Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty, 1890–1990
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty, ...
95 downloads
828 Views
2MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty, 1890–1990
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty, 1890–1990
Cheryl Shanks
Ann Arbor
Copyright © by the University of Michigan 2001 All rights reserved Published in the United States of America by The University of Michigan Press Manufactured in the United States of America c Printed on acid-free paper 2004
2003
2002
2001
4
3
2
1
No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, or otherwise, without the written permission of the publisher. A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Shanks, Cheryl, date Immigration and the politics of American sovereignty, 1890–1990 / Cheryl Shanks. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-472-11204-X (Cloth : alk. paper) 1. United States—Emigration and immigration—Government policy. 2. Emigration and immigration law—United States—History. I. Title. JV6483 .S536 2002 325.73'09'04—dc21 2001001223
Contents
Acknowledgments 1. Introduction
vii 1
2. Arguments about Immigrants
10
3. Whether to Exclude
31
4. Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
55
5. Whom to Exclude: The McCarran-Walter Act
96
6. Whom to Exclude, Whom to Prefer: The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
144
7. Whom to Exclude, Whom to Prefer: IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
187
8. Domestic Interests as Explanations
230
9. Structural Theories as Explanations
245
10. Conclusion: Sovereignty, Things, and People
268
Appendixes
285
Notes
295
Bibliography
339
Index
379
Acknowledgments
I have incurred debts, some quite great. I thank above all Ronnie Gruhn and Harold Jacobson. I am indebted as well to comments I received from Barbara Anderson, Lars-Erik Cederman, David L. Chappell, Matthew Evangelista, Eric Gampel, Ellen Gordon, James Holli‹eld, and A. F. K. Organski. My research was aided in various ways by the Center for Political Studies at the Institute for Social Research, the Immigration and Naturalization Service, the Institute for the Study of World Politics, the National Archives, Rackham Graduate School, and colleagues at Williams College and the Oakley Center for the Humanities and Social Sciences.
Contents
Acknowledgments 1. Introduction
vii 1
2. Arguments about Immigrants
10
3. Whether to Exclude
31
4. Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
55
5. Whom to Exclude: The McCarran-Walter Act
96
6. Whom to Exclude, Whom to Prefer: The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
144
7. Whom to Exclude, Whom to Prefer: IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
187
8. Domestic Interests as Explanations
230
9. Structural Theories as Explanations
245
10. Conclusion: Sovereignty, Things, and People
268
Appendixes
285
Notes
295
Bibliography
339
Index
379
Acknowledgments
I have incurred debts, some quite great. I thank above all Ronnie Gruhn and Harold Jacobson. I am indebted as well to comments I received from Barbara Anderson, Lars-Erik Cederman, David L. Chappell, Matthew Evangelista, Eric Gampel, Ellen Gordon, James Holli‹eld, and A. F. K. Organski. My research was aided in various ways by the Center for Political Studies at the Institute for Social Research, the Immigration and Naturalization Service, the Institute for the Study of World Politics, the National Archives, Rackham Graduate School, and colleagues at Williams College and the Oakley Center for the Humanities and Social Sciences.
CHAPTER 1
Introduction
Controlling access to citizenship helps states stay sovereign in the face of globalization. The transnational processes that governments support can also threaten governments’ power and their integrity. For example, economic interdependence allows extensive and rapid growth, upon which governments depend, yet it also subjects states to decisions made far away. One way that countries have chosen to adapt is to extend regulatory control over immigration and naturalization. In the United States, these are linked: legal immigrants may apply to become naturalized citizens. In most other advanced industrial states as well, full political membership has become harder to achieve, even as states have ceded control over the labor market, tourism and business travel, and goods, entertainment, services, and information.1 The United States has done so while easing visa restrictions for tourists and business travelers. Over the past century, the number of immigrants the United States will accept each year has steadily declined as a percentage of the U.S. population. When the numerical ceiling has gone up, it has done so by pulling previously unrestricted groups into the controlled category. By 1990 all immigrants were subject to a quota. Extending control over citizenship provides a counterbalance to the decontrolled economic realm. Sovereignty involves unique authority over a territory and what is on it, its population and its natural resources. As goods, lands, and resources are swept into the international market, governments have to de‹ne clearly who their citizens are lest they lose both of sovereignty’s de‹ning characteristics. Scholars and commentators on international politics often present sovereignty as a settled institution, a long-ago established fortress that globalization’s battering might or might not breach.2 The state, a passive rock, faces environmental assaults that threaten to erode it. Yet the state has taken steps to protect itself from outside forces, choosing when to cede, when to adapt, when to resist. Given the power of transnational trade and communications, and the desire of hundreds of millions of people to emigrate, inaction over the last century would have meant sovereignty’s end. Not only have governments pursued the various components
2
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
of globalization, but they have also pursued ways to enhance sovereignty. Governments have worked to maintain one type of boundary, that between citizen and noncitizen, while energetically undermining others. Sovereignty is a policy choice, constructed in the most ordinary sense. Destruction and creation take work, but so do maintenance and adaptation. Most observers of international politics take stability for granted and try to explain change. This study does the opposite, taking change for granted and trying to explain continuity in the face of powerful transnational forces. Demonstrating that to preserve or enhance sovereignty is a policy choice, and that immigration control is a core aspect of this choice, involves three separate arguments. One is purely theoretical or logical, the other two empirical as well.
First Argument
Since sovereignty involves supreme authority over an exclusive territory and population, a state has to know over what domain its authority extends, where it begins and others end. Boundaries are not suf‹cient to create sovereignty, but they are necessary.3 International relations theories customarily date this form of social organization from the Treaty of Westphalia in 1648.4 Before the Thirty Years War, which the treaty ended, who had supreme authority depended on the issue. Feudalism involved a web of obligations within overlapping hierarchies. The treaty codi‹ed a revolutionary change in this arrangement by granting to a single sovereign authority over all issues. The political domain was de‹ned by territory rather than issue. The sovereign could impose taxes, conscript anyone within the territory, dictate religion, and decide economic practices within set geographical boundaries. Modern sovereignty in this way rests on boundaries that de‹ne what is inside and what is outside. Both territory and population need to be known, and in theory, all territory belongs to one country, but only to one country. Alsace can be French or German but not both; Kashmir can be Indian or Pakistani but not both. The same is true of people. Dual citizenship is tolerated as long as its obligations are trivial and partial. For example, no state will tolerate a citizen ‹ghting for an enemy. International law and the highest domestic courts cement these practices as rights. Only the state can determine which people are its citizens. It does not even have to accept all of those born on its territory. When human and civil rights come into con›ict with sovereign rights, sovereign rights win. For this reason, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights declares that “everyone has the right to leave any country, including his
Introduction
3
own, and return to his country” and “everyone has the right to a nationality”; ‹nally, “everyone has the right to seek and to enjoy in other countries asylum from persecution.”5 But sovereigns do not have the corresponding obligation to admit those exercising their right to leave. People have a right to leave but not a right to enter. Within a country, civil rights follow this pattern. Those in the United States illegally, for example, or those legal immigrants who violate a law, can be jailed inde‹nitely without a hearing. Advocacy groups repeatedly decry this “violation of their civil rights,” yet noncitizens have no civil rights, as the U.S. Supreme Court has repeatedly ruled. In February 1999, it restated this stance with regard to the First Amendment when it ruled that “people [in the United States] unlawfully cannot shield themselves from deportation by claiming the government is trying to banish them simply because of their controversial political views.”6 The Court has not deviated from this position since it ‹rst stated it, after the Civil War. Law at all levels supports the theory of sovereignty’s absolute nature. Practice raises problems for theory. Territory and population are profoundly different aspects of sovereignty, in each of three respects. In practice, people move. Territory does not move. Boundaries might shift, even dramatically, but wherever they are, they signify the same thing. Parts of a territory cannot break off and start ›oating around, mixing with other territorial bits in a giant mosaic. This is, though, precisely what does happen with nationalities. Second, territory does not move itself; it has no agency. Individuals do have agency. If individuals rather than the state could decide who af‹liated where, the state would no longer be sovereign. States cannot always control a person’s physical location but a state can control a person’s political location, his or her political identity. A stowaway does not have to be given rights. It is in this way that control over naturalization is a sine qua non of sovereignty. Finally, people move as packages, taking with them their language, experience, skills, and politics. When territory transfers hands, the land itself does not need to be assimilated. Policies toward territory and population have also been sharply different. Territory has grown less important to state security over time.7 Territory matters largely in that it serves as a marker for citizenship. These are legal and symbolic values, having to do with the customs of sovereignty, rather than power. Territory is less relevant to the most powerful countries’ abilities to achieve their goals. In the past, the larger a territory, the better. Moscow’s distance from Paris was the most important defense Russia had against Napoleon. The Atlantic and Paci‹c Oceans have similarly protected the United States, and its size helped to make it economically self-suf‹cient. Technological changes have reduced territory’s value in attaining these goals. Markets transcend boundaries, are in fact
4
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
strongest when they do. Natural resources and agriculture are relatively less important in generating wealth than are manufacturing and services, which do not depend on land size. Japan, with no energy resources and little arable land, is a great power. Intercontinental missiles and airplanes have severed the link between size and safety. Indeed, the larger a country is, the bigger a target it is. Territory matters, but the amount a state controls does not determine its wealth or power. Population has meanwhile grown in importance. To mercantile states, more people meant more wealth.8 As welfare states developed, additional people meant additional costs, so their contribution had to be greater than the resources they could claim. In addition, people now evaluate their elected representatives in terms of the country’s per capita economic performance.9 Limiting the number of “capita” is easier than controlling the pace of economic growth. These technological, economic and political changes combined to make governments focus on their populations rather than on their territories.
Second Argument
Sovereigns control access to citizenship and in this way help maintain their sovereignty. That consequence might, however, not be the motivation for this practice. Governments might do this for other reasons; sovereignty could be an unintentional side effect. That governments deliberately control immigration in order to secure sovereignty is a second argument, an empirical one. Sovereignty does motivate governments—here, the United States—to extend regulatory control over immigration. Demonstrating this involves presenting evidence relevant to this contention and exploring the evidence in support of the most apparent alternative explanations. Most research on immigration policy views it as a domestic policy with domestic sources of change. In this view, it is a response either to unemployment and welfare cycles, or to lobbying by ethnic interest groups, or to parties’ desires to distinguish themselves from each other, or to changes in public opinion.10 Changes in federal immigration ceilings or preferences would, in this view, emerge in response to a rise in unemployment, a burst of ethnic lobbying, a change in the majority party, and/or a rash of popular xenophobia. All of these are plausible hypotheses and might account for legislative movement on immigration control. Many policymakers, however, cite the preservation of sovereignty as the motivation for their position. When legislators, the press, and the public argue about policy, they give reasons to support their proposals. When
Introduction
5
they want a policy because of its consequences for sovereignty, they say that. Because boundaries divide the inside world from that outside, their strength and location become a charged issue when international involvement threatens to blur the lines separating what is in from what is out. The major changes in American immigration policy have come during strong economic times, after a major change in the international system: the Chinese Exclusion Acts of 1882 were followed by the Quota Acts of 1921/24 (a response to World War I), McCarran-Walter of 1952 (a response to World War II and the cold war), Hart-Celler of 1965 (a response to decolonization during the cold war), and ‹nally the Immigration Reform and Control Act (IRCA) of 1986, which was paired with the revised Immigration and Nationality Act of 1990 and focused on foreign economic competition rather than military competition. In fact, the only time that immigration policy becomes a real issue at the national level, and Congress changes federal policy, is when there has been a major change in the international system. Domestic processes affect enforcement rather than overall policy. Any immigration policy has to answer two questions: how many people, and which ones. The ‹rst concerns numbers; the second, who will be excluded or preferred in making up those numbers. Restricting and extending regulatory control over the amount of immigration is an exercise of sovereignty, an enforcement of difference. Deciding which people can enter expresses in what way the country is different. Preferences and exclusions show how the country contrasts itself with those outside it. Reasons must be given for preferences and exclusions as well as for numbers. Evidence, then, comprises the reasons given by contestants in these policy debates, for and against controlling immigration. Combined with the evidence regarding the importance of unemployment and other in›uences that legislators face, reasons provide a clear picture of the dynamics driving policy change on this issue.
Third Argument
A third argument concerns the policy process itself. To have a chance of successfully becoming law, a proposal must be supported by arguments that conform to the particular demands of public interest debates.11 These arguments explain which values are at stake. They can become central to the debate, focusing attention on proposals that serve certain values rather than others. In this way, debate has the ability to transform policy outcomes. In a policy debate, contestants who do not attend to reasons cannot win. For example, say that two groups disagree about zoning policy regarding home of‹ces. One side argues in terms of traf‹c increasing in
6
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
residential neighborhoods. If the other side can show this to be false—say, by demonstrating that commuting drops, canceling the increase in commercial traf‹c—it can win. In fact, it can then use the opposition’s reason, traf‹c, to push through even broader changes in the law than it ‹rst thought possible or even wanted. The resulting policy will not be in the middle, nor will it be what one side initially advocated, as bargaining models would suggest. Instead, the result is a more extreme version of what one side wanted, a consequence of its ability to use its opponent’s reasons for its own purposes. Argumentation has a logic that can produce settlements wholly unanticipated by either side. National debates over American immigration policy follow this odd logic. What results is in fact never in the middle, but something off the charts. What provides a pattern to the policy processes is the set of arguments that tend to come up in discussions of immigration: the meaning of citizenship, consent, and national character, the importance of ethnic or ideological homogeneity, the message to allies. These all involve the country’s relation to the outside world.12 Each raises questions of identity and obligation, so the debates over immigration tend to involve the philosophical questions of duty to self and others, and what this says about the nature of self and others. Taken together, these arguments portray American debates over immigration as occasions when Americans renegotiate what sovereignty means to them.
The United States
The United States is at the center of this study, for methodological and practical reasons. Since the central questions involve change or continuity over time, evidence had to be gathered that covered as long a time as possible. Therefore, the study could focus on one country only. The United States should be the hardest case. American history and culture celebrate the immigrant. The Declaration of Independence complains about British colonial immigration policy. Stories of immigration are woven into national myth as well as history. American children learn of the Pilgrims, of Ellis Island and the Statue of Liberty; so powerful are these images that many educated adults are unaware that return migration to Europe at times exceeded immigration. Compared with others, the United States has always been an ethnically diverse society, with powerful norms in favor of pluralism, even when the reality has lagged behind the norm. In addition, compared with other industrial countries, the United States is underdeveloped as a welfare state. The average federal expenditure per capita on social services is thirteenth among the advanced industrial states,13 and a
Introduction
7
huge piece of this, social security, Medicare, and veterans’ bene‹ts, is devoted to the age group, or class, least likely to immigrate.14 Further, American hegemony has meant that the country sets the terms of its interaction with the outside and need not interpret investments or immigrants as invaders, as other countries would be quick to do.15 Finally, the United States accepts more immigrants annually than the next several countries put together. American myths, values, economic capacity, power, and policy history combine to create a presumption against protective immigration policies. American immigration policy has great practical signi‹cance as well, for those abroad as well as for American citizens. The number of immigrants annually admitted to the United States is at present equivalent to the population of entire countries. If the United States barred nonimmigrant visitors except from Sweden, Finland, and Norway, every citizen of all three countries could travel to the United States in the same year without disrupting the pattern. The sheer volume of this movement means that for millions of individuals, American immigration policy is of great importance.
Contributions of This Study
Analyzing immigration policy over the past century provides insight into a number of central theoretical questions. First, it shows how change in the international context can translate into change in a country’s sense of self, how the “us” changes in response to changes in “them.”16 Studies of foreign policy have long explored how one country’s behavior will affect another country’s behavior. Action-reaction models are aptly titled; they focus on what states do in response to each other’s actions. Some research has elaborated this model, exploring whether domestic institutions and cultures can shape a foreign policy response and whether a country’s foreign policy displays a unique personality.17 Immigration policy, unlike military or trade policy, tells us about a country’s identity as well as its interests. For this reason, it becomes possible to show how international action—changes in the distribution of power and nature of con›ict— shapes what a state thinks it is as well as what it does. Second, by following a policy that links identity and behavior, the study sheds light on theories that portray identity as well as behavior as a variable. Constructivist sociology and political science argue that policy and identity cannot be separated as easily as much international relations scholarship assumes.18 What people or institutions do affects what they are. Much constructivist work concerns itself with central philosophical
8
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
and theoretical issues, such as how this insight alters our notion of international structures. Applied work is sparse. This study describes how construction works at a practical level in one case. Because of experience, identity changes. This translates into policy governing admission and exclusion, and then into enforcement. Construction is, in this way, observable behavior. Third, viewing sovereignty as a policy choice makes it easier to address the otherwise vast question of “whither the state system.” Because sovereignty is a huge variable, observers have linked it to variables of comparable size, such as nationalism, the commons, multinational corporations, or international institutions. How these ought to be measured is unclear, what counts as change in one is unclear, and the scale overwhelms the consideration of human agency and choice. This leaves the impression that vast historical forces operate on their own, without human input. People do matter, as agents and not just objects of history. By linking sovereignty to legislative choice through immigration policy, this analysis shows one way to make sovereignty’s future approachable. Fourth, this study shows how participants in one of the most powerful democratic decision-making institutions in the world—the U.S. Congress—negotiated the relation between interests and values in determining the national interest. Often, foreign policy, like human agency, is portrayed as a compulsive search for material wealth and power. When values enter the discussion, they are dismissed as a cover for the real goals, which are allegedly material. That might be true for some issues, but for immigration policy, values trump interests every time. In fact, certain defeat awaits an immigration proposal that is framed in terms of money. Finally, these debates provide a rare window on what political membership means to Americans. In a world where states get citizens or subjects at birth, immigration policy provides the only place where it is acceptable to discriminate. Alternative policies that might achieve the same demographic result horrify publics and have high costs. Pervasive acceptance of jus soli and jus sanguinis—citizenship by place of birth or descent—means that countries get citizens at birth. People decry increasing the population’s size through compulsory fertility, as did Romania, or limiting it through government-enforced sterilization, as did India. Reducing it through discriminatory application of public health measures and selecting characteristics through eugenics shock the modern conscience on three grounds: their discriminatory nature, their reliance on ideas of biological superiority, and their suggestion of betrayal by one’s government. A prospective immigrant, on the other hand, is not “one of us,” and people do not consider selective immigration an ethical parallel to selective fertility or mortality policies. Immigration policy is the only place where a
Introduction
9
country can state baldly and illiberally whom it wants, whom it does not, and why. International law, domestic governments, and most people grant states authority to control immigration as a core right.
Organization
Policies, rather than the actual number of immigrants, are to be explained because policies establish boundaries and create political communities. The policies also articulate the value that a country places on the borders dividing its citizens from people elsewhere. In this way, statements about who may enter a political community describe how a society identi‹es the most important differences between itself and others. The number of immigrants actually arriving depends on millions of decisions made elsewhere, under a variety of conditions, and on the funding and politics of border patrols. Actual ›ows matter as a stimulus to later policy change. Policy toward immigrants—persons admitted for permanent residence and, eventually, citizenship—is the focus. The spotlight stays on potential citizens. The study starts by discussing the role that argumentation plays in shaping policy choice and describes the requirements that “the public interest” places on those advocating a position. Then, chapter 3 presents the arguments that legislators and others made for and against immigration restriction. Next, chapters 4 through 7 describe the ensuing sequence of debates over exactly how many and whom to exclude. These chapters are organized to provide evidence for and against the theses that sovereignty is a choice, that immigration policy is externally responsive, and that public interest requirements shape outcomes. Following these are two chapters considering alternative explanations. Chapter 8 evaluates the contention that material and domestic interests drive change; it analyzes the partisan content of congressional votes, variations in public opinion, and changes in the unemployment rate as correlates of immigration restriction. Chapter 9 evaluates the contention that broad analyses that ignore arguments do as well, or nearly as well, in explaining change in immigration policy as does the structure-argumentstructure model developed here. Finally, chapter 10 discusses the implications this study has for understanding structural change generally and for understanding policies regulating the mobility of people speci‹cally.
CHAPTER 2
Arguments about Immigrants
One sort of political negotiation best explains the direction of change in American immigration policy. Political negotiation can take several different forms. One involves the question of who gets what. Two or more sides can bargain over policy as a vendor and a buyer might haggle over a price until they reach a settlement somewhere between their starting points or, if each wants something different, they might agree to trade votes. This happens when the issue is how to distribute a measurable good: money, votes, personnel, the number of military bases. Power decides these issues. Many political problems correspond to this model of individuals with competing interests bargaining under scarcity, at least at one stage in a lengthier process. At other times, political negotiation involves the question of which values ought to guide policy. Disagreement can focus on whether a problem exists at all, or on which principle should be applied to solve it. A policy package—a goal plus a principle plus a solution—has a logical glue that makes compromise dif‹cult and, when it occurs, forces it to follow a different path than that which describes straight bargaining. At the heart of such policy packages are arguments, which connect problems and solutions with reasons. Success depends on persuasion rather than on material resources. Argumentation can produce policies that are fundamentally different from, and unpredictable from the standpoint of, simple material interests. In two circumstances, ignoring arguments is justi‹ed. Sometimes a choice does not exist, and to believe that one does is, in fact, to be deluded. For arguments to matter, choice has to be possible. If, for example, a country were to be annihilated unless it acted in a certain way, its “choice” to comply is forced and, because it was necessary, not a real choice. In circumstances of necessity, arguments are, paradoxically, irrelevant if actors are rational. This justi‹cation underlies structural theories of international relations as well as endgame analyses. In the long run, structural theorists contend, the broad forces that drive historical processes—movements of languages, religions and ideologies, technology, wealth, populations, knowledge—effectively eliminate choice. Structural transformations recon‹gure the incentives that actors face, making the rational choice 10
Arguments about Immigrants
11
obvious, obvious at any rate over time to most people. Moreover, the momentum of broad changes is such that no one decision, or even series of decisions, will have much of an impact. Ignoring arguments makes sense as well when consensus, rather than necessity, has made discussion super›uous. This can be the case in studies of implementation or of instrumental rationality.1 If a group (or person) agrees on goals and on how to achieve them, the issue left is whether experience proved those expectations right. The systematic gaps between what a person or organization ought to do and what is actually done can then be described in terms of bureaucratic routine, or incomplete information, or misperception, or stupidity. In both types of case, arguments are irrelevant because goals—preferences—are clear, and what counts as a good reason for doing something is also clear. Much, however, lies between the extremes of necessity and instrumentality.2 Politics often, maybe usually, involves competition to de‹ne social goals, and necessity is more often a rhetorical device than a reality. How argumentation works in democratic politics has not been systematically investigated. One reason is that many policies do result from horse-trading, and powerful analytical techniques such as game theory can explain quite a variety of political outcomes. It has therefore been easy to neglect classes of problems that lie outside this set. Additionally, a long tradition of thought, from Machiavellians to Marxists, insists that material interest (presumably known and measurable) drives political struggle; by corollary, reasons contestants express are nothing more than a smoke screen (though whom they could fool, if everyone operated this way, is never made clear). Arguments are, in this view, post hoc rationalizations for an outcome effected by power, for power. Often this view is attacked on normative grounds as cynical, a charge that has not been particularly productive. Here, the view is criticized on empirical grounds. Many political problems do not correspond to the material interest model. The dynamics of argumentation provide a better explanation for the process and its result. American immigration politics have consistently been of this type. In an argument, a position is backed by a reason. Importantly, the reason refers to something other than simply the person offering it. For example, a missile is considered better when it is more accurate. Accuracy is a value the arguer holds, but it is also a value that the arguer thinks is independent of his own preferences. It is a shared value, social as well as personal, and hence more than a preference. In a completely material bargaining situation, what persuades are not reasons but resources: I want this missile. Whether you acquiesce depends on whether you want it independently, whether I can force you to agree to it, or whether I have enough wealth to buy your consent. In any case, the position is backed by power.
12
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
This cannot reside in anyone other than the person holding it. “If we term those considerations on which a person acts motives and those which may be used in interpersonal communication reasons,” says Giandomenico Majone, “then we may say that not all motives need be reasons and that not all reasons function as motives.”3 This simple distinction—arguments are backed by common or shared values while bargaining positions are backed by individual resources—has huge implications for the results of policy disputes, as well as their dynamics. Reasons, unlike resources, can be seized by an opponent and used for his or her purposes. Reasons are powerful because they refer to common values, but this also makes them vulnerable to capture. If I base my argument for one missile on its accuracy, I make myself vulnerable to an opponent’s ability to demonstrate the superior accuracy of his or her missile. If I had simply held that I wanted the missile because I wanted it, and I was powerful, the opponent could not have used my position to bene‹t his or her side. It would make no sense for the opponent to claim that I was wrong about my own preferences. Reasons that one side provides become a common resource. Fights over reasons can make reasons more important than the result to which they are initially attached. In this way, reasons can lead toward a result that was not anticipated and that lies beyond the terrain over which the sides were initially ‹ghting. This explains how the result of an argument between A and C can result not in B, nor in anything else between A and C, but instead in Q (or π or something equally odd). The person who introduces justi‹cation into debate gambles not only that his or her reasons will prevail, but that those reasons will lead to the preferred policy and not be seen to support something else entirely. This is a risk that legislative contestants often must take, but that they often lose. Debates are often about social values, and so they often involve argumentation like this. The deliberative ideal is normatively and institutionally central to democratic political systems. Theorists of democracy, most prominently John Dewey, have argued that extensive debate educates citizens about their own values, even as it informs representatives of their constituents’ wishes.4 Dictatorial as well as democratic systems can value argumentation as a means to an end. By helping to integrate new information and opposing viewpoints into a picture of what is at stake and what can be done, broad discussion promotes prudence; for this reason, institutions from government bureaucracies to private ‹rms periodically attempt to encourage dissent. Yet, as Talcott Parsons argues, “Rational action, in the sense of action guided by valid knowledge, is at the same time action which is normatively oriented.”5 Arguments help to determine what is best to do, unless reason has little to do with decisions.
Arguments about Immigrants
13
There are two ways to resolve such disagreements over principle, one more like straight bargaining than like argumentation. Both show up in the politics surrounding American immigration control. One is procedural. If a majority of people take one side, it wins. If there is a tie, two philosophically incommensurate principles can coexist in practice. For example, a ‹ght between one group devoted to barring all immigration on the grounds that immigration destroyed community, and another group bent on eliminating national boundaries because they are arbitrary and hence unethical could compromise: an annual ceiling of, say, 150,000. Democracy provides a handy way to quantify, and thus speedily resolve, disputes about irreconcilable values. The other way to resolve disagreements is substantive and involves reframing the issue. Different principles attract, or require, different levels and types of support. If a dispute becomes “really about” one principle, participants will face pressure to support it. If settling land is in the national interest, those opposed to allowing immigrant settlers will have to provide an alternative way to serve the same national interest—keeping out rivals for land—or capitulate. Legislative and public struggles over immigration policy have taken both forms, but have been dominated by arguments about how to frame the national and public interests. In each era, immigration policy became “really about” a value seen to be newly primary. Through argument, one value emerged as central to the public interest, and immigration policy was redesigned to support it, in a way not predictable at the start of the debates. Before an argument can be determined to be in the public interest or not, or even to qualify as a “public interest type of argument,” it minimally has to be an argument, to contain a statement of cause and effect. This simple point is made (and then simple extensions detailed) because interest-based arguments imply that appeals to others are irrelevant, since the calculus of power alone decides who will prevail. The fact that an actor wants an outcome is suf‹cient argument, or rather, the force at that actor’s disposal alone decides how “persuasive” the argument is. But this only characterizes situations where reasons no longer matter, as when people ‹nally cast their ballots or troops head to the front. Before that point, when the action that the group will take is uncertain because the choices that people will make are still uncertain, arguments intervene to tilt the outcome in one direction. They do not replace calculations of interests; rather, they qualitatively affect the way that actors de‹ne or interpret their interests. One can do this by rede‹ning the nature of a situation, reorienting people by changing the way they locate themselves.6 For example, voters choose differently when the same referendum is “really about” taxes than
14
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
when it is “really about” recycling; the American public supported the Vietnam War when it was about containing communism and opposed it when it was about defeating nationalism. Reinterpreting a situation rede‹nes the sides in a con›ict and can affect choice by placing people on a side they do not want to be on. One can also change the way that actors de‹ne their interests by demonstrating the unintended consequences of a policy they advocate.7 For example, an advocate of sending food to famine victims might reverse his or her position if it were demonstrated that this would ›ood local markets with free products, discourage local farming, and result in even less food in the future. The value—helping victims—is upheld, but is more strongly attached to a new policy. In order to have a chance at persuading, an argument has to cite an effect that could realistically result from an action. For those arguments about the effects of an invasion to be plausible, the speci‹c consequences listed have to be reasonable expectations. What people see as reasonable depends at any point in time on their ideas about causation. Conceptual maps not only place an individual in a particular context, but also explain how that environment works.8 “Except in its crudest form,” argues Kathryn Sikkink, “the comprehension and formulation of facts and interests implies the existence of a conceptual apparatus [that helps] people grasp, formulate, and communicate social realities.”9 Plausible mechanisms of cause and effect that prevail at one time, or within one group, can be considered bizarre at another time. The convictions that witchcraft causes misfortune, that bloodletting cures disease, and that night air causes sickness are all arguments about cause and effect that have since been rejected, although for a long time each was plausible to a great number of people. Giandomenico Majone contends that “since policies exist for some time, their political support must be constantly renewed and new arguments are constantly needed to give the different policy components the greatest possible internal coherence and the closest ‹t to an everchanging environment.”10 Positions that succeed are held by those able to control the direction that an argument takes as it develops in a public arena, as well as to connect the argument convincingly to notions of the public interest.
Public Interest
The dynamics of justi‹cation can propel debate along a path. But not all paths are available; the requirement that policy be justi‹ed as in the public interest also limits debate. To be heard seriously, policies have to plausibly further the public interest, that which all members of a society share by
Arguments about Immigrants
15
de‹nition: “those interests which people have in common qua members of the public.”11 C. W. Casinelli elaborates the de‹nition: The public interest applies to every member of the political community; it is a value to be distinguished from something advantageous to one person and disadvantageous to another. . . . To say that an action is in the public interest is to judge it consistent with a political situation that is bene‹cial to everyone, if not immediately at least in the long run, and whether or not everyone realizes it.12 The distinction between the private and public interests of individuals is illustrated by the possibility that a regulatory or licensing policy is against one’s interest as an aspiring architect but is in one’s interest as a member of the public, or that conservation is in one’s interest as a member of the public although it might be to no living person’s material bene‹t. As members of the public, people have an interest in common taxation or traf‹c policies, though as wage earners or speeders they might not want them. The public interest can be conceived of as an end or as a means, as an interest in a speci‹c outcome or an interest in following certain decisionmaking procedures, whatever end is reached. When social goals are agreed on, the question of what is in the public interest is settled, so debate can focus on how to achieve it.13 Some means are more ef‹cient, less expensive, more fair. In the United States, supporters and opponents of af‹rmative action both argue in terms of equality, supporters and opponents of nuclear weapons both argue in terms of prudence and morality, and supporters and opponents of foreign aid both argue in terms of duty to the foreign poor. When social goals are in dispute or appear to be in con›ict with each other as often happens, discussion revolves around the content of the public interest. Is freedom of speech more or less important than freedom from hate speech? Is safety more important than ef‹ciency? Framing an issue in terms of the public interest is not suf‹cient to win, but it is necessary if one is to have a chance at winning. To win, one must persuade others that a policy is in their interest as members of the public. The policy can be in everyone’s private interest or no one’s; whether private interests are also served is irrelevant, though whether private interests are instead served is crucial. As Friedrich Kratochwil argues, public interest claims have to be universalizable, consider consequences, and serve community values.14 Claimants phrase their arguments in these terms, while detractors either argue for competing public values or contend that the public interest is a thin disguise for private interests. For example, one might argue that building a highway through a
16
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
wilderness area is in the public interest because it would help communications and commerce and give more people access to the wild. This is a formally proper public interest argument; to succeed, it would have to convince others that the value of increased mobility was more important than that of, say, preserving this wilderness. It would also have to persuade others that society would bene‹t, that its values would be furthered, rather than that private interests would win at the public’s expense. That some companies or individuals would bene‹t is to be expected; that the bene‹ts would be unequally realized is also to be expected. Neither example of private gain undermines the public interest claim. That interested parties are motivated to argue for a policy in public interest terms has no effect on whether the policy is in the public interest. In fact, as much as possible public and private interests should coincide. What would undermine a public interest claim is the demonstration that private interests achieve their ends at the public’s expense. For example, the highway might increase only one ‹rm’s pro‹ts but result in higher taxes for all and thereby reduce trade and employment. To be heard, a public interest argument must plausibly further community values. To be thwarted, it must be shown either to fail—to be particular rather than universal, to have harmful consequences, and so on—that is, to serve private interest at public expense—or to succeed while harming a competing public value. Each public or legislative debate about social goals is choreographed using a different combination of these same dance steps. A policy is shown to be universalizable and to further public values. One set of detractors seeks to demonstrate that it harms a competing and more important public value. A second set claims that the policy serves a private interest, hinting or showing that private values would succeed at a greater expense to public values. John Kingdon argues that “the proposals that survive to the status of serious consideration meet several criteria, including their technical feasibility, their ‹t with dominant values and the current national mood, their budgetary workability, and the political support or opposition they might experience.”15 This dynamic restricts and propels debate whether or not every (or indeed any) participant truly believes what he or she argues. Everyone in a public debate has to argue in terms of the public interest; even materialists have to be this type of hypocrite, have to argue this way whether they believe it or not. The resulting policy will be the same whether its proponents were sincere in the reasons they gave or not. Hypocrisy matters, moreover, only when it makes a difference whether an individual’s motives match his or her public justi‹cations. Choosing hypocrisy is only rational when one lies about values (reasons, not
Arguments about Immigrants
17
motives) that others share. Whether a given legislator is motivated by the values the public holds is immaterial; the arguments made speak to what the public believes or is thought to believe to be the social good (if not necessarily revealing what any single member of that public believes). The idea of the public interest shapes social policy. It structures how positions are de‹ned, places limits on the range of possible results, and affects how alternative outcomes are judged. Indeed it in›uences the way that claims are originally made and even conceived, as well as how competing claims are weighed or integrated. By allowing only some types of justi‹cation, public interest requirements weed out some possibilities and thereby help to determine which ‹nal decision will be taken. Within these limits, whether a speci‹c policy will be chosen depends on whether its advocates can control the dynamics of argumentation.
Arguments about Exclusion
“Whose interests ought to be taken into account?” is an ethical as well as political question. It should therefore be no surprise that the answers people give when questioned about immigrants will be, in a sense, ethical answers.16 Different ethical outlooks can lead to and justify different types of foreign policies. Legislators and citizens reach many of the same endpoints as those that international relations theories predict—exclusion, openness, selection by domestic similarities or geostrategic criteria—by debating ethically distinct positions. Such positions constrain arguments in much the same way that institutions constrain the political process. Argument types have a logic and dynamic that can in this way act as institutions. How people describe con›icts of value and interest regarding immigration depends on who is thought to have a legitimate interest and why it is thought legitimate. Ethical egoism is the perspective that one’s primary and sole obligation is to oneself. This is a moral position about obligations, but is not, strictly speaking, an ethical theory since it can provide no way to decide con›icts of interest.17 When claims compete, no principle intervenes to decide. What an egoist means to be persuasive about “I want something” is the “I.” “The Egoist is the man who holds that a tendency to promote his own interest is the sole possible, and suf‹cient, justi‹cation of all his actions”; alternately, “egoism holds that each individual’s reasons for acting and possible motivations for acting, must arise from his own interests and desires, however those interests may be de‹ned.”18 Attempts to defend egoism have relied on the notions that one has obligations to oneself, that
18
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
these are one’s highest obligations, and that in fact even if one tried to help others one would not do well because another’s true interests are unknowable. These can be extended to the duties of groups. National self-interest is understood to mean a state of affairs valued solely for its bene‹ts to the nation. The motive of national egoism, which leads men to seek this end, is marked by the disposition to concern oneself solely with the welfare of one’s own nation; it is self-love transferred to the national group.19 Realist arguments share the idea that the state should be given primacy of place in any con›ict of interest. Principled talk in world politics is, in this view, frivolous, and frivolity invites deception and attack. Henry Kissinger argues this. But the emphasis on principle has also produced a characteristic American ambivalence. Relations with a world of nations falling short of our ideal has always presented us with dilemmas. As a people, we have oscillated between insistence on our uniqueness and the quest for broad acceptance of our values, between trying to in›uence international developments and seeking to isolate ourselves from them, between expecting too much of our power and being ashamed of it, between optimistic exuberance and frustration with the constraints practicality imposes.20 If realism/egoism is accepted more widely in world politics than in civil society, this might be due to people’s perception of greater danger and higher stakes. Impending threats make arguments about the nature of the society one is defending super›uous. If immigrants are invaders, then little more need be said to those bent on protecting the state’s integrity. David Hendrickson argues, “There are instances in human history when the migration of peoples seems indistinguishable in its effects from conquest by an invading army.”21 Immigration can be even more dangerous than military invasion because it is less obvious and thus more insidious. A corollary to this view suggests sending emigrants to undermine enemies’ societies. Communitarian ideas also infuse justi‹cations by realists and are probably the most powerful and widespread of the reasons people give for believing that the government should always protect, preserve, or defend the country from foreigners.22 Not all realists are communitarians, or vice versa, but their arguments become fused especially in immigration debates because the issue is defending a particular, bounded, valued community.
Arguments about Immigrants
19
The community and its unique way of life, goes the basic argument, have an intrinsic value that the state must at all costs preserve. David Hendrickson, for example, contends, “The preservation of the state’s security, well-being and institutional integrity is the condition for the realization of other values, without which no civilized existence is possible at all.”23 A we-feeling of some sort is necessary both as a component of individual identities and as a justi‹cation for state institutions’ legitimacy. When this culture coincides with state boundaries, it cements them by providing “a common identity that grounds citizenship.”24 E. H. Carr speculates about the connection. The good of the state comes more easily to be regarded as a moral end in itself. If we are asked to die for our country, we must at least be allowed to believe that our country’s good is the most important thing in the world. The state thus comes to be regarded as having a right of self-preservation which overrides moral obligation.25 A way of life has an intrinsic value, so cultural pluralism at the global level, if not at the domestic, also ought to be valued for its own sake. Michael Walzer applies the communitarian position to the issue of immigration, or (as he puts it) membership. “Men and women do indeed have rights beyond life and liberty, but these do not follow from our common humanity; they are local and particular in character”; therefore, “the restraint of entry serves to defend the liberty and welfare, the politics and culture of a group of people committed to one another and to their common life.” This enables people to choose “in accordance with our understanding of what membership means in our community and of what sort of community we want to have,” whatever that meaning is, for “the distribution of membership is not pervasively subject to the constraints of justice.”26 Walzer draws on a long tradition. For Rousseau and Montesquieu, “consent must be mutual, and members of an existing community could properly refuse consent to membership of those who would disrupt their necessary homogeneity.”27 The state’s highest duty is to protect and preserve this community in (homogeneous) character as well as in minimal material fact. In 1787, Thomas Jefferson worried that emigrants from absolutist Europe would act with “unbounded licentiousness, passing, as is usual, from one extreme to another” and “infuse into” legislation “their spirit, warp and bias its direction, and render it a heterogeneous, incoherent, distracted mass.”28 Consequences for the political community decide how many, and which, immigrants are admissible. A third ethical position that can lead to a “realist” outcome draws on utilitarian arguments. The world threatens all, but it has a greater chance
20
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
of succeeding against liberal states because their democratic nature means that they can be “undermined from within.” Frederick Whelan characterizes one standard American argument as follows: In these circumstances, the citizens of liberal regimes must be on their guard; the preservation of liberal institutions where they exist must be the ‹rst priority, even if this means restricting some of the operations that liberal principles could have in a more ideal world. Liberal regimes must not only withstand aggression or deliberate subversion, on the part of competing types of regimes (such as monarchical ones) abroad; they must also avoid being “swamped” by immigrants in such numbers or at such a rate that the new residents cannot be assimilated into the liberal system, with the consequence that it is undermined from within.29 In this view, liberal institutions’ accessibility means that they are easily used by enemies. There is a ‹nal reason to advocate realist utilitarian understanding of the social good. Leaders’ duties are to work toward something like Pareto optimality, maximizing the good by promoting average happiness— within the borders. This imposes an unshirkable duty on a leader: “The individual may say to himself: ‘Fiat justitia, pereat mundus (Let justice be done, even if the world perish),’ but the state has no right to say so in the name of those who are in its care.”30 What distinguishes this use of utilitarian thought as realist in foreign policy is its insistence that the collective’s (state’s) interests should be de‹ned solely with reference to citizens’ interests—without reference to interests or (putative) rights of outsiders— however individual citizens de‹ne those interests; exclusion never need be justi‹ed with reference to the excluded. Notions of the social good get attached because how the (technical) exclusion question is answered in a particular instance depends on this calculus. If one believes that a state’s primary obligation, its justi‹cation for existing at all, is to preserve and promote a given community in the face of external encroachment, what one values about the borders it protects is what those divisions make possible: existence, or some civilized existence, or a uniquely civilized existence. Citizens live inside those borders; resources live outside, and that is how it should be. Immigration is judged in terms of its consequences for the state as sovereign. Almost every argument favoring or opposing immigration draws on this view or on its major competitors, a universalist egalitarianism or an internationalist particularism. Because liberal theories draw on ideas of individual liberty, equality, or rights, they can lead just as easily to an argument against state bound-
Arguments about Immigrants
21
aries as to one in favor of them: these principles do not require boundaries, so boundaries should not be respected, though they should be acknowledged as facts. “If the ‘veil of ignorance’ approach to questions of social justice was an attempt to eliminate morally arbitrary factors from judgments about the justice of particular social arrangements, there could be nothing more arbitrary than the wealth of the society in which one happened to have been born.”31 The other six billion people in the world ought to be considered unless reasons are given otherwise. In the Kantian view, people have rights conferred on them by nature, God, or reason, so national borders are irrelevant to our respect for those rights. Rights-based ideas of obligation do not necessarily require people or governments to allow as just all claims of right. Even Kant makes this distinction: It is not a question of hospitality but of right. Hospitality means the right of a stranger not to be treated as an enemy when he arrives in the land of another. One may refuse to receive him when this can be done without causing his destruction; but, so long as he peacefully occupies his place, one may not treat him with hostility. It is not the right to be a permanent visitor that one may demand.32 Kant argues that the right to sojourn derives from one’s inhabitancy of Earth and should be recognized generously because of its consequences: wanderers help to establish peaceful relations among people through which “the human race can gradually be brought closer and closer to a constitution establishing world citizenship.” Kant demands that we consider travel a most basic right and thus acknowledge it in practice, but he does not demand that we recognize as a right someone’s desire to enter a territory and stay. In addition, the Doctrine of Double Effect, that one may knowingly act in a way that will produce an impermissible outcome if that evil is minimized and is not one’s real, disguised aim, underlies the view that a state must admit those who will die if excluded, regardless of the consequences for itself, but may (and should) consider consequences for its own interests when doing so will not result in evil. Because of who they are, boat people must be admitted, in this view, but foreign medical graduates need not be. To act otherwise, in this view, is wrongly to defend privilege. Roger Nett argues that rights aim at some kind of initial equality in human transactions so that people may not be categorically disadvantaged; so that, for example, the subjugation of others may not be too easy for the situa-
22
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
tionally fortunate. . . . If we can justify any basic human right, freedom of movement is probably in that category.33 To discriminate among individuals one needs good reasons, and birthplace is just not a good reason. Borders turn rich states into laager states defending arbitrary privilege. Boundaries serve only discriminatory purposes; to pretend otherwise is to be a hypocrite. If boundaries are unjusti‹able, so are immigration restriction and selection. Utilitarians, on the other hand, universalize or self-minimize for very different reasons. Individuals have interests (not rights), and to maximize the good is to promote the average interest. Strategies are judged in terms of their consequences for the (equal) interests of all affected. In John Stuart Mill’s formulation, “the happiness which forms the utilitarian standard of what is right in conduct, is not the agent’s own happiness, but that of all concerned. As between his own happiness and that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator.”34 Utilitarians focus on consequences for themselves and others, to honor human equality. Whether a utilitarian will suggest admitting or excluding foreigners depends on how the interest-maximizing calculus comes out. Locke, for example, contended that admitting people would be generally good: the more people, the more productive labor. Locke “says that ‘I have sometimes heard it objected that they eat the bread out of our own people’s mouths,’ but then turns this into an indictment of those who wish to be protected from competition.”35 One can, though, imagine an economy (of declining returns) in which admissions (more labor) would reduce the good of the already present and of the admitted; exclusion would then be correct. What distinguishes this use of utilitarian thought as idealist is its presumption in favor of including in its calculus the interests of all concerned regardless of national boundaries. Idealists do not always go this far. How extensive our obligations to others are depends on the limits we place on their interests or rights, or the way we de‹ne those interests or rights to indicate the circumstances under which they need not be consulted. The most extreme universalist views depend on people accepting that distance does not matter.36 A liberal understanding can also lead to a view of obligations lying between the full negative and positive of the realist and universalist views. If obligation follows action, in this view, international practices that multiply connections also establish patterns of obligation. If one creates disaster, one is obliged to right it. The French, in this view, have one type of obligation to Algerians because of what France did to Algeria; another to Ivoriens because of what France did to the Côte d’Ivoire. Since obligations
Arguments about Immigrants
23
are determined by patterns of interaction, as interactions become more extensive and similar, so do obligations: If evidence of global economic and political interdependence shows the existence of a global scheme of social cooperation, we should not view national boundaries as having fundamental moral signi‹cance. Since boundaries are not coextensive with the scope of social cooperation, they do not mark the limits of social obligations.37 Interdependence is not, however, even and spontaneous, nor does it arise from a harmony of interests. In this view, people and countries owe and are owed by those they have harmed or helped in the past or those to whom they have extended promises. In this view, acts and promises have their own weight. A realist, for example, might think that acts such as breaking an alliance, unilaterally disengaging from an exchange rate mechanism, or failing to provide air cover to those whose invasion one has encouraged are bad because they reduce one’s power by damaging one’s credibility. A particularist would be more inclined to consider them bad in themselves, that is, would do so even if it could be known that the power bene‹ts outweighed the costs. As states and people have become more enmeshed, the particular has come to be more general; each country’s particular set of relationships, and hence of obligations, grows more to resemble that of other states. The broadest consensus on obligation arises in response to direct harm, for example, “if we caused a people to emigrate by actively eliminating their alternatives, then we are bound to admit them.” Less consensus surrounds obligations in response to the indirect effects of one’s actions, whether one has obligations to those emigrating as the eventual result of a process that one set in motion, either because the indirectness reduces responsibility or because even a real responsibility can be ful‹lled more effectively in other ways than accepting immigrants. Finally, if no special national obligations have been incurred, then the language of public debate can shift from national interest at the national level to social- or individual-level arguments about the public interest. Britain might not have obligations toward Peru, but many British might listen sympathetically to a few of their compatriots argue that they have attachments to some Peruvians that obligate Britain to act on their behalf. Others might be separately obliged because of their particular connections to you to aid your realization of your particular af‹liations. If one believes that people and communities create obligations whose principled ful‹llment can be validated by practice, one’s evaluation of state boundaries will be situation-speci‹c. They are good when they create
24
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
valued connections, bad when they deny them. Immigration is judged in terms of its consequences for ful‹lling or damaging those values that one has acquired.
Arguments about Immigrants
As a topic of public debate, immigration policy belongs to a unique, limited class. Defense policy, immigration policy, and policy regarding territorial boundaries or property ownership all concern not just what the state does, but what constitutes it. Defense policy and rules about who may own land and infrastructure assure a country’s territorial integrity. Defense policy has traditionally been concerned with maintaining territorial boundaries, while policy toward foreign ownership decides whether those boundaries will distinguish the state from others in material terms. Immigration policy also determines boundaries, in this case those separating citizens from noncitizens. Because it does this, immigration policy is a foreign policy and hence raises questions about the national interest. Both defense and immigration policies also affect all citizens equally in theory, but their implementation can hurt or bene‹t some groups more than others, as, for example, when defense spending or “investor immigrants” head to one region and silos or emergency refugees to another. Because some citizens gain and some lose, immigration and defense policies can be debated in terms of the public as well as the national interest; the justice of their domestic consequences can be reason to accept or reject them. Each also changes as the world beyond the borders changes. They differ in that immigration policy creates borders while defense policy protects them. In non- or postimperial states, territorial limits exist separately from a given defense policy, but the line separating citizens from noncitizens does not exist separately from the prevailing immigration policy. For this reason, regardless of how narrow the topic ostensibly under debate, the issue of how to justify national divisions always lurks in arguments about immigrants, and even small alterations in immigration policy change the group whose interests are to be served by such policies. In its most stylized form, policy justi‹cation proceeds by connecting an argument about a problem’s causes and an argument about its solutions to an argument about the public interest. Figure 1 illustrates the logic of their connections. John Kingdon notes that crises, political processes, or periodic reviews of accumulated knowledge can place a problem on the national agenda.38 In the case of foreign policies, whose justi‹cation requires an argument about the relation between one country and others, agenda-setting should be more crisis-driven, more responsive to the events
Arguments about Immigrants
25
External Change (Crisis of Context) ⇓ Causal Argument
Public Interest Argument
Policy Argument
Implementation
[X does/not produce Y]
[Y is/not in PI because]
[H should/not produce Y]
[H did/not produce Y]
X1 ⇒ Y1
Y1 ≠ PI
X2 ⇒ Y2
Y2 ⇒ PI
Policy A ⇒ Y2 & Y4
Policy A ⇒ Y2 & Y4
X3 ⇒ Y2
Y2 ⇒ PI
Policy B ⇒ Y2
Policy A ⇒ Y2 & Y4
X4 ⇒ Y4
Y4 ⇒ PI
Policy C ⇒ Y4 ↑ ↑ Efficiency
↑ ↑ Plausibility ↑
Ideas about Causation Perverse Effects Fig. 1.
↓
Justifying policy change
and processes beyond its borders that concern a country but over which it has little control. For this reason, ‹gure 1 includes crises of context as the dominant impetus to public debate on immigration policy. The rows in ‹gure 1 correspond to arguments. They show the way that causal arguments become linked to further arguments about whether the effect is, or is not, in the public interest, and whether policy should, or should not, seek to produce (or prevent) that effect. The ‹rst row displays the causal argument that “X causes Y,” which is then connected to a secondary argument that “Y is not in the public interest.” Depending on the nature of Y (the effect), one might argue further that public policy should ignore Y, or should seek to prevent Y. An example of the ‹rst would be “the shopping mall (X) causes smaller stores to shut down (Y)”; this is not in the public interest, either because the public should have no interest in which businesses survive in the marketplace (policy should ignore Y) or because the public has an af‹rmative interest in keeping small businesses open (policy should seek to prevent Y). The following rows illustrate similar arguments, this time linking the causes they cite positively to the public interest. These are in turn connected to arguments that speci‹c policies will create these desired effects or (at a later stage) that the policies have been implemented properly (or improperly). The second and third rows each represent arguments about how to achieve the same effect (Y2), while the
26
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
fourth row shows an argument about how to achieve a different effect (Y4). Each of these, it is argued, is in the public interest. After that process has selected the types of arguments that can be debated seriously, discussion turns to questions of ef‹ciency. Given that an effect is plausibly produced by a given cause and is in the public interest, how might it be produced most ef‹ciently? At this stage, discussion shifts toward consideration of a policy’s mechanics rather than its justi‹cation. Figure 1 outlines the skeleton of the policy process in a way that is applicable to debates that are quantitative and result in a middling compromise as well as to those that are qualitative and transformative. This schematic rendering implies an orderliness not present in public argumentation, but it clari‹es the connections that must be made in any public interest argument. It also highlights the points at which different standards come into play. Actual debates do not, of course, proceed from one box to the next; rather, they seem to be constructed piecemeal until they contain all that is required in some form, then to be re‹ned.39 An example will illustrate how the demands that this format makes on arguments in›uence those arguments and thus help to shape outcomes. Figure 2 presents a very simpli‹ed version of three arguments presented for and against immigration policy reform in the 1920s. In order to persuade legislators that a policy would solve a problem, individuals and representatives had to argue that (1) there was a problem, (2) it was a public interest problem rather than a private problem, and (3) its causes were both knowable and manipulable.40 They did this by linking an argument about a problem’s cause and an argument about its solution to values that were clearly in the public interest. In the early 1920s, for example, several arguments about the cause of social problems were considered true, proven by science or history or right reason. Each became linked to speci‹c public interest values. The claim that each civilization was a product of its founding race, and to endure could only be used by that race, seemed to many not only plausible but scienti‹cally demonstrable.41 The joint congressional immigration subcommittees retained a eugenicist; almost the entire biological faculties of the major American universities wrote joint letters urging Congress to attend to his and other scientists’ ‹ndings, and President Coolidge spoke in favor of this research pursuit. In this setting, opponents such as social reformer Jane Addams appeared to Congress to be stubbornly closing their eyes to scienti‹c evidence they did not wish to believe. What, asked Congress, should it believe: eminent American scientists who could demonstrate their ‹ndings, or nonscientists like Addams who were “morally certain” the scientists were wrong? Preserving and nurturing civil society made citizenship possible. Without it, the country would slide
Arguments about Immigrants
27
Russo-Japanese War World War I ⇓ Causal Argument
Public Interest Argument
Discriminating among citizens destroys democracy
Democracy must be preserved to guarantee a civic culture
We must avoid denying only some citizens' coethnics entrance
Heterogeneity causes civil and international war by creating an incoherent society
Preventing war is in the public interest because democracy is impossible without order and peace
Allowing in immigrants racially like Americans prevents war and preserves civilization
Class rifts cause civil war by stirring up hatred and inviting Bolsheviks to interfere in domestic affairs
Preventing war is in the public interest because democracy is impossible without order and peace
Banning unions will prevent civil war
Only “the white race” produced a civilization
Democracy depends on the ability to be self-governing
Allowing only whites to immigrate will preserve civilization
↑
↑ plausibility
Policy Argument
Implementation
(Since there was no policy in place, no arguments about implementation failures were made in this early period)
↑ ↑ efficiency
↑
↓ Ideas about Causation: Racism Causes War Perverse Effects: War with Japan, Depression Fig. 2.
Arguments of the 1920s
into a miserable Hobbesian lawlessness. Because citizens were created by both order and Anglo-American laws, maintaining them was in the public interest. As well-established as the belief in eugenics was the conviction that cultural and racial diversity caused war. Many Americans at the turn of the century viewed the Civil War as the regrettable result of having allowed African and European descendants to mix in one country. The Civil War, in this view, sundered the natural bonds that whites shared, giving them different interests that led them into war. Europe provided a more powerful example. Every time Europeans bumped into each other,
28
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
they started wars. Half the time they tried to drag Americans into the con›ict; all the time the wars produced refugees who streamed from rural areas to Ellis Island. Americans wanted both to avoid helping Europe and to avoid becoming like Europe. Since the wars sparked on ethnic fault lines, to many Americans the logical preventive was ethnic homogeneity. As the most fundamental components of the public interest, preserving peace and life clearly ought to motivate the government. Leading in an opposite direction were the teachings of liberal philosophers and economists, whose ideas had become the foundation for American institutions and founding myths. The free ›ow of goods and labor bene‹ted all; only the most irrational would interfere with the market, because in doing so they harmed themselves. Liberals were supposed to value tolerance; if this were not suf‹cient, liberal institutions were designed to balance competing interests so that only good would come of their competition. Above all, democracy was premised upon equality among citizens. Discriminating among them by allowing some citizens’ coethnics preferred entrance would create second-class citizens and ultimately gut the liberal values that had been deduced from natural law and that it was government’s duty to uphold. The arguments that civilizations blossomed from particular races, that diversity sparked war, and that inequality would destroy civil society did not lead anywhere until they were linked successfully with arguments about how these consequences hurt or aided interests that all American citizens shared. War is always, of course, a concern, but in the early 1920s it was a particularly salient one, whose power was linked to the fear that natural selection could destroy the United States and that the country’s recent wars were evidence of this. Democracy and liberalism were good, but goodness did not guarantee survival, only toughness did. Halting immigration did violate maxims entrenched in American institutions and liberal ethics: it was ungenerous and economically irrational, it distinguished among people by birthplace rather than by merit, and it represented a mean-spirited turning-away of those who, like the Pilgrims, sought refuge from persecution. It also ran contrary to the interests of ‹rms, families, scienti‹c institutes, missions, and other organizations, such as universities, whose clientele and work regularly crossed borders. All of these the restrictionists admitted to be true. They argued, and argued successfully, that democracies were especially vulnerable to open borders and that continuing to indulge in a laissez-faire approach was suicidal. Groups presented a variety of reasons for and against immigration restriction. In some cases, the proposals were consistent with each other, but in many cases they were not. Rather than contradicting each other outright, each spoke to a different type of concern and so gave stress to a
Arguments about Immigrants
29
different aspect of restriction than did others. The requirement of a majority (and in the case of immigration policy, usually a majority large enough to override a veto) means that unless one argument clearly dominates, consensus-builders will have to co-opt the arguments of others. In order to get a majority to stand with a policy, that majority will have to be armed with justi‹cations that ring true, that are simultaneously in the private and public interests of constituents. Arguments cannot be added the way that votes can. Consensus-building by its nature transforms the general understanding of why some action is being undertaken. In the case of the early 1920s, the three inconsistent and competing arguments presented above merged into one persuasive enough to carry in the House by ‹ve to one. What was required was a policy that let only whites immigrate, but that did not “disparage the ancestors of millions of our fellow citizens.” A quota system that allocated places based on the proportion of recent immigrants coming from various regions only managed to irritate everyone. It angered the liberals, who argued that capping Slavic immigration, which had been on the increase, sent an anti-Slav message to Americans from Eastern Europe. It annoyed the restrictionists, who believed that freezing quotas at their 1890 levels, when the “new” (dark-skinned, southern) Europeans constituted the majority of immigrants, simply slowed the rate of social collapse. Almost magically, the restrictionists hit on a solution that was not a compromise. (It had been proposed before in hearings but had no legislative takers.) If quotas were assigned to countries according to the proportion of American citizens—not recent immigrants—who could trace their ancestry there, they could not be said to be discriminatory. In fact, the restrictionists argued, to do otherwise was to discriminate against the ancestors of Anglo-Americans. Immigrants, selected in a way consistent with democratic principles, would be from the whitest countries. National origins quotas passed in 1924 and were implemented fully a few years later after the Bureau of the Census ‹nished going through census records from the time of the founding to determine Americans’ national origins. Standards of public argumentation and the requirement of a majority might be expected to sift what could be argued in the ‹rst place and thereby limit the range of arguments within which a compromise would have to be reached. In this case, although the arguments did pass through ‹lters on their way to the ›oor, their fusion produced a policy far more restrictive than any restrictionist had hoped! In this case, a crisis (World War I) made an idea (eugenicists’ claims that ethnic heterogeneity would tear apart the country and eventually cost lives) seem plausible. In the ensuing debate, a proposal that was originally obscure because it was far more reactionary than that of even the most
30
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
conservative critics of immigration policy could be shown neatly to turn liberals’ arguments against them and give restrictionists the victory. The resolution to this debate was anything but a compromise. A perceived crisis in the country’s international position provoked a surge of protectionism that centered on “the nation.” Arguments about the nature of the threat, and hence the nature of the threatened, became enmeshed in immigration policy, codifying in quite practical terms the difference between citizens and noncitizens. This pattern was repeated in each of the subsequent revisions of American immigration policy.
CHAPTER 3
Whether to Exclude
From the founding of the United States through World War I, no numerical ceilings governed immigration to the United States. Immigrants were not recruited, but neither were they capped. States admitted and taxed new arrivals and reaped the bene‹ts of new immigrants’ votes. New arrivals could always head west, wrest land from the Indians, and keep it from the Europeans. The frontier made inattention possible. Indeed, not until 1876, well after the Civil War, did the U.S. Supreme Court decide that the federal government, rather than the separate states, should decide who became a citizen; this complemented the relatively recent Fourteenth Amendment, establishing citizenship by birth on American soil. The federal government after the Civil War consolidated the rights of sovereignty in Washington, DC, removing from the states any prerogatives associated with a national government. Uniform, centralized rules regarding entry to citizenship were at the core of this change. The government had the right to exclude immigrants, but it had no basis for deciding whether it should exercise this right. The ‹rst debates on the topic covered the issue of whether exclusion of immigrants was even justi‹able, that is, whether Americans had any right to refuse entry to someone willing to come to the United States and become a citizen. After this early period, when the right of the country to exclude immigrants had been settled, these arguments were ritually reprised, to reaf‹rm their central points, but subsequent philosophical debate did not add substantially to the points ‹rst raised. Later debates centered on the questions of how many and which immigrants to exclude, not on whether exclusion was itself justi‹able. In this earliest period, however, that basic question had not been settled. Debate on what eventually resulted in the Chinese Exclusion Acts and the Quota Acts therefore developed in two conceptually distinct stages. The ‹rst, covered in this chapter, dealt with the question of exclusion’s legitimacy. The second, discussed in the next, involved the desirability of excluding particular people. That chapter therefore parallels the subsequent ones, for all focus on whom and how and how many, not on whether, to exclude. The question of whether banning someone from a community is 31
32
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
proper at all, or is proper for a democratic and liberal community, raises fundamental political and philosophical questions. Inescapably central is the problem of the extent and limits of social duties. Early arguments both against and in favor of capping immigration therefore drew directly on ethical arguments about individuals’ and societies’ duties to each other. This chapter ‹rst provides a brief overview of the historical context, outlining the history of immigration policy to the late nineteenth century when the topic of restriction found itself ‹rmly on the congressional agenda. The following section discusses in basic terms the ideal-typical ethical positions that underlie the positions articulated in the debates. Following these is an examination of the arguments made for and against imposing a numerical ceiling on immigration to the United States.
Early American Immigration Policy
Immigration up to the turn of the twentieth century was open in fact and principle, in spite of almost two centuries of periodic xenophobia. Not until 1868, with the passage of the Fourteenth Amendment, did the federal government de‹ne American citizenship; not until 1876 did it even claim its constitutional right to override state policies and establish a uniform rule of naturalization. Prior to this time, colonies, then states, pursued whatever course they wished.1 Some offered economic bonuses to settlers; others taxed them heavily to prompt them to move on. Some granted state citizenship instantly; others allowed it after a lengthy and rigorous trial. In spite of these variations, immigration remained numerically unrestricted for Europeans from the earliest colonial days in the 1600s through 1921. Although the American government never recruited immigrants,2 its stance toward immigration was neither accidental nor passive. Continued immigration served the government’s foreign and domestic purposes. The Declaration of Independence accused King George of “endeavor[ing] to prevent the population of these States; for that purpose obstructing the laws for naturalization of foreigners, refusing to pass others to encourage their migration hither, and the conditions for new appropriation of lands.” Homesteading helped to establish infrastructure, to develop the local treasury, to quell slave revolts, and to ‹ght American Indians;3 manifest destiny prevented European settlement. Since demand for immigration was high throughout many decades of this long period, the country had the luxury of getting what it wished without having to enact legislation. During periods of devastation in Europe, immigration soared. The Irish famine and the German revolution (1845–55), the 1880–90 European depression, and the beginning of World War I in 1914 saw the number of
Whether to Exclude
33
applications for admission rise dramatically, while during the American Civil War and economic depressions, immigration fell and was periodically exceeded by emigration. During these relatively rare fallow periods, the urban population on the East Coast pushed its way west. “Unregulated” westward expansion preempted the British, French, and Spanish and laid the groundwork for rebuf‹ng militarily any future claim they might make. American policies favoring immigration were consistent with those of the other mercantile powers of the day: the more wealth and the more people the better.4 At the same time, restrictionist sentiment was rarely dormant. Benjamin Franklin was neither ‹rst nor last to argue that “those who come hither are generally the most stupid of their own nation. . . . Not being used to liberty, they know not how to make a modest use of it. . . . even our government will become precarious.”5 The Alien and Sedition Acts of 1798, the ‹rst federal efforts at central immigration control, sought to exclude both revolutionaries and royalists ›eeing to the United States (and tilting the balance of the national political parties). At midcentury, the anti-immigrant Know-Nothing Party had gained enormous popular support, while nativist organizations rose to prominence with the waves of anti-Catholic and antiradical hysteria. By the late 1800s, they gave way to groups seeking to de‹ne in positive terms what it meant to be a “native American.”6 The Statue of Liberty, the country’s most famous symbol of its openness, was dedicated in 1886, ironically ending the long era of American consensus on immigration’s bene‹ts. America’s ‹rst codi‹cation of immigration policy—the Quota Acts— had its roots in the very late years of the nineteenth century. America had changed economically. Industrialism had altered its work-force requirements, and cycles of industrial depression and panic in 1870, 1907, and, later, in 1921 led many to conclude that the days of plenty had ended; immigrants could only displace Americans. New ideas also wielded a great deal of in›uence. Eugenics and vulgar Darwinism were in vogue, as were new ideas of hygiene and public health. Everywhere people saw scarcity and attendant con›ict. Contemporary events, both domestic and foreign, also in›uenced how people viewed problems and strategies for change. Of most importance, the Chinese Exclusion Acts of 1882 and 1892, sponsored by California’s nativist representatives, brought categorical exclusion into policy for the ‹rst time, while the Spanish-American War, whose result included colonial possessions, prompted a debate over America’s role in the world and potential status as a great imperial power.7 Although the country was becoming isolationist, pan-Americanism infused U.S. policy toward the Western Hemisphere. Meanwhile, congressional jurisdictional ‹ghts with the executive branch led a large faction in Congress to assert
34
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
the fundamentally domestic nature of any topic that Congress (especially the House of Representatives, which lacked authority over treaties) wished to control. In this setting, Congress established the Immigration Commission, usually known as the Dillingham Commission after its chair, to survey the status of laws relating to immigration and to recommend changes. Its forty-two-volume report had two impacts. First, it framed the debate. Its characterization of recent immigrants as poor, illiterate, and racially distinct, in contrast to the “old” immigrants who were entrepreneurs and educated, religious refugees, made exclusion politically possible by salvaging the country’s immigrant past. Second, it did all of the groundwork for a streamlined, comprehensive policy. The ‹rst immigration act, passed in 1917, codi‹ed existing law into a single, omnibus package. Its two signi‹cant innovations were its incorporation of a literacy test, designed to exclude those who were not substantially literate in any language, and its delineation of a single geographic zone, covering most of Asia, from which nonwhite immigration was barred. The literacy test and the Asian barred zone, like the old/new distinction earlier, signaled a massive change in the way people thought about immigration restriction. Debate on this provision foreshadowed that to come with the Quota Acts.
Early Debates
Previously, numerical restrictions on Europeans had been the side effect of policies designed to exclude individuals on the basis of their (presumed) lack of personal merit. Laws barred prostitutes, paupers, vagrants and vagabonds, criminals and polygamists from entry. Literacy, too, was an individual-level restriction and so could be said to be based on a person’s capabilities and acts rather than on his or her ascriptive characteristics. John Burnett argued that the literacy test would select the best people, while ceilings based on country of origin would only cull those “most loosely tied” to their homelands.8 The test’s real purpose, however, was clearly to exclude “undesirables” emigrating from southeast Europe; the test’s proponents did not bother to pretend otherwise. Restrictionists’ two goals were to reduce immigration’s volume and to redirect its sources to draw almost entirely from northwestern Europe wherein lived “Nordics.” Representative Dillingham stated bluntly: We took the nations from which this immigration came so largely, the eastern and southern nations of Europe, and ascertained what the literacy percentage was among the people of those nations. We saw at once that if we adopted the educational test, it would substantially
Whether to Exclude
35
decrease the volume of that stream 30 percent, which was just about what we wanted to accomplish. On the other hand, the educational test would in no way affect England or Scotland or Ireland or the Scandinavian countries or Germany or France.9 The literacy test’s proponents, mainly members of Congress from everywhere but the East Coast and urban centers, were not committed to immigrant education; rather, they wanted the test as a covert means of numerical and racial restriction. Illiteracy, to them, stood as an administratively convenient way to mark racial undesirables. Fairness was not the issue. Social survival was. “No where else is there a better illustration of the axiom that the individual must often suffer that the community may benefit; that there must be temporary individual inconvenience in favor of the general permanent convenience.”10 Its opposition, the executive branch, urban Democrats, and ethnic and religious societies, focused their objections not on the bill’s real purpose, numerical restriction, but on its expressed content, a ban on illiterates. Their objections, therefore, centered on its unfairness to individuals and its damage to how others would see the country: the test did not capture what it claimed, it was unworthy of the country’s past, and its effects would contradict foreign policy goals. Every president from Grover Cleveland to Woodrow Wilson who had a chance vetoed this bill on the grounds that illiteracy did not indicate lack of individual merit.11 Cleveland pointed out that “violence and disorder do not originate with illiterate laborers. They are rather the victims of the educated agitator.”12 Wilson vetoed the measure repeatedly, denouncing it as a test of opportunity rather than of character:13 “A literacy test is not only undesirable, but is unfair, unreasonable, and un-American and violates our time-honored principles that this country shall be a refuge for the oppressed of other lands, an asylum where the persecuted may come and worship their God.”14 “A literacy test,” argued others, “provides for an aristocracy of immigrants, and is therefore discriminatory and un-American.”15 Liberal principle could not stretch as far as the literacy test demanded. Neither could anyone charged with handling the country’s foreign affairs face the charge of hypocrisy. The bill “proposes to reverse the order of history and tradition, destroy the universal belief in America as a haven for the oppressed or those seeking relief from persecution of political or religious views by writing over the portals the inscription, ‘all hope abandon, ye who cannot read.’ (Applause).”16 George Kennan argued that the literacy test “will be even more effective than the existing extradition treaty in enabling the Russian Government to lay its hands on Russian revolutionists who come to us for protection from tyranny.”17 Representatives pointed out that its results would contradict other American foreign poli-
36
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
cies. “The Armenians, amongst whom there has been a massacre in the last eight months unparalleled in civilization . . . are to a large extent illiterate, and the survivor of a butchered Armenian family attempting to come to this country, where he or she would be cared for, would be barred out of it, because under Turkish misrule education has been denied.”18 While restrictionists used the language of competitive interest, drawing on images of self-preservation, and used the language of community instead of that of the individual, their opposition concentrated on principle, drawing on images of niceness. The sides talked past each other. Later debate largely echoed this dynamic. Restrictionists and liberals on the question of Asian immigration did not talk past each other; instead, they fought a head-on war of attrition that the restrictionists won. Congress had renewed the Chinese Exclusion Acts, then had banned Hindus and “oriental coolie labor” in separate acts. The Japanese alone had the dubious privilege of restricting emigration themselves, so that the embarrassment of their exclusion could be avoided. By 1917, all that was required for a comprehensive ban on Asians was to extend the ban outright to the Japanese and to codify all of the laws into a single package.19 The Asian Barred Zone had history, ef‹ciency, and popularity to recommend it. Its opponents concentrated on racial discrimination’s inequity. It is probably fair to say that they convinced none but the already converted. The Barred Zone then became the precedent used to restrict other groups by outlining geographical regions and setting targets for each sector, accomplished later during the Quota Acts. Restrictionist discussions such as these occupied, but did not dominate, the public agenda. Then came World War I. The prevailing image of the international environment as one of violent competition crystallized during World War I. Following the war, many claimed: There has never been a time when we could so well afford to ignore the rest of the world and devote ourselves to building up our own character and independence. . . . The world is in turmoil, and no one can foresee the conditions which will follow the treaty of peace. . . . It will not be a safe or fruitful time to preach or practice world philanthropy when all other nations are battling vehemently for their own interests. Why should we not then study our own interests, set our house in order, raise our standards of civilization, and for a period admit no dilution and cultivate a devotion to our own country?20 This world was cutthroat. “Nations and races have struggled for a place in which to exist and enlarge since before the years covered by human history. We are trying to maintain a place here for us and our children to
Whether to Exclude
37
which the crowded-out, hungry, unhappy millions of the Old World are struggling to come.”21 It was also zero-sum. “I am convinced that what is for the best interest of the United States on this immigration question may be diametrically opposed to the sel‹sh interest of other countries.”22 That war and its aftermath shaped America’s understanding of what sovereignty meant and what immigration restriction meant.23 The country’s new perception of itself as a creature struggling actively for self-preservation in a hostile, competitive world was only reinforced by its experience during World War I.
Arguments about Immigrants On the one hand, you will be told that the basic foundation of Government is practically lodged in four Hebrew words used by the Israelite in his Passover Services, meaning “all who are hungry may come and eat,” and that notwithstanding this ultra wide liberality, the country has grown from 4,000,000 to 110,000,000 population and has become the strongest Nation on the face of the globe. On the other hand, you will be told that all of this may have been true at one time, but now that we have more than 100,000,000 people of our own, we should keep our country to ourselves, for our own native population. Between these two extremes, you will ‹nd almost as many differences of opinion as Mr. Bok has found plans how to prevent war. —Abe Spring24
From 1890 to 1930, debate about immigration concentrated on four broad topics: restriction as a principle of policy, numerical restriction, the restriction of various subgroups, and, ‹nally, the policy intended as a compromise between the “fors” and the “againsts,” the national origins quota system.25 The following section traces arguments about immigration restriction in principle. At issue here are what reasons the policies’ proponents gave for championing them. The process of debating eventually created a consensus on how to describe immigration’s most important issues. This was not the result merely of one side dominating the other, nor was it a matter of compromise on negotiable points. Rather, the ‹nal consensus was new; it re›ected a social interpretation of the country’s goals that was created by the debate. Many in Congress, and many members of the public, saw the country’s recent involvement with Europe and its problems as an ominous sign
38
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
of troubles to come. Immigration from Europe had doubled in a decade, the consequence of changes in passenger shipping and the mail as well as industrial and national upheavals. Global markets’ integration also posed a serious problem. “The time was when the Paci‹c Ocean was a barrier, in a sense a protection,” mourned one. “It is now an avenue of approach.”26 Its solution was not easy. On one hand, the country had a history of immigration; on the other, it feared new immigrants. On one hand, a capitalist country supported trade; on the other hand, an independent country wanted to remain that way. Many believed that prosperity and survival might, tragically, be incompatible; money could only be made at the cost of autonomy—which is exactly what immigration signaled. If that were the choice, legislators declared, their decision was clear. “It is better to have a shortage of labor, if needs be, in our mines and manufactories rather than have that people come in who are not in accord with our ideas and ideals. As some one has said, ‘Better smokeless chimneys than a degenerate people.’”27 Free trade and unrestricted immigration meant giving up control over borders. If self-abnegation were the price, the country would forgo both prosperity and goodwill. Certainly, as a general proposition, increased national production is of vital importance to the whole country, and increased production is of vital importance to your own district. But if increased production of goods could only be secured by reduction of Americanism, by lowering our standards of living, by replacing the English language with a medley of other tongues, by substituting for American communities polyglot colonies where our Constitution and laws are neither respected nor understood, by changing the character of our race— then production is bought at too great a cost. When the cost is in dollars and cents we feel it, but, after all, we can pay it. The other cost we could not pay, for in paying it the American Nation would lose its soul.28 Immigration restriction, declared Samuel Shortridge, might interfere with trade, “but if it did interfere with trade, let it be so. I put man above trade. I put the men and women of America above coupons or bonds. I put the permanent welfare of my country above the temporary pro‹ts of commerce.”29 Added another, “I would rather see American citizenship re‹ned to the last degree in all that makes America what we hope it will be than to develop the resources of America at the expenses of the citizenship of our country.”30 Interdependence not only was a threat to autonomy from other coun-
Whether to Exclude
39
tries, but it also promised social upheaval. “The theory that America is a melting pot becomes absurd in a time when population rolls hither and thither about the globe like particles of quicksilver.” Thomas Busby blamed lagging assimilation and “IWW-ism” on interdependence. Immigrants used to “burn bridges,” he said, because they had no choice. Modern telegraph and radio, fast mails and steamship travel meant that they no longer had to.31 “Wealth has accumulated under the stimulus of oriental labor, but if you go out there now and look for American communities, you will see wasted homes and dismantled dwellings—Wealth accumulates and men decay.”32 One asked, “Is it better to insure perpetuity of our institutions or to have laborers? Which is foremost in your mind—need for laborers, or to save the United States?”33 Another representative answered (if an answer was needed): “By our tariff laws we could preserve and assure to ourselves our own markets, even if we had to surrender our other markets to cheap labor. It is more important to me to Americanize and spiritualize our own population than to extract wealth from other nations.”34 For this reason, the restrictive law “was considered by practically all as a primary step in our after-war reconstruction program.”35 International involvement of any sort would destroy the country. Interdependence speci‹cally threatened sovereignty. At the turn of the twentieth century, the American public viewed the international environment—which meant, in essence, Europe—as hostile but actively dangerous only if engaged on purpose as in the Spanish-American War.36 The danger Europe threatened was that of territorial conquest; Americans did not simply fear competition, they feared conquest and the end of their civilization. What was at risk were the country’s borders, its integrity. What was to be defended was, therefore, its sovereignty. And virtually every legislator speaking for immigration restrictions chose at some point to base his appeal explicitly on American sovereignty. These arguments focused on principle. Sovereignty, in this view, was absolute and basic. If outsiders could claim anything at all, especially the right to enter, the country would no longer be sovereign. Exclusion was, therefore, a sine qua non of sovereignty. Declared legislators again, and again . . . and again: “I would not debate the right of our Nation to exclude immigration. That is the inherent right of every nation, even the weakest on this globe.”37 The U.S. Supreme Court ‹rst articulated this absolutist view of sovereignty in relation to immigrants, and it is this view that is most often quoted and paraphrased by the legislators. When they upheld the exclusion of a twenty‹ve-year-old Japanese woman married to a U.S. citizen, the justices did not argue for exclusion in terms of anything that she had herself done, nor
40
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
did they argue in terms of a public interest, such as wages or public health, or even a national interest, such as defense. Instead, they invoked “sovereignty,” the broadest possible principle. It is an accepted maxim of International Law, that every sovereign nation has the power as inherent in sovereignty, and essential to selfpreservation, to forbid the entrance of foreigners within its dominions, or to admit them only in such cases and upon such conditions as it may see ‹t to prescribe. In the United States, this power is vested in the government to which the Constitution has committed the entire control of international relations, in peace as well as in war. It belongs to the political department of the government, and may be exercised either through treaties made by the President and Senate or through statutes enacted by Congress.38 That the right was inherent meant to the Court that the government’s authority was absolute; that the procedures involved were those of foreign policy meant that the executive and legislature, not the judiciary, controlled admission. The judiciary ruled that nothing Congress did in this entire area of law could ever be unconstitutional; it was unchallengeable. Congress took the leeway that the Supreme Court granted it. Senators and representatives stressed that their right to exclude immigrants was basic and constitutive, and contended that all arguments in favor of allowing, through a standing law, any immigration signaled a willingness to betray the country. This they applied only to immigrants; that is, not to travelers (though to do so was their privilege) but to those who would become citizens.39 Representatives echoed the Court time after time. “In the exercise of our inherent powers of sovereignty we have the undoubted right to prohibit the entrance of any or all immigrants or prescribe the conditions under which they may enter. We also have the undoubted right to expel and deport those who are found undesirable.”40 Congressional discretion meant that “no foreigner or foreign nation has any right in this country except what we give him. It is a matter of privilege and not a matter of right.”41 John Miller of Washington elaborated this theme. The ‹rst and highest exercise of the inherent power of a sovereign state is the right of determination of citizenship. Dependent upon this national attribute is the equal sovereign right of the independent State to say under what condition and in what manner and to what extent nationals of other countries may come and remain and their civil status. These principles are basic. They are powers exercised by nations since national organizations have been known and recognized among
Whether to Exclude
41
the family of mankind. There are theorists, sensationalists, moralists, and romancers who argue patiently, sometimes persuasively, against this national prerogative, calling it by the mild and inoffensive name of ‘policy,’ but none can dispute the principle. National right is one thing; it is fundamental, inherent, and permanent; national policy is quite another. In its broad sense it is the conduct or manner in which the national right is exercised.42 Now, the dignity and honor and stability of our country demand that all other nations of the earth abide by our sovereignty as a Nation.43 In this way, legislators served notice that compromise with the demands or wishes of foreigners, whether presented by a foreign government or by U.S. citizens, was simply impossible—and was impossible in principle, for it meant self-abnegation. Henry Cabot Lodge declared that the question of immigration “is perhaps the greater of fundamental sovereign rights. If a country can not say who shall come into the country, it has ceased to be a sovereign country; it has become a subject country.”44 Sovereignty under siege required defense, and restrictionists viewed their efforts to exclude immigrants as one component of the national defense. “The struggle for self-preservation is not, as many appear to believe, con‹ned to aliens seeking to enter the country, nor to aliens who, having gained lodgement by unfair means, resist all efforts to dislodge them, but is shared by Americans and aliens alike who have a right to be and remain here in unimpaired enjoyment of the blessings which this country has to offer.”45 If immigration continued, the country would cease to be, for its borders would be meaningless and its identity no longer unique: “Our immigration laws are designed primarily for the welfare not only of our citizens but of those aliens who have lawfully taken up residence in our midst. Just as self-preservation is the ‹rst law of nature amongst individuals, so it is amongst nations. Our ‹rst concern, therefore, must be for those who are here; in short, for our own country.”46 The Supreme Court found that To preserve its independence, and give security against foreign aggression and encroachment, is the highest duty of every nation; and to obtain these ends nearly all other considerations are to be subordinated. It matters not in what form such aggression and encroachment come, whether from the foreign nation acting in its national character (as in time of war) or from vast hordes of its people coming in upon us.47
42
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Representatives reiterated this year after year, and the theme never varied. “Self-preservation is the ‹rst law of nature, and if we are to be a distinctive nation, as we always have been, we must act today, now, and not in the years that are to come”;48 “when it [a country] surrenders its will in this respect [immigration control] to the will of some other people or nation or any group of peoples or nations it surrenders its life”;49 “indeed, the right of a nation to perpetuate its existence presupposes the right of that nation to say what foreign peoples shall come into its territory and what shall not.”50 The struggle was the survival of the ‹ttest; selective immigration meant that “the weaklings are weeded out abroad.”51 Each of these statements drew upon the idea that the country could not accomplish anything if immigrants continued to come because it would cease to be a country. The process of immigration was a process of erosion, against which defense was required. Protection sometimes replaced “self-preservation,” although what threat policy was supposed to protect against was unclear. Generally, the implied threat was destruction in the web of foreign entanglements; protection, as a value, applied generally to the country, not only to immigration but to trade and defense as well. “I will say to you,” declared Representative Focht, “that I am a Republican protectionist, a real protectionist. I am not only for a tariff, but I am in favor of protecting American industry and American labor.”52 Europe, generally, was the threat’s source: “It is obligatory for every generation, and particularly upon this, in view of the tremendous conditions prevailing in Europe, to protect the citizenship of this country, to keep up the average standard of citizenship, that this great Republic of ours may rest in safety.”53 Immigrants were like guns or goods. “We exclude defective seeds, defective cattle, and horses, and will not permit shrubbery and other inanimate life to be imported. Can it be that this and future generations of Americans are less important?”54 Consequences of the failure to protect were no clearer than was the threat. “Either America is to be ruled by Americans, or it is to become the stamping ground of cheap labor, alienism, internationalism, and hyphenism.”55 The extent, as well as the depth, of protective policies enacted during this Republican period mark it as isolationist. The country shunned alliances, rejected the League of Nations, restricted immigration, and imposed tariff walls. Congress saw these as mutually reinforcing. Not only did the federal government have ‹nal say over immigration, in its view it had the only say: sovereignty meant authority not only complete and absolute, but indivisible and unquestioned as well. John Works denounced those who would restrict immigration rather than eliminate it altogether, arguing, “We boast lustily of our independence and American-
Whether to Exclude
43
ism and then propose to surrender to another nation the right to determine who shall come to this country and make their homes here.”56 All agreed that “control over immigration should not, must not, be dependent even in the slightest degree upon the wish or desire of another country.”57 Setting into law annual quotas as maxima was, to many representatives, the same as giving countries minima, which was to surrender control. “I do not,” said Riley Wilson, “like to assent even temporarily to the proposition that any foreign nation shall be given the right and privilege of having admitted to this country any ‹xed number of its population during any prescribed period.”58 To give up this right now was to undermine the country’s recent moves toward isolation. “It must be remembered that one of the most important reasons for the rejection of the Covenant of the League of Nations was the fear that the League would arrogate to itself a measure of control over immigration.”59 If either refugee admissions or country quotas were established, “it would mean that any foreign country could force a minority group upon us that they did not happen to like by persecuting or mistreating them.”60 Restrictionists additionally agreed that passports, opinions about American immigration policy expressed by any noncitizen, and foreign governments’ emigration controls also infringed on U.S. sovereignty; giving in to them would destroy it. Voices other than American legislators’, especially opposing voices, and particularly foreign voices in opposition, outraged legislators and the enforcement bureaucracy, who hoped that “the astonishing protests of other governments demanding the right that they may recuperate at the expense of the people of the United States . . . should result very soon in the passage of an immigration restriction bill that will really restrict.”61 In addition, “no Government and no group in or out of America has the right to question the exercise of America’s discretion in making such a [selective] choice (Applause).”62 Many argued that foreign government regulation of emigration violated U.S. sovereignty. “Foreign countries are to-day dictating the class of immigrants that the United States must accept.”63 Passports themselves infringed on U.S. sovereignty because they were issued at the home government’s discretion; “foreign governments choose for us our immigrants in the ‹rst instance, because no citizen or subject of a country can become an immigrant unless he receives from his government a passport.”64 Sovereignty was, of course, at stake: “It is not the province of those in foreign lands to say what quota each race or group shall have. To grant this privilege is to abandon our sovereignty.”65 Or, “in other words,” as said Representative Mason, “the King of the other country determines for us who is allowed to come here.”66
44
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Any effort to bargain with foreign powers about foreign inspection and selection, if inaugurated, would at once place them in a position to claim a voice in the making of our immigration regulations. . . . The permanent loss of that right would be an irreparable calamity to America. . . . We will thereby become helpless to prevent their hungry and wretched millions from coming to America at will. Our complete and overwhelming ruin would follow inevitably and soon.67 Still bothering legislators and, especially, the Commissioner-General of Immigration, was that fact that the United States could not go to Europe and pick the best to become citizens. Instead, it had to wait for people to choose it, which meant that other countries’ sovereignty got in the way of the United States having a truly selective immigration policy.68 As a compromise, though, the legislators noti‹ed the public not only that foreign interests would not be incorporated into policy, but that they would not even be heard. Citizens expressing views that took foreign governments’ interests into account or that even coincidentally agreed with them also sought to undermine the country’s sovereignty. “It makes no difference whether an attempt is made to decide American questions for foreign reasons in mass meetings, in the press, or at the ballot box. The man who attempts to shape American questions to foreign standards and to settle them upon the basis of bene‹cial results to some foreign country can not be a good American citizen.”69 “America must be kept American,” said Calvin Coolidge in a message to Congress.70 Legislators who could not quite agree that the United States ought to be the sole object of their attention could at least agree that it came ‹rst. “We have got to keep what we have for ourselves and restrict that immigration that wishes to come to our borders.”71 “He that provideth not for his own household is worse than an in‹del, and what shall it pro‹t America if she shall afford asylum to all the earth and lose her own soul (Applause)?”72 “America ‹rst” punctuated speeches against taking others’ interests into account—even as a prudential measure—and proclaimed American independence, political maturity, and power. “I think, Mr. President, it is more important that this country should be relieved from having an onrush of immigration than it is for us to be so very careful in regard to whether or not we will offend other nations upon this question. . . . America ‹rst.”73 Refusing to hear others signaled power, the ability to exercise sovereign prerogatives. Weak powers kowtowed to others, but strong powers need not pay attention; therefore, the reasoning went, the country ought to refuse to take others into account as a way to
Whether to Exclude
45
signal its strength. Listening to others showed weakness and invited attempts to violate one’s sovereignty, to turn a country into a vassal state.
Absolute Sovereignty and Foreign Governments: The Example of Japan
Congress defended this absolute authority against two foes, foreign governments and the executive branch. The two, to the congressional mind, were closely intertwined. The lightning rod in Congress’s struggle to establish itself as the keeper of American sovereignty was the Gentlemen’s Agreement between the United States and Japan, which consisted of an understanding between the two foreign secretaries, established through correspondence in 1908 but never formalized, that Japan would “voluntarily” limit emigration to the United States, keeping it below the point at which Charles Evans Hughes, the secretary of state, felt that American anti-Asian racism would become activated.74 The voluntary and unwritten nature of this agreement was meant to save both countries the embarrassment of statutes banning Japanese immigration while allowing immigration from European countries. The two countries’ executive branches were then attempting to accommodate each other diplomatically, to negotiate terms to regulate their common presence and rivalry in the Paci‹c. But both houses of Congress found outrageous the means by which this accommodation was achieved. Japan objected not to its exclusion, but to what it rightly perceived to be racial discrimination. Even supporters of Japanese exclusion noted that “we all know what the purpose of this clause is, although not disclosed on its face. . . . I suppose it does not make any change in actual name whether you say Hindus and persons who cannot become citizens [but] to combine them takes away a lot of the bitterness.”75 In an effort to defeat the provision banning Japanese, the Japanese government subsidized English-language newspapers to be distributed in the United States, each containing testimonials from Japanese and American citizens. Ambassador Hanihara wrote to Secretary Hughes at Hughes’s request, pointing out the “grave consequences” of damage to U.S.-Japanese relations should the antiJapanese provision be incorporated into law. Congress interpreted this not only as a veiled threat, but as an effort to infringe American sovereignty, and erupted. Our form of government is known to other nations. . . . They know that every independent nation has the right to admit or exclude
46
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
whomsoever it wishes to admit or exclude. These are universally acknowledged rights of independent sovereign nations. . . . Who comes forward here now to object to this Nation exercising its universally acknowledged sovereign right and power? Who is it that intrudes into our councils? Who is it that insolently and impertinently demands that we abdicate, that we surrender our very independence of action as an independent Nation? Who is it that does this thing? The Senate knows; the country knows; it is Japan, whom we have befriended.76 William Borah was another among many constructing his argument from the same materials. It is dif‹cult for me to see how one nation can object to another nation determining who shall come to its borders to become citizens or inhabitants. It is one of the most fundamental things for which a nation contends; and the very fact that they assume to say that this Government shall not exercise the most fundamental right of sovereignty known to government itself is far more extraordinary than anything that we may do toward excluding them.77 The U.S. government shunned Japan, making it a pariah. The relationship was so damaged that many predicted the rise of anti-American militarism in Japan.78 In a similar vein, Italy protested, and Romania expressed its “painful surprise” and “disappointment” at the drastic reduction in the Romanian quota, noting in passing that halting remittances from workers back to Romania would slow the postwar economic recovery that America had pledged to assist.79 Again, Congress treated the foreign objection with outrage. Albert Johnson, head of the Committee on Immigration and Naturalization, said that “these astonishing protests of other governments demanding the right that they may recuperate at the expense of the people of the United States, together with the impudent threat of alien blocs here, should result very soon in the passage of an immigration restriction bill that will really restrict (Applause).”80 Once Italy, Romania, and Japan voiced objections, that fact alone became suf‹cient reason to exclude their nationals. The United States was not going to allow anyone to tell it what to do. John Phelan stated this position most bluntly when he argued, “A man who is able to enforce his will is much better entitled to a hearing in the court of nations than a man who is impotent and powerless, as the American people to a great extent believed themselves to be noncombatant before we demonstrated to the world our extraordinary ability in men and resources
Whether to Exclude
47
to ‹ght battles.”81 Later, when considering provisions that would give preference to British immigrants, German ethnics hit back using this same logic. They accused Congress of “trying to Anglicize America. You would ‹nally turn this country over to be a colony of Great Britain.”82 Foreign interest in American immigration policy meant to Congress foreign usurpation of American autonomy.
Absolute Sovereignty and Domestic Politics: Congress and the Executive
Congress fought many of its battles closer to home, with the executive branch. The rights “to regulate commerce with foreign nations” and to establish “a uniform rule of naturalization,” the Supreme Court reasoned, together implied a congressional right to control immigration. On the other hand, immigration was a matter of foreign relations, involving sovereignty, and so might belong to the executive branch. This indeterminacy haunted immigration battles. Through treaties, the executive had sought to regularize relations with other countries. John Box, an opponent of the executive branch, noted that “The President’s constant contact with delicate and dif‹cult questions of our foreign relations and the necessity of maintaining cordial diplomatic relations with other countries expose him and his advisors and agencies to the constant tendency toward too great liberality in immigration regulations.”83 Treaties of friendship and cooperation often expressly protected commerce and outlined reciprocal privileges of nationals, such as the right of each to travel and to own property in the other’s territory. Such had been true of the 1868 Burlingame Treaty between the United States and China, and such was true of the Gentlemen’s Agreement between the United States and Japan. But Congress abrogated the ‹rst in 1882, when it passed the ‹rst of the Chinese Exclusion Acts; it went on to abrogate the second in the Quota Acts. “Treaties . . . could only be made upon such conditions as were satisfactory to foreign Governments, so that the whole system of immigration control would pass to the treatymaking power. . . . Immigration regulation would pass to the President.”84 Congress painted the executive branch either as merely unconnected with the people or as positively in service of foreign governments and internationalist business agents. Just now there is a hidden, sinister plan to “dig under:” it is hoped, by a system of mining and sapping, to divert the control of this important question, this question of life and death, from the Halls of Con-
48
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
gress elected by the people, and place it in the secret chambers of the treaty-making power, over which the will of the people has much less direct and effective control, and with the Shipping Board and steamship companies, whose only interest is to make money by bringing millions from the Old World to America.85 The executive branch was, to the congressional mind, in direct service of foreign governments as well as of black marketeers. In fact, legislators (even legislators of the same party as the executive) viewed the executive as representing foreign interests in the United States. “In the case of a treaty you have the Executive . . . meeting the chancelleries of the world and agreeing to let their surplus population come and stay here. Under such a system you, my colleagues, and your people at home are to be silent and helpless.”86 Like foreign lobbyists or ambassadors, the executive staff sought primarily to promote foreign interests and to encourage foreign demands on the American people. Therefore, “if we allow our country’s diplomats to determine who shall come into our country, every other country will demand the same right later on.”87 The executive branch not only acted in preference of foreign peoples, but ceded authority to them. For this reason, although “immigration may be regulated by treaty or by law, [legislators] prefer the latter, as the law may be altered at any time to suit the needs of this Nation without the consent of the other country.”88 Its plenary status arose from the fact of sovereignty. As a way to capture control and to highlight its differences with the executive branch, Congress chose to insist that immigration was not in fact foreign, but domestic, domestic meaning nonnegotiable and under congressional control, foreign meaning subject to the approval of other countries. “Immigration and naturalization are domestic questions, and no people can come to the United States except upon our own terms.”89 Actually, the House of Representatives declared immigration policy domestic; the Senate believed it to be foreign—because the Senate had authority over foreign policy matters. Senators declared themselves “tired of Executive control not only of domestic questions but of foreign questions de‹ning the foreign policy of America. America’s foreign policy is determined by treaties rati‹ed by the Senate and not by mutual understandings of our Secretary of State and the secretary of foreign affairs of some other country.”90 But whether the policy was called foreign or domestic, it was up to the Congress, not the executive, to shape. Congress had the national interest at heart. “The very fact that this country freed itself from foreign entanglements, declaring its independence, proves very clearly that the United States of America was from its very inception destined to be the one Nation in the world free from the dominating and contumacious
Whether to Exclude
49
in›uences of the ever narrow and greedy European rulers or those who would seek to propagate their doctrines.”91 Which enemy was worse, foreign governments or the executive branch, is never clear in the record. Both wanted to curtail Congress’s right to exclude at whim. As it was, congressional authority was unchallengeable. “If we were inclined to be so arbitrary,” one legislator pointed out, “we would be well within our rights to decide that no immigrant should be admitted unless he was 6 feet 2 inches tall and had red hair.”92 Congress could recognize legislation as unfair but ‹nd it necessary: “If it takes arbitrary, discriminatory, or even despotic legislation to protect America and American institutions, in the name of God, let us have them! (Applause).”93 This right was expressed most concisely by Raker: “If we have a right to write a law to exclude people, we can write any law we want.”94
Conclusion
Recent involvement with Europe, both indirect through trade and direct through immigration and the war, prompted legislative action. Those who supported restriction in principle valued sovereign autonomy over all else. They advocated restrictive measures to preserve and protect the country’s very being against foreign governments and the executive branch, which served foreign governments. Those who opposed restriction often used the same reasons the restrictionists gave. Interdependence was one example of such dual usage. International ties affected the liberals’ arguments as much as they did the restrictionists’ views. Whereas the restrictionists drew from recent increases in immigration and trade, and from the war experience, the lesson that Europe and Europeans were dangerous, liberals drew positive conclusions about human interdependence. Migration was natural. One representative observed, rather mystically, that “movement . . . is life.”95 In debate, the presumption should be in favor of the immigrant; human ties transcend sovereign dictates. “You have a right to declare war against all immigrants; in fact, Congress has the right to do almost anything it desires. But is it fair, is it American, to exercise a power merely because you have it?”96 Movement and the connections it created were also facts of the modern age. To reject migration was to reject modernity. Said Sidney Gulick, “It seems to me, in view of the world situation, in which oceans have become rivers and steamships have become bridges, we can not set up an absolute, ›at policy of complete exclusion of any particular people.”97 Progress, in fact, depended not on isolation but on openness and encour-
50
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
agement of innovation. Turning around the restrictionists’ apocalyptic scenarios, James Gallivan remarked, “Let us not forget that history writes in large letters that the beginning of the decline and decadence of a nation starts when the bars are set against alien blood, and a doctrine of ‘self-centered complacency’ is established.”98 Whereas restrictionists learned from the war that ties among countries created avenues for harm, their opponents believed that borders created harm. Ties among people, if nurtured, could only lead to peace. This view rested on the notion of a fundamentally similar human race, arbitrarily divided into sovereign blocs. Sovereignty was not their friend. Restrictionists’ arguments centered on sovereign self-preservation. The arguments opposed, in principle, to restriction subtly challenged the assumption that borders de‹ned the limits of people’s obligations to each other. “I protest,” declared Walter Chandler, “against this outrage upon the elementary rights of human beings to live somewhere upon the earth in liberty, peace, and happiness.”99 Their advocates tended to be universalists, believing in the essential oneness of the “family of man,” or to adhere to what would later be known as a Rawlsian position. “I have always,” said Representative Hardy, “felt sympathy for the underdog, and tried to look at things from his eyes, to put myself in his place, to weigh justice and right with his scales.”100 Most objected to the arbitrariness of the quotas’ basis: birthplace. To the liberal mind, discrimination based on some chance circumstance not under any person’s control was irrational and unfair, hence loathsome. “All of the intelligence and all of the culture and all of the patriotism of the world is not gathered within the puny temples of our brains.”101 To underline their point, liberals (who, in this context, were those merely wishing to maintain the status quo) pointed to worthy heroes of Western history who had migrated and had certainly not been born in the United States. Representatives pointed out that “our ancestors came here from somewhere, and of course lots of good men are not born in this country. Jesus Christ, for instance.”102 Romulus and Remus founded Rome; Abraham was called from Ur.103 If the proposed restriction passed, “if a Moses attempted to come in, all his prescience and Godgiven prophecy would avail him nothing if there had already preceded him from the Nile to America 18 Egyptians.”104 Only one-third of the senators’, not to mention the Supreme Court justices’ and presidents’, names could be found on May›ower records.105 Harkening back to the recent war, one congressman “thought what a travesty on American ideals it would be if in passing this bill we would prevent coming to America the unknown mother of our revered unknown soldier.”106 Louis Marshall, then representing a Jewish organization, summed up this ethical stance.
Whether to Exclude
51
Nothing could be more arbitrary than such a regulation [as the quota law]. Our immigration laws would be based on a mere accident, not on the physical, moral, or intellectual qualities of him or her who now seeks admission but on the circumstance that others of the same nationality have in the past come in large or small numbers . . . whether such immigrants were individually good, bad, or indifferent.107 The Declaration of Independence “deduced the right to equality before the law, the right to participate in civil government, not from the accident of birth or condition, nor yet from race or color, but from the fact of manhood alone (Applause).”108 Acting against principle would poison the United States. “The person who attempts to raise religious and racial prejudice is unworthy of American citizenship. We are in grave danger of losing our sense of fair play and treating men according to their real worth.”109 Birthplace was arbitrary; discrimination based on arbitrary features was anathema to enlightened people. Selection based on birthplace was, therefore, unenlightened, illiberal, and un-American. Many saw in the restriction proposals a more nefarious discrimination than that based simply on birthplace. Birthplace was arbitrary, but it was also, in principle, random and applied equally to all non-Americans. But place of birth was chosen not only because it was administratively convenient but also because it stood for groups racially or politically distinctive. Sidney Gulick pointed out that if the legislators were sincerely concerned with reducing numbers while assuring a higher class of immigrant, they would have raised standards for individuals instead of excluded racial blocs; after all, he argued, this would have reduced the chance of Bolshevism and eliminated foreign policy problems. Race must, he reasoned, be the real focus of the legislators’ animosity.110 Quotas, in this view, were simple bigotry. “It is the narrowest policy that ever cursed the soul of man. It is the policy of the gentleman who says, ‘I am the elect of God. . . . This is a bill of proscription. . . . It belongs to the time of the rack and thumbscrew, when the argument was the scaffold and when philosophy found expression in the touch of persecution.”111 Others continued. The bill was “a monstrosity, the result of ignorance, of prejudice, of sectionalism, of that narrow sel‹shness which robs one of his sympathy for his fellow man.”112 Bigotry was an easy target for sarcasm. “Just now we hear nothing but hatred, nothing but the ravings of the exaggerated I—‘I am of the best stock; I do not want to be contaminated; I have produced the greatest literature; my intellect is the biggest; my heart is the noblest.’—and this is repeated in every parliament, in every country, by
52
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
every fool all over the world.”113 No person, let alone any country, should view others in this way. Expounding racial criteria in immigration policy was expected to create practical problems as well as those of principle. Such rules would offend American citizens who were told that people of their type were undesirable.114 Recent immigrants were full of hope and beginning to assimilate when they would be told that the country needed far fewer of their type. Discriminatory laws would demoralize new immigrants.115 Discrimination would also encourage sectional bigotry, as it labeled in law different population subclasses. The law would destroy that which it was attempting to protect: American unity. Some went further. Not only were birthplace quotas arbitrary and unfair, but they were hypocritical. “Once we get in we close the gates behind us and keep out the struggling immigrant who springs from the same ancestors as we do.”116 The legislator who stated this position most clearly ultimately rejected it, considering it (as did others in favor of restriction) emotional rather than rational. If I were to follow the dictates of sentiment and of humanitarian considerations, I would vote for an open door, because our forefathers, yours and mine, came here and enjoyed all these blessings, material and political, such as no other nation on earth affords. Then after we have come in and enjoyed these things we shut the door and shut out all others, who in a moral and ethical way, it seems to me, have as much right as we have. Yet I know that we can not consult our hearts only, but that we must consult our reason as well, and that tells me that there must be a restriction.117 Because, the reasoning went, Americans had applied one standard to themselves, they could not apply another to those whom chance had settled differently. If people could not be convinced that discrimination was always, or inherently, bad, perhaps they could be convinced that it was unnecessary or unworthy or imprudent. It was unnecessary because the United States could afford to bear the burdens that immigrants asked of it. “The Great War fell like a blight, like a curse upon the earth. Thrones were overturned, nations vanished, emperors and czars were executed and exiled. . . . Our casualties were few compared with the frightful losses of the combatants of other countries. We are to-day the wealthiest and happiest people of the world”; hence, refusing to help is “mean and sordid sel‹shness.”118 Discrimination was also unworthy of the United States. Without provision for refugees, “you will have the world reduced to this
Whether to Exclude
53
condition, that however desperate might be the peril, however frightful the persecution to which people of another country might be subjected, a fugitive from those dreadful countries would be sent back by the hand of our of‹cers to expiate in his own person our renunciation of the principles of civilization which we were supposed to embody in the highest degree during all our existence (Applause).”119 Because of the country’s history as a proponent of freedom, it owed the world laws in support of its words. Yet “no provision has been made so that men escaping on account of oppression—that is, political—may be allowed to make this country their haven of refuge, as has been recommended not only by the commission, but which has been the policy of this government from the very day of its foundation.”120 Restriction’s opponents objected to the language of the restrictive clauses, desiring instead something that would “accomplish what we are after with more credit to ourselves, and in such a way as is not contrary to our basic principles.”121 Discrimination was, ‹nally, imprudent. Jane Addams and others argued in terms of hypocrisy’s practical consequences and America’s new global role. “At this time when we are hoping that the United States may take a leading part in a new internationalism which will mean such a world reorganization as will guarantee respect for the rights of different nationalities, the passage of this law would be peculiarly unfortunate. How can we urge Russia, Austria, and Germany to recognize the claims of people against whom we are, at the same time, discriminating?”122 U. G. Murphy also focused on foreign policy problems. “The Chinese are saying what the Japanese are saying that apparently the white man proposes to have association for himself and by himself, if you are to have equality applying to the white man only. Apparently our legal attitude at the present time supports that contention; it places us in a very embarrassing position, that is those of us who stand for the liberal element.”123 Even the normally insular commissioner-general of immigration voiced this concern. “It is a question of serious importance,” said the commissioner, “whether it is desirable to set aside the traditional policy of the Government concerning the admission of peoples from foreign countries at a time when world conditions are being reestablished on lines calculated to promote more friendly relations, and when the Government is endeavoring to increase its merchant marine and extend its foreign commerce.”124 And in a criticism that foreshadowed arguments after the next world war, one representative pointed out that the country was advocating a policy espoused by its recently defeated foe. “Probably it is one of the evil legacies of the late war. You know that during the struggle we had the fancy to denounce Germany for advancing the idea of the ‘superman’ and ‘supernation.’ Now that doctrine of superiority which was originally sponsored in this country by the Ku-Klux-Klan seems
54
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
to have found expression in this proposed legislation.”125 Hypocrisy was not only wrong in itself but would hurt the country in its attempts to convince others to follow its lead internationally. “Have we come,” asked LeBaron Colt, “to that extreme view of isolation?”126 Interaction with Europeans and with the international trading system did not motivate the antirestriction arguments as they did the arguments in its favor; rather, antirestrictionists assumed their stance in opposition to the principles the restrictionists espoused, then used examples, such as the country’s history and recent experience in the war, to illustrate their points. They valued individuals rather than states, and neutrality rather than preference. Rejecting some immigrants was not new. What was new and emerged from this debate was the decision to protect sovereignty by controlling the border between citizen and noncitizen. Whom this sovereignty was supposed to protect became the topic of the ensuing, and partly simultaneous, debate on the nature of the threat that Americans faced. While arguments about limiting immigrant numbers were about having and protecting sovereignty, arguments about immigrant characteristics were about what was valuable about the inside and why it was worth protecting.
CHAPTER 4
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
While arguments for restriction emphasize social separateness, arguments for selection by characteristic highlight what, exactly, the separateness is supposed to protect. Reasons that contestants in a debate supply regarding speci‹c groups’ desirability or dangerousness might not reveal the truth about their private motives for policy change, but they do reveal the sorts of reasons that the public ‹nds acceptable, useful, or laudable. Arguments that people make about immigration policy, as about other border control policies, reveal the ways in which people think about borders’ value and the value of what those borders create or maintain, differences between the society inside and all of those outside. Tracing the way that public reasons change over time can, then, show how sovereignty’s social value has changed. Of interest are two questions: what did legislators and members of the public think would be the consequences of immigration, in general and of various groups, and how did one viewpoint come to dominate? This chapter approaches the question ‹rst by laying forth arguments made for and against immigration restriction. Those arguments concerned proposals that either died, were adapted or fused with others, or became successful. This is the ‹rst of four chapters asking the same questions; when they are taken together, they provide evidence about the relationship between arguments and policy change in this area and about the role of choice in creating a sovereignty at the center of which is exclusive control over people. The ‹rst section considers arguments made for and against excluding speci‹c numbers of immigrants; following it is one that covers arguments made about certain types of immigrants.
The Public Interest in Numbers of Immigrants
Competing assertions of sovereign prerogative often consumed the congressional debate, but in spite of congressional hopes, such assertions alone were not suf‹cient to convince Americans to halt, then reverse, immigration.1 The country had, after all, remained open to white Euro55
56
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
peans since their ‹rst settlement, and logically, the claim that the country should exclude merely because it could begged the question of why it had not done so before. Clearly, something had to have changed; some new threat had to justify predictions of impending disaster. The two possibilities, a change in who was coming and a change in how many were coming, each caused enormous alarm. Both assumed that immigration would destroy sovereignty, then went on to detail exactly how this would be accomplished. A majority of the arguments that legislators advanced in this period were arguments by analogy; the process of immigration was invasion, while its result was colonization. Fears about the numbers involved focused on two images of cultural destruction: that of invasion by multitudes intent on conquering and that of subversion by small cells or colonies loyal to foreign powers. Legislators considered them equally deadly. Reason (Metaphor): Armies and Armageddon
Americans opposed to immigration feared conquest. In the era around World War I, military analogies ran through discussion of immigration’s consequences. Martial imagery shaped how contestants framed the threat and responses to it. Immigration restriction was “a matter of national defense.”2 “During the decade immediately preceding the outbreak of the European war there came to our shores, with the momentum of an irresistible army, an average of over ten hundred thousand immigrants every year”;3 The commissioner-general in his 1928 retrospective on the Quota Acts pointed out that before restriction, “Ellis Island resounded for years to the tramp of an endless invading army.”4 As protectionism applied both to the economy and the polity, defense applied against both foreign soldiers and immigrants. “The duty of our Government to the people who compose it to meet and repel evils coming from other governments is absolute. It can make no difference whether these evil in›uences are war, destructive immigration, or whatever other thing it may be.”5 Thomas He›in compared open immigration to leaving the gates of Fort Mims open, which, he said, had led Indians to massacre its residents.6 Biblical prophecy also infused descriptions of immigration’s consequences. M. M. Neely, for example, declared: It is our duty to defend not only against enemies in arms but against the millions of physically, mentally, and morally inferior men and women scattered over Europe, Asia, Africa, Mexico, and the islands of the sea, who, as prospective immigrants, are awaiting their opportunity to rush to our shores. [If they are successful] we shall have
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
57
justi‹ed the following words of Isaiah: ‘Your land, strangers devour it in your presence, and it is desolate.’7 Yet more dramatically, Thomas He›in intoned, “Choose you this day whom you will serve, the god of good government in the United States or the mammon of immigration agents and steamship companies [bringing] an alien army with bombs and dangerous propaganda to come into our country, working injury to the institutions that our boys protected and defended with their blood and lives.”8 Apocalypse would follow invasion. “The foreign invader,” warned Thomas Lilly, “is not most dangerous when he comes as a hostile army, but when he comes into the ‹eld as an army of labor. So have all the nations of the past gone down.”9 Another, concerned about overstatement, observed that “though the steady stream of foreigners coming to our shores cannot be termed a ‘military’ invasion, as was the Hun invasion of the Roman Empire, it is an invasion which, if permitted to go unchecked, may have in the centuries to come the same fatal effect upon our country as did the Hun invasion of old.”10 In fact, “nations are destroyed by tides like this.”11 Jacob Milligan ampli‹ed this Lesson of History: “History teaches us that the downfall of the centers of civilization of the past has not been by armed invasion but by the bringing in of alien people as laborers or slaves.”12 Even actress Lillian Russell chimed in: “The higher civilizations of past ages, history teaches us, succumbed to such foreign invasions as now threaten us.”13 Reason (Metaphor): Virus and Poison
Viruses also invade. Another way to view the hazards immigrants posed was to view the American people as an organic whole and immigrants as a virus or poison. Much earlier, countries had undertaken to regulate the spread of disease through shipping restrictions and quarantine, but at the turn of the century, while infectious disease remained a problem, fears of contagion focused on political health rather than on physical health. “The body politic . . . is not unlike the human body. We are taught that germs of all diseases lie in the human system, and we are dependent upon the power of the system to generate enough combative force to destroy those germs.”14 Degeneracy and anarchism could infect, but so too could race itself be a virus. “I would quarantine this Nation against people of any government in Europe incapable of self-government for any reason, as I would against the bubonic plague. . . . I will admit the old immigration of the . . . light-haired, blue-eyed Anglo-Saxons or Celts”;15 “those who take this [melting pot] view forget that there is little or no similarity between the
58
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
clear-thinking, self-governing stocks that sired the American people and this stream of irresponsible and broken wreckage that is pouring into the lifeblood of America the social and political disease of the Old World.”16 Walter Chandler argued that “the citizenship of a nation, like the morals of character or the blood of the body, should be kept free from poison, corruption, and contamination.”17 Consumption would otherwise be swift. “Within a few short years . . . the endless tide of immigration will have ‹lled our country with a foreign and unsympathetic element . . . and the true spirit of Americanism left us by our fathers will gradually become poisoned by this uncertain element.”18 The response to sickness was to isolate and purge the body. This is what restrictionists advocated. Reason (Metaphor): Tariff and Prohibition
Immigration restriction can stand alone as a logical extension of the impulse to protect, but it can also stand in support of other isolationist policies. Excluding labor supports a protective tariff, as excluding subversives and internationalists aids military and diplomatic isolation. Not surprisingly, these three pillars of isolation became interlinked. Sometimes the economic arguments were no more rational than the racial arguments; for example, Richard Austin complained that millions of “idle slackers” were coming to the United States—to take jobs from American men (!)19—but often legislators viewed immigration policy as one pillar of a coherent protective policy. “I voted last week for an anti-dumping bill,” one observed, typically, “to prevent the dumping of manufactured products into this country, and I will vote for any bill to prevent the dumping of undesirable aliens into this country.”20 Restrictionists drew a parallel. “I can see no difference between a provision of law providing for a differential in the admission of goods and a similar provision relating to immigrants—not the slightest difference.”21 Citizens, feared legislators, would see this parallel too and would take revenge on legislators who did not follow through on their restrictionist promises. “If we erect a tariff wall to keep the underpaid labor of foreign countries from competing in foreign factories and on foreign farms with well-paid and self-respecting American labor, and if at the same time we let the foreign labor in to compete with our people, in their own yard, the American workingman would have a perfect right to complain that our tariff was made to protect the employer and not the employee and that our platform promises were a fraud and a snare.”22 If they did not take revenge on legislators, they might target each other. “There can be no greater danger to the Republic than unemployment, low wages, and poverty among our own people.”23 “If any of our people prefer to live as Europeans, it would be better for them to go
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
59
to Europe and live rather than jeopardize our Americanism and, through competition, destroy our prosperity by bringing Europe to America.”24 Immigration restriction was also bound up with another type of ban, that against alcohol. Again, the two policies were connected both symbolically and practically. At the symbolic level, each ban purported to steer the country back to wholesomeness, to protect the virtuous from the possibility of being overrun by the immoral. At a practical level, each ban required the same type of border control, which meant that someone intent on breaking the alcohol law could make some extra money breaking the immigration ban.25 Just as liquor smuggling shot up after Prohibition, and smuggling of goods shot up after Congress raised the tariff, immigrant smuggling shot up after Congress began to consider suspending immigration altogether. “Since the placing on the statute books of restrictive legislation and as a consequence more recent numerical limitation of immigration, the bootlegging of aliens—a lucratively attractive endeavor for the lawlessly inclined—has grown to be an industry second in importance only to the bootlegging of liquor.”26 Prohibition stood with the tariff and diplomatic isolation as a cornerstone of the country’s thoroughgoing attempt to close the borders and clean house.27 Immigration restriction was both an independent policy in support of this general goal and a supporting component of the other three policies. “Indeed, it seems strange that it should have taken so long for such a self-evident policy of fostering American institutions and protecting the welfare of the American public to have recommended itself to a people that has always prospered under a wise doctrine of tariff regulation and other measures designed to preserve American standards of living.”28 Reasoning by analogy guided visions of the result, as well as of the process, of immigration. Again, images of conquest and submission competed for primacy. Many feared that groups of foreigners would remain loyal to their country of origin, passively in time of peace but actively in time of war. They believed that other countries promoted this “internal colonization,” encouraging immigrants to maintain non-English newspapers, loan societies, remittances, and the like, in preparation for war or at least economic competition with the United States. In this view, immigrant groups were “indigestible lumps” at best and hostile colonies at worst, enervating the country, sickening it, and eventually destroying it altogether. Vying with this image was that of subversion or erosion, where the danger was not that of future trauma but of a slow wearing-away of the boundaries separating the United States from others. The country would simply cease to be. These two images focused on dangers emanating from without; the country’s purpose and value were, by implication, their opposites: wholeness and homogeneity, which were later extolled them-
60
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
selves. Legislators’ understandings of what they were to protect in›uenced their de‹nition of threat, but outside threats also shaped their views of the America they were to protect. Reason (Metaphor): Internal Colonization
That America certainly did not tolerate enemy colonies in its midst. Immigrants outside were armies; immigrants inside were subversive colonies, and “in but a few years these aliens in very despair will be pounding heavily at the very pillars of our Government, while those who have come ahead of them a few years back with their socialism, their communism, their Bolshevism, have been merely gnawing like rats at our foundations.”29 The United States was losing its integrity. “Foreign colonies,” worried James Byrnes, “have been created in the large cities,”30 and “when we contemplate that more than 10 percent of our total population owe and acknowledge allegiance to foreign ›ags and foreign governments, and decline to become ‘part and parcel’ of us, my friends, we must . . . admit that the time has come for prompt and decisive action (Applause).”31 Some viewed such colonies as a necessary by-product of too-rapid immigration, others saw them as a necessary consequence of racial difference, and still others saw them as key to a foreign plot to undermine the country. First, the pace of entry could, alone, be a problem. Through too-rapid immigration, the country was turning into a Babel. “When we have foolishly listened to a suf‹cient number of such appeals to ‹ll America with the pandemonium and woe which now curse so many parts of the world, who will relieve our children from the distress which we are cooking up for them now?”32 Heterogeneity was tantamount to dissolution: “There will be hundreds of motley, mongrel, anarchistic, jabbering millions here; but with such a people in the ascendancy, the country will have ceased to be America.”33 The immigration committee’s chair, Albert Johnson, warned that “the U.S. must act and act very soon for its own protection and for the protection of those who would enter whom we can neither feed nor support nor assimilate.”34 Second, and more troublesome, racial difference could be the source of these “colonies.” In 1911, the commissioner-general of immigration warned, “Another fact which tends to accentuate the seriousness of this change in race is the habit of most of the new immigrants to colonize.”35 This is due to an abundance “of alien races naturalized or born here whose hearts, like the hearts of their fathers, still give paramount homage to the old countries and clans from which they sprang. If tempted to it, under cir-
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
61
cumstances permitting it, they would side with alien races and foreign lands.”36 Race, not learning, made good citizens. Citizenship should be granted by ethnic descent, not any longer by place of birth. James Reed earnestly pointed out that just because “a cat has kittens in an oven, that does not make them biscuits.”37 If Asian immigration, for example, were allowed, “we would then become a Japanese and a Chinese colony.”38 In fact, “our failure to bar the Japanese has resulted in the development of alien colonies being entirely under the protection of a foreign government and amenable in only slight degree to American in›uence.”39 This situation was a consequence of the country’s failure to discriminate. “There are certain races that will not assimilate. They are foreign to each other. There are certain laws of Nature which man can not suspend, and there are certain laws of Nature which it is not desirable for man to undertake to suspend,” or the result will be “civil war.”40 Third, more ominously, other countries could and would, with hostile intent, purposely establish colonies within American borders. “It is well known that every nation in the world, except the United States and possibly a few others, encourages emigration of the least desirable of its citizens and subjects and strives to keep the most desirable within its own borders.”41 Starting before the war, “large numbers of undesirables from other countries have come here in such numbers as to suggest that some foreign countries are trying to unload on us not only their surplus but the most undesirable and most objectionable part of their surplus.”42 Such “alien colonies in the United States speaking foreign tongues, maintaining foreign community interests, reading only newspapers printed in their own languages, are un-American and a menace to the Republic.”43 A representative from California asked, “Are we to fall before the onslaught of peaceful invasion and look forward to the time that will surely come when the Japanese on the Paci‹c coast will hold the balance of power?”44 (Since Congress believed the norm to be Anglo-Saxon, by de‹nition immigrants from northwest Europe could not establish foreign colonies.) Pockets of non-Anglo immigrants would grow until they were the norm and the Anglos were a subject minority. Their threat could coalesce and become military. Immigration threatened international war, civil war, or at the very least, crime. “These foreign peoples who may not become citizens build up, as it were, an imperium in imperio—a state within a state, a country within a country. Is it necessary for me to argue that such a situation is charged with danger to America?”45 Countries within countries meant eventual war. The Japanese presented the most acute threat, for they were not only bellicose “by nature” but had developed an impressive navy. Further,
62
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
there is unquestionable evidence that they have a racial loathing for the people of the United States, and it is not only an economic question, therefore, but a military question. In case of a con›ict with Japan we would have to meet, not only a frontal attack but a rear attack, and hence the necessity of keeping ourselves prepared where we have such a large body of aliens notoriously hostile and who are still controlled by their national of‹cers in the United States.46 Once more, if evidence were needed, the recent war provided it. The Great War had for its incipiency assassinations from one of the countries from which you cry discrimination; the people among whom there has thrived anarchy and blackhand assassins; nationalities among whom much hatred is fomented; overthrow governments in a night and destroy those in power. Many nations who rule by might rather than by right. Can people of this kind come to America, settle in groups of their own kind in large cities, have a change of heart, and a change of mind? . . . No one can serve two masters.47 Immigration also promised civil strife. “We wish to check the increase of a foreign, alien people, who can not become citizens of the United States, and whose presence provokes domestic trouble and may cause national estrangement.”48 All aliens do not commit crimes, announced the chair of the immigration committee, “but much crime of a non-American kind is committed by them.”49 Because of their inherent racial tendencies or their learned political spinelessness, immigrants destabilized society. Reason: Subversion
Fear about domestic colonization rested on the assumption that communities of immigrants threatened America; there was some critical mass, perhaps the size of a foreign-language newspaper’s circulation, at which immigrants’ degeneracy became actively threatening. Fear about subversion, on the other hand, rested on the assumption that each individual posed a threat. Some in this period concentrated on the entrants’ illegal status. Foreshadowing debate in the 1980s, some worried about the country’s future, “especially when it is considered that there is such a great percentage of our population who may not even seek naturalization; who, so long as they remain with us, must preserve an alien status because of their illegal entry; whose ‹rst act upon reaching our shores was to break our laws by entering in a clandestine manner—all of which serves to emphasize the potential source of trouble, not to say menace, that such a situation
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
63
suggests.”50 Others were more upset that immigrants were in fact legal: “Is not this condition alarming, when such a great proportion of the voting strength of this country is in the hands of the foreign born?”51 Either way, immigrants would eat away the country’s core. Of particular concern to legislators was the possibility that government would be the immigrants’ target. These fears were closely tied to upheavals abroad. A century earlier, the federal government had been intent on keeping out the revolutionaries and royalists ›eeing the French Revolution; worries about anarchists reached their height after an anarchist immigrant assassinated President McKinley in 1901, while worries about Bolshevism intensi‹ed after the Russian revolution.52 “How can this Republic stand if we continue to permit all the scum of creation—the anarchists, the blackhand, and the bomb thrower—to come here from every portion of the world to undermine our institutions, destroy society, and overthrow the Government?”53 The problem with immigration was precisely that it muddied the difference between friend and enemy, and confused the country’s protectors. Subversion could be gradual. If immigration continues, “it is revolution from within, not danger from without, that will be the ever-present menace to the country (Applause).”54 The more immigration, the greater the threat. “Danger from within. How? you ask me. By people coming here who despise our form of government, who hate our institutions, and who spread the poisons of their dangerous propaganda.”55 Immigrant subversives, General Pershing warned, undermine morale.56 Even without evil intent, immigrants would eventually degrade the American way of life. “Americans should be grateful to the Providence that has guided them in protecting the American wage standard from the unfair, not to say impossible, standard that would be the outcome of the leveling process resulting from unrestricted introduction of foreign peoples.”57 If the country continued to accept immigrants fully, borders would become meaningless, and “we would sooner or later be no better off than the supplicants; in short, we would eventually have no need of immigration laws, since the inducements to come here would cease to exist.”58 Whether immigrants produced domestic colonies or wore away the social fabric, they would sicken and perhaps kill the country. The difference was only the rate and the obviousness of the country’s destruction. Reason: Good for the Rest of the World
Most restrictionists argued in terms of American self-interest, de‹ned narrowly and pursued competitively. Some, however, argued cleverly in terms of global welfare. “The world is upset and disturbed as never before. The
64
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Great War has left us an accumulation of problems that calls for all that is best in American statesmanship. We are burdened with a debt of more than twenty billions of dollars. Our international relationships involve dif‹culties and obligations never known before. . . . The preservation of the Republic is the greatest bene‹t we may hope to render humanity.”59 Immigration restriction was prudential; prudence bene‹ted all. “I believe in world cooperation and that we should assume our portion of responsibility to promote honest diplomacy, law, and order, and that peaceful methods may be substituted for hatred and war; but in order to faithfully serve the humanity of the world our country must keep her own household pure and uncorrupted.”60 Whether exclusion was justi‹able at all always lurked in the background; it was answered variously in different eras. A citizen working long in support of Asian immigration argued that “some say it is not fair to any nation to say ‘we are going to keep you out.’ My answer is that we can make our most important and our maximum contribution to the welfare of the world by making democracy here in America a success; and we can not make our democracy a success if we allow larger numbers continuously to come in than we can wholesomely transform into good and genuine American citizens.”61 The war made this necessary. With the poverty and dissatisfaction prevailing throughout the rest of the world at this time as an aftermath of the war, to permit them to come here without restriction, carrying the bitterness of heart and mingling with those of our citizens who are not entirely familiar with our country and its institutions, a poison may be spread to such an extent as to injure this Government, and in my opinion we must restrict the entrance of large groups at this time for the future welfare not only of our country but of all the peoples of the world. . . . I believe it [the bill] is necessary in order that a beacon shall be preserved on the face of this earth.62 In this view, America had value for all humanity, not just for Americans. To disable it by allowing immigration was to thwart a human dream. Finally, some argued in terms of global ef‹ciency. Excluding the illiterate would prompt more education in Europe, bene‹ting European peoples and governments.63 Moreover, helping people in Europe was a more ef‹cient use of the country’s, and the world’s, resources. “Oh, it would be better that we gave the half of all that we possess in means to help sustain them where they are than to bring them here. . . . Distress is here; discontent is here; world problems are here to make mischief right here.”64 Immigration would be a last resort. “By permitting the admission of some of
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
65
these persons, they may enjoy the privileges of America, in spite of the failure of the administration to help improve conditions over there so that they may stay at home and live in decency.”65 Restriction, and some foreign aid, would better serve everyone, not just Americans. Analogies of conquest—invasion, subversion, colonization—dominate the arguments for numerical restriction. These arguments emerge directly from those opposing immigration in principle; large numbers simply decreased the time that would elapse before sovereignty was irretrievable. The perceived threat was, still, external in origin and military in process. Its result would be the end of the country. Most discussion centered on how horrible the threat was, but when legislators did describe the value they were protecting, they referred to sovereignty, meaning not only the country’s independence but its integrity. The legislators saw its defense as an almost personal battle. Raker: We have two risks, one to stand up and enforce laws that will protect our country. Jenks: Yes, that is one. Raker: And another one, to yield to outside in›uences as against our sovereignty, and permit their immigration and colonization which would, if continued twenty years, practically sap the existence of the western country. We ought to be manly enough to stand for our sovereignty, if we have got to, ought we not?66 In the global struggle for self-preservation, a country either was sovereign—integral, mature, autonomous—or was not, was waiting instead for a death blow. Prudent states used their foreign policies prophylactically, neither allowing themselves to become weak enough to be conquered nor consuming others and exchanging danger from without for danger from within. Immigration, like imperial control of foreign territories, brought enemies within, making them harder to combat. Protection became yet more dif‹cult because enemies were of every sort. “The question of immigration involves economics, ‹nances, social life, social order, the perpetuity of our institutions, the life of the nation itself. We should not have maudlin sympathy but practical patriotism.”67 Practicality meant, in the standard analogy, “shutting the gates” to protect “the very vitals, the very heart of the Nation.”68 Because immigration policy protected sovereignty, it was nonnegotiable. Practical proposals in support of this position include immigration restriction or suspension, careful screening of immigrants to select those least likely to engage in subversion, and education programs to assimilate immigrants effectively and to prevent colo-
66
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
nization by way of ghettos. Each of these did become an element of an immigration bill. Those who supported immigration offered only one main argument—immigrants strengthen the country—with one main piece of evidence, American history. In a mercantile system, people are wealth. The United States was a settler country and had grown powerful by absorbing European human resources and exploiting American natural resources. “I believe that we do need more hands and more brains in this country and that a proper amount of development will come sooner if we will add to our population by immigration.”69 People are also power. It is interesting to learn what we have achieved since 1890. As a result of our entering the Cuban War and later acquiring the Virgin Islands, a new era has come in all the West Indies. We have become a power in the affairs of the Paci‹c, having taken Guam and the Hawaiian Islands. To-day we have under us the Philippines; we helped to bring to an end the con›ict between Russia and Japan, and by the holding of the recent conference in Washington have temporarily at least brought peace in the Paci‹c. We gave up the Chinese indemnity. We created the Panama Canal, and when the European Great World War seemed destined to terminate in favor of Germany, we went into the struggle with all of our resources of man power and material wealth and strength so that the Allies came out victorious. To-day we are the only power on the face of the earth which is not threatened by war and fears no one. Such is the story of the United States since 1890 with its increase of more than 35,000,000 of population.70 People were wealth. “I assert that every man of sound morals and sound health and good intelligence who comes to this country is an addition to the wealth and power of this country.”71 In the labor-intensive history of the country, the more people who settled the land, the greater the tax revenues, the more extensive the infrastructure, and the less likely that Europeans would invade the western territories. “America has been built up by immigration. Every immigrant that comes to our shores is both a producer and a consumer. Other countries go to war to acquire more territory and larger populations. We can easily absorb an additional hundred million men.”72 Glory came from size: the more, the better. Immigrants were especially helpful because they took work that Americans would not readily do. “To enact a bill at the present time containing a literacy test is to shut the doors of the United States to those who would come here, if come they do, to perform the rough manual labor which the average American has declined to do during the past 50
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
67
years.”73 They were the economy’s backbone. “Suppose,” asked Emanuel Celler, “we awoke one ‹ne morning and found all our population of foreign origin had departed. There would, perhaps, be no rolls for breakfast, no sugar for the coffee, and no meat for dinner . . . no butchers, no bakers, or candlestick makers.”74 Immigrants created wealth in the United States, and if the country was lucky, they would keep their wealth there, too. The United States could promote this by accepting additional immigrants, for “with families reunited [in the United States] the money for their support would be retained in our country and not continue to swell the formidable total of remittances abroad, a large part of our invisible export of capital.”75 This constant addition of new men and new blood to the Republic is as necessary for the health and refreshment, the expansion and continuance of civilization and all it means today as always. Immigration, the advent of new men, new blood, new brains and brawn in our land, is not a question of philanthropy for America; it is a matter of life or death, for the nation that seeks to arrest or sti›e the natural laws of life and movement must eventually pay the penalty of lawlessness in stagnation and arrested growth. In my judgment, immigration is power and wealth for the land which draws it, and only natural perversity and legislative stupidity will deprive us of its blessings.76 Later in the century, immigrants would be condemned for their economic motives; political migrants and refugees were good, economic migrants were bad. At the turn of the century, however, the reverse values held sway. To argue that immigrants were a bane, one demonstrated their political backgrounds and motives. To argue that they were a bene‹t, one showed their economic origins. Political was bad; economic was good.77 Liberal and restrictionist arguments had much in common, although their conclusions differed. Nationalist, competitive goals motivated those arguing against numerical restriction as well as those arguing for it; both focused on its effect on American strength. Like the restrictionists, liberals saw immigration, trade, and diplomacy connected directly. One in›uenced the other; policies should go hand in hand. They, again like the restrictionists, drew evidence for this viewpoint from the country’s recent experience during the war: the United States, the least xenophobic and most accepting of diverse immigration, had conquered Europe’s decadent nationalist powers. It emerged from the war the strongest of the Atlantic powers. The two differed mainly in whether they believed that strength came from an organic socioracial integrity or from numbers. Practical
68
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
proposals in support of this viewpoint include those to promote immigration for economic or political reasons. Immigration could, for them, either be entirely open or it could focus on sector-speci‹c recruitment campaigns. Allowing immigration to remain unrestricted numerically was implicitly on the table, for it meant preserving the status quo. Doing nothing would result in unrestricted immigration. Encouraging sector-speci‹c workers was also proposed, usually for the agricultural sector, which had seen its work force vanish as black labor moved northward.
The Public Interest in Certain Types of Immigrants
Although policies are framed in abstract principle, they always, in practice, apply to particular groups. Sometimes the abstraction is intended to hide that particularity. Even when it is not, interested parties do have particular constituencies. The American gate would not be shut on generic people, but on speci‹c, nameable people: business travelers with local ties, the relatives and compatriots of U.S. citizens or permanent residents. A large number of constituencies had an interest not only in whether restrictive policy became the law, but in whom it barred. Those in favor of numerical restriction had speci‹c groups in mind; those opposed did as well. Because restrictionists focused on the value of homogeneity, the cost of any involvement with Europe, and consistency of policy across hemispheres, those who favored immigration argued for the value of heterogeneity, the country’s cultural and geopolitical debt to Europe, and the uniqueness of the Western Hemisphere in U.S. history and policy. The reasons that restrictionists provided focused exclusively on the consequences for current American citizens. Those who opposed them claimed, besides such narrow bene‹ts, international obligations of cultural patrimony, of wartime alliance, of neighborliness; that is, they took other countries’ interests into account. Restrictionists, therefore, won. Reason: American Society—Homogeneity or Heterogeneity
Most arguing for restriction chose homogeneity as their goal, although a few restrictionists argued for racial selectivity on the grounds of fairness: Anglo-Europeans had settled the United States; it should therefore be preserved for their descendants. After all of the settlers’ hard work, the reasoning went, the bene‹ts should not go to latecomers. “We can contribute to people who are in dire need of our ‹nancial aid, but we can not conveniently give up to those people our homes and the homes that we and our
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
69
forefathers have built for the future generations of this country, and we should not be expected to.”78 Others argued in terms of democracy. Most Americans were in favor of racial discrimination; therefore, it was the democrat’s choice. “I think most of us are reconciled to the idea of discrimination. I think the American people want us to discriminate; and I don’t think discrimination itself is unfair.”79 The commissioner-general of immigration defended Congress’s decision to exclude Hindus as public charges using the same reasoning: since Americans discriminated against Hindus, Hindus would not be able to ‹nd employment and therefore would be public charges.80 But people offered such reasons for racial restriction only rarely. Homogeneity made possible most of what many restrictionists valued about the United States. It mattered to some not so much that citizens were of a particular stock so much as that they were of the same stock. Restrictionist John Works said that he objected to the Japanese not because they were of an inferior race, but because they were a different race.81 The representative from Mississippi explained why he valued sameness: “There is nothing more important for any democracy than a homogeneous population, with like traditions, like ideals, like aspirations, like thoughts concerning what is best for mankind, like tokens of citizenship, like pride, homogeneity.”82 Homogeneity should be valued not just in itself but for what it makes possible. “You can not have untrammeled law and order and wise liberty unless you have equality, and you can not have equality unless you have fraternity and likeness of thought, if not an identity.”83 Homogeneity led to stability, which made possible “common belief, common aspirations, common devotion.”84 Sameness also laid the foundation for social constancy. “The stability of a country depends upon the homogeneity of its population—where ideals and aspirations go along the same lines; where the ideals in relation to government, in relation to social conditions, and as to guarantees of property and personal rights are in harmony.”85 Figure 3 reproduces a graphic demonstration of the relationship between us and them, old and new. Difference was a threat. The Japanese belief that their emperor was connected to God meant that they could never assimilate while retaining their faith.86 “We have admitted the dregs of Europe until America has been orientalized, Europeanized, Africanized, and mongrelized to that insidious degree that our genius, stability, greatness, and promise of advancement and achievement are actually menaced.”87 These qualities were not just good to have but were necessary for survival. The strength of a nation—not to speak of its progress, its honor, its glory—the very strength of a nation lies in the oneness of its people. I
Fig. 3. “Old” and “new” European immigration—United States. (From the Congressional Record 65, pt. 4 [68C\1S], 14 March 1924, 4172.)
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
71
have only to invite the thoughts of men to travel over the earth and see those races which have maintained their nationality, their institutions, and it will be perceived that those nations which were uni‹ed, knit together have survived, while those made up of divergent interests, divergent races, hostile races, unsympathetic races have either fallen by virtue of dangers from within or have become easy prey to dangers from without.88 The country’s recent emergence as a world power brought attention to its faults. Still, “never anywhere in the history of all the world has there been a country with institutions as broad and great and liberal as this, and hence I believe it is time for us to look about and inquire whether at any time there is to be in this country such a thing as a distinctive nationality.”89 If the United States were to pursue international greatness, it must ‹rst clean house. Instability threatened the country because the pace of assimilation was too slow. “We already have as many foreigners here as the melting pot can melt, and, in my judgement, we have too many here already.”90 Foreign-language newspapers both signaled and created instability; they made obvious to English speakers how many preferred another language, but also how easy spreading foreign secrets in “code” would be. The English language divided “us” from “them.” The urban polyglot became the source of nervous joking, as well as army investigations. This is typical: “You know, a couple of fellows were walking along the streets of New York the other day when one stopped, and the other one said, grabbing him, ‘What’s wrong?’ The other said, ‘I thought I heard a couple of fellows talking English back there’ (Laughter).”91 Homogeneity’s most obvious advantages were those of culture. If everyone had been socialized into similar values and mores, communication was easier, and government was simpler. In this view, that those with similar backgrounds were of similar races was due to history, not inherence or destiny; “the desirability of an immigrant does not depend so much on his racial blood as it depends upon the moral standards of the country from which he comes.”92 Race was, then, simply an indirect indicator of political attitudes. The people coming to us from northern and western Europe readily assimilate and harmonize with our Government and our institutions. They have known freedom and have enjoyed freedom for more than a century. On the other hand, the people coming to us from eastern and southern Europe until recently were under the despotic Governments of Russia, Bulgaria, Turkey, Austria, Hungary, and so forth.
72
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
. . . they nursed hate from their mother’s breast. . . . Government to them has meant slavery and oppression. Out of this condition naturally grows anarchy, bolshevism, communism, syndicalism, and other monstrous conceptions of law and government. This was their only way of expressing themselves against intolerable conditions.93 The war had made homogeneity’s value felt. America then had “too many voices, too many languages, and too many people who have never thought of the purposes or principles of this country.”94 To assure stability during the peace, the country would assimilate those who were there, then balance foreigners’ rates of immigration against their ignorance of AngloSaxon law. But for many, what mattered most was not just that Americans were similar to each other, but that they were racially identical. Asian exclusion and its arguments became the lever used to exclude other groups.95 The ‹rst Chinese Exclusion Act had become settled policy by the time Congress considered European restrictions. Restrictionists used it to cement the idea that restriction, even racially based restriction, was in principle acceptable. Anglo legislators and prominent members of the public might, in the 1920s, argue that Asians were more hardworking, honest, or Christian than most Americans, or even that one numbered them among one’s friends. By considering “Europeans” to be a category parallel to “Asians,” restrictionists drew on the precedent of Asian exclusion to justify “old” European restriction. Figure 4 shows how this was illustrated for Congress. But one could not argue that intermarriage was acceptable. Without intermarriage, restrictionists pointed out, there was segregation, which would of necessity prevent full assimilation. “A democracy is founded on equality, but there can be no equality when there can not be, ultimately, intermarriage among the people of a community. It goes to the very foundation of our American institutions, and in a country like ours, where the Government consists of the voice of the people, if we deteriorate the people by bringing them against impossible competition we destroy the factors for making the union great and strong.”96 Therefore, “because physical assimilation of oriental peoples is impossible, their incorporation into the body politic is impracticable and unwise.”97 Allowing in Asians would create yet another racial underclass, another group condemned by the dictates of their genes to the purgatory of second-class citizenship. “The policy of exclusion is an established American policy; it has already avoided and practically solved one race problem; it will, if continued and extended, solve all that may present themselves.”98 In any event, “if the onrushing horde continues in unabated numbers the dominance of the Anglo-Saxon is doomed on this continent.”99
Fig. 4. Immigration—United States. Territory covered by immigration laws. (From the Congressional Record 65, pt. 4 [68C/1S], 14 March 1924, 4173.)
74
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Exactly how Asians and members of other groups were supposed to be different from or inferior to northwestern Europeans was detailed by the joint immigration committee’s house eugenicist, Harry Laughlin. His ‹ndings about relative intelligence and social behavior grounded racial exclusion scienti‹cally.100 He found ethnic groups in varying degrees to be substandard as workers, employers, community members, marriage partners, soldiers, and citizens. According to one report, New York in the 1910s spent $4 million annually just on insane Austrians, while 50 percent of Italians went crazy in the United States.101 “The Japanese do not create,” stated V. S. McClatchy, a California newspaper baron. “They imitate, improve, appropriate.”102 Americans were white. “Who are they about whom all these tears are being shed? Three hundred and forty-three Turks—also some 70 Africans.”103 Racial similarity produced what citizens valued about the United States. The commissioner-general of immigration re›ected that the acid test of any civilization, nation, or system of government is the men and women it produces, and with equal truth it may be said that the acid test of men and women at any time is the nation and system of government they evolve, the conditions of living they develop. To say that good immigration means good citizenship, is to state a selfevident truth, a fact so obvious that its bare assertion seems super›uous; [since 1882] the major test of eligibility to citizenship has been racial.104 This was especially important for the United States, whose sovereign was its majority; “it therefore makes a vast difference to us what that majority is, both now and in the future, and it is for us to decide while we are still that majority.”105 For 300 years this country got along ‹ne without any citizenship standards. True; but it is also true that for 3,000 years the world muddled along somehow without either science or order; but, gentlemen, that time has passed. We live in another age, the age of science, the age of progress based on the test of experience. In every branch of our civilization except citizenship, the most vital of all, our progress rests on standardization.106 If science demonstrated racial hierarchy, then racial standardization was the obvious next step. Figure 5 reproduces one of the graphs that Laughlin had entered into the Record.
Fig. 5. Intelligence rating. This is one of several charts presented by eugenicist Harry Laughlin to the immigration committees. (From Europe as an Emigrant-Exporting Country and the United States as an Immigrant-Receiving Nation, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives [68C/1S], 8 March 1927; between pages 1278 and 1279.)
76
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
With nonwhite citizens, American democracy was doomed to collapse. “We in this country have been so imbued with the idea of democracy, or the equality of all men, that we have left out of consideration the matter of blood or natural inborn heredity mental and moral differences. No man who breeds pedigreed plants and animals can afford to neglect this thing.”107 Assimilation was a failed dream. “We are slowly awakening to the consciousness that education and environment do not fundamentally alter racial values.”108 Not only did America’s own experience bear this out, but so did the entire history of Europe. That the people of all that region [southeastern Europe] are mongrels, mixed and intermixed from invading and near-by races from the north, from the brown people of the east, and the black people of the south is well known to every student. That they are incapable of working out the problems of government and protecting themselves against the destructive forces moving among them is made plain by their present plight and by conditions prevailing among them since antiquity and promising to continue forever.109 Europe’s problems, the problems it had foisted on the United States, were racial in origin. For the United States to escape the same fate, it had to work for racial identity. Racialists were more pessimistic than assimilationists about America’s capacity to overcome Old World differences. Homogeneity, whether of race or background, stabilized society. At best, heterogeneity meant “racial indigestion.”110 Too large a ›ow led to “indigestible lumps in the national stomach and . . . insoluble blood clots in the national circulation.”111 At worst, it would lead to war. Whereas those focused on domestic colonization feared that foreign-sponsored cells would rise up to cripple the country, those focused on homogeneity were frightened of civil strife. The Civil War, then only ‹fty years past, served as their model. The lesson they drew from it in this context was that racial difference was a drag on local communities, leading to con›ict. “Internal disorders become the consequence of unassimilable racial groups”;112 speci‹cally, “there has also been a menace to our institutions in not trying vigorously to weld the 42 nationalities here into a united people with a common language rather than in a happy-go-lucky way allowing them to transplant and perpetuate on American soil Old World hatreds and bolshevistic ideas.”113 Europe was always the premier model. “I believe now more ‹rmly than ever that races will stick together. There must be some reason. In Europe, where there is so much trouble, often when you cross a river you step from one nation to another nation. You ‹nd the people not only
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
77
speaking a different language but hating the people on the other side of the river with all their might . . . [just as is true of] the hyphenated American; we can see what we are breeding in the United States (Applause).”114 The American South was another model. Drawing an analogy to the southern Europeans and Asians, William Howard warned, “We have had a burden of a million and a half niggers in Georgia ever since the Civil War who were turned loose on us in their ignorance.”115 William Vaile, similarly, argued that “if we have to have another servient race brought into this country in order to promote production, then let us get along without the production, even if it hurts an industry of my own district (Applause).”116 Con›ict, which would likely be racial con›ict, could lead to all-out war. Restriction’s bottom line was to “prevent another race problem from arising up in this country”117 and leading again to war. Homogeneity became linked conceptually not only to American institutions’ stability but also to their quality. Good citizens (white citizens) made good government. President Coolidge in a message to Congress announced that “American institutions rest solely on good citizenship. They were created by people who had a background of self-government.”118 Representative Garber elaborated on this. “The strength of those institutions and of the Government does not lie in the area of our territory, our material resources, the number of our population, or our standing Army. It lies in the quality of our citizenship. . . . Lower the quality of citizenship and you decrease the quality of government. . . . What is the remedy? . . . Close the gates!”119 Importing bad people could corrupt citizens: “Importing cheap labor and people alien to our institutions, to our methods of government, is sti›ing unborn children and preventing them from having the privileges they ought to have in this country (Applause).”120 If immigrants were accepted, they would “reproduce here the conditions from which they ›ee.”121 Underlying the claim that the degree of the population’s whiteness created the strength of democratic institutions was the notion that institutions are themselves organic, a notion that also underlaid the idea that immigration was a virus or poison. Like children, institutions have a biological heritage that in›uences their strength. Republics are not exempt from mutability, or decay. Republics are no natural system. They are the highest form of civilized government where the rights of men are held of value. A republic is subject to internal dangers as well as foreign menaces. In order that it may live it is absolutely necessary that we maintain a certain type of citizenship. . . . But above all things, in order to assure the stability, in order to make certain the future strength and
78
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
righteousness of this Nation, we must strive for homogeneity among the citizenship. Therein lies the strength of a republic. As nearly as we can, we should seek for and have racial homogeneity; but assuredly we should have homogeneity in the sense of common belief, common aspirations, common devotion.122 Democratic institutions were peculiarly vulnerable to abuse. “Under our form of Government there is necessity for the highest intelligence, and therefore we are concerned with the types of men or races that shall be permitted to enter the United States and permanently abide therein.”123 The New York Chamber of Commerce asserted that “of all forms of administration, democracy is particularly susceptible to the in‹ltration of foreign elements that do not understand or appreciate the customs and government of the new land in which they settle.”124 American institutions were the product of a peculiarly white culture. “But do we wish to surrender this country to them [the Japanese] or shall we insist that this country shall be preserved for the white race?”125 Encouraged by others’ examples, representatives decided that, too, “our business is to build up, as the Australians are trying to do, a white man’s country.”126 California and the western territories were on the frontier, not only geographically but politically. “We on the western borders are the defenders of our white civilization. Are we to fall before the onslaught of peaceful invasion and look forward to the time when the Japanese on the Paci‹c coast will hold the balance of power?”127 Heterogeneity, of race or political socialization, divided the American public, segregating segments and thereby retarding its growth. This weakness, stemming from division and apathy even if not the result of a purposeful foreign plot, would eventually sap democratic institutions’ strength. Sooner or later, the country would die. Homogeneity attracted those most concerned about the devastation that pluralism wrought on American society and its international position. Neither the country’s particular war experience nor recent effects of interdependence motivated their arguments; rather, “war” in the abstract repelled them. War, any war, was due to pluralism—racial pluralism. The country had changed in many ways since the time that restrictionists perceived as its golden age. Ethnic diversi‹cation preceded the SpanishAmerican War and World War I and, many restrictionists believed, had forced the country into both wars, just as the presence of Black Americans had inevitably led the country into its civil war. This idea led restrictionists to advocate at least ethnic, but preferably racial, homogeneity. Putting this idea into practice could involve moves to declare an ethnic norm, then to deport those who deviated from it and/or to exclude new immigrants from
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
79
entry based on this classi‹cation. The main criterion for inclusion would be similarity to current Americans. Homogeneity, others argued, was not a worthwhile goal. At best, it was irrelevant to the country’s success. At worst, advertising America’s newfound commitment to homogeneity would antagonize foreigners and domestic minorities, leading to armed con›ict. World War I loomed here, too. Homogeneity’s sudden value confused many because during the war, “Such dangers as had threatened our government had been averted; such dangers as the world had never seen before had been suppressed. . . . We came forth a Nation of free men no longer recognizing any distinction of nationalities or creed. Our Republic had successfully ended the experiment of its existence and took its place, a full, round, high place—‹rst—among the powers of the earth.”128 The mixed country was the most successful. “We have recently emerged from the greatest war in history in which we may proudly say that our Nation reached spiritual heights never attained by any other nation.”129 The commissioner-general of immigration argued that to think otherwise was unpatriotic. “It is obvious that if the principles of our Government are sound they will stand the test of all conditions; and his con‹dence in and loyalty to them is of a wavering and conditional character who, either explicitly or by a necessary implication, discloses a belief that they require amendment in time of war. If they are not good in times of war, neither are they of value in times of peace.”130 Such worries were beneath the United States. “While this sort of national frailty is excusable in old nations, Asiatic or European, it is incomprehensible when found among the American people, full of the vigor of youth and absorbing unto itself all that is strong and virile in the human stock.”131 Homogeneity was simply not a relevant concern. Others argued that international problems or civil war would result not from too many groups, but from their forcible uni‹cation. It would be obvious to all that “we, in trying to restrict, in reality discriminate. We are now in the age of international amity. We are on friendly terms with all the great powers of the world. . . . The smoke of guns is hardly cleared away. The world still bleeds from the wounds of World War, and we in Congress are preparing to deal a blow to our friends and allies during this terrible con›ict waged so that the world might be safe for democracy.”132 The country itself would not be safe for democracy either, for “you are dividing your people into two classes, a superior class and an inferior class; and if anything can possibly bring Bolshevism in America it is class distinction, race hatred, and prejudice, which must cause discontent, which is unAmerican and undemocratic.”133 Acceptance of all citizens would assure peace; discrimination, even indirect discrimination through immigration policy, would assure bitterness.
80
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Whites were not better than others in any event. “If these ‘Nordics’ are God’s chosen people, why did they borrow their religion from the hills of Judea, their laws from the Roman forum, and their arts from the galleries of Athens?”134 Rather, “the belief in Nordic superiority has grown to large proportions mainly because people like to believe in such superiority and do not take the trouble to examine for the truth of such superiority.”135 Nordics were, in fact, worse behaved. “There is not a case on record where it can be said that the Italians have at any time . . . been so sel‹sh in their administration as to arrogate all the bene‹ts therefrom to themselves and their religious confreres. This has been done in many large cities and the culprits are by no means the immigrants from Southern Europe nor from Italy, but on the contrary they are Nordics and thoroughly Anglo-Saxon.”136 White supremacy was an ironic boast. Further reasons to oppose racial discrimination were the same as those given in opposition to the country’s general pursuit of homogeneity: it would cause embarrassment and lead to armed con›ict. Anti-Japanese laws would embarrass the administration.137 “We do contend that it [openness] is absolutely necessary at this time in order that the peaceful relations of the world shall continue, because as a matter of fact our relation to the Japanese immigrant is something more than that; it covers the broader relations of the Occident with the Orient.”138 Japan was, moreover, looking for an excuse for war: “With a danger I believe a serious one, with developments coming in the future that might lead to war, I think it is extremely important that we keep our skirts clear, and have nothing on this side that they can bring up as an excuse that there was discrimination against them, and things of that kind.”139 “Here we are, one on one side of the Paci‹c and the other on the other, and for the future peace of the world, for our own freedom from attack, and for the avoidance of friction, it is absolutely essential that we should maintain friendly relations with that country [Japan].”140 Domestic war could follow. Racial exclusion would “be the ‹rst instance in our modern legislation for writing into our laws the hateful doctrine of inequality between the various component parts of our population.”141 Discrimination would demoralize ethnic Americans.142 Liberals valued the principles upon which they believed the country had been founded and to which they believed it must remain true. Pluralism attracted those who believed that it created or re›ected strength. Decadent empires glori‹ed nativism. The United States was beyond such ideas. Individualism was also a founding liberal principle that could be honored only by assessing individuals on their merits, with merit understood to be calculated with regard only to a person’s acts. Liberals therefore desired a selection/restriction process based upon individual merit.
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
81
Since current policy excluded only on the basis of individual merit, liberals could argue for the status quo. They would also favor including Asians in the applicant pool, eliminating bloc restrictions. Reasons: Europe as Contaminant or Heritage
The argument constructed originally to explain Asian exclusion applied by extension to southern Europeans who were also not white by current standards. The anti-Asian argument did most of the logical work promoting European restriction (though most of the arguments were not strictly logical, even by loose standards). Rather, the impetus for restricting Europeans came from Americans’ lessons from the war. The American experience demonstrated that neither Europe nor former Europeans in the United States were to be trusted. Their loyalties during the war, in American eyes, damned immigrants who fought for the cause as well as those who fought against it. “The war awoke the public to the situation as never before.”143 It did so by revealing the sickness at the country’s core. “We boasted of the ‘melting pot’ and of our ability to assimilate all races and colors and tongues and tribes. When the war broke out in 1914, it became manifest that we had not really assimilated these alien additions to our population in any appreciable degree”;144 in fact, “during the Great World War, . . . it looked as though we had allowed in›uences to enter our borders that were about to melt the pot in place of us being the melting pot.”145 If an immigrant fought for the Allied cause, it was simply luck that the United States was ‹ghting on the side of his homeland. If he did not, that treachery showed the thinness of his ties to the United States. “The Americanization of these thirty-six and a third million of our population is, in many cases, only skin deep and is merely a mask to be quickly thrown aside when the interests of their dear fatherland are involved, as has been abundantly shown by the conduct of the so-called German-Americans during and since the World War.”146 If he stayed behind to work in the war effort, he was taking advantage of Americans’ absence to buy up the country. “From all the country comes the cry of the rank injustice of forcing American citizens into the war, while alien slackers are here in vast numbers enjoying the peaceful privileges of our country and immunity from ‹ghting for the very integrity of their countries.”147 If he refused to ‹ght, he was truly loathsome. “Certainly an alien subject of a country at war with the central powers becomes most undesirable here when he is able-bodied, within military age, has no dependents, and yet refuses to ‹ght either for this or for his own country.”148 Even had Congress considered European immigrants to have acted nobly during the war, it might not have changed its anti-European views.
82
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Isolating America from war meant isolating it from European wars, and if wars were in the Europeans’ blood, preventing war meant keeping out Europeans. In the decade before the war started, immigration to the United States had been increasing steadily; European immigrants were ever more visible in urban areas. During the war, Americans were sent to Europe, to live with Europeans and be killed taking care of their troubles. By the time of the Armistice, they had had enough. “A short time since we looked upon Europe with comparative indifference as she grappled with her great social problems, as we felt her problems could never be ours. But to-day we are not only face-to-face with those social problems but are fast being carried into European militarism, from which God grant we may be spared (Applause).”149 Isolation was the obvious answer. “We do not intend to close the door because we were here ‹rst; we close it because it is our door. We are now under a reaction of the effects of the World War; we are sick and tired of Europe and all its works; we want to develop our character along our own lines.”150 Europe was poison. Others explained restriction in a way that salvaged the country’s immigrant past. Times change and men change with them. It was originally true that the people who left America and came to Europe were the boldest, the bravest, the most enterprising, and those who most sought freedom; but tempora mutantur, nos et mutamur in illio—those times have changed and people have changed with the times. . . . The man who comes to America to-day is the wage-earner or else the political nondescript, who has been cast out in his own country because of socialistic or anarchistic opinions of some description.151 A tract entitled “Immigration and the Three Percent Restrictive Law,” written by Robert DeC. Ward, argued that the quality of new immigration was inferior, echoing the “new/old” distinction articulated decades earlier by Chairman Dillingham.152 Europeans had also been enemies. Excluding them on those grounds as well was fair.153 Apart from their behavior during the war, Americans still found much to fault in Europeans’ political allegiances. It seemed that everyone in Europe who was not a monarchist was an anarchist or a bolshevik. “They have never drawn the breath of freedom, they have never lived under a republic; and it is the history of most Latin [European] countries that a republic can not prevail, that they live greatly in revolution and fomentation. Any judge can constitute an alien an American citizen, but it takes a change of heart and mind to make an American.”154 Subservient
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
83
people could not last in a democracy, and “As you know, dictatorships are in existence in practically every country which claimed it was being discriminated against by the 1890 census date. However, we do not want that sort of government in this country. Mussolini has done marvels for Italy, but nobody here would want a government of that kind.”155 Neither did anyone want civil upheaval and revolution. “At the present time there is a good deal of turmoil in the various nations of the earth. There are certain places where one side gets into power to-day and another side tomorrow. The ‹rst side then takes to the woods, and they would all be political refugees. These seasons of turmoil reappear frequently, and this provision [for refugees] would send a ›ood tide to America.”156 War lurked everywhere. Civil wars turned into international wars, which bred revolutionary wars. Legislators especially feared a reenactment of the “Russian debacle ushering in the four horsemen of the Apocalypse.”157 To subvert the United States and strengthen themselves, moreover, “some of the foreign countries are preparing to dump on America ten, twelve, or ‹fteen million people.”158 Legislators feared that revolution could be contagious. Since the world’s Great War, many dangerous and deadly doctrines have sprung up throughout Europe; governments have been changed over night, and in many instances the rights of property and freedom of speech and action are unknown. These same dangerous and deadly doctrines have been spread throughout this country, to a great extent, by foreign propaganda and foreigners. . . . Not long since Lenin, the great leader of the Communist party, which controls Russia, died; and since that time over a thousand memorials have been held in this country for him. This shows the dangers which we face and that it is up to the American people to see that America is kept American (Applause).159 Suspension or vigilant immigration restriction was an obvious answer. Those unwilling to conclude that Europeans were all undesirable might still consider that the best Europeans would not emigrate; they would stay to rebuild. Those who immigrated, then, rather than Europeans in general, were policy’s targets.160 “The real workers, the men who would be economically useful, are remaining in their own countries assisting in their upbuilding and recuperation from the devastation of the war.”161 Emigrants could only be bad. “There are only two classes of immigrants who want to come to this country now, namely, the cowardly slacker who does not want to help rehabilitate the country in which he
84
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
lives and which was devastated by the war, and the other one is the man who wants to come here to accumulate worldly goods and then go back to the country from which he came.”162 Before the war, those who favored European exclusion did so for racial reasons. Southern Europeans were non-Anglo and therefore undesirable. After the war, Europeans’ behavior during the war years provided an additional reason to refuse them entry. Restrictionists valued a patriotism that many believed pluralism only weakened; Europe’s particular problems created speci‹c threats to American unity and strength that could be addressed narrowly. Implementing this could be done by targeting all Europeans or by focusing on racially inferior (southern) Europeans. As proposals to exclude Europeans proliferated, those who opposed this exclusion scrambled to make opposite arguments. Heterogeneity was better than homogeneity; European ties were a bene‹t, not a drag. Restriction’s opponents claimed that restriction was nothing more than an irrational xenophobia. The war and the present postwar period, both redolent with hysteria, offer the worst possible background for reasoning out the immigration problem. As a result of the ordeal of the war we are still hysterical about immigration. The ultra restrictionist and those behind the Johnson bill [for national origins quotas] claim we are a disunited people. Nothing is further from the truth. The war proved that of all nations in the combat we were the most united. We were successful in welding our many peoples without the use of force or coercion. The methods embodied in the Johnson bill are the forceful methods used by Germany to assimilate her people.163 The war was to blame for this new wave of feeling. “After every foreign war comes a resurgence of chauvinism. It is the scum that boils up out of the cauldron of disorder, bloodshed, and national hatreds.”164 Europe was neither bad nor good. “The ‹eld of thought recognizes no barriers. . . . We brought over the idea of deportation of radicals from France, not from the France of Rousseau, Jaurès, and Victor Hugo but from the France of the Bourbons.”165 Anti-European feeling had no basis. World War I was also important to restriction’s opponents. Europeans were enemies, but they were allies too; some even fought with American forces. Not only should Americans not shun Europeans, they owed many of them a great deal. “The adult foreigner now has a just obligation due him from this Nation, because of his services and the services of his fellows during the World War.”166 Many of the restrictionists’ targets were from southern Europe, but “Croatia and Slovenia were part of Austria-
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
85
Hungary, and every one of these Croatians and Slovenians knew that in case he became a prisoner of war, he would be shot as a traitor.”167 European countries would surely be confused. “At whom are you striking in this bill? Why, at the very people whom a short while ago you announced you were going to emancipate. We sent 2,000,000 men abroad to make the world ‘safe for democracy,’ to liberate these very people. Now you shut the door to them”;168 “It is curious to note that, taking the census of 1890 as a basis, Belgium, Bohemia, Italy, Yugoslavia, Poland, Rumania, and Russia, with whom we were associated as allies during the late con›ict, would be in the most unfavorable position.”169 If the recent alliance were insuf‹cient reason, current alliances surely must be. “We can not isolate ourselves, nor should we wound the sensibilities of our friends and allies.”170 Foreign relations were far too important to jeopardize in a ‹t of postwar prejudice. Restrictions would turn out to be super›uous anyway, making Europe’s inevitable retaliation ironic. “I believe that the economic rehabilitation of Europe has tended to check immigration and also has tended to increase the returning ›ow. I also believe that the destruction of autocracy and the establishment of new republics in Europe have tended to retard immigration and have also tended to increase the return movement.”171 Europe does not take protectionist legislation lightly, rewarding only openness. “But this [immigration] bill does not aim to open foreign markets. It aims to close them still further. It aims to anger many countries of Europe; its purpose will be to close European markets to American goods, agricultural, manufactured, and raw materials. . . . for the stigmatized nations of Europe will not take the insult lying down. They are going to bridle up, for all peoples have deep-seated national pride and national honor that must be satis‹ed.”172 The United States courted catastrophe in the interdependent world. “A discriminatory law may rebound to our embarrassment in the conduct of our foreign trade. . . . If these countries should choose to reciprocate by discriminating against American-made products, as is entirely within their rights, the effect of this law would be disastrous to our American industries.”173 Obligations underlined these interests: “We should not be so completely obsessed by nativism, by the shibboleth ‘America for Americans,’ as to forget that we belong to a family of nations with whom we desire to keep on friendly and cordial relations and to carry on international trade and commerce, [not] give affront to friendly nations and humiliate large numbers of our fellow citizens.”174 The Cuban ambassador warned that likely immigrants “will then select Europe in preference to the United States for traveling and for the purpose of education. As a result, the commercial and business relations of Cuba with the United States,
86
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
which depends to a large extent on this intercourse, will suffer, while those with Europe will tend to increase proportionately by the transfer of interest from the United States to Europe.”175 Isolation would harm the country economically, politically, and culturally. Principle was, also, at stake. The United States had a hand in creating the European conditions from which people ›ed. It should therefore have a hand in remedying the upheaval. “The conditions existing in Europe today . . . were created by causes that we approved and in which we participated. These same conditions that have made the lot of the human race desperate and pathetic were of our will, our vote, our action in this House, and I wish to enter a solemn protest in the very beginning against the utter lack of sympathy, international comity, and international gratitude wrapped up in the proposed passage of the measure.”176 Internationalists favored immigration generally and European immigration speci‹cally. Europeans were trading partners, and relatives, and allies. The American people owed Europe a great deal, and at least ought to have no complaint against Europeans. Since European immigration was unrestricted during the debates, liberals could simply argue against change, if they wished. Most, however, argued for the status quo: individual-level screening with no numerical or categorical limits.
Reason: Geopolitics—Consistency across Hemispheres or Pan-Americanism
Restriction applied to all Asians, and to most Europeans, but to no Americans. Congress exempted the Western Hemisphere from the quotas. In fact, the possibility of including them was hardly discussed. Legislators on the fringes, those who believed in comprehensive openness or in immigration suspension, attempted to use open immigration from the Americas to demonstrate hypocrisy, to show that restrictionists did not really care for restricting numbers, protecting labor and social stability, but intended instead to exclude based on race or to include for base economic reasons. Each side believed that “this bill is the kind of bill that locks the front door and leaves all the back windows and all the back doors open.”177 Ultrarestrictionists argued that the American public wanted to extend restriction to the Western Hemisphere178 and opposed “exceptions which would ›ood the country with Mexican peons and other pauper laborers.”179 Mexicans they found distasteful. “On the basis of merit Mexico is the last country in the world to which we should grant a special favor or extend a peculiar privilege. . . . Henceforth let us meet Mexicans and all
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
87
other immigrants in excess of the minimum quota at the international boundary line and the water’s edge with the stirring Garibaldian battle cry with which Pétain’s heroes turned the tide of victory at Verdun and proclaim to all the world ‘they shall not pass.’”180 Inconsistency and Mexicans’ undesirability were, however, the only reasons ultrarestrictionists gave. When staff pointed out that annual intra-American immigrants numbered only in the hundreds, the ultrarestrictionists abandoned this tack. Opponents of restriction, on the other hand, asserted that restriction threatened pan-American accord. The policy dictated by this amendment [to exclude Western Hemisphere migrants] is obviously unwise if we intend to attach any importance to the Pan-Americanism idea. We are alien to our neighbors in South and Central America by language. Their natural resort is to Paris and to Madrid. For every thing they buy and almost every thought they think they naturally refer to those two centers. If we want to hold them to us—and I think we do so long as we maintain the Monroe Doctrine—we have got to treat them differently from the rest of the world.181 Money was also at stake. “It is to Latin America, South America and Mexico, that this country must look for the promotion of trade, and, in large part, to increase our foreign commerce in order to build up and aid American industry.”182 Mexican laborers created prosperity for the United States and Mexico, and “trade and commerce mean peace.”183 Domestic peace would also be assured. “You speak about your socialism and everything like that, but whenever a man becomes a land owner that goes out the window and he becomes a different citizen.”184 Whereas European immigration promised nothing but social and political headaches, Mexican immigration had entirely economic consequences and would thereby maintain international accord. Because restriction’s opponents, largely northern and eastern legislators, had argued on principle, they would not reverse to support Western Hemisphere exclusion. Because restriction’s supporters, largely southern and western legislators, had not based their arguments on principle but on particular charges against Europeans, they could support continued openness without risking charges of hypocrisy. Because they represented large ranching states, they did so. The alliance of pan-Americanism and ranching interests, eased by a convenient lack of principled argument, exempted the Western Hemisphere from restriction with no ‹ght at all. This debate was entirely derivative of the main debate on European exclusion. Chang-
88
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
ing European policy became the strongest reason given for changing policy toward the Western Hemisphere. The debate, for this reason, makes no sense apart from the larger context. Resolving the Public Interest: The Quota Acts
Restrictionists valued sovereignty, autonomy, plenary exclusion, vigilant defense against domestic and foreign enemies, homogeneity to ensure social and institutional stability, and high racial and political standards to assure that the un‹t could not enter. They assessed the country’s options as if the country were an egoist (though they themselves might not be): of most value were a strong, independent identity, corporal health, and the means to defend oneself and reproduce. Opponents of restriction stressed liberal values: neutrality, equity, wealth. They assessed the country’s options as if the country were a universalist (though they, too, might not be): of most value was treating individuals as they deserved to be treated based on their past acts, as well as shunning behavior that categorized people according to characteristics that they had no control over. Restrictionists’ weakest point politically was their advocacy of arbitrary (racial) discrimination against citizens, that is, the charge that they were degrading citizens by disparaging others of their ethnic groups. Americans were, after all, supposed to consider citizens equal before the law. Monarchies, not democracies, separated citizens by law into classes. Their opponents’ weakest point was their denial that instability was a valid fear. As Americans, they could not pretend indifference to subversion. Both groups selected the proposals that became the Quota Law and the National Origins Quota Law from many other proposals; these are themselves a subset of imagined alternatives. Coming out of this debate could have been any number of policy decisions, ranging from doing away with screening altogether to suspending all immigration permanently, with the decision simply to maintain the status quo far more toward the liberal than the restrictive side. Rarely did contestants discuss the policy’s effects on others, but when the issue of relative power did come up, no one offered evidence other than that which would suggest that Europe would in fact be worse off than the United States. Restriction was the most popular proposal, for all of the reasons outlined above, and restriction’s advocates were far more numerous than its opponents. Figure 6 outlines the arguments that were made during this debate. Massive numerical restriction therefore became the starting point from which the ‹nal policy would be constructed. Those arguing against restriction on the grounds that it was wrong in principle should have been
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
89
Russo-Japanese War World War I ⇓ Causal Argument
Public Interest Argument
Discriminating among citizens destroys democracy
Democracy must be preserved to guarantee a civic culture
We must avoid denying only some citizens’ coethnics entrance
Heterogeneity causes civil and international war by creating an incoherent society
Preventing war is in the public interest because democracy is impossible without order and peace
Allowing in immigrants racially like Americans prevents war and preserves civilization
Class rifts cause civil war by stirring up hatred and inviting Bolsheviks to interfere in domestic affairs
Preventing war is in the public interest because democracy is impossible without order and peace
Banning unions will prevent civil war
Only the white race produced a civilization
Democracy depends on the ability to be self-governing
Allowing only whites to immigrate will preserve civilization
↑ ↑ plausibility
↑
Policy Argument
Implementation
(Since there was no policy in place, no arguments about implementation failures were made in this early period)
↑ efficiency
↑
↓ Ideas about Causation: Racism Causes War Perverse Effects: War with Japan, Depression Fig. 6.
Arguments made preceding the Quota Acts
least in›uential in ‹nalizing policy. Few took their position at all seriously, and they never even made a counterproposal. An assumption underlying their view, that Americans should not ignore foreigners’ claims, was anathema to all but a handful of nationally elected of‹cials. Yet two elements of it, that discrimination was wrong and that a policy that favored some subgroups over others was an insult and an injustice to everyone, struck a chord. The legislators would not go so far as to accept that Americans should not be favored over others—that was too radical, and their jobs, after all, were premised on a discrete electorate—but they were deeply enough committed to the view that citizens should be treated
90
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
equally to cringe at the accusation of favoritism. The proposal at the center of debate shifted from one outlining numerical restriction based on country of recent immigrants’ origin to one based on all (or rather almost all) Americans’ countries of origin. National origins quotas solved this dilemma. They did so, ironically for the liberals, by reducing even further the number of non-“Nordics”; the law’s amendment re›ected a move toward a more, not less, conservative policy than the one preceding it. Its amendment did, though, respond to the more resonant objections that the liberals brought. By basing the quotas on the national origins of the entire (Anglo-European—Africans and Asians were excluded from the assessment)185 population instead of the recent immigrants, no one could complain of discrimination. There were no longer second-class citizens. “Discrimination of citizens is unwise and improper. It is just and proper for a host to invite as his guests whomsoever he pleases, but having invited them it is unjust and improper to show any distinction among them.”186 Immigration would perfectly re›ect the citizens’ makeup. This justi‹cation persuaded not only most of those who had been restrictionist all along, but also most of the new members and most of those who had withheld their votes the ‹rst time. In 1921, the House chose, 276 to 33, with 120 not voting, to impose a ceiling of 150,000 immigrants per year, allocated by country according to the country’s contribution of immigrants in the recent past. Those who were strongly committed did not change their votes; only 18 of those who had voted de‹nitely yes or no changed their minds and voted the opposite way. Change came rather from two other directions, from selection through elections, which that year focused on the immigration question, and from the persuasion of those who had been teetering. Table 1 shows the actual immigration ›ows from the parts of the world discussed in the immigration debate, and then indicates the allotment given them by Congress. New members, who voted three to one for national origins quotas, replaced the old, and of those who had refrained from voting in the earlier period, twelve times as many chose restriction as chose to oppose it. In 1924, the House decided 308 to 62, with 63 not voting, to change the basis for distributing immigration slots: the national origins of the entire population, rather than of recent immigrants, was a more justi‹able basis for assigning quotas than were the alternatives. Although those opposed to restriction offered “national origins” as a way to free immigration, its logic meant a far more restrictive policy than restrictionists had ever advocated or even contemplated, and this is what the country got. Henry Cabot Lodge, a staunch restrictionist, was one of the ‹rst to propose national origins as a solution. “If such a basis is adopted, there
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
91
can be no question then of discrimination, because it will treat all races alike on the basis of their actual proportion of the existing population.”187 Others repeated this argument almost verbatim, establishing consensus by repetition. If we divide up our immigrants exactly in accordance with the national origins of our whole population, there can be no charge of discrimination.188 The idea of the national origins amendment is that we will establish a method against which there can not be the slightest accusation of discrimination . . . We talk about the melting pot to-day, and what we mean by the melting pot is that a nation of one kind of people is getting an in›ow of different kinds of people; but we will not need any melting pot if our immigration is just a cross section of our present population.189 If Congress were to adopt that ‹gure, 300,000, it would apportion that quota exactly in accordance with the national origin of every man, woman, and child in America today according to the 1920 census. The trouble with the present system and with this 1910 suggestion is that it divides the quota according to the foreign born of 1910 . . . dividing the quotas 45 [northwestern European] and 55 percent [southeastern] in a country whose actual population has its origin as 74 is to 13.190 I do . . . insist that we are entitled to consider those of us who were born here as another element in determining the quotas. But no plan except the ‘national origins’ plan recognizes this elementary point. . . . there is not one word that anyone can say against the principle of dividing our immigrants according to the national or racial origins of those already here.191 The fairest basis would be one which would make our immigration from European countries most nearly approximate in racial qualities the present population of the United States.192 The national origins system would make immigration restriction fair to United States citizens. It would treat new and old immigrants equally when allocating quotas. Legislators valued the nondiscrimination aspects of the law for this reason, but they also valued them particularly because of their experiences
TABLE 1.
Immigration Patterns Preceding Quotas and the Quotas Actual 1898
1907
EUROPE 222,213 1,209,399 Albania Andorra Armenia German Empire 17,111 37,807 Austria 39,797 338,452 (or Austria-Hungary) Hungary Czechoslovakia Belgium 695 6,396 Danzig Free City Denmark 1,946 7,243 Estonia France 1,990 9,731 Great Britain 38,021 78,977 Ireland 34,530 Greece 2,339 36,580 Iceland Italy 58,613 285,731 Latvia Liechtenstein Lithuania Luxembourg Monaco Netherlands 767 6,637 Norway 4,938 22,133 Poland 4,726 Portugal 1,717 9,608 Romania 900 4,384 San Marino Spain 577 5,784 Sweden 12,398 20,589 Switzerland 1,246 3,748 Trieste Turkey (“Turkey in Europe” 4,451 28,820 plus “Turkey in Asia”) USSR/Russia 29,828 258,943 (and Finland 1898) Finland 1,898 1,907 Serbia, Bulgaria, Montenegro 11,359 Bulgaria Australia 153 1,947 (including New Zealand) New Zealand
Legal 1915
1922
1925
1930
192,268
355,929 288
7,799 9,215
67,607 7,342
341,770 100 100 124 51,227 785
150,815 100 100 124 27,370
869 2,874 1,304 100 1,181 116 3,086 65,721 17,853 307 100 5,802 236 100 386 100 100 3,153 2,377 6,524 440 295 100 252 3,314 1,707
4,907 481
3,607 12,202 30,977 2,465 7,419
2,762 6,585 1,742
912 20,042 3,752
473 3,073 512 228 2,789 124 3,954 34,007 28,567 100 100 3,845 145 100 344 100 100 1,648 6,453 5,982 503 603 100 131 9,561 2,081
4,551
2,654
100
226
26,187
24,405
2,248
2,784
3,921 1,922 6,426 302 121
471 1,925 671 100 121
569 1,930 845 100 100
100
100
100
2,399 3,312 4,811 27,237 14,185 12,592 49,688
5,747 14,357 1,563 301 5,619 1,348 5,729 77,342 3,063 42,057 1,540 2,629 92
3,144 7,986
1,915 1,403 1,282
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts Northwestern Europe Southeastern Europe
79,112 143,101
227,791 981,608
79,200 113,068
MIDDLE EAST AFRICA
93
197,776 158,153
141,220 20,550
127,466 23,349
800
800
800
48
1,486
934
1,000
1,000
1,000
8
42
117
400
400
400
ASIA Afghanistan Bhutan China India Japan Nepal Siam
4,301
32,085
11,434
2,071 2,230
961 898 30,226
2,660 161 8,613
700 100 100 100 100 100 100 100
700 100 100 100 100 100 100 100
700 100 100 100 100 100 100 100
WEST HEMISPHERE Unspecified or other
5,356 102
41,762 515
111,206 1,445
no limit
no limit
no limit
229,299 1,285,349
326,700
357,803
164,667
153,714
OCEANIA
Total
Source: All data taken from the Bureau of Immigration Annual Report, various years, table III. Note: Italics indicate Bureau of Immigration classification as Northwestern Europe.
during the war and because a national origins basis appeared to be scienti‹c. Many believed that heterogeneity had almost cost the country the war. Unity was especially important when Europe and others threatened the country. “If the war made for national unity in a larger sense than ever before, it seems to me that it would be wisest and best to base immigration not upon a percentage of foreign born in the country in any one year but upon all those who have come to our shores at any time since the foundation of the Government.”193 Unity would be little disturbed if the quotas were distributed fairly, and nothing was fairer than science.194 “I live in a sphere that is entirely above politics. . . . Congress shall ‹x the total of immigration to be permitted in any one year; that it shall then apportion that total to the various nations in exact accordance with their proportionate representation in the whole population of the United States at the present time.”195 Congress amended the Quota Act until it was less easily challenged on the grounds that it violated a universal principle on which public interest arguments in the United States were based: that abhorring legal distinctions among those given citizenship. The American people identi‹ed a threat from within. Believing that heterogeneity was permanent and must lead to political dissolution, they
TABLE 2.
The Quota Acts, 1921 and 1924
Act
Numerical Restrictions
Preference Categories
Unrestricted (Nonquota Immigrants)
Immigration Act of February 5, 1917
[none specified]
[none specified]
[none specified]
Quota Act (Burnett-Smith)
Overall ceiling: 356,995
•1st: Parents of citizens over the age of 21; persons with agricultural skills; some husbands •2d: Wives and unmarried children of resident aliens
•Those who had resided continuously for one year in an independent country of the Western Hemisphere •Domestic servants •Professional classes such as nurses and ministers
•Unmarried children under 21 •Parents •Spouses of U.S. citizens over age 21 •Skilled agricultural workers and their wives and children under 16
•U.S. citizens' wives and unmarried children under 18 •Western Hemisphere natives, or residents for at least 5 years
Act of May 19, 1921
National Origins Quota Act (Johnson-Reed) Immigration Act of May 26, 1924
Method of allocation: Each European country received a cap equal to 3 percent of the persons born there who were living in the U.S. in 1910 (the latest available census). To 1929 Overall ceiling: 164,667 Method of allocation: Each European country received a cap equal to 2 percent of the number of persons born there residing in the U.S. in 1890. After 1929 Overall ceiling: 153,714 Method of allocation: Each country received a cap based on the proportion of all U.S. residents, in 1920, of that nationality.
Exclusions •Illiterate aliens •Natives of Asian Barred Zone
•No one ineligible for citizenship
Whom to Exclude: The Quota Acts
95
created borders as a way to create an outside and an inside. This made it possible to externalize difference, the threat, and protect against it. Numerical restriction came in response to a fear that sovereignty was at stake; they framed qualitative restrictions in oppositional terms. National origins quotas were the product of a long process of debate, in which legislators revised their arguments until they more fully evoked the principles on which the idea of a public interest in the United States rested and formed an “identity response” to America’s changing involvement with the international environment. Or, as Woodrow Wilson described it, immigration policy was “a policy in which our people have conceived the very character of their Government to be expressed, the very mission and spirit of the Nation in respect of its relations to the people of the world outside their borders.”196 Table 2 summarizes the way in which the Quota Acts altered immigration policy. Whether this way of seeing policy change fares as well (or badly) in general can be seen through its performance throughout the next three periods during which Americans considered immigration policy.
CHAPTER 5
Whom to Exclude: The McCarran-Walter Act
Immigration policy remained essentially unaltered throughout the Great Depression, in spite of the doubling of tariffs, massive unemployment, western migration, and labor organizing. (The only major legislation of this period allocated special entry to a handful of Basque shepherds.) Instead, it was diplomatic imperatives that arose during World War II that forced attention to immigration policy. In many ways, the next debate reprised the earlier one, yet the earlier laws had established what were to become axioms of policy and in this way provided a context for subsequent arguments. By 1924, restrictionists had convinced Congress not only to limit the volume of annual immigration, but also to sift immigrants by ethnicity. Numerical restriction and racial-ethnic exclusion were not, in principle, subject to debate. They de‹ned the status quo, structuring the way that Americans understood immigration policy and the way it might change, and shaping the arguments that all, both conservatives and reformers, offered in the future. The restrictionists’ greatest victory was their ability to plant their understanding of absolute sovereignty in the public mind. Later groups had to accept that policy, with all of its assumptions, as their starting point. This bene‹ted those desiring retrenchment. But circumstances had changed. The United States was involved once again with Europe, but this time it would remain an internationalist and accept or seek hegemony. Restrictionists had either to make their old arguments convincing in new conditions or to fashion new arguments leading to the same policy outcome. Those trying to defend an idea already planted in the public mind, then, also had some dif‹culty. Continuity too would be an active political choice. The strategies, successes, and failures of those wishing to continue restriction, as well as those of their opponents who were trying energetically to overturn restrictive policy, cannot be explained by reference to inertia; rather, both must be explained with reference to contemporary efforts. Several domestic and international events in the period following the Quota Acts’ passage in 1924 might have provoked a restrictionist backlash: the Depression, the international and domestic spread of Bolshevism and fascism, war and upheaval abroad, direct involvement in war, the 96
The McCarran-Walter Act
97
beginning of the cold war, and the creation of the United Nations, OECD, Marshall Plan, NATO, and other multilateral institutions. During this period, the United States repealed the Chinese Exclusion Acts (1943) and other Asian exclusions, enacted legislation to assist resettlement of displaced persons (1948), and overhauled basic immigration policy in what came to be known as the McCarran-Walter Act (1952). (Table 4 summarizes the ways in which McCarran-Walter departed from the Quota Acts.) It also, at times, did nothing: during the Depression, for example, there was no new general legislation: reasons proved unpersuasive.
Reason: Depression
In 1929, the same year that the Census Bureau ‹nished going back through its records to determine the population’s national origins, the stock market crashed. Unemployment rose from 3.2 to 23.6 percent in three years. It was at or above triple the 1929 value until 1942.1 If restrictive immigration policies are designed to shrink both the pool of competitors for jobs and the population for whose welfare the government is responsible, during the Depression legislators should further restrict, or even ban, immigration. They should also make efforts to target the immigrants most likely to compete with Americans economically. Yet they did nothing. During the decade following the stock market crash, legislators were indeed concerned about unemployment, banking, and investment. They were not any more concerned about immigrants in the 1930s than they had been in earlier decades; in fact, they rarely discussed immigration. When they did speak, legislators voiced the same types of convictions and worries in the 1930s that they had in the 1910s and 1920s. These included economic worries. They also included concern about race and protecting sovereignty more generally. Over eleven years of depression in the United States, 42 legislators, about a tenth of Congress, spoke at some point about immigration. This includes 3 defending it. Of these 42, only 10 at some point mentioned the economy when discussing immigration. Their purpose was to continue their old battle to ban immigration altogether. When they claimed the ›oor, they argued in terms indistinguishable from those they chose one and two decades earlier, such as race-based criminality: it “is quite singular that the assassins of Presidents and would-be assassins, many of them, have not been American citizens”;2 “For one, I am tired of seeing the name of Capone and other such names in every crime record that we read in our papers. I do not see the names of the Germans, the Swedes, of the English, of the Danes, the true American names, appearing in the crime records of
98
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
the country, in the agitators of the country who are trying to overthrow our form of government and do away with our laws and our institutions.”3 Control of immigration was still control of sovereignty. “America has the absolute right not only to determine the number, but to exclude immigrants of occupations not needed here, just as every other nation has that unquestioned sovereign right and exercises it”;4 [so in] “1924 we . . . practically cut out foreign immigration. That (Quota) act is called the second Declaration of American Independence.”5 Sovereignty depended on control over citizenship. “Here we have a country, but if there is not a soul living in that country there is nothing to it. The same thing would apply to a State if there were no people living in the State. The same thing applies to a nation; unless there are people living in that nation, it is no nation. A nation is simply made up of individuals.”6 Control over citizenship, moreover, was unilateral and plenary. “This country has a right to do whatever it wants to do to protect itself. This country must have immigration laws looking to the good of this country without consulting any other country [or we are] undone as a nation, . . . we are lost.”7 “No people in the world have a right to come into our country unless they come by our invitation. There is no right for the peoples of any country to come into our country and seek the advantages of American citizenship. We have a right to, and we should designate, what peoples may come into our country, and under what conditions they may come.”8 Legislators were, however, barely disturbed by the prospect of immigrants worsening the Depression. The causal model implicit in Depression-era arguments is the same as that typical of the earlier period. Social friction, economic-racial in origin, would lead to war. Either civil war (with sides de‹ned ethnically) would engulf the country, or an alienated group would invite a foreign country to invade, or people would bicker so extensively that the country would be too weak to resist opportunistic invasion. Whatever the spark, racial division marked the route to disastrous loss of integrity and sovereignty. Economic isolation thus served defense. Some emphasized one stage of this chain, such as the link between immigration and unemployment. The legislators who had focused on unemployment after World War I blamed immigration for the Depression. One claimed that “if we should deport the aliens now in the United States, I do not believe we would have a single American citizen out of employment.”9 Notably, only legislators who already supported restriction—had supported the Quota Acts—used depression conditions as evidence for exclusion. In fact, John Robsion used consensus on immigration restriction as a lever to argue for economic protection, not the other way around as is implied by the notion that restriction has an economic motivation. “It will not do our working people much good to keep foreigners
The McCarran-Walter Act
99
out of this country, and send aliens back to their home countries where they will produce shoes, clothing, pottery, machinery, and hundreds of other articles in industry and agriculture—working long hours with low wages and using the materials and products of their own country to produce these articles and then dump them into our own country. Restricted immigration and the protective tariff must go hand in hand.”10 Representatives declared that “it is primary that we protect our people and secondary that we solve our problems of trade and industry”11 because “the products of foreign labor coming into this country do more harm than the aliens we have coming here.”12 Economic competition in time of need raised issues of obligation. Why divide the starving world into blocs? Because that way, the government was responsible for a de‹nite number of people. The government had a good idea, too, about which persons it had most interest in protecting. “Let us feed and clothe those who pay taxes and ‹ght for us in preference to those who get our money and return to their own country and then ‹ght us.”13 Economic problems mattered to the government because they troubled the taxpayers, but also because they would, speci‹cally, invite communism or fascism. Foreign ideologies were a concern before the Depression, and they got attached to economic problems once it had set in. Just before the stock market crash, Thomas He›in argued that “foreign agents have intruded themselves into the very temple of American liberty and here at the altar place the Fascist agents of Mussolini are administering a foreign oath to the sons of American Italians and binding them in allegiance to Mussolini, the Catholic tyrant dictator of Rome.”14 During the Depression, communism could be imported and survive, or it could develop on its own. In 1932, legislators worried that Canada’s new anticommunist laws would provoke an in›ux to the United States;15 in 1935, a representative usually liberal on immigration questions worried that Boy Scouts coming to the United States for a jamboree would be able to bring in their communist parents.16 In hearings held during the Depression, legislators focused on communism as the outgrowth of industrial decadence.17 The outcome that legislators feared was the one that populists and leftists hoped for, though they could not agree on how to bring it about. J. Louis Engdahl, representing the National Council for the Protection of the Foreign Born, argued that immigration control “has but one object in view, to create deep-going divisions in the ranks of the working class, to destroy the solidarity of native and foreign-born workers through putting them in separate categories, which at the same time reacts against the unity of white and negro workers.”18 On the other hand, Hugo Black argued that open immigration hurt workers. “My own idea is that foreign immigration has been utilized by the big business interests of the country as a
100
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
direct weapon to break down the price of wages of the people of the land.”19 Communists could not agree whether open or closed immigration hurt workers, but legislators could agree that closed immigration kept out communists. The economy, when it was discussed, was most often listed among several areas of concern. Economic troubles mattered not in themselves but because they could ignite race war, which would lead to the collapse of sovereignty. Belief and ability arose organically from race. “As a student of population and of heredity and of genetics, I know that if a man with a civilization standard, say, of 10 marries a woman who has advanced on civilization’s path to the point of only 4, you will not reach the standard of 10 again in the posterity of that family for 300 years. . . . Self-preservation is a law among nations as it is among men.”20 Heterogeneity led to degradation of the American way of life, then to crime, subversion, war, and ‹nally to dissolution. “We are face to face with unrest, social problems, race problems, crime waves, riots, anti-American propaganda, wage reduction and other evils which are largely brought about by the seething hordes of undesirable aliens in America.”21 Depression would accelerate this process. Albert Johnson, for example, made a point of objecting to communists not out of fear about their economic ends but out of concern for American sovereignty. “We are not going to attempt to prevent the arrival or cause the deportation of those who have sympathetic feelings for people generally as communists; we are aiming at the international political communist who believes in one big union of government and against individual government.”22 Sovereignty protected civilization. Economic shock threatened sovereignty because people’s reactions threatened social order. The dramatic rate of downward change was, in the short run, more worrisome than the low level of economic output. “We are in the midst of one of the most violent and sudden economic changes our country has ever experienced. To adjust ourselves to these changes a new social policy must be adopted. Drastic curtailment of immigration from all sources is one of the ‹rst steps necessary before we can put our own house in order.”23 The aliens did not want to come anyway. A depressed country was hardly a magnet, and those who wanted to move were likely to be too poor to do so, emigrating from a country hit just as hard. Immigration to the United States slowed to 13 percent of its 1930 level, 4.5 percent of its 1924 level.24 Moreover, net migration was negative. Table 3 shows unemployment, immigration, and emigration ‹gures for the period 1929 to 1945. Some of this was attributable to administrative efforts to control immigration, efforts that angered the Congress because they circumvented its
The McCarran-Walter Act
101
authority. Consuls and immigration of‹cials relied on the public charge provision to bar a large proportion of applicants: Our Secretary of State, Mr. Stimson . . . said that his great of‹ce takes the credit for reducing immigration by 97 percent, without any law at all. . . . In each case the consul would ask the prospective immigrant whether he has a job awaiting him in the United States. If the answer is yes, then the immigrant is refused a visa because he is a contract laborer; if the answer is no, then the immigrant is refused a visa because he is likely to become a public charge.25 Stricter enforcement was easy in any case when the pool was small and self-selected. The self-regulating nature of economic migration, on one hand, and legislators’ identi‹cation of immigration with sovereignty, not with poverty, on the other, combine to explain legislators’ lack of interest in immigration during the Depression. Table 3 displays how immigration and unemployment covaried. Unemployment jumped up near 20 percent in the late 1930s when legislators began again to discuss restriction, but it was not unemployment that caught their attention. It was the prospect of war in Europe.
Reason: Isolation from Postwar Europe
Decades of debate about European wars, immigration, and sovereignty had sensitized Congress to changes in Europe that might force Americans face-to-face with Europeans, either as soldiers together in Europe or as neighbors in the United States. Involvement with Europe—including involvement with immigrants from Europe—was a slippery slope leading to war and undercutting democracy. Foremost in their minds in 1938 was the country’s experience during World War I. Explaining American Legion opposition to immigration, in 1929 a representative explained that “it was natural, I think, that those who had served abroad during the World War and had come into contact there with the elements of the French army which included the French territorial Asiatics and the French territorial Africans, and who had seen something else of the foreign element there, should look with alarm upon the idea of a great in›ux of those people or any of the foreign people to our shores.”26 Isolationism a decade later focused still on Europe and its wars. “Those who believe in reaching hands across the sea are in opposition to those with whom I ‹nd myself in accord, who stand for America ‹rst, and who are desirous ‹rst of keeping
TABLE 3.
Unemployment and Immigration during the Depression
Year
Unemployment Rate
Immigration
1928 1929 1930 1931 1932 1933 1934 1935 1936 1937 1938 1939 1940 1941
4.2 3.2 8.7 15.9 23.6 24.9 21.7 20.1 16.9 14.3 19.0 17.2 14.6 9.9
307,260 279,680 241,700 97,139 35,576 23,068 29,470 34,956 36,329 50,244 67,895 82,998 70,756 51,776
Emigration 77,457 69,203 50,661 61,882 103,300 80,081 39,771 38,834 35,817 26,736 25,210 26,651 21,461 17,115
Net Inflow or Outflow
Admissions
Departures
229,803 210,477 191,039 35,257 –67,719 –57,013 –10,301 –3,878 512 23,508 42,685 56,347 49,295 34,661
500,630 479,330 446,210 280,680 174,870 150,730 163,900 179,720 190,900 231,880 252,700 268,330 208,790 151,780
274,360 252,500 272,430 290,920 287,660 243,800 177,170 189,050 193,280 224,580 222,610 201,410 166,160 88,477
Source: Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report (Washington, DC: GPO, various years). Note: Immigrants are those admitted eligible to file for citizenship; emigrants are exiting citizens. Admissions includes both immigrants and “nonimmigrants,” those traveling to the country for business or pleasure. Similarly, departures includes emigrants and “nonemigrants,” temporary visitors on their way out.
Net Inflow or Outflow 226,280 226,830 173,790 –10,240 –112,790 –93,070 –13,270 –9,330 –2,380 7,300 30,090 66,920 42,630 63,303
The McCarran-Walter Act
103
the United States out of war by staying clear of any foreign entanglements or embroilments.” Robert Reynolds wanted to ban immigration and thereby “ban all the isms.”27 Samuel Dickstein, a friend of immigrants, similarly explained, “Naturally we want no war. We want to keep peace with the world. We talk about neutrality. We want neutrality not only from the standpoint of what the term implies but also in order to keep out of any trouble, particularly European trouble. In these times we must keep our borders protected, and when I speak of borders I am referring to protecting against the entrance of people who have no right to come here.”28 Isolation was the country’s right. The Constitution forces us to confer certain rights upon people born within our territory—but I don’t see why anybody who does not live within the United States and who does not have the opportunity to take part in American institutions, who does not have opportunity to grow up to be what we look upon as an American and to speak the English language, who doesn’t have any contact with our form of government—I don’t see why that person, no matter what their birth, what their lineage, I don’t see why we should confer citizenship on them.29 Immigrants, as armies, threatened to gut the country. “It is my opinion that the Committee on Immigration and Naturalization, when they have in their power such items as these, are just as much a line of defense as is our Army, our Navy, our airplane defense. If we are destroyed in this manner, we are just as surely destroyed as if our Army were defeated, our Navy sunk, and our air defense annihilated.”30 When Europe began its next war, Americans prepared to shield themselves from its fallout. The group over whom the public was later to feel such remorse, refugees from Nazi Germany, provoked the greatest amount of initial fear. In a Fortune poll conducted in 1938, 86 percent of respondents were against adding places for refugees.31 It was not that legislators were wholly ignorant of the conditions the refugees faced. “They are practically all Jews and will be sent back to a country where they are not wanted and will be subjected to hardship and persecution. On the other hand, I feel that we owe to the dignity and integrity of the citizenship of the United States a very strong duty. . . . I think too much of my own citizenship to degrade it in that way.”32 They believed that refugee immigration was no more than a “wedge” prying open the borders and enabling a ›ood of relatives to enter.33 If restriction had been based on claims about immigrants’ motives, then demonstrating that the new supplicants cared only for freedom would have changed legislators’ minds. But restriction
104
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
was not a response to arguments about motives. It was a response to arguments about Europeans’ essential Europeanness, their congenital inability to live democratically. For this reason, one group of Europeans persecuting another was to be expected; it was de‹nitely no reason to admit the persecuted. “Mr. Speaker, we have had enough experience with these European countries to know that we will get the worst of this deal. We always get the worst of it even when we are trying to save ourselves from them. In this new proposal we are attempting to save them from themselves.”34 Such was also true of Asians and Africans. Almost every disgruntled element that ever got into trouble in its own country had pleaded for admission into the United States on the ground that they were oppressed at home. . . . Suppose we should. . . . We would be inviting all the Communists in Germany and Italy and all the Fascists and Communists in Spain who are dissatis‹ed with their present regime. . . . then what about the oppressed of Ethiopia? Would we be expected to invite every Negro in Ethiopia who feels he is oppressed? Should we invite every Chinaman . . . ?35 “But the American people are not going to be deceived by this refugee bunk. This is just another scheme to bring additional thousands here who are not wanted in Europe.”36 Later representatives reviewed this period bitterly, using it as evidence to aid displaced persons. “There was no effort of any kind to save from death many of the refugees who could have been saved. . . . But the destructive policy of our organs of Government, particularly the State Department [by relying on the public charge provision during the Depression] brought about a condition so that not even the existing immigration quotas are ‹lled.”37 The regrets that some Americans felt were insuf‹cient to reopen the question of restriction. Aliens “have no rights to citizenship. They have the privilege of becoming citizens if they follow a path that we lay down to all of them alike. This is a straight and narrow path, which some do not like to take. Every country in the world guards its citizenship against people who are not in sympathy with their country and form of government.”38 Sovereignty was sovereignty. During the three years between the German annexation of Austria and American military engagement, the period when wars declared were not fought and adversaries were uncertain, American legislators lived in dread of being overrun by immigrants ›eeing Europe. Mr. Speaker, our President seems bound to embroil us in European entanglements. He is now asking the people of the United States to
The McCarran-Walter Act
105
make a haven for those who are undesirable to European dictators. . . . The President has gone on a visionary excursion into the warm ‹elds of altruism. With actual death-dealing red warfare being carried on between two great nations off to the west of us, and with rumors of wars coming to us every day from Europe—a veritable powder keg—why should we project ourselves into this danger? . . . Why add to our troubles and threaten our very existence?39 That fascism might threaten American interests or values, and thereby be suf‹cient cause to join in the war, was implicitly rejected. Instead, “the restriction of immigration and the deportation of alien criminals is a subject in which the American people are more thoroughly interested at this hour than any other subject . . . because it unquestionably has a relation to the mammoth subject of adequate national defense. . . . Are we for the Americans, or are we for those who live beyond the lucid blue waters of the Atlantic or the briny waves of the Paci‹c?”40 Refugees’ potential admission was not, however, the greatest danger the country faced. More dreadful was the prospect of immigrants dragging the country into war, then assuring defeat once ‹ghting started. Immigrant subversion would be the key to defeat—but immigration was necessarily subversive. Safety did not depend on immigrants’ benign motives but their absence. Our defense, in a sense, lies within the con‹nes of the United States. We have made vast preparations against the forces which would be used against us in time of war. If war were declared against us, if an invasion were attempted or were made, our observers maneuvering and operating our great airplanes could easily locate the enemy forces without. That would not be dif‹cult. But, Mr. President, there are millions and millions of aliens in this country who have been here for years upon years.41 In this view, “‘all enemies’ includes both foreign and domestic enemies. . . . I say that if war were to be declared tomorrow against the United States, . . . we would have 7,000,000 potential enemies spying within our midst. Termites are more dangerous than enemies from without, because an enemy from without may be observed.”42 Believing that immigrants’ presence alone was subversive enough to assure defeat did not stop many from pointing out speci‹c groups’ nefarious motives. Echoing earlier fears about Japanese colonies, representatives declared that “frequently we have read that prior to the subjugation of countries by aggressor nations tourists in large numbers have been sent
106
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
by the aggressor nations to the countries to be subdued and overrun. I am not at all sure that America and the West Hemisphere are not now being subjected in part to the same or a kindred procedure.”43 The danger grew both from Europe and from Japan. “I believe that ahead of America are perhaps some rather dark days. I think it is time we turned our attention de‹nitely toward the question of the presence in this country of 5,000,000 aliens. We have seen the map of Europe completely changed by the operations of a Nazi government which has boasted of the presence in each of the countries they have conquered of what is referred to as a ‘‹fth column.’”44 Speci‹cally, “no one knows how many agents of warring nations are posing as lecturers and journalists for the principal purpose of shaping American foreign policy.”45 Immigration and in‹ltration were indistinguishable, synonymous. This would be true, by de‹nition, of any country, but American democracy made the country particularly vulnerable to propaganda. The First Amendment and advanced technology combined to create particularly bad conditions. “Propaganda was one of the main avenues for developing a war attitude in the minds of the American people from 1914 to 1917. Today the masses are more subject to direct appeal than in 1914, because of the radio. . . . Foreign propaganda agents are using our freedom of the press and of speech for a purpose which may result in the destruction of our form of government.”46 Arguments about particular circumstances, such as American democracy, Nazi refugees, or Japanese intentions, though logically unnecessary, joined the main, principled claim—that any immigration destroyed sovereignty—to create a barrier of words protecting the country. Opposition to this renewed restrictionist wave also echoed that of earlier years, and liberals, too, rarely voiced opinions at all. Representatives noted that “in periods of war—and we are now in such a period—considerable hysteria develops and oftentimes injustice is done to very good people in our midst.”47 If democracy was right, it should be right in any circumstances. “In a period such as this period, the test of a democracy lies in the ability of that democracy to maintain its liberties, to preserve those liberties, and to have more freedom rather than less freedom during the period of crisis.”48 If citizens were free, they should be free in any circumstances. “Concentration camps, or their equivalent, should be kept beyond the pale of our democracy. They may prove to be a two-edged sword, cutting at our enemies today but striking at our patriots and defenders of democracy tomorrow.”49 Particular circumstances could not circumscribe the application of democratic principle. From the Depression’s beginning through its end and through the early war years in Europe, nothing changed. Neither the generally
The McCarran-Walter Act
107
accepted, public characterization of immigration nor policy itself was altered. Immigrants remained a racially distinct army threatening to steal sovereignty by “eviscerating the body politic”; therefore, policy held to its 150,000 annual level, divided among the (white) world’s peoples according to the nationality of the U.S. population. The 1920 census on which the quotas were based, picked because it was most recent, was never even updated. Individual immigrants mattered because of their race, not their skills. Congress gauged immigrants’ effects on a depressed nation by measuring not wages, nor investment, savings, or public expenditures, but “race problems, crime waves, riots.” The only change that prospective immigrants faced was the State Department decision to enforce the public charge provision more rigorously. Isolationist policies had accomplished what they were intended to accomplish: the country had isolated itself so effectively that its image of immigrants and of the outer world they represented did not change in spite of massive changes at home and abroad. It was not until Americans again faced Europeans and Asians in war that they again considered whether and how to establish borders between themselves and those outside.
Reason: Internationalism and World War II
Americans ultimately drew lessons from the war different from those they had drawn from World War I. It was not that their experience was so different objectively. An isolationist country again waited while Europeans started attacking each other, an internationalist president again advocated alliance with England, France, and Russia against Germany, the country was again confused about the relationship it should have with China and Japan, U.S. troops again went overseas and provided decisive force, and the country subsequently worried about employing its veterans and establishing an organization that would prevent a recurrence of European war. Some saw repetition too clearly: “We again have hundreds of thousands of Europeans knocking at the doors of the paradise of their fondest dreams.”50 The war did prompt one new observation that affected immigration policy. Geopolitical lines cut across lines of race. The major racial categories embedded in American law were “oriental,” “Southern European,” and “Nordic,” but in World War II, the United States allied with China against Japan, while Indians and Burmese fought for the Allies; Germans, Austrians and many French joined with Italians as enemies of the United States, while Switzerland and Spain held a neutrality sympathetic to the Axis powers. Ideology appeared as a second confounding factor, determining both sides in World War II and cohesion within sides, as
108
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
it had not done in the earlier war. What a nation racially was, what it believed, and what it did had no clear relationship to each other, though such a relationship had been assumed in the Quota Acts. Debate sought to reconcile these. Emerging from World War I had been a consensus about the war’s causes that had implications for immigration policy. Heterogeneity led to division; division led to domestic and foreign con›ict—and also negatively affected the country’s ability to ‹ght. This inability to ‹ght a clear external foe meant disintegration. Immigrants administered the fatal blow either through numbers, as armies, or by gradually eating away the country’s core, as subversive colonizers. Admitting immigrants from the belligerent countries would make the United States similar to them: racially confused and liable to slip into war at any time. It also rewarded the foreigners who had started the war, when they should in fairness be expected to stay and put right the damage. Continuity through 1943 is striking. The only pressing issue was what to do with enemy nationals stranded in the United States when war was declared. Once again the country had to externalize the threat if it were to ‹ght a war, and once again the threat was racial. Concentration camps were proposed to sequester German sailors in port and Japanese living on the West Coast. The camps were “partly for their own protection,” though primarily to isolate them from war operations because they “have highly developed espionage systems.”51 At least 6,000 native-born Japanese expatriated themselves by signing an agreement:52 “as a result of this evacuation or detention of the Japanese population a number of American citizens of Japanese ancestry, either because of political loyalty to Japan, or because of their reaction to the way they felt they were treated, expressed their desire to drop their United States citizenship.”53 Mandatory identi‹cation papers likewise, it was argued, protected good aliens and controlled bad ones. Administrators were especially sensitive to the possibility that Americans’ generalities about their enemies would alienate, if that were possible, friendly aliens in their midst. “We cannot, on one hand, revile the Nazi theories of racial supremacy, and, on the other, ignore the sinister implication of our immigration legislation that bars one people and not another, restrictions based on no moral or ethical ground save that of a man’s origin. We are paying a bitter price to learn the lesson of the interdependence of the world and its inhabitants. [Removing national origins quotas] will rob the Axis of their most telling barbed weapon on the battle of psychological warfare.”54 For instance, the problem they saw with deporting the expatriated Japanese was that “we are going to send back to Japan a group that knows us, knows our language, and feels very bitter toward us. We
The McCarran-Walter Act
109
are going to create a great problem for the Allied military government of Japan.”55 For this reason, the attorney general called on Americans not to discriminate against German, Italian, or Japanese permanent residents.56 The war dragged only one other problem into view, but it was one whose solution had wide implications for immigration policy. The Chinese, invaded by Japan and keeping fascist troops pinned down over a wide area, had been barred since 1882. Some Americans viewed this as a moral problem. All viewed it as a practical problem when the Axis powers began reminding the Chinese of this in their broadcasts over the Paci‹c. Congress then entertained proposals to repeal the Chinese Exclusion Acts by adding a quota of 105 for Chinese. To this time, that country’s quota of 100 applied to whites, usually of British ancestry, born in China; Chinese were barred for racial reasons. President Roosevelt declared that he regarded “this legislation as important and desirable, and I believe that its enactment will help us to win the war and to establish a secure peace.”57 He received a great deal of support. “If legislation permitting 105 Chinese to come into this country annually for permanent residence will help in anywise in the prosecution of this war and save and protect the lives of American soldiers to any extent whatever I believe there will be no objection to it by the American people.”58 Roosevelt, with an eye to the future, argued for materiel: “But China’s resistance does not depend alone on guns and planes and on attacks on land, on the sea, and from the air. It is based as much in the spirit of her people and her faith in her allies. We owe it to the Chinese to strengthen that faith. . . . It would be additional proof that we regard China not only as a partner in waging war but that we shall regard her as a partner in days of peace.”59 Slowly, but surely, we forge ahead to the realization that no man, no government, no people are islands entirely unto themselves; that inasmuch as what happens in one corner of the earth reverberates throughout all corners, or, to change the ‹gure, like waves that wash one shore because [of] stones that had been cast into the waters from the opposite shore. We in the West can no longer remain indifferent to what happens in the East, especially as the world shrinks daily in size. Our good President has stated: The United Nations are ‹ghting to make a world in which tyranny and aggression cannot exist; a world based upon freedom, equality, and justice; a world in which all persons, regardless of race, color or creed, may live in peace, honor, and dignity. And in so saying, the President of the United States was delineating our war aims. That is a mighty large program. It means the lib-
110
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
eration of oppressed peoples, as well as (and this I want to emphasize) the removal of discriminatory measures, not so thoroughly advertised, on the statute books of our own country.60 India, too, was an ally. “We are asking that the United States of America do not continue a discrimination against a people whom we want to have as our fellows in arms and to help us establish a peace in this world based on the good neighbor doctrine.”61 Legislators, however, continued to oppose admitting Chinese, for racial reasons. A quota “will not mislead anyone, even the Chinese whom it is intended to mislead, and go down in history as one more master stroke of meaningless diplomacy at the expense of a very important part of our immigration system.”62 Ironically, it was Japanese propaganda that ‹nally convinced Americans that the war was fundamentally not about race. China is being divided by Japan through propaganda which tells the Chinese that they should throw in their lot with the Asiatic race, that . . . the American people are not going to carry out the terms of its promises because they do not like the Chinese as shown by the Chinese Exclusion Acts. . . . Hitler could come in under a quota, Mussolini could come in under a quota, but Madame Chiang Kai-shek, or the ‹nest type of Chinese people, cannot. After the war it may be too late. China may not be in the war unless we give her some sort of moral support.63 This argument had power since many believed that Americans’ exclusion of the Japanese in the Quota Acts had led to Pearl Harbor. “In my opinion, that was what ‹nally brought on World War II.”64 “I could not help thinking of some Japanese who were saying, ‘What kind of people do you think we are? Do you think you could write into your statute books a law permanently branding us and stigmatizing us as inferior human beings because of the color of our skin without having us hate you and grit our teeth and strive until we could become strong enough to stick a knife between your ribs and twist it as we did at Pearl Harbor?”65 Pearl Buck, in 1943 testimony, remembered “the tremendous evil effect that our exclusion had on the Japanese navy, many years ago. . . . It was the death blow of liberalism; . . . had we been able to see what denial at that time meant, we probably would not have had this war. That has been the single thing that has made Japan regard us as an enemy.”66 Americans had to construe the con›ict as nonracial if they were to believe that they had a chance of winning.
The McCarran-Walter Act
111
We could not win a race war, even though we won all the battles. The colored people are two-thirds of the world’s population, and they can outwork and undereat and outlast the white man. Fortunately this is not a war between races. . . . This is still a war between those who believe in human freedom and those who believe in human slavery. We must keep it so. There cannot be a great war between the white and colored races in the next 10 years, or the next 100 years, or the next 300 years, if we keep ourselves—the white people—and the Chinese, the largest and strongest of the colored peoples, on the same side.67 Separating social purpose from race affected how people thought about the war, their enemies, and themselves. They took this new understanding into their analysis of Nazism as well and thus transformed the image of America that they projected into postwar immigration policy.68 This position gained so much rhetorical power that the commission President Truman established to decry the 1952 McCarran-Walter Act after it did pass made the same link between Japanese exclusion and Pearl Harbor.69 Rescinding Chinese exclusion was the one issue where Congress systematically discussed immigrants during the war. At the time, it drew no general conclusions from this reversal, and emerging from the war was a consensus similar in many ways to that prevailing after World War I. Heterogeneity led to disintegration; armies and subversive colonies did the country in. Admitting immigrants from belligerent countries would make the United States resemble them. This was all the same, but the war experience made the “them” different. In World War I, the problem that Americans saw with allied as well as enemy countries was racial; innate differences explained the anarchism and czarism propelling Europeans into con›ict. In World War II, the problem was ideological. Fascism, and to a lesser degree communism, motivated European belligerence—but fascism could not be innate. If it were, Americans had to expect a fascist interlude as well: since 1929, they had protected a 17 percent quota for Germans and a 4 percent quota for Italians because the Census Bureau uncovered these proportions in the national origins of the whole (white) population. Ideological heterogeneity thus joined racial difference as suf‹cient spark for national implosion. Communism and fascism arose from a diseased institutional culture, so they could not attract Americans unless American society and institutions were wanting; therefore, ideological and ethnic demands came from immigrants and enemies. Heterogeneity was still the problem, but it was ideological diversity more than racial difference that triggered disaster.
112
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Consensus that ideology and ideological subversion should be the country’s focus arose slowly and vaguely during the war years, as a way to distinguish the country from the Axis powers. Fascism was not described in Congress as intrinsically or morally wrong: the problem was that fascist authoritarianism led to war. But fascism never threatened subversion. If the United States were to be overtaken by fascism, it would not rot from within. To the contrary, it would itself become militaristic, authoritarian, and expansionist, in a sense hypersovereign. Fascism was, in addition, not a transcontinental identity but an ideology that magni‹ed the state.70 There was no such thing as international fascism that would draw fascists around the world to surmount the state system. It was precisely such a trans-sovereign movement that legislators feared. During the era of World War I, Congress ‹xated on ethnic identity as a danger of this type. By the end of World War II, communism presented the menace. Truman declared that “Communist tyranny has taken up where Hitler’s brutality left off.”71 Congress did not react against movements simply because they were novel and un-American. Fascism was both. The war did not change enough about the country to change immigration policy, but it did leave a legacy that was to affect how policy would be changed when the time came. Race and ideology had to be separate. Both or neither could present a problem, but in any case, they were not necessarily coincident. When Americans did react, they did so against movements whose logic demanded an identity beyond American borders. “Hyphenism” following the ‹rst war, and communism following the second, each threatened just this. Legislators never worried simply that they would lose a war. They worried that they would lose their country. Communism, like ethnically based foreign-policy irredentism, could not be fought once it had taken hold. Subversion had to be prevented.
Reason: Reconstruction for Security against Fascism
Debate about immigration policy after the war focused on its role in assuring that fascist aggression would not recur, or if it did, it would not draw the United States into war. The two possibilities were to isolate the country more effectively or to use immigration policy to prevent the recurrence of the dynamics that led to war. A strategy to achieve the ‹rst was clear: isolation. A strategy to achieve the second would depend on a theory of what had caused the war. The possibilities offered were ‹nancial catastrophe, alliances made weak by racial insults, isolation, and lack
The McCarran-Walter Act
113
of American credibility as either an opponent of eugenics or a user of force; the corrective was therefore money, deracialized policy, or an active internationalism. The debate’s boundaries, for both sides, were de‹ned by sovereignty. Immigration was, still, central to the country’s understanding of its sovereignty in relation to the rest of the world. “The subject matter is immigration, but the pending legislation involves far more than immigration. . . . The very meaning of the word ‘citizen’ is at issue. Fundamental problems of our foreign policy are involved. Our internal security is involved.”72 Because sovereignty underlay any discussion of immigration, legislators had to take care to separate policy concerning immigrants from that covering citizens. “The immigration law is different from any other law with which we have to deal. For instance, most of our laws deal with American citizens. An American citizen has rights under our law. He has recognizable rights, but an alien or a foreigner who has not yet arrived in our country has no such rights under our law. He must be here before he has any standing under our law. Then when we speak of the ‘rights of these people being invaded’ we are taking an untenable position.”73 It was also a tricky subject because it connected with so many other types of policies. In the light of our experience since World War I, there can hardly be a doubt that the regulation of immigration from foreign countries is a question pertaining to the ‹eld of international relations. It is true that, with a few outstanding exceptions, immigration has been regulated by domestic rather than international law, that is to say, by statute rather than by treaty. But so are tariffs or armaments. The domestic form of regulation should not obscure its international substance; immigration is a kind of human tariff and the liberal or restrictive immigration policy is as much a part of the foreign policy of a country as that of liberal or restrictive international trade. This has long been clear to every responsible statesman.74 The centrality of immigration policy was one powerful reason for letting it alone. Letting policy alone meant letting immigration policy secure an isolationist sovereignty. “What is the American doctrine, and what is the doctrine of every sovereign nation on the globe? It is that a country has a right to say who shall become one of its citizens. There is no right in any foreign person, whether he comes from the race from which I sprang or from any other race, to demand entrance here. The whole question is, What is a sound policy for America? That is all.”75
114
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Our problem in the future, until this superstate some people talk about or something else is devised, is to make America safe for the American people. We need to make up our minds that the period of idealistic preachings that has been going on for some years is at an end. We need to get back to the fundamentals and the bedrock idea that the highest type of political society that has yet been developed in this world and one which will at the same time work is the type known as a nation. The attribute of a nation is sovereignty. We have had immigration laws to protect our sovereignty and to protect the domestic economy of the Nation.76 Into the 1950s, congressional discussion of immigration meant discussion of sovereign isolation. “As a sovereign Nation we have a right to protect ourselves”77 because the Supreme Court has repeatedly and uniformly held that the right to exclude or to expel aliens, absolutely or under certain conditions, in war or in peace, is an inherent and inalienable right of every sovereign and independent nation. The exercise of that sovereign power by the United States of America should not be hampered, limited, nor thwarted by any other nation. If it be, by just so much has our Nation lost its sovereignty and independence.78 Sovereign isolation still prevented apocalypse. “The best proof that a nation can be ruined by unwise immigration policies is afforded by the history of Greece and Rome, which nations remained great and productive, and with a high state of civilization, so long as there were full-blooded Greeks and Romans to carry on their civilization. But they rapidly deteriorated when unwise immigration policies resulted in intermarriage with other races.”79 And internationalism still tempted fate. “I refuse to follow a leadership that is once again getting us dangerously involved in international affairs which might precipitate world war III.”80 Possible future economic troubles sometimes provided a rationale for restriction. Immigration could, for example, be banned for ‹ve years to help the postwar economy. “I think the time has arrived to close the gates, and not let anyone come into the United States until we have provided jobs for the citizens of our country, jobs for our men and women in uniform all over the world, jobs for our men and women who are now in war plants, and who will be unemployed, and who will have to be taken care of by the taxpayers when the war is over. When the war ends, the great ›ood of money will cease.”81 Too much Filipino labor, in another example,
The McCarran-Walter Act
115
could justify granting the Philippines the independence prerequisite to being placed under a quota.82 Unemployment, real or possible, served as a symbol of the harm that international contact did to the country. Employing foreigners could be bad in principle or simply self-defeating. “We now have a country to which millions of people want to come from all over the world, and I do not blame them. But, if we let down the bars in a misguided spirit of humanitarianism and let them all come in or let groups of favorites come in based on political pressures here, we will dilute and ultimately destroy the thing they came for.”83 Either way, only isolation could protect those already in the United States. Ignoring Europe meant shunning recent allies, which might set a precedent that would later haunt the country. Many argued, however, that these allies should not be rewarded with an increased quota; after all, they fought for their own homelands.84 Of course, “allies” might not even have fought. “We speak frequently of our allies, the treatment that should be accorded them. I think technically we had 30 or 40 allies in the World War, when for a vast majority of them the extent of their participation was to go down to the dock and unload lend-lease merchandise.”85 Of the best Europeans the American Legion believed in 1946 what it had in 1920, “that it would be better for the nations that were our allies that that type of adult immigrant who would be good for admission to this country could better serve us and his own country by staying at home for awhile and helping in the rehabilitation of his country.”86 If good people stayed put, immigrants were by de‹nition bad people. “Is it too much to ask of Europe’s millions that all must share the burden of reconstruction, the burden of each contributing his share so that Europe can some day achieve the standard of living we enjoy?”87 The United States owed Europe nothing. “I cannot join with those who think we are indebted to all the world and are obligated to cure the ills of all peoples. On the contrary, the world will not stand long enough for these peoples to pay their moral and material debts to this country.”88 This view had its roots in a general isolationism, but it slowly became popular with those advocating isolation only in the ‹eld of citizenship. Europeans staying put in Europe would help a country generally isolationist but also helped a country beginning to expand overseas. Pat McCarran argued that “Europe is not likely ever to pay its own way if it rebuilds its economy along the nationalistic lines that prevailed before the war. The only way in which Europe can make the maximum use of its resources is to develop into one big market and concentrate its production in the most advantageous locations.”89 This required labor. “We are now preparing to spend billions abroad in our grandiose plan of rehabilitating Europe. Tens of thousands of our young men will be occupied with this
116
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
task for years to come. In all fairness we should insist that for at least 10 years the citizens of France, England, Germany, Italy, and the other nations may not seek within our shores the civilization they could create in their own homelands.”90 Those who left had signaled by their leaving their unworthiness for American citizenship. “An adult male or an adult female wants to come to this country. If they are worth anything to this country they would be worth much more to the devastated countries in which they now live. . . . those who just want to run away from a problem would not, in my opinion, be very desirable to come here.”91 It also applied to the persecuted and uprooted. I notice in the State Department report on the Marshall plan the statement that there exists a shortage of labor in Europe, and that if the Marshall plan industries are set up as contemplated in the plan there will be a shortage of more than 600,000 workers. Is there any reason why displaced workers should not stay in Europe and become part of the life there and take their place in the economy which is being established there? . . . A great many persons entertain the opinion that the United States is a charity organization, that we are conducting an eleemosynary institution.92 If the displaced persons desire to work and better their condition, I want to know why they do not stay in Europe, cooperating under the Marshall plan.93 The ‹rst, isolationist view focused on keeping Europeans anywhere but in the United States; the second focused on keeping them in Europe. In spite of this change in reasons for restricting Europeans, those opposed to restriction used unchanged arguments, often those invoking universal principle. To exclude immigrants was to say that the country had “no room, Mr. President, even as there was no room at a certain inn at Bethlehem 2,000 years ago.”94 Since war’s horror was universal, compassion should be universal. There is a moral obligation that civilization and Christianity owe to their fellow man. It is not a legal obligation; it is not an obligation that can be enforced in any court of justice. But there is a moral and a humanitarian obligation that civilized Christian men owe to their less fortunate brothers, growing out of the great holocaust which has cost so much in treasure and in blood and in morale among the people of the world.95
The McCarran-Walter Act
117
The state boundaries that caused so much pain deserved not to be honored. “I do not know who it was that divided the world geographically by sections, but it certainly was no divine power.”96 Restrictionists “cannot justify it from anything that has ever been written in Scripture or in Democratic philosophy, nor can they justify it on the basis of practical politics or practical human relations in the world in which we live. The day of materialism and discrimination is over . . . this is a debate about what the philosophy of the Government of the United States is going to be about people.”97 To recognize a universal humanity meant not only to refrain from harming others but also to help them. If principle were not suf‹cient, practical bene‹ts might be. As in the earlier era, restriction’s opponents connected migration to wealth and power. “If we are to view the present position of the United States in accordance with unbiased historical judgements, we must recognize that our rapid rise to world power during the past 175 years has been based upon an increase from 4,000,000 to over 150,000,000 people.”98 Rivalry with the Soviet Union meant total, global preparedness, and it required “additional skilled manpower to realize the American production potential, to staff defense mobilization, and to give us elbow room in our population considering the world responsibilities which we must carry for the foreseeable future; second, to maintain the strategic balance between our population and that of the USSR.”99 Immigration could produce population asymmetry, which would deter attack. “A country with a static population is a country of the middle-aged, without the vigor and inventiveness of a growing people. From a defense angle alone we have to consider increasing population needs of this country,”100 because “the population of the Soviet Union, which is our principal rival in the world, is gaining rapidly, while ours is not making the progress it should to keep pace.”101 Modernity implied movement. If the country wanted to keep up, it had to recognize that interconnections among countries fed liberal power. “I think it is about time we began to think in terms of one world; that humanity is international; that human misery, distress, chaos, disease, economic instability, anywhere in the world, leads to the instability of our own Nation, as well as to the Nations immediately affected.”102 Closed borders invoked images of the Depression but also fascist Europe. “You remember that when the Nazi drive to conquer the world began, a dramatic phrase was coined—‘the lights went out’ in country after country. Today the gates clang shut. . . . There is a problem, I grant you, because more and more gates clang shut, and more and more barriers rise in the path of free intercourse of people.”103 Internationalism was not “a visionary excursion into the warm ‹elds
118
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
of altruism” but a practical, thrifty strategy for a new world power. In this way it differed from the universalism of the earlier era. “Our joining the United Nations Organization is an act of international cooperation that will save money for the United States, will carry out our agreed share of the support, repatriation, and resettlement of these victims of war and its aftermath, without change in our immigration laws or policies, and will terminate existing responsibilities for the displaced persons in the United States occupied zones.”104 The United States had to pay special attention to immigration because it had achieved global prominence in a time when all the world’s territory was claimed by some state. There was a time when a citizen who ›ed from persecution or tyranny in his own country could escape to a new world there to make valuable contributions to the welfare and history of a new democratic republic. That is the way we grew and became great. But today, in the year 1952, when travel is so swift and easy and when great governments are ostensibly and ostentatiously engaged in the work of international organization, a man who loses his country loses his place in the world too. As a stateless person he has no status in the world community.105 Liberals in the 1910s and 1920s argued that modern technology had at last reached a point where universal humanity’s fundamental equalities could be recognized, that generosity increased wealth and power, that internationalism bene‹ted America as well as others. Liberals in the 1940s and 1950s argued the same. In the 1950s, however, these same arguments began to be made with a subtle new twist. Ideology, not race, de‹ned the enemy. In fact, it was the enemies who were now racist. Allied unity and war propaganda depended on Americans eschewing racial grounds for exclusion. Actions, not characteristics, had to justify discrimination. “Any one of you who saw the picture Hitler Lives or any of the other authentic records of the master race philosophy and psychology, I think could not help be convinced that any adult who has ever felt or believed as these people feel and believe, cannot become a good American citizen.”106 Therefore, “no person who bore arms against us in World War II, no member of the Nazi party or of the Fascist Party, of the Gestapo, of the Storm Troopers, of the Schutz Staffel, of the Sturm Abteilung, or any organization or associations associated with or allied with the afore-mentioned parties or organizations can be admitted to this country.”107 As important as adding ideological categories was eliminating racial ones. “We should not give such great preference to the Nordic race, the
The McCarran-Walter Act
119
person with the blond hair, the Nazi who was guilty of murder.”108 Restrictionists, bigots, and liberals all had to come to terms with the new situation. “Germany is the second preferred nation of the world, with 27,000 quota numbers. It would seem to me that you haven’t the same Germany now you had before, and that it would be dangerous to this country to use up those numbers on any Nazis or Fascists or storm troopers, as I do not believe they can be assimilated now or a century from now.”109 Eliminating these categories would have a symbolic, diplomatic bene‹t. “All I want to do is simple justice, take those wasted quota numbers and put them to good use by dividing them amongst the nations that have quotas of less than 7000. . . . we would do away with the theory that was promulgated with such tremendous havoc, loss, and sadism to the world, promulgated by the man who came to power on a cannon top in Germany, Hitler, who advocated that which is very much akin to the national origins theory, namely, the herrenvolk and scarbenvolk . . . slavenvolk.”110 Some tried to reconcile the new fact that Germans were enemies with old fact of their desirability by targeting the Volkdeutsche for preferential treatment.111 Allies as well as enemies appeared different in this light. Racially unacceptable India supported the Allied cause with the largest army ever raised, so Asian exclusions became “a continued affront to the pride and self-respect of a valuable ally.”112 Security suddenly depended on equitable treatment, which could only be assured if Americans judged allies in neutral terms. “There should be equity somewhere and we cannot isolate ourselves from the rest of the world and we cannot say ‘we will do this for you but we will not do that for you.’”113 Ideological struggles changed how the country began to think of its partners. “The good opinion of our neighbors abroad is not to be purchased by economic favors alone. Moreover, it is not important to us solely as a means of securing military alliances. If we cannot do more than talk,” then there was no way to assure the “voluntary cooperation in our aims which I believe essential to our survival in a threatening world.”114 American interests were not in con›ict with European interests, and the world, at least among the Allies, was not zero-sum. “The displaced persons now in European camps are a deterrent to our attempts to bring order out of economic chaos, and a drain on the resources we are able to devote to such attempts”;115 they were not seen as Europeans who deserved to be penned up in Europe. Labor unions for the ‹rst time adopted the same view. In an ideological battle, loyalty mattered, and loyalty, unlike race, could change. Enemies in the war could not change their race but they could change their minds. To prevent this, some costs had to be accepted. “The CIO believes that the only hope of future peace, stability, and an improved standard of
120
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
living for workers everywhere in the world, lies in international cooperation and good will. A narrow isolationist position on immigration is contrary to current American foreign policy in regard to tariffs, relief, and other economic matters.”116 Immigration could even help labor. “We are assuming that all the people coming in under this quota are workers, and not possible employers of labor, and consumers”; moreover, if a quota of 153,000 damages the United States, “if that is so, gentlemen, then the faith in our economic system proclaimed to the world as the best, cannot be very strong.”117 Interests were served. “From a purely sel‹sh point of view, we can use these special skills, talents, and labor of these individuals in our expanding and dynamic economy.”118 The country should realize that “we need the rest of the world more than they need us. Our economic salvation depends upon the maintenance and extension of their good will won at such bitter cost. The potential market would keep our factories and wheels of industry at full peak.”119 Opening India, for example, would accomplish a dual purpose: “create a feeling of good will, that we will so need after the war [and] increase our exports—remember that.”120 Immigration would also help the cause. “Men and women who cannot be productively employed in the free countries of Europe are a net loss to the free world.”121 Attorney General Francis Biddle contended that “it is tremendously important in this coming world that we have friendly relations with these great nations. And I cannot believe that Americans, for instance, would be very eager to trade in the Orient if the orientals treated them as untouchables.”122 Unity was crucial. In several subtle but important ways, assumptions about other countries changed following World War II: global dynamics were not all zerosum, and alliance could bene‹t the United States; but allies could change their minds and slip away. The most impressive difference, however, was the awed self-consciousness that infused all arguments, all discussions, and all speeches. Legislators and interested parties never escaped the feeling that people around the world were listening to what they said, and, most surprisingly, that the country had a stake in how those people responded to even the most frivolous of American pronouncements. “Today the entire world is looking to America for human leadership, and it would seem inopportune at this postwar period to enact laws which might produce a bad effect upon peoples of our Allied Nations, and probably detrimental to our foreign policy.”123 Through its own actions, the country was thrust into the spotlight. “America formerly had a privileged position in the world. Other countries got into con›icts and we stood on the side and watched until we determined where our interests lay, and then we threw in our strength on this side or the other, and that usually tipped the scales. That fortunate day has gone. Today we are not an observer, we are one of
The McCarran-Walter Act
121
the main contenders.”124 Preeminence was irreversible without enormous social cost because it was the necessary result both of the country’s domestic arrangements and of its defense choices. The country had not just chosen leadership once, it had to choose leadership continually. Since it had retreated into isolation following the last war, it was especially important that it make clear to others that this would not happen again. “The American Federation of Labor therefore feels that we should maintain our present immigration quotas as an indication to the world that we intend to remain an active participant in world affairs, believing that to do otherwise, and especially to reduce our immigration quotas, would indicate that we are not willing to accept the responsibility of leadership.”125 Immigration restriction would indicate “that we were really isolationist at heart,” but this the country should see as a “complete abrogation of its responsibilities.”126 Like the AFL, “the Congress of Industrial Organizations at this time unequivocally opposes the passage of discriminatory legislation which in any way encourages national isolationism and belies the principles of American democracy upon which this country has been built.”127 For some, internationalism should engulf the country and carry over into defense, trade, and cultural exchange, just as isolationism had become total. To them, the new self-perception mandated a reinterpretation of the restrictionist past. The 1924 act “was formulated as an expression of selfinterest, not necessity, at a time when this Nation had not assumed its position as one of two leading nations of the world. From policies undertaken during tranquil years of secure, isolated peace and plenty, we can draw no guidance now in making policies for an insecure peace, when the mantle of leadership rests uneasily on our unaccustomed shoulders.”128 John Foster Dulles re›ected that “it is ironic and wrong that we who believe in the boundless power of human freedom should so long have accepted a static political role. [The founders] were not content merely to build a snug haven but they sought to create a political system which would inspire just government throughout the world.”129 Power, for the ‹rst time, depended on reputation—not a reputation to be materially powerful, but one to be morally authoritative. “This nation has the greatest aggregation of power on the face of the earth. We like to say that we possess moral power as well as physical power. Unless the United States gives moral leadership to its physical power, physical power will not long remain in America.”130 Where liberals and restrictionists disagreed was on the issue of whether that authority carried with it a responsibility to others. Antirestrictionist Hubert Humphrey argued yes, that leadership meant setting an example, while restrictionist Pat McCarran claimed that it did not: “This Nation is the last hope of western civi-
122
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
lization; and if this oasis of the world shall be overrun, perverted, contaminated, or destroyed, then the last ›ickering light of humanity will be extinguished.”131 Moral authority required the country to match its words and its actions. Sometimes this meant changing its words, but more often it meant changing its actions. Immigration policy, because it contained American foreign policy in micro form, became the most central but the toughest arena for working out the mandated changes. I pointed out that in the kind of world in which we live, we, as Americans, must recognize that as we legislate in the ‹eld of immigration we are not only legislating in the ‹eld of domestic policy, which some would like to separate neatly from foreign policy, but we are legislating in terms of our relationship to all the rest of the world. The philosophy which is embodied in this legislation may have a profound effect upon American policies and American relationships in areas of the world where today we stand very, very weak. I submit that there is nothing more important today than to remove from immigration policy the kind of slap-in-the-face which the present law gives, namely, racial discrimination, as it applies to those from the Asiatic area.132 Congress had to work out a consensus on what new circumstances meant for American policy. Clearly, the country was faced with a choice between suf‹cient allies—racially distinct allies—and immigration quotas not only based on race but excluding “bad” races. “In our so-called exclusion laws we had branded and stigmatized as inferior human beings the brown and yellow races, on the basis of the color of the pigment in their skin; something they were not responsible for and could not do anything about.”133 Following this, “the war in Europe was a war to decide which type of idea is to control the development of a billion people—the enormous resources and manpower and potential markets of Asia. Our democratic ideas have a better chance now than ever before to play that dominant role. But they cannot win if the democracies refuse to treat individual Asiatics as equal human beings.”134 It damaged morale during the war—“Is not such an exclusion an echo of the totalitarian ideas we seek to crush today?”135— and would damage alliance during the peace. Such morally appropriate measures bene‹ted the country materially and strategically. Indian good will, however, and our own moral satisfaction is not all we shall gain by the adoption of this resolution [to allow Indians to naturalize]. Our position at the San Francisco Conference will be
The McCarran-Walter Act
123
greatly strengthened in regard to discussing colonial policies with our allies. The criticism voiced frequently and widely in the United States against the colonial policies and imperialism of other nations has a certain degree of hypocrisy so long as, in our immigration laws, we ourselves refuse to treat all our allies on a basis of equality. We cannot successfully deplore a policy we practice. The practical aspect likewise should be taken into consideration. Next to Russia and China, India offers us the greatest potentiality for foreign trade during the rest of this century.136 These measures also prevented harm. Retaliation lurked in the background. Emerging from the war was a sense of American dominance, but it was dominance in a world composed of huge powers much more likely actively to threaten the United States. If we persist in telling other peoples that they are inferior, and supporting such a declaration by public law, America may well be consigned to ashes and sackcloth under the ‹re of bombs and under the terrible atrocities of people who are furious because they have been denied status and stature in the eyes of the citizens of the United States and the laws of this country. . . . I shall not cast my vote in this body to antagonize, to irritate or to humiliate a billion and a half people in this world.137 “China will emerge from this war as one of the four major powers. She will be a sovereign and independent nation, enjoying all the sovereign rights of other independent nations. If we persist in maintaining a policy of exclusion, what is to hinder China, and who could criticize her, if she in retaliation exercised her sovereign right to exclude our nationals from China?”138 Robert Alexander, from the Visa Division at the State Department, argued that China was not the only country that would retaliate and harm business travel.139 “I foresee grave consequences both abroad and at home through this constant, year after year, agitation against the European immigrants and their children and these repeated voices of distrust, discrimination, and disdain. You will learn that the poverty-stricken, wardepleted nations of Europe will not allow your contemptuous attitude toward them and your repeated affronts to their racial values to pass forever without challenge.”140 Once initiated, retaliation would spiral, as it had during the Depression and during World War II. Europe and South America are not going to stand idly by and take that kind of punishment. In retaliation and revenge they do the self-
124
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
same thing. We build high walls against France, against England, and against Canada, shutting out their persons and their goods. They build higher walls against us. We and these countries stand on top of those walls and thumb our noses at each other. Trade becomes stagnant and depression ensues.141 The executive branch and the Senate had become particularly sensitized to the negative as well as positive consequences of a tit-for-tat strategy. “We in this country, and particularly we in the Senate who deal with foreign relations, should realize that we should not throw brickbats at our neighbors across the sea by the passage of laws calculated to antagonize them.”142 Doing so in the nuclear age was especially dangerous. “Our scientists tell us that in this atomic age the only hope of the world is now to fracture the incrustations of the human heart and develop just a little good will.”143 The cold war changed the context within which risks were calculated.
Reason: Cold War—Consistency in Opposition to Communism
If leadership was the form, cold war was the substance of America’s place in the postwar world. Strangely, American leadership against an ideological foe during a real, tangible war had no effect on how legislators discussed immigrants or the country’s social goals, while American leadership against an ideological foe during an abstract, intangible war transformed perceptions of the enemy’s nature and the country’s purpose. The American people and the American government are learning today the moral equivalent of war. We are learning to do in peace what we did in war. The war has taught us that we cannot be happy all by ourselves. Our Government has recognized that the problems of food, labor, trade, security, and peace, in short everything which affects the national welfare, is international in scope. . . . Our immigration policies must be studied in the light of our present and future economic and foreign policies.144 Every move had signi‹cance. “In the war of ideas that is going on all over the world today, the ‹erce contest for people’s loyalties, this is a step of the utmost importance [against the] glacier of tyranny moving out of the Soviet Union over parts of Asia as well as Europe.”145 American society would have to change to meet the country’s new, self-declared international responsibilities. Believing that foreign policies
The McCarran-Walter Act
125
had to combine in a single package, some argued that an internationalist superpower could not tolerate a xenophobic society. In this period of high emotional tensions in our Nation, a spirit of blind, biased, nationalism seems to be overcoming millions of our fellow citizens. We see such blind nationalism manifest itself in connection with a great many policies and issues, and most prominently in connection with issues affecting foreign policy. Of course, questions of immigration are directly connected with the entire foreign policy attitude of the American people. [If the United States abandons openness] we shall antagonize millions of persons the world around, whose support, cooperation, and alliance we shall sorely need in the century ahead, as we go forward in that troubled period, in the contest between the free way of life and the enslaved way of life, the latter represented by Russian communism.146 Just as Chinese exclusion and the U.S.-China alliance during World War II could not coexist, southern European (refugee) exclusion and the Atlantic alliance could not coexist during the cold war. The 1924 Quota Act had declared the “new” immigrants from the Balkans to be racially suspect, but these suspect people became allies against communism. “We must ask ourselves what effect restrictions have upon the people of Greece, of Yugoslavia, and of Turkey—those key countries in our stand against communist aggression.”147 When an internationalist foreign policy and an isolationist immigration policy con›icted, many argued that it was the immigration policy that had to change. As in the case of the Balkan exclusions, internationalists argued against expatriating naturalized Italians who had voted in Italy after the war. Because a communist government could result, the Italian-American had to be forgiven: “The ballot cast by the individual Italian was weighed with consequences not only for his nation, but for the future of Europe and the peace of the world.”148 Moral authority would cap American power to assure alliance stability. Strategic defense centered in Europe. “Thoughtful persons are becoming increasingly aware of the direct and important relationship between the immigration policy of the United States and our policy of joining with other nations of the world in defense of our way of life. However the restrictive features of this bill will work the greatest hardship against those countries on the continent of Europe which are joined with us in the North Atlantic Pact.”149 Defense also depended, as it had in the past, on keeping enemies out of the Western Hemisphere. “The Caribbean is right on our doorstep, as are the other countries of South and Central America. Those are important defenses at our door. This is the goodwill of people which
126
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
we certainly want to keep. . . . I think it ought to be considered entirely in terms of American security, foreign policy, and friendship with our nextdoor neighbors.”150 Immigrants from western Europe as well as from the Americas should, therefore, be welcomed as a sign of American intent. Immigrants from Europe should be welcomed for practical reasons as well. Europe contained a population too large and too loosely tied to local community to remain politically stable. “In the past, what has happened when they have bulged to the seams? When their seams split, we had Mussolini, who tried to expand into Ethiopia.”151 Immigration to the United States would allow Europe to depressurize. One proposal, known as the Humphrey-Lehman bill, “would open our doors to limited numbers of otherwise quali‹ed aliens from the teeming and overcrowded cities and villages of Italy, Greece, Holland, Germany, and Austria—areas where surplus populations, indigenous and refugee, now strain the political stability and internal economy of the countries involved.”152 President Truman too argued that “one of the gravest problems arising from the present world crisis is created by the overpopulation in parts of Western Europe, aggravated by the ›ight and expulsion of people from the oppressed countries of Eastern Europe. The problem is of great practical importance to us because it affects the peace and security of the free world.”153 Overpopulation and immigration solutions affected other strategic areas. European overpopulation created problems in other areas. Truman argued that “overpopulation is one of the main factors preventing the fullest recovery of those countries where it exists. It is a serious drag on the economies of nations belonging to the North Atlantic Treaty Organization. A solution to this problem, therefore, becomes vitally necessary to strengthen the defense of the North Atlantic Community.”154 Immigration would solve those problems and solve problems in other areas as well. The transplanted Europeans could bene‹t the United States. A sound national policy would make it practicable for us to admit larger numbers of worthy immigrants from the overcrowded countries of the Old World. Thus, we would contribute our share toward the relief of population pressures in war-torn countries abroad and we would, at the same time, add to our supply of manpower so urgently needed here in order to assure continued and expanded productivity on our farms and in our factories which is so vital to our national security.155 Postwar security concerns differed from those understood before the war. A totalizing bipolar ideological con›ict meant that for the ‹rst time great powers had to be concerned about the way they were viewed, not just
The McCarran-Walter Act
127
by other great powers but by those in the periphery as well. Immigration policy’s symbolism gave it great weight. Owen Lattimore . . . suggests that after the war there is going to be a great deal of shopping around, so to speak, among the smaller Asiatic nations to see into whose orbit they would prefer to ‘cuddle,’ if I may use that phrase. . . . They are not so retarded in their thinking as we suppose. . . . They are adding up the political score, and certainly are going to try to veer in that direction which gives them the most advantage. . . . the three countries that have the most political attraction, or shall we call it ‘sex appeal’ toward the Asiatic people are America, Russia, and China. The other imperial nations are not in the picture.156 Not all of those concerned to ‹ght the ideological war drew the conclusion that internationalizing relations and liberalizing immigration were necessary to cement alliance. Pat McCarran, chair of the senate’s immigration committee, argued the opposite. Liberals and internationalists aided the communist cause. There is in custody of the subcommittee evidence which establishes beyond a reasonable doubt that there is extensive subversive activity being carried on in this country under the active direction and leadership of agents of foreign countries. . . . this situation has been vastly complicated by the growth of numerous international organizations and commissions with headquarters or of‹ces in this country, and the resultant groups of aliens that have been permitted to enter the United States. Our entire immigration system has been so weakened as to make it often impossible for our country to protect its security in this black era of ‹fth-column in‹ltration and Cold Warfare with the ruthless masters of the Kremlin.157 He continued: “The results of the war have placed the USSR in a position to take complete advantage of the facilities afforded by international bodies.”158 In an of‹cial Senate report, a committee under his supervision concluded that “Communist agents have used international organizations in this country as a vehicle for carrying on anti-American activity.”159 Communists worried about foreigners; therefore, “The communists are behind this so-called anti-genocide movement which they are trying to force onto this country through the so-called United Nations.”160 If internationalism aided communism, then the immigration guidelines that were to be liberalized in support of this internationalism also aided communism. Immi-
128
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
gration guidelines in this way became the ‹rst line of defense against communism. Weapons could prevent threats by states, including the Soviet state, but only immigration restrictions could prevent threats by foreign ideologies. Even before the war, subversion was greatly feared. If we hope to preserve our free democracy as was handed down to us by an illustrious ancestry; if we mean to perpetuate our liberty, we must immediately take steps to rid our land of these enemy aliens who are busily engaged in spreading the doctrines of hate and discontent, and who are boring from within, with a view to the ‹nal overthrow of our Government. It may require some painful surgery to remove this suppurating cancer. Mr. Speaker, the greatest menace to this country today does not come from abroad. Our greatest danger lies in the activities of these subversive in›uences, and the sooner we suppress them the better for our country—the last pure democracy on the face of the earth (Applause).161 Communism had to be foreign in origin and thus arrived only as an import. It also threatened to rot the country, to tear it apart starting on the inside. “We have as much to fear from our enemies from within as from without.”162 An external threat could be seen and protected against, but such an internal threat to the country’s sovereign integrity, once it took hold, the country could do nothing about. “Mr. President, this is a time of world tension and climactic struggle, when we should labor unceasingly to make America strong. . . . Should a third world war occur, I feel that this Nation would be faced with sabotage of its industrial resources by Red agents already in our midst, who have come into the country in the past few years.”163 Communist subversion would have two devastating consequences: it would eliminate social consensus and result in domestic chaos, and it would establish groups in the United States that were ready to sell the country to a foreign power. Since the rise of Soviet Russia during the past three decades, the problem of subversives has become a vital consideration in any evaluation of our immigration and naturalization policies. The impact of world events on our immigration system can no longer be ignored. As an international conspiracy, communism has organized systematic in‹ltration of our borders for the purpose of overthrowing the democratic Government of the United States of America by force, violence, and subversion. . . . Communism is, of necessity, an alien force. It is
The McCarran-Walter Act
129
inconceivable that the people of the United States would, of their own volition, organize or become part of a conspiracy to destroy the free institutions to which generations of Americans have devoted themselves.164 The Soviet state was communist and subversive, but it was also a state ready to conquer the United States. Communists necessarily immigrated, so protecting against communism meant excluding immigrants. Subversion “is not a home grown product [but] a ‹fth-column in‹ltration of an international conspiracy.”165 In fact, “nine out of every ten of the Communists that have been convicted of treason in this country were foreign born. If you want more of that element in here to wreck this country, ‹rst continue to tear down the gates of immigration. . . . We have a Cold War against these Reds here at home.”166 Communist versus anticommunist ‹ghts were not the only problems that communist subversion would precipitate. Racial strife, always imminent, would be touched off. “Communists are trying to force this so-called anti-segregation onto the people of the South, . . . try[ing] to force amalgamation of the whites and Negroes and in that way destroy the white race.”167 The Immigration and Naturalization Service prepared to guard against precisely this danger: “The guerrilla warfare of ideas is fought principally by in‹ltration into the body politic of those people whose political convictions and dogmas con›ict with those of this democracy. The uniform of communist ideology is not easy to identify—it may be a guise worn by a citizen or an alien. When worn by an alien or a naturalized citizen, it becomes the proper function of the Service, by every adjudicatory and enforcement means available, to subvert these ideological warriors.”168 At stake was internal cohesion. “America must have the power to expel these parasites who utilize our freedom as a cloak from which to slay free government.”169 It appears to me that the present world situation is being rather satisfactorily re›ected in this proposed legislation. While on the one hand we intend to correct certain shortcomings of our immigration and naturalization laws hampering the free and highly desirable international exchange of skills, scienti‹c experiences, and professional abilities by the free nations of the world, on the other hand we have taken notice of the activities of subversive elements inspired and directed by our enemies and we have tried to the best of our abilities to strengthen the safeguards protecting the internal security of the Nation.170
130
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
The cold fact is that agents of international communism today move freely across our borders to engage in espionage and anti-American propaganda, to plot with impunity the destruction of our free institutions. . . . today we are spending much of the treasure of this Nation to maintain our military might. Our efforts will prove futile, however, if the gate is left open for the entry of Trojan horses.171 What was at stake was government, for communist “favors the abolition of individual sovereign governments and the establishment of a major government.”172 For this reason, “the time has long passed when we can afford to open our borders indiscriminately to give unstinting hospitality to any person whose purpose, whose ideologic goal, is to overthrow our institutions and replace them with the evil oppression of totalitarianism.”173 The country had to prepare, through immigration policies, to accelerate the “battle which we are waging for the hearts and minds of men, a battle which we are waging not for self-interest but in order to preserve the peace and security of the world.”174
Policy Proposals: Displaced Persons, HumphreyLehman, McCarran-Walter
These strands of argument came together somewhat differently in each of the debates over a speci‹c policy proposal. The debate about displaced persons contained in microcosm the ideas and fears embedded in postwar discussion of immigration. Humanitarian reasons combined with interest in rehabilitating Europe to suggest allowing the displaced to resettle in the United States. Even those generally opposed to lifting restrictions on immigration favored settling displaced persons, for they “were displaced, were they not, as a result partly of the connivance of our own Government at Potsdam?”175 Humanitarian considerations could be served while pursuing the country’s self-interest as well. “Not only would such action save untold human suffering. It will be one more step toward solving the problems of settling Europe, and of lessening the necessity for large forces of occupation. It will be proof to the world that we are more than willing to pay the price of peace, the price of tolerance, of humanitarian understanding, and of realistic use of our riches to the end of world-wide freedom, justice, and peace.”176 The United States not only had an interest in developing its credibility, but had a duty to ful‹ll: “The war placed upon our country a great moral obligation to see to it that justice was done at the close of the war to the thousands upon thousands of displaced persons
The McCarran-Walter Act
131
who have, in fact, been placed in what amount to concentration camps.”177 Hegemonic leadership gave the country new tasks. Let us now consider the whole situation in the light of our foreign policy. The United States enjoys the highest moral credit of any nation in the world today. Any cause for which we plead had the sympathetic consideration of the majority of the nations of the United Nations. The maintenance of this position of leadership in the world gives us the opportunity of attaining a century of peace from today through the effectiveness of the United Nations, but it also involves the responsibility that we shall participate in the world’s problems and take our share of the world’s burdens. One of the most plaguing problems of the postwar era and constantly a stark reminder of the imprint of war are the refugees and displaced persons. We must take our share of this responsibility and in good season.178 But complicating this rather straightforward proposal to admit some refugees was the problem of the war. It was one thing to admit refugees from a war that had passed, another to admit refugees from a war just getting under way. With a war that was just starting, the refugees could be enemies. The stakes were higher for both sides, those for and those opposed to immigration. “After we have dealt with the problem of the displaced persons who were driven out by the Germans, we now have the problem of the displaced persons who were driven out by the communists.”179 President Truman pointed out that by de‹nition, displaced persons are neither communist nor fascist.180 “Is it likely that people who have been subjected to slave labor would try to bring the doctrine of communism into this country?”181 Meanwhile, Francis Bolton argued that displaced persons must go either to the United States or the Soviet Union, so the United States had better try to win.182 Those who disagreed viewed the displaced as they viewed all other Europeans: agitators. “There is certainly no good sense in any program that imports a great segment of European agitation into the American hemisphere.”183 Yet Truman had already set a policy in motion. Presidential Directive of 22 December 1945 had allotted 90 percent of the nonpreference portion of national quotas for displaced persons. It did not raise the numerical limit, but it did give displaced persons preference over the category remaining after all relatives and skilled persons had been admitted. The Displaced Persons Act, like immigration legislation before it and after it, passed by a large majority distinguished from its opposition not so
132
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
much by party as by region and support for a particular justi‹cation for evaluating immigrants.184 Although immigrants in general were undesirable—and these same legislators were to reaf‹rm the 150,000 ceiling and the national origins system four years hence—those who were displaced by the war were seen as an unusual subset of the population of prospective immigrants. They were viewed as the victims, not the initiators, of war; those who were unable to return to their homes at the war’s conclusions slid directly from the role of World War II refugees into the role of cold war refugees. Also entering into this vote was commitment to the principle of non-refoulement. It was morally impossible for representatives to vote to repatriate refugees, by force, into the areas from which they ›ed, even while those same representatives would refuse to allow those who had never left in the ‹rst place to emigrate to the United States. Commitment to non-refoulement seems to have increased during the postwar period; its strength helps to explain what otherwise appears to be an anomaly, antiNazi, anticommunist and anti-European anti-immigrant legislators voting at the height of McCarthyism and postwar debates on internationalism to admit European refugees. It should be noted that those similarly displaced by the Americans, their allies and enemies—again, of World War II but also the cold war—in the Paci‹c were not covered by this legislation and were never seriously considered for assistance. Europe was not only the center of the “geo” in geopolitics; it was also the center of “human” in humanitarian. In June 1948, the Displaced Persons Act gave countries housing refugees an extra 205,000 over the next two years. As a way to admit refugees without admitting more people than the ceiling allowed—and without displacing relatives and others given preference within those limits—the act provided that any excess would be charged against the country’s quotas in future years. Many of the smaller countries found their quotas mortgaged into the twenty-‹rst century, but the settlers who would have come to the United States then were allowed entry immediately. After an amendment to reinstate the displaced persons mortgages was rejected,185 the act passed in the House 289 to 91, with 50 not voting; and in the Senate 58 to 15, with 23 not voting.186 Communism’s actual military threat remained hypothetical until the Korean invasion in 1950. That invasion gave anticommunist restrictionists the evidence that they needed to sway opinion. “We have seen in Korea and elsewhere that the threat is a serious one. It is not going to do us any good to have a powerful army in Japan or in Germany, or in Africa, if millions of potential subversives are here in the United States where they can destroy us without military invasion.”187 The war could escalate. “The gathering of war clouds resulting from the Communist aggression in
The McCarran-Walter Act
133
Korea only serve to undermine [sic, underline] the threat to our national defense from the invasion of our borders by indeterminate numbers of illegal aliens.”188 The need for consistency reinforced the need for security. “Nothing can be more inconsistent than for us to pass the pending bill while at the same time we face growing casualty lists in the Korean war.”189 Similarly, “we are ‹ghting a war in Korea in the hope of checking world communism in that part of the world. The least we can do at home is to make sure that Communists do not take over our own part of the world.”190 The war in Korea presaged World War III and thereby showed legislators what American security demanded. Those opposed to restriction used the war to draw a very different lesson. Allies offended by racial exclusions were liable to become communist with enthusiasm. Restrictionists would erect an iron curtain around the United States—an iron curtain of arbitrary standards which would mark us for the rest of the world as a nation which declines to practice the principles which we preach. . . . What folly it is . . . to spend hundreds of billions of dollars on defense and to incur more than 100,000 casualties in Korea, and then to undercut this great investment of our boys’ blood and their parents’ money by passing a bill which turns the world against us, as the McCarran bill would do. . . . ‘We love you, but we love you from afar. We want you, but for God’s sake stay where you are.’191 Koreans would be offended, but Americans would also be handicapped. “As long as this needless insult, for example, to Koreans, remains on our statute books, we are sending our soldiers into that land to ‹ght with one hand tied behind their backs, or at least without the full moral armament they deserve and which it is our business to provide them.”192 Decisiveness was crucial to effective containment. Following the Displaced Persons Act, restrictionists and liberals each proposed a general law to overhaul general immigration policy. Table 4 summarizes the arguments made during this period for and against the restrictions that the McCarran-Walter Act eventually reaf‹rmed. The Humphrey-Lehman proposal liberalized both numbers and characteristics. While the legal ceiling would not rise, numbers actually admitted would increase because the slots that went unused each year, such as those for England, would be pooled and reallocated. The bill would abolish all discrimination on the bases of race and sex, instead establishing four equal preference categories: family members, refugees, “national need” (labor), and nonpreference. It was sold as anti-Nazi, for example, “This bill knocks in the head the
134
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
theory of superior races. This bill is opposed to the theory advanced by Hitler’s Germany and the war lords of Japan, and accepts the American theory of equality.”193 The Humphrey-Lehman bill did not, however, survive in spite of its supporters’ attempt to ‹libuster. Because of its failure to protect the country against an “invasion” by communists and Europeans, a motion to recommit the bill was rejected 28 to 44, with 24 not voting; it was again rejected in the Senate 27 to 51, with 18 not voting. Figure 7 portrays the arguments about immigrants that followed World War II. World War II prompted the return of attention to immigration policy, and evidence culled from the country’s experience with the war helped to change the types of arguments that could be considered consistent with the public interest. The war was, like its predecessor, initiated by Europeans and fought primarily by them. It was also decided by the Americans, who had entered late and had, in their opinion, saved the Europeans from themselves again. The recent context was less conducive to trans-Atlantic cooperation than had been that following World War I; depression, protectionism, and isolationism had separated the countries for decades before World War II. Americans’ propensity to get involved with Europeans had not changed. What had changed was their perception of threat. Nazism was simultaneously bellicose and racist; Stalinism, like fascism, was an ideological rather than an ethnic threat. The McCarran-Walter proposal kept the national origins quota system intact, including its reliance on the 1920 census. Its innovations were two. First, it established a Chinese quota and a single Asian quota. For the ‹rst time, those of Asian ancestry were eligible to immigrate. Most controversial was its insistence that those of Asian ancestry, no matter where born, count against this quota. The Asia-Paci‹c Triangle ancestry provision held that residents of “every country wholly situated north of 25th parallel of South latitude and between 60 degrees east and 165 degrees west longitude” would be chargeable to the 100-person quota. This applied to persons descended from residents of this area, as well as the region’s current occupants, to anyone “born outside the Asia-Paci‹c triangle who is attributable by as much as one-half of his ancestry.”194 Whereas a white French citizen would count against the French quota, a French citizen of as little as half Chinese ancestry would count against the Chinese quota. The other innovation was its communist exclusion provisions. The bill speci‹ed organizations whose membership, past or suspected, was suf‹cient to ban any applicant. Opponents labeled it racist, xenophobic, inimical to the country’s foreign policy efforts, and destructive of civil liberties. Adam Clayton Powell declared that “the ancestry test smacks
The McCarran-Walter Act
135
World War II European Aggression, but also Nazi Racism ⇓ Causal Argument
Public Interest Argument
Policy Argument
Ethnic nationalism causes civil and international war by creating a toocoherent society subject to fanaticism
Preventing war is in the public interest because civil society is impossible without order and peace
Allowing in only immigrants racially like Americans will cause war either by angering others or by feeding fascism at home
Ideological unity won World War II
Winning war is in the public interest
Allowing in only those ideologically like Americans will assure that the U.S. will be able to prevail again
Involvement with Europeans leads to entanglement and, eventually, war
Preventing war is in the public interest because civil society is impossible without order and peace
Keeping distance from European people is necessary if the country is safely to become closer to European governments
↑ ↑ plausibility
↑
Implementation National Origins Quotas provoked war and threatened civilization
↑ efficiency
↑
↓ Ideas about Causation: Racism Causes War, Ideology Wins War Perverse Effects: Provoked Japan, Rather Than Isolated the U.S. From It Championed Eugenic Immigration Policies Too Similar to the Nazis’. Fig. 7.
Arguments offered after World War II
closely of the infamous Nuremberg laws of Hitler Germany. . . . This bill sets up a Cape Town–Washington DC axis. That is what it does. This bill makes this no longer a land of the free, but a place only for Anglo-Saxons.”195 Others argued that “the McCarran-Walter immigration bill is a step in the direction of dictatorship and police methods.”196 Further, “the bill . . . would jeopardize our international relations.”197 The bill’s two main sponsors rejected their opponents’ criticisms entirely. Francis Walter argued in favor of the bill that it contained no sex discrimination or racial limits, added twelve new quota areas in Southeast Asia and the Arab Gulf, promoted immigration of skilled laborers, and
136
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
included an allowance for temporary labor while deporting “slackers” and tightening deportation, especially of communist in‹ltrators. He added that the bill continued to rely on the 1920 census because the 1940 and 1950 censuses were not yet ready.198 Pat McCarran, the bill’s cosponsor, argued that the law kept national origins quotas but did away with racial discrimination.199 McCarran-Walter passed the Senate by a voice vote on 22 May 1952. The conference report passed the House on 10 June 1952 by 203 to 53. One outcome of this bill was that the country excluded the same group of people for very different reasons. In some cases, the transition between justi‹cations was smooth. The Chinese had been racial outcasts until 1943; after 1949 they were ideological outcasts. In other cases, it was ‹lled with tension. Southern Europeans had been racially unsatisfactory, then were fascists or collaborators, but became refugees from communism. The old view and the new compromised uneasily by giving refugees preference within country limits that were no higher than before the war. Truman vetoed the act on 25 June 1952, arguing that What we do in the ‹eld of immigration and naturalization is vital to the continued growth and internal development of the United States—to the economic and social strength of our country—which is the core of the defense of the free world. Our immigration policy is equally, if not more, important to the conduct of our foreign relations and to our responsibilities of moral leadership in the struggle for world peace. . . . Today we have entered into an alliance, the North Atlantic Treaty, with Italy, Greece, and Turkey against one of the most terrible threats mankind has ever faced. We are asking them to join with us in protecting the peace of the world.200 Dean Acheson, of course, supported this position. “Immigration, like most important facets of our national life in these times, is closely linked with our foreign policy and objectives. Our immigration policy with respect to particular national or racial groups, will inevitably be taken as an indication of our general attitude toward them, especially as an indication of our appraisal of their standing in the world.”201 The executive branch, then and always more sensitive to the international implications of “national” policy, opposed the reaf‹rmation of restriction. Congress, however, supported it overwhelmingly, voting to override Truman’s veto. Those who had voted to welcome some displaced persons also voted to restrict their compatriots; in spite of turnover in the House, 117 representatives voted both for the Displaced Persons Act and for
The McCarran-Walter Act
137
McCarran-Walter. Liberals did not change their minds. Victor Anfuso, Emanuel Celler, Jacob Javits, and Peter Rodino were among those who voted against McCarran-Walter, and they had argued others should. The 117 were, rather, those who had transferred their analysis of World War II onto the cold war: safety meant distance from Europe. They were prudent humanitarians, worried about American sovereignty and security, and not certain of how to handle the post–World War II era. They included, for example, Thomas Jenkins, who had argued that “we have had enough experience with these European countries. . . . We always get the worst of it even when we are trying to save ourselves from them. In this new proposal we are attempting to save them from themselves.”202 But they also included Edward Rees, who had declared in 1943 that “If legislation permitting 105 Chinese to come into this country . . . will help in anywise in prosecution of the war . . . there will be no objection to it by the American people.”203 The majority position could have been summed up by John Vorys, when he argued, “We now have a country to which millions of people want to come from all over the world, and I do not blame them. But, if we let down the bars in a misguided spirit of humanitarianism and let them all come in or let groups of favorites come in based on political pressures here, we will dilute and ultimately destroy the thing they came for.”204 The world was too uncertain, and sovereignty too fragile, to take a chance on opening the borders. The executive branch never wavered in its support for liberalizing immigration policy. After Truman, Eisenhower, a Republican, joined its opponents. “We say—and we know—that the Communists are on the side of slavery, the side of inhumanity. Yet to the Czech, the Pole, the Hungarian who takes his life in his hands and crosses the frontier tonight—or to the Italian who goes to some American consulate—this ideal that beckoned him can be a mirage because of the McCarran Act.”205 Table 4 outlines the changes that the McCarran-Walter Act made to the Quota Act legislation. The executive branch wanted to abolish national origins restrictions, establish an overall maximum of 250,000 (up from 150,000), make preferences ›exible to meet refugees’ needs, and do away with mortgages. This meant keeping the one-sixth of 1 percent formula, but using the whole U.S. population, rather than only that of white ancestry, and basing quotas on the 1950 census. The executive derived this from a population total of 150,697,361 (134,971,622 white; 15,042,692 Negro; 369,637 Asian; 343,410 American Indian). Nevertheless, the House overrode Truman’s veto 278 to 112, with 40 not voting; the Senate overrode it on 27 June 1952 by 57 to 26, with 13 not voting. “The history of immigration laws,”
TABLE 4.
The McCarran-Walter Act
Act
Numerical Restrictions
Preference Categories
Unrestricted (Non-Quota) Immigrants •U.S. citizens' wives and unmarried children under 18 •Western Hemisphere natives, or residents for at least 5 years
National Origins Quota Act To 1929 (Johnson-Reed) Overall ceiling: 164,667 Method of allocation: Each Immigration Act of European country received May 26, 1924 a cap equal to 2 percent of the number of persons born there residing in the U.S. in 1890. After 1929 Overall ceiling: 153,714 Method of allocation: Each country received a cap based on the proportion of all U.S. residents, in 1920, of that nationality.
•Unmarried children under 21 •Parents •Spouses of U.S. citizens over age 21 •Skilled agricultural workers and their wives and children under 16
Immigration and Nationality Act (McCarran-Walter)
•Husbands of U.S. citizens •1st: Aliens with special skills, with their spouses and children, 50 percent •2d: Parents of U.S. citizens, 30 percent •3d: Spouses and children of resident aliens, 20 percent •4th: Other relatives of U.S. citizens, 25 percent culled from unused slots above •Nonpreference: Any remaining unused
Act of June 27, 1952
Overall ceiling: 154,657 Method of allocation: Each country given a cap equal to one-sixth of 1 percent of the persons in the U.S. in 1920 whose ancestry derived from that area. Established a minimum of 100, and granted Asian countries a general ceiling of 2000.
Exclusions •No one ineligible for citizenship
•Communists, as outlined in the Internal Security Act •Drug addicts •Anyone attempting fraud •Additionally established the alien address report system, which required aliens to report their addresses annually for inclusion in a central security file
The McCarran-Walter Act
139
observed the Immigration Commissioner in 1950, “has been one of increasing restriction.”206 Table 4 summarizes the changes that the McCarran-Walter Act made to American immigration policy. Supporters and opponents of immigration restriction generally, and the McCarran-Walter Act speci‹cally, agreed about the facts. The United States’ power gave it global preeminence, while its democratic system made it a model for others to emulate. Trade with American allies bene‹ted all involved. The Soviet Union, a second of disturbingly uncertain distance, sought to impair the United States by underwriting American communist groups and eastern European military satellites. Refugees from communist countries begged entrance into the United States; how the country handled their widely publicized entreaty would affect America’s ability to counter the Soviet threat. What these facts meant, though, the two sides could not agree on. They drew different conclusions about relations among the NATO countries; American interest in Europe and the Third World; the relevance of American leadership to the cold war’s outcome; the importance of consistency between domestic and foreign policies; and refugees’ motives and effects on American society, the economy, and political life. In short, they disagreed about the boundaries of American attention and interests. This difference accounts for an acute divergence between the immigration policies each side recommended. Isolationists saw the United States as a pure, and necessarily lonely, exemplar. Foreign policy was designed to prevent the outside world from affecting the country; interdependence subverted sovereignty. The society that American boundaries sheltered was fragile, based upon the slowly acquired—and tenuous—assimilation of non-English to democratic institutions. Government’s ‹rst duty was to de›ect foreign in›uences, to allow social and political integration to continue to the bene‹t of citizens. This was also government’s only duty; the world beyond its borders was none of its concern. In fact, attention to foreign people and problems would precipitate the country’s downfall. Enlarging or complicating the direct, two-way link between government and people would undermine domestic sovereignty. The relationship between ruler and ruled had not only to be tight but mutually exclusive in order for the country really to be sovereign. Further, if government enacted policies based not just on citizens’ values and interests but also on those of foreigners, the country was no longer sovereign domestically and was therefore not sovereign in relation to others. Taking a speci‹ed group of people into account was the essence of a government’s claim to sovereignty. If the group that a government considered increased because people renounced a foreign membership in exchange for American citizenship, then the country was structurally sta-
140
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
ble, sovereignty unthreatened. It was quantitatively but not qualitatively altered. If the group increased, however, because the government took into account views of people not citizens—or worse, took foreigners’ interests into account while ignoring segments of the local population—then the pact between citizen and government was broken. The boundaries separating those within and those outside the country were uncertain, sovereignty in jeopardy. Its citizens’ good, the value that a government must pursue, had nothing whatever to do with events or people or processes beyond the country’s borders. Internationalists conceived of America differently. Foreign policy should strengthen the United States; interdependence empowered the nation. Their image of the United States included American allies, so the boundary they thought crucial to the country’s survival, and sought to defend, was that between East and West, not that between the United States and others. They were as concerned as isolationists with separating “us” from “them,” but whereas isolationists de‹ned “us” as American citizens, internationalists included in the category other states and peoples, allies in the ‹ght against communism. American interests were tied up with Europe’s, and later the Southern Hemisphere states’, future. Taking potential allies’ views into account strengthened the United States. Enlarging the group of people that the country considered when evaluating policies that codi‹ed its relation with the rest of the world allowed the government to anticipate and control other countries’ concerns. Internationalism extended American power. To isolationists, internationalism eroded American sovereignty. This crucial difference underlies further distinctions between the points of view. To isolationists, what other countries thought of the United States mattered not at all. Foreign policy operated according to a logic unrelated to domestic values. For this reason, isolationists did not care whether others viewed American foreign policy, which might support ends at odds with domestic values, as hypocritical. Consistency between domestic and foreign policy, or among foreign policies, was valuable only if it strengthened policies’ mutual support in practical terms. Internationalists, in contrast, saw foreign policy as a sphere in which ties of interest and value bound others to the United States. Inconsistency meant hypocrisy, enough to turn potential allies away from the United States and toward its enemies. Internationalists believed that American power depended on leadership, leadership depended on credibility, and credibility depended on consistency. In this way only could norms and regimes of principle govern allies’ relations. Consistency of principle or value implied, as well, a consistent means of dividing citizens from aliens. To isolationists, immigrants were by
The McCarran-Walter Act
141
de‹nition subversives in that they comprised a class to which the government owed protection but which had no historical or legal tie to the country. Immigrants were likely also subversive in practice, since they by de‹nition had to arrive from communities at odds with the United States—and, to isolationists, all countries were at odds with the United States. If they were damaging with benign intent, they were profoundly destructive with subversive intent. Their presence was logically troublesome, practically exasperating, or directly threatening. In all cases, they muddied the border between what was inside and what outside sovereign purview. Internationalists, on the other hand, saw strength in immigrants. Those emigrating from allied countries increased ties of affection between the United States and its allies, added to the American work force, and relieved population pressure overseas. Those emigrating from enemy countries added to anticommunist convictions at home, provided intelligence, weakened the communist countries that could no longer exploit the emigrant, and provided important propaganda material. Wherever immigrants came from, they helped to clarify the divisions between East and West upon which American security and identity had come to depend. The difference between setting boundaries of concern at the American border or at the frontier between East and West had enormous implications for policy in other areas. It complicated the familiar left/right split. Internationalism of this sort could lead to liberal foreign and humanitarian aid policies; it also could justify neoimperialism or hegemonic paternalism. Isolationism, similarly, could protect reactionary racism and paranoid conservatism, but could also support efforts to curb the effects that American businesses and international bureaucracies had on Europe and the Third World. What that difference did mean was that internationalists viewed change at home and abroad as relevant for American foreign and immigration policies (and saw the difference between “at home” and “abroad” shrinking), while isolationists insisted on its irrelevance. Developments within the United States, such as the Depression and labor socialism, internationalists asserted, had implications for foreign policies. So, they claimed, did processes beyond the country’s borders, such as war and European colonial expansion. Such events sparked debate about policy boundaries and hence about immigrants. This debate eventually created consensus on an image of the country different enough from that embedded in the McCarran-Walter Act to justify revamping immigration policy. McCarran-Walter served as a pillar of isolationism. McCarran-Walter was not, however, in support of an isolationist foreign policy since there was no isolationist foreign policy. The U.S. government had concurrently organized a multitude of institutions to tie its fate to that of Europe,
142
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Japan, and Canada. Its trade, weapons, and ‹scal policies integrated its future with that of other countries. Nor were the isolationist immigration policies outlined in McCarran-Walter merely a holdover from an earlier time. Believing that external change had forced a reconsideration of its immigration policies, Congress examined the immigration and naturalization laws, held extensive hearings, set up independent commissions, and debated possible revisions. They did not let policy slide; they chose change in response to altered circumstances. But although the new circumstances involved American dominance and international reach, as well as a set of policies institutionalizing the new order, the new immigration policy codi‹ed more rigid boundaries between American citizens and others. McCarran-Walter represented a new way of thinking about sovereignty. Different issues, in different realms, could have different borders. Economic boundaries encompassed all noncommunist areas. Tourists, business travelers, laborers, commodities, manufactured goods, capital and ‹nancial ›ows all traveled where private citizens wished them to go; moreover, others could buy and sell parcels of American territory as well as industries. Ideological boundaries extended through the Western Hemisphere to Europe and Japan. Primary military boundaries divided NATO allies from others; secondary military boundaries were just the other side of communist-controlled regions. Political boundaries, those separating citizens from noncitizens, were the only boundaries coincident with the forty-eight states’ common borders.207 The United States secured direct control over people while eroding its control over goods and territory. The country increased its power by eliminating earlier borders channeling territorial allocation and trade ›ows.208 It secured its sovereignty by creating borders that strengthened the division between citizens and aliens. Although the McCarran-Walter Act would be challenged and eventually overturned, this bifurcation between policies toward citizens and toward things was to become characteristic of policy throughout the West for the remainder of the century. Change was signi‹cant but subtle. Americans ascribed their dominance in the war in part to their vast industrial base, huge work force and consumer market, and technological edge; their victory they ascribed also to their willingness to lead. Europe especially needed American guidance to save itself and to realize its economic potential. This was a potential dilemma. To Americans, sovereignty still meant independence from others’ in›uence as well as control. But whereas true interdependence and absolute sovereignty could not coexist, an expansive, dominant internationalism preventing others from controlling the United States could protect American sovereignty. The country could adopt an outgoing eco-
The McCarran-Walter Act
143
nomic internationalism without endangering its authority. Former congressman Nathan Perlman argued: Whether or not the policy of that time was wise, Congress could then have claimed for itself at least the virtue of consistency. The 1924 act was an integral part of the American attempt at international isolation. Since 1924 we have reversed our foreign policy and, in the interest of consistency, it is necessary that any immigration legislation now proposed likewise re›ect this reversal.209 Sovereignty depended not on complete control over resources, territory and people, but only over territory and people. Resources meant power; territory and population meant sovereignty. After both wars, Americans could reach back into their history and point to a tradition that was threatened by foreign involvements. The public culture was Anglo-Saxon, most people were of European descent, and American institutions had a republican basis. Americans did, in this sense, remain the same and judge immigrants’ threat to essential Americanness. But the “America” that immigration policy protected was plastic. There was by the 1950s no national identity that was de‹nite enough and excluded enough to provide a constant standard. It is not that the country went from thinking of itself as white to thinking that race did not matter; rather, it moved from thinking in racial terms to thinking in ideological terms. What was important changed; the context for American identity, and hence the standard to use in thinking about what to protect, changed with the external threat.
CHAPTER 6
Whom to Exclude, Whom to Prefer: The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
Often, the changes Congress made to the immigration act in 1965 are described as revolutionary. In one way, they are. Congress removed race from the categories governing immigration and naturalization exclusion. This was the ‹rst federal statement about access to citizenship that did not say “white,” “Negro,” “Oriental,” or something similar. It fundamentally and irrevocably altered the legal basis for choosing America’s citizen population. It allowed immigration from every country and gave each country the same numerical limit, which allowed signi‹cant Asian and African migration for the ‹rst time. The act did not, however, increase the number able to enter; in fact, it altered the legal ceiling by pulling under it a previously unlimited group, Western Hemisphere immigrants. In that way, Congress extended regulatory control over the number allowed to enter, a profoundly conservative act, at the same time that it liberalized categories describing the characteristics it desired in its immigrants. This shift was, as were previous revisions of immigration policy, precipitated by an external change that challenged an assumption about American identity and interests on which prevailing policy rested. Like World Wars I and II and the Korean War, decolonization changed the context in which the United States located itself. Immigration policy no longer meshed with, and in fact undermined, the country’s stance vis-à-vis the rest of the world. Reformers hashed out a response that redirected policy to protect against the threats or take advantage of the opportunities in this new world. This response was then adjusted— magni‹ed or modi‹ed—through debate, by pointing to an outcome that might exacerbate a current domestic con›ict. Recent strife over civil rights suggested to some in the early 1960s that American blacks would take unequal treatment of Africans and Asians as a denial of black equality with whites; this followed concerns in earlier decades that “ethnic” Americans would take immigration quotas that did not match Americans’ national origins as a statement that they were second-class citizens. As was true in earlier years, legislators believed that how immigration policy 144
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
145
treated foreigners revealed how Americans viewed their fellow citizens, their allies, and their enemies. Geostrategy had to be made consistent with domestic policies. Immigration policy made great propaganda, the currency of the cold war. From 1952 through 1965, as in earlier periods, immigration policy provided the arena for direct ‹ghts between two views of American boundaries, sovereignty, and citizenship. To the 1920s, nativists and universalists had struggled over whether to establish boundaries at all, then over whether those boundaries ought to create a citizen group protected from racially motivated wars and therefore de‹ned by race. To the 1950s, isolationists and idealists had argued over whether boundaries prevented or created war. Should the country enforce divisions assuming a racial threat against a white population, or an economic or ideological threat against a liberal population? From the mid-1950s to mid-1960s, proponents of autarky and internationalism clashed over whether, for practical and moral purposes, American principles and programs should stop at the ‹fty states’ edge or should extend throughout the West. To decide whether self-interest should include the interests of non-Americans was to determine whether the “self” included noncitizens, whether American identity had to be based on a potentially transnational principle. In each period two viewpoints dominated, one de‹ning the group to be taken into account narrowly, the other broadly. What changed were the reasons given to justify where the boundary should be drawn, because what changed by 1965 were legislators’ interpretations of what new events meant for sovereignty and power. The majority viewed American policies with bifocals for the ‹rst time, seeing distance and proximity with equal clarity. They worried about how foreigners as well as citizens would interpret what policy said about the desirability of people of their type. They worried about the symbolic and political effects of any group, internal or external, believing that the United States held them in secret contempt. The standard for measuring how much was too much was not the American citizen population but other potential immigrant populations. Early exclusionists had argued that the United States allowed too many Italians compared to native Americans; in 1965, reformers argued that it allowed too many Italians compared to Chinese. Global leadership, the legislators belatedly concluded, did matter. The United States was to remain as strict as ever when it came to numbers—it extended regulatory control over new groups, keeping the overall limit the same as it ever was—but it liberalized criteria governing those few who were allowed to enter. Communism abroad motivated both isolationists and internationalists, who lobbied for far-reaching measures to counter communist expan-
146
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
sion. Some worried about the cold war at home while others worried about communism abroad; some groups stressed nonintervention and noninvolvement while others wrestled with the issue of how to develop and project American hegemony. The difference between them was not de‹ned by a left/right split, nor a pluralist/anticommunist split, nor an interventionist/noninterventionist split. Rather, one group fought the cold war at home; the other fought it abroad. One group adopted a strategy of nonintervention toward the outside world; the other adopted it toward American society. Why and how legislators became convinced that immigration policy needed to be overhauled can be seen in their discussions of who owed what to whom, whose interests ought to be taken into account, and what legitimate interests were. Possible catalysts to change during this period are lessening unemployment, which could reduce economic fears and perhaps encourage consideration of temporary laborers; domestic developments such as the civil rights movement and Great Society legislation promoting domestic equality and redistribution of opportunity—these could have encouraged change in desired immigrant characteristics by reforming the way that Americans thought about community; and external or foreign policy developments, such as the crises creating Hungarian and Cuban refugees, decolonization, the Kennedy assassination (by an expatriate), and the Vietnam War, which could have strengthened the country’s resolve to help allies and hurt enemies in the cold war. The events least controllable by the U.S. government—civil rights demands, decolonization, and refugees—in fact provided the greatest stimulus to change. The following sections outline the viewpoint prevailing as the debate started— the isolationist position—and the internationalist viewpoint challenging this, then consider possible stimuli to change. Arguments for change had to be tailored to contrast with current policy. McCarran-Walter drew the boundaries of American concern narrowly, focused attention on internal cohesion, and de‹ned American citizens in racial and ideological terms. McCarran-Walter’s champions were leaders in the domestic ‹ght against communism, not the international ‹ght. Indeed, Pat McCarran argued against creating international institutions to function as international outposts against Soviet expansion. “The foreign aid years” de‹ned by the Marshall Plan, he argued, “have also created another type—a companion type—the psychological warfare warrior; the man whose purpose in life is to listen to foreign voices, observe foreign reactions, assess overseas angers and overseas jubilance. This is the sort of man who is a doctor of philosophy of alien emotion.”1 The purpose of foreign policy was to ‹x things overseas so that Americans would not need to bother further. “Few, if any, will quarrel with the original basic
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
147
objectives of this mutual security foreign aid program: to prevent Americans from again having to ‹ght and die on foreign battle‹elds.”2 Francis Walter, McCarran’s cosponsor, wanted American activity overseas to contract. Refugee slots were underused, he argued, because American reconstruction of Europe had been a success.3 Nothing more need be done. McCarran rejected an internationalist anticommunism. “If we do not reject the idea of immigration as an instrument of national policy, as a pawn in the game of power politics, then our country is certain to become little different from the countries which these people would like to leave.”4 Although he argued strenuously for anticommunist immigration provisions, McCarran opposed using immigration policy to ‹ght the cold war. But with the idea of using refugees as chips in an international poker game, to achieve some advantage for ourselves, I am not at all in sympathy. If we are going to help refugees because they are refugees, because they are homeless and hungry and ill-clothed, that is one thing; if we are going to make a show of helping refugees in order to win an election in some European country, or get an agreement out of some European government, or try to win the friendship of the people of some country of Europe, I say the objective is primarily a sel‹sh one, and unworthy of the traditions of the United States of America.5 The United States ought, in his view, to ignore the wishes of others. At stake was the absolute sovereignty developed at the turn of the century, an authority that had to remain unquestioned and unresponsive to foreign demands to survive. Francis Walter declared that “throughout all our history immigration laws have been based on the premise that one of the ‹rst functions of sovereignty is control of both quality and quantity of prospective new citizens. The only yardstick in arriving at this determination has been the interest and welfare of the American people.”6 Soliciting others’ views was wrongheaded and unproductive. “All other advanced countries in the world recognize their right to regulate immigration to correspond with the desires and welfare of their own citizens. The United States alone seeks world approval, and I might add to no avail.”7 Listening to others “would inevitably lead to the weakening of the institutions of this country; and if we do not remain strong, then immigration policy will become a moot question in any event.”8 Isolation secured defense. Restrictionists’ views echoed those of earlier years. Immigration meant invasion. To remain sovereign, the population had to remain ‹nite and controlled. “If we keep on adding to the number admitted into our country, eventually we shall ‹nd ourselves without a country, without lib-
148
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
erty, without freedom, and without opportunity for veterans who return from Korea.”9 War was near suicide; immigration was in fact suicide. “The people of America do not want to turn their country over to the European hordes. . . . we have given them our boys, we have given them our blood; we have given them our substance; for God’s sake do not give them our country.”10 Sending money abroad for reconstruction siphoned off power, but allowing immigrants in was worse, for it eroded sovereignty. “American citizens have been taxed untold billions of dollars to support foreign governments and foreign peoples. Now we are being asked to surrender the country itself to the world’s hordes who are just waiting for the immigration barriers to be lowered.”11 International politics was a struggle to determine the ‹ttest. “Self-preservation, in my opinion, is the ‹rst law of nature.”12 Immigrants were nonentities in a world composed of one’s own citizens and other governments. “Immigration laws, like trade laws and the like, come under the normal exercise of sovereign power”; therefore, it is not logically possible to discriminate against immigrants.13 Moreover, “there has been some indication that we should not hurt the feelings of our friends, but America comes ‹rst.”14 If other countries’ policies affected the immigration stream, America was not sovereign. Russia expels people; “is Russia, in this manner, to establish our immigration policy by actually determining the exact individuals who are to make up the America of the future?”15 Isolationists viewed immigration policy as negotiating the country’s relationship to the rest of the world. In this prevailing view, domestic values were the only appropriate standards to use to judge acceptable immigration. Internal subversion presented the greatest threat to the country’s future. “If we bring in 200,000 aliens, and if our security of‹cers are 99 44100 percent perfect in their job, there would still be 1,120 subversives who would get into the United States. . . . Conquest of the United States of America at this period in world history would be the key to the conquest of the world, regardless of whether achieved by immigration, in‹ltration, ‹fth-column action, and economic warfare, or by military operations.”16 Only through immigration could the country be subverted. “Consistent with the Kremlin-centered nature of the world conspiracy is the fact that the communist apparatus in our country is not a homegrown product, but is a weed transported from abroad. . . . At this very hour, the Communist Party is organizing all over this Nation cells and fronts under the guise of study groups for the purpose of propagandizing and agitating for the repeal or emasculation of the Immigration and Nationality Act [McCarran-Walter].”17 For “too long traitors to this country have taken advantage of the many wonderful bene‹ts provided citizens of the United States at the same
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
149
time they are plotting to destroy the country.”18 Lee Harvey Oswald might not have been able to enter the United States had Congress taken suf‹cient action earlier.19 To save the United States, Americans had the duty to preserve the status quo. From this standpoint, national origins quotas’ value was in their ability to guard stability. Strom Thurmond argued: The wish to preserve one’s identity and the identity of one’s nation requires no justi‹cation—and no belief in racial or national superiority—any more than the wish to have one’s own children, and to continue one’s family through them, need be justi‹ed or rationalized by a belief that they are superior to the children of others. There is no merit in the contention that the quota system is racist or morally wrong. Individuals, and groups, including nations, have an absolute and unchallenged right to have preferences for other individuals or groups, and nothing could be more natural than a preference based on a sense of identity.20 Isolationists argued for national origins policy using new reasons. They claimed to be democrats, not racists. “To the contrary, I assert that anyone who believes in the equality of man should share my views, because if men are truly equal, the people who constitute the most numerous part of the population of any nation are necessarily those who contribute most to that country and its development.”21 The national origins formula “treats persons differently because they are basically different.”22 Anglo-Americans might, for example, be better than others in their political habits. “If we transfer the pattern of our immigration to countries and people who have historically maintained a totalitarian concept of government, it will only be a matter of time until our Republic will veer from its traditions of freedom and democracy.”23 Although President Johnson argued that national origins quotas “disparage the ancestors of millions of our fellow Americans,”24 isolationists disagreed. “The national origins quota system is based on conditions existing in the United States, and for this reason, it is like a mirror re›ecting the United States.”25 What was most valuable was that which protected the status quo. Isolationists sought to conserve (or create) a particular version of the United States. The country they desired was the country they imagined existed in the 1870s or so, one in which English, Irish, and Germans dominated, in which democracy worked, people spoke English, and they cared about their neighbors rather than about foreigners. It was a world focused in on itself, protected through isolation and ignorance from the chaos abroad. The domestic and foreign spheres were to be kept separate; should
150
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
they touch, the foreign would pollute the domestic, and the domestic would leak into the foreign. Complementing isolation was a policy promoting an internal purge. If the society could eliminate bad in›uences, it could close the borders con‹dent that it would not be harmed. Isolation, not alliance, protected it from communism. Internationalists, by contrast, viewed the United States not as a discrete sovereign unit but as the center of the West, a vast political realm whose borders were limited only by militarily forti‹ed East Bloc boundaries. Sovereignty in this realm still depended on authority, but since the struggle was global, authority had to be global. There were, therefore, no limits on territories or peoples whose welfare ought to be considered when weighing policies. Universalists before this period had denied borders’ relevance. Internationalists, though they shared universalists’ concern with events and people outside the country, departed from universalists by acknowledging borders’ importance. Boundaries mattered in the cold war. Internationalists were, also, forward-looking. Whereas isolationists valued the status quo and therefore sought to measure current policy by its deviation from past policy, internationalists left the past behind: “as far as ancestors are concerned, I will say they are like turnips—like turnips—nothing good of them but what is in the ground.”26 Relevant distinctions between citizen and noncitizen were no more nor less than those between West and East, friend and foe: loyalty to liberal principles of social distribution. The cold war demanded an internationalism that clari‹ed the differences between East and West. Immigration policy had to encourage integration within the West and to weaken the East. Whereas isolationists drew narrow boundaries and worried about subversion, internationalists drew wide boundaries and worried about pushing back the threat. Isolationists relied on forti‹cation; internationalists depended upon leadership and tipping dominoes in their direction. Isolationists guarded against an internal threat by purging the country and then quarantining it. Internationalists defended against an external threat by changing that outside world. Leadership became of value in itself. It became important that the United States simply reign. Immigration policy became to some a symbol of general leadership, a signal that the United States would enact laws consistent with its pronouncements and would act on principle, that petty calculations of minor interests were beneath it. Internationalists understood the country to be establishing an age of American leadership de‹ned by norms governing exchange and cooperation on various issues.27 The United States wished “to do justice in terms of an open world extending not only to goods, but to people. That, I feel, is the ultimate objective of freedom and the ultimate objective of the kind of world in which we in the United States wish to live and wish everybody else to live.”28 For example,
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
151
“we have opened up a very important phase in which we have recognized that . . . there can be no free-trade doctrine worldwide unless there is free migration and free emigration of people. Without the free movement of people there cannot be a free movement of goods.”29 Immigration was one such issue, but was also an arena in which other issues intersected. “We can no longer avoid, as we did in that decade [1930s], the responsibilities that have been placed upon us as a leader of free nations. We must take care that our immigration policy, like every other aspect of our behavior toward foreign persons and states, re›ects the genuine and durable principles of our democracy.”30 Like isolationists, internationalists understood immigration policy as an important symbolic and practical statement about the country’s relationship to the rest of the world. American values were general, global principles for world emulation, not practical matters involving neatly de‹nable short-term interests. Constant, nagging awareness that military apocalypse might be imminent added to the burdens of leadership and to the stridency with which internationalists argued for gestures of goodwill. “In this challenging world, our country cannot stand still. It cannot isolate itself from the demands of our times that would destroy the fearful. . . . Mere material wealth is not total security in an atomic age. It takes moral courage to accept leadership and to make high decisions in keeping with the character of the growing, generous America that is the parent of us all.”31 The country could not shirk its responsibility. “At no time in the history of our Nation has there been a more desperate need, for the sake of preservation of civilization, to resolve misunderstandings, fears, and distrust among the peoples of the world. We are gripped by awareness that it is these tensions which have spurred nations in the race for military supremacy in atomic warfare.”32 Legislators saw U.S. immigration regulation as a key to the Western unity so crucial to defend the free world. For this reason, pronouncements of leadership during debates about immigration policy reform were far-reaching, oratorical, and vague, much more general than might be expected on a potentially narrow and technical topic of low politics: “For the sake of America’s greatness, its international prestige, and its position of moral leadership among the nations of the world, I urge this Congress to take swift action to undo the wrongs of the McCarran-Walter Act.”33 America had come of age. “The abolition of the national origins system would signify to all our maturity and the casting off of unreasoning fear.”34 Through reform, “we would once more prove that United States leadership of the free world in accordance with our policy declarations is not merely a ‹gure of speech but both effective and real.”35 Leadership was its fate. “We have been drawn inextricably into the affairs of the world, and on the security of America rests much of
152
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
the security of the world.”36 The United States, through this step, took a decisive step toward asserting, or accepting, hegemony. Forty years ago, the national origins quotas was [sic] ‹rst enacted into law. It was a time of fright when Americans, having recently emerged from World War I, seemed uncertain of themselves. Their reaction was to isolate themselves from the world, close their gates to new blood and new ideas, withdraw to the humdrum and the conventional. The repeal of the national origins quotas is a reaf‹rmation of our sturdy faith in human equality, of our enthusiasm for setting democratic standards for the rest of the world, of our willingness to lead a global community of peoples toward universal recognition of human dignity.37 This belief also explains why representatives could care about how their policies compared to others’. “I believe that we mark ourselves as a nation which has not yet fully grasped the signi‹cance of our role in the world when we allow other small countries—for example, like Venezuela—to show a record very much better than our own in respect to the resettlement of refugees and escapees.”38 Reputation was power; image was everything. Legislators hoped for imitation. “What we are trying to do is not only to grant material help to these [displaced] people, but to create a psychological atmosphere which is absolutely necessary to demonstrate the duty of leadership that belongs to America in guiding the way, so that other countries will follow our example, and actually do something about overpopulation [which led to communism] in a very substantial manner.”39 If the United States successfully outlined an action plan and a rationale to justify it, other countries could shoulder some of the burden. “As leader of the free world and the nation most blessed with the resources for a solution of the escapee problem, can we create an impression of unwillingness to bear our fair share?”40 (One act to admit refugees was in fact known as the Fair Share Law.) The United States had to articulate its conception of world order carefully, for much was at stake. “I am deeply convinced that we are faced not only with the crisis of defense, in connection with which we must catch up in missiles and rocketry—and unquestionably we will— but that we are also faced with the crisis of our relations with the world. These relations not only go to weaponry, but also go to immigration. This depends very largely upon the direction the free world will take due to the leadership implications of the immigration policy of the United States.”41 The country sought to articulate norms and thereby establish patterns. Such patterns would govern the West’s policies in the cold war. Korea had taught the United States that the war was real. It developed into a war
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
153
the United States could come to understand. Containing, and then rolling back, communism’s spread would reduce the military threat that the United States faced. Crucial to containment were secure alliances. Security depended on loyalty, loyalty depended on credibility, and credibility depended on consistency. How immigration changes affected allies’ perception of American commitment to the liberal, anticommunist principles on which alliances were (presumably) based would determine how ‹rmly they would be willing to stand with the North American alliance in the event of war. Isolationist and internationalist legislators believed that equalizing quotas sent a strong signal to allies about American intent. They disagreed about what that signal was. One dif‹culty they faced was uncertainty about exactly who those allies were. World War II had turned into the cold war so quickly that policies to take care of recent allies, current allies, and future allies piled on top of each other. Were ceilings to be equalized, World War II allies hurt would be England and Ireland. Dean Rusk wanted to save high quotas for these countries because “at a time when our national security rests in large part on a continual strengthening of our ties with these countries, it would be anomalous indeed to restrict opportunities for their nationals here.”42 Allies in the cold war were at least as important. “It is part and parcel of our foreign policy to make friends, particularly those of the NATO countries, where many of the refugees reside. . . . We have assumed world leadership and we must exercise world leadership.”43 But whereas World War II involved speci‹c allies in a de‹ned theater, the cold war involved all countries in a ›uid arena of battle. Could the United States give high quotas to all allies and potential allies in the cold war? Complicating this was the Quota Acts’ legacy of excluding southern Europeans. The very people about whose salvation presidents had declared foreign policy doctrines were denied immigration on ethnic grounds. “Only the communists pro‹t from the free world’s neglect of Italy, which is the source of Western civilization, culture, and religion.”44 The Truman and Eisenhower administrations were appalled; the Kennedy and Johnson administrations were outraged. “It is an affront not only to the extremely important emerging nations of Africa and Asia, but also to some of our closest allies, such as Greece and Italy.”45 Equalization would “contribute effectively to the strengthening of our allies in the Paci‹c and the development of our neighbors in South America.”46 Equalizing countries’ allotments within a de‹ned limit simultaneously solved the symbolic and practical problems involved in distributing numbers. Money as well as reputation was involved. Just as prisoners cost more per day in prison than they subsist on outside of it, refugees in Europe cost more to support than did displaced persons transferred to the United
154
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
States. “It has been estimated that we could save $2 1/2 billion in foreign aid by allowing 240,000 special quota immigrants [from Europe] to enter the United States over the next 3 years.”47 Equalization would save money by convincing wavering populations that the United States was a credible ally. “We have poured out billions of dollars to shore up the economies of our allies. Yet I can only wonder whether much of this material aid may come to naught if we cannot, by this relatively small token, demonstrate that we practice what we preach by extending help to those who have bravely fought and who have somehow managed to escape totalitarian tyranny.”48 Policies in different spheres cost different amounts, but all had similar effects. “There is no yardstick with which to measure the impact of our immigration policy upon our foreign relations and the reputation abroad. But it would not seem outlandish to suggest that in the long run this impact may well equal that of our economic aid programs.”49 An effective immigration policy could minimize problems in other areas. Isolationists meanwhile rejected arguments about allies in or out of the cold war and did not contribute to a discussion in which each side accepted that others’ perceptions mattered. Isolationist Pat McCarran, in a rare comment, asked why if the “free world” included Europe, Europeans had to come to America to be free.50 By the mid-1950s, the cold war had become such an accepted standard for measuring policy that those opposed to admitting refugees sometimes also cited practical consequences related to global U.S.-Soviet rivalry. Those advocating restriction had earlier asserted that other countries should fend for themselves and not expect American handouts. By 1953, however, restrictionists asked who, if the United States admitted refugees, “will be left in the foreign countries to ‹ght communism? There will be none but weaklings, and soon the countries who will send us the immigrants will have to surrender to Communist forces.”51 Those who opposed refugee admissions also linked admissions and leadership, though they thought that leadership was not crucial. “The United States is not the only nation with a critical stake in problems of world security.”52 As the cold war became entrenched, legislators increasingly identi‹ed American interests with American hegemony. Internationalist language and terms came to dominate, and the debate slowly became an intra-internationalist debate. Cold war propaganda replaced World War II aircraft carriers as the decisive destructive weapon. Just as the Japanese during World War II broadcast to the Indians, Burmese, and Chinese news of America’s racial exclusion policies, so did communists after the war advertise the same thing. “There are many who feel that the McCarran-Walter Act has gratuitously placed a powerful propaganda weapon in the hands of the Rus-
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
155
sians, and the Russians are making the most of it.”53 This could be turned around. Our country has arrived at a turning point in history—at a great moment when, through psychological warfare, we can press our advantage. One of the ‹nest means to do so is to send word behind the Iron Curtain that our doors are not closed to the refugees and escapees, but rather that we are willing to welcome reasonable numbers of those who we are sure are genuine partisans of the cause of freedom.54 This [McCarran-Walter] law is one of the greatest talking points against America which the Communist International has. We are held up to ridicule because of this law—a powerful country like ours—sound, prosperous, and stable— . . . We have lost more prestige abroad than we can compensate for with the Voice of America. This law, which the Daily Worker criticizes for its own purposes here, is priceless grist for the Communist propaganda mill abroad.55 I am deeply convinced that, in a package, they [immigration reforms] are as essential as is our massive effort to catch up in terms of the weapons race. If we do not expect—and certainly we do not—to resolve the con›ict in the world by world war III, then our other means—by economic and technical assistance; by recognition of human dignity, through enforcement of civil rights; and by immigration legislation which is just and fair, and takes account of what is taking place in the world, and takes account not only of our own strengths, but also of the weaknesses of our enemies, in terms of the things in which we believe and which we hold the most dear—that is the package—constituting, as I see it, the way by which we hope to avoid world war III.56 The United States has failed to take the initiative in the battle for the minds of men. Economic assistance is not alone the answer to the dilemma of our foreign policy. Men do not live by bread alone.57 Refugees, meanwhile, provided the best information that the allies could obtain on Soviet plans and operations.58 “We can advance the cause of world peace if we encourage the internal disintegration of the Red empire. One method to accomplish this is to aid Communist government of‹cials to abandon their positions of leadership, defect to the west, and provide us
156
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
with valuable information.”59 What the USSR lost, the United States gained. Of course, propaganda worked both ways. Restrictionist declarations that immigrants were nothing more than slackers, spies, and criminals were used by the Soviets to their advantage: only criminals and other degenerates would want to leave the Soviet Union for the United States.60 Refugees to the United States could, in turn, redefect.61 And “Woe betide us if we ever go down the road in an effort to wipe out all the things that our enemies might use in their propaganda programs against us, for this would result eventually in the elimination of the free enterprise system.”62 The country’s anticommunist fervor could be manipulated to the Soviets’ advantage. According to internationalists, immigration restrictions were obviously hypocritical as well as counterproductive because they undergirded a Paper, or Red Tape, Curtain around the United States keeping people out, just as East Bloc countries’ Iron Curtain kept them in. “Thousands of these refugees have escaped from Communist-dominated areas behind the Iron Curtain only to be confronted by another kind of unfriendly barrier—rigid immigration laws which have prevented many of these freedom ‹ghters and freedom lovers from earning a living and raising their families in countries dedicated to democratic ideals and institutions.”63 Claiborne Pell called immigration barriers a “paper wall”;64 many representatives drew general conclusions similar to those that Fernand St. Germain outlined, that U.S. goals should be “the re-establishment of refugees who cannot return to their native countries for religious, racial, political, or other reasons [which] is closely connected with our objectives to continue the provision for asylum and assistance to the oppressed, to extend hope in the process of freedom to the victims of communism, and to exemplify the differences which exist between free and captive societies by our sacri‹ces and actions in behalf of the less fortunate members of humanity.”65 American policy should contrast, not imitate, Soviet policy. Since the cold war between U.S. and Soviet allies was zero-sum, what helped the United States would harm the Soviets. This help could also be an absolute gain. Besides propaganda effects, economic bene‹ts were an obvious example. “Indeed,” argued Jacob Javits, “we should adopt a policy that will attract to the free world as many as possible who are gifted and effective, who can make a major contribution to our society, and deprive the Communists of this bene‹t.”66 By legalizing such admissions, the country would “help ourselves abroad by raising our prestige, and can help ourselves at home by enriching our national blood with new and worthy citizens.”67 By equalizing quotas, “we would recognize the individual
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
157
worth of each immigrant and his potential contribution to the development and growth of our national economy.”68 To others, military bene‹ts were more striking. “The people of the world are not blind to this sort of hypocrisy. We sometimes wonder why we do not enjoy everyone’s unbridled friendship. We ask why our embassies are picketed by those we believe we have helped.”69 Earlier, Pat Hillings had pointed out that “this is part of the new policy which will give the Russians such a bad time in their own back yard behind the Iron Curtain that they will not have a chance to start a third world war.”70 If it did the opposite of what the USSR did, the United States could not lose. In addition to stressing ways to win the zero-sum propaganda game between East and West, internationalists focused on ways to promote gains all around among the allies. Cooperation within the West was, in their view, positive-sum. This conviction underlaid proposals for cooperation in NATO as well as GATT, OECD, and regional international governmental organizations. One example of the win-win enthusiasm that permeated internationalist proposals about immigrants dealt with population size. While large populations in Europe were dangerous to Europe, a large population in the United States was bene‹cial, increasing American power. European overpopulation led to communist discontent. “Communism and totalitarianism thrive on unemployment, lack of housing, lack of food, and discontent.”71 This was true of Europe. “In many of these southern countries in Europe, for instance Italy and Greece, there is a national problem with communism because of the crowded conditions.”72 Once securely in the United States, however, immigrants lent their strength. “We have become a great nation. We have the greatest gross national product of any nation that ever existed. Our gross national product is approaching almost $700 billion. One of the reasons therefor, I think, is that we have siphoned off the best of the brain and brawn of nations all over the world, of all races and climes and origins.”73 The United States gained in absolute as well as relative terms. Central to the internationalists’ worldview was the conviction that international and domestic policies should at a minimum be consistent, and preferably be mutually reinforcing. This mattered at both the symbolic and practical levels. Domestic and foreign policy had to match if the country was to avoid the charge of hypocrisy. Domestic norms and behavior revealed to foreigners the country’s true beliefs; foreign policies told Americans how the government really thought of their concerns. In addition, domestic policy could support foreign policy, and vice versa, creating a synergy allowing American hegemony to burst forth. Domestic economic and trade policies should mesh, territorial defense and extended
158
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
deterrence should be mutually supporting, civil rights should be consistent with human rights policies, and policies toward citizens and toward foreigners should be calculated according to the same principles. Party platforms illustrate the way that public of‹cials on both the left and the right saw domestic and foreign policies integrating. As early as 1956, both major American parties saw immigration policies as linking domestic and foreign policies. Both intended that the revisions they advocated would streamline the link between the domestic and the foreign sphere. For example, in 1956: The Republican Party supports an immigration policy which is in keeping with the traditions of America in providing a haven for oppressed peoples, and which is based on equality of treatment, freedom from implications of discrimination between racial, nationality, and religious groups, and ›exible enough to conform to changing needs and conditions. We believe that such a policy serves our self-interest, re›ects our responsibility for world leadership, and develops maximum cooperation with other nations in resolving problems in this area.74 While: The Democratic Party favors prompt revision of the immigration and nationality laws to eliminate unfair procedures under which this country depends on quotas based on accident of national origin. Proper safeguards against subversive elements should be provided. We favor the elimination of the provision of laws that charge all persons admitted to our shores against quotas for future years. We also favor more liberal admission of relatives to eliminate the unnecessary tragedy of broken families.75 By 1960, both parties again pushed for reform. The Republicans argued that “immigration has been reduced to a point where it does not provide the stimulus to growth that it should, nor are we ful‹lling our obligations as a haven for the oppressed. . . . The guidelines of our immigration policy be based upon judgement of the individual merit of each applicant for admission and citizenship.76 The Democrats echoed the substance of this position. Besides blaming the national origins system on the Republicans, the Democratic party platform argued that “the national-origins quota system of limiting immigration contradicts the founding principles of this Nation. It is inconsistent with our belief in the rights of man. . . . The revision of immigration and nationality laws we seek will implement our belief
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
159
that enlightened immigration, naturalization, and refugee policies and humane administration of them are important aspects of our foreign policy.”77 Both parties intended immigration policy to provide a better link between the country’s domestic and foreign policy goals. Immigration guidelines linked domestic and foreign policies philosophically, for they spelled out how the country thought of itself, its purpose, and its relation to the rest of the world. In the context of the cold war, it articulated the gist of the difference between the United States and the Soviet Union. “The fundamental difference between us and the Communists is that we want an open world in which people can move from place to place, in order to give the greatest opportunities in life and in order to have the liberty of the world. The Communists want a society in which people cannot move. The Communists want a world which is restricted within compartments, controlled by the state. We want a world in which movement is easily possible.”78 Revising immigration policy to select on individual achievements rather than on group ascriptive traits would highlight that “the cornerstone of American political and social philosophy is built on the dignity of the individual, an individual to be evaluated as an individual.”79 Individuals, to internationalists, should be distinguished only horizontally, by location in sovereign space, not vertically according to an ethnic or even ideological hierarchy. Liberalism honors the individual, not the state, yet cold war ideology demanded that states secure their borders against individuals. “America’s struggle with totalitarianism is far more than a contest for dominance in world power politics. Above all, it is a struggle for the vindication of democracy’s belief in the individual worth of human beings as opposed to the totalitarian concept that individuals have no identity except as components in the political and economic structure of society.”80 Freedom of movement was a sine qua non of liberty. “There is probably no single matter of law or tradition that divides the free world from the Communist empire so dramatically as does the question of freedom of movement and migration. The Berlin Wall stands as a mute and monstrous testament to the power of the dictatorial state to curb the freedom of men to change their environment.”81 Liberalism demanded open borders; the cold war demanded realist politics, closed borders. What was a liberal country ‹ghting such a war to do? Treating all states equally, regardless of their varied population sizes, showed respect for sovereign equality and would ›atter newly independent states, encouraging them to ally with the United States. After numbers had been limited in this way, there was room for liberal principles. Individual equality could be respected within the con‹nes of sovereign equality. Altering immigration guidelines in a more cosmopolitan direction
160
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
would, hopefully, change American society for the better too. By integrating foreigners with Americans, Americans could be taught to take advantage of world opportunities. Unfortunately, argued internationalists, American provincialism retarded its advance. Such views, if thought, had not before been expressed in public debate. It is a popular but erroneous belief that reform of the immigration laws would throw open the United States to a ›ood of slave traders, hashish chewers, coolies, witch doctors, mountain bandits, and camel drivers. This xenophobic concept envisions the typical immigrant as an illiterate, cholera-ridden pagan, who would either usurp the job of an American workingman or go on the relief rolls; who would subsist on ‹sh heads and rice, father 13 children, and refuse to learn to speak English; who would lower property values wherever he lived; who would vote against school bond issues, hoard his money in tin cans and, who, in his idle hours, would run numbers, smoke opium, and revive the Tong wars.82 American society had to become more cosmopolitan because international society had become interdependent; American policy was to push that interdependence yet further. In the light of interdependence, American immigration policy looked shabby and outdated, an embarrassment. “Interdependence among nations has become an essential to amiable and progressive international relations and the fostering of a lasting peace. . . . Yet we have an immigration policy which is in part isolationist and wholly iniquitous, and one which lags behind the demands and ignores the phenomena of a world in motion.”83 Inconsistency meant inef‹ciency. Our immigration policy has lagged behind the promises of our tradition and the progress of the world. Trade crosses borders ever more freely; capital ›ows by the mere entering of ‹gures on ledgers; ideas spirit from one country to another as fast as the printing press and the airplane can carry them; news, protests, approvals, anger and gratitude travel with the speed of light. But people—the people who make the goods, create the capital, think and live the ideas—move almost as slowly as if the airplane or even the railroad had never been invented. . . . Olivetti typewriters and Fellini movies come here more smoothly and easily than the gifted people who make them.84 Interdependence allowed loftier sentiments. “Let us keep to the heights where we shall be unafraid to welcome the worthy in a world which con-
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
161
stantly grows smaller in size.”85 Interdependence also focused attention on individual rights and liberal norms, circumventing state boundaries. John Kennedy argued that “in an age of interdependence among nations, such a [national origins] system is an anachronism, for it discriminates among applicants for admission into the United States on the basis of accident of birth.”86 A liberal immigration policy had a central place in a world order dedicated to transnational cooperation. “The goal of world peace and brotherhood in this or any other generation can be furthered only in a climate of increasing understanding and good will among nations; important in the area of international relations are immigration policies and procedures. Inevitably a nation’s immigration laws re›ect its basic attitude toward nations and races.”87 Liberal neutrality suggested borders open at least to liberal people. Like isolationists, internationalists sought to create a particular version of the United States. The country they desired was the country they imagined could exist if the country chose to accept its responsibilities and to live up to its potential. It was a country that led the world out of the chaos abroad. Ignorance was dangerous. The domestic and foreign spheres should be integrated, because principle did not respect borders; furthermore, since other countries knew this, consistency would demonstrate American credibility. Complementing internationalism was a policy allowing domestic society to expand as it would according to its own impulses. If the country could eliminate bad foreign in›uences, it could open the borders con‹dent that it would not be harmed. Hegemony, not isolation, protected it from communism. A series of events provoked debate over immigration policy.
Reason: Duty to and Interest in Hungarian Refugees
In 1953, Peter Rodino pointed out that dramatic airplane escapes from the East Bloc were ‹ne in principle, but mortgaged quotas meant that only few could escape with U.S. approval unless the country wanted publicity about the fact that it would not offer escapees entry.88 Robert Hendrickson later argued that “the snarling little men of the Kremlin and the shivering puppets of their satellite empire are also looking on today. . . . For, in a very large measure, it [a bill to allow 209,000 refugees U.S. residence] represents a new blow at their recently demonstrated inability to keep their peoples in a slavish iron grasp growing rusty with the blood of their victims.”89 No serious action, however, was taken until early 1957. In late 1956, almost 200,000 Hungarians ›ed to the West after the Soviet military put an end to an anticommunist uprising in Hungary. Most
162
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
sought temporary or permanent residence in the United States. This group of refugees from the cold war faced an American refugee policy developed to protect the country from those uprooted during World War II. Displaced persons were to be retained in their homelands, if possible, to help rebuild them. If this was not possible, they were allowed to emigrate to one of several Western countries. Those who entered the United States were charged against their country’s quota, based on the national origins of the U.S. population; if refugees exceeded spaces, immigrants mortgaged future quotas for their countries. In 1952, the Hungarian quota was 865 annually (0.56 percent of the total), already mortgaged until 1985.90 Internationalists argued that the country simply had to take in the Hungarians if it wanted to retain credibility in the ‹ght against the Soviets. Richard Nixon reported to President Eisenhower: The Communist leaders thought they were building a new order in Hungary. Instead, they erected a monument which will stand forever in history as proof of the ultimate failure of international communism. Those people, both inside and outside of Hungary, who had the courage to expose by their actions this evil ideology for what it is, deserve all the gratitude and support which we in the free world are so willingly giving today.91 For the ‹rst time, immigration policy allowed that some people, by virtue of their actions, had earned entry to the United States and that the United States’ position created a responsibility for its consequences. Recognizing this, internationalists argued, was not just morally appropriate but practically necessary to U.S. strength because it bolstered American credibility. Eisenhower noted that “our position of world leadership demands that, in partnership with the other nations of the free world, we be in a position to grant that asylum”;92 and John Dingell pointed out that “the ‹rst question we must face up to is whether, as a matter of policy, we want people in Eastern Europe to escape. If we do, then logically we have to shape our immigration policy to accept the consequences of this decision. . . . The problem this has created for us is affected by the fact that wealth has responsibilities. . . . they want to know what standards we will apply in admitting them.”93 (The same could have been true of Cuban refugees, but accepting Cubans was easy because they ›ed from the Western Hemisphere, which faced no numerical ceiling. Cuban refugees could be excluded only if they were personally un‹t, e.g., were lunatics, prostitutes, or polygamists.) “If these escapees, beginning to realize the futility of spending more years in a camp, returned by the thousands as they are sure to do, then the United States from a propaganda
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
163
standpoint, will most certainly be discredited.”94 Immigration policy was one of many policies that together waged the cold war. Furthermore, since a global leader’s domestic and foreign policies merged into each other, domestic policy could send signals abroad and foreign policies could affect domestic loyalties. “We cannot afford to have a person risk ›ight from behind the Iron Curtain or other dictatorial government, only to ‹nd that the Free World will provide no haven for him. Such a situation would end in complete disillusionment with democracy, and would threaten the preservation of our democratic principles.”95 Overcrowding threatened the same result indirectly, although ironically the overcrowding was due in part to American encouragement of cold war refugees. “Population pressure” led to unrest, social explosion, and communism. “Our allies in Western Europe are overcrowded and they are burdened with refugees. Certainly, if we know anything about our foreign policy, we know that we are encouraging the people to ›ee the Iron Curtain in an attempt to break down the hold of the communists on the satellite countries.”96 The United States had already institutionalized an alliance with these countries. “Large numbers of nonproductive people undermine the basic security objectives of the North Atlantic community, objectives which are an essential part of the foreign policy of the United States. They reduce the capacity of the free world to establish an effective posture of defense against the threat of communist aggression.”97 German ethnics expelled from Eastern Europe threatened to destabilize Germany and hence NATO.98 Liberty abroad meant liberty at home, and vice versa. “The national origins formula of the 1924 law remained an unsurmountable obstacle to what the people of the United States wanted to do; namely, to accept the responsibility which the U.S. position of leadership in the world had imposed.”99 McCarran-Walter denied liberty to refugees. Therefore, McCarran-Walter was not the immigration policy of a liberal hegemon. What was good for the country internationally was good for it domestically. Eisenhower was only one of many who claimed no con›ict, in this area, between “our responsibility of world leadership and . . . our own self-interest.”100 For example, “it is sound policy to consider the needs of our own country ‹rst, and then to legislate in accordance with those needs. Those needs, of course, include the cooperation with free nations of the world, in order to help preserve our liberties.”101 International action was a no-lose proposition. A refugee admission bill, for example, “would contribute immeasurably to the economic and political stability of our allies. It would enhance our prestige throughout the world. It would encourage other nations to expand their resettlement programs. And it should strengthen our economy through the addition of productive
164
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
and much-needed agricultural and other workers.”102 Every transaction among allies was, in this view, positive-sum.
Reason: Decolonization and Credibility
People in former colonies were also engaged in translating ideas about equality and self-determination into action. The postwar wave of independence began in India and Pakistan in 1947 and reached its zenith from 1957 to 1963 when thirty-two countries achieved independence. During the period from 1945 to 1960, relations between the United States and its allies in the cold war although imperfect had reached a stage of some familiarity and predictability. How the newly independent countries would affect the cold war, internationalists believed, depended a great deal on how the NATO countries treated them. “Many countries of Asia and the Paci‹c have traditionally sought more than a token of immigration to the United States. These are the countries that will play a large and vital role in determining the future course of world events.”103 Decolonization affected isolationists’ arguments only to the extent that one isolationist asserted that preventing emigration was in the newly independent countries’ best interests: “We have sent Peace Corps personnel to the four corners of the world to teach new skills and modern scienti‹c techniques in the underdeveloped nations which are literally starving for trained workers. Are we now to establish a program which will literally skim the cream off the very countries that desperately need new skills to emerge from the dark ages?”104 But since the new countries were not concerned about a brain drain, neither were the internationalists concerned. The tone that the United States set, they believed, would at least affect and perhaps determine the cold war’s outcome. During these times, when we are striving to win over and hold in our camp the peoples of the uncommitted and underdeveloped areas of the world, this problem assumes larger proportions. For these are the very people we are slapping in the face with our national origins selections. It is the people of the young burgeoning nations, the newly emancipated countries of Asia who bear the brunt of the most extreme discrimination in our present law—the Asia–Paci‹c Triangle restrictions.105 The Third World would turn away from the United States. “Everyone recognizes that the challenges of emerging nations are tremendous. Let us not be further hampered in our efforts to join with them in free world endeav-
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
165
ors by the embarrassment of taking no action to move forcibly against the kind of national policy discrimination we know today under our immigration quota system.”106 Individuals, as well as governments, could become enemies. “It must be remembered that our immigration policies often make up the ‹rst and only personal contact that people of other countries have with the United States.”107 Decolonization provided an opportunity, and a risk. Doing other good works was a waste of time and money since immigration policy belied American motives. “We spend billions of dollars in foreign aid so that we can convince other nations that our democratic way of life is the best and then we say to the people of these countries when they wish to come into the United States, ‘sorry, you were born in the wrong country.’”108 Whereas military inferiority damaged the U.S. reputation, immigration policy directly affronted the newly independent. “If sputnik has caused us to lose face and threatens to drive noncommitted nations into the eastern camp, then how many years have we had of losing face among the noncommitted nations when America’s basic immigration law says that one group of people is more desirable than another?”109 McCarran-Walter “is very bad foreign policy in a day when the attitudes and actions of peoples other than northern and western Europeans are increasingly important to our future.”110 Retaliation was always possible. “If we are willing to continue laws discriminating against individuals because of race or national origin, what trust can we in turn expect from the emerging nations of Asia and Africa?”111 Retaliation would cause American losses to escalate. “Modernization of our immigration system will demonstrate to other nations, especially to the new and underdeveloped countries with whom we wish to maintain good relationships, our sincerity and responsibility. Failure to act would in the long run result in a weakening of our foreign relations and a decline in our domestic, economic, and social wellbeing.”112 If hegemony failed, the world would plunge again into a beggar-thy-neighbor nightmare. Finally, such policies would redound to the detriment of the United States population. “Such provisions are not only a diplomatic handicap in our relations with such pro-Western Asian nations as Japan, the Philippines, Thailand, and Malaysia, but they are also provisions which are morally indefensible to a nation committed to the proposition that all men are created equal.”113 As domestic ideals affected foreign perceptions, foreign policy standards affected the society that fashioned them. To a hegemon, domestic policy and foreign policy each grew from a continuum with a wide swath of overlap. Hegemony depended upon global reach, and decolonization extended sovereignty throughout the globe. Decolonization created a
166
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
large untested population that could vote American power up or down. “The manner in which we conduct ourselves, the manner in which we treat our friends in Asia, will determine to a great extent what our position will be as world leader.”114 Sovereign equality, like equality among citizens, had to be recognized in principle before substantive cooperation could proceed. “This bill will also demonstrate to the nations of the world that we recognize each nation as sovereign, with its citizens entitled to equal standing before our laws. I believe this will greatly bene‹t our relations with our friends and allies, particularly those in the Orient.”115 Equalizing countries’ legal treatment would create bankable goodwill.
Reason: Proxy War and Credibility
South Vietnam demonstrated the costs associated with a lack of goodwill. No wonder, argued internationalists, that the Vietnamese doubted American commitment when Americans refused to accept Vietnamese as fellow citizens on racial grounds. In Vietnam, we are spending $1.5 million a day and have suffered more than 2,000 casualties in support of the Saigon Government. The annual quota for South Vietnamese is 100. The population of South Vietnam is approximately 15 million. Evidently we are willing to commit the full strength of this Nation’s resources to the defense of liberty in Vietnam. At the same time, our immigration law makes it abundantly clear that while we may risk war for the right of the Vietnamese people to live freely and independently, we do not want them to live with us.116 War in Vietnam showed clearly that American hegemony demanded consistency of principle. Inconsistency would, sooner or later—though de‹nitely at the most inopportune and costliest time—›y in the face of national policies that depended for their success on cooperation among allies the world over. We have committed our Nation to the preservation of freedom for all peoples of the world; not only those of Northern Europe. It seems quite inconsistent that we should be asking people throughout the world to join us—to ‹ght and die for the cause of freedom and at the same time deny them an equal opportunity to become American citizens. The current policy also presents the ironic situation in which we are willing to send our American youth to aid these people in their
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
167
struggle against Communist aggression while at the same time, we are indicating that they are not good enough to be Americans.117 War did not fundamentally alter arguments people offered about international obligations and immigrants. Rather, internationalists took Vietnam as an example verifying their predictions about the likelihood of future military problems centering on regions that immigration policy slighted.118 Refugees who ›ed war, and those who stayed to ‹ght a war, as well as those to whom war might someday come—all would help the United States ‹ght the cold war if the United States formalized its belief in their equality by establishing an immigration policy honoring them. External events provided evidence to isolationists that reinforced their beliefs. Without a ban on immigration, other countries’ ‹ghts (Hungary, Vietnam) or decisions (decolonization) would generate exodus into the United States. The country would be accepting a passive role in determining its population. Since its population determined its destiny, to adopt a passive stance was to forgo its control over its own fate. Universalists, faced with the cold war, became internationalists: they worried about individuals in the context of states. They viewed these developments as evidence that American isolation gave the Soviet Union a propaganda advantage. The cold war internationalized the country’s defense, so it internationalized the basis for allocating immigration quotas. External developments changed the nature of the antirestrictionist argument. Domestic events had a reinforcing effect.
Reason: Unemployment
From 1952 through 1965, unemployment averaged 5.3 percent, up from 4.3 percent in the six years immediately following the war.119 Isolationists sometimes focused on potential job loss, raising questions of equity between citizens and aliens. Economic uncertainty could be suf‹cient reason to halt immigration. “It is exceedingly unwise to relax our immigration laws and increase the immigrants coming to the United States to any extent at a time when 7 million Americans are on public welfare, 3.8 million Americans are seeking in vain for jobs in which to earn daily bread for themselves and their families.”120 Americans owed the social surplus to other Americans. “‘Give me your jobless, your poor, your untrained masses yearning to draw unemployment checks. Send them to me, and I will register them to vote.’”121 Equity between the armed forces and civilians was also at stake. “Has anyone thought of the effect this additional 200,000 aliens will have on unemployment in our country, especially on
168
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
our soldiers returning from Korea?”122 Increasing unemployment would, additionally, weaken the country, making it more susceptible to communist takeover. “I do not believe that America can be made more strong or resolute in its determination to stop Communist imperialism by weakening our security structure, nor by disrupting the domestic economy by preempting jobs otherwise available to unemployed Americans.”123 In this period with a basically unchanged unemployment level, increasing exports, and an expanding consumer market, the numbers did not support claims that immigrants demonstrably harmed the economy. For this reason, it was rarely raised. Rather, unemployment’s importance was largely symbolic, raising questions of fairness and just expectations. For this reason, when it was discussed, it was raised by isolationists.
Reason: Racial Equity and the Civil Rights Movement
If legislators thinking about immigration policy were primarily responsive to domestic change, nothing could have shaken them up more during this period than the civil rights movement. In 1955, Martin Luther King led the Montgomery boycott; in 1957, President Eisenhower sent federal troops to Little Rock to defend desegregation. Internationalists drawing lessons for immigration policy from civil rights events claimed that morality demanded and American leadership required consistent treatment of individuals.124 The only isolationists to take civil rights developments into account when framing their arguments stated that “They [immigrants] will compete with the very class of American citizens our Federal Government is seeking to aid through its war on poverty. Unemployment among the Negro population of this country will not be eased regardless of the efforts of the administration to give them preferential treatment.”125 The other asked, similarly, whether immigrants did not worsen black opportunities. “Will the addition of still more minority groups from all parts of the world lessen or contribute to the increasing racial tensions and violence we are currently witnessing on the streets of our major cities?”126 Aiding immigrants raised the question of whether borders ought to extend responsibilities as well as to de‹ne the limits of obligation. Internationalists, however, felt that what was right for actual U.S. citizens was right for potential U.S. citizens. As the interface between the domestic and the international sphere, immigration policy could become the arena for demonstrating that one’s statements of principle were true and credible, statements made to American citizens as well as to friends and enemies abroad. “We must never forget that the world watches closely to see what this country does with regard to helping immigrants, just as it
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
169
follows closely what we do in the ‹eld of civil rights. In our view, reform of the immigration laws is an integral part of our responsibility as leader of the free world.”127 The civil rights movement focused legislators’ attention on national origins quotas’ implicit designation of an ethnic hierarchy in the United States. Initially, some viewed immigration primarily in terms of domestic politics, while others viewed it mainly as a component of the cold war. Eventually, most legislators saw it as both. By 1965, after the Voting Rights and Civil Rights Acts had passed, consensus could be parlayed, by analogizing, into a consensus on immigration reform. “It seems strange to me that at a time when the Congress is taking vigorous action to insure that no American will be denied their full privilege of citizenship because of race, we still maintain an immigration policy which relegates millions of other Americans to second-class citizenship because of national origin.”128 Legislators made an effort to identify immigration reform with Great Society legislation. “Just as we sought to eliminate discrimination in our land through the Civil Rights Act, today we seek by phasing out the national origins quotas to eliminate discrimination in immigration to this Nation composed of the descendants of immigrants”;129 International equality logically followed from domestic equality. “The requirements of a nation which is reaching for the Great Society compel us to change our immigration laws”;130 “This year, 1965, is a year of progress, a year when we and other men are beginning to move toward the realization of a society in which all men are truly free and equal.”131 Adjusting immigration policy would ease tension at the interface between domestic and international spheres. If civil rights and immigration policies were connected, and immigration and cold war foreign policies were connected, then immigration policies linked civil rights to the cold war. John Kennedy argued, “Whether we identify immigration policy with foreign policy or not, our friends do— including some of our own partners in NATO, against whom we discriminate. And our enemies so identify it also.”132 What the country did domestically was viewed by allies as important information concerning its credibility in other areas. “We are moving to right racial wrongs at home. It would be foolish as well as unjust not to do the same in our dealings with foreign peoples who seek admission. Our discriminatory immigration laws delight our enemies and dismay our friends abroad.”133 What the country did in foreign policy, domestic groups took as a sign of intent. In both cases, the “practice” to con‹rm the “preaching” was immigration reform. Legislators argued that immigration policy and civil rights are “very much the same kind of issue,”134 implicitly denying the relevance of a distinction between the domestic and the international sphere.
170
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Civil rights legislation was, in its own way, foreign policy, just as cold war policy was, in a way, domestic. Immigration policy stood right at the interface. “This country is now involved in a great struggle against the forces of discrimination and the apostles of bigotry. Our national energy and conscience are committed to that ‹ght and its quest for equality.”135 In fact, the Judiciary Committees handled both civil rights and immigration matters. The same legislators sat on the subcommittees dealing with these two issues and listened to testimony about both. Not surprisingly, they reached the same conclusions about each. “The United States again demonstrates to the world its ‹rm conviction that there shall be no discrimination or prejudice in this country, that persons shall be judged upon the basis of their individual merit, and that liberty, equality, and freedom can be enduring realities in this country.”136 Hiram Fong demonstrated how policy levels should be integrated. At home we are now attempting to revise our laws and practices to wipe out the last vestiges of racial discrimination against our own citizens. As we reappraise the relationship of citizen to citizen, is it not also good for us to reexamine this same relationship of man’s equality to man with other peoples of the world? For as we move to erase racial discrimination against our own citizens, we should also move to erase racial barriers against citizens of other lands in our immigration policies and laws, which are replete with racially discriminatory provisions. . . . At home, we have wiped out racial barriers in our armed forces, in interstate transportation, in our institutions of higher learning, and in many areas of our economy. We are making signi‹cant progress in desegregating our public schools, housing, business, and public accommodations, and protecting the voting rights of all citizens. It is imperative that we, as a Nation, recognize this great upheaval throughout the world for equal status.137 White Americans “must open our doors wide” to black Americans and to Africans and Asians, “to let democracy in.”138 Faith in the universality of equality required a universal extension of principle. “The essence of our democratic credo is the dignity of man. Our constant effort to implement fully this credo, and our vigilant protection of America’s heritage, require that our immigration policy be brought in line with the moral and ethical principles upon which our democracy is based.”139 Immigration policy could support or undermine civil rights. “We must remember that any
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
171
injustice in our immigration and naturalization law is a wedge which will weaken our political system and our long established, constitutionally guaranteed, doctrine that all men are created equal.”140 Policy had not only to be consistent, but to extend principle to its logical and practical limits. Comparing the in›uence that external and internal changes had on the pattern of arguments offered about immigration reform leads to one general conclusion about motives—or at least publicly acknowledged motives—for change. During this period, external events precipitated arguments for change. Domestic events were relevant when they provided additional evidence supporting reformers’ conclusions. The cold war’s emphasis on hearts and minds magni‹ed the importance of symbolic politics. America’s stance toward cold war refugees and newly independent peoples provided information that other countries could use to assess American reliability. Legislators in this debate played to an audience abroad, who wanted to know not how the United States treated its own citizens but how it would treat them. Domestic processes, on the other hand, did not impel discussion. Unemployment was not a real problem and was rarely raised; although unrest that led to the civil rights movement had begun a decade or two earlier, and had certainly been headline news, not until 1963 did legislators use the civil rights movement as evidence that their constituents’ values mattered one way or the other. Given representatives’ notorious weakness for pandering to their constituents, the centrality of domestic distributive concerns to this debate is therefore implausible. Providing additional evidence for externally locating the catalyst to change are representatives’ observations on this point. Francis Walter, cosponsor of McCarran-Walter, by 1961 observed, “It is not necessary, of course, to stress before this enlightened gathering that the economic, social, and political conditions of the world are not static. They change and therefore immigration laws and policies governing the admission of immigrants must change.”141 He said that “the time has come to analyze our immigration problems in depth. No such analytic study has been made since the economic, political, and social conditions of the entire world have undergone the most profound changes since the late 1940s.”142 These changes amounted to a revolution in America’s relationship with the rest of the world. “Much has changed during the past 40 years, at home and in the world around us, bearing upon a sound immigration policy which will serve the best interests of the United States and all our people.”143 Legislators considered McCarran-Walter almost immoral, but “even had this law been equitable and wise, it would be well to review whether changing requirements and times, and our changing role in the world community, have not made some of its provisions obsolete.”144 Too much had changed.
172
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Progressive as that 1952 law was, today it is very obsolete. More than 10 years have now passed since its enactment. Since then, our Nation and the world have witnessed revolutionary changes in almost every phase of life. Many areas emerged from colonial status to full nationhood. Many nations have challenged their form of government. There is greater clamor for freedom, liberty, and justice, and, worldwide, peoples are on the march seeking equality. Economic interdependence has shaken traditional economic, social, and political patterns.145 Revising foreign policies would ease America’s adjustment to its new role. “Just as world events of 25 years ago forced us to abandon splendid isolation the events of today must move us toward an immigration policy consistent with our philosophy as a free and democratic nation.”146 In 1952, many thought of the immigration problems and minor crises that the country faced as exceptional, as phenomena peculiar to the period immediately after the war. The majority not only voted for a policy loudly reiterating the 150,000 ceiling and national origins quotas, but voted for it by a margin large enough to overturn a presidential veto. For 1952 through 1965, however, many became convinced that the crises they faced were not aftershocks of World War II but early tremors of the cold war. The uprising in East Berlin, the Soviet invasion of Hungary, and the Berlin Wall crisis convinced Congress that Europe’s population remained far from settled; revolution in Cuba and decolonization convinced them that the world beyond Europe had to be taken on its own terms. By the early 1960s, so much ad hoc legislation had been passed that McCarran-Walter was having little practical effect on immigration ›ows, though still standing as a symbol of isolationist bigotry affecting the morale of allies in Vietnam and potential allies in Africa and Asia. Consensus about the necessity of institutional adaptation to the cold war developed slowly. John Kennedy introduced a bill to liberalize provisions regarding orphans and tuberculosis sufferers, stop mortgaging, and ease parole and asylum.147 In 1958, Congress voted to reinstate the mortgaged portions of country’s national quotas. As refugee crises multiplied, so did support for a more liberal refugee admissions policy. Problems in Berlin quickly followed invasion in Hungary and revolution in Cuba; the magnitude of the refugee ›ows that each generated was unprecedented, at least as a matter of which the United States might take control. Excluding refugees from enemy territory during a war, the cold war, was not at all the same as excluding persons displaced after a war. Jacob Javits observed that “in the last 24 hours, 1,741 East German refugees reached West Berlin. Since last Saturday noon alone over 5,000 have escaped to the free
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
173
world in this way. Only 2 weeks ago the rate was about 1,100 per day, and the previous estimate of 300,000 for 1961 which was considered high, may have to be revised upward.” He argued that this revealed many problems with life under communist rule and concluded that American “preparation must at least be equal to the con‹dence of the refugees. The archaic and discriminatory immigration laws fall far short of the mark in this respect.”148 Ad hoc legislation would never be enough. “A bill to provide suitably for refugees and escapees needs to recognize also that the problem is recurrent—we have already had two previous Refugee Relief Acts—that it erupts out of major foreign policy issues, and that we have a considerable amount of un‹nished business on hand right now.”149 The cold war was there to stay, so immigration policy should adjust. “In view of the unrest and turmoil in the world, and the brutal policies of the Soviets, it is almost inevitable that more and more men, women, and children are going to be driven from their homes.”150 Crises had become the normal way of life. “The fact of the refugee is an inescapable fact of contemporary history. Geographical partition produces refugees. Political division produces refugees. Supernationalist movements produce refugees.”151 The cold war, Congress realized, was indeed a war, not a battle. It would be around for decades to come. In the context of an ongoing war with the Soviet Union, internationalists argued that McCarran-Walter presented an immoral or simply poor image of the United States, which redounded to American disadvantage internationally. Others focused on its practical inadequacy in controlling immigration ›ows. Either way, Congress viewed its effects as perverse. The act sorted people into sets based not just on their own acts or beliefs but also on the institutional ideology of their home country: criminals subject to automatic exclusion included anticommunists convicted by a communist court.152 On the other hand, “France, the western nation with the heaviest proportion of Communists, enjoys a fairly liberal immigration quota under the McCarran-Walter Act.”153 Moreover, its racism was so extensive that it had dif‹culty specifying any unifying rationale for its varied exclusions. “The code of racial prejudice twists like a cowpath. To keep out Italians, Greeks, Turks, and Slavs, the McCarran-Walter Act relies on place of birth, not the ancestry of the applicant. To keep out Asians, the law ignores place of birth and relies on ancestry. For both groups, however, the law consistently ignores individual worth.”154 McCarran-Walter had allocated colonies a separate quota of 100, removing them from eligibility for admission under their parent country’s usually large ceiling. The effect was to exclude Negroes and Asians. McCarran-Walter was also a failure on its own terms, “as much a fail-
174
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
ure as a device as it is an embarrassment of a doctrine.”155 Actual immigration matched the American population’s national origins very loosely, as English and Germans did not care to emigrate.156 One could, further, measure its failure in the number of private bills (to allow an exception to the law) that legislators introduced annually. In the 79th Congress (1945–46), legislators introduced 14 bills; in the 80th (1947–48), 80; in the 81st (1949–50), 81; but in the 82nd (1951–52), 729.157 Besides private bills, Congress had enacted ad hoc legislation allowing for the relief of refugees and the entry of displaced persons, agricultural laborers, and Basque sheepherders.158 “The cumulative effect of this special legislation has so modi‹ed our immigration practice that the act of 1952 no longer represents our immigration quota policy. Of the 1 1/2 million quota immigrants authorized during the 1950s, only a million actually entered the United States. However, 1 1/2 million nonquota immigrants were admitted during the same period.”159 Streamlining legislation into a single, rationalized package would itself be of value, even without changing numbers or bases for exclusion.160 “I submit that when two-thirds of our immigrants come in outside the law, it is time to change the law.”161 McCarran-Walter’s insistence on channeling refugees through ‹xed country quotas, and on keeping those quotas at their 1924 levels, harmed executive branch efforts to ‹ght the cold war. The racially un‹t southern and eastern Europeans had become valuable prizes in the zero-sum ‹ght between the United States and the Soviet Union. Allowing escapees entry would give the United States material bene‹ts and relieve population pressures in NATO countries, but even altering the law to admit hypothetical refugees (since most could not escape) had great advantages in the war for hearts and minds. “Many of the people of East Germany, Poland, Hungary, Romania, Bulgaria, Czechoslovakia, and the Baltic States, have been forced to ›ee their homelands and break through the Iron Curtain because of the enslavement and terror visited on their homes by the Communists. Their case is an ever-increasing burden on our allies in the North Atlantic Treaty Organization and a burden on our own hearts.”162 President Eisenhower observed that “these refugees, escapees, and distressed peoples now constitute an economic and political threat of constantly growing magnitude. They look to traditional humanitarian American concern for the oppressed.”163 The executive branch took a stance against McCarranWalter on three grounds: it was inhumane, it denied the country needed workers, and it created a reputation unworthy of the country’s international position.164 McCarran-Walter was the policy of a post–World War I isolationist, not that of a post–World War II hegemon; it was not only irrelevant to the country’s goals but impeded its ability to reach them.
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
175
Reason: Credibility Means Consistency
Hegemony implied global reach; American hegemony implied equal treatment of countries and equality among individuals. Reformists pursued two principles simultaneously: globalization and equalization. To globalize was to modernize. This, for example, underlaid Humphrey’s proposal that the United States have a quota equal to 1/6 of 1 percent (the McCarran-Walter formula) of the country’s 1950 population, divided equally among countries.165 This would set the new ceiling at 251,000. Eisenhower later advocated modernizing by doubling the 154,000 quota, including refugees but removing the Asia-Paci‹c Triangle and racial provisions, and basing the ceiling on the 1960 census.166 Equality could extend to all sovereign states or could apply to all the world’s individuals. Table 5 outlines the relationship between American quotas for regions and those regions’ populations of individuals and states.167 Consensus grew that immigration guidelines should cover all countries and all peoples equally. Since states’ populations differed greatly in size, Philip Hart proposed setting a cap of 250,000, of which 50,000 would be refugees (previously covered by ad hoc legislation), 120,000 divided among states according to the proportion of the last decade’s immigration they had supplied, and 80,000 to be allocated among states according to the proportion of the world’s population they contained.168 Asians and southern Europeans bene‹ted from this move toward equality, since their allotments had been negligible or low. Their welfare was the yardstick that internationalist reformers used to gauge suf‹ciency. Yet some areas would lose out. England and Ireland would have to see their quotas dropped, and the Western Hemisphere had never faced numerical restrictions. Legislators found themselves in a dilemma: the logic of their positions required consistency, yet few isolationists or restrictionists actually wanted a policy that treated all countries alike. The left/right split, or Democrat/Republican split, did not coincide with the isolationist/internationalist split. Table 6 shows how these categories divided opinion. Some restrictionists did want all areas closed for immigration; others wanted to retain preferences for England and Ireland (for reasons of race or alliance) and the Western Hemisphere (for reasons of cheap labor).169 Some internationalists wanted to retain the same preferences, arguing that these extra allotments were goals toward which further reforms could strive, much as GATT supporters justi‹ed EC preferences—“No one regards, for example, as discriminatory the special relationship existing between member countries of the Common Market which has manifested itself in many ways, including the free movement of natives among the Common Market member countries”170—while others
176
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
argued that policy had to be consistent to be credible. Paul Findley argued that the Congress should equalize the hemispheres not by extending limits to the West but by removing them from the East.171 Cutting across the isolationist/internationalist divide was a schism dividing those advocating preferences from those demanding consistency. Table 6 outlines the differences between the left and right, and between the isolationists and internationalists. Internationalists who wanted to retain preferences implied that the larger the quota, the stronger the ally. “The absence of quotas within the Western Hemisphere is an invaluable adjunct to the good-neighbor policy.”172 The cold war again provided evi-
TABLE 5.
Regional Distribution of Quotas 1930 1950
1964
1970
1980
13 38 1.7
13 36 26b
15 40 40c
Africa, the Middle East, and the Philippines Percent of world’s populationa Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of U.S. ceiling allotted
11 13 0.7
12 15 1.1
Asia: Barred Zone Area Percent of world’s population Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of U.S. ceiling allotted
55 16 0.5
55 55 15 11 0.7d 1.1
57 20 14
58 20 20
Europe, Australia and New Zealand Percent of world’s population Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of U.S. ceiling allotted
28 43 62
25 43 80
23 31 51
21 26 18
18 21 21
Western hemisphere (not including the U.S.)e Percent of world’s population Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of U.S. ceiling allotted
6 28 36
8 27 18
9 20 46
9 18 41
9 19 19
Source: United Nations Demographic Yearbook, various years. aWorld population does not include that of the U.S. Percentages calculated from census data in the UN Demographic Yearbook, table 1 (various years). bStarting in 1969, each country in the Eastern Hemisphere was given a limit of 20,000 within a 170,000 maximum; the Western Hemisphere was given a 120,000 ceiling with no distribution by country. The allocation calculated in this column then is based on the number of countries among which a subquota is divided. It is the point at which countries equalize. cStarting in 1978, the hemisphere divisions were lifted but all countries were limited to the 20,000 ceiling. This means that the hypothetical distribution of immigration slots among regions just matches the proportion of the world’s countries in them. dUntil special legislation enacted from 1943 to 1952, the Asian quota was usable only by non-Asiatics, i.e., by those of European or African descent who happened to be born in Asia. Until this time, the quota for Asiatics was zero. eThe Western Hemisphere did not have a ceiling until 1965/1969. It is included through the whole period for the sake of consistency. “Ceiling allotted” for earlier years is the proportion of all legal immigrants coming from the Western Hemisphere.
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
177
dence. “We need all the friends we can muster—particularly at this time. We cannot afford to have any nations turn against us, particularly our neighbors to the south of us.”173 World War II demonstrated that this evidence should be taken seriously. “It took President Roosevelt to establish the good neighbor policy and renew old friendships. And we all recall how important those friends were to us during World War II.”174 Cuban threats underlined its importance. “All this, too, at a time when the ugly head of communism has been raised on the island of Cuba and we have been joined with other nations on this hemisphere to keep this, our hemisphere, the land of freedom and of government of, for, and by the people.”175 During the last days of debate, American troops landed in the Dominican Republic. “I am deeply concerned about the strong propaganda tool which the limitation of 120,000 would give to demagogues, especially Communist demagogues, in Latin America, who may play this theme to a fare-theewell.”176 The Monroe doctrine, originally directed against European imperialism, did double duty as an anticommunist statement. If these internationalists were inductive, in that they fashioned their case from visible contemporary threats, other internationalists were deductive, arguing that hegemony demanded consistency, and therefore American power demanded Western Hemisphere restriction. Since logic demanded restriction that many restrictionists did not want, these internationalists demanded logic. They wanted to force isolationists’ hands, to show that isolationists were not for closing all borders to protect America, but for closing the borders against speci‹c groups. The Committee on the Judiciary is asking the House to place a numerical ceiling on immigrants from all countries outside the Western Hemisphere. Would it not also be fair and just to place Latin American and Caribbean area immigration under a reasonable ceiling? In our foreign relations, does America want to convey the
TABLE 6.
Factions in the Debate Left
Right
Internationalist
Equalize quotas in the East; keep Western Hemisphere open
Equalize quotas in both hemispheres at a higher numerical level
Isolationist
Equalize quotas in both hemispheres at a lower numerical level to protect labor
Leave national origins quotas; keep Western Hemisphere open to allow labor migration
178
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
impression that the Scandinavians, the Germans, the Irish, the Italians, are less welcome here than someone else?177 Not extending the ceiling would put the Western Hemisphere in a “highly preferred position,” neither “fair, just and reasonable” nor “logical.”178 “To argue that the imposition of a numerical limitation is discriminatory to Latin American nations when we impose by this bill a numerical limitation against all the other nations in the world is not persuasive.”179 Legislators had to be able to justify their choices on some reasonable basis. Logical consistency did matter. Negotiated settlement on this issue was dif‹cult because the factions split across regions and parties. The split on the Western Hemisphere issue was decisive in the House, where the vote was 189 to 218, with 25 not voting, against limitation.180 The split on the issue of equalization was decisive in the Senate, and it is this issue that prevailed. The conference committee restored Western Hemisphere ceilings as a compromise because the Senate was worried about escalating Cuban refugees.181 Those advocating consistency won because the other arguments were internally contradictory, relying on assertions that a threat would obtain in one instance or region but not another. Restrictionists and internationalists desiring consistency noted that the cold war was not just in the Eastern Hemisphere. The Western Hemisphere provided a haven for those hoping to slip into the United States uncounted. “Certainly there is no reason in the world for Russia or her satellite countries to try to send subversive spies, saboteurs, and traitors into the United States through legal ports of entry, when all that is necessary for them to do is to place such persons on the border between the United States and Mexico and say, ‘Go to it, boys. No one will make any attempt to stop you.’”182 Both credibility and internal security suggested extending the ceiling west. “I am shocked beyond words that the Congress, which investigates practically everyone from a baby sitter to a kindergarten teacher, does not impose stringent controls in the case of immigration at the Mexican border.”183 Internationalists had gained support for their position by arguing for equality as a principle to help ‹ght the cold war. The cold war could not be both global and irrelevant in the Western Hemisphere.
Reason: Consistency
Isolationists’ assertions that immigration would increase irritated internationalists. Isolationist O. C. Fisher said that his “chief objection to this bill is that it very substantially increases the number of immigrants who will be
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
179
admitted each year, and it shifts the mainstream of immigration from western and northern Europe—the principal source of our present population—to Africa, Asia, and the Orient.”184 Echoing earlier arguments, isolationists such as Fisher worried that there would be more—too many—unassimilable people. Internationalists insisted that their intent was to equalize opportunity to immigrate, not to increase the volume of immigration. Advocates of the immigration reforms pointed out that any seeming increase was really the result of changes in accounting. In theory, there would be an “approximate doubling,” but “in practice, this would not result in any marked increase in immigration, since in the last 10 years, there has been an average annual entry of 150,000 immigrants outside the quotas.”185 A prominent supporter of immigration reform, Edward Kennedy, delineated how skeptics might be mistaken. As I have previously stated, the number of quotas authorized each year will not be substantially increased. The world total—exclusive of Western Hemisphere—will be 170,000, an increase of approximately 11,500 over current authorization. But 10,200 of that increase is accounted for by the inclusion of refugees in our general law for the ‹rst time. There will be some increase in total immigration to the United States—about 50,000 to 60,000 per year. . . . These are the numbers that go unused each year. . . . the percentage increase that immigration will represent is in‹nitesimally small.186 The new law in fact extended regulatory control to an area previously unrestricted. In 1958, Emanuel Celler, reform’s main sponsor in the House, wanted an increase to 250,000 based “on the average number of immigrants actually admitted into the United States within the last decade.”187 He successfully steered through Congress a bill that liberalized the way that the country determined acceptable immigrant characteristics in the context of no change in numbers. In 1965 he asked, “Do we appreciably increase our population, as it were, by the passage of this bill? The answer is emphatically ‘No.’ The thrust of this bill is no appreciable increase in numbers.”188 Table 5 outlines the regional distribution of numerical ceilings. Publicly avowed intent stressed characteristics exclusively, in a departure from previous debates. In the discussions up to 1952, the core concern had been the numbers of immigrants with particular characteristics. In 1965, legislators focused only on characteristics, declaring an intention neither to increase nor to decrease the volume of immigration into the country. Reasons publicly acceptable and persuasive in this period dealt
180
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
with equity and leadership, rather than with military and economic security, which underlaid efforts to tighten or eliminate restrictions on numbers. Contemporary public debate allowed consensus on liberalizing preferences and exclusions, and demanded agreement on keeping the publicly declared limit the same. Given that the law’s public intent was liberal on characteristics and restrictive on numbers, it is noteworthy that its effect (rarely publicly discussed and never mentioned as a goal) was the opposite, to continue to select the same immigrant characteristics as before, but to allow more to immigrate. By setting 74 percent of the preferences for family members, legislators assured that the immigrant stream could not shift source too quickly. They replaced the national origins quota law by “brothers and sisters” preferences, which allowed immigrants closely related to, and therefore of the same race as, citizens. Prior to 1965, for example, if 20 percent of the U.S. population was of French ancestry, 20 percent of the immigration quotas would be allotted to French unrelated to U.S. citizens. After 1965, 20 percent of the people in the United States would be eligible to admit their relatives—who most likely lived in France. In practice, this system was biased toward recent immigrants—though there were not many because of the Quota Act and McCarran-Walter restrictions—because they were most likely to have relatives abroad; in the mid-1960s, few May›ower descendants had siblings in England. Another 6 percent of the preferences would be for refugees, who had been entering via another administrative category before. The reasons changed, but they were reasons for selecting the same groups of people. On the other hand, assuming greater demand for immigration than the supply of places, pooling unused quotas meant that immigration would increase. Those from, for example, Italy, instead of being placed on a waiting list, would enter using the places that the British did not want. Actual immigration would increase. In intent, the bill was liberal on characteristics but conservative on numbers; in effect it was conservative regarding characteristics but liberal on numbers. These effects of the 1965 act, not part of the public negotiations about boundaries leading up to it, would become relevant to discussion only in later decades. Public interest arguments that hoped to succeed did not and could not advocate increasing numbers of immigrants. Successful arguments tied change in immigration policy to the national interest in protecting against a threat. Credibility in the cold war could demand consistency, but it did not require any change in numbers. Lyndon Johnson and other proponents of reform supported this “no change” interpretation of Hart-Celler’s effect on numbers. “The total number of immigrants would not be sub-
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
181
stantially changed. Under this bill, authorized quota immigration, which now amounts to 158,361 per year, would be increased by less than 7,000.”189 Similarly, “it is important to note that this new law will not open the ›oodgates of immigration. . . . [There is an] increase of only about 2,000 persons over the presently authorized annual total”;190 “the annual in›ux of foreigners will continue to be barely perceptible in a population as large and as heterogeneous as our own.”191 In fact, “this bill is more restrictive than present law. It imposes even more rigid requirements, and it sets more speci‹c limitations than does present law.”192 Legislators were anxious to demonstrate that the changes they sought did not weaken the borders that guaranteed American distinctiveness and integrity. Characteristics, not quantity, were legislators’ avowed target. “The question posed by this bill is not whether quota immigration should be substantially increased, but simply how we are to choose those who are admitted.”193 The bill was equitable. “Total immigration will not increase substantially under the newly proposed policy, but it will be more fairly apportioned.”194 As important, the bill streamlined immigration policy and reduced the hodgepodge of laws into a single package. “When anyone in your constituency asks you about our immigration policies, about the number of immigrants that are coming into this country, I think for the ‹rst time you can honestly say what the number will be.”195 Gaining control was an end in itself, regardless of the sorts of changes made to the laws. Figure 8 illustrates the arguments made. Only thirteen years separated McCarran-Walter from its successor, yet the majority in favor of the 1965 liberalization was larger than that for the earlier restriction. The House of Representatives voted 318 to 95 (with 19 not voting) in favor of the package of reforms;196 the Senate voted 76 to 18 (6 not voting);197 and the House ‹nally approved the conference report, which added a Western Hemisphere ceiling, by 320 to 69, with 42 not voting, an even larger margin than that by which they passed McCarran-Walter over Truman’s veto thirteen years earlier.198 Many of the members of Congress present to vote in 1952 were no longer in of‹ce in 1965, but of the 320 who voted for Hart-Celler, 40 had voted for McCarran-Walter (and 39 had voted against it) in 1952. The new members, who had been elected during the period when the United States threw its energy into putting international institutions into operation and into ‹ghting the cold war, voted overwhelmingly in favor of eradicating the racial categories and agreed to include the Western Hemisphere under the immigration ceiling. Minds did not change; the population of legislators changed. None of the 40 who had reversed their position over the past decade spoke on the issue during the debates, though the adherence of new members demonstrated that the arguments that the
182
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty Cold War ⇓ Public Interest Argument
Policy Argument
Implementation
Discriminating among citizens destroys American authority
Maintaining American credibility helps to secure and even to increase the country's power
The country must abolish racial discrimination in immigration policy if it is to retain credibility
Racial categories have offended old countries; offense to new countries will cost the country the cold war
Discriminating among citizens threatens civil tranquillity
Equality and civic peace are necessary for liberal democracy to maintain itself
The country must abolish racial discrimination in immigration policy if it is to attain social peace
Causal Argument
↑ ↑ plausibility
↑
↑ efficiency
↑
↓ Ideas about Causation: Racism Undermines Credibility; Credibility Creates Security Fig. 8.
Arguments made before Hart-Celler
minority had made during the early 1950s became more plausible as the decade progressed. Change developed within and across regions, and within and across across parties. Table 7 shows the changing balance among the yeas and nays across regions.199 Hart-Celler, or the Immigration and Nationality Act Amendments of 1965 as the new provisions are formally known, has sometimes been interpreted as a breakthrough for liberalism, revolutionizing the way that the country thought of, and treated, potential immigrants. This is true and untrue. It is partially true not because the act took halfway measures in immigration reform, but because it took full measures in one direction, when considering immigrants’ characteristics, and full measures in the opposite direction when considering immigrants’ quantity. Hart-Celler eliminated exclusions based on race. For the ‹rst time since just after the Civil War, race was irrelevant to eligibility for admission. Countries, moreover, received equal ceilings. Not only could Portugal send as many immigrants as England, but so could
The Immigration Reform Act of 1965
183
Pakistan or the Philippines. A country’s history as an embarkation point, or gene pool, for American citizens no longer mattered. Hart-Celler did not, however, increase the number of immigrants legally allowed to immigrate. The 1965 act raised the general ceiling from 150,000 to 270,000, but did so by bringing the previously unrestricted Western Hemisphere into the regulated group for the ‹rst time, allocating to immigrants from that region 120,000 places. For the decade 1955 to 1964, actual immigration from this region had averaged 109,000; during the early 1960s when debate about immigration was more intense, immigration from the Western Hemisphere jumped from 89,566 in 1960 to 110,140 in 1961; 130,740 in 1962; 144,680 in 1963; down to 135,820 in 1964 but then back up to 153,200 in 1965.200 Extending the legal ceiling to the Western Hemisphere primarily extended regulatory control and secondarily curtailed immigration from this region. Meanwhile, though, Congress’s having revised the categories covering immigrants’ characteristics—eliminating national origins quotas—had the consequence of increasing immigration from the Eastern Hemisphere, as the populous countries of Asia and Africa could for the ‹rst time send as many as 20,000 annually. Though the cap remained the same, the previously underused 150,000 for the Eastern Hemisphere was to be used fully after 1965. Legislators and those they invited to testify, however, mentioned neither of these effects on quantity. Several in fact took pains to point out that the law would have no effect on quantity at all, or else they provided volumes of numerical analyses demonstrating that actual immigration would decrease or increase by a couple of percentage points at most. What legislators stressed constantly was a move toward equity in the context of a ›ow numerically unchanged. Table 8 illustrates the ways in which Hart-Celler differed from its predecessor. For this reason, the 1965 immigration reforms are unique. Changes to
TABLE 7.
Regionalism in McCarran-Walter and Hart-Celler Northeast
South
Midwest
West
1952 Yes No Not voting
54 65 4
77 7 18
81 30 4
66 10 14
1965 Yes No Not voting
97 1 10
48 46 10
100 5 7
75 17 15
184
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
immigration policy before and after the 1965 act also made signi‹cant alterations in some areas and blessed the status quo in others, but reformists in other periods argued their case with explicit reference to numbers. A model argument common to the Quota Acts, to McCarranWalter, and later to the Immigration Reform and Control Act of 1986 was: We allow too many of these people. The central problem was a glut not just of generic immigrants but of particular immigrants; conversely, the problem was not “these people’s” mere presence, but their presence in numbers. Too many Chinese, too many Italians, too many anarchists or communists, too many illegal aliens undermined social integrity and would handicap the United States in its struggle against its enemies: racially and socially decadent European and Asian countries, crazy European anarchists, Soviet and Chinese communists, German and Japanese economic competition. Hart-Celler was an exception. Two changes led to McCarran-Walter’s eventual revision along the lines chosen. Decolonization convinced more legislators in 1965 than in 1952 that America had to lead and that its credibility affected the country’s security. The public interest had to be consistent with the national interest, and the cold war meant that national interest was international. Second, liberal internationalists accepted the bifurcation between economic and immigration policy initiated by isolationists in the early 1950s. Before McCarran-Walter, isolationists and internationalists had each argued for consistency among issue-areas: free trade in goods meant free trade in people; protectionism regarding defense and trade implied protection regarding people; and so on. McCarran-Walter’s advocates had managed to delink the issue-areas, achieving increased immigration restriction in a context of economic internationalism. Its 1965 reformers eventually accepted this split, targeting their proposals at content rather than form. Immigration policy could be formally, numerically restrictive while other policies were formally, numerically liberal—if they treated all countries alike. Peter Rodino, an internationalist, revealed that this choice was conscious when he declared, perfectly seriously, that “instead of logic and consistency [among issue-areas], I believe we must face reality and consider the national interest as being paramount.”201 Hart-Celler applied the most-favored-nation principle to an immigration policy that, unlike trade policy, sought to curtail volume. On one hand, policy in different issue areas could diverge. Trade policy, defense policy, human rights, immigration—each could follow its own logic. On the other, policy in domestic and foreign spheres could not diverge. Employment and trade policy, arms and alliances, civil rights and human rights, immigrants and citizens—all should be treated consistently. “Race and immigration, and how we resolve these problems may very well
TABLE 8.
Hart-Celler, the Immigration Reform Act of 1965
Act Immigration and Nationality Act (McCarran-Walter) Act of June 27, 1952
INA Amendments (Hart-Celler) Immigration and Nationality Act Amendments of October 3, 1965
Numerical Restrictions
Preference Categories
Unrestricted (Nonquota) Immigrants
Exclusions
Overall ceiling: 154,657 Method of allocation: Each country given a cap equal to one-sixth of 1 percent of the persons in the U.S. in 1920 whose ancestry derived from that area. Established a minimum of 100, and granted Asian countries a general ceiling of 2000.
•1st: Aliens with special skills, with their spouses and children, 50 percent •2d: Parents of U.S. citizens, 30 percent •3d: Spouses and children of resident aliens, 20 percent •4th: Other relatives of U.S. citizens, 25 percent culled from unused slots above •Nonpreference: Any remaining unused
•Husbands of U.S. citizens
•Communists, as outlined in the Internal Security Act •Drug addicts •Anyone attempting fraud •Additionally established the alien address report system, which required aliens to report their addresses annually for inclusion in a central security file
Overall ceiling: 290,000 Method of allocation: 120,000 general cap for the Western Hemisphere; 170,000 cap for the Eastern Hemisphere, with a limit of 20,000 per country per year.
•1st: Adult unmarried children of U.S. citizens, 20 percent •2d: Spouses and unmarried children of resident aliens, 20 percent •3d: Professionals, 10 percent •4th: Married children of U.S. citizens, 10 percent •5th: Brothers and sisters of U.S. citizens, 24 percent •6th: Other needed workers, 10 percent •7th: Conditional (refugees) •Nonpreference: Unused slots from above
•Spouses, children and parents of U.S. citizens •Ministers •Former employees of the U.S. government abroad •Foreign medical graduates
•Sexual deviation
186
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
be the key to America’s victory in the struggle for the moral leadership of the free world.”202 Inside or outside the country made no difference. Policy became integrated by topic, not by sphere; it became split between topics, not between spheres. Integrating domestic and international processes created the tensions that propelled debate. The set of tensions that the legislators faced all involved con›ict between sovereignty and global liberalism. One tension was between the domestic economy and international security. “The nub of the problem is how to protect the country against a great stream of immigrants who could have a dislocating effect on the economy, yet at the same time to ease the explosive effect of overpopulation in other countries and do our fair share in the refugee ‹eld.”203 Another tension was between traditional immigration and subversion, between democracy and treasonous speech. “We are a Nation dedicated to the idea of providing a land of opportunity for the oppressed of other lands. This has been one of the cornerstones of our democracy and it has helped to make us the great Nation that we are. Today, however, because of the Communist conspiracy, we must examine our immigration policies in the light of a serious security problem. The con›ict between our traditional desires and security has created the legislative impasse which now exists.”204 Autonomy and interdependence con›icted with each other, but each had advantages. One way to solve this dilemma was to choose an expansive sovereignty, one that allowed autonomy because it promoted asymmetrical interdependence. American hegemony erased the problem.
CHAPTER 7
Whom to Exclude, Whom to Prefer: IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
In 1965, American legislators weighed alternatives according to how they would play in the eyes of NATO allies, Eastern European citizens, and the uncommitted leaders of newly independent countries, as well as American citizens engaged in supporting the civil rights movement. The dominant reason for fashioning those reforms was concern about the lack of ‹t between the country’s claim to moral authority in the ‹ght against communism and its practice of racist exclusion mechanisms. Two decades later—paradoxically when the American administration was reviving cold war competition—what concerned representatives most about potential American citizens was not whether they were ideological exemplars but whether they could compete economically with the Germans and Japanese at an intensity suf‹cient to salvage American power and authority. As with the 1965 act, change in the country’s main international threat, rather than a profound or dramatic event such as a world war, prompted the reforms. This is particularly noteworthy since it is not as if the period from 1965 to 1990 was uneventful, in the American economy, in American domestic politics, or in the country’s relation to the rest of the world. During this period the war in Vietnam intensi‹ed and ended, as did public activism about the war; President Nixon removed the dollar from its role as linchpin of the international monetary system, normalized relations with China, negotiated détente with the Soviet Union, and resigned from of‹ce; the oil crisis destabilized Western economies and brought about a massive redistribution of wealth from the poorest and richest countries to the oil exporters; the Soviets asserted control in Poland and Afghanistan; and Iranian revolutionaries took Americans hostage in Tehran. During the 1980s, ongoing wars in Central America brought thousands of refugees to the country’s southern border and led to an ecumenical movement for sanctuary whose activities purposely transgressed American law. As Congress was ‹nalizing the 1990 act, the single most important circumstance controlling ideas about sovereignty and postwar immigration 187
188
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
policy, the cold war, silently ended. It is certainly plausible that any of these events, let alone landing men on the moon, could change the way the country thought of itself in relation to its environment. Yet it was something much more diffuse, fear of hegemonic decline and loss of global competitiveness, that dominated the arguments that legislators made regarding immigration policy. What changed was what the legislators believed external events signi‹ed, why they were important. During the late 1960s, legislators and the public drew lessons about the country’s position as global leader in the ‹ght against communism. Cuban refugees, for example, provided the United States with ammunition in the cold war against the Soviets. By the late 1980s, in contrast, Congress drew lessons about America’s ability to dominate European and Japanese markets. Congress’s interpretation of Central American refugees’ signi‹cance is one indicator of its changing standards for judging immigrants. Nicaraguan refugees—from a war that the executive branch interpreted as it had interpreted that in Cuba two decades earlier, as a proxy war—were not seen to raise the American score in the country’s ongoing struggle with the Soviets. Rather, these maybe–cold war refugees were seen as important primarily for economic reasons, because they brought in capital and skills, or because they absorbed funds that could have gone to citizens dislocated by American economic upheavals. Although in 1979 and 1980 American politicians largely saw the Central American wars as ideologically signi‹cant to the U.S.-Soviet rivalry, by the mid-1980s they interpreted their consequences for the United States almost solely in economic terms. This shift in standpoint affected some immigrant groups more than others. Soviet Jews, for example, were welcome when they were not allowed to leave the Soviet Union, but not welcomed when they were granted permission to exit. Koreans, in contrast, were welcomed ‹rst because of their loyalties in the cold war and later because of their bene‹cial effect in marginal economic areas. The “why” changed more than the “who,” although the “why” changed gradually, as the currency in which costs and bene‹ts were calculated changed from that of ideological struggle to that of economic survival. Regardless of the facts concerning America’s ability to outcompete its main economic rivals, or any semiobjective assessment of economic risks versus military, cultural, or health risks to the country, over two decades legislators rebuilt the framework within which they judged threats and gauged the country’s response. How they changed immigration policy and why reveals how their perception of the most important difference between Americans and all others was transformed. Wars’ results and the spin that diplomats could place on them mat-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
189
tered, still, because of their consequences for American reputation. That reputation, in turn, determined the country’s ability to lead the West and to win the cold war. Ed Koch of New York insisted that immigration policy continue to assist the country’s effort in the cold war: “Soviet leaders, and the Jews behind their guarded borders, must be told that Americans of all faiths, acting through their elected Congress, deplore Soviet treatment of a proud minority and will make them welcome here.”1 Democrat John Rarick argued that “History records that every country that the free world has abandoned has, upon being taken over by the Communists, suffered a blood-bath of its anti-communist and non-conforming citizen; witness Red China and Cuba . . . the militant collectivist state[s].”2 In 1973, immigration questions became linked to trade when the Jackson-Vanik amendment to the Trade Reform Act denied mostfavored-nation status to any country that did not allow emigration. Henry Kissinger, reported Senator Jesse Helms, explained that “the total thrust of these negotiations between American and Soviet of‹cials has been directed toward the problem of Jewish emigration from the Soviet Union, and not toward the emigration of all citizens from all Communist countries.”3 John Brademas echoed this when he said that “The refugee issue is but another challenge to the efforts of the United States to provide leadership for the free world.”4 But as the debate shifted to a broad concern with American borders, the cold war disappeared as the central principle de‹ning arguments over immigration policy. The last time any legislator linked it to a central immigration issue was when Paul Simon in 1985—in the middle of the 1980s defense buildup—argued that proposals to deport illegal immigrants mimicked Soviet policy.5 American leadership in the Third World, another cold war issue, continued to arise in the context of the immigration debate. Edward Kennedy and others argued that immigration from underdeveloped areas was bad not because of its effects on the United States but because it harmed those areas. “The issue here is especially complicated and ›uid—involving our own national belief in the freedom of movement, and the collective responsibility of the advanced nations to assist the progress of the underdeveloped areas.”6 This also operated as a political safety valve, retarding political progress abroad. “By acting as a safety valve for the underdeveloped countries and by accepting their excess population,” argued B. F. Sisk, “we enable them to delay taking action on their own to deal with economic and population problems.”7 American leadership demanded a prudent application of liberal principles. In 1976, Leonard Chapman, the Commissioner of the Immigration and Naturalization Service, justi‹ed restriction using military imagery:
190
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
In this hostile world we must be vigilant and ever alert if we are to preserve the freedoms, and the way of life which so many of our veterans have fought to ensure, and for which many have laid down their lives. . . . I am concerned about another type of invasion of our country. It is ongoing now, and has been for several years—although it has gone largely unnoticed. For the perpetrators are not wearing uniforms, and are not carrying weapons. They are not storming our beaches under the cover of artillery. Rather their invasion is a silent one, occurring mainly at night across our unprotected borders.8 When the cold war did actually end, legislators saw it as having little signi‹cance for immigration policy. One, William Lipinski, argued that the United States should accept immigrants to assure its continued credibility. “Why did we do the Berlin airlift—or go to war in Korea? The list goes on. Did we do all this just so we could tell the people we were ‹ghting to protect and liberate? Well, we are glad you’re free—just don’t think about moving into my neighborhood.”9 The cold war vanished from the immigration debate at least six years before it ceased to dominate discussion of defense policy. If all possible causes had generated discussion, this chapter would be divided into at least eleven sections: the Vietnam War, détente, disengagement of the dollar, normalization with China, the oil crisis, Watergate, martial law in Poland, the Soviet invasion of Afghanistan, the Iranian hostage crisis, Central American wars, and ‹nally the cold war. Since many of these were met with ringing silence, what follows is a review of the events that legislators did raise as evidence in debate—Vietnam, Iran, El Salvador/Nicaragua—followed by a review of those that they did not. Cold war reasons gave way to economic reasons in spite of objective similarities among circumstances the legislators discussed and in spite of the cold war’s intensi‹cation during this period.
Reason: Politics of Labeling Allies and Enemies— Vietnam, Iran, Central America
War in Vietnam, like the world wars, the Korean War and the cold war, highlighted the divergence between the principles for which America was willing to ‹ght and the principles by which it chose its citizens. After World War I, legislators argued that allies and enemies should be recognized as such in immigration policy; during World War II, Congress rescinded Chinese exclusion because of the Chinese effort against the Japanese; and in the late 1940s, a frustrated Truman found himself trying
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
191
to establish an alliance against the Soviet Union with people whom the Quota Acts banned. He, like presidents before him, argued strenuously that immigration and foreign policies had to be mutually reinforcing. The pattern continued during and after the Vietnam War. Alien soldiers fought, as did citizen troops, for the United States. Convinced that aliens could provide no higher proof of commitment, legislators argued that aliens serving in Vietnam should be allowed to naturalize, regardless of whether they had completed their residency and other requirements. “It should be axiomatic,” declared Edna Kelly, “that those who risk their lives in the defense of freedom are entitled to all of the bene‹ts and privileges which we can bestow upon them.”10 Representatives especially welcomed such loyalty from aliens at a time when many citizens refused military service. In 1968 Bob Wilson observed that “amidst domestic turmoil, caused by a vocal minority of antiwar protesters who feel no necessity to serve the United States, it is most heartening to ‹nd those of other countries who value what we stand for enough to be willing to risk their own lives.”11 A bill to waive administrative requirements for soldiers who wanted to naturalize passed the House with no opposition. Both supporters and opponents of aid to Vietnamese refugees argued for their positions by invoking the necessity for consistency. Americans could not treat allies from one war in one way and treat those from another war differently. Americans went into Vietnam in support of the noncommunist southern Vietnamese, establishing a de facto alliance with the south. Allies in every earlier war had been acknowledged as eligible for citizenship; allies in Vietnam ought also to be accepted. No one had raised the issue until the early 1970s, by which time the prospect that the allies would be abandoned seemed real. Many worried about the responsibility that they had incurred to the Vietnamese. In case of defeat or overthrow, it must be obvious to all Americans that millions of South Vietnamese will be liquidated in the name of peace by the Communist conquerors. The American people as well as our leaders owe a responsibility to the people of South Vietnam. It was the Americans who made the assurances that we would make South Vietnam safe from Communist aggression and control.12 Republican Millicent Fenwick framed America’s obligation as one of justice. “It seems patently unfair,” she said, “that the same individuals who diligently served us in Vietnam should now receive less than sympathetic understanding from us here.”13 Times were hard economically. Both conservative and liberal Democrats argued along the same lines. George Hud-
192
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
dleston contended that “it is up to our Nation, which bears a responsibility for the conditions which led the migrants here, to see that the assimilation is as easy as possible”;14 Edward Kennedy, who led the immigration debate in the Senate for most of this period, argued that “we have a special responsibility to help restore their lives, in part because we participated in a long war that helped to destroy the life they knew—and because our planes and ships helped many to reach our shores.”15 American policy had created the Vietnamese refugees; therefore, the country had an obligation to accept those that ›ed after Saigon fell. Others argued that immigration policy had to be consistent with the country’s historical traditions. The United States owed itself a policy of integrity, a policy in concert with American traditions. Peter Rodino, for example, argued that the refugees would provide many tangible advantages to the United States, but “ultimately, however, we must do this because it is the only right thing to do. We are a nation of immigrants, and when we reject our humble foreign origins, we will have ended our reason for being as a nation.”16 In fact, some argued, moral consistency overrode material interests. In 1975, unemployment was up to 8.9 percent. “However,” said Joshua Eilberg, “this does not change the fact that we have an obligation to welcome the refugees of the war in the best American tradition, as we welcomed the Hungarians and the Cubans before them.”17 America’s future policies were to be consistent with those of the present and those of the past. To share such a view was not necessarily to reach the same conclusions. Democrat James Abourezk decried what he saw as rank hypocrisy in the way the country had decided which groups would be accorded refugee status. Those ›eeing “fascism and barbarism in Chile” and those tortured “by several of our so-called allies” were ignored; meanwhile, Congress prepared to provide asylum for the Vietnamese, for “thousands of trained political assassins who operated the Phoenix program [reputed to be a CIA-sponsored program to train Vietnamese assassins], for Vietnamese who corrupted their own society using American money, food, and equipment; for prostitutes, bar girls, pimps and other undesirables.”18 In his view, Congress should grant refugee status regardless of ideology. Those opposed to allowing Vietnamese entry, however, typically framed their arguments in terms of the government’s primary obligation to American citizens. Race loomed obviously in the debate only once. The Senate ›atly rejected (6 to 74) Jesse Helms’s contention that aid to Vietnamese should be restricted to private charity because of “a growing belief that this Nation has experienced more and more social problems as a result of this melting-pot theory.”19 The House gave somewhat more sup-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
193
port to Democrat Donald Riegle’s proposal to provide to American citizens the same bene‹ts given to Vietnamese refugees (71 to 346).20 Most, though, shared Republican Jack Kemp’s contention that “if we do shut our doors to these individuals—for they are all individuals—we will have taken that ‹rst step into a dark chapter of sel‹shness and isolation.”21 In a debate that echoed those of earlier times, Congress voted to accept immigrants because they were allies, and because not to do so would be to diminish American moral credibility in the eyes of both American citizens and the outside world. Both sides argued not primarily against their congressional opponents but against American public opinion. Legislators were alarmed by polls taken following the fall of Saigon that showed 57 percent of Americans opposed to receiving those ›eeing, with only 32 percent in favor.22 “I was frankly ashamed,” admitted one, “of the antirefugee sentiment which surfaced just after the evacuation of Saigon.”23 Iranian students’ reaction to the hostage crisis of 1979 prompted congressional debate framed in term of “national security” versus “civil rights.” One measure of America’s integration with the rest of the world was the number of nonimmigrant visitors it received annually. Students, like tourists and business travelers, were not numerically restricted; many in fact had been recruited. Congress allowed the market to determine the number of nonimmigrant travelers because of its conviction that such visitors had only economic weight. They came, they spent or invested money, and they left. Those expected to make a political claim had to route themselves through the sluices providing entry to the American citizen population. The difference between immigrants and nonimmigrants was clear. Or it was clear until Iranian students in the United States demonstrated in favor of the Iranian takeover of the American embassy in Tehran. When Iranian students chained themselves to the Statue of Liberty alongside an anti-Shah banner, legislators demanded that they be expelled. They had, after all, violated the terms of their visas. “How can we command any respect in the world, or even of ourselves, if we do not begin again to act like the powerful and morally strong Nation we once were, and should be?” asked William Dickinson.24 Others sought solace in political fundamentalism. Larry MacDonald asserted that the incident challenged American sovereignty: “When a country ceases to defend its territory and the lives of its citizens without equivocation, it has ceased to exist as a sovereign power without identity or substance.”25 S. I. Hayakawa titled his bill, to consider all American embassies overseas U.S. territory, the “American Sovereignty Protection Act.”26 It would expand the de‹nition of war to include terrorism, thus allowing the United States to
194
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
classify nationals of countries linked to terrorism as enemy aliens, subject to deportation.27 Outraged that the Immigration and Naturalization Service could not readily supply details about the number or location of Iranian students in the United States, legislators insisted that it reform its record keeping. It did not, however, pass or even propose legislation to alter the Immigration and Nationality Act. Wars in Central America also produced claimants for asylum, bringing immigration policy again to congressional attention. Congress was split on whether the refugees were ›eeing, or were themselves, allies or enemies. To call a person a refugee was to acknowledge that he or she had a well-founded fear of persecution, so to call someone ›eeing an ally a refugee was to admit that one’s ally was probably persecuting its citizens.28 Although in Central America the U.S. government trained and helped to supply troops engaged in a civil war against communists, as it did in Vietnam, this did not provide reason to accept refugees from the war—though it did in the case of Vietnam; although the government interpreted the war as a proxy war, as it did that in Cuba, this too did not provide a reason to accept refugees—though it did in the case of Cuba. Refugees from Vietnam in the 1970s ›ed an American enemy. Refugees from Central America in the 1980s largely ›ed an American ally. Unlike the debate about Vietnamese refugees, at stake in the debate over granting refugee status to Central Americans was the rightness of American policy. Those opposed to American support for the Nicaraguan Contras thus labeled the “feet people” refugees. “I believe,” said David Durenberger, “that the United States bears a certain responsibility for the noncombatant deaths because of our support for the Salvadoran government and the military.”29 Dennis DeConcini alleged that the State Department resisted accepting the refugees, since it “knew” that to do so “would re›ect adversely on our Nation’s policy of assisting the government in El Salvador.” Instead, he said, it demonstrated the State Department’s “guilty conscience.”30 Those in support of American policy declared that the migrants were ›eeing the communists, not American allies, or insisted that they were only economic refugees. Steven Symms cautioned that “if we ignore the implications of the extension of the evil empire of the Soviet Union into the Western Hemisphere, no piece of paper, no law is going to stem the tide of people voting with their feet, seeking freedom in the United States.”31 On the other hand, those escaping from the Contras were economic refugees with no real moral claim to asylum.32 Other events during the period from the mid-1960s to the mid-1980s were largely ignored in legislative debates on immigration policy. Détente with the Soviet Union, opening of relations with China, the Bretton Woods
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
195
crisis, the oil crisis, Watergate, martial law in Poland, and the Soviet invasion of Afghanistan all went unremarked in the world of immigration politics. The geostrategic events of this period, all cold war–related, provided reasons to preserve, rather than to corrode, prevailing immigration restrictions, which had after all been designed to handle just such crises that a cold war leader could expect to face. To administration eyes, the difference between Vietnam and Central America on the one hand, and the Soviet invasion of Afghanistan on the other, was simply that Americans fought Soviet proxies in the former, while Soviets fought American proxies in the latter. This difference meant that the United States incurred a straightforward obligation to help its Vietnamese, Nicaraguan, and Honduran allies but was less obligated to those it helped in Afghanistan. Immigration policy already screened out communists, welcomed anticommunist refugees, and articulated a liberal standard for citizenship appropriate for a country claiming authoritative leadership of the West. None of these geostrategic events altered the nature of the world in which the United States existed, or the type of competition it faced, or the type of threat most dangerous to it. In fact, the big changes in the global distribution of power during this time, changes that the United States ignored when it re›ected on immigration policy, were those that it had sought and engineered. More cold war–related events were not going to motivate change in a policy already geared to deal with the fallout of the cold war. All they could do was provide more reasons to hold on to current policy. What ultimately did have a profound though indirect effect were the economic changes associated with the death of the dollar standard and the oil price shocks on the early 1970s. At the time, legislators perceived neither of these as signaling a structural change either in the American economy or in the country’s place in the international system. Immigrants were not discussed in 1971 because the dollar standard obviously had nothing to do with immigrants. Rejecting the dollar standard and accepting oil price hikes did, though, affect in›ation, the balance of manufacturing and service jobs, the U.S. balance of payments, and its ‹scal balance. While during the 1930s, the United States and its competitors both suffered greatly, in the late 1970s and early 1980s, the United States suffered while some of its competitors did not. American scholars and policymakers turned their attention to Japan and Germany, said to be gaining in economic health and power as the United States sought a way to ease structural economic pains. The United States believed itself to be engaged in an ideological and military ‹ght for which it was prepared. Immigration policy took care of that threat.
196
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Reason: Economic Threat
It did not take care of the new economic threat. During the 1980s, two subjectively separate standards coexisted: the United States was primarily engaged in a struggle for military dominance with the Soviet Union; the United States was primarily engaged in a struggle for economic dominance with Japan, Germany, and others. The two standards con›icted only in the area in which there was overlap, the topics of military spending and export controls of strategic products. In the 1980s, legislators devoted their efforts to reforms bene‹ting the United States in both its competitions. In 1990, after the collapse of the Berlin Wall, Congress comprehensively revised immigration policy to tailor it to a world whose threat to the United States was economic rather than military or ideological. The story of the 1960s and 1970s is one of continuing attention to alliance rivalries. The story of the 1980s is one of transition to a world in which economic competition mattered as much as did military hostility. Legislators and the public twice changed the standards by which they judged immigrants. Their starting point was ideological and military hegemony: the immigration that concerned the government had geopolitical causes and geopolitical consequences. The ‹rst shift was in the standards used to judge consequences. Causes remained the same—people whom Congress had seen as cold war refugees in 1965 they still viewed as such in 1975—but they judged the consequences of this immigration not in terms of the cold war but in economic terms. By the mid-1980s, there was another shift. Consensus was that the causes of immigrants’ desire to leave their homelands were a mixture of humanitarian, ideological, and economic problems, with the great majority of them economic. From political cause and political consequence, perception changed to political cause and economic consequence, and ‹nally to economic cause and economic consequence. These stages are most clearly visible examining changing American arguments about and policy toward speci‹c groups. In the 1960s, refugees from Cuba, for example, ›ed communism. Legislators measured their consequence for the United States in the propaganda and intelligence advantage that their ›ight gave the United States. A decade later, those who ›ed willingly or unwillingly left a communist enemy, but no longer carried much propaganda value with them. They did carry economic demands troubling to their new homeland. By the mid-1980s, Cuban refugees were seen primarily to ›ee economic distress in Cuba and to cause it in the United States. Economic considerations had always played some role, as had humanitarian and ideological considerations. What changed was the bal-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
197
ance among them and their political importance. Economic signi‹ed frivolous, unserious grounds for admission and was a label applied to groups that administrations did not want to accept. Good economic immigrants were necessary for the country to survive and indeed to dominate; bad economic immigrants would devastate the country’s chances to exceed Japan and Germany. By the 1980s, economic criteria came to be seen as necessary to assure American competitiveness. Good economic immigrants were “professionals” or “investors,” while bad economic immigrants were simply “economic.” This division did not pass unnoticed. The largely Democratic congressional Black Caucus, said Shirley Chisholm, “believes that the term ‘economic refugee’ was coined by the previous [Carter] administration to avoid this country’s obligations as a country of ‹rst asylum and because of racist presumptions about Haitians.”33 Similarly, Pennsylvania Republican Arlen Specter requested a report from the General Accounting Of‹ce on discriminatory application of asylum provisions. He, like the Black Caucus, was concerned that refugees were labeled bad/economic because they ›ed nonEuropean regions. The GAO reported to him that “those who described torture to support their asylum request had an approval rate of 4 percent in El Salvador cases, 15 percent in Nicaragua, 80 percent in Poland, and 64 percent in Iran.”34 In spite of such anger, policy began to adjust to the perception that the leadership other countries threatened most was not ideological or military, but economic. The adjustment began with new criteria to use in evaluating immigrants’ value. The cold war had provided a way to decide both legitimate reasons to immigrate and appropriate ways to understand immigrants’ value. This framework began to change with an awareness of immigrants’ economic costs. Conservative Jesse Helms argued that “Soviet expansion in Central America is causing havoc in Guatemala, Honduras, El Salvador and Costa Rica. Nicaragua is a Soviet base.” Although he sympathized with those ›eeing, he argued that refusing them entry would force their home governments to take care of them. To accept them as refugees was to bail out the communist governments.35 Democrat Les Aspin agreed, observing that “for many decades it has been the policy of dictatorial regimes to hem in their people and prevent anyone from getting out. . . . But now there is a shift away from the Soviet approach. Cuba and Vietnam exemplify the growing attitude that it is easier to rule if you simply let those elements that might coalesce as an opposition leave the country.” He commented that an open-door policy had been “acceptable to almost all Americans because, quite frankly, few people had the chance to get near the open door.”36 Immigrants’ costs had long been raised as good reason to be sparing
198
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
about admissions. From the nineteenth century immigrants had been charged with burdening the country racially, morally, and economically. They were educationally or genetically un‹t for democratic institutions and through some trick (that Americans never seemed to master) managed both to take jobs from Americans and to go on welfare. Some of these costs, to some degree and with some classes of immigrants, were likely correct. Determining which costs and how likely became the subject of government-sponsored, foundation-sponsored, and academic research. What was unique about this new cost-consciousness was that the arguments represented costs not as a forgone opportunity to aid citizens, but as an investment not made and workers not retrained, which were necessary to remain competitive with industrial economies overseas. What mattered was not immigrants’ domestic effects but their international effects. And the international effects that mattered were economic. In fact, the movement to excise the cold war from American immigration policy began much earlier than the cold war ended. Ironically, it was fading from importance as a determinant of immigrant characteristics as it was reaching its ‹nal crescendo under the Reagan administration. Early opponents of using ideology to exclude immigrants had framed their arguments in terms of ideology as a basis for American hegemony. A world leader should not be afraid to confront enemy ideas. In 1987, Daniel Moynihan contended that “by excluding aliens on ideological grounds, we behave as if we were afraid of their ideas, lending those ideas a credence that might evaporate under proper scrutiny.”37 As early as 1967, Edward Kennedy argued that “our de‹nition of refugees, still guided largely by a cold war framework, needs revision and reforms.”38 Barney Frank similarly connected American principles and international reputation: “It is truly inconsistent for this country to advocate the freedom of travel and the free ›ow of information and ideas, and at the same time to keep out individuals based on the content of speeches they intend to give in this country.”39 Other opponents argued that such restrictions harmed Americans’ and others’ enjoyment of their legal rights. Using these reasons to reverse the ban on ideological restrictions made it easier to argue that homosexuality as well should be removed from the list of exclusions. Although ideology was adopted and homosexuality was, arguably, not, opponents of using it as a basis for exclusion based their opposition on the same principles. In 1973, the American Psychiatric Association deleted homosexuality from its inventory of disorders; the American Surgeon General agreed in 1979. In its 1980 Annual Report, even the Immigration and Naturalization Service reported that “the Justice Department supports pending legislation that would remove homo-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
199
sexuality as a ground for excludability.”40 Alan Cranston, introducing a bill for repeal in 1985, noted, “Adoption of this legislation will end a form of discrimination which has no valid scienti‹c or medical basis and which violates traditional American respect for the privacy and dignity of an individual.”41 Categorical bans of all types, including ideological ones, violated individual rights; therefore, the argument went, they were suspect. Cultural and scholarly groups, frustrated in their efforts to get eminent writers to conferences in the United States, periodically complained that both visitors and immigrants could be excluded for activities that were not only perfectly legal for American citizens, but were speci‹cally protected by the Constitution or by international agreements. Advocating nationalization of the banking industry or acknowledging homosexuality would guarantee refusal of entry. The standard response that foreigners were, by de‹nition, not protected by the Constitution was unsatisfactory to those who believed that the Bill of Rights articulated protections that ought to apply to all. George McGovern in 1977 similarly used the Helsinki Final Act as a basis for arguing that immigrants not be excluded on ideological grounds. “If the United States is to remain an effective spokesman for the principle of ‘freer movement and contacts’ among nations and individuals, we must demonstrate to the world our own commitment to these ideals.”42 As an experiment, in 1987—after a 70 percent increase in the defense budget over seven years—ideology was removed from the list of exclusion criteria.43 It then became law as part of a State Department authorization bill. The international causes that propelled immigrants began also to be seen in economic terms. While some examined the economic effect of cold war immigrants, others questioned whether the immigrants in fact ›ed cold war con›icts. Cubans for example, had, to William Clay’s mind, forsaken their claim to refugee status if they had hesitated to leave, deciding to do so only after a decade following the revolution. The real refugees of Cuba left in the early 1960s when they had to ›ee for sanctuary. They were the ones who opposed Castro politically and who faced oppression and mistreatment at the hands of the Castro regime. What we have now in our Cuban refugee policy is a direct subsidizing of the welfare program of an alien nation.44 Similarly, though with less support from his peers, George Huddleston argued that Vietnamese were no different from Haitian refugees, having left their home country primarily to seek economic opportunity.45 Giving economic aid to a country instead of refugee status to its citi-
200
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
zens made sense if the underlying cause of their escape was economic. This strategy was proposed more often as the 1980s wore on. Early assertions that “we must therefore help to increase economic opportunities in other countries in order to reduce their out-migration”46 and observations such as “it costs far more to resettle a refugee in the United States or Europe than to give him hope in his own country”47 highlighted immigration policy’s economic inef‹ciency. No longer tied directly to nationalist-communist revolution, “the real problems,” said Ted Weiss, “are the factors which push refugees out of their own countries. Those problems are primarily explosive population increases in the Third World and the corresponding inability of Third World countries to provide adequate jobs for the millions of unemployed and underemployed who are already straining their economies.”48 Much of the ‹ght involved framing the issue. Aid to Mexico and plans for the North American Free Trade Agreement had one origin in concerns about immigration’s effect on American competitiveness. Edward Kennedy, for example, cautioned that “to deal effectively with this problem we are going to have to do what some of my other colleagues have stated, and that is to make Mexico the promised land so that people will want to go to Mexico, or stay in Mexico, because they realize there is real hope and opportunity, and that will be true in other problems of the ›ows of migration.”49 William Richardson, leader of the Hispanic Caucus, contended that the country should establish “‹rst, a free trade and coproduction zone along the United States–Mexican border; second, a United States–Mexican bilateral commission; third, a joint United States–Mexican development bank; and fourth, a multilateral commission on immigration.”50 Economic concerns overwhelmed marginal humanitarian considerations. “I feel very sorry for the many people in other parts of the world, especially Central America and Mexico,” declared James Tra‹cant. “But I think America must help them to ‹sh so they can feed themselves.”51 Opponents of this viewpoint took issue not with the underlying economic framework but with particular claims about the mechanism connecting foreign economic aid and emigration. Alan Simpson, cosponsor of reform legislation throughout the 1980s, argued that “if you increase the development assistance to Third World countries, you will ‹nd this phenomenon: That kind of activity will often increase emigration from that country. In other words, as they increase their productivity, their workability, their ability to earn—these same people who put together enough and then leave the country. They earn money suf‹cient to leave that country, whereas the poor person will stay there. He cannot move, he does not have any resources whatsoever.”52
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
201
Reason: Sovereignty and Hegemony
Sovereignty, undiscussed for decades, once again became the locus of public concern. When Americans had considered their greatest threat ideological, their concerns had centered on the consequences that discriminatory immigration policies could have on American reputation and hence leadership. The country perceived itself to have, in effect, two borders. One described the limits of the world it aimed to protect, separating communist countries from those identi‹ed with the West. The other separated the United States proper from its allies, which together provided a protective belt. Sovereignty was not a central issue because the boundary separating the United States from its main threat was not the U.S. border but that between East and West. Bloc cohesion, rather than sovereignty narrowly de‹ned, had been the policy goal. American immigration policy throughout this period re›ected this, taking both the fact of allies and the fact of U.S. dominance within the alliance into account. The United States constructed a two-tier system in which immigration, more carefully controlled than before, could reinforce its ability to meet this threat. Intra-alliance immigration fostered Western cohesion and assured that the United States would be considered a credible liberal authority, just as migration within an empire had been encouraged by mercantilist governments. Interalliance immigration, that is, encouraging refugees and defectors from the East, demonstrated that the United States was, as it claimed, preferable to the Soviet Union. Sovereignty returned as a central concern when the Western alliance no longer protected the country from its most serious threat, economic competition from within the Western alliance. Soon after Congress began to judge immigrants’ bene‹ts and costs in economic terms, it began explicitly to discuss threats in economic terms as well. If what was most important about immigrants was their economic impact, it made more sense to screen immigrants using economic standards than to use ideological standards to admit them but economic standards to gauge their effect. During the 1980s, two related ideas gained ground. One held that ideological exclusion criteria were bad: immoral, inef‹cient, and counterproductive. Another maintained that economic standards were good, far more important in measuring threat than was ideological pedigree. Both convictions developed in two stages. Up to 1989, people who argued for attention to international economic competition generally advocated adding economic considerations to the old policy. After 1989, they argued for replacing the old policy with one geared toward a world in which economic ‹ghts were central. These three convic-
202
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
tions—that ideological exclusions were misplaced, economic exclusions were wrongly ignored, and sovereignty was therefore being placed in jeopardy—came to undergird an increasingly popular alternative policy. Sovereignty resurfaced in the 1980s as a central concern partly because immigration policy had unintended consequences, but mainly because it was outmoded, its intended consequences irrelevant to the problems that the country faced. Edward Kennedy claimed that “there have been two unintended consequences of this [1965] revision: a few countries of the world have come to dominate the legal immigration system, and the level of immigration has risen dramatically. Neither result was intended, and both have occurred because of the emphasis on family connections.”53 While many agreed with Kennedy, this was not their main reason for advocating reform. Hart-Celler did in the main operate as intended. The problem was that one of the best immigration policies for a hegemon in an ideological battle was one of the worst immigration policies for an overextended ex-hegemon in an economic battle. Interest groups and legislators on both the left and the right during the 1980s turned their attention to discovering why the United States had ceased to be competitive economically. Although academics in various social sciences have examined this assertion on its merits as a description of observable structural change, few in Congress thought it necessary to assess whether this were true or to determine how to balance the ideological-military threat against the new economic threat in considering risk. Consensus on this new fact of life was in fact broad. Republicans and Democrats differed not in how they de‹ned the threat but in terms of which (American) policy they blamed for it. Republicans tended to blame unions’ and government’s protection of labor for pricing American goods out of the market, while Democrats pointed to defense spending. (Academics sometimes pointed to America’s overextension and subsidy of others’ military, but this was not a politically acceptable argument for either party.) People might disagree about whether Americans were overpaid or foreign workers were underpaid, but they agreed on the proximate cause of relative decline: American goods were overpriced. The belief took hold that immigration policy, as other policies, ought to be judged in terms of its effect on competitiveness. As Arlen Specter insisted, “the concern ought to be on productivity and competitiveness in the world market.”54 Immigrants became primarily factors of production. They could be separated into three categories: those who increased the country’s labor supply, those who improved labor quality, and those who contributed to the country’s capital base. While all of these had some constituency in theory, public interest arguments could be made only for the last two. Even were unemployment low, a general argument about increas-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
203
ing quantity could only be interpreted as a general argument in favor of reducing the level of wages across the board. Arguments about labor shortages had to target speci‹c sectors, demonstrably connected to those of high unemployment, if they were to appeal to the general social good. Two arguments involving the last two ways of thinking about immigrants’ economic effect met these criteria. First, skilled workers able to design products that the unemployed could then manufacture would help Americans without lowering their average standard of living. As Stanley Lundine argued, “Specialized technical skills such as engineering will be essential to maintaining and increasing the competitiveness of American industries in such a rapidly changing marketplace. We are in a time of economic transition, and this [preference for skilled workers] provision can help us to provide the talent necessary to keep American industry in the ballgame.”55 Jesse Helms was typical of those who agreed: “How do we expect America to remain competitive if our companies, who often face labor shortages in this country, can’t recruit the best talent and top notch researchers from abroad?”56 Also attractive was that this strategy would increase the population of skilled workers immediately, avoiding messy public policies. The alternatives, involving worker retraining, improving public education, and restructuring the connection between the manufacturing and service sectors, were every legislator’s nightmare. Second, many could and did argue that investors who became U.S. citizens would greatly bene‹t the American economic position. Tourists spent billions, but the problem with tourism as a solution was that it was two-way. Although “millions of visitors arrive every year from all over the world, [supplying] one of our largest sources of foreign trade revenue,”57 unfortunately “the U.S. runs a de‹cit on the tourism account of over $2 billion annually.”58 Immigrants, unlike tourists, would spend money for a lifetime. John LaFalce of New York ‹rst suggested, in 1979, preferring “entrepreneurs.”59 Say, the argument went, that an investor of $2 million could create ten jobs. Allowing him or her to acquire citizenship prevented repatriation of pro‹ts, and “this transfer of funds represents one more cash out›ow affecting adversely our balance-of-payments position.”60 Kept in, the wages and pro‹ts would both multiply through the economy. Moreover, since immigrants have a double effect, simultaneously increasing the population at their destination and decreasing that at their origin, the relative advantage to the United States would be double its absolute advantage; this money and these jobs were not only acquired by the United States but also denied to the investors’ homelands. Finally, an investor preference rewarded hard work. “Opening the gateway of opportunity to more of these deserving individuals,” said Alfonse D’Amato, “could only enhance our productivity and vitality as a culture.”61
204
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
The most potent opposition to this change of standards for judging desirability came from those who argued that economic standards themselves were an offensive way to gauge who ought to belong to the community. Central to the debate about illegal aliens was the con›ict between thinking about illegal residents in utilitarian or absolutist terms, that is, in terms of their economic consequences or in terms of what they had earned morally and politically. Either they should be judged according to what they had done—entered illegally versus paid taxes and served the community—or according to what they could do—boost or drain the pool of jobs and social services. A similar con›ict shot through the parallel debate about immigrants. Should economic immigrants be preferred? Or should the country privilege those, perhaps poor, who shared some set of communal norms? Dale Bumpers, of Alabama, argued most passionately against economic preferences. “Nobody ought to be admitted into this country simply because he can produce $250,000 [later $2 million] . . . I do not think the United States ought to indicate by allowing this to stay on the books that we will sell the United States piece by piece to the wealthiest bidders, to those who may be seeking a safe haven in the United States.”62 If this were to happen, he charged, “the road to the United States today, if this bill becomes law, will be a toll road.”63 Ben Nighthorse Campbell objected on similar grounds. “It remains inescapable that America would, for the ‹rst time in its history, be granting a statutory preference for citizenship based on wealth.”64 In this view, economic consequences were irrelevant and objectionable as the basis for choosing citizens, not because such consequences were unimportant but because doing so threatened to undermine how Americans understood citizenship. Forced to acknowledge these objections, those who advocated preferences for investors had to demonstrate how those preferences recognized individual achievement. It was not the consequences, they argued, that really mattered. Preferring the rich recognized industry and American value. Phil Gramm made the argument: Let us say you have a father in Hong Kong who has two sons. His clever son he puts into business and the son who is not quite so clever he sends to graduate school and he gets a Ph.D. But Hong Kong’s lease is ending and the Communists are about to take over, so the two sons decide they want to come to America. The Senator from Arkansas [Bumpers] asks, well, the one who has the money, does he love freedom? He has this money but does he love freedom? He is not asking the guy who has the Ph.D., if he loves freedom.65
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
205
Gramm’s approach was both to frame economic preferences in terms of desert, not consequence, and to question the justi‹cation for all preferences. Bumpers and those who agreed with him then framed their arguments in consequentialist terms. To rely on economic criteria for citizenship would be to accept market principles’ triumph over communitarian principles. Sovereignty would be empty as everything was for sale in the global market. “We are already being bought up,” he said. “Listen to this: the Japanese are ‹nancing 30 percent of our debt. There is over $1.5 trillion of foreign investment now. Every Governor I know is spending half his time in Europe and Japan trying to get people to come here and build plants. British investment in this country has gone up 192 percent since 1980. We are being bought out lock, stock, and barrel.”66 John Bryant of Texas charged that this bill is a culmination of the excesses of the 1980s, a period in which we tripled our national debt, a period in which we became the biggest debtor nation in the world, a period in which we became a country that no longer pay[s] its bills anymore without borrowing staggering sums of money, a period in which we sold off our most precious assets to the point that foreign ownership in our country has tripled in the last 7 years, and now we are selling our last and most precious possession, citizenship.67 Legislators agreed that economic competition challenged the United States and that it had to respond. They disagreed about whether to respond by trying to beat them or join them. Worries about competitiveness were not restricted to Republicans, or even to those in favor of immigration reform. Democrat Glenn Anderson echoed his colleagues’ analysis: “By letting in skilled workers and those who have special knowledge or technical ability, we improve the competitive structure of the U.S. economy, allowing us to better perform in the world marketplace. When we are under attack from nations like Japan, we must use all possible advantages of the brainpower and expertise that immigrants offer us.”68 Dale Bumpers, the most passionate opponent of preferences for investors, also framed his objections in these terms. “If we are going to talk about jobs,” he said, “let us talk about restoring the U.S. competitive edge.”69 Others such as Republican Harold Daub worried that increasing immigration would have the opposite of its intended effect. By encouraging immigration, the United States fostered dependence on labor-intensive production processes, giving businesses a disincentive
206
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
to invest time in the technological breakthroughs necessary for long-term competitiveness. “Amnesty,” he argued, “could damage the U.S. economy. The United States is moving toward a high-technology, computerized, robotized kind of economy and absorbing those large numbers of skilled workers from abroad would require the United States to develop a very different kind of economy.”70 Although these detractors disagreed about whether the change should be initiated through immigration or industrial policy, they agreed that some “changes are vitally necessary if the U.S. is to remain competitive in a global economic climate.”71 Two aspects of this framework for interpreting American goals were new: (1) economic concerns’ centrality (2) in a context that remained essentially cooperative and global. Economic dif‹culties had been raised in the past, though never as the decisive evidence requiring exclusion and never as important because of foreign competition. For example, the United States at different times believed that it owed returning veterans jobs, or that it needed to encourage agricultural labor, both of which were justi‹ed in terms of domestic distributive values. And in the 1960s its immigration policies had adapted to its chosen role as global leader and regime-maker. In the 1980s, the country began to substitute “economic” for “ideological” without also substituting “protectionist” for “internationalist.” The commissioner of an immigration study ordered during the Carter administration, for instance, outlined his view of the United States as enmeshed in a constraining web and as dependent on other countries to ful‹ll its objectives. we live in a shrinking, interdependent world and that world[’s] economic and political forces result in the migration of peoples. . . . The widespread magnitude of actual migration and the fear of other potential large-scale movements between countries has led many governments to adopt ever more restrictive immigration policies in an effort to maintain national control over borders and shores. The world situation today, however, throws into serious question the assumption that international migration can be controlled by domestic policy.72 The United States was going to have to negotiate, rather than assert, its international primacy. Interdependence posed a philosophical problem for the United States. On one hand, the country stood for liberalism. Its institutions rested on liberal principles, its economy found justi‹cation in liberal analysis, and its international authority depended upon it behaving in a way consistent with liberal tenets. On the other hand, liberalism when fol-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
207
lowed to its logical conclusion tended to erode borders. Nothing in liberal philosophy provided good reason to segregate markets or to exclude people, and much in it provided good reason not to. In fact, classical liberals such as Adam Smith and John Stuart Mill took as their starting point the conviction that such boundaries were irrational, forcing a society to accept an outcome less than optimal. Liberalism in one country can be just as odd a concept as socialism in one country. The dilemma was not acute as long as the country was strong enough to export its sense of order and justice. Hegemony made the apparent contradiction moot. Declining hegemony created con›icts that had not existed before among American policies. Trade had produced absolute and relative gains; later it was seen to produce absolute gains and relative losses. Refugees and immigrants had helped the United States and hurt the Soviet Union in their ideological ‹ght; later Soviet immigrants hurt the United States and helped the Soviet Union as the United States accepted, and the Soviet Union shunned, responsibility for their training, welfare, and social integration. American hegemony and liberal values rested on, and had institutionalized, a level of openness that could not be maintained if the United States were to assume the position of one among equals. It needed asymmetry. Symmetry involved feedback, and feedback threatened sovereignty. Theodore Hesburgh, former president of Notre Dame and commissioner of the 1980 immigration study, described the con›ict in this way: Some among us, often moved by deeply religious values, ask the question: Why should immigration be a problem? Why shouldn’t people be free to move wherever they want to? We are all one species, all children of one God; and from the beginning of time, human beings have been a curious, migratory species. Why not let down the barriers of nation-states and permit people to move freely? The questions almost answer themselves. Immigration is a problem because nearly all peoples believe in nationalism and wish to maintain the integrity of national ideologies and institutions. We believe this in the U.S., too, but not for narrow, nationalistic, sel‹sh purposes only, but also because we believe that our nation has become a symbol of the possibilities of freedom and the potentiality for justice. The existence of our nation as a nation is tied to the realization of high goals for all of humanity. Our nationalism is not inconsistent with internationalism.73 The United States had to settle for in›uencing the world passively, by setting an example, if it wanted to maintain its integrity. When it came to foreign people, a restrictive sovereignty rather than an expansive hegemony began to de‹ne American interests and obliga-
208
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
tions. What was once an interest, even a duty, became charity—and “as mortals, we live in a world of limits—and, tragically, that must include limits to our charity.”74 Accepting Cuban refugees, for example, was a luxury the United States could no longer afford. Robin Beard argued that “when Fidel Castro can decide to dump with impunity tens of thousands of undesirables on us, our national sovereignty is violated. Secure borders are an integral part of sovereignty.”75 Whereas the United States had looked on the world from a position of security, the world now seemed to loom up at it. “If the United States,” said Jennings Randolph, “is to continue to preserve a stable economic and political sovereignty in the face of the multitudes yearning for freedom and opportunity, we must temper our compassion and generosity.”76 Robert Garcia and Jesse Helms, very different men, agreed about the centrality of immigration control to the question of American sovereignty. While Garcia observed that “control over the entry of noncitizens is key to how we determine our national sovereignty,”77 Helms argued that “the fundamental question before us is the preservation and enforcement of our sovereignty.”78 Declining hegemony meant that the United States could no longer think only of what type of sovereignty it wanted, but had to consider how to preserve some type at all. Alan Simpson was the most blunt and speci‹c. Outraged about a Wall Street Journal editorial that claimed that he proposed to close the borders, Simpson outlined what open immigration would mean. “They [the Wall Street Journal] want a ‹ve-word constitutional amendment that says, ‘there shall be open borders.’ . . . Where that would lead us would be to a defenseless America without any security of its borders whatsoever. Absolutely stupid. . . . And the Civil War arose from the fact that some people wanted cheap, subservient labor.”79 When the United States could control the very geoeconomic and political structures that led immigrants to seek a place in the United States, explicit laws were important as symbolic statements revealing America’s sincere belief in the norms it espoused. When it thought it could no longer control them, laws became practically necessary. If sovereignty was the goal, lack of control was the problem. Legislators identi‹ed three problems that were logically, sequentially related. The ‹rst was de‹nitional. Regardless of how many immigrants admitted, or whom it admitted, the government must be in control of admissions. It, not the immigrants and certainly not foreign governments, had to dictate the who, when, and why of immigration. As Edward Kennedy argued, to consider only its citizens’ welfare was in fact the duty of every government: We are entitled as private individuals to make any sacri‹ces of our own interest that we may wish—for example out of compassion or in
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
209
order to satisfy our own moral beliefs. However, the primary obligation of government, indeed the very reason for its existence—and justi‹cation for its power—is to promote the national interest; that is the long-term well-being of the majority of the nation’s citizens and their descendants.80 The second problem had to do with numbers. Beyond a certain point, American institutions would not be able to handle immigrants even if Congress did retain control over entry. Finally, there was a problem with who could enter. Control was crucial. Without it, even were there no immigration, the country could not be considered sovereign. Alan Simpson used this argument to whip up congressional enthusiasm and attention: “Immigration to the United States is out of control and it is so perceived at all levels of government by the American people—indeed by people all over this world. I deeply feel that uncontrolled immigration is one of the greatest threats to the future of this Nation, to American values, traditions, institutions, to our public culture, and to our way of life.”81 The fact of control, not policy speci‹cs, Simpson argued was the central issue. “Because of this bill, we will know for the ‹rst time exactly how many immigrants will arrive in the United States in the coming year.”82 Control de‹nitely involved assuring that the U.S. government and not other governments determined who could become a citizen. Even a standing refugee policy was insuf‹cient, since “‘Baby Doc’ Duvalier and Fidel Castro and all the other despots in the world . . . can send to our shores any number of people at any time and decide who they will be.”83 Control also meant assuring that the government, not individuals—even if those individuals were citizens—decided who was eligible. If Congress were truly to have control, everyone, including relatives, had to be subjected to government limits. “If this Nation is to achieve true control over its immigration,” argued Eldon Rudd, “all entrants should fall under the annual ceiling.”84 Together, this meant that the government would be in a “position in which we, not other governments, or the people of other nations, control immigration to this country.”85 Legislators were aware of what scholars would call the theoretical implications of their choice. To choose control was to choose sovereignty. Anything less meant its abandonment. Among others, George Huddleston re›ected: Immigration presents us with one of the most basic of all social and legal problems: Is the concept of the nation-state legitimate? Behind all of the debates over immigration, there is that basic philosophical
210
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
and moral question. Is it legitimate for there to be a United States, for this country to have citizens and to de‹ne all other people in the world as noncitizens? Is it fair and right for the United States to prevent any person in the world from living here? [The country must say yes.] If we do not [agree], then we shall have to consider a revolution in the world order.86 Such a defense of particularism was necessary to justify sovereignty. The interdependence that the United States had helped to establish meant that sovereignty required more than a theoretical defense. The country had to construct the international-legal equivalent of a parachute. Immigrants presented two other closely related practical challenges to American sovereignty, one quantitative and the other qualitative. The ‹rst problem was too many people. The United States could not accept many people, in this view, even legal immigrants, without taking something away from citizens. Lloyd Bentsen of Texas noted that “we are the only nation that has virtually abdicated control of our borders and is unable to account for millions of aliens—legal and illegal—living, studying, and working in this country.”87 Similarly, Eldon Rudd of Arizona argued, “During the past two decades, immigration has increased to the point where we have lost virtually all control over our borders.”88 This was not a concern only in the Mexican border states. A Pennsylvanian contended in this context that “the Federal Government of the United States, or any Federal Government, any central government anywhere in the world, has as its primary responsibility the securing of its borders. . . . That just goes without saying, to preserve national unity, national identity, national cohesiveness, the borders must be secure.”89 And one of reform’s leading proponents, Romano Mazzoli, was from Kentucky: “The authority of Congress—indeed, its responsibility—to regulate immigration derives from a source even higher than the Constitution. . . . For Congress to ignore its responsibility in this area by failing to consider and enact immigration reform and control legislation is to ignore the very sovereignty upon which our Nation is based.”90 Sovereignty depended on control. The second problem involved the kind of people who had immigrated. Many immigrants were “immigrants” literally but not legally. Illegal immigration presented several problems. First, a sovereign country should at a minimum be able to stop persons from entering its territory without its consent. James Scheuer worried “that given the hemorrhaging that is occurring on our southern border, one could question our Nation’s sovereignty.”91 Second, numbers added up, and illegal immigrants’ numbers were especially hard to control. Like legal immigrants, illegal or
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
211
undocumented aliens92 added to the population and therefore contributed to all of the problems as well as all of the bene‹ts of citizens. Third, illegals were particularly bad for communities precisely because they were illegal. Their presence demonstrated that they were willing to break the law; in fact, that had been their ‹rst act. Bob Graham of Florida declared that “we must meet ›agrant disregard for our laws and the integrity of our borders with all the power and purpose of a great nation. . . . Our national security is being challenged. It is time we take control of access to our own, sovereign territory.93 Finally, the government increasingly found itself evaluated—as functionalists and even T. H. Marshall had argued it would—in terms of how well it provided for its citizens’ material well-being. Mack Mattingly reminded representatives that “the United States as a sovereign nation must ensure the well-being of its people.”94 Americans simultaneously believed in the free market and held the government directly responsible for increases in unemployment, in›ation, mortgage rates, and food prices. To have a national interest, obviously one ‹rst had to have a nation. Such discussions of sovereignty helped legally to ground a formal consideration of American national interests, but they could not help in determining what the content of those interests should be. A new appreciation of foreign economic interests and economic threats began in the 1980s to infuse references to America’s national interest. “By placing more emphasis on the skills and qualities that independent immigrants possess, immigration policy will be more closely coordinated with the national interest,” which interest was, in Alan Simpson’s view, to improve the country’s relative place. Rather than explain the connection, legislators took it for granted. For example, “our legal immigration system is not now serving the national interest as well as it should or could. Today, more than 90 percent—this is a rather startling ‹gure—of all immigrants enter this country without any screening at all of their impact on the U.S. labor market and without any determination of what our labor needs are,”95 or “I strongly believe that one of the objectives of our immigration policy should be to increase the number of immigrants who would come into this country because of greater skills. This is in our national interest.”96 In no other context was the national interest regarding immigrants mentioned. It was no longer discussed in ideological or cultural or military terms. Economic competition de‹ned, by implication, America’s core national interest regarding foreigners. To strengthen and then protect Americans’ economic position became the government’s central purpose. Once the framework for assessing costs and bene‹ts was settled, the camps divided predictably and
212
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
neatly. Those who believed that immigrants drained resources struggled against those who claimed that they contributed far more than they took. At one level, this was an empirical question. Presumably, it had a right answer that someone, possibly the Congressional Research Service or the General Accounting Of‹ce, could discover. At another level, the question was fundamental and philosophical—and the same. What legitimate value did borders serve? The ‹rst, cheap, answer was that always given, protecting Americans. The harder answer had to de‹ne both “American” and “protection.” Neither was easy. To this end, American society had to accomplish two things. First, it had to determine who Americans were, who was in the population for which the government was economically responsible. Next it had to assure that Americans were connected to international economic structures in which they could succeed, both in absolute and in relative terms. That speci‹cally meant encouraging employers and the highly skilled to immigrate. The ‹rst task, though, was to de‹ne the population that would serve as the denominator in calculations of gain and loss. Efforts to clarify the boundary separating citizen from noncitizen began ‹rst. They centered on the task of pushing the people who lived in a legal grey area either toward citizenship or toward deportation.
Reason: Helping or Eliminating the Underclass
Unlike many other countries, the United States never accorded legitimacy to a common class: persons who remained inde‹nitely in a political community, were subject to its laws and received its bene‹ts, but could not become citizens. Such a “second-class citizenry,”97 de‹ned variously as “alienated people who are neither ‹sh nor fowl,”98 as those “who are here under no particular identity,”99 and as “the Indian equivalent of the Untouchables,”100 was un-American. It was not the economic or demographic characteristics of this group but its indeterminate status that nagged at the legislators. A person either was a citizen—was born or naturalized in the United States, was protected by the U.S. Constitution, and was obligated to serve the government when it called—or was not. If not, constitutional protections did not apply. For the ‹rst time, American society grappled with applicants who ‹t neither of the traditional categories. Laws imagined two types of persons: citizens born on U.S. territory and aliens born elsewhere who lived in that same elsewhere while they applied for entry. In both cases, the government granted citizenship according to who a person was. In deciding what to do with the illegals, however, the government had
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
213
to consider what a person had to do to earn citizenship. To this date, the only persons who had been given citizenship in exchange for their efforts were those who had fought with the U.S. military in its major wars. The only intermediate category that the government recognized was the one that described persons moving briskly between these two stations. Before applying to naturalize, an immigrant had to maintain residence in the United States for a period of years, most commonly ‹ve. During this time, he or she would be given permanent residence status. An alien could maintain this status inde‹nitely, but permanent residents, like Cub Scouts, probationers, and assistant professors, were expected to retain this status for only a few years. It was something one grew out of. The category was analytically temporary largely because it was morally suspect. The worst one could say about undocumented aliens was that they were illegal, unchosen, and hence prone to break other laws; the best one could say about them was that they constituted an underclass subject to economic and political exploitation without even recourse to the vote. Employers were alleged to use illegals’ fear to exploit them and to have them deported before they were paid.101 Labor leader Lane Kirkland argued that “unless that [amnesty] is done, we will as a society be contributing to the continuing victimization of an underclass, made up of those whose fear of deportation makes them vulnerable to exploitation by unscrupulous employers and who are unable to protect themselves or to call upon the government for protection.”102 No one did or could argue that retaining such a class was in the public interest. Efforts to clarify the citizenship status of America’s population therefore focused on eliminating this group. Debate centered on whether to legalize (technically termed “adjustment of status”) or to deport the undocumented. Those advocating legalization, popularly known as “amnesty,” argued that these residents had earned civic recognition by contributing their labor, taxes, and respect for many years to an unresponsive country. Those advocating deportation contended that the residents had earned nothing, since they were unwanted, and had devalued American citizenship by their very presence. Everyone agreed that social control over America’s political borders was at issue. They disagreed about who had been taking advantage of whom. Consensus about the moral impossibility of allowing the illegal population to maintain itself inde‹nitely laid dormant until concerns about declining hegemony, crystallized by ‹scal and balance of payments de‹cits, grabbed the national agenda. Germany, already a feared competitor, was having dif‹culty ridding itself of its guest workers; Japan, doing better than Germany, had wisely not recruited any. “We were stunned,” said Alan Simpson, “at the situation that has occurred in Germany and
214
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
France with regard to temporary guest workers—the ‘Gastarbeiter’ program in Germany.”103 Americans viewed the underclass as a burden. Shedding it would free it to compete with more strength. But although economic change pushed the illegal immigration issue to the front of the congressional agenda, it was not simply in economic terms that Americans viewed the issue. Republicans and Democrats, Southerners, Midwesterners, and Easterners alike insisted that such an intermediate category was morally untenable. Lawton Chiles worried that “illegal aliens exist as a subclass in our society. They are beyond the obligations and protections of our laws,”104 while Charles Grassley viewed them as a “fugitive underclass, afraid to claim even the most basic of human rights.” The problem for them both was that “the existence of such a class of underground residents undermines the fabric of our democratic society.”105 The strength of the consensus against accepting an intermediate class can be measured by the anger that administration proposals of both parties elicited. As a step toward incorporating illegals into American political life, Carter suggested granting illegals permanent resident status. Shocked opponents declared that “for the ‹rst time in American history, an American President is attempting to create a new class of resident in this country.”106 A contrary proposal offered by the Reagan administration would have had these aliens pay taxes but receive no bene‹ts. This, too, was decried as the “establishment of an entire underclass.”107 Somehow, the country had to clarify who was in and who out without allowing a category in between. Reasons to incorporate the illegals into American political life drew on the belief that de jure membership ought to re›ect de facto membership. Participation in communal life, whether invited or not, created a presumption in favor of inclusion. This view drew, usually implicitly, on Locke’s suggestion that those subject to a country’s laws ought to have a voice in its affairs. Labor leaders such as Lane Kirkland argued for legalization’s practical and moral bene‹ts. By eliminating fear, amnesty would make exploiting undocumented workers harder. This would aid all workers.108 Others pointed out that legalization would produce taxpayers.109 Ron Dellums of California viewed the problem as both moral and practical: I would like to suggest that the legalization of the exploited subclass of undocumented workers is terribly important not only to those who would be allowed permanent residence, but for the Nation as a whole. We cannot, practically or morally, embark upon a massive and expensive effort to deport millions of people. We cannot continue to have an underground society whose people are forced to live in the
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
215
shadow of the law. And we cannot afford to have our society continually polarized into ethnic groups who are continually harassed by ethnic groups who, on the one hand, resent them, and on the other hand exploit their underclass status.110 In his view, the moral problem was one of debt to the alien. Detractors took the opposite position. Amnesty would not solve the practical problem—“To say that we are solving the problem of illegal immigration by declaring illegals legal is the exact equivalent of curing poverty by declaring poor people rich”111—nor would it erase the moral debt, which was to American citizens. Attorney General William French Smith unsurprisingly viewed the country’s dilemma in law-and-order terms, asserting that “this great nation [cannot] long tolerate the existence of a hidden foreign people within our borders, living apart from American laws.”112 Jesse Helms argued that this practical problem had a moral spin. “Amnesty also creates a moral problem in that it rewards law-breakers.”113 Summing up this position, Harold Daub mentioned that “there are a lot of people in this country who feel that amnesty in blanket terms without some rule attached to it, carte blanche, cheapens or devalues or shrinks, somehow just erodes the value of American citizenship.”114 Logically, it seems that one should decide who is to be protected before determining what they are to be protected from, but in practice these decisions were made together. In the 1980s, citing the Japanese or Germans as the threat implied that workers in manufacturing were to be protected; citing illegals as the threat implied citizens were to be protected; citing resource depletion as the threat implied that the world’s people were all to be saved from themselves. These diagnoses shared a theme. The United States had entered what academic Wayne Cornelius called “an era of limits,” in which the bottom of every barrel seemed visible. Jobs, welfare, fresh air, and compassion were all in ‹nite supply. Jobs, supposed to be created, not removed, by increases in employment, seemed to disappear. Every job taken by an alien was not only lost to an American, many believed, but likely to an underprivileged American. John Conyers, representing industry-oriented and largely black Detroit, asked: “Should we spend them [dollars] on Vietnamese ‘refugees’ or should we spend them on Detroit ‘refugees’?”115 For this reason, since the secretary of labor had to certify job shortages before aliens could ‹ll them, Frank Lautenberg proposed giving American workers this information before approving immigration.116 Such unemployment alone was dif‹cult enough to eliminate, but compounding it were shrinking welfare reserves. Job loss and welfare costs interacted to amplify the effect of each, “adding to our tax burden and bleeding the Nation’s economy.”117 Jack
216
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
McDonald argued, typically if contradictorily, that aliens “either create new ghettoes or go on welfare—when they are not taking jobs from needy citizens and driving them on welfare.”118 Aliens were even characterized as “preying on our schoolchildren by stealing their lunch money.”119 Proposals to con‹ne bene‹ts to legally admitted immigrants, though at least partly unconstitutional, were also popular.120 Entitlements were bad enough, warned George Huddleston, without setting up for illegal aliens “one of the greatest entitlement programs in the history of this country.”121 One could simply believe that aid would be useless. “Our country is full of people. If we bring in more, it will not so much improve the status of immigrants as it will lower the living standards of our own working people to the level of those in the world’s poor countries.”122 In a zero-sum world, trying to improve the lot of one group was impossible without harming that of another. “We cannot be so generous that we stretch our own scarce resources to the breaking point and diminish the quality of American life for all.”123 Many legislators looked back nostalgically on the days when, they imagined, such dif‹cult choices did not have to be made. Strom Thurmond, for example, looked back to “a time when this Nation could welcome millions of newcomers without jeopardizing the national interest.”124 America was once open to those with initiative, they said, but must now be shut. The country had recently been faced with vast numbers of such newcomers, which “are staggering and their economic consequences suffocating to what this goose that lays the golden egg must offer to those poor, those tired, those huddled masses yearning to breathe free.”125 America was also once geographically open, but must now be shut: “We are no longer the frontier America we once were, with vast undeveloped resources and wide open spaces.”126 In its ‹nal report, the commission charged by the Carter administration with a review of immigration policy concluded: If it is a truism to say that the United States is a nation of immigrants, it is also a truism that it is one no longer, nor can it become a land of unlimited immigration. As important as immigration has been and remains to our country, it is no longer possible to say as George Washington did that we welcome all of the oppressed of the world, or as did the poet, Emma Lazarus, that we should take all of the huddled masses yearning to be free.127 Scarcity explained the country’s impending break with what it viewed as its traditional generosity toward immigrants. Cosmopolitanism could lead to the same place as localism. In a zero-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
217
sum world, although Americans would be harmed, at least someone would be helped. Someone would ‹nd a job, get welfare, receive an education. To many, however, the world was even less benign. It was in America’s and the world’s interest, in fact, to reduce the American population. Americans consumed more resources and emitted more pollution than any other country. About 5 percent of the world’s population, Americans consumed a third of the world’s petroleum. In the 1970s, a movement for zero population growth had hoped to convince Americans that they must at a minimum halt population increases. By the 1980s, with fertility at below replacement levels, population control meant not fertility reduction but immigration restriction. “We have done a good job in birth control,” felt Lawton Chiles, “and in getting our population down. We are about a zero population. It is not going to mean anything if we take all of the problems of everybody else in the world on our shoulders, and that is the way it appears to be headed.”128 Americans, went a slightly different argument, were almost disgusting in their use of world resources. The least they could do was to prevent others from imitating their pattern, and the easiest way to do that was to keep them from entering the country. B. F. Sisk maintained: An additional 75 million people living in this country, using energy at an average U.S. consumption level (1972), is the equivalent of adding 4.65 billion people living at an Indian standard of living (expressed in terms of per capita energy consumption). This additional resource consumption—to say nothing of the needed timber, food, minerals, water, highways, homes, automobiles, employment, health care, et cetera, will dramatically increase pollution, deplete our forests, erode our soil and land, dwindle our fossil fuels, crowd our overburdened cities and escalate our taxes.129 Robert Dole, using the same strategy, reached complementary conclusions: “Assuming an immigrant on the average consumes as much energy as an American, the 4.5 million legal immigrants who came here in the 1970s require energy equivalent to half the oil production of the Alaska pipeline.”130 Environmentalists, often associated with left-liberal causes, ought in this view to shun proposals to liberalize immigration ceilings. “We will never have environmental stability in this country as long as our population grows that fast, because the demands on our dwindling supply of open land and natural resources are intensi‹ed.”131 Replying to critics, George Huddleston said, “As for the assertion that reasonable restraint would be a repudiation of the inscription on the Statue of Liberty—which, incidentally, were the words of a French poet and not a reasoned policy
218
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
developed by the Congress or the people of the United States—I believe that reason must be applied here also.”132 In 1884, he said, there had been no energy crisis. Perhaps the strongest measure of the hold that this framework had on discussions of immigration policy is the extent to which opponents shared its assumptions and engaged in debate within its narrow terms. When one charged that illegal aliens received refunds without paying taxes in the ‹rst place,133 others responded that aliens paid more in taxes than they consumed.134 A proposal to give high-immigration areas more in federal dollars to help them pay for social programs was countered by the argument that the areas ought to be paying the federal government: immigrants gave these areas more than they took.135 A complementary indicator is the scarcity of arguments such as the following, offered by Missourian Durward Hall. Such a clear exposition of homogeneity’s value would have been the norm only a few decades earlier: I do not doubt that many of the new immigrants will make good citizens. Good citizenship does not necessarily depend upon the color of a man’s skin. But, there is no evidence to justify an optimistic conclusion that it will inevitably bene‹t this Nation for these people of alien cultures to come here. It is their ‘problems’ and ‘concepts,’ which have kept their nations of origin from being great countries, with bene‹ts of liberty and prosperity for their citizens. Speci‹cally, I wonder just how this Nation bene‹ts from a decline of 54.3 percent in immigration from Northern and Western Europe while we have an increase of 442.6 percent from Hong Kong, 247.4 percent from China, 1,637.8 percent from India, 896.9 percent from the Philippines, 718.3 percent from Jamaica, and 1,415.5 percent from Trinidad and Tobago?136 A third measure of the hold that economic standards had on interpretations of American public interest is the degree to which people wishing to rely on old arguments had to make explicit their rejection of the old symbolism and the adoption of the new. Preferences for those who had a facility with the English language are a case in point. A couple of times proponents of an English-language preference echoed earlier arguments, as did S. I. Hayakawa when he said, “Language is a unifying instrument which binds people together. When people speak one language they become as one, they become a society.”137 So unacceptable had an argument in favor of cultural homogeneity become, and so prevalent had become economic criteria, that Edward Kennedy and Alan Simpson, cosponsors of the 1980s immigration reforms, enacted on several occa-
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
219
sions a stylized dialogue in which one would question preferences for English speakers and the other, usually Simpson, would explain that English was (1) a minor preference, that (2) had value because knowledge of the common language makes it easier to be a productive employee.138 They publicly shunned other reasons. Others went further, distancing themselves from old points of view by ridiculing arguments in their favor. Racial and cultural homogeneity were favorite targets. A few years after Congress rescinded the racial limits of McCarran-Walter, John Dow asserted that “having such a diversity assures that our country will consist of openminded people rather than those who are grounded in a narrow parochialism of centuries of living together without the introduction of new blood.”139 From multiculturalism came the country’s strength. Those who disagreed, ‹nally, took issue not with the measuring stick used but with the measure taken. Herman Badillo and others argued that “the problems of unemployment and economic dislocation will not be solved by pitting American-born workers against the foreign-born,” but by making hard choices about how opportunity and resources would be distributed within the American population.140 Patricia Schroeder similarly took issue with what she saw as scapegoating. Accepting that the severe economic competition the United States faced was its central challenge, she pointed out that the size of America’s foreign-born population was unlikely to matter one way or another. In the debate, contestants had taken for granted that the United States had the highest proportion of foreign-born compared to other countries because it had the highest number of immigrants annually. The United States also, though, had a population much higher than that of many host countries. According to a study Schroeder had requested, foreign-born accounted for a much higher proportion of populations elsewhere. While the United States was in the 5 to 9 percent range, many smaller countries contained as high as 70 percent aliens. Countries that the United States might consider peers were also higher, with Australia near 25 percent, Canada and Switzerland at 18 percent, and France at 13 percent. The list, she said, could go on.141 To be effective, decisions about who was out had to be complemented by decisions about who was in. Simply to clarify the citizen population would be to reassert sovereign control over borders without changing those borders’ purpose. Since expatriating and deporting deadwood citizens was unconstitutional, policy focusing only on American residents would not be suf‹cient. To make the borders effective in a struggle that was primarily economic, policy toward new immigrants also had to change. Immigration policy could help to improve America’s ability to export.
220
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
At issue in this debate was how the government should think about the future of American leadership. If one took for granted that American competitiveness and the era of its hegemony were closing, as most but not all did, then the country had three options. It could ‹ght to maintain its position as world leader, not only aggressively championing the norms and institutions that had secured its lead, but also striving to reverse its balance of payments, manufacturing, and ‹scal problems. Or it could try to protect itself from these institutions. When the United States had bene‹ted from the openness that these institutions required more than had other countries, the institutions were useful to it, but once others’ gains and its own became equal, the openness only produced vulnerability. A third option lay between these. The country could strengthen the international institutions that served its interests but allow others to bene‹t relatively more from them. It could choose to use the postwar “regimes” as a parachute. Which type of immigration policy the government would choose depended on which image of its future it decided to pursue. Its past choices affected its current possibilities. Just as the beggarthy-neighbor policies of the 1930s haunted those charged with designing industrial and trade policies to boost the United States out of its economic doldrums, so did the Quota Acts haunt legislators trying to fashion an immigration policy capable of limiting the population to which the government was economically accountable. By institutionalizing the lessons they drew from the Depression, postwar economic policy advisers changed firms’ interests as well as their beliefs about effective and legitimate trade policy, thus making protectionism far less likely a solution when similar dif‹culties arose in the future.142 A parallel openness had not been institutionalized in American immigration policy; in fact, Congress had extended regulatory control steadily until the only group that remained numerically unrestricted was close relatives. The liberalism embedded in immigration policy was instead that of barring discrimination among persons on account of ascriptive characteristics such as race or sex, or, increasingly, homosexuality or ideology. Liberal trade policies encouraged the free ›ow of goods across boundaries, but expected that consumers could discriminate among the goods according to their tastes. Liberal immigration policies allowed regulation at the border but disallowed discrimination among the people who entered. Whereas debate from the turn of the century to the mid-1950s had pitted a closed, protectionist, and xenophobic nationalism against a universalistic, utopian internationalism, that in the 1980s had adapted to the realities and contradictions of policy practice. It then became possible, even common, to say that “our nationalism is not inconsistent with internationalism. . . . As a nation, we cannot survive without international cooperation.”143
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
221
If the country’s national interest had become economic rather than ideological, this change had taken place within the context of a continuing commitment to liberal international institutions.144 These institutions had served American interests by securing agreement on a particular set of rules about conducting business and on a body of norms about legitimate and illegitimate goals and means of change.145 The American interest in these institutions had if anything grown stronger as the unilateral enforcement of its wishes became a less credible alternative. Regarding immigration policy, as well as other policies negotiating America’s foreign relationships, U.S. legislators judged their choice in terms of its consequences for American authority. For example, in 1970 Peter Rodino argued in terms of American ideological authority: “The position of the United States as a world leader demands that we, with other countries of the free world, be in a position to offer asylum to the oppressed.”146 But ‹ve years later, Jack Kemp warned that “few things, if any to me, could more dramatically illustrate the decline of a great nation and its people than the adoption of such a [restrictionist] point of view.”147 Later, Robert Garcia described what he considered an illiberal proposal as “an extraordinary program which gives the American public the impression that we are in a state of war with the rest of the world.”148 Charles Percy, equating an American-enforced liberal immigration regime with American hegemony, argued that “large refugee populations threaten the stability of countries of ‹rst asylum . . . [so an] amendment which combines immigrants and refugees under one ceiling would undermine our position of leadership in the international community.”149 By the late 1980s, a policy’s supposed effects on declining hegemony was commonly used as evidence in support of one or another position. In 1989, for example, Douglas Bereuter argued that preferences for investors were unfair and illiberal. “If the other body has its way, this Nation will clearly be forced to reconsider its status as leader of the free world.”150 Who quali‹ed as an American and what constituted legitimate protection could not be decided in the abstract. Exactly whom those decisions would affect, and how, in›uenced the determination. In the past, Congress had not had to consider the politics of enforcement as it did in the 1980s. Previous changes in immigration policy had altered the way that the government selected one set of foreigners, how it divided one alien from another alien. Proposals to grant amnesty to illegal aliens and then presumably to deport those unquali‹ed involved separating aliens from Americans inside the United States. This had been done once before, during World War II, when Japanese Americans, both citizens and noncitizens, had been interned. Although the government had reversed its order to incarcerate citizens, it had not offered those it released opportunities
222
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
equivalent to those available to the white population. Japanese Americans, like black citizens, faced legal as well as extralegal discrimination. The obvious, ef‹cient way to distinguish among American residents, identity cards, was impossible because of privacy concerns. In response, George Mitchell asked whether “we are contemplating a pass card system similar to that as exists in South Africa?”151 The remaining option, one which made most legislators queasy, was demanding identi‹cation and proof of citizenship from those citizens who INS of‹cials had some reason to suspect were foreign. This meant, in effect, frisking farmworkers, those with an accent, and those who looked non-Anglo. Abraham Kazen of Texas spelled out what this meant: “No blond white American faces the requirement of proving his citizenship when he applies for work, but under this legislation the Latin, the Oriental, the black and brown people of the Mediterranean and Caribbean lands would have to be challenged by every potential employer.”152 If these were the means, then the end, separating citizen from noncitizen clearly, many considered not worth pursuing. For all the costs the legislators thought they faced from having “leaking borders,” they were small compared to those they would incur by rounding up Hispanics. In 1982, these fears seemed to be realized. During INS “Operation Jobs,” its term for anti-illegal alien raids in the Southwest, the Service detained citizens for being brown.153 Rumors ›ew that American citizens had been taken to Mexico and abandoned because they were unable immediately to prove that they were born in the United States. Patricia Schroeder charged that “During Operation Jobs, . . . they did not ‹nd any aliens at all. . . . 99.3 percent of the people they picked up were from Latin America or the Caribbean; that is black or Hispanic.”154 Not all of the uproar came from those representing southern and western states. Cardiss Collins of Illinois charged, as did others, that the checks were racially motivated. “I seriously doubt that such fervor against undocumented workers would be stirred if they were ›eeing dictatorships and failing economies in Western Europe rather than in Latin America, the Caribbean, and Southeast Asia.”155 Henry Gonzalez summed up this position by noting that “the Statue [of Liberty] never looks south.”156 Table 9 outlines the proposals that were made for revising immigration policy.
Immigration Reform and Control Act
The idea of sanctioning those who employed illegal aliens solved this dilemma by providing a way to determine legality without discriminating among citizens. Edward Kennedy wanted sanctions to fall on employers,
TABLE 9.
The Immigration Act of 1990 Compared to the Laws and Proposals It Replaced
Category National level Immigrant relatives Family preferences Preference 1b Preference 2 Preference 4 Preference 5 Total family Independent Special Preference 3 Preference 6 Employment investors Selected Total independent Diversity Total immigrants aThis
Current Law
Actual 1987
KennedySimpson 1988
SimonKennedy 1989
Helms Amendment
none no limit
500,000 218,500
590,000 220,500a
600,000 220,000
600,000 220,000
54,000 70,200 27,000 64,800 216,000
11,382 110,758 20,703 68,966 211,809
33,000 143,000 22,000 22,000 440,000
24,200 148,000 23,000 64,800 480,000
14,400 136,800 24,000 64,800 460,000
no limit 27,000 27,000 0 0 54,000
3646 26,921 26,952 35 n/a 57,554
6000 27,600 27,600 4,800 54,000 120,000
6,000 27,600 27,600 4,800 54,000 120,000
4,200 46,200 46,200 2,800 40,600 140,000
590,000
600,000
600,000
and the 220,000 in the next column are estimated annual levels of a still-unlimited category. 1: Unmarried adult sons and daughters of citizens; 2: spouses and children of permanent residents; 3: persons in the professions and those of exceptional ability; 4: married sons and daughters of citizens; 5: never-married brothers and sisters of citizens; 6: skilled workers for which there is a demonstrated need; special. bPreference
Immigration Act of 1990
480,000
140,000 55,000 675,000
224
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
not on aliens, to prevent discrimination.157 As early as 1972, Peter Rodino offered a bill to ‹ne employers of illegal aliens $1,000,158 and in 1977 Don Bonker of Washington had suggested printing nonforgeable social security cards.159 He said that “rather than invest in costly and draconian measures to make a Berlin Wall out of our borders, as some suggest, or harass American citizens of foreign extraction, we must focus attention on the root cause of the illegal alien problem—the employment of illegal aliens in the United States.”160 Finally, an amendment to have all employers ‹ll out a two-identi‹cation af‹davit passed the House by 321 to 97, with 15 not voting.161 Peter Rodino, an advocate of reform, declared that “in my judgment, employer sanctions are essential if this country is to regain control of its borders. Indeed, it is our sovereign responsibility to do so.”162 It had to do this, but without violating citizens’ civil rights. Unlike those of earlier periods, votes on immigration reform in the late 1980s broke more along party lines than along regional lines, though this was only true for the House of Representatives. This was true both for the ‹rst votes on the Immigration Reform and Control Act (IRCA), which instituted employer sanctions and amnesty, and for the immigration reform legislation of 1990, which uni‹ed the numerical ceiling and revamped exclusion provisions. Republicans were almost evenly split on IRCA, while Democrats favored it by two to one; by 1990, the divisions had grown, so that three times as many Republicans opposed as favored the legislation, while three times as many Democrats favored as opposed it. The arguments made for and against these pieces of legislation resonated more closely with those generally associated with one or another political party than had arguments forwarded in the past. Economic worries were central to the debate and are central to explaining why parties should suddenly matter. The legislators agreed that American power worldwide was in danger and that the threat could be met by manipulating immigration policy. When the threat had been racial or ideological, neither party had a prepackaged solution to the problem or was identi‹ed as being particularly strong on the issue. At the turn of the century, neither Republicans nor Democrats were “whiter” than the other; at midcentury, neither was more anticommunist than the other. Each had to create a response from fairly raw materials. Economic programs, though, both had in abundance. They were waiting for just such a crisis to be used. The Republicans advocated open migration of labor and capital to stimulate the economy; the Democrats sought retraining and investment garnered from the surplus that the wealthiest owned. More Democrats than Republicans, therefore, wished to halt the employment of illegal aliens and to cap the aggregate number of immigrants that the country would annually accept. Figure 9 outlines the arguments that were made preceding the 1980s reforms.
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
225
Economic Competition with Japan and Germany ⇓ Public Interest Argument
Causal Argument
Policy Argument
Identification passes violate citizens' rights to privacy and mimic totalitarian states
Liberal democracy demands respect for the individual
The country must not mandate an identification card
Without a universal system, enforcement will be racially discriminatory
Racial discrimination raises political, moral, and practical problems for social stability
Any system to sort illegal from legal immigrants must be universal
Without a more highly skilled work force, the country will lose its comparative advantage in skilled production and will hence decline in power
Maintaining a predominance in power benefits the United States by deterring attack and securing favorable terms of trade
Immigration policy should favor those who will boost productivity, such as investors and highly skilled workers
Without a culturally cohesive population, the country will cease to be a community
Fragmentation will prevent the country from achieving anything economically, politically or culturally
Immigrants must be culturally like Americans
↑ ↑ plausibility
↑
Implementation
Favoring relatives resulted in too large a population of unskilled dependents
↑ efficiency
↑
↓ Ideas about Causation: Racism Causes War Perverse Effects: War with Japan, Depression Fig. 9.
Arguments made preceding the reforms of the 1980s
Party divisions did not emerge as clearly in discussions that involved the goals the country should set as they did in the debate over means. Members of both parties argued against identi‹cation badges or “internal passes,” worried about discriminatory application of IRCA’s enforcement provisions, and believed that the American economy needed to become more competitive if the country was to retain its position of preeminence. Paradoxically, it is because consensus on ends was so extensive that party divisions emerged in these votes. The earlier roll calls had been referenda
226
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
on the goals the United States should pursue, or rather on what the United States should be, a question more fundamental than those for which party functionaries prepared answers. The 1980s votes were not about this because competitiveness was agreed; they were about the means to this end, for which the parties had prepared positions. Party matters in immigration politics to the extent that disagreement centers not on ultimate goals but on means. Party politics have become more important as consensus has grown on the importance to the United States of meeting the challenges the external world presents to American power. In legislators’ minds, two distinct though interrelated tasks faced the United States. First, it needed to clarify its population. Citizens should be inside the country, and aliens outside it. Proposals to sanction employers and others who helped illegal aliens complemented those to give amnesty to those illegally resident for a long enough period that they had become de facto citizens. Legislators did not disagree about the validity of this goal; debate centered on how to achieve it without discriminating against citizens, especially on the basis of race. The second task was to improve the country’s position in the world economy. Expelling illegals was a ‹rst step, as illegal aliens were seen to be taking jobs and welfare bene‹ts that could go to citizens, but it was insuf‹cient. Figure 9 outlines the arguments made about legalization. In need of a more highly skilled labor force, and domestic—not foreign—investment, the country had two broad choices. It could construct an industrial policy guiding labor education and retraining, and investment into manufacturing and basic research. This would involve extensive cooperation from the public sector, across the ideological spectrum. It also would be expensive. Or it could try to attract investors and the highly skilled from abroad, which had the advantage of avoiding all of the social and economic costs of imposing and implementing an industrial policy. Given that Congress came to agree that these were its options, it is unsurprising that it chose to alter immigration policy (table 9 lists the possibilities and the choice). More interesting and signi‹cant is that it arrived at this array of options; that when faced with an external threat to its relative power, it again turned to immigration policy as one attractive avenue of change. Table 10 outlines the changes that the Immigration and Control Act and its successor legislation in 1990 made to the Immigration and Nationality Act. The U.S. Congress passed twin immigration reforms in the late 1980s. The Immigration Reform and Control Act of 1986 (IRCA) focused solely on persons already resident on U.S. territory. Its purpose was to clarify residents’ legal status, dividing them clearly into
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
227
citizen and noncitizen categories. The act allowed an amnesty for undocumented resident aliens who had been continuously present in the United States for some period of years, allowing them to use their residency toward naturalization.163 As Congress saw it, “there are really two thrusts to this bill. . . . One of them is to regain control over those borders. The other one is to prepare expeditious means for handling the procedures for asylum and deportation.”164 While the Immigration and Naturalization Service cleaned house, Congress set about repairing the fence. Legislators envisioned these bills as two stages of the same process. As Theodore Hesburgh, in charge of the Carter administration’s commission on immigration reform, argued, “We had to close the back door on illegal immigration to keep the front door open for legal immigration.”165 The Immigration Act of 1990 thoroughly revised American laws governing criteria for entry and exclusion. For the ‹rst time, all immigrants, regardless of place of birth, reason for emigrating, or relation to a U.S. citizen, became subject to numerical restrictions. The twin reforms followed the pattern established in the ‹rst part of the century by simultaneously extending regulatory control and liberalizing the criteria for exclusion. Congress understood itself to be acting to support, or re-create, American sovereignty. While some viewed this task as straightforward and unproblematic, others saw it as tragic. A liberal state could continue only if it remained a state, remained sovereign, and yet could only remain liberal if it recognized human equality regardless of birthplace. Dale Bumpers worried that the bill “presents us with a con›ict between our normal commitment to human rights, our Judeo-Christian beliefs and ethics, on the one hand, and on the other hand our commitment to the ‹rst law of nature, which is self-preservation.”166 Those enmeshed in the immigration debate saw clearly the tension between the liberalism and the nationalism that they were seeking to forward. Gary Hart, like Bumpers, re›ected that immigration restriction “is an issue which forces us to balance our Nation’s sovereignty—and ability to control the borders—with the role America has played as a haven for the oppressed. It is an issue which forces us to reconcile law enforcement needs with our commitment to civil liberties and civil rights.”167 He saw the tension as between sovereignty and American domestic liberalism. How this tension would be resolved both revealed the country’s values and shaped the country’s future. Edward Kennedy argued this when he said that “what we do on the issue of immigration says a great deal about the kind of society that we are and that we want to become.”168 And opponent George Huddleston observed that “immigration, without ques-
TABLE 10.
Immigration Reform and Control Act and Immigration Act of 1990
Act INA Amendments (Hart-Celler) Immigration and Nationality Act Amendments of October 3, 1965
IRCA Immigration Reform and Control Act of 1986 Immigration Act
Numerical Restrictions
Preferences Categories
Unrestricted (Non-quota) Immigrants
Overall ceiling: 290,000 Method of allocation: 120,000 general cap for the Western Hemisphere; 170,000 cap for the Eastern Hemisphere, with a limit of 20,000 per country per year
•1st: Adult unmarried children of U.S. citizens, 20% •2d: Spouses and unmarried children of resident aliens, 20 percent •3d: Professionals, 10 percent •4th: Married children of U.S. citizens, 10 percent •5th: Brothers and sisters of U.S. citizens, 24 percent •6th: Other needed workers, 10 percent •7th: Conditional (refugees) •Nonpreference: Unused slots from above
Increased from 600 to 5,000 the cap for immigrants from dependencies
•Retired employees of inter- • “Amnesty” for illegally national organizations present aliens resident in the •Countries adversely U.S. since January 1, 1982 affected by the 1965 act
To 1994 Overall ceiling: 700,000
•Family-sponsored immigrants, 71 percent •Employment-based immigrants, 21 percent •Diversity immigrants, 8 percent
Act of November 29, 1990 After 1994 Overall ceiling: 675,000
•Spouses, children, and parents of U.S. citizens •Ministers •Former employees of the U.S. government abroad •Foreign medical graduates
Exclusions •Sexual deviation
Reduced to 9 categories: •Health threats •Criminals •Security risks •Public charge risks •Labor competitors •Illegal entrants •Those without visas •Those ineligible for citizenship •Miscellaneous (polygamy)
IRCA and the 1990 Reforms
229
tion, is one of those rare policies which ultimately impacts upon almost every aspect of our society and economy, and to a large degree determines what kind of country we are.”169 The balance that Congress struck in the late 1980s again sought to liberalize the criteria governing which types of persons might immigrate, while extending national control over not only who, but also how many people might become citizens. Like its legal predecessors, its liberalism was qualitative; its conservatism quantitative. In the decade following the 1990 reforms, Congress discussed, and approved, three dozen bills relating in some way to the Immigration and Nationality Act. Most dealt with a single, and minor, element of the law; for example, P.L. 105-73 was entitled “To Amend the Immigration and Nationality Act to exempt internationally adopted children 10 years of age or younger from the immunization requirement in section 212(a)(1)(A)(ii) of such Act.” Of these many bills, only one received political attention. The “Illegal Immigration Reform and Responsibility Act of 1996” (P.L. 104-208) asked the INS to gather data on visitor entries and exits, to better monitor visa overstays. Business people, customs, and the INS, however, argued that this would tie down resources and back up traffic at the border; in 2001 it was effectively abandoned. As the twentieth century ended, legislators and the American public were largely content with the single, comprehensive limit that had resulted from the century of debate.
CHAPTER 8
Domestic Interests as Explanations
Most explanations for immigration policy, for increasing restrictiveness or for relaxation, focus on the accessible and obvious material interests that legislators and business people hold. Economic interests, such as competition for jobs—presumably good for employers and bad for unions—or welfare bene‹ts, and legislative interests, such as capturing the votes of an ethnic constituency or voting with the party, have been mentioned often as the main, if not only, reasons for policy change. The business community is interested in pro‹ts; therefore, they must lobby for openness when pro‹ts fall. Labor is interested in wage levels; therefore, it must lobby for restriction when unemployment rises. Legislators are interested in reelection; therefore, they must respond primarily to party demands, public opinion about immigrants, or immigrant interest groups. This view pervades attention to immigration policy among journalists, scholars, and talk-show hosts. It is mistaken in the main, although it captures part of the truth. In fact, congressional votes on immigration policy have never divided along party lines or on regional lines, and the times of increasing restrictionism have been times of economic boom in the United States. An examination of the evidence shows that regional politics and economic forces have strongly in›uenced enforcement but have had little effect on policy. During periods of high unemployment, for example, apprehensions and deportations have increased, as have exclusions. Federal policy has not changed during these times. This shows that congressional and public arguments about perceived threat do not shield “real” electoral or economic motives; in fact, they do not even correlate with them. Public opinion is random or reactive, not causal. Domestic elections and economic ups and downs explain change in enforcement, while foreign threat perception explains change in policy.
Partisanship
That legislators usually vote with their party is no secret. Presumably, a representative elected on a particular ticket chose to join that party 230
Domestic Interests as Explanations
231
because he or she shared most of the party’s ideals and concerns, or at least shared them more than he or she shared those of the alternative parties. Legislators who side against their party risk losing general electoral support from the party as well as consideration on future votes. For these reasons, both the timing of immigration policy changes and the outcome of particular votes should be explainable with reference to party. When the party associated with isolationism or protectionism took power, efforts to restrict immigration would start; when the party associated with internationalism or laissez-faire took power, efforts to open immigration would begin. Since legislative agendas are crowded and respond to ad hoc crises, party divisions should be clearer on speci‹c votes than they are on the timing of change. Major efforts to revamp immigration policy began in 1908, 1919, 1941, 1946, 1962, 1978, and 1982.1 In 1908, Republicans had dominated both houses of Congress and had claimed the presidency for thirteen years, or ‹ve Congresses. From 1913 through 1919, this situation was reversed; Democrat Woodrow Wilson led a Democratic Congress. During his tenure in 1917, the ‹rst law to set a numerical limit on immigration passed, over his veto. The timing of neither lends support to the new-party hypothesis. Since Franklin Roosevelt led a Democratic Congress for eight years before restriction of Chinese immigrants became a sustained political (rather than a special administrative) issue, the new-party hypothesis is also uncon‹rmed in that case. Such is also true of the post–World War II debate over immigration, which eventually led to the Displaced Persons Act of 1948 and the McCarran-Walter Act of 1952. From 1947 to 1949, Republicans dominated both houses of Congress, but for sixteen years before this and four years after this, Democratic presidents had led Democratic Congresses. What to do about immigration policy became a central issue in 1946, immediately after World War II—indeed, debate about Europeans as well as Asians started during the war—and continued through the beginning of the Eisenhower presidency. Two episodes, close together in time, lend some support to this hypothesis. When President Carter was elected in 1976, he was able to facilitate legislation desired by the longtime Democratic majority. Whether he or the legislators set the agenda, the constellation of party votes was suddenly in their favor. Less clear but also tending to support this hypothesis is the legislative change following the Carter presidency. Ronald Reagan’s election left a Democratic majority in the House but carried a Republic majority into the Senate for the ‹rst time in three decades. In the case of the beginnings of both Reagan’s and Carter’s presidencies, immigration found its way to the agenda one year after the change of party. Two other episodes lend support to a related idea, though one that
232
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
does not further the null hypothesis. The fact that the ‹rst major changes in general immigration policy happened just after Wilson’s defeat appears to lend support to the idea that while discussion of restriction might be unrelated to partisan rivalries, perhaps action on it is. The discussion of immigration policy that started in 1961 essentially continued the earlier debate that had been abandoned after McCarran-Walter’s passage in 1952, but no action was taken on it until 1965, when the large Democratic majorities took responsibility for passing the major series of Great Society bills. Given the simple evidence presented, the strongest case that can be made for the new-party hypothesis about when immigration ‹nds its way to the legislative agenda is that it might hold from the late 1970s through the 1980s. Party divisions should, in this view, be clearer on individual votes. Once an issue got all the way to a roll call vote, party stands should be clear and party leaders should have made the stakes clear to their members. The evidence from roll call votes on bills to revise immigration policy is mixed. Partisan divisions are sometimes signi‹cant and sometimes not. When they are, however, regional bloc voting proves to be a better predictor than party. As with the new-party hypothesis, the degree to which this rule holds changes over time. Table 11 summarizes the degree to which party differences and regional differences show up in the seventeen major congressional roll call votes on immigration. The votes and descriptive statistics describing them are contained in appendix B. In summary, for each vote was calculated the deviation from what one would expect if region or party were to have no in›uence in determining how legislators voted. For the seventeen major votes on immigration policy, region was signi‹cant in thirteen, party in seven. In fact, region was a stronger predictor than party in every vote up to the three House votes of the 1980s: those to pass IRCA, to af‹rm the IRCA conference report, and to pass the 1990 legislation. Splits along party lines sometimes help to explain the passage of a particular bill. In the 1980s, legislators’ party af‹liations were good predictors of the way that they would vote on bills. Before then, however, region systematically does better at anticipating the way a representative would vote; it also produced a chi-square larger than that for party for all
TABLE 11.
Party and Region in Congressional Voting
Region significant (<.05) Party significant (<.05) Region chi-square higher than party Party chi-square higher than region
13 7 14 3
Domestic Interests as Explanations
233
but three bills: the Refugee Act of 1980, the Immigration Reform and Control Act of 1986, and the Immigration Act of 1990. In each case, the difference was in the House vote and occurred in the later periods. Given this basic evidence, the strongest case that can be made for the hypothesis that partisanship drives voting is that as of the 1950s it became one among other factors, such as region, that help to predict voting, and it appears to be a better predictor for the period of the Reagan administration than for the earlier and later years.
Public Opinion
Systematic polls of American opinion about immigration policy do not exist. Good survey data are gathered at special times, when immigration has become a hot issue. For this reason, the data that are available describe unusual, unrepresentative, and irregular periods. Nevertheless, they might suggest a pattern of variation that corresponds to change in legislative attention to and action on immigration policy. Since data are not available before 1937, public opinion changes cannot help to illuminate early efforts to establish an immigration ceiling. However, in later legislative change, they should clarify the role that public wishes play. By “change in public opinion,” one can mean a change in the proportions of people with one or another conviction or one can mean a qualitative change in the nature of the opinions that people hold. Most of the data is directed solely at quantitative change, and a minority of it asks about speci‹c issues or groups. Sometimes pollsters asked the public about generic immigrants, although they did so when immigration was on the national agenda because it began to come disproportionately from one region of the world. For this reason, an unspoken and unwritten agenda often lurks behind the questions and answers. Responses about particular clusters of immigrants reveal an attitude in which the amount and identity of prospective immigrants are mixed. For example, probably the only famous opinion poll on American immigration policy, taken in early 1938, asked about a group of refugees from Nazi Germany.2 As would later be proven typical, 5 percent of respondents indicated that quotas should be raised, 9 percent did not know, 18 percent believed that the refugees should be admitted but without allowing quotas to be raised, and 68 percent of respondents agreed that “with conditions as they are, we should keep them out.” Later, higher percentages insisted that the country should not allow any additional European refugees to enter.3 Edwin Harwood points out that “Americans are restrictionist mainly on the quantity issue—how many immigrants to accept—rather than on
234
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
the quality issue—which nationalities should be allowed to enter.”4 For example, although when asked how they feel about the general level of immigration, Americans are restrictive, when asked about any individual for whom details are given, for example, a French-Canadian farmer or a young Kenyan businessman, they believe that the individual should be allowed to enter. He also noted that the proportion of Americans who believe that current levels of immigration are too low is always between 4 and 8 percent. What varies is the balance between those who believe that immigration is too high and those who have no opinion.5 American opinion is remarkably constant regardless of when it has been sampled. It is a “variable” that really does not vary. Table 12 displays the results of bottom-line polls conducted by Gallup or the Roper Center. Similar results come from polls about speci‹c crises and speci‹c groups. Americans do distinguish between allies and enemies, although they are on balance still opposed to allowing just anyone in. For example, regarding the Chinese, American allies in World War II, a poll asked: “After the war, would you like to see the number of Chinese allowed to come into this country, be ‹gured on the same basis as for people from European countries, or should the Chinese be barred as at present?” A full 50 percent of the respondents said “barred.” Eleven percent had no opinion, while the remaining 39 said that the Chinese ought to be allowed to come in.6 With respect to Vietnamese refugees resettling in the United States, about 30 percent in each poll approved and 50 percent disapproved.7 A majority of Americans is never in favor of liberalizing immigration ceilings, but that majority does sometimes liberalize its views by shifting to uncertainty. For example, in 1965 as Congress debated the bill that would TABLE 12. Public Opinion About Immigration Levels (percentage of those agreeing) 1953: “In general, do you think the United States is letting too many immigrants come into this country or not enough?” 1965, 1977, 1993, 1995: “Should immigration be kept at its present level, increased, or decreased?” Response Increased Present level Decreased No opinion
1953
1965
1977
1993
1995
13 37 39 11
8 39 33 20
7 37 42 14
6 27 65 2
8 28 62 4
Source: 1953: Roper Center, April 1955; 1965: Gallup Opinion Index (August 1965) 3; 1977: Gallup Opinion Index (June 1977) 143; USGALLUP.422002.R06 July 9–11, 1993; USGALLUP.95JUL7.R25 July 7–15, 1995.
Domestic Interests as Explanations
235
eliminate race and national origin as the basis for admissions, Gallup asked the public whether they would “favor or oppose changing the law so that people would be admitted on the basis of their occupational skills rather than on the basis of the country they come from” and found 51 percent in favor and 32 percent opposed. At the same time, while Congress adjusted preferences to give relatives 80 percent of the available slots, Americans responded 71 to 21 percent that it was “very important” that a new immigrant have occupational skills.8 The evidence makes it dif‹cult to avoid Harwood’s conclusion that public opinion lags behind of‹cial policy.
Interest Groups
Probably the two most widely held convictions of both academic analysts and the public are that immigrant interest groups and unemployment swings drive changes in American immigration policy. The strength of the belief in the in›uence that immigrant groups wield is oddly high given its logical inconsistency. Clearly, a group of immigrants ready to lobby for their compatriots would not be in the country in the ‹rst place unless the country’s policy already allowed their immigration. Cubans cannot lobby in the United States unless they are in the United States, and they cannot be in the United States unless someone besides Cubans has facilitated their entry. More sensible is the position that immigrants, like other interest groups, gel around policies that are put in place for other reasons and defend the policy in which they have acquired an interest. That such immigrant groups are in favor of increasing immigration or defending high immigration levels is a widespread corollary, also assumed. Why is unclear, since immigrant groups are diverse enough to include as many whose interest is in excluding further immigration as who desire to include others. In any case, immigrant interest groups might help to entrench policy once formulated, but they cannot cause initial change.
Unemployment
Unemployment affects all Americans, regardless of their origins. A commonly held view about changes in legal immigration levels holds that increases in unemployment will prompt demands for restriction.9 The assumed causal mechanism is straightforward. Unemployment among citizens rises because alien labor, which requires compensation below the level acceptable to citizens, elbows domestic workers out of their jobs. Increasing the supply of cheap labor decreases the demand for highly paid
236
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
local workers, who are laid off, ‹red, or simply not hired. Growing groups of disgruntled native laborers pressure their legislators to stop immigration. Meanwhile, big business, assumed to bene‹t from the higher pro‹t levels that low-wage workers allow, lobbies for open immigration, especially of those likely not to become unionized. The periodic dominance ‹rst of big business, then of big labor, drives the cycle of openness and restriction in American immigration policy. No evidence supports the hypothesis that unemployment affects immigration policy. At no time did the U.S. Congress revamp immigration policy during or immediately after a period of high unemployment. Congress makes major changes during the country’s best, not worst, years. In the 1920s, while the economy boomed, Congress debated, implemented, then revised two major laws to restrict immigration. It was not during the Depression but during the post–World War II boom that immigration next became a central political issue. When Congress passed the 1965 reforms, unemployment and in›ation were both minimal. Again, during the years of oil shocks and stag›ation, immigration was far from the congressional agenda. Not until the mid-1980s, after the worst recession, did the legislature again turn its attention to the question of restriction. Given this pattern, it should be unsurprising that the unemployment level varies in a direction opposite that predicted by this hypothesis.10 As unemployment goes down, immigration ceilings also tend to go down. Of course, it is possible that the public and legislators respond to other economic indicators. Following the same logic, one might argue that large trade de‹cits, or excessive dependence on imports and exports compared with other countries, might have the same effect on local economic interests, or at least on fears about how those interests will be affected. In a regression to determine the weight of economic indicators generally in explaining policy changes, however, none of the proximate variables that could be supposed to affect public perceptions of scarcity is predictive as this hypothesis expects; unemployment seems to be signi‹cant but in a direction opposite to that predicted. Such is also true of previous immigration; when it is high in the past, it is likely to be high in the future. And the other signi‹cant predictor measures something that no member of the public pays attention to. Table 13 shows the results of a regression equation using the independent variables that have been suggested to predict the U.S. immigration ceiling. The dependent variable is the legal immigration ceiling as a proportion of the American population. Since the hypotheses about possible causes of immigration change all posit that an event at Time X will prompt change in immigration policy at Time X+Y, a time-series regression weighs the possible Xs, unemployment, economic protection, imports and exports
Domestic Interests as Explanations
237
as proportions of U.S. GNP and of world imports and exports, and the number of countries eligible for a quota, and evaluates how well they predict immigration policy at time X+Y. Since the independent variables here achieved their highest signi‹cance when predicting the immigration ceiling three years hence (i.e., Y = 3), those are the results that are listed here. Table 13 shows how well these variables do in predicting the immigration ceiling three years later. Because there was no ceiling until 1921, there are 70 (1921 through 1990), rather than 100 (1891 through 1990) datapoints. The proportion of goods entering the United States as free and dutiable, that is, the overall tariff level, emerges as a helpful and robust predictor. Tariff levels, however, capture two phenomena distinct from public perceptions of pocketbook issues: they indicate the outcome of social struggles over domestic economic protection and show the extent to which foreign goods have been imported in spite of sectoral protection. Tariff levels do affect Americans’ incomes, but they do so by operating through prices and exchange rates. In this context, changes in their levels signify changes in institutional openness, not imminent changes in income. What this regression indicates is that the legal immigration ceiling, as a proportion of the U.S. population, is a reaction to a worsening American economy, whether one de‹nes as central the unemployment of individuals, the degree to which the country’s economic performance depends on trade, or the country’s relative economic vulnerability. It is predictable knowing the level of economic openness that Congress has chosen to secure; one can say that the legal ceiling is low when, three years earlier, actual immigration and unemployment have been low (not high as the counterhypothesis would predict), and tariff levels have been high. Shifts in party majorities, public opinion, and unemployment have been supposed to drive immigration restriction. Yet none does. Most
TABLE 13.
Explaining the Immigration Ceiling (in relation to the U.S. population)
Variable Constant Unemployment Proportion of free and dutiable imports Exports as a proportion of GNP Imports as a proportion of GNP U.S. share of world exports U.S. share of world imports Actual immigration Number of sovereign countries eligible for a quota
Coefficient .001 .0004 –.001 –.0011 –.012 –.000067 –.000126 .000000039 –.000036
Significance .717 .0021 .0108 .9181 .3908 .8497 .8460 .0000 .1453
Note: All of these variables except unemployment and the number of countries are actually residuals of the measure when regressed on time.
238
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
immigration votes are better predicted by region than by party af‹liation, and the timing of when such issues reach the national agenda does not seem to depend on reversals in dominant majorities. The American public is always opposed to increasing immigration, so there is no variation in this independent variable. The variation that does occur is not between those in favor of and those opposed to immigration, but between those who have an opinion and those who have none—and this shift occurs after the topic has hit the media, not before. Unemployment does not precede major efforts to overhaul immigration policy, but the reverse: unemployment declines before Congress attempts to extend its regulatory control. None of these null hypotheses, as stated, can be supported. Given this, the obvious question is why the conviction that material domestic interests propel restriction is so widespread and seemingly unshakable. There are two separate, though compatible, ways of answering this question. The ‹rst is that economic changes drive two processes close to but fundamentally different from immigration policy: administrative enforcement of the immigration statutes (apprehensions on the border) and the level of nonimmigrant arrivals. Migration responds to economic changes, even if immigration policy does not. Exchange rates affect tourism as well as exports, wage rates affect illegal immigration, and unemployment seems to account for many apprehensions and deportations. People come and go with great rapidity when the economy changes, but they are moving apolitically, not achieving and leaving citizenship. The second answer involves the same process discussed earlier, whereby interested parties make their arguments in public terms. Legislators frame their arguments for or against restriction with reference to unemployment, public opinion, and de‹cits. None of these is a plausible driving force since none varies with immigration policy changes or ceilings; they instead are statements of what legislators and the public take to be in the public interest. They are statements of what ought to be valued when contemplating immigration restrictions, not descriptions of what is actually prompting reform. The next section details the connections between nonimmigrant movement and economic changes, while the following one makes a case for interpreting these statements about constituencies and their interests as statements about values.
Economic Fluctuations and Actual Border Activity
Legislators opposed to restricting the number of immigrants have pointed out that immigration has been to a large extent self-regulating. During economic booms, legal immigration rises, nonimmigrant visitors and busi-
Domestic Interests as Explanations
239
ness travelers arrive in higher volumes, and illegal immigration soars. When unemployment and costs rise, immigration drops. Throughout the Depression, for example, not only did immigration drop—in part due to the efforts of the Immigration Service to enforce the “public charge” provision more strictly—but emigration rose, and in 1910, 1915, and then from 1931 to 1936, emigration exceeded immigration, making the ›ow to the United States negative. During the less severe downturns that characterize later years, delay replaces return migration. Prospective employees delay their applications, and family members wait until their relatives become ‹nancially stable before joining them. The year after unemployment rises, immigration declines; the two measures correlate at –.39.11 Illegal immigration is also thought to rise during economic booms, though hard data are scarce. People on business or tourist visas are economic visitors, but those who overstay their visas, or enter without one, edge toward citizenship. The longer they stay in the country and the more ties they establish, the greater their presumptive claim to consideration. Expelling “illegals,” whom the Immigration and Naturalization Service refers to as “undocumented aliens,” reinforces immigrant exclusions. Apprehensions, the prelude to detention and deportation, rise as the American unemployment rate rises.12 Since the interest in immigration declines when the economy sours, presumably attempts to immigrate illegally also decline. For this reason, increases in apprehensions cannot be taken as indicative of increases in attempts to enter illegally, but must be seen as the symptom of redoubled efforts at enforcement. Apprehensions have in fact increased exponentially. So have indicators of economic openness, such as the number of nonimmigrant visitors and reliance on imports, and measures of average wealth. Separately, levels of apprehensions have somewhat paralleled trends in the domestic economy; in the period since World War II, they correlate with the volume of nonimmigrants (.37), import reliance (.80), and per capita GNP (.49), but only weakly with unemployment. Yet when these variables are each held constant, unemployment emerges as a strong predictor. Table 14 describes the result of a time-series regression to explain apprehension levels. Apprehensions have risen with increases in unemployment and with America’s growing market for imports, indicators both taken to connote vulnerability by the media and members of the public as well as by some economists. They have also tended to go up as barriers to trade have disappeared. Felt vulnerability apparently translates into efforts to clarify the citizen population by expelling those who are illegally resident. If illegal immigration responds as closely to economic ›uctuations as
240
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
do changes in tourism and business travel, then those who are bent on stopping illegal immigration will have to halt the American economy. If immigrants are consumer durables, nonimmigrants are consumer disposables. Nonimmigrant visitors have entered the United States in such close relation with imports that one could believe that U.S. imports were each hand-carried by foreign couriers. Nonimmigrant travel and import volume correlate at .90 over the past century, or .94 since World War II. Nonimmigrant travel also correlates highly with American reliance on imports (imports as a proportion of GNP), .99 before World War II and .82 after it. Travelers clearly respond to economic booms and might also help to create them. Tourists and business people respond to the exchange rates that trade and productivity determine, but also bring in money, increasing American “exports” of services and goods. The number of travelers correlates highly with per capita GNP (unlagged), at .88, fairly steadily throughout the past century. Figure 10 shows increases in nonimmigrants and imports. That changes in these migrant categories are so highly correlated with economic ›uctuations highlights the extent to which immigration policy intervenes to recon‹gure the pattern of who goes where and when. At ‹rst glance, migration in response to economic or personal motives appears “natural,” and limits placed on it seem “unnatural.” Yet both are the result of policy consciously pursued. The contrast between what motivates foreigners to come to (and leave) the United States and what motivates legislators to select and exclude potential citizens emerges from the political decision to encourage one type of transborder movement and to discourage the other. Before World War II, isolationism was embedded in trade and in immigration policies. After World War II, the United States helped to create and enforce an order in which countries jointly reduced their barriers to trade, while it helped to cement an order in which they extended their barriers to citizenship. Legislators have allowed economic forces to drive immigration of persons who carry little or no political weight: tourists, students, business people, illegal workers; this is one rea-
TABLE 14.
Explaining Apprehensions
Variable
Coefficient
Constant Unemployment Free and dutiable imports Imports as a proportion of GNP
–173,700 34,866 –89,737 8,132,000
Note: R 2 is .51 for this regression.
Significance .0009 .0000 .0000 .0000
Domestic Interests as Explanations
241
Fig. 10. Nonimmigrants and imports. (Legend: white boxes, nonimmigrants; black boxes, imports.)
son for the widespread though mistaken belief that economics drives immigration policy.
Unemployment, Public Opinion, and the Public Interest
Another reason for this belief is the conviction that these forces ought to drive immigration policy. Therefore, it is reasoned, they do. This belief persists for two reasons: because some legislators and some parts of the public have an interest in others believing it to be true, or they want it to be true so intensely that they believe it to be true, and because it draws on a shared view that legislators ought to respond to these forces because that is their job; it is in the public interest. Explaining the persistence of many people’s erroneous belief that Jewish lobbies control American policy toward Israel, A. F. K. Organski has argued that “all of the major contributors to the making of American policy . . . ‹nd it convenient to believe that it is so.”13 The “utility of this illusion” has been great all around. Americans and others viewed Jewish lobbies with additional respect for their skillful use of their power, and legislators gained when their actions were interpreted as responses to their constituencies’ values rather than as duplicitous maneuvers. Lobbyists, legislators, and the public gain in the same way even when they sincerely believe in the positions they espouse, which most must do. If most did not, lying would be irrational because no
242
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
one would believe the lies. The analytical mistake is not found in taking people at their word concerning their desires, but in believing that since someone wants change, and change occurs, the desire caused the change. Regarding immigration policy, such could be said not only of organized immigrant groups, who have an interest in receiving credit for American policy toward their countries of origin, but also of a wide selection of individuals, who believe that how they fare personally matters to their elected representatives. Peers of the unemployed are, however, unlikely to view out-of-work individuals as more powerful because their representatives ‹ght unemployment. Whereas this is a possible motive for an organized group, it is untenable as the explanation for the public’s general commitment to the notion that policy ought to take public opinion and unemployment levels into account. Legislators can gain from lip service to this view only if people believe responsiveness to these forces is laudable. Both sincere and insincere appeals to the public interest depend on broad agreement on particular public interest values. In order for hypocrisy to be rational, let alone effective, what one lies about has to be viewed as good. Legislators do not give the reason that they were taking bribes as a defense against accusations of vote trading. There is, also, no reason to believe that the majority with a belief in the public interest excludes elected representatives. Given this, we need to ask why many legislators and members of the public believe that immigration policy should change in response to unemployment and public opinion. Why is this belief enduring and widespread? Public interest arguments in the United States share certain attributes; that is, while they can be inconsistent, each shares some of a set of characteristics. Some involve democratic norms, some involve loyalty to the Constitution or to statutes qua laws, and some involve an image or myth about the central message of American history or the role of the federal government. Invoking public opinion clearly draws on all three. Representatives are not just supposed to take public opinion into account; pursuing the public good, which is supposedly expressed through public opinion, justi‹es their jobs. Voting mechanisms force them to listen to their constituents, and American history has been one of broadening equality, in which individual interests and values are good, while “special” or group interests are bad. For all its complexity and quali‹cations, the injunction to do the public’s bidding is so strong that it is assumed to be a motive. Explicitly stating it draws attention to one’s involvement at the center of American democracy, the maintenance of which is in the public interest. Legislators are supposed to pay attention to public opinion, regardless of its content. They are also supposed to care for the common interests
Domestic Interests as Explanations
243
of their constituents, even if the constituents themselves are unaware of those interests. Defense has been justi‹ed in this way; so have education and common transportation networks. Employment is another substantive area in which Americans are assumed to have an interest and an opinion, even if they do not express it. As T. H. Marshall has argued, the public has expanded its notion of the government’s role in defending the public interest as it has changed its understanding of that interest’s content. Having once been predominantly concerned with securing negative liberties, then with positive liberties, governments now are expected to provide substantive goods such as economic welfare; citizens now judge governments in terms of how well they provide material bene‹ts.14 Among the economic measures that could be used to judge government performance, unemployment stands out as the popular, democratic measure. Efforts to save particular industries can be controversial since doing so might harm other parts of the public, and there is no consensus that protectionism serves the public good, but efforts to bolster general employment receive universal support. When one claims to be working to increase employment, one claims to be serving a public interest in which everyone agrees. To claim to be acting in these interests is, then, not to describe one’s motivations but to connect one’s actions with the common interest. Persons advocating a speci‹c change in immigration policy must link either its consequences or the process it requires to public values. This requirement, a familiar one, can be seen operating in the public debate on immigration policy throughout the twentieth century. The arguments that were made usually invoked common values, and the ones that succeeded—or emerged, since the process changed them—always did so. What dominates the public debate before the late 1970s are values articulated normatively. They can be general ethical principles: we must treat all persons alike, persons should be distinguished based only on their past acts, actions should be judged only in terms of their consequences, and so forth. They also can be statements of political value. Sovereignty allows us to realize our essential selves; purity secures the country’s place in history; allies and alien soldiers earn inclusion. In both types of case, the central point obviously involves duty and obligation, “value” topics. But we see that the distinction between interests and values does not differentiate private from public goods. When an interest is invoked, the person doing so engages in the same ritual of identifying with or helping to create a shared de‹nition of the public interest. This has been obscured because of the tendency not only to separate interests and values, but to assume that when an interest is named, it is the real motivation, whereas when a value is named, it is a smoke screen: interests describe, values pre-
244
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
scribe. But in neither case does one necessarily describe one’s original motivation or indicate one’s ideal. In fact, one’s true motivations, if they be known, do not matter. They will not in›uence publicly debated policy unless their ful‹llment can be expressed as something demonstrably in the public interest. Whether this requirement simply facilitates the ful‹llment of interests that were consistent with the social good when conceived or forces persons whose interests were sel‹sh and narrow to reshape them, the outcome is the same. To accomplish anything, arguments have to connect a policy with common interests. What the phenomenon of invoking immigrant pressure groups, public opinion, and unemployment reveals is that while many “values,” such as democratic participation, are in individuals’ interests, some “interests,” such as employment, are common values. This might be why they orbit the immigration debate so closely. A ‹nal reason for the persistence of the belief that domestic forces drive immigration policy change is the conviction that immigration policy is a domestic policy. Issues thought to be the concern only of local governments are also thought to be in›uenced only by local circumstances, by pressure groups, processes, and institutions that are essentially domestic. There are two reasons to question this perspective. First, that domestic policies have domestic in›uences does not follow logically; small countries are dependent on and easily in›uenced by events beyond their borders, and the large countries able to be self-suf‹cient seem often precisely because of their power to create connections to others. These conduits become mutually in›uential. Second, even were the domestic/foreign policy split to be respected, immigration policy is (like trade policy) a “foreign” policy in that it is directed toward—and indeed would make no sense without—an international system lying beyond a country’s borders. For all of these reasons, it should be no surprise that explanations grounded in the view that a purely local politics drives immigration policies fare badly in explaining actual change.
CHAPTER 9
Structural Theories as Explanations
Like domestic explanations, international-structural explanations could provide a more accurate, and simpler, alternative to the argument forwarded earlier about sovereignty and the public interest. Structural theorists might argue that these legislative discussions in fact occurred, and they did in a microsense shape policies’ details, but that the choices legislators thought that they were making from scratch were in a sense predetermined. Changes in the distribution of power, or in the country’s terms of trade and public demands for better living standards, or another equally broad phenomenon could have placed so much pressure on a country that a legislator would have had to favor restriction. The arguments, in this view, reveal legislators’ attempts to come to terms with the action they were compelled to take anyway, rather than the justi‹cations that are necessary to sanctify democratic action and move the nation forward. This chapter assesses structural theories generally as explanations for the changes examined earlier. Although systems-level structural theories of international relations, which deal directly with sovereignty and power, do not discuss immigration policy, each does imply hypotheses concerning quantitative restriction—concerning border control, the correlation between immigration and trade policies,1 and directional trends in each of those policies—as well as suggest a basis for determining which characteristics a country will seek in its immigrant population. Neorealism, functionalism, and hegemonic stability theories each identify minimal commonalities among states that de‹ne their constraints and incentives. The following sections outline the predictions they would make concerning boundary control, then evaluate them in the light of American immigration policy in the twentieth century. Since the evidence each requires is macrolevel time-series data, most of the evidence used to evaluate the theories is quantitative. Since none distinguishes between transborder ›ows of goods and persons (labor), they are all tested on data about both trade and migration. The ‹nal section evaluates the degree to which relatively simple structural theories explain either the content of immigration policy or the timing and direction of changes in it. 245
246
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Realism
Systems-level theories start by mapping the distribution of power and then deduce from this the dynamic pattern of interaction that should emerge. Neorealism starts by positing sovereign states with varying amounts of power, and then draws from this basic map principles governing alliance and con›ict points. In anarchy, self-preservation through security becomes the highest value. States assure security via alliance or autarky— but preferably autarky since any alliance must be uncertain.2 Sometimes rivalry becomes interbloc, as states ally to deter others, but such cooperation is ›eeting, for it creates vulnerability. Power and interdependence are incompatible. As Hans Morgenthau put it, states pursue power;3 they seek relative gains. Changes in power’s bases and distribution alter the threats and opportunities that states face, and therefore which strategy will be most effective in the short run in strengthening their autonomy and security. Sovereignty and power, authority and capabilities, are for realists ultimately a single idea, being able to do what one wants. States use borders to preserve what they have, although preservation might imply expansion to undermine opponents and provide a buffer. People and wealth each enable a state to ‹nance security, so policies toward people and markets reinforce each other. Each in the long run must tend toward assuring independence. The realist decision rule is quantitative and strategic. Calculating relative gains involves deciding on the net cost of some strategy, then comparing it to the alternatives. A realist sees both citizens and foreigners as resources carrying net costs or bene‹ts depending on individuals’ power vis-à-vis the state and their employers. A government ‹rst calculates whether an additional person’s marginal product—understood in political and ideological as well as economic terms— exceeds his or her cost. Power politics demands a second calculation, whether pulling people in helps other states more than it helps oneself, and decides on this point. The same sort of calculus will be made for trade as for immigration, since what ultimately matters in all spheres are relative gains and losses. In the short run, this goal could dictate a variety of policies, depending on the prevailing distribution of productive factors and costs, alliances, and power. On average, though, across states and over time, immigration and trade policies should be similar because all policies must serve autonomy.4 Realism anticipates a strong policy bias toward restricting free transborder ›ows threatening independence. Autonomy, for classical realists, also has a qualitative value. It matters because it makes possible survival, not just of people on a territory, but of a distinct culture valued for its own sake. The international environment, separate from and hostile to any one country, threatens life
Structural Theories as Explanations
247
directly, and one’s way of life indirectly. Since immigrants are foreigners of an enemy culture, realists would expect that the immigrants a country does accept would be culturally or ideologically similar to citizens; this dimension could change as the enemy changed. Structural realists, on the other hand, assume that a community’s values would remain stable through time. Table 15 summarizes the realist predictions about policy on several dimensions.
Hegemonic Stability Theory
Hegemonic stability theory shares many of realism’s premises. States seek power, they attempt to secure dominance over others and to avoid dependence, and their policies toward others depend on the prevailing distribution of power. Unlike realists, hegemonic stability theorists add the proposition that states will value order at the cost of some autonomy; bene‹ts that order makes possible justify ceding some ability to act unilaterally.5 In this view, the strongest state will bear much of the responsibility for articulating and enforcing a speci‹c order, in exchange for getting the type of order it wants. Smaller states will go along, sacri‹cing autonomy for the material bene‹ts order allows. Hegemonic stability theorists concentrate on explaining what for realists are medium-term policy paradoxes, policies that do not “go together.” Because hegemons must balance their unique interests with others’ to keep the order going, their policies would look irrational from a narrow realist standpoint. For example, to secure European dependence after World War II, the United States helped to rebuild Europe as a competitor. The hegemon disaggregates policy areas and
TABLE 15.
Realist Predictions: Summary
Goals
Security Self-preservation
Borders' function
Protect Preserve
Policies’ long-run direction
Toward autarky
Immigration and trade policies
Positively correlated
Policy toward immigrant quantity
Depends on immigrants' contribution to state power
Policy toward immigrant characteristics
Unchanging (neorealism) Changes as the enemy changes (realism)
248
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
manipulates them, allowing autonomy in some areas but undermining it in others. What remains a ‹rm boundary depends on the hegemon’s goals, which in turn depend on its domestic values and politics. Since these vary from hegemon to hegemon, knowing simply that some hegemon has secured an order will not tell one which types of goals it will pursue or which policies will come to dominate.6 One cannot on this basis predict what immigration policy will look like. Indeed, changes in the bases as well as the distribution of power drive policy change from era to era. British mercantilism undergirded the nineteenth-century notion of “the more people the better,” encouraging in›ows of people and goods while making expatriation almost impossible.7 American hegemony, however, arose with the welfare state and free trade. Americans preferred to allow capital, but not labor, to move freely, returning pro‹ts, but not people, to the United States. Other countries adapted to these hegemonies for the sake of order, but with declining British, then American, dominance, hegemonic stability theorists expect all policies eventually to snap back toward autarky.8 Like realism, hegemonic stability theory retains a strong bias toward autarky. Order among mutually vulnerable states is, after all, the anomaly the theory seeks to explain. On the other hand, hegemons secure rule by affecting other countries’ ideologies and values, which implies a measure of integration. A hegemon will occasionally accept costs in one area in exchange for stability in another; it might accept immigrants it does not want in exchange for other policy concessions. But a country would accept immigrants of a sort it did not want only during periods of stable hegemony, as part of a policy bargain. During periods of international disarray, immigration, like other policies, would move back toward autarky and closure. Table 16 summarizes hegemonic stability theory’s implications for analyzing a hegemon’s immigration policy.
Functionalism
Interdependence or functional integration theory views movements back toward autonomy as retrogressive. In David Mitrany’s formulation, increasing political participation and technological advances coincide with a more widespread view that government has a direct responsibility for people’s well-being.9 Any government can only cultivate a home market so intensely until returns begin to decrease. To stay in power, to give its increasingly vocal population what it wants, legislators must turn to economies outside the home market. Other governments face similar pres-
Structural Theories as Explanations
249
sures to cooperate, while economies of scale promise rewards for doing so. While an international organization comprised of states, Mitrany argues, “would de‹ne their territory as a means of differentiating between members and outsiders, a [cooperative] league would select and de‹ne functions for the contrary purpose of integrating with regard to them the interests of all.”10 These rewards are for individuals, not governments, which become weaker in the process of such integration. As ever broader institutions provide for their needs, citizens become loyal to them; “the State is no more than a convenient association, neither greater nor smaller in usefulness and authority than the many other associations in which members of a community organize their various interests.”11 Borders serve no purpose but to mark, arbitrarily, population in subsets capable of delegating authority to a representative. People dictate state policy, and since most concern themselves with absolute, not relative, gains, they support immigration to the point where immigrants’ marginal increase in national wealth equals their drain on central services. Since regions of the world economy differ in factor endowments, some countries will initially prefer importing capital to importing labor, but trade and migration serve the same purpose. People therefore judge them by the same standard: their contribution to wealth. Functionalists expect governments to open borders to facilitate resource ›ows. A desire for a better material standard of living motivates policy in the functional world. A functionalist would expect that in integration’s early stages, when people calculate social product within state boundaries, skill level and capital wealth would dominate the preference list; in later stages, when social product means world product, immigration would be entirely unrestricted. Table 17 summarizes functionalism’s expectations about immigration policy.
TABLE 16.
Hegemonic Stability Theory's Predictions: Summary
Goals
Order Stability
Borders’ function
To define the area to be used when calculating relative gains
Policies’ long-run direction
Toward autarky
Immigration and trade policies
Positively correlated in the long run Potentially different in the short run
Policy toward immigrant quantity
Depends on the nature of the hegemony
Policy toward immigrant characteristics
Depends on the nature of the hegemony
250
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Each of these perspectives implicitly hypothesizes some trajectory to autonomy and power, and to immigration and trade policies, based on what it pinpoints as the main engine powering large-scale change. Realism posits that states pursue security through autonomy, and hence would tend to guard against transnational processes. Both trade and immigration should tend toward restriction. Functional integration theory posits that states pursue wealth through cooperation and hence seek to promote transnational processes. Both trade and immigration should tend toward openness. Hegemonic stability theory, on the other hand, posits that in any era, states seek order through a system of rules consonant with the strongest state’s overall interests and domestic values. Immigration and trade policies will not necessarily parallel each other since the modal policy will mimic that of the hegemon. During nonhegemonic eras, however, states should slide back toward autarky. The following section uses evidence from the past century of American trade and immigration policies, and from the country’s experience with actual trade and immigration ›ows, to evaluate these structural theories’ predictive power.
Evidence: Immigrant Volume
Hypotheses dealing with immigrants’ volume and those dealing with immigrants’ characteristics will be separated initially because the ‹rst are quantitative, the second qualitative.12 Separated, each can be compared with parallel types of indicators to highlight change. The ‹rst analysis, of numerical control, is designed to test the structural theories’ implicit propositions about increases or decreases in the volume of allowed immigration and about the relationship between policies toward material resources and those toward citizenship. One test concerns the volume of transborder ›ows, of increases or decreases in the volume of goods, services, and citi-
TABLE 17.
Functionalism’s Predictions: Summary
Goals
Increased individual wealth
Borders' function
To define the area to be used when selecting a representative
Policies' long-run direction
Toward integration
Immigration and trade policies
Positively correlated
Policy toward immigrant quantity
Favors immigration
Policy toward immigrant characteristics
Favors the skilled
Structural Theories as Explanations
251
zens imported. Because of strong secular trends, both of these variables will be discussed in their population and productivity contexts. Trade matters as a proportion of GNP; immigration matters as a proportion of the U.S. population. The second test involves the correlation between trade and migration; all theories anticipate the two to be positively correlated, but expect their common trend to be in different directions. The second analysis concerns not quantity but quality: the nature of and stability in desired immigrants’ characteristics. The picture here, as always, centers on policy, rather than actual numbers of immigrants.13 Policy, not the actual ›ow of immigrants, is the dependent variable. What is to be explained or outlined in context are the ceiling’s level, the direction of its change, and the of‹cial distribution of quotas and preferences among immigrants. Following the statistical overview, the last section assesses structural theories’ utility for explaining American immigration policy. Structural theories’ simplest expectations involve the magnitude of international migration. Because large or unregulated ›ows threaten states, by muddying their borders and allowing destruction from within, realists enjoin governments to restrict the volume of immigration and to secure control over it. Functionalists expect, and hope for, the opposite. Maximizing personal incomes can only be accomplished by taking advantage of transnational technologies and marketing abilities. Borders only interfere with this. Persons, as laborers, investors, and consumers, should be allowed to travel where the market will take them. Immigration should increase as states cede control over transborder ›ows to markets. Legally allowed immigration to the United States, in proportion to the American population, has decreased. This is consistent with realist expectations and counter to functionalist expectations, both broadly construed. Comparing it to actual immigration indicates the degree to which the policy de‹nes what is really allowed; comparing it to actual in›ows of nonimmigrants measures the degree to which policy reduces “natural” in›ows. Legal limits to immigration policy are usually exceeded, though actual levels are usually within a few percentage points of the policy targets. The gap between legally allowed immigration and actual nonimmigrant volume is enormous, indicating that immigration policy in the United States has remained restrictive. If the demand for immigration has risen, as the increases in nonimmigrant visitors might indicate, then immigration policy has become more numerically restrictive over time. Realism, hegemonic stability theory, and functionalism each expect that immigration and trade policies will go together because each equates border control with sovereignty and sovereignty with autarky. Realists would claim that sovereign states’ pursuit of relative power demands such control, hegemonic stability theorists would agree but note that for a short
252
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
time a hegemon can relieve the necessity of pouring resources into border protection, and functionalists would argue that integration involves erosion and eventual abandonment of borders. As borders go, so goes sovereignty. Conversely, since states remain, borders must remain strong enough. All of the structural theories expect immigration and trade targets to covary positively; either both become more restrictive, or both become more open. Realists would expect them to tend, over the long run, in the direction of autarky; both slopes would be toward closed borders. Hegemonic stability theory anticipates autarkic policy only during periods without hegemonic stability. Policies should covary only from about 1920 to 1945 and from the 1970s to the present. Like realism, functionalism anticipates general covariance, though in the long run toward openness. To check this for the United States, we can compare tariffs,14 as a proportion of merchandise imports, with the legal immigration ceiling, as a proportion of the U.S. population. Another comparison focuses on imports in relation to GNP and the immigration ceiling over time: trade barriers are to national product as immigration ceilings are to national population. Some of these indicators are interrelated in a way that biases them against showing a directional split. Population increases do not necessarily lead to a higher import reliance, but they do affect GNP. Over the last century, the American population has increased steadily, and the world population has risen even more sharply. Over the same century, world product has skyrocketed. In a comparison of proportions, legal ceiling to population and imports to GNP, rising population and rising GNP are denominators—and related denominators. Increases in population will almost always affect GNP, which is, after all, an aggregate. This means that between these two numbers there is some built-in relationship. If immigrants produce anything, GNP will rise; economic growth attracts immigrants. Population and imports are separate but population and GNP are not. In a straight time-series, then, we should be surprised if any variables that rested on population and GNP were not related positively. In addition, systems theorists imply that the numerators ought to be related as well. The legal ceiling restricting immigration and protective trade policies, they would all argue, capture the same phenomenon: autarky. Immigration quotas are to population as tariff restrictions (which affect import levels) are to GNP. Whether they have been going up or down, they should be making their way together toward openness or closure. Since standard measures count these in opposite ways—a reduced immigration ceiling means a more restrictive policy, while a higher tariff indicates restriction—visually, or algebraically, positive covariance would be represented by two lines on a graph, each sloping in an opposite direc-
Structural Theories as Explanations
253
tion. A ‹rst glance at the graph shows this not to be the case. Figure 11 shows the relationship between the percentage of imports subject to tariffs—a measure of openness—and the numerical immigration ceiling as a percentage of the U.S. population—a measure of isolation. Immigration policy has become more restrictive as trade policy has become less protectionist. To check to see whether this is simply due to inertia of time, we remove the secular trend from each. This leaves a set of numbers that indicate deviation from the norm. What is left are shifts, rather than raw values or amounts, in the ratios of ceiling to population and tariffs to the value of imports. Before World War II, when Congress drove tariffs upward and curtailed immigration, these residual variables correlate at –.35, that is, they served the same restrictive purpose. Following the war, however, Congress lowered tariff barriers substantially while immigration remained under control as tight as ever. Statistically, this is shown by a turnabout from the –.35 before the war to a positive .55 after it. In fact, even this is deceptively low. In 1965, Congress raised the overall ceiling by adding 120,000 places for a previously unlimited group, Western Hemisphere migrants. Eastern Hemisphere migrants, who had before constituted the entire restricted group, were given only a slightly higher number of slots. This is not a leap but an accounting change. Consistent limits can be constructed in one of two ways: by adding actual Western Hemisphere immigration before the change, with the rationale that in not restricting it, Congress accepted its volume, or by subtracting the 120,000 from the ceiling after 1965, so the number consistently counts only Europeans, Asians, and Africans. Eliminating this arti‹cial jump in the ceiling changes the postwar correlation, again of residuals, to .85 or .73 depending on which indicator is used. Clearly, lowered trade barriers have accompanied tighter, not looser, controls on immigration. On the question of whether protectionist legislation extends across both trade and immigration, realism and functionalism both answered yes, they do in the long run. We see, however, that the proportion of imports subject to tariffs has, with two exceptions, decreased steadily and fairly dramatically, while the legislated tolerance level for immigrants has also declined. The reality as far as U.S. policy is concerned does not match what these theories predict. If the exceptions were during times of chaos following a hegemonic order’s collapse, hegemonic stability theory would appear to provide a plausible account of this. And in fact, from 1923 to 1945, the correlation between tariffs and the immigration ceiling drops; in the interwar period immigration restrictions and tariffs each got more protective (–.50 correlation),15 while in the post–World War II period tariffs eased while immigration restrictions did not (.85 correlation). From the mid-1970s to the
254
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Fig. 11. Consistent ceiling levels to population and tariffs to imports. (Legend: white boxes, consistent ceiling including Western Hemisphere; large black boxes, consistent ceiling counting only the Eastern Hemisphere; small black boxes, tariff percentage.)
present, however, this postwar statistical relationship has not degenerated, but has strengthened—to .96. If hegemonic cycles explain turnarounds, they do so only for the shift in the 1940s unless it is argued that hegemony did not change after 1945. American policy toward foreign trade has sought to eliminate barriers, while American policy toward immigrants has sought to strengthen them. Tariff levels measure protectionism, while import levels measure vulnerability to foreign markets.16 During the twentieth century, America’s dependence on foreign markets has increased while its proportion of foreign-born has decreased. Since World War II, the immigration ceiling has gone down while the U.S. shares of world imports (–.44 correlation) and exports (–.79 correlation) have gone up. As others have become more dependent on U.S. markets, the United States has also become more dependent on foreign markets. Since 1945, U.S. imports rose from 5 to 13.5 percent of its GNP, while its exports rose from 8 to 12 percent.17 U.S. trade also rose relative to the rest of the world. Its share of world imports rose from 11.5 to 17.8 percent from 1947 to 1985, but its exports meanwhile dropped from 28.8 to 11.3 percent.
Structural Theories as Explanations
255
As the American market became more responsive and vulnerable to external economic ›uctuation, a realist would expect the United States to have sought to insulate itself through tariffs and immigration restriction. As Americans consume a greater proportion of their GNP with imports, they lower the immigration ceiling.
Evidence: Regulatory Categories
One way to restrict the number of immigrants is to reduce the nominal ceiling on overall immigration. Another is to extend regulatory control over additional categories of immigrants. By 1990, all immigrants were subject to a numerical ceiling, but earlier in the century some groups’ migration was left uncontrolled. At times, their number exceeded that of those entering within quotas. If this were allowed to continue, that would suggest that the limits were allowed simply to erode. This is not the case. When immigration exceeded a set level for a few years, new legislation forced it down below the ceiling and reclassi‹ed additional groups as restricted. It is as if the problem of too-heavy traf‹c on the freeway were resolved by ‹ve years of traf‹c-impeding construction followed by changes to force more onto the turnpike. Which groups this amending legislation targets have not necessarily been those responsible for the earlier increase. Rather, Congress has juggled categories to ensure that the groups to remain unrestricted will be those that supply immigrants in fairly predictable amounts, steadily over many years. As interdependence has become more extensive, more groups have been regulated. Figure 12 illustrates the way that nonquota immigrant categories have changed over time. Three categories of immigrants—refugees, Western Hemisphere residents, and relatives—have at one time been allowed to immigrate without reference to how many others have also applied for admission. Increases in the number of nonquota immigrants have preceded legislation to peel categories away and reinsert them elsewhere with limits attached. For example, refugees were ‹rst charged against their country quotas, which were mortgaged against future country allocations if exceeded. The Baltic states, for example, had mortgages until about 2035. Congress forgave these mortgages and tried to deal with contemporary refugees on an ad hoc basis (mainly as parolees, who, when their status is adjusted, count as immigrants against their country of origin). When emergencies became chronic—or when America liberalized its de‹nition of what constituted an emergency—refugees were given their own preference category of 6 percent, or 17,400 annually. Refugees still exceeded these categories, so after
256
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
Fig. 12. Nonquota refugees, Western Hemisphere migrants, and relatives. (Legend: striped, Western Hemisphere migrants; black, nonquota refugees; white, relatives.)
a refugee admission averaging 85,645 from 1977 to 1979, the Refugee Act of 1980 integrated these miscellaneous mechanisms to ‹x the annual number at 20,000. The 1965 limit on the Western Hemisphere, to 120,000, followed an annual average immigration of only 110,808 in the preceding decade, though the number had been on the rise. Western Hemisphere migrants ‹rst faced limits when the U.S. Congress equalized policy toward all countries. In the then-current view, the choice was to allow all countries free immigration or to restrict them all equally. Congress chose equal restriction. Of relatives,18 refugees, and Western Hemisphere migrants, the three groups that have dominated this category, relatives have been least likely to arrive unpredictably.19 They were also the last to be subject to numerical controls. Relatives’ numbers had been rising as the two groups of immigrants, the Indochinese in the late 1970s and the resident illegal aliens in the mid-1980s, united their families. The pattern in this category of unrestricted migrants has been to separate, systematize, and limit various subgroups; in other words, to formalize numerical limits when the unwritten ones have been reached or exceeded. Unrestricted immigration has not, then, really been free numerically. Increasing regulation is consistent with the predictions of realism, but is inconsistent with those of functionalism. Since policy continued through the 1970s and 1980s unchanged, hegemonic stability theory alone is insuf‹cient as an explanation.
Structural Theories as Explanations
257
A comparison with policy toward, and ›ows of, nonimmigrants20 provides a simple contrast to permanent immigrants. It indicates the magnitude of immigration restriction and highlights how important the citizen-noncitizen distinction is to numerical limitation. The difference between these two groups is not simply how long they are allowed to remain, but what they are allowed to claim; one might be more acceptable in high numbers because it is so dif‹cult for it to cost anything or change much. One contrast, then, is in the limits of tolerance for certain types of claimants. If accurate ‹gures on global travel were available, one direct comparison might be made between the proportion of all travelers and all exports bringing money into the United States; another might be made between nonimmigrants and imports invading the United States. As outlined earlier in this chapter, visitors’ volume has increased as the U.S. share of world imports has gone up and share of world exports has declined. The government has made no attempt to regulate visitors’ volume except during wartime; in fact, presidents boost tourism in television commercials aired abroad. Since nonimmigrants are considered an economic bonus, with no costs—and are considered economic, not political—they are recruited, not restricted. American policy encourages, rather than ignores or restricts, nonimmigrant visitors. No one knows how many people would immigrate if they could. The volume of nonimmigration cannot provide a direct indicator of potential immigration because the categories draw from partly different pools; for example, a constantly traveling foreign investor might be content in his or her citizenship while a poor compatriot who has never traveled might do so if it became legally possible. At the same time, nonimmigrant travel does indirectly measure two components affecting the decision to emigrate, information and travel cost, and it in turn affects the levels of each, as volume lowers prices and travelers bring news. If these barriers are coming down, it is reasonable to assume that immigration demand will also rise, other things being equal. Though they are imprecise, these comparisons highlight the degree to which immigration policy restricts. While trade has risen exponentially, and the American economy, like many others, has become vastly more permeated every decade, U.S. immigration policy has consistently served protectionist and conservative ends. The number of immigrants admissible through normal routes has remained almost the same since the ‹rst ceiling in 1921 was shrunk three years later. When unrestricted immigrants have taken advantage too enthusiastically of that privilege, some open classi‹cations have become limited. When the laws and immigrants have each become too numerous, systematic limits have replaced the ad hoc or time-limited legislation that
258
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
injected ›exibility. The Immigration and Nationality Act has been amended in many important ways, all designed to increase control over the number of immigrants. Its purpose has been to contain, and occasionally to roll back. If world population is rising, and rising faster than the U.S. population, if costs are dropping and legally allowed in-movement is skyrocketing, holding fast not even to a proportion but a ‹xed number should be considered profoundly conservative. This process is consistent with that which realism would predict. Realism’s accuracy, however, remains suspect since it predicts protective immigration policy because it anticipates autarkic policies generally. American trade policy did not follow that path in the post–World War II world. Realism can explain why the United States might have pursued conservatism regarding immigration ceilings but not why it would simultaneously attempt to make its borders irreversibly open to trade.
Evidence: Immigrant Characteristics
The ‹rst analysis described the most basic and enduring use of immigration policy, controlling the number of potential new citizens. A second set of questions addresses the changing requirements for immigrant characteristics. The ceiling’s purpose is not simply to allow in a ‹xed number of persons, but persons of a certain sort. Which sort has changed over time. Neorealists and functionalists both expect American ideas about desirable immigrant characteristics to have been unchanging and to have focused on economic attributes. Neorealists predict that a country will decide to admit an immigrant who increases state power relative to others; functionalists predict absolute, not relative, gains to guide such judgments. Classical realists, on the other hand, would expect exclusion and selection criteria to change as the state’s main threat shifted. Also expecting change are hegemonic stability theorists who anticipate that selection criteria will be consistent with the hegemon’s ideology during periods of hegemonic dominance. A liberal hegemon would implement a policy that declared liberal principles the general norm. Speci‹cally, neorealism expects that criteria regarding immigrant characteristics are unchanging and wealth-based, while classical realism expects that they change with shifts in not only the distribution of power but in the nature of the threatening state. Hegemonic stability theory expects American immigration policy during its reign to move toward liberal criteria, but fall away from them and toward isolationist ones after its power began to wane. Functionalism anticipates an enduring predilection for laborers and investors. These hypotheses can be tested by tracing
Structural Theories as Explanations
259
whether and how immigration categories have changed over time. Policy provisions regarding immigrants’ characteristics can be divided into three groups: individual degeneracy, national origin, and preferences for skills or relation to a U.S. citizen.21 Regardless of whether one seeks to enter the United States as a tourist or prospective citizen, certain characteristics will guarantee exclusion. Starting in 1875, Congress began to detail attributes suf‹cient to eliminate a person’s chances of entering the country. (Since “the Asiatic races” were dealt with usually through general immigration policy, a ban on individual depravity and inferiority was intended to eliminate certain Europeans.) Table 18 lists the categories by the years in which they were introduced. Early exclusion categories focused on sexual morality, insanity, disability, disease, drug addiction, and poverty, all considered at the time evidence of degeneracy. Over the next century, three types of categories would be added. One, directed against fraud, targeted persons who breached administrative requirements: lost their papers, had none to begin with, were incorrectly classi‹ed, and the like. The second addition raised the ›oor. Simply demonstrating nondegeneracy was no longer suf‹cient; one must demonstrate that one would help the country. Literacy and needed skills became necessary minima. The third added category aimed at ideological threats. Following McKinley’s assassination by an anarchist immigrant, all anarchists were barred; with the rise of the cold war, all communists were barred. Realists and functionalists believed that criteria would be stable (functionalists believed that they would be stable and economic); hegemonic stability theory predicted an underlying stability sometimes eclipsed by a hegemon’s policies. Although this is but one part of the screen that ‹lters immigrants, the development of exclusion categories through time indicates the sort of constancy expected by neorealists. Functionalist expectations about economic criteria, hegemonic stability theorists’ expectations about liberalized categories, and classical realism’s expectation that changing threats would underlie changing exclusion categories are not borne out. What is evident in this selective category is that the early focus on public health endured, to be supplemented by occasional efforts to keep out those who would infect American society in other ways. If this category is the focus of change, change was minimal. Realists and hegemonic stability theorists expect that country of origin will matter a great deal when deciding whom to admit; it is central to the geopolitical advantages or disadvantages that accrue from admitting someone. Functionalists expect it to be a trivial component of immigration policy since it is irrelevant to a person’s economic bene‹ts. Both of these can capture American policy toward national origin from the mid-
TABLE 18.
Exclusion Categories by Year of Introduction
1875 •Convicted criminals •Prostitutes and their pimps 1882 •Lunatics and idiots •Those likely to become a public charge 1885 •Contract laborers [eliminated 1952] 1891 •Idiots and insane persons •Those suffering from any dangerous contagious disease •Paupers •Criminals having been convicted of a crime involving moral turpitude •Polygamists or those practicing or advocating the practice of polygamy 1903 •Epileptics •Those who have had two or more attacks of insanity •Professional beggars •Anyone accompanying an alien excluded due to incompetence •Anarchists or members of anarchistic classes 1907 •Anyone having a physical disease, defect or disability which may affect the ability to earn a living •Vagrants •Imbeciles and feebleminded •Unaccompanied children [eliminated 1952] 1917 •Those suffering from constitutional psychopathic inferiority •Chronic alcoholics •Those excluded and deported within the previous year •Stowaways •Those over 16, physically capable of reading, who cannot understand some language or dialect 1924 •Those without correct papers •Anyone ineligible to citizenship [referred to Asians] •Anyone claiming exemption as a Western Hemisphere resident who has resided there less than two years 1937 •Those without the correct preference class listed on their papers 1948- •Those engaged in activities that 1950 would be prejudicial to the public
1952
1965 1976
1978 1990
interest, or endanger the welfare, safety, or security of the United States. •Those who “are or at any time have been members of . . . the Communist Party of the United States, or any other totalitarian party of the United States or [anywhere]. . . . those who advocate or teach the overthrow by force or violence of the government of the United States . . .” unless one’s membership was required for survival and one has actively opposed the party for the previous five years. •Those whose intent in immigrating is sabotage or espionage •Those who have had one or more attacks of insanity •Narcotic drug addicts and convicted drug-traffickers •Those convicted of two or more major offenses [unless purely political] •Those coming to the United States to engage in any immoral sexual act •Skilled or unskilled labor, if the secretary of labor has certified sufficient domestic labor •Previous deportees •Smugglers of aliens •Mentally retarded persons •Sexual deviants [homosexuals] •Foreign medical graduates seeking to practice or train in the United States •Those who engaged in persecution under the Nazis Exclusion categories collapsed into nine: health threats, criminals, security risks, public charge risks, labor competitors, illegal entrants, those without visas, those ineligible for citizenship, and miscellaneous (includes polygamy). This gives officers wider discretion but at the same time removes communism and homosexuality as automatic reasons for exclusion.
Structural Theories as Explanations
261
1960s on, but neither comes close to describing the role that it played in the early years of immigration control. Congress eventually justi‹ed national origin criteria as a handy way to ensure global equality in the opportunity to immigrate. This implied that sovereign boundaries had come to serve as convenient administrative categories and nothing more. Whether this were in fact true or not, in the early twentieth century, no one would have made such a claim. National origin indicated race, with all that went along with it: moral standards, propensity to superstition, intelligence, and the ability to govern oneself. The preoccupation with parentage led Congress ‹rst to ban immigration from China, then from almost all of Asia, and next to curtail it sharply from areas in Europe thought to spawn ignorant and racially inferior emigrants. Country tables translated this ethnoracial selection system into an enforceable law: zero for Asiatics, no limits for the Western Hemisphere, and varying limits for the thirty European countries recognized in 1921. With time, and the cold war, national origin came to indicate ideology, rather than race. Following decolonization, Congress relativized its stand toward national origin, making all countries equal.22 It ensured a continued ability to screen subversives by relying on the exclusion criteria. Since World War II had raised Asian countries’ status to “restricted,” the last step in this globalization was the inclusion of previously unrestricted Western Hemisphere migrants under the ceiling. Eventually, even the division between the two hemispheres was abolished. At the moment quotas were made universal, the countries facing quotas were made almost equal. Instead of adding precise allocations within the extended global limit, each country was allowed to supply immigrants until it hit 20,000 or combined immigration had exhausted the aggregate. Relativism accompanied globalism. This can be seen most clearly in the con›uence of population and quota distributions over time. Table 19 shows the changes in how immigration slots were distributed geographically. As a country expands its diplomatic contacts and adds trading partners, it is not surprising that it should amend its immigration policies to cover new areas in its social circle. Immigrants have always traveled in greatest numbers on beaten paths.23 The United States could not help but clear such paths as its merchants and administrators involved themselves more heavily abroad. Anticipating or reacting to an increased number of immigration demand sites by extending restrictive limits to new areas is thus not unusual. What is notable, given the alternatives, is choosing to allocate slots by sovereign country, while gradually suspending judgment about the relative worth of immigrants’ homelands, an outcome that neither realists nor functionalists would expect. If American hegemony is de‹ned as internationalism plus liberalism,
262
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
then the changes in American policy’s use of national origins criteria mirrored and supported American hegemony. Before World War II, the liberalism that justi‹ed American domestic policies did not apply to American policy toward noncitizens. It was not until it set out to establish and maintain international institutions and regimes that foreign policy began self-consciously to re›ect liberal principles. To be credible, American deeds had to support its rhetorical advocacy of liberal principles. Obvious in the congressional debates is a heightened consciousness that the eyes of the world were on the legislators, and the American reputation was at
TABLE 19.
Regional Distribution of Immigration Slots 1930
1950
1964
1970
1980
1995
Africa, the Middle East and the Philippines Percent of world’s population Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of US ceiling allotted
11 13 0.7
12 15 1.1
13 38 1.7
13 36 26a
15 40 40b
16 34 34
Asia: Barred Zone Area Percent of world’s population Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of US ceiling allotted
55 16 0.5
55 55 15 11 0.7c 1.1
57 20 14
58 20 20
61 23 23
Europe, Australia and New Zealand Percent of world’s population Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of US ceiling allotted
28 43 62
25 43 80
23 31 51
21 26 18
18 21 21
14 25 25
Western Hemisphere (not including the U.S.)d Percent of world’s population Percent of world’s countries in the region Percent of U.S. ceiling allotted
6 28 36
8 27 18
9 20 46
9 18 41
9 19 19
9 18 18
Note: World population does not include that of the U.S. Percentages calculated from census data in the UN Demographic Yearbook, table 1 (various years), and the World Almanac and Book of Facts (various years). aStarting in 1969, each country in the Eastern Hemisphere was given a limit of 20,000 within a 170,000 maximum; the Western Hemisphere was given a 120,000 ceiling with no distribution by country. The allocation calculated in this column then is based on the number of countries among which a subquota is divided. It is the point at which countries equalize. bStarting in 1978, the hemisphere divisions were lifted but all countries were limited to the 20,000 ceiling. This means that the hypothetical distribution of immigration slots among regions just matches the proportion of the world’s countries in them. cUntil special legislation enacted from 1943 to 1952, the Asian quota was usable only by non-Asiatics, i.e., by those of European or African descent who happened to be born in Asia. Until this time, the quota for Asiatics was zero. dThe Western Hemisphere did not have a ceiling until 1965/1969. It is included through the whole period for the sake of consistency. “Ceiling allotted” for earlier years is the proportion of all legal immigrants coming from the Western Hemisphere.
Structural Theories as Explanations
263
stake. Policy changed to assure that all countries and peoples were treated equally. How this choice combines liberal principles with a consciousness of power can be seen by comparing this policy to possible alternatives. U.S. policy could have continued to differentiate among immigrants by drawing ‹ne geographic lines. Since justifying discrimination on the basis of race had to be abandoned, change had to come, but the liberal tradition could provide arguments to favor allocating slots by country, using sovereign divisions as a way to administer equal distribution among individuals. Pegging countries’ quotas to their populations, for example, would equalize global opportunity to emigrate to the United States, making immigrant representation more analogous to election to the House than the Senate. It thus could be argued to be more democratic. Instead, Congress gave every country the same potential ceiling. As countries achieved independence, giving them the same allotment served a symbolic purpose, like granting UN membership or embassy space, a procedure democratic among states if not among individuals. Theories incorporating American hegemony can account for this better than can the structural theories, which, after all, expect change to be linear when it occurs. Persons whose personal characteristics and country of origin qualify them for admission into the United States are sorted once more before they are given a visa. Within any country’s limit, some immigrants are preferred to others. The preference system can be seen as an effort at selection through positive means. Skills and capital have not guaranteed admission, though in some periods economic attributes were given more weight. Their weight has not varied with economic changes, as might be expected. The ‹rst quota laws provided that skilled agriculturists as well as parents, spouses, and children of U.S. residents could receive ‹rst preference, which at the time was 50 percent of the available slots. In 1952, during an economic boom, skilled workers and their families were given ‹rst preference and half the slots, but in 1965, another period of high employment, immigrant workers were reduced to two 10 percent slots. In 1976, during the oil recession, successful inclusion in one of these became more dif‹cult, as it then depended not just on space but also on a previous job offer. The late 1980s, a time of growing fears of economic decline, saw a move to enlarge economic preferences while raising quali‹cations for them. Legislators revising immigration policy build in preferences for workers when the economy is up, and labor is scarce, but also when the economy is down, when investment and skilled labor are seen to be in short supply. Relatives have always been preferred, though to what extent has varied. Male citizens’ wives and children were allowed to immigrate without reference to the quota. Within it, the earliest preferences allowed that 50
264
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
percent would be reserved for the wives and unmarried children of permanent residents, while the other 50 percent would be shared by agriculturists and parents and husbands of citizens. The 1952 reforms changed this somewhat. It put foreign husbands and wives on the same footing and created new divisions, which resulted in a 50 percent preference for the skilled and their families, leaving 50 percent for relatives. Many refer to the 1965 Immigration and Nationality Act amendments, however, as the “brothers and sisters act” because of their great push toward helping relatives enter. Seventy-four percent of places within the ceiling were reserved for brothers, sisters, and adult married and unmarried children; close relatives— parents, children, and spouses—remained eligible to immigrate outside these quotas. When all relatives were ‹nally brought within the regulated sphere in 1990, relatives were guaranteed 480,000 of 675,000 places. Congress gives relationship weight for a few different reasons. For one, getting relatives in is obviously in a person’s interest, whereas the bene‹ts of getting skilled laborers to immigrate can seem remote. In this sense, it is a preference for American citizens, not for foreigners. Relatives have also been seen to stabilize the country socially and economically. Particularly in the early part of the century, social welfare workers worried about the health and moral welfare of the immigrant men who had left their families behind. Allowing them to send for their wives relieved the public of the burden of caring for them and for absorbing the cost of the violence, sickness, and gambling that seemed to live in immigrant dormitories. Bringing their wives to the United States also kept their wages in the country, where they would multiply and bring more rapid prosperity. A ‹nal reason, though one for which no one argued explicitly, is that when immigrants are mostly relatives, immigrants are mostly of the same races as recently naturalized citizens. Eliminating selection by parentage was enormously important as a political and ethical statement, but the simultaneous enlargement of relatives’ preferences meant that immigrants were going to come from pretty much the same places. If one’s relatives were previously banned, one clearly could not join them in the United States. Relatives’ preference gave a momentum to the immigration stream, assuring continuity in country, race, language, wealth, and sometimes profession. Preferring relatives ful‹lls many separate and even contradictory demands at the same time. It appeases constituents, stops repatriation of wages, stabilizes families, and assures that the races, languages, and countries of origin of future immigrants will be almost identical to those of the recent past. Structural theories all anticipate that countries will seek to include those who can bene‹t it economically. What is a puzzle for all of them is not that economic preferences have been included, but that they have not
Structural Theories as Explanations
265
been central, they have declined as well as risen, and they have changed without apparent reference to changes in the U.S. economy. One possibility is that the country focuses on economic criteria when it competes with others for dominance. When sailing is clear, it indulges its citizens by preferring their relatives; when competition increases, though, preferences for relatives get scaled back. Realism and hegemonic stability theory were helpful in explaining change in the number of annual immigrants that federal policy would allow. Because structural theories are designed for such broad applications involving prediction of more or less of something, when they fared well and when they failed were fairly clear. These theories are less useful in helping to account for immigration policy regarding characteristics. Functionalism expects that policy will become more rational in economic terms. Abandoning race and national origin as criteria, instead favoring literacy and skills, is consistent with their expectations. That this liberalization escalated at the height of American hegemony is something that the hegemonic stability theorists might expect. But also true is that the standards for judging who should be excluded and who admitted followed the country’s changing understanding of the central threat that it faced, something that classical realists predicted. Each explains something if parsed and attached to one aspect of change.
Conclusion
By showing how a few factors create one central dynamic, structural theories attempt to explain broad phenomena clearly. They justify their ignorance of detail by arguing that minutia, while important, do not add much to an explanation, while they consume attention and resources. As explanations of American immigration policy in the twentieth century, structural explanations offer some surprises and some disappointments. When a theory anticipates an aspect of policy change, it does so well and accurately—but its predictive failure in other areas means that the causal mechanism it assumes, by which it justi‹es its prediction, must be wrong. The theory gets the right answer (in one area) for the wrong reasons. Realism and hegemonic stability can each plausibly explain the pattern of changes—or conservative nonchanges—in the immigration ceiling. Realism expects that states will pursue autarky unless they have no choice. Steadily reducing the proportion of immigrants cuts down the chaos and vulnerability that escalating immigration can signify. Hegemonic stability theory expects a country at the apex of hegemony to reveal a somewhat different set of policies than that which usually characterizes a self-protec-
266
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
tive country. Forgiving the mortgaged quotas and allowing immigrants to use the slots allotted them, which the United States did in the late 1950s to late 1960s, can be seen as the sort of gesture only a liberal hegemon would make. Power-based theories seem to help explain the direction of change. Theories that rely on liberal motives to some extent help to explain the nature of change. The hegemonic liberalism that can account for relaxation in the quantitative ceiling can help to explain the move toward liberal criteria in the mid-1960s. Functionalists, because they expect criteria to be more economically rational over time, would not be surprised that irrelevant characteristics such as race and, eventually, ideology were eliminated in favor of economic selection criteria. Classical realism can also shed some light on these changes, as it expects states to adjust their defenses as their enemies change. As the United States’ adversary shifted, the standards it used to judge immigrants acceptable changed in tandem. These mutually contradictory theories each can shed some light on this change since in it are con›ated two processes. The United States changed its assessment of what about its enemy was most threatening as it changed its understanding of who that enemy was. Not only did the country’s understanding of “good” immigrant characteristics become more liberal, but so did its understanding of “bad” and “enemy” characteristics. When Japan became the enemy in the nineteenth century, Americans construed the struggle between the United States and Japan as racial, so Japanese were excluded for racial reasons. When Japan became a threat in the 1980s, Americans construed the struggle as economic, so immigrants generally were excluded for economic reasons. Such is also true of China; Chinese were evaluated ‹rst in racial, then in alliance, then in ideological, and then in economic terms. The assumed link between what a people does and who it is has vanished. For this reason, theories that anticipate liberalization and those that anticipate a continued focus on the enemy are equally vindicated. Yet each of these theories anticipates these particular outcomes as a consequence of a speci‹c dynamic. While no structural theory should predict details, all should get the broad patterns; that is their justi‹cation for ignoring the details, and none can consistently explain the pattern of change we see. Even when neorealism, classical realism, hegemonic stability theory, and functionalism do get an immigration policy outcome right, they are wrong about trade, an area that each postulates should parallel immigration. Functionalism, which does the worst as an explanation of immigration policy, is likely to do relatively well on the question of trade, suggesting that realism’s strength as a prediction of, and explanation of, immigration policy conservatism is not generalizable. The causal processes that each theory postulates, if they were true, would result in a pattern of
Structural Theories as Explanations
267
outcomes: a certain type of trade policy, a certain level of numerical restriction, a certain standard to judge acceptable immigrants. If the pattern fails to materialize, that a theory got one right cannot be much more than coincidence. It cannot have been for the reason offered if that reason held in no other area. Therefore, even when a structural theory correctly predicts an immigration policy outcome, it must be wrong on the dynamic. Knowing the causal mechanism through which policies change is particularly important, if especially dif‹cult, in the case of macroprocesses. How and why a set of policies changes in particular ways—or refuses to budge, in spite of massive transformations in other areas—lie at the center of international relations scholarship. Elegant explanations are surely better than complex ones, especially when, as is the case with this exposition of immigration policy change, they are incomplete and leave unanswered questions. Yet if elegant theories do not explain the core dynamic of interest, their elegance does little good. Structural theories’ failure to explain the nature of and trends in immigration policy—a policy central to the preservation of contemporary state sovereignty—raises questions about their abilities to explain across issue-areas, and therefore to account for variation in the ways that even individual states preserve and use their sovereignty.
CHAPTER 10
Conclusion: Sovereignty, Things, and People
Sovereignty relies on jurisdiction over a population as well as a territory. With the development and spread of liberal nationalism, exclusive sovereignty has been valued and justi‹ed because of its importance in maintaining divisions among populations. Citizens value boundaries for their role in maintaining, or creating, a political community with unique traditions and values, a way of life. They are, both literally and ‹guratively, governments’ raison d’etat. When sovereignty is located in the people, controlling entry into and exit from that voting, resource- and rights-claiming population is crucial to protecting sovereignty. Governments, answerable to citizens and not to foreign governments, international organizations, or visiting aliens, seek to better the conditions of this bounded population, both by pursuing trade and investment and by limiting the growth of the claiming class. Because manipulating a population’s fertility and mortality horri‹es many publics, immigration policy becomes the only legitimate means to regulate the quantity and characteristics of a citizen population. In this way, immigration policy de‹nes who is inside and who outside a political system. Populist-nationalist justi‹cations for borders came to dominate thinking about sovereignty in the eighteenth century. The American and French Revolutions relied on the standard of popular consent for legitimacy in challenging a dominant center; the German and Italian uni‹cations a century later drew more openly on cultural traits to unify a population spread among many political units. Nationalism infused theorizing about the rights of states and populations. The nation-state became the ideal to which both states and nations aspired. The nation-state was strong because it was legitimate. This minimized internal con›ict and confusion, made communication possible, which eased commerce, and harnessed the energy that the nation voluntarily gave to the state.1 This ideal supported, as it grew from, the norm of self-determination, which gained a power of its own strong enough to legitimize sovereignty for colonial territories and ethnically distinct populations against the wishes of the imperial center. At the same time, liberalism guided the industrial nation-states’ eco268
Conclusion
269
nomic policies, including those toward land, minerals, and airspace as well as toward goods and ‹nancial ›ows. Private property was so central a value early on that governments like the United States pledged to support it as their raison d’être. Private ownership, however, extended to national ownership only in the communist countries in the twentieth century. Liberalism supported a division of spheres; the economic one was to remain in private hands. Free trade was the private choice. It became such a powerful ideal that even its detractors acknowledged its ability to generate the largest quantities of goods most ef‹ciently. The public sphere was political; the private was economic. Liberalism separated people as citizens, their public personae, from people as workers and owners, their private personae. This separation made possible the political regulation of persons as citizens and the economic deregulation of persons as laborers or investors. Nationalism and the ideal of the nation-state further justi‹ed the regulation of persons as citizens. Together, these produced states who identi‹ed with and served citizen populations that acted as nations politically and as individuals economically; these states produced a system de‹ned by strong norms—and government interests—in favor of nation-states’ rights to exclude persons and opposed to their rights to exclude goods. Territories, like things and information, are to be bought and sold. The mutual exclusiveness on which “sovereignty” rests obtains with regard to persons, not things. The result is a system of states that are mutually exclusive because each has a set of citizens unique to it. Asserting the “‹nal and absolute authority” that de‹nes sovereignty over people rather than over things both creates the liberal nationalist system and re›ects the dominance of a peculiar blend of liberal and nationalist values throughout the international system. It has become a norm that guides countries’ policies and how they are justi‹ed, even when the norm’s origin is wholly outside a country. It is used by states whose ‹rst contact with modern sovereignty was colonization, and by those that seek to colonize others. In an earlier period, both territories and populations de‹ned a country’s boundaries. The European empires extended their reach by claiming lands where their citizens had gone and claiming citizens wherever they took land. Mercantilist empires established exclusiveness of territory and population as they gathered toward their centers everything of value that they came across. Their inclusion of population as a source of power additional to territory re›ected changes in production that affected state power. When production began to replace extraction, labor’s quality began to matter a great deal. During the previous era, in which absolutist states staked out the ‹rst exclusive zones, territory provided the basis for
270
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
security and wealth. The industrial era that followed the mercantilist period relied on volumes of wage labor. When welfare guarantees supplemented the industrial outcome, persons were no longer clearly bene‹cial. Each came with a ‹xed cost, including schooling, infrastructure, and the minimal ‹nancial and public health measures necessary to support life and prevent disease, yet each did not yield returns to the state commensurate with this cost. Skills that promised high productivity became of more value. Barring those likely to receive public goods without contributing suf‹ciently to the public purse became more important. Changes in technologies of production and convictions about legitimate authority changed the basis of state power and shifted the foundation of sovereignty from land, to people and land, to people. That these changes were general, becoming shared by an increasing number of countries in each era, does not indicate that they were unchosen or inevitable. The institutions that people faced acted entirely as constraints only in the shortest of short terms. A lobbyist worried about the next day’s votes, or a lawyer who has to meet a court-imposed deadline, or a student who has to choose classes all face choices that are limited by the institutions within which they have to operate. But even extending the time frame a fairly short amount, say a year or even a month, allows the institution to be malleable. The bills that legislatures consider can be changed, and so can rules about what gets reviewed when; additional precedents mean that the law is never the same; universities change their courses, their faculties, their admissions and graduation requirements. Even the most powerful institutions are impermanent. The cold war, for example, organized whole societies as well as defense and research strategies, but the institutions it spawned did not survive its end. These sorts of institutional changes did not “occur” from “broad social forces,” they resulted from pressure exerted by the actions that individuals and groups took, whether those actions were intended to have the consequences they did, that is, they were the result of choices people made, or not. In the same way that change results from a pattern of new actions and new decisions, stability results from repeated choice. States, as well as legislatures and colleges, churches and corporations, last because people choose to support them. Their choices are affected by the institutions’ presence—an advocate would not lobby, or lobby in a certain way, without a legislature there to lobby—but are not determined entirely by it. People are not robots, or at least are not always robots. Beliefs about democracy and public accountability, as well as habits and a lack of re›ection, support legislatures. If minds change, legislatures falter. In this way, the inertia of institutions is not comparable to the inertia of a body in space. Momentum in social orders requires continued input of energy, which is
Conclusion
271
scarce and brings costs. Social practices have to be justi‹able and useful to continue. That they once were cannot explain their endurance. When structures act on people, they do so by shaping, though not dictating, people’s beliefs about their options. Those beliefs then support or undermine social structures. Decisions lie at the nexus between institutions and outcomes. When necessity is not overwhelming, choice is not an illusion; structures then do not determine outcomes. In these cases, people have real choices to make. If they are not irrational, by de‹nition their reasons dictate their choices. Social decision-making demands an additional step, that of relating one’s reasons to the public interest. Positions that qualify as public interest arguments have to promote public values, consider consequences, and apply to all citizens. This requirement ‹lters arguments, bene‹ting some and leaving others behind. In this way, values and interests merge to set standards by which to judge options. What constitutes the substance of a public interest varies among countries, but also changes over time as choices change. Which public values are served, which consequences seem good, or even relevant, and who counts as the public in whose interest a government acts can all be different from one time period to the next. The France of the Revolution and the France of Napoleon conceived of the public in different ways, pursued different values in its name, and evaluated results according to different standards. Some American colonies established themselves as homogeneous religious enclaves; states later explicitly eschewed religious categories. Originally the public in whose name the government acted was made up only of white, propertied men; over time it expanded to include the propertyless, women, and nonwhites. It still excludes people by birthplace. That too could conceivably change. In this way, borders change meaning as well as location. Who is inside a set of boundaries depends on who is outside it. It is possible to say both that if we are hill-dwellers, then they are valley-dwellers, and that if they are valley-dwellers, then we are hill-dwellers. The distinction depends on the source of change, on whether a change in self-perception changes how a group interprets outsiders, or whether changes beyond the borders force a reinterpretation of what is unique about those who remain inside. Even when territorial boundaries stay in the same place, what is seen to be most important about those boundaries changes over time. This changes how those boundaries are valued, and what about them is seen to be worthwhile or valueless. Throughout the twentieth century, population replaced territory as sovereignty’s core terrain. Boundaries among populations gained in importance as the boundaries dividing one land from another lost their centrality to a country’s self-de‹nition. At the same time, what was impor-
272
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
tant about these boundaries dividing populations from one another changed enormously. Broad changes in social ties and economic processes have simultaneously decreased the practical importance of territory and increased the value people place on social identities historically associated with territories. Territories are important in the advanced industrial states largely for their symbolic value in determining who is a citizen by birth and who is not. Borders now tend more to impede than to protect people’s economic goals and, to probably a lesser extent, their security goals. As functionalists expected, borders have become less relevant to many issues that interest people, and governments have been helping to reduce borders’ importance as material barriers. The cultural and economic “networks of interdependence” that have helped to universalize markets in goods and ideas have not, however, so far replaced national symbols and institutions as objects of people’s loyalty or the primary bases of their identities. The difference between the economic and political spheres is not objective. It is the result of very different ways of thinking about and justifying boundaries. In many ways, markets and states are similar, and to an extent even inseparable. Markets and states are each infused with complicated hierarchies and rules allocating power to those who participate in them. To function, each relies on a differentiation of resources, skills, and authority that produces inequality; to function properly, each must operate in a way to ameliorate this inequality. Wealth and power are, moreover, closely tied. If the wealthy choose, wealth can become power; if the powerful choose, power can become wealth. Yet markets and states are not justi‹ed identically. In fact, the liberal market and the nation-state operate very differently and produce very different social relationships. Markets seek to disguise the “nonmarket,” or power, relationships that lurk behind what is produced and bought. Products are to be apprehended as if their history made no difference. Only an item’s quality and utility for the consumer determine its value. Marxists and those who have followed in the materialist tradition rightly point out that all sorts of nonmarket factors enter into who produced and buys what. Labor is not free; even alienated wage labor is not free to move to the highest wage areas, and much of what is produced, for example, children or the daily maintenance of families, is accomplished without remuneration. Pure markets are, political economists argue, an illusion. But the illusion works. It is precisely this illusory quality that separates the “economic” from the “political.” In the economic realm, people are to operate according to market principles of supply, demand, value, and price. When any other of a product’s characteristics, such as its country of origin, matter to its purchaser, the market has failed. Markets oper-
Conclusion
273
ate when the politics that underlie them are invisible. This means that they operate when political boundaries, as well as the race, religion, or sex of a producer, are irrelevant. Economic boundaries are for command economies, not for liberal ones. National boundaries are, by contrast, central to the “political” sphere and in fact de‹ne it. Any political system, whether a democracy or a kingdom, has to establish boundaries within which central authority extends. As Craig Calhoun argues, “The modern notion of a popular will always assumed the existence of some recognizably bounded and internally integrated population.”2 De‹ning a domestic sphere means, at the same time, de‹ning the area over which authority does not extend and in which claimants have no right to be heard. Unlike the market, the nation needs boundaries in order to exist. In politics, unlike in markets, who is making a claim (product) matters. Creating an “in” creates an “out”; the rules describing the separation outline the value that the boundary has for those who make it. The nationalist ideal justi‹es both the creation and the maintenance of boundaries. The idea of popular sovereignty followed the French Revolution; it spread throughout the world, giving rise to claims for “national self-determination.” The availability of the nationalist justi‹cation for independence in fact allowed the creation of many states whose conformity to the European model was tenuous.3 When more than one state established distinct economic and political spheres, with boundaries and realms over which sovereign authority would be exerted, they created a distinct international system. The logics by which international systems have operated did not arise spontaneously from economic and political imperatives; rather, they resulted from social choices that could have been made differently. Borders, as Friedrich Kratochwil notes, are places of contact as well as of separation.4 What purpose separation serves depends on who is on the other side of the boundary. All of the characteristics that can distinguish people from one another—ascriptive group characteristics like race, or sex, or birthplace, acquired group characteristics like ideology or religion, ascriptive individual characteristics like beauty or size, and individually acquired characteristics such as education, skills, disease, or merit— all of these can provide a basis for establishing a boundary. Because identi‹cation has this oppositional nature, identities cannot be said to develop autonomously, in isolation, but should be seen as dependent on their environments. And environments change. From this standpoint were drawn three interrelated theses about how American immigration policies were established, then evolved. The ‹rst held that immigration policy is about sovereignty in practice as well as in theory. When legislators and other members of a public talk about
274
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
whether to establish or change the boundaries that separate their population from others, they believe themselves to be discussing sovereignty. An examination of the public record showed that sovereignty was not only the central justi‹cation for the original restriction, but was also raised before the passage of every subsequent piece of immigration legislation. Throughout all periods, American legislators understood sovereignty to demand control over the exclusive population of American citizens. Recourse to sovereignty as a reason for control changed very little over the past century. In the mid-1920s, Milton Garber declared that “in the exercise of our inherent powers of sovereignty we have the undoubted right to prohibit the entrance of any or all immigrants or prescribe the conditions under which they may enter.”5 In 1950, Samuel Hobbs declared that “the exercise of that sovereign power by the United States of America should not be hampered, limited, nor thwarted by any other nation. If it be, by just so much has our Nation lost its sovereignty and independence.”6 The turn from isolationism did not change this view as it related to citizens, although it did change that related to markets. In the 1960s, when American policy was global and expansionist, Strom Thurmond pointed out that “individuals, and groups, including nations, have an absolute and unchallenged right to have preferences for other individuals or groups, and nothing could be more natural than a preference based on a sense of identity.”7 Although sameness of culture or political belief was politically acceptable as a basis for de‹ning criteria governing inclusion, Congress’s plenary rights allowed it to de‹ne the boundaries separating citizen and noncitizen on any basis it chose, whether that be individual achievement or hair color. To give up the right to be arbitrary with regard to others’ populations was to give up sovereignty. Throughout the twentieth century, legislators re›ected on the centrality of immigration policy to national identity and the sovereignty of the American nation-state. Each era had its eloquent observers. In 1980, George Huddleston observed that “immigration presents us with the most basic of all social and legal problems: Is the concept of the nation-state legitimate?”8 Any of the statements involving the relationship between sovereignty and decisions about the legitimacy of exclusion could have been made in any of the eras. What immigration policy protects actually changes over time. Usually assumed to be given and unproblematic, a national identity, or what a society values about itself, changes over time along with changes in the international environment. Competition and foreign involvement change people’s interests and values, hence what they value or fear in potential citizens. Whereas in quantity countries’ immigration policies are protective, in terms of characteristics they are adaptive. Changes in desired immigrant
Conclusion
275
characteristics mirror changes in a country’s understanding of who it is competing with and why. Although concern with sovereignty was constant, what legislators pointed to as the greatest threat to sovereignty was not the same in each period. Part of the second thesis concerned the impetus for change in immigration policy. As a foreign policy, it was argued, immigration policy is directed toward, and responds to, what is beyond a country’s borders. Certain types of changes in the environment that surrounds a state will prompt it to reconsider those borders. In the 1920s, this was World War I; in the 1940s and 1950s, legislators pointed to World War II. By the 1960s, the cold war de‹ned America’s context. As Dwight Eisenhower argued, decolonization later presented American hegemony with a challenge that it had to meet in part through immigration reforms: “Our position of world leadership demands that, in partnership with the other free nations of the world, we be in a position to grant . . . asylum.”9 In 1984, foreign economic competition produced “a time of economic transition,” so new immigration policies were “necessary to keep American industry in the ballgame.”10 Because the impetus was external, it changed as the environment changed. This meant that who would be excluded changed; or, more accurately, that the basis for deciding whom to accept and whom to exclude would change, even if that did not alter the eligibility of particular individuals to immigrate. The central role of justi‹cation in shaping policy is perhaps seen most clearly here. When Congress chose to base immigration on race or “national origin,” the consequence was to favor those from northwestern Europe (England, Ireland, Germany), to regulate those from southern and eastern Europe (Italy, Bohemia, Romania), and to bar those from Asia (China, Japan, India). Changing the basis for exclusion from race to ideology was both politically and morally signi‹cant. Its effect was still to favor those from northwestern Europe, to regulate those from southern and eastern Europe, and to bar those from Asia. The map of acceptable and unacceptable races was similar to that of friendly and threatening ideologies. The reasons for excluding people changed more than the people who were actually excluded. That the justi‹cation for excluding people is more important than the resulting pattern of which individuals are excluded is revealed most strongly by the 1965 immigration reforms. Up to 1965, national origin and ideology governed immigration. In 1965, racial criteria were eliminated, but so were slots weighted by country of origin. Instead, every country would have an equal chance of sending emigrants to the United States, and those emigrants would not be classi‹ed according to race. This renunciation of ascriptive criteria was hugely important as a statement of prin-
276
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
ciple. In abandoning racial and national criteria, the United States declared to its and others’ citizens that achievement rather than birth gave individuals value. At the same time, preferences for citizens’ relatives were included in immigration policy. This was justi‹ed by the government’s duty to serve the citizens’ needs ‹rst, and to serve the public interest by helping to reunite families and to prevent repatriation of wages. Policy treated all citizens equally, as it had treated all foreign states equally. The reasons that the country would use when evaluating immigrants shifted 180 degrees. Yet the consequence was to alter the stream of actual immigrants by perhaps two degrees.11 Relatives were largely going to be of the same race and culture of the citizens who invited them to immigrate. The 1965 reforms allowed the Ghanaian quota to equal the Irish quota, but if no Ghanaians had been allowed to immigrate before 1965, they clearly could not join their relatives. Moreover, even had the law not preferred relatives, the costs of migrating mean that new migrants went to places where they have friends and job prospects, that is, to places where others in their situation have already been. The result was to alter the stream of actual migration relatively little, while altering enormously the basis for allowing immigrants. Because the resulting changes were relatively small, it would be dif‹cult to argue that the change in justi‹cation was merely a smoke screen for effecting a shift in the migrant stream. While changing the justi‹cation for choosing immigrants did not necessarily prevent speci‹c individuals from immigrating, or give others an advantage, it did in some important sense change who immigrated. Instead of “white, anticommunist, Irish” Ann who had been socialized into the “Anglo democratic participatory” system, Ann immigrated as the sister of John, a citizen. Changing the justi‹cation in a sense changed the immigrants. Also changing were the arguments about the public interest to be served by immigration restrictions. The ‹nal thesis about immigration policy held that arguments shaped outcomes by selecting the options that could be considered and by forcing reasons to be given. These reasons became a resource for all sides. The requirement of consensus-building meant that to reach a majority, a policy had to be justi‹able in terms that not only met public interest requirements but received widespread support. Arguments were not additive; the deliberative process was an intellectual one in which arguments were revised and transformed. The democratic process in this way did not just select among arguments, but helped to create new ones, and in this way changed how the public interest in one area was understood. The policies that resulted from such public debates are unpredictable
Conclusion
277
knowing only the tangible interests behind the advocates and the opponents. Unemployment, immigrant pressure groups, public opinion shifts, and party politics are all unsatisfactory explanations for the pattern of policy change. The dates of immigration policy reforms coincide not with bad economic times but with prosperous periods; groups cannot be in a legislative district to press for their compatriots unless national policy has already favored their entry; the public is always opposed to increasing the level of immigration; partisanship is signi‹cant in only half of the roll calls on immigration and is in almost all cases less signi‹cant than regionalism. If immigrant groups with the strongest ties to their home countries— groups of recent immigrants—fueled liberalization of immigration policy, the 1920s, when the percentage of foreign-born was the highest, should have been more liberal than the 1960s, when it was the lowest. If economic disaster provoked either rational attempts to reduce the labor force or economic scapegoating of immigrants, the Depression and the late 1970s should have been peak attempts to revamp policy. Instead, the 1930s saw no proposals to overhaul immigration policy and saw an in›ow reduced more by prospective immigrants’ reluctance to enter a depressed economy—and their desire to leave it, once in—than by the U.S. government’s legal or administrative efforts. The 1970s saw not only no efforts to reduce the numbers of immigrants, but the single largest ad hoc acceptance of immigrants in the country’s history, with the welcoming of the Indochinese refugees. Since public opinion about immigration seems to remain constant, it cannot account for any pattern of change. The requirement to reach a majority, and the requirement that that majority be able to justify its position to its constituency, de›ect the policy process from one in which tangible interests are simply traded and compromised (each side moves toward the other’s position) toward one in which participants must succeed in rede‹ning their own or others’ interests, and must do so in a way that is consistent with “the public interest.” Arguments are central to the process of reaching majority under these circumstances. Tracing the arguments that different sides made for and against immigration policy change in the twentieth century explains outcomes in a way that is impossible otherwise. It explains otherwise anomalous outcomes. In the 1920s, incorporating liberal arguments produced a more restrictive policy than the liberals had advocated. Negotiation and learning partly replaced compromise. Consensus did not involve each side moving toward the other, but some person or group synthesizing the valuebased arguments in such a way that one outcome could be broadly justi‹ed. In the 1920s, liberals raised the specter of racial discrimination against American citizens, which they argued would follow from a system
278
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
that delared, in effect, that immigrants from some regions were more desirable than others. This effect of the quota system, they argued, violated the principle of equality among citizens on which the public culture was based. Those who advocated restriction had to meet this challenge. They did so by changing the basis on which quotas were allocated from the national origin of recent immigrants to the national origin of the entire American population. The consequence was to include large blocks of spaces for the English, Irish, and Germans, who immigrated earlier in the nineteenth century but who were in a minority more recently, and in this way to shrink still further the number of immigrants from southern and eastern Europe available to immigrate. The consequence was the reverse of that hoped for by the liberals, yet many of them were forced to support it because it met their main objections. In the 1950s, recent experience with Asian allies and with Nazism brought leverage against racial exclusions. Because the victory became, over the course of the war, not just against German aggression but against fascism and racial supremacism, the United States had to cleanse its statutes of provisions that mimicked its adversaries. If the opponent had slid from a generic aggressor to a racial supremacist, the United States, as its opponent, had to identify itself not just as a defender of the peace, but as the defender of a speci‹c type of peace, one that excluded racialism. As Samuel Dickstein argued, the country “should not give such great preference to the Nordic race, the person with the blond hair, the Nazi who was guilty of murder.”12 Nazism had to be denounced. At the same time, Japan, not Germany, had brought the United States into the war, and Asians were considered much less assimilable than Europeans; complicating this yet further was the fact that the cold war involved both European and Asian adversaries and both European and Asian allies. The situation that resulted for the United States was an anticommunist immigration policy intended to protect the country in the cold war, overlaying a bizarre compromise regarding race: Nazis would be excluded as ideologues, but neither favored nor excluded as Aryans; southern Europeans would be admitted as refugees from communism rather than excluded as Slavs, and Asians would be eligible for admission—but would still be identi‹ed primarily as Asians. A decade later, U.S. hegemony made American immigration policy appear insular and petty. To ‹ght the cold war and retain credibility, liberals in Congress agreed that the American stance generally should be global, liberal, and favoring equality. Conservatives, who wanted at least to retain numerical restrictions but really to extend them, argued that granting all countries an equal quota, while preserving the exception for the Western Hemisphere, which the liberals advocated, was in fact con-
Conclusion
279
trary to the principle upon which they claimed to base their decision. If the liberals truly meant what they said about equality, argued the conservatives, they would bring the Western Hemisphere under the numerical umbrella. Not to do so was to practice favoritism, offensive to some domestic districts and to all European, African, and Asian countries. The liberals had to agree to extend restrictions because their case was argued in the liberals’ own terms. In the late 1980s, arguments about immigrants centered on their economic motivations and consequences. Those in favor of increasing immigration used aggregate measures, arguing that immigrants bene‹ted the economy generally. Those who opposed increases relied on sectoral measures, arguing that immigration hurt a particular class or part of the economy. They also argued, however, that the enforcement of sanctions against illegal immigrants, which they advocated, would hurt some groups and not others. Those liberal on the question of immigrant quantity based their arguments on utilitarian claims, such as the improvement of average welfare; those conservative on this issue focused on the rights of particular groups. The “compromise” that the liberals achieved was, again, a synthesis of principled claims rather than a bargain in which each side gave in some. It involved setting the legal ceiling just above where the de facto ceiling was, preferring those who would create jobs, and sanctioning employers who did not obtain proper documentation for all workers, regardless of race. By adopting the conservatives’ language of civil rights regarding particular groups, the liberals avoided having to allow for their “economic rights” to a piece of the growing pie—though that was the conservatives’ original grievance. In the context of trade ›ows, information and media transfers, and private travel, immigration policy must be seen as conservative, if not even reactionary. The advanced industrial countries all seek to extend regulatory control over access to citizenship and to limit the numbers of immigrants, while they cheer economic integration. There are two ways in which it is appropriate to describe American immigration policy as liberal. First, the United States has altered the bases on which it excludes and selects immigrants to correspond much more closely to the liberal ideal. Whereas the exclusion criteria once emphasized race and treated men and women differently, they shifted toward characteristics over which people had some control, such as their political convictions and their skills. Second, the United States has promoted, internationally, a set of liberal norms, such as those of open emigration and non-refoulement, and has tried to set an example for other countries to follow. As James Holli‹eld has argued, compared to what some international relations theories would expect, liberalism permeates the grounds
280
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
for exclusion in Western countries’ policies toward immigrants, an outcome understandable only by reference to the liberalism of United States hegemony.13 Compared to a go-it-alone system, the current system, enforced by the United States, is liberal. Compared to other countries’ policies, or to its policies in other areas, American immigration policy is profoundly conservative. On a per capita basis, the United States accepts fewer immigrants than many countries to which emigrants attempt to travel, including countries of permanent migration, such as the European countries, as well as countries such as Thailand, Congo, and Sudan, which provide ‹rst—and often last—asylum to millions of refugees. Over time, immigration as a proportion of the U.S. population has also declined, and regulatory control has extended over more groups each decade. By 1990 every immigrant had become subject to a numerical limit, which was de jure about what it had been de facto since limits were ‹rst established at the beginning of the century. In the context of its history in this area and its policies in other issue-areas, American immigration policy is quite conservative. American policy has also been transformed as the country’s place in the world has changed. Congress argued for the conservatism embedded in the immigration ceiling at the same time it advocated liberalizing the standards used to determine which sorts of people could immigrate. Eliminating geographical quotas indicated a shift toward the view that America faced, generically, all others; shifting emphasis from simple negative exclusion toward positively de‹ned preference, and from moral to ideological to economic grounds, shows that how and why these “all others” mattered were transformed as Americans identi‹ed different threats and purposes. Originally detailed quotas by race and country were supplemented by a simple two-tier preference system within them. Over time these have reversed. Quotas were extended to both hemispheres from a sole focus on Europe, then consolidated within each, and ‹nally combined into a single worldwide ceiling. At the same time, preference categories doubled and redoubled to sort those who would enter. The trend has been away from a focus on ascriptive, immutable characteristics, such as race or birthplace, toward those which are acquired. Even if in only a limited way, education, marriage, disease, or profession take into account experience. Calling a policy “protectionist” immediately raises the question of who is being protected from what. American policy protects citizens, or rather access to citizenship. This, not literal access to territory, or even access to American wealth, has been its central concern. Noncitizens wishing to visit are restricted only in ways whose purpose is to minimize the likelihood of their staking a political claim, for example, requiring an exit before granting a new tourist visa or demanding proof of full ‹nancial sup-
Conclusion
281
port before granting a student visa. Noncitizens are in fact encouraged to take advantage of access to U.S. territory not only as tourists but as purchasers of that territory: as real estate, businesses, government bonds. Protection instead operates through restriction of those who, upon entry, receive the right to petition for citizenship. Protection from what? Whom policy seeks to exclude has changed, or rather the grounds upon which law excludes (perhaps the same) people have changed. Protection implies threat, and this suggests that Americans’ understanding of what threatens them has changed. Particular efforts to exclude reveal points of perceived weakness—weakness de‹ned relative to others. Moral ‹ber, physical health, race, ideology, and economic potential are not even mutually translatable, and they have been combined only partially and inconsistently over time. At different times, the United States has seen each of these as the most important difference between itself and its competitors. As countries evolved jointly, so did Americans’ perceptions of the threats and opportunities that other countries’ citizens symbolized. Involvement has led to different lessons in other areas. After World War I, the country shied away from foreign entanglements in trade, alliances, and international organization. Just after World War II and in the mid-1960s, it pursued such entanglements aggressively. By the late 1980s this sequence had reversed, and severe economic problems raised questions about America’s chronic support for overseas allies and military interventions. The United States, the focus of this study, is only one of many states that rely on immigration policy to maintain a sovereign political sphere. The United States is, in fact, one of the gentlest and most liberal of the advanced industrial states. Australia, when it sought settlers, explicitly sought white settlers; like nineteenth-century California, it pursued a “white state” policy while it pursued diversi‹cation and integration into the world market. Japan throughout the twentieth century has refused to allocate citizenship to some minorities, notably Koreans, born on Japanese soil. Japanese citizenship is a complicated mixture of race, culture, and commitment that the government does not believe should be granted to just anyone born in, or socialized into, Japanese life. Most similar to Japan in many respects is Germany. Like Japan and many other states, most prominently Israel, citizenship accompanies descent rather than place of birth. During the period prior to uni‹cation, West German policy recognized all ethnic Germans descended from persons living within the pre–World War II borders as presumptive citizens.14 To claim citizenship, all such persons had to do was apply. Ethnicity itself, rather than language or any other cultural trait, brought the inclusion. The non-Ger-
282
Immigration and the Politics of American Sovereignty
manic guest workers imported primarily from Turkey and Yugoslavia were ineligible for citizenship unless at the express invitation of the German state, regardless of their years of residency, place of birth, skills, culture, or contribution to German society. Turks, in the German view, were simply not Germans. This view held and developed throughout the period of West Germany’s integration into the European and global markets. France and the United Kingdom have a somewhat more expansive method of determining citizenship, based more on territorial birthplace than on descent.15 Although those born in the territory to noncitizen parents are not automatically granted citizenship, the requirements for naturalization, such as residence and a knowledge of the language, are easily within reach for those born and raised in these countries. Acceptance of and participation in the public institutions that these states see as their greatest attribute is central to citizenship; ethnicity is relevant insofar as it affects one’s ability to integrate. The other West European countries, though they vary a great deal in the criteria they use to allocate citizenship to those born inside as well as outside their borders, all guard their abilities to determine to whom they are accountable. How important the distinction between economic integration and nationalist autonomy is can be seen, perhaps, most clearly in the policies that the European Union has—and has not—adopted with regard to the mobility of EU citizens.16 A central part of the reforms associated with the Single European Act allowed workers to migrate freely within the Union territories. Like goods, labor could move to the areas of highest reward, and in this way, it was hoped, the geographical maldistribution of labor and capital throughout the territories would dissolve. What has never been intended and is not on the agenda is free movement of citizens, that is, allowing individuals rather than states to determine who may accede to citizenship status. Workers can move across boundaries and thereby change their economic identities, but when citizens move, they keep their original status. Not only have the EU member countries made no collective efforts to merge economic and political movement, but the countries individually have scaled back access to citizenship. As they pursue economic integration, they seek to protect the separateness and autonomy of the nation. This study has implications for international relations theory more generally. Both systems theories, such as neorealism, functionalism, and dependency theory, and process theories such as those analyzing the effects of bureaucracies, or psychological models, or interest aggregation, take institutions for granted. Whether sovereignty, a bureaucracy, or ideologies help or hurt one’s ability to achieve one’s goals, they operate as givens, and primarily as constraints. What is studied then is how the insti-
Conclusion
283
tutions eliminate choices or are biased toward certain actors and thus channel outcomes. This makes logical sense. If one is to study behavior of a system, collective, or institution, one must be able to take that unit’s existence as granted and unproblematic. This cannot be done when the structures themselves are the independent variable, which they must be when the central question deals with fundamental institutions. To address the question of where states come from, one cannot take states as givens. Structures arise from broad social processes, but these, moreover, result from choice. How this process occurs has barely been approached in international relations theory. Structural theories take sovereignty for granted; process theories take the domestic institutions that shape the policy process for granted. What varies are then groups’ strategies for achieving their objectives. Yet structures are ›uid over the long run, and when they do operate they affect incentives, not determine outcomes. If they mandated actions, then history would be predetermined, its endpoint knowable. Choice would be illusory, decisions irrelevant. The point here is empirical as well as theoretical: institutions emerge from what societies choose; therefore, institutional constancy results from repeated choice in the face of change, and institutional change results from new choices. The causal mechanism that underlies institutional change is social decisions. These can be studied for their own sake, regardless of whether they produce outcomes different from those that abstract theories predict. They also can and should be studied when the causal mechanism at the center of a structural theory has to be wrong. It is also encouraging, as well as right, to think of sovereignty as a policy choice.
APPENDIX A
Data on Unemployment, Tariffs, Imports, Exports, GNP, and the Immigration Ceiling, 1890–1990
Data on Immigration
Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report. Washington, DC: GPO, various years. Immigration and Naturalization Service, Annual Report. Washington, DC: GPO, various years. Immigration and Naturalization Service, Statistical Yearbook of the Immigration and Naturalization Service. Washington, DC: GPO, various years. Immigration and Naturalization Service, unpublished annual statistics. Data on the United States Economy
Bureau of the Census, Statistical Abstract of the United States. Washington, DC: GPO, various years. Bureau of the Census, Historical Statistics of the United States, Colonial Times to 1970. Washington, DC: GPO, 1974. John Kendrick, Productivity Trends in the United States. Princeton: Princeton University Press for the NBER, 1961. Simon Kuznets, Capital in the American Economy: Its Formation and Financing. Princeton: Princeton University Press for the NBER, 1961. Simon Kuznets and Ernest Rubin, Immigration and the Foreign Born. NBER Occasional Paper 46, 1954. Data on the Global Population
United Nations, Demographic Yearbook. New York: United Nations, various years. United Nations, Historical Supplement to the Demographic Yearbook, 1948–1978. Ann Arbor: Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research, 1982. 285
286
Appendixes
Data on the Global Economy
United Nations, Statistical Yearbook. New York: United Nations, various years. United Nations, Yearbook of International Trade Statistics. New York: United Nations, various years. United Nations Conference on Trade and Development, Handbook of International Trade and Development Statistics. New York: United Nations, 1983. B. R. Mitchell, International Historical Statistics. International Telecommunications Union, Yearbook of Common Carrier Telecommunication Statistics. Geneva: United Nations.
APPENDIX B
Party and Region in Congressional Voting
Note: Every representative not a Republican was classified as a Democrat. This includes Progressive Republicans, Socialists, American Laborites, and Farmer Laborites. Chi-squares reported exclude “not voting” because the ordinal significance does not vary.
A.
House of Representatives, 1921 (Quota Act) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
52 22 50 124
80 3 23 106
85 6 31 122
59 2 16 77
276 33 120 429
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 37.59, p = .0000
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
179 17 93 289
97 16 37 140
276 33 120 429
Chi-square 2.26, not significant
287
288 B.
Appendixes Senate, 1921 (Quota Act) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
14 0 6 20
21 0 5 26
13 1 2 16
30 0 4 34
78 1 17 96
Yes No Not voting Total
Chi-square 4.70, not significant
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
44 0 12 56
34 1 5 40
78 1 17 96
Chi-square 1.27, not significant
C.
House of Representatives, 1924 (National Origins) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
53 43 26 122
83 2 20 105
101 15 11 127
71 2 6 79
308 62 63 433
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 78.23, p = .0000
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
161 27 34 222
147 35 29 211
308 62 63 433
Chi-square 1.57, not significant
D.
House of Representatives, 1948 (Displaced Persons) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
99 5 16 120
50 46 5 101
76 23 17 116
64 17 11 92
289 91 49 429
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 51.62, p = .0000
Appendixes
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
177 36 30 243
112 55 19 186
289 91 49 429
289
Chi-square 13.21, p = .0000
E.
Senate, 1952 (Humphrey-Lehman) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
12 5 3 20
4 19 3 26
5 8 3 16
6 19 9 34
27 51 18 96
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 14.06, p = .0010
Republican
Democrat
Total
7 25 13 45
20 28 5 51
27 51 18 96
Yes No Not voting Total
Chi-square 3.8, p almost .05
F. House of Representatives, 1952 (McCarranWalter Override) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
54 65 4 123
77 7 18 102
81 30 4 115
66 10 14 90
278 112 40 430
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 65.2, p = .0000
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
171 23 7 201
107 89 33 229
278 112 40 430
Chi-square 53.62, p = .0000
290 G.
Appendixes Senate, 1952 (McCarran-Walter Override) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
6 10 4 20
19 5 2 26
10 5 1 16
22 6 6 34
57 26 13 96
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 9.76, p = .0100
Republican
Democrat
Total
32 7 6 45
25 19 7 51
57 26 13 96
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 6.12, p = .0200
H.
Senate, 1957 (Kennedy) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
16 0 4 20
18 4 8 30
11 0 4 15
25 0 10 35
70 4 26 100
West
Total
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 9.99, p = .0100
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
35 1 10 46
30 3 16 49
65 4 26 95
Chi-square 1.26, not significant
I.
House of Representatives, 1965 (Hart-Cellar) Northeast
South
Midwest
104 0 4 108
35 62 8 105
97 13 2 112
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 131.18, p = .0000
82 20 5 107
318 95 19 432
Appendixes Republican
Democrat
Total
110 22 6 138
208 73 13 294
318 95 19 432
Yes No Not voting Total
291
Chi-square 4.4, p = .05
J. House of Representatives, 1965 (Hart-Celler Conference Report) Northeast
South
Midwest
97 1 10 108
48 46 10 104
100 5 7 112
Yes No Not voting Total
West 75 17 15 107
Total 320 69 42 431
Chi-square 93.62, p = .0000
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
119 10 11 140
101 59 31 291
320 69 42 431
Chi-square 13.19, p = .0010
K.
Senate, 1965 (Hart-Celler Conference Report) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
18 1 1 20
10 16 0 26
15 0 1 16
33 1 4 38
76 18 6 100
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 41.86, p = .0000
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
22 3 5 30
54 15 1 70
76 18 6 100
Chi-square 1.12, not significant
292 L.
Appendixes House of Representatives, 1986 (IRCA) Northeast
South
Midwest
59 27 7 93
47 47 10 104
57 36 13 106
Yes No Not voting Total
West 67 56 6 129
Total 230 166 36 432
Chi-square 7.48, p = .025
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
64 103 13 180
166 63 23 252
230 166 36 432
Chi-square 46.30, p = .0000
M. House of Representatives, 1986 (IRCA Conference Report) Northeast
South
Midwest
67 29 3 99
47 50 7 104
61 38 5 104
Yes No Not voting Total
West 63 56 6 125
Total 238 173 21 432
Chi-square 10.88, p = .005
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
75 92 10 177
163 81 11 255
238 173 21 432
Chi-square 19.50, p = .0000
N.
Senate, 1986 (IRCA Conference Report)
Yes No Not voting Total
Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
14 5 1 20
17 6 3 26
14 1 1 16
18 12 8 38
63 24 13 100
Chi-square 5.64, not significant
Appendixes
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
29 15 8 52
34 9 5 48
63 24 13 100
293
Chi-square 1.89, not significant
O. Senate, 1988 (Immigration Act of 1990, early version) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
19 0 1 20
22 1 3 26
14 0 2 16
33 3 2 38
88 4 8 100
West
Total
Yes No Not voting Total
Chi-square 2.88, not significant
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
38 3 2 43
50 1 6 57
88 4 8 100
Chi-square 1.57, not significant
P.
House of Representatives, 1990 (Immigration Act) Northeast
South
Midwest
72 19 2 93
27 78 4 109
64 40 1 105
Yes No Not voting Total Chi-square 59.46, p = .0000
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
45 125 4 174
186 67 6 259
231 192 10 433
Chi-square 90.80, p = .0000
68 55 2 125
231 192 10 433
294 Q.
Appendixes Senate, 1990 (Immigration Act) Northeast
South
Midwest
West
Total
18 2 0 20
21 4 1 26
15 0 1 16
35 2 1 38
89 8 3 100
Yes No Not voting Total
Chi-square 3.81, not significant
Yes No Not voting Total
Republican
Democrat
Total
36 5 2 43
53 3 1 57
89 8 3 100
Chi-square 1.46, not significant
Notes
Abbreviations
COIN Committee on Immigration and Naturalization CR Congressional Record
Chapter 1
1. Elizabeth Meehan, Citizenship and the European Community (London: Sage, 1993). 2. On erosion, see Richard J. Barnet and Ronald E. Muller, Global Reach (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1974); John Herz, “The Rise and Demise of the Territorial State,” World Politics 9/4 (July 1957), 473–93; Jarat Chopra and Thomas Weiss, “Sovereignty is No Longer Sacrosanct,” Ethics and International Affairs 6 (1992), 95–117; Jean-Marie Guehenno, The End of the Nation-State (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1995); Robin Brown, “Globalization and the End of the National Project,” Boundaries in Question, ed. John MacMillan and Andrew Linklater (New York: Pinter, 1995), 54–68; Vincent Cable, “The Diminished Nation-State: A Study in the Loss of Economic Power,” Daedalus 124/2 (spring 1995), 23–53; Walter B. Wriston, “Technology and Sovereignty,” Foreign Affairs 67/2 (winter 1988/89), 63–75; Saskia Sassen, Losing Control? (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); in opposition, Janice E. Thomson and Stephen D. Krasner, “Global Transactions and the Consolidation of Sovereignty,” Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, ed. Ernst-Otto Czempiel and James N. Rosenau (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1989), 195–219. There are thousands of popular and scholarly treatises on this theme, in addition to the large literature focusing on the loss of sovereignty in the European Union (Community). Even E. H. Carr, in The Twenty Years’ Crisis, foresaw the end of the nation-state (viii)! 3. Friedrich Kratochwil, “Of Systems, Boundaries, and Territoriality,” World Politics 39 (October 1986), 27–52. 4. For discussions of the origins and nature of sovereignty, see F. H. Hinsley, Sovereignty, 2d ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986); Stephen D. Krasner, “Sovereignty: An Institutional Perspective,” Comparative Political Studies 21/1 (April 1988) and “Westphalia and All That,” Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, ed. Judith Goldstein and Robert Keo-
295
296
Notes to Pages 3–7
hane (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993), 235–64; Hendrik Spruyt, The Sovereign State and Its Competitors (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994). 5. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948), articles 13(2), 15(1), 14(1). 6. Joan Biskupic and William Branigin, “Court Curbs Free Speech of Illegal Immigrants,” Washington Post (25 February 1999), A1. 7. For discussions of territoriality, see Ivo Duchacek, The Territorial Dimension of Politics—Within, Among, and Across Nations (Boulder: Westview, 1988); John Gerard Ruggie, “Territoriality and Beyond,” International Organization 47/1 (winter 1993). 8. Aristide Zolberg, “International Migration Policies in a Changing World System,” Human Migrations: Patterns and Policies, ed. William H. McNeill and Ruth S. Adams (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978), 241–86. 9. T. H. Marshall, Class, Citizenship, and Social Development: Essays (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1964). 10. See, for example, Charles Keely, “Immigration Composition and Population Policy,” Science 185/4151 (16 August 1974), 587–93; David M. Reimers, “Recent Immigration Policy: An Analysis,” The Gateway, ed. Barry Chiswick (Washington, DC; American Enterprise Institute, 1982), 13–53; Elizabeth Midgley, “Comings and Goings in Immigration Policy,” The Unavoidable Issue, ed. Mark Miller (Philadelphia: ISHI, 1983), 41–69; Gary Freeman, “Migration and the Political Economy of the Welfare State,” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May 1986), 51–63; “Race, Votes and Power: The Numbers Game,” Economist (26 December 1987), 63–66; Maldwyn Allen Jones, American Immigration, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992); Francis Fukuyama, “Immigrants and Family Values,” Commentary (May 1993), 26–32; Debra DeLaet, “Interest Group Politics, U.S. Immigration Policy, and Globalization,” presented to International Studies Association Meetings, February 1995; Thomas Espenshade and Katherine Hempstead, “Contemporary American Attitudes toward U.S. Immigration,” International Migration Review 30/2 (summer 1996), 535–70. 11. On political argument, see Brian Barry, Political Argument (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990); Giandomenico Majone, Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989). 12. Two other analyses of arguments, speci‹cally about different others, are William Lee Miller, Arguing about Slavery (New York: Knopf, 1995), and Stephen Riggins, ed., The Language and Politics of Exclusion (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1997). 13. David R. Cameron, “Public Expenditure and Economic Performance in International Perspective,” The Future of Welfare, ed. Rudolf Klein and Michael O’Higgins (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1985), 17. 14. Together these are about three-quarters of federal social service spending. Robert Morris, “Re-thinking Welfare in the United States: The Welfare State in Transition,” Modern Welfare States: A Comparative View of Trends and Prospects, ed. Robert R. Friedmann et al. (Sussex, England: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1987), table p. 85.
Notes to Pages 7–13
297
15. In fact, other studies of American immigration have adopted this puzzle: how can a liberal country justify keeping anyone out? See James F. Holli‹eld, Immigrants, Markets and States (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Gary Freeman, “Can Liberal States Control Unwanted Migration?” Annals (AAPSS) 534 (July 1994), 17–30. This approach also fuels much of the writing on migration and ethics, such as the work of Joseph Carens and Robert Goodin. Christian Joppke similarly asks why actual levels of immigration exceed the levels declared in policy, in his view a liberal outcome that needs explanation: “Why Liberal States Accept Unwanted Immigration,” World Politics 50 (January 1998), 266–93. 16. Fredrik Barth, Ethnic Groups and Boundaries: The Social Organization of Culture Difference, ed. Fredrik Barth (Boston: Little, Brown, 1969). 17. Matthew Evangelista, Innovation and the Arms Race (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988); Alastair Iain Johnston, Cultural Realism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995). 18. Work on sovereignty in this tradition includes John Gerard Ruggie, “Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity,” World Politics 35 (1983), 261–85; Alexander Wendt, “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory,” International Organization 41 (1987), 335–70; Alexander Wendt, “Collective Identity Formation and the International State,” American Political Science Review 88 (1994), 384–96; Thomas J. Biersteker and Cynthia Weber, eds., State Sovereignty as Social Construct (New York: Cambridge, 1996).
Chapter 2
1. The uses of rationality here follow those originally put by Weber: instrumental rationality looks to reasons for the means to an end, value rationality looks to the principles that guide moral action, and traditional rationality looks to what has been done in the past to provide a reason for current behavior. “Types of Social Action,” Economy and Society, ed. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 24–25. 2. Richard Dagger, “Politics and the Pursuit of Autonomy,” Justi‹cation, ed. J. Roland Pennock (New York: New York University Press, 1986), 271. 3. Giandomenico Majone, Evidence, Argument, and Persuasion in the Policy Process (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), 29. 4. John Dewey, Democracy and Education (New York: Free Press, 1944). This was proposed more recently by Robert Reich: “Politics . . . should entail the creation of contexts in which people can critically evaluate and revise what they believe.” Robert B. Reich, “Introduction,” The Power of Public Ideas (Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1988), 6. 5. Talcott Parsons, “The Role of Ideas in Social Action,” Essays in Sociological Theory, rev. ed. (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1954), 29–30. 6. The idea of issue-framing is discussed in Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, “The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice,” Rational
298
Notes to Pages 14–18
Choice, ed. Jon Elster (New York: New York University Press, 1986). Judith Goldstein and Robert Keohane refer to metaphorical road maps in Judith Goldstein and Robert O. Keohane, “Ideas and Foreign Policy: An Analytical Framework,” in Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993), 3–30. 7. Albert O. Hirshman, The Rhetoric of Reaction: Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy (Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 1991). 8. Judith Goldstein and Robert O. Keohane distinguish causal beliefs from worldviews and principled beliefs, and argue that each can affect behavior by serving as a road map, by de‹ning an equilibrium point, or by becoming embedded in institutions. Their schema is set up to address how ideas can delimit the options that a rational decision-maker would consider, rather than to explain how social debate creates ideas or why one is selected. See their “Ideas and Foreign Policy: An Analytical Framework,” in Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993), 7, 10. 9. Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), 6. 10. Giandomenico Majone, Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), 31. 11. Brian Barry, Political Argument (New York: Humanities Press, 1965), 190. Virginia Held discusses three dominant views about how the public interest ought to be determined in The Public Interest and Individual Interests (New York: Basic Books, 1970). 12. C. W. Casinelli, “The Public Interest in Political Ethics,” The Public Interest, ed. Carl J. Friedrich (New York: Atherton, 1962), 46. 13. Glendon Schubert, The Public Interest: A Critique of the Theory of a Political Concept (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1960), 31. 14. Friedrich Kratochwil, “On the Notion of ‘Interest’ in International Relations,” International Organization 36/1 (winter 1982), 1–30. 15. John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies (New York: HarperCollins 1984), 21. 16. See Laura Lynn Stoker, Morality and the Study of Political Behavior (University of Michigan, Ph.D. dissertation 1990), and her “Interests and Ethics in Politics,” American Political Science Review 86 (June 1992), 369–80. 17. Realism is different from ethical egoism in that it carries additional assumptions of relative maximization. For example, an egoist in Prisoner’s Dilemma would prefer the 3–3 to the 1–1 outcome but a realist would be indifferent. 18. First statement from G. E. Moore, “Is Egoism Reasonable?” 49; next from Thomas Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism (Oxford: Clarendon, 1970), 84. 19. Robert E. Osgood, Ideals and Self-Interest in America’s Foreign Relations (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 4. 20. Henry A. Kissinger, “The Moral Foundations of Foreign Policy,” American Foreign Policy, 3d ed. (New York: Norton, 1977), 200. 21. David Hendrickson, “Migration in Law and Ethics: A Realist Perspec-
Notes to Pages 18–22
299
tive,” Free Movement: The Transnational Migration of People and of Money, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin (New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster, 1992), 217. 22. I am aware that communitarians have quite a bit in common with other liberals, that many of the differences are exaggerated while others are understated, and that people have been arguing about this for a while. This point here is not to draw conclusions about “communitarianism,” for example (this is the sordid truth about communitarians), but to use ideas it values and explains to help explicate why people make certain types of arguments about exclusion. 23. David C. Hendrickson, “Migration in Law and Ethics: A Realist Perspective,” Free Movement: The Transnational Migration of People and of Money, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin (New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster, 1992), 215. 24. David Miller, “The Ethical Signi‹cance of Nationality,” Ethics 98 (July 1988), 657, emphasis in the original. 25. E. H. Carr, The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939, rev. ed. (New York: Harper, 1939/1946), 160. 26. Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York: Basic Books, 1983), xv, 39, 32, 61. 27. Peter H. Schuck and Rogers Smith, Citizenship without Consent: Illegal Aliens in the American Polity (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1985), 28. 28. Thomas Jefferson, Notes on the State of Virginia, ed. William Peden (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1955 [1787]), 85. Jefferson later changed his mind about immigrants. 29. Frederick G. Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement: An Open Admission Policy?” in Open Borders? Closed Societies? The Ethical and Political Issues, ed. Mark Gibney (Westport, CT: Greenwood, 1988), 22. 30. Hans Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, 10. This is exactly the response of Henry Stimson and Karl Compton to critics of the U.S. decision to drop atomic bombs on Hiroshima and Nagasaki. See Henry Stimson, “The Decision to Use the Atomic Bomb,” Harper’s 194/1161 (February 1947), 97–107+; Karl T. Compton, “If the Atomic Bomb Had Not Been Used,” Atlantic Monthly 178 (December 1946), 54–56. 31. Timothy King, capturing the point of view argued by John Rawls and Charles Beitz; “Immigration from Developing Countries: Some Philosophical Issues,” Ethics 93/3 (April 1983), 527. 32. Immanuel Kant, “Third De‹nitive Article for a Perpetual Peace,” extract from Perpetual Peace in On History, ed. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: BobbsMerrill, 1963), § 358, 102–3. 33. Roger Nett, “The Civil Right We Are Not Ready For: The Right of Free Movement of People on the Face of the Earth,” Ethics 81/3 (April 1971), 218, 219. 34. John Stuart Mill, “Utilitarianism,” Utilitarianism and Other Essays, John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham (New York: Penguin, 1987/1861), 288. 35. David Resnick, “John Locke and the Problem of Naturalization,” Review of Politics (summer 1987), 377.
300
Notes to Pages 22–35
36. Peter Singer argues that we have obligations actively to relieve human suffering, regardless of distance, and to the point at which our resources equalize; see “Famine, Af›uence, and Morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1/3 (spring 1972), 229–43. 37. Charles R. Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 151. 38. John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies (New York: HarperCollins, 1984), 17–18, 99. 39. John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies (New York: HarperCollins, 1984), 83. 40. John Kingdon notes that “problems” are solvable while “conditions” are not. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies (New York: HarperCollins, 1984), 115. 41. Richard Hofstadter describes this in Social Darwinism in American Thought, rev. ed. (Boston: Beacon, 1959). Examples include Madison Grant’s in›uential The Passing of the Great Race (New York: Scribner’s, 1916).
Chapter 3
1. See E. Edward Proper, Colonial Immigration Laws (New York: Columbia University Press, 1900), and an Immigration Bureau history of colonial immigration policy, in its Annual Report 1930. 2. The United States once had a program to facilitate the entry of temporary agricultural workers. Called the Bracero Program, it operated from 1942 through 1964. 3. Maldwyn Allen Jones, American Immigration (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960), 41. 4. Aristide Zolberg, “International Migration Policies in a Changing World System,” Human Migrations: Patterns and Policies, ed. William McNeill and Ruth S. Adams (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978), 241–86. 5. Benjamin Franklin letter to Peter Collinson, May 1753, in Edith Abbott, ed., Historical Aspects of the Immigration Problem: Select Documents (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1926), 415. 6. John Higham, Strangers in the Land: Patterns of American Nativism, 1860–1925, 2d ed. (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1958), 9. Note that “native American” until the 1960s always meant Anglo-European in the Americas since the time of the May›ower in theory if not in practice. 7. A good and direct discussion of this process is in James C. Thomson et al., Sentimental Imperialists (New York: Harper, 1981), 79–92. 8. John Burnett (D-AL), Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the Committee on Immigration and Naturalization (hereafter COIN), House of Representatives, 64th Congress, 1st Session (hereafter 64C/1S), 21 January 1916, 28. 9. William P. Dillingham (R-VT), Congressional Record (hereafter CR), v. 53, pt. 4 (64C/1S), 25 February 1916, 12773.
Notes to Pages 35–37
301
10. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Daniel J. Keefe), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1911 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1911), 3. 11. Also foreshadowing debate to come was both sides’ use of parable and fable to make their points. About literacy, for example, Herbert Friedenwald (individual) told the following story. “A Jew applied for a position as sexton of a synagogue, and when he was asked if he could read and write he said ‘No.’ So they could not employ him. But he went into business and was very successful, and one day he was perfecting a loan, and to the surprise of the new clerk he could not sign his name but made his mark, and the new clerk said to him, ‘Why, my God, can’t you write?’ ‘No,’ he said, ‘I cannot write.’ ‘And you have been able to make all this money while being unable to read and write. My God, what would you have been if you could read and write?’ And he replied, ‘I would have been a sexton of the synagogue.’” National Origins Provision of Immigration Law, Hearings before the Senate Committee on Immigration (70C/2S), 4–13 February 1929, 62. 12. Grover Cleveland, Senate Document 185 (54C/2S), 21 March 1897. 13. Woodrow Wilson (president), veto of 14 February 1913. He repeated his words in his veto message of 28 January 1915. Congress overrode the second veto to pass the Immigration Act of 1917. 14. Charles Cody (R-MD), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4803. 15. Ambrose Kennedy (R-RI), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4846. 16. Joseph (Hampton) Moore (R-PA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4844. 17. George Kennan, letter to the House COIN. Further Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (62C/2S), 2 February 1912, 60. 18. William S. Bennet (R-NY), CR v. 53, pt. 4 (64C/1S), 25 February 1916, 3163. 19. Excluded were “persons who are natives [the committee did not consider Anglo-Europeans natives of Asia even if they were born there, so this did not apply to them] of islands not possessed by the United States adjacent to the Continent of Asia, situate south of the twentieth parallel of latitude north, west of the one hundred and sixtieth meridian of longitude east of Greenwich, and north of the tenth parallel of latitude south, or who are natives of any country, Province, or dependency situate on the Continent of Asia west of the one hundred and tenth meridian of longitude east from Greenwich and south of the ‹ftieth parallel of latitude north, except that” Australia and New Zealand did not count. In sum, this included all of Asia and the Paci‹c Islands from Japan to Afghanistan and Ceylon to Mongolia. CR v. 54, pt. 2 (64C/2S), 12 January 1917, c. 1290. 20. Frederick Gillett (R-MA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4860. 21. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, pt. 6 (67C/2S), 5 May 1922, 6409. 22. Robert Bacon (R-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5901. 23. See, for example, John Higham, Strangers in the Land: Patterns of American Nativism, 1860–1925, 2d ed. (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1958), 301.
302
Notes to Pages 37–42
24. Letter from Abe Spring, Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (14 January–12 February 1924), 1163. 25. This chapter uses for its source material the complete congressional debate about immigration (as well as alien and refugee) policies logged in the Congressional Record volumes running from 1894 to 1930. It also relies on the available records of congressional hearings held during this time period. 26. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5806. 27. Samuel D. McReynolds (D-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5856. 28. William Vaile (R-CO), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 509. 29. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5806. 30. Ellison Smith (D-SC), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 9 April 1924, 5962. 31. Thomas Jefferson Busby (D-MS), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 9 April 1924, 6124. 32. James Phelan (D-CA), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives, 66C/1S, 12 June–25 September 1919, 197. 33. John Watkins (D-LA), Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives, 14 January–12 February 1924, 1038. 34. Frederick Gillett (R-MA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4860. 35. David Walsh (D-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6354. 36. L. Ethan Ellis, Republican Foreign Policy, 1921–1933 (New Bruswick: Rutgers University Press, 1968), 13. 37. Clarence Lea (D-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5696. 38. U.S. Supreme Court, Nishimura Ekiu v. U.S. 142 U.S. 651 (1891) at 659 (decided 18 January 1892). 39. Wesley Jones (R-WA), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 927. 40. Milton C. Garber (R-OK), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5693. 41. Samuel D. McReynolds (D-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5854. 42. John Miller (R-WA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5883 43. John Raker (D-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5892. 44. Henry Cabot Lodge (R-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 14 April 1924, 6305. 45. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull) Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1927 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1927), 2. 46. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull) Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1928 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1928), 3. 47. Supreme Court 130 U.S. 606 48. Earl Michener (R-MI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5907. 49. Bertrand Snell (R-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 4 April 1924, 5643. 50. Thomas Jefferson Busby (D-MS), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 11 April 1924, 6123. 51. John Cable (R-OH), CR v. 65, pt. 4 (68C/1S), 26 February 1924, 3422. 52. Benjamin Focht (R-PA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4806.
Notes to Pages 42–47
303
53. William Borah (R-ID), CR v. 53, pt. 4 (64C/1S), 25 February 1916, 12764. 54. James Aswell (D-LA), CR v. 64, pt. 6 (67C/4S), 3 March 1923, 5435. 55. Charles Stengle (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5848. 56. John Works (R-CA), CR v. 53, pt. 4 (64C/1S), 14 July 1916, 11024. 57. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 62, pt. 12 (67C/2S), 31 August 1922, 12062. 58. Riley Wilson (D-LA), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 502. 59. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 62, pt. 12 (67C/2S), 31 August 1922, 12062. 60. Walter Newton (R-MN), CR v. 64, pt. 1 (67C/4S), 13 December 1922, 437. 61. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 65, pt. 3 (68C/1S), 20 February 1924, 2841. 62. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 65, pt. 5 (68C/1S), 15 March 1924, 4268. 63. Albert Vestal (R-IN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 2 April 1924, 5443. 64. James J. Davis (Secretary of Labor) letter to Albert Johnson (COIN Chair), Correspondence with Executive Departments, COIN, House of Representatives (68C/1S), 17 April 1924, 1194. 65. Ralph Lozier (D-MO), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6264. 66. William Mason (R-IL), CR v. 61, pt. 2 (67C/1S), 13 May 1921, 1436. 67. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, pt. 6 (67C/2S), 5 May 1922, 6409, 6410. 68. Commissioner-General of Immigration, Bureau of Immigration, Annual Reports 1927 through 1930 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1927–1930), 8 (1927), 259 (1928), 4 (1929), 11–12 (1930). 69. Riley Wilson (D-LA), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 502. 70. Calvin Coolidge (president), quoted in CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5853. 71. William Vaile (R-CO), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 21 April 1921, 562. 72. Frank Mondell (R-WY), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 22 April 1921, 588. 73. Park Trammell (D-FL), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 928. 74. Its origin was in response to California’s attempt to segregate schools. The state government let the law die for fear that it would jeopardize the Paris peace talks then under way. James Phelan, Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives, 68C/1S 187. 75. James Mann (R-IL), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4868; reiterated by Everis Hayes (CA), CR v. 54, pt. 2 (64C/2S), 12 January 1917, 1294. 76. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 14 April 1924, 6303. 77. William Borah (R-ID), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 14 April 1924, 6304. 78. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 4 (68C/1S), 14 March 1924, 4170. 79. Romanian ambassador’s letter in CR v. 65, pt. 3 (68C/1S), 20 February 1924, 2841. 80. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 65, pt. 3 (68C/1S), 20 February 1924, 2841. 81. James Phelan (D-CA), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (68C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 183–84. 82. Gustave Sonnenburg (individual), National Origins Provision: Immigration Act of 1924, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (69C/2S), 18–26 January 1927, 70. 83. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, pt. 6 (67C/2S), 15 April 1922, 6410.
304
Notes to Pages 47–52
84. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, pt. 6 (67C/2S), 15 April 1922, 6410. 85. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, pt. 8 (67C/2S), 2 June 1922, 8070 86. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5876. 87. James Thomas He›in (D-AL), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 9 April 1924, 5960. 88. John Cable (R-OH), CR v. 65, pt. 4 (68C/1S), 26 February 1924, 3166. 89. James Phelan (D-CA), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives, 12 June–25 September 1919, 184. 90. Claude Swanson (D-VA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 14 April 1924, 6307. 91. Charles Stengle (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5848. 92. Bertrand Snell (R-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5643. 93. Will Taylor (R-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5872. 94. John Raker (D-CA), Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives, 68C/1S, 14 January–12 February 1924, 1044. 95. James Gallivan (D-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5849. 96. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5654. 97. Sidney Gulick, Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 45. 98. James Gallivan (D-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5850. 99. Walter Chandler (R-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 9 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 8228. 100. Rufus Hardy (D-TX), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4797. 101. James Reed (D-MO), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 3 May 1921, 949. 102. T. J. Brooks (individual), Hearings, 11 January 1912, 30. 103. Ralph Gilbert (D-KY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6260. 104. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 12 (68C/1S), 23 January 1924, 1328. 105. Joseph Cannon (R-IL), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4778. 106. Peter Tague (D-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5874. 107. Louis Marshall (individual), Further Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (62C/2S), 2 February 1912+, 34. 108. Richard Aldrich (R-RI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5896. 109. Isaac Siegel (R-NY), CR v. 64, pt. 5 (67C/4S), 26 February 1923, 4719. 110. Sidney Gulick, Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 91. 111. James Reed (D-MO), CR v. 60, pt. 4 (66C/3S), 19 February 1921, 3463. 112. Meyer London (Socialist-NY), CR v. 54, pt. 3 (64C/2S), 1 February 1917, 2450. 113. Meyer London (Socialist-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 515. 114. LeBaron Colt (R-RI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 2 April 1924, 5413. 115. LeBaron Colt (R-RI), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 21 May 1921, 924. 116. John O’Connor (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 4 April 1924, 5647. 117. Ole J. Kvale (Farmer Laborite-MN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5919.
Notes to Pages 52–57
305
118. Walter Chandler (R-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 9 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 8227. 119. Bourke Cockran (D-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 22 April 1921, 585. 120. Immigration of Aliens into the United States, House Report 95, 64th Congress, 1st session (1916), pt. 2: minority views, 2. 121. U. G. Murphy (individual), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/2S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 83. 122. Jane Addams (individual), Hearings on HR 558, House of Representatives, 20 January 1916, 59. 123. U. G. Murphy (individual), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June 12–25 September 1919, 74. 124. Commissioner-General of Immigration (A. Caminetti), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1919 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1919), 62. 125. James Gallivan (D-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5849. 126. LeBaron Colt (R-RI), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 924.
Chapter 4
1. No systematic polling captures American opinion on immigrants during this era. Historians agree that it was a period of anti-immigrant feeling, but if the pattern in later public opinion polls holds during this earlier period, this means that the proportion in favor of immigration remained constant and tiny, while a portion of the noncommittal became, temporarily, opposed to immigration. Immigration legislation, though, does not follow such shifts in public opinion. Or, rather, it does, but public opinion shifts as dramatically and as often in legislatively fallow periods. See Rita James Simon, Public Opinion and the Immigrant: Print Media Coverage, 1880–1980 (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1985), and Edwin Harwood, “American Public Opinion and U.S. Immigration Policy,” Annals (AAPSS) 487 (September 1986), 201–12. 2. Wesley Jones (R-WA), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 923. 3. M. M. Neely (WV), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4870. 4. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1928 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1928), 1. 5. Jeff Busby (D-AL), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6122. 6. Thomas He›in (D-AL), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6545. 7. M. M. Neely (WV), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6626. 8. Thomas He›in (D-AL), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 3 May 1921, 963. 9. Thomas Lilly (D-WV), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5695. 10. Fred Vinson (D-KY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 11 April 1924, 6121. 11. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5876. 12. Jacob Milligan (D-MO), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6259. 13. Reported in CR v. 62, pt. 6 (67C/2S), 15 April 1922, 5558. 14. Benjamin Rosenbloom (WV), CR v. 65, pt. 6 68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5851.
306
Notes to Pages 57–62
15. Martin Dies (TX), Further Restriction of Immigration Part 4, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (62C/2S), 2 February 1912, 50. 16. Fred Purnell (R-IN), CR v. 65, pt. 5 (68C/1S), 17 March 1924, 4391. 17. Walter Chandler (R-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 9 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 8227. 18. Lucian Parrish (D-TX), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 511. 19. Richard Austin (TX), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4805. 20. John Hill (R-MD), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 21 April 1921, 566. 21. Irvine Lenroot (R-WI), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 927. 22. William Vaile (R-CO), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 509. 23. John Robsion (R-KY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5667. 24. Charles Linthicum (D-MD), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 11 April 1924, 6163. 25. Lilius Rainey (D-AL), CR v. 64, pt. 1 (67C/4S), 13 December 1922, 438. 26. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1927 (Washington, DC: 1927), 15. 27. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 64, pt. 5 (67C/4S), 23 February 1923, 5181. 28. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1927 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1927), 2. 29. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 62, pt. 12 (67C/2S), 31 August 1922, 12065. 30. James Byrnes (D-SC), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 4 April 1924, 5652. 31. Will Taylor (R-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5871. 32. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 64, pt. 5 (67C/4S), 23 February 1923, 4425. 33. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, pt. 8 (67C/2S), 2 June 1922, 8069. 34. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 496. 35. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Daniel J. Keefe), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1911 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1911), 118. 36. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, pt. 8 (67C/2S), 2 June 1922, 8070. 37. James Reed (D-MO), National Origins Provisions of Immigration Law, Hearings before the Senate Committee on Immigration (70C/2S), 4–13 February 1929, 60. 38. John Raker (D-CA), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/2S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 80. 39. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 62, pt. 12 (67C/2S), 31 August 1922, 12060. 40. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5743. 41. William Harris (D-GA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5738. 42. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 64, pt. 1 (67C/4S), 13 December 1922, 435. 43. Addison Smith (R-ID), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5698. 44. James MacLafferty (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5680. 45. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5806. 46. James Phelan (D-CA), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives, 12 June–25 September 1919, 191. 47. Samuel D. McReynolds (D-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5856. 48. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5747.
Notes to Pages 62–67
307
49. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 62, pt. 12 (67C/2S), 31 August 1922, 12060. 50. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1925 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1925), 12–13. 51. Samuel D. McReynolds (D-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5852. 52. So concerned were government of‹cials about subversion that the various branches spent close to a decade determining that “philosophical anarchists” (i.e., those who advocated doing away with government but did not advocate violence), were equally a menace. See, for example, the discussion in Lopez v. Howe, 259 F. 401 (1918). 53. Percy Quin (D-MS), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4805. 54. John McKenzie (R-IL), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4777. 55. Thomas He›in (D-AL), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 915–16. 56. Reported in National Origins Provisions of Immigration Law, Hearings before the Senate Committee on Immigration (70C/2S), 3–14 February 1929, 89. 57. Commissioner-General of Immigration, Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1926 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1926), 2; reiterating the Annual Report 1913, 15. 58. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1927 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1927), 2. 59. Henry Steagall (D-AL), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6171. 60. Arthur Greenwood (D-IN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6263. 61. Sidney Gulick, Percentage Plan for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 42. 62. Benjamin Rosenbloom (WV), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5851. 63. Simeon Fess (R-OH), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4843. 64. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 501. 65. Royal Copeland (NY), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6530. 66. John Raker (D-CA) and James W. Jenks (individual), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 178–79. 67. Hubert Stephens (MS), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6545. 68. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5742. 69. James Reed (D-MO), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 3 April 1924, 5471. 70. Isaac Siegel (D-NY), CR v. 64, pt. 5 (67C/1S), 26 February 1923, 4714. 71. James Reed (D-MO), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 3 May 1921, 949. 72. Meyer London (Socialist-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 552. 73. Isaac Siegel (D-NY), CR v. 54, pt. 3 (64C/2S), 1 February 1917, 2444. 74. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 2 (68C/1S), 23 January 1924, 1328, 1329. 75. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1930 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1930), 12. 76. James Gallivan (D-MA), CR v. 54, pt. 3 (64C/2S), 1 February 1917, 2449.
308
Notes to Pages 67–74
77. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 4 (68C/1S), 14 March 1924, 4173. 78. Thomas Lilly (D-WV), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5695. 79. David Reed (D-MO), Hearings before Senate Committee 1924. 80. Commissioner-General of Immigration (A. Caminetti), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1915 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1915), 16. 81. John Works (CA), CR v. 53, pt. 4 (64C/1S), 14 July 1916, 11018. 82. John Williams (R-MS), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 957. 83. John Williams (R-MS), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 957. 84. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5742. 85. Riley Wilson (D-LA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5673. 86. B. F. Welty (OH), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 46; James MacLafferty (CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5681. 87. John Tillman (D-AR), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5865. 88. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5742. 89. Benjamin Focht (R-PA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4806. 90. Percy Quin (D-MS), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 22 April 1921, 572. 91. J. N. Tincher (R-KS), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5918. 92. William Holaday (R-IL), CR v. 65, pt. 4 (68C/1S), 26 February 1924, 3257. 93. John Robsion (R-KY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5665. 94. John Raker (D-CA), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 514. 95. Asians were excluded as immigrants in two steps. Naturalization was only “to apply to aliens being free white persons and to aliens of African nationality and persons of African descent.” This had excluded Asians from naturalizing, but they had been theoretically capable of immigrating, then remaining permanent residents. The Quota Act stopped this. Section B noted that “no alien ineligible to citizenship shall be admitted to the United States.” 96. James Phelan (D-CA), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 204. 97. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 62, pt. 12 (67C/2S), 31 August 1922, 12060. 98. Commissioner-General of Immigration (A. Caminetti), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1919 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1919), 65. 99. Benjamin Focht (R-PA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4807. 100. He presented his work to the committee in Analysis of America’s Modern Melting Pot, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives, 67C/3S, 21 November 1922; The Eugenical Aspects of Deportation, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (70C/1S), 21 February 1928; Europe as an EmigrantExporting Continent and the United States as an Immigrant-Receiving Nation, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (68C/1S), 8 March 1924. 101. Document 2003 (64C/2S), 38. 102. V. S. McClatchy (individual), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 34. 103. Riley Wilson (D-LA), CR v. 62, pt. 4 (67C/2S), 16 March 1922, 3976.
Notes to Pages 74–80
309
104. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1927 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1927), 21. 105. Scott Leavitt (R-MT), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6265. 106. Thomas Schall (R-MN), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4800. 107. Harry Laughlin quoted in Senate Hearings 1924. 108. Grant Hudson (R-MI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 4 April 1924, 5641. 109. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 64, pt. 5 (67C/4S), 23 February 1923, 4425. 110. Charles Stengle (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5848. 111. William Bruce (MD), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 9 April 1924, 5955. 112. Ralph Gilbert (D-KY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6262. 113. Commissioner of Naturalization (Richard K. Campbell), Naturalization Report 1924 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1924), 9. 114. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 65, pt. 4 (68C/1S), 1 March 1924, 3424. 115. William Howard (GA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4873. 116. William Vaile (R-CO), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 21 April 1921, 569. 117. Arthur Free (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5927. 118. Calvin Coolidge, quoted in CR v. 65, pt. 5 (68C/1S), 15 March 1924, 4265. 119. M. C. Garber (D-OK), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5689. 120. Elton Watkins (D-OR), CR v. 65, pt. 2 (68C/1S), 23 January 1924, 1897. 121. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 64, pt. 5 (67C/4S), 23 February 1923, 4424. 122. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5742. 123. Samuel Shortridge (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5742. 124. New York Chamber of Commerce letter in National Origins Provision of Immigration Law, Hearings before the Senate Committee on Immigration (70C/2S), 4–13 February 1929, 40–41. 125. V. S. McClatchy (individual), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 34. 126. James Phelan (D-CA), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 196. 127. James MacLafferty (R-CA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5680. 128. Richard Aldrich (R-RI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5895. 129. Charles Mooney (D-OH), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5910. 130. Commissioner of Naturalization (Richard K. Campbell), Annual Report 1917 (Washington: GPO, 1917), 6. 131. Meyer London (Socialist-NY), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 24 March 1916, 4793. 132. Clarence McLeod (R-MI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5675. 133. Nathan Perlman (R-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 4 April 1924, 5675. 134. Charles Mooney (D-OH), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5911. 135. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 2 (68C/1S), 23 January 1924, 1330. 136. Dr. Charles Fama (individual), Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives, 14 January–12 February 1924, 1028. 137. Harold Knutson (Democrat Farm Laborite-MN), Percentage Plans for
310
Notes to Pages 80–84
Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 27. 138. U. G. Murphy, Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 73–74. 139. James W. Jenks (individual), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 177. 140. Theodore Burton (R-OH), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6249. 141. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 5 (68C/1S), 15 March 1924, 4571. 142. LeBaron Colt (R-RI), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 2 May 1921, 924. 143. James Aswell (D-LA), CR v. 64, pt. 6 (67C/4S), 3 March 1923, 5435. 144. John McSwain (D-SC), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5683. 145. Ellison Smith (D-SC), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 9 April 1924, 5961. 146. William Harris (D-GA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 7 April 1924, 5738. 147. Deportation of Certain Aliens, House Report 127 (65C/1S), 4 August 1917, 2. 148. Deportation of Certain Aliens, House Report 127 (65C/1S), 4 August 1917, 2. 149. William Coleman (PA), CR v. 53, pt. 5 (64C/1S), 25 March 1916, 4842. 150. Knut Wefald (Farmer Laborite-MN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6272. 151. John Williams (R-MS), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 3 May 1921, 956. 152. Reprinted in CR v. 62, pt. 6 (67C/2S), 15 April 1922, 5562. 153. James W. Jenks (individual), Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (66C/1S), 12 June–25 September 1919, 158. 154. Samuel D. McReynolds (D-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5852. 155. Capt. John Trevor (individual), National Origins Provision: Immigration Act of 1924, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (69C/2S), 18–26 January 1927, 33. 156. Marvin Jones (D-TX), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 22 April 1921, 588. 157. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 62, pt. 12 (67C/2S), 31 August 1922, 12065. 158. Thomas He›in (D-AL), CR v. 60, pt. 4 (66C/3S), 19 February 1921, 3449. 159. Samuel D. McReynolds (D-TN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5853. 160. House Report 95, Immigration of Aliens into the United States (64C/1S), January 1916, 45. 161. James Husted (R-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 549. 162. David Kincheloe (D-KY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6236. 163. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 4 (68C/1S), 14 March 1924, 4170. 164. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 510. 165. Meyer London (Socialist-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 515. 166. Raymond Crist, Director of Citizenship, Commissioner of Naturalization Annual Report 1919 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1919), 8.
Notes to Pages 85–97
311
167. W. Frank James (R-MI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5669. 168. Meyer London (Socialist-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 1 (67C/1S), 20 April 1921, 515. 169. Adolph Sabath (D-IL), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 4 April 1924, 5578. 170. Schuyler Merritt (R-CT), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6242. 171. LeBaron Colt (R-RI), CR v. 62, pt. 6 (67C/2S), 15 April 1922, 5557. 172. Robert Clancy (R-MI), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5927. 173. David Walsh (D-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6356. 174. Oscar Larson (R-MN), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6243. 175. Correspondence with Executive Departments, COIN, House of Representatives (68C/1S), 17 April 1924, 1196 (letter dated 24 January 1924). 176. Walter Chandler (R-NY), CR v. 61, pt. 9 (67C/1S), 20 April 1924, 8227. 177. John P. Hill (R-MD), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5843. 178. Commissioner-General of Immigration (Harry E. Hull), Bureau of Immigration, Annual Report 1926 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1926), 2. 179. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 62, 8 (67C/2S), 2 June 1922, 8069. 180. M. M. Neely (WV), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6625, 6627. 181. David Reed (PA), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6623. 182. Holm Borsum (NM), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6628. 183. Duncan Fletcher (FL), CR v. 65, pt. 7 (68C/1S), 15 April 1924, 6632. 184. W. J. Driver (individual), Restriction of Immigration, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (68C/1S), 14 January–12 February 1924, 1055. 185. David Reed (PA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 2 April 1924, 5468. 186. Ralph Gilbert (D-KY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6262. 187. Henry Cabot Lodge (R-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 4 April 1924, 5568. 188. Robert Bacon (R-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5904. 189. David Reed (PA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 9 April 1924, 5943. 190. David Reed (PA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 9 April 1924, 5943. 191. John J. Rogers (R-MA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 12 April 1924, 6226. 192. John Box (D-TX), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 3167. 193. Robert Bacon (R-NY), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 8 April 1924, 5903–4. 194. Not that the national origins system met its goals. The system was much criticized among other reasons because it counted as British immigrants the many whose names were Anglicized upon entry and was based on censuses during periods when various groups feared to disclose their ancestry, as with the Germans in 1920. See National Origins Provision: Immigration Act of 1924, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (69C/2S), 18–26 January 1927, 72. 195. David Reed (PA), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 2 April 1924, 5473. 196. First veto message, CR v. 54, pt. 3 (64C/2S), 2445–46.
Chapter 5
1. United States, Bureau of the Census, Historical Statistics of the United States: Colonial Times to 1970 (Washington, DC: Government Printing Of‹ce, 1975). 2. Robert Green (D-FL), CR v. 76, pt. 4 (72C/1S), 18 February 1933, 4431.
312
Notes to Pages 98–103
3. Daniel Steck (D-IA), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 24 April 1930, 7605. 4. John Cable (R-OH), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 20 June 1930, 11376. 5. John Robsion (R-KY), CR v. 81, pt. 4 (75C/1S), 18 May 1937, 5549. 6. Robert Reynolds (D-NC), CR v. 80, pt. 3 (74C/2S), 3 February 1936, 1966. Both sides in these debates used scripture and sayings of American forefathers constantly. For example, the title of Truman’s 1952 commission to overturn restriction was Whom We Shall Welcome, taken from a pro-asylum speech George Washington gave in 1783. 7. James (Thomas) He›in (D-AL), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 17 April 1930, 7215. 8. Daniel Steck (D-IA), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 24 April 1930, 7605. 9. James (Thomas) He›in (D-AL), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (17 April 1930), 7210. 10. John Robsion (R-KY), CR v. 79, pt. 2 (74C/1S), 19 February 1935, 2241. 11. Robert Green (D-FL), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 14 April 1930, 7045. 12. John Schafer (R-WI), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 14 April 1930, 7045. 13. Coleman Blease (D-SC), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 17 April 1930, 7210. 14. James (Thomas) He›in (D-AL), CR v. 71, pt. 1 (71C/1S), 7 June 1929, 2504. 15. Exclusion and Expulsion of Communists, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (72C/1S), 23 February to 15 March 1932, 6. 16. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), CR v. 79, pt. 6 (74C/1S), 25 April 1935, 6401, 7700. 17. One exception was an argument forwarded by Oakley Johnson (University of Michigan) that students become communist when disillusioned by the difference between the glowing reports of American magnanimity that they learn in school and the nasty reality of American exclusion. No one bought the argument. Exclusion and Expulsion of Communists, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (72C/1S), 23 February–15 March 1932, 30. 18. J. Louis Engdahl (individual), Exclusion and Expulsion of Communists, Hearings before the House Committee on Immigration and Naturalization (72C/1S), 23 February–15 March 1932, 9. 19. Hugo Black (D-AL), CR v. 72, pt. 1 (71C/2S), 17 April 1930, 7213. 20. Albert Johnson (R-WA), CR v. 72, pt. 2 (71C/2S), 8 January 1930, 1538. 21. Robert Green (D-FL), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2 S), 14 April 1930, 7044. 22. Albert Johnson (R-WA), Exclusion and Expulsion of Communists, Hearings before the House COIN (72C/1S), 23 February to 15 March 1932, 46. 23. Richard Welch (R-CA), CR v. 74, pt. 2 (71C/3S), 20 January 1931, 2684. 24. Immigration and Naturalization Service, Statistical Yearbook of the Immigration and Naturalization Service (or Annual Report) (Washington, DC: GPO, various years). 25. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), CR v. 74, pt. 2 (71C/3S), 6 January 1931, 1499, 1500. 26. Frederick Steiwer (R-OR), CR v. 71, pt. 1 (71C/2S), 6 June 1929, 2425. 27. Robert Reynolds (D-NC), CR v. 84, pt. 1 (76C/1S), 23 February 1939, 1823.
Notes to Pages 103–9
313
28. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), CR v. 85, pt. 1 (76C/2S), 5 October 1939, 136. 29. William Poage (D-TX), To Revise and Codify the Nationality Laws of the United States into a Comprehensive Nationality Code, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (76C/1S), 17 January–5 June 1940, 49. 30. Leland Ford (R-CA), CR v. 86, pt. 5 (76C/3S), 17 May 1940, appendix 3023. 31. Fortune (May 1938). 32. Clarence Hancock (R-NY), CR v. 81, pt. 4 (75C/1S), 18 May 1937, 4721–22. 33. Robert Reynolds (D-NC), CR v. 84, pt. 1 (76C/1S), 23 February 1939, 1821. 34. Thomas Jenkins (R-OH), CR v. 83, pt. 4 (75C/3S), 17 February 1938, 4229. 35. John Rankin (D-MS), CR v. 83, pt. 7 (75C/3S), 20 May 1938, 7187. 36. James (Will) Taylor (R-TN), CR v. 85, pt. 2 (76C/2S), 3 November 1939, 1376. 37. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), CR v. 89, pt. 3 (78C/1S), 15 December 1943, A5496. 38. Thomas Jenkins (R-OH), CR v. 81, pt. 4 (75C/1S), 18 May 1937, 4725. 39. Thomas Jenkins (R-OH), CR v. 83, pt. 4 (75C/3S), 28 March 1938, 4227. 40. Robert Reynolds (D-NC), CR v. 84, pt. 1 (76C/1S), 16 January 1939, 366, 367. 41. Robert Reynolds (D-NC), CR v. 84, pt. 7 (76C/1S), 20 June 1939, 7538–39. 42. Robert Reynolds (D-NC), CR v. 84, pt. 1 (76C/1S), 16 January 1939, 370. 43. Lindley Beckworth (D-TX), CR v. 87, pt. 8 (76C/3S), 19 June 1941, A2956. 44. Arthur (Tom) Stewart (D-TN), CR v. 87, pt. 6 (76C/3S), 3 July 1941, 5811. 45. Lewis Thill (R-WI), CR v. 86, pt. 5 (76C/3S), 18 April 1940, 4755. 46. Lewis Thill (R-WI), CR v. 86, pt. 5 (76C/3S), 18 April 1940, 4767. 47. William King (D-UT), CR v. 86, pt. 1 (76C/3S), 25 January 1940, 682. 48. Vito Marcantonio (American Laborite-NY), CR v. 86, pt. 8 (76C/3S), 22 June 1940, 9034. 49. John Meyer (D-MD), CR v. 87, pt. 8 (76C/3S), 18 November 1941, 8967. 50. William Jenner (R-IN), CR v. 95, pt. 4 (81C/1S), 15 October 1949, 14695. 51. Horace (Jerry) Voorhis (D-CA), CR v. 88, pt. 1 (77C/1S), 4 February 1942, 1659. 52. Ugo Carusi, Commissioner of Immigration, Study of Immigration and Naturalization Laws and Problems, Hearings before the House COIN (79C/1S), pt. 1, 24 April and 2 May 1945, 6. 53. Edward Ennis, Director of the Alien Enemy Control Unit, War Division, Department of Justice, Study of Immigration and Naturalization Laws and Problems, Hearings before the House COIN (79C/1S), pt. 1, 24 April and 2 May 1945, 38. 54. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 90 (78C/2S), 7 March 1944, A1427. 55. Edward Ennis, Director of the Alien Enemy Control Unit, War Division, Department of Justice, Study of Immigration and Naturalization Laws and Prob-
314
Notes to Pages 109–12
lems, Hearings before the House COIN (79C/1S), pt. 1, 24 April and 2 May 1945, 42. 56. Francis Biddle (Attorney General), CR v. 88, pt. 1 (77C/1S), 1 February 1942, A351. 57. Franklin D. Roosevelt (president) letter to Samuel Dickstein (D-NY) dated 5 March 1945, To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 79. 58. Edward Rees (R-KS), CR v. 89, pt. 3 (78C/1S), 21 October 1943, 8624. 59. Franklin D. Roosevelt (president) message to Congress, 11 October 1943. 60. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 2–3. 61. John Folger (D-NC), CR v. 91, pt. 7 (78C/1S), 10 October 1945, 9540. 62. John Bennett (R-MI), CR v. 89, pt. 3 (78C/1S), 21 October 1943, 8623. 63. Sam Dickstein (D-NY), CR v. 89, pt. 3 (78C/1S), 23 March 1943, 5966, 5967. 64. William Floyd (Regular Veterans’ Association), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 22. 65. Walter Judd (R-MN), CR v. 91, pt. 7 (78C/1S), 10 October 1945, 9541. He argues this with more detail in CR v. 95, pt. 2 (81C/1S), 1 March 1949, 1678–80. 66. Pearl Buck (individual), Repeal of the Chinese Exclusion Acts, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (78C/1S), 19 May–3 June 1943, 76. 67. Walter Judd (R-MN), CR v. 89, pt. 3 (78C/1S), 21 October 1943, 8633. 68. For discussions of the Asian exclusion acts’ repeal, see Fred Riggs, Pressures on Congress: A Study of the Repeal of Chinese Exclusion (New York: Columbia University Press, 1950), and Myron Weiner, “Asian Immigrants and U.S. Foreign Policy,” Immigration and U.S. Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley (Boulder: Westview, 1990), 192–213. 69. Whom We Shall Welcome, requested 4 September 1952, submitted 1 January 1953 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1953), 45. 70. There seems to have been some confusion in Congress about what fascism was. When the immigration committee chair (Lesinski) asked an American Legion representative, “Is there any difference between a Fascist, a Nazi, and a Communist?” the Legionnaire replied, “I do not know that there is. They are all just based on a fallacious theory of Godlessness and that the state or party is the source from which all power and rights obtain, whereas our theory is that our rights are divinely given. This is written right into our law.” To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 9. 71. Harry Truman (president), message of 24 March 1952, CR v. 98, 13 May 1952, 5107.
Notes to Pages 113–17
315
72. Herbert Lehman (D-NY), CR v. 98, 13 May 1952, 5100, 5101. 73. Thomas Jenkins (R-OH), CR v. 80, pt. 3 (74C/2S), 3 February 1936, 1384. 74. Nathan D. Perlman, justice and former congressman (R-NY), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), 21 February–6 March 1946, 55. 75. Walter George (D-GA), CR v. 98, 22 May 1952, 5774. 76. William Pittenger (R-MN), CR v. 91, 10 October 1945, 9540. 77. Herbert O’Conor (D-MD), CR v. 95, pt. 4 (81C/1S), 25 April 1949, 4999. 78. Samuel Hobbs (D-AL), CR v. 96, pt. 8 (81C/2S), 17 July 1950, 10456. 79. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 94, pt. X (80C/2S), 2 June 1948, 6904. 80. Lawrence Smith (R-WI), CR v. 98, 21 May 1952, 5663. 81. Robert Reynolds (D-NC), CR v. 90, pt. 5 (78C/2S), 11 August 1944, 6906. 82. George Norris (Independent Republican-NE), CR v. 72, pt. 7 (71C/2S), 21 April 1930, 7426. 83. John Vorys (R-OH), CR v. 98, 24 April 1952, 4411. 84. William Poage (D-TX), CR v. 97 (82C/1S), 13 February 1951, 1251, 1256; John Robsion (R-KY) 10 October 1945, 9539. 85. Hubert Ellis (R-WV), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Allies and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 39–40. 86. Mr. Twomey (American Legion), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 11. 87. John C. Williamson (Veterans of Foreign Wars), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quota, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 17. 88. Hubert Ellis (R-WV), CR v. 91, 11 July 1945, A3394. 89. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), Foreign Aid Appropriation Bill 1950 and 1951, Hearings before the Senate Committee on Appropriations 1949 and 1951, 268. 90. John C. Williamson (Veterans of Foreign Wars), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), 21 February–6 March 1946, 17–18. 91. Ed Gossett (D-TX), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), 21 February–6 March 1946, 47. 92. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 94 (80C/2S), 26 May 1948, 6455–6; 2 June 1948, 6900. 93. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 94 (80C/2S), 2 June 1948, 6903. 94. Carl Hatch (D-NM), CR v. 93, 21 July 1947, 9476. 95. Alben Barkley (D-KY), CR v. 93, 26 July 1947, 10330. 96. Abraham Multer (D-NY), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4318. 97. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 98, 15 May 1952, 5230. 98. John Pastore (D-RI), CR v. 98, 14 May 1952, 5162.
316
Notes to Pages 117–20
99. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 97 (82C/1S), 13 September 1951, 11285. 100. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4314. 101. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 97 (82C/1S), 13 September 1951, 11285. 102. Matthew Liff (National Council of Union Labor Legionnaires), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 100. 103. Arthur Klein (NY), CR v. 95, pt. 4, 19 July 1950, A5229. 104. Thomas Gordon (D-IL), CR v. 93, 26 June 1947, 7741. 105. William Benton (D-CT), CR v. 98, 21 May 1952, 5618. 106. Ed Gossett (D-TX), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 2. 107. Ed Gossett (D-TX), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 21 February–6 March 1946, 2. 108. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), Study of Naturalization Laws and Procedures, Hearings before Subcommittee II of the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 9 May–5 June 1945, 15. 109. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), Study of Naturalization Laws and Procedures, Hearings before Subcommittee II of the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 9 May–5 June 1945, 1–2. 110. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4305. 111. William Jenner (R-IN), CR v. 96 (81C/2S), 5 April 1950, 4739. 112. Clare Boothe Luce (R-CT), To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 11. 113. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), Study of Immigration and Naturalization Laws and Problems, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), pt. 1, 24 April and 2 May 1945, 14. 114. James (O’Brien) McMahon (D-CT), CR v. 98, 14 May 1952, 5217. 115. Georgia Lusk (D-NM), CR v. 93, 26 July 1947, A4008. 116. Leo Goodman (Congress of Industrial Organizations), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 88. 117. Matthew Liff (National Council of Union Labor Legionnaires), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 99. 118. Herbert Lehman (D-NY), CR v. 98, 19 May 1952, 5429. 119. Matthew Liff (National Council of Union Labor Legionnaires), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 100.
Notes to Pages 120–23
317
120. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and To Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 9. 121. Harry Truman (president), message of 24 March 1952, CR v. 98, 13 May 1952, 5108. 122. Francis Biddle (attorney general), To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 55. 123. Leonard Pasqual (Order of the Sons of Liberty), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 49–50. 124. Walter Judd (R-MN), CR v. 98, 26 June 1952, 8217–23. 125. Lewis G. Hines (American Federation of Labor), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 79. 126. Margaret Stone (National Women’s Trade Union League), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 98. 127. Leo Goodman (Congress of Industrial Organizations), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 87–88. 128. Georgia Lusk (D-NM), CR v. 93, 26 July 1947, A4008. 129. John Foster Dulles (R-NY to 1949; secretary of state 1953+), “A Policy of Boldness,” reprinted from Life in CR v. 98, 19 May 1952, 5398, 5399. 130. James (O’Brien) McMahon (D-CT), CR v. 98, 14 May 1952, 5167. 131. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 98, 16 May 1952, 5330. 132. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 98, 19 May 1952, 5432. 133. Walter Judd (R-MN), CR v. 95, pt. 2 (81C/1S), 1 March 1949, 1678. 134. Walter Judd (R-MN), CR v. 91, 10 October 1945, 9541; Celler spoke the same words 7 March 1945 in To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 4. 135. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 3. 136. Clare Boothe Luce (R-CT), To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 11. 137. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 98, 15 May 1952, 5230. 138. Thomas Ford (R-CA), CR v. 89, pt. 3 (78C/1S), 21 October 1943, 8627. 139. Robert C. Alexander (State Department), To Deny Admission to the
318
Notes to Pages 123–29
United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 2, 20 March–8 May 1946, 114. 140. David Walsh (D-MA), CR v. 71, pt. 2, 13 June 1929, 2777. 141. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 75, pt. 8 (72C/1S), 18 April 1932, 8438. 142. Harley Kilgore (D-WV), CR v. 98, 21 May 1952, 5638. 143. Everett Dirksen (R-IL), CR v. 91, 10 October 1945, 9542. 144. Nathan D. Perlman, justice and former congressman (R-NY), To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), 21 February–6 March 1946, 55–56, 57. 145. Walter Judd (R-MN), CR v. 95, pt. 2 (81C/1S), 1 March 1949, 1678. 146. Wayne Morse (D-OR), CR v. 98, 21 May 1952, 5609. 147. Hugh Addonizio (D-NJ), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4309. 148. James Delaney (D-NY), CR v. 96, pt. 1 (81C/2S), 2 February 1950, 1388. 149. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4309. 150. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4319. 151. John Pastore (D-RI), CR v. 98, 14 May 1952, 5167. 152. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 98, 12 March 1952, 2141. 153. Harry Truman (president), message of 24 March 1952, CR v. 98, 13 May 1952, 5107. 154. Harry Truman (president), message of 24 March 1952, CR v. 98, 13 May 1952, 5107. 155. Louis Heller (D-NY), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4311. 156. Cornelia Bryce Gifford Pinchot (individual), To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and To Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 7–14 March 1945, 57. 157. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 95, pt. 4 (81C/1S), 25 April 1949, 4993. 158. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 95, pt. 4 (81C/1S), 25 April 1949, 4994. 159. Senate Report 1515, The Immigration and Naturalization Systems of the United States (81C/2S), 20 April 1950, 781–82. 160. John Rankin (D-MS), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4320. 161. James (Will) Taylor (R-TN), CR v. 85, pt. 1 (76C/2S), 3 November 1939, 1377–78. 162. Hamilton Fish (R-NY), CR v. 87, pt. 8 (76C/3S), 23 June 1941, A3003. 163. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 94, pt. 1 (80C/2S), 2 June 1948, 6904. 164. Immigration and Naturalization Systems of the United States, Senate Report 1515 (81C/2S), 20 April 1950, 781, 782. 165. Herbert O’Conor (D-MA), CR v. 95, pt. 4 (81C/1S), 20 September 1949, 13058. 166. John Rankin (D-MS), CR v. 98 (82C/2S), 23 April 1952, 4315, 4316. 167. John Rankin (D-MS), CR v. 98, 23 April 1952, 4320. 168. Acting Commissioner of Immigration (A. R. Mackey), Immigration and Naturalization Service Annual Report 1950 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1950), 3. 169. Karl Stefan (R-NE), CR v. 96, pt. 8, 13 July 1950, 10453. 170. Francis Walter (D-PA), CR v. 97 (82C/1S), 5 February 1951, 988.
Notes to Pages 130–37
319
171. Herbert O’Conor (D-MA), CR v. 95, pt. 4 (81C/1S), 20 September 1949, 13059, 13060. 172. Albert Johnson (R-WA), Exclusion and Expulsion of Communists, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (72C/1S), 23 February–15 March 1932, 68. 173. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 95, pt. 4 (81C/1S), 25 April 1949, 4993. 174. Herbert Lehman (D-NY), CR v. 98, 22 May 1952, 5761. 175. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 94, pt. 1 (80C/2S), 2 June 1948, 6892. 176. Chase Going Woodhouse (D-CT), CR v. 92, pt. 12 (79C/2S), 31 July 1946, A4662. 177. Wayne Morse (D-OR), CR v. 94 (80C/2S), 1 June 1948, 6792. 178. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 93, 29 April 1947, A1995. 179. Paul Douglas (D-IL), CR v. 98, 19 May 1952, 5412. 180. House Document 382, Message from the President of the United States, 7 July 1947, 8330. 181. Harley Kilgore (D-WV), CR v. 95, 15 October 1949, 14686. 182. Frances Bolton (R-OH), CR v. 93, 25 July 1947, A3822. 183. William Chapman Revercomb (R-WV), CR v. 93, pt. 2, 25 March 1947, 2506. 184. A later chapter provides evidence concerning the role that regionalism and partisanship played in voting on these acts. 185. CR v. 98, 22 May 1952, 5778. 186. House vote in CR v. 94, pt. 6 (80C/2S), 7887–88. 187. George Dondero (R-MI), CR v. 96 (81C/2S), 27 June 1950, 9303. 188. George Dondero (R-MI), CR v. 96 (81C/2S), 27 June 1950, 9303. 189. William Benton (D-CT), CR v. 98, 21 May 1952, 5616. 190. George Dondero (R-MI), CR v. 97 (82C/1S), 8 October 1951, 12814. 191. William Benton (D-CT), CR v. 98, 14 May 1952, 5149, 5150. 192. Walter Judd (R-MN), CR v. 96, 14 August 1950, 12466. 193. George Miller (D-CA), CR v. 95, pt. 1 (81C/1S), 1 March 1949, 1685. 194. Immigration and Nationality Act (McCarran-Walter), HR 5678 (82C) P.L. 414; 66 Stat. 163, 27 June 1952, title II, chapter 1, section 202. 195. Adam Clayton Powell (D-NY), CR v. 98, 25 April 1952, 4435, 4439. 196. Louis Heller (D-NY), CR v. 98, 26 June 1952, 8224. 197. Arthur Klein (D-NY), CR v. 98, 26 June 1952, 8224. 198. Francis Walter (D-PA), CR v. 98, 13 March 1952, 2284–85. 199. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 98, 13 May 1952, 5089. 200. Harry Truman, Immigration and Nationality Act—Message from the President of the United States (H. Doc. No. 520), 25 June 1952. 201. Dean Acheson (secretary of state), in Whom We Shall Welcome, report requested 4 September 1952, submitted 1 January 1953 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1953), 47. 202. Thomas Jenkins (R-OH), CR v. 83, pt. 4 (75C/3S), 17 February 1938, 4229, previously cited. 203. Edward Rees (R-KS), CR v. 89, pt. 3 (78C/1S), 21 October 1943, 8624, previously cited.
320
Notes to Pages 137–49
204. John Vorys (R-OH), CR v. 98, 24 April 1952, 4411, previously cited. 205. Dwight Eisenhower (presidential candidate), speech of 17 October 1952, in Whom We Shall Welcome, requested 4 September 1952, submitted 1 January 1953 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1953), 60. 206. Acting Commissioner of Immigration (A. R. Mackey), Immigration and Naturalization Service Annual Report 1950 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1950), 37. 207. In fact, political borders were somewhat smaller than federal boundaries, in that they contained only citizens, and not all of those who happened to be on U.S. territory at a given time. 208. With the development of intercontinental ballistic missiles, the country also increased its power by eliminating borders’ importance to defense. 209. Nathan Perlman (justice and former congressman (R-NY)), To Deny Admission to Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas, Hearings before the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/2S), pt. 1, 21 February–6 March 1946, 55–56.
Chapter 6
1. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10113. 2. Harold Donohue (D-MA), CR v. 102, pt. 7 (84C/2S), 8 June 1956, 9892. 3. Francis Walter (D-PA), CR v. 101, pt. 8 (84C/1S), 11 July 1955, 12173. 4. Brady Gentry (D-TX), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10157. 5. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10115. 6. Francis Walter (D-PA), CR v. 103, pt. 7 (85C/1S), 8565. 7. Maston O’Neal (D-GA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21786. 8. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 21 September 1965, 24552. 9. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10114. 10. Howard Smith (D-VA), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10150. 11. John McClellan (D-AR), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 21 September 1965, 24555. 12. Joseph (Frank) Wilson (D-TX), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10153. 13. Ovie C. Fisher (D-TX), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21774. 14. H. Allen Smith (R-CA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 24 August 1965, 21572. 15. Brady Gentry (D-TX), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10157. 16. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10114, 10115. 17. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 100, pt. 7 (83C/2S), 6 July 1954, 9757. 18. John Robsion (R-KY), CR v. 100, pt. 1 (83C/2S), 11 January 1954, 134. 19. Michael Feighan (D-OH), CR v. 110, pt. 6 (88C/2S), 10 April 1964, 7628; Frank Lausche (D-OH), CR v. 111, pt. 2 (89C/1S), 20 January 1965, 1248. 20. James (Strom) Thurmond (R-SC), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 17 September 1965, 24237. 21. Sam Ervin (D-NC), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 17 September 1965, 24231.
Notes to Pages 149–55
321
22. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 21 September 1965, 24551. 23. James Eastland (D-MS), CR v. 102, pt. 11 (84C/2S), 27 July 1956, 15004. 24. Lyndon Johnson (president), H. Doc. 52, CR v. 111, pt. 1 (89C/1S), 13 January 1965, 638. 25. Sam Ervin (D-NC), CR v. 111, pt. 3 (89C/1S), 4 March 1965, 4144. 26. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 24 August 1965, 21579. 27. To this extent, regimes originate with early cold war attempts to make allied cooperation automatic. The core work on regimes is collected in Stephen D. Krasner, ed., International Regimes (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983). 28. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 20 September 1965, 24472. 29. John Dent (D-PA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21777. 30. Torbert MacDonald (D-MA), CR v. 106, pt. 5 (86C/2S), 22 March 1960, 6314. 31. John Pastore (D-RI), CR v. 103, pt. 11 (85C/1S), 21 August 1951, 15497. 32. Charles Diggs Jr (D-MI), CR v. 101, pt. 2 (84C/1S), 10 March 1955, 2679. 33. Victor Anfuso (D-NY), CR v. 101, pt. 1 (84C/1S), 11 January 1955, 262. 34. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21759. 35. H. Alexander Smith (R-NJ), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 30 June 1953, 7622. 36. Homer Ferguson (R-MI), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10115. 37. Jacob Gilbert (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21770. 38. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 106, pt. 5 (86C/2S), 17 March 1960, 5892. 39. John Pastore (D-RI), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10095. 40. John Dingell (D-MI), CR v. 103, pt. 2 (85C/1S), 18 February 1957, 2190. 41. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 104, pt. 1 (85C/2S), 29 January 1958, 1274. 42. Dean Rusk, Congressional Quarterly, 20 July 1964, 100. 43. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10152. 44. Thomas Lane (MA), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 27 July 1953, 9953. 45. Carlton Sickles (D-MD), CR v. 109, pt. 11 (88C/1S), 19 August 1963, 15358. 46. H. Alexander Smith (R-NJ), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 30 June 1953, 7622. 47. Thomas Lane (D-MA), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 27 July 1953, 9953. 48. Irving Ives (R-NY), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10100. 49. Philip Hart (D-MI), CR v. 109, pt. 12 (88C/1S), 23 August 1963, 15781. 50. Patrick McCarran (D-NV), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10114. 51. Herman Welker (R-ID), CR v. 99, pt. 8 (83C/1S), 29 July 1953, 10246. 52. Herman Welker (R-ID), CR v. 99, pt. 8 (83C/1S), 29 July 1953, 10246. 53. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), The Stranger at Our Gate: America’s Immigration Policy (New York: Public Affairs Committee, 1954), pamphlet no. 202, 20. 54. Alexander Wiley (R-WI), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 10 July 1953, 8424. 55. Herbert Lehman (D-NY), CR v. 102, pt. 3 (84C/2S), 20 February 1956, 2970.
322
Notes to Pages 155–62
56. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 104, pt. 1 (85C/2S), 29 January 1958, 1276. 57. Kenneth Keating (R-NY), CR v. 107, pt. 6 (87C/1S), 3 May 1961, 7071. 58. Robert Hendrickson (R-NJ), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10102. 59. Patrick Hillings (R-CA), CR v. 100, pt. 1 (83C/2S), 22 February 1954, 2091. 60. Robert Hendrickson (R-NJ), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 15 July 1953, 8885. 61. Daniel Flood (D-PA), CR v. 101, pt. 8 (84C/1S), 11 July 1955, 10238. 62. John McClellan (D-AR), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 21 September 1965, 24554. 63. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 104, pt. 13 (85C/2S), 6 August 1958, 16311. 64. Claiborne Pell (D-RI), CR v. 108, pt. 4 (87C/2S), 19 March 1962, 4484. 65. Fernand St. Germain (D-RI), CR v. 108, pt. 4 (87C/2S), 19 March 1962, 4537. 66. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 103, pt. 1 (85C/1S), 25 January 1957, 972. 67. Kenneth Keating (R-NY), CR v. 103, pt. 6 (85C/1S), 4 June 1957, 8328. 68. Hiram Fong (R-HI), CR v. 109, pt. 10 (88C/1S), 29 July 1963, 13462. 69. Joseph Clark (D-PA), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 20 September 1965, 24500. 70. Pat Hillings (R-CA), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10154. 71. Alvin Bentley (R-MI), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10158. 72. Silvio Conte (R-MA), CR v. 105, pt. 6 (86C/1S), 7 May 1959, 7755. 73. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21757. 74. CR v. 104, pt. 13 (85C/2S), 6 August 1958, 16392. 75. CR v. 104, pt. 13 (85C/2S), 6 August 1958, 16392. 76. CR v. 107, pt. 15 (87C/1S), 19 September 1961, 20222. 77. CR v. 106, pt. 14 (86C/2S), 31 August 1960, 18847. 78. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 106, pt. 5 (86C/2S), 17 March 1960, 5892. 79. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 102, pt. 10 (84C/2S), 23 July 1956, 14127. 80. Philip Hart (D-MI), CR v. 108, pt. 4 (87C/2S), 21 March 1962, 4675. 81. Claiborne Pell (D-RI), CR v. 109, pt. 2 (88C/1S), 7 February 1963, 2030. 82. John Lindsay (R-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 6 (89C/1S), 13 April 1965, 7978. 83. Albert Cretella (R-CT), CR v. 102, pt. 6 (84C/2S), 2 May 1956, 7359. 84. Robert Kennedy (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 20 September 1965, 24485. 85. John Pastore (D-RI), CR v. 103, pt. 11 (85C/1S), 21 August 1957, 15497. 86. John Kennedy (president), CR v. 109, pt. 10 (88C/1S), 23 July 1963, reprinted 31 July 1963, 13769. 87. Claude Pepper (D-FL), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21794. 88. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 25 March 1953, 2322. 89. Robert Hendrickson (R-NJ), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10101. 90. For a table of mortgages, see CR v. 98 (82C/2S), 19 May 1952, 5412. 91. Richard Nixon (vice president), CR v. 103, pt. 1 (85C/1S), 17 January 1957, 730–31.
Notes to Pages 162–68
323
92. Dwight Eisenhower (president), H. Doc. 85, CR v. 103, pt. 1 (85C/1S), 31 January 1957, 1355. 93. John Dingell (D-MI), CR v. 103, pt. 1 (85C/1S), 18 February 1957, 2190–91. 94. William Langer (R-ND), CR v. 102, pt. 8 (84C/2S), 8 June 1956, 10872. 95. Leverett Saltonstall (R-MA), CR v. 108, pt. 16 (87C/2S), 21413. 96. DeWitt Hyde (R-MD), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10151. 97. Joe Holt (R-CA), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10160. 98. Paul Douglas (D-IL), CR v. 99, pt. 8 (83C/1S), 29 July 1953, 10243. 99. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 110, pt. 1 (88C/2S), 13 January 1964, reprinted 29 January 1964, 1389. 100. Dwight Eisenhower (president), State of the Union Address, CR v. 102, pt. 1 (84C/2S), 12 January 1956, 1502, repeated almost verbatim 8 February 1956, 2384. 101. Arthur Watkins (R-UT), CR v. 102, pt. 11 (84C/2S), 27 July 1956, 15006. 102. Irving Ives (R-NY), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10101. 103. Hiram Fong (R-HI), CR v. 109, pt. 12 (88C/1S), 23 August 1963, 15780. 104. Durward Hall (R-MO), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21775. 105. Hugh Addonizio (D-NJ), CR v. 105, pt. 5 (86C/1S), 15 April 1959, 5859. 106. Claiborne Pell (D-RI), CR v. 107, pt. 6 (87C/1S), 3 May 1961, 7257. 107. Ogden Reid (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 3 (89C/1S), 23 February 1965, 7979. 108. Paul Fino (R-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21807. 109. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 104, pt. 1 (85C/2S), 16 January 1958, 665. 110. William Proxmire (D-WI), CR v. 106, pt. 5 (86C/2S), 18 March 1960, 5960. 111. Kenneth Keating (R-NY), CR v. 107, pt. 1 (87C/1S), 23 January 1961, 1082. 112. Leverett Saltonstall (R-MA), CR v. 108, pt. 16 (87C/2S), 21413. 113. Ronald Cameron (D-CA), CR v. 111, pt. 2 (89C/1S), 10 February 1965, 2494. 114. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 28 July 1953, 10107. 115. Brockman Adams (D-WA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21766. 116. John Lindsay (R-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 6 (89C/1S), 13 April 1965, 7978. 117. Thomas O’Neill (D-MA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21790. 118. No legislator in the public record, though, ever claimed that the Vietnamese were ‹ghting badly or attempting to sabotage the war out of spite, although this was what their general arguments implied was to be feared. 119. Unemployment ‹gures from Census Bureau, Statistical Abstract of the United States, various years, and Historical Statistics of the United States: Colonial Times to 1970 (Washington, DC: GPO). 120. Sam Ervin (D-NC), CR v. 111, pt. 3 (89C/1S), 4 March 1965, 4144. 121. Maston O’Neal (D-GA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21786. 122. William Jenner (R-IN), CR v. 99, pt. 8 (83C/1S), 29 July 1953, 10239.
324
Notes to Pages 168–72
123. John Stennis (D-MS), CR v. 103, pt. 3 (85C/1S), 2 March 1957, 2938. 124. Legislators in earlier eras charged that immigration policy revealed to Americans how the country felt about people of their heritage. This made some sense when the Americans spoken of were ‹rst- or second-generation immigrants and could personalize charges leveled in the debate. More interesting is that this argument was also made regarding black Americans and Africa in the 1960s. Whereas Bohemians after a few decades were no longer identi‹ed with AustriaHungary or Czechoslovakia, one to four hundred years after the last signi‹cant in›ux of blacks to the country, in the terms of public debate black Americans were still foreign. 125. Maston O’Neal (D-GA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21786. 126. John McClellan (D-AR), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 21 September 1965, 24556. 127. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 107, pt. 1 (87C/1S), 23 January 1961, 1081. 128. Frank Annunzio (D-IL), CR v. 111, pt. 5 (89C/1S), 6 April 1965, 7135. 129. Laurence Burton (R-UT), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21783. 130. Abraham Ribicoff (D-CT), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 22 September 1965, 24782. 131. Bernard Grabowski (D-CT), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21793. 132. John Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 103, pt. 12 (85C/1S), 29 August 1957, 16493. 133. Stephen Young (D-OH), CR v. 111, pt. 13 (89C/1S), 5 August 1965, 19581. 134. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 110, pt. 1 (88C/2S), 15 January 1964, 477. 135. Benjamin Rosenthal (Democrat-Liberal-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 9 (89C/1S), 1 June 1965, 12104. 136. John Conyers (D-MI), CR v. 111, pt. 19 (89C/1S), 6 October 1965, 26152. 137. Hiram Fong (R-HI), CR v. 109, pt. 12 (88C/1S), 23 August 1963, 15765, 15766. 138. Alfred Santangelo (D-NY), CR v. 108, pt. 17 (87C/2S), 5 October 1962, 22607. 139. Philip Hart (D-MI), CR v. 109, pt. 2 (88C/1S), 7 February 1963, 2022. 140. Torbert MacDonald (D-MA), CR v. 101, pt. 4 (84C/1S), 13 April 1955, 4413–14. 141. Francis Walter (D-PA), CR v. 107, pt. 5 (87C/1S), 13 April speech reprinted 17 April 1961, 6026. 142. Francis Walter (D-PA), CR v. 108, pt. 9 (87C/2S), 27 June 1962, 11968. 143. Michael Feighan (D-OH), CR v. 110, pt. 6 (88C/2S), 10 April 1964, 7628. 144. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 110, pt. 16 (88C/2S), 21 August 1964, 20860. 145. Hiram Fong (R-HI), CR v. 109, pt. 12 (88C/1S), 23 August 1963, 15766. 146. Philip Hart (D-MI), CR v. 108, pt. 4 (87C/2S), 21 March 1962, 4675.
Notes to Pages 172–75
325
147. John Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 103, pt. 8 (85C/1S), 27 June 1957, 10455–56. 148. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 107, pt. 11 (87C/1S), 9 August 1961, 15222. 149. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 103, pt. 1 (85C/1S), 25 January 1957, 972. 150. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 105, pt. 7 (86C/1S), 2 June 1959, 9523. 151. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 104, pt. 1 (85C/2S), 16 January 1958, 665. 152. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), The Stranger at Our Gate: America’s Immigration Policy (New York: Public Affairs Committee, 1954), pamphlet no. 202, 16. 153. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), The Stranger at Our Gate: America’s Immigration Policy (New York: Public Affairs Committee, 1954), pamphlet no. 202, 21. 154. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), The Stranger at Our Gate: America’s Immigration Policy (New York: Public Affairs Committee, 1954), pamphlet no. 202, 14. 155. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 17 September 1965, 24226. 156. Hugh Addonizio (D-NJ), CR v. 100, pt. 12 (83C/2S), 19 August 1954, 15232. 157. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 100, pt. 12 (83C/2S), 19 August 1954, 15232. 158. These sheepherders, who became something of a joke, were destined for Nevada, home of Pat McCarran, chair of the senate immigration subcommittee. 159. Philip Hart (D-MI), CR v. 108, pt. 4 (87C/2S), 21 March 1962, 4674. 160. Michael Feighan (D-OH), CR v. 110, pt. 6 (88C/2S), 10 April 1964, 7627. 161. Ogden Reid (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 3 (89C/1S), 23 February 1965, 3401. 162. Homer Ferguson (R-MI), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 24 April 1953, 3745. 163. Dwight Eisenhower (president), CR v. 99 (83C/1S), 23 April 1953, 3693–94. 164. Dean Rusk, Congressional Quarterly Weekly Report, 24 May 1965. 165. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), The Stranger at Our Gate: America’s Immigration Policy (New York: Public Affairs Committee, 1954), pamphlet no. 202, 23; introduced by Jacob Javits (NY), CR v. 100, pt. 4 (83C/2S), 12 April 1954, 4985; Peter Rodino (NJ), CR v. 103, pt. 2 (85C/1S), 7 February 1957, 2189. 166. Dwight Eisenhower (president), H. Doc. 36, CR v. 106, pt. 5 (86C/2S), 17 March 1960, 5894. 167. These divisions differ from those used by the Immigration and Naturalization Service, though they mirror those used by Congress. The INS summarizes immigration by geographical division, whereas immigration law separates immigrants by political divisions. For example, in its summaries the INS groups together all immigrants from Asia, including both those from Israel and those from Mongolia, whereas immigration law separates Asia into the Barred Zone and the colonial areas, regulated differently. The divisions used above are those on which laws were based. 168. Philip Hart (D-MI), CR v. 108, pt. 4 (87C/2S), 21 March 1962, 4675. 169. Restrictionist Patrick McCarran (D-NV) managed to institutionalize annual special legislation admitting Basque sheepherders to the United States. They headed for ranches in Colorado . . . and Nevada.
326
Notes to Pages 175–82
170. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21811. 171. Paul Findley (R-IL), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21783. 172. John Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 103, pt. 11 (85C/1S), 29 August 1957, 16493. 173. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21762. 174. James Corman (D-CA), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21813. 175. Barratt O’Hara (D-IL), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21815. 176. Jacob Javits (R-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 20 September 1965, 24470. 177. Clark MacGregor (R-MN), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 24 August 1965, 21573–74. 178. William McCulloch (R-OH), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21579. 179. Cornelius Gallagher (D-NJ), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21797. 180. CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21816. 181. House Report 1101, September 1965. 182. Herbert Lehman (D-NY), CR v. 100 (83C/2S), 3 March 1954, 2556. 183. Hubert Humphrey (D-MN), CR v. 100 (83C/2S), 3 March 1954, 2558. 184. Ovie C. Fisher (D-TX), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21773. 185. Frank Horton (R-NY), CR v. 110, pt. 9 (88C/2S), 28 May 1964, 12223. 186. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 17 September 1965, 24228. 187. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 104, pt. 1 (85C/2S), 16 January 1958, 665. 188. Emanuel Celler (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21757. 189. Lyndon Johnson (president), H. Doc 52, CR v. 111, pt. 1 (89C/1S), 13 January 1965, 639. 190. Robert Giaimo (D-CT), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21767. 191. Jacob Gilbert (D-NY), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21771. 192. Arch Moore (R-WV), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21780. 193. Robert Kennedy (D-NY), testimony reprinted in CR v. 110, pt. 13 (88C/2S), 22 July 1964, 16590. 194. Donald Irwin (D-CT), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 24 August 1965, 21597. 195. Arch Moore (R-WV), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 30 September 1965, 25658. 196. CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21816. 197. CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 22 September 1965, 24783. 198. CR v. 111, pt. 19 (89C/1S), 30 September 1965, 25664. 199. Please refer to chapter 9 for evidence that the differences by region are stronger than those for party.
Notes to Pages 183–93
327
200. These numbers are from the Immigration and Naturalization Service, Statistical Yearbook of the Immigration and Naturalization Service (Washington, DC: GPO), various years. 201. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 111, pt. 16 (89C/1S), 25 August 1965, 21812. 202. Harry Golden (individual), CR v. 110, pt. 18 (88C/2S), 20 August 1964, reprinted 2 October 1964, 23607. 203. Everett Dirksen (R-IL), CR v. 106, pt. 5 (86C/2S), 18 March 1960, 5948. 204. Frank Thompson (D-NJ), CR v. 101, pt. 7 (84 C/1S), 28 June 1955, 9429.
Chapter 7
1. Ed Koch (D-NY), CR v. 117, pt. 4 (92C/1S), 4 March 1971, 5118. 2. John Rarick (D-LA), CR v. 117, pt. 8 (92C/1S), 7 April 1971, 10266. 3. Jesse Helms (R-NC), CR v. 120, pt. 29 (93C/2S), 10 December 1974, 38830. 4. John Brademas (D-IN), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14358. 5. Paul Simon (D-IL), CR v. 131, pt. 17 (100C/1S), 11 September 1985, 23323. 6. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 113, pt. 2 (90C/1S), 30 January 1967, 1907–8. 7. B. F. Sisk (D-CA), CR v. 123, pt. 22 (95C/1S), 4 August 1977, 27727. 8. Leonard Chapman (Commissioner of the Immigration and Naturalization Service), CR v. 122, pt. 13 (94C/2S), 1 June 1976, 16145. 9. William Lipinski (D-IL), CR v. 135, pt. 116 (101C/1S), 13 September 1989, H5662. 10. Edna Kelley (D-NY), CR v. 114, pt. 4 (90C/2S), 4 March 1968, 4918. 11. Robert Wilson (R-CA), CR v. 114, pt. 4 (90C/2S), 4 March 1968, 5351. 12. John Rarick (D-LA), CR v. 117, pt. 8 (92C/1S), 7 April 1971, 10266. 13. Millicent Fenwick (R-NJ), CR v. 122, pt. 9 (94C/2S), 12 April 1976, 10576. 14. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 121, pt. 12 (94C/1S), 16 May 1975, 14849. 15. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 121, pt. 12 (94C/1S), 16 May 1975, 14860. 16. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14339. 17. Joshua Eilberg (D-PA), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14340. 18. James Abourezk (D-SD), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 8 May 1975, 13499. 19. Jesse Helms (R-NC), CR v. 121, pt. 12 (94C/1S), 16 May 1975, 14852, 14859. 20. Donald Riegle (D-MI), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14365. 21. Jack Kemp (R-NY), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14355. 22. This particular poll is representative of those at the time although it was not speci‹cally discussed. The question to which the public responded was “Thinking about the Indochinese refugees, the so-called ‘boat-people,’ . . . would you favor or oppose the U.S. relaxing its immigration policies so that many of these
328
Notes to Pages 193–200
people could come to live in the U.S.?” Gallup Opinion Index 170 lists this ‹gure (September 1979, 9). 23. John Anderson (R-IL), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14325. 24. William Dickinson (R-AL), CR v. 125, pt. 24 (96C/1S), 8 November 1979, 31536. 25. Lawrence MacDonald (D-GA), CR v. 125, pt. 24 (96C/1S), 9 November 1979, 32033. 26. Samuel Hayakawa (R-CA), CR v. 126, pt. 5 (96C/2S), 26 March 1980, 6671. 27. Samuel Hayakawa (R-CA), CR v. 127, pt. 1 (97C/1S), 6 January 1981, 179. 28. Leon Gordenker makes this point in general—not about Nicaraguan refugees—in Refugees in International Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1987). 29. David Durenberger (R-MN), CR v. 129, pt. 8 (98C/1S), 18 May 1983, 12827. 30. Dennis DeConcini (D-AZ), CR v. 129, pt. 11 (98C/1S), 26 May 1983, 14127. 31. Steven Symms (R-ID), CR v. 131, pt. 17 (100C/1S), 16 September 1965, 23807. 32. CR v. 133, pt. 15 (100C/1S), 28 July 1987, 21325. 33. Shirley Chisholm (D-NY), CR v. 127, pt. 8 (97C/1S), 14 May 1981, 9894. 34. Arlen Specter (R-PA), CR v. 133, pt. 2 (100C/1S), 20 January 1987, 1525. 35. Jesse Helms (R-NC), CR v. 129, pt. 8 (98C/1S), 16 May 1983, 12365. 36. Les Aspin (D-WI), CR v. 126, pt. 18 (96C/2S), 5 September 1980, 24422. 37. Daniel Moynihan (D-NY), CR v. 133, pt. 1 (100C/1S), 6 January 1987, 456. 38. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 113, pt. 2 (90C/1S), 30 January 1967, 1907–8. 39. Barney Frank (D-MA), CR v. 130, pt. 11 (98C/2S), 31 May 1984, 14755. 40. Alan C. Nelson (commissioner), Immigration and Naturalization Service, Annual Report 1980 (Washington, DC: GPO, 1980), 11. 41. Alan Cranston (D-CA), CR v. 131, pt. 1 (100C/1S), 21 January 1985, 655. 42. Robert Drinan (D-MA), CR v. 123, pt. 9 (95C/1S), 19 April 1977, 11128. 43. This number is based on data in table 1, page 17, of IISS, The Military Balance, 1988–1989 (London: International Institute for Strategic Studies, 1988). 44. William Clay (D-MO), CR v. 116, pt. 14 (91C/2S), 4 June 1970, 18409. 45. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 127, pt. 17 (97C/1S), 1 October 1981, 22741. 46. Edward Roybal (D-CA), CR v. 123, pt. 22 (95C/1S), 5 August 1977, 27816. 47. Claiborne Pell (D-RI), CR v. 126, pt. 13 (96C/2S), 23 June 1980, 16339. 48. Theodore Weiss (D-NY), CR v. 128, pt. 23 (97C/2S), 17 December 1982, 32016. 49. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 129, pt. 8 (98C/1S), 28 April 1983, 10204. 50. William Richardson (D-NM), CR v. 131, pt. 12 (100C/1S), 24 June 1985, 16938.
Notes to Pages 200–209
329
51. James Tra‹cant (D-OH), CR v. 134, pt. 52, 20 April 1988, H2176. 52. Alan Simpson (R-WY), CR v. 129, pt. 8 (98C/1S), 28 April 1983, 10226. 53. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 134, pt. 87, 14 June 1988, S7721. 54. Arlen Specter (R-PA), CR v. 135, pt. 93 (101C/1S), 13 July 1989, S7872. 55. Stanley Lundine (D-NY), CR v. 130, pt. 12 (98C/2S), 19 June 1984, 17062. 56. Jesse Helms (R-NC), CR v. 135, pt. 92, 12 July 1989, S7750, echoed CR v. 135, pt. 93 (101C/1S), 13 July 1989, S7872. 57. Lawrence Pressler (R-SD), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 13 August 1982, 21027. 58. Frank Annunzio (D-IL), CR v. 116, pt. 21 (91C/2S), 10 August 1970, 28082. 59. John LaFalce (D-NY), CR v. 125, pt. 20 (96C/1S), 28 September 1979, 26877. 60. Carl Curtis (R-NE), CR v. 121, pt. 3 (94C/1S), 7 February 1975, 2816. 61. Alfonse D’Amato (R-NY), CR v. 134, pt. 31, 15 March 1988, S1844. 62. Dale Bumpers (D-AR), CR v. 129, pt. 8 (98C/1S), 16 May 1983, 12385–86. 63. Dale Bumpers (D-AR), CR v. 135, pt. 92, 12 July 1989, S7769. 64. Ben Nighthorse Campbell (D-CO), CR v. 136, pt. 150 (101C/2S), 27 October 1990, H12362. 65. William (Phil) Gramm (R-TX), CR v. 134, pt. 30, 14 March 1988, S2131. 66. Dale Bumpers (D-AR), CR v. 135, pt. 92, 12 July 1989, S7769. 67. John Bryant (D-TX), CR v. 136, pt. 150 (101C/2S), 27 October 1990, H12366. 68. Glenn Anderson (D-CA), CR v. 136, pt. 127 (101C/2S), 3 October 1990, E3098. 69. Dale Bumpers (D-AR), CR v. 134, pt. 30, 14 March 1988, S2129. 70. Harold Daub (R-NE), CR v. 131, pt. 18 (100C/1S), 19 September 1985, 24270. 71. Jack Brooks (D-TX), CR v. 136, pt. 127 (101C/2S), 3 October 1990, H8717. 72. U.S. Immigration Policy and the National Interest 4, 20. 73. Theodore Hesburgh (president, Select Commission on Immigration and Refugee Policy), CR v. 127, pt. 7 (97C/1S), 13 May 1981, 9535. 74. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 127, pt. 24 (97C/1S), 16 December 1981, 32234. 75. Robin Beard (R-TN), CR v. 127, pt. 4 (97C/1S), 24 March 1981, 5115. 76. Jennings Randolph (D-WV), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20845. 77. Robert Garcia (D-NY), CR v. 128, pt. 23 (97C/2S), 16 December 1982, 31808. 78. Jesse Helms (R-NC), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20858. 79. Alan Simpson (R-WY), CR v. 136, pt. 136 (101C/2S), 12 October 1990, S15037. 80. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 127, pt. 24 (97C/1S), 16 December 1981, 32234. 81. Alan Simpson (R-WY), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20827.
330
Notes to Pages 209–15
82. Alan Simpson (R-WY), CR v. 134, pt. 31, 15 March 1988, S2212. 83. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 126, pt. 12 (96C/2S), 18 June 1980, 15278. 84. Eldon Rudd (R-AZ), CR v. 128, pt. 23 (97C/2S), 16 December 1982, 31791. 85. Lawton Chiles (D-FL), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20843. 86. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 126, pt. 25 (96C/2S), 12 December 1980, 33868. 87. Lloyd Bentsen (D-TX), CR v. 128, pt. 16 (97C/2S), 17 August 1982, 21669. 88. Eldon Rudd (R-AZ), CR v. 130, pt. 11 (98C/2S), 11 June 1984, 15744. 89. George Gekas (R-PA), CR v. 131, pt. 18 (98C/2S), 19 September 1985, 24268. 90. Romano Mazzoli (D-KY), CR v. 132, pt. 21 (99C/2S), 9 October 1986, 29988. 91. James Scheuer (D-NY), CR v. 132, pt. 21 (99C/2S), 9 October 1986, 30054. 92. Although some, including the INS, prefer “undocumented” I use “illegal” because it is colloquial and more readily understandable. 93. Daniel (Bob) Graham (D-FL), CR v. 133, pt. 11 (100C/1S), 4 June 1987, 14638. 94. Mack Mattingly (R-GA), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20846. 95. Alan Simpson (R-WY), CR v. 134, pt. 30, 14 March 1988, S2121. 96. Richard Shelby (D-AL), CR v. 135, pt. 92, 12 July 1989, S7751. 97. Howard Berman (D-CA), CR v. 130, pt. 7 (98C/2S), 11 April 1984, 9056. 98. Daniel Glickman (D-KS), CR v. 130, pt. 12 (98C/2S), 11 June 1984, 17037. 99. Daniel Glickman (D-KS), CR v. 130, pt. 13 (98C/2S), 20 June 1984, 17247. 100. James McNulty (D-AZ), CR v. 130, pt. 13 (98C/2S), 20 June 1984, 17250. 101. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 128, pt. 23 (97C/2S), 16 December 1982, 31785. 102. Lane Kirkland (individual), CR v. 129, pt. 4 (98C/1S), 7 March 1983, 4114. 103. Alan Simpson (R-WY), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 13 August 1982, 21052. 104. Lawton Chiles (D-FL), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20842. 105. Charles Grassley (R-IA), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20866. 106. Herman Badillo (D-NY), CR v. 123, pt. 22 (95C/1S), 5 August 1977, 27785. 107. Robert Garcia (D-NY), CR v. 127, pt. 13 (97C/1S), 23 July 1981, 17029. 108. Lane Kirkland testimony, reprinted CR v. 129, pt. 4 (98C/1S), 7 March 1983, 4115. 109. Lawrence Smith (D-FL), CR v. 132, pt. 21 (99C/2S), 9 October 1986, 29991. 110. Ron Dellums (D-CA), CR v. 130, pt. 13 (98C/2S), 20 June 1984, 17239. 111. William Frenzel (R-MN), CR v. 130, pt. 13 (98C/2S), 20 June 1984, 17290. 112. William French Smith (attorney general) letter to Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 128, pt. 22 (97C/2S), 14 December 1982, 30609.
Notes to Pages 215–19
331
113. Jesse Helms (R-NC), CR v. 128, pt. 13 (97C/2S), 22 July 1982, 17712. 114. Harold Daub (R-NE), CR v. 131, pt. 18 (100C/1S), 19 September 1985, 24271. 115. John Conyers (D-MI), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14348. 116. Frank Lautenberg (D-NJ), CR v. 135, pt. 92, 12 July 1989, S7778. 117. Richard White (D-TX), CR v. 117, pt. 27 (92C/1S), 5 October 1971, 34914. 118. Jack McDonald (R-MI), CR v. 117, pt. 33 (92C/1S), 29 November 1971, 43349. 119. Ron Packard (R-CA), CR v. 132, pt. 18 (99C/2S), 23 September 1986, 25384. 120. Such proposals became popular on several occasions. One advocate is James Buckley (R-NY), CR v. 121, pt. 26 (94C/1S), 20 October 1975, 33082; also see John Exon (D-NE), CR v. 135, pt. 93 (101C/1S), 13 July 1989, S7859. The U.S. Supreme Court, in Plyler vs. Doe (1982), found that states, in this case Texas, could not deny federally guaranteed public bene‹ts such as education to children who were illegal immigrants. 121. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 126, pt. 12 (96C/2S), 18 June 1980, 15270. 122. John Ashbrook (R-OH), CR v. 124, pt. 12 (95C/2S), 6 June 1978, 16421. 123. Robert Byrd (D-WV), CR v. 135, pt. 93 (101C/1S), 13 July 1989, S7902. 124. James (Strom) Thurmond (R-SC), CR v. 129, pt. 8 (98C/1S), 28 April 1983, 10191. 125. Harold Daub (R-NE), CR v. 130, pt. 13 (98C/2S), 20 June 1984, 17247. 126. CR v. 130, pt. 12 (98C/2S), 13 June 1984, 16278. 127. U.S. Immigration Policy and the National Interest (Washington, DC: GPO, 1982), 2. 128. Lawton Chiles (D-FL), CR v. 126, pt. 12 (96C/2S), 18 June 1980, 15284. 129. B. F. Sisk (D-CA), CR v. 124, pt. 24 (95C/2S), 2 October 1978, 33123. Parentheses in original. 130. Robert Dole (R-KS), CR v. 126, pt. 12 (96C/2S), 18 June 1980, 15287. 131. Robin Beard (R-TN), CR v. 127, pt. 4 (97C/1S), 24 March 1981, 5115. 132. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 125, pt. 18 (96C/1S), 6 September 1979, 23242. 133. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 127, pt. 12 (97C/1S), 14 July 1981, 15604–5. 134. Edward Roybal (D-CA), CR v. 128, pt. 23 (97C/2S), 17 December 1982, 32019; echoed by Republican Rudolf Boschwitz (R-MN), CR v. 134, pt. 30, 14 March 1988, S2139. 135. CR v. 136, pt. 127 (101C/2S), 3 October 1990. 136. Durward Hall (R-MO), CR v. 118, pt. 1 (92C/2S), 18 January 1972, 34–35. 137. Samuel Hayakawa (R-CA), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 13 August 1982, 21071. 138. CR v. 135, pt. 93 (101C/1S), 13 July 1989, S7862. 139. John Dow (D-NY), CR v. 114, pt. 9 (90C/2S), 30 April 1968, 11048. 140. Herman Badillo (D-NY), CR v. 120, pt. 19 (93C/2S), 23 July 1974, 24814.
332
Notes to Pages 219–27
141. Patricia Schroeder (D-CO), CR v. 132, pt. 12 (99C/2S), 22 July 1986, 17332. 142. Judith Goldstein, “Ideas, Institutions, and American Trade Policy,” International Organization 42/1 (winter 1988), 179–217. 143. Theodore Hesburgh (chair, Select Commission on Immigration and Refugee Policy), words of early May, reprinted in CR v. 127, pt. 7 (97C/1S), 13 May 1981, 9535. 144. James Holli‹eld, Immigrants, Markets and States: The Political Economy of Postwar Europe (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992). 145. John Ruggie, “International Regimes, Transactions and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order,” International Regimes, ed. Stephen D. Krasner (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983), 195–231. 146. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 116, pt. 11 (91C/2S), 5 May 1970, 14209. 147. Jack Kemp (R-NY), CR v. 121, pt. 11 (94C/1S), 14 May 1975, 14355. 148. Robert Garcia (D-NY), CR v. 127, pt. 20 (97C/1S), 10 November 1981, 27179. 149. Charles Percy (R-IL), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20878. 150. Douglas Bereuter (R-NE), CR v. 135, pt. 151 (101C/1S), 1 November 1989, H7911. 151. George Mitchell (D-ME), CR v. 130, pt. 12 (98C/2S), 12 June 1984, 15955. 152. Abraham Kazen (D-TX), CR v. 118, pt. 23 (92C/2S), 12 September 1972, 30167. 153. William Armstrong (R-CO), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 13 August 1982, 21015. 154. Patricia Schroeder (D-CO), CR v. 128, pt. 23 (97C/2S), 18 December 1982, 32151. 155. Cardiss Collins (D-IL), CR v. 130, pt. 11 (98C/2S), 11 June 1984, 15705. 156. Henry Gonzalez (D-TX), CR v. 132, pt. 21 (99C/2S), 9 October 1986, 29993. 157. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 128, pt. 10 (97C/2S), 10 June 1982. 158. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 118, pt. 13 (92C/2S), 4 May 1972, 15811. 159. Don Bonker (D-WA), CR v. 123, pt. 27 (95C/1S), 21 October 1977, 34788. 160. Don Bonker (D-WA), CR v. 125, pt. 3 (97C/1S), 11 March 1981, 4115. 161. Daniel Lungren (R-CA), CR v. 130, pt. 12 (98C/2S), 15930. 162. Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 132, pt. 22 (88C/2S), 15 October 1986, 31631. 163. Although the people granted amnesty were already on American soil, that grant was legally identical to approval to immigrate. Each person was entitled to establish legal residence in the country and to ‹le for naturalization after the statutory period had elapsed. 164. William McCollum (R-FL), CR v. 130, pt. 11 (98C/2S), 11 June 1984, 15718. 165. Theodore Hesburgh (chair, Select Commission on Immigration and Refugee Policy), quoted by Peter Rodino (D-NJ), CR v. 134, pt. 110, 28 July 1988, H6064. 166. Dale Bumpers (D-AL), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 13 August 1982, 21036.
Notes to Pages 227–36
333
167. Gary Hart (D-CO), CR v. 131, pt. 18 (100C/1S), 20 September 1985, 24503. 168. Edward Kennedy (D-MA), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20832. 169. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 128, pt. 15 (97C/2S), 12 August 1982, 20838.
Chapter 8
1. For these purposes, a major effort is de‹ned as at least four days of legislative discussion on at least one bill in each House of Congress, combined with hearings on the issue, while immigration policy is still de‹ned as the package of policies that sets out the restriction and admission criteria faced by most of the world. This discussion minimum is reasonable because any change requires this. This de‹nition also helps to exclude the hundreds of occasions when individual congresspeople introduce bills that go nowhere, which happens every session. This de‹nition also serves to exclude debate over policy toward one very small group of potential immigrants, such as Cuban, Salvadoran, or Haitian immigrants to the United States, that may be peripheral to American immigration policy. 2. Fortune Magazine (May 1938). 3. While these polls do measure American insularity and anti-Semitism, they also reveal a more complex picture of American opinion. For example, in 1939, 83 percent of Americans said that larger numbers of Germans should not come, while only (given this result) 71 percent said the same regarding Jewish exiles. The hostility toward Jews seems to have been extended in full measure to non-Jewish immigrants. This data is reported in Rita Simon, Public Opinion and the Immigrant: Print Media Coverage, 1880–1980 (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1985), 33. 4. Edwin Harwood, “American Public Opinion and Immigration Policy,” Annals (AAPSS) 487 (September 1986), 206. 5. Edwin Harwood, “American Public Opinion and Immigration Policy,” Annals (AAPSS) 487 (September 1986), 202. 6. Gallup Organization, National adult (N = 1,500) USGALLUP.43– 301.QT09, 26 August–2 September 1943. 7. Gallup Opinion Index May 1975, #119; Gallup Opinion Index September 1979 #170. 8. Gallup Political Index August 1965, #3. 9. Wayne Cornelius cites 1981 research (in Spanish) by Jorge A. Bustamante that in Cornelius’s words “places heavy emphasis on these economic indicators as determinants for public tolerance for the presence of Mexicans in U.S. labor markets.” See Cornelius, America in the Era of Limits: Migrants, Nativists, and the Future of U.S.-Mexican Relations (La Jolla: UCSC Center for U.S.-Mexican Studies, 1982), working paper II, footnote 7. 10. For example, in a regression to explain change in (the residual of) the
334
Notes to Pages 239–48
immigration ceiling divided by the U.S. population, unemployment is most signi‹cant when lagged three years: it is not statistically signi‹cant even when it is the only independent variable (p = .08) and washes out immediately when any other variables are added. 11. As with the other data presented here, correlations are with residuals, with the exception of unemployment, which has no secular trend. 12. An apprehension is “the arrest of a deportable alien by the Immigration and Naturalization Service. Each apprehension of the same alien in a ‹scal year is counted separately.” The deportable alien subject to this apprehension is “an alien in the United States subject to and of the 19 grounds of deportation speci‹ed by the Immigration and Nationality Act. This includes any alien illegally in the United States, regardless of whether the alien entered illegally or entered legally but subsequently violated the terms of his or her visa” (Statistical Yearbook of the INS 1988, 138, 139). 13. A. F. K. Organski, The $36 Billion Bargain: Strategy and Politics in U.S. Assistance to Israel (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990), 27. 14. T. H. Marshall, Class, Citizenship and Social Development: Essays (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1964).
Chapter 9
1. Trade policy dates and trade volume are here used solely as a comparison, as a measure against which to view immigration policy and immigrant volume. They are not the essay’s focus. 2. Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics (New York: Random House, 1979), 164–65. 3. Hans Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, 5th ed. rev. (New York: Knopf, 1978). 4. An immigrant is “an alien admitted to the United States as a lawful permanent resident. Immigrants are those persons lawfully accorded the privilege of residing permanently in the United States” (Statistical Yearbook of the INS 1988, 141). Immigrants may petition for citizenship. 5. Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), chap. 3; Duncan Snidal, “The Limits of Hegemonic Stability Theory,” International Organization 39/4 (autumn 1985), 579–614. 6. Discussion of this point is in John Gerard Ruggie, “Multilateralism: The Anatomy of an Institution,” International Organization 46/3 (summer 1992), 561–98. 7. Aristide R. Zolberg, “International Migration Policies in a Changing World System,” Human Migration: Patterns and Policies, ed. William H. McNeill and Ruth S. Adams (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978), 241–86. 8. This view infuses, for example, work done in regime theory. Without hegemony, states should move toward autarky, bringing about chaos. Order without
Notes to Pages 248–54
335
hegemony requires explanation. See Robert Keohane, After Hegemony, and Stephen Krasner’s preface to International Regimes (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983). 9. David Mitrany, A Working Peace System (Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1966). 10. David Mitrany, The Progress of International Government (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1933), 116, emphasis in the original. 11. David Mitrany, The Progress of International Government, 68. 12. One work, Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin’s Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and of Money (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1992), starts with the assumption that trade has become freer while immigration policies have not necessarily become so, then goes on to examine the ethical implications of continued immigration restriction. But examining these policies’ actual trends and relationships and detailing them over a long period of time are important because the central theories in international relations each contain implicit hypotheses about these relationships and trends. Realism and functionalism, for example, each deny that different border control policies are heading in different directions at all. 13. Data used to test these hypotheses are drawn from public sources and except where an alteration is explicitly indicated in the text have not been reconstructed. Sources from which the set was compiled are listed in a codebook attached to the dataset, so they are not generally cited in the text. All variables cover the years from 1890–1989 or as many of those years for which data are available or sensible. For example, the National Bureau of Economic Research constructed consistent GNP ‹gures for this whole period, but the Immigration and Naturalization Service did not always count alien border crossings, and Congress did not establish a numerical limit until 1921. The statistical picture is fairly complete, but even so, only cases (years) for which all information is available have been used. 14. Tariffs are a tricky measure because the proportion of imports subject to them depends not just on the level Congress sets but also, of course, on the volume of dutiable and nondutiable goods that people then decide to purchase. I am using tariffs levied as a proportion of dutiable goods as the best measure available, rather than the best measure, period. The main American legislative interventions into the tariff level are the McKinley tariff of 1890, Wilson-Gorman of 1894, Dingley of 1897, Payne-Aldrich of 1909, Underwood of 1913 (all in the 40 percent range), Fordney McCumber of 1922 and Smoot-Hawley of 1930 (both boosting tariffs into the 50 percent range), the Reciprocal Trade Agreements Act of 1930 and the Extension Acts of 1945 and 1948. Legislation following these are titled “trade expansion act of . . .” and lower tariffs into the GATT rounds. Prior to World War II, these legislative dates coincide with those to restrict immigration. They are within months of each other. 15. Numbers in parentheses indicate correlations between residual variables. 16. Robert Keohane and Joseph Nye distinguish between sensitivity and vulnerability in their Power and Interdependence (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977). “Sen-
336
Notes to Pages 254–68
sitivity involves degrees of responsiveness within a policy framework—how quickly do changes in one country bring costly changes in another and how great are the costly effects? . . . The vulnerability dimension of interdependence rests on the relative availability and costliness of alternatives the various actors face” (12, 13). 17. These and following uncited ‹gures are my own, calculated in the data set upon which this section is based. 18. Some relatives have been quota immigrants and some have been nonquota. Different groups of relatives have fallen into different categories at different times. 19. Relatives stayed mainly outside a numerical ceiling until the 1980s, when the large numbers of Vietnamese refugees began to petition for their relatives’ admission. Relatives were then pulled entirely under the numerical ceiling. 20. A nonimmigrant is “an alien who seeks temporary entry to the United States for a speci‹c reason. The alien must have a permanent residence abroad and qualify for the nonimmigrant classi‹cation sought. The nonimmigrant classi‹cations are: foreign government of‹cials, visitors for business and for pleasure, aliens in transit through the United States, treaty traders and investors, students, international representatives, temporary workers and trainees, representatives of foreign information media, exchange visitors, ‹ances(ees) of U.S. citizens, intracompany transferees, and NATO of‹cials” (Statistical Yearbook of the INS 1988, 143). 21. Refugees have for the most part been handled outside of regular immigration policy. They were ‹rst charged against country quotas, then accorded parole status or adjusted through special ad hoc legislation. In 1965, they received a small preference within the general policy, but by the late 1970s it became clear that the refugee problem was too unwieldy to remain a part of a policy that was revised only once a generation. In 1980, refugees were taken care of through separate legislation. 22. Before the 1960s, colonial territories were included in the allotment assigned to the metropole. During this period, colonies received a cap; in addition, only “white” or “Negro” residents were eligible. 23. Competing demographic theories of migration each rest on this central fact. See Larry Sjaastad, “The Costs and Returns of Human Migration,” Journal of Political Economy 70/5 (1962), 80–93; Julie DaVanzo, “Microeconomic Approaches to Studying Migration Decisions,” Migration Decisionmaking, ed. Gordon DeJong and Robert W. Gardner (New York: Pergamon, 1981), 90–130; Michael P. Todaro, “Internal Migration in Developing Countries,” Population and Economic Change in Developing Countries, ed. Richard A. Easterlin (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), 361–402.
Chapter 10
1. Katherine Organski and A. F. K. Organski, Population and World Power (New York: Knopf, 1961); A. F. K. Organski, Jacek Kugler, J. Timothy Johnson,
Notes to Pages 273–82
337
and Youssef Cohen, Births, Deaths, and Taxes: The Demographic and Political Transitions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984). 2. Craig Calhoun, “Nationalism and Ethnicity,” Annual Review of Sociology 19 (1993), 211–39. 3. James Mayall, Nationalism and International Society (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 27. 4. Friedrich Kratochwil, “Of Systems, Boundaries, and Territoriality.” 5. Milton C. Garber (R-OK), CR v. 65, pt. 6 (68C/1S), 5 April 1924, 5693. 6. Samuel Hobbs (D-AL), CR v. 96, pt. 8 (81C/2S), 17 July 1950, 10456. 7. James (Strom) Thurmond (R-SC), CR v. 111, pt. 18 (89C/1S), 17 September 1965, 24237. 8. George Huddleston (D-AL), CR v. 126, pt. 25 (96C/2S), 12 December 1980, 33868. 9. Dwight Eisenhower, House Document 85, CR v. 103, pt. 1 (85C/1S), 31 January 1957, 1355. 10. Stanley Lundine (D-NY), CR v. 130, pt. 12 (98C/2S), 19 June 1984, 17062. 11. The large-scale changes in the racial composition of the American population in the 1970s and 1980s had their origin in the ad hoc admission of refugees from the Indochina wars. Once they had been given permission to enter as prospective citizens, they could petition for their relatives’ entry. Since few Southeast Asians had immigrated earlier, this was the ‹rst opportunity for this “market” to be tapped; response was therefore huge. 12. Samuel Dickstein (D-NY), Study of Naturalization Laws and Procedures, Hearings before Subcommittee II of the COIN, House of Representatives (79C/1S), 9 May to 5 June 1945, 15. 13. James Holli‹eld, Immigrants, Markets, and States (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992). 14. See Kay Hailbronner, “Citizenship and Nationhood in Germany,” Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Rogers Brubaker (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1989), 67–79. 15. For discussion, see William Rogers Brubaker, “Citizenship and Naturalization: Policies and Politics,” Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1989), 106–8. 16. For overviews and discussions of immigration in the European Union, see Giuseppe Callovi, “Regulation of Immigration in 1993: Pieces of the European Community Jig-Saw Puzzle,” International Migration Review 26/2 (summer 1992), 353–72; Sarah Collinson, Beyond Borders: West European Migration Policy Towards the Twenty-‹rst Century (London: Royal Institute of International Affairs, 1993); Elizabeth Meehan, Citizenship and the European Community (London: Sage, 1993).
Bibliography
I.
Government Documents
U.S. Congress: Acts, Reports, and Summaries
United States (Congress). 1891–1990. Congressional Record. United States (Congress). 1990. The Immigration Act of 1990. United States (Congress). 1989. “The Immigration Act of 1989 (Symposium).” Congressional Digest 68 (October): 225–56. ———. (Congress). 1986. Immigration Reform and Control Act of 1986: S 1200; PL 99–603. (6 November). ———. (Congress). 1986. “Should Congress Enact Senate-Passed Immigration Reform Legislation?” Congressional Digest 65 (March): 69–96. ———. (Congress). 1983. “Should Congress Enact the Pending ‘Immigration Reform and Control Act’? (Symposium).” Congressional Digest 62 (August/September): 195–224. ———. (Select Commission on Immigration and Refugee Policy). 1980. U.S. Immigration Policy and the National Interest. Washington, DC: GPO. ———. (Congress). 1980. Refugee Act of 1980: PL 96–212; 94 Stat. 102. ———. (Senate). 1979. US Immigration Law and Policy, 1952–1979. Report at the Request of the Committee on the Judiciary for Formulation of the Select Commission on Immigration and Refugee Policy. 96th C, 1st S. ———. 1979. Naturalization Laws. Washington, DC: GPO. ———. (Congress). 1978. Act of October 5, 1978: PL 95–412; 92 Stat. 907. (Combined hemispheric quotas into worldwide quota.) ———. (Congress). 1976. Immigration and Nationality Act Amendments of 1976: PL 94–571; 90 Stat. 2703. (Extended preference system to Western Hemisphere.) ———. (House of Representatives). 1965. Amending the Immigration and Nationality Act and for Other Purposes. Report 745 (6 August). 89th C, 1st S. ———. (Senate). 1965. Amending the Immigration and Nationality Act and for Other Purposes. Report 748. (15 September) 89th C, 1st S. ———. (Congress). Immigration Act of 1965: PL 89–236; 79 Stat. 911. ———. (Congress). 1953. US President’s Commission on Immigration and Naturalization. Whom We Shall Welcome? (1 January). ———. (Congress). 1952. Immigration and Nationality Act—Message from the President of the United States. H Doc 520. (25 June). 339
340
Bibliography
———. (Congress). 1952. Immigration and Nationality Act of 1952 (McCarranWalter): PL 414; 66 Stat. 163. ———. (Senate). 1952. S 2842 (Humphrey) 82d C, 2d S, secs 201, 203. ———. (Senate). 1950. The Immigration and Naturalization Systems of the United States. S R 1515. (20 April). ———. (Congress). 1948. 62 Stat. 635. (Endanger safety.) ———. (Congress). 1947. Message from the President of the United States. H Doc 382 (7 July). ———. (Congress). 1946. 60 Stat. 416. (Philippines reallowed.) ———. (Congress). 1943. 57 Stat. 70 (29 April). ———. (Congress). 1943. 22 Stat 58. (Repeal of the Chinese Exclusion Act of 1882.) ———. (Congress). 1940. 54 Stat. 673. (Anyone ever a member.) ———. (Congress). 1924. Immigration Act of 1924: PL 139; 43 Stat. 153. (Gentleman’s Agreement: none not naturalizable allowed to immigrate.) ———. (House of Representatives). 1924. Correspondence with Executive Departments. 68th C, 1st S. (17 April). ———. (Congress). 1924. 43 Stat. 253. (Made American Indians citizens.) ———. (Congress). 1921. Quota Act of 1921: 42 Stat. 5. ———. (Congress). 1920. 41 Stat. 1008. (Subversives.) ———. (Congress). 1918. 40 Stat. 1012. (Subversives Exclusion.) ———. (Congress). 1917. Immigration Act of 1917: 39 Stat. 874. (Barred Zone, sec. 3; Bracero program, chap. 29.) ———. (Congress). 1917. Deportation of Certain Aliens. HR 127. 65th C, 1st S. (4 August). ———. (Congress). 1916. Immigration of Aliens into the United States. HR 95. (January). 64th C, 1st S. ———. (Congress). 1907. 34 Stat. 898. (Chinese Exclusion Act extended to Japanese.) ———. (Congress). 1903. 32 Stat. 1213. (Excluded anarchists.) ———. (Congress). 1902. 32 Stat. 176. (Chinese exclusion permanent.) ———. (Congress). 1892. 27 Stat. 25. (Chinese exclusion extended.) ———. (Congress). 1888. 25 Stat. 476. (Chinese reentry abrogated.) ———. (Congress). 1882. Chinese Exclusion Act of 1882: 22 Stat. 58. (6 May). (Excluded Chinese and contract laborers.) ———. (Congress). 1882. 22 Stat. 214, ch. 376. (Public charge, lunatic, idiot.) ———. (Congress). 1875. 18 Stat. 477 pt. 3. (3 March). (Convicts, prostitutes.) ———. (Congress). 1798. 1 Stat. 570. (25 June). (“Dangerous to the peace and safety of the United States.”) U.S. Congress: Hearings
———. (Senate). 1965. Subcommittee on Immigration and Naturalization, Committee on the Judiciary. Immigration: Hearings. 89th C, 1st S. (Sam Ervin on non-Europeans’ lack of contribution to the U.S.).
Bibliography
341
———. (Congress). 1952. Hearings before the President’s Commission on Immigration and Naturalization. 82d C, 2d S. ———. (Congress). 1951. Subcommittees of the Committees on the Judiciary. Revisions of Immigration, Naturalization and Nationality Laws: Joint Hearings. 82d C, 1st S. (Anti-Asian). ———. (Senate). 1945. Committee on Appropriations. Foreign Aid Appropriation Bill 1950 and 1951. ———. (House of Representatives). 1948. Subcommittee on Immigration and Naturalization of the House Committee on the Judiciary. Hearings on HR 5004. (19, 21 April; serial 18). (No sense in lists of excludables.) ———. (House of Representatives). 1946. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. To Deny Admission to the United States of Certain Aliens and to Reduce Immigration Quotas., parts 1 and 2. 79th C, 2d S. (21 February). ———. (House of Representatives). 1945. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Study of the Problems Relating to Immigration and Deportation and Other Matters, parts 1 through 6. 79th C, 1st S. (6 August). ———. (House of Representatives). 1945. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Repeal of the Chinese Exclusion Acts. 78th C, 1st S. (19 May to 3 June). ———. (House of Representatives). 1945. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. To Grant a Quota to Eastern Hemisphere Indians and to Make Them Racially Eligible for Naturalization. 79th C, 1st S. ( 7–14 March). ———. (House of Representatives). 1945. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Study of Immigration and Naturalization Laws and Procedures. 79th C, 1st S. (9 May–5 June). ———. (House of Representatives). 1945. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Study of Immigration and Naturalization Laws and Problems. 79th C, 1st S., parts 1 and 2 (24 April–2 May). ———. (Senate). 1945. Committee on Immigration. To Permit All People from India Residing in the United States to be Naturalized. 79th C, 1st S. (26 April). ———. (House of Representatives). 1943. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Repeal of the Chinese Exclusion Acts: Hearings. 78th C, 1st S. (19 May). ———. (House of Representatives). 1941. Subcommittee on Immigration and Naturalization, Committee on the Judiciary. Permitting Admission of 400,000 Displaced Persons into the United States: Hearings. 80th C, 1st S. ———. (House of Representatives). 1940. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. To Revise and Codify the Nationality Laws of the United States into a Comprehensive Nationality Code. 76th C, 1st S. (17 January–5 June). ———. (House of Representatives). 1939. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Admission of German Refugee Children. 76th C, 1st S. (24 May). ———. (House of Representatives). 1935. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Deportation of Aliens. 74th C, 1st S. (9 April). ———. (House of Representatives). 1932. Committee on Immigration and Natu-
342
Bibliography
ralization. To Exclude and Expel Alien Fascists and Communists. 74th C, 1st S. (3 April). ———. (House of Representatives). 1932. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Exclusion and Expulsion of Communists. 72st C, 1st S. (revised) (23 February–15 March). ———. (House of Representatives). 1932. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Suspension for Two Years of General Immigration Into the United States. 71st C, 3d S. (15 December). ———. (House of Representatives). 1930. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Exclusion of Immigration from the Philippine Islands. 71st C, 2d S. (10 April). ———. (House of Representatives). 1930. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Immigration from Countries of the Western Hemisphere, 71st C, 2d S. (14 March) ———. (House of Representatives). 1930. Subcommittee of Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Naturalization. 71st C, 2d S. (26 February). ———. (House of Representatives). 1930. Subcommittee of Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Proposed Amendments to the Immigration Act of 1924. 71st C, 2d S. (27 January). ———. (House of Representatives). 1930. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Quota Preferences for Certain Immigrants. 71st C, 2d S. (21 January). ———. (House of Representatives). 1930. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. National Origins Provision of Immigration Law. 70th C, 2d S. (4–13 February) ———. (House of Representatives). 1928. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Amendments to the Immigration Act of 1924. 70th C, 1st S. (27 March). ———. (Senate). 1929. Committee on Immigration. National Origins Provisions of Immigration Law. 70th C, 2d S. (4–13 February). ———. (Senate). 1928. Committee on Immigration. National Origins Provisions of Immigration Law. 70th C, 1st S. (15 March). ———. (House of Representatives). 1928. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. The Eugenical Aspects of Deportation. (21 February). ———. (House of Representatives). 1928. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Immigration from Countries of the Western Hemisphere. 70th C, 1st S. (21 February). ———. (House of Representatives). 1927. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. National Origins Provision, Immigration Act of 1924. 69th C, 2d S. (18 January). ———. (Senate). 1924. Committee on Immigration. Selective Immigration Legislation. 68th C, 1st S. (February 13). ———. (House of Representatives). 1924. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Restriction of Immigration. 68th C, 1st S. (14 January–12 February).
Bibliography
343
———. (House of Representatives). 1924. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Europe as an Emigrant-Exporting Continent and the United States as an Immigrant-Receiving Nation. 68th C, 1st S. (8 March). ———. (House of Representatives). 1922. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Analysis of America’s Modern Melting Pot. 67th C, 3d S. (21 November). ———. (House of Representatives). 1919. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Percentage Plans for Restriction of Immigration. 68th C, 1st S. (12 June–25 September). ———. (House of Representatives). 1916. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Immigration of Aliens into the United States. HR 95. 64th C, 1st S. parts 1 and 2. ———. (House of Representatives). 1916. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Restriction of Immigration. 64th C, 1st S. (20 January). ———. (House of Representatives). 1915. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Entrance of Chinese Aliens into the United States. 63d C, 3d S. (7 January). ———. (House of Representatives). 1914. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Hindu Immigration, parts 1 through 3. 63d C, 2d S. (13 February). ———. (House of Representatives). 1913. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Restriction of Immigration. 63d C, 2d S. (6 December). ———. (House of Representatives). 1912. Committee on Immigration and Naturalization. Further Restriction of Immigration. 62d C, 2d S. (2 February).
U.S. Government Departments
United States. Constitution of the United States of America. Amendment 14. (A. 1, sec. 8, cl. 4) 1858. ———. (Department of Justice). Administrative Decisions under Immigration and Nationality Laws. Washington, DC: GPO. ———. (Department of Justice, Immigration and Naturalization Service). (Periodical). Statistical Yearbook of the Immigration and Naturalization Service and Annual Report. Washington, DC: Department of Justice. Previously INS Annual Report, and Bureau of Immigration Annual Report. ———. Commission for the Study of International Migration and Cooperative Economic Development 1987–1990. Unauthorized Migration: Addressing the Root Causes (14 March 1989). ———. (Department of Justice, Immigration and Naturalization Service). 1987. Immigration and Naturalization Service Resource Guide for Congressional Staffs. ———. (General Accounting Of‹ce). 1988. Immigration: The Future Flow of Legal Immigration to the US. (January). ———. (General Accounting Of‹ce). 1982. Information on the Enforcement of
344
Bibliography
Laws Regarding Employment of Aliens in Selected Countries (31 August). Washington, DC: GPO. ———. (Select Commission on Immigration and Refugee Policy). US Immigration Policy and the National Interest (30 April). ———. (Commission on Civil Rights). 1980. The Tarnished Door: Civil Rights Issues in Immigration. Washington, DC: GPO. ———. (National Security Council). 1953. Psychological Value of Escapees from the Soviet Orbit. Security memorandum (26 March).
U.S. Supreme Court
United States (Supreme Court). 1982. Plyler vs. Doe: 102 S Ct. 2382. (Unconstitutional to limit free education to U.S. citizens.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1952. Harisades vs. Shaughnessy: 342 US 580. (Right of exclusion from sovereignty; Congress’s right to make uniform naturalization rules.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1950. Knauff vs. Shaughnessy: 338 US 537. (Plenary exclusion.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1922. Ozawa vs. US: 260 US 178. (Japanese ineligible for naturalization.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1904. US vs. Sing Tuck: 194 US 161. (Habeas corpus dissent.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1904. Turner vs. Williams: 194 US 279. (Permissible to ban based on beliefs and opinions.) Bridges vs. Wixon: 326 US 135 (1945) concurring. ———. (Supreme Court). 1893. Fong Yue Ting vs. US: 149 US 711. ———. (Supreme Court). 1891. Nishimura Ekiu vs. US: 142 US 651. ———. (Supreme Court). 1889. Chae Chan Ping vs. US: 130 US 581. (Chinese exclusion constitutional.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1875. Henderson v. Mayor of the City of New York: 92 US 259. (Foreign commerce.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1857. Scott vs. Sandford: 19 how. (US) 393. (Dred Scott: Negroes are not citizens.) ———. (Supreme Court). 1849. Smith v. Turner: 48 US 282. (Foreign commerce.) United States Democratic Party. 1984. “Immigration: Democratic Platform 1984.” Congressional Digest 63 (October): 250+. United States Republican Party. 1984. “Immigration: Republican Platform 1984.” Congressional Digest 63 (October): 249+.
II.
Secondary Sources
Abbott, Edith, ed. 1926. Historical Aspects of the Immigration Problem: Select Documents. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bibliography
345
———. 1924. Immigration: Select Documents and Case Records. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Abbott, Grace. 1917. “The Immigrant and American Internationalism.” In The Immigrant and the Community, 267–81. New York: Century. Abrams, Elliott. 1983. “Diluting Compassion.” New York Times (5 August): 23. Abrams, Elliott, and Franklin S. Abrams. 1975. “Immigration Policy—Who Gets In and Why?” Public Interest 38:3–29. Abrams, Franklin S. 1984. “American Immigration Policy: How Strait the Gate?” U.S. Immigration Policy, ed. Richard R. Hofstetter. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Originally in Law and Contemporary Problems 45 (spring 1982): 115–23. Adler, Cyrun, and Aaron Margalith. 1943. American Intercession on Behalf of Jews in the Diplomatic Correspondence of the United States, 1840–1938. New York: American Jewish Historical Society. Agamben, Giorgio. 1998. Homo Sacer. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Ainsworth, Robert G. 1986. Illegal Immigrants and Refugees—Their Economic Adaptation and Impact on Local U.S. Labor Markets: A Review of the Literature. Washington, DC: National Commission for Employment Policy (October). Aleinikoff, T. Alexander. 1989. “Federal Regulation of Aliens and the Constitution.” American Journal of International Law 83 (October): 862–71. ———. 1986. “Theories of Loss of Citizenship.” Michigan Law Review 84:1471. Allen, James P., and Eugene J. Turner. 1988. “Where to Find the New Immigrants.” American Demographics (September): 22–27, 59–60. Alonso, William. 1987. “Identity and Population.” In Population in an Interacting World, ed. William Alonso, 95–125. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Amnesty International. 1986. The Imprisonment of Persons Seeking to Leave a Country or Return to Their Own Country. London: Amnesty International. Anderson, Benedict. 1992. Imagined Communities. 2d ed. London: Verso. Anderson, Perry. 1979. Lineages of the Absolutist State. London: Verso. Anker, Deborah. 1984. “The Development of U.S. Refugee Legislation.” Immigration and Refugee Policy [In Defense of the Alien, V. VI], ed. Lydio Tomasi. New York: Center for Migration Studies. Appleman, I. 1966. “That New Immigration Act: Changes That Were Made in the Nation’s Immigration Policy by the Passage Last Year of a New Immigration and Nationality Act.” American Bar Association Journal 52 (August): 717–22. Arrow, Kenneth J. 1963. Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: Wiley. Auerbach, Carl A. 1978. “Freedom of Movement in International Law and United States Policy.” In Human Migration: Patterns and Policies, ed. William H. McNeill and Ruth S. Adams, 317–35. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Auerbach, Frank L., and Elizabeth J. Harper. 1973. Immigration Laws of the United States: A Textbook, 2d ed. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. Axelrod, Bernard. 1972. “Historical Studies of Emigration from the United States.” International Migration Review 6/1 (spring): 32–49. Bach, Robert L. 1986. “Immigration: Issues of Ethnicity, Class, and Public Policy in the United States.” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May): 139–52.
346
Bibliography
———. 1985. “Political Frameworks for International Migration.” In The Americas in the New International Division of Labor, ed. Steven E. Sanderson. New York: Holmes and Meier. ———. 1978. “Mexican Immigration and the American State.” International Migration Review 12 (winter): 536–58. Baldwin, Robert. 1982. “The Political Economy of Protectionism.” In Import Competition and Response, ed. Jagdish Bhagwati, 263–92. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Baras, Victor, and Milton Himmelfarb, eds. 1978. Zero Population Growth—For Whom? Westport, CT: Greenwood. Barnet, Richard J., and Ronald E. Muller. 1974. Global Reach. New York: Simon and Schuster. Barry, Brian. 1992. “The Quest for Consistency: A Sceptical View.” In Free Movement, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin, 279–87. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster. ———. 1983. “Self Government Revisited.” In The Nature of Political Theory, ed. David Miller and Larry Siedentop. Oxford: Clarendon. ———. 1982. “Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective.” In Ethics, Economics and the Law: Nomos XXIV, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman. New York: New York University Press. ———. 1973. The Liberal Theory of Justice. Oxford: Clarendon. ———. 1965. Political Argument. New York: Humanities Press. ———. 1962. “The Public Interest.” In The Public Interest, ed. Carl J. Friedrich. New York: Atherton. Barry, Brian, and Robert E. Goodin, eds. 1992. Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and of Money. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster. ———. 1988. “Symposium on Duties Beyond Borders.” Ethics 98:647–756. Barth, Fredrik, ed. 1969. Ethnic Groups and Boundaries. Boston: Little, Brown. Bauer, Raymond, Ithiel de Sola Pool, and Lewis Dexter. 1972. American Business and Public Policy. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton. Bayles, Michael D. 1980. Morality and Population Policy. Montgomery: University of Alabama Press. ———, ed. 1976. Ethics and Population. Cambridge: Schenkman. Bean, Frank D., and Teresa S. Sullivan. 1985. “Immigration and Its Consequences: Confronting the Problem.” Society 22 (May/June): 67–73. Bean, Frank D., Georges Vernez, and Charles B. Keely. 1989. Opening and Closing the Doors: Evaluating Immigration Reform and Control. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for The Rand Corporation and Urban Institute. Becker, Gary S. 1990. “Opening the Golden Door Wider—To Newcomers with Knowhow.” Business Week (11 June): 12. ———. 1958. “Competition and Democracy.” Journal of Law and Economics 1:105–9. Beijer, Gunther. 1981. “The Political Refugee: 35 Years Later.” International Migration Review 15 (spring/summer): 26–34.
Bibliography
347
Beitz, Charles. 1983. “Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment.” Journal of Philosophy 80. ———. 1979. “Bounded Morality: Justice and the State in World Politics.” International Organization 33/3. ———. 1979. Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Beitz, Charles, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Scanlon, and A. John Simmons, eds. 1985. International Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Bendix, Reinhard. 1964. Nation-Building and Citizenship: Studies of Our Changing Social Order. New York: Wiley. Bennett, David H. 1988. The Party of Fear: From Nativist Movements to the New Right in American History. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Bennett, Marion T. 1966. “The Immigration and Nationality Act of 1952, as Amended to 1965.” Annals (AAPSS) 367 (September): 127–36. ———. 1963. American Immigration Policies: A History. Washington, DC: Public Affairs Press. Bernard, William, ed. 1950. American Immigration Policy—A Reappraisal. New York: Harper. Berry, Jeffrey M. 1989. The Interest Group Society, 2d ed. Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman. Biersteker, Thomas, and Cynthia Weber, eds. State Sovereignty as Social Construct. New York: Cambridge University Press. Billington, Ray A. 1974. The Origins of Nativism in the United States, 1800–1844. New York: Arno. Biskupic, Joan. 1990. “Sweeping Changes Abroad Confound US Policy.” Congressional Quarterly Weekly Report 48 (24 February): 592–96. ———. 1990. “Social Policy: Law/Judiciary: Sizable Boost in Immigration OK’d in Compromise Bill.” Congressional Quarterly Weekly Report (27 October): 3608–9. Bodin, Jean. [1606] 1962. The Six Bookes of the Commonweale, ed. Kenneth D. McRae. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Body-Gendrot, Sophie, and Martin A. Schain. 1992. “National and Local Politics and the Development of Immigration Policy in the United States.” In Immigrants in Two Democracies: French and American Experience, ed. Donald L. Horowitz and Gerard Noiriel, 411–38. New York: New York University Press. Bohman, James. 1991. New Philosophy of Social Science: Problems of Indeterminacy. Cambridge: MIT Press. Bohning, Wolf R. 1984. Studies in International Labour Migration. London: Macmillan. ———. 1979. “International Migration and the International Economic Order.” Journal of International Affairs 2:182–200. Borjas, George J. 1990. Friends or Strangers: The Impact of Immigrants on the US Economy. New York: Basic Books.
348
Bibliography
———. 1987. “Self-Selection and the Earnings of Immigrants.” American Economic Review 77 (September): 531–53. Borjas, George J., and Marta Tienda. 1987. “The Economic Consequences of Immigration.” Science 235 (6 February): 645–51. Bouscaren, Anthony T. 1963. International Migrations since 1945. New York: Praeger. ———. 1959. The Security Aspects of Immigration Work. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Bouvier, Leon F. 1992. Peaceful Invasions: Immigration and Changing America. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for the Center for Migration Studies. Bouvier, Leon F., and Robert W. Gardner. 1986. Immigration to the US: The Un‹nished Story. Population Bulletin No. 41 (November). Brierly, J. L. 1928. The Law of Nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Briggs, Vernon M., Jr. 1991. “Immigration Policy: Political or Economic?” Challenge 34 (September/October): 12–19. ———. 1986. “The ‘Albatross’ of Immigration Reform: Temporary Worker Policy in the United States.” International Migration Review 20 (winter): 995–1019. ———. 1984. Immigration Policy and the American Labor Force. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. ———. 1983. “Nonimmigrant Labor Policy in the United States.” Journal of Economic Issues 17 (September): 609–30. ———. 1975. “Mexican Workers in the United States Labor Market: A Contemporary Dilemma.” International Labor Review 112 (November): 351–68. Brimelow, Peter. 1995. Alien Nation: Common Sense about America’s Immigration Disaster. New York: Random House. Brod, Harry. 1992. Hegel’s Philosophy of Politics. Boulder: Westview. Brody, David. 1956. “American Jewry, the Refugees, and Immigration Restriction.” Publications of the American Jewish Historical Society 45:219–47. Brown, Lester. 1972. World Without Borders. New York: Random House. Brown, Peter G., and Henry Shue, eds. 1983. The Border That Joins: Mexican Migrants and US Responsibility. Totowa, NJ: Rowman, Little‹eld. ———. 1981. Boundaries: National Autonomy and Its Limits. Totowa, NJ: Rowman Little‹eld. Brownlie, Ian. 1983. Basic Documents in International Law. 3d ed. Oxford: Clarendon. ———. 1979. Principles of Public International Law. 3d ed. New York: Oxford University Press. Brubaker, William Rogers. 1992. Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1989. “Introduction”; “Citizenship and Naturalization: Policies and Politics”; “Membership without Citizenship: The Economic and Social Rights of Noncitizens.” In Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and
Bibliography
349
North America, ed. William Rogers Brubaker, 1–27, 99–127, 145–62. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for the German Marshall Fund. Bruce, John Campbell. 1954. The Golden Door: The Irony of Our Immigration Policy. New York: Random House. Bull, Hedley. 1987. “Population and the Present World Structure.” In Population in an Interacting World, ed. William Alonso, 74–94. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1977. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics. New York: Columbia University Press. Bundy, McGeorge. 1984. “The United States Government and the Population Problem Abroad.” Population and Development Review 10/3 (September): 505–10. Burch, Guy. 1945. Population Roads to Peace or War. Washington, DC: The Population Reference Bureau. Business Week. 1989. “The New America/Demographics: The Last Huddled Masses.” 25 September, 6. Buzan, Barry. 1991. People, States and Fear: An Agenda for International Security Studies in the Post–Cold War Era. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Cafferty, Pastora San Juan, Barry R. Chiswick, Andrew N. Greenley, and Teresa S. Sullivan. 1983. The Dilemma of American Immigration: Beyond the Golden Door. New Brunswick: Transaction. Calavita, Kitty. 1984. U.S. Immigration Law and the Control of Labor, 1820–1924. London: Academic Press. Calhoun, Craig. 1993. “Nationalism and Ethnicity.” Annual Review of Sociology 19:211–39. Callahan, Daniel. 1971. Ethics and Population Limitation. New York: Population Council. Callovi, Giuseppe. 1992. “Regulation of Immigration in 1993: Pieces of the European Community Jig-Saw Puzzle.” International Migration Review 26/2 (summer): 353–72. Cameron, David R. 1985. “Public Expenditure and Economic Performance in International Perspective.” In The Future of Welfare, ed. Rudolf Klein and Michael O’Higgins. New York: Basil Blackwell. Cannistraro, Philip V., and Gianfausto Rosoli. 1979. “Fascist Emigration Policy in the 1930s: An Interpretive Framework.” International Migration Review 13 (winter). Capassakis, Evelyn. 1981. “Passport Revocations or Denials on the Ground of National Security and Foreign Policy.” Fordham Law Review 49 (May). Carens, Joseph H. 1992. “”Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective.” In Free Movement, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin, 25–47. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster. ———. 1989. “Membership and Morality: Admission to Citizenship in Liberal Democratic Societies.” In Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Rogers Brubaker, 31–49. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for the German Marshall Fund.
350
Bibliography
———. 1988. “Nationalism and the Exclusion of Immigrants: Lessons from Australian Immigration Policy.” In Open Borders? Closed Societies? The Ethical and Political Issues, ed. Mark Gibney, 41–60. Westport, CT: Greenwood. ———. 1988. “Immigration and the Welfare State.” In Democracy and the Welfare State, ed. Amy Gutmann, 207–30. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 1987. “Who Belongs? Theoretical and Legal Questions about Birthright Citizenship in the United States.” University of Toronto Law Review 37:413–43. Review of Schuck and Smith. ———. 1987. “Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders.” Review of Politics 49 (spring): 251–73. Carey, James B. 1964. “American Labor Looks at Immigration: United States Is Offending Her Allies by Imposing Unfair Trade Restrictions.” Free Labour World (June): 19–22. Carr, Edward H. 1945. Nationalism and After. New York: Macmillan. ———. [1939] 1946. The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939. Rev. ed. New York: Macmillan. Carroll, Holbert N. 1966. The House of Representatives and Foreign Affairs. Rev. ed. Boston: Little, Brown. Casella, Alexander. 1988. “Asylum-Seekers in Europe: A Humanitarian Quandary.” World Today 44 (November): 187–91. Casinelli, C. W. 1962. “The Public Interest in Political Ethics.” In The Public Interest, ed. Carl J. Friedrich. New York: Atherton. Castells, M. 1975. “Immigrant Workers and Class Struggles in Advanced Capitalism: The Western European Experience.” Politics and Society 5/1: 33–66. Castles, Stephen. 1985. “The Guests Who Stayed—The Debate on ‘Foreigners Policy’ in the German Federal Republic.” International Migration Review 19/3 (fall): 517–34. Castles, Stephen, and Godula Kosack. 1985. Immigrant Workers and Class Structure in Western Europe. 2d ed. London: Oxford University Press. Chanda, Nayan. 1988. “Immigration Lottery.” Far Eastern Economic Review 139 (31 March): 36. Chaney, Elsa. 1981. “Migrant Workers and National Boundaries: The Basis for Rights and Protections.” In Boundaries: National Autonomy and Its Limits, ed. Peter Brown and Henry Shue, 37–77. Totowa, NJ: Rowman Little‹eld. Chiswick, Barry R. 1988. “Legal Aliens: Toward a Positive Immigration Policy.” Regulation 12:17–22. ———. 1982. The Gateway: US Immigration Issues and Policies. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute. Cigler, Allan J., and Burdett A. Loomis. 1990. Interest Group Politics. 3d ed. Washington, DC: Congressional Quarterly. Claude, Inis L., Jr. 1971. Swords into Ploughshares: The Problems and Progress of International Organization. 4th ed. New York: Random House. Cockroft, James. 1986. Outlaws in the Promised Land: Mexican Immigrant Workers and America’s Future. New York: Grove Press.
Bibliography
351
Cohen, Bernard C. 1973. The Public’s Impact on Foreign Policy. Boston: Little, Brown. Cohen, Marshall. 1984. “Moral Skepticism and International Relations.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 13:299–346. Cohodas, Nadine. 1989. “Social Policy: Immigration: New Drive Begun to Revise Visa-Allotment System.” Congressional Quarterly Weekly Report (4 March): 446–49. Collinson, Sarah. 1993. Beyond Borders: West European Migration Policy Towards the Twenty-‹rst Century. London: Royal Institute of International Affairs. Compton, Karl T. 1946. “If the Atomic Bomb Had Not Been Used.” Atlantic Monthly 178 (December): 54–56. Congressional Digest. 1977. “Controversy in Congress over Proposed Amnesty for Illegal Aliens.” October. 56. ———. 1975. “Controversy over Proposals to Reduce the Number of Illegal Aliens in the U.S.” January. 54. Congressional Quarterly. 1990. The Presidents and the Public. Washington, DC: Congressional Quarterly. Congressional Quarterly Weekly Report. 1965. “President Signs Immigration Bill into Law.” (8 October): 2036–44. ———. 1965. “Administration Will Push Revision of Immigration Law.” (8 January): 45–48. ———. 1963. “Changes in Immigration Quotas Possible in 1963.” (22 March): 422–23. ———. 1960. “Immigration Quota Changes under Eisenhower Proposal.” (25 March): 469. Cook, James. 1990. “The More the Merrier: Interview with Julian Simon.” Forbes (11 June): 77–81. Cordtz, Dan. 1965. “Immigration Reform Bill’s Smooth Passage Re›ects New Composition in Congress.” Wall Street Journal 166 (4 October): 16. Cornelius, Wayne A. 1982. America in the Era of Limits: Migrants, Nativists, and the Future of US–Mexican Relations. La Jolla, CA: UCSD Center for U.S.Mexican Studies. Cornelius, Wayne A., and R. Anzaldue Montoya, eds. 1983. America’s New Immigration Law: Origins, Rationales, and Political Consequences. La Jolla, CA: UCSD Center for U.S.-Mexican Studies. Cox, Robert W. 1984. “Social Forces, States, and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory.” In Culture, Ideology, and World Order, ed. R. B. J. Walker, 258–99. Boulder: Westview. Craig, Richard B. 1971. The Bracero Program: Interest Groups and Foreign Policy. Austin: University of Texas Press. Cranston, Maurice. 1976. “The Political and Philosophical Aspects of the Right to Leave and to Return.” In The Right to Leave and to Return, ed. Karel Vasak and Sidney Liskofsky, 21–35. New York: American Jewish Commission. Crovitz, L. Gordon. 1990. “Come One, Come All: The Economics of Immigration Compels a Change in US Policy.” Barron’s 70 (26 February): 9.
352
Bibliography
Curran, Thomas J. 1975. Xenophobia and Immigration, 1820–1930. Boston: Twayne. Dagger, Richard. 1986. “Politics and the Pursuit of Autonomy.” In Justi‹cation, ed. J. Roland Pennock. New York: New York University Press. DaVanzo, Julie. 1981. “Microeconomic Approaches to Studying Migration Decisions.” In Migration Decisionmaking, ed. Gordon DeJong and Robert W. Gardner, 90–130. New York: Pergamon. Davis, Kingley. 1958. “Population and World Power.” Population and World Politics, ed. Philip M. Hauser. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Detter de Lupis, Ingrid. 1982. International Law and the Independent State. 2d ed. Brook‹eld, VT: Gower. Dinnerstein, Leonard, and David M. Reimers. 1988. Ethnic Americans: A History of Immigration and Assimilation. 3d ed. New York: Harper and Row. DiSipio, Louis. 1987. “Social Science Literature and the Naturalization Process.” International Migration Review 21/2 (summer): 390–405. Divine, Robert A. 1957. American Immigration Policy, 1924–1952. New Haven: Yale University Press. Dixon, David. 1983. “Thatcher’s People: The British Nationality Act of 1981.” Journal of Law and Society 10/2: 161–80. Dominguez, Jorge I. 1990. “Immigration as Foreign Policy in U.S.-Latin American Relations.” In Immigration and Foreign Policy, eds. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 150–66. Boulder: Westview. Donges, Jurgen B. 1987. “International Migration and the International Division of Labor.” In Population in an Interacting World, ed. William Alonso, 129–48. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Donner, Ruth. 1983. The Regulation of Nationality in International Law. Helsinki: Finnish Society of Sciences and Letters. Doppelt, Gerald. 1978. “Walzer’s Theory of Morality in International Relations.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 8:3–25. ———. 1975. “Statism without Foundations.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 9:398–403. Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row. Dowty, Alan. 1987. Closed Borders: The Contemporary Assault on Freedom of Movement. New Haven: Yale University Press. Dreifus, Claudia. 1987. “No Refugees Need Apply.” Atlantic (February): 32–35. Dummett, Ann. 1976. Citizenship and Nationality. London: Runnymeade Trust. Dummett, Ann, and Andrew Nichols. 1990. Subjects, Citizens, Aliens and Others: Nationality and Immigration Law. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Dunlevy, James A., and Henry A. Gemery. 1978. “Economic Opportunity and the Response of ‘Old’ and ‘New’ Immigrants.” Journal of Economic History 38/4: 901–17. Duster, Troy. 1988. “Social Implication of the ‘New’ Black Underclass.” Black Scholar (May/June): 2–9.
Bibliography
353
Duvachek, Ivo. 1988. The Territorial Dimension of World Politics—Within, Among, and Across Nations. Boulder: Westview. Dyck, Arthur. 1971. “Population Policies and Ethical Acceptability.” In Rapid Population Growth: Consequences and Policy Implications, V. II, 618–38. National Academy of Sciences. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Ebert-Miner, Allan. 1985. “The INS and the Law: Enforcement or Violation?” Christianity and Crisis 45 (27 May): 205–8. Economic Council Letter. 1960. “Are the Communists Shaping Our Immigration Policy?” 15 January, 1–4. The Economist. 1991. “France: Race for Votes, Votes for Race.” 28 September. 320:57–59. ———. 1989. “East German Refugees: Not So Fast.” 9 September. 312:56. ———. 1989. “West Germany: The New Yuppies.” 23 September. 312:62+. ———. 1989. “The Gradually Disappearing Republic: Alias East Germany.” 16 September. 312:12–13. ———. 1989. “A Different Sort of Frontier Crossing.” 12 August. 312:40–41. ———. 1989. “A Way Round the Wall.” 29 July. 312:42. ———. 1989. “Immigration: Skills, Please.” 22 July. 312:23. ———. 1988. “Wilkommen, Sort of.” 10 September. 308:54+. ———. 1988. “Huddled Masses, If They’re Useful.” 19 March. 306:31. ———. 1987. “Immigration: A Flood to a Trickle.” 21 March. 302:22+. ———. 1987. “New Rules for a Human Tide.” 17 January. 302:29. ———. 1986. “Fairer Entry for Free Thinkers.” 15 February. 298:28. ———. 1986. “The Nine Lives of Immigration Reform.” 18 October. 301:31–32. Ehrlich, Paul, et al. 1979. The Golden Door: International Migration, Mexico and the United States. New York: Ballantine. Ellis, L. Ethan. 1968. Republican Foreign Policy, 1921–1933. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press. Elster, Jon. “Causal Explanation.” In Explaining Technical Change: A Case Study in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Cambridge University Press. Espenshade, Thomas J., and William J. Serow, eds. 1978. Economic Consequences of Slowing Population Growth. New York: Academic Press. European Community. 1980. European Agreement on a Transfer of Responsibility for Refugees. FAIR. (Federation for American Immigration Reform). 1988. Immigration Report. July. Fairchild, Henry Pratt. 1949. “Public Opinion and Immigration.” Annals (AAPSS) 262 (March): 185–92. ———. [1913] Rev. ed. 1925. Immigration: A World Movement and Its American Signi‹cance. New York: Macmillan. Fallows, James. 1989. More Like Us. Boston: Houghton Mif›in. Fauchille, Paul. 1924. “The Rights of Emigration and Immigration.” International Labour Review 9 (March). Faurioli, Georges. 1984. “US Immigration Policy and the National Interest.” Humanist 44 (May–June): 5–14+.
354
Bibliography
Federal Republic of Germany/Federal Ministry of the Interior. 1985. Record of Policy and Laws Related to Foreigners in the Federal Republic of Germany. Bonn: GPO. The Federalist. 1921. New York: Scribner’s Sons. Feliciano, Florentino. 1983. International Humanitarian Law and Coerced Movement of Peoples across State Boundaries. San Remo: International Institute of Humanitarian Law. Ferguson, Yale H. 1989. The State, Conceptual Chaos, and the Future of International Relations Theory. Boulder: Westview. Ferris, Elizabeth G., ed. 1987. Central American Refugees and the Politics of Protection. New York: Praeger. ———. 1985. Refugees in World Politics. New York: Praeger. Fishkin, James S. 1983. “The Boundaries of Justice.” Journal of Con›ict Resolution 27/2: 356–58. Fogel, Walter A. 1979. “The Moral Dimensions of a Temporary Worker Program.” Center Magazine (September/October). Fourlanos, Gerassimos. 1986. Sovereignty and the Ingress of Aliens: With Special Focus on Family Union and Refugee Law. Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell International. Fragomen, Austin T., Jr. 1979. “Alien Employment.” International Migration Review 13/3: 527–31. ———. 1975. “Permanent Resident Status Rede‹ned.” International Migration Review 9/1: 63–68. Francese, Peter. 1990. “Aging America Needs Foreign Blood.” Wall Street Journal (27 March): 4. Francis, Samuel T. 1986. Illegal Immigration—A Threat to US Security. London: Centre for Security and Con›ict Studies/Institute for the Study of Con›ict. No. 192. Franklin, Frank George. 1906. The Legislative History of Naturalization in the United States: From the Revolutionary War to 1861. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Freeman, Gary P. 1986. “Migration and the Political Economy of the Welfare State.” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May): 51–63. ———. 1979. Immigrant Labor and Racial Con›ict in Industrial Societies: The French and British Experience, 1945–1975. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Frieden, Jeff. 1988. “Sectoral Con›ict and Foreign Economic Policy, 1914–1940.” International Organization 42/1 (winter): 59–90. Friedman, C. Robert. 1984. “The Law of Return: Ethnic Division in Israel.” Antioch Review 42 (winter): 47–59. Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ———. 1953. “The Methodology of Positive Economics.” In Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Fuchs, Lawrence H. 1992. “Thinking about Immigration and Ethnicity in the
Bibliography
355
United States.” In Immigrants in Two Democracies: French and American Experience, ed. Donald L. Horowitz and Gerard Noiriel, 39–65. New York: New York University Press. ———. 1990. “The Blood of All Nations: The Triumph of Inclusivity in Immigration Policy.” Ethnicity and Public Policy 7. ———. 1984. “Cultural Pluralism and the Future of American Unity: The Impact of Illegal Aliens.” International Migration Review 18 (fall): 800–813. ———. 1982. “US Immigration Policy and the National Interest.” In US Immigration Today [In Defense of the Alien, V. IV.], ed. Lydio F. Tomasi et al., 1–9. Staten Island: Center for Migration Studies. Gaddis, John Lewis. 1992. “International Relations Theory and the End of the Cold War.” International Security 17 (winter): 5–58. Gainer, Bernard. 1972. The Alien Invasion: The Origins of the Aliens Act of 1905. New York: Crane, Russak. Gallaway, Lowell E., et al. 1974. “The Distribution of the Immigrant Population in the United States: An Economic Analysis.” Explorations in Economic History 11/3: 213–26. Gallup Opinion Index, various issues. Gardner, Richard N. 1965. “The Politics of Population: A Blueprint for International Cooperation.” In The Population Crisis: Implications and Plans for Action, ed. Larry K.Y. Ng, 285–97. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Geddes, Barbara. 1991. Paradigms and Sand Castles in the Comparative Politics of Developing Areas. Chicago: Northwestern University Press. Gellner, Ernest. 1983. Nations and Nationalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Gibney, Mark, ed. 1988. Open Borders? Closed Societies? The Ethical and Political Issues. New York: Greenwood. ———. 1988. “Who Is Our Favorite Refugee Today?” Human Rights 15 (summer): 30–33+. ———. 1988. “A ‘Well-Founded Fear’ of Persecution.” Human Rights Quarterly 10 (February): 109–21. ———. 1987. “Give Me Your Huddled Anticommunists.” Christianity and Crisis 47 (August 3): 256. ———. 1986. Strangers or Friends: Principles for a New Alien Admission Policy. Westport, CT: Greenwood. Glazer, Nathan, ed. 1990. “New Rules of the Game.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 15–25. Boulder: Westview. ———, ed. 1985. Clamor at the Gates: The New American Immigration. San Francisco: ICS Press. ———. 1983. Ethnic Dilemmas, 1964–1982. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1975. Ethnicity: Theory and Experience. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Glazier, Ira A., and Luigi DeRosa, eds. 1986. Migration across Time and Nations: Population Mobility in Historical Contexts. New York: Holmes and Meier.
356
Bibliography
Goldstein, Judith. 1988. “Ideas, Institutions, and American Trade Policy.” International Organization 42/1 (winter): 179–217. Goldstein, Judith, and Robert O. Keohane, eds. Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, 235–64. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Goodin, Robert E. 1992. “If People Were Money . . .” In Free Movement, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin, 6–22. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster. ———. 1992. “Commentary: The Political Realism of Free Movement.” In Free Movement, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin, 248–64. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster. ———. 1988. “What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?” Ethics 98:663–86. ———. 1982. Political Theory and Public Policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Goodwin-Gill, Guy. 1986. “International Law and the Detention of Refugees and Asylum-Seekers.” International Migration Review 20/2 (summer): 193–219. ———. 1983. The Refugee in International Law. New York: Oxford University Press. ———. 1978. International Law and the Movement of Persons. Oxford: Clarendon. Gordenker, Leon. 1987. Refugees in International Politics. New York: Columbia University Press. ———. 1983. “The International Setting of American Refugee Policy.” In The Unavoidable Issue: US Immigration Policy in the 1980s, ed. D. G. Papademetriou and Mark J. Miller, 251–70. Philadelphia: Institute for the Study of Human Issues. Gordon, Charles. 1982. Immigration and Nationality Law. New York: Bender. Gordon, C. 1966. “Hardships under the Immigration Laws.” Annals (AAPSS) 367 (September): 85–92. ———. 1947. “Racial Limitations in Immigration and Naturalization Laws.” Foreign Policy Reports 23 (April): 20 ff. Gordon, Milton. 1964. Assimilation and American Life. New York: Oxford University Press. Gordon, Robert J., ed. 1986. The American Business Cycle: Continuity and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press for the NBER. Gourevitch, Peter. 1978. “The Second Image Reversed.” International Organization 32 (autumn): 881–912. Graham, Otis, Jr. 1988. “Immigration and the National Interest.” In US Immigration Reform in the 1980s: Reappraisal and Reform, ed. David E. Simcox, 124–36. Boulder: Westview. Grant, Doug, et al., eds. 1979. Refugees: A World Report. New York: Facts on File. Grant, Madison. 1916. The Passing of the Great Race. New York: Scribner’s. Greenberger, Robert S. 1989. “Now That Soviet Jews Are Freer to Emigrate, US Is Less Hospitable.” Wall Street Journal (June 23): 1.
Bibliography
357
Guehenno, Jean-Marie. 1993. The End of the Nation-State. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Haas, Ernst B. 1964. Beyond the Nation-State: Functionalism and International Organization. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Hager, Wolfgang. 1982. “Protectionism and Autonomy.” International Affairs 58 (summer): 413–28. Hailbronner, Kay. 1989. “Citizenship and Nationhood in Germany.” In Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Rogers Brubaker, 67–79. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for the German Marshall Fund. Hall, Prescott F. 1906. Immigration and Its Effects upon the United States. New York: Holt. Hall, Thomas E. 1990. Business Cycles: The Nature and Causes of Economic Fluctuations. New York: Praeger. Hammar, Tomas. 1992. “Laws and Policies Regulating Population Movements: A European Perspective.” In International Migration Systems: A Global Approach, 245–66. New York: Oxford University Press. ———. 1990. Democracy and the Nation-State: Aliens, Denizens and Citizens in a World of International Migration. Brook‹eld, VT: Avebury. ———. 1989. “State, Nation, and Dual Citizenship.” In Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Rogers Brubaker, 81–95. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for the German Marshall Fund. ———. 1986. “Citizenship: Membership of a Nation and of a State.” International Migrations 24/4 (December): 735–48. ———. 1985. “Dual Citizenship and Political Integration.” International Migration Review 19/3 (fall): 438–50. ———, ed. 1985. European Immigration Policy: A Comparative Study. New York: Cambridge University Press. Handlin, Oscar. 1990. “The Nineteenth-Century Immigration.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keeley, and Linda Wrigley, 26–39. Boulder: Westview. Hannum, Hurst. 1990. Autonomy, Sovereignty, and Self-Determination: The Accommodation of Con›icting Rights. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. ———. 1985. The Right to Leave and Return in International Law and Practice. Washington, DC: The Procedural Aspects of International Law Institute. Hansen, Marcus Lee. 1964. The Immigrant in American History. Rev. ed. New York: Harper and Row. ———. 1945. The Atlantic Migration, 1607–1860. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Hardin, Garrett. 1969. “The Tragedy of the Commons.” Science 162 (13 December): 1243–48. Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking. Oxford: Clarendon. Harper, Elizabeth J. 1975. Immigration Laws of the United States: A Textbook
358
Bibliography
Integrating Statutes, Regulations, Administrative Practices, and Leading Court and Administrative Decisions. 3d ed. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. Harrison, R. J. 1978. “Neofunctionalism.” In International Organisation: A Conceptual Approach, ed. Paul Taylor and A. J. R. Groom, 253–69. New York: Nichols. Harwood, Edwin. 1986. “American Public Opinion and US Immigration Policy.” Annals (AAPSS) 487 (September): 201–12. ———. 1986. In Liberty’s Shadow: Illegal Aliens and Immigration Law Enforcement. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution. ———. 1983. “Alienation: American Attitudes toward Immigration.” Public Opinion (June/July) 6: 49–51. ———. 1983. “Can Immigration Laws be Enforced?” Public Interest (summer): 107–23. ———. 1983. “The Crisis in Immigration Policy.” Journal of Contemporary Studies 6/4 (fall): 45–59. Hathaway, J. C. 1984. “The Evolution of Refugee Status in International Law: 1920–1950.” International and Comparative Law Quarterly 33:348–80. Haward, Michael. 1976. War in European History. New York: Oxford University Press. Hayakawa, Samuel Ichiye. 1983. “On Immigration Law Reform.” Inter-American Economic Affairs 36 (spring): 85–89. Hegel, G. 1949. Philosophy of Right. Oxford: Clarendon. Heisler, Barbara S. 1985. “Sending Countries and the Politics of Emigration and Destination.” International Migration Review 19/3 (fall): 469–84. Heisler, Barbara S., and Martin O. Heisler. 1986. “Transnational Migration and the Modern Democratic State: Familiar Problems in New Form or a New Problem?” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May): 12–22. Heisler, Martin O. 1986. “Transnational Migration as a Small Window on the Diminished Autonomy of the Modern Democratic State.” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May): 153–66. Held, Virginia. 1970. The Public Interest and Individual Interests. New York: Basic Books. Helliwell, John. 1998. How Much Do National Borders Matter? Washington, DC: Brookings Institution. Hendrickson, David C. 1992. “Migration in International Law and Ethics: A Realist Perspective.” In Free Movement, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin, 213–31. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster. Herz, John. 1957. “The Rise and Demise of the Territorial State.” World Politics 9/4 (July): 473–93. Hiemenz, Ulrich, and K. W. Schatz. 1979. Trade in Place of Migration. Geneva: International Labour Organization. Higham, John. 1984. Send These to Me: Immigrants in Urban America. Rev. ed. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. ———. 1958. “Another Look at Nativism.” Catholic Historical Review 44:147–58. ———. 1958. Strangers in the Land: Patterns of American Nativism, 1860–1925. 2d ed. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Bibliography
359
Hinsley, F. H. 1986. Sovereignty. 2d ed. New York: Cambridge University Press. Hintjens, H. M. 1992. “Immigration and Citizenship Debates: Re›ections on Ten Common Themes.” International Migrations 30/1 (March). Hirschman, Albert O. 1991. The Rhetoric of Reaction: Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1981. “Exit, Voice, and the State.” In Essays in Trespassing: Economics to Politics and Beyond, 246–65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ———. 1974. “Exit, Voice and Loyalty: Further Re›ections and a Survey of Recent Contributions.” Social Science Information 8 (February). ———. 1970. Exit, Voice and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Hobsbawm, Eric J. 1990. Nations and Nationalism since 1780. New York: Cambridge University Press. Hoffman, Abraham. 1975. Unwanted Mexican Americans in the Great Depression: Repatriation Pressures, 1929–1939. Tucson: University of Arizona Press. Hoffmann, Stanley. 1981. Duties beyond Borders. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press. Hofstadter, Richard. 1959. Social Darwinism in American Thought. Rev. ed. Boston: Beacon Press. Hofstetter, Richard R., ed. 1984. US Immigration Policy. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. ———. 1982. “Economic Underdevelopment and the Population Explosion: Implications for US Immigration Policy.” Law and Contemporary Problems (spring). Holborn, Louise W. 1975. Refugees, A Problem of Our Time: The Work of the UN High Commissioner for Refugees, 1951–1972. Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Holden, Constance. 1988. “Debate Warming up on Legal Migration Policy.” Science (July 15). Holli‹eld, James F. 1992. Immigrants, Markets and States: The Political Economy of Postwar Europe. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1992. “Migration and International Relations: Cooperation and Control in the European Community.” International Migration Review 26/2 (summer): 568–95. ———. 1990. “Immigration and the French State: Problems of Policy Implementation.” Comparative Political Studies 23 (April): 56–79. Horowitz, Donald L. 1992. “Immigration and Group Relations in France and America.” In Immigrants in Two Democracies: French and American Experience, ed. Donald L. Horowitz and Gerard Noiriel. New York: New York University Press. Horowitz, Donald L., and Gerard Noiriel, eds. 1992. Immigrants in Two Democracies: French and American Experience. New York: New York University Press. Hoyt, Edward. 1952. “Naturalization under the American Colonies: Signs of a New Community.” Political Science Quarterly 677 (June): 248–66. Hull, Elizabeth. 1985. Without Justice for All: The Constitutional Rights of Aliens. Westport, CT: Greenwood.
360
Bibliography
Humphrey, Hubert H. 1954. The Stranger at Our Gate. New York: Public Affairs Committee. Pamphlet No. 202. Huntington, Samuel P. 1973. “Transnational Organizations and World Politics.” World Politics 25 (April): 333–68. Hurd, Ian. 1999. “Legitimacy and Authority in International Politics.” International Organization 53 (spring): 379–408. Hutchinson, Edward P. 1981. Legislative History of American Immigration Policy, 1798–1965. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. ———. 1949. “Immigration Policy since World War I.” Annals (AAPSS) 262 (March): 15–21. Icduygu, Ahmet, and E. Fuat Keyman. 2000. “Globalization, Security, and Migration: The Case of Turkey.” Global Governance 6 (July–September): 383–98. Ingles, Jose D. 1963. Study of Discrimination in Respect of the Right of Everyone to Leave Any Country, Including His Own, and Return to His Country. New York: United Nations, Economic and Social Council, Commission on Human Rights, Subcommission on Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities. International Institute for Strategic Studies. 1988. The Military Balance, 1987–1988. London: International Institute for Strategic Studies. Isbister, John. 1996. The Immigration Debate. West Hartford: Kumarian. Jacobsen, Michael, and Stephanie Lawson. 1999. “Between Globalization and Localization: A Case Study of Human Rights versus State Sovereignty.” Global Governance 5 (April–June): 203–19. Jacobson, Harold K. 1984. Networks of Interdependence: International Organizations and the Global Political System. 2d ed. New York: Knopf. Jaeger, G. 1981. “Refugee Asylum—Policy and Legislative Developments.” International Migration Review 15. Jefferson, Thomas. [1787] 1955. Notes on the State of Virginia, ed. William Peden. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Jerome, Harry. 1926. Migration and Business Cycles. St Albans, VT: Messenger Press for the NBER. Johnston, H. J. M. 1972. British Emigration Policy, 1815–1830: Shovelling out Paupers. Oxford: Clarendon. Jonas, Manfred. 1990. “Immigration and US Foreign Policy: The Interwar Period.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 57–70. Boulder: Westview. ———. 1966. Isolationism in America, 1935–1941. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Jones, Maldwyn Allen. 1960. American Immigration. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kalven, Jamie. 1987. “US Visa Policy: The Machinery of Exclusion.” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists 43 (May): 21–30. Kansas, Sidney. 1927. U.S. Immigration: Exclusion and Deportation. Washington, DC: Washington Publishing Company. Kant, Immanuel. 1963. “Third De‹nitive Article for a Perpetual Peace.” In On History, ed. Lewis White Beck. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Bibliography
361
Katzenstein, Peter J., ed. 1978. Between Power and Plenty: Foreign Economic Policies of Advanced Industrial States. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Keely, Charles B. 1990. “Immigration in the Interwar Period.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 43–56. Boulder: Westview. ———. 1979. US Immigration: A Policy Analysis. New York: Population Council. ———. 1974. “Immigration Composition and Population Policy.” Science 185:587–93. ———. 1971. “Effects of the Immigration Act of 1965 on Selected Population Characteristics of Immigrants to the United States.” Demography 8:157–69. Kendrick, John W. 1961. Productivity Trends in the United States. Princeton: Princeton University Press for the NBER. Kennedy, Edward. 1966. “The Immigration Act of 1965.” Annals (AAPSS) 367 (September): 137–49. Kennedy, John F.; rev. Robert Kennedy. 1964. A Nation of Immigrants. New York: Harper. Keohane, Robert O. 1984. After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Keohane, Robert O., and Joseph S. Nye. 1977. Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition. Boston: Little, Brown. Kettner, James. 1978. The Development of American Citizenship, 1608–1870. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Key‹tz, Nathan. 1971. “Migration as a Means of Population Control.” Population Studies 25:63–72. Kindleberger, Charles. 1973. The World in Depression, 1929–1939. Berkeley: University of California Press. ———. 1965. “Mass Migration, Then and Now.” Foreign Affairs 43/4 (July): 647–58. King, Timothy. 1983. “Immigration from Developing Countries: Some Philosophical Issues.” Ethics 93/3 (April): 525–36. Kingdon, John W. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown. Kissinger, Henry A. 1977. “The Moral Foundations of Foreign Policy.” American Foreign Policy. 3d ed. New York: Norton. Kitagawa, Joseph M., ed. 1984. American Refugee Policy: Ethical and Religious Re›ections. Minneapolis: Winston Press for the Episcopal Church. Klusmeyer, Douglas. 1996. Between Consent and Descent: Conceptions of Democratic Citizenship. Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment. Knight, Jack. 1992. Institutions and Social Con›ict. New York: Cambridge University Press. Konvitz, Milton R. [1953] 1977 reprint. Civil Rights in Immigration. Westport, CT: Greenwood. Kraft, Michael. 1984. “Political Responses to Population Stabilization and Decline in the US and Western Europe: Implications for Population Policy.” In Public Policy and Social Institutions, ed. Harrell R. Rodgers. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Kraly, Ellen P. 1990. “US Refugee Policies and Refugee Migration since World
362
Bibliography
War II.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 73–98. Boulder: Westview. Krane, R. E., ed. 1975. Manpower Mobility across Cultural Boundaries: The Case of Turkey and West Germany. Leiden: Brill. Krasner, Stephen D. 1999. Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 1993. “Westphalia and All That.” In Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, ed. Judith Goldstein and Robert O. Keohane, 235–64. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ———. 1988. “Sovereignty: An Institutional Perspective.” Comparative Political Studies 21/1 (April). ———. 1983. “Regimes and the Limits of Realism: Regimes as Autonomous Variables.” In International Regimes, ed. Stephen D. Krasner. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ———, ed. 1983. International Regimes. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Kratochwil, Friedrich. 1986. “Of Systems, Boundaries, and Territoriality.” World Politics 39 (October): 27–52. ———. 1982. “On the Notion of ‘Interest’ in International Relations.” International Organization 36/1 (winter): 1–30. Krikorkian, Mark. 1989. “Af‹rmative Action and Immigration.” Christian Science Monitor 11 (September): 2. Kritz, Mary, ed. 1983. US Immigration and Refugee Policy: Global and Domestic Issues. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. Kritz, Mary M., Charles B. Keely, and Silvano M. Tomasi, eds. 1981. Global Trends in Migration: Theory and Research on International Population Movements. Staten Island: Center for Migration Studies. Krueger, Fred. 1984. “Land of the Free, Home of the Eligible.” Christianity and Crisis 44 (July 9): 274–78. Kubat, Daniel, ed. 1979. The Politics of Migration Policies: The First World in the 1970s. Staten Island: Center for Migration Studies. Kuznets, Simon. 1973. Population, Capital and Growth: Selected Essays. London: Heinemann. ———. 1961. Capital in the American Economy: Its Formation and Financing. Princeton: Princeton University Press for the NBER. ———, and Ernest Rubin. 1954. Immigration and the Foreign Born. NBER Occasional Paper 46. Kymlicka, Will. 1995. Multicultural Citizenship. Oxford: Clarendon. ———. 1988. “Liberalism and Communitarianism.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18:181–203. Lamm, Richard D., and Gary Imhoff. 1985. The Immigration Time Bomb: The Fragmenting of America. New York: E. P. Dutton. Lansing, Paul. 1981. “Freedom to Travel: Is the Issuance of a Passport an Individual Right or a Government Prerogative?” Denver Journal of International Law and Policy 11 (fall). Layton-Henry, Zig, ed. 1991. The Political Rights of Migrant Workers in Western Europe. Beverly Hills: Sage.
Bibliography
363
Legro, Jeffrey. 2000. “Whence American Interationalism.” International Organization 54 (spring): 253–89. Leibowitz, Arnold H. 1984. “The Of‹cial Character of Language in the United States: Literacy Requirements for Immigration, Citizenship, and Entrance into American Life.” Aztlan 15 (spring): 25–70. LeMay, Michael C. 1987. From Open Door to Dutch Door: An Analysis of US Immigration Policy since 1820. New York: Praeger. ———. 1985. The Struggle for In›uence: The Impact of Minority Groups on Politics and Public Policy in the United States. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. ———, ed. 1989. The Gatekeepers: Comparative Immigration Policy. New York: Praeger. Lewis, W. Arthur. 1978. The Evolution of the International Economic Order. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Lichtenberg, Judith. 1981. “National Boundaries and Moral Boundaries: A Cosmopolitan View.” In Boundaries: National Autonomy and Its Limits, 79–100. Totowa, NJ: Rowan and Little‹eld. Liebman, Lance. 1992. “Immigration Status and American Law.” In Immigrants in Two Democracies: French and American Experience, ed. Donald L. Horowitz and Gerard Noiriel, 368–90. New York: New York University Press. Lindblom, Charles. 1977. Politics and Markets. New York: Basic Books. Lippmann, Walter. 1937. “Rough-Hew Them How We Will.” Foreign Affairs 15 (July). Lockhead, Carolyn. 1988. “Business: Giving Immigration Points to the Skilled and Educated.” Insight (5 September): 40–43. Loescher, Gilburt, and B. Nichols. 1988. The ‘Moral Nation’: Humanitarianism and US Foreign Policy in the 1980s. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press. Loescher, Gilburt D., and John A. Scanlon. 1986. Calculated Kindness: Refugees and America’s Half-Open Door, 1945 to the Present. New York: Free Press. ———. 1984. “Human Rights, US Foreign Policy, and Haitian Refugees.” Journal of Interamerican Studies and World Affairs 26 (August): 313–56. ———, eds. 1983. “The Global Refugee Problem: U.S. and World Response.” Annals (AAPSS) 467 (May). Entire issue. Lowell, B. Lindsay, Frank D. Bean, and Rodolfo de la Garza. 1986. “The Dilemmas of Undocumented Immigration: An Analysis of the 1984 Simpson-Mazzoli Vote.” Social Science Quarterly 67 (March): 118–27. Majone, Giandomenico. 1989. Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven: Yale University Press. Malan, Rian. 1983. “The Necessary Alien: We All Want Immigration Reform, Just Don’t Take Our Maids.” California Magazine (December): 55–56. Malthus, Thomas. 1971. An Essay on the Principle of Population; Or, a View of Its Past and Present Effects on Human Happiness. 7th ed. New York: A. M. Kelly.
364
Bibliography
Mann, Michael. 1986. The Sources of Social Power: A History of Power from the Beginning to A.D. 1760. New York: Cambridge University Press. Marrus, Michael R. 1985. The Unwanted: European Refugees in the Twentieth Century. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Marshall, T. H. 1964. “Citizenship and Social Class.” In Class, Citizenship, and Social Development (Essays), 65–122. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. Martin, David A. 1989. “Effects of International Law on Migration Policy and Practice: The Uses of Hypocrisy.” International Migration Review 23/3 (fall): 547–78. ———. 1987. Major Issues in Immigration Law. Federal Judicial Center. Martin, P., and A. Richards. 1980. “International Migration: Boon or Bane?” Monthly Labor Review (October): 4–9. Martin, P. L., and D. Meissner. 1990. EC-92 and Immigration Issues in Europe. Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Martin, Philip L. 1986. Illegal Immigration and the Colonization of the American Labor Market. New York: Center for Migration Studies. Martin, Philip L., and Marion F. Houstoun. 1984. “European and American Immigration Policies.” In US Immigration Policy, ed. Richard Hofstetter, 29–54. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Marty, Martin. 1978. “Migration: The Moral Framework.” In Human Migration: Patterns and Policies, ed. William McNeill and Ruth S. Adams, 387–403. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Marx, Karl. 1938. Critique of the Gotha Programme. New York: International Publishers. Masanz, Sharon. 1980. History of the US Immigration and Naturalization Service: A Report Prepared at the Request of Senator Edward Kennedy, Chairman, Committee on the Judiciary, United States Senate, for the Use of the Select Commission on Immigration and Refugee Policy. Washington, DC: GPO. Massey, Douglas S. 1990. “The Social and Economic Origins of Immigration.” Annals (AAPSS) 510 (July): 61–72. ———. 1988. “Economic Development and International Migration in Comparative Perspective.” Population and Development Review (September): 383–413. ———. 1981. “Dimensions of the New Immigration to the United States and the Prospects for Assimilation.” Annual Review of Sociology 7:57–85. Mathias, Charles McC. 1981. “Ethnic Groups and Foreign Policy.” Foreign Affairs 59 (summer): 975–98. Mayall, James. 1990. Nationalism and International Society. New York: Cambridge University Press. McCarthy, Kevin, and David J. Ronfeldt. 1982. US Immigration Policy and Global Interdependence. Santa Monica: Rand Corporation. McClellan, Grant S., ed. 1981. Immigrants, Refugees, and US Policy. New York: H. W. Wilson. McConnell, Scott. 1988. “The New Battle over Immigration.” Fortune (9 May): 90–99. McNeill, William. 1987. “Migration in Premodern Times.” In Population in an Interacting World, ed. William Alonso, 15–35. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bibliography
365
———. 1984. “Migration in Historical Perspective.” Population and Development Review 10/1 (March): 1–18. McNeill, William, and Ruth S. Adams, eds. 1978. Human Migration: Patterns and Policies. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Meadows, Donella H., et al. 1972. Limits to Growth: A Report of the Club of Rome’s Project on the Environment. New York: Universe Books. Mearsheimer, John J. 1990. “Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War.” International Security 15:5–56. Meehan, Elizabeth. 1993. Citizenship and the European Community. London: Sage. Meissner, Doris, et al. 1993. International Migration Challenges in a New Era. New York: Trilateral Commission. Merino, Catherine L. 1988. “Compromising Immigration Reform: The Creation of a Vulnerable Subclass.” Yale Law Journal 98 (December): 409–26. Mill, John Stuart. [1861] 1987. “Utilitarianism.” In Utilitarianism and Other Essays, John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham. New York: Penguin. Miller, David. 1988. “The Ethical Signi‹cance of Nationality.” Ethics 98 (July): 647–62. Miller, Mark J. 1989. “Political Participation and Representation of Noncitizens.” In Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Rogers Brubaker, 129–43. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for the German Marshall Fund. ———. 1989. “New Immigration in Western Democracies: The United States and Europe Compared.” International Review of Comparative Public Policy 1/1. ———. 1986. “Policy Ad-Hocracy.” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May). ———. 1982. “The Political Impact of Foreign Labor: A Re-evaluation of the Western European Experience.” International Migration Review 16/1 (spring): 27–60. ———. 1981. Foreign Workers in Western Europe: An Emerging Political Force. New York: Praeger. Miller, Richard W. 1987. Fact and Method: Explanation, Con‹rmation and Reality in the Natural and Social Sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Milner, Helen V. 1988. Resisting Protectionism: Global Industries and the Politics of International Trade. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Milward, Alan. 1992. The European Rescue of the Nation-State. Berkeley: University of California Press. Mitchell, Christopher. 1989. “International Migration, International Relations and Foreign Policy.” International Migration Review 23/3 (fall): 681–708. Mitrany, David. 1966. A Working Peace System. Chicago: Quadrangle. ———. 1933. The Progress of International Government. New Haven: Yale University Press. Mlinar, Zdravko, ed. 1992. Globalization and Territorial Entities. Brook‹eld, VT: Avebury. Moe, Terry M. 1979. “On the Scienti‹c Status of Rational Models.” American Journal of Political Science 23:215–43. Mondale, Walter. 1979. “United States Progress to Assist the World’s Refugees.” US Department of State Bulletin 2031:1–3.
366
Bibliography
Montweiler, Nancy H. 1987. The Immigration Reform Law of 1986: Analysis, Text, and Legislative History. Washington, DC: Bureau of National Affairs. Moore, Stephen. 1991. “Immigration Policy: Open Minds on Open Borders.” Business and Society Review 77 (September): 36–40. ———. 1990. “Flee Market: More Refugees at Lower Cost.” Policy Review 52 (September): 64–68. Moore, Wilbert E. 1949. “America’s Immigration Treaties during World War II.” Annals (AAPSS) 262 (March): 31–38. Moran, William F., Jr., ed. 1965. Population Growth: Threat to Peace? New York: P. J. Kennedy for the Catholic Association for International Peace. Morgenthau, Hans J. 1978. Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace. 5th ed. New York: Knopf. ———. 1949. “National Interest and Moral Principles in Foreign Policy.” American Scholar 18:207–12. ———. 1948. “The Twilight of International Morality.” Ethics 58:77–99. ———. 1940. “Positivism, Functionalism, and International Law.” American Journal of International Law 34:260–84. Morris, Milton D. 1985. Immigration: The Beleaguered Bureaucracy. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution. Morris, Robert. 1987. “Rethinking Welfare in the United States: The Welfare State in Transition.” In Modern Welfare States: A Comparative View of Trends and Prospects, ed. Robert R. Friedmann et al. Sussex: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Morrow, James. 1988. “Social Choice and System Structure in World Politics.” World Politics 41:75–97. Moulier-Boutang, Yann. 1985. “Resistance to the Political Representation of Alien Populations: The European Paradox.” International Migration Review 19/3 (fall): 485–92. Moynihan, Daniel P. 1977. “Defenders and Invaders.” Washington Post (13 June). Munk, Erika. 1987. “INS Fights Foreign Invaders.” Drama Review 31 (spring): 117–19. Myrdal, Gunnar. [1940] 1962 reprint. Population: A Problem for Democracy. Gloucester, MA: Peter Smith. Nafziger, J. A. R. 1983. “The General Admission of Aliens under International Law.” American Journal of International Law 77 (October). Nagel, Thomas. 1970. The Possibility of Altruism. Oxford: Clarendon. Nardin, Terry. 1992. “Alternative Ethical Perspectives on Transnational Migration.” In Free Movement, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin, 267–78. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf/Simon and Schuster. ———. 1983. Law, Morality, and the Relations of States. Princeton: Princeton University Press. National Research Council, Panel on Immigration Statistics. 1985. Immigration Statistics: A Story of Neglect. Washington, DC: National Academy Press Noelle-Neumann, Elisabeth, ed. 1981. The Germans: Public Opinion Polls, 1967–1980. Westport, CT: Greenwood.
Bibliography
367
Nett, Roger. 1971. “The Civil Right We Are Not Ready For: The Right of Free Movement of People on the Face of the Earth.” Ethics 81/3 (April): 212–27. New York Times. 1988. “Europeans Adopt Plan to End Curbs on Capital Flows.” (14 June): A1. ———. 1988. “Study on European Borders.” (31 March): D9. ———. 1987. “Illegal Aliens Slowly Finding Path to Citizenship.” (7 November). ———. 1985. “A Troubling Drop in Immigrant ‘Quality.’” (21 December): sec. 3, p. 3. Newland, Kathleen. 1979. “International Migration: The Search for Work.” Worldwatch Paper 33 (November). Nincic, Djura. 1970. The Problem of Sovereignty in the Charter and in the Practice of the United Nations. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Nordlinger, Eric. 1981. On the Autonomy of the Democratic State. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. O’Grady, John. 1952. “The McCarran Immigration Bill.” Commonweal 56 (2 June): 263–65. Organski, A. F. K. 1990. The $36 Billion Bargain: Strategy and Politics in U.S. Assistance to Israel. New York: Columbia University Press. Organski, A. F. K., Jacek Kugler, J. Timothy Johnson, and Youssef Cohen. 1984. Births, Deaths, and Taxes: The Demographic and Political Transitions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Organski, Katherine, and A. F. K. Organski. 1961. Population and World Power. New York: Knopf. Orren, Gary R. 1988. “Beyond Self-Interest.” In The Power of Public Ideas, ed. Robert B. Reich. Cambridge: Ballinger. Osgood, Robert E. 1953. Ideals and Self-Interest in America’s Foreign Relations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ozsvany, E. 1983. The Participation of the Alien in Public Affairs. Council of Europe. Papademetriou, Demetrios G. 1988. “International Migration in North America and Western Europe: Trends and Consequences.” In International Migration, Volume I: Trends and Prospects, ed. Reginald Appleyard. Paris: UNESCO. Papademetriou, Demetrios G., and Nicholas DiMarzio. 1986. Undocumented Aliens in the New York Metropolitan Area. Washington, DC: Center for Migration Studies. Papademetriou, D. G., and Mark J. Miller. 1983. “Immigration and US Foreign Policy.” In The Unavoidable Issue: US Immigration Policy in the 1980s. Philadelphia: Institute for the Study of Human Issues. Personnel Journal. 1989. “EEOC Issues Undocumented Alien and Title VII Policy Statement.” 68 (14 July): 14. Persons, Stow. [1944] 1952 reprint. “The Americanization of the Immigrant.” In Foreign In›uences in American Life, ed. David F. Bowers. New York: Peter Smith. Petersen, William. 1978. “International Migration.” Annual Review of Sociology 4:533–75.
368
Bibliography
———. 1965. The Politics of Population. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. Piaget, J., and A. M. Weil. 1970. “The Development in Children of the Idea of the Homeland and of Relations with Other Countries.” In Learning about Politics: A Reader in Political Socialization, ed. Roberta S. Sigel. New York: Random House. Piore, Michael J. 1986. “The Shifting Grounds for Immigration.” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May): 23–33. ———. 1980. “Another View on Migrant Workers.” Dissent 27:347+. ———. 1979. Birds of Passage: Migrant Labor and Industrial Societies. New York: Cambridge University Press. Portes, Alejandro. 1979. “Illegal Immigration and the International System: Lessons from Recent Legal Mexican Immigrants to the United States.” Social Problems 26/4. ———. 1978. “Migration and Underdevelopment.” Politics and Society 8:1–48. Portes, Alejandro, and J. Borocz. 1989. “Contemporary Immigration: Theoretical Perspectives on Its Determinants and Modes of Incorporation.” International Migration Review 23/3 (fall): 606–30. Portes, Alejandro, and John W. Curtis. 1987. “Changing Flags: Naturalization and Its Determinants among Mexican Immigrants.” International Migration Review 21/2 (summer): 352–71. Postell, Claudia. 1987. “New Immigration Bill Poses Major Changes.” Trial 23 (January): 77–79. Preston, Samuel. 1984. “Children and the Elderly: Divergent Paths for America’s Dependents.” Demography 21/4 (November): 435–57. Preston, William. 1994. Aliens and Dissenters: Federal Suppression of Radicals, 1903–1933. Chicago: University of Illinois Press. Proper, Emberson Edward. 1900. Colonial Immigration Laws: A Study of the Regulation of Immigration by the English Colonies in America. New York: Columbia University Press. Public Agenda Foundation. 1986. Immigration: What We Promised, Where to Draw the Line. Dayton, OH: Domestic Policy Association. Pytte, Alyson. 1989. “Hill Presses Administration over Policy on Emigres.” Congressional Quarterly Weekly Report 47 (April 29): 984–85. Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1958. “Justice as Fairness.” Philosophy Review 67:164–94. Reimers, David M. 1992. Still the Golden Door: The Third World Comes to America. 2d ed. New York: Columbia University Press. ———. 1982. “Recent Immigration Policy: An Analysis.” In The Gateway: US Immigration Issues and Policies, ed. Barry Chiswick, 13–53. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute. Resnick, David. 1987. “John Locke and the Problem of Naturalization.” Review of Politics 49 (summer): 368–88. Riche, Martha F. 1983. “Immigration Statistics.” American Demographics 5 (October): 38–39.
Bibliography
369
Richmond, A. A. 1984. “Socio-cultural Adaptation and Con›ict in ImmigrantReceiving Countries.” International Social Science Journal 36/3: 519–36. Richmond, Anthony H. 1988. Immigration and Ethnic Con›ict. London: Macmillan. Riggs, Fred. 1950. Pressures on Congress: The Repeal of the Chinese Exclusion Acts. New York: Columbia University Press. Ritchey, P. Neal. 1976. “Explanations of Migration.” Annual Review of Sociology 2:363–404. Robey, Bryant. 1987. “Locking up Heaven’s Door.” American Demographics 9 (February): 24–29+. Rockett, Ian R. 1983. “American Immigration Policy and Ethnic Selection: An Historical Overview.” Journal of Ethnic Studies 10 (winter): 1–26. Rogers, Rosemarie. 1986. “The Transnational Nexus of Migration.” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May): 34–50. ———., ed. 1985. Guests Come to Stay: The Effects of European Labor Migration on Sending and Receiving Countries. Boulder: Westview. Romer, Christina D. 1987. “Gross National Product, 1909–1928: Existing Estimates, New Estimates, and New Interpretations of World War I and Its Aftermath.” NBER Working Paper 2187 (March). Rosberg, Gerald M. 1978. “Legal Regulation of the Migration Process: The ‘Crisis’ of Illegal Immigration.” In Human Migrations: Patterns and Policies, ed. William McNeill and Ruth S. Adams. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. ———. 1977. “Aliens and Equal Protection: Why Not the Right to Vote?” University of Michigan Law Review 77:1092–1136. Rose, Arnold M. 1969. Migrants in Europe: Problems of Acceptance and Adjustment. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Rose, Peter I. 1985. “The Politics and Morality of US Refugee Policy.” Center Magazine 18 (September/October): 2–13. ———. 1984. “Some Re›ections on Refugee Policy.” Dissent 31 (fall): 484–86. Rosenberg, Howard R., and John W. Mamer. 1987. “The Impact of the New Immigration Reform Act.” California Agriculture 41 (March/April): 30–32. Ruggie, John Gerard. 1993. “Territoriality and Beyond.” International Organization 47/1 (winter): 139–74. ———. 1992. “Multilateralism: The Anatomy of an Institution.” International Organization 46/3 (summer): 561–98. ———. 1983. “Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity.” World Politics 35:261–85. ———. 1983. “International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order.” In International Regimes, ed. Stephen D. Krasner, 195–231. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Sadler, Blair L. 1977. “Legal and Ethical Implications of Reducing Immigration.” In Population Policy and Ethics: The American Experience, ed. Robert M. Veatch, 411–30. New York: Irvington-Wiley.
370
Bibliography
Safran, William. 1986. “Islamization in Western Europe: Political Consequences and Historical Parallels.” Annals (AAPSS) 485 (May): 98–112. Salera, Virgil. 1960. US Immigration Policy and World Population Problems. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute. Sandel, Michael J. 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sapiro, Virginia. 1984. “Women, Citizenship, and Nationality: Immigration and Naturalization Policies in the United States.” Politics and Society 13/1: 1–26. Sassen, Saskia. 1996. Losing Control? Sovereignty in an Age of Globalization. New York: Columbia University Press. ———. 1990. “US Immigration Policy toward Mexico in a Global Economy.” Journal of International Affairs 43 (winter): 369–83. Saunders, John, ed. 1986. Population Growth in Latin America and US National Security. Boston: Allen and Unwin. Sauvy, Alfred. 1949. “European Migrations: Regulations and Treaties.” Annals (AAPSS) 262 (March): 22–30. Scanlon, John A., and O. T. Kent. 1988. “The Force of Moral Arguments for a Just Immigration Policy in a Hobbesian Universe: The Contemporary American Example.” In Open Borders? Closed Societies? The Ethical and Political Issues, ed. Mark Gibney, 61–107. Westport, CT: Greenwood. Schattschneider, E. E. 1935. Politics, Pressures, and the Tariff. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Schauer, Fred. 1986. “Community, Citizenship, and the Search for National Identity.” Michigan Law Review 84:1504. Schifter, Richard, and David Burgess. 1987. “The Supreme Court and a ‘WellFounded Fear of Persecution.’ ” Atlantic Community Quarterly 25 (summer): 213–21. [Schmitter] Heisler, Barbara. 1985. “Sending Countries and the Politics of Emigration and Destination.” International Migration Review 19/3 (fall): 469–84. Schmitter, Barbara E. 1983. “Immigrant Minorities in West Germany: Some Theoretical Concerns.” Ethnic and Racial Studies 6 (July): 308–19. Scholes, Walter V., and Marie V. Scholes. 1970. The Foreign Policies of the Taft Administration. Columbia: University of Missouri Press. Schubert, Glendon. 1960. The Public Interest: A Critique of the Theory of a Political Concept. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Schuck, Peter H. 1992. “Immigration, Refugee, and Citizenship Law in the United States.” In Immigration in Two Democracies: French and American Experience, ed. Donald L. Horowitz and Gerard Noiriel, 333–56. New York: New York University Press. ———. 1989. “Membership in the Liberal Polity: The Devaluation of American Citizenship.” In Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Rogers Brubaker, 51–65. Lanham, MD: University Press of America for the German Marshall Fund. ———. 1987. “The Status and Rights of Undocumented Aliens in the United States.” International Migration 25:125–38.
Bibliography
371
———. 1985. “Immigration Law and the Problems of Community.” In Clamor at the Gates: The New American Immigration, ed. Nathan Glazer. San Francisco: ICS Press. ———. 1984. “The Transformation of Immigration Law.” Columbia Law Review 84/1: 1–90. Schuck, Peter H., and Rogers Smith. 1985. Citizenship without Consent: Illegal Aliens in the American Polity. New Haven: Yale University Press. Schultze, Charles L. 1967. National Income Analysis. 2d ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Schwartz, Abba. 1968. The Open Society. New York: Morrow. Sell, Ralph R. 1983. “Analyzing Migration Decisions: The First Step—Whose Decision?” Demography 20:299–311. Seller, Maxine S. 1984. “Historical Perspectives on American Immigration Policies: Case Studies and Current Implications.” In US Immigration Policy, ed. Richard R. Hofstetter, 137–62. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Shacknove, Andrew E. 1985. “Who Is a Refugee?” Ethics 95/2 (January): 274–84. Shalloo, J. P. 1949. “United States Immigration Policy.” In Essays in History and International Relations in Honor of George Blakeslee, ed. D. E. Lee and G. E. McReynolds. Worcester, MA: Clark University. Shankman, Arnold M. 1982. Ambivalent Friends: Afro-Americans View the Immigrant. Westport, CT: Greenwood. Shue, Henry. 1980. Basic Rights: Subsistence, Af›uence, and US Foreign Policy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 1983. “The Burdens of Justice.” Journal of Philosophy 80:600–608. Sidgwick, Henry. 1891. The Elements of Politics. London: Macmillan. Sikkink, Kathryn. 1991. Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Simcox, David E., ed. 1988. US Immigration in the 1980s: Reappraisal and Reform. Boulder: Westview. Simon, Julian L. 1989. The Economic Consequences of Immigration. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell. ———. 1987. “The Price of Citizenship: Auctioning Immigration Visas Helps Foreigners and Americans Alike.” Policy Review 39 (winter): 71–72. ———. 1977. Economics of Population Growth. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Simon, Rita J. 1985. Public Opinion and the Immigrant: Print Media Coverage, 1880–1980. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. ———. 1974. Public Opinion in America, 1936–1970. Chicago: Rand-McNally. Simpson, Alan K. 1984. “The Politics of Immigration Reform.” International Migration Review 18/3 (fall): 486–504. Singer, Peter. 1972. “Famine, Af›uence, and Morality.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1/3 (spring): 229–43. Sjaastad, Larry. 1962. “The Costs and Returns of Human Migration.” Journal of Political Economy 70/5: 80–93.
372
Bibliography
Skerry, Peter. 1989. “Borders and Quotas: Immigrants and the Af‹rmative Action State.” Public Interest 96 (summer): 94–97. Slobodan, Djajic. 1987. “Illegal Aliens, Unemployment, and Immigration Policy.” Journal of Development Economics 25 (February): 235–49. Smith, Anthony D. 1995. Nations and Nationalism in a Global Era. Cambridge: Polity Press. ———. 1986. The Ethnic Origins of Nations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Smith, James Morton. 1956. Freedom’s Fetters: The Alien and Sedition Laws and American Civil Liberties. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Smith, Rogers. 1997. Civic Ideals. New Haven: Yale University Press. Smyser, W. R. 1985. “Refugees: A Never-Ending Story.” Foreign Affairs 64 (fall): 154–68. Snidal, Duncan. 1985. “The Limits of Hegemonic Stability Theory.” International Organization 39/4 (autumn): 579–614. Sober, Elliott. 1988. Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. Cambridge: MIT Press. Social Policy. 1990. “INS Raids Underscore Need to Know, Protect Rights.” 20 (winter): 21. Sowell, Thomas. 1996. Migrations and Cultures. New York: Basic Books. Spengler, Joseph J. 1975. Population and America’s Future. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman. ———. 1974. Population Change, Modernization, and Welfare. Englewood, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Spruyt, Hendrik. 1994. The Sovereign State and Its Competitors. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Stahl, Charles, ed. 1988. International Migration Today, Volume II: Emerging Issues. Paris: UNESCO. The Statesman’s Yearbook, annual. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Stein, Dan. 1989. “The Immigration Act of 1989.” Testimony before the Subcommittee on Immigration and Refugee Affairs, Committee on the Judiciary, US Senate, re Proposed Legislation S 358. 101st C, 1st S. (3 March). Stephenson, George M. 1926. A History of American Immigration, 1820–1924. New York: Russell and Russell. Stimson, Henry. 1947. “The Decision to Use the Atomic Bomb.” Harper’s 194/1161 (February): 97–107+. Stoker, Laura L. 1992. “Interests and Ethics in Politics.” American Political Science Review 86 (June): 369–80. ———. 1990. Morality and the Study of Political Behavior. Ph.D. diss., University of Michigan. Stolnitz, George J. 1978. “International Migration Policies: Some Demographic and Economic Contexts.” In Human Migration: Patterns and Policies, ed. William H. McNeill and Ruth S. Adams, 307–16. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Strange, Susan. 1985. “Protectionism and World Politics.” International Organization 39 (spring): 233–60.
Bibliography
373
Suhrke, Astri. 1983. “Global Refugee Movements and Strategies of Response.” In US Immigration and Refugee Policy: Global and Domestic Issues, ed. Mary Kritz. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. ———. 1983. “Indochinese Refugees: The Law and Politics of First Asylum.” Annals (AAPSS) 467 (May). Sutton, Francis X. 1987. “Refugees and Mass Exoduses: The Search for a Humane, Effective Policy.” In Population in an Interacting World, ed. William Alonso, 201–26. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Swamy, Gurushri. 1985. “Population and International Migration.” World Bank Staff Working Papers 689. Symonds, Richard, and Michael Carder. 1973. The United Nations and the Population Question, 1945–1970. New York: McGraw-Hill. Takacs, Wendy. 1981. “Pressures for Protection: An Empirical Study.” Economic Inquiry 9:687–93. Taylor, Paul. 1978. “Functionalism: The Theory of David Mitrany.” In International Organisation: A Conceptual Approach, ed. Paul Taylor and A. J. R. Groom, 236–52. New York: Nichols. Teitelbaum, Michael S. 1985. Latin Migration North: The Problem for US Foreign Policy. New York: Council on Foreign Relations. ———. 1984. “Immigration, Refugees, and Foreign Policy.” International Organization 38/3 (summer): 429–50. ———. 1984. “Political Asylum in Theory and Practice.” Public Interest 76 (summer): 74–86. ———. 1980. “Right versus Right: Immigration and Refugee Policy in the United States.” Foreign Affairs 59/1 (fall): 21–59. Tenney, Alvin. 1907. Social Democracy and Population. New York: Columbia University Press. Therborn, Goran. 1991. “Cultural Belonging, Structural Location and Human Action: Explanation in Sociology and Social Science.” Acta Sociologica 34:177–91. Thomson, James C., Jr., Peter W. Stanley, and John Curtis Perry. 1981. Sentimental Imperialists: The American Experience in East Asia. New York: Harper and Row. Thomson, Janice E., and Stephen D. Krasner. 1989. “Global Transactions and the Consolidation of Sovereignty.” In Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, ed. Ernst-Otto Czempiel and James N. Rosenau. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. Tilly, Charles. 1985. “War Making and State Making as Organized Crime.” In Bringing the State Back In, ed. Peter B. Evans, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and Theda Skocpol. New York: Cambridge University Press. ———. 1978. “Migration in Modern European History.” In Human Migration: Patterns and Policies, ed. William H. McNeill and Ruth S. Adams. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Tobier, Emanuel. 1985. “Immigrants and Immigration Policy, Past and Future.” Journal of the American Planning Association 51 (autumn): 518–21.
374
Bibliography
Todaro, Michael P. 1980. “Internal Migration in Developing Countries.” In Population and Economic Change in Developing Countries, ed. Richard A. Easterlin, 361–402. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Todaro, Michael, and Lydia Maruszko. 1987. “Illegal Migration and US Immigration Reform: A Conceptual Framework.” Population and Development Review 13/1 (March): 101–14. Tomasi, Silvano M., and Charles B. Keely. 1975. Whom Have We Welcomed? The Adequacy and Quality of United States Immigration Data for Policy Analysis and Evaluation. New York: Center for Migration Studies. Tucker, Robert W. 1990. “Immigration and Foreign Policy: General Considerations.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 1–14. Boulder: Westview. ———. 1977. The Inequality of Nations. New York: Basic Books. ———. 1972. A New Isolationism: Threat or Promise? New York: Universe Books. Tucker, Robert W., Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, eds. 1990. Immigration and US Foreign Policy. Boulder: Westview. Tung, Roger Ko-Chih. 1985. “Voting Rights for Alien Residents—Who Wants It?” International Migration Review 19/3 (fall): 451–67. ———. 1981. Exit-Voice Catastrophes: Dilemma between Migration and Participation. Stockholm: University of Stockholm Studies in Politics (no. 18). ———. 1975. “The Voiceless 13 Million Non-Citizens in the New Athenian Democracies.” Scandinavian Migration and Minority Review 4. Turack, Daniel C. 1972. The Passport in International Law. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. Turner, Bryan S. 1986. Citizenship and Capitalism: The Debate over Reformism. London: Allen and Unwin. Turner, Frederick C. 1965. “The Implications of Demographic Change for Nationalism and Internationalism.” Journal of Politics (February): 87–108. Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1986. “The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice.” In Rational Choice, ed. Jon Elster. New York: New York University Press. US News and World Report. 1989. “Give Me Your Tired Engineers, Your Poor Biochemists, Your Huddled Computer Scientists Earning Big Fees.” July 24: 12. Vasak, Karel, and Sidney Liskofsky. 1976. The Right to Leave and to Return. New York: American Jewish Commission. Vattel, Emerich. 1861. The Law of Nations, ed. Joseph Chitty. Philadelphia: Johnson. Vernez, Georges, ed. 1990. Immigration and International Relations: Proceedings of a Conference on the International Effects of the 1986 Immigration Reform and Control Act (IRCA). May. Washington, DC: Urban Institute and Rand Corporation. Vernon, Raymond. 1971. Sovereignty at Bay: The Multinational Spread of US Enterprises. New York: Basic Books.
Bibliography
375
Vialet, Joyce. [1988] 1989. “Brief History of US Immigration Policy.” Immigration and Nationality Act, Appendix X. (April). Washington, DC: GPO. Vittoz, Stan. 1978. “World War I and the Political Accommodation of Transitional Market Forces: The Case of Immigration Restriction.” Politics and Society 8/1: 49–78. Walker, R. B. J. 1990. “Security, Sovereignty, and the Challenge of World Politics.” Alternatives 15:3–27. Wall Street Journal. 1990. “Editorial.” 3 July. Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. New York: Random House. ———. 1964. “The Stability of a Bipolar World.” Daedalus 93/3: 881–909. ———. 1959. Man,the State and War. New York: Columbia University Press. Walzer, Michael. 1992. What It Means to Be an American. New York: Marsilio Bros. ———. 1985. “The Moral Standing of States: A Response to Four Critics.” In International Ethics, ed. Charles Beitz, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Scanlon, and A. John Simmons. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 1983. Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. New York: Basic Books. ———. 1979. “The Moral Problem of Refugees.” New Republic 180 (10 February): 15–17. Warren, Robert, and J. M. Peck. 1980. “Foreign-born Emigration to the US: 1960–1970.” Demography 17:71–84. Warren, Robert, and Ellen Percy Kraly. 1985. The Elusive Exodus: Emigration from the United States. Washington, DC: Population Reference Bureau. Wattenberg, Ben J. 1989. “The Case for More Immigrants.” US News and World Report 106 (13 February): 29–31. Wattenberg, Ben J., and Karl Zinsmeister. 1990. “The Case for More Immigration.” Commentary (April): 19–25. Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society, ed. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich. Berkeley: University of California Press. Weiner, Myron. 1992. “International Population Movements: Implications for Foreign Policies and Migration Policies.” In Immigrants in Two Democracies: French and American Experience, ed. Donald L. Horowitz and Gerard Noiriel, 439–61. New York: New York University Press. ———. 1990. “Asian Immigrants and US Foreign Policy.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 192–213. Boulder: Westview. ———. 1990. Security, Stability and International Migration. Cambridge: MIT Center for International Studies. ———. 1987. “International Emigration and the Third World.” In Population in an Interacting World, ed. William Alonso, 173–200. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1985. “On International Migration and International Relations.” Population and Development Review 11/3 (September): 441–55.
376
Bibliography
———. 1971. “Political Demography: An Inquiry into the Political Consequences of Population Change.” In Rapid Population Growth: Consequences and Policy Implications, V. II., 567–617. National Academy of Sciences. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Weintraub, Sidney. 1992. “North American Free Trade and the European Situation Compared.” International Migration Review 26/2 (summer): 506–24. Weintraub, Sidney, and Stanley R. Ross. 1982. “Temporary” Alien Workers in the United States: Designing Policies from Fact and Opinion. Boulder: Westview. Weintraub, Sidney, and C. Stolp. 1987. “The Implications of Growing Interdependence.” In The Future of Migration. Paris: OECD. Wendt, Alexander E. 1987. “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations.” International Organization 41:335–70. Whelan, Frederick G. 1988. “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement: An Open Admission Policy?” In Open Borders? Closed Societies? The Ethical and Political Issues, ed. Mark Gibney, 3–39. Westport, CT: Greenwood. ———. 1983. “Principles of US Immigration Policy.” University of Pittsburgh Law Review 44/2: 447–84. ———. 1981. “Citizenship and the Right to Leave.” American Political Science Review 75 (September): 53–63. Widgren, Jonas. 1989. “Asylum-Seekers in Europe in the Context of South-North Movements.” International Migration Review 23/3 (fall): 599–605. Wiers, Paul. 1949. “International Implications of American Immigration Policies.” Annals (AAPSS) 262 (March): 39–44. Wihtol de Wenden, Catherine. 1991. “Immigration Policy and the Issue of Nationality.” Ethnic and Racial Studies 14 (July): 319–32. ———. 1991. “The Absence of Rights: The Position of Illegal Immigrants in Europe.” In The Political Rights of Migrant Workers in Western Europe, ed. Zig Layton-Henry, 27–46. Beverly Hills: Sage. Wihtol de Wenden, Catherine, and Jacqueline Costa-Lascoux. 1984. “Immigration Reform in France and the United States: Re›ections and Documentation.” International Migration Review 18/3 (fall): 613–22. Wilcox, Walter F. 1969. International Migrations, Volume I: Statistics; Volume II: Interpretations. Compiled for the ILO, edited on behalf of the NBER. New York: Grodon and Breach Science Publishers. Wittke, Carl. 1949. “Immigration Policy Prior to World War I.” Annals (AAPSS) 262 (March): 5–14. World Refugee Survey. 1992. New York: United States Committee for Refugees. Wyman, David S. 1984. Abandonment of the Jews. New York: Pantheon. Yans-McLaughlin, Virginia. 1990. Immigration Reconsidered: History, Sociology, and Politics. New York: Oxford University Press. Yivo Institute for Jewish Research. 1945. The Classi‹cation of Jewish Immigrants and Its Implications, a Survey of Opinion. New York: Yivo Scienti‹c Institute. Yof‹e, David. 1983. Power and Protectionism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Bibliography
377
Zimmerman, William. 1987. Open Borders, Nonalignment, and the Political Evolution of Yugoslavia. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Zolberg, Aristide R. 1990. “The Roots of US Refugee Policy.” In Immigration and US Foreign Policy, ed. Robert W. Tucker, Charles B. Keely, and Linda Wrigley, 99–120. Boulder: Westview. ———. 1989. “The Next Waves: Migration Theory for a Changing World.” International Migration Review 23/3 (fall): 403–30. ———. 1989. Escape from Violence: Con›ict and the Refugee Crisis in the Developing World. New York: Oxford University Press. ———. 1988. “The Roots of American Refugee Policy.” Social Research 55 (winter): 649–78. ———. 1987. “Keeping Them Out: Ethical Dilemmas of Immigration Policy.” In International Ethics in the Nuclear Age, ed. Robert J. Myers, 261–97. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. ———. 1987. “Wanted But Not Welcome: Alien Labor in Western Development.” In Population in an Interacting World, ed. William Alonso, 36–73. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ———. 1986. “International Factors in the Formation of Refugee Movements.” International Migration Review 20/2 (summer): 151–69. ———. 1984. “International Migration and Foreign Policy: When Does a Marginal Issue Become Substantive?” Immigration and Refugee Policy [In Defense of the Alien, V. VI.], ed. Lydio Tomasi. New York: Center for Migration Studies. ———. 1983. “Contemporary Transnational Migrations in Historical Perspective: Patterns and Dilemmas.” In US Immigration and Refugee Policy, ed. Mary Kritz. Lexington, MA: DC Heath. ———. 1983. “The Formation of New States as a Refugee-Generating Process.” Annals (AAPSS) 467:24–38. ———. 1983. “Patterns of International Migration Policy: A Diachronic Comparison.” In Minorities: Community and Identity, ed. C. Fried. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. ———. 1981. “Origins of the Modern World System: A Missing Link.” World Politics 23/2 (January): 253–81. ———. 1981. “International Migrations in Political Perspective.” In Global Trends in Migration: Theory and Research on International Population Movements, ed. Mary M. Kritz, Charles B. Keely, and Silvano M. Tomasi. New York: Center for Migration Studies. ———. 1978. “International Migration Policies in a Changing World System.” In Human Migration: Patterns and Policies, ed. William H. McNeill and Ruth S. Adams, 241–86. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Zucker, Norman L., and Naomi Flink Zucker. 1987. The Guarded Gate: The Reality of American Refugee Policy. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Index
Note: Unattributed quotes in the text are cited by page number and the note number that follows the quote; for example “166n. 115” indicates that the quote before note 115 on page 166 is given by Brockman Adams. Abourezk, James, 192 Acheson, Dean, 136 Adams, Brockman, 166n. 115 Addams, Jane, 26, 53 Addonizio, Hugh, 125n. 147, 164n. 105, 174n. 156 Afghanistan, 195 Agriculturalists, skilled, 263 Aldrich, Richard, 51n. 108, 79n. 128 Alexander, Robert, 123 Alien and Sedition Acts, 33 American Legion, 101, 115 Amnesty, 206, 213–15. See also Illegal immigrants; Immigration Reform and Control Act Anderson, Glenn, 205 Anderson, John, 193n. 23 Anfuso, Victor, 137, 151n. 33 Annunzio, Frank, 169n. 128, 203n. 58 Apocalypse, 57, 83 Apprehensions, 238. See also Control Arguments, 13–14, 276–79; and reasons, 11–12 Armenians, 35 Armies, immigrants as, 56–57, 103, 190 Armstrong, William, 222n. 153 Ashbrook, John, 216n. 122 Asian Barred Zone, 34, 36, 164, 175, 176 Asians, 72, 74, 173 Aspin, Les, 197
Assassins, immigrants as: of McKinley, 63, 259; of presidents generally, 97. See also Lee Harvey Oswald Aswell, James, 42n. 54, 81n. 143 Atomic age, 124, 151 Austin, Richard, 58 Australia, 78, 219, 281 Austria, 71, 74, 126; insane Austrians, 74 Bacon, Robert, 37n. 22, 91n. 188, 93n. 193 Badillo, Herman, 214n. 106, 219 Barkley, Alben, 116n. 95 Barnet, Richard, 1n. 2 Barry, Brian, 5n. 11, 15n. 11, 250n. 12 Barth, Fredrik, 7n. 16 Basque shepherds, 96, 174 Beard, Robin, 208, 217n. 131 Beckworth, Lindley, 106n. 43 Beitz, Charles, 23n. 37 Belgium, 85 Bennet, William, 36n. 18 Bennett, John, 110n. 62 Bentley, Alvin, 157n. 71 Benton, William, 118n. 105, 133n. 189, 133n. 191 Bentsen, Lloyd, 210 Bereuter, Douglas, 221n. 150 Berman, Howard, 212n. 97 Bible, 56, 117 379
380
Index
Biddle, Francis, 109n. 56, 120 Bierstecker, Thomas, 7n. 18 Biskupic, Joan, 3n. 6 Black, Hugo, 99 Black Americans: and Civil War, 78; Congressional Black Caucus, 197; as former slaves, 77; migration north, 68; and race war, 129; and unemployment, 168; See also Civil Rights Movement; Detroit Blease, Coleman, 99n. 13 Blue eyes, preference for, 57 Bohemia, 85, 275 Bolshevism, 51, 60, 63, 76, 79, 96. See also Cold war; Communism; Ideology Bolton, Francis, 131 Bonker, Don, 224 Borah, William, 42n. 53, 46 Border, control of, 209. See also Apprehensions Borsum, Holm, 87n. 182 Boschwitz, Rudolph, 218n. 134 Boundaries, issue-speci‹c, 142 Box, John, 37n. 21, 43n. 62, 44n. 67, 47, 48n. 85, 48n. 86, 57n. 11, 60n. 32, 60n. 33, 61n. 36, 61n. 42, 76n. 109, 77n. 121, 86n. 179, 91n. 192 Boy Scouts, 99 Brademas, John, 189 Brooks, Jack, 206n. 71 Brooks, T. J., 50n. 102 Brown, Robin, 1n. 2 Brubaker, William Rogers, 282n. 15 Bruce, William, 76n. 111 Bryant, John, 205 Buck, Pearl, 110 Buckley, James, 216n. 120 Bulgaria 71, 174 Bumpers, Dale, 203–5, 227 Burlingame Treaty, 47 Burma, 154 Burnett, John, 34 Burton, Laurence, 169n. 129 Burton, Theodore, 80n. 140
Busby, Thomas Jefferson (Jeff ), 39, 42n. 50, 56 Byrd, Robert, 216n. 123 Byrnes, James, 60 Cable, John, 42n. 51, 48n. 88, 98n. 4 Cable, Vincent, 1n. 2 Calhoun, Craig, 273 California, 61, 78, 281 Callovi, Giuseppe, 282n. 16 Cameron, David, 6n. 13 Cameron, Ronald, 165n. 113 Caminetti, A., 53n. 124, 69n. 80, 72n. 98 Campbell, Ben Nighthorse, 204 Campbell, Richard, 76n. 113, 79n. 130 Canada, 99, 124, 219 Cannon, Jospeh, 50n. 105 Carens, Joseph, 7n. 15 Carr, E. H., 1n. 2, 19 Carter, Jimmy, administration, 206, 216, 231 Carusi, Ugo, 108n. 52 Casinelli, C. W., 15 Celler, Emanuel, 46n. 78, 50n. 104, 67, 80n. 135, 84n. 163, 108n. 54, 110n. 60, 117n. 100, 119n. 110, 120n. 120, 122n. 135, 124n. 141, 137, 149n. 26, 151n. 34, 153n. 43, 157n. 73, 163n. 99, 165n. 109, 173n. 151, 174n. 157, 175n. 170, 177n. 173, 179 Central Intelligence Agency (CIA), Phoenix program, 192 Chapman, Leonard, 189 Chandler, Walter, 50, 52n. 118, 58, 86n. 176 Chiang Kai-shek, Madame, 110 Chile, 192 Chiles, Lawton, 209n. 85, 214, 217 China, 61, 123, 136, 189, 194, 218, 266, 275; opinion poll about, 234 Chinese Exclusion Acts, 31, 33, 36, 72, 97, 109, 125, 190 Chisholm, Shirley, 197 Chopra, Jarat, 1n. 2
Index Citizens, second-class, 72, 212 Civil Rights Movement, 144, 168–71 Civil War, U.S., 27, 31, 76, 208; and black Americans, 78 Clancy, Robert, 85n. 172 Clark, Joseph, 157n. 69 Clay, William, 199 Cleveland, Grover, 35n. 12 Cockran, Bourke, 53n. 119 Cody, Charles, 35n. 14 Cold war, 124–30, 144–61; allies, 153; bloc politics, 201. See also Bolshevism; Communism; Ideology Coleman, William, 82n. 149 Collins, Cardiss, 222 Collinson, Sarah, 282n. 16 Colonization, by immigrants, 59 Colt, LeBaron, 52n. 114, 52n. 115, 54, 80n. 142, 85n. 171 Communism: exclusion provisions, 134; provoke race war in U.S., 129. See also Bolshevism; Cold war; Ideology; USSR Communitarians, 18–19, 205, 210 Compton, Karl, 20n. 30 Concentration (internment) camps, in U.S., 106, 108, 221 Congo, 280 Congress, U.S. partisanship in, 230–33 Constitution, U.S., 199; Fourteenth Amendment, 32. See also Supreme Court Constructivism, 7–8 Conte, Silvio, 157n. 72 Conyers, John, 170n. 136, 215 Coolidge, Calvin, 26, 44, 77 Copeland, Royal, 65n. 65 Corman, James, 177n. 174 Cornelius, Wayne, 215, 235n. 9 Costa Rica, 197 Cranston, Alan, 199 Cretella, Albert, 160n. 83 Criminality, of immigrants, 97–98, 100 Crist, Raymond, 84n. 166 Croatia, 84
381
Cuba, 85, 146, 162, 172, 177, 188, 189, 196, 197, 199, 208 Curtis, Carl, 203n. 60 Czechoslovakia, 137, 174 Czempiel, Ernst-Otto, 1n. 2 Dagger, Richard, 11n. 2 D’Amato, Alfonse, 203 Daub, Harold, 205, 215, 216n. 125 DaVanzo, Julie, 261n. 23 Davis, James, 43n. 64 Declaration of Independence, 6, 51, 98 Decolonization, 144, 164–66, 172, 275 Deconcini, Dennis, 194 DeLaet, Debra, 4n. 10 Delaney, James, 125n. 148 Dellums, Ron, 214 Democracy, as resilient, 106 Democratic Party, 158, 175, 202, 224. See also Voting Dent, John, 151n. 29 Detente, 194 Detroit, 215 Dewey, John, 12 Dickinson, William, 193 Dickstein, Samuel, 49n. 96, 80n. 141, 99n. 16, 101n. 25, 103, 104n. 37, 110n. 63, 119n. 108, 119n. 109, 119n. 113, 278 Dies, Martin, 57n. 15 Diggs, Charles, 151n. 32 Dillingham, William, 34–35, 82 Dillingham Commission, 34 Dingell, John, 152n. 40, 162 Diplomatic embarrassment, 53, 85 Dirksen, Everett, 124n. 143, 186n. 203 Displaced persons, 119, 136, 152 Displaced Persons Act, 130–32 Dole, Robert, 217 Dollar standard, 195 Domestic interests, 230–44 Domestic policy, consistency with foreign policy, 158 Dominican Republic, 177
382
Index
Dondero, George, 132n. 187, 133n. 188, 133n. 190 Donohue, Harold, 147n. 2 Douglas, Paul, 131n. 179, 163n. 98 Dow, John, 219 Drinan, Robert, 199n. 42 Driver, W. J., 87n. 184 Duchacek, Ivo, 3n. 7 Dulles, John Foster, 121 Durenberger, David, 194 Duvalier, Jean-Claude (“Baby Doc”), 209 Eastland, James, 114n. 79, 116n. 92, 116n. 93, 128n. 163, 130n. 175, 147n. 8, 149n. 22, 149n. 23 Economic prosperity, American, 66–67, 157; and immigration, research on, 198 Economic sphere, 272–73 Economic standards, as basis for selection, 67, 196–200, 204 Eilberg, Joshua, 192 Eisenhower, Dwight, 137, 153, 162n. 92, 163, 168, 174, 175, 275 Elections, U.S., 231 Ellis, Ethan, 39n. 36 Ellis, Hubert, 115n. 85, 115n. 88 El Salvador, 194, 197 Emigration, from U.S., 100; from poor countries, 164 Employer sanctions, 222, 226 Employment. See Unemployment Engdahl, Louis, 99 England, 116, 124, 153, 174, 175, 275 Ennis, Edward, 108n. 53, 109n. 55 Entitlements. See Welfare Environmentalists, 217 Ervin, Sam, 149n. 21, 149n. 25, 167n. 120 Espenshade, Thomas, 4n. 10 Ethics, 17–24 Ethiopia, 104 Eugenics, 8, 26, 27, 33, 74
Europe, 27, 76, 81–86, 101, 126, 148; southern, 136 European Community, 175 European Union, 282 Evangelista, Matthew, 7n. 17 Exclusion, 31–54 Exclusion categories, 260 Executive branch, as enemy, 47 Exon, John, 216n. 120 Fama, Charles, 80n. 136 Feighan, Michael, 149n. 19, 171n. 143, 174n. 160 Fenwick, Millicent, 191 Ferguson, Homer, 152n. 36, 174n. 162 Fess, Simeon, 64n. 63 Findley, Paul, 176n. 171 Fino, Paul, 165n. 108 First amendment, 3; making U.S. vulnerable, 106 Fish, Hamilton, 128n. 162 Fisher, Ovie C., 148n. 13, 178 Fletcher, Duncan, 87n. 183 Flood, Daniel, 156n. 61 Floyd, William, 110n. 64 Focht, Benjamin, 42, 71n. 89, 72n. 99 Folger, John, 110n. 61 Fong, Hiram, 157n. 68, 164n. 103, 170, 172n. 145 Ford, Leland, 103n. 30 Ford, Thomas, 123n. 138 Foreign aid, 165 Fortune magazine, 103n. 31 France, 22, 84, 101, 116, 124, 173, 219, 271; revolution in, 63, 268, 273 Frank, Barney, 198 Franklin, Benjamin, 33 Free, Arthur, 77n. 117 Freeman, Gary, 4n. 10, 7n. 15 Frenzel, William, 215n. 111 Friedenwald, Herbert, 35n. 11 Fukuyama, Francis, 4n. 10 Functionalism, 248–50, 252, 256, 258, 266, 272
Index Gallagher, Cornelius, 178n. 179 Gallivan, James, 49n. 95, 50, 54n. 126, 67n. 76 Gallup polls, 193n. 22, 233–35 Garber, Milton, 40n. 40, 77, 274 Garcia, Robert, 208, 214n. 107, 221 Gekas, George, 210n. 89 General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT), 157 Genocide, 127 Gentleman’s Agreement, 45. See also Japan Gentry, Brady, 147n. 4, 148n. 15 George, Walter, 113n. 75 German-Americans, 81 Germany, 32, 84, 104, 116, 119, 126, 132, 163, 174, 178, 275, 281; or airlift, 190; and Berlin Wall, 159, 172–73, 196, 224; East Germany, 174; and economic competition, 187, 202; and guestworkers, 213 Ghana, 276 Giaimo, Robert, 181n. 190 Gilbert, Jacob, 152n. 37, 181n. 191 Gilbert, Ralph, 50n. 103, 76n. 112, 90n. 186 Gillett, Frederick, 36n. 20, 39n. 34 Glickman, Daniel, 212n. 98, 212n. 99 Golden, Harry, 186n. 202 Goldstein, Judith, 1n. 4, 13n. 6, 14n. 8, 220n. 142 Gonzalez, Henry, 222 Goodin, Robert, 7n. 15 Goodman, Leo, 120n. 116, 121n. 127 Gordenker, Leon, 194n. 28 Gordon, Thomas, 118n. 104 Gossett, Ed, 116n. 91, 118n. 106, 118n. 107 Grabowski, Bernard, 169n. 131 Graham, Bob, 211 Gramm, Phil, 204–5 Grant, Madison, 26n. 41 Grassley, Charles, 214 Great Depression, 96–101
383
Greece, 114, 125, 126, 136, 153, 157, 173 Green, Robert, 97n. 2, 99n. 11, 100n. 21 Greenwood, Arthur, 64n. 60 Guatemala, 197 Gulick, Sidney, 49, 51, 64n. 61 Hailbronner, Kay, 281n. 14 Haiti, 197, 199, 209 Hall, Durward, 164n. 104, 218 Hancock, Clarence, 103n. 32 Hardy, Rufus, 50 Harris, William, 61n. 41, 81n. 146 Harwood, Edwin, 55n. 1, 233–34, 235 Hart, Gary, 227 Hart, Philip, 154n. 49, 159n. 180, 170n. 139, 172n. 146, 174n. 159, 175 Hart-Celler Act (1965), 144–86 Hatch, Carl, 116n. 94 Hayakawa, Samuel I., 193, 194n. 27, 218 He›in, Thomas, 48n. 47, 56, 57, 63n. 55, 83n. 158, 98n. 7, 99 Hegemonic stability theory, 247–48, 249, 252, 253, 258, 265 Hegemony, 53, 96, 120–23, 131, 145, 150–54, 161, 165, 175, 188, 207, 220–21, 261–62, 278 Held, Virginia, 15n. 11 Heller, Louis, 126n. 155, 135n. 196 Helmes, Jesse, 189, 192, 197, 203, 208, 215 Helsinki Final Act, 199 Hendrickson, David, 18, 19 Hendrickson, Robert, 155n. 58, 156n. 60, 161 Herz, John, 1n. 2 Hesburgh, Theodore, 207, 220n. 143, 227 Heterogeneity, and war, 111 Higham, John, 33n. 6, 37n. 23 Hill, John, 58n. 20, 86n. 177 Hillings, Pat, 157 Hindus, 36, 45, 69. See also India
384
Index
Hines, Lewis G., 121n. 125 Hinsley, F. H., 1n. 4 Hirshman, Albert O., 14n. 7 Hispanic Caucus, 200 Hitler, Adolf, 110, 112, 118–19, 134, 135 Hobbs, Samuel, 114n. 78, 274 Hofstadter, Richard, 26n. 41 Holaday, William, 71n. 92 Holland, 126 Holli‹eld, James, 7n. 15, 221n. 144, 279 Holt, Joe, 163n. 97 Homogeneity, and democracy, 68, 218 Homosexuality, 198 Honduras, 197 Hong Kong, 218 Horton, Frank, 179n. 185 Howard, William, 77 Huddleston, George, 84n. 164, 191–92, 199, 209, 210n. 86, 216, 217, 218n. 133, 227, 229n. 169, 274 Hudson, Grant, 76n. 108 Hughes, Charles Evans, 45 Hull, Harry, 41n. 45, 41n. 46, 56n. 4, 59n. 26, 59n. 28, 63n. 50, 63n. 58, 67n. 75, 74n. 104, 86n. 178 Humanitarianism, 116, 130, 137; inhumaneness, 174 Humphrey, Hubert, 117n. 97, 121, 123n. 137, 126n. 152, 155n. 53, 166n. 114, 171n. 144, 173n. 150, 173n. 152, 173n. 153, 173n. 154, 175n. 165, 178n. 183 Hungary, 71, 137, 146, 172, 174; refugees, 161–64 Husted, James, 83n. 161 Hyde, DeWitt, 163n. 96 Hypocrisy, 16, 35, 53–54, 140, 157, 242 Identity cards, 222 Ideology, 99, 111, 201, 259. See also Bolshevism; Cold war; Communism Illegal immigrants, 62, 210, 212–16, 239; as underclass, 212. See also
Amnesty; Immigration Reform and Control Act Immigration: numerical ceiling, 55; characteristics, 258–65 Immigration Reform and Control Act (IRCA), 187–230. See also Amnesty; Illegal immigrants India, 8, 110, 119, 120, 122, 154, 212, 217, 218, 275. See also Hindus Interdependence, 38, 108, 109–10, 120, 124, 140, 160–61, 206, 255, 272 Interest groups, 235 International organizations, 127, 141, 157, 220, 221 Investment: preferences for, 202–3, 204; foreign in U.S., 205 Iran, hostage crisis, 193–94, 197 Ireland, 32, 153, 175, 178, 275 Irwin, Donald, 181n. 194 Isolationism, diplomatic and political, 101–2, 114–15, 139–42, 147, 149–50, 154, 178 Israel, 281 Italy, 46, 74, 85, 99, 104, 116, 125, 126, 136, 153, 157, 173, 178, 275 Ives, Irving, 154n. 48, 164n. 102 Jackson-Vanik amendment, 189 Jamaica, 218 James, Frank, 85n. 167 Japan, 45–47, 61–62, 69, 74, 78, 80, 105–6, 108, 111, 132, 154, 165, 184, 205, 227, 266, 275, 281; and Pearl Harbor, 110; and economic competition, 187, 202 Javits, Jacob, 117n. 99, 117n. 101, 126n. 150, 131n. 178, 137, 150n. 28, 152n. 38, 152n. 41, 155n. 56, 156, 159n. 78, 169n. 127, 169n. 134, 172, 173n. 149, 177n. 176 Jefferson, Thomas, 19, 32. See also Declaration of Independence Jenkins, Thomas, 104n. 34, 104n. 38, 105n. 39, 113n. 73, 137n. 202 Jenks, James, 65, 80n. 139, 82n. 153
Index Jenner, William, 107n. 50, 119n. 111, 168n. 122 Johnson, Albert, 43n. 57, 43n. 59, 43n. 61, 46n. 80, 59n. 27, 60, 61n. 39, 62n. 49, 64n. 64, 72n. 97, 77n. 114, 83n. 157, 100, 130n. 172 Johnson, Lyndon, 149, 153, 180, 181n. 189 Johnson, Oakley, 99n. 17 Johnston, Alastair, 7n. 17 Jones, Maldwyn, 4n. 10, 32n. 3 Jones, Marvin, 83n. 156 Jones, Wesley, 40n. 39, 56n. 2 Joppke, Christian, 7n. 15 Judd, Walter, 110n. 65, 111n. 67, 121n. 124, 122n. 133, 122n. 134, 124n. 145, 133n. 192 Kant, Immanuel, 21 Kazen, Abraham, 222n. 152 Keating, Kenneth, 155n. 57, 156n. 67, 165n. 111 Keefe, Daniel, 35n. 10, 60n. 35 Keely, Charles, 4n. 10 Kelly, Edna, 191 Kemp, Jack, 193, 221 Kennan, George, 35 Kennedy, Ambrose, 35n. 15 Kennedy, Edward, 174n. 155, 179, 189, 192, 198, 200, 202, 208, 209n. 80, 218, 222–23, 227 Kennedy, John, 153, 161, 169, 172 Kennedy, Robert, 160n. 84, 181n. 193 Keohane, Robert, 1n. 4, 247n. 5, 253n. 16 Kilgore, Harley, 124n. 142, 131n. 181 Kincheloe, David, 84n. 162 King, Martin Luther, 168. See also Civil Rights Movement King, Timothy, 21n. 31 King, William, 106n. 47 Kingdon, John, 16, 24 Kirkland, Lane, 213, 214. See also Labor Kissinger, Henry, 18, 189
385
Klein, Arthur, 117n.103, 135n. 197 Know-Nothing Party, 33 Knutson, Harold, 80n. 137 Koch, Ed, 189 Koreans, 188 Korean War, 132–33, 152; veterans of, 148, 168 Krasner, Stephen, 1n. 2, 1n. 4, 150n. 27 Kratochwil, Friedrich, 1n. 3, 15, 273 Ku Klux Klan, 53 Kvale, Ole, 52n. 117 Labor, 38–39, 42, 57, 59, 63, 66, 211; cheap, 208; intensity in manufacturing, 205; Mexican, 87; poll, 235; skilled vs. unskilled 135, 202–3, 211, 269; unions, 119, 213; working-class solidarity, as the real target of antiimmigration laws, 99. See also Kirkland, Lane; Unemployment LaFalce, John, 203 Lane, Thomas, 153n. 44, 154n. 47 Langer, William, 163n. 94 Language, 38, 60, 71, 77, 218. See also Literacy Larson, Oscar, 85n. 174 Lattimore, Owen, 127 Laughlin, Harry, 74, 76n. 107 Lausche, Frank, 149n. 19 Lautenberg, Frank, 215 Lea, Clarence, 39n. 37 League of Nations, 42, 43 Leavitt, Scott, 74n. 105 Lehman, Herbert, 113n. 72, 120n. 118, 130n. 174, 155n. 55, 178n. 182 Lenin, V. I., 83 Lenroot, Irvine, 58n. 21 Liberalism, 28, 35, 80, 159, 207, 269. See also Universalism Liff, Matthew, 117n. 102, 120n. 117, 120n. 119 Lilly, Thomas, 57, 69n. 78 Lindsay, John, 160n. 82, 166n. 116 Linthicum, Charles, 59n. 24
386
Index
Lipinski, William, 190 Literacy, 64, 66, 259; newspapers, 71; test, 34–35. See also Language Locke, John, 22, 214 Lodge, Henry Cabot, 41, 90 London, Meyer, 51n. 112, 52n. 113, 66n. 72, 79n. 131, 84n. 165, 85n. 168 Lozier, Ralph, 43n. 65 Luce, Claire Booth, 119n. 112, 123n. 136 Lundine, Stanley, 203, 275n. 10 Lungren, Daniel, 224n. 161 Lusk, Georgia, 119n. 115, 121n. 128 MacDonald, Lawrence, 193 MacDonald, Torbert, 151n. 30, 171n. 140 MacGregor, Clark, 178n. 177 Mackey, A. R., 129n. 168, 139n. 206 MacLafferty, James, 61n. 44, 69n. 86, 78n. 127 Majone, Giandomenico, 5n. 11, 12n. 3, 14 Malaysia, 165 Mann, James, 45n. 75 Marcantonio, Vito, 106n. 48 Marriage, interracial, 72 Marshall, Louis, 50–51 Marshall, T. H., 4n. 9, 211, 243 Marshall Plan, 116, 146 Mason, William, 43 Mattingly, Mack, 211 Mayall, James, 273n. 3 May›ower, 50, 180 Mazzoli, Romano, 210 McCarran, Patrick, 115, 121, 127, 130n. 173, 136, 146–47, 148n. 16, 148n. 17, 154, 175n. 169 McCarran, Walter, 96–143 McClatchy, V. S., 74, 78n. 125 McClellan, John, 148n. 11, 156n. 62, 168n. 126 McCollum, William, 227n. 164 McCulloch, William, 178n. 178 McDonald, Jack, 215–16
McGovern, George, 199 McKenzie, John, 63n. 54 McLeod, Clarence, 79n. 132 McMahon, James, 119n. 114, 121n. 130 McNulty, James, 212n. 100 McReynolds, Samuel, 40n. 41, 62n. 47, 63n. 51, 82n. 154, 83n. 159 McSwain, John, 81n. 144 Meehan, Elizabeth, 1n. 1, 282n. 16 Mental inferiority, 56 Mercantilism, 66, 269 Merritt, Schuyler, 85n. 170 Mexico, 86–87, 178, 200 Meyer, John, 106n. 49 Michener, Earl, 42n. 48 Midgely, Elizabeth, 4n. 10 Mill, John Stuart, 22, 207 Miller, David, 19n. 24 Miller, George, 134n. 193 Miller, John, 40 Miller, William Lee, 6n. 12 Milligan, Jacob, 57 Mitchell, George, 222 Mitrany, David, 248–49 Mondell, Frank, 44n. 72 Monroe Doctrine, 87, 177. See also Western Hemisphere Montesquieu, 19 Mooney, Charles, 79n. 129, 80n. 134 Moore, Arch, 181n. 192, 181n. 195 Moore, G. E., 17n. 18 Moore, Joseph, 35n. 16 Morgenthau, Hans, 20n. 30, 246 Morris, Robert, 7n. 14 Morse, Wayne, 125n. 146, 131n. 177 Moynihan, Daniel Patrick, 198 Multer, Abraham, 117n. 96 Murphy, U. G., 53, 80n. 138 Mussolini, 83, 99, 110 Nagel, Thomas, 17n. 18 National debt, 205 National interest, 211, 221 Nationalism, 268
Index National origins, 29, 149, 161, 164, 261 Nazism, 106, 278; and American racism, 108; former Nazis barred from entry, 118; refusing refugees ›eeing from, 103 Neely, M. M., 56, 57n. 7, 87n. 180 Nelson, Alan C., 199n. 40 Nett, Roger, 21–22 Newton, Walter, 43n. 60 New York Chamber of Commerce, 78 Nicaragua, 194, 197; refugees from, 188 Nixon, Richard, 162, 187 Nonimmigrants: policy toward, 257–59; volume of, 238–41, 250 Nordics, 80, 118–19 Norris, George, 115n. 82 North America Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA), 200 North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO), 125, 126, 136, 139, 142, 153, 157, 163, 164, 169, 174 O’Connor, John, 52n. 116 O’Conor, Herbert, 114n. 77, 129n. 165, 130n. 171 O’Hara, Barratt, 177n. 175 O’Neal, Maston, 147n. 7, 167n. 121, 168n. 125 O’Neill, Thomas P., 167n. 117 Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD), 157 Organski, A. F. K., 241, 268n. 2 Organski, Katherine, 268n. 1 Orphans, 172 Osgood, Robert, 18n. 19 Oswald, Lee Harvey, 146, 149 Packard, Ron, 216n. 119 Pakistan, 165 Parole, 255 Parrish, Lucian, 58n. 18 Parsons, Talcott, 12 Pasqual, Leonard, 120n. 123 Passports, 43
387
Pastore, John, 117n. 98, 126n. 151, 151n. 31, 152n. 39, 161n. 85 Peace Corps, 164 Pell, Claiborne, 156, 159n. 81, 165n. 106, 200n. 47 Pepper, Claude, 161n. 87 Percy, Charles, 221 Perlman, Nathan, 79n. 133, 113n. 74, 124n. 144, 143 Persecution, 35 Pershing, General, 63 Phelan, James, 39n. 32, 45n. 74, 46, 48n. 89, 62n. 46, 72n. 96, 78n. 126 Philippines, 114–15, 165, 183, 218 Pinchot, Cornelia Bryce Gifford, 127n. 156 Pittenger, William, 114n. 76 Poage, William, 103n. 29, 115n. 84 Poland, 137, 174, 195, 197 Population: immigrants as a proportion of, 219; overpopulation in Europe and third world, 126, 152, 157, 163, 174, 189; overpopulation in U.S., 217; underpopulation in U.S., 157 Powell, Adam Clayton, 134 Power, distribution of, 245 Pressler, Lawrence, 203n. 57 Prohibition, 59 Proper, Edward, 32n. 1 Protectionism, 85, 98–99, 101–7, 280. See also Tariffs Proxmire, William, 165n. 110 Public charge provision, 69, 101, 107, 239 Public interest, 5, 14–17, 184, 241–44, 271, 276 Public opinion, 193, 233–35, 242 Purnell, Fred, 58n. 16 Quin, Percy, 63n. 53, 71n. 90 Quota Acts, 55–96, 220 Race, 192, 275; and citizens, 61; and civilization, 100; and cold war pro
388
Index
Race (continued) paganda, 145, 155, 156, 157; and discrimination among citizens, 52, 91; and identity cards, 225; and quota assignments, 51, 134 Racism, of enemy, 53, 118 Rainey, Lilius, 59n. 25 Raker, John, 41n. 43, 49, 61n. 38, 65, 72n. 94 Randolph, Jennings, 208 Rankin, John, 104n. 35, 127n. 160, 129n. 166, 129n. 167 Rarick, John, 189, 191n. 12 Rawls, John, 50 Reagan, Ronald, administration, 198, 214, 231 Realism, 18, 19, 246–47, 251–52, 256, 258, 265 Red hair, as reason for exclusion, 49 Reed, David, 69n. 79, 87n. 181, 90n. 185, 91n. 189, 91n. 190, 93n. 195 Reed, James, 50n. 101, 51n. 111, 61, 66n. 69, 66n. 71 Rees, Edward, 109n. 58, 137n. 203 Refugee Act of 1980, 256 Refugees: 52–53, 131, 147, 152, 153, 155–56, 167, 172, 179, 192, 194, 255; ›eeing from Nazis, 103–4; poll, 233 Regionalism, 183, 232, 238, 262. See also Voting Regulatory categories, 255–58 Reid, Ogden, 165n. 107, 174n. 161 Relatives, of U.S. citizens, 158, 180, 202, 220, 255–56, 263–64; poll, 235 Republican Party, 158, 175, 202, 204. See also Voting Resnick, David, 22n. 35 Revercomb, William Chapman, 131n. 183 Revolutionaries, immigrants as, 97–98 Reynolds, Robert, 98n. 6, 103, 105n. 40, 105n. 41, 105n. 42, 114n. 81 Ribicoff, Abraham, 169n. 130 Richardson, William, 200 Riegle, Donald, 193
Riemers, David, 4n. 10 Riggins, Stephen, 6n. 12 Riggs, Fred, 111n. 68 Robsion, John, 58n. 23, 72n. 93, 98, 99n. 10, 149n. 18 Rodino, Peter, 125n. 149, 137, 159n. 79, 161, 184, 192, 213n. 101, 221, 224 Rogers, John, 91n. 191 Romania, 8, 46, 85, 174, 275 Rome, 57, 114 Roosevelt, Franklin, 109, 177, 231 Roper polls, 233–35 Rosenau, James, 1n. 2 Rosenbloom, Benjamin, 57n. 14, 64n. 62 Rosenthal, Benjamin, 170n. 135 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 19 Roybal, Edward, 200n. 46, 218n. 134 Rudd, Eldon, 209, 210 Ruggie, John, 3n. 7, 7n. 18, 221n. 145, 248n. 6 Rusk, Dean, 153, 174n. 164 Russell, Lillian, 57 Russia, 71, 85, 123, 148. See also USSR Sabath, Adolph, 85n. 169 St. Germaine, Ferdinand, 156 Saltonstall, Leverett, 163n. 95, 165n. 112 Sanctuary movement, 187 Santangelo, Alfred, 170n. 138 Sassen, Saskia, 1n. 2 Scandinavians, 178 Schafer, John, 99n. 12 Schall, Thomas, 74n. 106 Scheuer, James, 210 Schroeder, Patricia, 219, 222 Schubert, Glendon, 15n. 13 Schuck, Peter, 19n. 27 Science, 74, 93 Scienti‹c exchange, 129 Self-preservation, 36, 41–42, 50 Shelby, Richard, 211n. 96
Index Shortridge, Samuel, 38, 46n. 76, 61n. 40, 61n. 45, 62n. 48, 65n. 68, 69n. 84, 71n. 88, 78n. 122, 78n. 123 Sickles, Carlton, 153n. 45 Siegel, Isaac, 51n. 109, 66n. 70, 67n. 73 Sikkink, Kathryn, 14 Simon, Paul, 189 Simon, Rita, 55n. 1, 233n. 3 Simpson, Alan, 200, 208, 209, 211, 213–14, 218 Singer, Peter, 22n. 36 Sisk, B. F, 189, 217 Sjaastad, Larry, 261n. 23 Slavs, 173 Slovenia, 84 Smith, Addison, 61n. 43 Smith, Ellison, 38n. 30, 81n. 145 Smith, H. Alexander, 151n. 35, 153n. 46 Smith, H. Allen, 148n. 14 Smith, Howard, 148n. 10 Smith, Lawrence, 114n. 80, 214n. 109 Smith, Rogers, 19n. 27 Smith, William French, 215 Snell, Bertrand, 42n. 49, 49n. 92 Snidal, Duncan, 247n. 5 Sonnenburg, Gustave, 47n. 82 South Africa, Cape Town, 135 Spain, 104 Specter, Arlen, 197, 202 Spring, Abe, 37 Sputnik, 165 Statelessness, 118 Steagall, Henry, 64n. 59 Steck, Daniel, 98n. 3, 98n. 8 Stefan, Karl, 129n. 169 Steiwer, Frederick, 101n. 26 Stengle, Charles, 42n. 55, 49n. 91, 76n. 110 Stennis, John, 168n. 123 Stephens, Hubert, 65n. 67 Stewart, Arthur, 106n. 44 Stimson, Henry, 20n. 30 Stoker, Laura, 17n. 16 Stone, Margaret, 121n. 126
389
Subversion, 62, 105, 128, 141, 148 Supreme Court, U.S., 3, 39–40, 41, 47, 63n. 52, 114, 216n. 120 Swanson, Claude, 48n. 90 Switzerland, 219 Symms, Steven, 194 Tague, Peter, 50n. 106 Tariffs, 42, 58, 96, 113, 252–55; in regression, 236. See also Protectionism Taxes, 99, 148, 218 Taylor, Will, 49n. 93, 60n. 31, 104n. 36, 128n. 161 Territory, 3–4 Terrorism, 193–94 Thailand, 165, 280 Thill, Lewis, 106n. 45, 106n. 46 Thompson, Frank, 186n. 204 Thomson, James, 33n. 7 Thomson, Janice, 1n. 2 Thurmond, Strom, 149, 216, 274 Tillman, John, 69n. 87 Tincher, J. N., 71n. 91 Todaro, Michael, 261n. 23 Torture, 197 Tourists, 203, 257, 259; as potential subversives, 105 Trade, 38; de‹cits in, 236; free, 151, 160; and nonimmigrant volume, 240, 257; volume of, 254 Tra‹cant, James, 200 Trammell, Park, 44n. 73 Trevor, John, 83n. 155 Trinidad and Tobago, 218 Truman, Harry, 112, 120n. 121, 126n. 153, 126n. 154, 131, 136n. 200, 153, 190–91 Turkey, 71, 74, 125, 136, 173, 282 Tversky, Amos, 13n. 6 Unemployment, 98, 102, 114–15, 117, 120, 167–68, 174, 184, 192, 215; data on 235–37. See also Labor USSR, 117, 127, 128, 139, 154, 167;
390
Index
USSR (continued ) “the Kremlin,” 127, 148, 161; Jewish refugees from, 188, 189. See also Cold war; Communism; Russia United Nations, 118, 127, 131, 263; San Francisco Conference, 122 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2–3 Universalism, 20–22, 49–50, 116, 262–63. See also Liberalism Utilitarians, 19–20, 204 Vaile, William, 38n. 28, 44n. 71, 58n. 22, 77 Venezuela, 152 Vestal, Albert, 43n. 63 Vietnam, 190, 197, 199; refugees from, 234, 256 Vietnam War, 146, 166, 187 Vinson, Fred, 57n. 10 Virus, immigrants as, 57–58 Voorhis, Horace, 108n. 51 Vorys, John, 115n. 83, 137 Voting, 63, 90, 132, 134, 181, 183, 192; partisanship and regionalism in, 287–94 Voting Rights Act, 169 Walsh, David, 39n. 35, 85n. 173, 123n. 140 Walter, Francis, 129n. 170, 135, 147, 171 Waltz, Kenneth, 246n. 2 Walzer, Michael, 19 Ward, Robert DeC., 82 Watkins, Arthur, 163n. 101 Watkins, Elton, 77n. 120 Watkins, John, 39n. 33 Weber, Max, 11n. 1 Wefald, Knut, 82n. 150
Weiner, Myron, 111n. 68 Weiss, Theodore, 200 Welfare: domestic, 217–18, 270; global, 63–66; immigrants on, 167 Welch, Richard, 100n. 23 Welker, Herman, 154n. 51, 154n. 52 Welty, B. F., 69n. 86 Wendt, Alexander, 7n. 18 Western hemisphere, 68, 125–26, 176–78, 253, 255–57, 279; Latin America, 177; pan-Americanism, 86–88. See also Monroe Doctrine Westphalia, Treaty of, 2 Whelan, Frederick, 20 White, Richard, 215n. 117 Wiley, Alexander, 155n. 54 Williams, John, 69n. 82, 69n. 83, 82n. 151 Williamson, John, 115n. 87, 116n. 90 Wilson, Joseph, 148n. 12 Wilson, Riley, 43, 44n. 69, 69n. 85, 74n. 103 Wilson, Robert, 191 Wilson, Woodrow, 35n. 13 Woodhouse, Chase Going, 130n. 176 Works, John, 42, 69 World War I, 36, 50, 52, 56, 62, 64, 67, 78, 79, 101; allies, 84; evidence for U.S. strength 79, 84; and immigrants’ loyalties, 81 World War II, 177; and allies, 109, 121–22, 133; and ideology, 110–12, 119 Wriston, Walter, 1n. 2 Young, Stephen, 169n. 133 Yugoslavia, 85, 125, 282 Zolberg, Aristide, 4n. 8, 33n. 4, 248n. 7