1 Introduction and Background
My puipose in writing this book is to examine of the origins and impact of the agreement ...
30 downloads
955 Views
16MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
1 Introduction and Background
My puipose in writing this book is to examine of the origins and impact of the agreement on trade-related aspects of intellectual property rights (TRIPS) negotiated during the Uruguay Round of talks of the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT). The principle theme of the book is that the TRIPS agreement is not in the best social welfare interest of the poor countries and that its effective imposition on them by the rich countries has far more to do with the exercise of real political and economic power than it does with the positive economic benefits the agreement's Supporters claim it can deliver. To support this assertion, I provide a critical examination of the theoretical literature and empirical evidence as they pertain to the impact of intellectual property rights (IPRs) on such important economic variables as export performance, foreign investment, and economic Igrowth. This examination demonstrates the overall weakness of the positivist economic case in favor of a strong international IPR regime, at least as it applies to the poor countries.1 The book then proceeds to provide a political and economic analysis that explains why the poor countries acceded to the TRIPS agreement notwithstanding the lack of positivist economic evidence in favor of its benefits. The analysis here is driven by a theory of the state in the global system which is itself the product of a method I choose to describe as "critical eclecticism." By this term I mean that the approach to state theory I adopt is inspired by several well-established traditions in radical;political economy and international relations theory that speak to, or carry implications for, the relations between the state and civil society. The constituent approaches are (1) world systems theory, (2) Gramscian hegemony, and (3) internationalization of capital. My method is critical in two senses of the word. First, it is critical in the same sense that these constituent traditions are critical. That is, it calls into question the dominant institutional infrastructure by which the global system is administered, and it advocates fundamental reforms to benefit the world's marginalized majority. Second, it is critical in the sense that it does not attempt to include or reconcile all aspects of each of the three component radical research traditions. It recognizes that each tradition has differences of emphasis and strength and draws on these as they advance the analysis at
4
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
hand. I do argue that the three approaches are in fact mutually consistent at a fundamental level. I do not pretend to settle old debates among and between the schools that have often taken on a polemical character in the past. Having advanced the general political and economic analysis of the TRIPS agreement, the book then proceeds to illustrate with a pair of case studies of two important industries where the struggle over IP is especially strongly waged. These are the pharmaceutical and agricultural biotechnology sectors. In each of these cases, an attempt is made to specify the IPR issues and demonstrate how the TRIPS agreement operates to define and extend capitalist social relations of production on a global scale. It does this in part, I argue, by operating as a mechanism of (Gramscian) consensual hegemony. At the same time, it is recognized that ideological struggle is not strictly determined and that the door is open for counterhegemonic efforts. These cases reveal the conditions under which counterhegemony is more likely to succeed. TRIPS is a relatively recent phenomenon and the literature devoted to its analysis is still relatively undeveloped. Most of the work that has been done in this area by scholars from the developed countries tends to promote the benefits of a strong international IPR regime. I know of no work in this area that approaches the general case of the TRIPS agreement from a radical perspective of political and economic international relations of the type I develop here. Later in this chapter I review some of the recent related literature and show how my own contribution extends, improves on, and/or corrects this work. The TRIPS Agreement in Basic Outline The TRIPS agreement is not a sui generis system for the international protection of intellectual property rights. It traces its historical and juridical roots to several earlier international agreements, two of which date back to the nineteenth century. The Paris Convention for the Protection of Industrial Property of 1883 and the Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works of 1886 were precursors of the TRIPS agreement. The Paris agreement required signatory nations to provide national treatment for foreign innovations in the areas of patents, trademarks, industrial designs, appellations of origin, and utility models, while the Berne Convention did the same for copyrights. National treatment, however, does not require nations to provide any particular standard of protection. It merely requires that whatever level is provided to domestic works also be provided to foreign works. Essentially, then, the Paris and Berne conventions amount to nondiscrimination agreements in the area of IPRs rather than agreements that establish
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND 5
minimum standards. Nonetheless, the two conventions were not universally embraced: some countries chose not to becomie signatories in the belief that the agreements represented constraints on the countries' abilities to reap the benefits of technological transfer and development.2 In 1893 the Paris and Berne conventions were merged into a single secretariat to be administered by the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)(Ryan 1998, p. 126). WIPO subsequently becameapart of the United Nations system in 1974. Its mission is to help nations develop multilateral norms governing IP, help nations develop national legislation, and facilitate the negotiation of international treaties. As Ryjan notes, however, WIPO operated under the same constraints as its predecessor agreements. That is, while some members of WIPO attempted to| press for effective minimum standards for IP protection, there was within the organization considerable resistance to these attempts as well. Neither was WIPO endowed with an effective mechanism to enable it to enforce what minimum provisions its membership was able to agree to. The inadequacies of WIPO can fairly be identified as the inspiration motivating the movement to establish the TRIPS agreement as part of the multilateral trade negotiating system and institutional framework. The demonstrated effectiveness of the latter in liberalizing trade, its effectiveness in enforcing its various provisions, and its ability to settle disputes, or at least limit their negative fallout, made the GATT/World Trade Organization (WTO) an obvious choice for those who advocated a strengthening of the international IPR regime. The basic function of the TRIPS agreement is to establish and enforce minimum international standards for the protection of intellectual property. As such, it does not literally seek to bring about the international harmonization of IPRs inasmuch as nations are free to adopt national IPR regimes that provide more extensive protection than that called for by the agreement. It does require that nations adhere to the main provisions of the Paris and Berne conventions while calling for nothing that derogates nations' obligations to one another under those agreements. Thus, for example, the basic principles of national treatment and most favored nation are strongly enshrined in the TRIPS agreement.3 | Beyond this, as noted, the TRIPS agreement stipulates that certain minimum requirements for IP protection be met by the WTO nations. In the area of copyright, works are afforded a period of exclusionary protection equal to fifty years after the life of the author, and copyright protection is extended beyond printed matter to include sound and video recordings (Articles 12 and 14). Copyright protection is also provided to computer software programs as well as to compilations of data that represent a necessary degree of intellectual creativity.4 Minimum patent protection is established at twenty
6
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
7
years and is extended by the prohibition of patent discrimination based on the place of invention, field of technology, or whether products are imported or locally produced (Article 27.1). Industrial designs are given similar protection for periods of at least ten years (Article 26.1). Article 18 allows for the registration of trademarks for periods of seven years that are indefinitely renewable, while Article 16 grants exclusive right of use of a registered trademark. Geographical indications are protected by Articles 22 and 23. There are also some especially notable exceptions to the protections offered by the TRIPS agreement. Where patents are concerned, exceptions apply to living organisms developed by traditional methods. Compulsory licensing of patented products or processes is not allowed except in cases of national emergency. Transitional arrangements are allowed to enable poorer countries to update their legislation and establish the necessary administrative machinery to apply and enforce the law. Five years' grace is granted to less developed and transition countries with an additional five years for the poorest of these. All countries are expected to be compliant by 2005.
were especially prominent. Opposing the agreement were many middle and less developed countries, particularly India imd Brazil, which seek to nurture incipient knowledge-intensive industries of their own. Predictably, the scholarly literature is also represented by voices that stand in support of the agreement, however qualified in some instancesjand those that are opposed to it. I shall state at the outset my own view that the TRIPS agreement is not in the best interests of the poor countries of the \yorld. More accurately, I do not believe it to be in the best material interests of the poor majorities who live and work in these countries. Neither is it cle|ar that the agreement operates in the best interests of workers and consumers in general. A major task of this book is to explicate the reasons for such skepticism. A second major task is to provide an ex post facto explanation for the accession to the agreement by those very same poor countries. This explanation, I argue, must properly be conducted in political economic terms—a type of analysis I shall define in due course. Before delving into these and other related questions, however, a consideration of the relevant academic context is in order.
Recent Literature
Mainstream Economics Justifications of the TRIPS Agreement
There have been a number of recent book-length publications (monographs and collected editions) devoted to the internationalization of intellectual property rights. In this brief review, I shall call attention to the strengths and weaknesses of a representative sample of these works in a manner that I hope makes clear the need for a political economic analysis of the type that I propose of the prevailing IPR regime. Some of the recent works are supportive of the prevailing IPR system, albeit with qualifications, while others are highly critical. Some of the recent scholarship may be considered, at least as I understand the concept, political economic in character while other works focus on the sociological, philosophical, or juridical aspects of IPRs. In drawing attention to these distinctions, I do not wish to denigrate the valuable contributions made by authors who write from a disciplinary emphasis that differs from my own. I wish only to convince the reader that a space exists that my own contribution seeks to fill. It will also be clear that I disagree with several of the general perspectives as well as the particular interpretations of the salient issues offered by the authors I review. This should come as no surprise to those even distantly familiar with the nature of intellectual property discussions.
Standard economics justifications for intellectual property rights typically commence by recognizing that IPRs entail an inherent contradiction. On the one hand, welfare is maximized in a competitive economy by the free and complete availability of information. On the other hand, the production of knowledge and knowledge-intensive goods requires, as does any production in a market-based economy, incentives. Such incentives will be lacking in a regime that does not provide some restrictions on the access to information. This contradiction has led many economists to pose the problem in terms of "optimal" IPRs. Primo Braga (1990), in an early survey of the literature cites seminal contributions by Arrow (1962), NorcJhaus (1969), and Scherer (1972) in his discussion of the optimal patent length, for example. Primo Braga recognizes that more recent theoretical developments, involving such dynamic considerations as the cost of patent races and the pace and reach of knowledge diffusion, call into question: these early results. His general conclusion, however, is that there is a greater danger of insufficient investment in research and development (R&D) in developing countries rather than overinvestment.
The negotiations leading up to the establishment of the TRIPS agreement were extremely contentious. Leading the effort to establish the TRIPS were the United States, several European countries, and Japan. In these efforts, the U.S.-based pharmaceutical, telecommunications, and computer companies
In a more recent World Bank discussion paper, Primo Braga and coauthors Fink and Paz Sepulveda (2000) provide an updated survey of the economic impact of IPRs in the post-TRIPS environment. These writers once again note the welfare ambiguity of IPRs, paying particular attention to the questions of knowledge production and diffusion. They make the argument
8
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
that while the short-term static impact of a strong IPR regime may well involve a welfare loss, owing to the exercise of monopoly power on the part of sellers of knowledge-based commodities and production processes, the longterm effects may be beneficial given the presence of additional, largely institutional, conditions. They note in particular the need for an effective competition policy that operates to ensure that the benefits of increased R&D expected to follow from a stronger regime are widely spread. The development of the "human resource base" of the poorer countries is seen as necessary to increasing these benefits, as are greater macroeconomic stability and more open trade and investment regimes (p. 48). Even more fundamental for Braga, Fink, and Paz Sepulveda is the necessity of promoting a pro-IPR consensus among the broad swath of national stakeholders. They write: A first step for a developing country reforming its IPR regime should be to support initiatives that promote consensus. It is important to bring together all affected parties—local "pirates," research-based companies, universities, consumer groups, government agencies, industrial property offices, IPRs lawyers, and others—to discuss what IPRs "do" and "don't do," while attempting to evaluate the economic impact of IPRs reforms. Such an exercise can provide useful input for the formulation of new laws and help in identifying adversely affected groups and in the design of appropriate compensatory mechanisms, (p. 47) This particular quotation raises a number of interesting issues. The first is the implicit admission that a fundamental task faced by proponents of a stronger IPR regime such as that embodied by the TRIPS agreement is to create a propitious ideological climate as a precondition for the success of such a regime. Apparently for these World Bank economists, the success of the TRIPS is primarily a problem of winning the confidence of those for whom the agreement can be expected to have potentially profound material consequences, even "local 'pirates."' What is especially peculiar about this advice is that it comes on the heels of the admission by the authors that the available theoretical and empirical evidence is unable to demonstrate conclusively the alleged benefits of the enhanced regime. The authors give not a moment's consideration to the possibility that strengthening the IPR regime might be the wrong thing to do for a poor country. Second, the authors make reference to "compensatory mechanisms" designed to reduce the burden of a stronger regime on those who are adversely affected. They refer in this case to the use of such options as parallel imports, compulsory licenses, and price controls as tools to be used to alter the distributional impacts of stricter control over intellectual property. These tools
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND 9
will be discussed in later chapters. The important questions to raise here are ones that the authors ignore altogether: What are the political economic conditions required for a country to successfully employ such measures and under what conditions will these measures be adequate to the country's developmental and distributional goals? Just as the establishment of the TRIPS agreement represented a struggle between Contending international as well as intranational interests, the continuing application and interpretation of the agreement can be expected to be no less contentious. The authors' emphasis on consensus thus appears naive at best and disingenuous at worst. Another recent work that takes an.essentially positive view of the TRIPS agreement is Keith Maskus's IntellectuaUProperty Rights in the Global Economy (2000). Like the other authors already cited, Maskus notes that IPRs have basically contradictory effects on! (at least) short-term welfare. He argues that the theoretical prediction of the outcome of a strengthening of the IPR regime depends on the particular assumptions invoked. In his review of the available empirical evidence, including his own work, however, Maskus finds much to recommend the agreement and argues that its long-term net benefits are likely to outweigh its short-term costs. In particular, Maskus is optimistic about the agreement's potential 1:0 promote for the poorer countries higher levels of international trade ard investment, foreign direct investment, and economic growth, each of which he believes is critical for promoting economic development. Once aj;ain, Maskus's optimism is contingent on the willingness and ability of th; developing country to adopt a wide range of additional market reforms. He notes especially the importance of policies to bring greater flexibility to the labor market, to promote and regulate industrial competition, and to promote free trade. Many of these policy suggestions will be recognizable to anyone familiar with the so-called Washington consensus of the 1990s. Given the similarities between Maskus's analysis and that of the authors discussed earlier, it should not come as a surprise to find that the former suffers from substantially the same shortcomings as the latter. Most prominently, Maskus, writing from a purely ieco'homic perspective, fails to give due recognition to the play of political forces and events. He pays little attention, for example, to the global political context in which the Uruguay Round of the GATT was conducted. While he recognizes in passing that the poorer nations faced considerable political pressure to assent to the TRIPS agreement, he does not examine the class-based origins or consequences of that pressure. Mainstream economists frequently justify their choice to minimize or marginalize political considerations in their analyses by suggesting that such considerations are outside of their disciplinary purview and more properly
10
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
require the attention of political scientists and/or international relations specialists. I would argue, however, that the tendency to consider apparently pure economic categories and evidence in isolation often results in a misinterpretation of that evidence. Take, for example, Maskus's data that show a correlation between strength of IPR regime and trade openness. Maskus interprets this correlation as a limited proof that a successful IPR regime must be accompanied by a liberal trading regime. But another interpretation is possible. Dependency theory might argue that strong IPR regimes together with a high degree of trade openness are typical of small nations and reflect dependency on external economic relationships and vulnerability to political pressure emanating from the more powerful countries. It is well known, for example, that certain former colonies of the nineteenth-century European powers adopted in wholesale fashion the strong IPR regimes of their colonizers. These former colonies also remain highly dependent on international trade, often with these same developed countries. Lacking a broader analytical framework, Maskus does not consider such a possibility. The TRIPS Agreement and International Law Standard economic interpretations of the TRIPS agreement, such as those discussed above, note the theoretical ambiguity of its likely impacts on the poorer countries yet still generally come down in favor of the agreement. The willingness to endorse the agreement may be driven by a belief in its historical inevitability and fueled by the expanding sense of market triumphaiism that characterized the close of the Uruguay Round. This same attitude of final victory, in fact, resides at the heart of the Washington consensus and defines the aggressive neoliberalism of the 1990s typical of NorthSouth economic relations.5 The suggestion that the TRIPS agreement is now an unavoidable part of the international political economic superstructure seems to be at the heart of Carlos M. Correa's recent analysis in his Intellectual Property Rights, the WTO and Developing Countries (2000). Correa is an Argentine lawyer who considers the likely impact of the agreement on the southern nations that remain largely technologically and economically dependent on the North. He regards the agreement as a form of "technological protectionism" imposed by the United States with the aim of consolidating an international division of labor under which northern countries generate innovations and southern countries constitute the market for the resulting products and services (p. 5). As I shall argue in later chapters, in my estimation this is not far off from an accurate description of the agreement's effective motivation. Correa goes on to discuss rather convincingly the limited potential impact of
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
11
the agreement in terms of its alleged long-term benefits. He suggests, for example, that DFI flows are not likely to bfe an important benefit inasmuch as IPRs are but one, and not the most important, determinant of these flows. Also, once IPRs reach a certain level of Harmonization among the southern economies, they cease being a basis of differentiation between them for potential foreign investors and are, therefore!, less relevant to DFI decisions (p. 30). Neither does Correa consider technology transfer from North to South as a necessary outcome of the TRIPS agreement. While the TRIPS may create the conditions for such a transfer, it may also operate to impair the ability of the southern economies to negotiate favorable terms. Given Correa's skepticism regarding the motivation and likely consequences of the agreement, one might expect him to advocate its outright renunciation by the South. Rather than choose this course, Correa instead suggests that the poorer countries seek ways to adopt the agreement in a fashion that will yield them benefits. He; asserts, "Despite the origins and main forces behind the TRIPS Agreement... this Agreement still contains elements that, duly applied, may permit a certain balance in its implementation" (p. 6). The main body of Correa's book then is devoted to a legal parsing of the agreement's sections and subsections in a search for language that will enable an interpretation of the TRIPS iiseful to southern interests. Correa supplements his legal analysis with suppo ting case law citations on relevant IPR disputes that judicial authorities, including those that adjudicate WTO dispute settlements procedures (DSP) hearings, presumably would find persuasive. Thus, Correa maintains that Articles 7 and 8 permit member countries to take into account their own public interests in devising and implementing IPR law. In the area of pater ;t law, less developed countries are free to define the concept of "invention" through their own national legislation or through administrative and judicial practice. There is no obligation under the TRIPS agreement to adhere to aiunique concept of "invention" nor to adhere to a definition inspired by the expansive approach that exists in a developed country such as the United States (p. 51). This flexibility would be especially relevant in devising IPR policies in evolving and incompletely settled areas of IP, such as living orgahisms and computer software. Correa notes that plant varieties may be! protected by a less demanding sui generis approach to IPRs that permit farmers and researchers greater rights than would a patent system of protection. More generally, he argues that less developed countries (LDCs) may choose interpretations of the TRIPS agreement as it bears on plant genetic resources consistent with recently struck international agreements supported by the United Nations, such as the International Undertaking (IU) and the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD), that seek to guarantee access tothese materials. He also argues that the
12
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
TRIPS agreement provides latitude with respect to the permissibility of parallel imports, compulsory licenses, and exclusions to IPRs based on a variety of national concerns considered to be of overriding importance—for example, public order or morality. To his credit, Correa does a much better job than Primo Braga, Fink, and Sepulveda in setting out the conditions under which such "compensatory mechanisms" might be applicable. Moreover, in general, he provides prospective opponents of the TRIPS with useful legal advice and guidelines for challenging the agreement on its own terms and in its own language. Ultimately, however, Correa's approach confronts several important limitations in both its analytical reach and its practical, political usefulness. The most important constraint faced by those who would adopt Correa's legalistic approach is that although the agreement is worded in a manner that allows a variety of competing and conflicting interpretations of many important issues, as a practical matter, such conflicts will be resolved within the WTO's disputes settlements procedures (DSP). Even nonlawyers know that judicial reviews are hardly ever simply a matter of equally capable and wellendowed parties submitting their claims to otherwise disinterested judges for dispassionate consideration and resolution. The settlement of conflicts in the real world depends on the technical expertise and other resources that the contending parties can bring to bear in presenting their respective cases. As Correa is well aware, however, one of the many inequalities that separate the North and South resides precisely in their respective capabilities to marshal legal, technical, and administrative resources in defense of their interests in national and international forums. Even on those occasions when poor countries do manage to win a favorable ruling in the WTO, it is an open question as to how effective or binding the judgment will be on the behavior of the richer country or corporate producers it represents. The GATTAVTO DSP operates by permitting compensatory retaliation toward countries that are found in violation of its provisions. Large developed countries can much more easily absorb such measures than can smaller, less developed ones. This has been historically true of normal trade disputes and we should expect it to be no less true of disputes involving IPRs. A country like the United States can be expected, then, to ignore DSP judgments rendered against it when they are not very costly and yet still take advantage of the mechanism to press its own complaints. Neither can we expect the United States to abandon its tendency to resort to unilateral pressures when the WTO does not work as efficaciously as it would like. Correa himself notes that the United States has recently imposed unilateral punishments against Argentina for alleged IPR violations although such unilateral actions stand in contradiction to the TRIPS agreement (p. 9). He also notes that the United States has aggressively employed other bilateral pressures to
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
13
convince other Latin American and Caribbean nations to make extra TRIPS concessions (p. 110). Finally, a limiting feature of Correa's legal approach is that it envisions nation-states acting on behalf of an imagined national interest. This is entirely understandable insofar as the TRIPS is in fact an agreement struck by nation-states. But it can hardly be realistically assumed that nations are homogeneous entities whose interests on IPRs and other matters can be univocally expressed. The TRIPS agreement!, however interpreted, provides no mechanism or agency for the expression of nonofficial perspectives. Even when these perspectives are expressed via the agency of nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), their impact on TRIPS deliberations must necessarily pass through the filter of the state. It is a shortcoming of Correa's book that it provides no discussion of how state institutions and policies mediate between domestic groups and classes and their international counterparts in the context of the IPR debate. As I shall demonstrate, this shortcoming is shared by a substantial portion of the recent literature in this area. The TRIPS and International Capital Duncan Matthews's Globalising Intellectucl Property Rights: The TRIPS Agreement (2002) is an authentically political ^conomy treatment of the TRIPS agreement. What makes it so is the author's concern to detail the origins of the agreement as arising from the pressure exerted on policy makers by corporate interests to include the issue of IPRs on the negotiating agenda of the GATT Uruguay Round. Moreover, unlike seme previous studies (i.e., Ryan 1998), Matthews demonstrates that these inte rests were not exclusively U.S.based, but instead included well-organized industrial groups in Europe and Japan. He argues in fact that had the Europeans and Japanese corporations not lobbied heavily in favor of including IPRs in the negotiations, the TRIPS agreement would never have been realized. The difference between U.S., on the one hand, and European and Japanese!corporate involvement, on the other, in promoting the agreement, according to Matthews, was more a matter of lobbying style than it was commitment to the objective of strengthening the global IPR regime. Whereas U.S. busiriess interests were able to operate in a very direct way to influence policy making by the United States Trade Representative (USTR), European- and Japanese-based companies needed to negotiate a more complicated and multilayered bureaucracy to influence policy. In the case of Europe, the problem of arriving at a consensus strategy for including IPRs in the negotiations was made more complicated by the emergence of the European Union. Matthews also provides a much needed corrective to the tendency to
14
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
view corporate, capitalist competitors as representing essentially national actors engaged in a global, competitive arena. He stresses instead the multinational character of the enterprises most likely to benefit from a strengthened global IPR regime. The role played by the global pharmaceutical industry is particularly salient in this regard. It is this same global, capitalist alliance that has also assumed major responsibility for seeing that the agreement is enforced. Matthews shows that the institutional mechanisms for the enforcement of the TRIPS, the WTO and WIPO, lack the oversight capabilities necessary for monitoring member-country compliance to its provisions. This function then is effectively relegated to private sector concerns who file complaints with the official regulatory bodies when they believe a violation has occurred. While the corporations themselves cannot play the role of plaintiff in WTO mediated disputes, they can, in Matthews's words, act as "the eyes and ears" of the developed country members in the disputes settlements procedures and in formulating legislation and administrative procedures (p. 4). The object of this regulatory activity is, of course, primarily the poorer, less developed countries. Matthews does a good job of describing the potential costs and benefits of the agreement and their likely uneven incidence on the populations of the LDCs. He recognizes that the TRIPS agreement is bound to generate sympathizers among those groups that are-able by virtue of training and connections to forge productive connections as input providers to the large transnational corporations who are the prime movers behind the agreement. These winners from the "talented class" will not be required to emigrate in order to advance their careers. Overall, however, according to the author, the results of the agreement will be to exacerbate the economic dependence of the poor countries on the developed world, which owns and controls the large share of the world's patents. The question of effective enforcement of the TRIPS agreement raises for Matthews interesting questions about its long-term viability.6 In particular, he is concerned about the ultimate cohesiveness of the international capitalist alliance required for its functioning. This cohesiveness is threatened by the fact that nation-states typically pursue multifaceted foreign policies that inevitably bring them into conflict. While these developed nation-states may be able to form a temporary alliance to bring into-existence a regulatory instrument that addresses a mutually felt need and general purpose, the actual functioning of the regime may well bring them into conflict with one another as well as with the LDCs. Moreover, national policies must address themselves to a wide range of national and international concerns—for example, international security or human rights—that in some circumstances dominate and conflict with those associated with IPRs and their administra-
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
15
tion. There can be no presumption that the developed nation-states will achieve the same unanimity of outlook in these other areas that they have in the area of IPRs. While these concerns of Matthews are logical, I do not agree that they constitute realistic obstacles to the future functioning of the TRIPS agreement. Moreover, I believe that Matthews's overestimation of their severity derives from the lack in his analysis ofia sufficiently articulated theory of the state in the global economy. Mattheivs seems at times to operate on the basis of an implicit instrumentalist theory of state power wherein corporate actors are able to manipulate, directly or indirectly via access to key officials, the policy-making apparatus.7 WJiile there is at times some truth to this perspective, it fails to account for the ability of the state at other times to resist or ignore particular corporate! interests in order to attend to the general conditions required by capitalism for its expansion and reproduction on a global scale. The TRIPS agreement is precisely a part of this sort of general condition, which in recent decades has been identified as global neoliberalism. Neoliberal reform should not be oversimplified as implying the wholesale retreat of the state. It should be understood rather as constituting the sorts of structural changes in the global economic system that provide the best conditions for general capitalist reproduction. Clearly, this commitment by the state may conflict at times with the demands of particular segments of capital, including those relating to intellectual property. It should not come as a surprise, then, when particular IPRs are not given priority of treatment by the state. A second criticism to make of Mattiews's analysis concerns his treatment of class relations, which results in some inconsistencies and confusion. At times, Matthews makes clear that the TRIPS agreement is the result of the lobbying efforts of a transnational capitalist class. At other times, he writes as if policy outcomes, including those related to the interpretation and enforcement of IPRs, were strictly a matter of contending struggles between domestic class fractions. Moreover, he seems to regard differences in national policy agendas as a potential deterrent to the long-term success of the agreement. I believe that a less j contradictory interpretation of the intraclass struggle over the TRIPS has more to do with the distinction that separates competitive from monopoly capital than it does with the national versus transnational origins of capital. The IPR debate is mostly a matter of the desire of monopoly capital to capture the firm-specific rents associated with knowledge-based outputs and processes. Certainly there are competitive firms as well as other domestic class fractions that will seek to challenge the terms and conditions under which commodified knowledge is traded in the marketplace. At times, this challenge is bound to be presented in
16
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
thoroughly nationalistic discursive forms and cultural appeals. Those who wish to contest the hegemony exercised by noncompetitive transnational firms, however, would do well to keep in mind that the desire of these firms for profit provides a better guide to their behavior than their imagined nationalistic allegiances. Ideology and Intellectual Property Rights In contrast to neorealist interpretations of IPR policy such as that provided by Matthews, it is interesting to consider the views of others who see the issue in terms of ideology. Susan Sell, for example, in her Power and Ideas: North-South Politics of Intellectual Property and Antitrust (1998), places ideology at the center of an analytical approach she describes as "interpretivist neoliberal theory." Interpretivism, according to Sell, emphasizes "the intersubjective dimensions of international politics and treats interests as endogenous" (pp. 11-12). It privileges the force of ideas as compared to the materialism Sell associates with the more established analytical traditions that dominate international relations theory (p. 22). Individual nation-states, according to the author, are "unit-level learners and actors" who define and redefine a negotiating agenda in the pursuit of national self-interest. She then describes the rise and decline of the negotiating positions of southern states relative to northern states in such areas as restrictive business practices, technology transfer, antitrust, and IPRs, paying particular attention to the post1970 period. Sell asserts that while northern states have managed to win the hearts and minds of southern states in some of these areas—for example, antitrust, they must still resort to coercion to enforce IPRs. Sell is optimistic, however, that southern unit-level actors (i.e., national governments) possess the capacity to learn from experiences, consider new ideas, and develop new negotiating positions. The ideological shift necessary for the success of the TRIPS agreement may be currently under way as nascent indigenous capitalist groups with an interest in strengthening local IPR regimes begin to emerge in some southern states. In this context, Sell cites several opportunities for collaboration between southern-based companies to work with northern-based corporations and business associations to develop the needed incentives (pp. 212-214). Sell's book, with its emphasis on the power of ideas, provides a welcome offset to the tendency of much international relations analysis to ignore the role played by ideology altogether. She seems, however, to set up a false dichotomy between explanations that appeal either to materialist factors or to ideological factors without giving due consideration to those that emphasize the interaction of such forces. Interestingly, she does allow for precisely
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND 17
this last possibility in her admission that Gramscian approaches provide this sort of interaction.8 She writes that Gramsbian approaches "take ideas seriously and stress the close relationship betvyeen power structures and ideas" (p. 12). She unreflectively rejects this option, however, on the grounds that Gramscian theories themselves privilege structural explanations over those that emphasize the autonomous influence; of ideas. Again she opts instead for an interpretivist position that allows for a greater role played by "voluntarism and choice" (p. 13). i The problem is that this "interpretivist' perspective is ultimately unconvincing. While it is easy to show that policies of nations undergo changes over time, the chances of these policies becoming effective in the long run clearly have a great deal to do with such matters as technology, economic crises, and other conjunctural (structural) events. Sell herself seems to realize this at several points in her argument where she demonstrates the importance of stmctural factors in shaping the "learning" experiences of both developed and developing nations during the 1970s and 1980s. The economic crisis of the 1980s, for example, forced the developing countries to abandon their demands for a code of conduct for the regulation of transnational corporation behavior that sought to advance the development goals of the poorer countries (p. 97). The flaw in Sell's own structural analysis is her insistence on treating nation-states as "unit-level actors." This reatment leaves the indefensible impression that nations are univocal and obscures the fact that they are composed of competing, often conflicting, classes and that classes themselves may be characterized by divisions. This fa lure to recognize class dynamics has important implications for Sell's analysis of the state and its policy-making apparatus. Rather than reify the state as a univocal, unit-level "learner," it makes much more historical sense to interpret it as an arena within which a (class-based) struggle for power takes plabe. By extension, then, it makes more sense to speak of regime change than of state learning to describe the shifts that characterize the redirections !of state exercise of power and policy making. Once again Sell herself does aigoqd job of illustrating precisely this point in her description of the conjunctural problems of external debt and economic crises that plagued many developing countries during the 1980s. On an ideological level, these problems had the result of replacing antidependency development policies with new ruling groups and elites who were more favorably inclined to a proinarket, neoliberal vision. The latter view, not coincidentally, was the one being espoused by the International Monetary Fund and the commercial bank establishment, upon whom these countries depended for relief. If this ideological transformation could be called "unit-level learning," it is a narrow and coerced type of learning indeed.
18
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
As noted earlier, Sell ultimately modifies her argument to admit that structural and material forces do act in concert with ideological ones. By way of conclusion she writes: Overall, this book presented proximate causes for particular changes in intellectual property and antitrust attitudes and policies. Perhaps this analysis could be made compatible with structural and instrumentalist/rationalist theories. The explanations presented here might well fit into a broader Gramscian analysis, (emphasis added, p. 229) I think that Sell is correct to describe her explanations as "proximate causes." This suggests that deeper, more fundamental forces are at work. I also believe that her qualified intimation that Gramscian analysis might have something significant to offer after all needs to be taken seriously. Unfortunately, she never pursues this line of investigation. A superior job of describing the interplay between power, ideas, and intellectual property is provided by Christopher May in his book A Global Political Economy of Intellectual Property Rights (2000). In this work, May is primarily interested in examining IP from the standpoint of its ideological or philosophical justification. He begins by considering IPRs from the perspective of two well-established philosophical traditions. The first of these, associated with the seventeenth-century British philosopher John Locke, is described by May as an instrumentalist justification on the grounds that the establishment of property is "instrumental" to the ends of promoting profitable human activities (p. 25). The second tradition, associated with the eighteenth-century German philosopher Georg Hegel, is called a "self-developmental" justification insofar as property enables individuals to establish and realize their full human personalities. May also considers a pragmatic, or economic, justification for IP that is based in the utilitarian tradition. He argues that most ideological justifications of IP involve some combination of these traditional philosophical defenses of property and property right. May recognizes that the philosophical justification of IP is necessarily conducted within a historically defined social structure. Such a structure is defined as a set of institutions and behavioral norms that are themselves the outcome of the exercise of power. May borrows from Susan Strange (1988) the useful notion of the "knowledge structure" to describe that portion of the social structure specifically concerned with defining the limits of "acceptable knowledge." The knowledge structure is one of several structures that govern the functioning of the international political economy. Others include the security, financial, and productive structures. These structures interact to produce material outcomes with definite distributional consequences. That
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND 19
is to say, the outcomes produced are in no way class-neutral. The exercise of class power determines both the content of die knowledge structure and how this and other structures condition the functioning of the international political economy.9 Strange and May's concept of the knowledge structure provides an effective means of overcoming the false dichotomy between ideological and structural forces posed by Sell. May argues that the knowledge structure interacts with other structures in a dialectical fashion to influence the course of develi
opment of the international economy over time (p. 39) and shows how this development encourages the conversion of knowledge into commodities. This conversion process he aptly terms the "newf enclosure" and notes that the TRIPS agreement is its most recent and effective instrument. Like several of the other works I have considered in this review (Matthews is the exception), May's analysis is constrained by its essentially nationalist perspective. For May, the TRIPS agreement appears as a victory for certain fractions of U.S. corporate capital, especially those firms in the pharmaceutical, entertainment, and informatics industries. This perspective, I believe, underestimates the degree to which the agreement advances the interests of a transnational capitalist class. The corporations served by the agreement, as Matthews demonstrates, are largely transnational ones which, while headquartered in particular geographical locations, seek to maximize profits on their global operations. The goal of profit maximization dominates considerations of national allegiance or identity. May also runs into problems in his treatment of the state and the exercise of state power. In fact, he never explicitly add -esses these questions but seems to operate implicitly on neorealist assumptions. This perspective and its limitations will be discussed in detail in Chapter 4. For now, it is sufficient to point out that neorealist theories posit the state as a collective maximizing agent seeking to advance a well-defined national interest. From this perspective, the TRIPS would be understood as ah agreement imposed by strong nations on weaker ones. The problem with subh an interpretation, once again, is that it offers a distorted understanding ofj a global economic system that has broken the bounds of national production and accumulation. I shall close this review with a few comments on a third book that looks at the question of intellectual property rights from a largely ideological perspective. In Shamans, Software, and Spleens: Law and the Construction of the Information Society (1996), James Boyle considers the issue of intellectual property largely from a legal standpoint. Unlike Carlos Correa's investigation considered earlier, however, Boyle is less interested in discussing the technical aspects of the law as it applies to an interpretation of the TRIPS than he is in understanding the ideological context within which our under-
20
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
standing of IP has emerged. To employ May's terminology, Boyle is interested in providing a description of how the knowledge structure as it applies to IP came to be constructed; "constructed" is Bolye's characterization and is typical of much "postmodern" analysis. At the base of this construction, says Boyle, is the image of the "romantic author." This concept refers to those individuals who are taken to be the original creators, or transformers, of knowledge and its applications and on whom property rights are conferred as an incentive or reward for their original contributions. Boyle believes, however, that the concept has been pushed too far: "I argue that this is a bad thing for reasons of both efficiency and justice; it leads us to have too many intellectual property rights, to confer them on the wrong people, and dramatically to undervalue the interests of both the sources of and the audiences for the information we commodify" (pp. x-xi). Boyle's work is dedicated to an examination of a variety of information issues that he describes as "puzzles." The legal concept of copyright is laden with contradictions concerning the reach of ownership rights. He asks, for example, why blackmail and insider trading are illegal. Such practices, after all, involve the use of information to advance a position of market advantage, just as do more acceptable forms such as copyrights. Key to Boyle's analysis of such puzzles is the distinction between the public and private spheres, which, following Karl Marx, is fundamental to an understanding of the functioning of law in the modern liberal state. In the public sphere, we are, as citizens, all equal—distinctions of class have no standing. In the private sphere, however, differences of wealth, social background, and opportunity are determinative of real outcomes for individuals and their communities. For Boyle, the public-private distinction enables the inhabitants of a modern liberal state to ideologically reconcile a sort of social cognitive dissonance. It is also on this axis of public-private distinction that many questions involving IPRs are resolved (pp. 26-27). Applying the author-centered paradigm to IPRs, Boyle argues that the concept stands as a gateway through which one must pass to acquire IPRs. Not all innovations, however, pass easily through. A widely disproportionate share, in fact, is claimed by rich countries and far fewer by poor countries. Boyle notes: Curare, batik, myths, and the dance "lambada" flow out of the developing countries, unprotected by a suite of intellectual property rights, while Prozac, Levis, Grisham, and the movie Lambada! flow in—protected by a suite of intellectual property laws, which in turn are backed by the threat of trade sanctions, (p. 125)
21
Boyle argues that this disparity is not entirely a consequence of the operation of the IP system. However, the system operates to exacerbate the disparity owing to a centuries-old international division of labor in which poor countries specialize in providing primary products and raw materials for which the "authorial regime" assigns a value of zero in terms of IP (p. 126). Scientists are deemed to be "authors" who transform nature. Farmers, on the other hand, are seen as a part of the naturally evolvjing community operating on the basis of an unchanging tradition. The contributions of farmers are consequently made invisible and unlikely to command a high reward in the market, even when they can be shown to be economically productive. It is an easy leap to attribute such contributions to! the public sphere, a commons whose exploitation then becomes the target |of the private sphere by the authentic "author" (p. 130). The result is a system characterized by its colossal unfairness as well as its inefficiency. In speculating about the character of and! alternatives to the prevailing IP system, Boyle asks a number of useful questions. Does this system rest on evidence or on faith? Do we want to consider a system that would have more protection for information production and less protection for the production of innovation? Do all the types of innovation that get protection actually need it? If not, is it necessary, for reasons of administration and formal realiz ibility, to cast our net so wide? In its overall effects, does this system disp-oportionately help or hurt developing countries and the individual author or creator? Does this system undervalue the public domain and, if so, will it actually end up diminishing future innovation and impeding future innovators? (pp. 140-141) Boyle makes the extremely important point that a single "Procrustean" concept of information production and ownership will not be able to satisfactorily address this list of questions for the diverse types of production in which human societies are engaged. And yet such! a concept is precisely what the TRIPS agreement seeks to impose. Overview of the Chapters Chapter 2 provides a critical review of the' traditional philosophical approaches to the concept of property right. It includes a discussion of the Lockean labor theory of property, the Hegelian personality justification, and the utilitarian justification (both in its familiar Benthamite version and its less familiar, but useful, Godwinian interpretation). The approaches inspired by Locke and Hegel are found to fail to offer compelling justifications for private property
22
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
in ideas. The utilitarian philosophies, especially that associated with Bentham, also have difficulties. Parallels may be drawn between the applicability of these philosophic approaches to IPRs and to proposals calling for an international agreement on minimum labor standards for workers. One might well ask why there is no such agreement on trade-related international labor standards (TPJLS) that would provide for workers a degree of the protection such as that offered by the TRIPS for those who claim ownership of intellectual property. The answer is that advocates for a TRILS agreement have not been able to mobilize nearly as effectively to imprint the emerging international regulatory infrastructure as have the proponents for stronger IPRs. Chapter 3 examines the institution of intellectual property from the perspective of positivist economic science. By positivist economic science I refer to the research tradition that places primary emphasis on the formulation and tests of hypotheses drawn from abstract models of economic processes. It is well known that this is the dominant research tradition among academic and professional economists. In the examination of this literature, I do not pretend, however, to endorse the positivist approach as a preferred one. To the contrary, I tend to believe that it often results in a very selective and ideologically biased presentation of evidence. It does, however, present evidence of a type nonetheless with which critical social science should contend rather than ignore. By critical social science, including critical economics, I refer to those research traditions that challenge both the substantive assertions and the methodological premises of the dominant discourse. As opposed to the ahistorical and methodological individualism of positivist economics, critical social science has typically emphasized the importance of historical context and the central role played by groups, including classes. In this chapter I review recent theoretical treatments of the effect of patents on various measures of economic welfare and/or important economic policy targets. The findings are generally ambiguous, though the general conclusions seem to suggest that poor nations are better off if left to their own devices in forming an optimal national IPR regime. I also review the available econometric evidence on the impact of the strength of IPR regime on certain target variables, such as exports, direct foreign investment (DFI), and the rate of economic growth. Included in this review is my own respecification and test of an empirical model presented in an often cited paper by Lee and Mansfield (1996) that purports to show the beneficial effects of strong IPRs on DFI. These results overturn Lee and Mansfield's findings. In general, the empirical evidence is shown to be too weak to support the contention that the TRIPS agreement offers adequate short- or mediumterm benefits to justify its accession by poor countries. The central argument advanced in Chapter 4 is that a political economic
INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
23
analysis of IPRs requires corresponding theories of the state, class, and capital as they operate in the global econohry. Several candidate theories from international political economy and international relations theory are available. Three in particular provide useful insights for the analytical task at hand. These are world systems theory, associated with writers such as Immanuel Wallerstein (1974), Samir Amin (1974), and Arghiri Emmanuel (1972); hegemony theory, inspired by Antonio Gramsci (1971) and developed by Giovanni Arrighi (1993), Roberjt Cox (1996), and Stephen Gill (1993) among others; and internationalization of capital, theorized by Christian Palloix (1977) and more recently developed by Dick Bryan (1995). For some social scientists the sort of theoretical eclecticism represented by the selective use of elements from this collection of theories may be initially offputting. I hope to convince the reader, however, that a critical eclecticism is both appropriate and even necessary to the issues at hand. Chapter 5 applies the findings of the preceding chapter to provide an explanation for the establishment of the TRIPS agreement as part of the international institutional infrastructure governing the capitalist world system. This explanation appeals equally to the concepts of Gramscian (consensual) hegemony and direct (bilateral) coercion. Where the latter is concerned, the role of U.S. trade policy is given emphasis. In this explanation, however, the United States is represented not as an aspiring hegemonic state in the spirit of hegemonic stability theory, but as the representative of a transnational capitalist class. The limitations of other competing interpretations (Van Grasstek 1990; Ryan 1998) are discussed. Chapter 6 is one of two case studies < )f the application of the TRIPS agreement to specific industrial contexts. The pharmaceutical industry is chosen because it is among the most important to discuss from the perspective of global human welfare and because of the disproportionate influence that transnational drug producers had in influencing the negotiations leading to the establishment of the agreement. The failure of the international pharmaceutical industry to address the health problems of poor countries is discussed, as is the likely (negative) consequences for the ability of poor countries to devise indigenous solutions to those problems in the face of the TRIPS. The pharmaceutical industry is also presented as a case for which the prospects for counterhegemonic organization and struggle are very good, as evidenced by the recent Doha Declaration. The second of the two case studies, in Chapter 7, concerns the impact of a strengthened global IPR regime on-biotechnology and agriculture. This case study is included because agricultural biotech has important environmental implications as well as tremendous implications for the ability of the world's impoverished to provide themselves with the basic necessities of life. The
24
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
case makes a useful contrast to.the pharmaceutical case study for at least a couple of reasons. First, ag biotech in its IPR dimensions involves not just new commodities, but also new production processes. This fact has important implications for the process of internationalization of capital discussed in other chapters. A second, and perhaps related, reason concerns the apparently reduced prospects for successful, counterhegemonic resistance to the power of transnational capital. Conclusions and lessons for action are considered in the final chapter. This chapter provides a brief discussion of the future of the TRIPS agreement. It then concentrates on drawing general lessons from the two case studies provided in chapters 6 and 7. These lessons are of two sorts. The first set attempts to show how the cases provide support for the general political economic interpretation of the TRIPS agreement as it is set out in Chapter 5. The second set concerns the conditions and limitations of counterhegemonic action and organization.
2 The Ideology of Intellectual Property
With the close of the Uruguay Round of the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) and the establishment of the World Trade Organization (WTO) in 1995, several nontariff, trade-related issues achieved a new or heightened visibility in international economic negotiations. The official position of the United States required t$e inclusion of so-called intellectual property rights (IPRs) as a topic of GAIT negotiation. The view of the U.S. Trade Representative was that respect for intellectual property (IP) was a sufficiently contentious issue involving actual and potential violations of patents, copyrights, trademarks, and so on that it required international institutional oversight and, if necessary, trade-related sanctions. These functions were seen as appropriately falling within the purview of the WTO. It is highly likely that in the absence of an agreemeit on trade-related intellectual property rights (TRIPS), the United States would have withdrawn its support for the Uruguay Round of GATT talks and i he agreement establishing the WTO would never have been ratified. The Uruguay Round of GATT was rotable for several other innovations instrumental to a rationalization of the global capitalist system. Agreements were reached on liberalizing trade in services, increasing market access to previously protected areas such as textiles and agriculture, and strengthening the disputes settlements mechanisml Equally notable in recent years has been the increased willingness of groups who have been left out of formal negotiations to assert their own claims and to challenge the outcomes of the official international process. These groups include, among others, trade unionists, environmental and human rights activists, and animal rights advocates. They have called for modifications of the WTO principles and procedures to take due recognition of the negative fallout of a global system of production and distribution whose njotor force is unconstrained profit maximization. These calls have been met in the mainstream press with a combination of condescending explanations of the benefits of unrestrained trade and outright derision.1 ; The mainstream press critique of; civil society's demands have been supported by much academic analysis that argues for the exceptionalism of in25
26
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
tellectual property rights within the context of the WTO—an exceptionalism that does not apply to minimum international labor standards, for example. Maskus (1999) argues that WTO oversight of intellectual property rights is justified by the fact that IPRs are inextricably linked to the international exchange of goods and services. A weak regime of protection weakens the incentive to export to markets where the threat of imitation is high. Moreover, a generally weak international regime of uniform IPRs may have a discouraging effect on innovation (Aoki and Prusa 1993). Weak IPRs then act as a barrier to exports, resulting in reduced welfare. An understanding of the legitimacy of TRIPS involves presuppositions about what we regard as the legitimate reach of the concept of property and property rights, about the relationship between these, however understood, and about the role of the market in a global economy. In this chapter I shall examine some of the well-known and widely discussed theories of property and property right.2 The writers whose ideas will be examined had little to say about intellectual property as such. An important part of the task here will be to show the applicability and/or limitations of these theories to intellectual property, as well as evaluate their internal cogency when applied to knowledge and knowledge-based commodities. It is not the position taken here that traditional justificatory arguments relating to private property rights provide an adequate explanation for the emergence of the TRIPS agreement. Any such explanation would necessarily involve considerations of political economy. Nonetheless, negotiations and debate that lead to international agreements are rarely exercises in raw geopolitical power wherein the strong impose terms on the weak without any recourse to ideological justification. This review will provide a useful context within which to critically evaluate the competing claims surrounding the debate on TRIPS and the place of intellectual property in the global economic system. Philosophic Interpretations of Property and Property Right \ The term property conjures up for most people images of land and/or material possessions that confer on their owners rights of use as well as the right to exclude others from their use. A moment's reflection, however, reveals this conception to be overly narrow for our purposes. The notion of intellectual property, for example, refers to something decidedly less tangible, although no less useful, than this. What intellectual property has in common with other forms, however, is at least the possibility of exclusivity of use. The notion of exclusion itself raises the question of organized and legitimate force. An understanding of legitimate force helps us to get nearer a generalized concept of property as a socially and politically contingent category.
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
27
Put simply, property is what the law defines it to be. Laws relating to property are, in turn, grounded in justificatory theories. Some of these theories involve notions of moral right while others !are more instrumental in character. Locke's Labor Theory of Property John Locke is perhaps the quintessential itheorist of property as right. Property right, like all rights according to Locke, is derived from natural law. Natural law philosophy posits God as the creator of humankind, from which view follow various obligations owed by humankind to him. According to this view, God is a creator and therefore owner of his creation, including us. Humankind's fundamental obligation (and right) is to preserve God's creation. Toward this end God has made available to humanity his nonhuman creation. God's nonhuman creation then:is appropriated by humanity as its common property for the purposes of its common preservation. Locke writes in his Second Treatise (1698): God, who hath given the World to Men in common, hath also given them reason to make use of it to the best advantage of Life, and convenience. The Earth, and all that is therein, is given to Men for the Support and Comfort of their being. And though all ihe Fruits it naturally produces, and Beasts it feeds, belong to Mankind in common, as they are produced by the spontaneous hand of Nature; and no x>dy has originally a private Dominion, exclusive of the rest of Mankind, in any of them, as they are thus in their natural state: yet being given for the use of Men, there must of necessity be a means to appropriate them some way or other before they can be of any use, or at all beneficial to any particular Man. (1963, chapter 5, section 26) The problem for Locke is how to demonstrate that the need to appropriate God's natural gift leads us to (justifies) the notion of private property right. Locke manages this demonstration by drawing a distinction between humankind's common property given by the creator and the individual's acquisition in that property. Locke shows :hat this acquisition derives from a fundamental, inviolate principle of self-ownership: Though the Earth, and all inferior Creatures be common to all Men, yet every Man has a property in his o>vn Person. This no Body has any Right to but himself. The Labour of his body, and the Work of his Hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he removes out of the State that Nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his Labour with, and joyned to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his Property. It being by him
28
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
removed from the common state Nature placed it in, hath by this labour something annexed to it, that excludes the common right of other Men. For this Labour being the unquestionable Property of the Labourer, no Man but he can have a right to what that is once joyned to, at least where there is enough, and as good left in common for others, (section 27) According to Locke, the much greater part of the value of property is that which we may attribute to the labor that people "mix" with God's gift of nature. Undeveloped nature, in fact, provides very little that could be considered useful to human beings considered singly or in society. The mere appropriation of food in its natural state—for example, picking berries in the woods—requires the expenditure of labor that adds to the food's value and therefore confers on it the status of private property owned by those who expended the effort. It is apparent from this oft quoted statement of Locke's that his conception of private property right, grounded in natural law philosophy, is not an unlimited or unconditional one. The concluding qualifying clause, "at least where there is enough, and as good left in common for others," suggests that Locke recognizes the logical possibility of an overaccumulation of property that would not be morally justified. Accumulation beyond the use and convenience of individuals that results in waste is regarded by Locke as an infringement on the rights of others to "as good." As a practical problem, however, Locke is unconcerned with this possibility for two reasons. First, the resource-to-population ratio is sufficiently high to permit anyone to have "as good" as anyone else. Locke repeatedly points to the abundance of land and other resources that remain in a state of nature in America, waiting to be taken under production by the application of European labor. Second, even in the comparatively developed English society of his day, where the enclosure movement had definitively established private property in land, the invention of money resulted in a means to accumulate property in a manner that does not lead to waste even as it permits the expansion of individual estates. He argues: But since Gold and Silver, being little useful to the life of Man in proportion to Food, Rayment, and Carriage, has its value only from the consent of Men, whereof Labour yet makes, in great part, the measure, it is plain, that Men have agreed to disproportionate and unequal Possession of the Earth, they having by a tacit and voluntary consent found out a way, how a man may fairly possess more land than he himself can use the product of, by receiving in exchange for the overplus, Gold and Silver, which may be hoarded up without injury to any one, these metalls not spoiling or decay-
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
29
ing in the hands of the possessor. This partage of things, in an inequality of private possessions, men have made practicable out of the bounds of Societie, and without compact, only by putting a value on gold and silver and tacitly agreeing in the use of Money. For in Governments the Laws regulate the right of property, and the possession of land is determined by positive constitutions, (section 50) From this passage we see that Locke regards the accumulation of money as an essentially benign process inasmuch as it "may be hoarded up without injury to any one." This interpretation in ttarn might suggest that he does not have a conception of money as finance capital or that he does not see finance capital as playing a particularly limiting function in society at large. Quite to the contrary, however, Locke explicitly interprets the role of private accumulation, in money form or otherwise, as playing a positive, utilitarian role in the development of society according to divine mandate. What is remarkable from the above passage is that Locke suggests that the emergence of money is a matter of consent—that is, "tacitly agreeing in the use of Money." Locke provides no explicit justification for the assumption that the money economy is the result of a broad-based agreement. The implied evidence for this assertion is that money has evolved as a generally acceptable means of payment in a world of voluntary exchange. Even more remarkable is that for Lrjcke private property itself is both logically and historically prior to the sta;e. We see in Commons, which remain so by Compact, that 'tis the taking any part of what is common, and removing it out of the state Nature leaves it in, which begins the Property; without which the Common is of no use. And the taking of this or that part, does not depend on the express consent of all the Commoners. Thus the Grass my'Horse has bit; the Turfs my Servant has cut; and the Ore I have digg'd in any place where I have a right to them in common with others, become my Property, without the assignation or consent of any body, (section 28) The fact that consent is not required to validate private property suggests that property exists in a state of nature rather than as the result of a socially created law and state. The obvious question; then is, What is the function of civil society (law and the state) in relation to property? For Locke, the answer is clear; the function of civil society is precisely the defense of the natural right to property. In Chapter 9 of the Second Treatise he writes, "The great and chief end therefore, of Mens uniting into Commonwealths, and putting themselves under government, is the Preservation of their Property." Govern-
30
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
ment, then, has in Locke's conception a largely negative function of defending those rights that already exist in a state of nature. This is necessary, according to Locke, since while humans are endowed with reason by their creator, they are not all equally so endowed. God gave the World to Men in Common;... He gave it to the use of the Industrious and Rational, (and Labour was to be his Title to it;) not to the Fancy and Covetousness of the Quarrelsom and Contentious. He that had as good left for his Improvement, as was already taken up, needed not complain, ought not to meddle with what was already improved by another's Labour, (chapter 5, section 34) To ensure that the more "Quarrelsom and Contentious" do not infringe on the property of the "Industrious and Rational," humans have entered freely into a commonwealth wherein they relinquish their individual sovereignty in favor of laws and institutions that operate in the interests of preserving the property of all. Ryan (1984, p. 41) argues that Locke's defense of the inequality engendered by private property might be on firmer ground if appeal is made to the essentially utilitarian argument that such inequality makes possible a higher level of productivity out of which the landless peasant or worker may enjoy a higher standard of living than would otherwise be the case. Ryan also cbrrectly notes that such a comparison involves additional unsubstantiated assumptions about how we could make valid comparisons given the impossibility of testing the hypothesis. Locke's own preference for comparing the landless laborer of his own time and place with the wild savage in a state of nature is hardly adequate, given the impossibility of assessing the subjective evaluation of their respective social and material positions.
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
31
provides ideological justification for unlimited private accumulation. He argues that Locke was steeped in the assumptions that motivated the bourgeois political economy of his time. Among these was the notion that human beings had a natural propensity for accumulation. Accumulation in fact was equated with moral rationality. In the primitive stage of the state of nature, accumulation could be condemned when it resulted in spoilage. The invention of money in the second, more advanced stage of the state of nature, however, enabled productive accumulation to occur. Productive accumulation was morally praiseworthy (rational) precisely because, far from depriving others of the means to a living, it provided those who did not possess more than their own labor power with su|ch a means. Once again, what is especially remarkable about Locke's argument here is the assumption that differential accumulation beyond the needs of an individual or a family occurs logically prior to the establishment of the state and civil society. For Locke, the emergence of money and markets somehow becomes a matter of universal human consent. The emergence of civil society and the state then serves the negative purposes of protecting private property. Not only does Locke provide us with a justification of differential property rights grounded in his philosophy of natural law and natural rights, but he also derives a corresponding theory of class and class-based political rights. According to Locke, the accumulation of p roperty for productive purposes is the rational expression of natural law. Insofar as individuals do not accumulate, this is taken as evidence of their imperfect rationality. The mass of propertyless laborers are thus taken to be less than fully rational and therefore incapable of full participation in the political life of civil society. The Utilitarians
The question is frequently posed concerning the political intent of the Lockean doctrine of property. Reasonable arguments can be marshaled that Locke's theory was an attempt to undermine the political and economic prerogatives of vestigial medieval authority as well as provide ideological legitimacy to Britain's emergent capitalist class. The first of these arguments is well posed by Tully (1980), who notes that Locke sought to undermine the "Adamite theory" of property, according to which God gave the world to Adam to distribute in turn to his progeny. By extension, property has come under the dominion of the aristocracy, which traces its own lineage to these first owners. Locke in his approach to natural law and natural rights logically undermines not only this property claim but also the divine rights origin of aristocratic rule.
It is well known that a keystone philosophic concept supporting much of the neoclassical economic edifice is provided by utilitarianism. Utility maximization is taken to be a guiding behavioral assumption driving rational agents in an efficient resource-allocating market syst ;m. It is not at all surprising to find notions familiar to utilitarian philosophy providing justification for property in such a system. At the same time, however, a certain strain of utilitarianism also plays a strong justificatory role in support of social arrangements that place a greater premium on egalitarianism than is provided by market capitalism.
We can contrast this aspect of Locke's thinking with the interpretation, offered for example by Macpherson (1964), that Locke's theory of property
In his An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice (1793), the nineteenth-century British philosopher William Godwin poses the following question:
Godwin's "Genuine System of Property"
32
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
What is the criterion that must determine whether this or that substance capable of contributing to the benefit of a human being ought to be considered as your property or mine? To this question there can be but one answer— Justice. Let us then recur to the principle of justice. (1926, vol. 2, book 8) Godwin's understanding of justice is a thoroughly utilitarian one. As it relates to property, justice is entirely a matter of who will benefit the most from ownership. From this perspective, Godwin condemns the prevailing system of private property, which he regards as both unjust and irrational, and provides a vision of a just and rational alternative based on strictly egalitarian principles. Implicit in both his critique and his vision are definite notions as to what constitutes the good—that is, well-led—life and the just society. Neither of these objectives can be realized, according to Godwin, if society is characterized by large inequalities in the distribution of income and wealth. The poor who toil long hours for the bare means of subsistence will never have the leisure to pursue higher callings involving the cultivation of the mind and spirit. Likewise, those who dedicate themselves to the pursuit of material luxuries are distracted from these same higher callings and mistakenly confuse the status gained by the ownership of large estates with that associated with substantial accomplishments. It is only such accomplishments, however, that win their possessors the social distinction and approbation for which human beings long. Godwin is something of a minimalist in his views concerning the real material needs and wants of rational human beings. Beyond the basic needs of food, clothing, and shelter, and these in modest quantities, the fundamental material requirements for the well-lived life are exceedingly few and could easily be satisfied with a correspondingly limited amount of labor and exertion. Allowing for the equitable sharing of this labor and its fruits, the human race could be liberated from the injustice and oppression that follows from a system in which the great masses toil in service to an elite that is overindulged in sensual pleasures but otherwise spiritually and intellectually impoverished. Godwin does not provide us with a historical explanation as to how or why the prevailing, socially dysfunctional system of property ownership came to be established. He is certain, however, that once it is replaced by what he calls the "genuine system of property" ("genuine" based on his understanding of justice), the new system will prove its worth and become a permanent basis for human social relations. This is ensured by Godwin's assumption regarding the essential rationality of humankind. Godwin is convinced that once having experienced the benefits of an egalitarian society, individuals will have no incentive to resort to unnecessary accumulation of property.
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
33
There will be no need to accumulate to guard against adverse contingencies since society as a whole will address such possibilities collectively. Status will no longer attach to property, removing this as a possible inducement to individual accumulation. According to Godwin, in fact, any tendency toward such accumulation will come to be regarded as a sort of social pathology akin to murder. Godwin also responds to what he anticipates to be the likely practical objections to his alternative system of genuine property. To the argument, for example, that an egalitarian distribution of property would remove incentive to work and inventiveness (industry), he replies that, to the contrary, equality will result in moral and intellectual improvement which will in turn work against the tendency toward indolence. Also, as already noted, under Godwin's "genuine system" the labor requirement is anticipated to be collectively shared and therefore individually light enough so that shirking will not be an issue. To the contrary, argues Godwin, "It is so light a burthen as rather to assume the appearance of agreeable relaxation and gentle exercise than of labour" (chapter 4). Bentham's "Security" Defense If the case for private property on a utilitarian basis is weak in the hands of William Godwin, it receives more than adequate support from that nineteenthcentury thinker who is most closely associated with the utilitarian philosophical tradition—namely, Jeremy Bentham. Bentham's utilitarianism, in contrast to the utopianism of Godwin, is concerned with the practical issue of legislating in a society whose institutioial premise of capitalism, including private property, he took for granted. Not surprisingly, therefore, his ideological defense of property is straightforwardly an ideological justification of capitalism. According to Bentham, human happiness consists in four subordinate ends of the legislative process. These are subsistence, abundance, equality, and security (Bentham 1987, Principles of Civil Code)} Bentham is aware that these four goals are not independent of one another. Abundance, for example, presupposes subsistence. It is also evident that abundance makes subsistence and equality feasible objectives. To the extent that equality and security conflict with one another, Bentham believes that preeminence must be given to security: In legislation, the most important object is security. Though no laws were made directly for subsistence, it might easily be imagined that no one would neglect it. But unless laws are made directly for security, it would be quite useless to make them for subsistence. You may order production; you may
34
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
command cultivation; and you will have nothing. But assure to the cultivator the fruits of his industry, and perhaps in that alone you will have done enough.... . . . We cannot arrive at the greatest good, except by the sacrifice of some subordinate good. All the difficulty consists in distinguishing that object which, according to the occasion, merits pre-eminence. For each, in its turn, demands it; and a very complicated calculation is sometimes necessary to avoid being deceived as to the preference due to one or the other, (chapter 3) Bentham's belief that equality is a subordinate goal of legislation is based on his concern for production incentives and the expectations of the producers themselves.
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
35
Secondarily, Bentham believes that; the abundance produced under a regime of secure property rights provides a sort of social insurance during periods of calamity. Societies that lack the ability to produce a surplus find themselves vulnerable to wars or natural disasters. Interestingly, however, he is silent as to how the surplus is to be transferred from its owners to the population at large in the event that it is so required. A possible answer is via taxation. This would seem to involve a change in legislation that would fundamentally upset the expectations that Bentham is so concerned to secure in the first place. There is no mistaking Bentham's understanding as to the meaning of property and the basis for property right. This understanding sharply distinguishes his thought from the natural law theorists such as Locke.
Equality ought not to be favoured except in the cases in which it does not interfere with security; in which it does not thwart the expectations which the law itself has produced; in which it does not derange the order already established. If all property were equally divided, at fixed periods, the sure and certain consequence would be, that presently there would be no property to divide. All would shortly be destroyed. Those whom it was intended to favour, would not suffer less from the division than those at whose expense it was made. If the lot of the industrious was not better than the lot of the idle, there would be no longer any motives for industry, (chapter 3)
The idea of property consists in an established expectation; the persuasion of being able to draw such or such; an advantage from the thing possessed, according to the nature of the case. Now this expectation, this persuasion, can only be the work of law. I cannot count upon the enjoyment of that which I regard as mine, except through the promise of the law which guarantees it to me. It is law alone which permits me to forget my natural weakness. It is only through the protect on of the law that I am able to inclose a field, and to give myself up to its [cultivation with the sure though distant hope of harvest, (chapter 8)
The security that Bentham seeks by legislation to ensure is the knowledge that individuals will enjoy the fruits of their labors. If people did not have this expectation, their willingness to labor, rather than to steal, might well be called into question. Security, then, is a requirement for subsistence. In this there does not seem any particular contradiction between his position and the more egalitarian position of Godwin. How then does Bentham rationalize the substantial inequalities of wealth and property that are unacceptable to Godwin? There are two answers to this question. First, Bentham, unlike Godwin, is far more willing to equate increases in human happiness with expanded human consumption. For Bentham, equality is not an end in itself. Equality in certain limited circumstances may be instrumental to the realization of the utilitarian ideal—the greatest sum of human happiness, but it does not replace this ideal. Abundance is also instrumental to that goal. For abundance to be realized, however, requires what Bentham calls "industry," which in turn requires security. Again he writes, "the attraction of pleasure; the succession of wants; the active desire of increasing happiness, will procure unceasingly, under the reign of security, new efforts towards new acquisitions" (chapter 4).
In anticipation of possible objections from those who insist on a natural rights basis for property, Bentham grants that human beings have also operated on the basis of a natural e. •pectation concerning what they are able to acquire and possess that is anterior to law. He argues, though, that such possession is "miserable and precarious" because it is enforced only by physical force. The corresponding expectation is therefore feeble and momentary, whereas a strong and permanent expectation can result only from law. | Bentham also anticipates objections from those who argue that property rights operate against the interests,of those who lack property. Here he finds convenient the image of man in a state of nature—that is, the uncivilized savage—that was used so effectively by Locke in his own arguments in defense of property. Bentham argues ithat the laws that protect property work to the benefit of the propertyless by; enabling them to rise above the state of nature. Property secured by law enables them to have regular labor and regular wages, rendering them less vulnerable to the vicissitudes and calamities of nature. Moreover, the prospect of accumulation engenders even among the propertyless a desire to possess and overcomes in them an aversion to
36
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
labor. This prospect is effective, however, only when secured by law in the form of property right. It is that right which has vanquished the natural aversion to labour; which has given to man the empire of the earth; which has brought to an end the migratory life of nations; which has produced the love of country and regard for posterity. Men universally desire to enjoy speedily—to enjoy without labour. It is that desire which is terrible; since it arms all who have not against all who have. The law which restrains that desire is the noblest triumph of humanity over itself, (chapter 9) Bentham's defense of property makes clear his commitment to the ascendant capitalism of his day. In considering various arguments that criticize private property, Bentham makes a counterargument that would be familiar to any modern economist who extols the virtues of the capitalist entrepreneur. Essentially Bentham argues that attacks on private property, if allowed, would have the ill effect of destroying the investment climate necessary for capitalist development. Individual capitalists, argues Bentham, are capable of overcoming individual, transitory setbacks. He writes: A transitory calamity, though great, never destroys the spirit of industry. It is seen to spring up, after devouring wars which have impoverished nations, as a robust oak, mutilated by tempests, repairs its losses in a few years and covers itself with new branches. Nothing is sufficient to deaden industry, except the operation of a domestic and permanent cause, such as a tyrannical government, bad legislation, and intolerant religion which drives men from the country, or a minute superstition which stupefies them, (chapter 10) Now while Bentham follows the above observation with passing comments on the destructive effects of various "acts of violence" perpetrated by the despotic state on the industrious spirit, he makes clear that his chief concern is for the security of property: That government, odious to every thinking man, has never known that state cannot grow rich except by an inviolable respect for property. It has never had but two secrets of statesmanship—to sponge the people, and to stupify them. Thus the finest countries of the earth, wasted, barren, and almost abandoned, can hardly be recognized under the hands of barbarous conquerors, (chapter 10) Finally, although Bentham regards the objective of equality as secondary in relation to the security of property, he is fairly sanguine for the prospects
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
37
of greater equality as long as security is ensured. The great equalizer for Bentham is death, since at death particular properties cease to have owners. Bentham has no particular objection to the use of state power for redistributive purposes in the matter of estates. He rationalizes this position by arguing that this sort of redistribution does nothing to disrupt prevailing expectations. Bentham also notes an empirical tendency in the direction of greater equality over time as long as the law is; vigilant in combating monopoly privileges (including entails) and otherwise refrains from establishing obstacles to free commerce. This natural redistribution offers far greater prospects for future prosperity, he argues, than that based on violent upheaval as might attend upon revolutionary redistribution, for example. Here, once again, we see the primacy of security for Bentham as a condition for social progress. Hegel and the Necessity of Private Property The Hegelian theory of property is an example of what Waldron( 1988) typifies as an argument based on general right (GR). A GR-based argument is distinguished from an argument based on special right (SR), which predicates property right on the occurrence o some contingent event or action taken by the individual(s) asserting the right. Thus, for example, Locke's labor theory of ownership is a SR-based argument inasmuch as the right to property follows from the expenditure of labor by those who claim property in that with which their labor becomes mixed. A GR-based argument, by contrast, does not take property right to be based on any such contingent event or action, but rather argues that sorr.e individual interest is sufficiently important inherently to justify a particular property rights regime.3 For Hegel, this compelling individual interest is a matter of what he calls "practical freedom." "Freedom" here is not to be understood in the libertarian sense of "absence of restraint." RauW the Hegelian notion of freedom is the "realization of necessity." Human beings are essentially rational creatures. They possess, therefore, the ability to understand what they rationally must do. That understanding in turn is the essence of their freedom (Ryan 1984, p. 120). In like manner, Hegel is concerned to "explain" the logical necessity of property. Historical progress requires that people develop the capacity to participate in the ethical community (Waldron 1988, p. 347). For this to occur, people must develop personality, understood as a sense of their individual capacities and wills. Property facilitates the development of personality in two ways. First, it enables basic needs to be satisfied. Second and more importantly, property is a vehicle by which the individual makes a transition from an inner, subjective world to the external, objective world.
38
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
39
The reasonableness of property consists in its satisfying our needs, but in its superseding and replacing the subjective phase of personality. It is in possession first of all that the person becomes rational. The first realization of my freedom in an external object is an imperfect one, it is true, but it is the only realization possible so long as the abstract personality has this first-hand relation to its object. (Hegel 1996, first section, paragraph 41).
and even at the expense of other rights, must win the victory In property my will is personal. But the person, it must be observed, is the particular individual, and, thus, property is ithe embodiment of this particular will. Since property gives visible existence to my will, it must be regarded as "this" and hence as "mine." This is the important doctrine of the necessity of private property. (Hegel 1996, section 46)
Mind or freedom, according to Hegel, is necessarily embodied. At a primitive level it is embodied in particular subjects (human and finite). As it matures and develops, it transcends these limited forms and externalizes itself in a higher and more universal embodiment. The first step in this process of externalization is for the subjective human being to establish the fact of individual personality in the world of material objects. This is done by appropriating, owning, and controlling objects in the material world. As Ryan points out, Hegel's theory effectively amounts to a "first taker" argument for possession. One who appropriates and controls first need not justify possession. The ethical burden of justification falls on the person who would dispossess an established owner. Dispossession that is not justified by a prior claim is unethical inasmuch as it fails to respect the will of the previous possessor. Property ownership as the embodiment of will is an important concept in Hegel's theory. In this regard, property becomes linked to work. This embodiment of will implies, first, that labor has in some way altered some physical object in a sense that can be understood only in relation to the will of the laborer. Second, the altered object effects a change in the will itself. The subjective will then, in altering the material world, also alters itself. How will property-owning contribute to the self-realization of personality? Waldron explains the connection as follows: "Modifying something in the external world changes the subject too. Since he takes responsibility for his production, identifying it as the product of his will, he has to shape his will and his intentions so that they become apt for this sort of stable and constraining vision" (1988, p. 373).
Even where artificial persons are created and endowed with ownership functions, these purely legal entities are only made possible by the individuals who cooperate to create them (Ryan 19,84, p. 128). An additional argument for the private character of property is based on the Hegelian imperative mat human beings command recognition. The need for will to be recognized by other contending wills is the basis for the limits imposed on the latter provided by private property. Law and contract have evolved so as to provide individuals with the concrete "fences" that delimit relationships and permit the subjective: personality to emerge into a public world (Waldron 1988, p. 377). Hegel's view of the political and economic organization of society is decidedly bourgeois. His views on property suggest a nation of small and interdependent property owners who bear responsibility for themselves and their families. Hegel was aware, however, of the increasing commercialization of the society in which he lived. He also recognized the class divisions that characterized society and was concerned with the conditions for social stability. Ryan illustrates this concern'of Hegel's as follows:
The necessarily private character of property derives from the fact that the embodiment of will is the embodiment of individual will. This is true notwithstanding Hegel's concern for the development of the ethical community. The ethical community itself, however, is composed of ethical individuals who realize themselves as such only through the externalization process that requires private property. In the agrarian laws of Rome may be found a conflict between collective and private ownership of land. Private possession is the more reasonable,
Hegel evidently feared that the commercial mind would apply its contractual and calculative schemes to eveify aspect of life. He was fearful that the independent, individualist, rationalist intellect would provide a powerful solvent of political loyalty; and when he did not fear that, he feared that any state in which the urban bourgeoisie held power would be one in which mean-spirited enterprises predominated, not those of a world historical kind. (1984, p. 139) j Given this concern, Hegel believed that government had a role to play in regulating market forces—for example, iprice controls and subsidies. Hegel's concerns about the destabilizing consequences of an unregulated market system included a fear that the system had-a tendency to produce a propertyless class that often struggled (and failed) to keep itself out of poverty. In his view, civil society has a duty to provide for the physical necessities of the impoverished, but he also shares the modern concern about what effect poor relief might have on the incentive to work (Waldron 1988, p. 380).
40
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Hegel's concern about the destabilizing effects of poverty does not make him an egalitarian by any means. To the contrary, he sees inequality in wealth and income as the natural consequence of the inequality to be found in individual persons' abilities and characters. He writes: Sometimes the demand is made for equality in the division of the soil of the earth, and even of other kinds of wealth. Such a claim is superficial, because differences of wealth are due not only to the accidents of external nature but also to the infinite variety and difference of mind and character. In short, the quality of an individual's possessions depends upon his reason, developed into an organic whole. We cannot say that nature is unjust in distributing wealth and property unequally, because nature is not free and, therefore, neither just nor unjust. It is part a moral desire that all men should have sufficient income for their wants, and when the wish is left in this indefinite form it is well-meant, although it, like everything well-meant, has no counterpart in reality. (Hegel 1996, section 49) Hegel goes on to argue that even if a social scheme could be devised to distribute goods equally, the resultant equality would be temporary inasmuch as the inherent inequalities in the characters and abilities that define individuals would re-create inequality. He argues then, "What does not permit of being carried out, ought not to be attempted." Interestingly, however, notwithstanding manifest inequality in the distribution of goods and property, Hegel insists that everyone must have some property in order to achieve personality. As there are many who possess no property, Hegel seems to imply that not all people are eligible for this distinction. The Ideology of Intellectual Property The thinkers whose ideas I have outlined in the above sections never had much to say about intellectual property as such. Their chief concern was to justify real property, including land. The question we must pose here then is, How well do the theories stand up when they are applied to intellectual property? The Labor Theory of Intellectual Property Justin Hughes (1988) has argued that Locke's labor theory approach applies fairly well. Hughes's position is based on an essentially neo-Platonic interpretation of ideas as existing in an immaterial "commons." When these ideaforms are mixed with individual labor, they become effective in the material world. For Hughes, intellectual laborers are entitled to property rights in a
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
41
manner analogous to those who toil on [the natural commons and thereby create value-added. Hughes, in fact, goes as far as to argue that the Lockean approach applies with greater force to intellectual property than it does to physical property. This is because the essence of the intellectual commons renders unnecessary the "Lockean proviso" that takings leave "enough, and as good" for others. While the proviso might be an important qualification in a developed market economy where scarcities prevail, an important characteristic of intellectual goods is nonrivalryiof use. Hence, any taking from the Platonic ether of potential ideas does nothing to diminish the ability of anyone else from doing likewise. In fact, the development of ideas has a great potential to expand the intellectual commons inasmuch as the development of a particular idea often gives rise to additional intellectual creation. I will argue that Hughes's interpretation of Locke's theory, while interesting, is essentially flawed. The first difficulty is Hughes's argument that ideas are the result of the labor expended by isolated individuals. I find this a dubious proposition both as an explanation of how new ideas emerge and as a valid justification for private property. Ideas as such are the result of social rather than individual creation. This does! not mean that individuals may not make particular contributions to the stockj of intellectual and cultural capital. Clearly, however, such contributions must necessarily work on previously existing ideas that are .themselves the pre duct of a social process. Even the most novel of individual human insights, for example, requires the use of language—a social product for which no one person may take credit. The notion that ideas already have a prior existence in a "common," only waiting to be discovered by individuals, is an absvj rdity. The human race is not somehow endowed with intellectual raw materials out of which new and useful ideas and concepts are developed. Rather, these "raw materials" are themselves entirely the result of a social process and, therefore, a social product. Granting that individuals do make contributions to knowledge in ways that are useful to others, could it be arguecl that they deserve some reward for their effort? Locke's labor theory certainly argues that they do. As Hughes points out, Locke's thinking was grounded in the presumption that labor itself was something that people would Ordinarily seek to avoid in the absence of adequate reward. Property, then, is justified as the proper reward for such labor. How applicable is this sort of argument in the context of intellectual property? Are scientists, inventors, and other creative people well described by this view of human nature? I do not believe they are. Neither do I believe that the creative work usually associated with intellectual property is anathema, or even unpleasant, to the people who typically engage in it. Quite to the contrary, those who engage in intellectual and creative endeavors derive a
.LECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
ount of satisfaction in the creative process itself and find ultimate i^-. .....1 discovery and creation. This view does not require that we take an especially Pollyannaish attitude about human nature. Intellectual and creative people are not indifferent to worldly comforts and material goods. I do not believe, however, that such rewards figure as the primary incentives that explain their works. Most creative people would regard material rewards rather as the coincidental benefits of their success. Marginal increases or decreases in such rewards would not then have an appreciable effect on the rate of creative or inventive activity. Intellectual Property and the Lockean Proviso What about the status of the "Lockean proviso" as it applies to intellectual property? Does the appropriation of intellectual goods leave "enough, and as good" for others? It is in consideration of this question that the differences separating intellectual property from other kinds of property become most apparent. The appropriation and use of most physical property by individuals obviously deprive others, at least temporarily, from its simultaneous possession and/or use. The creation of private property right legitimates this exclusionary relationship. In the case of intellectual property right, on the other hand, the point is to create the basis for and legitimate such a relationship where none would otherwise exist. That is, given the public goods characteristics of intellectual goods, the creation of private property in such goods involves two types of issues. The first is what economists refer to as nonrivalry in use. My use of an idea in no way impedes anyone else's full use of the same idea. Moreover, the marginal cost of use of an idea is zero. The second issue is the difficulty of exclusion. How can those who are not inclined to pay for the use of an idea be excluded from its use? This is the clear purpose of intellectual property right. In a sense, then, the Lockean proviso is both well met and irrelevant. It is well met in the sense that the appropriation of intellectual property certainly does leave "enough, and as good" for others. At the same time, however, the very purpose of copyrights, patents, and the other instruments of institutionalized rights in such property is to prevent free access to such "enough, and as good." Hughes argues that intellectual property provides us with the quintessential Lockean justificatory case for private property. Hughes also argues that because new ideas provide the basis for additional intellectual insights, protection is called for. Intellectual property protection adds to the extensiveness of the "commons" and thereby creates a basis for an expansion of generalized human welfare. Here it is evident that Hughes is appealing to an essentially utilitarian, rather than a rights-based, argument for private property protection. As before, I have my doubts about
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
43
the essential assumption that private property rights are a necessary or appropriate incentive for the creation and dissemination of intellectual goods and services. Why should not a fixed monetary amount or public recognition and approbation be sufficient as a reward? Other issues relevant to the utilitarian perspective will be examined below. Intellectual Property and Efficiency Another qualification to place on the legitimacy of private property in Locke's theory is that it should not result in waste. In Locke's theory, this qualification applies with obvious force to the waste that may result if physical property is accumulated beyond the ability off its possessor to make adequate (efficient) use of it. If land is accumulated,' for example, but remains fallow because its owner lacks the time or other complementary inputs to employ it efficiently, then such accumulation would ;lack legitimacy, particularly if it deprived another of its efficient use. For Locke, this qualification did not amount to an effective limit on the accumulation of private property in a money economy since property could always be accumulated in a fungible and nonperishable form—namely, money capital. The money economy, according to Locke, emerges as a matter of the common assent of humankind. There are a number of questionable poim s regarding this aspect of Locke's theory as it applies to intellectual propert). The first concerns this issue of waste. The relevant question is, To what extent does the monopolization of new and valuable ideas via patents and copyrights involve waste? It would seem a considerable loss to limit the benefits of discovery and innovation when they involve zero marginal cost of pr eduction and very little or no cost of dissemination. Hughes makes the argument that the waste qualification is irrelevant to intellectual property inasmuch as ideas are not perishable. I think this is a very questionable assertion. The history of patents is rife with examples of cases in which new ideas and innovations have been delayed or permanently lost by interests who used patents to prolong their existing intellectual and physical capital stock. The Limitations of Intellectual Property Interestingly, Hughes also suggests that the concept of intellectual property rights is of limited applicability. He \yrites, "Intellectual property systems are more suitable for a Lockean justification than are physical property systems because a growing set of central1 ideas are never permitted to become private property and are held in a permanent common" (emphasis in original, p. 319).
44
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Hughes identifies certain categories of ideas that are subject to becoming "depropertized." These include common, "everyday ideas"—for example, walking your dog on a leash—and extraordinary ideas—for example, the human genome map. The latter category itself is decomposable into (1) ideas that reveal extraordinary facts about the world—for example, the theory of electromagnetism, and (2) those that have already established widespread use—for example, the use of architectural columns. Hughes cites particular case law that has liberated certain ideas into the sphere of the public domain. The general principle he derives is expressed as follows: In short, some ideas become "depropertized." Originally, they could have been subject to private ownership (unlike the first kind of extraordinary ideas), but the pressure to keep them in the common increases as the ideas become increasingly important to the society. As an idea becomes extraordinary, it is clear the common will not have "enough and as good" if the rights to the idea continue to be privately held. (p. 320) Once again I believe that Hughes's position should be greeted with skepticism. While he asserts that some ideas become "depropertized," he offers no explanation as to how, when, and if this is likely to happen in particular cases. The most problematical case involves what he refers to as "extraordinary ideas." In the current climate of rapid technological change and scientific discovery, many candidates, ranging from biotechnology to a new understanding of the creation of the cosmos, may qualify as falling into this category. Many of these discoveries have the potential to radically modify our understanding of ourselves and our potential. Who is to decide, and under what conditions? What constitutes a sufficiently important and fundamental insight as to qualify it as a public idea? Would, for example, private control over a new drug capable of ridding the world of the AIDS virus leave "enough, and as good" for those not wealthy enough to afford its purchase price? Obviously the answer is "no " The Lockean proviso, then, is clearly violated in such a case. It would seem in fact that for an extraordinary idea to become depropertized, a necessary, and perhaps even sufficient, condition would be that established property rights in it would have to be difficult to enforce, leading to their wholesale violation.4 The typical rejoinder to this argument, of course, is that to the extent that private property rights are not respected or effectively enforced, then the incentive for their creation and development in a market economy is undermined. At this point the justificatory ground has shifted from a Lockean basis to a utilitarian one. Further consideration will be given to the applicability of the utilitarian argument below. First, however, I would like to take up the possibilities offered by the Hegelian, "personality"-based justification as it might apply to intellectual property.
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
45
Freedom, Recognition, and Intellectual Property Recall that Hegel's primary concern is his concept of freedom, which requires the ability of individuals to overcome their narrow subjectivity and "externalize" themselves as part of a higher and larger embodiment, to wit, an ethical community. Property is logically necessary toward this end insofar as it permits people to develop personality. For Hegel, the creative act that results in property and personality simultaneously was viewed primarily as the transformation of a material reality. There seems no reason, however, why his theory could not accommodate intellectual property as well. Certainly the creation and expression of an idea is often a powerful means of extending or externalizing subjectivity. Hughes notes that this is especially true of artistic work. He goes as far as to argue that the personality argument might even preclude certain less artistic types of intellectual property. He writes: A property system protecting personality will have difficulty finding reliable indicia for when people do and do not have a "personality stake" in particular objects. The personality justification also leaves some nagging theoretical questions. Even if we reliably could detect when a person possesses a "personality stake" in an object, we surely would find that personality is manifested to varying degrees in different objects. . .. . . . Poetry seems to lend itself to personality better than trade secrets, symphonies better than microchip masks. Should poetry as a category receive more protection than microch p masks? Should some categories receive no protection at all from the p ysonality justification? (p. 339) In this interpretation I believe that Hughes is taking a narrower understanding of personality than that intended by Hegel. He seems to view property merely as the receptacle of personality rather than the means of development of personality as well. It is true, as Hughes himself argues, that the creation of some types of intellectual property is subject to greater constraints than others. For example, ideas that serve utilitarian objectives—that is, satisfy needs—must often also satisfy efficiency requirements. To the extent that such constraints exist, Hughes claims that the production of ideas reduces the opportunity for personality expression. This interpretation, it seems to me, misses the more general focus of Hegel's views on personality development as a means to overcome the narrowness of individual subjectivity. It would seem by Hegel's requirement that such an overcoming should join the individual to an ethical community that scientific discovery would contribute as much to personality development as conventionally understood artistic expression. Moreover, discoveries;in science and the practical arts certainly provide their discoverers with social recognition, a requirement for personality explicitly recognized by HegelJHughes argues that this recognition fol-
46
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
lows more forcefully from money payments made to the holders of intellectual property rights: "Recognition" involves more than lip service. If I say "this forest is your property" and then proceed to flagrantly trespass, cut your timber, and hunt your deer, I have not recognized your property rights. Similarly, verbal recognition of an intellectual property claim is not equal to the recognition implicit in a payment. Purchasers of a copyright work or licensees of a patent form a circle of people recognizing the creator as a person, (p. 349) There are several problems with this interpretation of Hegel's recognition motivation for private property. First of all, why is monetary payment an appropriate and sufficient means of providing the necessary recognition? Most scholarly work, such as that routinely published in academic journals, for example, provides no direct financial compensation to its creator at all. It does oftentimes, however, provide substantial professional recognition and even, in some cases, wide public acclaim. Second, even if it is admitted that some intellectual property is deserving of a monetary reward, what is the appropriate amount of such reward? Hughes apparently is prepared to grant full rights of monopoly exploitation inherent in copyright and patent protection. How do we know if such rights are appropriate or excessive? In cases where the original creator has alienated the property rights to a third party, what are the appropriate rewards to this new possessor?5 Should they be the same as those of the original creator? However we answer these latter two questions, it would certainly seem that we are fully outside the purview of anything related to Hegel's recognition requirement. Third, what exactly is Hughes claiming recognition for in the above-quoted passage? Clearly it is private property rights in ideas themselves rather than for personality as described by Hegel. Indeed, it is hard to understand how monopoly exploitation of intellectual property can aid in the externalization of the individual into an ethical community, particularly as the uninhibited use of such property in no way deprives the creator of the same use. To the contrary, we can cite many cases in which the free dissemination of ideas provides the opportunity of personality development for creators as well as for the beneficiaries of their creations. The argument that creators need incentive for their creations, once again, takes us into the philosophical ground tilled by the utilitarian school (at least in its Benthamite version), and we turn to a consideration of these arguments next. Intellectual Property and the Greatest Good Utilitarian arguments are by far the most popular defenses of private property and it is not surprising that they find their way into discussions of intel-
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
47
lectual property. As we have seen in the present discussion, other arguments based on right and personality sometimes appeal to utilitarian considerations to buttress weak spots in their own justificatory edifices. The most commonly encountered version of the utilitarian argument is that private property rights and their economic exploitation 'provide the necessary incentive for the production of useful knowledge. In this sense, the production of intellectual products is not regarded any differently from any other form of capitalist production. That is, the intellectual capitalist is motivated by the prospect of high returns and in their absence will turn his or her talents, time, and effort elsewhere in the economy. This reallocation of intellectual resources, it is presumed, will result in a Pareto inferior state (one that results in a net reduction of social welfare) compared to that in which intellectual property rights are established and respected. As noted earlier, I believe there is reason to doubt that the producers of ideas can realistically be characterized as intellectual capitalists who are most strongly motivated by the prospect of substantial economic profit. Even if we grant, however, that some firms employ creative thinkers for this very reason, the utilitarian justification runs up against a rather formidable and obvious logical difficulty.6 Clearly, the goal! of utility maximization is best served by the widest possible dissemination of new knowledge and the products and services derived from that knowlecge. The purpose of intellectual property rights, however, is precisely to limt this dissemination contingent . on the willingness and ability to pay. Admitt ng that idea-related production might suffer in the absence of some required reward, the important utilitarian question is, What is the minimum required reward necessary to procure the maximum dissemination of new and useful knowledge? I do not believe that any regime of private property rights in ideas or intellectually derived goods and services can be presumed to ahswfer this question. Patents, copyrights, and trademarks create monopoly power that is inconsistent with the maximization of social welfare. Moreover, when private, profit-maximizing firms are given the necessary protection to induce them to produce and market intellectual property and its derivatives, there can be no presumption that such firms will be responsive to human: need that is not effectively represented in the market by purchasing power. ^These facts constitute, then, a double incidence of market failure. The neoclassical economic response tb the problem of market failure is frequently expressed in what is known as the Coase theorem.7 According to this result, economic efficiency is maximized when agents are free to bargain and property rights are clearly specified. Ifmatters little whether the owners of such property are private individuals or a single public authority. The theorem is often applied to the problem of common public goods. In the absence of
48
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
assignable propertyrights,economic agents will have little incentive to engage in the efficient use of such resources, often leading to their overexploitation.8 There are several reasons, however, why the Coase theorem has doubtful application as a defense of private property rights in ideas. First, the need for assignable property rights does not definitely establish an argument for private property rights. There is no reason in principle why government might not efficiently allocate the use of common public goods according to some democratically chosen objective. Second, ideas are not the type of "common public goods" that the theorem has in mind. Air, water, and, in a bygone era, common pasture lands are "public goods" in the sense that they share the characteristic of nonexclusiveness of use. The need to institutionalize exclusive use is the motivation behind assigning property rights. What such goods do not share with ideas, however, is nonrivalry of use. One particular use by a particular individual of "common public goods" such as air, water, and land may indeed preclude other uses by other people. This cannot be said of intellectual "goods and services," since one person's use of an idea in no way conflicts with another's use of it. In fact, where intellectual property is concerned, it probably makes much more sense to speak of the "tragedy of the anticommons" in the manner of Heller and Eisenberg (1998).9 In this scenario, a resource (new knowledge) is subject to underuse when multiple owners of "upstream knowledge" have therightto exclude others, leaving no one with an effective privilege of "downstream" use. This circumstance is perhaps best illustrated by the recent, widely published announcements surrounding the mapping of the human genome. Private profit-seeking companies have taken out patents on thousands of DNA sequences, precluding their study by other scientists. There is a huge speculative aspect to this behavior since the patent-seeking companies are betting that by gaining control over a sequence of DNA they will eventually come to possess the entire gene of which it is a constituent part. The gene in turn could be the key to an important (and profitable) diagnostic or treatment procedure or drug. The tragedy, however, is that this sort of speculation impedes the process of scientific discovery. More typically, market failure calls out for public policy relief in the form of market regulation or the direct provision of public goods. What is clear is that some sort of market intervention seems inevitable where intellectually derived goods and services are concerned. The important question is whether this intervention takes the form of state-established monopoly rights granted to private firms to produce and distribute, or something else— for example, direct state provision or market regulation of intellectual goods and services. It is also clear that to this point much more has been accomplished in providing intellectual property rights with international applica-
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
49
tion than any other imaginable formula for treating the complex of questions surrounding knowledge-based production. The reasons for this preference are to be found in a consideration of]international political economy rather than in philosophically based justificatory arguments. Finally, it is worthwhile to observe that the case for IPRs is not well supported from the perspective of Godwinian utilitarianism, with its emphasis on distributive justice grounded in egalitarianism. Godwin would certainly regard the pursuit of knowledge and its applications as self-sufficient goals of a well-lived life, not requiring pecuniary leewards. The concept of treating knowledge and technology as commodities tp be sold rather than as the means to human liberation would be anathema to this perspective. TRIPS and the Idea of Property It is apparent that the advocates of a TRIPS agreement regard knowledge and technology as commodities to be produced by private enterprises making use of privately owned and employed resources and sold in markets that are increasingly global. If the production of high-tech outputs is differentiated from other sorts of internationally traded commodities, it might be argued, the difference wouldinvolve the substantial outlay in terms of research and development (R&D) that is required before a marketable commodity is ever offered for sale. In the absence of a strong regime of intellectual property rights, the argument follows, intellectual property entrepreneurs would not have the incentive to undertake the necessary investment in inventive activity. The result would be a reduced flow in such activity and a corresponding reduction in the level of aggregate social we] fare.10 This reduction, of course, would have to be weighed against the welfare cost associated with the exercise of monopoly power in new technology, j^ut, say the defenders of TRIPS, the net benefits of property rights enforcement are positive for all concerned. What are we to make of the assumption Ithat knowledge and technology are marketable commodities? As Perelman (1998) points out, knowledge and technology have all the aspects of public g0ods. That is, while the production of applied knowledge and technology ijnay have substantial fixed startup costs, its marginal cost is zero. That i$ to |say, once new knowledge enters the public domain, it exists for anyone to appropriate and make use of. Moreover, as already noted, knowledge has the characteristic of nonrivalry of use. Hence, as Perelman puts it, there is no scarcity value attached to knowledge. For this reason, the only way that the iinitial possessors of this would-be commodity can earn profit is to create a scarcity. Creating scarcities is precisely the objective of enforceable private property rights. This view of knowledge production stands in obvious contradiction to the
50
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
assumption that the resultant products are privately produced and sold in competitive markets. The creation of artificial scarcities via patents, licenses, trademarks, and so on, results in legally sanctioned monopoly power, which, when exercised, reduces quantity and raises prices. The argument that the opportunity to exercise market power is a necessary incentive for firms to recoup the costs of R&D is at face value plausible, but demands critical scrutiny and empirical verification. In this context, two important questions must be addressed. First, to what extent is inventive activity a function of prospective market returns? Second, to what extent are the fixed costs of R&D really privately borne? I have argued that the history of creative human activity does not suggest that the creative impulse is bound, or even largely motivated, by the desire for monetary gain. Scientists, artists, and inventors engage in creation and exploration primarily to give expression to their personalities. Economic exploitation of a novel idea typically occurs after the inventive or creative act. It is implausible, then, that failure to strengthen IPR regimes in peripheral countries will have a negative effect on the rate of innovation in center countries. Innovation will respond to local conditions in center countries. The adoption of center country innovations will proceed at a more rapid rate in the periphery in the absence of strong IPRs that limit the application of innovations or that require high fees and/or prices to be paid for them." On this basis it is hard to see how the uniformity of IPRs sought by the TRIPS agreement would advance social welfare. The development of new ideas into useful commodities is undoubtedly more closely tied to the prospect of material reward. A reasonable case could be made, then, that strong IPRs are required to ensure a flow of such rewards. It needs to be remembered, however, in assessing the likely magnitude of the incentive, that the costs of R&D include a substantial nonprivate, or social, component. Public universities and research institutes, public spending on military and nonmilitary technologies, and public spending on primary and secondary education are all related to the technological capacity of a society and reflect the public good aspects of new knowledge. Correspondingly, such spending ought to reflect the public's claim on the fruits of technological progress even when these may emanate from private enterprises.12 The political economic reality in this age of neoliberalism is that taxsupported research tends to favor subsidization of corporations at the expense of consumer-tax payers. Gorman (2000) reports on the specific case of the pharmaceutical companies who have benefited from several recent changes in U.S. patent law. The Bayh-Dole Act of 1980 made it legal to transfer exclusive licensing rights to private companies for any new scientific discoveries arising from federally financed research. This law was augmented six
THE IDEOLOGY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
51
years later by additional legislation that permitted government researchers at federal laboratories to make deals with corporations to transfer their marketable findings. The result is that important drugs (such as AZT for the treatment of AIDS), although developed by federal research monies, are marketed by private companies (Glaxco Wellcome) at excessively high prices. Given the current magnitude and pace Of scientific breakthroughs and technological change, there is a correspondingly rapid race to capture the real, potential, and merely imagined spoils via the multiplication of new patents. The process has the earmarks of the land rush that characterized frontier settlement in nineteenth-century America. The [problem, as we noted earlier in citing Heller and Eisenberg, is that the new patents themselves inhibit the creative process that might result in additional welfare-enhancing technical progress. This is not an entirely new problem, given that the pace of technical innovation has long been dictated by the desire of capitalist interests to capture as fully as possible the rents associated with their given stock of intellectual and physical capital. Insofar as much of the new science relates to such fundamental areas of human concern as health care and food production and security, however, there is an especially urgent need for this science to be conducted in a manner appropriate to our interests as a species and not narrowly in the interests of profit. The TRIPS agreement does nothing that directly responds to these general interests and, as suggested, may operate against them. In fact, in some of the important areas of technological development that the TRIPS agreement is most concerned to protect, such as pharmaceuticals, it is arguable that competition is exceedingly wasteful. With several large companies each competing t :> develop the same set of new wonder drugs, firms are dedicating billions pf dollars to redundant R&D. The TRIPS agreement adds greater incentive to this wastefulness by increasing the potential payoff to the winners in the race to patent new drugs. Summary and Conclusion The main arguments of this chapter can; be summarized as follows: traditional justificatory defenses of exclusive] private property rights apply very weakly, if at all, to intellectual property, ilockean and Hegelian (personality) justifications are found ultimately to appeal to essentially utilitarian arguments. Utilitarian arguments themselves, however, fail insofar as exclusionary property rights cannot be a priori presumed to promote social welfare, particularly in a world comprising of manifest market imperfections and inequality in the distribution of income; and wealth. It is evident that several important questions raised in this chapter appeal to empirical evidence for their answers. Do the producers of intellectual goods,
52
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
for example, respond primarily to material incentives? Does the flow of innovation change as the legal regime governing intellectual property changes? Is there good reason to expect that these responses are invariant across differences in national income levels and cultures? Economists and others have investigated these and related questions but have not arrived, to my knowledge, at any definitive results.13 Needless to say, however, the lack of widespread agreement on the empirical evidence has not served as a deterrent to the establishment of the TRIPS agreement to protect intellectual property. As will be described in detail in Chapter 5, this establishment was largely the result of efforts made by the U.S. Trade Representative (USTR) on behalf of such patent-sensitive transnational corporations as Pfizer Chemical and IBM.14 These and other companies launched an educational campaign under the aegis of the GATT's Advisory Committee on Trade Policy and Negotiations (ACTPN). This effort was directed at the USTR as well as to members of Congress to get them to understand the benefits that would follow from a stronger global IPR regime. The campaign was successful. The USTR made acceptance of the TRIPS a condition for U.S. participation in the Uruguay Round of the GATT talks and also threatened recalcitrant alleged violators of U.S. IPRs with unilateral sanctions. It borders on the trivial to note that justificatory arguments of the sort we have considered in this chapter are typically ideological rationalizations for the real political power wielded by groups whose interests they serve. It should not for this reason be concluded, however, that the arguments are themselves trivial. The strength or weakness of such ideological rationalizations could be a critically important determinant to the success or failure of an international agreement insofar as they confer apparent legitimacy. While advocates for popular change are not well funded and influential in the official corridors of national and international policy making, they must themselves be able to construct justifications for the positions they criticize as well as espouse.
Intellectual Property and Positivist Economic Science
As noted in Chapter 1, the economics of intellectual property rights (IPRs) is characterized by what Keith Maskus jterms "dancing the dual distortion" (2000, p. 27). By this Maskus refers to the following facts. IPRs are exclusive rights granted to the creators of knowledge-based commodities to market their creations. This grant is deemed necessary in order for the creators to engage in creative activity and production. The grant of these same rights, however, also confers on their possessors monopoly power that can be used to limit access to the creation, resulting in higher than socially optimal prices. There can be no general a priori presumption as to the net welfare consequences of this trade-off. The issue is further complicated when we turn to the open economy and recognize that the world is composed of a variety of national experiences that differ in terms of their needs for and ability to produce knowledge-based goods and services. Not surprisingly, developed countries such as the United States, Japan, and the European nation;; are strong advocates for strengthening the global IPR regime, while the less developed countries face considerable increases in the cost of imported goods, services, and technology transfer as a result of such strengthening. In between is a third group whose position is ambiguous. This group, which includes India, Brazil, Mexico, and several East Asian nations, have in common with the poorer countries a need to access and imitate innovations that emanate from the technologically advanced parts of the world. They are also characterized by increasing, in some cases quite sophisticated, capacities for technological innovation and product development. Correspondingly,;they are characterized by constituencies that both oppose and support stronger IPRs. Notwithstanding their welfare ambiguity, at least from a theoretical point of view, global IPRs have recently bjeen given institutional support and legitimacy in the form of the trade-related intellectual property rights (TRIPS) agreement. The TRIPS was negotiated as a; part of the Uruguay Round of the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) largely at the insistence of the United 53
54
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
States, which made the agreement a requirement for its participation in the multilateral discussions. The TRIPS agreement establishes minimum standards for the protection of intellectual property (IP) that all signatory nations must meet. It represents an advance over its historical predecessors (e.g., the Paris Convention on patents, the Berne Convention on copyrights) in some important ways. TRIPS broadens the field of coverage of patent rights to include new areas of technology involving chemical and pharmaceutical products and processes, food products, integrated circuit design, and breeders' rights for new plant varieties. Patent durations have been lengthened to twenty years, which is the standard under U.S. law but substantially longer than for most other countries, including those of the developed world. Moreover, the burden of proof in infringement cases is reversed such that defendants must demonstrate that they are not in violation of protected innovations. The TRIPS agreement also goes well beyond previous international agreements and institutions for the protection of IP in its enforcement powers.1 The agreement provides for border controls, preliminary injunctions, seizure and/or destruction of illegal goods, and civil and criminal penalties. Moreover, disputes involving the agreement will be subject to the settlements procedures applied to alleged trade violations brought before the World Trade Organization (WTO). While most developed countries are already in substantial compliance with the minimum standards called for by the TRIPS, the legal and administrative costs of bringing the IP protection systems of most poor countries into compliance are expected to be quite substantial. Under the circumstances, it might well be asked why the poorer, less developed nations would agree to the inclusion of the TRIPS agreement as part of the multilateral trade negotiation infrastructure. As already suggested, part of the answer is that improving intellectual property rights derives some support from a segment of the populations of poorer countries that is directly involved in research and development (R&D) and product innovation. A far more compelling explanation, however, is provided by the political and economic circumstances surrounding the issue. It may be fairly argued that the developed nations, led by the United States, proffered both a carrot and a stick to induce the less developed countries to agree to the TRIPS. The carrot involved further liberalization of trade in areas of particular importance to the poorer countries; the stick was the explicit threat of unilateral sanctions leveled at violators of national IPR law. Inasmuch as national standards, particularly those of the United States, could be regarded as more demanding than those embodied in the TRIPS, the decision to comply was all the more obvious. It should not be thought, however, that the TRIPS agreement is written in •ete. As is true of any international agreement, it is subject to review, dment, and even, possibly, revocation. It necessarily follows, then, that
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE
55
a continuous examination of the agreement's costs and benefits to its signatory nations is required. The purpose of this chapter is to provide a critical examination of the available economic evidence to date on the welfare implications of strengthening the global IPR regime, particularly as they apply to the less developed countries. The chapter first considers briefly the main theoretical argument in favor of strengthening the international regime as well as the counterargument that such action is inimical to th $ welfare of poor nations. The bulk of the chapter is concerned with what the existing empirical studies have to tell us about these issues. ! Positivist "versus Critical Method The title of this chapter refers to positivist economic science and the reader may reasonably wonder precisely what this expression refers to and how positivist economic science differs from other kinds of economic science and evidence. The distinction between the modifiers positivist and critical is not peculiar to economics and, in fact, has broad application across the social sciences.2 In general, positivism refers to a research tradition based on the following assumptions: (1) a strict separation between the investigator as subject and the object of investigation; (2) a commitment to the search for evidence in support of universally valid laws and generalizations; (3) a preference for methodological abstraction as revealed, for example, in the construction and use of theoretical models; (4) reliance on quantitative measures for key variables and their use in probabilistic tests of hypotheses. In general, the positivist social science method cerives its inspiration from the success enjoyed by eighteenth- and nine :eenth-century natural sciences, especially physics, that essentially developed along very similar methodological principles.3 Many critics of positivism take exception to virtually each of these assumptions. Those who adopt a "historici >t" methodological stance, for example, take exception to positivism's strict subject/object dichotomy as well as its claims to the universality of its laws.* Cox expresses these objections to positivism in the following terms: The historicist approach to social science does not envisage any general or universally valid laws which can be explained by the development of appropriate generally applicable theories. For historicism, both human nature and the structures of human interaction change, if only very slowly. History is the process of their changing. One cannot therefore speak of "laws" in any generally valid sense transcending historical eras, nor of
56
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
structures as outside of or prior to history. Regularities in human activities may indeed be observed within particular eras, and thus the positivist approach can be fruitful within defined historical limits, though not with the universal pretensions it aspires to. (1986, pp. 243-244) As this passage makes clear, Cox does not reject outright the potential of positivism to present evidence of a type. Rather he rejects the notion that any particular positivist evidence can have universal applicability. Failing to recognize the indeterminacy of human subjects and of the institutions that are constructed by human activity and that constrain human behavior, positivism is ahistorical. As such, positivist research results can neither claim universality nor provide explanations for historical change. The point of critical theory, by contrast, is, in part, precisely to examine the institutional constraints within which people make choices and also to study the process by which institutions themselves are changed. By extension, then, it also examines the process by which human response itself changes. Far less, therefore, is taken as "given" by a critical social science approach than by a positivist one. Putting the difference that separates positivist and critical social science another way, it is fair to say that the critical approach is dynamic insofar as it is concerned with the development of social scientific categories, while positivism is static inasmuch as it treats these same categories as abstract universals. Again, the point here is not to delegitimate positivism, but rather to delimit the range of its relevance. Cox suggests the circumstances under which either the positivist or the critical approach would be an appropriate choice: In choosing between the two approaches, much depends upon one's idea of what theory is for. I have suggested two broad purposes corresponding to the two approaches: a problem-solving purpose, i.e., tacidy assuming the permanency of existing structures, which is served by the positivist approach; and a critical purpose envisaging the possibilities of structural transformation which is served by the historicist approach. The usefulness of all theory, whether problem-solving or critical, is in its applicability to particular situations. But whereas problem-solving theory assimilates particular situations to general rules, providing a kind of programmed method for dealing with them, critical theory seeks out the development potential within the particular. (1986, p. 244) The research that is reviewed in the following sections, then, is based on a problem-solving approach to the question of the economic impact of privately held, exclusionary property rights in intellectual property. It is an approach that takes as given the prevalence of capitalist social relations of
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE
57
production as well as the endowments of social, economic, and political advantages that these relations entail. Its concerns are largely with productive and allocative efficiency considered from the perspective of static social welfare. I argue that the evidence presented by this research is worthy of consideration even by those who are otherwise inclined to adopt a critical theoretical stance, among whom I would include myself. This is so for two reasons. First, it is a fact that the world as it exists is indeed dominated by capitalist social relations of production, precisely as is assumed by positivist economic science. Without accepting the prehensions of some that this fact is universal and immutable, there would seem to be inherent intellectual value in exploring regularities of human behavior within this particular historical context. Second, and more importantly, the body of evidence presented by positivist economic science is frequently called upon HI support of the case in favor of the TRIPS agreement. It is an important pillar of May's knowledge structure as it applies to the TRIPS debate. Familiarity with this evidence by those who take a critical attitude toward the agreement then would seem imperative. Theoretical Approaches The basic theoretical justification for TRIPS does not differ in any important way from the arguments that have long; been advanced for the defense of patent and copyright protection in general. While economists have recognized the potential for monopoly abuse of the market power conferred by such protection, it is held that in the absence of exclusive rights to exploit the products of inventiveness the rates of both scientific discovery and innovation will lag, with negative welfare consequences all around. Recognizing the second-best nature of such devices, much of the early theoretical work done by economists has focused on the optimal length of patent and copyright protection, the costs of patent races, and the effects of patents on the rate of technological diffusion.5 Nordhaus (1969,1972) and Scherer (1972), for example, have determined that optimal patent length depends inversely on the elasticity of demand for innovations. This is so since greater elasticity is associated with greater welfare gain derived from increases in consumer surplus.6 Inasmuch as demand elasticities differ across innovations, it would seem that a standard, fixed term length of patent would not be socially efficient. The gains of variable patent lengths, however, have to be measured relative to the administrative costs saved by adoption of a uniform, fixed term. An issue of particular concern as it bears on patent races is the potential for costly duplication of research efforts. Beck (1981) and Dasgupta and
58
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Stiglitz (1980) have identified conditions under which industrial R&D may exceed the socially optimal levels. Dasgupta (1987) makes a distinction in this instance between basic scientific research and development of innovations. Whereas inventors tend to see innovations in terms of their potential for profit, scientists see their work in terms of contributions to the body of knowledge. The former predictably are far more concerned than the latter with capturing the rents that patents and/or secrecy would provide. As several authors have recently pointed out, however, even university scientists have in recent years become more concerned about the proprietary character of their scientific findings. Knowledge diffusion may also respond to the breadth and depth of IPRs. Innovators will be inspired to promote the absorption of their new products and processes to the extent that the legal superstructure provides them with the incentives for doing so (Burstein 1984). Even compulsory licensing of patented innovations may diffuse knowledge if adequate royalties are provided. Certainly each of these issues has potential importance for less developed countries (LDCs). Patent length, efficient research, and diffusion of technology all have potentially important implications for increasing the standards of living of the majority of people in the world, especially those who are confined to countries where those standards are now particularly low. It is not obvious, however, that the solution to global poverty reduction lies in the direction of making more rigorous the global IPR regime. A number of theoretical studies have focused on the welfare losses imposed on LDCs by tighter IPR standards. Chin and Grossman (1990) find that the welfare interests of the technology-producing and -exporting countries stand in fundamental contradiction to those of the consuming and importing countries. The welfare gains to the first set of countries derive from the oligopolistic pricing power exerted by the producers of knowledge-based outputs. This power is partly exercised in a manner designed to force market exit from the industry by the dominant firms—that is, strategic predation. For the second group of countries, the failure to provide protection to IP improves welfare under certain plausible circumstances. Among these circumstances is that the share in consumption of the innovation of the importing country does not exceed some particularly high threshold level—that is, 88 percent. That this rather demanding criterion will be met is not very likely, given that innovations that originate in developed countries usually respond to market conditions typical of those same countries.7 Chin and Grossman also consider the possibilities for cooperation between the two sets of countries. If the welfare gains enjoyed by the producer/ exporter countries are sufficiently large, then the possibility exists that the consumer/importer countries could be convinced to provide IP protection if
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 59
these gains are shared. Such an "efficient bargaining with compensation" strategy improves global welfare, the authors show, when the productivity of R&D is sufficiently high. For comparatively minor innovations, however, the LDCs are better off imitating innovations originating in the developed countries rather than providing protection. Similar conclusions are reached when the possibility is introduced of licensing otherwise protected IP. The welfare ambiguities of strengthening IPRs are also brought into sharp relief in an article by Subramanian (1991). Making the usual distinctions between developed producer/exporter and less developed consumer/importer nations, as well as between static and dynamic benefits of IP protection, the author notes the high probability of conflict involving IP that is easily imitated. The poorer importing countries,^ obviously, will prefer low levels of protection, while the developed exporters with press for higher levels. Lower levels are the likely outcome under two circumstances. The first is when dynamic: benefits are inconsequential, leaving only the static welfare gains to be realized as a result of free riding. When dynamic benefits are important, low levels of protection are still to be expected in the case where the importing country is too small for its particular IPR regime to have any real effect on the producer/exporter decision to engage in R&D. Another element given consideration by Subramanian, but usually overlooked by other theoretical treatments, s the possibility of discriminatory IP protection. In countries possessing an indigenous R&D capacity, it might make sense to provide domestic inventors and producers with patent protection but deny the same treatment to foreigners. Under the reasonable assumption that the domestic producer i s a relatively high-cost one, there is bound to be some sacrifice of consumer surplus. The author argues, however, that this loss could be more than compensated for by the realization by the domestic producer/inventor of the profits associated with the new product or process. There is also the possibility that providing discriminatory protection to national producers will generate greater technological spillover effects than those apt to flow from even lower-cost foreign producers of the same or similar outputs. This case ther amounts to an "infant-industry" argument for discriminatory IPR protection. There are some cases in which the interests of the two sets of countries are likely to be congruent rather than cohflictual. One such case occurs when the new knowledge-based production is not easily imitated and requires the cooperation of the developed country's inventors to facilitate the transfer of technology. The other case occurs when a group of consumer/importer countries is able to collectively coordinate and strengthen their IPR regimes so as to induce producer/exporters to develop new products and processes that are especially coveted. For the poorer countries, such innovations might be drugs
LLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Topical diseases such as malaria, or types of seeds and other inputs That are particularly suitable to tropical and semitropical climates. Deardorff (1992) also argues that extending the reach of IP protection beyond those countries where it finds original support does not necessarily improve welfare. Proceeding from the usual assumptions that innovations originating from some countries find markets around the world, he constructs a model that measures the gain in welfare from an increased flow of new products and processes against the losses emanating from the distortions of monopoly pricing. The problem, as Deardorff sees it, is that the flow of innovations attendant on the extension of patent protection suffers from diminishing returns as more countries are included. At some point, the cost of providing IP protection for existing inventions will outweigh the benefits of providing the incentive to produce new ones. Even if global welfare does improve, there can be no presumption that the welfare of the importing countries will not decline. Once again, a determining factor here is the proportion of the market that resides in the innovation-importing regions. If this is not sufficiently high, then the likelihood is that these regions will suffer a deterioration in welfare as the IPR regime is strengthened. Deardorff arrives at the conclusion that for these reasons the poorest countries of the world should not be held to the same standards for IPRs as the rest of the world. In a dynamic general equilibrium model, Helpman (1993) orice again divides the world into two distinct regions, one that innovates (the North) and the other that imitates (the South). Here the author identifies four avenues via which a tighter international IPR regime would work its welfare effects. These are identified as (1) terms of trade, (2) product composition, (3) availability of products, and (4) intertemporal allocation of consumption. The terms of trade and product composition effects are straightforward. Goods that are not imitated by the South are produced by the North under monopoly conditions and are correspondingly priced at a markup over northern wages, which are taken, reasonably, to be higher than southern wages. An increase in the strength of IPRs reduces southern imitation, resulting in an increase in the proportion of global output produced under such monopoly conditions and, correspondingly, in the level of northern prices relative to southern prices. Strengthening IPRs hurts southern workers two ways here. First, the share of its output from manufacturing declines as such production shifts to the North. Second, the overall terms of trade shift against the South. It is notable that in Helpman's model the welfare of northern workers may also be reduced by the same increase in monopoly power wielded by northern producers under a tighter IPR regime. This is so since these workers are also consumers of goods whose prices rise as the rate of imitation falls. Since the North generally also realizes an increase in monopoly profits under stronger IPRs as well
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 61
as improved terms of trade, however, it is not a priori clear what the net welfare consequences will be. j In terms of the availability of products, Helpman recognizes that strengthening intellectual property protection may have an effect on the rate of innovation. The important finding in this regard according to the author's model is that the initial effect of stronger IPRs bn the rate of innovation is positive but that the longer-term effect may be negative. This occurs because stronger IPRs lengthen the expected tenure of a monopolistic supplier in the market while reducing the incentive to innovate, A reduction in innovations is associated with a reduction in the number of available products and, therefore, a reduction in welfare. The negative welfare impact is especially evident for the South, which does not share in monopoly profits associated with innovation. Finally, Helpman shows that even though a temporarily increased rate of innovation may improve product availability and welfare for the South, these improvements are never sufficient to compensate the region for its longer-term losses. The reason for this is that a high rate of subjective discount will result in a larger long-run decline and a smaller short-run increase in the rate of innovation (p. 1266). It is clear from this brief summary of the limited theoretical literature that the welfare consequences of strengthening IPRs are, at best, ambiguous and that there is significant reason, moreover, to believe that the interests of the more developed, innovation-producing rations stand in conflict with those of the less developed, importing or imitating nations. Consideration of the available, though also limited, empirical literature may shed additional light on the debate. Before turning to these studies, however, it may also be useful to examine the TRIPS in light of the findings of the above-reviewed theoretical work. To do this, it will be useful, in turn, to review the specific content of the TRIPS agreement as it applies to patents. The TRIPS agreement provides patent protection for products and processes in all fields of technology, including biotechnology and animal and plant breeders' rights, with some exceptions (Maskus 2000). The minimum length of patent protection is twenty years from the date of application. This minimum period is longer than that provided for by the national laws of virtually every developed country with the exception of the United States, where twenty years is fairly standard. Exclusive rights to production and import are granted to patent holders. Patent holders are not required to carry out domestic production of patented goods and are not required to grant licenses to others for this purpose. Under certain circumstances related to health, nutrition, or some other social purpose, temporary compulsory licenses may be required of a patent holder, though in these cases the license grantor must be provided with adequate, market-based remuneration. The
62
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 63
adjudication of cases involving the alleged violation of patent rights places the burden of proof on defendants, who must demonstrate that their product or process does not infringe on an existing patent right. While implementation of the TRIPS agreement allows for a grace period of five years for developing and transition countries, the agreement when fully operational is expected to apply on a nondiscriminatory, most-favorednation basis for all WTO members. TRIPS enforcement will require both civil and criminal penalties as well as border measures. The standard WTO dispute settlement function is expected to be applied to TRIPS cases. The cost of bringing national law into compliance and constructing the legal and administrative infrastructure where it does not currently exist in particular countries is anticipated to be quite high. Given these characteristics of the agreement and in light of the theoretical considerations described above, the relevant question to consider is, Is the TRIPS agreement a good deal for the less developed countries? I believe that the tentative answer to this question must be that it is not a good deal for the LDCs. The reasons are as follows: First, it is clear that the TRIPS is primarily motivated by a desire of the United States and other industrialized countries (or, to speak more accurately, the transnational corporations based in these countries) to secure for themselves monopoly power in the production and sale of certain commodities and processes in the global economy at large. These commodities and processes are knowledge-intensive ones and already have large, established markets in the developed countries themselves. While the agreement seeks greater harmonization of IPR standards across the legal systems of the developed countries, it is clear that the greatest efforts at legal and administrative reform must come from the middle and less developed countries. The import of this observation is that the new goods, services, and processes likely to be the objects of TRIPS are not those that are predominately consumed in the poorer countries of the world. The small share of the markets for innovations in poor, and even middle developed, countries is also exacerbated by income inequality and the limited effective demands typical of such countries. Hence the requirement for welfare improvement identified by Chin and Grossman that the importing/imitating country account for a large share of consumption of the protected commodities is unlikely to be met.
Third, the most-favored-nation (MFN) treatment requirement of the TRIPS agreement renders irrelevant the suggestion by Subramanian that discriminatory IP protection in favor of domestic innovators and imitators may be a welfare-superior alternative for the less developed countries. Moreover, the MFN provision of the TRIPS should have precisely the effect predicted by Helpman—that is, strengthening thej international IPR regime should operate to shift knowledge-based production toward those countries that already possess a comparative advantage in technology. In other words, the TRIPS agreement fails to recognize the applicability of an infant-industry argument to knowledge-based productio|n. The MFN provision also obviously precludes the possibility of £)eardorrr's suggestion that a globally welfaresuperior approach to IPRs would exclude the poorest countries from the requirements imposed by the strengthened international regime. In fact, as suggested above, the TRIPS is accurately understood as precisely an effort to bring LDCs into compliance with; behavior that is generally accepted by the developed countries. Finally, as argued by Subramanian, whereas welfare gains by the LDCs are more likely to occur as a result of stronger IPRs if they inspire innovation rather than imitation, the TRIPS agreement was motivated precisely in order to provide stronger global protection to industries whose outputs have been found easy to imitate. Intellectual property is, in fact, often defined as involving commodities characterized b y highfixedcosts but very low, or zero, marginal costs of production. It is precisely the ease of imitation that has given rise to the desire to strengther the global IPR regime. It is to be expected, then, that such a strengthening will result in transforming the welfare gains associated with imitation into producers' rents. This analysis, therefore, seems to remonstrate the following tentative conclusions. A strengthening of global IPRs in the form of the TRIPS agreement would be ambiguous in its effect on global welfare and, probably detrimental to the welfare interests of LDCs. Before we can remove the "tentative" qualifier from these conclusions^ however, it would be useful to consider the relevant empirical studies that have been conducted.
Second, the restrictions on compulsory licensing called for by the TRIPS agreement will limit the potential dynamic benefits associated with technological transfer, knowledge spillovers, and other externalities. Such potential dynamic effects are also limited by the stipulation in the TRIPS that internationally harmonized patent law may not require local production of the protected goods and processes.
Obviously, one way to address theoretically ambiguous results is via empirical investigation. The issues of the size and incidence of standard, static welfare effects are only part of the challenge to empirical researchers concerned with the economic impact of IPRs. Equally, or even more, important are the impacts of IPRs on rates of innovation, technology transfer, skill acquisition, foreign direct investment, and international trade. The empirical literature,
Empirical Studies
64
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
while still young, has addressed each of these issues to a certain extent. The earliest studies (Stalson 1987; U.S. International Trade Commission 1988; Feinberg and Rousslang 1990) focused on the potential welfare impact of stronger IPRs for the developed, innovating countries. Not surprisingly, these studies have generally found that the failure to enforce the existing international agreements regulating IPRs as codified by the Paris and Berne Conventions cost the developed countries billions of dollars in lost revenues. Yet, when Maskus (1990) extended the Feinberg and Rousslang study to include the LDCs, he concluded that global welfare declined notwithstanding the increase in profits realized by firms who could sell their protected innovations at higher prices. Empirical Measures oflPR Strength Cross-country empirical analysis of the economic impact of IP protection faces the formidable problem of devising measures of the strength of IPRs in a uniform way for a large number of countries. Early studies addressed this issue merely by noting which countries had in fact endorsed the standard international conventions without paying much attention to the degree of actual enforcement. A more sophisticated measure was devised by Rapp and Rozek (1990), who came up with an index of IP protection (here referred to as the RR index). The index is calculated for a nation based on the existence of patent law along with the exclusions allowed by the law. The index does not take into consideration a nation's ability to enforce the law or the law's actual effectiveness. The range of values for the index is 1 to 5, with 1 indicating the virtual absence of patent protection and 5 indicating a system of enforcement and protection close to that found in the United States. A comparison of Rapp and Rozek's index with per capita income clearly shows a direct relationship between the two.8 High-income countries (above US$7,000 for 1985) have an average value on the index of 4.14, middle-income countries (US$2,500-$7,000) have an average of 2.62, and low-income countries (below US$2,500) have an average of 2.46. A more recent attempt to quantify IPRs was undertaken by Ginarte and Park in 1997. Like Rapp and Rozek, Ginarte and Park calculate an index of IPR protection by examining the patent law of individual countries. Their index (here referred to as the GP index) goes beyond the RR approach by examining in greater detail the particular aspects of the law, including duration of protection, extent of coverage, membership in international patent agreements, provisions for loss of protection, and enforcement measures. Moreover, Ginarte and Park make an attempt to assess the degree of strength of the law by considering such matters as the availability of preliminary in-
65
Table 3.1 IPR Index Scores
Full sample N Average Median CV Increases Decreases High-income N Average Median CV Increases Decreases Mid-income N Average Median CV Increases Decreases Low-income N Average Median CV Increases Decreases
RR1984
GP1985
GP1990
GP1995
116 2.90 3 0.49 n.a. n.a.
108 2.44 2.52 0.39 n.a. n.a.
109 2.45 2.52 0.40 9 4
116 2.73 2.71 0.32 34 3
27 4.14 4 0.26 n.a. n.a.
26 3.37 3.32 0.19 n.a. n.a.
28 3.43 3.32 0.23 5 1
30 3.70 3.86 0.17 15 1
33 2.62 2 0.41 n.a. n.a.
27 2.24 2.26 0.29 n.a. n.a.
27 2.29 2.01 0.30 2 2
34 2.54 2.61 0.23 13 1
56 2.46 2 0.56 n.a. n.a.
55 2.11 2.41 0.44 n.a. n.a.
54 2.12 2.41 0.44 2 1
52 2.33 2.57 0.33 6 1
Source: Maskus (2000) , p. 95. Reprinted with permission
junctions, reversibility of burden of proof, and contributory infringement actions. No attempt is made by the GP index, however, to gauge the degree of enforcement. Values are assigned to tie various subcomponents in such a manner that the overall index measures from 0 to 5, with 0 indicating, as in the RR index, the complete absence of IPR protection and 5 indicating maximum protection. The GP index was also calculated for 1985 and 1990 and recently updated for 1995, thus permitting the ability to assess improvement or deterioration in individual countries' IPR regime. Table 3.1, replicated from Maskus (2000), summarizes both the RR and GP index scores for the three categories of countries described above. It is notable, once again, from data on the GP index that there exists a direct relationship between this measure and the level of per capita income
66
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
as it is identified in the three groups of countries. This is entirely in keeping with the frequently repeated observation that more developed countries possess both the technical means to support research and development as well as the markets to give incentive to product and process innovations. As in the case of the RR measure, we find for the GP index that the difference between average index scores separating the middle-income and low-income groups of countries is quite small for the 1984-85 period. Finally, it is notable that the GP index shows increases for all groups of countries over the 1985-95 decade. The increases are particularly dramatic between 1990 and 1995—an interval that includes the negotiation of the Uruguay Round of GATT and the introduction of the TRIPS agreement. Hypothesis Tests Positivist economic methodology, having established a means by which to measure the phenomenon that it considers to be central to its investigation, proceeds by specifying a model that will yield hypotheses that are testable in the statistical sense. In this subsection we shall consider a variety of such testable hypotheses that economists have considered especially important in the discussion of IPRs and economic development. Trade The first specific empirical relationship to be examined here concerns the impact of IPRs on trade flows between the developed and less developed countries. Maskus and Penubarti (1995) pose the question as follows: Do differential patent laws influence international trade flows? They note the theoretical ambiguity of conflicting "market expansion" and "market power" effects. The first of these occurs when stronger patent rights reduce the cost of exports of knowledge-based goods and services. The second occurs when the monopoly power conferred by patents allows firms to restrict exports in the interest of profit maximization. To test the relative strength of these effects, the authors specify an empirical version of an international trade model first developed by Helpman and Krugman (1985). The empirical model expresses bilateral gross imports as a function of the following variables: production of the exporting country, size of market of the importing country, importer's per capita income, and measures of trade resistance such as tariff rates. The model is augmented by the inclusion of a measure of patent strength—in this case, the RR index. Data for exporters are for the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD) countries while importers are represented by a data set for
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE
67
seventy-seven developed and less developed countries. The model is estimated over a pooled data set for twenty-nine categories of manufactured goods as well as separately for each of the twenty-nine industries. Also, the model is estimated by disaggregating the pooled data set into patent-sensitive and patent-insensitive groups. For the largest, pooled data set, Maskus and Penubarti's regression results show a positive and statistically significant result between patent strength and imports. When the data set is disaggregated by industry, however, no such statistically significant relationship between these variables is found among those industries identified as patent-sensitive, although several of the patent-insensitive industries reveal the positive (and significant) relationship. These findings suggest that for patent-sensitive industries the market power effect of stronger patent protection across countries dominates the market expansion effect and vice versa for patent-insensitive industries. One is tempted to conclude from these results that if the goal of the TRIPS agreement is to promote international trade, the agreement ought to be extended only to those industries that are patent-insensitive. The paradox is obvious inasmuch as pressure for the agreement emanates precisely from industries that are in fact patent-sensitive. The authors also estimate a specification of their model that allows for interaction effects between level of development and strength of patent protection. In this specification, the results reveal several industries whose import volumes respond positively to stronger patent rights, particularly for larger developing nations. This is also a potentially interesting result when considered in the context of the TRIPS agreement. The agreement, as noted, seeks virtually universal harmonization of IPRs and, beyond a modest grace period for the very poorest countriesj does not differentiate among more, less, and least developed nations. The MFN approach under which the WTO operates does not discriminate either between nations according to their sizes, levels of development, nor their threats to imitate otherwise patentable goods, services, and productive processes. Ins ofar as such characteristics are important determinants of the market expansion versus market power effects of stronger patent rights, the TRIPS agreement would seem to be an inefficient instrument for promoting trade. A more recent but similar study was conducted by Smith (1999), who poses the question "Are weak patent rights a barrier to US exports?" U.S. state-level data are employed in an estimable gravity model of export performance. The gravity model is specified with the following explanatory variables: per capita income of exporters (states) and importers (countries), the populations of exporters and importers, distance between them, and tariff rates. This framework is augmented by the inclusion of patent right/dummy
68
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
variable interaction terms to test the interesting hypotheses regarding the effects of patent rights on trade. Two alternative sets of dummy variables are chosen to test different hypotheses. The first set identifies different levels of development, while the second identifies different levels of imitation threat. Both the RR and GP indexes of patent strength are employed in the analysis, with very similar results, according to the author, although she reports only those employing the RR measure.9 The results of Smith's empirical analysis show that the strength of patent rights (PR) matters for U.S. exports for only one of the four development groups she identifies, the lower middle income group.10 This group covers 30 percent of the total sample of ninety-six countries. The other patent right/ development group interaction terms turn out to be negative in sign wherever statistical significance is indicated. Thus the market expansion effect seems to dominate only in the case of this particular group of importers, while the market power effect prevails in the other groups, or neither effect outweighs the other. Additional regressions are run that replace the PR/development level terms with PR/threat of imitation interaction effects. Threat of imitation is measured by an index constructed on the basis of data taken from UNESCO to represent a nation's research capabilities and from the United Nations Human Development Report (2001) on educational attainment. Again the countries are divided into four groups ranging from high to low imitative ability. The regression results show, not surprisingly, that the market power effect dominates in the case of the weakest threat of imitation while the market expansion effect dominates in the strongest imitation group. For the intermediate threat to imitate groups, the results are ambiguous in sign and lack statistical significance. It is interesting to note that there are but four countries in Smith's sample that belong to each of the two groups that her empirical analysis identifies as trade susceptible (in a positive sense) to increasing patent strength. These countries are Bolivia, Romania, Tonga, and Turkey, which together represent only 5.5 percent of the LDCs in the analysis." Smith also estimates the effect of stronger patent rights on the volume of U.S. exports and finds that this volume is likely to increase in the case of countries with strong imitative abilities but currently weak rights, and to decrease in the case of countries with weak imitative abilities and weak rights. Again, none of this is surprising. What is rather remarkable, however, is the author's estimate that the combined effect of increasing global patent protection to the levels envisioned by the TRIPS agreement is likely to reduce U.S. exports by anywhere from 2.6 to 5.4 percent in the most patent-sensitive industries over the next ten years. That is, overall, the market power effects
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 69
are likely to dominate the market expansion effects by a substantial amount for patent-sensitive U.S. exports. A priori there is no reason that we should expect much different outcomes from other countries that produce and export knowledge-based outputs. Direct Foreign Investment A second question that researchers have attempted to investigate empirically in recent years concerns the relationship between the strength of a nation's IPR regime and its ability to attract direct foreign investment (DFI). The connection between IPRs and DFI is potentially important insofar as the latter is one way that technology may be transferred between nations. It is not necessarily clear, however, precisely how this relationship would work. On the one hand, the perception by investors that the IPR regime is strong or improved may reduce the perceived riskiness or cost of an investment. Risk is reduced when the probabilities are reduced that proprietary knowledge and techniques will be appropriated without compensation. Costs are reduced when firms do not have to;take extraordinary steps to protect such knowledge and techniques. On the other hand, DFI is sometimes viewed by multinational firms as a secpnd-best strategy by which to take advantage of their specific assets and advantages and one that relates negatively to the strength of a country's IPRs. For example, if it is true that export of knowledge-based commodities is discouraged by weakness in IPRs, as is sometimes alleged, then EFI may provide the firm with the opportunity to service a market and exploit its advantages while maintaining arms-length control over the dissem nation of its product and processes. Similarly, DFI may be regarded as preferable to direct licensing of a technology for the same reasons of closer c ontrol. A recent attempt to shed empirical light on the relationship is undertaken by Lee and Mansfield (1996). In this stjudy the authors surveyed a random sample of 100 major U.S. companies spread over six manufacturing industries as to their views of the IPR regimes in fourteen less developed countries. Respondents, mostly top executives or corporate patent attorneys, were asked about their willingness to transfer their latest technologies to wholly owned subsidiaries in these countries as well as' their willingness to enter into jointventure associations with local partner firms. The countries chosen were those that possessed substantial industry capacities and those that had been involved in IP disputes. On the basis of the survey responses, the authors calculate for each of the six industry groups the percentage of firms responding that the IPR regime is too weak to permit the transfer of technology. The mean of these percentages is taken as the measure of IP weakness (PAT) for each country
70
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 71
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Table 3.2 Patent Rights and DFI Variable
Lee and Mansfield model
Modified Lee and Mansfield model
Augmented Lee and Mansfield model
constant
-239 (-0.71) -14.0 (-1.91)* 81.2 (1.92)* 737 (4.47)'* 72.4 (3.94)" -24.7 (-0.73) 16.9 (0.47)
-4,260.067 (-2.193)* -841.270 (-1.259) 559.601 (2.019) 10,920.22 (4.576)** 715.598 (3.250)** 114.505 (0.313) 606.397 (1.840)
-2,656.269 (-1.495) -1,189.111 (-2.027) 364.626 (1.464) 10,012.24 (4.801)** 633.312 (3.321)** -311.820 (-0.877) 136.789 (0.404) 982.646 (2.497)* .81 21
PAT/GP90 MSIZE MEX L1NV IND OPEN INFRA adj. R 2 N
0.57 14
.74 21
and is used as an explanatory variable in the authors' regression analysis. The dependent variable in this analysis is the volume of U.S. direct investment in a particular country and the hypothesis of interest is that this variable is inversely related to the weakness of the country's IPRs. Additional variables are entered on theright-handside of the regression model as controls. These include measures for size of market (MSIZE), level (stock) of prior direct foreign investment (LINV), degree of industrialization (IND), degree of economic openness (OPEN), and a dummy variable to identify Mexico (MEX).12 The authors' least squares estimates are given in column 2 of Table 3.2. The regression results show that several of the signs of the parameter estimates are those predicted by theory. U.S. DFI tends to be directed to larger and more open markets. Economies of agglomeration suggest that flows of DFI are directed where existing stocks of foreign assets are greater. The Mexico dummy variable estimate is positive and highly significant. The estimate attached to the industrialization variable has a sign contrary to the theoretical prediction but turns out to be not statistically significant. Neither is significance indicated in the case of the economic openness variable. The most salient finding of all for Lee and Mansfield concerns the inverse relationship found between patent weakness and U.S. DFI flows. The negative parameter estimate turns out to be significant at the .05 level.13 The important conclusion drawn by the authors then is that patent weak-
ness among these countries tends to discourage DFI by these American firms. A cursory examination of Lee and Mansfjield's method and data suggests that their results should be met with caution1 and perhaps even some skepticism. The sample size for their analysis is 'extremely small and subject to selection bias. These authors analyze only fourteen countries in their sample, including, by their own accounting, those involved in IP disputes. The measure they develop for weakness of patent protection is also subject to bias introduced by the subjective evaluation of evaluators who may themselves be party to these same disputes. It makes a great deal of sense to ask how robust the Lee and Mansfield findings are to changes in both the sample ak well as the measure for IP protection. Toward this end I make the following changes to the Lee and Mansfield estimation model. First, the authors' measure of patent weakness (PAT) is replaced by the Ginarte and Parks index of intellectual propertyrights(GP90). The 1990 values are chosen as coming closest in time to the Lee and Mansfield (LM) study. Substituting the GP measure for Lee and Mansfield's surveybased indicator allows for an expansion of the sample size from fourteen to twenty-one countries. The new sample contains all but one (Taiwan) of the countries used in the LM study. The measures used for the right-hand side explanatory variables are also retained in the modified model, as is the Wheeler and Mody (1992) data source used in the LM analysis. The least squares results of this new estimation are given in column three of Table 3.2. Inspection of these new results shows tnat they are similar to the LM findings (column 1) in several important respects. Nearly all the signs on the coefficients are the same (the exception being the positive sign for IND). In several cases the levels where statistical significance are indicated are also the same. The key important difference in th^ two models, however, turns up when we consider the meanings of their respective coefficients on the measure for strength of IP regime. Recall that in Ithe LM model PAT refers to the weakness of patents, whereas GP90 refers to the strength of the overall IP system. Hence a negative coefficient for the latter variable suggests a conclusion opposite to that arrived at by Lee and Mansfield. That is, the new results suggest greater U.S. DFI flows to those countries with weaker IP regimes. The lack of statistical significance attached to the coefficient prevents us, of course, from embracing this contrary conclusion. Afinalspecification of the model, however, is suggestive. In drawing on the data and arguments of Wheeler and Mody, Lee and Mansfield neglected to include in their version of the regression model several variables examined by the former. Among these were an index of country risk and another that provided a measure of the quality of the nation's physical infrastructure. For obvious reasons, these would be important considerations for international investors.
72
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Wheeler and Mody themselves found the infrastructure measure to be a significant determinant of foreign investment, but not their risk index variable. Lee and Mansfield excluded the infrastructure variable on the grounds that it is highly correlated with industrialization (IND). Calculating the correlation coefficient between Wheeler and Mody's IND and their measure for quality of infrastructure (INFRA) for the present sample of countries shows a high value (.65) but one that is far from collinearity. When INFRA is included in the specification, the estimation results for this augmented version of the LM model are obtained and shown in column four of Table 3.2. These parameter estimates show, once again, findings very similar to those for the modified LM model (column three). The important differences in this case are the statistically significant impact that infrastructure quality has for DFI flows and the increased statistical significance attached to the negative coefficient linking IPR strength (GP90) to DFI. Here we find the probability of rejecting the null hypothesis reduced to .06. When we use INFRA to substitute for IND, we obtain nearly identical results (not shown), though the probability of rejecting the hypothesis of a negative relationship between IP strength and DFI is raised slightly to .08. Finally, the important point here is not necessarily to empirically establish the negative relationship between strength of IPR regime and flows of U.S. DFI. It is rather to demonstrate the lack of robustness of Lee and Mansfield's findings of a positive relationship between the variables. That is to say, there can be no empirically based presumption that strengthening intellectual property protection via the TRIPS agreement holds out the promise of increased DFI from the United States to the less developed countries of the world. The available evidence clearly indicates, rather, that such characteristics as the prior stock of DFI and the quality of infrastructure are far more important determinants of these flows.14 At this point an important question needs to be asked. Even if it could be shown that strengthening IPRs stimulated DFIflows,could we conclude that such flows are welfare improving to the poorer countries in the short and long runs? Certainly, much has been written about the benefits of foreign capital to growth and development. Among these alleged benefits is the prospect of the transfer of technology and improvements in productive efficiency. It has yet to be empirically demonstrated, however, that these benefits are greater than those that are obtained via the alternative of direct imitation and/ or adaptation of foreign technologies in the absence of strong patent protection. Clearly the primary targets of the TRIPS agreement, as well as those who provided the strongest resistance to the agreement, are constituted by those countries, such as India and Brazil, that have a substantial indigenous research and development capability. An important, but heretofore unexplored
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 73
question is, What are the effects of increased DFI on the indigenous technical capacities of countries like these? If DF;I results in the transfer of technology and productivity improvements, then it is possible that it raises the overall level of productive efficiency in the receiving economy as long as these benefits outweigh those realized by the free-riding alternative. If DFI displaces indigenous R&D, however, the probability of a positive net benefit contribution is decidedly reduced. r There is also an important distributional and equity aspect to this issue. To what extent does the transfer of technology via foreign investors aided by stronger patent and copyrights help to raise the well-being of a wide swath of the population of a poor country? While itl may be true that foreign investors pay higher than average wages, there are many well-documented cases in which DFI has had a highly distorting impact on the structure of a LDC's economy and society. Agriculture is a particularly important area of concern. The transfer of techniques developed in!scientifically advanced countries such as the United States often has profound effects on the productivity levels of Third World agriculture. As will be documented in Chapter 7, it also has equally profound, and disastrous, consequences for the patterns of landownership, employment, and well-being jof the rural populations of these countries. Critics of the TRIPS who worry about the agreement's implications for breeders' rights, the cost of seed consequences for landownership and employment are well justified in their concerns. There can be no a priori presumption that these impacts will be benign for the majority of rural residents, Neither does past experience provide a basis for optimism. Economic Growth The third and final empirical relationship to examine here concerns the impact of stronger IPRs on the potential for economic growth in the less developed world. As in the cases of trade and foreign investment already discussed, there is not a wide literature to review. The theoretical case for the growth-promoting benefits of stronger global IPRs is, at least in part, related to the issues already discussed—namely, international trade and foreign investment. That is, insofar as stronger and harmonized IPRs across nations promote international trade and investment, the argument goes, there will result a more globally efficient allocation of resources that will, in general, promote growth. Beyond this, however, it is further argued that stronger global IPRs will promote more innovation, technology transfer, and technological spillovers that in turn provide global economic growth with an additional boost.15
74
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
On the other hand, there exists the possibility that IP protection could have a dampening effect on the propensity to innovate if firms choose to exploit existing market advantages to the neglect of innovative activities. Intellectual property protection in this light acts like any other form of industrial protection.16 If this is the case, then the strengthening of IPRs could conceivably have negative effects on economic growth. Once again, theoretical ambiguity suggests that we appeal to the available empirical evidence. Once again, however, the available empirical evidence is quite thin. In recent years, two studies have been conducted that explore the relationship between IPRs and economic growth for cross-country samples. The first of these is by Gould and Gruben (1996), who draw on the endogenous growth literature to specify a single equation regression model whose dependent variable is the average annual rate of growth of gross domestic product (GDP) per capita over the period I960 to 1988. Several versions of the benchmark model are specified, employing as explanatory variables the level of GDP as of 1960, the investment ratio, and the secondary school rate in 1960, among other measures." The data set includes ninetyfive developed and LDCs and the right-hand-side variable representing the strength of IPRs is the Rapp and Rozek index of patent protection. Out of concern for both measurement error and possible endogeneity of the regressor, the authors choose to take an instrumental variables approach to the estimation. Toward this end, they specify an auxiliary equation with the log of the RR index as a function of several of its underlying determinants, including average duration of patent protection, a set of dummy variables indicating membership (or not) in various international IPR agreements, a set of dummy variables indicating whether or not the country is signatory to agreements on patent protection for particular industries and products, and several other country characteristics. The predicted values from this regression are then used on the right-hand side of the primary growth equation.18 Two versions of the growth model with IPRs are estimated. The first includes only the instrumented version of IP protection among the explanatory variables, while the second employs the instrument along with some additional ancillary regressors.19 In each case, the IPR variable is found significant at least at the .1 level. The fact that statistical significance is reduced when the additional ancillary regressors are added to the model raises question about the robustness of the results. Since few of these variables are found to be significant, we must naturally wonder what the outcome for the IPR variable would be if it was combined with a set of ancillary regressors with greater ability to contribute to the overall explanatory power of the model.20 Gould and Gruben are themselves aware of the potential lack of robust-
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 75
ness in their results because the next step; in their analysis is to examine the role played by international competition i|n conditioning economic growth's relation to IPRs. To do this, they specify various alternative dummy variables that identify countries with greater than average levels of economic openness. Employing a variety of specifications, the authors are able to present evidence that suggests that relatively open countries display higher rates of economic growth in the presence of greater IP protection than do relatively closed countries. They conclude on this basis that the character of a country's trade regime plays a role in determining riow IPRs affect economic growth, with more open and competitive economies benefiting more than closed and less competitive ones. A second study to explore the empirical relationship between IPRs and economic growth was published by Park and Ginarte (1997)—the same authors who developed the index of IPRs discussed earlier. One of the improvements that these authors claim for their work is precisely their index, which they argue demonstrates more variability than the Rapp and Rozek measure used in Gould and Gruben's paper. Another contribution they claim is their ability to demonstrate that the effects of stronger IPRs in promoting economic growth occur not in a direct fashion, but rather in their operation through the process of productive factor iccumulation. The modeling strategy of Park and Gin irte is to specify a system of equations to be estimated simultaneously via seemingly unrelated regression (SUR). In the primary equation of interest, the economic growth equation, three explanatory variables are treated as instruments—the investment ratio, schooling, and the R&D ratio. These variables are in turn regressed on a set of additional ancillary variables that includes Ginarte and Park's own index of IPRs. Separate regressions are run for the total sample size of sixty nations as well as for the thirty richer and thiity poorer nations. In no case is the GP index found to be significant in the primary growth equations. The index is found to be a statistically significant determinant of physical capital accumulation and R&D (though not schooling) for the overall sample and for the subsample involving the richer countries. It is not, however, found to be significant for the subset of poorer countries. The authors suggest from these results that either the LDCs do not respond to material incentives in the same way as the developed countries, or that a significant part of their R&D efforts is imitative rather than innovative. The latter of these two possibilities seems the more plausible. More significant are the policy conclusions drawn by the authors. Here they argue that LDCs ought not to be expected to support stronger IPR regimes until they themselves have established substantial abilities and institutions to take advantage of these same rights. As things stand, most poor countries with very limited R&D capacities hardly see the advantage to
76
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND POSITIVIST ECONOMIC SCIENCE 77
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
them of limiting their abilities to imitate in favor of providing greater security to foreign providers of innovations. This is especially so given the costs of establishing and enforcing the strengthened regime. As noted earlier, some proponents of the TRIPS agreement have argued that LDCs can give a stimulus to economic growth by strengthening their IP regimes. As afinalexperiment, I would like to consider the following simple regression model that posits economic growth (GROWTH) as the left-handside variable to be explained. The regressors include the average annual rate of gross domestic investment (GDI) and the rate of gross secondary school enrollments (SECED).21 These variables have been identified as robust determinants in cross-country growth models. The regressor of interest here is the change in the GP index of intellectual property rights (DGP) taken between 1970 and 1985. If stronger IPRs are associated with stronger growth, then the coefficient estimate should obviously be positive. The time period over which the model is estimated is 1980 through 1990. As this decade was a traumatic one for several Latin American countries, a dummy variable (LAT) is included in the specification to identify the region. Likewise, an Asian dummy (ASIA) is included that is intended to capture the "booming" behavior of several of the Asian newly industrialized countries—the famous NICS— of that region. The least squares regression results, where values in parentheses are t statistics, are given below. GROWTH = 5.018 CONSTANT - 0.407 DGP + 0.276 GDI - 0.029 SECED - 1.383 LAT (5.594)**
(-0.503)
(5.468)** (-2.656)**
(-2.241)*
+ 1.051 ASIA (1.837) F statistic = 18.396; adjusted R2 = .68; N = 43; ** = .01; * = .05.
The above results suggest that, as in previous models of this type, investment is an important positive determinant of growth. Curiously, however, the human capital variable (SECED) does not turn out to have the predicted positive sign. It may be that the secondary school enrollment ratio is a poor measure for this variable. The most salient result shown is the lack of a positive relationship between improving IPRs (DGP) and economic growth over this period. The estimated coefficient, though not statistically significant, is actually shown to be negative.
Based on this evidence, there would not seem to be any reason to expect the TRIPS agreement to have an immediate; beneficial impact on economic growth. Defenders of TRIPS may reasonably reply that ten years is too short a period over which to definitely assess the impact of an upgrade in the IPR regime on economic growth. I would certainly agree that more time and data are needed to arrive at final conclusions. I would also assert, however, that at this stage of the evidence greater skepticism than optimism is warranted regarding the alleged growth-inducing effects! of the agreement. Conclusion The findings of this review may be briefly |summarized as follows: (1) the theoretical literature suggests that the static welfare consequences of a stronger and harmonized international regime of IPRs are probably negative for the poorer countries of the world; (2) the empirical literature thus far has not been able to establish with a reasonable degree of confidence that stronger IPRs will have benefits for the poorer countries in terms of expanded trade, increased flows of DFI, technology transfer, ;or economic growth; (3) for the foreseeable future, the main beneficiaries o!f harmonized IPRs will be the developed nations from which the large bulk of innovations derive. Advocates of the TRIPS agreement will u ndoubtedly respond that a longterm perspective is required before the success of the agreement in providing its expected benefits for the LDCs will be realized. Some will also argue that TRIPS-related benefits require that a whole range of liberalization measures also be adopted, including free trade, industrial privatization and deregulation, and labor market reform in the direction of greater flexibility. Still others will argue that additional industrial regula :ory institutions will be required to ensure that the benefits of stronger IPR are reaped by producers and consumers in the LDCs. Whatever the merits of these arguments, they do not in themselves constitute an adequate justification for the TRIPS. Thus far, defenders of the agreement have not demonstrated that the TRIPS will provide net benefits that exceed those associated with the alternative of free imitation of technologies developed in the technologically advanced areas of the world. They have not demonstrated that the flow of innovations would be substantially reduced in the absence of the TRIPS nor that the TRIPS has resulted in greater innovation effort in the direction of goods, services, and techniques that are of special concern and benefit to those who reside in poor countries. Clearly, time is required for questions such as these to be resolved. In the meantime, however, there is no compelling case made that LDCs should support the TRIPS agreement. Notwithstanding the available evidence, or lack of it, the TRIPS agree-
78
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
ment is an established fact. This raises the obvious question as to why the LDCs would accede to an agreement whose evident costs-benefits ratio is so high. The answer to this question, alluded in the introduction of this book, is not hard to understand for students of the political economy of multilateral negotiations. Namely—the developed countries, and particularly the United States, introduced additional potential costs and benefits into the negotiating calculus of the poorer nations that could not be ignored. The threat of unilateral punishments of IPR violations combined with the enticement of improved market access for the LDCs' trade proved to be of decisive importance for securing their acceptance of the agreement. The "how?" and "why?" of this political economy is the subject of the chapters to follow. Here it is sufficient to note that future such agreements, or modifications to existing ones, are also likely to be dictated by political economy factors rather than the weight of positive evidence.
Capital, Class, alnd the State in the Global lEconomy
The arguments ana evidence of the previous two chapters demonstrate that the trade-related aspects of intellectual property rights (TRIPS) agreement can hardly be understood as the result of either a compelling philosophical defense of exclusionary property rights in intellectual property or of the ability of its proponents and defenders to provide a convincing case of the agreement's positive potential impact on short-term economic welfare and long-term economic development, particularly as these relate to the poor countries. And yet, as a matter of fact, the TRIPS is currently a part of the international regulatory framework that governs the global capitalist economy. A key objective of this and the following chapter is to provide a reconciliation of this contradiction. Such a reconciliation, it is apparent, must be found in a political economy; an£ lysis. That is, it requires an analysis that focuses on the real power relationships as they exist between those who are well served by the agreement and those who are not. The debate surrounding the TRIPS, as is true of virtually all international agreements of its type, has been represented as a contest between nations. Certainly it is true that the actual negotiations leading up to the signing of the TRIPS were conducted by official representatives of the governments that are members of the multilateral trade system. It shall be argued here, however, that such a view is at best superficial and at worse a deliberate ideological obfuscation of a more fundamental reality grounded in class divisions and, correspondingly, class conflict. Examination of real power relationships at the level of the global economy necessarily requires that we take appropriate consideration of the exercise of state power. This requires in turn that we have an adequate theoretical understanding of the meaning of the state, that we understand how state power is exercised, and that we understand how classes attempt to imprint the particular structures of state power in ways that operate to advance their interests. This discussion of the state is the principle concern of the present chapter. The results of this discussion will then be used to develop a political eco79
80
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
nomic analysis appropriate to the specific issue of the TRIPS agreement in Chapter 5. Political economic analysis, like any other, requires a set of assumptions or theoretical framework for its execution. International political economic theory and its close cousin, international relations theory, provide a number of candidate frameworks from which we might choose. The job of the following section will be to assess the capabilities of three of these models to undertake the analytical task at hand.' Having arrived at an appropriate set of theoretical tools, I shall attempt to craft a coherent interpretation of the capitalist state in the global economy useful for an understanding of the political economy of the TRIPS. Hegemony, World Systems, and the Internationalization of Capital Of the three theoretical frameworks that I wish to examine for their potential insights into the state of the global economy, one is derived from international relations (IR) theory and the other two are drawn from international political economy (IPE). In his textbook Brawley (1998, pp. 405—406) distinguishes between IR and IPE as follows: International political economy is the analysis of the-interaction of power and the processes of wealth creation at the international level; international relations is the study of politics involving an international dimension—that is, relations between states and external actors (states and nonstate actors), as well as between nonstate actors and other external actors (states and nonstate actors), or involving the formulation of a policy with repercussions for actors outside the country. The fundamental difference between IR theory and IPE, at least as I understand it, is the broader overview of the former. That is, whereas IPE tends to focus on economic institutions and relationships between nations through the prism of the exercise of political power, IR theory takes an even wider view. This wider view, while not dismissing the insights of IPE, also pays close attention to broader political factors, including the exercise of military power and international diplomacy. It is also probably fair to say that, generally speaking though not necessarily so, the practitioners of IPE are most likely to be primarily trained in economic theory while those who specialize in IR are more likely trained in political science. Hegemony Theory The theory of hegemonic stability has been an important paradigm of IR theory for several decades. Its most notable proposition is that a liberal world
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
81
trading system requires that a particular nation-state (the hegemon) impose sufficient order in an otherwise anarchic w|orld to permit the free flow of goods, services, and capital. According to Lake (1993), the theory has at least two distinct variants—leadership theory and hegemony theory. What they have in common is the notion that states operate as unitary political actors who in turn operate as rational maximizers of the national interest. Each theory is also inclined to define national interest in economic terms and to promote a liberal trading and investment system as the best guarantor of that interest. Leadership theory argues that in seeking to maximize national welfare a leader state will promote an international economic infrastructure that has the characteristics of a public good (Kindleberger 1973, 1981). Among the particular elements of this infrastructure are included a stable international medium of exchange, a sufficient source of international liquidity, and adequate guarantees that define and protect basic property rights. The leader country that provides these elements or stimulates their collective, international provision obviously will enjoy their benefits. It is also clear, however, that other nations will also benefit—even those that have no hand at all in their provision. Leadership theory then posits the necessity of a leader state to overcome this free rider problem. Lake notes that an interesting debate that has arisen in the literature concerns the manner in which the leader state is able to "stimulate" the provision of the international economic superstructure. "Benevolent" leadership occurs when the leader state assume; all or a substantial portion of the cost of providing the infrastructure. "Coercive" leadership occurs when the leader state is able to force other nonleader, or follower, states to assume a portion or all of these costs. Coercion is necessary inasmuch as free riders, by definition, are not inclined to beai such costs. If coercion is to be chosen over benevolence, then the question of the efficiency of the coercive mechanism must be considered. Efficient coercion is more likely the greater is the leverage exercised by the leader state over the dependent follower states. Another interesting issue in the literature highlighted by Lake concerns whether the leadership function must be performed by a single state or if a collection of states can perform the task. Lake notes Kindleberger's argument that the difficulties of bargaining among a collection of leaders are likely to frustrate the necessary cooperation required for providing the international infrastructure. Ultimately, then,! a single state will have to take on the responsibility of leadership. Lake, however, is persuaded by the arguments of other public goods theorists that multiple states may reap sufficient net benefits to overcome barriers to cooperation. He concludes that a single
82
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
leader is not necessary for the provision of an adequate international economic infrastructure (1993, p. 465). Hegemony theory differs from leadership theory in assuming that the interests of states may conflict in the international economic arena. One or more states may prefer an open trading system while others may prefer greater autarky. Whether the actual system is more open or closed will depend on the ability of a particular state, the hegemon, to enforce a liberal trading system. The long history of global capitalism suggests that at various periods a hegemon is able to impose such a system. The three regimes that most theorists discuss in this context are the period of Dutch domination during the seventeenth century, the Pax Britannica of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, and the American regime of the twentieth century. The fundamental hypothesis of the theory is that the exercise of political, economic, diplomatic, and military power by these hegemonic states at the zeniths of their dominance is correlated with relative liberalism in international trade rela-' tions. Periods of history during which trade protectionism is more likely occur when a hegemonic power finds its control in decline. The decline may be caused by challenges from other would-be hegemons or by global economic, military, or political crisis. In any case, the interim during which no particular state is clearly hegemonic is one of decreased interstate cooperation and relative economic autarky. Hegemony theory has been met with many of the same kinds'of theoretical uncertainties that have plagued leadership theory. Can we be certain that a global hegemon, for example, will perceive its self-interest in terms of a liberal trading system? Optimal tariff theory suggests that a large, powerful trading country will realize an improvement in its terms of trade by erecting an appropriately high, yet nonprohibitive, tariff. This works by reducing domestic demand for imports sufficiently to cause the price of these goods to fall. The new trade theory associated with Krugman and others (1986) argues that appropriate tariff policy of a global technological leader may provide it with a comparative advantage in new industries that produce under conditions of economies of scale and decreasing costs. Is a single hegemon either necessary or sufficient for a stable liberal trading system? Krasner (1976) argues that the fundamental hegemonic actor is actually a system of highly developed states rather than a single dominant nation-state. This collection of highly developed states will have a core set of similar interests—for example, national income, economic growth, social stability—that motivates the construction of the international economic infrastructure that it will impose (if necessary) on those nation-states that perceive their own interests as opposing. At the same time, Krasner takes the standard neoclassical economic view that free trade is Pareto improving. That
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
83
is, all countries stand to benefit from trade. The conflict between large, powerful states and smaller, dependent ones is largely confined to the issue of who stands to gain more—that is, the distribution of relative benefits. Krasner's view stands in stark contrast to the theory of Gramscian hegemony advanced by theorists Stephen Gill (1993) and Robert Cox (1996). For Gramsci, hegemony was a term used to describe the manner in which one class, or class fraction, sought to control qther classes in a particular society. State power is instrumental in this control but not in itself sufficient inasmuch as the power of the state is largely a matter of coercion. The notion of control favored by Gramsci and Gramscians involves the consent of the controlled classes themselves. The mechanism that ensures such control was termed by Gramsci the extended state, which incorporated important elements of civil society as well as the state apparatus itself. Control is exercised then not only through the coercive capabilities of the state, but via the moral and intellectual leadership of these ;key elements of civil society. The direction of the extended state is the prerogative of what Gramsci terms the historic bloc. Rupert (1993) provides a description of the Gramscian historic bloc as follows: Gramsci's concept of historic bloc bridges the structured separation of state and society in capitalist social formatio is, in so far as the ideological leadership of a class or class fraction provides a measure of coherence to a range of apparently disparate social practices (cultural, political, economic).To the extent that a class orfractionis able to articulate a unifying ideology which presents itself as universal, which can elicit the variety of social practices, it may create the basis of hegemonic leadership in both state and civil society —that is, in Gramsci's expanded or integral state, (p. 80) Based on these Gramscian ideas, the concept of hegemony is here more usefully reformulated to denote, to use Cox's phrase, "a fit between power, ideas, and institutions" (1996, p. 104) that applies not to particular states but rather to a larger world order. Cox is not satisfied to explain the conditions for the stability of a particular world ordet. Rather he seeks to explain why particular world orders come into existenc;, how they operate, and why they are subsequently succeeded by other wor d orders. He sees the interaction between the social relations of production and the material conditions under which production is carried out as being fundamentally important in the determination of a given world order.2 As befits his Gramscian influence, he prefers a historical materialism that emphasizes the reciprocal determination of ideas and the material conditions of production. The neo-Gramscians believe that during the late twentieth century the
84
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
world order evolved in the direction of globalization based on (hyper)liberalism. This evolution, like all such historical change, was dictated by crisis in the prevailing world order and in its corresponding historic bloc. This crisis had a variety of facets, including the collapse of state capitalism both in the western democracies and in the former Soviet Union and the collapse of the Bretton Woods international monetary system. The emphasis on political economic cooperation, planning, and control inherent in the previous world order has given way to a new one based on liberalization of markets (including labor markets), privatization of state enterprises and (some) functions, and the globalization of productive activity. States certainly have a role to play in the transformation of the world order. They are not, however, the fundamental unit of analysis that they are in the neorealist theory of hegemonic stability. They are rather, as Cox puts it, intermediating actors in the relationship between the development of global social forces and the configurations of social forces at the local level. Corresponding to the new global world order is the internationalization of the state, a process that began in the post-World War II period with the establishment of a variety of multinational agencies and institutions, such as the International Monetary Fund (IMF), the World Bank, the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) and the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO). The process accelerated over the last decades of the century corresponding to the crises alluded to above as well as to the emergence of a new, globally defined historic bloc. This dominant bloc is composed at its apex, according to Cox (1986, p. 234), of a transnational managerial class that directs the operations of transnational corporations and financial institutions. It is supported by a plethora of international administrators, officials, and intellectuals who administer and provide surveillance, technical support, and moral justification for the global system. As the neo-Gramscians point out, hegemony in the new world order does not consist in a particular state's dominance in the pursuit of its narrow self-interest, as per the neorealist interpretation, but rather in promoting the interests of the new historic bloc as the consensus interests of an undifferentiated "global welfare." Dependency and World Systems Theory Dependency theory developed in the 1960s as an alternative and critical interpretation of the underdevelopment of what was then referred to as the Third World. It arose as an alternative to various "modernization" theories of economic backwardness that posited this condition in terms of a variety of "obstacles" to development. Such modernization approaches see underdevelopment as deriving from the lack of some key productive factor (e.g.,
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
85
capital, educated workforce) or from the inadequate development of key institutions (e.g., markets, bureaucratic efficiency). These lacks are perceived as obstacles to be overcome before the i dynamic of capitalist growth and development can take off and propel "backward" societies to higher levels of per capita income and consumption. Several of the modernization theories place emphasis on alleged cultural obstacles in the form of precapitalist institutions and ideologies that impair the impulse to capital accumulation and productive efficiency necessary for economic and social development. Such societies have often been characterized ajs "semifeudal." Dependency theory, on the contrary, argues that the underdeveloped countries are fully capitalist and have been feo since the period of their initial colonization by the European mercantile powers in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. The underdevelopment of the Third World in fact owes precisely to its incorporation into the capitalist world system on a subordinate and dependent basis. The particular role of the underdeveloped countries, according to the dependency theorists, has historically been to provide primary commodities in trade to the center, developed countries. The international trading system, via the mechanism of unequal exchange, extracts surplus value from the direct producers (peasants and workers) of the underdeveloped societies. This extracted surplus value in turn provides the basis for both capital accumulation and higher liv.ng standards for those who reside in the center countries. In the peripheral, underdeveloped countries, however, the result of this exploitation is the general impoverishment of direct producers even as local landowners and capitalists enjoy incomes and standards of living approximating those found in the center countries. The similarity between the standards of living and consumption of the local bourgeoisie and those of their center country counterparts is not accidental inasmuch as the former are closely tied to the latter as managers of subsidiaries of transnational corporate operations headqaartered in the center countries, or as suppliers to these same operations. World systems theory (WST) has a £ reat deal in common with dependency theory, including having as part of its motivation the repudiation of modernization theory. Like dependency theory, it sees the world economy as constituted by a single capitalist mode of production that emerged in Europe as early as the sixteenth century. Also, it-posits the existence of an underdeveloped periphery that owes its underdeveloped status to its exploitation by a commercially and militarily more pdwerful center. Unlike the dependency theory, however, the world system perspective also posits the existence of an intermediate strata of nations that it refers to as the semiperiphery (Wallerstein 1974). Countries that occupy a position in the semiperiphery have achieved what the original dependency theorists denied is possible—namely, capital-
86
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
ist development. It is, however, a limited form of capitalist development, involving industries producing commodities for which there exist wellestablished global markets and employing production methods that are far from the technological frontier. Moreover, this limited capitalist development is a highly dependent sort. This is so in two senses. First, much of the production of the industries in semiperiphery nations is the output of transnational firms that are headquartered in the center countries. Alternatively, they may be joint ventures among foreign center capital, local capital, and/or the local state that rely heavily on technology and management provided by center country firms. Second, much of this production is sold as inputs for further production in center country industries. Hence, the industrial production of semiperipheral countries is of a decidedly lower order than the industrial production of center countries, albeit fitting within the globally defined division of labor. WST also differentiates itself from dependency theory in some other ways. The dependency approach typically takes the nation-state as the unit of analysis and seeks to describe the consequences for the peripheral society of its relationship with a capitalist center country. WST, in contrast, eschews the external-internal focus of dependency theory in favor of one that attempts to explore the dynamics of development of the capitalist world economy as a whole (Bomschier and Chase-Dunn 1985, p. 4). WST is also said to be able to resolve the differences that sometimes arise within the dependency school as to the possibility of capitalist development within the periphery itself. It is argued that the peripheral nations may experience a sort of limited development in the sense of an increase in productivity and income while remaining constrained by their position in the global hierarchy of capitalist production. Some countries may even pass from peripheral status to the semiperiphery, and vice versa. At the same time, the theory defines "underdevelopment" as a characteristic of countries whose development potential has been realized and whose limited development has been uneven with regard to different social groups, regions, economic sectors, and institutions. Bornschier and Chase-Dunn argue that there is a moral dimension to this definition in the sense that underdevelopment reflects a perceived discrepancy between the aspirations of people and the ability of the social structure characteristic of the peripheral society to fulfill those aspirations up to and including basic needs (p. 8). WST is thoroughly historical. Its essential task is to provide an understanding of the functioning of the world capitalist system via an examination of its evolution, starting from what has been termed the long sixteenth century. An integral component of the structure and dynamics of the modern (capitalist) world system is the interstate system. The interstate system
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
87
comprises multiple nation-states of varying degrees of power and influence. While no particular state has had complete control over the entire world economy, the history of the modern world system shows that various identifiable subperiods correspond to periods of relative hegemony of particular states. For the seventeenth and lasting into the mid-eighteenth centuries, the hegemonic state was the United (Dutch) Provinces. This was succeeded by the period of British supremacy that lasted until World War I and the collapse of the gold standard, which opened the Way for the period of American hegemony in the twentieth century. j Hegemonic transitions are occasioned by intense rivalry among would-be hegemons for the dominant position in the system.3 This rivalry involves competition in economic, political, diplbmatic, and cultural arenas (Wallerstein, 1984, pp. 38-39). The hegemonic nation-state is the one that carves out a decisive efficiency advantage in production, commerce, and finance. This advantage is secured by a long (thirty-year) period of war, after which the victor constructs an international institutional framework designed to buttress its own hegemony. The dominant position of the winner, however, is not permanent. According to Wallerstein, success in the race for the hegemonic top spot carries with it the conditions for future challenges to that very position. This is particularly so inasmuch as the period of hegemonic consolidation is accompanied by global economic liberalization. Hence, the free flow of goods, capital, and technology both advances the interests of the capitalist class of the hegemonic core ration and legitimizes the system globally. This same liberalization, however, creates opportunities for other potential hegemons. The hegemonic core nation is also made vulnerable by the rising demands of its domestic working class for a share of the spoils provided by unequal exchange. Hegemonic transition oceurs when these tendencies effectively undermine the efficiency advantage of the dominant nation-state, after which ensues another^ long period of intense competition among its potential successors. Out of tfc is competition emerges a new dominant core state that sets the rules for the; next long wave of global capitalist accumulation. Some world systems theorists have argued for a necessary functional interdependence between the interstate system and the capitalist character of the modern world economic system. If the system was dominated by a single state, then the capitalist class would lack the autonomy to pursue its class interests. On the other hand, the international mobility of capital enables it to constrain the power of any particular state from excessive expansion to the point of absolute global hegemony (Chase-Dunn 1981). WST has been subject to multiple lines of criticism both from within the Marxian tradition of which it is ai part and from outside that tradition.4
88
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
World systems theorists have responded to their critics both by accommodating some criticisms with suitable modifications and elaborations of their specific categories and claims and by dismissing other particular criticisms. Thus, for example, WST has been criticized by some for focusing too closely on the economic relationships between nations to the neglect of an adequate discussion of the dynamics of their internal politics and of the relative autonomy of the capitalist state. WST has responded with the argument that the economics versus politics dichotomy is a sterile one for the purposes of understanding the development and functioning of the modern world system. Chase-Dunn (1981) has attempted to elaborate a theory of the interstate system based on the world systems approach. He argues that the development of the interstate system, as well as of its constituent nation-states, occurs alongside and interdependent with the global process and mechanisms of capital accumulation. Hence he finds that economics and politics are not characterized by separate logics in the modern world system, but rather are linked together by a single logic. Giovanni Arrighi (1993) has gone further in developing WST to provide a political economic model of hegemonic crisis and transition over the whole 500-year period of the modern world system.5 While approaches such as these do not grant politics the degree of "relative autonomy" that some would argue they possess, neither'do they reduce political events and actors to mere superstructural appendages of global economic forces. Internationalization of Capital A question that WST has been less successful at addressing concerns the status of class and class relations in the global economy. Some argue that this lacuna in the WST approach stems from its excessive concern with international exchange in the world economy leading to the transfer of surplus from the periphery to the core (the sphere of circulation) at the expense of an adequate examination of the conditions under which surplus value is actually produced (the sphere of production). The internationalization of capital (IOC) approach, on the other hand, seeks to explain the conditions under which capitalism reproduces itself on an international scale. In this the approach draws inspiration from Marx's discussion in volume 2 of Capital (1977) of the circuits of capital. The circuits of commodity capital, money capital, and productive capital have their international counterparts in international trade, international finance, and transnational corporate production. Failure to integrate each of these circuits into the analysis will lead to a distorted and incomplete understanding of global capitalist development in terms of the self-expansion of capital. This latter notion is criti-
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
89
cal if we are to have a proper theory, rather than a mere ad hoc description, of some of the system's tendencies. I Another critically important aspect to a more complete understanding of capitalism's dynamics concerns the nature of capitalist competition. Writing from an IOC approach, Jenkins (1987) argues that many political economists (including some Marxians) interpret bapitalist competition as the number of firms populating an industry or the extent of industrial concentration. Industrial concentration is often measured! in terms of market shares. These theories view capitalist competition, then, k% the polar opposite of monopoly capital. Moreover, capitalist competition is bften viewed as a process whereby market equilibrium is attained until such time as a new exogenous disturbance arises. Jenkins believes that this is incorrect. The emergence of monopoly capital does not suggest a diminution in the competitive struggle among capital and capitalists. Monopoly power may endow particular firms with the ability to exploit their market positions in the pursuit of super profits (surplus value), but these will be short-run opportunities. Competition among large monopolistic producers occurs in a variety of ways other than in terms of price. The introduction of new products and production processes, particularly in new, unexploited markets, is especially important. As innovativefirmsenjoy abovenormal profits, however, the incentive to imitate increases, thus increasing attempts at market entry. As Jenkins puts it then, "Success in achieving a quasi-monopolistic position leads to its ow n destruction" (p. 48). An especially important agent in the IOC approach is the transnational corporation (TNC). The TNC is the purveyor not only of productive capital but also of technology to the host country. In this way the circuits of capital referred to earlier assume international d mensions, first via international trade (circuit of circulation) and subsequently via TNC production (circuit of production) in selected host countries. The transition from international trade to international production by TNCs takes r. lace over distinct historical stages and is promoted by policies adopted by host states. Exchange rate and protectionist trade measures, for example, provide TNCs with the incentive to establish directly productive facilities in rations they might otherwise service via exports. In this way it is apparent that the IOC theory regards the state in the peripheral society as possessing a substantial degree of autonomy from both center capitalist interests as well as center states. Peripheral states are not mere agents in the machinations of center-based capitalists' designs for the organization of the global economy. For a less developed country to be properly characterized as capitalist,according to the IOC approach, it is not sufficient that the three circuits of capital be established within its borders. Rather, as Cypher (1979) claims; it is also necessary that the circuits
90
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
articulate and function together in a manner that results in self-expanding economic growth and capital accumulation. IOC Critique of WST IOC theory has been highly critical of the world systems approach to international political economy. Its most fundamental critique has been that WST limits its understanding and application of the concept of the capitalist mode of production to only one of the three circuits of capitalist circulation, the circuit of circulation. From this fundamental error follows a number of empirical difficulties besetting the WST. Cypher asks: How did "peripheral" nonacting nations create OPEC? What of the Stabex system, the Non-Aligned Movement, UNCTAD and so forth? What are the implications of revolutions in banking which created a world-wide market for credit? What were the implications of the internationalization of production? Why was so much capital exported to build capacity for manufacturing with the end of final sales in less-developed regions? What were the implications of the many and varied programs promulgated by the governments of the less-developed nations which were destined to control or alter the effects of transnational corporations in these regions? How could some "peripheral" nations export sophisticated machine tools to the "core" nations, while others generated their own high technology or failing that bought it outright from the transnationals? Why had so many less-developed nations attained such respectable per capita growth rates? (1979, p. 36) By limiting itself to the sphere of circulation (international trade), says Cypher, the dependency theorists fail to recognize that surplus value is not created in the act of exchange but in the act of production. If surplus value is transfered from the less developed to the more developed countries, this is the result of the weakness of the system of production in the latter. This weakness is related in turn to its noncapitalist character rather than the alleged capitalist character of global commodity exchange. A second serious shortcoming of the WST is its failure to develop an adequate analysis of class and class struggle, particularly as they apply to the less developed social formation. The actual differentiation that we observe among the social formations that constitute the Third World is the result of variation in the dialectical process involving internal social development and external relations. The social formation of any particular less developed country cannot be supposed to arise as a result of its unidirectional imposition by a more powerful external force. It is rather the result of internal class struggle
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
91
and the external movements of core nations. That some less developed nations actually develop while others do not cannot be reduced to the operations of external, core capitalist interests alone. A third mistake of the dependency school identified by Cypher concerns its analysis of the role of technology.^ Unequal exchange for the dependency theorists arises out of unequal methods of production.6 The issue of unequal methods of production, howevdr, does not attach itself exclusively, or even primarily, to the core-periphery dichotomy. For Cypher, it is rather a matter of "imperial capitalist rivalry." By this he means that technological innovation is one of the mechanisms by which capitalist firms seek to appropriate surplus value from one! another, other branches of industry, or other regions and countries. There can be no presumption, however, that this competition is in any sense limited to maneuvers between developed (core) and less developed (peripheral) countries. Quoting Lall (1975), Cypher notes that advanced, industrialized countries may be as "dependent" as less developed ones for particular kinds of technology. Some less developed countries (e.g., Brazil, India) have demonstrated themselves to be as technologically innovative as other countries we typically assume to belong to the core (e.g., Canada, Belgium) (pp. 47—4-8). Moreover, the bargaining position of less developed naticns such as Brazil and Mexico for the transfer of technology appears to be improving over time. This is a point central to the main concerns of the argument surrounding the TRIPS agreement and will be revisited in the chap ers that follow.7 What are we to make of the IOC critique of WST? There can be no doubt that IOC theory provides a necessary corrective to the tendency of the early dependency writers to focus excessively on international trade under conditions of unequal exchange as i mechanism of surplus value transfer from the periphery to the core of the global economic system. IOC theory also provides much needed analysis of the mechanisms of surplus production as well as the dialectics of social formations in historically specific contexts. Notwithstanding t i e contributions of IOC, I do not believe that there are sufficient grounds to argue that this approach displaces WST, nor do I believe that the former is necessarily inconsistent with the latter.8 As noted earlier, WST has evolved considerably since its early expressions in the dependency writings of Frank (1969) and Dos Santos (1970). Moreover, it has evolved in directions that easily accommodate many of the objections of Cypher and other IOC advocates. Most WST writers today embrace the argument that dependent, peripheral nations are capable of economic growth and capitalist (albeit limited and uneven) development. Some pay particular attention to the ways that transnational corporations
92
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
integrate themselves into the periphery and semiperiphery of the global capitalist system. In so doing, they study how foreign capital interacts, constrains, and is constrained by the dynamic of domestic class interactions and the state in the host nation. No serious reader of the WST literature can argue that the theory is fixated on the sphere of circulation to the neglect of the other aspects of the operation of capital. The evolution of WST, in part, undoubtedly represents a response to its critics, including those associated with the IOC perspective. I believe that, at the same time, the WST retains some of its important identifying elements that distinguish it from other approaches, including IOC. The first of these is its vision of a hierarchically organized world capitalist system. It is apparent that capitalist social relations and productive forces continue to develop within the periphery and semiperiphery at a pace and in a manner that make these areas of the world subordinate to those areas characterized by higher per capita incomes, higher standards of health and education, more sophisticated technological capacities, and more powerful military capacities. The latter areas are also the source of the bulk of the world's flows of portfolio and direct foreign investment capital. Not coincidentally, they are also the countries that dominate the international institutions and agencies that have come to be identified in recent years with the phenomenon of neoliberalization. Neoliberalism from theperspective of the less developed countries is best understood as a sort of forced march away from state-directed economic development, typified by import substitution during the 1950s and 1960s and export promotion in the 1980s. It has been accompanied by greater access to markets of less developed countries by transnational capital via relaxation of the laws and restrictions governing their behavior in host country markets. It has also been accompanied by the privatization of formerly state-owned companies and labor market reforms that have reduced the costs of production in these countries. In recent years it has involved financial market reforms that render local financial institutions more accountable to foreign creditors as well as more vulnerable to destabilizing short-run movements of "hot" (portfolio) capital. These developments have rendered the less developed countries less able to pursue autonomous development strategies or even independent short-run stabilization policies. They have made the pursuit of social policies to alleviate poverty all but impossible. Quite to the contrary, neoliberalism has in many cases directly led to an increase in absolute and relative poverty. In sum, we have witnessed since the 1980s a reassertion of the dependency relations described by the WST. It is in this context that we must understand the recent movement toward strengthening and harmonization of intellectual property rights. It will be argued in the sections to follow that the
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
93
TRIPS agreement is a component institution of an emerging international regulatory superstructure designed to facilitate the circulation and accumulation of capital on an international scale. B;efore describing how the TRIPS fits in this general function, it will be useful to examine the more general issue of state power and its evolution in a global context. State Theory and the Global Economy In this section, I wish to examine selected exemplars of the research traditions outlined above and draw from them \Vhat insights they provide for an understanding of the exercise of state power jin the contemporary global capitalist system. In the section to follow, I shall attempt to consolidate what I consider the most salient of these insights into a coherent interpretation of global state power that will aid us in our understanding of the purpose of the TRIPS agreement. The implications of this interpretation for the TRIPS will be suggested at the close of the chapter, and a full discussion of the political economy of the TRIPS will be undertaken in Chapter 5. Some commentators have argued that the development of the global economy since World War II has had the effect of undermining the power of the state. The increased international mobility of capital in particular has rendered far more difficult the exercise of national state power. The argument I wish to make, however, is that far from undermining state power, such developments have forced the emergence of an incipient global capitalist state whose instruments are supranational hegemonic institutions. Among these are the International Monetary Fund, the World Bank, and the World Trade Organization (WTO). The emergence of these supranational institutions by no means portends the end of interstate rivalry. Nation-states will continue to contend with each other to advance both their, own objectives and the interests of the classes and class fractions that are best able to exert pressure on them. The salient point here is that an important areni within which interstate rivalry plays itself out is the determination of the s pecific content of the emergent supranational institutions. In the immediate aftermath of World War II, the United States could well be described as a hegemonic state. Not only was it able to exert a higher degree of domestic economic policy independence than any other developed country in the world economy, but it possessed disproportionate ability to pursue via economic, diplomatic, and military means its interests around the globe. Most importantly for the present purposes, the United States was able to shape the postwar supranational institutions in the interests of its Cold War geopolitical objectives as well as global capitalist expansion.
94
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
The Rise and Fall (and Rise) of U.S. Hegemony Giovanni Arrighi (1993) has insightfully written about the evolutionary process by which particular states have come to occupy a position of world hegemony—a position which he describes as the power of a state to exercise governmental functions over a system of sovereign states. In true Gramscian spirit, he describes a dominant state as hegemonic "if it leads the system in a desired direction and, in so doing, is perceived as pursuing a universal interest" (p. 150). As he notes, however, this definition overlooks the difficult task of defining "a universal interest" within the context of the interstate system. At the level of individual states, hegemony may be pursued in the interests of some conception of "the national interest." At the international level, it is fairly clear that a universal interest must be understood in terms of a universal class. Without identifying this universal class as a capitalist class, Arrighi generally notes as much when he writes: A state may therefore become world hegemonic because it can claim with credibility to be the motor force of a universal expansion of the collective power of rulers vis-a-vis subjects. Or, conversely, a state may become world hegemonic because it can claim with credibility that the expansion of its power relative to some or even all other states is in the general interest of the subjects of all states, (p. 151) In contrast to world systems theorists such as Wallerstein, Arrighi rejects identifying the interstate system with the capitalist world economy. He argues that the division of the world into separate states may or may not facilitate the accumulation of capital from a historical perspective. Whether the benefits of the interstate system of rule exceed the costs depends on how the system organizes and regulates competition between states as well as between enterprises. An interstate system, for example, that relies on costly wars and disrupts international commerce, finance, and the networks of international production does not serve well the end of capitalist accumulation. A particular nation-state that can overcome the contradictions between the (often territorialist) tendencies of the interstate system and the needs of capitalist accumulation on an increasingly global scale is likely to emerge as the hegemonic state. Throughout the history of the modern world (capitalist) system, hegemonic states have been concerned to reduce the cost of its control and direction. Arrighi interprets the concept of "balance of power" in just such terms. He writes:
CAPITAL, CLASS. AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
95
The balance of power can be interpreted as an instrument by means of which capitalist rulers can, individually or as a group, reduce protection costs absolutely and relative to competitors and rivals. . . . The secret of capitalist success is to have one's warsifought by others, if feasible for free and, if not, at the least possible cost. (p. 156) Some neoclassical political economists; and neorealist IR theorists would interpret the above argument in terms of jpublic goods theory. The relevant notion here is the external economies associated with providing protection. In the post-World War II era, the United S|tates maintained a global military capability whose goal was the containment of the influence of the Soviet Union and the spread of counterhegemonic revolutions. Financial support for the Marshall Plan helped to rebuild the European and Asian economies necessary for the expansion of U.S. export markets and foreign investment outlets. Funding provided for multilateral agencies such as the World Bank, IMF, and a variety of regional development banks, along with various bilateral trade and foreign assistance programs, also assisted U.S. Cold War and economic objectives in the Third World. While the spending associated with these programs was instrumental for U.S.; capitalism, narrowly considered, clearly it played a vital role in the promotion of a global capitalism as well as global capitalist rivalry. By the 1970s, the world economy had entered into a crisis that was interpreted by many as a crisis of hegemonic stability. The dominant position of the United States in the post-Vietnam period was under challenge by the rising economic might of Europe and, especially, Japan. U.S. fiscal and payments deficits were becoming a source of serious concern. Simultaneous high rates of inflation and unemployment cast doubts on the ability of Keynesian policies to provide desired microeconomic stability, and there was a growing belief that the Western economies had entered a "post-Fordist" era of production relations in which the big-management, big-labor compromise was subject to renegotiation. Trade protectionism was on the rise, notwithstanding the Tokyo Round of the GATT, with import quotas and voluntary export restraints having replaced tariffs as the preferred protectionist instruments. By the end of the decade, it was apparent that the once seemingly unassailable position of the U.S. econoiriy was under challenge by traditional rivals in Europe and Japan, but alsb by the rising East Asian newly industrialized countries (NICs). The response to this situation of crisis, shared to a greater or lesser extent by the European countries and particularly by Great Britain, was a renewed commitment to liberal ideology and policy practice, at least as they applied
96
INTELLECTUAL FROPERTY RIGHTS
to social expenditure and labor relations. U.S. foreign policy during the 1980s was an intensification of Cold War rhetoric combined with increased military and diplomatic pressure against regimes (e.g., Sandinistan Nicaragua) that evinced a predisposition toward any model that contradicted in any important way the neoliberal prescription for capitalist economic growth and development. The debt crisis of the 1980s opened the way for the imposition of neoliberal reform in many peripheral and semiperipheral countries. Needing to satisfy IMF conditionality requirements for emergency loans, many of these countries were forced to cut social spending, privatize state-owned enterprises, implement tax reforms, deregulate rules pertaining to foreign investment, remove exchange controls, and introduce so-called labor flexibilization policies.9 In the absence of such reforms, countries found themselves effectively isolated from lines of international bank credit necessary to avoid financial crisis and breakdown. The IMF and its sister institution, the World Bank, then became very powerful, supranational institutions, exercising the function of consensual control characteristic of Gramscian hegemony. The genesis of supranational institutions providing order to the world capitalist trading system is to be found in the various treaties established by the Settlement of Westphalia in 1648, following the Thirty-Year War.10 The purpose of these treaties was to protect the property of noncombatants and to lower trade barriers, thus permitting an expansion of world trade even during periods of intense interstate territorialist rivalry (Arrighi 1993, p. 162). The further development of the required institutions, however, necessitated the eventual supersession of the Westphalia System by what Arrighi refers to as free-trade imperialism. He contrasts the two as follows: The Westphalia System was based on the principle that there was no authority operating above the interstate system. Free-trade imperialism, in contrast, established the principle that the laws operating within and between states were subject to the higher authority of a new metaphysical entity—the "world market"—allegedly endowed with supernatural powers greater than anything pope and emperor had ever mastered in the medieval system of rule. (p. 173) Free-trade imperialism, dominated by Great Britain during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, was itself superseded in the twentieth century by a U.S.-led restoration of the Westphalia System. According to Arrighi, this was the result of several factors. First was a process of socialization of war and state making that elevated the claims of political and economic participation of the masses of non-Western peoples and propertyless masses of the
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
97
West. This restoration was accompanied by a process of decolonization of the non-Western parts of the periphery and an increase in state economic management in the West, accompanied byhigh I mass consumption. The United States was uniquely positioned to play a hegemonic role in this restoration in the aftermath of World War II by virtue ;of its commanding economic position. It succeeded in its role, once again, iby virtue of its ability to present its national interests as embodying a universal interest, particularly in the context of the Cold War struggle. Arrighi pays less attention to some jadditional factors that explain the restoration of what he calls a modified Westphalia System under the direction of the United States. First is the advance in the technology of warfare. Nuclear weapons effectively rendered obsolete the notion of interstate rivalry among the industrialized, center countries based on territorialist expansionism. Such rivalry henceforth would have to be based on economic rather than military might.11 Second is the process referred to earlier as the internationalization of capital. With the advent of global finance and production, a territorialist geopolitical strategy is neither required nor justified for capitalist reproduction and expansion. To the contrary, the costs of winning and maintaining a territorial empire are too large relative to its benefits to appeal to a postmodern, profit-maximizing logic. The IOC places a premium on the harmonization of the rules and regulations that govern the treatment of capital. This is an outcome of the mobility of capital and the tendency of states to compete in offerir g a regulatory environment propitious to its reproduction and expansion. The restored Westphalia System of tf.e twentieth and twenty-first centuries is then indeed a modified one, as Arrighi suggests. While the hegemonic state (i.e., the United States) has disproportionate power in defining the general and specific content that constitutes the supranational institutions and their rules of procedure, this same state is also subject to those same institutions and rules. The important point, then, is that under the current interstate system that devolves power to international institutions and agencies, all states, including the hegemonic state, face constraints on their decision making and their ability to act unilaterally. This is often decried as a loss of national sovereignty by those who nostalgically ook back to an earlier era. Hegemony and International Capital A second important implication, again overlooked by Arrighi, who fails to give adequate weight to the IOC perspective, is that the contemporary system under U.S. hegemony is directed by a hegemonic bloc that is not strictly national in its origins and far from nationalist in its motivations and concerns.
98
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
While such institutions as the IMF and World Bank may be disproportionately funded and represented by the United States, their leadership, functionaries, and consultants are actually drawn from all over the world, including even the poorest nations. What the overwhelming majority of these individuals have in common, however, is a shared worldview on neoliberal economic ideology and policy practice that, not coincidentally, is indistinguishable from the dominant view of U.S. academic economists and policy practitioners. This coincidence of perspective is hardly surprising, given that many of the officials of the powerful, supranational agencies, especially those in leadership positions, received their academic training in U.S. (and British) universities. Writing from the IOC perspective, Bryan (1995) argues that the state performs two primary and one secondary function in relation to the accumulation of capital.12 The primary functions involve securing the labor system and securing the monetary system. Securing the labor system refers to establishing the institutions and legal arrangements whereby capital is provided with an adequate supply of labor, without which the production and appropriation of surplus value could not occur. Securing the monetary system refers to provision and regulation of the money supply, without which commodity circulation and capital's realization cannot occur. The secondary function of the state is to mediate between the often conflicting interests of the different parts of social capital. That is, the state sets down the rules within which otherwise anarchic economic competition takes place.13 Ambiguities (contradictions) arise in the specific formulations of state policies inasmuch as divisions exist between particular capitals (portions of overall social capital) as they relate to the process of international accumulation. A task of the state, then, is to mediate among the divergent interests of these fractions of social capital. Bryan writes: In securing the conditions of accumulation, the nation state will implement policies which advance the interests of some parts of capital at the expense of other parts of capital, and not out of some "higher" aggregate good, but simply because competition makes capital's requirements of state policy incompatible. (1995, p. 87) What makes the realization of these functions especially problematical since the 1970s is the increased international mobility of capital. In securing the conditions for the production, circulation, and realization of value under an accumulation regime that includes international mobility of capital, state policy itself assumes an international dimension. Hence it is no more correct to speak of domestic economic policy than it is to speak of domestic capital accumulation.
CAPITAL. CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
99
Bryan interprets the redirection of maproeconomic policy since the 1970s in terms of the balance of payments constraint. Prior to the 1970s, the conventional maeroeconomic wisdom in dealing with payments deficits involved a reliance on exchange rate adjustments and accommodating short-run capital flows (Keynesianism), or monetary [management (monetarism) to provide long-run internal balance (stable price, full employment equilibrium) and external payments balance. What this conventional wisdom failed to appreciate was that international capital movements during the 1970s were increasingly of the autonomous variety Moreover, they were growing increasingly larger and more destabilizing for the purposes of maeroeconomic management. As a result, maeroeconomic policy became increasingly internationally oriented. The reorientation of maeroeconomic policy in turn has had important implications for international trade policy, with which it is now inextricably linked. Whereas prior to the 1970s the conventional arguments for free trade were couched in terms of the doctrine of comparative advantage, more recently trade policy has turned toward justifications expressed in terms of competitive advantage. The difference between these two is understood as follows. Comparative advantage is said to be based on differences in nations' endowments of productive resources, geography, climates, and other "natural" conditions of production, resulting n differences in relative productive efficiencies leading to differences in autarky prices. The notion of competitive advantage differs inasmuch as it explicitly recognizes the international mobility of capital. It is this mobility, in fact, that accounts for the autonomous capital flows that confounded the expectations of standard maeroeconomic theory and policy. In the context of international trade theory and policy, the implications are equally important. The main implication is that policy makers must be concerned with a nation's ability to attract capital (credit and investment) that is in essence international in its origins and allegiances. More properly, international capital is said to have no national allegiance; its one and only motivation is to secure as high a rate of profit (surplus value) as possible. The ability to attract mobile capital then depends on an industry's ability to achieve and maintain high levels of productivity, or rates of surplus value, in Marxist terminology. Once again, Bryan is keen to point out that the issue of productivity applies to industries rather than to the nation as a whole. Policies, then, are appropriately directed to promoting productivity advances at the industry level. This applies to initiatives that promote advances in existing industries as well as to the promotion of new, technologically sophisticated industries. The search for competitive advantage as an objective of the state has been widely referred to as "industrial policy."
100
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
101
State policy promotes productivity gains for industries, as noted by Bryan, by securing the money supply and the labor supply. In recent years, securing the labor supply has meant gaining a greater degree of control over institutions whose ostensible function is the representation of labor, including unions and labor laws and regulations. The state must also mediate competition among and between individual capitals inasmuch as individual firms will differ in the manner and conditions that link them in the global accumulation process. In this perspective, the state is an arena of struggle for individual capitals. Under the stimulus provided by the balance of payments constraint, the winners in this struggle to influence the specific content of state policies will be those that are most able to engage in the inherently competitive process of global capital accumulation.
support those policies that promote the position of domestic companies or that make the domestic economy an attractive place for internationally mobile capital to locate. Labor is expected under this nationalistic banner to assume an attitude of cooperation as a sort of junior partner in an arrangement that privileges the requirements of -this capital with the promise that benefits will flow downward in labor's direction as well. The appeal to patriotic policy, says Bryan, is also employed as a means to individuate among and between nations and acts as a sort of nontariff barrier between each nation's workers. In this way, the inherently international process of capital's reproduction and expansion takes on the appearance of nationality and crossnational working-class conflict.
The state's response to this competition among capitals also has implications for the world's working classes. The burden of competition in the pursuit of internationally mobile capital falls primarily on workers, who must offer higher rates of surplus value (i.e., productivity increases) while accepting lower wages. For these same working classes, however, the competition is typically presented not as a global competition among international capitals and the states that attempt to procure for them the necessary conditions for their expanded reproduction, but rather as a competition among and between nations. Like the Gramscian hegemonic theorists, Bryan tells us that the construction of a concept of "national interest" reflects the interests of the dominant part of capital, which seeks the allegiance of labor. This concept of national interest is a misreading of reality, however, when it presupposes that capital accumulation is an inherently national process served by national economic policies. The recent emphasis on "national competitiveness" makes palatable economic policies that promote international accumulation at the level of individual capitals (enterprises) by providing them with a patina of concern for national welfare. Bryan writes:
A Critical and Eclectic Theory of the State in the Global Economy
Yet in applying national policy to international accumulation, there is not an abandonment of national agendas. The contradiction between the internationality of national accumulation and the nationality of state regulation is not solved by the subordination of the latter to the former, but by the role of the state policy being recast so that the dominance of global calculation is presented as beneficial for all nationals. In particular, the working class in each nation must be convinced that the pursuit of international competitiveness is an agenda of labor as well as capital, (p. 186) Bryan elaborates on this important point concerning ideological control by explaining the relevance of "patriotism as economic policy." According to this conception, "patriotism" requires the citizens of a particular nation to
I wish to propose here a theory of the state that is both critical and eclectic. The term "critical" is used here in a dual way. First, "critical" is used to suggest an approach that rejects mainstream (i.e., realist, liberal) interpretations of both the state and of economicj laws and categories as providing ideological justification for prevailing institutions and power relations, including established notions of intellectual property rights as codified in the TRIPS agreement. Second, the term "critical" is also used to refer to an approach that selectively adopts elements from the several theoretical approaches outlined above while rejecting those elements that are found not useful to the particular project at hand—that is, of providing a cogent political economy analysis of the TRIPS a; it applies to the poor countries. My approach is also eclectic in the senss that it combines the useful elements of these same theories, each of which has its roots in the Marxian political economy tradition. This stylized combination of "critical eclecticism" is what I understand to be the essence of a dialectical investigatory method. The idea of confronting theory with historical structures, rather than abstracting from these via invocation of ceteris paribus, also gains endorsement from Cox, who writes as fellows: Dialectic is introduced, first, by deriving the definition of a particular structure, not from some abstract model of a social system or mode of production, but from a study of the historical situation to which it relates, and second, by looking for the emergence of rival structures expressing alternative possibilities of development. (1986, p. 220) An important insight arising from the study of Bryan's IOC approach is simply that, nations are important- By this Bryan means that (1) the func-
102
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
tioning of the international capitalist economy does not have the same effects everywhere in the world, and (2) how particular nations articulate themselves in the global accumulation process depends, in part, on the exercise of state power. What Bryan and the IOC perspective demonstrate is that notwithstanding these facts, no meaningful distinction may be drawn between national accumulation and accumulation on a world scale. What the IOC perspective neglects to give explicit emphasis to, however, is the differences between nations and degree of this articulation of nations with respect to the global accumulation process. A salient contribution of the world systems school, meanwhile, is its ability to explain the historical development by which various nations have become enmeshed in the global capitalist system. In this system, it is undeniably true that nations differ in the concrete mechanisms by which capital is transferred and operates to produce surplus value. Moreover, national differences account for the particular social relations of production by which surplus is appropriated and redirected around the world. All of this is well described by the IOC approach in its treatment of the three circuits of capital. It also seems clear, however, in keeping with the WST approach, that the process of capital accumulation and expanded reproduction has given rise to a particular spatial and hierarchical international division of labor whose form continues to be dictated by international capital in a manner that relegates more exploitative functions to peripheral and semiperipheral locations while maintaining relatively less exploitative functions in the center. It follows that if particular nations enter into the internationalization of capital on different historical terms and conditions, and if they perform differing functions in the process of capital's expansion and reproduction, then particular national states will have both differential limitations and impacts on the functioning of the system itself. Herein resides the meaning of hegemony and of the hegemonic state. While it may be true, as suggested by the IOC view, that the United States government does not ultimately exercise its power and influence in promoting a national capitalist agenda considered apart from the interests of international capital, it remains decidedly true that the U.S. government exercises disproportionate power in the shaping of the infrastructure within which the process of global accumulation takes place. It is also true that the technologically advanced, industrialized countries, referred to by world systems theorists as the center countries, possess greater ability than the peripheral and semiperipheral countries in this same function, even if it is true that they also serve global, rather than national or regional, ends. Identification of the United States as the hegemonic state in the modern world system derives from its ability to impose the necessary order not in the
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
103
interest of U.S. capitalist competitiveness, but rather in the interest of global capital accumulation, in which U.S. capitalism claims a disproportionate share. From this perspective, then, there is no inconsistency in the claims that U.S. international policy initiatives advance ai universal interest. This universal interest is a class interest, rather than a general welfare interest. That the United States rather than some other center country occupies the position of hegemonic state derives from the historical circumstances described above. These historical circumstances explain why U.S. culture, law, and institutions are more completely grounded in economic liberalism than those of any other existing state. The internationalization of capital requires maximum liberalism subject to the constraints identified by Bryan as the functions of state power—securing the rhoney system, securing the labor system, and the mediation of the contradictory interests of different parts of capital. The extension of U.S.-style culture, laws, and institutions to the global economy, designed precisely to secure these functions on behalf of the worldwide corporate bourgeoisie, is what is best understood by the term neoliberalism. Neoliberalism and Hegemony Neoliberalization traces its beginnings to th $ creation of the post-World War II supranational organizations that were desi *ned to promote the internationalization of capital. The most notable of these were the IMF, the World Bank, and the GATT. These institutions had; as their fundamental purpose the establishment of conditions (exchange rate stability, open markets) necessary to the facilitation of international trade ((international circulation of commodity capital) and international investment (international circulation of productive and money capital). Each of them is also distinguished in its historical origins by the heavy hand of U.S. diplomacy and economic dominance in the postwar period.w Voting power in the IMF and World Bank is determined on the basis of contributions of money capital to the organizations. By this formula, the United States has had a dominant voice since the inception of their operations. The administration and operation of the GATT were carried out on a nominally more democratic basis, with each country given equal voting power in resolving trade disputes -and subject to the same codes of conduct. The effective operation of GATT, however, was always a matter of deliberation and negotiation among and between the industrialized (center) countries, with the peripheral and semiperipheral countries assuming a marginal role. The United States was able to shape the character of the world trading system to its advantage through its ability to influence the negotiating agenda and the inclusion of various exceptions and escape clauses. Its
104
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
use of unilateral trade policy also gave the United States an unparalleled advantage over others in dictating the conditions of international exchange, including market access. The ability of GATT to promote a liberal trading system from its inception through the early 1970s (Tokyo Round) was limited at best. Large categories of commodities, such as agriculture, textiles, and services, were largely unaffected. While average levels of tariffs were substantially reduced, nations were able to replicate their protectionist effects via a variety of nontariff barriers (e.g., quotas, voluntary export restraints) as well as widespread invocation of the various escape clauses embedded in the agreement. Domestic political pressure for protection among the center developed countries was driven by continuing economic crisis provoked, in part, by rising international commodity prices and falling profit rates in the center. The 1980s, led by President Ronald Reagan in the United States and Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher in Great Britain, saw the full flowering of neoliberalism, defined domestically by a reduction in taxes and in the industrial regulatory oversight functions of the state. In poor countries, neoliberalism was aided and abetted by an external debt crisis that provided ideological justification and real political leverage for a wide variety of economic reform programs that had the effect of rendering these countries more open both to global market forces as well as to international agreements that facilitated capital's global expansion. Countries seeking relief from the burden of external debt obligations were often forced into negotiations with the IMF and World Bank. Emergency finance is provided by these institutions on the condition that certain changes be made in the structure and functioning of the soliciting countries' social and economic institutions. Often these reforms have as a goal "greater labor marketflexibility,"a euphemism for steps required to dismantle labor unions and other protections for workers. In this regard, the country is frequently enjoined to mimic the labor market conditions that prevail in countries that have achieved higher rates of economic growth. The United States, once again, is found to be the model par excellence for reform, and the ideology of market neoliberalism, combined with liberal structural reform, is advanced as a recipe for securing the conditions for stable economic growth. The neoliberal recipe unabashedly promotes the accumulation and expanded reproduction of capital on an international scale, while it also presents itself as the only good alternative to economic stagnation and even retrogression in the poor countries. Neoliberal doctrines were widely adopted as the basis for policies of new governing elites in so-called transition economies.15 The concept of "transition" is understood to apply to an intellectual, ideological conversion as much as to a structural, institutional transformation.
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
105
That is, neoliberalism had become an integral part of the knowledge structure of the body of policy makers, international consultants, international financial managers, and other opinion makers exerting their influence in all parts of the expanding global system.16 Neoliberalism had become hegemonic. The Emergent Global Capitalist State As noted earlier, the infrastructure for an incipient global capitalist state has been developing since as early as the seventeenth century. This development accelerated during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, only to be interrupted by world war and economic crisis. It is useful to conceptualize the particular contents of this emergent infrastructure in terms of Bryan's taxonomy of primary and secondary state functions—securing the monetary system, securing the labor supply (primary), and mediating conflict between capitals. The task of securing the international monetary system was performed in the nineteenth century by the classical gold standard, which both provided a source of liquidity necessary to facilitate the international circulation of commodity andfinancecapital (international trade and investment) and provided monetary discipline for the constituent nations that composed the system. Not coincidentally, the gold standard also helped to secure the hegemonic position of England in the international cap: talist system as well. While international crises interrupted the functioning of the gold standard in the first half of the twentieth century, a transformed version of it was established after World War II in the form of the Brettor Woods system. In this version, of course, the U.S. dollar replaced gold as th«; anchor commodity to the international monetary system, just as the United States had replaced Great Britain as the hegemonic power in the global capitalist economy. While the Bretton Woods international monetary system functioned imperfectly for less than thirty years, it did enable a dramatic expansion of trade and international investment. Even after the demise of the formal system of fixed exchange rates in 1971, the Bretton Woods institutions (IMF and World Bank) have continued to play important roles in opening ihe periphery and semiperiphery to capitalist penetration. The problem of securing labor supply on an international level also received some attention by the formation of a supranational organization. The International Labor Organization (ILO) was established early in the twentieth century during a period of intense international struggle for ideological hegemony in the wake of the Russian Revolution. The modus operandi for the ILO was to establish minimally acceptable standards for the treatment of workers by their employers. Signatory Rations to the organization's charter were expected to enact and enforce laws-to ensure that these standards were
106
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
met. These nations' labor practices are regularly monitored and reports are prepared detailing the degree to which particular countries fall short in their commitments. Those that are found to be lacking in compliance to the various conventions promulgated by the organization are then subject to moral suasion to bring about the desired reforms. The limitations of the ILO as an effective advocate for the workers of the world are fairly obvious. The first resides in the organization's tripartite administrative structure. Representatives are chosen from each nation's labor, industrial, and government sectors, each of which is given equal status and powers of representation in the organization's deliberative bodies. Conflict then is endemic to the organization at multiple levels. Within any particular national representation, conflicts, essentially class-based, separate the interests of national labor and national capital. Added to these are conflicts that arise in the struggle for influence or control over (national) state policy in regard to labor rights. A national position on securing labor supply in the context of the ILO, then, becomes a displaced, or reflected, manifestation of domestic class conflict, albeit with an important qualification. Compounding these conflicts are those that represent the competing claims of nations. That is, national differences in labor law and standards are typically treated as part of the struggle for competitive advantage, and labor is faced with a question of dividing loyalties between class and nation. Neither has the ILO ever had an effective enforcement mechanism to protect the rights of workers. Countries have frequently been found in violation of the various conventions without suffering any real, material sanctions, as they might if they had been found in violation of the GATT. Moreover, many signatory nations have never even ratified the ILO's most important conventions. The fact that these gaps exist in the most fundamental aspects of the ILO's administrative capabilities raises serious doubts about its abilities to advance the interests of the world's working population and suggests that its more important function is as an additional pillar in the construction of consensual hegemony. Extending the reach of supranational governmental institutions has also fulfilled the third of Bryan's functional definitions of the state—mediation of conflict between capitals. This functional purpose was given great support in the course of the Uruguay Round of GATT/WTO negotiations by the inclusion of an agreement on trade-related investment measures, or TRIMS.'7 The purpose of the TRIMS agreement was to eliminate restrictions on the ability of international capital to locate anywhere in the world and operate freely in the competitive pursuit of surplus (profit). TRIMS are then understood as those restrictions placed by host governments on TNCs in their operations. An example would be local content requirements that increase the
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
107
demand for domestic inputs in the production process of the corporation and thereby promote domestic employment A second example might involve an export performance requirement that calls for a particular level or percentage of the TNCs local production to be exported in order to alleviate a foreign exchange bottleneck. Still a third [example would require the TNC to transfer technology to local producers in ways that the foreign producer is not inclined in the absence of the requirement. Clearly, the implication of restrictions such as these is the real possibility that the TNC will not be able to realize the same level of profit that itlmight otherwise, since the requirements are imposed by a host government whose objectives are not identical with TNC profit maximization.18 The United States first introduced proposals for a TRIMS agreement following the 1982 meeting of GATT ministers. Support for the proposals was provided by the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD) countries with the exception of Australia, and opposition came from a group of semiperipheral and peripheral countries, especially India, Brazil, Argentina, Mexico, Egypt, Hungary, and the Asian NICs. The effort to bring TRIMS into the purview of the GATT proceeded apace during the 1990s and finally bore fruit at the conclusion of the Uruguay Round in 1993 with an agreement to ban all TRIMS that called for local content and trade-balancing requirements. The agreement was to be phased in over five years for the poorer countries and to apply immediately for all others.19 A similar story can be told about U.S. leadership in establishing a new GATT/WTO regime, the General Agreem;mt on Trade Services (GATS). In recent decades, service trade has increasin, ly come to displace trade in merchandise in the U.S. current account. The ategory of service trade includes financial services, which have grown very rapidly, along with the trend toward deregulation and liberalization of the financial sectors of many countries that had previously placed substantial controls on credit markets. The important point here is that beginnir g with the creation of the Bretton Woods institutions following World War II, and accelerating since the crisis years of the 1970s, neoliberalism and globalization have conjoined to create an expanded international regime of accumulation requiring supranational regulatory institutions. This point is expressed very well by Yaghmaian (1998) who writes; The emerging accumulation requires the formation of suitable regulatory mechanisms to guarantee free mobility of all forms of capital and the removal of spatial constraints upon the circuits of money, productive and commodity capital. The internationalization of capital requires the creation of global (supranational) institutions^ and regulatory arrangements to guar-
108
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
antee the smooth reproduction of internationalized wage relations, and secure the regime of international accumulation. The regulatory requirements of international accumulation are institutionalized through the ascendancy of global neoliberalism. (1998, p. 253, emphasis in original) It is in this context that an understanding of the recent TRIPS agreement must be placed. The TRIPS, like the TRIMS and GATS, is another product of the Uruguay Round, a particularly fruitful moment for global capital. The TRIPS fulfills a state function surprisingly overlooked by Bryan in his taxonomy—that of securing (intellectual) property. It does this by defining knowledge as property, transforming passive knowledge into active knowledge, in May's terminology. It then provides the regulatory infrastructure to ensure that active knowledge functions as capital. It is premature to characterize this collection of supranational institutions and regulatory mechanisms as a global state, for several reasons. First, the range and depth of regulatory functions performed by the IMF, World Bank, GATTAVTO, and other entities are insufficient to the tasks demanded by an authentic state, even one committed to neoliberalism. The global political economy has a long way to go before it achieves the degree of integration to be managed by a unitary international authority. And this, of course, is another way of saying that individual nation-states retain a substantial degree of autonomy over their policy making. Even where substantial autonomy has been ceded to the historical movement in the direction of wider integration, the process in many cases seems to have reached a temporary equilibrium at the regional level. Second, what follows is that national policy itself is still obviously important and remains an important arena for intranational class conflict. Thus, it remains true that even for the United States, the hegemonic state in shaping the content and style of the emerging supranational regulatory institutions, contradictions abound in the behavior of the state as it pursues its mediation function. Third, inasmuch as state power remains an object of contention among and between classes at the national level, the increasing global character of class remains obscure. This observation is entirely instrumental to the purposes of the (global) capitalist hegemonic bloc insofar as it operates against the formation of an effective counterhegemonic bloc,At the same time, however, it also renders more difficult the task of resolving the contradictions in state policy alluded to above. Fourth, owing to the still early stages of the process of IOC, it is clear that there remains substantial unevenness in the integration and articulation of national accumulation processes with the process of global accumulation. This unevenness also is the historical legacy of imperialist penetration of the periphery by the capitalist center.
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
109
The result is that the world remains composed of nations and nation-states differentiated in their respective abilities to shape the character of the emerging global economy, its governing regulatory institutions and mechanisms, and the terms of their incorporation intb the global economy. All of this is to suggest that it is far too premature to suggest, as some have done, that we have arrived at a postimperialist age. Having arrived at an interpretation of state power in the global capitalist system, I shall attempt to show in the following chapter how the TRIPS agreement was constructed to perform its specific international regulatory functions. Subsequent chapters will demonstrate the consequences of the agreement for two important lines of productive activity, each of which carries distinctive implications for human Swell-being as well as for the likely future of the TRIPS agreement itself. Appendix: Hymer on the Internationalization of Capital and the Law of Uneven Development An early IOC writer is Stephen Hymer (1979), who sees an oligopolistically organized multinational corporate system as the vehicle facilitating the IOC. He sees the development of this system as analogous to the development of the national corporation in the United Slates in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries in terms of the socialization of capital. He writes: [T]he national corporation abolished "private" property through collectivization and gave it a social character as essentially the common capital of a class. The overriding interest of this class is not the war of each against each, but the common need of all to naintain the capitalist society, that is, the rights of property to income and 1 he assurance of an adequate supply of labor to generate that income. Similarly, the multinational corporate system tends to abolish national capital and create a world system in which output is produced cooperatively to i greater degree than ever before, but control remains uneven; capitalists, as trustees of society, continue to pocket a good share of the proceeds, (p. 84; At the same time, however, Hymer sees the emerging world capitalist economy as very uneven in its development and hierarchically arranged in its social and productive organization. Again he writes: [A] regime of North American multinational corporations would tend to produce a hierarchical division of labor between geographical regions corresponding to the vertical division of labor within the firm. It would tend to
IfO
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
centralize high-level decision-making occupations in a few cities in the advanced countries, surrounded by a number of regional sub-capitals, and confine the rest of the world to lower levels of activity and income, i.e., to the status of towns and villages in a New Imperial System, (p. 55) Hymer seems quite able to reconcile the IOC and WST approaches into a coherent account of the operation of multinational corporations and their consequences for uneven capitalist development. This unevenness is seen to be the outcome of the multinational corporation's ability to reproduce on the scale of the global economy the hierarchical structure that is internal to the firm itself. While technology is instrumental to its ends, the determining factor is the organization of the giant corporation. It must be stressed that the dependency relationship between major and minor cities should not be attributed to technology. The new technology, because it increases interaction, implies greater interdependence but not necessarily a hierarchical structure It is not technology which creates inequality; rather it is organization that imposes a ritual judicial asymmetry on the use of intrinsically symmetrical means of communications and arbitrarily creates unequal capacities to initiate and terminate exchange, to store and retrieve information, and to determine the extent of the exchange and terms of the discussion. Just as colonial powers in the past linked each point in the hinterland to the metropolis and inhibited lateral communications, preventing the growth of independent centers of decision making and creativity, multinational corporations (backed by state powers) centralize control by imposing a hierarchical system, (p. 66) Finally, it is worth noting what Hymer has to say about the implications of the IOC regarding the need for and exercise of state power. Like many commentators on the contemporary globalization process, he believes that the spread of power of the multinational corporation would have the effect of undermining the traditional powers of the national state. As the following quotation makes clear, however, this does not necessarily imply the end of the state as such. International government refers to the erosion of-the traditional powers of nation-states and the emergence of international policy instruments in line with the tendency of the multinational corporation to internationalize capital and labor. When a corporation invests abroad, it not only sends capital and management out, but also establishes a system for drawing foreign capital and labor into an integrated world network. When many firms from many countries do this together on an expanded scale, as has been true over the
CAPITAL, CLASS, AND THE STATE IN THE GLOBAL ECONOMY
111
last decade and will be true in the next, they are forming a new world system. They are unifying world capital ^nd world labor into an inter-locking system of cross-penetration that completely changes the system of national economies that has characterized world capitalism for the past three hundred years. This process reduces the independence of nation-states and requires the formation of supranational institutions to handle the increased interdependence. To create a world market where state frontiers disappear, a world system is needed in which the separate interests, laws, governments, and systems of taxation and regulation are lumped together into a unified code of laws on the rights and limits of private property, (p. 76)
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
5 The Political Economy of TRIPS
The agreement on trade-related intellectual property rights (TRIPS) became a part of the international regulatory infrastructure as a result of negotiations leading up to and concluding the Uruguay Round of the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) at the close of 1994. The agreement entered into effect in 1995 and bound its signatory nations to an array of obligations that would effectively harmonize the rules regarding patents, trademarks, copyrights, and trade secrets at levels approximating those found in the United States, the nation with undoubtedly the most demanding set of standards for the protection of intellectual property in the world. The agreement is a 'remarkable negotiating and political achievement for several reasons. First, the agreement was struck in spite of the strong initial objections of many of the participants to the negotiations and only the lukewarm support of several others. The countries that most strongly opposed the agreement, such as Brazil, India, and Korea, are characterized by a desire both to have cheap access to foreign knowledge-intensive goods and services and to possess substantial indigenous technology sectors of their own. The countries that supported the TRIPS, in some cases only weakly, have well-developed technology-intensive productive capacities. These countries include the European nations and Japan. In general, these countries have well-developed laws regarding the treatment of intellectual property rights, though in many cases the legal standard is not as demanding as that which exists in the United States. By far, the United States was the dominant voice advocating on behalf of the TRIPS agreement. Second, the agreement does not have a direct bearing on the vast majority of traded goods and services that constitute the bulk of trade in the world system. Rather, its most important application is to a'narrow range of commodities and processes that are characterized by high initial fixed costs of production combined with very low marginal costs of duplication. Under these circumstances, the attractiveness of unauthorized imitation is quite obvious. Outstanding examples of such goods include pharmaceuticals, films and recordings, and computer software. Industries such as these produce 112
113
outputs of considerably high value, but they do not involve a large number of producing firms. Third, the agreement was struck in the absence of demonstrable evidence of its necessity to the promotion of the world's welfare. Without a doubt, the agreement will have a very positive effect|on the fortunes of some industries and individuals. Equally doubtless, however, is that these benefits will come at a considerable cost to the welfare of others, at least in the short run. Neither does the available evidence make a Convincing case that the long-run welfare of the world's majority is best served by the global harmonization of intellectual property rights as called for by the TRIPS.1 The question naturally arises then, Why was the TRIPS agreement successfully established as part of the governing regulatory infrastructure for the world economy? The answer is a matter of political economy. That is to say, we can understand why the TRIPS was established, and what role it can be expected to perform, only when we understand the political and economic forces that called forth its existence and the interests they serve. Necessarily, a political economic analysis requires a corresponding theory of the state. This theory was described in the preceding chapter in some detail and is briefly summarized here. Beginning in this aftermath of World War II and accelerating after 1973, the capitalist world system has adopted a new, global regime of accumulation. This regime oi accumulation is characterized by an unprecedented international mobility of capital. Capital is understood in each of its forms of circulation as commodity, money, and productive capital The internationalization of capital has created the need for a set of regulatory, supranational institutions in order n delimit the competition among and between individual capitals while perrritting global capitalist accumulation to proceed. The fact that these supranational institutions have emerged does not mean that individual nation-state s are made irrelevant. Individual nation-states still must mediate among ana between the demands made by the individual capitals within their jurisdictions. Nation-states also attempt to imprint the substance and rules of proce lure of the supranational institutions. A nation is described as hegemonic :f it possesses a disproportionate ability to shape the structure and functioning of these institutions and to otherwise dictate the terms on which global capitalist accumulation occurs. It does not follow from this that the hegemonic state exercises hegemony strictly in the interests of a domestic class or classes. Given the current global regime of accumulation based on internationalization of capital, hegemony is necessarily exercised based on the requirements for the expanded reproduction of global capital. In class terms, hegemony is exercised on behalf of the objective needs of an international hegemonic (historic) bloc that seeks to present its own class interest as the universal interest.
114
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
The TRIPS agreement is best understood as one of several regulatory mechanisms designed to facilitate the international accumulation of capital. It operates to define and protect international property rights and thereby mediate in the international competition among and between individual capitals whose interests in regards to knowledge-based production often conflict. The purpose of this chapter is to trace the historic evolution of the agreement within the context of the theory of the state just described. It is also to demonstrate how the agreement should be expected to operate in service to the needs of global capital accumulation and the implications of its operation for the reproduction of social (class) relations on which accumulation is based. The Precursors to TRIPS The TRIPS agreement is not a sui generis institution. It is historically and logically predated by a number of international agreements that have advanced the cause of protection for intellectual property. The two most important of these, the Paris and Berne conventions, were established in the late nineteenth century. The Paris Convention The Paris Convention for the Protection of Intellectual Property was signed in 1883 to provide protection to holders of patents, trademarks, industrial designs, and marks of origin by the "repression of unfair competition." The Paris Convention does not stipulate minimum common standards across countries for the protection of intellectual property (IP). Neither does it require that a nation provide protection to specific forms of IP nor that it conform to particular rules as regards compulsory licensing, for example. It does require that signatory nations provide national treatment for the IP that emanates from all other signatory nations. That is to say, a nation's IP law must be applied on an equal basis to foreign and domestic claim-holders, and foreigners have recourse to the same legal remedies in cases involving alleged infringements of rights. The convention also provides a means by which claims of priority in an invention may be established throughout the membership, should disputes arise surrounding such claims. While the Paris Convention was initially established as an agreement among countries that were like-minded in their treatments of intellectual property rights, it has been modified and expanded over time in both its specific content and in the number of signatory nations. Today, over one hundred nations are signatories to the convention, most of which are less developed countries (LDCs).
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
115
The Berne Convention The Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works was signed in 1886 and amended over the years to provide copyright protection for published works, defined broadly to include books, articles, pamphlets, musical compositions, drawings, paintings, ;and other forms of artistic expression. Protection of the latter is not provided to particular performances, but only to the works themselves. Neither may "ideas" as such, as they might be embodied in a published work, for exarriple, enjoy protection, but only the particular writing itself. The minimum p|eriod of protection required by the convention is fifty years after the lifetinjte of the author. Like the Paris Convention, the Berne Convention is based oh the principles of nondiscrimination and national treatment. The range of membership for the Berne Convention is substantially broader than for the Paris Convention. One interpretation for the disparity is that less developed (peripheral) countries are more likely to have artists and performers who would demand such protection than they would have inventors who demand patent protection. Interestingly, until; 1988 the United States was not a Berne signatory because its national copyright law failed to conform to the requirements of the convention. In particular, U.S. copyright law differed from the Beme requirements insofar as the 'moral rights" of authors were concerned. Moral rights are those that have nothing necessarily to do with economic issues but bear on such matters as the rights of authors after original copyright has been transferred to another party.2 The Berne Convention stipulates that these rights be protected, while the U.S. federal statute was less demanding. As an alternative to the Berne Convention, the United States negotiated under the auspices of the United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) the Universal Copyright Convention (UCC) in 1952. While the UCC was fully consistent with U.S;. law, it included fewer signatories nations as members and provided less protection than the Berne agreement. Moreover, it carried the proviso that English language works published by U.S. authors be printed in the United State (Stalson 1987, pp. 25-26). The World Intellectual Property Organization and Its Limitations The supranational institution that held primary responsibility for the administration of intellectual property rights agreements for most of the twentieth century was the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO), headquartered in Geneva. WIPO operated informally; as the combined secretariat of the Paris and Berne conventions and was formally established in 1967. It
116
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
became part of the United Nations system in 1974 (Ryan 1998, pp. 126127). WIPO is regarded as the preeminent institution in the world as regards technical matters bearing on intellectual property rights (IPRs). It is also regarded, particularly by those with a keen interest in strengthening IPRs, as an institution with very serious limitations—limitations that are shared by the international agreements it is charged with administering. The major limitation of the Paris Convention from the perspective of U.S. businesses, according to Stalson (1987), is the agreement's inability to defend patents. The convention does not stipulate that signatory countries meet any particular standard for patent provision and protection. All it requires is that the national standard be applied in a nondiscriminatory fashion. Logically, then, if a country's law provides no patent protection to domestic individuals or firms, it is perfectly compliant in providing no such protection to foreign claimants. A second major limitation of the Paris Convention often cited by its critics is its treatment of compulsory licensing. The original convention stipulated that a member nation retained the right to compel a patent holder to issue a license whenever the patent holder's monopoly on the patented product or process threatened abuses of monopoly power. Abuse of monopoly power certainly would include restriction of output with a view toward pushing prices high above the cost of production in pursuit of surplus profit. The most frequently cited abuse, however, involves the failure to produce at all— that is, the failure to "work the patent." From the patent holder's perspective, the profit-maximizing logic might require that the patent be worked in only a few locations and other, far-flung markets served by exports. From the patentgranting country's perspective, however, patent rights that do not contribute employment and technology transfer are of very limited usefulness. Compulsory licensing is often also invoked for products and production processes that serve some necessary and immediate social welfare purpose, such as fighting disease or an environmental calamity.3 Still a third shortcoming of the Paris Convention identified by U.S. businesses with IP interests is its neglect of process patents. In some cases, patents on particular products have lapsed or have been deemed impermissible, but the process for their production may be novel and especially efficient. The developer of such a process will then have an interest in an exclusionary right to employ or sell the process. Stalson argues that while most developed countries recognize the legitimacy of such claims and extend the reach of their patent law to include process patents, the same cannot be said for LDCs. Many LDCs, in fact, lack the legal discovery procedures that would force alleged patent infringers to reveal sufficient information on their production methods necessary to bring a complaint (1987, p. 24).
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
117
WIPO is unique among United Nations organizations in that its activities render the organization capable of self-finance. In particular, WIPO provides patent application services, for which it charges a fee, under the Patent Cooperation Treaty (PCT). Under the PCT, those who wish to establish a patent in multiple countries submit a single application to WIPO, which acts as a clearinghouse for all member countries! simultaneous consideration. The process establishes the applicant's priority of claim to the patent and saves substantial time and expense that would! otherwise be incurred in multiple national application procedures. Given the increase in applications submitted to WIPO under the PCT, the WIPO's dependence on country contributions to sustain its activities has been reduced to almost trivial levels. Ryan estimates, for example, that the portion df WIPO's budget accounted for by U.S. official contributions was 1.5 percent of the organization's total budget in 1990 (1998, p. 129). This is a far srhaller portion than for most other United Nations agencies and substantially less than for the budgets of such powerful supranational institutions as the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and World Bank. The self-financing ability of WIPO is a two-edged sword for the United States and the business interests it represents. Unlike decision making in the IMF and World Bank, where effective control is related to financial contribution, WIPO decision making is more eveily dispersed over its membership, which is numerically dominated by peripieral and semiperipheral countries. WIPO does not lend itself, then, to easy hegemonic manipulation. Ryan suggests the frustration of global capital in t lis respect very well: Business enterprises from the industrialized countries praise the teaching function of WIPO—when they know about it. But in general the intellectual property-intensive firms were dissatisfied with the level of protection offered by the international regime administered by the organization. Like other institutions associated with the! United Nations (with its dominance by developing countries), the international intellectual property regime developed with loose rules, weak dispute settlements mechanisms, and no ability to enforce provisions of international treaties. (1998, p. 131) In contrast to the weak enforcement' capabilities of WIPO, the GATT has proven itself quite capable of imposing penalties on countries that were recalcitrant in meeting their obligations as signatory nations. Countries found to be in violation of GATT's provisions are required to desist from the objectionable practices. If they do not, they are subject to compensatory retaliation. While it can hardly be said to operate in an equitable manner, GATT's dispute settlements procedures have operated as an effective
118
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
mechanism to facilitate market access and the circulation of commodity capital around the globe. 4 The GATT is also characterized by an institutional feature that strongly enhances its power as an instrument of hegemonic control. This is the requirement that all signatory nations adhere to all provisions of the GATT. In other words, a nation is not at liberty to pick and choose which provisions of the agreement it will abide by and which it will ignore. Rather, any nation that rejects a particular provision, or side agreement, negotiated under the aegis and constitutive of the GATT will find itself outside of the protections and advantages of the agreement as a whole. Thus the strategy for the transformation of the existing international IPRs regime from a mere statement of ideals into an effective legal infrastructure complete with powers of enforcement became clear—it was made part of the GATT. The Historic Bloc and the Creation of Global Hegemony Gramsci describes his concept of historic bloc as follows: "Structures and superstructures form an 'historic bloc.' That is to say the complex, contradictory and discordant ensemble of the superstructures is the reflection of the ensemble of the social relations of production" (1971, p. 366). This "complex contradictory and discordant ensemble" unites to present its class interest as the universal interest. It necessarily then must sublimate the individual, often conflicting, short-run interests of its constituent parts in order to achieve a more lasting collective objective—namely, hegemony. Rupert elaborates on this notion: An historic bloc articulates a world view, grounded in historically specific socio-political conditions and production relations, which lends substance and ideological coherence to its social power. It follows, then, that hegemonies and historic blocs have specific qualities relating to particular constellations, their underlying class forces and productive relations. They can be conservative or revolutionary. (1993, p. 81) If we accept Rupert's conception, it follows that historic blocs must necessarily adapt to changing historical conditions (namely, specific sociopolitical conditions and production relations). While Gramsci was especially concerned with the requirements for hegemony at the level of the Italian nation-state in the first half of the twentieth century, the question that confronts us at the beginning of the twenty-first century concerns the composition of the historic bloc in the face of the internationalization of capital. Beyond this, we also wish to understand how this adapted historic bloc confronts the problem of the internationalization of IPRs.
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
119
Robert Cox (1993) provides insight into the first of these two questions with his own interpretation of Gramsciaiji hegemony as it bears on the issue of international relations theory. Here Cbx takes care to emphasize that by "hegemony" is not meant the domination of one or several state(s) by another. It is not to be confused with what is ordinarily understood as imperialism (pp. 59-60). Rather, particular states are hegemonic insofar as they are critical to the formation of a historic blocl This bloc, however, is universal in its vision. Cox writes: ! On the basis of this tentative notatipn, it would appear that, historically, to become hegemonic, a state would have to found and protect a world order which was universal in conception, i.e., not an order in which one state directly exploits others but an; order which most states (or at least those within reach of the hegemony) could find compatible with their interests. . . . It would most likely give prominence to opportunities for the forces of civil society to operate on the world scale (or on the scale of the sphere within which hegemony prevails). The hegemonic concept of world order is founded not only upon the regulation of inter-state conflict but also upon a globally conceived civil society, i.e., a mode of production of global extent which brings about links among social classes of the countries encompassed by it. (1993, p. 61) By Cox's criteria, the hegemonic state is not only powerful in its own right but able to project its culture, institutions, technology, and social relations abroad so that they become model > to be emulated even by those nations that have not achieved the same level of development of the material forces and conditions of production. He adds to his description of hegemony the following: Hegemony at the international leve' is thus not merely an order among states. It is an order within a worlct economy with a dominant mode of production which penetrates into all countries and links into other subordinate modes of production. It is also a complex of international social relationships which connect the social classes of the different countries. . . . World hegemony, furthermore, is expressed in universal norms, institutions and mechanisms which lay down general rules of behavior for states and for those forces of civil society that act across national boundaries— rules which support the dominant mode of production. (1993, p. 62) Cox's description suggests that the historic bloc is not composed solely by official (i.e., governmental) elements. Civil society plays at least as important a role in its constitution. As the function of this bloc is to propagate
120
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
universal norms and rules of behavior, it is clear that intellectuals and other cultural standard-bearers have at least as strong an influence in their formulation as lawmakers. The resulting institutions and mechanisms that give operational significance to these norms and rules reflect the real and perceived interests of cross-national classes. Finally, Cox recognizes that one of the important mechanisms of world hegemony is international (supranational) organizations. Such organizations, he argues, possess certain features that are expressive of their hegemonic function: (1) they embody the rules that facilitate the expansion of hegemonic world orders; (2) they are themselves the product of the hegemonic world order; (3) they ideologically legitimate the norms of the world order; (4) they co-opt the elites from peripheral countries; (5) they absorb counterhegemonic ideas. The argument to be made here is that the TRIPS agreement performs precisely these functions. TRIPS and the Extended Global State By institutionalizing on a global scale the IPR regime that exists in the United States, the system's most liberal (from capital's perspective) constituent member nation-state, the TRIPS agreement facilitates the expansion of global capitalism while reinforcing the currently prevailing hierarchy of production and power relations. The technological advantages that capitalism's imperialist history confers on the center of the system are solidified by a harmonization of patent laws. These laws act as an obstacle to the transfer and adaptation of knowledge to the needs of workers and consumers worldwide, especially those residing in the periphery, while preserving for the center-based transnational corporations (TNCs) technological superiority and control. The TRIPS agreement in essence institutionalizes a global division of labor in which an international elite, residing primarily in but not confined to the United States, Europe, and Japan, protects the competitive advantage of these powerful TNCs. The harmonization of IPRs likewise reduces the risk and cost associated with international investment, thus promoting an increase in the circulation of both commodity and money capital, which, again, originates primarily in the center and acts to extract surplus throughout its global operations. In all its aspects then, the TRIPS agreement has the potential to aid in the expansion of the prevailing hegemonic order. The TRIPS agreement was manifestly the product of intense efforts of the hegemonic historic bloc to impose its vision first on the decision-making process of the U.S. state and later on the multilateral negotiations leading up to the Uruguay Round of GATT. Leading this effort were executives of Pfizer Chemical and IBM. Pfizer is one of the largest chemical and pharmaceutical transnational corporations in the world, while IBM is the well-known com-
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
121
puter giant. These companies made effective use of the Advisory Committee on Trade Polity and Negotiation (ACTPN^ set up by the United States Trade Representative (USTR). ACTPN allows businesses to help the USTR articulate its negotiating strategy in bilateral and multilateral forums. In 1986, at the beginning of the Uruguay Round of GATT, the ACTPN was chaired by Edmund T. Pratt, chief executive officer (CJEO) of Pfizer (Ryan 1998, p. 68). Pratt emphasized the importance of making IPRs a priority negotiating issue in the upcoming trade talks. The committee also worked closely with the Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America (PhRMA), which undertook a heavy lobbying effort in the U.S. Congress to convince legislators of the importance of strengthening patent protection across the globe. Also, Pratt and IBM's CEO, John Opel, organized the Intellectual Property Committee (IPC) to coordinate the lobbying efforts of a number of large TNCs on the issue of IPRs and trade. Among the companies represented were chemical and pharmaceutical firms Merck, Johnson & Johnson, Dupont, Bristol-Myers, and Monsanto; entertainment conglomerate Warner Communications; and computer giant Hewlett-Packard (Ryan 1998, p. 69). The IPC not only functions as a lobbying organization for the firms it represents, but also works very closely with the USTR in formulating policy and negotiating strategy. The organization, for example, has a direct hand in formulating reports on the compliance records of foreign countries in regard to domestic IP law and international agreements. This organization also makes recommendations to the USTR regarding unilateial sanctions on countries it deems to be engaging in "unfair trading practices" based on alleged IPR violations. A fundamental task of the historic bloc is to provide ideological legitimacy to the push for the harmonization of IPRs. An important function of such agencies as ACTPN and IPC is to "educate" domestic and international policy makers on IP problems and issues J.S interpreted by the transnational corporate perspective. The agencies are supported in this task by legal experts, public relations specialists, economists, and other communications experts. The fact that the media industries have such a keen interest in the strict interpretation of information as private property is a tremendous advantage for the bloc as a whole. As Chapter 2 made clear, ideological defenses of private property rights in information have encompassed a wide range of philosophic traditions, running from natural law approaches in the seventeenth century to more familiar arguments grounded in the utilitarian tradition. Perhaps the most effective approach in recent years, however, is that which links the necessity for a strong and harmonized global IPR regime to the more general call for global neoliberalism. Neoliberalism preaches that strong economic growth can come about only in the presence of reforms that remove the
122
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
heavy hand of government regulation from the functioning of otherwise efficient private markets. Thus states are urged (often required) to privatize state-owned enterprises, reduce government spending and indebtedness, make labor markets more flexible, remove protectionist trade policies, and reduce or eliminate restrictions on foreign investment, foreign exchange transactions, and international capital movements. The fact that many countries have not arrived at the promised land of economic growth and prosperity despite enacting many of these reforms has not dissuaded the conventional wisdom away from the neoliberal prescriptions. Rather, it has been noted that these reforms are necessary but not in themselves sufficient. In addition to these structural economic reforms, goes the argument, it is necessary also to carry out a number of institutional and juridical reforms. These include all manner of legislation and institution building designed to combat corruption, promote efficiency and transparency, and increase the protection of property. It is in the context of these so-called second-stage reforms that the call for stronger IPRs must be understood. The important point to make here is that by aligning the TRIPS with these neoliberal reforms, the agreement takes on an air of historical necessity and inevitability that is virtually impossible, or at best foolish, to oppose. We can understand from this vantage point, then, the feelings of isolation that the Indian negotiating team felt in its ultimately futile opposition to the TRIPS agreement. In discussing the global contextual factors within which the agreement was negotiated, Sen (2001) writes: The third reason, which was perhaps the most significant, was the debt crisis. This effectively put a large number of countries, including some of the more powerful developing countries, into receivership. International Monetary Fund and World Bank conditionalities were based upon an export dependent strategy, and many of these countries were "advised" to participate constructively in the Uruguay Round negotiations as part of the strategy for recovery. The debt crisis, and the institutional response, also reflected the intellectual ascendancy of the neo-liberal model . . . The cumulative impact of these developments was to erode developing country solidarity, isolate them [Indian negotiators] intellectually, and weaken them tactically. India's efforts to defy this-process within the negotiating process were therefore a little too ambitious, (pp. 8-9) The inevitability hypothesis carries with it the injunction to either "get the institutions right" or otherwise fall further behind in the race to catch up'to the global leaders, or even the late developers, in terms of technical capacity, economic productivity, and, ultimately, a high material standard of living.
123
Negotiations and Co-optation A certain amount of co-optation of developing country elites in the context of the Uruguay Round multilateral economic negotiations was virtually required as a matter of the definition of the success of the negotiations. The GATT World Trade Organization (WTO) negotiations require a consensus agreement in order to arrive at closure! Moreover, as noted earlier, acceptance of the overall GATT/WTO agreement, and whatever perceived benefits derived, requires that the agreement be accepted in its entirety. This requirement, then, presupposes that initial opposition to particular parts of any agreement, such as the TRIPS in thb Uruguay Round, be overcome. One way of overcoming opposition is to seek a genuine compromise on basic issues of disagreement. Alternatively, consensus could be reached by eliminating from the basic negotiating agreement the subtexts that prove especially difficult for some participants to accept. Neither of these was the route chosen during the Uruguay Round in the negotiation of the TRIPS. Rather, the TRIPS was effectively imposed by primarily center country interests by a combination of hegemonic consensus seeking and coercion. Hegemonic consensus seeking operated by expanding the historic bloc to include key elements of the bourgeoisie of the peripheral and semi peripheral countries which were made to see the recessity of the agreement by a process identified as "linkage bargaining;' Linkage bargaining, according to Ryan (1998, p. 12), occurs when a negotiator offers something of value to a counterpart as a means of convincing th(; counterpart to offer concessions on matters considered valuable to the negotiator. This sort of "horse trading" proved especially effective in co-opting elites in the otherwise recalcitrant countries. It was also, I shall argue, consistent with the objectives of what I have referred to as the internationalization of capital. It was not, however, itself a sufficient approach. As will be shown next, blatant coercion also played a key role in the negotiating process. U.S. Trade Policy and Hegemonic Coercion: Alternative Interpretations Recently several international political economy (IPE) and international relations (IR) interpretations of the TRIPS agreement have been advanced that focus oh the role of the United States as a "global hegemon." In contrast to the Gramscian use of the term, the concept of hegemony in this context has more in common with the notion of coercion than it does with ideological consensus. In this section, I would; like to offer a critical review of these interpretations as a means of explicating my own understanding of how the
124
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
TRIPS functions as an instrument of hegemonic coercion and of the role played by the U.S. state. The functioning of the TRIPS as a mechanism of consensual hegemony will be addressed in the succeeding section. Hegemonic Stability and the TRIPS A 1990 study sponsored by United Nations Conference on Trade and Development (UNCTAD) (Van Grasstek 1990) interprets the TRIPS agreement from the perspective of hegemonic stability theory. Here the argument is made that hegemonic countries become more interested in the issue of IPRs and their protection when their hegemonic position in the world economy comes under threat. This occurs at a relatively late stage in the period of their dominance when other countries have emerged as competitive threats. The formal assertion of IPRs then represents a defensive step to protect the erosion of international economic dominance. In the case of the TRIPS, according to the UNCTAD study, the particular hegemon under threat is the United States, though it is recognized that even a relative technological latecomer like Japan has a common interest in the strengthening of IPRs on an international scale. The primary targets of the TRIPS are those developing countries that have sufficient indigenous technological capacity to qualify as potential innovators but are more likely, in the short to medium terms, to be imitators, or outright appropriators, of imported technology. Because it is not necessarily apparent to these countries that a regime of strong IPRs serves the long-run purpose of enhancing global economic welfare, the United States assumes the role of hegemonic leader by bringing the issue into the international forum of GATT7WTO multilateral negotiations. In the context of international trade liberalization discussions, the United States hopes to convince its recalcitrant trading partners of the mutual benefits of an IPR regime that bears a striking resemblance to U.S. law on patents, trademarks, copyrights, and trade secrets. The UNCTAD study appropriately lays important emphasis on the role of hegemony, but like most studies of hegemonic stability it interprets hegemony strictly in terms of the struggle for global power among nation-states. It is clear, however, that in regard to the TRIPS agreement it is the power of transnational capital that is being served by the USTR rather than the United States as a nation. One of the primary objectives of privatelyfinanced,quasiofficial organizations such as the IPC was to eliminate so-called parallel imports. Parallel imports occur when a country is able to import commodities that have been produced under conditions involving alleged IPR violations. Such prohibitions under U.S. law, for example, prevent U.S. consumers from purchasing generic substitutes for expensive, patented pharmaceuticals from
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
125
Canada. Clearly the intent of this law is to preserve the monopoly pricing power of the giant multinational drug manufacturers. The UNCTAD report is more on the rriark in its description of "coercive bilateralism" (Van Grasstek 1990, p. 104). Coercive bilateralism refers to the use of national trade policy to force a nation's trading partners into trade agreements (bilateral or multilateral) that they wjould otherwise eschew. U.S. trade law is well stocked with weapons to be usejd for this purpose. These weapons include two pieces of legislation passed during the Reagan administration. The first is the 1984 Trade and Tariff Act,! which authorizes the president to negotiate international agreements for intellectual property with trading partner countries and to lower trade barriers involving knowledge-based goods and services. The second law is the Omnibus Trade and Competitiveness Act of 1988, which is particularly important as a means of U.S. coercive bilateralism. Specifically, the 1988 law contains a provision known as "Special 301," which calls for commercial retaliation against countries that fail to upgrade their IP law to be more consistent with U.S. law. Special 301 was in turn combined with an update of the 1974 U.S. Trade Law called "Super 301" that identified a list of particular countries that Iwere considered guilty of "unfair trading practices," including those that desalt with knowledge-based goods and services. Super 301 also goes well beyond previous incarnations of aggressive bilateralism inasmuch as it seeks r. erformance standards as opposed to mere procedural standards against which to assess foreign trading partners' willingness to engage in fair trade. This means that the effective test of trade "fairness" is the increase in the U.S. share of trading partner imports and not merely the rules that govern trade in particular commodities. These laws have been used by the United States Trade Representative both to debar imports into the United States that involve production considered to be in violation of U.S. IP law as well as to force access to foreign markets for knowledge-intensive exports. Milner (1991) notes that large exporters and transnational corporations are apt to view the value of Section 301-type legislation in terms of its ability to force open markets, while domestically oriented firms and labor unions are more concerned with the market protection it affords. Clearly, corporations with an interest in the promotion of a strong and harmonized international IPR regime are more likely to fall into the former category. Section 301 law for these capitals then has instrumental value in advancing the multilateral trading system rather than limiting its reach. The target countries include both industrialized as well as less developed countries, though a disproportionate number of actions have been taken against the LDCs. This group includes the more technologically advanced among the less developed countries, or semiperiphery, inasmuch as these countries are sophisticated enough to have both indigenous and poten-
126
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
tially competitive high-tech capacities as well as internal markets for their outputs. The U.S. State: "Liberal, Pluralist Hegemon" or Vanguard of the Global Historic Bloc? In his book-length study entitled Playing by the Rules: American Trade Power and Diplomacy in the Pacific (1995), Michael Ryan pays particular attention to the impact of U.S.-East Asian economic relations on the development of political momentum resulting in the TRIPS agreement. He notes that the USTR has concentrated its Section 301 weapons disproportionately on East Asian countries because the region embraced aggressive export promotion, with the United States as a prime target market, as the basis for its development strategy during the 1970s and 1980s. Ryan's analysis is grounded in a theoretical model that combines the classical realism of international relations theory with liberal political economy. Classical realism argues that foreign policy is driven by state actors who wish to maximize national power, security, and wealth. While linkage bargaining is often instrumental in bilateral negotiations, coercion is as likely to dictate policy decisions. Liberal political economy places a greater emphasis on the prospects for international cooperation and assigns a prominent role to international organizations, including multinational corporations, as agents. From this perspective, the goals of nation states involve absolute economic gains. Multilateral negotiations are understood as positive-sum games. Within this interpretative framework, Ryan argues that trade diplomacy may be characterized along a continuum of strategies, ranging from poweroriented to rule-oriented. Power-oriented trade diplomacy, a notion akin to coercive bilateralism, is based on the unilateral imposition by more powerful parties of dispute settlements arrangements on weaker parties. Rule-oriented diplomacy arrives at dispute settlements via appeal to internationally (multilaterally) arrived-at norms and procedures. Late twentieth-century trade diplomacy, argues Ryan, is neither purely power-oriented nor purely rule-oriented. Rather, a combination of both approaches prevails, with the GATT providing the rules-based elements but with elements (such as Section 301 trade law) of power diplomacy also in use. Based on an analysis of forty U.S. trade disputes with three East Asian nations (Japan, Korea, and Taiwan) from 1974 to 1989, Ryan derives what he considers to be two important generalizations as regards the practice of trade diplomacy. The first is that two explanatory variables account for the willingness of the USTR to undertake the application of Section 301 complaints against alleged unfair trading practices by East Asian countries. These
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
127
variables are (1) the commercial competitiveness of the complaining industry and (2) the GATT regime utility of the ciase. The first of these refers to the ability of the complaining firms or industry to possess at least a potential competitive advantage in world markets. The argument is made that USTR will not consume limited resources and diplomatic capital on cases that do not involve internationally competitive producers. GATT regime utility refers to the GATT-based rules consistency pf the complaint. By this is meant, does the complaint clearly identify a violation of the rules established by the GATT for the multilateral trading system? These generalizations are logically consistent, says Ryan; with the characterization of the United States as a "pluralist, liberal regulatory hegemon." By the "pluralist, liberal" characterization, Ryan means that the United States is a weak state with limited powers and checks and balances that grew without major external security threats and with increasing wealth and relative egalitarianism. The U.S. pursues a liberal regulatory industrial-policy strategy, which asserts that markets allocate resources more efficiently, give incentives to produce what the public wants, give incentives to workers to acquire useful skills, conserve scarce gotids by setting their prices high, offer a high degree of economic freedom, an
128
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
eral trade policies is evidence of the declining relative competitive capabilities of U.S. producers in key manufacturing industries. Ryan asserts, to the contrary, that the evidence shows that the United States is better understood as "no longer a 'benevolent hegemon' in agriculture and traditional manufacturing markets and 'an ascending hegemon' in service and intellectual property-based markets" (p. 22). I agree with Ryan that the declining hegemon hypothesis is incorrect. I find fault, however, with his alternative interpretation of the U.S. state as a "pluralist, liberal regulatory hegemon" precisely because it downplays the disposition of the state to perform on the basis of the dominant class interests as well as its failure to account for the international character of the dominant class, or historic bloc, to use the Gramscian terminology. This vision of the state is an extension of Ryan's basic conceptual model, which, as noted earlier, is grounded in classical realist and liberal political economy, which tends to minimize, or ignore outright, class-based social relations of production and their inherently exploitative and conflictual character. The epistemological tradition preferred by Ryan sees states rather as agents of national interests, which, while perhaps differentiated socially and economically in some ways, also enjoy a substantial harmony of cultural outlook. I suggest the following interpretation of Ryan's main empirical findings. The USTR is responsive in its Section 301 investigations and actions to those firms and industry groupings that are internationally competitive, well organized, and well funded.5 These, of course, are characteristics of most transnational corporations. The finding that Section 301 initiations follow complaints that are supported by GATT-based trading rules suggests the need for international capital to have a globally consistent regulatory system and the willingness, even preference, of the U.S. executive to aid in the construction of the required supranational superstructure. Ryan also finds, at first blush paradoxically, that some smaller, nationally limited capitals (e.g., shoemakers) have successfully lobbied the USTR to initiate Section 301 actions on their behalf. Does this reflect the pluralist character of the U.S. state? Interestingly, Ryan provides us with an explanation that suggests the answer to this question is "no." He writes: The importance of GATT in the USTR calculus also helps explain the puzzle that remained from the discussion above about why the USTR takes up the cases of small interest groups. The leather case was initiated by USTR (and subsequently linked with the footwear dispute, since the latter could be seen as a subset of the former) because it possessed precedent value beyond the economic value. It was the first attempt by the U.S. to make the Japanese political economy conform with the rules and
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
129
principles of the GATT and liberal-rnarket political economy. A U.S. trade policymaker said, "Leather and fodtwear was [a] medium to attack the Japanese system." Another U.S. polidymaker mused: "Nobody would have believed then that it would result in 1990 with the Structural Impediments Initiative. Now we are demanding the complete restructuring of the Japanese economy." (p. 44) i We could hardly ask for a more elegant statement of the goals of the global capitalist historic bloc—a restructuring of the global legal framework as it bears on international economic relations with a view to the restructuring of the global economy on a neoliberal basis. Neoliberal is here understood not in its nineteenth century sense of competition among atomistic firms, but rather in terms of the removal of the obstacles to the free circulation of largescale commodity, money, and productive capital. This reinterpretation of Ryan's empirical results holds with special force for the case of intellectual property rights. Special 301 trade law was initially used against South Korea in 1985. U.S. pharmaceutical companies complained that Korea failed to provide adequate protection to U.S. products inasmuch as Korean IP law only covered the process by which drugs were produced, Thus, if a domestic firm produced an identical product via a distinct production process, this was not deemed a violation of the law. Korean producers were then able to reverse engineer several patented drugs, devise new methods for their production, and thereby capture a share of a lucrative market. U.S. pharmaceutical companies also complained about the inadequate length of patent protection provided by Korean law, arguing that twelve years was inadequate to earn profits on new produ :ts that often required a decade or more after the initial filing of the patent to bring to market (Ryan 1998, p. 74). Thus, the USTR decided to launch a Section 301 investigation and pursue bilateral negotiations with Korea over these alleged unfair trading practices at the same time that it sought to put ] PRs on the table for the multilateral Uruguay GATT talks. Ryan argues that the United States pursued a divideand-conquer strategy designed to undermine the solidarity of the less developed countries in their stand against negotiating on intellectual property (p. 75). After two years of these bilateral negotiations, an agreement was reached whereby Korea would amend its patent law to allow American companies to patent production processes as well as products. In the aftermath of these and other reforms to Korea's IP law, however, the International Intellectual Property Alliance (IIPA), yet another IP lobbying group (Ryan 1998, pp. 6 9 72), submitted a number of additional complaints to the USTR alleging the failure of the Korean government to effectively enforce its law. As a result, Korea was placed on the watch list under Section 301 of the 1988 trade act.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Uso placed on the Section 301 watch list of the 1988 Omnibus Trade Act was China, which had been accused of a variety of copyright violations of U.S.-produced books, films, music recordings, and computer software. China was also accused of extensive trademark violations. The stakes in the bilateral negotiations were high for both countries. The Chinese market for knowledge-based goods and services is enormous, and violations of copyrights, patents, and trademarks were estimated to cost U.S. companies hundreds of millions of dollars per year. At the same time, however, the huge U.S. market for Chinese manufactures provided the USTR with abundant negotiating leverage, particularly when potential sanctions were aimed at producers in the southern coastal province of Guangdong.6 The fact that China was keen on accession to the GATT provided additional leverage that U.S. negotiators could use to press the Chinese for improvements in their treatment of foreign IPRs. After a period of intense negotiations in which the USTR threatened sanctions and the Chinese in turn threatened retaliation, an agreement was reached in 1995 that called for the Chinese to crack down on the producers of illegal knockoffs of U.S. goods. Goods were to be seized and individuals were to be fined and/or jailed. Steps were to be taken to ensure the authenticity of imports. Customs inspectors were to receive training, and special efforts and resources were to be invested in improvements in the Chinese enforcement infrastructure, including its judiciary. As Ryan notes, "These were extraordinary terms: never before had a bilateral trade agreement done so much to build national institutions" (1998, p. 83). More to the point, however, is that the threat of Section 301 sanctions had a powerful effect on the construction of international institutions, namely the TRIPS agreement. This is so in two ways. First, insofar as the IPR concerns of the United States could be met by their inclusion in a multilateral agreement, the legitimacy of U.S. unilateral measures was undermined. The United States, in fact, had been widely criticized for pursuing bilateral negotiations related to charges of unfair trading practices. Second, the peripheral and semi peripheral countries that were expected to conform to the new standards set by the TRIPS understood that bilateral negotiations with the United States on these issues would probably leave them much worse off in the long run. Unilateral sanctions imposed under Section 301 were limited only by what the USTR considered to be appropriate and acceptable within the context of bilateral costs and benefits calculations. Moreover, the TRIPS framework at least offered the possibility of a formal disputes settlements procedure wherein the poorer countries might prevail in particular cases and at least work to limit the damage in cases where they were not.
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
131
The Generalized System of Preferences Section 301 threats were not the only instrument of coercive hegemony employed by the United States to shape the Content and character of the Uruguay Round. The Generalized System of Preferences (GSP) was also used as leverage to compel conformity to the TRIPS agreement. The GSP was created in the 1970s presumptively as a way to improve access to the large markets of the developed countries for the exports of the poorer ones. Under the GSP, participating importing countries identify a list of goods to be given preferential treatment and then allocate import quota rights to LDCs deemed eligible. The U.S. GSP list of traded gooeis includes those of particular export importance to the poorer countries thbt are also produced in the United States under conditions of protectionism. These include textiles, shoes, and certain agricultural commodities, such as sugar and peanuts. While the system may have been motivated by a concern to promote the benefits of trade for the LDCs, it has effectively operated as a means to exert trade pressure on these same countries. The United States requires that countries wishing to participate in its GSP program meet a variety of eligibility criteria relating to their own trading practices. In recent years, these requirements have been expanded to include a country's record on IPRs. GSP concessions can operate either positively or negatively as a bargaining chip with respect to IPR negotiations. In 1997, for example, the USTR withdrew 50 percent of its allotted GSP concessions to Argentina, attacking this country on complaints from PhRMA, the lobbying group for the pharmaceuticals industry. PhRMA charged that the Aigentine government had stood by while patent pirates had deprived U.S.firms;of more than half a billion dollars' worth of business annually. The decrease in! GSP concessions was estimated to cost a variety of Argentine industries around $13 million a year in lost export sales, or around 5 percent of Argentine trade, to the United States (Hanson 1997). In March 2001 the USTR withheld expanded access to GSP participation to South Africa under similar circumstances. This case involved claims that South African drug manufacturers wei e violating the IPRs of such multinationals as Glaxo, Bristol-Meyers, and Mjrck, manufacturers of the drugs to fight the AIDS virus (Cooper, Zimmerman, and McGinley 2001). Gramscian Hegemony and the TRIPS The Special 301, Super 301, and GSP operate as effective mechanisms of hegemony not necessarily because they are frequently invoked as rewards and punishments levied on peripheral and semiperipheral countries reluctant to conform to center country standards and dictates. They function effec-
132
tively because they enhance the bargaining position of center country interests in multilateral forums. That is. it is the threat of unilateral sanctions rather than their actual execution by the United States that has brought the TRIPS agreement into existence as a part of the international regulatory infrastructure. In this way, Special 301, Super 301, and GSP serve in an indirect rather than direct capacity the needs of center capitalist interests. One may reasonably ask, Why should the United States wish to establish its preferred IPR regime within the institutional and administrative structure of the GATT/WTO rather than impose it via the strategy of bilateral coercion? It is in consideration of this question that the limitations of the hegemonic stability approach become most evident. It is also in consideration of this question that the power of the Gramscian hegemony perspective becomes clear. Here it is useful to recall Cox's understanding of Gramscian hegemony as "a fit between power, ideas, and institutions" (1996, p. 104). It is useful also to recall that this conception applies not at the state level, but to the larger world order. If it is true, as the world systems theorists contend, that the modern world system is in the throes of a crisis, then it is natural to expect a search for a new "fit between power, ideas, and institutions." It is also to be expected that the historic bloc that directed the old order will attempt to influence as far as possible the structure and content of the emergent hegemony. The fact of the erosion of U.S. hegemonic economic power and the rise of international competition explains the expanded role of multilateral institutions such as the GATT/WTO, the IMF, and the World Bank. The fact that the emergent world order is founded on the reemergence of global neoliberalism (termed hyperliberalism by Cox) helps to explain the continued dominance of the United States in shaping the institutions of the new order. The United States, politically, socially, and culturally, remains the sine qua non among nations as the model for liberal capitalism. It provides the guidelines for the new historic bloc to formulate its supranational legal superstructure that will direct globally integrated capitalism. The essence of Gramscian hegemony, as noted earlier, is not coercion, but rather consensus. As such, the task of the TRIPS is to present IP standards and law as they are found in the United States, not as the ideological manifestation of a particular class interest, but rather as serving global economic welfare. The incorporation of TRIPS into the formal institutional multilateral trading system, GATT/WTO, operates to lend the IPR agreement a mantle of moral authority and historical necessity lacking in bilateral agreements that often emerge from Section 301-type negotiations. The latter often do little to conceal that a "solution" is being imposed on the weaker by the ger of the parties involved in the dispute, additional tactical and ideological advantage of the incorporation of V
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
133
TRIPS into the WTO is the ability to use other trade-related issues as leverage in IPR negotiations. This is precisely what occurred during the Uruguay Round when the United States and other center countries made concessions on trade-related matters considered important from the perspective of certain sectors and their associated capitals in ihe periphery in return for their otherwise grudging acceptance of the TRIPS. Ryan describes this tactic of "linkage bargaining" and its effectiveness iri the following terms: Linkage-bargain diplomacy can be exploited to achieve treaties in diplomatically and politically difficult areas in which agreement would otherwise be elusive. WIPO, with its authority limited to intellectual property issues, could not offer linkage-bargaining opportunities. GATT multilateral trade negotiations, however, could offer opportunities for creative bargaining, because the proposed agenda for the 1980s round of negotiations included textiles and apparel, agriculture, services, foreign direct investment, and government procurement. (1998, p. 92) The areas that are of most importance to the ipoorer countries, of course, are textiles and agriculture. In the past, howevejr, these same sectors have also been the beneficiaries of substantial protection within the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (CECD) countries. The Multi-Fiber
Arrangement
Liberalization of textile trade involved the piaseout of the notorious MultiFiber Arrangement (MFA), which limited access to center country markets of textiles and apparel exports from the periphery. The MFA was originally negotiated in 1973 as part of the Tokyo RouAd of GATT. Up until then, textiles had barely been touched on in multilateral trade negotiations even though they were then and continue to be an important area of comparative advantage for industrializing economies.7 While negotiated under the aegis of GATT, the MFA ran contrary to its spirit and letter by permitting countries to negotiate bilateral restrictions on textile trade. Typically, this meant that center importers, such as the United States, the European nations, and Canada, could impose a quota limitation on a peripheral country exporter that represented a threat to the center importer's domestic industry. Quotas could be imposed on specific products according to the degree of threat represented by foreign competition. The exporters most frequently targeted were those in East Asia, Brazil, India, and Pakistan. The Uruguay Round negotiated a ten-year phaseout of the MFA beginning on January 1, 1995, replacing it with the Agreement on Textiles and
134
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Clothing (ATC). The ATC divides the ten-year phaseout period into four stages during which quota restrictions that exist under prevailing bilateral agreements are to be reduced and eventually eliminated. The agreement also requires that all countries provide improved access to their markets in textile trade. Thus, if a particular textile-exporting country that wishes greater access to the United States market, for example, is not forthcoming in liberalizing access to its own market with respect to U.S. goods, the WTO may allow the United States to delay or suspend its quota liberalization measures. The ATC also allows for delays to the quota liberalization process in the event that the importer country can demonstrate a threat of "serious damage" to domestic producers. While the ATC does not define "serious damage" in specific terms, it allows this "transitional safeguard" protection of up to three years for the import-competing industry. Ultimately, however, it is clear that replacing the MFA with the ATC will have important consequences for the structure of the global textiles industry. Center countries will continue to play a role in the design and marketing stages of apparel, with some, like the United States, Canada, and Australia, continuing to play an important role as providers of raw materials. It is clear, however, that many cutting and assembly operations will be removed to parts of the world where labor costs are low and productivity is high, thus enlarging the rate of surplus value obtained on textile manufacture. The Uruguay Round negotiations on textile trade thus had multiple important consequences for the process of internationalization of capital. The negotiations were used as leverage in bargaining over the TRIPS agreement and they helped in the rationalization of an increasingly globally integrated textiles industry. It is significant that the set of countries that were targeted by the MFA considerably overlap with the set of countries most resistant to the implementation of a stronger international IPR regime. In this sense, then, it seems apparent that the replacement of MFA by ATC was part of the purchase price of the TRIPS. From the IOC perspective, however, this was a bargain.8 The Agreement on Agriculture The other important sector in which concessions were made to make the TRIPS agreement more palatable to at least some of the poorer countries was agriculture. Like textiles, agriculture had always been treated in multilateral trade negotiations as exceptional. Many developed countries are characterized by agricultural sectors possessing political influence disproportionate to the number of individuals directly involved in production. This, in part," stems from the tremendous technological and structural change that has occurred in agriculture in the twentieth century. Prior to World War II, substan-
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
135
tial portions of the populace in the center countries were dedicated to agricultural labor. The agricultural crisis that accompanied the Great Depression of the 1930s resulted in an agricultural policy to promote and protect agricultural incomes from future instability. Since then, technological change has boosted labor productivity and moved labor off the farms and into the urban manufacturing and service sectors. The 1970s budgetary crises forced the OECD countries to reexamine their policies and reduce the support provided to protection of the agricultural sector. This same reexamination has also forced policy makers to consider bringing agriculture within the full logic of liberalization as propounded by th|e GATT. Agriculture also differs from textiles as !a matter of multilateral trade dispute and negotiation, inasmuch as the primary disputants are the center (OECD) countries in relation to one another's official agricultural practices. These practices involve tariffs and quotas but also production subsidies, export subsidies, and sanitary and phytosanitary standards. The peripheral and semiperipheral countries ceitainly had an important stake in the outcome of agricultural negotiations inasmuch as agriculture constitutes a substantial share of these countries' economic activity and trade.9 It is far from clear, however, that the modifications made by the Uruguay Round to its treatment of agricultural trade provide real benefits to food producers in the poor countries, especially to small farmers. How exactly were the rules changed by the Uruguay Round? Agricultural trade rules were codified in :he Uruguay Round by its Agreement on Agriculture (AA). The most significant change introduced by the AA involved tariffication. Tariffication refers to the conversion of nontariff trade barriers (NTBs), such as import quotas into tariff equivalents, with the planned reduction of the latter over time.10 Upper limits are placed on agricultural tariffs and developed countries are required to reduce these by an average of 36 percent (less developed countries by 24 percent) over six years. In addition, minimum market access targets were established that required countries to increase the share of domestic consumption serviced by imports to at least 5 percent by the year 2000. This rule would apply to goods faced with prohibitive (exclusionary) tariffs. To achieve this standard, countries would employ what is called a tariff rate que ta (TRQ). Under a TRQ, a country would impose a lower rate of tariff on imports until the market access target is reached (Hoekman and Kostecki 2001). A second potentially important change in the GATT/WTO regime governing agricultural trade concerns the level of direct support provided to producers and exporters by their governments. This support covers primarily production and export subsidies but includes price supports and administered prices. Countries are required to calculate the dollar value of all such support provided to agriculture across all commodities and programs to de-
136
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
rive a so-called aggregate measure of support (AMS). They are then expected to reduce their AMS by 20 percent by 2000 relative to a base period that extends from 1986 to 1988. Lesser requirements were demanded of the less developed countries, which were also given a longer period (until 2005) to come into compliance. The least developed countries were, in fact, essentially exempted from any AMS requirements. Notwithstanding these changes in the trade rules governing agriculture, their impact will probably be minimal, particularly in the short to medium runs. The reasons have to do with the ways the rules were implemented. Take, for example, the issue of tariffication. The conversion of NTBs to tariff equivalents reduces protection only as long as the resultant tariffs fall within meaningful tariff limits ("bindings"). The negotiation of the Uruguay Round's AA actually often allowed the inclusion of tariff bindings in excess of the tariff equivalents of the NTBs. The European Union's Common Agricultural Policy (CAP), for example, set its tariff bindings 60 percent above the tariff equivalent for its NTBs in the late 1980s. The U.S. bindings were set at 45 percent above its tariff equivalents (Hoekman and Kostecki 2001, p. 217). This practice of "dirty tariffication" resulted in a substantial reduction in the anticipated liberalization of agricultural trade and in some cases actually increased the rates of protection provided to producers of "sensitive products" (Ingco 1996). The rules on the AMS are also finessed by certain exclusions and exceptions as well as by its manner of application. The United States and the European Union (EU), for example, agreed that deficiency payments and compensation arrangements, wherein farm incomes were protected under the condition that acreage under production would be reduced, would not be included in the AMS and that the scheme would be applied not on a commodity basis but rather to agriculture as a whole. As the United States and EU account for around 40 percent of global agricultural trade, the exceptions that they insisted on had an important effect in limiting the liberalizing reach of the agreement. Defenders of the AA, however, argue that its real value lies not in its immediate liberalizing effects. Rather, its salient importance consists in the fact that for the first time agriculture has been brought within the normal negotiating oversight of the multilateral trading system. That is to say, the Uruguay Round went a long way in removing agriculture's exceptionalism and opens the door to greater liberalization in future rounds of negotiations. This may well be true. For the short to medium term, however, it is hard to see how the AA serves the majority of the world's agricultural producers. Support for the agreement from within the group of peripheral and semi peripheral countries was sharply divided. Those who lobbied for the
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
137
agreement during the Uruguay Round wer!e identified informally as the Cairns Group,11 composed of the United States, Brazil, Argentina, New Zealand, and certain Southeast Asian countries such as Malaysia, Thailand, and the Philippines. What these countries have in common is the dominance of their national agricultures by IargeLscale producers of cash crops and/or well-organized agricultural middlemen (Bello 1999). Those countries that opposed the AA, on the other hand, are characterized by agricultural sectors wherein smaller producers predominate. This group includes France and several other European countries but also Asian countries such as Japan and South Korea. To the extent tltat agriculture in these nations becomes increasingly subject to an international capitalist rationality, we should expect to see greater consolidation of agricultural holdings, greater rural-urban migration, less food self-sufficiency, a reduction in biodiversity, and greater cultural homogenization. Sanitary and Phytosanitary Standards The fact that the poorer nations were managed by such a divide-and-conquer strategy is evidence to some of the consequences of a lack of Third World solidarity. It could just as easily be accounted for, however, by the dominance of international capital hegemony. Additional evidence of the latter interpretation is provided by another aspect of the AA that has received less discussion. This concerns the progress mac e in the area of sanitary and phytosanitary standards (SPS) harmonization. SPS are motivated, in part, by a concern that imported goods meet the same standards for health and safety required of domestically produced alternatives. Countries, reasonably, do not want imports to present a threat either to domestic consumers or to their loc;al environments. At the same time, SPS may act as a disguised form of protectionism when the rules require imported goods to meet standards tha : are significantly higher than those required of locally produced substitutes , or when they have little or no relation to any reasonable health, safety, or environmental objective. In fact, at the time of the Uruguay Round, there was a concern that some countries were increasingly resorting to this type of protectionism just as progress was being made in reducing other, more common! forms of protection. Naturally, initial differences existed among and between nations regarding reforms leading to harmonization of SPS. Not surprisingly, perhaps, the United States and the EU were strongly in favor of greater harmonization efforts leading toward standards that reduced restrictions on trade and were justified on the basis of scientific evidence. The EU group expressed a concern that countries that placed a high value on health and safety should not
138
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
be expected to lower their SPS. The Cairns Group differed from the EU in arguing that importing nations should bear responsibility for justifying SPS measures (Croome 1999). Many developing countries were also in favor of harmonization of SPS in order to overcome obstacles to their trade and expand market access, particularly to the larger markets of the center countries. Given this seeming consensus on the desirability of harmonization, it is easily understood how the agreement on SPS was struck relatively painlessly as compared to many of the other component agreements of the Uruguay Round. The importance of the SPS agreement can be properly appreciated only in the context of the general tendency toward internationalization of capital and is also related in a direct way to the TRIPS agreement. Harmonization of SPS standards gives an additional boost to the international division of labor by clearing away regulatory obstacles to knowledge-based production. The position of biotechnology in particular is improved inasmuch as innovators face reduced risk associated with SPS red tape and the concerns of so-called minority science—the scientific concerns of those who oppose the majority outlook on a particular scientific issue or innovation. The WTO's dispute settlements procedures as it applies to SPS allows it to minimize or ignore minority opinions in rendering decisions (Wagner 2000). In other words, the SPS agreement removes the ability of countries to make independent scientific judgments on the suitability as regards health and safety of products entering their markets. This type of manufacture and imposition of a de facto scientific consensus should be understood as another facet of Gramscian consensual hegemony. Ignoring the fact that such minority science may turn out to be right, what the SPS harmonization agreement accomplishes is a reduction in regulatory risk. Working hand in hand with the TRIPS agreement, it therefore operates to enhance the international mobility of capital in all its forms. Summary and Conclusion Given the clear instrumental value of U.S. direct bilateral coercion as well as the U.S. role as hegemonic leader in the Uruguay Round, it is tempting to conclude that the TRIPS agreement is the outcome of the reimpositioh of U.S. economic control over the international political economic superstructure a la the theory of hegemonic stability. The difficulty with this interpretation is that it presumes that the TRIPS acts in the unified national interest of a single state. This is a false inference on at least two counts. First, contrary to the hegemonic stability thesis, it is no more possible to identify a unified national interest in intellectual property rights in the United States than it is in any other country. A strengthening of global IPRs will impose differential
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF TRIPS
139
interclass as well intraclass costs and benefits in the United States. The primary beneficiaries of the TRIPS will be those who own and manage the multinational capital responsible for the finance, production, and distribution of knowledge-based commodities around the world. Their benefits will derive from the enhanced monopoly pow;er conferred by stronger patents, copyrights, and trade secrets. It is true that the majority of these owners and managers reside in the center countries of the world capitalist system, including the United States, but it cannot b;e imagined that they constitute a unified national interest. It is more accurate to describe them as providing leadership to an international historic blocj. Second, it is more accurate to describe jthe TRIPS agreement, along with other such additions to the regulatory superstructure of the world capitalist system as the General Agreement on Trade |in Services (GATS) and the agreement on trade-related investment measures (TRIMS), not as responding to the policy dictates of a particular hegemonic state, but rather as responding to an evolving global process of increased movements of financial, production, and commodity capitals. That is to say, it is the internationalization of capital that has provoked the requisite construction of global institutions. The seemingly privileged (hegemonic) position of the United States in this institution building is owing to this country's leadership position as vanguard of the neoliberal orthodoxy. Even in this outwardly nationalistic context, however, the ideological function of neoliberal orthodoxy is to serve a universal rather than a particular (national) interest. While the internationalization of capital displays a universal compulsion to seek higher and higher rates of surplus extraction to feed its own reproduction and expansion, it is apparent that lot all nations enter the process at the same historical moment and on the sane terms. The world capitalist system today continues to display many of the hierarchical characteristics of the earlier, prewar, imperialist era. The post-Ifordist international division of labor assigns low-level processing and manufacturing activities to those parts of the world (periphery and semiperipheiy) where labor costs are low and can be kept at rates of increase lower than the rates of productivity increase, owing to the weakness of institutions and laws to defend labor rights and interests. Design, marketing, finance, and higher-order technological functions are retained at the center of the system, which continues to be characterized by higher levels of educational attainment, greater resources dedicated to research and development, and a virtual monopoly on the ability to fashion the dominant cultural (including juridical) superstructure within which global production is carried out. The TRIPS agreement is just such an element of this cultural superstructure. By harmonizing and strengthening property rights in knowledge-based products and processes, the agreement lends
140
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
greater predictability and rationality to the production and circulation systems. Risks and costs are reduced, speeding the circuits of capital. Surplus value is increased due to the greater monopoly (price-setting) power conferred by exclusive ownership. Greater legitimacy is attributed to capitalism overall as the concept of commodification itself gains greater circulation and apparent acceptability. The question of legitimacy, however, is not a closed issue. Counterhegemonic efforts have called into question the provisions of the TRIPS agreement and even the concept of intellectual property rights, especially as they pertain to knowledge-based commodities critical to basic human needs, such as food and medicines. It is natural to ask the question, What are the conditions for successful counterhegemony and the redefinition of property and property rights that advance the interests of the world's marginalized majorities? Do these conditions differ depending on the type of commodities, scientific activities, or production processes at issue? Does global capital have a greater stake in defending certain types of IPRs more than others? These are some of the questions to be pursued in the chapters to follow.
6 TRIPS and th^ Global Pharmaceutical Industry
It is hardly surprising that the U.S. pharmaceutical industry led the effort to have intellectual property rights (IPRs) included among the new topics to be considered by the Uruguay Round of multilateral trade negotiations in the 1980s and 1990s. Pharmaceuticals possess all of the obvious characteristics that make them susceptible to the distortions associated with intellectual property. First, their production is highly intensive in research and development effort and thereby entails massive fixed costs. Pharmaceuticals Research and Manufacturers of America (PhRMA), a major lobbying organization for the U.S. drug industry, estimates that the typical new drug requires $350 million and ten to twelve years to bring to markst.1 Second, pharmaceuticals are typically produced in highly concentrated industries under oligopolistic, or near monopolistic, conditions. Pharmacei tical firms possess considerable market power to restrict the supplies and to raise the prices of their most important commodities in the pursuit of economic rent. Third, many of the most valuable pharmaceuticals are produce d out of cheap basic chemicals, rendering the marginal cost of production }uite low. Countries with limited innovative capacities, but otherwise sufficiient technical and manufacturing abilities, often target valuable drugs for imitation and sale at prices far below those charged by the original innovating firms. The drug companies, arguing that these facts imply an unwarranted constraint on their profitability, then press for tighter rules governing intellectuajl property, particularly in the area of patent protection. The TRIPS Agreement and Pharmaceuticals The trade-related aspects of intellectual property rights (TRIPS) agreement negotiated; during the early 1990s operates to secure IPRs in the pharmaceutical sector in the following ways. First, Article 27 of the agreement stipulates that "patents shall be available for any inventions, whether products or processes, in all fields of technology" and that patent rights should be "en141
142
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
joyable without discrimination as to the field of technology." This article suggests, then, that World Trade Organization (WTO) countries are no longer free to determine which commodities they will provide with IPR protection, if any at all, as was the case, for example, under the Paris Convention on patents. According to the latter agreement, countries were merely required to provide foreigners with "national treatment." If a nation, however, provided no protection to domestic intellectual property (IP), then it was not required to provide such protection to foreign interests. Under the TRIPS, all WTO countries are expected to modify national law to provide such protection. Up until the negotiation of the TRIPS, many poorer countries provided no IPR protection to pharmaceuticals precisely because they lacked an indigenous productive capacity in this line of production. Many countries, in fact, encouraged imitation of foreign pharmaceutical innovations in order to reduce the cost of providing their benefits to their own populations. Article 33 requires member states to grant patepCRrotection for a minimum of twenty years from the application filing daWflArticle 28 confers on the owners of patents the exclusive right to prevent third parties without consent from making, using, offering for sale, selling, or importing covered products. This provision, therefore, makes illegal the practice of so-called parallel imports wherein a country might import patented pharmaceuticals from a country that manufactures them in violation of a patent. Article 31 sets out specific circumstances and conditions under which countries may allow unauthorized production based on a patented product or process, otherwise known as compulsory licensing. Among other requirements, those seeking the license must provide adequate remuneration to the patent holder, and the decisions regarding authorization and remuneration are subject to judicial review. Under a strict interpretation of these new rules, then, a country with a strong indigenous imitation capacity, such as India or Brazil, would no longer be free to appropriate foreign patented production processes or commodities for either domestic use or reexport without risking substantial retaliatory trade sanctions. Each of these provisions carries certain important qualifications, however. For example, while Article 27 extends the availability of patent protection to include pharmaceutical goods and the processes for their production, Article 7 stipulates that the "protection and enforcement of intellectual property rights should contribute to . . . the mutual advantage of producers and users of technological knowledge and in a manner conducive to social and economic welfare, and to a balance of rights and obligations" (Matthews 2002, p. 143). This clearly suggests that IPRs are not an end unto themselves but should be understood in terms of their instrumental value in serving broader social objectives. This opens the door to a less than literal application of patentrightswhen this
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
143
application stands in open conflict with otheij deserving social ends. Article 28 is similarly subject to heavy qualification orj the grounds of the so-called exhaustion or first-sale principle which provides that a member state may limit application of patent right once a product protected by the patent has been sold. In other.words, a patent provides the [patent holder with the exclusive right offirstsale. After the good has entered the market as a result of this sale, the buyer has complete rights over its subsequent disposition, including its resale. To the extent that a nation adopts an| international version of this exhaustion principle, parallel irpports are perfectly consistent with the TRIPS agreement.2 Likewise, Article 31 delimits the circumstances under which compulsory licensing may be allowed, but by no means precludes its possibility. Compulsory licenses may be allowed, for example, to prevent abuses of monopoly power, in the interests of public health and safety (Article 8), or in the interest of national security (Article 73). Challenging the TRIPS The important general point here is that the TRIPS agreement is subject to continuous interpretation, challenge, and reinterpretation. Since its inauguration with the completion of the Uruguay I:ound in 1994, the TRIPS has in fact come under almost constant challenge in the area of pharmaceutical trade—precisely the global industry most responsible for the establishment of the agreement in the first place. The specific context for this challenge involved the HIV/AIDS pandemic in theless developed countries, especially in Brazil and South Africa. The challenge its elf amounted effectively to both an unofficial and official refusal to enforce the patent claims of the producers of the various pharmaceutical combinations that have been proven effective in combating the transmission of HIV, treating its victims, and extending the lives of people with AIDS. When the anti-AIDS drug manufacturers brought claims and threatened sanctions against those they charged with violations of their IPRs, they encountered stiff resistance grounded not only in a specific interpretation of the TRIPS itself by the developing countries, but perhaps as significantly, in the form of widespread protests by nongovernmental organizations (NGOs) and other popular organizations (Watson 2001). The crowning achievement of this resistance was the 2001 WTO Ministerial Conference in Doha, Qatar, which produced the Declaration on TRIPS and Public Health, known as the Doha Declaration. The Doha Declaration affirmed the right of governments to take whatever measures necessary to ensure public health, even when these measures conflicted with the IPR interests of patent holders.3 While the Doha Declaration does not have legal power in the WTO's dispute settlement process, it does signal an important
144
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
ideological achievement for those who view the TRIPS agreement as antithetical to the interests of the poor majorities residing in the countries dependent on imports or investments from the center countries to satisfy their needs for knowledge-based goods and services. The purpose of this chapter is to discuss the global, class-based contradictions surrounding the application of the TRIPS agreement to pharmaceuticals production and trade. It serves as a case study of the TRIPS and the limits of coercive and consensual hegemony in the contemporary world capitalist system. Such a case study may contain lessons for future counterhegemonic efforts. The Structure of the Global Pharmaceutical Industry The pharmaceutical industry is truly global in scale and scope. Virtually every major producer in the industry is transnational in its production and marketing operations, and many operate internationally in research and development. It also remains true, however, that the bulk of pharmaceutical activity—production, consumption, trade—occurs among and between the center (developed) countries. While the large center-based transnational corporations (TNCs) provide exports to and/or produce pharmaceutical commodities in the peripheral and semiperipheral (less developed) countries, many of these latter countries maintain their own indigenous pharmaceutical sectors. To simplify a complex industry, the taxonomy developed by Ballance, Pogany, and Forstner (1992) is helpful. These authors divide the global pharmaceutical industry into three types of producers: large, integrated corporations (type A firms); innovative companies (type B); and reproductive firms (type C). The first type encompasses what I have identified above as the "major producers" in the global industry. Volume and value of these firms' outputs, however, are not necessarily their most distinguishing characteristics. What separates them from the rest of the industry, rather, is their commitment to research and development (R&D) and their global strategies in the marketing and distribution networks (Ballance, Pogany, and Forstner 1992, p. 5). Innovative (type B) firms are described as having the capabilities of developing new products (new molecular entities, or NMEs), but are more likely to dedicate themselves to producing patent-expiring drugs. Typically such firms lack the R&D, marketing, and distribution capacities to compete with the large transnational corporations in product development and sales. Nonetheless, these innovator firms may themselves operate on a limited transnational basis and account for significant exports. Reproductive (type C)firmstend to be small, often family owned, firms that produce strictly for local markets and do not engage in R&D activity. Much of the output produced by reproductive firms consists of drugs whose patents have expired
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
145
and that are sold to public health agencies. This is particularly so in the less developed countries. It is likely that such firms will also produce some drugs whose patents are still in force. : All of the countries identified by Ballance, Pogany, and Forstner (1992, p. 8) as possessing type A pharmaceutical firms are members of the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD). In 1990, these ten countries accounted for 69 percent of the world's total production and 68 percent of global exports of pharmaceuticjals. Countries whose industry fell into the type B category accounted for 22 jpercent of production and 27 percent of exports. Per capita consumption of pharmaceuticals in 1990 in type A countries was $151 as compared to $12 in type B countries and less than $10 in type C countries.4 Industrial Concentration in the Pharmaceutical Industry Not only is the pharmaceutical industry overwhelmingly dominated by firms headquartered in the center countries and producing for markets in these same countries, but the industry is characterized by a high degree of industrial concentration within these countries. As noted, the United States is home to the largest firms in the industry, accounting in 1995 for thirteen of the top twenty leading producers in the world.5 "hese twenty firms in 1995 produced 70 percent of the top selling product; in the world, with the ten largest firms accounting for 45 percent of sales. Not only is the pharmaceutical industry among the most concentrated of global industries, but the pace of concentrat ion has accelerated in recent years as the result of a new wave of mergers and, acquisitions among the industry's already large firms.6 These mergers are jut tified by the companies involved as offering economies of scale and scope in their R&D operations. Just as likely, however, is the fact that mergers provide opportunities to cut costs and improve the bottom line precisely as an! alternative to new product development. The motivation for the recent acquisition of SmithKline by Glaxo, for example, was the expiration of a patent on Glaxo's Zantac, an antiulcer drug. Glaxo sought to replace this product with another "block buster" drug" called Avandia—a treatment for diabetes- produced by SmithKline (Sorkin 2000). Moreover, the huge monopolies that result from the mergers are far less likely to engage in R&D leading to new drugs that lack very substantial market potential. What we can be sure of is that the market power wielded by the pharmaceutical giants is substantial. This market power translates into the ability to control market supplies and prices. Datajshow a sharp increase in the prices of essential drugs consumed in developing countries beginning in the mid-1980s,
146
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY 147
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
which coincides with the first wave of intense mergers and acquisitions in the industry.7 Prescription drug prices have continued to climb at rates substantially greater than the general level of prices in the developed nations during the 1990s and into the new century. Industry spokespersons plead that the price increases are driven by the expense of developing new drugs. It is notable, however, that the pharmaceutical industry actually spends more on direct marketing and advertising than it does on R&D. U.S. companies spent more than $2 billion in direct marketing to U.S. consumers in 2000 (Barakat 2002). Although prices charged by the big pharmaceutical companies in poor countries are typically well below those charged in richer countries, they are still frequently above what poor families can afford to pay. Big Pharm also possesses substantial political power as a result of its wellorganized, well-financed lobbying agencies and its ability to generate millions of dollars in campaign contributions. Between 1990 and 2002, the pharmaceutical industry went from twenty-seventh to eighth ranked among industries contributing to U.S. federal elections campaigns, with total contributions increasing by a factor of eight. In the year 2000, the industry contributed over $26 million, with about 70 percent going to Republican candidates (Center for Responsive Politics 2002). Of this amount, $3.8 million was contributed by just three firms (Bristol-Myers Squibb, Pfizer, and Eli Lilly), who donated over 80 percent of the funds to Republican candidates. It is not surprising, then, to find former industry executives in positions of power and influence in the present Republican administration. The most obvious example is the current director of the Office of Management and Budget, Mitch Daniels, who is a former executive of Eli Lilly. Pharmaceuticals and Health Several facts regarding the global pharmaceutical industry's dominance by a handful of large transnational corporations operate against the health and welfare of the world's poor majorities. First, these corporations are driven by the profit motive to service markets that regard their products as part of life's necessities and that possess the incomes, or health insurance programs, to back their needs with purchasing power. It would be surprising, therefore, if the companies did not allocate the greatest share of their R&D resources and develop product lines relevant to those markets. Global research and development expenditures dedicated to finding cures or treatments for so-called tropical diseases are but a small fraction of the total. Data taken from PhRMA, the well-funded industrial lobbying group, show the geographic distribution of its members' R&D efforts in the year 2000. The data clearly show that the overwhelming share of foreign R&D by
Table 6.1 R&D Expenditure by Geographic Area for U.S.-Based PhRMA Member Companies, 2000 Geographic area
Millions of dollars
Africa Asia/Pacific Australia/New Zealand Canada Central/Eastern Europe Japan Latin America Middle East Western Europe Uncategorized
11.1 40.3 53.1 245.7 242.8 564.1 139.5 59.1 2,441.2 870.2
Total
4,667.1
Percentage share of total
!
0.2 0.9 1.1 5.3 5.3 12.1 3.0 1.3 52.3 18.6
100.0
Source: Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America, Industry Profile, (2002). Reprinted with permission. ;
U.S.-based pharmaceutical TNCs is undertaken in areas (Western Europe, Canada, and Japan) that share the per capita income and consumption characteristics of the United States. The area receiving the least R&D attention, Africa, is the poorest region. Second, it is an unfortunate fact of life for the poorer nations that the diseases with which their majority populations am afflicted differ markedly from those that afflict the majorities residing in the r.ch countries. To a considerable extent, as a matter of fact, the diseases themselves reflect the very same richpoor dichotomy that distinguishes the more gleneral consumption habits and lifeways of the two groups. At the risk of overgeneralizing, it may be said that the diseases afflicting rich country populations, such as coronary heart disease, stroke, diabetes, and various cancers, tend largely to result from excessive consumption and a sedentary lifestyle. While these types of diseases are certainly to be found in the poor countries as well, much more prevalent are infectious and communicable diseases (e.g., malaria, yellow fever, Chagas' disease, sleeping sickness) and diseases that are the result of poverty and nutritional deficiencies (e.g., tuberculosis, diarrhea, and pneumonia). The R&D effort of U.S.-based drug companies, once again, reflects the market potential of innovations as indicated in Table 6.2, reproduced from PhRMA, that shows resources dedicated according to pharmaceutical product class. Table 6.2 shows that less than 13 percent of PhRMA R&D expenditures in 2000 were dedicated to developing preparations designed to treat infective and parasitic diseases.
148
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
Table 6.2 Domestic R&D of PhRMA Companies by Product Class, 2000 Pharmaceutical preparations Affecting neoplasms, endoctrine system and metabolic diseases Acting on the central nervous system and sense organs Acting on the cardiovascular system Acting on the respiratory system Acting on the digestive or genito-urinary system Acting on the skin Vitamins and nutrients Acting on infective and parasitic diseases Biologicals Diagnostic agents Other human use Veterinary-use pharmaceuticals and biologicals Uncategorized Total
Dollar expenditure (millions)
Share of total (percent)
3,872.0
18.1
3,955.4 2,305.0 696.6
18.5 10.8 3.3
846.7 182.3 0.2
4.0 0.9 0.0
2,717.0 664.5 107.8 1,366.8
12.7 3.1 0.5 6.4
349.9 4,299.5
1.6 20.1
21,363.7
100.0
Source: Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America, Industry Profile, (2002). Reprinted with permission.
Within this group of preparations, even less attention has been paid to developing treatments for the specific diseases that affect the poor countries most acutely. Of 1,223 new drugs introduced into the international market between 1975 and 1997, less than one percent were developed to treat these diseases (Bosnian and Mwinga 2000). Even when a new drug is developed to treat a disease endemic to poor countries, there is no reason to expect that the dictates of market economics will justify its rapid introduction into poor communities. An example is a vaccine developed by Wyeth-Ayerst Laboratories to combat the rotavirus—a pathogen that afflicts the gastrointestinal system, causing severe diarrhea and dehydration (Hall 1999). The disease claims less than a hundred lives per year in the United States, but somewhere between 600,000 and 800,000 lives, mostly children, in the poor countries. However, at $100 for a full-course treatment of the vaccine, it will be years before it is introduced into the countries where it can be of most benefit. As Hall explains, drugs like the rotavirus vaccine diffuse slowly into poor countries only after demand in more affluent markets has been satisfied and
149
production efficiencies reach the point where it can be produced at sufficiently low cost while still returning the requisite profit. A similar situation prevailed with respect to the recombinant hepatitis B vaccine, which was developed in 1986 but took an additional twelve years to be distributed in significant amounts in the less developed world. It is important to note that these lags occur even though the R&D expense and effort to develop lifesaving drugs are frequently supported, in part, by taxpayer money. The development of the rotavirus vaccine, for example, was aided by resources invested by the National Institutes of Health (NIH). The NIH, however, provided no funds for testihg the vaccine in the poor countries. It is natural to ask why the tests are not conducted by pharmaceutical agencies, both public and private, within the less developed countries themselves. The answer is that most of these countries lack the resources and technical capacity to conduct such tests. Those countries that do possess the ability and resources, the so-called type B countries with innovator pharmaceutical industries, face the additional constraint of patent laws that inhibit both the transmission of the lifesaving drugs and the test results necessary for their regulatory approval. Ultimately, the failure to develop and make available pharmaceutical products and processes to save lives in the poor countries must be viewed as an exercise in market failure. Pharmaceuticals as a Public Good More positively, one can reasonably argue t lat lifesaving drugs are a form of public good requiring public provision. This implies a role for either government subsidization or direct government provision of pharmaceuticals and health care more generally. As noted, the public sector does perform this role to a limited but important extent in the center countries. Institutions such as the Centers for Disease Control (CDC) and the NIH in the United States typically dedicate substantial funds and human resources to R&D and the dissemination of results in developing treat nents to combat a variety of diseases. Publicly funded universities also play an important role in providing the basic research leading to important health care breakthroughs. In the peripheral and semiperipheral countries, the public health sector commands a decidedly smaller share of social output than is true for the center countries. According to United Nations Development Programme data in 1998, the top seventeen countries ranked by its Human Development Index (HDI) allocated an average of 6.5 percent of gross domestic product to public health.8 The comparable ratios for the middle and lower HDI countries were 2.9 and 1.7 percent, respectively. Poor countries have lower public expenditure ratios in part because they have less efficient tax systems. Since
150
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
the early 1980s, they have also reduced public spending of all sorts under pressure by international lending institutions, led by the International Monetary Fund (IMF). These pressures were generated by the rising external indebtedness of the less developed nations during the 1970s and 1980s and the subsequent debt crisis. To qualify for additional lending, the borrower countries had to agree to conditions set by the IMF and designed, among other things, to bring down public sector spending. The subsequent budget cuts in many nations led to sharp reductions in spending on public health. Not surprisingly, these cuts were also associated in these countries with rising incidences of infectious and poverty-related diseases. Public Health Alternatives Without an innovative, independent, domestic, private pharmaceutical sector and/or an adequately funded and competent public health establishment, what alternatives exist for the development of effective treatments of tropical diseases? One possibility involves the emergence of civil society institutions with global reach and vision. An example is provided by the Malaria Genome Project (MGP), a consortium of public agencies (including universities) and nongovernmental organizations dedicated to searching out novel ways to defeat the malaria parasite (Enserink 2000). The scientific strategy of the MGP attempts to identify a compound that will block the enzyme unique to the parasite. Such a compound is called a protease and its identification requires in turn that researchers crack the genetic code of the parasite Plasmodium falciparum. There are two important points to make about this strategy. First, it differs from previous attempts to combat the malaria virus by identifying and developing compounds to poison it. The problem with this approach is that over time the malaria parasite developed resistence to the compound. Second, the protease approach to fighting malaria potentially has an important economic advantage. This advantage resides in the fact that the same basic approach is taken by the recently developed anti-HIV drugs used to fight AIDS. If the HIV compounds can be used as a blueprint for developing and manufacturing antimalarial treatments, then, it is argued, the basic research conducted by the MGP and others can be provided to private pharmaceutical companies to do the job. Enserink quotes Bert Spilker, senior vice president of PhRMA, the influential pharmaceutical lobby, as follows: "if an old drug is found to have some activity in malaria, I can personally guarantee the companies would fight each other to license it" (2000, p. 1958). One can hardly doubt Spilker's guarantee. The problem this raises, however, points to the inherent limitations of such civil society solutions to the question of public goods and their provision. While the major drug manufac-
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
151
turers may well be eager to take advantage of the successful research carried out by such consortia as MGP, what assurances are there that such publicprivate cooperation will enable the delivery of the needed product at a price low enough to reach the target populations? In the final analysis, the objective of the private manufacturers is still profit. Inevitably, the first step of the drug companies upon achieving a deliverable version of the lifesaving compound will be to file a patent application on its manufacture. It follows that the fortuitous fact that economies of scale and scope are more easily reached in the case of the antimalarial protease bearing a family resemblance to its anti-HIV cousin does not necessarily ensure that the cost savings will be passed along to the suffering victims of disease.9 An obvious additional question concerns treatments for tropical diseases which bear no scientific nor economic relationship to some "profitable disease" like HIV/AIDS. Sleeping sickness (trypanosomiasis) is a disease spread by the bite of the tsetse fly, which is found throughout sub-Saharan Africa. The disease has recently made a comeback as a result of cutbacks in eradication programs forced on countries suffering;from rising internal and external public debts. Sleeping sickness attacks the Central nervous system, causing hallucinations, lethargy, and sometimes vio ent behavior. Ultimately victims fall into coma before dying. The European manufacturer of melarsopol, the only effective treatment against the disease has recently decided to discontinue production, citing the lack of a market despite the fact that 300,000 new patients are infected yearly (Vesely 2000). While private sector health industry advocates argue that the best way to address such unmet health needs is to involve some type of public-private partnership, virtually every such proposal sets two nonnegotiable conditions. The first is that the public sector must defra} the cost of R&D and delivery of the essential treatments, or both. Second, any workable solution must respect patent rights of the firms developing the products. Patents and Pharmaceuticals The U.S. pharmaceutical industry frequently points out the importance of patent protection in promoting the development of new products. It is estimated that the average cost of developing' and bringing a new product to market is half a billion dollars. At the same time, pharmaceutical product development is highly risky, with only a few of the thousands of compounds designed and screened advancing into the preclinical testing phase, and only a small percentage of these are ultimately approved by the U.S. Food and Drug Administration. Glover (2002) states that the average time required to develop a new drug increased from 8.1 years in 1960 to 14.2 years in the
152
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
1980s and 1990s. Given that the patent length provided by U.S. law is twenty years from the date that the application is filed, this gives a short window of market exclusivity for the developers of a new product. The average period of effective patent life for new medicines introduced in the early to mid1990s, with patent-term restoration, according to Glover, is only eleven to twelve years. Other patented inventions that are not subject to the same degree of regulatory oversight enjoy on average 18.5 years of effective patent life. Glover's general argument, then, is that the pharmaceutical industry requires the full range of patent protection provided by current law as well as relief from unnecessary regulatory red tape. In the absence of this sympathetic treatment, he fears that the ability of the industry to continue to develop and market life-improving and lifesaving drugs will be significantly diminished. Moreover, if IPRs are not vigorously enforced, the argument goes, new investment needed to fund the intense R&D effort will not be attracted to the industry, and the pipeline of new products will quickly dry up. Not only will there be a subsequent reduction of new brand-name drugs, but the flow of generic imitations will also slow to a trickle. It has been observed by other industry experts that the flow of pharmaceutical breakthrough drugs has already shown signs of slowing down in recent years. Pharmaceutical Prices and Profits Notwithstanding these dire predictions, the pharmaceutical industry continues to rank among the most profitable industries in the American and global economic landscapes. Gottlieb (2001) reports that the U.S. pharmaceutical industry was the most profitable industry in the American economy during 2001. The top ten companies saw profits increase by 32 percent in a year that saw the overall profits of the Fortune 500 companies decline by 53 percent. Moreover, the industry has ranked at or near the top by Fortune's measures of profitability for the past three decades. An important question to consider, then, is this: Given the high R&D cost and riskiness associated with product development, and given the deceleration in the industry's rate of new product development in recent years, how has the pharmaceutical industry managed to maintain such an impressive profit record? The answer is a combination of the following factors. First, the pharmaceutical industry has undergone a tremendous surge of merger and combination activity in recent years. Large firms have combined with other large firms to create truly huge industrial behemoths. These combinations have a positive impact on profits in several ways. They reduce managerial redundancy and overhead costs, resulting in more efficient production. Second, they give rise to economies of scale and scope in the production process
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
153
that are an additional source of cost savings. Third, mergers reduce competition within the industry and increase the pjrice-setting ability of the remaining firms. The monopoly price-setting ability of the pharmaceutical giants is manifest in the rapid rate at which drug prices have risen in recent years. The companies themselves argue that such price increases are motivated by the equally rapid increases in R&D and regulatory related costs. The robust profit picture for the industry, however, demonstrates that the ability to set prices is also a key part of the picture. A second factor accounting for the extraordinary profit performance of the pharmaceutical industry concerns patents. While it is true that the typical length of patent under U.S. law is twenty years, there are myriad methods by which patents and patent law may be manipulated to extend effective patent protection. For example, an expiring patent on a drug may be effectively extended when the manufacturer makes a minor modification in its chemical composition and patents the new compound. Similarly, the manufacturer may patent, or modify an existing patent on, the method by which a certain drug is administered (Mullin 2002b). Another strategy followed by brand-name manufacturers of a drug is to take out patents on the generic versions of their products before their original patent expired. This tactic allows the manufacturer an additional thirty months of patent protection and control over the market. Patent attorneys may also file frivolous suits designed to obstruct entry by generic manufacturers of their products (McCarthy 2002). When generic versions of previously patented drugs are able to penetrate the market, the big pharmaceutical companies spend billions of dollars every year in marketing to maintain their market shares. Direct-to-consumer advertising in the United States by the big drug makers tripled to $3 billion between 1997 and 2001 (Mullin 2002a). Pharmaceuticals, the TRIPS, and the Poorer Countries The pharmaceutical industry is an especially important one for the peripheral and, especially, the semiperipheral countries of the world. Drugs are a knowledge-intensive industry. The capital and raw materials requirements of pharmaceuticals are not nearly as important to a successful industry as are the knowledge and technical capacity for formulating the requisite compounds. Several semiperipheral countries, such as India, Brazil, Argentina, South Africa, and Korea, possess the scientific capacity to at least carry out an imitative function in the production: of important drugs. This ability provides an important basis for pharmaceutical industrial development in these countries. It is also, presumably, an important fact motivating the push for strengthening the global IPR regime as embodied in the TRIPS agreement.
154
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
There is good reason to believe, however, that contrary to the assertions of TRIPS proponents, the agreement will have a negative impact on the development of the pharmaceutical industries in the semiperipheral countries. TRIPS and Pharmaceutical Technology Recent research on the Japanese pharmaceutical industry shows that the ability offirmsto grow depends on their capacities to expand their stock of technology (Watanabe et al. 2002). Technology growth in turn depends on two sources: an indigenous component that responds to R&D expenditure, and an external component derived from technological spillovers from other companies. The second source of technology is found to be particularly important for smaller firms. Not only is technology spillover important as a stimulant to the firm's growth as measured in sales, but it is also directly associated with an increase in the firm's ability to assimilate technology. Small pharmaceutical firms wishing to achieve a self-sustaining level of technical dynamism must reach a threshold stock of technology. The authors of the study unfortunately do not explain precisely how the technology spillovers are to occur beyond invoking the standard neoclassical assumptions that technology is bought and sold in competitive markets and that its price reflects its marginal productivity. These assumptions may not be dramatically unrealistic when applied to Japan, where firm-specific IPRs are not traditionally given the same level of protection that they would receive in the United States or Europe. The Japanese government, in fact, has placed a far greater emphasis on the national dissemination of technology. When applied to the international transfer of technology in the context of the TRIPS agreement, however, these assumptions would seem to be patently unrealistic. The whole point of stronger IPRs, after all, is to provide their possessors with monopoly rents associated with exclusive ownership of the innovations. A strengthening of IPRs in the pharmaceutical industry can then be expected to raise the cost of technological spillovers, reduce the rate of spillovers, reduce the assimilative capacity of the small firms that tend to dominate the industries of the semiperipheral countries, and retard the development of the pharmaceutical industries in these countries. The result will be the further expansion and rationalization of the global pharmaceutical industry, directed by center-based transnational corporations. The loss to the semiperipheral and peripheral countries includes, but is not limited to, the opportunity to develop an industry that is at least potentially more responsive to the health care needs of those who reside in tropical and semitropical regions and who lack the high incomes associated with center-country health care consumption.
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
155
TRIPS and Social Welfare in the Indian Pharmaceutical Market Watal (2000) has examined the welfare consequences of the TRIPS agreement for India's pharmaceutical industry. India's industry has been very successful at producing cheap generic versions of brand-name drugs for domestic use and for export. The industry is composed mostly of small producers who employ half a million people. The country's 1970 patent law made provisions for process patents but not for product! patents.10 This created abundant incentive for Indian scientists to reengineer the way key pharmaceuticals are produced, with the result that India is largely self-sufficient despite having liberalized its trade beginning in the early 1990s. A consequence of the relatively competitive structure of the Indian pharmaceutical industry is that the rate of price increase for drugs has been well below the general rate of inflation for the country (Gerster 2000). Watal's analysis shows that the change in effective IPR regime as a result of the implementation of the TRIPS agreement will have a substantial negative impact on Indian welfare measuring between $50 and $141 million.11 These losses are the result of increases in product prices when the industry moves to a more monopolistic structure. The bulk of this welfare loss is transferred to foreign-based transnational corporations in the form of pretax profit. Watal also considers some possible alternative policy reactions by the Indian government to this potential welfare Io; s. He finds that price regulation offers only limited relief. Under the current formula for determining prices under the country's drug price law, prices under patent-bred monopoly conditions will still be higher than in the absen ;e of pharmaceutical monopoly power. A reformulated pricing policy may, o:i the other hand, have a discouraging effect on producers or imports. Watal's preferred policy approach involves compulsory licensing of patented technology, which, he notes, is allowable under the TRIPS agreement und^r certain conditions. He notes that the welfare superiority for India of this approach will depend heavily on the royalty payment terms demanded by the foreign licensors. He also seems, in my estimation, to underestimate the resistance that these foreign patent owners would present to demands for compulsory licenses. Compulsory Licenses and Exceptions to the TRIPS Among the conditions set by the TRIPS agreement for compulsory licensing is that the resultant production and sales be limited to the country in which the license is granted. That is, a country may not produce for export on the basis of patented technology obtained via a compulsory license. For peripheral countries that lack even an imitative technical capacity, the opportunity
156
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
to import generic versions of important brand-name drugs is of prime importance. Without this alternative, far fewer individuals afflicted with life-threatening diseases could afford treatment. The implementation of the TRIPS agreement, however, puts this lower-cost alternative in jeopardy. The cost of a single drug (fluconazole) used to treat HIV-infected patients costs $20 a day in Kenya, where the drug is protected by patent. A generic version of the drug produced in Thailand costs only 70 cents per day (Hoffman 1999). Certainly, then, even in the unlikely event that a compulsory license might be obtained for a particular drug in a particular circumstance in a particular country, this is far from a sufficient solution to the problem confronted by many poor countries of the monopoly power conferred by TRIPS in the trade in life-enhancing, lifesaving drugs. In general, the TRIPS agreement is not unambiguous as to how particular pharmaceutical patents are to be enforced. Article 27 of the agreement states that governments may exclude a pharmaceutical from patent protection when essential to protect public health or the environment. Article 30 stipulates that WTO members may provide "limited exceptions to the exclusive rights conferred by a patent." Article 31 permit&*compuIsory licensing under certain circumstances and certain conditionsXThese qualifying aspects of the TRIPS, it would seem, provide the poorer countries with all the latitude they need to void those patent restrictions that result in limited availability and increased prices of important drugs. A country would only need to declare a national health emergency and cite this as sufficient justification to compel licensing of a product to a local producer, permit parallel imports of a generic substitute, or permit production of a similar generic product by a local firm that has not paid royalties or fees to the foreign patent holdenj Each of the "escape clauses" contained of the TRIPS, however, carries a variety of important qualifications (Bass 2002).^rticle 30 is qualified by the requirement that "exceptions do not unreasonably conflict with a normal exploitation of the patent and do not unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of the patent owner, taking account of the legitimate interests of third parties7(emphasis added). Article 31 cites a substantial list of qualifying conditions before compulsory licensing may be permitted under the agreement. Among these are the condition that the patent holder shall receive appropriate compensation for the patent and that such compensation shall take into account the economic value of the license and be subject to judicial review. A compulsory license may be granted only under the condition that the licensee hasfirstattempted to obtain authorization from the patent holder on reasonable commercial terms and that such efforts remain unsuccessful after a reasonable period of time has passed.ut is clear from these qualifications that there exists a great deal of room for competing interpretations of
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
157
the agreement. Jvloreover, the ability to bargain and/or impose a particular interpretation is paramount in determining jits effective content and reach. This bargaining and negotiation process has all the characteristics of an exercise in hegemonic contestation. Just as it was a leading actor in the introduction and promulgation of the TRIPS as a part of the international regulatory superstructure, so too the U.S. pharmaceutical industry has been a strong voice in the agreement's interpretation and application since 1995. Two recent cases suffice to illustrate how the U.S.-based transnational prndnners hav£ made use of U.S. trade law to shape the implementationof the TRIPS to sUit their purposes. Brazil's Industrial Property Law and South Africa's Medicines Act Following the 1995 implementation of the TRIPS agreement, Brazil passed its own Industrial Property Law (IPL) in 1997 to bring it into compliance with the agreement. The Brazilian law, however, carried the proviso that patented products would receive protection only if they were produced locally. This is known as a "local working requirement." Its justification derives from the quite reasonable assumption that the anticipated benefits of the TRIPS (e.g., increased investment, technology transfer) are not likely to be realized in the absence of such a requirement. The la>v stipulates that in the absence of local production of patented products, Brazil would have the option of requiring compulsory licensing of those products it deemed to be of sufficient importance. Brazilian pharmaceutical companies then, for example, would be permitted to produce generic versic ns of drugs considered particularly important to the country's public health goals. On the strength of the 1997 IPL, Brazilian pharmaceutical companies have been able to develop a drug cocktail treatment for HIV/AIDS at a fraction of the price of similar treatments sold in the United States. Nonetheless, the United States filed a complaint with the WTO in February 2001 alleging that the Brazilian law was in violation of Article [27 of TRIPS and that the practice of allowing production of generic versions of patented medicines effectively discriminated against exports of these drugs from foreign-based companies that held the patents. Similar circumstances surrounded the South African Medicines and Related Substances Control Amendment Act (Medicines Act) in 1997. The Medicines Act permits so-called parallel imports of pharmaceuticals during national health crises. Parallel imports occur when a patented product is imported from a firm that produces a lower-cost generic version of the commodity. Parallel imports are likely to provoke objections when they involve
158
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
unauthorized production of generic imitations.12 As in the Brazilian case, South Africa's law was largely motivated by a desperate need to combat a public health emergency associated with the spread of the HIV/AIDS virus. As was also true in the Brazilian case, in 1998 the United States reacted with threats of unilateral retaliation, placing South Africa on the United States Trade Representative's (USTR) watch list of countries that fail to comply with intellectual property rights. The response by AIDS activists both within and outside of South Africa provides us with an interesting lesson on the importance of Gramscian hegemonic struggle as a defining force helping to shape the ideological underpinnings of the global system. It is useful then to consider this case in greater detail. HIV/AIDS, Intellectual Property, and the TRIPS According to UNAIDS, (the Joint United Nations Program on HIV/AIDS and main advocate for global actions on the epidemic) HIV/AIDS infects about 40 million people worldwide, with 38.5 million of these residing in the periphery and semiperiphery. Of the latter figure, 28.5 million reside in subSaharan Africa (UNAIDS 2002a). During 2001, approximately 3.5 million Africans became infected with the HIV virus while another 2.2 million died of AIDS. An estimated 55 million Africans will suffer premature deaths as a result of AIDS in the absence of more than moderately effective interventions over the next twenty years. At the end of 2001, 11 million children lost one or both parents to AIDS, and at least 10 percent of those aged fifteen to forty-nine in twelve African countries are infected. This last figure points up the tremendous economic impact the epidemic is expected to have on the African economy via its impact on the continent's labor force. Rosenberg (2001) speculates that by the year 2010 South Africa can expect an economy reduced by 20 percent relative to its potential due to the crisis. South Africa, of course, is not the only poor country facing the HIV/AIDS epidemic. Asia, with 6.6 million persons, actually has more HIV/AIDSinfected people than any other region in the world after sub-Saharan Africa. India alone is home to nearly 4 million of these, while China saw a 67 percent increase in reported infections in 2001. Latin America and Eastern Europe also saw large increases in infections in 2001. The Brazilian Response to the Crisis As noted earlier, poor countries, particularly those that constitute the semiperiphery of the world capitalist system, have not been passive in the face of the crisis. Several have developed generic versions of drug treat-
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
159
ments that were initially developed by thej large, center-based pharmaceutical TNCs. The case of Brazil is especially noteworthy. In 1994, the World Bank estimated that Brazil would have 1.2 million HIV-infected people by the year 2000. In fact, by the end of 2001; the country had around half that many. The reasons for this relative successistory is that the Brazilian government made a commitment during the 1990s to provide its affected population with the combination drug therapy dp. which survival depends. To do this at a cost within the reach of many of the country's infected poor, the government had to pass legislation that directed the nation's pharmaceutical industry to manufacture the generic versions of the drugs (antiretrovirals and protease inhibitors) that are the key to effective treatment. Rosenberg (2001) reports that since 1997 virtually all Brazilians in need of the therapy receives it regardless of their ability to pay. Cheap generic drugs are only part of the Brazilian solution, however. The triple drug therapy is complicated, requiring that people take the medicines in a timely and sequential fashion and often with adequate nourishment. In communities in which the rates of poverty are high and rates of literacy are low, effective treatments typically require adequate health outreach resources in addition to the drugs themselves. Brazil is in the fortunate position of having a well-developed system of public and nongovernmental organizations (NGOs) dedicated to public and community health outreach. This network has done a good j ob of identifying the population of infected and at-risk individuals, providing them with the therapy, instructing them in its use, and monitoring their treatment (Rosenberg 2001). The cost of this health infrastructure is substantial but must be considered economically efficient in comparison with the economic and social cost :>f an unchecked AIDS pandemic in the country. Moreover, not only has the e ffort to prevent and treat AIDS in Brazil had a salutary impact in relation to HIV/AIDS, but it is also credited with containing other diseases, such as tuberculosis. As noted, Brazil's relative success in combating HIV/AIDS included a policy decision to ignore the exclusivity claims of pharmaceutical compa-' nies such as Merck, manufacturer of the antiretroviral Stocrin, and Glaxo Wellcome, which produces the AIDS dm* AZT. As a result, the price of these and other drugs dropped dramatically in the Brazilian market. Between 1996 and 2000, the price of AIDS drugs with no generic substitute declined by only 9 percent. In contrast, those for which generics are produced fell 79 percent (Rosenberg 2001). To remain competitive, the TNC manufacturers of the brand-name versions of the drugs were themselves forced to lower prices. At the same time, these companies, aided by their agent the USTR, pursued actions against the Brazilian government designed to force modifications to their patent law.
160
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
As we saw, the basis of the U.S. complaint alleged that Article 68 of Brazil's 1997 Industrial Property Law violated Article 27 of the TRIPS agreement, which requires WTO member nations to recognize that "patents shall be available and patent rights enjoyable without discrimination as to the place of invention, the field of technology and whether products are imported or locally produced." In contradistinction, Brazil's Article 68 permits compulsory licensing of patented technology in the event that the patentee fails to meet local working requirements. At the heart of the dispute is the precise meaning of the expression "local working requirement."13 The U.S. interprets such a requirement as being fully met as long as the products deriving from the patent are provided by the patentee in the market in which the patent is taken out. Thus, exports of pharmaceuticals to Brazil by companies such as Merck and Glaxo Wellcome are consistent with the working requirement. The Brazilian interpretation, however, is stronger, or strict. It suggests that compulsory licensing is legitimate in the case where a patented technology or process is not manufactured or utilized within Brazil itself. The justification for this strict interpretation is not hard to understand. An often cited rationalization for TRIPS is that it promotes technological transfer from technology-rich countries to technology-poor ones. How is such a transfer to be effectively made unless directly productive facilities utilizing the patented products and/or processes are established in the latter countries? As a semiperipheral country seeking to expand its capacity to' produce technically sophisticated commodities, Brazil is naturally eager to maximize its assimilation of technology from all sources. While the United States understands this motivation, it rejects it as a form of protectionism and, therefore, as a justifiable basis for Article 68. Brazil rejoined that its basis for compulsory licensing is not limited to its developmental ambitions. It charges that the pharmaceutical TNCs have exploited their monopoly pricing power in their pricing of their products to combat HIV/AIDS. Article 5 of the Paris Convention, which is incorporated in the TRIPS in Article 2.1, permits countries to assign compulsory licenses in the event of such abuse. Additionally, Brazil has invoked Article 7 of TRIPS, which requires that countries adopt a flexible approach to IPRs conducive to "the promotion of technological innovation and to the transfer and dissemination of technology, to the mutual advantage of producers and users of technological knowledge and in a manner conductive to social and economic welfare, and to a balance of rights and obligations" (cited in Brennan 2001). Finally, under Article 30 of the TRIPS, Brazil justified its actions as a response to a national public health emergency, even though the United States never addressed this issue in its complaint. The U.S. complaint never reached the stage at which the WTO's dispute
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
161
resolution machinery could act. Rather it was withdrawn following a threeday conference in June 2001 held by the United Nations General Assembly. The Special Session was dedicated to discussion of the international HIV/ AIDS crisis, and the United States government came under criticism for its inadequate response. At about the same: time, the United Nations Human Rights Commission, having for several years framed the HIV/AIDS scourge as a human rights issue, passed a resolution (Commission on Human Rights 2001) that called on states, "to facilitate,! wherever possible, access in other countries to essential preventive, curative or palliative pharmaceuticals or medical technologies used to treat pandemics such as HIV/AIDS or the most common opportunistic infections that accompany them, as well as to extend the necessary cooperation, wherever possible, especially in times of emergency." A year later, this same body, in its Report of the Secretary-General (Commission on Human Rights 2002), recalled the recommendations of the Fourth WTO Ministerial of June 26-29,2001, that "the TRIPS Agreement does not prohibit member States from taking measures to provide access to medicines at affordable prices and to promote public health and nutrition." The Doha Declaration An even more important breakthrough oc curred in late 2001 at a ministerial meeting of the WTO held in Doha, Qater, where an agreement was struck that allows countries to import generic versions of patented drugs to treat HIV/AIDS and other health crises (Winestock and Cooper 2001). The large pharmaceutical manufacturers waged a campaign to prevent the agreement, which also allows the poorest countries to delay implementation of patent laws on drugs for ten years. The president of PhRMA, Alan Holmer, for example, lobbied the U.S. Trade Representative to reject the agreement but was unsuccessful. The usual arguments concerning the detrimental impact of such an agreement on incentives for pharmaceutical R&D failed to overcome an intense effort by governmental z nd nongovernmental campaigns to secure it. The latter organizations include i well-coordinated work by Oxfam America, the Nadar Consumer Project on Technology, Doctors Without Borders, and the Third World Network, as well as AIDS activist organizations from around the world. The nonresponsiveness of the USTR to the pharmaceutical industry's pleas owed much to the fact that the U.S. government itself established a precedent for ignoring the patent of a foreign-based manufacturer. In the panicked aftermath of the attacks on the World Trade Center in New York City, serious concerns were raised involving the possibility of bioterrorism. Specifically, U.S. officials feared that the countrywas vulnerable to an attack involving
162
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
anthrax and that the supply of medicines to treat infections was inadequate to the potential need for them. In reaction to this fear, U.S. Secretary of Health Tommy Thompson declared his readiness to appropriate the patent on Cipro, an antibiotic to fight anthrax, owned by Bayer AG, unless the German-based company agreed to lower its price. This obviously undermined USTR head Robert Zoellick's ability to resist similar arguments involving health security pressed by the nations afflicted with the HIV/AIDS crisis.14 While the Doha agreement is a significant moment in the counterhegemonic struggle over intellectual property rights, it is important to recognize it as an incomplete victory.15 As proponents of the TRIPS were quick to point out in the aftermath of Doha, the agreement does nothing to alter the legal status of IPRs as embodied in the TRIPS. Nancy Pekarek, spokesperson for GlaxoSmithKline PLC, is quoted as saying, "I wouldn't say we're upset about this. The language [of the declaration] maintains the integrity of WTO protections of patents."16 Commenting on the status of the Doha Declaration, another industry lobbyist proclaimed it merely a political declaration rather than a legal challenge to the WTO rules. This attitude suggests then that while Big Pharm may have lost a battle, it still intends to wage war on violators of its patents. Looked at another way, the outcome in Doha as it affects pharmaceutical IPRs might be seen as a strategic retreat by center country trade ministers who saw concessions on AIDS drugs as the price to be paid for future rounds of multilateral trade negotiations. Interestingly, some industry insiders in the aftermath of the Doha talks argued that the declaration would have no impact on drug company profits. Industry analyst Hemant K. Shah claims, "It's a public-relations black eye, but it has no consequences whatsoever to the bottom line," while Pfizer CEO Henry McKinnell says that the agreement "will have zero effect on company profits" (Harris and Zimmerman 2001). These last comments certainly have the flavor of industry spin designed to settle the nerves of Big Pharm stockholders. In this case, the comments are more than likely true, given both the low marginal cost of production associated with pharmaceutical manufacture as well as the limited effective demand to be exploited in poor country markets. If they are true, however, it raises again some problematical questions for TRIPS advocates. Most fundamentally, if poor country markets are so marginal to the profits of pharmaceutical TNCs, then why did the industry lobby so intensively on behalf of the TRIPS agreement in the first place? The answer probably has more to do with longrun control over the global market for its future products than it does with short- or medium-run profit maximization. From the perspective of the poor countries themselves, the important question would seem to be the following: Wouldn't the best interests of poor country welfare be served by more flexibil-
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
163
ity in the structuring and interpretation of intellectual property rights as they bear on lifesaving drugs and therapies than that contained in the TRIPS agreement? We have seen that the likely answer to this question emanating from the periphery and semiperiphery areas of the world is an emphatic "yes." This raises then the following important question: What are the alternatives to the TRIPS approach to IPRs that would provide the poor countries with lifeenhancing, lifesaving pharmaceutical commodities and therapies? Is There an Alternative Model for Providing Lifesaving Drugs to Poor Countries? The problem of delivering lifesaving, lifd-enhancing commodities and therapies to the poor majorities must confront two essential difficulties. The first is that private, profit-seeking firms will not serve a market that fails to meet minimum rates of return on research, development, and marketing outlays however great may be the human cost in terms of mortality and debility. The other hard fact is that these same poor majorities lack the incomes required to provide these minimum requisite rates of return. The pharmaceutical executive, then, who argues that the underlying problem is not patents as much as it is poverty is making a valid point Inasmuch, however, as fatal and debilitating diseases are themselves an important constraint on economic growth and development, it must also be conceded that the failure to address the health care needs of poor people is to permanently consign them to both illness and poverty. Thus, as Scherer (2000) points out, we have a prime example of the kind of vicious circle frequently encountered in povertystricken nations. Alternative Patent Arrangements The way out of this conundrum must involve a formula to develop and make available the required drugs and therapies at as low a price as possible to those in need. Some people have argued that appropriately structured patent law may provide an answer. In this view, rather than require all countries to adopt the same set of patent laws and regulations, special patent arrangements could be devised that encourage pharmaceutical producers to enter otherwise risky or nonremunerative markets. An example that is favored by the pharmaceutical industry is known as a "roaming patent." This refers to an agreement with a private manufacturer to provide a new product in a new market in exchange for market exclusivity, or an extension of such exclusivity, on a product already marketed there. Such arrangements to date have not, however, proven to be particularly fruitful even in the markets of center,
164
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
developed countries. According to Trouiller et al. (2002), the average extension of drug patents among OECD countries between the 1980s and 1990s was six years, so that the average remaining patent life from the moment the drug was marketed averaged fourteen years. The result was a slight increase in the number of products, though the average rate of innovation was unchanged. Given this performance in markets regarded as far less risky than those found in poor countries, and given the scant R&D record of Big Pharm in developing treatments for tropical diseases, one cannot be optimistic that such an approach could be a successful alternative. Similar considerations apply to proposals involving government subsidies to private producers to develop commodities and treatments for neglected diseases. The issue of minimum adequate rate of return to induce R&D is compounded by the problem of adequate government finance to cover the cost of the subsidies. Unless rich countries can be counted on to help poorer countries cover the cost of subsidies, it is hard to see how the latter can pursue this path. Public-Private Partnerships An alternative preferred by some observers involves the promotion of publicprivate partnerships (PPPs). As the name suggests, PPPs are cooperative working arrangements involving a private entity (a corporation or nonprofit organization) and a government agency (a national government, a subnational government agency, or an international organization). Any PPP involving a private corporation faces the difficult problem of securing its cooperation in the absence of providing it with adequate pecuniary returns. 'Adequate" in this context is likely to mean levels of profit approximating those the corporation would expect to realize if it were to operate as an independent, profitmaximizing company. It is true that some pharmaceutical TNCs have lately engaged in PPPs to develop drugs for tropical diseases. Trouiller et al. (2002) describe, for example, the Medicines for Malaria Venture and the Global Alliance for Tuberculosis. These PPPs operate as nonprofit entities funded by public and philanthropic monies while engaging private corporations, development agencies, and academic institutions to develop new medicines for these diseases. As the authors note, however, corporate participation is'actually fairly limited; The Medicines for Malaria Venture operates fourteen projects, of which five have no industrial partner. In the remaining nine, only six companies are involved. Moreover, as Trouiller et al. further note, drug development is one thing; marketing and distribution of the end-products in a manner that ensures access by low-income patients is another. The ability of drug TNCs to participate in R&D is not in question. It is their willingness to part with the
TRIPS AND THE GLOBAL PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY
165
intellectual property rights that result that raises concerns. The dearth of PPPs involving corporate participation that address; the problems of less high-profile tropical diseases (implying narrower potential markets) also suggests the real limitation of the corporate philanthropic impulse. PPPs that operate independently of corporate participation face the problem of marshaling resources. Even a large international organization such as the World Health Organization (WHO) is constrained by limits on its finances, which derive mostly from member nation dues. The obvious solution, then, is for such institutions to increase their members' financial obligations in order to acquire the requisite resources to mbunt effective campaigns against the neglected diseases.17 This may be an obvious solution, but it is hardly an easy one. The United States has made clear- its distaste for funding international institutions whose goals and procedures are in conflict with its official policy positions and initiatives. Insofar as the latter are determined by private TNCs, including the global pharmaceutical giants, that way of developing an effective alternative to health care research and development seems to be blocked. It is easy, however, to be excessively pessimistic in this regard. The Doha Declaration demonstrates that the outcome of hegemonic struggle is frequently open to contestation. A well-coordinated effort by leaders in the periphery and semiperiphery, working with nongovernmental organizations, can shape to some degree the form and content of the global regulatory superstructure in ways that bring international capital to a greater level of accountability in international health matters than it has ever assumed before. It would seem necessary and natural, for example, that the need for a globally coordinated health care and research and development capacity be met by a globally coordinated and effective international tax mechanism capable of financing it. A unitary tax on the incomes from the global operations of the drug TNCs to help finance R&D on the neglected diseases, as well as to provide effective delivery of treatments and therapies, would be a good place to start. Tax credits could be provided to those firms thai; dedicate resources to these important efforts. Such an approach is a superior alternative to PPPs for the obvious reason that the voluntaristic character of the latter is replaced by a legal obligation. It also differs in its greater ability to separate resource mobilization from program administration and reduce the tendency for opportunistic behavior on the part of the corporations.18 Armed with the necessary finance, the WHO would be able to hire the research talent to develop the lifesaving, lifeenhancing products and therapies needed in the poorer areas of the globe. Economies of scale and of scope in R&D would provide welcome cost-savings, as would the lack of a need to engage in multibillion-dollar marketing efforts.
166
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Further social savings would be realized by the elimination of competing firms engaging in redundant research and development activities. Moreover, R&D centered on an international body such as the WHO would be more inclined to transfer its nonpatented technology freely to the emerging pharmaceutical and health care industries in the periphery and semi periphery, providing a boost to their development.
Intellectual Property Rights and the Agricultural Biotechnology Revolution
Technological progress has been a defining characteristic of agriculture since human beings first moved beyondjthe hunter-gatherer stage and began to cultivate the means for their subsistence. The ability to cultivate products for food and fiber is responsible for the transformation of nomadic human populations into settlements and the production of surpluses. These surpluses in turn provided the material basis for a division of labor, a hierarchical stratification of social relations, and the emergence of nonproductive classes. In the absence of thej latter, it is doubtful that the written word could have developed and with it the tremendous acceleration of technological development that has liters illy transformed the planet. It has been argued persuasively that at the root of the developed/underdeveloped divide that has characterized the modern world system is the relative rapidity of the development of agriculture and agricultural technique around the world (Diamond 1997). Toward the end of the twentieth century, there began the latest in a series of revolutions in agricultural technology that has involved the emergence of genetically modified organism^ (GMOs). GMOs are claimed by some to hold out the promise of increasing the quantity and quality of food and fiber and at the same time reducing the demands placed on agricultural resources and the environment at large. Critics argue that bioengineering has potentially dangerous environmental and human safety consequences. They believe that insufficient study of GMOs has been done to risk their release on the public. Other critics conter d that dominance of the new technologies by a handful of transnational corporations (TNCs) has had negative consequences for the structural characteristics of agriculture, leading to reduced competition and a loss of social welfare. It is feared that this restructuring will be especially hard felt in those countries whose working populations are still largely dedicated to agricultural pursuits. These countries are, of course, precisely those that constitute the world system's peripheral and semiperipheral areas. 167
168
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Intellectual Property in Agriculture At the center of the debate over agricultural biotech is the question of intellectual property rights (IPRs). There are, in fact, some striking parallels between the agricultural biotech and the pharmaceutical industries that have promoted both to the lead in advocating globally strengthened IPRs.1 Like pharmaceuticals agricultural biotech requires large fixed expenditures in research and development (R&D). Estimates of the dollar cost of developing a useful GMO run into the hundreds of millions of dollars, including the cost of testing and trials to meet health, safety, and environmental standards. At the same time, it is claimed that the resultant breakthrough products and processes are subject to relatively cheap imitation, duplication, or reverse engineering, so the huge investment in R&D may be quickly lost unless adequate intellectual property protections are provided. In this event, it is frequently argued, the necessary incentives to engage in the research effort required to bring forth such useful commodities will also be lost. Agricultural technology, like lifesaving drugs, is also said to have other characteristics that we associate with public goods. Biotech research draws on plant germplasm, the .basic stuff of plant genetics, which is often taken to be a fundamental endowment of humanity. Public institutions, both national and international, frequently undertake the function of caretaker of these resources and are often instrumental in both their conservation and development. These same institutions, including publicly funded research centers and universities, engage in basic research and development that is often provided free of charge to private companies for further development into commodities. Agricultural technology also frequently has important uncompensated environmental costs that can affect not only the industry itself but human health more generally. It is not surprising, then, that governments attempt to promote the public welfare by regulating agricultural biotech, just as they regulate the pharmaceutical industry, in order to ensure health, safety, and the appropriate reach of intellectual property rights. Agriculture and Trade Agriculture is among the most debated and contentious areas engaged by the multilateral trading system. Most countries, both developed and less developed, have attempted at one time or another to make agriculture an exception to the rules of free trade. The exceptionalism of agriculture has a lot to do with the very rapid pace of technological change that has occurred in the sector in the twentieth century. Before the Great Depression, 50 percent of the U.S. labor force was still engaged in pursuits directly tied to agricultural
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
169
production. Rapid increases in farm productivity, themselves considered by most economic historians to be a significant contributing factor in the Depression, resulted in massive rural to urban migrations beginning in the 1930s and lasting well into the post-World War tl period. Policies enacted during the 1930s and 1940s to combat rising rural 'poverty provided agriculture with a degree of economic protection not found! elsewhere in the economy. These policies included subsidies and price supports as well as tariff and nontariff trade barriers. The United States was joined by many European countries in providing protection to agriculture. Agricultural lobbies in these countries have traditionally enjoyed political influence disproportionate to the numbers of workers engaged in farming or raising livestock. In part, this influence has reflected a sort of cultural attachment to small, family owned farms. Paradoxically, it also reflects, however, the political strength of large agribusiness corporations. In almost every country where domestic and international policies have been marshaled to provide agriculture with protection and support, appeal is invariably made to the need for food security. Agriculture, it is argued, is exceptional precisely because its products are fundamentally important to national welfare. Leaving a nation's food supply to the vagaries of international markets is unduly risky. This sort o" argument seems to apply rather well to poor nations, especially those tha; encounter balance-of-payments crises from time to time that prevent them from importing essential commodities. For the more developed nations it seems like a specious argument but one with abundant populist attractiveness. Since the Uruguay Round of General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) negotiations, the exceptionalism of agriculture has come under reexamination. There are two interdependent reasons for this. First, as noted earlier, increased access to the agricultural markets of the center countries by the less developed countries (LDCs) was ls&d during the negotiations as a bargaining chip to induce the latter to accept inclusion of the trade-related aspects of intellectual property rights (TRIPS) agreement. It is not clear that this carrot was ultimately as determinative of LDC acquiescence as was the threatened stick of unilateral trade sanctions (i.e., U.S. Section 301 trade law), but it is frequently cited among the relevant motivations.2 More obvious is the second reason, which involves the desire of the centerbased agribusiness industry to have greater intellectual property (IP) protection for their biotechnological innovations. As a result, the TRIPS agreement expressly includes plant breeding as among the products and processes to be covered. It is remarkable that less than twenty years ago agriculture and livestock raising were also considered exceptional in the sense that their outputs were considered beyond the reach of patentable materials. While a great deal
170
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
of debate remains as to the precise contours of the new rules governing IPRs in living materials, it seems certain that the evolving international division of labor will create pressures for the commodification of all sorts of new organisms and biotechnical processes, with potentially dramatic consequences for how people work and live. In this chapter, we will consider both these pressures and some of the possible consequences. There are some important ways in which ag biotech differs from the pharm case. The first, as already suggested, is that while the pharmaceutical industry produces commodities of largely unchallenged usefulness and desirability, the agricultural biotech industry faces substantial challenges regarding the ultimate desirability of its outputs. While this chapter cannot pretend to provide a resolution of the various controversies surrounding the biotechnological revolution in plant and animal breeding currently under way, it seems necessary at least to offer a review of the salient issues under debate. Ultimately, however, I take the position that how we think about the desirability of particular GMOs is separable from the institutional and juridical context within which they are produced. A second important way that the ag biotech case differs from the pharm case involves the fact that the former is intricately involved in shaping the forces and relations of production, whereas the latter is largely concerned with the production of commodities.3 As we shall see, this fact has enormous implications for the ability of center-based capital to extend its reach over global production processes as well as the process of commodification of social and productive relationships. The TRIPS agreement, it will be argued, is an effective instrument for global capitalism precisely because it promotes these tendencies. Before we consider the details of these political economy arguments, however, it will be useful to consider the technical and environmental implications of the agricultural biotechnology revolution. The Biotech Debate Two interrelated technical issues are debated by proponents and opponents of biotechnology. Thefirstconcerns the benefits and risks to human health, safety, and welfare of GMOs. The second concerns the risks to the environment at large, including traditional agriculture and the security of the food supply. The Case for Agricultural Biotech Proponents of ag biotech cite as their most compelling argument the anticipation of large increases in yields of food and fiber crops as a result of the new technology. These proponents draw parallels to the green revolution
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
171
(GR) that began fifty years ago and tripled the [yields of important feed grains such as wheat, corn, and rice. Inasmuch as diminishing returns have set in for GR technology, however, it is imperative that the potential of biotech be exploited and made available, especially in those parts of the world where human population increases continue to outstrip agriculture's ability to feed them, particularly in the less developed countries where food shortages and hunger are regular occurrences. The urgency c-f technical progress is particularly acute given that agricultural resources arfe themselves diminishing, due to urban expansion, soil erosion and degradation, and increasing demands placed on fresh water supplies. I The biotech solution to these problems is to develop GMOs with certain desirable characteristics, such as drought tolerance or herbicide and pest resistance. New varieties can also be produced with ^enhanced nutritional content or even with novel nutrients to combat illnesses and nutritional deficiencies.4 Varieties can be developed that raise the energy content of feed grains, resulting in larger and healthier animals than traditional feeds produce and in less time. GMOs can also be developed that prolong the shelf life of crops so that less is lost to wastage. In general, the new technologies hold out the potential for enormous increases in agricultural efficiency, even compared to the advances made by GR high-yielding varieties during the 1950s and 1960s. Also, argue biotech's advocates, these benefits can be realized at a reduced cost to the environment and with greater farm worker safety. Agricultural GMOs developed for internal pest resista ice will require fewer external pesticide applications. This will mean less exposure to these chemicals by agricultural workers. It will also mean less chemical runoff into the soil, air, and groundwater supplies, making these safer for other uses. An example is provided by so-called B.t. corn. B.t. refers to Bacillus thuringiensis, a bacterium that, when spliced into corn, produces a protein toxic to pests but harmless to human beings. Similarly, GMOs have; been developed that provide resistance of some crops to herbicides that are especially effective against certain weeds. In the absence of this resistance, farmers would have to use other herbicides that are more dangerous to the environment. Finally, some proponents also argue that biotech has the potential to combat the problems of genetic erosion and genet c uniformity. Genetic erosion occurs when the gene pool is contracted by the extinction of species. This is dangerous because it narrows the options in the range of species and characteristics of species at our disposal for future use. Once a species or characteristic is eliminated from the gene pool, no amount of genetic manipulation or recombination can bring it back. Genetic uniformity occurs when a particular species is so widely adopted that it becomes excessively vulnerable to catastrophe. If a particular variety of corn becomes uniformly adopted in an
172
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
area, for example, a pest or pathogen could wipe out all or most of the entire crop, leaving terrible food shortages and hunger in its wake. Proponents argue that ag biotech could combat genetic erosion associated with loss of species by introducing into endangered species traits that enable them to resist better the threats to their existence. Thus, for example, if a particular species is threatened by a disease, a gene from another, diseaseresistant plant, even one that is not a close relative, could be inserted in order to enhance the species* chances for survival. Biotechnology combats genetic uniformity insofar as biotech engineers "create" a wide spectrum of new and differentiated varieties, each developed in response to a particular market niche. Also, biotechnology engineers can respond far more rapidly than traditional breeding methods to radical changes in environmental conditions that would otherwise result in catastrophic crop disasters (Goss 1996). The Case Against Agricultural Biotech Not surprisingly, opponents of agricultural biotechnology take exception to virtually every one of the above claims. Rather than regard ag biotech as the fount of green revolution-style productivity increases, opponents tend instead to stress the potential for agricultural and environmental calamity as a consequence of new and mostly untested techniques. These perceived threats are largely the result of a belief that bioengineering is extremely vulnerable to the law of unintended (environmental) consequences. B.t. corn may be used as an example of the kind of vulnerability represented by agricultural GMOs. The pest resistance engineered into corn could ultimately result in the emergence of pests that are themselves resistant to the B.t. toxin. Herbicide-resistant crops could pass that very resistance over to weedy relatives, resulting in the emergence of a "superweed" that cannot be controlled by any herbicide. Introducing new GMOs into ecosystems different from those where they were initially developed and tested creates even more uncertainty as to their ultimate environmental impacts. According to biotech advocates, these sorts of dangers are unlikely inasmuch as the fertility of hybrid plants that develop from a cross of crops and wild plants is typically very low. Other plant scientists are not so sanguine, however. Recent study has shown, for example, that plants beyond the initial hybrids carrying the gene for herbicide resistance have in fact emerged (Kling 1996). Moreover, these plants had very fertile pollen, suggesting a strong possibility for further propagation. This cross-fertilization of wild populations has even occurred over substantial distances, reducing confidence that the environmental effects of GMOs can be controlled by careful, selective limitation of cultivated areas.
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
173
Neither is it obvious that the new varieties will be less chemical-intensive than the ones they replace. They may merely replace one kind of chemical treatment with another. Certainly the chemical companies that are at the forefront of ag biotech research expect their efforts to promote sales of the chemical complements that accompany the use of the newly engineered seeds. Exception is also taken to the claims th!at ag biotech can reverse the current tendencies toward genetic erosion and genetic uniformity. To the contrary, if the GMOs are as high-yielding and efficient as advocates claim, there will be tremendous economic pressure for their adoption, including, and especially, in the periphery and semiperiphery nations. This will almost certainly lead to greater genetic uniformity!. The fact that poor countries will also be forced into adoption of these same varieties as a matter of competitive necessity suggests a double jeopardy for the problem of genetic erosion. First, these countries will replace their own traditional varieties with the new, bioengineered ones. Second, more land area will be brought under cultivation to accommodate these new varieties, displacing wild areas wherein resides the bulk of the world's genetic diversity. It is well to remember that while the poor countries of the world are poor in respect to common measures of economic welfare, they tend still; to be environmentally rich and diverse as compared to the developed center countries. In fact, as will be discussed in greater detail below, the poo:' countries constitute the earth's genetic repository from which are withdraw n the basic materials out of which new agricultural and other biotechnical innovations emerge. The introduction and spread of new, economically domi lant plant varieties developed by the agribusiness transnational corporations could have the effect of undermining the gene bank upon which these sa:ne innovations depend. Finally, the claim that the new agricultural GMOs represent the world's best chance at defeating the scourge of hunger and malnutrition has been challenged on a number of bases. First, insufficient research has been conducted regarding the safety of GMOs for human use. While producers of such crops insist that they are perfectly safe, there exists worldwide opposition to their unrestricted integration into the global trading system. Producers and sellers of the transgenic crops even resist labeling their commodities as such from fear that they will be irrationally rejected in the marketplace. Consumers, on the other hand, insist that they have a right to know what they are buying. There is also fear that traditionally bred varieties can become contaminated in the absence of careful efforts to label and segregate the genetically modified ones. Second, as Table 7.1 indicates, most of the research and development of GM crops has been conducted in the center countries, and particularly in the United States, on crops that have a central role to play in the food and fiber
174
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION 175
Table 7.1 Global Area Dedicated to Genetically Modified Crops, 1996-2002 (in million hectares) 1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
United States 1.5 Argentina 0.1 Canada 0.1 China 1.1 South Africa 0 Australia <0.1 Romania 0 Mexico <0.1 Bulgaria 0 Spain 0 Germany 0 France 0 Uruguay 0 Indonesia 0 Ukraine Portugal Colombia Honduras
8.1 1.4 1.3 1.8 0 0.1 0 <0.1 0 0 0 0 0 0
20.6 4.3 2.8 <0.1 <0.1 0.1 0 <0.1 0 <0.1 0 <0.1 0 0 0 0
28.7 6.7 4.0 0.3 0.1 0.1 <0.1 <0.1 0 <0.1 0 <0.1 0 0 <0.1 <0.1
30.3 10.0 3.0 0.5 0.2 0.2 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1
35.7 11.8 3.2 1.5 0.2 0.2 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1
39.0 13.5 3.5 2.1 0.3 0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1 <0.1
<0.1 <0.1
<0.1 <0.1
<0.1 <0.1
<0.1
1.7
11.0
52.6
58.7
Country
Total
1996
27.8
39.9
44.2
Source: International Service for the Acquisition of Agri-biotech Applications, www. isaaa.org. Reprinted with permission.
systems of these countries. The most prominent success story, as noted above, involves corn. Far less attention has been paid to research on crops that predominate in tropical and semitropical environments and that play a large role in the food and fiber systems of the poor countries.5 Insofar as the poor countries are integrated into the biotechnical revolution, it is not likely that they will be so on terms that are propitious to their own socieconomic advance. Rissler and Mellon (1993) express this concern as follows: Biotechnology companies cannot develop products for people who cannot afford pay [sic] for them. Unfortunately, most of the world's hungry are too poor to buy traditionally bred crops, much less the expensive products of biotechnology. Given the limited interest that industry and universities currently have in the crops of the developing world, for the time being genetic engineering will play a minor role, at best, in the coming crisis of world food production, (p. 10) Third, opponents argue that alternatives to biotechnical engineering exist that address the problems of food sufficiency and security without carrying
the risks inherent in genetic manipulation. Sustainable, "systems-based" approaches to agriculture that rely on natural defenses against pests and pathogens are to be preferred to either chemically intensive or genetic manipulation techniques. Such approaches are preferred on the basis of their comparatively benign consequences for the environment asiwell as for worker and consumer health and safety. The argument that sustainable practices produce inadequate yields is countered with the observation thatjthe real roots of hunger and malnutrition in the world have far less to do with agricultural productivity than is generally imagined. Sustainable agricultural practices are technically capable of feeding the world. The real constraints to solving the hunger problem are social and political and, as the above quotation makes clear, there is no reason to expect the biotechnical approach to ease these constraints. Clearly, the debate surrounding the scientific claims of ag biotech still awaits additional empirical evidence before its outstanding questions can be resolved. It is notable, however, that the lack of study has not slowed the pace of research and development on new GMOs and has barely slowed the rate of their introduction into the increasingly global food and fiber systems. In trying to account for these facts, we are clearly, once again, confronted with forces that are broadly political economy in nature and beyond the narrowly scientific and technical debate. We need then to understand the actors engaged in the political economy struggle for hegemony in the area of agricultural biotechnology and how they operate. This is the task of the next section. The Juridical and Ideological Landscape In this section I wish to outline the juridical and ideological basis for property rights in living organisms (particularly plants) as it has developed both in the United States and in the world as a whole over the course of the twentieth century, particularly in the post-World War II period—the period of the ascendency and relative decline of U.S. hegemony in the world capitalist system and the emergence of an incipient global state. U.S. IP Law and Agriculture The first U.S. law that provided IP protection to plants was the Plant Protection Act (PPA), passed in 1930. To understand the reach of this law, it is necessary to understand the distinction between plants that reproduce sexually and those that reproduce asexually. Sexual reproduction of plants occurs through the transfer of pollen from the male organ of the flower (the stamen) to the female organ (the ovule), resulting in fertile seed. Asexual reproduction occurs; in the absence of this transfer and is typically occasioned by the
176
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
direct grafting of one part of a plant onto another, or the propagation of a plant from the cutting of another. Asexual reproduction techniques are generally limited to fruit trees, nuts, and ornamental plants. The PPA extended patent protection only to these classes of plants and was therefore of limited commercial significance. Despite the lobbying efforts of the American Seed Traders Association, the law was explicitly excluded from application to sexually reproducing plants, on the basis that such plants tend to genetic instability and drift and therefore present difficult problems of enforcement, (Kloppenburg 1988, pp. 132-133).6 In addition to such practical problems, officials hesitated to grant monopoly rights, even for a short period, in basic crop seed—a notion that found substantial political resistance among farmers. The PPA was not without utility for commercial enterprises that specialized in the propagation of seed for sale. The act itself differed from standard patent law in that novel varieties of seed were not required to pass a utility test as might apply to an industrial, patentable invention. It was only necessary that the new plant be novel in some particular characteristic, even if not superior to any existing variety. This would establish an important precedent for future considerations of plant patents. In the decades immediately following the passage of the PPA, the seed companies began to intensify both their R&D and marketing efforts. Kloppenburg (1988) describes a two-pronged strategy of the companies. First, the companies worked to develop hybrid varieties of corn that possessed the extremely marketable, characteristic of high yields. More important than the fact of high yields, however, is the additional fact that hybrid seed suffers a dramatic reduction in fertility beyond the first generation. That is to say, seed saved from a hybrid parent will not be subsequently very productive. This disadvantage from the farmer's perspective is a gain for the commercial seed developer—namely, the seed fully becomes a commodity with a welldeveloped potential as a market exchange value. In turn, an important part of the social production process comes under the greater direction of the seed companies and less under the direction of the farmer. The seed companies were strongly aided in the effort to develop hybrid com varieties by the United States Department of Agriculture as well as a variety of publicly funded state agricultural experiment stations. In fact, it is probably more accurate to say that these public agencies conducted the bulk of the R&D, with the seed companies dedicated primarily to marketing the end products. The problem faced by the companies, however, was that they found themselves in competition with the public agencies, which were inclined to distribute seed to farmers freely rather than sell it to them. The experience of developing hybrid corn convinced the companies that they needed to be more involved in the R&D process. The companies sought to
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
177
promote a social division of labor whereby the applied development function would be carried out by themselves afid the basic science would be conducted by the public agencies. Kloppenburg describes the significance of hybridization as follows: Hybridization had provided a solution to the biological barrier to capital penetration posed by the seed. Just as important, the companies engaged in hybrid seed-com production had been able to supplant public agencies as the principal developers of commercial varieties. The experience of hybrid com showed seedsmen that both the biological bbstacle posed by the seed and the institutional obstacle posed by the state could be overcome, (p. 134) The second prong of the seed companies' strategy involved their attempts to weaken regulatory oversight of the industry. Seed producers argued that buyers (i.e., farmers) should be the arbiters of quality rather than state experiment stations, which by the 1950s had begun to publish lists of certified seed (Kloppenburg 1988, p. 135). In this way, the door was opened to greater product differentiation and marketing opportunities for the new varieties developed by the companies themselves. During the 1950s, then, the seed companies began to displace the publicly funded experiment stations in new variety development and seed marketing. In 1970, Congress passed the Plant Variety Protection Act (PVPA), which granted protections to new varieties of sexually reproducing plants and dramatically changed the landscape as regards IPRs in agriculture and plant breeding. The new law established that "the breeder of any novel variety of sexually reproducing plants (except fungi, bacteria, and hybrids) . . . is entitled to plant variety protections" (quoted m Scalise and Nugent 1995, p. 88). With this law, commercially valuable crops such as corn and cotton are afforded IP protections under the conditions! that the new variety exhibits a novel characteristic that differentiates the variety from existing varieties and that the novel characteristic is uniform and commercially acceptable. The latter conditions are intended to ensure a nee sssary degree of quality control in the new variety. The PVPA made two important exceptions to the exclusionary privileges it provides to innovative plant breeders. The first is the research exception, which allows plant scientists to reproduce a protected variety for legitimate research purposes. The second, more important, exception is extended to farmers and is known as "farmers' privilege." Under this doctrine, farmers are granted two significant rights: (1) to sell crops produced from a protected variety for purposes other than reproduction; and (2) to save seed from their protected crops for future use, including for planting. The first of these rights is a logical necessity to farmers who must sell their outputs. The second,
178
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
however, carries important implications for breeder-innovators. Essentially it raises the possibility that the sale of a new variety of seed yields its innovator only a one-time return rather than the recurrent returns that would be the result of repeated sales of the new commodity. Moreover, the farmers' privilege exemption also allows the initial purchasers of innovative seed to sell the seed they have saved from their plantings without compensating the original developer of the seed. While the farmers' exemption suggests the potential for a dramatic limitation on the ability of the PVPA to provide IP protection to private sector seed producers, seed technology involving hydridization ensured that the market for commercial seed would continue to develop. It also ensured the further development of the commodification of agriculture as an industry and the rise to dominance of transnational capital on food and fiber production.7 An extremely important juridical and ideological development, which did not even directly involve the agricultural industry, was the 1980 Supreme Court ruling in the case of Diamond v. Chakrabarty. Prior to this ruling, the court system was not inclined to favorably consider the notion of the patentability of living matter. Amanda Chakrabarty was a microbiologist who had genetically engineered a bacterium (Pseudomonas) capable of breaking down the components of crude petroleum. This invention has obvious utility in treating oil spills. The Supreme Court ruling, overturning earlier rulings by the U.S. Patent Office that denied the inventor's patent application, asserted that Chakrabarty's invention satisfied Congress's intentions on such key terms as "composition of matter" and "manufacture" (Scalise and Nugent 1995). Subsequent Court rulings have upheld the Diamond v. Chakrabarty decision, and the upshot is a ruling that has changed the prospects for biotechnology entirely. Into this brave new juridical world, plant biotechnologists have rushed to develop new GMOs that promise to alter the entire basis of global agriculture —both the commodities it produces and the way they are produced. The International Legal Struggle over Breeders' Rights The development of legal doctrine and institutions to protect IP in breeders' innovations in the United States had its counterparts in Europe. In 1961, the Union for the Protection of New Varieties of Plants (UPOV) was created by six European nations as an effort to establish and harmonize plant breeders' rights (PBRs) on an international basis. The UPOV is administered in cooperation with the World Intellectual Property Organization and has been revised and updated several times since its initial inception. The most recent revision expands the scope of breeders' rights to include a greater number of species and genera for which protection is available, provides for a longer
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
179
term of protection, and restricts both farmers' privileges and researchers' exemptions. These changes, reflecting the advances in biotechnology's capacity to manipulate and exploit the genetic content of living organisms, seek to provide innovators greater protection- The vast majority of these innovators reside in the center countries and it is not surprising to find that most of the signatories to the UPOV are these same countries, while periphery and semiperiphery countries have been much slower to become members. For many countries (including the world's poorest), the stimulus to adopt the conditions of and become members of the UPOV was the establishment of the TRIPS agreement. The TRIPS and Plant Breeders' Rights Although the TRIPS agreement makes no explicit mention of the UPOV, it requires WTO members to provide either patent protection for new plant varieties or, as an alternative, an effective sui generis system of law for PBRs, or some such combination of the two.8 TRIPS also obliges its members to provide patent protection for microbiological and nonbiological processes for plant and animal production. Plants and animals other than microorganisms and essentially biological processes for the production of plants and animals may be excluded from patent protection. Other limits on IPRs for living organisms may be imposed consistent with application of the TRIPS agreement to limitations for other industrial innovations. For example, patents may be prohibited in order to protect public order or morality, including to protect animal or plant life or health. Compulsory licenses may be issued under certain circumstances, including that "adequate remuneration" be provided and that th :y be subject to judicial review. Member noncompliance is enforced.by the threat of trade sanctions just as it would be for other violations of IPRs established by the agreement. Also, as in other areas of contention between the center and periphery and semiperiphery involving the TRIPS discussion, negotiations surrounding PBRs were not separable from the other aspects of Uruguay Round deliberations. Poorer countries were subject to the same range of incentives and threats in the context of PBRs that led to their acquiescence to the TRIPS as a whole. While the TRIPS agreement is a significant event in the process of achieving greater universality of IPRs in the area of food and fiber production and consumption, there still exists a great deal of ideological and institutional ambiguity surrounding the question of IPRs and living organisms and the application of IPRs to agriculture. This ambiguity in turn has provoked some interesting attempts to turn the relevant political discourse in a counterhegemonic direction. One such attempt is embodied in the International Un-
180
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
dertaking on Plant Genetic Resources (IU). This agreement was established as a resolution of the Twenty-second Session of the Food and Agricultural Organization Conference held in Rome in the fall of 1983. Its purpose was to "promote international harmony in matters regarding access to plant genetic resources for food and agriculture" and "to ensure that plant genetic resources of economic and/or social interest, particularly for agriculture, will be explored, preserved, evaluated and made available for plant breeding and scientific purposes" (FAO/CGRFA 1983). The substantive content of the IU, which has been endorsed by well over a hundred signatory nations, includes recognition that genetic resources are the "common heritage of mankind" and that all measures possible need to be taken to ensure equitable access. Equitable access in this context, however, must be understood to include not just the raw germplasm that is found most frequently in the poor countries, but also the elite breeding materials developed from this material in the rich countries. In addition, the IU calls for the establishment of so-called farmers' rights (Resolution 5/89). These refer to compensation schemes that make payments to (informal) plant breeders in poor countries for the use of germplasm. Such payments recognize their contribution not only to plant innovations, but also to the maintenance of genetic biodiversity, the absence of which would imperil the planet's long-term ability to provide itself with essential raw materials, food, and medicines. Resolution 4/89 of the IU sets forth a case that the undertaking is not inconsistent with PBRs as codified by the UPOV. It is clear, however, that important inconsistencies exist in the two outlooks. The clearest contradiction exists in the simultaneous assertions that there can be unrestricted access to elite breeding materials developed in the center countries by those who reside in the periphery, and that the developers of these materials can enjoy intellectual property protections that enable them to set the conditions for access or exclusion. This contradiction is apparent to critics of the undertaking, such as U.S. State Department spokesperson Melinda Kimble, who asks: Why have we arrived at this impasse? Certainly one element has been the emergence of the principle of mutually agreed terms that is now controlling germplasm exchange in the broadest sense. From an economic perspective, this formula may best accommodate and protect the interests of all parties. From a scientific perspective, however, these arrangements will reduce exchanges of germplasm and limit use of and research on germplasm as the potential for a return will be critical in a decision to undertake a conditioned exchange. An unintended consequence of reduced collection and exchange may well be more rapid loss of genetic resources as only the most promising strains will be studied. Moreover, an increasing part of the flow of germplasm will take place in the private rather than the public sector. (1998, p. 70)
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
181
From the perspective of Kimble and other critics of the IU, attempts to restrict the flow of "raw" germplasm will have an important negative impact on scientific advances in the broad area of biotechnology. At the same time, requirements that compensation be paid to those who have had a hand in the development and preservation of "raw" germplasm, it is argued, will raise the cost of investments in the development of biotechnical innovations. Taken in combination, then, these views advocate |a strengthening of private sector IPRs as they apply to recent biotechnical innovations emanating from the center-based agribusiness transnational corporations, but a maintenance of the status quo as regards the free international flow of basic plant germplasm. i The U.N. Convention on Biological Diversity This sort of unequal exchange in plant genetic resources advocated by center capitalist interests received a more recent challenge from the United Nations Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD). The convention was a by-product of the U.N. Conference on Environment and Development, held in Rio de Janeiro in 1992. Its purposes are to conserve biological species, genetic resources, habitats, and ecosystems; to ensure- the sustainable use of biological materials; and to provide for the fair and equitable sharing of benefits derived from genetic resources (United Natiohs 1997). It makes provisions for both ex situ and in situ conservation of genetic resources. The first refers to germplasm banks located outside the native habitat of a species, while the latter refers to one located within the species' native habitat. The CBD also requires that signatory nations adopt regulations to conserve biological resources and that these regulations apply to private corporations within the nations' jurisdiction. It establishes a fund :o assist developing countries to implement its provisions and to promote the transfer of technology to these countries from the developed countries "wtjtere such transfer does not prejudice intellectual property rights or patents." By the end of 1992,156 countries had sighed and ratified the CBD, with the United States the most conspicuous exception.9 Opposition to the CBD in the United States was led by conservative political interests against domestic restrictions on land use and what these interests regard as costly environmental protection legislation. The United States did sign the agreement in 1993 when the Clinton administration succeeded that Of George Bush. This reconsideration of the CBD probably signaled a changed attitude on the part of U.S. industrial interests as much as it did the shift in political outlook. Failing to sign the agreement left U.S -based corporations without the leverage to influence its future direction and provisions and raised the risk that these companies could be left out of expanding opportunities for bioprospecting in the genetically resource-rich areas of the world. At the same time, it is useful to note that as of this date the U.S. Congress has yet to ratify the convention.
182
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
Although the CBD addresses itself to agriculture in general terms and cites the dangers of declining agricultural diversity and the threat this poses to food security, the convention is a very wide-ranging document that encompasses an almost unwieldy number of different kinds of particular concerns. Sharper international focus was provided to agriculture in the mid-1990s by the socalled Leipzig Declaration, named after the city that hosted the International Technical Conference on Plant Genetic Resources. The conference was organized by the UN Food and Agricultural Organization (FAO). The Leipzig Declaration specifies a global action plan that calls for new on-farm (in situ) conservation techniques in regard to food crops that provide training to farmers, especially women, as well as for the preservation ex situ of wild plants that are potentially important for food production. It also calls for the development of plans to aid in the alleviation of food-related disasters. Emphasis is placed on the need to "strengthen local capacity to produce, distribute and market farm-saved seed of crop varieties essential for food security, to help diversity and agricultural production systems through the increased use and commercialization of local and under-utilized crops" (FAO 1996). Financing for the global action plan is to be provided in part by the parties to the Convention on Biological Diversity, predominantly by the developed countries. The plan also explicitly recognizes the need "to realize Farmers' Rights as defined in FAO Resolution 5/89." Once again, however, it is apparent that contradictions exist in a plan that emphasizes equity and farmers' rights and yet also insists on its compatibility with profit-oriented, exclusionary breeders' rights. U.S. State Department spokesperson Kimble expresses the challenge of squaring this particular circle in the following terms: The problem is—as always—financing. Although we believe many actions can be taken within the framework of existing resources and donor countries can better target current programs to advance this action plan, yet we still come back to the question of whether or not it is in an individual country's interest to take actions that it will not be generously compensated for by the international community, with direct unconditioned assistance to mitigate the potential losses of plant genetic resources. Although this demand for compensation remains part of the FAO theology, in reality, no matter what we say about farmers and their rights, farmers and their communities preserved landraces, varieties, and seeds over centuries because it was essential to their very survival. (1998, p. 71) It is apparent from this statement that the United States, while placing a high value on the work of preserving genetic resources, feels no particular moral or fiduciary responsibility to help bear the burden of its associated cost as it pertains to the major repositories of genetic diversity in the world today—namely,
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
183
the peripheral countries. Kimble makes clear that a solution to the conundrum is provided by the adoption of institutions that parallel those developed in the United States for the preservation of plant genetic resources. She writes: At Leipzig, we focused on promoting similar models to that of the USA and stressed that it is every nation's interest to inventory, collect, use, and preserve their existing stock of genetic resources for food and agriculture. In the USA, these actions were not considered luxuries but essential public actions that provided more flexibility tola dynamic, private agriculture sector. Replicating this model, we believed, could be achieved with the right combination of national, bilateral, multilateral, and hopefully, private sector funding that would promote the implementation of the Leipzig GAP as an essential building block in any sustainable future. (1998, p. 72) Emphasizing the private sector aspect of the model, Kimble makes clear what she regards as essential. An essential ingredient in making a more privately funded system work is expanding plant variety protection into true intellectual property patent protection—and this is where Benefit Sharing with developing countries becomes a dominant issue. For us to preserve some measure of the old system, we need to build a more persua; ive case than we have been able to do so far that IPR and Benefit Sharing are not mutually exclusive. This is the key to convincing the developing world that we are not exploiting their germplasm. Kimble insists that "benefit sharing" is the appropriate province and responsibility of local agencies and must be addressed at the national level. The more immediate concern of the State Department, it would appear, is altering the perceptions of the developing world as regards the good intentions of center country TNCs and setting aside the '''theology" of international agencies such as the FAO. That is, the challenge faced by the organic intellectuals of the historic bloc is to establish the legitimacy of an expansion of IPRs in the areas of genetically modified organisms and biotechnology while reducing as far as possible, or maintaining at a low level, the cost, availability, and accessibility of raw materials (germplasm). A major part of this ideological effort is directed at shaping the discourse as to what precisely constitutes authentic intellectual property and "mankind's common heritage." I shall argue below that the dominant historic bloc has been mostly successful in these tasks and that its successes have placed serious limits to date on the options for counterhegemonic alternatives. Before I discuss these limits, however, it will be useful to consider more fully how the TRIPS agreement may be ex-
184
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
pected to affect both production techniques as well as the social relations of production in what is becoming a global agricultural economy. Agricultural Technology and International Capital As noted earlier, the emergent biotechnical revolution in agriculture is often compared to another agricultural "revolution" that occurred in the postwar period—the green revolution. There are some similarities between the two as well as some important differences that we should consider. The Green Revolution The green revolution (GR) refers to the development of several so-called super varieties of crops (wheat, corn, and rice) beginning in the mid-1940s, mostly in research centers in the center, developed countries, with funding provided by the Ford and Rockefeller foundations. The primary objective of the research was to develop high-yielding varieties (HYVs) that could be raised under a variety of growing conditions, including those found in poor countries. The development of adequate HYVs took considerable time and resources but ultimately proved successful in increasing yields dramatically. Under ideal conditions, Borlaug wheat—named for its chief architect, Norman Borlaug—produced nine times the yield of earlier varieties. The International Rice Research Institute in the Philippines was credited in the early 1960s with producing a "miracle rice" whose yields were nearly double those of the earlier varieties. Optimism surrounding the successes of the GR was soon tempered, however, by the realization of what Wharton (1969) terms the revolution's second generation problems. Foremost among these is the fact that the dramatic yield increases associated with the HYVs require large increases in complementary agricultural inputs, especially large amounts of fertilizer and irrigation. While the GR proponents liked to stress that the new varieties are scale neutral and therefore, from a technical point of view, within the means of smaller cultivators, the reality was that small adopters lacked the knowledge and resources to be successful. Given the large increases in yields attained by the better endowed adopters, therefore, price declines drove many small cultivators off their farms and into the migratory streams looking for alternative employment in the urban sector. The GR, then, had profoundly negative social consequences in direct relation to the technical successes in raising yields. Radical critics of the GR, such as Cleaver (1972), argue that the introduction of the HYVs into the peripheral countries was guided by neoimperialist motivations. According to Cleaver, the essential motivation behind the GR
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
185
was the desire to remake Third World agriculture in the image of center country agribusiness. While purporting to enable the poorer countries to become food self-sufficient, the GR has rendered them more dependent and vulnerable and has given rise to a number of contradictions. The most obvious of these contradictions is that the introduction of the HYVs has reproduced even greater inequalities in income and wealth for the reason cited above, concerning the differential ability of small peasant producers, as compared to that of their larger competitors, to afford the package of inputs required for HYV use.10 Some have argued that the solution to this problem is institutional change, including land reform and greater provision of credit and extension services. Such reforms would undoubtedly be an| aid to small-scale agriculture in the poor countries, but there is nothing in the GR package that advances such reforms and much that serves to work against their implementation. The major beneficiaries of the GR, according to Cleaver's critique, are the large-scale growers who successfully aidopt the complementary package of chemical- and machine-intensive inputs along with the HYV seed, and the sellers of these inputs and seed who export them from the developed countries. Oftentimes the transnational corporate agribusinesses also take charge of marketing the outputs of the reengineered production process and are able to extract additional profits in their capacity as monopsony buyers. The GR then operates as a technological mechanism by which capital is able to transform social production in ways favorable to the accumulation of capital on a global scale. The individual farmer who survives this production process is correspondingly transformed from an independent proprietor into a highly dependent subcontractor whose range o|f productive responsibility has been radically narrowed and specialized. Those former farmers who do not survive are transformed into a dispossessed rural proletariat who provide wage labor to the reengineered agricultural production process or, as noted, migrate to join the urban labor force. The GR had another important effect, described by Kloppenburg (1988). The international agricultural research centers (IARCs) established by the large foundations in the poor host nations acted as conduits for the transfer of germplasm back to the center countries. In this manner, the center countries were able to gather and maintain ex| situ stocks of genetic raw materials out of which seed developers could develop HYVs, including hybrids, for reintroduction back to the periphery. Kloppenburg writes: The IARCs are not only a mechanism for encouraging capitalist development in the Third World countryside, they are also vehicles for the efficient extraction of plant genetic resources from the Third World and their transfer to the gene banks of Europe,; North America, and Japan. It is not hap-
186
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
penstance that the CGIAR [Consultative Group on International Agricultural Research] institutions are located in the Vavilov centers of genetic diversity." The CGIAR system is, in one sense, the modern successor to the eighteenth- and nineteenth-century botanical gardens that served as conduits for the transmission of plant genetic information from the colonies to the imperial powers, (p. 161) Agricultural Biotech, Capital, and Political Economy
International
After this brief description of the green revolution and its role in the internationalization of capital as it applies to agriculture, it is natural to ask how the emergent agricultural biotechnical revolution compares. The most obvious difference concerns technology. The green revolution was concerned with developing HYVs of crops through intensively applied, but otherwise wellknown, breeding techniques. That is, by cross-breeding different parent lines of otherwise identical species with differentiated characteristics, researchers sought to develop lines that produced dramatic increases in yields and were productive under a variety of growing environments. These lines also needed to resist disease and be amenable to efficient harvesting methods. Moreover, they needed to have the characteristics that would make them desirable as finished commodities. Given the long list of requisite characteristics;'it is not surprising that so much time and effort was devoted to the research effort. Borlaug wheat, the first of the successful HYVs, took twenty years (194464) to develop and had to overcome a variety of failures before a line suitable for generalized release was developed. The great technical advantage of the newer recombinant techniques of the biotechnical revolution is that the desirable characteristics of one organism can be directly introduced into another. This means that the development of a GMO takes less time than traditional breeding techniques require. Also, whereas under traditional approaches involving sexual reproduction, the parents of a new line must be sexually compatible, no such requirement is necessary for the recombinant techniques. Thus some highly desirable characteristic from one organism may, in principle, be introduced into a second, unrelated organism, resulting in a third that is the first of its species to display the desired trait. In this fashion, the range of potential GMOs from recombinant techniques is far larger than would result from traditional breeding methods. The truly important implication of this essentially technical issue, however, is that the emergent agricultural biotechnology is far richer in its potential to generate a wide range of new agricultural commodities. The intensification of agriculture's commodization, in turn, carries im-
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
187
portant implications for the continuing transformation of the social relations of agriculture production on a global scale. This point will be further developed below. \ The technical differences separating the GR from the biotechnology revolution (BR) are matched by differences in jtheir political economic underpinnings. Whereas the GR was the result of a (quasi-public effort to develop new varieties of crops that would be distributed worldwide at as low a cost as possible, the BR is a largely private secltor undertaking motivated by the prospect of profit. In this respect, it is interesting to consider the transformation undergone by the IARCs established to spearhead the GR research effort in the 1940s. Initially these centers were established in a variety of sites in the peripheral countries to perform two;functions (Kloppenburg 1988, pp. 160-166). The first function was to collect and evaluate raw germplasm from indigenous landraces and primitive cultiyars out of which the HYVs would be developed. The second was to enable the agricultural gene banks located in the center countries to amass a collection of genetic materials that would serve as the basis for their own agricultural R&D. The activities of the IARCs were coordinated and directed by another] Rockefeller and Ford foundations creation called the Consultative Group on nternational Agricultural Research (CGIAR), established in 1971. IBPGR Versus CGIAR: The Struggle for Hegemony in Global Agriculture As the realization of the threats of genetic erosion and uniformity began to dawn on agricultural experts during the 1970s, a debate arose as to how and where to organize and direct an institutior al response to these problems. The United Nations FAO held several international conferences and established a Crop Ecology Unit specifically for this purpose. The CGIAR, however, argued that it possessed the necessary research capabilities for the job. A compromise solution was found that created the International Board for Plant Genetic Resources (IBPGR) in 1974 and formally linked it to the United Nations. But as Kloppenburg points out, iffective control remained with the privately funded CGIAR. The IBPGR is housed in the FAO's Rome headquarters and superficially appears to be an integral part of the United Nations system. However, the board's budget is provided not by the FAO but by a group of twenty-two national governments and other organizations that are members of the CGIAR. With the exception of India, China, and the United Nations Environment Programme, all of the donors represent the advanced capitalist nations. Sixty-
188
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
nine percent of the IBPGR's 1984 budget was underwritten by just six of these donors: Canada, Japan, Netherlands, United Kingdom, United States Agency for International Development, and the World Bank. The board's policies are set not by debate among member nations of the FAO but through decision-making processes internal to the CGIAR. The IBPGR may cloak itself in the "internationalist" legitimacy provided by its association with the FAO, but the board is not subject to the control of the United Nations. The financial heart and political soul of the IBPGR is elsewhere, (p. 164) From its inception, the CGIAR and its constituent centers operated on the principle that genetic resources constituted a "common heritage of mankind" and their preservation amounted to a public good calling for collective action. As a corollary to this principle, it was maintained that access to these resources should be open to all. Over the twenty-year period following the establishment of the CGIAR, intellectual property became an issue of increasing concern on the part of both the public and private interests that held stakes in the CGIAR. Even as late as 1989, however, the CGIAR still adhered to the "common heritage" view as articulated in the following policy statement regarding ex situ collections of plant genetic materials. The CGIAR regards the preservation of variability in plant germplasm as vital for research in subjects related to crop improvement. It is the CGIAR policy that collections assembled as a result of international collaboration should not become the property of any single nation, but should be held in trust for the use of present and future generations of research workers in all countries throughout the world, (quoted in Hawtin and Reeves 1998, p. 44) For center country agricultural biotech interests, the relevant question has become, Should the CGIAR function be limited to plant genetic material trusteeship? That is, with the technological advances that have made it possible to commodify knowledge in agriculture, consideration of appropriate comparative advantage delegates the function of genetic preservation to the quasi-public IARCs while increasingly assigning the applied R&D function to private capital. The center countries seek to enforce this division of labor via their disproportionate financial support of the entire research infrastructure. U.S. Agency for International Development (USAID) spokespersons articulate the changing character of the CGIAR system's role in agricultural research in the following terms: Research efforts on crop and livestock breeding, agricultural systems, germplasm preservation, and agricultural policies have been at the foundation of the IARCs* activities and remain an important component for the
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
189
achievement of global food security; hoWever, recent achievements spawned by the biotechnology revolution in agriculture and recent treaty development, such as the CBD, are changing [institutional paradigms and thereby necessitating a critical review of the Centers' roles and comparative advantages with respect to genetic resources. (Chambers and Bertram 1998, p. 60) The same spokespersons set out how U.S|. policy can be expected to influence this change and its significance for trie nation's corporate constituents. The third general point we would likelto make is that from an investment perspective, the USA continues to provide substantial support to the CGIAR with this year's commitment reaching $26 million. And among all donors, the USA still ranks third behind Japan and the World Bank despite a recent history of reduced funding. From a technical leadership perspective, the USA still maintains a significant role among donors to the CGIAR—a role that may likely expand given U.S. experience with a number of ancillary issues related to biotechnology, bioprospecting, biosafety, and IPR. Fourth, the position takes on added significance given the past and continuing contributions of the IARCs in USAID's development agenda, especially when that agenda is considered in relation to U.S. economic competitiveness in an increasingly globalized trade environment and in relation to U.S. diplomatic and security interests, (p. 61) In specifying the specific official U.S. recommendations for reform of the IARCs, USAID urges open access for twenty-five globally important food and forage crops in both national and international collections. At the same time, its support for sharing the benefits that result from the applied R&D on these genetic "raw materials" is far more muted: With regard to Benefit Sharing, the USA feels strongly that maintaining access represents an obvious benefit for less developed nations, given that it contributes to a continued strong research base in the USA and other advanced nations that provides both direct and indirect benefits to other nations in the form of improved varieties and applications, many of which have a broad spectrum of use across many crops and geological zones. Even in the current era, where privatization of agricultural varieties and knowledge is prevalent, the case can be made that the inventions that result from this privatized knowledge base ultimately lead to a greater public good and that, in itself, is an implicit type of compensation. Given the substantial U.S. contribution to the CGIAR system, the USA can logically argue that maintenance of an unrestricted free release policy within the system also represents an important form of Benefit Sharing, (p. 62, emphasis added)
190
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
These statements made by USAID officials are worth quoting at length insofar as they reflect the official U.S. position regarding the global division of labor as it bears on agricultural research, innovation, and production in the wake of the second (biotechnical) green revolution. The schema that unfolds from this position has the peripheral nations acting as the repositories and caretakers of an ever diminishing global plant-related gene bank. The center countries are expected to have the right of unlimited access to this bank, for which they are required to pay no explicit access fee. On the basis of this access, center-based transnational corporations convert the preserved raw germplasm into new GMOs that possess a variety of characteristics from a use-value perspective. More to the point, however, these GMOs possess the desirable characteristic from capital's point of view of marketability; that is, they possess exchange value. The GMOs are instruments through which international capital expands its reach into lines of social production that heretofore had been foreclosed by the communal nature of knowledge. In May's terminology, biotechnology has enabled the conversion of passive knowledge into active knowledge and its encapsulation by corporations in the commodity form (2000, p. 20). The reduced levels of international funding provided by the center countries for the IARCS referred to in the above quotations reflect a restructuring of research responsibilities attendant on the new technologies that have transformed knowledge into its active, commodity form. As private capital takes on greater responsibility for applied research, the IARCs preservation and repository functions are seen as primary ones requiring less resources. This restructuring parallels a similar restructuring of the division of labor that occurs in other lines of technology wherein public and quasi-public agencies, including public universities, are allocated the tasks of basic research, while applied, proprietary research is left to corporations. Or, alternatively, when public and quasi-public agencies maintain a role in applied developmental work, they are encouraged to form partnerships with private capital under agreements that spell out in clear terms the disposition of joint results as privately appropriated intellectual property. Winners and Losers in the "New Green Revolution" Explicit in the above statements is the neoliberal myth that the operation of the capitalist market as the bearer of social welfare is sufficient to provide appropriate compensation to all actors and classes according to their particular role in the social division of labor. The center-based biotech TNCs will be rewarded with profits, while the direct producers (including indigenous farmers and peasants in the periphery as well as center and periphery workers)
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION 191
will benefit by the opportunity to purchase at market-determined prices the resultant commodities. No attention is paid here either to the actual market conditions under which the GMOs will be produced and marketed or to the distributional consequences. Neither are the impacts on or the implications for changes in patterns of social production accounted for. Little notice is taken, for example, of what the restructured global division of labor will mean for traditional agricultural practices and employment in the peripheral countries, nor of the traditional knowledge out of which comes the rich gene pool of plant varieties on which future fjiotech innovations depend. That there are reasons to doubt the generalized welfare gains to be enjoyed by the internationalization of capital in the agricultural biotech sector is evident from several economic studies on the industrial organizational impacts of the biotechnology revolution. Bijman (2001) points out that the firms that stand in the vanguard of the; new green revolution are in large measure the same ones that profited so heavily from the first GR—namely, the transnational chemical and seed companies that played so important a role in developing and marketing hybrid seeds. A major difference between the two periods of intense technological progress is that the more recent biotech revolution has seen equally intense mergers and acquisitions among and between firms in previously separate industries, so that today the largest ag chemical corporations are also the largest seed companies. Moreover, these same ag chemical and seed giants have sought greater economies of scale and scope via further mergers with new biotech firms, so that the resultant enterprises are able to control virtually every aspect of the production chain short of farm labor itself. Increasing concentration in the ag biotech industry suggests that the alleged welfare benefits of innovation may be neither as large as is conventionally suspected nor as equitably distributed. The ability of noncompetitive or imperfectly competitive firms to limit supply and exploit monopoly pricing power in the marketing of innovative inputs is critical in this regard. Moschini and Lapan (1997) specify theoretical models that demonstrate that the economic welfare effects of innovation depend on whether the innovation itself is "drastic" and whether the market for inputs pri6r to innovation is concentrated (non- or imperfectly competitive). A "drastic" innovation is one that is efficiency-enhancing enough to displace previously existing technologies, leaving the new innovator with sufficient market-pricing power to charge a correspondingly monopoly profit-maximizing price. Such drastic innovations in the ag biotech industry today are being developed by large corporations, such as Monsanto, that already possess considerable market power in the chemical and seed industries. The results described by Moschini and Lapan would then appear to follow:
192
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
This means that the conventional welfare measures that apply to publicly produced innovations will not be appropriate in these circumstances and in general will tend to overstate the true gross benefits attributable to the innovations. Although this is an important conclusion, it should be noted that the most dramatic implication of correctly accounting for the monopolistic behavior entailed by IPRs is not on the overall size of the benefits but on the distribution of the welfare gains from innovations. In particular, for innovations introduced by suppliers of agricultural inputs, we find that what is conventionally measured as benefits to consumers and agricultural producers could in fact be largely captured by the innovating firms, (p. 1241) We can see, then, that there is reason to doubt the beneficence of private exclusionary IPRs in agriculture from a static welfare perspective. There may also be even more compelling reasons to be concerned about their longerterm dynamic implications. Innovations that emanate from monopolistic firms may create a kind of path dependency for future innovations. Kloppenburg sets out this possibility very well in his description of the development of hybrid seed technology. Once the course had been set for the development of hybrid corn seed development, other possibilities, including the improvement of nonhybrid ("open pollinated") populations of corn, were rejected as impractical by comparison to the new technology. Likewise, it is easy to imagine that once considerable public and private resources have been committed to the recombinant genetic technology path in agriculture, alternative methods that may be preferred on biosafety, environmental, or social welfare grounds will be dismissed as technologically impractical by comparison. The important point made by Kloppenburg and others, however, is that the initial choice of technology path is likely to be dictated by political factors rather than by the inherent efficiency advantages of the chosen technology. Given the hegemonic position held by international capital in the global economy, the political choices as revealed in the TRIPS and other international agreements have given determinative direction to the technological path that privileges the accumulation of capital. These choices are those that bring knowledge into the circuit of capital. Counterhegemonic Response and Its Limits I have argued that the TRIPS agreement represents a partial attempt on the part of the hegemonic bloc to provide international capital with the ideological, juridical, and regulatory infrastructure required to expand the compass of its circulation and to bring into its orbit previously excluded spheres of social activity (production). Technology aids this process when it enables
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
193
the commodization of previous use valuqs and/or alters the social relations of production in a manner that separates direct producers from the means of production and renders them subservient to the rule of capital. At the beginning of the twentieth-first century, it is evident that knowledge has increasing potential as an instrument of capital. Research and development efforts are being increasingly directed to finding ways to render knowledge into capital and to place it in service to the nee<jls of its global expansion. This fact carries with it an associated tendency of making workers, peasants, and consumers more dependent on decisions thit are made in the interests of the pursuit of transnational capitalist profit even when these interests conflict with the needs for employment security, environmental sustainability, worker and consumer safety, fair wages and pricbs, and public health. It is not surprising to find, therefore, a globally organized challenge to these trends. While this challenge is not entirely defined along a rich country-poor country axis, it is certainly true that a disproportionate share of the resistance emanates from the periphery and semiperiphery, particularly where the questions of agricultural technology and its relationship to food sufficiency and hunger are most urgently encountered. Institutionalized
Counterhegemony
As we saw in the previous section, at an international level, a component of the counterhegemonic strategy on the part of some representatives of the poor countries is to press for the recognition of farmers' rights, or some sort of benefit-sharing arrangement, in exchange for unrestricted access to their plant germplasm reserves, as well as the recognition of IPRs in living organisms developed primarily in the rich, center countries. Such an agreement is at the heart of the 1983 International Undei taking on Plant Genetic Resources, the 1992 Convention on Biological Diversity, and the Leipzig Declaration of the mid-1990s. These agreements are notable for two similarities. The first is that they all maintain that they respect the concept of, and are consistent with, private, exclusionary property right > in living organisms. It is clear, in fact, that the agreements are qualified and constrained so as to be rhetorically consistent with the stipulations of the TRIPS agreement to which they are effectively and juridically subject. The secondary status the agreements possess relative to the TRIPS owes much to the fact that the TRIPS, unlike the other agreements, enjoys (1) international legal status and (2) an enforcement mechanism. Second, the United States, headquarters to many of the world's transnational corporations that seek unrestricted access to the world's germplasm reserves as well as the protection of IPRs in genetically modified organisms, stands opposed to the agreements. This opposition, as we have
194
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
seen, is rooted in a belief that the agreements, notwithstanding their claims of consistency with privately claimed IPRs, do not go far enough in providing protection to intellectual innovations in biotechnology. Benefit sharing is also rejected on the basis of its presumed impracticality and the inappropriateness of assigning the responsibility for determining the administration of such proposals to international bodies. Official opposition by the United States, spurred by the organized interests of international capital, can be expected to render the form and content of these qualifying agreements contested terrain for the foreseeable future. I will argue here that, in this struggle for ideological hegemony, international capital currently commands the high ground. The reason is that the would-be counterhegemonic agreements (the International Undertaking, the CBD, the Leipzig Declaration) have allowed the hegemonic bloc to define the terms of the discourse. They have, to borrow May's terminology, embraced the knowledge structure of the international capitalist hegemonic bloc. In so doing, they have conceded what properly must be resisted, the commodification of knowledge and its insertion into the circuit of capital. In other words, once it is admitted that knowledge is "ownable," the worldview of global capitalism is provided fundamental support. What is left after this is established are negotiations over the terms of trade between the center and the periphery. Given the disparities that exist between center and periphery countries regarding market characteristics, information asymmetries, and the typical leverage exercised by capital in its relation to labor characteristic of capitalist production, unequal exchange in knowledge-based commodities is virtually inevitable. Moreover, in embracing the concept of knowledge as commodity and productive capital, the agreements also embrace the entire logic of capitalist accumulation and its attendant neoliberal ideology. Considered from this vantage point, the would-be counterhegemonic resistance must be considered a fundamental victory for international capital that reaches well beyond the narrower consideration of "who owns knowledge." It represents rather a solidification of the neoliberal myth of global market forces as guarantor of a socially optimal allocation of resources, maximizer of productive efficiency, promoter of growth, and so on. It helps to narrow the field of technically and socially imaginable alternatives that might impinge on the freedom of international capital. Ultimately, then, this form of would-be counterhegemonic resistance must be considered "counter-counterhegemonic." The Coase Theorem and the (De)construction of Hegemony The limitations of the Convention on Biological Diversity are made clear in a recent article by Boisvert and Caron (2002). These authors note that the
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
195
CBD has carried out a radical break with previous international approaches to the issue of conserving biological diversity by replacing an emphasis on direct institutional regulation with a variant of the Coase theorem. As noted in Chapter 2, the Coase theorem, named after economist Ronald Coase, argues that the problem of optimal resource conservation necessitates clearly defined property rights in the relevant Resources. If resources are treated as public goods available to all, there exists no particular agent charged with either their efficient use or their long-run optimal use. The likely result is their dissipation through overuse or by neglect of their husbandry. By the assignment of definite, exclusive property rights, on the other hand, the potential for the profitable exploitation of the resources creates the conditions for the development of markets wherein they can be traded and thus allocated to their highest-valued uses. Applied to living organisms, this theorem suggests the abandonment of the "common heritage of mankind" view of raw plant germplasm in favor of assigning property rights in such resources to farmers and indigenous groups who have traditionally developed and cultivated them from wild landraces. Ownership of the remaining landraces themselves would be assigned to public or quasi-public agencies in the countries where they are maintained in situ. As Boisvert and Caron point out, the very notion of plant germplasm as an exploitable resource adopted by the CBD represents a sea change in interpretation. Whereas former approaches of environmental law strove toward preservation and aimed at preventing exploitation, the Convention on Biological Diversity combines conservation with the use of biological resources for commercial purposes. Exploitation is not only restored to favor and no longer considered a threat to the environment, it is the very heart of the institutional device designed by the Convention. (2002, p. 152) Ideological embrace of the Coase theorem requires what the authors term the "apology of private property." By this they mean the belief that privately held property rights are the necessary and sufficient condition for the socially efficient use of scarce resources. Common property institutions are considered unable to avoid the "tragedy of the commons" identified by Hardin (1968) and briefly described above. Boisvert and Caron usefully point out the fallacies in this position, however. First, it is a false comparison to suggest that the only alternatives to resource allocation involve the unrestricted access implied by free common goods and the restricted access provided by exclusionary private property rights. This dichotomy ignores the possibilities of limited access inherent in control over common resources by a public authority. The neoclassical economic rejoinder to this possibility is to argue
196
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
that governments possess neither sufficient incentives nor information to allocate resources to their socially optimal uses. This is the familiar "government failure" argument. It is apparent, however, that market failure is a larger threat to biodiversity than government failure. The threats of genetic erosion and genetic uniformity that the world currently faces follow, after all, not from excessive public control of genetic resources, but rather from their private exploitation for profit. Moreover, while it is undoubtedly true that public stewardship of genetic raw materials would result in a pattern for their social use different from that which would prevail under their privatization, there can be no presumption that the latter is socially superior to the former. A second fallacy identified by Boisvert and Caron relates to the proper interpretation of Coase's 1960 article. The widespread misinterpretation known as the "Coase theorem" neglects two important qualifying conditions identified by the author. The first is that private market allocation of scarce resources is efficient in the absence of transactions costs. The second is that property rights can be unambiguously defined. These qualifying characteristics are frequently violated in markets that trade traditionally recognized commodities—that is, those involving physical or material attributes that imply exclusivity or rivalry in use. When applied to commodified knowledge derived from traditional production methods in poor countries, the severe limitations of the theorem should be obvious. Put plainly, what is the likelihood that well-informed, equitable contracts embodying the true social value of genetic exchange-values will be struck between center country-based, biotech TNCs and their poor country negotiating counterparts? Boisvert and Caron suggest an answer:
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
197
Neither can it be seriously argued, as per the requirements made by Coase himself, that property rights in genetic resources can be unambiguously assigned. Those who have developed and maintained the coveted materials are in fact difficult or impossible to identify. This is, in fact, one of the principle arguments made by center-based opponents of the benefit-sharing provisions of the CBD. If it is rejoined that while individual cultivators may not be identifiable, it may be possible to compensate the communities from which the resources are drawn, the problem of identification is merely displaced to a broader and more general level. Genetic material is developed by overlapping communities over many generations. In addition, this development is never merely an economic matter: it involves;an indissoluble cultural element that defies pecuniary expression. Therefore', the concept of bioprospecting cannot pretend to legitimacy in communities where contract relationships run counter to traditional understandings of plant cultivation. Brush (1999) describes the inherent contradictions in the following terms: [T]he contract mode and its ensuing relationships for obtaining biological resources are incongruous with the nature of indigenous knowledge and management of biological resources. These resources and their attendant knowledge are products of "bio-coopeiation," and their collective management is intimately connected to the ecology of subsistence agriculture and crop evolution, (p. 537)
There is no such thing as a global standard agreement in the Convention [on Biological Diversity] that could be used as a blueprint when drafting such contracts. The Convention promotes bilateral negotiations between States, or at least public institutions, on the one hand and private bilateral organizations on the other hand, to define the terms of the contracts of access to and exploitation of biological resources. Such agreements, the terms of which are often kept secret, are subject to no external arbitration. The benefit-sharing measures they provide for strongly depend on the respective powers and negotiating skills of the parties. <2002, p. 156)
The expansion of the "contract mode" is part of the larger project of the transnational capitalist hegemonic bloc to extend its control over larger areas of the globe. Consensual hegemony is apparent in the CBD's embrace of such notions of "biopiracy" and "bioprospecting" wherein the latter is considered a corrective to the former. "Biopiracy" of genetic resources presupposes that such resources are "owned" by! some interests who have been illegally deprived of them (Brush 1999). "Bioprospecting" suggests that such resources represent potential exchange values and are recognized and valued as such by local communities. Attendant upon the acceptance of these concepts, however, is the additional acceptance! of an essentially capitalist epistemology with profound implications for the transformation of noncapitalist forms of social production. Brush writes:
Even if we overlook the clear asymmetries in information and negotiating skills of the contracting parties, we still must confront the fact of market power possessed by the large, imperfectly competitive biotech corporations. One can easily imagine a company like Monsanto standing in an essentially monopsony buyer's position relative to the possessors of some potentially profitable species of plant or animal genetic resource.
The concept of bioprospecting emerged in a period that saw international development and lending agencies embrace the neoliberal politics of privatization, politics that could also be recast as a means to empower Third World states and their local communities Bioprospecting is one of the more fully developed proposals to transform common heritage into a stream of compensation. However, this mecha-
198
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
nism involves appropriation from the public domain. Bioprospecting contracts for crop genetic resources change the relationship not only between farmers and collectors but also among farmers and farming communities. As an incursion into the public domain, bioprospecting reveals pitfalls similar to other incursions, for instance in closing the agrarian commons and the penetration of capital into peasant societies, (pp. 538-539) The penetration of global capital into peasant societies and poor country agriculture in general has important potential consequences both for those who seek their livelihoods from the land and for those who seek to fulfill their "assigned task" of maintaining genetic plant diversity. As noted, it involves the replacement of social production relationships based on the production of use values by those based on the production of exchange values. This may occur when an essentially cooperative system is replaced by a competitive one, thus hindering or making obsolete the processes of knowledge sharing and free exchange that have traditionally served to develop and maintain stocks of plant germplasm. As Brush points out, there is a certain indissolubility between agriculture and culture considered more widely. Bioprospecting and contractual control over genetic resources presuppose a far more individualistic culture than that found in areas of high genetic diversity. The development and preservation of adequate diversity may require instead a communal culture that prioritizes the public domain over the private. The FAO as a Site of Resistance The above analysis should suggest, then, the preferability of an alternative counterhegemonic resistance strategy, one that involves the creation of public offsets to the power of international capital to define the discourse and design the operative international regulatory superstructure. The specific international institutions within which to confront the power of capital may already exist in partial and imperfect form. The Food and Agricultural Organization, for example, has operated, in part, as a forum to resist the domination by international capital of what may be properly defined as "mankind's common heritage" where plant genetic resources are concerned. In the 1983 International Undertaking on Plant Genetic Resources discussed earlier, Article 2 defines this common heritage to include "special genetic stocks" (including elite and current breeders' lines and mutants). This ensures that commercially developed cultivars are included in the set of plant germplasm to which all nations are to have unrestricted access—no less so than the peasant-produced varieties (Kloppenburg 1988, p. 173). Also, as Kloppenburg usefully points out, Article 7 of the IU specifies that base collections in gene banks will be maintained by a net-
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
199
work of international centers, under the auspices of the FAO, that will provide for unrestricted exchange of plant geneticl resources. Private capitalist interests, and the state machinery that is used to advance those interests, are opposed to this alternative insofar as it involves the surrender of control over access to genetic resources to an international agency. The FAO is a United Nations organization wherein, at least in principle, decisions are made on the basis of one-nation, one-vote. Policy making for the organization, then, may be dominated by a majority composed of periphery and semiperiphery countries that believe their best interests are served by the elimination of restrictions on access to all types of genetic resources, including those that are claimed to represent proprietary applied knowledge. There are reasons, as suggested above,! however, to believe that the FAO represents only a partial and imperfect instrument of counterhegemonic resistance to the capacities of international capital to shape the discourse and substantive content of biotechnical development. The first is that the organization depends heavily on the center countries for its finance. This is a limitation it shares with all United Nations organizations. The power of the purse is a strong weapon to wield in determining; the agendas of the FAO and similar international organizations. This power has also shown an ability to constrain the effectiveness of initiatives such as the IU. Largely due to objections by the center countries, most prominently he United States, the IU is limited to voluntary compliance by its signatories and no real consequences result when nations ignore it altogether. Second the FAO allows standing only to national governments and their representatives. This suggests that the problem of counterhegemonic resistance is once again a matter of its ability to capture or otherwise imprint state policy making at the national level. Poor countries are themselves, of course, characterized by important class divisions and fragments. Insofar as the dominant voices from within the poor countries are aligned with international (transnational) capital, state policy in these countries may be as committed to a course of defining and strengthening the global IPR regime as that typica of the center countries. That is to say, there can be no necessary presumption that the-struggle over "who owns knowledge" is a strictly North-South affaijr. Not only are the class interests of southern nations ambiguous, but the same can be said of northern nations. The biotech revolution has definite implications for agricultural workers and consumers in the center developed nations. Small farmers, for example, find themselves in the position of choosing production methods dictated by the emerging biotechnology in order to remain competitive. This need extends well beyond merely choosing to use the newer hybrid, or otherwise genetically modified, seeds. It includes as well the adoption of an entire package of capital- and chemical-intensive
200
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
complementary inputs. The use of these inputs, in turn, often dictates the timing and intensity of the production process so that little discretion is left to the individual farmer, who increasingly becomes a provider of raw, unskilled labor power almost indistinguishable from his urban counterpart. In other words, the proletarianization of the rural labor force that occurs under the pressure of biotechnical change in the periphery also occurs in the center, albeit on a reduced <. cale in the latter, given the much smaller numbers of direct producers involved. The globalization of the regulatory mechanisms of the state required for capitalist hegemony suggests that an effective response requires a counterhegemonic effort that is also globally organized. In the area of agriculture, this strategy should include the attempt to capture control of existing institutions, such as the FAO and the various international agricultural research institutions. These agencies could then develop agricultural technologies that are safe for producers and consumers, recognize the imperative to maintain a healthy and diverse plant gene pool, and support the widespread adoption of technologies and practices without regard to the capitalist potential for surplus extraction and accumulation. What is needed, in other words, is a new green revolution that is motivated by the objective of eliminating hunger and malnutrition in the world and is unmediated by the capitalist imperative. The Farm Gate as a Site of Resistance While the large bulk of biotech crops are grown in North America, their introduction into the poorer countries is becoming an issue of growing contentiousness, pitting growers against one another and growers against consumer and environmental advocates. It is perhaps predictable that Argentina is first among the semiperipheral countries to have embraced genetically modified (GM) crops in a significant fashion. Its temperate agricultural zone growing conditions make transfer of these crops a logical choice for U.S.based transnational corporations such as Monsanto. The fact that Argentina's agriculture suffered along with the rest of the country from economic depression for most of the 1990s makes its farmers especially receptive to innovations that hold out the promise of increased yields while driving down production costs. Argentina is also highly dependent on its agriculture to generate foreign exchange in order to finance imports as well as to service its lingering external debt ("Argentine Farms: Unhappy" 1994). Between 1996 and 2002, then, the area under transgenic crops increased from around 100,000 hectares to well over 13 million hectares.12 The impact of GM crops has hardly been limited to Argentina, however.
AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY REVOLUTION
201
Argentina's northern neighbor, Brazil, is the world's second largest soybean producer after the United States. Unlike Argentina, however, Brazil has not approved the use of GM crops, largely out of fear that they will be shut out of the European markets, which have prohibited their introduction. The Europeans, in fact, require labeling of all products containing GM ingredients and look to Brazil as their prime supplier of rion-GM soybeans and other foods that are "GM-free."13 The contradictions are compounded by the fact that many Brazilian growers, particularly the largest ones, see themselves placed at a cost disadvantage and have begun planting moc ified seed smuggled in from Argentina. The potential for transgenic contamination, however, is not limited to those farmers who knowingly use the modified seed. GM-free fields can be pollinated by modified beans growing in neighboring fields or even at some distance away, resulting in the unknowing production of a GM crop. The result is that Brazilian marketers cannot offer any real guarantees that their product is pure of transgenic contamination (Stecklow and Moffett 1999). Methods exist, however, to detect the presence of the modified gene within a particular crop, and the Brazilian government undertakes field inspections. Where it has detected transgenic beans it has seized and destroyed the plants. Conflicts and contradictions at the level of the farm gate are reflected at the level of the state. Brazil's central government has established legal and institutional mechanisms to both promote and control agricultural biotechnical R&D (Jepson 2002). These mechanisms have worked both in concert and in competition with transnational capitalist interests, such as Monsanto and Novartis, to open Brazilian agriculture to the introduction of GMOs. At the same time, however, environmentalists and growers opposed to their introduction have used the courts and local governments to resist the commercialization of the new crops. International org inizations such as Greenpeace and the British Consumers' Association have also actively participated in the effort to prevent dissemination of the technology by contributing field detection processes and legal resources. The result, according to Jepson, is a rescaling of the politics of transgenic technology into "multi-scalar political configurations, strategies and discourses," the outcome of which is far from determined by the "overwhelming" power of international capital.14 It is apparent from this South Americar example that the battle over intellectual property rights is hardly a simple case of North-South conflict. It also demonstrates that struggles over IPR issues may have strong intranational as well as international dimensions. Successful counterhegemony, it would seem then, requires effective organization and communication across a variety of levels to unite the various class fractions and interest groups that seek to redefine the dominant knowledge structure. In the concluding chapter, I will comment further on the particular challenges this task presents.
202
Appendix :
Genetically Engineered Crops Allowed on the U.S. Market
Product Canola Canola Canola
Institution (s) Bayer Monsanto Monsanto
Engineered traits(s) Sources of new genes Resist glufosinate herbicide to control weeds Bacteria, virus Resist glufosinate to control weeds Arabidopsis, • bacteria.virus Altered oil for soap and food products Calif bay, turnip rape, bacteria,
Canola
Bayer
Chicory
Bejo Zaden
Male sterile to facilitate hybridization. Resist glufosinate Male sterile to facilitate hybridization
^JctUJUL'illUy
Corn
Bayer
Corn Corn
Bayer Bayer
Corn Corn
Corn Corn Corn Corn
Dow/Mycogen Dow/Mycogen Dupont/Pioneer DuponVPioneer Monsanto/ DeKalb Monsanto/ DeKalb Monsanto, Monsanto Monsanto Syngenta
Corn
Syngenta
Corn (pop) Corn (sweet)
Syngenta
Corn Corn Corn
Syngenta
Cotton
Monsanto/ Bayer
Cotton
Monsanto/ Bayer Monsanto Monsanto University of Saskatchewan Cornell University and University of Hawaii Monsanto
Cotton Cotton Flax Papaya Potato Potato Potato Soybean Soybean Soybean Squash Squash Sugarbeet Sugarbeet Tomato (cherry) Tomato Tomato Tomato Tomato
Resist glufosinate to control weeds. Male sterile to facilitate hybridization Resist glufosinate to control weeds Resist glufosinate. B.t. toxin to control insect pests B.t. toxin to control European corn borer Resist glufosinate. B.t. toxin. (Lepidopteran) Male sterile to facilitate hybridization B.t. toxin to control pests (European corn borer) Resist glufosinate B.t. toxin to control European corn borer Resist glyphosate. B.t. toxin. Resist glyphosate B.t. toxin to resist insect pests (European corn borer) B.t. toxin to resist insect pests (European corn borer) B.t. toxin to resist insect pests (European corn borer) B.t. toxin to resist insect pests (European corn borer)
Name/date LibertyLink 2000 Roundup Ready 1999 Laurical 1995
virus Bacteria
Seedlink 2000
Bacteria
SeedLink 1997
Bacteria, virus
SeedLink (date unknown)
Bacteria, virus Bacteria, virus Bacteria, virus Corn, bacteria, virus
LibertyLink (date unknown) StarLink 1998 (approved for animal feed only) NatureGard 1995 Herculex I 2001
Potato, corn, bacteria,, virus Bacteria
Name unknown 1998 B.t.-Xtra1997
Bacteria, virus
Name date unknown
Bacteria, virus Arabidopsis, bacteria, virus Arabidopsis, bacteria, virus Bacteria
YieldGard 1996 Name unknown 1998 Roundup Ready 1998 B.t. 11 1996
Corn, bacteria, virus
Knock Out 1995
Corn, bacteria, virus
Knock Out 1998
Bacteria
B.t.11 1998
Resist bromoxynil herbicide. B.t. toxin to control pests (bollworms and tobacco budworms) Resist bromoxynil herbicide
Bacteria
Name unknown, 1998
Bacteria, virus
BXN Cotton 1995
B.t. toxin to control pests Resist glyphosate Resist sulfonylurea herbicide to grow in soils with herbicide residues Resist papaya ringspot virus
Bacteria Arabidopsis, bacteria, virus Arabidopsis, bacteria
Bollgard 1995 Roundup Ready 1996 CDCTriffid 1999
Bacteria, virus
Sunup, Rainbow 1997
Bacteria
NewLeaf 1995
Bacteria, virus
NewLeafY1999
Bacteria, virus Bacteria, virus Soybean, bean, bacteria, virus
NewLeaf Plus 1998 Name unknown 1998 Name unknown 1997
Petunia, soybean, bacteria, virus Bacteria, virus
Roundup Ready 1995 Freedom II 1995
Bacteria, virus
Name unknown 1997
Bacteria, virus Bacteria, virus
Name unknown 2000 Name unknown 1999
Bacteria
Name unknown 1996
Tomato bacteria
Endless Summer 1995
Tomato, bacteria virus
FlavrSavr 1994
Bacteria
Name unknown, 1995
Tomato, bacteria, virus
Name unknown, 1995
B.t. toxin to control insect pests (Colorado potato beetle) B.t. toxin to control pests. Monsanto Resist potato virus Y Monsanto B.t. toxin. Resist potato leafroll virus Bayer Resist glufosinate Dupont Altered oil to increase stability, reduce polyunsaturated fatty acids Monsanto Resist glyphosate Seminis Resist watermelon mosaic and zucchini vegetable seed yellow mosaic viruses Seminis Resist watermelon mosaic 2, zucchini vegetable seed yellow mosaic, cucumber mosaic viruses Bayer Resist glufosinate Monsanto and Resist glyphosate Syngenta Agritope Altered ripening to enhance fresh market value DNA Plant Altered ripening to enhance fresh Technology market value Monsanto and Altered ripening to enhance fresh Calgene market value Monsanto Altered ripening to enhance fresh market value Thicker skin and altered pectin to Zeneca enhance processing value
Source: Adapted from Union of Concerned Scientists, www.ucsusa.org/food and_environment/biotechnology/page.cfm?paeeID=337.
COUNTERHEGEMONY AND THE FUTURE OF TRIPS 205
8 Counterhegemony and the Future of TRIPS
The Future of TRIPS As emphasized earlier, the trade-related aspects of intellectual property rights (TRIPS) agreement is not written in stone. Its effectiveness as part of the global regulatory system will greatly depend on its application, interpretation, and enforcement in particular cases. The various writers reviewed in Chapter i provide a range of views on the likely success of the agreement to speed the development process in the poor countries. Maskus (2000), for example, takes the position that the long-term effectiveness of TRIPS to promote such benefits as foreign direct investment, technology transfer, and economic growth will depend on the ability and willingness of the poor countries to enact a rather substantial menu of liberal economic reform measures. They will also need, he argues, to develop the requisite juridical and administrative institutions necessary to enforce the agreement. Curiously, the lack of these prerequisites does not cause Maskus to call into question the wisdom of accession to the agreement by the poorer countries even in the face of a paucity of theoretical and empirical evidence that it will provide the sought-after benefits. Duncan Matthews is less optimistic about the prospects for TRIPS. His doubts, however, are not motivated by concerns for the imagined development-inducing benefits of the agreement. Rather he believes that the coalitional stability among the developed countries that enabled the establishment of the agreement as a working part of the World Trade Organization (WTO) may be lacking when it comes to its enforcement. Early cases involving disputes settlements on matters related to intellectural property rights (IPRs), he notes, have been dominated by disagreements between developed country interests (2000, pp. 129-130). Susan Sell (1998) also registers some doubts about the agreement's effectiveness tied to the willingness and ability of poor countries to engage in the kind of "unit-level learning" necessary to encourage acceptance of its specific articles and provisions. She contrasts the difficulty of winning acceptance for the TRIPS with the willingness of the poor countries to adopt the 204
competitiveness policies associated with the Code of Conduct for the Control of Restrictive Business Practices. Interestingly, she attributes the relative success of the latter to the influence of ("Chicago school" economics, which was so influential, especially in Latin America, in the 1970s and 1980s. Not considered by Sell, however, is the fact; that Chicago economics also places a large premium on the defense of property rights and sees these as part of the now dominant neoliberal vision. Doubtless, economists such as Coase would include intellectual property rights among those requiring clear definition in order to promote the efficient operation of markets. Perhaps the real difference between the cases considered by Sell has more to do with the fact that IPRs provide more opportunities for class-based resistance than does antitrust policy. This possibility points up the wbakness of Sell's "interpretivist neoliberal" approach, which largely eschews class analysis. How the TRIPS agreement continues to evolve over time will be a matter of the relative abilities of contending classes and class fractions to exert pressure on state agencies and on public opinion. The agreement, properly understood, is an evolving instrument of state power as well as an arena within which international classes struggle to exert material and ideological control (hegemony). The writers who seem to best appreciate the class character of the TRIPS, May and Boyle, both speak to the possibilities for counterhegemonic resistance to the agreement. May (2000), who is primarily concerned to examine the justificatory arguments that support the intellectual property (IP) regime, claims that these approaches fail to provide adequate justification. His own argument leads him to advocate a reform project by which knowledge producers, rather than knowledge owners, would be recognized and rewarded. In a similar vein, Boyle (1996) urges the abandonment of the "author-centered" approach to IPRs in favor of one that operates [in the interests of both sources and audiences. In general, he stresses the importance of providing greater protection for the public domain from which useful innovations must draw essential inspiration and material inputs. It is significant that neither May nor Boyle ultimately calls into question the essential legitimacy of privately held IPRs. May seems finally to accept what amounts to a kind of pragmatic, or economic, justification for IPRs based on the widening of the notion of social utility in a manner that allows for the construction of a public domain of knowledge. As a practical matter, this might involve empowering international organizations—for example, the World Health Organization (WHO) and the Food and Agricultural Organization (FAO)—to gain control over key patents and copyrights that they would exercise in the interests of wide public accessibility. Alternatively, it might require, the creation of "hybrid laws" that provide rewards and recognition to knowledge creators while limiting the kind of alienability of inno-
206
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
vations that has often been the basis of their monopoly exploitation of markets. In such a manner, May sees potential for the rebalancing of rights of individuals versus corporations. Boyle likewise asserts that preserving the public domain does not always mean getting rid of property rights, but rather expanding the concept in ways that introduce needed flexibility (1996, pp. 168-169). He is especially interested in exploring a variety of sui generis systems for IP protection that would address a corresponding variety of market situations. Apparently, Boyle is no more willing than May to take seriously the possibility that the market should not be the arbiter of information allocation. For these authors, acceptance of the central role of the market appears as a grudging acceptance of the limits to counterhegemony in the neoliberal global environment. I believe that both May and Boyle offer some insights for the reform of the global IPR regime. Especially useful are their respective arguments that demonstrate the general inappropriateness of the TRIPS agreement especially as it applies to the development aspirations of the poor countries. May's suggestion that reforms that empower international organizations as key agents in promoting the widest possible dissemination of knowledge and its applications is well taken, though, as I have argued in chapters 6 and 7, there are important limitations on these institutions as they are currently embedded in the global capitalist regulatory structure. Moreover, in the absence of a challenge to the concept of knowledge as a commodity, it is difficult to see how the world's poor majorities, who are defined precisely by their lack of market power, can expect to realize substantial progress. A challenge to the concept of knowledge as commodity is, of course, simultaneously a direct challenge to the knowledge structure that underlies the functioning of the global capitalist system. Moreover, as Boyle appropriately notes, carving out space for a reformulation of our understanding of the public nature of knowledge will require greater attention to coalitional politics (p. 168). It is to the possibility for global coalitional political effort that I wish to dedicate the final sections of this book. The Emerging Global State and Counter-hegemonic Challenges The TRIPS agreement has been described here as a particular agency of an emerging global state, the fundamental function of which is to secure IPRs on behalf of the owners of knowledge-based commodities and capital. The state was described in Chapter 4 as both an instrument of hegemonic control used by the dominant fractions of the IPRs and as an arena within which classes contend in order to advance their interests. These functions are obviously related in an important way, since, insofar as a
COUNTERHEGEMONY AND THE FUTURE OF TRIPS 207
class, or class fraction, successfully competes to imprint and shape the form and content of the state and its agencies, it also advances its more general hegemonic control of the structure of the world system. In this way, state apparatuses then more closely assume the character of hegemonic instruments. There can be no presumption, however, that the state and its particular agencies are ever necessarily under the complete domination of a particular class or class fraction. No such determinism can be attached to the historical process of class struggle. At the present historical juncture, it is apparent that transnational capital occupies a hegemonic position relative to many of the most powerful global state regulatory apparatuses. Institutions such as the International Monetary Fund (IMF), World Bank, and WTO operate to secure the conditions for capital's expanded international reproduction. Other global institutions, especially those associated with the United Nations, are less perfectly under the control of international capital. In either case, coordinated efforts to challenge this domination by a well-organized counterhegemonic resistance may prove effective in altering particular outcomes to the benefit of the world's marginalized majorities. We saw in Chapter 6 that global publ c pressure was capable of forcing the large transnational pharmaceutical companies into altering their pricing policies for HIV/AIDS drugs to enable larger numbers of the world's poor access to the lifesaving treatments. While this represents a victory for these potential victims, however, it is a very United kind of victory for those who seek more substantive changes in the manner in which new technologies are developed to address human problems. It does nothing, for example, to alter the knowledge structure that constructs new technologies as potential exchange values to meet an effective market demand. Neither does it in any way alter the social relations of producti on of knowledge-based commodities that place priority of productive purpose on the generation of profit. The limited concessions made by the drug companies are more accurately seen as a strategic retreat in the face of widely publicized criticism of their pricing practices. These concessions have public Relations benefits without requiring sacrifice of the basic underlying moral or juridical claims inherent in exclusionary IPRs. These claims, therefore, liye another day to operate in other markets. This strategic retreat, then, can be seen as an effective exercise of Gramscian (consensual) hegemony (chapter 5). Similarly, the proposals that seek to provide the cultivators of plant genetic resources in poor countries with compensation in exchange for the exclusionary breeders'rightsfueling the biotech revolution offer a very limited vision of counterhegemonic resistance: In fact, they are not counterhegemonic at all inasmuch as they represent a complete "buy-in" to the dominant knowl-
208
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
edge structure, which excludes from discussion any alternative to assignable individual property rights to knowledge-based innovations. Such compensation schemes seek to redistribute rents rather than to challenge prevailing exploitative social relations of production. A truly counterhegemonic research and development program would devote itself to the development of productive innovations that would enable increases in productivity in lines of production important to the direct use of local, indigenous communities. Moreover, the resultant innovation would be freely shared, be safe to use by cultivators, and would not represent a threat to environmental integrity. The political challenge to counterhegemonic efforts is to mobilize politically in order to gain control over sufficient resources to finance such alternative technologies. The redirection of international agencies such as the FAO and WHO is made difficult by the methods by which they are currently financed, involving as they do voluntary contributions from member national governments. It has been proposed from time to time that global taxes be imposed whose revenues could be used to fund necessary programs of international reach. For example, a carbon tax on carbon-based fuel usage would have the twin, though offsetting, benefits of providing a disincentive to users of these resources, thus helping to reduce the rate of environmental degradation, while generating substantial revenues. Estimates of the potential redistributi ve impact of a carbon tax measure in the hundreds of billions of dollars (Paul and Wahlberg 2002; Cooper 1998). While some of these funds would logically be used to develop sustainable energy alternatives, there is no reason why a portion could not also be used to fund the development of other technologies, including those associated with health and nutrition, that serve pressing human needs in the poor nations. Another sort of global tax is a levy on short-term international capital and currency movements. Such a tax was originally suggested in 1972 by economist James Tobin and has hence been referred to as a "Tobin tax." It was proposed by Tobin (1974) as a means of reducing destabilizing flows of speculative capital, promoting long-term investment, and providing local monetary authorities with greater autonomy in the conduct of their policies. Like the carbon tax, the Tobin tax has dual, offsetting objectives if viewed in terms of its revenue and redistributive potential.1 Paul and Wahlberg (2002) estimate, however, that a 0.2 percent tax on international currency transactions that reduces such transactions by 50 percent would still generate around $300 billion per year. The redistribution potential of these funds would depend largely on what portion of them is transferred from the points of their collection (mostly the center countries) to the agencies and countries (mostly in the periphery) with the greatest need of resources to develop technologies that service basic needs.
COUNTERHEGEMONY AND THE FUTURE OF TRIPS
209
Despite the economic and environmental rationality of carbon and currency transactions taxes, the political pressures lined up against their widespread adoption are formidable. Resistance to global taxation of any sort is highly likely to come from the affected industries. The world financial industry, almost entirely dominated by center country-based oligopolies, can be expected to strongly oppose proposals' that increase the cost of their operations and reduce the freedom of movement of capital. Appeal to the market stabilizing logic of the proposal is unlikely to win much support among these interests since a considerable amount of their profit is generated precisely by their ability to leverage market instability. Even if a Tobin tax were established, more general resistance from;center countries would be met by the additional proposal that its proceeds, or any substantial portion thereof, be transferred either to the poor countries or to international agencies like the WHO, FAO, or United Nations Development Programme that are likely to work in their favor. Similarly, in the case of the carbon tax, resistance would be met in the form of a well-organized, carbon fuel-based, energy-industrial complex. This is a truly transnational industrial web that includes energy producers, refiners, and distributors, as well as the myriad parts of the global automotive industry, among others. Resistance to a tax in tiis case would not be confined to center country capitalist interests but undoubtedly would include those that are based in oil- producing and -exporti lg peripheral and semiperipheral nations as well. Insofar then as nation-state governments hemsel ves are dominated by global capitalist interests, the difficulties of creating and financing transnational regulatory agencies that are autonomous of these same interests are magnified. There would seem to be, therefore, a certain indissoluble relationship between effective transnational political organization and national political organization. The question is how to create effective linkages among and between the various civil society groups that have an in :erest in alternatives to the international IPR regime as a means of creating innovations that service vital human needs independent of the commodity-capital nexus. A possible answer involves the organizational capacities and technical abilities of international nongovernmentaljorganizations (NGOs). Organizations like the Union of Concerned Scientists, Greenpeace, and Medecins Sans Frontieres (MSF, Doctors Without Borders) combine technical alternatives with significant political leverage. The limitations faced by progressive NGOs, however, are very similar to those constraining those international organizations that attempt to operate in the interest of the world's marginalized majorities. That is, the organizations are largely beholden to governments and/ or well-endowed corporations for funding. Even when they can obtain funds
210
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
from private individuals or endowments, they may face constraints on the use of funds or on their ability to advance a social or political agenda. The rapid proliferation of NGOs beginning in the 1980s in fact has been interpreted by some (Klees 1998; Edwards and Hulme 1996) as .responding to and serving the neoliberal agenda. In effect, the growth in NGOs is the result of the retreat of the state in its social welfare function. NGOs have moved into the void to provide a variety of social services. In many cases, they have served a subcontracting function relative to the state and must engage in a fiercely competitive environment to order to attract a limited (and reduced) amount of available resources. In such an environment, it is often impossible to wage a meaningful counterhegemonic political campaign and still attract sufficient funding to provide necessary social services to needy constituencies, or to even survive. The point here is not to minimize or denigrate the authentically progressive work done by some NGOs notwithstanding this problem, but merely to call attention to their inherent limitations. Counterhegemony and Politics The above discussion of the limited prospects for reform of institutions under global capitalism is not intended to suggest that counterhegemonic challenges are futile. In fact, as stated earlier, I believe that ongoing efforts to influence the form and content of policies of the various international agencies assigned to regulate the global economic system are worthwhile and an essential part of any counterhegemonic program. I also believe that the work of progressive NGOs to provide alternative models and organization is equally essential to any attempt to reshape the knowledge structure that defines our human potential and goals. What I wish to emphasize by way of conclusion to this discussion, however, is the continuing, fundamental importance of progressive, organized, political effort to capture and shape political institutions, including the state, at all levels. Resolution of the problems created by the private appropriation and exploitation of knowledge will not be achieved in piecemeal fashion. It will require, more likely, a broadly coordinated effort involving workers, consumers, environmentalists, intellectuals, and progressive activists of all stripes who face the threat of, and wish to oppose, the new knowledge enclosure as one aspect of the capital-commodity nexus. The internationalization of capital implies the internationalization of the social relations of production. This in turn implies that workers around the world, for example, increasingly face similar challenges in advancing their social, material, and political interests. I do not wish to imply here that the conditions of struggle faced by workers are the same everywhere. Clearly, this is not true. It is increasingly clear, however, that the ability of workers
COUNTERHEGEMONY:AND THE FUTURE OF TRIPS 211
and their organizations to advance their interests in one part of the global capitalist system depends on the strength yf workers in other parts of the system. Weakness in labor organizations in one country undermines the strength of similar organizations in other countries. Recognition of this international interdependency has caused labor organizations to increase their efforts to forge closer, collaborative working arrangements with one another. It has also fueled greater coordinated efforts among international labor groups and their allies to press for minimum international labor standards, particularly as they affect occupational health and safety, the right to organize, and the use of child labor. The challenge faced by those seeking progressive change is to broaden and deepen the agenda to include the various social concerns that affect the lives of the marginalized majorities along with those vulnerable to marginalization. In the area of intellectual property, a significant portion of this challenge involves the construction of a counterhegemonic discourse as it applies to the production of knowledge and technology and access to their uses. Workers in the center countries, especially the United States, face rising costs for health care at the same time that public and corporate provisions of such care are in retreat. For many of these people, including a growing cohort of the retired, the necessity of breaking the patent power of the pharmaceutical TNCs is becoming apparent. The rising cost of prescription drugs is a burden that is made worse by the inability of consumers to purchase generic versions of pharmaceuticals. There is a clear commonality of interest, therefore, between users of lifesaving, life-enhancing medicines and producers of these goods in a wider dissemination of the technology for their manufacture. The majority of workers and their families worldwide also have an interest in safe and environmentally responsible methods of producing all manner of output, especially food. Political work at boti the domestic and international levels needs to focus on pressuring states to allocate resources in the search for alternatives to the agroindustrial biotechr ology model. There exists plentiful historical evidence that publicly supported and directed research and development efforts have been particularly effective in achieving groundbreaking advances in both these broad areas of technological endeavor. Those who seek progressive change in the way that technology is produced and disseminated cannot cede the ideological ground to those who insist on the centrality of the capital-commodity nexus to technological progress. The Special Problem of the United States Any globally organized effort to find alternatives to the transnational capitalistdominated knowledge structure that conditions our understanding of the "lim-
212
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
its of the possible" as it applies to technology and social justice must contend with the special problem of the United States. By this, I do not refer merely to the fact that the U.S. government is especially aggressive in formulating and executing policies that advance a precapitalist, neoliberal agenda within and without its borders. As noted particularly in Chapter 5, the push to include the TRIPS agreement in the Uruguay Round discussions was given especially strong support by the United States Trade Representative. Neither do I only have in mind the additional fact that U.S.-based transnational corporations are in the forefront of the process of internationalization of capital. Rather, the real challenge to confront for progressive political activists in the United States is the pervasiveness of an ideology grounded in liberal individualism and dedicated to unconstrained consumerism. In other words, nowhere on earth does the force of consensual capitalist hegemony make itself felt more than in the United States of America. As a consequence, proposals that call for either a greater role for public authority or for internationalism are greeted with widespread suspicion and hostility even among large segments of the marginalized and soon to be marginalized. Progressive efforts that focus exclusively, or even primarily, on the moral obligations of average Americans to provide the poor countries with greater access to technology, finance, markets, or aid are not likely to be well received. Neither are moral condemnations of U.S. foreign and economic policies abroad likely to attract favorable attention unless they can also be shown to operate against popular domestic interests. To the contrary, as long as the discourse of "national competitiveness" reigns supreme, American workers will continue to regard their counterparts in both the poor and relatively rich nations as a potential or actual threat to be subdued with ever greater investments in proprietary capital and technology. It is a fact, however, and perhaps an ironic one, that the internationalization of capital is currently undermining the ideological basis for American exceptionalism as it also undermines the ability of U.S. labor organizations to defend workers' material standards of living. The prospects for a new internationalism in which American workers begin to appreciate the common cause they share with workers and other popular (e.g., peasants) classes all over the world cannot be dismissed. Economic and political crises that have greeted the beginning of the twenty-first century have generated a growing sense of skepticism in the United States regarding the neoliberal globalization project as they have elsewhere. Distrust of transnational capital has reached unprecedented levels in the wake of the stock market collapse and the revelations of corporate insider manipulations of equities prices that benefited an elite at the cost of the jobs and pensions of ordinary Americans. In the area of intellectual capital, as noted, American consumers of phar-
COUNTERHEGEMONY AND THE FUTURE OF TRIPS 213
maceuticals have begun to press for modification of trade rules that currently debar them from access to lower-priced brand-name drugs and generic substitutes. Recently, President Bush felt cpmpelled to support new trade rules that would limit the pharmaceutical industry's ability to keep Canadian generic substitutes for patented drugs out of the U.S. market.2 Some American farmers have recently organized to oppose the biotech revolution that prioritizes the bottom line of transnational agricultural input producers in disregard for their own livelihoods as independent farmers as well as the security of the food supply-3 Political developments such as these provide abundant reminders that the contradictions of capitalist development provide opportunities for counterhegemonic response e jen in those sites where the capitalist fortress seems most impregnable. There can be no presumption, therefore, that we have arrived at any final conclusions to the increasingly important question, Who owns knowledge?
Notes
Chapter 1 1. By "positivist" economics I refer to the dominant analytical tradition within the discipline that emphasizes the methods of nodel building and hypothesis testing as the means to establish the regularities and generalizations that many consider to constitute scientific results. I comment in greater detail on the usefulness and limitations of this tradition in Chapter 3. | 2. This applies most prominently to the poor countries, though it is notable that the United States is only a recent signatory to the Berne Convention. 3. The distinction between national treatment and most-favored-nation treatment is simple. National treatment means that national claimants cannot be given deference as compared to foreign claimants. Most-favored-nation treatment means that discriminatory treatment between foreign claimants is prohibited. 4. It would be possible to copyright cross-country statistics that provide an economic profile of the world, for example. In thi s case, the compilation may be copyrighted but not the data itself. It would not be p( issible to copyright the phone book, as a counterexample. 5. John Williamson is frequently given crodit for coining the term "Washington consensus" (WC) and is probably the most frequently cited proponent of this view. Though not identified as such, an early exemplar of the WC is found in an article authored by Williamson (1983) in the America t Economic Review in which he advocates that IMF loans to poor countries should link the goals of relaxing external liquidity constraints to solvency considerations. 6. This is an issue that will be pursued in gre ater detail in the concluding Chapter 8. 7. The instrumentalist-structuralist debate :>n the nature of the capitalist state has been waged among radical and Marxist scholars since at least as far back as the 1970s (Milliband 1969; Poulantzas 1978). For a receit overview, see Barrow (2000). State theory in the context of global capitalism is c Mitral to the discussion of the TRIPS agreement and will be taken up in detail in Chapter 4. 8. See the collection edited by Gill. (190:J) for an overview of Gramscian approaches as they apply to international relations theory. 9. There would seem to be a great deal of overlap between Strange and May's concept of "knowledge structure" and the Gramscian notion of hegemony. One could, in fact, argue that the knowledge structure is the vehicle by which hegemony is established and exercised. Gramscian hegemony is taken to be consensual in that it appeals to an accepted, or correct, view of the world and how it operates, or how it should operate. At the same time, this hegemony represents a particular class perspective which is posited not as a class perspective,* but as a universal one. 215
216
NOTES TO PAGES 52-70
NOTES TO PAGES 25-50
Chapter 2 1. For a sample of the latter reaction, see "March Madness" and "Protest Too Much" in New Republic 222, no. 18 (May 1, 2000): 9. 2.1 do not attempt a comprehensive review of the writings of all those who have had interesting insights into the nature of property. The thinkers whose theories I do consider are frequently invoked by modern scholars who have examined the historical development of private property rights. These scholars include Ryan (1984, 1987), Macpherson (1978), and Waldron (1988). 3. A utilitarian argument such as Bentham's, according to Waldron, is qualitatively distinct from arights-basedargument of any kind. 4. This seems to be precisely what has occurred in the recent case of South Africa, where popular pressure on international drug manufacturers has forced them to make their anti-ATDS medications available at far more reasonable prices than they were initially willing to sell them. 5. Hughes notes Hegel's views on the alienation of intellectual property rights. He argues that Hegel ultimately opts for a utilitarian (economic) defense of such alienation (Hughes 1988, p. 349, n. 243.) 6. It has been widely noted that much of the "seed capital" for the intellectual goods and services marketed by private corporations is derived from tax-financed, public sources. Government, through funding of its own research centers or public universities, is an important source of basic and applied science that is routinely turned over to the private sector for further development or immediate commercialization. Even when private corporations fund their own research and development departments, these activities are often the direct and indirect beneficiaries of favorable tax laws and public subsidies. For a useful discussion of the often uncomfortable relationship between academe, government, and private corporate interests over the issue of new knowledge and property, the interested reader should consult "The Common Good" (1999); Whipple (1999); and Mitchell (1999). 7. This is derived from Coase (1960). 8. Some readers will be familiar with this problem as "the tragedy of the commons" as described by Hardin (1968). 9. The expression "anticommons" is intended to evoke the antithetical notion of Garrett Hardin's famous "tragedy of the commons" (1968), which justified private property rights based on the potential for overexploitation of common property. 10. The incentive and security justifications for property have their roots in the British utilitarian philosophical tradition, which has otherwise been extremely influential in mainstream economic theory. See Ryan (1984) for discussion. 11. Students of economic history know that technology transfer to the late developing nations, including the United States and Japan, was precisely facilitated by the widespread disrespect of the early developing nations' best attempts to slow the international flow of technology. The major difference between the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries and the twentieth and twenty-first is that in the former periods technology was more often embodied in goods and physical capital, whereas in the current period it is less so. For specifics regarding America's early experience as a technological borrower, consult Rosenburg (1972). 12. A strictly Marxian view, of course, rejects the historical or moral legitimacy of privately held capital of any sort. In this view, all capital, including intellectual prop-
217
erty, is the product of a social labor process and in a society of associate producers' would be held in common. : ; 13. Some of these questions are taken up in the next chapter, while others are considered by Correa (2000), and Maskus (2000), and Maskus and Konan (1994). 14. See Ryan (1998), especially his chapter 4, for details. Chapter 3 1. The TRIPS agreement effectively replaces a United Nations institution called the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO), which holds a similar mandate but has lacked effective enforcement power. \ 2. It is probably accurate to say the distinction is actually less recognized among economists than it is among other social scientists. This owes less to its applicability than to the ideological dominance of positivikm within economics. 3. An important distinction is to be drawn between positivist social science and a derivative methodological approach referred to as logical positivism. The latter tradition is most closely associated with the Vienna Circle and more particularly with Karl Popper. Logical positivism shares many of the presumptions of positivism as regards the purposes and methods of science. It goes to the extreme position, however, of asserting that the fundamental purpose of positive science is not explanation at all. It is, rather, prediction. As such, the truth value of assumptions that are built into a testable model is immaterial. For detailed discussion, see Katouzian (1980), Hausman (1989), and the collection of articles edited bjy Marr and Raj (1982). 4. Cox (1986) identifies" Giambattista Vieo (1774/1970) as an originator of historicism and Robert Gilpin (1984) and Ralf E'ahrendorf (1959) as among his modem intellectual heirs. 5. Siebeck et al. (1990) provide an overview of the early work on these issues. 6. The limitations of static economic welfare analysis are well known. The assumption of a given endowment and allocation of productive resources and incomes predetermines the positions of market suppl) and demand curves. These in turn dictate market-clearing prices, which, in turn, help define the division of gains between producers and consumers, and so on. Changes in these initial endowments may yield differences in the pattern of supply and demmd, market-clearing prices, and, therefore, static welfare outcomes. These latter pos sibilities are, of course, beyond the pale of a static, problem-solving approach, but at the heart of a critical one. 7. This argument will be familiar to those acquainted with Vernon's (1966) product cycle theory. 8. Rapp and Rozek calculated their index based on data available for 116 countries for 1984. 9. Smith reports that the correlation coeficient between the 1984 RR and 1985 GP indexes is .75 (1999, p. 158, n. 11). : ; 10. The groups are identified in terms of per capita U.S. dollar income as high (8356 and above), upper middle (2696-8355), lower middle (675-2695), and low (1-674). 11. Though it should be noted that the sample size is somewhat reduced for the threat of imitation interaction term due to missing data. 12. The dummy is included given Mexico's proximity and advanced integration with the United States. 13. Statistical significance at the .01 and .05 levels is indicated by ** and *, respectively.
218
NOTES TO PAGES 72-91
14. Interestingly, neither Wheeler and Mody, Lee and Mansfield, nor the present analysis is able to establish a positive and statistically significant relationship between EDI and economic openness. In the Wheeler and Mody paper, in fact, a negative and significant relationship is found. 15. See Taylor (1994) for a theoretical discussion of the consequences of asymmetric protection of IPRs for trade, wages, and economic growth. 16. See Braga and Willmore (1991) for discussion of how protectionism affects the choice of firms to innovate or imitate. 17. As Levine and Renelt (1992) have noted, the empirical literature on economic growth is notorious for the lack of robustness in its results over alternative model specifications. Measures of the investment rate and human capital formation, however, seem to recur regularly as significant determinants of growth in cross-country samples. 18. The instrumental variable (IV) approach reduces the number of usable observations to seventy-nine. 19. These additional variables include the literacy rate, number of assassinations, number of revolutions and coups per year, and dummy variables to identify sub-Saharan African and Latin American countries. 20. Adjusted /?-square increases from .59 to .64 in the "enriched" equation. 21. The data sources for the variables are as follows: for GROWTH, 1988 World Development Indicators; for GDI, Penn World Table 5.6; for SECED, Human Development Report (United Nations 2001). The sample covers forty-three developed and less developed countries. Chapter 4 1. Clearly there are far more than three models that might be considered. In the interest of an efficient presentation, I choose to focus on three that 1 believe are potentially well suited to the analytical tasks. 2. Cox, following Gramsci, at the same time points out that he explicitly rejects "historical economism" (1996, pp. 131-132). 3. It will be immediately apparent that the WST concept of hegemony concentrates on the exercise of power by states in the interstate system in a fashion more consistent with realist interpretations of international relations than with the broader and more complex Gramscian understanding of the term, 4. Shannon (1989) does a nice job of reviewing the debate between WST theorists and their critics, which has at times taken on sectarian overtones. 5. Arrighi's views will be given much further discussion below. 6. Notably, Cypher admits that the dependency approach is not entirely oblivious to the importance of production in its analysis. 7. An additional and, in my opinion, less credible criticism sometimes leveled at WST is that, as a "structuralist" theory of the world economy, it leaves little room for human agency, promoting a sort of political quiescence and, therefore, operating to undermine counterhegemonic political action. The assertion that structuralist analysis somehow negates a progressive political project is a non sequitur. It would seem, on the other hand, that effective politics requires an understanding of both constraints and opportunities that only an understanding of structure can provide. Chase-Dunn (2002) argues, for example, that WST demonstrates that the best opportunities to challenge the dominant nodes of power in the world capitalist system
NOTES TO PAGES 91-98; 219
occur in the semiperiphery. It is here that development of productive forces has occurred sufficiently to create a working class with potential to challenge capitalist social relations, but without the sort of social democratic compromises that tend to mute labor militancy, as has occurred in the center countries. Whatever plausibility this particular argument may have, I believe that Chase-Dunn's general point regarding the usefulness of WST for informing counterhegemony organization and resistance is correct. 8. Stephen Hymer (1979) has written extensively on the role of the multinational corporation in promoting both the internationalization of capital and the "law of uneven development." His work, in my viewj provides a good illustration of how the dependency/IOC theories offer complementary rather than competing perspectives on underdevelopment. Perhaps not coincide^tally, Hymer arrived at an understanding of the exercise of state power in the globalteconomyvery close to the view I seek to advance in my own argument. Hymer's views, which are worthy of consideration in some detail, are taken up in the appendix td this chapter. 9. Tax reform in the less developed countries more often than not involved the imposition of a national value-added tax on consumption goods. Such a tax is well known to be regressive in its incidence, falling disproportionately on low-income households. Labor flexibiHzation is a euphemism for policies that delegitimate labor unions artd grant greater latitude to employers in their hiring practices. 10. The Settlement of Westphalia established the modern system of states even as it dissolved the Holy Roman Empire. Besides resolving a variety of territorial disputes, the settlement is said to have marked the end of religious warfare and promoted a new era of religious toleration. These latter accomplishments must be understood as helping to provide a propitiojus climate for the expansion of capitalist accumulation. 11. This is not to suggest, of course, that military strength was no longer relevant to conceptions of national strength and security. It is rather to argue that military might was no longer the sine qua non of interstate competition among developed capitalist states. Only under such circumstances, for example, could Japan emerge as a contender for global hegemonic leadership in the late twentieth century. 12. Noting that states perform certain necessary functions in facilitation of capital accumulation is not necessarily to adopt a "functionalist" theory of the capitalist state. According to such a theory, forms of state opntrol invariably correspond to particular requirements of capital's reproduction. Jessob (1990), for example, argues that whether or not state form follows function is problematical. He writes: Despite the loud and frequent proclamation by some Marxist theorists that the state is simply the ideal collective capitalist, its institutional separation clearly permits a dislocation between the activities of the state and the needs of capital. Conversely, although some theorists (such as Hindess and Hirst) sometimes seem to suggest that there is a necessary non-correspondence between the state and the economic region, correspondence does seem possible but must be constituted in the course of a struggle whose outcome is always contingent (p. 206). ; For a more complete discussion of the form-function nexus as it applies to the theory of the capitalist state, see Jessop (1982). 13. The "secondary" character of (this function is not to suggest its relative unimportance as compared to the other "primary" functions, according to Bryan (1995, p. 72). It is secondary only because its historical contingency depends on the charac-
220
NOTES TO PAGES 116-145 221
NOTES TO PAGES 103-115
ter of capitalist competition, whereas the primary functions are a matter of logical necessity for capitalist accumulation. 14. The hegemonic position of the United States is given further evidence by the failure of an additional proposed Bretton Woods institution, the International Trade Organization (ITO). As a precursor organization to the GATT, the ITO was an especially ambitious proposal that sought to oversee not only international trade but also international investment, commodity agreements, state trading, and international macroeconomic coordination. All of this was deemed by the United States to require too great a devolution of authority to the organization and was effectively vetoed on this basis. 15. While some scholars limit the term transition economy to refer to the former Soviet Union and Eastern European nations that began to develop market systems in the late 1980s, others have employed the term more widely to include those nations in the periphery and semiperiphery whose reform measures did not require the complete dismantling, or abandonment, of a full command system. 16. For contrasting views of the spread of neoliberal doctrine in Latin America, it is interesting to compare Petras (1992) with Hojman (1994). 17. The North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA) can be understood as a precursor agreement to the Uruguay Round that accomplished on a regional basis what the WTO is established to address on a global level. An interpretation of the NAFTA perfectly consistent with the perspective of IOC under U.S. hegemonic leadership adopted here is provided by Panitch (1994), who writes: What is particularly important to stress, however, is that this is not something imposed on the Canadian and Mexican states by American capita! and stale as external to the latter, rather it reflects the role adopted by the Mexican and Canadian states in representing the interests of their bourgeoisies and bureaucracies as these are already penetrated by American capital and administration, (emphasis in original, p. 75)
18. Morrissey and Rai (1995) explain that the motivation for TRIMS among the less developed countries often involves a desire to offset the distortions caused by the restrictive business practices, such as transfer pricing, of the TNCs themselves. The authors note that nothing in the TRIMS agreement of GATT 1994 recognizes that such efficiency-reducing distortions may emanate from the TNCs. Moreover, the authors show that the TRIMS agreement is inadequate to its alleged task of increasing welfare. 19. Notwithstanding the GATT TRIMS agreement, the United States wasted no time demonstrating the seriousness of its resolve to combat TRIMS unilaterally when in 1996 it applied Section 301 sanctions against Australia on the basis of its use of an export subsidy program. Capling (1997) provides discussion of the political dynamics of Australian opposition to the GATT TRIMS agreement. Chapter 5 1. TRIPS proponents cannot even draw on a well-established body of theory comparable to the Ricardian trade doctrine used for so long to support a liberal world trading system. 2. The differences between U.S. law and that of the Beme Convention may materially affect, for example, the ability of a magazine editor to alter an author's work to conform to the magazine's particular space requirements. For additional discussion, see Stalson (1987).
3. Stalson notes that notwithstanding its official opposition to compulsory licensing of patents by foreign governments, the U.S. government has compelled patent holders to license users as a remedy to unfa; r competition, to promote educational goals, and as part of its Atomic Energy and Clean Air Acts (1987, p. 23). 4. For a discussion of the asymmetric functioning of the GATT in its dealings with poorer and richer countries, seeTussie (1987). 5. Ryan recognizes that the ability to lobby the USTR is only for those firms and industries that are well-heeled, noting that the legal fees run into the hundreds of thousands of dollars and an entire case may cost the soliciting industry a million dollars (1995, pp. 36-37). 6. As Ryan (1998, p. 82) points out, Guangdong province is home to a class of wealthy and politically influential entrepreneurs who would be especially vulnerable to the type of sanctions brought against them by the USTR. 7. It is perhaps the fact that the GATT was primarily an agreement among center countries with competing textile sectors that&ept this line of production in such an exceptional status as regards trade liberalization. The poorer countries were literally peripheral actors in the early GATT talks and could not move to include textiles within the full orbit of trade negotiations. 8. Perhaps the most interesting aspect of the ATC negotiated during the mid1990s is that it did not include trade from the largest textile exporter in the world— namely, China. The agreement applies only jto WTO members, and China did not accede to the organization until 2001. Before the admission of China, the ACT would have imposed a tremendous cost on Chinese textile producers (Jacobs 1995). The Uruguay Round then had the additional advantage for the historic bloc of preparing the ground for negotiating China's accession to the WTO. 9. The category of tropical products has historically been separated out from the rest of GATT- concerned agricultural discussions. Usually, however, the effects have been more rhetorical than substantive. During- the Uruguay Round, tropical products were not, in fact, given serious treatment apart from the discussions surrounding agricultural issues more generally (Crome 1999). 10. Standard static welfare analysis suggests that NTBs that impose absolute limits on market access to foreign goods have greater costs to consumers and greater negative overall welfare costs than do comparably protectionist tariffs. 11. "Cairns" refers to the northern Queensland (Australia) city where a group of ministers from countries with substantial interests in agricultural exports initially met in August 1986.
Chapter 6 1. PhRMA (1996/1997) and cited in Ryan (1998, p. 30). 2. See Correa (2000) for more complete discussion of "international exhaustion" as it might be interpreted under the TRIPS, li 3. As 't Hoen (2002) points out, the Dbha|beclaration is far from a definitive solution to the conflict between IP protection dnd the needs of public health protection. 4. Per capita consumption figures are given in constant 1980 prices. 5. Data are from Schweitzer (1997, 'p. 21), who cites an unpublished paper by Chang (1995). j ; 6. See "Drug mergers change health landscape," American Medical News, January 31,2000. !
222
NOTES TO PAGES 146-162
7. The exercise of market power by the transnational pharmaceutical companies is not limited, of course, to the U.S. market. Challu (1995) shows that new legislation in Italy to strengthen patents is associated with a 200 percent increase in prices. The new law is also connected to a decrease in market share of Italy's national laboratories, a decrease in the number of drug inventions, and a deterioration in the country's pharmaceutical trade balance. 8. For additional data and a description of the UNDP Human Development Index, consult Human Development Report 2001 (United Nations Development Programme 2001). 9. The funding for the Malaria Genome Project comes from an independent research-funding agency called the Wellcome Trust. The Wellcome Trust describes itself as a charity, and one of its self-articulated guiding principles is that "research funded by the Trust is charitable in nature (i.e., gives adequate public benefit with only incidental private benefit) and is not constrained by commercial or other interests of the researcher. Discoveries, inventions, and other knowledge arising from Trust-funded research are made freely available to the wider scientific community." Greater detail may be found at the following Internet address: ww.wellcome.ac.uk/en/1/awt.html. 10. Indian law limited process patents to seven years. 11. The measures take into consideration differing assumptions regarding the elasticity characteristics of demand and amount to between 3 and 8 percent of the total pharmaceutical market. 12. South Africa's Medicines Law also permits compulsory licensing, although the law has never been used for this purpose. This fact did not prevent the South African Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association and forty pharmaceutical TNCs from bringing suit against the South African government for alleged violations of the TRIPS (Bass 2002). 13. See Brennan (2001) for a more complete discussion of the legal particulars of the dispute. 14. Scherer (2000) tells of a recent U.S. Supreme Court decision that seems to provide a precedent that delegitimates the authority of the WTO to establish and enforce international patent standards. In the case, Florida Prepaid Post-secondary Education Expense Board v. College Savings Bank, a majority ruled that Congress had exceeded its authority in nullifying individual states' immunity from patent infringement suits in federal courts (in cases where states provided due process). By analogy, argues Scherer, individual nation-states may not be subject to the dictates of supranational authority, such as the WTO, under similar "life-and-death" circumstances when they provide due legal process and "reasonable compensation." 15. At a recent meeting the WTO TRIPS Council reached an agreement that relaxes the rules prohibiting countries from importing generic versions of patented drugs designed to fight life-threatening diseases such as AIDS, malaria, and tuberculosis. For further details see "Trade agreement addresses drug access for poor countries." The agreement had been heavily resisted by the United States pharmaceutical industry (Becker 2003). The U.S. ultimately accepted the agreement under the condition that additional text was included that seriously circumscribes its application and limits its effectiveness. This additional text, called the "December 16" or "Motta text," stipulates a variety of administrative rules and procedures before imports of generics may be permitted. One effect of these restrictions is to preclude the possibility of economies of scale in the production of generics for export and make them less economically viable (MSF 2003). In addition to the Motta text, the United States has
NOTES TO PAGES 162-185
223
insisted that the new agreement apply only in cases of national health emergency, thus preventing poor countries from taking steps to prevent such emergencies from occurring in the first place. If nothing else, this latest agreement and its accompanying publicity are a prime illustration of the continuing struggle for Gramscian (consensual) hegemony as it applies to the international D?R regime. 16. Quoted in Winestock and Cooper (2001). 17. This does not exclude the possibility of charitable contributions from such private philanthropic agencies as the Gates [Foundation, for example. Such contributions cannot, however, be assumed to occur, in the necessary amounts when they are needed. ITiat is to say, the important work of providing health care to the world's poor majorities cannot be subject to the caprice (j>f "soft money" budgeting. 18. See Zimmerman (2001) for a journalistic account of how pharmaceutical TNCs have prevented the transfer to poorer countries of patented vaccine technology developed under the auspices of a PPP. Chapter 7 1. Some large TNCs such as Monsanto and Pfizer actually straddle the two industries. 2. Neither is it obvious how forthcoming the center countries will actually be in providing the promised improved access. U.S. president George W. Bush has already indicated his willingness to play the card ofj trade protectionism in his bid for reelection in 2004. I 3. In the language of Marxian economics, this point could be made by noting that while pharmaceutical outputs tend to invoh e capital in its circuit of circulation, agriculture biotech implicates capital in both its circuits of production and circulation. 4. See the appendix to this chapter for a detailed listing of GMOs that are currently approved by the United States Department of Agriculture and Environmental Protection Agency for use and sale in the United States. Not all crops are currently being marketed. Some are currently being! marketed under names other than those indicated in the table. Once a crop passes through the regulatory process, it may be sold under a variety of different names. Consult the Web site of the Union for Concerned Scientists at www.ucsusa.org for mcjire detail. 5. This is obviously another point in wjhich the ag biotech case closely parallels the pharmaceutical case. j 6. Kloppenburg (1988, p. 300, n. 1) notes that, as of 1985, patents for about 5,000 plants have been issued under the PPA—abtjmt 70 percent for ornamentals, 20 percent for fruits, and 10 percent for trees and shrubs. 7. For additional discussion of how hybridization transformed the technology and social relations of production agriculture, see Berlan and Lewontin (1986). 8. The 1991 revision of UPOV can be understood as an attempt to update the agreement so as to make it TRIPS effective. See Lesser (2000) for discussion of the limitations of UPOV as an effective sui generis system of PBRs for TRIPS purposes. 9. Some critics have argued that a measure of the popularity of the convention for many countries owes precisely to the U.S. refusal to become a part of the agreement. For these countries, the convention is a means to assert their sovereign rights of control over their genetic resources against encroachments of foreign interests (Raustiala and Victor 1996). 10. Other contradictions noted by Cleaver include regional disparities and uneven
224
NOTES TO PAGES 186-213
development arising from the fact that HYVs and their related technologies perform differently according to the quality of land employed. Ecological contradictions arise because the use of chemical herbicides and pesticides contaminates land and water resources and has a negative impact on human health. Also, the problems of genetic erosion and uniformity are often cited as outcomes of the widespread introduction of HYVs. 11. Vavilov centers are collection of plant genetic materials gathered from the five continents in the 1920s and 1930s by the N.I. Vavilov All-Russian Scientific Research Institute of Plant Industry. The institute is named for Nikolai I. Vavilov who was its director from 1917. 12. See Table 7.1. 13. Soybeans are an important ingredient in a wide variety of processed foods as well as an important form of animal feed. 14. Jepson argues that the fact that GM innovations tend to enter the production process at particular stages, rather than to transform the entire process of agricultural production, limits the ability of transnational capital to capture and dominate the production process and thereby alter production relations. I believe this author may, however, underestimate the transforming power of ag biotech to alter the costs of production in ways that will place larger, better endowed growers in a privileged position relative to the global market. Also, the real crux of the biotech debate as it concerns Brazilian soybeans appears to turn on the marketability of the commodity in European markets. To some extent, this consideration, which is clearly external to Brazil itself, illustrates the country's continuing vulnerability as a semiperipheral country. At the same time, these facts do not invalidate Jepson's well-considered observations on the indeterminate nature of the juridical-political struggle over GM technology. Chapter 8 1. A similar type of tax on capital account (international financial) transactions has been proposed by Schaberg (1998) as a way of reducing the instability caused by rapid movements of portfolio, "hot," capital into and out of emerging and less developed market economies. It should be clear that proposals such as these whose intent is to stabilize the operational impacts of the internationalization of capital are really far from adequate if the intention is wholesale transformation of the global regime of accumulation. 2. There remains considerable debate about the effectiveness of the Bush plan as compared to alternatives proposed by Bush's political opponents. For discussion, see Adams and Hitt (2002). 3. The Center for Food Safety (CFS) has recently organized a legal petition on behalf of Northern Plains wheat farmers and directed to the United States Department of Agriculture to impose a moratorium on the development of genetically modified wheat (GMW). Among the claims of the petitioners is the fear that GMW will contaminate non-GMW via pollination. Given the resistance of foreign markets to genetically modified crops, farmers fear the loss of markets abroad as well as negative environmental side effects. Consult the CFS Web site at www. centerforfoodsafety.org for more details.
References
Adams, Chris, and Greg Hitt. 2002. "Bush deals blow to big drug makers." Wall Street Journal, October 22: A3. Amin, Samir. 1974. Accumulation on a World Scale: A Critique of the Theory of Underdevelopment. New York: Monthly Review Press. Aoki, Reiko, and Thomas J. Prusa. 1993. "International standards for intellectual property protection and R&D incentives." Journal of International Economics 35, no. : 3/4 (November): 252-270. "Argentine farms: Unhappy." 1994. Economist 332, no. 7877 (August 20): 36. Arrighi, Giovanni. 1993. 'The three hegemonies of historical capitalism." In Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations, ed. Stephen Gill, 148-185. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Arrow, Kenneth J. 1962. "Economic welfare and the allocation of resources for inventions." In The Rate and Direction of Invent ve Activity, ed. R.R. Nelson, 609-625. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Ballance, Robert, Janos Pogany, and Helmut Forstner. 1992. The World's Pharmaceutical Industries: An International Persp ective on Innovation, Competition and Policy. London: Edward Elgar. Barakat, Pierre. 2002. "Prescription drug prices continue to soar." Business and Economic Review 48, no. 2 (January-March): 25-26. Barrow, Clyde W. 2000. "The Marx problem in Marxian state theory." Science and Society 64, no. 1 (Spring): 87-118. Bass, Naomi A. 2002. "Implications of the TRIPS agreement for developing countries: Pharmaceutical patent laws in Brazil and South Africa in the 21st century." George Washington International Law Review 34, no. 1:191-222. Beck, R.L. 1981. "Competition for patent monopolies." Research in Law and Economics 3: 91-110. Becker, Elizabeth. 2003. "Poor nations can purchase cheap drugs under accord." New York Times, August 31,2003, www.nytimes.com. Bello, Walden. 1999. "The WTO's big losers?' Far Eastern Economic Review 162, no. 25 (June): 54. I Bentham, Jeremy, 1987. The Theory of Legislation. Littleton, CO: F.B. Rothman. Berlan, Jean-Pierre, and Richard C. Lewontin. 1986. "The political economy of hybrid corn." Monthly Review 38, no. 3 (July/August): 35^17. Bhagwati, Jagdish N., and Hugh T. Patrick, eds. 1991. Aggressive Unilateralism: America's 301 Trade Policy and the World Trading System. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. 225
226
REFERENCES
Bijman, W J J . 2001. "How biotechnology is changing the structure of the seed industry." International Journal of Biotechnology 3, nos. 1/2: 82-94. Boisvert, Valerie, and Armelle Caron. 2002. "The Convention on Biological Diversity: An institutionalist perspective of the debates." Journal of Economic Issues 36, no. 1 (March): 151-166. Bornschier, Volker, and Christopher Chase-Dunn. 1985. Transnational Corporations and Underdevelopment. New York: Praeger. Bosman, Maarten, and Alwyn Mwinga. 2000. "Tropical diseases and the 10/90 gap." Lancet 356 (December): S63. Boyle, James. 1996. Shamans, Software, and Spleens: Law and the Construction of the Information Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Braga, Helson C , and Larry N. Willmore. 1991. "Technological imports and technological effort: An analysis of their determinants in Brazilian firms." Journal of Industrial Economics 39, no. 4 (June): 421-433. Brawley, Mark R. 1998. Turning Points: Decisions Shaping the Evolution of the International Political Economy. Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press. Brennan, Terrence M. 2001. "The United States and Brazil agree to disagree over Brazil's patent law." Intellectual Property and Technology Law Journal 13, no. 9 (September): 1-6. Brush, Stephen B. 1999. "Bioprospecting the public domain." Cultural Anthropology 14, no. 4 (November): 535-555. Bryan, Dick. 1995. The Chase Across the Globe. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Burstein, M.L. 1984. "Innovations and property rights: Introduction." Economic Inquiry 22, no. 4 (October): 608-633. Capling, Ann. 1997. "Who makes trade policy? Australia and the Uruguay Round agreement on trade-related investment measures (TRIMS)." Australian Journal of International Affairs 51, no. 3 (November): 339-354. Center for Responsive Politics. 2002. "Pharmaceutical/Health products: Long-term contribution trends," www.opensecrets.org/index.asp. Challu, Pablo M. 1995. "Effects of the monopolistic patenting of medicine in Italy since 1978." International Journal of Technology Management 10, no. 2-3: 237-252. Chambers, Judith, and Robert Bertram. 1998. "The U.S. position on the Consultative Group on International Agricultural Research." In Intellectual Property Rights III, Global Genetic Resources: Access and Property Rights, ed. Steve A. Eberhart, Henry L. Shands, Wanda Collins, and Richard L. Lower, 59-67. Madison, WI: Crop Science Society of America. Chang, R.R. 1995. "The top 100 pharmaceutical products in the United States from 1980 to 1992." UCLA Department of Health Services, unpublished paper cited in Schweitzer (1997). Chase-Dunn, Christopher. 1981. "Interstate system and capitalist world economy: One logic or two?" In World-System Structure: Continuity and Change, ed. W. Ladd Hollist and James N. Rosenau, 30-53. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. . 2002. "Globalization from below: Toward a collectively rational and democratic global commonwealth." ANNALS, American Association for the Advancement of Science 581 (May): 48-61. Chin, Judith C , and Gene M. Grossman. 1990. "Intellectual property rights and NorthSouth trade." In The Political Economy of International Trade: Essays in Honor of Robert E. Baldwin, ed. Ronald Jones and Anne O. Kruegar, 90-107. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.
REFERENCES
227
Cleaver, HaiTy M., Jr. 1972. "Contradictions of the green revolution." Monthly Review 24, no. 2 (June): 80-111. Coase, Ronald. 1960. "The problem of social cost." Journal of Law Economics 3, no.l (October): 1-44. "The common good." 1999. New Scientist 164;, no. 2210 (October 30): 3. Cooper, Helene, Rachel Zimmerman, and Laurie McGinley. 2001. "Patents pending: AIDS epidemic traps drug firms in a vise: Treatment vs. profits." Wall Street Journal, March 2: AI. Cooper, Richard N. 1998. "Toward a real global warming treaty." Foreign Affairs 77, no. 2 (March/April): 66-79. | Correa, Carlos M. 2000. Intellectual Property Rights, the WTO and Developing Countries. London: Zed Books. Cox, Robert. 1986. "Social forces, states, and world orders: Beyond international relations theory." In Neorealism and Its Critics, ed. Robert O. Keohane, 204-254. New York: Columbia University Press. . 1993. "Gramsci, hegemony and international relations: An essay in method." In Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations, ed. Stephen Gill, 49-66. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. -. 1996. Approaches to World Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Croome, John. 1999. Reshaping the World Trading System. The Hague: Kluwer Law International. Cypher, James M; 1979. "The internationalization of capital and the transformation of social formations: A critique of the monthly review school." Review of Radical Political Economics 11, no. 4 (Winter): 33-49. Dahrendorf, Ralf. 1959. Class and Class Confl let in Industrial Society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Dasgupta, Partha. 1987. "The economic theoiy of technology policy: An introduction." In Economic Policy and Technological Performance, ed. P. Dasgupta and Paul Stoneman, 7-23. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dasgupta, Partha, and Joseph Stiglitz. 1980. " t Uncertainty, industrial structure and the speed of R&D." Bell Journal of Economics 11, no. 1 (Spring): 1-28. Deardorff,AlanV. 1992. "Welfare effects of global patent protection." Economica 59, no. 233 (February): 35-51. Dhar, Biswajit, and C. Niranjan Rao. 1996. ""rade-relatedness of intellectual property rights " Science Communication 17, nc. 3 (March): 304-325. Diamond, Jared. 1997. Guns, Germs and Steel: The Fates of Human Societies. New York: W.W. Norton. Dos Santos, Teotonio. 1970. "The structure of dependence." American Economic Review 60, no. 2 (May): 235-246. "Drug mergers change health landscape." 2000. American Medical News 43, no. 4 (January 31): 4. Edwards, Michael, and David Hulme. 1996. "Too close for comfort? The impact of official aid on non-governmental organizations." World Development 24, no. 6 (June): 961-973. Emmanuel, Arghiri. 1972. Unequal Exchange: A Study of the Imperialism of Trade. New York: Monthly Review Press. Enserink, Martin. 2000. "Malaria researchers wait for industry to join fight." Science 287, no. 5460 (March 17): 1956-1958. Evans, Peter B. 1989. "Declining hegemony and assertive industrialization: US-Brazil
228
REFERENCES
conflicts in the computer industry," International Organization 43 (Spring): 207238. FAO. 1996. "PR 96/26—Leipzig Declaration." Food and Agricultural Organization Press Releases, www.fao.org/waicent/ois/press_ne/presseng/h22f.htm. FAO/CGRFA. 1983. International Undertaking on Plant Genetic Resources. Twentysecond Session of the FAO Conference. Rome. Feinberg, R.M., and D.J. Rousslang. 1990. "The economic effects of intellectual property infringements." Journal ofBusiness 63, no. 1 (January): 79-90. Foer, Franklin. 2000. "Protest too much." New Republic 222, no,18, May 1: 21-23. Frank, Andre Gunder. 1969. Latin America: Underdevelopment or Revolution? New York: Monthly Review Press. Gerster, Richard. 2000. "How WTO/TRIPS threatens the Indian pharmaceutical industry." Third World Network, www.twnside.org.sg/title/twrl20h.htm. Gill, Stephen, ed. 1993. Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gilpin, Robert. 1984. "The richness of the tradition of political realism." International Organization 38, no. 2 (Spring): 287-304. Ginarte, Juan Carlos, and Walter G. Park. 1997. "Determinants of patent rights: A cross-national study." Research Policy 26 (May): 283-301. Glover, Gregory J. 2002. "Testimony for the Pharmaceutical Research and Manufactures of America Before the Federal Trade Commission and Department of Justice—Antitrust Division." Washington, DC, March 19, www.phrma.org/publications/quickfacts/24.06.2002.431.cfm. Godwin, William. 1926. An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Gorman, Judith. 2000. "Golden fleece: Tax-paid research gives companies new drugs they sell back to us at exorbitant prices." Progressive Populist 6, no. 13 (July 15), www.populist.com/00.13.golden.fleece.html. Goss, Peter J. 1996. "Guiding the hand that feeds: Towards socially optimal appropriability in agricultural biotechnology innovation." California Law Review 84, no. 5 (October): 1395-1437. Gottlieb, Scott. 2001. "Drug companies maintain 'astounding' profits." British Medical Journal 324, no. 7345 (May 4): 1054. Gould, David M., and William C. Gruben. 1996. "The role of intellectual property rights in economic growth." Journal of Development Economics 48, no. 2 (March): 323-350. Gramsci, Antonio. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. New York: International Publishers. Hall, Stephen S. 1999. "Science triumphs, market fails." Technology Review 102, no. 1 (January/February): 78. Hanson, David. 1997. "Argentina punished for patent piracy."- Chemical and Engineering News 75, no. 4 (January 27): 10-11. Hardin, Garrett. 1968. "The tragedy of the commons." Science 162, no. 3859, December 13: 1243-1248. Harris, Gardiner, and Rachel Zimmerman. 2001. "Drug makers say WTO setback will not have significant impact." Wall Street Journal, November 15: B5. Hausman, Daniel H. 1989. "Economic methodology in a nutshell." Journal of Economic Perspectives 3, no. 2 (Spring): 115-127. Hawtin, Geoffrey, and Timothy Reeves. 1998. "Intellectual property rights and access
REFERENCES
229
to genetic resources in the Consultative Grdup on International Agricultural Re-r search." In Intellectual Property Rights HI, Global Genetic Resources: Access and Property Rights, ed. Steve A. Eberhart, Hejnry L. Shands, Wanda Collins, and Richards L. Lower, 41-58. Madison, WI: Crpp Science Society of America. Hegel, Georg W.F. 1996. The Philosophy of Right. Trans, by S.W. Dyde. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. Heller, Michael A., and Rebecca S. Eisenberg. 1998. "Can patents deter innovation? The anticommons in biomedical research." Science 280, no. 5364, May 1:698-701. Helpman, Elhanan. 1993. "Innovation, imitation, and intellectual property rights." Econometrica 61, no. 6 (November): 1247-1280. Helpman, Elhanan, and Paul Krugman. 1985. Market Structure and Foreign Trade. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hoekman, Bernard M„ and Michel M. Kostecki. 2001. The Political Economy of the World Trading System. New York: Oxford University Press. Hoffman, Vivian. 1999. "Health groups say poor nations need access to generic drugs." Boston Globe, November 27: A15. Hojman, David E. 1994. "The political economy of recent conversions to market economics in Latin America." Journal of Latin American Studies 26, pt. 1 (February): 191-219. Hughes, Justin. 1988. "The philosophy of intellectual property." Georgetown Law Journal 77, no. 2 (December): 287-366. Hymer, Stephen. 1979. The Multinational Corporation: A Radical Approach: Papers by Stephen Herbert Hymer, ed. Robert B. Cihen, Nadine Felton, Morley Nkosi, and Jaap van Liere. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ingco, Merlinda D. 1996. "Tariffication in the Uruguay Round: How much liberalisation?" World Economy 19, no. 4 (Ju y): 425-446. Jacobs, Brenda A. 1995. "Textiles and apparel Erade under WTO." China Business Review 22, no. 2 (March/April): 35-36. Jenkins, Rhys. 1987. Transnational Corporations and Uneven Development: The Internationalization of Capital. London: Methien. Jepson, W.E. 2002. "Globalization and Brazilian biosafety." Political Geography 21, no. 7 (September): 905-925. Jessop, Bob. 1982. The Capitalist State. New York: New York University Press. . 1990. State Theory: Putting the Capitalist State in Its Place. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. | Katouzian, Homa. 1980. Ideology and Method in Economics. New York: New York University Press. Kimble, Melinda. 1998. "The U.S. position in thi development of international treaties that impact genetic resources." In Intellectual Property Rights III, Global Genetic Resources: Access and Property Rights, ed. Steve A. Eberhart, Henry L. Shands, Wanda Collins, Richards L. Lower, 69-75. Madison, WI: Crop Science Society of America. Kindleberger, Charles P. 1973. The World in Depression, 1929-1939. Berkeley: University of California Press. . 1981. "Dominance and leadership in the international economy: Exploitation, public goods and freerides."International Studies Quarterly 25, no. 2 (June): 242-254. Klees, Steven J. 1998. "NGOs: Progressive TOOL or neoliberal force?" Current Issues in Comparative Education 1, no. 1 (November 15): 1-6.
230
REFERENCES
Kling, James. 1996. "Could transgenic supercrops one day breed superweeds?" Science 274, no. 5285, October: 180-181. Kloppenburg, Jack R. 1988. First the Seed: The Political Economy of Plant Biotechnology, 1492-2000. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Krasner, Steven D. 1976. "State power and the structure of international trade." World Politics 28, no. 3 (April): 317-347. Krugman, Paul R., ed. 1986. Strategic Trade Policy and the New International Economics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lake, David A. 1993. "Leadership, hegemony, and the international economy: Naked emperor or tattered monarch with potential." International Studies Quarterly 37, no. 4 (December): 459-489. Lall, Sanyaja. 1975. "Is 'dependence' a useful concept in analyzing underdevelopment?" World Development 3, no. 11/12 (November/December): 799-810. Lee, Jeong-Yeon, and Edwin Mansfield. 1996. "Intellectual property protection and U.S, foreign direct investment." Review of Economics and Statistics 78, no. 2 (May): 181-186. Lesser, W. 2000. "An economic approach to identifying an 'effective sui generis system* for plant variety protection under TRIPS." Agribusiness 16, no. 1 (Winter): 96-114. Levine, Ross, and David Renelt. 1992. "A sensitivity analysis of cross-country growth regressions." American Economic Review 82, no. 4 (September): 942-963. Locke, John. 1963. Two Treatises of Government. New York: Cambridge University Press. Macpherson, C.B. 1964. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. , ed. 1978. Property: Mainstream and Critical Positions. Toronto:,.University of Toronto Press. Mar, Willam L., and Baldev Raj, eds. 1982. How Economists Explain: A Reader in Methodology. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. "March madness." 2000. New Republic 222, no. 18 (May 1): 9. Marx, Karl. 1977. Capital. Vol. 2. New York: International Publishers. Maskus, Keith E. 1990. "Normative concerns in the international protection of intellectual property rights." World Economy 13, no. 3 (September): 387-409. . 1999. "Regulatory standards in the WTO: Comparing intellectual property rights with competition policy, environmental protection, and core labor standards." Institute for International Economics working paper 00-1, January. . 2000. Intellectual Property Rights in the Global Economy. Washington, DC: Institute for International Economics. Maskus, Keith E., and Denise Eby Konan. 1994. "Trade-related intellectual property rights: Issues and exploratory results." In Analytical and Negotiating Issues in the Global Trading System, ed. Alan V. Deardorff and Robert M. Stern. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Maskus, Keith E., and Mohan Penubarti. 1995. "How trade-related are intellectual property rights?" Journal of International Economics 39, no. 3-4 (November): 227-248. Matthews, Duncan. 2002. Globalising Intellectual Property Rights: The TRIPS Agreement. London: Routledge. May, Christopher. 2000. A Global Political Economy of Intellectual Property Rights: The New Enclosures? London: Routledge/RIPE studies in the global political economy.
REFERENCES
231 .
McCarthy, Michael. 2002. "US states file lawsu ;t against Bristol-Myers Squibb" Lancet; 359, no. 9323 (June): 2092. Milliband, Ralph. 1969. The State in Capitalist Society. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Milner, Helen. 1991. "The political economy of U.S. trade policy: A study of the Super 301 provision." In Aggressive Unilateralism, ed. Jagdish Bhagwati and Hugh T. Patrick, 163-180. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Mitchell, K. 1999. "Scholarship means dollayship, or, money in the bank is the best tenure." Environment and Planning 31, noj 3 (March): 381-388. Morrissey, Oliver, and Yogesh Rai. 1995. "The GATT agreement on trade related investment measures: Implications for developing countries and their relationship with transnational corporations." Journal of Development Studies 31, no. 5 (June): 702-724. Moschini, Giancarlo, and Harvey Lapan. 1997- "Intellectual property rights and the welfare effects of agricultural R&D." American Journal of Agricultural Economics 79, no. 4 (November): 1229-1242. MSF (Medecins Sans Frontieres). 2003. "US seeks further restrictions on generic medicines for developing countries." Press Release (August 25), www.doctorswithoutborders.org/pr/2003/08-25-2003_pf.html. Mullin, Rick. 2002a. "Global sales keep rising." Chemical Week 164, no. 20 (May 15): 28. ; . 2002b. "States sue Bristol-Myers over cancer drug patents." Chemical Week 164, no. 24 (June 12): 13. Nordhaus, W.D. 1969. Invention, Growth and Welfare. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. . 1972. "The optimum life of a patent : Reply." American Economic Review 62, no. 3 (June): 428-431. Palloix, Christian. 1977. "The self-expansion af capital on a world scale." Review of Radical Political Economics 9, no. 1 (September): 1-28. Panitch, Leo. 1994. "Globalisation and the state." In Socialist Register, 1994, ed. Ralph Milliband and Leo Panitch, 50-93. London: Merlin Press. Paul, James A., and Katarina Wahlberg. 2002. "Global taxes for global priorities." Global Policy Forum, www.globalp3licy.org/socecon/glotax/general/ glotaxpaper.htm. Park, Walter G., and Juan Carlos Ginarte. 1997- "Intellectual property rights and economic growth." Contemporary Economic policy 15, no. 3 (July): 51-61. Penn World Table, pwt.econ.upenn.edu/. | Perelman, Michael. 1998. Class Warfare in the information Age. New York: St. Martin's Press. Petras, James. 1992. "Retreat of the intellectuals." In Latin America in the Time of Cholera, ed. James Petras and Morris Morley, 158-169. New York: Routledge. Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America. 1996/1997. Annual Report. Washington, DC. . 2002. PhRMA Annual Membership Survey, www.phrma.org/publications/ publications/profile02/index.cfm. Primo Braga, Carlos A. 1990. "Guidance: from economic theory." In Strengthening Protection of Intellectual Property in Developing Countries: A Survey of the Literature, ed. Wolfgang E. Siebeck, 17-32.Washington, DC: World Bank. Primo Braga, Carlos A., Carsten Fink, and Claudia Paz Sepulveda. 2000. Intellectual Property Rights and Economic Development. Washington, DC: World Bank.
232
REFERENCES
Poulantzas,Nicos. 1968. Political Power and Social Classes. London: New Left Books. . 1978. State, Power, Socialism. London: New Left Books. Rapp, Richard X, and Richard P. Rozek. 1990. "Benefits and costs of intellectual property protection in developing countries." Journal of World Trade 24, no. 5 (October): 75-102. Raustiala, Kal, and David G. Victor. 1996. "The future of the Convention on Biological Diversity." Environment 38, no. 4 (May): 16-45. Rissler, Jane, and Margaret Mellon. 1993. Perils Amidst the Promise: Ecological Risks of Transgenic Crops in a Global Market. Cambridge, MA: Union of Concerned Scientists. Rosenberg, Tina. 2001. "Look at Brazil." New York Times Magazine, January 28: 26. Rosenburg, Nathan. 1972. Technology and American Economic Growth. White Plains, NY: M.E. Sharpe. Rupert, Mark. 1993. "Alienation, capitalism and the inter-state system." In Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations, ed. Stephen Gill, 67-92. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ryan, Alan. 1984. Property and Political Theory. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. . 1987. Property. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Ryan, Michael P. 1995. Playing by the Rules: American Trade Power and Diplomacy in the Pacific. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press. . 1998. Knowledge Diplomacy: Global Competition and the Politics of Intellectual Property Rights. Washington, DC: Brookings Institute. Scalise, David G., and Daniel Nugent. 1995. "International property protections for living matter: Biotechnology, multinational conventions and the exception for agriculture." Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law 27, no. 1 (Winter)83-99. Schaberg, Marc. 1998. "Globalization and financial systems: Policies for the new environment." In Globalization and Progressive Economic Policy, ed. Dean Baker, Gerald Epstein, and Robert Pollin, 195-214. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Scherer, EM. 1972. "Nordhaus's theory of optimal patent life: A geometric reinterpretation." American Economic Review 62, no. 3 (June): 422-427. . 2000. "The pharmaceutical industry and world intellectual property standards." Vanderbilt Law Review 53, no. 6 (November): 2245-2254. Schweitzer, Stuart O. 1997. Pharmaceutical Economics and Policy. New York: Oxford University Press. Sell, Susan K. 1998. Power and Ideas: North-South Politics of Intellectual Property and Antitrust. Albany: State University of New York Press. Sen, Julius. 2001. Negotiating the TRIPS Agreement: India's Experience and Some Domestic Policy Issues. Jaipur: CUTS Centre for International Trade, Economics and Environment. Shannon, Thomas R. 1989. An Introduction to the World-System Perspective. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Siebeck, Wolfgang E., Robert E. Evenson, William Lesser, and Carlos A. Primo Braga, eds. 1990. Strengthening Protection ofIntellectual Property Rights in Developing Countries: A Survey of the Literature. World Bank Discussion Papers, no. 112, Washington, DC: World Bank. Smith, Pamela J. 1999. "Are weak patentrightsa barrier to U.S. exports?" Journal of International Economics 48, no. 1 (June): 151-177.
REFERENCES 233;
Sorkin, Andrew Ross. 2000. "Behind biggest drr g merger, quest for a research pipe-; line." New York Times, January 18: CI. Stalson, Helena. 1987. Intellectual Property Rights and U.S. Competitiveness in Trade. Washington, DC: National Planning Association, Committee on Changing International Realities. \ Stecklow, Steve, and Matt Moffett. 1999. "Soys' from Brazil." Wall Street Journal, December 28: Al. Strange, Susan. 198$. States and Markets. London: Pintar Publishers. Subramanian, Arvind. 1991. "The international [economics of intellectual property right protection: A welfare-theoretic trade pc-licy analysis." World Development 19, no. 8 (August): 945-956. | Taylor, M. Scott. 1994. "TRIPS, trade, and growth." International Economic Review 35, no. 2 (May): 361-381. ! 't Hoen, Ellen. 2002. "TRIPS, pharmaceutical patents, and access to essential medicines: A long way from Seattle to Doha." Chicago Journal of International Law 3, no. 1 (Spring): 27-46. Tobin, James. 1974. "The new economics, one decade older." The Eliot Janeway Lectures on Historical Economics in Honor of Joseph Schumpeter, 1972. Princeton: Princeton University Press. "Trade agreement addresses drug access for poor countries." 2003. Nation's Health 33, no. 9 (November): 16. Trouiller, Patrice, Piero OHiaro, Els Toreele, and James Orbinski. 2002. "Drug development for neglected diseases: A deficient market and a public-health policy failure." Lancet 359, no. 9324 (June): 2188-2194 Tully, James. 1980. A Discourse on Property: John Locke and His Adversaries. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tussie, Diana. 1987. The Less Developed Countri zs and the World Trading System: A Challenge to the GATT. New York: St. Martin s Press. United Nations. 1997. "CBD: What the Convent on says." UN Chronicle 34, no. 2: 22-23. United Nations Development Programme. 2001. Human Development Report 2001. New York: Oxford University Press. United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights. 2001. "The Office of The United Nations High Commissioner for Hum in Rights. Access to medication in the context of pandemics such as HIV/AIDS. Ur>HCHR Resolution 2001/33 (April). . 2002. Access to medication in the context of pandemics such as HIV/AIDS: Report of the Secretary-General. United Nations Economic and Social Council, E/CN.4/2002/52, January: 1-17. UNAIDS. 2002a. Fact Sheet 2002: Sub-Sahatan Africa. Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS, July, www.unaids.org/en/defaykt.asp. . 2002b. Report on the global HIV/AIDSi epidemic July 2002. Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS, www.unaids.org/en/resources/publications/ corporate+publications/report+on+the+global+hiv_aids+epidemic+2002+.asp U.S. International Trade Commission. 1988. Foreign Protection of Intellectual Property Rights and the Effect on U.S. Industry and Trade. Washington, DC: Government Printing Office. Van Grasstek, Greg. 1990- "Trade-related intellectual property rights: United States trade policy, developing countries and the! Uruguay Round." In Uruguay Round: Further Papers on Selected Issues. Geneva: UNCTAD.
234
REFERENCES
Vemon, Raymond. 1966. "International investment and international trade in the product cycle" Quarterly Journal of Economics 80, no. 2 (May): 197-207. Vesely, Milan. 2000. "Why curing baldness is more lucrative than saving African lives." African Business 256 (July/August): 39. Vico, Giambattista. 1774/1970. The New Science of Giambattista Vico. Trans, from the third edition by Thomas Goddard Bergin and Max Harold Fisch. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Wagner, J. Martin. 2000. "The WTO's interpretation of the SPS agreement has undermined the right of governments to establish appropriate levels of protection against risk." Law and Policy in International Business 31, no. 3 (Spring): 855-859. Waldron, Jeremy. 1988. The Right to Private Property. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1974. The Modern World System. Vol. 1. New York: Academic Press. . 1984. The Politics of the World-Economy: The States, the Movements and the Civilizations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Watal, Jayashree. 2000. "Pharmaceutical patents, prices and welfare losses: Policy options for India under the WTO TRIPS agreement." World Economy 23, no. 5 (May): 733-752. Watanabe, Chihiro, Makoto Takayama, Akira Nagamatsu, Takashi Tagami, and Charla Griffy-Brown. 2002. "Technology spillover as a complement for high-level R&D intensity in the pharmaceutical industry." Technovation 22, no. 4 (April): 245-258. Watson, Rory. 2001. "Oxfam accuses Pfizer of 'moral bankruptcy.'" British Medical Journal 323, no. 7306 (July): 186. Wharton, Clifton R., Jr. 1969. "The green revolution: Cornucopia or Pandora's box." Foreign Affairs 47, no. 3 (April): 464-476. Wheeler, David, and Ashoka Mody. 1992. "International investment location decisions." Journal of International Economics 33, no. 1/2 (August): 57-76 Whipple, Dan. 1999. "Seeds of controversy." Futurist 33, no. 8 (October): 10-12. Williamson, John. 1983. "On seeking to improve IMF conditionality." American Economic Review 73, no. 2 (May): 354-358. Winestock, Geoff, and Helene Cooper. 2001. "Activists outmaneuver drug makers at WTO—poor nations can ignore patents to meet public-health needs." Wall Street Journal, November 14: A2. World Development Indicators. 1988. Washington, DC: World Bank. Yaghmaian, Behzad. 1998. "Globalization and the state: The political economy of global accumulation and its emerging mode of regulation " Science and Society 62, no. 2 (Summer): 241-265. Zimmerman, Rachel. 2001. "Some question whether drug makers play too large a role in vaccine fund." Wall Street Journal, December 3: A12.
Index
acquired immune deficiency syndrome (AIDS), 44, 51, 131, 143, 150-51, 158, 207 Adams, Chris, 224n8.2 Advisory Committee on Trade Policy Negotiation (ACTPN), 121 aggregate measure of support (AMS), 136 Agreement on Agriculture (AA), 134-37 Agreement on Textiles and Clothing (ATC), 133-34 agriculture, 73 biotechnology, 170-75 B.t. corn, 171 research and development, 168,176,187 and trade, 168 American Seed Traders Association, 176 Amin, Samir, 23 Aoki, Reiko, 26 Argentina, 153 GM crops, 200-1 Arrighi, Giovnanni, 218n4.5 Arrow, Kenneth, 7 Asian NICs, 76, 95, 107 ATC, 221n5.8 Australia, 134 AZT, 51, 159 Ballance, Robert, 144-45 Barakat, Pierre, 146 Barrow, Clyde, 215nl.9 Bass, Naomi, 156, 222n6.12 Bayer AG, 162 Bayh-Dole Act, 50 Beck, R.L., 57
Backer, Elizabeth, 222n6.15 Belgium, 91 Bentham, Jeremy, 33-37, 216n2.3 Berlan, Jean-Pierre, 223n7.7 Berne Convention, 4, 54, 64, 114-15, 215nl.2 as compared to U.S. copyright law, 155, 220n5.2 Bertram, Robert, 189 Bhagwati, Jagdish, 127 Bijman, W.J.J., 191 tiopiracy, 197 t ioprospecting, 197-98 biotechnology revolution (BR), 187, 191, 207 implications for workers, 199-200 Boisvert, Valerie, 194-96 Bolivia, 68 Borlaug, Norman, 184 Borlaug wheat, 184,186 ijlornschier, Volker, 86 Bosnian, Maarten, 148 Boyle, James, 19-21, 205-6 Braga, Helson, 218n3.16 Brawley, Mark, 80 Brazil, 72, 91, 107, 112, 133, 137, 142, 153 agricultural biotech, 201 j Industrial Property Law (IPL), 157-58, 160 HIV infections, 159 pharmaceutical industry, 157 TRIPS negotiations, 7, 53 Brennan, Terrence, 160, 222n6.13 Bretton Woods, 84, 105 235