can be regarded as having the following five submeanings in general use: (a) (b) (c) (d)
‘volunteer to give’ (offer smbd food/a prize, offer smd a job/chance, etc.); ‘volunteer to do’ (offer to babysit, offer free legal advice, etc.); ‘potentially have’ (offer many advantages, offer scope for improvement, etc.); ‘do, perform’ (offer an apology/one’s apologies, offer (up) a prayer, etc.).
It is this last submeaning that is found in stretched verb constructions, in which nouns like advice, answer and argument are found, with the last two frequently occurring in the negative. The overall meaning of offer in stretched verb constructions is something like ‘do something willingly or because one has agreed to’. The verb provide, across the total range of its uses, appears to have five submeanings:
11
11
(a) ‘supply (needs)’ (provide meals, provide aid, provide for the children, etc.); (b) ‘take precautions, insure against’ (provide against injury, provide for possible accidents, etc.); (c) ‘ensure, make arrangements (for)’ (provide for the detention of terrorists, provide that terrorists be detained, etc.);
11
11
11
111
111
The individual thin verbs 189 (d) ‘cause, make possible’ (provide opportunities, provide amusement, etc.); (e) ‘perform’ (provide the accompaniment/entertainment, etc.). Of these meanings, three are found in stretched verb constructions: for the (a) meaning provide assistance (to) (= ‘assist’) can be cited; for the (d) meaning provide amusement (to/for) (= ‘amuse’) is found; and for the (e) meaning provide the accompaniment (for) (= ‘accompany’) is an example. The range of collocating nouns thus tends to refer to events that can be interpreted as positive services, such as accompaniment, aid, amusement, answer, assistance, and the general meaning of provide as a thin verb is ‘ensure the occurrence of an event by supplying goods or performing a service’. For the verb receive four submeanings have been found somewhere amongst its general uses: (a) ‘benefit from a gift (of goods or money)’ (receive a gift, receive a prize, receive a pay rise, receive an award, etc.); (b) ‘be the recipient of a communication’ (receive a letter, receive news, receive a report, receive a reply/answer, etc.); (c) ‘experience action by others’ (receive education, receive an ovation, receive good/bad treatment, receive attention, receive aid/help, receive someone’s approval/ attention, etc.); (d) ‘welcome, demonstrate pleasure at playing host to’ (receive the guests, receive a deputation, receive the athletes with acclaim, etc.). As these examples show, eventive objects are found with all of the submeanings (a), (b) and (c), although submeaning (c) is probably the most general and the most frequent; submeaning (d) occurs with an eventive prepositional objoid (receive with acclaim). As an antonym of give, the verb receive is probably tailor-made for the function of thin verb in stretched verb constructions with the underlying object as subject, in other words, with an overall ‘passive’ meaning, as in receive good treatment from smbd beside treat smbd well. It seems to occur with eventive nouns denoting experience of action by others (absolution, acclaim, approval, attention), help (advice, aid, assistance) and communication (answer).
111
Finally, among thin verbs of medium frequency, we come to the verb suffer, which is more limited in its semantic range, having two basic meanings, (a) and (b) and one transferred meaning (c) that is valid for thin verb use:
111
(a) ‘feel pain, depression, etc. at’ (suffer terribly, suffer in the cold, etc.); (b) ‘be affected by illness’ (suffer from asthma/cancer/a cold, etc.); (c) ‘experience smth unpleasant’ (suffer a setback, suffer casualties, suffer the consequences, etc.).
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
190 The thin verb Examples of eventive nouns that occur with suffer are abuse, affront, aggression, agony, ailment, alienation, annihilation, annoyance and awakening, all referring to unpleasant experiences, including awakening, which is typically premodified in this use with adjectives like rude and unpleasant.
IV.1.iv Thin verbs of low and very low frequency Turning now to verbs of low frequency and freedom of collocation, i.e. those with less than sixty occurrences in the LOB corpus, we can concentrate on those that occur in more than one stretched verb construction. There are five constructions with undergo, four with put-in, three with arouse, commit, render, secure, work-out, and two with attract, capture, command, file, incur, induce, indulge, practise, put-on, stir-up. It is apparent that these verbs generally have a more specific meaning than those in the middle group. On the question of the number of submeanings, we find (in the CIDE for instance) commit with five meanings, put-on and work-out with four, command and secure with three, practise, put-in and render with two, and arouse, attract, capture, file, incur, induce, indulge, stir-up and undergo with one each. Such verbs obviously have less broadness of meaning and consequently less need for special meanings to be picked out for use in stretched verb constructions. The most common of these low frequency thin verbs in stretched verb constructions, undergo, is worthy of a special note because of its significant role in giving a passive meaning . It has no obvious polysemy apart from the fact that it has a slightly different meaning when it has things rather than persons as a subject: in the latter case the meaning is something like ‘experience a possibly unpleasant process or change’, whereas in the former case there is an even more general meaning along the lines of ‘be affected by the action of an agent’. In either case the meaning is already eminently suited for use as a thin verb with a ‘passive’ meaning. It is found with nouns that designate a process, whether or not they have a kindred verb, such as the following total list of object nouns found in the LOB corpus: change (4), coupling, discipline, examination, experience, experiment, increase, ordeal, process, sentence, spring-cleaning, test, treatment (2). In our stretched verb constructions we find undergo combining with the eventive nouns acclimatization, adaptation, amalgamation, analysis, assimilation. Considering finally very low frequency thin verbs that are unique (or nearly so) to one particular deverbal noun, we find the following examples in our data: add an appendage to smth (cf. append smth to smth else); dance attendance on smbd (cf. attend smbd); drive home an argument (cf. argue for smth); launch an assault/attack on smbd/smth (cf. assault smbd/smth, attack smbd/ smth); lodge an appeal/application (cf. appeal against smth, apply for smth);
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
The individual thin verbs 191 minister aid to smbd (cf. aid smbd); put on an act/affectation (cf. act, affect smth). Such thin verbs all have a fairly precise meaning that limits their suitability as partners of (eventive) nouns. Only add, of the examples cited, is used in a concrete sense: adding an appendage is like adding any other kind of addition, though the noun appendage tells us little about the nature of the item added or appended. Though not used in a concrete meaning, put on is at least used in one of its most common figurative meanings (= ‘affect’, as in putting it on). The verbs dance and minister are used with a secondary meaning that means barely more than ‘perform, carry out’ but uses the literal meaning as a hint about the manner of the activity: dancing attendance is a showy or decorative performance, while ministering aid is a serious or devoted performance. The (partly complex) thin verbs drive home, launch and lodge, on the other hand, have abstract meanings that are metaphorically derived from the concrete literal sense, mostly with a meaning that is coloured by ‘Aktionsart’ or verbal aspect (see below, section IV.2.ii). Except for add, these very low frequency thin verbs do not seem to have any special semantic or other reason for their restrictive use. They are simply collocations that have developed. The verb add, on the other hand, is semantically congruent with its eventive noun attachment, and puts us in mind of cognate verb constructions (see section, V.1.iii). Having surveyed the individual semantic contributions of thin verbs and their interaction with eventive nouns, it is time to ask in what ways they may contrast with each other to produce a systematic semantic contribution. The range of thin verbs compatible with a given eventive noun depends partly on the range of different meanings that can be envisaged with that verb. In particular, the following points emerge: deverbal nouns that refer to events involving two or more participants may allow a distinction of VOICE (to be discussed in section IV.2.i); deverbal nouns that refer to events with duration may pick out a difference of PHASE or ASPECT (discussed in IV.2.ii); deverbal nouns that have a meaning that is open to a variety of antonymy (for instance, reversive antonymy) may involve an implicit contrast of POLARITY (discussed in IV.2.iv).
1
IV.2 The grammatical meanings of thin verbs
1
1
11
11
11
11
IV.2.i Thin verbs, verb valency and verbal voice At the very beginning of our discussion of the different basic stretched verb constructions and particularly of what we called Construction 6102 we noted that some stretched verb constructions correspond semantically to simplex active verb patterns, some to simplex passive verb patterns and some to simplex causative verb patterns. Our scheme of types of restructuring in Part II took account of this point. For instance, give one’s attention to smth is active (= ‘attend to’), receive smbd’s attention is passive (= ‘be attended to’), and draw smbd’s attention to smth is most commonly interpreted as causative (= ‘cause smbd to attend to smth = cause smth to be attended to by smbd’). Obviously, the selection of the thin verb must play an important part in determining the ‘verbal voice’ of the stretched verb construction. Two of the commonest thin verbs, make and give, for example, are used almost exclusively in constructions with an active meaning, e.g. make an adaptation (of smth), give advice (to smbd), whereas the verbs undergo and receive are used almost always with a passive meaning, e.g. undergo adaptation, receive advice ( from smbd). The semantics of make and give, involving, as they do, production or transmission of a product, clearly suggest an active meaning, while the semantics of undergo and receive, involving, as they do, suffering or benefiting from an action, clearly suggest a passive meaning. But in some cases the picture is more complex. It should be made clear at the outset that we are not faced here with the relations of ‘active’ and ‘passive’ in the strict grammatical sense, but in the sense of the semantic relations usually associated with them. Thus undergo adaptation is not a passive elaborated verb structure but simply one with a semantic structure that is typically expressed with a passive sentence, because the subject of undergo is ‘affected/patient’, a typical object role for
102 See Table 1.1 and the discussion of it in I.2.i; see also the discussion of Construction 6 in I.2.ii.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 193 a change-of-state verb. Other verbs, however, have different constellations of semantic roles for their noun phrases and preposition phrase elaborators: mental process verbs, for instance, can have an ‘experiencer’ (= ‘human processor’) as subject with the ‘mental focus’ (= ‘phenomenon focused upon’) as object, as do verbs like love, fear; but they can equally have the reverse pattern as in the case of the verbs enthral, frighten. Both patterns are found in the thin verbs in our data: thus feel and suffer (as in feel annoyance, suffer agony) have the ‘experiencer’ as their subject, whereas cause and inflict have the ‘mental focus’ as their subject (as in cause annoyance, inflict agony). The stretched verb constructions they form can be viewed as ‘active’ or ‘passive’ depending on the simple verb they are kindred with, as shown by the following correspondences between verb forms with different patterns: SUBJECT ‘mental focus/stimulus’ + OTHER ELABORATOR*
SUBJECT ‘experiencer’ + OTHER ELABORATOR* ‘mental focus/
‘experiencer’
stimulus’
annoy (smbd) cause annoyance (to/for smbd )
be annoyed (by smbd/smth) suffer annoyance (from smbd)
cause agony to smbd/cause smbd agony inflict agony on smbd
agonize about/over smth/smbd suffer agony (at the hands of smbd)
Note: * i.e. object, prepositional object/objoid or perject (= ‘agent phrase’). An examination of the above data shows that, by comparison with the corresponding simple verb structure, suffer annoyance can be interpreted as semantically ‘passive’, whereas suffer agony must be seen as semantically ‘active’. But the thin verb suffer makes a similar semantic contribution in the two cases, indicating a mental process experienced by the subject. Any voice classification of stretched verb constructions103 must therefore be seen not so much as the assignment of a semantic feature as rather labelling a relationship to the kindred simplex verb construction. What we are discussing here therefore is stretched verb constructions with a passive semantics. Thus: ‘active’ = ‘passive’ =
retention of simplex semantic role distribution reversal of simplex semantic role distribution
The voice labels are thus in principle semantically neutral, although ‘active’ correlates strongly with an ‘agent’ subject and a ‘patient’ object, and
103 The question of a passive syntax for stretched verb constructions will also be considered in section V.2.iii.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
194 The thin verb ‘passive’ with the reverse constellation. Bearing this in mind and noting that cases like agony/agonize are relatively unusual,104 we can nevertheless make some generalizations about the choice of thin verb in ‘active’ and ‘passive’ structures for the majority of cases. This seems to depend on the kind of state, process or event described and the way persons or things are involved in it. In one type of process or event the simplex verb construction has a verb like advise with an ‘agentive’ human subject and a human object or prepositional object or objoid that is ‘affected’; other typical verbs are absolve, admit, apologize to, and the meaning usually involves a speech-act. In the corresponding stretched verb constructions we find give or grant in ‘active’ patterns and find, get, receive or secure in ‘passive’ patterns, e.g. give/grant versus receive absolution; give versus find/get/receive approval. In addition, there are cases of more individually selected thin verbs, such as hurl/shout versus suffer/come in for abuse and commit versus incur aggression. A second group of patterns has a mental process verb like annoy, a ‘mental stimulus’ subject, and an ‘experiencer’ object; other typical verbs include alarm, alienate, amuse, anger and astonish, all verbs of emotion. In the equivalent stretched verb constructions the ‘active’ thin verb is most commonly cause and occasionally meet with, while the ‘passive’ verbs used include feel, find and suffer, e.g. cause ≠ feel alarm; cause ≠ find amusement; cause, meet with ≠ feel, suffer annoyance. Some eventive nouns only occur in ‘passive’ constructions, e.g. find, meet with acceptance (cf. also agreement, application). A third group of patterns correspond to simplex verb constructions with an ‘agentive’ subject (as in the case of the advise group) but this time with an inanimate ‘affected’ object; the verbs involve structural processing of some kind, such as add, adapt, amalgamate, analyse, assimilate. Stretched verb constructions of this kind have make as their ‘active’ thin verb and undergo or be in/under in the corresponding ‘passive’ construction, e.g. make an adaptation ≠ undergo adaptation; make an addition ≠ be in addition; make an analysis ≠ be under analysis. Interestingly, the eventive noun is countable in the ‘active’ construction and uncountable in the ‘passive’ (cf. section III.1.ii, above). The concept of a ‘causative voice’ involves both grammatical and semantic complexities. Strictly speaking, English does not have CAUSATIVE as a morphological category (as Turkish has, with suffixes like -(d)ir-, -(i)t-, -er-, cf. Lewis (1967: 144–6)), nor even as a standard syntactic construction (as French has, with faire + infinitive). Rather it has a number of competing syntactic patterns (all of them involving embedding) with a causative value (cause smbd to do smth, have smbd do smth, make smbd do smth, etc.), and more importantly a lexical feature CAUSATIVE that relates different lexical items (e.g. kill – die) and different polysemous readings for 104 In other words, the vast majority of English mental process verbs (e.g. annoy, surprise) in the active have a ‘mental focus/stimulus’ subject and an ‘experiencer’ object, so that to fill the general need for animate subjects they are mainly used in the passive.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 195 the same lexical item (as in melt – melt the butter, walk – walk the dog). Since this semantic feature is regularly lexicalized in English, it is natural for it to be the basis for a series of stretched verb constructions, e.g. win smbd’s approval for smth (cf. cause smbd to approve (of ) smth), draw smbd’s attention to smth (cf. cause smbd to attend to smth). But causativity is not a simple concept, and we need to ask precisely what meaning or meanings can be involved. A first point to note is that causativity is a matter of degree. The causing agent can be the sole causer, the principal causer or just a joint causer. Moreover, the causing may involve taking action to further the likelihood of an event (cause smbd to do smth) or even overcome the resistance of some other person(s) (make smbd do smth); but in a more limited interpretation, it can simply be a matter of doing nothing to prevent action being undertaken by some other person(s) (permit/enable smbd to do smth). A stretched verb construction like draw smbd’s attention to smth has the first kind of causative interpretation, whereas one like give smbd access to smwh has the second. A further complication involves the interaction between participants. In a classic case the causer C instigates action by the agent A that affects the patient P; thus C makes, causes or permits A to do something to P. We find this meaning in sentences (1)(a) and (b), with a simplex verb in a causative structure in the first case, and with an appropriate stretched verb construction in the second. (1)
(a) Colin got Adrian to apologize to Priscilla. (b) Colin elicited/got an apology from Adrian for Priscilla.
But in a different construction (which we might call a ‘reflexive causative’ construction) C and P are one and the same person, so that C causes or permits A to do something to P. This can be illustrated by: (2)
(a) Colin got Adrian to apologize to him [ = Colin]. (b) Colin elicited/got an apology from Adrian (for himself).
In (2)(b) an unexpressed goal for the apology is taken to be coreferential with the subject-causer. A thin verb that seems to be regularly used in this way is gain in the constructions gain access/admission/admittance. A further complication for causative patterns arises from differences in semantic valency patterns for verbs. Of the patterns listed below we have already noted (3)(a) and (b) (which correspond as semantic ‘active’ and ‘passive’), but we also need to take account of (3)(c) and (d): (3)
‘mental focus/stimulus’ + SECOND ELABORATOR ‘experiencer’ e.g. The affair caused annoyance to the president. (b) SUBJECT ‘experiencer’ + SECOND ELABORATOR ‘mental focus/stimulus’ e.g. The president felt annoyance at the affair.
(a)
SUBJECT
196 The thin verb (c)
‘agent’ + SECOND ELABORATOR ‘mental focus/ stimulus’ e.g. The president gave his attention to the affair. (d) SUBJECT ‘causer-instigator’ + SECOND ELABORATOR ‘experiencer’ (+ THIRD ELABORATOR ‘mental focus/stimulus’) e.g. The official drew the president’s attention (to the affair).
1
1
1
SUBJECT
Concentrating now on the third and fourth of these semantic valency patterns, we see that (3)(c) differs from (3)(b) in having an ‘agent’ rather than an ‘experiencer’ as subject. But (3)(d) differs from (3)(c) in having a ‘causer-instigator’ as subject, with the ‘agent’ relegated to an ‘experiencer’ role, in this case that of genitive qualifier of the eventive noun occurring as object. Some thin verbs occur in both the (a) pattern and in the unexpanded version of the (d) pattern, an example being attract as in: (4)
(a) The affair attracted the president’s attention/the attention of the president [cf. (3)(a)] (b) The official attracted the president’s attention/the attention of the president [cf. (3)(d)].
11
11
11
11
In these examples the subject is ‘mental focus/stimulus’ in the (a) sentence but ‘agent’ in the (b) sentence, despite the identity of the thin verb attract. Similarly, the verb cause can have either an ‘agent’ or a ‘causer/instigator’ as subject. The range of thin verbs used in ‘causative’ patterns is not as wideranging as that found in ‘active’ or ‘passive’ patterns, but still reasonably broad. Whether for semantic reasons or as arbitrary collocations, certain combinations of causative thin verbs with eventive noun seem to be favoured as more natural, e.g. bring about an agreement/a collapse, cause an ache, elicit an answer/apology, inspire admiration, precipitate an attack, provoke aggression/an attack, spark off applause/an argument, stimulate activity. We turn finally to examples of stretched verb constructions in which the thin verb is neither active nor passive, nor even causative: we have termed these thin verbs ‘neutral’, and in the data collected so far they seem to be just two in number, have and be, the latter occurring in Construction 4 with the preposition in. The ten examples found seem to fall into four rough semantic types, all of them ‘stative’ in meaning. A first set has a meaning ‘have/be in a cooperative arrangement with others’ (with be in submeaning (f) ‘pass through the (temporary) state/quality designated as . . . (-ness)’ or with have in submeaning (d) ‘be in (a relationship to smbd)’ )105 and encompasses examples like be in accord/agreement/alliance with smbd, have an agreement/alliance with smbd. A second group has a semantic value something like ‘have a policy (for future action)’ (submeaning (g) of 105 See above section IV.1.ii.
11
11
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 197 have ‘intuit, feel, be mentally driven by’), comprising have an aim/approach, have aspirations. In a different group again is have an appeal (submeaning (f) ‘have the mental effect on smbd (of V-ing)’ above), while be in alternation, expressing one kind of status a person or thing can have, could probably also be fitted under submeaning (f) of the verb be. It is worth noting that the different possibilities for have mean that something like an ‘active’–‘passive’ contrast can be found in pairs like have admiration for smbd (submeaning (g) ‘intuit, feel, be mentally driven by’) and have the admiration of smbd (submeaning (f) ‘produce the mental effect on smbd (of V-ing), be the mental goal of smbd’s emotion’), with the selection of determiner and preposition making a vital semantic contribution (see above, sections III.1.ii and III.2.ii).
11
111
111
111
111
IV.2.ii Thin verbs, ‘Aktionsart’ and verbal aspect Valency and voice characteristics are not the only major contribution that thin verbs make to the meaning of stretched verb constructions; the choice of thin verb also indicates the kind of action, state, etc. involved, or alternatively its phase; in other words, it makes a contribution in the area of ‘Aktionsart’ or ‘verbal aspect’. The terms ‘Aktionsart’ and ‘verbal aspect’ (translating Russian Д) are used to indicate the different ways the event denoted by the verb phrase (i.e. its action, state, etc.) is mapped on to the dimension of time. These terms are used differently by different writers,106 but it is possible to envisage three levels of description: (i) An underlying semantic level, where the states, processes, etc. of the world of our experience are described; this is the fundamental level at which ‘Aktionsart’ operates. (ii) A lexical level, at which lexical items are selected, each with its individual ‘aspectual character’ (Lyons 1977: 706); for instance, individual verbs can be ‘durative’, ‘inceptive’, or ‘iterative’, etc. (iii) A morphological level, which covers the various ways, derivational, inflectional, and periphrastic, in which a lexeme or lexeme group can be modified to express the appropriate duration, timing, etc. of the state or process; thus a verb (phrase) can be put into the ‘perfective’ or ‘perfect’ or ‘progressive’ aspect. The expression (VERBAL) ASPECT typically refers to this level (iii), i.e. contrasting inflectional and/or periphrastic forms of any verb lexeme like ‘perfect(ive)’, whereas the term ‘Aktionsart’ refers to level (ii), i.e. unchanging semantic qualities of a given verb lexeme (such as ‘durative’, 106 Important contributions include Joos (1964), Vendler (1967), Palmer (1974), Lyons (1977), Dowty (1979), Davidson (1980), Givon (1984), Hopper and Thompson (1984), Langacker (1987), Frawley (1992), Egg (1995).
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
198 The thin verb ‘inceptive’, or ‘iterative’) or to level (i), i.e. the situations the verb (phrase) denotes, like ‘states’. But verbal aspect and ‘Aktionsart’ interact in various ways, and both refer to the duration and timing of different states, processes and events. Semantic contrasts of the kind described at level (i) can thus be produced in various ways: at level (ii) by changing the lexical verb (e.g. travel versus arrive), by changing the verbal construction (e.g. tire versus tire out, attack versus be on the attack), or at level (iii) by changing the derivational, inflectional or periphrastic morphology of the verb. In this study the focus is on the first type of contrast, i.e. on ‘Aktionsart’ at the deepest semantic level. Sometimes we talk about single events, but often we group similar events together as repetitions or habitual actions. This obviously complicates the whole question of the duration of events, since an event that has no real duration can acquire some when it is repeated, so that, for instance, while a cough is momentary, a bout of coughing clearly lasts through time. For the sake of simplicity and brevity, this discussion is limited to simple events. Most sentences can be seen as embodying a proposition that refers to a state of affairs or an event, let us say to an ‘eventuality’.107 A verb is typically used to describe the basic type of eventuality, with noun phrases and preposition phrases added to elaborate the meaning: thus freezing, knowing somebody or something, growing, running (a mile) and building something can be seen as different types of eventuality (or ‘situation’). Although actions are often thought of as the classic eventuality-types that verbs designate, some of the most frequently used verbs designate STATES, in other words, internally unchanging ‘conditions’ (such as be (out of touch), feel (unhappy), have (blue hair), like (bananas), lack ( help)) or static ‘positions’ (such as be at home, stay away, live abroad ), in which an entity finds itself. This means that they are compatible with duration adverbials like for six weeks, ( for) a long time, even when they refer to one specific occasion, cf.: (1)
(a) (b) (c) (d)
Sophie was once out of touch for six weeks. Sophie felt unhappy for a long time. Sophie had blue hair throughout the holiday. Sophie lacked help for ages.
(2)
(a) Sebastian was in the garden for twenty minutes. (b) Sebastian stayed at home for hours on end. (c) Sebastian lived abroad for two years.
States of either type (conditions or positions) can thus be seen as having duration, i.e. persisting through time and as unchanging during this period. 107 Many writers prefer the term ‘situation’, but this suggests both a limitation to states rather than events and also a limitation to a particular time and place; the concept of ‘ type of eventuality’ is not limited in either of these ways.
11
11
11
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 199 They are therefore static eventuality types. They answer questions like What was the situation? or What state, condition or position was S. in?, whereas all other eventuality-types are ‘happenings’ and answer questions What did S. do? or What happened?. One kind of happening is the second eventuality-type, PROCESSES, which (like states) can persist through time but (unlike states) are ‘dynamic’, in the sense that they involve change through time. They can be interpreted as including not only natural processes, as expressed by verbs like grow, rust, leak, float but also agent-controlled processes like walk, read, play, meditate, which would normally be described as ‘activities’. Both of these kinds of process can cooccur with standard duration adverbials, cf.: (3)
(a) On that occasion the ship floated for two months. (b) After that the ship rusted for years. (c) The ship leaked for twenty minutes before anyone noticed.
(4)
(a) That time Sebastian walked for hours and hours. (b) Then Sebastian played (monopoly) for days on end. (c) On that occasion Sebastian meditated for a while.
111
111
As we have already noted, both kinds of process, natural and agentcontrolled, can be seen as happenings involving the subject. The processes (and activities) we have just considered all have duration, but the extent of this duration has to be specified outside the verb elaboration structure, or alternatively can be queried with a question like For how long . . . . . . ?/How long . . . . . . for?. Some combinations of verb with object of other elaborator specify a limited amount of the process of activity as an elaboration of the verb, so that the verb elaboration structure names a complex eventuality-type, e.g. grow six inches, age ten years, play a match. Such verb phrases are not combinable with normal duration adverbials, cf.: (5)
(a) *Sebastian grew six inches for two years. (b) *Sebastian and Sophie played a game of chess for two hours.
but they can be used with an in-phrase of duration, cf.: (6)
(a) Sebastian grew six inches in two years. (b) Sebastian and Sophie played a game of chess in two hours.
111
111
This is presumably because the scope of the process (or activity) has already been limited by a frame, making a duration adverbial for inappropriate, but one with in natural. Such eventuality types are termed ‘intergressives’ by Egg (1995); but it seems simpler to refer to them simply as FRAMELIMITED PROCESSES (or ‘frame-limited activities’, in the case of those
1
1
200 The thin verb that are agent-controlled). They are also found in more complex verb constructions like have a try, take a breath. States and processes (regardless of whether they are frame-limited) both have duration but differ in that processes are dynamic, i.e. constitute happenings. The third major class of eventuality-type, which is also dynamic, differs from both states and processes in having no duration, i.e. being punctual, at least in the eyes of the language user. This group is given the label ‘achievements’ by Vendler (1967) and Dowty (1979), and is referred to as ‘punctual changes’ by Egg (1995); but to emphasize their suddenness and their capacity for being agent-controlled in some cases but not in others, we shall call them simply STROKES.108 The three major types of eventuality are therefore differentiated thus:
1
11
11
11
11
STATES PROCESSES STROKES
static = unchanging dynamic = changing dynamic = changing
with duration with duration without duration
Strokes are therefore momentary happenings, such as the unplanned blink, have an accident, occur to me, notice the time (which might be called ‘turn-ups’) and the planned wink, climb (a hill), throw a ball, note the time (which might be termed ‘coups’). Strokes of both types are of course very natural with punctual time adverbials like at three-o’clock or after the meeting but are incompatible with duration adverbials, unless they are given an iterative or habitual interpretation, as in: (7)
(a) Sophie blinked/winked for ten minutes. (b) Sebastian noted/noticed the time all morning.
Both of these sentences have to be interpreted with the V-ed word meaning ‘kept on V-ing’. Within the class of strokes there are two groups of verb meanings that, while referring to a momentary or punctual event, locate this at one end of a resulting state or process, at the beginning in the case of INCEPTIONS (as in ignite, join, launch a boat, start a clock, set out for London), at the end in the case of TERMINATIONS (as in close a meeting, arrive home). Inceptions imply the occurrence of a state or process that follows the incipient event: for instance, igniting implies a later process of burning, while setting out (for somewhere) implies a later process of going (somewhere). Similarly, for terminations there is an implied preceding event: closing a meeting implies previously holding or chairing it, while arriving implies going or coming. But both inceptions and terminations can be regarded as sub-varieties of strokes. It may also be useful to recognize a comparable subcategory of CONTINUATIONS, a 108 The term suggests on the one hand unplanned strokes of fortune and on the other planned strokes of genius, etc.
11
11
11
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 201 subvariety of processes that implies an earlier process with potential discontinuation: it can be illustrated with verbs like continue and retain. Apart from the three basic eventuality types (states, processes and strokes) and their variants (inceptions, terminations and continuations), there are some compound eventuality types composed of combinations of these. The best known of these is often referred to, following Vendler (1967) and Dowty (1979), as ‘accomplishments’, and can be viewed as a combination of a process (or activity) and an ensuing termination. Verbs or verb phrases that denote processes which come to a climax as their end-point, belong to this category, some being uncontrolled events, like leak out, mature, develop a cold, others being agent-directed, like build a house, catch up (with somebody), learn a poem. Since, however, the term ‘accomplishment’ suggests an agent, we shall use the term CULMINATIONS, as a more neutral term, reserving ‘accomplishment’ for the agent-directed subvariety. Because they simultaneously refer to the process and its climax, culminations allow apparently contradictory sentences like: (8)
111
(a) The tree is in the process of maturing, but hasn’t actually matured yet. (b) Sophie’s been catching Olga up for two hours but still hasn’t caught her up. (c) They’ve been building the house for two years but haven’t quite built it yet.
Such sentences are not possible with frame-limited processes, because the frame limit measures the extent of the process or activity without referring to an end-point as the climax. But culminations share with frame-limited processes the possibility of combining with duration adverbials with in, cf.:
111
111
111
(9)
(a) Sebastian grew six inches in a year. (b) They built a house in a year.
For such duration adverbials no climax is needed; all that is needed is an activity with clear limits, a requirement that both eventuality types fulfil. There is a second type of compound eventuality (one that has so far not been given prominence in the literature) which can be seen as the reverse of culminations; we can term them EXERTIONS. They involve a combination of an inception and a process or state, such that the verb phrase refers both to the initial action of taking up the process or state and to the continuation of it. Verb patterns like stand up, remember (something) and take aim all seem to have this double value, so that we can find uses like (10) that are typical of a stroke (or ‘achievement’) and uses like (11a) or (b) that are typical of a state or process:
1
202 The thin verb (10) (a) (b)
At that moment Sophie suddenly stood up. At that moment Sebastian suddenly remembered the name.
(11) (a) (i) Sophie stood up for ten minutes. (ii) Sebastian remembered the name for ten minutes (but then forgot it again). (b) (i) Sophie’s standing up lasted ten minutes. (ii) Sebastian’s remembering of the name lasted for ten minutes.
1
1
11
11
11
11
The sentences of (11b) are particularly interesting, in that they are strictly ambiguous between an interpretation referring to the inception part of the exertion (i.e. the act of taking up the required state or process) and the more natural interpretation, in which it is the following state or process that lasts for the time referred to. The context of (11a), on the other hand, is slightly less helpful, because it is also found with purely inceptive verbs that implicitly suggest the following process like obtain (the book), which suggest the meaning ‘(begin to) have’. But true exertion verbs refer to a process or state that, once started, can thus be kept going for some time, with the same verb phrase referring both to the starting and the continuation of the process. The label EXERTION is meant to capture this double value. The two examples of exertions we have considered represent slightly different semantic types. The expression stand (up) represents a physical movement to a new (bodily) position and the retaining of this position for some time: further examples are sit (down), lie (down). The verb remember, by contrast, involves a controlled mental act of retrieving something from the memory followed by the retention of it in consciousness for a certain period; forget covers the reverse process, mostly an uncontrolled one, followed by a state of oblivion. The third example cited earlier, take aim, suggests a combination of the physical and the mental, in that the person represented by the subject takes up a bodily position suitable for perceptual activity and then remains in it as long as necessary; an example of the same type is head (for home, etc.). The examples given so far from this proposed new type of ‘Aktionsart’ have been taken from English, but the phenomenon is not limited to English. Considering the French equivalent of sit (down), we find that taking up of the bodily position would be expressed through s’asseoir, while the state following it would be expressed through être assis; but of course in one sense it is different forms of the same verb that are being used. In German things are somewhat different in that two different, but morphologically related, verbs are used, sich setzen and sitzen. But at least one other language, Swahili, is like French in using different forms of the same verb to express both the change to a new state and the new state itself. In this sense a Swahili verb like -simama ‘stand (up)’ can be said to have a double meaning of ‘completion of action and/or resultant state’, cf. Ashton (1944: 15; 37). The following examples can be considered as typical:
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 203 (12) (a) Wanasimama ‘They are standing up [ACTION]’ (b) Wamesimama ‘They have stood up [ACTION] = They are standing up [STATE]’ Further Swahili verbs that follow a similar pattern include -choka ‘be/ become tired’, -furahi ‘be/become happy’, -jaa ‘be/become full’, -kwisha ‘finish, be finished’, -potea ‘be/get lost’, -shiba ‘be/become full with food’ -vaa ‘have/put on (clothes)’. Culminations and exertions are two clear cases of compound eventuality types, but there is possibly a third. Some strokes and processes seem to imply a physical change of state, location or ownership for the entity affected, the so-called ‘patient’ (regardless of whether human or not); indeed this apparently applies to all cases where there is a physical effect on the entity denoted by the object, so that the past participle of the verb also appears naturally as an adjective, cf.: (13) (a) Sophie noticed the window. [cf. *the noticed window] (b) Sophie criticized the window. [cf. ?the criticized window] (14) (a) Sophie cracked the window. [cf. the cracked window] (b) Sophie cleaned the window. [cf. the cleaned window] (c) Sophie borrowed the window. [cf. the borrowed window] The eventuality type found in the examples of (14) might be called ‘treatments’ or ‘strokes/processes with result’, but they can be regarded as a special case of a stroke or process respectively. The full range of eventuality types, both simple and compound, is summed up in Figure 4.1. In examining it we can note that just as ‘activity’ is a label for agent-controlled processes, so ‘act’ is a label for a broad group of agent-controlled eventuality types with a time limitation, ranging from agentive frame-limited activities, e.g. play a match, through agentive culminations (‘accomplishments’), e.g. build a house, to the different kinds of agentive strokes (‘coups’), e.g. wink, join, arrive home. The term ‘event’ is even broader in scope, taking in a comparable range but not limited to agent-controlled types, thus only excluding states and unlimited processes (and activities).109 Finally, ‘Aktionsarten’ are linked to verbal aspect, which for English chiefly means the progressive and the perfect, but cf. Mitchell (1979). These periphrastic forms are in principle possible with all verb lexemes, but in fact the progressive is only natural with verbs denoting processes, because its primary meaning is that a process is or was in progress at a 109 In his discussion of this question, Lyons (1977: 483) defines ‘events’ (including ‘acts’) as momentary; but he takes no account of frame-limited processes (including activities), which are extended in time, although they would normally be thought of as ‘events’.
204 The thin verb
1 EVENTUALITY TYPES
static (by definition also: durative) = STATES [A] (when controlled: → POSITIONS [B])
dynamic = HAPPENINGS
1
durative = PROCESSES [C] (when controlled: → ACTIVITIES [D])
unlimited frame-limited (‘intergressives’)
durative-punctual (i.e. process + termination) = CULMINATIONS [E] (when controlled: → ACCOMPLISHMENTS [F])
1
punctual-durative (i.e. inception + process) = EXERTIONS [G]
11
11
11
11
EXAMPLES [A] S. had blue eyes. [B] S. lived abroad. [C] S. grew (six inches). [D] S. played (a match). [E] S. matured. [F] S. built a house. [G] S. stood up. [H] S. had an accident. [I] S. threw the ball. [J] S. set out. [K] S. carried on. [L] S. arrived.
punctual (i.e. ‘instant change’)
self-sufficient change = STROKE [H] (when controlled: → ACTS [I]) start of process = INCEPTION [J] middle of process = CONTINUATION [K]
end of process = TERMINATION [L] N.B. (i) Agent-controlled subvarieties of [E] (i.e. [F]), [G], [H] (i.e. [I]), [J], [K] and [L] constitute ‘acts’. (ii)Punctual and durative-punctual eventualities (and sometimes limited processes) are said to be ‘telic’.
Figure 4.1 Scheme of eventuality types.
11
11
11
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 205 particular point in time. Sentences like those of (15) with a process verb or verb phrase in the progressive are thus perfectly natural: (15) (a) The crowd was applauding Sybil. (b) The crowd was giving Sybil applause. Stative verbs, however, do not naturally occur in the progressive, cf.: (16) (a) ?These results are agreeing with our earlier ones. (b) *These results are being in agreement with our earlier ones. Verbs that are punctual in meaning, i.e. those that refer to strokes, are normally reinterpreted in the progressive to refer (not to an event in progress but) to an event about to happen, cf.: (17) (a) Sebastian was apprehended as he was assassinating the President. (b) Sebastian was apprehended as he was carrying out the assassination.
111
111
111
111
In examples (15) to (17) we have observed cases in which a simplex verb construction and a stretched verb construction display the same eventuality type (process, state and stroke, respectively); but in (18) we find a contrast between the simplex verb, which designates a process, and what we have come to call a ‘stretched verb construction’, which designates an inception (a subvariety of stroke), cf.: (18) (a) They were applauding when the explosion took place. (b) They were bursting into applause when the explosion took place. (19)
They were about to applaud when the explosion took place.
The meaning of (18)(b) is closer to that of (19) than to that of (18)(a), because the stretched verb construction burst into applause, referring as it does to a punctual eventuality type, is incompatible with an ‘in progress’ interpretation. One particular ‘stretched verb construction’ – the one we referred to in Part I as Construction 4 – is especially interesting in connection with the progressive, because, as Zhang (1995: 95–6) points out, it has a meaning that is partly similar to that of the progressive. Zhang cites example (20), to which we could add example (21), as evidence for her claim that, while a progressive verb form shares with its non-progressive counterpart a ‘dynamic’ component to its meaning (as opposed to the ‘stative’ value of a prepositional–nominal construction), it shares with the prepositional–
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
206 The thin verb nominal construction a ‘localized’ meaning (as opposed to the ‘general’ meaning of the non-progressive verb), cf. (20) (a) (b) (c) (d)
We were in the lead. We were leading (the race). We led the (whole) race. We went into the lead.
(21) (a) The ship was in motion. (b) The ship was moving. (c) The ship moved. It might be better to say that the prepositional–nominal stretched verb construction of the (a) examples simply describes the state or condition of the subject rather than saying what the subject is doing; in other words it conveys a state, i.e. the state of the subject. The simplex verb construction in the progressive (in the (b) examples), on the other hand, clearly describes a process, one that is in progress and that we see neither the beginning nor the end of; in other words, we have only a partial view of this process. The simplex verb construction in the non-progressive form of (20)(c) also refers to a process, but to the whole of it, from start to finish. The stretched verb construction of (20)(d), by contrast, refers only to the inception of such a process. Turning now to (21)(c), which is analogous in form to (20)(c), we see that it does not have an entirely comparable semantic value, since it combines the meanings of inception and following process: in other words, it constitutes an EXERTION. If we examine the simplex verbs corresponding to our collection of stretched verb constructions, we find about a dozen culminations (e.g. analyse, ascend), about half a dozen exertions (e.g. appear), about half a dozen inceptions (e.g. acquire, approach), about three dozen processes (e.g. abuse, advance, alter, applaud), about half a dozen states (e.g. admire) and about four dozen strokes (e.g. achieve, add, allocate, announce, assassinate, award). But to what extent are these eventuality types altered in the corresponding stretched verb constructions? Looking at the ‘Aktionsart’ of each stretched verb construction, we find that in about three-fifths of cases this remains unchanged; in these cases their raison d’être must lie elsewhere. But the remaining two-fifths of stretched verb constructions have an eventuality type that is different from that of the simplex verb construction: the selected thin verb is likely to play the major part in marking this ‘new’ eventuality type. Even in the other threefifths of unchanging ‘Aktionsarten’, the thin verb may partly have the function of reinforcing the chosen ‘Aktionsart’. So to what extent do thin verbs correlate with particular eventuality types? Let us begin with two reservations. First, we saw in the previous
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 207
11
section that thin verbs play a major part in the area of valency and voice; any value they have in the field of ‘Aktionsart’ or aspect will therefore be within this limitation. In addition, we know from the first section of this Part that there are certain verbs, most notably make, give and carry out in ‘active’ patterns and undergo in ‘passive’ patterns, that in any case have a high frequency in stretched verb constructions, making them unlikely to be limited to a single ‘Aktionsart’. Given these limitations, what can be said about the contribution of thin verbs in this semantic area? The most characteristic verbs with an ‘active’ value for the different eventuality types, apart from make, give and carry out, are as follows:
11
STATE PROCESS
11
111
111
111
111
FRAME-LIMITED PROCESS CULMINATION EXERTION STROKE INCEPTION TERMINATION
be, have conduct, engage in, indulge in, practise, provide, render deliver, have, mount arrive at, come to, do, form, reach, work out assume, inspire, put on add, bring (in), effect, grant, perform, present, record, subject arouse, burst into, go into, induce, initiate, precipitate, spark off, spring into, strike up drive home
In our data there are some eventive nouns that permit a rich enough range of thin verbs to give these the function of distinguishing different aspects, e.g. mount/launch/press home an attack. In stretched verb constructions with a ‘passive’ value there is a less clear marking of ‘Aktionsart’, with (apart from undergo) feel, find and suffer being used for both processes and strokes. With ‘causative’ structures, too, the ‘Aktionsarten’ are less well discriminated, although verbs like promote and stimulate seem best suited to processes, such as activity, while other verbs, like bring about, obtain and secure, are semantically more suited to acts like culminations or strokes. The thin verb is not the only possible place for marking eventuality types: we should recall (from Part III) that the ‘Aktionsart’ of a stretched verb construction can also be signalled by the countability of its noun phrase. Thus while processes predominantly use constructions with a singular mass noun phrase or a solo noun phrase, as in commit aggression, provide aid (to smbd), give applause (to smbd), heap abuse (on smbd), make atonement, suffer agony, other eventuality types favour normal countable noun phrases like carry out the/an attack, make the/their announcement(s). Indeed it can be argued that in some sense the difference between things and substances among nominal entities corresponds to the difference between acts and activities for agent-controlled eventuality types.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
208 The thin verb
IV.2.iii Thin verbs and minor semantic features Roughly one-quarter of the stretched verb constructions in our database have had assigned to them, in addition to their voice and aspectual characteristics, a ‘special’ feature representing an additional facet of meaning not found for the majority of constructions. Such features often account for the existence of a range of thin verbs as potential partners for a given eventive noun. If we consider, for instance, the stretched verb constructions that include the thin verb offer, we find the examples offer an answer to smth, offer an apology to smbd (for smth), offer an argument for smth and offer advice to smbd. The thin verb offer used in these constructions is very close to give in the same context, and this is a meaning that is different from the one found in its most literal uses, where it refers to an act of presenting something to another person as a possible gift or opportunity for them to accept or reject, as in offer a book to smbd, offer a job to smbd. In offer an answer to smth, etc. there is not this sense of a choice for the recipient to receive something later: if one is offered an answer, one can hardly refuse it, because it has already been given. The examples offer aid to smbd and offer assistance to smbd are perhaps border-line cases in this respect, because although theoretically they refer to aid or assistance that is offered and can be refused, very commonly in actual use there is an inference that it will be accepted. Despite these partial exceptions, all stretched constructions that include offer seem to retain a semantic component of tentativeness and, to some extent, potentiality (rather than reality). Offer an answer to smth is not quite synonymous with give an answer to smth, and this TENTATIVENESS feature is the extra element exhibited by the offer construction. A rather similar meaning is found in some stretched verb constructions of Type 4, with the verb be followed by a preposition. The examples found, be in aid of smth, be in answer to smbd/smth, be on approval, although having rather different individual meanings, all seem to share the semantic feature EXPECTATION (rather than actual taking place) of the event. If something is ‘in aid’ of a cause or a project, it is aimed at aiding this cause or project. This is even true in the case of an expression like be in remembrance of smbd/smth, with which the event of remembering involves looking back in time, because the stretched construction refers to intended future remembering. The construction be on approval is similar, except that it has a ‘passive’ meaning: something is on approval, if it has been sent, etc., in the expectation that it will be approved of (and subsequently bought). Expressions with under, such as be under anaesthesia, be under analysis, be under arrest, be under attack are also ‘passive’ but seem to involve a slightly different meaning, roughly ‘be affected at the present time by the effects of the process named by the corresponding verb’. It is not clear whether the process itself is still going on: in the case of analysis it probably still is,
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 209 while in the case of anaesthesia and arrest, the process is over but the effects are still present. In either case, we can sum up the meaning with the semantic label ‘persisting effects’, or simply PERSISTING EFFECT. A few stretched verb constructions seem to have a semantic feature that we can call INTENSITY, in the sense that the verbal meaning seems to have an inbuilt degree adverbial modifier corresponding to an adverb like ‘strongly, intensely’: examples are command the attention of smbd (= ‘strongly attract . . .’), focus one’s attention on smth (= ‘strongly direct . . .’), suffer agony/ annoyance (= ‘intensely feel . . .’). A semantically related group including forge an alliance with smbd, secure admission/admittance to smwh, secure/win the approval of smbd, work out an arrangement has a component of meaning that could be summed up as success WITH DIFFICULTY, or, in a word, ‘arduous’. One or two constructions in the collection are characterized by a disapproving attitude on behalf of the language-user: thus the collocations like commit an act and indulge in acting suggest an activity that is viewed very or rather unfavourably. Such cases are be marked as SOCIAL DISAPPROVAL.
IV.2.iv Thin verbs and positive polarity All of the constructions we have considered refer to an actual eventuality rather than its absence. But for many eventive nouns there is a corresponding semantically negative stretched verb construction: for instance, corresponding to give admittance to smbd there is refuse admittance to smbd, and, with a slightly different negative relationship, corresponding to make an allegation there is withdraw an allegation. Since the meaning of our normal semantically positive stretched verb constructions partly depends on their contrast with the corresponding negative construction, it is worth considering briefly the question of the positive-negative contrast, or ‘polarity’, as it is often called. First, it is necessary to distinguish the different kinds of negative meaning illustrated by the examples just mentioned, refuse admittance to smbd and withdraw an allegation: the first of these has the meaning ‘not to (start to) admit somebody’, while the second has the meaning ‘stop alleging something’, put more generally ‘not to (allow to) start an eventuality’ versus ‘(cause to) stop an eventuality’. Some eventive nouns allow just one of these possibilities, others both, and still others neither. Most of them seem to be ‘acts’ (i.e. agentive culminations, exertions, strokes, inceptions or terminations) rather than some other kind of eventuality. We can list the most common examples, compared with their positive counterparts:
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
210 The thin verb ‘(CAUSE/PERMIT SMBD TO) PERFORM AN ACT’
give access make an accusation record an achievement give admission/ admittance take advice come to/have an agreement commit aggression give aid call an alert make an allegation feel anger arouse the anger of smbd make/lodge an appeal have sm appeal make/put in an application have an argument make an arrangement give one’s assent give assistance
‘NOT (CAUSE/ PERMIT SMBD TO) PERFORM AN ACT’
refuse access – – refuse admission/ admittance refuse/disregard advice block an agreement – refuse aid – – suppress one’s anger – – – – – – refuse one’s assent refuse assistance
‘(CAUSE/PERMIT SMBD TO) STOP PERFORMING AN ACT’ – withdraw an accusation negate an achievement – – renege on/break an agreement cease aggression suspend/cut off aid call off/cancel an alert withdraw an allegation swallow one’s anger calm smbd’s anger withdraw an appeal lose one’s appeal110 withdraw an application settle an argument cancel an arrangement withdraw one’s assent cut off assistance
An examination of these examples shows that, although refuse is the most common thin verb for the first negative meaning and withdraw is for the second, there is a certain degree of collocational restriction in their choice: potential collocations like, for instance, ?withdraw aggression or ?cancel an allegation would be highly deviant. This partly results from the individual differences in meaning between the types of eventuality referred to, but also involves arbitrarily selected lexical combinations, such as settle an argument. By contrast with both types of negative stretched verb construction, the positive type simply asserts that the eventuality actually did arise. Apart from this obvious point, is there any significance in the existence of the 110 This construction is ambiguous, the meaning intended here being ‘lose one’s attractiveness’. The construction is also exceptional in another way: it refers to a state, in fact to the coming to an end of a state, rather than to an act, as in all the other cases.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Grammatical meanings of thin verbs 211 contrasting negative constructions? It may well be that if such a negative construction is in the back of the speaker’s mind, a stretched verb construction will be selected in preference to a simplex verb construction. For instance, if the speaker is thinking about and later will talk about ‘settling an argument’ he or she will perhaps favour talking about ‘having an argument’ rather than simply ‘arguing’.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Part V
The lexical status of stretched verb constructions
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
11
V.1 The semantics of stretched verb constructions
11
11
111
111
111
111
V.1.i Idioms, metaphors and collocations Having considered stretched verb constructions from the point of view of their internal structure and their relationship to each other, we must now turn to the question of the part they play in the language as a whole. We have seen that they involve certain arbitrary restrictions on the combination of words, a feature that reminds us of idioms; on the other hand, we have analysed them grammatically and semantically, as we would for any normal construction. It therefore seems necessary to consider briefly the range of word combinations that are not freely formed grammatical constructions but rather selected as wholes from the lexicon. The entire field of idioms, established metaphors and collocations is an extremely complex one, and every specialist in the field seems to have a different approach and a different way of dividing up the phenomena, with the result that the technical terms have different meanings for different writers, cf. Welte (1990: especially chapter V). In his general discussion of idioms Makkai (1972: 24–6; 54–8) first distinguishes what he variously calls ‘phraseological idioms’, ‘phraseologically fixed formulas’ or ‘idioms of encoding’ (in which it is a matter of the selection of a particular lexical item to suit a collocational partner, as in our stretched verb constructions, or the selection of a preposition in a non-literal sense) from what he regards as ‘genuine semantic idioms’ (in which the meaning of the whole cannot be deduced from a knowledge of the meaning of the component lexemes). This second broad type of ‘semantic idiom’ covers all cases of irregular semantic combinations, but the two main subtypes he distinguishes are ‘lexemic’ and ‘sememic’ idioms. Although the basis for the distinction lies in the theory of stratificational grammar, in practice ‘lexemic’ idioms operate at the level of words and phrases and are at least partly opaque, whereas ‘sememic’ idioms mainly involve clauses and sentences that are semantically at least semitransparent in meaning.111 Makkai further divides his lexemic idioms (1972: 135–69) into phrasal verbs, ‘tournure idioms’ (a rather mixed bag, including 111 Makkai also envisages ‘hypersememic idioms’, which again operate at the sentence level but in a pragmatic way; however, the boundary between sememic and hypersememic idioms is less than crystal clear.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
216 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions many verb phrases), irreversible binomials, phrasal compound idioms, ‘incorporating verb idioms’ and pseudo-idioms (containing a unique element like cran- or fro). Of the various subvarieties of sememic idioms (1972: 169–79) he lists, the only one that does not involve full sentences is ‘first base idioms’, which apart from their reference to the game of baseball seem indistinguishable from ‘tournure idioms’. In their account of idioms and related phenomena Burger et al. (1982) offer what they call a ‘hybrid structural/semantic classification’, which is partly inspired by scholars in Russian phraseology. Besides stretched verb constructions (‘Streckformen’ or ‘Funktionsverbgefüge’) their subcategories include ‘phraseological wholes’ (roughly, full idioms), ‘phraseological connections’ (in which one element, in connection with the other, receives a special interpretation), ‘pattern formations’ (which follow a stereotyped syntactic pattern and have a standardized meaning), phraseological similes, irreversible binomials, ‘fixed phrases’ (which are sentence-length idioms), and finally proverbs and commonplaces. Stretched verb constructions themselves are defined by the criterion of replaceability with a simplex verb derived from the same stem as the abstract deverbal noun that lies at the heart of the construction. Roos (1989) offers a slightly different analysis, or at least a different terminology. As a general term for all word combinations that are not formed purely by grammatical rule he uses the term ‘fixed expressions’. These he then divides into subtypes that are ‘not always clearly delimited and frequently overlap’ (1989: 217), embracing proverbs, stereotypes and clichés, catchphrases, quotations, slogans and similes or stereotype comparisons, and, apart from idioms, irreversible binomial, social formulae and gambits. Roos also refers to what he calls ‘two productive patterns’, one of which is ‘verb + it’, the other being ‘verbal groups, i.e. expressions with almost empty verbs: have a look, make a move, take care’; the latter are discussed in Dirven (1989: 46–9), an earlier contribution in the same volume, but not under the heading of ‘idioms’ or other expressions characterized by ‘idomaticity’. In her account of the field of ‘phraseology in the broad sense’, i.e. nonliteral expressions, Palm (1995) distinguishes between ‘idiomatic’ and ‘non-idiomatic’ expressions, listing under the latter ‘non-idiomatic wordpairs’ (i.e. binomials), speech-act formulae or clichés, sayings or commonplaces, formulaic expressions of the mass media, standard epithets (‘stehende Epitheta’) and terminological designations (‘terminologische Benennungsstereotype’). Within idiomatic expressions (‘phraseology in the narrow sense’) she distinguishes those that are fully idiomatic as against those that are only partly idiomatic, and her ‘types’ of idiomaticity include transparent metaphors, opaque metaphors and ‘specializations’, i.e. expressions consisting entirely of grammatical words. But stretched verb constructions are apparently excluded from any kind of phraseology because they simply serve to express aspect (1995: 2).
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 217
111
Mel’cˇuk (1998) refers to all constructions that are not freely and regularly constructed as ‘set phrases’ or ‘phrasemes’. These are divided up according to whether they involve a purely semantic restriction (‘semantic phrasemes’) or whether they also or solely involve a restriction on permitted combinations of individual words or phrases (‘pragmatic phrasemes’ or ‘pragmemes’). Semantic phrasemes are then further subdivided into full phrasemes (i.e. idioms with irregular meaning), quasi-phrasemes or quasiidioms (i.e. combinations that include the expected semantically regular meaning but have an additional unpredictable semantic component), and finally semi-phrasemes or collocations (i.e. constructions in which one free semantic choice is combined with one contingent choice). Collocations, in their turn, are subclassified into four groups depending on the way the contingent form and meaning of the semantically dependent element are selected. Mel’cˇuk also proposes a theory of lexical functions to account for the precise semantic value such dependent items may have: in the field of stretched verb constructions this identifies three semantic types of thin verb112 according to the position of the eventive noun, ‘Oper’ for eventive nouns as objects ( . . . declared war on . . . ), ‘Labor’ for eventive nouns as prepositional objects113 ( . . . went to war with . . . ), and ‘Func’ for eventive nouns in subject position (War broke out between . . . ). Certainly for Mel’cˇuk stretched verb constructions are an important kind of collocation, and collocations are at the heart of phraseology. A more practical approach to phraseological units is represented by the work of Moon (1998). She breaks down non-literal expression into three basic types, each of which has subdivisions: anomalous collocations consist of ill-formed collocations (by and large, etc.), cranberry collocations (to and fro, etc.) and phraseological collocations (in action, on show, etc.); formulae subdivide into simple formulae (you know, in this day and age, etc.), sayings (an eye for an eye, etc.), proverbs (enough is enough, etc.) and similes (as nice as pie, etc.); and finally metaphors are subclassified as transparent metaphors (rock the boat, etc.), semi-transparent metaphors (grasp the nettle, etc.), and opaque metaphors (kick the bucket, etc.). Stretched verb constructions would probably have to be accommodated under phraseological collocations (‘those where there is a limited paradigm operating at one (or more) of the word-slots . . . but the realizations are restricted to a small set that is not fully productive’); but they are also in a sense both ‘formulaic’ and ‘metaphorical’. In the face of this lack of a theoretical and terminological consensus, it seems reasonable to attempt a generally acceptable summary of the facts about non-literal constructions. Such a summary was attempted by Barkema (1996), and the one presented below differs from his mainly in
111
112 Alternatively called ‘support verb’, ‘light verb’, or, to use Mel’cˇuk’s own expression, ‘semi-auxiliary verbs’. 113 Some of Mel’cˇuk’s ‘(prepositional) objects’ would count as (prepositional) objoids in the analysis offered in the present study.
11
11
11
111
111
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
218 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions emphasis and terminology. This present account will be set out under the six criteria of semantic analysability, lexical selection, regularity of combination, degree of deviation from linguistic norm, grammatical patterns involved, and pragmatic or textual interpretation (of a sentence). But it goes without saying that they are all interconnected. Probably the most striking feature of a non-literal construction is its SEMANTIC ANALYSABILITY (or irregularity), i.e. the fact that it has a meaning that cannot be totally ascribed to the meanings of its constituent words semantically combined in accordance with the grammatical construction(s) of which they are part. Its semantic analysability is therefore at best only partial. In fact, we can make a distinction between those cases in which the whole construction has a special meaning and those in which one word has a special value in the context of the construction. In the first case the meaning of the construction as a whole is subject to semantic adjustment relative to the regular or ‘natural’ meaning of the phrase, and three kinds of such adjustment can be distinguished, although it is in practice often difficult to draw lines between them, and they should be thought of as prototypes rather than clearly defined categories. In the first subvariety, the basic meaning of the constituents and of the construction is maintained, but with a slight shift in the mean-ing of the whole and of at least one of the parts. This is the typical situation in the case of a compound lexeme, such as black market ‘illegal trading system’ or take a/the hint ‘understand and act on a veiled message’. When, however, the construction involves a shift to another, normally figurative, plane of meaning, as in rough diamond ‘superficially unattractive but fundamentally worthy person’ or draw the line at smth ‘reach the limits of one’s willingness’, we normally speak of an established metaphor or a meta-phorical idiom. Finally, the term pure or opaque idiom is appropriate for those cases in which, for the normal speaker, all semantic links to the ‘natural meaning’ are absent, as in red herring ‘irrelevant issue’ or get smbd’s goat ‘annoy smbd’. The other main type of semantic irregularity is when a single word (rather than the construction as a whole) has an abnormal value in the construction under examination. This may be a special semantic adaptation (to suit the context)114 of the word in question but one that still can be linked to the basic meaning of the word in question, giving rise to a kind of polysemy, as in white wine ‘yellowish-coloured wine’, offer resistance ‘voluntarily perform resistance = resist’; we could call such combinations RESTRICTED COLLOCATIONS. The other possibility is that the word in question has a unique idiomatic meaning only in combination with one partner word and that the meaning is unrelated to the basic meaning, resulting in homonymy, as in tall story ‘improbable story’ or crack a joke ‘make/tell 114 In Allerton (1982: 27–9; 89–90) and (1984a: 21ƒ) the notion of ‘semantic tailoring’ is introduced to describe this.
11
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 219
111
a joke’; such combinations could be termed ONE-SIDED IDIOMS. Both of these phenomena can be considered as collocational in a broad sense, and in both cases there is one word that is freely chosen for its meaning, the ‘base’, and another that collocates with it, the ‘collocant’. An alternative terminology, suggested in Allerton (1984a) is ‘master’ and ‘servant’, in the sense that the ‘servant’ word is selected and semantically dominated by its partner ‘master’ word. The BBI Dictionary, i.e. Benson et al. (1986a), which aims to exclude idioms, covers both of these kinds of collocation. An aspect of non-literal expressions that is closely linked to their semantic irregularity is their LEXICAL SELECTIVITY. Of course any semantic limitation within a construction involves a simultaneous restriction on the choice of its constituent words, so that all the semantic phenomena we have just considered, most particularly the latter two, restricted collocation and one-sided idioms, are also lexical in nature; they most commonly involve the interaction between lexical choice in different grammatical categories, for instance choosing the appropriate adjective for a particular noun. But sometimes a lexical item has a very limited contribution to make, because it is partly or even largely redundant in the construction in which it occurs. Such redundant collocants occur mainly in patterns like coordination (safe and sound, aches and pains), similes (as fit as a fiddle) and structures with repetition (man to man, hour after hour), in each of which one element is redundant to some degree. The lexical selection of such redundant elements is partly determined by semantic relations like nearsynonymy, co-hyponymy or exemplification, but partly also by phonological factors like alliteration and assonance (or total identity, in the case of repetition!). A further aspect of idioms, collocations and the like, which partly overlaps with the semantic and lexical aspects we have just considered is the question of their REGULARITY OF COMBINATION. In virtually all of the patterns and examples taken account of so far there has been a grammatically regular construction with lexical or semantic restrictions on the occurrence of one or more of the constituents. We could have a mild degree of grammatical irregularity in the repetitive noun-plus-prepositionplus-(identical) noun constructions like man to man, which have the value of an adverbial, despite their strange internal structure with a preposition in a position where we would expect a conjunction like and. A slightly higher degree of grammatical deviance is to be seen in examples like by and large, in which a coordination of preposition and adjective yields an adverb.115 The use of unique items like the kith of kith and kin, or the lurch of leave in the lurch, could be seen as cases of lexical irregularity.
111
115 Normally coordination involves items of the same grammatical class which are combined to give a compound structure still of the same basic class, e.g. hills and valleys (constituents and construction: nouns), above and beyond (constituents and construction: prepositions).
11
11
111
111
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
220 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions No matter how irregular a construction is, it still belongs to the language and is in principle shared by all speakers. But linguistic change is possible at all times, and some speakers, such as poets, comedians or outsider groups, are often at the forefront of such innovations. Any linguistic expression may therefore be absolutely normal or it may show some degree of DEVIATION FROM THE SEMANTIC OR PRAGMATIC NORM. An individualistic poet may produce a new metaphor, for instance, that is so deviant that it makes all readers and listeners pause in puzzlement, for instance, Dylan Thomas’s stained with spilt words. Alternatively we may immediately recognize an expression as new but on a familiar pattern, so that it is novel rather than deviant; this would explain the origin of expressions like in work in bureaucratic or journalistic English (as an antonym for out of work). If, on the other hand, an expression is not only normal but even extremely frequent and perhaps more so than its semantics would justify, then it can be labelled as hackneyed.116 Many idioms, metaphors and collocations would deserve this epithet, but also such relatively unidiomatic expressions as clichés, sayings, proverbs and the like. They would all be located at one end of a scale of deviance or normality running from deviant through novel and normal to hackneyed. Non-literal expressions can be seen then to follow (or in some cases, depart from) standard grammatical patterns. Depending on the size of the unit they represent, they can be said to operate at different LEVELS OF GRAMMATICAL STRUCTURE. Some clearly (regardless of their internal structure) function as phrase-constituents in that they replace or could be replaced by a word of the appropriate class but need partner words to become a phrase: for instance, red herring could be replaced by a noun (e.g. diversion), offer resistance to by a verb (resist), up and coming by an adjective (rising), etc. Others seem to operate at the level of phrases (i.e. potential direct constituents of the sentence), e.g. the end of the road (a noun phrase), go to rack and ruin (a ‘verb phrase’, i.e. an elaborated verb structure), of course (a sentence adverbial). Finally, some expressions appear in the role of sentences, which can be exemplified by one of the many proverbs English has, or by a modern expression like I hear what you’re saying with the meaning ‘I know what you mean’; any grammatical classification of these will need to be textual or pragmatic rather than strictly syntactic. Finally sentence-level expressions need to be described in terms of their PRAGMATIC or TEXTUAL INTERPRETATION, i.e. function in the text or discourse. On the one hand, they can be classified in the usual way according to their grammatical structure, i.e. whether they are formally statements, commands, or questions. On the other, they can be seen grouped according to the kind of speech-act value they have: thus A stitch in time saves nine is obviously a piece of advice, while Pride comes before a fall 116 This use of the term ‘hackneyed’ thus corresponds roughly to Barkema’s (1996) ‘familiar (construction)’ and Pawley and Syder’s (1983: 205) ‘memorized sequences’.
11
11
11
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 221 is clearly a warning. Finally, such expressions can be seen as making a particular kind of textual contribution, depending on whether they represent conventional wisdom, a witticism, an insult, an official notice, etc. It might be possible to locate here also the kind of pragmatic or sociolinguistic norms that have the effect of making speakers prefer or not prefer eighteen months to a year and a half or one and a half years, and other such preferences discussed as a possible fourth level of cooccurrence restriction by Allerton (1984a). Now that we have surveyed these criteria, we are ready to summarize them in Table 5.1, bearing in mind that further categories might be required. What then is the status of stretched verb constructions relative to other non-literal expressions? They clearly belong to the nominal or the adjectival subclass of restricted collocations, in which a noun or adjective is the base of the collocation; further they belong to the subvariety in which the base noun or adjective is an eventive one and whose collocants include a thin verb and possibly a thin preposition. Moreover, to qualify as full members of the group, their eventive noun or adjective must be morphologically related to a verb, so that, for instance, have an allergy to smth, be an allergy {of smbd}, be allergic to smth all contain an eventive noun or adjective and follow one of the grammatical patterns we have established for stretched verb constructions. But there is no corresponding simplex verb construction, simply because there is no verb *allergize or *allergue or the like. If we apply our criteria rigorously, we can at best regard such cases as examples of a defective stretched verb construction (see section V.1.iv,). We shall be considering the question of the analysability or compositionality of stretched verb constructions in the next section, but it is already clear that, like all restricted collocations (and even semi-idioms), but unlike opaque idioms, they do at least have partial analysability. On the other hand, they are like idioms in being memorized and recalled as wholes from the memory. This leads us to the question whether they can be counted as lexemes or not, a question we will address in section V.2.iii. But already at this stage, we can say that, unlike some collocations (e.g. ADVERBIAL INTENSIFIER + ADJECTIVE, such as very good, absolutely excellent), they seem like single multi-word lexemes in that they might well require a separate entry in a dictionary that attempts to specify all standard unpredictable word combinations. We can sum up this point rather crudely like this:
111
Opaque idioms
Stretched verb constructions
Other collocations
Free constructions
in memory in memory not in memory lexeme status no lexeme status no lexeme status semantic analysis semantic analysis semantic analysis
111
in memory lexeme status no semantic analysis
1
1
1
222 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions Table 5.1 Phraseological units – defining criteria for subtypes A. SEMANTIC ANALYSABILITY ( = MEANING OF WHOLE COMPARED WITH PARTS) 1. Whole of construction affected: (a) normal meaning for construction but with additional semantic feature (compound(/complex) lexeme) (b) special figurative meaning for whole construction (= standard metaphor) (c) special opaque meaning for whole construction (= opaque idiom) 2. One constituent affected: (a) specially adapted meaning (→ polysemy) for one constituent (N.B. semantic adaptability of modifiers) (= restricted collocation, cf. B.2(b)) (b) special unique meaning (→ homonymy) for one element (= one-sided idiom) B. 1. 2.
11
11
11
11
LEXICAL SELECTIVITY Fixing of lexical choice of ‘minor’ element: N in simile; P in adverbial PP, P after N/Adj/V; thin V in VP; Degree intensifier n AdjP (selection of collocant to fit base in restricted collocation, cf. A.2(a)) Redundant presence of coordinated elements that are ‘similar’ through repetition and/or synonymy and/or phonological similarity (redundancy of element in coordinative or comparative construction, etc.)
C. REGULARITY OF COMBINATION 1. Grammatically regular pattern but restrictions of combination: (a) both elements restricted (cf. A.1(b) and (c)) (b) one element restricted (cf. A.2(b)) (c) one element with neutralization of semantic distinctions (cf. A.2(a)) 2. Grammatically regular pattern but one element unique (lexical deviance) 3. Grammatically irregular pattern (grammatical deviance) D. 1. 2. 3. 4.
DEGREE OF DEVIATION FROM LINGUISTIC NORM Deviant combination (new ‘unnatural’ metaphor (or idiom??)) Original combination (new ‘natural’ metaphor (or idiom??)) Standard combination (lexicalized/established (semi-)idiom, metaphor or collocation) Hackneyed combination (common lexicalized (semi-)idiom, metaphor or collocation; or cliché, saying, proverb)
E. 1 2. 3.
GRAMMATICAL PATTERNS INVOLVED Lexeme level: N, Adj, V, etc. Phrase level: NP, AdjP, VP, etc. Sentence level (See F below)
F.
PRAGMATIC/TEXTUAL INTERPRETATON, i.e. FUNCTION IN TEXT OR DISCOURSE Grammatical structure (statement, command, question) Speech-act type (advice, warning, request, etc.) Textual contribution (conventional wisdom, witticism, insult, etc.)
1. 2. 3.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 223
V.1.ii The analysability and malleability of stretched verb constructions Semantic analysability was the first criterion we considered in our general analysis of non-literal constructions. In the case of stretched verb constructions, we can say that, as restricted collocations, they have one element, the eventive noun, as a collocational base with its normal meaning, but other elements, including a thin verb, which are semantically tailored to fit the meaning of the base. Our survey of the meanings of thin verbs (in section IV.1) and thin prepositions (in section III.2.ii) showed this clearly. But semantic analysability implies grammatical analysability. Fraser (1970) and Makkai (1972: 52–4, 150–2) (cf. also Björkman (1978) and Radford (1988: 422–4; 430–1)) discuss the extent to which idioms permit manipulations such as exchanges of words, insertion of additional words, permutations of word order and complex transformations such as passivization. Fraser goes so far as to propose a scale of (in)flexibility in the shape of idioms, a so-called ‘frozenness hierarchy’. This ranges such manipulative ‘operations’ on a scale from (at the one extreme) those, like gerundive nominalization, that are possible for all except maximally frozen idioms, to (at the other extreme) those, like clefting, that are only possible for the most analytic of idioms. An idiom like pluck up courage, for instance, is said to be totally frozen, in that the noun phrase courage cannot be varied (*pluck up bravery), the particle up cannot be postposed (*pluck courage up), and passivization is impossible (*Courage was plucked up). A fixed expression like throw in the towel, on the other hand, allows an alternative noun (throw in the sponge), allows the particle in to be postposed (throw the towel in), and probably permits passivization ((?)The towel was thrown in). If we now consider stretched verb constructions in this light, how malleable or frozen do they turn out to be? If we take an example like put in an application (for the job), compared with the simplex construction apply for the job, we find that a near-synonym can replace the noun (put in a request) that the particle can be postposed (put an application in) and that passivization is possible (The job was applied for). Furthermore, the malleability of the construction is confirmed by other tests, e.g. possible variations in the object noun phrase, cf. put in a new application, put in two applications. In general, then, it is clear that stretched verb constructions, if measured against the scale of frozenness of idiomatic constructions, come at the least frozen end of the scale. But it is worth going one step further and asking precisely which parts of a stretched verb construction are totally flexible and which are subject to restrictions of manipulation. Stretched verb constructions are varied in structure, but they all have a thin verb and an eventive noun as part of its elaboration, which in turn is at the heart of a noun phrase; many of them also contain a thin preposition or a particle adverb (or both). We can therefore compare a typical stretched verb construction like put in the application with a comparable
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
224 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions freely rule-generated construction like put out the milk-bottle with respect to grammatical features of this kind: Change in:
FREELY GENERATED CONSTRUCTION
STRETCHED VERB CONSTRUCTION
(BASIC
put out the milk-bottle
put in the application
choice of aspect
be putting out the milk-bottle
be putting in the application
choice of verb
throw out the milk-bottle
?throw in the application
choice of determiner
put out that milk-bottle
put in that application
choice of number
put out the milk-bottles
put in the applications
choice of noun
put out the milk-carton/box
put in the request/*?attempt
noun phrase → coordinate
put out the milk-carton and the milk-bottle
?put in the request and the application
choice of particle
put out/away the milk-bottle (PREDICTABLE MEANINGS)
put in/back the application (UNPREDICTABLE MEANINGS)
clause →relative
the milk-bottle I put out
the application I put in
voice →passive
the milk-bottle was put out
the application was put in
position of particle
put the milk-bottle out
(?) put the application in
FORM)
Looking individually at these tests for flexibility, we find, first of all, that tense and aspect operate as for any other elaborated verb structure. The checks on the grammatical features of the noun phrase (choice of number, determiner) yield positive results in this case and indeed in most cases; but some stretched verb constructions with have (e.g. have a cry, have a read, have a swim, have a wash) seem to have a less nominal meaning in their noun phrase, with the result that such variations in its form are less plausible (e.g. ?have the cry, ?have two cries, cf. further discussion in section, V.1.iii). Varying either the thin verb or the eventive noun alone can bring about an unidiomatic sequence, because they are collocationally restricted, as we
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 225 know. Similarly the choice of adverbial particle (where there is one) is collocationally linked to the selection of thin verb. It is nevertheless clear, even from a schematic look at one example, that stretched verb constructions like put in a/the application do not fall far short of freely generated constructions in terms of operational malleability. That is why they were given the kinds of syntactic description assigned to them in Part II. Eventive noun phrases often function, for instance, as objects in the strict sense: this is a guarantee for their ability to participate in a corresponding passive sentence or to allow clefting. Stretched verb constructions are, however, sensitive as regards their choice of thin verbs, as well as particles and thin prepositions (wherever these occur). As we saw in Part IV, the choice of these elements is made with special reference to the identity of the eventive noun, which seems to adapt or ‘tailor’ their semantics to suit its own needs. Apart from these issues of semantic analysability, there is also the question of the differential syntactic analysis of the stretched constructions compared with their simple counterparts. One aspect of this concerns the link between adverbial particle and verb within a thin phrasal verb. In all phrasal verbs this is a strong link, and obviously it gets stronger the more opaque the semantics of the phrasal verb is; but this seems to make little difference to the mobility of the particle in normal uses of phrasal verbs, so that, for instance, turn the application down is just as acceptable as turn down the application, despite the opaqueness of turn down ‘reject’. When, however, such opaque phrasal verbs appear inside a stretched verb construction, the combination of selectional restrictions (particle–verb and verb–noun) can have the effect of freezing the mobility of the sequence VERB + PARTICLE + NOUN PHRASE, presumably so that the hearer can process the verb–particle combination before combining it with the eventive noun. As a result a pattern like strike up an acquaintance becomes highly abnormal if given the perfectly normal structural ordering *?strike an acquaintance up. It is also worth recalling the restriction (that we noted in section III.2.ii) on the movement of certain preposition phrases linked to eventive nouns: often the preposition phrase dependent on a verb corresponds to a prepositional qualifier of the eventive noun in the corresponding stretched verb construction (as in commit an assault on smbd, provide an answer to smth), but sometimes it retains its status of prepositional objoid or object (as in focus attention on smth, present an award to smbd). Constructions of the first type are more malleable in that, in passive sentences, the preposition phrase concerned can either follow the eventive noun into subject position or stay put in post-verb position, whereas constructions of the second type are bound to stay put, cf.: (1)
(a) An assault on the prisoner had clearly been committed. (b) An assault had clearly been committed on the prisoner.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
226 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions (2)
(a) ??Abuse at the prisoner had clearly been hurled. (b) Abuse had clearly been hurled at the prisoner.
It is perhaps stating the obvious to note that stretched verb constructions containing a prepositional objoid are less malleable than those with a prepositional qualifier of the eventive noun.
V.1.iii Stretched verb constructions compared with rival patterns Stretched verb constructions appear to have a relatively high degree of semantic and syntactic analysability, and yet they seem to be idiosyncratic enough to need recording in the lexicon. Lexically they will obviously have close links to their kindred simplex verb constructions and to other rival patterns. How then do they essentially differ from these? At the level of individual constructions each one has its own precise meaning which has been individualized to meet a precise semantic need. A simplex verb, as a lexical item, most often involves polysemy, but the eventive noun or adjective related to it is often restricted to one of the polysemous readings. The verb act, for instance, has at least three clearly different but still related meanings, namely ‘perform dramatically’, ‘behave’ and ‘be active’ as found in the phrases act brilliantly, act strangely and act quickly; but when it comes to stretched verb constructions, we see that do some acting has only the first meaning, while take action has only the third meaning. Similarly, whereas the verb absorb can have the literal meaning ‘integrate a substance into a fabric’ but also the figurative meaning ‘occupy the attention of’, the corresponding adjective-based constructions be absorbent and be absorbing can respectively have only the first or only the second meaning. Sometimes the polysemy goes so far that it almost becomes a case of homonymy, as in the meanings of accompany, roughly ‘go somewhere with somebody’ and ‘play a musical instrument in a background role simultaneously with another performer’; and only the second of these interpretations is possible in provide the accompaniment. Selecting a stretched verb construction can therefore have the effect of resolving a possible ambiguity between polysemous readings for a particular lexical item. Can we also say something more general about the different types of stretched verb construction? Let us begin with a comparison with simplex verb constructions. There are two obvious differences between simplex and stretched elaboration structures. The first is that simplex structures present the event in the form of a noun, thus tending to reify it (i.e. make it appear like an entity, rather than a true event that actually takes place); an exception is Structure 1, which turns the event into an adjectival quality. The second obvious difference is that simplex structures are relatively short (in other words, ‘unstretched’), giving them a directness of expression and style,
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 227 whereas stretched structures are more expansive, a quality that, interestingly, is in most cases associated with a formal style (e.g. hold a conversation), but in some cases with an informal one (e.g. have a chat), as we shall see shortly. There are verbs which only ever appear in a simplex construction, either because they have no kindred eventive noun, or because the existing eventive noun is ‘inert’, in the sense that it does not combine with a thin verb to form a stretched verb construction. Verbs like abscond, afford, allay, amass, amble, ask, assail and astound have no corresponding deverbal noun for describing the kind of eventuality involved, apart from the universally available gerund (which is found in the do sm V-ing construction, discussed below, in section V.1.iii). Verbs such as abdicate, abolish, absorb, abstain, accelerate, accede, accomplish, accumulate adopt, anticipate, arrive, assemble, attain, augment and avoid differ in that they do have kindred nouns (abdication, abolition, absorption, abstention, accession, accomplishment, etc.), but are the same in that they nevertheless do not have any stretched verb construction to offer; it is impossible to say, for instance, *make an abdication, *carry out the abolition of smth or *do an abstention. In all of these cases the speaker has no choice but to use the simplex verb construction; and yet the verbs do not seem to have taken on a broader meaning themselves to compensate for the lack of kindred stretched verb constructions. When we look at the individual types of stretched verb construction, we realize that they each have their own specific meanings, as we saw in Part I. Structure 1 patterns like be helpful (to smbd), with an adjective at their heart, convert the eventive meaning of the simplex verb into a quality in the form of a propensity to perform or undergo the action or state in question. The ‘active’ meaning of a propensity to perform can be seen in examples like be agreeable, be acquisitive, while the ‘passive’ meaning of the tendency to be the target of an activity or process is found in examples like be abhorrent, be abominable. In non-progressive verb forms (e.g. be agreeable, be abominable) a relatively permanent characteristic is suggested, whereas in progressive uses (e.g. be being agreeable, be being abominable) some temporary behaviour is being referred to. Moreover, as we noted earlier, the greater optionality of verbal elaborators in this adjective-based construction means that the person or thing referred to by the object or prepositional objoid in the simplex verb construction is de-emphasized, the subject therefore being more highlighted. For example, in be agreeable (to the proposal) there is less weight on the proposal agreed to than in agree to the proposal. But of course the major difference remains the fact that the verb-based construction refers to an actual activity, while the adjective-based one is concerned with propensities and tendencies. The noun-centred constructions of Structure 2 have an agentive noun at their heart, as in be a helper of smbd; in some cases, with a kind of ‘passive’ meaning, the noun has instead a ‘patientive’ value, as in be the/an addressee. This means that the subject is seen as having a perhaps permanent, perhaps
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
228 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions temporary role of causer or of target of the event described by the simplex verb. The event itself therefore tends to be slightly backgrounded in favour of this role relative to the event. As in the case of Structure 1 patterns, other entities connected with the event (corresponding to objects and the like of the kindred simplex verb) are even more de-emphasized. For instance, in using the expression be an assistant, we tend to forget who is being assisted, while in saying be the addressee, we often disregard the issue of who addressed the object implicitly referred to. Turning now to Structure 3 patterns, we should recall that they involve a slight semantic anomaly, in that a copular relationship is suggested between an entity, the subject, and an event, the descriptor (= predicative), so that, for instance, somebody or something is said to be a help or be an addition or be an affront. We assumed above that be needs to be understood either figuratively or in a special sense like ‘cause, give rise to, become a source of’. Although the overall meaning is perhaps slightly problematic, compared with Structures 1 and 2, the grammatical subject’s responsibility for the event and more particularly for its results is brought into focus: the persons in question have done something which has this event (e.g. helping, an adding or an affronting, in the cited examples) as a result. Thus the event is seen as an independent phenomenon but one that has a cause involving the entity referred to by the subject. Coming next to Structure 4, we can appreciate that this still involves a copular verb with a descriptor (= predicative), though in the less well studied form of a preposition phrase, and as such can still be seen as ascribing a quality to the subject. But the presence of a preposition in the pattern seems to give an indirectness of meaning, suggesting not so much a major actor as a background circumstance like place, time, or indirect or partial cause. As we noted above, to be of help suggests something weaker or less definite than to help, and to be in the lead something more temporary and transitory than to lead. The precise interpretation of the preposition phrase varies from construction to construction because each has an individually lexicalized interpretation, though this must of course be compatible with the semantic range of the preposition and of the deverbal noun. The examples of (3) give the main semantic structures: (3)
SUBJECT
‘ACTIVE’
+
be +
‘agent, cause’ on, of, in e.g. be on the attack, of assistance, in control
‘NEUTRAL’ ‘characterized entity’ e.g. be in accord ‘PASSIVE’
PREPOSITION
in
‘affected entity’ under e.g. be under attack, under control
+
NOUN
‘process’ ‘state’ ‘process’
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 229 As we noted above, copular verbs other than be are used, such as remain, seem, and when a change of state has to be expressed, this is done with the dynamic verbs get, come and go (but not become), in some cases with a change of preposition, such as in to into, and on to on to. This means that there has been a shift to our Structure 5. Structure 5, then, (like its close relative Structure 6) includes a noncopular verb, i.e. one that fundamentally denotes a happening (rather than a state), although the basic event is rendered by the deverbal noun. How is it possible to have an event expressed in two places? If we compare examples like go on to the attack or present smbd with an award with their kindred simplex constructions, we can see the thin verbs go and present as semantic components that have been extracted from the meaning of the verbs attack and award respectively. The thin verbs extracted in this way in Structure 5 patterns can be divided into three semantic groups: some constructions have a verb of motion with a preposition of destination (e.g. come/go to smbd’s aid, come to an agreement, go to arbitration, move into action); a second group has verbs of activity with a preposition suggesting ‘local environment’ (e.g. indulge in some acting, fill smbd with alarm); a final group with a ‘passive’ meaning has verbs of experiencing with a preposition interpretable as source or cause (e.g. meet with acceptance, suffer from an ailment). In all cases the event is presented as a noun and therefore reified as an entity, but as one that is only linked to the verb of motion, activity or suffering via a preposition, with the result that event comes to be interpreted as a kind of circumstance, rather than a directly involved entity. Structure 6 patterns, by contrast, have the event appearing as an entity that forms part of the valency of the thin verb, giving the impression that the event is experienced more directly. Since it is the largest group, it is not surprising that the range of thin verbs used is much wider, as will be recalled from Table 4.1 in Part IV. The most frequent verbs used in Structure 6 include: make, give, carry out, cause, grant, provide, offer, do, form, put in, take, arouse, commit, gain, go, perform, present, render, secure, work out (with an ‘active’ value); have, get, come, take (with a ‘neutral’ or variable value); and receive, suffer, feel, undergo, find (with a ‘passive’ value). The use of this pattern is thus well-suited to expressing the idea of an event as an entity, and as such one that has been performed by somebody and has affected somebody or something, with either of these primary participants in the event appearing in subject position, depending on the particular construction, and especially on the choice of thin verb. Some Structure 6 patterns may need to be accorded special status, most particularly those involving have followed by an object noun phrase consisting of the indefinite article with a zero-derived deverbal noun, in which the latter has not become a true noun but retains its essential verb status, as in have a taste, have a swim. This pattern was subjected to intensive investigation by Wierzbicka. She suggests that a distinction can be made between the have an N pattern and the have a V pattern (1982: 757f ),
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
230 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions such that the first has a true derived noun, possibly with a suffix, and the second has such an ad-hoc converted verb–noun, as seen in the contrast between have an argument and have an argue. The crux of the distinction comes with verbs that have a normal derived noun formed by zero-derivation, so that the noun and the crypto-verbal pseudo-noun look identical; such a pair would be exemplified by give a talk compared with have a talk (except that the first construction has give rather than have). The talk of give a talk is clearly a lexicalized noun with its own specific meaning (‘informal lecture’), whereas the talk of have a talk is very close to the meaning of the verb. Wierzbicka tries to distinguish these two nouns talk by saying that the second one in some sense remains a verb, and regularly displays certain semantic features, roughly agentivity, a time limitation, experiential consequences only for the performer, and (at least potential) repeatability. In practice, however, she claims that this general semantic value is subject to a number of more specific semantic restrictions, for which Wierzbicka’s semantic formulae could be simplified as follows: (i)
‘aimless and/or recreational, self-beneficial activity’ (have a walk, have a swim, have a lie-down, etc.); (ii) ‘intentional insignificant knowledge-seeking perceptual action’ (have a look, have a smell, etc.); (iii) ‘tentative insignificant knowledge-seeking action’ (have a try, have a look for smth, have a think, etc.); (iv) ‘semi-voluntary possibly self-beneficial action’ (have a cough, have a yawn, have a cry, etc.); (v) ‘pleasurable partial (oral) consumption of things’ (have a bite, have a lick, have a chew, etc.); (vi) ‘(oral-nasal) consumption of substances’ (have a drink of smth, have a smoke, have sniff of smth, etc.); (vii) ‘possibly pleasurable activity involving another entity’ (have a kick of smth, have a throw of smth, have a read (of smth), etc.); (viii) ‘possibly appearance-enhancing self-directed activity’ (have a wash, have a shave, have a bath, etc.); (ix) ‘mutually pleasurable joint bodily activity’ (have a kiss, have a cuddle, have a dance, etc.); (x) ‘possibly pleasurable joint speech activity’ (have a chat, have a gossip, have a laugh, etc.). If this analysis is correct, even with one or two amendments of detail, it represents a chain of polysemous variants of one construction. The meaning of the construction as a whole would be something like ‘a finite, short or self-contained action, completed or broken off, repeatable, and carried out either as an experiment or for the benefit of the subject’. A more important issue, probably, is Wierzbicka’s claim that this proposed construction represents a distinguishably different construction
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 231 from the one we have in the main been dealing with, because the verbderived word, although nominal in appearance, does not become a full noun but retains a partly verbal character. What is the evidence for this? The identity of form with the verb is not sufficient to make the word in question into a verb, since zero-derived deverbal nouns well outside the bounds of this construction are quite common in English (of which countable examples are (an) ache, (an) alarm, (an) attack. A more plausible basis for differentiation is in the measurable countability or enumerability of the events described in the noun phrase: it does not seem normal to ask if somebody is going to have ‘one cough or two coughs’, ‘one wash or two washes’, etc. Equally, the choice of adjectives with this ‘noun’ is somewhat limited: one can ‘have a good cough’, for instance, but whether one can (in a similar sense) ‘have a loud cough’ or ‘have a long cough’ is rather more doubtful. The problem is that such criteria seem to be a matter of degree, and each example tested in this way seems to give slightly different results. It seems unsure, therefore, whether Wierzbicka’s label ‘have a V ’ for such constructions can be fully justified; something like ‘have a [V + Ø]N’ would be more appropriate, since no clear grammatical line can be drawn between, say, have a dance in Wierzbicka’s sense and have a dance (together) in the sense of ‘dance the next waltz, etc. (together)’. There is of course a semantic difference between the two, for instance in the meaning of have; but this difference is no greater than that between have in have a dance and have in have a shock, although the latter takes a subject that is not even an ‘agent’ but rather an ‘experiencer’ or a ‘patient’. It would therefore appear necessary to regard all of these haveconstructions as stretched verb constructions, subdividing them according to various criteria. If we do this for have-constructions, we shall certainly want to do it also for do-constructions, although patterns like do sm advertising, do sm dancing, do sm knitting do seem very close to the simplex patterns advertise, dance, knit, with very little possibility of insertion of an adjective before the pseudo-noun advertising, dancing, knitting. One thing that Wierzbicka’s ‘have a V ’ and what she could have called ‘do sm V-ing’ have in common is their openness to new formations, their informal style and thus the fact they are thus less likely to be recorded in dictionaries. Having considered how individual stretched verb constructions differ from each other and from simplex verb constructions, we should now compare them with possible rival constructions. There are two main candidates, verbs with cognate or semantically predictable objects (such as give/present a gift/present), and phrasal verbs (such as hand in/over). Let us consider them in that order. Constructions consisting of a verb and an object (or other form of complementation) that are closely related, in a morphological and/or semantic sense, can be regarded as a special case of stretched verb constructions. In a standard stretched verb construction the verb is thin (or ‘light’) in the sense that either it already has a broad range of meaning including
1
1
1
232 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions polysemy or it has developed a special semantically weak sense in constructions of this kind. In our discussion of thin verbs in Part IV we distinguished four grades of frequency, of which the lowest was very low frequency verbs that are unique (or nearly so) to one particular deverbal noun. In some cases this limitation seems to be arbitrary (e.g. lodge an appeal/application), but in two cases the choice was, from a semantic point of view, highly appropriate, namely add an appendage to smth, put on an act/affectation. If we extend our exemplification beyond words with initial A- we find many further examples, including strike a blow, eat food, play a game, teach a lesson, lead a life, swear an oath, paint a picture, give a present, ask a question, tell a story. With their tight semantic coherence, such combinations are felt by native speakers to be very natural, and they occur with high frequency. Somewhat less natural are combinations in which the verb and the noun are not only semantically close but also morphologically related. These are verbs with so-called ‘cognate objects’, such as those of (4), which to a greater or lesser degree are unusual in everyday use and have a rather literary flavour: (4)
11
11
11
11
die a tragic/miserable death, do a good/the deed, dream a strange dream, give a gift, grin a friendly grin, laugh a nervous laugh, live a life, paint a painting, see a (strange) sight, sing a song, smile a mischievous smile.
These constructions seem odd partly because of what Bolinger (1979) calls the ‘chime’ effect, but partly also for syntactic reasons. The most unnatural of them seem to be those in which the verb most commonly occurs in the intransitive pattern, i.e. die, dream, grin, laugh, live, smile; in these cases the construction would be limited to special registers, such as poetic and religious English or archaic proverbs. This same limitation seems to apply, however, to some of the grammatically regular patterns, like give a gift, see a sight; the obvious alliteration (or, in some cases, total repetition) is associated in language-users’ minds with special poetic effects, and if these are not intended, the expression is best avoided. Sometimes a synonymous verb or noun is the obvious alternative, as in the examples of (5): (5)
COGNATE VERB
live a life paint a painting tell a tale do a good deed give a gift
SYNONYMOUS VERB
→ → → → →
lead a life (or have a life) paint a picture tell a story do a good turn give a present, present a gift
In a few cases the verb with ‘cognate’ object is perfectly normal, e.g. sing a song, and, although an unusual case, this still requires an explanation. It may appear strange that such combinations occur at all, if the object is
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 233 in any case semantically redundant, but usually either the verb or the noun has shifted its semantics slightly, so that the two do not constitute a perfect match. Sometimes the noun has a more specialized meaning, so that the verb naturally allows other objects, for example, there are other things to sing than a song (as in sing an aria, sing a hymn, sing a nursery rhyme); but even if the meaning of the noun is a perfect semantic match for the cognate verb, it is usually possible to distinguish subvarieties of the object (as in paint a painting but also paint a portrait). In other cases the verb has developed polysemy and its other meanings allow other objects, cf. paint a door beside paint a painting/picture. An example with a clearly Latin eventive noun is add an addendum to smth, which could be compared with add an appendix to smth. Apart from cognate object constructions, the other construction that rivals stretched verb constructions117 is that of PHRASAL VERBS (in the narrower sense, i.e. combinations of verb and adverbial particle). They constitute another way of forming a new lexeme, as an alternative to derivation and compounding, but also to stretched verb constructions. Amongst others, we could consider the following examples: (6)
PHRASAL VERB
KINDRED SIMPLEX VERB CONSTRUCTION
act up act out add smth in/on/up answer smbd back average smth out
act ‘behave’ act ‘perform dramatically’ add smth to smth else answer smbd average smth
An inspection of these examples shows that such phrasal verbs differ from the simplex construction in one of two ways: they may add an extra semantic feature, as in the last two examples, and perhaps also resolve polysemous vagueness, as in the first two examples; or they may bring about a minor syntactic restructuring, as in the add examples, where the particle of the phrasal verb (in/on/up) structurally replaces the prepositional objoid phrase (to smth else). But we rarely find the more substantial kinds of syntactic restructuring we discussed for stretched verb constructions in Part II. Phrasal verbs also differ in that they lack the nominalization (or adjectivalization) value that we find in stretched verb constructions. Finally, phrasal verbs tend to belong to informal English, whereas the majority of stretched verb constructions belong to the formal end of the stylistic spectrum. The third type of non-simplex alternative to stretched verb constructions is the structure usually referred to as ‘catenative patterns’. Palmer 117 A further rival construction is that of verbs with redundant opaque idiomatic objects, such as argue the toss beside the simplex argue (with smbd) and the stretched verb construction have an argument.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
234 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions (1974: 21–5; 166–7) defines catenatives as non-auxiliary verbs (because they fail the four tests of auxiliaries, Negation, Interrogation, ‘Code’ and Emphasis) which are followed by non-finite verb forms and allow recursion; the category is thus displayed in patterns with a gerund like come dancing, go skating, start speaking, carry on smoking, finish writing, succeed in escaping, or with an infinitive like come to agree, manage to escape. It has become clear that stretched verb constructions are patterns in which the event is not expressed through the main verb but through some dependent of it, and only some catenative patterns have this characteristic, including the examples already cited. These seem to fall into a number of discrete types. The pattern of come/go + GERUND seems to be limited in its first element to one of the two cited verbs (thus excluding *walk dancing, *rush skating) and in its gerund to verbs denoting organized pleasurable physical activity, typically sport or self-entertainment, cf. also go drinking/shopping/climbing, but not *go eating/sleeping/reading. Although this structure apparently has a semantic basis, it is clearly limited in its potential, and it can be seen as giving rise to restricted collocations, which can be compared with stretched verb constructions like go for a walk, have a swim. A second type has a verb of phase beginning, continuing or finishing followed by gerund in all cases or an infinitive of beginning or continuing, thus start speaking/to speak, continue speaking/to speak, finish speaking. Such constructions can be compared semantically with the stretched verb constructions we discussed above under the heading of ‘Aktionsart’ (section IV.2.ii); thus start applauding can be compared with burst into applause, or finish attacking can be compared with drive home an attack. But this kind of catenative pattern remains a productive syntactic pattern, without any real lexical limitations. A final group of examples involve a verb that describes success or fate followed by the infinitive or gerund, such as succeed in escaping, come to agree, manage to escape, chance to fall. This pattern, too, must be seen as a normal syntactic structure with no limitation on the choice of the non-finite verb, but, like stretched verb constructions, it does involve a displacement of the semantic event from the main verb position, which is filled instead by what Palmer (1965: 161) refers to as an ‘adverbial’ use of the verb.
V.1.iv Defective stretched verb constructions Stretched verb constructions, in the sense defined in Part I, are elaborated verb structures containing a thin verb and a deverbal noun or adjective, such that there is a simpler kindred construction with the underlying verb at its heart. In this sense a ‘stretched verb construction’ is a construction in which the eventive meaning expressed in a simplex construction by the verb alone has been stretched out over the thin verb and its accompanying eventive noun or adjective. But another way of interpreting the expression ‘stretched verb construction’ is to regard it as including any verb elaboration structure that is ‘stretched’ in the sense of ‘non-minimal’,
11
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 235
111
i.e. ‘consisting of more than just a simple intransitive verb’. In this interpretation there would be no requirement for a kindred simplex construction. Constructions of our type that only fit into this broader category can be termed DEFECTIVE STRETCHED VERB CONSTRUCTIONS. A construction such as make an effort (to do smth) is superficially similar to a stretched verb construction like make an attempt (to do smth); but, whereas the latter construction has a corresponding simplex construction attempt (to do smth), such a possibility is lacking for make an effort (to do smth), because it has no related verb. Similarly defective constructions can be found that are adjective-based: for instance, unlike be ablaze (or be afloat) which corresponds to the verb blaze (or float), the pattern be adamant (or be adequate) has no kindred simplex verb construction. It almost goes without saying that pairs of nounbased and adjective-based constructions can even be found that still have no corresponding simplex verb construction: one such is have an apoplexy and be apoplectic, which have no kindred verb, unlike have an argument (with smbd) and be argumentative, which have the corresponding simplex construction argue (with smbd). A list of all these types,118 indicating the Construction type and a putative non-existent kindred verb, is displayed in Table 5.2. If we examine the range of patterns exemplified in Table 5.2 we find all of the Structures 1 to 6 represented, although Structures 4, 5 and 6 are perhaps slightly underrepresented compared with their frequency in normal stretched verb constructions. These are the structures with the clearest eventive meaning, and thus the closest semantic relationship to the verb; so their underrepresentation is not so surprising. Defective stretched verb constructions have no kindred lexical verb, and it is therefore impossible to identify an ‘underlying’ syntactic structure. This obviously means that they cannot be classified according to the syntactic restructuring scheme used in Part II. But is the proposed form for the hypothetical verbs suggested in Table 5.2 so unrealistic? In some cases (e.g. *apprentice) they are actual verbs of former times that have fallen into disuse. For other cases we know that in the past some new verbs have been analogically formed through so-called BACK-FORMATION, i.e. cancellation of a suffix or vowel change, such as British English burgle formed from burglar¸ or, more recently, originally in computer English, the verb access formed from the noun access. All such reconstructed verb forms are based on the reversal of regular morphological patterns (mainly suffixation, vowel-change or zero-formation, see section III.1.i, especially Table 3.2). The hypothetical verb form can indeed be regarded as a UNIQUE MORPHEME, cf. Hockett (1958: 126–7), Allerton (1979: 50). It provides just the sort of patterning that native speakers can (and in the future most
111
118 i.e. cases of ‘verbless’ constructions that are noun-based, adjective-based or both. It is also worth noting that cases can be found of the converse situation, i.e. of an eventive noun that has a kindred verb but does not form any stretched verb constructions, e.g. deceleration; such nouns can be referred to as INERT DEVERBAL NOUNS.
11
11
111
111
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
236 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions Table 5.2 List of defective stretched verb constructions (numbered according to their construction type) Stretched verb constructions
Hypothetical verb1
be an aberration (3) be in abeyance (4) be able to do smth (1), have the ability to do smth (6) be abnormal (1), show abnormalities (6) have/take up an abode (6) be absurd (1), be an absurdity (3) be an accomplice (2) be accidental (1), be an accident (3)
*ABER *ABEY
be accurate (1) be adamant that . . . (1) be addictive (1) (‘active’); be addicted (1), be an addict (2), have an addiction (6) (all ‘passive’) be adulterous (1), be an adulterer (2), commit adultery (6) be adversarial (1), be an adversary (2) be an aesthete (2), practise aestheticism (6) have an affinity with smth/smbd (6) be affluent (1), live in affluence (5), enjoy affluence (6) cause an affray (6) be afraid (1) be agnostic (1) be ajar (1) be an alcoholic (2) have allegiance to smbd (6) be allergic (1), have an allergy (6) be alluring (1) have an altercation with smbd (6) be an amateur (2), practise amateurism (6) be amorous (1) be ambiguous (1), show ambiguities (6) be ambitious (1), have (an) ambition (6) make amends (6) draw/make an analogy (6) be anecdotal (1), tell anecdotes (6) do sm angling (6)
*ABLE *ABNORMALIZE/-IFY °ABIDE *ABSURDIFY *ACCOMPLE *ACCIDE, *ACCIDENTALIZE *ACCURE *ADAM(E) *ADDICT (verb) *ADULTER *ADVERT *AESTHETICIZE/-IFY *AFFINE *AFFLU(ENC)E *AFFRAY *FRAY *AGNOST(IC)IZE *JAR *ALCOHOLIZE *ALLIEGE *ALLERGE *ALLURE2 *ALTERCATE *AMATE *AMORE *AMBIGUE *AMBIT °AMEND *ANALOGIZE *ANECDOTIZE °ANGLE3
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 237 Table 5.2 (continued) Stretched verb constructions
Hypothetical verb1
cause anguish (6) be antipathetic (1), feel/show antipathy (6) be the antithesis (3) be anxious (1), feel/suffer anxiety (6) be apathetic (1), feel apathy (6) be apoplectic (1), suffer apoplexy (6) make an appointment with smbd (6) be apprenticed (1), be an apprentice (2) receive approbation (6) be arrogant (1), show arrogance (6) be artistic (1), be an artist (2), do art (6) be assiduous (1), show assiduity (6) be asthmatic (1), have asthma (6) be athletic (1), be an athlete (2), do athletics (6) be attached to smbd (1), feel/form an attachment for smbd (6) be audacious (1), have audacity (6) be austere (1), practise austerity (6) be an author (2) be autocratic (1), practise autocracy (6) do autocross (6) carry out/do an autopsy (6) be auxiliary (1), be an auxiliary (2) be averse to smbd/smth (1), have an aversion for smbd/smth (6) be aware of smth/smbd (1), show awareness of smth/smbd (6) be awesome (1), be awed (1), inspire awe (6)
*ANGUISH (verb) *ANTIPATHIZE *ANTITHESIZE *ANXIE *APATHIZE *APOPLEX °APPOINT *APPRENTICE *APPROB(AT)E *ARROGUE/°ARROGATE *ARTIFY *ASSIDUE *ASTHMATIZE *ATHLETICIZE °ATTACH *AUDACE *AUSTERIFY *AUTH *AUTOCRAT(IC)IZE *AUTOCROSS *AUTOPSIZE *AUXILIARIZE °AVERT *WARE *AWE4
Notes: 1 Non-existent verbs are marked with an asterisk; extant verbs with a different meaning are marked with a raised circle. The suggested form of non-existent verbs is of course purely speculative, although based on existing patterns. Some of the forms may already have been used. 2 The verb allure(d ) is recorded in some dictionaries but only has only nine occurrences in the BNC. 3 The verb exists in earlier English with appropriate meaning, ‘fish (for)’, but as a verb now only seems to be used in this sense in the fixed expressions such as go angling and do sm angling. 4 The verb is given in several dictionaries, but only a handful of clearly verbal instances are attested in the BNC.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
238 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions probably will) use to form new verbs, though admittedly some do not seem to yield particularly natural forms (e.g. be agnostic, be austere) and will probably retain their anomalous position. New verbs that have been formed by back-formation (such as burgle and access) have been given a syntactic character; so should it not be possible to foresee the syntactic possibilities of the hypothetical verbs of Table 5.2? In some cases the morphological form of the eventive noun or adjective strongly suggests an underlying form that is a hypothetical intransitive verb, such as be an aberration (*aber), be in abeyance (*abey), take up one’s abode (°abide ‘live’). In other cases it is more difficult to judge, particularly between verbs that could have a prepositional object or objoid, such as have an altercation with smbd (*altercate with smbd), be antipathetic towards smbd (*antipathize? with/? against smbd). In still other cases the hypothetical verb is clearly transitive, e.g. receive approbation (*approb(at)e). With time, then, defective stretched verb constructions can become normal ones through the establishment of a fully operative verb. But there is no reason for language change to move just in the direction of providing verbs for more and more eventive nouns. Things might just as well go in the opposite direction, that of verbs disappearing and giving way to the more extensive use of (increasingly defective) stretched verb constructions. This direction of change was indeed recommended by C. K. Ogden in his Basic English: he recommended, for instance, replacing all verbs outside the eighteen basic ones he retained with complex verb structures, including stretched verb constructions (e.g. put in motion, give a push to, cf. Ogden (1968: 26)) and also phrasal verbs. It is also the direction taken by some languages, in which stretched verb constructions are more commonly used than in English. We shall consider this point in section V.2.i.
11
V.2 Stretched verb constructions and the lexicon
11
11
111
111
111
111
V.2.i The cross-language status of stretched verb constructions It was made clear as early as section I.1.i that stretched verb constructions need to be recorded in the lexicon of a given language, because they represent a phenomenon that is partly arbitrary and language-specific. Languages may have similar construction potentials, but each language seems to make its own selection between its constructions for any individual construction, and this takes on its own specific meaning. To recall some examples, English has run the risk of smth but not *run (the) danger of smth, whereas German has precisely the equivalent of this, namely Gefahr laufen; or, in English there is make or lodge a complaint, while French has the equivalent of *carry/put down a complaint, namely porter/déposer une plainte, and German has *put in/raise a complaint, namely eine Beschwerde einlegen/ erheben. Despite these differences the general pattern is similar in these cases, and so we are naturally led to ask just how similar and how different languages are both in their potential for the general pattern and in their actual occurrence of individual stretched verb constructions. As we noted in Part I, stretched verb constructions are a welldocumented phenomenon in German, where the excessive use of them has been criticized as bad (bureaucratic) style. Attention has been given both to constructions with an eventive accusative noun phrase, i.e. our Structure 5 (e.g. eine Entscheidung treffen/fällen, literally ‘hit/fell a decision’), and to expressions with an eventive preposition phrase (e.g. zur Entscheidung kommen/gelangen, literally ‘come/reach to the decision’). In his wellexemplified discussion Heringer (1989: 106–13) also discusses degrees of grammaticalization and of idiomaticity, and points to differences in valency and in phases of an action. In French too such constructions have long been recognized. For instance, Dubois (1969: 24), under the general heading of ‘transformations’ and of ‘correspondances’, identifies constructions with faire, e.g. faire des calculs ‘do some calculations’, faire ses lavages ‘do one’s washing’, faire un sourire ‘do (= give) a smile’, faire du tapage ‘make noise(s)’, all of which
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
240 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions correspond to simple verbs (in these cases, calculer, laver, sourire and taper respectively). Björkman’s (1978) corpus-based study is limited to cases in which the eventive noun appears without an article, e.g. accorder attention à quelque chose (literally ‘accord attention to smth’) or faire signe à quelqu’un (literally ‘make sign to smbd’). It is true that these two types, with and without an article in the eventive noun phrase, are more clearly distinguishable in French than in English, with its zero article for plural countable and mass nouns (Simatos 1997). The question also arises for French grammarians what relationship both of these types have to what we have termed ‘defective stretched verb constructions’, such as faire honte à quelqu’un ‘make (= cause) shame to smbd’, or, for that matter to idiomatic expressions like faire part à quelqu’un ‘inform’. All such constructions are found particularly in formal language (e.g. legal texts) apparently just as much in French as in German, cf. François and Grass (1997), also Cortès (1997). They can also be found in radio announcements, e.g. Vous êtes à/sur l’écoute de France Musiques ‘You are listening to France Musiques (literally, you are on the listen to France Musiques’). Turning to other Romance languages, we find Spanish stretched verb constructions dealt with by Pottier (1972: 81) and Gutiérrez (1993: 128–9) under the label ‘lexía compleja’. Examples mentioned include: hacer falta ‘be lacking’ (literally ‘do/make a lack’) corresponding to the simplex verb faltar ‘lack’, and hacer une pregunta ‘ask a question’ (literally ‘do/make a question’) corresponding to the simplex verb preguntar ‘ask’. (Both examples also illustrate a tendency some languages have to make more extensive use of a verb corresponding to do/make as a thin verb.) For Italian, unpublished research by E. Mombelli reveals a wide range of examples, even with the limitation to orthographical initial A, including Structure 1 (e.g. essere alterativo ‘be changeable’), Structure 2 (e.g. essere un affascinatore ‘be a fascinator, i.e. fascinate’), Structure 4 (e.g. essere/stare in adorazione di qualcuno ‘be in adoration of smbd, i.e. adore’), Structure 5 (e.g. prendere qualcuno in adozione ‘take in adoption, i.e. adopt’), and Structure 6 (e.g. piantare l’accampamento (‘plant the camp, i.e. pitch camp’). A glance at any Russian dictionary quickly reveals examples of nounbased stretched verb constructions: some of these have thin verbs corresponding to those in the equivalent English expression, e.g. prinmátj rjesˇénije ‘take (a) decision’ (cf. rjesˇátj ‘decide’), zadavátj voprós ‘put (a) question’ (cf. voprosˇátj ‘question (VERB)’), or nahodjítj udovoljstjvje ‘find contentment’ (cf. udovljetvorjátjsja ‘content oneself’); others have a different verb selection, e.g. djélatj doklád ‘do/make a lecture/report’ (cf. dokládivatj ‘lecture/report (VERB)’). Preposition phrase structures can also be found, e.g. prjihodjítj k soglasˇénno ‘arrive at an agreement’ (cf. soglasˇátjsja ‘agree’). The situation is possibly not very different in Modern Greek, where, according to Mackridge (1987: 356–9) many ‘idioms’ (some of which are probably stretched verb constructions) make use of a few common verbs, such as vázo ‘I put’, vlázo ‘I take out/off’, ékho ‘I have’, káno ‘I do’.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Stretched verb constructions and the lexicon 241 In Persian and in Turkish stretched verb constructions, whether standard or defective, seem to be widely used. As regards Persian, Lambton (1953: 85–93) writes as follows: Many verbs are formed with a Verbal Noun and a simple verb such as kardan. The tendency in Modern Persian is to use such constructions rather than the simple verb. Lambton quotes examples like radar kardan (rather than rada∫tan) ‘persuade, oblige’, and ku∫e∫ kardan (rather than ku∫idan) ‘try, strive’. He particularly mentions lists a dozen verbs including kardan ‘do, make’, but also namudan ‘show’, da∫tan ‘have, possess’, dadan ‘give’ and eight or so others, which all act as thin verbs. In Turkish, on the other hand, one thin verb predominates, namely etmek (‘do, make’) or its ‘detransitivized’ equivalent yapmek, cf. Lewis (1967: 154–7). Some of these constructions apparently go back to an originally Turkish pattern, e.g. yardan etmek ‘help (VERB)’, literally ‘do help’. But the pattern really seems to have come into its own with nouns borrowed from Arabic, e.g. kabul etmek ‘accept’, literally ‘do/make acceptance’, or mukayese etmek ‘compare’, literally ‘do/make comparison’, and in many cases only the Arabic noun, not its kindred verb, was borrowed into Turkish. Later the pattern was extended to loans from European languages, e.g. organize etmek. Stretched verb constructions can also be found in at least some languages of southern and eastern Asia. With regard to Hindi, Snell and Weightman (1989: 191–4) refer to a category of ‘conjunct verbs’, for some of which ‘the noun component retains its function as a noun’. For Chinese, Scurfield (1991: 16–18, 92–3) reports numerous verb–noun constructions formed, for instance, with daˇ ‘strike, hit’ (e.g. daˇha¯qian ‘snore (VERB))’ or with ch¯ı ‘eat’ (e.g. ch¯ıj¯ıng ‘be shocked’). Similar expressions can be found in Japanese, such as koi o shite ‘love ACC. do = love (VERB)’, or juuatsu ni kurishin ‘pressure DAT. suffer = suffer pressure’, cf. also Miyamoto (1999). Swahili is one African language that seems to have stretched verb constructions, both standard ones and defective ones. In the role of thin verb we find, for instance: -fanya ‘do, make’ (e.g. -fanya jaribio ‘make an attempt’ beside -jaribu ‘attempt (VERB)’); -piga ‘hit, strike’ (e.g. -piga mbio ‘strike a run = run beside’; -kimbia ‘run away’). Further common thin verbs are -choma ‘pierce, stab’; -enda ‘go’; -funga ‘close’; -ona ‘see’; -pata ‘get’; -tia ‘put’; -toa ‘put out, offer’. Such verbs probably form as many defective stretched verb constructions (e.g. -fanya kazi ‘do work (NOUN) = work (VERB)’; -piga makuu ‘do pride = be arrogant’) as they form standard ones. More generally, we could say that it is easier to imagine a language with defective stretched verb constructions and no simplex ones than a language with the reverse situation. As noted earlier, Ogden’s Basic English came close to having this characteristic, since its few lexical verbs had the
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
242 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions main function of forming constructions with nouns as their objects, and most of these nouns were abstract. We could easily imagine a more extreme form of Basic English (that we could call ‘One-Verb English’) in which there would be just one lexical verb with the meaning ‘do’ (in the broadest possible sense), and every action, process, state, etc. would be expressed through a verb phrase consisting of this unique verb combined with an appropriate eventive noun, e.g. do laughter (for laugh), do a trip (for go), do existence (for be), etc. Presumably different eventive nouns would need to be found to represent active and passive viewpoints for the same event, but some of these are already available, e.g. do a victory (for win, defeat) beside do a loss, do a defeat (for lose, be defeated). Such a language, though improbable, is conceivable and may even be found as a stage foreign learners of a language go through. At any event, it would be a language whose verb phrases included no intransitive verbs, but only defective stretched verb constructions. A language of the reverse type is more difficult to imagine; this would have to be a language which had no defective stretched verb constructions, only simplex ones. It might also be that for every stretched verb construction there were a kindred simplex verb, and vice versa; this seems a less plausible possibility, because it would involve such a luxuriant lexicon. Against this general background, English seems to have a moderate mixture of defective and standard stretched verb constructions, as well as inert simplex verbs (without a corresponding stretched verb construction).
V.2.ii The psycholinguistic and cognitive status of stretched verb constructions How do language users process stretched verb constructions? In particular, do they deal with them differently compared with the way they deal with other word patterns? Language-users need to process sentences both as hearers or readers, i.e. as language-receivers, and as speakers or writers, i.e. as language-producers. When language-receivers perceive phonetic or graphic sequences representing a particular sentence, in order to interpret these semantically, they need to recognize both the lexical units and the grammatical patterns they appear in, before they go on to combine these into a global meaning for each sentence. Language-producers, on the other hand, start from a global meaning for the sentence they want to produce (although they may not have all the details worked out at the outset) and then have to select both the most suitable lexical units and appropriate grammatical patterns, before realizing these in the form of sequences of speech-sounds or graphemes. The vital question for us is how far these processes need to be specially adapted to accommodate stretched verb constructions and other multiword lexical units. Are such constructions exceptions to the general pattern
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Stretched verb constructions and the lexicon 243 or simply special cases of it? For instance, although it is known that for the vast majority of human beings most language-processing takes place in the left hemisphere of the brain, there is evidence, according to Obler and Gjerlow (1999: 86–7) that right-brain-damaged patients find use of non-literal language difficult: Brownell et al. (1994), for instance, showed that such patients have problems with sarcasm and metaphorical meaning. The reasons why non-literal language presents difficulties for the language-receiver are clear: successful semantic interpretation of such linguistic patterns entails going beyond single-word lexemes and/or standard grammatical rules, and may necessitate keeping open two widely different readings for an opaque idiom like get smbd’s goat, for a standard metaphor like skate on thin ice, or even for a stretched verb construction like raise taxes.119 This may give rise to parallel processing of two semantic interpretations until one of them can be safely discarded. In any case, some kind of ‘on-line’ processing is called for: listener–readers cannot possibly wait until the end of a sentence before developing possible interpretations of it; they must use clues like grammatical requirements and collocational restrictions of words already processed to predict what is to come. The processing problems of speaker–writers are somewhat different: they have to select semantically appropriate lexical units, no matter whether of one word or more, the difference being that the latter type has a preprogrammed complex lexico-grammatical structure (which incidentally makes certain demands on their memory and easily gives rise to errors of form and to blends). One level of structuring that seems to be particularly important for language producers is the topic–comment or theme–rheme division, which in English is closely associated with the subject–predicate division, cf. Halliday (1970), Allerton (1978, 1980). It has often been pointed out that most metaphors and idioms appear in the predicate rather than in the subject, presumably because the subject most commonly needs to make an unequivocal identification of the entity that constitutes the topic of the sentence and non-literal language is generally not the best way of doing this. (This even applies to nominal metaphors and idioms like rough diamond or red herring, which are only suitable as descriptors, not as identifiers.) Although stretched verb constructions are only partly idiomatic, they are certainly verb phrase structures, and although Mel’cˇuk (1998) includes subject–verb combinations in his lexical functions, there are relatively few tight collocation restrictions for such combinations (e.g. day breaks but night falls, cf. above, section I.2.ii.). From the stand-point of both speaker–writer and hearer–reader, nonliteral expressions clearly require special treatment, but the progression
119 The expression is ambiguous between an interpretation as a stretched verb construction meaning simply ‘tax (VERB)’ and a literal interpretation meaning ‘increase taxes’.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
244 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions from opaque idioms through standard metaphors to stretched verb constructions is like a sliding scale. Stock et al. (1993: 229 et passim) argue that there is no need to envisage a straight choice between opaque, unanalysable idioms treated as ‘big words’ on the one hand, and transparent analysable metaphors treated as modified metaphors on the other. Instead, idioms could be recorded in the mental lexicon as ‘sequences of individual entries which have particularly strong associative links holding between them’ (Garman 1990: 242). But each idiom would at the same time have a global meaning which could be directly accessed, so that go through the motions, for instance, would on the one hand have a simple meaning (roughly ‘carry an action out in a purely superficial way’) but at the same time a constructed meaning rather like that of, say, go through the plans, which would require a selection of the meaning of go in the context of through, a recognition of the meaning of motion, an identification of a given set of motions, etc. Ultimately this analytic processing will not of course be relevant for the semantic interpretation of go through the motions, but this fact does not finally become clear until the last word of the expression, motions, has been processed. This double analysis of idioms and metaphors obviously imposes a greater load on the decoding hearer–reader, and it is only in the case of semantically transparent expressions that the word-by-word analysis pays off. Figure 5.1 presents a simple schematic model for the hearer–reader’s processing of free expressions, metaphors and different kinds of idiom. The psycholinguistic map of Figure 5.1 could obviously offer different processing routes for different kinds of expression. It assumes a word lexicon, a phrase lexicon and a grammar, all of them connected and all containing semantic specifications (for words, fixed phrases and grammatical constructions respectively). The input to it (0) (which would be a sequence of words in a particular arrangement, i.e. with particular inflectional marking, a particular sequence, etc., and a regularly constructed pattern) would pass through the word lexicon, consult the grammar, emerging with a literal meaning (1), after which it would proceed to the pragmatics, where it would receive a pragmatic interpretation. An ungrammatical idiom, such as by and large, would enter the word lexicon, but would then be rejected by the grammar and consequently barred from further lexical processing for literal meaning and forced out (2) into the opaque part of the phrase lexicon, where it would pick up an idiomatic meaning. An opaque idiom like make no bones about smth, although grammatically acceptable, would be rejected as involving a semantic anomaly (due to the incompatibility of its constituent lexical meanings) and again be passed directly (2) to the opaque part of the phrase lexicon. A transparent metaphorical idiom, like ride for a fall, would likewise be rejected but would be rerouted (3) to the transparent part of the phrase lexicon. Expressions that are acceptable both grammatically and semantically, such as skate on thin ice or get smbd’s goat, will first be processed in the usual way
Stretched verb constructions and the lexicon 245
11
semantic interpretation (0)
(1)
phonological input
111
111
(1)
(4)
(3) PRAGMATICS
pragmatic interpretation
GRAMMAR
semantic anomaly (4A)
semantic clue
(4B)
(3) (3/4B)
transparent
11
111
literal meaning pragmatic anomaly
(2)
11
111
WORD LEXICON
PHRASE LEXICON (2)
opaque
metaphorical meaning idiomatic meaning (2/4A)
Figure 5.1 Schematic model of semantic processing by the reader–hearer.
by the word lexicon and the grammar to give a fully acceptable literal meaning, and it is only when this literal meaning proves pragmatically doubtful that the expression will be returned for an alternative interpretation to the phrase lexicon, to the opaque part for the first example (4A), and to the transparent part for the second (4B); such expressions will thus have two interpretations that can be processed in parallel. Finally, restrictive collocations, i.e. grammatical expressions that include a superficial semantic incompatibility between two of its component words, such as swallow one’s pride, could be forced (as in the case of the metaphorical idiom ride for a fall) (3) into the transparent part of the phrase lexicon for semantic reinterpretation of one (or occasionally both) of these words, normally the semantically more flexible one, in this case the verb swallow. Since stretched verb constructions can be considered as a subvariety of this pattern, we shall assume that they receive a similar treatment and follow this path (3).
V.2.iii The lexicographic status of stretched verb constructions Although words like ‘lexicon’ and ‘grammar’ are used by some linguists to refer indiscriminately to an aspect of psycholinguistic competence or performance and to language reference works aiming to help the language user, there is little clear evidence of a close correspondence between the two senses of the words. How then do things look in the world of books that are tools for language users? The grammatical patterns of a language are described in a grammar. The words of a language are listed alphabetically in a dictionary and semantically in a thesaurus. Idioms and other
1
1
1
11
11
246 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions fixed expressions have special dictionaries devoted to them, e.g. Cowie et al. (1975/1983), Wood and Hill (1979); but increasingly they are being included in standard dictionaries, and they have always been included in thesauruses. Where then are stretched verb constructions and similar restricted collocations to be found? To a limited extent they are also recorded in normal modern dictionaries, but not so consistently as idioms are.120 Dictionaries of idioms, however, usually exclude them. The only work attempting to list them comprehensively is the BBI Combinatory Dictionary i.e. Benson et al. (1986a); but, as noted in Part I, this dictionary covers less than half of the constructions found in our database, and, more importantly, they are simply listed as verb–noun combinations, without further grammatical or semantic specification. So would a dictionary that listed stretched verb constructions and described their grammatical and semantic characteristics be feasible or desirable? It would certainly be possible and worthwhile to compile a full list of these constructions, and to specify for each one the kind of grammatical and semantic information discussed in this volume. Indeed such a book would represent a major contribution to the academic study of English (and even general) linguistics. But would it correspond to the needs of the native speaker of English or to the learner of it as a foreign language? Two different uses of a compilation of stretched verb constructions can be envisaged, use by language-producers (i.e. speakers or writers) and use by language-receivers (i.e. listeners and readers). What, first, are the needs of language-producers, more particularly of writers, when they have an idea and wish to express it appropriately, possibly through a stretched verb construction? They can comb through a dictionary, or preferably a thesaurus or dictionary of synonyms (as indeed many of us often do), but as we have noted these contain relatively few restricted collocations, such as stretched verb constructions. If they turn to the BBI Combinatory Dictionary they will need to start from some actual linguistic item (rather than ‘pure meaning’), and they will find many collocations,121 but they will have no means of differentiating them semantically from each other or from the kindred simple lexical item. This is also the essential problem for readers or hearers of such expressions: they can check in the BBI dictionary that the expression they have come across exists, but they will themselves need to intuit its meaning by combining the meanings of the constituent words. A non-native learner of English is not given the vital information that, whereas take a guess and take a throw have to be understood in an ‘active’
11
11
120 The excellent Collins English Dictionary, for instance, includes the metaphorical idioms draw a blank and draw the line under both the noun and the verb in each case, but not the stretched verb constructions draw an analogy or draw a comparison under either the verb or the noun. 121 Collocations are only locatable via their head word, not through their collocating word.
11
11
111
111
111
111
be a help [to smbd]
be of help [to smbd]
come/go to the help {of smbd}
give help to smbd
receive/get help (from smbd)
help out
be an accomplice of smbd (Structure 2),
give succour to smbd (Structure 6)
give a hand to smbd,
Structure 3
Structure 4
Structure 5
Structure 6 ‘active’
Structure 6, ‘passive’
Phrasal verb
Defective stretched
verb construction
Idiom
give a lift to smbd (BRITISH
lend a hand to smbd,
be a helper [of smbd]
Structure 2
COLLOQUIAL)
–
receive/get assistance (from smbd)
give/render assistance [to smbd]
come/go to the assistance {of smbd}
be of assistance [to smbd]
–
be an assistant (of smbd)
–
be helpful [to smbd]
Structure 1
assist smbd
help smbd
Structure 0
–
–
–
–
be an abettor of smbd
–
abet smbd
–
–
receive/get aid (from smbd) –
give aid [to smbd]
come/go to the aid {of smbd}
–
be an aid
–
–
aid smbd
Table 5.3 Range of structures in the semantic field (‘benefit some other person(s) by undertaking or joining some work on their behalf’)
11
1
1
1
11
11
248 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions sense (as roughly ‘guess’ and ‘throw’ respectively), take a call and take a knock have ‘passive’ meanings (roughly ‘be called’ and ‘be knocked’ respectively). Or, to take an example from the field of noun complementation, the BBI dictionary gives for and to as prepositions that follow the word example, but fails to say that these introduce a phrase designating the ‘experiencer’, i.e. the person for whom the discussed entity is an example; but in German the corresponding preposition für ‘for’ is commonly used to introduce a phrase designating the ‘phenomenon exemplified’, for which English uses the of, a preposition not listed by the BBI. Thus despite the great benefits this dictionary has brought, its listing of collocations largely without meanings has its limitations. How can such needs be met? What the writer or speaker looking for some kind of verb needs is not a separate list of stretched verb constructions but, for every semantic field, a thesaurus-like list of all relevant lexical items, whether simple verbs, derived verbs, stretched verb constructions, cognate or predictable object constructions, phrasal verbs or verbal idioms. Within the list for each field, every item should have a full grammatical specification, to ensure its correct use, and a comprehensive semantic description, to enable speaker–writers to distinguish their meaning and use. For example, the verbs show and explain would need to be distinguished grammatically in that show appears in the constructions show smbd smth and show smth to smbd, while explain only appears in the construction explain smth to smbd; equally the two verbs would need to be distinguished semantically, in that while show can be through words or actions, explain can only be through words. No comprehensive semantic map of the world of our experience has yet been devised; so access to a lexical item being searched for will, for the present, still need to be through other lexical items that are semantically related to it. In the case of multi-word lexical items access can, as one option, be through their constituent words. For instance, put up resistance, will need to be accessed through resistance, because the basic meaning is something like ‘resist’, and indeed the noun resistance may already be in the speaker’s mind; on the other hand, it may be that put up (as the earlier word in the string) is what comes to mind first, and a list of eventive nouns, both deverbal and non-deverbal, that collocate with it (such as resistance, fight, defence, case) will be useful.122 This means that the proposed dictionary-thesaurus will need to have lexical entries with multiple access, through semantic category, through near-synonyms, through kindred
11
11
122 It seems natural to assume that a deviant collocation should be corrected by changing the collocant rather than the base word, but some of the non-native speaker examples cited by Howarth (1998: 177–85) should probably be corrected by changing the eventive noun rather than the thin verb (or ‘delexical verb’ to use Howarth’s term), e.g. when the reward is attained should probably be corrected to when the objective is attained rather than to when the reward is received.
11
11
11
111
111
Stretched verb constructions and the lexicon 249 constructions, through head word, through minor word, etc. Such multiple access could obviously be achieved more efficiently, if the reference work were in electronic form. Let us finally consider briefly and very provisionally what kind of information the proposed (electronic) ‘panlexical’ dictionary-thesaurus could contain in one part of one semantic field, that of helping, assisting and aiding a person in some task. A caveat required right at the outset is that, given the polysemy of words and the partial overlapping of their meanings, the semantic field selected for analysis is by no means clearly delimited. The polysemy of the verb help is such that, as well as referring to a person’s acting alongside the person in need, to lighten a task or difficulty (as in help the doctor with the operation), it also refers to cases in which the person in need is inactive so that the helper has to take over (as help an accident victim); a further meaning refers to the useful role a person or thing can have of making a task or difficulty easier (as help (protect) against arthritis). None of the stretched verb constructions and none of the nearsynonymous simplex verbs assist, aid, abet has quite this broad range of meaning. The full range of lexical items to be considered is given in Table 5.3. It includes the simple verb lexemes abet, aid, help and assist, as well as a range of stretched verb constructions based on them, a phrasal verb, two idioms and two defective stretched verb constructions. Assuming that similarity in form suggest some similarity of meaning, we can begin by considering the semantic differences between the four basic verbs. They all refer to a process of beneficial action to the advantage of someone with a task or problem, but the context of the event or the way it is viewed differs. In the case of help, it may be any kind of context, including a personal one; with assist it is in a general organizational context, normally in a minor role; with aid it is mainly in a medical or financial context; and with abet it is in an activity that is seen as undesirable. Stylistically, help is neutral, but assist is slightly formal, and abet and aid are very formal, the latter much more so than its noun homonym. The grammatical potential of these four verbs also differs, affecting their meaning. The differences can be clarified by listing their possible constructions more fully:
111
help smbd assist smbd aid smbd abet smbd
help smbd with smth assist smbd with smth – –
help smbd in smth assist smbd in smth – abet smbd in smth
help smbd to do smth – – –
111
The pronoun smbd in the above patterns represents the direct object, which means that each of the patterns has an alternative passive from, e.g. be helped (by smbd). The patterns show that, whereas help, assist and abet can be used with an in-phrase denoting an enterprise, only help and assist can
250 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions
11
be used with a with-phrase to denote the task or difficulty; it also shows that only help can occur with an infinitive suggesting the task was completed, while assist and abet have in plus a gerund as their only non-finite clause option. Turning now to the stretched verb constructions, and beginning with Structure 1, we find that help is the only verb represented, with the pattern be helpful [to smbd]. As an adjective-based construction, Structure 1 assigns a meaning that relates to a quality of the subject, in this case the subject’s attitude or intention: the subject is a person who is trying to engage in some (usually minor) activity that might further the activity under discussion and is making these efforts externally evident. There are two examples of Structure 2 patterns, namely be a helper of smbd and be an assistant of smbd. Structure 2 regularly has the meaning ‘have the particular role, function or duty of helping or assisting’ and therefore by implication also of probably carrying out some of these duties, especially if there is a mention of the task or the time it was due to be carried out. But the action associated with this role is only inferred, not asserted, so that it is quite possible for a helper or an assistant not to help or even be helpful. The meaning of the noun assistant seems to be directly related to that of the verb assist, because it refers to someone who helps in an organizational capacity. The case of helper is slightly different in that, rather than just having the general meaning of ‘person who helps’, it seems to suggest ‘a person who helps informally or temporarily’. Finally, for Structure 3, we should note the defective stretched verb construction be an accomplice, which has clearly negative connotations, in that it suggests that the activity being furthered is undesirable or even criminal. In this sense it fills the gap left by the absence or rarity of a construction ?be an abettor of smbd.123 It will be recalled that Structure 3, exemplified by be a help and less commonly by be an aid,124 is semantically anomalous in suggesting that a person (the subject) can be an event, but that through some metaphorical interpretation it comes to mean that the person causes the action concerned or its results. In this case it is the act of helping or aiding that is involved, and the emphasis seems to be on the effectiveness of the contribution, rather than on the actor or the act itself. It is worth noting that to be a great help and to be no help are more common than to be a slight help or to be some help, so that it tends to be seen in terms of black and white, rather than various shades of grey. Our next pattern, Structure 4, can be based on either of the verbs help or assist, appearing in the forms be of help and be of assistance. Compared
11
123 The noun abettor is only represented by a single instance in the BNC, and this is in the formal legal phrase as an aider and abettor. 124 In the English of recent sports reporting a noun assist has developed with the meaning ‘pass, etc. that contributes to a goal’, but it is not predicated of a personal subject.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
11
111
111
Stretched verb constructions and the lexicon 251 with the expression be a help, its rival be of help is a more formal expression, which is typically used in polite offers to do something for somebody on a person-to-person basis, but the contribution that is being offered is not very substantial. The meaning is something like ‘help in a minor way’. The corresponding expression with assistance, with its slightly formal stylistic tone, is even more limited in the contribution suggested. The expressions come/go to smbd’s help/assistance/aid are examples of Structure 5, in which the eventive noun appears in prepositional objoid position. For this pattern there is no doubt about the substantial contribution being made by the person designated by the subject; indeed, come/go to smbd’s help implies that extra efforts have to be made by the agent, not necessarily travelling (as a literal interpretation of come/go would suggest) but at least going to special lengths to help someone who is in serious need of help. It is clearly implied then that the person to be helped is in a difficult position, although the precise kind of help required seems more matter-of-fact in the case of the assist-based expression, but more dramatic in the case of come/go to the aid of smbd, which comes close to come to the rescue of smbd. The choice between come and go seems to depend on whether the speaker identifies with the person helped (come) or not (go). The final type of stretched verb construction is Structure 6, in which the eventive noun, in this case, help, assistance or aid, is the direct object of the verb. In the ‘active’ version of the construction the verb is give (or render, especially with assistance) and the person helped, assisted or aided is in indirect object position, whereas in the ‘passive’ version the verb is receive (or, more informally, get) and the receiver of help, etc. appears as an indirect objoid introduced by from. Apart from this kind of ‘lexical passivization’ achieved through the change of thin verb, it is also possible to subject the pattern with give to the syntactic transformations of indirect object shift and/or passivization. This means that corresponding to a simplex verb sentence like (7) there is the whole range of Structure 6 possibilities given in (8) and (9): (7)
(a) (b)
Agnes helped Peter. Peter was helped by Agnes.
(8)
(a) (i) (ii) (b) (i) (ii)
Agnes gave help to Peter. Agnes gave Peter help. Help was given to Peter (by Agnes). Peter was given help (by Agnes).
(9)
(a) (b)
Peter received help from Agnes. Help was received by Peter from Agnes.
111
111
The differences in meaning between these different possibilities are a matter of the perspective from which the information is presented – what the
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
252 The lexical status of stretched verb constructions starting point is, what is emphasized or de-emphasized, etc. Regardless of format, all of these Structure 6 patterns agree in stressing the voluntary contribution made by the helper (Agnes in the examples of (7), (8) and (9)), stressing that the act was by no means a matter of course. The constructions tell us much less about how effective the help was or even to what degree it was really accepted by the intended beneficiary, a doubt that does not arise in the case of the simplex construction with the verb help. When Structure 6 contains the noun assistance (rather than help), the meaning goes in the direction of the weaker, more formalized help that we have already noted. With the noun aid, on the other hand, it goes in a more idiosyncratic direction: give aid to smbd (unlike go to the aid of ) in Modern English strongly suggests medical or financial aid (as noted above), probably because the aid has been used so frequently with this meaning in official and mass media language. By contrast, the defective stretched verb construction give succour to smbd, which also follows Structure 6, is highly formal, literary and archaic, but it is not limited to the medical or financial fields. Phrasal verbs are an alternative kind of kindred construction, which manages to achieve through the addition of a single limiter adverb what stretched verb constructions do through more extended expansion and restructuring. There is only one (non-transparent) phrasal verb in the semantic field we are considering, namely help out in the sense of ‘give informal help in a temporary mild emergency’. When the verb help is used with other adverbial particles, as in help smbd in, help smbd out (in a literal sense, e.g. out of a door), help smbd up, etc., the construction can be regarded as a literal but polysemous use of help with the meaning ‘assist to go somewhere’. Apart from help out, the only other combination of this type with a partly non-literal meaning is help smbd through (a difficulty, etc.), but the meaning is transparently metaphorical. In the semantic field of helping and assisting there is also a common idiom, namely give smbd a hand; it generally refers to practical help and is typically used informally amongst friends. A more formal variant, is lend smbd a hand. In contemporary British English slang there is the further informal invariant give smbd a lift. These stylistic limitations of social register are an aspect of the use of stretched verb constructions and other nonliteral expressions that has not been given sufficient attention in this book. It is clear that some stretched verbs constuctions (e.g. meet with acceptance, bring in an acquittal, afford sm amusement to smbd) are highly formal, but that others, particularly the special ones we noted with have and do (e.g. have a smell/go, do sm knitting/tidying up) are informal. These limitations of use should of course be recorded in any future dictionary, just as they should be for other items of vocabulary. This brief survey of the main lexical options in the semantic field of helping, assisting, etc. should have given an indication of the grammatical semantic complexity of the possibilities and what points need to be borne
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Semantics of stretched verb constructions 253 in mind in distinguishing them. As was noted at the outset, the field is not clearly delimited, and many lexical items could have been included from adjacent fields (e.g. serve smbd, be of service to smbd, support smbd (in smth), give/lend support to smbd); but the survey is illustrative of the kind of material that needs to be described and how difficult it is to describe it. This only serves, however, to underline the challenge that lies ahead for lexicographers, lexicologists, semanticists and grammarians in this field. They need to unite in the task of producing really comprehensive usable dictionary-thesauruses for more sophisticated language users.
1
A final thought
1
1
11
11
11
11
‘Die Sprache ist ein Gewölke, an dem jede Phantasie ein anderes Gebilde erblickt.’ [Language is a bank of cloud in which every imagination detects a different pattern.] (Jean Paul)
11
Appendix 1 A classification of English adverbials
11
11
I. Sentence adverbials (= clause modifiers) 1. Interpretational adverbials (a) attitudinal subject oriented: wisely, characteristically (b) attitudinal message-oriented: surprisingly, interestingly (c) probabilistic (message-oriented): possibly, obviously
111 2. Presentational adverbials (a) (b) (c) (d)
validity-oriented: superficially, really, ultimately viewpoint-oriented: legally, chemically, sexually style-oriented: briefly, metaphorically honesty-oriented: honestly, frankly, confidentially
3. Conjunctional adverbials: incidentally, firstly, moreover
111
111
111
4. Contingential adverbials (a) cause/result: because of the fog, on my account; to no avail, with success (b) concession: despite the fog, nevertheless (c) condition: in the event of rain, otherwise
II. Setting adverbials (= clause constituents) 5. Subject(/Object) adjuncts (a) (b) (c) (d)
vicariative: for me, on Mary’s behalf volitional: (un)willingly, (un)intentionally comitative: alone, with John, together statal: drunk, smiling, with a hat on
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
256 Appendix 1 6. Place adverbials (a) locational: in Switzerland, on the floor, there (b) directional (i) origin: from Geneva, from there (ii) path: along the motorway (iii) destination: to Zurich, there (c) distance-indicating: for 50 miles 7. Time adverbials (a) timing (i) absolute: yesterday, at two-o’-clock (ii) relative: soon, already, later, during the meal (iii) event-oriented: for the dance, for dancing (b) duration: briefly, for two hours, interminably (c) frequency: occasionally, often, three times a week 8. Environmental adverbials in the rain, in fog, in the dark
III. Word-modifying adverbials (= phrase constituents) 9. Lexical verb modifiers (a) aspect/range: medically, formally (b) method: automatically, with a hammer, without any tools (c) manner (i) subject-oriented: carefully, slowly (ii) process-oriented: beautifully, secretly (d) degree: greatly, so much, slightly, to a certain degree, partially 10. Adjective(/adverb) modifiers (a) aspect/range: medically, formally (b) manner: beautifully, secretly (c) degree: very, so, slightly, partially 11. Particle modifiers (a) adverb-modifying: right, just, about (b) preposition-modifying: right, just, fully, close (c) numeral-modifying: roughly, exactly
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Classification of English adverbials 257
IV. Universal qualifiers (= phrase appendages) 12. Restrictors (a) polar: only, too, mainly, particularly (b) serial: first, next, last, finally
1
Appendix 2 Types of adjective modifying deverbal nouns – their correspondences1 to adverbial types (according to collocations found in the LOB)
1
1
ASPECT/RANGE (‘subcategory of N’) Corresponding to VIEWPOINT/RESPECT
medical (advice, attention ‘treatment’) military (advice) ministerial (action, advice) morphemic (analysis) morphological (analysis) personal (achievement, adjustment, affront, appeal, appraisal) physical (attack ‘assault’, attraction) poetic (achievement) political (action, advance, alliance, argument ‘quarrel’) preventive (action) probabilistic* (approach) religious (affiliation) respiratory* (action) ritual (authority ‘authorization’) scriptural (argument ‘rationale’) semantic* (analysis) sensory (adaptation) sexual (assault, attack ‘assault’) social (achievement, action, adjustment, advance, appraisal) spiritual (annihilation, authority ‘authorization’)
11
aesthetic (appreciation) chemical (analysis, attack ‘chemical deterioration’) civil* (authority ‘authorization’) clinical (approach) commercial (agreement, arrangement) constitutional (advance) economic (achievement, aid) educational (achievement) financial (aid, assistance) grammatical (analysis, approach) historical (appeal) industrial* (achievement) intellectual (approval) lawful (authority ‘authorization’) legal (action, attack ‘criticism’, authority ‘authorization’) liberal (approach) linguistic (analysis) logical (analysis, approach)
11
1 Examples marked with an asterisk have been assigned to their corresponding adverbial type in a more indirect way, in the sense that there is no corresponding simple adverb in -ly but that an adverbial can be found that is lexically related, e.g. the adjective old corresponds to in the old days but not to *oldly.
11
11
11
11
11
111
111
Types of adjective modifying deverbal nouns 259 structural (analysis) syntactic (analysis) technical (advice, approach, assistance) thematic (appeal) theoretical (approach, assumption) thermal (analysis) tribal (authority ‘authorization’) verbal (adjustment) visual (attention ‘concentration’) Corresponding to
METHOD
administrative (abuse) atomic* (attack ‘assault’) commercial (advertisement) compulsory (acquisition) functional (application ‘use’) intercrystalline* (attack ‘chemical deterioration’) nuclear* (attack ‘assault’) one-way* (analysis) opening* (address) spectrographic (analysis) statistical (analysis) two-handed (attack ‘assault’) written* (advice) Corresponding to PLACE Danish* (allocation) domestic (aid) external (assistance, attack ‘assault’) foreign* (aid, assistance) frontal (attack ‘assault’) international (arrangement) national (average)
111
111
Corresponding to AGENT/ STIMULUS (i.e. SUBJECT) American* (achievement, aggression)
Anglo-Russian* (agreement) atmospheric* (attack ‘chemical deterioration’) bilious* (attack ‘illness’) Chinese* (agitation) critical* (acclaim) divine* (approval) human* (agony) international (agreement, assistance) Marxist* (analysis) mutual (annihilation) national* (agony, agreement) oppositional* (approach) parental* (assistance) personal* (attendance ‘service’) professional (assistance) royal* (assent) Russian* (aggression, answer) professional* (assistance, attention ‘treatment’) specialist* (advice) Western* (alliance) Yugoslav* (approval) Corresponding to GOAL (i.e. OBJECT) bacterial* (analysis) communist* (affiliation) musical (appreciation) personal (attack ‘criticism’) popular (appeal)
(‘additional quality of N’)
QUALITY
Corresponding to ATTITUDINAL – SUBECT-ORIENTED audacious (assertion) characteristic (abstinence) pathetic (attempt)
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
260 Appendix 2 Corresponding to ATTITUDINAL – MESSAGE-ORIENTED classical (assumption) conventional (allowance) common (assumption) disastrous (attack ‘assault’) due* (allowance) essential* (achievement, action) excellent* (agreement) famous* (advice) important (advance, aim, anger, assumption) interesting (attempt) much-needed* (addition) necessary* (action, adjustment) plausible (assumption) radical (alliance) reasonable (agreement, average) striking (agreement) sudden (attack ‘illness’) uncongenial* (acquaintance) unexpected (agreement, attention ‘concentration’) unexplained* (attack ‘illness’) unfortunate (application ‘request for job’) unjustified (assumption) unreasonable (attack ‘criticism’) unthinkable (action) welcome* (addition) well-known* (attack ‘criticism’) Corresponding to
VOLITIONAL
adventitious (attraction) conscious (assistance) deliberate (attempt) intentional (action) unconscious (attempt) Corresponding to
RESULT/
OUTCOME
abortive (attempt) affirmative (answer)
corrosive (attack ‘chemical deterioration’) favourable (answer) successful (application ‘use’, assault) unsuccessful (attempt) useful (attempt) Corresponding to MANNER PROCESS-ORIENTED balanced* (advance) best* (advice, aid, answer) blatant (assessment) complicated* (agitation, argument ‘rationale’) convulsive (agony) curious (advertisement, argument ‘rationale’) delayed* (action) delightful (adaptation, approach) different (account) direct (action, answer, application ‘use’) dramatic (action) effective (action, arrangements, assessment) excellent (advice) false (account, assumption) familiar* (ache) formal (agreement, announcement, application ‘submission’) fraudulent (application ‘use’) good* (action, advice, agreement) gradualist (approach) graduated* (addition) hidden* (authority ‘authorization’) improved* (agreement) insidious (argument ‘rationale’) intricate (adjustment) irregular (association) natural (application ‘use’) official (announcement) plain* (application ‘submission’)
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of adjective modifying deverbal nouns 261 poor (attempt) practical (application ‘use’) proper (adjustment, advice) public (appearance) rapid (action) ready (application ‘use’) restrictive (amendment) right* (approach) satisfactory (answer) scurrilous (attack ‘criticism’) separate (access, application ‘use’, assessment) shabby (attack ‘criticism’) similar (application ‘submission’) simplifying* (amendment) sound (advice) special (appeal ‘plea’) specific (action, arrangements) starring* (appearance) straight* (acting, answer) straightforward (adaptation) suitable (appointment ‘nomination for job’) sweet (agony) valuable (assistance) wholesome* (advice) working* (arrangement) wrong (answer) Corresponding to MANNER – SUBJECT-ORIENTED aggressive (action) bland (assumption) brisk (action) careful (analysis, application ‘use’) clever (arrangement) concerted (action) constructive (attention ‘concentration’) contemptuous (amusement) cool (aim ‘targeting’) crazy (attack) decisive (action) determined (attempt)
disagreeable (accompaniment) discreet (answer) discriminatory (action) disinterested (assessment) doctrinaire (attack ‘criticism’) eager (acceptance) earnest (appreciation) expert (advice) feeble (attempt) flattering (assumption) friendly* (advice) genuine (agreement) graceful (admission ‘confession’) grumbling (action) happy (association) humble (address) inborn* (appreciation) interpretive* (analysis) melancholy* (assessment) menacing (anger) meticulous (account) mysterious (appeal ‘attraction’) nagging (authority ‘authorization’) natural (act) objective (appraisal) painstaking (account) parochial (assessment) pathetic (appeal ‘plea’) pious (act) polite (applause, attempt) positive (action, approach, assessment) practical (approach) purposive (action) quick (appreciation) quiet (attention ‘concentration’) rapt (attention ‘concentration’) realistic (acting, adjustment, approach) reflective* (acting) reliable (answer) righteous (anger) ruthless (action) sardonic (attention ‘concentration’)
1
1
1
262 Appendix 2 silent (agony) slow (advance) sudden (anger) superficial (account) successful (adjustment) sympathetic (approach) systematic (account) tacit (assumption) undogmatic (approach) uneasy (astonishment) unquestioning (acceptance) violent (attack ‘assault’) wicked (amusement) Corresponding to
METHOD
experimental (advance) pictorial (allusion) smoothed* (average)
11
11
11
11
immediate (action, aid, aim, answer) last-moment* (adjustment) later (amendment) latest* (acquisition, addition) modern* (attempt) new* (addition, advice, approach, attempt) old* (ache) present (agreement, arrangement) present-day* (arrangement) previous (account, acquaintance, appearance, assumption) prior* (agreement, assumption) prompt (appearance) subsequent (affirmation) timely* (assistance) corresponding to
Corresponding to SUBJECT ADJUNCT (Comitative and Statal) collective (agreement) common (agreement, approach) helpless (amazement) joint (account, action) mutual (agreement) open-mouthed (attention ‘concentration’) near-panic* (action) petrified* (amazement) Corresponding to
TIME
TIME
–
DURATION
fifty-year-old* (association) long* (answer, association) long-term* (agreement, aid, aim) short* (answer) short-term* (agreement) temporary (assumption) twelve-minute* (appearance) Corresponding to
TIME
–
FREQUENCY
–
annual (allowance) yearly* (average)
RELATIVE
current (attack ‘criticism’) earlier* (act) early* (acceptance) following* (analysis) foregoing* (analysis) fresh* (agony) future* (achievement)
corresponding to
SERIAL
RESTRICTOR
first (action, analysis, appearance, assault, assumption, attempt) final (act, action, agreement, approach, ascent)
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of adjective modifying deverbal nouns 263 last (analysis, assertion, attendance ‘presence’) next* (attempt) second (assumption, attempt) EXTENT (‘quantitative specification of N’)
Corresponding to
DEGREE
adequate (access) big* (amalgamation, award) biggest* (achievement) complete (agreement, answer, assurance) considerable (agreement, appeal ‘attraction’, application ‘use’, attention ‘concentration’, authority ‘authorization’) elementary* (account) full (account, agreement, allowance, analysis, assessment) fuller* (account) fully-fledged* (action) great* (achievement, affront, argument ‘quarrel’, attention ‘concentration’, authority ‘authorization’) greatest* (application ‘use’) growing* (anger) higher* (authority ‘authorization’) immense (amusement) little* (annotation) long* (account, addition) major* (aggression, agitation, attack ‘criticism’) maximum* (allocation, assimilation) modest (addition) powerful (appeal ‘attraction’) scant* (attention ‘concentration’)
sharp (attention ‘concentration’) substantial (agreement) sufficient (answer) supreme* (act of courage) 2 tremendous (attraction) utmost* (assurance) whole (approach, attention ‘concentration’) wide (acceptance) wider (amalgamation) Corresponding to CONJUNCTIONAL
additional (aid) further* (assistance, attack ‘assault’) other* (= ‘more’) (attack ‘assault’) Corresponding to ATTITUDINAL – MESSAGE-ORIENTED noteworthy* (achievement) remarkable (achievement) significant (advance) Corresponding to ATTITUDINAL – SUBJECT-ORIENTED reasonable (acceptance) Corresponding to MANNER – SUBJECT-ORIENTED bad* (attack ‘illness’) bitter (argument ‘quarrel’) convincing (assurance) concentrated (attention ‘concentration’) emphatic (appeal ‘plea’) vigorous (argument ‘quarrel’)
2 The corresponding adverb supremely modifies not the underlying verb act, but the underlying adjective of the noun in the preposition phrase modifying the noun courage.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
264 Appendix 2 Corresponding to MANNER – PROCESS-ORIENTED best* (argument ‘rationale’) close (association) comprehensive (account) correct (alignment) detailed* (account, appraisal, approval, argument ‘rationale’) exhaustive (analysis) free (access, admission ‘entrance’) good* (attendance ‘presence’) heavy* (attendance ‘presence’) intimate (acquaintance) keener (appreciation) large* (attendance ‘presence’) prominent (attention ‘concentration’) radical (advance) spectacular (achievement, advance) true (alignment) valid (argument ‘rationale’) Corresponding to
PATH
direct (access) Corresponding to
Corresponding to
FREQUENCY
common (agreement) general (acceptance, acknowledgement, agreement, approval) habitual (acceptance) numerous* (amendments) occasional (aid, attack ‘illness’) regular (allowance, attendance ‘presence’) repeated (application ‘use’, attempt) single (application ‘use’, attack ‘illness’) usual (assumption) Corresponding to
SERIAL
RESTRICTOR
first (aim) final (authority ‘authorization’)
PLACE
close (agreement, approach, attention ‘concentration’) closer* (attention ‘concentration’) continental* (advance) nearer* (approach) universal (agreement, answer) widespread* (advance, agreement, amazement, assent) Corresponding to
preliminary (arrangements) short* (account, attack)
DURATION
brief (account, appearance) constant (attention ‘concentration’) long* (account, addition)
FACTUAL STATUS (‘normal/ questionable member of the category N’)
Corresponding to
VALIDITY
actual (achievement, appreciation) apparent (adjustment) fundamental (assumption) general (aim) implicit (assumption) implied* (affirmation) overall* (authority ‘authorization’, average) real (agony) token* (appearance) traceable* (attempt) true (alignment) ultimate (aim)
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Types of adjective modifying deverbal nouns 265 Corresponding to
LIKELIHOOD
definite (answer) likely* (arrangements) obvious (assumption) possible (adjustment, appointment ‘nomination for job’) proposed* (alteration) undoubted (authority ‘authorization’) Corresponding to
POLAR
RESTRICTOR
central (aim) main (advance, argument ‘rationale’, attraction ‘concentration’) mere (act) only* (appearance)
particular (assessment, attention ‘concentration’) primary (aim) principal (assumption) special (assessment, attention ‘concentration’) single* (act) proposed* (alteration) Corresponding to MANNER – PROCESS-ORIENTED approximate (coverage) imprecise (analysis) moving* (average) Corresponding to MANNER – SUBJECT-ORIENTED genuine (agreement)
1
Appendix 3 Potential of eventive3 nouns for thin verbs4
1
1
11
ABHORRENCE ABOMINATION ABORTION
ABRIDGEMENT ABSOLUTION
ABSTINENCE ABUNDANCE ABUSE
11
ACCEPTANCE ACCESS
feel be carry-out do induce perform make give grant pronounce receive practise be be come-in (for) heap hurl shout shower suffer take find meet (with) gain get give grant
ACCLAIM ACCLIMATIZATION ACCOMMODATION
ACCOMPANIMENT ACCORD
ACCOUNT
ACCUSATION ACHE ACHIEVEMENT ACKNOWLEDGEMENT ACQUAINTANCE
receive undergo arrive (at) come (to) find reach work out provide be (in) come (to) reach call (to) give render bring make feel have record register be make be have make strike-up
11
11
3 Agentive nouns are excluded, because they (together with agentive adjectives) regularly take a copular verb (be, become, etc.). 4 Phrasal verbs are spelt with a hyphen to mark their unity as one lexical item. Prepositional verbs are recorded with the preposition in parentheses. When a thin verb is used in two different constructions with the same eventive noun, this is recorded as ‘× 2’.
11
Potential of eventive nouns for thin verbs 267 ACQUISITION ACQUITTAL ACT ‘deed’ ACT ‘performance’ ACTING ACTION
11 ACTIVITY
11 ADAPTATION
ADDITION
111
111
111
111
ADDRESS ADJOURNMENT ADJUDICATION ADJUSTMENT ADMIRATION
make bring-in commit perform put-on do indulge (in) go (into) initiate move (into) take engage (in) stimulate carry-out do make undergo be be (in) come (in) make deliver give grant carry-out make make feel inspire
AFFECTATION AFFILIATION AFFIRMATION AFFRONT AGGLOMERATION AGGRAVATION AGGRESSION
AGITATION AGONY
AGREEMENT
ADMISSION
‘confession’
make
ADMISSION
‘entrance’
ADMITTANCE ADVANCE ADVANTAGE ADVERTISEMENT
ADVICE
gain give grant secure gain secure make give place publish put run give
AID
AILMENT AIM ‘purpose’ AIM ‘direction
shooting’
offer receive take assume put-on form make × 2 be suffer form cause carry-out commit incur provoke suffer stir-up experience feel suffer arrive (at) be be (in) bring out come (to) conclude enter have make negotiate reach work-out be (in) come (to) extend give go (to) minister offer provide × 2 receive suffer (from) have
of take
1
268 Appendix 3 AIR AIRING
ALARM
1
ALERT ALIENATION
1
ALIGNMENT ALLEGATION ALLIANCE
11
11
ALLOCATION ALLOWANCE ALLUSION ALTERATION ALTERNATION AMALGAMATION AMBUSH AMAZEMENT AMENDMENT AMPLIFICATION AMPUTATION AMUSEMENT
ANAESTHESIA
11
11
ANALYSIS
give get give have arouse cause create feel fill (with) call cause suffer bring (into) make be (in) enter (into) forge form have make make be make do make be (in) undergo lie (in) wait (in) cause make provide carry-out afford cause feel find provide × 2 be (under) induce produce be be (under) do make
ANGER
ANNIHILATION ANNOTATION ANNOUNCEMENT ANNOYANCE
ANNULMENT
ANSWER
APOLOGY
‘attraction’ ‘plea’ ‘request for adjudication’
APPEAL APPEAL APPEAL
APPEARANCE APPEASEMENT APPENDAGE APPLAUSE
subject (to) undergo arouse cause incur show stir-up suffer make issue make cause feel suffer get grant obtain be be (in) elicit get × 2 give make obtain offer provide receive elicit express get × 2 make × 2 obtain offer × 2 have make file lodge put-in make put-in practise add break (into) burst (into) give
Potential of eventive nouns for thin verbs 269
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
APPLICATION
spark-off show
‘effort’ APPLICATION
‘request’
file make put-in send-in submit APPLICATION ‘use’ be find have APPOINTMENT ‘job’ give make APPRAISAL give make APPRECIATION feel have APPROACH have ‘attitude’ APPROACH make ‘contact’ APPROPRIATION make APPROVAL be (on) find get × 2 give × 2 meet (with) receive secure win × 2 ARBITRATION carry-out conduct go (to) ARGUE have ARGUMENT get ‘quarrel’ have spark-off ARGUMENT be ‘rationale’ drive-home offer present press put-forward
ARRANGEMENT
‘agreement’ ARRANGEMENT
‘timetable’ ARRANGEMENTS
‘prepare’ ARREST
ARTICULATION ASCENT ASPIRATION/S ASSASSINATION ASSAULT ASSENT ASSERTION ASSESSMENT
ASSIGNMENT ASSIMILATION ASSISTANCE
ASSOCIATION ASSUMPTION ASSURANCE ASTONISHMENT
ATONEMENT ATTACHMENT ATTACK
come (to) make work-out make be (under) carry-out effect make perform place (under) give make have carry-out commit give × 2 make carry-out do make give undergo be (of) come (to) give go (to) offer provide provide (with) render form make × 2 give × 2 arouse cause feel make add be be (on) be (under) carry-out launch
270 Appendix 3
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
ATTEMPT ATTENDANCE
make mount precipitate press press-home provoke spark-off have × 2 make × 2 put-in
ATTRACTION AUCTION AUDIT AUTHORITY
AUTHORIZATION
‘being present’ ATTENDANCE
‘service’ ATTENTION
‘concentrate’
dance attract × 2 capture × 2 catch × 2 command × 2 devote draw focus get × 2 give hold × 2
AUTOGRAPH AVERAGE
AVOWAL AWAKENING AWARD
pay receive × 2 retain × 2 feel put-up (for) do give grant grant × 2 give × 2 grant × 2 give be calculate work-out make suffer be give grant make present × 2 receive
11
Appendix 4 Complete list of stretched verb constructions5 found indicating obligatoriness/optionality with brackets distinguished in section II.1.iii
11
11
111
111
111
111
be ABANDONED be an ABETTER/-OR of smbd feel sm ABHORRENCE [at smbd/smth] be ABHORRENT (to smbd) be an ABHORRER of smth be ABOMINABLE (for smbd) be an ABOMINATION carry-out an ABORTION (on smbd) do an ABORTION (on smbd) induce an ABORTION (in smbd) perform an ABORTION (on smbd) be an ABORTIONIST be ABORTIVE be an ABRIDGER of smth make an ABRIDGEMENT of smth be an ABSCONDER be ABSENT [from smth] be an ABSENTEE [from smth] give ABSOLUTION [from smth] (to smbd) grant ABSOLUTION [from smth] (to smbd) pronounce ABSOLUTION [from smth]
receive ABSOLUTION [from smth] (from smbd) be ABSORBENT be ABSORBING (to/for smbd) be an ABSTAINER practise sm ABSTINENCE (from smth) be in ABUNDANCE be ABUNDANT be an ABUSE [of smth] come-in for sm ABUSE (from/at the hands of smbd) heap ABUSE on/upon smbd hurl ABUSE (at smbd) shout sm ABUSE (at smbd) shower ABUSE on/upon smbd suffer sm ABUSE (from/at the hands of smbd) take sm ABUSE [from smbd] be an ABUSER (of smbd) be ABUSIVE [to/towards smbd] be ACCEPTABLE [to smbd] find sm ACCEPTANCE [from smbd] meet with sm ACCEPTANCE [from smbd]
5 N.B. (1) Indirect objects are always given in their prepositional form (cf. section II.1.ii), but the non-prepositional form can be deduced following the model give an ADDRESS to smbd implies give smbd an ADDRESS, on the understanding that it applies only to the verbs cause, give, grant, make and offer with the prepositions to and for. (2) In noun phrases the indefinite article a(n) + NOUN implies the possibility of a plural noun phrase; similarly the possibility of sm + NOUN imples the possibility of Ø + NOUN, but not vice versa.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
272 Appendix 4 gain ACCESS [to smth/smwh] get ACCESS [to smth/smwh] give ACCESS [to smth/smwh] (to smbd) grant ACCESS [to smth/smwh] (to smbd) be ACCESSIBLE (to/for smbd) receive smbd with ACCLAIM undergo ACCLIMATIZATION be ACCOMMODATING [towards/to smbd] arrive at an ACCOMMODATION [with smbd] come to an ACCOMMODATION [with smbd] find an ACCOMMODATION [with smbd] reach an ACCOMMODATION [with smbd] work out an ACCOMMODATION [with smbd] provide the ACCOMPANIMENT [for smbd/smth] be an ACCOMPANIST {of smbd} be in ACCORD >with smbd/ smth< come to an ACCORD >with smbd< [about smth] reach an ACCORD >with smbd< [about smth] call smbd to ACCOUNT (for smth) give an ACCOUNT of smth (to smbd) render an ACCOUNT of smth (to smbd) be ACCOUNTABLE (to smbd) [for smth] bring an ACCUSATION [against smbd] make an ACCUSATION [against smbd] be an ACCUSER of smbd be ACCUSTOMED to smth make smbd ACCUSTOMED to smth feel an ACHE (smwh)
have an ACHE (smwh) record an ACHIEVEMENT register an ACHIEVEMENT be in ACKNOWLEDGEMENT of smth make an ACKNOWLEDGEMENT of smth be an/the ACQUAINTANCE {of smbd} have an ACQUAINTANCE with smbd/smth make the ACQUAINTANCE {of smbd} strike-up an ACQUAINTANCE >with smbd< make smbd ACQUAINTED with smth make an ACQUISITION be ACQUISITIVE bring-in an ACQUITTAL commit an ACT of a certain kind perform an ACT of a certain kind put-on an ACT do sm ACTING indulge in sm ACTING go into ACTION initiate ACTION move into ACTION take ACTION be ACTIVE engage in an/sm ACTIVITY stimulate an/sm ACTIVITY be an ACTOR carry-out an ADAPTATION [to smth] do an ADAPTATION [to smth] make an/sm ADAPTATION [to smth] undergo an ADAPTATION be an ADDITION [to smth] come in ADDITION [to smth] make an ADDITION [to smth] deliver an ADDRESS [to smbd] give an ADDRESS [to smbd] be an ADDRESSEE [of smth]
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Stretched verb constructions 273 be an ADHESIVE (for smth) grant an ADJOURNMENT of smth carry-out an ADJUDICATION [between people] make an ADJUDICATION [between people/things] be an ADJUDICATOR [between people] make an ADJUSTMENT [to smth] feel ADMIRATION for smbd inspire the ADMIRATION {of smbd} be an ADMIRER {of smbd} gain ADMISSION [to smwh/ smth] give ADMISSION [to smwh/smth] to smbd grant ADMISSION [to smwh/smth] to smbd make an ADMISSION (of/about smth) (to smbd) secure ADMISSION [to smwh/ smth] gain ADMITTANCE [to smwh/ smth] secure ADMITTANCE [to smwh/ smth] be an ADORER of smth/smbd make an ADVANCE be an ADVANTAGE [to smbd] give an ADVANTAGE to smbd be ADVANTAGEOUS (to/for smbd) place an ADVERTISEMENT (for smth) smwh publish an ADVERTISEMENT (for smth) put an ADVERTISEMENT (for smth) smwh run an ADVERTISEMENT (for smth) give sm ADVICE (about smth) [to smbd] offer sm ADVICE (about smth) [to smbd]
receive sm ADVICE (about smth) (from smbd) take ADVICE (about smth) (from smbd) be an ADVOCATE of smth assume an AFFECTATION put-on an AFFECTATION form an AFFILIATION >with smbd< make an AFFIRMATION (of smth) make an AFFIRMATION (to the effect) that + Clause be an AFFRONT [to smbd] suffer an AFFRONT (from/at-thehands-of smbd) be AFLOAT be AGAPE at smbd/smth be an AGENT {of/for smbd} form an AGGLOMERATION cause an/sm AGGRAVATION [of smth] carry-out AGGRESSION (against smbd/smwh) commit AGGRESSION (against smbd/smwh) incur AGGRESSION (from/ at-the-hands-of smbd) provoke AGGRESSION (from/ at-the-hands-of smbd) suffer AGGRESSION (from/ at-the-hands-of smbd) be AGGRESSIVE (towards smbd) be an AGGRESSOR against smbd stir-up AGITATION (against smbd/smth) be an AGITATOR (for/against smth) be AGLEAM be AGLITTER be AGLOW experience sm AGONY [with/about/over smth] feel sm AGONY [with/about/over smth]
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
274 Appendix 4 suffer sm AGONY [with/about/ over smth] arrive at an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] be an AGREEMENT [between sm pple] be in AGREEMENT >with smbd/smth< [about smth] be in AGREEMENT [with smth] bring about an AGREEMENT >between people< [about smth] come to an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] conclude an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] enter into an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] have an AGREEMENT >with smbd< make an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] negotiate an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] reach an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] work-out an AGREEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] be in AID of smth/smbd come to the AID {of smbd} extend sm AID to smbd give sm AID (to smbd) go to the AID {of smbd} minister sm AID to smbd offer sm AID [to/for smbd] provide sm AID [for smbd] provide smbd with sm AID receive sm AID (from smbd) render sm AID to smbd suffer from an AILMENT have an AIM (of doing/being smth) take AIM [at smbd/smth] give an AIR to smth get an AIRING give an AIRING to smth have an AIRING
arouse sm ALARM (in smbd) cause sm ALARM (in smbd) create sm ALARM (among pple) feel sm ALARM [at smth] fill smbd with ALARM be ALARMING (for smbd) be ALARMIST be an ALARMIST be ALERT (to smth) make smbd ALERT to smth call an ALERT cause ALIENATION (in smbd) suffer ALIENATION bring smth into ALIGNMENT be ALIVE make an ALLEGATION (that + Clause) (to smbd) be in ALLIANCE >with smbd< enter into an ALLIANCE >with smbd< forge an ALLIANCE >with smbd< form an ALLIANCE >with smbd< have an ALLIANCE >with smbd< make an ALLOCATION [of smth] to smbd make an/sm ALLOWANCE for smth be an ALLUSION to smbd/smth make an ALLUSION to smbd/ smth be an ALLY {of smbd} do an ALTERATION [to smth] make an ALTERATION [to smth] be ALTERNATE be in ALTERNATION >with smth/smbd< undergo AMALGAMATION >with smth< cause sm AMAZEMENT (to smbd) be AMAZING to/for smbd lie in AMBUSH [for smbd] wait in AMBUSH [for smbd] make an AMENDMENT [to smth] provide sm AMPLIFICATION [of /for smth]
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Stretched verb constructions 275 carry out an AMPUTATION (of smth) afford sm AMUSEMENT to smbd cause sm AMUSEMENT (for smbd) feel sm AMUSEMENT [at smth] find sm AMUSEMENT [in smth] provide sm AMUSEMENT (for smbd) provide smbd with sm AMUSEMENT
be AMUSING (for smbd) be under ANAESTHESIA induce ANAESTHESIA (in smbd) produce ANAESTHESIA in (smbd) be an ANALYSIS [of smth] be under ANALYSIS do an ANALYSIS of smth make an ANALYSIS of smth subject smth to an/sm ANALYSIS undergo an/sm ANALYSIS be ANALYTIC(AL) (about smth) arouse the ANGER {of smbd} cause sm ANGER incur the ANGER {of smbd} show sm ANGER stir-up the ANGER {of smbd} be ANGRY (with/at smbd) (about/ at smth) make smbd ANGRY suffer ANNIHILATION (at-thehands-of smbd) make an ANNOTATION [on smbd/ smth] issue an ANNOUNCEMENT (about smth) make an ANNOUNCEMENT (about smth) cause sm ANNOYANCE (to/for smbd) feel sm ANNOYANCE [with/at/about smbd/smth] suffer sm ANNOYANCE (from/ at-the-hands-of smbd) be ANNOYED (with/at smbd) (about/at smth)
make smbd ANNOYED be ANNOYING (for smbd) get an ANNULMENT [of smth] (from smbd) grant an ANNULMENT [of smth] [to smbd] obtain an ANNULMENT [of smth] (from smbd) be an ANSWER [to smth] be in ANSWER to smth elicit an ANSWER [to smth] [from smbd] get an ANSWER [to smth] [from smbd] – with intent get an ANSWER [to smth] [from smbd] – without intent give an ANSWER [to smth] (to smbd) make an ANSWER [to smth] (to smbd) obtain an ANSWER [to smth] [from smbd] offer an ANSWER [to smth] (to smbd) provide an ANSWER [to smth] receive an ANSWER [to smth] [from smbd] be ANSWERABLE (to smbd) [for smth] be ANTAGONISTIC towards smbd be APOLOGETIC [about smth] (to smbd) elicit an APOLOGY [for smth] [from smbd] express one’s APOLOGIES [about/for smth] (to smbd) get an APOLOGY [for smth] [from smbd] – with intent get an APOLOGY [for smth] [from smbd] – without intent make an APOLOGY [for/about smth] [to smbd] make one’s APOLOGIES [about/ for smth] (to smbd)
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
276 Appendix 4 obtain an APOLOGY [for smth] [from smbd] offer an APOLOGY [for/about smth] [to smbd] offer one’s APOLOGIES [about/ for smth] be APPALLING (for smbd) have an/sm APPEAL (for smbd) make an APPEAL to smbd (about smth) file an APPEAL [against smth] [with smbd] lodge an APPEAL [against smth] [with smbd] put-in an APPEAL [for/against smth] [to smbd] make an APPEARANCE [smwh] put-in an APPEARANCE [smwh] practise APPEASEMENT add an APPENDAGE [to smth] break into APPLAUSE (at smth) burst into APPLAUSE (at smth) give sm APPLAUSE (for smth) [to smbd/smth] spark off APPLAUSE (from smbd) be an APPLICANT [for smth] be an APPLICATION [for smth] file an APPLICATION [for smth] find sm APPLICATION have an APPLICATION make an APPLICATION [for smth] (to smbd) put-in an APPLICATION [for smth] send-in an APPLICATION [for smth] submit an APPLICATION [for smth] (to smbd) show APPLICATION give an APPOINTMENT to smbd make an APPOINTMENT give an APPRAISAL of smth (to smbd) make an APPRAISAL of smth feel sm APPRECIATION for smbd/smth
have an APPRECIATION of smth be APPRECIATIVE [of smth/smbd] have an APPROACH [to smth] make an APPROACH [to smbd] (about smth) make an APPROPRIATION (of smth) [for smbd] be on APPROVAL find the APPROVAL {of smbd} get APPROVAL [for smth] [from smbd] get the APPROVAL {of smbd} [for smth] – with intent get the APPROVAL {of smbd} – without intent give (one’s) APPROVAL [for smth] [to smbd] give (one’s) APPROVAL [to smth] meet with the APPROVAL {of smbd} receive the APPROVAL {of smbd} secure the APPROVAL {of smbd} [for smth] seek the APPROVAL {of smbd} [for smth] win APPROVAL [for smth] [from smbd] win the APPROVAL {of smbd} [for smth] be APPROXIMATE be an ARBITRATOR (between pple) carry-out ARBITRATION [between people] conduct ARBITRATION [between people] go to ARBITRATION have an ARGUE >with smbd< spark off an ARGUMENT (between people) (about smth) get into an ARGUMENT >with smbd< (about smth) have an ARGUMENT >with smbd< (about smth) be an ARGUMENT for/against smth
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Stretched verb constructions 277 drive-home an ARGUMENT [for smth] offer an ARGUMENT [for smth] present an ARGUMENT [for smth] press an ARGUMENT [for smth] put-forward an ARGUMENT [for smth] be ARGUMENTATIVE come to an ARRANGEMENT >with smbd< [about smth] make an ARRANGEMENT [(for smbd) to do smth] work-out an ARRANGEMENT [(for smbd) to do smth] make (sm) ARRANGEMENTS [for smth] be an ARRANGER (of smth) be under ARREST carry-out an ARREST effect an ARREST make an ARREST perform an ARREST place smbd under ARREST put smbd under ARREST be ARTICULATE (about smth) make smth ARTICULATE give ARTICULATION to smth make an/the ASCENT [of smwh/ smth] be ASLEEP be an ASPIRANT to smth have an ASPIRATION (to be/ do smth) carry-out an/the ASSASSINATION [of smbd] commit an ASSAULT (on smbd) give one’s ASSENT (to smbd) [for smth] give one’s ASSENT [to smth] make an ASSERTION [that-Clause] carry-out an ASSESSMENT [of smth/smbd] do an ASSESSMENT [of smth/ smbd]
make an ASSESSMENT [of smth/ smbd] give an ASSIGNMENT to smbd undergo ASSIMILATION >with/(in)to smth< be of sm ASSISTANCE [to smbd] come to the ASSISTANCE {of smbd} give sm ASSISTANCE [to smbd] go to the ASSISTANCE {of smbd} offer sm ASSISTANCE [to smbd] provide sm ASSISTANCE [for smbd] provide smbd with sm ASSISTANCE
render sm ASSISTANCE [to smbd] be an ASSISTANT {of smbd} be an ASSOCIATE >of smbd< form an ASSOCIATION >with smbd< make an ASSUMPTION (about smbd/smth) make an ASSUMPTION (that-Clause) give an ASSURANCE [about/of smth] [to smbd] give an ASSURANCE [that-Clause] [to smbd] be ASTONISHING (to/for smbd) arouse sm ASTONISHMENT (in smbd) cause sm ASTONISHMENT (in smbd) feel sm ASTONISHMENT [at smth/smbd] be ASTOUNDING (to/for smbd) make ATONEMENT [for smth] add an ATTACHMENT [to smth] be an ATTACK [on smbd/smth] be on the ATTACK be under ATTACK carry-out an ATTACK (on smbd/ smth) come under ATTACK
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
278 Appendix 4 launch an ATTACK (on smbd/ smth) make an ATTACK (on smbd/smth) mount an ATTACK (on smbd/ smth) precipitate an ATTACK (on smbd/ smth) (by smbd) press an ATTACK (on smbd/smth) press-home an ATTACK (on smbd/ smth) provoke an ATTACK (on smbd/ smth) (by smbd) spark off an ATTACK (on smbd/smth) (by smbd) have an ATTEMPT [at doing smth] have an ATTEMPT [at smth] make an ATTEMPT [at smth] make an ATTEMPT to do smth put in an ATTENDANCE [at smth] dance ATTENDANCE on smbd be an ATTENDANT attract the ATTENTION {of smbd} – human subj attract the ATTENTION {of smbd} – inanimate subj capture the ATTENTION {of smbd} – human subj capture the ATTENTION {of smbd} – inanimate subj catch the ATTENTION {of smbd} – human subj catch the ATTENTION {of smbd} – inanimate subj command the ATTENTION {of smbd} –human subj command the ATTENTION {of smbd} – inanimate subj devote one’s ATTENTION to smth/smbd draw the ATTENTION {of smbd} to smth focus one’s ATTENTION on smth/smbd
get the ATTENTION {of smbd} – human subj get the ATTENTION {of smbd} – inanimate subj give sm/one’s ATTENTION to smth/smbd hold the ATTENTION {of smbd} – human subj hold the ATTENTION {of smbd} – inanimate subj pay sm ATTENTION [to smth/ smbd] receive ATTENTION (from smbd) receive the ATTENTION {of smbd} retain the ATTENTION {of smbd} – human subj retain the ATTENTION {of smbd} – inanimate subj be ATTENTIVE [to smbd/ smth] feel an ATTRACTION for smbd/ smth be ATTRACTIVE (to/for smbd) put smth up for AUCTION do an AUDIT (of smth) give AUTHORITY [to do smth] (to smbd) grant AUTHORITY [to do smth] (to smbd) give AUTHORIZATION [for smth] (to smbd) give AUTHORIZATION [to do smth] (to smbd) grant AUTHORIZATION [for smth] (to smbd) grant AUTHORIZATION [to do smth] (to smbd) give one’s AUTOGRAPH (to smbd) be AUTOMATIC make smth AUTOMATIC be an AVENGER be an AVERAGE [of sm things]
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Stretched verb constructions 279 calculate an AVERAGE [of sm things] work-out an AVERAGE [of sm things] make an AVOWAL (that-Clause) suffer an AWAKENING be an AWARD [to smbd]
give an AWARD [to smbd] grant an AWARD [to smbd] make an AWARD (to smbd) present an AWARD [to smbd] present smbd with an AWARD receive an AWARD (from smbd)
1
Glossary
1
1
11
11
11
11
(AE): an adverbial required by the valency of a verb, e.g. (live) abroad/in the country; (last) long/for two hours.
ADVERBIAL ELABORATOR
AUXILIARY VERB STRUCTURE:
the total range of elements (tense, primary and modal auxiliaries) that can help specify a lexical verb in a finite clause for tense, modality, etc.
DESCRIPTOR:
(also called ‘predicative/complement’) an elaborator of a copular verb (e.g. be, become, seem), the subvarieties being ADJECTIVAL DESCRIPTOR (= AD, e.g. (be) doubtful ), NOMINAL DESCRIPTOR (= ND, e.g. (be) a doubter) and PREPOSITIONAL DESCRIPTOR (= PD, e.g. (be) in doubt).
ELABORATED VERB STRUCTURE:
a lexical verb together with all the
elaborators its valency requires. ELABORATOR:
a phrase that (partially) satisfies the valency requirements of a verb, adjective or noun.
EVENTIVE NOUN:
a noun denoting a type of state or happening (e.g. amendment, answer, arrival), normally derived from a verb and traditionally referred to as ‘nomen actionis’. (OF NOUN) (FC): a finite clause required by the valency of a noun, e.g. (allegation) that the arrangement is dishonest.
FINITE CLAUSE COMPLEMENT
(F): a finite clause required by the valency of a verb, e.g. (allege) that the arrangement is dishonest.
FINITE CLAUSE ELABORATOR
(GQ): a noun qualifier that may take the form of either a preposed possessive noun phrase or a postposed of-phrase, e.g. Sebastian’s (attention) or (the attention) of Sebastian.
GENITIVAL QUALIFIER
(OF NOUN) (GC): a structure of preposition plus gerund clause used to complement (i.e. complete the valency of) a noun, e.g. (the habit) of singing late at night.
GERUND COMPLEMENT
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Glossary
281
(G): a gerund clause (possibly including its own independent subject) that is acting as an elaborator of a verb, e.g. (anticipated) (her) singing a wrong note.
GERUND ELABORATOR
(IO): an elaborator of a verb that is a second object, i.e. occurs in addition to a direct object, which it either precedes or follows with the preposition to or for, like us/to us in the sentence: Tony brought us a piano/brought a piano to/for us.
INDIRECT OBJECT
(IÖ): an elaborator of a verb that is a second objoid, i.e. occurs in addition to a (direct) objoid, which it precedes, like us in the sentence: The piano cost us fifty pounds.
INDIRECT OBJOID
(OF NOUN) (IC): a gerund clause used to complement (i.e. complete the valency of) a noun, e.g. (the tendency) to sing late at night.
INFINITIVE COMPLEMENT
(I): an infinitive clause (possibly including its own independent subject) that is acting as elaborator of a verb, e.g. (wanted) (her) to sing a wrong note.
INFINITIVE ELABORATOR
(L): an adverbial particle that is used as part of the valency of a lexical verb, combining with it (possibly also with an object) to give a phrasal verb, e.g. ( fall) over, ( put smbd ) off.
LIMITER ADVERB
(= DIRECT OBJECT) (O): a noun phrase that is part of the valency (= elaboration) of a verb (which it directly follows, except in structures with ‘fronting’ or with a prepositionless indirect object) and that corresponds to the subject of the related passive sentence with the same verb, e.g. the piano in Tony brought (us) the piano, corresponding to The piano was brought ((to) us) by Tony.
OBJECT
(= DIRECT OBJOID) (Ö): a noun phrase that is part of the valency (= elaboration) of a verb (which it directly follows, except in structures with ‘fronting’) but that does not correspond to the subject of the related passive sentence with the same verb, e.g. (The piano cost (us)) fifty pounds (with no corresponding sentence: *Fifty pounds were cost by the piano).
OBJOID
(OO): a noun phrase elaborator of a verb that is optionally preceded by a preposition and that occurs after the object but unlike the indirect object cannot be moved to the position before the direct object, e.g. Tony envied Margaret ( for) her longevity.
OBLIQUE OBJECT
( J): a by-preposition phrase that occurs in a passive sentence with the same meaning (of agent, experiencer, stimulus, etc.) as the subject in the corresponding active sentence, e.g. by Tony in: The committee was organized/admired/impressed by Tony (corresponding to Tony organized/admired/impressed the committee).
PERJECT
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
282 Glossary (PO): a noun phrase in a preposition phrase that is not adverbial but determined by the valency of the verb (with the choice of preposition determined by the verb) such that this noun phrase can act as subject in a corresponding passive sentence, e.g. The committee looked at/ objected to/interfered with the proposal (corresponding to The proposal was looked at/objected to/interfered with by the committee).
PREPOSITIONAL OBJECT
(PÖ): a noun phrase in a preposition phrase that is not adverbial but determined by the valency of the verb (with the choice of preposition determined by the verb) such that this noun phrase cannot act as subject in a corresponding passive sentence, e.g. The committee differed from/clashed with the minister (with no corresponding sentences *The minister was differed from/clashed with by the committee).
PREPOSITIONAL OBJOID
(PQ): a constituent of a noun phrase that follows and qualifies the head noun and that takes the form of a postposed preposition phrase in which the choice of preposition is determined by the individual noun, e.g. (attention) to detail beside (interest) in detail.
PREPOSITIONAL QUALIFIER
STRETCHED (ELABORATED) VERB STRUCTURE/CONSTRUCTION:
a non-minimal elaborated verb structure in which the verb itself is ‘thin’ (i.e. has a ‘lighter’ or ‘weaker’ meaning than usual) and the eventive meaning (normally carried by a verb) is expressed in a noun phrase or adjective phrase, e.g. give us some help, come to our help, be of help to us, be helpful to us.
(S): an obligatory noun phrase elaborator of a lexical verb that normally directly precedes it and determines its number/person concord and that, when pronominal, occurs in the nominative form; the perject in a passive sentence is said to be the ‘deep’ or ‘underlying’ subject because it corresponds to the subject of a related active sentence.
SUBJECT
THIN VERB:
a lexical verb used with a meaning that is ‘lighter’ or ‘weaker’ than usual because the ‘eventive’ meaning verbs normally carry is expressed by an elaborating noun phrase or adjective phrase, e.g. give, make, come (to) in give an answer, make a statement, come to an agreement.
VALENCY:
the requirement or potential that a lexical word (verb, adjective or noun) has for the presence of one or more structures whenever it occurs, in the way that a classic intransitive verb requires a subject but does not tolerate an object.
11
Bibliography
11
11
111
111
111
111
Aarts, J. (1991). ‘Intuition-based and observation-based grammars’. In: Aijmer, K. and Altenberg, B. English Corpus Linguistics: Studies in Honour of Jan Svartvik. London: Longman, 44–62. Aarts, J. M. G. and Calbert, J. P. (1979). Metaphor and Non-metaphor. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Abney, S. P. (1987). The English Noun Phrase in its Sentential Aspect. Cambridge, Mass.: doctoral thesis, MIT. Aijmer, K. and Altenberg, B. (1991). English Corpus Linguistics: Studies in Honour of Jan Svartvik. London: Longman. Akimoto, M. (1999). ‘Collocations and idioms in Late Modern English’. In: Brinton, L. J. and Akimoto, M. Collocational and Idiomatic Aspects of Composite Predicates in the History of English (= SLCS47). Amsterdam: Benjamins, 207–38). Algeo, J. (1995). ‘Having a look at the expanded predicate’. In: Aarts, B. and Meyer, C. F. (eds), The Verb in Contemporary English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Allerton, D. J. (with French, M. A.) (1975). ‘Morphology: the forms of English’. Chapter 3 of: Bolton, W. F. (ed.), The English Language [= vol. X of the Sphere History of English Literature]. London: Sphere Books, 79–134. Allerton, D. J. (1978). ‘The notion of “given-ness”, and its relation to presuppositions and to theme’. Lingua 31, 133–68. Allerton, D. J. (1979). Essentials of Grammatical Theory. London: Routledge. Allerton, D. J. (1980). ‘Grammatical subject as a psycho-linguistic category’. Transactions of the Philological Society 1980, 40–61. Allerton, D. J. (1982). Valency and the English Verb. London: Academic Press. Allerton, D. J. (1984a). ‘Three (or four) levels of word cooccurrence restrictions’. Lingua 37, 17–40. Allerton, D. J. (1984b). ‘Verb + Predicative constructions and their limitations’. In: Fries, U. and Hasler, J. (eds), Anglistentag 1982 Zürich. Gieen: Hoffman Verlag, 411–20. Allerton, D. J. (1987a). ‘English intensifiers and their idiosyncracies’. In: Steele, R. and Threadgold, T. (eds), Language Topics: Essays in Honour of Michael Halliday, vol. 2. Amsterdam: Benjamins, 15–31. Allerton, D. J. (1987b). ‘The linguistic and sociolinguistic status of proper names’. Journal of Pragmatics 11, 61–92. Allerton, D. J. (1988). ‘“Infinitivitis” in English’. In: Klegraf, J. and Nehls, D. (eds), Studies in Descriptive Linguistics (essays on the English Language and Applied Linguistics on the Occasion of Gerhard Nickel’s 60th Birthday). Heidelberg: Julius Groos, 11–23.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
284 Bibliography Allerton, D. J. (1990a). ‘Language as form and pattern: grammar and its categories’. In: Collinge, N. E. (ed.), An Encyclopaedia of Language. London: Routledge, 68–111. Allerton, D. J. (1990b). ‘Linguistically strange word combinations’. In: Bridges, M. (ed.) (1990). On Strangeness [= Swiss Papers in English Language and Literature 5]. Tübingen: Narr, 25–38. Allerton, D. J. (1992). ‘Problems of Modern English grammar II – Disagreement about agreement (findings); and new topic’. English Studies 73, 458–70. Allerton, D. J. (1994). ‘Valency and valency grammar’. In Asher, R. E. and Simpson, J. M. Y. (eds) The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 4878–86. Allerton, D.J., Carney, E. and Holdcroft, D. (eds) (1979). Function and Context in Linguistic Analysis: A Festschrift for William Haas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Allerton, D. J. and Cruttenden, A. (1974). ‘English sentence adverbials: their syntax and their intonation in British English’. Lingua 27, 1–29. Allerton, D. J. and Cruttenden, A. (1978). ‘Syntactic, illocutionary, thematic and attitudinal factors in the intonation of adverbials’. Journal of Pragmatics 2, 155–88. Allerton, D. J. and Koya, I. (forthcoming). ‘Pre-/postpositional predicatives’: crosslanguage syntactic category or conventional implicature?’. To appear. Alverson, H. (1994). Semantics and Experience: Universal Metaphors of Time in English, Mandarin, Hindi and Lesotho. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Anderson, J. M. (1997). A Notional Theory of Syntactic Categories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Aronstein, P. (1924). Englische Stilistik. Leipzig/Berlin: Teubner. Asher, R. E. and Simpson, J. M. Y. (eds) (1994). The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. Oxford: Pergamon Press. Ashton, E. O. (1944). Swahili Grammar. London: Longman. Atkins, B. T. and Zampolli, A. (eds) (1994). Computational Approaches to the Lexicon. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bache, C. (1997). The Study of Aspect, Tense and Action: Towards a Theory of the Semantics of Grammatical Analysis. Frankfurt: Lang. Bäcklund, U. (1981). Restrictive Adjective-Noun Collocations in English. Umeå: Acta Universitatis Umensis. Bahns, J. (1996). Kollokationen als lexikographisches Problem: eine Analyse allgemeiner und spezieller Lernerwörterbücher des Englischen. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Barkema, H. (1996). ‘Idiomaticity and terminology: a multi-dimensional descriptive model’. Studia Linguistica 50, 125–60. Bazell, C. E., Catford, J. C., Halliday, M. A. K. and Robins, R. H. (1966). In Memory of J. R. Firth. London: Longman. Bechtel, W. and Abrahamsen, A. (1991). Connectionism and the Mind. Oxford: Blackwell. Benson, M. (1989). ‘The structure of the collocational dictionary’. International Journal of Lexicography 2, 1–14. Benson, M., Benson, E. and Ilson, R. (1986a). The BBI Combinatory Dictionary of English: a Guide to English Word Combinations. Amsterdam: Benjamins. Benson, M., Benson, E. and Ilson, R. (1986b). Lexicographic Description of English. Amsterdam: Benjamins. Björkman, S. (1978). Le type avoir besoin: étude sur la coalescence verbo-nominale en français. Uppsala: Acta Universitatis Upsaliensis (Studia Romanica Upsaliensia 21).
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Bibliography 285 Bloomfield, L. (1935). Language (British edition). London: Allen and Unwin. (American edition, 1933.) Bolinger, D. L. (1979). ‘The jungle theory of double -ing’. In: Allerton, D. J., Carney, E. and Holdcraft, D. (eds), Function and Context in Linguistic Analysis: a Festschrift for William Haas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 41–56. Brinton, L. J. and Akimoto, M. (1999). Collocational and Idiomatic Aspects of Composite Predicates in the History of English (= SLCS 47). Amsterdam: Benjamins. Brownell, H., Gardner, H., Prather, P. and Martino, G. (1994). ‘Language communication and the right hemisphere’. In: Kirshner, G. S. (ed.), Handbook of Neurological Speech and Language Disorders. New York: Marcel Decker, 325–49. Burger, H., Buhofer, A. and Sialm, A. (1982). Handbuch der Phraseologie. Berlin: de Gruyter. Byrne, L. S. R. and Churchill, E. L. (1986). A Comprehensive French Grammar (3rd edition, revised by G. Price; 1st edition 1950). Oxford: Blackwell. Cameron, D. (1988). Combinations of ‘Empty’ Verb with (De)Verbal Noun in Contemporary English. Basle: Lizentiatsarbeit der Universität Basel. Cattell, R. (1984). Complex Predicates in English. Sydney: Academic Press. Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton. Chomsky, N. (1970). ‘Remarks on nominalization’. In: Jacobs, R. and Rosenbaum, P. S. (eds), English Transformational Grammar. Waltham, Mass: Ginn, 184–221. Chomsky, N. (1976). Reflections on Language. London: Fontana. Chomsky, N. (1990). ‘On the nature, use and acquisition of language’. In: Lacan, W. G. (1990). Mind and Cognition: a Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 627–46. Chung, S. and Timberlake, A. (1985). ‘Tense, aspect and mood’. In: Shopen, T. (ed.), Language Typology and Syntactic Description III: Grammatical Categories and the Lexicon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 202–58. Clark, E. V. (1992). ‘Conventionality and contrast: pragmatic principles with lexical consequences’. In: Lehrer, A. and Kittay, E. F. (eds), Frames, Fields and Contrast: New Essays in Semantic and Lexical Organization. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum, 171–88. Collinge, N. E. (ed.) (1990). An Encyclopaedia of Language. London: Routledge. Cortès, C. (1997). ‘Décider, prendre une décision: du verbe à la locution verbale’. In: Fiala, P., Lafton, P. and Pignet, M.-F. La locution: entre lexique, syntexe et pragmatique, identification en corpus, traitment, apprentissage. (Publication di l’INALF, collection ‘Saint Cloud’). Paris: Klincksieck, 19–35. Cottrell, G. W. (1994). ‘Connectionist approaches to natural language processing’. In Asher, R. E. and Simpson, J. M. Y. (eds), The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 698–706. Cowie, A. P. (1990). ‘Language as words: lexicography’. In: Collinge, N. E. An Encyclopedia of Language. London: Routledge, 671–700. Cowie, A. P. (1994). ‘Phraseology’. In: Asher, R. E. and Simpson, J. M. Y. (eds), The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 3168–71. Cowie, A. P. (1998a). ‘Introduction’. In: Cowie, A. P. (ed.), Phraseology: Theory, Analysis and Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1–20. Cowie, A. P. (1998b). ‘Phraseological dictionaries: some east-west comparisons’. In: Cowie, A. P. (ed.), Phraseology: Theory, Analysis and Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 209–28. Cowie, A. P. (ed.) (1998c). Phraseology: Theory, Analysis and Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
286 Bibliography Cowie, A. P., Mackin, R. and McCaig, I. R. (1975/1983). Oxford Dictionary of Current Idiomatic English, volumes 1 and 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cruse, D. A. (1986). Lexical Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cruse, D. A. (1995). ‘Polysemy and related phenomena from a cognitive linguistic point of view’. In: St. Dizier, P. and Viegas, E. (eds), Computational Lexical Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 33–49. Culicover, P. (1996). Principles and Parameters: an Introduction to Syntactic Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Daniels, K. (ed.) (1963). Substantivierungstendenzen in der deutschen Gegenwartssprache. Düsseldorf: Schwann. Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dirven, R. (1989). ‘Verbs and verb phrases’. In: Dirven, R. and Putseys, Y. A User’s Grammar of English: Word, Sentence, Text, Interaction, Part A. Frankfurt-am-Main: Lang, 15–52. Dirven, R. and Putseys, Y. (eds) (1989). A User’s Grammar of English: Word, Sentence, Text, Interaction, Part A. Frankfurt-am-Main: Lang. Dixon, R. M. W. (1988). A Grammar of Boumaa Fijian. Chicago: University of Chicago. Dowty, D. (1979). Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel. Dras, M. and Johnson, M. (1996). ‘Death and lightness: using a demographic model to find support verbs’. Available electronically from cmp-lg/9610001, see www. mpce.mq.edu.au or [email protected] Dubois, J. (1969). Grammaire structurale du français. Paris: Larousse. Egg, M. (1995). ‘The intergressive as a new category of verbal Aktionsart’. Journal of Semantics 12, 311–56. Engelen, B. (1968). ‘Zum System der Funktionsverbgefüge’. Wirkendes Wort 18, 289–303. Fernando, C. and Flavell, R. (1981). On Idiom: Critical Views and Perspectives. Exeter: University of Exeter. Fiala, P., Lafon, P. and Piguet, M.-F. (1997). La locution: entre lexique, syntaxe et pragmatique, identification en corpus, traitement, apprentissage. (Publication di l’INALF, collection “Saint Cloud”). Paris: Klincksieck. Fillmore, C. J. (1968). ‘The case for case’. In: Bach, E. and Harems, R. T. (eds), Universals in Linguistic Theory. New York: Holt Rinehart, 1–88. Fillmore, C. J. (1971). ‘Some problems for case grammar’. In: O’Brien, R. J. (ed.), Report of the 22nd Round Table Meeting on Linguistics and Language Studies (= MSSL 24). Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 35–56. Fillmore, C. J. (1977). ‘The case for case re-opened’. In: Cole, P. and Sadock, J. M. (eds), Syntax and Semantics, Volume 8: Grammatical Relations. New York: Academic Press, 59–81. Fillmore, C. J. and Atkins, B. T. S. (1992). ‘Towards a frame-based lexicon: the semantics of RISK and its neighbours’. In: Lehrer, A. and Kittay, E. F. (eds), Frames, Fields and Contrast: New Essays in Semantic and Lexical Organization. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrance Erlbaum, 75–102. Fillmore, C. J. and Atkins, B. T. S. (1994). ‘Starting where the dictionaries stop: the challenge of corpus lexicography’. In: Atkins, B. T. and Zampolli, A. (eds), Computational Approaches to the Lexicon. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 349–93. Fillmore, C. J., Kay, P. and O’Connor, C. (1988). ‘Regularity and idiomaticity in grammatical constructions: the case of let alone’. Language 64, 501–38.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Bibliography 287 Firth, J. R. (1957). Papers in Linguistics 1934–1951. London: Oxford University Press. Fodor, J. R. and Katz, J. J. (eds) (1964). The Structure of Language, Readings in the Philosophy of Language. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. Fontenelle, T. (1998). ‘Discovering significant lexical functions in dictionary entries’. In: Cowie, A. P. (ed.), Phraseology: Theory, Analysis and Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 189–207. François, J. and Grass, T. (1997). ‘Les constructions à verbe support en lexicographie juridique bilingue (allemand/francais)’. In: Fiala, P., Lafon. P. and Piguet, M.-F. La locution: entre lexique, syntexe et pragmatique, identification en corpus, traitement, apprentissage. (Publication di l’INALF, collection ‘Saint Cloud’). Paris: Klincksieck, 183–98. Fraser, B. (1970). ‘Idioms within transformational grammar’. Foundations of Language 6, 22–42. Frawley, W. (1992). Linguistic Semantics. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. Garman, M. (1990). Psycholinguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gibbs, R. and Nayak, N. (1989). ‘Psycholinguistic studies on the syntactic behaviour of idioms’. Cognitive Psychology 21, 100–38. Gibbs, R., Nayak, N., Bolton, J. and Kapper, M. (1989). ‘Speakers’ assumptions about the lexical flexibility of idioms’. Memory and Cognition 17, 58–68. Gibbs, R., Nayak and Cutting, C. (1989). ‘How to kick the bucket and not decompose: analysability and idiom processing’. Journal of Memory and Language 28, 567–93. Givon, T. (1984). Syntax: a Functional–Typological Introduction I. Amsterdam: Benjamins. Gläser, R. (1986). Phraseologie der englischen Sprache. Leipzig: Verlag Enzyklopädie; and Tübingen: Niemeyer. Goldberg, A. C. (1995). Constructions: a Construction Grammar Approach to Argument Structure. Chicago: University of Chicago. Greenbaum, S. and Quirk, R. (1970). Elicitation Experiments in English: Linguistic Studies in Use and Attitude. London: Longman. Gross, G. and Kiefer, F. (1995). ‘La structure événementielle de substantifs’. Folia Linguistica 29, 43–65. Gross, M. (1981). ‘Les bases empiriques de la notion de prédicat sémantique’. Language 63, 7–52. Gross, M. (1994). ‘Constructing lexicon-grammars’. In: Atkins, B. T. and Zampolli, A. (eds), Computational Approaches to the Lexicon. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 213–63. Gutiérrez, M. L. (1993). Estructuras sintácticas del español actual, 4th edition (1st edition 1978). Alcobendas (Madrid): Sociedad General Española de Librería. Haas, W. (1966). ‘Linguistic relevance’. In: Bazell, C. E., Catford, J. C., Halliday, M. A. K. and Robins, R. H. In Memory of J. R. Firth. London: Longman, 116–47. Haas, W. (1980). ‘Sentence meanings and truth-values’. In: Brettschneider, G. and Lehmann, C. (eds), Wege zur Universalienforschung. Tübingen: Narr, 65–75. Halliday, M. A. K. (1966). ‘Lexis as a linguistic level’. In: Bazell et al. In Memory of J. R. Firth. London: Longman, 148–162. Halliday, M. A. K. (1970). ‘Language structure and language function’. In: Lyons, J. (ed.), New Horizons in Linguistics. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 140–65. Halliday, M. A. K. (1985). An Introduction to Functional Grammar. London: Edward Arnold. Harris, Z. S. (1957). ‘Cooccurrence and transformation in linguistic structure’. Language 33. 283–340. (Reprinted in Fodor and Katz (1964: 155–210) and in Householder (1972: 151–85).)
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
288 Bibliography Heringer, H.-J. (1989). Lesen, Lehren, Lernen: eine rezeptive Grammatik des Deutschen. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Herrlitz, W. (1973). Funktionsverbgefüge vom Typ ‘in Erfahrung bringen’. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Hockett, C. F. (1958). A Course in Modern Linguistics. New York: Macmillan. Hopper, P. and Thompson, S. (1984). ‘The discourse basis for lexical categories in universal grammar’. Language 60, 703–52. Householder, F. W. (ed.) (1972). Syntactic Theory I: Structuralist. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Howarth, P. (1998). ‘The phraseology of learners’ academic writing’. In: Cowie, A.P. (ed.), Phraseology: Theory, Analysis and Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 161–86. Jackendoff, R. S. (1977). X-bar Syntax: a Study of Phrase Structure. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Jespersen, O. (1933). Essentials of English Grammar. London: Allen and Unwin. Jespersen, O. (1942). A Modern English Grammar on Historical Principles VI. Copenhagen: Ejnar Munsgaard/London: Allen & Unwin. Joos, M. (1964). The English Verb. Madison, Wisc.: University of Wisconsin Press. Keller, R. E. (1978). The German Language. London: Faber and Faber. Kelly, E. F. and Stone, P. J. (1975). Computer Recognition of English Word Senses. Amsterdam: North Holland. Kirchner, G. (1952). Die Zehn Hauptverben des Englischen – im Britischen und Amerikanischen. Halle: Niemeyer. Kjellmer, G. (1994). A Dictionary of English Collocations, 3 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Koya, I. (1992). Subjecthood and Related Notions: a Contrastive Study of English, German and Japanese. Basle: Birkhäuser. Kruisinga, E. (1932) A Handbook of Present-day English, II/3. Groningen: Noordhoff. Laczkó, T. (1985). ‘Deverbal nominals and their complements in noun phrases’. In: Kenesei, I. (ed.), Approaches to Hungarian 1: Data and Descriptions. Szeged: Jate, 92–118. Lakoff, G. and Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we Live by. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Lambton, A. K. S. (1953). Persian Grammar (paperback edition with key, 1974). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Langacker, R. A. (1987). ‘Nouns and verbs’. Language 63, 53–94. Langacker, R. A. (1987, 1991). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, 2 vols. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. Leech, G. N. (1991). ‘The state of the art in corpus linguistics’. In: Aijmer, K. and Altenberg, B. (eds), English Corpus Linguistics: Studies in Honour of Jan Svartvik. London: Longman, 8–29. Leech, G. N. (1992). ‘Corpora and theories of linguistic performance’. In: Svartvik, J. Directions in Corpus Linguistics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 105–22. Lehrer, A. and Kittay, E. F. (eds) (1992). Frames, Fields and Contrasts: New Essays in Semantic and Lexical Organization. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum. Lepschy, A. L. and Lepschy, G. (1988). The Italian Language Today, 2nd edition (1st edition: 1977). London: Routledge. Lewis, G. L. (1967). Turkish Grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Bibliography 289 Lipka, L. (1990). An Outline of English Lexicology. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Lyons, J. (1966). ‘Towards a notional theory of the parts of speech’. Journal of Linguistics 2, 209–36. Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mac Cormac, E. R. (1985). A Cognitive Theory of Metaphor. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Mackin, R. (1978). ‘On collocations: “words shall be known by the company they keep” ’. In: Strevens, P. D. (ed.), In Honour of A. S. Hornby. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 149–65. Mackridge, P. (1987). The Modern Greek Language: a Descriptive Analysis of Standard Modern Greek. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Magnusson, U. and Persson, G. (1986). Facets, Phases and Foci: Studies in Lexical Relations in English. Umeå: Almqvist & Wiksell. Makkai, A. (1972). Idiom Structure in English. The Hague: Mouton. Marchand, H. (1969). The Categories and Types of Present-day English Word-Formation, 2nd edition (1st edition: 1960). Munich: C. H. Beck. Matthews, P. H. (1979). Generative Grammar and Linguistic Competence. London: Allen and Unwin. Matthews, P. H. (1981). Syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Matthews, P. H. (1993). ‘Central concepts of syntax’. In: Jacobs, J., von Stechow, A., Sternefeld, W. and Vennemann, T. (eds), Syntax: an International Handbook of Contemporary Research. Berlin: de Gruyter, 89–117. McIntosh, A. (1961). ‘Patterns and ranges’. Language 37, 325–37. Mel’cˇuk, I. (1982). ‘Lexical functions in lexicographic description’. In: McCawley, M., Gensler-Orin, D., Brugman, C., Civkutis, I., Dahlstrom, A., Krile, K. and Sturm, R., Proceedings of the 8th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society. Berkeley: UCB, 427–444. Mel’cˇuk, I. (1988). ‘Semantic description of lexical units in an explanatory combinatorial dictionary’. International Journal of Lexicography 1, 165–88. Mel’cˇuk, I. (1992). ‘Changer et changement en français contemporain (étude sémanticolexicographique)’. Bulletin de la Société de Linguistique de Paris 87, 161–223. Mel’cˇuk, I. (1993). ‘La phraséologie et son rôle dans l’enseignement/apprentissage d’une langue étrangère’. Études de linguistique appliquée 92, 82–113. Mel’cˇuk, I. (1998). ‘Collocations and lexical functions’. In: Cowie, A. P. (ed.), Phraseology: Theory, Analysis and Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 23–53. Mel’cˇuk, I. et al. (1984, 1988, 1992). Dictionnaire explicatif et combinatoire du fançais contemporain: recherches lexico-sémantiques I, II, III. Montreal: Presses de l’Université de Montréal. Michaelis, L. A. and Lamprecht, K. (1996). ‘Toward a construction-based theory of language function: the case of nominal extraposition’. Language 72, 215–47. Mitchell, T. F. (1975). ‘Syntax (and associated matters)’. In: Bolton, W. F. (ed.), The English Language (= Sphere History of Literature in the English Language, vol. 10). London: Sphere Books, 135–213. Mitchell, T. F. (1979). ‘The English appearance of aspect’. In: Allerton, D. J., Carney, E. and Holdcroft, D. (eds), Function and Context in Linguistic Analysis: a Festschrift for William Haas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 159–84. Miyamoto, T. (1999). The Light Verb Construction in Japanese: the Role of the Verbal Noun. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
290 Bibliography Moon, R. (1998). ‘Frequencies and forms of phrasal lexemes in English’. In: Cowie, A. P. (ed.), Phraseology: Theory, Analysis and Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 79–100. Mustajoki, A. (2000). ‘Functional syntax as a basis for contrastive analysis’. Paper given to the “Linguistikkreis” of the University of Basle, 11 April, 2000. Nagy, W. (1978). ‘Some non-idiom larger-than-word units in the lexicon’. Papers from the Parasession on the Lexicon. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society, 289–300. Nattinger, J. R. and DeCarrico, J. S. (1992). Lexical Phrases and Language Teaching. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Newman, J. (1996). Give: a Cognitive Linguistic Study. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter. Nickel, G. (1968). ‘Complex verbal structures in English’. IRAL 6, 1–21. Obler, L. K. and Gjerlow, K. (1999). Language and the Brain. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. Ogden, C. K. (1968). Basic English: International Second Language, revision prepared by E. C. Graham. New York: Harcourt Brace. Olsson, Y. (1961). On the Syntax of the English Verb (Gothenburg Studies in English 12). Gothenburg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgensis. Palm, C. (1995). Phraseologie: eine Einführung. Tübingen: Gunter Narr. Palmer, F. R. (1965). A Linguistic Study of the English Verb. London: Longman. Palmer, F. R. (1974). The English Verb. London: Longman. Paradis, C. (1997). Degree Modifiers of Adjectives in Spoken British English. Lund: Lund University Press. Pawley, A. and Syder, F. H. (1983). ‘Two puzzles for linguistic theory: nativelike selection and nativelike fluency’. In: Richards, J. C. and Schmidt, R. W. (eds), Language and Communication. London: Longman, 191–226. von Polenz, P. (1985). Deutsche Satzsemantik, Grundbegriffe des Zwischen-den-Zeilen-Lesens. Berlin: de Gruyter. Pottier, B. (1972). Introduction à l’étude linguistique de l’espagnol. Paris: Hispanoamericanes. Poutsma, H. (1904–26). A Grammar of Late Modern English. Groningen: Noordhoff. Quirk, R. (1995). Grammatical and Lexical Variance in English. London: Longman. Quirk, R., Greenbaum, S., Leech, G. and Svartvik, R. (1972). A Grammar of Contemporary English. London: Longman. Quirk, R., Greenbaum, S., Leech, G. and Svartvik, J. (1985). A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language. London: Longman. Radford, A. (1988). Transformational Grammar: a First Course. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Radford, A. (1997). Syntax: a Minimalist Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rensky´, M. (1964). ‘English verbo-nominal phrases: some structural and stylistic aspects’. Travaux Linguistiques de Prague 1, 289–99. Roos, E. (1989). ‘Idioms’. In: Dirven, R. and Putseys, Y. A User’s Grammar of English: Word, Sentence, Text, Interaction, Part A. Frankfurt-am-Main: Lang, 215–41. Rosch, E. (1977). ‘Human categorization’. In: Warren, N. (ed.), Advances in CrossCultural Psychology, vol. 1. London: Academic Press. Rosch, E. (1978). ‘Principles of categorization’. In: Rosch, E. and Lloyd, B. B. (eds) Cognition and Categorization. Hillsdale; New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum, 27–48. Rose, J. H. (1978). ‘Types of idioms’. Linguistics 203, 55–62.
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Bibliography 291 Ruhl, C. (1989). On Monosemy: a Study in Linguistic Semantics. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press. Schenk, A. (1994). Idioms and Collocations in Compositional Grammars. Utrecht: Research Institute for Language and Speech. Scurfield, E. (1991). Chinese. London: Hodder and Stoughton. Siller-Runggaldier, H. (1996). Das Objektoid: eine neue syntaktisch-funktionale kategorie, aufgezeigt anhand des italienischen. Wilhelmsfeld: Gottfried Egert. Simatos, I. (1997). ‘Référence et argumentalité du GN dans les locutions verbales’. In: Fiala, P., Lafon, P. and Piguet, M.-F. La locution: entre lexique, syntexe et pragmatique, identification en corpus, traitement, apprentissage. (Publication di l’INALF, collection ‘Saint Cloud’). Paris: Klincksieck, 77–102. Sinclair, J. McH. (1966). ‘Beginning the study of lexis’. In: Bazell, C. E., Catford, J. C., Halliday, M. A. K. and Robins, R. H. In Memory of J. R. Firth. London: Longman, 410–30. Sinclair, J. McH. (ed.) (1987). Collins COBUILD English Language Dictionary. London: Collins. Sinclair, J. McH. (1991). Corpus, Concordance, Collocation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Snell, R. and Weightman, S. (1989). Teach Yourself Hindi. London: Hodder and Stoughton. Sommerfeldt, K.-E. and Schreiber, H. (1996). Wörterbuch der Valenz etymologisch verwandter Wörter: Verben, Adjektive, Substantive. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Stein, G. (1991). ‘The phrasal verb type “to have a look” in Modern English’. IRAL 29, 1–29. Stock, O., Slack, J. and Ortony A. (1993). ‘Building castles in the air: some computational and theoretical issues in idiom comprehension’. In: Cacciari, C. and Tabossi, P. (eds), Idioms: Processing Structure and Interpretation. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Erlbaum, 229–47. Strevens, P. D. (ed.) (1978). In Honour of A. S. Hornby. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stubbs, M. (1995). ‘Collocations and semantic profiles: on the cause of the trouble with quantitive studies’. Functions of Language 2, 23–55. Stubbs, M. (1996). ‘ “Eine Sprache idiomatisch sprechen”: Computer, Korpora, kommunikative Kompetenz und Kultur’. In: Mattheier, K. (ed.), Norm und Variation. Bern/Frankfurt: Lang, 151–67. Stubbs, M. (1998). ‘A note on phraseological tendencies in the core vocabulary of English’. Studia Anglica Posnaniensia 33, 399–410. Svartvik, J. (1992). Directions in Corpus Linguistics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Svensson, P. (1998). Number and Countability in English Nouns. Umeå: Umeå University. Tannen, D. (1989). Talking Voices: Repetition, Dialogues and Imagery in Conversational Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tesnière, L. (1959). Éléments de syntaxe structurale. Paris: Klincksieck. Trnka, B. (1928). ‘Analysis and synthesis in English’. English Studies 10, 138–44. Tschichold, C. (1996). ‘English Multi-Word Units (= MWUs) in a lexicon for natural language processing’. Basle: Doktorarbeit der Universität Basel. Tutin, A. (1997). ‘Codage des constructions à verbe support pour un lexique de TALN’. Actes de TALN ’97 (Grenoble). Ungerer, F. and Schmid, H.-J. (1996). An Introduction to Cognitive Linguistics. London: Longman. Vendler, Z. (1967). ‘Verbs and times’. In: Vendler, Z. Linguistics in Philosophy. New York: Cornell University Press, 97–121.
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
292 Bibliography Vogel, P. M. (1996). Wortarten und Wortartenwechsel: zu Konversion und verwandten Erscheinungen im Deutschen und in anderen Sprachen. Berlin: de Gruyter. Welte, W. (1990). Englische Phraseologie und Idiomatik. Frankfurt/Berne: Lang. Wierzbicka, A. (1982). ‘Why you can have a drink when you can’t *have an eat’. Language 58, 753–99. Wood, R. T. and Hill, R. J. (1979). The Macmillan Dictionary of English Colloquial Idioms. London: Macmillan. Zhang, L. (1995). A Contrastive Study of Aspectuality in German, English and Chinese. New York: Lang.
11
Index
11
11
111
111
111
111
Aarts 30 Abney 124 Abrahamsen 8 absolutive adjective 163 abstract noun 65 achievements 200 actional meaning 74 active (voice) 10, 11, 38 active meaning 192 activities 203 adjectival descriptor 119 adjective 13, 24, 25 adjective meaning 59 adjective-based stretched verb structure 23 adjectives in -ed/-en 161 adverb-based stretched verb structure 23 adverbial 45, 126, 141 adverbial elaborator 45 affirmative 10 affixation 113 -age 116 agentive adjective 32, 113, 163 agentive noun 23, 25, 32, 59, 227 agentive-eventive meaning 136 agentive-eventive noun 146 Akimoto 5 Aktionsart 234 -al 116 Algeo 5 Allerton 7, 17, 27, 36, 38, 39, 42, 43, 46, 102, 113, 124, 125, 139, 141, 172, 219, 221, 235, 243 alliteration 219, 232 ambiguity 116, 226
analysability 221 analysability, semantic 218 -ance/-ence 113, 117 Arabic 241 arbitrariness 6 Aronstein 5 article, definite 125 article, indefinite 53, 125, 229 Ashton 202 aspect 115, 224 aspect adjective 140, 141 -ation/-ition/-ution 117 attributive 14 auxiliary verb 7, 125 back-formation 238 Barkema 217 base 219 Basic English (Ogden) 238 BBI dictionary 32, 219, 246, 248 Bechtel 8 behaviourism 30 Benson 8, 219, 246 binomial 216 Björkman 5, 223, 240 BNC 32 Bolinger 232 Brinton 5 Brown corpus 32 Brownell 243 Burger 216 Cameron 32 case 39 catenative pattern 233 causative voice 194
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
294 Index causativity 195, 196 Chinese 241 Chomsky 8, 9, 125 classifier 125 clause 46 clefting 12, 17, 42, 121, 223 cognate object 232 cohesion 102 collocant 219 collocation 7, 11, 28, 30, 54, 172, 191, 196, 215, 217, 245 collocational restrictions 139, 210 common noun 125 complement 41 complementation 4, 25 complex sentence 17 composite predicate 5 compound 218 compounding 113 concord 39 concrete nouns 178 connectionist approach 8 Construction Grammar 8 context 30 continuations 201 conversion 4 cooccurrence restrictions 11, 22, 221 coordination 219 copular verb 26, 27, 43, 54, 59, 66, 159, 228, 229 corpora 30 corpus-based approach 30 Cortès 240 Cottrell 8 countability 207 countable noun 119, 125, 127, 136, 231 coups 200, 203 Cowie 246 Cruse 3 Cruttenden 139 Culicover 124 culminations 201, 203 DeCarrico 5 definite genitive NP 134 demotion 108 derivation 4, 113, 159, 197 derivational suffix 118
descriptor 23, 28, 39, 42, 59, 63, 66, 69, 161, 228 determiner 6, 124, 136, 224 determiner phrase 124 deverbal noun 8, 75, 102, 113, 115, 121, 178, 216 deviance 220 dictionary 8, 31, 36, 221, 245 dictionary, electronic 248 direct object see object Dirven 216 discourse 220 do-constructions 231 Dowty 200, 201 Dras 7 Dubois 239 duration 198 duration adverb 144 duration adverbial 199 dynamic meaning 24, 29 Egg 199, 200 elaborated verb structure 4, 20, 22, 24, 59 elaboration 4 elaborator 47, 49, 52, 54, 100, 105 elicitation tests 31 ellipsis 52 end-focus 102 Engelen 5 epithet 216 errors 26, 30, 243 eventive adjective 54 eventive meaning 99, 109, 118 eventive noun 20, 26, 32, 52, 66, 100, 127, 171, 217 eventive object 105 eventive verb 21, 29, 66, 69, 77 eventuality 198, 199, 201, 203, 205, 209 exemplification 219 exertion 202, 206 expanded predicate 5 expectation 208 experiencer 27, 193 extent adjective 143 factual status adjective 144 Fillmore 8, 23
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Index 295 finite clause 46 finite complement 47 Firth 30 fixed expression 216 flexibility 224 formal style 29, 227 formula 217 François 240 Fraser 223 French 7, 194, 202, 239 frequency 172, 186 frequency adverb 144 frequency adverbial 142 frequency of stretched verb constructions 31 fronting 40, 165 function words 170 functional categories 49 Funktionsverbgefüge 5, 216 Garman 244 generative grammar 8 genitival qualifier 47 genitive qualifier 102 German 5, 6, 24, 25, 202, 239, 248 gerund 118 gerund complement 47 gerund structure 46 Gjerlow 243 Goldberg 8, 17 gradability 139 gradable adjective 163 grammatical restructuring 102 Grass 240 Greek 240 Greenbaum 31 Gutiérrez 240 Haas 3, 9 hackneyed phrase 220 Halliday 30, 41, 243 happenings 199, 200 Harris 9, 10, 11, 12, 13 have-constructions 229, 231 head 23 Heringer 5, 239 heteronymy 3 Hill 246 Hindi 241
homonymy 174, 218, 226 hyponymy 115 -ia 118 idiom 5, 16, 174, 215, 243 idiomaticity 239 inanimate subject 179 inception 200, 205 inceptive meaning 75, 157, 182 inchoative meaning 75 incorporation 101 incubus 151 indirect object 76, 77, 100, 104, 251 indirect objoid 44 infinitive complement 47 infinitive structure 46 inflection 197 informal style 29, 227, 231, 233 -ing 118 inherence 140 intensifier 141, 163 intensity 209 interference 24 intergressives 199 intransitive verb 70, 100, 104 introspection 31 intuition 26 intuition-based approach 30 -ion 117, 135 -is 118 Italian 240 -ity 118 Jackendoff 125 Japanese 241 Jespersen 5, 7, 42 Johnson 7 Keller 5 key word 7 kindred relation 13, 17 Kirchner 5 Kjellmer 31 Koya 27 Kruisinga 5 Lambton 241 Leech 30 Lewis 194, 241
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
296 Index lexical function 7, 22, 217 lexical gap 25 lexical irregularity 219 lexical item 36, 197 lexical passivization 101, 251 lexical phrase 5 lexical selectivity 219 lexical verb 7, 24, 28, 100 lexicalist approach 8 lexicon 4, 7, 16, 17, 172, 215, 226, 244 light verb 7 limiter adverb 102, 103 LOB corpus 32, 173, 186 location 120 locution verbale 5 Lyons 197 Mackridge 240 Magnusson 115 Makkai 215, 223 manner adverb 143 manner adverbial 119 Marchand 113, 116, 117, 118, 119, 120 mass noun 125, 127, 207 master word 219 Matthews 17 meaning differences 6, 9, 15, 20 meaning of thin verbs 172 Mel’cˇuk 7, 22, 217, 243 -ment 117, 135 metaphor 27, 215, 243 method adverb 142 Michaelis 8 Mitchell 30, 203 Miyamoto 241 modal verbs 125 Moon 217 morphology 16, 198 native speaker 26, 31, 32, 246 Nattinger 5 negative 10, 188 New Collins Concise Dictionary 32 nomen actionis 115 nomen agentis 136 nominal paraphrase 5 nominalization 66, 101, 106, 223
noun-based stretched verb structure 23 number of stretched verb constructions 31, 32, 170 numeral 125 object 6, 8, 23, 27, 39 object position 35, 77 objoid 23, 43, 99, 102 Obler 243 obligatoriness 39, 49, 108 oblique form 39 oblique object 44 obsolete verbs 235 Ogden 238, 241 omission 49 optionality 49, 106, 108, 109, 127 overrepresented verbs in stretched verb constructions 174 Palm 216 Palmer 233 particle 225 partitive construction 29 passive (voice) 10, 11, 38, 45, 121 passive meaning 69, 156, 190, 192, 229 passivization 17, 36, 66, 100, 101, 105, 110, 154, 223 see also lexical passivization patient 164, 203 performance 26, 30 periphrasis 197, 203 perject 36, 106 Persian 241 persisting effect 209 Persson 115 phase 197 phrasal verb 5, 45, 76, 102, 110, 215, 225, 233 phrase lexicon 244 phraseme 217 phraseology 16, 215, 216 place adverb 144 place adverbial 27 plesionymy 3 polarity 209 polysemy 17, 113, 118, 174, 186, 218, 226 possessive 134, 151, 177
11
11
11
111
111
111
111
Index 297 potentiality 208 Pottier 240 Poutsma 5 Prague school 5 predication 115 predicative 14, 25, 26, 29, 39, 42, 54, 120, 161 prefixation 4 preposition 25, 26 preposition phrase 45 prepositional object 225 prepositional objoid 37, 59, 66, 69, 74, 75, 102, 104, 107, 108, 119, 148, 154, 225 prepositional qualifier 47, 69, 104 prepositional verb 70 process 199 processes 203 productivity 17, 26 progressive 205, 206 pronominalization 11 proper noun 125 proverb 216, 220, 232 pseudo-idiom 216 qualifier 66, 101 quality adjective 141, 142, 161 Quirk 7, 22, 24, 31, 41, 102, 125, 139, 140, 161 quotation 216 Radford 223 range adjective 140, 141 rare verbs 23 see also thin verb, unique reciprocal verb 52 relative clause 100 restrictor 145 Roos 216 Ruhl 174 Russian 240 scalar adjective 163 scalar modification 164 Scurfield 241 semantic contribution 7 semantic feature 127, 195, 209, 233 semantic role 6, 100, 101, 105, 106, 109, 148, 151, 164, 193 semantic selection 173
sensory verb 119 sentence adverb 144 sentence adverbial 142, 145 servant word 219 Simatos 240 simile 216, 219 simplex elaborated verb structure 24 simplex verb construction 20 Sinclair 30 slogan 216 Snell 241 social disapproval 209 solo eventive noun 134 solo noun 126, 207 Spanish 240 speech-act ·184, 194, 216, 220 static meaning 29 stative meaning 24, 196 Stein 5, 7 Stock 244 stratificational grammar 215 strokes 200, 203 Structure 0 22, 23, 24, 25, 28, 29, 48 Structure 1 24, 25, 26, 27, 48, 54, 58, 59, 62, 63, 106, 113, 159, 161, 164, 176, 182, 226, 227, 228, 240, 250 Structure 2 23, 25, 26, 27, 48, 59, 62, 113, 121, 136, 146, 157, 175, 227, 240, 250 Structure 3 26, 27, 48, 63, 64, 65, 66, 68, 69, 106, 176, 228, 250 Structure 4 27, 28, 48, 66, 68, 70, 73, 75, 106, 107, 155, 156, 157, 176, 228, 240, 250 Structure 5 29, 48, 70, 74, 75, 76, 99, 106, 107, 108, 156, 169, 177, 229, 239, 240, 251 Structure 6 23, 29, 31, 35, 48, 77, 99, 100, 101, 102, 103, 106, 107, 155, 169, 229, 240, 251, 252 style see informal/formal style subject 6, 14, 39, 65, 225, 227 subject adjunct adverbial 142 subject complement 120 success with difficulty 209 suffix 16, 26, 157 suffixation 4, 113 support verb 7
1
1
1
11
11
11
11
298 Index Swahili 202, 241 synonymy 3, 15 syntax 17, 24 telic adjective 163 telic modification 164 tense 224 terminations 200 textual contribution 221 that-clause 46 thematic status 107 theme-rheme 243 thin verb 7, 217 neutral 196 unique 172 thin verbs add 191, 207 arouse 207, 229 arrive at 207 assume 207 attract 196 be 174–6, 207 bring (in) 207 bring about 196, 207 burst into 207 carry out 229 cause 186, 193, 194, 196, 229 come 176–7, 229 come in for 194 come to 207 commit 194, 229 conduct 207 dance 191 deliver 207 do 177–8, 207, 229 drive home 191, 207 effect 207 elicit 196 engage in 207 feel 186, 193, 194, 207, 229 fill 229 find 187, 194, 207, 229 form 187, 207, 229 gain 195, 229 get 178–9, 194, 229 give 179–81, 189, 192, 194, 229 go 181–2, 229 go into 207 grant 188, 194, 207, 229
have 182–3, 196, 207, 224, 229 hurl 194 incur 194 induce 207 indulge (in) 207, 229 inflict 193 initiate 207 inspire 196, 207 launch 191, 207 lodge 191 make 183–4, 192, 194, 229 meet 229 meet with 194 minister 191 mount 207 move 229 obtain 207 offer 188, 208, 229 perform 207, 229 practise 207 precipitate 196, 207 present 207, 229 press home 207 promote 207 provide 188, 207, 229 provoke 196 put in 229 put on 191, 207 reach 207 receive 189, 192, 194, 229 record 207 refuse 210 render 207, 229 secure 194, 207, 229 shout 194 spark off 196, 207 spring into 207 stimulate 196, 207 strike up 207 subject 207 suffer 189, 193, 194, 207, 229 take 184–6, 229 undergo 190, 192, 194, 229 withdraw 210 work out 207, 229 time adverbial 142, 200 -tion 117 transformation 8, 9, 10, 12, 13, 17, 35, 43, 105, 121, 223
11
11
Index 299 transitive verb 99 translation 24 treatments 203 Trnka 5 Turkish 194, 241 Tutin 7 uncountable noun 119 underrepresented verbs in stretched verb constructions 174 ungradable adjective 163 unique morpheme 235 -ure 118
111
111
111
Weightman 241 Welte 215 Wierzbicka 7, 229, 230, 231 Wood 246 word formation 4, 8, 16, 135, 235 X-bar theory 125 -y 118
11
111
valency requirement 45 Vendler 200, 201 verb meaning 6, 48 verbo-nominal phrase 5
valency 22, 25, 26, 27, 36, 38, 48, 74, 77, 119, 141, 169, 172, 187, 239
zero derivation 27, 118, 135, 231 Zhang 205