HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
What are the lessons of history for the study of international politics? Do intern...
186 downloads
4509 Views
3MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
What are the lessons of history for the study of international politics? Do international relations scholars twist history? Are historians antiquarians? This book is a major contribution to the debate about philosophy and method in history and international relations. Thomas W.Smith draws on insights from historiographic theory and analyzes international relations scholarship from classical realism to structural, quantitative, and postmodernist work. The study highlights often licentious historical methods in international relations, as well as convergence between the disciplines in style, method, and paradigmatic focus. Topics covered include: • • • • • •
interpretation and the politics of history; anecdotalism, selection bias, and theoretical filtering; use and abuse of history in foreign policy; structural and quantitative history; postmodernist history and politics; historical skepticism and international relations theory.
Smith argues that much of international relations—in theory and practice —rests on narrow and often deterministic readings of history. He shows how historical construction and interpretation chip away at scientific renderings of international politics. This skeptical view of history illuminates international relations as a realm of contingency and moral choice. Thomas W.Smith is Assistant Professor of International Relations at Koç University, Istanbul.
ROUTLEDGE ADVANCES IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS AND POLITICS 1 FOREIGN POLICY AND DISCOURSE ANALYSIS France, Britain and Europe Henrik Larsen 2 AGENCY, STRUCTURE AND INTERNATIONAL POLITICS From ontology to empirical enquiry Gil Friedman and Harvey Starr 3 THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF REGIONAL COOPERATION IN THE MIDDLE EAST Ali Carkoglu, Mine Eder, Kemal Kirisci 4 PEACE MAINTENANCE The evolution of international political authority Jarat Chopra 5 INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS AND HISTORICAL SOCIOLOGY Breaking down boundaries Stephen Hobden 6 EQUIVALENCE IN COMPARATIVE POLITICS Edited by Jan W. van Deth 7 THE POLITICS OF CENTRAL BANKS Robert Elgie and Helen Thompson 8 POLITICS IN A GLOBALIZED WORLD Martin Shaw 9 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Thomas W.Smith 10 IDEALISM AND REALISM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Robert M.A.Crawford
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Thomas W.Smith
London and New York
First published 1999 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group
"To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge's collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk." This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. © 1999 Thomas W.Smith All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Smith, Thomas W., 1962– History and international relations/Thomas W.Smith p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. International relations. 2. History. I Title JZ1242.S64 1999 327.1’ 01–dc21 98–51213CIP ISBN 0-203-20124-8 Master e-book ISBN
ISBN 0-203-26580-7 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0-415-17865-7 (Print Edition)
FOR MY PARENTS
CONTENTS
Acknowledgments
vii
1
Introduction
1
2
The historical problem in international relations
7
3
History, contingency, and the roots of realism: Reinhold Niebuhr and E.H.Carr
33
4
History, analogy, and policy realism: Hans J.Morgenthau and George F.Kennan
59
5
The poverty of ahistoricism: Kenneth N.Waltz and neorealist theory
89
6
“The importance of being scientific”: J.David Singer and the correlates of war
115
7
Exit from history? Postmodern international relations
143
8
Conclusion: history, skepticism, and the recovery of theory
173
Notes
185
References
191
Index
211
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I wish first to thank Kenneth W.Thompson, Michael Joseph Smith, David C.Jordan, Norman A.Graebner, and Dante Germino for directing this study when it was my doctoral thesis at the University of Virginia. I also wish to thank my friends and colleagues for their help and support: Alice Ba, Stephen Calabrese, Andrew Clem, Desmond Dewsnap, Cary Federman, Daniel Landis, Amy Nagle, Christopher Sabatini, Thomas Sakats, Ilter Turan, Scott Waalkes, Helga Welsh, and Marshal Zeringue. I would also like to thank James A. Smith, Jr. for his encouraging comments on a draft of Chapter 3; Paul W. Schroeder for his remarks on Chapter 5; J.David Singer, who took time from his busy schedule to discuss Chapter 6 with me; and Patrick Yott, of the Alderman Library Social Science Data Center at the University of Virginia, for his assistance, also with Chapter 6. The errors and infelicities that remain are my own. A special thanks is due Deniz Bingöl, my research assistant at Koç University, whose hard work and good cheer were invaluable in the final stages of this project. I gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the Earhart Foundation, the Institute for the Study of World Politics, the Miller Center of Public Affairs and the Woodrow Wilson Department of Government and Foreign Affairs at the University of Virginia, and the College of Administrative Sciences and Economics at Koç University. The discussion of Michael Oakeshott in Chapter 2 was originally published in “Michael Oakeshott on History, Practice, and Political Theory,” History of Political Thought, 17 (1996), pp. 591–614. Copyright ©, Imprint Academic, Exeter, United Kingdom. The Reinhold Niebuhr material in Chapter 3 first appeared in “The Uses of Tragedy: Reinhold Niebuhr’s Theory of History and International Ethics,” Ethics and International Affairs, 9 (1995), pp. 171–91. Copyright ©, Carnegie Council on Ethics and International Affairs, New York. The section in Chapter 4 devoted to George Kennan was first published in “Historical Learning and the Setting of Foreign Policy: The Case of George F. Kennan,” Miller Center Journal, 4 (1997), pp. 95–105. Copyright ©, Miller Center of Public Affairs, University of Virginia, Charlottesville, Virginia. They are reprinted here with permission.
1 INTRODUCTION
Out of our conceptions of the past, we make a future. Hobbes (1994:32) “The past,” the great skeptic of British philosophy Michael Oakeshott once noted, is “a field in which we exercise our moral and political opinions, like whippets in a meadow on a Sunday afternoon” (Oakeshott 1962:166). Prompted by Oakeshott’s critique of history-as-ideology, this study scrutinizes international relations theory and research across the methodological spectrum from classical realism to quantitative and postmodernist work. Perhaps because it is a child of history, international relations, as it has developed, has tried to distance itself from historical discourse, through methodological and theoretical innovations seeking general knowledge about international and global politics. In this flight from the old ways of history, researchers have tended to downplay the historical content of their own work, and, at times, to embrace an easy historical empiricism. This uncritical view of the past has contributed to an often licentious historical method, with history serving less as an independent body of evidence than as a trove to be plundered, and which in the discipline’s most scientific work saddles history with more certainty than it can bear. The historical problem is to some extent inherent in the material. As Hans Morgenthau noted in an opening passage of Politics Among Nations (1948), The most formidable difficulty facing a scientific inquiry into the nature and ways of international politics is the ambiguity of the material with which the observer has to deal.… The first lesson the student of international politics must learn and never forget is that the complexities of international affairs make simple solutions and trustworthy prophecies impossible. It is here that the scholar and the charlatan part company… In every political situation contradictory tendencies are at play…which tendency actually will prevail is anybody’s guess. The best the scholar can do, then, is to trace the different tendencies which, as potentialities, are inherent in a certain international situation. (Morgenthau 1948:4–6)
2 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Quincy Wright, an early advocate of the quantitative study of international politics and one of the field’s greatest interdisciplinarians, had especially kind words for history. He noted that “in their emphasis on contingency [historians] provide a healthy antidote to the overenthusiastic social scientist,” and that an appreciation of history lent the student of war a balanced sense of continuity and change, of uniqueness and repetition, of causation and contingency, and of choice and standards. He can better realize the complexity and uncertainty of human affairs, the many factors to be considered in making judgments, the dangers of abstraction, of dogmatism, of prediction, of action, and of inaction. He can better understand the abundance and variability of human values and the opportunities as well as the insecurities of any situation. (Wright 1955:87, 89) Now more frequently cast in the mold of political science, students of international politics have largely abandoned these earlier ideas about the nature of history and the limits that history suggests for social science research. Today, “rigorous,” often grand, historical models are the norm, as is routine disregard for the problems of historical discourse. The historical problem: an overview In its most basic outline, the historical problem in the field of international relations comprises epistemology, ideology, and sociology. Epistemologically, history turns out to be an indispensable, but fickle, research partner. It is decidedly not the independent body of evidence touted by Leopold von Ranke (1874: vii) as history “as it really was” (wie es eigentlich gewesen ist). If getting history right is “like nailing jelly to the wall,” as Peter Novick suggests in his highly controversial, meticulously documented That Noble Dream: The “Objectivity Question” and the American Historical Profession (1988:1), then the use of history in social science is no less challenging. Plunging into the historical literature, the researcher is quickly enmeshed in lively debate over description and explanation. History turns out to be not so much an archival puzzle, whose parts eventually fall neatly into place, than a patchwork of often incongruous facts and more or less plausible inferences, interpretations, and impressions. This is particularly the case as the historian moves into the realm of meaning and causality. As Stanley Hoffmann has argued (1987: 455), “many different readings of the same reality are possible. Even if all historians agreed on the facts, they would still disagree on the respective weight of those facts; in the act of ‘imaginative reconstruction’ that any causal analysis performs, assessments of motivation and causal efficiency vary considerably.” Ideologically, history is ripe for partisan selection and interpretation. As the theorist constructs and reconstructs histories, allying inquiry with one interpretive
INTRODUCTION 3
school and carefully ignoring others, the findings risk being dictated or distorted by individual ideological or intellectual commitments. In place of searching historical inquiry, we get a lawyer’s brief that confuses evidence and advocacy. In terms of sociology, the customs and conventions of international relations have increasingly fostered a kind of heedlessness toward historical questions. It has become standard practice to brandish easy anecdotes and analogies, pursue ahistorical, stand-alone theory, or else to approach the “history” part of the enterprise as merely a formal testing stage on the road to theory. This is symptomatic of a broader affliction in the field. Yosef Lapid (1989:249–50) suggests that, for many years, international relations has held “the dubious honor of being among the least self-reflexive of the Western social sciences.” Most debate in the discipline takes place within a“positivist” framework; it is assumed that rationally justified assertions about the “essential” nature of politics can be scientifically verified by observing its historical manifestations. Critics of theory and history generally respond with theory and history of their own, in what often becomes an all-ornothing contest of evidence and ideas. Rarer are examinations of the field’s underlying assumptions and methods, particularly regarding the historical evidence itself, or the field’s roots in social science. Most of the historical challenges described in this study fall within the following categories: Selection bias: as the title of Barbara Geddes’s article (1990) states, “the cases you choose affect the answers you get.” This is the overarching problem in historical usage across the social sciences. Selection bias can be systematic, resulting from shoddy research; or it can be instrumental, aimed at promoting a particular theoretical position. Partisan selection bias is usually accompanied by the sin of omission of studiously avoiding unhelpful history. In all social science research, potential alternative explanations often reside in sources not enlisted or data not collected. Anecdotalism generalizes from carefully chosen particulars. This is often more of a didactic tool than a research method, as the theorist airily presents handpicked events and narratives in order to corroborate his/her ideas. Analogies may be anecdotal as well, as the scholar or policymaker sees current dilemmas closely mirrored in the past. Although it is a sub-set of selection bias, the anecdotal fallacy is so prevalent as to warrant special mention. Ahistoricism promotes political theory emptied of content and context, often in an effort to sidestep the idiosyncrasies of political choice and the processes of change. Theorists may also be ahistorical in failing to recognize the impact of moment et milieu on their own research, thus presenting historically contingent constructs as timeless laws of politics. The field is ahistorical as well in its focus on contemporary history and policy issues (Buzan and Little 1994:233–4), and in its tendency to read the present back into the past. Theoretical filtering interprets history through one’s theoretical lens. This practice is to some degree unavoidable: history needs theory to lend it coherence. At the extreme, theoretical filtering produces tautological research, undermining history’s
4 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
role as an independent source of corroboration or falsification, as the case may be. Theoretical filtering is related to the quantitative fallacy as well, which arises when statistical methods propel research in a particular substantive direction. In postmodern work, a fixation on diversity and difference may prove so fine a filter that any similarities across historical periods or event are lost, thus walling off the past from the present. Cathedrals of clay: here one constructs theories of painstaking precision as though the medium of research were Carrara marble rather than the softer stuff of history. This fallacy is common among quantitative researchers, who assume a tight affinity between historical data and history as it really was. Statistical methods allow for a great deal of sophistication and precision in research and theory, yet this precision may overstep the archival and historiographic evidence on which quantitative data are based. Bridging history and international relations Three preliminary comments may be made about work that attempts to bridge the disciplines of history and international relations. First, although some political scientists are loath to admit it, historians, at their best, are the furthest thing from antiquarians. Not only do historians interpret culture and politics with originality and flair, they also bear the daunting task of dismantling myths and preserving the past from ideology and oblivion. The adage goes that history can be written well only in a free country. By the same token, historians are in no small way guardians of the open society. “Why do ruling classes fear history?,” asks Harvey Kaye (1996). Anyone who has read Orwell, Kundera, or Koestler, or who knows the story of Picasso’s Guernica, understands that people in power invariably espouse a certain view of history. Some dictators have literally turned history into fiction, creating an “official story” out of whole cloth, or airbrushing politically inconvenient people from its pages. More subtly, states propagate heroic historical myths about themselves, viewing past wars, for example, as cleansing, redemptive struggles. Political leaders may cultivate what A.D.Smith (1995:63) terms “ethnohistory,” an amalgam of selective historical truth and idealization, in order to create and control political identity (see also Hobsbawm 1993). In one way or another, ideological history depicts the past merely as a sort of ante room opening onto the political present. The free hand of the historian and the unencumbered hurly-burly of historical argument are the surest safeguards against these abuses. It was not for nothing that Khrushchev is reputed to have said, “Historians are dangerous, and capable of turning everything topsyturvy. They have to be watched” (quoted in Owen 1995:3). Warts and all, historical research and debate help to preserve integrity in politics. Second, it should come as no surprise that history is a dynamic enterprise, constantly being rethought and rewritten. In the past few years alone, a flap erupted over how the Smithsonian Institution in Washington, DC should represent, fifty years on, the Enola Gay bombing of Hiroshima; Robert McNamara published an
INTRODUCTION 5
apologia for his lies that had spurred on the war in Vietnam; rather more ambiguous evidence has emerged concerning the Gulf War, undercutting what was at the time a tightly scripted portrayal of events; emerging from their forced hibernation, national historiographies are resurfacing in Eastern Europe and the former Soviet republics; in Moscow, the Soviet archives were ceremoniously opened at the end of the cold war, yet since that time access to the documents has been severely restricted; the stock of past presidents and prime ministers rises and falls on the tides of historical argument and evidence; under the pall of special prosecutors, state papers in some countries are probably more sanitized than ever; even the venerable American State Department series, Foreign Relations of the United States, has possibly become the source of disinformation, its editors declaring that their own government tampered with, and denied them, important evidence. There is little reason to believe that the current state of historical evidence and judgment is definitive or final. This itself would signal the end of history. Lately, “historical revisionism” has become a pejorative term, used first in reaction to Marxist interpretations of the origins of the cold war, and, more recently, in the backlash against postmodern relativism in social and cultural studies (see Windschuttle 1997). At times, revisionist history is plainly pernicious. Issue after issue of the upright-sounding Journal of Historical Review, for example, carries “debate” about the “Holocaust myth.” Presumably, the publication’s high-minded banner (“bringing history into accord with the facts”) and its use of a sturdy, oldfashioned type for its masthead, are supposed to lend plausibility to its vile assertions. During the cold war, official Polish history had little to say about the massacre of Polish officers in the forest near Katyn by the Soviets in 1940 “until a joint Polish-Soviet commission charged with filling in historical ‘blank spots’… declared it to be history” (Blok 1992:122). For reasons related to state security and national unity, many historians in Turkey have for decades denied that a separate or overlapping Kurdish identity may exist within the country’s borders. Until only very recently, Kurds were known euphemistically as “Mountain Turks.” Historical revisionism is not always wrong, however. In many ways, revision is the lifeblood of the historian’s craft, as old verities are revisited, beliefs change, new documents and other artifacts are disclosed, and innovative inter pretive models are employed (Gaddis 1997b: preface and Leffler 1995). This seems especially true when it comes to recent and contemporary political history. There is a certain timeliness and relevance attached to contemporary accounts, as historians attempt to bring coherence to the chaos of current events. Nevertheless, there are perils as well in passing historical judgment even as “the eggs are frying,” as Hemingway once noted in one of his front-line dispatches during the Spanish Civil War. Judgments will almost certainly change when viewed with the clarity and insight that often come with historical distance and detachment. Finally, when working at the intersection of politics and history it is helpful to recall that the “disciplines” are contrived. Each represents a voice and method of discourse that provide a coherent framework for making intelligible one facet of experience. In their eagerness to erect academic walls, however, the disciplines risk
6 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
isolating themselves, in effect shattering human experience. Fortunately, the social sciences resist this tendency. As the great social science historian Fernand Braudel notes (1980:25–6), “the social sciences force themselves on each other, each trying to capture society as a whole, in its ‘totality.’ Each science encroaches on its neighbors, all the while believing it is staying in its own domain.” Events in one realm reverberate in others. Economics spills over into politics, and vice versa; anthropology, psychology, and linguistics borrow and trade ideas; history adopts insights and problems from its neighbors, and reflects them back again. This process is, of course, congenial to liberal learning. This book traces the combative intimacy of two disciplines having a great deal in common, yet struggling to maintain their separate identities. I hope it will be clear just how much students of international relations are indebted to historians, and vice versa, and how connected the two disciplines are in method, style, and content, and in terms of the paradigms guiding their ideas. In many ways, the similarities between the fields are more striking than the differences. My hope in this study is to elucidate in a single argument a central problem of method and content across a very diverse discipline. The theories and research explored here represent a wide range of approaches to history in international politics, including philosophical, theological, inductive, policy-oriented, deductive, quantitative, and postmodernist work. The theorists and projects under review are also widely regarded as the finest exemplars of their respective method, thus providing the most rigorous “defense” of each against the author’s skepticism. The chapters flow chronologically. They also move, generally, from contingent views of history toward nomothetic political science analysis, before lapsing into the kaleidoscope histories of postmodernism. If any strand of international thought is not represented here (and many important ones are not), it is for reasons of space and because of the breadth of the field. Given the broad sweep of the study, some of the approaches that are treated will no doubt be given short shrift. I ask the reader’s indulgence for these shortcomings, as no slight is intended.
2 THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Ian Lustick has encouraged students of politics to confront “the largely (now) uncontested claim that the work of historians is not understood by historians to be, and cannot legitimately be treated by others as, an unproblematic background narrative from which theoretically neutral data can be elicited for the framing of problems and testing of theories” (Lustick 1996:605). The problem, as Benedetto Croce once noted, is that simple chronicle is but the “corpse of history,” il cadavere, for “history without interpretation is history without the historical problem” (quoted in Florovsky 1969:353–4). Because it rests on inference of things past, historical thought is bound up in a web of prejudice and politics and honest disputes over ambiguous evidence. The effect, most fundamentally, is that there are histories, not history. While history is the only “empirical” evidence theorists of international politics can exploit, a diversity of interpretations would seem to support an array of theories, even contradictory ones.1 This is a difficult notion for theorists and researchers in the discipline of international relations, who have long turned to historical writings as a source of insight and a field of evidence in which to test their ideas. James Bryce argued in International Relations (1922: vi–vii), “It is history which, recording the events and explaining the influences that have molded the minds of men, shows us how the world of international politics has come to be what it is. History is the best—indeed the only—guide to a comprehension of the facts as they stand.” Updating this idea, Bruce Bueno de Mesquita (1996: 53) notes that “For the social scientist the events of history are a laboratory in which to test their claims about how variables are associated with each other; to test their theoretical propositions about causation.” As either political backdrop or behavioral laboratory, history is never far removed from international theory and research. When theory is constructed from the bottom up, history provides the building blocks. When theory is built from the top down, history serves to test or falsify theoretical concepts. Case studies are focused, comparative historical analyses. The learning and institutionalist literature is explicitly historical and evolutionary. When quantitatively oriented researchers speak of “events data” or “data-making,” they are referring to historical representations abstracted from a welter of evidence. Normative theorists stress the historical context of moral action. Marxist theorists seek to uncover the hidden histories upon which international theory is founded, while postmodernists point
8 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
out privileged views of the past that have shaped the discipline. Marxists and postmodernists criticize conventional interpretations of history, yet both are at pains to use history against traditional theory to reveal its contingent character. Formal theory, including game theory, is perhaps the most ahistorical of theoretical approaches, yet increasingly it too is being put to the historical test. Nor is the historical canon in international relations particularly slim. The Victorian historian and politician John Seeley argued that history was “a school for statesmen” on the claim that “History is past politics and politics present history” (quoted in Stern 1973:199). This sentiment underpinned the alliance at the turn of the century between diplomatic history and the emerging discipline of international relations. Today, most students of international politics still turn to event-centered military, diplomatic, or imperial history, such as those by Thucydides, Guicciardini, Fénelon, Albrecht-Carrié, Gulick, Kagan, Howard, and Gaddis; or to the theory-rich “world” histories of Toynbee, Dehio, McNeill, Kennedy, and others. A third traditional focus is on the philosophical “histories” of Smith, Kant, Gibbon, Marx, Spengler, Halle, Fukuyama and others. However, the emergence of new theories and approaches has opened new realms of historiography beyond the standard repertoire of “high” political history. Increasingly, researchers are drawn to the “slow-time” history advocated by the Annales school, accounts of civilizations, cultures, and other non-Westphalian (i.e. based on the European nation-state model) polities, as well as many of the rapidly expanding universe of “new” social and economic histories: of technology, trade, labor, demography, ethnicity, institutions, ideas, popular culture, customs, norms, and so forth. Christopher Hill (1985:141–2) notes of this eclecticism in historical usage, “in some respects international relations in the United States tends to be closer to history than it is in Britain, where the subject is generally thought to be ‘traditionalist,’ i.e., heavily historical.” History, theory, and epistemology As Peter Burke (1992a: 1) has noted, the relation between history and social theory is “deceptively simple.” To begin with, “history” is an ambiguous word. It refers to the aggregate of past events in general, or to the train of events connected with a particular place, person, culture, mentality, etc. But history also refers to attempts to represent or re-create those pasts. History may take the form of chronicle, annals, narrative, tale, story, or statistical analysis. The ancient Greeks thought of history as a learning or knowing by inquiry, and believed that it could be either true or imaginary. Today, history is generally taken to be true, even scientific, in its methods and claims, yet it can also be seen as artistic or novelistic. It may center on events or on broader social, cultural, or economic traces or trends. It may be presented as happenstance or determined, as a seamless web or a series of discrete periods. It may be didactic or belletristic. It may be politically engaged or value-free. Social theory is only slightly less ambiguous. As Raymond Aron (1967:2) explains, theory may be considered either as “contemplative knowledge, drawn from ideas or from
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 9
the basic order of the world…the equivalent of philosophy,” or as “a hypothetical, deductive system consisting of a group of hypotheses whose terms are strictly defined and whose relationships between terms (or variables) are most often given mathematical form.” Thus, one should bear in mind that different kinds of historians turn to theory for different reasons, just as different theorists use history for a variety of ends. Even within the disciplines, assumptions, methods, and “needs” vary markedly. However, it is interesting to note that across disciplines these differences often fade. A diplomatic historian may have more in common with a realist theorist than with an environmental historian. A postmodern theorist will identify more with a social historian than a classical liberal theorist. Such methodological and ideological differences probably divide social research more than any real or imagined disciplinary walls. It is difficult to assign respective “roles” to social scientists and historians because they so rarely stay within them. Certainly the dichotomies customarily employed to distinguish history from political science—particular/ general, explanation/understanding, nomothetic/idiographic, narrative-based/ theory-based, presentist/antiquarian, policy-relevant/ivory towerish, active/contemplative, theoretical/empirical, and so on—are belied by the diversity and overlap of the fields. Still, theory and history both have their limits, and here the fields stand to complement each other: Historians and social theorists have the opportunity to free each other from different kinds of parochialism. Historians run the risk of parochialism in an almost literal sense of the term. Specializing as they usually do in a particular region, they may come to regard their “parish” as completely unique, rather than a unique combination of elements each one of which has parallels elsewhere. Social theorists display parochialism in a more metaphorical sense, a parochialism of time rather than place, when they generalize about “society” on the basis of contemporary experience alone, or discuss social change without taking long-term processes into account. (Burke 1992a:2) Despite these converging interests, acrimony between the history and international relations disciplines, in particular, seems to be the norm. Some theorists revel in the belief that their craft was built upon the lifeless body of history. They see historians as antiquarians lacking in any rigorous methodology, or worse, as deceivers who conceal the assumptions and models guiding their narratives. Alternatively, historians are thought simply to line up the facts. Political scientists then step forward with their dynamic methods and put the facts to relevant use. Some historians respond with disdain for the “baseless” designs of international theory. Christopher Thorne, for one, mocks international relations’ loftier abstractions as “super-rational exercises,” “divorced from the complexities provided
10 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
by historical evidence; riding high into a quasitheological stratosphere; delivered in an unlovely tongue” (Thorne 1988:6–7). Students of international politics have offered similar critiques of their own field. Martin Wight (1966:32) notes: It may seem puzzling that, while the acknowledged classics of political study are the political philosophers, the only acknowledged counterpart in the study of international relations is Thucydides, a work of history. And that the quality of international politics, the preoccupations of diplomacy, are embodied and communicated less in works of political or international theory than in historical writings… It is not simply that historical literature is doing a different job from systems analysis. Historical literature at the same time does the same job—the job of offering a coherent structure of hypotheses that will provide a common explanation of phenomena; but it does the job with more judiciousness and modesty, and with closer attention to the record of international experience. Writing in 1972, Hedley Bull maintained that the theoretical literature on international politics “illuminates the subject more than the literature of diplomatic history.” Yet, he added, If we compare the historical with the theoretical study of international relations it is clear that the literature of diplomatic history is still of more evenly high quality, that the standards of the historian’s profession are more clearly discernible, his canons of judgements less open to dispute, his territory less encroached upon by the crank or the charlatan, the imparting of his knowledge and techniques more clearly by itself an education. (Bull 1972:32) In recent years, several high profile cases have reinforced stereotypes about history and theory. Francis Fukuyama’s (1992) “end of history” thesis and Samuel Huntington’s (1996) “clash of civilizations” idea, for example, were met with a stream of derision from historians (and many theorists) critical of their grand claims about the past and future of world politics. These criticisms, like most clichés about history and theory, tend to exaggerate tensions between the two fields. Though sometimes marching in different methodological directions, history and international relations remain cognate disci plines. Indeed, across a vast middle, students of history and politics are doing much the same thing: trying to explain and/or understand events and their underlying causes, often with an eye toward the future. Also, one cannot help but notice the parallel development of international relations and international history since mid-century: from unit-level analyses of foreign policies to the study of international systems; from a focus on great powers to the effects of revolutions and popular movements; from narrative to economic and statistical emphases, and back to narrative; from discrete studies
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 11
of domestic and foreign politics to synthesis of the two; from statist approaches to global ones; to a growing interest in the social underpinnings of politics. Along the way theorists have been steady—if sometimes selective—consumers of historiography, at times doing their own archival work and historical construction. Conversely, diplomatic historians, but also historians of culture, civilization, and globalization, have profited from international relations theory. Gordon Craig (1983:9) acknowledges a debt to theorists for encouraging historians to seek correlations and comparisons across cases with an eye toward prediction. John Lewis Gaddis (1990:422) advocates and practices what he calls interdisciplinary “bumping,” of ideas and criticisms. Melvyn Leffler (1995:179) does not shackle his work to any single model, but nevertheless professes to be “more and more impressed with the utility of theory,” noting how different theories “illuminate prospective causal relationships and interactions” that might otherwise have been left unexplored. The epistemology gap What has not bridged the disciplines, however, is concern about the nature and uses of historical knowledge itself. Philosophers of history do attempt to address the limits of historical claims. In international relations, however, the historical problem is often glossed over or ignored. This book should make clear the extent to which mainstream theorists strip history of its thorny dilemmas, and essentially treat ambiguous historical evidence unambiguously. The laboratory idea of history, in particular, seems rooted in the positivist philosophy of society associated with Hume, Condorcet, Saint-Simon, Spencer, and, above all, Auguste Comte. Comte argued that we “have to contemplate social phenomena as susceptible of prevision, like all other classes, within the limits of exactness compatible with their higher complexity.” Social scientists must “abandon the region of metaphysical idealities, to assume the ground of observed realities by a systematic subordination of imagination to observation,” on grounds that “there is no chance of order and agreement but in subjecting social phenomena, like all others, to invariable natural laws.” Ultimately for Comte, the task of social science was to “introduc[e] into the study of social phenomena the same positive spirit which has regenerated every other branch of human speculation” (quoted in Gee 1950:161–2). Perhaps because international relations has developed along generally positivist lines, problems of historiography and the validity of its use by theorists have been neglected in favor of more tractable questions regarding research method and design. As Nevil Johnson notes in The Limits of Political Science (1989:29), in the midst of this preoccupation with method, history has too often served merely as a “dignified background” to an outwardly scientific methodology, yet that epistemologically the whole project “hangs in the air.” Debate about history often centers on how best to tease out the laws, patterns, tendencies, trends, and probabilities of political behavior, how large a sample of historical evidence is adequate to test a hypothesis, the choice of case studies and the fit of analogies,
12 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
even the finer points of coding The New York Times (Puchala 1990). Several chapter titles in Richard Neustadt and Ernest May’s Thinking in Time (1986) typify this attitude: “Dodging bothersome analogues,” “Inspecting issue history,” “Finding history that fits,” “Noticing patterns.” Despite its pivotal role in building and testing theory, historiography is quite often treated as given, with causality fixed, and disputes over evidence and interpretation resolved. “History” becomes bedrock of knowledge to be quarried and applied. The theorist seems mainly concerned with locating the richest vein, choosing his picks and shovels, and exhibiting the gems he selects to greatest advantage. This methodological veneer obscures a raft of crucial questions. Is history, as Edmund Burke (1989:155) said, “a great volume…unrolled for our instruction?” Or is it “not so much a series of events as a magic mirror where everyone sees what he wants?” (Thorne 1983:123). What does it mean to ground theory in history? How autonomously do theorists treat historical knowledge? Is the theorist’s evidence rigged? Are facts subordinated to ideology? How strictly do readings of history govern theory’s causal, predictive, and normative tasks? One study of historiography concludes that our understanding of the past is dominated by a complacent, Anglo-centered view of history as “the progress of natural rights and democratic governance” (Appleby et al. 1994:107–16). Is international relations an accomplice here? A broader problem lies in the tension between historical understanding and social science explanation. The historian’s concern is thought to be with the particulars of specific events, with adherence to milieu et moment, while theoretical pronouncements are seen to point to general explanations and predictions of world politics. How does the theorist wrap his mind around a class of phenomena without doing violence to the differences inherent in the material? Another problem is simply interpretive. As one scholar notes, No matter how detailed and thorough an historical inquiry may be, it certainly cannot leave us with a unique correlation between the various empirical variables which will force all observers to make identical inferences and conclusions. Instead the available evidence allows for a number of more or less plausible interpretations. (Njølstad 1990:223)
History—like politics—elicits more than its fair share of criticism. Aristotle believed that poetry was more philosophical and of higher value than history. Goethe called meaning and direction history “the most absurd of all things,” a “web of nonsense for the higher thinker” (quoted in Löwith 1949: 53). The OED cites Matthew Arnold’s reference to that “huge Mississippi of falsehood called history.” Oscar Wilde once remarked that the only duty we have to history is to rewrite it. The skepticism underpinning this study is meant to be constructive. To be sure, history is an imperfect craft. As Paul Veyne points out (1984:3–14), history can be
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 13
a “true” account, but ultimately that account is based on “mutilated knowledge,” on more or less pronounced “traces” of the past. Ernst Cassirer described in The Philosophy of the Enlightenment (1962) the eighteenth-century transformation of scientific inquiry from the Cartesian esprit de système, which sought to resolve fundamental problems of existence and epistemology through abstract reason, to a more modest esprit systématique, which in place of unequivocal answers held out a methodology of hypothesis, testing, and inference. Some of historiography’s most ardent critics, particularly postmodern ones, set historical study beside a Cartesian ideal in place of the more humble modern standards. An extreme Foucauldian view holds that the historian is absolutely shackled by politics and prejudice, that history is an exercise in power and domination. This is a forceful, but probably minority view, even among postmodernists. Yet, as Carlo Ginzburg has noted, rather than treating artifacts as a potential “window,” however imperfect, on the past, some critics turn historical evidence into “a wall which by definition precludes any access to reality.” Holding history to an absolutist scientific standard amounts to a sort of “inverted positivism” employed to repudiate all historical understanding (Ginzburg 1991:83). Avenues to history: correspondence and construction A brief tour d’horizon of the historical problem in international relations behind us, this section sets out two ways of understanding history: Ranke’s formulation of history “as it really was,” and Michael Oakeshott’s constructionist theory of history. These two approaches to history and their respective interpreters are considered seminal by historical epistemologists. The section is foundational to my overall argument in that it frames a debate about the nature of historical knowledge from which international theorists, judging from their often naive use of history, have too often been sheltered. Ranke and correspondence Almost every major debate in contemporary historiographic theory takes as its starting point Leopold von Ranke’s “critical method” of sophisticated archival technique and non-judgmental style. Ranke advocated above all else the autonomy of historical inquiry from moral and political values. In the preface to his first book, History of the Latin and Teutonic Nations From 1494 to 1514 (1887) he wrote: “History has had assigned to it the office of judging the past and of instructing the present for the benefit of future ages. To such high offices the present work does not presume; it seeks only to show history as it really was” (wie es eigentlich gewesen ist).2 History “as it really was.” This is probably the most quoted phrase about historiography. The statement is generally seen as a manifesto for a positivist or scientific approach to history. Called by one biographer (Krieger 1977:3) the “Copernicus” of historical knowledge, Ranke envisioned the historian’s task as that of dispassionately presenting the “objective nature of the great facts…free from the
14 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
mutual accusations of the contemporaries and the often restricted view of their posterity” (Iggers and Moltke 1973:150). This “strict representation” of the facts, “be it ever so narrow and unpoetical, is, beyond doubt, the first law” (Ranke 1887: vi). Apart from this, the historian would banish himself from his books. As Ranke wrote in his History of England (1875), in it he had tried “to extinguish my own self. to let the things speak and the mighty forces appear which have arisen in the course of the centuries” (Krieger 1977:5).3 Ranke aspired to a method that sharply separated subject and object, fact and value, history and fiction. For Ranke, the historian was no mere compiler or collator of data, but in weaving a narrative the historian was thought literally to re-create the past. Ranke saw historiography as corresponding to a series of actual past events that exist independent of historical thought and writing. As he noted in one essay, “We should be satisfied with simple information—satisfied that it merely corresponds to the object” (Iggers and Moltke 1973:39–40). The appendix to History of the Latin and Teutonic Nations, “In Criticism of Modern Historians,” made Ranke’s reputation as an historiographic theorist. In it, Ranke reproached historians for writing histories cobbled together from other histories. He catalogued a number of errors, plagiarisms, and deceptions in the works of Machiavelli, Guicciardini, and other Renaissance historians and memoirists (the latter more likely to engage in self-acquittal and score-settling than balanced reporting), and suggested that the reliance of latter-day historians on such contemporary accounts had perpetuated myths and misstatements from the Renaissance. Ranke taught that the critical historian must instead focus on the primary sources, testing and vetting historical accounts against the facts as embodied in the documents. The result of these researches would be “essential” history, concrete, and value-free (Unparteilichkeit). Ranke believed that this plain narrative, with its close attention to “authorities” and careful scholarly apparatus, constituted history’s claim to autonomy; abstract causal explanation was best left to philosophers. Yet, even Ranke was no Rankean. He meant history to be critical and colorless, but as Wilhelm Dilthey remarked, “In Ranke all the forces of the nine teenth century come alive” (quoted in Wines 1981:2). Most of all, Ranke was a Romantic; his idea of “essential” history extended beyond facts, into the realm of the spirit. The ultimate task of the historian was not merely to describe, but to intuit the sweeping ideas of history as embodied in individual events and actors. “After criticism, intuition is necessary. The result is a sympathetic comprehension of the universe” as a realm of cultural creativity and spiritual development embodied in the lives of nations (Wines 1981). Ranke wrote in “The Great Powers” (1833) that “Out of the clash of opposing forces, in the crucial moments of danger—collapse, resurgence, liberation—the most decisive developments are born” (p. 97). He concluded: World history does not present such a chaotic tumult, warring, and planless succession of states and peoples as appear at first sight. Nor is the oftendubious advancement of civilization its only significance. There are forces
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 15
and indeed spiritual, life-giving, creative forces, nay life itself, and there are moral energies, whose development we see. They cannot be defined or put in abstract terms… They unfold, capture the world, appear in manifold expressions, dispute with and check and overpower one another. In their interaction and succession, in their life, in their decline or rejuvenation, which then encompasses an ever greater fullness, higher importance, and wider extent, lies the secret of world history. (in Iggers and Moltke 1973:100) Herbert Butterfield (1969:100) has noted that “Great historians…have to be rescued from the cages into which their…successors try to confine them.” This is the case with Ranke. Translated into the idiom of Anglo-American empiricism, Ranke’s historicism was stripped of this Romanticism, leaving only the empirical method. With the notable exceptions of Macaulay and Carlyle, nineteenth-century British historiography adhered to a mildly Rankean positivism. E.H.Carr points (1961:15), perhaps too stridently, to the era’s “fetishism for facts” and its treatment of documents as the historian’s “Ark of the Covenant”: “The reverent historian approached them with bowed head and spoke of them in awed tones. If you find it in the documents, it is so.” Butterfield, however, notes (1969:108) an appreciation of the duality of Ranke, who “on the one hand opened in the modern field the era of scientific research is the man who on the other hand stood as the supreme apostle of ‘general history.’” Arthur Marwick reports some resistance at the universities in Britain (“Research! Research! A mere excuse for idleness; it has never achieved, and never will achieve, any results of the slightest value!”4), yet the critical method took root. Lord Acton, who had commended the “fidelity” of Ranke’s “miniaturepainting” yet faulted him for lacking the “breadth of touch requisite to do justice to great popular and national movements,” nevertheless set the task for contributors to The Cambridge Modern History (1902–10), as “meet[ing] the scientific demand for completeness and certainty…as we approach the final stage in historical learning”; “Our Waterloo,” he wrote “must be one that satisfies French and English, Germans and Dutch alike” (Acton 1973:247, 249). In his 1896 report to the syndics of Cambridge University Press, Acton prophesied, with more confidence than Ranke ever had, that advances in technique would yield “ultimate history.” “All information is within reach and every problem has become capable of solution” (Acton 1907:12). Similarly, when J.B.Bury proclaimed, in 1902, that history was “simply a science, no less and no more,” he meant that history was concrete and ultimately knowable (quoted in Marwick 1970:62). With the rise of the historical profession in the United States, Ranke’s historicism was most earnestly misinterpreted and made the creed of the guild. The “scientific school” of the late nineteenth century claimed Ranke as its archetype, a misidentification Georg Iggers (1962:20) suggests may be rooted in the difference between the German conception of “science” (Wissenschaft), which denotes any sort of systematic research, and the more exacting canons of American natural science. 5 Herbert Baxter Adams noted of Ranke: he “determined to hold strictly to the facts
16 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
of history, to preach no sermon, to point no moral, to adorn no tale, but to tell the simple historic truth” (quoted in Iggers 1968:63–4). Frederick Jackson Turner declared that, thanks to the German historian, “That inductive study of phenomena which has worked a revolution in our knowledge of the external world was applied to history” (quoted in Novick 1988:28–9). Harvard’s Ephraim Emerton called Ranke the founder of “the doctrine of true historical method,” adding, “If one must choose between a school of history whose main characteristic is the spirit, and one which rests upon the greatest number of recorded facts, we cannot long hesitate…Training has taken the place of brilliance and the whole world is today reaping the benefit” (quoted in Iggers 1968:64). Ranke was designated the first honorary member of the American Historical Association, and, after his death in 1886, the history department at Syracuse University acquired his papers along with his desk, chairs, and writing utensils, which were displayed like a shrine. The devout state-centeredness of Ranke’s analysis and his insistence on the primacy of foreign policy (Primat der Aussenpolitik) has resonated especially with students of diplomatic history. This branch of historiography, which traditionally has focused on event-centered history as implied in state documents and other “high” political artifacts, comes closest to Ranke’s own work. Ranke’s international history was also his most controversial. Like Thucydides, whose political thought he analyzed in his dissertation at the University of Leipzig, Ranke saw the balance of power as a fundamental mechanism of inter-state politics. The two shared a sense of how crucial were the spiritual aspects of power and conflict. Yet while there is a tragic cast to Thucydides’ grasp of power and ethics, Ranke romanticized conflict: “Victory falls wherever the greatest energy, the most vital concentration of force, lies. What we describe as material force has in itself a higher significance, for the greatest possible unfolding of the rule of the spirit reveals itself among the most resolute.” Elsewhere he speaks of the “supreme law” of national independence “requir[ing] that the state mobilize all its inner resources for the goal of selfpreservation” (Wines 1981:256, 257). The pitfalls of this triple alliance—a glorified state, a spiritual view of power, and total moral commitment to the struggle—are not hard to find. Werner Stark remarks that “Behind the radiant Ranke looms the sinister Bismarck” (ibid.: 12). Pieter Geyl (1958:28) wonders if Hitler may loom there as well. Geyl points to the dangers of “objective” narrative that acknowledges no extra-historical standards in interpreting history. He acquits Ranke of this, but argues that it is nonetheless an attitude promoted by the critical method and that in lesser minds may have abetted the rise of National Socialism. Even Nietzsche condemns the German historical school for inculcating “that admiration for the ‘power of history’ which in practice transforms every moment into a naked admiration for success and leads to an idolatry of the factual” (quoted in Callinicos 1995:10). It is instructive that Ranke did claim autonomy for his historical narrative, refusing to parrot the “political” historians whose partisan and teleological scholarship aimed to propel Germany toward unification. The most jingoistic of German historians—Droysen, Sybel, Treitschke and others—faulted Ranke, despite his great-nation views, for what they saw as an
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 17
excessive and unpatriotic objectivity (Gay 1974:75–6). This is perhaps more an ethical problem than an epistemological one, but like most modern realists, Ranke, especially in the connection between balance-of-power history and his sanction of the state’s war footing, drew a clear connection between history “as it really was” and realpolitik beliefs and practices. Oakeshott and constructionism Vying with this scientized version of Rankeanism as correspondence and representation is the idea of history as an interpretive construction. Toward the close of the nineteenth century, Dilthey, Croce, F.H.Bradley, and others challenged Ranke’s empirical method from the perspective of philosophical idealism. Oakeshott, Collingwood, Becker, Robinson, and Beard refined the constructionist view in the twentieth century, where it remains a staple of pragmatic historical thought. Constructionism does not presume that history can or should correspond to actual past events, nor does it claim to divorce the historian from the object of his inquiry. History is not a transparent set of positive facts to be mastered by the historian or applied by the student of politics. The past as an actual series of historical events or as a causal lineup of historical actors is considered unknowable in any strict sense. Rather, history is the “ideate,” spoken, or written understanding of that past. As Michael Oakeshott (1990:99) puts it, “History is the historian’s experience. It is ‘made’ by nobody save the historian; to write history is the only way of making it.” Historical constructionism is rooted in the experience-centered skepticism of idealist epistemology. Knowledge, it is said, does not exist independent of experience. At least it is impossible to discern the “essence” of things apart from how they are apprehended. As Diderot (1963:35) wrote in his Lettre sur les Aveugles (1749), “On appelle Idéalistes ces Philosophes qui, n’ayant conscience que de leur existence et des sensations qui se succèdent au dedans d’eux-mêmes, n’admettent pas autre chose.” Oakeshott traces this attitude to Hobbes’s skepticism and to his contention in the Leviathan (1651) that understanding must begin with experience, “for there is no conception in a man’s mind, which hath not at first, totally, or by parts, been begotten upon the organs of sense” (Hobbes 1947:xxiii). In the idealist construction of knowledge, the mind is said to transform a jumble of perceptions into meaningful and coherent worlds of knowledge —history, politics, science, art, etc. These Oakeshott calls “modes” of experience: they are “arrests” or abstractions of the whole of experience. A mode is not arbitrarily drawn, but is authentic so far as it offers “an autonomous manner of understanding, specifiable in terms of exact conditions, which is logically incapable of denying or confirming the conclusions of any other mode” (Oakeshott 1983:2). By precisely describing a mode’s governing logic, idealists seek above all to avoid the problem of ignoratio elenchi, the irrelevance engendered when argument or inference passes from one mode of discourse to another. (Gilbert Ryle calls this a “category mistake.”) Modalists would argue, for example, that countering poetry with science
18 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
or philosophy with literature does not advance understanding. For this reason, Oakeshott insisted that history can support no practical conclusions. The historical past, he wrote, “is a complicated world, without unity of feeling or clear outline: in it events have no over-all pattern or purpose, lead nowhere, point to no favoured condition of the world” (Oakeshott 1962:166). This, surely, is an overstatement of the incommensurability of historical and practical knowledge, but in it is a great truth, namely that non-historical interests constantly encroach upon history. At work here is a constructionist rather than a correspondence logic. As Oakeshott (1990:108) argues, “To pursue ‘what really happened’ as distinct from simply ‘what the evidence obliges us to believe,’ is to pursue a phantom. And the shortest way of disposing of history altogether is to suppose that what is known in history is a fixed, finished and independent past. A form of experience wedded to this purpose is infatuated with the impossible and joined with the contradictory.” For Oakeshott, historical inference demanded single-minded engagement with the evidence. It was sparked exclusively by artifacts from bygone times that had survived more or less intact to the historian’s day. The Gospel according to St. Mark, the score of Figaro, Hobbes’s Leviathan, the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, Fountains Abbey, a parish register of marriages: these are the historian’s materials. He or she “understands” the past via these artifacts alone, not by way of hearsay or intuition or any perceived non-historical need. These footprints of the past provoke and sustain historical inquiry, but they are not in themselves “historical.” The record does not speak for itself; historical events and actors are never simply observable “data.” The historian takes the evidence and transforms it into history, aiming to understand “men and events more profoundly than they were understood when they lived and happened” (Oakeshott 1950/1951: 350). Ultimately, Oakeshott (1990: 93) argues, “The historian’s business is not to discover, to recapture, or even to interpret; it is to create and construct.” History is not a branch of scientific “discovery,” nor is it an imperfect representation of anything. The historical past has not survived; rather, it is a novel creation based on the artifacts. Because this process is bound up in the historian’s mind, prejudice in selection and interpretation is inescapable. Oakeshott (ibid.: 99–100) argues, “There is no fact in history which is not a judgement, no event which is not an inference.” Halfskeptics have distinguished between evidence and interpretation, claiming to be “scientific” in their research, yet admittedly narrative and subjective in their writing. 6 Yet constructionists can be skeptical even of the “facts,” which at the extreme are said not to exist until the historian creates them. As against orthodox American historiography, Carl Becker noted in 1910 that however unassailable the sources, “the historical fact is a wonderfully elusive thing after all, very difficult to fix, almost impossible to distinguish from ‘theory,’ to which it is commonly supposed to be so completely antithetical.” Instead of the historian “‘sticking to the facts,’ the facts stick to him” (Snyder 1958:10, 24). E.H.Carr’s selectivity thesis likewise aims to unsettle the distinction between fact and value, calling a “preposterous fallacy” the belief in a “hard core of historical facts existing objectively and independently of the interpretation of the historian.” Carr suggested that the historian approaches
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 19
“the facts” like “fish on a fishmonger’s slab.” The historian “collects them, takes them home, and cooks and serves them in whatever style appeals to him” (Carr 1961:10, 6). Constructionists are especially wary of ideological abuses of history. Even when the historian is devoted to his or her craft, there is still room for skepticism. As Charles Beard put it in his famous essay against objectivity, “That Noble Dream” (1935), “Beyond doubt, scholars of competence can agree on many particular truths and on large bodies of established facts.” But it “denies philosophy” to believe that it is “possible for men to divest themselves of all race, sex, class, political, social, and religious predilections and tell the truth of history as it actually was” (Beard 1935:76–7). Oakeshott’s concerns about treating history as a treasure house have been mentioned. He insisted that “history is thinking about the past for the sake of the past; it is a way of thinking about the past free from all extraneous interests” (Oakeshott 1936: 78). He contended that to interpret the evidence with some practical or moral end in mind was, by definition, to descend into ideology. He tagged historical ideologists as “vulgar rag-pickers,” in whose hands artifacts are “transformed from being resonant, ambiguous circumstantial survivals of bygone human life into emblematic actions and utterances…entirely divorced from their circumstances.” “A record reputed to be a mine of prophetic utterances may be consulted at random, after the manner of the sortes Vergilianae,” he argued, and here the yield is not advice but an alleged unavoidable destiny and the courage to accept it. The Old Testament, its character as the recorded past of the ancient Hebrew people ignored and belief in its alleged divine authorship suspended, has long been known as an unequalled collection of exemplars of human character and situation and a rich vocabulary of verbal and situational images, of parables and analogies, in terms of which to understand, express and respond to current situations. (Oakeshott 1983:58) For Oakeshott, history was not the handmaiden for any other branch of knowledge, or for any political creed. Nor was history to be interpreted in terms of any imposed contrivance of teleology, evolution, or development. “We shall not find unity in history unless we have first constructed history on a principle of unity,” he declares (Oakeshott 1990:142).7 In order to preserve the integrity of his story, the teleologisthistorian must either ignore as “non-events” whatever does not fit within his straitjacket plot, or he must sculpt events to make them fit. Oakeshott sanctioned historical periodization, although he discouraged overburdening these conceptualizations—“the Carolingian Empire,” “the Protestant Reformation,” “European Liberalism,” etc.—with categorical finality. Only the “flimsiest partition” distinguishes one historical event from another, as “there is nothing solid or absolute in their character” (ibid.: 122). We should not, therefore, confuse the historian’s “tentative, multiform historical identities” with the “stark, monolithic
20 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
products” of facile classifications and ideological constructions (Oakeshott 1983: 117–18). Oakeshott (ibid.: 58) defined history constructed within these strictures as an “argued invitation to imagine the intricacies and the coherence of a condition of human circumstance which has not survived.” History remained a modest construct, with historical truth tied to an obligation to the evidence and centered on the coherence of the story. When the historian is successful, i.e., when events are understood independent of subsequent events or contemporary desires, the past exhibits at most “a peculiarly tentative and intermediate kind of intelligibility” (Oakeshott 1962:159). The image of historical construction Oakeshott evokes in On History (1983) is that of a country “dry wall,” whose stones are held together not by mortar, but by their roughly interlocking shapes. If this wall should totter or rifts appear, these eccentricities are seen not as defects, but as characteristics of history. Historians may prefer not to dwell on the soundness of their constructions. Hayden White claims (1966:112) that since the mid-nineteenth century, most historians have affected a kind of “willful methodological naiveté,” that there is “resistance throughout the entire profession to almost any kind of critical selfanalysis.” Peter Novick (1988:15, 593) suggests that “reflecting on epistemology” is “what historians do worst, or at least badly,” either out of “utter indifference” to epistemological questions or in “tacit recognition that the issues involved [are] too hot to handle.” While White and Novick are probably not representative spokesmen for the historical profession, no serious historiographic theory today denies the impact of presentism and bias on historical thought. The historian may seek what Jakob Burckhardt described as the “Archimedean point outside events” where objective judgments are possible, knowing, however, it will not be found. As HansGeorg Gadamer (1992:18) once put it, “We stand at the end of our own reflections.” No historian is divorced from non-historical interests. The real question is the extent to which these extracurricular engagements color his/her history. We now take up this problem as it relates to social science theory. History, theory, and social science Historians are themselves divided over the relation of their craft to other realms of social inquiry. (See, for example, Marwick 1970, Hofstadter 1973, Dunn 1978, Fogel and Elton 1983, and Appleby et al. 1994.) History’s affinity for social science is generally seen to turn on questions of objectivity and on the possibility of deriving historical trends, patterns, or laws from the available evidence. This possibility rests in turn on the notion that knowledge exists objectively and independently of apprehension and interpretation. However, even if objectively understood, is each past event sui generis, and thus resistant to inclusion in scientific constructs? Are there timeless historical and political precepts, or are social studies purely contextual? Can there be what Carl Hempel (1942) calls, in the locus classicus of the deductive historical method, a “function of general laws in history”? Does
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 21
Oakeshott (1936:78) overstep in his insistence on the “absolute impossibility of deriving from history any generalizations of the kind which belong to a social science,” and that anyone who attempts to wed history and social science is “ignorant of the nature of either and careless of the interests of both”? Inference versus observation In its relation with social science, history is torn between inference and observation on one hand, and idiography and nomothesis on the other. As we have seen, the inference—observation question is at the center of the Ranke—Oakeshott debate, with Ranke claiming to “observe” events via the documents, and Oakeshott creating historical inferences based on the artifacts. This “inside—outside” dilemma parallels Dilthey’s famous distinction between the sciences and the humanities. According to Dilthey, the humanities were an inward experience (Erlebnis) where, in the case of history, the historian grapples imaginatively with evidence of the past with the aim of understanding the motivations and beliefs behind events and actions. The aim of scientific knowledge, on the other hand, was to explain (begreifen) phenomena presented as outward spectacles. (See Collingwood 1956: 171–6.) Dilthey found it appropriate, then, that students of the natural sciences use the language of causality, and that students of the humanities speak the language of experience. This distinction is also a factor of the sociology of knowledge and of scientific discovery. All knowledge is conditioned in some way, although critical theories most commonly regard truth as defined by power and interests, as with Marx, Mannheim, Lukács, Foucault, and others. E.H.Carr was arguably the field’s first critical theorist in his contention that ethical and theoretical commitments, “far from being the expression of absolute and a priori principles, are historically conditioned, being both products of circumstances and interests and weapons framed for the furtherance of interests” (Carr 1946: 68). As we will see in our discussion of postmodernism in Chapter 7, the discipline has, in this critical sense, come full circle. Thomas Kuhn’s idea of the ambiguity of paradigms in science has had a similar effect on more formal research programs. Kuhn argued in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) that paradigms structure otherwise haphazard research, but they also impose boundaries on inquiry. This is why paradigmatic “normal science” persists even as anomalies mount. Scientific (including historical) knowledge does not steadily accumulate in a way that can be rationally reconstructed. Rather, only with a broader upheaval in the ethos of scientific discovery does one paradigm supplant another. Kuhn maintained that paradigms were doubly problematic in their relation to history. Not only did paradigmatic orthodoxies blinker the scientist’s interpretation of the historical evidence, but also scientific logic was itself innately Whiggish, that is to say, unequivocally linear, cumulative, and presentcentered about its own disciplinary history (Kuhn 1962:137). The problem with any such contentions about the relativity of knowledge is that the critic must claim to have achieved some privileged position from which to make a critique. What is
22 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
unassailable in any case is that the social scientist is part of the history from which his/her knowledge is constructed, and at any moment that knowledge may have to be amended or abandoned altogether. Moreover, as Alan Ryan (1970:19) and others have argued, historical description and explanation can be self-fulfilling. For instance, the vision of a zerosum cold war held by President Truman’s National Security Council appears (with Soviet help) to have produced exactly that: its initial assumptions were “confirmed” by the actions that flowed from those assumptions. This is not to suggest that we merely re-imagine the history of international relations in terms of some peaceable kingdom, nor need it lead to total skepticism about our socially conditioned constructs. We can say, however, that the social dimensions of theory and policy blur the divide between belief and knowledge. Caution seems especially apt as we venture onto the boggy ground of ascribing meanings to historical events. As Max Weber, himself primarily an historian interested in generalization, nevertheless made clear, the shortcoming of historical discourse is that it can only ever provide a self-centered meaning to events, that the broadest “theoretical” patterns in history are as much the products of conceptualization as of actual observation: The fate of an epoch which has eaten of the tree of knowledge is that it must know that we cannot learn the meaning of the world from the results of its analysis, be it ever so perfect; it must rather be in a position to create this meaning itself. It must recognize that general views of life and the universe can never be the products of increasing empirical knowledge. (Weber 1949:57) Idiography versus nomothesis A second axis of tension in history and theory is that between “idiography” (particular-description), and “nomothesis” (law-generation, with attendant “if x then y” causal claims). It is here, really, that history and the social sciences, depending on one’s view, either meet or diverge. On this point, the anthropologist Margaret Mead once wisecracked that historians study “the unique event in all its uniqueness” (quoted in Thorne 1988:36). The environmental historian E.L. Jones has noted that if the “uniqueness problem” is “carried to the extreme of ignoring all regularities, the very possibility of social science is denied and historians are reduced to the aimlessness of balladeers” (quoted in King et al. 1994:43). Particularists such as Oakeshott defend the differentia specifica of historical events and actors, insisting that “where comparison begins, as a method of generalization, history ends.” “Liberalism felled the Berlin Wall,” or “democracies are pacific,” are not, then, historical statements. Oakeshott claims that “the relation between events is always other events.” The implication is that historical understanding requires no “theory,” but rather lies in “a greater and more complete detail…a world of events in which no lacuna is tolerated” (Oakeshott 1990:166, 141). Thus, we can
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 23
never know history with any scientific rigor, since to do so requires strict causal links (necessary and sufficient) between events. Oakeshott (1983:75–6) insists that strict causality is a standard of science not of history, and attempting to bridge this “unresolvable categorical distinction” is to engage in a “pretentious muddle.” On the nomothetic front is Carl Hempel’s path-breaking use of the deductive method in historical interpretation. “The methodological unity of empirical science,” Hempel argues, demands that “general laws have quite analogous functions in history and in the natural sciences” (Hempel 1942: 48, 35). Hempel employs what has variously been called “the regularity model,” the “covering model,” or the “deductive” method of “prediction and control.” Under whatever rubric, historical interpretations are deduced from general assumptions that appear to “cover” it and similar cases. Hempel suggests that history has always been “scientific,” that causality is implicit in all historical writing. Linking actions with events with terms like “causes,” “outcomes,” “origins,” “influence,” “development,” “growth,” and “decline,” suggests that the relationship between events is not one of happenstance, but that the outcome stated was a necessary consequence of the action depicted. The idea is that general causal assumptions can be “scientifically” confirmed or disconfirmed, as Hempel put it, “by suitable empirical findings” (ibid.: 35). Writ large, this is essentially the tension between history and theory. The “ideal type” of historian emphasizes meaning, difference, content, context, and complexity. His theorist counterpart focuses on regularities, generalization, and economical explanation. Set Kenneth Waltz’s (1979) universal guide for explaining war—the military structure of the international environment —beside Geoffrey Blainey’s (1973) thirty-three different conditions and caveats on war, and the contrast between the disciplines is clear. In several ways, however, this is a false distinction. In either discipline, “facts” do not simply exist waiting to be incorporated into research. Historians as well as theorists rely on generalizations, models, and concepts. These are indispensable to historical writing; without some sort of framework, evidence and ideas lack meaning or coherence. “Facts may be facts,” Hugh Stretton wrote, “but theories order them and explanations select them.” Stretton continues: “by historians…and by many other social scientists whether or not they admit it, explanations have to be chosen by some principle of value, fashion or chance; no ‘scientific’ principle can replace them” (Stretton 1969: v, 60). The historian always works according to some hypothesis. The real task is to derive a premise that “will neither lead him into the systematic error of interpretation according to a general principle unsupported by evidence or insufficiently comprehensive, nor leave him with disiecta membra which cannot be brought into any intelligible relations with the actualities of human life” (Introduction to Herodotus 1947: xii). Moreover, in ways that are rarely acknowledged, the logic of most historical explanation (though not of Oakeshott’s) mirrors that of scientific explanation. The burden of much of history is to show that events were to be expected, given certain antecedent conditions. As Hempel points out, there is a causal claim here. There is also a suggestion, at least, that in
24 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
the future one might expect similar consequences under similar conditions. In a crude manner, this is what it means to possess a “sense of history.” When confronted with historical skepticism, an historian may plead that the story is being told as well as possible, given personal limitations and those of the evidence. When a theorist encounters “historical” concerns, he or she is apt to seek refuge in the canons of social science. A common rejoinder is that theory cannot be bounded by specific historical events. Theory is a model, a roadmap, or a lens with which to make sense of the history. Theory should be elegant and parsimonious. Its function is not to struggle with the facts, but to illuminate the general trends or tectonics of international politics. Granted, theoretical statements are abstracted from a far richer historical context, and precisely because the theorist is given to generalization, there is perhaps more chance of interpretive recklessness than with an historian. Less convincing, however, is the theorist’s contention that his compact causal model transcends interpretive questions. Let us retire the idea that the historical problem has little bearing on international relations theory. Theory is not a license to twist history or to fudge questions of causality, periodization, or intent. It is a tool for understanding, not a creed to be defended at any cost. And even if we consider international relations a theoretical science on the methodological grounds proposed by Morton Kaplan (1961:24)— “the science of the discipline does not lie in absolute certainty but in reasonable belief, in definite canons of procedure and investigation, and in the attempt to permit confirmation or falsification even though of an imprecise order”— historical testing, with all its attendant problems, remains the sine qua non for international relations as a progressive stream of knowledge. Traditionalists versus scientists This question has been muddled in the debate in international relations between “traditionalists” and “scientists,” the former concerned with more or less “historical” judgments, the latter with value-free generalizations and predictions. Traditionalists contend that because political scientists have cut “themselves off from history and philosophy,” they hold a “callow and brash” view of international studies (Bull 1969a: 37). Some claim that historical interpretation is the crux of the study of international affairs. As Martin Wight (1966:33) formulaically suggested, “Politics: International Politics=Political Theory: Historical Interpretation.” Behavioral political scientists typically respond that historical interpretation has no place in scientific abstraction, that it is impossible to “squeeze juice from the historian’s turnip” (Meehan 1968:108–9). Historical interpretation is theoretically unstructured, intuitive, anecdotal, idiosyncratic, and irreproducible—in short, unscientific. This division is over-simple, and does violence to the achievements of both camps. In fact, there is constant tension in theory—and history—between generalization and historical content. As A.H.Birch (1969) and Richard Little (1991, 1995) have argued, history and social science cannot be distinguished in terms of
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 25
epistemology and method, but only by the kind of research questions asked. Little notes: This tug between the desire to understand both the particular and the general is not…peculiar to the “classical approach.” It is an endemic feature of the social sciences. The failure to appreciate this point has led to a false dichotomy between “classical” and “scientific” approaches and the odd notion, propagated by some historians who have lacked any self-conscious awareness of their own methods, that history is concerned with unique events whereas social science is concerned with a search for general laws. Social scientists and historians have no option but to rely on methods which ensure that some link is maintained between understanding the particular and explaining the general. (Little 1995:15) How does one draw a line between history and abstraction and still maintain this link? The “scientific” reply is most often tied to the quest for a “general,” usually “systems,” theory of international politics, and aims to balance theoretical simplicity and depth of explanation. Yet, as Weber again argued, “for the knowledge of historical phenomena in their concreteness, the most general laws, because they are most devoid of content are also the least valuable. The more comprehensive the validity—or scope—of a term, the more it leads us away from the richness of reality” (Weber 1949:80). Indeed, in international relations, the quest for parsimony has sparked something of a race to the bottom in terms of historical content. This seems counterproductive in such a complex field as international politics. Instead of trying to understand events, causal models may simply assume that the way things turned out was foreordained. It is easy to forget that in politics the interplay between necessity and choice can be intense and often indeterminate. Process is no less important than structure. For these reasons, theorists should perhaps build outward from historical understandings. In doing so, they should attach, as Martin Wight once counseled (1966:32), a liberal dose of “judiciousness and modesty” to their historical claims. “Using” history: proof or plunder? According to Benedetto Croce’s (1941:19) famous slogan, all history is contemporary history. “The practical requirements which underlie every historical judgment give to all history the character of ‘contemporary history,’ because, however remote in time events thus recounted may seem to be, the history in reality refers to present needs and present situations wherein those events vibrate.” If history is malleable in the historian’s hands, the whole notion of using history in other pursuits begs added skepticism. As the theorist constructs and reconstructs histories, there is danger that the creation will be dictated or distorted by personal ideological or intellectual commitments. This practice can reduce the “archive” of
26 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
international relations to little more than “self-fulfilling hindsight” (Booth 1995: 332–3). The argument developed here is that abuses of history are tied to the rigidity of theory and to the extravagance of the theorist’s claims on history. The ambiguities of historical evidence seem lost on many international relations scholars. It has been suggested that the discipline’s mainstream has hewed to an uncomplicated Rankeanism vis-à-vis history, which is neither uncomplicated nor Rankean. This has not always been so. Writing in 1959, Kenneth Waltz remarked that theory itself was chiefly responsible for the mutability of historical evidence. “The idea we entertain becomes a filter through which we pass our data,” he noted. “If the filter is good or the data selected carefully, they will pass like milk through cheesecloth. The recalcitrance of the data may cause us to change one filter for another, to modify or scrap the theory we hold—or it may produce ever more ingenious selections and interpretations of the data.” Waltz concluded that it was impossible to resolve theoretical dilemmas “historically.” Since the “evidence” is easily tailored to meet expectations, historical argument tends merely to reproduce the logic of the arguer (Waltz 1959b: 60). We shall see in Chapter 5 that Waltz later tempered his skepticism, and in Theory of International Politics (1979) advocated rigorously deductive theory, which he believed could be confirmed if derivative hypotheses withstood testing against “hard” historical cases. This about-face notwithstanding, doubts linger about the firm findings of international relations research that hinges on history. If one is at all ambivalent about historical evidence, two or three contrary cases ought not to overturn a theory; but then neither should a selected handful of consistent ones confirm it. Currently the consensus among “theory—hypothesis—testing” researchers is against the low falsification threshold associated with Karl Popper (1959, 1965), and in favor of Imre Lakatos’s “sophisticated methodological falsification,” which tests theory not only against the “facts,” but against other theories as well (Lakatos 1970). Again, this may be a case of political science outpacing the material. We shall see as well that Lakatos himself had grave doubts about “scientifically”— oriented social science methodology, wondering if it was not merely “pseudo-intellectual garbage.” Climbing the pyramids of antiquity Researchers will bicker over methodology, but often skepticism about history is simply trampled in a rush of aggressive conclusions promoting a particular intellectual stance. One is reminded of Nietzsche’s (1965:225) critique of those “curious tourists and laborious beetle-hunters climbing up the great pyramids of antiquity.” Critics charge that theorists rummage through history books seeking “authorities” for their theoretical views. Indeed, the more distant an historical example or analogy, the more easily it seems to pass into evidence. Such criticism has remained at the margin of international relations scholarship, raised most often by historians familiar with theory. A general objection is that theorists make cavalier use of historical narrative, designing what Collingwood
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 27
(1956:257–61) called “scissors-and-paste” history, a jerrybuilt pastiche of “events.” A more specific indictment is that theorists jettison historical particularism, essentially forcing history to lie in the Procrustean bed of political inquiry. Christopher Hill (1985:142), for example, notes a tendency, especially among American theorists, to “play fast and loose with the historian’s concerns with particularity and context.” Paul Schroeder (1994a: 148) worries that researchers will “go at history like a looter at an archeological site, indifferent to context and deeper meaning, concerned only with taking what can be immediately used or sold.” Not altogether whimsically, Christopher Thorne (1983:123) offers the metaphor of “Clio as callgirl,” and cites a parallel in Jean Genet’s The Balcony, in which Madam Irma, keeper of the brothel she calls her “House of Illusions,” finds that each patron, “when he rings the bell and enters, brings his own scenario, perfectly thought out.” A case in point is the treatment of Kant’s idea of a “pacific federation” composed of constitutional republics. The Königsberg philosopher’s thesis has been translated into contemporary debate in the hypothesis that democratic states do not go to war with each other, and is a standard premise of liberal international theory. The proposition seems straightforward enough and appears amenable to empiricalhistorical testing. However, a recent flurry of “historical” scrutiny has only clouded the issue. Consider two articles, one by John Owen, the other by Christopher Layne, in a 1994 issue of International Security. The writers each probe four historical cases. In fact, they address two of the same cases—Anglo-Union acrimony during the American Civil War, and Anglo-American tensions in 1895–6 in connection with the Venezuela—British Guyana boundary dispute—and in doing so rely heavily on the same history books. In the articles, each author rallies historiographic evidence in support of his argument, yet the conclusions drawn from that evidence are at loggerheads. Owen (1994:124) finds that “The liberal commitment to individual freedom gives rise to foreign policy ideology and governmental institutions that work together to produce democratic peace.” Layne (1994:49) resolves that “the world remains what it always has been: international politics continues to occur in an anarchic, competitive, self-help realm.” The disjunction lies in the history—or, more precisely, in the selection and interpretation of historiography. Both articles are well within the norms and conventions of historical usage in international relations, yet both authors draw selectively on the historical record. They are either unaware of the conditional and competing nature of the relevant facts, or else they are acutely aware of this problem and have deliberately spotlighted helpful citations and obscured contrary claims, but without then qualifying their “historical” and theoretical conclusions. In discussion of the Trent Affair in 1861, for example, Layne (1994:19) quotes a bellicose Prime Minister Palmerston as threatening “to inflict a severe blow upon, and read a lesson to the United States which will not soon be forgotten.” Owen (1994:113), on the other hand, quotes Palmerston’s reluctance to use force, due to the “Shackles of Principle and of Right & Wrong on these Matters.” A more judicious reading of the evidence might be that the Prime Minister was ambivalent about starting a war with the Union. Instead, the researchers proceed based on
28 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
evidence consonant with their initial assumptions, and extrapolate in a manner probably unintended by the historians whom they cite. And lest we think the interpretive problem is overcome through quantitative “coding” of historiography in place of narrative evidence, that approach, as will be clear in Chapter 6, also warrants robust skepticism. Quantitative scrutiny of the democratic peace premise has bogged down in definitional squabbles about what constitutes a democracy, and about the relationship between wars and “near misses.” Critics argue that the direction of causality may be reversed, the correlation may hold only for the cold war years, or that some unexplored factor may better account for the liberal peace. The quality of diplomacy is neglected, minor wars and major conflicts are weighted equally, and ultimate calculations are deemed statistically insignificant (see Spiro 1994, and Farber and Gowa 1995).8 Flagrant history spinning is easily exposed by fuller historiographic reference. More interesting for our purposes are good-faith disputes over interpretation, where even-handed analysis does not necessarily defuse interpretive clashes. At heart, the dilemma is one of indeterminacy in evidence and interpretation. The problem is especially pronounced in history and affects the gamut of international studies. Even when “what happened” is not in dispute, how or why a particular event happened—causal links that many consider it theory’s task to provide—often is. Was Hitler’s rise to power the result of one man’s cunning or of the collapse of the political and economic institutions of “respectable” Germany, or some other amalgam of causes? Were the Vietcong promoting Asian nationalism or abetting Communist expansion? Did dropping atomic bombs on Hiroshima and Nagasaki end the war? When addressing such questions, engaging the historical record is imperative, but the answers given remain highly interpretive and frequently polemical. Following the recent (perhaps selective) de-classification of Soviet and Chinese archival materials on the Korean War, for example, what happened seems resolved, but the motivations and intentions of the actors, as well as the broader meaning of the war, are more hotly contested than ever.9 The problem of interpretation and indeterminacy is likely to worsen with time. Ankersmit (1994:167–72) argues that due to the fecundity of historians (there have been more historians working since 1960 than in all previous time back to Herodotus), the field is burdened with riches. New theories lead to a cascade of new historiography, old problems are revisited, and revisionist accounts accumulate. Selection and interpretation become even more necessary, not because there is too little information, but because there is too much. Presentism and statecraft A further interpretive challenge lies in the historicity of theory itself. Like a work of history, theory may reveal as much about the author and his/her world than about the subject under scrutiny. Those who look to theory for anything resembling consistent “laws” or patterns of international behavior will be discouraged by how markedly theories parallel contemporary political problems and structures. This is
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 29
a recurrent meta-theoretical critique in the field. In Twenty Years’ Crisis (1946), E.H.Carr held that inter-war “idealist” philosophies of international politics were shaped by a “harmony-of-interests” ideology rooted in the Victorian laissez-faire economic regime. Less stridently, Stanley Hoffmann has described how international relations emerged as a distinctly “American” social science in the context of peculiar circumstances, and bears all the marks of its milieu. Morgenthau’s balance-of-power theory, while broadly applicable, was also bound up in the emerging cold war: Morgenthau meant to be apropos. Waltz’s structural interpretation of world history mirrors the “mature” bipolar world in which he was theorizing—a world that expired unexpectedly. Postmodern theory reflects many of the dislocations of globalization alongside the resurgence of nativist and nationalist politics. As Charles Reynolds (1973:113–14) has argued, “‘Significance’ and ‘meaning’ in historical interpretation are…intimately related to the present. While historical anachronisms should be avoided in reconstructing the past, the reconstruction itself will always be influenced by, and relative to, the historian’s present. The historian is concerned not only with explaining present traces of the past, but also with his own experience in relation to this.” Ludwig Dehio’s Precarious Balance (1963), for example, traces the hegemonic designs made on Europe by men from Carlos V to Hitler, yet the book’s silent central character is Stalin. Peter Fleiss’s Thucydides and the Politics of Bipolarity (1966) recasts the Peloponnesian War in a distinctly twentiethcentury matrix. Paul Kennedy’s excellent Rise and Fall of the Great Powers (1987) reflects many of the insecurities of Western economic and military might in the late twentieth century. More critically, Butterfield (1931:31) warned that “The study of the past with one eye…on the present is the source of all sins and sophistries in history.” He feared that history would be commandeered to affirm prevailing circumstances and commitments. Yet, even in the absence of ideology, a certain degree of presentism seems inescapable. This is particularly true of international relations, where the tension between academic detachment and meeting current crises is so acute. Whatever the setting, we should probe the past for edifying parallels. Historical analogies and immediately applicable “lessons” are preferable to careening from one crisis to the next. However, we should accept that the lessons drawn may not be strictly “historical.” In terms of “using” history in setting foreign policy as opposed to detached political research, Jack Levy makes an important distinction between actual “learning” from history, and the “instrumental” use of the past to buttress preexisting policy preferences. As A.J.P.Taylor once put it, “Men use the past to prop up their prejudices” (Levy 1994a: 306). The results are disheartening in both cases. Organizational psychologists have argued that learning is “myopic, incremental, and ignorant,” shaped “less by history than by the frames applied to that history” (ibid.: 283). Robert Jervis contends that “People pay more attention to what happened than to why it has happened. Thus learning is superficial, overgeneralized, and based on post hoc ergo propter hoc reasoning. As a result, the
30 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
lessons learned will be applied to a wide variety of situations without a careful effort to determine whether the cases are similar on crucial distinctions” (ibid.: 29–4). Similarly, Ernest May’s “Lessons” of the Past (1973) argues that analogic reasoning in statecraft has been misguided because it rests on surface similarities and draws on a shallow pool of examples. May’s chief epistemological point is that through “cognitive dissonance” statesmen shape information to fit expectations, pigeonholing events into a handful of hackneyed “historical” models. A meatier study of the psychology involved here is Yuen Foong Khong’s Analogies at War (1992). Khong confirms that historical analogies are crucial in the political tasks of advocacy and justification, but he contends that they also undergird the “knowledge structures” guiding policy. He finds that decisionmakers continue to cling to analogies even after it becomes clear that the analogy does not hold. All these studies agree that the “lessons” learned are often contradictory or simply wrong, and in any case are skewed toward the present crisis (see also Vertzberger 1986). Beyond the cold war Theorists, it seems, are in a double bind. If drawn uncritically, distant historical analogies are strained. Yet research focused on recent or contemporary history suffers from the “parochialism of time,” still too much “with us” for meaningful analysis. Theorists, for example, had a history-spinning field day with the end of the cold war, gleaning remarkably diverse historical and theoretical “lessons” from that important snapshot event. We find vindication of classical realism (Kennan 1994), indeed of “Thucydidean” thinking (Bagby 1994); nostalgia for bipolar stability (Mearsheimer 1990); support for contingency-based theory (Gaddis 1992/ 1993); justification for neo conservativism (Muravchik 1991) and neoWilsonianism (Gusterson 1993); and credit to the European peace movement (Kaldor 1995). Kenneth Waltz (1993) has even managed a post mortem that fits neorealist theory. Of course, at work here is what Nevil Johnson (1989:45) calls the “fallacy of misplaced history,” where the theorist “speculate[s] like a political journalist” on the contemporary “passing show,” without the benefit of depth of understanding or of hindsight. The smuggest cold war obituaries now founder in a mire of bloody ethnicism, new tides of human migration, nuclear proliferation, and a checkered record of multilateral diplomacy and peacekeeping. Perhaps a better way of contending with the end of the cold war is to see it as a time of uncertainty and imagination. The cold war was a most dramatic example of what the Annalistes call a “matrix-event” (événement-matrice), which structures historical interpretation and meaning. What lies ahead is uncertain. The novelist Malcolm Bradbury notes (1990:21) that “for 50 years imagination and intelligence have been imprisoned in a world laid down by the Iron Curtain set across Europe. Yet more largely, it has lived in an historical interpretation divided between two massive 20th century ideologies.” As we venture into realism in the next chapters it will be clear just how much that conflict has structured political theory and
THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 31
historical interpretation. The end of the cold war is now a decade behind us, yet we still live in a time, as Bradbury noted, of “rising uncertainties…developing hopes and estranging fears, above all in a world that will not stay still.” Amid such hope and fear, it is not clear that a revolution is needed in our understanding of history and politics, but a reappraisal certainly is.
32
3 HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM Reinhold Niebuhr and E.H.Carr
The historical problem goes to the heart of the realist approach to the theory and practice of international relations. As Herbert Butterfield and Martin Wight (1966: 12–13) note of the realists, “Their point of view has on the whole been historical. They have tended to suppose that the continuities in international relations are more important than the innovations; that statecraft is an historical deposit of practical wisdom growing very slowly…and that it is a useful enterprise to explore the corpus of diplomatic and military experience in order to reformulate its lessons in relation to contemporary needs.” Realists regard history as an indispensable source of insight because it provides a vehicle for piercing the fog of the present and gaining a wider perspective from which to judge events. Just as one steps back from an impressionist painting or a church facade in order to bring its patterns and motifs into focus, only at an historical remove do the otherwise disconnected features of political life exhibit a certain symmetry and structure. This chapter explores the roots of realism in the ideas of Reinhold Niebuhr, an American theologian, and E.H.Carr, an English Marxist. The chapter first examines the intellectual origins, in Thucydides and Machiavelli, of the realist effort to bridge history and theory. The chapter then turns to Niebuhr’s theory of history as it underpins his views on tragedy, the ethics of statecraft, and the possibilities of political science. Included is a critique of Niebuhr’s most “empirical” historical investigation, The Structure of Nations and Empires (1959). In its discussion of Carr, the chapter explores the “sociology of knowledge” and the progressivist interpretation of history and the impact of both on Carr’s realism. The section also includes a discussion of the problem of power and historical judgment. Both of these theorists offered a complex and contingent view of history, fluid in process and open-ended in its possibilities. Neither considered history to be amenable to scientific explanations free of interest and prejudice. Political choice was not simply the product of “necessity” or historical laws. The discussion presented here is foundational to Chapter 4, which is devoted to the “policy realism” of Hans J.Morgenthau and George F.Kennan; and to Chapter 5, which examines the structural or “neorealist” theory of Kenneth N.Waltz. In those chapters, we will see the contingent view lose ground to necessity as the science of international relations develops.
34 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Philosophical and historical roots As an approach to international relations, realism represents a philosophical world view, a framework for interpreting history, and a body of normative thought. Realism is informed by classical writings, by Judeo-Christian anthropology and ethics, by modern secular thought, by historical reference, and by the particulars of given problems. Thucydides, Aristotle, St. Augustine, Machiavelli, Hobbes, Hume, Rousseau, Burke, and Weber are the prominent stations on this journey, and this distinguished heritage is reflected in the paradigm’s range and depth (see Smith 1986). Realists embrace several fundamental premises concerning international politics. First, realists share a pessimistic view of human nature. Human nature is the prime mover. It propels history, yet remains untouched by historical reforms and progress. Second, sovereign states are the main actors in the international arena, where they seek to maximize power and/or security, and to pursue their interests in competition with other states. Third, the international realm is anarchic, i.e., no supra-national authorities or norms effectively govern state behavior. Fourth, moral choice is important in international politics, yet it must be considered in light of the foregoing assumptions. Many realists see international politics and domestic politics as separate ethical spheres. These characteristics apply, for the most part, to both “classical” realists —i.e., the first “wave” of realist thinkers including Niebuhr, Carr, Butterfield, Wight, Georg Schwarzenberger, Nicholas Spykman, Louis Halle, John Herz, Morgenthau, Aron, Arnold Wolfers, Kennan, and Henry Kissinger—as well as their more “scientific” successors, known as “neorealists,” and led by Kenneth Waltz. The classical approach is in some ways a broader enterprise than orthodox political science. Classical realists rely openly on the exercise of values and judgment, and believe that, if subjected to strict standards of proof, they can say little of significance about international politics (see Bull 1969a).1 Neorealists have nevertheless attempted to develop an elegant, deductive theory of international politics, disposing of human nature, political personalities, and the character of individual states in favor of ahistorical explanations of political behavior derived from ideas about the structure of the international environment. Largely on its historical credentials, realism became the leading approach to international politics in the postwar years. If, as Martin Wight (1966:32–3) once suggested, international theory implies at most “the kind of rumination about human destiny to which we give the unsatisfactory name of philos ophy of history,” then realists see history, in its most basic outline, as a great and tragic cycle. It represents an unending struggle for power and interests, where conflict is at times unavoidable. Realism arose in reaction to idyllic assumptions—largely about history —of nineteenth- and early twentiethcentury thought on international politics. All of the classical realists watched the peace of Versailles collapse into the chaos and ideological virulence of the 1930s. All had the memory of Hitler’s appeasement at Munich seared onto their psyches. Many realist thinkers fled the war in Europe,
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 35
bringing with them to the United States and Britain deep-seated convictions about continental realpolitik and its failings. Realists, moreover, seem comfortable with history, moving easily between historical description and theoretical pronouncements. Many—Butterfield, Wight, Halle, Kennan, Carr—were trained in history or were practicing historians. Modern realists follow in particular two of their doctrinal forebears— Thucydides and Machiavelli—in their attitude toward history. Herodotus gave us the Greek term, histori ē , originally meaning research, investigation, or wisdom, from which the word “history” is derived. However, this did not stop “the father of history” from being, by Rankean standards, a notoriously unreliable chronicler, as likely to attribute causality to the intervention of the gods as to more mundane forces. Thucydides’ History of the Peloponnesian War (c. 400 BC) set a new norm for historical investigation. Thucydides was a great defender of rigorous methodology, and offered devastating critiques of the standards of evidence employed by his predecessor. Yet, even Thucydides claimed that it was impossible for historians to write accurately about the past. He presented his own methods and proofs as appropriate only for contemporary accounts, a sort of classical journalism, and even then did not name his “eye-witnesses,” whom, he cautioned, “gave different accounts of the same events, speaking out of partiality for one side or the other or else from imperfect memories” (Thucydides 1972:48). Nor did his attention to method prevent him from lacing his History with “theoretical” assertions, and heightening its effect through that famous classical device, reconstructed oratory. Thucydides’ introduction to the History is a touchstone for modern realists: It may well be that my history will be less easy to read because of the absence of a romantic [mythic] element. It will be enough for me, however, if these words of mine are judged useful by those who want to understand clearly the events which happened in the past and which (human nature being what it is) will, at some time or other and in much the same ways, be repeated in the future. My work is not a piece of writing designed to meet the taste of an immediate public, but was done to last forever. (ibid.: 48)
The Athenian’s great work has proved remarkably enduring, in no small way molding the matrix of modern thought on war. Thomas Hobbes’s first publication, in 1629, was a translation of the History. Hobbes prefaced the edition by noting that it was “the principle and proper work of history…to instruct and enable men, by the knowledge of actions past, to bear themselves prudently in the present and providently towards the future.” He judged Thucydides to be “the most politic historiographer that ever writ [who] may from the narrations draw out lessons to himself, and of himself be able to trace the drifts and counsels of the actors to their seat” (quoted in Rahe 1995/1996:111). To this day, realists read Thucydides for his insights into human nature, national character, the clash of cultures, the problems
36 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
of power, the quality of leadership, and the importance of political rhetoric. Thucydides’ most profound insights concern the moral tragedy of war. His Melian Dialogue, perhaps the sharpest juxtaposition of ethical appeal and the strong arm of authority ever depicted, is set at the heart of the narrative, and many classicists consider it the centerpiece of the book. On a more “empirical” level, realists cleave to Thucydides’ archetypal logic that “what made war inevitable was the growth of Athenian power and the fear which this caused in Sparta” (Thucydides 1972:49). The key to the phrase is the term anankē which is usually translated as “necessity” or “compulsion,” and suggests that the Spartans had little or no choice but to go to war. This statement is frequently cited as a pristine expression of what realists call the security—power dilemma. This is the idea that the measures deemed necessary to protect a state inherently clash with the security imperatives of its neighbors. By many accounts, this is the central problem of international politics. It is also easy to see why Thucydides’ tale of politics, diplomacy, and war in a bipolar world, would ring so clearly with students and statesmen during the cold war. Secretary of State George C.Marshall, in a 1947 speech at Princeton University, doubted “whether a man can think with full wisdom and with deep convictions regarding certain of the basic international issues today who has not at least reviewed in his mind the period of the Peloponnesian War and the Fall of Athens” (quoted in Connor 1984: 3). Michael Howard, writing in 1984, suggested that a thousand years thence, historians may conclude of the late twentieth century: “What made war inevitable was the growth of Soviet power and the fear which this caused in the United States” (Howard 1984:102). Robert Gilpin (1988:15) is typical of more recent readers. He notes that “Thucydides’ theory of hegemonic war constitutes one of the central organizing ideas for the [modern-day] study of International Relations.” Gilpin adds (1981:7) that the great work, “is as meaningful a guide to the behavior of states today as when it was written in the fifth century BC.” The way that political scientists and historians respectively have treated Thucydides’ “inevitability” assertion about the circle of power, fear, and violence is emblematic of a “great debate” between the two disciplines which will figure throughout this study. Abandoning the obvious and embracing a single cause or type of cause, Thucydides took a crucial step in the direction of science. For here was the suggestion that a consistent underlying phenomenon produced the war. Thucydides suggested that the “truest cause” did not lie in the individual offenses and grievances that preceded the conflicts, indeed the real reason would be “most likely to be disguised by such an argument” (Thucydides 1972:49). Yet while students of international politics have been quick to recognize the political scientist in Thucydides, his talk of inevitabilities warming the cockles of their hearts, historians have been intrigued that the Athenian in his new-found rigor should insist on a single truest cause for the war. Why the parsimony? By viewing all twenty-seven years of conflict as a single war, was Thucydides barred from assigning different causes to different parts of it? Is his pronouncement unhistorical in its reductionism? “Is this a statement of social psychology, or an assertion of
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 37
inevitability?,” asks one historian. “Where does it leave responsibility for the war?” (Murray 1986:194). Other factors were at work: Thucydides enumerated several lesser causes. However, the “theory” he settled on, and which realists echo, is that the war was caused by the imbalance of classical power. After Thucydides, no thinker influenced the realists more than Machiavelli did. The Florentine’s notorious “how-to” for rulers, The Prince (1532), is sometimes cited as having sparked the realists’ love affair with power as well as their devilish ethics. More importantly, Machiavelli invented a way of thinking about the interconnectedness of history, reality, and “policy,” which remains at the core of modern realism. Machiavelli was concerned with la verità effetuale (things as they really are). He was going for reality, and not for its shadows. In what may have been a barb at Plato, he noted, “many writers have imagined for themselves republics and principalities that have never been seen nor known to exist in reality; for there is such a gap between how one lives and how one ought to live that anyone who abandons what is done for what ought to be done learns his ruin rather than his preservation” (Machiavelli 1979:126–7). Well-ordered states (stati bene ordinati) were to be fashioned not on transcendent principles or a paradigm laid down in heaven, but on experience. Machiavelli thus became the first political theorist deliberately to ground his ideas in discourse on the nature of history and historical events. Where did Machiavelli’s ideas come from? In short, they were derived from the classics as read in the dim light of a murderous and coup-ridden fifteenth-century Florence. This was the cusp of the Renaissance. Emerging from the long Medieval night, Machiavelli pored over the “histories” of Polybius, Xenophon, Tacitus, and Livy, reaping their lessons and rendering them in contemporary form. Thus, while Machiavelli’s Prince was more a mythical work, his Discourses on Livy (1531) was a compendium of inductive historical gleanings designed to be useful. Indeed, he claimed that Italy’s ailments stemmed in large part from not possessing a proper knowledge of histories, for in reading them we do not draw out of them that sense or taste that flavor which they have in themselves… Wishing, therefore, to free men of this erroneous way of thinking, I deemed it necessary to write about all those books by Livy which the malignity of time has not taken from us…to draw from them that practical knowledge one should seek from an acquaintance with history books. (Machiavelli 1979:170–1)2 In this, Machiavelli was nothing if not modern. Indeed, he likened his own discoveries in politics to the discovery of the New World. Enlivened by the budding Renaissance focus on man’s role in controlling and shaping the world around him, his quarrying of the past was a case of active rather than contemplative history. Machiavelli’s methods were secular, scientific, and empirical, concerned with causes and effects and aimed at setting out the means to assigned ends. Machiavelli expressed his modern ideas in a new vocabulary of action and science. The prince
38 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
was the “new prince,” who had seized power rather than inherited it. He pitted his virtù—courage, masculinity, skill, excellence, ability, audacity, ingenuity—against the fickle forces of what Machiavelli called fortuna, which we might think of today as the contingent and accidental in history. These modern ideas were nevertheless to be accompanied by reverence for the ancient customs. Machiavelli found it expedient to mythologize classical honor and glory, and set them against the decadence and corruption of the present, a type of moralism or nostalgia not unknown in modern realism. The most important concept in Machiavelli is that of necessità, or political necessity. For Machiavelli, history was in constant, recurrent motion. Politics involved ceaseless struggle, with no lasting repose, and no prince would succeed who did not respond with cunning and vigor. The idea of necessity has developed into the general “realist” principle that the nature of international politics sharply limits the range of statesmen’s moral and practical choices, and that when the survival of the state is deemed to be in jeopardy, choice all but disappears. For this, Machiavelli has been cited as the originator of the doctrine of raison d’état, which holds that because the state is supreme in the hierarchy of ethics, whatever means are necessary to protect the well-being of the state are ipso facto justified (see Smith 1986: 10–12). Machiavelli’s reason-of-state argument was not simply a moral apology for power, however, but was propelled by a germ of Italian nationalism (italianità), this too being a new idea. In a passage from The Prince, titled “An Exhortation to Liberate Italy from the Barbarians,” he quoted from Livy, “Here justice is great: Only those wars that are necessary are just, and arms are sacred when there is not hope except through arms” (Machiavelli 1979:163). Livy’s words, written fourteen centuries earlier in the defense of Rome, were thus extended to the plight of Machiavelli’s own beloved Italy, caught unprotected in the midst of the ultramontane wars. In this way, classical ideas bubbled up through the centuries. Taken together, Machiavelli’s historical inferences represent an important strand of civic thought on the autonomy of politics, political order and balance, liberty, law, constitutionalism, and nationalism. Individual leaders are important appendages to this body of ideas, but the state and its preservation are at its heart. In this, Machiavelli’s use of the classics affirms what Petrarch had said: “What is any history but the praise of Rome?” (quoted in Whitfield 1971:73). These early ideas about history, tragedy, and necessity have worked their way deep into modern realist thought. As Martin Wight (1966:26) summed up the realist “historical” disposition: “international politics is the realm of recurrence and repetition; it is the field in which political action is most regularly necessitous.” At this juncture, we will simply note that realists’ reading of history and their focus on recurrence and necessity have provoked sharp objections. One critic has noted that “realist historical credentials have led something of a charmed life within the discipline” (Rosenberg 1994:60). Another suggests that realists “did not believe in the future… They look back over twenty-five centuries of unbroken struggle and shake hands with Thucydides” (Booth 1995:332). Francis Fukuyama, whose own
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 39
“end of history” thesis was informed by recent headlines, asserts that “realists talk as if history did not exist” (Fukuyama 1992:246). The uses of tragedy: Reinhold Niebuhr’s theology of history Contemporary research in international relations is largely concerned with generating good “data,” developing new models, and testing “scientific” hypotheses. Why, then, study the philosophy of history of an American heartland theologian with whom most students in the field are barely, if at all, acquainted? The answer is this: in Niebuhr, we find a view of history and of human nature from which even the most “empirical” renderings of political realism are derived. Niebuhr’s philosophy points toward realism’s choice of variables, the distinction between domestic and international affairs, the chasm between individual and collective ethics, the resistance of international problems to quick fixes, the role of tragedy, the problem of the contingent in history, and the perils of historical complacency. This section, then, will provide a clear sense of where realism came from. It will also begin to suggest where and why Niebuhr’s more scientific descendants may have gone astray. Niebuhr’s sweeping philosophy has, it is true, left an ambiguous legacy. Paul Scherer, Niebuhr’s colleague at Union Theological Seminary, noted, “[Niebuhr’s] metier is to work not with miniatures but with murals…with the spread of some vast engagements on many fronts, with the impact of worlds, with the panorama of a civilization, with maps of centuries and continents in high relief” (Scherer 1984: 398). Similarly, the editors of Reinhold Niebuhr on Politics (Davis and Good 1960) described the theologian’s writings as fluid, complex, and full of “dialectical cantilevers.” “By whatever label,” they profess, “it would be very unNiebuhrian to understand Niebuhr’s thought as a fixed system. He warns against too confident and closed a science of politics… To freeze these understandings into a rigid, completely coherent system would do violence to their spirit” (Davis and Good 1960:x–xi). Niebuhr’s greatest legacy, however, may be his political ethic, a manner of moral reasoning anchored in theology but alive to the complexities and contingencies of history. This ethic—at once prophetic and pragmatic, progressive but decidedly unidealist, humane while cognizant of moral ambiguities—rests on a paradoxical conception of history as a realm of perennial conflict, but one nonetheless open to contingency and change. At the nucleus of Niebuhr’s ethic is an appreciation of tragedy. In politics, he argued, tragedy “is constituted of conscious choices of evil for the sake of good. If men or nations do evil in a good cause; if they cover themselves with guilt in order to fulfill some high responsibility; or if they sacrifice some high value for a higher or equal one they make a tragic choice” (Niebuhr 1952:vii). Tragedy must profit from the tension between what Niebuhr called the “impossible possibility” of the absolute love ethic of the Gospel and the practical demands of governance. He observed, “We know that we cannot purge ourselves of the sin and guilt in which we are involved by the moral ambiguities of politics
40 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
without also disavowing responsibility for the creative possibilities of justice” (Niebuhr 1943:284). Thus, like St. Augustine, Niebuhr offered no escape from the problems of history, but neither did he view history as inevitably tragic. Precisely because Niebuhr maintained the ethical tensions inherent in statecraft, his sensibility remains a lively corrective to triumphalism in international affairs, and to shallow thoughts on the novelty of our time. Human nature and historical contingency Niebuhr’s political theory rests on a contingent view of history. This view of history calls to mind Machiavelli’s account of the jousting of princely virtù with the swollenriver forces of fortuna. History was not subject to inevitabilities, laws, or wooden structure, and implied at best only crude cycles, patterns, and “lessons.” It conveyed no inherent logic or Aristotelian kernel that predestined its development. What mattered were the uniqueness of human experience and the endless and untold effects that one historical event had on others. As Benedetto Croce (1941:90) put it, “Every act stands altogether in relation to itself and altogether in relation to something else; it is both a point of repose and a stepping stone; and if it were not so it would be impossible to conceive the self-surpassing growth of history.” For Niebuhr, then, there were “no ‘essences’ in history because every historical configuration represents an amalgam of natural necessity and human freedom” (Niebuhr 1959:288). This duel between determinism and volun tarism flowed from Niebuhr’s wedding of the Pauline doctrine of grace and the Augustinian doctrine of sin, and the contradictions that resulted were central to Niebuhr’s anthropology. Humanity was a dual vessel: proud, selfish, brutish, lustful of power, destructive and parochial; but also bright, rational, generous, creative and spirited. The result was moral contradictions and ambiguities from the individual to the societal level. Hence, ideas about history which favored human rational potential were refuted by the darker side of humanity, while those which saw life as driven merely by necessity and greed were contradicted by humanity’s spirited and creative side. An effective theory of politics would embrace both facets of human nature, the indeterminate interplay of the two demanding a “dynamic interpretation of the social process,” and of social ethics in particular (Niebuhr 1943:245). This was, in broad outline, the aim of Niebuhr’s Gifford Lectures given at the University of Edinburgh in the spring and fall of 1939, and published as Human Nature (1941) and Human Destiny (1943). Niebuhr set out to unite sin-centered Reformation thought with more humane Renaissance concepts, hinted at in Machiavelli, which reflected the desire for the fulfillment of life in history. Niebuhr welcomed this leaven since strict Reformation thought regarded the problem of justice as wholly insoluble by reason of human sin, and hence failed to illuminate “the possibilities and limits of realizing increasing truth and goodness in every conceivable historic and social situation” (Niebuhr 1943:204–5). Together, the two series of lectures represent the full symmetry of Niebuhr’s thought. They yield a bright, yet realistic, picture of humanity and delineate the tragic tensions of the
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 41
human condition. “Life in history,” he wrote, “must be recognized as filled with indeterminate possibilities. There is no individual or interior spiritual situation, no cultural or scientific task, and no social or political problem in which men do not face new possibilities of the good and the obligation to realize them” (ibid.: 207). Niebuhr was distinctly agnostic about developments within history. Scrutiny of historiography might yield insight into contemporary problems, but experience remained a singular mix of perennial and novel events, and only the “imagination can piece together the multifarious and kaleidoscopic configurations which make up the ‘raw stuff’ of history” (Niebuhr 1963:18). Likewise, complex causality and the intrusion of the contingent undermined the predictive possibilities of social theory. “In both nature and history,” he insisted, “each new thing is only one of an infinite number of possibilities which might have emerged at that particular juncture… We can trace a series of causes in retrospect, but we can never predict the future with accuracy” (Niebuhr 1945:4). He reminded readers that only one nineteenth-century historian, Jacob Burckhardt, had foretold the sophisticated political tyrannies of the twentieth century. As part of his broader critique of utopianism, Niebuhr rejected the notion of “redemptive history”—history as the record of unequivocal progress, marching toward an idyllic historical end. True, progress occurred in the accumulation of knowledge, the perfection of technology, the mastery of the environment, and expanding economic and political cooperation. However, Niebuhr insisted that such progress in “technics” did not connote moral progress. Niebuhr spent much of his life thundering against liberal culture and its reluctance to recognize the residual strength of power and self-interest across history. “The actual achievements of man in history,” he argued, “are always corrupted by the twin evils of the tyrannical subordination of life to life and the anarchic conflict of life with life. There is therefore no pure ethical norm in history; nor any hope of history gradually purifying itself so that it will achieve this norm” (Niebuhr 1943:81). Niebuhr was also critical of the positivist idea of “mastering” history by translating the methods of the natural sciences into the social realm. Niebuhr saw this fond dream of modernity as deeply flawed. To sever politics from its roots in the humanities and plant it among the “pure” sciences was to perpetrate an epistemological charade that ultimately “obscures the grand tragic outlines of contemporary history, and offers vapid solutions for profound problems” (Niebuhr 1952:60). Niebuhr’s well-known critique of Christian pacifism was also rooted in this tension between religious ideals and political demands. Following St. Augustine’s notion of the “mournful warrior,” he believed that the assumption that nothing was worth dirty hands was both foolish and cynical. War could not be dismissed outright, but had to be weighed in terms of power, interests, and norms. The more thoroughgoing Reformation hope of such theologians as H.Richard Niebuhr (Niebuhr’s brother), Karl Barth, and Adolf Bultmann for an exclusively transcendent kingdom bred, Reinhold argued, a radical vertical dialectic between history and heaven, the absolute nature of which tended to spawn aloofness and defeatism. Niebuhr believed that such deference to providence constituted a total
42 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
denial of political necessity, thus “destroy[ing] the tension between the final demands of God upon the conscience and all the relative possibilities for realizing the good in history” (Niebuhr 1943:195). Still, Niebuhr avoided medievalism and fatalism in his views. History was not fixed; it was an amalgam of contingency, diversity, and unity, full of possibilities. Niebuhr’s historical hopes were evident in the importance he accorded leadership, the role of ideas, and broad-based political activism. According to Arthur Schlesinger, Jr., Niebuhr fashioned “liberal conclusions from Augustinian premises,” achieving in a generation a “revolution in the bases of American liberal political thought” (Schlesinger 1984:221, 214). The possibilities of history challenged us morally, giving substance (and ambiguity) to moral life. Tragedy as historical motif Niebuhr’s Augustinian leaning is the bleakest and best-known feature of his realism. As he concluded, “Where there is history at all there is freedom, where there is freedom there is sin” (Niebuhr 1943:80). Niebuhr’s philosophy emerged in an age of disenchantment, as the First World War upended the rosy assumptions about political life that had flourished in the nineteenth century. The day before the British entered the war, Henry James wrote a friend: “The plunge of civilization into this abyss of blood and darkness… is a thing that so gives away the whole long age during which we have supposed the world to be, with whatever abatement, gradually bettering, that to have to take it all now for what the treacherous years were all the while really making for and meaning is too tragic for words” (quoted in Fussell 1975:8). Niebuhr was similarly affected. The First World War, he wrote, “made me a child of the age of disillusionment. When the war started I was a young man trying to be an optimist without falling into sentimentality. When it ended and the full tragedy of its fratricides had been revealed, I had become a realist trying to save myself from cynicism” (Niebuhr 1928:1161). The tragic ironies of that period would shadow the whole course of his thought. Niebuhr’s view of tragedy was rooted equally in an understanding of human nature and human freedom. In this, his philosophy was distinctly at odds with the leading streams of American social thought in the 1920s and 1930s: Walter Rauschenbusch’s sanguine Social Gospel and John Dewey’s scientistic pragmatism. Because their anthropology was simplistic and their politics unidimensional, neither one, Niebuhr argued, reckoned with tragedy. During his Marxist period, Niebuhr had entertained the possibility of egalitarian ideals inspiring collective virtue, but by 1939, he had grown skeptical of collective ethics, seeing wise selfinterest as the height of group morality. Through its Weberian apparatuses, the state coerces allegiance to its ends, or it may turn to the more deft methods of propaganda, symbolism, and nationalist pieties. By whatever means, the state achieved a bogus “independent centre of moral life,” before which even the moral individual bent the knee because the political order was also the source of his security (Niebuhr 1943:208). Without voices of dissent to bridle its excesses—what
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 43
Niebuhr called the “prophetic minority”—the state would collapse into cupidity and self-righteousness.3 This natural tragedy was dramatically compounded in politics, a realm marked by moral ambivalence and competing values. As A.C.Bradley notes (1950:70), It will be agreed that in all tragedy there is some sort of conflict —conflict of feelings, modes of thought, desires, wills, purpose; conflict of persons with one another, or with circumstances, or with themselves… The essential tragic fact is the self-division and intestinal warfare of the ethical substance, not so much the war of good with evil as the war of good with good. If politics were not tragic they would involve no conscience-wrenching decisions, no balancing of Jeffersonian “great goods,” no moral reasoning. Antimonious goods bid for political precedence: sovereignty and multilateralism, principle and interest, order and justice, liberty and community. It seems less strange, then, that Niebuhr should have advocated tragedy in political life. He argued that great leaders had always made tragic choices among competing principles, and suggested that when statecraft was stripped of tragedy it turned sentimental and faddish. The conduct of foreign affairs was at heightened risk. While the ambiguities of domestic political decisions were perhaps more immediately apparent, with distance and ignorance came a dangerous moral clarity which issued in simplism, abstraction, and ideology. This “sloganization” of foreign policy demonized foreign leaders or entire political systems, while at the same time falsely inflating a nation’s own virtue. In his tragic realism, Niebuhr cleaved to the Augustinian adage: “The peace of the world is based on strife.” The persistence of power and conflict across political history was both a source of tragedy and a point of paradox. Power could be harnessed and beguiled, but never fully eliminated from communal life. As he observed, “Society merely cumulates the egoism of individuals and transmutes their individual altruism into collective egoism so that the egoism of the group has a double force. For this reason no group acts from purely unselfish or even mutual intent and politics is therefore bound to be a contest of power” (Niebuhr 1953:363). Against this backdrop, Niebuhr viewed the balance of power, that archetypal tragic construct, as an irreplaceable international strategy. In contrast to the natural order, which entailed an organic balance, in history this equilibrium could only be a tragic human artifice. This view sets Niebuhr apart from the more scientific and structural realists who succeeded him. The balance was nonetheless fraught with ambiguities, and hinged on historical contingencies. It was “a principle of justice in so far as it prevents domination and enslavement; but it is a principle of anarchy and conflict in so far as its tensions, if unresolved, result in overt conflict” (Niebuhr 1943:266). Order was given priority, but the balance was not an end in itself. Rather, the balance was the sine qua non underpinning the higher good of justice: “There has never been a scheme of justice in history which did not have a balance of power at its foundation” (Niebuhr 1940:104).
44 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Although he accepted this tragic side of the quest for justice, Niebuhr vowed to temper its pursuit. In “speaking truth to power,” he stressed power’s dark ironies and illusions, warning that a nation, however virtuous, may become the mirror image of its foe if it crudely opposed power with power. In The Irony of American History (1952) he quoted from a letter John Adams wrote to Jefferson: “Power always thinks it has a great soul and vast views beyond the comprehension of the weak; and that it is doing God’s service when it is violating all His laws. Our passions, ambitions, avarice, love and resentment, etc., possess so much metaphysical subtlety and so much overpowering eloquence that they insinuate themselves into the understanding and the conscience and convert both to their party” (Niebuhr 1952: 21). Niebuhr echoed Lord Acton’s warnings about the seductive sway of power. While only power could mitigate abuses of power, this mitigation could never be exercised with easy conscience. It was perhaps for this reason that Niebuhr so seldom spoke of just war, which might too easily rationalize killing. Consider Niebuhr’s translation of this ethic into the nuclear age, a time, as Stanley Hoffmann (1987:449) notes, when “tragedy may blot out meaning.” Characteristically, Niebuhr referred to the nuclear dilemma as “the ‘balance of terror’ by the grace of which we have a precarious peace” (quoted in Bennett 1982: 93). He expressed grave moral doubts about nuclear weapons, noting that “if we ever made first use of such a bomb we would annihilate our civilization morally in the process of defending it physically,” but had little political timidity about their possession (Niebuhr 1950a: 7). Tragedy and irony buttressed an orthodox deterrence ethic: build atomic weapons but foreswear their first use. Underlying that ethic, however, was a rare understanding of atomic weaponry, namely, that the West’s nuclear foreign policy was no less morally ambiguous by virtue of its relative justice vis-à-vis the Soviets. Indeed, that an “innocent” nation had become steeped in nuclear guilt was for Niebuhr one of the great ironies of the American experience. Niebuhr’s realism arguably deepened in the face of absolute power. While it is true that Niebuhr consistently criticized as naive movement toward unilateral disarmament and a non-nuclear foreign policy, by 1950 he was convinced that however distasteful, a long-term modus vivendi with the Soviets had become a tragic necessity. With time, and with Stalin’s death, Niebuhr would temper his anticommunism and turn an ironic eye on American cold war politics and culture. He was critical of US leaders who were blind to the necessary precariousness of coexistence, and was outraged by John Foster Dulles’s hypocritical moralism, which he saw as a monstrous twisting of the Christian tradition. He also criticized the imprudence of Dulles’s “brinkmanship,” and excoriated considerations of preventive nuclear war, insisting that nuclear war was inconceivable and that the superpowers shared a common responsibility for averting disaster. He was sharply critical as well of Henry Kissinger’s apparently serious consideration, in a volume published by the Council on Foreign Relations, of a “tactical” nuclear war in Europe. Niebuhr almost certainly would have denounced, perhaps on grounds of both economic justice and strategic prudence, more recent American policies of “multiplying” nuclear deterrence.4
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 45
The fallacy of historical determinism Despite its recurrence in history, tragedy was not inevitable. Niebuhr’s critique of determinism in history prefaced Isaiah Berlin’s famous denunciation of historical inevitability. The turn to determinism, Berlin (1959:77–8) wrote, “springs from a desire to resign our responsibility, to cease from judging provided we be not judged and above all be not compelled to judge ourselves, from a desire to flee for refuge to some vast amoral, impersonal whole of nature or history.” While essentially agreeing with Berlin, Niebuhr nonetheless challenged the Oxford philosopher’s failure to move beyond the negative task of confronting deterministic presumptions (see Niebuhr 1955: 24). Lest it be seen as irrevocably pessimistic, Niebuhr distinguished his view of tragedy from tragic determinism, as a too consistent reliance on the “tragedy” of things could degenerate into cynicism and violence. Most importantly, every form of historical determinism, including the idea of political necessity, robbed people of moral responsibility. As Niebuhr wrote in a 1950 article in World Politics: Even when the historic situation is as tragic as our contemporary one, and when a careful estimation of historic probabilities is bound to lead to more pessimistic than optimistic conclusions, we have no right to speak of “inevitabilities” in history. Men are always agents, and not merely the stuff, in the historical process. If modern culture has been inclined, at times, to overestimate the power of the human will over historical destiny, there is yet no reason we should abdicate the responsibility of that will in this tragic hour. (Niebuhr 1950b: 338–9) The furthest irony of Niebuhrian tragedy was that, from a theological perspective, history both was and was not tragic: “Life remains self-contradictory in its sin, no matter how high human culture rises; that the highest expression of human spirituality, therefore, contains also the subtlest form of human sin. The failure to recognise this fact, and nothing more, is to reduce history to simple tragedy. But the basic message of Christian faith is a message of hope in tragedy” (Niebuhr 1937: 18–19). This was the leaven in Niebuhr’s realism, and it was here that he clashed with more thoroughgoing realists, whom he accused of underappreciating the resilience of the human spirit, even under the strain of necessity. “I do not think we will sacrifice any value in the ‘realist’ approach to the political order,” Niebuhr wrote (1962: 102) in a perhaps too strong rejoinder to Hans Morgenthau, “if we define [it] in terms which do not rob it of moral content.” The Structure of Nations and Empires In his final and in some ways most ambitious book, The Structure of Nations and Empires (1959), Niebuhr attempted through a sweeping view of history “to describe the historical constants and variables in the dominion of nations and empires” (p.
46 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
8). Several observations may be made about the volume, as Niebuhr’s inquiry demonstrates the link between his broader philosophy and his “empirical” historical views. Niebuhr’s stated purpose was to edify a “young nation suddenly flung to a position of world responsibility by its great power,” and specifically to demonstrate that neither Soviet imperialism nor its connection to the secular creed of communism was without precedent (p. ix). He argued that Soviet empire-builders shared a great deal in common with imperial rulers from Babylon, Persia, Pagan and Christian Rome, medieval Islam, the Spanish and British empires, the Egyptians, and the Aztecs. In each case, imperial authority rested not simply on the rational application of power, but was fused with the prestige and “majesty” derived from the identification of political order with divine order. Niebuhr found recurrent tensions between order and justice, between the desire to conquer and coerce, and the craving for the equality and liberty of a true political community. He saw a pattern of the “integral” community, whether city-state or nation, giving way to the larger structure of dominion, the empire. However, he also claimed that the growth of freedom imparted a “forward movement” to history —it, too, was fraught with ambiguities, chiefly the “permanent moral embarrassment” of pretension and excess in maintaining any political order (p. 2). The contingent view prevailed. To the annoyance of philosophers of history as well as political scientists, Niebuhr’s historical patterns—mirroring his portrayal of social life in general—were in fact streams of contradiction and indeterminacy, of history as a mix of contrivance and tradition, the universal and the particular. “History,” he wrote, “is a realm in which human freedom and natural necessity are curiously intermingled. Man’s freedom constantly creates the most curious and unexpected and unpredictable emergences and emergencies in history. All efforts to discern patterns of recurrence, after the manner of Spengler and Toynbee, or patterns of development, in the fashion of Hegel, Spencer, or Comte, must do violence to the infinite variety in the strange configurations of history” (p. 7). Niebuhr was skeptical of the Marxist interpretation of history, built as it was atop the French physiocratic theory that nature and history were equally subject to absolute laws. Such “idealism” could be its own worst enemy. Pursued with sufficient purpose and force, the dream of an earthly paradise would almost certainly turn into a nightmare. Niebuhr also clashed with the liberalism of Locke, Smith, and Kant. He argued that Lockean liberalism was less a rationally calculated design than the product of traditional loyalties and patterns of conduct. This made it a dubious imprint for the rest of the world. Some of Niebuhr’s most caustic remarks were reserved for those “bland fanatics” who saw the “highly contingent” achievements of Western civilization as “the final form and norm of human existence” (p. 298). He argued that the Western version of the “open society” was unique, and that outside of a historic liberal framework, “free elections”—that mantra of democratic-liberalism—would be an empty phrase. As for Smith and Kant, Niebuhr argued that the anatomy of sovereignty hindered the emergence of economically, morally, and politically autonomous individuals. People remained bound to, and by, political groups.
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 47
Similarly, this was not a scientific treatise on imperialism. With the exception of Britain’s relatively benign “missionary motive,” Niebuhr centered on the consequences and expressions of dominion, rather than on why empires rise and fall. Perhaps overly sensitive to the communist indictment of Western capitalism as inherently imperialistic, Niebuhr downplayed the economic impetus, and his discussions of colonialism in Latin America, Africa, and Ireland are not his most perceptive. He was clearly convinced of “the moral superiority of British imperialism,” not least because the British eventually departed, leaving behind a sound administrative structure and maintaining commonwealth ties. In terms of the causes of imperialism, Niebuhr maintained that motives were always mixed. Religion, economics, and glory were important inducements to empire, although not in any fixed proportions or under any specified conditions. The British, for example, had wed Milton’s conception of “God’s Englishman” to an eye for profit, but “manners” entered into it as well. As that mouthpiece of imperialism, Sir Thomas Raffles, put it: “Britain leads the fashion and gives the law” (p. 206). However, the main burden of Structures of Nations and Empires was to shed light on contemporary Russian imperialism. On this point, the book is a good example of the pitfalls of relying too consistently on historical analogies, or, put more sharply, of working backward from present-day opinion to historical analogue. Niebuhr held that all empires had been buttressed by ideology. He noted how Cicero had extolled the protection (patrocinium) the Roman empire afforded; how Seneca had falsified facts in lauding Nero; how the Chinese empire rested on a “Confucian monarchy”; how the Christian empire under Constantine had “combin [ed] the genius of the Caesars with the spirit of Christ,” and used religion to mask its crimes and exalt its rule; how Eusebius of Caesarea, Constantine’s chief apologist, had turned the ruler’s enemies into the “enemies of truth,” for which Burckhardt pronounced him “the most consistently dishonest historian of antiquity” (pp. 93– 5); how even Thomas Aquinas had been flexible in his moral estimation of the papal empire in the thirteenth century, and had projected the idolatry of the Church onto the secular empire. Niebuhr painted these apologists and dissemblers as the forerunners of the early Soviet ideologists—Lenin, Zinoviev, Kamenev, Trotsky, Stalin, and Sokol’nikov. Niebuhr found a strict monotheistic faith to be the best imperial cement. Ideally, the ruler held both the keys to power and the keys to heaven. Whereas religiously pluralistic or polytheistic empires had to rely on their own imperial structures as the ultimate arbiter of authority, under monotheism, power and authority were indivisible. The emperor invokes the direct mandate of one true god. In his sprint through imperial history, Niebuhr lingered longest on the great medieval empire of Islam, stretching from Córdoba to Baghdad. He found the analogy to contemporary communism striking. He linked up Islamic fanaticism with the priestkings of “Holy Russia,” and Muscovy as the seat of Orthodox Christianity with Mecca. “Communism,” Niebuhr noted, “is a religion within the framework of a modern secular culture in which the ‘logic of history’ takes the place of Allah as the absolute source of meaning, and the writings of Marx and Lenin become the
48 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
sacred texts, analogous to the Koran” (p. 117). Both systems, Niebuhr argued, mingled religious zeal and military prowess. Both converted conquered peoples to the faith and integrated them into a “theocratic” state. Both were totalitarian. As Schumpeter had noted, Islam “determined daily conduct, shaped the whole world outlook…permeated the mentality of the believer, made him someone who was characteristically different from all other men, [and] opened up an unbridgeable gulf between him and the infidel, turning the latter into the arch enemy with whom there could be no true peace.” Niebuhr determined that in communism, as in medieval Islam, this totalitarian impulse produced “an almost demonic historical dynamism” (p. 117). Of course, the Soviet government was nothing if not a gang of mullahs, steeped in dogma and canonical texts. However, communism remained an elitist creed that did not easily displace or insinuate itself into local religions and myths. Given the coercive nature of Russian rule, the idea that the denizens of the Soviet Republics were “converts” to communism seems far-fetched. The parallel with Islamic history invested the Soviet Union with a false vitality, pumping up the achievements of militant communism, and transforming the Red Army into a sea of jihad warriors. With the luxury of hindsight, it is clear that Niebuhr credited Soviet policies with more consistency than they deserved. He overstated the success of the Russification of the Soviet Republics. He was particularly impressed that Moscow’s tentacles had reached as far as the Islamic schools of Tashkent, which had fallen under communist administration. He claimed that “the Russian bloc is certainly more cohesive than our own,” without considering the fragility that might imply (p. 28). His focus on the majesty of the state and the grandeur of dogma also led him to overestimate the awe with which the Third World held the Soviet Union. He insisted that “the Russians have all the immediate advantages in the Middle East and in Asia and Africa” (p. 281). Generally, Niebuhr’s surface history issued in surface pronouncements about the contemporary scene, conferring greater credence on ideology than was warranted, and exaggerating the Russian appetite for war. We shall see in the next chapter that Hans Morgenthau more coolly assessed the Soviet creed as a way of veiling oldfashioned power, while George Kennan’s profound understandings of the Russian experience prompted him to emphasize the historic burdens of empire as opposed to its vitality. Structures of Nations and Empires ends on a note of sober optimism. In keeping with his open-ended view of history, Niebuhr wonders whether independent centers of Russian power would not emerge; whether the Central Committee of the Communist Party would not ultimately check the power of the Executive, much as the Whig lords had done in England in the eighteenth century; whether the Soviet success in the realm of education might turn the citizenry against the regime. The nuclear age underscored how history had not resolved the problem of political order, but rather had enlarged it. “Our best hope,” Niebuhr wrote, “rests upon our ability to observe the limits of human freedom even while we responsibly exploit its creative possibilities” (p. 299).
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 49
Niebuhr assessed Even in these words, it is clear that Niebuhr offered no precise science of politics or paradigmatic moral method. Both science and ethics would have to contend with the inconclusive character of history. Niebuhr’s historical “rumination” was distinctly paradoxical. Although he sought in religion what Burckhardt calls the “Archimedean point outside events,” from which the meaning of history might be discerned, he maintained that history was stubbornly enigmatic, that “no ultimate sense of the meaning of life is rationally compelling” (Niebuhr 1984:17). History revealed flashes of coherence and moral meaning, but no clear pattern. Politics did not constitute a series of rational calculations. Nor could political ideas be entombed in doctrine. Niebuhr’s moral and historical judgment represented a sort of “prophetic pragmatism,” a dialectical approach to politics whose two faces paralleled the respective theses of the Human Nature and Human Destiny Gifford Lectures. His philosophy comprised human frailty, collective excess, state-centered foreign affairs, the tendency of states to trumpet parochial aims as universal norms, and the ideological cloaking of the pursuit of national interests, and at its most strident characterized social life as “a perpetual state of war” (Niebuhr 1932:19). Alongside these “realist” precepts, Niebuhr invoked a traditional normative theory that transcended interests and conflict in the name of justice. Taken together, these contradictory impulses represented an ethical sensibility animated by specific problems in the context of historical contingency and change. Ultimately, relativism was the authentic political experience. “The trials and tribulations of history are sometimes better schoolmasters than any amount of moral precept,” Niebuhr noted (1942:1). Other times, presumably, they were not. Distilling a formal ethical stance from this historical mix of power, interests, ideals, and ambiguities required a prudential judgment cognizant of the moral and strategic complexities of statecraft, but which nonetheless transcended satisfaction with the status quo. As Niebuhr concluded (1932:4), “Politics will, to the end of history, be an area where conscience and power meet, where the ethical and coercive factors of human life will interpenetrate and work out their tentative and uneasy compromises.” As you like it: E.H.Carr and historical relativism The English historian and diplomat E.H.Carr carried forward this relative and contingent view of history and politics. Carr wrote biographies of Dostoevsky, Marx, and Bakunin, works on nationalism, socialism, and revolution, and a 10volume history of Soviet Russia. The focus here will be on two other works of Carr’s: Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939 (1939; 2nd ed. 1946), a strikingly original analysis of international power and morality, and What Is History? (1961), a seminal statement on historical philosophy and method. Carr stands apart from the other realists for his “sociology of knowledge.” This is the idea, derived from Karl Marx’s German Ideology (1846), that man is a product of his surroundings, and that ultimately all knowledge, including historical knowledge, is contingent upon social
50 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
and economic forces. Carr’s sociology and general irreverence make him perhaps the field’s sharpest observer of power and ideology masquerading as truth. Political beliefs did not correspond to absolute and a priori principles, but were “the product of circumstances and interests and weapons framed for the furtherance of interests” (Carr 1946:68). Carr was bold enough to suggest that realism could not monopolize truth either. Realism, he wrote, “often turns out in practice to be just as much conditioned as any other mode of thought. In politics, the belief that certain facts are unalterable or certain trends irresistible commonly reflects a lack of desire or lack of interest to change or resist them” (ibid.: 89). Twenty Years’ Crisis borrowed liberally from Niebuhr’s Moral Man and Immoral Society. Carr wished to see “utopianism penetrate the citadel of realism,” a problem he said that Niebuhr had analyzed “with almost cynical clearsightedness” (ibid.: 91). He cited from Moral Man: “Without the ultrarational hopes and passions of religion, no society will have the courage to conquer despair and attempt the impossible; for the vision of a just society is an impossible one, which can be approximated only by those who do not regard it as impossible. The truest visions of religion are illusions, which may be partly realised by being resolutely believed” (ibid.: 91). This passage mirrored Carr’s own outlook. Unlike Niebuhr, however, Carr’s values were to be found in history and not outside of history. His theology was the idea of progress. He saw history as linear rather than cyclical, and it was this belief that unleashed his hopes for a fundamental restructuring of the international system. “Cliché for cliché” he noted of the maxims surrounding the historian’s craft, “I should prefer the one about freeing oneself from ‘the dead hand of the past’” (Carr 1961:29). Twenty Years’ Crisis: sociology of knowledge and the utopian critique Carr’s critique of inter-war idealism rested on the theories of Karl Mannheim. Mannheim had attempted to transform the Marxist idea of the “false consciousness” of the defenders of the status quo into a general tool of social analysis. He argued that knowledge was never disinterested and detached. One’s ideas were the product of one’s place in the social and historical fabric. The task of critical theory was to unmask this “sociology of knowledge,” and thus arrive at a clearer understanding of the relation between interests and ideas. As Mannheim asserted in Ideology and Utopia (1936), critical “political discussion, is from the very first…the tearing off of disguises” (quoted in Buzan et al. 1993:176). This is an apt metaphor for Carr’s Twenty Years’ Crisis, which set out to unmask the chief creed of nineteenth-century international politics, namely the harmony of interests. The book argued brilliantly that ideology followed interest. In a world of haves and have nots, the haves make the laws and fix the principles. Carr saw the doctrine of the harmony of interests arising from Jeremy Bentham’s “felicific calculus” of “the greatest happiness good for the greatest number,” wedded to Adam Smith’s laissez-faire faith that an “invisible hand” directed selfish interests to the
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 51
common good. In politics, this issued in several cardinal beliefs: by pursuing their own interests, states thereby furthered the interests of the international community; all nations shared an interest in peace; conquest did not pay; right thinking would lead to right action; any clash of interests was the result of wrong calculation. As Norman Angell had argued in The Great Illusion (1914), war was simply a “failure of understanding” (p. 25). Carr noted that it was also a common tactic of the privileged to “throw moral discredit on the under-privileged by depicting them as disturbers of the peace.” He quoted Arnold Toynbee on a particular crisis: “International law and order…were in the true interests of the whole of mankind… whereas the desire to perpetuate the region of violence in international affairs was an anti-social desire which was not even in the ultimate interests of the citizens of the handful of states that officially professed this benighted and anachronistic creed” (p. 83). Carr protested that the harmony of interests was not an absolute verity, but was an ideology that had served to buttress the competitive capitalism and colonial rule of Victorian England. It was “an ingenious moral device invoked, in perfect sincerity, by privileged groups in order to justify and maintain their dominant position” (p. 80). Carr extended this critique of the “adjustment of thought to purpose” to the general tendency of states to couch parochial pursuits in universalist dogma. The sanctity of treaties, the primacy of peace, the obligations of the Covenant of the League of Nations: these were not eternal principles but reflected the entrenched interests of the Goliath powers. “Free trade” was the paradise of the economically strong, “solidarity” and “internationalism” the rhetoric of empire, and “peace through law” the cty of satisfied states. As Carr noted, these principles were “but the unconscious reflexions of national policy based on a particular interpretation of national interest at a particular time” (p. 87). While adherents of “utopian internationalism” accepted the nostrums of nineteenth-century politics as universal, Carr retorted that they were bankrupt and dangerously nostalgic. With the emergence of regional power centers and autarkic states these principles no longer applied. Yet, international studies remained encumbered by this ideological hangover from the Victorian Age. After 1914, Carr explained, “men’s minds naturally fumbled their way back, in search of a new utopia, to those apparently firm foundations of nineteenth-century peace and security” (p. 26). The prism of progress Carr’s sociology of knowledge led him to discern history as it was not understood at the time. Twenty Years’ Crisis illustrates the unwitting nature of interwar principles and pronouncements: they were in fact the products of power, economics, and collective psychology. Carr apparently seemed to follow an orthodox “realist” approach to using history in political science. He was explicit about the importance of grounding theory in history: “The utopian, fixing his eyes on the future, thinks in terms of creative spontaneity: the realist, rooted in the past, in terms of causality” (p. 11). He cited Machiavelli’s verità effetuale as one of the “foundation-stones” of
52 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
the realist method, suggesting that the Florentine was the first thinker to view “history [as] a sequence of cause and effect, whose course can be analysed and understood by intellectual effort, but not (as the utopians believe) directed by ‘imagination’” (p. 63). Nevertheless, Carr argued that the whole enterprise of political science sprang from Seeley’s aphorism that “history is past politics, and politics present history.” Carr would later note of this approach: All this implies, of course, a somewhat old-fashioned belief in the lessons of history. Everyone knows the quip that “one learns nothing from history except that one learns nothing from history”; and we have all heard of the generals and admirals who were busy fighting the previous war. It is inherent in the human condition that lessons are sometimes wrongly learnt, or the wrong lessons learnt. The positivist notion of a cast-iron structure of facts clamped down on the passive and disembodied observer will not withstand scrutiny, and has been discarded both by the historian and by the scientist. The writing of history, like any other form of human inquiry is a process of selection and interpretation intimately bound up with the preoccupations, preconceptions, and prejudices—what is more politely called the ideology—of the investigator. Ideology is the point where history and politics meet. (Carr 1975:246) Carr’s skepticism was rooted in the idealist epistemological tradition of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Like Dilthey, Croce, Collingwood, Beard, Oakeshott, and Becker, Carr held that “the social sciences— and history among them —cannot accommodate themselves to a theory of knowledge which puts subject and object asunder, and enforces a rigid separation between the observer and the thing observed” (Carr 1961:158). Knowledge was not merely given, discoverable with increased effort or superior training. It was the product of shifting social circumstances. Carr was likewise concerned with supplanting the “fact fetishism” of the Rankean school. He insisted that “the historian is necessarily selective. The belief in a hard core of historical facts existing objectively and independently of the interpretation of the historian is a preposterous fallacy, but one which it is very hard to eradicate” (ibid.: 10). His likening of historical facts to fish on a fishmonger’s slab was noted earlier. Nonetheless, Carr believed that the historian’s task was to “master and understand [the past] as the key to the understanding of the present” (ibid.: 29). The rigorous historian would build hypotheses, search for historical laws, and develop analogies. He or she would consider a “multiplicity of causes” yet “work through the simplification, as well as through the multiplication, of causes” (ibid.: 116–18). He did not believe, however, that Rankean objectivity was possible. Instead, he subscribed to what Mannheim termed “relational objectivity.” As Carr describes it: “the facts of history cannot be purely objective, since they become facts of history only in virtue of the significance attached to them by the historian. Objectivity in history—if we are still to use the conventional term—cannot be an objectivity of fact,
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 53
but only of relation, of the relations between fact and interpretation, between past, present, and future” (ibid.: 159). Hence, “objective” history required first, frank recognition of the relativity of knowledge teamed with the imagination to surpass these limits. Carr (ibid.: 163) required the historian to “rise above the limited vision of [one’s] own situation in society and in history.” Histories proved important and enduring to the degree that their author succeeded in this. Second, the “objective” historian must have the capacity to project his vision into the future. Carr argued that the historian’s standards of significance and relevance will be validated or invalidated teleologically, for history was a “progressive science” which moved toward broader and deeper insights into the course of events. Like Hegel and Marx—indeed, like many of the utopians he skewered Carr settled on the idea of progress as the principle upon which history was to be based. In What Is History? he approvingly quoted Acton that progress is “the scientific hypothesis on which history is to be written.” “History properly so-called,” Carr wrote, “can be written only by those who find and accept a sense of direction in history itself. The belief that we have come from somewhere is closely linked with the belief that we are going somewhere. A society which has lost belief in its capacity to progress in the future will quickly cease to concern itself with its progress in the past.” He added that modern historiography could not survive without faith in progress, “since it is this belief which provides it with its standard of significance, its touchstone for distinguishing between the real and the accidental” (ibid.: 176, 165). In this, we are to believe that Carr had discovered a point within events from which to judge history. He essentially recasts Niebuhr in a secular mold: The absolute in history is not something in the past from which we start; it is not something in the present, since all present thinking is necessarily relative. It is something still incomplete and in process of becoming— something in the future towards which we move, which in the light of which, as we move forward, we gradually shape our interpretation of the past. This is the secular truth behind the religious myth that the meaning of history will be revealed in the day of judgment. (ibid.: 160–1) In short, the historian’s task was to fit past events into a pattern of progress. Carr never shrank from defending the idea of progress against bloodless skeptics and political scientists. He ended What Is History? affirmatively: Sir Lewis Namier warns me to eschew programmes and ideals, and Professor Oakeshott tells me that we are going nowhere in particular and that all that matters is to see that nobody rocks the boat, and Professor Popper wants to keep that dear old T-model on the road by dint of a little piecemeal engineering, and Professor TrevorRoper knocks screaming radicals on the nose, and Professor Morison pleads for history written in a sane conservative
54 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
spirit. I shall look out on a world in tumult and a world in travail, and shall answer in the well-worn words of a great scientist: “And yet—it moves.” (ibid.: 208–9) In Twenty Years’ Crisis, history also moves, in dialectical fashion. This should not be unexpected. As Carr argues, The political process does not consist, as the realist believes, purely in a succession of phenomena governed by mechanical laws of causation; nor does it consist, as the utopian believes, purely in the application to practice of certain theoretical truths evolved out of their inner consciousness by wise and far-seeing people. Political science must be based on a recognition of the interdependence of theory and practice, which can be attained only through a combination of utopia and reality. (p. 13) Pressing the point, Carr starkly juxtaposed different historical and ideological models: utopia and reality, purpose and fact, freedom and necessity, theory and practice, intellectuals and bureaucrats, Left and Right, ethics and politics. Given his emphasis on the conditions of knowledge, Carr’s “evidence” is drawn chiefly from the history of political thought and expression, presumably the best barometer of the “realities” of the time. On the utopian side, he mocked the “idealist” statesmen, noting, for example, how Robert Cecil had assured the Assembly of the League of Nations in 1931 that “there has scarcely ever been a period in the world’s history when war seemed less likely than it does at the present” (p. 36); how Norman Angell had moralized about “muddled thinking” as the barrier to world order (p. 39); how Sir John Simon had appealed to the power of public opinion during the Manchurian crisis. Simon told the House of Commons, “when public opinion, world opinion, is sufficiently unanimous to pronounce a firm moral condemnation, sanctions are not needed” (p. 36). Carr noted derisively that “Woodrow Wilson’s ‘plain men throughout the world,’ the spokesmen of ‘the common purpose of enlightened mankind,’ had somehow transformed themselves into a disorderly mob emitting incoherent and unhelpful noises” (p. 38). Carr then interpreted: “The simplicity of these explanations seemed almost ludicrously disproportionate to the intensity and complexity of the international crisis… The breakdown of the nineteen-thirties was too overwhelming to be explained merely in terms of individual action or inaction. Its downfall involved the bankruptcy of the postulates on which it was based” (p. 40). Carr contrasted idealism with an extreme realism, which he identified with Thrasymachus and the Athenian generals (“justice is the right of the stronger”), and with the stance, derived from a pedestrian reading of Machiavelli, that “morality is the product of power…ethics become, in the last analysis, the study of reality” (pp. 63–5). Carr’s realism also enlisted Jean Bodin, Hobbes, Francis Bacon, Baruch Spinoza, Hegel, Oswald Spengler, and the German Geopolitik historical school,
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 55
probably a reference to Ranke, Kjellen, Treitschke, and others. Lenin’s realism is cited: “politics…have their own objective logic independent of the prescriptions of this or that individual or party” (p. 66); as is Engels’ dictum that “without force and iron ruthlessness nothing is achieved in history” (p. 102). Carr suggests that Schopenhauer had aptly summed up the realist view of history as “consist[ing] of the insight that, throughout the jumble of all these ceaseless changes, we have ever before our eyes the same unchanging being, pursuing the same course to-day, yesterday, and forever.” “Realism,” in short, was an overly determined and pessimistic mode of thought, devoid of any spur to purposive or meaningful action, and “plainly repugnant to the most deep-seated belief of man about himself” (p. 92). As Hedley Bull once pointed out (1969b:628), Carr’s lively method bears all the characteristic defects of a polemical essay. Carr’s fund of historical illustrations vastly overstates ideological and pragmatic divisions. He drives theorists and statesmen into two opposed camps, in the process trampling historical ambiguities and subtleties of thought. History “as it really was” could never have been so neatly apportioned. Nevertheless, Carr hoped that the realist and the utopian would meet, and that international politics would evolve by way of breakthroughs set around concession and compro mise. Invoking the logic of management—labor relations in Twenty Years’ Crisis, he pointed to the notion of force majeure as a principle of peaceful change. “A successful foreign policy,” he argues, “must oscillate between the apparently opposite poles of force and appeasement” (p. 223). Carr offers remarkably few historical examples of this fine-tuned dialectical internationalism. He points to the shifts in Franco-German power relations and resultant Locarno Treaty as “a simple and revealing illustration of the working of power politics.” He argues that by 1925, “the Ruhr invasion had brought little profit to France, and had left her perplexed as to the next step. Germany might one day be powerful again. Germany, on the other hand, still feared the military supremacy of France, and hankered after a guarantee. It was the psychological moment when French fear of Germany was about equally balanced by Germany’s fear of France; and a treaty which had not been possible two years before, and would not have been possible five years later, was now welcome to both” (pp. 105–6). There was, of course, no utopianism involved here. Carr’s analysis rests solely on the “objective” power positions of France and Germany, and employs a somewhat uncomplicated view of power.5 Carr did, however, describe the Anglo-Irish pact of 1921 as a “striking success” in peaceful change based on a mixture of “yielding to threats of force,” and the “necessary moral foundation” of a “stock of common feeling” about what was “just and reasonable” in relations between the two countries, and in the readiness of both “to make sacrifices in the interest of conciliation” (pp. 220–1). Power politics and historical judgment Another of Carr’s paradigms for a successful foreign policy was the Munich settlement of 1938. Munich is now widely considered the nadir of European diplomacy in the twentieth century. Under threat from Hitler, the great powers
56 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
presided over the dismemberment of Czechoslovakia according to ethnic composition, with the Sudetenland to be ceded to Germany and other regions to go to Poland and Hungary. At the time, however, many people in Britain, France, and Germany warmly received the agreement, believing it had averted war in Europe. Carr, too, welcomed the compromise. The first edition of Twenty Years’ Crisis (1939), written in 1938 and 1939, and dedicated “to the makers of the coming peace,” contained a detailed strategic and moral justification for the settlement with “Herr Hitler.” (A.J.P.Taylor called Carr’s essay “a brilliant argument for appeasement” (quoted in Smith 1986:85).) The book was in page proof on 1 September 1939, the day Germany invaded Poland. In the preface to the book’s second, 1946, edition, Carr noted that what he had done was “to recast phrases…to modify a few sentences which have invited misunderstanding, and to remove two or three passages relating to current controversies which have been eclipsed or put into a different perspective by the lapse of time” (Carr 1946:vii). The most notorious passage which did not find its way into the 1946 edition stated: If the power relations of Europe in 1938 made it inevitable that CzechoSlovakia should lose part of her territory, and eventually her independence, it was preferable (quite apart from any question of justice or injustice) that this should come about as the result of discussion round a table in Munich rather than as the result either of a war between the Great Powers or of a local war between Germany and Czecho-Slovakia. (Smith 1986:83) Carr went on to defend the ethics of the Munich settlement as “the nearest approach in recent years to the settlement of a major international issue by a procedure of peaceful change,” which blended power politics with “the element of morality…in the form of the common recognition by the Powers, who effectively decided the issue, of a criterion applicable to the dispute: the principle of self-determination” (quoted in Smith 1986:84). Hedley Bull (1969b:627) cautioned against dwelling, “with the disadvantage of hindsight,” on Carr’s appalling misreading of Munich. The question turns on whether or not the dismemberment of Czechoslovakia was inevitable, given the fact of German power. Carr’s phrasing on this is cryptic, but his stance can perhaps be traced to a philosophy that attached a belief in the “relative and pragmatic character of thought itself” to a preoccupation with power (Carr 1946:67–8). Twenty Years’ Crisis was written “with the deliberate aim of counteracting the glaring and dangerous defect of nearly all thinking, both academic and popular, about international politics in Englishspeaking countries from 1919 to 1939—the almost total neglect of the factor of power” (ibid.: vii). Overcompensating for this defect, Carr was left without much of an anchor outside of power. This led Morgenthau (1962b: 43) to observe of Carr: “It is a dangerous thing to be a Machiavelli. It is a disastrous thing to be a Machiavelli without virtù.” Still, Carr was not alone among
HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 57
the realists in recognizing the relative standards of judgment and action. Moreover, Carr’s faith in progress, though impossible to reconcile with his insistence on power politics, cannot be dismissed. It lends a melancholy air to his conclusion that “Power goes far to create the morality convenient to itself, and coercion is a fruitful source of consent” (Carr 1946:236). Like Niebuhr, Carr never satisfactorily synthesized power and morality, but Carr did grasp how the tension between the two accounted for “the complexity, the fascination and the tragedy of all political life” (ibid.: 93). It is perhaps ironic that Carr’s sharpest critique of realism (based, as described above, on a polemical depiction of the tradition from Athens to Lenin), rested on its acceptance, without moral comment, of whatever history had in store: On the “scientific” hypothesis of the realists, reality is thus identified with the whole course of historical evolution, whose laws it is the business of the philosopher to investigate and reveal. There can be no reality outside the historical process… Condemning the past on ethical grounds has no meaning; for in Hegel’s words, “philosophy transfigures the real which appears unjust into the rational.” What was, is right. History cannot be judged except by historical standards. It is significant that our historical judgments, except those relating to a past which we can ourselves remember as the present, always appear to start from the presupposition that things could not have turned out otherwise than they did… If the American War of Independence had ended in disaster, the Founding Fathers of the United States would be briefly recorded in history as a gang of turbulent and unscrupulous fanatics. Nothing succeeds like success. “World history,” in the famous phrase which Hegel borrowed from Schiller, “is the world court.” (ibid.: 66–7) It would be wrong to accuse Carr of harboring such an amoral view of history. True, he did not foresee the elimination of power from political life. After all, political ideas—all ideas—were shaped by power. However, this did not determine the actual direction that history would take. Carr hoped that in the future power would be staked to broader aims rather than sovereign territories. “Few things are permanent in history,” he offered, “and it would be rash to think that the territorial unit of power is one of them” (ibid.: 229). In Nationalism and After (1945), Carr had history marching through a sequence of historical periods toward international cooperation, and overcoming “the catastrophic growth of nationalism and bankruptcy of internationalism,” which he believed was the chief reason for the collapse of world politics (Carr 1945:17). In the final chapter of Twenty Years’ Crisis, “Prospects for a New International Order,” Carr conceded that “it is easy to read past history as a gradual development leading up, with occasional relapses, to [the] consummation [of the nation-state],” and yet that “there is a clearly marked trend towards integration and the formation of ever larger political and economic units”
58 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
(Carr 1946:228–9). This is not the tragic cycle generally associated with realist history. Although embarking on the “hard ruthless analysis of reality which is the hallmark of science,” Carr’s assertion that social thought and action, including individual ethics, were determined by power was simply unhistorical in its reductionism (ibid.: 10). Carr captured brilliantly the grinding weight of the status quo. For this, his critique remains important and provocative, especially in this neoliberal age, where “democratization,” economic integration, and the new laissezfaire rarely receive much reflection. Still, one wonders if Carr’s insights do justice to history or theory. His relativism led him, in the Munich case, into a moral morass, but it also fueled a certain political naïveté. In The Soviet Impact on the Western World (1947:3), for example, Carr touted Soviet pluralism and command economics as the wave of the future, that “the missionary role which had been filled in the first world war by American democracy and Woodrow Wilson had passed in the second world war to Soviet democracy and Marshall Stalin.” No one would deny that intellectual activity is free of the taint of interest and conviction. Ideology may well be the point where history and politics meet, but some critical distance is both necessary and possible. Conclusion In its origins, international relations theory adhered to a complex and contingent view of history. Niebuhr and Carr expressed divergent views about human nature, the historical process, and the standards of historical judgment, yet each, through his own faith, underscores the possibilities of history. If by ‘science’ is meant a body of systematically verified beliefs that is able to transcend interest and prejudice, neither Niebuhr nor Carr was very accommodating. Niebuhr saw history as a mass of contradiction and contingency. The gravamen of Carr’s grievance against “realism,” ever since its classical wellsprings, was its determinism. In the next chapters, we will see the subtleties, paradoxes, dualisms, and contradictions inherent in early realism be eroded precisely because they are antithetical to political science. The idea that prejudice and circumstance could affect one’s views of history and historical process will be dismissed as a vestige of pre-scientific thinking. With the advent of policy realism, historical laws will begin to be erected in place of contingency, while in structural and quantitative analysis the contingent view will fade from sight.
4 HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM Hans J.Morgenthau and George F.Kennan
It was noted at the beginning of the previous chapter that the policy-oriented approach to history is at least as old as Machiavelli, whose Discourses on Livy argued for a new activism in politics guided by “the powerful examples which history shows us” (Machiavelli 1979:170). Like Machiavelli, the realists discussed in this chapter— Hans Morgenthau and George Kennan—viewed history in a political context. Social scientists may survey a large number of historical cases in the search for correlates and causes that offer generic explanations for international behavior. These practical theorists, however, set their sights on history that would be relevant to America’s burgeoning global role and the demands of the cold war. Policy realism was in this sense more a matter of prudence than of science. My task in this chapter is to trace this relationship between history, theory, and practice. I suggest that while classical realism is rich in historical detail, its portrayal of history is inseparable from the realist philosophy we have explored thus far. As Oakeshott observed, “philosophy is the world reflected in the mirror of the philosophic eye, each image the representation of a fresh object, but each determined by the character of the mirror itself” (introduction to Hobbes 1947: xix). The chapter first explores Hans Morgenthau’s method of distinguishing historical contingency from historical law, the latter being the godmother of political science. Second, I shall look at Morgenthau’s conception of the balance of power. In contrast to Niebuhr’s tragic conception, as a “scientific” theory it foreshortens historical discussion and downplays political process. It is further suggested that the appalling failures of balance-ofpower politics in the twentieth century perhaps prompted realists to idealize the attainments of the balance in past centuries. Third, the discussion takes up the problem of transforming ideas about history into political practice, focusing on the historical foundations of George Kennan’s theory of containment. Finally, the chapter revisits the tension in realist thought between science and philosophy. Between contingency and science: Hans J.Morgenthau and realist history Niebuhr and Carr toppled the idealist edifice by exposing the flaws of moral certainty and laissez-faire, but it was Hans Morgenthau who erected a systematic
60 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
realist theory to take its place. A refugee from Hitler’s Germany, Morgenthau conceived of politics in terms of power and interests, and was skeptical that law, ethics, or reason could resolve political dilemmas. “The truth of political science,” he wrote, “is the truth about power, its manifestations, its configurations, its limitations, its implications, its laws” (Morgenthau 1962a: 37). At the same time, Morgenthau recognized the “ineluctable tension” between ethical commands and political necessity, and deemed the moral evaluation of power the indispensable task of political theory. Transplanted to the gentler soil of America, tapping into a deep realist vein instilled in the American polity by the Federalists, and evolving symbiotically with the new internationalism of American postwar foreign policy, this tempered realpolitik thrived. Morgenthau became the doyen of realists. It was he, explains John Vasquez, who best “expressed, promulgated and synthesized” the approach, becoming the “single most important vehicle for establishing the dominance of the realist paradigm within the field” (quoted in Ferguson and Mansbach 1988:97–8). Scientific Man vs. Power Politics Morgenthau’s influence on international relations originated with his treatise on political philosophy and method, Scientific Man vs. Power Politics (1946). The book was emphatically at odds with the surging tide of behavioral social science. Begun late in the summer of 1940, a time when Morgenthau recalls being shaken by the fall of France, it stands alongside Oakeshott’s “Rationalism in Politics” (1962) as one of the great dissents against the scientific-rationalist framework for political theory and practice. Echoing Carr’s critique of scientific utopianism, Morgenthau argued that the rationalist approach had embraced the Enlightenment belief in the power of science, and tried to make it into an instrument of social redemption. Political history was thus transformed into a succession of problems amenable to scientific solutions. On the international front, it was assumed that the problem of war would yield to refinements in international organization, legal rules, and economic union. Morgenthau contended that this “dogmatic scientism” in political planning and prediction was wrong-headed. “The principles of scientific reason are always simple, consistent, and abstract; the social world is always complicated, incongruous, and concrete.” Politics was an art and not a science. Sound governance required “not the rationality of the engineer but the wisdom and moral strength of the statesman” (p. 10). Morgenthau insisted that a realistic political philosophy must reject the canons of science, and adopt instead the quite different proposition that all politics were power politics. He argued that human nature was multifaceted, yet that one element, the animus dominandi, or lust for power, predominated in politics. “Power politics, rooted in the lust for power which is common to all men [is] inseparable from social life itself,” he contended (p. 9). At core, political acts were always aimed at keeping, increasing, or demonstrating power. The lust for power could be constrained and controlled, but never eliminated from politics. Morgenthau
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 61
considered it folly to view the struggle for power, as “democratic peace” proponents did, as a phase coinciding with autocratic government, which was bound to wither away with the democratization of foreign policy. War was neither an historical accident nor an “aristocratic pastime or totalitarian atavism,” but was a recurrent human tragedy (p. 47). He believed that nations were peace-loving under certain external conditions and warlike under others, and hence was skeptical of the Kantian position, but also of a number of historical interpretations claiming that monarchy was the most peaceful form of government (pp. 65–7). Nor could war be vanquished Leviathan-style by subordinating political action to a central authority or a general body of law. Woodrow Wilson, the realists’ barn side of a target, had told Congress in 1917, “We are at the beginning of an age in which it will be insisted that the same standards of conduct and of responsibility for wrong done shall be observed among nations and their governments that are observed among the individual citizens of civilized states” (pp. 43–4). Morgenthau considered this the “soothing logic of a specious concord” (p. 203). Morgenthau produced as evidence of the bankruptcy of scientific rationalism a litany of simplistic and shortsighted blueprints for international peace that had “failed to stand the trial of history” (p. 39). Coming in for criticism are the Abbé de Saint-Pierre’s Project for Perpetual Peace in Europe (1713–17); other philosophes and physiocrats; Kant and Comte; Marxist formula followers; free-trading liberals; socialengineering positivists; inter-war idealists; French planners; Wilsonian promoters of the Treaty of Versailles and the League of Nations; advocates of a benign Leviathan “coordinate state”; perfectionists, moralists, and every other stripe of internationalist, uninitiated in the “obstinate realities” of the international scene. All of these schemes, according to Morgenthau, suffered from historical myopia. Each “deduced from the limited experience of a certain age universal laws which were found wanting when applied to conditions different from those under which they were originally developed” (p. 85). He warned that such historical naïveté courted catastrophe in an anarchic world, the inevitable analogy in 1946 being the failure of the liberal democracies to recognize the problem of power and ally against Hitler before it was too late. Curiously, in the midst of Scientific Man’s assault on applied political science, Morgenthau was signaling the way toward a rational science of international politics. He was careful to maintain that beneath the chaos and contingency of history there were certain perennial forces that shaped social life. These, he said, were “the general causes of which particular events are but the outward manifestations” (p. v). Morgenthau recognized, however, that social science was not a detached and omniscient enterprise, but was largely socially constructed and conditioned. Hence, “the historic relativity of all political philosophy” (p. 20). Abstract reason was a mirage. “In the social sciences, the social conditions determine not only the ulterior purpose but also the object of inquiry, the investigator’s relation to it, his assumptions, methods, and immediate aims” (p. 162). Developments in science were “carried by the irrational forces of interest and emotion to where those forces want it to move” (p. 155). Moreover, social engineers
62 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
failed to grasp that political values were beyond the reach of science. Whoever believed that science alone could reveal the mysteries of politics was the “true dogmatist who universalizes cognitive principles of limited validity and applies them to realms not accessible to them” (p. 220). This sphere of Morgenthau’s thought had more in common with the sociology of knowledge we saw in Mannheim and Carr than it has with present-day “scientific realists.” “Rational reconstructions” of the paradigm wrongly regard Morgenthau’s work as a crude prototype, whose scientific shortcomings have been bred out over the decades (see, for example, Tellis 1995). Politics Among Nations Morgenthau made his theory explicit in the landmark work, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, first published in 1948. Downplaying the contingency and social construction of Scientific Man, the great text very nearly founded the scientific study of international relations in the United States. Whereas the field had traditionally centered on institutions, norms, current events, and diplomatic history, Morgenthau formulated a nomothetic, or law-based, approach to political understanding and action. His method, like Plato’s, was architectonic, building outward from a conception of human nature to the character of the state, the nature of the international system, and the necessary tasks of statecraft. The design was positivist in that it sought, within limits, to detect “those elemental biopsychological drives” of society “that determine political relations among nations and to comprehend the ways in which those forces act upon each other and upon international political relations and institutions” (pp. 39, 18). The volume is rich in historical allusion, yet, as Michael Joseph Smith (1986:141) points out, “the main message of the book is that the crucial features of the international landscape have remained remarkably constant over history.” Tolstoy, Thucydides, and the Dead Sea Scrolls all attest to the ubiquity of the struggle for power. Politics Among Nations was intended as a guidebook for the student and the statesman alike. What Niebuhr had said in 1932 was more appropriate than ever in the immediate postwar years: “The political situation and problem of America in world affairs can be put in one sentence: America is at once the most powerful and politically the most ignorant of modern nations” (quoted in Rosenthal 1991: 38). The period found US leaders sitting atop a new world order and casting about for principles of understanding and action. Morgenthau’s book furnished both. It offered a framework for aligning America’s great power status with a great power foreign policy. Although Keynes once noted that every policy initiative had its origins in the scribblings of some academic, it is impossible to trace with certainty the intellectual promptings of particular policies. Morgenthau’s ideas, expressed in his books, in a flood of essays in outlets from Encounter and Commentary to The New Leader and The New York Review of Books, and in many public forums (it is said he never turned down an invitation to lecture), helped set the tone, though not always the content, of American statecraft. At the same time, Morgenthau
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 63
sought to make realism a public philosophy. He considered this a crucial task in a democracy, which, as de Tocqueville observed, may be the worst form of government when it came to conducting foreign relations. Particularly in the United States, the constitutional separation of powers, partisan politics, regional differences, and the various international affinities and affections of a nation of immigrants, could fuel a cacophonous foreign policy. Morgenthau, like all the realists, believed in the adage that politics should end at the water’s edge. The thesis of Politics Among Nations was readily accessible. Morgenthau’s bedrock belief, though not stated explicitly in the book’s first edition, was that politics were governed by “objective laws that have their roots in human nature” (p. 4). It was possible, therefore, to develop a rational theory of politics that reflected those laws. Again, the lust for power, “universal in time and space,” was his focus (p. 38). As he later explained, the concept provided “a kind of rational outline of politics, a map of the political scene. Such a map does not provide a complete description of the political landscape as it is in a particular period of history. It rather provides the timeless features of its geography distinct from their ever changing historic setting” (Morgenthau 1962a:48). The power motive was more than a theoretical prop. Morgenthau also considered it the constitutive principle of politics as a distinct sphere of human activity. By definition, all politics were power politics. International behavior that hinged on another variable was walled off from the political realm. Economic, cultural, or environmental concerns, for example, were not “political” relations inasmuch as they did not involve power. The boundaries of politics and power thus coincided neatly—probably too neatly. We shall see in Chapter 6 how difficult it is to sever the subtle bonds between political power and other state and societal functions. Morgenthau’s view of power was noteworthy for its catholicity, however. By power, he referred not to brute force or political violence, but to the psychological leverage of “man’s control over the minds and actions of other men” (p. 32). Those weary of material-realist recitals of tanks, warheads, and men at arms will appreciate Morgenthau’s inclusion of geography, industry, natural resources, including “the power of oil,” military preparedness, population, national morale and character, effective institutions, and diplomatic competence. These myriad forms of power, complicated by “all the contingencies of history and nature” ensured that evaluating national power would always be an imperfect art (pp. 172–4). Morgenthau married this belief in the ubiquity of power to the pursuit of state interests. The result was his famous formulation of “interest defined in terms of power.” Here was an organizing principle for a discipline adrift: We assume that statesmen think and act in terms of interest defined as power, and the evidence of history bears that assumption out. That assumption allows us to retrace and anticipate, as it were, the steps a statesman—past, present, or future—has taken or will take on the political scene. We look over his shoulder when he writes his dispatches; we listen in on his conversation with other statesmen; we read and anticipate his very thoughts. Thinking in
64 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
terms of interest defined as power, we think as he does, and as disinterested observers we understand his thoughts and actions perhaps better than he, the actor on the political scene, does himself. (p. 5) Following these guideposts of power and interests, researchers would not be misled by professed motivations or purported ideological preferences. Hypocrisy between diplomatic thought and practice was the rule. Morgenthau regarded ideas and ideology as “pretexts and false fronts behind which the element of power, inherent in all politics, can be concealed” (p. 103). Ideology was a palliative that rendered involvement in power politics psychologically and morally acceptable to leaders and their constituents. Morgenthau encouraged students of politics to be skeptical of the “official” rationale for diplomatic decisions, but also to distrust the rationale that the diplomat himself believed he was fulfilling. Unswerving research would sever the knot of ideology, and assign causes to political acts based on realist assumptions. This was the essence of Morgenthau’s “empirical” method: skeptical toward science as a means of social salvation, yet supportive of a modest science of realism. One caveat before we move on to Morgenthau’s views on the relationship between history and theory: although Morgenthau subscribed to a bleak view of history and human nature, it would be wrong to depict him as international relations’ dark prince. Describing politics in the hard-boiled terms of power and interests was not equivalent to approving of this condition. As Georg Schwarzenberger (1951:3) observed, “It may be ‘Machiavellian’ to indulge in power politics but it would be too much honour to describe in such terms scientists whose questionable privilege it is to analyse such relations. As a type they are not sufficiently demoniac to warrant the description of professors of international immorality.” Realists believe that recognizing the role of power is the first step toward addressing the problem of war. Likewise, setting the national interest as a normative standard is not an invitation to excess. Realists believe that there are limits to interests, and that this renders the principle a source of moderation and restraint. History and theory Morgenthau’s approach was deeply “grounded in history.” He insisted that political argument and understanding conform to “the historical processes as they actually take place,” he hewed to a Burkean predominance of historical precedent over abstract principle, and he adduced abundant historical evidence in support of his positions (Morgenthau 1985:4). As was mentioned earlier, Morgenthau also adopted a nomothetic outlook on history. He contended that “objective laws” or the “static essence” of politics could be sifted from the chaos of historical contingencies.
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 65
On this last point, Morgenthau’s method broke with previous approaches to the study of international politics. As we have seen, earlier theorists focused more on the storminess and unpredictability of the international sphere, and less on the laws that might govern state behavior under these conditions. Morgenthau formalized his predecessors’ attention to human nature, making it into the linchpin of realist science. He argued (ibid.: 20) that “the events [political analysts] must try to understand are, on the one hand, unique occurrences. They happened in this way only once and never before or since. On the other hand, they are similar, for they are manifestations of social forces. Social forces are the product of human nature in action.” He also believed that history revealed a repetitiveness and constancy in certain “rational” political choices that made politics susceptible to theoretical analysis—although he conceded that the persistence of “irrational” behavior worked against the elaboration of theory. Morgenthau’s method entailed two steps. The first was inductive and intuitive, involving philosophical thought on history and human nature. Although derived by way of historical reflection, this insight, once attained, was supra-historical: it tapped into a “store of objective, general truths” that transcended time and space (Morgenthau 1962a: 45). Whereas the natural scientist discovered laws through observed uniformities in nature, discerning social laws required a leap from history to philosophy. The result was knowledge, not of “single facts but of the eternal laws by which man moves in the social world.” As Morgenthau (1946:219–20) put it, “The Aristotelian truth that man is a political animal is true forever; the truths of the natural sciences are true only until other truths have supplanted them.” Reflecting on the perennial problems of government, “more-than-scientific man” became “the representative of true reason,” the “true realist” who “does justice to the true nature of things.” Obversely, a defective philosophy imposed a false logic on history. Morgenthau believed this had been the case with the rational-scientists, whom history had provided with “false analogies but had taught…nothing.” Rationalists misconstrued history as a struggle between reason and unreason, and detected in the historical record only “confirmation of, or a deviation from, the rational scheme with which they approach the political reality.” “What Carl L.Becker has said of the eighteenth-century philosophers is true of their nineteenth- and twentiethcentury heirs: ‘The eighteenth-century Philosophers, like the medieval scholastics, held fast to a revealed body of knowledge, and they were unwilling and unable to learn anything from history which could not…be reconciled with their faith” (ibid.: 37–8). The second step of Morgenthau’s approach involved deduction and empirical testing, as philosophical propositions were plunged back into history. It was this experimentation with “rational hypotheses” which gave “theoretical meaning to the facts of international politics,” and made the scientific writing of political history possible (Morgenthau 1985:5). Again, value-free political inquiry was a phantom. Empirical claims stemmed from general principles—often unacknowledged—about humanity and society. Hence, Morgenthau sought to combine philosophy and
66 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
science into a coherent understanding of politics. He argued that due to an academic rift, particularly deep in the United States, between philosophy and science, political philosophy had grown sterile and irrelevant to the issues of the day; political science, severed from the history of political thought, had grown intellectually starved. The political philosophers he most admired—Aristotle, Kautilya, Hobbes, Machiavelli, Weber, perhaps Nietzsche—were also, in Morgenthau’s estimation, great political scientists, who “deriv[ed] concrete, empirically verifiable propositions from abstract philosophical ones” (Morgenthau 1962a:41). Thus, an amalgam of science and philosophy carried Morgenthau from history to theory and back into history. At the same time, Morgenthau believed that the uncertainties of history signaled the limits of political science. Although the purpose of political science was to understand politics in a theoretical manner, this was an inherently tentative enterprise. Political science could “indicate certain trends and…state the possible conditions under which one of those trends is most likely to materialize in the future.” It could go no further without “losing itself in unscientific speculation” (Morgenthau 1946: 134–7). Here the scholar and the charlatan parted ways. It was in this context that he claimed (1967:211) that modern theorists and researchers in international relations were “repelled by history; for history is the realm of the accidental, the contingent, the unpredictable.” History, which had embodied the ambiguities of situations and actors, had been replaced by historical “data.” Quantitative researchers, systems analysts, and other sophisticated research strategists went about scaling the peaks of science without looking to see how solid the rock was in which they were planting their pitons. This conceit of method left modern theorists with no historical sense of the uncertainties of politics and the intractability of the human condition. This kind of bald empiricism was also profoundly anti-theoretical. Again, Morgenthau believed that theory stood apart from history; it transcended mere facts to capture timeless features of the social landscape. In history too, Morgenthau believed that a divide between theory and fact was untenable. History, he said, echoing Seeley, was “philosophy learned from examples” (Morgenthau 1962a:328). Great historical narratives sought out the nexus between individual events and perennial human concerns. Thucydides and Ranke, for instance, were deeply philosophical historians, for whom theory was “like the skeleton which, invisible to the naked eye, gives form and function to the body” (ibid.: 65). Morgenthau also commended Arnold Toynbee’s work as an antidote to the “unproblematic poverty of scientific historiography,” and claimed that the English historian had “awakened the historic imagination from its dogmatic slumber,” and had reached a plane of comprehension “beyond the ken of empirical verification.” At this high level, Morgenthau considered the difference between history and international relations as one of form rather than substance. According to Morgenthau (1962b:55–6), the historian “presents his theory in the form of a historical recital using the chronological sequence to events as demonstration of his theory. The theoretician, dispensing with the historical recital, makes the theory explicit and uses historic facts in bits and pieces to demonstrate his theory.”
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 67
Policy history This is essentially how Morgenthau used history. He did not refer theory to the historical record in a rigorous way, through either formal case studies or large n analyses. He was skeptical that worthwhile quantitative work, at least, was possible. Rather, he carefully selected historical vignettes that illustrated realist principles: The League of Nations’ niggling retort to the Soviet invasion of Finland in 1939 showed the futility of legalism; Richard Cobden’s Victorian speeches brought home the folly of commercial liberalism; the protracted “great game” between Britain and Russia for control of Central Asia demonstrated the competitive balance of power; quibbling about the design of the negotiating table at the Paris peace talks on Vietnam illustrated the policy of prestige; Japan’s euphemistic Asian “co-prosperity zone” exemplified the ideology of imperialism. On larger policy questions, Morgenthau developed more elaborate historical reference. Consider his approach to two issues in American foreign policy: the war in Vietnam and US foreign aid. Morgenthau argued that the Vietnam debate was typical of a revolutionary age: How should a country respond to a hostile political movement that transcended national boundaries? What bearing did a universal political creed have on national interests? How to deal with revolutions that might be hijacked by true believers? Morgenthau (1965:20) noted that “twice before in modern history, these questions had to be answered.” First, there was the example of Britain’s posture toward Revolutionary France, a great power which, like the Soviet Union, seemed to be the fountainhead of a worldwide political religion. Morgenthau broached possible diplomatic avenues by sketching out the debate among Edmund Burke, Charles James Fox, and William Pitt, then British Prime Minister. Fox, apparently, had argued that England was not threatened by France, or, for that matter, by the principles the Revolution espoused. Burke held, conversely, that the Revolution subverted the very “order of things, under which our part of the world has so long flourished…We are at war with a principle…of which there is no shutting out by fortresses or excluding by territorial limits. No lines of demarcation can bound the Jacobin empire. It must be extirpated in the place of its origin, or it will not be confined to that place” (ibid.: 20). It was left to Pitt to apply the standard of the national interest. What was at stake, said the Prime Minister, was “security—security against a danger, the greatest that ever threatened the world—security against a danger which never existed in any past period of society…We saw that it was to be resisted no less by arms abroad, than by precaution at home; that we were to look for protection no less to the courage of our forces than to the wisdom of our councils; no less to military effort than to legislative enactment” (ibid.: 20). Morgenthau’s second precedent for Vietnam was British Foreign Minister Castlereagh’s discriminating diplomacy in the 1820s. At the time, the absolute monarchs of Europe were terrified of the various liberal and nationalist movements afoot on the continent. Russia, in particular, seemed to be using antagonism toward liberalism in order to mask its own imperial ambitions. Amid this aristocratic
68 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
hysteria, Castlereagh was the picture of restraint. He opposed Russian expansion, but refused to identify liberalism per se as the enemy of Britain. As he reportedly admonished the Russian ambassador in 1820, “It is proposed now to overcome the revolution; but so long as this revolution does not appear in more distinct shape, so long as this general principle is only translated into events like those of Spain, Naples and Portugal —which, strictly speaking, are only reforms, or at the most domestic upsets, and do not attack materially any other State—England is not ready to combat it” (ibid.: 21). At the same time Castlereagh wrote to his brother: “It is not possible for the British Government to take the field in fruitlessly denouncing by a sweeping joint declaration the revolutionary dangers of the present day.” British leaders could “not regard mere declarations as of any real or solid value independent of some practical measure actually resolved upon; and what that measure is which can be generally and universally adopted against bad principles overturning feeble and ill-administered governments, they have never yet been able to divine” (ibid.: 21). Strategic choices were to be driven by interests and considered in context. On foreign aid, Morgenthau argued that behind the label of “economic development” was a process in the nature of the time-honored practice of political bribery. The main difference was that the “elaborate machinery” of government aid —legions of economists and development experts—was less effective than oldfashioned diplomats in achieving political goals. Recognizing this, states should adopt a more rational scheme of apportioning aid. Morgenthau noted that in the past it had been “proper and common” for governments to pay a pension—a bribe —to foreign ministers and ambassadors from other countries. Sir Henry Wooten, Britain’s eminent ambassador to Venice in the seventeenth century, received such a tribute. The Elizabethan representative to Madrid, Lord Robert Cecil, secured a pension from the Spanish court. In the decades before the Revolution, French officials had plied Austrian statesmen with lavish subsidies. Diplomats were also paid for their cooperation in concluding treaties. At the signing of the Treaty of Basel of 1795, by virtue of which Prussia agreed to withdraw from the war against France, the French government gave 30,000 francs to Prussian Minister Hardenberg, who complained of the meagerness of the sum. In 1801, the Margrave of Baden earmarked 500,000 francs for “diplomatic presents,” of which French Foreign Minister Talleyrand received 150,000. Morgenthau reported that “it was originally intended to give him only 100,000, but the amount was increased after it had become known that he had received from Prussia a snuffbox worth 66,000 francs as well as 100,000 francs in cash” (Morgenthau 1962b: 256–7). The point was that what appeared to modern eyes as scandal and graft, in fact represented what had traditionally been a forthright way of securing political advantage. These are examples of policy history: a way of illustrating historically the principles and direction of statecraft. The method is more prudential than empirical. “What happened” was less critical than the “moral” or “lesson” derived from events, which was generally at the expense of the historical process, and often devoid of actual policy content. The moral on Vietnam was that interests were not
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 69
infinite. Statesmen should not drag crusades into the political realm, where interests should predominate. Having made this point, whether or not the cases chosen were analogous to Vietnam was not, in the end, terribly significant. The lesson on foreign aid had to do with the primacy of politics. International aid should be part of a coherent foreign policy firmly under political control. Morgenthau’s “pristine” examples of political money helped cut through the tangle of ideology to reveal the political nature of foreign aid. That past statesmen may have placed personal interests ahead of national ones, or that the documents on French subsidies to Austria were released by the revolutionary council as evidence of the corruption of the ancien régime, was, again, of marginal importance. The method is very effective. Analogies are clearly stated, doubts are dispelled, and the logic advanced seems inescapable. Yet, for all its richness, the approach is selective and anecdotal, apparently driven by the realist world view. Although Morgenthau is generally considered an inductivist, in these instances the principles precede the history. Rather than plunging theory into history, this is more a case of using history to confirm propositions that have already been established philosophically. The principles being argued might be sound, but it is debatable how “scientific” they are. At the first, intuitive, step of Morgenthau’s method, understandably no historical protocols or “rules of evidence” are offered; but none is posed at the “empirical” stage either. Without knowing if the cases are representative, one cannot uphold in any rigorous way the general validity of the theory. To Morgenthau, this line of criticism would presume more certainty than social science can provide. As Aristotle said, any inquiry could only be as precise as the subject matter allowed. Throughout his work, starting with the disclaimers of Scientific Man, Morgenthau maintained that there were no absolutes in politics. Hence, his “modest expectations of a circumspect theory” (Morgenthau 1966:65). This skepticism did not, however, deter him from making strong historical claims: that “no nation has ever been completely immune” from “that iron law of international politics, that legal obligations must yield to the national interest” (Morgenthau 1951:144); that attempts to avert war through collective action, disarmament, or institutions were “doomed to failure”; that misjudging national power was the definitive reason that states declined. Morgenthau’s strongest “historical” arguments were more axiomatic than empirical. The principles invoked may reside, with Toynbee’s ideas, beyond the ken of empirical verification. This begs a crucial question for classical realists: how does one translate historical “wisdom”—which surely exists; there is a difference in historical awareness between the statesman and the public administrator—into defensible political understanding and action? We take up this question now in regard to the balance of power, and below, in our discussion of George Kennan’s historical approach to containment.
70 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
History and the balance of power Realists view the balance of power as one of the mainsprings of international politics. International laws and norms are important, but the balance of power is the surest curb on the untrammeled exercise of state power. Indeed, the balance makes possible the existence of a diverse community of states. Perhaps inevitably, realists projected this image back into history, emphasizing events that demonstrated the balance and privileging early advocates of the approach. Although the balance of power idea enjoys wide currency, its meaning and significance have been bandied about for three centuries. The anonymous author of Europe’s Catechism (1741) called the balance “an equal Distribution of Power among the Princes of Europe, as makes it impractical for the one to disturb the Repose of the other” (quoted in Sheehan 1996:2). Burke was ambivalent toward the practice. He believed strongly that it preserved the independence of weak nations, yet he also believed that balance of power policies and the web of alliances they produced in fact spread conflict. The strategy, he wrote, had “been the original of innumerable and fruitless wars… The foreign ambassadors constantly residing in all courts, the negotiations incessantly carrying on, spread both confederacies and quarrels so wide, that whenever hostilities commence, the theater of war is always of a prodigious extent” (quoted in Ferguson and Mansbach 1988:193). G.Lowes Dickenson, a promoter of the League of Nations, contended in The International Anarchy (1926) that no strategy had been more perilous, for “all history shows every balance has ended in war” (quoted in Smith 1986:58). Butterfield (1966:133) notes that “more than most of our basic political formulas, this one seems to come from the modern world’s reflections on its own experience.” George Liska pointed to a “misplaced desire for precision in a concept that is at once the dominant myth and the fundamental law of interstate relations” (quoted in Sheehan 1996:2). M.S.Anderson suggests that this slippery concept has too often served as a “substitute for thought” (quoted in Schroeder 1994b: 6). The historian A.F.Pollard summed up this conceptual riot: “Like ‘liberty,’ ‘independence,’ and ‘the freedom of the seas’ or of the straits, the balance of power may mean almost anything; and it is used not only in different senses by different people, or in different senses by the same people at different times, but in different senses by the same person at the same time” (quoted in Gulick 1967: v). Morgenthau went a long way toward clearing up this confusion. He conceived of the balance in two main ways. First, he saw it as “a universal social phenomenon” signifying “stability within a system composed of a number of autonomous forces” (Morgenthau 1985:188). In international politics, the balance acted as “arbiter” of the two “basic patterns” of conduct—that of “status quo” states interested in preserving the existing distribution of power, and that of “imperialist” states interested in its revision or overthrow. If one assumed that states were concerned with their power positions relative to other states, it was reasonable to expect that efforts to keep pace with, or even outstrip, their competitors would ensue. Morgenthau carried this logic a step further. Whereas Niebuhr had viewed the
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 71
balance as a deliberate human construct, Morgenthau saw it as “inevitable” and “mechanistic.” “The aspiration for power on the part of several nations, each trying either to maintain or overthrow the status-quo, leads of necessity to a configuration that is called the balance of power and to policies that aim at preserving it.” The balance conveyed the force of nature. Morgenthau pointed to parallels in the “automatic stabilizing processes” of the human body and the “social homeostasis” of society, and extended these analogies to the international sphere (ibid.: 187, 190). Second, the balance provided a normative framework for political order. It was a device for preserving the system and the diverse elements it comprised. One of the earliest normative expressions of the balance of power, the Preamble to the Treaty of Utrecht of 1713, which concluded the War of the Spanish Succession, adopted an almost idealistic tone, noting that “a just Balance of Power…is the best and most solid foundation of mutual friendship and a lasting general concord” (quoted in Sheehan 1996:16). For Morgenthau the virtues of the practice lay more in the independent liberties it secured. Save for the balance, he argued, “one element will gain ascendancy over the others, encroach upon their interests and rights, and may ultimately destroy them” (Morgenthau 1985:189). Morgenthau found a robust model in Federalist 51, one of the essays written by Alexander Hamilton, John Jay, and James Madison and published pseudonymously in 1787 and 1788. Federalist 51 argued that “inventions of prudence” must be fashioned to check and balance power: This policy of supplying, by opposite and rival interests, the defect of better motives, might be traced to the whole system of human affairs, private as well as public. We see it particularly displayed in all the subordinate distributions of power, where the constant aim is to divide and arrange the several offices in such a manner as that each may be a check on the other— that the private interests of every individual may be a sentinel over the public rights. These inventions of prudence cannot be less requisite in the distribution of the supreme powers of the state. (ibid.: 189) In a domestic setting, such as that envisioned by the Federalists, the need for the balance was ameliorated by shared interests, common values, and, most of all, the central authority of the state. The international sphere, where norms were erratic and overarching authority nonexistent, relied more starkly on the balance for political order. The balance of power, then, was both a species of “natural history” and a diplomatic institution, a fact as well as a norm. Morgenthau envisioned two ideal types of international balance: direct opposition (bipolarity), and competitive equilibrium (multipolarity). Historically, these configurations had comprised interrelated sub-systems as well: in Central and Eastern Europe, Italy, the Balkans, Korea, the Southern Cone of Latin America, and elsewhere according to the period. The “balance” was, in fact, dynamic. As British Foreign Minister George Canning
72 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
had implied, “Is [the balance of power] not a standard perpetually varying, as civilization advances, and as new nations spring up, and take their place among established political communities?” (ibid.: 210–11). As the expansion of the international system quickened in the nineteenth century, the “main weights” of the balance migrated to the periphery. The Monroe Doctrine reproduced old-world rivalries in the new. Colonialism extended the system to Africa, Asia, and the Middle East. By 1914, virtually no region of the world was untouched by the “European” balance. For the first time in history, the stage was set for world war. Amid the flux of the system and the regional rivalries it contained, the balance dictated continuous interventions and adjustments. Here the many faces of power gave way to more material ones, as balancing entailed territorial compensations (whose “tidy mechanics” Edward Vose Gulick (1967:251) called “quid pro quo with a measuring cup”), the partition of states (as in the Polish case), arms build-ups (almost never disarmament), and the formation of alliances. Particular responsibility fell to the “holder of the balance”—usually Britain acting from its position of “splendid isolation”—to form and change alliances and alignments as the balance required. Alternative explanations Balance-of-power theory has largely coincided with balance-of-power historiography, particularly in regard to the European and Anglo-American experience. The medievalist historian William Stubbs suggested in 1886 that the balance was “the principle which gives unity to the political plot of European history” (quoted in Sheehan 1996:169). A century earlier, Burke had extended this logic outward. He observed that “If Europe does not conceive the independence and the equilibrium of the empire to be in the very essence of the system of balance of power in Europe…all the politics of Europe for more than two centuries have been miserably erroneous” (quoted in Morgenthau 1985:220). A formidable historical school has grown up around the idea of the balance of power, including Thucydides, Giovanni Rucellai, Francesco Guicciardini, François Fénelon, Ranke, Edward Gibbon, AlbrechtCarrié, Ludwig Dehio, A.J.P.Taylor, Winston Churchill, Gulick, and many others. Paul Schroeder, however, has been a powerful revisionist in this regard. His work deserves special mention. Schroeder claims that he cannot construct a history of Europe from 1648 to 1945 around the principle Stubbs had proclaimed. Looking at the French Revolutionary and Napoleonic Wars, the Crimean War, the First World War, and the Second World War, Schroeder finds that most states (great and small) when faced with crucial threats to their security and independence, responded in other (less costly and less provocative) ways. These included bandwagoning (i.e., choosing to join “the stronger side for sake of protection and payoffs, even if this meant insecurity vis-à-vis the protecting power and a certain sacrifice of independence”), a practice “historically more common than balancing”; hiding from and ignoring threats; declaring neutrality or adopting a defensive posture;
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 73
and attempting to transcend conflict through some institutional arrangement (Schroeder 1994a: 116–18; see also Sheehan 1996:162–7). Consider Schroeder’s views on the Napoleonic Wars and the Second World War. He asserts that during the Napoleonic struggles “every major power in Europe except Great Britain—Prussia, Austria, Russia, Spain— bandwagoned as France’s active ally for a considerable period. Wars continued to break out mainly not because European states tried to balance against France as a hegemonic power, but because Napoleon’s ambition and lawless conduct frustrated their repeated efforts to hide or bandwagon” (Schroeder 1994a: 121). Not until Napoleon’s signal defeat at Leipzig in October 1813 did his coalition break up, with smaller states flocking —bandwagoning—to the winning allied side. The pattern reemerged during the Second World War, as Germany’s mounting power and militarism prompted extensive hiding and bandwagoning across the continent. Belgium, Holland, Denmark, and Norway chose neutrality, while at Munich, Chamberlain and Daladier attempted a partnership for peace with Germany. Existing alliances that might have checked Hitler collapsed rather than solidified. The FrenchCzechRussian compact had ceased to exist at Munich, and the Little Entente of Czechoslovakia, Romania, and Yugoslavia was moot by 1935, when Yugoslavia began colluding with Germany. Mussolini allied with Hitler in May 1939, and Molotov and Ribbentrop affirmed their unholy pact that August. During the course of the war, Hungary, Romania, Bulgaria, and Vichy France “sided” with Hitler. Neutral Sweden, Turkey, Switzerland, Spain, and Argentina leaned toward Germany as long as the war appeared to be going Berlin’s way. In a study of nineteenth-century Europe, Schroeder (1989) notes that the idea of the balance of power seems “indispensable” in making sense of the Congress system, yet he contends that such a balance was a rare bird in the diplomatic language (and presumably thought) of the period. Statesmen were more given to explain and justify policies in terms of preserving peace, observing treaties and legal rights, upholding the social order, thwarting revolution, and satisfying national interests, honor, or popular opinion. More importantly, Schroeder finds that this distinction holds for diplomatic practice as well. The Congress countered threats not by forming “blocking coalitions,” as a means of balancing power or threats, but by attempting to incorporate the renegade state into a restraining alliance or partnership. He calls this arrangement “political equilibrium”: political equilibrium required that (1) the rights, influence and vital interests claimed by individual states in the international system be somehow balanced against the rights, influence and vital interests claimed by other states and the general community, and (2) that a balance or harmony exist between the goals pursued by individual states, the requirements of the system, and the means used to promote one’s interests. Oversimplified, political equilibrium meant a balance of satisfactions, a balance of rights and obligations and a balance of performance and payoffs, rather than a balance of power. (ibid.: 143)
74 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Schroeder concludes that the statecraft undergirding Europe’s nineteenth-century repose meshes better with an explanation based on norms, laws, and interests than on a competitive balance of power. Indeed, he infers that “pure balance of power politics destroys political equilibrium rather than sustains it” (ibid.: 135). He argues that in the decade before 1914, the equilibrium was supplanted by a resurgent competitive balance, which, especially by undermining the legitimacy of Austria, set the stage for the conflagration that followed. The fact that this is contested historiographic ground does not invalidate balanceof-power theory. Bandwagoning, hiding, transcending, and equilibrium are, in effect, competing concepts with which to explain state strategies. We will see in the next chapter that bandwagoning is generally associated with weak states. A distinction between short- and long-term outcomes would perhaps be illuminating as well. Schroeder’s illustrations do suggest that in significant instances there were a number of “rational” choices open to states —indeed, there were evidently times when national interests were defined in ways that clashed with the balance of power. The balance is perhaps a more ambivalent concept than many realists allow. Schroeder hews to a more legalistic or associative view of state practices than most realists do. However, fixity on realist theory can also close off harder-bitten interpretations of history. As one student of Clausewitz notes, “The century 1815– 1914 is conveniently …pictured as a century of comparative peace, stability, and progress in Europe. Another way of seeing it, grimmer but per-haps more instructive, is as an incubation period” (Anatol Rappoport in Clausewitz 1968:27). Despite Morgenthau’s focus on the balance as “the very law of life” of a system of independent states, he constantly conceded its failings: its historical unreality, its uncertainty, and its inadequacy as a moral benchmark (Morgenthau 1962a: 330). In its manifestations, the balance would only ever approximate its theoretical ideal. The imprecision of gauging power led states to seek not just a margin of safety, but an absolute superiority in power. States must actually aim not at a balance—that is, equality—of power, but at superiority of power in their own behalf…since no nation can foresee how large its miscalculations will turn out to be, all nations must ultimately seek the maximum of power obtainable under the circumstances… The limitless aspiration for power, potentially always present…in the power drives of nations, finds in the balance of power a mighty incentive to transform itself into an actuality. (Morgenthau 1985:227–8)
The security dilemma obtained even in a balanced system, with power racing rather than power balancing the rule. Policies aimed at maintaining the balance of power were the same policies that destabilized the balance and led to war. Morgenthau nevertheless insisted that the idea of the balance was sound: “The instability of the international balance of power is due not to the faultiness of the
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 75
principle but to the particular conditions under which the principle must operate in a society of sovereign nations” (ibid.: 187). The conditions that produced that idea were unique: eighteenth-century Europe. That era represented “the golden age of the balance of power in theory as well as in practice. It was during that period that most of the literature on the balance of power was published and that the princes of Europe looked to the balance of power as the supreme principle to guide their conduct in foreign affairs” (ibid.: 209). At the time, European politics were radically multipolar. Administratively, the continent was a patchwork of fiefdoms, duchies, and principalities, with hundreds of sovereign “states” in Germany alone. At the time as well, realpolitik truly was the “sport of kings,” with rulers abandoning partners and embracing new ones with all the promiscuity of a masked ball. Back home, rulers were free to commit blood and treasure to the cause, unencumbered by domestic sentiment or, apparently, ethical concerns. When wars did occur, they issued, as Gibbon said, in “temperate and undecisive contests” (ibid.: 234). The result was a fluid international system marked by fickle loyalties, constant intrigue, and endless permutations of force. Morgenthau contended that this blend of power and suspicion constrained international actors. Since risks were so difficult to calculate, states tended to be intensely risk averse, thus checking their own ambitions and preserving the system. Like the chaos of Adam Smith’s competitive capitalism from which order nevertheless emerged, here, too, swirling uncertainties gave rise to a sort of order. (We will see in the next chapter that neorealists take the opposite view, that the fewer the centers of power, the more stable the system.) These conditions have receded ever since. The international system transformed itself into what Morgenthau called the “new” balance of power. The number of influential actors shrank from hundreds in the eighteenth century to scores in the nineteenth, to less than a dozen at the outbreak of the First World War, to two at the end of the Second World War. Militarism and propaganda overran the idea of the balance. Nationalism became a driving force in politics. Entire populations and economies were mobilized for war, bent on total victory. The magnitude of US and Soviet power stripped Britain of its traditional balancing role. The “empty spaces” of Asia and Africa, where the great powers had vented their lusts without destroying the European core, became sovereign states. Eventually the “flexibility and uncertainty” of the earlier balance gave way to the grinding impact of the cold war, of “two giants eyeing each other with watchful suspicion” (ibid.: 379). For Morgenthau, this mix of structure and ideology poisoned the rational conduct of foreign policy. At times, Morgenthau was a fervent cold warrior. He believed that the United States consistently underestimated Russian power and, on the heels of the Soviet Union’s successful atomic tests in 1949, he urged the country to embark, with “frantic speed,” on a crash program of rearmament as a “matter not of political necessity but of national survival” (quoted in Smith 1986:150, 153). More often, though, Morgenthau was a cold war critic. His detached analysis and skepticism of ideology led him to a more circumspect view of Soviet intentions than we saw, for example, with Niebuhr. He condemned the doctrinal mindset of American strategists, and their inability to discriminate among interests abroad.
76 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Echoing Burke, he decried the fettering network of alliances that American “pactomania” had wrought. Nothing signaled the corruption of the balance of power as clearly as the war in Vietnam. Since the mid-1950s, Morgenthau had warned against military involvement in Indochina, and his growing frustration with American policies—holding fast to what he called “the doctrine of war without end” —is evident in his stream of essays as the war unfolded (1968).1 The Vietnam debacle even prompted Morgenthau, in the 1978 edition of Politics Among Nations, to consider the possibilities of a “pathological,” or “countertheory” of international relations centered on irrational choices. Romanticizing international society Perhaps the greatest differences between the old and new balance of power lay in the concept’s normative underpinnings. Politics Among Nations can be read as a long lament for the demise of “international society,” by which Morgenthau meant that system of aristocratic mores that had governed the great dance of European diplomacy. In Morgenthau’s stylized account of the era, the war of all against all was mediated by a set of rules. Elite values were cosmopolitan; diplomats shared a common language (French); they pursued a closely-held harmony of interests; and their masters were less hampered than their twentieth-century counterparts by domestic politics and plodding bureaucracies. Moreover, the legitimacy of power politics was unquestioned. Morgenthau’s attachment to this period of “moral and political unity of Europe” is extraordinary (Morgenthau 1985:236). It is a romantic notion of a historic Europe united in interests and anchored by the balance of power. Morgenthau cites the eighteenth-century legal theorist, Eméric Vattel: Europe forms a political system, a body where the whole is connected by the relations and different interests of nations inhabiting this part of the world. It is not as anciently a confused heap of detached pieces, each of which thought itself very little concerned in the fate of others, and seldom regarded things which did not immediately relate to it. The confined attention of sovereigns…makes Europe a kind of republic, the members of which, though independent, unite, through the ties of common interest, for the maintenance of order and liberty. (ibid.: 235) This is, of course, a markedly different view of politics than the billiard ball model Morgenthau depicts elsewhere in the book. In the European context at least, Morgenthau’s normative findings call into question his structural ones. He contended that the Westphalian system was premised not on “the balance of power, but…a number of elements, intellectual and moral in nature, upon which both the balance of power and the stability of the modern state system repose” (ibid.: 237). The balance was largely socially constructed. It reflected, Morgenthau noted, a “social system of international intercourse within which for almost three centuries
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 77
nations lived together in constant rivalry, yet under the common roof of shared values and universal standards of action” (ibid.: 359). Morgenthau argued that this idea of Europe prevailed from 1648 to 1772 and from 1815 to 1933, though its foundations eroded with the coming of the French Revolution, the upheavals of 1848, and the decline and collapse of the aristocratic internationale. Eventually, what Castlereagh had called “the general system of Europe” fragmented into its national parts, each raising its parochial norms to universal principles (ibid.: 236). One can argue on the strength of Morgenthau’s evidence that the balance of power, far from being a “natural” state of affairs, was an ideology or social construct flowing from the peculiar circumstances of European history. Morgenthau made clear that the normative and empirical premises of the balance no longer held. “That common ‘system of arts, and laws, and manners,’ ‘the same level of politeness and cultivation,’ and the ‘sense of honour and justice,’ which Gibbon had detected in ‘the general manners of the times’ and which for Fénelon, Rousseau, and Vatel were a lived and living reality, have today in the main become a historic reminiscence, lingering on in learned treatises, utopian tracts, and diplomatic documents, but no longer capable of moving men to action.” The supranational ethic underpinning the system had become “rather like the feeble rays, barely visible above the horizon of consciousness, of a sun which has already set” (ibid.: 273–4). As a working principle of international order, then, the balance seems remote from an international system where the preferred distribution of power has slipped away, along with its determining rules and the élan, for a time, of its practice. The advent of the nuclear age raised troubling moral and strategic questions about the balance. While it is sometimes asserted that realists were merely justifying the cold war, Morgenthau’s historical judgment, his affection for the aristocratic system, seems to have embodied a reaction against the horrendous dysfunctions of the balance of power in the twentieth century. From this standpoint, the machinations of an elite clan sharing values and struggling for power perhaps seemed appealing. Indeed, Morgenthau hoped that some of the practices of historic European diplomacy could be rejuvenated. He often argued that diplomacy should be taken out of parliamen-tary hands and removed from the public spotlight. Yet, even in terms of that sliver of experience known as power politics, the “golden age” of the balance was not always golden. The balance’s main reason for existence —preserving the independence and integrity of all its members, especially weak ones —was often violated. Under the rubric of the balance, Poland was partitioned (in 1772, 1793, and 1795) out of existence. Morgenthau deplored this most egregious abuse of the balance, but the system’s failings were more general. Small states were usually the first to be sacrificed. Gulick notes (1967:75–6) that while moderation was an important principle of the balance, it was hardly an absolute standard: “coalition wars cannot be called moderate, and the extinction of weak powers under the plea of balance of power surely cannot be termed moderate. The fear, suspicion, and rapid changes of policy…do not by any stretch of the imagination appear to have been moderate.” As for large states, Quincy Wright (1942:652–3) found that in the years 1650–1900, France, Austria, Great Britain, Russia, Prussia, Spain,
78 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Netherlands, Sweden, Denmark, Turkey, and Poland, each was enmeshed in war, on rough average, four out of every ten years—nor were they necessarily mild conflicts. Schroeder takes a dark view of Europe’s “international society”: Seeking durable peace through a balance of power was futile first because there never was or could be any general consensus on what a suitable balance was; almost every individual state had a concept of a European balance which contradicted the concepts envisioned and pursued by others. Secondly, the assumptions, methods, and devices required by balance-of-power politics and actually used to achieve and maintain the supposed desirable balance blocked the peaceful resolution of conflicts except in temporary, unstable ways, directly promoted conflict, and made the periodic escalation of particular conflicts into general systemic war more likely. Thirdly, the size, structure, power, and geographical position of the various European states virtually guaranteed that the free play of competitive forces among them would not result in a general stability, independence, and balance, but in destruction for some, mutilation for others, dependence for still others, and hegemony, if not outright empire, for one or two. (Schroeder 1994b:10) Two concluding points may be made about the balance of power. First, as fact or norm, the concept lends a certain changelessness to history. Regardless of the composition of the system, balances have always arisen and always will. In this, the balance of power is no different from any other nomothetic account of international politics in which a grasp of the “essential” or “recurrent” elements of history comes at the expense of understanding historical change (see Hoffmann 1977:35). Morgenthau often wrote of the “dynamic quality” of international relations, yet his theory more often soars from peak to peak, lighting on history’s fixed landmarks. Second, in contrast to Niebuhr’s tragic conception of the balance, as a scientific theory it represents a limited historical project, distant from process and idealized in its historical depiction. This method is perhaps prompted by the fear of “falling back into history”—i.e., that theorists must stand apart from what their historian colleagues are doing—but one wonders if theoretical concepts simply might not withstand rigorous historical scrutiny (see Rosenberg 1994:19). Morgenthau’s own inquiry into the European balance paints an intricate web of social and structural factors, peculiar to time, place, culture, and class. One could even argue that the inevitability thesis is a rejection of history and of tragedy. Weighing historical processes, as reflected in an account of D-Day or the Afghan mujahedin, the Iwo Jima statue, or a Le Carré novel, one is hard pressed to defend the automatic nature of the balance of power. Churchill promised blood, sweat, and tears, not a mechanical balance. We will see in the next chapter that neorealists carry this impulse to its logical ahistorical end.
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 79
Morgenthau’s legacy In form, Morgenthau’s approach is not unlike the scientific-rationalists he criticized for having promoted a progressivist philosophy disguised as science. Morgenthau, too, tried to square one of the West’s great intellectual traditions with a science of history. Morgenthau’s philosophy may be superior and his science more plausible. Still, one wonders if statecraft can be explained with reference to a set of laws. Morgenthau walks a thin beam between the nomothetic and the contingent. He makes a forceful historical claim that states follow their interests, while at the same time exhorting statesmen to do just that. The same is true of the “scales” of the balance of power alongside the concept’s normative justification. These are very different conceptions of the same phenomena, one law-driven, the other the outcome of choices made freely or under duress. It is difficult to reconcile Morgenthau’s “objective laws” (which are purported to operate in spite of the actor’s preferences) with a normative accent on tragic statecraft. If leaders acted as predicted, the normative counsel would be redundant.2 Indeed, Morgenthau would be the last person to suggest that we can take the statecraft out of politics; necessity did not make statesmen into automatons. All the same, that is where historical laws lead. As Niebuhr made plain, tragedy involved deliberate decisions that went against the current of events. Ultimately, Morgenthau, too, believed that character and discretion were crucial to sound leadership. At a forum shortly before his death, he stressed the constraints that the strategic environment imposed on presidential statecraft, but he left no doubt that it was “essentially the character of the president which determines the outcomes of the policy” (Morgenthau 1983:5). One of his last projects was a lengthy essay on the impact that Lincoln’s religious faith had had on the great and tragic statesman’s politics (Morgenthau and Hein 1983). Morgenthau perhaps pioneered a science of politics that grew too scientific. While he attempted to fit political science, glove over fist, atop a political philosophy, his “scientific” successors would forego attempts to join the two, indeed, would grow hostile toward any philosophical “intrusion” on their newfound verities (see Thompson 1984). Moreover, while the forms of Morgenthau’s theory are scientific, especially as set out in Politics Among Nations, the substance is more prudential. It aims to cultivate wise statecraft rather than to defend strict historical laws. The result is a philosophy of international relations, in the venerable realist tradition, unmatched in its counsel of restraint, its frostiness toward platitudes, and its eye for ideology. One is reminded of what Oakeshott said about Hobbes having fused the art of history (“the ordered register of past experiences”) and prudence (“the power to anticipate experience by means of the recollection of what has gone before”) (introduction to Hobbes 1947: xxiii–iv). Morgenthau was a profound and articulate voice in this great tradition; but it is a tradition of philosophy, not of science.
80 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
George F.Kennan and the historical foundations of containment Realists are often accused of providing intellectual cover for America’s involvement in the cold war.3 Morgenthau, from his “inevitability” perspective, recalled this was exactly what happened: I had my first experience as a theoretician of international relations under the Truman—Acheson administration of America’s foreign policy. Theory then provided a theoretical justification for what the policy makers were doing, you may say, instinctively—what they were doing pragmatically, on a mere day-by-day basis…the policy of containment was never officially formulated. It grew as an almost instinctive reaction to the threat of Russian imperialism… There was no theory in support of these new policies. It was only as an afterthought that theoreticians developed a doctrine in the form of a theoretical framework which gave rational justification to the new policies. (Morgenthau 1962a:73–4)
Morgenthau’s point was that necessity had driven early cold war policies. Theory had followed practice. John Lewis Gaddis has noted (1982:4) that containment of the USSR was “much on the minds of Washington officials from 1941 on,” as the Soviets went from ally to enemy. There was, however, a critical interlude in American foreign policy at the close of the Second World War when troops were withdrawn from Central Europe, forces were drawn down at home, military spending plummeted from $81 billion in 1945 to $13 billion in 1947, and Europe fell into despair. All this happened before containment. It was George Kennan, above all, who “theorized” containment before it happened. He did so from a uniquely historical perspective, and his case, which we now take up, suggests the difficulties of rendering historical understandings, particularly subtle ones, into foreign policy. History and statecraft One of Kennan’s more intriguing books is The Marquis de Custine and His “Russia in 1839” (1971), in which Kennan recounts the French aristocrat’s travels through Russia in the summer of that year and the controversy surrounding the publication, in 1841, of the Marquis’s book, a searing, tabloidstyle critique of Russian political culture and Czarist abuses during the reign of Nicholas I.Kennan judged that Russia in 1839 was perhaps an unfair book about nineteenth-century Russia, but that it was an excellent book, “probably the best of books,” about the Russia of Stalin and Brezhnev and Kosygin. As Kennan saw it, in the Marquis’s depiction of Nicholas I were all the seeds of Stalinism:
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 81
The absolute power of a single man; his power over thoughts as well as actions; the indecent association of sycophancy upwards with brutality downwards; the utter disenfranchisement and helplessness of the popular masses; the nervous punishment of innocent people for the offenses they might be considered capable of committing rather than one they had committed; the neurotic relationship to the West; the frantic fear of foreign observation; the obsession with espionage; the secrecy; the systematic mystification; the general silence of intimidation; the preoccupation with appearances at the expense of reality; the systematic cultivation of falsehood as a weapon of policy; the tendency to rewrite the past. (Kennan 1971:124–5) This is the gist of Kennan’s approach to the past as a foundation for presentday political analysis and diplomatic practice. There are no exact historical analogies to today’s dilemmas, but understanding the past is imperative to understanding the present. Whatever a regime’s current ideology or outward mask, continuity matters more than change. Political culture, administra tive methods, national character, the nature and scope of interests, all display persistent traces and patterns. As Mark Twain said, history may not repeat itself; but it rhymes. Kennan was a student of Russian language, literature, and culture. He studied traditional Russian history (as opposed to “Sovietology”) under Otto Hoetsch and Karl Stählin at the University of Berlin in the course of his Foreign Service training in the late 1920s and early 1930s. As director of the policy planning staff of the State Department from 1947 to 1949, and as ambassador to the Soviet Union and later Yugoslavia, Kennan’s ideas about history were at the core of his vocation, most famously in his elucidation of the idea of containment of the USSR. During a raft of visiting fellowships and in his long tenure at Princeton’s Institute for Advanced Study, Kennan produced monographs on Russian and American diplomacy, histories of nineteenth-century Franco-Russian relations, a study of the origins of the First World War, three volumes of memoirs, several more on statecraft in the nuclear age, and, more recently, an unusual work of political philosophy, Around the Cragged Hill (1993), and a collection of essays, At a Century’s Ending (1996). Throughout, he has been a vigorous and literary sage. Kennan’s affinity for history seems to rest as much on philosophical tenets as on empirical methods. His “moral closeness” to history springs from an apparently spiritual, more or less Burkean, traditionalism. He believes that “Wherever the authority of the past is too suddenly and too drastically undermined—wherever the past ceases to be the great and reliable reference book of human problems—wherever, above all, the experience of the father becomes irrelevant to the trials and searchings of the son—there the foundations of man’s inner health and stability begin to crumble, insecurity and panic begin to take over, conduct becomes erratic and aggressive” (Kennan 1954:34). This traditionalism should also seep into political practice. Kennan suggests that the complete diplomat reads history closely, but also grasps a received code of political conduct. In this fashion, broadly construed
82 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
“historical” knowledge is preserved and woven into everyday conduct. Still, when Kennan exhorts us to forswear the “histrionics of moralism” (1985/ 1986:212)—to shun a foreign policy aimed at defending our ethical sensibilities rather than our national interests—his pronouncement issues from within a generally liberal tradition. History and containment This traditional ethic surfaces repeatedly in Kennan’s bleak view of the destructive messianism of Soviet communism—its claim to upend tradition and supplant human nature, and its conceit of “creating truth” quite apart from “objective reality.” Echoing Morgenthau, Kennan argued in his famous Long Telegram (1946), that Soviet ideology was a tool of historic Russian interests, “borne along by deep and powerful currents of Russian nationalism” (Kennan 1967:557). Fear of capitalist encirclement was a hangover from old anxieties about being ringed by hostile states. However, Kennan also argued that Russia’s history and societal temperament fueled a special virulence and sophistication—almost a pathology—in the ideological state. Even in Custine he found “the terrible, cynical, demeaning contempt for the truth that seemed to pervade Russian government and society… the cultivation of a series of massive fictions—fictions not just subconsciously and innocently appropriated into the minds of the bearers but deliberately conceived, perpetuated, and enforced” (Kennan 1971:80). In telling us how immoderate and un-Burkean Russian society can be, Kennan engages in cultural or collective psychohistory. True, he gives us great swaths of event-centered “political” history stretching back to the Grand Duchy of Muscovy in the thirteenth century, through the rise and fall of czars, and the reach and recoil of the Russian empire. But Kennan’s history extends as well to the psychological machinations of Russian society, its congenital insecurity, mental fusion of aggression and defense, “Oriental secretiveness,” conspiracy, “self-hypnotism,” “savage class distinctions,” and xenophobia. As he wrote of his diplomatic tour in Moscow in the 1930s: “Politically, I had to go back into Russian history and to probe the origins of the traditional suspicion and diffidence on the part of the Russian rulers, I had to weigh the effects of climate on character, the results of century-long contact with Asiatic hordes, the influence of medieval Byzantium, the national origins of the people, and the geographic characteristics of the country” (Kennan 1967:74). Kennan’s “X” article, “The Sources of Soviet Conduct” (1947), the cornerstone of containment, reads like Edward Gibbon’s sweeping cultural commentary, though with only a trace of Gibbon’s moralism from the high ground of reason. More than once, Kennan quotes the Enlightenment historian’s Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (1776–88), as here, describing the earnest deceptions and self-deceptions of the Bolsheviks: “From enthusiasm to imposture the step is perilous and slippery; the Demon of Socrates affords a memorable instance how a wise man may deceive himself, how a good man may deceive others, how the
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 83
conscience may slumber in a mixed and middle state between self-illusion and voluntary fraud” (Kennan 1947:567). Clearly, Kennan did not use a reproducible historical method to arrive at his view of Russian politics. His ample survey of Russian culture and anthropology was informed as much by Tolstoy and Gogol and Dostoevsky as by Klyuchevski’s lectures on Russian history that Kennan read in Berlin. Kennan is interested in more than political history, more than the balance of power, more, even, than patterns of national interests. He says he is drawn instead to history’s personal dramas, “the mystery of the individual personality—its ultimate autonomy of decision—its interaction with the mass” (Kennan 1989:21). No doubt, his cultural reading of Russian history eclipsed many individual dilemmas. Yet, even if not systematically set out, this focus on Russia’s political personality reflects an era when national character and civic resolve were regarded as critical in the East-West struggle. These subtleties of style and method may well have doomed Kennan’s historical arguments. What befell his vision of containment is instructive in the difficulties of transposing history into policy. Kennan was confident, based on his knowledge of Russian history, that Soviet foreign policy was propelled by domestic factors. The party line “is not based on any objective analysis of the situation beyond Russia’s borders; that it has, indeed, little to do with conditions outside of Russia; that it arises mainly from basic inner-Russian necessities” (Kennan 1967:549). Soviet leaders would trump up threats and exploit traditional fears in order to solidify their own tyranny. They would flatten domestic foes, perhaps smear them as agents provocateurs in the pay of hostile powers. Nevertheless, hewing to the well-worn tracks of historic Russian external relations, the Politburo would not be militarily reckless or adventuristic. This would needlessly risk the Kremlin’s prestige. Most importantly, Kennan assured the West that, behind a veil of vigor and industry, the Soviet system contained the seeds of its own decay. The United States and its allies might hasten the day, but the passage of time was certain to produce “either the break-up or the gradual mellowing of Soviet power.” Until then, the policy should be one of “long-term, patient but firm and vigilant containment of Russian expansive tendencies” (Kennan 1947:582, 575). Kennan meant containment to be a political instrument, marked by “cool and collected” diplomacy, not “threats or blustering or superfluous gestures of outward ‘toughness’” (ibid.: 575). Yet, already in the spring of 1946 he foresaw that containing his own colleagues might be the more difficult task. It would be hard to “restrain the hot-heads and panic-mongers and keep policy on a firm and even keel” (see Miscamble 1992:28). Of course, Kennan’s fears were realized. His view was eventually overrun by harder-bitten analyses of the Soviet threat. Containment, codified in NSC-68, became primarily a military, albeit defensive, doctrine. As the cold war escalated, he increasingly felt, he wrote later, “like one who has inadvertently loosened a large boulder from the top of a cliff and now helplessly witnesses its path of destruction in the valley below, shuddering and wincing at each successive glimpse of disaster” (quoted in Zakaria 1996:6).
84 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Had Kennan at the time turned his political profiling skills on his State Department colleagues, he might have realized how distant his ideas were from theirs. To say in the face of the Kremlin’s diplomatic bluster and elaborate military parades, that Soviet-style expansion had over the centuries exacted a “severe tax on Tsardom” looked to many like a policy of insouciance, and a retreat into history. The un-Washington character of Kennan’s language and historical deductions may also have contributed to rejection of his recommendations. His own writings could be deeply ambivalent. (William F.Buckley called Kennan “one of the principal ambiguists among the American intelligensia” (quoted in Hixson 1989: ix).) Defending the primacy of diplomacy in one argument, Kennan would stress “the adroit and vigilant application of counter-force at a series of constantly shifting geographical and political points” in the next (Kennan 1947:576). Generally, the reaction to Kennan’s “policy history” was to seize on the combative, workaday “lessons” it contained, and to discard the longer-term, moderating ones. When Dean Acheson was Under-Secretary of State, for example, he dismissed Kennan’s muted estimation of the USSR’s intentions and its history of risk aversion, emphasizing instead the Soviet capacity for aggression. Later, at the State Department helm, Acheson would welcome NSC68 as an appropriate tool with which to “bludgeon” the executive into setting an aggressive policy. As Acheson later recalled, Kennan’s “recommendations …were of no help; his historical analysis might or might not have been sound, but his predictions and warnings could not have been better” (Miscamble 1992:26). Lost on policymakers, Kennan’s “Shakespearean insight and vision,” as Louis Halle called it, is exactly the sort of approach that sets social scientists’ teeth on edge. Reading Kennan’s Gibbonesque passages, one can almost hear the chorus of derision—“intuitive,” “folkloric,” “anti-scientific,” “unoperationalizable,” “dyadspecific,” and on and on. Apparently, though, Kennan’s attention to the long term was fruitful. This is clearest in his views that political motivations can be deeply anchored in the national psyche; that, especially on rhetorically-charged issues, professional diplomacy remains an important tool of statecraft; and that historical perspective can be a source of moderation in policy. The depth of Kennan’s views of the Soviet Union, for example, makes for less dire scenarios than we saw in Niebuhr. Within this framework, Kennan provides a plausible description of the end of the cold war. As previously mentioned, Kennan expected that Kremlin high priests would soften their ideology, and he believed in the historic perils of “imperial overstretch,” to use Paul Kennedy’s words. The following assessment of Russian political economy, from the 1947 “X” article, also rings true: “Russia will remain economically a vulnerable, and in a certain sense an impotent, nation, capable of exporting its enthusiasms and of radiating the strange charm of its primitive political vitality but unable to back up those articles of export by the real evidences of material power and prosperity” (Kennan 1947:578). That said, Kennan was surprised by how abruptly and bloodlessly the end came. Kennan continues to try to bridge the gap between plausible and useful history: pointing, in 1983, to late nineteenth-century Europe in order to illuminate the
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 85
“dreadful and dangerous condition” of US—Soviet relations, where antagonism, suspicion, and militarization formed “the familiar characteristics, the unfailing characteristics, of a march toward war” (quoted in Oberdorfer 1991:30); comparing the complex, post-cold war foreign vista to that which confronted the early Republic in the wake of the Napoleonic Wars and the splintering of the Spanish Empire (Kennan 1995); or mapping the rivers of hatred in the Balkans (Kennan 1993b). It would be foolish to deny that Kennan’s ideas have not been, to some extent, politically instrumental. The more interesting question is whether he twisted his history to fit his politics. Kennan scholar David Mayers suggests that there was no need. Precisely because of the meticulousness of his scholarship, Kennan’s monographs serve as compelling “exercises in political edification and resonate with lessons for American leaders,” raising “a warning from the past and [an] implied rebuke of present trends” (Mayers 1988:219–20). Mayers notwithstanding, Kennan’s interpretation of the immediate origins of the cold war is couched to vindicate the idea of political, rather than military, containment. As Kennan tells it, with the Marshall Plan putting down roots and the Berlin Blockade successfully thwarted, he felt the time was ripe for “serious talks” with the Russians. Thus, he wrote, “it was one of the great disappointments of my life to discover that neither our Government nor our Western European allies had any interest in entering into such discussions at all. What they and the others wanted from Moscow…was essentially ‘unconditional surrender.’ And they were prepared to wait for it. This was the beginning of 40 years of cold war” (Kennan 1994: A17). This is a plausible, though not universally held, interpretation of events. Most explanations consider the intransigence of both sides. It should be noted that Kennan has also been accused of distorting history in order to blame the cold war squarely on Russia. William Appleman Williams (1956: 222–4), the shrillest of these critics, blasted Russia Leaves the War, the first volume of Kennan’s Pulitzer Prize-winning SovietAmerican Relations, 1917–1920 (1956) on grounds that the diplomat-turnedchronicler had rearranged Russia’s historical scenery in order to justify containment, perhaps even in hopes of cadging a job as Secretary of State in the event that Adlai Stevenson were to be elected President. Despite these charges, Kennan’s historical claims seem to maintain a basic modesty and balance. As a practicing historian, after all, he is struck most by how subjective and open-ended history is: “its multi-dimensional quality, its lack of tidy beginnings and endings, its stubborn refusal to be packaged in any neat and satisfying manner…every beginning and ending of every historical work is always in some degree artificial and contrived” (Kennan 1960:205). Kennan insists that the historian is never merely a purveyor of facts. At his disposal are “only the hieroglyphics of the written word, as preserved in the crumbling old documents, and sometimes a few artifacts that have survived the ravages of time and neglect— perhaps even a portrait, or a drawing, or, if he works in recent history, a photograph or two. But these evidences only hint at the real story—they don’t tell it” (Kennan 1986: 42). The telling is left to the historian’s imagination.
86 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
This unassuming method becomes a foil for too certain a science of history. The texture of Kennan’s history could not be more different from the pinpoint “eventsdata” we shall see in Chapter 6. “In the fabric of human events, one thing leads to another,” Kennan observes in American Diplomacy (1950:50); “Our action in the field of foreign affairs is cumulative; it merges with a swelling stream of other human happenings; and we cannot trace its effect with any exactness once it has entered the fluid substance of history.” Admittedly, Kennan is not exactly brimming with an historical logic to diplomatic practice. If anything, he represents a sort of fatalism in his belief that the Russian character would endure, or, similarly, that Tashkent would always be Tashkent. Nevertheless, if he sounds at times like a man from another century, in other ways he can be quite acute. He recognizes the limits in statecraft of relying solely on eurocentric history, pointing, as an example, to the aridity of applying Westphalian logic to the Chinese experience; and he is alert to the fallacies of tracking cross-cultural historical “stages.” This skepticism also seems to underlie Kennan’s entreaties for a modest, self-effacing foreign policy, where, he says, “our own national interest is all we are really capable of knowing and understanding” (ibid.: 103). Conclusion: through a glass darkly This is also the thesis of an eerily current essay of Kennan’s, “America and the Russian Future,” which appeared in Foreign Affairs in 1951. Kennan concedes in the article how superficial and imperfect our knowledge is. He notes that if there are laws of politics, they will be peculiar to circumstance, modified by national character, and vulnerable to contingency—all of which means that the better part of political prediction is spent poking at historical tea leaves. “These things being so,” he concludes, “we must admit with respect to the future of government in Russia, we see ‘as through a glass, darkly’” (Kennan 1951:368). However, there is another sort of darkness in Kennan’s realist approach generally: a deep historical pessimism that casts gloom on the narrative as well as the lessons of history. If classical realism represents a philosophy of history, as Martin Wight believes that all international theory must, it is a somber outlook. More to the point, realist history has sustained a philosophy of prudence in statecraft. In pursuit of the Aristotelian ideal of bridging theoretical and practical wisdom, policy realism has perhaps issued in grimmer scenarios than those of detached political science.4 That said, however, many of the subtleties of realist thought, especially normative ones, stem from that same Aristotelian commitment. A troubling suggestion in this chapter, however, is that those subtleties translate poorly into policy. Percolating through political and bureaucratic filters, “realism” has prompted schemes that bear little resemblance to the theory, even taking into account the diversity of realist thought. Policymakers may prefer historical deductions that bear at least the color of science. Realism’s attention to history lends a salutary “concreteness” to interna tional theory, but its predisposition to inquire into certain features of the international
HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 87
landscape at the expense of others threatened to cut short debate and sharpen foreign policies. Realists too easily link the idea of historical inevitability to that of political necessità. The challenge for realists is to avoid this trap of tragedy. Too much pessimism and prudence risks closing off alternative scenarios and blinding leaders to obvious historical changes. As Niebuhr cautioned in The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness (1944: 176), “if hopes are dupes, fears may be liars.” Realists continue to take perverse pleasure in the defects of legalism and populism in foreign policies, but that is the reality today, and the result is not all windy Wilsonian moralism either. World politics are still distant from what the poet Seamus Heaney called “that further shore where hope and history rhyme,” but the record has not been irretrievably grim.
88
5 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM Kenneth N.Waltz and neorealist theory
Bernard Crick once noted (1964:239) that American political thought seems always to be evolving from “mere opinion” to “scientific knowledge,” as enthusiastic revisionists haul ideas out of the shadows and up the peaks of science. Neorealists claim to have done precisely this with classical realism, replacing their forebears’ ideas about human nature, historical contingency, and diplomatic practice with an elegant theory of international politics. At the center of neorealism’s scientific claims is its avowed ahistoricism. Neorealists contend that their predecessors’ attention to history reflected a basic misconception of theory. In place of an unwieldy “struggle with the facts,” neorealists offer a timeless deductive theory in the tradition of natural science. The anarchical structure of the international realm is the cornerstone of the project. Neorealists argue that structure explains more about the history of international relations, and does so more economically, than any other level of analysis.1 This chapter first briefly describes neorealism’s foundations in the philosophy of science. It then examines the writings of the preeminent neorealist, Kenneth Waltz, focusing on his landmark work, Theory of International Politics (1979), which, according to one study, “revived the flagging fortunes of the Realist tradition” (Buzan et al. 1993:1). Turning toward structural research more generally, the chapter explores historical challenges, problems of theorizing historical change, and questions of statecraft and ethical choice. A further section reviews Stephen M.Walt’s Revolution and War (1996), a recent addition to the neorealist literature, highlighting the problem of “theoretical filtering,” or how a closed theoretical design may unduly narrow the researcher’s range of historical interests and evidence. Waltz has had a vast impact on the discipline, both in the development of the neorealist research project, and in various reactions against it. In terms of the use of history in international relations, Waltz has pervasively affirmed—even for his critics —that rigorous deductive methods are a way of overcoming the historical problem. A “scientific research programme” Since the mid-1980s, neorealism has dominated international relations in the United States, although its position of “intellectual hegemony” has perhaps passed
90 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
its peak (Burchill 1995:83). In the field’s empirical wing, Waltz’s theory spawned a number of structural hypotheses about geopolitics (for example, Gilpin 1981, Mearsheimer 1990, Liberman 1993, and Mastanduno 1997); nuclear proliferation (for example, Frankel 1993, and Sagan and Waltz 1995); political economy (for example, Gowa 1989 and Grieco 1995); international cooperation (for example, Oye 1986, Snidal 1991, and Mearsheimer 1994/1995); the formation of alliances (for example, Walt 1987, Snyder 1990, Labs 1992, and Schweller 1994); and actual foreign policymaking (Elman 1996). Neorealism has also elicited two main countertheories: neoliberalism and constructivism. These are errant, though identifiable, children of Waltz in that they adopt much of his method and language and mirror many of his assumptions about the philosophy of science (see, for example, Baldwin 1993, Kegley 1995, and Wendt 1995). Neorealism has prompted scores of philosophical and empirical challenges from a wide range of other perspectives as well.2 Neorealists argue that the inductivist approach to theory lays an inadequate foundation for a cumulative science of international politics. For Waltz, theory is a tool that makes political explanation possible. It is “a picture, mentally formed, of a bounded realm or domain of activity…and of the connections among its parts” (Waltz 1979:8). Without a theory, we are left with disconnected and randomly selected facts. Moreover, theory should be ahistorical in the sense that it is liberated from details of history, and is meant to apply with equal force to any historical period. “Though related to the world about which explanations are wanted,” Waltz suggests (ibid.: 6–7), theory “always remains distinct from that world. ‘Reality’ will be congruent neither with a theory nor with a model that may represent it.” On these grounds, Waltz describes Quincy Wright’s The Study of International Relations (1955), for example, as a profoundly anti-theoretical enterprise, attempting “a synthesis of all possibly relevant knowledge” (Waltz 1959b: 66). He criticizes the Correlates of War project, the subject of the next chapter, on the grounds that its “data-making” is naïvely inductive. Without a theory, one does not know where to begin, or what data to generate (Waltz 1975: 9). He tars the entire school of classical realists as “behavioralists” who strove to bring theory into focus with history. They failed “to take the fateful step beyond developing concepts to the fashioning of a recognizable theory.” Waltz concedes that Morgenthau presented “elements of a theory…but never a theory…without a concept of the whole he could only deal with the parts.” He adds that Morgenthau “was fond of repeating Blaise Pascal’s remark that ‘the history of the world would have been different had Cleopatra’s nose been a bit shorter’ and then asking ‘How do you systemize that?’ His appreciation of the role of the accidental and the occurrence of the unexpected in politics dampened his theoretical contribution.” Waltz is equally critical of Aron’s explication of the qualitative difference between economic man and political man, and the challenges this poses for a theory of politics: “Aron did not relate obvious differences between economics and politics to the requirements of theory construction. He merely identified differences in the confident belief that because of them no international-political theory is possible” (Waltz 1990: 24–6).
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 91
If the deductive method is, as Buzan et al. (1993:191) note, “happily adrift from the world,” where does theory comes from? According to Waltz (1979: 9), theory is a creative act that transcends “experimental” history. “The longest process of painful trial and error will not lead to the construction of a theory unless at some point a brilliant intuition flashes, a creative idea emerges.” While inductivists propose to build theory out of facts, Waltz points out that “many of the greatest natural scientists, even in the nonage of their disciplines, built upon highly abstract and truly breathtaking generalization” (Waltz 1959b: 58). Theory requires more abstraction and less history. Logical inquiry must begin with a conceptual proposition, and then deduce and test assumptions derived from it. Only after a theory is established may evidence be systematically canvassed. Waltz cites Albert Einstein: “A theory can be tested by experience…but there is no way from experience to the setting up of a theory” (Waltz 1979:7). The deductive mode of inquiry that Waltz champions has assumed nearcanonical status in the natural sciences. Some social scientists have adopted this model, believing that a social “physics” may be derived through a chain of logical deductions. As Carl Hempel did with history, deductivists pursue “covering laws.” They deduce particular outcomes from general assumptions. Elegance (simplicity) and parsimony (economy of explanation, not enumerating causes unnecessary to account for the facts) are considered virtues here. It is probably fair to say that, in the wake of Theory of International Politics, most empirical work in international relations, at least in the United States, has adhered more or less to the main propositions of deductive social science.3 Many of Waltz’s critics have responded in kind, attempting to falsify neorealism and suggesting other deductive and positivist paths of research. Even constructivists, who have tried to redirect the discipline away from neorealist materialism and toward the social underpinnings of “state” behavior, espouse “a very pro-science line” and “fully endorse the scientific project of falsifying theories against evidence” (Wendt 1995:75). According to deductivists, a rigorous process of falsification compensates for this theoretical elegance. This is the laboratory idea of testing theory against historical facts. Karl Popper’s (1959 and 1965) rigorous doctrine of falsification is well known, notably his example that the proposition that all swans are white is falsified by the existence of a single black swan. (Cf. Ashley (1986:261, 298, n. 9 and 11.) Waltz applauds Popper’s critique of induc tivism, although he is less taken with Popper’s low empirical threshold for falsifying theory. Waltz argues that testing theories is “a difficult and subtle task…questions of truth and falsity are somehow involved, but so are questions of usefulness and uselessness. In the end, one sticks with the theory that reveals most, even if its validity is suspect” (Waltz 1979:123–4). What Waltz is describing is Imre Lakatos’s “sophisticated methodological falsification.” Lakatos argues that theories should be tested not so much against the “facts” as against other theories. His model states (Lakatos 1970: 116):
92 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
a scientific theory T [is] falsified if and only if another theory T′ has been proposed with the following characteristics: (1) T′ has excess empirical content over T: that is, it predicts novel facts, that is, facts improbable in the light of, or even forbidden, by T; (2) T′ explains the previous success of T, that is, all the unrefuted content of T is contained (within the limits of observational error) in the content of T′; and (3) some of the excess content of T′ is corroborated. This simply means that a few falsifying cases do not overturn a theory. According to Lakatos, a good theory subsumes a number of previously disparate generalizations in a single explanatory system. In terms of falsification, there is no such thing as a “crucial case.” No single experiment capsizes a theory. The important thing is how well a proposition withstands repeated attempts at falsification. If it does well, the theory grows in stature; it has proved its mettle, and research based on the model gains momentum. If it does poorly, the theory is subjected to further tests, refashioned, or, in extreme circumstances, discarded. What Lakatos calls a “positive heuristic” arises among researchers, and a “protective belt” of auxiliary assumptions and hypotheses is erected around the theory’s core. These peripheral assumptions endure actual testing. The idea is to shield the core theory through the project’s fits and starts, even as postulates based on it may be upended. Only when the number of anomalies becomes overwhelming is the model displaced by a theory that appears to offer greater explanatory power. Within this rigorous framework, neorealists set out to fashion what Lakatos calls a “scientific research programme,” a focused progression of experiment and criticism. The idea was, literally, to discipline the field of international relations. Researchers would dedicate themselves to one theoretical approach over an extended period, and not be deterred by initial contrary findings.4 The anarchical structure of the international realm has been neorealism’s core, and has sustained a range of hypotheses and testing aimed at generating novel explanations and predictions about inter-state relations. The apparatuses of the discipline have also supported this research program, with several journals well disposed toward neorealist research. “Scientific” realists have also traced the evolution of realism, using Lakatos’s procedure for “rationally reconstructing” the paradigm. The “steps” of realist scientific discovery are thus retraced by recounting the paradigm’s “internal history.” In such reconstructions of field, the realists that have been discussed thus far are deemed “foundational” thinkers in a linear progression of increasingly sophisticated and precise theories which ends with Waltz. One account that explicitly follows Lakatos’s methodology describes realism’s “growth of objective knowledge” in this way: what “began as a philosophical reflection on the nature and behavior of security-seeking entities, has gradually been transformed—however imperfectly—into the abstract, deductive formulations which modern social science demands” (Tellis 1995:4).
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 93
As noted earlier, Lakatos himself was uncertain to what degree his assumptions and methods applied to the social sciences. He noted (1970:175–6 n.) that much social science theorizing was lacking in rigor, and required “patched-up, unimaginative series of pedestrian ‘empirical’ adjustments.” He was particularly dubious of attempts to quantify social studies, fearing that statistics might function “primarily to provide a machinery for producing phony corroborations and thereby a semblance of ‘scientific progress’ where, in fact, there is nothing but an increase in psuedo-intellectual garbage.”5 Setting Lakatos’s own doubts aside, it is interesting to note that while Waltz claims to have hurdled the “logical-positivist” problem of the behavioral realists, the whole process of falsification hinges on historical evidence. In other words, because neorealist theory is deliberately “underdetermined” by the “facts,” the wall between history and theory stands. Nevertheless, in terms of developing the research program, the empirical battle wages on in the “experimental” literature. Waltz obviously holds a sophisticated view of the relationship between theory and fact. He notes, especially in his early work, that “facts” are “theory-laden.” “Direct” observation is influenced by expectations, and the distinction between evidence and observation is often blurred. He also contends that “empirical verification, while important, cannot produce certainty, in the social or in the natural sciences, for by the most intricate and oft-repeated tests one does not exclude alternative possibilities.” Consequently, he says, “historical refutation is seldom accepted as conclusive” (Waltz 1959b: 57–9). In his later writings, however, Waltz holds that, if subjected to “hard cases,” a theory may in fact be “confirmed,” although he notes that any test is conclusive only in reference to the assumptions postulated. The possibility lingers that some untried series of tests might undercut a theory, just as a new theory may explain or predict more than the abstraction at hand (Waltz 1979: 123–4). Nevertheless, when Waltz suggests that deductive methods have subdued the historical problem, we might bear in mind the serene protocol he establishes in Theory of International Politics for testing a theory: 1. State the theory being tested. 2. Infer hypotheses from it. 3. Subject the hypotheses to experimental or observational tests. 4. In taking steps two and three, use the definitions of terms found in the theory being tested. 5. Eliminate or control perturbing variables not included in the theory under test. 6. Devise a number of distinct and demanding tests. 7. If a test is not passed, ask whether the theory flunks completely, needs repair and restatement, or requires a narrowing of the scope of its explanatory claims. (ibid.: 13) Although presented as straightforward scientific procedures, these are challenging standards by which to judge historical evidence. Neorealism has been able to
94 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
sidestep troublesome historiography because a few contrary cases do not overturn the theory, but the entire research program will be paralyzed if dismissing historical evidence becomes common practice. Early Waltz: philosophy, history and the pursuit of parsimony This section looks briefly at the development of Waltz’s ideas. This development is germane to our topic because it traces a leading theorist’s attempts to bridge a skeptical view of history and rigorous structural theory. Despite Waltz’s insistence on a uniquely “political” voice of inquiry, there are unavoidable parallels with other fields. In many ways, international relations was ripe for structural analysis. Structuralism made its mark in sociology and anthropology in the works of Émile Durkheim and Claude Lévi-Strauss. Structural work revolved around the idea that social characteristics were interrelated in a systematic way, and that ordered relationships could be discovered among these social “facts” and institutions without resorting to psychology or history. Writing for a 1954 international theory symposium, Waltz acknowledged the appeal of historical discourse, noting how the play of the mind over historical evidence elicited patterns of behavior, parallels with contemporary dilemmas, and pitfalls to be avoided. He suggested as well that an anchor in history helped save analysts from being swept up in vogue methodologies and strategic fads. However, there were limits to historical inquiry. Waltz pointed to Warren S.Thompson’s warning, in 1929, that without some sort of global distributive justice, population pressures alone would lead the “havenots” to launch war on the “haves.” He noted that Thompson’s estimate of cause “seems to be stated in a form that permits empirical-historical testing,” yet when the thesis is unpacked, “it becomes impossible to estimate the significance, or insignificance, of this one factor without relating it to others” (Waltz 1959b: 54). Why have intense population pressures not always resulted in wars? What might constrain the wrath of the impoverished? Would a more equitable distribution of wealth necessarily reduce the incidence of war? Data never clearly show these sorts of correlations. What was needed was a nonhistorical and nonempirical framework—a theory— with which to establish those ties. Waltz’s own grasp of the imperfections of historical knowledge bolsters his defense of ahistorical theory. He recognizes problems of objectivity, “utility,” and presentism in history. As noted above, his early skepticism centered on the problem that historical “facts” are easily tailored to fit the observer’s expectations. “It would be foolish to argue that simply by taking a more intensive look at the data one can build a compelling case for one or the other explanatory theory,” he explains. “Staring at the same set of data, the parties to the debate came to sharply different conclusions for the images they entertained led them to select and interpret the data in different ways. The estimate of cause is an idea related to but not identical with the occurrence one seeks to explain. The idea we entertain becomes a filter through which we pass our data” (ibid.: 60). If one were convinced that democracies
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 95
are pacific, for instance, it would be easy to argue that democratic wars were preventive or defensive actions. Alternatively, one might argue that democracy had slipped, perhaps at the hands of an overzealous president or a frenzied legislature. Waltz’s skepticism about using history has been obscured by his broader theoretical achievements. His most conspicuous revision of classical realism is a causal reversal in explaining state behavior under anarchy. Broadly speaking, classical realists followed what Waltz calls the “inside-out” method of theorizing. They saw foreign policies originating at the individual and state level. Human nature, calculations of interests, political leadership, national character, and a variety of other domestic factors drove decisions. Neorealists, by contrast, suggest that state behavior is generated by the structure of international power, and a state’s relative position in the system. Neorealists thus proceed from the international realm and backtrack toward unit-level analysis, discounting classical ideas about interests, leadership, values, and so forth. To this end, Waltz’s book, Man, the State and War (1959a), re-categorizes the history of political thought around the problem of war. Spinoza, Kant, and Rousseau provide the philosophical models for what Waltz calls the three “images” of political life: the individual, the state, and the international realm. Spinoza saw political ills as an outgrowth of individual passions. Kant believed that, over time, war weariness, cosmopolitanism, and the proliferation of constitutional states would yield international reforms. For Rousseau, international behavior was a risky game in which survival and cooperation were always at odds. Waltz draws a handful of historical analogies and makes a seven-page dash through European history, from the origins of the First World War to the 1956 Hungarian uprising. However, the book is primarily a synthesis of traditional political philosophy. These “ahistorical analyses,” he says, “lay bare the logic of civil society and at the same time make clear why the logic does not carry men past the establishment of separate states to the founding of a world state” (ibid.: 228). Waltz deals adeptly with the “level of analysis” problem. His critique of reductionism in explaining political conduct is effective, particularly his extended treatment of the first-image “psychologism” of behavioralism. Waltz also argues persuasively that the “irrationalities” of clashing political preferences cannot be attributed to a fixed human nature: While human nature no doubt plays a role in bringing about war, it cannot by itself explain both war and peace, except by the simple statement that man’s nature is such that sometimes he fights and sometimes he does not. And this statement leads inescapably to the attempt to explain why he fights sometimes and not others. If human nature is the cause of war and if, as in the systems of the first-image pessimists, human nature is fixed, then we can never hope for peace. If human nature is but one of the causes of war, then, even on the assumption that human nature is fixed, we can properly carry on a search for the conditions of peace. (ibid.: 30)
96 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
Sounding much like Niebuhr, Waltz suggests that “First-image optimists betray a naïveté in politics that vitiates their efforts to build a new and better world. Their lack of success is directly related to a view of man that is simple and pleasing, but wrong” (ibid.: 39). Analysis centered exclusively on the state is not very productive either. Even if it is true that bad states make war, says Waltz, “the obverse of this statement, that good states mean peace, is an extremely doubtful proposition” (ibid.: 122). Viewed in isolation, the failings of each causal tier are apparent. We need an integrated theory that includes the idea of structure. “The action of states, or, more accurately, of men acting for states, make up the substance of international relations. But the international political environment has much to do with the ways in which states behave. The influence to be assigned to the internal structure of states in attempting to solve the war—peace equation cannot be determined until the significance of the international environment has been considered” (ibid.: 122–3). A causal hierarchy is beginning to crystallize. Waltz sees the first and second images as methodologically intractable. They are diverse and malleable, and thus “underpredictive” from a deductive standpoint. The third image, however, is the “more inclusive nexus of causes” and is therefore the final determinant of war and peace. It is “social structure—institutionalized restraints and institutionalized methods of altering and adjusting interests—that counts” (ibid.: 230–1). In a world of sovereign states, conflict is inevitable. “Each state pursues its own interests, however defined, in the way it judges best. Force is a means of achieving the external ends of states because there exists no consistent, reliable process of reconciling the conflicts of interest that inevitably arise among similar units in a condition of anarchy” (ibid.: 238). Waltz illustrates his principal idea—international anarchy—by recounting Rousseau’s parable of the stag hunt: as the hunting party closes in on the deer, one of its members is distracted by a hare. Making a quick calculation about his individual interests, the hunter deserts the collective effort, spooks the stag, and chases after a unilateral dinner of hare. Rousseau suggests that the uncooperative hunter is acting rationally. Because any member of the party may decide to defect, it is in the interest of each to do so first. Again, conflict is inevitable. It is a “byproduct of competition and attempts at cooperation in society…conflict results from the seeking of any goal — even if in the seeking one attempts to act according to Kant’s categorical imperative” (ibid.: 171). Citing John McDonald, Waltz concludes, “Everybody’s strategy depends on everybody else’s” (ibid.: 201). This problem has been given mathematical form by game theorists and has been rediscovered by comparativists and international relations scholars as “two-level” and “nested” games (see the classic Neumann and Morgenstern 1944, and the more recent Evans, Jacobson and Putnam 1993). Waltz’s excellent “second-image” book, Foreign Policy and Democratic Politics (1967) is an historically rich snapshot of the provenance of American and British foreign policies. In it, Waltz presents a very different view of what drives state behavior. As he remarks at the outset, “adding the internal to the external dimension of foreign
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 97
policy makes for many complications” (Waltz 1967: v). He finds that, in setting foreign policy, democratic polities are hobbled by their inclusive, debate-driven, and populist governance. In an instructive counterpoint to this plodding process, Waltz invokes Bismarck, who, when questioned in the Reichstag about his foreign policy, reportedly told the members of the lower house that the conduct of foreign affairs was difficult enough without “three hundred asses” trying to impose their illinformed opinions. Waltz concludes not only that “third-image” constraints are distorted as they filter through democratic institutions and processes, but that foreign policies originate at the unit level. They are not rational and ineluctable responses to external conditions of anarchy. Waltz describes all too well how US foreign policy acquires a “Dixiecrat” drawl, just as class interests and civil service mandarins set the tone of British foreign relations. Waltz’s early work is perhaps most important for its insistence that there be international relations theory. Leery of empiricism and aware of the attendant epistemological problems, Waltz exhorts theorists to indulge in abstraction, to transcend the descriptive and anecdotal. The problems of empiricism, he writes, “constitute not merely a justification for theory but an argument that theorizing is an omnipresent, though often merely implicit, operation” (Waltz 1959b:54–5). Waltz made his own theory explicit in Theory of International Politics, the main design of which is the subject of the next section. Theory of International Politics When it was published in 1979, Theory of International Politics got a chilly reception. Hedley Bull (1980:20) called Waltz’s work a “reductio ad absurdum of its own starting point,” with implications “at loggerheads with common sense.” Margaret Bates (1981:589) noted that “the quest for explanatory power turns into a search for descriptive adequacy.” Richard Rosecrance (1981:712–13) decried Waltz’s “extreme structural formulation,” which “fails to pay attention to the real differentiation of state units that has taken place in the last one hundred years.” Waltz’s former teacher, William T.R. Fox, suggested (1980:493) that “A new Plato or a new Aristotle writing in the field of International Relations would…be a theorist whether or not he plays the game according to Waltz’s philosophy of science rules.” Theory of International Politics offers a bleak assessment of postwar international theory. Waltz notes that “nothing seems to cumulate, not even criticism”—a problem he attributes to the field’s stubbornly anti-deductive leaning (p. 18). Waltz labels as “reductionist” theories that encompass first- and secondimage analysis. His criticism of classical realism on these grounds has already been mentioned. Much of this book is devoted to upending competing “systems” theories. Waltz shows that Lenin, Hobson, Galtung, Wallerstein, Hoffmann, Rosecrance, and Kaplan are all inductivists of one sort or another. Waltz’s corrective to this, true to the “third-image” focus of Man, the State and War, is the idea that structure is the “prime mover” in international politics. Analysis must center on the international system itself, as distinct from the character of states and people.
98 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
Although the shape of the system is determined by the interactions and character of states, each state is “black-boxed” into a rational unitary whole. Its component parts and dynamics are assumed in the theory rather than incorporated as variables. Amid Waltz’s scientific goings on, it is easy to forget that he is a realist. He adheres to an unreconstructed realist view regarding the pursuit of interests and conflict among nations. “The ruler’s, and later the state’s, interest provides the spring of action; the necessities of policy arise from the unregulated competition of states; calculation based on these necessities can discover the policies that will best serve a state’s interest; success is the ultimate test of policy, and success is defined as preserving and strengthening the state” (p. 117). However, the methods of economics, not of history, inform Waltz’s realism. He believes economics is a more “mature” science than international relations by virtue of its development of deductive theory. He also believes that the economic model is proper. “Reasoning by analogy is helpful where one can move from a domain where theory is well developed to one where it is not. Reasoning by analogy is permissible where different domains are structurally similar” (p. 89). Throughout the book, Waltz draws parallels between balance-of-power theory and neoclassical microeconomic theory, i.e., ideas about how market forces condition the behavior of firms. The idea is that the international structure shapes political outcomes just as “the market” intervenes between economic acts and outcomes. In both cases, order emerges out of self-interested acts and the interactions of the units. “No state intends to participate in the formation of a structure by which it and others will be constrained. International-political systems, like economic markets, are individualist in origin, spontaneously generated, and unintended” (p. 91). Structural incentives and punishments devalue norms, transcend the vagaries and intentions of specific actors, and lend coherence to decisionmaking. Waltz believes that this logic applies not only to the 350 years of Westphalian history, but “obtains whether the system is composed of tribes, nations, oligopolistic firms, or street gangs” (Waltz 1990:37). The economic model is an attractive parallel, a way of rationalizing decisionmaking and outcomes in an anarchic and competitive realm. Then again, the analogy prompts a number of questions: Is power fungible? (See Keohane 1986: 184.) Is it useful to think of power as a single currency, encompassing different types of capabilities? Are the ends that states seek constant enough that the parallel with firms holds? Does military power translate directly into political power? How might one gauge the strength of what Montesquieu calls the “spirit of a nation”? Looming over the entire analogy, however, is the rational choice problem. The economic model assumes that we can confer a rationale upon acts, and that outcomes can be reliably anticipated. True, firms and states try to survive in a competitive and unregulated realm (the neoclassical assumption). However, whereas firms survive by maximizing returns, states survive by very diverse means. As Raymond Aron argues in Peace and War (1966:8–18), the rules of the game are never clear in politics; the ends of political action vary with the actors. Unlike soccer players or economic man, for whom winning or “maximizing satisfactions” are
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 99
unambiguous and universal goals, diplomats and soldiers pursue no single, rational end. Not all states function alike. They initiate policies and react to events in different ways. Waltz defines his “market,” the international system, according to three criteria: its ordering principle, the character of its units, and the distribution of unit capabilities within it (pp. 88–97). Looking at the modern world through this lens, he makes a number of observations: • the international system is anarchic; • under anarchy, states are functionally alike in that all seek survival through “selfhelp.” The character of states “drops out” of the equation; they become “units” that differ only in their material capabilities for survival; • the system is (was) bipolar; • states’ positions in the system are determined by their relative power capabilities —“the placement of states affects their behavior and even colors their character” (p. 127); • these capabilities are translated into political power through the “utility of force”; and • the system tends toward self-perpetuation. Various balances of power arise as alliances form to counter revisionist states. In structure, Waltz seeks a broadly plausible reason why states behave the way they do; “why the range of expected outcomes falls within certain limits,” “why patterns occur,” “why events repeat themselves” (p. 69). Although his theory is not a theory of foreign policy, its main implication is that state choices are driven by external conditions. Configurations of power “socialize” state behavior. This is the basis for Waltz’s balance-of-power hypotheses. Either “states” are rationally persuaded toward a balance, or a hidden hand of structure impels them there. These structural incentives override ideology and other unit-level characteristics. As Waltz argues elsewhere (1986:329), “state behavior varies more with differences of power than with differences in ideology, in internal structure of property relations, or in governmental form. In self-help systems, the pressures of competition weigh more heavily than ideological preferences or internal political pressures.” In Theory of International Politics, Waltz submits into evidence two “hard cases”: the FrancoRussian “Dual Alliance,” formalized in 1894 in reaction to the “Triple Alliance” of Germany, Austria-Hungary, and Italy; and US rearmament following the Second World War. He contends that second-image analysis would not anticipate these alliances. “Republicans” and “cossacks” did not want to ally. Americans and their leaders wanted to retrench in isolation, not divide the globe with the Soviets. Waltz points also to the dynamics of the cold war. He argued that although the United States and the USSR comprised very different, if not antithetical, social and political orders, the behavior of each was remarkably similar. The idea is that these parties were driven by structure; they acted as balancers despite themselves.
100 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
Many of these assertions have been challenged on logical as well as historical grounds. Before addressing those challenges, I would like to relate three hypotheses Waltz derives from his third-image focus. Each presents intractable problems in terms of historical testing. Interdependence increases opportunities for conflict. “Interdependence,” Waltz (1979: 138) writes, “looks different when viewed in the light of our theory.” If one assumes that the international system is premised on “self-help,” then interdependence produces vulnerability. “Close interdependence means closeness of contact and raises the prospect of at least occasional conflict. The fiercest civil wars and the bloodiest international ones have been fought within arenas populated by highly similar people whose affairs had become quite closely knit together. It is hard to get a war going unless the potential participants are somehow closely linked… It would seem to follow that a lessening of interdependence is desirable” (Waltz 1970: 205). In fact, Waltz is sanguine on this point. He believes that during the cold war, bipolarity effectively curbed the spread of interdependence, and that economic might is furthered by state power. Challenging Charles Kindleberger’s contention that “the nation-state is just about through as an economic unit,” Waltz argues (1979:94) that “economic capabilities cannot be separated from the other capabilities of states … States use economic means for military and political ends; and military and political means for the achievement of economic interests.” The state remained the ultimate arbiter of economic activity: “When the crunch comes, states remake the rules by which other actors operate” (p. 94). This line of reasoning would perhaps apply to the rise of the “trading state,” but less so to the emergence of multi-national commercial networks. Wallerstein (1974) and others deny that there is such a thing as national development in the modern world system (see also Rosecrance 1986, Kennedy 1987, and Strange 1996). Bipolarity is best. Morgenthau preferred a multipolar balance to a bipolar one because the uncertainties generated by multiple power centers instilled greater caution in statesmen. Waltz favors bipolarity; he contends that it cultivates “transparency” in the system, which breeds general stability and predictability in statecraft. “Those who are elevated to power and direct the activities of great states are not wholly free agents… The pressures of a bipolar world will strongly encourage them to act in ways better than their characters might otherwise lead one to expect” (Waltz 1964:906–7). In extolling the advantages of bipolarity, Waltz returns to the economic analogy, citing duopoly benefits, prospects for collusion, heightened foreseeability, lowered transaction costs, and so forth. Waltz’s prime exhibit is the postwar world. Writing in 1964, when US troops in Vietnam were still “military advisors,” Waltz was able to sanction bipolarity’s lack of “peripheries” as a systemic virtue. In a multipolar world, “the dangers are diffused, responsibilities unclear, and definition of vital interests easily obscured.” Such a precarious order tempts leaders into rash adventures. In a bipolar system, on the other hand, there are no shadowy zones on the map. International politics is a zero-sum game where “caution, moderation, and the management of crisis come to be of great and obvious importance” (ibid.: 884). The idea is a clear reflection of its times. But
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 101
Waltz seems blind to the potential for escalation that bipolarity implies, a problem he later acknowledges with respect to the US military buildup that began in the Carter administration and continued through most of the Reagan period, and which “burned up resources that could have safely been put to constructive use” (Waltz 1993:54). The same sort of presentism fueled Waltz’s predictions that the United States and the USSR would long endure as the predominant world powers, a quite different prophecy from Kennan’s historically inspired vision of the rot of the Soviet Union. More nuclear weapons may be better. According to Waltz (1979:180), nuclear weapons did not transform the nature of strategy. “Gunpowder,” he notes, “did not blur the distinction between the great powers and the others… nor have nuclear weapons done so.” Waltz’s provocative thesis is also linked to the stability of the long bipolar peace, where the “balance of terror” reinforced an already stable bipolar system by heightening the risks of miscalculation. He suggests (1981:3–4) that “much of the writing about the spread of nuclear weapons has this unusual trait: It tells us that what did not happen in the past is likely to happen in the future, that tomorrow’s nuclear states are likely to do to one another what today’s nuclear states have not done. A happy nuclear past leads many to expect an unhappy nuclear future.” Through the “measured spread” of nuclear weapons, he writes, new nuclear states “will confront the possibilities and feel the constraints” of their newly acquired power. They will be “more concerned for their safety and more mindful of dangers… Nations that have nuclear weapons have strong incentives to use them responsibly.” He argues that this logic applies even more forcefully to weak states. “A nuclear Libya, for example, would have to show great caution, even in rhetoric, lest she suffer retaliation in response to someone else’s anonymous attack on a third state” (ibid.: 30, 12). Two observations may be made about Waltz’s theory. First, although Waltz is of the ex nihilo “brilliant intuition” school of theoretical insight, one wonders if his theory was not born of the interplay of observation and abstraction. In many ways, Theory of International Politics depicts the seemingly settled bipolarity of what Waltz (1979:203–4) calls the “mature,” post-Nixon world, where prescriptions for statecraft devolve into the “managerial” tasks of maintaining this “sensible duopoly.” Writing in the tradition of E.H. Carr, Robert Cox has noted (1986:248) that neorealism “appears ideologically to be a science at the service of big-power management of the international system.” Cox sees an “unmistakably Panglossian quality” to Waltz’s defense of bipolarity, noting that “the historical moment has left its indelible mark upon this purportedly universalist science.” Second, Waltz’s method prevents him from exploring the origins and underpinnings of anarchy, actual state calculations about their power positions visà-vis other members of the system, and what it is, exactly, that states do. Although he is content to do so, Waltz can merely describe the mechanics of the system itself. There is a kind of modesty here. “Although neorealist theory does not explain why particular wars are fought,” Waltz writes (1988: 44), “it does explain war’s dismal recurrence through the millennia.” He suggests that asking balance-of-power theory
102 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
to explain specific policies of states is like expecting the law of gravity to predict the “wayward path of a falling leaf” (Waltz 1979:121). In this respect, Justin Rosenberg (1994:27) suggests that Waltz isolates only a permissive cause, as opposed to any efficient causes, of war. Neorealism is “a contradiction of perpetual peace rather than a theory of international politics.” If neorealist theory has a deterministic ring to it, Waltz insists that this is not the case. Indeed, when challenged on this, he relaxed his stance somewhat, claiming only that “structure shapes and shoves the units of a system” (Waltz 1986:336). Still, perhaps more than most classical realists, Waltz is of the “recurrence and repetition” school of international thought. In this, neorealist theory is nothing if not a philosophy of history. Waltz (1979:66) notes: The texture of international politics remains highly constant, patterns recur and events repeat themselves endlessly. The relations that prevail internationally seldom shift rapidly in type or in quality. They are marked instead with dismaying persistence, a persistence that one must expect so long as none of the competing units is able to convert the anarchic international realm into a hierarchic one. The enduring anarchic character of international politics accounts for the striking sameness in the quality of international life through the millennia. Historical critiques The nub of historical objections to neorealist theory and research is that an exclusive focus on structure and on the “striking sameness” of inter-state behavior shrouds crucial historical distinctions and leaves little room for explaining or understanding even large-scale change. Waltz simply notes (1986: 341) the constancy of balance of power politics “as practiced over the millennia, from ancient China and India, to the Greek and Italian city states, and unto our own day.” The assumption of anarchy Recall that the neorealism begins with anarchy as an inventive ordering principle. At some point, however, the idea of structure is taken to represent structure in fact. Declaring that the world has never been hierarchically governed, neorealists do not delve into the particulars. The system is assumed to exist in the form Waltz proposes (see Buzan et al. 1993:182–6). This either-or attitude parallels earlier realist notions that the makeup of the international system could only be either state pluralism or a world state. Barry Buzan and Richard Little (1994) take up the question of international system via a long view of history that extends beyond Europe and the Westphalian centuries. This critique of neorealism is rooted in the English School tradition associated with Wight, Bull, Butterfield, John Vincent, Michael Howard, Adam Watson, and other members of the British Committee for the Theory of
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 103
International Politics. Instead of accepting structure as an atemporal framework of analysis, the idea is to consider what ‘international system’ means in a more historically patient and probing way. Buzan and Little (ibid.: 231) suggest that even the most abstract of international relations theories are eurocentric, and thus are “skewed by the historically unrepresentative, and rather brief, record of events in one corner of the planet.” They point to what they term the “anarchophila” of realism, especially structural realism. This is the “disposition to assume that the structure of the international system has always been anarchic, that this is natural, and (more selectively) that this is a good thing” (ibid.: 236). The approach unleashes a number of questions glossed over in Waltz: How big does a system have to be? Is a system composed solely of military-political interactions? Can culture or economics engender systems? Do all international systems have structural effects, i.e., do systems always shape behavior among its “units”? Indeed, when Waltz evokes “ancient China and India,” and the “Greek and Italian city states,” as evidence of the cross-cultural and timeless nature of anarchy, he is reciting a standard realist litany of historical international systems. It may be that the field’s anarchists favor these periods precisely because they represent some of the “few historical times and places that resemble the international anarchy of modern Europe” (ibid.: 234). One also wonders if these periods do not leap to mind because they form the historical backdrop to the usual suspects in realism’s multicultural pantheon: Sun Tzu, Kautilya, Thucydides, and Machiavelli, respectively. A longer and wider historical survey suggests that Waltz and other anarchy-based systems theorists are narrowly informed. The kind of global structure that Waltz proposes, with politicomilitary systemic effects, has been in existence for about the past 500 years. Before that—and arguably “unto our own day”—systems somewhere between anarchy and hierarchy appear to have been the norm. Buzan and Little (ibid.: 249) suggest that almost nowhere (except in the relatively short history of modern Europe) is anarchy persistent. Numerous cases offer reasons to question the neorealist argument that anarchy is self-sustaining: in South Asia, East Asia, the Middle East and the Mediterranean, anarchic systems regularly and repeatedly collapsed into empires or suzerain systems. If one focused on East Asia and the Middle East (rather than on Europe as we mostly do) the question would be why hierarchic systems persist. Adam Watson (1992) elaborates on this broader range of “ordering principles.” His survey extends from the first stirrings of the Sumerian system 5000 years ago (as inferred from cuneiform tablets) to the contemporary scene. He posits a spectrum of international orders, stretching from anarchy at one extreme, through hegemony, suzerainty, and dominion, to empire at the other (see also Mann 1986). For Watson, absolute independence (sovereignanarchy) as well as absolute empire are theoretical extremes that do not exist in practice. Yale Ferguson and Richard Mansbach (1995) have offered an equally rich view of non-Westphalian polities which encompasses
104 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
a vast assortment of other (often divided or crosscutting) political identities and loyalties. They contend that statist language and theory create a false sense of continuity in the international system. This tendency to regard Westphalian polities as timeless also underpins statist ideology, “reinforcing the institution it purports to describe and explain” (ibid.: 24). For now, let us set aside the broader criticism of the assumption of anarchy on grounds of interdependence and international society. A critique of the billiard ball model of realism will be advanced in the concluding chapter of this book. Do states act alike? “If there is any distinctly political theory of international politics, balanceof-power theory is it” (Waltz 1979:117). Consonant with his philosophy of science, Waltz exhibits little interest in the underlying history and process by which the balance of power happens. Balancing is an automatic response to changes in the contours of systemic power. Wendt argues (1987) that the neorealist conception of structure fails to explain political conduct, because it fails to develop any linkage with human agency. It is not simply that neorealism fails to consider agency and process. More important is the assumption that there are sharp limits to historical choice. In this, the theory veils a profound belief about political necessity. It also downgrades the effects of political process, institutions, conceptions of legitimacy, and so on (cf. Howard 1991:188–200). The degree to which political action is structured by the system is almost postmodernist in force. If postmodern politics are imprisoned by the structure of language and knowledge, then neorealist politics are surely imprisoned in the structure of power. This can lead to a facile view of political dynamics. The neorealist John Mearsheimer (1994/1995: 13), for example, breezily observes that “the balance of power is the independent variable which explains war.” Paul Schroeder’s criticisms of balance-of-power theory, discussed in the previous chapter, apply with far greater force here. Interestingly, Schroeder is a “systemic” historian whose analyses focus on the interactions between states and the international system. He writes that Ranke’s Primat der Aussenpolitik (primacy of foreign policy) is obsolete, but that historians must nevertheless continue to interpret international affairs in terms of its own dynamics and norms, “not as a dependent variable of any other systems or structures in society” (Schroeder 1994b:ix). As we have seen, Schroeder’s system is mildly “institutional.” He describes an international order in which the use of force is regulated by conventional norms of political conduct and association. He also suggests that what international politics have meant in practice has always been bound up in the ideology of the practitioner and the context of his times. In this sense, statecraft is not simply shaped by one’s relative power position; rather, statesmen play a role in creating and changing the system in which they operate. Thus, while the Congress of Vienna is often hailed as a restoration of the European balance in the wake of the Napoleonic Wars, Schroeder contends—as against the “sameness” principle of neorealism—that the Congress transformed the European system. A “competitive
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 105
balance-of-power struggle,” he writes, gave way to a system founded on “benign shared hegemony and the mutual recognition of rights underpinned by law” (ibid.: 580). We also suggested in the previous chapter that states, especially weak ones, do not necessarily “balance” against power or threats, but exhibit a range of responses including denial, isolation, embracing the threatening state in a restraining alliance, diplomatic settlements, and bandwagoning with aggressors. Schroeder points to the diverse strategies that states adopted in response to Austrian Emperor Joseph II’s 1785 attempt to “exchange” the Austrian Netherlands (Belgium) for Bavaria, a swap, which, if successful, would have heightened and centralized Austrian power and thus threaten the German equilibrium. Schroeder notes that “the balance” at stake was not simply a material one existing between the great Austrian and Prussian powers. He suggests that “the balance” referred also to the virtues represented by the Reich constitution, which provided for certain liberties within Germany’s many states. (This, he notes, “is another indication of the ways in which a purely powerpolitical view of international politics is too crude to capture vital elements of the process.”) Many “units” hid from the Austrian threat, ignored the issue, or remained neutral, even while acknowledging that Austria’s triumph would likely harm their interests. Some states—Prussia and Hanover—did balance. Others began by hiding out, then bandwagoned with the winning Prussian side. Still others tried to transcend the threat, banding together in an attempt to revive and reform the institutions of the Reich as a means of guaranteeing territorial rights and arbitrating future disputes (Schroeder 1994a: 118–19). Schroeder contends that this type of scenario, in which different states perceive and respond to the same threat in different ways, recurred in almost all the major crises of the Westphalian era (the Napoleonic wars and the Second World War were discussed in the previous chapter). He writes that neorealist theory “not only prevents scholars from seeing and explaining the various strategies alternative to balancing, or the different functions and roles of various actors within the system, but even blocks a genuine historical understanding of balancing conduct and the balance of power itself as a historical variable, changing over time, conditioned by historical circumstances, and freighted with ideological assumptions” (ibid.: 148). As for the assertion that self-help and the security imperative preclude any international division of labor, Schroeder points out that states have frequently taken on different functions within international systems. Waltz’s contention that “the domestic imperative is ‘specialize!’” while “the international imperative is ‘take care of yourself!’” is over-simple. In the nineteenth century, for example, functional cooperation was the norm. Britain claimed a special role as holder of the European balance, Russia saw itself as guardian of the monarchical order, Switzerland acted to keep the passes between Germany and Italy out of any single great power’s control, Denmark and Sweden guarded the entrance to the Baltic, the Ottomans blocked hegemony over the Turkish straits. Schroeder argues that specialization was in fact a sound state strategy, and that a failure to specialize might be punished. He also argues that it would be wrong to see these roles as reducible to their impact
106 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
on security and the balance of power (ibid.: 124–7). One could also say that this was not the system forcing compliance on the units so much as it was the units working “inside-out” to keep the system afloat. Schroeder concedes on this and other issues that history offers no “ironclad” retort to neorealism. Still, the neorealist framework almost certainly forces misexpla-nations upon the evidence. Schroeder concludes that neorealism’s assumptions about the “unchanging, repetitive nature of balance-of-power politics and outcomes throughout the ages, may make its theory of international politics simple, parsimonious, and elegant; they also make it, for the historian at least, unhistorical, unusable, and wrong” (ibid.: 129). The problem of change As noted earlier, Waltz’s world is remarkable for its changelessness and its focus on structure at the expense of process. Anarchy, ironically, is an extraordinarily stable social condition. Richard Ashley (1986:290–2) offers what is perhaps the most thoroughgoing critique of the approach on these grounds. He argues that neorealism is silent on four crucial historical dimensions, what he calls the “four p’s: process, practice, power, and politics.” Historical and political process is occluded by a “fixity of theoretical categories” and “pregiven structure.” Practice vanishes as “men and women, statesmen and entrepreneurs, appear as mere supports for the social process that produces their will and the logics by which they serve it.” Each is reduced “to some idealized Homo oeconomicus, able only to carry out, but never to reflect critically on, the limited rational logic that the system demands of them.” Neorealism’s portrayal of power is entirely material, denying the social bases and limits of power. That is, unlike Morgenthau, neorealism fails to see power as a social or psychological relationship. Ashley stresses that “no other position on power could possibly be compatible with neorealism’s atomistic and utilitarian conceptions of international order.” Finally, politics are reduced “to those aspects which lend themselves to interpretation exclusively within a framework of economic action under structural constraints.” Politics becomes “pure technique… strategy is deprived of its artful and performative aspect, becoming instead the mere calculation of instruments of control.” John Ruggie, like Schroeder, contends that functional differentiation does occur among states, and indeed is indispensable in understanding systemic change. Ruggie is thus reluctant to see the character of the units “drop out” of the analysis. He contends that international politics have not been static; anarchy has a history. Unit-level change in the foundations of anarchy has in the past underpinned the transformation of the international system, he insists, pointing to the shifting notions of sovereignty and legitimacy behind the passage from medieval Europe to the modern state system. Because the medieval system reflected “a patchwork of overlapping and incomplete rights of government,” it was a tangle of anarchy and hierarchy. It was also impossible to distinguish the conduct of “international” affairs from domestic ones. These were not unitary, sovereign actors; there was no
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 107
absolute boundary between public territories and private estates. The medieval polity was a “segmental realm,” but its parts were separated from each other by principles that are profoundly different from those of the modern age. It is thus a bald anachronism to force neorealist logic on the period; it is “historically inaccurate, and nonsensical besides.” Shifts in the bases of sovereignty produced the modern state system. To assume that the new principles are now timeless is to deny the motion of history. As Ruggie summarizes, “the problem with Waltz’s posture is that, in any social system, structural change itself ultimately has no source other than unit-level processes. Waltz’s theory of ‘society’ contains only a reproductive, but no transformational logic” (Ruggie 1986:142, 152). One attempt to describe the medieval period in neorealist terms has drawn sharp censure for its portrayal of history. Markus Fischer (1992), employing the neorealist model, reports that the historical record “shows,” “suggests,” and “indicates” that medieval polities were constrained by Europe’s power structure as well as by the norms of Christendom. The implication is that neorealism explains European politics even before the dawn of Westphalia. In response, Rodney Hall and Friedrich Kratochwil (1993:491) argue that Fischer’s thesis rests on precarious historiographic ground—that he has allied himself with historians with “structuralist methodological proclivities” and has studiously avoided unhelpful historiography. The critics suggest that “it should be possible to learn from historical materials by treating the dead fairly or even sympathetically…The credibility of claims of neorealist scholarship to scientific status is not enhanced by arguments that appear to violate explicit injunctions of science against selective use of data.” The ransacking problem is raised, but the exchange, including Fischer’s response (1993), also suggests that international theory is being overworked, especially if its validity rests on specialized debate among historians. Waltz does not deny that international change—albeit glacial—occurs. “Surveying the rise and fall of nations over the centuries,” he notes, “one can only conclude that national rankings change slowly. War aside, the economic and other bases of power change little more rapidly in one major nation than they do in another” (Waltz 1979:177). Furthermore, “The death rate among states is remarkably low.” “Who is likely to be around 100 years from now -the United States, the Soviet Union, France, Egypt, Thailand, and Uganda? Or Ford, IBM, Shell, Unilever, and Massey-Ferguson?” (ibid.: 95). Waltz’s conception of what is changing—namely national power capabilities—is striking because it is so sharply circumscribed. Neorealism appears incapable of envisaging any outcome that transcends the calculus of power and control. One is tempted to say that this is not historical change. The advent of nuclear weapons, the rise of capitalism, the Enlightenment, the Islamic conquest of Africa, the spread of Confucian teachings—these varieties of history are homogenized in a sea of structure. Outside of their connection to power they are merely ideas, technologies, and social forces with no specific bearing on the international system. Then, of course, there is the end of the cold war. If neorealism’s stock prospered alongside the grand strategic thinking and arms racing of the 1980s, it plummeted
108 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
(or should have) when the cold war ended and the international system changed differently and more rapidly than structuralists had anticipated. This was, after all, precisely the sort of tectonic upheaval one would expect the theory to explain or predict. Waltz (1993:50) has since offered a quasi-structuralist reading of events: “The political and economic reconstruction attempted by the Soviet Union followed in part from external causes… Economic reorganization, and the reduction of imperial burdens, became an externally imposed necessity, which in turn required internal reforms.” The fact remains that the Soviet Union crumbled, and bipolarity ended with virtually no change in Soviet military capabilities. Nor did the superpower standoff end in the sort of hegemonic war prophesied by many neorealists. The whole affair, rooted in less than systemic factors, seriously undermined the approach (see Everts 1992). Gaddis argues that fixity on structure blinded neorealists to this possibility: Structuralists see time as a scale against which to measure events, but they pay little attention to the fact that the passage of time, in and of itself, also shapes events. In this respect, they resemble those pre-Darwinian paleontologists who believed in the immutability of species: despite being surrounded by evidence showing that animals, plants, and even land forms had evolved over time, these scientists simply assumed the absence or the unimportance of evolution and therefore lacked the means to understand, account for, and anticipate structural change. (Gaddis 1992/1993:38) Through the looking glass: Stephen Walt’s Revolution and War In some ways, Waltz anticipated Gaddis’s criticism. Waltz conceded that theory was an “image” or “idea” through which historical evidence is filtered. “Knowledge, it seems, must precede theory, and yet knowledge can precede only from theory” (Waltz 1979:8).6 This paradox is unavoidable in any research. Waltz’s skepticism is aimed largely at historical inductivists who believe that theory will materialize at the end of their inquiry. Nevertheless, its implications are no less profound for deductive theory and scientific research projects. Indeed, because the problem arises when preconceptions precede observation, an inductivist might be less disposed to interpret things in a particular way. How has this problem affected actual research within the neorealist program? This section considers a prominent current example of neorealist inquiry, Stephen M. Walt’s Revolution and War (1996). Revolution and War has been the subject of a journal symposium and conference roundtables. One reviewer notes that the book represents “one more piece of evidence that [neo]realism remains a rich and vibrant research tradition despite recurrent claims to the contrary” (Desch 1997:126). Walt’s central contribution to the field is to emphasize how perceptions about power affect state behavior. This is not a new idea, but it is helpful inasmuch as it has enriched
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 109
the neorealist framework of material capabilities. In Origins of Alliances (1987), Walt proposed that states balance not only against power, but also against threats. He carries this idea forward in Revolution and War. Whether or not this is the sort of “patched-up adjustment” of neorealism that Lakatos criticized in deductive social science, Walt’s threat-based approach is a signal example of second-generation neorealist theory and research. If the approach appears to have more in common with Robert Jervis’s classic Perception and Misperception in International Politics (1976) than with Theory of International Politics, it should be noted that Walt’s language, assumptions, belief in deductive science, as well as his view of the international realm as composed of rational, unitary, self-seeking states whose motivations are reducible to security interests, are all firmly in the neorealist tradition. Revolution and War examines the international impact of revolutions. The book pursues an explicitly systemic approach. “Decisions to go to war are not made in a vacuum. War is ultimately a response to problems that arise between two or more states. Understanding revolution and war thus requires an international-political perspective: instead of focusing primarily on the revolutionary state itself, we should consider how revolutions will affect the relationship between the state and the other members of the system” (p. 12). He contends that revolutions are watershed events in the international system, causing sudden shifts in the balance of power, altering patterns of international alignments, casting doubt on existing agreements and diplomatic norms, and enticing other states to try to improve their own geopolitical positions. Foreign aggressors may exploit the national upheaval that attends revolutions. Later, when the revolution has been solidified, its leaders may enter a heady period during which they attempt to export the revolution. Revolutionary states and foreign powers often exaggerate each other’s hostile intentions, and conflict ensues. All of these concerns, Walt argues, are mediated by state (elite) perceptions. Setting out to rectify a number of “folk theories” about revolution and war, Walt theorizes that revolutions intensify security competition and increase the probability of war by altering each side’s perceptions of the balance of threats. In addition to affecting the balance of power, a revolution also fosters malign perceptions of intent and a perverse combination of insecurity and overconfidence, based primarily on the possibility that revolution will spread to other countries. Although war does not occur in every case, strong pressures for war are always present and, invariably, the level of security competition increases significantly. (p. viii) Revolution and War suggests several intriguing dynamics that underpin this “security competition.” What Walt terms “spirals of suspicion” mount as threats and insecurities are exaggerated on both sides. Revolutionaries resort to bombastic language, stress historic wrongs in inter-state relations, and interpret other states’ reactions in the worst possible light. If status quo powers respond in kind, even mild diplomatic disputes are likely to escalate. When either revolutionary or
110 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
reactionary fervor is linked to a belief that one holds an offensive advantage, conflict becomes even more probable. Walt’s interest in perceptions yields a further observation: good information is scarce during revolutionary periods. Normal channels of inter-state communications collapse at precisely the moment when they are most needed. Diplomats are withdrawn, intelligence networks are curtailed, scholarly exchanges are suspended, and media freedoms are circumscribed. All the while, nefarious accounts of revolutionary intentions are sown abroad by counterrevolutionary émigrés. Walt carries forward the theory-hypothesis-testing method. He compares “processtracing” case studies, precisely the sort of analysis so lacking in Waltz’s approach. Looking at revolutions in France (1789), Russia (1917), Iran (1979), China (1949), America (1776), Turkey (1921), and Mexico (1910), Walt effectively bridges levels of analysis and strikes a good balance between economy of explanation and historical content, making extensive use of historical evidence and interpretation. Walt considers his theory “supported” if the mechanisms described above were present, even if war did not result. Wars did follow close on the heels of the French, Russian, Iranian, and Chinese revolutions. Walt argues that war did not result in the other cases because leaders decided that the costs outweighed the benefits of conflict. He suggests that these decisions were gauged according to perceptions about the offense—defense balance and beliefs about whether or not the revolutions might be exported. Interestingly, Walt is trying to make an elite preferences argument, yet he has difficulty discerning elite preferences. He relies on an oftenepigrammatic method that highlights “state” perceptions as expressed in the public pronouncements of Lenin, Trotsky, Mao, Khomeini, and others. Walt has little trouble finding historical examples to demonstrate his main ideas. His thesis, after all, is not that revolutions cause war, but only that they heighten security competition in the system. This stance allows Walt to gainsay historians’ suggestions that wars were on the horizon whether or not they were propelled by revolution (p. 118). His historiographic focus does appear to be largely governed by the degree of theoretical fit. He devotes eighty pages each to the French and Russian revolutions, and sixty pages to the Iranian case. The American, Mexican, Turkish, and Chinese revolutions, where the thesis seems to apply in only the most general way, if at all, are canvassed in a single chapter. The international impact of the French Revolution, his first case study, seems to provide a kind of template by which to view the other revolutionary periods. The French Revolution is probably so deeply ingrained in our thinking that this is unavoidable. Walt contends that his cases show how “revolutions have independent causal effects on the level of security competition and the probability of war” (p. 333). However, it seems difficult to separate these effects, as Walt claims to have done, from other sources of conflict. Walt points, for example, to Poland’s invasion of Russia in 1920 as evidence that the 1917 revolution had created an inviting vacuum. However, it seems equally plausible that the systemic upheavals of the First World War, rather than the Russian Revolution, “caused” Poland to take the offensive.
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 111
At other turns, Walt seems to fit the evidence to his theory. In keeping with his hypotheses, he describes the Soviets’ “highly paranoid view of world politics” as a generic revolutionary trait (p. 203). Kennan, as we have seen, suggested that this paranoia had much deeper roots. The Chinese Revolution no doubt indirectly affected the outbreak of the Korean War, but the case fits a number of other theoretical scenarios as well (p. 323). Newly available archival materials suggest that Stalin had more influence over North Korea than did Mao (see Foot 1996:473–82). The Turkish case seems to be a particularly poor fit, leading Walt to judge that its “familiar dynamics or revolutionary situations” took on “a muted and less dangerous form” (p. 310). Whether this was a revolution at all remains a point of lively debate. At the time, the outline of “Turkey” (as mapped at the Treaty of Sevères) was in dispute. The “liberation” movement drove the occupation forces from Anatolia and Thrace, before leading an extraordinarily successful (and often heavy-handed) program of modernization and westernization. This consensus was slow to emerge, however. Initially, the movement was a hydra-head of diverse elites, ranging from Kemalists espousing a kind of Anatolian nationalism, other nationalists who harked back to the French Revolution, the Turanists, who envisioned a Pan-Turkic state stretching across Central Asia to China, and a strong retinue of Ottoman military officers and civil servants who intended to reestablish the Caliphate and rebuild the empire. Again, the Turkish case seems to have been more a question of perceptions and misperceptions than of objective assessments of international threats, if any. The European powers appear to have imposed their own “orientalist” interpretations on events, which is particularly ironic given Atatürk’s eventual orientation of Turkey toward Western manners and mores. Ultimately, the revolution probably enhanced Turkish relations with Europe far more than it undermined them. The international effects of the Iranian Revolution best buttress Walt’s thesis. The Iranian case highlights Walt’s vast improvement over Waltz’s analysis: material capabilities alone could never do justice to the meaning of revolutionary Iran. Ayatollah Khomeini certainly provided abundant provocative “foreign policy” pronouncements. On one occasion Khomeini stated, “we have in reality, then, no choice but to…overthrow all treacherous, corrupt, oppressive, and criminal regimes” (p. 210). On another, “it is only through the active, intentional pursuit of martyrdom that unjust rulers can be toppled” (p. 215). The bounty on Salman Rushdie’s head was also unambiguous. The Iran—Iraq War was almost certainly sparked by Baathist fears that the revolution might spread. Still, it seems problematic to squeeze the Islamic theocracy into a self-help unit, treating it as just another revolutionary state. The possibility also exists that Khomeini’s threats were manufactured in order to cement his hold on power—though admittedly this would not assuage perceptions abroad. V.S.Naipaul has argued recently (1997) that to think of the Iranian stance toward the West in terms of rational “foreign policy goals” is to misjudge a cynical system of domestic control. Revolutions heighten uncertainties, and create power vacuums and geopolitical opportunities. They may have profound impacts on both security and economic
112 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM
interests. Besides posing this insight in a fashion acceptable to political scientists, one wonders about the originality and profundity of Walt’s contribution. More importantly, Walt’s approach leaves whole realms of questions unasked. His inquiry remains encased in neorealist assumptions about the nature of international politics. The real filtering lies in the idea that states seek security above all else. Explanations are couched exclusively in terms of capabilities, threats, and power vacuums. The “selfhelp” assumption sustains the validity of the comparison. Otherwise, changes in international context and norms would cast doubt on comparisons of the international reaction to, say, the American and Iranian revolutions. The assumption is that states will go to war when these conditions are present. What might inhibit this outcome? How might international institutions mitigate the uncertainties that put states on edge in revolutionary times? What role could third parties play? Can revolutions enhance concord between states? In several of Walt’s cases, war did not follow revolution, and these questions remain unanswered because they are unasked. Conclusion: politics without process Waltz notes that “the more complex and intricate the matters being studied are, the stronger the urge ‘to be simple-minded’” (Waltz 1990:27). In political analysis, parsimony may be a dubious virtue. Being simple-minded closes off other ways of understanding, abbreviates inquiry, and undercuts progress in the field. It may also veil a complacent historical epistemology. As Kratochwil (1993:64) has noted, a “Platonist preconception” with form has dominated structural theory. “The search for invariable laws of international politics has not only significantly reduced the number of interesting questions, it has also led to premature closure… The unchanging or cyclical nature of international politics is substituted for the investigation of actual processes and decisions.” Besides affirming that power politics are here to stay (and that arsenals should remain well stocked), Waltz offers no counsel to the prince. Indeed, having toiled so long to isolate a theory of international politics, Waltz closely guards his achievement. No one has argued more consistently than he that neorealism is not, and was never intended to be, a theory of foreign policy (Waltz 1996). Meanwhile, neorealist claims about structural effects have grown so extensive as to very nearly render the theory unassailable to historical challenges, i.e., unfalsifiable (Elman et al. 1995:194). Ironically, this is exactly what neorealists used to say of classical realism. Other visions of the international system open up realms of inquiry rather than close them off. It is worth pointing out in this regard that, while neorealists revere Thucydides for explaining the Peloponnesian War in terms of economics, they are often guilty of a reductionist view of the Athenian’s great History, which is shaded by far more than relative numbers of spiked shields, hoplites, and archers. Thucydides was intrigued as well by the “spirit” of the Athenians, by different forms of power, the psychology of clashing cultures and economies, open versus closed societies, innovation versus resistance to change, self-reliance versus international
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 113
commerce, constitutions and law, the role of rhetoric, the dislocations of social and economic upheaval. Thucydides also grasped the moral tragedy of war. Waltz notes that international affairs are conducted “in the brooding shadow of violence,” but the ethical implications of anarchy are left unexamined (Waltz 1979:102). Discourse on international ethics generally revolves around the tension between political necessity and moral demand, with ethical choices either derived from “rules” or based on calculations of expected consequences. In neorealism, such questions are deemed “unscientific” or “metaphysical,” in any case, beyond the pale of theoretical discourse. A foreign policy based on the third-image, says Waltz, “is neither moral nor immoral, but embodies merely a reasoned response to the world around us” (Waltz 1959a:238). Neorealists seem convinced that states, much less individuals, are powerLess to alter the system in which they find themselves. If structural theory does not actively sanction existing structures, it at least fuels a certain fatalism about change. This itself is an ethical stance. As one critic notes of the “science” of international relations: “The subject is unavoidably normative. It is not that normative concerns ought to be addressed, rather that they have always been at the centre of the subject. Lying at the heart of value-neutrality was a very powerful normative project, one every bit as ‘political’ or ‘biased’ as those approaches marginalised and delegitimised in the name of science” (Smith 1992:490). Wedded to structure and sameness, neorealism restrains rather than inspires meliorist hopes. Diplomats may conclude that ethics no longer matter.
114
6 “THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” J.David Singer and the Correlates of War
The use of history in international relations reaches its methodological zenith in the quantitative approach. While neorealism pursues scientific rigor by way of deductive theory and empirical falsification, quantitative political science employs the full arsenal of computer and statistical methods in heavily inductive fashion. Quantitative researchers believe that their methods remedy many of the historical problems recounted in the preceding chapters: selection bias, interpretive prejudice, theoretical filtering, anecdotalism, and ahistoricism. “The historian can continue to pile up facts and do his case studies but only as he borrows from the social sciences can he produce hard evidence or compelling interpretations of the past,” argues J.David Singer, founder and director of the Correlates of War project at the University of Michigan Center for Research on Conflict Resolution. Failing this scientific rigor, “our understanding of the past will remain in the hands of the literati, responding to one revisionist or counter-revisionist interpretation after another, as the consensus ebbs and flows” (Singer 1969:82).1 Begun in 1963, the Correlates of War (COW) is today the premier behavioral research program in international politics. Heralding a true science of international relations, the project held out reproducible, long-term historical study in place of the “intuition,” “folklore,” and “armchair theorizing” that have marked “several centuries of pre-operational speculation” and “wisdom literature” about the causes of war (Singer 1981:1). A succession of researchers has compiled a statistical database for major wars, alliances, civil conflicts, and systemic attributes from 1816 to 1992. (COW data sets include Singer and Small 1972, Small and Singer 1982, and Singer and Small 1994a, 1994b.) Analysts continue to digest historical accounts, and work based on COW data is ongoing around the globe. (The latest bibliography of COWbased research is Diehl 1992.) Pursuing a diverse agenda of data-making, index construction, statistical manipulation, and theoretical modeling, the project’s contribution has come in the form of fragmentary findings and as the result of its more narrowly posed hypotheses. As yet, there has been no major breakthrough in the study of war (see Vasquez 1987).2 Quantitative work is the most scientific approach to international relations in that its historical sample extends far beyond the cases cited anecdotally or analogically in traditional work, and its statistical analyses are, in themselves, objective and reproducible. Nevertheless, it is also the most historical approach in
116 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
that its findings and prescriptions hinge entirely on “coded” historiography. As Donald Puchala (1990:64) has noted, “behaviorists were not ignoring history. They were coding it!” Indeed, the COW has done extraordinarily heavy historical lifting, in terms of both numbers of hours and history books, far outpacing any other research project in the field. Nevertheless, historical appraisals of the COW, and of quantitative international relations generally, have typically amounted to blanket pronouncements on social science methods, and have ignored the cliometrics debate among historians. This chapter first places quantitative international relations in the context of social science history, before exploring the COW as a case of behavioral science. It then addresses problems of “data-making,” the procedure by which narrative history is transformed into statistical indicators, and attempts to replicate a randomly selected sample of COW historical data. The chapter moves on to address the “quantitative fallacy,” before, finally, assessing the COW and other quantitative work from the perspective of historical skepticism. History by the numbers The strength of quantitative history, or cliometrics as it is also known, is that it offers a method of systematic, comparative historical research buttressed by clear standards of evidence. Figures take the place of “feel,” variables are defined and delimited, operations are precisely described. Once a data set has been prepared, it can be subjected to any number of statistical tests. Perhaps the most common application is the “large n” analysis of “aggregate” data, meaning that historical hypotheses are put simultaneously to many cases, usually with the help of a computer. The hope is that such “longitudinal” or “time-series” analyses may reveal patterns and associations which had been not simply undiscovered, but were undiscoverable using traditional methods. Is it possible to extend quantitative methods to international history? Is this a worthwhile strategy for exploring the causes or correlates of war? Does the quantitative historian, as one critic suggested, “borrow the vices of other disciplines and surrender the virtues of his own”? (Fischer 1970:37). Because the traditional— quantitative argument in politics is paralleled so closely in the debate over historical methods, a brief review of what has happened in Clio’s domain is in order. Cliometrics was born the twin of l’histoire annaliste, the “bottom—up,” socioeconomic history invented by Marc Bloch and Lucien Febvre of the Annales school in the 1920s.3 The annalistes denounced “event-centered,” “political” history as superficial and elitist. Far more important was the history of everyday life (la vie quotidienne) which, when studied over the long term, would reveal the “geologic” contours underlying societies and economies. These were historical problems that required quantitative inquiry: tariffs, divorces, the growth of industry, patterns of trade and extraction, exchange rates, crop yields, literacy rates, caloric intake, and so on. The method was urged on other historical genres as well. Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie’s insistence that “history that is not quantifiable cannot claim to be scientific” was a slap at narrativists, but also undercut traditional nomothetic
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 117
practitioners who believed that their work, while not quantitative, was nevertheless scientific (see Jarausch 1985: 14). Georges Lefebvre, the great historian of the French Revolution, coined what would become the password for a generation of quantitative historians: “Il faut compter” (quoted in Thomas 1966:275). The admonition to count got a rocky reception. Arthur Schlesinger, Jr. (1962: 770) noted in 1962 that “almost all important questions are important precisely because they are not susceptible to quantitative answers.” In his presidential address to the American Historical Association that same year, Carl Bridenbaugh (1963:325– 6) inveighed against “scientific” approaches to history, which he saw as “culturally impoverished” and revealing “little if any historical sense.” He announced, “The finest historians will not be those who succumb to the dehumanizing methods of social sciences… Nor will the historian worship at the shrine of that Bitch-goddess, QUANTIFICATION.” Nevertheless, the method spread in popularity in the 1960s and profited from computing advances in the 1970s. In 1966, the TLS published a famous series, “New Ways in History,” pitching cliometrics’ statistical methods and socioeconomic content. The lead piece noted that it “seemed certain that the computer will replace the ‘stout boots’ worn by the advanced historians of the past generation,” and that econometrics especially offered “definitive solutions” to historical debates (Thomas 1966:276). Another contributor added that cliometrics had liberated history from the “tyranny of literature” by making intelligible a cache of new sources (Weaver 1966). Elsewhere, François Furet (1971:160) saw cliometrics not merely as “a transformation of the raw material of history,” but as representing “a revolution in historiographical consciousness.” Lee Benson (1966:12–13) hailed a “genuinely scientific historiography,” and held out the possibility of discovering or developing general laws of human behavior. Sophisticated mathematics and models soon meant that narrativist historians did not know what their behavioralist brethren were up to. Two cultures emerged, one qualitative and “humanistic,” the other quantitative and claiming the mantle of science. For some historians, the idea that their craft might be enriched by the social sciences implied a certain shoddiness or inadequacy in traditional work. Traditional historians also felt coerced to accept historical assertions grounded in thousands of hours of research and the latest statistical technologies. For many, the only options were to accept quantitative findings uncritically, or, more likely, simply ignore them. The divide deepened as historians took sides in several high profile cases, most prominently the publication of Robert Fogel and Stanley Engerman’s Time on the Cross: The Economics of American Negro Slavery (1974). Based on data on 80,000 slaves drawn from probate and census records from fifty-four counties in eight Southern states between 1775 and 1865, the book’s authors argued that slavery was a relatively mild form of industrial organization, that slave families rarely were rent apart, that slaves adhered more or less to a Protestant work ethic, and that however ethically abominable slavery was, economically it was a rational strategy. Fogel and Engerman claimed to have demolished a century’s worth of slavery historiography, yet a series of hostile reviews, many written by economists
118 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
and statisticians, suggested that their strong conclusions rested on indefensible interpretation of sources and defective manipulation of data (see Handlin 1979:206– 6). Unfortunately for the behavioral camp, Time on the Cross had securely hitched its claims to the quantitative method. The episode was seen to vindicate the skeptics, lending credence to Mark Twain’s aphorism about “lies, damned lies, and statistics.” Historians were most alarmed, however, that evangelical cliometrics would erode the humanistic and literary foundations of the discipline. In its utopian stage, quantification held out a computerized version of Acton’s pledge of a “Rankean” historical science of “completeness and certainty.” Quantitative claims have since receded. Revisiting the new history in the TLS in 1975, Elie Kedourie (1975:238– 40) cooled to the approach, calling quantitative “scientism” a “paradoxical, not to say impossible, quest,” and urging historians to abandon the “dizzying heights of method” for the more solid ground of resourceful and imaginative description. Theodore Rabb, a founder of The Journal of Interdisciplinary History, noted in 1981 that “The great hopes of the early days of the computer have apparently been disappointed; now there is a more limited role for those who wish to count” (Rabb 1981:322). Still, despite what Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie (1977:136) called the “futile banishment proceedings” taken against it, a modest cliometrics is ensconced in the canons of historiography. It is important to recall, however, that although methods have progressed from IBM keypunch technology to a cornucopia of software packages, quantification does not replace the historian’s interpretive and logical skills. The method may lend a keener edge to research and causal claims than those based on narrative, but quantitative findings rely nonetheless on the accuracy of the data employed. In any case, today’s “new” historians are not limited to numbers. “Bottom—up” history is now being applied to cultural “mentalities,” material and popular culture, intellectual and labor history, and historical sociology in the manner of Charles Tilly. Through all of this, only the most tenuous link has existed between cliometrics and diplomatic history. Happily, the construction of diplomatic history has evolved over the years from “dry-as-dust” monographs summarizing official communiques toward a richer interpretive practice, tracking inter national trade, technology transfers, political economy, environmental issues, institutional roles and bureaucratic politics, as well as providing new takes on traditional areas of power and statecraft. (Many practitioners now prefer the more inclusive term, “international history.”) Rarely, though, has diplomatic history taken the form of straight quantitative work. Charles Maier notes (in a survey of diplomatic history that sparked a raft of rebuttals), that “Rankean exegesis still forms the basis of the craft,” suggesting that “history from the bottom up takes its toll in a field of human activity that is still largely executed, if not ultimately shaped, from the top down” (Maier 1980: 356–7). This may be why the many historians who favor social science methods rarely attempt diplomatic history. The Journal of Interdisciplinary History, Comparative Studies in Society and History, Journal of Social History, Social Science History, and
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 119
Historical Methods are all venues for longitudinal studies seeking greater comparative content and broader generalizations than found in traditional outlets. Yet, over the past 10 years these journals combined have published no articles based on “operationalized” diplomatic historiography. Meanwhile, Diplomatic History, Revue d’histoire diplomatique, The International History Review, and Diplomacy and Statecraft have hewed to traditional methods. Singer and long-time COW historian-inresidence Melvin Small organized a diplomatic history section of the Social Science History Association, but the group disbanded a few years later for lack of conference papers (Small 1990:21 n. 1). The hope, voiced by Ole Holsti and Robert North (1965:155), was that “modern social science methods coupled with the use of computers may transform history into something approaching a laboratory of international behavior.” Today, however, virtually no one is doing quantitative diplomatic history on the history side; the initiative for cliometric work in international politics rests almost entirely with political scientists. The COW as behavioral science: “systematic, visible, explicit, and reproducible” (Jones and Singer 1972:20) The COW has been the source of scores of articles and several books addressing a wide range of empirical questions on war. Among the COWs own basic findings (some of which are hotly contested among COW “users”), are the following: • There were 209 international wars between 1816 and 1992; • The international arena remains “fundamentally as war-prone as it has been since the Congress of Vienna,” although war is perhaps becoming less frequent but more lethal (Small and Singer 1979:80). Of the 177 years under study, some kind of international war was underway every year except 1908; • European states were the most bellicose. Since the Congress of Vienna the most frequently warring nations were: Britain (52 wars), France (44), Turkey (27), Russia/Soviet Union (25), China (17), and Italy (15); • States won 65 percent of the wars they initiated; they lost 28 percent of them; • Wars do not appear to begin with any cyclical regularity. Peak amounts of war underway, however, show a strong periodicity in the range of 15 to 20 years; • There is a fickle relationship between alliances and security. In the nineteenth century, the greater the number of formal alliances covenanted by states, the less likely was war to occur; in the twentieth century the opposite is true; • Preparing for war rarely ensures peace. Disputes between and among major powers tend to escalate into war if preceded by an arms race; disputes not preceded by an arms race do not; • A “transparent” international system of disparate powers seems to promote peace; findings are mixed on the bipolar/multipolar question, although a “tight” bipolar system is associated with greater amounts of war; and • There is reason to be skeptical of “democratic peace” claims. “States with such governments have not been noticeably peace-prone or unaggressive over our
120 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
historical period…they did become involved in quite a few wars, and not always as defenseless victims of a dictator’s aggression” (Small and Singer 1976:67–8). Geller and Singer (1998:87–8) note that the evidence that democratic dyads are more pacific than non-democratic pairs is “consistent and cumulative,” although there are competing explanations for this phenomenon. Singer’s principal claim is that these and other COW findings are distinguished from mere assertions by virtue of the rigorous, reproducible manner in which they are derived (Singer 1965:75). That is to say, the project’s methodology underpins its epistemology. Singer’s work is a running indictment on these grounds of the tactics employed by traditional researchers. He calls international relations “methodologically, the most retarded segment of one of the most retarded social sciences,” and anticipates a day when the “antiscientific” mentality, “untouched by any post-Ptolemaic tendencies,” will seem as anachronistic in the study of global politics as alchemy or astrology do to today’s natural scientists (Singer 1989:225). Co-investigator and diplomatic historian Melvin Small makes the parallel claim that “Historians of international relations are among the most methodologically conservative of a conservative trade,” clinging to “ways little changed since the time of Thucydides” (Small 1990:29). The idea is that the field’s Luddites have produced volumes of “literary speculation” on the causes of war, but no hard evidence. Funded initially by the Carnegie Corporation and later by a series of grants from the National Science Foundation, and, most recently, the United States Institute of Peace, the COW has sought policy as well as intellectual “payoffs.” Singer has never hesitated to link up the project with a long stream of progressivist, quantitative peace research back to Jean de Bloch’s six-volume work La Guerre Future, published in Paris in 1898, which used a mathematical model to argue that modern firearms and social organization had made war an economic impossibility, to Lewis Richardson’s accounts of “deadly quarrels,” and Pitirim Sorokin’s and Quincy Wright’s studies of war and revolution. Singer has never said that politics can be a pure science. Like “hard” science, though, the COW is ardently nomothetic, or law generating, in its approach to history. “The moment that one goes beyond the telling of a single narrative or the interpretation of a single case, one is into the ‘nomothetic’ mode, and is thus laying the groundwork for cumulative knowledge” (Singer 1990a:142). Singer dismisses the differentia specifica school, suggesting that an “undue preoccupation, yea obsession, with the unique, the discrete, the non-comparable, is what has largely kept history from developing into a cumulative discipline” (Singer 1969:77). “[W] e begin with the assumption that there are indeed regularities in the origins of different types of wars, and that they are discoverable…we assume that those regularities are as relevant to the future as to the past” (Singer 1972a:244). The project has pursued these regularities inductively, waiting agnostically for the data to mount before making theoretical claims. As statistical patterns emerge, the mode of inquiry becomes increasingly theoretical and the search for causal patterns more focused. Singer sees deductive theory as fashioned from “whole cloth”
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 121
and limited in compass, often producing dueling monocausal explanations. With its built-in flexibility and sophisticated computing, the COW is prepared for complexity. Thus, if states go to war based on an elaborate, multi-level logic that changes with the international environment, presumably this can be discovered. As an agnostic, however, Singer should also be prepared for indeterminacy. If states go to war for all sorts of reasons, if there is no clear pattern, that too would be an important discovery. This behavioral road to theory follows a three-fold epistemology: existential, correlational, and explanatory. Existential knowledge. The lion’s share of the COWs work has been devoted to transforming historical narrative and other artifacts into data sets on war (defined as combat between armed forces including at least one member of the international system in which at least 1000 battle deaths occur annually). Because the COW is heavily inductive, this initial marshaling of evidence is critical. Deciding what to study is, of course, a “theoretical” exercise, but the COWs attempt not to sift the historiography for theory-friendly cases seems to have succeeded. As Singer notes, “we set up our coding rules and then examine all the cases which qualify; there is much less of a tendency to ransack history in search of those isolated cases which satisfy one’s theoretical or rhetorical requirements of the moment” (Singer 1969:79). The COW has created a massive trove of statistical evidence. Its data sets, published as The Wages of War (Singer and Small 1972) and Resort to Arms (Small and Singer 1982), are avowedly existential, while the 1994 update is a computer file with minimal text. “All we have done is to generate a particular set of data and then refined and systematized it into a multitude of potentially useful forms,” write Singer and Small (1972:374). The value of the work is more instrumental than intrinsic. The data comprise: identification of all international wars from 1816 to 1992, and the magnitude, severity, and intensity of each; systemic data including amounts of war begun and underway, secular trends, cycles and periodicity, and seasonal distribution in the incidence of war. Data at the national level include the warproneness of nations, and statistics on victory, defeat, and battle deaths. Similar compilations are made for civil wars. Other indicators include, at the national level: industrial capabilities, military preparedness, diplomatic standing, and regime stability. At the “dyadic” level are alliances and other diplomatic ties, shared membership in international organizations, and geographical proximity. In terms of regional and global “ecologies,” the COW has prepared data on the “configurations” formed by alliances and other diplomatic bonds, power polarity, and the distribution of capabilities. Supplementary data touch on trade patterns, demographic history and ethnic composition. The Behavioral Correlates of War (BCOW) tracks 34,000 discrete diplomatic, economic, military, and unofficial “moves” in the midst of some forty-eight international crises. Correlational knowledge. The second level of knowledge builds on the first. The goal is a “correlational coefficient,” a measure of the association between two or more variables, generally between a class of events or occurrences associated with
122 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
war (outcomes) and certain state-level traits or system-level conditions or configurations (predictors). Singer (1990a: 139) is quick to point out that correlation is necessary but not sufficient to establish a cause. He advises social scientists to “forget about (or, at least, sidestep) causality. Almost any social process of interest can occur via so many different and unobservable routes that we would have to make inferential leaps of heroic proportions in order to specify causality.” However, assuming the existential work is sound, quantitatively derived correlations are more reliable than patterns “observed” via narrative. Thus, rigorous statistical techniques permit at least a “modicum of prudently inferred causality” (Singer 1979: 162). Explanatory knowledge. This is the prize. Synonymous with theory (“a reproducible and compelling explanation of a given class of events” (ibid.: 162)), explanatory knowledge illuminates why a correlation holds historically and why it will or will not hold in the future: it has predictive value. “Correlational knowledge can carry us part way,” says Singer, “but until we have built and empirically tested a theory which offers a compelling explanation of the changing as well as the constant associations in the past, we make predictions of less than desirable solidity” (ibid.: 162–3). Arguably, this is the most creative or intuitive aspect of the COW, as the researcher shelves his coding manual and quits the mechanics of correlation in favor of theory. This is also the site of some of the project’s most innovative cliometric work. In what Singer dubs the “controlled historical experiment,” regression analysis is used to “isolate” the effects of individual predictor variables as a way of pinpointing causality. A good analogy is a flight simulator, on which crash investigators experiment with different weather patterns and rudder positions in order to match the flight-data record of an airplane that has crashed. In the COW’s case, a computer acts as the simulator, the historical record holds the blackbox information, and the outbreak of war is the plane crash. As Singer explains: we can experiment with a large number of contending explanations. If we begin with a reasonably extensive and accurate database, we can experiment with differing magnitudes of our key variables. And if we are willing to move back into the referent historical world when we run into dead ends in the simulation, we can achieve a valuable interplay between our deductive and inductive emphases. These and other virtues add up to a method in which we can ultimately—by a systematic trial-and-error procedure—“reproduce” diplomatic history. (ibid.: 165) For Singer this is the surest way to unravel “the almost inevitable system dynamics” underlying 175 years of world politics (ibid.: 162). The researcher not only subjects correlation-inspired hunches to the “hard facts of history” but also jigs multiple variables, i.e., hones personal hypotheses, until a good “fit” emerges. Through this
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 123
sophisticated seesawing between imagination and testing, it is hoped that a consistent body of theory will fall into place. Data-making: doing history or undoing it? “The problem of science in international relations,” Singer writes, “is ultimately the problem of data-making,” of translating historical traces into “operational” language (Singer 1965:78). Because quantitative experiments rise or fall based on the quality of their inputs, explicit coding criteria are imperative to sort through a bewildering array of artifacts and generate good historical data. This is no small task. As Singer notes, “in no social science field is [data-making] any more difficult than in international relations. Even the original gathering of reliable facts is surrounded with the impediments of governmentally imposed secrecy and distortion as well as the diffuseness of such facts in time and space” (ibid.: 69). Each time the COW data set has been published, its creators have disclaimed that they were “painfully aware of the inconsistencies and dissimilarities that made the original datamaking operations a source of such agony and frustration” (Small and Singer 1982:23). Is it history? Can historical narrative or archival materials be “coded” and statistically manipulated without undoing the standards that make it “historical” in the first place? It seems to me that cliometricians are “doing history.” Even if the description of diplomatic events takes statistical form, the broader questions addressed are not so different from those raised by comparatively minded narrativists. These days, certainly, the scholarship of social science historians is widely accepted by their guild peers. Most importantly, cliometrics is a creative process, governed by certain rules of historical construction. As Small (1990:33) describes it, “Much of our data is literally made by converting the buzzing welter of historical traces into analytically useful indicators.” Whatever its “end use,” this is knowledge produced. Is it reliable, valid knowledge? The cliometric refrain about having transcended the foibles of the humanities rests above all on the claim of reproducibility, that hallmark of science where findings are “confirmed” by re-running tests and reproducing results. Repeatedly in quantitative work, we hear that the traditionalist’s personal idiosyncrasies have been squelched. Singer (1990a: 298) suggests that experimenter bias “need not concern those of us who conduct historical experiments.” After all, the major purpose of clear operational procedures is “to minimize or eliminate those pre-investigative biases which make traditional research so unproductive of generalized, high confidence knowledge, and so ephemeral in its scientific effects” (Singer 1972b: 87). Singer even rejects the rubric of “content analysis,” as data-making is sometimes called, on the argument that coders are not analyzing anything, but are merely translating historical information from the narrative to the numerical idiom. For all this talk of reproducibility, however, it is important to recognize that replications of COW findings have centered almost exclusively on the
124 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
“experimental” stage: they target the project’s modeling efforts and computer runs, not the historical data themselves. Reproducing outputs is in any case a modest feat. Outputs should be perfectly reproducible, or nearly so, since they involve plugging a given set of numbers into a well-defined computer operation. Reproducing the data is much harder. Even with the coding manual in hand, it is impossible to know exactly how statistical indices were tabulated in the first place. We cannot re-create the individual and group decisions regarding historical selection, interpretation, and reconciliation taken by COW investigators. Of the history books strewn upon his desk, which does the investigator choose to follow? Is he or she drawn to an elegant account? Does he or she have an eye for a good university press? John Vasquez (1987:115–16) reports that among the COW team there is “constant discussion on [data reliability], only a small portion of which finds its way into print.” What are the project’s principles of historical selection? How does it resolve inconsistencies? The COW bibliography lists, with a handful of exceptions, only those sources finally adopted, not all the materials consulted. If a particular historian’s estimates or interpretations are ultimately discarded, the book does not appear. This practice gives a smoother gloss to data-making and to the data themselves than perhaps was the case (Small and Singer 1982: Appendix A). Also, the more obscure a conflict is, generally the less information we have about it. Conversely, there may be a host of perspectives on prominent wars, necessitating a certain amount of “picking over” the evidence. Thus the COWs details on the Changkufeng War (Japan and the Soviet Union, two weeks in 1938) appear to have been drawn only from Alvin Coox’s Anatomy of a Small War (1977), the BritishZulu War (1879) is represented by one book, Donald Morris’s Washing of the Spears (1965), the Central American War of 1907 (Nicaragua, Honduras, El Salvador) by another, Pedro Zamora Castellanos’s Vida Militar de Centro América (1934), a general account of military affairs on the isthmus published by the Guatemalan Army press. Evidence of the Javanese War (1825–30) rests on E.S.de Klerck’s History of the Netherlands East Indies (1938) and Bernard Vlekke’s Nusantara (1960). Meanwhile eight sources are cited for the First World War, six for the Second World War. The effect is probably unique to history: a paradox of obscurity, where little-treated wars seem historically “settled,” while debates continue to surround major conflicts. The COWs minor coding conveniences add up as well. In tracking alliances, for example, it was decided to code only written undertakings, not de facto or secret ones, and not to code alliances forged during wartime. Treaty obligations are inferred literally from the document, without considering any informal arrangements or other contexts. By a similar legalistic logic, the Russo-Afghan War (1979–1988), for example, is not considered an international war at all, but is subsumed in the Afghan Civil War. COW researchers also routinely construct missing materials through “informal estimates,” mathematical extrapolations, “moving averages,” and graphic “curvefitting” (see Singer 1990a: 121–2). It is also clear when examining the COWs protocols that some figures cannot be tallied with the kind of precision the project advertises. As a rule, the most intractable of these involve battle deaths. Between the fog of war and the fog of
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 125
history, where the numbers are fiddled in war office propaganda, memoirs, state papers, and nationalist historiography, body counts are notoriously hard to pin down. Lewis Richardson complained after “long searches in the pages of literary history,” that such sources were deplorably vague on the subject of casualties. We look for numbers but find instead phrases such as “many fell in battle” or “routed their enemies” or “suffered heavy loss” or “Thus closed the struggle which for seven years had stained the peninsula with blood.” The number killed in one or two outstanding battles may be mentioned, but these melancholy statistics are seldom totaled for the whole war. Military historians…sometimes give precise casualties for their own forces, but only very vague statements about their enemies. (Richardson 1960:9–10) Richardson’s way around this was to use logarithmic scaling of the magnitude of war death instead of absolute numbers. The COW has tried to overcome the problem through more exhaustive research, poring over shelf-loads of histories written in the nineteenth century, adding machine at hand, trying to recapture earlier, presumably more accurate, estimates. That these estimates are more accurate is, it seems fair to say, largely an article of faith. Interestingly, the project claims to have found the vast carnages of the twentieth century more difficult to calculate than earlier wars. Especially troublesome were the First World War, the Second World War, Korea, Vietnam, Iran—Iraq, and the Gulf War, in which it estimates 100,000 Iraqi combatants died. Acknowledging these problems, the COW rates its battle death figures as either “high confidence” or “somewhat lower confidence” estimates. Of the battle deaths listed for the 118 inter-state wars identified in Resort to Arms, twenty-nine are “high confidence” numbers, while eighty-nine merit “somewhat lower confidence” for one or more participant. (No confidence levels accompany battle fatalities for the ninety wars that appear for the first time in the 1994 update.) These qualifications vanish in subsequent calculations, to profound effect. Because war dead is a primary indicator used to construct other indices, “lower confidence” estimates creep into virtually every corner of the data set. The severity of war, for example, is inferred directly from battle deaths. In turn, the intensity of war is calculated by dividing a composite number (nation-months at war, estimated size of pre-war armed forces, estimated total pre-war population) into the total number of fatalities. These carnage figures are then used to calculate “annual amounts of war underway,” from which a series of systems-level secular, cyclical, and periodic trends are derived. These same fatality figures are incorporated into a basket of state-level patterns including warproneness, win-loss—battle death ratios, initiator—battle death ratios, and national performance in war.
126 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Is the Correlates of War “realist”? These are difficult numbers compounded in derivative indicators. Broad, theoretical biases accumulate as well. Even in inductive work, data-making cannot proceed willy-nilly; especially when working with a large number of cases, some theoretical selectivity is required. This is part of the small n/large n tradeoff: although hobbled by truncated sample size, small n work can be historically “rich,” i.e., it can incorporate a great many variables and tell a fuller story; large n work, by contrast, surveys many cases but can scrutinize only a few variables lest the project become unwieldy. Thus, in quantitative work especially, initial assumptions are critical since these few indicators will determine the broad contours of the data. One of the ironies of the COW is that Singer, an exuberant critic of realism, opted to work within the paradigm. The result, he notes, is a “rather familiar set of variables” apropos of state-centered power politics, militaryindustrial capabilities, alliances, polarity, and so forth (Singer 1976:26). Leng and Singer (1990: 224) suggest that “a realpolitik perspective identifies the key variables to which policymakers historically have directed their attention in the course of disputes in which their security is threatened.”4 Some COW researchers sound downright Waltzian in their views on global conflict, pointing to “the constancy and timelessness of basic inter-state relations” (Gochman and Maoz 1990:221). However, nowhere does Singer admit that the realists had got it right. The aim rather was to wade into the paradigm, constructing more precise and complex realist models, eventually putting its hypotheses to the empirical test. Collecting realist data is the sensible way to proceed here. At the same time, Singer hopes to remain alert to alternative theoretical schemes. This is the agnostic’s strategy of traveling far along the inductive road before committing to a particular paradigm. The COW simply has not made the data needed to explore whole realms of international politics, apparently deciding that it would be more profitable to focus on the dyadic military logic by which conflicts unfold rather than test the influence that economics, international norms, international organizations, or black-letter law may have on war. The project’s state-centeredness has its empirical pitfalls as well. Most glaringly, extra-systemic wars (colonial or imperial conflicts in which at least one combatant was not a member of the state system) are coded as if the system actor were the only participant. Thus, looking at the data, the only combatants in the Javanese War (1825–30), the Congo Arabs War (1892), and the Mozambique War (1964–75) were Holland, Belgium, and Portugal, respectively. In such wars, virtually no data are recorded for any non-system member, a significant coding decision given that extrasystemic wars account for two-thirds of COW conflicts. In these 134 cases, the project’s concern with the inter-actionary dynamics of war simply falls down. Looking exclusively at system members through a Westphalian lens helps to formalize and operationalize conflict, but the practice no doubt portrays war as a more tractable problem than it really is.5
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 127
On the question of validity and reliability, we must in the end rely on the COWs assurances of respectable “inter-coder reliability,” a measure of how similarly different people code the same material. Inter-coder reliability is, as Singer says, a factor of the “clarity, explicitness, and precision of the coding rules” (Singer 1990a: 119).6 More importantly, though, it is a factor of the consistency of the material being coded. That consistency happens to be quite high in the case of the COW since coding of events, actions, targets, etc., proceeds on the basis of a “clean” history: a master verbal chronology in which ambiguities and/or discrepancies that may have existed in the original sources have been smoothed over or reconciled. Given this ready-to-wear approach, where coders are handed these assumptions and this set of facts, outcomes should be reasonably close. The real historical work, the “agony and frustration” part—slogging through the history books, delving in the archives and state papers, dredging up memoirs and media reports, drawing inferences, choosing narratives and extracting what is important—has already been done. Hewing to the coding rules, the coder merely gives this prefabricated history its final, operational form. A more meaningful test would involve having our coders, preferably seasoned diplomatic historians, march up the steps of the Library of Congress or the Bibliothèque Nationale or some other depository of knowledge, where each researcher would then select, digest, and harmonize his sources. Then he would start coding. Bound up in historical judgments and expertise, this sort of replication would be far rowdier than the COWs perfunctory routine. Think of the problems lurking in the realist, declinist, progressivist, nationalist, Marxist, and other ideological or axe-grinding histories and hagiographies our investigators might discover in the stacks! The point is, if subjected to a true test of reproducibility, intercoder reliability would presumably plummet. Testing randomly: selected COW data I am not a diplomatic historian and had at my disposal only a good university research library, yet my own attempt to replicate COW data supports a skeptical view. I first had a computer randomly select five COW wars: Sepoy, Italian Unification, Italo-Turkish, Chaco, and Indonesian Independence. Without knowing which sources the COW used or what numbers it had arrived at, I then constructed data for each war’s primary indicators: magnitude (nation-months: the sum of all the participants’ months of active involvement, emphasizing, as the COW does, military rather than legal events), severity (battle deaths by participant), and intensity (calculated two ways: battle deaths per nation-months, and battle deaths per 10,000 population). My findings are as recorded in Tables 6.1 to 6.5. The Sepoy War (1857–9)—Table 6.1 Sen (1992:5) states that “no military revolt in the world has produced so much literature.” The conflict has drawn commentary from Disraeli, Marx, and Victorian
128 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Table 6.1 Sepoy War (1857–9)
do-gooders, to contemporary Indian nationalists. There is a yawning interpretive gulf in the literature over whether the war was a “mutinous uprising” against the British by the sepoys, the native soldiers of the Bengal Army, or whether it was a “Great Rebellion” or “Popular Resistance,” a premonition of the independence movement. Not surprisingly, debate about causes and consequences has been lively, even coloring battleto-battle accounts. A recent history suggests that, despite its ardor, this debate has been fueled by “a sparse diet of questionable depositions, muddled accounts, dubious journals, and the narratives of shell-shocked survivors with axes to grind” (Ward 1996:555). Others note an “inevitable bias” born of “superficial, inadequate and essentially partisan” British source materials and a dearth of documents on the side of the “mutineers” (Harrison 1980: lvi and Mutiny Reports from Punjab 1976: introduction). Amid this “orgy of murder,” battle deaths, especially on the Indian side, are extremely hazy. There are plausible accounts of individual battles, yet the “Independence Movement” school claims that the insurrection was general. It is unclear who among the Indians were fighting, much less dying. A “Narrative of Events” issued by the Raj several months into the conflict noted that “in consequence of the general nature of the rebellion and the impossibility of identifying the majority of the rebels the Magistrate recommended the wholesale burning and destruction of all villages proved to have sent men to take active part in the rebellion” (Majumdar 1963:390). Making this gruesome calculus even more precarious is the fact that the conflict raged in the midst of near pestilence across Northern India, a region that during the conflict became known as the “Famine Tract.” Bhargava (1992:142) estimates that between starvation and forced emigration, 500,000 Indians died. In such an atmosphere, it is folly to pretend anything approaching accuracy in gauging battle deaths. Embree (1963:63) says only that “hundreds and thousands” gave up their lives. (The COWs 1994 estimate of total battle deaths, including Indian ones, is 15,000. I preserved the 1982 methodology—which neglects extrasystemic actors, i.e., the Indians—in order to compare intensity figures.) On British casualties, Edwardes (1963:202) is the least
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 129
equivocal and most quoted, noting that 2034 men died in action, while 8987 succumbed to “sunstroke and sickness.” Following the COWs criterion of including all “war theater” deaths induced by combat wounds, exposure, or disease, I adopted these figures and added the roughly 400 British non-combatants thought to have been massacred at Cawnpore and Lucknow. The War of Italian Unification (1859)—Table 6.2 This conflict is often considered part of the lengthy ferment of the Risorgimento from 1848 until 1870, when Rome was finally wrested from the Pope. This periodization makes for a protracted, low-intensity conflict usually referred to as the War(s) of Italian Independence. That said, historians have been just as likely to compress the periodization, identifying a number of separate wars —although because the COW has included none of Garibaidi’s southern campaign, it has perhaps misnamed the war. I collected data through 1861 only to discover later that the COW was referring only to the three-month conflict more commonly known as “The War of 1859” or “The Franco-Austrian War.” Also, neatly packaging Piedmont-Papal States and Piedmont-Sicily as distinct wars results in a misleadingly simple picture of Garibaldi’s crusade. (According to my research, the Papal States were not a member of the state system. The COW defines a member of the state system as an entity of at least 500,000 inhabitants whose sovereignty was “legitimized” by both Britain and France posting to its capital a resident diplomat above the rank of chargé d’affaires. In 1860, the Papal States met the population criteria, yet Britain’s envoy to the Eternal City was a lowly counsel general.) Most troublingly, the Westphalian model distorts the dynamics of Italy’s unification. This was a case of anarchy mitigated by nationalism. As the conflict spread south, not everyone was averse to being “conquered” by Piedmont, and the fighting was punctuated with a series of plebiscites. In the literature, battle death estimates range widely and mix “methodologies,” referring to “killed, wounded, or missing” one day, and “fallen” or “losses” the next. I compiled my decidedly “low confidence” figures according to the four major battles, employing a killed-to-wounded ration of 1:3.5. At times, I split the difference between accounts. The COW adopted some unusual population figures. The Italo-Turkish War (1911–12)—Table 6.3 Prime Minister Giolitti described Italy’s attempt to wrest Libya from the Ottoman Empire as “a war sui generis” (Herrmann 1989:332). Prompted by a surge in nationalism at home, the Italian campaign quickly became mired in a delicate mess as Germany and Austria tried diplomatically to constrain Italy’s actions, which they feared might topple the feeble old man of Europe. Thus, third and fourth parties whom the COW does not acknowledge were crucial “participants” in the war. As Bosworth (1996:63) notes, “It was a war in which experts in warfare were less important than experts in bribery.” On participants and periodization, the
130 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Table 6.2 War of Italian Unification (1859)
anthropologist Evans-Pritchard (1949) argues that it was more an Italo-Sanusi War than an Italo-Turkish one, and that resistance led by Sanusi guerillas continued for a decade following the Peace of Ouchy. He also cautions that Italian battle accounts must be read “with reserve,” as they are probably distorted by state censorship and the belief that an “African” war could only be a runaway victory for Italy. Beehler, a former US Navy commodore and naval attaché to several American embassies, writes as a naval advocate. He almost certainly exaggerates the significance of Italy’s naval warfare, which is portrayed elsewhere as a diversion from the stalled desert war. Beehler’s book (1913) comes complete with block letters to call attention to crossroads where peacetime Turkey neglected to prepare for war, thereby sealing its doom. Also, tucked into the volume was a sheet of paper that appeared to be a handtyped entreaty from the author directing the reader to the “Lesson” of the book, namely that “the weak are prey for the strong man armed,” adding that “oceans no longer protect us from oversea invasion but facilitate it,” hence “the urgent necessity of an adequate U.S.Navy.” My battle death guesswork for “Turkey” is elevated by reports that 180,000 natives were killed in Cyrenaica province between 1911 and 1914.
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 131
Table 6.3 Italo-Turkish War (1911–12)
The Chaco War (1932–5)—Table 6.4 After the War of the Triple Alliance, the Chaco War was South America’s greatest armed conflict. Fought in one of the most desolate places on earth, over rumored oil riches, the war was more of a patriotic clash than a rational, interest-based affair. As Clodfelter (1992:703) notes, “there were probably fewer gallons of oil in the area won than there had been gallons of blood sacrificed to win it.” As the numbers suggest, at the time, the war had a profound impact on the nations involved. Roughly 15 percent of all Paraguayans and 10 percent of Bolivians saw duty in the Chaco. Bullets continue to fly in contemporary Latin American historiography of the war, with no shortage of heroes, martyrs, and villains. This is the sort of “toysoldier” war—with two system members, clean start and stop dates, and minimal non-combatant involvement—that most easily conforms to the COW’s coding criteria. The Indonesian War (1945–6)—Table 6.5 This conflict is usually considered part of the Indonesian War of Independence stretching from 1945 to 1949. The COW focuses on the British/Indian “replacement” of the departed Japanese until Dutch forces could arrive, and on a major pacification effort by the Dutch beginning in December 1946, including Westerling’s notorious six-week campaign on the island of Sulawesi, in which perhaps 40,000 Indonesians were butchered to death (Zainu’ddin 1980:224 and Neill 1973:329). After March 1947, negotiations took the forefront, although the
132 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Table 6.4 Chaco War (1932–5)
Smith sources: Zook (1960), Clodfelter (1992), and Farcau (1996).
Dutch continued a series of potent “police actions” between July 1947 and February 1949, which included indiscriminate shelling of Medan, Palembang, Modjokerto and other cities. As many as 4000 additional islanders were killed. Because of systemmember battle death inclusion criteria, the entire “guerilla phase” of the independence struggle (lasting about two years) is missing from the COWs calculations. The COW does not include these tens of thousands of Indonesian battle dead because Indonesia was not at the time a member of the state system. The coding introduces an extraneous dynamic to the conflict, where “war” ends abruptly when the numbers fall below the threshold; conflict does not peter out into peace. I opted for the “orthodox” periodization, hence the quite different nation-month periods and intensity figures. There seems to be no satisfactory way to account for Indian troops acting as British agents. Almost all “British” battle deaths were members of the 4th Indian Division. (According to its 1994 methodology, the COW lists zero British deaths, and a total of 5000 battle-related deaths.) As the conflict dragged on, world opinion probably became Indonesia’s strongest ally. The perils of data-making Sifting for details on nineteenth-century diplomatic postings in a crumbling, onionskin Alamanach de Gotha (which is the size of a deck of cards and written in French), I developed a new appreciation for the grueling work of datamaking. I am afraid, however, that what really stood out in my attempted replication were the historical problems associated with the process. First, the COWs exclusion of non-system members from its data seems to me indefensible. As I noted earlier, the project
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 133
Table 6.5 Indonesian War (1945–6)
inflicts this Westphalian bias upon 134, or fully two-thirds, of the 209 conflicts it identifies. The practice ensures that any logic of war discerned in these cases (and in the aggregate) will be seriously flawed. Most wars are simply not of the tidy “toysoldier” variety, with two system members, clean start and stop dates, faithful military records, and minimal non-combatant “interference.” Second, historical inferences and interpretations can be quite fluid, even as they relate to “factual” questions such as battle deaths. It was revealing to track the historical “archaeology” of the data, as qualified battle death estimates, for example, were repeated matterof-factly by later writers. I was reminded of the adage that history does not repeat itself; historians repeat each other! Third, differences in periodization affect statistical results, with intensity figures being especially volatile. Do we conceive of one long war or a series of short ones? Was a war preceded or followed by a number of guerilla raids or police actions that fall outside our definitions? To say that this is a question of “clear coding criteria” seems inadequate. Fourth, soaking in the histories, one appreciates the complexity of events, as well as some of the distortions imposed by the quantitative method. With the possible exception of the Chaco War, the COW seems to have missed the central dynamic of each of the wars under study. Finally, the exercise chips away at the notion that thoroughness in historical research will necessarily lift the interpretive mist from events. The opposite may be true. As the critic Leonard Woolf once noted: “the moment one begins to investigate the truth of the simplest facts that one has accepted as true it is as though one had stepped off a firm narrow path into a bog or a quicksand—every step takes one steps deeper into the bog of uncertainty” (quoted in Guralnik 1994: xii).
134 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
When one compares the reliability of different data sets, it becomes clear what a quagmire war research can be. War data sets are most at odds over what they include. The COW compared its first list of wars with six prior compilations covering comparable time frames and found “an overall interstudy agreement of only 12 percent,” although Singer and Small (1972:79) suggest that if we control for different theoretical foci and inclusion rules, disagreement is less severe. Edward Mansfield compared the wars in common in five different war data sets—those compiled by Wright, Richardson, Small and Singer, Bueno de Mesquita, and Levy —on a number of variables and found marked differences, most surprisingly a low correlation (about 0.22) from one compilation to the next between numbers of wars begun in any particular year, a figure that remained low even after the data were adjusted to include only inter-state wars, thus eliminating those hard-to-date colonial conflicts (Mansfield 1988:25–6). Perhaps nowhere is the volatility of war data more conspicuous than in the evolution of the COWs own data sets. In between the 1982 list (international wars n=118) and the 1994 list (international wars n=209), COW researchers added five inter-state wars fought during the 1980s and early 1990s (Falklands, Lebanon, SinoVietnamese, Gulf War, and Azeri-Armenian), but also, citing a “relaxation” in the inclusion criterion on battle deaths, they have added a remarkable eighty-five international wars between 1816 and 1980 which were not included in the earlier survey (Singer and Small 1994a: 8–11). These ballooning numbers have to be unsettling for researchers who have based their work on the earlier data. Data-making is not a science. A data set’s crisp tabulations are the fruit of a painstaking, but ultimately untidy, historical process where theory shapes the broad outline of the data while individual coders craft its finer features. Given variances from one compilation to the next, as well as each data set’s internal yardsticks, claims of reproducibility should be scrutinized closely. The problem seems less a factor of research design or disingenuous investigators than of the nature of the material, with its competing and controversial truths. Small puts a brave face on the historical problem, in the end appealing to the macro-validity of the data: “For the social scientist, the question is how valid is the indicator for the thousands of cases in the sample, not whether each figure represents absolute historical reality” (Small 1979: 75). Yet, as we saw with battle deaths and other primary indicators, it is precisely the aggregate numbers that get muddled. “Guesstimates” snowball into conjecture as imprecisions and biases in selection, interpretation, and coding are reproduced throughout the data. However candid COW researchers are about the agonies of data-making, the project nevertheless proceeds on the basis of a clean set of data points which effectively conceals, but does not eliminate, the historical problem. Contending with the quantitative fallacy When method is king, does it rule the material? According to David Hackett Fischer, a frequent history error is the “quantitative fallacy,” which arises when a factor’s
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 135
importance rests on its susceptibility to measurement. Historians should count everything they can, Fischer encourages, but singleminded behavioralism can bypass qualitative questions and impel the historian into some causal backwater just because that is where the numbers happen to be (Fischer 1970:90–4). Cliometric international relations seems especially prone to the quantitative fallacy. Security, power, interests, aggression, prestige, deterrence, polarity, and democracy are all ambiguous abstractions that resist counting. Since the COW purports to quantify national attributes, inter-state relationships, and actual diplomatic behavior, let us look at how validly it measures one element from each of the categories: material capabilities, prestige, and crisis behavior. Material capabilities. The COW calculates state power capabilities according to six figures: population (total and urban), industry (energy consumption and steel production), and military capabilities (size of armed forces and level of military spending). This material-realist conception of power, a husk of classical realist criteria, departs forthwith from Morgenthau’s idea of political power as a psychological construct. COW criteria seem better suited to study nineteenthcentury European realpolitik, with its “quid pro quo with a measuring cup” approach to the balance of power, than contemporary foreign affairs. Even then the COW sidesteps questions of geography, military morale, strategic competence, public opinion, and autonomy in decisionmaking, the strength of political institutions, and regime legitimacy, not to mention all the intricacies of culture, ideology, or national identity. Not that these are easy concepts to grasp: Singer is probably right in believing that such variables are “too idiosyncratic, state-specific, and dyadspecific to permit valid comparisons across space and time” (Singer 1990b: 55). Still, the quantitative method debars us from exploring them at all. Prestige. COW seeks to measure the “diplomatic importance” or “status” attributed to states by other states without regard to power, capabilities, and influence (Singer and Small 1966:236). The indicator is constructed by tallying the number of diplomatic missions and the rank of the foreign emissaries accredited and dispatched to each state capital. The presence or absence of an embassy and top envoys is thought to imply the host country’s diplomatic status. More than a few implausible rankings turn up, however. In 1955, Mexico (17th) is deemed of greater diplomatic importance than the Soviet Union (18th). In 1960, Italy leads the list. In 1965 Israel (13th) is on par with the Soviet Union (15th); and North Vietnam ranks 112th. In 1970 the United States is ranked 6th, trailing Holland (2nd), Belgium (4th), and Switzerland (5th); the Soviet Union (17th) is deemed less diplomatically important than Austria, Denmark, Pakistan, and Yugoslavia (13th– 16th, respectively); while pre-Nixon China is ranked 63rd, lagging Sudan (32nd), Mali (46th), and Guinea (49th). Something is clearly amiss. A better measure of diplomatic stature might focus on diplomatic outcomes, or factor in military-industrial capabilities or trade prowess, which must have some bearing on prestige. Again, the COW forestalls any such complex of factors. We are left with a lonely indicator, which again is folded into other variables and operations.
136 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Crisis behavior. Coding of the project’s truly behavioral questions spirals into the interpretive stratosphere, demanding judgment-calls that fall well outside the “explicit descriptive dimensions” outlined in the BCOW protocols for coding militarized inter-state crises (Leng 1995). What was the “specific precipitant event”? What was the “tempo” of the action? Were threats and ultimata made? (These prejudicial terms have been euphemized into “intend action” and “request action.”) Were threats conditional or unconditional? Did they challenge the “vital interests” of the target? Were they a “serious affront” to the “dignity or prestige” of the target state? Did a “display of military force” constitute an “alert,” a “mobilization,” or a “show of force”? Did the use of force constitute a “blockade,” an “occupation of territory,” a “seizure,” a “clash,” a”declaration of war,” or a full-blown “war”? Were trade talks an “economic consultation” or an “advise (economic)”? (Note the “neatness effect” flowing from the precise, either-or options available to coders.) These questions were plucked from the BCOWs behavioral “choice tree.” The approach replaces static explanations of outcomes, such as geography or regime type, with a dynamic model of “influence attempt-response sequences.” Thirty-four thousand distinct “events” surrounding forty-eight international disputes have been fitted into 132 different military, diplomatic, economic, and unofficial categories. Most of the crises comprise hundreds of distinct events. The most complex case is the 1956 Suez Crisis (Egypt, Britain, France, Israel), with 2300 events. Each crisis is then translated into a string of numerical event codes that can be analyzed statistically. COW researchers see in the data evidence that “the evolution of interstate disputes is more structured than is often believed” (Gochman and Leng 1983:98). Crises tend to escalate more rapidly when “vital interests” are at stake, and great power involvement aids effective conflict resolution. Moreover, how one negotiates seems to sway outcomes: coercive tactics are likely to elicit defiant responses, while chances are that “reciprocity” (“mixing tit-for-tat responses with occasional accommodative initiatives”), will yield a peaceful resolution (Leng and Singer 1990). Dispute behavior may be less structured than the COW suggests. Its hierarchical choice tree gives the impression that history is not path dependent but path determined. In hindsight, the “steps to war” lead ineluctably to the outcome, each limb representing an isolated, independently operating, mechanistically causal link. The assumption is that an added pinch of “consultation,” a dollop of “political concession,” or a touch less “violation of international law” would send the process branching off in a more pacific direction. However, strict causal tiers may confer an artificial coherence on crisis decisionmaking, obscuring broader historical processes or neglecting other causes. In other words, this could be neatly sketched post hoc ergo propter hoc reasoning. If a “show of strength” is followed by an “evacuation,” or if an “antiforeign riot” is followed by a “change in economic assistance,” were the events that followed caused by the events that preceded them? This is a challenge for any historical construct, although “diagramming” state behavior in this way assumes an unequivocal cause and effect, something more easily hedged in narrative. The connection between events is direct (“antiforeign
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 137
riot→new economic package”) rather than implied (“Two days after the riots in Manila, the Prime Minister unveiled a new foreign aid package.”). When coding begins, causal rumination ends. The method cannot abide any modesties of narrative: “perhaps,” “appears,” “seems,” “suggests,” etc. If there are historical ambiguities, they are better preserved in narrative. This is not to suggest that diplomacy is immune to path dependence. Decisionmakers always work within historical contexts. Constraints are imposed by previous decisions taken, and the range of choices narrows. However, this is different from an iron cage of causality. There were choices along the way, things did not have to turn out the way they did. As Lawrence Stone (1977:38) warns, “crunching historical explanation into a single one-way hierarchy of causation… threatens to strangle imaginative historical inquiry. It blocks off any possibility that historical explanation may, in fact, be a much messier and more loose-ended process. To borrow the language of the engineers, it may be a nonlinear, multipleloop feedback system, with many semiindependent variables, each responsively reacting to the influence of some, or all, of the others.” Indeed, the BCOWs precision coding, with its 132 discrete inputs neatly divided into functionally distinct military, diplomatic, economic and unofficial actions, almost certainly demands artificially sharp coding distinctions. Can we truly sever, as the BCOW does, a “military intrusion” from a “violation of territory”? Can we treat “supply nuclear weapons” and “political intervention” as separate occurrences? Is there a clear line between official and unofficial actions? It is not clear that these are independent variables. Cause and effect may spill back and forth across different state functions. Certainly diplomatic initiatives are taken bearing in mind various military and economic relationships, or a military intervention might be for economic reasons. Modeled after a decision-tree rather than a continuum, the COW does not entertain the possibility that war may be politics (or economics) by other means, that there might be a unity to foreign policy. Clausewitz will be spinning in his grave. The question is crucial because this is international history, with its gray zones of diplomacy, and oftentimes intentional lacunae of ambiguity, where words and deeds may target a domestic audience or an unnamed third party as much as an obvious foreign adversary. Paul Schroeder has noted that it is deceptive to code only overt behavior since doing nothing is one of the most important “actions” in foreign policy. The effect of nonintervention can be passive cooperation, such as Germany’s tacit encouragement of French colonialism in Asia and Africa as a “safe” outlet for la mission civilisatrice. It can be over-simple to categorize diplomatic ties in terms of either conflict or cooperation, since alliance and antagonism often coincide as states join or seek alliances for reasons of control as well as friendship. Austro-Prussian behavior during the Schleswig-Holstein dispute and the resulting Danish-German War in 1863–4, for example, appears on the surface to be a litany of shoulder-to-shoulder cooperation between Austria and Prussia against the Danes: allying to intervene in the dispute between Denmark and the German Confederation; together muscling the other German states out of deciding the issue;
138 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
presenting a joint ultimatum to Denmark; launching and fighting the war together; agreeing jointly to an armistice; in lock-step resuming hostilities after negotiations broke down at the Conference of London; together imposing terms on defeated Denmark; declaring joint sovereignty over the conquered provinces and sharing administrative duties. Yet, what looks like a catalogue of cooperation was in fact part and parcel of Bismarck’s strategy to undercut Austria’s influence in Germany, and throughout the entire episode Austria was trying unsuccessfully to resist the Prussian’s designs. This in mind, Schroeder asks us to imagine the following sequence of events: “(1) A man takes a woman by the hand; (2) He puts his arm around her; (3) He draws her close to him; (4) He kisses her; (5) He strangles her.” Only a deluded coder would treat these as five separate actions, four amicable, one deadly, but this is essentially how diplomatic history is translated into events data (Schroeder 1977:4–8). The quantitative fallacy at each of these levels of analysis, whether we are looking at power, prestige, or actual state behavior, is that the “aggregate” data are actually a compilation of disaggregated historical traces. Even the narrativist does not start at the beginning of the story: his periodization is somewhat arbitrary; there are always earlier antecedents. As Maitland famously put it, “Such is the unity of history that anyone who endeavors to tell a piece of it must feel that his first sentence tears a seamless web” (quoted in Marwick 1970:326). This is radically the case with snapshot data points, each of which has no history. “Historical context” turns out to be cross-sectional, as “time series analysis” usually means looking at a few historical shavings under a glass slide. It is unclear how well the approach captures the longitudinal character of international conflict (see Goertz 1994:172). By focusing on the immediate logic of conflict, and pegging a number of indices to the war’s “initiator,” the COW sidesteps problems of deep causality and underlying motivations. Not all wars start with tanks crashing across borders. They may be preceded by generations of low-grade tensions, motivations bred in the bones of the participants. Knowing that India “started” the Bangladesh War of 1971 is no substitute for understanding the poisonous history of the subcontinent. Was the Sinai War of 1956–7 precipitated by Nasser nationalizing the Suez Canal, or earlier by Britain and the United States withdrawing support for the Aswan Dam, or earlier still by Zionism itself? Causality works at many different levels. The BCOW cites Egyptian border raids as the “first hostilities” in the Sinai War, while the main COW data set credits Israel with initiating the conflict some months later, yet neither project really accounts for decades of enmity between Arabs and Jews. Across quantitative work, such complex questions of responsibility and periodization are handled in too simple a manner. Finally, a word on the qualitative side of war. Raymond Aron (1966:328–30) once observed that although “all national histories resemble each other in the eyes of the statistician or the moralist,” in fact some historical episodes are “creative,” setting precedents and spurring ideas, while others turn out to be “historically sterile.” The COW adopts an homogeneous conception of conflict. The project does draw distinctions in some operations, notably in measuring alliance
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 139
configurations, though for the most part all states and all wars end up in the same stew. The Lopez War (Argentina, Brazil, Paraguay, 1864–70), the Riffian War (France and Spain, 1921–6), or the Soccer War (Honduras and El Salvador, five days in 1969) are considered analogous to the Second World War or the Gulf War in the sense that each, equally, is plumbed for the logic of conflict. Behavioral dyads are treated generically as well: the Pastry War (France and Mexico, 1838–9) and the Rann of Kutch (India and Pakistan, three months in 1965) lumped with the Anschluss and the Fashoda Crisis. Individual diplomatic and military “moves” are analogized too, at times uncongenially. Russia’s occupation of the Danube principalities in 1853 is classified as a “show of force” preceding the Crimean War, as are Egyptian troop movements near the canal during the Suez Crisis and the Soviet Union’s “air-shows” in the throes of the Berlin Crisis. Ship rammings and trawler line cuttings during the Cod War (Iceland, Britain, et al., 1975–76) are classified exactly the same way. Viewed through a lens of prudence or discretion, crucial distinctions emerge. Lessons gleaned in the aggregate may be ill-suited for a great power uniquely placed in the international system, or for a modern Asian city-state, or a diminutive country nestled in a federalist Europe. Moreover, in the realm of self-given meanings rather than scientifically conferred ones, some historical analogies loom inordinately large, either as high-water marks to emulate or debacles to avoid. As one scholar notes of the “Copenhagen complex” (the fixation spawned by Britain’s capture of the neutral Danish fleet in 1807), it “seeped into men’s perceptions and became part of the vocabulary of political life,” influencing German foreign policymaking in particular for a century (quoted in Levy 1994a: 280). In 1914 and again in 1939, the French General Staff diligently studied “the lessons of last time” and committed appalling strategic and tactical blunders as a consequence. Desert Storm, Munich, the “loss” of China, Vietnam, the Suez Crisis, the War of the Pacific, the Conquest of Mexico, and the ill-fated UN intervention in Somalia all became touchstones for subsequent foreign-policy decisions. In sum, the quantitative approach tends to focus on the obvious exterior to what are almost certainly complex and deep-seated phenomena. It is like comparing buildings by Frank Lloyd Wright and Frank Gehry on square footage alone. Therein lies a fallacy. For this reason, qualitative history, in depth and in context, may prove more fruitful in explaining international politics. As David Dessler has argued, it may be that only careful and intensive case studies, contending with a complex of variables over the long term, will reveal the underlying “generative structures and processes” of causality (Dessler 1991: 352). Balance-of-power politics is probably best understood by charting the depths of German and British diplomatic-economic history over the decades prior to the First World War—a close reading across levels of causality and considering far-flung variables as well as those closer to home. The role of prestige in international politics is highlighted by a keen look at the motivations that seem to have driven involvement in the Korean War. Steeping oneself in the history of the Cuban Missile Crisis may reveal the forest of crisis behavior better than hundreds of choice trees.
140 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Rigor on its face: cliometrics assessed “The good of counting,” Dr. Johnson remarked in 1783, “is that it brings everything to a certainty which before floated in the mind indefinitely” (quoted in Stone 1977: 17). The danger of counting in international relations, however, is that the method will burden history with more certainty than it can bear. Quantitative work helps curb impressionism, anecdotalism, and selection bias in historical usage in the field, and reins in theoretical wanderings too far from the historical “record.” It can also prod other researchers to define clearly their assumptions and terms, and, unlike structuralists, quantitative researchers are willing and methodologically able to work across levels of analysis. The COW in particular has broached a number of counter-intuitive challenges to orthodox international relations, which have spurred more theoretically focused qualitative work. The project’s findings on obverse alliance indicators in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries have kindled further work in that field. Early on, Singer engaged the bipolar/multipolar question, while more recent (and more skeptical) COW work has pointed to the multidimensionality of polarity and its aversion to precise measurement. The project has also contributed to the democratic peace debate, both through its own early work on the subject, and through its BCOW dyads being incorporated into Bruce Russett’s (1993) research. It has also advanced an array of smallerscale findings. Throughout, the project has been a source of inspiration as well as a clearinghouse of methods and data for quantitative analysts. Still, the COWs approach exhibits a certain quaintness. From the start, the COW assumed that the “facts” of diplomatic history existed independent of interpretation and theory, that the historical scientist really did “go naked into the laboratory.” It also deemed that those facts could be extracted from the larger story without doing violence to the parts or the whole. Yet, repeatedly we see the material shoehorned into the method—a method not particularly congenial to diplomatic history, with its murky motivations and where perceptions about security, power, prestige, interests, and norms seem so important. These ambiguities appear to be characteristic of a sphere where states (and other entities) pursue a variety of political ends defined in a variety of ways. The greatest folly of quantitative work may be that it strips this ambiguity from political inquiry. Michael Howard (1983:192–3) notes that the narrative military historian creates order out of chaos, “with neat little blocks and arrows moving in a rational and orderly way, with the principles of war being meticulously illustrated,” and that this, he says, is “an almost blasphemous travesty of the chaotic truth.” If quantitative methods make an even greater travesty of the truth, they are doing us no favors. This may be why diplomatic historians have shied away from cliometrics. Driven by the admonition to count, the method may not track the most fruitful predictors of state behavior. Indeed, it may trivialize war and diplomacy, as easily quantifiable indicators stand in for less tangible but perhaps more theoretically important factors. Claims of reproducibility, meanwhile, seem overstated. Interpretive problems are concealed in a neat set of “de-bugged” history, a composite of “hard”
“THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 141
and “soft” numbers where errors in the “independent” variables are reproduced across the data which, nevertheless, become the authority for all manner of assertions. One can imagine how apocryphal history might become hard data. It has been remarked that the COW, like other data-making enterprises, has spawned an “invisible college” of researchers who use its data. More to the point, low reliability in correlations between data sets suggests that unique inclusion rules and coding interpretations make each compilation an island of knowledge, bounded by its own definitions and models of conflict. This may be the reason that quantitative work rarely cumulates much beyond the research communities that sprout up around each data set. Thus, to the skeptic’s eye, the more guarded quantitative conclusions are, the more confidence they inspire. Appearances to the contrary, cliometrics does not have a clinch on rigor. As M.J.Moroney has noted, the method induces “delusions of accuracy.” “When the job is done it looks very accurate. It is an easy and fatal step to think that the accuracy of our arithmetic is equivalent to the accuracy of our knowledge about the problem in hand” (quoted in Duvall 1976:70). The method’s comparative advantage in rigor does seem inflated. “Data” are very seductive, yet no amount of statistical trapeze-swinging or quantitative boosterism should divert us from fundamental historical questions. Even when cliometrics reveals a particular pattern or correlation, how that relationship is interpreted remains a historical judgment, ambiguities and all. Finally, how has the COW fared as an exercise in nomothetic science? What laws of behavior does it propose? Thirty years hence, hundreds of histories have been digested and megabytes of data prepared, yet the theoretical denouement remains just around the corner. Despite great optimism and enormously hard work, the project’s crucial explanatory phase is lagging badly. The fact is that the material still exhibits “no dominant theoretical strand, no culminating argument, no recurrent cadenza” (Small and Singer 1982:292). With COW data widely available, it is not surprising that research based on that information is strewn across the literature. Still, the findings remain fragmented. Singer has edited several volumes of disparate papers, but to date has not attempted to integrate them.7 Surveying this pinnacle of historical work in international relations, elevated by quantitative methods and the canons of social science, the obvious question is why has the payoff been so paltry? A better question might ask if there is an anti-payoff. With no robust correlations to show, not to speak of theoretical coherence, the most rigorous conclusion might be that state behavior is not so formulaic or nomothetic after all. Indeed, it may be misguided to take too Olympian a cyberview on the problem of war. Middle-range theories buttressed by a close reading of a variety of histories may turn out to be more fruitful. Quantitative researchers might consider the conclusion of that masterly work of social science history, Fernand Braudel’s The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II: “we must visualize a series of overlapping histories, developing simultaneously. It would be too simple, too perfect, if this complex truth could be reduced to the rhythms of one dominant pattern” (Braudel 1992:651). This anticipates some
142 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
strands of postmodernism explored in the next chapter, and is one of a number of remedies that will be advanced in the final chapter.
7 EXIT FROM HISTORY? Postmodern international relations
To the postmodern eye, the field’s scientific theorists resemble eighteenthcentury encyclopédistes, amassing information in hopes of discovering the underlying unity of knowledge. Postmodernists regard this as an impossible task. In the kaleidoscopic world of postmodernism, knowledge is fragmented, relative, and particular. Truth does not exist in the form of “laws” of history or human behavior. There are no universal political structures or normative values. The scientific formalism that postmodernists abhor is most evident in the quantitative research we have just surveyed, but in fact it underpins all positivist social thought back to the eighteenth century, perhaps to Machiavelli. As Chris Brown notes (1994:60), all postmodernists —post-structuralists, post-positivists, post-Fordists, feminists, Foucauldians, critical theorists, methodological anarchists, dissident theorists, Marxist epistemologists, Gramscians, the Frankfurt School, and American neopragmatists—are united by “a sense of the futility of the defences of modernist rationality offered by traditional supporters of the Enlightenment Project.”1 Postmodernist theory is extraordinarily diverse, encompassing a wide array of aesthetic and epistemological challenges to “modernity,” itself a contested idea. Even so, the broad challenges postmodernism poses for history and politics are relatively straightforward. Postmodernists forcefully reject Ranke’s archival method and Acton’s optimism regarding the “completeness and certainty” of history. Indeed, postmodernists view all historical truth claims as unfounded. They scorn high political accounts, both of the great-man and drum-and-trumpet varieties, and denounce “philosopher’s history” conveying universal lessons or tracing the meaning and direction of events. Some postmodernists (for example, Jameson 1983: 125) contend that we live in a “perpetual present,” as the flux of events leads to “the disappearance of a sense of history.” Others (for example, Baudrillard 1994) view history as a dustbin of recycled images and ideologies. Still others follow Michel Foucault’s (1984:95) claim that “all knowledge rests upon injustice,” and view history as a Western myth that oppresses people from other cultures. But few postmodernists reject history altogether. As this chapter should make clear, postmodernists rely on de-formalized history, apart from “heroic” or statist scripts. Postmodernists identify closely with the “new” narrative historians, who have democratized and localized history. Postmodernists are keenly aware of the problems of history, so much so that their historicism threatens all historical
144 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
learning. Nevertheless, postmodern views of history have produced a number of novel explanations for international politics. These include strategies for “decentering” power, “counter-memorializing” political theory, historicizing identity politics, reconsidering the impact of time and space, and rethinking globalization and pastiche. Postmodern knowledge: content over form In 1995, The New York Times described the conflict in Bosnia as a “postmodern war,” in which the distinction between armies and peoples dissolved, hi-tech weaponry played little role, tribal identity supplanted national loyalty as the seat of conflict, and atavistic warlords terrorized United Nations peacekeepers —all of which was filmed by camera crews for immediate global consumption (Cohen 1995). The war underscores several themes in postmodern historical and political analysis: The Fallacy of “Metanarratives.” That this war happened at all belies several modern “metanarratives” (grand theories), namely, the march of progress, the end of history, and the rise of European unity (Lyotard 1984). The West failed to comprehend this tribal bloodletting because it did not fit the modern models. Genocide, which the “civilized” world had declared would never happen again, was, in fact, happening again. International paralysis over intervention illustrated the lack of universal norms that might spur multilateral action. Anti-essentialism. There are no pure Platonic forms. Social life is plastic, ephemeral, and amorphous. Local culture and local knowledge shatter universal conceptions of truth. Different readings of events are different realities, in this case based on ethnic identity. Modern institutions are not natural or permanent. There was no “essential” Yugoslavia, but neither is there an essential Bosnia or Greater Serbia. Despite their organic rhetoric, these are “imagined communities” (Anderson 1983). Pastiche. Pastiche refers to a hodgepodge of eclectic forms that coexist and sometimes clash in the postmodern world: modern/pre-modern, religious/ secular, universal/parochial, high/low technology, high/low culture, Fordism/ handicrafts, traditional/rational-bureaucratic, etc. In the Bosnian case, ethnic clans browbeating world government is a perfect pastiche. A multiplicity of new (and a return to old) forms of political association undermine the state as the sole seat of power and object of political allegiance. Pastiche challenges “totalizing” descriptions of social phenomena. Societies may move in several different directions at the same time. Power/knowledge. Foucault (1980) argues that knowledge is inherently political, that a web of specific social conditions governs truth. People in power shape truth by manipulating language, symbols, and images. In the Yugoslav case, cohesion and then war were justified by officially sponsored views of history. Tito held Yugoslavia together by exploiting images of federalism and interpretations of foreign threats. Slobodan Milosevic and Franjo Tujman have torn the country apart by exploiting ethnic Serb and Croat (respectively) versions of history.
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 145
Time-space compression. The war illustrates the fragmentation of time and the twisting of historical memory. Centrifugal forces in culture and history shatter statist geography, unsettle continuity in international politics, and encroach on traditional modes of political deliberation. Geography becomes a mental construct (Harvey 1990). Instant news emancipates us from time. The media anticipate and influence events. Knowledge and images are commodified for global consumption. Spectators become inured to violence (Baudrillard 1994). As these concepts suggest, fragmentation as much as globalization is the hallmark of postmodernity. The former Yugoslavia is only one of a number of modern states that have been challenged along fault lines of language, culture, tradition, and ethnohistory. This is indicative of a global trend toward separatism, regionalism, and cultural and ethnic nationalism. According to the Carnegie Commission on Preventing Deadly Conflicts (1997:25–9), virtually all violent conflicts in the world today are being waged within states, often with domestic irredentist fighting as factions seek to reclaim and ethnically cleanse legend-veiled regions. But postmodernists see centrifugal forces everywhere: in the growing popularity of “gated communities,” in the resurgence of private and parochial schools, in privatization and the devolution of power and money to states and provinces, in disintegrating urban life, declining civic spirit, and spreading alienation and despair. Postmodernists acknowledge that the information revolution has brought people together, but hasten to add that it also provides a soapbox for cranks and spawns Internet chat rooms devoted to exclusive interests. Idiosyncratic versions of truth flourish in this environment. In radical politics, Marx’s internationalist battle cry, “the workingmen have no country,” has given way to local fundamentalisms, neofascism, cults of tradition, and spates of terror. The death of metanarrative Postmodernists argue that in such an atmosphere, universal myths and archetypes are obsolete. Hence, Jean-François Lyotard’s canonical statement that “the postmodern condition” is defined by “incredulity toward metanarratives” (grands récits), and “the failure of the universal.” “Modern,” conversely, designates “any science that legitimates itself with reference to a metadiscourse…making an explicit appeal to some grand narrative, such as the dialectics of Spirit, the hermeneutics of meaning, the emancipation of the rational or working subject, or the creation of wealth” (Lyotard 1984: xxiii–iv). The great political narratives of modernity—Marxist utopianism, the Enlightenment unfolding of reason, Capitalism, Nationalism, Revolution, Emancipation, Modernization—certainly can strain credulity. Postmodern critiques tend to single out the Enlightenment, which is doubly flawed for its scientistic methods and progressivist faith (precisely the critique of Enlightenment thought made by classical realists such as Niebuhr, Morgenthau, and Kennan). Certainly not all the political promises of the Enlightenment have been met. The growth of knowledge was to have been liberating and intellectually enriching. Public
146 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
administration would stem the arbitrary use of power, heighten productivity, and free people from backward thinking and practices. “Only through such a project,” notes David Harvey (1990:12), “could the universal, eternal, and the immutable qualities of all of humanity be revealed.” The twentieth century, the test tube of modernity, has shattered any such optimism. Paul Fussell, writing about the First World War, points to the “hideous embarrassment to the prevailing Meliorist myth which had dominated the public consciousness for a century.” The prosperity of the welfare state has been matched by novel Leviathan efficiencies in coercion, cruelty, surveillance, and fear. International politics have seen the advent of nuclear war and total war; technology, propaganda, mass movements, unconditional surrender, Machtpolitik, jack-booted glorification of violence and “corpse-like obedience” have become wedded to the state (Fussell 1975:8). For some postmodernists, Hitler and Stalin represent Enlightenment thought run amok. For others, totalitarianism represents the logical conclusion of the Enlightenment project, that the quest for human emancipation was doomed to become a system of universal oppression. This was the thunderclap that issued from the Frankfurt School, the wellspring of Critical Theory, beginning with its AntiSemitism Project in the 1940s. Walter Benjamin set the tone: “The current amazement that the things we are experiencing are ‘still’ possible in the twentieth century is not philosophical. This amazement is not the beginning of knowledge— unless it is the knowledge that the view of history which gives rise to it is untenable” (quoted in Wiggershaus 1994:327). Benjamin’s colleagues Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer argued in Dialectic of Enlightenment (1972) that such horrors as genocide and purges were inherent in modernity. They were not vestiges of primitivism that the instruments of civilization had failed to eradicate or suppress, but rather were seated at the core of progressive thought, before tunneling outward and spilling forth in events. In short, “Enlightenment was totalitarian” (ibid.: 328). The scientific domination of nature was extended to humankind, crushing dissenting expressions of culture and personality. Here, critical theory dovetails with “traditional” critiques of the gospel of progress. Voegelin, Arendt, de Jouvenel, Oakeshott, Popper, Koestler, Orwell and others have argued that modern, “totalizing” ideologies and “scientific” renditions of politics may turn gnostic and genocidal. Above all, the end of modernity signals the death of the great paradigm of science. Fairly or unfairly, postmodernists contend that all science is ensnarled in the Enlightenment myth, that “the hero of knowledge works toward a good ethicopolitical end—universal peace” (Lyotard 1984:xxiv). Postmodernists claim that, as a foundation for knowledge, science verges on the totalitarian. Any project aimed at the pursuit of truth is wrong-headed, as there is no final and definitive truth “out there” waiting to be discovered. Lyotard contends that science creates and then consumes this discovery ethos in order to justify itself. The conditions of scientific truth, the “rules of the game,” he claims, are “immanent in that game…they can only be established within the bonds of a debate that is already scientific in nature… there is no other proof that the rules are good than the consensus extended to them
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 147
by the experts” (ibid.: 29). Postmodernists not only tear at the moorings of science, but also the methods they suggest in place of science are further undermining. As Rosenau (1992:8) suggests, postmodernists “seek to ‘locate’ meaning rather than ‘discover’ it. They offer ‘readings’ not ‘observations,’ ‘interpretations’ not ‘findings’; they ‘muse’ about one thing or another. They never test because testing requires ‘evidence,’ a meaningless concept within a post-modern frame of reference.” All discussions are equally “interesting.” Distinctions may be made on aesthetic and sometimes moral grounds, but not on the basis of epistemology. In place of science, there is what Lyotard calls “narrative” (as opposed to metanarrative), which simply means discourse that does not depend upon prior justification for truth; it is not “founded” on anything. Narratives are pragmatic, “legitimated by the simple fact that they do what they do” (Lyotard 1984:23). To the scientist, of course, narrative practices reflect an alien mentality: savage, primitive, backward, composed of opinion, custom, tradition, prejudice, ignorance, and ideology. Lyotard claims (ibid.: 27–9), however, that science has trouble logically grounding its own claims. It rests upon the Enlightenment idea, yet the rules of science dictate that this debt not be acknowledged. Science “cannot know and make known that it is the true knowledge without resorting to the other, narrative, kind of knowledge, which from its point of view is no knowledge at all.” Without mooring or center, the postmodern world may seem disorienting and terrifying. For many postmodernists, though, these realizations are liberating. Monolithic truth, after all, could be arrogant and authoritarian, used to justify privilege and make the poor and the weak feel inadequate. Now truth is pluralistic and contextual, redefined as “self-understanding” or perspective, and changing with ethnicity, gender, class, race, age, religion, time, place, etc. (Rosenau 1992:78–81). Non-Western peoples no longer lag behind “universal” forms of culture or development. People may now embrace their own experience and culture, and move to traditional rhythms rather than world time. The narratives of international relations For postmodernists today, the bankruptcy of Enlightenment thought is obvious, and the modern myths are in the process of being dismantled. Yet, international relations continues to resist the sublime of the postmodern. The field remains almost exclusively modernist in outlook and method, representing reality through sweeping world-historical forms (for example, structural realism, world-systems theory, the balance of power, hegemonic stability, the rise and fall of great powers, long waves in international political economy, the end of history, the clash of civilizations) as well as more modest, but nonetheless universal, aprioristic concepts (for example, sovereignty, anarchy, security, Asian tigers, Islamic fundamentalism, international law, human rights, etc.). According to postmodernists, each of these, as a foundational narrative, is a sham. Just as E.H.Carr argued of the harmony of interests and free trade, they are “naturalized” conventions, i.e., historically constituted trajectories raised to the level
148 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
of model or law. They explain individual, unique events by inserting them into formal explanatory systems and lines of progress. Postmodernists argue that this conformity and standardization deprives us of history by denying the authenticity and uniqueness of events, as well as the variety of other, potential historical constructions. Security policy, for example, can be viewed as historically conditioned responses to crises of identity or perceptions about anarchy (Campbell 1992). Postmodernists explode the assumption of anarchy (Ashley 1995). They blur the line between domestic and international politics through “rearticulations of political time and space” (Walker 1993:79). Postmodernists contend that there is nothing natural about democratic elections or free markets (Rosenberg 1994). International development and modernization are not assured, certainly not along preconceived lines. “Development” can be destructive of traditional social fabric and ways of knowledge. Samir Amin (1989:114) argues that eurocentric “humanist universalism” has “brought with it the destruction of peoples and civilizations who have resisted its spread.” International law does not necessarily benefit all mankind, but may be rigged in favor of the industrialized North (Grovogui 1996). The universality of human rights flies in the face of all postmodern thought. “New” history and postmodern politics What narratives do postmodernists tell? Much of the difficulty in understanding how postmodernists use history is due to the fact that postmodernists typically endorse local knowledge, yet remain skeptical toward knowledge in general.2 Postmodernists subvert most of the conventions of historiography. They resist truth claims, and willfully blur history and fiction. Many see history as nostalgia, anachronism, or myth. Some postmodernists reject the idea that people make their own history, believing that events are determined by chance and trivia rather than voluntarism. Others renounce the idea of history as a coherent and worthwhile object of study. Postmodern history has been controversial, to put it mildly (see, for example, Windschuttle 1997). Critics claim that postmodernism undercuts professional standards and subverts long-established rules of historical narrative. By dismissing the idea of historical correspondence to a true past, postmodernism is said to invite a general disregard for truth. Even the quest for truth as the historian’s ideal is relinquished, replaced by an “anything goes” attitude that fosters Oliver Stone-style fictionalizations of history, in which the historian is free to exploit any gap or ambiguity in the record. Critics claim that postmodern political correctness stifles free debate, and that its murky jargon enfeebles the mind. Many critics find postmodernism’s ties to Nietzsche especially noxious. The philosopher’s specter hangs over postmodern history, both in his subjectivism regarding truth and, more distantly, in the admonition to destroy the past in order to make way for the supermen of the future. Perhaps the most cutting criticism of postmodern history is that its relativism erodes ethical judgment—that of the author, the audience, the
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 149
discipline, and in any moral lessons that one might draw from the past. One critic (Gilley 1996) calls this “History without morality, history without truth.” That said, postmodernists are not, for the most part, antihistorical. Rather, they view history, and its role in political life, differently than their modern counterparts. First, postmodernists highlight forms of historical knowledge that are diminished or disqualified within the hierarchy of science. In this, postmodernists have “brought that peripheral, blurred area between history and fiction close to the center of contemporary historiographical debate” (Ginzburg 1991:87). Second, while traditionalists seek to explain or understand the past, postmodernists seek to “problematize” it, to unmask its biases, assumptions, and political uses. As Brenda Marshall (1992:4) explains, Postmodernism is about history. But not the kind of “History” that lets us think we can know the past. History in the postmodern moment becomes histories and questions. It asks: Whose history gets told? In whose name? For what purpose? Postmodernism is about histories not told, retold, untold. History as it never was. Histories forgotten, hidden, invisible, considered unimportant, changed, eradicated. It’s about the refusal to see history as linear, as leading straight up to today in some recognizable pattern. (It is worth inserting that modernity can be inimical to history. It defines itself in opposition to the past, turning to history chiefly in order to establish what modernity is not. The past’s sepia tones affirm the brilliant hues of modern novelty. But history holds few lessons for modernity, whose gaze is always on the future.) In the postmodern attitude toward the past, again there is confluence between political and historiographic theory. Historians and political scientists breathe the same academic air and register similar frustrations with social science. More importantly, the postmodern ethos encourages breaking down boundaries of inquiry. It even entails something of a duty to borrow from other fields, and the rules for doing so are relaxed. Postmodernists thus lapse easily between history and politics. It would be wrong to say that postmodernist politics “borrows” postmodern history in the way that, say, realist theory may turn to realist history for evidence. Rather, methods and insights from other fields are bundled with one’s own ideas, with none of the anxieties usually felt when appropriating from another discipline. In terms of method and content, both fields have seen theory cum philosophy of history be chipped away by the tighter focus of “micro-narratives”— smaller, stand-alone accounts that make no claim to universality. Given the historical profession’s characteristic ambivalence about its affiliation with social science, many historians have found “small is beautiful” a palatable creed. The skepticism with which most political scientists view postmodern narrative is also understandable, since the entire nomothetic tradition is at stake. Lawrence Stone became the standard bearer for the new historical sensibility with his essay, “The Revival of Narrative: Reflections on a New Old History” (1979). Stone argued that the historical profession had undergone a transformation during
150 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
the 1970s, as the premise of social science history, “that a coherent scientific explanation of change in the past” was possible, was widely contested. He urged that historical subjects be broadened to include aspects of everyday life that had been neglected by the Annalistes’ penchant for studying large, often quantifiable, historical trends. This reflected the growing belief “that the culture of the group, and even the will of the individual, are potentially at least as important causal agents of change as the impersonal forces of material output and demographic growth” (quoted in Iggers 1997:97). New narrative lent itself to explanations that focused on human agency and political process much more than structural conditioning. Stone later became a great defender of history against postmodern incursions, but here he shares a great deal in common with his future foes. Both dispense with world history and historical “geology,” embracing instead modest narratives joined to local culture and knowledge. New history and postmodern politics both view “heroic” history as obsolete— narrow, elitist, victorious, patriarchal, or merely dry in its veneration of great events and deeds. Great-man history is thought to attach excessive importance to individuals, presenting history in dramatic form, with leading roles and tragic choices. Rosenau (1992:64) suggests that the method does not chronicle great men; it creates them. The method also bars access to the chaos and complexity of reality. A state at war, for example, is a vast machine, a fact concealed in military history that confines itself to the deeds of warlords. Drum-and-trumpet history glorifies conquests and triumphs, when “victories” may in fact be more equivocal and less precise in their effects than Churchillian history suggests. Names, dates, battles, wars, treaties, winners, losers, etc., all seem tangible on the historian’s page, yet they mask important details. Chief among these for postmodernists is the politics of historical representation itself. Struck by the link between power and “discourse” (practices and patterns of speech and writing), postmodernists typically see this “old” approach to history as justifying “old” raison d’état politics. It reflects and reproduces established powers and interests and diplomatic practices. Old history is also seen as handmaiden to dubious political teleologies—the nation-state, the rise or fall of the West, the march of civilizations, world capitalism, global federalism, and so on. The approach is unacceptable because it assumes history is going someplace in particular, fulfilling a premeditated trajectoral narrative. Postmodernists are generally receptive, however, to new history’s populist and localist views of the past. New history features fragmented and diverse subjects. Redressing modernism’s supposed contempt for ordinary people, it directs research away from the high and mighty, and toward socially invisible and inarticulate people. It explores microhistory, or “petite histoire,” as cultural close-up, as in Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie’s Montaillou (1978) or Natalie Zemon-Davis’s famed Return of Martin Guerre (1983). It attempts to salvage “illegitimate,” “discredited,” “deviant,” “estranged,” and other neglected subjects. It advocates “victim’s” history, women’s “(her)story,” black history, and other “niche” accounts. New history is generally social in nature, but on a small scale, elevating the ordinary and the humdrum over global theory. Asef Bayat’s Street Politics (1997), for example, bridges
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 151
history and politics in analyzing poor people’s social movements in revolutionary Iran, a process Bayat describes as “quietly encroaching” on state power. New history is also interested in how identities are shaped and practiced, for example in George Chauncey’s Gay New York (1994). It privileges peripheral peoples and “fourth world” accounts, sharing much in common with ethnography, as in Eric Wolf’s Europe and the People Without History (1982). New history includes subaltern (of subjugated, especially colonized, people, usually a reference to the Indian subcontinent) and post-colonial histories such as Michel-Rolph Trouillot’s Silencing the Past (1995), which seeks to recover Haitian history from colonialism. This approach also employs “heteroglossia,” meaning that the Actonian Voice of History is replaced by “varied and opposing voices,” a device that underlines multiple viewpoints and conflicting interpretations of events (Burke 1992b: 239). As evidence, new historians frequently cite “secret texts,” “hidden transcripts,” and other unorthodox sources, as in James C.Scott’s Domination and the Arts of Resistance (1990), equally a work of new politics and new history. Seeing identity shaped at home and hearth, new history incorporates local vernacular, myth, legend, story, and song. Benedict Anderson’s Imagined Communities (1983) and Kirsten Hastrup’s volume, Other Histories (1992) are good examples of this. New history emphasizes the oral tradition, as in Elizabeth Tonkin’s Narrating Our Pasts (1992), which describes traditional storytelling across Africa, or Patricia Turner’s I Heard It Through the Grapevine (1993), a major study of rumor in American black culture. A classic of the genre is Ronald Fraser’s Blood of Spain (1986), an oral history of the Spanish Civil War. Fraser argues that oral narratives are valuable as “straight” history, but that omissions and oversights and reworkings of historical consciousness also expose deeper currents of culture and politics. New historians view the oral tradition as a bond of narrative and memory that preserves traditions and identity. It serves as a kind of “kitchen-table” resistance to “official” history, as in Eastern Europe, China, and the Soviet Union. It may be a tool of cultural resistance for oppressed people—secret Jews, for example—or minorities and nationalities whose language has been banned in public and in print. This was the case with Catalan, Gallego, and Basque in Franco’s Spain, part of the caudillo’s campaign to abolish “dissident” political memory. This was also true of Kurdish in Turkey until 1991 (uses of Kurdish language and culture in other than folkloric fashion are still discouraged) and in East Timor following the Indonesian occupation in 197 5, as Jakarta has sought to undermine East Timor’s common indigenous tongue, Tetum. Ironically, use of Portuguese in East Timor has emerged as an everyday form of resistance against Indonesian domination. Oral history is perhaps the only way to grasp the horror of concentration camps, gulags, or prison cells, and even then it falls short of recapturing what really happened. Postmodernists take a broader view of art as historical and political artifact. The “opera-house” definition of culture succumbs to popular culture, at least the high/ low distinction is deemed artificial, or reality is a pastiche of the two. Fernand Braudel’s (1979) notion of “material civilization” is extended to encompass popular and populist traces. Slang, aphorism, jokes, film, newsreels, advertisements, graffiti,
152 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
street art, reggae, rap, or 1950s lounge music, as well as dime-store comics, tabloid newspapers, television sitcoms, video games, and other manifestations of “kitsch,” are all considered valid expressions of human experience and a suggestive archive of political culture. Stephen Whitfield’s Culture of the Cold War (1991), for example, argues that the cold war was sustained through the use of popular media. John Johnson’s Latin America in Caricature (1980) contends that United States public opinion and foreign policy toward Latin America were reduced, literally, to cartoons. Postmodernists suggest that these “tacky” images may reflect greater emotional appeal and political meaning than the prism of high politics. The historian Warren Susman wonders if “Mickey Mouse may in fact be more important to an understanding of the 1930s than Franklin Roosevelt” (quoted in Rosenau 1992:66). New history “privileges,” that is, pays special attention to or elevates, the local, the neglected, the inarticulate, the powerless. In theory, postmodernists reject privileging of any sort: all perspectives are equally valid. But in practice, they do privilege the oppressed in order to restore balance to a long tradition of heroic historical representation. New historians typically claim only to be telling stories, or describing rather than explaining. Yet, also in a positive way, the “polyvocality” of new history gives voice to previously muted and marginalized political actors, and is keenly attuned to popular groundswells of political change. The crisis of representation If new history no longer seems very new, that is because it has passed easily into the profession. Most historians today are probably doing one form or another of new history, or have been influenced by it. This is less the case with postmodernism’s more radical critiques. Postmodernists claim that history and time cannot be represented through conventional historical models. The so-called “crisis of representation” reflects postmodernists’ great interest in language and in “texts,” a term used to denote all human artifacts—cave paintings, buildings, literature, political oratory, film, foreign policy, etc. Most people will probably accept that language is an imperfect medium; it is impossible to represent reality without distortion. However, postmodernists reverse this relationship between reality and representation. Language is now said to produce a world of its own making. It does not convey reality, it constitutes reality. Postmodernists apply this critique to spoken and written texts, but also to texts in general. Hence the “linguistic turn” in virtually every field in the humanities and social sciences. All discourse — architectural, artistic, literary, political, historical, and so on—is subjugated to what Frederic Jameson (1972) called “the prison house of language.” Thus, amid “modern” debate about facts versus textual representations, or historical events versus historiography, the French philosopher Jacques Derrida intervenes to announce that there is no “outside-the-text”: “Il n’y a pas de hors-texte.” The world certainly exists independent of language. Derrida’s statement is usually understood to mean that our comprehension of things, nonetheless, is always
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 153
textualized, or cast in terms of language (see Callinicos 1995:3). Derrida uses the term différance to refer to the gap between a word (the signifier) and the thing to which it refers (the signified). He contends that no one-to-one correspondence exists between them. Expression is derivative, a copy or “simulacrum” of something else. Words contain traces of other words, images refer to other, similar images. These never convey clear meanings because there is no privileged spot from which a definitive meaning can be ascribed. There will always be gaps between what an author intends to say, what he actually says, and what the reader understands. To make this clear, Derrida would write certain problematic words “sous rature” or “under erasure.” He would write a word, cross it out, then leave it on the page, still legible beneath his redaction. Derrida’s point was that words were necessary, yet inadequate for the tasks set for them (Sarup 1993:33). The larger point is that the structure of language collapses, taking truth with it. All debates are deemed “intertextual,” with no final resting point or resolution. The determination of thought by language leads to Roland Barthes’s widely reported “death of the author.” Barthes argues that any text is comprised of a “tissue of quotations drawn from the innumerable centres of culture” (quoted in Bertens 1995:7). Regardless of what the author intends, he or she remains a mouthpiece for language, culture, and context. Conversely, the readers of a text take on a heightened role. They no longer passively imbibe the author’s “message,” rather, they interpret a text according to their own cultural and mental markers. This is gibberish when contrasted to the liberal idea of history as an individual creation. Even Oakeshott claimed that history was “the historian’s experience” and no one else’s. The view of history as a linguistic and cultural construction meshes neatly, however, with pre-modern notions of history as story. The storyteller, troubadour, balladeer, and saga writer convey traditional, collective knowledge. They do not claim ownership of the narrative, nor do they claim to be telling the truth as measured against some external standard. The liberal idea of the author as a unique, copyrightable voice would appear much later (along with what Harold Bloom called the “anxiety of influence,” that the authors’ ideas are not their own). History as politics Michel Foucault lends a sharp political edge to constructed knowledge. Foucault is a consummate reductionist in his political theory. He views not merely all politics, but all knowledge, in terms of power and domination. This is the power/knowledge (pouvoir-savoir) construct noted earlier. Foucault rejects the juridical and institutional study of power in favor of analysis of the techniques and tactics of domination. Mitchell Dean (1994:152) felicitously calls this the “anti-Leviathan” approach to power. Foucault contends that the creation and transmission of knowledge is regulated by the episteme of the era. Episteme governs discourse, by setting the boundaries to how people think, talk, and act. In turn, “discursivity” engenders a “regime” of truth, “linked in a circular relation with systems of power which produce and sustain it” (Foucault: 1980: 131–3). Thus, the crisis of
154 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
representation is acutely political. The will to power is transubstantiated into a “will to knowledge” (la volonté de savoir). Theory is practice, part of the workings of power and domination. The definitions and methods of knowledge are at the center of the permanent coercions that keep “bodies docile.” This is especiaily true of “theoretical” history, i.e., accounts in which a theoretical lens will “filter, hierarchise, and order” knowledge (ibid.: 83). In his own “historical” work, Foucault carries out what he first termed “archae ology” and later “genealogy,” an approach associated with Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals (1887). Genealogy is a “history of the present.” It illumines the conditions and rituals of power. Genealogy does not claim to have discerned the true meaning of the past, nor does it aim to present a complete picture of the past. By confining itself to the present, genealogy intends to avoid the dead end of trying to represent events bound up in past, and hence inaccessible, discursive archives. Genealogy is not so much an historical method as it is a sustained assault on the philosophical approach to history. Far from rejecting history, Foucault claims that genealogy demands “relentless erudition,” “patience and a knowledge of details,” and “a vast accumulation of source material” (Foucault 1984:76–7). In short, it requires more history and less theory. Still, its aim is to destroy the idea of history as stable or monotonous or unfolding according to some transcendental plan. Fittingly, Foucault’s discussion of genealogy streams forth in the language of dissolution: “divergence,” “marginalism,” “dissociation,” “disintegration,” “selfdestruction,” “inconstancy,” “dismantling,” “decadence,” “singularity,” “inaccuracy,” “impermanence.” As this outpouring of skepticism washes over traditional history, it reveals that knowledge is a matter of perspective. “We want historians to confirm our belief that the present rests upon profound intentions and immutable necessities. But the true historical sense confirms our existence among countless lost events, without a landmark or a point of reference” (ibid.: 89). History as literature Derrida and Foucault generally see history as a branch of politics. Hayden White, a prominent historiographic theorist, argues that history is a branch of literature, though certainly with political and ideological colorations. Treating history as literature in style and/or content is not new. Many dissident (i.e., non-Rankean) nineteenth-century historians, particularly Anglo-Saxon ones, wrote popular histories in novelistic form. Thomas Babington Macaulay, the doyen of these literary historians, once noted that “facts are but the dross of history,” and his own work often fell afoul of those facts. Arthur Marwick (1970:51–2) recounts a wonderful passage in Macaulay’s History of England (1848–55) in which William III bids farewell to the States of Holland before setting out for Britain. Macaulay writes: “In all that grave senate there was none who could refrain from shedding tears. But the iron stoicism of William never gave way; and he stood among his weeping friends calm and austere, as if he had been about to leave them only for a short visit to his hunting-grounds at Loo.” This is, in fact, a direct plagiarism from the
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 155
Odes of Horace, describing Regulus making his farewell to the Senate. The imitation may be conscious or unconscious, and we do not know the king’s actual state of calm or austerity, but this compelling, classical image adheres to the historian’s as well as the reader’s imagination. For White, this is how all history works. He argues that we must treat “historical work as what it most manifestly is: a verbal structure in the form of a narrative prose discourse” (quoted in Jenkins 1995:146).3 The historian uncovers certain facts, but when it comes to plot, he employs a repertoire of culturally specific literary conventions. The historian is a vessel for literary and rhetorical culture. White is interested in telling the truth about history, but he claims that beyond isolated facts there is no truth to tell. History has neither rhyme nor reason. Whether the historian is aware of it or not, these literary models alone infuse history with meaning. As soon as the historian steps beyond the mere recital of structured facts in the form of annals or chronology, he is, to use a Derridean word, signifying. All plots become metaplots. Author and reader turn to the devices of literature in order to grasp what is, in fact, a chaos of singular events. White steps beyond earlier constructionist assertions to elaborate a scheme by which history drifts into literature.4 He argues that historical artifacts are first selected and arranged from the “unprocessed historical record” into a chronicle that pinpoints a beginning and an end. The historian then fashions a “primitive” story, adopting a “hierarchy of significance” that assigns priorities and chains of causation. This stage in historical construction entails a measure of invention and interpretation on the historian’s part, and is drawn to suit his intended audience. The account is then sharpened by formal historical explanations according to the conventions of argument, emplotment, and ideology. By emplotment, White means a culturally resonant and recognizable meaning that is produced and then encoded into the story; he contends that in all history this mythos takes one of four forms: romance, comedy, tragedy, or satire. As for ideology, White holds that “every history is attended by specifically determinable ideological implications,” and he lists four: anarchical, conservative, radical, and liberal. He adds a final twist in the form of tropes, or figurative uses of language. White again points to four: metaphor, metonymy (substituting for the name of a thing the name of an attribute of it), synecdoche (using a more comprehensive term in place of a less comprehensive one), and irony. These are, respectively, representational, reductionist, integrative, and negational in their usage. Tropes are significant for White because he believes that “direct,” corresponding language is inadequate to recount what really happened. Instead, the historian must circle around the subject, identifying things by reference to other things, incorporating singular events into broader categories or reducing them into manageable parts, or, in the case of irony, explaining through opposition. The way in which this rhetorical recipe is “cooked up” produces the historian’s signature style. But in the end, the explanatory effect is the same as that of a poem or novel. White’s taxonomy may come across as Procrustean and maddeningly linguistic. Still, the idea of culturally specific story lines should not be dismissed.
156 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
Such icons allow us to imagine a reality that is whole and complete. A number of other iconic scripts leap to mind: paradise lost, pride goeth before the fall, Athens and Sparta, the Bildungsroman, the cautionary tale, vanquished villains, and tales of redemption, to mention a few Western standards that might guide political explanations. Hayward Alker, a (modern) micro-structuralist, suggests that “mythopoetic” or “moral-ideological” narratives are imbedded in all social science paradigms and theoretical traditions (Alker 1996:270–2). Thucydides, for example, may be read as a morality play in which the gods castigate Athens for her hubris. Malthusians prophesy damnation in the form of subsistence wages to check the prolificity of the laboring classes. Marxists offer earthly salvation. Stories may be far more complex as well. But, like fairy tales, they still adhere to definite scripts, which may be formally analyzed using scriptural hermeneutics, grammatical reconstructions, plot summaries, and other models. (See also Suganami 1997.) Although most interest in the literary aspects of political theory is animated by Lyotardian skepticism toward metanarratives, it is possible that “culturally resonant” stories may exhibit patterns across cultures, and that these may be amenable to formalization. Citing Jonathan Culler, Alker (ibid.: 173) foresees research related to cross-cultural “essences” in terms of the norms and expectations that infuse all literary texts. These and other literary aspects of historical narrative are not lost on historians. Norman Davies, Richard Price, Golo Mann, Simon Schama, and other working historians have experimented with different ways of couching narrative, writing history backwards, introducing heteroglossia in the text, and engaging a variety of fictional forms (see Burke 1992b). Though no postmodernist, Schama has taken to writing what he terms “historical novellas,” which, he says, “while they may at times appear to observe the discursive conventions of history,” are in part, “pure inventions, based, however, on what documents suggest” (quoted in Callinicos 1995: 3). Other experiments further blur the line between fiction as history, as historiography edges toward the “non-fiction novels” of Truman Capote or Norman Mailer. The distinguished historian William McNeill, a devotee of Toynbee and defender of world history, argues that history must reach the mythical plane in order to make intelligible the “elastic, inexact character of truth, especially truth about human conduct” (McNeill 1986:7). On a related front, some postmodernists see no reason that the disjointed nature of reality should not be reflected in a more fragmentary approach to history (Burke 1992b: 237–8). History may read like Yeats, Joyce, Kafka, Faulkner, Huxley, García Marquez, or Rushdie. Some argue that literary pastiche or filmic montage, which edit chronology and image sequence, may offer a better likeness of reality than traditional writings. Faulkner, who wrote fragmented stories about history and memory in the American South, once noted that the past is constantly with us; it is not even past. García Marquez has argued that shifting images and broken time of “magical realism” may seem fantastical to the rational European mind, but they are the everyday reality in Latin America.
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 157
History as commodity Finally, a word is in order about Lyotard’s (1984) notion of “commodity culture” as it relates to history and historiography and what is sometimes called the “heritage industry.” For Lyotard, knowledge is commodified and mercantilized, reaching a fever pitch in the “computer society.” This leads to a not very flattering view of what historians typically do. Historical bestsellers tap into current consumer political and aesthetic tastes, seek out market niches, and avail themselves of the retailing ploys of book clubs. Museum curators make a spectacle of the past, violently squeezing history into thematic exhibitions that target audience appeal and boost gift shop sales. University historians and political scientists embrace academic fads and succumb to institutional and political demands. Edward Said (1979:295–300), for example, contends that historical representation of the Orient was shaped by European academics, and later by elites in the American State Department and defense establishment, the RAND Corporation, the Middle East Studies Association and other politically privileged cadres. No doubt there is some hyperbole here. Postmodernists may be working on Nietzsche’s bon mot that truth inheres only in the exaggerations. Yet, as someone who has lived in the Near East and has had some opportunity to compare its reality with its “otherly” representation, Said’s thesis, in any case, does not seem so outlandish to me. Patrick Joyce has argued that “the major advance of ‘postmodernism’ needs to be registered by historians: namely that the events, structures and processes of the past are indistinguishable from the forms of documentary representation, the conceptual and political appropriations, and the historical discourses that construct them” (quoted in Callinicos 1995). Students of politics should also take note. A promising trend in each of the postmodernist critiques explored here is that the politics of historical representation are ripe for “deconstruction.” For Derrida, deconstruction meant attempting to hoist a text on its own petard by revealing ways in which the author’s words are employed inconsistently and paradoxically. But deconstruction can also simply mean exposing political motives and ideologies. Postmodernists are clear that discourse involves strategy; people have “projects,” a term usually used unflatteringly to describe advocacy that is concealed in language and method. Whatever one decides to call it, dismantling ideological biases (and laying bare what is privileged and what is censored), is a form of sound and affirmative historical inquiry. Shifting explanations We have seen that postmodernists view history as perspective with politics. There is no single, objective reality, but rather a multiplicity of experiences, some of which have achieved “privileged” status, typically because they benefit established interests. The resultant “hegemonic discourse” is a disguised system of control and domination that legitimates and safeguards its own favored status. This broadened intellectual and historical ambit elicits new forms of political analysis and
158 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
explanation. It also points to a kind of subterranean history of possibilities. As Richard Ashley notes (1989:33), historical narratives privilege “one or another subject as the sovereign center, the ultimate origin and register of truth and meaning, in whose terms all else must be interpreted.” Here I set out briefly several postmodernist reformulations of international theory that rest upon this “problematized” understanding of history. I focus on shifting views of power, critiques of the anarchy/ sovereignty problem, strategies of “counter-memory,” foreign policy as identity politics, radical views of time and space, and an emerging pastiche theory of globalism. Decentering power Foucault argues that one of the great failings of political theory is its fixation upon the person of the sovereign. “We need to cut off the King’s head; in political theory that has still to be done” (Foucault 1980:121). Postmodernists in international relations follow suit, rejecting the “juridicalpolitical” theory of sovereignty and removing the analysis of power (and there is a great deal of emphasis on power) from the center to the margins — from the head, as it were, to the extremities of the body politic, thus connecting with the political actors whose stories new historians recount. In this “decentered” analysis, identities and boundaries are constantly in motion. The rituals of power are now played out everywhere, on the factory floor, in the office, within families, in the structure of institutions, in language itself. Richard Ashley and R.B.J.Walker argue that decenteredness is increasingly the condition of everyday global life: “narratives of knowing and doing intersect in mutually destabilizing ways, contingency threatens to displace necessity, the very identity of the subject is put in doubt, and human beings live and toil as exiles, deprived of any absolute territory of being to call home.” They point to working mothers torn between home and career; draft-age youths who see themselves as cosmopolitan, yet are expected to take up arms in the name of national security; “foreign” workers who find themselves suspended between two different cultures and jurisdictions, belonging fully to neither; journalists who must make impossible distinctions between domestic, international, environmental, economic, sports, and fashion news; businessmen torn between traditional identity and the identity of the marketplace; peace activists dissatisfied equally with nationalist and universalist rhetoric (Ashley and Walker 1990b: 260–1). Each of these experiences chips away at that great signifier of international relations, state sovereignty. These are experiences of exile. Rocked from its narrative foundations, life becomes ambiguous, paradoxical, and deterritorialized. Identities, loyalties, and values span cultures and continents, or fall in the interstices of sovereign space. Ashley and Walker argue that one can no longer speak of rational individuals whose identities are given, and whose interests coincide with those of their compatriots. The postmodern condition throws shared moral principles into doubt, jeopardizes social norms, and fragments common sense. Citing the Bulgarian-French
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 159
psychoanalyst and cultural theorist Julia Kristeva, they suggest that exile leads to dissidence. Estrangement from the certain truths of modernity creates a space in which one can think and act outside of the forms of knowledge imposed by essentialist narratives. This leads in turn to new ways of power and resistance, as people confront “a diversity of representational practices that would traverse them, claim their time, control their space and their bodies, impose limitations on what can be said and done, and decide their beings” (ibid.: 261). As the sovereign state recedes, new complexities and identities emerge. This type of discourse undercuts the “naturalness” of sovereignty and the concomitant “fact of anarchy.” Here, postmodernists are up against a formidable tradition of Western political philosophy that has “reified” the nation-state, mentally fashioning it into a “real” thing. Anarchy as well as its remedies, notably the “domestic analogy,” are said to be rooted in caricaturized Hobbesian, Kantian, and Grotian representations of reality. In the section on counter-memory that follows, we will see how postmodernists seek to expose the disjunction and incoherence of this “tradition.” In terms of contemporary international relations, Ashley argues that (especially North American) discourse has been “disciplined” by the twin assumptions of anarchy and sovereignty. To be considered a “serious thinker” in this milieu, one must pose questions that in one sense or another address the “anarchy problématique.” This applies equally to theorists of realism, liberalism, world order, economic interdependence, international cooperation, international institutions, and so forth. Each understands the world in terms of the absence of a global Leviathan and the presence of a multiplicity of sovereign states. Each locates the sovereign state at the heart of personal analysis, ignoring other historical and potential forms of social organization (Ashley 1995: 95–6). Even the appellation “international relations” is laden with these assumptions. Ashley contends that sovereignty is an “heroic practice,” another Foucaultian idea. Sovereignty is said to be “double-voiced,” that is, it turns on a dichotomy, in this case on the opposition of sovereignty versus anarchy, with sovereignty privileged as the regulative ideal. In one voice, this heroic practice holds out sovereignty as representing resolution, meaning, security, domesticity, and truth. In another, it invokes the perils of anarchy, “a fearsome time and place of ambiguity, contingency, and chance,” where truth is contested and power is arbitrary (ibid.: 103). Posed in this either-or fashion, sovereignty becomes the natural and necessary antidote to the absence of knowledge and authority—an absence modernity cannot tolerate. Ashley describes this as a discourse of domestication, a foundation for universal truth and security within its domain. Modern sovereignty also domesticates the wilds of history. For Ashley, modernity denotes a “disposition to privilege some historically imposed limitations of human knowing and doing as essential to ‘reasoning man’s’ sovereign being and, as such, as the already present transcendental foundation and source of humans’ capacities for the autonomous use of reason in history” (ibid.: 99–100). The strategy of the modern sovereign is to “enclose history,” to mark contingency and ambiguity as deviant and fearsome, and thus to discipline historical “indeterminacy and
160 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
equivocity…to impose boundaries and ‘domesticate’ the chance, contingency, and ambiguity of a pluralistic history” (ibid.: 102). The success of sovereign interpretations of history, i.e., of reifying the nation-state teleology, is not based on repression, nor is it beholden to classical or Christian conceptions of divine reason. Instead, sovereignty is uttered by the anthropocentric voice of modernity. The weight of historical contingency and not knowing bears down on “reasoning man.” He relents, believing that he is mastering his own historical contingency by acknowledging power and truth as mediated by the sovereign state. Postmodernists argue as well that when political identity is bundled with sovereignty, identity is reduced to a sense of place, to the “flat Euclidean spaces of modernity” (Walker 1993:176). The modern mind (and state), with its penchant for fixity in categories, systematically excludes other forms of social organization and other axes of identity such as culture, class, race, and gender. In the international context, fixed geography is said also to privilege spatial conceptions of identity (identity as loyalty to place) over temporal ones (identity as tradition or shared history). Postmodernists emphasize that the emergence of the Westphalian system was an historically specific pattern of political differentiation. A new canon of diplomacy and law restructured political space, curtailing medieval forms of divided sovereignty, of overlapping and crosscutting loyalties where localism and universalism coexist (ibid.: 117). Universalism is now pursued within the bounds of the sovereign state. In this context, identity and difference become another heroic, binary practice with its rituals of inclusion and exclusion. Postmodernists regard these absolutist boundaries as obsolete. What is needed in theory and practice is a shift away from international politics toward a global politics that recognizes exile space and dissident identities. Counter-memory Postmodernists define “memory” and “counter-memory” as opposed historical strategies for reading a text. Memorialization is said to encase history in an “originary” past, where ambiguities and uncertainties are forgotten. This memorialized past then serves to “ground” modern disciplinary thought and political practice. Counter-memorialization, by contrast, contests this iconic, foundational reading of history. It resists the “politics of forgetting” and seeks to retain the ambiguities and complexities of the history of any discipline and the classic texts that anchor it. Memorial history fixes the past along neat dichotomous markers that impose discipline and order on an ambiguous and chaotic past. It papers over paradox, ambiguity, and uncertainty. Instead, it attributes a high degree of coherence to a text as well as a central logic—a plot, White would say—of crisis overcome and ambiguity resolved. A text is thus easily summarized and caricaturized, its basic themes encapsulated and enumerated (Ashley and Walker 1990a: 384). Through catechistic invocation, these themes become the substructure of paradigm and tradition. Ultimately, they transmute a contextual, temporal historical construction
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 161
into a powerful myth of origin. As Walker (1993:27) argues, “Other points of departure are rendered trivial or even unthinkable. The highly problematic character of claims about origins, continuities, teleologies, progressions and ruptures is conveniently forgotten.” Counter-memorialized readings of history refuse to repeat this “willful amnesia,” instead approaching “settled,” “classic” texts as “openly contested cultural terrain,” and analyzing “afresh the ways in which classic texts contend with ambiguity, uncertainty, and resistant counterinterpretations.” Like genealogy, counter-memory is said to require more history, not less. It is conceived as an exercise in fealty toward texts: honoring detail, specificity, and context, and retaining intended paradoxes and crises of interpretation. This is another tactic to problematize essentialist interpretation, but it is more than that, it is a joyous reading of a problematic past. Counter-memory aims “to enrich not diminish, the cultural resources of a discipline, community, or culture…to appreciate the intrinsic ambiguity, uncertainty, irony, and recombinatorial possibilities of its own textual inheritance” (Ashley and Walker 1990a: 385). Postmodernists are not unique in this, but they do face the task with greater irreverence (and joy) than the typical historian of political thought. It also bears mentioning that international theory is full of cracks into which to drive this wedge. Critics have long held that students of international politics are licentious in their use of the classics. Michael Donelan (1990:42) observes that political philosophers often become mere “ventriloquists’ dummies” in the hands of their modern international relations manipulators. Walker asserts precisely this in his counter-memorializing deconstruction of Machiavelli as the foundation for traditional international relations. Walker argues that modern theories of international relations express assumptions about political community that crystallized in the early modern period, with Machiavelli and his conception of lo stato as expounded in The Prince at the roots of “a tradition, an origin, a code, a centre, a home from which one can set out to explore the contingencies and transformations of the world outside” (Walker 1993:44). Walker contends that an originary reading of Machiavelli caricatures a complex mind as well as a complex time. Immunized from critical analysis, Machiavelli becomes the legal and geopolitical expression of sovereignty, an “ahistorical apology for the violence of the present” (ibid.: 31). Blind acceptance of this tradition in turn debars us from fundamentally confronting the narratives by which the state bestows legitimacy on its power apparatus. A counter-memorializing reading attempts to limn the Florentine’s “historical moment” of cultural and religious ferment on the cusp of modernity. Countermemory opens up connections to Machiavelli’s other works, The Discourses, The History of Florence, and The Art of War. These texts are then seen for what they are: feints and thrusts in the wide-ranging negotiations among Machiavelli, Savonarola, Guicciardini, and others about the character of civic humanism, political legitimacy, political ethics, the roots of identity, and the role of the church (Ashley and Walker 1990a: 386). This fuels a more searching and unsettled depiction of Machiavelli as a voice of crisis rather than essence. The point is that the “tradition”
162 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
of international relations is not, in fact, rooted in a fixed historical marker of power and authority. Ashley and Walker suggest that the same sort of historicism holds for Hobbes, Rousseau, Bentham, Marx, Kant, Weber, and so on. All the pillars of the tradition “emerge and reply to historical circumstances where margins widen, ambiguity and chance seem to undermine every certain referent, temporality seems to displace every extratemporal standpoint” (ibid.: 383). Historicizing identity The finest example of the new historicism in international relations is David Campbell’s Writing Security (1992). Amid orthodox, revisionist, post-revisionist, and “joint-venture” interpretations of the cold war, Campbell casts American foreign policy in a fresh light. He places security at the heart of identity politics. He argues that, historically, global threats have been interpreted in ways that define domesticity and foreignness. United States foreign policy has represented the “other” as a way of creating and controlling American identity. Like Ashley and Walker, Campbell sees the production of identity as a way of mastering geopolitical ambiguity. He suggests that the Hobbesian conception of anarchy rests on a stylized history, in which one form of social organization and identity (the church) is supplanted by another (the state) at a clear juncture (Westphalia). A nuanced reading of history will appreciate the coeval emergence of states and the international system. This leads Campbell to a different conception of foreign policy: Foreign policy shifts from a concern of relations between states which takes place across ahistorical, frozen and pregiven boundaries, to a concern with the establishment of the boundaries that constitute, at one and the same time, the “state” and the “international system.” Conceptualized in this way, foreign policy comes to be seen as a political practice that makes “foreign” certain events and actors… The construction of the “foreign” is made possible by practices that also constitute the “domestic.” In other words, foreign policy is “a specific sort of boundary-producing political performance.” (ibid.: 69) In this context, Campbell argues that the “constant articulation of danger through foreign policy is…not a threat to a state’s identity or existence; it is its condition of possibility” (ibid.: 12). The national security estate identifies and interprets threats so as to create and maintain a consensus about security. Crisis becomes a permanent part of the cultural terrain. Threats enforce closure on the community at risk; they set the behavioral and normative boundaries of the community being protected. In this way, identity is constituted in opposition to “foreign” threats. Unlike essentialist or materialist views of security, this approach is antifoundational. National interests and security are not founded on anything. They are highly arbitrary, resting solely on imagination, interpretation, and rituals of
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 163
inclusion and exclusion. Campbell believes this is especiaily true of the United States, which he calls the imagined community par excellence. “There has never been a country called ‘America,’ nor a people known as ‘Americans’ from whom a national identity is drawn… Defined therefore more by absence than presence, America is peculiarly dependent upon representational practices for its being. Arguably more than any other state, the imprecise process of imagination is what constitutes American identity” (ibid.: 105). Campbell supports his claim with extensive use of foreign policy “texts” drawn from American political and cultural history. He argues that civilization and barbarism was the leading trope of eighteenth-century boundary building. America is said to have imagined itself in moralistic opposition to the primitive “Old World,” and later through the myth of the frontier, which created boundaries against “Indians” and, within its borders, “Africans.” In the nineteenth century, the image of civilization and barbarism was replaced by the metaphor of the normal and the pathological. Campbell points to the proliferation of medical language framing foreign policy texts of the period. Political elites used the “trope of the body” in order to define the moral and physical space of identity. The “other” was described in terms of disease, infection, cancer, epidemic, madness, and so on, while foreign policy pronouncements cited dangers of degeneration, miscegenation, and decay. (This discourse parallels broader nineteenth-century cultural trends linked to ideas about evolution, eugenics, sociology, anthropology, etc. In their infancy, the “human sciences” lent themselves to a number of dubious social projects, particularly the policing of race.5) For Campbell, such “socio-medical discourse” served to regulate American political hygiene. It rendered threats in bodily form, and invoked the authority of diagnostic nomenclature as well as the necessity for often-invasive intervention. Now the health and security of the patient depended on the specialized knowledge of “national security managers” (ibid.: 96). For Campbell, this is the tradition of social purity in which Kennan described the “malignant parasite” of communism, and Ronald Reagan responded to the 1985 hijacking of a TWA aircraft in Beirut by claiming that no nation was “immune” from terrorism: “If we permit it to succeed anywhere it will spread like a cancer, eating away at civilized societies and sowing fear and chaos everywhere.” “In such discourse,” Campbell notes, “there are no gray areas, no complexities, no historicized understandings, no doubts about the self, and no qualms about the nature of the response” (ibid.: 97). The cold war extended this “geography of evil” as a way of scripting American identity (ibid.: 143). The “red scare” followed an American pattern of what Campbell calls the “apocalyptic mode” of statecraft, in which exorbitant fears are used to quell dissidence and prescribe action against impending disaster (ibid.: 153). Campbell highlights the “quasi-puritan” sermons shaping from on high the discourse of the cold war. Through the florid preaching of NSC directives, the Security State set out to displace God as the object of ultimate loyalty. War became domestic politics by other means. The security community turned on the enemy within, tilling the soil for McCarthyism. Campbell’s recounting of the loyalty-
164 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
security programs of 1947–57 is enough to make one’s skin crawl. His discussion of the cultural crisis of the 1960s is also compelling. Campbell argues that rational assessments of the cold war fail to grasp the motivations behind these policies. He contends that world communism, the economic collapse of Europe, Red China, North Vietnam, Cuba, Nicaragua, Libya, etc. never posed a threat in terms of traditional calculations of military power. They were dangerous because of their “proclivity for anarchy and disorder” (ibid.: 32). Policing these threats was a way of policing America’s image of itself. Enmity toward communism and the Soviet Union functioned as a code for the inscription of boundaries. Through “a series of ritualized performances…the figuration of difference as otherness in the cold war rendered a contingent identity (‘the West,’ ‘America,’ et al.) secure” (ibid.: 195). How will the United States maintain difference and identity in an increasingly interdependent and homogenized world? Campbell argues that the war on drugs during the Reagan and Bush (and now Clinton) administrations has parroted the fear-mongering script of the cold war, citing the “clear and present danger” to sovereignty, security, authority, families, values, children, and so on. The drug war has also been openly militarist in imagery and language, with talk of offensives, eradication, and boot camps; it has in fact been militarized along US borders and in the Andean campaign to staunch the supply of cocaine. Campbell argues that McCarthyist drug testing was just one of a number of hysterical erosions of civil rights in the effort to ferret out this particular un-American activity. He contends that “drug profiles” were reinvented stereotypes rooted in a long tradition of linking drug use to psychological, sexual, and political deviants, and of pegging minorities and “foreign” ethnics as habitual abusers. Turning to another branch of political economy, Campbell looks at how Japan has been depicted at a time when the boundary between domestic and foreign industry is increasingly blurred. He cites a revisionist trend in academic discussions of “the Japan problem” that emphasizes what Steven Schlossstein calls the United States’s “dark side” of “racism, insularity, arrogance, narrowness, and resentment” (ibid.: 228). This is paralleled in the economic press’s depiction of Japan “buying up” America in the 1980s, even though Japan’s share of total foreign assets in the US remained fairly steady during the period (and lagged behind the percentage held by the Netherlands and Britain). Villainous portrayals of Japanese people in advertisements and in popular fiction and movies further darkened American perceptions of Japan. Campbell argues these “texts,” like the “deviance” attached to drug use, delimit everything that America is not, thus again negatively defining American identity. This fascinating thesis raises a number of questions: Is identity constituted chiefly in relation to difference? It seems one could construct an affirmative theory of identity as well. To what extent is identity molded by elite pronouncements? At times, one wonders if Campbell does not bend the evidence to his thesis. Some of his claims seem to parallel the colorful oratory from the likes of Billy Graham, J.Edgar Hoover, and Strom Thurmond that Campbell favors as evidence. Occasionally, a throwaway line by a cabinet member or political appointee will be portrayed as firm identity policy. Is the construction of identity as top-down as this
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 165
model suggests? Who is scripting whom? During the McCarthy period, and certainly during the 1960s, there was a great deal of dissent against elite “scripts.” Likewise, anti-drug diktats by the Reagan and Bush administrations resonated with many Americans, but a great many others found Ronald (and Nancy) Reagan’s “just say no” campaign ludicrous. Linguistic deconstructions are probably more likely than reserved historiography to fall in this trap of rhetoric. Interestingly, Writing Security claims to be a genealogy, not a history. Campbell states at the outset that other, valid interpretations of American foreign policy are possible. Nevertheless, like many postmodernist works, the book presents evidence and argument in relatively traditional form. And while the book’s claims are not posed as necessarily true, they are presented with greater solidity than one might expect. Disrupting time and space While modernists follow a rational, orderly conception of space and time, postmodernists emphasize discontinuity, historical “moments,” bursts of insight, and spatial fragmentation. Some postmodernists take the idea of past, present, and future to be egocentric and presentist. They aim to remove contemporary man from the position at the center of history he has held since the Renaissance. Others reject “chronophonism,” the assumption that time is linear or chronological. A cyclical, random, or erratic vision of time may be equally engaging; or it is possible to think of time as spherical, with the present drifting between horizons of past and future. Unsurprisingly, this departure from linearity engenders skepticism about modern notions of cause and effect. Postmodern analysis casts occurrences in terms of contingency, discontinuity, complexity, and intertextuality. Events are essentially authorless. Everything is related to everything else; it is impossible to isolate causes or “heroic” agents. It can be tyrannical, even, to suggest that certain inputs produce a certain outcome (Rosenau 1992:32–3). Postmodernists reconceptualize space as well. They attempt to undo the Age of Discovery view of the world as a finite, mappable entity that can be integrated into a universal body of knowledge. David Harvey argues that modern geography rests on an “outside” perspective honed in the art of the Renaissance. He argues that modern mapmaking creates a “seeing eye” that hovers above the earth, a perspective that is privileged as authentic and scientific despite its distance from the human mind. This “outside” cartography departed radically from medieval ideas about the relationship between people and place, and was instrumental in locating people in sovereign space by clarifying and controlling boundaries, property, identity, and an array of other spatial practices (Harvey 1990:242–4). Postmodernists reject this systematically fixed view of the world. They consider boundaries fluid, mental constructs, and deem the local space of traditional communities more authentic than scientific geography. In the postmodern concept of “hyperspace,” geography collapses altogether. Space is no longer fixed; all places are in flux. What does this mean for world politics? In one take on the contemporary scene, Jean Baudrillard pessimistically calls history “a catastrophic process of recurrence
166 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
and turbulence.” There is nothing new under the sun in the form of original or unique events. Instead, history is an “immense simulation model,” in which politics recycles leftover ideologies and images of conflict (Baudrillard 1994:7, 11). Baudrillard suggests that the dissolution of empires, for example, results in recycled microhistories: micro-imperia, micro-dictatorships, micro-autarkies, and so forth. Like the shards of a shattered mirror, each reflects the polity from which it was dispersed. Baudrillard also applies this idea of recycled imagery and virtuality to the Gulf War. He declares that the Gulf War was only imagery, a “quasi-unreal event,” an “orgy of simulation,” stripped of authenticity and meaning. He argues that the war followed a second-hand script, hatched during the cold war, that could be played out without the use of nuclear weapons only after the collapse of the Soviet Union. The war’s virtuality was driven by the media as well. It was not simply conveyed by television, but was made by televi sion. The war was a spectacle of imagery, laden with manipulative “anticipation of effects, morbid simulations, [and] emotional blackmail,” and consumed by a public “overexposed to the media, underexposed to memory” (Baudrillard 1994:62–3). Postmodern ideas about “synchronism” and “diachronism” (single-time and dualtime) are especially germane to development studies. Postmodernists typically adopt the diachronic view that traditional cultures are not lagging behind modern ones, but instead are following their own calendars. This makes for a less egocentric view of non-Western societies and an almost ethnological interest in cultural dignity. Here, postmodernists, perhaps more than other theorists, cut through the familiar forms of liberalism to appreciate differences in politics and culture. Although synchronism by other names has long been the bane of modernization theory, postmodern critiques are particularly acute, extending beyond the fallacy of mechanistic development in their expression of contempt for the blind teleology and “outside” benchmarks of moral and material status of the development ethos. Postmodernists also turn modernization back on the industrialized world, where productive capitalism is thought to trap people in a mechanical, “time-clock” regime (Harvey 1990: 226–39). Postmodernists also offer cogent explanations for civil and ethnic strife based on the fragmentation of time within states and societies. In Israel, for example, a Biblical past coexists uneasily with a modern state. In the political geography of Africa, a modern statist narrative arbitrarily overlays a tribal one. During the prelude to the war in Yugoslavia, Serbian nationalist texts “centered” the Battle of Kosovo Field, in which Ottoman troops routed Serbian forces, and laid claim to their Balkan empire. The fact that Kosovo Field took place in 1389 did little to diminish its evocative reality in this late twentieth-century ethnic cauldron. Some Serbs still refer pejoratively to Bosnian Muslims as “Turks.” Serbian defendants at the Yugoslav war crimes tribunal in The Hague have founded their defenses on historic fears of Muslim persecution. Such atavistic uses of history and memory suggest that social groups may be forever haunted by their past. However, postmodernists also make the case that people are not bound by history. The centrifuge of modernity has separated societies from their prior practices. Unlike realists (and Annalistes), who focus on the almost
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 167
geologic “slow-time” of social life, postmodernists are struck by the impermanence of social forms. “The transitoriness of things makes it difficult to preserve any sense of historical continuity,” argues Harvey (ibid.: 11). This lends plasticity to politics: states are protean, the international system is more ephemeral than modernists assume. Moreover, volatility in geopolitical and other commitments heightens insecurity. Lyotard (1984:66) sees a trend toward “creative turmoil,” in which “the temporary contract is in practice supplanting permanent institutions in the professional, emotional, sexual, cultural, family, and international domains, as well as in political affairs.” Paul Virilio’s Speed and Politics (1986) argues that contracting time and space accelerate military logistics to a permanent state of crisis management. James Der Derian’s Antidiplomacy: Spies, Terror, Speed, and War (1992) suggests that power is now more compelling in time than in space, that swiftness has become the greatest military comparative advantage. The lightning speed of unfolding events and communications also increases fears that “nothing takes place in real time. Not even history. History in real time is CNN, instant news, which is the exact opposite of history” (Baudrillard 1994:90). The rapidity and “imagification” of events may render obsolete modern modes of political deliberation and circumspect statecraft, particularly those rooted in the frozen time of the cold war. Postmodernists lock horns with Marxists over the question of historical laws, but when it comes to the effects of global capitalism the two are frequent allies. Marx and Engels wrote in The Communist Manifesto (1848) of the explosive effects of capitalism spurring the “canalization of rivers,” “the clearing of whole continents,” achieving “wonders far surpassing Egyptian pyramids, Roman aqueducts, and Gothic cathedrals.” The social and cultural dislocations of capitalism are even more striking: “All fixed, fast-frozen relations, with their train of ancient and venerable prejudices and opinions, are swept away, all new-formed ones become antiquated before they can ossify. All that is solid melts into air” (Marx and Engels 1991:738–9). Marx’s prediction that economics would ultimately turn on the economy of time also seems borne out in the compression of time and space of capital accumulation. Time is money, the expression goes. Today, capital is also radically deterritorialized. Transactions are instantaneous, occurring, as Marx envisioned, in “the twinkle of an eye.” Postmodernists echo this great critique of modern political economy, pointing to the socioeconomic implosions sweeping the “peripheral” world, and seeing the globalization of production for profit as a vast regime of social and political control. Central Asia, for instance, has been transformed in less than a decade from a backwater of the cold war to an epicenter of geo-economic rivalry, as vast oil supplies “commodify” the former Soviet republics. The juggernaut of Chinese “market-Leninism” may radically change the nature of that country’s society and politics. The economic collapse in Southeast Asia has seen domino theory recycled as “contagion theory”—the idea that if one country’s economy is permitted to implode, it could start an uncontrollable chain of events involving markets and investors around the globe (Sanger 1998).
168 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
Globalization and pastiche When Oliver Reiser coined the term “globalization” in Planetary Democracy (1944), he envisioned the process in unmistakably metanarrative form, as the “planetary synthesis of cultures” into a kind of universalistic humanism. This triumphalist tone resounds in neoliberal appraisals of globalization, both in terms of commerce and democracy. Postmodernists are not alone in decrying this way of thinking, nor in pointing out the ill effects of globalization, notably the bland homogeneity spurred by time-space compression and the diffusion of capitalist “technoculture,” a process that may suppress or even eradicate traditional identities (Scholte 1996: 48–9). However, unlike many critics and advocates, postmodernists do not view globalization as an inevitable, totalizing process. Rather, eclecticism replaces the master script of globalization. The contemporary landscape is seen as a pastiche of global, local, and hybrid cultures, as modernist narratives intersect with local history to create novel social complexities and configurations. Traditional cultures negotiate with global practices and norms, assimilating some easily, rejecting others, or producing hybrid forms in which global mores are tailored to local conditions. One sees this eclecticism in everyday dualities of shopping malls/farmers’ markets, storytelling/information highway, Fordism/flexible accumulation, global blockbusters/independent film-making, state agencies/NGOs, federalist movements/militia movements, and so forth. Postmodernists explore how these disparate scripts interact across different realms of society: Who profits from globalization? Do the benefits of globalism outweigh the violence done to traditional forms of economic exchange and political organization? Are benefits evenly distributed? How does globalization influence society and psychology? How to square the universalization of liberal democracy with the troubled welfare state? Importantly, postmodernists and other critical theorists argue that globalization entails more than these kinds of rationalistic and structural reforms: it also demands a degree of cultural amnesia, an erosion of history and memory, a forgetting of the old symbols and norms of authority, and an (arguably, forced) march into globalist terra incognita. Because globalization threatens identities and cultures, it may elicit indigenist or atavistic reactions. The revival of historical enmities—real or imagined—shores up identity, clarifying or reclarifying the “we” and the “they” in the face of global homogenization, anomie, and disempowerment. Folkways become a form of resistance, but so may protectionist, nationalist, racial, or ethnic appeals fuel a kind of renationalization and remercantilization. Harvey (1990:306) notes that “there are abundant signs that localism and nationalism have become stronger precisely because of the quest for the security that place always offers in the midst of all the shifting that flexible accumulation implies.” Zygmunt Bauman (1997:65) contends that globalization and tribalization are “close allies and fellow conspirators.” In this age of pastiche, an understanding of local history is perhaps more important than ever, particularly since both Marxism and modernization theory (and a great deal of international relations theory) discount the role of culture and
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 169
historical forms of political association (Kellner 1998:34). A monoperspective is gone. People live local lives in the shadow of global culture and capital, neither fully autonomous, nor fully members of universal civil society and economy. No longer can one speak of whole societies as “traditional” or “developing.” Countries move in different directions at once. Historical continuities coexist with modernization and change; novel forms do not necessarily signal a complete rupture with the past. Even developed states witness neo-Luddite movements, various fundamentalisms, “mininationalisms,” splintered identities, and localized violence. Local history is essential to appreciate the historic allure of nativism and to demystify mythistorical appeals. Amid this eclectic geography, borders—even within states—become increasingly poignant. Whether in Bosnia, Mexico, or Turkey, or in ASEAN, the EU, NATO, or NAFTA, questions of culture and identity are central to drawing boundaries. Again, local history illuminates these shifting and overlapping frontiers of identity. It is impossible to do full justice here to the impact of pastiche on the study of international politics. Suffice it to say that pastiche parallels a growing commitment to pluralism in the field, particularly as the discipline awakens to the social constructs underpinning politics. The title of Yosef Lapid and Friedrich Kratochwil’s volume, The Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory (1996) speaks for itself, as does that of Jill Krause and Neil Renwick’s collection of essays, Identities in International Relations (1996). Socially-based constructivist theory borrows heavily from postmodernist identity politics (Wendt 1992). Increasingly, one discerns twists of pastiche in “traditional” works as well, such as Fred Halliday’s Rethinking International Relations (1994), Anthony Smith’s Nations and Nationalism in a Global Era (1995), or Ian Clark’s Globalization and Fragmentation (1997). James Rosenau’s Along the Domestic-Foreign Frontier (1997:31) describes the ambivalence of contemporary politics in terms of “fragmegration” (a portmanteau word for fragmentation and integration). Rosenau argues that this emerging world view is marked by imaginary, fluid, or porous frontiers, a diversity of actors, issues, values, norms, practices, and global structures, and the centrality of “citizen skills” in taming a turbulent world. Conclusion Despite an alleged disdain for the past, postmodernists exhibit a broad interest in history and a salutary self-consciousness about the politics of historical representation. Disgruntlement with positivism and the assumptions that it entertains has led postmodernists to reassess what Rankean history has offered (and failed to offer) international relations, and to question the field’s canon of received historical verities. In this, postmodernism throws open doors for the mind, revealing new vistas, problems, and relationships. Nevertheless, linguistic, cultural, or contextual determinism is no better than any other form of determinism. Foucaultian postmodernism perhaps underappreciates people’s capacity for independent thought and action, and, when pursued to its
170 EXIT FROM HISTORY?
logical conclusion, ends in despair. By closely historicizing ideas and events, postmodernists threaten to immure them within a parti cular past. An unstinting belief in difference blinds theorists to parallels, analogies, and similarities that may, in fact, exist. One may also ask, how postmodern is it? Theorists of international politics who bear that appellation are invariably critical of high politics, but this is accompanied by a sense that local knowledge is the level of analysis with the richest payout. Even hardened postmodern epistemologists often accept nontraditional histories at face value, or report their own discoveries in a tone of belief reminiscent of Waltz discoursing on great-power strife. There is more than a vestige of positivism in the idea that marginalized historical actors offer a more authentic and fruitful archive than state papers or press conferences. Postmodernists may romanticize traditional resistance, much as cosmopolitans idealize the “global village.” Celebrations of, say, the Ogoni in Nigeria or the Zapatistas in Chiapas can fall into folkloric “otherness,” reducing indigenous peoples to anti-globalist icons. More importantly, there is a profoundly illiberal side to postmodernism that raises questions about the historical and political responsibilities of social theorists. Some versions of postmodernism reject the idea of shared humanity and universal norms of freedom, human rights, or international law. These beacons of hope fade into the mists of particular cultures. This is one of the reasons that critics have encouraged postmodernists to abandon the role of gadfly and contribute affirmatively to the field. Keohane (1988) has challenged postmodernists to propose and pursue a reflective research program of their own. Waltz, Mearsheimer, Holsti, and others have voiced similar admonishments from what postmodernists view as the comfortable cave of orthodoxy (Smith 1996:34). But there is a postmodern project that is looser, hipper, more localist than that of social scientists. Arguably, postpositivists are among the most activist theorists in the field. In place of structural sameness and scientific detachment, postmodernists assume a multiplicity of pragmatic truths, an idea akin to Aristotelian phronesis, or practical wisdom. While much of the reaction to globalism is vilified as atavistic, tribalist, or fundamentalist, for example, one may also see resistance to globalization as favoring a renewal of small-scale collective solidarities, which may or may not be tied to place (Scholte 1996:53). In this vein, Richard Rorty has explored a kind of anti-foundational communitarianism based not on belief in God or Reason, but on historic practices and affinities. Rorty notes, “If we give up this hope, we shall lose what Nietzsche called ‘metaphysical comfort,’ but we may gain a renewed sense of community. Our identification with our community—our society, our political institutions, our intellectual heritage —is heightened when we see this community as ours rather than nature’s, shaped rather than found, one among many which men have made…what matters is our loyalty to other human beings clinging together against the dark, not our hope of getting things right” (quoted in Novick 1988:541). Much, though certainly not all, of this project turns on a new vision of history, not as social science laboratory or gigantist narrative, but as a site of complexity and possibility. Hayden White submits a strategy for using history in a time of
HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 171
apparently history-less chaos, arguing that the crisis of representation frees us from the “terror of history”: Since the second half of the nineteenth century, history has become increasingly the refuge for all those “sane” men who excel at finding the simple in the complex and the familiar in the strange. This was all very well for an earlier age, but if the present generation needs anything at all it is a willingness to confront heroically the dynamic and disruptive forces in contemporary life. The historian serves no one well by constructing a specious continuity between the present world and that which preceded it. On the contrary, we require a history that will educate us to discontinuity more than ever before; for discontinuity, disruption, and chaos is our lot. (quoted in Jenkins 1995:144–5) It is hard to be a little postmodern. Nevertheless, postmodern insights increasingly find their way into “traditional” international thought. In Britain, Canada, and Australia, critical theorists have drawn epistemology to the center of the discipline in a way that underscores the narrowness of the field’s great (positivist) debates (Smith 1996). In the United States, there is a vigorous cadre of postmodernists, yet the mainstream seems intent on rescuing the discipline from them. A recent survey on history and international relations in the journal International Security aimed to defend diplomatic history, which is described as one of the few remaining outposts of “pre-postmodern” history (Elman and Elman 1997). Traditionalists fear that diplomatic history is being elbowed aside by politically correct “social history,” a pastiche of inference and artifice “uncoupled from objective evidence” (Haber et al. 1997: 40). The conceit of this argument is that it equates “objective” history with high political history, and suggests that broader social forces cannot be represented in a rigorous way, or else are trivial in their effects. One wonders if this is not the political equivalent of Matthew Arnold’s attempt, in Culture and Anarchy (1869), to defend Victorian high culture against the low-brow tide of “Barbarians, Philistines, and Populace.” The populist usurpation in international relations is perhaps less dire—and the views being defended less deserving—than they may seem. Serious scholarship can no longer shrug off concerns about the nature of evidence and the diversity of politics.
172
8 CONCLUSION History, skepticism, and the recovery of theory
This study has attempted to examine critically the historical assumptions, methods, and evidence underpinning a range of approaches to international politics. The relation between history and international relations is indeed deceptively simple. What are breezily thought of as “empirical” historical questions are to the skeptic’s eye a troublesome link in a science of international politics. Modern theorists attempt to transcend the ambiguities of political choices and a diversity of state practices and “bottom—up” politics. History is tidily packaged or transformed into data, then fitted to mechanical laws and economical explanations. Postmodern theorists view history with sharp skepticism, but nevertheless render historical and “genealogical” judgments that cut against the grain of Enlightenment political thought and practice. At the same time, the divide between history and international relations is not nearly as stark as it is often painted. History is a discipline in motion, and is not immune to theory. Historians would be at sea without models and concepts and narratives that lend coherence to the artifacts and, perhaps, intimate the stories they tell. Similarly, theory often parallels current political problems and historical structures. Rarely are history and theory distinct spheres overlapping, like a Venn diagram, only at the “testing” stage. “Theory” does not refer simply to abstraction, or “history” simply to the canvassing of a body of evidence. Moreover, the parallel development of the disciplines—from great-power narrative, systems analysis, cliometrics, populist appeals, and back to narrative—suggests that the historians and political scientists do, in fact, converse. The involution of international relations theory Nevertheless, theorists continue to rend from the historical record ever more ingenious explanations for international politics. In empirical war research alone we find “heretofore neglected variable” explanations hinging on prestige, trade expectations, environmental scarcity, ascendant power, descendant power, interdependence as a condition of peace, inter-dependence as a condition of war, strategic culture, power structures, threat structures, governance structures, social structures, regional security regimes, democracy, nationalism, culture, justice, religion, and civilization. The quest for parsimony encourages theorists to identify these sparse
174 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
models. Heedlessness toward the historical problem seals their success. It appears not to hinder one’s career if one’s theoretical claims are “counter-intuitive,” even slightly outrageous. Surveying this embarrassing riches of theories, half-theories, and hunches, K.J.Holsti (1987) labeled international relations the “dividing discipline.” It seems likely, however, that the field is undergoing not division but involution. Involution refers to increasingly complex or intricate development within fixed parameters. The result of this process, explains the anthropologist Arthur Goldenweiser, is progressive complication, a variety within uniformity, virtuosity within monotony. This is involution… The basic forms…have reached finality, the structural features are fixed beyond variation, inventive originality is exhausted. Still, development goes on. Being hemmed in on all sides by a crystallized pattern, it takes the function of elaborateness. Expansive creativeness having dried up at the source, a special kind of virtuosity takes its place, a sort of technical hairsplitting. (quoted in Geertz 1963:80–1) The involution of the field yields a gothic proliferation of “historically corroborated,” but often flatly contradictory, theories. The discipline has largely settled on orthodox political science methods, notably the theory-hypothesistesting approach, as the way to proceed. Driven to publish novel ideas, yet boxed in by this pattern of inquiry, theorists fashion increasingly meticulous designs, and, like Talmudic scholars or Marxist dogmatists, expound on arcane distinctions and haggle over pennies. This discourse proceeds apparently unconcerned whether or not the ideas being entertained can be tested and sustained historically. The approach may simply yield islands of highly abstract theory that exist for their own sake, without any sense of meaning or purpose. Indeed, the Lakatosian emphasis on identifying a “winning” theory makes one wonder if students of politics have not internalized the conflicts they study. The fine-tuned linguistics of postmodernist theory threatens to fall into the same trap. This theoretical elaboration, with its medieval flavor, may simply be selfdefeating. It is important to recall that theory arises in response to interpretive problems. Because historical evidence is complex, we need a theory to direct our inquiry. Yet, while theory is a guide for framing questions, it also becomes a template for answering them. This undercuts any role that history might play as an independent body of evidence. Within a research program, where the bounds of inquiry are stipulated, theory may be merely self-verifying. We propose hypotheses and interpret historical evidence in light of our theoretical project, which we then claim to have confirmed and advanced. Thus, despite its apparent industry and vigor, research within the bounds of political science does not necessarily evolve toward greater understanding or more powerful explanations. Since history is filtered through theory, a proliferation of theories further fragments historical interpretation. Supporting historical evidence
CONCLUSION 175
surfaces in the wake of theory; but then, it surfaces in the wake of most theories. Theorists generally find what they are looking for. History is rich enough and ambiguous enough to sustain a wide range of narratives. The unfixed nature of theory and history often has researchers reeling from fad to counter-fad. As Yale Ferguson and Richard Mansbach lamented in The Elusive Quest (1988), the academic zeitgeist more than any rational scientific progression seems to buffet theory along. The historical problem, then, seems partly a theoretical problem, a consequence of the parsimony and elegance of theory, and the ensuing extravagance of its claims on history. The simpler the model, the more Procrustean its treatment of history; reasoning outward from an unbending principle “forces” the researcher to twist the evidence. Grand structure and overbroad axioms alike seem misguided, not least because they encourage a licentious historical method. It would not be too fanciful to say that the search for historical laws or something very much like them, long dismissed as quixotic by most historians, has been taken up by international theorists. Brimming with Victorian confidence, Seeley championed “scientific” historical methods, as the way to uncover “great truths having…scientific generality and momentous political bearings,” notably “the laws by which states rise, expand, prosper and fall” (quoted in Thorne 1988:19). Moderate the language slightly, and Seeley has described international relations’ more ambitious research projects. In this quest for novelty and parsimony, we have seen theorists try to recast economic thought in political terms. Microeconomic theory has offered a particularly alluring model for structuralists. As Stanley Hoffmann suggests (1987: 15) of international relations in America, this “fascination with economics…has led scholars to pursue the chimera of a masterkey. They have believed that the study of a purposive activity aimed at a bewildering variety of ends, political action, could be treated like the study of instrumental action, economic behavior.” Many theorists adapt theories of the firm, in which competitive markets shape behavior in predictable ways, to the workings of the international system; or else theory is inspired by the workings of economic efficiency, linking up political choices to the production of goods or the allocation of resources. Both approaches see in the dynamics of politics a “hidden hand” guiding interest and conflict to an equilibrium. The economic approach seems wrongheaded as applied to politics. Soldiers, diplomats, populations, cultures, or civilizations rarely seem to acquit themselves like rational economic actors. Economic choices revolve around the single, reducible goal of maximizing satisfactions. Political choices are motivated by many different goals, pursued in many different ways. This would cripple Pareto-optimal or rational choice models that claim to have discovered a behavioral blueprint beneath the apparent chaos of political conduct. More importantly, this sort of closed explanatory world tends to impose uniformity upon political diversity. Historical license is probably required in order to sustain the illusion that the researcher has struck on a masterkey, either by carefully avoiding unhelpful historiography, or canceling the search after uncovering a few confirming cases.
176 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Researchers can even be oddly candid about their historiographic forays in search of “best cases” offering “goodness-of-fit.” I discuss this further below, but the diversity of political goals suggests that ample historical content is required in order to understand what does inform decisions. Instead of imposing a rationale on political behavior, researchers should critically “consult,” via historical work, the people and processes involved. Pursued seriously, this imperfect art will help to keep theory within the pale of plausibility. Unfortunately, the plausibility of international relations theory is increasingly being drawn into question, and not only by postmodern critics. The American diplomat David Newsom (1996:121–9) has argued recently that faux science and masterkey-ism have left the lion’s share of the discipline’s research stranded in academia. Sloppy analogies and inaccurate accounts of the policy process have undercut the field’s credulity and deepened the fault line between theory and practice. The role of theorists as commentators on the current scene—considerable in the days of Niebuhr, Morgenthau, Kennan, and Aron—has been abdicated to the pundits. Perhaps worst of all, political science departments have become parched terrain in which to cultivate future diplomats and political leaders. Recovering history and theory A recent wave of commentaries on selection bias in the social sciences exhibits little sense of the historical dimensions of the problem. Political scientists have tended to “methodologize” historical challenges. Questions about epistemology are neglected in favor of more tractable problems about research design, in a way that furthers the clinical view of history. Works by Barbara Geddes (1990), David Collier (1995), and Collier and James Mahoney (1996) do not mention history or historiography at all. Gary King, Robert Keohane, and Sidney Verba’s celebrated Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research (1994) brushes over historical questions (see Lustick 1996). The trio note (King et al.: 133) that investigatorinduced selection bias is an “endemic problem” in research, though it appears not to extend to historical selection. Instead, we are told to consult “good historians” who “understand which events were crucial” (ibid.: 53). The book does discuss (ibid.: 212–13) the perils of analogical reasoning, yet the hazards are seen to lie in the method’s shallow basis for generalizing, not, historically, in the analogy being poorly drawn. Two works have looked more closely at these problems. Donald Puchala, a selfdescribed refugee from positivist political science, argues that it is hopeless to found international studies on the idea of historical truth. Following Rorty, Gadamer, Adorno, and others, he invites students of international affairs to abandon any epistemological claims in favor of a “pragmatic” attitude toward history, that “we may finally be prepared to allow truth to be useful instead of controversial” (Puchala 1995:3). Puchala perhaps has in mind something like the “consensus historiography” practiced in the United States in the 1950s, which employed motifs of shared values rather than societal conflict. While pragmatic views of history—
CONCLUSION 177
foundation myths, core norms, collective goods, and the like—may have virtuous effects on domestic polities, international parallels have proved elusive. The conjoining threads of international history are more apt to enflame animosities: the myth of the “white man’s burden,” imposed Lockean, Smithian, Marxist, or Fukuyaman evolution, visions of manifest destiny, dependencia narratives, or vulgarized realist histories. Arguably, theorists have been pragmatic, and that has been part of the problem. Ian Lustick’s paper, mentioned at the outset, illustrates clearly the problem of multiple historical records. However, Lustick appears not to grasp what this implies for research. He attempts to dissuade social scientists, faced with different renderings of the same reality, from throwing off the theoryhypothesis-testing harness. He suggests that the problem can be mitigated if researchers “direct explicit and systematic attention to historiography… and demonstrate self-consciousness in the selection of source material and in the construction of stylized background narratives.” He advises researchers to lay bare their historiographic allegiances, to seek regularities across interpretive schools, and to mediate different accounts through “quasitriangulation.” Lustick points to a “silver lining” in the historical cloud: acknowledging the diversity of historical accounts and expanding our database “will help, not hinder, efforts to find opportunities for study in which cases outnumber variables” (Lustick 1996:605, 615–16). Lustick seems less concerned that there are rival explanations; he turns a philosophical question into a methodological game. More accounts means more cases. One could adopt this method and do a multiple-case comparative analysis of a single event! If pragmatism seems defeatist and political science tinkering inadequate, where do we turn? My own view is that historical work should, in epistemology, inhabit a middle ground between naïve chronicle and pure subjectivism. In method, it should abandon the treasure-house view of history in favor of greater reflection and research. In place of trying to distill the essence of politics from history, theorists might wade deeper into history’s complexities. A more supple conception of theory is also in order. Theory should seek as much light as possible, and avoid a monolithism that flattens diversity and closes off ideas. For the ancient Greeks, theory meant considering, contemplating, or speculating outside of fixed forms of thought. In this vein, theorists might reconsider involuted theory, and instead relax their scientific claims and nomothetic judgments, and tether their ideas closer to the ambiguities of the material. Oakeshott often said that a “conversational” style of theorizing was more fruitful than rudely juxtaposing truth claims. This in mind, let us consider some remedies to the historical problem, and a broader view of what historical skepticism might mean for international relations. “History is not a feeding trough” So declared the nineteenth-century historian Dietrich Schäfer (quoted in Marwick 1970:63–4). Understanding rather than instrumentality should guide historical usage. We should resist viewing the past as an arsenal of unambiguous weaponry
178 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
to be deployed in international relations’ theory wars. Historical inference should be guided by a critical spirit rather than by convenience. Historical evidence should not be manipulated in order to flatter one’s ideology or to embellish one’s teleological edifice. Patterns and perennials should not extend far beyond the artifacts or arbitrarily occlude events that do not fit. Recalling that in “pure” history there is no such thing as an aberration, theorists should acknowledge contrary historiography. Theorists who contend with a variety of historical schools and arguments are likely to produce what are ultimately more compelling—and complex —insights. Often the best history is the most engaged, not that which appears to have been written on another planet. At least one knows where the historian stands; it is also clear that his/her work represents in some sense an argument (and often a coherent view of the world), rather than an infallible disquisition or edict on the past. Researchers might go to some pains to consult histories that do not necessarily share their theoretical proclivities—realist, structural, liberal, conservative, military, economic, etc. If the goal is truly to “test” theoretical claims, then disturbing a cozy consensus between history and theory suggests that research is proceeding apace. As Georg Schwarzenberger noted in Power Politics (1951:10, 18), “Practically every generation rewrites its history books, and not always for the reason that new documents have come to light… Students of international relations could do worse than to analyze any situation from all relevant points of view… In cases of doubt, it is wise to remember that the choice is hardly ever between white and black but only between various shades of gray.” Nor should accounts be ripped from context. It can be deceptive to approach historiography as a series of detachable events, which flow neatly one to the next. There will, of course, be tears in Maitland’s famous “seamless web” of history, but this is not to claim that events and broader social movements can be understood and evaluated apart from the broader processes in which they are embedded. Taking a cue from the Annalistes and the new historians, researchers might weigh broader conceptions of international history than traditional, “event-centered” politics. Viewing foreign affairs only through “diplomatic,” “military,” or “political” lenses surely yields a distorted account of complex events and long-term trends. J.H.Hexter referred to this old problem as “tunnel history.” By this, Hexter meant the practice of splitting the past into a series of tunnels, each continuous from the remote past to the present, but practically self-contained at every point and sealed off from contact with or contamination by anything that was going on in any of the other tunnels. At their entrances these tunnels bore signs saying diplomatic history, political history, institutional history, ecclesiastical history, intellectual history, military history, economic history, legal history, administrative history, art history, colonial history, social history, agricultural history, and so on. (Hexter 1961:194)
CONCLUSION 179
Lest one assume that this arrangement evolved because it represented the most fruitful approach to the past, Hexter points out that tunnel history originated with the peculiar filing systems of various public and private archives. The system was perpetuated, until the Annales breakthrough and other interdisciplinary and postmodernist efforts, by historians themselves, and survives in the social sciences to the extent that each discipline draws on “its” historical tributary in research. In international relations, as in international history, what tunnels are relevant and which walls should be breached are matters of some dispute. (I know a political theorist who, at a faculty senate meeting, proposed renaming his department “The Department of War and Imperialism,” since that seemed to be how most of his colleagues conceived of politics.) Event-centered, “headline” history can be enriched, though probably not replaced, by cultural, sociological, normative, and economic foci, as well as aspects of cultural psychology and identity politics. Political economy and studies of globalization, certainly, are booming in both disciplines. Top-down or bottom-up? This eclecticism in history and theory is changing the face of international relations. As was noted at the end of the previous chapter, it has also sparked defenses of oldfashioned diplomatic history. As noted, Charles Maier (1980: 356) contended that the nature of international politics resisted any movement toward “methodological democratization.” “Rankean exegesis” was still the mainstay of diplomatic history because international affairs were still dominated by necessitous, top-down statecraft. More recently, traditionalists have skewered new historians for the flimsiness of their constructs and have called for a renaissance in elite-based diplomatic history, where at least there is a hard core of documentary evidence of the sort “that statesmen and diplomats, at least at one time, scrupulously maintained” (Haber et al. 1997:39). Whether or not this represents the advent of the “documentary fallacy” remains to be seen. The suspicion lingers that this historiographic claim is, in the first instance, a theoretical claim—and one that many historians and political scientists contest vigorously. (As noted, the more inclusive designation “international history” seems to be gaining in favor.) What is really at issue is the Westphalian, dare we say, “realist,” “billiard ball” assumption that states are “unitary, rational actors.” Lashing back at social history and postmodernism, traditionalists welcome Ranke’s aim to recount history “as it really was,” yet in the same gate slips Ranke’s belief that high politics as reflected in state papers is the level, focus, and method of historical analysis which best explains international outcomes. An exclusively, or even primarily, top-down model seems increasingly difficult to justify as high politics are eroded by the democratization of foreign policies and the free flow of money, goods, and ideas. Fred Halliday (1996: 324) suggests that the realist wedding of history and international relations, in particular, “rests on a rather limited, if not dated, conception of history itself—that of diplomacy and
180 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
wars, with little space for more recent developments of economic, social and popular orientation.” Even the assumption of anarchy requires a leap of imagination. As Hedley Bull (1977) argued so well, foreign affairs unfold not under stark anarchy, but under the precarious norms of an anarchical society. Although some postmodern work might lead one to think otherwise, states are not apt to wither away any time soon. However, many other forces coexist alongside the state system, tempering anarchy, and, at times, sparking local reactions. One cannot assume these forces away as inconsequential, or of such minor effect, that theory can afford to overlook them. Of course, there are other, less tractable ways of thinking about international politics that employ matrices that are more complex or center on the interstices of domestic and international realms, or work across different facets of society. Forty years ago, A.E.Campbell decried the dominance of that “tradition of historiography, long-established…that diplomatic history can be studied as a thing apart, and that the relations of nation-states proceed with little reference to…the emotions and the private interests of the people who live in them” (quoted in Thorne 1988). The historical sociologist Michael Mann suggests (1986:16–17) that states are “functionally promiscuous.” “Complexities proliferate the more we probe. Military alliances, churches, common language, and so forth, all add powerful, sociospatially different networks of interaction.” Mann acknowledges that “to conceive of societies as confederal, overlapping, intersecting networks rather than as simple totalities complicates theory,” yet no rigor need be lost in the process. A great deal of relevance stands to be gained. The enemy in today’s world is not great-power strife or dyadic conflict so much as it is violence and chaos flowing from anomie and terrorism and ethnic conflict, as empires collapse and the cartography of states is tested from below. Much of the field is now focusing on the influence of non-state factors in political development, on shifting notions of sovereignty and political loyalty, the interaction between global and local forces, economics and identity, and so forth. This sort of layering seems vastly superior to the “levels-of-analysis” lottery, where the theorist decides at the outset where to focus his inquiry. This kind of work is messy and localist. It rewards smaller narratives and greater historical expertise as a way of illuminating underlying causes and historical precedents. There may also be less pressure to bend history to fit universal theory. New history need not usurp the traditional narrative approach. In fact, eventcentered narrative is undergoing something of a recovery in contemporary historiography, though in a way that favors description over analysis, and which stresses the context in which events are imbedded as well as how they affect, and are understood by, “ordinary people.” In addition, historians increasingly recognize that their narratives, like all narratives, are conditional constructs (Burke 1992b:235). This eclecticism may be seen as invigorating theory and history, not gutting them. It may also engender greater appreciation for political change. The most pedestrian historian is attentive to change, yet theorists of international politics more likely direct our interest to continuities rather than innovations. The static assumptions of many theories, wedded to law-based analysis, can yield a sort of behavioral
CONCLUSION 181
fatalism that presumes fixed patterns: political choices as thought to be more or less determined by certain conditions and configurations of variables; states and other actors reacting similarly to similar circumstances. Theories of international change are still rare, or, like neorealism, depict change in glacial terms. One might expect that as a discipline matures, dynamic theories would replace static ones. However, international relations has marched in the opposite direction. Carr thought more about change than Waltz ever did. The failure of the discipline to anticipate the collapse of the Soviet Union was a striking indication of this theoretical paralysis. The field was hardly looking for dramatic change. The Winter 1989/1990 issue of International Security, under the banner of “New Challenges for Soviet Security Policy,” explained the necessary incrementalism of Soviet foreign relations and Western responses. One piece ventured to ask, “Beyond the Brezhnev Doctrine: A New Era in Soviet-East European Relations?” A year earlier, the journal had been probing urgent questions like, “Is There a Tank Gap?” and whether or not conventional European security could rest upon the “3:1 Rule,” which held that an aggressor required three times its opponent’s “power” on the ground in order to pierce the adversary’s front-line defenses. In retrospect, of course, it all has a surreal quality. As bells tolled the Soviet demise, most of the discipline proved stone deaf. Kennan’s “X” article, steeped in Czarist history and Russian cultural psychology, foretold the collapse better than the array of modern theories. Consider statecraft when conferring causality The failure to understand the end of the cold war is related to the fact that much of theory resides at a “safe” distance from everyday politics. Nearly forty years ago, J.David Singer (1961:78) lamented that students of international politics “roamed up and down the ladder of organizational complexity with remarkable abandon.” Most theorists, Singer included, eventually landed on the systems rung. Several dovetailed circumstances favored this model: its analogy to classical economic theory; consensus on the approach among behavioralists; the structural aversion to cracking open the “black box” of the state; perhaps the perception that systemic research connoted systematic research. Most importantly, the systems path seemed to be ascending to that El Dorado of the field: a “general theory” of international relations. The problem with distant theory is that it foists a rationale upon events and actors. Theorists and researchers working at any level of analysis might play more light on political process. The orthodox approach, beginning with Morgenthau “looking over the diplomat’s shoulder,” has been less concerned with understanding the rationale behind political acts, than it is with conferring a rationale upon those acts—without regard to the actor’s intentions or motivations. Intentions are difficult to gauge, but that does not make them any less important. The path to understanding foreign policymaking almost certainly travels through the minds of foreign policymakers. Unlike the tides, which rise and fall by no will of their own,
182 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
setting and executing foreign policy requires human agents. Diplomatic behavior, where motivations are murky and where perceptions about security, power, prestige, interests, economics, and norms are so important, seems particularly uncongenial to “outside” explanations. Viewed from afar, the “dynamic” “at work” in political choice may seem clear. Yet, the fit between our model and the events it purports to decipher disregards the uncertainties, the contingencies, and the ends sought that attended the decision at the time. Imputed rationales curtail debate about necessity versus discretion in statecraft, and disregard the fragile circumstances that surround political processes. Ascribing causes to diplomatic decisions has become an excuse to ignore or transcend ambiguous historical evidence. This could well be missing the point. With politics working at many different levels and social domains, it is entirely possible, as Aron (1966:7) contended, that “the ambiguity in ‘international relations’ is not to be imputed to the inadequacy of our concepts: it is an integral part of reality itself.” Only historical inquiry can bridge this gap between political acts and scientific explanations. As Peter Winch argued in The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy (1958), “no historical situation can be understood simply by ‘applying’ such laws, as one applies laws to particular occurrences in natural science. Indeed, it is only in so far as one has an independent historical grasp of situations…that one is able to understand what the law amounts to at all” (Winch 1958:136). This is the idea advanced earlier of “consulting” political actors and processes to keep one’s theory on track. Did foreign policy acts occur as hypothesized? Were decisions taken for the reason(s) our model provides? Were leaders influenced or inspired by pressure from below? Theoretical assertions require historical ballast. Again, this is an imperfect art. At the level of traditional diplomatic history, content analysis of public speeches is probably not the way to proceed. As Thucydides and Ranke both found, personal accounts are often tainted, as memoirists flatter their own deeds and wisdom; in most countries, extensive state secrecy is still in place; mentalities and norms are difficult to gauge; coding of diplomatic history seems of marginal utility. Still, historical evidence nevertheless remains the raw material of research in the field. Its defects do not justify historically distant, “hang-in-the-air” assertions. Distant theory is most distressing, however, because it overwhelms the human factor in history. Politics are seen to unfold at a great remove from ordinary experience. The historian William Dray (1963:132–3) deplored how “covering” explanatory models—the deductive method—raise “a kind of conceptual barrier to a humanistically oriented historiography.” The same is true of political models that conceal people and process behind a mass of variables, or, as the case may be, one big variable. Many theorists celebrate having diminished the place of leadership or diplomatic practices or the perceived meaning of events in their explanations. The same analysts will be hard pressed to grasp, say, the 1989 revolutions in Eastern Europe without reference to Adam Michnik or Václav Havel or Mikhail Gorbachev, or without some sense of the tenor of the times. These are the social sciences. This same detached logic of necessity buttresses the belief that outcomes were somehow
CONCLUSION 183
foreordained. Even under the most compelling conditions, history wie es eigentlich gewesen ist was bound up in individual or collective choices. Structure and process were both at work. Nor were political decisions simply mechanically causal; they were also morally responsible. As Hugh TrevorRoper noted (1981:364), “History is not merely what happened: it is what happened in the context of what might have happened.” The fruit of skepticism International relations theory dwells in the twilight between history and prophecy, and it is sometimes tempting to conclude that its “back to the future” arguments fail on both counts. Parsimonious social science explanations seem something of a charade, marching, methodological banners flying, into the fog of human history. History is not the autonomous body of evidence empirical researchers envision; it is theory-laden, present-centered, and the source of a rainbow of interpretations. Although the patterns of history are not as facile or nomothetic as social scientists might like them to be, we can make modest claims on history and derive broad historical lessons. But those lessons are complex and ambivalent; closer to intimations, they underscore the abiding predicaments of world politics—the dilemmas of power and security, of jealous sovereignty and the precariousness of world community—but steer us along no definitive theoretical or practical path. Given this empire of circumstance, skepticism remains a sound position. The historian H.A.L.Fisher once noted that “Men wiser and more learned than I have discerned in history a plot, a rhythm, a predetermined pattern. These harmonies are concealed from me. I can see only one emergency following upon another… only one safe rule for the historian: that he should recognize in the development of human destinies the play of the contingent and the unforeseen” (quoted in Wight 1992:29). Fisher was arguing against the idea of progress, but he was not proposing a doctrine of cynicism and despair. Indeed, not knowing, or withholding judgment, keeps us alive to the possibilities of history, just as structure and determinism may fuel complacency about our lot. One can argue that the historical process itself challenges us morally, giving substance (and ambiguity) to moral life. As Arthur Schlesinger Jr. notes (1966: 17), history should lead us “to a profound and humbling sense of human frailty.” It should lead us to the perception, “so insistently demonstrated by experience and so tragically destructive of our most cherished certitudes,” that “the possibilities of history are far richer and more various than the human intellect is likely to conceive.” And yet, since “the tragedy of history implicates us all in the common plight of humanity, we are never relieved, despite the limits of our knowledge and the darkness of our understanding, from the necessity of meeting our obligations.” Only normative theory can suggest where those obligations lie. The fruit of skepticism is the knowledge that the elaborate machinery of political science cannot fathom the potential of history. At some point, scientific understandings fail us. As Kant (1970:63) wrote, “Such illusory wisdom imagines
184 HISTORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
it can see further and more clearly with its mole-like gaze fixed on experience than with the eyes which were bestowed on a being designed to stand upright and to scan the heavens.” Empirical work needs a more critical attitude toward history, especially awareness of presentism and ideological spin, but also of the conditional character of history itself. “History,” in the words of the Dutch historian Pieter Geyl (1949:16), “is indeed an argument without end.” We should view what is for historians their own “great debate” about the precision and use of their craft as a path toward greater rigor and relevance in our own ideas.
NOTES
2 THE HISTORICAL PROBLEM 1 Important works on the relation between history and international relations include Bryce (1909), Hughes (1960), Gilbert (1968), Birch (1969), Jensen (1969), Ford (1972), Reynolds (1973), Purnell (1976), Small (1976), Schroeder (1977), Stone (1977), Singer (1978), Lauren (1979), Maier (1980), Friedländer et al. (1981), Craig (1983), Thorne (1983), Hill (1985), Gaddis (1987), Thorne (1988), Sked (1989), Njølstad (1990), Howard (1991), Kavanagh (1991), Watson (1992), Hall and Kratochwil (1993), Salomon (1993), Buzan and Little (1994), Levy (1994b), Schroeder (1994a), Spence (1994), Buzan and Little (1995), Puchala (1995), Ferguson and Mansbach (1996), Lustick (1996), Elman and Elman (1997), Gaddis (1997a), Ingram (1997), Levy (1997), Schroeder (1997), and Suganami (1997). 2 The original German is in Ranke (1874: vii). Georg Iggers points out that “eigentlich,” the key to the phrase, had an ambiguity in nineteenth-century German that it no longer has. The word meant “actually” or “really,” but it also meant “characteristic” or “essential.” Iggers attributes this latter usage to Ranke, and suggests that a better translation of the phrase might be, “how, essentially, things happened” (see Iggers and Moltke 1973: xix, 137). 3 Cf. Marc Bloch’s (1963:140) plea to historians not to become obsessed with judging their subjects: “Robespierrists! Anti-Robespierrists! For pity’s sake, simply tell us what Robespierre was.” Cf. also Ernst Renan’s stricture that history be written “with as much supreme indifference as if [it] were written in another planet” (Snyder 1958:8). 4 This was the reported rejoinder of Benjamin Jowett, Master of Balliol College, Oxford, to William Stubbs’s attempts to instill Ranke’s method in undergraduates. From 1866 to 1884, Stubbs held the Regius Professorship of Modern History at Oxford (see Marwick 1970:54–5). 5 Of the luminaries of nineteenth-century American historiography, George Bancroft, who studied under Ranke in Germany, probably comes closest to the master’s greatnation Historismus. Bancroft’s magisterial History of the United States (1834–1840) sees reflected in US history the tide of a universal democratic spirit, and in the case of “manifest destiny,” harmony between divine will and US national interests. 6 The classic statement is Ernst Bernheim’s Lehrbuch der historischen Methode (1889), which focuses on the “logic of discovery,” setting aside narrative construction as a
186 NOTES
matter of aesthetics and ideology. Similar arguments are made in Goldstein (1976) and Ankersmit (1983). 7 Here Oakeshott builds on criticism of the “Whig” interpretation of history, which Herbert Butterfield (1931:v) described as “the tendency in many historians … to praise revolutions provided they have been successful, to emphasise certain principles of progress in the past and to produce a story which is the ratification if not the glorification of the present.” Cf. this culminatory account of history with R.H.Tawney’s contention that “Historians give an appearance of inevitability to an existing order by dragging into prominence the forces which have triumphed and thrusting into the background those which they have swallowed up” (Tawney 1912: 177). 8 Spiro (1994:62) notes, “it is important to remember that the subjective judgments by which variables are coded in data sets have significant and important effects on the results yielded by analysis of those data.” He adds (ibid.: 78) that such analysis elevates a static explanation (regime type) over path-dependent explanations, such as a shifting balance of power, thereby “remov[ing] the variables from their historical context.” See also Russett et al. (1995), wherein the authors essentially accuse each other of manipulating data to conform to their theories. The broader interpretive question is lost in this thicket of blame laying. 9 See the collection of papers prepared for the conference, “The Korean War: An Assessment of the Historical Record,” sponsored by The Korea Society and The KoreaAmerica Society and held at Georgetown University, 24–25 July, 1995.
3 HISTORY, CONTINGENCY, AND THE ROOTS OF REALISM 1 This is not to suggest that the classical approach is unique to realism. 2 Oakeshott (1983:39) hastens to point out that “it was in ‘Livy,’ a well-known collection of legenda, lying upon his table in Sant’Andrea in Percussina, and not at all in ‘Roman history,’ that Machiavelli found the exemplars of human conduct which he used so effectively to identify current situations, to express his reading of what was afoot in his time, to predict what was likely to come of it and to counsel and admonish the rulers of his day.” 3 Niebuhr first spoke of a nascent prophetic minority in Moral Man and Immoral Society (1932:87). Although the idea of a moral elite (not necessarily religious in inspiration; “realist” liberals might play this role) was a product of Niebuhr’s more radical days, it is a notion he advocated, and in many ways embodied, throughout his life. See Smith (1986:110–11). 4 By the late 1950s, Niebuhr had begun to question on prudential as well as ethical grounds the wisdom of expanding the United States’ nuclear arsenal. In a perhaps revealing passage he noted, “The uniqueness of this development probably can only be explained by the fact that economic power is more readily transmuted into military power than into political power” (Niebuhr 1959:295). 5 Michael Joseph Smith (1986:75–6) has pointed to the shallowness of Carr’s historical probing, specifically his “virtually determinist” “sole reliance on undifferentiated power as an explanatory factor.”
NOTES 187
4 HISTORY, ANALOGY, AND POLICY REALISM 1 Morgenthau wrote scores of essays against American intervention in Vietnam. For his trouble, he incurred the wrath of the Johnson administration, which stripped him of his security clearance and, perhaps, investigated his private affairs. In one piece, Morgenthau (1965) expressed “the likelihood of Soviet military intervention” in Indochina. 2 For variations on this theme see Claude (1962:25–37) and Tucker (1952: 214–24). Tucker suggested that Morgenthau confused empirical and normative analysis: that when he posited the “laws” by which politics did work, he was actually describing the norms by which politics should work. 3 Hoffmann (1987:10), for example, argues: What the leaders looked for, once the cold war started, was some intellectual compass which would serve multiple functions: exorcise isolationism, and justify a permanent and global involvement in world affairs; rationalize the accumulation of power, the techniques of intervention, and the methods of containment apparently required by the cold war; explain to a public of idealists why international politics does not leave much leeway for pure good will, and indeed besmirches purity; appease the frustrations of the bellicose by showing why unlimited force or extremism on behalf of liberty was no virtue; and reassure a nation eager for ultimate accommodation, about the possibility of both avoiding war and achieving its ideals. “Realism,” however critical of specific policies, however (and thus self-contradictorily) diverse in its recommendations, precisely provided what was necessary. 4 I would be remiss if I did not mention that in a statistical survey of research in the field, John Vasquez found that in 7000 applications of realist hypotheses, 90 percent were either proved weak or were falsified. He tested a bare-bones conception of “realism,” which conceived of states as autonomous, unitary, self-seeking, and rational. He suggests that psychological approaches may pose the greatest challenge to realism. “Rational” choices were heavily influenced by beliefs, perceptions, and the different ways that statesmen digested information (Vasquez 1983: 176–203).
5 THE POVERTY OF AHISTORICISM 1 The title of this chapter is inspired in equal parts by Karl Popper’s The Poverty of Historicism (1957) and Richard Ashley’s (1986) essay “The Poverty of Neorealism.” 2 The most concise survey of neorealism’s impact on the field is Keohane (1986). The following other commentaries and critiques only scratch the surface. Challenges from the classical realist school include Thompson (1996:125–45) and Forde (1995). A critique of neorealism built around the role of prestige in international politics is Mercer (1996). For the constructivist position, see Wendt (1987 and 1992) and Katzenstein (1996). Representing critical theory are Ashley (1986) and Cox (1986). In
188 NOTES
3 4
5
6
terms of historical change, see Walker (1987) and Kratochwil (1993). For criticisms from the standpoint of globalization theory, see the essays in MacMillan and Linklater (1995) and Hirst and Thompson (1996). Critiques grounded in historical sociology include Spruyt (1994) and Hall (1986). The “democratic peace” thesis is a direct challenge to neorealism. See Nincic (1994), and Brown et al. (1996). Weighing in on behalf of the English School are Buzan and Little (1995) and Little (1995). See Richard Ashley’s (1986:26–63) discussion of “the triumph of scientific realism.” The crispest exposition of the Lakatosian aims of the neorealist research program is Tellis (1995). A number of other neorealists have been explicit in adhering to Lakatos’s progressive approach to science. See, for example, Elman (1996). See also Vasquez (1997). In fairness, neorealist research has generally not relied on quantitative analyses. However, see Walt (1987:275, Table 16, and 289–91, Appendix II). The field’s increasingly frequent invocation of Lakatos over the past decade is probably a function of the sociology of the discipline, not a reflection of any great awareness of Lakatosian research parameters. Of course, Lakatos’s forgiving view of theory meshes well with Waltzian and other deductive views of theory. This is a restatement of Kant’s idealist epistemology, which held that the world could only be observed through a synthetic framework of a priori principles (see Kant 1970: 16–17). The affinity with constructionist historians is also apparent.
6 “THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING SCIENTIFIC” 1 Here Singer speaks of “the importance of being scientific.” 2 Independent appraisals of the COW include Duvall (1976), Job and Ostrum (1976), Starr (1976), Vasquez (1987), Dessler (1991), and Gaddis (1992/1993). 3 The School is named after the journal Annales d’histoire économique et sociale, founded by Bloch and Febvre at Strasbourg in 1929. After the Second World War the journal was renamed Annales: Économies, sociétés, civilisations, and was edited by Febvre and later Fernand Braudel at the Sixième Section of the École Politiques des Hautes Études. 4 John Vasquez argues that data-making is a “paradigmatic activity.” In other words, it operates within the bounds of Kuhnian “normal science.” Vasquez’s “color it Morgenthau” thesis holds that virtually all quantitative work in international relations has adopted realist precepts. See Vasquez (1979) and Vasquez (1983: 139–41). 5 The 1994 data set makes a nod toward this problem, providing an aggregate figure for all battle-related combatant deaths sustained in extra-systemic wars. This does give a better sense of the overall killing. Unfortunately, the number is not broken down by participant, making a muddle of a series of intensity figures based on battle deaths per each participant’s population and months at war. Also, importantly, COW researchers have recently proposed a new typology of war. Included are three new categories of extra-systemic wars that involve non-state actors. One of these is a futurelooking classification of wars composed entirely of non-state actors, which some COW participants see as a trend in conflict around the world. If carried through, this would entail an enormous recoding task, as well as a rethinking of many of the project’s central claims. See Wayman et al. (1997).
NOTES 189
6 The COW claims inter-coder reliability as impressively high as 0.94 using Scott’s pi, although reliability falls off in more complex coding procedures. 7 Geller and Singer (1998) is a broad survey of the state of the art of quantitative research on war, much of which is based on COW data. The book falls short of a “synthesis” of quantitative work in the field, for reasons the authors make plain (Geller and Singer 1998:3–5). Nevertheless, the survey is clearly organized around a number of important themes at the decisionmaking, regime, dyadic, and systemic levels, and will prove useful as an extended literature review.
7 EXIT FROM HISTORY? 1 These are contested categories. Brown distinguishes postmodern theory from critical theory, but affirms that all postmodern approaches are united by skepticism toward Enlightenment social science: no small commonality. Yosef Lapid (1989) sees postpositivists united by concerns about paradigms, perspectives, and relativism. The relation between Marxism and postmodernism is hotly debated. On these points see also Vasquez (1995) and Brown (1994). General surveys of post-modernism readers may wish to consult include Harvey (1990), Bertens (1995), and, for a skeptical take on postmodern social science, Rosenau (1992), which includes a helpful glossary of postmodern terms. Ninkovich (1998) is an excellent review of recent postmodern literature in international relations. 2 Pauline Rosenau (1992) makes a helpful distinction between skeptical and affirmative postmodernism, which I generally adopt. However, I would amend this to say that most postmodernists seem to be of two minds: skeptical on certain issues, affirmative on others. Postmodernists in international relations generally seem more affirmative than Rosenau allows. 3 Cf. W.B.Gallie’s statement that “history is a species of the genus story” (quoted in Alker 1996:297). 4 For a fuller explanation of White’s theory than is possible here, see Jenkins (1995: 146–73), on which this discussion is based. 5 Thanks to Desmond Dewsnap of the University of Southern California for pointing this out to me.
190
REFERENCES
Acton, Lord [John Dalberg-Acton] (1907) “Report to the Syndics of the Cambridge University Press,” in The Cambridge Modern History: Its Origin, Authorship and Production, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. — (1973) “Letter to the Contributors to the Cambridge Modern History,” in F.Stern (ed.) The Varieties of History: From Voltaire to the Present, New York: Vintage. Alker, H.R. (1996) Rediscoveries and Reformulations: Humanistic Methodologies for International Studies, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Amin, S. (1989) Eurocentrism, New York: Monthly Review Press. Anderson, B.R.O’G. (1983) Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, London: Verso. Angell, N. (1933) The Great Illusion, New York: G.P.Putnam. Ankersmit, F.R. (1983) Narrative Logic: A Semantic Analysis of the Historian’s Language, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. — (1994) History and Tropology: The Rise and Fall of Metaphor, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Appleby, J., Hunt, L., and Jacob, M. (1994) Telling the Truth about History, New York: Norton. Arnold, M. (1869) Culture and Anarchy: An Essay in Political and Social Criticism, London: Smith, Elder. Aron, R. (1966) Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, Malabar, FL: Robert E.Krieger. — (1967) “What Is International Theory?,” in J.C.Farrell and A.P.Smith (eds.) Theory and Reality in International Relations, New York: Columbia University Press. Ashley, R.K. (1986) “The Poverty of Neorealism,” in R.O.Keohane (ed.) Neorealism and Its Critics, New York: Columbia University Press. — (1989) “Living on Border Lines: Man, Poststructuralism, and War,” in J.D. Derian and M.J.Shapiro (eds.) International/Intertextual Relations: Postmodern Readings of World Politics, Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. — (1995) “The Powers of Anarchy: Theory, Sovereignty, and the Domestication of Global Life,” in J.D.Derian (ed.) International Theory: Critical Investigations, New York: New York University Press. Ashley, R.K. and Walker, R.B.J. (1990a) “Reading Dissidence/Writing the Discipline: Crisis and the Question of Sovereignty in International Studies,” International Studies Quarterly 34:367–416. Ashley, R.K.and Walker, R.B.J. (1990b) “Speaking the Language of Exile: Dissident Thought in International Studies,” International Studies Quarterly 34:259–68. Askew, W.C. (1942) Europe and Italy’s Acquisition of Libya, 1911–1912, Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Bagby, L.M.J. (1994) “The Use and Abuse of Thucydides in International Relations,” International Organization 48:131–53.
192 REFERENCES
Baldwin, D. (1993) (ed.) Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate, New York: Columbia University Press. Bancroft, G. (1834–1840) History of the United States, 3 vols., Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Bates, M. (1981) (Review of K.N.Waltz, Theory of International Politics), The Journal of Politics 23:588–90. Baudrillard, J. (1994) The Illusion of the End, trans. C.Turner, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Bauman, Z. (1997) Postmodernity and Its Discontents, New York: New York University Press. Bayat, A. (1997) Street Politics: Poor People’s Movements in Iran, New York: Cambridge University Press. Beard, C. (1935) “That Noble Dream,” The American Historical Review 41:74–87. Becker, C.L. (1910) “Detachment and the Writing of History,” The Atlantic Monthly 106: 524–36. Beehler, W.H. (1913) The History of the Italian-Turkish War, Annapolis, MD: AdvertiserRepublican. Bennett, J.C. (1982) “Reinhold Niebuhr’s Social Ethic: The Later Years,” Christianity and Crisis 12 April: 91–5. Benson, L. (1966) “Quantification, Scientific History, and Scholarly Innovation,” AHA Newsletter 4 (June): 11–16. Berlin, I. (1959) Historical Inevitability, London: Oxford University Press. Bernheim, E. (1889) Lehrbuch der historischen Methode, Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot. Bertens, H. (1995) The Idea of the Postmodern: A History, London: Routledge. Bhargava, M.L. (1992) Saga of 1857: Success and Failures, New Delhi: Reliance Publishing House. Birch, A.H. (1969) “Historical Explanation and the Study of Politics,” Government and Opposition 4:215–30. Blainey, G. (1973) The Causes of War, New York: Free Press. Bloch, M. (1963) The Historian’s Craft, New York: Knopf. Blok, A. (1992) “Reflections on ‘Making History,’” in K.Hastrup (ed.) Other Histories, London: Routledge. Bodart, G. (1908) Militar-Historisches Kriegs-Lexikon, 1618–1905, Vienna: C.W.Stern. Booth, K. (1995) “Dare Not to Know: International Relations Theory versus the Future,” in K.Booth and S.Smith (eds.) International Relations Theory Today, University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press. Bosworth, R.J.B. (1996) “Italy and the End of the Ottoman Empire,” in M.Kent (ed.) The Great Powers and the End of the Ottoman Empire, London: Frank Cass. Bradbury, M. (1990) “Frontiers of Imagination,” The Guardian 15 February: 21. Bradley, A.C. (1950) Oxford Lectures in Poetry, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Braudel, F. (1979) Civilisation Matérielle, Économie et Capitalisme: XVe-XVIIIe Siécle, Paris: A.Colin. — (1980) On History, trans. S.Matthews, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. — (1992) The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II, trans. S.Reynolds, abridged by R.Ollard, New York: HarperCollins. Bridenbaugh, C. (1963) “The Great Mutation,” The American Historical Review 68: 315–31. Brown, C. (1994) “Critical Theory and Postmodernism in International Relations,” in A.J. R. Groom and M.Light (eds.) Contemporary International Relations: A Guide to Theory, London: Pinter.
REFERENCES 193
Brown, M.E., Lynn-Jones, S.M., and Miller, S.E. (eds.) (1996) Debating the Democratic Peace, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bryce, J. (1909) “The Relations of Political Science to History and to Practice,” American Political Science Review 3 (February): 1–19. — (1922) International Relations, New York: Macmillan. Bueno de Mesquita, B. (1996) “The Benefits of a Social-Scientific Approach to Studying International Affairs,” in N.Woods (ed.) Explaining International Relations Since 1945, New York: Oxford University Press. Bull, H. (1969a) “International Theory: The Case for a Classical Approach,” in K. Knorr and J.N.Rosenau (eds.) Contending Approaches to International Politics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (1969b) “The Twenty Years’ Crisis Thirty Years On,” International Journal 24: 625–38. — (1972) “The Theory of International Politics,” in B.Porter (ed.) The Aberystwyth Papers: International Politics, 1919–1969, London: Oxford University Press. — (1977) The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, New York: Columbia University Press. — (1980) “International Relations,” TLS 4 January: 20. Burchill, S. (1995) “Realism and Neo-realism,” in S.Burchill and A.Linklater (eds.) Theories of International Relations, New York: St. Martin’s. Burke, E. (1989) Reflections on the Revolution in France, New York: Anchor Books. Burke, P. (1992a) History and Social Theory, Cambridge: Polity Press. — (1992b) “History of Events and the Revival of Narrative,” in P.Burke (ed.) New Perspectives on Historical Writing, University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press. Bury, J.B. (1902) “The Science of History,” in F.Stern (ed.) (1973) The Varieties of History: From Voltaire to the Present, New York: Vintage. Butterfield, H. (1931) The Whig Interpretation of History, London: George Bell. — (1966) “The Balance of Power,” in H.Butterfield and M.Wight (eds.) Diplomatic Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. — (1969) Man on His Past: The Study of the History of Historical Scholarship, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Butterfield, H. and Wight, M. (eds.) (1966) Diplomatic Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Buzan, B. and Little, R. (1994) “The Idea of ‘International System’: Theory Meets History,” International Political Science Review 15:231–55. — (1995) “Reconceptualizing Anarchy: Structural Realism Meets World History,” European Journal of International Relations 2:403–38. Buzan, B., Jones, C., and Little, R. (1993) The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism, New York: Columbia University Press. Callinicos, A.T. (1995) Theories and Narratives: Reflections on the Philosophy of History, Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Campbell, D. (1992) Writing Security, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Carnegie Commission on Preventing Deadly Conflicts (1997) Preventing Deadly Conflicts, New York: Carnegie Corporation. Carr, E.H. (1939) The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations, London: Macmillan. — (1945) Nationalism and After, London: Macmillan.
194 REFERENCES
— (1946) The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations, 2nd ed., New York: Harper & Row. — (1947) The Soviet Impact on the Western World, New York: Macmillan. — (1961) What Is History?, New York: Vintage. — (1975) “The View from the Arena” (review of W.Laqueur and G.L.Mosse (eds.) Historians ‘in Politics), TLS 7 March: 246. Cassirer, E. (1962) The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, trans. F.C.A.Koelln and J.P.Pettegrove, Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Castellanos, P.Z. (1925) Vida Militar de Centro America, Guatemala City: Editorial del Ejército. Chauncey, G. (1994) Gay New York: Gender, Urban Culture, and the Makings of the Gay Male World, 1890–1940, New York: Basic Books. Childs, T.W. (1990) Italo-Turkish Diplomacy and the War over Libya, 1911–1912, Leiden: E.J. Brill. Clark, I. (1997) Globalization and Fragmentation: International Relations ‘in the Twentieth Century, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Claude, I.L. (1962) Power and International Relations, New York: Random House. Clausewitz, C. von (1968) On War, ed. with an intro. by Anatol Rappoport, Baltimore, MD: Penguin. Clodfelter, M. (1992) Warfare and Armed Conflicts, Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Cohen, R. (1995) “In Sarajevo, Victims of a ‘Postmodern’ War,” New York Times 21 May: 1. Collier, D. (1995) “Translating Quantitative Methods for Qualitative Researchers: The Case of Selection Bias,” American Political Science Review 89:461–6. Collier, D. and Mahoney, J. (1996) “Insights and Pitfalls: Selection Bias in Qualitative Research,” World Politics, 49 (October): 56–91. Collier, R. (1963) The Sound of Fury, London: Collins. Collingwood, R.G. (1956) The Idea of History, London: Oxford University Press. Connor, W.R. (1984) Thucydides, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Coox, A. (1977) The Anatomy of a Small War, Westport, CT: Greenwood. Cox, R.W. (1986) “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory,” in R.O.Keohane (ed.) Neorealism and Its Critics, New York: Columbia University Press. Craig, G.A. (1983) “The Historian and the Study of International Relations,” The American Historical Review 88:1–11. Crick, B. (1964) The American Science of Politics: Its Origins and Conditions, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Croce, B. (1941) History as the Story of Liberty, New York: Norton. Dahm, B. (1971) History of Indonesia in the Twentieth Century, London: Praeger. Davis, H.R. and Good, R.C. (eds.) (1960) Reinhold Niebuhr on Politics: His Political Philosophy and Its Application to Our Age as Expressed in His Writings, New York: Scribner’s. Dean, M. (1994) Critical and Effective Histories: Foucault’s Methods and Historical Sociology, London: Routledge. Dehio, L. (1963) The Precarious Balance: The Politics of Power in Europe, 1494–1945, trans. C.Fullman, London: Chatto & Windus. De Klerck, E.S. (1938) History of the Netherlands East Indies, Rotterdam: Brusse. Der Derian, J. (1992) Antidiplomacy: Spies, Terror, Speed and War, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
REFERENCES 195
Desch, M.C. (1997) “Realism, Revolution, and International Relations,” (review of Stephen Walt’s Revolution and War), Mershon International Studies Review (Supp. to International Studies Quarterly, 4l), supp. 1 (May): 125–6. Dessler, D. (1991) “Beyond Correlations: Toward a Causal Theory of War,” International Studies Quarterly 35:337–55. Dickenson, L. (1926) The International Anarchy, 1904–1914, London: G.Allen and Unwin. Diderot, D. (1963) Lettre sur les Aveugles, Geneva: E.Droz. Diehl, P.F. (1992) “The Correlates of War Project: A Bibliographic Essay, 1961–1991,” International Studies Notes 17 (Spring): 21–33. Donelan, M. (1990) Elements of International Political Theory, Oxford: Clarendon. Dray, W.H. (1963) “The Historical Explanation of Actions Reconsidered,” in S.Hook (ed.) Philosophy and History, New York: New York University Press. Dumas, S. and Vedel-Peterson, K.O. (1923) Losses of Life Caused by War, London: Oxford University Press. Dunn, J. (1978) “Practising History and Social Science on ‘Realist’ Assumptions,” in C.Hookway and P.Pettit (eds.) Action and Interpretation: Studies in the Philosophy of Social Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Duvall, R. (1976) “An Appraisal of the Methodological and Statistical Procedures of the Correlates of War Project,” in F.W.Hoole and D.A.Zinnes (eds.) Quant-itative International Politics: An Appraisal, New York: Praeger. Edwardes, M. (1963) Battles of the Indian Mutiny, London: Batsford. Elman, C. (1996) “Horses for Courses: Why Not Neorealist Theories of Foreign Policy?,” Security Studies 6 (Autumn): 7–51. Elman, C. and Elman, M.F. (1997) “Diplomatic History and International Relations Theory: Respecting Differences and Crossing Boundaries,” International Security 22 (Summer): 5–21. Elman, C, Elman, M.F., and Schroeder, P.W. (1995) “Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look,” International Security 20 (Summer): 182–95. Embree, A.T. (ed.) (1963) 1857 in India: Mutiny or War of Independence?, Boston, MA: D.C.Heath. Evans, P.B., Jacobson, H.K., and Putnam, R.D. (eds.) (1993) Double-Edged Diplomacy: International Bargaining and Domestic Politics, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Evans-Pritchard, E.E. (1949) The Sanusi of Cyrenaica, Oxford: Clarendon. Everts, P.P. (1992) “The Events in Eastern Europe and the Crisis in the Discipline of International Relations,” in P.Allan and K.Goldmann (eds.) The End of the Cold War: Evaluating Theories of International Relations, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Farber, H.S. and Gowa, J. (1995) “Polities and Peace,” International Security 20 (Fall): 123– 46. Farcau B.W. (1996) The Chaco War: Bolivia and Paraguay, 1932–1935, Westport, CT: Praeger. Ferguson, Y.H. and Mansbach, R.W. (1988) The Elusive Quest: Theory and International Politics, Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press. — (1996) Polities: Authority, Identities and Ideology, Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press. Fischer, D.H. (1970) Historians’ Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Inquiry, New York: Harper. Fischer, M. (1992) “Feudal Europe, 800–1300: Communal Discourse and Conflictual Practices,” International Organization 46:427–66.
196 REFERENCES
— (1993) “On Context, Facts, and Norms: Response to Hall and Kratochwil,” International Organization 47:493–500. Fleiss, P. (1966) Thucydides and the Politics of Bipolarity, Nashville, TN: Louisiana State University Press. Florovsky, G. (1969) “The Study of the Past,” in R.H.Nash (ed.) Ideas in History, vol. 2, The Critical Philosophy of History, New York: Dutton. Fogel, R.W. and Elton, G.R. (1983) Which Road to the Past?, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Fogel, R.W. and Engerman, S.L. (1974) Time on the Cross: The Economics of American Negro Slavery, Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Foot, R. (1996) “Leadership, Perceptions, and Interest: Chinese-American Relations in the Early Cold War,” Diplomatic History 20:473–82. Ford, T.H. (1972) “Toward a Better Relation between History and Political Science,” Government and Opposition 7:207–28. Forde, S. (1995) “International Realism and the Science of Politics: Thucydides, Machiavelli, and Neorealism,” International Studies Quarterly 39:141–60. Foucault, M. (1980) Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977, trans. and ed. C.Gordon, New York: Pantheon. — (1984) “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” in P.Rabinow (ed.) The Foucault Reader, New York: Pantheon. Fox, W.T.R. (1980) (Review of K.N.Waltz, Theory of International Politics), American Political Science Review 74:492–3. La Foy, M. (1946) The Chaco Dispute and the League of Nations, Bryn Mawr, PA: Bryn Mawr Press. Frankel, B. (1993) “The Brooding Shadow: Systemic Incentives and Nuclear Weapons Proliferation,” Security Studies 2 (Spring/Summer): 37–78. Fraser, R. (1979) Blood of Spain: An Oral History of the Spanish Civil War, New York: Pantheon. Friedländer, S., Kapur, H., and Reszler, A. (eds.) (1981) L’Historien et Les Relations Internationales: Recueil d’etudes en hommage a Jacques Freymond, Geneva: Institute Universitaire de Hautes Études Internationales. Fukuyama, F. (1992) The End of History and the Last Man, New York: The Free Press. Furet, F. (1971) “Quantitative History,” Daedalus 100:151–67, Fussell, P. (1975) The Great War and Modern Memory, New York: Oxford University Press. Gadamer, H.-G. (1992) Reason in the Age of Science, trans. F.G.Lawrence, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gaddis, J.L. (1982) Strategies of Containment: A Critical Appraisal of Postwar American National Security Policy, New York: Oxford University Press. — (1987) “Expanding the Data Base: Historians, Political Scientists, and the Enrichment of Security Studies,” International Security 12 (Summer): 3–21. — (1990) “New Conceptual Approaches to the Study of American Foreign Relations: Interdisciplinary Perspectives,” Diplomatic History 14:405–23. — (1992/1993) “International Relations Theory and the End of the Cold War,” International Security 17 (Winter): 5–58. — (1997a) “History, Theory, and Common Ground,” International Security 22 (Summer): 75–85. — (1997b) We Now Know: Rethinking Cold War History, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Garner, W.R. (1966) The Chaco Dispute, Washington, DC: Public Affairs Press.
REFERENCES 197
Gay, P. (1974) Style in History, New York: Basic Books. Gebrandy, P.S. (1950) Indonesia, London: Hutchinson. Geddes, B. (1990) “How the Cases You Choose Affect the Answers You Get: Selection Bias in Comparative Politics,” in J.A.Stimson (ed.) Political Analysis: An Annual Publication of the Methodology Section of the American Political Science Association, vol. 2, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Gee, W. (1950) Social Science Research Methods, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Geertz, C. (1963) Agricultural Involution: The Processes of Ecological Change in Indonesia, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Geller, D.S. and Singer., J.D. (1998) Nations at War: A Scientific Study of International Conflict, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Geyl, P. (1949) Napoleon: For and Against, London: Jonathan Cape. — (1958) Debates with Historians, New York: Meridian. Gilbert, A.N. (1968) “International Relations and the Relevance of History,” International Studies Quarterly 12:351–59. Gilley, S. (1996) “History Without Morality, History Without Truth,” History Today 46 (May): 11–13. Gilpin, R. (1981) War and Change in World Politics, New York: Cambridge University Press. — (1988) “The Theory of Hegemonic War,” in R.I.Rotberg and T.K.Rabb (eds.) The Origin and Prevention of Major Wars, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ginzburg, C. (1991) “Checking the Evidence: The Judge and the Historian,” Critical Inquiry 18:79–92. Gochman, C.S. and Leng, R.L. (1983) “Realpolitik and the Road to War: An Analysis of Attributes and Behavior,” International Studies Quarterly 27:97–120. Gochman, C.S. and Z.Maoz (1990) “Militarized Interstate Disputes, 1816–1976,” in J.D. Singer and P.F.Diehl (eds.) Measuring the Correlates of War, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Goertz, G. (1994) Contexts of International Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Goldstein, L.J. (1976) Historical Knowing, Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. Gooch, J. (1986) The Unification of Italy, London: Methuen. Gowa, J. (1989) “Bipolarity, Multipolarity, and Free Trade,” American Political Science Review 79:1245–66. Grieco, J.M. (1995) “The Maastricht Treaty, Economic and Monetary Union and the Neorealist Research Programme,” Review of International Studies 21:21–40. Grovogui, S.N. (1996) Sovereigns, Quasi Sovereigns, and Africans, Minneapolis, MA: University of Minnesota Press. Gulick, E.V. (1967) Europe’s Classical Balance of Power, New York: Norton. Guralnick, P. (1994) Last Train to Memphis: The Rise of Elvis Presley, Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Gusterson, H. (1993) “Realism and the International Order After the Cold War,” Social Research 60:297–300. Haber, S.H., Kennedy, D.M., and Krasner, S.D. (1997) “Brothers Under the Skin: Diplomatic History and International Relations,” International Security 22 (Summer): 34–43. Hall, J. (ed.) (1986) States in History, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Hall, R. and Kratochwil, F. (1993) “Medieval Tales: Neorealist ‘Science’ and the Abuse of History,” International Organization 47:479–91. Halliday, F. (1994) Rethinking International Relations, Basingstoke: Macmillan.
198 REFERENCES
— (1996) “The Future of International Relations: Fears and Hopes,” in S.Smith, K.Booth, and M.Zalewski (eds.) International Theory: Positivism and Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Handlin, O. (1979) Truth in History, Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Harrison, A.T. (ed.) (1980) The Graham Indian Mutiny Papers, Belfast: Public Record Office of Northern Ireland. Harvey, D. (1990) The Condition of Postmodernity: An Inquiry into the Origins of Cultural Change, Oxford: Blackwell. Hastrup, K. (ed.) (1992) Other Histories, London: Routledge. Hempel, C.G. (1942) “The Function of General Laws in History,” Journal of Philosophy 39: 35–48. Herodotus (1947) The Persian Wars, intro. F.R.B.Godolphin, New York: Modern Library. Herrmann, D.G. (1989) “The Paralysis of Italian Strategy in the Italian-Turkish War, 1911– 1912,” English Historical Review 104:332–56. Hexter, J.H. (1961) Reappraisals in History, London: Longman. Hill, C. (1985) “History and International Relations,” in S.Smith (ed.) International Relations: British and American Perspectives, Oxford: Basil Blackwell/The British International Studies Association. Hirst, P. and Thompson, G. (1996) Globalization in Question: The International Economy and the Possibilities of Governance, Cambridge: Polity Press. Hixson, W.L. (1989) George F. Kennan: Cold War Iconoclast, Oxford: Columbia University Press. Hobbes, T. (1947) Leviathan, or the Matter, Forme and Power of a Commonwealth Ecclesticall and Civil, ed. with intro. by M. Oakeshott, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. — (1994) The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic, New York: Oxford University Press. Hobsbawm, E. (1993) “The New Threat to History,”New York Review of Books 16 December: 62–4. Hoffmann, S. (ed.) (1977) Contemporary Theory in International Relations, Westport, CT: Greenwood. Hoffmann, S. (1987) Janus and Minerva: Essays in the Theory and Practice of International Politics, Boulder, CO: Westview. Hofstadter, R. (1973) “History and the Social Sciences,” in F.Stern (ed.) The Varieties of History: From Voltaire to the Present, New York: Vintage. Holsti, K.J. (1987) The Dividing Discipline: Hegemony and Diversity in International Theory, Boston, MA: Allen & Unwin. Holsti, O.R. and North, R.C. (1965) “The History of Human Conflict,” in E.B. McNeil (ed.) The Nature of Human Conflict, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Holt, E. (1970) Risorgimento: The Making of Italy, 1815–1870, London: Macmillan. Horkheimer, M. and Adorno, T.W. (1972) Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. J. Cumming, New York: Herder and Herder. Howard, M. (1983) The Causes of Wars and Other Essays, London: T.Smith. — (1984) “The Causes of War,” The Wilson Quarterly 8 (Summer): 90–103. — (1989) “Structure and Process in History,” TLS 23–29 June: 687–98. — (1991) The Lessons of History, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Hughes, H.S. (1960) “The Historian and the Social Scientist,” The American Historical Review 66:20–46.
REFERENCES 199
Huntington, S.P. (1996) The Clash of Civilizatiom and the Remaking of World Order, New York: Simon and Schuster. Iggers, G.G. (1962) “The Image of Ranke in American and German Historical Thought,” History and Theory 2:17–40. — (1968) The German Conception of History: The National Tradition of Historical Thought from Herder to the Present, Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press. — (1997) Historiography in the Twentieth Century: From Scientific Objectivity to the Postmodern Challenge, Hanover, NH: University Press of New England. Iggers, G.G. and Moltke, K. von (eds.) (1973) Ranke: The Theory and Practice of History, New York: Bobbs-Merrill. Ingram, E. (1997) “The Wonderland of the Political Scientist,” International Security 22 (Summer): 53–63. Ireland, G. (1938) Boundaries, Possessions and Conflicts in South America, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Jameson, F. (1972) The Prison-House of Language, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (1983) “Postmodernism and Consumer Society,” in H.Foster (ed.) The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays in Postmodern Culture, Port Townsend, WA: Bay Press. Jarausch, K.H. (1985) “(Inter)national Styles of Quantitative History,” Historical Methods 18:13–19. Jenkins, K. (1995) On “What Is History?” From Carr and Elton to Rorty and White, London: Routledge. Jensen, R. (1969) “History and the Political Scientist,” in S.M.Lipset (ed.) Politics and the Social Sciences, New York: Oxford University Press. Jervis, R. (1976) Perception and Misperception in International Politics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Job, B.L. and Ostrum, C.W. (1976) “An Appraisal of the Research Design and Philosophy of Science of the Correlates of War Project,” in F.W.Hoole and D. A.Zinnes (eds.) Quantitative International Politics: An Appraisal, New York: Praeger. Johnson, J.J. (1980) Latin America in Caricature, Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. Johnson, N. (1989) The Limits of Political Science, Oxford: Clarendon. Jones, S.D. and Singer, J.D. (1972) Beyond Conjecture in International Politics, Itasca, IL: F.E.Peacock. Kahin, G. (1952) Nationalism and Revolution in Indonesia, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Kaldor, M. (1995) “Who Killed the Cold War?,” The Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists 51(July/ August): 57–60. Kant, I. (1970) Kant’s Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss, trans. H.B.Nisbet, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kaplan, M.A. (1961) “Problems of Theory Building and Theory Confirmation in International Politics,” in K.Knorr and S.Verba (eds.) The International System: Theoretical Essays, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Karpat, K.H. (1985) Ottoman Population, 1830–1914, Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press. Katzenstein, P.J. (ed.) (1996) The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics, New York: Columbia University Press. Kavanagh, D. (1991) “Why Political Science Needs History,” Political Studies 39: 479–95. Kaye, H.J. (1996) Why Do Ruling Classes Fear History?, New York: St. Martin’s. Kedourie, E. (1975) “New Histories for Old,” TLS 7 March: 238–40.
200 REFERENCES
Kegley, C.W., Jr. (ed.) (1995) Controversies in International Relations Theory: Realism and the Neoliberal Challenge, New York: St. Martin’s. Kellner, D. (1998) “Globalization and the Postmodern Turn,” in R.Axtmann (ed.) Globalization and Europe: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, London: Pinter. “X” [Kennan, G.F.] (1947) “The Sources of Soviet Conduct,” Foreign Affairs 25: 566–82. Kennan, G.F. (1946) “Excerpts from Telegraphic Message from Moscow of February 22, 1946” [The Long Telegram], in G.F.Kennan (1967) Memoirs, 1925–1950, Boston, MA: Little, Brown. — (1950) American Diplomacy, 1900–1950, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. — (1951) “America and the Russian Future,” Foreign Affairs 29:351–70. — (1954) Realities of American Foreign Policy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (1956) Soviet-American Relations, 1917–1920, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (1960) “The Experience of Writing History,” The Virginia Quarterly Review 36 (Spring): 205–14. — (1967) Memoirs: 1925–1950, Boston, MA: Little, Brown. — (1971) The Marquis de Custine and His “Russia in 1839,” Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (1985/1986) “Morality and Foreign Policy,” Foreign Affairs 64 (Winter): 205–18. — (1986) “History, Literature and the Road to Peterhof,” The New York Times Book Review 29 June: 1, 42. — (1989) “The History of Arnold Toynbee,” The New York Review of Books 1 June: 19–22. — (1993a) Around the Cragged Hill: A Personal and Political Philosophy, New York: W.W.Norton. — (1993b) “The Balkan Crisis: 1913 and 1993,” The New York Review of Books 15 July: 3–7. — (1994) “The Failure in Our Success,” The New York Times 14 March: A17. — (1995) “On American Principles,” Foreign Affairs 74 (March/April): 116–26. — (1996) At a Century’s Ending: Reflections, 1982–1995, New York: W.W. Norton. Kennedy, P. (1987) The Rise and Fall of the Great Powers: Economic Change and Military Conflict from 1500 to 2000, New York: Random House. Keohane, R.O. (ed.) (1986) Neorealism and Its Critics, New York: Columbia University Press. Keohane, R.O. (1988) “International Institutions: Two Approaches,” International Studies Quarterly, 32:379–96. Khong, Y.F. (1992) Analogies at War: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu, and the Vietnam Decisions of 1965, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. King, B. (1899) A History of Italian Unity, London: James Nisbet. King, G., Keohane, R.O., and Verba, S. (1994) Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Kratochwil, F. (1993) “The Embarrassment of Changes: Neo-realism as the Science of Realpolitik without Politics,” Review of International Studies 19:63–80. Krause, J. and Renwick, N. (eds.) (1996) Identities in International Relations, Basingstoke: Macmillan. Krieger, L. (1977) Ranke: The Meaning of History, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Kuhn, T.S. (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Labs, E.J. (1992) “Do Weak States Bandwagon?,” Security Studies 1 (Spring): 383–416. Ladurie, E. le R. (1977) “Motionless History,” Social Science History 1:115–36. — (1978) Montaillou: Cathars and Catholics in a French Village, 1294–1324, trans. B. Bray, London: Scolar Press.
REFERENCES 201
Lakatos, I. (1970) “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,” in I.Lakatos and A.Musgrave (eds.) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lapid, Y. (1989) “The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in a PostPositivist Era,” International Studies Quarterly 33:235–54. Lapid, Y. and Kratochwil, F. (eds.) (1996) The Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory, London: Lynne Rienner. Lauren, P.G. (ed.) (1979) Diplomacy: New Approaches in History, Theory, and Policy, New York: The Free Press. Layne, C. (1994) “Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace,” International Security 19 (Fall): 5–49. Leffler, M.P. (1995) “Presidential Address: New Approaches, Old Interpretations, and Prospective Reconfigurations,” Diplomatic History 19:173–96. Leng, R.J. (1995) Behavioral Correlates of War, 1816–1979 [code book], Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-university Consortium for Political and Social Research (ICPSR 8606). Leng, R.J. and Singer, J.D. (1990) “Militarized Interstate Crises,” in J.D. Singer and P.F. Diehl (eds.) Measuring the Correlates of War, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Levy, J.S. (1994a) “Learning and Foreign Policy: Sweeping a Conceptual Minefield,” International Organization 48:279–312. — 1994b) “The Theoretical Foundations of Paul W.Schroeder’s International System,” The International History Review 16:715–44. — (1997) “Too Important to Leave to the Other: History and Political Science in the Study of International Relations,” International Security 22 (Summer): 22–33. Liberman, P. (1993) “The Spoils of Conquest,” International Security 18 (Fall): 125–53. Little, R. (1991) “International Relations and the Methodological Turn,” Political Studies 39:463–78. — (1995) “Neorealism and the English School: A Methodological, Ontological and Theoretical Reassessment,” European Journal of International Relations 1:9–34. Löwith, K. (1949) Meaning in History, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lustick, I.S. (1996) “History, Historiography, and Political Science: Multiple Historical Records and the Problem of Selection Bias,” American Political Science Review 90:605–18. Lyotard, J.-F. (1984) The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans. G. Bennington and B.Massumi, foreword F.Jameson, Manchester: Manchester University Press. Machiavelli, N. (1979) The Portable Machiavelli, P.Bondanella and M.Musa (eds. and trans.), New York: Penguin. McClure, W.K. (1913) Italy in North Africa, London: Constable. MacMillan, J. and Linklater, A. (eds.) (1995) Boundaries in Question: New Directions in International Relations, London: Pinter. McNeill, W.H. (1986) Mythistory and Other Essays, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Maier, C.S. (1980) “Marking Time: The Historiography of International Relations,” in M.Kammen (ed.) The Past Before Us: Contemporary Historical Writing in the United States, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Majumdar, R.C. (1963) The Sepoy Mutiny and the Revolt of 1857, Calcutta: Firma K. L. Mukhopadhyay. Mannheim, K. (1936) Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge, New York: Harcourt, Brace.
202 REFERENCES
Mann, M. (1986) The Sources of Social Power, vol. 1, A History of Power from the Beginning to A.D. 1760, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mansfield, E.D. (1988) “The Distribution of Wars Over Time,” World Politics 41: 21–51. Marshall, B.K. (1992) Teaching the Postmodern: Fiction and Theory, New York: Routledge. Marwick, A. (1970) The Nature of History, New York: Dell. Marx, K. and Engels F. (1991) “The Communist Manifesto,” in W.Ebenstein and A.O.Ebenstein (eds.) Great Political Thinkers: Plato to the Present, 5th ed., Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace. Mastanduno, M. (1997) “Preserving the Unipolar Moment: Realist Theories and U.S. Grand Strategy after the Cold War,” International Security 21 (Spring): 49–88. May, E. (1973) “Lessons” of the Past: The Use and Misuse of History in American Foreign Policy, New York: Oxford University Press. Mayers, D. (1988) George Kennan and the Dilemmas of U.S.Foreign Policy, New York: Oxford University Press. Mearsheimer, J.J. (1990) “Back to the Future: Instability in Europe After the Cold War,” International Security 15 (Summer): 5–56. — (1994/1995) “The False Promise of International Institutions,” International Security 19 (Winter): 5–49. Meehan, E.H. (1968) Explanation in Social Science: A System Paradigm, Homewood, IL: Dorsey Press. Mercer, J. (1996) Reputation and International Politics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Miscamble, W.D. (1992) George F.Kennan and the Making of American Foreign Policy, 1947– 1950, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Mitchell, B.R. (1992) International Historical Statistics, New York: Stockton Press. Morgenthau, H.J. (1946) Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. — (1948) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, New York: Knopf. — (1951) In Defense of the National Interest: A Critical Examination of American Foreign Policy, New York: Knopf. — (1962a) The Decline of Democratic Politics (vol. 1 of Politics in the Twentieth Century), Chicago: University of Chicago Press. — (1962b) The Restoration of American Politics (vol. 2 of Politics in the Twentieth Century), Chicago: University of Chicago Press. — (1965) “Globalism: Johnson’s Moral Crusade,” The New Republic 3 July: 19–22. — (1966) “The Purpose of Political Science,” in J.C.Charlesworth (ed.) A Design for Political Science: Scope, Objectives, and Methods, Philadelphia, PA: The American Academy of Political and Social Science. — (1967) “Common Sense and Theories of International Relations,” in J.C.Farrell and A.P.Smith (eds.) Theory and Reality in International Relations, New York: Columbia University Press. — (1968) “Bundy’s Doctrine of War Without End,” The New Republic 2 November: 18–20. — (1978) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 5th ed., New York: Knopf. — (1983) “Constraints on Presidential Leadership in Foreign Policy,” in J.S. Young (ed.) Problems and Prospects of Presidential Leadership in the Nineteen-Eighties, Lanham, MD: University Press of America. — (1985) Politics Among Nations, 6th ed., rev. K.W.Thompson, New York: Knopf. Morgenthau, H.J. and Hein, D. (1983) Essays on Lincoln’s Faith and Politics, ed. K. W.Thompson, Lanhan, MD: University Press of America.
REFERENCES 203
Morris, D. (1965) Washing of the Spears, New York: Simon and Schuster. Muravchik, J. (1991) “At Last, Pax Americana,” The New York Times 24 January: A19. Murray, O. (1986) “Greek Historians,” in J.Boardman, J.Griffin, and O.Murray, The Oxford History of the Classical World, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mutiny Reports from Punjab and N.W.F.P. (1976), Lahore: al-Biruni. Naipaul, V.S. (1997) “After the Revolution,” The New Yorker 26 May: 46–69. Neill, W.T. (1973) Twentieth-Century Indonesia, New York: Columbia University Press. Neumann, J. von and Morgenstern, O. (1944) Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Neustadt, R.E. and May, E.R. (1986) Thinking in Time: The Uses of History for Decision-makers, New York: The Free Press. Newsom, D.D. (1996) The Public Dimension of Foreign Policy, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Niebuhr, R. (1928) “What War Did to My Mind,” The Christian Century, 27 September: 1161–63. — (1932) Moral Man and Immoral Society, New York: Scribner’s. — (1937) Beyond Tragedy: Essays on the Christian Interpretation of History, New York: Scribner’s. — (1940) Christianity and Power Politics, New York: Scribner’s. — (1941) Human Nature (vol. 1 of The Nature and Destiny of Man: A Christian Interpretation (1949)), New York: Scribner’s. — (1942) “The Unity of History,” Christianity and Crisis 4 May: 1–2. — (1943) Human Destiny (vol. 2 of The Nature and Destiny of Man: A Christian Interpretation (1949)), New York: Scribner’s. — (1944) The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness: A Vindication of Democracy and a Critique of Its Traditional Defense, New York: Scribner’s. — (1945) “Editorial,” Christianity and Society 10 (Spring): 4. — (1950a) “The Hydrogen Bomb,” Messenger 28 February: 7. — (1950b) “A Protest Against a Dilemma’s Two Horns,” World Politics 2: 338–44. — (1952) The Irony of American History, New York: Scribner’s. — (1953) “Human Nature and Social Change,” The Christian Century 50:363. — (1955) “Determinism in History,” (Review of Isaiah Berlin’s Historical Inevitability), The New Leader 38 (21 November): 24. — (1959) The Structure of Nations and Empires: A Study of the Recurring Patterns and Problems of the Political Order in Relation to the Unique Problems of the Nuclear Age, New York: Scribner’s. — (1962) “Response,” in Reinhold Niebuhr: A Prophetic Voice in Our Time, ed. H.R.Landon, Greenwich, CT: The Seabury Press. — (1963) “History’s Limitations in the Nuclear Age,” The New Leader 4 February: 18–19. — (1984) “Intellectual Autobiography,” in Reinhold Niebuhr: His Religious, Social, and Political Thought, ed. C.W.Kegley, New York: Scribner’s. Nietzsche, F. (1965) “The Use and Abuse of History,” in The Philosophy of Nietzsche, ed. G.Clive, New York: Mentor. Nincic, M. (1994) Democracy and Foreign Policy: The Fallacy of Political Realism, New York: Columbia University Press. Ninkovich, F. (1998) “No Post-Mortems for Postmodernism, Please,” Diplomatic History 22:451–65.
204 REFERENCES
Njølstad, O. (1990) “Learning from History? Case Studies and the Limits to TheoryBuilding,” in N.P.Gleditsch and O.Njølstad (eds.) Arms Races: Technological and Political Dynamics, London: SAGE/International Peace Research Institute, Oslo. Novick, P. (1988) That Noble Dream: The “Objectivity Question” and the American Historical Profession, New York: Cambridge University Press. Oakeshott, M. (1936) “History and the Social Sciences,” in the Institute of Sociology (ed.) The Social Sciences: Their Relations in History and Teaching, London: Le Play House Press. — (1950/1951) “Mr. Carr’s First Volume,” Cambridge Review 4:344–52. — (1962) Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays, New York: Basic Books. — (1983) On History and Other Essays, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. — (1990) Experience and Its Modes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Oberdorfer, D. (1991) The Turn: From the Cold War to a New Era: The United States and the Soviet Union, 1983–1990, New York: Poseidon. Owen, J.M. (1994) “How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace,” International Security 19 (Fall): 87–125. Owen, U. (1995) “Editorial,” Index on Censorship 3:3. Oye, K.W. (ed.) (1986) Cooperation Under Anarchy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Popper, K.R. (1957) The Poverty of Historicism, Boston, MA: Beacon Press. — (1959) The Logic of Scientific Discovery, London: Hutchinson. — (1965) Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, New York: Harper & Row. Puchala, D.J. (1990) “Woe to the Orphans of the Scientific Revolution,” Journal of International Affairs 44:59–80. — (1995) “The Pragmatics of International History,” Mershon International Review (Supp. to International Studies Quarterly) 39, supp. 1:1–18. Purnell, R. (1976) “The Relevance of Ancient History to the Contemporary Study of International Politics,” British Journal of International Studies 2:27–40. Rabb, T. (1981) “Coherence, Synthesis, and Quality in History,” The Journal of Interdisciplinary History 12:315–32. Rahe, P.A. (1995/1996) “Thucydides’ Critique of Realpolitik,” Security Studies 5 (Winter): 105–41. Ranke, L. von (1833) “The Great Powers,” in G.G. Iggers and K. von Moltke (eds.) (1973) Ranke: The Theory and Practice of History, New York: Bobbs-Merrill. — (1874) Geschichten der Romanischen und Germanischen Völker, Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot. — (1875) A History of England Principally in the Seventeenth Century, Oxford: Clarendon. — (1887) History of the Latin and Teutonic Nations From 1494 to 1514, trans. P.A. Ashworth, London: George Bell. Reid, A. (1981) “Indonesia: Revolution without Socialism,” in R.Jeffrey (ed.) Asia: The Winning of Independence: The Philippines, India, Indonesia, Vietnam, Malaya, London: Macmillan. Reiser, O. (1944) Planetary Democracy: An Introduction to Scientific Humanism and Applied Semantics, New York: Creative Age Press. Reynolds, C. (1973) Theory and Explanation in International Politics, London: Martin Robertson. Richardson, L.F. (1960) Statistics of Deadly Quarrels, ed. Q.Wright and C.C.Lienau, Pittsburgh, PA: Boxwood Press.
REFERENCES 205
Rosecrance, R. (1981) “International Theory Revisited,” International Organization 35: 691– 713. — (1986) The Rise of the Trading State: Commerce and Conquest in the Modern World, New York: Basic Books. Rosenau, J.N. (1997) Along the Domestic-Foreign Frontier: Exploring Governance in a Turbulent World, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rosenau, P.M. (1992) Post-modernism and the Social Sciences: Insights, Inroads, and Intrusions, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Rosenberg, J. (1994) The Empire of Civil Society: A Critique of the Realist Theory of International Relations, London: Verso. Rosenthal, J. (1991) Righteous Realists: Political Realism, Responsible Power, and American Culture in the Nuclear Age, Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana University Press. Ruggie, J.G. (1986) “Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity: Toward a Neorealist Synthesis,” in R.O.Keohane (ed.) Neorealism and Its Critics, New York: Columbia University Press. Russett, B.R. (1993) Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for a Post-Cold War World, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Russett, B.R., Layne, C, Spiro, D.E., and Doyle, M.W. (1995) “Correspondence: The Democratic Peace,” International Security 19 (Spring): 164–84. Ryan, A. (1970) The Philosophy of the Social Sciences, New York: Pantheon. Sagan, S.D. and Waltz, K.N. (1995) The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: A Debate, New York: Norton. Said, E.W. (1979) Orientalism, New York: Vintage. Salomon, K. (1993) “What is the Use of International History?,” Journal of Peace Research 30:375–89. Sanger, D.E. (1998) “Contagion Effect: A Guide to the Modern Domino Theory,” New York Times 2 August. Sarup, M. (1993) An Introductory Guide to Post-Structuralism and Postmodernism, 2nd ed., Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press. Scherer, P. (1984) “Reinhold Niebuhr—Preacher,” in Reinhold Niebuhr: His Religious, Social, and Political Thought, ed. C.W.Kegley, New York: The Pilgrim Press. Schlesinger, A., Jr. (1962) “The Humanist Looks at Empirical Social Research,” American Sociological Review, 27. Schlesinger, A., Jr. (1966) “On the Inscrutability of History,” Encounter 22 (November): 10–17. — (1984) “Reinhold Niebuhr’s Role in American Political Thought,” in Reinhold Niebuhr: His Religious, Social, and Political Thought, ed. C.W.Kegley, New York: The Pilgrim Press. Scholte, J.A. (1996) “Globalisation and Collective Identities,” in J.Krause and N.Renwick (eds.) Identities in International Relations, London: Macmillan. Schroeder, P.W. (1977) “Quantitative Studies in the Balance of Power: An Historian’s Reaction,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 21:3–21. — (1989) “The Nineteenth Century System: Balance of Power or Political Equilibrium?,” Review of International Studies 15:135–53. — (1994a) “Historical Reality vs. Neo-realist Theory,” International Security 19 (Summer): 108–48. — (1994b) The Transformation of European Politics, 1763–1848, Oxford: Clarendon Press. — (1997) “History and International Relations Theory: Not Use or Abuse, but Fit or Misfit,” International Security 22 (Summer): 64–74.
206 REFERENCES
Schwarzenberger, G. (1951) Power Politics: A Study of International Society, 2nd ed., New York: Praeger/The London Institute of World Affairs. Schweller, R. (1994) “Bandwagoning for Profit: Bringing the Revisionist State Back In,” International Security 19 (Summer): 72–107. Scott, J.C. (1990) Domination and the Arts of Resistance: Hidden Transcripts, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Sen, S. (1992) The Historiography of the Indian Revolt of 1857, Calcutta: Punthi-Pustak. Sheehan, M. (1996) The Balance of Power: History and Theory, London: Routledge. Shreeves, W.G. (1984) Nationmaking in Nineteenth Century Europe, London: Nelson. Singer, J.D. (1961) “The Level-of-Analysis Problem in International Relations,” in K.Knorr and S.Verba (eds.) The International System: Theoretical Essays, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (1965) “Data-Making in International Relations,” Behavioral Science 10:68–80. — (1969) “The Incompleat Theorist: Insights Without Evidence,” in K.Knorr and J.N.Rosenau (eds.) Contending Approaches to International Politics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (1972a) “Research Note: The ‘Correlates of War’ Project: Interim Report and Rationale,” World Politics 24:243–70. — (1972b) “Theorists and Empiricists: The Two-Culture Problem in International Politics,” in J.N. Rosenau et al. (eds.) The Analysis of International Politics, New York: The Free Press. — (1976) “The Correlates of War Project: Continuity, Diversity, and Convergence,” in F.W.Hoole and D.A.Zinnes (eds.) Quantitative International Politics: An Appraisal, New York: Praeger. — (1978) “The Behavioral Approach to Diplomatic History,” in A.DeConde (ed.) Encyclopedia of American Foreign Policy: Studies of the Principal Movements and Ideas, vol. 1, New York: Scribner’s. — (1979) “The Peace Researcher and Foreign Policy Prediction,” in J.D.Singer (ed.) The Correlates of War I: Research Origins and Rationale, New York: The Free Press. — (1981) “Accounting for International War: The State of the Discipline,” Journal of Peace Research 28:1–18. — (1989) “The Making of a Peace Researcher,” in J.Kruzel and J.N.Rosenau (eds.) Journeys Through World Politics: Autobiographical Reflections of Thirty-four Academic Travelers, Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. — (1990a) Models, Methods, and Progress in World Politics: A Peace Research Odyssey, Boulder, CO: Westview Press. — (1990b) “Reconstructing the Correlates of War Data Set on Material Capabilities of States, 1816–1985, in J.D.Singer and P.F.Diehl, Measuring the Correlates of War, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Singer, J.D. and Small, M. (1966) “The Composition and Status Ordering of the International System: 1815–1940,” World Politics 18:236–82. Singer, J.D. and Small, M. (1972) The Wages of War, 1816–1965: A Statistical Handbook, New York: John Wiley. — (1994a) Correlates of War Project: International and Civil War Data, 1816–1992 [computer file], Ann Arbor, MI: Inrer-University Consortium for Political and Social Research (ICPSR No. 09905).
REFERENCES 207
— (1994b) Correlates of War Project: International and Civil War Data, 1816–1992 [codebook], Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research (ICPSR No. 09905). Sked, A. (1989) “The Study of International Relations: A Historian’s View,” in H.C.Dyer and L.Mangasarian (eds.) The Study of International Relations: The State of the Art, New York: St. Martin’s. Small, M. (1976) “The Applicability of Quantitative International Politics to Diplomatic History,” The Historian 38:281–304. — (1979) “The Quantification of Diplomatic History,” in P.G.Lauren (ed.) Diplomacy: New Approaches in History, Theory, and Policy, New York: The Free Press. — (1990) “History and the Correlates of War,” in C.S.Gochman and A.N.Sabrosky (eds.) Prisoners of War? Nations-States in the Modern Era, Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. Small, M. and Singer, J.D. (1976) “The War-Proneness of Democratic Regimes, 1816– 1965,” The Jerusalem Journal of International Relations 1:50–69. — (1979) “Conflict in the International System, 1816–1977,” in J.D.Singer(ed.) Explaining War, Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. — Z(1982) Resort to Arms: International and Civil Wars, 1816–1980, Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Smith, A.D. (1995) Nations and Nationalism in a Global Era, Cambridge: Polity. Smith, M.J. (1986) Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger, Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press. Smith, S. (1992) “The Forty Years’ Detour: The Resurgence of Normative Theory in International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 21: 489–506. — (1996) “Positivism and Beyond,” in S.Smith, K.Booth, and M.Zalewski (eds.) International Theory: Positivism and Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Snidal, D. (1991) “Relative Gains and the Pattern of International Cooperation,” American Political Science Review 85:701–26. Snyder, G.H. (1990) “Alliance Theory: A Neorealist First Cut,” Journal of International Affairs 44:103–23. Snyder, P.L. (ed.) (1958) Detachment and the Writing of History: Essays and Letters of Carl L.Becker, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Sorokin, P. (1937) Social and Cultural Dynamics, 3 vols, New York: American Books. Spence, J.E. (1994) “Entering the Future Backwards: Reflections on the Current International Scene,” Review of International Studies 20:3–13. Spiro, D.E. (1994) “The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace,” International Security 19 (Fall): 50–86. Spruyt, H. (1994) The Sovereign State and Its Competitors: An Analysis of Systems Change, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Starr, H. (1976) “An Appraisal of the Substantive Findings of the Correlates of War Project,” in F.W.Hoole and D.A.Zinnes (eds.) Quantitative International Politics: An Appraisal, New York: Praeger. Stern, F. (ed.) (1973) The Varieties of History: From Voltaire to the Present, New York: Vintage. Stillman, W.J. (1898) The Union of Italy, 1815–1895, Cambridge: The University Press. Stone, L. (1977) “History and the Social Sciences in the Twentieth Century,” in C.F.Delzell (ed.) The Future of History: Essays in the Vanderbilt University Centennial Symposium, Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press. — (1979) “The Revival of Narrative: Reflections on a New Old History,” Past and Present, 85 (November): 3–24.
208 REFERENCES
Strange, S. (1996) The Retreat of the State: The Diffusion of Power in the World Economy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stretton, H. (1969) The Political Sciences: General Principles of Selection in Social Science and History, New York: Basic Books. Suganami, H. (1997) “Stories of War Origins: A Narrativist Theory of the Causes of War,” Review of International Studies 23:401–18. Tawney, R.H. (1912) The Agrarian Problem in the Sixteenth Century, London: Longmans, Green. Tellis, A.J. (1995) “Reconstructing Political Realism: The Long March to Scientific Theory,” Security Studies 5 (Winter): 3–100. Thomas, K. (1966) “The Tools and the Job,” TLS 7 April: 275–6. Thompson, K.W. (1984) “Philosophy and Politics: The Two Commitments of Hans J. Morgenthau,” in K.W.Thompson and R.J.Myers (eds.) Truth and Tragedy: A Tribute to Hans J. Morgenthau, New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction. — (1996) Schools of Thought in International Relations: Interpreters, Issues, and Morality, Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press. Thorne, C. (1983) “International Relations and the Promptings of History,” Review of International Studies 9:123–35. — (1988) Border Crossings: Studies in International History, Oxford: Basil Blackwell/The East Asian Institute. Thucydides (1972) History of the Peloponnesian War, trans. R.Warner, ed. M.I.Finley, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Tonkin, E. (1992) Narrating Our Past: The Social Construction of Oral History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Trevor-Roper, H. (1981) “History and Imagination,” in H.Lloyd-Jones, V.Pearl, and B. Worden (eds.) History and Imagination: Essays in Honour of H.R.Trevor-Roper, London: Duckworth. Trouillot, M.-R. (1995) Silencing the Past: Power and the Production of History, Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Tucker, R.W. (1952) “Professor Morgenthau’s Theory of Political ‘Realism,’” American Political Science Review 46:214–24. Turner, P.A. (1993) I Heard It Through the Grapevine: Rumor in African-American Culture, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Urlanis, B.T. (1960) Voini I Narodo-Nacelenie Evropi (War and the Population of Europe), Moscow: Government Publishing House. Vasquez, J.A. (1979) “Colouring it Morgenthau: New Evidence for an Old Thesis on Quantitative International Politics,” British Journal of International Studies 5: 210–28. — (1983) The Power of Power Politics: A Critique, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. — (1987) “The Steps to War: Toward a Scientific Explanation of Correlates of War Findings,” World Politics 60:108–45. — (1995) “The Post-Positivist Debate: Reconstructing Scientific Inquiry and International Relations Theory After Enlightenment’s Fall,” in K.Booth and S.Smith (eds.) International Relations Theory Today, University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press. — (1997) “The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative versus Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz’s Balancing Proposition,” American Political Science Review 91:899–912.
REFERENCES 209
Vertzberger, Y.Y.I. (1986) “Foreign Policy Decisionmakers as Practical-Intuitive Historians: Applied History and Its Shortcomings,” International Studies Quarterly 30: 223–47. Veyne, P. (1984) Writing History: Essay on Epistemology, Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press. Virilio, P. (1986) Speed and Politics: An Essay on Dromology, New York: Columbia University Press. Vlekke, B. (1960) Nusantara, Chicago: Quadrangle. Walker, R.B.J. (1987) “Realism, Change and International Political Theory,” International Studies Quarterly 31:65–86. — (1993) Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wallerstein, I. (1974) “The Rise and Future Demise of the World Capitalist System: Concepts for Comparative Analysis,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 16: 387– 415. Walt, S.M. (1987) The Origins of Alliances, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. — (1996) Revolution and War, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Waltz, K.N. (1959a) Man, the State and War; A Theoretical Analysis, New York: Columbia University Press. — (1959b) “Political Philosophy and the Study of International Relations,” in W.T.R.Fox (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. — (1964) “The Stability of a Bipolar World,” Daedalus 93:881–909. — (1967) Foreign Policy and Democratic Politics: The American and British Experience, Boston, MA: Little, Brown. — (1970) “The Myth of National Interdependence,” in C.P.Kindleberger (ed.) The International Corporation: A Symposium, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. — (1975) “Theory of International Relations,” in F.I.Greenstein and N.W. Polsby (eds.) Handbook of Political Science, vol. 8, International Politics, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. — (1979) Theory of International Politics, New York: Random House. — (1981) The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: More May Be Better, Adelphi Paper No. 171, London: International Institute for Strategic Studies. — (1986) “Reflections on Theory of International Politics: A Response to My Critics,” in R.O.Keohane (ed.) Neorealism and Its Critics, New York: Columbia University Press. — (1988) “The Origins of War in Neorealist Theory,” in R.I.Rotberg and T.K.Rabb (eds.) The Origin and Prevention of Major Wars, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. — (1990) “Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory,” Journal of International Affairs 44 (Spring): 21–37. — (1993) “The Emerging Structure of International Politics,” International Security 18 (Fall): 44–79. — (1996) “International Politics Is Not Foreign Policy,” Security Studies 6 (Autumn): 54–7. Ward, A. (1996) Our Bones Are Scattered: The Cawnpore Massacres and the Indian Mutiny of 1857, New York: H.Holt. Watson, A. (1992) The Evolution of International Society: A Comparative Historical Analysis, London: Routledge. Wayman, F.W., Sarkees, M.R., and Singer, J.D. (1997) “Inter-state, Intra-state, and Extrasystemic Wars, 1816–1995: A New War Typology, with Trends in Modern Warfare” (unpublished ms.).
210 REFERENCES
Weaver, P.R.C. (1966) “The Tyranny of Literature,” Times Literary Supplement 28 July: 663–4. Weber, M. (1949) The Methodology of the Social Sciences, trans. and ed. E.A.Shils and H.A. Finch, New York: The Free Press. Wehl, D. (1948) The Birth of Indonesia, London: Allen and Unwin. Wendt, A. (1987) “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory,” International Organization 41:335–70. — (1992) “Anarchy Is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics,” International Organization 46:391–425. — (1995) “Constructing International Politics,” International Security 20 (Summer): 71–81. White, H.V. (1966) “The Burden of History,” History and Theory 5:111–34. Whitfield, J.H. (1971) “Machiavelli’s Use of Livy,” in T.A.Dorey (ed.) Livy, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Whitfield, S.J. (1991) The Culture of the Cold War, Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press. Wiggershaus, R. (1994) The Frankfurt School: Its History, Theories, and Political Significance, trans. M.Robertson, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Wight, M. (1966) “Why Is There No International Theory?,” in H. Butterfield and M.Wight (eds.) Diplomatic Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. — (1992) International Theory: The Three Traditions, ed. G.Wight and B.Porter, New York: Holmes & Meier/The Royal Institute of International Affairs. Williams, W.A. (1956) “The Convenience of History,” The Nation September 15: 222–4. Winch, P. (1958) The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Windschuttle, K. (1997) The Killing of History: How Literary Critics and Social Theorists Are Murdering Our Past, New York: Free Press. Wines, R. (ed.) (1981) Leopold von Ranke: The Secret of World History, New York: Fordham University Press. Wolf, C. (1948) The Indonesia Story, New York: John Day. Wolf, E. (1982) Europe and the People Without History, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Woodman, D. (1955) The Republic of Indonesia, New York: Philosophical Library. Wright, Q. (1942) A Study of War, 2 vols, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. — (1955) The Study of International Relations, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Zainu’ddin, A.G.T. (1980) A Short History of Indonesia, New Melbourne: Cassell. Zakaria, F. (1996) “Divining Russia” (Review of George F.Kennan, At a Century’s Ending), New York Times Book Review 7 April: 6. Zemon-Davis, N. (1983) The Return of Martin Guerre, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Zook, D.H. (1960) The Conduct of the Chaco War, New York: Bookman.
INDEX
Acheson, D. 84 Acton, Lord 44, 52, 142; The Cambridge Modern History 14–15 Adams, H.B. 15 Adams, President J. 43 Adorno, T. and Horkheimer, M.: Dialectic of Enlightenment 145–2 Alamanach de Gotha 132 Albrecht-Carrié, R. 7 Alker, H. 156 American Civil War (1861–5) 26 American Historical Association 15, 116 Amin, S. 147 analogical reasoning 28–1, 47–9, 66–69, 84– 9, 97–2, 175–3 anank ē 35 anarchy: Bull, H. critique 179–7; historical critiques 101–8; neorealist model 96–3; postmodern critique 157–6, 161–9; realist conception 33 Anderson, B.: Imagined Communities 151 Anderson, M.S. 70 Angell, N.: The Great Illusion 50 Ankersmit, F.R. 27 Annales (Annales d’histoire économique et sociale/Annales: Économies, sociétés, civilisations) 7, 30, 115–1, 149, 177–5 Anschluss (1938) 138 antiquarianism 3 appeasement 34, 55–8 Arendt, H. 146 Aristotle, 12, 33, 64, 65, 69, 86, 170
Arnold, M. 12; Culture and Anarchy 170 Aron, R. 8, 33, 90, 98, 138, 175, 181 Ashley, R.: counter-memory 160–8; hegemonic discourse 157; identity and geopolitics 161; modern sovereignty critique 158–6; neorealism critique 105; and Walker, R.B.J. on decentering power 157–6 atavism 143, 166 Augustine, Saint 33, 39 Bacon, F. 54 balance of power: alternative explanations for 72–7; and cold war 74–9; as historiographic school 72; history of idea 69–3; and moral reasoning 43, 73; Morgenthau, H.J. theory 70–5, 73–8; neorealist model 104–10; Niebuhr, R. theory 43; Schroeder, P.W. revisionism 72–7 bandwagoning 72–6, 104 Bangladesh War (1971) 137 Barth, K. 41 Barthes, R. 153 Basel, Treaty of (1795) 68 Bates, M. 97 Baudrillard, J. 165–3 Bauman, Z. 168 Bayat, A.: Street Politics 150
211
212 INDEX
Beard, C.A. 16, 18, 51 Becker, C. 16, 18, 51, 65 Behavioral Correlates of War (BCOW) 121; coding methods 135–1; path dependence 135–2; process tracing 135–3 Benjamin, W. 145 Benson, L. 116 Bentham, J. 161 Berlin, I. 44–6 Birch, A.H. 24–6 Bismarck, O. von 96 Blainey, G. 23 Bloch, J. de: La Guerre Future 120 Bloch, M. 115 Bodin, J. 54 Bosnian War (1992–5) 143–50 Bradbury, M. 30 Bradley, A.C. 42 Bradley, F.H. 16 Braudel.: and Annales 188n.; history and social science 5; material civilization 151; The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II 141 Brezhnev, L. 80 Bridenbaugh, C. 116 British Committee for the Theory of International Politics 102 British-Zulu War (1879) 124 Brown, C. 142 Bryce, J.: International Relations 6 Buckley, W.F. 83 Bueno de Mesquita, B. 6, 134 Bull, H. 9, 54, 56, 97, 102, 179 Bultmann, A. 41 Burckhardt, J. 20, 40, 47, 48 Burke, E. 11, 33, 64, 67, 70, 72, 75 Burke, R 7 Bury, J.B. 15 Bush, President G. 163 Butterfield, H. 14, 31, 33–5, 102; balance of power 70; historical presentism 28–1; Whig interpretation of history 186n.
Buzan, B. 90, 102 Campbell, A.E. 179 Campbell, D.: creation of cold war identity 163; McCarthyism 163; US portrayal of Japan 164; US war on drugs 163–1; Writing Security 161–71 Canning, G. 71 Capote, T. 156 Carlos V 28 Carlyle, T. 14 Carnegie Corporation 119 Carnegie Commission on Preventing Deadly Conflicts 144 Carr, E.H. 14, 21, 31, 33–5, 48–58, 61, 101, 147; harmony of interests critique 49–2; on historical knowledge 51–4; on historical lessons 51; and historical selection 18, 52; idea of progress in 52; Locarno Treaty (1925) 55; Munich Conference (1938) 55–8; Nationalism and After 57; objectivity in history 52; power and historical judgment 55–58; progressivist historical interpretation 51–7; realism critique 49; sociology of knowledge 31, 49–2; The Soviet Impact on the Western World 58; task of the historian 52–5; Twenty Years’ Crisis 28, 49–3; What Is History? 52 Carter, President J. 100 Cassirer, E.: The Philosophy of the Enlightenment 12 Castellanos, P.Z.: Vida Militar de Centro America 124 Castlereagh, Viscount 67, 76 Cecil, Lord R. 68 Cecil, R. 54 Central American War (1907) 124 Chaco War (1932–5) 130–7, 132 Changkufeng War (1938) 124
INDEX 213
Chauncey, G.: Gay New York 150 chronophonism 165 Churchill, W. 72 Cicero 47 Clark, I.: Globalization and Fragmentation 169 Clausewitz, K. von 73, 136 Clinton, President W.J. 163 cliometrics: advent 115–3; Annales 115–1; creative process 123–9; and diplomatic history 118; reception by historians 116–2; reproducibility 119; see also Correlates of War; Singer, J.D.; Small, M. Cod War (1975–6) 138 cold war: and balance of power 74–9; and emergence of international relations theory 61–5, 187n.; foreign policy texts 162–70; Kennan, G.F. on origins 81–8; Morgenthau, H.J. on origins 74–9, 79–4; neorealist explanation of collapse 107; shaping historical interpretation 29–2; theoretical paralysis 180–8; Waltz, K.N. on stability 100–5 Collier, C. 175 Collingwood, R.G. 16, 26, 51 Comparative Studies in Society and History 118 Comte, A. 10, 46 Condorcet, Marquis de 10 Congo Arabs War (1892) 126 Congress of Vienna (1815) 104–9, 119 constructivism 89, 90 contagion theory 167 containment: Gaddis, J.L. on 80; Kennan, G.F. on 81–86; Long Telegram and 81–6; Morgenthau, H.J. on theory and practice 79; NSC-68, codified in 83; origins of 79–4, 187n.;
as political instrument 83; US domestic political impact 161–70; and “X” article 82 Coox, A.: Anatomy of a Small War 124 Correlates of War (COW): alliances 119, 139; assessed 139–7; background 113, 119–5; battle deaths gauged 124–30; bipolar stability 119, 139; confidence levels 125; contrasting data sets 132–9; controlled historical experiments 122; correlational knowledge 121; crisis behavior 135–3; data sets 121; data-making 122–32; data-testing 127–7; eurocentric bias/exclusion of nonsystem members 126, 132; existential knowledge 120–6; explanatory knowledge 121–7; inclusion criteria 120, 132–9, 188n.; major findings 118–4; materials capabilities measured 135; neorealist critique 89; nomothetic approach 120, 140–7; positivism 139–6; prestige gauged 135; qualitative critique 138–5; quantitative fallacy 134–45; realism of 125–2; reproducibility 119, 123–9, 126–32, 128– 7, 140; volatility of data 134; see also cliometrics; data-making; Singer, J.D.; Small, M. Council on Foreign Relations 44 counter-memory 159–8 Cox, R. 101 Craig, G. 10 Crick, B. 87 Critical Theory 142, 145 Croce, B. 6, 16, 24, 39, 51 Cuban Missile Crisis (1962) 139
214 INDEX
Danish-German War (1863–4) 137 data-making: BCOW (Behavioral Correlates of War) 135–3; paradigmatic activity 125–1, 188n.; perils 132–9; quantitative fallacy 134–45; reproducibility 123–30; Schroeder, P. critique 136–3 Davies, N. 156 Dean, M. 153–60 Dehio, L. 7, 72; The Precarious Balance 28 democratic peace: and Correlates of War 119, 139; historiographic debate 26–9; Kant, I. 26–9; quantitative analysis 27, 186n.; Russett, B. 139, 186n. Der Derian, J.: Antidiplomacy: Spies, Terror, and Speed 167 Derrida, J. 152–9, 154, 156 Dessler, D. 139 Dewey, J. 42 Dickenson, G.L.: The International Anarchy 70 Diderot, D.: Lettre sur les Aveugles 17 Dilthey, W. 13, 16, 21 Diplomacy and Statecraft 118 Diplomatic History 118 Donelan, M. 160 Dray, W. 182 Droysen, J.G. 16 Dulles, J.F. 44 Durkheim, E. 93 East Timor 151 Emerton, E. 15 Engels, F. 54 Enlightenment: Cartesian view 12; Morgenthau, H.J. critique 59–3; Niebuhr, R. critique 40–2; and positivism 10–11; postmodern critique 142, 145–2 Enola Gay 4
Europe’s Catechism 11 European peace movement 30 événement-matrice 30, 138 Fashoda Crisis (1898) 138 Faulkner, W. 156 Febvre, L. 115 Federalist 51 71 Fénelon, F. 7, 72, 76 Ferguson, Y 103–8; and Mansbach, R. The Elusive Quest 174 First World War (1914–18) 110, 124, 125 Fischer, D.H. 134 Fischer, H.A. L. 183 Fischer, M. 106 Fleiss, R: Thucydides and the Politics of Bipolarity 28 Fogel, R. and Engerman, S.: Time on the Cross:The Economics of American Negro Slavery 117 Foreign Relations of the United States 4 Foucault, M. 12, 21; archeology and genealogy 153–60; history as politics 153–60; juridical-political sovereignty critique 157; on power/knowledge 142 Fox, C. 67 Fox, W.T.R. 97 Franco-Russian Alliance (1894) 99 Frankfurt School 145 Fraser, R.: Blood of Spain 151 French Revolution (1789) 76 Fukuyama, F. 7, 9, 38 Furet, F. 116 Fussell, P. 145 Gadamer, H.-G. 20 Gaddis, J.L. 5, 7, 10, 80, 107 Galtung, J. 97 García Marquez, G. 156 Garibaldi, G. 128 Geddes, B. 2, 175 German historical school 16, 54 Geyl, R 16, 183 Gibbon, E. 7, 72, 74;
INDEX 215
Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire 82 Gilpin, R. 35 Ginzburg, C. 12 globalization 28; begetting cultural amnesia 168; and hybridization 168–6; postmodern views of 167–6 Goldenweiser, A. 173 Gorbachev, M. 182 Graham, B. 164 Gukciardini, F. 7, 13, 72, 161 Gulf War (1991) 4, 125, 138, 165–3 Gulick, E.V. 7, 72, 77 Hall, R. 106 Halle, L. 7, 33–5, 84 Halliday, F. 179; Rethinking International Relations 169 Hamilton, A. 71 Hardenberg, K.A. 68 harmony of interests 28, 50–3 Harvey, D. 145, 165, 168 Hastrup, K.: Other Histories 151 Havel, V. 182 Heaney, S. 86 Hegel, G.W.F. 46, 54 Hempel, C. 20, 23, 90 Herodotus 28, 34 Herz, J. 33 heteroglossia 150 Hexter, J.H. 178 Hill, C. 7, 26 Historical Methods 118 historicizing identity 161–71 history: and balance of power 69–5; and causality 2, 21–3, 36; context of 137, 177–5; and contingency 29; counter-memory 159–8; covering model 23; defined 7–8; differentia specifica of 22; event-centered 7; and experience 16–17; Foucauldian 153–60;
genealogy 154, 164; Herodotus and histori 34; ideology 2, 18–19, 24–6, 153–60; idiographic versus nomothetic 22–5; inference versus observation 20–3; Kennan, G.F. on subjectivity 85–86; laboratory 6, 90–5; linguistic turn in 152–9; literature 154–2; policy, translated into 66–69, 86–1; and political necessity 31, 35; as politics 153–60; post-historical world 170–8; postmodern critique 153–63; quantitative approaches, emergence of 115–3; reactions to postmodern 170; selection 2–3, 18, 26–9, 94, 123–9, 175–5; skeptical view vii–3, 10–12, 16–20, 21–3, 25–8, 51–5, 94, 132–9, 147–4, 153–63, 182–90; social science approach 20–6; Thucydides on standards of evidence 34; top-down versus bottom-up 178–8; traditional versus scientific 24–6; as Western myth 142; Whiggish view 21 history and international relations: balance-of-power historiography 72; and foundational narrative 147; historical analogies 28–1, 97–2; historical sociology 179–7; involution of 171–82; levels of analysis 178–6; new history and postmodern theory 147– 8; parallel development of 10; policy history 66–69, 86–1; Procrustean treatment 11, 24–9, 28–1, 69, 86–1, 104–12, 110–16, 125–2, 134–45, 153–62, 174–2; Ranke and 15–16, 25, 178–6; relationship between 3–5, 7, 8–10, 22–6, 93–8, 149–8, 177–5, 182; respective appropriation of Thucydides 35–7; role of skepticism 94, 132–9, 147–4, 153– 63, 182–90;
216 INDEX
selection bias 2–3, 18, 26–9, 94, 123–9, 175–5; top-down versus bottom-up history 178– 8; US contrasted with Britain 7 Hitler, A. 27, 28, 34, 60 Hobbes, T. vii, 33, 35, 54, 65, 79, 161; Leviathan 17 Hobson, J.A. 97 Hoetsch, O. 81 Hoffmann, S. 2, 28, 44, 97, 174, 187n. Holsti, O. 118, 170 Hoover, J.E. 164 Howard, M. 7, 35, 102, 140 Hume, D. 10, 33 Huntington, S. 9 Huxley, A. 156 Iggers, G. 15 Indonesian War (1945–6) 131 International History Review 118 international relations theory: ambiguities 181; and classical Greek theory 177; consideration of statecraft in 181–9; defined 8; historical skepticism 182–90; involution of 171–82; microeconomic theory analogy 98–3, 174–2; as philosophy of history 33–5, 38; recovery 176–4; role of 24; testing 25; see also Carr, E.H.; Correlates of War; Kennan, G. E; Morgenthau, H.J.; neorealism; Niebuhr, R.; postmodernism; realism; Singer, J.D.; Waltz, K.N. International Security 26, 170, 180–8 Iran-Iraq War (1980–8) 111, 125 Italo-Turkish War (1911–12) 129–6
Jameson, F. 152 Javanese War (1825–30) 124, 126 Jay, J. 71 Jefferson, President T. 43 Jervis, R. 29; Perception and Misperception in International Politics 108 Johnson, J.: Latin America in Caricature 151 Johnson, N. 11, 30 Jones, E.L. 22 Joseph II, Emperor 104 Journal of Historical Review 4 Journal of Interdisciplinary History 117, 118 Journal of Social History 118 Jouvenel, B. de 146 Joyce, J. 156 Joyce, P. 156 Kafka, F. 156 Kagan, D. 7 Kamenev, L.B. 47 Kant, I. 7, 26–9, 46, 94, 161, 183 Kaplan, M. 24, 97 Kautilya 65, 103 Kaye, H. 3 Kedourie, E. 117 Kennan, G.F. 31–4, 33–5, 79–86, 145, 163, 175, 181; American Diplomacy 86; on analogic reasoning 84–9; Around the Cragged Hill 81; At a Century’s Ending 81; and end of the cold war 84, 86; historical method 80–5, 84–86; laws of politics 86; Long Telegram 81–6; The Marquis de Custine and His “Russia in 1839” 80, 82; moralism 81; national interest 86; origins of containment 81–86; pessimism 86; post-cold war world 84–86; Russian domestic politics 83; Russian political culture 82–8; Soviet political economy 84;
INDEX 217
Soviet-American Relations, 1917–1920 85; Stalinism 80; Williams, W.A. critique 85; “X” article 82–8 Kennedy, P. 7, 84; Rise and Fall of the Great Powers 28 Keynes, J.M. 62 Khomeini, Ayatollah 109, 111 Khong, F.K.: Analogies at War 29 Khrushchev, N. 4 Kindleberger, C. 100 King, G., Keohane, R., and Verba, S.: Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research 175–3; historical selection bias 175–3 Kissinger, H. 33, 44 Kjellen, R. 54 Klerck, E.S. de: History of the Netherlands East Indies 124 Koestler, A. 3, 146 Korean War (1950–3) 27, 125, 139 Kosovo Field, Battle of (1389) 166 Kosygin, A.N. 80 Kratochwil, F. 106, 112 Krause, J. and Renwick, N.: Identities in International Relations 169 Kristeva, J. 158 Kuhn, T.: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 21 Kundera, M. 3 Kurds, in Turkish historiography 4; cultural resistance 151 Ladurie, E. le R. 116, 117; Montaillou 150 Lakatos, I. 25, 108, 173; quantitative analysis 92; scientific research programs, 91–6 Lapid, Y. 2; and Kratochwil, F. Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory 169 Layne, C. 26–9 League of Nations 50, 54, 60, 70 Lefebvre, G. 116 Leffler, M. 5, 10 Lenin, V.I. 47, 47, 54, 97, 109
Lévi-Strauss, C. 93 Levy, J. 29, 134, 138 Liska, G. 70 Little Entente of Czechoslovakia, Romania, and Yugoslavia (1920–1) 72 Little, R. 24–6, 102 Livy 36, 37–9, 186n. Locarno Treaty (1925) 55 Locke, J. 46 Lopez War (1864–70) 138 Lukács, G. 21 Lustick, I. 6, 176 Lyotard, J.-F. 144–1, 146, 156 Macaulay, T.B. 14; History of England 154 Machiavelli, N. 13, 31, 33, 34, 39, 51, 65, 103, 142; Art of War 161; counter-memorialized reading 160–8; Discourses on Livy 36–8, 58, 161; historical method 36–8; History of Florence 161; Italian nationalism 37–9; modernity of 37; philosophy of history 37; The Prince 36–8, 160; realism, roots of 36–9 Madison, President J. 71 Mahoney, J. 175 Maier, C. 118, 178 Mailer, N. 156 Maitland, F.W. 137, 177 Mann, G. 156 Mann, M. 179 Mannheim, K. 21, 52, 61; Ideology and Utopia 49–2 Mansbach, R. 103–8 Mansfield, E. 132 Mao 109 Marshall Plan 85 Marshall, B. 148 Marshall, G.C. 35 Marwick, A. 14, 154 Marx, K. 7, 21, 47, 144, 161; capitalism, global effects of 167; The Communist Manifesto 167;
218 INDEX
German Ideology 49 May, E.: “Lessons” of the Past 29 May, E. and Neustadt, R.: Thinking in Time 11 Mayers, D. 85 McCarthyism 163–1 McDonald, J. 96 McNamara, R. 4 McNeill, R. 7 McNeill, W. 156 Mead, M. 22 Mearsheimer, J. 104, 170 Melian Dialogue 35 metanarrative 143, 144–3 Michnik, A. 182 Middle East Studies Association 156 Milosevic, S. 144 Molotov-Ribbentropp Pact (1939) 72 Monroe Doctrine 72 Montesquieu, C.L., Baron de 98 Morgenthau, H.J. 28, 31–4, 56, 81, 135, 145, 175; American alliance building 75; balance of power 69–5, 73–9; bipolar stability critique 74; cold war critic 75; cold war theory and practice 79–4; Enlightenment critique 59–3; historical method 64–9; history truncated 78, 86–1; on ideology 63; international society romanticized 75– 78; international system 74–9; knowledge, relativity of 61; laws of politics 61–5, 78; leadership 78–3; legacy 78–3; multipolarity 74; nationalism 74; neorealist critique of 89–4; nuclear age 74, 76–1; policy history 66–69; political science 60–4, 64–9; Politics Among Nations vii, 61–7, 75; positivism of 61; power politics 59–4, 62–6;
prudence 79; realism as public philosophy 62; Scientific Man vs. Power Politics 59–4, 69; on Thucydides and Ranke 66; and Toynbee 66; on US foreign aid 68; and Vietnam War 66–68, 75, 186n. Moroney, M.J. 140 Morris, D.: Washing of the Spears 124 Mozambique War (1964–75) 126 Munich Settlement (1938) 34, 55–8 Naipaul, V.S. 111 Napoleonic Wars (1796–1815) 72, 84–9 narrative history 147–8, 156 Nasser, A. 137 National Science Foundation 119 National Security Council 21, 83–8, 163 nationalist historiography: Eastern Europe 4; and ethnohistory 3–4; in Machiavelli 37–9; Turkish 4 neorealism: anarchy assumption 102–8; Ashley, R. critique 105; classical realism critique 87; end of cold war explained 107; eurocentrism 102–7; historical change 105–12; historical critiques 102–12; history truncated 104–12, 110–16, 111– 18; international ethics 112–18; philosophy of history 101–6; political process 111–18; Ruggie, J. critique 105–11; Schroeder, P. critique 104–10; state blackboxed 97; theory of foreign policy 112; see also Walt, S.M.; Waltz, K.N. new history 7; and oral tradition 151; and popular culture 151; postmodern politics 147–8;
INDEX 219
privileging 152; and traditional narrative 180 Newsom, D. 175 Nicholas I 80 Niebuhr, H.R. 41 Niebuhr, R. 31, 33, 61, 78, 84, 95, 145, 175; assessed 48; balance of power 43–5; British imperialism 46–8; The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness 86; Gifford Lectures 40; historical determinism critique 44–6; human nature and historical contingency 39–2; The Irony of American History 43; liberalism critique 46; liberalism in 41; Moral Man and Immoral Society 49; Morgenthau, H.J. critique 45 nuclear age 44, 186n.; pacifism critique 41; progress critique 40–2; prophetic minority 42, 186n.; relativism 48; religion, role in imperialism 47–9; Structure of Nations and Empires 31, 45–48; tragic conception of history 41–4 Nietzsche, F.W. 16, 25–8, 65, 148, 170; and Foucault 154; Genealogy of Morals 154 North, R. 118 Novick, P. 20; That Noble Dream: The “Objectivity Question” and the American Historical Profession 2 Oakeshott, M. 12, 51, 58, 146, 153, 177; constructionist theory of historiography 16–20; historical causality 20–2; historical skepticism 16–19; history and practice 17; On History 19–1 orientalism 110–16 Orwell, G. 3, 146 Owen, J. 26–9
Palmerston, Lord 27 Pastry War (1838–9) 138 path dependence 135–2 Peace of Ouchy (1912) 130 periodization, historical 19, 24, 85, 132 Petrarch 38 philosophical history 7; Kennan, G.F. on 80–5; Machiavelli, N. on 37; neorealism and 101–6; Niebuhr, R. on 41–4; Ranke and 13–14; Wight, M. theory 33–5 phronesis 170 Pitt, W. 67 Plato 36, 61 political necessity 31, 35, 37–9, 86 Pollard, A.F. 70 Polybius 36 Popper, K. 25, 90–5, 146 positivism 2, 11, 14, 92, 139–6 postmodernism: anti-essentialism 143; atavism 166; commodity culture 156; counter-memory 159–8; crisis of re-presentation 152–9; decentering power 157–6; Derrida and différance 152–8; disrupting time and space 164–4; foundational narrative 147; globalization 167–6; hegemonic discourse 156–4; heroic history critique 149–6; historicizing identity 161–71; history as literature 154–2; history as politics 153–60; illiberalism of 170; metanarrative critique 143, 144–3; overview 143–50; pastiche in 143; power/knowledge 144; Rorty, R. rendition 170; synchronism versus diachronism 166; time-space compression 144; traditional reactions to 170; trope of the body 162–70; universal truth 146–3, 148;
220 INDEX
war imagery 165–3 presentism: historical 2–3, 18–19, 24–7, 28–2, 101, 186n. Price, R. 156 Puchala, D. 115, 176 quantitative fallacy 134–45 quantitative history: see cliometrics; Correlates of War Rabb, T. 117 raison d’état 37 RAND Corporation 156 Ranke, L. von 2, 104, 142, 169, 184n.; American historical profession 15; balance-of-power historiography 72; correspondence theory of history 12–16; History of England 13; History of the Latin and Teutonic Nations from 1494 to 1514 13; international relations theory 25, 178–6; levels of analysis 178–6; and political realism 15–16 Rann of Kutch (1965) 138 Rauschenbusch, W. 42 Reagan, President R. 100, 163, 164 realism: anarchy 33; and balance of power 43–5, 69–9, 100–5; defined 33; human nature 33; moral choice 33; neorealist contrast 87, 94; origins of cold war 187n.; philosophy of history 33–5, 37–9; political necessity 31, 35, 37, 38, 86; quantitative testing 187n.; Rankean history 15–16, 25, 178–6; rational reconstruction 61, 91–6; Schroeder, P.W. revisionism 72–7; see also Carr, E.H.; Kennan, G. R; Morgenthau, H.J.; neorealism; Niebuhr, R.;
Waltz, K.N. Reiser, O.: Planetary Democracy 167 revisionism, historical 4–5, 27–28 Revue d’histoire diplomatique 118 Reynolds, C. 28 Richardson, L. 120, 132; on gauging battle deaths 124–30 Riffian War (1921–6) 138 Robinson, J.H. 16 Rorty, R. 170 Rosecrance, R. 97 Rosenau, J.: Along the Domestic-Foreign Frontier 169 Rosenau, P. 146, 149, 189n. Rosenberg, J. 101 Rousseau, J.-J. 33, 76, 94, 96 Rucellai, G. 72 Ruggie, J. 105–11 Rushdie, S. 111, 156 Russian Revolution (1917) 110 Russo-Afghan War (1979–88) 124 Ryan, A. 21 Ryle, G. 17 Said, E. 156 Saint-Simon, H.C. 10 Saint-Pierre, Abbé de: Project for Perpetual Peace in Europe 60 Savonarola, G. 161 Schäfer, D. 177 Schama, S. 156 Scherer, P. 38 Schlesinger, A., Jr. 41, 116, 183 Schlossstein, S. 164 Schroeder, P. 26, alternative explanations to balance of power 72–7; data-making critique 136–3; neorealism critique 104–10; on political equilibrium 72–7; realist view of international society critiqued 77 Schwarzenberger, G. 33, 63–7; Power Politics 177 Scott, J.C.: Domination and the Arts of Resistance 150
INDEX 221
Second World War (1939–45) 72, 124, 125, 138 security—power dilemma 35 Seeley, J. 7, 51, 66, 174 Seneca 47 Sepoy War (1857–9) 128 Sevères, Treaty of (1920) 110 Simon, J. 54 Sinai War (1956–7) 137–4 Singer, J.D. and Small, M.: and content analysis 123; experimenter bias 123; Resort to Arms 121, 125; theory defined 121–7; The Wages of War 24; see cliometrics; see also Correlates of War skepticism: historical vii–3, 10–12, 21–3, 94, 132–9, 139–7; Beard, C. theory 18; Carr, E.H. view 18, 51–5; Nietzsche, F. 25–8; Novick, P. 2; Oakeshott on 16–20; postmodernism and 147–4, 153–63; uses in international relations 182–90 Small, M. 118, 134; data-making 123; resistance to quantitative history 119; see Correlates of War; Singer, J.D. Smith, Adam 46, 74 Smith, Anthony 3, 7 Smith, M.J. 61, 186n. Soccer War (1969) 138 Social Science History 118 Social Science History Association 118 Sokol’nikov, G.Y. 47 Sorokin, P. 120 Spencer, H. 10, 46 Spengler, O. 7, 46 Spinoza, B. 54, 94 Spykman, N. 33 Stählin, K. 81 Stalin, J. 44, 47, 58, 80 Stark, W. 16 Stone, L. 149
Stretton, H. 23 Stubbs, W. 72 Suez Crisis (1956) 135, 138 Sun Tzu 103 Susman, W. 151 Sybel, C.L.H. von 16 Tacitus 36 Talleyrand, C.M. de 68 Taylor, A.J.P. 29, 55, 72 theoretical filtering 3, 25–9, 29–2, 86–1, 109– 16, 125–2, 153–60, 174–2 Thompson, W.S. 93–8 Thorne, C. 9 Thrasymachus 54 Thucydides, 7, 9, 15, 29, 31, 33, 72, 103; History of the Peloponnesian War 34–7, 112; moral tragedy of war 112; roots of realism 34–7 Thurmond, S. 164 Tilly, C. 117 Tocqueville, A. de 62 Toynbee, A. 46, 50, 156 Treitschke, H. von 16, 54 Trent Affair (1861) 27 Trevor-Roper, H. 182 Triple Alliance of Germany, AustriaHungary, and Italy (1882–1915) 99 Trotsky, L. 47 Trouillot, M.-R.: Silencing the Past 150 Tujman, F. 144 tunnel history 178 Turkish Revolution (1921) 110–16 Turner, F.J. 15 Turner, R: I Heard It Through the Grapevine 151 US foreign aid 68 US Institute of Peace 119–5 Utrecht, Treaty of (1713) 71 Vasquez, J. 59, 123–9, 187n. Vattel, E. 75, 76 Venezuela-British Guyana border dispute (1895–6) 26 Versailles, Treaty of (1919) 34, 60
222 INDEX
Veyne, P. 12 Vietnam Wars (1945–75) 100, 125; Morgenthau, H.J. critique 66–68, 75 Vincent, J. 102 Virilio, R: Speed and Politics 166 Vlekke, B.: Nusantara 124 Voegelin, E. 146 Walker, R.B. J.: on counter-memory 160–8; on decentering power 157–6 Wallerstein, I. 97, 100 Walt, S.M.: Revolution and War 107–16 Waltz, K.N. 23, 25, 28, 30, 33, 170; analogic reasoning 97–2; assessment 101–6; bipolar stability 100; change 105–12; covering laws 90; deductive method 89–4, 93–8; economic model 98–3; eurocentrism 102–7; Foreign Policy and Democratic Politics 96; functional similarity of states 104–10; historical confirmation 92; history truncated 102–8, 105–12; interdependence and conflict 99–4; international ethics 112–18; Lakatos, I. 91–6; levels of analysis 95–96; Man, the State and War 94–96; nuclear weapons 100–5; Popper, K. 90–5; Soviet Union collapse 107; structural analysis 93; theory and fact 92, 107–13; theory defined 89–4; Theory of International Politics 90, 92, 96, 97–6; US and British foreign policy contrasted 96 War of Italian Unification (1859) 128–5 War of the Triple Alliance (1864–70) 130 Watson, A. 102,
critique of anarchy 103–8 Weber, M. 22, 24, 33, 65, 161 Wendt, A. 104 White, H. 20; on history as literature 154–2; uses of history 170 Whitfield, S.: Culture of the Cold War 151 Wight, M. 9, 24, 24, 31, 33, 38, 86 Wilde, O. 12 Williams, W.A. 85 Wilson, President W. 58, 60 Whitfield, S.: The Idea of Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy 182 Wolf, E.: Europe and the People Without History 150 Wolfers, A. 33 Woolf, L. 132 Wooten, H. 68 Wright, Q. 2, 77, 120, 132; The Study of International Relations 89 Xenophon 36 Yeats, W.B. 156 Zemon-Davis, N.: The Return of Martin Guerre 150 Zinoviev, G.Y. 47