This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
(4)
Note that this example is in the case of a "gap" and satisfies condition (L), so by Theorein 4 there exists a unique stationary triplet. First, let us consider the case where ~/~ < b, i.e., the monopoly price on the static demand curve (4) equals b_. Observe that since the seller will never offer a price more favorable than she would if she were facing the strongest buyer type for sure, the buyer will always accept äny price below b_ with probability one. Thus, in any sequential equilibrium, the seller's payoff must be no lower than her static monopoly profits, b_. Meanwhile, Stokey (1979) showed that the optimal selling policy of a dynamic monopolist with perfect commitment power consists of charging the static monopoly price, and never lowering price thereafter [see also the closely related "no-haggling" result of Riley and Zeckhauser (1983)]. Since a monopolist lacking commitment power can only do worse, the seller's equilibrium profits must also be no higher than her static equilibrium profits. We conclude that there is a unique sequential equilibrium outcome, with the seller charging the price b, and all buyer types accepting. Note that this equilibrium is supported by the unique stationary triplet V ( Q ) = (1 - Q)b, t ( Q ) = 1, and using (3), P ( q ) = (1 - 3)/~ + 3b for q 6 [0, ~] and P ( q ) = b for q c (~, 1]. When c~D > b, bargaining necessarily takes place over multiple periods, but the above argument still contains the key to uniqueness of the stationary triplet. Indeed, let us define ql as the lowest value of the state such that b is a monopoly price on the residual demand curve starting at ql, i.e.,/~(~ - ql) = b(1 - ql). A parallel argument to the orte given above then establishes that once the state reaches beyond ql, the seller will necessarily end the bargaining immediately, by offering the price b. The role of condition (L) in Theorem 4 is to more generally guarantee the existence of a critical level ql < 1 such that whenever the state exceeds ql the dispersion of valuations of the remaining buyer types is such that it no longer pays the seller to price discriminate amongst them. With the endplay tied down, backward induction on the state then completes the uniqueness argument. To see how this works, observe that there exists a q2 < ql, such that whenever the state is in (q2, q 1] the seller will select to bring the state in the interval (ql, 1]. Indeed, whenever q2 is sufficiently near ql, any potential gain from increased
L.M. Ausubel et al.
1916
price discrimination over the interval (q2, ql ] is outweighed by the loss due to delayed receipt of the profits V(ql). In out two-type model, when the state is in (q2, ql] the monopolist will therefore offer Pl = (1 - 3)/~ + 6b_, which all buyer types in [0, c)] accept. In this fashion, we can keep on recursively extending the stationary triplet to the entire interval [0, 1]. Buyer types in the interval (qi, q i - l ] will be indifferent between accepting Pi and waiting one period to receive Pi-1, and the state qi is such that the monopolist is indifferent between offering Pi ( w i t h all buyer types in (qi, qi - 1] accepting) and offering p i - I ( w i t h all buyer types in (qi, qi-2] accepting). More precisely, we can compute the following explicit solution. Let q-1 = 1, q0 = c), and inductively define the sequence ql > q2 > " " > qN from: mn = e~~-(n-1)mn-1
(n /> 2),
(5)
and the initial condition ma = (c~ - 1)m0, using m,~ = qn-~ - q,z, o~ = b / ( b - b_), and N = min{n: qn ~< 0}. Also, let Pn be such that a buyer with valuation/~ is indifferent between accepting Pn today and waiting n periods to receive the offer b: Pn = (1 - 3n)/; ÷ 3'~b.
(6)
THEOREM 5. Let v(q) be given by (4), and let qN <~ 0 < qN-I < "'" < qo = ~l be defined by (5). Then with every (purified) sequential equilibrium o f the seller-offer game is associated the unique stationary triplet: P(Q) =ph, t(Q)=qn
2,
V ( Q ) -= p n - l ( q n - 2 - Q) + ~V(qn-2),
PROOF. See Deneckere (1992).
Q ~ (qn,qn 1], Q E (qn,qn-/] /fn > 1, Q E (ql,1]
/fn = 1,
Q~(qn,qn
i]
Q 6 (ql, 1]
ifn=l.
/fn>l,
and
and
[]
According to Theorem 5, when qN < 0 bargaining lasts for N periods. The seller starts out by offering the price PN-1 = P ( q N - 2 ) , which is accepted by all buyer types in the interval [0, qN-2]. Play then continues with the seller offering pN-2, which all buyer types in (qN-2, qN-3] accept, and so on, until the state qo is reached at which point the seller makes the final offer po. When qN = 0, the seller can freely randomize between charging PN and P N - I. However, given the outcome of the randomization, the remainder of the equilibrium path is uniquely determined: if the seller initially selects PN play lasts for (N -t- 1) periods, and if she selects PN-1 play lasts for N periods. Note, however, that the condition qN = 0 is highly nongeneric, in two senses. First, if the initial state is slightly different from qN the outcome is unique. Secondly, since the condition qN = 0 is equivalent to mo ÷ . . • + m N = 1, it follows from (5) that for generic («, 8) the outcome path is unique.
Ch. 50: Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1917
The closed form (5) also allows us to investigate the behavior of the solution as bargaining frictions become smaller, i.e., players become more patient [see also Hart (1989), Proposition 2]. Intuitively, for fixed acceptance function P, the seller will discriminate more and more finely as she becomes more patient, approaching perfect price discrimination on the acceptance function P as 8 converges to one. Counteracting this is that for fixed seller behavior, as the buyer becomes more patient, the acceptance function will become flatter and flatter, in the limit approaching the constant b = v (1) as 8 converges to 1. If we fix 8s and let 8B converge to one, the seller loses all bargaining power. On the other hand, if we fix 6B and let 8s increase, the seller will gain bargaining strength [Sobel and Takahashi (1983)]. With equal discount factors, the two forces more or less balance each other out. To see this, note from (5) that mn is decreasing, and hence that the number of bargaining rounds N is increasing in 6. However, as the limiting solution to (5) is given by mn = oenm0, we see that regardless of the discount factor, the number of bargaining rounds is bounded above by: N = m i n { n : e~"m0/> 1}. While the number of equilibrium bargaining rounds therefore increases with 3, the existence of a uniform upper bound to the number of bargaining rounds implies that the cost of delay (as measured by the forgone surplus) vanishes as 8 approaches one. A slightly weaker, but qualitatively similar, proposition has become known in the literature as the "Coase Conjecture", after Nobel laureate Ronald Coase, who argued that a durable goods monopolist selling an infinitely durable good to a demand curve of atomistic buyers would lose its monopoly power if it could make frequent price offers [Coase (1972)]. The connection with the durable goods literamre obtains because to every actual buyer type in the durable goods model, there corresponds an equivalent potential buyer type in the bargaining model. To formally state the Coase Conjecture, let us denote the length of the period between successive seller offers by z, and let r be the discount rate common to the bargaining parties, so that 8 = e -rz . We then have: THEOREM 6 (Coase Conjecmre). Suppose we are in the case o f a gap. Then f o r every e > 0 and valuationfunction v(.), there exists ~ > 0 such that, f o r every time interval z E (0, ~) between offers and f o r every sequential equilibrium, the initial offer in the seller-offer bargaining game is no more than b -5 e and the buyer accepts the seller's offer with probability one by time ~.
PROOF. Gul, Sonnenschein and Wilson [(1986), Theorem 3].
[]
Note that Theorem 6 immediately follows from Theorem 4, by selecting ~ ~< c / N , and by noting that since the highest valuation buyer always has the option to wait until period N to accept the price b, the seller's initial price can be no more than (1 - 8N)v(0) + 8Nb, which converges to b as z converges to zero. For empirical or
1918
L.M. Ausubel et al.
experimental work, Theorem 6 has the unfortunate implication that real bargaining delays can only be explained by either exogenous limitations on the frequency with which bargaining partners can make offers, or by significant differences in the relative degree of impatience between the bargaining parties.
3.1.2. Alternating offers When the uninformed party makes all the offers, the informed party has very limited means of communication. At any point in time, buyer types can only separate into two groups, those who accept the current offer and thereby terminate the garne, and those who reject the current offer in order to trade at more favorable terms in the future. Since higher valuation buyer types stand to lose more from delaying trade, the equilibrium necessarily has a screening strucmre. In the alternating-offer game, screening will still occur in any seller-offer period, for exactly the same reason. During buyer-offer periods, however, the informed party has a much richer language with which to communicate, so a much richer class of outcomes becomes possible. There is now a potential for the buyer to signal his type, with higher valuation buyer types trading oft higher prices for a higher probability of acceptance. But as in the literamre on labor market signaling, many other types of outcomes can be sustained in sequential equilibrium, with different buyer types pooling or partially pooling on common equilibrium offers. Researchers have long considered many of these equilibria to be implausible, because they are sustained by the threat of adverse inferences following out-of-equilibrium offers. Unfortunately, the literature on refinements has concentrated mostly on pure signaling garnes [Cho and Kreps (1987)], so there exist few selection criteria applicable to the more complicated extensive-form games we are considering here. In narrowing down the range of equilibrium predictions, researchers have therefore resorted to criteria which try to preserve the spirit of refinements developed for signaling games, but the necessarily ad hoc nature of those criteria has led to a variety of equilibrium predictions [Rubinstein (1985a), Cho (1990b), Bikchandani (1992)1. ~2 To select plausible equilibria, Ausubel and Deneckere (1998) propose a refinement of perfect equilibrium, termed assuredly perfect equilibrium (APE). Assuredly perfect equilibrium requires stronger player types (e.g., lower valuation buyer types) to be infinitely more likely to tremble than weaker player types, as the tremble probabilities converge to zero. The purpose of making the strong player types much more likely to tremble is to rule out adverse inferences: following an unexpected move by the informed party, beliefs must be concentrated on the strong type, unless this action yields the weak
12 One notable exception is Grossman and Perry (1986a), who develop a general selection critefion, termed perfect sequential equilibrium, and apply it to the altemating-offerbargaining game (1986). However,perfect sequential equilibria do not generally exist, and in fact fall to do so in the alternating-offerbargaining game when the discount factor is sufficiently high. This is unfortunate, as the case where bargaining frictions become small is of special importance in light of the literamre on the Coase Conjecture. General existence is also a problem in Cho (1990b) and Bikchandani (1992).
Ch. 50:
Bargaining with lncomplete Information
1919
type its equilibrium utility. 13 Thus beliefs are not permitted to shift to the weak type unless there is a reason why (in the equilibrium) the weak type may wish to select the deviant action. APE has the advantage of being relatively easy to apply, and is guaranteed to always exist in finite garnes. Importantly, for the two-type alternating-offer bargaining model given by (4), Ausubel and Deneckere (1998) show that for generic priors there exists a unique APE.14 We will describe this equilibrium outcome here only for the garne in which the seller moves first (this facilitates comparison with the seller-offer garne). For this purpose, let us define fi = max{n e Z+: 1 - 6 2 n - 2 - ~2n-lly-1 < 0}. The meaning of fi is that in equilibrium, regardless of the fraction of low valuation buyer types, the game always concludes in at most 2fi + 2 periods. This should be contrasted with the seller-offer garne, where the number of bargaining rounds grows without bound as the seller becomes more and more optimistic. The intuition behind this difference is that as the number of remaining bargaining rounds becomes larger, the seller extracts more and more surplus from the weak buyer type. 15 At the same time, there is an upper bound on how much the seller can extract, namely what he would obtain in the complete-information garne against the weak buyer type. In the seller-offer game, this is all of the surplus, explaining why with this offer structure the number of effective bargaining rounds can increase without bound as the seller becomes more and more optimistic. In contrast, in the complete-information alternating-offer garne the seller receives only a fraction 1/(1 + 8) of the surplus (when it is his turn to move). Consequently, in the alternating-offer garne the number of effective bargaining rounds taust be bounded above, no matter how optimistic the sellerJ 6 For the sake of brevity, we will consider here only the case where fi > 1 (note that this necessarily holds when 3 is sufficiently high). Qualitatively, the equilibrium has the following stmcture. Whenever it is the buyer's turn to make a proposal, all buyer types pool by making nonserious offers, until the seller becomes convinced he is facing the low valuation buyer. At this point, both buyer types pool by making the low valuation buyer's complete-information Rubinstein offer, r0 = 3_b/(1 + ~), which the seller accepts. The sequence of prices offered by the seller along the equilibrium path must keep the high valuation buyer indifferent, so we must have: pn = (1
- ~2n-1)~)
nc~2n-lr0,
n = 1. . . . . fi,
(7)
13 If an action yields the weak type less than its equilibrium utility, then in approximating garnes, the weak type must be using that action with minimum probability. As the ratio of the weak to the strong type's tremble probability converges to zero, fimifing beliefs will have to be concentrated on the strong type. 14 More precisely, they show that finte horizon versions of the altemating-offer bargaining garne in which the buyer makes the last offer has a unique APE for generic values of the prior. Below, we describe the limit of this equilibrium as the horizon length approaches infinity. 15 Formally, this is reflected in the fact that both sequences of prices (6) and (8) are increasing in n, and converge to/~ as n converges to infinity. 16 Formally, fi is the largest integer such that Pn remains below /3 = ,~/(1 + 3), the complete information seller offer against the weak buyer type.
1920
L.M. A u s u b e l et al.
unless the seller is extremely optimistic, in which case the garne starts out with ,6 = B/(1 + ~), the seller's offer in the c o m p l e t e - i n f o r m a t i o n garne against the weak buyer type. A n a l o g o u s to the seller-offer game, the sequence of cutoff levels qn is constructed so that at qn (n = 1 . . . . . h) the seller is indifferent b e t w e e n charging p~ and p h - l, and at qa+ 1 the seller is indifferent b e t w e e n charging/3 and pa. Formally, let q_ l = 1, qo = q, and inductively define the sequence of cutoff levels ql > q2 > " - > qa > qh+l ]:rom m l = (of -- 1)m0, m2 = f i ~ - I (1 q- ~ ) - l m l , mn= fi6-(2n-3)mn-1,
for 3 ~< n ~< h,
(8)
and m a + l = coma, where fi = b/[b - r0] and co = (1 - ~2){)/[/õ _ Ph]. To rule out n o n g e n e r i c cases, and again analogously to the seller-offer garne, let N = max{n ~< fi + 1: qn >~ 0}, and suppose qN > 0: THEOREM 7 [Ausubel and Deneckere (1998)]. Consider the alternating-offer garne,
and suppose that qN > O. Then in the unique APE outcome, foIlowing histories with no prior observable buyer deviations, the buyer uses a stationary acceptance strategy. If N <~h, this acceptance strategy is given by: P(q) = pn,
q c («~, q~-l], 0 <~n <~N,
P(q) = min{ph, fi},
« 6 [0, «N].
(9)
In equilibrium, the seller successively makes the offers PN, PN-1 . . . . . Pl, with the buyer accepting according to (9) and making nonserious counteroffers until Pl has been rejected. The buyer then counteroffers ro, which the seller accepts with probability olle.
If N = h + 1, the buyer's acceptance strategy is given by: P(q)=Pn,
qc(qn,qn-l], 0~
P(q) = ~,
q ~ [0, q~].
(10)
In equilibrium, the seller starts out by offering ~, which all buyer types in [0, ~~] accept, and all other lypes reject. Following a nonserious buyer offer, the seller then randomizes between the offers P;7 and P~-1 so as to make the weak buyer type indifferent between accepting and rejecting the previous seller offer 17 Following the offer pg the seller continues with the offers P~-I, Ph-2 . . . . . pl, and following the offer Pa-1 the seIler continues with the offers P~-2 . . . . . Pl. In each case, the buyer accepts according to (10), and makes nonserious counteroffers until Pl has been rejected. The game then ends with the buyer counteroffering ro, which the seller accepts with probability one.
17 In other words, denoting the weight on Ph by ~b,we have/~ -/3 = a2{q~(,~_ Ph) + (1 - ~b)(,~- pfi 1)}-
Ch. 50: Bargainingwith Incomplete Information
1921
One of the main thrusts of the literature on static signaling models has been to show that refinements based on stability [Kohlberg and Mertens (1986)] tend to select signaling equilibria [Cho and Sobel (1990)]. For example, Cho and Kreps (1987) show that in the Spence labor market signaling game with two types, the Intuitive Criterion selects the Pareto efficient separating equilibrium (it is easily verified that APE would select the same outcome). In contrast, in the alternating-offer bargaining game considered above, the buyer uses only fully-pooling offers along the equilibrium path. The intuition for why pooling obtains is that the strong buyer type tries to separate by making a nonserious offer and delaying trade. The only alternative for the weak buyer type is therefore to make a separating offer, which yields the worst possible (completeinformation) utility level. Meanwhile, stationarity of the equilibrium acceptance strategy provides the seller with an incentive to accelerate trade, and therefore (by the usual Coase Conjecture argument) to charge a relatively low price following rejection of the nonserious offer. But then a revealing offer cannot be optimal, so the equilibrium has to be pooling (see the discussion surrounding Theorem 12 for related intuition). In fact, from Theorem 7, we can see that the strong version of the Coase Conjecture also holds in the alternating-offer garne: there exists a uniform bound M such that regardless of the discount factor 3 trade occurs in at most 2M - 1 periods. Indeed, mn is decreasing in • for all n <~ fi, and fi converges to infinity as 6 converges to 1, so we can find M by recursing mn at 6 = 1. Note that M must be finite, because m2(1) = 20ml and rnn (1) = Omn-1 (1) where 0 = (1 + « - 1 ) > 1. It is interesting to compare the effect of shifting bargaining power to the informed party on equilibrium bargaining delay. For this purpose, let us denote the solution to (5) 1 , some by m ns and the solution to (8) by m a. Observe that mô = m 0a and m s1 = m a. straightforward but tedious algebra shows that m ns(6) < m a (3), for n ~> 2. We conclude that as long as the alternating-offer garne starts out with a seller offer below/3, is the alternating-offer garne requires more offers, and has a lower acceptance probability than the seller-offer game. Moreover, the alternating-offer garne results in additional delay because (with the exception of the final bargaining round) only seller-offer periods result in trade. Hence the traditional wisdom that bargaining becomes more efficient as the informed party gains bargaining strength proves to be incorrect. Finally, it should be noted that when the seller is so optimistic that she starts with the highest possible offer/3, the equilibrium requires her to randomize with positive probability two periods later. Unlike in the seller-offer garne, randomization in seller offers may thus be necessary along the equilibrium path. 3.1.3. The buyer-offer game and other extensive forms In the game where the buyer makes all the offers, it is clearly a sequential equilibrium for the buyer to always offer the seller his cost c, and for the seller to accept any price
18 As discussed above, this is necessarily the case when 3 is sufficientlylarge.
1922
L.M. Ausubel et al.
above c with probability one. Ausubel and Deneckere [(1989b), Theorem 4] show that this is in fact the only sequential equilibrium. Intuitively, the seller can do no bettet than in the complete-information garne where the buyer is known to have valuation v(1), but since the buyer makes all the offers, he can extract all of the surplus no marter what his valuation. We conclude that the buyer-offer garne always achieves an efficient outcome, regardless of whether or not there is a gap, condition (L) holds, or the magnitude of the discount factor. More generally, we can study the impact of transferring bargaining power from the seller to the buyer by considering the (k,/)-alternating-offer bargaining garne, in which the seller and buyer alternate by making k and 1 successive offers, respectively. The ratio k~ l measures the relative frequency with which the seller gets to make offers, and hence is a measure of his bargaining strength. Note that in the complete-information case, this garne yields the same outcome as the alternating-offer game in which the seller's discount factor is given by 3s = 31 and the buyer's discount factor is given by 3B = 3k. Thus, the ratio p =-- k / 1 can also be interpreted as the relative degree of impatience between the bargaining parties. Observe now that in any sequential equilibrium, the weakest buyer type taust earn at least what he would in the complete-information case, so we have U(1) ) v(1)~s(1 - ~B)/(1 -- ~S~B), which converges to v(1)/(1 + p) as approaches 1. Since v(1) is the maximum surplus available, we conclude that when p is small all sequential equilibria taust yield bargaining outcomes that are nearly efficient. This conclusion obtains regardless of whether or not there is a gap. Admati and Perry (1987) consider an alternating-offer extensive form garne that differs from Rubinstein's garne in that the length between successive offers is chosen endogenously by the players. Thus, when a player rejects an offer, he commits unilaterally to neither make a counteroffer not receive another offer unfil a length of time of his choice has elapsed. During this time period, all communications are closed oft, and the commitment is irrevocable. Admati and Perry analyze the two-type model given by (4), and apply a forward-induction-like refinement. When the prior on the weak type is sufficiently high, this refinement uniquely selects a separating equilibrium. 19 The seller starts out by making the offer/5 = {)/(1 + 3), which the weak buyer type accepts, and the strong buyer type rejects. The strong buyer type then delays any further negotiation until a time of length T has elapsed, at which point it makes its complete-information counteroffer r0 = 3b/(1 + ~), which the seller accepts. T is chosen such that the weak buyer type is indifferent between accepting the seller's initial offer, and mimicking the low buyer type. This equilibrium has an intuitive structure strongly reminiscent of the Riley outcome in the Spence labor market signaling model, hut this elegance comes at a strong price: the buyer is committed not to receive any counteroffer during the time interval of length T. Note that the seller has an incentive to make such a counteroffer, for once the buyer has chosen T, his type is revealed to be strong. In fact, both parties would
19 For intermediate values of the prior, there are multiple equilibria, and for sufficientlylow values of the prior the seller offers the strongbuyer'scomplete-informationprice.
Ch. 50: Bargainingwith IncompleteInformation
1923
be better off settling immediately at the price r0, and the buyer knows this is the case, but is committed not to reopen the lines of communication until time T [Admati and Perry (1987), Section 8.4]. If the communication channels were allowed to reopen any earlier, the signaling equilibrium would be destroyed. Indeed, in the alternating-offer garne analyzed in the previous section, separation never occurs.
3.2. Interdependent values Consider the trading situation in which a seller who is privately informed about the quality of a used car faces a potential buyer who cares about the quality of the vehicle. As we saw in Section 2, there then exists a trading mechanism that can achieve the efficient outcome if and only if the buyer's expected valuation exceeds the valuation of the owner of the highest quality car, i.e., E[v(q)] >~ c(1). This raises two interesting questions for extensive-form bargaining. First, assuming that the above condition holds, will the same forces that operate in the private values model to produce efficient trade when bargaining frictions disappear still permit the efficient outcome to be reached when values are interdependent? Second, assuming that the above condition is violated, will the limiting trading outcome at least be ex ante efficient, in the sense that it maximizes the expected gains from trade subject to the IC and IR constraints? So rar, the literature has only studied the bargaining garne in which the uninformed party (the buyer) makes all the offers [Evans (1989), Vincent (1989)]. Our discussion here is based upon Deneckere and Liang (1999). The arguments establishing existence of equilibrium for the interdependent values with a gap closely parallel those of Gul, Sonnenschein and Wilson (1986). Consequently an analogue of Theorem 6 holds, with c(q) taking the role of v(q), with one important difference: it is no longer the case that the number of bargaining rounds is uniformly bounded above, regardless of the discount factor (if this were the case, then as the discount factor converged to one, the efficient outcome would obtain even when E[v(q)] < c(1), contradicting Theorem 2). As in the private values case, generically there is a unique equilibrium outcome, and equilibrium outcomes are sustained by a unique stationary triplet. In equilibrium, the buyer successively increases his offers over time. Low-quality seller types accept low prices, while high-quality seller types suffer delay in order to credibly prove they possess a higher-quality vehicle. The intuition for uniqueness is analogous to the orte given in Section 3.1.1: under condition (L), once the buyer's beliefs cross a threshold level, he finds it no longer worthwhile to price discriminate among the remaining seller types. 2° To illustrate consider the simple two-type model:
c(q)=O,
v(q)----«,
forO~
c(q)=s,
v(q)=s+~6,
for~ < q ~< 1,
20 See Samuelson(1984) for a generalization of Stokey's"no price discrimination"result to the interdependent values case.
1924
L.M. Ausubel
e t al.
where oe > 0 and fi > 0, since we are in the case of a gap. Note that the private values case obtains when « = s + fl, so this is a generalization of the example studied in Secfion 3.1.1. See Evans (1989) for a treatment of the special case in which c~ = 0. Let q 1 = 1, q0 = q, and inductively define the sequence ql > q2 > ' " > qN from: r a n = e s - e 3 -(n l)mn_1
(n~2),
and the initial condition ml = f i s - l m o , using mn = q~~-l - qn and the terminal condition N mmmin{n: qn ~< 0}. Finally, let Pn = s~ n. Then with every sequential equilibrium is associated the unique stationary triplet: P(Q) =ph,
Q~(qn,qn
1];
Q E (qn, qn-1] and n > 1,
t ( Q ) = qn-2,
Q E (ql, 1];
~1,
V ( Q ) = (ot - Pn-1)(qn-2 - Q) q- 6 V ( q n - 2 ) ,
Q ~ (qn, qn-1] and n > 1,
= (« -- PO)(qo -- Q) +/3(1 - q0),
Q ~ (ql, qo],
= / 3 ( 1 - Q),
Q ~ (qo, 1].
The idea behind the above construction is as follows. Seller types in (0, 1] are held to their reservation value, because the buyer has the sole power to make offers. The last price offered will therefore be equal to s. Seller types in the interval [0, ~] must be indifferent between accepting the offer Pn and waiting n periods to receive the offer Po = s, so we must have Pn = s6 n. The breakpoints qn are constructed so that when the state is qn the buyer is indifferent between offering Pn (and hence trading with types in (qn, qn-1]), and offering Ph-1 (and hence trading with types in (qn-1, qn-2])Note that, in the private-values case, the sequence {m l, m2 . . . . } is strictly increasing and bounded below when ~ converges to 1. This is still the case here when « ~> s. But when e~ < s, the sequence is decreasing as long as n remains such that ~" < e~/s. As 6 converges to 1, the range of integers for which this inequality holds increases without bound, so it is possible for the number of bargaining rounds to increase without bound as 3 converges to 1. This allows us to investigate the conditions under which the Coase Conjecture will and will not hold. For this purpose, let us explicitly denote the dependenee o f mi on ~ by mi (~), and define:
a=~-~mi(1)=(1-~l) i=0
1+ S - - Ol
We then have: THEOREM 8 [Deneckere and Liang (1999)]. Consider the two-type interdependent values model defined above. Then the Coase Conjecture obtains if and only if a ~ 1. When
Ch. 50: Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1925
a < 1, then as ~ converges to 1, all seller types in [0, 1 - a) trade immediately at the price sp 2, and all types in (1 - a, 1] trade at the price s after a delay o f length T discounted such that e - r T = p2, where p = oe/s.
The condition a ~> 1 can be written in the more familiar form E(v(q)) ) c(1), so Theorem 8 says that when bargaining frictions disappear, inefficient delay occurs if and only if this is mandated by the basic incentive constraints presented in Theorem 2. When E(v(q)) < c(1) every trading mechanism necessarily exhibits inefficiencies. However, the limiting bargaining mechanism described in Theorem 8 exhibits more delay than is necessary. To see this, observe that social welfare is increased by having all types q ~ (1 - a, ~] trade at the price sp 2 at time zero. In the resulting mechanism the buyer will have strictly positive surplus; this means we can increase the probability of trade on the interval (~, 1] and thereby further increase welfare.
4. Sequential bargaining with one-sided incomplete information: The "no gap" case The case of no gap between the seller's valuation and the support of the buyer's valuation differs in broad qualitative fashion from the case of the gap which we examined in the previous section. The bargaining does not conclude with probability one after any finite number of periods. As a consequence of this fact, it is not possible to perform backward induction from a tinal period of trade, and it therefore does not follow that every sequential equilibrium need be stationary. If stationarity is nevertheless assumed, then the results parallel the results which we have already seen for the gap case: trade occurs with essentially no delay and the informed party receives essentially all the surplus. However, if stationarity is not assumed, then instead a folk theorem obtains, and so substantial delay in trade is possible and the uninformed party may receive a substantial share of the surplus. These qualitative conclusions hold both for the seller-offer garne and alternating-offer garnes. Following the same convenient notation as in Section 3, let the buyer's type be denoted by q, which is uniformly distributed on [0, 1], and let the valuation of buyer type q be given by the function v(q). The seller's valuation is normalized to equal zero. The case o f " n o gap" is the situation where there does not exist A > 0 such that it is common knowledge that the gains from trade are at least A. More precisely, for any A > 0, there exists q z 6 [0, 1) such that 0 < v(q~) < A . Opposite the conclusion of Theorem 4 for the gap case, we have: LEMMA 2. In any sequential equilibrium o f the infinite-horizon seller-offer garne in the case o f "no gap", and f o r any N < cx~, the probabiIity o f trade before period N is strictly less than one. PROOF. By Lemma 1, at the start of any period t, the set of remaining buyer types is an interval (Qt, 1]. The seller never offers a negative price [Fudenberg, Levine and
1926
L.M. Ausubel et al.
Tirole (1985), Lemma 1]. Consequently, a price of (1 - ~)v(q) - e will be accepted by all buyer types less than q, since a buyer with valuation v(q) is indifferent between trading at a price of (1 - 8)v(q) in a given period and trading at a price of zero in the next period. Suppose, contrary to the lemma, that there exists finite integer N such that Q N = 1. Without loss of generality, let N be the smallest such integer, so that QN-~ < 1. Since acceptance is individually rational, the seller must have offered a price of zero in period N - 1, yielding zero continuation payoff. But this was not optimal, as the seller could instead have offered (1 - 6)v(q) - e for some q ~ ( q N - 1 , 1), generating a continuation payoff of at least (q - Q N - I ) [ ( 1 -- 8)v(q) -- e] > 0 (for sufficiently small e), a contradiction. We conclude that QÆ < 1. [] A result analogous to Lemma 2 also holds in the alternating-offer extensive form. However, as we have already seen in Section 3.1.3, the result for the buyer-offer garne is qualitatively different: there is a unique sequential equilibrium; it has the buyer offering a price of zero in the initial period and the seller accepting with probability one. Much of the intuition for the case of "no gap" can be developed from the example where the seller's valuation is commonly known to equal zero and the buyer's valuation is uniformly distributed on the unit interval [0, 1]. This example was first smdied by Stokey (1981) and Sobel and Takahashi (1983). In our previous notation: v(q)=l-q,
for q c [0, 1].
(11)
In the subsections to follow, we will see that the stationary equilibria are qualitatively similar to those for the "gap" case, but that the nonstationary equilibria may exhibit entirely different properties. 4.1. Stationary equilibria
Assuming a stationary equilibrium and given the linear specification of Equation (11), it is plausible to posit that the seller's value function (V (Q)) is quadratic in the measure of remaining customers, that the measure of remaining customers (1 - t (Q)) which the seller chooses to induce is a constant fraction of the measure of currently remaining customers, and that the seller's optimal price ( P ( t ( Q ) ) ) is linear in the measure of remaining customers. Let r denote the real interest rate and z denote the time interval between periods (so that the discount factor ~ is given by ~ ~ e-rZ). In the notation of Section 3: V ( Q ) = «z(1 - Q)2,
(12)
1 -
Q),
(13)
P ( t ( Q ) ) = Vz(1 - Q),
(14)
t(Q)
= flz(1
-
where c~z, fiz and Vz are constants between 0 and 1 which are parameterized by the time interval z between offers. Equations (12)-(14) can be solved simultaneously, as follows.
Ch. 50: Bargainingwith Incomplete Information
1927
Since the linear-quadratic solution is differentiable and t (Q) is defined to be the arg max of Equation (2), we have: 0 r OÖi[ P ( Q ). (Q~ -
Q) -[- ~V (Q')]Q,=t(Q ) = 0 .
(15)
Furthermore, with t (Q) substituted into the right-hand side of Equation (2), the maximum must be attained:
v(o) = P(,(e)). ( t ( o ) - o) + ~v(,(o)).
(16)
Substituting Equations (12), (13) and (14) into Equations (3), (15) and (16) yields three simultaneous equations in az,/3z and Yz, which have a unique solution. In particular, the solution has eez = 1/2y z and: (17) [Stokey (1981), Theorem 4, and Gul, Sonnenschein and Wilson (1986), pp. 163-164]. Qualitatively, the reader should observe that in the limit as the time interval z between offers approaches zero (i.e., as 3 --+ 1), ?/z converges to zero. From Equation (14), observe that Vz is the seller's price when the state is Q = 0. This means that the initial price in this equilibrium may be made arbitrarily close to zero (i.e., the Coase Conjecture holds). Moreover, since «z = 1/2yz, the seller's expected profits in this equilibrium may be made arbitrarily close to zero. According to (17), the convergence is relatively slow, but for realistic parameter values, the seller loses most of her bargaining power. For example, with a real interest rate of 10% per year and weekly offers, the seller's initial price is 4.2% of the highest buyer valuation; this diminishes to 1.63% with daily offers. Further observe that, since the linear-quadratic equilibrium is expressed as a triplet {P (.), V (.), t (.)}, this sequential equilibrium is stationary. However, this model is also known to have a continuum of other stationary equilibria; see Gul, Sonnenschein and Wilson [(1986), Examples 2 and 3]. Unlike the other known stationary sequential equilibria, the linear-quadratic equilibrium has the property that it does not require randomization oft the equilibrium path. In the literature, stationary sequential equilibria possessing this arguably desirable property are referred to as strong-Markov equilibria; while stationary sequential equilibria not necessarily possessing this property are often referred to as weak-Markov equilibria. The linear-quadratic equilibrium of the linear example is emblematic of all stationary sequential equilibria for the case of "no gap", as the following theorem shows: THEOREM 9 (Coase Conjecture). For every v(.) in the case o f "no gap " and f o r every e > O, there exists ~ > 0 such that, f o r every time interval z ~ (0, ~) between offers and f o r every stationary sequential equilibrium, the initial price charged in the seller-offer garne is less than e.
1928
L.M. Ausubel et al.
PROOF. Gul, Sonnenschein and Wilson (1986), Theorem 3.
[]
If extremely mild additional assumptions are placed on the valuation function of buyer types, then a stronger version of the Coase Conjecture can be proven. The standard Coase Conjecture m a y be viewed as establishing an upper bound on the ratio between the seller's offer and the highest buyer valuation in the initial period; the uniform Coase Conjecture further bounds the ratio between the seller's offer and the highest-remaining buyer valuation in allperiods of the game. For L, M and « such that 0 < M ~< 1 ~< L < oo a n d 0 < « < oc, let: BL,M,~ = {V(.): V(0) = 1, V(1) = 0 and M(1 - q)~ <~ v(q) <~ L(1 - q)~ for all q ~ [0, 11}.
(18)
The family -TL,M,« has the property that if v E f'L,M,«, then every truncation (from above) of the probability distribution of buyer valuations (renormalized so that the valuation at the truncation point equals one) is guaranteed to also be an element of 5C/M,M/C,«. If a uniform ~ (of Theorem 9) can be found which holds for all 1) E .~'L/M,M/L,c~, then the ratio between the seller's offer and the highest-remaining buyer valuation is bounded by « in all periods of the garne. We have: THEOREM 1 0 (Uniform Coase Conjecture). For every 0 < M <~ 1 <~ L < oc, 0 < « < cx), and « > O, there exists ~ > 0 such that f o r every time interval z E (0, ~) between offers, f o r every v E ,TL,M,« and f o r every stationary sequential equilibrium, the initial price charged in the seller-offer garne is less than «. PROOF. Ausubel and Deneckere (1989a), Theorem 5.4.
[]
The same qualitative results hold in alternating-offer extensive forms for the case of no gap. Some additional assumptions above and beyond stationarity are made in the literature, but the stationarity assumption appears to be the driving force behind the results. Gul and Sonnenschein (1988), in analyzing the gap case, and Ausubel and Deneckere (1992a) assume stationarity. 21 They also assume that the seller's offer and acceptance rules are in pure strategies, 22 and that there is "no free screening" in the sense that any two buyer offers which each have zero probability of acceptance are required to induce the same beliefs. Similar to the seller-offer garne, these imply:
21 To be more precise, they assume requirement (3) and a slightly weaker version of requirement (2) in the definition of stationarity from Section 3. Their assumptions of pure strategies and no free sca'eeningimply requirement (1). 22 In light of Section 3.1.2, the pure strategy assumption on seller acceptances may be inconsistent with refinements of sequential equilibrium; but a similar result likely holds under weaker assumptions.
Ch. 50: Bargainingwith IncompIete Information
1929
THEOREM 1 1 Uniform Coase Conjecture). For every 0 < M <~ 1 <~ L < oc, 0 < « < cx~, and « > O, there exists ~ > 0 such that f o r every time interval z 6 (0, ~) between offers, for every v E UL,M,« and f o r every stationary sequential equilibrium, the initial serious (seller or buyer) offer in the alternating-offer garne is less than e. PROOF. Ausubel and Deneckere (1992a), Theorem 3.2.
[]
For the no gap case, the Coase Conjecture is equivalent to the notion of "No Delay" which Gul and Sonnenschein (1988) prove for the gap case: for sufficiently short time interval between offers, the probability that trade will occur within « time is at least 1 - e. This equivalence holds in the seller-offer as well as in the alternating-offer garne. There is an especially enlightening explanation for the fact that stationary sequential equilibria of the alternating-offer garne closely resemble those of the seller-offer garne. In a sense which may be made precise, stationary equilibria of the alternating-offer garne are as if the extensive form permitted offers only by the uninformed party: exogenously, both traders are permitted to make offers; endogenously, equilibrium counteroffers by the informed party degenerate to null moves. To see this, observe that the stationarity, pure-strategy and no-free-screening restrictions on sequential equilibrium mandate that, at each time when it is the informed agent's turn to make an offer, the informed agent partitions the interval of remaining types into two subintervals (one possibly degenerate): a high subinterval (who "speak" by making a serious offer) and a low subinterval (who effectively "remain silent" by making a nonserious offer). Choosing to speak reveals a high valuation, which is information that the uninformed agent can exploit in the ensuing negotiations. Remaining silent signals a low valuation. Let b denote the lowest buyer valuation in the speaking subinterval - as well as the highest buyer valuation in the silence subinterval. Following speaking, the seller captures a price of at least b_6/(1 + ~), ä la Rubinstein (1982), which as the time between offers shrinks toward zero, converges to 1/2b. Meanwhile, also as the time between offers shrinks toward zero, the terms of trade for the silence interval become increasingly favorable: ä la the Uniform Coase Conjecture, the ratio between the next price and b converges to zero. Thus, silence becomes increasingly attractive relative to speaking and, for sufficiently short time intervals, delay becomes preferable to revealing the damaging information for all types of the informed party. In other words, you recognize that "anything you say can and will be used against you". Therefore, regardless of valuation, you decline to speak, since "you have the right to remain silent". More formally: THEOREM 12 (Silence Theorem). Let v belong to ff2L,M,el and let r be any positive interest rate. Then there exists ~ > 0 such that, f o r every time interval z E (0, ~) between offers and f o r every stationary sequential equilibrium satisfying the pure-strategy and no-free-screening restrictions, the informed party never makes any serious offers in the alternating-offer bargaining game, both along the equilibrium path and after all histories in which no prior buyer deviations have occurred.
1930
L.M. Ausubel et al.
PROOF. Ausubel and Deneckere (1992a), Theorem 3.3.
[]
Thus, stationary equilibria of the alternating-offer bargaining game with a time interval z between offers closely resemble stationary equilibria of the seller-offer bargaining garne with a time interval 2z between offers, for sufficiently small z. Moreover, for many distributions of valuations, "sufficiently" small does not require "especially" small: for the model with linear v(.), the silence theorem holds whenever ~ > 0.83929 [Ausubel and Deneckere (1992a), Table I]; with a real interest rate r of 10% per year, this holds for all z < 21 months, not requiring a very quick response time between offers at all.
4.2. Nonstationary equilibria In the case of no gap, stationarity is merely an assumption, not an implication of sequential equilibrium. As we saw in the last subsection, the stationary equilibria converge (as the time interval between offers approaches zero) in outcome to the static mechanism which maximizes the informed party's expected surplus. The contrast between stationary and nonstationary equilibria is most sharply highlighted by constructing nonstationary equilibria which converge in outcome to the static mechanism which maximizes the uninformed party's expected surplus. Again, consider the example where the seller's valuation is commonly known to equal zero and the buyer's valuation is uniformly distributed on the unit interval [0, 1]. The static mechanism which maximizes the seller's expected surplus is given by:
P(q) =
{1, O,
i f q ~< 1/2, i f q > 1/2,
[ 1/2,
x(q) = / 0 ,
i f q ~< 1/2, i f q > 1/2.
(19)
In terms of a sequential bargaining garne, this means that, although it is possible to intertemporally price discriminate, the seller finds it optimal to merely select the static monopoly price of 1/2 and adhere to it forever [Stokey (1979)]. The intuition for this result - in terms of the durable goods monopoly interpretation of the model - is that the sales price for a durable good equals the discounted sum of the period-by-period rental prices, and the optimal rental price for the seller in each period is always the same monopoly rental price. A seller who lacks commitment powers will be unable to follow precisely this price path [Coase (1972)]. If the seller were believed to be charging prices of Pn = 1/2, for n = 0, 1, 2 . . . . . the unique optimal buyer response would be for all q E [0, 1/2) to purchase in period 0 and for all q 6 (1/2, 1] to never purchase (corresponding exactly to the static mechanism of Equation (19)). But, then, the seller's continuation payoff evaluated in any period n = 1, 2, 3 . . . . equals zero literally. Following the same logic as in the proof of Lemma 2, there exists a deviation which yields the seller a strictly positive payoff, establishing that the constant price path is inconsistent with sequential equilibrium. However, while the static mechanism of Equation (19) cannot literally be implemented in equilibria with constant price paths, Ausubel and Deneckere (1989a) show
Ch. 50: Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1931
that the seller's optimum can nevertheless be arbitrarily closely approximated in equilibria with slowly descending price paths. The key to their construction is as follows. For any ~7 > 0, and in the game with time interval z > 0 between offers, define a main equilibrium path by: P n = p 0 e -onz,
forn=0,1,2
.....
(20)
Also consider the (linear-quadratic) stationary equilibrium which was specified in Equations (12)-(14) and in which Vz was solved in Equation (17). Define a reputationalprice strategy by the following seller strategy: Offer Pm in period m, if Pn was offered in all periods n = 0, 1 . . . . . m - 1,
(21)
Offer prices according to the stationary equilibrium, otherwise, with the corresponding buyer strategy defined to optimize against the seller strategy (21). It is straightforward to see that, for sufficiently short time intervals between offers, the reputational price strategy yields a (nonstationary) sequential equilibrium. This is the case for all Po 6 (0, 1); and for Po = 1/2, the sequential equilibrium converges in outcome (as ~ --+ 0 and z --+ 0) to the static mechanism (19) which maximizes the seller's expected payoff. A heuristic argument proceeds as follows. First, observe that the price path {pn},zcc__0 yields a relatively large measure of sales in period 0 and then a relatively slow trickle of sales thereafter. Hence, if the main equilibrium path is selfenforcing for the seller in periods n = 1, 2 . . . . . it will automatically be self-enforcing in period n = 0. Second, let us consider the seller's continuation payoff along the main equilibrium path, evaluated in any period n = 1, 2 . . . . . Let q denote the state at the start of period n. Given the linear distribution of types and the exponential rate of descent in price, it is easy to see that the seller's expected continuation payoff, Jr, is a stationary function of the state: zc(q) = )vz (1 -- q)2,
(22)
where )~z depends on ~ and is parameterized by z. Moreover, for every ~ > 0: ;v = lim ;vz > 0. Z--+0
(23)
Meanwhile, we already saw in Equation (12) that the seller's payoff from optimally deviating from the main equilibrium path is given by V (q) = oez(1 - q)2, where oez -+ 0 as z --+ 0. Thus, for any ~ > 0, there exists ~ > 0 such that, whenever the time interval between offers satisfies 0 < z < ~, we have )vz > oez, and so the seller's expected payoff along the main equilibrium path exceeds the expected payoff from optimally deviating. We then conclude that the reputational price strategy yields a sequential equilibrium.
1932
L.M. Ausubel et al.
This construction generalizes to ai1 valuation functions v ~ 5L,M,« and to all bargaining mechanisms. It is appropriate to restrict attention here to incentive-compatible bargaining mechanisms that are ex post individually rational, since the buyer will never accept a price above bis valuation in any sequential equilibrium and the seller will never offer a price below her valuation. Continuing the logic developed in Theorem 2, 23 we have the following complete characterization: LEMMA 3. For any continuous valuation function v(.), the one-dimensional bargaining mechanism {p, x} is incentive compatible and ex post individually rational if and onIy if p : [0, 1] --+ [0, 1] is (weakly) decreasing and x is given by the Stieltjes integral: x(q) = - flq v(r) dp(r). PROOF. Ausubel and Deneckere (1989b), Theorem 1.
[]
Moreover, we can translate the outcome path of any sequential equilibrium of the bargaining garne into an incentive-compatible bargaining mechanism, as follows. For buyer type q, let n(q) denote the period of trade for type q in the sequential equilibrium and ler Ó (q) denote the payment by type q. Define:/3(q) = e -rn(q)z and 2(q) = Ó(q) e -ri~(q)z. Then {/3, 2} thus defined can be reinterpreted as a direct mechanism- and the fact that it derives from a sequential equilibrium immediately implies that {/3, 2 } is incentive compatible and individually rational. We will say that {p, x} is implemented by sequential equilibria of the bargaining game if, for every e > 0, there exists a sequential equilibrium inducing static mechanism {/3, 2} with the property that {/3, 2} is uniformly close to {p, x} (except possibly in a neighborhood of q = 1):
I~(q)-p(q)l<e,
Vqc[0,1-e),
and
1 2 ( q ) - x ( q ) [ < e , VqŒ[0,1].
(24)
The reasoning described above for the static mechanism which maximizes the seller's expected payoff extends to every incentive-compatible bargaining mechanism. In place of the exponentially descending price path {Ph },~°c_-0, we substimte a general specification which approximates the incentive-compatible bargaining mechanism, for q ~ [0, 1 - e] and induces an exponential evolution of the state, for q E (1 - «, 1]. In place of the linear-quadratic equilibrium following deviations, we substitute a stationary equilibrium, which is guaranteed to exist (Theorem 4) and to satisfy the Uniform Coase Conjecmre (Theorem 10). We have: 23 The analogue to L e m m a 3 for the case where the seller is informed and the buyer uninformed follows directly from Theorem 2, as follows. With private values, i.e., g(s) = b for all s, the first inequality in Theorem 2 is automaticalty satisfied. Since we are in the case of no gap, seller type ~ cannot profitably trade with the buyer, so ex post individual rationality requires x(~) - ~p(~) = 0. Consequently, it follows from Theorem 2 that: x(s)=sp(s)+
p(z)dz=~p(~)
-
zdp(z).
Ch. 50: Bargainingwith IncompleteInformation
1933
THEOREM 13 Folk Theorem). Let the valuation function v(.) belong to -~L,M,«. Then every incentive-compatible, ex post individually rational bargaining mechanism {p, x }
is implementable by sequential equilibria of the seller-offer bargaining game. PROOR Ausubel and Deneckere (1989b), Theorem 2.
[]
A folk-theorem-like result also holds in the alternating-offer garne, since each of a continuum of sequential equilibria from the seller-offer garne can be embedded as equilibria in the alternating-offer game. At the same time, there is an upper bound on the price at which the buyer can be expected to trade. Suppose that the seller holds the most "optimistic" beliefs: the buyer's type equals 0 and so the buyer's valuation equals v(0). Then, even in the complete-information game, if the seller offers any price greater than (1/(1 + 6))v(O), the buyer is sure to turn around and reject [Rubinstein (1982)]. In the limit as the time interval approaches zero, the seller can extract no more than one-half the surplus from the highest-valuation buyer. Thus, we have: THEOREM 14. Ler the valuation function v(.) belong to ärL,M,«. Then an incentivecompatible, ex post individualIy rational bargaining mechanism {p,x} is imple-
mentable by sequential equilibria of the alternating-offer bargaining game if and only if: p(0)v(0) - x ( 0 ) ~> 1/2v(0). PROOF. Ausubel and Deneckere (1989b), Theorem 3.
[]
4.3. Discussion of the stationarity assumption One useful way to understand the effect of the stationarity assumption is to see its impact on the set of equilibria of a standard supergame. Consider, for example, the infinitely repeated prisoners' dilemma - or any infinite supergame in which the stage garne has a unique Nash equilibrium. Since (unlike the bargaining game) this is literally a repeated garne and the play of one period has no effect on the possibilities in the next, there is no state variable at all. Stationarity restricts attention to equilibria in which the play in any period is history-independent; in other words, trigger-strategy equilibria are ruled out by assumption. (Equivalently, as in the bargaining garne with one-sided incomplete information, stationarity restricts attention to equilibria of the infinite-horizon garne which are limits of equilibria of finite-horizon versions of the same garne.) The unique stationary equilibrium is the static Nash equilibrium played over and over. This analogy strongly suggests that it is wrong to assume away the nonstationary equilibria. While it is interesting to know the implications of stationarity, a restriction to stationarity excludes many of the interesting effects which led economists to analyze dynamic garnes in the first place. Of course, stationarity is essential to the analysis of the "gap" case, since it is implied (not assumed). But to the extent that "no gap" is the appropriate condition on primitives, nonstationary equilibria and their qualitative properties are an essential part of the analysis.
1934
L.M. Ausubel et al.
5. Sequential bargaining with two-sided incomplete information With two-sided incomplete information, incentive compatibility and individual rationality are incompatible with ex post efficiency. As we saw in Corollary 1 of Section 2, so long as the supports of the seller and buyer valuations overlapped, the static bargaining mechanism necessarily entails situations where the buyer's valuation exceeds the seller's valuation yet trade occurs with probability strictly less than one. Furthermore, as we saw in the fourth paragraph following Theorem 2, since any sequential equilibrium of the dynamic bargaining garne can be expressed as a static mechanism, this immediately implies that the search for ex post efficient sequential equilibria is fi'uitless. The more interesting starting-point is to ask: Can the ex ante efficient static bargaining mechanism be replicated in a dynamic offer/counteroffer bargaining garne, or does the dynamic garne necessarily entail greater inefficiency than the static constrained optimum? Ausubel and Deneckere (1993a) establish that, for distribution functions exhibiting monotonic hazard rates, the ex ante efficient static bargaining mechanism can essentially be replicated in very simple dynamic bargaining garnes: THEOREM 15. If F1 (s) / f l (s) and [F2(b) - 1]/f2(b) are strictly increasing functions, then: (i) there exists )~s 6 (0, 1) such that, f o r every )~ ~ [)~s, 1], the ex ante efficient mechanism which places weight )~ on the seller is implementable in the seller-offer game; and (ii) there exists )~/, c (0, 1) such that, f o r every )~ c [0, )~b], the ex ante efficient mechanism which places weight )~ on the seller is implementable in the buyer-offer garne. PROOF. Ausubel and Deneckere (1993a), Theorem 3.1.
[]
The flavor of this result is most easily seen in the standard example where the seller and buyer valuations are each uniformly distributed on the unit interval. For this special case of the theorem, calculations reveal that )~s = 1/2 = ;%. This means that, for the case of equal weighting ()~ = 1/2) focused on by Chatterjee and Samuelson (1983) and Myerson and Satterthwaite (1983), we can come arbitrarily close to replicating the constrained optimum both in the seller-offer garne and the buyer-offer garne. Moreover, since equilibria of the seller- and buyer-offer garnes can be embedded in sequential equilibria of the alternating-offer garne, this means that the entire ex ante Pareto frontier is implementable in the altemating-offer bargaining garne. There need not be any additional inefficiency arising from the dynamic nature of the game, above and beyond the inefficiency already introduced by the two-sided incomplete information. While the (upper) boundary of the set of all sequential equilibria is thus known, little exists in the way of results refining the set of sequential equilibrium outcomes. Cramton (1984) posited sequential equilibria of the infinite-horizon seller-offer bar-
Ch. 50: Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1935
gaining garne with the additional properties that: (a) the seller fully reveals her type in the course of making offers; and (b) in the continuation garne following the seller's revelation, players adopt the strategies from a stationary equilibrium of the garne of one-sided incomplete information. The seller thus uses delay to credibly signal her strength: low-valuation seller types make revealing offers early in the garne, while high-valuation seller types initially make nonserious offers until revealing later in the garne. Cho (1990a) posited equilibria of finite-horizon seller-offer bargaining garnes with the properties that: (a) the seller's pricing rule is a separating strategy after every history; (b) equilibria satisfy a continuity property resembling trembling-hand perfection; (c) equilibria satisfy a monotonicity restriction on beliefs; and (d) equilibria are stationary. However, both the Cramton (1984) and Cho (1990a) constructions ultimately exhibit an unfortunate property, when the seller and buyer distributions have the same supports and for short time intervals between offers. By the stationarity assumption, the lowest seller type is subject to the Coase Conjecture, earning a payoff arbitrarily close to zero. Meanwhile, higher seller types offer prices which always exceed their respective types. The lowest seller type thus faces a very strong incentive to mimic a higher seller type, breaking the equilibrium unless essentially all higher types encounter extremely long delays before trading. Thus, a No Trade Theorem holds: In the limit as the time interval between offers decreases toward zero, the ex ante expected probability of trade in these equilibria converges to zero [Ausubel and Deneckere (1992b), Theorem 1]. Two other articles present plausible outcomes of dynamic bargaining games with twosided incomplete information in which trade occurs to a substantial degree but which are inefficient compared to the constrained static optimum. 24 Cramton (1992) extends and analyzes the Admati and Perry (1987) extensive-form garne to an environment with a continuum of types and two-sided incomplete information. The garne begins with effectively a war of attrition between the seller and the buyer: there is a seller type s(t) and a buyer type b(t) who are each supposed to reveal themselves by making serious offers at time t. Thus, as the game unfolds without serious offers getting made, each party becomes more pessimistic about his counterpart's valuation. A serious offer once made - fully reveals the offeror's type. The other player then either accepts the serious offer or further delays trade so as to credibly convey his own type and, when trade
24 Perry (1986) analyzes an alternating-offergarne with two-sided incomplete information about valuations, but where the cost of bargaining takes the form of a fixed cost per period rather than discounting. He establishes the existence of a unique sequential equifibrium when the players' fixed costs are unequal. When it is the turn of the player with the lower bargaining cost to make an offer, this player proposes essentially its monopoly price, which the other player accepts if it yields nonnegativeutility. When it is the turn of the player with the higher bargaining cost to make an offer, this player leaves the garne without making an offer. Thus, trade - if it occurs at all - occurs in the initial period. However, inefficientlylittle trade occurs compared to the constrained static optimum. Perry's garne illustrates the principle that there is no possibility for signaling through delay when the incomplete information is about valuations but the bargaining cost is a fixed cost each period. Signaling requires the presence of an action which is relatively less costly for one type than another; in this game, the cost of delay is equal across all types.
1936
L.M. Ausubel et al.
occurs following both players' fnll revelation, it occurs at the complete-information price. Ausubel and Deneckere (1992b) consider the seller-offer bargaining game and construct a continuum of equilibria, all with the property that the seller's first serious offer reveals essentially all the information which she will ever reveal. One interesting equilibrium in this class is the "monopoly equilibrium": the seller fully reveals her type in the initial period by offering essentially the monopoly price relative to her valuation; and then follows a slowly descending price path thereafter. This equilibrium is also ex ante efficient - provided that all of the weight is placed on the seller.
6. Empirical evidence Bargaining is pervasive in our economy. Thus, it is not surprising that there is a substantial empirical literature. However, only recently has this work sought to examine the data in light of strategic bargaining theories with private information. Bargaining models with private information are especially well suited for empirical work, since a main feature of the data is the occurrence of costly disputes. These disputes arise naturally in models with incomplete information. However, private information models involve several challenges for empirical work. First, the models are often complex, making estimation difficult. Second, the results tend to be sensitive to the particular bargaining procedure, the source of private information, and the form of delay costs. In most empirical settings, the bargaining rules and the preferences of the parties cannot be fully identified. The researcher then may have too rauch freedom in selecting assumptions that "explain" particular facts. Finally, the theory predicts how ex post outcomes depend on realizations of private information, yet the researcher typically is unable to observe private information variables, even ex post. We focus on one of the most prominent examples of bargaining - union contract negotiations - in understanding bargaining disputes. Kennan and Wilson (1989) analyze attrition, screening, and signaling models, and contrast the theoretical predictions of these models with the main empirical features of strike data. They emphasize five empirical findings: • Strikes are unusual, occurring in 10 to 20 percent of contract negotiations. • The relationship between strike duration and wages is ambiguous. McConnell (1989) found that wages declined 3% per 100 days of strike in the U.S., but Card (1990) found no significant relationship between strike duration and wages. • Strikes are more frequent in good times [Vroman (1989), Gunderson, Kervin, and Reid (1986)], yet strike duration decreases in good times [Kennan (1985), Harrison and Stewart (1989)]. • Strike activity varies across industries. • Settlement rates tend to decline with strike duration [Kennan (1985), Harrison and Stewart (1989), Gunderson and Melino (1990a)]. In all of the models, strikes (or their absence) convey private information in a credible way. A key feature of attrition models is winner-take-all outcomes. In an attrition model,
Ch. 50: Bargainingwith Incomplete Information
1937
each side attempts to convince the other that it can last longer, so the other should concede the entire pie under negotiation. One side clem'ly wins at the expense of the other. In contrast, wage bargaining typically involves compromise. For this reason, we focus on screening and signaling models. The standard setting assumes that the union is uncertain about the firm's willingness to pay. In this case, under either screening or signaling, the duration of the strike conveys information to the union about the firm's willingness to pay. A firm with a greater willingness to pay settles early at a high wage; whereas, a firm with a low willingness to pay endures a strike in order to convince the union to accept a low wage. A documentary film, Final Offer, of the 1984 negotiations between GM Canada and the UAW provides anecdotal evidence for this explanation for strikes. Early in the strike the union leaders are discussing whether they should accept GM's last offer. One says, "You might convince me that that's all there is after a month, but not after five days". Another says, "If they think it will take a short strike to convince workers to accept, they're wrong". S creening and signaling models share several features: (1) strike incidence and strike duration increase with uncertainty over private information variables, and (2) wages fall with strike duration. However, there are important differences in wages and strike activity. The standard screening model assumes that the union makes a sequence of declining wage demands, with each demand chosen optimally given beliefs about the firm's willingness to pay and the firm's acceptance and offer strategy. A critical assumption is that the firm employs a stationary acceptance strategy. At every point in the negotiation, a firm with value v accepts any wage demand below w(v). Most importantly, this assumption means that the firm's acceptance rule cannot depend on the rate of concession by the union. This greatly limits the equilibrium set, assuring that all equilibria satisfy the Coase (1972) conjecture. As the time between offers shrinks, the union loses its bargaining power and makes offers that are close to the Rubinstein wage between the union and the lowest-value firm. Strike duration falls to zero and strike incidence increases to one, but the convergence is slow. Screening then has the property that wages, strike incidence, and strike duration all depend critically on the period over which the union can commit to a wage demand. Kennan and Wilson (1989) argue that the Coase conjecture may explain why in boom times strikes are more frequent but shorter. This would follow if the union has a shorter commitment period in boom times; however, it is not clear why the time between offers would vary with the business cycle. One potential difficulty with the screening model is that, because of the Coase property, strike durations must be short when the commitment period is short. In the U.S., mean strike durations are about 40 days. If offers can be made every day, then the standard screening model may predict strikes that are too short given plausible interest rates and levels of uncertainty. Hart (1989) provides an explanation. If bargaining costs are low initially, but then increase at some point during the strike, say when inventories run out, then strikes can be much longer. Another explanation is given by Vincent (1989). If the parties' valuations are interdependent, then strikes of significant duration can occur even as the time between offers goes to zero.
1938
L.M. Ausubel et al.
The signaling model arises when the time between offers is endogenous [Admati and Perry (1987)]. Then the informed party (the firm) has an incentive to delay making an offer unfil after a sufficient time has passed to credibly reveal its private information. The critical assumption hefe is that the uninformed party (the union) is unable to make a counteroffer while it is waiting for the firm to make an offer. Aside from the union's initial demand, all settlements are ex post fair, in that the wage is the full-information Rubinstein (1982) wage. The union's initial demand is chosen to balance the cost of delay and the terms of settlement. This initial demand is accepted by the firm if its willingness to pay is sufficiently high. Otherwise the firm makes a counteroffer after waiting long enough to make the Rubinstein wage credible. Signaling and screening can be compared along a number of dimensions: • Screening outcomes depend critically on the minimum time between offers; signaling outcomes are insensitive to the minimum time between offers. • Screening outcomes strongly favor the informed party (the firm); signaling outcomes are roughly ex post fair. Hence, wages are higher under signaling and are more sensitive to the firm's private information. • Dispute incidence and dispute durations are higher under signaling. Indeed, dispute incidence is always greater than 50% in the standard signaling model. However, introducing a fixed cost of initiating a strike can lead to any level of strike incidence. Cramton and Tracy (1992) emphasize that the union has multiple threats. The union can strike or the union can hold out, putting pressure on the firm while continuing to work. Holdouts take the form of a slowdown, work-to-rule, sick-out, or other in-plant action. From the union's point of view, holdouts have two advantages: (1) workers are paid according to the expired contract, and (2) workers cannot be replaced. The union selects the threat, strike or holdout, that gives it the highest payoff. Since the desirability of each threat depends on observable factors, modeling this threat choice is important to understanding key features of the data. When striking is the only threat, then strike incidence depends essentially on the degree of uncertainty; whereas, with multiple threats strike incidence can vary as the composition of disputes changes with the attractiveness of each threat. For example, holdouts are more desirable when the current wage is high, and strikes are more desirable when unemployment is low and the workers have better outside options. In Cramton and Tracy (1992), a union and a firm are bargaining over the wage to be paid over the next contract period. The union's reservation wage is common knowledge. The firm's value of the labor force is private information. Bargaining begins with the union selecting a threat, either holdout or strike, which applies until a settlement is reached. In the holdout threat, the union is paid the current wage under the expired contract. There is some inefficiency associated with holdout. An outcome of the bargaining specifies the time of agreement, the contract wage at the time of agreement, and the threat before agreement. Following the union's threat choice, the union and firm alternate wage offers, with the union making the initial offer. The time between offers is endogenous.
Ch. 50: Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1939
The equilibrium takes a simple form. If the current wage is sufficiently low, the union decides to strike; otherwise, the union holds out. A second indifference level is determined by the union's initial offer. The firm accepts the union's initial offer if its valuation is above the indifference level, and otherwise rejects the offer and makes a counteroffer after sufficient time has passed to credibly signal the firm's value. A primary result is that dispute activity increases with uncertainty about private information. Tracy (1986, 1987) tests this basic result by using stock price volatility as a proxy for the amount of uncertainty in contract negotiations. With U.S. data, he finds that strike incidence and strike duration increase with greater relative volatility. Cramton and Tracy (1994a) fit the parameters of the mode1 to match the main features of the U.S. data from 1970 to 1989. They also estimate dispute incidence and dispute composition. Consistent with the theory, strike incidence increases as the strike threat becomes more attractive, because of low unemployment or a real wage drop over the previous contract. However, the model performs less weu in the 1980s than in the 1970s, suggesting a structural change in the post-1981 period. One explanation for a shift is an increase in the use of replacement workers following President Reagan's firing of striking air traffic controllers. Indeed, there was a shift away from strikes and towards holdouts in the 1980s. Cramton and Tracy (1998) investigate the extent to which the hiring of replacement workers can account for these changes. They build a model in which a firm considers the replacement option because it improves the firm's strike payoff relative to the union's, resulting in a lower wage. However, a firm taust balance this improvement in the terms of trade with the cost of replacement. A firm only uses replacements if its cost of replacement is sufficiently low. The union, anticipating the possibility of replacement, lowers its wage demand in the strike threat in order to reduce the probability of replacement. This risk of replacement, then, reduces the attractiveness of the strike threat, making it more likely that the union adopts the holdout threat at the outset of negotiations. For all large U.S. strikes in the 1980s, the likelihood of replacement is estimated. Consistent with the model, the composition of disputes shifts away from strikes as the predicted risk of replacement increases. Hence, a ban on the use of replacement workers should increase strike activity. Moreover, a b a n on replacement increases uncertainty, since replacement effectively truncates the firm's distribution of willingness to pay [Kennan and Wilson (1989)]. The Canadian data provide an opportunity to test this theory. Quebec instituted a ban on replacements in 1977, and British Columbia and Ontario introduced a similar ban in 1993. Gunderson, Kervin, and Reid (1989) find that strike incidence does increase with a b a n on replacements, and Gunderson and Melino (1990b) find strikes are longer after a ban. Bndd (1996) and Cramton, Gunderson, and Tracy (1999) examine the effect of a b a n on replacement workers on wages and strike activity. Budd does not find significant effects from the ban using a sample of single province contracts in manufacturing from 1965-1985. In coutrast, with a larger sample of contract negotiations from 1967-1993, Cramton, Gunderson, and Tracy find that prohibiting the use of replacement
1940
L.M. Ausubel et aL
workers during strikes is associated with significantly higher wages, and more frequent and longer strikes. Predictions of the bargaining models are sensitive to how threat payoffs change over time. Hart (1989) shows that strike durations are much longer in a screening model when strike costs increase sharply when a crunch point is reached (say inventories run out). Cramton and Tracy (1994b) consider time-varying threats within a signaling model. Strike payoffs change as replacement workers are hired, as strikers find temporary jobs, and as inventories or strike funds run out. The settlement wage is largely determined from the long-run threat, rather than the short-run threat. As a result, if dispute costs increase in the long run, then dispute durations are longer and wages decline more slowly during the short run. Allowing time-varying threats helps explain empirical results. Settlement rates are lower during periods of eligibility for unemployment insurance [Kennan (1980)]. Strike durations are longer during business downturns [Kennan (1985), Harrison and Stewart (1989)]. Wages might not decrease with strike durations [Card (1990)]. Moreover, the theory can help explain the costly actions firms and unions take to influence threat payoffs. An important feature of union contract negotiations is that they do not occur in isolation. Information from one contract negotiation may be linked with other contract negotiations within the same industry. Kuhn and Gu (1996) interpret holdouts in this way. In their theory, holdouts are used as a delaying tactic to get information about other bargaining outcomes in the same industry. When private information is correlated among bargaining pairs, there is an incentive to hold out, since one bargaining pair benefits from information revealed in the negotiation of another pair. Three predictions stem from this theory: (1) holdouts should increase when more bargaining pairs negotiate concurrently, (2) there should be a clustering of holdout durations within an industry, and (3) holdouts ending later are less apt to end in strikes. A panel of Canadian manufacturing contract negotiations from 1965 to 1988 support these predictions, A further implication of the linked information is that strike incidence can be reduced to the extent that private information is revealed in related contract negotiations. Kuhn and Gu (1995) find support for this hypothesis. In addition to within-industry links, contracts are linked over time. Today's negotiation is just one in a sequence of negotiations between the union and the firm. The current negotiation affects the hext negotiation in two ways: a wage linkage and an information linkage. The wage linkage is as in Cramton and Tracy (1992). The current wage is the starting point for negotiations and determines the attractiveness of striking versus holding out. An information linkage arises when the private information between contracts is correlated. Kennan (1995) studies a screening model of repeated negotiations where the firm's willingness to pay follows a Markov process. One implication of this model is a rachet effect. A firm is more hesitant to give in today, knowing that doing so will worsen its position in the next negotiation. More importantly, Kennan's model of repeated negotiation can explain some of the observed links between prior and current contract negotiations. For example, Card (1988, 1990) finds that strike incidence is
Ch. 50." Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1941
higher after a short strike in the prior negotiation, and lower after either no strike or a long strike in the prior negotiation.
7. E x p e r i m e n t a l evidence Strategic theories of bargaining with private information only recently have been evaluated in the experimental laboratory. The advantage of an experimental test of the theory, compared with an empirical test, is that the experimenter is able to observe the distribution and realizations of private information. The power of empirical tests is limited because the parties' degree of uncertainty taust be estimated indirectly from the data, under the assumption that the theory is true. This has led most researchers to test other empirical implications of the model, such as the slope of the concession function. The experimenter, on the other hand, can construct an environment that conforms much more closely to the theoretical setting. In this way, less ambiguous tests of the theory can be performed. Unfortunately, even in tightly controlled experiments, some ambiguity will remain, since the subjects may have relevant private information about their preferences that the experimenter is not privy to. 25 Most of the experimental work on strategic bargaining has focused on testing dynamic models with full information 26 or static models with private information. 27 Much could be learned by considering dynamic bargaining with private information. By introducing private information into a dynamic bargaining environment, we are able to observe how uncertainty influences the incidence and duration of disputes. This has been the focus of much of the theoretical and ernpirical work, and yet few experimental tests have been done.
References Admati, A., and M. Perry (1987), "Strategic delay in bargaining", Review of Economic Studies 54:345-364. Akerlof, G.A. (1970), "The market for 'lemons': Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism", Quarterly Journal of Economics 84:488-500. Ausubel, L.M. (2002), "A mechanism generalizing the Vickrey auction", Econometrica, forthcoming. Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1989a), "Reputation in bargaining and dnrable goods monopoly", Econometrica 57:511-532. Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1989b), "A direct mechanism characterization of sequential bargaining with one-sided incomplete information", Journal of Economic Theory 48:18-46. Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1992a), "Bargaining and the right to remain silent", Econometrica 60:597-626.
25 This point is emphasized by Forsythe, Kennan and Sopher (1991) and Ochs and Roth (1989). 26 Binmore, Shaked and Sutton (1985, 1988, 1989), Neelin, Sonnenschein and Spiegel (1988), and Ochs and Roth (1989). 27 Forsythe, Kennan and Sopher (1991) and Radner and Schotter (1989).
1942
L.M. Ausubel et al.
Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1992b), "Durable goods monopoly with incomplete information", Review of Economic Studies 59:795-812. Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1993a), "Efficient sequential bargalning', Review of Economic Studies 60:435-462. Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1993b), "A generalized theorem of the maximum", Economic Theory 3:99-107. Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1994), "Separation and delay in bargaining", mimeo (University of Maryland and University of Wisconsin-Madison). Ausubel, L.M., and R.J. Deneckere (1998), "Bargaining and forward induction", mimeo (University of Maryland and University of Wisconsin-Madison). Ayres, I., and E. Talley (1995), "Solomonic bargaining: Dividing a legal entitlement to facilitate Coasean trade", Yale Law Joumal 104:1027-1117. Bikhchandani, S. (1992), "A bargaining model with incomplete information", Review of Economic Studies 59:187-204. Binmore, K., M.J. Osborne and A. Rubinstein (1992), "Noncooperative models of bargaining', in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Game Theory, Vot. 1 (Notth Holland, Amsterdam), 179-225. Binmore, K., A. Shaked and J. Sutton (1985), "Testing noncooperative bargaining theory: A preliminary study", American Economic Review 75:1178-1180. Binmore, K., A. Shaked and J. Sutton (1988), "A further test of noncooperative bargaining theory: Reply", American Economic Review 78:837-840. Binmore, K., A. Shaked and J. Sutton (1989), "An outside option experiment", Quarterly Jonrnal of Economics 104:753-770. Budd, J.W. (1996), "Canadian strike replacement legislation and collective bargaining: Lessons for the United States", Induslrial Relations 35:245-260. Card, D. (1988), "Longimdinal analysis of strike activity", Journal of Labor Economics 6:147-176. Card, D. (1990), "Strikes and wages: A test of a signalling model", Quarterly Journal of Economics 105:625660. Chatterjee, K., and W. Samuelson (1983), "Bargaining under incomplete information", Operations Research 31:835-851. Cho, I.-K. (1990a), "Uncertainty and delay in bargaining', Review of Economic Studies 57:575-596. Cho, I.-K. (1990b), "Characterization of equilibria in bargaining models with incomplete information", mimeo (University of Chicago). Cho, I.-K., and D.M. Kreps (1987), "Signalling garnes and stable equilibria", Quarterly Journal of Economics 102:179-222. Cho, I.-K., and J. Sobel (1990), "Strategic stability and nniqueness in signaling garnes", Journal of Economic Theory 50:381-413. Coase, R.H. (1960), "The problem of social cost", Journal of Law and Economics 3:1-44. Coase, R.H. (1972), "Durability and monopoly", Journal of Law and Economics 15:143-149. Cramton, P. (1984), "Bargaining with incomplete information: An infinite-horizon model with continuous uncertainty", Review of Economic Studies 51:579-593. Cramton, P. (1985), "Sequential bargalning mechanisms", in: A. Roth, ed., Garne Theoretic Models of Bargaining (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England). Cramton, P. (1992), "Strategic delay in bargaining with two-sided nncertainty", Review of Economic Studies 59:205-225. Cramton, P., R. Gibbons and P. Klemperer (1987), "Dissolving a partnership efficiently", Econometrica 55:615-632. Cramton, P., M. Gunderson and J. Tracy (1999), "The effect of collective bargaining legislation on strikes and wages", Review of Economics and Statistics 81:475-489. Cramton, P., and J. Tracy (1992), "Strikes and holdouts in wage bargaining: Theory and data", American Economic Review 82:100-121.
Ch. 50: Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1943
Cramton, R, and J. Tracy (1994a), "Wage bargaining with time-varying threats", Journal of Labor Economics 12:594-617. Cramton, E, and J. Tracy (1994b), "The determinants of U.S. labor disputes", Journal of Labor Econornics 12:180-209.
Cramton, E, and J. Tracy (1998), "The use of strike replacements in union contract negotiations: The U.S. experience, 1980-1989", Journal of Labor Economics 16:667-701. Crawford, V.E (1982), "A theory of disagreernent in bargaining", Econometrica 50:607-637. Cremer, J., and R. McLean (1988), "Full extraction of the surplus in Bayesian and dominant strategy auctions", Econornetrica 56:1247-1258. Dasgupta, E, and E. Maskin (2000), "Efficient auctions", Quarterly Journal of Econornics 115:341-388. Deneckere, R.J. (1992), "A simple proof of the Coase conjecmre", mimeo (Northwestern University). Deneckere, R.J., and M.-Y. Liang (1999), "Bargaining with interdependent values", mimeo (University of Wisconsin-Madison). Evans, R. (1989), "Sequential bargaining with correlated values", Review of Economic Studies 56:499-510. Farrell, J., and R. Gibbons (1989), "Cheap talk can rnatter in bargaining", Journal of Economic Theory 48:221-237. Femandez, R., and J. Glazer (1991), "Striking for a bargain between two cornpletely informed agents", Arnerican Econornic Review 81:240-252. Forsythe, R., J. Kennan and B. Sopher (1991), "An experimental analysis of strikes in bargaining garnes with one-sided private information", American Econornic Review 81:253-278. Fudenberg, D., D.K. Levine and J. Tirole (1985), "Infinite-horizon models of bargaining with one-sided incomplete information", in: A. Roth, ed., Garne Theoretic Models of Bargaining (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England). Fudenberg, D., and J. Tirole (1983), "Sequential bargaining with incornplete information", Review of Economic Studies 50:221-247. Gresik, T.A. (1991a), "Efficient bilateral trade with statistically dependent beliefs", Journal of Econornic Theory 53:199-205. Gresik, T.A. (1991b), "Ex ante efficient, ex post individually rational trade", Journal of Economic Theory 53:131-145. Gresik, T.A. (1991c), "Ex ante incentive efficient trading mechanisms without the private valuation restriction", Journal of Economic Theory 55:41-63. Gresik, T.A., and M.A. Satterthwaite (1989), "The rate at which a simple rnarket converges to efficiency as the number of traders increases: An asymptotic result for optimal trading rnechanisms", Journal of Economic Theory 48:304-332. Grossrnan, S.J., and M. Perry (1986a), "Perfect sequential equilibrium", Journal of Econornic Theory 39:97119. Grossman, S.J., and M. Perry (1986b), "Sequential bargaining under asymmetric information", Journal of Econornic Theory 39:120-154. Gul, E, and H. Sonnenschein (1988), "On delay in bargaining with one-sided uncertainty", Econometrica 56:601-612. Gul, E, H. Sonnenschein and R. Wilson (1986), "Foundations of dynamic monopoly and the Coase conjecture", Journal of Economic Theory 39:155-190. Gunderson, M., J. Kervin and E Reid (1986), "Logit estimates of strike incidence frorn Canadian contract data", Journal of Labor Econornics 4:257-276. Gunderson, M., J. Kervin and E Reid (1989), 'q?he effect of labottr relations legislation on strike incidence", Canadian Journal of Economics 22:779-794. Gunderson, M., and A. Melino (1990a), "Estirnating strike effects in a general model of prices and quantities", Journal of Labor Econornics 5:1-19. Gunderson, M., and A. Melino (1990b), "The effects of public policy on strike duration", Journal of Labor Economics 8:295-316.
1944
L.M. Ausubel et al.
Haller, H., and S. Holden (1990), "A letter to the editor on wage bargaining", Joumal of Economic Theory 52:232-236. Hm'rison, A., and M. Stewart (1989), "Cyclical ttuctuations in strike durations", American Economic Review 79:827-841. Hart, O.D. (1989), "Bargaining and strikes", Quarterly Journal of Economics 104:2544. Hart, O.D., and J. Tirole (1988), "Conü~act renegotiation and Coasian dynamics", Review of Economic Studies 55:509-540. Jehiel, R, and B. Moldovanu (2001), "Efficient design with interdependent valuations', Econometrica 69:1237-1260. Kennan, J. (1980), "The effect of unemployment insurance payments on strike duration", Unemployment Compensation: Studies and Research 2:467-483. Kennan, J. (1985), "The dnration of contract strikes in US manufacturing", Journal of Econometrics 28:5-28. Kerman, J. (1995), "Repeated contract negotiations with private information", Japan and the World Economy 7:447-472. Kennan, J. (1997), "Repeated bargaining with persistent private information", mimeo (Department of Economics, University of Wisconsin-Madison). Kennan, J., and R. Wilson (1989), "Strategic bargaining models and interpretation of strike data", Journal of Applied Econometrics 4:$87-S 130. Kennan, J., and R. Wilson (1993), "Bargaining with private information", Journal of Economic Literature 31:45-104. Kohlberg, E., and J.-F. Mertens (1986), "On the strategic stability of equilibria", Econometrica 54:1003-1037. Krishna, V., and M. Perry (1997), "Efficient mechanism design", Working Paper (Penn State University). Kuhn, R, and W. Gu (1995), "The economics of relative rewards: Sequentiai wage bargaining", Working Paper (McMaster University). Kuhn, P., and W. Gu (1996), "A theory of holdouts in wage bargaining", Working Paper (McMaster University). Makowski, L., and C. Mezzetti (1993), "The possibility of efficient mechanisms for trading an indivisible object", Joumal of Economic Theory 59:451-465. Maskin, E., and J. Tirole (1994), "Markov perfect equilibrium", mimeo (Harvard University). Matsuo, T. (1989), "On incentive compatible, individually rational, and ex-post efficient mechanisms for bilateral trading", Jonrnal of Economic Theory 49:189-194. McAfee, R.R (1992), "Amicable divorce: Dissolving a partnership with simple mechanisms", Joumal of Economic Theory 56:266-293. McAfee, R.E, and R Reny (1992), "Correlated information and mechanism design', Econometrica 60:395422. McConnell, S. (1989), "Strikes, wages, and private information", American Economic Review 79:801-815, Mirrlees, J.A. (1971), "An exploration in the theory of optimal taxation", Review of Economic Studies 38:175-208. Mookherjee, D., and S. Reichelstein (1992), "Dominant strategy implementation of Bayesian incentive compatible allocation mles", Journal of Economic Theory 56:378-399. Myerson, R.B. (1981), "Optimal auction design", Mathematics of Operations Research 6:58-73. Myerson, R.B. (1985), "Analysis of two bargaining problems with incomplete information'', in: A. Roth, ed., Game Theoretic Models of Bargaining (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 115-147. Myerson, R.B., and M.A. Satterthwaite (1983), "Efficient mechanisms for bilateral trading", Journal of Economic Theory 28:265-281. Neelin, J., H. Sonnenschein and M. Spiegel (1988), "A further test of noncooperative bargaining theory", American Economic Review 78:824-836. Ochs, J., and A.E. Roth (1989), "An experimental study of seqnential bargaining", American Economic Review 89:355-384. Osborne, M.J., and A. Rubinstein (1990), Bargaining and Markets (Academic Press, Boston).
Ch. 50: Bargaining with Incomplete Information
1945
Perry, M. (1986), "An example of price formation in bilateral simations: A bargalning model with incomplete information", Econometrica 54:313-321. Perry, M., and EJ. Reny (1993), "A non-cooperative bargaining model with strategically timed offers", Journal of Economic Theory 59:50-77. Perry, M., and P.J. Reny (1998), "An ex-post efficient anction", mimeo (University of Pittsburgh). Radner, R., and A. Schotter (1989), "The sealed-bid mechanism: An experimental study", Journal of Economic Theory 48:179-220. Riley, J., and R. Zeckhanser (1983), "Optimal selling strategies: When to haggle, when to hold firm", Quarterly Journal of Economics 98:267-289. Rubinstein, A. (1982), "Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model", Econometrica 50:97-109. Rubinstein, A. (1985a), "A bargaining model with incomplete information about time preferences", Econometrica 53:1151-1172. Rubinstein, A. (1985b), "Choice of conjectures in a bargaining game with incomplete information", in: A. Roth, ed., Game Theoretic Models of Bargaining (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 99-114. Rubinstein, A. (1987), "A sequential strategic theory of bargaining", in: T. Bewley, ed., Advances in Economic Theory (Cambridge University Press, London), 197-224. Rustichini, A., M.A. Satterthwaite and S.R. Williams (1994), "Convergence to efficiency in a simple market with incomplete information", Econometrica 62:1041-1064. Säkovics, J. (1993), "Delay in bargaining gmnes with complete information", Journal of Economic Theory 59:78-95. Samuelson, W. (1984), "Bargaining under asymmetric information", Econometrica 52:995-1005. Samuelson, W. (1985), "A comment on the Coase theorem', in: Alvin R., ed., Garne Theoretic Models of Bargaining (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England). Satterthwaite, M.A., and S.R. Williams (1989), "The rate of convergence to efficiency in the buyer's bid double auction as the market becomes large", Review of Economic Stndies 56:477-498. Sobel, J., and I. Takahashi (1983), "A multi-stage model of bargaining", Review of Economic Studies 50:411426. Stokey, N.L. (1979), "Intertemporal price discrimination', Quarterly Journal of Economics 93:355-371. Stokey, N.L. (1981), "Rational expectations and durable goods pricing", Bell Journal of Economics 12:112128. Tracy, J.S. (1986), "An investigation into the determinants of U.S. strike activity", American Economic Review 76:423-436. Tracy, J.S. (1987), "An empirical test of an asymmetfic information model of stfikes", Journal of Labor Economics 5:149-173. Vincent, D.R. (1989), "Bargaining with common values", Joumal of Economic Theory 48:47-62. Vincent, D.R. (1998), "Repeated signalling garnes and dynamic trading relationships", International Economic Review 39:275-293. Vrmnan, S.B. (1989), "A longitudinal analysis of strike activity in U.S. manufacturing: 1957-1984", American Economic Review 79:816-826. Williams, S.R. (1990), "The transition from bargaining to a competitive market", American Economic Review 80:227-231. Williams, S.R. (1991), "Existence and convergence of equilibria in the buyer's bid double auction", Review of Economic Studies 58:351-374. Williams, S.R. (1999), "A characterization of efficient, Bayesian incentive compatible mechanisms", Economic Theory 14:155-180. Wilson, R. (1985), "Incentive efficiency of double auctions", Econometrica 53:1101-1116.
Chapter 51
INSPECTION GAMES* RUDOLF AVENHAUS Universität der Bundeswehr München BERNHARD VON STENGEL London School of Economics SHMUEL ZAMIR The Hebrew University of Jerusalem
Contents 1. Introduction 2. Applications
1949 1950
2.1. Arms control and disarmament
1950
2.2. Accounting and auditing in economics 2.3. Environmental control
1952 1954
2.4. Miscellaneous models
1955
3. Statistical decisions
5.1. Definition and introductory examples
1956 1957 1962 1965 1969 1969 1974 1976 1977
5.2. Announced inspection strategy
1980
3.1. General garne and analysis 3.2. Material accountancy 3.3. Data verilication
4. Sequential inspections 4.1. Recursive inspection garnes 4.2. Timeliness garnes
5. Inspector leadership
6. Conclusions References
1982 1984
*This work was supported by the German-Israeli Foundation (G.I.E), by the Volkswagen Foundation, and by a Heisenberg grant from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft. Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
1948
R. Avenhaus et al.
Abstract Starting wiCh the analysis of arms control and disarmament problems in the sixties, inspection games have evolved into a special area of garne theory with specific theoretical aspects, and, equally important, practical applications in various fields of human activity where inspection is mandatory. In this contribution, a survey of applications is given first. These include arms control and disarmament, theoretical approaches to auditing and accounting, for example in insurance, and problems of environmental surveillance. Then, Che general problem of inspection is presented in a game-theoretic framework chat extends a statistical hypothesis testing problem. This defines a game since the data can be strategically manipulated by an inspectee who wants to conceal illegal actions. Using this framework, two models are solved, which are practically significant and technically interesting: material accountancy and data verification. A second important aspect of inspection garnes is the fact chat inspection resources are limited and have to be used strategically. This is demonstrated in the context of sequential inspection garnes, where many machematically challenging models have been studied. Finally, the important concept of leadership, where the inspector becomes a leader by announcing and committing himself to his strategy, is shown to apply naturally to inspection garnes.
Keywords inspection garne, arms control, hypothesis testing, recursive game, leadership J E L classification:
C7 2, C 12
Ch. 51: InspectionGames
1949
1. Introduction
Inspecfion garnes form an applied field of garne theory. An inspection garne is a mathematical model of a situation where an inspector verifies that another party, called inspectee, adheres to certain legal rules. This legal behavior may be defined, for example, by an arms control treaty, and the inspectee has a potential interest in violating these rules. Typically, the inspector's resources are limited so that verification can only be partial. A mathematical analysis should help in designing an optimal inspection scheme, where it taust be assumed that an illegal action is executed strategically. This defines a game-theoretic problem, usually with two players, inspector and inspectee. In some cases, several inspectees are considered as individual players. Garne theory is not only adequate to describe an inspection situation, it also produces results which may be used in practical applications. The first serious attempts were made in the early 1960's where game-theoretic studies of arms control inspections were commissioned by the United States Arms Control and Disarmament Agency (ACDA). Furthermore, the International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA) performs inspections under the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty. The decision rules of IAEA inspectors for detecting a deviation of nuclear material can be interpreted as equilibrium strategies in a zero-sum game with the detection probability as payoff function. In these applications, game theory has proved itself useful as a technical tool in line with statistics and other methods of operations research. Since the underlying models should be accessible to practitioners, traditional concepts of game theory are used, like zero-sum garnes or garnes in extensive form. Nevertheless, as we want to demonstrate, the solution of these garnes is mathematically challenging, and leads to interesting conceptual questions as well. We will not consider inspection problems that are exclusively statistical, since our emphasis is on garnes. We also exclude industrial inspections for quality control and maintenance, except for an interesting worst-case analysis of timely inspections. Similarly, we do not consider search garnes [Gal (1983); O'Neill (1994)] modeling pursuit and evasion, for example in war. Search garnes are distinguished from inspection garnes by a symmetry between the two players whose actions are usually equally legitimate. In contrast, inspection games as we understand them are fundamentally asymmetrical: their salient feature is that the inspector tries to prevent the inspectee from behaviug illegally in terms of an agreement. In Section 2, we survey applications ofinspection garnes to arms control, auditing and accounting and ecouomics, and other areas like environmental regulatory enforcement or crime control. In Section 3, we provide a general game-theoretic framework to inspections which extends the statistical approach used in practice. In these statistical hypothesis testing problems, the distribution of the observed random variable is strategically manipulated by the inspectee. The equilibrium of the general non-zero-sum garne is found using an auxiliary zero-sum garne in which the inspectee chooses a violation procedure and the
1950
R. Avenhaus et al.
inspector chooses a statistical test with a given false alarm probability. We illustrate this by two specific important models, namely material accountancy and data verification. Inspeetions over time, so far primarily of methodological interest, are the subject of Section 4. In these garnes, the information of the players about the actions of their respective opponent is very important and is best understood if the garne is represented in extensive form. If the payoffs have a simple strncture, then the garnes can sometimes be represented recursively and solved analytically. In another timeliness garne, the optimal inspection times, continuously chosen from an interval, are determined by differential equations. In Section 5 we discnss the inspector leadership principle. It states that the inspector may commit himself to his inspection strategy in advance, and thereby gain an advantage compared to the symmetrical situation where both players choose their actions simultaneously. Obviously, this concept is parficularly applicable to inspection garnes.
2. Applications The majority of publications on inspection games concerns arms control and disarmament, usually relating to one or the other arms control treaty that has been signed. We survey these models first. Some of them are described in mathematical detail in later sections. Inspection garnes have also been applied to problems in economics, particularly in accountancy and auditing, in enforcement of environmental regulations, and in crime control and related areas. Some papers treat inspection games in an abstract setting, rather than modeling a particular application. 2.1. Arms control and disarmament
Inspection garnes have been applied to arms control and disarmament in three phases. Studies in the first phase, from about 1961 to 1967, analyze inspections for a nuclear test ban treaty, which was then under negotiation. The second phase, about 1968 to 1985, comprises work stimulated by the Non-Proliferation Treaty for Nuclear Weapons. Under that treaty, proper use of nuclear material is verified by the International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA) in Vienna. The third phase lasts from about 1986 until today. The end of the Cold War brought about new disarmament treaties. Verification of these treaties has also been analyzed using game theory. In the 1960's, a test ban treaty was under negotiation between the United Stares and the Soviet Union, and verification procedures were discussed. Tests of nuclear weapons above ground can be detected by satellites. Underground tests can be sensed by seismic methods, but in order to discriminate them safely from earthquakes, on-site inspections are necessary. The two sides never agreed on the number of such inspections that they would allow to the other side, so eventually they decided not to ban underground tests in the treaty. While the test ban treaty was being discussed, the problem arose as to how an inspector should use a certain limited number of on-site inspections, as provided by the
Ch. 51: lnspectionGames
1951
treaty, for verifying a rauch larger number of suspicious seismic events. Dresher (1962) modeled this problem as a recursive garne. The estimated number of events and the number of inspections that can be used are fixed parameters. We explain this garne in Section 4.1. It formed the basis for rauch subsequent work. With political backing for scientific disarmament studies, the United States Arms Control and Disarmament Agency (ACDA) commissioned game-theoretic analyses of inspections to the Mathematica company in the years 1963 to 1968. Game-theoretic researchers involved in this or related work were Aumann, Dresher, Harsanyi, Kuhn, Maschler, and Selten, among others. Publications on inspection garnes of that group are Kuhn (1963) and, in general, the reports to ACDA edited by Anscombe et al. (1963, 1965), as well as Maschler (1966, 1967). In a related study, Saaty (1968) presents some of the existing developments in this area. Many of these papers extend Dresher's garne in various ways, for example by generalizing the payoffs, or by assuming an uncertainty in the signals given by detectors. The Non-Proliferation Treaty (NPT) for Nuclear Weapons was inaugurated in 1968. This treaty divided the world into weapons states, who promised to reduce or even eliminate their nuclear arsenals, and non-weapon states who promised never to acquire such weapons. All states which became parties to the treaty agreed that the IAEA in Vienna verifies the nuclear material contained in the peaceful nuclear fuel cycles of all states. The verification principle of the IAEA is material accountancy, that is, the comparison of book and physical inventories for a given material balance area at the end of an inventory period. The plant operators report their balance data via their national organizations to the IAEA, whose inspectors verify these reported data with the help of independent measurements on a random sampling basis. Two kinds of sampling procedures are considered in all situations, depending on the nature of the problem. Attribute sampling is used to test or to estimate the percentage of items in the population containing some characteristic or attribute of interest. In inspections, the attribute of interest is usually if a safeguards measure has been violated. This may be a broken seal of a container, or an unquestioned decision that a datum has been falsified. The inspector uses the rate of tampered items in the sample to estimate the population rate or to test a hypothesis. The second kind of procedure is variable sampling. This is designed to provide an estimate of or a test on an average or total value of material. Each observation, instead of being counted as falling in a given category, provides a value wbich is totaled or averaged for the sample. This is described by a certain test statistic, like the total of Material Unaccounted For (MUF). Based on this statistic, the inspector has to decide if nuclear material has been diverted or if the result is due to measurement errors. This decision depends on the probability of a false alarm chosen by the inspector. Game-theoretic work in this area was started by Bierlein (1968, 1969), who emphasized that payoffs should be expressed by detection probabilities only. In contrast, inspection costs are parameters that are fixed externally. This is an adequate model for the IAEA which has a certain budget limiting its overall inspection effort. The
1952
R. Avenhaus et al.
agency has no intent to minimize that effort further, but instead wants to use it most efficiently. Since 1969, international conferences on nuclear material safeguards have regularly been held by the following institutions. The IAEA organizes about every five years conferences on Nuclear Safeguards Technology and publishes proceedings under that title. The European Safeguards Research and Development Association (ESARDA) as well as the Institute for Nuclear Material Management (INMM) in the United States meet every year and publish proceedings on that subject as well. Here, most publications concern practical matters, for example measurement technology, data processing, and safety. However, decision theoretical approaches, including game-theoretic methods, were presented throughout the years. Monographs which emphasize the theoretical aspects are Jaech (1973), Avenhaus (1986), Bowen and Bennett (1988), and Avenhaus and Canty (1996). Some studies on nuclear material safeguards are not related to the NPT. The U.S. Nuclear Regulatory Commission (NUREG) is in charge of safeguarding nuclear plants against theft and sabotage to guarantee their safe operation, in fulfillment of domestic regulations. In a study for that commission, Goldman (1984) investigates the possible use of game theory and its potential role in safeguards. In the mid-eighties, when the Cold War ended, new disarmament treaties were signed, like the treaty on Intermediate Nuclear Forces in 1987, or the treaty on Conventional Forces in Europe in 1990 [see Altmann et al. (1992) on verification issues]. The verification of these new treaties was investigated in game-theoretic terms by Brams and Davis (1987), by Brams and Kilgour (1988), and by Kilgour (1992). Variants of recursive games are described by Ruckle (1992). In part, these papers extend the work done before, in particular Dresher (1962).
2.2. Accounting and auditing in economics In economic theory, inspection garnes have been studied for the auditing of accounts. In insurance, inspections are used against the 'moral hazard' that the client may abuse his insnrance by frand or negligence. Our summary of these topics is based on Borch (1990). We will also consider models of tax inspections. Accounting is usually understood as a system for keeping track of the circulation of money. The monetary transactions are recorded in accounts. These may be checked in full detail by an inspector, which is called an audit. Auditing of accounts is often based on sampling inspection, simply because it is unnecessarily costly to check every voucher and entry in the books. The possibility that any transaction may be checked in full detail is believed to have a deterring effect likely to prevent irregularities. A theoretical analysis of problems in this field naturally leads to a search for suitable sampling methods [for an outline see Kaplan (1973)]. The concepts of attribute and variable sampling described above for material accountancy apply to the inspection of monetary accounts as well. In particular, there are tests to validate the reasonableness of account balances, without classifying a particular observation as correct or falsified.
Ch. 51:
lnspection Games
1953
These may be considered as variable measurement tests and are sometirnes termed 'dollar value' sarnples in the literature. These theoretical investigations include the use of game-theoretic methods. An early contribution that employs both noncooperative and cooperative garne theory is given by Klages (1968), who describes quite detailed models of the practical problems in accountancy and discusses the rnerits of a garne-theoretic approach. Borch (1982) forrnulates a zero-sum inspection garne between an accountant and his ernployer. The accountant, who is the inspectee, rnay either record transactions faithfully or cheat to embezzle some of the company's profits, and the ernployer rnay either trust the accountant or audit his accounts. If the inspectee is hortest, he receives payoff zero irrespective of the actions of the inspector. In that case, the inspector gets payoff zero if he trusts and has a certain cost if he audits. If the accountant steals while being trusted, he has a gain that is the ernployer's loss. If the inspector catches an illegal action, he has the sarne auditing cost as before but the inspectee must pay a penalty. Borch interprets mixed strategies as 'fractions of opportunities' in a repeated situation, but does not forrnalize this further. The emp]oyer may buy 'fidelity guarantee insurance' to cover losses caused by dishortest accountants. The insurance may require a strict auditing system that is costly to the employer. Borch (1982) considers a three-person garne where the insurance comparty inspects or alternatively trusts the ernployer if he audits properly. The employer is both inspectee, of the insurance cornpany, and inspector, of his accountant. No interaction is assumed between insurance cornpany and accountant, so this garne is fully described by two birnatrix garnes. For general 'polyrnatrix' garnes of this kind see Howson (1972). Borch (1990) sees many potential applications of garnes to the economics of insurance: in any situation where the insured has undertaken to take special rneasures to prevent accidents and reduce losses, there is a risk - usually called m o r a l h a z a r d - thät he may neglect bis obligations. The insurance cornpany reserves the right to inspect that the insured really carries out the safety rneasures foreseen in the insurance contract. This inspection costs rnoney, which the insured rnust pay for by an addition to the prerniurn. Moral hazard has its price. Therefore, inspections of econornic transactions raise the question of the most efficient design of such a system, for example so that surveillance is minimized or even unnecessary. These problems are closely related to a variety of economic rnodels known as p r i n c i p a I - a g e n t p r o b l e m s . They have been extensively studied in the economic literature, where we refer to the surveys by Bairnan (1982), Kanodia (1985), and Dye (1986). Agency theory focuses on the optimal contracted relationships between two individuals whose roles are asymmetric. One, the principal, delegates work or responsibility to the other, the agent. The principal chooses, based on his own interest, the payrnent schedule that best exploits the agent's self-interested behavior. The agent chooses an optimal level of action contingent on the fee schedule proposed by the principal. Orte irnportant issue in agency theory is the asymmetry of information
1954
R. Avenhaus et al.
available to the principal and the agent. In inspection garnes, a similar asymmetry exists with respect to defining the rules of the garne; see Section 5. We conclude this section with applications to tax inspections. Schleicher (1971) describes an interesting recursive game for detecting tax law violations, which extends Maschler (1966). Rubinstein (1979) analyzes the problem that it may be unjust to penalize illegal actions too hard since the inspectee might have committed them unintentionally. In a one-shot garne, there is no alternative to the inspector but to use a high penalty, although its potential injustice has a disutility. Rubinstein shows that if this garne is repeated, a more lenient policy also induces the inspectee to legal behavior. Another model of tax inspections, also using repeated garnes, is discussed by Greenberg (1984). A tax function defines the tax to be paid by an individual with a certain income. An audited individual who did not report its income properly must pay a penalty, and the tax authorities can audit only a limited percentage of individuals. Under reasonably weak assumptions about these functions and the individuals' utility functions on income, Greenberg proposes an auditing scheme that achieves an arbitrary small percentage of tax evaders. In that scheme, the individuals are partitioned into three groups that are audited with different probabilities, and individuals are moved among these groups after an audit depending on whether they cheated or not. A similar scheme of auditing individuals with different probabilities depending Oh their compliance history is proposed by Landsberger and Meilijson (1982). However, their analysis does not use garne theory explicitly. Reinganum and Wilde (1986) describe a model of tax compliance where they apply the sequential equilibrium concept. In that model, the income reporting process is considered explicitly as a signaling round. The tax inspector is only aware of the overall income distribution and reacts to the reported income. 2.3. Environmental control
Environmentalcontrol problems call for a game-theoretic treatment. One player is a firm which produces some pollution of air, watet or ground, and which can save abatement costs by illegal emission beyond some agreed level. The other player is a monitoring agent whose responsibility is to detect or better to prevent such illegal pollution. Both agents are assumed to act strategically. Various problems of this kind have been analyzed. However, contrary to arms control and disarmament, these papers do not yet address specific practical cases. Several papers present game-theoretic analyses of pollution problems bnt deal only marginally with monitoring problems. Bird and Kortanek (1974) explore various concepts in order to aid the formulation of regulations of sources of pollutant in the atmosphere related to given least cost solutions. Höpfinger (1979) models the problem of how to determine and adapt global emission standards for carbon dioxide as an infinite stage game with three players: regulator, producer, and population. Kilgour, Okada, and Nishikori (1988) describe the load control system for regulating chemical oxygen demand in water bodies. They formulate a cost sharing garne and solve it in some illustrative cases.
Ch. 51:
Inspection Garnes
1955
In the last years, pollution control problems have been analyzed with game-theoretic methods. Russell (1990) characterizes current enforcement of U.S. environmental laws as very likely inadequate, while admitting that proving this proposition would be extremely difficult, exactly because there is so little information about the actual behavior of regulated firms and government activities. As a remedy, a one-stage game between a polluter and an environmental protection agency is used as a benchmark for discussing a multiple-stage garne in which the source's past record of discovered violations determines its future probabilities of being monitored. It is shown that this approach can yield significant savings in limiting the extent of violations to a particular frequency in the population of polluters. Weissing and Ostrom (1991) examine how irrigation institutions affect equilibrium rates of stealing and enforcement. Irrigators come periodically into the position of turntakers. A turntaker chooses between taking a legal amount of water and taking more water than authorized. The other irrigators are turnwaiters who must decide whether to expand resources for monitoring the behavior of the turntaker or not. For no combination of parameters the rate of stealing by the turntaker drops to zero, so in equilibrium some stealing is always going on. Güth and Pethig (1992) consider a polluting firm that can save abatement costs by illegal waste emission, and a monitoring agent whose job it is to prevent such pollution. When deciding on whether to dispose of its waste legally or illegally the firm does not know for sure whether the controller is sufficiently qualified or motivated to detect the firm's illegal releases of pollutant. The firm has the option of undertaking a small-scale deliberate 'exploratory pollution accident' to get a hint about the controller's qualification before deciding on how to dispose of its waste. The controller may or may not respond to that 'accident' by a thorough investigation, thus perhaps revealing his type to the firm. This sequential decision process along with the asymmetric distribution of information constitutes a signaling garne whose equilibrium points may signal the type of the controller to the firm. Avenhaus (1994) considers a decision theoretic problem. The management of an industrial plant may be authorized to release some amount of pollutant per unit time into the environment. An environmental agency may decide with the help of randomly sampled measurements whether or not the real releases are larger than the permitted ones. The 'best' inspection procedure can be determined by the use of the Neyman-Pearson lemma; see Section 3 below. 2.4. M i s c e l l a n e o u s models
A number of papers do not belong to the above categories. Some of these deal - at least theoretically - with smuggling or crime control, other papers treat inspection games in an abstract setting. Thomas and Nisgav (1976) consider a garne where a smuggler tries to cross a strait in one of M nights. The inspecting border police has a speedboat for patrolling on k of these nights. On a patrolled night, the smuggler runs some risk of being caught. The game is described recursively in the same way as the garne by Dresher (1962). The
1956
R. Avenhaus et al.
only difference is that the smuggler must traverse the strait even if there is a patrol every night, or else receive the same worst payoff as he would if he were caught. The resulting recurrence equation for the garne has a very simple solution where the garne value is a linear function of k/M. B aston and B ostock (1991) generalize the paper by Thomas and Nisgav (1976). They clarify some implicit assumptions made by these authors, in particular the full information of the players about past events, and the detection probability associated with a night patrol. Then, they study the case of two boats and derive explicit solutions that depend on the detection probabilities if one boat or both are on patrol. The case of three boats is solved by Garnaev (1994). Sequential garnes with three parameters, namely number of nights, patrols, and smuggling acts, are solved by Sakaguchi (1994) and Ferguson and Melolidakis (1998). Among other things, Baston and Bostok (1991) and Sakaguchi (1994) reproduce the result by Dresher (1962), which they are not aware of. Ferguson and Melolidakis (2000) present an interesting unifying approach to these results, based on Gale (1957). Goldman and Pearl (1976) study inspections in an abstract setting, where the inspector has to select among several sites where an inspectee can cheat, and only a limited number of sites can be inspected in total. A simple model is successively refined to study the effects of penalty levels and inspection resources. Feichtinger (1983) considers a differential garne with a suggested application to crime control. The dynamic control variables of police and thief are the 'rate of law enforcement' and the 'pilfering rate', respectively. Avenhaus (1997) analyzes inspections in local public transportation systems and shows that inspection rates used in practice coincide with the game-theoretic equilibrium. Filar (1985) applies the theory of stochastic games to a generic 'traveling inspector model'. There a r e a number of sites, each with an inspectee that acts as an individual player. Each site is a state of the stochastic game. That state is deterministically controlled by the inspector who chooses the site to be inspected at the next time period. The inspector has unspecified costs associated with inspection levels, travel, and if he fails to detect a violation. The players' payoffs are either sums up to a finite stage, or limiting averages. In this model, all inspectees can be aggregated into a single player without changing equilibria. For finite horizon payoffs, the garne has equilibria in Markov strategies, which depend on the time and the state but not on the history of the garne. For limiting average payoffs, stationm'y strategies suffice, which only depend on the state. 3. Statistical decisions Many practical inspection problems are based on random sampling procedures. Furthermore, measurement techniques are often used which inevitably produce random and systematic errors. Then, it is appropriate to think of the inspection problem as being an extension of a statistical decision problem. The extension is game-theoretic since the inspector has to decide whether the inspectee has behaved illegally, and such an action is strategic and not random.
Ch. 51: lnspection Games
1957
In this section, we first present a general framework where we extend a classical statistical testing problem to an inspection garne. The 'illegal part' of that garne, where the inspectee has decided to violate, is equivalent to a two-person zero-sum game with the non-detection probability as payoff to the violator. If that garne has a value, then the Neyman-Pearson lemma can be used to determine an optimal inspection strategy. In this framework, we then discuss two important inspection models that have emerged from statistics: material accountancy and data verification.
3.1. General garne and analysis In a classical hypothesis testing problem, the statistician has to decide, based on an observation of a random variable, between two alternatives (H0 or H1) regarding the distribution of the random variable. To make this an inspection garne, assume that the distribution of the random variable is strategically controlled by another 'player' called the inspecree. More specifically, the inspectee can behave either legalIy or illegally. If he behaves legally, the distribution is according to the null hypothesis H0. If he chooses to act illegally, he also decides on a vioIation procedure which we denote by co. Thus, the distribution of the random variable Z under the alternative hypothesis H1 depends on the procedure co which is also a strategic variable of the inspectee. The statistician, called the inspector, has to decide between two actions, based on the observation z of the random variable Z: calling an alarm (rejecting H0) or no alarm (accepting H0). The random variable Z can be a vector, for instance in a multi-stage inspection. This rather general inspection garne is described in Figure 1. The pairs of payoffs to inspector and inspectee, respectively, are also shown in Figure 1. The status quo is legal action and no alarm, represented by the payoff 0 to both players. The payoffs for undetected illegal behavior are - 1 for the inspector and 1 for the inspectee. In case of a detected violation, the inspector receives - a and the inspectee - b . Finally, if a false alarm is raised, the inspector gets - e and the inspectee - h . These parameters are subject to the restrictions 0<e
0
0
(3.1)
since the worst event for the inspector is an undetected violation, an alarm is undesirable for everyone, and the worst event for a violator is to be caught. Sometimes it is also assumed that e < a, which means that for the inspector a detected violation, representing a 'failure of safeguards', is worse than the inconvenience of a false alarm. A pure strategy of the inspectee consists of a choice between legal and illegal behavior, and a violation procedure co. A mixed strategy is a probability distribution on these pure strategies. Since the garne under consideration is of perfect recall, such a mixed strategy is equivalent to a behavior strategy given by the probability q for acting illegally and a probability distribution on violation procedures co given that the inspectee acts illegally. Since the set ~ of violation procedures may be infinite, we assume that it includes, if necessary, randomized violations as well, which are therefore also denoted by co. That is, a behavior strategy of the inspectee is represented by a pair (q, co).
R. Avenhaus et al.
1958 nspectee)
'~~~~-~V ~
(-~) (°o)
(-;) (1 ~)
Figure 1. Inspection garne extending the statistical decision problem of the inspector, who has to decide betweenthe null hypothesis H0 and alternativehypothesis H 1 aboutthe distributionof the randomvariable Z. H0 meanslegal actionand H 1 m e a n s illegalactionof the inspecteewith violationprocedure ~o.The inspector is informedaboutthe observationz of Z, but does not knowif H0 or H 1is true. There is a separate information set for each z. The inspectorreceives the top payoffs, the inspectee the bottompayoffs. The parameters a, b, e, h are subjectto (3.1).
A pure strategy of the inspector is an alarm set, that is, a subset of the range of Z, with the interpretation that the inspector calls an alarm if and only if the observation z is in that set. A mixed strategy of the inspector is a probability distribution on pure strategies. A strategy of the inspector (pure or mixed) is also called a statistical test and will be denoted by 8. The alarm set or sets used in such a test are usually determined by first considering the errorprobabilities of falsely rejecting or accepting the null hypothesis, as follows. A statistical test 8 and a violation strategy co determine two conditional probabilities. The probability of an error of the first kind, that is, of a f a l s e alarm, is the probability «(8) of an alarm given that the inspectee acts legally, which is independent of co. The probability of an error of the second kind, that is, of non-detection, is the probability ß (8, co) that no alarm is raised given that the inspectee acts illegally. The inspection game has then the following normal form. The set of strategies of the inspector is A. The set of (behavior) strategies (q, co) of the inspectee is given by [0, 1] x £2. The payoffs to inspector and inspectee are denoted I(8, (q, co)) and V (6, (q, co)), respectively, where the letter ' V ' indicates that the inspectee may poten-
Ch. 51:
Inspection Games
1959
tially violate. In terms of the payoffs in Figure 1, these payoff functions are
I(3, (q, co)) = (1 -- q)(--e«(3)) + q(--a -- (1 - a)fl(3, co)), V(3, (q, co)) = (1 We are looking for an 3", (q*, co*) so that
q)(-h«(3)) + q(-b + (1 + b)/3(3, co)).
(3.2)
equilibrium of this noncooperative game. This is a strategy pair
~(~*, (q*, «)) ~>~(~, (q*,«)) V(3*, (q*, co*)) ~> V(,~*, (q, co))
for all 3 E A,
(3.3)
for all q E [0, 1], co E ~ .
Usually, there is no equilibrium in which the inspectee acts with certainty legally (q* = 0) or illegally (q* = 1). Namely, if q* = 0, then by (3.2), the inspector would choose a test 3" with oe(3*) = 0 excluding a false alarm. However, then the equilibrium condition for the inspectee in (3.3) requires - b + (1 + b)fl(3*, co*) ~ O, which means that the non-detection probability fi(3*, co*) has to be sufficiently low. This is usually not possible with a test 5" that has false alarm probability zero. On the contrary, such a test usually has a non-detection probability of one. Similafly, if q* = 1, then the inspector could always raise an alarm irrespective of his observation to maximize his payoff, so that « (5*) = 1 and fl (~*, co) = 0. However, then the equilibrium choice of the inspectee would not be q* = 1 since h < b by (3.1). Thus, in equilibrium, 0 < q* < 1,
(3.4)
and the inspectee is indifferent between legal and illegal behavior: - h « ( 3 * ) = - b + (1 + b)fl(3*, co*).
(3.5)
With respect to the non-detection probability fi, the payoff function in (3.2) is monotonically decreasing for the inspector and increasing for the inspectee. Thus, given any test 3, the inspectee will choose a violation mechanism co so as to maximize fi (3, co). In equilibrium, the inspectee will therefore determine co* (which depends on 3) so that fi(& co*) = maxo)cs2 fi(& co). Typically, fi is continuous and co ranges in a compact domain, so the m a x i m u m is achieved. On the side of the inspector, it is useful to choose first a fixed false alarm probability « and then consider only those tests that result in this error probability. Denote this set of tests {3 ~ A I o1(3) = ee} by A«. For these tests, the inspector's payoff in (3.2) depends only on the non-detection probability. Thus, he will choose that test 3" in A« that minimizes the worst-case non-detection probability fi(3*, co*). It follows that in equilibrium, the non-detection probability is represented by B(o0 := min m a x , ( & co).
(3.6)
1960
R. A v e n h a u s et al.
That is, the inspector's strategy is a minmax strategy with respect to the non-detection probability. This suggests that, given a false alarm probability ee, the equilibrium nondetection probability 13(ot) is the minmax value of a certain auxiliary zero-sum garne Ga which we call the 'non-detection' game: DEFINITION. Given the inspection garne in Figure 1 and « 6 [0, 1], the non-detection garne G« is the zero-sum garne (Aa, £2, fi), where: The set of strategies 8 of the inspector is Aa, the set of all statistical tests with false alarm probability oe. The set of strategies £2 of the inspectee consists of all violation strategies co. The payoff to the inspectee is the non-detection probability fi (8, co), which he tries to maximize and the inspector tries to minimize. In other words, the non-detection game Ga captures one part of our original game, namely the situation resulting after the inspectee has decided to behave illegally and the inspector has decided to use tests with false alarm probability •. Thus, Ga does not depend directly on the parameters a, b, e, h of the original game, but rather on the fact that these parameters determine the value of e~ in equilibrium. In order to find an equilibrium as in (3.3), we assume that the minmax value 13(«) in (3.6) of the game G« is a function 13 : [0, 1] --+ [0, 1] that fulfills 13(0) = 1, 13(1) = 0,
13 is convex, and continuous at 0.
(3.7)
These conditions imply that 13 is continuous and monotonically decreasing. An extreme example is the function 13(«) = 1 - « which applies if the inspector ignores his observation z and calls an alarm with probability «, independently of the data. The properties (3.7) are standard for statistical tests. In particular, 13 is convex since the inspector may randomize. THEOREM 3.1. Assume that for any false alarm probability ol, the non-detection garne G« has a value 13(oOfulfilling (3.7), where the optimal violation procedure co* in G«
does not depend on of. Then the inspection garne in Figure 1 has the equilibrium (8*, (q*, co*)), where: The false alarm probabiIity ol* = oe(8*) is the solution of -hc~* = - b + (1 ÷ b)13(oe*).
(3.8)
The probability q* of illegal behavior is given by q* =
e
e - (1 - a)13'(c~*)
(3.9)
where 13~(ot*) is a sub-derivative of the function 13 at oe*. The inspection strategy 8* and the violation procedure co* are optimal strategies in Ge,.
Ch. 51:
Inspection Garnes
1961
PROOF. Equation (3.8) is implied by (3.5). The probability q* of illegal behavior is determined as follows. By (3.7), the inspector's payoff in (3.2) is a convex combination of two concave functions of «, orte decreasing, the other increasing. For q = q*, the resulting concave function taust have its maximum at oe* (see also Figure 10 in Section 5 below). This implies (3.9), if the derivative fl/(o~*) of the function fl at o~* exists. Otherwise, one may take any sub-derivative/7~(ee*), defined as the derivative of any tangent supporting the convex function/3 at its argument of*. Since the zero-sum garne Ge, has a value, its solution 6", co* is part of an equilibrium, as argued above. Even if the inspector changes both of* and 3", he cannot improve his payoff by the assumption [due to Wölling (2000)] on co*. [] Usually, this equilibrium is unique. It is easy to see that by (3.7), Equation (3.8) has a unique solution «* in (0, 1). If/3 is differentiable at «*, then q* is also a unique solution to (3.9). The optimal strategies in the garne G«, are usually unique as well. At any rate, they are equivalent since the value fl («*) of the garne is unique. Theorem 3.1 shows that the inspection game is in effect 'decomposed' into two garnes which can be treated separately, such that the solution of one garne becomes a parameter of the second garne. Technically, this decomposition works as follows: solve the nonzero-sum garne in which the strategies are « E [0, 1] (false alarm probability) for the inspector, q E [0, 1] (probability for acting illegally) for the operator and in which the payoff functions are given by (3.2). The equilibrium («*, q*) is determined by Equations (3.8) and (3.9) and «* becomes a parameter of the zero-sum garne G « , The solution of G « is given by the optimal test (of significance ee*) and the optimal diversion strategy. The non-zero-sum game which determines the false alarm and violation probabilities is of a 'political' nature. The significance of the numerical values of these probabilities, thus, may be debated by practitioners since the latter depend on payoffs which are highly questionable: they are hard to measure since they are supposed to quantify political effects. The zero-sum game Ge,, which we may refer to as the non-detection garne, is of a technical nature, devoid of political considerations: given that the operator has decided to act illegally and the inspector has decided to restrict himself to false alarm probability ot*, what is the optimal statistical test for the inspector and what is the optimal illegal behavior (for the operator)? This garne is less debatable 'politically' but usually more challenging mathematically. In fact, many inspection games in the literature deal only with zero-sum models of this kind. Operationally, the most important tool for solving G« is the Neyman-Pearson lemma [see, e.g., Lehmann (1959)]. We assume first that the garne G« has a value, which can therefore be written as ß (o0 = max min fi (6, co). w~S2 ~EAc~
Hereby, the non-detection probability fl (3, co) for a given false alarm probability et is minimized, assuming that co (and thus the alternative hypothesis) is fully known. The corresponding best test 6" is described by the Neyman-Pearson lemma. This lemma
1962
R. Avenhaus et aL
provides a test procedure to decide between two simple hypotheses, that is, hypotheses which determine the respective probability distributions completely. With 8* thus found, it is offen possible to describe an optimal violation procedure co* against this test, which usually does not depend on ee. Then, it remains to show that these strategies form an equilibrium of the game Ga. In the following, we will demonstrate the use of the Neyman-Pearson lemma with two important applications. 3.2. Material accountancy
Material accountancy procedures are designed to control rare, dangerous, or precious materials. In particular, the material balance concept is fundamental to IAEA safeguards, where the inspector watches for a possible diversion of nuclear material and the inspectee is the operator of a nuclear plant. We consider the case of periodic inventory measurements. Further details of this model are described in Avenhaus (1986, Section 3.3). Consider a certain physical material balance area and a sequence of n inventory periods. At the beginning of the first period, the amount I0 of material under control is measured in the area. During the /th period, 1 ~< i ~< n, the known net amount Si of material enters the area, and at the end of that period, the amount Ii is measured in the area. The quantity Z i = [ i _ l -t- Si - [i,
l <~ i <~ n ,
is called the material balance test statistic for the/th inventory period. Under H0, its expected value is zero (because of the preservation of matter), Eo(Zi) = O,
(3.10)
1 <~i «. n.
Under HI, its expected value is/~i, El(Zi)=#i,
l«.i<~n, Z#i
=/~,
(3.11)
i
where/14 is the amount of material diverted in the/th period, and where/~ is the total amount of material to be diverted throughout all periods. Given normally distributed measurement errors, the random (column) vector Z = (Z1 . . . . . Z,,) 7 is multivariate normally distributed with covariance matrix Z, which is the same for H0 and HI. The elements of this matrix are given by
Cov(Zi, Z j) =
[ var(Zi) - var(Ii) -var(/i) 0
for i = j, for i = j - 1, forj=i-1, otherwise.
Ch. 51:
Inspection Games
1963
The two hypotheses to be tested by the inspector are defined by the expectation vectors E0 (Z) and El (Z) as given by (3.10) and (3.11). According to our general model, the 'best' test procedure is an equilibrium strategy of the inspector. By Theorem 3.1, this is an optimal strategy of the non-detection garne G« = (Aa, £2,/~). In this zero-sum game, the inspector's set of strategies Aa is, as above, the set of test procedures with a fixed false alarm probability te. The inspectee's set of strategies £2 is the set of all diversion vectors/x = (/zl . . . . . /~n) T that have fixed total diversion/z, that is, fulfill 1T/z = # with 1 = (1 . . . . . l) T. We assume - and will later show - that this garne has an equilibrium. Furthermore, this equilibrium involves only pure strategies of the players. For fixed diversion/x, the alarm set of the best test (the set of observations where the null hypothesis is rejected) is described by the Neyman-Pearson lemma. It is given by the set of observations z = (zl, . . . , z,2) x
{z flfo(z)(Z) } > k
,
(3.12)
where fl and f0 are the densities of the random vector Z = (Z1 . . . . . Zn) T under H~ respectively H0. These are 1
fl (Z) = "
~/(27r)"- 1~71
exp ( - ~1 • (z
-
//,)T ~ I(Z __ ~)) '
and the density f0 has the same form with # replaced by the zero vector. Finally, k is a parameter that is determined according to the false alarm probability «. This alarm set is equivalent to the set {z [ / x T z ' - l Z > X'}
(3.13)
for some U, which means that the test statistic is the linear expression j~T~-I Z. Since Z is multivariate normally distributed, a linear combination a T z of its components, for any n-vector a, is univariate normally distributed with expectation 0 under H0 and aT/~ under Hl, and variance aT27a. Thus, the expected value o f / t T x - 1 Z is E(/zTzT_IZ ) = { 0 #Tx-l/t and its variance
under H0, under Hl"
R. Avenhaus et al.
1964
Surprisingly, mean and variance are equal under H~. Therefore, the probability of detection as a function of the false alarm probability is given by 1 - / ~ = 4~ ( ~ Z ' - l / z
- q~_«)
(3.14)
where 4) denotes the Gaussian or normal distribution function and q l-« the corresponding quantile (given by the inverse of 45). THEOREM 3.2. The optimal strategy of the inspectee in the non-detection garne Gc~for material accountancy is
~* =
~:1. ~
(3.15)
1T~I"
The value fl* of the game is given by the equation
# 1-~*-- q~( l~,/iV2i q' _~),
(3.16)
which describes the probability of detection in equilibrium. The optimal strategy 3" of the inspector is based on the test statistic 1 T z with the alarm set {z I 1Tz > 1T~-T~ • ql «}. The strategy pair 3*, I~* is an equilibrium of G«. PROOF. By (3.14), the optimal diversion vector /L* minimizes / z T 2 ; - I # for all /L subject to 1T/~ = #. Since Z -1 is symmetric, the gradient of this objective function is 2/LTz -1 , whereas the gradient of the constraint equation is 1T. For the optim u m / z =/z*, these gradients are collinear with a suitable Lagrange multiplier, which means that #* is a multiple of 2~1 as in (3.15). With /L = #* in (3.14) one obtains (3.16). The test statistic used in the alarm set (3.13), suitably scaled, is 1Tz. S ince it has variance 1T2;1, the alarm set corresponding to the false alarm probability « is {z ] 1TZ > 17«/]B~l'ql «}. Finally, we show that these optimal strategies fulfill the equilibrium criterion ß(3*,#)~~(3*,#*)-..
f o r a l l 3 @ A « , /z~S2.
Since we have constructed the Neyman-Pearson test for any diversion strategy/z, the right inequality is just the Neyman-Pearson lemma applied to #*. The left inequality holds for all # as equality since the optimal test 3* is based on the statistic 1 T z which is normally distributed with mean 1T/z and variance 1T2~l, that is, this distribution, and hence the detection probability, does not depend on the diversion vector/L, as long as 1T/z = #. [] This solution deserves several remarks. Both players use pure strategies. In particular, the inspectee does not randomize over diversion plans. By proving the equilibrium
Ch. 51: Inspection Garnes
1965
property with the Neyman-Pearson lemma, we did not have to consider all possible tests 3 of the inspector explicitly. Even defining the set of these strategies would be complicated. The optimal test procedure 6" does not depend on the total diversion/z. This adds to the appeal of the model since the total diversion tx might not be known. It is a parameter of the non-detection garne which is only relevant for the violation strategy in (3.15). The optimal test statistic of the inspector is
1T Z = ~-~ Zi ~- Io -~- ~-'~ Si - In i=1
i=1
which is the overall material balance for all periods. This means that the intermediate inventories are ignored. In fact, the same result is obtained if one considers the problem of subdividing a plant into several material balance areas: for the general payoff structure used so rar, the equilibrium strategy of the inspector does not require subdividing the plant. This example demonstrates the power of the Neyman-Pearson lemma of statistics in connection with the game-theoretic concept of an equilibrium. We should emphasize that, as in many game-theoretic problems, finding a pair of equilibrium strategies can be rather difficult, while it is usually easy to verify its properties.
3.3. Data verification As already mentioned, I A E A safeguards are based on material accountancy, which derives from the physical principle of the preservation of matter. A second, operational principle of the I A E A is data verification. The inspector has to compare the material balance data reported by the plant operators (via their national authorities) with his own findings in order to verify that these data are not falsified for the purpose of concealing diversion of nuclear material. Since both sets of data, those of the operators and of the inspector, are based on measurements, statistical errors cannot be avoided. Furthermore, since one has to assume that the operators will - if at all - falsify their reported data strategically, decision problems arise which are very similar to those analyzed before. Again, the Neyman-Pearson lemma has to be applied, and again very interesting solutions, both from a theoretical and practical point of view, are obtained. We present an analytical model taken from Avenhaus (1986). It has a number of variations which have been solved in the literature or which a r e a topic of current research, as outlined below. Assume that a nuclear plant is shut down and that the plant operator, the inspectee, has collected the nuclear material in K classes with Ni batches in the/th class, i = 1 . . . . , K. Typically, each class represents a particular type of measurement method. The operator has measured all contents of all batches and has reported the results to an inspector of the IAEA. The inspector, in turn, measures some of the material contents in order to compare them with the reported ones. His decision problem will be how to allocate his limited inspection effort. Before we can describe this, we have to make assumptions
R. Avenhaus et al.
1966
about the measurement statistics, and, as we will see, about the possible falsification of the data. L e t vij be the true value of the content of the j t h batch of t h e / t h class, and let eij be the operator's random measurement error. The measurement result Xij c a n therefore be written as
xij
=
Vij -t- eij
for i = 1 . . . . . K, j = 1 . . . . . Ni.
(3.17)
We assume that the random variables E i j associated with the errors are independent and normally distributed with zero expectation and variances a ol 2 that are specific to the class i and to the operator's instruments, written as
Eij ~ N ( O , a2i)
for/=
1 . . . . . K, j =
1 . . . . . Ni.
Under the null hypothesis H0, no data are falsified. Then, the data reported by the operator are given by (3.17). Under the alternative hypothesis H1, the operator is assumed to falsify all bateh data of one class by a class-specific positive amount/*i, so that each batch in that class is reported to contain/z i more material than it actually does. In that case, the reported data are given by
Xij
= Vij
--}-lZi q- eij
for i = 1 . . . . . K, j = 1 . . . . . Nj.
Of course, this is a very restrictive assumption about the falsification that takes place. It may be justified with practical arguments, for example manipulation of the calibration of the measuring instruments. More general assumptions are very difficult to handle. We will mention approaches in that direction below. The inspector verifies ni randomly chosen items in t h e / t h class with the help of his own measurements. Without loss of generality, let these be the first ni ones. Then, the inspector's findings Yij a r e
Yij
--= vij --}- d i j
for i = 1 . . . . . K, j = 1 . . . . . nj.
The random variables D i j associated to the inspector's errors dij are independent and normally distributed with zero expectation and variances a ~ ,
Dij~N(O,a~i )
fori=l
. . . . . K, j = l
. . . . . ni.
The inspector is not interested in estimating the true values !)ij but only in verifying the reported data. Therefore, he uses the differences
Zij
= Xij --
Yij
for i ---- 1 . . . . . K, j = 1 . . . . .
ni
Ch.51: InspectionGarnes
1967
for constructing his verification test. According to our assumptions, we have Zij~N(izit,~r
fori=l,...,K,
2)
j=l
. . . . . ni, t = 0 , 1 ,
where ~r2 = ~roi2+ 0"/2/,and where
Bit = {0#i
fort=0(H0), for t = 1 (H1).
The inspector uses the Neyman-Pearson test. As above in (3,12), its alarm set is with z ----(zl~ . . . . . zKnx) given by
z
fo(z)
> X ,
where for t = 0, 1
ft(z)= (~-I
1
)
(vF2_~cri)n , i=i
( 1B~'~ (ZiJ--P~it)2~
.exp - ~
;/~
i=1 j=l
].
Therefore, the alarm set is explicitly given by
z
Zij > z
7~ '=
~ j=l
Now we have under Ht, t -= 0, 1,
Z«i2 i=I
--'~1 ziJ~i . ~ N
/.Z2 t?, ~-]niv]. K #2~ nj-O - i=I
j=
Thus, the probabilities of error of the first and second kind are given by ù ~
oe=l-4~
/
Zn
and
x-,K
9
#(,
fl=
Vc,=,n,~ If we eliminate )~' with the help of «, then we get the non-detection probability
fl = 1 -- crp
ni - ~ -- ql-c~
•
(3.18)
1968
R. Avenhaus et al.
In order to describe the strategy sets of the players, let us assume that the operator wants to falsify all data by the fixed total amount/~. Furthermore, let one measurement by the inspector in t h e / t h class, i = 1 . . . . . K, cost the effort el, where the total effort available, measured in monetary terms or inspection hours, is s. This means, according to Theorem 3.1, that we consider the following non-detection game Ge. THEOREM 3.3. Let G« be the zero-sum garne in which the sets of strategies for inspec-
tor and inspectee are, respectively,
n = (nl .....
nK)
and
eini =
I L ---- (/~1 . . . . .
l~K)
Nißi
= Iz
.
i=1
i=i
The payoff to the inspectee is il(n, IL) defined by (3.18). Considering n as a vector of continuous variables, this garne has an equilibrium n*, IL*, given by Ni (7i
E
IC*
~ K = I Njaj ~
for i -= 1. . . . . K. /z*
B
.O-iß
(3.19)
'
Elf_l Njaj v/è~ The value of the garne is
~(ù*,IL*) = 1-®(\ 2 K _ l -~~ ) Nj~rjq/~--ql-« " PROOF. The equilibrium conditions say that for all n, IL in the strategy sets
~(ù*, IL)~ ~(-*, IL*)<~z(ù, IL*) holds. By (3.18), this is equivalent to K
* ~2
K
n i - - >t Z n*
/L~2
K
/~.2 for all n, IL.
The right inequality is identically fulfilled. Since Y~f-1 Ni IZi = Iz, the left inequality is just a special case of the Cauchy-Schwarz inequality ( ~ aZ)(F_, bZ) >~( ~ aibi)2 with a z = Niß2i/ai ~ and b 2 = Niai ~/~l. [] The sampling design defined by (3.19) is known in the statistical literature as Neyman-Chuprov sampling [see, e.g., Cochran (1963)]. The above model provides a game-theoretic justification for this sampling design.
1969
Ch. 51: lnspectionGarnes
This data verification problem has a lot of ramifications if one assumes more general falsification strategies. It may be unrealistic to assume that all batches in class i are falsified by the same amount #i. In particular, this is the case for a high total diversion # that can no longer be hidden in measurement errors for the individual batches. In that case, it turns out that the inspectee will concentrate bis falsification on as few batches as possible, in the hope that these will not be measured by the inspector. A theoretical analysis of the general case is very difficult. Some approaches in this direction have been made for unstratified problems, that is, only a single class of batches; see Avenhaus, Battenberg and Falkowski (1991), Mitzrotsky (1993), Avenhaus and Piehlmeier (1994), Piehlmeier (1996), and Battenberg and Falkowski (1998).
4. Sequential inspections Certain inspections evolve over a number of stages. The number of inspections may be limited, and statistical errors may occur. The models presented in this section vary with respect to the information of the players about the course of the game, the rules for detecting a violation, and the resulting payoffs. 4.1. Recursive inspection garnes
We consider sequential inspections with a finite number of inspection stages. Their models can be defined recursively and their solution is given by a recurrence equation, which in some cases is solved explicitly. The recursive description implies that each player learns about the action of the other player after each stage, which is not always justified. This is not problematic if the inspectee can violate at most once, so we consider this case first. The inspection game introduced by Dresher (1962) has n stages. At each stage, the inspector may or may not use an inspection, with a total of m inspecfions permitted for all stages. The inspectee may decide at a stage to act legally or illegally, and will not perform more than one illegal act throughout the garne. Illegal action is detected if and only if there is an inspection at the same stage. Dresher modeled this garne recursively, assuming zero-sum payoffs. For the inspector, this payoff is one unit for a detected violation, zero for legal action throughout the game, and a loss of one unit for an undetected violation. The value of the game, the equilibrium payoffto the inspector, is denoted by I (n, rn) for the parameters 0 ~< m ~< n. For m = n, the inspector will inspect at every stage and the inspectee will act legally, and similarly the decision is unique for m = 0 where the inspectee can safely violate, so that I(n,n)=O
forn~>O
and
I(n,O)=-i
forn>O.
(4.1)
For 0 < m < n, the garne is represented by the recursive payoff matrix as shown in Figure 2. The rows denote the possible actions at the first stage for the inspector and the
1970
R. Avenhaus et al.
ect ee ---------•ßnsp Inspector~
legal action
inspection
z(,~
no inspection
1, ~
-
-
violation 1)
IOz - 1, rn,)
1 -1
Figure 2. The Dresher garne, showing the decisions at the first of n stages, with at most one intended violation and m inspections, for 0 < m < n. The garne has value 1 (n, m). The recursively defined entries denote the payoffs to the inspector.
columns those for the inspectee. If the inspectee violates, then he is either caught, where the garne terminates and the inspector receives 1, or not, after which he will act legally throughout, so that the garne eventually tenninates with payoff - 1 to the inspector. After a legal action of the inspectee, the garne continues as before, with n - 1 instead of n stages and m - 1 or m inspections left. In this game, it is reasonable to assume a circular structure of the players' preferences. That is, the inspector prefers to use his inspection if and only if the inspectee violates, who in turn prefers to violate if and only if the inspector does not inspect. This means that the garne has a unique mixed equilibrium point where both players choose both of their actions with positive probability. Hence, if the inspector's probability for inspecting at the first stage is p, then the inspectee taust be indifferent between legal action and violation, that is, p.
l(n
-
1) + (1
1,m-
-
p) • l(n
-
1,m)
= p +
(1 - p ) . ( - 1 ) .
(4.2)
Both sides of this equation denote the garne value I (n, m). Solving for p and substituting yields 1, m ) + l ( n 1,m) + 2 -
l(n I(n,m)
-
= 1(n -
I(n-
1,m - 1) 1,m - 1)"
(4.3)
With this recurrence equation for 0 < m < n and the initial conditions (4.1), the garne value is determined for all parameters. Dresher showed that Equations (4.1) and (4.3) have an explicit solution, namely
m
i=0 1
--
The p a y o f f s in Dresher's model have been generalized by Höpfinger (1971). He assumed that the inspectee's gain for a successful violation need not equal his loss if he is caught, and also solved the resulting recurrence equation explicitly. Furthermore, zerosum payoffs are not fully adequate since a caught violaüon, compared to legal action
Ch. 51:
Inspection Garnes
1971
pectee
legal action
Inspector~
v(~-l,~-
violation
1)
-b
inspection I(n--l,m-
ma
1) v ( ~ - 1, ~ )
no inspection
I(~ 1,o)
-1
Figure 3. Non-zero-sum garne at the first of n stages with m inspections, 0 < m < n, and equilibrium payoff I (n, m) to the inspector and V(n, m) to the inspectee. Legal action throughout the game has reference payoff zero to both players. A caught violation yields negative payoffs to both, where 0 < a < 1 and 0 < b.
throughout, is usually undesirable for both players since for the inspector this demonstrates a failure of his surveillance system. A non-zero-sum garne that takes account of this is shown in Figure 3. There, I(n, m) and V(n, m) denote the equilibrium payoff to the inspector and inspectee, respectively (' V' indicating a potential violator), and a and b a r e positive parameters denoting the losses to both players for a caught violation, where a < 1. Analogous to (4.1), the cases m = n and m = 0 are described by
I(n, n) = O, V(n, n) = O,
for n ~> 0
and
I(n, O) = - 1 , V(n, O) = 1,
for n > 0.
(4.4)
THEOREM 4.1. The recursive inspection garne in Figure 3 with initial conditions (4.4) has a unique equilibrium. The inspectee 's equilibrium payoff is given by
V(n,m)=(n21)/~-~.(?)bm-i
(4.5)
i=0
and the inspector's payoff by '(n,m)=-(n-1)/~-2(~)(-a)m-i. m
(4.6)
i=0
The equilibrium strategies are determined inductively, using (4.5) and (4.6), by solving the game in Figure 3. PROOF. As an inductive hypothesis, assume that the player's payoffs in Figure 3 are such that the garne has a unique mixed equilibrium; this is true for n = 2, m = 1
1972
R. Avenhaus et al.
by (4.4). The inspectee is then indifferent between legal action and violation. As in (4.2) and (4.3), this gives the recurrence equation
V(n, m) =
b. V ( n - l,m) ÷ V ( n - l , m - 1 ) V ( n - 1 , m - 1 ) + b + 1 - V ( n - 1,m)
for V(n, m), and a similar expression for I(n, m). The verification of (4.5) and (4.6) is shown by Avenhaus and von Stengel (1992), which generalizes and simplifies the derivations by Dresher (1962) and Höpfinger (1971). The assumed inequalities about the mixed equilibrium can be proved using the explicit representations. [] The same payoffs, although with a different normalization, have already been considered by Maschler (1966). He derived an expression for the payoff to the inspector that is equivalent to (4.6), considering the appropriate linear transformations for the payoffs. Beyond this, Maschler introduced the Ieadership concept where the inspector announces and commits himself to his strategy in advance. Interestingly, this improves his payoff in the non-zero-sum game. We will discuss this in detail in Section 5. The recursive description in Figures 2 and 3 assumes that all players know about the game state after each stage. This is usually not true for the inspector after a stage where he did not inspect, since then he will not learn about a violation. The constant payoffs after a successful violation indicate that the garne terminates. In fact, the game continues, but any further action of the inspector is irrelevant since then the inspectee will only behave legally. As soon as the the players' information is such that the recursive structure is not valid, the problem becomes difficult, as already noted by Kuhn (1963). Therefore, even natural and simple-looking extensions of Dresher's model are still open problems. Von Stengel (1991) shows how the recursive approach is still possible with special assumptions. Similar sequential games with three parameters, where the garne continues even after a detected violation, are described by Sakaguchi (1977, 1994) and Ferguson and Melolidakis (1998). The inspector's full information after each stage is not questioned in these models. In the situation studied by von Stengel (1991) the inspectee intends at most k violations and can violate at most once per stage. The inspectee collects one unit for each successful violation. As before, n and rn denote the number of stages and inspections. Like Dresher's garne, the garne is zero-sum, with value I (n, m, k) denoting the payoff to the inspector. That value is determined if all remaining stages either will or will not be inspected, or if the inspectee does not intend to violate: I (n, n, k) = O,
I (n, O, k) = - min{n, k},
I (n, m, O) = O.
(4.7)
If the inspector detects a violation, the garne terminates and the inspectee has to pay a positive penalty b to the inspector for being caught, but the inspectee does not have to return the payoff he got for previous successful violations. This means that at a stage the
Ch. 51:
Inspection Garnes
1973
Inspectee Inspecto~.__~
legal action
violation
inspection
[(n - 1, ra - 1, h)
b
no inspection
i(~
-
1, ~,~, k)
z ( ~ - 1, ~ , k - 1) - 1
Figure 4. First stage of a zero-sum garne with n stages, m inspections, and up to k intended violations, for 0 < m < n. The inspectee collects one unit for each successful violation, which he can keep even if he is caught later and has to pay the nonnegative amount b. The inspector is informed after each stage, even with no inspection, if there was a violation or not.
inspector does not inspect, a violation reduces k to k - 1 and a payoff of 1 is 'credited' to the inspectee, and legal action leaves k unchanged. Furthermore, it is assumed that even after a stage with no inspection, it becomes common knowledge whether there was a violation or not. This leads to a garne with recursive structure, shown in Figure 4. THEOREM 4.2. The recursive inspection garne in Figure 4 with initial conditions (4.7) has value
(2~,) z(ù, m, ~ ) :
"'+'"
(ra;l)
s(n, m )
wheres(n,m)=~-~~(~)b
m-i.
i=0
The probability p o f inspection at the first stage is p = s (n - 1, m - 1) / s (n, m ).
PROOF. Analogously to (4.3), one obtains a recurrence equation for I ( n , m, k), which has this solution shown by von Stengel (1991). [] In this game, the inspector's equilibrium payoff I (n, m, k) decreases with the number k of intended violations. However, that payoff is constant for all k ~> n - m since n-k then (ra+l) = 0. Indeed, the inspectee will not violate more than n - m times since otherwise he would be caught with certainty. Theorem 4.2 asserts that the the probability p of inspection at the first stage, determined analogously to (4.2), is given by p = s(n - 1, m - 1 ) / s ( n , m ) and thus does not depend on k. This means that the inspector need not k n o w the value of k in order to play optimally. Hence, the assumption in this game about the knowledge of the inspector after a period without inspection can be removed: the solution of the recursive garne is also the solution of the garne without recursive structure, where - more realistically the inspector does not know what happened at a stage without inspection. This is analyzed by von Stengel (1991) using the extensive form of the garnes. Some sequential models take into account statistical errors of the first and second kind [Maschler (1967); Thomas and Nisgav (1976); Baston and Bostock (1991); Rinderle (1996)]. Explicit solutions have been found only for special cases. -
1974
R. Avenhaus etaL
4.2. Timeliness g a m e s
In certain situations, the inspector uses a number of inspections during some time interval in order to detect a single violation. This violation is detected at the earliest subsequent inspection, and the time that has elapsed in between is the payoff to the inspectee that the inspector wants to minimize. The inspectee may or may not observe the inspections. In reliability theory, variants of this game have been studied by Derman (1961) and Diamond (1982). An operating unit may fail which creates a cost that increases with the time until the failure is detected. The overall time interval represents the time between normal replacements of the unit. A minmax analysis leads to a zero-sum game with the operating unit as inspectee which cannot observe any inspections. A more common approach in reliability theory, which is not our topic, is to assume some knowledge about the distribution of the failure time. Another application is interim inspections of direct-use nuclear material [see, e.g., Avenhaus, Canty and von Stengel (1991)]. Nuclear plants are regularly inspected, say at the end of the year. If nuclear material is diverted, one may wish to discover this not after a year but earlier, which is the purpose of interim inspections. One may assume either that the inspectee can violate just after he has observed an interim inspection, or that such observations or alterations of his diversion plan are not possible. The players choose their actions from the unit time interval. The inspectee violates at some time s in [0, 1). The inspector has m inspections (m ~> 1) that he uses at times t l , . . . , im, where his last inspection must take place at the end of the interval, tm = I. He can choose the other inspection times freely, with 0 ~< tl ~< ... ~< im-1 ~< tm = 1. The violation is discovered at the earliest inspection following the violation time s. Then, the time elapsed is the payoff to the inspectee given by the function V(S, tl . . . . . t m - l ) = t k - - S
fort~-l«.s
k = l . . . . . m,
(4.8)
where to = 0 and tm = 1. It is useful to assume that if the times of inspection and violation coincide, tk-1 = s, then the violation is not detected until the next inspection at time rk. The inspector's payoff is the negative of the payoff to the inspectee. If the inspector deterministically inspects at times ti = i / m for i = 1 . . . . . m, a violation is discovered at most after time 1 / m has elapsed. This is indeed an optimal inspection strategy if the inspectee can observe the inspections. In that case, the inspectee will violate immediately after the kth inspection assuming he can react without delay, where k is uniformly chosen from {0 . . . . . m - 1}. That is, the violation time s is uniformly chosen from {to, tl . . . . . tm-1}. Note that s is conditional upon the inspector's action. Then by (4.8) the expected time after the violation is discovered is 1 1 l ( t l - to) + ra(t2 - tl) + " " + m(tm - tn-1) = m1 ( t m - to) 1/m. A more involved model of such observable inspections is studied by Derman (1961). Each interim inspection detects a violation only with a certain fixed probability. In addition to the time until detection, there is a cost to be paid for each inspection. Derman describes a deterministic minmax schedule for the inspection times where ti is
Ch. 51: lnspection Games
1975
not proportional to i as before with ti = i / m , but a quadratic function of i, so that the inspections accumulate towards the end of the time interval because of their cost. If the inspections cannot be observed, then the violation time s and the free inspection times t l , . . . , tm-1 are chosen simultaneously. This is an appropriate assumption for inspecting an unreliable unit if the inspections do not interfere with the operation of the system. This game is completely solved by Diamond (1982). We will demonstrate the solution of the first nontrivial case m = 2. For m = 2, the inspector has one free inspection at time tl, for short t, chosen from [0, 1]. The inspectee may select his violation at time s 6 [0, 1). This is a zero-sum game over the unit square with payoff V(s, t) to the inspectee where, by (4.8), V(s't)=
{ t-sl- s
ifsifSt.
(4.9)
This describes a kind of duel with time reversed where both players have an incentive to act early but after the other. By (4.9), the inspectee's payoffis too small if he violates too late, so that he will select s with a certain probability distribution from an interval [0, b] where b < 1. Consequently, the inspector will not inspect later than b. THEOREM 4.3. The zero-sum garne over the unit square with payoff V(s, t) in (4.9) has the following solution. The inspector chooses the inspection time t from [0, b] according to the density function p(t) = 1/(1 - t), where b = 1 - 1/e. The inspectee chooses his violation time s according to the distribution function Q (s ) = l/e(1 - s) f o r s c [0, b], and Q(s) = l f o r s > b. The value o f the garne is 1/e. PROOF. The inspector chooses t 6 [0, b] according to a density function p, where o b p(t) dt = 1.
(4.10)
The expected payoff V(s) to the inspectee for s 6 [0, bi is then given as follows, taking into account that the inspection may take place before or after the violation: V(s) = =
f0~(1 - s ) p ( t ) dt ÷ f~ (t - s ) p ( t ) dt fo~p(t) dt + r ~tp(t) dt - s io~p(t) dt. dS
If the inspectee randomizes as described, then this payoff must be constant [see Karlin (1959, Lemma 2.2.1, p. 27)]. That is, its derivative with respect to s, which by (4.10) is given by p(s) - sp(s) - 1, should be zero. The density for the inspection time is therefore given by p(t) --
1
1-t'
1976
R. Avenhaus et aL
with b in (4.10) given by b = 1 - 1/e. The constant expected payoff to the violator is then V(s) = 1/e. For s > b, the inspectee's payoffis 1 - s which is smaller than 1/e so that he will indeed not violate that late. The optimal distribution of the violation time has an atom at 0 and a density q on the remaining interval (0, b]. We consider its distribution function Q (s) denoting the probability that a violation takes place at time s or earlier. The mentioned atom is Q (0), the derivative of Q is q. The resulting expected payoff - V ( t ) for t c [0, b] to the inspector is given by V(t) = t Q ( O ) +
L'
= tQ(O)+t
(t-s)q(s)ds+
L'
q(s)ds+
= t Q ( t ) + Q(b) - Q(t) -
f~
(1-s)q(s)ds
S~
q(s)ds-
fo~
sq(s)ds
fo~s q ( s ) d s .
Again, the inspector randomizes only if this is a constant function of t, which means that (t - 1) • Q(t) is a constant function of t. Thus, because Q(b) = Q(1 - l / e ) = 1, the distribution function of the violation time s is for s ~ [0, b] given by 1 Q(s) = e
1 1- s
and for s > b by Q(s) = 1. The nonzero atom is given by Q(0) = 1/e.
[]
Unsurprisingly, the value 1/e of the garne with unobservable inspections is better for the inspector than the value 1/2 of the garne with observable inspections. The solution of the garne for m > 2 is considerably more complex and has the following features. As before, the inspectee violates with a certain probability distribution on an interval [0, b], leaving out the interval (b, 1) at the end. The inspections take place in disjoint intervals. The inspection times are random, but it is a randomization over a one-parameterfamily of pure strategies where the inspecfions are fully con'elated. The optimal violation scheine of the inspectee is given by a distribution function which is piecewise defined on the m - 1 time intervals and has an atom at the beginning of the garne. For large m, the inspection times are rather uniformly distributed in their intervals and the value of the garne rapidly approaches 1/(2m - 4) from above. Based on this complete analytic solution, Diarnond (1982) also demonstrates computational solution methods for non-linear loss functions.
5. Inspector leadership The leadership principle says that it can be advantageous in a competitive situation to be the first player to select and stay with a strategy. It was suggested first by von
Ch. 51: InspectionGarnes
1977
Stackelberg (1934) for pricing policies. Maschler (1966) applied this idea to sequential inspections. The notion of leadership consists of two elements: the ability of the player first to announce his strategy and make it known to the other player, and second to commit himself to playing it. In a sense, it would be more appropriate to use the term commitment power. This concept is particularly suitable for inspection garnes since an inspector can credibly announce his strategy and stick to it, whereas the inspectee cannot do so if he intends to act illegally. Therefore, it is reasonable to assume that the inspector will take advantage of his leadership role.
5.1. Definition and introductory examples A leadership garne is constructed from a simultaneous garne which is a game in normal form. Let the players be I and II with strategy sets ,4 and £2, respectively. For simplicity, we assume that ,4 is closed under the formation of mixed strategies. In particular, ,4 could be the set of mixed strategies over a finite set. The two players select simultaneously their respective strategies 3 and co and receive the corresponding payoffs, defined as expected payoffs if g originally represents a mixed strategy. In the leadership version of the garne, one of the players, say player I, is called the leader. Pläyer II is called thefollower. The leader chooses a strategy g in ,4 and makes this choice known to the follower, who then chooses a strategy co in £2 which will typically depend on g and is denoted by o3(3). The päyoffs to the players are those of the simultaneous garne for the pair of strategies (g, co(8)). The strategy g is executed without giving the leader an opportunity to reconsider it. This is the commitmentpower of the leader. The simplest way to construct the leadership version is to start with the simultaneous garne in extensive form. Player I moves first, and player II has a single information set since he is not informed about that move, and moves second. In the leadership garne, that information set is dissolved into singletons, and the rest of the game, including payoffs, stäys the same, as indicated in Figure 5. The leadership garne has perfect information because the follower is precisely informed about the announced strategy g. He can therefore choose a best response co(g) to g. We assume that he always does this, even if g is not a strategy announced by the leader in equilibrium. That is, we only consider subgame perfect equilibria. Any randomized strategy of the follower can be described as a behavior strategy defined by a 'locäl' probability distribution on the set £2 of choices of the follower for each announced strätegy g. In a zero-sum garne which has a value, leadership has no effect. This is the essence of the minmax theorem: each player can guarantee the value even if he announces his (mixed) strategy to his opponent and commits himself to playing it. In a non-zero-sum garne, leädership can sometimes serve as a coordination device and as a method for equilibrium selection. The garne in Figure 6, for example, has two equilibria in pure strategies. There is no rule to select either equilibrium if the players are in symmetric positions. In the leadership garne, if player I is made a leader, he will
1978
R. Avenhaus et al.
Simultaneous game
Leadership v
e
r
s
~ 5 I
II
~) Figttre 5. The simultaneous garne and its leadership version in extensive form. The strategies 6 of player I include all mixed strategies. In the simultaneous garne, the choice o»of player II is the same irrespective of 3. In the leadership version, player I is the leader and moves first, and player II, the follower, may choose his strategy ~o(3)depending on the announced leader strategy 3. The payoffs in both garnes are the same.
i•
L
R 8
0
T 9
0 0
9
B 0
8
Figure 6. Garne where the unique equilibrium (T, L) of the leadershi version is one of several equilibria in the simultaneous garne. select T, and player II will follow by choosing L. In fact, (T, L) is the o n l y equilibrium of the leadership garne. Player II m a y even consider it advantageous that player I is a leader and accept the payoff 8 in this equilibrium (T, L) instead of 9 in the other pure strategy equilibrium (B, R) as a price for avoiding the undesirable payoff 0. However, a simultaneous garne and its leadership version may have different equilibria. The simultaneous garne in Figure 7 has a unique equilibrium in mixed strategies:
1979
Ch. 51: lnspection Games
t7
L 1
T
-1
_1/~
-1 0
1
B -1
0
Figure 7. A simultaneous garne with a urlique mixed equilibrium. Its leadership version has a unique equilibrium where the leader announces the same mixed strategy, but the foUower changes his strategy to the advantage of the leader.
player I plays T with probability ½ and B with probability ~, and player II plays L with probability ½ and R with probability 2. The resulting payoffs are 23 ' 3 1" In the leadership version, player I as the leader uses the same mixed strategy as in the simultaneous garne, and player Il gets the same payoff, but as a follower he will act to the advantage o f the leader, for the following reason. Consider the possible announced mixed strategies, given by the probability p that the leader plays T. If player II responds with L or R, the payoffs to player I are - p and p / 2 - 1, respectively. W h e n player II makes these choices, his own payoffs are p and 1 - 2 p , respectively. He therefore chooses R for p < ½, L for p > ½, and is indifferent for p = ½. The resulting payoff to the leader as a function of p is shown in Figure 8. The leader tries to maximize this payoff, which he achieves only if the follower plays L. Thus, player I announces any p that is greater than or equal to ½ hut as small as possible. This means announcing
0
1/3
1
payoff to I
p
$ - 1/3
- 2/3
i
L
-1 Figtu'e 8. Payoff to player I in the garne in Figure 7 as a function of the probability p that he plays T. It is assumed that player II uses his best response (L or R), which is unique except for p* = 1. Player I's equilibrium payoff in the simultaneous game is indicated by o, that in the leadership version by ..
1980
R. Avenhaus et al.
exactly 1, as pointed out by Avenhaus, Okada, and Zamir (1991): if the follower, who is then indifferent, were not to choose L with certainty, then it is easy to see that the leader could announce a slightly larger p, thus forcing the follower to play L and improve his payoff, in contradiction to the equilibrium property. Thus, the unique equilibrium of the leadership garne is that player I announces p* = ½ and player II responds with L and deterministically, as described, for all other announcements of p, which are not materialized. 5.2. Announced inspection strategy
Inspection problems a r e a natural case for leadership games since the inspector can make his strategies public. The inspectee cannot announce that he intends to violate with some positive probability. The example in Figure 7 demonstrates the effect of leadership in an inspection garne, with the inspector as player I and the inspectee as player II. This garne is a special case of the recursive game in Figure 3 for two stages (n = 2), where the inspector has one inspection (m = 1). Inspecting at the first stage is the strategy T, and not inspecting, that is, inspecting at the second stage, is represented by B. For the inspectee, L and R refer to legal action and violation at the first stage, respectively. The losses to the players in the case of a caught violation in Figure 3 have the special form a=½ andb=l. In this leadership garne, we have shown that the inspector announces his equilibrium strategy of the simultaneous garne, but receives a better payoff. By the utility assumptions about the possible outcomes of an inspection, that better payoff is achieved by legal behavior of the inspectee. It can be shown that this applies not only to the simple garne in Figure 7, but to the recursive game with general parameters n and m in Figure 3. However, the inspectee behaves legally only in the two-by-two games encountered in the recursive definition: if the inspections are used up (n > 0 but m = 0), then the inspectee can and will safely violate. Except for this case, the inspectee behaves legally if the inspector may announce his strategy. The definition of this particular leadership garne with general parameters n and m is due to Maschler (1966). However, he did not determine an equilibrium. In order to construct a solution, Maschler postulated that the inspectee acts to the advantage of the inspector when he is indifferent, and called this behavior 'Pareto-optimal'. Then he argued, as we did with the help of Figure 8, that the inspector can announce an inspection probability p that is slightly higher than p*. In that way, the inspector is on the safe side, which should also be recommended in practice. Maschler (1967) uses leadership in a more general model involving several detectors that can help the inspector determine under which conditions to inspect. Despite the advantage of leadership, announcing such a precisely calibrated inspection strategy looks risky. Above, the equilibrium strategy p* = ½ depends on the payoffs of the inspectee which might not be fully known to the inspector. Therefore, Avenhaus, Okada, and Zamir (1991) considered the leadership game for a simultaneous garne with incomplete information. There, the gain to the inspectee for a successful violation is
Ch. 51: lnspection Garnes
1981
a payoff in some range with a certain probability distribution assumed by the inspector. In that leadership garne, unlike in Figure 8, the inspector maximizes over a continuous payoff curve. He announces an inspection probability that just about forces the inspectee to act legally for any value of the unknown penalty b. This strategy has a higher equilibrium probability p* and is safer than that used in the simultaneous garne. The simple game in Figure 7 and the argument using Figure 8 are prototypical for many leadership garnes. In the same vein, we consider now the inspection game in Figure 1 as a simultaneous game, and construct its leadership version. Recall that in this garne, the inspector has collected some data and, using this data, has to decide whether the inspectee acted illegally or not. He uses a statistical test procedure which is designed to detect an illegal action. Then, he either calls an alarm, rejecting the null hypothesis H0 of legal behaviòr of the inspectee in favor of the alternative hypothesis H1 of a violation, or not. The first and second error probabilities « and/3 of a false rejection of H0 or H1, respectively, are the probabilities for a false alarm and an undetected violation. As shown in Section 3.1, the only choice of the inspector is in effect the value for the false alarm probability c from [0, 1]. The non-detection probability fl is then determined by the most powerful statistical test and defines the function fl («), which has the properties (3.7). Thereby, the convexity of fl implies that the inspector has no advantage in choosing o~ randomly since this will not improve his non-detection probability. Hence, for constructing the leadership garne as above in Secfion 5.1, the value of « can be announced deterministically. The possible acfions of the inspectee are legal behavior H0 and illegal behavior Hl. According to the payoff functions in (3.2), with q = 0 for H0 and q = 1 for H1, and the defnition of il(c), this defines the game shown in Figure 9. In an equilibrium of the simultaneous garne, Theorem 3.1 shows that the inspector chooses c* as defined by (3.8). Furthermore, the inspectee violates with positive probability q* according to (3.4) and (3.9). This is different in the leadership version. THEOREM 5.1. The leadership version of the simultaneous garne in Figure 9 has a unique equilibrium where the inspector announces c* as defined by (3.8). In response to c, the inspectee violates if c < c*, and acts legally if a >~c*.
!~~.~pectee Inspector
legal action Ho
violation //1
-hc~
Œ [o, 1] --COL
- b + (1 + ó ) 9 ( ~ ) -a
- (1 -
a)t3(a)
Figure 9. The garne of Figure 1 with payoffs (3.2) depending on the false alarm probability ce. The nondetection probability il(c) for the best test has the properties (3.7).
R. Avenhaus et al.
1982
payoff to Inspector
~0
OZ*
0
I
--eß*
me
ma
-1
Y
Figure 10. The inspector's payoff in Figure 9 as a function of ce for the best responses of the inspectee. For oe < ce* the inspectee behaves illegally, hence the payoff is given by the curve H 1. For « > o~* the inspectee behaves legally and the payoff is given by the line H0. In the simultaneousgarne, the inspectee plays H 1 with probability q* according to (3.9), so that the inspector's payoff, shown by the thin line, has its maximum for a*; this is bis equilibrium payoff, indicated by o. The inspector's equifibriumpayoff in the leadership game is marked by o. PROOF. The response of the inspectee is unique for any announcement of o~ except for «*. Namely, the inspectee will violate if « < oe*, and act legally if a > o~*. The inspector's payoffs for these responses are shown in Figure 10. As argued with Figure 8, the only equilibrium of the leadership game is that in which the inspector announces o~*, and the inspectee acts legally in response. [] Summarizing, we observe that in the simultaneous game, the inspectee violates with positive probability, whereas he acts legally in the leadership garne. Inspector leadership serves as deterrence from illegal behavior. The optimal false alarm probability o~* of the inspector stays the same. His payoff is larger in the leadership game.
6. Conclusions One of our claims is that inspection games constimte a real field of applications of game theory. Is this justified? Have these games actually been used? Did game theory provide more than a general insight, did it have an operational impact? The decision to implement a particular verification procedure is usually not based on a game-theoretic analysis. Practical questions abound, and the allocation of inspection effort to various sites, for example, is usually based on rules of thumb. Most stratified sampling procedures of the I A E A are of this kind [IAEA (1989)]. However, they can often be justified by game-theoretic means. We mentioned that the subdivision of a plant into small areas with intermediate balances has no effect on the overall detection probability if the violator acts strategically - such a physical separation may only improve
Ch. 51:
lnspection Garnes
1983
localizing a diversion of material. With all caution concerning the impact of a theoretical analysis, this observation may have influenced the design of some nuclear processing plants. Another question concems the proper scope of a game-theoretic model. For example, the course of second-level actions - after the inspector has raised an alarm - is offen determined politically. In an inspection game, the effect of a detected violation is usually modeled by an unfavorable payoff to the inspectee. The particular magnitude of this penalty, as well as the inspectee's utility for a successful violation, is usually not known to the analyst. This is often used as an argument against garne theory. As a counterargument, the signs of these payoffs offen suffice, as we have illustrated with a rather general model in Theorem 3.1. Then, the part of the garne where a violation is to be discovered can be reduced to a zero-sum garne with the detection probability as payoff to the inspector, as first proposed by Bierlein (1968). We believe that inspection models should be of this kind, where the merit of garne theory as a technical tool becomes clearly visible. 'Political' parameters, like the choice of a false alarm probability, are exogenous to the model. Higher-level models describing the decisions of the states, like whether to cheat or not, and in the extreme whether 'to go to war' or not, should in out view not be blended with an inspection garne. They are likely to be simplistic and will invalidate the analysis. Which direction will or should research on inspection garnes take in the foreseeable future? The interesting concrete inspecfion garnes are stimulated by problems raised by practitioners. In that sense we expect continued progress from the application side, in particular in the area of environmental control where a ffuifful interaction between theorists and environmental experts is still missing. Indeed there are open questions which shall be illustrated with the material accountancy example discussed in Section 3.2. We have shown that intermediate inventories should be ignored in equilibrium. This means, however, that a decision about legal or illegal behavior can be made onty at the end of the reference time. This may be too long if detection time becomes a criterion. If one models this appropriately, one enters the area of sequential garnes and sequential statistics. With a new 'non-detection garne' similar to Theorem 3.1 and under reasonable assumptions one can show that then the probability of detection and the false alarm probability are replaced by the average run lengths under H1 and H0, respectively, that is, the expected times unfil an alarm is raised [see Avenhaus and Okada (1992)]. However, they need not exist and, more importantly, there is no equivalent to the Neyman-Pearson lemma which gives us constructive advice for the best sequential test. Thus, in general, sequential statistical inspection garnes represent a wide field for future research. From a theoretical point of view, the leadership principle as applied to inspection garnes deserves more attention. In the case of sequential garnes, is legal behavior again an equilibrium strategy of the inspectee? How does the leadership principle work if more complicated payoff structures have to be considered? Does the inspector in general improve his equilibrium payoff by credibly announcing his inspection strat-
1984
R. Avenhaus et al.
e g y ? W e t h i n k t h a t f o r f u r t h e r r e s e a r c h , a n u m b e r o f r e l a t e d i d e a s in e c o n o m i c s , like p r i n c i p a l - a g e n t p r o b l e m s , s h o u l d b e c o m p a r e d m o r e c l o s e l y w i t h l e a d e r s h i p as pres e n t e d here. I n this c o n t r i b u t i o n , w e h a v e tried to d e m o n s t r a t e t h a t i n s p e c t i o n g a r n e s h a v e real a p p l i c a t i o n s a n d are u s e f u l tools for h a n d l i n g p r a c t i c a l p r o b l e m s . T h e r e f o r e , t h e m a j o r e f f o r t in t h e future, also in the i n t e r e s t o f s o u n d t h e o r e t i c a l d e v e l o p m e n t , s h o u l d b e s p e n t in d e e p e n i n g t h e s e a p p l i c a t i o n s , a n d - e v e n m o r e i m p o r t a n t l y - in t r y i n g to c o n v i n c e p r a c t i t i o n e r s o f the u s e f u l n e s s o f a p p r o p r i a t e g a m e - t h e o r e t i c m o d e l s .
References Altmann, J., et al. (eds.) (1992), Verification at Vienna: Monitoring Reductions of Conventional Armed Forces (Gordon and Breach, Philadelphia). Anscombe, EJ., et al. (eds.) (1963), "Applications of statistical methodology to arms control and disarmament", Final Report to the U.S. Arms Control and Disarmament Agency under contract No. ACDA/ST-3 by Mathematica (Princeton, N.J.). Anscombe, EJ., et al. (eds.) (1965), "Applications of statistical methodology to arms control and disarmament", Final Report to the U.S. Arms Control and Disarmament Agency under Contract No. ACDA/ST-37 by Mathematica (Princeton, N.J.). Avenhaus, R. (1986), Safeguards Systems Analysis (Plenum, New York). Avenhaus, R. (1994), "Decision theoretic analysis of pollutant emission monitoring procedures", Annals of Operations Research 54:23-38. Avenhaus, R. (1997), "Entscheidungstheoretische Analyse der Fahrgast-Kontrollen", Der Nahverkehr 9/97 (Alba Fachverlag, Düsseldorf) 27-30. Avenhaus, R., H.E Battenberg and BJ. Falkowski (1991), "Optimal tests for data verification", Operations Research 39:341-348. Avenhaus, R., and M.J. Canty (1996), Compliance Quantified (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Avenhans, R., M.J. Canty and B. von Stengel (1991), "Sequential aspects of nuclear safeguards: Interim inspections of direct use material", in: Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Facility Operations-Safeguards Interface, American Nuclear Society, Albuquerque, New Mexico, 104-110. Avenhaus, R., and A. Okada (1992), "Statistical criteria for sequential inspector-leadership garnes", Journal of the Operations Research Society of Japan 35:134-151. Avenhans, R., A. Okada and S. Zamir (1991), "Inspector leadership with incomplete information", in: R. Selten, ed., Garne Equilibrium Models IV (Springer, Berlin) 319-361. Avenhaus, R., and G. Piehlmeier (1994), "Recent developments in and present state of variable sampling", in: IAEA-SM-333/7, Proceedings of a Symposium on International Nuclear Safeguards 1994: Vision for the Future, Vol. I. IAEA, Vienna, 307-316. Avenhaus, R., and B. von Stengel (1992), "Non-zero-sum Dresher inspection garnes", in: E Gritzmann et al., eds., Operations Research '91 (Physica-Verlag, Heidelberg) 376-379. Balman, S. (1982)~ "Agency research in managerial accounting: A survey", Journal of Accounting Literature 1:154-213. Baston, V.J., and F.A. Bostock (1991), "A generalized inspection garne", Naval Research Logistics 38:171182. Battenberg, H.E, and B.J. Falkowski (1998), "On saddlepoints of two-person zero-sum garnes with applications to data verification tests", International Journal of Garne Theory 27:561-576. Bierlein, D. (1968), "Direkte Inspektionssysteme", Operations Research Verfahren 6:57-68. Bierlein, D. (1969), "Auf Bilanzen und Inventuren basierende Safeguards-Systeme", Operations Research Verfahren 8:30-43.
Ch. 51:
lnspection Games
1985
Bird, C.G., and K.O. Kortanek (1974), "Garne theoretic approaches to some air pollution regulation problems", Socio-Economic Planning Sciences 8:141-147. Borch, K. (1982), "Insuilng and auditing the auditor", in: M. Deistler, E. Fürst, and G. Schwödianer, eds., Garnes, Economic Dynamics, Time Seiles Analysis (Physica-Verlag, Würzburg) 117-126. Reprinted in: K. Borch (1990), Economics of Insurance (North-Holland, Amsterdam) 350-362. Borch, K. (1990), Economics of Insurance, Advanced Textbooks in Economics, Vol. 29 (North-Holland, Amsterdam). Bowen, W.M., and C.A. Bennett (eds.) (1988), "Statistical methodology for nuclear material management", Report NUREG/CR-4604 PNL-5849, prepared for the U.S. Nuclear Regulatory Commission, Washington, DC. Brams, S., and M.D. Davis (1987), "The veilfication problem in arms control: A garne theoretic analysis", in: C. Ciotti-Revilla, R.L. Meriltt and D.A. Zinnes, eds., Interaction and Communication in Global Politics (Sage, London) 141-161. Brams, S., and D.M. Kilgour (1988), Game Theory and National Security (Basil Blackwell, New York) Chapter 8: Veilfication. Cochran, W.G. (1963), Sampling Techniques, 2nd edn (Wiley, New York). Derman, C. (1961), "On minimax surveillance schedules", Naval Research Logistics Quarterly 8:415-419. Diamond, H. (1982), "Minimax policies for unobservable inspections", Mathematics of Operations Research 7:139-153. Dresher, M. (1962), "A sampling inspection problem in arms control agreements: A game-theoretic analysis", Memorandum No. RM-2972-ARPA, The RAND Corporation, Santa Monica, CA. Dye, R.A. (1986), "Optimal monitoring policies in agencies", RAND Journal of Economics 17:339-350. Feichtinger, G. (1983), "A differential garnes solution to a model of competition between a thief and the police", Management Science 29:686~599. Ferguson, T.S., and C. Melolidakis (1998), "On the inspection garne", Naval Research Logistics 45:327-334. Ferguson, T.S., and C. Melolidakis (2000), "Garnes with finite resonrces", International Journal of Garne Theory 29:289-303. Filar, J.A. (1985), "Player aggregation in the traveling inspector model", IEEE Transactions on Automatic Control AC-30:723-729. Gal, S. (1983), Search Garnes (Academic Press, New York). Gale, D. (1957), "Information in games with finite resources', in: M. Dresher, A.W. Tucker and P. Wolle, eds., Contributions to the Theory of Garnes III, Annals of Mathematics Studies 39 (Pilnceton University Press, Pilnceton) 141-145. Garnaev, A.Y. (1994), "A remark on the customs and smuggler garne", Naval Research Logistics 41:287-293. Goldman, A.J. (1984), "Strategic analysis for safeguards systems: A feasibility study, Appendix", Report NUREG/CR-3926, Vol. 2, prepared for the U.S. Nuclear Regulatory Commission, Washington, DC. Goldman, A.J., and M.H. Pearl (1976), "The dependence of inspection-system performance on levels of penalties and inspection resources", Journal of Research of the National Burean of Standards 80B: 189236. Greenberg, J. (1984), "Avoiding tax avoidance: A (repeated) game-theoretic approach", Journal of Economic Theory 32:1-13. Güth, W., and R. Pethig (1992), "Illegal pollufion and monitoilng of unknown quality - a signaling garne approach", in: R. Pethig, ed., Conflicts and Cooperation in Managing Environmental Resources (Springer, Berlin) 276-332. Höpfinger, E. (1971), "A game-theoretic analysis of an inspection problem", Unpublished manuscript, University of Karlsruhe. Höpfinger, E. (1979), "Dynamic standard setting for carbon dioxide', in: S.J. Brams, A. Schotter and G. Schwödianer, eds., Applied Garne Theory (Physica-Verlag, Würzburg) 373-389. Howson, J.T., Jr. (1972), "Equilibila of polymatrix garnes', Management Science 18:312-318. IAEA (1989), IAEA Safeguards: Statistical Concepts and Techniques, 4th rev. edn. (IAEA, Vienna).
1986
R. Avenhaus et al.
Jaech, J.L. (1973), "Statistical methods in nuclear material control", Technical Information Center, United States Atomic Energy Commission TID-26298, Washiugton, DC. Kanodia, C.S. (1985), "Stochastic and moral hazard", Journal of Accounting Research 23:175-193. Kaplan, R.S. (1973), "Statistical sampling in auditing with auxiliary information estimates", Journal of Accounting Research 11:238-258. Karlin, S. (1959), Mathematical Methods and Theory in Garnes, Programming, and Economics, Vol. II: The Theory of Infinite Garnes (Addison-Wesley, Reading) (Dover reprint 1992). Kilgour, D.M. (1992), "Site selection for on-site inspection in arms control", Arms Control 13:439-462. Kilgour, D.M., N. Okada and A. Nishikori (1988), "Load control regulation of water pollution: An analysis using garne theory", Joumal of Environmental Management 27:179-194. Klages, A. (1968), Spieltheorie und Wirtschaftsprüfung: Anwendung spieltheoretischer Modelle in der Wirtschaftsprüfung. Schriften des Europa-Kollegs Hamburg, Vol. 6 (Ludwig Appel Verlag, Hamburg). Kuhn, H.W. (1963), "Recursive inspection garnes", in: EJ. Anscombe et al., eds., Applications of Statistical Methodology to Arms Control and Disarmament, Final report to the U.S. Arms Control and Disarmament Agency under contract No. ACDA/ST-3 by Mathematica, Part III (Princeton, NJ) 169-181. Landsberger, M., and I. Meilijson (1982), "Incentive generating state dependent penahy system", Joumal of Public Economics 19:333-352. Lehmann, E.L. (1959), Testing Statistical Hypotheses (Wiley, New York). Maschler, M. (1966), "A price leadership method for solving the inspector's non-constant-sum garne", Naval Research Logistics Quarterly 13:11-33. Maschler, M. (1967), "The inspector's non-constant-sum-game: Its dependence on a system of detectors", Naval Research Logistics Quarterly 14:275-290. Mitzrotsky, E. (1993), "Game-theoretical approach to data vefification" (in Hebrew), Master's Thesis, Department of Statistics, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem. O'Neill, B. (1994), "Game theory models of peace and war", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Game Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 29, 995-1053. Piehlmeier, G. (1996), Spieltheoretische Untersuchung von Problemen der Datenverifikation (Kovaß, Hamburg). Reinganum, J.F., and L.L. Wilde (1986), "Equilibrium verification and reporting policies in a model of tax compliance", International Economic Review 27:739-760. Rinderle, K. (1996), Mehrstufige sequentielle Inspektionsspiele mit statistischen Fehlern erster und zweiter Art (Kova~, Hamburg). Rubinstein, A. (1979), "An optimal conviction policy for offenses that may have been committed by accident", in: S.J. Brams, A. Schotter and G. Schwödiauer, eds., Applied Garne Theory (Physica-Verlag, Würzburg) 373-389. Ruckle, W.H. (1992), 'q'he upper risk of an inspection agreement", Operations Research 40: 877-884. Russell, G.S. (1990), "Garne models for structuring monitoring and enforcement systems", Natural Resource Modeling 4:143-173. Saaty, T.L. (1968), Mathematical Models of Arms Control and Disarmament: Application of Mathematical Strnctures in Politics (Wiley, New York). Sakaguchi, M. (1977), "A sequential allocation garne for targets with varying values", Journal of the Operations Research Society of Japan 20:182-193. Sakaguchi, M. (1994), "A seqnential game of multi-opportunity infiltration", Mathematica Japonicae 39:157166. Schleicher, H. (1971), "A recursive garne for detecting tax law violations", Economies et Sociétés 5:14211440. Thomas, M.U., and Y. Nisgav (1976), "An infiltration garne with time dependent payoff", Naval Research Logistics Quarterly 23:297-302. von Stackelberg, H. (1934), Marktform und Gleichgewicht (Springer, Berlin). von Stengel, B. (1991), "Recursive inspection garnes", Technical Report S-9106, Universität der Bundeswehr München.
Ch. 51:
Inspection Garnes
1987
Weissing, E, and E. Ostrom (1991), "Irrigation institutions and the garnes irrigators play: Rule enforcement without guards", in: R. Selten, ed., Garne Equilibrium Models II (Springer, Berlin). Wölling, A. (2000), "Das Führerschaftsprinzip bei Inspektionsspielen", Universität der Bundeswehr München.
Chapter 52
ECONOMIC HISTORY AND GAME THEORY AVNER GREW*
Department~Economic~ S t a ß ~ Unive~i~ Stanford, CA, USA
Contents
1. Introduction 2. Bringing game theory and econornic history together 3. Game-theoretical analyses in economic history 3.1. The early years: Employing general game-theoretical insights 3.2. Coming to maturity: Explicit models 3.2.1. Exchange and contract enforcement in the absence of a legal system 3.2.2. The stare: Emergence, nature, and function 3.2.3. Within states 3.2.4. Between states 3.2.5. Culture, institutions, and endogenous institutional dynamics 3.3. Conclusions
References
1991 1992 1996 1996 1999 1999 2006 2009 2014 2016 2019 2021
*The research for this paper was supported by National Science Foundation Grants SES-9223974 and SBR9602038. I am thankful to the editors, Professor Jacob Metzer, and an anonymous referee for very useful comments. First draft of this paper was written in 1996.
Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
1990
A. Greif
Abstract This paper surveys the small, yet growing, literature that uses garne theory for economic history analysis. It elaborates on the promise and challenge of applying garne theory to economic history and presents the approaches taken in conducting such an application. Most of the essay, however, is devoted to studies in economic history that use game theory as their main analytical framework. Studies are presented in a way that highlights the fange of potential topics in economic history that can be and have been enriched by a game-theoretical analysis.
Keywords economic history, institutions JEL classification: C7, NO
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Garne Theory
1991
1. Introduction Since the rise of cliometrics in the mid-60s, the main theoretical framework used by economic historians has been neo-classical theory. It is a powerful tool for examining non-strategic situations in which interactions are conducted within markets or shaped by them.1 Garne theory enables the analysis to go further by providing economic history with a theoretical framework suitable for analyzing strategic, economic, social, and political situations. Among such strategic situations are: economic exchange in which the number of participants is relatively small, political relationships within and between states, decision-making within regulatory and other governmental bodies, exchange in the absence of impartial, third-party enforcement, and intra-organizational relations. Such situations prevail even in modern market economies and were probably even more prevalent in pre-modern economies. Furthermore, game-theoretic insights have provided support to the economic historians' long-held position that history matters. While neo-classical economics asserts that economies identical in their endowment, preferences, and technology will reach the same equilibrium, economic historians have long held that the historical experience of various economies indicates the limitations of this assertion. Garne theory augmented this position by providing a theoretical framework whose insights reveal a role for history in economic systems. Garne theory points, for example, to the potential sensitivity of outcomes to rules and hence to institutions, the possibility of multiple equilibria and hence the potential for distinct trajectories of instimtional and economic changes, the crucial role of expectations and beliefs and hence the potential importance of the historical actors, and the possible role of evolutionary processes and change in equilibrium selection. In short, garne theory indicates that within the framework of strategic rationality, different historical trajectories are possible in situations identical in terms of their endowment, preferences, and technology. 2 Applying game theory to economic history can also potentially enrich game theory. History contains unique and, at times, detailed information regarding behavior in strategic situations, and thus it provides another laboratory in which to examine the relevance of the game-theoretic approach and its insights into positive economic analysis. Furthermore, historical analyses guided by garne theory are likely to reveal theoretical issues that, if addressed, would contribute to the development of garne theory and its ability to advance economic analysis. This essay surveys the small, yet growing, literature that employs garne theory in economic history. Section 2 briefty elaborates on the promise and challenge of applying garne theory to economic history and presents the approaches taken in conducting such applications. Section 3 presents studies in economic history that either utilize 1 On the Cliometric Revolution, see Williamson (1994). Hartwell(1973) surveysthe methodologicaldevelopments in economichistory. For the many contributions generatedby the neo-classicalline of research in economic history, see McCloskey(1976). For recent discussion, see the session on "Cliometrics after Forty Years" in the AER 1997 (May). I further elaborateon these issues in Greif (1997a, 1998a). 2 See Greif (1994a) for such a comparativegame-theoreticanalysisof two late medievaleconomies.
1992
A. Greif
game theory as their main analytical framework or examine the empirical relevance of game-theoretical insights. This section contains two sub-sections. The first discusses economic history studies that use only general game-theoretical insights to guide the analysis. The second discusses economic history studies that use a context-specific game-theoretic model as their main theoretical framework. In either sub-section the studies are presented according to the issues they examine in economic history. Clearly, it is impossible to elaborate on a myriad of papers in such a short essay, so a brief description of each paper is provided with only a few described in detail. Their (subjective) selection is influenced by their relative complexity, methodological contribution, or representativeness. Finally, since the goal of this essay is to survey applications of game-theoretical analysis to economic history, it does not systematically evaluate their arguments (although references to published comments on papers are provided).
2. Bringing game theory and economic history together Economic history can benefit greatly from a theory enabling empirical analysis of strategic situations since issues central to economic history are inherently strategic. For example, economic history has always been concerned with the origin, impact, and path dependence of non-market economic, social, political, and legal institutions. 3 Indeed, this concern with non-market institutions logically follows from Adam Smith's legacy and the neo-classical economics which often identify the rise of the modern economic system with the expansion of the market system. This view implies, however, that an analysis of non-market situations is required to understand past economies, their functioning, and why some of them, but not others, transformed into market economies. Hence, a theoretical framework of strategic, non-market situations can expand our comprehension of issues central to economic history. The ability of game theory - the existing theoretical framework for analyzing strategic situations to advance an empirical and historical study - should be judged empirically. Yet, certain conclusions of game-theoretical analysis make its application to economic history both challenging and promising. Game theory indicates that outcomes in strategic situations are potentially sensitive to details, that various equilibrium concepts are plausible, and (given an equilibrium concept) multiple equilibria may exist. Thus, applying game theory to economic history may be challenging since economic history is, first and foremost, an empirical field and economic historians are trying to understand what has actually transpired, why it transpired, and to what effect. One may argue that a theoretical analysis, whose conclusions regarding outcomes are non-robust 3 For a discussion of the methodological differences between economic history and economics, see Backhouse (1985, pp. 216-221). For institutional studies during the nineteenth century in the German and English Historical Schools, see, for example, Weber (1987 [1927]); Cunningham (1882). On the general theory of path dependence see David (1988, 1992). See also Footnote 1.
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Garne Theory
1993
and empirically inconclusive (in the sense that many outcomes are consistent with the theory), provides an inappropriate foundation for an empirical study. Interestingly, however, the game-theoretical conclusions regarding non-robustness and inconclusiveness are in accordance with the conceptual foundations of historical analysis - namely, that outcomes depend on the details of the historical context, that "economic actors" can potentially matter, and that the non-economic aspects of the historical context, such as religious precedents or even chance, can influence economic outcomes. Game theory provides economic history with an explicit theoretical framework that does not lead to the ahistorical conclusion that the same preferences, technology, and endowments lead to a unique economic outcome in all historical episodes. The conclusions of game-theoretical analysis that challenge its empirical applicability make it a particularly promising theory for historical analysis since it can be used for analyzing strategic situations in a way that is sensitive to, and reveals the importance of, their historical dimensions. Studies in economic history that use garne theory have differed in their responses to the challenge and promise presented by the potential non-robustness and inconclusiveness of game-theoretical analysis. They all began with a historical study aimed at formulating the relevant issue to be examined. They used general game-theoretical insights - such as the possibility of coordination failure, the importance of credible commitment, or the problem of cooperation in a multi-person prisoners' garne situation - to "frame" the analysis, that is to say, they explicitly specify the issues needing to be addressed, provide an organizing scheme for the historical evidence, or highlight the logic behind the historical evidence. 4 Some studies went so far as to undertake a game-theoretic analysis of various issues and they responded to the non-robustness and inconclusiveness problems in one of two (not mutually exclusive) ways. Some studies responded to the non-robustness and inconclusiveness by basing the historical analysis only on those game-theoretic insights that are conclusive and robust. 5 The empirical investigation was thus guided by generic insights applicable in situations with such features. An example of such general insights would be that bargaining in the presence of asymmetric information can lead to negotiation failure. Reliance on general insights comes at the cost of limiting the ability to empirically substantiate a hypothesis. Without an explicit model it is difficult to enhance confidence in an argument by confi'onting the details of the historical episode with the details of the theoretical argument and its implications. In particular, without specifying the strategies employed by the players, it is difficult to empirically substantiate the analysis. Yet, the potential benefit of relying on general insights is the ability to discuss important situations without being constrained by the ability to explicitly mode1 them.
4 See, for example, North [(1981), Chapter 3] and Kantor (1991). "The power of garne theory - and it's the way I've used it - is that it makes you s~ucture the argument in formal terms, in precise t e r m s . . . " [North (1993), p. 27]. 5 For a somewhat similar approach in the Industrial Organization literature, see Sutton (1992).
1994
A. Greif
Other studies found it useful to confront non-robustness and inconclusiveness differently. A detailed empirical study of the historical episode under consideration was conducted and it provided the foundation for an interactive process of theoretical and historical examination aimed at formulaUng a context-specific model that captured an essence of the relevant strategic situation. 6 This interactive historical and theoretical analysis sufficiently constrained the model's specification, basing it on assumptions in which confidence can be gained independently from their predictive power, and ensured that the analysis did not impose the researcher's perception of a situation on the historical actors. 7 The resulting context-specific model provided the foundation for a game-theoretical analysis of the situation whose predictions could be compared with the historical evidence. At the same time, the model extended the examination of the extent to which its main conclusions are robust with respect to assumptions whose appropriateness is historically questionable. In short, these studies confronted non-robustness and inconclusiveness by utilizing a context-specific model. Such models enhance "general insight" analysis by generating falsifiable predictions, as well as the ability to check robustness and to gain a deeper understanding of the issues under consideration. Yet, despite these advantages, analysis based on a context-specific model is restricted to cases where such models can be formulated. Economic history studies utilizing a game-theoretic, context-specific model mostly utilized two basic equilibrium concepts: Nash equilibrium and sub-game perfect equilibrium. These two concepts have the advantage of including most other equilibrium concepts as special cases, as well as having intuitive, common-sense interpretations. 8 Using these inclusive equilibrium concepts implies, however, that multiple equilibria are more likely to exist and the analysis is more likely to be inconclusive. In other words, it amplifies the two problems for empirical historical analysis associated with inconclusiveness, namely, identification and selection. Studies have differed in their responses to these problems. Some studies, whose aim was to understand the logic beyond a particular behavior, considered the analysis complete when they revealed the existence of an equilibrium corresponding to that particular behavior. They did not aspire to substantiate that the behavior and expected behavior associated with that particular equilibrium were those that prevailed in the historical episode under consideration. If they attempted to account for cooperation, for example, they were satisfied with arguing that an equilibrium entailing cooperation existed. By and large, they neither tried to substantiate that this particular equilibrium - rather than another one entailing cooperation - indeed prevailed,
6 Clearly, the essence of the issue that is captnred should be both important and orthogonal to other relevant issues. 7 For example, the King of England, Edward the First, noted in 1283 that insufficient protectiort to allen merchants' property rights deterred them fi'om coming to trade. His remark enhances the confidence in the relevance of a model in which commitment to alien traders' property rights can foster their trade [Greif et al. (1994)]. 8 For an introduction to these concepts, see, for example, Fudenberg and Tirole (1991) or Rasmusen (1994).
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Garne Theory
1995
nor did they examine how this equilibrium was selected or compare their analysis with a possible non-strategic account for cooperation. In other studies the need to identify a particular strategy was avoided by concentrating on the analysis of the set of equilibria. 9 This approach was adopted particularly in studies that examined the impact of changes in the rules of the garne on outcomes.l° In other cases when the argument revolved around the empirical relevance of a particular strategy, the problem of identification was confronted by employing direct and indirect evidence to verify the use of this particular strategy (or some subset of the possible equilibrium strategies with particular features). Direct evidence of the historical relevance of a particular strategy is explicit documentary accounts reflecting the strategies that were used, or were intended to be used, by the decision-makers. 11 Such explicit documentary accounts are found in such diverse historical sources as business correspondence, private letters, legal procedures, the constitutions of guilds, the charters of firms, and records of public speeches. Clearly, statements about intended courses of action can be just talk, but indirect evidence can enhance confidence in the empirical relevance of a particular strategy. Indirect evidence is an empirical confirmation of predictions generated under the assumption that a particular strategy was employed. The predictions generated by various economic history studies utilizing garne theory cover a wide range of variables, such as price movements, contractual forms, dynamics of wealth distribution, exits, entries, price, and various responses to exogenous changes. In some studies it was possible to test these predictions econometrically but in others, because of the nature of their predictions, such tests could not be performed. 12 For example, the analysis of labor negotiation presented in Treble (1990), as discussed below, predicts that labor disputes should be a function of bargaining procedures. Because different procedures were in effect in the historical episode under consideration, this prediction could have been examined econometrically. The analysis in Greif (1989), which is also discussed below, predicts that traders' social structures should be a function of the strategy merchants used to punish an overseas agent who cheated a merchant. The analysis predicts in particular thät a strategy of collective punishment would lead to a horizontal social structure in which traders would serve as both merchants and agents. While this prediction can be objectively verified, it cannot be econometrically tested. The advantage of confirming predictions based on an econometric test is that this test provides a significance level. Such analysis, nevertheless, is restricted only to issues that generate econometrically testable predictions. But orte can increase the confidence in a hypothesis also by comparing its predictions - without using econometrics and hence having a significance level - with predictions generated under alternative hypotheses.
9 See, for example, Greif et al. (1994), particularly Proposition 1. 10 E.g., Milgrom et al. (1990); Greif et al. (1994). 11 For an example of the extensive use of such evidence, see Greif (1989). 12 For examples of econometric analyses see Porter (1983); Levenstein (1994). For non-econometric analyses see Greif (1989, 1993, 1994a); Rosenthal (1992).
1996
A. Greif
So far, economic history has studied the problem of equilibrium selection entailed by multiple equilibria in a way that has been influenced more by the conceptual foundations of historical analysis rather than by game-theoretical literature dealing with refinements or evolutionary game theory. Most authors accounted for the selection of a particular equilibrium by invoking aspects of the historical context. One paper cited the public commitment of Winston Churchill to a particular strategy as being fundamental in the selection of a particular equilibrium.13 Other papers pointed out that factors outside the game itself had influenced equilibrium selection. Among these were immigration that provided information networks, political changes that determined the initial set of players, and focal points provided by religious and social attitudes. 14 Some authors, particularly those interested in comparing two historical episodes, theoretically identified the range of parameters or variables that were required for one particular equilibrium to prevail rather than another. This theoretical prediction was compared with the empirical evidence regarding these variables in the historical episodes under consideration. 15
3. Game-theoretical analyses in economic history This section presents studies in economic history that use garne theory. In line with the above discussion of the methodology employed by such studies, they are grouped according to those that use "generic insights" (Section 3.1) and those that use "contextspecific models" (Section 3.2). In both sub-sections the presentation is organized by historical topics but it implicitly suggests the potential benefits of economic history studies using game theory to further empirical evaluation and to extend various aspects of the theory itself. I will return to this issue later in the section. Space limitation precludes a detailed examination of all the papers in either section. But to illustrate the methodological differences between the papers in the two sub-sections, I will provide a somewhat longer presentation of a study [Greif (1989, 1993, 1994a)] that uses a context-specific model.
3.1. The early years: Employing general game-theoretical insights The first economic history papers that used general insights from garne theory were published in the early 1980s. They examined such topics as regulations, market structure, and property-rights protection. As for their game-theoretic method, they used nested games, a situation in which the rules of one garne are the equilibrium outcome of another game. Furthermore, they provided empirical evidence of problems encountered
13 Maurer (1992). 14 E.g., Greif(1994a). 15 E.g., Rosenthal (1992); Greif (1994a); Baliga and Polak (1995).
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Game Theory
1997
in bargaining under incomplete information and suggested that off-the-path-of-play expected behavior might indeed influence economic outcomes, as formalized in the notion of sub-game-perfect equilibrium. R e g u l a t i o n s : Economic historians have for a long time emphasized the importance of the historical development of regulatory agencies and regulations in the US. Davis and North (1971), for example, argued that regulations were a welfare-enhancing process of institutional changes driven by the potential profit from regulating the economy. In contrast, using a game-theoretical analysis of endogenous regulations, Reiter and Hughes (1981) have argued that the process was not necessarily welfare-enhancing. In their formulation, economic agents and regulators are involved in a non-cooperative dynamic garne with asymmetric information in which the regulators pursue their own agendas. To advance their agendas, they are also involved in a cooperative garne with political agents in which they try to influence the political process through which the next period's legal and budgetary framework of the non-cooperative game is determined. While Reiter and Hughes did not attempt to explicitly solve the model, it provided them with a paradigm to discuss the emergence of the "modern regulated economy" as reflecting redistributive considerations, efficiency-enhancing motives, and political factors. Interestingly, around the same time David (1982) combined cooperative and noncooperative garne theory in the opposite direction to examine "regulations" associated with the feudal system. His analysis used the Nash bargaining solution to examine transfers from peasants to lords of the manor. This analysis was incorporated within a broader garne in which the feudal system itself reflects an equilibrium of the repeated garne between peasants and a coalition of lords. Eichengreen (1996) used garne theory to examine the regulations that, according to his interpretation, were crucial to Europe's rapid post-World War II economic growth. The basic argument is inspired by the concept of sub-game perfection. Following the war there was a very high return on capital investment, but inducing investment required that investors were assured that e x p o s t , after they had made a sunk investment, their workers would not hold them up and reap all the gains. At the same time, for workers not to find it optimal to act in this way they had to be assured that in the long run they would gain a share in the implied economic growth. Credible commitment by workers and investors alike was made through state intervention. The state acted as a third-party enforcer of labor relationship regulations and social welfare programs that ensured a sufficiently high rate of return to investors and workers alike. M a r k e t structure: A market's structure is fundamental in determining an industry's conduct and performance. Traditionally, economic historians have not considered that the structure of a market can be influenced by strategic interactions. Yet Carlos and Hoffman (1986) argued that strategic considerations determined the structure of the fur industry in North America during the early nineteenth century. The two companies that operated in this industry from 1804 to 1821 (the Northwest Company and the Hudson's Bay Company) could have benefited from collusion or merger and there was no antitrust legislation to hinder either. Yet, both companies were engaged in an intense conflict that led to a depletion of the animal stock. Carlos and Hoffman argued that the persistence of
1998
A. Greif
this market structure reflects the difficulties of bargaining with incomplete information. General insights from bargaining models with incomplete information indicate that it is possible to fail to reach an expost efficient agreement because each side attempts to misrepresent its type, players are likely to bargain over distributive mechanisms rather than allocations, and disagreement may result from a player's cornmitment to a tough strategy. Indeed, although the correspondence between the companies indicates that both recognized the gains from cooperation, each was trying to mislead the other. Furthermore, the two companies did not bargain over the allocation of joint profits but tried to reach a merger. After failing to merge, they bargained over a distribution of the territory that each would exploit as a monopolist. Also, negotiations prior to 1821 broke down partially because of the Hudson's Bay Company's commitment to a particular, very demanding strategy. The impetus for their final merger was the intervention of the government following a period of intense and ruinous competition. Hence, Carlos and Hoffman's analysis indicates that strategic considerations influenced the market's structure and provided "empirical evidence on the problems encountered in bargaining under incomplete information" (p. 968). 16 Security ofproperty rights: Financing the government by issuing public debt is one of the peculiar features of the pre-modern European economy. Arguably, this type of financing facilitated the rise of security markets [e.g., Neal (1990)] and provided the foundation for the modern welfare state. Yet, for a pre-modern ruler to gain access to credit he had to be able to commit to repay it despite the fact that he stood, roughly speaking, above the law. How could rulers commit to repay their debts? Why in some historical episodes did rulers renege on their obligations and in others respect them? Clearly, in a one-shot garne between a ruler (who can request a loan and renege after receiving it) and a potential lender (who can decide whether or not to make a loan), the only sub-game perfect equilibrium entails no lending. Veitch (1986) has argued, based on Telser's (1980) idea of self-enforcing agreements, that repetition and potential collective retaliation by lenders enlarged the equilibrium set and enabled rulers to commit to repay their debts, and hence to borrow. He has noted that in medieval Europe rulers often borrowed from members of a particular group, such as Jews, Templars, or the Italians, while debt repudiation was often carried out against the group as a whole rather than against particular members. 17 Veitch argued that this indicates that repudiation was curtailed by the threat of collective retaliation by the group. The threat was credible due to the ethnic, moral, or political relations among the lenders. The threat was effective as long as the ruler did not have any alternative group to borrow from, implying that the emergence of an alternative group would lead to
16 The analysis is based on Myerson's (1984a, 1984b) work on a generalized Nash bargaining solution and Crawford's (1982a) model in which it is costly (for exogenousreasons) to change a strategy after committing to it. As Carlos and Hoffman (1988) later recognize in their response to Nye (1988), subsequent theoretical developments provided models bettet suited to capturing the essence of the historical situation. 17 Or against a particular sub-groupsuch as an Italian company.
Ch. 52: EconomicHistory and GarneTheory
1999
repudiation against the previous group, as indeed was orten the case.18 Similarly, Root (1989) argued that during the 17th and 18th centuries corporate bodies, such as villäge communities, provincial estates, and guilds, enabled the King of France to commit to pay debts. They increased the opportunity cost of a breach, thereby restraining the king's ability to default and enabling hirn to borrow. Indeed, the rise of corporate bodies that loaned to the king in the eighteenth century is associated with a lower interest and bankruptcy rate relative to the seventeenth century. North and Weingast (1989) and Weingast (1995) N a h e r expanded the study of the relations between credible commitment, property-rights security, and political power. If indeed security of property rights is a key to economic growth (as conjectured by North and Thomas (1973)), how was such security achieved in past societies governed by kings with military power superior to that of their subjects? North and Weingast argued that the Glorious Revolution of 1688 enabled the King of England to commit to such security, thereby providing institutional foundations for growth. During this revolution and the years of civil war prior to it, the Parliament established its ability and willingness to revolt against a king who abused property rights. This enabled the king to commit to the property rights of bis subjects. Furthermore, to enhance the credibility of this threat and to limit the king's ability to renege, various measures were taken. The king's rights were clearly specified to foster coordination among members of the Parliament regarding which of the king's actions should trigger a reaction. The Parliament gained control over taxation and revenue allocation, an independent judiciary was established, and the king's prerogatives were curtailed. In support of the view that the Glorious Revolution enhanced property-rights security, North and Weingast pointed to the rise, during the eighteenth century, in sovereign debt and in the number and value of securities traded in England's private and public capital markets and the general decline in interest rates.19 3.2. Coming to maturity: Explicit models 3.2.1. Exchange and contract enforcement in the absence of a legal system Neo-classical economics has long emphasized that an impartial legal system fosters exchange by providing contract enforcement. Yet even in contemporary developed and
18 This analysis is insightful and novel but it is incomplete. For example, it is mistaken in arguing that a selfenforcing agreementamongthe Italian companiesis a necessary conditionfor a sub-gameperfect equilibrium in which the ruler does not repudiate. 19 Carmthers (1990) criticized the claim that placing limits on the king enabled England to borrow, while Clark (1995) cast doubts on the claim that property rights were insecure prior to 1688. He examined the rate of return on private debt and land, and the price of land from 1540 to 1800, and was unable to detect any impact from the Glorious Revolution. Weingast (1995) applied the model of Greif et al. (1994) to fttrther examine how constitutional changes during the Glorious Revolution enhanced the king's ability to borrowby increasing his ability to commit.
2000
A. Gre~
developing economies, rauch exchange is conducted without relying on contract enforcement provided by the state. (See further discussion in Greif (1997b).) This phenomenon has been even more prevalent in past economies where, in many cases, there was no state that could provide an impartial legal system. Yet, the institutional foundations of exchange in past societies were not studied in economic history before the introduction of garne theory because there was no appropriate theoretical framework. Some of the first economic history papers that utilized context-specific, explicit models were those that employed symmetric and asymmetric information repeated garne models to examine institutions that provided informal contract enforcement in various historical episodes. They provided such enforcement by linking past conduct and future economic reward. Although such games usually have multiple equilibria and the equilibrium set is sensitive to their details, they were found to facilitate ernpirical examination when the analysis concentrated on the equilibrium set, and when the historical records were rich enough to constrain the model and enable identification of the equilibrium that prevailed. Apart from indicating the empirical relevance of repeated garnes (with perfect or imperfect monitoring), these studies show that game-theoretical analysis can highlight diverse aspects of a society, such as the inter-relations between economic institutions and social structures. They indicate how third-party enforcement can be made credible even in the absence of complete information, or a strategy that punishes someone who fails to punish a deviator. Finally, the studies indicate that it is misleading to view contract enforcement based on formal organizations and on repeated interaction as substitutes, since formal organizations may be required for the long hand of the future to sustain cooperation. "Coalitions" and informal contract enforcement: Much of the spectacular European growth from the eleventh to the fourteenth centuries is attributed to the Commercial Revolution - the resurgence of Mediterranean and European long-distance trade. The actions and explicit statements of contemporaries indicate the important role played by overseas agents who managed the merchants' capital abroad. Operating through agents, however, required overcoming a commitment problem since agents who had control over others' capital could act opportnnistically. To establish an efficient agency relationship, the agent had to commit ex ante to be honest ex post and not to embezzle the merchant's capital that was under his control (in the form of money, goods, and expensive packing materials). It is tempting to conclude, as Benson (1989) has argued, that an agent's concern about his reputation - namely, his concern about bis ability to trade in the future - perrnitted such a commitment. Yet, this argument is unsatisfactory since it presents an incomplete theoretical analysis and, worse, since it implicitly claims that it is enough to comprehend a historical situation by examining only a theoretical possibility without examining any empirical evidence. Comprehending if and how the merchant-agent commitment problem was mitigated in a particular time and place requires detailed empirical research and a context-specific theoretical analysis. A satisfactory empirical and theoretical analysis should address at least the following issues. If repetition enabled cooperation, should the model be of infinite or finite horizon? If an infinitely repeated garne is appropriate, how was the unraveling problem
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Garne Theory
2001
mitigated (that is, why wouldn't an agent cheat in his old age)? Should the model be an incomplete-information model? Should it include a legal system? How was information acquired and transmitted? Should the set of traders and agents be considered exogenous? Could an agent begin operating as a merchant with goods he had embezzled? Who was to retaliate if an agent embezzled goods? Why was the threat of retaliation credible? What were the efficiency implications of the particular way in which the merchant-agent commitment problem was alleviated? Why did this particular way emerge? Greif (1989, 1993, 1994a) examined these and related questions with respect to the Jewish Maghribi traders who operated during the eleventh century in the Muslim Mediterranean. The historical and theoretical evidence indicates that agency relations were not governed by the legal system and that the appropriate model is an infinitely repeated garne with complete information. (Greif (1993) discusses why an incompleteinformation model was ruled out and below I discuss how the unraveling problem was mitigated.) Specifically, it argues for the relevance of an efficiency-wage model with two particularly important features: matching is not completely random but is conditioned on the information available to the merchants, and sometimes a merchant has to cease operating through an hortest agent. 2° A model incorporating these two features shows that a (sub-game perfect) equilibrium exists in which each merchant employs an agent from a particular sub-set of the potential agents and all merchants cease operating through any agent who ever cheated. This collective punishment is self-enforcing since the value of future relations with all the merchants keeps an agent hortest. An agent who
20 Specifically, the model is that of a One-Sided Prisoner's Dilemma game (OSPD) with perfect and complete information. There are M merchants and A agents in the economy, and it is assumed that M < A. Players live an infinite number of periods, agents have a time discount factor/3, and an unemployed agent receives a per-period reservation utility of q~u ~> 0. In each period, an agent can be hired by ordy one merchant and a merchant can employ only one agent. Matching is random, but a merchant can restrict the matching to a sub-set of the unemployed agents that contains the agents who, according to the information available to the merchant, have previously taken particular sequences of actions. (The following assumes that the probability of re-matching with the same agent equals zero for all practical considerations.) A merchant who does not hire an agent receives a payoff of x > 0. A merchant who hires an agent decides what wage (W ~>0) to offer the agent. An employed agent can decide whether to be honest or to cheat. If he is honest, the merchant's payoff is y - W, and the agent's payoff is W. Hence the gross gain from cooperation is •, and it is assurned that cooperation is efficient, y > z + ~bu. The merchant's wage offer is assumed credible, since in reality the agent held the goods and could determine the ex post allocation of gains. For that reason, if the agent cheats, the merchant's payoff is 0 and the agent's payoff is « > en- Finally, a merchant prefers receiving tc to being cheated or paying W = ee, that is, x > V - ct. After the allocation of the payoffs, each merchant can decide whether to terminate his relations with his agent or not. There is a probability o', however, that a merchant will be forced to terminate agency relations and this assumption captures merchants' limited ability to commit to future employment due to the need to shift commercial operations over places and goods and the high uncertainty of commerce and life during that period. For a similar reason, the merchants are assumed to be unable to condition wages on past conduct (indeed, merchants in neither group did so). Hence, attention is restricted to an equilibrium in which wages are constant over time. (For an efficiency wage model in which this result is derived endogenously, see MacLeod and Malcomson (1989). Their approach can be used for this analysis as weil but is omitted to preserve simplicity.)
2002
A. Greif
has cheated in the past and thus is not expected to be hired by merchants will not lose this value if caught cheating again. Thus, if a merchant nevertheless hires such an agent, the merchant has to pay a higher (efficiency) wage to keep the agent hortest (relative to an agent who did not cheat in the past). Each merchant is thus induced to hire only hortest agents - agents who are expected to be hired by others. Acquiring and transmitting information during the late medieval period was costly, and hence the model should incorporate a merchant's decision to acquire information. Since merchants could gather information by forming an information-sharing network, suppose that each merchant can either "Invest" or "Not Invest" in "getting attached" to such a network before the game begins, and that his action is common knowledge. Investing entails a cost at each period in return for which the merchant learns the private histories of all the merchants who also invested; otherwise, he knows only his own history. Under the collectivist equilibrium, history has value and thus merchants are motivated to invest even though cheating does not occur on the equilibrium path. The effectiveness of a collective punishment in inducing efficiency-enhancing agency relationships is undermined if an agent who cheated is not restricted from using the capital he embezzled as profitably as the merchant he cheated. If an agent can use the capital he embezzled as profitably as the merchant by becoming a merchant himself and hiring an agent, his lifetime expected utility is higher following cheating relative to a situation in which he cannot. This implies that to induce honesty, a merchant has to pay a higher wage to his agent. As a matter of fact, this wage has to be so high that it would be better for an individual to be an agent rather than a merchant. Agents would have to be paid more than half of the return on each business venture. The need to pay such a high wage, in turn, increases the set of situations in which merchants would not initiate efficiency-enhancing agency relationships, finding them to be unprofitable. However, there is no historical evidence that agents were restricted exogenously from investing capital in trade. Such a restriction can be generated endogenously, however, under collective punishment. In particular, an agent who himself also acts as a merchant (and invests his capital through agents) can be endogenously deterred from embezzling under collective punishment (even when his share in a business venture is less than that of a merchant). When an agent also acts as a merchant, a strategy specifying non-punishment of agents who cheated a merchant who had cheated while acting as an agent is both self-enforcing and further reduces the agent's gain from cheating. It potentially enables hiring agents despite their ability to invest the capital they embezzled in trade. When agency relations are governed by a "coalition" - by a group of merchants using the above strategy with respect to a particular group of agents - the collective punishment enables the employment of agents even when a specific merchant and agent are not expected to interact again. The gains from cooperation within the coalition (compared to hiring agents based on bilateral punishment), and the expectations concerning future hiring mnong the coalition's members, ensure the coalition's "closeness". Coalition members are motivated to hire and to be hired only by other members, while non-
Ch. 52: Economic History and Garne Theory
2003
members are discouraged from hiring the coalition's members. 21 Similarly, since mernbership in the coalition is valuable, an overlapping generations version of the model in which sons inherit their fathers' membership and support them in their old age, shows how the unraveling problem can be avoided. Holding a son liable for his father's actions can motivate a father to be honest even in his old age. The above theoretical discussion provides sorne of the conditions for and implications of governing agency relations by coalitions. Some of these implications are distinct from those generated by a bilateral efficiency-wage rnodel [Shapiro and Stiglitz (1984)] or a model of incornplete information about agents' types. For example, within the coalition agency relations are likely to be flexible - rnerchants shift among agents and hire agents even for a short time in cases of need. Merchants also prefer hiring other merchants as their agents, perhaps through forms of business associations that require agents' capital investments. Further, rnernbers of the coalition are likely to be segregated from other merchants in the sense that they will not establish agency relations outside the coalition even if these relations - ignoring agency cost - are more profitable. Similarly, the sons of coalition rnernbers are likely to join the coalition. Indeed, the geniza documents that reflect the operation of the Maghribis reveal the above conditions for, and implications of, governing agency relations by a coalition. They reflect a reciprocity based on a social and commercial information network with very flexible and non-bilateral agency relations. There was no merchant or agent "class" among the Maghribis while merchants hired other merchants as their agents and utilized forms of business associations that required agents' investments. Furtherrnore, the Maghribis did not establish agency relations with other (Jewish or non-Jewish) traders even when these relations were considered by thern to be very profitable. To begin operating in a new trade center, some Maghribis immigrated to this center and began providing agency relations. Finally, traders' sons indeed supported their fathers in their old age and inherited rnernbership in the coalition and family members were held morally (but not legally) responsible for each other. Notably, these observed features among the Maghribis did not prevail among the Italian traders who operated (particularly from the twelfth century) in the same area as the Maghribis, trading in the same goods, and using comparable naval technology. Bilateral, rather than collective, punishment was the norm that prevailed among Italian traders. (See further discussion below.) In addition to this indirect evidence for the governance of agency relations arnong the Maghribis by a coalition, the geniza contains direct evidence on various aspects of the coalition. Explicit statements reflect the expectations for a rnultilateral punishment, the economic nature of the expected punishment, the linkage between past conduct and fumre employment, the interest that all coalition members took in the relations between a specific agent and merchant, and so forth. Further, the geniza reveals the existence of a set of cultural rules of behavior that alleviated the need for comprehensive agency contracts and coordinated responses by indicating what constituted "cheating". 21 See, in particular, Greif(1994a).
2004
A. Greif
The factors leading to the selection of this particular strategy are also reflected in the historical records, which suggest that multilateral punishment prevailed among the Maghribis because of a social process and cultural traits. The Maghribis were descendants of Jewish traders who left the increasingly politically insecure surroundings of Baghdad and emigrated to North Africa during the tenth century. Arguably, this emigration process, as well as their cultural background which emphasized collective responsibility, provided them with an initial social network for information transmission and made the collective punishment strategy a focal point. This particular social process and cultural background led to the governance of agency relations by a coalition, while the economic incentives generated by the coalition strengthened the Maghribis' distinct social identity. Indeed, the Maghribis retained their separate identity within the Jewish population until they were forced, for political reasons, to cease trading. This interrelation between social identity and the economic institution that govemed agency relations suggests that the Maghribi traders' coalition did not necessarily have an efficient size. But because expectations regarding future employment and collective punishment were conditional on a particular ascribed social identity, there was no mechanism for the coalition to adjnst to its economically optimal size. Clay (1997) studied the informal contract enforcement institution that prevailed among long-distance American traders in Mexican California. Her evidence suggests that, in contrast to the situation among the Maghribis, the traders did not sever all their relations with an agent who cheated any of them. To understand this difference, Clay noted that an agent among these traders had a monopoly over credit transactions with members of a particular Mexican community. Since contract enforcement within each community was based on informal social sanctions, in order to sell on credit a trader had to settle in a community, marry locally, raise his children as Catholics, and speak Spanish at home. Furthermore, the small size of the Mexican communities implied that it was profitable for only one retailer to integrate in this way. Clay incorporated this feature in an infinitely repeated garne with imperfect monitoring, and found that the strategy of permanent and complete punishment of a trader who cheated in agency relations would have been Pareto-inferior. Such a strategy barred all the traders from operating in the community where the cheater had a monopoly over contract enforcement. A strategy entailing a partial boycott for a limited time following a first instance of cheating Pareto-dominates the complete boycott strategy. The boycott is partial in the sense that it does not preclude transactions requiring the use of the cheater's local enforcement ability. A complete boycott follows only after an act of cheating during a boycott. Direct and indirect evidence indicates that such a strategy was utilized by the traders. Hence, an environment different from that of the Maghribis led to a different Pareto-superior strategy. Contract enforcement among "anonymous" individuals: Two studies examined contract enforcement over time and space among "anonymous" individuals. 22 Such contract 22 More accurately,the exchange modeled in this line of research is "impersonal".See discussion in Greif (2000a).
Ch. 52:
Economic Histoty and Garne Theory
2005
enforcement over time was required at the Champagne Fairs in which, during the twelfth and the thirteenth centuries, much of the trade between northern and southern Europe was conducted. Milgrom, North and Weingast (1990) argued that in the large community of merchants who frequented the fairs, a reputation mechanism could not enable traders to commit to respect their obligations since such a large community lacked the social network required to make past actions known to all. Furthermore, the fairs' court could not directly impose its decision on traders after they left the fairs. Milgrom, North and Weingast suggested that a Law Merchant system, in which a court supplements a multilateral reputation mechanism, can ensure contract enforceability in such cases. Suppose that each pair of traders is matched only once and each trader knows only his own experience. Further assume that the court is capable only of verifying past actions and keeping records of traders who cheated in the past. Acquiring information and appealing to the court is costly for each merchant. Despite these costs, however, there exists a (symmetric sequential) equilibrium in this infinitely repeated, completeinformation garne in which cheating does not occur and merchants are induced to provide the court with the information required to support cooperation. It is the court's ability to activate the multilateral reputation mechanism by collecting and dispensing information that provides the appropriate incentives. Furthermore, there exists an equilibrium in which the traders' threat to withdraw from future trade is sufficient to deter the court from abusing its information to extort money from the traders. However, the paper does not go far enough in establishing the historical validity of its argument; it only points out that the fairs' authorities controlled who was permitted to enter the fairgrounds. Court and other historical records from western and southern Europe dating back to the mid-twelfth century indicate the operation of another mechanism that enabled anonymous contracting over time and place. Traders applied a principle of community responsibility that linked the conduct of any trader with the obligations of every member of bis community. For example, if a debtor from a specific community failed to appear at the place where he was supposed to meet his obligations, the lender could request the local court to confiscate the goods of any member of the debtor's community present at that locality. Those whose goods were confiscated could then seek a remedy from the original debtor. Traders used intra-community enforcement mechanisms to support inter-community exchange. Historians have considered this "community responsibility system" for contract enforcement to be "barbaric" since it sometimes led to "retaliation phases" in which an accusation of cheating led to the end of trade between two communities for an extended time. Further, some other facts about the system - such as regulations aimed at increasing the cost of default to a lender, attempts of wealthy merchants from large communifies to be exempt from the system, and its demise at the end of the thirteenth century remain unexplained. Greif (1996a, 2000a) used a repeated, imperfect-monitoring garne that captures the essence of the situation to explain these features as well as evaluate the pros and cons of the system.
2006
A. Greif
The analysis indicates the rationale behind the costly retaliation phases as an on-theequilibrium-path-of-play behavior required to maintain cooperation. They reflect asymmetric information between two local courts which, at times, reached different conclusions regarding the fulfillment or non-fulfillment of the contractual obligations. The regulations that increased the cost of default to the lender, and the attempts of wealthy merchants from large communities to be exempt from it, reflect the moral hazard problem generated by the system. Efficiency required that a lender verify the borrower's creditworthiness. But the system implied that he also considered the future possibility of obtaining compensation from the borrower's community, leading to misallocation of credit. Increasing the lender's cost of default mitigated this problem, while well-to-do members of wealthy communities were particularly interested in being exempt from the system since their community's wealth and size fostered the moral hazard problem. While they had the personal reputation required to borrow without community responsibility, their wealth enabled less creditworthy members of their community to borrow as well. These wealthy merchants thus had to pay the cost required to enable other members of their community to borrow and they gained less and paid more for the community responsibility system and therefore they wanted to be exempt from it. The model and historical evidence suggest that the decline of the system followed an increase in its cost in terms of retaliation phases and the moral hazard problem. The cost increase was due to the rising number of trading communities, the increased wealth of some communities, and social and political integration that enabled one to falsify his community's membership. 3.2.2. The state: Emergence, nature, and function The European stares were important economic decision-makers and the competition among them is often invoked to account for the rise of the Western World. Several studies used dynamic and repeated garnes with complete information and dynamic games with incomplete information to examine the relations between economic factors and the origin and nature of the European state. They indicate the importance of viewing a state as a self-enforcing institution, and the role of intra-state organizations in enhancing cooperation among various elements within the state, and they advance new interpretations of the parliamentary system. Finally, they reveal a reason why wars may occur eren in a world with symmetric information and transferable utility. The emergence and origin of the state: Among the most intriguing cases of state formation in medieval Europe is that of the Italian city states. They were formed through voluntary contracts and many of them experienced very rapid economic growth from the eleventh to the fourteenth centuries. Genoa is a case in point. It was established around 1096 for the explicit purpose of advancing the profits of its members, and indeed it emerged from obscurity to become a commercial empire that stretched from the Black Sea and beyond to northern Europe. Advancing the economic prosperity of Genoa required cooperation between Genoa's two dominant noble clans (and their political factions). They could militarily cooperate in raiding other political units or acquiring commercial rights from them, such as low customs or parts of ports which yielded
Ch. 52: Economic History and Garne Theory
2007
rent every period after their acquisition. The acquisition of such rights was the key to the city's long-term economic prosperity. Yet, for cooperation to emerge, each clan had to expect to gain from it despite each clan's ex p o s t ability to use its military power to challenge the other for its share in the gains. No clan made such an attempt from 1096 to 1164, but from 1164 to 1194 inter-clan warfare was frequent. Was inter-clan cooperation in acquiring rights prior to 1164 limited by the need to ensure the self-enforceability of the clans' contractual relations regarding the distribution of gains? Why did inter-clan warfare occur after 1169? Did the clans attempt to alter the rules of their garne to enhance cooperation after 1164? These questions have been raised by historians but could not be addressed without an appropriate game-theoretical formulation. Greif (1994a, 1998c) analyzed this situation as a dynamic garne with complete information regarding the clans' military strength, hut uncertainty regarding the outcome of a military conflict. The analysis indicates that self-enforceability may limit cooperation in the acquisition of rights. If the clans are at a mutual-deterrence equilibrium with less than the efficient number of rights, it may not be in a clan's interest to cooperate in acquiring additional rights. In a mutual-deterrence equilibrium with less than the efficient number of rights, neither clan challenges the other since the expected cost of the war and the cost implied by the possibility of defeat outweigh the expected gains from capturing the other clan's share. With additional rights, the increase in the expected benefit for a clan from challenging may exceed the increase in the expected cost of potential defeat, leading to either a military confrontation or a clan being forced to increase its investment in military ability. This "political cost" of acquiring rights implies that each clan may find it optimal to cooperate in acquiring less than the efficient number of rights. The above analysis is incomplete since in the case of Genoa there is no justification for taking the clans' share in the gains as exogenous. Can the clans necessarily overcome the economic inefficiency implied by the political cost by re-allocating the gains? Suppose that one clan finds it beneficial to chatlenge the other given its share in the gains and military strength. Although the garne is one of complete information, there still may be no other Pareto-superior equilibrium in which inter-clan war is prevented. It may not exist due to the uncertainty involved about military conflicts and the clans' ability to use its share in the gains to increase its military strength. Increasing the share in the gains of the clan that is about to challenge decreases the gains from a victory but increases the chance of winning. The other clan may thus be better off fighting while retaining its original allocation. Hence, the ability of Genoa's clans to cooperate could have been constrained by the extent to which their relations were self-enforcing. But was this historically the case? Did the need for self-enforceability constrain the clans' economic cooperation? Under the assumption that it did, the model yields various predictions, such as the time-path of cooperation in raids and the acquisition of rights, investment in military strength, and responses (including inter-clan military confrontation) to various exogenous changes. These predictions are confirmed by the historical records. It was only in 1194 that a process of learning and severe external threat to Genoa motivated the clans to establish a self-enforcing organization which was known as a p o d e s t ä (that is, a "power"). It altered the rules of the political game in Genoa to
2008
A. Gre«
increase the set of parameters (including the number of rights) under which inter-clan cooperation could be achieved as a mutual deterrence equilibrium outcome. Furthermore, the podesteria coordinated on such an equilibrium. Essentially, the podestä was a non-Genoese hired for one year to govern Genoa and supported by his own military contingent. Thepodesteria's self-enforcing regulations were such that the podestä could commit to use his military power (only) against any clan attempting to militarily challenge another. It was under the podesteria, which formally lasted about 150 years, that Genoa reached its political and commercial apex. Understanding Genoa's commercial rise requires comprehension of its political foundations. 23 Green (1993) analyzed the emergence of the parliamentary government of England during the thirteenth century, an event which arguably contributed to England's subsequent growth. His analysis supports the conjecture that a shift to parliamentary government alleviates the cost of communicating private information. The existing balance-ofpower theory that views changes in governmental systems as indicative of changes in the technology of capturing or defending property, fails to explain a central provision in the Magna Carta (1215). Instead of requesting tax cuts, the English barons insisted that the king should request their consent for new taxes. Green argues that this request reflects the benefit of communication and exchange between the parties. The loss of the English Crown's possessions in France shortly before 1215 and the growing complexity of European politics increased the threat of an external invasion of England and implied that the king had better information regarding such an invasion. To see why such an external threat and private information might make a political system based on communication Pareto-optimal, Green analyzed the following model. Consider a one-period garne in which a ruler can always expropriate (at most) half of the subject's crop. There is some probability of an external threat to the whole crop which the ruler can successfully confront by (a) taking a costly action such as assembling an army, and then (b) confronting the threat (without any additional cost). If there is no threat the ruler prefers half the crop over taking the costly action. If there is a threat the ruler prefers taking the action if provided with two-thirds of the crop rather than not taking the action and getting no share at all. The subject can provide the ruler with twothirds of the crop between the time of events (a) and (b). Whether the external threat is about to materialize or not is the ruler's private information. In this model there is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium in which the ruler communicates that the external threat has materialized by taking the costly action and the subject provides him with two-thirds of the crop. Despite the cost of the communication, this equilibrium Pareto-dominates the equilibria in which there is no communication. Hence, a shift to parliamentary government may reflect the benefit of such costly communication. Committing to respect property rights: The five bankruptcies of the Spanish Crown (1557, 1575, 1596, 1607, and 1627) during the height of Spanish economic and political dominance are orten used to demonstrate the limitations of a pre-modem public 23 See also Rosenthal (1998), who examinedhow the garnebetweenkings and noblesin France and England influenced economicand political outcomes.
Ch. 52: Economic History and Game Theory
2009
finance system [Cameron (1993), p. 137]. The rulers' inability to commit to the property rights of their lenders hindered their ability to borrow. In a detailed historical and game-theoretic analysis, Conklin (1998) advanced a different interpretation of these bankruptcies as reflecting a routine realignment of the king's finances. In other words, they do not reflect the failure of a system but its effective operation. These bankruptcies were not a wholesale repudiation of obligations to creditors. They were initiated by the Genoese, the king's foreign lenders, who ceased providing hirn with credit. In response, the king ceased paying the Genoese and negotiated a partial repayment of his debt to them with debt obligations directly linked to particular tax-generating assets the king had in Spain. The Genoese could sell these obligations to Spain's elite, namely, the king's local lenders. 24 After this realignment, the Genoese resumed lending. For this analysis, Conklin used a repeated garne with state variables, an important component of which is that the king "cares" about the welfare of his Spanish lenders. The justification for this specification was the king's dependency on these elite Spaniards for tax collection, administration, and military operations. Solving for a Pareto-optimal, sub-game-perfect equilibrium using a computer algorithm indicated that financial realignment should have occun'ed when the king reached the limit of his ability to commit to the Genoese. Shifting some of this debt to his elite to whom he could commit was a prerequisite for additional lending. This interpretation gains additional support, such as the particularities of the tax collection system and the king's willingness to prey on the wealth of particular Spaniards while continuing to pay his local debt. 3.2.3. Within stares
Garne theory facilitated the analyses of historical market structures (the number and relative size of firms within an industry), financial systems, legal systems, and development. At the same time, these analyses used historical data sets that enabled the exarnination of game-theoretical industrial organization models, confirmed game-theoretical predictions regarding the relations between rules and behavior, suggested the role of banks and the distribution of rent in initiating a move from one equilibrium to another, and inspired new game-theoretical models of financial and market structure. M a r k e t s t r u c t u r e a n d c o n d u c t : Business records from the period prior to and following the Sherman Act provide unique data sets for examining the relations between strategic behavior and market structures. Their analysis substantiated the importance of predation and reputation in influencing market structures, enabled empirical examination of models of tacit collusion, indicated limits of using only indirect (econometric) evidence in examining inter-firm interactions, and suggested that existing models of market structures are deficient in ignoring the multi-dimensionality of inter-firm interactions. 24 In the process the Genoesehad to bear some losses.
2010
A. Greif
Bums (1986) examined the role that a reputation for predatory pricing played in the emergence of the tobacco trust between 1891 and 1906. An econometric analysis of the purchases of 43 rival firms by the old American Tobacco Company indicated that alleged predation significantly lowered the acquisition costs, both for asserted victims and, through reputation effects, for competitors that sold out peacefully. Similarly, Gorton (1996) examined the formation and implication of reputation in the Free Banking era (1838-60) during which new banks could enter the market and issue notes. Economic historians noticed, but found it difficult to explain, that "wildcat" ("fly by night") banking was not a pervasive problem during this period. The Diamond (1989) incompleteinformation model suggests that if some banks were wildcats, some were not, and some could have chosen whether to be wildcats or not. A process of reputation formation may have deterred banks from choosing to become wildcats. Due to information asymmetry, all banks initially faced high discount rates, but following the default of the wildcats the discount rate declined due to the reputation acquired by the surviving firms. This decline, in mm, further motivated firms that could choose whether or not to be wildcats. Gorton conducted an econometric analysis of various aspects of these conjectures (particularly whether new banks' notes were discounted more and if this discount depended on the institutional environment), which confirmed the importance of reputation in preventing wildcat operations. 25 Weiman and Levin (1994) combined direct and indirect (econometric) evidence to examine the development and implication of the strategy employed by the Southern Bell Telephone Company to acquire a monopoly position between 1894 and 1912. In contrast to the usual assumption in industrial organization, the strategic variable that enabled it to become a monopoly was not only price but also investment in toll lines ahead of demand, isolating independents in smaller areas, and influencing regulations by increasing the cost of competition to the users. Similarly, Gabel (1994) substantiated that between 1894 and 1910 AT&T acquired control over the telephone industry through predatory pricing. Despite its short-term cost, price reduction enabled AT&T to deter entry and to cheaply buy the property of independents. This strategy was facilitated by rate regulations and capital market imperfections that prevented independents from entering on a large scale. 26 In a classic study, Porter (1983) examined collusion of a railroad cartel (the "Joint Executive Committee") established in 1789 to set prices for transport between Chicago and the East Coast. Using data from 1880 to 1886 the study tested and could not reject the relevance of Green and Porter's (1984) theory of collusion with imperfect monitoring and demand uncertainty. (The alternative was that price movements reflected exogenous shifts in demand and cost functions.) According to the Green and Porter theory, price wars occur on the equilibrium path due to the inability of firms to distinguish between
25 See also Ramseyer's(1991) smdyof the relations between credible commitmentand contractual relations in the prostitution industry in ImperialJapan. 26 See also Nix and Gabel(1994).
Ch. 52: EconomicHistory and Garne Theory
2011
shift in demand and a firm's defection. A sufficiently low price triggers a price war of some finite length, and although all firms realize that no deviation has occurred, punishment is required to retain collusion. Similar results were obtained by Ellison (1994), who compared the Green and Porter model with that of Rotemberg and Saloner (1986) in which price wars never transpire and on-the-path prices exhibit a counter-cyclical pattern. The Green and Porter model also provides the theoretical framework used by Levenstein (1994, 1996a, 1996b) to examine collusion in the pre-WWI US bromine industry. An econometric analysis could not reject the Green and Porter model, indicating that price wars stabilized collusion. Yet, Levenstein (1996a) claimed that this conclusion is misleading. Using ample direct evidence, Levenstein substantiated that only a few wars stabilized collusion in the Green and Porter sense and these were short and mild. Long and severe price wars were either bargaining instruments aimed at influencing the distribution from collusion, or a profitable deviation from collusive behavior made possible by asymmetric technological changes. Finally, similar to the studies discussed above, her paper casts doubt on the empirical relevance of the strategic models of collusion which assume that price is the only strategic variable. In the bromine industry, collusion of firms was facilitated by altering the industry's information structure and marketing system [Levenstein (1996b)]. Financial systems and development: The nature and role of financial intermediaries that functioned prior to the rise of banks and securities markets have hardly been examined, limiting our understanding of pre-modern financial markets. Furthermore, the relations between development and distinct financial systems (differentiated by the natute and relative importance of banks and securities markets) have been examined by economic historians [Mokyr (1985), p. 37]. Only recently has the application of garne theory to historical research facilitated the analysis of alternative intermediaries, enabled exploring the origins and implications of diverse financial systems, and suggested a heretofore unexamined role for banks in coordinating development. Hoffman, Postel-Vinay, and Rosenthal (1998) used a repeated-game model and an unusual data set from Paris (1751) to theoretically and econometrically examine the operation of a credit system as an alternative to banks and security markets. In Old Regime France, notaries had property rights over the records of any transaction they registered. Hence, they had a monopoly over the information required for screening and matching potential borrowers and lenders. Their ability to provide credit market intermediation, however, could have been hindered by a "lock-in" effect. Unless they were able to commit not to exploit their monopoly power, potential participants in the credit rnarket would have been deterred from approaching them. A game-theoretical formulation of this problem revealed that it could have been mitigated by an equilibrium in which notaries shared information with each other to reduce each notary's monopoly power over bis clients. Indeed, the data confirms the behavior associated with this equilibrium. There is a consensus among economic historians that different financial and industrial systems prevailed in the first and second major industrialized European countries
2012
A. Greif
- namely, England and Germany. 27 English firms were relatively small and tended to be financed through tradeable bonds and arm's-length lending. The German firms, however, were large and tended to be financed by loans from particular banks which closely monitored them. Motivated by this difference, Baliga and Polak (1995) attempted to explore its origins and rationale using a dynamic game capturing the moral hazard problem inherent in industrial loans. Entrepreneurs would provide only second-best effort levels in the absence of monitoring, while costly monitoring induces more effort. Monitoring exhibits internal economies of scale while markets for tradeable loans exhibit external economies of scale. The analysis provides the foundation for potentially beneficial future empirical analysis. It leads to comparative statics predictions regarding the relations between exogenous factors (such as base interest rates, firm size, and the lender's bargaining power) and the entrepreneur's choice of financial arrangements. Furthermore, it indicates the possible impact of the entrepreneurs' wealth and the market in government securities on the efficiency and selection of financial arrangements. When the analysis is further extended to an entry game in which entrepreneurs choose a firm's size and banks choose whether to acquire monitoring ability, multiple equilibria exist, indicating a possible rationale for the emergence and persistence of different systems. The role of banks in coordinating development is suggested by the "big-push" theory of economic development [Murphy et al. (1989)]. When externalities make investment profitable only if enough firms invest at the same time, failure to coordinate on such a simultaneous investment may lead to an "underdevelopment trap". Inspired by this model and the positive historical correlation between rapid industrialization and large banks with some market power or with large equity holdings in industrial firms, Da Rin and Hellmann (1998) developed a model of the role of banks in coordinating a transition to an equilibrium in which firms invest. Utilizing a dynamic garne with complete information they suggested that this positive correlation reflects the role of large banks in initiating a move from one equilibrium to another. A necessary condition for banks to coordinate industrialization is that at least one bank (or coordinated group of banks) is large enough to initiate a big push by subsidizing the investment of a critical mass of firms to induce them to invest. A bank's monopoly power or capital investment is required, however, to motivate that bank to coordinate by enabling it to benefit from the industrialization it triggered. Law, development, and labor relations: 2s Game-theoretical models were used to evaluate the impact of legal rules and procedures on development and labor relations in various historical episodes. Rosenthal (1992) established that, despite the efficiency of several potential drainage and irrigation projects in France from 1700 to 1860, they were not carried out. In contrast, efficient projects were undertaken in England during this period, as well as in France after the French Revolution. The efficient projects were
27 Somerecent papers doubt this difference; see Fohlin (1994) and Kinghornand Nye (1996). 28 See also Milgromet al. (1990) and Greif (1996a, 2000a).
Ch. 52: Economic History and Game Theory
2013
not carried out since the village which had some de facto or de jura property rights over the land, and the lord who wanted to initiate the project, failed to reach an agreement regarding the distribution of the gains. Rosenthal conjectured that the distinct legal features of Old Regime France accounted for this failure. To demonstrate that the legal features of the Old Regime could have inhibited reaching an agreement, Rosenthal used a dynamic incomplete-information garne. Central to the model is asymmetric information regarding the legal validity of the village's rights over the land and the "burden of proof" rule, namely, whether the property rights will be assigned to the lord or the village if neither party is able to establish de jura rights over the land. The analysis indicates that legal prohibition on out-of-court settlements, the burden of proof rule that favored the village, and the high cost of using the legal system, increased the number of efficient projects that lords would find unprofitable to initiate. All these features of the legal system prevailed in Old Regime France but not in England or post-revolutionary France. 29 Treble (1990) examined the impact of legal regulations on wage negotiations in the British coal industry from 1893-1914. These negotiations were conducted in "conciliation boards", and in cases of disagreement an arbitrator had to be used. The number of appeals made to arbitrators differed greatly among coal fields, and ranged from as low as 11 percent to as high as 56 percent (per number of negotiations). The economic historians' traditional explanation of these differences is that they reflected differences in the negotiators' personalities. Treble, however, modeled the bargaining process as a game which [unlike many other bargaining models, such as Farber (1980)] generated predictions regarding the frequency of appeals to arbitration. Treble's analysis predicted that because delay in reaching an agreement had a strategic value, the more the constitution of a particular conciliation board permitted delay without arbitration, the less arbitration would be used. When this hypothesis and the alternative, that appeal depended on personalities or reflected asymmetric information regarding the arbitrator's preference [Crawford (1982b)], was placed under econometric analysis, it could not be rejected. Moriguchi (1998) has utilized a game-theoretic framework to conduct a comparative study of the evolution of labor relations in Japan and the US from 1900 to 1960. She modeled the relationships between potential employers and employees as a repeated garne and examined the resulting set of equilibria for various parameter values. Furthermore, she examined the political ramifications of various equilibria and how, in turn, they influenced the endogenous political formation process of labor regulations. This framework enabled her to provide a novel interpretation of the evolution of labor relationships. The combined theoretical and historical analysis highlights, for example, the essence of employer paternalism as a mechanism to move from one equilibrium to another, and the importance of the Great Depression in causing a bifurcation of the equilibrium selected in each economy. Furthermore, the analysis indicates the importance 29 See also Besley,Coate, and Guinnane (1993), who studied the evolution of laws governingprovisionsfor the poor.
2014
A. Greif
of various factors that led to the persistence of each equilibrium after the Great Depression, such as coordination cost and sunk investment in complementary regulations and technology.
3.2.4. Between stares Applying repeated and static games to historical analyses has indicated the importance of non-market institutions in influencing the historical process through which longdistance trade grew and the empirical relevance of the ideas behind renegotiation-proof equilibrium. 3° It has also lent support to the New International Trade Theory, by indicating the implications of the intra-firm incentive structure on inter-firm strategic interaction, how strategic international relations impact domestic economic policy, how cooperation can evolve, and what the relations are between equilibrium selection and credible, public communication. International trade: Greif, Milgrom, and Weingast (1994) examined the operation and implications of an institution that enabled rulers during the late medieval period to commit to the security of alien traders' property rights. Having a local monopoly over coercive power, any medieval ruler faced the temptation to abuse the property of alien merchants who frequented his realm. Without an institution enabling a ruler to commit ex ante to secure alien merchants' rights, they would not have come to trade. Since trade relationships were expected to be repeated, one may conjecture that a bilateral reputation mechanism in which a merchant whose rights were abused ceased trading, or an uncoordinated multilateraI reputation mechanism in which a subgroup larger than the one that was abused ceased trading, could surmount this commitment problem. This conjecture, however, is wrong. Although each of these mechanisms can support some level of trade, neither can support the efficient level of trade. The bilateral reputation mechanism fails because, at the efficient level of trade, the value of fumre trade of the "marginal" traders to the ruler is zero, and hence the ruler is tempted to abuse their rights (irrespective of the distribution of the gains from trade and the ruler's discount factor). In a world fraught with information asymmetries, slow communication, and different possible interpretations of facts, the multilateral reputation mechanism is prone to fail for a similar reason. Hence, theoretically, a multilateral reputation mechanism can potentially overcome the commitment problem only when the merchants have some organization to coordinate their actions. Such a coordinating organization implies the existence of a Markov-perfect equilibrium in which traders come to trade (at the efficient level) as long as a boycott is not announced, but none of them come to trade if one is announced. The ruler respects the merchants' rights as long as a boycott is not announced, but abuses their rights otherwise. When a coordinating institution exists, trade may plausibly expand to its efficient level. 30 The discussion above regarding agencyrelations and anonymoustrade also relates to the insfitutions and long-distance trade. For art elaboration of the insights providedby game-theoretical analyses of long-distance trade in history, see Greif (1992).
Ch. 52: EconomicHistory and Game Theory
2015
Although the strategy just described leads to a perfect equilibrium, the theory in this form remains unconvincing considering the ideas behind renegotiation-proof equilibrium. According to the above equilibrium strategies, when a coordinating institution declares an embargo, merchants will pay attention to it because they expect that the ruler will abuse a violator's property rights. But are these expectations reasonable? Why would a ruler not encourage embargo-breakers rather than punish them? Encouragement is potentially credible since during an effective embargo the volume of trade shrinks and the value of the marginal trader increases; it is then possible for bilateral reputation mechanisms to become effective. This possibility limits the potential severity of an embargo and potentially hinders the ability of any coordinating organization to support efficient trade. In such cases, the efficient level of trade can be achieved when a multilateral reputation mechanism is supplemented by an organization with the ability to coordinate responses and ensure the traders' compliance with boycott decisions. Direct and indirect historical evidence indicates that during the Commercial Revolution an institution with these attributes - the merchant guild - emerged and supported trade expansion and market integration. Merchant guilds exhibited a range of administrative forms - from a subdivision of a city administration, such as those of the Italian city-states, to an inter-city organization, such as the German Hänsa. Yet, their functions were the same: to ensure the coordination and internal enforcement required to make the threat of collective action credible. The nature of these guilds and the dates of their emergence reflect historical as weil as environmental factors. In Italy, for example, each city was large enough to ensure that its merchants were not "marginal" and its legal authority ensured their merchants' compliance with the guild's decisions. In contrast, the relatively small German cities had to organize themselves as one guild through a lengthy process to be able to inflict an effective boycott. Irwin (1991) utilized a game-theoretical model to examine the competition between the English Eäst India Company and the Dutch United East India Compäny during the early seventeenth century. The Dutch were able to achieve dominance in the trade in pepper brought from the Spice Islands of Indonesia, although both companies had similar costs and sold the pepper for the same price in the European market. To understand the sources of Dutch dominance, Irwin argued that the nature of the competition in the pepper market resembles Brander and Spencer's (1985) model of duopolistic competition in which two companies exporting a single good are engaged in a one-period Cournot (quantity) competition. The English and Durch companies competed mainly in the market for pepper and both were state monopolies whose charters could have been revoked (de jura or de facto) in any period. If this was indeed the situation, Brander and Spencer's analysis indicates that any trade policy shifting one company's reaction function outward increases its Nash equilibrium profit while reducing that of the other. The policy that seems to have shifted the Dutch company's reaction function was instituted through its charter. It specified that its managers' wages should be a function of the company's profit and volume of trade, thereby shifting the company's reaction func-
2016
A. Gre~
tion outward [as in Fershtman and Judd (1987)]. 31 The intra-firm incentive structure influenced inter-firm competition. International relations: Maurer (1992) conducted a case study of the A n g l o - G e r m a n naval arms race from 1912 to 1914, providing an interesting example of actual equilibrium selection and the "evolution of cooperation" [Axelrod (1984)]. During this period the arms race resembled a repeated prisoners' dilemma garne as both countries recognized the high cost it entailed. Some informal cooperation had been achieved when, in 1912, the First Lord of Britain's Admiralty, Winston Churchill, publicly announced a fit-for-tat strategy. Beyond the number of battleships already approved for building in Germany and Britain, Britain would build two battleships for each additional German battleship. The Germans adopted their best response of not producing additional battleships after testing the credibility of Churchill's announcement. Thus the arms race and public spending were diverted in other directions, such as construction of destroyers, the build-up of ground troops, and enhancing the battleships' features. Negotiafion over a formal and broader arms-control agreement failed, however, particularly because both parties were concerned that the discussion would worsen their relations by raising the contentious security issues reflected in the naval competition and its link to the wider issue of the European balance of power.
3.2.5. Culture, institutions, and endogenous institutional dynamics A long tradition in economic history argues that culture and institutions influence economic performance and growth. 32 The study of the inter-relations between institutions and culture, however, has been hindered by the lack of an appropriate theoretical framework. This has limited the ability to address questions that seem to be at the heart of developmental failures: W h y do societies evolve along distinct institutional trajectories? W h y do societies fail to adopt the institutional structures of more economically successful ones? How do past institutions influence the rate and direction of institutional change? Garne theory provides a theoretical framework that facilitates addressing these questions and revealing why institutional dynamics is a historical process. Greif (1994a, 1996b) integrated game-theoretical and sociological concepts to conduct a comparative historical analysis of the relations between culture and institutions.
31 Irwin argues that this result supports the view of mercantilism as a strategic trade policy. Arcand and Brezis (1993) take a similar stand. 32 E.g., North (1981). For an elaboration on various concepts of institutions in economics and economic history and the contribution of the garne-theoreticperspective, see Greif (1997c, 1998b, 2000b). Similar to the above papers, institufions are defined hefe as non-technologicallydetermined factors that direct and constrain behavior while being exogenous to each of the individuals whose behavior they influence but endogenous to the society as a whole. (Hence, an institution can reflect actions taken by all the individuals whose behavior the institution influeuces or actions taken by other individuals or organizations, such as the court or the legislature.)
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Garne Theory
2017
The analysis considers the cultural factors that led two pre-modern traders' societies - the Maghribis from the Muslim world and the Genoese from the Latin world - to evolve along distinct institutional trajectories. It builds on a distinction between two elements of institutions - expectations and organizations - which is made possible by game theory. A player's expectations about the behavior of others are part of the nontechnologically determined constraints that a player faces. Organizations such as the credit bureau, the court of law, or the firm, can potentially constrain behavior as well by changing the information available to players, changing payoffs associated with certain actions, or introducing another player (the organization itself). Clearly, organizations can be either exogenous or endogenous to the analysis (as discussed in Greif (1997c)). When they are endogenous their "introduction" means that they are transformed from being an off-the-path-of-play recognized or unrecognized possibility to an on-the-pathof-play reality. This framework enables the explicitation of a role of culture in institutional dynamics. Specifically, as mentioned above, the different cultural heritages and social processes of the Maghribis and the Genoese seem to have led to a selection of distinct equilibria in the merchant-agent garne. The Maghribis reached a "collectivist equilibrium" that entailed a collective punishment, while the Genoese reached an "individualist equilibrium" that entailed bilateral punishment. What is more surprising, however, is that a game-theoretical and empirical analysis indicates that once the distinct expectations associated with these strategies were formed with respect to agency relations they became "cultural beliefs" and transcended the original garne in which they had been formed. They transcended it in the sense that they influenced subsequent responses to exogenous changes in the rules of the garne and the endogenous process of organizational development, or, in other words, they became a cultural element that linked games. Classical garne theory does not say much about such inter-game linkages: actions to be taken following an expected change in the rules of the garne are part of the (initial) equilibrium strategy combination, while an equilibrium that will be selected following an unexpected change in the rules of the garne has no relation to the equilibrium that prevailed prior to the change. Yet, comparing the responses of both groups to exogenous changes indicates that the equilibria selected following unexpected changes in the rules of the game had a predictable relationship to the equilibria that prevailed prior to the change. 33 Cultural beliefs provided the initial conditions in a dynamic adjustment process through which the new equilibria were reached. Furthermore, the initial equilibria were related in a predictable manner to subsequently historical organizational innovations. Differences in organizational innovations among the two groups regarding organizations such as the guild, the court, the family firm, or the bill of lading, can be consistently accounted for as reflecting incentives generated by the expecta-
33 Similarresults emergedin experiments. See Camererand Knez (1996).
2018
A. Greif
tions that following an organizational change, the original cultural beliefs will still prevail. 34 The analysis of institutions among the Maghribis and Genoese in the late medieval period suggests the historical importance of distinct cultures and initial organizational features in influencing institutional trajectories and economic development. Interestingly, the cultural and organizational distinctions among the Maghribi and Genoese societies resemble those found by social psychologists and development economists to differentiate contemporary developing and developed economies. In any case, the analysis indicates how cultural traits and organizational features that crystallized in the past influence the direction of institutional change. Societies evolve along distinct institutional trajectories because past cultural beliefs and organizations transcend the particular situation in which they were formed and influence organizational innovations and responses to new situations. Furthermore, societies fail to adopt the institutional structures of more economically successful ones because they can only adopt organizational forms and formal rules of behavior. The behavioral implications of these, however, depend on the prevailing cultural beliefs, which may not change despite the introduction of new organizations and rules. The analysis of agency relationships among the Maghribis and Genoese also sheds some light on the sources of endogenous institutional change. The rate of institutional changes depended on organizational innovations while their particular cultural beliefs provided members of each group with distinct incentives to invent new organizational forms. Other studies that applied garne theory to historical analysis indicate additional ways that past institutions influenced the rate of institutional change. As elaborated in Greif (2000b), existing institutions cause endogenous institutional change by directing processes through which "quasi-parameters" change. Quasi-parameters are institutional and other features - such as preferences, technological and other knowledge, and wealth distribution - that are either part of the rules of the garne or can be taken as exogenous in a study of institutional statics because (of when) they change slowly and only their cumulative change causes institutions to change. 35 Existing institutions and their implications direct the process through which quasi-parameters change, and thereby they can, over time, cause existing institutions no longer to be an equilibrium - i.e., selfenforcing. In other words, processes caused by existing institutions can lead, over time, to endogenous institutional change.
34 Yet, the theory cannot account for the timing of these organizational changes. Historically, it took a long time to introduce an organization despite the incentives and possibility of an earlier inlroduction. 35 The main reasons for this discontinuousinfluence are that the mapping from quasi-parametersto an equilibrium is a set-to-point mapping and that institutions coordinate behavior. Because a particular equilibrium can prevail for a large set of quasi-parameters,there is a range in which they may change and equilibrium will still exist. At the same time, because changes in the cultural beliefs associated with the prevailing equilibrium the shared expeetations that coordinate behavior on it - require coordination, that equilibrium is likely to persist despite the changes in quasi-parameters. See further Greif (2000b). -
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Garne Theory
2019
To iIlustrate endogenous institutional change, consider again the above discussion of the community responsibility system that supported inter-community "anonymous" exchange during the late medieval period [Greif (2000a)]. During the late thirteenth century, attempts were made throughout Europe to abolish this system and to establish alternative contract enforcement institutions based, in particular, on a legal system administrated by state that held a trader, and not his community, liable for his contractual obligations. A game-theoretic and historical examination of the transition away from the community responsibility system suggests that, ironically, it reflects the system's own implications. The community responsibility system was eroding the quasi-parameters that made it self-enforcing. It enabled trade to expand and merchants' communities to grow in size, number, and economic and social heterogeneity. These changes implied that over time the community responsibility system was no longer an equilibrium. The increase in intra-communities' economic heterogeneity, for example, implied (as discussed previously) that some cornmunity members had to bear the cost of the community responsibility system without benefiting from it. Hence, they used their political influence within their community to abolish the system. 3.3. Conclusions
Although all the above studies integrate game-theoretical and economic history analyses, they differ in their objectives, their methodologies, and the weight placed on theory versus history. Yet, they forcefully indicate the potential contribution of combining economic history, garne theory, and economics. Garne theory has expanded the domain of economic history by permitting examination of important issues that could not be adequately addressed using a non-strategic framework. It enabled the examination of such diverse issues as contract enforcement in medieval trade, the economic implications of legal proceedings in Old Regime France, trade rivalry between the Dutch Republic and England, bargaining in England's coal raines, and the process through which the industrial structure emerged in the US. It provided, among other insights, new interpretations of the nature and economic implications of merchant guilds, the Glorious Revolution, the role banks play in development, the structures of industries, and the free-banking era.
More generally, these studies indicate the promise of applying garne theory to economic history to advance out understanding of a variety of issues whose study requires strategic analysis. Among them are the nature and implications of the institutional foundations of markets, the legal system, the inter-relations between culture and institutions, the link between the potential use of violence and economic outcomes, the impact of strategic factors on market structures, and the economic irnplications of organizations for coordination and information transmission. Further, although all the above studies used equilibrium analysis, they illuminated the sources and implications of changes and path dependence. Incentives and expectations on and oft the equilibrium path indicate the rationale behind the absence or occurrence of changes, while institutional path dependence was found, for example, to be due to acquired knowledge and infor-
2020
A. Greif
mation, economies of scale and scope associated with existing organizations or technology, coordination failure, distributional issues, capital market imperfections, and culture. 36 Perhaps the most important contribution of analyses combining the game-theoretic and historical approaches is that they provide additional support for the importance of examining strategic situations and the empirical usefulness of garne theory. Indeed, history provides an unusual laboratory in which to examine the empirical relevance of garne theory since it contains unique data sets regarding strategic situations and the relationship between rules and outcomes. Interestingly, infinitely repeated garnes that have been considered by many as indicating the empirical irrelevance of garne theory because they usually exhibit multiple equilibria, were found to be particularly useful for empirical analysis. Further, the studies discussed above also demonstrate the limitations of the theory and suggest directions for future development. For example, they indicate in the spirit of Schelling (1960) and Lewis (1969) that understanding equilibrium selection may require better comprehension of factors outside (the current formulation) of garnes, such as culture. Similarly, the study of organizations and organizational path dependence indicates the importance of considering the process through which the rules of the game are determined and the implications of organizafions on the equilibrium set and equilibrium selection. Finally, economic history analyses using garne theory have enhanced our knowledge regarding issues central to economics, such as the nature and origin of institutions, the strategic determinants of industry structures and trade expansion, collusion, property rights, the economic implications of political institutions, labor relations, and the operation of capital markets. Hence, they provide an additional dimension to the long and productive collaboration between economic history and economics. Furthermore, these analyses indicate the need for and the benefit of combining theoretical and empirical research that transcends the boundaries of history, economics, political science, and sociology. The application of garne theory to historical analysis is still in its infancy. Yet, it seems to have already reaffirmed McCloskey's (1976) claims regarding the benefits of the interactions between economic history and economics in general. It has provided an improved set of evidence to evaluate current theories, suggested theoretical advances, and expanded our economic understanding of the nature, origin, and implications of various economic phenomena.
36 On path dependence and institufions, see North (1990), who emphasizes economics of scale and scope, network externalities, and a subjectiveviewof the world, and David (1994), who emphasizesconventions,informationchannels and codes as "sunk"organizationalcapital, interrelatedness, complementaritiesand precedents. E.g., knowledge:Hoffmanet al. (1998); scale, scope,coordination, and culture: Greif(1994a), Weiman and Levin (1994); distribution: Rosenthal(1992). For recent discussions of institutional path dependence, see North (1990), David(1994), and Greif (1994a, 1997b, 1997c, 2000b).
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Garne Theory
2021
Referenccs Arcand, J.-L.L., and E. Brezis (1993), "Protectionism and power: A strategic interpretation of a mercantilism theory", Working Paper (Department of Economics and CRDE, University of Montreal). Axelrod, R. (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation (Basic Books, New York). Backhouse, R. (1985), A History of Modern Economic Analysis (Basil Blackwell, New York). Baliga, S., and B. Polak (1995), "Banks versus bonds: A simple theory of comparative financial institutions", Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper no. 1100 (Yale University). Brander, J.A., and B.J. Spencer (1985), "Export subsidies and international market share rivalry", Joumal of International Economics 18:83-100. Benson, B.L. (1989), "The spontaneous evolution of commercial law", Southem Economic Joumal 55:644661. Besley, T., S. Coate and T.W. Guinnane (1993), "Why the workhouse test? Information and poor relief in nineteenth-century England", Working Paper (Economics Department, Princeton University). Bums, M.R. (1986), "Predatory pricing and the acquisition cost of competitors", Joumal of Political Economy 94:266-296. Camerer, C., and M. Knez (1996), "Coordination in organizations: A garne theoretic perspective", Working Paper (Califomia Institute of Technology). Cameron, R. (1993), A Concise Economic History of the World (Oxford University Press, Oxford). Carlos, A.M., and E. Hoffman (1986), "The NoNa American fur trade: Bargaining to a joint profit maximum under incomplete information, 1804-1821", Joumal of Economic History 46:967-986. Carlos, A.M., and E. Hoffman (1988), "Garne theory and the North American fur trade: A reply", Journal of Economic History 48:801. Carruthers, B.E. (1990), "Politics, popery and property: A comment on North and Weingast", Joumal of Economic History 50:693-698. Clark, G. (1995), "The political foundations of modern economic growth: England, 1540-1800", The Joumal of Interdisciplinary History 26:563-588. Clay, K. (1997), ''Trade without law: Private-order institutions in Mexican Califomia", The Joumal of Law, Economics & Organization 13:202-231. Conldin, J. (1998), "The theory of sovereign debt and Spain under Philip II", Journal of Political Economy 106:483-513. Crawford, V.E (1982a), "A theory of disagreement in bargaining", Econometrica 50:607~i38. Crawford, V.E (1982b), "Compulsory arbitration, arbitral risk, and negotiated settlements: A case study in bargaining under asymmetric information", Review of Economic Smdies 49:69-82. Cunningham, W. (1882), The Growth of English Industry and Commerce (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Da Rin, M., and T. Hellmann (1998), "Banks as catalysts for industrialization", Working Paper 103 (IGIER). David, EA. (1982), "Cooperative garnes for medieval warriors and peasants", mimeo (Department of Economics, Stanford University). David, EA. (1988), "Path dependence: Putting the past into the future of economics", Technical Report 533 (IMSSS, Stanford University). David, EA. (1992), "Path dependence and the predictability in dynamic systems with local network extemalities: A paradigm for historical economics", in: C. Freeman and D. Foray, eds., Technology and the Wealth of Nations (Pinter Publishers, London). David, EA. (1994), "Why are institutions the "Carriers of History"?: Path-depeudence and the evolution of conventions, organizations and institutious", Structural Change and Economic Dynamics 5:205-220. Davis, E.L., and D.C. North (1971), Instimtional Change and American Economic Growth (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Diamond, D.W. (1989), "Reputation acquisition in debt market", Journal of Political Economy 97:828-862. Eichengreen, B. (1996), "Institutions and economic growth: Europe after World War II", in: N. Crafts and G. Toniolo, eds., Economic Growth in Europe since 1945 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge).
2022
A. Gre~
Ellison, G. (1994), "Theories of cartel and the joint executive committee", Rand Journal of Economics 25:3757. Farber, H.S. (1980), "An analysis of final-offer arbitration", Journal of Conflict Resolution 24:683-705. Fershtman, C., and K.L. Judd (1987), "Equilibrium incentives in oligopoly", American Economic Review 77:927-940. Fohlin, C.M. (1998), "Relationship banking, liquidity, and investment in the German industrialization", Journal of Finance 53:1737-1758. Fudenberg, D., and J. Tirole (1991), Game Theory (MIT l:äess, Boston). Gabel, D. (1994), "Competition in a network industry: The telephone industry, 1894-1910", The Journal of Economic History 54:543-572. Gorton, G. (1996), "Reputation formation in early bank note markets", Journal of Political Economy 104:346397. Green, E.J. (1993), "On the emergence of parliamentary govemment. The role of private information", Quarterly Review: Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis, Winter:2-16. Green, E.J., and R.H. Porter (1984), "Noncooperative collusion under imperfect price information", Econometrica 52:87-100. Greif, A. (1989), "Reputation and coalitions in medieval trade: Evidence on the Maghribi traders", Journal of Economic History 49:857-882. Greif, A. (1992), "Institutions and international trade: Lessons from the commercial revolution", American Economic Review 82:128-133. Greif, A. (1993), "Contract enforceability and economic institutions in early trade: The Maghribi traders' coalition", American Economic Review 83:525-548. Greif, A. (1994a), "Cultural beliefs and the organization of society: A historical and theoretical reflection on collectivist and individualist societies", Journal of Political Economy 102:912-950. Greif, A. (1994b), "On the political foundations of the late medieval commercial revolution: Genoa during the twelfth and thirteenth centuries", Journal of Economic History 54:271-287. Greif, A. (1996a), "Markets and legal systems: The development of markets in late medieval Europe and the transition from community responsibility to an individual responsibility legal doctrine", Manuscript (Stanford University). Greif, A. (1996b), "On the study of organizations and evolving organizational forms through history: Reflection from the late medieval family firm", Industrial and Corporate Change 5:473-502. Greif, A. (1997a), "Cliometrics after forty years: Microtheory and economic history", American Economic Review 87:400-403. Greif, A. (1997b), "Contracting, enforcement and efficiency: Economics beyond the law', in: M. Bruno and B. Pleskovic, eds., Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics (The World Bank, Washington, DC) 239-266. Greif, A. (1997c), "Microtheory and recent developments in the study of economic institutions through economic history", in: D. Kreps and K. Wallis, eds., Advances in Economic Theory, Vol. II (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) 79-113. Greif, A. (1998a), "Historical institutional analysis: Garne theory and non-market seif-enforcing institutions during the late medieval period", Annales 53:597-633. Greif, A. (1998b), "Historical and comparative institutional analysis", American Economic Review 88:80-84. Greif, A. (1998c), "Self-enforcing political systems and economic growth: Late medieval Genoa", in: B. Bates, A. Greif, M. Levi, J.-L. Rosenthal and B. Weingast, eds., Analytic Narrative (Princeton University Press). Greif, A. (2000a), "Impersonal exchange and the origin of markets: From the community responsibifity system to individual legal responsibility in pre-modern Europe", in: M. Aoki and Y. Hayami, eds., Communifies and Markets (Oxford University Press) Chapter 2. Greif, A. (2000b), "Historical (and comparative) institutional analysis: Self-enforcing and self-reinforcing economic institutions and their dynamics" (Stanford University, Book MS).
Ch. 52:
Economic History and Game Theory
2023
Greif, A., E Milgrom and B. Weingast (1994), "Coordination, commitment and enforcement: The case of the merchant guild", Jottrnal of Political Economy 102:745-776. HartweU, R.M. (1973), "Good old economic history", Journal of Economic History 33:28-40. Hoffman, ET., G. Postel-Vinay and J.-L. Rosenthal (1998), "What do notaries do? Overcoming asymmetric information in financial markets: The case of Paris, 1751", Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 154:499-530. Irwin, D.A. (1991), "Mercantilism as strategic la'adepolicy: The Anglo-Dutch rivalry for the East India trade", Jonrnal of Political Economy 99:1296-1314. Kantor, E.S. (1991), "Razorback, tcky cows and the closiug of the Georgia open fange: The dynamic of institutional change uncovered", Journal of Economic History 51:861-886. Kinghorn, J.R., and J.V. Nye (1996), 'The scale or production in Western economic development: A comparison of official industry statics in the United States, Britain, France and Germany, 1905-1913", Journal of Economic History 56:90-112. Levenstein, M.C. (1994), "Price wars and the stability of collusion: Information and coordination in the nineteenth century chemical cartel", Working Paper (Economics Department, University of Michigan). Levenstein, M.C. (1996a), "Do price wars facilitate collusion? A study of the bromine cartel before World War r', Exploration in Economic History 33:107-137. Levenstein, M.C. (1996b), "Vertical restraints in the bromine cartel: The role of distributors in facilitating collusion", Working Paper (Department of Economics, University of Michigan). Lewis, D. (1969), Convention: A Philosophical Study (Harvard University Press, Cambridge). MacLeod, W.B., and J.M. Malcomson (1989), "Implicit contracts, incentve compatibility and involuntary unemployment", Econometrica 57:447-480. Maurer, J.H. (1992), "The Anglo-German naval rivalry and informal arms control, 1912-1914", Conflict Resolution 36:284-308. McCloskey, D.N. (1976), "Does the past have useful economics?", Journal of Economic Literature 14:434461. Milgrom, ER., D. NoCh and B.R. Weingast (1990), "The role of insttutions in the revival of trade: The medieval law merchant, private judges and the Champagne fairs", Economics and Politics 2:1-23. Mokyr, J., ed. (1985), The Economics of the Industrial Revoluton (Rowman and Allanheld, Totowa, NJ). Moriguchi, C. (1998), "The evolution of employment systems in the United Stares and Japan, 1900-1960: A comparative historical and institutonal analysis", Ph.D. Thesis (Stanford University). Murphy, K., A. Shleifer and R. Vishny (1989), "Industrialization and the big push", Jottrnal of Economic Perspectves 97:1003-1026. Myerson, R.B. (1984a), "Two-person bargaining problems with incomplete information", Econometrica 52:461-487. Myerson, R.B. (1984b), "Cooperative garnes with incomplete information", International Journal of Game Theory 13:69-96. Neal, L. (1990), The Rise of Fiuancial Capitalism (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Nix, J., and D. Gabel (1993), "AT&T strategic response to competition: Why not preempt entry?", Journal of Economic History 53:377-387. North, D.C. (1981), Structure and Change in Economic History (Norton, New York). North, D.C. (1990), Institutions, Institutonal Change, and Economic Performance (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). North, D.C. (1993), "An interview with Douglass C, North", The Newsletter of the Cliometric Society 8:7-12, 24-28. North, D.C., and R.E Thomas (1973), The Rise of the Western World (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). North, D.C., and B. Weingast (1989), "Constitutions and commitment: Evolution of institutions governing pubfic choice", Journal of Economic History 49:803-832. Nye, J.V. (1988), "Game theory and the North American fur trade: A cormnent", Joumal of Economic History 48:677-680.
2024
A. Greif
Porter, R.H. (1983), "A smdy of cartel stability: The joint executive committee, 1880-1886", The Bell Journal of Economics 14:301-314. Ramseyer, J.M. (1991), "Indentured prostitution in imperial Japan: Credible commitments in the commercial sex industry", Journal of Law Economic and Organization 7:89-115. Rasmusen, E. (1994), Garnes and Information, Second Edition (Basil Blackwell, Oxford). Reiter, S., and J. Hughes (1981), "A preface on modeling the regulated United Stares economy", Hofstra Law Review 9:1381-1421. Root, H.L. (1989), "Tying the king's hands: Credible commitments and royal fiscal policy during the old regime", Rationality and Society 1:240-258. Rosenthal, J.-L. (1992), The Fruits of Revolution: Property Rights, Litigation and French Agriculture, 17001860 (Cambridge University Press, Carnbridge). Rosenthal, J.-L. (1998), "The political economy of absolutism reconsidered", in: B. Bates, A. Greif, M. Levi, J.-L. Rosenthal and B. Weingast, eds., Analytic Narrative (Princeton University Press, Princeton). Rotemberg, J.J., and G. Saloner (1986), "A supergame-theoretic model of price wars during booms", American Economic Review 76:390-407. Schelling, T. (1960), The Strategy of Conflict (Harvard University Press, Cambridge). Shapiro, C., and J.E. Stiglitz (1984), "Equifibfium unemployment as a worker discipline device", American Economic Review 74:433-444. Sutton, J. (1992), Sunk Costs and Market Structure (MIT Press, Cambridge). Telser, L. (1980), "A theory of self-enforcing agreements", Journal of Business 22:27-44. Treble, J. (1990), "The pit and the pendulum: Arbitration in the British coal industry, 1893-1914", The Economic Jonrnal 100:1095-1108. Veitch, J.M. (1986), "Repudiations and confiscations by the medieval state", Jottrnal of Economic History 46:31-36. Weber, M. (1987 [1927]), General Economic History (Transaction Books, London). Translated by EH. Knight. Weiman, D.F., and R.C. Levin (1994), "Preying for monopoly? The case of Southern Bell Telephone Company, 1894-1912", Journal of Political Economy 102:103-126. Weingast, B.R. (1995), "The political foundations of limited government: Parliament and sovereign debt in 17th and 18th centuries England", in: J.N. Drobak and J. Nye, eds., Frontiers of the New Institutional Economics, Volume in Honor of Douglass C. North (Academic Press, Sah Diego). Williarnson, S.H. (1994), '"l'he history of cliometrics", in: Two Pioneers of Cfiometrics (The Cliometrics Society, Miami University, Ohio).
Chapter 53
THE SHAPLEY
VALUE
EYAL WINTER
Center for Rationality & Interactive Decision Theory, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem, Israel
Contents 1. Introduction
2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9.
The framework Simple garnes The Shapley value as a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function Alternative axiomatizafions of the value Sub-classes of garnes Cooperation structures Sustaining the Shapley value via non-cooperative garnes Practice 9.1. Measuring states' power in the U.S. presidential election 9.2. Allocation of costs
References
Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2027 2028 2030 2031 2033 2037 2039 2045 2049 2049 2051 2052
2026
E. Winter
Abstract This chapter surveys some of the literamre in game theory that has emerged from Shapley's seminal paper on the Value. The survey includes both contfibutions which offer different interpretations of the Shapley value as well as several different ways to characterize the value axiomatically. The chapter also surveys some of the literature that generalizes the nofion of the value to situations in which a priori cooperation structure exists, as well as a different literature that discusses the relation between the Shapley value and models of non-cooperative bargaining. The chapter concludes with a discussion of the applied side of the Shapley value, primarily in the context of cost allocation and voting.
Keywords Shapley value, cooperative games, coalitions, cooperation structures, voting J E L classification: C71, D72
Ch. 53:
The Shapley Value
2027
1. Introduction To promote an understanding of the importance of Shapley's (1953) paper on the value, we shall start nine years earlier with the groundbreaking book by von Neumann and Morgenstern that laid the foundations of cooperative garne theory. Unlike noncooperative garne theory, cooperative garne theory does not specify a garne through a minute description of the strategic environment, including the order of moves, the set of actions at each move, and the payoff consequences relative to all possible plays, but, instead, it reduces this collection of data to the coalitional form. The cooperative garne theorist must base his prediction strictly on the payoff opportunities, conveyed by a single real number, available to each coalition: gone are the actions, the moves, and the individual payoffs. The chief advantage of this approach, at least in multipleplayer environments, is its practical usefulness. A real-life situation fits more easily into a coalitional form garne, whose structure has proved more tractable than that of a non-cooperative garne, whether that be in normal or extensive form. Prior to the appearance of the Shapley value, one solution concept alone ruled the kingdom of (cooperative) garne theory: the von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. The core would not be defined until around the same time as the Shapley value. As set-valued solutions suggesting "reasonable" allocations of the resources of the grand coalition, the von Neumann-Morgenstern solution and the core both are based on the coalitional form garne. However, no single-point solution concept existed as of yet by which to associate a single payoff vector to a coalitional form garne. In fact the coalitional form game of those days had so little information in its black box that the creation of a single-point solution seemed untenable. It was in spite of these sharp limitations that Shapley came up with the solution. Using an axiomatic approach, Shapley constructed a solution remarkable not only for its attractive and intuitive definition but also for its unique characterization by a set of reasonable axioms. Section 2 of this chapter reviews Shapley's result, and in particular a version of it popularized in the wake of his original paper. Section 3 turns to a special case of the value for the class of voting garnes, the Shapley-Shubik index. In addition to a model that attempts to predict the allocation of resources in multiperson interactions, Shapley also viewed the value as an index for measuring the power of players in a game. Like a price index or other market indices, the value uses averages (or weighted averages in some of its generalizations) to aggregate the power of players in their various cooperation opportunities. Alternatively, one can think of the Shapley value as a measure of the utility of players in a garne. Alvin Roth took this interpretation a step further in formal terms by presenting the value as a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function. Roth's result is discussed in Section 4. Section 5 is devoted to alternative axiomatic characterizations of the Shapley value, with particular emphasis on Young's axiom of monotonicity, Hart and Mas-Colell's axiom of consistency, and the last-named pair's notion of potential (arguably a singleaxiom characterization).
E. Winter
2028
To be able to apply the Shapley value to concrete problems such as voting situations, it is important to be able to characterize it on sub-classes of garnes. Section 6 discusses several approaches in that direction. Section 7 surveys several attempts to generalize the Shapley value to a framework in which the environment is described by some a priori cooperation structure other than the coalitional form garne (typically a partition of the set of players). Aumann and Drèze (1975) and Owen (1977) pioneered examples of such generalizations. While the Shapley value is a classic cooperative solution concept, it has been shown to be sustained by some interesting strategic (bargaining) garnes. Section 8 looks at some of these results. Section 9 closes the chapter with a discussion of the practical importance of the Shapley value in general, and of its role as an estimate of parliamentary and voter power and as a rule for cost allocation in particular. Space forbids discussion of the vast literature inspired by Shapley's paper. Certain of these topics, such as the various extensions of the value to NTU garnes, and the values of non-atornic garnes to emerge from the seminal book by Aumann and Shapley (1974), are treated in other chapters of this Handbook.
2. The framework Recall that a coalitionalform game (henceforth game) on a finite set of players N = {1, 2, 3 . . . . , n} is a function v from the set of all coalitions 2 N to the set of real numbers R with v(0) = 0. v(S) represents the total payoff or rent the coalition S can get in the garne v. A value is an operator ~b that assigns to each garne v a vector of payoffs q5(v) = (~bl, (b2 ..... ~ßn) in IRn. q~i(v) stands for i's payoff in the garne, or altematively for the measure of i's power in the game. Shapley presented the value as an operator that assigns an expected marginal contribution to each player in the garne with respect to a uniform distribution over the set of all permutations on the set of players. Specifically, letzr be a permutation (or an order) on the set of players, i.e., a one-to-one function from N onto N, and let us imagine the players appearing one by one to collect their payoff according to the order fr. For each player i we can denote by pi7E = {j: 7r(i) > 7c(j)} the set of players preceding player i in the order re. The marginal contribution of player i with respect to that order rc is v(p i U i) - v ( p i ) . Now, if permutations are randomly chosen from the set/7 of all permutations, with equal probability for each one of the n ! permutations, then the average marginal contribution of player i in the garne v is
cki(v) = l/n! ~_ù [v (p~Ui i ) - v ( p i ) ] , 7cE/7
which is Shapley's definition of the value.
(1)
Ch. 53:
The Shapley Value
2029
While the intuitive definition of the value speaks for itself, Shapley supported it by an elegant axiomatic characterization. We now impose four axioms to be satisfied by a value: The first axiom requires that players precisely distribute among themselves the resources available to the grand coalition. Namely, EFFICIENCY. Y~'iöN q~i(V) = v ( N ) .
The second axiom requires the following notion of symmetry: Players i, j c N are said to be symmetric with respect to garne v if they make the same marginal contribution to any coalition, i.e., for each S C N with i, j ~ S, v(S U i) = v(S U j). The symmetry axiom requires symmetric players to be paid equal shares. SYMMETRY. l f players i and j are symmetric with respect to garne v, then qbi (V) =
4~j(v). The third axiom requires that zero payoffs be assigned to players whose marginal contribution is null with respect to every coalition: DUMMY. If i is a dummy player, i.e., v(S U i) - v(S) = 0 for every S C N, then
4~i (v) = O. Finally, we require that the value be an additive operator on the space of all garnes, i.e., ADDITIVITY. (b(v + to) = ~b(v) + ~(w), where the garne v + w is defined by (v +
w)(S) -~ v(S) + w(S) f o r all S. Shapley's amazing result consisted in the fact that the four simple axioms defined above characterize a value uniquely: THEOREM 1 [Shapley (1953)]. There exists a unique value satisfying the efficiency, symmetry, dummy, and additivity axioms: it is the Shapley value given in Equation (1). The uniqueness result follows from the fact that the class of games with n players forms a 2 n- 1-dimensional vector space in which the set of unanimity garnes constitutes a basis. A garne uR is said to be a unanimity garne on the domain R if un(S) -= 1, whenever R C S and 0 otherwise. It is clear that the dummy and symmetry axioms together yield a value that is uniquely determined on unanimity garnes (each player in the domain should receive an equal share of 1 and the others 0). Combined with the additivity axiom and the fact that the unanimity games constitute a basis for the vector space of garnes, this yields the uniqueness result.
2030
E. Winter
Here it should be noted that Shapley's original formulation was somewhat different from the one described above. Shapley was concerned with the space of all games that can be played by some large set of potential players U, called the universe. For every game v, which assigns a real number to every finite subset of U, a carrier N is a subset of U such that v(S) = v(S M N) for every S C U. Hence, the set of players who actually participate in the game must be contained in any carrier of the garne. If for some carrier N a player i is not in N, then i must be a dummy player because he does not affect the payoff of any coalition that he joins. Shapley imposed the carrier axiom onto this framework, which requires that within any carrier N of the garne the players in N share the total payoff of v (N) among themselves, lnterestingly, this axiom bundles the efficiency axiom and the dummy axiom into one property.
3. Simple games Some of the most exciting applications of the Shapley value involve the measurement of political power. The reason why the value lends itself so well to this domain of problems is that in many of these applications it is easy to identify the real-life environment with a specific coalitional form game. In politics, indeed in all voting situations, the power of a coalition comes down to the question of whether it can impose a certain collective decision, or, in a typical application, whether it possesses the necessary majority to pass a bill. Such situations can be represented by a collection of coalitions W (a subset of 2N), where W stands for the set of "winning" coalitions, i.e., coalitions with enough power to impose a decision collectively. We call these situations "simple garnes". While simple garnes can get rather complex, their coalitional function v assumes only two values: 1 for winning coalitions and 0 otherwise (see Chapter 36 in this Handbook). If we assume monotonicity, i.e., that a superset of a winning coalition is likewise winning, then the players' marginal contributions to coalitions in such garnes also assume the values 0 and 1. Specifically, player i's marginal contribution to coalition S is 1 if by joining S player i can turn the coalition from a non-winning (or losing) to a winning coalition. In such cases, we can say that player i is pivotal to coalition S. Recalling the definition of the Shapley value, it is easy to see that in such garnes the value assigns to each player the probability of being pivotal with respect to his predecessors, where orders are sampled randomly and with equal probability. Specifically,
d?i(v) = [{rc E 17; p i Ui ~ W a n d p / ¢ w } l / n ! . This special case of the Shapley value is known in the literature as the Shapley-Shubik index for simple games [Shapley and Shubik (1954)]. A very interesting interpretation of the Shapley-Shubik index in the context of voting was proposed by Straffin (1977). Consider a simple (voting) garne with a set of winning coalitions W representing the distribution of power within a committee, say a parliament. Suppose that on the agenda are several bills on which players take positions. Let
Ch. 53:
The Shapley Value
2031
us take an ex a n t e point of view (before knowing which bill will be discussed) by assuming that the probability of each player voting in favor of the bill is p (independent over i). Suppose that a player is asking himself what the probability is that his vote will affect the outcome. Put differently, what is the probability thät the bill will pass if and only if I support it? The answer to this question depends on p (as well as the distribution of power W). If p is 1 or 0, then I will have no effect unless I am a dictator. But because we do not know which bill is next on the agenda, it is reasonable to assume that p itself is a random variable. Specifically, let us assume that p is distrihuted uniformly on the interval [0, 1]. Straffin points out that with this model for random bills the probability that a player is effective is equivalent to his Shapley-Shubik index in the corresponding garne (see Chapter 32 in this Handbook). We shall demonstrate this with an example. EXAMPLE. Let [3; 2, 1, 1] be a weighted majority garne, 1 where the minimal winning coalitions are {1, 2} and {1,3 }. Player 2 is effective only if player 1 votes for and player 3 votes against. For a given probability p of acceptance, this occurs with probability p (1 p). Since 2 and 3 are symmetric, the same holds for player 3. Now player l's vote is ineffective only if 2 and 3 both vote against, which happens with probability (1 - p)2. Thus player I is effective with probability 2p - p2. Integrating these functions between 0 and 1 yields q~l = 2/3, ~b2 = ~b3 = 1/6. It is interesting to note that with a different probability model for bills one can derive a different well-known power index, namely the Banzhaf index (see Chapter 32 in this Handbook). Specifically, if player k's probability of accepting the bill is Ph, and if p l . . . . . Pn are chosen independently, each from a uniform distribution on [0, 1], then player i's probability of being effective coincides with his Banzhaf index.
4. The Shapley value as a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function If we interpret the Shapley value as a measure of the benefit of "playing" the garne (as was indeed suggested by Shapley himself in his original paper), then it is reasonable to think of different positions in a garne as objects for which individuals have preferences. Such an interpretation immediately gives rise to the following question: What properties should these preferences possess so that the cardinal utility function that represents them coincides with the Shapley value? This question is answered by Roth (1977). Roth defined a position in a garne as a pair (i, v), where i is a player and v is a garne. He then assumed that individuals have preferences defined on the mixture set M that contains all positions and lotteries whose outcomes are positions. Using " ~ " to denote indifference and ">-" to denote strict preference, Roth imposed several properties on preferences. The first two properties are simple regularity conditions:
1 In a weighted majority garne [q; wI . . . . . ton], a coalition S is winning if and ordy i f EiES Wi ~ q"
2032
E. Winter
A1. Let v be a garne in which i is a dummy. Then (i, v) ~ (i, vo), where vo is the null garne in which every coalition earns zero. Furthermore, (i, vi) >- (i, vo), where vi is the game in which i is a dictator, i.e., vi ( S) -= 1 if i ~ S and vi ( S) = 0 otherwise. The second property, which relates to Shapley's symmetry axiom, requires that individual preferences not depend on the names of positions, i.e., A2. For any garne v and permutation yr, (i, v) ~ (yr(i),
7g(l))). 2
The two remaining properties are more substantial and deal with players' attitudes towards risk. The first of these properties requires that the certainty equivalent of a lottery that yields the position i in either garne v o r game w (with probabilities p and 1 p) be the position i in the garne given by the expected value of the coalitional function with respect to the same probabilities. Specifically, for two positions (i, v) and (i, w), we denote by Ip(i, v); (1 - p)(i, w)] the lottery where (i, v) occurs with probability p and (i, w) occurs with probability 1 - p. A3. Neutrality to Ordinary Risk: (i, ( p w + (1 - p ) v ) ) ~ [p(i, w); (1 - p)(i, v)]. Note that a weaker version of this property requires that (i, v) ~ [(1/c)(i, cv); (1 1/c)(i, v0)] for c > 1. It can be shown that this property implies that the utility function u, which represents the preferences over positions in a garne, taust satisfy u(cv, i) = cu(v, i). The last property asserts that in a unanimity game with a carrier of r players the utility of a uon-dummy player is 1 / r of the utility of a dictator. Specifically, let vR be defined by VR (S) = 1 if R C S and 0 otherwise. A4. Neutrality to Strategic Risk: (i, VR) ~ (i, ( 1 / r ) v i ) . An elegant result now asserts that: THEOREM [Roth (1977)]. Let u be a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function over positions in garnes, which represents preferences satisfying the f o u r axioms. Suppose that u is normalized so that u(i, vi) = 1 and ui (i, vo) = O. Then u(i, v) is the Shapley value of player i in the garne v. Roth's result can be viewed as an alternative axiomatization of the Shapley value. I will now survey several other chm'acterizations of the value, which, unlike Roth's utility function, employ the standard concept of a payoff function.
2 fr(v) is the garne with yr(v)(S) = v(re(S)), where re(S) = {j; j = re(i) for some i 6 S}.
Ch. 53: The Shapley Value
2033
5. Alternative axiomatizations of the value One of the most elegant aspects of the axiomatic approach in game theory is that the same solution concept can be characterized by very different sets of axioms, sometimes to the point of seeming unrelated. But just as a sculpture seen from different angles is understood in greater depth, so is a solution concept by means of different axiomafizations, and in this respect the Shapley value is no exception. This section examines several alternative axiomatic treatments of the value. Perhaps the most appealing property to result from Definition (1) of the Shapley value is that a player's payoff is only a function of the vector of bis marginal contributions to the various coalitions. This raises an interesting quesfion: Without forgoing the above property, how far can we depart from the Shapley value? "Not much", according to Young (l 985), whose finding also yields an alternative axiomatization of the value. For a garne v, a coalition S, and a player i ¢ S, we denote by Di (v, S) player i's marginal contribution to the coalition S with respect to the garne v, i.e., D i (v, S) = v(S U i) - v(S). Young introduced the following axiom: STRONG MONOTONICITY. Suppose that v and w are two games such that f o r some i c N Di (v, S) >/Di (w, S). Then cBi(v) ». ~)i (W).
Young then showed that this property plays a central role in the characterization of the Shapley value. Specifically, THEOREM [Young (1985)]. There exists a unique value Ó satisfying strong monotonicity, symmetry, and efficiency, namely the ShapIey value. Note that Young's strong monotonicity axiom implies the marginality axiom, which asserts that the value of each player is only a fnnction of that player's vector of marginal contributions. Young's axiomatic characterization of the value thus supports the claim that the Shapley value to some extent is a synonym for the principle of marginal contribution - a time-honored principle in economic theory. But we taust be clear about what is meant by marginal contribution. In Young's framework, as in Shapley's definition of the value, players contribnte by increasing the wealth of the coalition they join (or decreasing it if contributions are negative). This caused Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) to ask the following question: Can the Shapley value be derived by referring the players' marginal contributions to the wealth generated by the entire multilateral interaction, instead of tediously listing all the coalitions they can join? Offhand, the question sounds somewhat amorphous, for how is one to define an "entire interaction"? Absent a satisfactory definition, we shall proceed by way of supposition. Suppose each pair (N, v) is associated with a single real number P ( N , v) that sums up the wealth generated by the entire interaction in the game. We are already within an ace of defining marginal contributions. Specifically, player i's marginal contribution with respect to (N, v) is simply: Dip(N,v)
= P(N,v)-
P(N \i,v),
2034
E. Winter
where (N \ i, v) is the game v restricted to the set of players N \ i. To be associated with a measure of power in the game, these marginal contributions need to add up to the total resources available to the grand coalitions, i.e., v(N). So we will say that P is a potential function if
Z
Di P(N, v) = v(N).
(2)
lEN
Moreover, we normalize P to satisfy P(0, v) = 0. Given the mild requirement on p, there seems to be enough flexibility for many potential functions to exist. The remarkable result of Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) is that there is in fact only orte potential function, and it is closely related to the Shapley value. Specifically, THEOREM [Hart and Mas-Colell (1989)]. There exists a unique potential func-
tion P. Moreover, the corresponding vector of marginal contributions ( D I p ( N, v) . . . . . D n P(N, v)) coincides with the Shapley value of the garne (N, v). Let us note that by rewrifing Equation (2) we obtain the following recursive equation:
P(N, v ) = (1/INI)Iv(N) + ~-~ P(N \ i, v)].
(3)
icN
Starting with P(0, v) = 0, Equation (3) determines p recursively. It is interesting to note that the potential is related to the notion of "dividends" used by Harsanyi (1963) to extend the Shapley value to garnes without transferable utility. Specifically, let ~ T c N aTur be the (unique) representation of the game (N, v) as a linear combination of unanimity games. In any unanimity garne u r on the carrier T, the value of each player in T is the "dividend" dT = ar/[TI, and the Shapley value of player i in the game (N, v) is the sum of dividends that a player eams from all coalitions of which he is a member, i.e., ~ ( T ; i e r / d r . Given the definition and uniqueness of the potential funcfion, it follows that P(N, v) = Y~~TdT, i.e., the total Harsanyi dividends across all coalitions in the game. One can view Hart and Mas-CoMl's result as a concise axiomatic characterization of the Shapley value - indeed, one that builds on a single axiom. In the same paper, Hart and Mas-Colell propose another axiomatization of the value by a different but related approach based on the notion of consistency. Unlike in non-cooperative game theory, where the feasibility of a solution concept is judged according to strategic or optimal individual behavior, in cooperative garne theory neither strategies nor individual payoffs are specified. A cooperative solution concept is considered attractive if it makes sense as an arbitration scheme for allocating costs or benefits. It comes as no surprise, then, that some of the popular properties used to support solution concepts in this field are normative in nature. The symmetry axiom is a case in point. It asserts that individuals indistinguishable in terms of their contributions
Ch. 53:
2035
The Shapley Value
to coalitions are to be treated equally. One of the most fundamental requirements of any legal system is that it be internally consistent. Consider some value (a single-point solution concept) ~b, which we would like to use as a scheme for allocating payoffs in games. Suppose that we implement q~ by first making payment to a group of players Z. Examining the environment subsequent to payment, we may realize that we are facing a different (reduced) garne defined on the remaining players N \ Z who are still waiting to be paid. The solution concept q~ is said to be consistent if it yields the players in the reduced game exactly the same payoffs they are getting in the original garne. Consistency properties play an important role in the literature of cooperative game theory. They were used in the context of the Shapley value by Hart and Mas-Colell (1989). The difference between Hart and Mas-Colell's notion of consistency and that of the related literature on other solution concepts lies in their definition of reduced garne. For a given value qS, a garne (N, v), and a coalition T, the reduced garne (T, v r ) on the set of players T is defined as follows: vr (S) = v (S U T «) - ~
q~i(v Isur«)
for every S C T,
iŒTc
where VIR denotes the garne v restricted to the coalition R. The worth of coalition S in the reduced garne Vr is derived as follows. First, the players in S consider their options outside T, i.e., by playing the garne only with the complementary coalition T c. This restricts the game v to coalition S U T c. In this game the total payoff of the members of T c according to the solution Ó is ~ i c T c ~)i (U[SUT «). Thus the resources left available for the members of S to allocate among themselves are precisely VT ( S). A value Ó is now said to be consistent if for every garne (N, v), every coalition T, and every i c T, one has ~bi (T, Vr) = Ói (N, v). Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) show that with two additional standard axioms the consistency property characterizes the Shapley value. Specifically, THEOREM [Hart and Mas-Colell (1989)]. There exists a unique value satisfying symmetry, efficiency and consistency, namely the Shapley value. 3 It is interesting to note that by replacing Hart and Mas-Colell's property with a different consistency property one obtains a characterization of a different solution concept, namely the pre-nucleolus. Sobolev's (1975) consistency property is based on the following definition of the reduced garne:
~,~,~~ Qmùx E~~~~,~ iEQ ~~,,~~ ] ~f,~~ ~ cN\T 3 Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) in fact showedthat instead of the efficiencyand symmetryaxioms it is enough to require that the solution be "standard" for two-person games, i.e., that for such garnes ~bi ({i, j}, v) = v(i) + (1/2)[v({i, j}) - v(i) - v(j)].
2036
E. W i n ~ r
v~(S)=~¢i(v)
ifS=T,
and
v~(S)=0
ifS=0.
iET
Note that in Sobolev's definition the members of S evaluate their power in the reduced garne by considering their most attractive options outside T. Furthermore, the collaborators of S outside T are paid according to their share in the original game v (and not according to the restricted game as in Hart and Mas-Colell's property). It is surprising that while the definifions of the Shapley value and the pre-nucleolus differ completely, their axiomatic characterizations differ only in terms of the reduced game on which the consistency property is based. This nicely demonstrates the strength of the axiomatic approach in cooperative garne theory, which not only sheds light on individual solution concepts, but at the same time exposes their underlying relationships. Hart and Mas-Colell's consistency property is also related to the "balanced contributions" property due to Myerson (1977). Roughly speaking, this property requires that player i contribute to player j ' s payoff what player j contributes to player i's payoff. Formally, the property can be written as follows: BALANCED CONTRIBUTION. For every two players i and j, ~i(v)
-
~i(VIN\j)
:
¢ j (v) -- ~oj (VIN\j).
Myerson (1977) introduced a value that associates a payoff vector with each game v and graph g on the set N (representing communication channels between players). His result implies that the balanced contributions property, the efficiency axiom, and the symmetry axiom characterize the Shapley value. We will close this section by discussing another axiomatization of the value, proposed by Chun (1989). It employs an interesting property which generalizes the strategic equivalence property traceable to von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944). Chun's coalitional strategic equivalence property requires that if we change the coalitional form garne by adding a constant to every coalition that contains some (fixed) coalifion T C N, then the payoffs to players outside S will not change. This means that the extra benefit (or loss if the added constant is negative) accrues only to the members of T. Formally: COALITIONAL STRATEGIC EQUIVALENCE. F o r all T C N and a c R, let w aT be the garne defined by wä ( S) = a if T C S and 0 otherwise. For all T C N and a E R, if v = w + wä, then d?i (v) = (ai (w) for all i E N \ T.
Von Neumann and Morgenstern's strategic equivalence imposes the same requirement, but only for IT1 =- 1. Another similar property proposed by Chun is fair ranking. It requires that if the underlying game changes in such a way that all coalitions but T maintain the same worth, then although the payoffs of members of T will vary, the ranking of the payoffs within T will be preserved. This directly reflects the idea that the ranking of players' payoffs within a coalition depends solely on the outside opfions of their members. Specifically:
Ch. 53: The Shapley Value
2037
FAIR RANKING. Suppose that v(S) = w ( S ) f o r every S ~ T; then f o r all i, j c T, fbi(v) > dpj(v) if and only if ~bi(w) > qSj(w). To characterize the Shapley value an additional harmless axiom is needed. TRIVIALITY. If VO is the constant zero garne, i.e., vo(S) = 0 f o r all S C N, then dpi(vo) : Of o r all i E N. The following characterization of the Shapley value can now be obtained: THEOREM [Chun (1989)]. The Shapley value is the unique value satisfying efficiency, triviality, coalitional strategic equivalence, and fair ranking.
6. Sub-classes ofgames Much of the Shapley value's attractiveness derives from its elegant axiomatic characterization. But while Shapley's axioms characterize the value uniquely on the class of all games, it is not clear whether they can be used to characterize the value on subspaces. It sounds puzzling, for what could go wrong? The fact that a value satisfies a certain set of axioms trivially implies that it satisfies those axioms on every subclass of games. However, the smallem the subclass, the less likely these axiorns are to determine a unique value on it. To illustrate an extreme case of the problem, suppose that the subclass consists of all integer multiples of a single garne v with no d u m m y players, and no two players are symmetric. On this subclass Shapley's symmetry and dummy axioms are vacuous: they impose no restriction on the payoff function. It is therefore easy to verify that any allocation of v ( N ) can be supported as the payoff vector for v with respect to a value on this subclass that satisfies all Shapley's axioms. Another problem that can arise when considering subclasses of garnes is that they may not be closed under operations that are required by some of the axioms. A classic example of this is the class of all simple games. It is clear that the additivity axiom cannot be used on such a class, because the sum of two simple garnes is typically not a simple garne anymore. One can revise the additivity axiom by requiring that it apply only when the sum of the two garnes falls within the subclass considered. Indeed, Dubey (1975) shows that with this amendment to the additivity4 axiom, Shapley's original p r o o f of uniqueness still applies to some subclasses of garnes, including the class o f all simple garnes. However, even in conjunction with the other standard axioms, this axiom does not yield uniqueness in the class of all monotonic 5 simple garnes. To redress this problem, Dubey (1975) introduced an axiom that can replace additivity: for two simple garnes v and v/, we define
4 Specifically, one has to require the axiom only for garnes vi, v2 whose sum belongs to the underlying subclass. 5 Recall that a simple garne v is said to be monotonic if v(S) = 1 and S C T implies v(T) = 1.
2038
E. Winter
by min{v, v'} the simple game in which S is winning if and only if it is winning in both v and v r. Similarly, we define by max{v, v r } the game in which S is winning if and only if it is winning in at least one of the two games v and v r. Dubey imposed the property of MODULARITY. 4ffmin{v, vr}) + qS(max{v, vr}) = q~(v) + ~b(vr).
One can interpret this axiom within the framework of Roth's model in Section 3. Suppose that ~bi (v) stands for the utility of playing i's position in the game v, and player i is facing two lotteries. In the first lottery he will participate in either the game v or the garne v r with equal probabilities. The other lottery involves two more "extreme" garnes: max{v, vr}, which makes winning easier than with v and v r, and min{v, vr}, which makes winning harder. As before, each of these garnes will be realized with probability 1/2. Modularity imposes that each player be "risk neutral" in the sense that he be indifferent between these two lotteries. Note that min{v, v r } and max{v, v r} are monotonic simple garnes whenever v and v r are, so we do not need any conditioning in the formulation of the axiom. Dubey characterized the Shapley value on the class of monotonic simple games by means of the modularity axiom, showing that: THEOREM [Dubey (1975)]. There exists a unique value on the class of monotonic 6 simple garnes satisfying efficiency, symmetry, dummy, and modularity, and it is the ShapleyShubik value. When trying to apply a solution concept to a specific allocation problem (or game), one may find it hard to justify the Shapley value on the basis of its axiomatic characterization. After all, an axiom like additivity deals with how the value varies as a result of changes in the garne, taking into account games which may be completely irrelevant to the underlying problem. The story is different insofar as Shapley's other axioms are concerned, because the three of them impose requirements only on the specific game under consideration. Unformnately, one cannot fully characterize the Shapley value by axioms of the second type only 7 (save perhaps by imposing the value formula as an axiom). Indeed, if we were able to do so, it would mean that we could axiomatically characterize the value on subclasses as small as a single garne. While this is impossible, Neyman (1989) showed that Shapley's original axioms characterize the value on the additive class (group) spanned by a single garne. Specifically, for a garne v let G(v) denote the class of all games obtained by a linear combination of restricted garnes of v, i.e., G(v) = {v r s.t. v r = ~ i kivIsi, where ki are integers and vlsi is the game v restricted to the coalition Si }. 6 The sarne result was shownby Dubey (1975) to hold for the class of superadditive simple games. 7 A similar distinction can be made within the axiomatization of the Nash solution where the symmetryand efficiency axioms are "within garnes" while IIA and Invarianceare "between garnes".
Ch. 53: The Shapley Value
2039
Note that by definition the class G(v) is closed under sumrnation of games, which makes the additivity axiom well defined on this class. Neyman shows that: THEOREM [Neyman (1989)]. For an 3, v there exists a unique value on the subclass G(v) satisfying efficiency, symmetry, dummy, and additivity, namely the Shapley value. It is worth noting that Hart and Mas-Colel1's (1989) notion of Potential also characterizes the Shapley value on the subclass G(v), since the Potential is defined on restricted garnes only.
7. Cooperation structures One of Shapley's axioms which characterize the value is the symmetry axiom. It requires that a player's value in a garne depend on nothing but his payoff opportunities as described by the coalitional form garne, and in particular not on the his "name". Indeed, as we argued earlier, the possibility of constructing a unique measure of power axiomatically from very limited information about the interactive environment is doubtless one of the value's most appealing aspects. For some specific applications, however, we might possess more information about the environment than just the coalitional form garne. Should we ignore this additional information when attempting to measure the relative power of players in a garne? One source of asymmetry in the environment can follow simply from the fact thät players differ in their bargaining skills or in their property rights. This interpretation led to the concept of the weighted Shapley value by Shapley (1953) and Kalai and Samet (1985) (see Chapter 54 in this Handbook). But asymmetry can derive from a completely different source. It can be due to the fact that the interaction between players is not symmetric, as happens when some players are organized into groups or when the communication structure between players is incomplete, thus making it difficult if not impossible for some players to negotiate with others. This interpretation has led to an interesting field of research on the Shapley value, which is mainly concerned with generalizations. The earliest result in this field is probably due to Aumann and Drèze (1975), who consider situations in which there exists an exogenous coalition structure in addition to the coalitional form garne. A coalition structure B = (& . . . . . Sm) is simply a partition of the set ofplayers N, i.e., [_J Sj = N and Si f) Sj = 0 for i ¢ j. In this context a value is an operator that assigns a vector of payoffs ~b(B, v) to each pair (B, v), i.e., a coalition structure and a coalitional form garne on N. Aumann and Drèze (1975) imposed the following axioms on such operators. First, the efficiency axiom is based on the idea that by forming a group, players can allocate to themselves only the resources available to their group. Specifically, RELATIVE EFFICIENCY. For every coalition structure B = (S1 . . . . , Sm) and 1 <~k <~ m, we have ~ j ~ & qSj(B, v) = v(Sk).
2040
E. Winter
The remaining three axioms are straightforward extensions of their counterparts in the benchmark model. SYMMETRY, For every permutation ~ on N and every coalition structure B, we have O(rc B, ~rv) = Jvqb(B, v), where Jv B is the coalition structure with (~r B)i = rr Si.
DUMMY. I f i is a dummy player in v, then Ói (B, v) = 0 for all B. ADDITIVITY. qb(B, v + w) = O(B, v) q- ~)(B, to) for all B and any pair of games v and w. Aumann and Drèze showed that the above axioms characterize a value uniquely. This value assigns the Shapley value to each player in the garne restricted to bis group. Specifically, for each coalition S and garne v, we define by v] S the garne on S given by (v]s)(T) ----v(T) for all T C S. We now have: THEOREM [Aumann and Drèze (1975)]. For a given set of players N and a coalition structure B, there exists a unique B-value satisfying the four above axioms, nameIy Ói (B, 1)) = ~i (riß(i)), where B(i) denotes the component of B that includes player i, and Ó stands f o r the Shapley value. Aumann and Drèze then defined the coalition structure of all the major solution concepts in cooperative game theory, in addition to the Shapley value. In so doing they exposed a startling property of consistency satisfied by all but orte of them. The Shapley value is the exception. Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) would later show that the Shapley value satisfies a version of this property (discussed earlier in Section 5). In Aumann and Drèze's fi'amework, the coalition structure can be thought of as representing contractual relationships that affect players' property rights over resources, i.e., players in S c B "own" a total resource v(S), from which transfers to players outside S are forbidden. This is apparent from both the definition and the efficiency axiom that depends on the coalition structure. Roughly speaking, players from orte component of the partition cannot share benefits with any player from another component. But in real life coalition formation often takes place merely for strategic reasons without affecting the fundamentals of the economy. A group may form in order to pressure another group, or to enhance the bargaining position of its members vis-ä-vis other members without affecting the constraint that all players in N share the total pie v(N). It is thus reasonable to ask whether it is possible to extend the Shapley value to this context as well. Owen (1977), Hart and Kurz (1983), and Winter (1989, 1991, 1992) take up this question. Owen proposed a value, like the Shapley value, in which each player receives his expected marginal contribution to coalitions with respect to a random order of players. But while the Shapley value assumes that all orders are of equal probability, the Owen value restricts orders according to the coalition structure. Specifically, for a given coalition strucmre B, let us consider a subset of the set of all orders, which includes only
Ch. 53: The Shapley Value
2041
the orders in which players of the same component of B appear successively. Denote this set of orders 17(B). The set of orders FI(B) can be obtained by first ordering the components of B and then ordering players within each component of the partition. According to the Owen value, each player is assigned an expected marginal contribution to the coalition of preceding players with respect to a uniform distribution over the set of orders i n / 7 ( B ) , More formally, let B = (S1 . . . . . Sm) be a coalition structure. Set FI(B) = {zr 6 / 7 ; if i, j E Sk and zr(i) < re(r) < 7r(j), then r c Sk}, which is the set of all permutations consistent with the coalition structure B. The Owen value of player i in the garne v with the coalition structure B is now given by
c~i(B,v)=(1/[/7(B)l)
~ [v(p i U i ) - v ( p i ) ] . ~rcFI(B)
Note that the Owen value satisfies efficiency with respect to the grand coalition, i.e., the total payoff across all players is v(N). This is due to the fact that the total marginal contribution of all players with respect to a fixed order sums up to precisely v(N). Like the Shapley value, the Owen value can be characterized axiomatically in more than orte way, including the way proposed by Owen himself and that of Hart and Kurz (1983). We will introduce here orte version that was used in Winter (1989) for the characterization of level structure values, which generalize the Owen value. First note that for a given coalition structure B = ($1 . . . . . Sm) and garne v, we can define a "garne between coalitions" in which each coalition Si acts as a player. A coalition acting as a player will be denoted by [Si]. Specifically, the worth of the coalition { [ S / l ] . . . . . [Sik]} is v(Sil U S i 2 , . . , USik). We will denote this garne by v*. We now impose two symmetry axioms: SYMMETRY A«ROSS COALITIONS. If players [Sk] and [Sl] are symmetric in the game v*, then the total values for these coalitions are equal, i.e., ~ s l ~bj(B, v) =
~sk ~J (8, v). SYMMETRY WITHIN COALITIONS. For any two players i and j who are symmetric in v and belong to the same coalition in B, i.e., i, j E Sk c B, we have Oi(B, v) -=
O«(B, v). We recall that the Owen value satisfies: EFFICIENCY. ~ i c N qSi(B, v) = v(N). With the above axioms we now have: THEOREM [Owen (1977)]. For a given set of players N and a coalition structure B, the Owen value is the unique B-value satisfying symmetry across coalitions, symmetry within coalitions, dummy, additivity, and efficiency.
2042
E. Winter
Hart and Kurz (1983) formulated a different axiom which can be used to characterize the Owen value requiring that: INESSENTIAL GAMES AMONG COALITIONS. If v(N) = ~ k v(Sk), then for all k we have ~ j ~ s k c~j(B, v) = v(Sk). Hart and Kurz (1983) show that this axiom together with symmetry, additivity, and a carrier axiom combining dummy and efficiency yield a characterization of the Owen value. Hart and Kurz also used the Owen value to model processes of coalition formation. Other papers take the Owen value as a starting-point either to suggest alternative axiomatizations or to develop further generalizations. Winter (1992) used the consistency and the potential approach to characterize the Owen value. Calvo, Lasaga, and Winter (1996) used Myerson's approach of balanced contributions for another axiomatization of the Owen value. In Owen and Winter (1992), the multilinear extension approach [see Owen (1972)] was used to propose an alternative interpretation of the Owen value based on a model of random coalitions. Finally, Winter (1991) proposed a general solution concept, special cases of which are the Harsanyi (1963) solution on standard NTU garnes and the Owen value for TU garnes with coalition structures (as well as other non-symmetric generalizations of the Shapley value). As argued earlier, there is an intrinsic difference between Aumann and Drèze's interpretation of coalition structures and that of Owen. Thinking of coalition structures as unions or clubs, which define an asymmetric "closeness" relation between the various individuals, suggests several alternatives for introducing cooperation structures into the Shapley value ffamework. One such approach was proposed by Myerson (1977), who used graphs to represent cooperäfion structures between players. This important paper is discussed thoronghly in Monderer and Samet (see Chapter 54 in this Handbook). Another approach that is closer to Owen's (and indeed generalizes it) was analyzed by Winter (1989). Here cooperation is descfibed by the notion of (hierarchical) level structures. Formally, a level strucmre is a finite sequence of partitions B = (B1, B2 . . . . . Bin) such that Bi is a refinement of Bi+ 1. That is, if S ~ Bi, then S C T for some T ~ Bi+i. The idea behind level structure is that individuals inherit connections to other individuals by association to groups with various levels of commitment. In the context of international trade, one can think of Bm (the coarsest partition) as represenfing ffee trade agreements within, say, Nafta, the European Union, Mercusor, etc. Each bloc in this coalifion strucmre is partifioned into countries, each country into federal states or regions, and so on down to the elementary units of households, In order to define the extension of the Owen value within this framework, we adopt the interpretation that the partition B j represents a stronger connecfion between players than that of the coarser Bk where k > j. Ler us think of a permutafion as the order by which players appear to collect their payoffs. To make payoffs dependent on the cooperation structure, we restrict ourselves to orders in which no player i follows player j if
Ch. 53: The Shapley Value
2043
there is another player, say k, who is "closer" to player i and who has still not appeared. Formally, we can construct this set of orders inductively as follows: For a given level structure B = (B1 . . . . . Bin), define Hm
~
{re E/7; for each l, j E S ~ Bm and i E N, re(l) < re(i) < re(j) implies i E S}
and /Tr = {re 6 H r + l ; for each l, j E S e Br and i E N, re(1) < re(i) < re(j) implies i 6 S}. The proposed value gives an expected marginal contribution to each player with respect to the uniform distribution over all the orders that are consistent with the level structure B, i.e., the orders in/71. Specifically, (gi(B, v) = (1/I/71l) ~
[1)(pi U i ) -
v(p~r)].i
(4)
rc~/71
Note that when the level structure consists of only one partition (i.e., m = 1), we are back in Owen's framework. Moreover, in contrast to the special case of Owen, in which there is only one garne between coalitions, this framework gives rise to m garnes between coalitions, one for each hierarchy level (partition). We denote these games by V 1 , 1)2 . . . . . Vm . The following axiom is an extension of the axiom of syrnmetry across coalitions that we defined earlier in relation to the Owen value. COALITIONAL SYMMETRY. Ler B = ( B 1 , . . . , Bin) be a level structure. For each level 1 <~ i <~ m, if S, T E Bi are symmetric as players ([S] and [T]) in the game v i and if S and T are subsets o f the same component in Bj f o r all j > i, then ~ r ~ S Or (B, v) = ~ r ö T ~r (B, 1)). In order to axiomatize the level structure value, we need another symmetry axiom that requires equal treatment for symmetric players within the sarne coalition: SYMMETRY WITHIN COALITIONS. Irk and j are two symmetric players with respect to the garne v, where f o r every level 1 <~i <~m, and any non-singleton coalition S E BI, then k E S iff j E S, and 4)i(B, v) -=qSj(B, v).
Using straightforward gerleralizations of the rest of the axioms of the Owen value, it can be shown that: THEOREM [Winter (1989)]. There exists a unique level structure value satisfying coalitional symmetry, symmetry within coalitions, dummy, additivity, and efficiency. This value is given by (4).
2044
E. Winter
Several other approaches to cooperation structures have been proposed. We have already mentioned Myerson (1977), who uses a graph to represent bilateral connections (of communications) between individuals. An interesting application of Myerson's solution was proposed by Aumann and Myerson (1988). They considered an extensive form game in which players propose links to other players, sequentially. Using the Myerson value to represent the players' returns from each graph that forms, they analyze the endogenous graphs that form (given by the subgame perfect equilibria of the link formation garne). Myerson (1980) discusses conference structures that are given formally by an arbitrary collection of coalitions representing a (possibly non-partitional) set of associations to which individuals belong. Derks and Peters (1993) consider a version of the Shapley value with restricted coalitions, representing a set of cooperation constraints. These are given by a mapping p : 2 N --+ 2 N, such that (1) p ( S ) C S, (2) S C T implies p ( S ) C p ( T ) , and (3) p ( p ( S ) ) = p ( S ) . This mapping can be interpreted as institutional constraints on the communications between players, i.e., p (S) represents the most comprehensive agreement that can be attained within the set of players S. Van den Brink and Gilles propose Permission Structures, based on the idea that some interactions take place in hierarchical organizations in which cooperation between two individuals requires the consent of their supervisors. Permission structures are thus given by a mapping p : N --+ 2 N, where j ~ p ( i ) stands for " j supervises i". The function p imposes exogenous restrictions on cooperation and allows for an extension of the Shapley value. I will conclude this section by briefly discussing another interesting (asymmetric) generalization of the value. Unlike the others, this one was proposed by Shapley himself (see also Chapter 32 in this Handbook). Shapley (1977) examines the power of indices in political games, where players' political positions affect the prospects of coalition formation. Shapley's aim was to embed players' positions in an m-dimensional Euclidean space. The point xi ~ R m of player i summarizes i's position (on a scale of support and opposition) on each of the relevant m "pure" issues. General issues faced by legislators typically involve a combination of several pure ones. For example, if the two pure issues are government spending (high or low) and national defense policy (aggressive or moderate), then the issue of whether or not to launch a new defense missile project is a combination of the two pure issues. Shapley's suggestion was to describe general issues as vectors of weights w =- ( w l . . . . . wm). Note that every vector w induces a natural order over the set of players. Specifically, j appears after i if w • xi > w . x j (where x • y stands for the inner product of the vectors x and y). The main point to notice here is that different vectors induce different orders on the set of players. To measure the legislative power of each player in the game, orte has to aggregate over all possible (general) issues. Let us therefore assume that issues occur randomly with respect to a uniform distribution over all issues (i.e., vectors w in Rm). For each order of players re, let 0(re) be the probability that the random issue generates the order 7r. Thus the players' profile of political positions (xl, x2 . . . . . Xn) is mapped into a probability distribution over the set of all permutations. Shapley's political value yields an expected marginal contribution to each player, where the random orders are giveu by the prob-
Ch. 53:
The Shapley Value
2045
ability distribution 0. Note that the political value is in the class of Weber's random order values [see Weber (1988)]. A random order value is characterized by a probability distribution over the set of all permutations. According to this value, each player receives his expected marginal contribution to the players preceding him with respect to the underlying probability distribution on orders. The relation between the political value and the Owen value is also quite interesting. Suppose that the vector of positions is represented by m clusters of points in IR2, where the cluster k consists of the players in Sk, whose positions are very close to each other but further away than those of other players (in the extreme case we could think of the members of Sk as having identical positions). It is pretty clear that the payoff vector that will emerge from Shapley's political value in this case will be very close to the Owen value for the coalition structure B :
(Sl .....
Sm).
8. Sustaining the Shapley value via non-cooperative garnes If the Shapley value is interpreted merely as a measure for evaluating players' power in a cooperative game, then its axiomatic foundation is strong enough to fully justify it. But the Shapley value is often interpreted (and indeed sometimes applied) as a scheine or a rule for allocating collective benefits or costs. The interpretation of the value in these situations implicitly assumes the existence of an outside authority - call it a planner which determines individual payoffs based on the axioms that characterize the value. However, simations of benefit (or cost) allocation are, by their very nature, situations in which individuals have conflicting interests. Players who feel underpaid are therefore likely to dispute the fairness of the scheme by challenging one or more of its axioms. It would therefore be nice if the Shapley value could be supported as an outcome of some decentralized mechanism in which individuals behave strategically in the absence of a planner whose objectives, though benevolent, may be disputable. This objective has been pursued by several authors as part of a broader agenda that deals with the interface between cooperative and non-cooperative garne theory. The concern of this literature is the construction of non-cooperative bargaining games that sustain various cooperative solution concepts as their equilibrium outcomes. This approach, offen referred to in the literature as "the Nash Program", is attributed to Nash's (1950) groundbreaking work on the bargaining problem, which, in addition to laying the axiomatic foundation of the solution, constructs a non-cooperative game to sustain it. Of all the solution concepts in cooperative garne theory, the Shapley value is arguably the most "cooperative", undoubtedly more so than such concepts as the core and the bargaining set whose definitions include strategic interpretations. Yet, perhaps more than any other solution concept in cooperative game theory, the Shapley value emerges as the outcome of a variety of non-cooperative garnes quite different in structure and interpretation. Harsanyi (1985) is probably the first to address the relationship between the Shapley value and non-cooperative garnes. Harsanyi's "dividend garne" makes use of the relation
2046
E. Win~r
between the Shapley value and the decomposition of garnes into unanimity garnes. To the more recent literature which uses sequential bargaining garnes to sustain cooperative solution concepts, Gul (1989) makes a pioneering contribution. In Gul's model, players meet randomly to conduct bilateral trades. When two players meet, one of them is chosen randomly (with equal probabilities 1 / 2 - 1 / 2 ) to make a proposal. In a proposal by player i to player j at period t, player i offers to pay rt to player j for purchasing j ' s resources in the garne. If player j accepts the offer, he leaves the game with the proposed payoff, and the coalition {i, j} becomes a single player in the new coalitional form game, implying that i now owns the property rights of player j. If j rejects the proposal by i, both players retum to the pool of potential traders who meet through random matching in a subsequent period. Each pair's probability of being selected for trading is 2~(nr (nr - 1)), where nt is the number of players remaining at period t. The game ends when only a single player is left. For any given play path of the game, the payoff of player j is given by the current value of his stream of resources minus the payments he made to the other players. Thus, for a given strategy combination ~r and a discount factor 6, we have O~
v'(,,,6)= ~(1- 6)[v(M;)- r~]6', 0 where M[ is the set of players whose resources are controlled by player i at time t and 6 is a discount factor. Gul confines himself to the stationary subgame perfect equilibria (SSPE) of the game, i.e., equilibria in which players' actions at period t depend only upon the allocation of resources at time t. He argues that SSPE outcomes may not be efficient in the sense of maximizing the aggregate equilibrium payoffs of all the players in the economy, but he goes on to show that in any no-delay equilibrium (i.e., an equilibrium in which all pairwise meetings end with agreements) players' payoffs converge to the Shapley value of the underlying game when the discount factor approaches 1. Specifically, THEOREM [Gul (1989)]. Let cr (6k) be a sequence o f SSPEs with respect to the discount factors {6/c}which converge to 1 as k goes to infinity. If cr(6k) is a no-delay equilibrium for all k, then U i (er (6k ), 6k ) converges to i's Shapley value o f V as k goes to infinity. It should be argued that in general the SSPE outcomes of Gul's game do not converge to the Shapley value as the discount factor approaches 1. Indeed, if delay occurs along the equilibrium path, the outcome may not be close to the Shapley value even for 6 close to 1. Gul's original formulation of the above theorem required that cr (6k) be efficient equilibria (in terms of expected payoffs). Gul argues that the condition of efficiency is a sufficient guarmatee that along the equilibrium path every bilateral matching terminates in an agreement. However, Hart and Levy (1999) show in an example that efficiency does not imply immediate agreement. Nevertheless, in a rejoinder to Hart and
Ch. 53: The Shapley Value
2047
Levy (1999), Gul (1999) points out that if the underlying coalitional game is strictly convex, 8 then in his model efficiency indeed implies no delay. A different bargaining model to sustain the Shapley value through its consistency property was proposed by Hart and Mas-Colell (1996). 9 Unlike in Gul's mode1, which is based on bilateral agreements, in Hart and Mas-Colell's approach players submit proposals for payoff allocations to all the active players. Each round in the game is characterized by a set S C N of "active players" and a player i c S who is designated to make a proposal after being randomly selected from the set S. A proposal is a feasible payoff vector x for the members in S, i.e., Zj~sXj ~~-v(S). Once the proposal is made, the players in S respond sequentially by either accepting or rejecting it. If all the members of S accept the proposal, the garne ends and the players in S share payoffs according to the proposal. Inactive players receive a payoff of zero. If at least one player rejects the proposal, then the proposer i runs the risk of being dropped from the garne. Specifically, the proposer leaves the garne and joins the set of inactive players with a probability of 1 - p, in which case the garne continues into the next period with the set of active players being S \ i. Or the proposer remains active with probability p, and the garne continues into the next period with the same set of active players. The garne ends either when agreement is reached or when only one active player is left in the garne. Hart and Mas-Colell analyzed the above (perfect information) garne by means of its stationary subgame perfect equilibria, and concluded: THEOREM [Hart and Mas-Colell (1996)]. For every monotonic and non-negative l° garne v and f o r every 0 «, p < 1, the bargaining game described above has a unique stationary subgame perfect equilibrium (SSPE). Furthermore, if as is the SSPE payoff vector of a subgame starting with a period in which S is the active set o f players, then as = 49(v Is) (where 49 stands f o r the Shapley value and v ls f o r the restricted garne on S). In particular, the SSPE outcome o f the whole garne is the Shapley value o f v. A rough summary of the argument for this result runs as follows. Let as,i denote the equilibrium proposal when the set of active players is S and the proposer is i c S. In equilibrium, player j 6 S with j ~ i should be paid precisely what he expects to receive if agreement fails to be reached at the current payoff. As the protocol specifies, with probability p we remain with the same set of players and the next period's expected proposal will be as = 1/[SI Y~~iEsas, i" With the remaining probability 1 - p, players i will be ejected so that the next period's proposal is expected to be as\i. We thus obtain the following two equations for as,i:
(1) ~ j aJs,i = v(S) (feasibility condition), and 8 We recall that a game v is said to be strictly convexif v(S Ui) - V (S) > v(T t3i) - v(T) whenever T C S and SS&T. 9 In the original Hart and Mas-Colell (1996) paper, the bargalning garne was based on an underlying nontransferable utility garne. 10 v(S) >10 for all S C N, and v(T) <~v(S) for T C S.
2048
E. Winter
j (2) a s,i = paJs + (1 - p)ds\ i (equilibrium condition). Rewriting the second condition we notice that the two of them correspond precisely to the two properties of Myerson (1977), which we discussed in Section 5 and which together with efficiency characterize the value uniquely. In a recent paper, Perez-Castrillo and Wettstein (1999) suggested a garne that modifies that of Hart and Mas-Colell (1996) so as to allow the (random) order of proposals to be endogenized. The game runs as follows. Prior to making a proposal there is a bidding phase in which each player i commits to pay a payoff vi to player j. These bids are made simultaneously. The identity of the proposal is determined by the bids. Specifically, the proposer is chosen to be the player i for which the difference between the bids made by i and the bids made to i is maximized, i.e., i -~ argmax~eN [Y~~j v/ - ~ j v~] (players' bids to themselves is always zero). If there is more than one player for which this maximum is attained, then the proposer is chosen from among these players with an equal probability for each candidate. Following player i's recognition to propose, the game proceeds according to Hart and Mas-Colell's protocol, with p = 1. Namely, upon rejection, player i leaves the garne with probability 1. Perez-Castrillo and Wettstein (1999) show that this garne implements the Shapley value in a unique subgame perfect equilibrium (since the garne is of a finite horizon, no stationarity requirement is needed). Almost all the bargaining garnes that have been proposed in the literature on the implementation of cooperative solutions via non-cooperative equilibria are based on the exchange of proposals and responses. A different approach to multilateral bargaining was adopted in Winter (1994). Rather than a model in which players make full proposals concerning payoff allocations and respond to such proposals, a more descriptive feature of bargaining situations is sought by assuming that players submit only demands, i.e., players announce the share they request in return for cooperation. A coalition emerges when the underlying resources are sufficient to satisfy the demands of all members. I will describe here a simple version of the Winter (1994) model and some of the results that follow. Consider the order in which players move according to their name, i.e., player 1 followed by 2, etc. Each player i in his turn publicly announces a demand di (which should be interpreted as a statement by player i of agreeing to be a member of any coalition provided that he is paid at least di). Before player i makes bis demand, we check whether there is a compatible coalition among the i - 1 players who already made their demands. A coalition S is said to be compatible (to the underlying garne v) if S can satisfy the demands of all its members, i.e., ~ j e s dj <~v(S). If compatible coalitions exist, then the largest one (in terms of membership) leaves the garne and each of its members receives bis demand. The game then proceeds with the set of remaining players. If no such coalition exists, then player i moves ahead and makes his demand. The game ends when all players have made their demands. Those players who are not part of a compatible coalition receive their individually rational payoff. Consider now a garne that starts with a chance move that randomly selects an order with a uniform probability distribution over all orders and then proceeds in ac-
Ch. 53: The Shapley Value
2049
cordance with the above protocol. We call this game the demand commitment garne. Winter (1994) shows that the demand commitment game implements the Shapley value if the underlying game is strictly convex. THEOREM [Winter (1994)]. For strictly convex (cooperative) garnes, the demand commitment garne has a unique subgame perfect equilibrium, and each player's equilibrium payoff equals his Shapley value. Winter (1994) also considers a protocol that requires a second round of bidding in the event that the first round ends without a grand coalition that is compatible. It can be shown that with small delay costs the Shapley value emerges not only as the expected equilibrium outcome for each player, but that the actual demands made by the players in the first round coincide with the Shapley value of the underlying garne. Several other papers have followed the same approach in different contexts. Dasgupta and Chiu (1998) discuss a modified version of the Winter (1994) game, which allows for the implementation of the Shapley value in general garnes. Roughly, the idea is to allow outside transfers (or gifts) that will convexify a non-convex garne. A balanced budget is guaranteed by a schedule of taxes dependent on the order of moves. Bag and Winter (1999) used a demand commitment-type mechanism to implement stable and efficient allocations in excludable public goods. Morelli (1999) modified Winter's (1994) model to describe legislative bargaining under various voting rules. Finally, Mutuswami and Winter (2000) used demand mechanisms of the same kind to study the formation of networks. They also noted that if the mechanism in Winter (1994) is amended to allow a compatible coalition to leave the game only when it is connected (i.e., only when it includes the last k players for some 1 ~< k ~< n), then the resulting garne implements the Shapley value not only in the case of convex games but in all games. 9. Practice
While garne theory is thought of as "descriptive" in its attempt to explain social phenomena by means of formal modeling, cooperative garne theory is primarily "prescriptive". It is not surprising that rauch of the literature on cooperative solution concepts finds its way not into economics journals but into journals of management science and operations research. Cooperative garne theory does not set out to describe the way individuals behave. Rather, it recommends reasonable rules of allocation, or proposes indices to measure power. The prospect of using such a theory for practical applications is therefore quite attractive, the more so for its single-point solution and axiomatic foundation. In this section, I discuss two areas in which the Shapley value can be (and indeed has been) used as ä practical tool: the measurement of voter power and cost allocation. 9.1. Measuring states' power in the U.S. presidential election The procedure for electing a president in the United States consists of two stages. First, each state elects a group of representatives, or "'Great Electors", who comprise the Elec-
2050
E. Winter
toral College. Second, the Electoral College elects the president by simple majority rule. It is assumed that each Great Elector votes for the candidate preferred by the majority of his/her state. Since the Electoral College of each state grows in proportion to its census count, a narrow majority in a densely populated state, like California, can affect an election's outcome more than wide majorities in several scarcely populated states. Mann and Shapley (1962) and Owen (1975) measured the voting power of voters from different states, using the Shapley value together with the interesting notion of compound simple garnes. Let M1, M2 . . . . . Mr~ be a sequence of n disjoint sets of players. Let wl, w2 . . . . . wn be a sequence of n simple garnes defined on the sets M1 . . . . . Mn respectively. And let v be another simple game defined on the set N = {1, 2 . . . . . n}. We will refer to the players in N as distxicts. The compound game u = v[wl . . . . . wn] is a simple game defined on the set M = Mi t_J M2 U - . . U Mn by u(S) = v ( { j l w j ( S 71Mj) = 1}). In words: We say that S wins in district j if S's members in that district form a winning coalition, i.e., if wj (S 71Mj) = 1. S is said to be winning in the garne u if and only if the set of districts in which S is winning is itself a winning coalition in v. In the context of the presidential face, Mj is the set of voters in state j , wj is the simple majority garne in state j, and v is the electoral college garne. Specifically, the electoral college garne can be written as the following weighted majority game [270; Pl . . . . . Ps1], where 51 stands for the number of states, and Pi is the number of electors nominated by a state i (e.g., 45 for California and 3 for the least populated states and the District of Columbia). In general compound garnes, Owen has shown that the value of player i is the product of his value in the garne within his district and the value of his district in the game v, i.e., cbi(u) = Ój (1J)Ói(Wj). Since the districts' games are all symmetric simple majority garnes, the value of each player in the voting garne in his state is simply 1 divided by the number of voters. To compute the value of the garne v, Owen used the notion of a multilinear extension [see Owen (1972)]. Overall, he found that the power of a voter in a more populated state is substantially greater than that of a voter in a less populated state. For example, California voters enjoy more than three times the power of Washington D.C. voters. Others have used the Shapley value (as well as other indices) to measure political power. Seidmann (1987) used it to compare the power of governments in Ireland following elections in the early and mid 80s. He argued that a government's durability greatly depends on the distribution of power across opposition parties, which can be estimated by means of the Shapley-Shubik index. Carreras, Garcfa-Jurado, and Pacios (1993) used the Shapley and the Owen value to evaluate the power of each of the parties in all the Spanish regional parliaments. Fedzhora (2000) uses the Shapley-Shubik index to study the voting power of the 27 regions (oblasts) in the Ukraine in the run-off stage of the presidential elections between 1994 and 1999. She also compares these indicators to the transfers that Ukrainian governments were making to the different regions. Another interesting application of the Shapley value to political science is due to Rapoport and Golan (1985). Immediately after the election of the tenth Israeli parliament, 21 students of political science, 24 Knesset members, and 7 parliamentary correspondents were
Ch. 53:
The Shapley Value
2051
invited to assess the political power ratlos of the 10 parties represented in the Knesset. These assessments were then compared with various power indices, including the Shapley value. The value provided the best fit for 31% of the subjects, but the authors claimed the Banzhaf index performed better. 9.2. Allocation o f costs
The problem of allocating the cost of constructing or maintaining a public facility among its various users is of great practical importance. Young (1994) (see Chapter 34 in this Handbook) offers a comprehensive survey of the relation between garne theory and cost atlocation. An interesting allocation rule for such problems, which is closely related to the Shapley value, emerges from the "Airport Garne" of Littlechild and Owen (1973). Specifically, consider n planes of different size for which a runway needs to be built. Suppose that there arem types of planes and that the construction of a runway sufficient to service a type j plane is c j with Cl < c2 < .-- < Cm. Let N j be the number of planes of type j so that U N j = N is the set of all planes which need to be service& A runway servicing a subgroup of planes S C N will häve to be long enough to allow the servicing of the largest plane in S. This gives rise to the following natural cost-sharing garne (in coalitional form) defined on the set of planes: c ( S ) = cj(s) and c(0) = 0, where j (S) -~ max{jIS N N j 7& 0}. Littlechild and Owen's (1973) suggestion was to use the garne c to determine the allocation of cost by applying the Shapley value on the garne. Note that the garne v can be decomposed into m unanimity garnes. Specifically, define Rk = Rk U Rk + l U . . . U Rm and consider the coalitional form garnes vk with vk ( S) = 0 when S (q Rk -----0 and Vk (S) = ck -- Ck-1 otherwise (we set co = 0). It is easy to verify that the sum of the games vk is exactly the cost-sharing garne, i.e., vl (S) + . . . + Vm (S) = c ( S ) for every coalition of planes S. The additivity of the Shapley value implies that the value of the garne c is ~b(c) = ~P(vl) + . . - + qS(Vm). But each vk is a unanimity garne with (gi(vk) = 0 for i ~ N \ Rk and ~bi(Vk ) = (Ck -- Ck-1)/]Rkl for i ~ Rk. We therefore obtain that the Shapley value of the garne c is given by q~i(c) = (c2 - cl)/IR11 ÷ (c3 c2)/IR21 + ' " + (cj - c j - 1 ) / I R j[ for a plane of type j. The rule suggested by Littlechild and Owen (1973) has the following interesting interpretation. First, all players share equally the cost of a runway for type 1 planes. Then all players who need a larger facility share the marginal extra cost, i.e., c2 - cl. Next, all players who need yet a larger runway share equally the cost of upgrading to a runway large enough to service type 3 planes. We now continue in this manner until all the residual costs are allocated, which will ultimately allow for the acquisition of a runway long enough to service all planes. A version of the Airport garne was studied by Fragnelli et al. (1999). Their work was part of a research project funded by the European Commission with the aim of determining cost allocation rules for the railway infrastructure in Europe. Fragnelli et al. realized that the original Airport garne is ill-suited to their problem since the maintenance cost of a railway infrastructure depends on the number of users. They constructed
2052
E. Winter
a n e w g a r n e w h i c h d i s t i n g u i s h e s c o n s t r u c t i o n costs ( w h i c h d o n o t d e p e n d o n t h e n u m b e r o f users) f r o m m a i n t e n a n c e costs, a n d d e r i v e d a s i m p l e f o r m u l a for t h e S h a p l e y v a l u e o f t h e garne. T h e y also u s e d real data c o n c e r n i n g the m a i n t e n a n c e o f r a i l w a y i n f r a s t r u c tures to e s t i m a t e the a l l o c a t i o n o f cost a m o n g d i f f e r e n t users.
References Aumann, R.J., and J. Drèze (1975), "Cooperative garnes with coalition structures", International Journal of Garne Theory 4:217-237. Aumann, R.J., and R.B. Myerson (1988), "Endogenous formation of links between players and of coalitions: An application of the Shapley value", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 175-191. Aumann, R.J., and L.S. Shapley (1974), Values of Non-Atomic Games (Princeton University Press, Princeton). Bag, EK., and E. Winter (1999), "Simple subscription mechanisms for the production of public goods", Journal of Economic Theory 87:72-97. Banzhaf, J.E III (1965), "Weighted voting does not work: A mathematical analysis", Rutgers Law Review 19:317-343. Calvo, E., J. Lasaga and E. Winter (1996), "On the principle of balanced contributions", Mathematical Social Sciences 31:171-182. Carreras, E, I. Garcia-Jurado and M.A. Pacios (1993), "Estudio coalicional de los pm-lamentos autonómicos espafioles de régimen comün", Revista de Estudios Polfticos 82:152-176. Chun, Y. (1989), "A new axiomatization of the Shapley value", Games and Economic Behavior 1:119-130. Dasgupta, A., and Y.S. Chiu (1998), "On implementation via demand commitment garnes", International Journal of Garne Theory 27:161-190. Derks, J., and H. Peters (1993), "A Shapley value for garnes with restricted coalitions", International Journal of Garne Theory 21: 351-360. Dubey, E (1975), "On the uniqueness of the Shapley value", International Journal of Garne Theory 4:131-139. Fedzhora, L. (2000), "Voting power in the Ukrainian presidential elections", M.A. Thesis (Economic Education and Research Consortium, Kiev, Ukraine). Fragnelli, V., I. Garda-Jurado, H. Norde, E Patrone and S. Tijs (1999), "How to share rallway infrastructure costs?', in: I. Garcla-Jurado, F. Patrone and S. Tijs, eds., Garne Practice: Contfibutions from Applied Garne Theory (Kluwer, Dordrecht). Gul, E (1989), "Bargaining foundations of Shapley value", Econometrica 57:81-95. Gul, F. (1999), "Efficiency and immediate agreement: A reply to Hart and Levy", Econometrica 67:913-918. Harsanyi, J.C. (1963), "A simplified bargaining model for the n-person cooperative garne", International Economic Review 4:194-220. Harsanyi, J.C. (1985), "The Shapley value and the risk dominance solutions of two bargaining models for characteristic-function garnes", in: R.J. Aumann et al., eds., Essays in Garne Theory and Mathematical Economics (Bibliographisches Institut, Mannheim), 43-68. Hart, S., and M. Kurz (1983), "On the endogenous formation of coalitions", Econometrica 51:1295-1313. Hart, S., and Z. Levy (1999), "Efficiency does not imply immediate agreement", Econometrica 67:909-912. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1989), "Potential, value and consistency', Econometrica 57:589-614. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1996), "Bargaining and value", Econometrica 64:357-380. Kalai, E., and D. Samet (1985), "Monotonic solutions to general cooperative garnes", Econometriea 53:307327. Littlechild, S.C., and G. Owen (1973), "A simple expression for the Shapley value in a special oase", Management Science 20:99-107. Mann, I., and L.S. Shapley (1962), "The a-priori voting strength of the electoral college", American Political Science Review 72:70-79.
Ch. 53:
The Shapley Value
2053
Monderer, D., and D. Samet (2002), "Variations on the Shapley value", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 3 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 54, 2055-2076. Morelli, M. (1999), "Demand competition and policy compromise in legislative bargaining", American Political Science Review 93:809-820. Mutuswami, S., and E. Winter (2000), "Subscription mechanisms for network fomaation", Mimeo (The Center for Rationafity and Interactive Decision-Making, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem). Myerson, R.B. (1977), "Graphs and cooperation in garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 2:225-229. Myerson, R.B. (1980), "Conference strucmres and fair allocation rules", International Joumal of Garne Theory 9:169-182. Nash, J. (1950), "The bargaining problem", Econometrica 18:155-162. Neyman, A. (1989), "Uniqueness of the Shapley value", Garnes and Economic Behavior 1:116-118. Owen, G. (1972), "Multilinear extensions of garnes", Management Science 18:64-79. Owen, G. (1975), "Evaluation of a presidential election garne", American Political Science Review 69:947953. Owen, G. (1977), "Values of garnes with a priori unions", in: R. Henn and O. Moeschlin, eds., Essays in Mathematical Economics and Garne Theory (Springer-Verlag, Berlin), 76-88. Owen, G., and E. Winter (1992), "The multilinear extension and the coalition value", Garnes and Economic Behavior 4:582-587. Perez-Castrillo, D., and D. Wettstein (1999), "Bidding for the surplus: A non-cooperative approach to the Shapley value", DP 99-7 (Ben-Gurion University, Monaster Center for Economic Research). Rapoport, A., and E. Golan (1985), "Assessment of political power in the Israeli Knesset", American Political Science Review 79:673-692. Roth, A.E. (1977), "The Shapley raine as a von Neumann-Morgenstem utility", Econometrica 45:657-664. Seidmann, D. (1987), "The distribution of power in Da'il E'ireann", The Economic and Social Review 19:6168. Shapley, L.S. (1953), "A value for n-person garnes", in: H.W. Kuhn and A.W. Tucker, eds., Contributions to the Theory of Garnes II (Annals of Mathematics Studies 28) (Princeton University Press, Princeton), 307-317. Shapley, L.S. (1977), "A comparison of power indices and a nonsymmetric generalization", P-5872 (The Rand Corporation, Santa Monica, CA). Shapley, L.S., and M. Shubik (1954), "A method for evaluating the distribution of power in a committee system", American Political Science Review 48:787-792. Sobolev, A.I. (1975), "The charactefization of optimality principles in cooperative garnes by functional equations", Matliematical Methods in Social Sciences 6:94-151 (in Russian). Straffin, RD. (1977), "Homogeneity, independence and power indices", Public Choice 30:107-118. Straffin, ED. (1994), "Power and stability in polifics", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 32,1127-1152. Von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern (1944), Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton University Press, Princeton). Weber, R. (1988), "Probabilistic values for garnes", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 101-120. Weber, R. (1994), "Garnes in coalitional form", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Game Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 36, 1285-1304. Winter, E. (1989), "A value for garnes with level structures", International Journal of Garne Theory 18:227242. Winter, E. (1991), "A solution for non-transferable utility garnes with coalition stmcture", International Journal of Game Theory 20:53-63. Winter, E. (1992), "The consistency and the potential for values with garnes with coalition structure", Games and Economic Behavior 4:132-144. Winter, E. (1994), "The demand commitment bargaining and snowballing cooperation", Economic Theory 4:255-273.
2054
E. Winter
Young, H.P. (1985), "Monotonic solutions of cooperative garnes", International Journal of Garne Theory 14:65-72. Young, H.P. (1994), "Cost allocation", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Game Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 34, 1193-1235.
Chapter 54
VARIATIONS ON THE SHAPLEY VALUE DOV MONDERER
The Technion, Haifa, Israel DOV SAMET
Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv, Israel
Contents 1. Introduction 2. Preliminaries 3. Probabilistic values 4. Efficient probabilistic values (quasivalues) 5. Weighted values 6. Symmetric probabilistic values (semivalues) 7. Indices of power 8. Values with a social structure References
Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2057 2058 2059 2060 2062 2066 2069 207l 2075
2056
D. Monderer and D. Samet
Abstract This survey captures the main contributions in the area described by the title that were published up to 1997. (Unformnately, it does not capture all of them.) The variations that are the subject of this chapter are those axiomatically characterized solutions which are obtained by varying either the set of axioms that define the Shapley value, or the domain over which this value is defined, or both. In the first category, we deal mainly with probabilistic values. These are solutions that preserve one of the essential feamres of the Shapley value, namely, that they are given, for each player, by some averaging of the player's marginal contributions to coalitions, where the probabilistic weights depend on the coalitions only and not on the game. The Shapley value is the unique probabilistic value that is efficient and symmetric. We characterize and discuss two families of solutions: quasivalues, which are efficient probabilistic values, and semivalues, which are symmetric probabilistic values. In the second category, we deal with solutions that generalize the Shapley value by changing the domain over which the solution is defined. In such generalizations the solution is defined on pairs, consisting of a garne and some structure on the set of players. The Shapley value is a special case of such a generalization in the sense that it coincides with the solution on the restricted domain in which the second argument is fixed to be the "trivial" orte. Under this category we survey mostly solutions in which the structure is a partition of the set of the players, and a solution in which the structure is a graph, the vertices of which are the players.
Keywords Shapley value, quasivalue, semivalue, non-symmetric values, probabilistic values, weighted values
JEL classification: C71, D46, D63, D72, D74
Ch. 54: Variationson the Shapley Value
2057
1. Introduction The variations that are the subject of this discussion are those axiomatically characterized solutions that are obtained by varying the set of axioms which define the Shapley value, or the domain over which this value is defined, or both. We first capture axiomatically, in Section 3, those solutions that preserve one of the essential features of the Shapley value, namely, that they are given, for each player, by some averaging of the player's marginal contributions to coalitions, where the probabilistic weights depend on the coalitions only and not on the garne. We call the family of all such solutions probabilistic values. The Shapley value is the unique probabilistic value that is efficient and symmetric. In the following sections we characterize and discuss two families of solutions: quasivalues, which are efficient probabilistic values, and semivalues, which are symmetric probabilistic values. In Section 4 we discuss quasivalues. These solutions are related to the descriptions of the Shapley value as a random-order value: it is the expected marginal contributions of the players when they are randomly ordered. Indeed a solution is a quasivalue if and only if it is a random-order value. The Shapley value is the special random-order value in which the random orders are uniformly drawn. Quasivalues can be equivalently described by choosing at random the "arrival" times of the players, rather than their order, and taking the expected marginal contribution of a player to the players who arrived before hirn. In particular, the Shapley value is obtained when the arrival times are independent and each is uniformly distributed in the unit interval. When arrival times are independent, the quasivalue has another representation as a path value: the value can be computed by integrating the derivative of the multilinear extension of the garne along a certain path. In Section 5 we characterize and discuss a family of quasivalues - the weighted Shapley values - which was introduced by Shapley alongside the Shapley value. Semivalues are discussed in Section 6. The symmetry axiom, which plays a central role in the characterization of semivalues, is reflected in the probabilities that define the value: they depend only on the size of coalitions. A semivalue does not, of course, have to be efficient. We show that the specific deviation of a semivalue from efficiency defines it uniquely. That is, if the magnitude of the deviation from efficiency is the same for two semivalues in each garne, then they coincide. A probabilistic value defined on the set of all garnes is necessarily additive. When the set of games is restricted to simple garnes (that is, garnes in which the worth of a coalition is either 0 or 1), then additivity cannot be applied. Yet, all the generalizations discussed so rar can be axiomatically defined for this class of games when the transfer axiom replaces that of additivity, This is done in Section 7. Section 8 deals with solutions that generalize the Shapley value by changing the domain over which the solution is defined. In such generalizations the solution is defined on pairs, consisting of a game and some structure on the set of players. The Shapley value is a special case of such a generalization in the sense that it coincides with the solution on the restricted domain in which the second argument is fixed to be the "trivial"
2058
D. Monderer and D. Samet
one. Under this category we survey mostly solutions in which the sta'ucture is a partition of the set of the players, and a solution in which the structure is a graph the vertices of which are the players.
2. Preliminaries Let N be a finite set with n elements, n >~ 1. Elements of N are called players. Any subset of N is called a coalition. For a coalition S, we denote N \ S by S c. We denote by C = C ( N ) the set of all coalitions, and by Co = Co(N) the set of all nonempty coalitions. A garne on N is a set function v : C --+ R, where R denotes the set of real numbers, with v(0) = 0. We will write v(S U i) for v(S U {i}), and v(S \ i) for v(S \ {i}). A garne v is additive if for every pair of disjoint coalitions S, T E C, v(S U T) = v(S) + v ( T ) , and it is superadditive if for each pair of such coalitions, v(S U T) ». v(S) + v ( T ) . It is monotone if v(S) «, v ( T ) for every S _c T. A garne v is simple if v(S) ~ {0, 1} for every SEC. Player i is a null player in v if v(S to i) - v(S) = 0 for every S ___N \ i. A coalition M is a carrier of v if M « consists of null players. Hence, M is a carrier for v if and only if v(S M M ) ---- v(S) for all S c_ N. Player i is a dummy player in v if there exists an a E R such that v(S U i) - v(S) = a for every S ~ N \ i. The set of all garnes is denoted G = G ( N ) and the set of all additive games is denoted A = A ( N ) . We naturally identify an additive garne v 6 A with the vector x E R N defined by xi = v(i) for every i E N. For each such x E R N and for every S E C we denote x (S) = Y~~i~s xi. A permutation of N is a one-to-one function that maps N onto N. The set of all permutations on N is denoted by 69 = 69 (N). The set of all one-to-one functions r : N --+ {1 . . . . . n} is denoted by OR = OR(N). Each v E OR is identified with a complete order on N. In this order, i comes before j if r ( i ) < v ( j ) . For a garne v and a permutation 0 we define O*v ~ G by O*v(S) = v(O(S)) for all S 6 C. Let H c G. A solution on H is a function aß : H --+ A. We will use the terms operator and solution interchangeably. The domain of a solution is G whenever it is not explicitly specified otherwise. It is useful to single out a list of possible properties of solutions (axioms) that have been discussed in the literature. (A.1) aß satisfies the additivity axiom or is additive if aß(u + v) = aß(u) + aß(v) for every u, v E G. (A.2) aß is homogeneous if aß(uv) = c~aß(v) for every v E G and c~ E R. (A.3) aß satisfies the linearity axiom, or is linear, if it is additive and homogeneous. (A.4) aß satisfies the projection axiom, or is a projection, if aß(/z) = / z for every /zEA. (A.5) aß satisfies the nullplayeraxiom if aßv(i) =- 0 for every v c G and every null player i in v. (A.6) aß satisfies the dummy player axiom if aßv(i) = a for v 6 G and for every dummy player i such that v(S U i) - v(S) = a for every S __. N \ i.
Ch, 54:
Variations on the Shapley Value
2059
(A.7) aß satisfies the positivity axiom, or aß is positive, if aßv(i) >~ 0 for every i whenever v is a monotone garne.
(A.8) aß satisfies the Milnor axiom, or is a Milnor operator, if for every v and i 6 N, min (v(S U i) - v(S)) <~ aßv(i) <~ max (v(S U i) - v(S)).
SC_N\i
S~N\i
(A.9) aß satisfies the symmetry axlom or is symmetric if aß(O'v) = O*aßv for every v c G and every permutation 0. (A.10) aß satisfies the efficiency axiom or is efficient if aßv(N) = v(N) for every
v~G. (A.11) aß satisfies the carrier axiom if aßv(M) = v(M) for every v c G and every carrier M of v. We state the above axioms for solutions defined on G, but will sometimes use them for solutions defined on strict subsets of G. In such a case, an axiom is to be understood as holding whenever possible. Thus, for example, if aß is a solution on H C G, the projection axiom should be read as aß/z = / z whenever/z ~ H N A.
3. Probabilistic values For a finite set M we denote by A ( M ) the set of all probability measures on M. That is, p ~ A ( M ) if p : M --+ [0, 1] and ~m~M p(m) = 1. We denote by Ep the expectation operator with respect to p. The set of all subsets of N \ i is denoted by C i = C i (N). For each game v, we denote by Dir the set function defined on C i by D i r ( s ) :- v(S U i) - v(S). We call D i r ( s ) the marginal contribution of i to S. A solution aß is called aprobabilistic value, iffor each player i there exists a probability pi E A(ci), stich that aßv(i) is the expected marginal contribution of i with respect to pl. Namely,
Bv(i) = Ep~(Div) = Z p i ( s ) ( v(S U i) - v(S)). S¢C i
(3.1)
The Shapley value, which inspired this definition, is the probabilistic value defined by the probabilities pi defined by pi (S) = 1/(n (ns1)), where s denotes the number of elements in S. We denote the Shapley value by q~ = ~oN. It can be easily verified that the probability measures pi in (3.1) are uniquely determined by aß. Probabilistic values can be axiomatically characterized as follows. THEOREM 1. Let aß be a solution. Then the following three assertions are equivalent: (1) aß is a probabilistic value. (2) aß is a linear positive operator that satisfies the dummy axiom. (3) aß is a linear Milnor operator.
D, Monderer and D. Samet
2060
Weber (1988) proved the equivalence of (1) and (2). Monderer (1988, 1990) proved the equivalence of (2) and (3). Shapley (1953a) proved that the Shapley value is the unique solution that satisfies the additivity, symmetry and carrier axioms. 1 The following is one of many other characterizations of the Shapley value. We single out this particular characterization [which is proved in Weber (1988)] because it can serve as the basis for a unified approach to analyzing the variations on the Shapley value. THEOREM 2. The Shapley value is the unique solution which is a symmetric and effi-
cient probabilistic value. The main variations on the Shapley value retain the condition of being a probabilistic value (i.e., that a player's value depends linearly and positively on his marginal contributions), while relaxing one of the other two conditions in Theorem 2. We call an efficient probabilistic value a quasivalue, and a symmetric probabilistic value a semivalue. Quasivalues are discussed in Sections 4 and 5, semivalues in Sections 6 and 7. REMARKS. (1) As probabilistic values are characterized by axioms that do not mix values of different players, they can be defined and characterized for each player separately. Such an approach was taken by Weber (1988). (2) Weber (1988) proved that Theorem 1 holds for solutions defined on the class of monotone games. One can deduce from Monderer (1988) and from a remark in Weber that the equivalence of (1) and (3) in Theorem 1 continues to hold for solutions defined on the class of superadditive garnes.
4. Efficient probabilistic values (quasivalues) We begin with an important characterization of quasivalues. For each r E OR we define the operator ~or by ~0r v ( i ) = v ( { j E N: z ( j ) ~< r ( i ) } ) -
v ( { j ~ N: r ( j ) < r ( i ) } ) .
If we think of T as the order in which players enter the "room" where the game takes place, then q)r (i) is the marginal contribution of i to the coalition of players that preceded hirn. For every b ~ A(OR) we define a solution ~0b by
~obv(i) = ~ ~°rv(i)b(z) • r¢OR 1 He proved this result for solutions deflned on the set of superadditive garnes, with finite support, on a universal set of players; but his proof, as is weil known, can also be used to charactefize the Shapley value on the space G(N) of all garnes on N.
Ch. 54: Variationson the Shapley Value
2061
Thus, ~obv(i) is the expected m a r g i n a l contribution of i, where the order of entering the r o o m is selected according to b. A solution ~ is called a random-order value if there exists b ~ z~ (OR) such that =~o b. It is easy to verify that every r a n d o m - o r d e r value is a quasivalue. Indeed, given b
A(OR) we can define for each i ~ N and S ~ C i, pi(S) = b ( { r
E OR: r ( j ) < r ( i ) i f f j
E S}).
(4.1)
If we insert the pi's from (4.1) into (3.1), the resulting probabilistic value ~ß coincides with q)b. The following t h e o r e m of Weber (1988) shows that the converse is also true. THEOREM 3. A solution is a quasivalue if and only if it is a random-order value. Note that the Shapley value is a r a n d o m - o r d e r value with b ( r ) = 1/n! for every r
OR. 2 It can be easily verified that for every b c A(OR) there exist n r a n d o m variables that are j o i n t l y distributed in the cube [0, 1] N with a density function and therefore with absolutely c o n t i n u o u s m a r g i n a l distribution functions (Oli)i~N, such that for every r 6 0 R
(Zi)icN
b ( r ) = p r o b ( z r - l ( i ) < zr l(.i) for every 1 ~
(4.2)
This enables us to interpret ¢pb in terms of r a n d o m arrival times, as follows. We think of the value of the r a n d o m variable zi as the time of arrival of player i in the "room". The m a r g i n a l contribution of i, w h e n he arrives at time t, is his m a r g i n a l contribution to the set of other players who arrived up to time t. Define
N ( t ) = {j c N: zj <~t}.
(4.3)
T h e n N ( t ) is a r a n d o m coalition in C and it can be easily verified that 1
q)bv(i) =
f0
E ( v ( N ( t ) U i) - v ( N ( t ) \ i)Izi = t) do~i (t),
(4.4)
where the integral in (4.4) is the R i e m a n n - S t i e l t j e s integral. Thus, we have shown that a solution 7t is a r a n d o m - o r d e r value, if and only if there exist n r a n d o m variables
2 Observe that for sufficiently large n the affine map b --~ ~ob is not one-to-one. Indeed, the affine dimension of the convex set A (OR) is n! - 1, while the affine dimension of the set of quasivalues is less than n (2n 1 _ 1), because each quasivalue ~ß is uniquely determined by a vector ( p l , p 2 . . . . , ph) in XicNA(C i) which, in addition, satisfies the necessary linear conditions for the efficiency of 7t. It is still to be checked whether the uniform distribution over OR is the only one that gives rise to the Shapley value.
D. Monderer and D. Samet
2062
(Zi)i~N, which are jointly distributed in the cube [0, 1] N, and have a density function, such that ger(i) is given by the right-hand side of (4.4), where (Cli)i6 N a r e the marginal distribution functions. Owen (1972) defined the multilinear extension of a garne v. Each coalition S can be identified with an extreme point, es, of the cube [0, 1] N, where es is the characteristic function of S. Therefore, each garne v can be considered as a function on the extreme points of the cube and hence it can be uniquely extended to a multilinear function on the cube, which is denoted by ~. Owen showed that if the random variables that define b via (4.2) are independent, then for every i: q0»v(i) =-
1 ~~ ~ («(t)) d«i (t).
f0
(4.5)
In particular, the Shapley value is determined by n i.i.d, random variables that are uniformly distributed in [0, 1]. Therefore, 1 0~
~ov(i) =
f0
~xi (te) dt,
where e = e N . The presentation of the solution qjb, in (4.5), gives rise to another namral solution. A solution ge is a path value if there exists an absolutely continuous nondecreasing path « : [0, 1] --+ [0, 1] N with «(0) = 0 and «(1) = e such that for every game v and every player i, ~ v ( i ) is defined by the right-hand side of (4.5). Alternatively, ~ is a path value if there exists b c A(OR) such that ~p = q)b, and there exist n independent random variables that are distributed in [0, 1] with absolutely continuous distribution functions such that (4.2) holds. It can be verified that not every quasivalue is a path value. REMARKS.
(1) Gilboa and Monderer (1991) discussed quasivalues defined on subspaces of games. They gave necessary and sufficient conditions that ensure that such quasivalues can be extended to quasivalues on G. (2) Monderer (1992) used the concept of quasivalue in order to provide a gametheoretic approach to the stochastic choice problem. He used Theorem 3 to confirm a conjecture of Block and Marschak (1960), which had already been proved before by Falmagne (1978). The relationship between the stochastic choice problem and quasivalues was further analyzed by Gilboa and Monderer (1992).
5. Weighted values
Weighted values compfise a special class of quasivalues, and more specifically of path values. We describe two forms of such values. Both were introduced by Shapley (1953a,
Ch. 54:
Variations on the Shapley Value
2063
1953b), alongside the standard Shapley value, and were axiomatized by Kalai and Samet (1987). Let co E RN+ (that is, coi > 0 for every i E N). Recall that a unanimity garne us, for S E Co, is defined by us(T) = 1 for T _ S and us(T) = 0 otherwise, and that the set of unanimity garnes, for all S E Co, is a basis for the linear space G of games. The positively weighted value q¢o (which is called the co-value) is the unique linear operator satisfying
q)°)us(i ) =
[
coco(S
10,
)'
for/e S for/ES
for each unanimity garne us. If coi = n1 for every i e N, then q)co is the Shapley value. Owen (1972) has shown that positively weighted values are path values, the path « being defined by
e~i(t) = t c°i f o r e v e r y t c [0, 1].
(5.1)
Note that the mapping co ~ ~o~° is homogeneous of degree zero, that is, q)z~o= ~oo) for every )~ > 0. Therefore, we can restrict our attention to vectors co in the relative interior of A (N), which we call weight vectors. We turn now to an axiomatic characterization of positively weighted values. A solution aß is strictly positive if for every monotone game v without null players, aßv(i) > 0 for every i 6 N. It is easily verified that a probabilistic value aß is strictly positive, if and only if pi (S) > 0 for every i and every S E C i , where {pi: i E N} is the collection of probability measures that define aß via (3.1). A coalition S is said to be a coalition ofpartners or a p-type coalition, in the garne v, if, for every T C S and each R ~ S c, v(R U T) = v(R). A solution aß satisfies the parmership axiom if, whenever S is a p-type coalition,
aßv(i) = aß(aßv(S)us)(i)
for every i e S.
The proof of the following theorem is given in Kalai and Samet (1987): THEOREM 4. A solution is a positively weighted value, if and only if it is a strictly positive probabilistic value that satisfies the partnership axiom. The set of positively weighted values is not closed in the space of solutions. Obviously every solution which is the limit of positively weighted values is a probabilistic value that satisfies the partnership axiom. We turn now to characterize such solutions by introducing the concept of weight systems. A weight system is a vector w = (wS)sECo in xS~CoA(S) that satisfies ws _
wF
wT (S )
(5.2)
2064
D. Monderer and D. Samet
whenever i 6 S __c T and w T ( S ) > 0. Note that any weight vector co can be identified with the weight system w, where w s = o~i for every i 6 S c Co. The set of all weight systems is denoted by )4;. For w 6 ~4; the weighted value ~ow (which is called the wvalue) is defined as the unique linear operator which is defined for every unanimity garne us by
{w s, for i ~ s, ~°Wus(i) =
0,
(5.3)
f o r i ~ S.
The w-value of a unanimity garne in (5.3) can be interpreted as follows. Every weight system w defines an ordered partition (Nl . . . . . NI¢) of N (where k depends on w). The players in N1 are those players i for whom w/N > 0. The coalition Nh, for 1 < h ~< k, (U h-I N1) c
(I Ih-1 N1) c, f o r w h i c h 11)i /=1 > 0. consists of all the players i in ~~l=l For S c Co, let h = h(S) be the frst index for which S N Nh # 0. Then ~0~ allocates among the players in S A Nh their share, u s ( N ) = 1, proportional to their weights in w Nh while ~oWus(i) = 0 for all other players. To show that every weighted value is a path value, Kalai and Samet (1987) defined independent random variables zi, i c N with pairwise disjoint supports, such that if ih C Nh, for h = 1 . . . . . k, then prob(zh > zi 2 > " ' ' > Zik) • 1. The distribution of each zi is defined on its support in [0, 1] by a linear transformation of the distribution given in (5.1) with
tO~N~~_l 1 - " N S when i c Nh. Kalai and Samet (1987) proved:
coi =
THEOREM 5. A solution is a weighted value if and only if it is a quasivalue that satisfies the partnership axiom. Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) presented two new approaches to value theory: the potential approach and the consistency approach. They showed that these approaches are naturally extended to the case of positively weighted values. Hefe we present their theory using a slighfly different notation. For a garne v and a coalition S we denote the restriction of v to S by v s. That is, v s ~ G(S) and v s (T) = v(T) for every T ~ C(S). Let AG = Usc_N G(S). A function P:AG--+ R is a co-potentialfunction, for a weight vector co 6 A ( N ) (that is, c o i > 0 for every i 6 N), if for every v c G
~_~(p(vS)-p(vS\i))=v(S),
P(v~)=O and
foreveryS#O.
(5.4)
iöS
Note that if (5.4) holds, then it also holds for every v ~ G ( T ) for S c T C N. Hart and Mas-Colell proved that there exists a unique co-potential function, denoted by P~o, and called the co-potential function of G. It satisfies 1
p~o(vs ) =
L
~(u(t)«s) dt, t
Ch. 54:
Variations on the Shapley Value
2065
where o~(t)(i) = t `°i for every i c N, and where for x, y ~ R N, x y is the vector defined b y ( x y ) i -= xiyi for every i C N. The e-potential function, Pe, is called the potential function (or simply the potential) of G. Note that Po)v ---- E ( 1 f~ v ( N ( t ) ) dt), where N ( t ) is given by (4.3) with the random variables (Zi)ieN defined by (5.1). Hart and Mas-Colell also proved: THEOREM 6. Let co ~ A (N) be a weight vector. Then f o r every game v and every i
99c°v(i)
:coi[Pco(v N) --
e N,
po)(vN\i)].
We now present the consistency property of weighted values. A function ~ß :AG U s c c A(S) is called an extended solution if Ov s c A(S) for every S ~ C. Thus, an extended solution is a collection of solutions ~ßs on G(S) such that OSvS = ~ v s for every coalition S. L e t ~ be an extended solution and let T _c S. We define the reduced (s,~) garne v T ' c G ( T ) as follows:
V(TS'~)(F) = v ( F U (S \ T)) -
~
~vFU(S\T)(i),
for all F __cT.
icS\T
An extended solution ~p is consistent if for every garne v 6 G, coalition S, and coalition T _ S,
~BV(TS'¢)(j) = VerS(j)
for every j C T.
Hart and Mas-Colell prove that for a fixed weight vector co, the co-weighted Shapley value, regarded in a natural way as an extended solution (that is, (~o~°)s = ~o°A, where cos is the restriction of co to S), is consistent. Moreover, they proved that if an extended solution ~ is consistent and coincides with the co-weighted extended value on twoperson games, then it is the co-weighted extended value on AG. They further used the consistency axiom to give an axiomatic characterization for positively weighted values. THEOREM 7. An extended solution is a co-value, f o r some weight vector co, if and only if it is consistent, and f o r two-person games it is efficient, TU-invariant 3, and monotonic. We end this discussion with a result concerning the weighted values of a garne as a set-valued solution. Whatever the meaning of the weight vector w, it reflects certain properties or information about the players, not derived from the garne, but rather given exogenously. If we lack this information, we can consider the less informative set-valued solution W ( v ) = {q)Wv: w ~ I/V}. Let C(v) denote the core of v and let AC(v) be the anti-core of v, which consists of all x E A such that x (S) ~< v (S) for every S and x (N) = v(N). Monderer, Samet, and Shapley (1992) proved: 3 That is, ~ß(av{i'j) + #{i'J}) = aßv {i'j} -[- #{i,j}, for every i 5~j, a > 0 and # a A.
2066
D. Monderer and D. Samet
THEOREM 8. F o r e v e r y g a m e v,
C(v) U AC(v) c_ W(v). That there is such a general relationship between the core and values is somewhat surprising in light of the difference in concept behind these solutions. Theorem 8 generalizes a theorem of Weber (1988), who proved that C(v) c_ Q(v), where Q(v) is the Weber set, i.e., the set of all O(v) where 7" ranges over all quasivalues. REMARKS.
(1) Monderer, Samet and Shapley (1992) discussed geometrical and topological properties of the set of weight systems W (which is homeomorphic to the set of weighted values, because the map w --> ~ow is one-to-one). W can easily be seen to be homeomorphic to the set of conditional systems that was discussed in the literature on non-cooperative garne theory [e.g., see Myerson (1986) and McLennan (1989a, 1989b)]. The main theorem of McLennan (1989b) states that this set is homeomorphic to a ball. Monderer, Samet and Shapley (1992) proved that for a strictly convex game v, W is mapped homeomorphically onto the core of v by the mapping w --+ q)wv. This gives a new proof for McLennan's theorem. Moreover, the well-studied geometry of the core of strictly convex games [see Shapley (1971)] is reflected in the structure of W. (2) Shapley (1981) proposed a family of weighted cost allocation schemes which, when translated into the language of cooperative garne theory, yield the dualweighted values. The dual garne, v*, of a game v is defined by: v* (S) = v(N) v(SC). For w E W, the dual w-weighted value is defined by: G~vw= ~0Wv,. Shapley gave an axiomatization for solutions ~B:G x W --+ A of the form (v, co) -+ ~o,~°v. Kalai and Samet (1987) axiomatized the family of dual-weighted values, explored the relationship between weighted and dual-weighted values, and used this relationship in order to give an axiomatization of the Shapley value that does not use the symmetry axiom. Dual-weighted values are also discussed in Monderer, Samet and Shapley (1992), where it is shown that a theorem analogous to Theorem 8 can be stated for these solutions.
6. Symmetric probabilistic values (semivalues) As semivalues are not efficient (except for the Shapley value), they cannot be considered as mechanisms for benefit or cost shariug. However, they can be interpreted as indices of power. The structure of power is usually described by a simple garne, and therefore it is of interest to study semivalues as solutions defined on such garnes. But before doing so, we first analyze semivalues on all of G. Recall that the probabilities ( p i ) i ~ N , where pi E A(Ci), by which a probabilistic value ~ß can be expressed, as in (3.1), are uniquely determined by gr. If in addition O is
Ch. 54." Variations on the Shapley Value
2067
symmetric, i.e., it is a semivalue, then it can easily be seen that pi (S) depends only on the number of elements of S. That is, there exists a function 13- {0, 1 . . . . . n - 1 } --+ [0, 1] such that for every i, pi (S) =/3 (s),
(6.1)
where s denotes the number of elements in S. Obviously, n-1
Z
il(s)
(n-l)
=1"
s
(6.2)
s=0
Thus, we get the following characterization of semivalues given in Dubey, Neyman and Weber (1981): THEOREM 9. A solution ~ is a semivalue if and only if there exists a function B:{0, 1..... n-
1}--+ [0, 1],
that satisfies (6.2) such that ~ß = q)~, where for every garne v and player i,
~ofiv(i) = ~
fi(s)(v(S Ui)-- v(S)),
i 6 N.
(6.3)
S~C i
Moreover, the correspondence fl --+ ~ofi is one-to-one. Note that the Shapley value is q)B for il(s) - n(,Tl l ) for every 0 ~< s ~< n - 1. The Banzhaf value 4 is the semivalue defined by fi (s) = 2n1- 1 • By removing the efficiency axiom from the list of axioms defining the Shapley value, we obtain the family of semivalues. Thus, for a semivalue ~p, ~ v ( N ) is not necessarily v(N). It is interesting, then, to note that it is precisely what ~ gives to the grand coalition N, in the various garnes, which determines g,. This is what we state and prove next. THEOREM 10. Let gq and ge2 be two semivalues 5 that satisfy for each garne v, ~ßl v ( N ) = ~ 2 v ( N ) .
(6.4)
TheYl ~1 = ~2. 4 See Secfion 7. 5 This theorem can be proved for more general solutions, namely, for non-posifive semivalues which are linear, symmetric soluUons that satisfy the dummy axiom. Roth (1977) proved a special case of this stronger version of Theorem 10. He showed that the Banzhaf value is the only non-positive semivalue ~ that satisfies gtv(N) = q)bz v(N) for every garne v, where q)bz is the Banzhaf value.
2068
D. Monderer and D. Samet
PROOF. Let $ be the linear space of operators spanned by the set of semivalues. By Theorem 9, S is n-dimensional. For every garne v we define a linear functional fv : S --+ R, by f~(10) = 10v(N). Fix an order r on N, and for k = 1 . . . . . n, let vk be the unanimity garne on {r - l (1) . . . . . r - I (k)}. It is easily verified that fvl . . . . . fr,, äre linearly independent. Therefore, if 10 6 S and f~k (10) --= 0 for k = 1 . . . . . n, then 10 = 0. Thus, if 101 and 10~ satisfy (6.4), then 101 - 102 = 0. [] Dubey, Neyman and Weber (1981) characterized semivalues defined on garnes with finite support on an infinite universe of players. Let U be an infinite set of players. Denote by G f = G f ( U ) the space of all garnes on U with a finite carrier, and by A f = A f ( U ) the space of all additive garnes in G f . A solution, in this context, is a function 10 : G f --+ A f . The symmetry of a solution is defined as before, with slight and obvious changes. Probabilistic solutions are defined as follows. For every finite subset of players M and for every v E G ( M ) , denote by VM the natural extension of v to C(U), that is, VM(T) = v ( T A M) for T ___ U. Every solution 10 on G f defines a solution 10M on G ( M ) by 10M v(i) = 10VM (i) for every v e G ( M ) and every i c M. We say that 10 is a probabilistic value on G(U) if for every finite subset of players, M, 10M is a probabilistic value. Defining a semivalue as a probabilistic and symmetric solution, note that 10 is a semivalue if and only if 10M is a semivalue for every finite coalition M. THEOREM 11. Let U be an infinite set of players and let 10 be a solution on G f . Then 10 is a semivalue if and onIy if there exists a Borel probability measure ~ on [0, 1] such that f o r every finite coalition N with n elements, and for every v ~ G f with carrier N, 10v = 10~v, where, B~v(i)=
~
fln(s)(v(SUi)-v(S)),
i eN,
SCC_N\i
with fin(s) =
f0 l t s ( 1 - t ) n - S - l d ~ ( t )
forO<~s<~n-1.
(6.5)
Moreover, the correspondence ~ --+ 10~ is one-to-one. Note that (6.5) can be rewritten in terms of random independent arrival times like (4.4),
1
10v(i) =
f0
E ( v ( N ( t ) tA i) - v ( N ( t ) \ i)[zi = t)d~(t),
where N(t) is the random set defined in (4.5) with respect to n i.i.d, random variables Zl . . . . . z~, uniformly distributed on [0, 1]. Observe, however, that unlike (4.4) the integration here is with respect to ~ and not zi.
Ch. 54: Variationson the Shapley Value
2069
REMARKS. (1) Dubey, Neyman and Weber (1981) discussed continuity properties o f semivalues on Gf. For every v ~ G f the variation norm of v is: [[vl[ = inf{u(N) + w(N)}, where the supremum is over all monotone garnes u, w c G f such that u - w = v. With this norm both G f and A f are normed spaces. The continuity of semivalues is defined with respect to this norm. It is proved that a semivalue 7t~ is continuous if and only if ~ is absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure m on [0, 1], and its R a d o n - N i k o d y m derivative with respect to m is bounded, when considered as a m e m b e r of Lee(0, 1), that is, 1[dd~m[lee <: ~ . Moreover, the mapping g ~ ~ß~(g), where ~(g)(A) = )CAg dm, is an isometry in the natural sense. (2) Monderer (1988) discussed semivalues defined on symmetric subspaces of G. He proved that every such semivalue can be extended (not necessarily in a unique way) to a semivalue on G. Note that if ~ß is a semivalue and GO is the subspace of garnes v for which ~ßv(N) = v(N), then the restriction of lb' to any symmetric subspace of G ~ is a Shapley value on this subspace. Monderer's theorem proves that every Shapley value on a symmetric subspace of garnes is obtained in this manner.
7. Indices of power We denote the class of simple garnes by SG. A coalition S is a winning coalition in a simple garne v if v(S) = 1, and it is a losing coalition if v(S) = 0. Of special interest are monotone simple garnes. In such garnes, a superset of a winning coalition is a winning coalition, and a subset of a losing coalition is a losing one. 6 This property reflects the natural idea, especially for voting games, that by adding members to a coalition it becomes stronger. The set of monotone simple games is denoted by MSG and MSG \ {0} is denoted by MSG +. The set of superadditive simple garnes is denoted by SSG, and SSG + is SSG \ {0}. A solution defined on a subset of simple garnes is called an index ofpower. We refer the reader to Dubey and Shapley (1979), and Owen (1982) for a partial reference to articles about the use of indices of power in various areas, such as political science, law and electrical engineering. Other tban the linearity axiom, all axioms in Section 2 are applicable (and make sense with respect) to indices of power. We now present the transfer axiom, introduced by Dubey (1975), 7 which in some sense substitutes for the finearity axiom for indices of power. For any two garnes v and w we define the games (v v w) and (v/x w) by: (v v w)(S) = max(v(S), w(S)) and (v A w)(S) = min(v(S), w(S)). Note that both garnes are simple whenever v and w a r e simple games. 6 Many authors refer to a garne v c SG as a 0-1 garne, and reserve the notion "simple garne" for what we called a monotone simple garne, and some of those anthors even exclude the garne v = 0 from the set of simple garnes. 7 The name was suggested by Weber (1988).
D. Monderer and D. Samet
2070
(A. 12) A solution ge defined on a set M of simple games satisfies the transfer axiom if for every v, w E M for which v v w and v A w belong to M,
7r(v) + O(w) = 7r(v v w) + 7r(v A w). The next theorem, which is proved in Weber (1988), characterizes probabilistic valnes, and hence quasivalues and semivalues on simple garnes. THEOREM 12. An index of power defined on the set of simple garnes, or on the set of monotone simple garnes, is a probabilistic value if and only if it satisfies the transfer, dummy, and positivity axioms. Consequently, an index of power is a quasivalue on these sets of garnes if and only if it satisfies the transfer, durnmy, positivity and efficiency axioms, and it is a sernivalue if and only if it satisfies the transfer, dummy, positivity and symmetry axioms. Note that every probabilistic value ¢ that is defined on a set of simple games, which contains the unanimity garnes, can be uniquely extended to a probabilistic value on G. Moreover, if ~p is a quasivalue on such a set of simple garnes, then its extension is a quasivalue on G and if ~p is a semivalue, then its extension is a semivalue. This follows from the fact that the symmetry and efficiency axioms are "linear" axioms, in the sense that if they hold for a symmetric linear base of garnes then they hold for every garne. The extension property of power indices implies, in particular, that every quasivalue on simple garnes is a random-order value (see Theorem 3). Representations of indices of power as random-order values, or probabilistic values, have a special flavor. Let v 5~ 0 be a simple monotone garne, and let r ~ OR. The pivot for r in v is the unique player j = jT for whom the s e t R j , of players preceding j in r, is a losing coalition, while Rj U j is winning. Thus, for a probability measure b on the set of orders A(OR), ~pbv(i) is the b-probability that i is the pivot. In particular, the Shapley value [which is also called the Shapley-Shubik index of power - see Shapley and Shubik (1954)] of a player i in v is his probability of being the pivot when all orders have equal probability. We say that i is a swing for a coalition S in v, if v(S) = 0 and v(S U i) = 1. Let ~ be a probabilistic value defined by the probabilities pl . . . . . pn on C 1. . . . . C n , respectively. Then ~ßv (i) is the pi -probability that i is a swing for a random coalition of the other voters, s The Banzhaf index of power [Banzhaf (1965)] has been extensively discussed in the literature. Dubey and Shapley (1979) characterized the Banzhaf index on MSG + in the same way that Roth (1977) characterized the Banzhaf value on G (see Footnote 5). Lehrer (1988) gave another characterization, based on the behavior of an extended index of power when applied to garnes in which coalitions of the original garne are amalgamated into one player, as follows. For every 0 C T C N choose a player ir in T. Let v 8 See Straffin (1988) for other probabilistic interpretations of the Shapley-Shubik and the Banzhaf indices of power.
Ch. 54." Variations on the Shapley Value
2071
be a simple garne and let T be a nonempty coalition. Define two garnes v[v] and v~] on the set of players T c U {iT} as follows: v[T](S) = v~](S) = v(S) for every S c T e, and for every such S,
V[T](SUiT)=v(SUT)
and
v[m~](SUiT)= max v ( S U B ) . (OcBC_T
THEOREM 13. Let ~ß be an extended semivalue on the sets of simple garnes on subsets of N, 9 and let (iT)OcTcN be a collection of players such that iT E T. Then ~t is the Banzhaf index of power if and only if for every two-player coalition T = {i, j},
~v(i) + ~ v ( j ) <~tlrV[T](iT). Moreover, 7e is the Banzhaf index if and only if for each such T, Bv(i) + ~ßv(j) ~ ~ßVlnT](iT). REMARKS. (1) Einy (1987) characterized semivalues on MSG(U), when U is an infinite universe set of players. Actually he proved the "semivalues" part of Theorem 12 in such a setup. In his papers (1987, 1988), he also provided a formula for the Banzhaf index of power of a monotone simple game v in terms of the minimal winning coalitions of this garne. (2) For every positive weight vector w = (Wl . . . . . wn), and 0 < c < 1 we define the weighted majority garne, Vw,c with a quota c as follows:
Vw,c(S) =
{1, 0,
i f w ( S ) ~c; i f w ( S ) < c.
Dubey and Shapley (1979) have proved the following intriguing equality. For any probabilistic index of power ~p, fd ~ßVw,c(i) dc = wi.
8. Values with a social structure In all the variations on the Shapley value discussed in this section, there is some structure on the set of the players which is involved in determining the value of a garne. All are extensions of the Shapley value, because when the structure on N is the "trivial" one, where triviality depends on the type of structure used in the solution, then the value is the Shapley value.
Thatis, ~ : UscN SG(S) --+USCN A(S), 7er ~ A(S) for v ~ SG(S), and the restriction of ~ to SG(S) is a semivalue for every S c N.
9
2072
D. Monderer and D. Samet
Aumann and Drèze (1975) were the first to introduce such a structure into the smdy of value, by changing the efficiency axiom. Instead of assuming that the grand coalition, N, forms and allocates its worth, v(N), among its players, they assumed that there is a fixed partition zr -= {B1 . . . . . Bin} of N, which they called a coalitional structure, such that each coalition, Bh, forms and allocates its value, v(Bk), among its members. Using the following axioms they characterized a unique solution called the rc-value. A solution ~ is zr-efficient if for every garne v, ~pv(Bk) = V(Bk) for all 1 ~< k <~ m. A permutation 0 is rr-invariant if O(Bk) = Bh for every k, and ~ is zr-symmetric if ~ß(O*v) = O*Ov for every rc-invariant permutation 0. Aumann and Drèze (1975) proved: THEOREM 14. There exists a unique probabilistic value ~o~ which is Jr-symmetric and rc-efficient, called the ~r-value, and it is given by: ~ozrv(j) =~pvB~(j)
for j ~ Bh.
(8.1)
Note that by (8.1), for i c Bk, ~o~v(i) depends only on the game v ~k. Hence, the power of a player i 6 Bh to negotiate with players outside Bh is not taken into account when computing his share of v (Bh). Myerson (1977) studied a value, called the fair allocation rule, where the social structure is given by a graph with vertex set N. An arc (i, j) in graph g can be thought of as signifying some social relation, say a neighborhood or a channel of communication, between players i and j. For each coalition S, we denote by g ls the restriction of the graph g to the vertices in S. By 7rgls we denote the partition of S into the connected components of g Is. The axiomatization of the fair allocation rule is accomplished by fixing the garne v, and varying the social structure. A function (a : GR -+ A, where GR is the set of all graphs on N, is a fair allocation rule if it satisfies two properties: it is relatively efficient, by which we mean that Óg(S) = v(S) for every connected component of g; and it is fair in the sense that for any two graphs g and h such that h = g t J {(i, j)}, Bh(i) - (ag(i) = Oh(j) - (ag(j). Thus, (a is fair if, by adding an arc to a graph, the players forming this arc equally gain or lose. Myerson (1977) proved: THEOREM 15. For any garne v ~ G, there exists a unique function (am : GR ~ A which is a fair allocation, and it is given by, (a~m (g)=~o(vlg),
Ch. 54:
Variations on the Shapley Value
2073
where q9 is the Shapley value, and vlg is the garne which satisfies for each coalition S,
(vlg)(S)= ~
v(T).
TE7Cg[s
Note that each of the coalitions in the partition of N to its connected components, i.e., the partition rrglN, forms and allocates its worth among its members. Moreover, like the case of the 7r-value, the value of a player, in the fair allocation rule, is determined s o M y by the restriction of the garne to the coalition in rrg[N, of which he is a member. The following solution, introduced by Owen (1977), is based on a coalition structure, i.e., a partition 7v = {Bi . . . . . Bin} of N. But unlike the previous two solutions, it is a quasivalue, and as such it is efficient in the usual sense, that is, the players allocate the worth of the grand coalition N. By Theorem 3, a quasivalue is a random-order value, and the value proposed by Owen (1977) is the random-order value ~0b~ , defined by the probability distribution b~ ~ A (OR), which we describe next. We say that an order r is consistent with 7c if for each k = 1, . . . , m, all players in Bk an'ive "together" in the following sense. If i arrives before j, and both are in Bk, then all the players arriving between i and j are also in Bk. Let b~r ~ A (OR) be the probability measure that is uniformly distributed over all orders that are consistent with Jr. That is, it assigns the probability lm !b I !...bin ! to each such order, where bk denotes the number of players in Bk. This value, called the 7r-coalitional structure (cs) value was characterized in various setups by Owen (1977) and by Hart and Kurz (1983). We denote it by ~0es and need some additional notations before we can present a modified version of their axiomatization. Let 7c be a partition of N. For each v 6 G we define a partitional garne v~, the players of which are the coalitions in 7r, as follows. For each F c 7c,
We say that B1 and B2 are symmetric players in v~r if for every F __c~ that does not conrain BI and B2, v~ ( F U {B1 }) = v~r ( F U {B2}). A solution ~p satisfies the 7r-coalitional symmetry axiom if ~ßv(B1 ) = ~pv(B2) whenever B l and B2 are symmetric players in v~. The proof of the following theorem can be derived from Owen (1977) and Hart and Kurz (1983): THEOREM 16. Let ~ be a solution and let 7r be a partition. Then ~p is the 7r coalitional structure value if and only if gr is a random-order value that satisfies the 7r-symmetry and the 7r-coalitional symmetry axioms. Owen (1977) and Hart and Kurz (1983) explored some interesting properties of the Owen value. One such property is that the total value of a coalition B in 7r equals the
2074
D. Monderer and D. Samet
Shapley value of the player B in the game vr. That is,
~ocsv(B) = ~ovrr(B) = ~
~ov~ (i).
i~ß
The next question is how do the players in B distfibute the total amount available to them, ~ovrr(B). To answer this, we define for B ~ Jr a garne V(rr,B) in G(B). Let S _ B and denote by w s IS the partition refining ~r by splitfing B into S and B \ S. The garne v0r, B) is defined by:
1)(7c,B)(S) = (pb~BlSl)(S),
S c_ B.
THEOREM 17. For each i ~ B, ~ob~ v( i ) = (pvor,B) ( i ). Owen showed that Theorem 17 holds for i 6 S if zr8 IS is defined as the partition of N \ (B \ S) obtained from 7r by replacing B with S (i.e., the players in B \ S simply disappear). Hart and Kurz showed that Theorem 17 also holds when we define the game v0r, n ) by defining 7rB ]S as the partition obtained from 7r by replacing B with S and the singletons of B \ S. REMARKS. (1) Myerson (1980) extended the notion of the cooperation graph to a cooperation hypergraph, where a link can be formed among the members of a coalition with more than two players. (2) Amer and Carreras (1995) extended the notion of the cooperation graph to the weighted cooperation graph, called a cooperation index. More formally, a cooperation index is a function w : C -+ [0, 1] , where w(S) may be interpreted as the probability of a communication link among the members of S. Namrally, it is required that w({i}) = 1 for every player i. Amer and Carreras (1997) further discussed cooperation indices in the context of weighted Myerson values. (3) Owen (1977) and Hart and Kurz (1983) gave an axiomatic characterization of the coalitional structure value as an operator which is defined on pairs (v, re), using axioms that consider changes in the values of such an operator when both the game and the partition are changed. (4) McLean (1991) defined and analyzed coalitional structure random-order values, as follows. Let ~ be a partition of N and let b E A (OR). b is consistent with rr if b(r) = 0 for every order r which is not consistent with 7r. A random order value is a 7r random order coalitional structure value if it is defined by some b ~ A(OR) which is consistent with Jr. Levy and McLean (1989) defined and characterized weighted coalitional structure values.
Ch. 54:
Variations on the Shapley Value
2075
(5) McLean and Ye (1996) developed the theory of coalitional structure semivalues for finite games.
(6) Winter (1992) characterized the Owen value by a consistency property which generalizes the one given in Hart and Mas-Colell (1989). He also generalized the potential approach and showed that the Owen value, Myerson value and A-D value can be developed through this approach. (7) Winter (1989) developed the theory of values defined on pairs (v, p), where v G and p = (zrl . . . . . 7rm) is a decreasing sequence of partitions. 10 (8) Lucas (1963) and Myerson (1976) dealt with values of generalized garnes, where the worth of a coalition also depends on the partition into coalitions generated by the players.
Referenees Amer, R., and E Carreras (1995), "Garnes and cooperation indices", International Journal of Garne Theory 3:239-258. Amer, R., and E Carreras (1997), "Cooperation indices and weighted Shapley values", Mathematics of Operations Research 22:955-968. Aumann, R.J., and J.H. Drèze (1975), "Cooperative garnes with coalition structures", International Journal of Garne Theory 4:217-237. Banzhaf, J.F., IlI (1965), "Weighted voting does not work: A mathematical analysis", Rutgers Law Review 19:317-343. Block, H.D., and J. Marschak (1960), "Random ordering and stochastic theories of responses", Cowles Foundation Paper, No. 147. Dubey, P. (1975), "On the uniqueness of the Shapley value", International Journal of Garne Theory 4:131-139. Dubey, E, and L.S. Shapley (1979), "Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index", Mathematics of Operations Research 4:99-131. Dubey, P., A. Neyman and R.J. Weber (1981), "Value theory without efficiency", Mathematics of Operations Research 6:122-128. Einy, E. (1987), "Semivalues of simple garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 12:185-192. Einy, E. (1988), "The Shapley value on some lattices of monotonic garnes", Mathematical Social Sciences 15:1-10. Falmagne, J.C. (1978), "A representation theorem for finite random scale systems", Journal of Mathematical Psychology 18:52-72. Gilboa, I., and D. Monderer (1991), "Quasivalues on subspaces of garnes", International Joumal of Garne Theory 19:353-363. Gilboa, I., and D. Monderer (1992), "A garne theoretic approach to the binary stochastic choice problem", Journal of Mathematical Psychology 36:555-572. Hart, S., and M. Kurz (1983), "Endogenous formation of coalitions", Econometrica 51:589~14. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1989), "Potential, value and consistency", Econometrica 57:589-614. Kalai, E., and D. Samet (1987), "On weighted Shapley values", International Joumal of Game Theory 16:205222. Lehrer, E. (1988), "An axiomatization of the B anzhaf value", International Journal of Garne Theory 17:89-99. Levy, A., and R.R McLean (1989), "Weighted coalition structure values", Garnes and Economic Behavior 1:234-249.
10 The idea for dealing with such values appears in Owen (1977).
2076
D. Monderer and D. Samet
Lucas, W.E (1963), "n-Person garnes in partition function form", Naval Research Logistics Quarterly 10:281298. McLean, R.E (1991), "Random order coalition strncture values", International Joumal of Garne Theory 20:109-127. McLean, R.E, and T.X. Ye (1996), "Coalition strncture semivalues of finite garnes", Rutgers University. McLennan, A. (1989a), "Consistent systems in noncooperative garne theory", International Journal of Garne Theory 18:141-174. McLennan, A. (1989b), "The space of condidonal systems is a ball", International Journal of Garne Theory 18:127-140. Monderer, D. (1988), "Values and semivalues on subspaces of finite garnes", International Joumal of Garne Theory 17:321-338. Monderer, D. (1990), "A Milnor condition for nonatomic Lipschitz garnes and its applications", Mathematics of Operations Research 15:714-723. Monderer, D. (1992), "The stochastic choice problem: A garne theoretic approach", Journal of Mathematical Psychology 36:547-554. Monderer, D., D. Samet and L.S. Sbapley (1992), "Weighted Shapley values and the core", International Joumal of Garne Theory 21:27-39. Myerson, R.B. (1976), "Values of garnes in partition function form", International Journal of Garne Theory 6:23-31. Myerson, R.B. (1977), "Graphs and cooperation in garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 2:225-229. Myerson, R.B. (1980), "Conference stmctures and fair allocation rules", International Jottrnal of Garne Theory 9:169-182. Myerson, R.B. (1986), "Multistage garnes with communication", Econometrica 54:323-358. Owen, G. (1972), "Multilinear extension of garnes", Management Sciences 5:64-79. Owen, G. (1977), "Values of garnes with a priori unions", in: R. Henn and O. Moeschlin, eds., Matbematical Economics and Garne Theory (Springer, Berlin). Owen, G. (1982), Garne Theory, 2nd edn. (Academic Press, Orlando). Roth, A.E. (1977), "Bargaining ability, the utility of playing a game, and models of coalition formation", Journal of Mathematical Psychology 16:153-160. Roth, A.E., ed. (1988), "The Shapley Value (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Shapley, L.S. (1953a), "A value for n-person garnes", Annals of Mathematics Studies 28:307-317. Shapley, L.S. (1953b), "Additive and non-additive set functions", PhD Thesis (Dept. of Mathematics, Princeton University). Shapley, L.S. (1971), "Cores of convex garnes", International Journal of Garne Theory 1:11-26. Shapley, L.S. (1981), "Discussant's comments: Equity considerafions in traditional full cost allocation practices", in: Proceedings of the University of Oklahoma Conference on Cost Allocation, April 1981, 131-136. Shapley, L.S., and M. Shubik (1954), "A method for evaluating the distribufion of power in a committee system", American Political Science Review 48:787-792. Straffin, P.D., Jr. (1988), "The Shapley-Sbubik and Banzhaf power indices as probabilities", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value (Cambridge University Press, Cambfidge) 71-81. Weber, R.J. (1988), "Probabilistic values for garnes", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value (Carnbfidge University Press, Cambridge) 101-119. Winter, E. (1989), "A value for garnes with level strnctures", International Journal of Garne Tbeory 18:227240. Winter, E. (1992), "The consistency and potential for values of garnes with coalition sn-ucture", Garnes and Economic Behavior 4:132-144.
Chapter 55
VALUES OF NON-TRANSFERABLE
UTILITY GAMES
RICHARD E McLEAN
Department of Economics, NJ Hall, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ, USA
Contents 1. Notation and definitions 1.1. General notation 1.2. Transferable utility garnes 1.3. Non-transferable utility garnes
2. Values and bargaining solutions 2.1. Random order values 2.2. Weighted Shapley values 2.3. The Shapley value 2.4. Bargaining solutions on FNB
3. The Shapley NTU value 3.1. The definition of the Shapley NTU value 3.2. An axiomatic approach to the Shapley NTU value 3.3. Non-symmetric generalizations of the Shapley NTU value
4. The Harsanyi solution 4.1. The Harsanyi NTU value 4.2. The Harsanyi solution 4.3. A comparison of the Shapley and Harsanyi NTU value
5. Multilinear extensions for NTU garnes 5.1. Multilinear extensions and Owen's approach to the NTU value 5.2. A non-symmetric generalization 5.3. A comparison of the Harsanyi, Owen and Shapley NTU approaches
6. The Egalitarian solution 6.1. Egalitarian values and Egalitafian solutions 6.2. An axiomatic approach to the Egalitarian value 6.3. An axiomatic approach to the Egalitalian solution
7. Potentials and values of NTU garnes 7.1. Potentials and the Egalitarian value of finite garnes 7.2. Potentials and the Egalitarian solution of large garnes
8. Consistency and values of NTU garnes 8.1. Consistency and TU garnes: The Shapley value
Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2079 2079 2079 2079 2081 2081 2081 2082 2082 2083 2083 2085 2088 2091 2091 2093 2095 2096 2096 2099 2099 2100 2100 2101 2102 2103 2103 2105 2109 2109
2078
R.P. McLean
8.2. Consistency and NTU garnes: The Egalitarian value 8.3. The consistent value for hyperplane garnes 8.4. The consistent value for general NTU games 8.5. Another comparison of NTU values 9. Final remarks 9.1. Values and cores of convex NTU garnes 9.2. Applications of values for NTU garnes with a continuum of players 9.3. NTU values for games with incomplete information References
2110 2110 2113 2115 2116 2116 2117 2117 2118
Abstract This chapter surveys a class of solution concepts for n-person games without transferable utility - NTU games for s h o r t - that are based on varying notions o f " f a i r division". A n NTU garne is a specification of payoffs attainable by members of each coalition through some joint course of action. The players confront the problem of choosing a payoff or solution that is feasible for the group as a whole. This is a bargaining problem and its solution may be reasonably required to satisfy various criteria, and different sets of rules or axioms will characterize different solutions or classes of solutions. For transferable utility games, the main axiomatic solution is the Shapley Value and this chapter deals with values of NTU garnes, i.e., solutions for NTU garnes that coincide with the Shapley value in the transferable utility case. We survey axiomatic characterizations of the Shapley N T U value, the Harsanyi solution, the Egalitarian solution and the nonsymmetric generalizations of each. In addition, we discuss approaches to some of these solutions using the notions of potential and consistency for NTU garnes with finitely many as well as infinitely many players.
Keywords non-transferable utility, Shapley value, Harsanyi solution, Egalitarian solution, consistency, potential, consistent value
JEL classification: C710, C780
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2079
1. Notation and definitions 1.1. General notation Throughout this chapter, we work with a set o f p l a y e r s N = {1, 2 . . . . . n}. If S _c N, then iS] denotes the cardinality of S and N s is the ISI-dimensional Euclidean space whose axes are labelled with the members of S. The non-negative (positive) orthant of N s will be denoted by Ns+ ( 8~ + +s ) . Similarly, the non-positive orthant -Ns+ will be written 8t s . I f x e 8~N, then x s e 8t s is the "projection" o f x onto 8t s. The vector (1 . . . . . 1) in N s will be denoted l s . The "indicator vector" Z r 6 9l N is defined by )(~- = 1 if i e T and X~ = 0 if i ~ T. We write x ~> y if x i >~ yi f o r all i and x > y if x i > yi for all i. If x and u belong to N s and t e 8~, then x • u denotes the inner product, tx denotes scalar multiplication, and x * u ~ 9l s is defined by (x • u) i = xiu i. If A, B c 8t N, y 6 ~N and t ~ ff/then A + B is the Minkowski sum of A and B, A + y = A + {y}, y * A = {y * x I x e A} and tA = {tx I x c A}. The Pareto efficient boundary of A is denoted OA and the complement of A is written ~ A. If A is convex, then A is smooth if there exists a unique supporting hyperplane at each point of OA. A set A is comprehensive if x e A and x ~> y imply that y e A. To simplify the notation we will not distinguish between i and {i }. The symbol "V' denotes set theoretic subtraction.
1.2. Transferable utility garnes A TU game is a set function v : 2 N --+ 8] satisfying v(0) = 0. (If X is a set, then 2 x denotes the power set o f X.) The 2 n - l - d i m e n s i o n a l vector space of TU garnes is denoted by GN. If ~ : GN ---> ~)~N is a function and S c N, define (Ov)(S) -- ~ i e s ~i (1)). A garne v is monotonic if v(S) <~ v ( T ) whenever S _ T. For each nonempty T c N, the unanimity garne UT is defined by UT(S) = 1 if T c S and u r ( S ) = 0 otherwise. (It is well known that the collection {uT}o¢r_CN is a basis for GN.) Player i e N is a null player in v if v(S U i) - v(S) = 0 whenever S c_ N \ i , while player i e N is a dummy player in v if v(S U i) - v(S) = v(i) whenever S ~ N \ i . Players i and j are substitutes in v if v(S U i) = v(S U j ) whenever S c_ N \ { i , j}. A coalition S ~ N is flat in v if v(S) = ~ i c s v(i). The collection of n! orderings of the elements of N will be denoted F2N. If R = (il . . . . . in) is an element o f ~QN and i = i~, let X i ( R ) -~ {il . . . . . ik-1} be the set of players thatprecede i in R. ( X i (R) = 13 if i = il .) The marginal contribution o f i in R in the garne v is defined as z~i ( R, v) =-- v( Xi ( R ) U i) - v( Xi ( R ) ). Finally, let M ( U2N ) denote the set o f probability measures on F2N. 1.3. Non-transferable utility games An N T U garne V is a con'espondence that assigns to each nonempty S _c N a nonempty subset V ( S ) c 8i s. If V is an N T U garne, let V*(S) = V ( S ) x {0 N\s} for each S _ N. (In many treatments, an N T U garne is defined as V* rather than V.) If V and W a r e NTU
2080
R.PM c L e an
garnes, t ~ 9t and L 6 91N, then (V + W)(S) = V(S) + W(S), ()~ * V)(S) = ) s , V(S), and (tV)(S) = tV(S). Define FN to be the set of NTU garnes V for which each set V (S) is a proper, convex, closed, comprehensive subset of 91s. In the discussion that follows, we will need to consider certain subclasses of Fu whose members satisfy some of the following additional restrictions: (1) V(N) is smooth; (2) i f x , y ~ OV(N) andx >/y, thenx = y; (3) for each S ___N, there exists an x E 91u such that V*(S) c_ V(N) + x; oc is a sequence in V(S) with Xm+l >~Xm for each m, then there exists (4) if {Xm}m=~ y ~ 91s such that Xm <~y for all m; (5) for each S _c N, the set of extreme points of V(S) is bounded. The main subclasses of Fu that we study are listed now: F~ consists of those garnes in Fu satisfying conditions (1), (2) and (3) above, BN1 consists of those garnes in FN satisfying conditions (1), (2), (3) and (5) above, F 2 consists of those garnes in Fu satisfying conditions (1) and (2) above, FN3 consists of those garnes in FN satisfying condition (4). Condition (1) above is a regularity condition that guarantees that utility is locally transferable according to uniquely determined rates of transfer. Condition (2) is a "nonlevelness" assumption and guarantees that a normal vector to a boundary point of V (N) has positive components. Condition (3) is a weak version of monotonicity while (4) is a weak boundedness assumption. Condition (5) is important for the existence of some of the concepts we discuss below. If v ~ Gu, then the NTU garne corresponding to v is defined by
~~')={~~~'~~~i~-~~'~l icS
If V corresponds to v, we will sometimes say that v generates V. For each T ___N, the NTU game corresponding to the unanimity game u T will be denoted Ur. The collection of all NTU garnes corresponding to TU garnes is denoted FrNU and, obviously, F~ u c_ For any NTU garne V E FN, let dv ~ 91u be the vector with d~ = max{x i I xi V(i)} for each i. The collection of V E FN with dv ~ V(N) is denoted FNIR. A garne V 6 F~ R is a Pure Bargaining Problem if
V (S) = {x ~ N s ] xi <~dir for eachi ~ S} for each S ~ N, dv ~ ÕV(N) and the set {x E V(N) I x >~dr} is compact. The class of bargaining problems in F~ R is denoted FN~ .
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable UtilityGames
2081
2. Values and bargaining solutions We will record several solutions for TU garnes and bargaining problems whose NTU extensions are the focus of this chapter. We will also provide statements of characterization theorems since they will be referenced in the sketches of proofs of their NTU generalizations.
2.1. Random order values For each p ~ M(~2N), the p-Shapley value is the linear function ~0p : GN -+ ~N defined as follows:
Bp(V) = ~ p ( R ) A i ( R , v). RcF2 A p-Shapley value is also called a random order value or a quasivalue and four axioms characterize the class of such values. In the statements of the axioms, ~ß : Gg ---->~N is a function. SI: (Linearity) For every vl, v2 ~ GN and real numbers «1 and ot2, B(Œ1Yl -~-O~2Y2) = Œl ~t(Yl ) -~- 0t2~(Y2).
$2: (Efficiency) For each v c GN, Oßv)(N) ----v(N). $3: (Null Players) If i is a null player in v, then ~i (y) = 0. $4: (Monotonicity) If v is monotonic, then ~ßi (v) ~> 0 for all i 6 N. PROPOSITION 2.1.1 [Weber (1988)].An operator ~ß : GN --+ ~)~Nsatisfies S1-$4 if and
only if there exists p e M (~ ) such that ~ß : ~Op. 2.2. Weighted Shapley values We now turn to a special class of p-Shapley values, the weighted Shapley values. If w 6 ~N+, let pW C M(~2) be the probability measure defined as follows: n I - - - k' 1
f o r e a c h R : ( i i , i 2 . . . . . in) CU2N, p W ( R ) : l - I l w i ~ / ~ - ~ w b I. k1: l l
:--tl
Hence, orderings are constructed according to the following procedure. Player i e N is chosen to be at the end of the line with probability w i / ~ j e N wJ. Given that the players in S are already in line, player i c N \ S is added to the front of the line with probability wi / ~ jeN\S wj" Define the weighted Shapley value with weight vector w (of simply the
w-Shapley value) as the operator ~pp~ : GN --> fitN. For simplieity, we will denote ~pp~ as ~ow.
R.RMcLean
2082
The w-Shapley value was defined in Shapley (1953a) and axiomatized in Kalai and Samet (1987) where it is called the "weighted Shapley value for simple weight systems". The w-Shapley value satisfies S 1-$4 but two other axioms are required to characterize the class of w-Shapley values. First, $4 taust be strengthened to guarantee that each R c a'-2Noccurs with positive probability. S4': (Positivity) If v ~ G N is monotonic and contains no null players, then ~ßi (v) > 0 for all i ~ N. The second axiom guarantees that the probability measure on orders has the special form pW for some w c 91N+. A coalition T c N is apartnership in v if v(S U R) = v(A) whenever S _c T, S ~ T and A c_ N \ T . For example, T is a partnership in uT. $5: (Partnership) If T is a partnership in v, t h e n l/.ri (v) = ~ i [(I~rv)(T)UT ] for each
icT. Informally, Axiom $5 states that the behavior of a partnership T in a garne v is the same as the behavior of T in u r in the sense that the fraction of ( ~ v ) ( T ) received by i ~ T is the same as i's fraction of the one unit being allocated to T in uv. PROPOSITION 2.2.1 [Kalai and Samet (1987)]. An operator ~ß : GN ~ ~t N satisfies Axioms S1, $2, $3, S d and $5 if and only if there exists w ~ NN+ such that ~ = ~Ow. REMARK 2.2.2. Axioms S1, $2, $3, $4 and $5 characterize the weighted Shapley values for "general weighted systems" [see Kalai and Samet (1987)].
2.3. The Shapley value If w 6 gtN+ and w i = wJ for all i, j ~ N, then pW(R) = ~.1 for each R ~ X?. In this case, we write ~ow simply as ~o and refer to ~o as the Shapley value. An additional axiom is required to guarantee equal weights. $6: (Substitution) I f i and j are substitutes in v, then ~ßi (v) = o J (v). PROPOSITION 2.3.1 [Shapley (1953b)]. An operator ~B:G N ~
~}~N satisfies Ax-
ioms S1, $2, $3 and S6 if and only if gr = % 2.4. Bargaining solutions on FNB Let w = (w 1, W 2 . . . . .
tOn) 6 9t+N+ be a vector of weights. For a game V 6 FN~, define
Crw( V ) = argmax I - [ ( xi - d~ ) wi" xcV(N) icN
x >~dv
The set «w (V) is a singleton because V ( N ) is convex and the function Crw : FNB --~ gt N
Ch. 55:
Values of Non-Transferable Utility Games
2083
is the weighted Nash Bargaining Solution with the weight vector w or simply the wNBS. One can charactefize the w-NBS on FN8 axiomatically and a proof may be found in Roth (1979) or Kalai (1977a). If the components of the weight vector are identical, then we write rrw simply as a and refer to a as the Nash Bargaining Solution or NBS for short. The NBS was defined and axiomatically characterized in Nash (1950) and a detailed discussion may be found in Chapter 24. We will be interested in another solution for bargaining problems. Again, let w 9~N+, V C FN8 and define
rw(V) : = d r + t*(V, w)w where t*(V, w) = max[t ] dv + tw c V(N)]. The function rw : Fff ~ ~)~N is the wproportional solution with weight vector w. If the components of w a r e all equal, then we write rw simply as r and refer to r as the (symmetric) proportional solution for V. The w-proportional solution was defined and axiomatized in Kalai (1977b).
3. The Shapley NTU value 3.1. The definition of the Shapley NTU value Let V E FN and for X E ~N+, define vk(S) = s u p [ X s . z I z 6 V(S)]. The TU garne vx is definedfor V if vk (S) is finite for each S. DEFINITION 3.1.1. A vector x 6 ~N is a Shapley NTU value payoff for V ~ FN if there exists k ~ ~tN+ such that: (1) x ~ V(N), (2) vk is defined for V, (3) ,k • x = ¢p(vk). Condition (1) states that x is feasible for the grand coalition. Conditions (2) and (3) are best understood by frst looking at a two-person game in FNB. In this case, conditions (1), (2) and (3) are equivalent to: (x 1, x 2) ~ arg max[klx ' -+-k2x2 I x c V(1, 2)] and
)~I(x1-dI)=)v2(x2-d2).
2084
R.PMcLean
These are precisely the two conditions that characterize (x 1, x 2) as the NBS of V. Inmitively, an arbitrator might desire to choose a payoff (x 1, x 2) e V (1, 2) that is "utilitarian" in the sense that x 1 + x 2 = max[z I + z 2 I z e V(1, 2)] and "equitable" in the sense that x 1 - dlv = x 2 - d 2 (i.e., ner utility gains are equal). In general, these two criteria cannot be satisfied simultaneously. However, it may be possible to rescale the utility of the two players and achieve a balance of utilitarianism and equity in terms of the rescaled utilities. This is precisely what is accomplished by the NBS. Hence, conditions (1) and (2) of Definition 3.1.1 provide an extension of utilitarianism to the n-player problem while condition (3) is an extension of equity. (The indefinite article is used here because other extensions of equity and efficiency are possible as shown in Sections 4 and 6 below.) An alternative definition of Shapley NTU payoffis possible using the idea of dividend in Harsanyi (1963). DEFINITION 3.1.2. A vector x e ff[N is a Shapley NTU value payoff for V ~ FN if there exists Z 6 ~N+ and a collection of numbers {ort }~¢r_cN such that:
(1)
x e V(N),
(2) vx is defined for V, (3))~ixi = ~-~~TCN: i~T OlT and Sims ETC_S: i c T OIT = vz(S) whenever S __c_N. The equivalence of Definitions 3.1.1 and 3.1.2 follows from the fact that
i~S TES: i c T
Tc_S
[See Aumann and Shapley (1974), Appendix A, Note 5.] The numbers C~T are interpreted as dividends that will be paid to the members of T. Suppose that the proper subcoalitions of S have all declared their dividends. Then each i E S collects ~TcS: SCT,icT aT and condition (3) of Definition 3.1.2 requires that each member of S receive a dividend a s equal to
v»~(s)-~ß
I2
icS Tc_s: STET, icT
~~
Since each player in S receives the same dividend, condition (3) is an alternative view of the equity requirement of a Shapley value payoff. From Definition 3.1.1, we see that, if V corresponds to v ~ GN, then L must be a positive multiple of 1N so that q9(v) is the unique Shapley NTU value payoff for V. The Shapley NTU value is also an extension of the NBS to general NTU games in the sense that these solutions coincide for V e FN~ whenever 4~ (V) 5& 0. PROPOSITION 3.1.3. I f V e FN~, then qb(V) = {o-(V)).
Ch. 55:
Values of Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2085
PROOF. Using an argument from convex programming, it can be shown that x = o-(V) if and only if there exists ~ 6 9~+N+ such that (i) oi(xi - dir) = oJ(x j - d j ) for all i, j 6 N and (ii) 7" x = max[~, z ] z 6 V(N)]. Let V E FNB and suppose y e 4~(V) with associated comparison vector )~ c ~N+. It follows that y c V(N) and that vz(S) is flat f o r e a c h S ~ N . Inparticular, vx(S) = E i e s Xi d vi for each S ~ N. Therefore,
•
-
-Xd v=
vz(N)-Evx(j) jEN
for each i, (i) and (ii) are satisfied and it follows that x = er(V). Conversely, suppose that x = (r(V). Then there exists X e 9~N+ such that (i) and (ii) are satisfied. Letting oh(N) = max[)~ " z [z e V(N)] and vx(S) ---- E i e S ~"i dvi for each S 5&N, we conclude that vx is defined for V. Since ) ~ i x i = (flio)k), it follows that x is a Shapley NTU value payoff for V. []
3.2. An axiomatic approach to the Shapley NTU value In the previous section, it was shown that the set of Shapley NTU value payoffs coincides with the Shapley value for the TU garnes and the Nash Bargaining Solution for pure bargaining games. Thus, it is natural to synthesize the axiomatic characterization of these two solutions in an effort to construct a characterization for the Shapley NTU value. This approach is precisely the method of attack in Aumann (1985a) and Kern (1985). Let q5 : FN1 --+ ~f~N be the correspondence that associates with each V in F u1 the set of NTU value payoffs. The solution correspondence 4~ will be referred to as the Shapley correspondence. Let/~N1 be the set of NTU garnes V E FN~ such that ~ ( V ) ~ 0. In the statement of the axioms, ~P :/~N1 --+ ~ is a correspondence and U, V and W a r e garnes in/~N1 . A0: (Non-Emptiness) ~P(V) ~ 0. A I : (Efficiency) ~o(V) c 0 V (N). A2: (ConditionalAdditivity) If U ----V + W, then [q/(V) + tP(W)] M OU(N) c_ kü(U). A3: (Unanimity) If UT corresponds to the unanimity garne with carrier T, then ~(uT) = {x~'/ITI}. A4: (Scale Covariance)If~ E 9~N+, then qJ(o~, V) --=t~, q/(V). AS: (Independence of lrrelevant Alternatives) If V (N) c W (N) and V (S) = W (S) for S 5~ N, then gt(W) M V(N) c_ ~P(V). Axioms A0 and A1 are self-explanatory. A2 states that whenever the sum of two solution payoffs is Pareto optimal in the sum garne, then it taust be a solution payoff for the sum garne. A3 combines the symmetry and null player axioms of the TU theory. Mathematically, this axiom specifies a unique payoff for the NTU garnes corresponding to unanimity garnes. Axioms A4 and A5 are Nash's axioms extended to the NTU framework.
R.RMcLean
2086
The next three lemmas [all found in Aumann (1985a)] provide the essential steps in the characterization of the Shapley correspondence. LEMMA 3.2.1. IfqJ : ~ l __+ ~ satisfies Axioms AO A4 then ~ ( V ) = {g)(v)} whenever
V corresponds to the TU garne v. PROOF. For each real number oe, let V a correspond to the TU game o~v. Using A0, A1, A2 and A3, we deduce that ~P(V °) = {0}. Using Axioms A1 and A2 again, it can be shown that gt(V-1) + ~P(V) = {0} so A0 implies that qJ(V -1) = - k o ( V ) and each is single-valued. Combining A4 with the results above, we deduce that ~P(o~V) = c q~ (V) for all scalars ol. Using A3 it follows that q~(U~r) = o~~P(Ur) = { « X r / [ T [} = {~o(«ur)}. Since {ur}~¢r_CN is a basis for GN we can express each v • GN as v = ~ O ¢ r C N arUT SO that V = E T U~ r for the NTU garne V corresponding to v. Applying A1 and A2, we deduce that
Since ~P(V) is a singleton set, q ' ( V ) = {~o(v)}. LEMMA 3.2.2. If O satisfies axioms AO-A4, then ~ (V) c_ cB(V), for each V
[]
• F1N.
PROOF. Choose y • q~(V). By Axiom A1, y • OV(N). Using Axiom A4 and the nonlevelness assumption, we can assume without loss of generality that the unique normal to V(N) at y is A = 1N. If V ° corresponds to the TU garne that is identically zero, then y • Õ(V(N) + V°(N)) and V + V ° corresponds to vz. So using Lemma 3.2.1, A2 and Lemma 3.2.1 again, we get
)~*y • [~'(V)+CO}]@a(V(N)+V°(N)) : [~(V) + ~(V°)] N a(V(N) + V°(N)) _~
~,(v + v °)
Thus Z • y = ~0(vz) and we conclude that y • ~ ( V ) .
[]
LEMMA 3.2.3. If q~ satisfies Axioms AO-A5, then q~(V) c_ q/(v), for each V • Fk" PROOF. Choose y • q~(V) and A • 9~N+ such that vz is defined and X • y = ~p(v~). Let Vz be the NTU game corresponding to vz and define a game W as follows: {Vz (N)
W(S)=
xS.v(s)
if S = N, ifS¢N.
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable UtilityGames
2087
Since k • y c O(W), it follows that W 6/~N~ and Axiom A0 implies that ~ ( W ) 7~ 0. Again, let V ° correspond to the TU game that is identically zero so that Vk = W + V ° and O(W(N) + V°(N)) = OW(N). Using Lemma 3.2.1 and A2 and A1, we get
{e(~z)} = ~v(vz) = ~o(w + v 0) D [~P(W) + {0}] A O(W(N) + V°(N))
= q~(W) N OW(N) = ff'(W). Having already shown that ~o(W) ¢ 0, we conclude that ko(W) = {q)(vz)} = {k • y}. Since k * V(N) c_ W(N) and k s * V(S) = W(S) for S 7~ N, we can use A5 and A4 to deduce that {k • y} = q/(W) A [k * V(N)] _c q s ( k . V) = k • ~o(V) and, therefore,
y ~ q~(v).
[]
As the reader may verify, the Shapley correspondence O satisfies Axioms A 0 - A 5 and the main characterization result for the Shapley NTU value can now be stated. THEOREM 3.2.4 [Aumann (1985a)]. A correspondence gt : ~~ __+ ~ N satisfies Ax-
ioms AO-A5 if and only if q/ = O. If A5 is dropped from the axiomatization, then one obtains the following result as a consequence of Lemma 3.2.2. THEOREM 3.2.5 [Aumann (1985a)]. The Shapley correspondence •
satisfies Axioms AO-A4 and if q/ is any other correspondence satisfying Axioms AO-A4, then ~ ( V ) c_ O(V).
In Kern (1985), an alternative version of the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) is offered. ASt: (Transfer Independence of IrrelevantAlternatives) Ler V and W be games and let x 6 q/(V). If there exists a k ~ 9tN+ and a collection {~S}SC_N with ~N = X such that for each S c_ N, ~s c OV(S) N ÕW(S), k s is normal to V(S) at ~s and k s is normal to W(S) at ~s, then x 6 gt(W). As a general mle, IIA-type axioms stipulate that, once a solution has been determined, we can alter the garne "far away" from the solution and obtain a new game with the same solution. Indeed, this aspect of Nash's Bargaining Solution has been criticized on a variety of grounds and has resulted in alternatives to the NBS in which IIA has been replaced by other axioms. Axiom A51 has a local flavor as well. If ~s c ÕV (S) M 0 W(S) and k s is normal to V(S) and W(S) at ~s, then OV(S) and OW(S) are "similar near ~s". This is certainly true for S = N because of the smoothness assumption. When V and W are related in this way, the axiom requires that x 6 g'(W) i f x 6 ~ü(V). LEMMA 3.2.6. If q/" F1N ~ ~ N satisfies Axioms AO_A4 and A5 I, then O(V) c__gt(V),
for all V c F~.
2088
R.RMcLean
PROOF. Let y E q~(V). Then y E OV(N) and there exists )~ E N~+ such that )~ is a normal vector to V ( N ) at y, vz is defined and )~ • y = ~o(vz). Define the game W as in the proof of Lemma 3.2.3 and, using the same argument found there, conclude that )~ • y c g'(W). Upon defining L-1 = ( ~ . . . . . 1 ) , we deduce from A4 that y c q/(W)~) where Wz = )~- 1 . W. Therefore, y 6 ÓWx (N) and from the definition of W it follows that )~ is normal to W»~(N) at y. Since Wz(S) = V(S) for S ¢ N, we conclude that there exists a collection {~s}scN with ~Æ = y such that for each S c__N, ~s c 0 V ( S) M0 W)~( S) and ) s is normal to V (S) and Wz (S) at ~s- The conditions of A5' are therefore satisfied and it follows that y c ~v(V). [] It is easy to verify that the Shapley correspondence q3 satisfies A5' [see Kern (1985), Theorem 5.2] so Lemmas 3.2.2 and 3.2.6 combine to yield the following charactefization. THEOREM 3.2.7. A correspondence qj : ~ l __+ ~ N satisfies Axioms AO-A4 and A5 r if
and only if ql = 4. REMARK 3.2.8. Theorem 3.2.7 is essentially Theorem 5.5 of Kern (1985). However, Kern uses only Axioms A4 and A5' and a third axiom requiring that ~P(V) = {~0(v)} whenever V corresponds to the TU garne v. Lemma 3.2.1 makes clear the relationship between these two axiom systems. REMARK 3.2.9. In the statements of Theorems 3.2.4 and 3.2.7, the domain of the correspondence ~P is F~ and some may find this an aesthetic drawback. However, there are smaller domains that one could work with. For example, the characterization theorems will still be true if one works with the smaller collection F'~. For V 6 F'N1, a fixed point argument can be used to verify that A0 holds. For a more detailed discussion see Aumann (1985a). The existence question is also treated at length in Kern (1985) where conditions different from smoothness and nonlevelness of V(N) are identified that guarantee the existence of Shapley NTU value payoffs.
3.3. Non-symmetric generalizations of the Shapley NTU value In the axiomatic characterization of the Shapley value, the Nash Bargaining Solution and the Shapley NTU value, some type of symmetry postulate is required. Basically, these symmetry axioms all guarantee that two players who affect the garne in the same way will receive the same payoff. However, one can envision circumstances in which two players who are identical in terms of the data of the garne might nonetheless be treated asymmetrically in the arbitrated solution. For example, two workers with the same productivity may be treated differently because orte has attained seniority. Thus, an arbitrator might assign weights to the individuals that reflect the relative "importance" of each person in the resolution of the bargaining problem. Our next problem is to define and axiomatize a weighted Shapley NTU value that generalizes the symmetric
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2089
NTU value defined above and that coincides with the w-NBS on FN8 and the w-Shapley value on F S U. DEFINITION 3.3.1. Let w e 9tN+. A vector x ~ ~f~N iS a w-ShapleyNTUvaluepayoff for V c FN if there exists )~ ~ fltN+ such that: (1) x E V ( N ) , (2) vx is defined for V, (3) ;~ • x = ~ow(v)~). The correspondence qsw that associates with each V the set of all w-Shapley value payoffs is called w-Shapley correspondence. Given Proposition 2.2.1, it is reasonable to conjecture that the axiomatic characterization of Cw weakens Axiom A3 (by dropping symmetry) and imposes NTU analogues of the positivity and partnership axioms ($4 ~ and $5) used in the characterization of qgw on GN. A T : (Null Players) For each 0 ¢ T __cN, there exists qT 6 9~N such that q/(Ur) = {qT} and q~ = 0 if i ~ T. This axiom generalizes the unanimity Axiom A3 in that it allows players within a carrier to receive different payoffs but it still requires 45 to be single-valued on the carrier garnes. A6: (Positivity) If v is a monotonic TU garne without null players and if V is the NTU garne corresponding to v, then x e 9t~+ for each x 6 qt(V). A7: (Partnership) Let T be a partnership in a TU game v and ler V correspond to v. If x ~ q/(V ) then there exists y ~ q/( ( ~ j e r x J) UT) such that x i _ yi for each i ~ T. The next lemma generalizes Lemma 3.2.1 to the case where no symmetry requirement is imposed. Note that the domain of the correspondence q/is F'N1 . LEMMA 3.3.2. Suppose that a correspondence q / : F ~ -+ ff[N satisfies Axioms AO, AI, A2, A3 ~ and A4. Then there exists an operator ge : GN -+ 9t N satisfying $1, $2 and $3 such that q/(V) = {ge(v)} whenever V corresponds to the TU game v. PROOF. Suppose q/satisfies the axioms and let {qT}~#TCN be the collection specified by Axiom A3 ~. For each 0 7~ T ___N, define ~ß(uT) = qT and linearly extend ge to all of GN. The resulting ge is obviously linear and A1 implies that iß is efficient. It can be verified using an induction argument that the null player axiom is satisfied. Using the same argument as that used in the proof of Lemma 3.2.1, we conclude that q~(V) is a singleton whenever V corresponds to a TU garne. Since
it follows that q~(V) = {ge(v)}.
[]
2090
R.RMcLean
LEMMA 3.3.3. Ifq/ : ~ ~ --+ 9iN satisfies Axioms AO, A1, A2, A3 r, A4, A6 and AT, then there exists a w ~ 9iN+ such that O(V) = {~0w(V)} whenever V corresponds to the TU garne v. PROOF. Suppose V corresponds to v ~ GN. Using Lemma 3.3.2, we conclude that ~ü(V) = {~ß(v)} where ~p : GN ---> 9iN satisfies S1, $2 and $3. Since qJ satisfies A6 and A7, it follows that ~ß satisfies $4 ~ and $5 so applying Proposition 2.2.1 yields the result. [] Using Lemma 3.3.3 above and the techniques of Lemmas 3.2.2 and 3.2.3, we can prove the following generalization of Theorem 3.2.4. THEOREM 3.3.4 [Levy and McLean (1991)]. A correspondence gt : ~ ~ _-+ 9iN satisfies Axioms AO, A1, A2, A3 ~, A4, A5, A6 and A7 if and only if there exists a w ~ 9iN ++ such that q/(V) = q~w. REMARK 3.3.5. Theorem 3.3.4 can be extended to the case of "general weight systems" of Kalai and Samet (1987). This extension is accomplished by weakening the positivity axiom A6 (to the monotonicity axiom A6 / below) and using Theorem 2 in Kalai and Samet (1987) instead of Proposition 2.2.1. The w-Shapley correspondence obviously coincides with the w-Shapley value if V corresponds to a garne v ~ GN. Furthermore, the w-Shapley correspondence is an extension of the w-NBS as well and we record a generalization of Proposition 3.1.3 that utilizes an essentially identical proof. PROPOSITION 3.3.6. If w C 9i N++and V ~ F u , then qsw(V ) = {~rw(V)}. In Section 2.1, we presented the notion of random order value for TU garnes as a generalization of the w-Shapley value. In a similar way, Levy and McLean ( 1991 ) define and axiomatize a random order NTU value that generalizes the weighted Shapley NTU value discussed above and thus construct a taxonomy of NTU values with and without symmetry. Recall that M(~2N) is the set of probability measures o n ~2N and ~0p : GN -+ 9iN is the p-Shapley value corresponding to p ~ M(~2N). DEFINITION 3.3.7. Let p c M(ff2N). A payoff vector x 6 9iN is a p-Shapley N T U value payoff if there exists )~ c 9i~+ such that: (1) x e V ( N ) , (2) v~ is defined for V, (3))~ *x = q)p(VZ). The set of all p-Shapley NTU value payoffs of a game V is denoted C p ( V ) and the correspondence that assigns to each V the set of p-Shapley NTU value payoffs is
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2091
called the p-Shapley correspondence. Our characterization of q)p weakens the positivity A x i o m A 6 to A6 ~. A 6 ' : (Monotonicity) If v is a monotonic TU garne and if V is the N T U garne corresponding to v, then x 6 9t N whenever x ~ ~ ( V ) . Suppose a correspondence q/ satisfies A1, A2, A 3 ' , A4 and A6'. By combining L e m m a 3.3.2 and Proposition 2.1.1, we deduce that there exists p E M(S2) such that qs(V) = {~0p(V)} whenever V con'esponds to v ~ G N . This observation and the techniques of Lemmas 3.2.2 and 3.2.3 yield the next characterization result. THEOREM 3.3.8 [Levy and M c L e a n (1991)]. A cormspondence ~ : FJN ~ ~:~N satisfies Axioms AO, A1, A2, A3', A4, A5 and A 6 ~ if and only if there exists a p c M ( ~2 ) such that q/ = @p.
4. The Harsanyi solution 4.1. The Harsanyi N T U value A payoffconfiguration is a collection { x s } o c r c N with x s E ~ s for each S. For simplicity, we will denote a payoff configuration by {xs}. If v ~ GN and S __cN, then vls represents the restriction of v to 2 s and ~o(vls) is the Shapley value of the ISI player garne vls. In Harsanyi (1963), a different extension o f NBS and the Shapley value to general N T U garnes is given. DEFINITION 4.1.1. A vector x c ~N is a Harsanyi N T U value p a y o f f for V ~ FN if there exists a payoff configuration {xs } with XN = x and k 6 ~N++ such that: (1) x s ~ OV(S) for each S, (2) k • x = maxzev(N ) k . z, (3) k s • x s = ~o(Okls) for each S where bk(S) = k s • x s . REMARK 4.1.2. Definition 3.1.1 for the Shapley N T U value can be restated so as to facilitate a comparison with the Harsanyi NTU value. In particular, a vector x 6 9t N is a Shapley N T U value payoff for V ~ FN if there exists a payoff configuration {xs} with XN = x and k 6 3t+N+ such that: (1") x s c OV(S) for each S, (2*) k s • x s = maxzev(s) k s • z for each S, (3*) k * x = q)(Ox) where 0h(S) = k s • x s . Comparing the definitions of the Shapley and Harsanyi N T U values, we see that both solutions are defined in terms of a comparison vector k ~ 9~+N+, a payoff configuration {xs} with x s ~ 0 V ( S ) for each S, and a T U garne bk where ~k (S) = k S . x s . The Shapley N T U value requires that ~3z(S) = maxz~v(s) k s • z for every S c N (so that ~»~ -----vk) while the Harsanyi value requires this only for S = N. On the other hand, the Harsanyi
2092
R.PMcLean
NTU value requires that ) s , xs = qo(~x]s) for every S _c N while the Shapley NTU value requires this only for S = N. If N = {1, 2}, then the two definifions are identical and both coincide with the NBS. In light of the discussion in Section 3.1, conditions (2) and (3) in Definition 4.1.1 are, respectively, the extensions of the utilitarian and equity properties of the NBS. Comparing these conditions with 2* and 3* in the definition of the Shapley NTU value, we see that the Shapley NTU value emphasizes coalitional utilitarianisrn while the Harsanyi NTU value ernphasizes coalitional equity. The definition of Harsanyi NTU value can also be restated in terms of dividends in the spirit of Definition 3.1.2. For a proof of the equivalence of the two definitions, see Section 2.2 in Imai (1983). DEFINITION 4.1.3. A vector x ~ ~N is a Harsanyi NTU value payoff for V c FN if there exists a payoff configuration {xs} with XN = x, a vector )~ 6 gtN+ and a collection of numbers {eT }O¢T_CN such that: (1) xs ~ 3V(S) for each S, (2) ;~ - x = max~cv(N) X • Z, (3) UX~s = ETc_s: i~T°tT for each S G N and each i c S. As in Definition 3.1.2, the number « v is interpreted as a dividend that each player in T receives as a mernber of T. If coalition S were to form, then each i 6 S would receive the payoff x~. Condition (1) requires that xs be efficient and condition (3) requires that i's rescaled payoff Xixis be equal to his accumulated dividends. From Definition 4.1.1, it is easy to verify that, if V corresponds to v 6 GÆ, then qg(v) is the unique Harsanyi NTU value payoff for V. To see this, note that if x is a Harsanyi value payoff, then the associated vector X must be a positive scalar multiple of 1N. If {xs} is the associated payoff configuration, then ls • xs = v(S) so vx is a positive multiple of v and, therefore, XN = x = q~(v). Conversely, define xs = qg(v]s). Then {xs} satisfies the three conditions of the definition and XN = qffv) is the Harsanyi NTU value payoff. Like the Shapley NTU value, the Harsanyi NTU value is an extension of the NBS to general NTU garnes in the sense that the Harsanyi value coincides with the NBS for V EF~. PROPOSITION 4.1.4. Suppose that V c Fó~. If y is a Harsanyi NTU value payoff vector for V, then y = fr(V). PROOF. Suppose y is a Harsanyi NTU value payoff for V. Then Definition 4.1.3 irnplies that there exist numbers {«T}0~aT_CN and a payoff configuration {xs} with xs c 3V(S) for all S such that XN = y and
Xi X Si
-~-
K-" /'~ Tcs:
OIT iET
Ch. 55." Values o f Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
for each i c S _c N. Hence, )~ixi{i}
:
i Let S = O'{i} SO 0t{i} _~ )~i d v.
2093
{i, j}.
Then
~. i X Si =
a{i} ~- a S =)~ i d vi +ots so x~ = d vi
.q_ Ots/)i. Since xs and (d/v d j ) are both in 0 V(S) it follows that a s = 0. Using this argument inductively, we conclude that a s = 0 if 1 < [SI < n. Hence, x~ = d~ whenever 1 < IS[ < n. Therefore,
for all i, j c N. Combining this fact with condition (2) in Definition 4.1.3, we can use the argument in the proof of Proposition 3.1.3 and conclude that XN = y is the NBS for V. []
4.2. The Harsanyi solution Harsanyi's general approach for NTU garnes can be given an axiomatic foundation if we take the point of view that the entire payoff configuration should be treated as the outcome. DEFINITION 4.2.1. A payoff configuration {xs} is a Harsanyi solution for V • F u if there exists k c ~N+ such that: (1) xs ~ 3 V ( S ) for all S c N, (2) X. XN = maxzev(N) X • z, ( 3 ) ) S , xs = qg(~;~ls) for all S c N where ~3z(S) = ) s . xs. Note that we are distinguishing between a Harsanyi solution payoff configuration and a Harsanyi NTU value payoff vector. (In the literature, the term "Harsanyi solution" is ordinarily used for both of these concepts.) Obviously, it follows from the definition that if {xs} is a Harsanyi solution, then XN is a Harsanyi NTU value payoff. The correspondence that associates with each V ~ F 2 the set of Harsanyi solution payoff configurations for V is called the Harsanyi solution correspondence and is denoted H. Let/~2 be the set of V 6 F 2 such that H ( V ) ¢ 0. In the axioms below, U, V and W are garnes and q~ : ~ 2 __+ l-Isc_N R s is a payoff configuration valued correspondence. H0: (Non-Emptiness) qJ (V) 5~ 0. H I : (Efficiency) If {xs} ~ q/ (V) then xs ~ 0 V (S) for each S ___N. H2: (ConditionaI Additivity) If U = V + W, {xs} ~ q/(V), {Ys} c ~P(W) and xs + Ys ~ OU (S) for each S, then {xs + Ys} c qr(V). H3: (Unanimity Garnes) If T ___ N is nonempty, then ~P(UT) = {Zs} where zs = xS/ITJ if T c S and zs = 0 otherwise. H4: (Scale Covariance) ~ ( a • V) ---={{a s * xs} I {xs} ~ ~ ( V ) } for every a 6 ~RN+. H5: (Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives) If {xs} ~ tP (W) and if xs ~ V (S) c_ W ( S ) for each S, then {xs} ~ q/(V). The axioms for the Harsanyi solution correspondence on/~N2 can be readily compared with those for the Shapley correspondence on /~N1 . Axioms H 0 - H 5 are payoff config-
2094
R.P McLean
uration analogues of A0-A5 and they are used in Hart (1985a) to prove the following characterization theorem. THEOREM 4.2.2 [Hart (1985a)]. A correspondence q/ : ~2 ~ I-IscN RS satisfies Axioms HO-H5 if and only if q-" = H. PROOF. For v ~ GN, let h(v) = {xs} where xs = 9(vls). If V corresponds to v, then H ( V ) = {h(v)} so F TU c .F2 N. (See the discussion preceding Proposition 4.1.4.) Now the proof proceeds in several steps: Step 1: Since q/satisfies H0-H4, it follows that q0(V) = {h(v)} whenever V corresponds to v ~ GN. This is the analogue of Lemma 3.2.1. Step 2: Since qJ satisfies H0-H4, one can show that q~(V) __ H ( V ) for each V c ~2. This is the analogue of Lemma 3.2.2. Step 3: Finally, it can be proved that H ( V ) ~ O ( V ) whenever q/ satisfies H0-H5, thus providing a payoff configuration version of Lemma 3.2.3. The proof is completed by verifying that H satisfies these axioms. [] The Harsanyi correspondence can be axiomatically characterized on FN2 if H ( V ) is not required to be nonempty. To accomplish this, H3 must be strengthened and an additional axiom must be imposed. H3+: (Unanimity Garnes) For each real number c and nonempty T _c N, let U~ be the game corresponding to the TU garne CUT. Then q/(U~) = {zs} where zs = (c/ITI)x s if T c__S and zs = 0 otherwise. H6: (Zero Inessential Garnes) If 0 6 ÕV(S) for each S, then {0} c ko(S). THEOREM 4.2.3 [Hart (1985a)]. A correspondence qJ : F 2 --+ I~S~N RS satisfies Axioms H1, H2, H3 +, H4, H5 and Hó if and only if gv = H. We conclude this section with a brief discussion of a weighted generalization of the Harsanyi solution analogous to the w-Shapley NTU value. DEFINITION 4.2.4. Let w 6 31N + + " A payoffconfiguration {xs} is a w-Harsanyi solution for V 6 FÆ if there exists )~ c 9~N+ and a collection of numbers {«r}O¢TCN such that: (1) xs E OV(S),
(2) L. XN = maxzcv(Æ) ,~" Z, (3) z i • x~ = w i ~ r ~ s : i~r e r .
If the tO i a r e all equal then the w-Harsanyi solution reduces to the Harsanyi solution. Axiom H3 (of H3 +) imposes symmetry on the NTU value. If H3 is generalized in the same way that A3 is generalized to A3 r, then the class of weighted Harsanyi solutions ean be axiomatized. Other nonsymmetric generalizations of the Harsanyi solution [ineluding NTU extensions of the TU coalition structure values smdied in Owen (1977),
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2095
Hart and Kurz (1983) and Levy and McLean (1989)] are discussed in Winter (1991) and Winter (1992). 4.3. A comparison o f the Shapley and Harsanyi N T U value
EXAMPLE 4.3.1. Let N = {1,2,3} and for each e E [0, 1/2], consider the garne V« defined as: Ve(i) = {x E R [i} I x «. 0}; Ve(1, 2) = {x E R(l'2) I ( x l , x 2) ~< (½, ½)}; V«(1, 3) = {x c R (1'3} [ (x 1, x 3) ~< (e, 1 - «)}; VE(2, 3) -= {x E R {2'3} ] (x 2, x 3) ~< (s, 1 - e)}; V«(N) -= {x E R u [ x ~ y for some y 6 C}; where C = convex hull {(1/2, 1/2, 0), (~, 0, 1 - ~), (0, E, 1 - e)}. This game appears in Roth (1980) and has generated a great deal of discussion in the literature [see Aumann (1985b), Roth (1986), Aumann (1986) and Hart (1985b)] which we summarize here. The Shapley NTU value is (½, 1, ½) with comparison vector k = (1, 1, 1) and the Harsanyi NTU value is ( ~, 2 ~, ) with the same )~. Essentially, Roth argues that (½, ½, 0) is the only reasonable outcome in this garne since (½, ½) is preferred by {1, 2} to any other attainable payoff and {1, 2} can achieve (½, ½) without the aid of player 3. In this example, (1, ½, 1) is the NTU value because the TU garne vk corresponding to Ve is symmetric although the NTU garne Ve is certainly not symmetric. Aumann counters that there are circumstances in which (½, ½, 1) is an expected outcome of bargaining. If coalitions form randomly, then 1 might be willing to strike a bargain with 3 in order to guarantee a positive payoff since, if he were to reject an offer by 3, then 2 might strike a bargain with 3 leaving 1 with nothing. A similar argument holds for 2. This argument is less compelling when e is very small. Hence, one might argue that 3 should get something but that the payoff to 3 should decline as e declines. In fact, it is precisely the Harsanyi NTU value that is close to (ä-, ½, 0) for small e and, therefore, may better reflect the underlying structure. EXAMPLE 4.3.2. Let N = {1, 2, 3} and for each e E [0, .2] consider a three-person, two-commodity pure exchange economy with initial endowments a l = (1 - «, 0), a2 = (0, 1 - e) and a3 = (e, s) and utility functions u l ( x , y) = min{x, y} = u2(x, y) and u3(x, y) = (1/2)(x + y). The NTU game Ve associated with this economy is: Ve(i) = {x E R {il I xi ~ 0} i f i = 1, 2; V«(3) ---={x E R {3} I x 3 ~< e}; V e ( 1 , 2 ) = { x E R {l'2}lxl +x2~< 1 - - e , x 1 ~ 1 - e , x 2~< l - e } ; V e ( i , 3 ) = {x E R {i'3}1(x i , x 3 ) ~ < L ~ , x i « e , x 3 <~ 1+et 2 " i f i = 1,2; Ve(N) = {x ~ R NIx 1 + x 2 + x3 <~ 1, x i ~< 1 for each i}. This example is a simplified version of one that appears in Shafer (1980) and is due to Hart and Kurz (1983). The payoffs at the unique Harsanyi NTU value (evaluated at the
R.PMcLean
2096
corresponding allocation) with comparison vector (1, 1, 1) are: ul(½ 5e6,2l 5e6) = 1 5~ u 2 ( ½ _ ~ , l _ ~ ) , 5~ a n d u 3 ( ~ , ~ ) = ~ . T h e p a y o f f s a t t h e unique 2 6' ~ --2 6' Shapley NTU value (evaluated at the corresponding allocation) with comparison vector (1, 1, 1) a r e : U1(52 5e 5 5e 5 5e ,5 5e 5 5e 5 5e and 12' 12
u3(1 + 4, ;- + ~ ) : ;- + 4
~)
- - 12
]~,U2k]~
12' 12
f r ) - - 12
12'
Shafer argues that the Shapley NTU value is not a reasonable solution in this "economic" example. If e = 0, then player 3 has no endowment yet he receives a nonzero allocation because of the "utility producing" properties of his utility function. The computation of the Shapley NTU value depends upon the assumption that utility is transferable and this is clearly at variance with the usual notions of ordinality in general equilibrium theory. However, one can use the same reasoning as found in the previous example and argue that if coalitions form randomly, then 3 might reasonably receive a nonzero payoff though such a payoff taust be small if « is small. This is precisely the property exhibited by the Harsanyi N T U value in this example. What conclusion is to be drawn from these examples? In Hart (1985a), a case has been made that the Harsanyi N T U value is a good solution concept for NTU garnes with a small number of players while the Shapley NTU value is appropriate for "large" garnes. The latter statement seems justified in light of the equivalence principle discussed in Chapter 36 and Remark 7.2.7 below.
5. Multilinear extensions for NTU games
5.1. Multilinear extensions and Owen's approach to the NTU value Another approach to the value of an NTU game is provided in Owen (1972b) and is based on the concept of multilinear extension. Let v c GN and define fv : [0, 1] n --> 9t as
r fv(xl . . . . . Xn)= E [ E x i SŒN L ieS
7
E ( 1 - xi)[v(S). Ai~S
The function fv is called the multilinear extension of v (MLE for short) and is defined in Owen (1972a). For each i e N, it can be shown that
af~
oxW= I2 [IxJ 1-I (~-~j)[~(s~i)-~(s)] S~N\i jeS
j~SUi
so that
8B(t . . . . . t) = E tlSl(1 -- t)n-ls[-l[v(S O i ) - v(S)]. Oxi S~N\i
2097
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Games Upon integrating with respect to Lebesgue measure, one obtains
f0
(t . . . . . t) dt = q)i (v).
1
Oxi
In Owen (1972b), the MLE is defined in an analogous way for NTU garnes. For each V ~ FN, recall that V*(S) = V(S) x {0Nis} and (abusing notation slightly) define
fv(xl . . . . .
xn)
: Z I E JciE (1 --Xi)] SCNLi~S
V*(S)"
ißS
For each x e [0, 1] t7, f r ( x ) is the sum of comprehensive, convex sets and is therefore comprehensive and convex. Suppose that there exists a differentiable function FV : ~lN X ~t~tN --> ~ßl with the property that Of r (x) = {u ~ ~:~N ] FV (u, x) = 0} whenever x > 0. That is, Fv implicitly defines the Pareto boundary of f v (x). To construct a value for V, Owen makes the following informal argument. Bargaining takes place over time. At time t e [0, 1], player i has accumulated a payoff of ui (t) as a result of a "commitment" of xi (t) up to time t. If the vector u(t) is Pareto optimal given x(t) > 0, then Fv (u (t), x (t)) = 0. If the payoff and commitments of j E N \ i are fixed at time t, then a change in i's commitment from xi (t) to xi (t ÷ At) should result in a corresponding change in i's payoff so as to maintain Pareto optimality. This means that
O[;Vaui[bti(t+ At)--bti(t)]-~- OFv [xi(t +
A t ) -- xi (t)] ~ O.
If ri is the rate of change of commitment of player i, then (assuming x, u and Fv are differentiable) we are led to the following system of differential equations for i 6 N: r OFv .1 Oxi L-Õ-üTui.a
xi(t) = ri (t), ui(O) = xi(O) ~--0. The initial conditions are interpreted to mean that at t = 0, each player is committed and has accumulated a payoff of zero. If (~, ü) is a solution to this system with J?(t) > 0 for 0 < t ~< 1, then for each such t, Fv (ü (t), ~ (t)) = 0 so that ü (t) is Pareto optimal for f v (x (t)). In particular, ü (1) is Pareto optimal for f r ( 2 ( 1 ) ) = f r ( 1 . . . . . 1) = V ( N ) . Owen refers to ü(1) as a "generalized value" and has shown that both the Shapley value and the NBS are generalized values for the appropriate systems of differential equations.
R.P. McLean
2098
PROPOSITION 5.1.1 [Owen (1972b)]. Ler V correspond to v E GN. Then for each x > O, Fv (u, x) = ~ i c N üi -- fv (x). Furthermore, ifri (t) =- 1 for each i, then there is a solution (~, ü) to the system of differential equations with ü(1) = ~0(v). PROOF. If fv is the MLE of v, then f r ( x ) = {u ~ ~fl~N[~i~NUi ~ f r ( x ) whenever x >OsothatFv(u,x)=~j~~ieNUi - f v ( x ) . H e n c e , aF~axi-- Oxiafvand ~OFvœ 1 So d~i _ afv(xi(t))
dt
__ O f v ( t . . . . .
Oxi
t)
OXi
Upon integrating and using the fact that ü (0) = 0, we obtain U i ( 1 ) -=
foo'~ oxi
(t . . . . . t) dt = q)i(v).
[]
PROPOSITION 5.1.2 [Owen (1972b)]. Ler V ~ FNB with dv = O. Then for each x > O,
Fv (u, x) = g(u/I~icN xi). Furthermore, if ri (t) = 1 for each i, then there is a solution (fc, ü) to the system of differential equations with ü(1) = o-(v). PRO OF. Since dv = 0, it follows that f v (xl . . . . . xn) = [l~ieN x i ] V ( N ) . If the Pareto optimal surface of V(N) is defined by g(u) = 0, then Fv (u, x) = g(u/I-IiEN xi) whenever x > 0. Thus,
ÕFv
gi(u/I~ieNXi )
OUi
l~jEN Xj
where gi is the partial derivative of g with respect to the ith argument. In addition,
OFv
Z
OXi
1_ k
gk 1 7 \llj ~Nxj
Uk XiI~j eNxj
Now let u* be the NBS for V. Since V(N) is convex, it follows that g(u*) = 0 and u*gi (u*) = u~gj (u*) for each i, j 6 N. It is now easy to verify that ~i (t) = t and üi (t) = tnu~ solve the system of differential equations. Since ü(1) = u*, we have the desired result. [] REMARK 5.1.3. In the case of Proposition 5.1.1, it is not difficult to show that the initial value problem associated with Fv has a unique solution (i.e., the one given in the proof of the proposition) and, therefore, the Shapley value is the unique "generalized value" of an NTU game derived from a TU garne. The uniqueness question is more complicated in the case of Proposition 5.1.2 due to the behavior of the function Fr(u, x) = g ( u / I ~ i c N xi) near (u, x) = (0, 0). However, Hart and Mas-Colell (1991)
Ch. 55." Values of Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2099
have shown that there is a unique solution to the initial value problem associated with this F v as well. Hence, there is a unique generalized value for garnes in FN~ which is precisely Nash's Bargaining Solution. 5.2. A non-symmetric generalization
In the previous section, ri (t) was interpreted as the rate of change of commitment of i. In Owen (1972a), it also is interpreted as the density function of a random variable that describes the time at which i joins a coalition. In Propositions 5.1.1 and 5.1.2, this random variable is assumed to be uniformly distributed on [0, 1] but there are other possibilities. Let w = (w I ..... to n) E giN+ and define ri (t) -= w i t wi-1 . For this density, larger values of the weight parameter correspond to higher likelihoods of "late arrival". PROPOSITION 5.2.1. Let V correspond to v E G N . Then f o r each x > O, F v (u, x ) = ~ i ~ N Ui -- f r ( X ) . Furthermore, i f ri (t) : t o i t w i - I f o r each i, then there is a solution (fc, ü) to the system o f differential equations with ü(1) = ~0w(v). PROOF. Following the proof of Proposition 5.1.1, we deduce that
üi(l)
=
f01 V f v ( t
w' ,
...,
t w n ) w i t wi-1 dt.
Since this integral is ~0/ (v) [Owen (1972a) or Kalai and Samet (1987)], the result follows. [] PROPOSITION 5.2.2. Let V E f'NB with d v = O. Then f o r each x > O, F v ( u , x ) = g(u / l ~ i e N Xi ). Furthermore, if ri (t) = w t w - 1f o r each t, then there ts a solunon (~, ü) to the system o f differential equations with ü (1) = aw ( V ). PROOF. As in Proposition 5.1.2, let d v = 0 and let the Pareto optimal surface of V ( N ) be given by g(u) = 0. Then {u*} = Crw(V) if and only if g(u*) = 0 and
gi (u *) - ~ = g j for each i, j E N. Letting W = Y]4eN toi, it is now easy to verify that x i ( t ) -= t w` and üi (t) = t wu* solve the system of differential equations with ri (t) = w i t w i - 1 for each i E N. Since üi (1) = u*, we have the desired result. [] 5.3. A comparison o f the Harsanyi, Owen and Shapley N T U approaches
Although the solution derived from the M L E coincides with the Shapley value on TU garnes and the NBS on a class of pure bargaining garnes, it does not coincide with the
2100
R.PMcLean
NTU value or the Harsanyi value for general NTU garnes. To see this, consider the following example fl'om Owen (1972b). EXAMPLE 5.3.1. Let N = {1, 2, 3} and define V as follows: V(1,2,3):{uEN N [ Ul - ] - u 2 - [ - u 3 ~ 1 , bti ~ 1, u i - [ - u j ~~. 1 f o r all i, j } ; V(1,2)={uEN{l'2l[ul+4u2<~l, Ulk
6. The Egalitarian solution 6.1. Egalitarian values and Egalitarian solutions Up to now, this chapter has been concerned with solutions for NTU garnes that yield the NBS and Shapley value on appropriate subclasses. However, one could take any pair of ùrelated solutions" for pure bargaining garnes and TU games and look for a common extension to a larger class of NTU garnes. This program has been carried out in Kalai and Samet (1985) where they define the w-Egalitarian solution for NTU garnes which coincides with the w-Shapley value on F TU and the w-proportional solution r to on FN~ . There are acmally two possible approaches to the Egalitarian solution, depending on whether one defines a "solution" to be a payoff vector in N Æ or a payoff configuration in [-Isc_N Ns. DEFINITION 6.1.1. Let w E ~;N ++- A payoff configuration {xs} is a w-Egalitarian solution for V ~ FN if there exists a collection of numbers {aT }0ereN such that: (1) xs c OV(S) for each S _ N, (2) x si _-- w i Y~~rcs: i~T OrT for all i E S and all S _c N. DEFINITION 6.1.2. A payoff vector x E N N is a w-Egalitarian value payoff for V c Fu if there exists a w-Egalitarian solution payoff configuration {xs} for V with XN -= x. REMARK 6.1.3. Comparing Definitions 4.2.4 and 6.1.1, we see that (at least structurally) a w-Egalitarian solution "looks like" a w-Harsanyi solution. As the reader may verify, the following more precise comparison can be made. If {xs} is a w-Egalitarian solution for V and 1N • XN = max[1N • Z [ Z E V(N)], then {xs} is a w-Harsanyi solution with comparison vector 1N. On the other hand, every (symmetric) Harsanyi
Ch. 55." Valuesof Non-Transferable UtilityGames
2101
solution happens to be a w-Egalitarian solution. In particular, a payoff configuration {xs} is a (symmetric) Harsanyi solution for V if and only if there exists )~ E 9tN+ such that )~ • XN = max[)~ • z I Z e V(N)] and {xs} is a w-Egalitarian solution with w = (1/)~ 1. . . . . 1/,V'). The motivation for the definitions of Egalitarian solution and value is best understood by considering a two-person garne V e/ùN8 . In this case, a payoff vector x ----(x I , x 2) is a (symmetric) Egalitarian value payoff if:
xeOV(1,2)
and
xl-dl=x2-d~.
Therefore, x is precisely the (symmetric) proportional solution r ( V ) for the twoperson bargaining problem as described in Section 2.4 [see Kalai (1977b)]. Geometrically, x is the intersection of the 45 ° line emanating from the point (d l , d 2) and the boundary of V(1, 2). In our discussion of the NBS, we stated that an arbitrator in ideal circumstances would like to choose a solution (x 1, x 2) that satisfies utilitarianism (i.e., X 1 " } - X 2 • max[z 1 + z 2 [ z e V(1, 2)]) and equity (i.e., x I - d I = x 2 - d2). Since these are generally incompatible, the NBS seeks a point (x 1, x 2) for which there exists some )~ e N~5~ } such that )~ • x will simultaneously satisfy these two criteria in the rescaled problem )~ • V. By comparison, the proportional solution maintains the equity condition that x 1 _ d l = x 2 _ d 2 but dispenses with utilitarianism by requiring that x merely be efficient for N. Hence, conditions (1) and (2) of Definition 6.1.1 extend respectively the notions of efficiency and equity as they are interpreted in the proportional solution. When V corresponds to a TU garne v, it follows immediately from the definitions that the w-Egalitarian, w-Shapley and w-Harsanyi NTU value payoffs for V are identical and coincide with the w-Shapley value for V. Therefore, the w-Egalitarian value is a solution concept that extends the w-Shapley value and the w-proportional solution to the class of general NTU garnes. REMARK 6.1.4. Definitions 6.1.1 and 6.1.2 translate into an algorithm for computing w-Egalitarian values and solutions. For each i, define «{i} = d ~ / w i . For each S with [SI ~> 2, inductively define ots as max[t r zs(t) e V(S)] where z~(t) = wi[t + ZTCS, T~-S: iöT OlT]" If this process is well defined for each S c N, then {zs(«s)} is a w-Egalitarian solution payoff configuration and z N (0/N) is a w-Egalitarian value payoff.
6.2. An axiomatic approach to the Egalitarian value The correspondence tbat associates with each V the set of w-Egalitarian value payoffs will be denoted Ew. In this section, we will provide an axiomatization of the wEgalitarian value correspondence on the class FN3 (see Section 1.3). From Remark 6.1.4, it follows that Ew(V) can consist of at most one element. Since Ew(V) 7~ 0 for each V e / ù 3 , we will treat Ew :/ùN3 - + ~N as a function.
2102
R.RMcLean
To state the axioms, we need a few more definitions and we follow the terminology in Hart (1985c). If F : F~ --+ N ~ is a function, then the vector ( F ( V ) ) T ~ N r will be written F r ( V ) . A coalition T _ N is a carrier for V if V(S) = V ( S n T) x Ns_\ r whenever S f3 T 7~ 0. A garne is individually rational monotonic (1R monotonic for short) if V+(S) x V+(i) c_ V+(S U i) where V+(T) = {x c V ( T ) I x i >~ dir, for each i ~ T}. If 13 7~ T c__N and a ~ N N w i t h a i = 0 for i ~ T, define the NTU garne VT,a as follows: Vr,a(S) = {a s } + N s_ if T ~ S and Vr,a(S) = N s_ otherwise. In the axioms below, F : F 3 ~ N N is a function and V and W a r e NTU garnes. E l : (Individual Rationality) If V is IR monotonic then F i (V) >~d~ for each i 6 N. E2: (Carrier) If S is a carrier for V, then F S ( v ) ~ OV(S). E3: (Additivity ofEndowments) I f a ~ N u w i t h a i • 0 for i ~ T and if F(Vr,a) = a, then F ( V + VT,a) = F ( V ) + a. E4: (Egalitarian Monotonicity) If T ~ N, V ( T ) c_ W ( T ) and V(S) = W ( S ) for all S 7~ T, then F r ( V ) <~ F r ( W ) . ES: (Continuity) F is continuous with respect to the Hausdorff topology on FN3 . E1 states that the payoff to player i must be individually rational if whenever i joins S c N \ i , such an arrangement does not eliminate individually rational payoffs that were available to i and S separately. E2 combines an efficiency property and a null player property. Since any superset T of a carrier S is also a carrier of V, it follows that F r ( V ) ~ OV(T) whenever S _c T. In particular, F ( V ) E OV(N). If S is a carrier of V and i ¢ S, then E2 implies that F i ( V ) <~ O. E2 is an NTU extension of a similar axiom used in the characterization of the TU Shapley value [see Shapley (1953b)]. Axiom E3 has the following interpretation. Let a 6 N N with a i = 0 for i ~ T and ler V be an NTU garne and define W = V + VT",a. Then W ( S ) = V(S) + {a s} if T _ S and W ( S ) = V(S) otherwise. Hence, W simply translates the payoffs of a superset S of T by a s and leaves the attainable sets of other coalitions unchanged. If a is acceptable in the sense that F(VT,a) = a, then E3 requires that the solution for W be precisely F ( V ) + a. Egalitarian monotonicity states that the members of a coalition T should be no worse oft if their attainable set expands while those of all other coalitions remain unchanged. Finally, E5 is a regularity condition. The main characterization theorem for the Egalitarian value may now be stated. THEOREM 6.2.1 [Kalai and Samet (1985)]. A function F : I "3 --4 N N satisfies E l - E 5
if and only if there exists w ~ NN++ such that F = Ew. 6.3. An axiomatic approach to the Egalitarian solution The Shapley and Harsanyi NTU values do not satisfy E3 [see Hart (1985c), p. 318] or E4 [see Kalai and Samet (1985)]. In addition, the Shapley and Harsanyi correspondences have closed graphs but are not continuous. There is also another important distinction between these solutions (first indicated in Kalai (1977b) for au vs rw) that lies in the way they respond to the rescaling of utilities. The Shapley NTU value and the Harsanyi
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable UtilityGarnes
2103
solution are scale covariant in the sense of Axioms A4 and H4 while the Egalitarian value and the Egalitarian solution satisfy such a condition only for rescalings that put the same weight on each individual's utility. Despite these differences, the Harsanyi solution and the Egalitarian solution are more closely related than one might believe at first glance. Recall that Theorem 4.2.3 states that a payoff configuration valued correspondence satisfies H1, H2, H3 +, H4, H5 and HO on FN2 if and only if it is the Harsanyi solution. The next result shows that by dropping H4 (scale covariance) and enlarging the domain of the other axioms to all of Fu, we can actually characterize the Egalitarian solution in terms of the axioms used in the characterization of the Harsanyi solution. Let Ew denote the payoff configuration valued correspondence that associates with each V a FÆ the set of w-Egalitarian solution payoff configurationsfor V. The symmetric Egalitarian solution correspondence will be written simply as E. A
THEOREM 6.3.1 [Samet (1985)]. A correspondence ~ : FN --~ I-Isc_N ~~l~Ssatisfies H1,
H2, H3 +, H5 and H6 if and only if q/ : Ê. We can characterize Êw on FN if we modify the unanimity garnes axiom H3 + in an appropriate way. H3W: (Unanimity Garnes) For each real number c and nonempty T _c N, let U~ be the garne corresponding to the TU garne cuT. Then q/(U~.) -~ {zs} where z~ ---( c w i / ~ j s ~ w j) i f i E T c S and z~ : 0 otherwise. THEOREM 6.3.2 [Sarnet (1985)]. A correspondence q/" FN -+ I-[scN ~)~S satisfies H1, H2, H3 w, H5 and H6 if and only if qt = Ew.
7. Potentials and values of NTU garnes
7.1. Potentials and the Egalitarian value of finite games In Hart and Mas-Colell (1989), the notion of potential for TU garnes was introduced. These authors used the potential to provide a new axiomatization of the Shapley value for TU garnes using the concepts of reduced garne and consistency and we briefly review their approach next. In this section and in Section 8 below, let G denote the set of all pairs (N, v) where N is a finite set and v is a TU garne in GN. If (N, v) is a TU garne and S c N, we will write (S, v[s) simply as (S, v). In a similar fashion, let F denote the set of all pairs (N, V) where N is a finite set and V is a NTU game in FN satisfying the nonlevelness condition (3) in Section 1.3. In addition, let F ~U denote the games (N, V) where V ~ F~ U.
R.P. McLean
2104
Let w = {w i } be a collection of positive weights. A w-potential on G is a function Pw : G -+ ~ satisfying Pw (0, v) = 0 and
~[Pw(N, icN
v) - Pto(N\i, v)] ----v(N).
The following result provides a characterizafion of the weighted TU Shapley value in terms of potentials. THEOREM 7.1.1 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1989)]. There exists one and only one wpotential on G. Furthermore,
w i [Pw (N, v)
-
Pw ( N \ i , v)]
:
i (N, ~ow
v)
f o r all i ~ N. The definition of potential can be extended to NTU garnes. A w-potential on F is a function Pw : F ---> ~t satisfying Pw (0, V) = 0 and
(wi[Pw(N, V) - P w ( N \ i , V)])ieN E OV(N) whenever N # 0. THEOREM 7.1.2 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1989)]. There exists one and only one wpotential on F. Furthermore,
w i [ P w ( N , V) - P w ( N \ i , V)] : E w ( N V) f o r all i ~ N. Recall (see Remark 6.1.3) that a payoff configuration {xs} is a (symmetric) Harsanyi solution for V if and only if there exists £ ~ ~tN+ such that )~ - XN = max[)~ • Z I z V (N)] and {xs} is a w-Egalitarian solution with w -----(1/)~ I . . . . ,1/~'*). Hence, we have the following characterization of Harsanyi NTU value payoffs in terms of potentials. If )~ e ~tN+, let ~-1 : = (1/)~1 . . . . . 1/)~n). THEOREM 7.1.3 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1989)]. A payoffvector x ~ ~t N is a Harsanyi N T U value payoff vector f o r the garne (N, V) if and only if there exists a collection of positive weights {~ i } such that ~,ixi Œ P~-I(N, V) -- P ~ - I ( N \ i , V)
foreachi
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2105
and k-x:
max k . z . z~V(N)
7.2. Potentials and the Egalitarian solution of large games An N T U garne form is a correspondence V". 9t17 + --+ 91 and a finite type NTU game with ?Z 17 a continuum of players is defined as a pair (a, V) where • c 91++ and V : 9t+ --+ 91 is a garne form• A garne form has the following interpretation. Each profile x c fit+ is interpreted as a "coalition" and x i represents the total "number" (i.e., mass) of players of type i in the coalition. If a c V(x), then a i represents the per capita payoff to the players of type i in the coalition x. Hence, alx I is the total payoff to the type i players in coalition x. A solution function for a garne form V is a mapping ~"• N++ n --+ 91~ such that ~(x) c OV(x) for each x 6 91~+. In particular, ~i (x) is interpreted as the payoff to each type i player and the total payoff to the players of type i is therefore xi~ i (X). The characterization of the Egalitarian solution for finite NTU garnes in terms of a potential function presented in Theorem 7.1.2 suggests an extension to the case of large garnes with finitely many types. If V is a garne form, then a solution function ~" 91n ++ ~ 911~ for V is Egalitarian if ~ admits a potential, i.e., if there exists a differentiable function P . 91++ --+ 91 such that .
17
~(x) = V P ( x ) for each x c 91~_+. Thus, we are ideally interested in the existence of a differentiable function P such that V P ( x ) 6 0 V ( x ) for each x ~ 91n + + " Unfortunately [as shown in Hart and Mas-Colell (1995a)], such a function may not exist, even for "well-behaved" garne forms. This necessitates a weaker definition of solution and potential. DEFINITION 7.2.1. Let V be a garne form. A generalized solutionfunction for V is a mapping ~ "91~_+ --~ 91n such that ~(x) c OV(x) for almost all x c ~~~+. DEFINITION 7.2.2• A function P • 91~+ --+ 91 is a Lipschitzpotential for V if P is Lipschitz continuous and V P ( x ) c 0 V ( x ) for each x 6 91n + + at which P is differentiable. Every Lipschitz potential for V defines a generalized solution since (by the classical Rademacher theorem) a Lipschitz continuous function is differentiable almost everywhere. Even if we content ourselves with Lipschitz potentials (and their induced generalized solutions), we are still left with the problem of choosing a reasonable candidate from among the different Lipschitz potentials that may exist for a given garne form. Taking their cue from certain problems in the theory of partial differential equations [see, e.g., Fleming (1969)], Hart and Mas-Colell (1995a) introduce the variationalpotential and show that, while not necessarily the unique Lipschitz potential, it does satisfy many
2106
R.P. M«Lean
desirable properties and is the "right" potential if one approaches the problem from an asymptotic viewpoint. To construct the variational potential, let v" ~~_+ x ~~ --+ ~ U {cx~}denote the support function of the set V(x), i.e.,
v(x,p)=
sup p . a .
acV(x) Next, let AC(x) denote the set of absolutely continuous functions V " [0, 1] --+ N~+ U {0} satisfying y(0) = 0 and V(1) = x. The variational potential for V is defined for each x ~ ++ as follows:
P * (x) =
min
[ 1
Y(')cAC(x)Jo V(y(t), y(t)) dt.
In order for P* (x) to be well defined (and have other desirable properties), the garne form V taust satisfy certain restrictions. Let ~ denote the set of garne forms V : N~_ --~ satisfying (A.1)*-(A.3)* and (A.4)-(A.9) in Hart and Mas-Colell (1995b). These assumptions include the familiar requirements that, for each x ~ ~"+, V (x) be a nonempty, closed, convex, comprehensive, proper subset of Nn. However, these assumptions also guarantee that the support function of the set V(x) satisfies certain regularity requirements, including differentiability in x. THEOREM 7.2.3 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1995 a)]. Let V E G. For each x E N~_+, P* (x)
is well defined and the resuIting function P* : ~Rn++~ ~ is Lipschitz continuous hence differentiable almost everywhere. Furthermore, V P * ( x ) E OV (x) whenever P* is differentiable at x. To illustrate the variational potential, suppose that V is a TU garne form defined by
V(x)=
{
"
aEOtnlEai«
i <~f(x)
]
i=1 where f . • N n++ --+ ~ is a (sufficiently weil behaved) differentiable function. For each t, the support function v evaluated at (x, p) = (V(t), f/(t)) is finite only if for each i, ) i (t) = fl (t)V i (t) for some fi (t)/> 0. If we choose the normalization 13(t) = 1/ t , then Vx = tx is a solution to this system of differential equations satisfying the boundary conditions Vx(0) = 0 and Vx (1) = x. Therefore,
V(yx(t), }'x(t)) = l f ( t x )
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable UtilityGames
2107
so that
P*(x)=folv(yx(t),yx(t))dt=follf(tx)dt and we obtain
°9-L Oxi (c0 = f01ù0-f-f d t o x(to0 i for each « 6 9t~_+. For finite NTU garnes generated by TU garnes, the Egalitarian solution coincides with the TU Shapley value. In the case of NTU garne forms, the Egalitarian solution of a garne form generated by a finite-type nonatomic TU garne coincides with the Aumann-Shapley value and is obtained by the familiar diagonal formula. In summary, each V 6 ~ admits at least one Lipschitz potential, the variational potential P*, and the variational potential can be used to define a generalized solution for the garne (•, V). The variational potential may not be the unique Lipschitz potential even for well-behaved garne forms [see Section V.8 of Hart and Mas-Colell (1995a)] so a given garne form may have different generalized solutions corresponding to different Lipschitz potentials. However, the variational potential does exhibit several features that indicate that it is the "right" definition of Egafitarian solution, especially for applications. Some of these are summarized in the following result: THEOREM 7.2.4 [Hart and Mas-CoM1 (1995a)]. Suppose that V ~ G. (i) If Q is a Lipschitz potential for V, then P* (x) >/Q(x)for all x ~ 9ln++. (il) If V admits a continuously differentiable potential P, then P = P*. (iii) If V is a hyperplane garne form, then the variational potential P* is the unique Lipschitz potential for V. A complete specification of an Egalitarian solution requires that we define the solu12 tion for all profiles x ~ 9~++, even those at which P* is not differentiable. If we are willing to allow the solution to be set-valued at points at which P* is not differentiable, then the Lipschitz continuity of P* suggests that Clarke's generalized gradient can be used to complete the description of an Egalitarian solution based on the variational potential. DEFINITION 7.2.5. For each De ~ ~n++ and each V 6 G, the Egalitarian solution E*(o~, V) is defined as
E*(«, V) = [vCp*(«) + ~~] n OV(«) where v C p * (x) denotes the Clarke generalized gradient at x [see Clarke (1983)].
2108
R.P. McLean
Hart and Mas-Colell (1995a) prove that v C p * ( x ) = {VP*(x)} whenever P* is differentiable at x. Since v C p * ( x ) = conv{y I Y = l i m V P * ( x k ) , xk --~ x and P* is differentiable k at each xk }, it follows that [ v C p * ( x ) + 9~~_] M OV(x) ~ 95 if P* is not differentiable at x. Another strong justification for the variational Egalitarian solution is provided in Hart and Mas-Colell (1995b) where they develop an asymptotic approach to the definition of Egalitarian solution for a garne form V. In the spirit of the asymptotic value of nonatomic TU garnes, the garne form V is approximated by a sequence of finite NTU games{ Vr }. If the associated sequence of Egalitarian solutions { E (Vr) } has a limit, then that limit is defined as the "asymptotic Egalitarian solution" of the game form V. Let « E ~t~_+ be a profile in which each «i is a positive integer. For each positive integer r, construct a finite N T U game (Nr, Vr) as follows. The player set Nr consists of roli players of type i and the total number of players is INrl = r ( ~ i oli). For each S c_ Nr, ler mi(S) denote the number of type i players in S and let tzr(S) := ( m l ( S ) / r . . . . . m ~ ( S ) / r ) . Hence, /xt(Nr) = c~. The set Vr(S) is defined as follows: z E Vr (S) if and only if there exists (al . . . . . a,,) E V ( # r (S)) such that zj = ai whenever player j E Nr is of type i. As r increases the finite garnes (Nr, Vr) become better approximations of the continuum garne («, V). Since the potential preserves the symmetries of Vr, it is completely determined by the values of/z r (S). To define the potential, let Lr
=
{(z1 .....
Zn) ] for each i, 0 <~zi <~Oti and rzi
is
an integer}.
The potential of (5/,-, Vr) is a function Pr : Lr --+ ~ satisfying Pr (0) = 0 and for each ZELr, 12
DPr(Z) = (DiPr(Z))i=l := ( P r ( z ) - Pr(Z(')))~l E OV(z) where
z(i) = (zl, ..., zi-1, zi _ it, zi+l ....•
zn)
if z i >~ 1/r and z (i) = z otherwise. THEOREM 7.2.6 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1995b)]. Suppose that V ~ ~. Then for each o/ E }RN ++.• (a) l i m r - . ~ ( 1 / r ) P r ( « ) = P*(ot). (b) If P* is differentiable at o~, then limr-.o~ DPr (oe) = V P * (~). (c) limr->ec dist[DPr («), E* («, V)] = 0, where the dist[DPr (o0, E*(~, V)] := inf{][DPr («) - ~]L ] ~ E E*(o~, V)}.
Ch. 55: ValuesofNon-Transferable UtilityGarnes
2109
Property (a) states that the potentials of the approximating garnes converge to the variational potential P* of (a, V) for every « e ~N+. If P* is differentiable at of, then E*(«, V) = {VP*(«)}. Property (b) says that if P* is differentiable at «, then the sequence of Egalitarian values for the approximating sequence of garnes converges to precisely the single Egalitarian value of («, V) as defined by the variational potential. If P* is not differentiable at «, then the sequence of Egalitarian values for the approximating sequence of garnes may not converge. However, every convergent subsequence of {DPr («)}r~_l will have a limit in [ v C p * ( « ) + ~~_] M OV(«). REMARK 7.2.7. GiventherelationshipbetweentheHarsanyiNTUvalue and the Egalitarian value for finite player garnes (see Remark 6.1.3), it is natural to propose an analogous notion of Harsanyi value for finite type NTU garnes with a continuum of players using the variational potential. This is accomplished in Hart and Mas-Colell (1996b) where the authors show that the Walras equilibria of a large economy need not be Harsanyi value allocations. This stands in contrast to the Value Equivalence Principle: in an economy with many agents and smooth preferences the Walras equilibria and the Shapley NTU value allocations coincide. For the special class of "diagonal Harsanyi value payoffs", Imai (1983) does provide an equivalence result for finite-type market garnes.
8. Consistency and values of NTU games
8.1. Consistency and TU games: The Shapley value Many solutions of TU garnes have axiomatic characterizations that employ some notion of "reduced garne" and "consistency". [For a survey see Driessen (1991).] Let (N, v) be a TU garne, let S be a subset of N and 1et ~p be a solution. Loosely speaking, a reduced garne Vs~ is a garne with player set S derived from v by paying the players outside S their payoffs according to ~p. A solution ~p is consistent if the payoff to a player in S when ~p is applied to vs~ is the same as that player's payoff when ~p is applied to the original garne v. There are several possible constructions of a reduced garne and Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) provide a definition that is appropriate for the study of the Shapley value. In particular, Hart and Mas-Colell show that the Shapley value is the unique solution that is "standard" for two-person garnes and is consistent with respect to their definition of reduced garnes. Let G and F be defined as in Section 7.1 above. A solutionfunction 7t on G is a mapping that associates with each (N, v) e G a payoff vector ~(N, v) = (7ri (N, V))icN C o~N. A solution function ~p on F is a mapping that associates with each (N, V) E F a payoffvector iß(N, V) = (~ri (N, V))iöN E {)~N. If (N, y) is a TU garne, ~p is a solution function on G, and T ~ N, define the reducedgame (T, v~) as follows:
{ v(S t2 (N\T)) - ~ i c N \ T l~ri (S U (N\T), v), v~(S)=
0,
if 0 ¢ S C T; ifS=0.
R.P. McLean
2110
A solution function 7t on G is consistent if for each game (N, v) and each T c N,
~ßi(T,V~T)=~i(N,v )
for all i E T.
THEOREM 8.1.1 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1989)]. A solution function ~ on G is consistent and coincides with the Shapley value on two-person garnes if and onIy if ~ ( N , v) = qg(N, v) whenever (N, v) E G. 8.2. Consistency and NTU garnes: The Egalitarian value The definition of reduced garne and consistency can be extended to NTU garnes in a natural fashion. For each solution function ~O on F, each game (N, V) ~ F and each T ~ N, define the reducedgame (T, VT~) as follows: B ( S ) = {x E [RS I (x, (Tt j (S U (N\T),
V)«cN\T ) E V(8
U (N\T))}.
A solution function ~p on F is consistent if, for each (N, V) and T ___N, ~i (T, V~) = ~ßi (N, V)
for all i c T.
The definitions of reduced garne and consistency coincide with those given in Section 8.1 if V corresponds to a TU garne. The following result extends Theorem 8.1.1 to the NTU case.
THEOREM 8.2,1 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1989)]. A solution function ~ß on 1" is consistent and coincides with the proportional solution on two-person garnes if and only if Te(N, V) = E(N, V) whenever (N, V) E 1". 8.3. The consistent value for hyperplane garnes Since the NTU definition of consistency reduces to TU consistency, we can apply Theorem 8.1.1 and make a simple observation: any solution function on F that satisfies consistency and coincides with the TU Shapley value on two-player TU garnes taust coincide with the TU Shapley value on the class of TU games. Theorem 8.2.1 illustrates this idea since any solution that is proportional on two-player garnes taust coincide with the Shapley value on two-player TU garnes. A natural question now arises: does there exist a solution function on F that satisfies consistency and coincides with the Nash Bargaining Solution for two-player problems? If this question has an affirmative answer, then the resulting soluüon would be different from the Egalitarian solution function but would still coincide with the TU Shapley value on TU garnes. In fact, Maschler and Owen (1992) have shown that such a solution function does not exist. In particular, they
Ch. 55." Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2111
have shown that consistency, symmetry, efficiency and scale covariance are incompatible. However, there does exist a solution function that extends the TU Shapley Value and the NBS as we will see in Section 8.4 below. In order to construct this solution, we need to extend the concept of marginal contribution to NTU garnes. Let (N, V) be an NTU garne. Suppose that R = (il . . . . . in) is an element of ~ and recall that d~ = max{x i ] x i E V(i)}. The marginal contribution of ik in R in the garne V is defined inductively as follows: A il (R, V) = d vil
and Aik(R, V) = max{« ik I (x i~, ( A J ( R , v))j~li I ..... i, 1}) c V(il . . . . . ik-l, ik)} for each k ~> 2. Rearranging the numbers A il (R, V) . . . . . A in (R, V) yields the marginal worth vector
~(R, v) := (z~~(R, v) . . . . . A"(n, V)). Since 8(R, V) ~ Õ V ( N ) for each ordering R, a natural random order value for V is defined by Y~~Rcs?1 8 ( R, V). However, this point is not guaranteed to be in 0 V ( N ) unless 0 V ( N ) is convex. If V ~ F TU, then 0 V ( N ) is convex and A i (R, V) = A i (R, 1)) (as defined in Section 1.2) where v generates V. In this case, Y~~nes2 ~ 8 ( R , V) is precisely the Shapley value payoff vector for the TU game that generates V. We will present a random order solution for general NTU garnes in the next section. First, we will consider a class of games introduced in Maschler and Owen (1989) on which they have defined a random order value that satisfies a weakened version of consistency. An NTU game (N, V) is a hyperplane garne if for each S _c N, there exists a vector as c N s + and a real number b(S) such that V (S) = {x E 9t s [ as " x <~b(S)}. The set of all hyperplane games in F is denoted F a . Hyperplane games are NTU garnes associated with "prize garnes" [see Hart (1994)]. The consistent value on F H is the solution function K : F H --+ fitn defined as K ( N , V) = ~
1
~ 3 ( R , V).
RCg2
Note that K ( N , V) ~ 8 V ( N ) if (N, V) 6 F x4 since every marginal worth vector 8(R, V) ~ OV (N) and OV (N) is convex. Furthermore, K (N, V) = q)(N, v) if V ~ F Tu and v is the TU garne that generates V.
R.RMcLean
2112
The consistent value on F H does not satisfy the Hart-Mas-Colell defnition of consistency but it does satisfy two weaker notions of consistency. DEFINITION 8.3.1. A solution function aß on F is completely consistent if for each (N, V) E F,
Z
aßi(s, V~s~) = /1~ [ NkI--1 1\)aß i (N, V)
foralliEN
ScN :IS[=k, iES whenever 1 ~< k ~< [N[. DEFINITION 8.3.2. A solution function aß on F is globally consistent if for each (N, V) e F ,
E aßi(S' V~S) =2n-laßi(N' V) S~N S¢0
for all i E N.
Clearly, consistency implies complete consistency and complete consistency implies global consistency. Complete consistency is defined in Maschler and Owen (1989) (where it is called consistency) and global consistency is defined in Orshan (1992). Global consistency can be used to axiomafize the consistent value on F H. Players i and j are substitutes in V if for every S c_ N\{i, j}, the following condition holds: for every xs E gis and for every ~ ~ 9t,
(xs,~)EV(SUi)
ifandonlyif
(xs,~)EV(SUj).
If V corresponds to a TU game v, then i and j are substimtes in V if and only if they are substitutes in v as defined in Section 1.2. If a E giN, let (N, Vffdd) be the garne defined by
vadd(s) = {x E giS [ E xi <~.F_«ai }. i~S iŒS " In the axioms below, aß is a solution function on F. CI: (Efficiency) aß(N, V) E OV(N). C2: (Symmetry) aßi(N, V) = aßJ(N, V) whenever i and j are substitutes in V. C3: (Scale Covariance) For each )~ ~ giN+ and each a 6 gi N,
aß(N, )~ * V q- Vädd) = )~• aß(N, V) + {a}. THEOREM 8.3.3 [Maschler and Owen (1989), Orshan (1992)]. A solutionfunction aß
on F H satisfies C1, C2, C3 and global consistency if and only if aß = K.
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Games
2113
Hart (1994) provides yet another axiomatization of K on F H and to present that result, we need one more defnition. For each i and each S containing i, define:
D l ( s , V) = max{xi I (x ~, « ( S \ i , V)) ~ V(S)}. Note that D i (S, V) is uniquely determined by the condition (D i (S, V ) , gr(S\i, V))
av(s). C4: (Marginality) If (N, V) and (N, W) are garnes and if D i (S, V) = D i (S, W) for each S c N, then ~i (N, V) = o J (N, W). If ~ß is efficient and if V corresponds to a TU garne, then D i (S, V ) = v(S) - v ( S \ i ) and C4 coincides with the marginality axiom for TU garnes found in Young (1988). In fact, the next result is an extension of Theorem 1 in Young (1988) to the hyperplane garnes. THEOREM 8.3.4 [Hart if and only if ~ = K.
(1994)]. A solution function ~ß on E H satisfies C1, C2 and C4
8.4. The consistent value f o r general N T U garnes We can now use the consistent value for hyperplane garnes as a tool to extend the consistent value to a class of general NTU games. Let (N, V) be an NTU garne and let A = {kS}SC_N be a collection with Xs 6 N s + . We will call such a collection a comparison system. If sup[Xs • z I z 6 V(S)] is finite for each S, then we can define a hyperplane garne VA where, for each S _c N,
VA(S) = {x C N s [ XS . X <~ s u p [ k s . z I Z ~ V(S)]}. In this case, we say that the hyperplane garne VA is definedfor V. If VA is defined for V, then the restriction (S, VA) is a hyperplane garne with player set S and it follows that K ( S , VA) ~ OVA(S) for each S c N. As with the other solution concepts we have presented, we will distinguish between values as payoff vectors and solutions as payoff configurations. DEFINITION 8.4.1. A payoff configuration {xs} is a cons&tent solution payoffconfiguration for (N, V) if there exists a comparison system A ----{kS}SC_N such that (i) xs E V(S) for all S; (ii) VA is defined for V; (iii) xs = K ( S , VA) for all S. DEHNITION 8.4.2. A payoff vector x e 9t n is a consistent valuepayoff for (N, V) if there exists a consistent solution payoff configuration {xs } such that XN = x. Every hyperplane garne (hence every game generated by a TU garne) has a unique consistent payoff configuration and a unique consistent value. If (N, V) is a hyperplane
R.P. McLean
2114
garne and if {as}seN is the associated collection of normals, then VA is defined for V if and only if A = {tas}sc_N for some t > 0. Hence, VA = V whenever VA is defined, so the only possible consistent solution is the payoff configuration {K(S, V)}SC_N. Since V is a hyperplane garne, it follows that K(S, V) ~ OV(S) for each S and we conclude that {K (S, V)} s_cN is the unique consistent solution payoff configuration for V and that K ( N , V) is the unique consistent value payoff. An alternative characterization of consistent solution payoff configurations is possible. THEOREM 8.4.3 [Hart and Mas-Colell (1996a)]. Let ( N , V) be an NTU game. A payoff configuration {xs} is a consistent solution payoff configuration for V if and only if there exists a comparison system A = {XS}SC_N such that: (i) xs E OV(S) for each S c_C_N; (il) VA is defined for V and Xs • xs = max[Xs, z I z c V (S)]for each S c_ N; (iii) For each S c N and for each i ~ S,
jcS\i
jeS\i
REMARK 8.4.4. Suppose that V 6 F u and suppose that {xs} is a consistent solution payoff configuration for V with an associated comparison system {XS}SC_N. Condii tions (i) and (ii) imply that xs ---- (dv)ies for each S __ N, S # N and condition (iii) implies that
j cN \ i
.jEN\i
J J - d j ) for each i E N. Applying condition Therefore, )~~v(x~v- d~) = ?71 Ej~N )~N(XN (ii) to S = N, we conclude (as in the proof of Proposition 3.1.3) that XN = cr(V). Hence, the consistent value coincides with the Shapley value on the TU garnes and the Nash Bargaining Solution on the pure bargaining garnes. Maschler and Owen (1992) provide an existence theorem for the consistent value using a fixed-point argument and Owen (1994) presents an example in which the consistent value is not a singleton set. The consistent value does not satisfy consistency on F (since the consistent value does not satisfy consistency on FU). In addition, Owen (1994) shows that the consistent value does not satisfy complete consistency on F. A consistency based axiomatization on a suitably large class of NTU games that contains F H and coincides with K on F H remains an open problem.
Ch. 55: Valuesof Non-Transferable UtilityGarnes
2115
8.5. Another comparison of NTU values Recall that, in the game Ve of Example 4.3.1, the Shapley NTU value payoffis (½, ½, ½) with comparisõn vector )~ = (1, 1, 1) and thät the Harsanyi NTU value payoffis (I E 21 5' e ~ )with the same )~. Roth argues that (½, 3, I 0) is the only reasonable outcome 3' while Aumann counters that there are circumstances in which (3, 3, ½) is reasonable as an expected outcome, though this argument is less compelling when e is very small. Hence, one might argue that 3 should get something but that the payoff to 3 should decline as e declines, a feature captured by the Harsanyi NTU value in this example. The unique consistent value payoffvector is (1 + ~, 1 + ~, 2 (1 - e)) with comparison system A = {1s}. This solution can be justified using an argument based on a repeated bargaining model. Suppose that, with equal probability, one player is chosen randomly to propose a feasible payoff in Ve (N) and suppose that player i has been chosen. If i's first-round proposal is unanimously accepted, then the bargaining game ends and the players receive their specified payoffs. If at least one player rejects i's proposal, then i exits the garne with probability p and stays in the garne with probability 1 - p. If S is the set of remaining players (so S -----N with probability 1 - p and S = N \ i with probability p), then a rnember of S (possibly i if S = N) is chosen with equal probability to propose a feasible payoff in Ve(S) in the second round, and the process repeats itself. When a player exits, he receives a payoff of 0 and never reenters the bargaining process. In order to obtain payoffs of 1/2 in this bargaining game, players 1 and 2 need the agreernent of player 3 (since (I, I ' 0) c Ve(N)) or they need player 3 to have exited the garne (since (½, I) 6 V~(1, 2)). If 2 exits before 1 and 3, however, then 1 ends up with a payoff of e (if he strikes a bargain with 3) or 0 (if he fails to strike a bargain with 3). Hence, 1 and 2 are concerned with striking a deal before 3 exits the bargaining process. In the extreme case of e = 0, player 3 is in a powerful position. Players 1 and 2 rnay be willing to make a relatively large first-round concession to 3 (which 3 accepts) in order to avoid a payoff of 0 if 3 is not the frst player to exit. This is reflected in the consistent value payoff of (~, ~-, ~) in the garne V0. In the other extreme case in which e = 1, players 1 and 2 can guarantee themselves a payoff of 1/2 each, with or without the presence of player 3. Again, this situation is reflected in the consistent value payoff of (½, ½, 0) in the game V1 and supports Roth's (static) argument in favor of (I, »1 0). Finally, the garne V1/2 is completely symmetric and the consistent value of (3, 3, 3) reflects this symmetry. Note that, unlike the Shapley NTU value, the consistent value specifies syrnmetric payoffs only when the underlying NTU garne itself is symmetric. The justification for the consistent value in this example as the outcorne of a dynamic bargaining rnodel extends to general NTU garnes. In Hart and Mas-Colell (1996a), the authors present a dynamic bargaining rnodel as described above and prove that, for a large class of NTU games (basically the class F~), every limit point (as p --+ 0) of a sequence of subgame perfect equilibrium payoff configurations is a consistent value payoff configuration. If the NTU game is a pure bargaining garne, then every subgame
R.RMcLean
2116
perfect equibrium payoff vector of the associated dynamic garne converges to the Nash Bargaining Solution. If V corresponds to a TU garne v, then the associated dynamic garne has a unique subgame perfect equibrium payoff vector that converges to the Shapley value of v.
9. Final remarks 9.1. VaIues and cores of convex N T U garnes As we have repeatedly emphasized, the values and solutions presented in this chapter are all based on axiomatized notions of fairness. A n important alternative concept is that of the core, which is defined in terms of coalitional stability. Let V be an NTU garne. A vector x 6 ~ N can be improved upon if there exists an S ___N and y E V (S) such that yi > x i ' for each i E S. DEFINITION 9.1.1. A vector x E ~~N is a core payoff for V if x E V ( N ) and x cannot be improved upon. The set of core payoffs of V is denoted core(V). If V corresponds to v E GN, then x 6 core(V) if and only if I s • x s >/v(S) for each S _ N and 1N • x «, v(N). If v e GN, we will write core(v). In the TU case, it is not generally true that ~0(v) ~ core(v) even if core(v) is not empty. However, ~0(r) E core(v) if v is a convex garne. A garne v E GN is convex (or supermodular) if v(S) + v ( T ) <~ v(S U T) + v(S M T) whenever S, T ___N. Convex garnes were first studied in Shapley (1971), where it was shown that the value is an element of the core of a convex game. However, the actual result is more general than this and we describe it now. For v ~ GN and R E £2, define the marginal worth vector 3(R, v) as the point in ~N whose /th component is A i ( R , v). In Theorem 3 of Shapley (1971), it is shown that the set of extreme points of the core of a convex garne v is precisely the set {3(R, V)}RE~? of marginal worth vectors and, therefore, the Shapley value belongs to the core. However, this also means that every random order value belongs to the core of a convex game, i.e., if v is convex, then
U ~Op(V)=core(v). pcM(~) Weber (1988) has shown that core(r) c_ Up~M(~) ~Op(V) for any game v E GN, Ichiishi (1981) proved that if the converse is true, then v is convex. We are interested in the extent to which these results generalize to convex NTU garnes and the p - S h a p l e y value correspondence 4~p. A game V E FN is cardinal convex if V*(S) + V * ( T ) c V * ( S U T) + V * ( S C3T) [see Sharkey (1981)]. It is easy to show that if v is a convex TU garne and if V is the NTU garne derived from v, then V is cardinal
Ch. 55:
Values of Non-Transferable Utility Games
2117
convex. It is also straightforward to show that if V is cardinal convex and if vz is defined V, then vz is a convex TU garne. Define the inner core of an NTU garne V to be incore(V) =- {x ~ V(N) I v~ is defined for some )~ 6 ~N+ and )~ * x E core(v~)}. By combining the definitions with the results for TU garnes mentioned above, we conclude that for any NTU garne V, incore(V) ___UpeM(S?) ~Op(V) and in fact we have: PROPOSITION 9.1.2 [Levy and McLean (1991)]. If V is a cardinal convex garne, then UpcM(X2) ~Õp(V) = incore(V). It is well known that incore(V) c core(V) for any V so Proposition 9.1.2 generalizes results in Kern (1985, Theorem 4.4) and Ichiishi (1983, p. 148). Although incore(V) _ core(V), this containment can be strict if V does not correspond to a TU garne. In fact, incore(V) may be a nonempty, proper subset of core(V) even if V is cardinal convex. For an example see Levy and McLean (1991).
9.2. Applications of values for NTU garnes with a continuum of players Many political and economic situations are best modelled as garnes with infinitely many players. The value theory of such garnes comprises an extensive literature beginning with the fundamental study of Aumann and Shapley (1974). Values of NTU games with a continuum of players have been studied in several contexts. Value allocations are discussed extensively in Chapter 36 and, for economies with a continuum of agents (and satisfying a number of other regularity conditions), a "value equivalence" principle holds: the set of Walras allocations is equal to the set of value allocations. Another economic application of the NTU value arises in the theory of "Power and Taxes" as originally presented in Aumann and Kurz (1977a, 1977b). [See also Aumann, Kurz and Neyman (1987) and Osborne (1984) and the references cited therein.]
9.3. NTU values for garnes with incomplete information In many bargaining problems, individuals possess private information that affects their evaluation or utility of different outcomes. In the presence of incomplete information, the resolution of bargaining is complicated by the fact that the arbitrator taust request that the agents reveal their types before he can recommend an outcome. Of course, the agents will behave strategically and will "misrepresent" themselves to the arbitrator in a way favorable to themselves. For treatments that generalize the NBS to the incomplete information case, see Harsanyi and Selten (1972) and Myerson (1984a). In Myerson (1984b), the NTU value is extended to cooperative garnes with incomplete information in a way that generalizes the results of Myerson (1984a) for the pure bargaining case.
2118
R.RMcLean
Refcrences Aumalm, R. (1985a), "An axiomaüzation of the non-transferable utility value", Econometrica 53:599-612. Aumann, R. (1985b), "On the non-transferable utility value: A comment on the Roth-Shafer examples", Econometrica 53:667-677. Aumann, R. (1986), "A rejoinder', Econometilca 54:985-989. Aumann, R., and M. Kurz (1977a), "Power and taxes", Econometrica 45:1137-1161. Aumann, R., and M. Kurz (1977b), "Power and taxes in a multi-commodity economy", Jottrnal of Public Economics 9:139-161. Aumann, R., M. Kurz and A. Neyman (1987), "Power and public goods", Jottrnal of Economic Theory 42:108-127. Aumann, R., and L.S. Shapley (1974), Values of Nonatomic Garnes (Princeton University Press, Princeton,
NJ). Clarke, E (1983), Optimization and Nonsmooth Analysis (Wiley Interscience, New York). Dilessen, T. (1991), "A survey of consistency properties in cooperative garne theory", SIAM Review 33:4359. Fleming, W. (1969), "The Canchy problem for a nonlinear first order partial differential equation', Journal of Differential Equations 5:515-530. Harsanyi, J. (1963), "A simplified bargaining model for the n-person garne", International Economic Review 4:194-220. Harsanyi, I., and R. Selten (1972), "A generalized Nash bargaining solution for two person bargaining garnes with incomplete information", Management Science 18:80-106. Hart, S. (1985a), "An axiomatization of Harsanyi's non-transferable utility solution", Econometilca 53:12951313. Hart, S. (1985b), "NTU garnes and markets: Some examples and the Harsanyi solution", Econometrica 53:1445-1450. Hart, S. (1985c), "Axiomatic approaclies to coalitional bargaining', in: A. Roth, ed., Game Theoretic Models of Bargaining (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) 305-319. Hart, S. (1994), "On pilze garnes", in: N. Megiddo, ed., Essays in Garne Theory in Honor of Michael Maschler (Springer, New York) 111-121. Hart, S., and M. Kurz (1983), "On the endogenous formation of coalitions", Econometrica 51:1047-1064. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1989), "Potential, value and consistency", Econometilca 57:589-614. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1991), Personal Communication. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1995a), "Egalitarian solutions of large games: A continuum of players", Mathematics of Operations Research 20:959-1002. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1995b), "Egalitarian solutions of large garnes: The asymptotic approach", Mathematics of Operations Research 20:1003-1022. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1996a), "Bargaining and value", Econometilca 64:357-380. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1996b), "Harsanyi values of large economies: Noneqtfivalence to competitive equilibria", Garnes and Economic Beliavior 13:74-99. Ichiishi, T. (1981), "Supermodularity: Applications to convex garnes and the greedy algorithm for LP", Journal of Economic Theory 25:283-286. Ichiishi, T. (1983), Garne Theory for Economic Analysis (Academic Press, New York). Imai, H. (1983), "On Harsanyi's solution", International Journal of Game Theory 12:161-179. Kalai, E. (1977a), "Non-symmetric Nash solutions and replications of two person bargaining", International Jonrnal of Garne Theory 6:129-133. Kalai, E. (1977b), "Proportional solutions to bargaining situations: Interpersonal utility comparisons", Econometilca 45:1623-1630. Kalai, E., and D. Samet (1987), "On weighted Shapley values", International Journal of Game Theory 16:1623-1630.
Ch. 55:
Valuesof Non-Transferable Utility Garnes
2119
Kalai, E., and D. Samet (1985), "Monotonic solutions to general cooperative garnes", Econometrica 53:307327. Kern, R. (1985), "The Shapley transfer value without zero weights", International Joumal of Game Theory 14:73-92. Kurz, M. (1994), "Garne theory and public economics", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 33, 1153-1192. Levy, A., and R. McLean (1989), "Weighted coalition strncture values", Garnes and Economic Behavior 1:234-249. Levy, A., and R. McLean (1991 ), "An axiomatization of the non-symmetric NTU value", International Journal of Garne Theory 19:109-127. Maschler, M., and G. Owen (1989), "The consistent Shapley value for 1iyperplane garnes", International Journal of Garne Theory 18:389-407. Maschler, M., and G. Owen (1992), "The consistent Shapley value for garnes without side payments", in: R. Selten, ed., Rational Interaction: Essays in Honor of John Harsanyi (Springer, New York) 5-12. Myerson, R. (1984a), "Two person bargaining problems with incomplete information", Econometrica 52:461487. Myerson, R. (1984b), "Cooperative garnes with incomplete information", International Journal of Garne Theory 13:69-96. Nash, J. (1950), "The bargaining problem", EconomeWica 28:155-162. Orshan, G. (1992), "The consistent Shapley value in hyperplane garnes from a global standpoint", International Joumal of Garne T1ieory 21:1-11. Osbome, M. (1984), "W1iy do some goods bear 1iigher taxes tlian others?", Jottmal of Economic Theory 32:301-316. Owen, G. (1972a), "Multilinear extensions of garnes", Management Science 18:64-79. Owen, G. (1972b), "Values of garnes without side payments', International Journal of Garne Theory 1:94109. Owen, G. (1977), "Values of garnes with a pfiori unions", in: R. Heml and O. Moesclilin, eds., Essays in Mathematical Economics and Garne Theory (Springer, New York) 76-88. Owen, G. (1994), "The non-consistency and non-uniqueness of the consistent value", in: N. Megiddo, ed., Essays in Garne T1ieory in Honor of Michael Maschler (Springer, New York) 155-162. Peleg, B. (1986), "A proof that the core of an ordinal convex garne is a von Neumann-Morgenstem solution", Mathematical Social Sciences 11:83-87. Roth, A. (1979), Axiomatic Models of Bargaining, Lecmre Notes in Economics and Mathematical Systems, No. 170 (Springer, New York). Rotli, A. (1980), "Values of garnes without side payments: Some difficulties with current concepts", Econometrica 48:457-465. Roth, A. (1986), "On the NTU value: A reply to Aumann", Econometrica 54:981-984. Samet, D. (1985), "An axiomatization of the Egalitarian solution", Mathematical Social Sciences 9:173-181. Shafer, W. (1980), "On the existence and interpretation of value allocations", Econometrica 48:467-476. Shapley, L. (1953a), "Additive and non-additive set functions', PhD Thesis (Department of Mathematics, Princeton University). Shapley, L. (1953b), "A value for n-person garnes", in: H. Kuhn and A. Tucker, eds., Contributions to the Theory of Games II (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ) 307-317. Shapley, L. (1969), "Utility comparisons and the theory of garnes", La Decision (Editions du Centre National de le Recherche Scientifique, Paris). Shapley, L. (1971), "Cores of convex garnes", International Joumal of Garne T1ieory 1:11-26. Sharkey, W. (1981), "Convex garnes without side payments", International Joumal of Garne Theory 11:101106. Thomson, W. (1994), "Cooperative models of bargaining", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 35, 1237-1284.
2120
R.RMcLean
Weber, R. (1988), "Probabilistic values for games", in: A. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd Shapley (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) 101-119. Winter, E. (1991), "On nontransferable utility games with coalition strncture", International Joumal of Garne Theory 20:53-64. Winter, E. (1992), "On bargaining position descriptions in NTU games: Symmetry versus asymmetry', International Journal of Garne Theory 21:191-111. Young, H.E (1988), "Individual contribution and just compensation", in: A. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd Shapley (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) 267-278.
Chapter 56
VALUES OF GAMES WITH INFINITELY MANY PLAYERS ABRAHAM NEYMAN Institute of Mathematics and Center for Rationality and lnteractive Decision Theory, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem, Israel
Contents 1. Introduction 1.1. An oufline of the chapter
2. 3. 4. 5.
Prelude: Values of large finite garnes Definitions The value onpNA and bv~NA Limiting values 5.1. The weak asymptotic value 5.2. The asymptofic value
6. 7. 8. 9.
The mixing value Formulas for values Uniqueness of the value of nondifferentiable garnes Desired properties of values 9.1. Sl~ong positivity 9.2. The partition value 9.3. The diagonal property
10. Semivalues 11. Partially symmetric values 11.1. Non-symmetric and partially symmetric values 11.2. Measure-based values
12. The value and the core 13. Comments on some classes of garnes 13.1. Absolutely continuous non-atomic garnes 13.2. Garnes inpNA 13.3. Garnes in bv1NA
References
Handbook of Game Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.rd All rights reserved
2123 2123 2125 2127 2129 2133 2134 2135 2140 2140 2150 2151 2151 2151 2151 2152 2154 2155 2157 2159 2161 2161 2161 2161 2162
2122
A. Neyman
Abstract This chapter studies the theory of value of garnes with infinitely many players. Garnes with infinitely many players are models of interactions with many players. Often most of the players are individually insignificant, and are effective in the game only via coalitions. At the same time there may exist big players who retain the power to wield single-handed influence. The interactions are modeled as cooperative games with a continuum of players. In general, the continuum consists of a non-atomic part (the "ocean"), along with (at most countably many) atoms. The continuum provides a convenient framework for mathematical analysis, and approximates the results for large finite games well. Also, it enables a unified view of games with finite, countable, or oceanic player-sets, or indeed any mixture of these. The value is defined as a map from a space of cooperative games to payoffs that satisfies the classical value axioms: additivity (linearity), efficiency, symmetry and positivity. The chapter introduces many spaces for which there exists a unique value, as well as other spaces on which there is a value. A garne with infinitely many players can be considered as a limit of finite garnes with a large number of players. The chapter studies limiting values which are defined by means of the limits of the Shapley value of finite garnes that approximate the given garne with infinitely many players. Various formulas for the value which express the value as an average of marginal contribution are studied. These value formulas capture the idea that the value of a player is his expected marginal contribution to a perfect sample of size t of the set of all players where the size t is uniformly distributed on [0,1]. In the case of smooth games the value formula is a diagonal formula: an integral of marginal contributions which are expressed as partial derivatives and where the integral is over all perfect samples of the set of players. The domain of the formula is further extended by changing the order of integration and derivation and the introduction of a well-crafted infinitesimal perturbation of the perfect samples of the set of players provides a value formula that is applicable to many additional garnes with essential nondifferentiabilities.
Keywords garnes, cooperative, coalitional form, transferable utility, value, continuum of players, non-atomic
JEL classification: D70, D71, D63, C71
Ch. 56." Valuesof Garneswith Infinitely Many Players
2123
1. Introduction The Shapley value is orte of the basic solution concepts of cooperative game theory. It can be viewed as a sort of average or expected outcome, or as an a priori evaluation of the players' expected payoffs. The value has a very wide range of applications, particularly in economics and political science (see Chapters 32, 33 and 34 in this Handbook). In many of these applications it is necessary to consider garnes that involve a large number ofplayers. Often most of the players are individually insignificant, and are effective in the garne only via coalitions. At the same time there may exist big players who retain the power to wield single-handed influence. A typical example is provided by voting among stockholders of a corporation, with a few major stockholders and an "ocean" of minor stockholders. In economics, one considers an oligopolistic sector of firms embedded in a large population of "perfectly competitive" consumers. In all these cases, it is fruitful to model the garne as one with a continuum of players. In general, the continuum consists of a non-atomic part (the "ocean"), along with (at most countably many) atoms. The continuum provides a convenient framework for mathematical analysis, and approximates the results for large finite garnes weH. Also, it enables a unified view of garnes with finite, countable, or oceanic player-sets, or indeed any mixture of these.
1.1. An outline of the chapter In Section 2 we highlight a sample of a few asymptotic results on the Shapley value of finite garnes. These results motivate the defnition of garnes with infinitely many players and the corresponding value theory; in particular, Proposition 1 introduces a formula, called the diagonal formula of the value, that expresses the value (or an approximation thereof) by means of an integral along a specific path. The Shapley value for finite games is defined as a linear map from the linear space of garnes to payoffs that satisfies a list of axioms: symmetry, efficiency and the null player axiom. Section 3 introduces the definitions of the space of games with a continuum of players, and defines the symmetry, positivity and effciency of a map from games to payoffs (represented by finitely additive garnes) which enables us to define the value on a space of garnes as a linear, symmetric, positive and efficient map. The value does not exist on the space of all garnes with a continuum of players. Therefore the theory studies spaces of garnes on which a value does exist and moreover looks for spaces for which there is a unique value. Section 4 introduces several spaces of garnes with a continuum of players including the two spaces of games, pNA and bv'NA, which played an important role in the development of value theory for nonatomic garnes. Theorem 2 asserts that there exists a unique value on each of the spaces pNA and bvtNA as well as on pNAec. In addition there exists a (unique) value of norm 1 on the space tNA. Section 4 also includes a detailed outline of the proofs. A garne with infinitely many players can be considered as a limit of finite garnes with a large number of players. Section 5 studies limiting values which are defined by
2124
A. Neyman
means of the limits of the Shapley value of finite garnes that approximate the given game with infinitely many players. Section 5 also introduces the asymptotic value. The asymptotic value of a garne v is defined whenever all the sequences of Shapley values of finite garnes that "approximate" v have the same limit. The space of all garnes of bounded variation for which the asymptotic value exist is denoted ASYMP. Theorem 4 asserts that ASYMP is a closed linear space of garnes that contains b # M and the map associating an asymptotic value with each game in ASYMP is a value on ASYMP. Section 6 introduces the mixing value which is defined on all games of bounded variation for which an analogous formula of the random order one for finite garnes is well defined. The space of all garnes having a mixing value is denoted MIX. Theorem 5 asserts thatMIX is a closed linear space which containspNA, and the map that associates a mixing value with each game v in MIX is a value on MIX. Section 7 introduces value formulas. These value formulas capture the idea that the value of a player is his expected marginal contribution to a perfect sample of size t of the set of all players where the size t is uniformly distributed on [0, 1]. A value formula can be expressed as an integral of directional derivative whenever the garne is a smooth function of finitely many non-atomic measures. More generally, by extending the garne to be defined over all ideal coalitions - measurable [0, 1]-valued functions on the (measurable) space of players - this value formula provides a formula for the value of any garne in pNA. Changing the order of derivation and integration results in a formula that is applicable to a wider class of garnes: all those garnes for which the formula yields a finitely additive game. In particular, this modified formula defines a value on bv'NA or even on bv~M. When this formula does not yield a finitely additive garne, applying the directional derivative to a carefully crafted small perturbation of perfect samples of the set of players yields a value formula on a much wider space of garnes (Theorem 7). These include garnes which are nondifferentiable functions (e.g., a piecewise linear function) of finitely many non-atomic probability measures. Section 8 describes two spaces of garnes that are spanned by nondifferentiable functions of finitely many mutually singular non-atomic probability measures that have a unique value (Theorem 8). Orte is the space spanned by all piecewise linear functions of finitely many mutually singular non-atomic probability measures, and the other is the space spanned by all concave Lipschitz functions with increasing retums to scale of finitely many mutually singular non-atomic probability measures. The value is defined as a map from a space of games to payoffs that satisfies a short list of plausible conditions: linearity, symmetry, positivity and efficiency. The Shapley value of finite garnes satisfies many additional desirable properties. It is continuous (of norm 1 with respect to the bounded variation norm), obeys the null player and the dummy axioms, and it is strongly positive. In addition, any value that is obtained from values of finite approximations obeys an additional property called diagonality. Section 9 introduces such additional desirable value properties as strong positivity and diagonality. Theorem 9 asserts that strong positivity can replace positivity and linearity in the characterizafion of the value on pNAeo, and thus strong positivity and continuity can replace positivity and linearity in the characterization of a value on pNA. A strik-
Ch. 56." Valuesof Garnes with lnfinitely Many Players
2125
ing property of the value on pNA, the asymptotic value, the mixing value, or any of the values obtained by the formulas described in Section 7, is the diagonal property: if two garnes coincide on all coalitions that are "almost" a peffect sample (within e with respect to finitely many non-atomic probability measures) of the set of players, their values coincide. Theorem 11 asserts that any continuous value is diagonal. Section 10 studies semivalues which are generalizations of the value that do not necessarily obey the efficiency property. Theorem l 3 provides a characterization of all semivalues on pNA. Theorems 14 and 15 provide results on asymptotic semivalues. Section 11 studies partially symmetric values which are generalizations of the value that do not necessarily obey the symmetry axiom. Theorems 15 and 16 characterize in particular all the partially symmetric values on pNA and pM that are symmetric with respect to those symmetries that preserve a fixed finite partition of the set of players. A corollary of this characterization on pM is the characterization of all values on pM. A partially symmetric value, called a/z-value, is symmetric with respect to all symmetries that preserve a fixed non-atomic population measure/z and (in addition to linearity, positivity and efficiency), obeys the dummy axiom. Such a partially symmetric value is called a/z-value. Theorem 18 asserts the uniqueness of a/z-value on pNA(Ix). Theorem 19 asserts that an important class of nondifferentiable markets have an asymptotic #-value. Garnes that arise from the study of non-atomic markets, called market garnes, obey two specific conditions: concavity and homogeneity of degree 1. The core of such garnes is nonempty. Section 12 provides results on the relation between the value and the core of market games. Theorem 20 asserts the coincidence of the core and the value in the differentiable case. Theorem 21 relates the existence of an asymptotic value of nondifferentiable market garnes to the existence of a center of symmetry of its core. Theorems 22 and 23 describe the asymptotic/z-value and the value of market garnes with a finite-dimensional core as an average of the extreme points of the core.
2. Prelude: Values of large finite games This section introduces several asymptotic results on the Shapley value ge of finite garnes. These results can serve as an introduction to the theory of values of garnes with infinitely many players, by motivating the definitions of garnes with a continuum of players and the corresponding value theory. We start with the introduction of a representation of garnes with finitely many players. Let £ be a fixed positive integer and f : R e --+ IR a function with f ( 0 ) ----0. Given Wl . . . . . Wg 6 JR~_, define the n-person garne v = [ f ; wl ..... we] by
A special subclass of these games is weighted majority garnes where g = 1, 0 < q < ~ i ~ l wi and f(x) = 1 if x ~> q and 0 otherwise. The asymptotic results relate to se-
2126
A. Neyman
quences of finite games where the function f is fixed and the vector of weights varies. If the function f is differentiable at x, the directional derivative at x of the function f in the direction y ~ R e is f y ( X ) : = lime_,0+(f(x + ey) - f ( x ) ) / e . The following result follows from the proofs of results on the asymptotic value of non-atomic games. It can be derived from the proof in Kannai (1966) or from the proof in Dubey (1980)• PROPOSITION 1. Assume that f is a continuously differentiable function on [0, 1] •. For every e > 0 there is 3 > 0 such that if w l . . . . . wn E Re+ with (the normalization) ~in=l wi = (1 . . . . . 1) andmax~= 1 I[wil] < 3, then
aßv(i) - L l f w i ( t . . . . . t ) d t ~ «lltO/ll, where v = [ f ; Wl . . . . . Wn]. Thus, f o r every coalition S o f players,
Bp(S)
- Ji I fw(s)(t .....
t)dt
< «,
where ~ v ( S ) = E i E S ~ßv(i) and w ( S ) = ~ i c s tOi.
The limit of a sequence of garnes of the form [ f ; w ~ , . • tonk], k where f is a fixed function and w~, • " " » w nk k is a sequence of vectors in IRe+ with ~ n ik= 1 w i~ = ( 1 , " " ' 1) and maxT~ 1 IIwi [[ --+k~m 0 can be modeled by a 'garne' of the form f o (/zl . . . . . /zg) w h e r e / z = (/*1 . . . . . /ze) is a vector of non-atomic probability measures defined on a measurable space (I, C). If f is continuously differentiable, the limiting value formula thus corresponds to: ~o( f o tz) (S) = f01 f~(s) (t . . . . . t) dt.
The next results address the asymptotics of the value of weighted majority games. The n-person weighted majority game v = [q; to1 . . . . . Wn] with wl . . . . . Wn ~ IR+ and m 0 < q < Ei=I toi, is defined by v(S) = 1 if E i e s wi >/q and 0 otherwise. PROPOSITION 2 [Neyman (1981a)]. For every e > 0 there is K > 0 such that if v = [q; w l, • • •, Wn] is a weighted majority garne with w l, .. ., tOn C ]~+, Ei=ln wi = 1 and K m a x ~ l wi < q < 1 - K maxn~ wi, Bv(S)
- E
wi
<8
ieS
f o r every coalition S C {1 . . . . . n}.
Ch. 56." Values of Garnes with Infinitely Many Players
2127
In particular, if v~ -- [qÆ; w~ . . . . . wnk~] is a sequence of weighted majority garnes with w/~/> 0, ~in~l w~ ---~k~~ 1, and qk ---~k-+~ q with 0 < q < 1, then for any sequence of coalitions S~ C {1, .. •, nk}, l B I ) k ( S k ) - - ~ iESk 10ik ---~k~~ O. The limit of such a sequence o f weighted majority garnes is modeled as a garne of the form v = fq o tz where # is a non-atomic probability measure and fq (x) -----1 if x ~> q and 0 otherwise. The non-atomic probability measure # describes the value of this limiting garne:
~v(s)=u(s). The next result follows easily from the result of Berbee (1981). PROPOSITION 3. Let w l . . . . . wn, . • • be a sequence o f positive numbers with oo Wi=I Z i=1
and 0 < q < 1. There exists a sequence o f nonnegative numbers ~ßi, i ~ 1, with Y~~i:l I/Zi : 1, such t h a t f o r every e > 0 there is a positive constant 6 > 0 and a positive integer no such that i f v = [q'; ul . . . . . Uni is a weighted majority garne with n >~ no, Iq' - q l < ~ a n d ~ i n = l Iwi - ui] < ~, then
]~pv(i) - ~ßi] < e. Equivalently, let vk = [qk; w~ . . . . . wnk~] be a sequence of weighted majority garnes with Y~f~-I w/k - - + k ~ ~ 1 and w jk - + k ~ w w j and qk ---~k~~ q. Then the Shapley value of player i in the garne Vk converges as k --+ cx~ to a limit 7ti and ~-~~i:1 ~ i = l . The limit of such a sequence of weighted majority garnes can be modeled as a garne of the form v : fq o IZ w h e r e / z is a purely atomic measure with atoms i : 1, 2 . . . . and # ( i ) = wi. The sequence ~Pi describes the value of this limiting garne:
B/)(S) : ~
~ri.
iös
3. Definitions The space of players is represented by a measurable space (I, C). The members o f set I are called players, those o f C - coalitions. A game in coalitional form is a real-valued function v on C such that v(0) = 0. For each coalition S in C, the number v ( S ) is interpreted as the total payoff that the coalition S, if it forms, can obtain for its members; it is called the worth of S. The set of all garnes forms a linear space over the field of real numbers, which is denoted G. We assume that (I, C) is isomorphic to
2128
A. Neyman
([0, 1],/3), where B stands for the Borel subsets of [0, 1]. A game v isfinitely additive if v(S U T) = v(S) + v ( T ) whenever S and T are two disjoint coalitions. A distribution of payoffs is represented by a finitely additive game. A value is a mapping from garnes to distributions of payoffs, i.e., to finitely additive garnes that satisfy several plausible conditions: linearity, symmetry, positivity and efficiency. There are several additional desirable conditions: e.g., continuity, strong positivity, a null player axiom, a dummy player axiom, and so on. It is remarkable, however, that a short list of plausible conditions that define the value suffices to determine the value in many cases of interest, and that in these cases the unique value satisfies many additional desirable properties. We start with the notations and definitions needed formally to define the value, and set forth four spaces of games on which there is a unique value. A game v is monotonic if v(S) >~ v ( T ) whenever S D T; it is of bounded variation if it is the difference of two monotonic garnes. The set of all garnes of bounded variation (over a fixed measurable space (I, C)) is a vector space. The variation of a garne v 6 G, IIv II, is the supremum of the variation of v over all increasing chains S1 C $2 C ... C Sn in C. Equivalently, Ilvll = inf{u(I) + w(1): u, w a r e monotonic garnes with v = u - w} (inf0 = co). The variation defines a topology on G; a basis for the open neighborhood of a game v in G consists of the sets {u c G: llu - vlI < e} where e varies over all positive numbers. Addition and multiplication of two garnes are continuous and so is the multiplication of a garne and a real number. A game v has bounded variation if IIv II < co. The space of all garnes of bounded variation, BV, is a Banach algebra with respect to the variation norm [[ 11, i.e., it is complete with respect to the distance defined by the norm (and thus it is a Banach Space) and it is closed under multiplication which is continuous. Let ~ denote the group of automorphisms (i.e., one-to-one measurable mappings O from I onto I with 0 -1 measurable) of the underlying space (I, C). Each O in ~ induces a linear mapping O . of B V (and of the space of all games) onto itself, defined by ( O . v ) ( S ) = v ( O S ) . A set of games Q is called symmetric if O. Q = Q for all 6) in ~. The space of all finitely additive and bounded garnes is denoted FA; the subspace of all measures (i.e., countably additive garnes) is denoted M and its subspace consisting of all non-atomic measures is denoted NA. The space of all non-atomic elements of FA is denoted AN. Obviously, NA C M C FA C BV, and each of the spaces NA, AN, M, FA and BV is a symmetric space. Given a set of garnes Q, we denote by Q+ all monotonic games in Q, and by Q1 the set of all garnes v in Q+ with v(I) = 1. A map ~o: Q -+ B V is called positive if ¢p(Q+) c BV+; symmetric if for every O c G and v in Q, O . v E Q implies that ~o(O,v) = O,(~0v); and efficient i f f o r every v in Q, (~ov)(1) = v(I). DEFINITION 1 [Aumann and Shapley (1974)]. Let Q be a symmetric linear subspace of BV. A value on Q is a linear map ¢p: Q --+ FA that is symmetric, positive and efficient. The definition of a value is naturally extended also to include spaces of garnes that are not necessarily included in BV. Thus let Q be a linear and symmetric space of garnes.
Ch. 56: Valuesof Garnes with lnfinitely Many Players
2129
DEFINITION 2. A value on Q is a linear map from Q into the space of finitely additive games that is symmetric, positive (i.e., q)(Q+) c BV+), efficient, and q)(Q A BV) C FA. There are several spaces of games that have a unique value. One of them is the space of alS garnes with a finite support, where a subset T of I is called a support of a garne v if v(S) ---- v(S (q T) for every S in C. The space of all games with finite support is denoted FG. THEOREM ] [Shapley (1953a)]. There is a unique value on FG. The unique value ~ß on FG is given by the following formula. Let T be a finite support o f the garne v (in FG). Then, ~ßv(S) ----0 for every S in C with S A T = 0, and for t 6 T,
2Z where n is the number of elements of the support T, the sum runs over all n ! orders of T, and 79t~ is the set of all elements of T preceding t in the order T~. Finite garnes can also be identified with a function v defined on a finite subfield zr of C: given a real-valued function v defined on a finite subfield zc of C with v(0) = 0, the Shapley value of the garne v is defined as the additive function ~ß : zr --+ R defined by its values on the atoms of zr; for every atom a of re,
1
grv(a) = ~ ~'R.[v(/ga~ U a ) - v('Pa~)], where n is the number of atoms of z~, the sum runs over all n ! orders of the atoms of zr, and 79ff is the union of all atoms of zr preceding a in the order ~ .
4. T h e value on pNA and bv1NA Ler pNA (pM, pFA) be the closed (in the bounded variation norm) algebra generated by N A (M, FA, respectively). Equivalently, pNA is the closed linear subspace that is generated by powers of measure in ]VA ~ [Aumann and Shapley (1974), L e m m a 7.2]. Similarly, p M (pFA) is the closed algebra that is generated by powers of elements in M (FA). Let ]l II~ be defined on the space of alS garnes G by Ilvll~ = inf{/z(I): # c NA +, # - v c B V +, # + v ~ B V + } + 8up{Iv(S)l: S ~ Œ}. In the definition o f [[v[[~, we use the c o m m o n convention that inf 0 -----co. The definition of Il [[2 is an analog of the C l norm of continuously differentiable functions; e.g., if f is continuously differentiable on [0, 1] and /x is a non-atomic probability
A. Neyman
2130
measure, [If o/zll ~ = max{If'(t)]: 0 ~< t ~< 1} + max{[f(t)[: 0 ~< t ~< 1}. Note that I[uv ]1~ ~< llu Iloc IIv II~c for two games u and v. The function v ~-~ [Iv II~ defines a topology on G; a basis for the open neighborhood of a garne v in G consists of the sets {u 6 G: [lu - vll~c < e} where e varies over all positive numbers, The space of garnes pNAoc is defined as the II 11c~ closed linear subspace that is generated by powers of measures in NA 1 . Obviously, p N A ~ C pNA (11 IIoc ) l] II)- Both spaces contain many garnes of interest. If/~ is a measure in NA 1 and f : [0, 1] -+ IR is a function with f ( 0 ) = 0, then f o I~ ~ pNA if and only if f is absolutely continuons [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Theorem C] and in that case I]f o/~ [[ = fò If~(t)] dt where f~ is the (Radon-Nikodym) derivative of the function f , and f o I~ ~ p N A ~ if and only if f is continuously differentiable on [0, 1]. Also, if/~ = (/~l . . . . , #t0 is a vector of NA measures with range {/z(S): S c d} = : ~(t~), and f is a C l function on ~(/z) with f ( / z ( 0 ) ) --- 0, then f o/z ~ p N A ~ [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Proposition 7.1]. Let bvrNA (bv~M, bv~FA) be the closed linear space generated by garnes of the form f o/z where f ~ bv ~-----:{ f : [0, 1] -+ R [ f is of bounded variation and continuous at 0 and at 1 with f ( 0 ) = 0}, and/z ~ NA 1 (/z c M 1, /z E FA1). Obviously, p N A ~ C pNA C bv~NA C bv~M C bv~FA. THEOREM 2 [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Theorems A, B; Monderer (1990), Theorein 2.1]. Each o f the spaces pNA, bvINA, p N A ~ has a unique value. The proof of the uniqueness of the value on these spaces relies on two basic arguments. Let/z 6 NA 1 and let G(/x) be the subgroup o f ~ of all automorphisms 69 that are B-measure-preserving, i.e., # ( O S ) = / z ( S ) for every coalition S in C. Then the set of all finitely additive garnes u that are fixed points of the action of ~(tx) (i.e., @,u --- u for every 69 in ~(/z)) are games of the form ol#, « E R (here we use the standardness assumption that (I, C) is isomorphic to ([0, 1], B)). Therefore, if Q is a symmetric space of garnes and q) : Q ~ FA is symmetric,/z c NA 1, and f : [0, 1] -+ R is such that f o / z c Q, then O , ( f o #) = f o tz for every (9 6 G(/z). It follows that the finitely additive garne q)(f o/z) is a fixed point of ~(/z), which implies that ~o(f o/z) = o~/z. If, moreover, q) is also efficient, then q)(f o #) = f(1)/z. The spaces pNA and bv1NA are closed linear spans of games of the form f o/z. The space p N A ~ is in the closed linear span of games of the form f o # with f o/z in p N A ~ . Therefore, each of the spaces pNAoc, pNA and bvtNA has a dense subspace on which there is at most one value. To complete the uniqueness proof, it suffices to show that any value on these spaces is indeed continuous. For that we apply the concept of internality. A linear subspace Q of B V is said to be reproducing if Q = Q+ - Q+. It is said to be internal if for all v in Q,
IIv[I = inf{u(1) + w(1): u, w c Q+ and v = u - w}. Clearly, every internal space is reproducing. Also any linear positive mapping ~o from a closed reproducing space Q into B V is continuous, and any linear positive and efficient
Ch. 56." Valuesof Garnes with lnfinitely Many Players
2131
mapping ~o from an intemal space Q into B V has norm 1 [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Propositions 4.15 and 4.7]. Therefore, to complete the proof of uniqueness, it is sufficient to show that each of the spaces pNA, bv1NA and pNAec is intemal. The closure of an intemal space is internal [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Proposition 4.12] and any linear space of garnes that is the union of intemal spaces is intemal. Therefore one demonstrates that each of these spaces is the union of spaces that contain a dense intemal subspace. There are several dense intemal subspaces o f p N A [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Lemma 7.18; Reichert and Tauman (1985); Monderer and Neyman (1988), Section 5]. The proof of the intemality of bvtNA is more involved [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Section 8]. Note thät if Q and Q~ are two linear symmetric spaces of garnes and Q D Q', the existence of a value on Q implies the existence of a value on Q~. However, the uniqueness of a value on one of them does not imply uniqueness on the other. There are, for instance, subspaces o f p N A which have more than one value [Hart and Neyman (1988), Example 4]. There are however results that provide sufficient conditions for subspaces of pNA to have a unique value. For a coalition S we define the restriction of v to S, rs, by r s ( T ) = v(S A T) for every T ~ C. A set of games M is restrictable if vs c M for every v ~ M and for every S E C. Hart and Monderer [(1997), Theorem 3.6] prove the uniqueness of the value on restrictable subspaces of p N A ~ that contain NA. This is the non-atomic version of the analogous result for finite garnes proved in Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) and Neyman (1989). Existence of a value on pNA and bv'NA is proved in Aumann and Shapley, Chapter I. We outline below a proof that is based on the proof of Mertens and Ney// man (2001). Assume that v = ~i=1 f/ o /z i with fi ~ bv ~ and Izi E NA I. Define 9v(S) = ~i= n 1 J~(1)/zi(S). It follows from the continuity at 0 and 1 of each of the functions ä~ that
• j~(1)m(s) i=1
=
lim -
e--~ 0+ E 1
f°l-EI~
J~ (t + e ß i ( S ) ) --
i=1
f/(t)
'/_-~1
1
dt.
By Lyapunov's Theorem, applied to the vector measure (/zl . . . . . /zn), for every 0 ~< t ~< 1 - « there are coalitions T C R with/zi (T) = t and IZi (R) = t + eßi (S). Therefore, if v is monotonic,
v(R)-l)(T)=Zfi(t+6[~i(S))i=1
fi(t)
~0,
i=1
n and therefore ~pv(S) >1 O. In particular, if 0 = ~ i = 1
fi
o IL i - -
k ~ j = l gJ o t)j where
B , gj ~ bv' and #i, vj E NA 1, ~ i n l fi(1)/zi = ~~=1 g j ( 1 ) v j , and thus also ~pv is well defined, i.e., it is independent of the presentation. Obviously, gor ~ NA C FA and ~pv(I) = v(1) and ~o is symmetric and linear. Therefore q9 defines a value on the linear and symmetric subspace of bvtNA of all garnes of the form ~i~=1 fi o #i with n
A. Neyman
2132
a positive integer, f/ c bv I and #i ~ NA 1. We next show that q) is of n o r m 1 and thus has a (unique) extension to a c o n t i n u o u s value (of n o r m 1) on bvINA. For each u E FA, Ilu Il = sups~e lu (S) I + lu (SC)i. Therefore, it is sufficient to prove that for every coalition S c C, Iq)v(S)[ + I¢pv(SC)l ~ [[vl[. For each positive integer m let So C $1 C $2 C . - . c Sm and S~ C Sf C . . . C Sc be measurable subsets of S and S c = I \ S respectively with a n d # i ( S j ) = ù5T;tx~ j •( S c) . For every 0 ~< t ~< ùSTr Bi (Sj) = ,~Tr/A(S) j • 1 let Lt be a measurable subset of I \ (Sm U Sc0 with/zi (It) = t. Define the increasing sequence of coalitions To C Tl C - . . C T2m b y TO = It, T2j-1 = It U Sj U S j _ 1 and T2j = It U S./U S~, j = 1 . . . . . m. Obviously, 2m
I1~11 /> Y-~~I~(Tj) - ~ ( T s - , ) I j=l O7--1
>> ~_, v(T2j+l) - v(T2j) + 2.., v(T2j) - v(T2j-~) • j=o
j=~
1
Set e = tlZZT"Note that
/i
~
fi(t-Fej-Feßi(S))-Zfi(t-l-je
= Li=I 1JO 8
i
L/__~IJ~(t -F«I~i(S))
) dt
1
fi(t)
dt--+m-+oo q0v(S),
i 1
and similarly
1 ,,« ,~ r tl
_-
tl
1f'[ '/_~l ~; (,) - ~i=1 A. (t -
-
)]
«~~i (s c
))] at ~,tl~~
~o~,(sc).
As
f~(t+«j+«m(s))
v(v2s+~) - ~ G 2 s ) = i=1
-~_,f,.(t+j«), i=1
and
v(T2j)-v(T2j-,)=
fi(t+2je)-Zfi(t+2je-elzi(SC)), i=1
i=1
Ch. 56:
2133
Values of Garnes with Infinitely Many Players
we deduce that for each fixed 0 ~< t ~< e,
fi (t + ej + elZi (S)) - E j=0
i=1
i
fi(t q- je) i
" ° + ~[~~(~+~j~-~~(~+~~-~~~(s •
~))l] ~l,~,,
i=1
and therefore [qgv(S)[ + Iq)v(SC)] <~ [Ivll. It follows that the map ~0, which is defined on a dense subspace of bvWA and with values in NA, is linear, symmetric, efficient, and of norm 1, and therefore ~0 has a unique extension to a continuous value on bvWA. The bounded variation of the functions fi is used in the above proof to show that the • b mtegrals f~ f ( x ) dx, 0 ~< a < b <~ 1, are well defined. Therefore, the proof also demonstrates the result of Tauman (1979), i.e., that there is a unique value of norm 1 on IFNA: the closed linear space of garnes that is generated by garnes of the form f o # where # ~ NA 1 and f ~ IF = { f : [0, 1] --+ ]R [ f ( 0 ) = 0, f integrable and continuous at 0 and 1 }. The integrability requirement can also be dropped. Mertens and Neyman (2001) prove the existence of a value (of norm 1) on the spaces ~AN D 'NA: the closure in the variation distance of the linear space spanned by all garnes f o/z where/z 6 AN 1 DNA I and f is a real-valued function defined on [0, 1] with f ( 0 ) = 0 and continuous at 0 and 1. Moreover, the continuity of the function f at 0 and 1 can be further weakened by requiring the upper and lower averages of f on the intervals [0, e] and [1 - e, 1] to converge to f ( 0 ) = 0 and f ( 1 ) , respectively. The existence of a value (of norm 1) on pNA and bvWA also follows from various constructive approaches to the value, such as the limiting approach discussed immediately below and the value formulas approach (Section 7). Other constructive approaches include the mixing approach (Section 6) that provides a value on pNA. Each constructive approach describes a way of "computing" the value for a specific game. The space of all garnes that are in the (feasible) domain of each approach will form a subspace and the associated map will be a value. Each of the approaches has its advantages and each sheds additional interpretive light on the value obtained. We start with limiting value approaches.
5. Limiting values Limiting values are defined by means of the limits of the Shapley value of the finite garnes that approximate the given garne. Given a garne v on (I, C) and a finite measurable field zr, we denote by vr the restriction of the garne v to the finite field Jr. The real-valued function v:r (defined on Jr)
A. Neyman
2134
can be viewed as a finite game. The Shapley value for finite games 7rv~ on zr is given by (~ßvrc )(a) = 1 Z [ v ( 7 9 ~ U a ) _ v ( 7 9 ~ ) ] 7"4
'
where n is the number of atoms of re, the sum runs over all orders ~ of the atoms of re, and 79ff is the union of all atoms preceding a in the order 7~. 5.1. The weak asymptotic value The family of measurable finite fields (that contain a given coalition T) is ordered by inclusion, and given two measurable finite fields zr and zr ~ there is a measurable finite field ~rH that contains both zr and zc~. This enables us to define limits of functions of finite measurable fields. The weak asymptotic value o f the game v is defined as lim~r grv~r whenever the limit of grv~r (T) exists where 7r ranges over the family of measurable finite fields that include T. Equivalently, DEFINITION 3. Let v be a game. A game qgv is said to be the weak asymptotic value of v if for every S 6 C and every e > 0, there is a finite subfield zc of d with S 6 7r such that for any finite subfield zr t with 7r~ D re, IOv~,(S) - q0v(S)l < e. REMARKS. (1) Let v be a garne. The game v has a weak asymptotic value if and only if for every S in C and e > 0 there exists a finite subfield rc with S 6 zr such that for any finite subfield rr r with 7r~ D re, I7rvTr,(S) - 7tv~(S)I < e. (2) A garne v has at most one weak asymptotic value. (3) The weak asymptotic value ~0v of a garne v is a finitely additive game, and I[~ov Il ~< llvll whenever v E BV. THEOREM 3 [Neyman (1988), p. 559]. The set o f all garnes having a weak asymptotic value is a linear symmetric space o f garnes, and the operator mapping each garne to its weak asymptotic value is a value on that space. I f ASYMP* denotes all garnes with bounded variation having a weak asymptotic value, then ASYMP* is a closed subspace o f B V with bv~FA C ASYMP*. REMARKS. The linearity, symmetry, positivity and efficiency of ~p (the Shapley value for garnes with finitely many players) and of the map v ~ v~r imply the linearity, symmetry, positivity and efficiency of the weak asymptotic value map and also imply the linearity and symmetry of the space of garnes having a weak asymptotic value. The closedness of ASYMP* follows from the linearity of 7t and from the inequalities [I7rv~r11 ~< IIv~ II ~< Ilvll- The difficult part of the theorem is the inclusion bv1FA C ASYMP*, on which we will comment later. The inclusion bvrFA C ASYMP* implies in particular the existence of a value on bv1FA.
Ch. 56: Valuesof Garnes with lnfinitely Many Players
2135
5.2. The asymptotic value
The asymptotic value of a game v is defined whenever all the sequences of the Shapley values of finite games that "approximate" v have the same limit. Formally: given T in C, a T-admissible sequence is an increasing sequence (tel, zr2 . . . . ) of finite subfields of C such that T ~ Zrl and Ui 7ri generates C. DEFINITION 4. A garne ~0v is said to be the asymptotic value of v, if limk-+oc Ov~r~(T) exists and = ~ov(T) for every T 6 C and every T-admissible sequence (7ri)~l. REMARKS. (1) A game v has an asymptotic value if and only if lim~_+~ a p r i l ( T ) exists for every T in C and every T-admissible sequence 79 = (Jrk)~_-l, and the limit is independent of the choice of 79. (2) For any given v, the asymptotic value, if it exists, is clearly unique. (3) The asymptotic value q)v of a garne v is finitely additive, and II~0vll ~< Ilvll whenever v ~ BV. (4) If v has an asymptotic value q)v then v has a weak asymptotic value, which = q)v. (5) The dual of a game v is defined as the game v* given by v*(S) = v ( I ) - v ( I \ S ) . Then ~pv* = ~pv~ = lB(f-~)~r, and therefore v has a (weak) asymptotic value if and only if v* has a (weak) asymptotic value if and only if ( ~ Ü 2) has a (weak) asymptotic value, and the values coincide. The space of all games of bounded variation that have an asymptotic value is denoted ASYMP. THEOREM 4 [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Theorem F; Neyman (1981a); and Neyman (1988), Theorem A]. The set o f all garnes having an asymptotic value is a linear symmetric space o f garnes, and the operator mapping each garne to its asymptotic value is a value on that space. A S Y M P is a closed linear symmetric subspace o f B V which contains bv~ M. REMARKS. (1) The linearity and symmetry of ~p (the Shapley value for garnes with finitely many players), and of the map v -+ v~, imply the linearity and symmetry of the asymptotic value map and its domain. The efficiency and positivity of the asymptotic value follows from the efficiency and positivity of the maps v --+ v~r and v~ -+ 0 v ~ . The closedness of A S Y M P follows from both the linearity of ~p and the inequalities
I[lPv~ Il ~< IIv[l~ ~< IIvll. (2) Several authors have contributed to proving the inclusion b v t M C ASYMP. Let F L denote the set of measures with at most finitely many atoms and Ma all purely atomic measures. Each of the spaces, bv~NA, bv~FL and bvrMa is defined as the closed subspace of B V that is generated by garnes of the form f o # where f ~ bv ~ and/x is a probability measure in NA 1, F L 1, or Mä respectively.
A. Neyman
2136
Kannai (1966) and Aumann and Shapley (1974) show that pNA C ASYMP. Artstein (1971) proves essentially that pM~, C ASYMP. Fogelman and Quinzii (1980) show that pFL C ASYMP. Neyman (1981a, 1979) shows that bv1NA C ASYMP and bv~FL C ASYMP respectively. Berbee (1981), together with Shapley (1962) and the proof of Neyman [(1981 a), Lemma 8 and Theorem A], imply that b v IMa C ASYMP. It was further announced in Neyman (1979) that Berbee's result implies the existence of a partition value on bv~M. Neyman (1988) shows that bv~M C ASYMP. (3) The space of garnes, bv~M, is generated by scalar measure games, i.e., by garnes that are real-valued functions of scalar measures. Therefore, the essential part of the inclusion bv~M C ASYMP is that whenever f c bv' and/~ is a probability measure, f o/z has an asymptotic value. The tightness of the assumptions on f and/z for f o/z to have an asymptotic value follows from the next three remarks. (4) pFA ~ ASYMP [Neyman (1988), p. 578]. For example, Iz3 ¢ ASYMP whenever /-~ is a positive non-atomic finitely additive measure which is not countably additive. This illustrates the essentiality of the countable additivity of lz for f o/z to have an asymptotic value when f is a polynomial. (5) For 0 < q < 1, we denote by fq the function given by fq (x) = 1 if x ~> q and fq (x) = 0 otherwise. Let/z be a non-atomic measure with total mass 1. Then fq o tz has an asymptotic value if and only if/z is positive [Neyman (1988), Theorem 5.1]. There are garnes of the form fq o #, where/z is a purely atomic signed measure with Iz(I) = 1, for which f ! o/~ does not have an asymptotic value [Neyman (1988), Example 5.2]. 2
These two comments illustrate the essentiality of the positivity of the measure/z. (6) There are garnes of the form f o/z, where # 6 NA 1 and f is continuous at 0 and 1 and vanishes outside a countable set of points, which do not have an asymptotic value [Neyman (1981a), p. 210]. Thus, the bounded variation of the function f is essential for f o # to have an asymptotic value. (7) The set of garnes DIAG is defined [Aumann and Shapley (1974), p. 252] as the set of all garnes v in BV for which there is a positive integer k, measures/zl . . . . . /zk NA 1, and e > 0, such that for any coalition S 6 C with I~i(S) - Izj(S) <~ ~ for all 1 ~ i, j <~k, v(S) = O. DIAG is a symmetric linear subspace o f A S Y M P [Aumann and Shapley (1974)]. (8) If #1,/z2, /z3, are three non-atomic probabilities that are linearly independent, then the garne v defined by v(S) = min[/zl(S),/z2(S),/z3(S)] is not in ASYMP lAumann and Shapley (1974), Example 19.2]. (9) Garnes of the form fq o I~ w h e r e / z 6 M 1 and 0 < q < 1 are called weighted majority games; a coalition S is winning, i.e., v(S) = 1, if and only ifits total #-weight is at least q. The measure/z is called the weight measure and the number q is called the quota. The resu]t bvtM C ASYMP implies in particular that weighted majority garnes have an asymptotic value. (10) A two-house weighted majority garne v is the product of two weighted majority garnes, i.e., v = (fq o/z)(f« o v), where/z, v E M 1, 0 < c < 1, and 0 < q < 1. If/z, v
Ch. 56: Valuesof Games with Infinitely Many Players
2137
N A 1 with/z 7~ v and q ~ 1/2, v has an asymptotic value if and only if q 7~ c. Indeed, if q < c, (fq o # ) ( f c o v) - (f« o v) ~ D I A G and therefore (fq o l z ) ( f c o v) c b v ' N A + D I A G c A S Y M P ,
and if q = c ¢ i/2, (fq o tx)(fc o v) f~ A S Y M P [Neyman and Tauman (1979), proof of Proposition 5.42]. I f / z has infinitely many atoms and the set of atoms of v is disjoint to the set of atoms of/z, (fq o I z ) ( f c o v) has an asymptotic value [Neyman and Smorodinski (1993)]. (11) Let ,A denote the closed algebra that is generated by games of the form f o/z where/z c NA 1 and f E bv ~ is continuous. It follows from the proof of Proposition 5.5 in Neyman and Tauman (1979) together with Neyman (1981a) tbat ,A C A S Y M P and that for every u c ..4 and v ~ bv~NA, uv c A S Y M P . The following should shed light on the proofs regarding asymptotic and limiting values.
Let 7r be a finite subfield of C and let v be a garne. We will recall formulas for the Shapley value of finite garnes by applying these formulas to the garne vr. This will enable us to illustrate proofs regarding the limiting properties of the Shapley value ~ßv~r of the finite game v~r. Let A(Jr), or A for short, denote the set of atoms of re. The Shapley value of the garne v~ to an atom a in A is given by
¢'vrc(a) = ~ .
~[,,(e~ T£
u a) _ v(p«~)],
where lA[ stands for the number of elements of A, the summation ranges over all orders T¢ of the atoms in A, and P h is the union of all atoms preceding a in the order R. An alternative formula for ~v~ could be given by means of a family Xo, a c A(7r), of i.i.d, real-valued random variables that are uniformly distributed on (0, 1). The values of Xa, a c A(zr), induce with probability 1 an order 7~ on A; a precedes b if and only if Xa < Xb. AS Xa, a ~ A , are i.i.d., all orders are equally likely. Thus, identifying sets with their indicator functions, and letting I (Xo <~ Xb) denote the indicator of the event Xa <~ Xb, the value formula is
Burc(a)~-EUu(~_ibl(Xb ~Xa))--v(~bI(Xb<Xa))l" ~" " b c A
bcA
Thus, by conditioning on the value of Xa, and letting S ( t ) , 0 <~ t <~ 1, denote the union of all atoms b of 7c for which Xb <~ t, we find that ~ßv~ (a) = fo 1 E ( v ( S ( t ) U a) - v ( S ( t ) \ a)) dt.
2138
A. Neyman
Assurne now that the garne v is a continuously differentiable fnnction of finitely many non-atornic probability rneasures; i.e., v = f o / z , w h e r e / z = (/zl . . . . . /zn) ~ (NA1) n and f " ~ ( # ) --+ 7-4 is continuously differentiable. Then
v(S(t) U a) - v(S(t) \ a) = n-2--~_, O f (y)txi (a) i:1 a~i where y is a point in the interval [/z(S(t) \ a), I~(S(t) U a)]. Thus, in particular, ~a~~ ]v(S(t) tOa) - v(S(t) \ a)[ is bounded. For any scalar rneasure v, v(S(t)) is the surn ~ a ~ A ( r c ) v(a)I(Xa ~ t), i.e., it is a surn of [A(zr)] independent random variables with expectation tv(a) and variance t(1 t)v2(a). Therefore, E(v(S(t))) = tv(I) and
Var(S(t)) = t(1-t) ~
v2(a) ~< t ( l
-t)v(I)max{v(a):
a e
A(rr)].
aeA(~) oo Therefore, if # = (/zl ~ , . . ~ /zn) is a vector of measures, and ( Y'(k)k=_t is a sequence of finite fields with rnax{[~j(a)[: 1 ~< j ~< n, a ~ A(Zrk)} - + k - ~ ~ O, tz(S(t)) converges in distribution to t / t U ) ; so if T is a coalition with T e 7tk for every k, then
n
[v(Sk(t) U a ) - v(Sk(t) \ a ) ] - + k ~ ~
Z ~xi (tl~(I)) txi(T)' i=1
aCT a6A(2rk)
and therefore limk-+~c ~ v ~ k (T) exists and lirn grv~~ (T) = k---> o o
f01 fu(r)(tlz(I)) dt.
For any T-admissible sequence (Zrk)~__1 and non-atomic rneasure v, max{v(a): a E A(rrk)} --+k-+~ 0. Therefore any garne v = f o/z, where f is a continuously differentiable function defined on the fange of tz, {/z(S): S c C}, has an asymptotic value q)v whenever # = (#1 . . . . . /zn) is a vector of non-atomic measures. Also, given any e > 0 and a non-atornic element v of FA+, there exists a partition Jr such that max{v(a): a ~ A(Tr)} < e. Therefore v = f o / x has a w e a k asymptotic value ~vv whenever/~ = (/z I . . . . . /xn) is a vector of non-atomic bounded finitely additive measures. In both cases the value is given by 1
~ov(S) =
fO0
f~(s) (tt~(I)) dt.
The following tool which is of independent interest will be used later on to show how to reduce the proof of bv~NA C ASYMP (or bv~M C ASYMP) to the proof that fq o Ix E ASYMP where fq (x) = I (x ~> q), 0 < q < 1, and/x e NA 1 (of/x e M 1).
Ch, 56: Valuesof Garnes with Infinitely Many Players
2139
Let v be a monotonic game. For every o~ > 0, let v a denote the indicator of v ~> ~, i.e., va(S) = I ( v ( S ) >~ cO, i.e., v«(S) = 1 if v(S) ». et and 0 otherwise. Note that for every coalition S, v(S) = f ö va(S)doe. Then for every finite field re, 7rv~ = f ö ~ ( v a ) ~ d« = f ö (I) ~p(va)jr doe. Therefore if (7rk)~__l is a T-admissible sequence such that for every o~ > 0, l i m k ~ ~ O(v~)~k (T) exists, then from the Lebesgue's bounded convergence theorem it follows that limk--,ec ~pv~~(T) exists and lim ~ßvzr~(T)= fo v(1) ( l i m 7tv « (T))do~.
k-+oo
\k-+oo
3zk
Thus, i f f o r each « > 0, v « = I ( v >~~) has an asymptotic value c,ov a, then v also has an asymptotic value ~0v, which is given by f ö ~°v« (T) du = ~ov(T). The spaces A S Y M P andASYMP* are closed and each of the spaces bvWA, b v t M and bv~FA is the closed linear space that is generated by scalar measure garnes of the form f o # with f E bv ~ monotonic and # e NA 1, I~ e M ~, IX ~ FA 1 respectively. Also, each monotonic f in bv' is the sum of two monotonic functions in bv r, one right continuous and the other left continuous. If f E bv ~, with f monotonic and left continuous, then ( f o/z)* = g o #, with g 6 bv ~ monotonic and right continuous. Therefore, to show that b v W A C A S Y M P ( b v ' M C A S Y M P or bvtFA C ASYMP*), it suffices to show that f o # e A S Y M P ( o r c ASYMP*) for any monotonic and right continuous function f in bv ~ and/z ~ NA 1 ( # e M ~ or/~ 6 FA1). Note that (f o #)a(S) = I(f(#(S))
>/«) = I(Iz(S) >~inf{x: f ( x ) >~et}) = f q ( # ( S ) ) ,
where q = inf{x: f ( x ) ~> oe}. Thus, in view of the above remarks, to show that bv'NA C A S Y M P (or bv~M C ASYMP), it suffices to prove that fq o IZ ~ A S Y M P for any 0 < q < 1 and # 6 NA 1 (or/~ 6 M~), where f q ( x ) = 1 i f x ~> q and = 0 otherwise. The proofs of the relations fq o IZ e A S Y M P for 0 < q < 1 and # 6 ]VA 1 (or # e Mä or B ~ M 1) rely on delicate probabilistic results, which are of independent mathematical interest. These results can be formulated in various equivalent forms. We introduce tbem as properties of Poisson bridges. Ler X1, X2 . . . . be a sequence of i.i.d, random variables that are uniformly distributed on the open unit interval (0, 1). With any finite or infinite sequence w = (Wi)i= 1 or t/3 = (Wi)~I of positive numbers, we associate a stochastic process, Sw('), or S(.) for short, given by S(t) = Y'~4 wi[(Xi ~ t) for 0 ~< t ~< 1 (such a process is called a pure jump Poisson bridge). The proof of fq o tz e A S Y M P for # e ]VA 1 uses the following result, which is closely related to renewal theory. PROPOSITION 4 [Neyman (198la)]. For every e > 0 there exists a constant K > O, such that if Wl . . . . . wn are positive numbers with zin=l Wi = 1, and K maxn=l wi < q < 1 -- K max,_ 1 wi then I1
~~_~lwi - Prob(S(Xi) i=1
E [q,q
-~- Wi))] « «.
2140
A. Neyman
The proof of fq o IX E A S Y M P for /z ~ Ma uses the following result, due to Berbee (1981). PROPOSITION 5 [Berbee (1981)]. For every sequence (wi)~=l with wi > O, and every 0 < q < ~i°C=l tOi, the probability that there exists 0 «. t <~ 1 with S(t) = q is O, i.e., Prob(3t, S(t) = q) = O.
6. The mixing value An order on the underlying space I is a relation T¢ on I that is transitive, irreflexive, and complete. For each order 7~ and each s in I, define the initial segment I (s; Te) by I(s; Te) = {t ~ I: s ~ t } . An order 7-¢ is measurable if the cr-field generated by all the initial segments I(s; ~ ) equals C. Let ORD be the linear space of all games v in B V such that for each measurable ~ , there exists a unique measure ~o(v; ~ ) satisfying ~p(v; 7-¢)(I(s; ~ ) ) = v ( I ( s ; 7~))
for all s E I.
Let/-~ be a probability measure on the underlying space (l, C). A/~-mixing sequence is a sequence ( O 1 , 0 2 . . . . ) of/z-measure-preserving automorphisms of (I, C), such that for all S, T in C, l i m k ~ ~ # ( S A O k T ) = # ( S ) # ( T ) . For each order 7-¢ on I and automorphism O in ~ we denote by OT¢ the order on I defined by O s O T ¢ @ t ~ s ~ t . If v is absolutely continuous with respect to the measure/~ we write v « / ~ . DEFINITION 5. Let v E ORD. A garne q0v is said to be the mixing value of v if there is a measure/zv in ]VA l such that for all/~ in NA 1 with/zv « / ~ and all lz-mixing sequences ( O 1 , 0 2 . . . . ), for all measurable orders ~ , and all coalitions S, limk-~~ ~0(v; O k ~ ) ( S ) exists and = (~ov)(S). The set of all games in ORD that have a mixing value is denoted MIX. THEOREM 5 [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Theorem E]. M I X is a closed symmetric linear subspace o f B V which contains pNA, and the map ~o that associates a mixing value qov to each v is a value on M I X with Iigoll <~ 1.
7. Formulas for values Let v be a vector measure garne, i.e., a game that is a function of finitely many measures. Such games have a representation of the form v = f o/~, where/~ = (#1 . . . . . /~n) is a vector of (probability) measures, and f is a real-valued function defined on the range T¢(/~) of the vector measure iz with f ( 0 ) = 0.
Ch. 56: Valuesof Garnes with Infinitely Many Players
2141
When f is continuously differentiable, and # = (/.tl . . . . . ] ~ n ) is a vector of nonatomic measures with IZi(1) 5~ O, then v = f o/~ is in pNAec(C pNA C ASYMP) and the value (asymptotic, mixing, or the unique value on pNA) is given by Aumann and Shapley (1974, Theorem B), 1
~ov(S) = ~o(f o lz)(S) =
f0
f~(s) ( t # ( I ) ) dt
(where fù(s) is the derivative of f in the direction of/x(S)); i.e.,
B ( f o Iz)(S) =
± f01~~ [zi (S)
t ~ l (I) . . . . . tlZn (I)) dt.
i=1
The above formula expresses the value as an average of derivatives, that is, of marginal contributions. The derivatives are taken along the interval [0,/z(1)], i.e., the line segment connecting the vector 0 and the vector # ( I ) . This interval, which is contained in the range of the non-atomic vector measure #, is called the diagonal of the range of B, and the above formula is called the diagonalformula. The formula depends on the differentiability of f along the diagonal and on the game being a non-atomic vector measure game. Extensions of the diagonal formula (due to Mertens) enable one to apply (variations of) the diagonal formula to games with discontinuities and with essential nondifferentiabilities. In particular, the generalized diagonal formula defines a value of norm 1 on a closed subspace of B V that includes all finite garnes, bv'FA, the closed algebra generated by bvWA, all games generated by a finite number of algebraic and lattice operations 1 from a finite number of measures, and all market games that are functions of finitely many measures. The value is defined as a composition of positive linear symmetric mappings of norm 1. One of these mappings is an extension operator which is an operator from a space of garnes into the space of ideal games, i.e., functions that are defined on ideal coalitions, which are measurable functions from (I, C) into ([0, 1], B). The second one is a "derivative" operator, which is essentially the diagonal formula obtained by changing the order of integration and differentiation. The third one is an averaged derivative; it replaces the derivatives on this diagonal with an average of derivafives evaluated in a small invariant perturbation of the diagonal. The invariance of the perturbed distribution is with respect to all automorphisms of (I, C). First we illustrate the action and basic properties of the "derivative" and the "averaged derivative" mappings in the context of non-atomic vector measure garnes. The derivative operator [Mertens (1980)] provides a diagonal formula for the value of vector measure garnes in bv'NA; let/z = (/xt . . . . . #n) ~ (NA+) n and ler f : T¢(/z) --+ IR 1 Max and min.
A. Neyman
2142
with f ( 0 ) = 0 and f o/z in bvINA. Then f is continuous a t / z ( I ) and/z(0) = 0, and the value of f o/z is given by
q)(foß)(S)
=
lim 1 C]1-~ «~o+ e Jo [f(t#(I)
+ e ß ( S ) ) - f ( t l ~ ( I ) ) ] dt
1 j l 1-e
=
lim
e--+O+ 266
[f(tlz(I) + eß(S)) - f(t~(I)
- e/z(S))] dt.
The limits of integration in these formulas, 1 - « and e, could be replaced by 1 and 0 respectively whenever f is extended to R n in such a way that f remains continuous at /x(I) and/z(O). Let tx = (tzl . . . . . tzn) c (NA+) n be a vector of measures. Consider the class 5c(/z) of all functions f :T~(/z) --+ 1R with f(O) = O, f continuous at 0 a n d / x ( l ) , f o/z of bounded variation, and for which the limit
lim 12e f 1-e [ f ( t t z ( I ) + «tz(S)) - f ( t l Z ( 1 ) - «/z(S))] dt «--,o
exists for all S in C. Note that f ~ .T(/z) whenever f is continuously differentiable with f (0) = 0. An example of a Lipschitz function that is not in äc(/z) where/z is a vector of 2 linearly independent probability measures is f ( x l , x2) = (xl - x2) sinlog Ixl - x2[. Denote this limit by D v (S) and note that D v is a function of the measures/zl . . . . . /Zn ; i.e., D v = f o Ix for some fnnction f that is defined on the range of/z. The derivative operator D acts on all garnes of the form f o Iz, IZ ~ (NA+) n, and f ~ 5c(/z); it is a value of norm 1 on the space of all these games for whieh D ( f o tz) ~ FA. Let v = f o/z, where/z E (NA+) n and f c .T(/z). Then D ( f o IZ) is of the form f o / z , where f is linear on every plane containing the diagonal [0,/z(I)], f ( t x ( 1 ) ) = f ( t z ( I ) ) and Ilf o Iz [I ~ 11f o/z Il. There is no loss of generality in assuming that the measures B1 . . . . . /z,, are independent (i.e., that the fange of the vector measure 7~(#) is fulldimensional), and then we identify f with its unique extension to a function on IRn that is linear on every plane containing the interval [0,/z(I)]. The averaging operator expresses the value of the garne f o/x ( = D ( f o I~) for f in B(/z)) as an average, E ( ~ i =n 1 ~ • ( z ) ~ i ) , where z is an n-dimensionalrandom variable whose distribution, P~, is strictly stable of index 1 and has a Fourier transform ~ to be described below. W h e n / z l . . . . . /zn are mutually singular, z = (zl . . . . , z~) is a vector of independent "centered" Cauchy distributions, and then
()
~(y) = exp - ~ / x i (I) \
i=l
(~)
IIm II .
= exp -
i=1
Ch. 56:
Values of Games with Infinitely Many Players
2143
Otherwise, let v ~ NA + be such that #1 . . . . , ttn are absolutely continuous with respect to v; e.g., v = ~ # i . Define N u : N n --+ I~n by H
Then z is an n-dimensional random variable whose distribution has a Fourier transform ~z(Y) = e x p ( - N u ( y ) ) . Let Q be the linear space of games generated by garnes of the form v = f o # where # = (/Zl ..... tZn) ~ (NA+) n is a vector of linearly independent non-atomic measures and f 6 f ' ( # ) . The space Q is symmetric and the map ~o: Q --~ FA given by
B ( f ° B) = EPu (fl*(s)(z)) = EP" ( ~'~~ O ~xi(Z)]zi(S) fi is a value of norm 1 on Q and therefore has an extension to a value of norm 1 on the closure Q of Q. The space Q contains bvWA, the closed algebra generated by bv'NA, all garnes generated by a finite number of algebraic and lattice operations from a finite number of non-atomic measures and all garnes of the form f o t t where tt 6 (NA+) ~ and f is a continuous concave function on the range of #. To show that Epu(fr,(s)(z)) is well defined for any f in f ( t t ) , orte shows that f is Lipschitz and therefore on the one hand [f(z + 3/z(S)) - f(z)]/6 is bounded and continuous, and on the other hand, given S in C, for almost every z (with respect to the Lebesgue measure on R n) fu(s) (z) exists and is bounded (as a function of z). The distribution P# is absolutely continuous with respect to Lebesgue measure and therefore Ep~ (fr,(s)(z)) is well defined and equals limo-+0 Ep~ ( [ f ( z + ~/z(S)) - f(z)]/~) (using the Lebesgue bounded convergence theorem). To show that Ep~ (fu(s) (z)) is finitely additive in S, assume that S, T are two disjoint coalitions. For any 3 > 0, let P~ be the translation of the measure P~ by - 3 / z ( S ) , i.e.,
B ( B ) = P~(B 4- 61z(S)). Since P~ converges in norm to P~ as ~ --+ 0 (i.e.,
IIP~ -
P~ll ~~-~0
~lz(T)) - f(z)]/3 is bounded, it follows that
j~Eù~ ([/(z +
~~(s) + ~ ù ( v ) ) - ? ( z +
~~(s))]/~)
= lim E»~ ( [ f ( z + S / z ( T ) ) - f ( z ) ] / ~ ) 8--+0
tz
= l i ö Ep~ ( [ f ( z + 3 # ( T ) ) -
f(z)]/3) = Ep u (fu(T)(Z)).
0), and [f(z +
2144
A. Neyman
Therefore
Ep~ (f~(suT)(z)) = lim Epù ( [ f ( z + aß(S) + a ß ( r ) ) 3--+0 -
i(z + au(s)) + i(z + ~ù(s)) -/(z)]/a)
= E,% (f~(s)(Z)) + Epù (/~(r)(z)). We now turn to a detailed description of the mappings used in the construction of a value due to Mertens on a large space of garnes. Let B(I, C) be the space of bounded measurable real-valued functions on (I, C), and B+(I, C) = { f E B(I, C): 0 ~< f ~< 1} the space of"ideal coalitions" (measurable fuzzy sets). A function ~ on B+(I, C) is constant sum if ~ ( f ) + ~(1 - f ) = ~(1) for every f c B+(I, C). It is monotonic if for every f , g ~ B+(I, C) with f ~> g, ~ ( f ) >i O(g). It isfinitely additive if ~ ( f + g) = 0 ( f ) + ~ (g) whenever f , g 6 B + (I, C) with f + g ~< 1. It is of bounded variation if it is the difference of two monotonic functions, and the variation norm II~ IImv (or II~ [[ for short) is the supremum of the variation of 0 over all increasing sequences 0 ~< f~ ~< f2 <~ " " ~< 1 in B+(I, C). The symmetry group ~ acts on B+ (I, C) by (@, f)(s) = f (Os).
extension operator is a linear and symmetric map gr from a linear symmetric set of games to real-valued functions on B+(I, C), with (grv)(0) = 0, so that (~v)(1) = v(I), [I7~vl[mv ~< Ilvll, and 7rv is finitely additive whenever v is finitely additive, and 7rv is constant sum whenever v is constant sum. DEFINITION 6. An
It follows that an extension operator is necessarily positive (i.e., if v is monotonic so is 7rv) and that every extension operator ~ on a linear subspace Q of BV has a unique extension to an extension operator 1} on 0 (the closure of Q). One example of an extension operator is Owen's (1972) multilinear extension for finite games. For another example, consider all games that are functions of finitely many non-atomic probability measures, i.e., Q -- { f o (/z] . . . . t~n): n a positive integer,/z i E NA 1 and f : ~(IZl . . . . . #n) --+ R with f ( 0 ) = 0}, where T~(/~I . . . . . /xn) -= {(/Zl (S) . . . . . #niS)): S E C} is the range of the vector measure (#1 . . . . . lz~). Then Q is a linear and symmetric space of garnes. An extension operator on Q is defined as follows: for /z = (/~1 . . . . . /zn) 6 (NAl) '~ and g ~ B+(I, C), let ¢z(g) = (fl gd/Zl . . . . . fl gd#n) and define ~ ( f o Iz)(g) ----f(Iz(g)). Then it is easy to verify that t/r is well defined, linear, and symmetric, that 7rv(1) = v(1), 7tv is finitely additive whenever v is, and 7rv is constant sum whenever v is. The inequality [I7rv]llBv <~ Ilvll follows from the result of Dvoretsky, Wald, and Wolfowitz [(1951), p. 66, Theorem 4], which asserts that for every /~ c (NAI) n and every sequence 0 ~< fl ~< f2 ~< " " ~< fk ~< 1 in B+(I,C), there exists a sequence 0 C $1 C $2 C ... C Sk C I with lz(f,) = tz(Si). This extension operator satisfies additional properties: ( 7rv)( S) = v( S), ~ß( vu) = ( ~v)( 7ru), O ( f o v) = f o ~ v whenever f : I R ~ IR with f ( 0 ) = 0, !/r(v /x u) = 0Bv) A (Ou) and 7r(v v u) ----(1/rv) v 0Bu). The NA-topology on B(I, C) is the minimal topology
Ch. 56." Values of Garnes with Infinitely Many Players
2145
for which the functions f ~ # ( f ) are continuous for e a c h / z c NA. For every game v ~ pNA, ~ v is NA-continuous. Moreover, as the characteristic functions Is c Bi+ (I, C), S c C, are NA-dense in B 1 (I, C), ~pv is the unique NA-continuous function on B I (I, C) with 7tv(S) -----v(S). Similarly, for every garne v in pNA' - the closure in the supremum norm o f p N A - there is a unique function ~ : B i ( I , C) -+ R which is NA-continuous and O(S) = v(S). Moreover, the map v ~ O is an extension operator on pNA I and it satisfies: ~ ü = Fü, ~ A u = v A u and F v ü = v v u for all v, u ~ p N A r and ( f o v) = f o F whenever f : R - + l~ is continuous with f ( 0 ) = 0. Another example is the following natural extension map defined on bv~M. Assume that # ~ M 1 with a set of atoms A = A ( # ) . Let v = f o/z with f ~ bv ~ a n d / z 6 NA 1. For g c Bl_(I, C) define ~ßv(g) = E ( f ( I z ( g A c + Y~~aeA Xaa))) where A c = I \ A and (Xa)a~A are independent {0, 1}-valued random variables with E(Xa) = g(a). If v = ~ k i = 1 l)i, Vi = f i o ]d,i w i t h / z i @ M 1 and fi E bv ~ we define Ov(g) = ~ ~ ~ ~i(g). It is possible to show that Il7tv IIzBv ~< IIv Il and thus in particular F is well defined (i.e., it is independent o f the representation of v) and can be extended to the closure of all these finite sums, i.e., it defines an extension map on bv~M. The space bv~NA is a subset of both bvIM and Q and the above two extensions that were defined on Q and on bvIM coincide on bv~NA, and thus induce (by restriction) an extension operator ~ß on bv~NA and on pNA. The extension on bv~NA can be used to provide formulas for the values on bv'NA and on pNA. Given v in Q, we denote by ~ the extension (ideal garne) t} v. We also identify S with the indicator of the set S, Xs, and the scalar t also stands for the constant function in B+(I, C) with value t. Then, if v ~ pNA, for almost all 0 < t < 1, for every coalition S, the derivative OF(t, S) = : lims-~0[F(t) + Ss) - F(t)]/6 exists [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Proposition 24.1] and the value of the garne is given by 1
~ov(S) =
f0
OF(t, S) dt.
For any garne v in bvINA, the value of v is given by
Bv(S) ---- lim
8--+0+
il0'8
= lim 1
[~(t + 3S) - #(t)] dt
/l-181[F(t + 8s) -
F(t - 8 s ) ] dt.
8-+0ëg JL81
More generally, given an extension operator ~ß on a linear symmetric space of garnes Q, we extend ~ = Ov, for v in Q, to be defined on all of B(I, C) by ~ ( f ) = O(max[0, m i n ( l , f ) ] ) (and then we can replace the limits 18[ and 1 - [81 in the above integrals with 0 and 1 respectively, and define the derivative operator grD by BDÜ(X)
~~- lim f l
~-~o Jo
F(t + S X ) - f~(t - 8X) ~ dt
A. Neyman
2146
whenever the integral and the limit exists for all X in B(I, C). The integral exists whenever ~ has bounded variation. The derivative operator is positive, linear and symmetric. Assuming continuity in the NA-topology of ~ at 1 and 0, ~D also satisfies ~PoO(ol + fiX) = ~~3(1) + fi[gtDf~](X) for every « , fl c IR, so that ~PDV is linear on every plan in B(I, C) containing the constants and gtD is efficient, i.e., O D ' ( l ) = ~(1). The following [due to Mertens (1988a)] will (essentially) extend the previously mentioned extension operators to a large class of garnes that includes bvIFA and all games of the form f o / z where # = (/Zl . . . . , #n) 6 NA. Intuitively we would like to define ~PEv(f) for f in B~(I, C) as the "limit" of the expectation v(S) with respect to a distribution P of a random set that is very similar to the ideal set f . Let 5t- be the set of all triplets ~ = (st, v, e) where 7r is a finite subfield of C, v is a finite set of non-atomic elements of FA and « > 0.5 c is ordered by ot = (re, v, e) ~< c¢/ = (7d, v ~, e r) if 7r~ D 7r, v ~ D v and e I ~ c. (.T, ~<) is filtering-increasing with respect to this order, i.e., given ol = (fr, v, e) and «~ = ( S , v ~, e ~) in ~c there is « " = (zd r, v", e") with « " >~ c¢ and c# >~ c~~. For any « = (zr, v, e) in )c and f in B+(I, C), Pc~,f is the set of all probabilities P with finite support on C such that I ~ s e c SP(S) - fl -~ ]Ep(S) - f ] < e uniformly on I (i.e., for every t 6 I , [ ~ s c c P ( S ) I ( t ~ S) - f ( t ) [ < e), and such that for any Tl, T2 in 7r with 7"1 M 7"2 = 0, T1 M S is independent of T2 M S, and for all # in vlz(S N TD = fT~ f d/z. That P « , f 7~ 0 follows from Lyapunov's convexity theorem on the range of a vector of non-atomic elements of FA. For any garne v, and any f E B+(I, C), let ~(f)
= lim
sup
Ep(v(S))-- lim
°lc'F PeP«'f
sup
~_v(S)P(S)
°t~ff'PePee,f SeC
and v_(f) = lim
inf
ctc~" PEP«,f
Ep(v(S)).
The definition of ~ is extended to all of B(I, C) by ~ ( f ) = ~(max(0, m i n ( l , f ) ) ) . Note that if v is a garne with finite support, then for any f in B+(I, C), fJ(f) = v_(f) coincides with Owen's multilinear extension, i.e., letting T be the finite support of v,
S c T sES
seT\S
and whenever v is a function of finitely many non-atomic elements of FA, Vl, ..., Vn, i.e., v = g o (Vl . . . . . vn) where g is a real-valued function defined on the range of (Vl . . . . . Vn), then for any f c B+ (I, C)
Ch. 56:
Valuesof Games with Infin#ely Many Players
2147
Let Ve = {X ~ B+(I,C): s u p x - i n f x ~< e}. Let D be the space of all games v in BV for which ~ sup{v(x) - v(X): X ~ Ve} --+ 0 as « ~ 0 + . Obviously, D D De where De is the set of all garnes v for which v ( x ) = _v(x) for any X ~ Ve. Next we define the derivative operators q)D ; its domain is the set of all garnes v in D for which the integrals (for sufficiently small e > 0) and the limit
[~ODV](X) = lim [ ~ ~(t + r x ) - - ~ ( t - - r X ) r~0J0
2r
dt
exist for every x in B(I, •). The integrals always exist for games in BV. The limit, on the other hand, may not exist even for garnes that are Lipschitz functions of a non-atomic signed measure. However, the limit exists for many garnes of interest, including the concave functions of finitely many non-atomic measures, and the algebra generated by bv'FA. Assuming, in addition, some continuity assumption on ~ at 1 and 0 (e.g., ~ ( f ) - + ~(1) as i n f ( f ) - + 1 and ~ ( f ) ~ ~(0) as s u p ( f ) ~ 0) we obtain that ~ODV obeys the following additional properties: ~ODv(X) + q)DV(1 -- X) = V(1) whenever v is a constant sum; [~ODv](a + bx) = a v ( 1 ) + b[~oDv](x) for every a, b c 1R. THEOREM 6 [Mertens (1988a), Section 1]. Let Q = {v ~ Dom~oD: ~ODV~ FA}. Then
Q is a closed symmetric space that contains DIFb, DIAG and bv'FA and q)D : Q -+ FA is a value on Q. For every function w : B(I, C) ~ R in the range of ~0D, and every two elements X, h in B(I, C), we define Wh (X) to be the (two-sided) directional derivative of w at X in the direction h, i.e.,
Wh(X) = lim [ w ( x + 6h) - w ( x - 8h)]/(28) 8-+0 L
whenever the limit exists. Obviously, when w is finitely additive then wh (X) = w(h). For a function w in the range of ~OD and of the form w = f o/z where # = (#1 . . . . . #n) is a vector of measures in )VA, f is Lipschitz, satisfying f (alz(I) + bx) = a f ( # ( 1 ) ) + b f ( x ) and for every y in L ( ~ ( / z ) ) - the linear span of the range of the vector measure /x - for almost every x in L(T~(/z)) the directional derivative of f at x in the direction y, fy (x) exists, and then obviously wh ()~) = f u (h) (Iz (X)). The following theorem will provide an existence of a value on a large space of games as well as a formula for the value as an average of the derivatives (~ODo ~vÆv)h(X) = Wh (X) where X is distributed according to a cylinder probability measure on B(I, C) which is invariant under all automorphisms of (I, C). We recall now the concept of a cylinder measure on B(I, C). The algebra of cylinder sets in B(I, C) is the algebra generated by the sets of the firm/z -1 (B) where B is any Borel subset of IRn and # = (/x~ . . . . . /zn) is any vector of measures. A cylinder probability is a finitely additive probability P on the algebra of
2148
A. Neyman
cylinder sets such that for every vector measure # = (/zl . . . . . /zn), P o # - ~ is a countably additive probability measure on the Borel subsets of R n. A n y cylinder probability P on B(I, C) is uniquely characterized by its Fourier transform, a function on the dual that is defined by F(/x) = ER (exp(i/z(X)). Let P be the cylinder probability measure on B(I, C) whose Fourier transform F p is given by Fe (/z) = exp(-Illzll). This cylinder measure is invariant under all automorphisms of (I, C). Recall that (I, C) is isomorphic to [0, 1] with the Borel sets, and for a vector of measures # = (/zl . . . . . #n), the Fourier transform of P o iz -1 , Feo~_~ is given by Feo~_~ (y) = e x p ( - N # ( y ) ) , and P o / ~ - l is absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure, with moreover, continuous R a d o n - N i k o d y m derivatives. Let QM be the closed symmetric space generated by all garnes v in the domain of q)D such that either ~ODV ~ FA, or q)o (v) is a function of finitely many non-atomic measures. THEOREM 7 [Mertens (1988a), Section 2]. Let v ~ QM. Then for every h in B(I, C),
(qOD(V))h(X) exists for P almost every )~ and is P integrable in X, and the mapping of each garne v in QM to the garne ~ov given by
is a value of norm 1 on QM. REMARKS. The extreme points of the set of invariant cylinder probabilities on B(I, C) have a Fourier transform Fm,« (/x) = exp(im/z(1) - cr Illzll) where m ~ R, ~r >~ 0. More precisely, there is a one-to-one and onto map between countably additive measures Q on II{ x R + and invariant cylinder measures on B(I, C) where every measure Q on N x IR+ is associated with the cylinder measure whose Fourier transform is given by f
FQ (tz) = I Fm,c, (IZ) dQ(m, a). JR ×R+ The associated cylinder measure is nondegenerate if Q (r = 0) = 0, and in the above value formula and theorem, P can be replaced with any invariant nondegenerate cylinder measure of total mass 1 on B(I, C). Neyman (2001) provides an alternative approach to define a value on the closed space spanned by all bounded variation garnes of the form f o/z w h e r e / z is a vector of nonatomic probability measures and f is continuous at /z(0) and /z(I), and QM. This alternative approach sterns from the ideas in Mertens (1988a) and expresses the value as a limit of averaged marginal contributions where the average is with respect to a distribution which is strictly stable of index 1. For any IRn-valued non-atomic vector measure/~ we define a map q)~ from Q(/z) the space of all garnes of bounded variation thät are functions of the vector measure # and are continuous a t / z ( 0 ) and a t / z ( I ) - to BV. The map q)~ depends on a small positive constant 3 > 0 and the vector measure/z = (/zl . . . . . /zn).
Ch. 56." Valuesof Games withlnfinitely Many Players
2149
For 6 > 0 let la (t) = I (33 ~< t < 1 - 33) where I stands for the indicator function. The essential role of the function la is to make the integrands that appear in the integrals used in the definition of the value well defined. Let/z = (it1 . . . . . #n) be a vector of non-atomic probability measures and f : ~ ( # ) --+ IR be continuous at it(0) and i t ( I ) and with f o It of bounded variation. It follows that for every x c 2T¢(#) - it(I), S E C, and t with la(t) = 1, tlt(1) + 3x and t # ( I ) + 3x + &x(S) are in 7~(#) and therefore the functions t ~+ la(t) f (t#(I) + 3x) and t ~ la(t)f(ttx(1) + 6x + alt(S)) are of bounded variation on [0, 1] and thus in particular they are integrable functions. Therefore, given a garne f o / , ~ Q(#), the function Ff,~, defined on all triples (3, x, S) with a > 0 sufficiently small (e.g., a < 1/9), x ~ ]Rn with ax E 2Te(it) - it(I), and S E C by
Fe:#(3,x, S) = fo 1 Ia(t)
f (ttz(I) + 32x -4- 33it(S)) - f (tlt(1) + a2x) 33
dt,
is weil defined. Let P~ be the restriction of Pu to the set of all points in {x c IRn: 3x c 2T¢(#) #(I)}. The function x ~-> FU,#(& x, S) is continuous and bounded and therefore the function qga~defined on Q(lt) x C by
~~
~pu f o B, S)
=f~F(~) Ff, u ( & x , S) dP~(x),
where AF(lt) stands for the affine space spanned by ~ ( l t ) , is well defined. The linear space of games Q ( # ) is not a symmetric space. Moreover, the map ~0u violates all value axioms. It does not map Q (it) into FA, it is not efficient, and it is not symmetric. In addition, given two non-atomic vector measures, It and v, the operators ~0a~and q)~ differ on the intersection Q(/z) M Q(v). However, it turns out that the violation of the value axioms by ~o/~ a diminishes as 3 goes to 0, and the difference q)~ ( f o #) - ~0~(g o v) goes to 0 as 3 --+ 0 whenever f o It = g o v. Therefore, an appropriate limiting argument enables us to generate a value on the union of all the spaces Q (it). Consider the partially ordered linear space £ of all bounded functions defined on the open interval (0, 1/9) with the partial order h >- g if and only if h(3) ~> g(3) for all sufficiently small values of 6 > 0. Let L : £ --+ 1R be a monotonic (i.e., L(h) >~ L(g) whenever h >- g) linear functional with L(1) = 1. Let Q denote the union of all spaces Q (it) where It ranges over all vectors of finitely many non-atomic probability measures. Define the map ~0 : Q ~ R c by ~ov(S) = L(~o~(v, S)) whenever v E Q(#). It turns out that ~0 is well defined, ~0v is in FA (whenever v ~ Q) and ~o is a value of norm 1 on Q. As ~0 is a value of norm 1 on Q and the continuous extension of any value of norm 1 defines a value (of norm 1) on the closure, we have: PROPOSITION 6. ~0 is a value of norm 1 on Q.
2150
A. Neyman
8. Uniqueness of the value of nondifferentiable garnes The symmetry axiom of a value implies [see, e.g., Aumann and Shapley (1974), p. 139] that if/z = (/zl . . . . . tzn) is a vector of mutually singular measures in NA 1, f : [0, 1] ~ --~ IR, and v -----f o/z is a garne which is a member of a space Q on which a value q) is defined, then n
Bv = ~ _ a i ( f ) l z i . i=1 n a i ( f ) = f ( 1 . . . . . 1), and if in addition f is The efficiency of ~o implies that Y~.i=l symmetric in the n coordinates all the coefficients ai ( f ) are the same, i.e., ai ( f ) = ¼f(1 . . . . . 1). The results below will specify spaces of garnes that are generated by vector measure garnes v = f o/z where # is a vector of mutually singular non-atomic probability measures and f : [0, 1] n ~ IR and on which a unique value exists. Denote by )~rk+ the linear space of function on [0, 1] ~ spanned by all concave Lipschitz functions f : [0, 1] ~ --+ R with f ( 0 ) = 0 and f y ( x ) «. f s ( t x ) whenever x is in the interior of [0, 1]k, y 6 R~+ and 0 < t ~ 1. M~ is the linear space of all continuous piecewise linear functions f on [0, 1] k with f ( 0 ) = 0. DEFINITION 7 [Haimanko (2000d)]. CONs (respectively, LINs) is the linear span of games of the form f o / z where for some positive integer k, f 6 ~r~_ (respectively, f c/~¢k+) and/z = (#1 . . . . . /Zk) is a vector of mutually singular measures in NA 1. The spaces CONs and LINs are in the domain of the Mertens value; therefore there is a value on CONs and on LINs. If f 6 ~k+ or f 6 )~r~, the directional derivative fy (x) exists whenever x is in the interior of [0, 1] k and y E N k, and for each fixed x, the directional derivative of the function y w-~ fy (x) in the direction z 6 IRk, lim fy+«z(X) - fy(X) e--+O+ 8 exists and is denoted Of(x; y; z). I f / z = (/zl . . . . . #~) is a vector of mutually singular measures in NA 1 and 9M is the Mertens value,
~oM(f o I~)(S) = fO 1 Of(tlk; X; Iz(S)) dt where 1~ = (1 . . . . . 1) 6 IR~ and X = (X~ . . . . . Xk) is a vector of independent random variables, each with the standard Cauchy distribution. THEOREM 8 [Haimanko (2000d) and (2001b)]. The Mertens value is the unique value on CONs and on LINs.
Ch. 56: Valuesof Garneswith Infinitely Many Players
2151
9. Desired properties of values The short list of conditions that define the value, linearity, positivity, symmetry and efficiency, suffices to determine the value on many spaces of garnes, like p N A ~ , pNA and bv~NA. Values were defined in other cases by means of constructive approaches. All these values satisfy many additional desirable properties like continuity, the projection axiom, i.e., ~0v = v whenever v c FA is in the domain of q~, the dummy axiom, i.e., ~ov(S c) = 0 whenever S is a carrier of v, and stronger versions of positivity.
9.1. Strong positivity One of the stronger versions of positivity is called strong positivity: Let Q c BV. A map ~o: Q -+ FA is strongly positive if ~ov(S) >~~ow(S) whenever v, w ~ Q and v(T U S ~) v(T) >1 w ( T U S ~) - w ( T ) for all S ~ ___S and T in C. It turns out that strong positivity can replace positivity and linearity in the characterization of the value on spaces of "smooth" garnes. THEOREM 9 [Monderer and Neyman (1988), Theorems 8 and 5]. (a) Any symmetric, efficient, strongly positive map from pNAec to FA is the AumannShapley value. (b) Any symmetric, efficient, strongly positive and continuous map from pNA to FA is the Aumann-Shapley value.
9.2. The partition value Given a value q) on a space Q, it is of interest to specify whether it could be interpreted as a limiting value. This leads to the definition of a partition value. A value q9 on a space Q is a partition value [Neyman and Tauman (1979)] if for every coalition S there exists a T-admissible sequence (zrk)k=l~ such that q)v(T) = limk-+ec ~v~~ (T). It follows that any partition value is continuous (with norm ~< 1) and coincides with the asymptotic value on all garnes that have an asymptofic value [Neyman and Tanman (1979)]. There are however spaces of games that include ASYMP and on which a partition value exists. Given two sets of garnes, Q and R, we denote by Q * R the closed linear and symmetric space generated by all garnes of the form uv where u ~ Q and v ~ R. THEOREM 10 [Neyman and Tauman (1979)]. There exists a partition value on the closed linear space spanned by ASYMP, bvINA • bvINA and A * bv~NA * bvZNA.
9.3. The diagonal property A remarkable implication of the diagonal formula is that the value of a vector measure garne f o IZ inpNA or in bv~NA is completely determined by the behavior of f near the
A. Neyman
2152
diagonal of the range of/z. We proceed to define a diagonal value as a value that depends only on the behavior of the game in a diagonal neighborhood. Formally, given a vector of non-atomic probability measures # = (/xl . . . . . /zn) and « > 0, the « - # diagonal neighborhood, 7?(/z, «), is defined as the set of all coalitions S with [Lti (S) - / ~ j (S) I < for all 1 ~< i, j ~< n. A map q) from a set Q of garnes is diagonal if for every e - / x diagonal neighborhood D(/x, e) and every two games v, w in Q N BV that coincide on D(/z, e) (i.e., v(S) = w(S) for any S in ©(/z, e)), ~0v = ~0w. There are examples of non-diagonal values [Neyman and Tauman (1976)] even on reproducing spaces [Tauman (1977)]. However, THEOREM 1 1 [Neyman (1977a)]. Any continuous value (in the variation norm) is diagonal. Thus, in particular, the values on (pNA and) bv'NA [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Proposition 43.1], the weak asymptotic value, the asymptotic value [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Proposition 43.11], the mixing value [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Proposition 43.2], any partition value [Neyman and Tauman (1979)] and any value on a closed reproducing space, are all diagonal. Let DIAG denote the linear subspace of BV that is generated by the garnes that vanish on some diagonal neighborhood. Then DIAG C ASYMP and any continuous (and in particular any asymptotic or partition) value vanishes on DIAG.
10. Semivalues Semivalues are generalizations and/or analogies of the Shapley value that do not (necessarily) obey the efficiency, or Pareto optimality, property. This has stemmed partly from the search for value function that describes the prospects of playing different roles in a garne. DEFINITION 8 [Dubey, Neyman and Weber (1981)]. A semivalue on a linear and symmetric space of games Q is a linear, symmetric and positive map ~ : Q -+ FA that satisfies the projection axiom (i.e., ~ v = v for every v in Q o FA). The following result characterizes all semivalues on the space FG of all games having a finite support. THEOREM 12 [Dubey, Neyman and Weber (1981), Theorem 1]. (a) For each probability measure ~ on [0, 1], the map gr~ that is given by
~r«v(S) = fo 1 3v(t, S) d~(t),
Ch. 56." Valuesof Garneswith lnfinitely Many Players
2153
where ~ is Owen's multilinear extension o f the game v, defines a semivalue on FG. Moreover, every semivalue on FG is o f this f o r m and the mapping ~ --+ gr~ is 1-1. (b) ~ß~ is continuous (in the variation norm) on G if and only if ~ is absolutely continuous w.r.t, the Lebesgue measure ~ on [0, 1] and d~/dX c Loo[0, 1]. In that case, [1~~IIBv = IId~/d)~llcc. Let W be the subset of all elements g in Loo[0, 1] such that fo1 g(t) dt = 1. THEOREM 13 [Dubey, Neyman and Weber 1981), Theorem 2]. For every g in W, the map ~ßg :pNA ~ FA deßned by 7:gv(S) =
O~(t, S ) g ( t ) d t
is a semivalue on pNA. Moreover, every semivalue on pNA is o f this form and the map g --+ ~ßg maps W onto thefamily ofsemivalues on pNA and is a linear isometry. Let Wc be the subset of all elements g in W which are (represented by) continuous functions on [0, 1]. We identify W (Wc) with the set of all probability measures ~ on [0, 1] which are absolutely continuous w.r.t, the Lebesgue measure X on [0, 1], and their R a d o n - N i k o d y m derivative d~/dX c W (~ Wc). DEFINITION 9. Let v be a game and let ~ be a probability measure on [0, 1]. A garne q)v is said to be the weak asymptotic ~-semivalue of v if, for every S E C and every æ > 0, there is a finite subfield zr of C with S 6 Jr such that for any finite subfield zr: with fr: D 7r, I7:~v.,(s)
-
~0v(s)[ < «.
REMARKS. (1) A garne v has a weak asymptotic ~-semivalue if and only il, for every S in C and every e > 0, there is a finite subfield rr of C with S 6 rc such that for any subfield re' with 7r: D 7r, I~~vTr'(S) - ~ß~v~r(S)[ < e. (2) A garne v has at most one weak asymptotic ~-semivalue. (3) The weak asymptotic ~-semivalue 99v of a garne v is a finitely additive garne and Ikovll ~< [[vll IId~/d)~rr~ whenever ~ ~ W. Let ~ be a probability measure on [0, 1]. The set of all garnes of bounded variation and having a weak asymptotic ~-semivalue is denoted ASYMP* (~). THEOREM 14. Let ~ be a probability measure on [0, 1]. (a) The set o f all games having a weak asymptotic ~-semivalue is a linear symmetric space o f garnes and the operator that maps each garne to its weak asymptotic -semivalue is a semivalue on that space.
A. Neyman
2154
(b) ASYMP*(~) is closed ~ ~ c W ~=~pFA C ASYMP*(~) ~=~pNA C ASYMP*(~). (c) ~ 6 Wc ~ bv'NA C bv'FA c ASYMP*(~). The asymptotic ~-semivalue of a garne v is defined whenever all the sequences of the -semivalues of finite garnes that "approximate" v have the same limit. DEFINITION 10. Let ~ be a probability measure on [0, 1]. A game ~ov is said to be the asymptotic ~-semivalue of v if, for every T 6 C and every T-admissible sequence (7r i)i=l, ~ the following limit and equality exists: lim ~«v~k(T ) = ~ov(T).
]¢--+cx~
REMARKS. (1) A game v has au asymptotic ~-semivalue if and only if for every S in C and every S-admissible sequence 72 = (7ri)~l the limit, limk-+oc ~k~vm (S), exists and is independent of the choice of 72. (2) For any given v, the asymptotic ~-semivalue, if it exists, is clearly unique. (3) The asymptotic ~-semivalue q)v of a game v is finitely additive and [l~0vlIBv ~< ][v]LBvlld~/d,~ll~ (when ~ ~ W). (4) If v has an asymptotic ~-semivalue ~ov, then v has a weak asymptofic ~-semivalue
(= ~ov). The space of all games of bounded variation that have an asymptotic ~-semivalue is denoted ASYMP(~ ). THEOREM 15. (a) [Dubey (1980)]. pNA~ C ASYMP(~) and if ~ov denotes the asymptotic ~semivalue of v ~ pNAoc, then ]]cpv[[~ ~< 2[Ivl[~. (b) pNA C p M C ASYMP(~) whenever ~ E W. (c) bv'NA C bv'M C ASYMP(~) whenever ~ c Wc.
11. Partially symmetric values Non-symmetric values (quasivalues) and partially symmetric values are generalizations and/or analogies of the Shapley value that do not necessarily obey the symmetry axiom. A (symmetric) value is covariant with respect to all automorphisms of the space of players. A partially symmetric value is covariant with respect to a specified subgroup of automorphisms. Of particular importance are the trivial group, the subgroups that preserve a finite (or countable) partition of the set of players and the subgroups that preserve a fixed population measure. The group of all automorphisms that preserve a measurable partition/7, i.e., all automorphisms 0 such that OS = S for any S 6 / 7 , is denoted G(/7). Similarly, if 17 is a a-algebra of coalitions (/7 C C) we denote by Œ(/7) the set of all automorphisms 0
Ch. 56." Valuesof Garnes with lnfinitely Many Players
2155
such that OS = S for any S E / 7 . The group of automorphisms that preserve a fixed m e a s u r e / z on the space of players is denoted ~(/z).
11.1. Non-symmetric and partially symmetric values DEFINITION 1 1. Let Q be a linear space of garnes. A non-symmetric value (quasivalue) on Q is a linear, efficient and positive map ~k : Q --+ FA that satisfies the projection axiom. Given a subgroup o f automorphisms 7-/, an 7-[-symmetric value on Q is a non-symmetric value ~ß on Q such that for every 0 E ~ and v E Q, ~(O,v) = O,(~v). Given a a - a l g e b r a / 7 , a 17-symmetric value on Q is a G(/7)-symmetric value. Given a m e a s u r e / z on the space of players, a #-value is a 9 ( # ) - s y m m e t r i c value.
A coalition structure is a measurable, finite or countable, partition /7 of I such thät every atom o f / 7 is an infinite set. The results below characterize all the G(/7)symmetric values, w h e r e / 7 is a fixed coalition structure, on finite games and on smooth garnes with a confinuum of players. The charactefizafions employ path values which are defined by means of monotonic increasing paths in B + (I, C). A path is a monotonic function • : [0, 1] - + B I ( I , C) such that for each s E I, y(O)(s) = 0, •(1)(s) = 1, and the function t ~ V (t)(s) is continuous at 0 and 1. A path • is called continuous if for every fixed s E I the function t w-> y ( t ) ( s ) is continuous; NA-continuous if for every IZ E )VA the function t ~ / z ( V ( t ) ) is confinuous; and Fl-symmetric ( w h e r e / 7 is a partition of I ) if for every 0 ~< t ~< 1, the funcfion s ~ V(t)(s) is / / - m e a s u r a b l e . Given an extension operator ~ on a linear space o f garnes Q (for v E Q we use the notafion = gtv) and a päth V, the •-path extension of v, ~×, is defined [Haimanko (2000c)] by vz(f) =v(Y*(f)) where y* : B~_ (l, C) -+ B~+(I, C) is defined by v * ( f ) ( s ) = v ( f (s) )(s). For a coalition S E C and v ~ Q, define
9)×(v)(S) : ~« 1
fl-~
[Oz ( t I + e S ) - v z ( t l ) ] d t
and DIFF(•) is defined as the set of all v E Q such that for every S E C the linfit q)z (v)(S) = lime--,0+ ~@ (v)(S) exists and the game q)z (v) is in FA. PROPOSITION 7 [Haimanko (2000c)]. D I F F ( v ) is a closed linear subspace of Q and
the map q)z is a non-symmetric value on D I F F ( y ) . l f Fl is a measurable partition (or a a-algebra) and • is Fl-symmetric then q)z is a Fl-symmetric value. In what follows we assume that Q = bv1NA with the natural extension operator and /7 is a fixed coalition structure.
A. Neyman
2156
THEOREM 16 [Haimanko (2000c)]. (a) y is NA-continuous et, pNA C DIFF(y). (b) Every non-symmetric value on pNA()~), )~ e NA 1, is a mixture of path values. (c) Every 17-symmetric value (where 17 is a coalition structure) on pNA (on FG) is a mixture of 17-symmetric path values. REMARKS [Haimanko (2000c)]. (1) There are non-symmetric values on pNA which al"e not mixtures of path values. (2) Every linear and efficient map 7r :pNA -+ FA which is 17-symmetric with respect to a coalition structure 17 obeys the projection axiom. Therefore, the projection axiom of a non-symmetric value is not used in (c) of Theorem 16. The above characterization of all H-symmetric values on pNA()O as mixtures of path values relies on the non-atomicity of the garnes in pNA. A more delicate construction, to be described below, leads to the characterization of all 17-symmetrie values on pM. For every game v in bv'M there is a measure ~. • M l such that v e bv~M()O. The set of atoms of ;~ is denoted by A()0. Given two paths Y, Y~, define for v • bv~M()O, f • B~_(I, C) ~Sy,y,(f) = ~y,, where y ~~= y [ l - A0~)] + y ' [ A 0 0 ] and v --+ ~ is the natural extension on bv'M. It can be verified that ~y,y, is well defined on bv'M, i.e., the definition is independent of the measure )~. For a coalition S • C and v • bv'M, define
'
s
[vx'y'(tl + eS)
~y,y,(tl)]dt.
We associate with bv~M and the pair of paths Y and y ~the set DIFF(y, Y') of all garnes v e bvrM such that for every S 6 C the limit 9y,y' (v)(S) = limos0+ 9~, (v)(S) exists and the garne 9y,v,(v) is in FA. THEOREM 17 [Haimanko (2000c)]. (a) DIFF(y, Y') is a closed linear subspace of bv~M and the map 9y,y' : DIFF(y, y ) --+ FA is a non-symmetric value. (b) Given a measurable partition (or a er-algebra) 17, 9y, y' is 17-symmetrie whenever s ~ y(t)(s) and s ~ y'(t)(s) are 17 measurablefor every t. (c) If17 is a coalition structure, any 17-symmetric value on pM is a mixture of maps 9y,×' where the paths Y and y ~are continuous and 17-symmetric. REMARKS [Haimanko (2000c)]. (1) If Y is NA-continuous and the discontinuities of the functions t ~+ y'(t)(s), s • I, are mutually disjoint, p M C DIFF(y, yt). In particular if y and yt are continuous, p M C DIFF(y, y~) and therefore if in addition y (t) and y~(t) are constant functions for each fixed t, y and yr are G-symmetric and thus q)y,v'
Ch. 56: Valuesof Garnes with lnfinitely Many Players
2157
defines a value of norm 1 on pM. These infinitely many values on p M were discovered by Hart (1973) and are called the Hart values. (2) A surprising outcome of this systematic smdy is the characterization of all values on p M . Any value on p M is a mixture of the Hart values. (3) If /7 is a coalition structure, any F/-symmetric linear and efficient map ge : bv1M --+ FA obeys the projection axiom. Therefore, the projection axiom of a nonsymmetric value is not used in the characterization (c) of Theorem 17. Weighted values are non-symmetric values of the form q)y where F is a path described by means of a measurable weight function w : I -+ IR++ (which is bounded away from 0): for every y ( s ) ( t ) = t w(s). Hart and Monderer (1997) have successfully applied the potential approach of Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) to weighted values of smooth (continuously differentiable) games: to every game v c p N A ~ the garne
fg ~
( Pwv)(S) = dt is in p N A ~ and ~oyv( S) = ( Æwv)ws(1). In addition they define an asymptotic w-weighted value and prove that every garne in p N A ~ has an asymptotic w-weighted value. Another important subgroup of automorphisms is the one that preserves a fixed (population) non-atornic measure #. 11.2. Measure-based values Measure-based values are generalizations and/or analogues of the value that take into account the coalition worth function and a fixed (population) measure #. This has stemmed partly from applications of value theory to economic models in which a given population measure/x is part of the models. Ler/z be a fixed non-atomic measure on (I, C). A subset of games, Q, is #-symmetric if for every O c 9(#) (the group of/z-measure-preserving automorphisms), O, Q = Q. A map ~o from a/z-symmetric set of games Q into a space of garnes is/z-symmetric if B O , v = O, qJv for every (9, in ~(#) and every garne v in Q. DEFINITION 12. Let Q be a/z-symmetric space of garnes. A Iz-value on Q is a map from Q into finitely additive garnes that is linear, #-symmetric, positive, efficient, and obeys the dummy axiom (i.e., q)v(S) = 0 whenever the complement of S, S c, is a carrier of v). REMARKS. The defnition of a/x-value differs from the definition of a value in two aspects. First, there is a weakening of the symmetry axiom. A value is required to be covariant with the actions of all automorphisms, while a #-value is required to be covariant only with the actions of the/z-measure-preserving automorphism. Second, there is an additional axiom in the definition of a/z-value, the dummy axiom. In view of the other axioms (that q)v is finitely additive and efficiency), this additional axiom could be viewed as a strengthening of the efficiency axiom; the/z-value is required to obey ~ov(S) = v(S) for any carrier S of the garne v, while the efficiency axiom requires it
A. Neyman
2158
only for the carrier S = I. In many cases of interest, the dummy axiom follows from the other axioms of the value [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Note 4, p. 18]. Obviously, the value on pNA obeys the dummy axiom and the restriction of any value that obeys the dummy axiom to a #-symmetric subspace is a/x-value. In particular, the restriction of the unique value on pNA to pNA(I~), the closed (in the bounded variation norm) algebra generated by non-atomic probability measures that are absolutely continuous with respect to #, is a/~-value. It turns out to be the unique/x-value on pNA(Iz). THEOREM 18 [Monderer (1986), Theorem A]. There exists a unique tx-value on pNA(tz); it is the restriction to pNA(Ix ) of the unique value on pNA. REMARKS. In the above characterization, the dummy axiom could be replaced by the projection axiom [Monderer (1986), Theorem D]: there exists a unique linear, #symmetric, positive and efficient map ~0:pNA(#) --~ FA that obeys the projection axiom; it is the unique value on pNA (/z). The characterizations of the/~-value on pNA(/x) is derived from Monderer [(1986), Main Theorem], which characterizes all/z-symmetric, continuous linear maps from pNA (/z) into FA. Similar to the constructive approaches to the value, one can develop corresponding constructive approaches to/z-values. We start with the asymptotic approach. Given T in C with # ( T ) > 0, a t~-T-admissible sequence is a T-admissible sequence (:r~, :ra . . . . ) for which limk__+~(min{#(A): A is an atom of rrk}/max{#(A): A is an atom of 7rk}) ----1. DEFINITION 13. A garne ~ov is said to be the tz-asymptotic value of v if, for every T in c~ , the following limit and C with/z(T) > 0 and every/~-T-admissible sequence (7( i)i~_l equality exists lim ~ v ~ k (T) =
~ov(T),
k-->-oc
REMARKS. (1) A game v has a tx-asymptotic value if and only if for every T in C with /z(T) > 0 and every /~-T-admissible sequence 79 = (:ri)~l, the limit, limk__>~ grvnk (T) exists and is independent of the choice of 79. (2) For a given garne v, the #-asymptotic value, if it exists, is clearly unique. (3) The/x-asymptotic value ~ov of a garne v is finitely additive and II~ovIl ~< IIv Il whenever v has bounded variation. The space of all garnes of bounded variation that have a #-asymptotic value is denoted by ASYMP[tz]. THEOREM 19 [Hart (1980), Theorem 9.2]. The set of all garnes having a Iz-asymptotic value is a linear Ix-symmetric space of garnes and the operator mapping each garne to its tz-asymptotic value is a I~-value on that space. ASYMP[Ix] is a closed lz-symmetric
Ch. 56:
Values of Garnes with Infinitely Many Players
2159
linear subspace o f B V which contains all functions o f the form f o (Izl . . . . . IZn) where IZl . . . . . tzn are absolutely continüous w.r.t, tz and with Radon-Nikodym derivatives, dlzi/dlz, in L2(/z) and f is concave and homogeneous o f degree 1.
12. T h e value and the core
The Banach space of all bounded set functions with the supremum norm is denoted BS, and its closed subspace spanned by pNA is denoted pNA t. The set of all garnes in p N X that are homogeneous of degree 1 (i.e., ~(oef) = o~fi(f) for all f in B+(I, C) and all ee in [0, 1]), and superadditive (i.e., v(S U T) >~ v(S) + v ( T ) for all S, T in C), is denoted H t. The subset of all games in H ' which also satisfy v ~> 0 is denoted H~_. The core of a garne v in H ~ is non-empty and for every S in C, the minimum of # ( S ) when/x runs over all elements/z in core (v) is attained. The exact cover of a garne v in H ~ is the garne min{/z(S): /~ E Core(v)} and its core coincides with the core of v. A garne v 6 H ~ that equals its exact cover is called exact. The closed (in the bounded variation norm) subspace of B V that is generated by pNA and DIAG is denoted by pNAD. THEOREM 20 [Aumann and Shapley (1974), Theorem I]. The core o f a game v in p N A D N H t (which obviously contains pNA N H I) has a unique element which coincides with the (asymptotic) value o f v. TItEOREM 21 [Hart (1977a)], Let v ~ H~ . If v has an asymptotic vaIue ~ov, then ~ov is the center o f symmetry o f the core o f v. The garne v has an asymptotic value ~ov when either the core o f v contains a single element v (and then ~ov = v), or v is exact and the core o f v has a center o f symmetry v (and then ~ov = v). REMARKS. (1) The second theorem provides a necessary and sufficient condition for the asymptotic value of an exact garne v in H~_ to exist: the symmetry of its core. There are (non-exact) garnes in H~_ whose cores have a center of symmetry which do not have an asymptotic value [Hart (1977a), Section 8]. (2) A garne v in Hj_ has a unique element in the core if and only if v c pNAD. (3) The conditions of superadditivity and homogeneity of degree 1 are satisfied by all garnes arising from non-atomic (i.e., perfectly competitive) economic rnarkets (see Chapter 35 in this Handbook). However, the games arising from these markets have a finite-dimensional core while games in H~_ may have an infinite-dimensional core. The above result shows that the asymptotic value falls to exist for games in H~_ whenever the core of the garne does not have a center of symmetry. Nevertheless, value theory can be applied to such garnes, and when it is, the value turns out to be a "center" of the core. It will be described as an average of the extreme points of the core of the garne
ucH;.
A. Neyman
2160
Let v e H~_ have a finite-dimensional core. Then the core of v is a convex closed subset of a vector space generated by finitely many non-atomic probability measures, vl . . . . . vn. Therefore the core of v is identified with a convex subset K of R I~, by a = (al . . . . . an) E K if and only if ~ a i ß i E Core(v). For almost every n a z in R n there exists a unique a(z) = (al(z) . . . . . an(z)) in K with ~ i = 1 i(z)zi ~ ~ m i n { ~ ~ = 1 aizi: (al . . . . . an) E K}. THEOREM 22 [Hart (1980)]. If vl . . . . . Vn are absolutely continuous with respect to IZ and dvi/dl z E L2(/z), then v ~ ASYMP[t x] and its #-asymptotic value qg/xv is given by
B#v = fR" ~
ai (z)vi dN(z)
where N is a normal distribution on Nn with 0 expectation and a covariance matrix that is given by
EN(ZiZj)=
\ d / z / t \ d/z ] d/z.
Equivalently, N is the distribution on IRn whose Fourier transform q)N is given by
q)N(Y)
=
( /,(~ (~t) ~ ) Yi
exp -
d#
.
\i=1
THEOREM 23 [Mertens (1988b)]. The Mertens value of the game v e H~_ with a finite-
dimensional core, qov, is given by q)v = fR,~ (~_~ai(z)vi) dG(z) where G is the distribution on ]Rt~ whose Fourier transform ~oo is given by q)G(Y) --e x p ( - N ~ ( y ) ) , v = (Vl . . . . . vn) and Nu is defined as in the section regardingformulas f o r the value. It is not known whether there is a unique continuous value on the space spanned by all garnes in H~_ which have a finite-dimensional core. We will state however a result that proves uniqueness for a natural subspace. Let MF be the closed space of garnes spanned by vector measure games f o # e H~_ where/~ = (/zl . . . . . /~~) is a vector of mutually singular measures in NA 1. THEOREM 24 [Haimanko (200la)]. The Mertens value is the only continuous value
on MF.
Ch. 56: Valuesof Games with Infinitely Many Players
2161
13. C o m m e n t s on s o m e classes o f garnes
13.1. Absolutely continuous non-atomic games A garne v is absolutely continuous with respect to a non-atomic measure IZ if for every e > 0 there is 3 > 0 such that for every increasing sequence of coalitions k $1 C $2 C - . . C S2k with ~ i = l tz(S2i) - / z ( $ 2 i - 1 ) < 3, ~ki=l [v(S2i) - v ( S 2 i - l ) l < e. A garne v is absolutely continuous if there is a m e a s u r e / z E NA + such that v is absolutely continuous with respect to #. A garne of the form f o / z where # 6 NA 1 is absolutely continuous (with respect t o / z ) if and only if f : [0, # ( I ) ] --+ ~ is absolutely continuous. An absolutely continuous garne has bounded variation and the set of all absolutely continuous garnes, AC, is a closed subspace of B V [Aumann and Shapley (1974)]. If v and u are absolutely continuous with respect to/x c NA + and v ~ NA + respectively, then vu is absolutely continuous with respect to # ÷ v. Thus A C is a closed subalgebra of BV. It is not known whether there is a value on AC. 13.2. Games in pNA The space pNA played a central role in the development of values of non-atomic garnes. Garnes arising in applications are often either vector measure garnes or approximated by vector measure garnes. Researchers have thus looked for conditions on vector (or scalar) measure garnes to be in pNA. Tauman (1982) provides a characterization of vector measure garnes in pNA. A vector measure garne v ----f o / z w i t h / x c (NAI) n is in pNA if and only if the function that maps a vector measure v with the same fange a s / z to the garne f o v, is continuous a t / z , i.e., for every e > 0 there is 3 > 0 such that if v ~ (NA~) n has the same range as the vector measure/x and ~ ' i ~ l ][/zi - vi I] < 3 then ]lf o # - f o v[I < e. Proposition 10.17 of [Aumann and Shapley (1974)] provides a sufficient condition, expressed as a condition on a continuous non-decreasing realvalued function f : R n --+ ]~, for a garne of the form f o # where /z is a vector of non-atomic measures to be in pNA. Theorem C of Aumann and Shapley (1974) asserts that the scalar measure garne f o / z ( # E NA l) is in pNA if and only if the real-valued function f : [0, 1] --+ ~ is absolutely continuous. Given a signed scalar measure # with range I - a , b] (a, b > 0), Kohlberg (1973) provides a sufficient and necessary condition on the real-valued function f : I - a , b] --~ ~ for the scalar measure garne f o # to be in pNA. 13.3. Games in bv~NA A n y function f ~ bv ~ has a unique representation as a sum of an absolutely continuous function f a c that vanishes at 0 and a singular function f s in bv', i.e., a function whose variation is on a set of measure zero. The subspace of all singular functions in bv' is denoted s ~. The closed linear space generated by all garnes o f the form f o # where
2162
A. Neyman
f E s' and # E NA l is denoted s'NA. Aumann and Shapley (1974) show that bvINA is the algebraic direct sum of the two spaces pNA and sINA, and that for any two games, u E p N A and v E s'NA, [[u + v[J = I[ull + IIvll. The norm of a function f ~ bv', Il/Il, is defined as the variation of f on [0, 1]. If # E NA 1 and f E bvt then ]lf o/zl[ = Ilfll. Therefore, if (fi)i~l is a sequence of functions in bv' w i t h ~ ~ = 1 ][fi II < o c and (/zi)~=l is a sequence of non-atomic probability measures, the series ~i=l°<~ fi O ],Li converges to a garne v ~ bvINA. If the functions fi are absolutely continuous the series converges to a garne in pNA. However, not every garne in pNA has a representation as a sum of scalar measure garnes. Ifthe functions fi are singular, the series ~ i ~ 1 f / o / z i converges to a garne in sZNA, and every game v E srNA is a countable (possibly finite) sum, v = ~i°°=l f/ O ]-£i, where f/ E s' with I[vl[ = Y~,i°°=l Ilf/II and ],~i E NA 1. A simple game is a garne v where v(S) E {0, 1}. A weighted majority game is a (simple) game of the form [~
if#(S)~>q if/z(S) < q
{Ò
if/z(S) > q if #(S) ~< q
v(S) = or
v(S) =
where/~ E FA + and 0 < q < / z ( 1 ) . The finitely additive measure/z is called the weight measure and q is called the quota. Every simple monotonic garne in bv'NA is a weighted majority game, and the weighted measure is non-atomic.
References Artstein, Z. (1971), "Values of games with denumerably many players", International Journal of Garne Theory 1:27-37. Aubin, J. (1981 ), "Cooperative fuzzy garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 6:1-13. Aumann, R.J. (1975), "Values of markets with a continuum of traders", Ecouometrica 43:611-646. Aumann, R.J. (1978), "Recent developments in the theory of the Shapley value", in: Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians, Helsinki, 994-1003. Aumann, RJ., R.J. Gardner and R. Rosenthal (1977), "Core and value for a public goods economy: An example", Journal of Economic Theory 15:363-365. Aumann, RJ., and M. Kurz (1977a), "Power and taxes", Econometrica 45:1137-1161. Aumann, R.J., and M. Kurz (1977b), "Power and taxes in a multi-commodity economy", Israel Journal of Mathematics 27:185-234. Aumann, R.J., and M. Kurz (1978), "Power and taxes in a multi-commodity economy (updated)", Journal of Public Economics 9:139-161. Aumarm, R.J., M. Kurz and A. Neyman (1987), "Power and public goods", Journal of Economic Theory 42:108-127. Aumann, R.J., M. Kurz and A. Neyman (1983), "Voting for public goods", Review of Economic Studies 50:677-693.
Ch. 56:
Valuesof Garnes with Infinitely Many Players
2163
Aumaim, R.J., and M. Perles (1965), "A variational problem arising in economics", Joumal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications 11:488-503. Aumann, R.J., and U. Rothblum (1977), "Orderable set functions and continuity IlI: Orderability and absolute continuity", SIAM Journal on Control and Optimization 15:156-162. Aumann, R.J., and L.S. Shapley (1974), Values of Non-atomic Games (Princeton University Press, Princeton,
NJ). Berbee, H. (1981), "On covering single points by randomly ordered intervals", Annals of Probability 9:520528. Billera, LJ. (1976), "Values of non-atomic garnes", Mathematical Reviews 51:2093-2094. Billera, L.J., and D.C. Heath (1982), "Allocation of shared costs: A set of axioms yielding a unique procedure", Mathematics of Operations Research 7:32-39. Billera, L.J., D.C. Heath and J. Raanan (1978), "Intemal telephone billing rates: A novel application of nonatomic garne theory", Operations Research 26:956-965. Billera, L.J., D.C. Heath and J. Raanan (1981), "A unique procedure for allocating common costs/rom a production process", Joumal of Accotmting Research 19:185-196. Billera, L.J., and J. Raanan (198l), "Cores of non-atomic linear production garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 6:420-423. Brown, D., and EA. Loeb (1977), "The values of non-standard exchange economies", Israel Joumal of Mathematics 25:71-86. Butnariu, D. (1983), "Decompositions and ranges for additive fuzzy measul"es", Fuzzy Sets and Systems 3:135-155. Butnariu, D. (1987), "Values and cores of fuzzy garnes with infinitely many players", International Joumal of Garne Theory 16:43-68. Champsaur, E (1975), "Cooperation versus competition", Journal of Economic Theory 11:394-417. Cheng, H. (198 l), "On dual regularity and value convergence theorems", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 6:37-57. Dubey, E (1975), "Some results on values of finite and infinite garnes", Ph.D. Thesis (Cornell University). Dubey, P. (1980), "Asymptotic semivalues and a short proof of Kannai's theorem', Mathematics of Operations Research 5:267-270. Dubey, P., and A. Neyman (1984), "Payoffs in nonatomic economies: An axiomatic approach', Econometfica 52:1129-1150. Dubey, P., and A. Neyman (1997), "An equivalence principle for perfectly competitive economies", Journal of Economic Theory 75:314-344. Dubey, P., A. Neyman and R.J. Weber (1981), "Value theory without efficiency", Mathematics of Operations Research 6:122-128. Dvoretsky A., A. Wald and J. Wolfowitz (1951), "Relations among certain ranges of vector measures", Pacific Journal of Mathematics 1:59-74. Fogelman, E, and M. Quinzii (1980), "Asymptotic values of mixed garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 5:86-93. Gardner, RJ. (1975), "Studies in the theory of social institutions", Ph.D. Thesis (Comell University). Gardner, R.J. (1977), "Shapley value and disadvantageous monopolies", Journal of Economic Theory 16:513517. Gardner, R.J. (1981), "Wealth and power in a collegial pofity", Joumal of Economic Theory 25:353-366. Gilboa, I. (1989), "Additivization of nonadditive measures", Mathematics of Operations Research 14:1-17. Guesnerie, R. (1977), "Monopoly, syndicate, and Shapley value: About some conjecmres", Journal of Economic Theory 15:235-251. Haimanko, O. (2000a), "Value theory without synmaetry", International Journal of Garne Theory 29:451-468. Haimanko, O. (2000b), "Partially symmetric values", Mathematics of Operations Research 25:573-590. Haimanko, O. (2000c), "Nonsymmetric values of nonatomic and mixed garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 25:591-605.
2164
A. Neyman
Halmanko, O. (2000d), "Values of garnes with a continuum of players", Ph.D. Thesis (The Hebrew University of Jernsalem). Haimanko, O. (200la), "Payoffs in non-differentiable perfectly competitive TU economies", Joumal of Economic Theory (forthcoming). Haimanko, O. (2001b), "Cost sharing: The non-differentiable case", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 35:445-462. Hart, S. (1973), "Values of mixed garnes", International Journal of Garne Theory 2:69-85. Hart, S. (1977a), "Asymptotic values of games with a continuum of players", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 4:57-80. Hart, S. (1977b), "Values of non-differentiable markets with a continuum of traders", Journal of Mathematical Economics 4:103-116. Hart, S. (1979), "Values of large market games", in: S. Brams, A. Schotter and G. Schwodiauer, eds., Applied Garne Theory (Physica-Verlag, Heidelberg), 187-197. Hart, S. (1980), "Measure-based values of market garnes', Mathematics of Operations Research 5:197-228. Hart, S. (1982), "The number of commodities required to represent a market garne", Journal of Economic Theory 27:163-169. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1989), "Potential, value and consistency", Econometrica 57:589-614. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1995a), "Egalitarian solutions of large garnes. I. A continuum of players", Mathematics of Operations Research 20:959-1002. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1995b), "Egalitarian solutions of large games. II. The asymptotic approach", Mathematics of Operations Research 20:1003-1022. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1996), "Harsanyi values of large economies: Nonequivalence to competitive equilibria", Garnes and Economic Behavior 13:74-99. Hart, S., and D. Monderer (1997), "Potential and weighted values of nonatomic games", Mathematics of Operations Research 22:619-630. Hart, S., and A. Neyman (1988), "Values of non-atomic vector measure games: Are they linear combinations of the measures?", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 17:31-40. Imai, H. (1983a), "Vofing, bargaining, and factor income distribution", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 11:211-233. Imai, H. (1983b), "On Harsanyi's solution", International Joumal of Garne Theory 12:161-179. Isbell, J. (1975), "Values of non-atomic garnes', Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 83:539-546. Kannai, Y. (1966), "Values of games with a continuum of players", Israel Jounaal of Mathematics 4:54-58. Kemperman, J.H.B. (1985), "Asymptotic expansions for the Shapley index of power in a weighted majority garne", mimeo. Kohlberg, E. (1973), "On non-atomic garnes: Conditions for f o/x C pNA", International Journal of Garne Theory 2:87-98. Kuhn, H.W., and A.W. Tucker (1950), "Editors' preface to Contributions to the Theory of Games (Vol. I), in: Annals of Mathematics Study 24 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ). Lefvre, F. (1994), "The Shapley value of a perfectly competitive market may not exist", in: J.-F. Mertens and S. Sorin, eds., Game-Theoretic Methods in General Equilibrium Analysis (Kinwer Academic, Dordrecht), 95-104. Lyapunov, A. (1940), "Sur les fonction-vecteurs completement additions", Bull. Acad. Soc. URRS Ser. Math. 4:465-478. Mas-Colell, A. (1977), "Competitive and value allocations of large exchange economies", Joumal of Economic Theory 14:419-438. Mas-Colell, A. (1980), "Remarks on the game-theoretic analysis of a simple distribution of surplus problem", International Journal of Garne Theory 9:125-140. McLean, R. (1999), "Coalition strncture values of mixed games", in: M.H. Wooders, ed., Topics in Mathematical Economics and Garne Theory: Essays in Honor of Robert J. Aumann (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI), 105-120.
Ch. 56:
Valuesof Games with Infinitely Many Players
2165
McLean, R.E, and W.W. Sharkey (1998), "Weighted Aumann-Shapley pricing", Intemational Journal of Garne Theory 27:511-523. Mertens, J.-E (1980), "Values and derivatives", Mathematics of Operations Research 5:523-552. Mertens, J.-E (1988a), "The Sbapley value in the non-differentiable case", Intemational Joumal of Garne Theory 17:1-65. Mertens, J.-E (1988b), "Nondifferentiable TU markets: The value", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value, Essays in Honor of Loyd S. Shapley (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 235-264. Mertens, J.-E (1990), "Extensions of garnes, purification of strategies, and Lyapunov's theorem", in: J.J. Gabszewicz, J.-E Richard and L. Wolsey, eds., Economic Decision-Making: Games, Econometrics and Optimisation. Contributions in Honour of J.H. Drèze (Elsevier Science Publishers, Amsterdam), 233-279. Mertens, J.-E, and A. Neyman (2001), "A value on rAN", Center for Rationality DP-276 (The Hebrew University of Jernsalem). Milchtaich, I. (1997), "Vector measure games based on measures with values in an infinite dimensional vector space", Garnes and Economic Behavior 24:25-46. Milchtaicb, I. (1995), "The value of nonatomic games arising from certain noncooperative congestion garnes", Center for Rätionality DP-87 (The Hebrew University of Jerusalem). Milnor, J.W., and L.S. Shapley (1978), "Values of large games. II: Oceanic garnes", Mathemafics of Operations Research 3:290-307. Mirman, L.J., and A. Neyman (1983), "Prices for homogeneous cost functions", Journal of Mathematical Economics 12:257-273. Mirman, L.J., and A. Neyman (1984), "Diagonality of cost allocation prices", Mathematics of Operations Research 9:66-74. Mirman, L.J., J. Raanan and Y. Tauman (1982), "A sufficient condition on f for f o/x to be in pNAD", Journal of Mathematical Economics 9:251-257. Mirman, L.J., D. Samet and Y. Tauman (1983), "An axiomatic approach to the allocation of fixed cost through prices", Bell Journal of Economics 14:139-151. Mirman, L.J., and Y. Tauman (1981), "Valeur de Shapley et repartition equitable des couts de production", Cahiers du Seminaire d'Econometrie 23:121-151. Mirman, L.J., and Y. Tauman (1982a), "The continuity of the Aumann-Shapley price mechanism", Journal of Mathematical Economics 9:235-249. Mirman, LJ., and Y. Tauman (1982b), "Demand compatible equitable cost sharing prices", Mathematics of Operations Research 7:40-56. Monderer, D. (1986), "Measure-based values of non-atomic games", Matbematics of Operafions Research 11:321-335. Monderer, D. (1988), "A probabilistic problem arising in economics", Journal of Mathemafical Economics 17:321-338. Monderer, D. (1989a), "Asymptotic measure-based values of nonatomic garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 14:737-744. Monderer, D. (1989b), "Weighted majority garnes have many #-values", International Journal of Garne Theory 18:321-325. Monderer, D. (1990), "A Milnor condition for non-atomic Lipschitz garnes and its applications", Mathematics of Operations Research 15:714-723. Monderer, D., and A. Neyman (1988), "Values of smooth nonatomic garnes: The method of multilhlear approximation", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 217-234 (Cbapter 15). Monderer, D., and W.H. Ruckle (1990), "On the symmetry axiom for values of non-atomic garnes", International Journal of Mathematics and Mathematical Sciences 13:165-170. Neyman, A. (1977a), "Continuous values are diagonal", Mathematics of Operations Research 2:338-342. Neyman, A. (1977b), "Values for non-transferable utility garnes with a continuum of players", TR 351, S.O.R.LE. (Cornell University).
2166
A. Neyman
Neyman, A. (1979), "Asymptotic values of mixed games", in: O. Moeschlin and D. Pallaschke, eds., Garne Theory and Related Topics (North-Holland, Amsterdam), 71-81. Neyman, A. (198 la), "Singular garnes have asymptotic values", Mathematics of Operations Research 6:205212. Neyman, A. (198 lb), "Decomposition of ranges of vector measures", Israel Joumal of Mathematics 40:54-65. Neyman, A. (1982), "Renewal theory for sampling without replacement", Annals of Probability 10:464-481. Neyman, A. (1985), "Semi-values of political economic garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 10:390-402. Neyman, A. (1988), "Weighted majority garnes have asymptotic value", Mathematics of Operations Research 13:556-580. Neyman, A. (1989), "Uniqueness of the Shapley value", Garnes and Economic Behavior 1:116-118. Neyman, A. (1994), "Values of games with a continuum of players", in: J.-E Mertens and S. Sorin, eds., Game-Theoretic Methods in General Equilibrium Analysis, Chapter IV (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordreeht), 67-79. Neyman, A. (2001), "Values of non-atomic vector measure garnes", Israel Jottmal of Mathematics 124:1-27. Neyman, A., and R. Smorodinski (1993), 'q?he asymptotic value of the two-house weighted majofity garnes", mimeo. Neyman, A., and Y. Tauman (1976), "The existence of nondiagonal axiomatic values", Mathematies of Operations Research 1:246-250. Neyman, A., and Y. Tauman (1979), "The partition value", Mathematics of Operations Research 4:236-264. Osborne, M.J. (1984a), "A reformulation of the marginal productivity theory of distribution", Econometrica 52:599-630. Osbome, M.J. (1984b), "Why do some goods bear higher taxes than others?", Journal of Economic Theory 32:301-316. Owen, G. (1972), "Multilinear extension of games", Management S cience 18:64-79. Owen, G. (1982), Garne Theory, 2nd edn. (Academic Press, New York), Chapter 12. Pallaschke, D., and J. Rosenmüller (1997), "The Shapley value for countably many players", Optimization 40:351-384. Pazgal, A. (1991), "Potential and consistency in TU garnes with a continuum of players and in cost allocation problems", M.Sc. Thesis (Tel Aviv University). Raut, L.K. (1997), "Construction of a Haar measure on the projective limit group and random order values of nonatomic games", Journal of Mathematical Economics 27:229-250. Raut, L.K. (1999), "Aumann-Shapley random order values of non-atomic games," in: M.H. Wooders, ed., Topics in Mathematieal Economics and Game Theory: Essays in Honor of Robert J. Aumarm (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI), 121-136. Reiehert, J., and Y. Tanman (1985), "The space of polynomials in measures is internal", Mathematics of Operations Research 10:1-6. Rosenmüller, J. (1971), "On core and value", in: R. Henn, ed., Operations Research-Verfahren (Anton Hein, Meisenheim), 84-104. Rosenthal, R.W. (1976), "Lindahl solutions and values for a public goods example", Journal of Mathematical Economics 3:37-41. Rothblum, U. (1973), "On orderable set functions and continuity I", Israel Journal of Mathematics 16:375397. Rothblum, U. (1977), "Orderable set functions and continuity II: Set functions with infinitely many null points", SIAM Journal on Conlxol and Optimization 15:144-155. Ruckle, W.H. (1982a), "Projections in certain spaces of set functions", Mathematics of Operations Research 7:314-318. Ruckle, W.H. (1982b), "An extension of the Aumann-Shapley value concept to functions on arbitrary Banach spaces", International Journal of Garne Theory 11:105-116. Ruclde, W.H. (1988), "The linearizing projection: Global theories", International Journal of Game Theory 17:67-87.
Ch. 56:
Valuesof Games with lnfinitely Many Players
2167
Samet, D. (1981 ), Syndication in Market Games with a Continuum of Traders, DP 497 (KGSM, Northwestern University). Samet, D. (1984), "Vector measures are open maps", Mathematics of Operations Research 9:471-474. Samet, D. (1987), "Continuous selections for vector measures", Mathematics of Operations Research 12:536543. Samet, D., and Y. Tanman (1982), "The determination of marginal cost prices under a set of axioms", Econometrica 50:895-909. Samet, D., Y. Tauman and I. Zang (1984), "An application of the Aumann-Shapley prices to the transportation problems", Mathematics of Operations Research 9:25-42. Santos, J.C., and J.M. Zarzuelo (1998), "Mixing weighted values for non-atomic garnes", International Jottrnal of Garne Theory 27:331-342. Santos, J.C., and J.M. Zarzuelo (1999), "Weighted values for non-atomic garnes: An axiomatic approach", Mathematical Methods of Operations Research 50:53~53. Shapiro, N.Z., and L.S. Shapley (1978), "Values of large garnes I: A limit theorem", Mathematics of Operations Research 3:1-9. Shapley, L.S. (1953a), "A value for n-person garnes", in: H.W. Kuhn and A.W. Tucker, eds., Contributions to the Theory of Garnes, Vol. II (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ), 307-317. Shapley, L.S. (1953b), "Additive and non-additive set functions", Ph.D. Thesis (Princeton University). Shapley, L.S. (1962), "Valnes of garnes with infinitely many players", in: M. Maschler, ed., Recent Advances in Garne Theory (Ivy Curtis Press, Philadelphia, PA), 113-118. Shapley, L.S. (1964), "Values of large garnes VII: A general exchange economy with money", RM 4248 (Rand Corporation, Santa Monica). Shapley, L.S., and M. Shubik (1969), "Pure compefition, coalitional power and fair division", International Economic Review 10:337-362. Sroka, J.J. (1993), "The value of certain pNA garnes through inflnite-dimensional Banach spaces", International Joumal of Game Theory 22:123-139. Tauman, Y. (1977), "A nondiagonal value on a reproducing space", Mathematics of Operafions Research 2:331-337. Tauman, Y. (1979), "Value on the space of all scalar integrable garnes", in: O. Moeschlin and D. Pallaschke, eds., Game Theory and Related Topics (North-Holland, Amsterdam), 107-115. Tauman, Y. (1981a), "Value on a class of non-differentiable market garnes", International Jonmal of Garne Theory 10:155-162. Tauman, Y. (1981b), "Values of market games with a inajofity mle", in: O. Moeschlin and D. Pallaschke, eds., Garne Theory and Mathemafieal Economics (North-Holland, Amsterdam), 103-122. Tauman, Y. (1982), "A charactefization of vector measure garnes in pNA", Israel Journal of Mathematics 43:75-96. Weber, R.J. (1979), "Subjectivity in the valuation of games", in: O. Moeschlin and D. Pallaschke, eds., Garne Theory and Related Topics (North-Holland, Amsterdam), 129-136. Weber, R.J. (1988), "Probabilisfic values for games", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value, Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley (Canlbfidge University Press, Cambfidge), 101-119. Wooders, M.H., and W.R. Zame (1988), "Values of large finite garnes", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value, Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley (Cambfidge University Press, Cambridge), 195-206. Young, H.P. (1985), "Monotonic solufions of cooperative games", International Journal of Game Theory 14:65-72. Young, H.P. (1985), "Producer incentives in cost allocation", Econometrica 53:757-765.
Chapter 57
VALUES OF PERFECTLY COMPETITIVE ECONOMIES* SERGIU HART Center for Rationality and Interactive Decision Theory, Department of Economics, and Department of Mathematics, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem, Israel
Contents 1. 2. 3. 4.
Introduction The model The Value Principle Proof of Value Equivalence 4.1. Value allocations are competitive allocations 4.2. Competitive allocations are value allocations 5. G e n e r a l i z a t i o n s a n d e x t e n s i o n s 5.1. The non-differentiable case 5.2. The geometry of non-atomic market garnes 5.3. Other non-atomic TU-values 5.4. Other NTU-values 5.5. Limits of sequences 5.6. Other approaches 5.7. Ordinal vs. cardinal 5.8. Impeffect competition References
*The author thanks Robert J. Aumann and Andreu Mas-Colel! for their comments. Handbook of Gäme Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2171 2172 2175 2176 2176 2177 2178 2178 2178 2180 2180 2181 2181 2182 2182 2182
2170
S. Hart
Abstract Perfectly competitive economies are economic models with many agents, each of whom is relatively insignificant, This chapter studies the relations between the basic economic concept of competitive (or Walrasian) equilibrium, and the game-theoretic solution concept of value. It includes the classical Value Equivalence Theorem together with its many extensions and generalizations, as well as recent results.
Keywords perfect competition, value, Shapley value, competitive equilibrium, value equivalence principle
JEL classification: C7, D5
Ch. 57." Valuesof PerfectlyCompetitiveEconomies
2171
1. Introduction
This chapter is devoted to the study of economic models with many agents, each of whom is relatively insignificant. These are referred to as perfectly competitive models. The basic economic concept for such models is the competitive (or Walrasian) equilibrium, which prescribes prices that make the total demand equal to the total supply, i.e., under which the markets clear. The fact that each agent is negligible implies that he cannot singly affect the prices, and so he takes them as given when finding his optimal consumption, or "demand". Game-theoretic concepts, particularly "cooperative game-theoretic" solutions (like core and value), are supported by very different considerations from the above. First, such solutions are based on the "coalitional garne" which, in assigning to each coalition the set of possible allocations to its members, abstracts away from specific mechanisms (like prices). And second, they prescribe outcomes that satisfy certain desirable criteria or postulates (like efficiency, stability, or fairness). Nevertheless, it turns out that game-theoretic solutions may yield the competitive outcomes. The prime example is the Core Equivalence Theorem (see the chapter of Anderson (1992) in this Handbook) which states that, in perfectly competitive economies, the core coincides with the set of competitive allocations. Here we will study another central solution concept, the (Shapley) value (see the chapter of Winter (2002) in this Handbook). The value, originally introduced by Shapley (1953) on the basis of a number of simple axioms] turns out to measure the "average marginal contributions" of the players. It is perhaps best viewed as an "expected outcome" or an "a priori utility" of playing the garne. The first work on values of perfectly competitive economies is due to Shapley (1964) (see also Shapley and Shubik (1969)), who considered differentiable exchange economies (or markets) with transferable utilities (TU), and showed that, as the number of players increases by replication, the Shapley values converge to the competitive equilibrium. To extend this result, two developments were needed. One was to develop the theory of value for garnes with a continuum of players (the "limit game") and, in particular, to obtain the Shapley (1964) result in this framework; see Aumann and Shapley (1974) (and the chapter of Neyman (2002) in this Handbook). The other was to define the concept of value for general non-transferabte utility (NTU) garnes; see Harsanyi (1963) and Shapley (1969) (and the chapter of McLean (2002) in this Handbook). This culminated in the general VaIue Equivalence Theorem of Aumann (1975): In a differentiable economy with a continuum of traders, the set of Shapley (1969) value allocations coincides with the set of competitive allocations. Next, the non-differentiable case was studied by Champsaur (1975) (limit of replicas) and by Hart (1977b) (a continuum of traders), who showed that one direction always
1 Efficiency,symmetry,dummyplayerand additivity.
2172
S. Hart Table 1 The Value Principle
Limit of replicas
Continuum of agents
Differentiable
TU
Shapley (1964)
Aumann and Shapley (1974)
(Equivalence)
NTU
Mas-Colell (1977)
Aumann (1975)
General (lnclusion)
TU
Champsaur (1975)
Hart (1977b)
NTU
holds - all value allocations are competitive- but not necessarily the converse. Together with the work of Mas-Colell (1977) (limit of replicas in the NTU case), the picmre was completed, resulting in the Value Principle: In perfectly competitive economies, every Shapley value allocation is competitive, and the converse holds in the differentiable case; see Table 1. In the TU-case, the concept of value is clear and undisputed (of course, its definition in the case of a continuum of players entails many difficulties). This is not so in the NTU-case. There are different ways of extending the Shapley TU-value, and which one is more appropriate is a matter of some controversy (see the references in Subsecfion 5.4). The Value Principle stated above was exclusively established for the Shapley (1969) NTU-value (also known as the ")~-transfer value"). Recently, Hart and Mas-Colell (1996a) studied the Harsanyi (1963) NTU-value in perfectly competitive economies, and showed that these value allocations may be different from the competitive ones, even in the differentiable case (and that, moreover, this is a robust phenomenon). Since the Harsanyi NTU-value is no less appropriate than the Shapley NTU-value (and possibly even more so), this casts doubt on the general validity of the Value Principle, in particular when the economy exhibits substantial NTU features; see Subsection 5.4. The chapter is organized as follows: Section 2 presents the basic model of an exchange economy with a continuum of agents, together with the definitions of the appropriate concepts. The Value Principle results are stated in Section 3. An informal (and hopefully instructive) proof of the Value Equivalence Theorem is provided in Section 4. Section 5 is devoted to additional material, generalizations, extensions and alternative approaches.2 2. The model
As we saw in the Introducfion, there are various ways to model "perfectly competitive" economies. One is to consider sequences of economies with finitely many agents, where the number of agents increases to infinity; see Subsection 5.5. Another is to study directly the "limit" economy with a confinuum of agents. Indeed, to model precisely the
2 Precise definitions and statements are given for one main result (the Value Equivalence Theorem with a continuum of traders); the rest of the material is presented in a less formal manner.
Ch. 57: Valuesof Perfectly Competitive Economies
2173
intuitive notion that an individual's influence on the whole economy is negligible, orte needs infinitely many participants. As Aumann (1964, p. 39) says, " . . . the most natural model for this purpose contains a continuum of participants, similar to the continuum of points on a line or the continuum of particles in a fluid". Our basic model is that of a pure exchange economy (or market) with a continuum of traders, and consists of the following: E1 The commodities (or goods): £ = 1, 2 . . . . . L; the consumption set of each agent is thus 3 IR~_. E2 The space oftraders: A measure space (T, fr,/x), where: T is the set oftraders (or agents); ~, a cr-field of subsets of T, is the set of coalitions; and/x, a probability measure 4 on fr, is the popuIation measure (i.e., for every coalition S c ~, the number/z(S) 6 [0, 1] is the "mass" of S, relative to the whole space T). E3 The initial endowments: For every trader t c T, a commodity vector e(t) = (e I (t), e 2 (t) . . . . . e L (t)) c 1R~_, where e e (t) is the quantity of good £ initially owned by trader t. E4 The utilityfunctions: For every trader t E T, a function ut :Re+ --+ R, where ut(x) is the utility of t from the commodity bundle x 6 I~~. We make the following assumptions: G1 (Measurability) e(t) is measurable in t and ut(x) is jointly measurable in (t, x) (relative to the Borel «-field on IR~ and the cr-field ~ on T). G2 (Endowments) Every commodity is present in the market, i.e., 5 f r e d/x » 0. G3 (Utilities) The utility functions ut are all strictly monotonic (i.e., x > y implies ut (x) > ut (y)), continuous and uniformly bounded (i.e., there exists M such that lut(x)l <~ M for all x and t). G4 (Standardness) (T, ~,/x) is isomorphic to 6 ([0, 1], ~3, v), the unit interval [0, 1] with the Borel «-field ~3 and the Lebesgue measure v; in particular, # is a nonatomic measure. All of these assumptions are standard; we will refer to G 1 - G 4 (in addition, of course, to E l - E 4 ) as the general case. Some assumptions (like uniform boundedness of the utility functions) are made for simplicity of presentation only; the reader should consult the relevant papers for more general setups. Finally, we introduce an additional set of assumptions known as the differentiable case:
3 IR is the real line, and IRL is the non-negative oNaant of the L-dimensional Euclidean space. 4 I.e., # is non-negative a n d / x ( T ) = 1. 5 For vectors x, y ~ IRL, we take x ~> y and x » y to mean, respectively, x g ~> ye and x g > ye for all g. Next, x => y means x ~> y and x 5~ y (i.e., x ~ ~> yg for all g, with at least orte strict inequality). 6 There is little loss of generality here; see Aumann and Shapley (1974, Chapter VIII).
s. Hart
2174
D1 The utility functions ut are all concave and continuously differentiable on 7 IRL+, and their gradients Vut are u n i f o r m l y b o u n d e d and u n i f o r m l y positive in b o u n d e d subsets of 8 ~~_. D2 The initial e n d o w m e n t s are u n i f o r m l y b o u n d e d (i.e., there exists M such that ee(t) ~< M for all ~ and t). A n allocation x is a feasible outcome of this exchange economy, i.e., a redistribution of the total initial endowment. That is, x : T --~ R~_ is an integrable function, where x(t) ~ 1R~ is agent t's final c o m m o d i t y bundle, which satisfies:
B x d / z = f r ed/z.
(2.1)
We now define the two concepts that will be the concern of this chapter: competitive equilibrium and value. A n allocation x is competitive (or Walrasian) if there exists a price vector p E R L, p ~ 0 such that, for every agent t ~ T, the bundle x(t) is m a x i m a l with respect to ut in t's budget set Bt(p) : = {x ~ ]RL: p - x ~< p . e(t)} (i.e., ut(x(t)) >>. ut(y) for all y 6 Bt(p)). W e refer to e(t) as t's supply, and to x(t) as t's demand; equality (2.1) then states that total d e m a n d equals total supply. A n allocation x is a Shapley (1969) (NTU-)value allocation (see the chapter of M c L e a n (2002) in this Handbook) if there exists a collection )~ = ()~t)te r of nonnegative weights (formally, a m e a s u r a b l e function )~ : T ---> IR+) such that 9
fs
)~tut(x(t)) d/z(t) : q)vx(S),
for every S e ~,
(2.2)
where v~ is the TU-garne defined b y vA(S) : = m a x { J s £tut(y(t))dlz(t): y ( t ) e I R L f o r a l l t c S
and f s Y d / ~ = f s e d / x }
(2.3)
for all coalitions S e ~, and q)vz is the "asymptotic value" (see the chapter of N e y m a n (2002) in this Handbook) of the garne vx. That is, if utilities were transferable b e t w e e n 7 Including the boundary of RL; that is, ut is continuously difterentiable in the interior of ]RL+,and all its partial derivatives can be continuously extended to the boundary of N L. 8 I.e., for every M < ec there exist c > 0 and C < ec such that c < Out(x)/Ox ~ < C for all t, ~ and x with I[x[[ ~<M. 9 Equivalently, in "density" terms, Xtut (x(t)) ----(d(~pvx)/dlO(t) for #-almost every t. The fight-hand side (which is the Radon-Nikodym derivative of ~0v£ with respect to #) may be viewed as the "value of t'; in out informal arguments, we will abuse notation and write it as ~Pvx(t), so (2.2) becomes £t ut (x(t)) = ~pvx(t) for (almost) every t (just like the case when there are only finitely many agents).
Ch. 57: Valuesof Perfectly Competitive Economies
2175
the traders at the rates )~, then the value of the resulting TU-garne (2.3) would in fact be achievable without transfers (2.2).
3. The Value Principle In this section we will state the main results on the relations between value and competitive equilibria. The following two theorems comprise what is known as the Value Principle. THEOREM 3.1 (Value Equivalence). In the differentiable case: The set of Shapley value allocations coincides with the set of competitive allocations. THEOREM 3.2 (Value Inclusion). In the general case: The set of Shapley value allocations is included in the set of competitive allocations (and there are cases where the inclusion is strict). In other words: First, value allocations are always competitive. And second, competitive allocations are value allocations provided the economy is appropriately differentiable (or smooth). In the framework of the previous section (markets with a continuum of agents), the "general case" refers to E l - E 4 together with G1-G4; the "differentiable case", to E l - E 4 , G1-G4 and D l - D 2 . Value Equivalence has been proved by Aumann (1975). We will provide an informal - and hopefully instructive - proof in the next section. Value Inclusion has been proved by Hart (1977b); see Subsections 5.1 and 5.2 below. As stated in the Introduction, parallel results have been obtained in other frameworks (like limits of sequences, transferable utility, etc.; recall Table 1 and see Section 5). All of these results use the concept of NTU-value due to Shapley (1969) (defined in the previous section). However, there are other notions of an NTU-value. A prominent one is the Harsanyi (1963) NTU-value. We have: PROPOSITION 3.3. In the differentiable case: The set of Harsanyi value allocations may be disjoint from the set of competitive allocations. This is shown by Hart and Mas-Colell (1996a), who provide a robust example with a unique Harsanyi value which is different from the unique competitive equilibrium. This clearly raises doubts about either the Harsanyi value or the Value Principle. In view of the additional literature, Hart and Mas-Colell (1996a) suggest that, since the Harsanyi concept is no less appropriate than the Shapley one (and perhaps even more so), it follows that the Value Principle may not be valid in general - particularly when the economy is far removed from the transferable utility case. See Subsection 5.4.
2176
S. Hart
4. Proof of Value Equivalence We now provide an informal proof for the Value Equivalence Theorem 3.1, in the framework of Section 2 (under all the assumptions there, including differentiability); in particular, "value" stands for "Shapley NTU-value". 4.1. Value allocations are competitive allocations Let x be a value allocation with corresponding weights )~. We ignore technical ¢omplications and assume that x(t) » 0 and )~« > 0 for all t. Also, we will write "for all t" where in fact it should say "for #-almost every t", and we regard a point t as if it were a "real agent".l° First, we have f)~tut(x(t)) d#(t) =
UA (T)
(4.1)
by (2.2) for T together with ~0vA(T) = vA(T) (since the TU-value is efficient). Thus the maximum in (2.3) for T is achieved at x. Therefore 11 )~tVut(x(t)) =)~t,Vut,(x(t'))
for all t, t' ~ T
(4.2)
(this is standard: if not, then a reallocation of goods between t and t ~would increase the total utility vA(T)). Ler p be the c o m m o n value of 12 )~tVut (x(t)) for all t: Vut(x(t)) = (1/Lt)p
f o r a l l t 6 T.
The utility functions ut are concave; therefore ut (y) ~< ut (x(t)) + Vut (x(t)) - (y - x(t)), from which it follows that if p . y ~< p . x(t) then ut(y) «. ut (x(t)).
(4.3)
Next, we claim that the asymptotic value pvz of vA satisfies p vA(t) = )~tut (x(t)) + p - (e(t) - x(t)).
(4.4)
The intuition for this is as follows: The value of t is t's marginal contribution to a random coalition Q (this holds in the case of finitely many players by Shapley's formula, 10 As in the case of finitely many agents. More appropriately, one should view dt as the "agent"; we prefer to use t since it may appear less intimidating for some readers. 11 We write V u (x) for the gradient of u at x, i.e., the vector of partial derivatives ( 0 u (x) / 0x ~ ) g= 1,.., L. 12 Letting p = (Pg)g=l,...,L, one may interpret p~ as the Lagrange multiplier (or "shadow price") of the
constraint fr xe = fr ee'
Ch. 57: Values of Perfectly Competitive Economies
2177
and it extends to the general case since the asymptotic value is the limit of values of finite approximations). Now a "random coalition" Q, when there is a continuum of players, is a perfect sample of the grand coalition T. (Assume for instance that we have a large finite population, consisting of two types of players: 1/3 of them are of type l, and 2/3 of them of type 2. The coalition of the first half of the players in a random order will most probably contain, by the Law of Large Numbers, about 1/3 players of type 1 and 2/3 of type 2. This holds for "one half" as well as for any other proportion strictly between 0 and 1.) Therefore the average marginal contribution of t to Q is essentially the same as t's marginal contribution to the grand coalition 13 T, which we can write suggestively as
9v~ (t) = vz (T) - vz (T\{t}). Since vz (T) is the result of a maximization problem, its derivative ("in the direction t") is obtained by keeping the optimal allocation fixed and multiplying the change in the constraints by the corresponding Lagrange multipliers.14 The optimal allocation is x (by (4.1)); rewriting )eT X d/x= fT e d # as fT\{tl x dtz = fT\{t} e d # + (e(t) - x(t)) d/z(t) shows that the change in the constraints is 15 e(t) - x(t); and the Lagrange multipliers are p. Therefore indeed
9 v z ( t ) = X t u , ( x ( t ) ) + p . ( e ( t ) - x(t)). In other words, the marginal contribution of t to the total utility v~(T) consists of t's weighted utility contribution )~tut (x(t)), together with his ner contribution of commodities e(t) - x(t), evaluated according to the "shadow prices" p (i.e., the marginal weighted utilities, which are c o m m o n to everyone by (4.2)). We have thus shown (4.4). Comparing (2.2) (see Footnote 9) and (4.4) implies that p - (e(t) - x(t)) = 0
for all t,
which together with (4.3) shows that x is a competitive allocation relative to the price vector p.
4.2. Competitive allocations are value allocations Let x be a competitive allocation with associated price vector p. From the fact that x(t) is the demand of t at the prices p (i.e., p . y ~< p . e(t) implies u t ( y ) <~ ut(x(t))), it 13 Technically, one uses here the homogeneity of degree 1 of v, hence the homogeneity of degree 0 of its derivatives. 14 Since the first order condition (that of vanishing derivatives) is satisfied at optimal allocations, the change in the optimal allocation is, in the first order, zero. This is the so-called "Envelope Theorem"; see, e.g., MasColell, Whinston and Green (1995, Section M.L). 15 In "density" terms.
&Hart
2178
follows that the gradient Vut (x(t)) is proportional to p (again, we assume for simplicity that x(t) » 0 for all t). That is, there exist )~t > 0 such that
LtVut(x(t)) = p
for all t.
This implies that the m a x i m u m in the definition of v~(T) (for this collection )~ = (Xt)t) is attained at x. As we saw in the previous subsection (recall (4.4)), the asymptotic value q)vz of vz satisfies
q)vx (t) = )~tut(x(t)) + p . ( e ( t ) - x(t)). But x(t) is t ' s demand at p, so p • x(t) = p • e(t) (by monotonicity), and therefore ~0vz(t) = )~tut(x(t)), thus completing the proof that x is indeed a value allocation (by (2.2)).
5. Generalizations and extensions 5.1. The non-differentiable case In the general case (i.e., without the differentiability assumptions), the Value Inclusion Theorem says that every Shapley value allocation is competitive, and that the converse need no longer hold. In fact, in the non-differentiable case the asymptotic value of vx may not exist (since different finite approximations lead to different l i m i t s ) ] 6 and so there may be no value allocations at all. Moreover, even if value allocations do exist, they correspond only to some of the competitive allocations; roughly speaking, values "select" certain "centrally located" equilibria. The proof that every Shapley value is competitive is based on generalizing the value fõrmula (4.4); see Hart (1977b) and the next subsection.
5.2. The geometry o f non-atomic market garnes A (TU-)market garne is a garne that arises from an economy as in Section 2 (see (2.3)). To illustrate the geometrical structure that underlies the results of this chapter, suppose for simplicity that there are finitely many types of agents, say n, with a continuum of mass l / n of each type. A coalition S is then characterized by its composition, or profile, s = (sl, s2 . . . . . sn) E R~_, where si is the mass of agents of type i in S. Formula (2.3) then defines a function v = vz over profiles s; that is, 17 v :IR~_ ~ ]R. Such a 16 A necessary condition for the existence of the asymptotic value is that the core possess a center of symmetry; see Hart (1977a, 1977b). Note that the convex hull of k points in general position does not have a center of symmetry when k ~>3 (it is a triangle, a tetrahedron, etc.). 17 In fact, only s ~<(I/n, 1/n ..... I/n) matter.
Ch. 57." Valuesof Perfectly Competitive Economies
2179
function is clearly super-additive (i.e., v(s + s/) >~ v(s) + v(s') for all s, s I c R ~ ) and h o m o g e n e o u s o f d e g r e e 1 (i.e., v(o~s) = « v ( s ) for e v e r y s 6 IR~ and ~ ~> 0), and h e n c e concave. 18 Let 7 = (1/n, 1/n . . . . . 1/n) denote (the profile of) the grand coalition. A p a y o f f v e c t o r 19 re ----(fr1, re2 . . . . . zen), w h e r e rci is the p a y o f f o f each agent o f type i, is in the core o f v if ~-~~i=ln7.gi7 i = v(7) and Y~~~I 7riSi ~ V(S) for every s ~< 7. Thus re is nothing other than a n o r m a l vector, or " s u p e r g r a d i e n t " (recall that v is c o n c a v e ) to v at 2° 7. In particular, if v is differentiable, then the c o r e has a u n i q u e element: the gradient V r ( 7 ) o f v at 7. A s for the T U - v a l u e o f v, it is obtained as in Subsection 4.1 (see the considerations leading to (4.4)) as follows. A s s u m e first that v is continuously differentiable. T h e profile q o f a r a n d o m coalition Q is (approximately) proportional to that o f the grand coalition, i.e., q ~ oe7 for s o m e « 6 (0, 1) (by the L a w o f L a r g e Numbers). T h e m a r g i n a l contribution o f an agent o f type i to such a coalition Q is thus g i v e n by the partial derivative (Ov/Osi)(q) ~ (Ov/Osi)(ots), w h i c h equals (Ov/Osi)(7) by h o m o g e n e i t y . T h e r e f o r e the value o f type i is (Ov/Osi)(7), and the value p a y o f f v e c t o r is Vr(s-) - identical to the core. 21 If v is not differentiable, then the partial derivatives are r e p l a c e d by directional derivatives, w h i c h c o r r e s p o n d to supergradients, and are again i n d e p e n d e n t o f oe by h o m o geneity. The set o f supergradients is convex, therefore averaging (over r a n d o m coalitions) implies that the value vector is also a supergradient o f v at 7 - and so in this case too the value b e l o n g s to the core. S u m m a r i z i n g : In a non-atomic TU-market game, the value belongs to the core, and is the unique element in the core in the differentiable case. But the core and the set o f c o m p e t i t i v e allocations c o i n c i d e - this is the C o r e E q u i v a l e n c e T h e o r e m (see the chapter o f A n d e r s o n (1992) in this Handbook, and note that differentiability is not required) w h i c h yields the Value Principle in the T U - c a s e . M o v i n g n o w to the N T U - c a s e , note that if rr = (zel, ~2 . . . . . Jrn) is a Shapley N T U value with weights 22 )~ = ()~1,)~2 . . . . . ~.n), then the v e c t o r ()~ lYfl, )~2ze2 . . . . . )~nzen) is the T U - v a l u e o f vx (see (2.2)) and so, as w e h a v e seen above, it is a supergradient o f vz at 7. T h e r e f o r e Y~~~1 )~ircisi ~ v~ (s) for e v e r y s, i m p l y i n g that rc cannot be i m p r o v e d upon by a coalition o f profile s (recall the definition o f vx as a m a x i m u m ) . In other words,
18 Such a function may be called "conical": its subgraph {(s, ~) E N% x I~: ~ ~< v(s)} is a convex cone. 19 We only consider type-symmetric payoffs, where agents of the same type receive the same payoffs. 20 I.e., the graph of the linear function h(s) := re. s is a supporting hyperplane to the subgraph of v (which is a convex cone; see Footnote 18) at the point (~, v(s-)) (and thus also on the whole "diagonal" {(«~, v(a~)): a/> 0}). 21 Another proof of this statement can be obtained using the potential approach of Hart and Mas-Colell (1989): Given v, there exists a unique function P -~ P(v):N~_ -+ R with P(0) = 0 and s • VP(s) = v(s) for all s - the potential of v - and moreover VP(~) is the value payoff vector. When v is homogeneous of degree 1, the Euler equation implies s - Vr(s) -----v(s), and so P = v and VP(s~ = Vv(s~ (or: value = tore). 22 Li is the weight corresponding to agents of type i (recall that, for simplicity, we assume type-symmetry).
2180
s. Hart
rc belongs to the (NTU) core of the economy, and so it is a competitive allocation by the Core Equivalence Theorem. This establishes the Value Inclusion result of Theorem 3.2. For precise presentations of these topics, the reader is referred to Shapley (1964), Hart (1977a, 1977b) and Hart and Mas-Colell (1996a, Section VII). 5.3. Other non-atomic TU-values
In the non-differentiable case, many of the relevant TU-garnes may not have an asymptotic value. 73 This happens when different sequences of finite garnes that approximate the given non-atomic garne have values that converge to different limits. (The simplest such case is the so-called "3-gloves market"; see Aumann and Shapley (1974, Section 19) and recall Footnote 16.) Therefore one looks for other TU-value concepts. One approach (frst used by Aumann and Kurz (1977)) modifies the definition of the asymptotic value by considering only those finite approximations with players that are (approximately) equal in size, where "size" is determined by the underlying population measure/~. The resulting measure-based value (or I~-value) is shown by Hart (1980) to exist under wide conditions and, moreover, to yield a competitive allocation (i.e., the Value Inclusion result of Theorem 3.2 continues to hold for this value). An explicit formula, involving an appropriate normal distribution, is obtained for the resulting competitive price; this price may then be viewed as an "expected equilibrium price"0 where the expectation is taken over random samples of the agents. Another approach, due to Mertens (1988a, 1988b), defines a value concept on a large space of non-atomic garnes, which includes all markets (whether differentiable or not); again, the Value Inclusion Theorem 3.2 holds for the Mertens value as well. 5.4. Other NTU-vaIues
Extending the concept of the Shapley value from the class of TU-garnes to the class of NTU-games is a conceptually challenging problem. One looks for an NTU-solution concept that, in particular: (i) extends the Shapley (1953) value for TU-garnes; (ii) extends the Nash (1950) bargaining solution for pure bargaining problems; (iii) is covariant with independent rescalings of the utility functions; 24 and (iv) satisfies postulates like efficiency and symmetry. However, all this does not yet determine the solution, and additional constructs are needed. The two major NTU-value concepts are due to Harsanyi (1963) and to Shapley (1969). In fact, Shapley introduced his NTU-value originally as a simplification of the Harsanyi NTU-value. It then turned out to be of interest in its own right, and has been
23 See howeverHart (1977b, TheoremC). 24 In the TU-case, where there is a commonmedium of utility transfer, one may multiply all utilities by the same constant without changingthe problem. In contrast, in the NTU-case, each player's utility may be multiplied by a diffèrent constant.
Ch. 57: Valuesof Perfectly Competitive Economies
2181
used in various models, economic and otherwise. However, further research has indicated that the Harsanyi concept may well be the more appropriate one, at least in some cases; see Aumann (1985a, 1985b, 1986), Hart (1985a, 1985b), Roth (1980, 1986) and Shafer (1980) for some of the issues related to the interpretation and appropriateness of these concepts. The Harsanyi NTU-values of large differentiable economies 25 were smdied by Hart and Mas-Colell (1996a). It is shown, first, that the Value Inclusion result holds in some cases; 26 and, second, that in general the two (non-empty) sets of allocations the Harsanyi values and the competitive equilibria - may be disjoint. Moreover, this "non-equivalence" is a robust phenomenon, and a result of being far removed from the transferable utility case (i.e., the lack of substitutability among the agents' utilities). Another NTU-value that has recently been analyzed is the consistentNTU-value (see Maschler and Owen (1989, 1992), and also Hart and Mas-Colell (1996b)). For a first smdy on the connections between this value and the core, see Leviatan (1998). 5.5. Limits o f sequences
Rather than analyze the limit economy with a continuum of agents, one may instead consider sequences of finite economies. The simplest such approach, originally used in the study of the Core Equivalence Theorem, is that of"replicas": Each agent is replaced by r identical agents, and one looks at the limit as r increases to infinity. The results here are the same as in Theorems 3.1 and 3.2: Limits of Shapley value allocations are competitive, and the converse holds in the differentiable case. See Shapley (1964) (differentiable, TU); Champsaur (1975) (non-differentiable, TU and NTU); MasColell (1977) and Cheng (1981) (differentiable, NTU); and also Wooders and Zame (1987a, 1987b) for a "space of characteristics" framework (non-differentiable, TU and NTU). 5.6. Other approaches
Among the other approaches to the Value Equivalence result, one should mention the axiomatic characterization of solutions of large economies due to Dubey and Neyman (1984, 1997), which capmres many of the interesting concepts - competitive equilibrium, core, value - and thus implies their equivalence. Other works use non-standard analysis [Brown and Loeb (1977)] or fuzzy games [Butnariu (1987)].
25 The frameworkis that of a continuumof agents of finitely many types, as in Subsection 5.2. Moreover,as it is shownin Hart and Mas-Colell (1995a, 1995b), the analysis is bome out by limits of finte approximations. 26 Specifically,when the Harsanyi value is "tight".
2182
S. Hart
5. 7. Ordinal vs. cardinal The competitive allocations and the core are clearly "ordinal" concepts: They depend only on the preference relations of the agents and not on the particular utility representations. How about the value? The construction in Section 2 uses given utility functions ut. However, the relative weights )~t are obtained endogenously (as a "fixed-point" where (2.2) holds). Thus, if we were to apply linear transformations to the functions ut (with different coefficients for different t) the NTU-value allocations would not change. Moreover, a careful look at the proof of the Value Equivalence result in Section 3 shows that only "local" information is used (e.g., gradients or marginal rates of substitution), and so applying differentiable monotonic transformations will not marter either. Therefore, the NTU-value depends only on the preference orders, and is indeed an "ordinal" concept. In fact, Aumann (1975) (and others) works directly with collections of utility representations (rather than with one utility representation and weights )~, as we do here27).
5.8. Imperfect competition Perfect competition corresponds to all agents being individually insignificant. Imperfect competition results when there are "large" agents. This is modelled by population measures that are no longer non-atomic; the atoms are precisely the large agents. A n interesting question is whether it is worthwhile for a coalition to become an atom, i.e., a "monopoly". For when this is measured by the value, see Guesnerie (1977) and Gardner (1977) (compare this with the results for the core; see the chapter of Gabszewicz and Shitovitz (1992) in this Handbook). For other economic applications, the reader is referred to the chapter of Mertens (2002) in this Handbook.
References Anderson, R.M. (1992), "The core in perfectly competitive economies", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 1 (North-Holland,Amsterdam) Chapter 14, 413-457. Aumann, R.J. (1964), "Markets with a continuum of traders", Econometrica 32:3930. Aumann, R.J. (1975), "Values of markets with a continuum of traders", Econometrica43:611-646. Aumann, R.J. (1985a), "An axiomatization of the non-transferableutility value", Econometrica 53:599-612. Aumann, R.J. (1985b), "On the non-transferable utility value: A comment on the Roth-Shafer examples", Econometrica 53:667-678. Aumann, R.J. (1986), "Rejoinder", Econometrica 54:985-989. Aumann, R.J., and M. Kurz (1977), "Power and taxes in a multi-commodity economy", Israel Journal of Mathematics 27:185-234. Aumann, R.J., and L.S. Shapley (1974), Values of Non-Atomic Garnes (Princeton University Press).
27 This ")~-approach"is commonly used, and we hope it will thus be easier on the reader.
Ch. 57." Values of Perfectly Competitive Economies
2183
Brown, D., and RA. Loeb (1977), "The values of non-standard exchange economies", Israel Journal of Mathematics 25:71-86. Butnariu, D. (1987), "Values and cores of fuzzy garnes with infinitely many players", International Joumal of Game Theory 16:43~58. Champsaur, P. (1975), "Cooperation vs. competition", Journal of Economic Theory 11:394-417. Cheng, H. (1981 ), "On dual regularity and value c onvergence theorems", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 6:37-57. Dubey, P., and A. Neyman (1984), "Payoffs in nonatomic economies: An axiomatic approach", Econometrica 52:1129-1150. Dubey, P., and A. Neyman (1997), "An equivalence principle for peffectly competitive economies", Journal of Economic Theory 75:314-344. Gabszewicz, J.J., and B. Shitovitz (1992), "The core in imperfecfly competitive economies", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 1 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 15,459-483. Gardner, R.J. (1977), "Shapley value and disadvantageous monopolies", Journal of Economic Theory 16:513517. Guesnerie, R. (1977), "Monopoly, syndicate, and Shapley value: About some conjectures", Joumal of Economic Theory 15:235-251. Harsanyi, I.C. (1963), "A simplified bargaining model for the n-person cooperative game", International Economic Review 4:194-220. Hart, S. (1977a), "Asymptotic value of garnes with a continuum of players", Journal of Mathematical Economics 4:57-80. Hart, S. (1977b), "Values of non-differentiable markets with a continuum of traders", Journal of Mathematical Economics 4:103-116. Hart, S. (1980), "Measnre-based values of market garnes", Mathematics of Operations Research 5:197-228. Hart, S. (1985a), "An axiomatization of Harsanyi's non-transferable utility solution", Econome~ica 53:12951313. Hart, S. (1985b), "Non-transferable utility garnes and markets: Some examples and the Harsanyi solution", Econometrica 53:1445-1450. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1989), "Potential, value and consistency", Econometrica 57:589-614. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1995a), "Egalitarian solutions of large garnes: I. A continuum of players", Mathematics of Operations Research 20:959-1002. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1995b), "Egalitarian solutions of large garnes: II. The asymptotic approach", Mathematics of Operations Research 20:1003-1022. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1996a), "Harsanyi values of large economies: Non-equivalence to competitive equilibria", Garnes and Economic Behavior 13:74-99. Hart, S., and A. Mas-Colell (1996b), "Bargaining and value", Econometrica 64:357-380. Leviatan, S. (1998), "Consistent values and the core in continuum market garnes with two types", The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Center for Rationality DP-171. Maschler, M., and G. Owen (1989), "The consistent Shapley value for hyperplane garnes", International Journal of Garne Theory 18:389-407. Maschler, M., and G. Owen (1992), "The consistent Shapley value for garnes without side payments", in: R. Selten, ed., Rational Interaction (Springer) 5-12. Mas-Colell, A. (1977), "Competitive and value allocations of large exchange economies", Journal of Economic Theory 14:419-438. Mas-Colell, A., M.D. Whinston and J.R. Green (1995), Microeconomic Theory (Oxford University Press). McLean, R.E (2002), "Values of non-transferable utility garnes", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 3 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 55, 2077-2120. Mertens, J.-E (1988a), "The Shapley value in the non-differentiable case", International Journal of Garne Theory 17:1-65. Mertens, J.-E (1988b), "Nondifferentiable TU markets: The value", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value (Cambridge University Press) 235-264.
2184
S. Hart
Mertens, J.-E (2002), "Some other applications of the value", in: R.J. Aumarm and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 3 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 58, 2185-2201. Nash, J. (1950), "The bargaining problem", Econometrica 18:155-162. Neyman, A. (2002), "Values of games with infinitely many players", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, cds,, Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 3 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 56, 2121-2167. Roth, A.E. (1980), "Values of garnes without side payments: Some difficulties with current concepts", Econometrica 48:457-465. Roth, A.E. (1986), "On the non-transferable utility value: A reply to Aumann", Econometrica 54:981-984. Shafer, W. (1980), "On the existence and interpretation of value allocations", Econometrica 48:467-477. Shapley, L.S. (1953), "A value for n-person garnes", in: H.W. Knhn and A.W. Tucker, eds., Contributions to the Theory of Garnes lI, Annals of Mathematics Studies 28 (Princeton University Press) 307-317. Shapley, L.S. (1964), "Values of large games VII: A general exchange economy with money", RM-4248-PR (The Rand Corporation, Santa Monica, CA). Shapley, L.S. (1969), "Utility comparison and the theory of garnes", La Décision (Editions du CNRS, Paris) 251-263. Shapley, L.S., and M. Shubik (1969), "Pure competition, coalitional power, and fair division", International Economic Review 24:1 39. Winter, E. (2002), "The Shapley value", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 3 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 53, 2025-2054. Wooders, M., and W.R. Zame (1987a), "Large garnes: Fair and stable outcomes", Journal of Economic Theory 42:59-93. Wooders, M., and W.R. Zame (1987b), "NTU values of large garnes", Stanford University, I.M.S.S.S. TR-503 (mimeo).
Chapter 58
S O M E O T H E R E C O N O M I C A P P L I C A T I O N S OF T H E VALUE* JEAN-FRAN~OIS MERTENS
Center for Operations Research and Econometrics (CORE), Université Catholique de Louvain, Louvain-la-Neave, Belgium
Contents 1. 2. 3. 4. 5.
Introduction The basic model Taxation and redistribution Public goods without exclusion
2187 2187 2189 2192
Economies with fixed prices
2196 2196 2196 2197 2197 2200 2200
5.1. Introduction 5.2. Dividend equilibria 5.3. Value allocations 5.4. The main result 5.5. Concluding remarks
References
*Based on Chapter 10 of Game-Theoretic Methods in General Equilibrium Analysis, J.-E Mertens and S. Sorin (editors), Vol. 77 of NATO ASI Series D, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994. Permission to use this material is gratefully acknowledged.
Handbook of Game Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2186
J.-E Mertens
Abstract
Selected applications of the NTU Shapley value to settings other than that of general equilibrium in perfect competition. Three models are considered: Taxation and Redistribution, Public Goods, and Fixed Prices. In each case, the value leads to significant conceptual insights which, while compelling once understood, are far from obvious at the outset.
Keywords NTU Shapley value, taxation, redistribution, public goods, fixed prices JEL classification: H23, D45, D72, C71
Ch. 58: SomeOtherEconomicApplicationsof the Value
2187
1. Introduction The concept of value has proved to be a powerful tool in analyzing economic models. Indeed, since the Shapley value can be interpreted in terms of "marginal worth", it is closely related to traditional economic ideas (see Chapter 57 of this Handbook, which presents the Value Equivalence Theorem). Though other important applications exist, we focus here on three applications of values to economic models outside the general equilibrium model; each describes a different departure from the market environment. The first two are economic-political models dealing with taxation. Taxation has (at least) two purposes: redistribution and the financing of public goods. The classical literature assumes that a benevolent government aims to maximize some social utility function. The garne approach is quite different: it assumes that the policy of the government is determined by the interests of those who elect it. Both with redistribution and with public goods, the value is a natural tool to analyze the corresponding games. The last section deals with fixed-price economies. Throughout this chapter, we will provide intuitions on why orte would expect the results to hold (or not), rather than detailed proofs. For the latter, the reader may consult the original papers.
2. The basie model Define a competitive economy as (T, ~, e, (ut)t~r) where T = [0, 1] stands for the set of traders, endowed with Lebesgue measure/z; IR~_is the commodity space; e : T --->Re+, integrable, is the initial allocation; ut : Re+ --->IR is the utility function of t. An allocation is a (measurable) map x: T ~ 1R~_such that f r xt/z(dt) = fr etlx(dt). An individual trader is best viewed as an "infinitesimal subset" dt of T. Thus et/z (dt) is trader dt's endowment, xt/z(dt) denotes what he gets under an allocation x, and ut (xt)/x(dt) is the utility he derives from it. We assume ut (0) ----0.
Value allocations. Consider a positive "weight" function )~ : T --->IR+ (integrable). The worth vz (S) of a coalition S C T with respect to )~ is the maximum "weighted total utility" it can get on its own, i.e., when the members of S reallocate their total endowment among each other. In the above setting, vz (S) = maX { fs)~tu~(xt)tz(dt) such that fsxtlz(dt) = fsetlz(dt) ]. The value of a trader is his average marginal contribution to the coalitions to which he belongs, where "average" means expectation with respect to a distribution induced by a random order of the players. Thus, the value of trader dt is (~ovz) (dt) -:
E[vz(Sät U dt)
-
vz(Sdt)],
(1)
Z-EMer~ns
2188
where Sdr is the set of players "before d t " in a random order, and E stands for "expectation". A n allocation x is called a value allocation if there exists a weight function )~ such that ((pvx)(dt)
=
Ztut(xt)tz(dt)
for all t; in words, if it assigns to each trader - and hence to each coalition - precisely its (weighted) value.
Value equivalence. It is useful for the sequel to review here the argument showing that a value allocation x is also Walrasian. Note first that it is efficient - achieves the worth vz(T) of T (i.e., f r kfut(xt)Iz(dt) = v~(T)); this follows from the efficiency of the value (i.e., vz(T) = (~ovz)(T)) and the definition of value allocation. Denoting the gradient of ut at x by ulf(x), we have
Vtl, t2 E T, Zt, u~, (xt,) = ,t-t2u~2(xt 2) (otherwise, society could always profitably reallocate its endowment, contradicting x's efficiency). Call this common value p. Next, for any eoalition S, define an S-alIocation as a (measurable) map x s : S --+ IR~ with xS#(dt) = et/x(dt); it is just like an allocation, except that it reallocates within S only. As with allocations, if such an x s achieves vz (S), then
fs
fs
in particular, this applies to Sdt. Now Sdt is a "perfect sample" of T, in the sense that in Sät the distribution of players is the same as in T. F r o m this it may be seen that the c o m m o n value of the gradients for Sdt is also p. Hence, d t ' s contribution to Sat is twofold: the weighted utility of dt itself, and the change in the other traders' aggregate utility due to d t ' s joining the coalition. Under the new optimal allocation of the endowment of Sdt U dt, dt gets xt/z(dt) and therefore its weighted utility is )~tut(xt)Iz(dt). So et/x(dt) - xt/z(dt) must be distributed among the traders in Sdt, so their increase in utility is p . [et - xt]/z(dt). So ((pv;O(dt) = p . [et - xt]/~(dt) + )~tut(xt)lx(dt), so from the definition of "value allocation" it follows that p . [et - xt] = O. Now (xt, ut (xt)) is on the boundary of the convex hull of the graph of ut. Otherwise, it would be possible to split trader dt (i.e., the bundle xt dt allocated to hirn) into several
Ch. 58: SomeOtherEconomicApplications of the Value
2189
players so that the weighted sum of their utilities would be greater than dt's utility, contradicting x's efficiency. Together with the equality of the gradients, this yields
Vx e ~e+: z,[u,(x,)- ù,(~)] >/p. ( x , - x). Hence, xt maximizes ut (x) under the constraint p . x ~< p- xt, and hence under the constraint p •x ~< p . et. So x is a Walrasian allocation corresponding to the price system p.
3. Taxation and redistribution Much of public economics regards the government as an exogenous benevolent economic agent that aims to maximize some social utility, usually the sum of individual utilities [see Arrow and Kurz (1970)]. This ignores the workings of a democracy, in which government actions are determined by the pressures of competing interests, whose strength depends on political power (voting) and economic power (resources). This section, based on Aumann and Kurz (1977a, 1977b), applies this idea to the issues of taxation and redistribution. In our model, each agent has an endowment and a utility function, taxation and redistribution policy is decided by majority voting, and each agent can destroy part or all of his endowment, which we may think of, e.g., as labor. Thus while any majority can levy taxes even at 100% and redistribute the proceeds among its own members, anyone can decide not to work, so that the majority gets nothing by taxing the income from his labor. Though he will not feel better (no utility of leisure is assumed), he can use this as a threat to make the majority compromise. This influences the composition of the majority coalition and the tax policy it adopts. We start from the previous model but with a single commodity. Since we want to allow for threats and non-transferable utilities, we use the Harsanyi-Shapley NTU value. Suppose given a weight function )~. Then the worth of the all-player coalition T is
vz(T)=max{ fT)~tut(xt)#(dt) such that fTxtlx(dt) = fretlz(dt) ]. Suppose now that two complementary coalitions S and T \ S form. Think of vz(S) as the aggregate utility of S if it bargains against T \ S. As in Nash (1953), suppose that the two parties can commit themselves to carrying out threat strategies if no satisfactory agreement is reached. If under these strategies S and T \ S get f and g respectively, then they are bargaining for vz(T) - f - g, and, under the symmetry assumption, this is split evenly. Hence, S gets ½(v)~(T) + f -- g) and T \ S gets ½(v~(T) + g - f), so that the derived game between S and T \ S is a constant-sum garne. The optimal threat strategy for the majority coalition is to tax at 100%, while the optimal threat strategy for the minority is to destroy all of its endowment; indeed, in this way the majority ensures its own endowment, and the minority ensures getting
J.-E Mertens
2190
nothing, while each side is prevented from getting more. Thus the reduced garne value is
{ max{fs£tut(xt)Iz(dt ) s.t. fsxttx(dt) = fsettz(dt)}, qz(S)
=
O,
if/z(S) > ½; if/z(S) < ½;
and we have vz (S) = ½[qz (T) 4- qz (S) - qz ( T \ S ) ] ; it follows that (~ovz)(dt) = (~oqz)(dt) =
E[qz(Sdt
U dt) - q z ( S d t ) ] .
As in the previous section, Sat is almost certainly a perfect sample of T. We can then use the self-explanatory notation Sdr = 0 T, where 0 E [0, 1] is the size of the sample. If we think of the players as entering a room at a uniform rate but in a random order, then 0 can be viewed as the random time when dt enters the room, and thus is uniformly distributed. Hence (q)q;0(dt) = f01 [qz(OT U dt) -
q)~(OT)] dO.
Now there are three different cases: (1) both OT and OT U dt are majorities; (2) both are minorities; (3) OT is a minority, but OT U dt is a majority; i.e., dt is pivotal. Suppose qz (T) is achieved at the allocation x. Then dt's expected contribution in the three cases is as follows, case 1 being as in the last section: (1) ½£t [ut (xt) -
u~t(xt).
(x, -
et)]tz (dt)
[----f~ [q~ (0 T U dt) - qx (0 T)] d0]; 2
(2) ½(0 -- 0 ) [ = fo-/Z(d0(0) d0]; 1
(3)
lqx(T)Iz(dt)
[=
2 1 f½_~(dO[qx(2T) -- 0] dt].
All in all, therefore, 1
~ov;~(dt) = ~oqz(dt) -----i ()~t [ut (xt) -
u~t(xt).
(xt -
et)]
4- qx (T))/z (dt).
By the definition of value allocations, q)vz(dt) )~tut(xt)lz(dt) and, as in the previous section, )~tu/t(xt) is constant in t, say = p. It follows that =
£tut(xt)
= qz(T) -- p" (xt -- et),
Ch. 58:
Some Other Economic Applications of the Value
2191
B-a.e. In the case of a single commodity (g = 1) this comes to ut(xt) u~(xt)
et-xt--
C
(2)
for all t, where C = q ~ ( T ) / p is a constant. Defining value allocation as in Section 2, we find that (2) is necessary and sufficient for x to be a value allocation. Moreover, (2) has a single solution (x, C), and C is positive. This constitutes the main result in Aumann and Kurz (1977a). Now to the economic interpretation. The left side of (2) is the (signed) tax on t. Note that when the utility functions ut are increasing and concave, et is increasing in xt or, more intuitively, xt is increasing in et - but with slope < ½. That is to say, marginal tax rates are between 50% and 100%. Though there is no explicit uncertainty in the model, define the f e a r o f ruin as the ratio ut(xt)/u~(xt). To explain why, consider its reciprocal u:/u. Suppose that some player is ready to play a garne in which with probability 1 - p his initial fortune x is increased by a small amount e and with probability p he is ruined and his formne is 0. If he is indifferent between playing the garne or not, p / e is a measure of his boldness (at x) - and so, its reciprocal e / p a measure of his fear (of ruin). Indifference means that
u(x) = p . O + ( 1 - p) . u(x + e). Hence, when e goes to zero, e / p goes to u ( x ) / u : ( x ) . Thus, the tax equals the fear of ruin at the net income, less a constant tax credit. EXAMPLE. We end this section with an example of an explicit calculation of tax policy. Let all agents t have the same utilities ut(x) = u(x) = x ~, where 0 < oe ~< 1. The fear o f ruin is then u(x)
x«
x
u1(x)
« x «-1
ot
lntegrating, we get C=
:ù~x>,,x, f~l/~ ~=-c~,+ 0 . . . . Œ
e,
o/
since fT e = fT X. Hence the tax et - xt is given by
et -- xt --
'(f~)
1 + o~
et --
e
;
this m a y be thought of as a uniform tax at the rate of 1/(1 + « ) , followed by an equal distribution of the proceeds among the whole population. Recalling that the exponent «
2192
J.-E Mertens
is an inverse measure of risk aversion, we conclude that the more risk averse the agents are, the larger the tax rate is. As a comment, recall that all estimates of coefficients of relative risk aversion are strongly negative - say ranging from « : - 2 to ot = - 1 5 (!) (cf., e.g., Drèze (1981)), wlth u t ( x ) -- x ~,e , and note the hmltmg result for ol = 0. This is clearly due to the enormous power attributed here to the majority: for o~ ~< 0, it can - and will under the above "optimal threats" - pur the minority effectively outside its consumption set. It might be interesting to investigate in this context (say « ' s distributed between - 15 and + 1) the implications of the traditional requirement that laws should be anonymous. For example, formulations of the sort: t's net tax T(yz, r) is a function only of his reported (i.e., not destroyed) endowment Yt (0 « Yt <~ et) and of the distribution r (in duality with the space of all Lipschitz functions of y) of those yt's such that: (a) budget balance always holds, (b) T is jointly continuous, monotone and with slope ~< 1 in y, (c) an increase in r in the sense of first-order stochastic dominance decreases Ty for all y and T(0, .), and (d) absence of "monetary illusion" - since the model satisfies it, - i.e., for )~ > 0, denoting by r z the image of r under y w+ Xy, one has T()~y, r ~) = ;~T(y, r). One might even want to add progressivity: (e) TyI >~ 0, or equivalently: consumption is concave in y; or still equivalently: tax is convex in consumption. And then the normal effect of an increased dispersion of r (second-order stochastic dominance) would also be to decrease T; for all y and T(0, .): more tax receipts becoming available, everyone and every marginal dollar should benefit from it. (Observe that the above tax policy, T ( y , r) = ~ 1 (y - ~), satisfies all those requirements.) The aim here is clearly not to have to play explicitly with ideas like a higher utility for society of individuals with a lower risk aversion, and still to exhibit some similar effect. And bopefully less than all the above requirements would be sufficient to determine the solution. •
c~f_
Œt
.
.
•
4. Public goods without exclusion The second purpose of taxation is the financing of public goods. As with redistribution, considering government as subject to the influence of its electors, rather than benevolently maximizing some social welfare function, sheds new light on the subject. As in Auman, Kurz and Neyman (1983, 1987), a Public Goods E c o n o m y is modeled by a continuum of agents, endowed with resources and voting rights, who take part in the production of non-exclusive public goods. More precisely, when a coalition forms, it chooses one strategy amongst the available, which together with the complementary coalition's choice determines the bundle of public goods that is produced. A natural question is the dependence of the outcome of the game on the distribution of voting rights, which should at first sight exert a major influence. But the Harsanyi-Shapley NTU Value leads to the surprising new and pessimistic result that the distribution of
Ch. 58: SomeOtherEconomicApplications of the Value
2193
voting rights has (little or) nothing to do with the choice. Aside from its proof, this result is reinforced by an economic argument based on the implicit pfice of a vote. A nonatomic public goods economy is modeled by the set of agents T = [0, 1], the space IR~+ of resources, and the public goods space IR~. There is a correspondence G from IR~+ to IRt~, representing the production function, which takes compact and nonempty values, ut • IR+ -+ IR is t's utility function, v is a nonatomic voting measure with v ( T ) = 1. Every agent has resources that can be used to produce public goods. The voting measure v is not necessarily identical to the population measure/z. For example, it is possible that noncitizens do not have the right to vote. A vote takes place and the majority decides which public good(s) will be produced. The minority is not entitled to produce public goods but, as in the previous model, it has the right to destroy its resources. The important point is that once the public good has been produced, the minority may not be excluded from consuming it. •
1//
THEOREM 1. In the voting garne, the value outcomes are independent o f the voting measure v.
Consider an example with two public goods, TV and libraries. There are two kinds of agents in two equally weighted sets: one kind is fond of TV programs, the other of books. Assume further that TV fans possess all the voting rights. Then one might expect that after the voting, TV programs will be the only available leisure. But as it happens, both TV and books will be available in equal amounts! Whatever the voting rights, the same bundle of public goods will be chosen. SKETCH OF PROOF. We first describe the Harsanyi-Shapley NTU value of a game, also used in Section 3. For a fixed weight function k, every coalition S announces a threat strategy zs that it will can'y out if negotiations with the complementary coalition T \ S fail. Together with T \ S ' s strategy, zs yields S a total payoff of V(S) = U(zs, z r \ s ) ( S ) . After these announcements, the players are in a fixed-threat TU garne, and its solution is taken to be the Shapley value. So each player wants the threats of the various coalitions of which he is a member to be chosen so as to maximize his own final payoff according to this Shapley value. This can be shown to imply that all members of any given coalition S unanimously want to maximize H ( S ) = V(S) - V ( T \ S). zg Since the same holds for T \ S, the optimal threat strategies z s and ZT\ s are the saddle points of the two-person zero-sum garne H ( S ) . Let q~(S) = U(z*s, Z~\s)(S) be the total payoff to S when both S and T \ S carry out their optimal threats. Define wx(S) = q~(S) - q x ( T \ S ) = H ( S ) ( z *S, Z~\s), * " thus w z ( S ) measures the "bargaining power" of S - its ability to threaten. Define also vA(S) = ½(wz (S) + wz (T)). As argued in the previous section, vz (S) is the total utility S can expect to result from an efficient compromise with T \ S. Observe that ~ovz = ~oqz (since the difference is a garne where every coalition gets the same as its complement), hut whereas qz might depend on the particular choices of optimal threats z s, • that is not so for vz. The function vz is the
2194
J.-F. M e r t e n s
Harsanyi coalitional form of the garne with weight function )~, and as before, we define a value allocation as a bundle y achieving the Harsanyi-Shapley NTU value, i.e., such that
~ovx(S) = f )~tut(Yt)tz(dt)
forevery S.
,IS
We know 1
(pv)(dt)
----
f0
[v(OT U dt)
-
v(OT)] dO.
We want to compare this expression for two different voting measures v and ~: 1
(~ov r - ~0v«)(dt) =
f0
[(v r - v~)(OT U dt) - (v v - v~)(OT)] dO.
We call a coalition S even if S is either a majority under both v and ~ or a minority under both v and ~. If S is even, so is T \ S and their strategic options are the same under v and ~, i.e., v r (S) - v ~ (S) = 0. Every peffect sample of the whole population OT is even - it is determined by its size. For OT U dt, it is even if 0 > ½ or 0 < ½ - 3 [with 3 = max(v(dt), ~(dt))]. The previous difference thus amounts to: I
(q)v r -- q)v«)(dt) = j l 2-~ [ (v r - v~)(OT V dt)] d0 l
lf~ [(wr 2 -a
w~)(OTUdt)]dO.
If w r (0 T U dt) is achieved at the outcome y, then, by additivity of the integral, and homogeneity:
wV(OT Udt) = HY(OT Udt) = UY(OT) q- 2UY(dt) - UY((1 - O)T) = (20 - 1)UY(T) -t- 2)~tut(Yt)Iz(dt). Now 20 - 1 as well as b~(dt) are infinitesimal. Independently of the voting measure v, we have shown that in the relevant fange (0 6 [1 __ & ½]), wr (0 T U dt) is infinitesimal: the idea is that, under those circumstances, both the coalition and its complement resemble ½T, thus are close to each other, and whatever the outcome, they enjoy the same utility derived from the common consumption of the same public good. Nobody enjoys a real bargaining advantage, and the efficient compromise induced by the Shapley value leads to equal treatment.
Ch. 58:
Some Other Economic Applications of the Value
Going back to more technical arguments, assume all t. Then UY ( T ) <~
2195
ut(y) <~K
for all feasible y and
K f z,~(dt).
Given any coalition S, and 3 > 0, partition S into Sl U - . . U Sn, with and n ~< 2/3. Then we obtain
(v + ~)(Si) <~3,
~ov~(S) - ~0v~(S)
= -~ } 2
_~ 2o- l)(VY:(r~-vY~,(r~)+2[«,,)~r(u,(y[)-ut(y~i))iz(dt) dO
i=1 I
~< ~1 . n -
f7
( 2 0 - 1) dO • (2K)
f
)~,#(dt) +
1.4KSJs)~tlz(dt)
<~2K~[fr)~t#(dt)+fs)~ttx(dt)]<~4K~f )~tl~(dt). This being true for all 3, we obtain q)v~(S) = q)v~(S). This being true for any weight function )~, the result follows.
[]
Though counterintuitive, this result might have been guessed from a similar analysis conducted in a transferable-utility (TU) context: we allow agents to trade their votes for money. The outcome of such a TU garne consists of a public goods vector and a sidepayment vector. In the book vs. TV garne, it can easily be derived from the following conditions: (1) It is Pareto-optimal. (2) Under sensible assumptions, the only Pareto-optimal situation involves a production of (½, ½) with the accompanying schedule of side-payments from book fans to TV fans. (3) To have this outcome approved, as book fans need only 50% of the vote and thus can play TV fans oft against each other, they drive the price of a vote down to zero and can achieve the desired outcome without effective payments. In the case of non-exclusive public goods, every agent endowed with a voting right is potentially a free-rider: he believes his personal vote not to influence the final outcome, which he may like dr dislike, and is thus ready to sell it even at a low price. This is wrong in the case of redistribution dr more generally of exclusive public goods, where, as here, voting is assumed not to be secret, and the identity of the voters is crucial in eventually determining everyone's payoff. To conclude this section, we stress the connection between the TU and NTU situations: the TU garnes that we obtain corresponding to the latter are similarly public good economies, but in addition have a single desirable private good available for transfers.
2196
J.-E Mertens
5. Economies with fixed prices 5.1. Introduction In economies with fixed prices all trading must take place at exogenously given prices, which determine (together with the positive orthant) a new consumption set - the net trade set - for each trader. This model has been used to describe market failures such as unemployment. In general, pfice rigidities prevent market clearance: a trader's consumption set is exogenous and, under the standard assumptions, his utility functiou has an absolute maximum, a satiation point, generally in the interior of the consumptiou set; it may be the case that for any price vector, at least orte of the traders' utility functions is satiated; this trader uses less than the maximum budget available to hirn, creatiug a total budget excess. EXAMPLE. Consider a fixed-price exchange economy with one commodity and two traders. Let their net trade sets be X1 = X2 = [ - 5 , +5] and their utility functions Ul (x) = - ( x - 1) 2 and u2(x) = - ( x + 2) 2. Since the satiation points are respectively 1 and - 2 , if p > 0 then x~ = 0 and x~ = - 2 . Hence, the market does not clear. Similarly ifp < 0 orifp =0. This suggests a generalization of the equilibrium concept in the general class of markets with satiation: the total budget excess is divided among all the traders, as dividends, so that supply matches demand. However, Drèze and Müller (1980) extended the First Theorem of Welfare Economics to this equilibrium concept, proving it to be too broad: with appropriate dividends, one can obtain any Pareto-optimum. In this respect, the Shapley value leads to more specific results (Aumann and Drèze, 1986): the income allocated to a trader depends only and monotonically on his trading opportunities and not on his utility function! This will be formally stated in Section 5.4, which includes a sketch of the proof. A formulation in the particular context of fixedprice economies will then be presented.
5.2. Dividend equilibria Define a market with satiation as M ~ = (T; ~; (Xt)teT; (Ut)tcT), where T = {1 . . . . . k} is a finite set of traders, R e is the space of commodities, Xt C 1Re is trader t's net trade set, supposed to be compact, convex, with nonempty interior and containing 0, and uf is trader t's utility function, assumed concave and continuous on Xt. A price vector is any element in ]Re. Let Bt = {x ~ Xt [ ut(x) = maxycx, ut(y)} be the set of satiation points of trader t. Bt is nonempty, i.e., every trader has at least one satiation point. For simplicity, traders such that 0 6 Bt may be taken out of the economy. They are fully satisfied with their initial endowment. Thus we will suppose that Vt, 0 ~ Bt. An allocation is a vector x e 1-Irrt Xt such that ~ t c r xt = 0.
Ch. 58: SomeOther EconomicApplications of the Value
2197
As noted above, competitive equilibria m a y fail to exist since, whatever the price vector, a trader m a y well refuse to make use of his entire budget, thus preventing the market from clearing. The idea of dividends is to let the other traders use the excess budget. A dividend is a vector c ~ IRk. A dividend equilibrium is a triple constituted of a price q, a dividend c and an allocation x such that, for all t, xt maximizes ut(x) on Xt subject to q • x ~ ct.
5.3. Value allocations This is the "finite" version of the definition in Section 2. A comparison vector is a non-zero vector )~ ~ IR~+. For each )~ and each coalition S C T, the worth of S according to )~ is
vz(S)=max{~)~tut(xt) " tES
s.t. Z x t tES
= O a n d Y t ¢ S, xt e X t } ;
vz(S) is the m a x i m u m total utility that coalition S can get by internal redistribution when its members have weights )~t. An allocation is called a value allocation if there exists a comparison vector )~ such that )~tut(xt) = ~0vx(t) for all t, where 9vx is the Shapley value of the garne vx.
5.4. The main result M n, the n-fold replica of market M 1, is the market with satiation where every agent of M 1 has n twins. Formally stated: • T~ = Ui~T Tin (the set o f n k traders). • Vi 6 T, [T/n ] = n (there are n traders of type i). • Y t e T F, u t = u i a n d X t = X i . ELBOW ROOM ASSUMPTION. For all J C {1 . . . . . k},
0~
bdZ + S:~'] I i c j Bi i~J .a
In words, if it is possible to satiate all traders in some J simultaneously, then it is also possible to do so when they are restricted to the relative interior of their satiation sets, and the others to that of their net trade sets. Note that since the right-hand side is the boundary of a convex subset of R e, its dimension is at most (g - 1). Since the possible J are finite in number, the assumption holds for all hut an (g - 1)-dimensional set of total endowments. In that respect, it is generic. An allocation ~ of M n is an equal treatment allocation if traders of the same type are assigned the same net trade. Trivially, there is then an associated allocation x of M l .
2198
J.-E Mertens
THEOREM 2. Consider a sequence (Xn)nei~ where x n is an allocation corresponding to an equal treatment value allocation in M n. Let x ~ be a limit o f a subsequence o f (xn)n eN. Then, there is a dividend (vector) c and a price vector q such that (q , c, x co) is a dividend equilibrium where • c is nonnegative, i.e., Vi, ci >/0 • c is monotonic, i.e., Vi, Xi C X j ~ ci <~c j .
What gives substance to the theorem is the following existence result. PROPOSITION 3. There exists an equal treatment value allocation f o r every M n. SKETCH OF PROOF OF THEOREM 2. This sketch is very informal. To make things simpler, suppose that: • ~ i )C = 1 (normalizaUon); • Vi, x~ and ~7 converge; • Vi, x n and x ~ are in int(Xit); • Vi, ui is strictly concave and confinuously differenfiable on Xi. Call those types i for which limn~c~ )~tiz= 0 lightweight, the rest heavyweight. Suppose that the weights of all the lightweight types converge to 0 at the same speed. We have
v(i,:), vn, ~;u',(xT)= ~~u)(x~)(=:qO). In the limit, 'v'(i,
j), )~C~u~i (x~) = L j~ u j' ( x T ) ( = : C a ) .
Now consider the contribution of a trader to a coalition S. If S is "large enough", it is very likely to be a good sample of the population T ~ . Thus an optimal allocation for S is approximately the optimal x n for T n . The first term of the new trader's contribution is what he gets for himself. Since he does not change the optimal allocation by rauch, this is )~~ui (x~). The second term is his influence on the other traders' ufilities. Since the net trade must equal zero and all gradients are equal, this is approximately _ q n . xin. Thus, the contribution is approximately A = )nUi (Xn) __ q n . Xn" If S is "small", the previous considerations do not hold. However, a new trader's contribution to a (small) coalition is uniformly bounded. This follows, e.g., frorn the continuous differentiability of the utilities on the compact net trade sets. Moreover, the probability P" of S being a small coalition goes to zero as n goes to infinity. Denote by 8 ] the expected contribution of a trader t of type i conditional on the coalition being small. Now we have (very roughly): ~ov~(t) ~ (1 - P " ) a + pn~n.
Ch. 58." Some Other Economic Applications of the Value
2199
/ t'tx Since ~pv~(t) = ~~i/ ' t u i~xi ) we have:
)~nui (xn) ~ (1 - p~)A + P~,S7. Hence, et/
qn . xi,~ ~ _ _-1 p n ( 8n - "knui (xn))"
(3)
Note that Pn / ( 1 - p n ) --+ O. Suppose there is no lightweight type. If simultaneous satiation of all traders is possible, then this is the Shapley value for all sufficiently large n, since then X~ > 0 for all i. It is clear that the theorem holds then, for any price system q, and ci = C sufficiently large. Otherwise, u iI ( x m i ) 7~ 0 for at least some i. Hence, because of the equality of the gradients, u'. ( x ~ ) 5~ 0 for all j. Hence q m ~ 0 and for all i, the gradient of ui at J J x m is in the direction of qm. Going to the limit in (3) gives q m . xÜ = 0. Hence, x ~ maximizes u i ( x ) on X i subject to q m . x ~< 0. Hence, it is an ordinary competitive equilibrium and trivially a dividend equilibrium. Suppose now that type i is lightweight. We have q m = 0. Hence uj' (xjm) = 0 for any heavyweight type j; that is to say, x ~ satiates j. Before letting n go to infinity, divide equality (3) by I]q~ Il. We shall see that 3's order of magnitude is greater than that of )~n. i ui ~xn~ t i ~" Assume, for simplicity, that the sequence qn/[[qn ]] converges to some point q. We get:
pH q . x ~ = lim (6~ n-~m (1--Pn)l]qn Il
-- )~i
Ui(Xi ))"
Denote this quantity ci. If u I ( x ~ ) --= 0, then x~c maximizes ui over X i . Hence it maximizes ui over {x E X i , q • x <~ ci}. The same holds if u i' ( x ~ ) 7~ 0, because then q is in the direction of !
oo
Ui(X i ). We claim that ci is nonnegative, depends monotonically on Xi, and not at all on ui. A lightweight trader t's joining a "small" coalition S contributes to three utilities: (i) his own, (ii) that of other lightweight traders, and (iii) that of heavyweight traders. Roughly (again), since we are considering a small coalition, the heavyweight träders are probably not all simultaneously satiated. Since the weights in (i) and (ii) tend to zero when n becomes large, when trader t joins the coalition, his resources are best used if distributed to unsatiated heavyweight traders. His ability to give his resources depends only and monotonically on Xt, and not on ut. Though the optimal redistribution of t's resources may involve several heavyweight traders, giving it all to only one trader gives a lower bound to (iii): 67 is of larger order than )n. This establishes our claim about ci.
J.-E Mertens
2200
If trader t is h e a v y w e i g h t , contributions (i) and (ii) in ~~' are at least c a n c e l l e d out by )~n i u i~(xn'~ i j ' since ) ~ ~ u i ( x ~ ) is the m o s t t can ger. Thus, the rest of the a r g u m e n t is as b e f o r e with q ' x / ~ <~ n
[ c o m p o n e n t (iii) of 3]
and ci defined as the right side o f this inequality. Since i is h e a v y w e i g h t , x ~ satiates. B y the a b o v e inequality, it also satisfies the budget constraint. []
5.5. Concluding remarks A question eluded until n o w is: " W h a t about the core in an e c o n o m y that allows satiation?" R e m e m b e r that an allocation is in the core if it cannot be i m p r o v e d u p o n by any coalition. This can be understood either in a strong or a w e a k way. T h e strong version requires that no " w e a k i m p r o v e m e n t " is possible. That is to say that it is not possible that s o m e m e m b e r s are strictly better oft w h i l e others are not worse oft. With this definition the C o r e E q u i v a l e n c e T h e o r e m for replica e c o n o m i e s applies. A n d since the set of c o m p e t i t i v e equilibria m a y be empty, the s a m e holds for the core. O n the other hand, the " w e a k " core m a y be too large and not e v e n enjoy the equal treatment property. Either way, the core does not yield m u c h insight into these e c o n o m i e s .
References Arrow, K.J., and M. Kurz (1970), Public Investment, the Rate of Return, and Optimal Fiscal Policy (Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD). Aumann, RJ. (1964), "Markets with a continnum of traders", Econometrica 32:39-50. Aumann, RJ. (1975), "Values of markets with a continuum of traders", Econometrica 43:611-646. Aumann, R.J., and J.H. Drèze (1986), "Values of markets with satiation or fixed prices", Econometrica 54:1271-1318. Aumann, R.J., and M. Kurz (1977a), "Power and taxes", Econometrica 45:1137-1161. Aumann, R.J., and M. Kurz (1977b), "Power and taxes in a multi-commodity economy", Israel Journal of Mathematics 27:186-234. Aumann, R.J., M. Kurz and A. Neyman (1983), "Voting for pnblic goods", Review of Economic Studies 50:677~693. Aumann, R.J., M. Kurz and A. Neyman (1987), "Power and public goods", Journal of Economic Theory 42:108-127. Champsaur, E (1975), "Cooperation versus competition", Journal of Economic Theory 11:394-417. Drèze, J.H. (1981), "Inferring risk tolerance from deductibles in insurance contracts", The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance 20:48-52. Drèze, J.H., and H. Müller (1980), "Optimality properties of rationing schemes", Journal of Economic Theory 23:150-159. Harsanyi, J.C. (1959), "A bargaining model for the cooperative n-person game", in: A.W. Tncker and R.D. Luce, eds., Contributions to the Theory of Games IV, Ann. of Math. Smdies 40 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ) 325-355.
Ch. 58:
Some Other Economic Applications of the Value
2201
Mertens, J.-E, and S. Soiln (eds.) (1994), Game-Theoretic Methods in General Equilibrium Analysis, Vol. 77 of NATO ASI Seiles - Seiles D: Behaviottral and Social Sciences (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht). Nash, J.E (1953), "Two-person cooperative garnes", Econometrica 21:128-140. Shapley, L.S. (1953), "A Value for n-person games", in: H.W. Ktthn and A.W. Tucker, eds., Contilbutions to the Theory of Garnes II, Ann. of Math. Studies 28 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ) 307-317. Shapley, L.S. (1969), "Utility comparisons and the theory of garnes", in: La Décision (Editions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS), Paris) 251-263.
Chapter 59
STRATEGIC ASPECTS OF POLITICAL SYSTEMS JEFFREY S. BANKS*
Division of Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA, USA
Contents
1. Introduction 2. The cooperative approach 3. Sophisticated voting and agendas 4. The spatial environment 5. Incomplete information References
2205 2205 2207 2214 2220 2227
*Deceased December 21, 2000. The editors are grateful to David Austen-Smith and Richard McKelvey, who saw the manuscript through the rinal stages of the production process. It was evident from Jeff's marginal notes that he had intended to add material to the introductory section. However, since the paper seemed otherwise complete, it was decided not to alter the manuscript from the stare that Jeff left it in.
Handbook of Game Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2204
J.S. Banks
Abstract
Early results on the emptiness of the core and the majority-rule-chaos results led to the recognition of the importance of modeling instimtional details in political processes. A sample of the literature on game-theoretic models of political phenomena that ensued is presented. In the case of sophisticated voting over certain kinds of binary agendas, such as might occur in a legislative setting, equilibria exist and can be nicely characterized. Endogenous choice of the agenda can sometimes yield "sophisticated sincerity", where equilibrium voting behavior is indistinguishable from sincere voting. Under some conditions there exist agenda-independent outcomes. Various kinds of "structureinduced equilibria" are also discussed. Finally, the effect of various types of incomplete information is considered. Incomplete information of how the voters will behave leads to probabilistic voting models that typically yield utilitarian outcomes. Uncertainty among the voters over which is the preferred outcome yields the pivotal voting phenomenon, in which voters can glean information from the fact that they are pivotal. The implications of this phenomenon are illustrated by results on the Condorcet Jury problem, where voters have common interests but different information.
Keywords voting, political theory, social choice, asymmetric information
JEL classification: DT1, D72, D82, C70
Ch. 59:
StrategicAspects of Political Systems
2205
1. Introduction In this paper I review a small, selective sample of the existing literature on gametheoretic models of political phenomena. Let X denote a set of outcomes, and N = { 1, . . . , n} a finite set of voters, with n ~> 2 and with each i • N having a binary preference relation Ri o n X. In what follows we consider two separate environments: (1) the finite environment, where X is finite and, for all i • N , Ri is a weak order; and (2) the spatial environment, where X C 8~k is compact and convex and each Ri is a continuous and strictly convex weak order. 1 In either case let T~n denote the set of admissible preference profiles, with c o m m o n element p.
2. The cooperative approach One popular approach to collective decision-making is to suppress any explicit behavioral theory and model the interaction as a simple cooperative garne with ordinal preferences. Thus let 79 C 2 N denote the set of decisive or winning coalitions, required to be non-empty, monotonic (C • 79 and C c C ~ implies C ' • D) and proper (C • 79 implies N \ C ~ :D). The (strict) social preference relation of D at p is defined as xPT?(p)y
iff
SC • 7P s.t. x P i y 'v'i • C,
and the core of 79 at p is C(D, p) = {x • X: ~y • X s.t. y P D ( p ) x } . Results on the possible emptiness of the majority-rule core have been known for some time. For instance, in the finite environment Condorcet (1785) constructed his famous three-person, three-alternative "paradox": x Pl Y P1 z, y P2 z P2 x , z P3x ['3 Y. In the spatial environment, as convex preferences are single-peaked we know from Black (1958) that the majority-rule core will be non-empty in one dimension; however as Figure 1 demonstrates it is easy to construct three-person, two-dimensional examples where the core is empty. In this example individuals' preferences are "Euclidean": for all x, y • X , x Ri y if and only if IIx - x ~II ~< Ily - x i [I, where x i is i ' s ideal point. These results are generalized to arbitrary simple rules by reference to the rule's Nakamura number, O(D), which is equal to ex) i f t h e rule is collegial, i.e., ["]ceT) C 7~ 0, and is otherwise equal to
CE'D'
1 Theseassumptions on preferences are stronger than necessary for some of the results below; however they facilitate comparisons across a variety of models.
2206
J.S. Banks
X1
I X3
0X2 Figure 1.
In words, the Nakamura number of a non-collegial simple rule D is the number of coalitions in the smallest non-collegial subfamily of D. For non-collegial rules this number ranges from a low of three (e.g., majority rule with n odd) to a high of n (e.g., a quota rule with q = n - 1). Part (a) of the following is due to Nakamura (1979), while part (b) is due to Schofield (1983) and Strnad (1985): PROPOSITION 1.
(a) In the finite environment, C(D, p) ¢ 13for all p ~ 7~" if and only if [XI < ~(D). (b) In the spatial environment, C(D, p) ~ 0 for all p ~ R n if and only if
k < ~(D) - 1. Thus, for any simple rule one can identify, for both the finite and the spatial environment, a critical number such that core non-emptiness is only guaranteed when the number of alternatives or the dimension of the policy space is below this number. As a corollary, we see that if the number of alternatives is at least n, or the dimension of the
Ch. 59: StrategicAspects of Political Systems
2207
policy space at least n - 1, then for any non-collegial rule the core will be empty for some profile of preferences. Furthermore, generalizing the logic of the Plott (1967) conditions for a majority-rule core point, one can identify a second critical number (necessarily larger than the first) for non-collegial simple rules in the spatial model with the following property: assuming individual preferences are in addition representable by smooth utility functions, if the dimension of the policy space is above this second number the core will "almost always" be empty. Specifically, the set of utility profiles for which the core is empty will be open and dense in the Whitney C ~ topology on the space of smooth utility profiles [Schofield (1984), Banks (1995), Saari (1997)]. Therefore core non-emptiness for noncollegial simple rules will be quite tenuous in high-dimensional policy spaces. Finally, McKelvey (1979) showed that when the core of a strong (C ~ 7? implies N \ C E 77) simple rule is empty, the strict social preference relation PT)(P) is extremely badly behaved, in the following sense: given any two alternatives x, y c X there exists a finite set of alternatives {al . . . . . am} such that xPT)(p)al PD(p)a2PT~(P)... PT~(p)amPT~(P)y. That is, one can get from any one alternative to any other, and back again, via the strict social preference relation. 2 It is difficult to overstate the impact these "chaos" theorems have had on the formal modeling of politics. Most importantly for this paper, the theorems gave rise to a newfound appreciation for political institutions such as committee systems, restrictive voting rules, etc. The theorems implied that additional strncture was required on the collective decision-making process so as to generate a well-posed, i.e., equilibrium, model. These institutional features then became the foundation of or the motivation for various non-cooperative garne forms used to study specific political phenomena. In what follows we will examine a set of these garne forms in depth, maintaining for the most part a focus on majority rule. Further, given the intrinsic appeal of majority-rule core points when they exist, we will inquire as to whether a game form is "Condorcet consistent"; that is, do the equilibrium outcomes correspond to majority-rnle core points when the latter exist?
3. Sophisticated voting and agendas Consider the finite environment, where we make the additional assumptions that each individual's preference relation is a linear order, thereby ruling out individual indifference; and that n is odd. Together these imply that the strict majority preference relation is complete (although of course not necessarily transitive), and therefore that any majority-rule core alternative is unique and is strictly majority-preferred to any other alternative, i.e., it is a "Condorcet winner". 2 An analogous result holds for non-strong rules when the strict social preference relation is replaced with the weak social preference relation [Austen-Smithand Banks (1999)]. One implication of this is that, when the core is empty, the transitive closure of the weak social preference relation exhibits universal indifference.
J.S. Banks
2208
x~ ~ w
z
(a)
x w z wy
wz
w
(b) Figure 2.
We consider sequential voting methods for selecting a unique outcome from X. Specifically, the voting procedures we examine can be characterized as occurring on a binary voting tree F = ( A , Q, O) having many features in common with an extensive form garne of perfect information: A is a finite set of nodes, and Q is a precedence relation on A generating a unique initial node L1 as well as a unique path between all ;% ;C E A for which ;~Q;C. The precedence relation Q partitions A into decision nodes A d and terminal nodes A t, where A t = {)~ E A: )~~Q)~ for no )C E A} and A d = A \ A t . The qualifier "binary" implies that each decision node )~ E .A d has precisely two nodes immediately following it, l 0~) and r ()~) (for "lefl" and "right", respectively), and decision nodes characterize instances when a majority rote is taken over which of these two nodes to move. Finally, the funcfion 0 : A t -+ X assigns to each terminal hode exactly one of the alternatives; we require 0 to be onto, so that each element of X is the selected outcome for some sequence of majority decisions. Figure 2 gives two examples of vofing trees. Given a vofing tree F , a strategy for any i E N is a decision rule ai : A d - + {l, r} describing how i rotes at each decision hode. A profile of strategies a = (al . . . . . an) then determines a unique sequence of majority-rule decisions through the vofing tree, ulfimately leading to a parficular terminal hode )~(a) E .At, and hence an outcome O(L(a)) E X . Thus for any profile of preferences p we have a well-defined (ordinal) non-cooperative garne. "Sophisticated" vofing strategies are generated by iteratively deleting weakly dominated strategies [Farquharson (1969)], which can be characterized as follows [McKelvey and Niemi (1978), Gretlein (1983)]: (1) at all finäl decision nodes (i.e., those only followed by terminal nodes) individual i rotes for her preferred alternative among those associated with the subsequent two terminal nodes (note that this consfitutes the unique undominated Nash equilibrium in the subgame); (2) at penultimate decision nodes i votes for her preferred alternative from those derived from (1), given common knowledge of preferences; and so on, back up the voting tree. This process, which is equivalent to simply applying the majority preference relation P (p) via backwards inducfion to F , can be characterized formally by associating with each node )~ C .A its sophisticated equivalent s(;~) E X , which is the outcome that will ultimately
Ch. 59: StrategicAspectsof PoliticalSystems
2209
be selected if node )~ is reached. The mapping s(.) is defined inductively by: (a) for all )~ c A t, s(;.) = 0()0, (b) for all ;~ c A d, s 0 0 = s(I()~)) if s(lOO)P(p)s(rO~)) and s()0 = s (r ()0) otherwise. This process leads to a unique outcome s (L~), referred to as the sophisticated voting outcome (although the strategies generating s ()~1) need not be unique since for some )~ it may be that l()~) = r(k)). The outcome s(kl) obviously depends on the voting tree F ; however it depends on the preference profle p only through the majority preference relation, P(p), and so we denote the sophisticated voting outcome associated with F and P as s(F, P). Finally, we know from McGarvey (1953) that for any complete and asymmetric relation P on X there exists a value of n and a profile of linear orders p such that P is the majority preference relation associated with (n, p). Since these parameters are here unrestricted, spanning over all complete and asymmetric relations P on X is equivalent to spanning over all (n, p). The qualifier "sophisticated" is meant to contrast such behavior with "sincere" voting, in which branches are labeled with alternatives and at each decision node voters simply select the branch associated with the more preferred alternative. For instance, let X = {w, x, y, z} and n = 3, with preferences given by zPlxPlYP1 w, wP2zP2xP2y, Y P3w P3zP3x, and consider the subgame in Figure 2(b) beginning at node )~. S incere voting would require 1 to vote for z over y; however, since w will majority-defeat z if z is selected at )~, y will defeat w if y is selected at )~, and yPlw, l's sophisticated strategy is to vote for y at k. On the other hand, both 2's and 3's sophisticated strategy prescribes voting sincerely at k. It is evident that the specifics of the voting tree play an important role in the determination of the sophisticated voting outcome; for instance, x is the outcome in Figure 2(a) but y is the outcome in Figure 2(b) given the above preference profile. For any majority preference relation P define V(P) = {x ~ X: 3F s.t. x = s(F, P)} as the set of alternatives which are the sophisticated voting outcome for some binary voting game, and consider the following definition of the top cycle set:
T(P)={xcX:
VyCx~X,
3{al . . . . . ar}C_Xs.t.
al = x , ar = y , andVt c {1 . . . . . r -
1}, atPat+l}.
In words, x is in the top cycle set if and only if we can get from x to every other alternative via the majority preference relation P. If x is a Condorcet winner then it is easily seen that T(P) = {x}. Otherwise T(P) contains at least three elements, and can in general include Pareto-dominated alternatives; for instance, in the above example T(P) = X, but zPix for all i ~ N. McKelvey and Niemi (1978) prove that for all P, V (P) c_ T(P), while Moulin (1986) proves that for all P, T(P) c_ V(P). Taken together we therefore have, PROPOSITION 2. Forall P, V(P) = T(P). Thus all binary voting procedures are Condorcet consistent, and so if P admits a Condorcet winner then the equilibrium outcome will be independent of the voting pro-
2210
J.S. Banks
cedure in place. Conversely, in the absence of a Condorcet winner the voting procedure itself will play some role in determining the collective outcome, where at times these outcomes can be inefficient. Much of the work on voting procedures and agendas has focused on the amendment voting procedure of which the garne in Figure 2(b) is an example. Thus two alternatives are put to a vote; the winner is then paired with a new alternative, and so on. This procedure is attractive for a number of reasons, not the least of whieh is that it is consistent with the rules of the US Congress governing the perfecting of a bill through a series of amendments to the bill (i.e., Roberts' Rules of Order). An amendment procedure is characterized by an oi-dering of X or agenda « : {1 . . . . . m} --* X, where the first vote is between o~(1) and «(2), the winner then faces c¢(3), etc. Let F« denote the voting garne associated with the agenda c¢, and let A ( P ) = {x ~ X: 3o~ s.t. x = s(F«, P)} denote the set of sophisticated voting outcomes when restricting attention to amendment procedures. Building on the work of Miller (1980) and Shepsle and Weingast (1984), Banks (1985) provides the following characterization of the set A(P): ler T ( P ) = {Y c X: P is transitive on Y} be those subsets of alternatives for which the majority preference relation is transitive, and g ( P ) =- {Y c_ X: Vz ~ Y ~y c Y s.t. y P z } be those subsets of alternatives for which every non-member of the set is majority-defeated by some member of the set. If P is transitive on the set Y then there will exist a unique P-maximal element of Y; label this alternative ra(Y) and define B ( P ) = {x ~ X: x = ra(Y) for some Y e Œ(P) N g(P)}. Note that (i) for all P, B ( P ) c_ T(P); (ii) as with T ( P ) , if a Condorcet winner exists B ( P ) will coincide with this alternative, and otherwise consist of at least three elements; and (iii) in contrast to T ( P ) any x ~ B ( P ) cannot be Pareto-dominated by any other alternative. 3 For instance, in the above example B ( P ) = {y, z, w }, excluding the Pareto-dominated alternative x. PROPOSITION 3. For all P, A ( P ) = B(P). Therefore the amendment procedure always generates Pareto-efficient outcomes. On the other hand, in the absence of a Condorcet winner there remains a sensitivity of this outcome to the particular agenda employed. Two theoretical conclusions naturally arise at this level of the analysis. The first is that we should at times observe individuals voting against their "myopic" best interests, as voter 1 does in the above example. The second is that in the absence of a Condorcet winner there will be a diversity of induced preferences over the set of possible agendas; therefore to the extent the agenda is itself endogenously determined we have merely pushed the collective decision problem back one step (albeit limiting the relevant set of alternatives to A ( P ) ) . We consider each of these conclusions in turn.
3 If z P i x for all i e N then z P y for all y such that x P y by the transitivity of individuals' preferences; so if x = ra(Y) for some Y ~ "T(P) then Y ~ E ( P ) .
Ch. 59: StrategicAspects of Political Systems
2211
With respect to "insincere" behavior, consider the spatial environment, with preference profile p for which the rnajority-mle core is empty, and suppose that m ~< n alternatives from X are selected to make up an amendment procedure in the following manner: initially voter m selects an alternative x • X to be o~(m), i.e., the last alternative to be considered; then voter m - 1, with knowledge of «(m), selects o~(m - 1), etc., with voter 1 selecting ot(1). A proposal strategy for i ~< m is thus of the form 7ri "X (m-i) ~ X ; given a profile of proposal strategies :r = (Tr 1 . . . . . yt'm) let x(7r) = («(1; Jr) . . . . . «(m; :r)) denote the resulting amendment agenda. An equilibrium is then defined as (a) sophisticated voting strategies over any set of m alternatives from X, and (b) subgame perfect proposal strategies for all i ~< m. Finally, recall that for amendment procedures each hode )~ • A d is a vote between alternatives of(j) and «(k), for some j, k ~< m, and hence sincere voting is well-defined. Austen-Smith (1987) proves the following. PROPOSITION 4. In any equilibrium the proposal strategies re* are such that all individuals vote sincerely on x(7r*). Therefore when the alternatives on the agenda are endogenously chosen, we have "sophisticated sincerity" as the equilibrium voting behavior of the individuals will be indistinguishable from sincere voting. In particular, observing sincere voting is not inconsistent with sophisticated voting; rather, the evidence of sophisticated voting will be much more indirect, with its influence felt through the proposals that make up the agenda. With respect to the endogenous choice of agenda for a fixed set of altematives, suppose there exists a "status quo" alternative which must be considered last in the agenda. For instance, after various amendments to a bill have been considered and either adopted or rejected, the bill in its final form is voted on against the status quo of "no change" in the policy. Let Xo 6 X denote this status quo policy, and let A(Xo) denote the set of agendas with oe(m) = Xo, Finally, say that x • X is an agenda-independent outcome under the amendment procedure if x = s(F~, P) for all « • ,A(Xo). The presence of an agenda-independent outcome would obviously extinguish any conflict over the choice of agenda. Orte possibility of course is that Xo itself is an agenda-independent outcome, which only occurs when Xo is a Condorcet winner. Alternatively, consider the following condition: Condition C:
Bx • X s.t.
(i) x Pxo, and (ii) x Py Vy # x s.t. y Pxo.
To see that this is sufficient for agenda independence, note that an amendment procedure generates a particular form of assignment 0 of terminal nodes to alternatives; for instance, in Figure 2(b) each of x, y, and z are paired with the final alternative w at least once, and all final pairings involve w. This is a general feature of amendment
2212
J.S. Banks
procedures, so consider the voting garne formed by replacing each final decision node k 6 F« with the majority-preferred alternative among its two immediate successors, s (k). Label this voting garne F~ (P), and note that the alternatives in this garne, denoted X ~, are given by any y E X for which y P x o , along with possibly Xo itself (if x o P z for some z E X). Now if there exists an alternative x* ~ X ~ which is majority-preferred to all others in X ~ (i.e., x* is a Condorcet winner in X'), then applying Proposition 2 we have that x* = s ( F ~ ( P ) , P) regardless of the structure of the voting game F ~ ( P ) , in particular regardless of the ordering « ~ .A(xo). But then x* is an agenda-independent outcome. As an example of an environment where Condition C holds, consider the following classic model of distributive politics, which we label DP [Ferejohn et al. (1987)]: each i E N is the sole representative from district i in a legislature, and district i has associated with it a project that would generate political benefits and costs of bi > 0 and ci > 0, respectively. Assume ci =Bcj for all i, j E N, and assume without loss of generality that Cl < c2 < ... < cn. The problem before the legislature is to decide which (if any) of the projects to fund; thus an outcome is a vector x = (xl . . . . . xn) ~ {0, 1}t7 = X, where xi = 1 denotes funding t h e / t h project and xi = 0 denotes rejection. For any x E X let F ( x ) c_ N denote the projects that are funded. If project i is funded the benefits accrue solely to legislator i, whereas the costs are divided equally among all the legislators; if project i is rejected, legislator i receives zero benefits but still taust bear her share of the costs of any funded projects. Thus the utility for legislator i derived from any outcome x 6 X can be written
Z;=I
Ui (X) = b i x i
cjxj
Define x a E X by F ( x a) = {i E N: i «. (n + 1)/2} and assume that for all i E F ( x a ) , ui (x a) > 0; that is, the least-cost majority of projects generates a strictly positive utility for those legislators receiving projects. Finally, let the status quo alternative be Xo = (0 . . . . . 0), i.e., no project is funded. PROPOSITION 5. procedure.
x a
is the agenda-independent outcome in D P under the amendment
To see this, note first that for an alternative x to be majority-preferred to Xo it must be that F (x) > n/2, for otherwise a majority of legislators are receiving zero benefits while bearing positive costs, thereby generating a utility strictly less than zero. Second, among those alternatives with F ( x ) > n / 2 there is one alternative that is majority-preferred to all others, namely x a. This follows since for any x ~ x a such that F ( x ) > n / 2 , all i 6 {1 . . . . . (n + 1)/2} taust be bearing a strictly higher cost (since project cost is increasing in the index) while receiving no higher benefit (either xi = 1 and i receives the same benefit or else xi = 0 and i receives a strictly lower benefit). Therefore the majority coalition of {1 . . . . . (n + 1)/2} prefers x a to any other outcome which has a
Ch. 59:
2213
Strategic Aspects of Political Systems
3,1,2
3,1
3,2
3
1,2
1
2
0
Figure 3.
majority of projects funded, and since ui (Xa) > 0 for all members of this coalition x a is majority-preferred to Xo as well. Therefore Condition C holds, with x a the agendaindependent outcome. Notice that for this problem there exists another voting procedure which might actually seem more natural, namely, where each project is considered one at a time, and accepted or rejected according to a majority vote. Such a procedure would again generate an outcome x ~ {0, 1 }n, although the procedure would look quite different from the amendment procedure. For instance, suppose n = 3, and the projects are considered in the order 3, 1, 2; then the binary voting tree would look as in Figure 3 (where for simplicity we list F ( x ) rather than x). Using the above utilities we can compute the sophisticated voting strategies: at each of the four final decision nodes the coalition {1, 3} prefers not to fund project 2, so this project is defeated regardless of the previous votes. Given this, the coalition {2, 3} prefers not to fund project 1 at the two penultimate nodes, and similarly the coalition {1, 2} prefers not to fund project 3 at the initial node. Therefore the sophisticated voting outcome is that n o n e of the three projects is funded. Furthermore, this logic is independent of the order in which the projects are considered, and immediately extends to the n-project environment. Therefore, the outcome under the "project-by-project" voting procedure is invariably the status quo Xo = (0 . . . . . 0). We can generalize from this example and create a different form of agenda independence for the special case where the outcome set X is of the form X = {0, 1}k, with the interpretation being that xi = 1 signifies acceptance of issue i and xi = 0 rejection. Equivalently, an outcome can be thought of as a (possibly empty) subset J _c K = {1 . . . . . k} of accepted issues, with individual preference and hence majority preference then defined over these subsets. An issue-by-issue procedure considers each of the k issues one at a time, and is characterized by an agenda t : K --+ K which orders
2214
J.S. Banks
the k issues. Let FL be the issue-by-issue voting garne associated with the agenda t, and say that x 6 X is an agenda-independent outcome under the issue-by-issue procedure if x = s(FL, P) for all t. Consider the following restriction on majority preference: Condition S:
For all J ___{1 . . . . . k} and all j E J, J \ { j } P J .
In words, slightly smaller (by inclusion) subsets of accepted issues are preferred by a majority to largex'. To see that S is sufficient to guarantee agenda independence, note that any final decision hode corresponds to a vote of the form J vs. J \ { j } (where t ( j ) = k). If S holds then issue j will be rejected regardless of the earlier votes, i.e., regardless of the contents of J. By backwards induction, then, the penultimate rotes are of the form jr vs. J f \ { d } (where t(d) = k - 1) and again d is defeated regardless of J ' . Continuing this logic, we see that if S holds then all issues are rejected for any ordering of the issues. Thus we have not only agenda independence but we have identified the sophisticated voting outcome as (0 . . . . . 0), all issues rejected. Returning to the above example, we have, PROPOSITION 6. Xo is the agenda-independent outcome in D P under the issue-by-issue procedure. Therefore, as with the amendment procedure, if attention is restricted to issue-byissue procedures there will not exist any conflict over the agenda to use. Finally, note that if it were put to a rote whether an amendment procedure or an issue-by-issue procedure should be adopted in DR a majority (namely, the members of F ( x a ) ) would prefer the former to the latter regardless of the agenda subsequently employed.
4. The spatial environment It is evident that what drives the previous result is the decomposability of the collective choice problem into n smaller problems ("fund project i", "don't fund project i ' ) , as well as the separability of legislators' preferences aeross these n problems. This deeomposability has a natural analogue in the spatial environment, when we think of each dimension of the policy space as a separate issue to be decided. To keep matters simple we make the simplifying assumption that X is rectangular, X = [x__1, ~1] x ..- x [x k, ~~], so that the feasible choiees along any one dimension are independent of the choices along the others. We return to the notion of separable preferences below. As in the previous section, with n odd and each Ri strictly convex the majority-rule core, if non-empty, will consist of a single element, x c, where x c is stricfly majoritypreferred to all other alternatives. On the other hand, Figure 1 demonstrated that, no matter how nice individual preferences are, in two or more dimensions a majority-rnle core point rarely exists, i.e., for every alternative there is another that is majority-preferred
Ch. 59: StrategicAspects of PoliticalSystems
2215
to it. From this perspective then no alternative is stable, in that for any alternative there exists a majority coalition with the willingness and ability to change the collective decision to some other alternative. Now suppose that we constrain the influence of majority coalitions by requiring that any such change from one alternative to another must be accomplished via a sequence of one-dimension-at-a-time changes. For any x, y • X, define I(x, y) = {j ~ {1 . . . . . k}: xj 7~ yj} as the set of issues along which x and y disagree. Then since not all of these changes will necessarily be accepted, in considering a move from x to y the set of possible outcomes are those points in X of the form x + (y - x) J, where J c_ I(x, y) and for any vector z • ~U and subset J _c {1 . . . . . k}, z / = zi if i • J and z/J = 0 otherwise. For instance, in two dimensions the set of possible outcomes is given by {(xl, x2), (Xl, Y2), (Yl, x2), (Yl, Y2)}. Thus for any ordered pair of alternatives (x, y) • X 2 and any ordering l of the elements of l ( x , y) we have a well-defined issue-by-issue voting procedure F~(x, y); and given individual and hence majority preferences P on X we can compute the sophisticated voting outcome s(F~(x, y), p).4 Say that an outcome x* • X is a sophisticated voting equilibrium if for any y ¢ x* 6 X and any ordering L of I(x*, y), s(F~ (x*, y), P) = x*. That is, an alternative is a sophisticated voting equilibrium if no dimension-by-dimension change can be produced when all individuals vote sophisticatedly. Finally, say that individual i's preferences are separable if for all (x, y) • X 2, J ~ I(X, y) and j ~ J, [x + (y - x)J]Ri[x -4- (y X) J\{j}] if and only if [x + (y -x){J}]Ri [x]. Kramer (1972) then proves the following: -
PROPOS1TION 7. If for all i • N, Ri is separable, then there exists a sophisticated
voting equilibrium. Since preferences are strictly convex, continuous and separable, and n is odd, along issue dimension j there will exist a unique point x ] given by the median of the individuals' ideal points. Letting x* = (x~n . . . . . x~~), separability of preferences then implies that for any y e X Condition S above is satisfied: for any subset of changes J __ I (x*, y) an individual's preferences over J and J \ {j } (where j • J) are completely determined by their preferences along dimension j, and since x ] = x f a majority prefers J \ { j } to J. Kramer (1972) actually proves the existence of an issue-by-issue median, i.e., an alternative for which no one-dimensional change could attract a majority, without requiring separability. However he also shows by way of example that without separability one can construct situations in which two one-dimensional changes away from x m, together with sophisticated voting, will occur. Note that if a Condorcet winner x c exists, it must be that x c = x m, and so issue-by-issue voting is Condorcet consistent. On the
4 Since individuals may be indifferent between accepting and rejecting a change on an issue we add the behavioral assumptionthat when indifferent an individual rotes against the change.
2216
J.S. Banks
other hand, even when a Condorcet winner does not exist a sophisticated voting equilibriurn will exist (with separable preferences), due to the constraints placed on movements through the policy space. Kramer (1972) is the first example of what became known as the structure-induced equilibrium approach to collective decision-making (as opposed to preference-induced equilibrium, i.e., the core). A second example is given by Shepsle (1979) where, rather than directly impeding a majority's influence through the policy space, the choice of collective outcome is decentralized into a set of k one-dimensional decisions by subgroups of individuals. Thus define a committee system as an onto function « : N --+ K = {1 . . . . . k}, with the interpretation that x(i) is the single issue upon which i 6 N is influential. For all j 6 K, let N ~ ( j ) = {i c N: «(i) = j} denote the set of individuals, or "committee" assigned to issue j, and for simplicity assume IN ~ (J)l is odd for all j 6 K. The committees play "Nash" against one another, taking the decisions on the other issues as given, and use majority rule to determine the outcome on their issue. Thus let F(x; j ) = {y ~ X: Yt = xl for all 1 7~ j} denote the set of feasible alternatives the committee N K(j) can generate, given that x summarizes the choices by the other committees, and similarly let CK(x; j ) C F(x; j ) denote the set of majority-rule core points for the committee. An outcome x* 6 X is a K-committee equilibrium if, for all j ~ K, x* c CK(x*; j ) ; that is, no majority of any committee can implement a preferred outcome. PROPOSITION 8. For all K, a x-committee equilibrium exists. Since individual preferences are strictly convex and confinuous on X, for each (x, j) ~ X x K the preferences of each i c N K ( j ) will be single-peaked on F(x; j ) and hence C K(x; j ) will be equal to the unique median of the ideal points of members of N « (j) along F(x; j ) . And since preferences are continuous and the median function is continuous, we have that dz(.; j ) : X --+ X is a continuous function, as is the funcK tion B : X --+ X defined b y / 3 ( x ) = (C~(x; 1) . . . . . CÆ (x, k)). By Brouwer's fixed-point theorem there exists x* c X such that x* = B(x*). A few comments on this model are in order. The first is that if committees were to move sequentially as opposed to simultaneously, equilibria need not exist since the induced preferences for members of the committee moving first need not be singlepeaked along their issue when the latter committees' responses are taken into account [Denzau and Mackay (1981)]. On the other hand, if individual preferences are assumed to be separable it is easily seen that this will not be a concern, and in fact the equilibrium will be independent of the order in which the committees report their choices. Second, although as stated this model is a combination of cooperative (within committee) and non-cooperative (between committee) elements, we can easily make the entire process non-cooperative: let the strategy space for each i 6 N K(j) be given by [x j, 2J ], with the outcome function being the Cartesian product of the median choices along each dimension. If individuals' preferences are separable then i c N x ( j ) would have a dominant strategy to choose her ideal outcome from [x j, 2J], thereby imple-
Ch. 59: Strategic Aspects of Political Systems
2217
menting the (now unique) x-committee equilibrium. If preferences are non-separable this ideal outcome may depend on the median choices along the other dimensions. However, taking these other choices as fixed, i's best response is to choose her ideal outcome from [x j, YJ ], and therefore any K-committee equilibrium will constitute a Nash equilibrinm of the above garne (although there may be others). Finally, in contrast to Kramer (1972) here one does not necessari]y get Condorcet consistency, even with separable preferences. This is so because the "core" voter can only be on a single committee, and eren then there is no assurance she gets her way along the relevant dimension. To see this let k = 3 and n = 9, and let all individuals have Euclidean preferences, with ideal points x 1 = (0, 0, 0), x 2 = x 3 = (1, 0, 0), x 4 = x 5 = ( - 1 , 0 , 0 ) , x 6 = (0, 1,0), x 7 = ( 0 , - 1 , 0 ) , x 8 = (0,0, 1), and x 9 = ( 0 , 0 , - 1 ) . Then the majority-rule core is at (0, 0, 0); but if the committee for the first dimension is given by {1, 2, 3} the first coordinate in any equilibrium is 1. On the other hand, if x is such that NK(1) = {1, 2, 4}, NK(2) = {3, 6, 7}, and NK(3) = {5, 8, 9}, then in fact the tc-committee equilibrium is at the core. The above model was motivated by the committee system employed in the US Congress. Parliamentary democracies also typically display a certain structure in their co]lective decision-making, a structure which might again be leveraged to produce equilibrium predictions [Laver and Shepsle (1990), Austen-Smith and Banks (1990)]. In parliaments the locus of control is much more at the party level as opposed to the individual level; however to avoid modeling intraparty behavior we imagine an n-party world with perfect party discipline so as to remain consistent with out n-individual analysis. As with the committee model each dimension of the policy space is associated with a different "ministry", the differences being that here a single party controls a ministry, and a party can control more than one ministry. Thus let 79(K) denote the power set of K, and define an issue allocation as a mapping co : N --+ 79(K) such that Uco(i)=K iEN
and,
for alli, j ~ N ,
co(i) Aco(j)=O.
That is, each issue is assigned to precisely one party, with co(i) denoting the issues under the influence of party i. Let £2 denote the (finite) set of such mappings. Parties for which co(.) ¢ 0 constitute the governing coalition, and play Nash against one another to determine an outcome from X; thus the strategy sets are of the form S~° = l-[.jco»(i)[xj, x j], and the outcome function is simply the admixture of the various choices. Let E(co) C X denote the set of Nash equilibrium outcomes for the allocation co. Given out stated assumptions on individual/party preferences, a standard argument establishes that E(co) is non-empty for each allocation co in £2. Further, as in the committee model, if preferences are separable then each member of the governing coalition will have a dominant strategy, implying for each co ~ £2 the Nash equilibrium will be unique. Hereafter we assume this uniqueness holds regardless of the separability of preferences. In the above model of Sheps]e (1979) the committee system tc was exogenous, thereby leaving the puzzle of collective choice somewhat unfinished. In contrast, hefe
2218
J.S. Banks
we endogenize the choice of allocation: let E = U~ocs? E(co) C X denote the (finite) set of outcomes implementable by some allocation, and note that each i ~ N has welldefined preferences defined over E and hence (by uniqueness) well-defined induced preferences over the set of allocations I2. Rather than modeling the choice of allocation and hence the government formation process explicitly [as in, e.g., Austen-Smith and Banks (1988) or Baron (1991)], Laver and Shepsle (1990) and Austen-Smith and Banks (1990) explore various core concepts associated with the set E of implementable outcomes. The most straightforward concept, although by no means the most reasonable, is to identify the weighted majority core on the restricted set of outcomes, E. That is, each party has a certain number of seats and hence "weight" in the legislature; an alternative x 6 E is an "allocation" core if there does not exist y ~ E which a weighted majority prefers. Note that any such prediction gives not only a policy from X, but also the identity of the government and the distribution of policy influence within the government. Furthermore, since the set of implementable outcomes E is much smaller than the set of all possible outcomes X, these allocation core points can exist even when a core point in X does not. In fact, since E is finite the former need not lead the precarious existence the latter orten do in multiple dimensions with respect to small changes in preferences. Finally, since co(i) = K, i.e., allocating all issues to a single party, is allowed, we have that the profle of ideal points {x i . . . . . x n } is necessarily a subset of E. Therefore, if we add the assumptions that the party weights are such that no coalition has precisely 1/2 the weight (i.e., weighted majority rnle is strong) and that each Ri is representable by a continuously differentiable utility function ui : X ~ ~t, then when x c exists (and is interior to X) it must be that x c =- x i for some i 6 N, and hence we have a weighted version of Condorcet consistency holding. This would give an instance of one-party government where that party does not itself hold a majority of the seats (i.e., a one-party, minority government). Austen-Smith and Banks (1990) prove the following: PROPOSITION 9. I f n = 3 a n d , f o r a l l i ~ N , R i is E u c l i d e a n , t h e n t h e a l l o c a t i o n c o r e is n o n - e m p t y .
In fact, with n = 3 the allocation core is either equal to one of the ideal points, or else is equal to the issue-by-issue median (cf. Figure 1). Even without a general existence theorem, Layer and Shepsle (1996) take the model's predictions to the data on postWorld War II coalitional governments in parliamentary systems, and find an admirable degree of consistency. Each of the above three models employs some element of "real world" legislative decision-making to provide the analytical traction necessary to generate equilibrium predictions. The final model we consider in this section is relatively more generic, and is meant to capture individual and collective behavior in more unstrnctured situations. Specifically, we look at a discrete time, infinite horizon model of bargaining where, in contrast to Rubinstein-type bargaining with a deterministic proposer sequence, the proposer in each period is randomly recognized. Thus in period t ---- 1, 2 , . . , indi-
Ch. 59: StrategicAspects of Political Systems
2219
vidual i 6 N is recognized with probability /zi ~> 0 as the current proposer, where ~ j ~ N / z j = 1. Upon being recognized she selects some outcome x 6 X, and upon observing x each individual rotes either to accept or reject. If the coalition of individuals voting to accept are in 79, where 79 is some simple rule, the process ends and the outcome is (x, t); otherwise the process moves to period t ÷ 1. Individual i's preferences are represented by a continuous and strictly concave utility function u i : X --+ 91++ and discount factor 3i c [0, 1], with the utility to i from the outcome (x, t) then being 6~-lui (x). This model, due to Banks and Duggan (2000), extends to the spatial environment the earlier work of Baron and Ferejohn (1989) in which this bargaining protocol was studied in a "divide-the-dollar" environment with "selfish" linear preferences, i.e., X = {x E [0, 1In: ~ i c N X i 1} and for all i 6 N and x E X, ui(x) = xi, and where the focus was on majority rule. Banks and Duggan (2000) restrict attention to equilibria in stationary strategies, consisting of a proposal Pi c X offered anytime i is recognized; and a voting rule vi : X -+ {accept, reject} independent both of history and of the identity of the proposer. To prove existence they need to allow randomization in the proposal-making; thus each i 6 N selects a probability distribution 7ri 6 7)(X) (with the latter endowed with the topology of weak convergence). However, each individual observes the realized policy proposal prior to voting. Finally, they characterize only "no-delay" equilibria in which the first proposal is accepted with probability one. When 3i < 1 for all i E N it is easily seen that all stationary equilibria will involve no delay; however, since individuals here are allowed to be perfectly patient (i.e., 3i = 1) this amounts to a selection from the set of all stationary equilibria. Let u = (ul . . . . . un), and as before let C(79, u) _ X denote the core of the simple rule 79 at the profile u. =
PROPOSITION 1 0. (a) There exist stationary no-delay equilibria; (b) I f (~i = 1 f o r all i E N and either 79 is collegial or X is one-dimensional, then (~r~ . . . . . 7r*) is a stationary no-delay equilibrium if and only /f ~i*({x*}) = 1 for all i E N and f o r some x* c C(79, u). Comparing this result to Proposition 1, and cognizant of the fact that here we are assuming strict concavity rather than strict quasi-concavity (i.e., strictly convex preferences), we see first that equilibria exist for all profiles u, all simple rules 7), and all dimensions of the policy space k. Further, when individuals are perfectly patient we get a core equivalence result precisely when the core is non-empty for all profiles u and simple rules 79 (i.e., k = 1) and when the core is non-empty for all profiles u and all dimensions of the policy space k (i.e., 79 collegial). Banks and Duggan (2000) also show that the set of stationary no-delay equilibria is upper-hemicontinuous in (among other parameters) the discount factors, and hence if individuals are "almost" perfecfly patient all equilibrium outcomes will be "close" to the core.
2220
J.S. Banks
Another interesting comparison is with the equilibrium predictions of the issue-byissue model and the parliamentary model described above. In Figure 1 both of these models predict the issue-by-issue median x 'n as the unique equilibrium outcome. On the other hand, it is readily apparent that in the bargaining model under majority rule any equilibrium proposal lies on the contract curve between the proposer and one of the remaining individuals, with the exact location of the proposals (and the probability distribution over them) depending on the underlying parameters. Thus, the former two models predict a rauch more centrist outcome than does the bargaining mode1.
5. Incomplete information All of the models surveyed in the previous two sections have been examples of political processes in which the set of individuals N directly chooses the collective outcome from X. We begin this section with the classic model of representative democracy, namely, the Downsian model of electoral competition, and analyze it in the context of Proposition 1. In the basic model two candidates, A and B (~ N) simultaneously choose policies Xa, Xb E X ; upon observing these policies individuals simultaneously vote for either A or B (so no abstentions), with the majority-preferred candidate winning the election and implementing her announced policy. The candidates have no policy interests themselves, and only care about winning the election: the winning candidate receives a utility payoff of 1, while the loser receives - 1 . Given any (Xa, Xb)-pair each i 6 N has a weakly dominant strategy to vote for the candidate offering the preferred policy according to ui, with i voting for each with probability 0.5 when ui (xa) = ui (Xb). Thus, given knowledge of voter preferences the two candidates are engaged in a symmetric, zero-sum garne with common strategy space X, and so in any equilibrium each taust receive an expected payoff of zero. It is easily seen that a pure strategy equilibrium to this garne exists if and only if the majority-rule tore is non-empty: if the core is empty then given any xb there exists a policy which majority-defeats it, and hence if adopted by A would generate payoffs (1, - 1 ) . Conversely, if x c is in the core candidate C guarantees herself an expected payoff of zero, and so if xa and xb are core policies (Xa, Xb) constitutes an equilibrium. From Section 2 we know that the majority-rule core in the spatial environment is equal to the median voter's ideal point when the dimension of the policy space is one, thus giving the original prediction of Downs (1957) that both candidates would locate there. On the other hand, we also know that when this dimension is greater than one the core is almost always empty, and so pure strategy equilibria typically fail to exist. One possible escape route of course is to consider mixed strategies, as was done by Banks and Duggan (2000) in the bargaining context. However, while existence of mixed strategy equilibria is assured in the finite environment, 5 in the spatial environ5 See [Laffondet al. (1993)] for a characterization of the supportof the mixedstrategyequilibria in the finite environment.
Ch. 59." Strategic Aspects of Political Systems
2221
ment it has proven to be somewhat more elusive given the inherent discontinuities in the majority preference relation and hence in the above zero-sum game [however see Kramer (1978)]. Alternatively, one can smooth over these discontinuities by positing a sufficient amount of uncertainty, from the candidates' perspective, about the intended behavior of the voters. To this end let the probability i • N votes for candidate A, given announced policy positions (Xa, xb), be pi (ui (Xa), ui (Xb)), with 1 -- Pi being the probability of voting for B (so again no abstentions). Candidates are assumed to maximize expected vote, which, in the absence of abstentions, is equivalent to maximizing expected plurality. Thus A solves maxZpi(ui(x),ui(xb) xcX iEN
),
with a similar expression for B. As in the bargaining model, we assume that, for all i • N, ui is strictly concave and maps into the positive real line. PROPOSITION 1 1. (a) If f o r all i c N, Pi (') is concave increasing in its first argument and convex decreasing in its second, then a pure strategy equilibrium exists. (b) If pi(') can be written as
p, (u~(~o), ù~(~»)) = p(ù,(~o) - u~ (~»)), where ~ is increasing and differentiable, then in equilibrium Xa = Xb = X u, where x u solves
max ~
ui (x).
i~N
(c) If pi(') can be written as
p, (u,(Xa), ui(~~)) = ~(ù,(~~)/u~ (~»)), where ~ is increasing and differentiable, then in equilibrium Xa ~ Xb = x n, where x n solves
max~!?_.ln(ui(x)). leN
Thus, while (a) [due to Hinich et al. (1972)] provides sufficient conditions for the existence of a pure strategy equilibrium in the candidate garne, (b) and (c) demonstrate that, in certain situations, these equilibrium policies will coincide with either utilitarJan or Nash social welfare optima. Beyond any normative significance, this implies that the candidates' equilibrium policies are actually independent of their expected plurality
J.S. Banks
2222
functions, and, therefore, independent of the structure of the incomplete information in the model (other than the requirement that/3 and/3 only depend on i through ui). Part (b) extends the result of Lindbeck and Weibull (1987) for a model of income redistribution, while (c) is an extension of a result for the familiar binary Luce model employed by Coughlin and Nitzan (1981) and others, where pi(ui(Xa),ùi(Xb))=
ui(Xa) Ui(Xa)"t-Ui(Xb)
Orte weakness of the probabilisfic voting model is that the analysis starts "in the middle", by positing some voter probability functions without generating them from primitives. This can be remedied by assuming that, from the candidates' perspective, there exist some additional considerations beyond a comparison of policies which influence the voters' decisions and which are unknown to the candidates. We can think of these as non-policy characteristics of the candidates, or (equivalently) as the candidates' fixed positions on some other policy dimensions. For example, if i c N votes for candidate A if and only if ui (Xa) > ui (xó) + 13, where 13 is distributed according to a smooth function G, then Pi (ui (Xa), ui (Xb)) is simply equal to G(ui (Xa) - ui (Xb)) and (b) is satisfied. Additionally, if G is uniform on an interval [13, ~] sufficiently large (and containing zero), then Ui(Xa)--Ui(Xb)--fl pi("i(Xa),Ui(Xb)) =
13-13
and hence p will be linearly increasing in Ui (Xa) and linearly decreasing in Ui (Xb), and therefore (a) is satisfied. Alternatively, the "bias" term 13 could enter in multiplicatively rather than additively, thereby generating a form as in (c). Orte immediate consequence of moving back to this more primitive stage is to qualify the welfare statements above: it is not the sum of the individual utilities that is actually being maximized, but rather the sum of the known components of their utilities. 6 In the previous model incomplete information concerning voter behavior was present, in that the candidates could not perfectly predict how policy positions would be translated into votes. However, the decision problem on the part of the voters was straightforward: given only two alternatives, and with complete information about their own preferences, each voter's weakly dominant strategy was simply to vote for her preferred alternative. Suppose now that there exists some uncertainty among the voters about which is the preferred alternative [Austen-Smith and Banks (1996)]. Specifically, let X = {A, B}, and let there be two possible states of the world, S = {A, B}, with zr 6 (0, 1) the prior probability that the state is A. Individual i's preferences over outcome-state pairs (x, s) are represented by ui : X x S ---> {0, 1}, with ui(x, s) = 1 if
6 See [Banks and Duggan (1999)] for these and other extensions of results in probabilisticvoting.
Ch. 59: Strategic Aspects of Political Systems
2223
and only if x = s. Hence, in contrast to the heterogeneous preferences assumed in all of the above models, hefe the individuals have a common interest in selecting the outcome to match the state. Individuals simultaneously vote for either A or B, with B being the outcome if and only if h individuals vote for it, where h 6 {1 . . . . . n}. Thus h ----(n + 1)/2 means that majority rule is being employed, whereas h ----n means that B is the outcome only if the individuals unanimously vote for B. While individuals share a common interest, they possess potentially different information conceming the true state, and hence the optimal choice, in that prior to voting each i 6 N receives a private signal ti ~ Ti correlated with the true state. Thus let vi : Ti --+ X denote a voting strategy for i, v = (Vl, . . . , vn) a profile of voting strategies, t -----(tl . . . . . th) C=1-'IicN Ti a profile of signals, and d = (d~ . . . . . dn) c X n a profile of individual decisions. Given a common prior p (-) over profiles of signals, then, we have a Bayesian garne among the voters, with the expected utility of a pair (d, t) equal to the probability the true state is equal to the collective decision conditional on t. Defining c(d) c X by c(d) = B if and only if [{i ~ N: di -----B}[ ~> h, we can write this as Pr[s = c(d); tl, which (via Bayes' Rule) is equal to Pr[s ----c ( d ) & t ] / p ( t ) . Moreover, since p ( t - i ; ti) = p(t)/Y~~~-i p(ti, t-i), we can simplify the expression for the expected utility of i choosing di, conditional on ti and v, from
E U (di ; tl, v) = Z p ( t - i ; tl)Pr[s = c(di, v(t-i ) ) & tl T i p(t) to
E U (di; ti, v) = Z Pr[s c(di, v(t-i) ) • tl T i ~ T - i p(ti, t - i ) =
Now in comparing the difference in expected utility from voting for A or B, we can obviously ignore the denominator above; further, this difference will only be non-zero when i is pivotal in determining the outcome. Therefore let
TP_i(v) = {t-i c T_,:
I{J e N\{i}: vj(tj)---- B}I--h- 1}
be the set of others' signals for which, according to v, i is pivotal. Finally, when i is pivotal her decision is equal to the collective decision, and hence we get that EU(A; ti, v) - E U ( B ; tl, v) ~ 0 Z
i f a n d only if
[Pr[s ----A & tl - Pr[s = B & tl]/> 0.
Bi(~) Thus, in identifying which is the better decision each individual conditions on being pivotal, which (through v) limits the set of possible inferences she can have about others' information.
2224
J.S. Banks
The presence of this "pivotal" information can have dramatic effects on individuals' voting behavior. The first thing to note is that, unlike when information is complete, sincere voting is no longer a weakly dominant strategy, where 1)i is sincere if, for all ti c Tl, vi(ti) ~- A if and only if E [ u i ( A , .); ti] > E [ u i ( B , .); tl]. As a simple example, let n = 5, rr = 0.5, h = (n + 1)/2, and for all i 6 N let 7) = {a, b} with Pr[ti = a; s = A ] = P r [ / i = b; s = B ] = q > 0.5. Thus there are four pure strategies: "always vote A", "always vote B", "vote A if and only if ti = a " , and "vote A if and only if t i = b " , with the third strategy being sincere. Suppose voters 1 and 2 play "always A" while 3 and 4 play the sincere strategy; then 5 should play "always B" since the only time 5 is pivotal is when t3 = t4 = b, in which case eren if t» = a Bayes' Rule implies the more likely state is B. Therefore sincere voting is not a weakly dominant strategy. On the other hand, sincere voting does constitute an equilibrium: if the others are behaving sincerely and i is pivotal, she infers that two of the others have observed a and two have observed b. Given the symmetry of the situation these signals cancel out when applying Bayes' Rule, and so it is optimal for i to behave sincerely as well. The reason sincere voting constitutes an equilibrium is that majority rule is the "right" rule to use in symmetric situations such as this, in the sense that if all the signals were known choosing A if and only if a majority of the signals were a would maximize the likelihood of making the correct decision [Austen-Smith and Banks (1996)]. Conversely, suppose we keep all the underlying parameters the same but use unanimity rule, h = n [Feddersen and Pesendorfer (1998)]. Then it is easily seen that sincere voting does not constitute an equilibrium: under unanimity voter i is pivotal only when all others are voting for B. But if the others vote for B if and only if their signals are b, i prefers to vote for B when pivotal even if ti = a, as the (inferred) collection of n - 1 b's overwhelms her one a. On the other hand, everyone adopting the "always B" strategy is not an equilibrium either, since in this case i is always pivotal and hence infers nothing about the others' signals. Thus when ti = a i should vote for A. (Of course, everyone adopting the "always A" strategy is an equilibrium, since nobody is ever pivotal.) Therelore, to find interesting symmetric equilibria Feddersen and Pesendorfer (1998) look to mixed strategies, letting ~r (ti) E [0, 1] be the probability a type-t/individual votes for B. Beyond symmetry, they require the strategies to be "responsive" to the private signals, so that ~r (a) 5~ « (b). It is readily apparent that, given the symmetry of the environment, any such equilibrium under unanimity will be of the form 0 < cr(a) < 1 = er(b), i.e., vote for B upon observing the signal b, and randomize upon observing a. The goal is to compare unanimity rule to majority rule, as well as any other rule, in terms of the equilibrium probability of the collective making an incorrect decision. As they let the population size n vary, we can parametrize the rules by V ~ (0, 1) and set h = Fvn] where for any r ~ fit+, Fr] is the smallest integer greater than or equal to r (e.g., V = 0.5 is majority rule). PROPOSITION 12. (a) Under unanimity rule there exists a unique responsive symmetric equilibrium; as n --+ ~ er(a) --+ 1, and the probabilities o f c h o o s i n g A when the stare is B and choosing B when the stare is A are bounded a w a y f r o m zero.
Ch. 59: StrategicAspects of Political Systems
2225
(b) For any y E (0, 1) there exists n ( y ) such that f o r all n >~ n ( y ) there exists a responsive symmetric equilibrium; as n ~ cxz any sequence o f such equilibria has the probabilities o f choosing A when the state is B and choosing B when the stare is A converging to zero. Therefore from the perspective of error probabilities unanimity rule is unambiguously the worst rule for large collectives. Furthermore, Feddersen and Pesendorfer (1998) show by way of a twelve-person example that "large" need not be very large. They interpret this result as casting doubt on the appropriateness of using unanimity rule in, for instance, legal proceedings. 7 The preceding result showed how a model that Proposition 1(a) would suggest is trivial under complete information, namely, when there are only two alternatives, becomes not so trivial with the judicious introduction of incomplete information. Our last model shows the same phenomenon with respect to Proposition l(b), and is due to Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987). Consider a one-dimensional policy space X = 9t within which two players, labelled the committee C and the floor F, interact to select a final policy. 8 Two different procedures are considered, yielding two different garne forms: under a "closed" rule C makes a take-it-or-leave-it proposal p E 91, where if F rejects the proposal the status quo policy s E 91 is implemented. In contrast, under the open rule F can select any policy following C's proposal, thereby rendering the latter "cheap talk". As with Feddersen and Pesendorfer (1998), Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987) are interested in a comparison of these two rules with respect to the equilibrium outcomes they generate, with the motivation here being that F has the ability to choose ex ante which procedure to adopt. With complete information F would surely prefer the open rule, given its lack of constraints. However, suppose that under either rule, if z E 91 is the chosen policy the final outcome is not z but is rather x = z + t, where t is drawn uniformly from [0, 1] and whose value is known to C but unknown to E Thus a strategy for C under either rule is a mapping from [0, 1] to 91; however, to distinguish the two, let p ( t ) denote C's proposal under the closed rule and m ( t ) C's "message" under the open rule. Similarly, let a (p) denote the probability F accepts a proposal of p 6 91 from C under the closed rule, and p ( m ) the policy F selects following the message m 6 91 under the open rule. Players' utilities over final outcomes are quadratic: Uc (x) = - ( x - Xe)2, Xc > 0, and u f (x) = - x 2. Thus Xc measures the heterogeneity in the players' preferences. Given this specification, if F's updated belief about the value of t has mean T her best response under the closed rule is to accept p if [IP - 711 ~< IIs - 711 and reject otherwise, i.e., select p or s depending on which is closer to 7. Under the open rule, given mean 7 F's best response is simply to select p = - 7 . As with most signaling garnes there exist multiple equilibria under either rule. Under the open rule Gilligan and Krehbiel select the "most informative" equilibria, which have
7 Howeversee [Coughlan(2000)] for a rebuttal. 8 We can think of F as the median member of the legislature, and C as the median member of a committee.
2226
zs. Banks
the following partition structure [Crawford and Sobel (1982)]: let to = 0 and tN(x«) = 1, where N ( x c ) is the largest integer satisfying I2N(1 - N)xcl < 1. For 1 < i < N ( x c ) define ti by ti
=
tli + 2i(1 - i)Xc;
thus the equilibria will be parametrized by the choice of tl. Given a distinct set {ml . . . . . raN} = M of messages C's strategy is of the form m*(t) = m j if and only if t ~ [tj-1, tj). Given F's updated belief her optimal response to any m j ~ M is p* (m j ) = - (tj - tj _ 1)/2. Faced with this strategy C's strategy above is optimal if and only if for all i = 1 . . . . . N ( x « ) , ti is indifferent between sending m*(ti - e) and m*(ti + e), which holds only when ti+l = 2tl - t i - i - 4Xc,
which is a second-order difference equation whose solution is given above. Of particular relevance is the fact that N ( x c ) is decreasing in Xc, and tends to infinity as Xc tends to zero. The equilibrium Gilligan and Krehbiel select under the closed rule has the following path of play: (1) for t E [0, sl] U Is3, 1], p*(t) = Xc - t, and a * ( p * ( t ) ) = 1; (2) for t (Sl, s2], p*(t) ----4Xc + s, and a * ( p * ( t ) ) = 1;(3)for t ~ (s2, s3), p*(t) = ~ ~ (s, s +4Xc) and a* (p* (t)) = 0. Thus, when the shift parameter t is sufficiently sma11 or sufficiently 1arge, C is able to separate and implement her optimal outcome. A third region of types pools together and has their proposal accepted, while a fourth has their proposal rejected, with the logic of the latter being that s + t, the outcome upon rejection, is already close to Xc (in fact, s3 = Xc - s). PROPOSITION 13. There exists -Y > 0 such that i f xc < ~ then the floor's ex ante equilibrium utility under the closed rule is greater than rhat under the open rule.
Therefore, as long as the preferences of the committee and floor are not too dissimilar, the floor prefers to grant the committee a certain amount of agenda control. The intuition behind this result is the following: under both the open and the closed rule the equilibrium expected utility of F is decreasing in Xc, so that as their preferences become less diverse F is better off under either rule. For the open rule this is true since the more homogeneous the preferences the greater is C's ability to transmit information, leading to a more informed decision by E Under the closed rule the set of types that separate and subsequently implement their ideal outcome is itself increasing as Xc decreases, and as x« decreases C's ideal outcome becomes more favorable from F's perspective. Now in selecting the closed rule over the open rule F faces a distributional loss, due to C's being able to bias the resulting outcome in her favor, as well as an informational gain, due to the increased amount of information transmitted and the assumed risk aversion of F. As Xc decreases this distributional loss tends to be outweighed by the informational gain, implying the closed rule is preferable.
Ch. 59: StrategicAspects of Political Systems
2227
References Austen-Smith, D. (1987), "Sophisticated sincerity: voting over endogenous agendas", Amefican Political Science Review 81:1323-1330. Austen-Smith, D., and J. Banks (1988), "Elections, coalifions, and legislative outcomes", American Political Science Review 82:409-422. Austen-Smith, D., and J. Banks (1990), "Stable governments and the allocation of policy portfolios", Ameriean Polifical Science Review 84:891-906. Austen-Smith, D., and J. Banks (1996), "Information, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem", American Political Science Review 90:34-45. Austen-Smith, D., and J. Banks (1999), "Cycling of simple rules in the spatial model", Social Choice and Welfare 16:663-672. Banks, J. (1985), "Sophisficated voting outcomes and agenda control', Social Choice and Welfare 1:295-306. Banks, J. (1995), "Singularity theory and core existence in the spatial model", Journal of Mathematical Economics 24:523-536. Banks, J., and J. Duggan (1999), "The theory of probabilistic voting in the spatial model of elections", Working paper. Banks, J., and J. Duggan (2000), "A bargaining model of collecfive choice", Amefican Political Science Review 94:73-88. Baron, D, (1991), "A spatial bargaining theory of government formation in parliamentary systems", Amefican Polifical Science Review 85:137-164. Baron, D., and J. Ferejohn (1989), "Bargaining in legislatures°', American Political Science Review 83:11811206. Black, D. (1958), The Theory of Committees and Elections (Canabfidge University Press, Cambfidge). Condorcet, M. (1785/1994), Foundations of Social Choice and Political Theory, Transl. I. McLean and F. Hewirt, eds. (Edward Elgar, Brookfield, VT). Coughlan, P. (2000), "In defense of unanimous jury verdicts: mistrials, communication, and strategic voting", Amefican Political Science Review 94:375-393. Coughlin, P., and S. Nitzan (1981), "Electoral outcomes with probabilistic voting and Nash social welfare maxima", Jottrnal of Public Economics 15:113-122. Coughlin, P. (1992), Probabilisfic Voting Theory (Cambridge University Press, New York). Crawford, V., and J. Sobel (1982), "Strategic information transmission", Econometrica 50:1431-1451. Denzan, A.o and R. Maekay (1981 ), "Strncmre-induced equilibfia and perfeet foresight expectations", American Journal of Political Science 25:762-779. Downs, A. (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy (Harper and Row, New York). Farquharson, R. (1969), The Theory of Vofing (Yate University Press, New Haven). Feddersen, T., and W. Pesendorfer (1998), "Convicting the innocent: the infefiofity of unanimous jury verdicts", Amefican Political Science Review 92:23-36. Ferejohn, J., M. Fiorina and R. McKelvey (1987), "Sophisficated voting and agenda independence in the distfibutive potitics setting", Amefican Journal of Polifical Science 31:169-193. Gilligan, T., and K. Krehbiel (1987), "Collective decision making and standing committees: an informational rationale for restrictive amendment procedures", Jottmal of Law, Economics and Organization 3:287-335. Greflein, R. (1983), "Dominance elimination procedures on firtite alternative garnes", International Journal of Game Theory 12:107-113. Hinich, M., J. Ledyard and P. Ordeshook (1972), "Nonvofing and the existence of equilibrium under majofity rule', Journal of Economic Theory 4:144-153. Kramer, G. (1972), "Sophisficated vofing over mulfidimensional choice spaces", Jottrnal of Mathematieat Sociology 2:165-180. Kramer, G. (1978), "Existence of electoral eqinlibfium", in: P. Ordeshook, ed., Garne Theory and Polifical Science (NYU Press, New York).
2228
J.S. Banks
Laffond, G., J. Laslier and M. Le Breton (1993), "The bipartisan set of a tournament", Garnes and Economic Behavior 5:182-201. Laver, M., and K. Shepsle (1990), "Coalitions and cabinet government", American Political Science Review 84:873-890. Laver, M., and K. Shepsle (1996), Making and Breaking Governments (Cambridge University Press, New York). Lindbeck, A., and J. Weibull (1987), "Balanced-budget redistributions as the outcome of political competition", Public Choice 52:273-297. McGarvey, D. (1953), "A theorem on the construction of vofing paradoxes", Econometfica 21:608-610. McKelvey, R. (1979), "Generalized conditions for global intransitivities in formal voting models", Journal of Economic Theory 47:1085-1112. McKelvey, R., and R. Niemi (1978), "A mulfistage garne representation of sophisticated voting for binary procedures", Journal of Economic Theory 18:1-22. Miller, N. (1980), "A new solution set for tournaments and majofity voting: further graph-theorefical approaches to the theory of voting', Amefican Journal of Political Science 24:68-96. Moulin, H. (1986), "Choosing from a toumament", Social Choice and Welfare 3:271-291. Nakamura, K. (1979), "The vetoers in a simple garne with ordinal preferences", International Journal of Garne Theory 8:55-61. Plott, C. (1967), "A notion of equilibrium and its possibility under majority mle", American Economic Review 57:787-806. Saari, D. (1997), "The generic existence of a core for q-rules", Economic Theory 9:219-260. Schofield, N. (1983), "Generic instability of majority rule", Review of Economic Smdies 50:695-705. Schofield, N. (1984), "Social equilibrium cycles on compact sets", Joumal of Economic Theory 33:59-71. Shepsle, K, (1979), "Institufional arrangements and equilibfium in multidimensional voting models", Amefican Journal of Political Science 23:37-59. Shepsle, K., and B. Weingast (1984), "Uncovered sets and sophisticated voting outcomes with implications for agenda instimtions", American Journal of Polifical Science 28:4%74. Stmad, J. (1985), "The structure of continuous-valued neutral monotonic social functions", Social Choice and Welfare 2:181-195.
Chaßter 60
GAME-THEORETIC ANALYSIS OF LEGAL RULES AND INSTITUTIONS JEAN-PIERRE BENOa'T* and LEWIS A. KORNHAUSER t
Department of Economics and School of Law, New York University, New York, USA
Contents
1. Introduction 2. Economic analysis of the common law when contracting costs are infinite
Articles
2231 2233 2233 2235 2237 2241 2243 2245 2247 2249 2251 2252 2259 2262 2263 2263
Cases
2269
2.1. The basic model 2.2. Extensions within accident law 2.3. Other interpretations of the model
3. Is law important? Understanding the Coase Theorem 3.1. The Coase Theorem and complete information 3.2. The Coase Theorem and incomplete information 3.3. A cooperative game-theoretic approach to the Coase Theorem
4. Garne-theoretic analyses of legal rulemaking 5. Cooperative game theory as a tool for analysis of legal concepts 5.1. Measures of voting power 5.2. Fair allocation of losses and benefits
6. Concluding remarks References
*The support of the C.V. Starr Center for Applied Economics is acknowledged. tAlfred and Gail Engelberg Professor of Law, New York University. The support of the Filomen D'Agostino and Max E. Greenberg Research Fund of the NYU School of Law is acknowledged. We thank John Ferejohn, Mark Geist:feld, Marcel Kahan, Martin Osbome and William Thomson for comments.
Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2230
J.-P. Benoft and L.A. Kornhauser
Abstract We offer a selective survey of the uses of cooperative and non-cooperative garne theory in the analysis of legal rules and institutions. In so doing, we illustrate some of the ways in which law influences behavior, analyze the mechanism design aspect of legal rules and instimtions, and examine some of the difficulties in the use of game-theoretic concepts to clarify legal doctrine.
Keywords economic analysis of law, Coase Theorem, accidents, positive political theory, voting power J E L classification: C7, D7, K0
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and lnstitutions
2231
1. Introduction Game-theoretic ideas and analyses have appeared explicitly in legal commentaries and judicial opinions for over tbirty years. They first emerged in the immediate aftermath of early reapportionment cases that redrew districts in federal and state elections in the United States. As the U.S. courts struggled to articulate the meaning of equal representation and to give content to the slogan "one person, one vote", they considered, and for a time endorsed, a concept of voting power that has game-theoretic roots. At approximately the same time, the publication of Calabresi (1961) and Coase (1960) provoked an outpouring of economic analyses of legal rules and institutions that continues to grow. In the late 1960s, the first game-theoretic models of contract doctrine [Birmingharn (1969a, 1969b)] appeared. Models of accident law in Brown (1973) and Diamond (1974a, 1974b) followed a few years later. In the mid-1980s, the explicit use of garne theory in the economic analysis of law burgeoned. The early uses of game theory encompass the two different ways in which garne theory has been applied to legal problems. On the one hand, as in the reapportionment cases, courts and analysts have adopted game-theoretic tools to further the goals of traditional Anglo-American legal scholarship. In this tradition, both judge and commentator seek to rationalize a set of related judicial decisions by articulating the underlying normative framework that unifies and justifies the judicial doctrine. In this use, which we shall call doctrinal analysis, game-theoretic concepts elaborate the meaning of key, doctrinal ideas that define what the law seeks to achieve. On the other hand, as in the analyses of contract and tort, garne theory has provided a theory of how individuals respond to legal rules. The analyst considers the garnes defined by a class of legal rules and studies how the equilibrium behavior of individuals varies with the choice of legal rule. In legal cultures that, as in the United States, regard law as an instrument for the guidance and regulation of social behavior, this analysis is a necessary step in the task facing the legal policymaker. It is worth emphasizing that nothing in this analytic structure fies the analyst, or the policymaker, to an "economic" objective such as efficiency or maximization of social welfare. In this essay, we offer a selective survey of the uses of garne theory in the anälysis of law. The use of game theory as an adjunct of doctrinal analysis has been relatively limited, and our survey of this area is correspondingly reasonably exhaustive. In contrast, the use of garne theory in understanding how legal rules affect individual behavior has been pervasive. Garne theory has been explicitly applied to analyses of contract, 1 torts between strangers, 2 bankruptcy and corporate reorganization, 3 corpo-
1 E.g., Birmingham (1969a, 1969b), Shavell (1980), Komhauser(1983), Rogerson (1984), and Hermalin and Katz (1993). 2 E.g., Brown (1973), Diamond (1974a, 1974b), Diamondand Mirrlees (1975), and Shavell (1987). 3 E.g., Baird and Picker (1991), Bebchuk and Chang (1992), Gertner and Scharfstein (1991), Schwartz (1988, 1993), and White (1980, 1994).
2232
J.-R Beno~t and L.A. Kornhauser
rate takeovers and other corporate problems, 4 product liability, 5 and the decision to settle rather than litigate 6 and the consequent effects on the likelihood that plaintiff will prevail at trial. 7 Kornhauser (1989) argues that virtually all of the economic analysis of law can be understood as an exercise in mechanism design in which a policymaker chooses among legal rules that define garnes played by citizens. Moreover, certain traditional subdisciplines of economics and finance, such as industrial organization, public finance, and environmental economics, are inextricably tied to legal rules. Game-theoretic models in those fields invariably shed light on legal rules and instimtions. Given the size and diversity of this latter literature, we cannot provide a comprehensive survey of game-theoretic models of legal rules and hence make no attempt to do so. Furthermore, in some areas at least, such literature surveys already exist: see, for example, Shavell (1987) on torts, Cooter and Rubinfeld (1989) on dispute resolution, Kornhauser (1986) on contract remedies, Pyle (1991) on criminal law, Hart and Holmstrom (1987) and Holmstrom and Tirole (1989) on the incomplete contracting literature, Symposium (1991) on corporate law generally and Harris and Raviv (1992) on the capital strucmre of firms. In addition, Baird, Germer and Picker (1994) is an introduction to garne theory that presents the concepts through a wide variety of legal applications. Having forsworn comprehensive coverage, we have three aims in this survey. Our first is to suggest the wide variety of legal rules and instimtions on which garne theory as a behavioral theory sheds light. In particular, we illustrate the ways in which legal rules influence individual behavior. Our second is to emphasize the mechanism design aspect that underlies many game-theoretic analyses of the law. Our third is to examine some of the difficulties in the use of game-theoretic concepts to clarify legal doctrine. In Section 2, we examine the simple two-person garne that underlies much of the economic analysis of accidents as well as the analysis of contract remedies and tort. In this model, the legal rule serves as a direct incentive mechanism. In Section 3, we examine the insights that game-theoretic models have provided into the "Coase Theorem" which often serves as an analytic starting point for economic analyses of law. In Section 4 we introduce a literature that extends the use of garne theory as a behavioral predictor from private law to public law and the analysis of constitutions. Section 5 discusses the small literature that has used game theory in doctrinal analysis. Section 6 offers some concluding remarks.
4 E.g., Bebchuk (1994), Bulow and Klemperer (1996), Cramton and Schwartz (1991), Grossman and Hart (1982), Kahan and Tuckman (1993) and Sercu and van Hulle (1995). 5 E.g.,Oi (1973), Kambhu (1982), Polinskyand Rogerson(1983), and Geistfeld (1995). 6 E.g., Bebchuk (1984), Daughety and Reinganum (1993), Hay (1995), Png (1982), Reinganum (1988), Reinganum and Wilde (1986), Shavell (1982), Spier (1992, 1994). 7 E.g.,Priest and Klein (1984), Eisenberg (1990), Wittman (1988).
Ch. 60: Game-TheoreticAnalysis of LegalRules and Institutions
2233
2. Economic analysis of the c o m m o n law when contracting costs are infinite
2.1. The basic model Brown (1973) offers a simple model of accident law. We discuss it extensively here for two reasons. First, it underlies many, if not most, economic analyses of law that examine how legal rules can solve externality problems. Second, and more importantly, this simple model of torts illustrates clearly the use of garne theory as a theory of the behavior of agents in response to legal rules. There are three decisionmakers: the legal policymaker, generally thought of as the Court, and two agents, called the (potential) injurer I and the (potential) victim V. Agents I and V are each independently engaged in an activity that may result in harm to V. They simultaneously choose an amount x and y, respectively, to expend on care. These amounts determine the probability p(x, y) with which V may experience a loss and the value L(x, y) of such a loss. The functions p(x, y) and L(x, y) are c o m m o n knowledge. The policymaker seeks to regulate the (risk-neutral) agents' choices of care levels. The policymaker selects a legal rule from a family of permissible rules of the form R (x, y; X, Y), where R (x, y; X, Y) is the proportion of the loss L (x, y) legally imposed on I , and the parameters X ~> 0 and Y ~> 0 will be interpreted as I ' s and V's standard of care, respectively. Although this framework is simple, it enables a comparison of many legalrules. Thus, a general regime of negligence with contributory negligence is characterized by a loss assignment function of the form:
R(x,y;X,Y) =
{1 0
ifx<Xandy~>Y, otherwise.
(la)
Under a pure negligence rule the injttrer is responsible whenever she falls to take an "adequate" level of care; this corresponds to 0 < X < ec, Y ----0. With strict liability the injurer is responsible for damage regardless of the level of care she takes; this corresponds to X = ~ , and Y ----0. 8 Under strict liability with contributory negligence the injurer is responsible whenever the victim takes an adequate level of care; thus, X = oe, 0
8 The legal literature generally distinguishes between "strict liability rules" and "negligence mies". As the text indicates, a strict liability rule (without contributory negligence) can be understood as a member of the general class of negligence with contributory negligence mles. A different distinction between strict liability and negligence mies is suggested by Equation (lb) below; namely, that untier strict liability the default bearer of liability, i.e., the party who bears the loss when each party meets her standard of care, is the injurer rather than the victim.
J.-P.Benottand L.A. Kornhauser
2234
Strict liability with dual contributory negligence has a different pattern of liability defined by:
R ( x , y ; X, Y) =
{1 0
ifx<Xory>/Y,
(lb)
otherwise. 9
Under a rule of comparative negligence, R may assume values strictly between 0 and 1 when each party fails to meet its standard of care. Any given rule R(x, y; X, Y) defines a two-person non-zero-sum garne between l and V. Each agent seeks a level of care that minimizes her expected personal costs. Thus, I chooses x to minimize:
x + p(x, y)L(x, y)R(x, y; X, Y)
(2)
while V chooses y in order to minimize:
y ÷ p(x, y)L(x, y)[1 - R(x, y; X, Y)].
(3)
In principle, an economic analysis studies the equilibria of these various garnes. Once these equilibria have been identified, the policymaker can choose the rule that induces the best equilibrium, given the social objective function. The analysis is thus not inextricably linked to a search for an efficient or welfare maximizing rule. One can as easily search for the rule that minimizes the accident rate or equalizes care expenditures or for any other social objective that the policymaker seeks to implement. One way to proceed would be to analyze the case law to identify the Court's objective function and then choose the legal rule that induces the equilibrium that is best in these terms. In practice, however, and perhaps unfortunately, the literature has to a large extent chosen as objective function the minimization of the expected social costs of accidents, 1° That is, the minimization of:
x + y + p(x, y)L(x, y).
(4)
Let (x*, y*) be the (assumed) unique minimizing care levels. Consider the common law regime of negligence with contributory negligence as characterized by (1 a). Clearly choosing standards X ----x* and Y = y* induces the agents to take the optimal levels
9 In fact, if we rename the parties, the pattern of liability under this rule is identical to the pattern under negligencewith contributorynegligence.Put differently,in Brown's modelùthe loss is perfectly transferable between parties and the legal mle simply assigns the loss to one party or another. This is not an adequate model of personal injury, since a personal injury may alter V's utilityfunction, and some injuriesmay not be compensable.See, for example,Arlen(1992) for a modificationthat addresses the problemof personalinjury. 10 Diamond(1974b), Kornhauserand Schotter (1992), and Endres and Quemer (1995) study how the equilibria change as the standards of care change and are thus examples of excepfionsto this general practice.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and lnstitutions
2235
of care. However, these are not the only such standards. In fact, an infinite number of rules of the form {X = x*, Y E [0, y*]} and of the form {X ~ [M, cx~] for sufficiently large M, Y = y*} induce an equilibrium in which the agents adopt care levels that are socially optimal. Consider first a rule with X = x* and Y ~< y*. When I chooses x*, V is responsible for the total loss, i.e., R = 0. From (3) V chooses y to minimize:
y + p(x*, y)L(x*, y) But this is just (4) shifted down by x* (given that I chooses x*) so that (3) is also minimized at y*. Likewise, given V's choice of y*, I minimizes (2) by choosing x*. 11 A similar argument shows that (x*, y*) is the equilibrium for those garnes in which Y = y* and X is sufficienfly large. Thus, efficiency can be obtained even if the court can only observe the level of care being taken by orte of the parties. In particular, if the court can only observe x, then an appropriate pure negligence rule is efficient - the court sets X = x*, Y = 0 and lets V, whose action it cannot observe, optimize against l ' s choice. Similarly, when the court only observes y, the strict liability with contributory negligence rule (X = ~ , Y = y*) is efficient. Notice that these payoff functions, which accurately capture the structure of the negligence rule, are discontinuous at the standard of care.12 This discontinuity plays an important role in generating the efficient outcome, because it allows both agents to "see" the full cost of their decisions. For example with the rule X = x* and Y = 0, I bears the full cost of the accident in the event he chooses x < x*, and none of the cost at x = x*. Therefore, at a choice of x = x*, I ' s marginal cost of lowering x is the entire accident cost. At the same time, when I chooses x = x*, V bears the entire loss and sees the full cost of her actions. 2.2. E x t e n s i o n s w i t h i n a c c i d e n t l a w
Several modificafions of this basic framework have been studied. Shavell (1987) analyzes a model in which each party chooses both a level of care and a level of activity, but the allocafion of the loss still depends only on the parties' choice of care levels. Unsurprisingly, no legal rule can induce both parties to choose efficient acfivity levels and efficient care levels; after all, the court has only one instrument (for each party) to
11 (X*, y*) is the only pure strategy equilibriumfor games with the standards of care as indicated. Suppose I chooses x f < x*. If V chooses yl < Y, then V's cost is yt + p ( x ~, j ) L ( x ~, y ) > x* - x I + y* + p ( x *, y *) L (x *, y *) > y* > Y. Therefore V would choose Y and l's best response to Y is X = x* ~ x t. If I chooses x > x*, she rnakes urmecessaryexpenditureson care. 12 Kahan(1989), however, argues that these payofffunetionsdo not correctly modelthe measure of damages. He contends that, in an appropriate model, the payoffs are continuousfunctions.These functionsstill show the agent the full marginalcost of her decisions.
2236
J.-P. Behobt and L.A. Kornhauser
control the two decisions that each party makes. One can still identify the rule that is best given the social objective function. Shavell (1987) also investigates the impact of an insurance market on care decisions. (See also Winter (1991) for a discussion of the dynamics of the market for liability insurance.) A number of other variants of this model have also been analyzed. Green (1976) and Emons and Sobel (1991), for example, study the equilibria of the basic model of negligence with contributory negligence when injurers differ in the cost of care. Beard (1990) and Kornhauser and Revesz (1990) consider the effects of the potential insolvency of the parties on care choice. Shavell (1983) and Wittman (1981) analyze garnes with a sequential strucmre. Leong (1989) and Arlen (1990) smdy negligence with contributory negligence rules when both the victim and the injurer suffer damage. Arlen (1992) studies these same rules when the agents suffer personal (or non-pecuniary) injury. Several authors have integrated the analysis of the incentives to take care into a fuller description of the litigation process that enforces liability rules. Ordover (1978) shows that when litigation costs are positive some injurers will be negligent in equilibrium. Craswell and Calfee (1986) studies how uncertainty concerning legal standards affects the equilibria. Polinsky and Shavell (1989) studies the effects of errors in fact-finding on the probability that a victim will bring suit and hence on the incentives to comply with the law. Hylton (1990, 1995) introduces costly litigation and legal error. Png (1987) and Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1988) study the effect of the rate of settlement on compliance. Png (1987) and Hylton (1993) consider how the rule allocating the costs of litigation between the parties affects the incentives to take care. Cooter, Kornhauser, and Lane (1979) assumes that the court only observes "local" information about the private costs of care and the costs of accidents. In their model the courts adjust the standards of care over time and converge to the optimum. Polinsky (1987b) compares strict liability to negligence when the injurer is uncertain about the size of the loss the victim will suffer. Many authors have compared the efficiency of negligence with contributory negligence rules to comparative negligence rules. Under a rule of comparative negligence injurer and victim share the loss when both fail to meet the standard of care. That is, the injurer pays the share
R(x, y; X, Y) =
1 f (x, y; X, Y) 0
1
f o r x < X a n d y ~> Y, f o r x < X and y < Y, otherwise (x/> 0),
where 0 ~< f ( x , y; X, Y) ~< 1. Landes and Posner (1980) argues that both rules can induce efficient caretaking; Haddock and Curran (1985) and Cooter and Ulen (1986) argue for the superiority of comparative negligence when actual care levels are observed with error; Edlin (1994) argues that with the appropriate choice of standards of care the two rules perform equally well even when such error is present. Rubinfeld (1987)
Ch. 60: Game-TheoreticAnalysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2237
considers the performance of comparative negligence when the court cannot observe the private costs of care.
2.3. Other interpretations of the model This model can be recast to yield insights into other areas of law. Indeed, some [Cooter (1985)] have suggested that the pervasiveness of this model shows the inherent unity of the c o m m o n law. While this claim seems too strong - c o m m o n law rules govern a wider set of interactions than those described here - the model does illuminate a wide variety of legal institutions. To begin, we reinterpret the problem in terms o f remedies for breach of contract. Consider, for example, two parties, a buyer B and a seller S, contemplating an exchange. 13 B requires a part produced by S. The value to B of the part depends upon the level of investment y that B makes in advance of delivery. Denote this value by v (y). y is known as the "reliance" level, as it indicates the extent to which B is relying upon receiving the part. S agrees to deliver the part and chooses an investment level x. This results in a probability [1 - p ( x ) ] that S will successfully deliver the part and a probability p ( x ) that he will not perform the contract. B pays S an amount k up front for the part. A legal rule R(x, y) determines the amount R(x, y ) v ( y ) that S taust pay B if S fails to deliver the part. S then chooses x to maximize:
k - x - p ( x ) v ( y ) R ( x , y),
(5)
while B simultaneously chooses y to maximize: - k - y + [1 - p ( x ) ] v ( y ) + p ( x ) R ( x , y ) v ( y ) .
(6)
This model is perfectly congruent to Brown's basic model of Section 2.1. To see this, first subtract a term g(y) from the victim's objective function (3). We interpret g(y) as V's (added) payoff from her investment of y, should no accident occur. In Brown's basic model g(y) is zero. This corresponds to a potential victim who, by taking care, can reduce the value of her assets that are at risk, say by putting some o f them in a fireproof safe, but whose actions have no effect on the overall value of the assets. On the other hand, consider a potential victim whose investment deterrtfines the value of some assets should no accident occur, but which assets will be completely lost in the event of an accident. Then g(y) = L ( y ) ( = L(x, y)) in (3). If this investment affects only the value of the assets, and not the probability that they are lost, then p(x, y) = p(x). Now the accident model o f Equations (2) and (3) is identical to the breach of contract model (5) and (6) (with v(y) -- L ( y ) and k = 0).
13 The model in the text is similar to ones presented in Shavell (1980), Kornhauser (1983) and Rogerson (1984).
J.-P. Beno?tand L.A. Kornhauser
2238
Thus, the accident interpretation and the contract interpretation differ largely in the characterization o f the net benefits o f the victim's action. Despite this congmence, courts, and analysts, have treated these situations differently. Rather than rules setting standards o f care X and Y to determine liability for breach of conlract, courts have commonly used a "reliance measure", R(x, y) = R(y) = y / v ( y ) (so that R ( y ) v ( y ) = y),14 and an expectation measure, R (x, y) = 1. These measures of contract damages are mles of"strict liability" as the amount of the seller's liability is not contingent on its own decisions; they are also "actual damage" measures as they depend on the actual, as opposed to any hypothetical, choice of the Buyer. It is easy to see that neither of these two damage measures will generally induce an efficient level of care and reliance. The total expected social welfare of the contract is [1 - p(x)]v(y) - x
- y.
Let (x*, y*) maximize this social welfare function] 5 Thus,
p'(x*) = - 1 / v ( y * ) , or p ( x * ) = 0 a n d p'(x*) < 1/v(y*), v'(y*) = 1 / ( 1 - p(x*)). When R(y) = 1, B ' s maximizing choice, Ye, is independent of S's action and is implicitly defined by v l ( y e ) = 1. Given this, S's equilibrium action is defined by:
p' (Xe) = -1/V(ye). Note that (Xe, Ye) = (x*, y*) only when p(x*) = 0. W h e n p(x*) ~ O, this expectation measure leads to too much reliance on the part of B; S, however, adopts the optimal amount of care given B ' s reliance. Under the reliance measure R (y) = y / v (y), B ag ain maximizes independently of S by setting: vI(yr)=l.
14 R(y)v(y) = y is one interpretation of a reliance measure. Some legal commentators understand reliance as a measure that places the promisee in the same position he would have been in had the contract not been made. Reliance then includes the opportunity cost of entering the contract. On this interpretation, reliance damages would equal expectation damages in a competitivemarket. 15 We assume sufficientconditions for a unique nonzero solution, and that all out functions are differentiable.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and lnstitutions
2239
S's equilibrium action is now defined by: p'(xr) = -1/yr. Again Yr is efficient only if p(xr) = 0. In this case, S adopts the efficient level of care too. Otherwise, B under-relies and S breaches too frequently given B's reliance. We may also use this example to suggest how non-efficiency concems might enter into the legal analysis. Consider a technology in which, by taking a reasonable amount of care, S can get p close to 0; further reductions in p a r e very costly without much gain. Indeed, there may be a residual uncertainty which S cannot avoid. Then the solutions to the three programs above may well all result in a very small probability of nonperformance. The solutions will all be close to each other, so that faimess considerations may easily outweigh efficiency considerations. Under the reliance measure, for instance, when S fails to deliver despite his "best efforts" he taust only repay B for B's out-of-pocket (or reliance) losses, rather than the loss of B's potential gain, which may be quite high. 16 Brown's model of accident law is easily converted to a model of the taking of property. The Fifth Amendment to the Constimtion of the United States requires that "property not be taken for a public use without compensation". How does the level of required compensation affect the extent to which the landowner develops her land and the nature of the public takings? We follow the model in Hermalin (1995). Let the landowner choose an amount y to expend on land development, resulting in a property value v(y). v(y) is an increasing function of her investment. The value of the land to the government is a random value whose realization is unknown at the time the landowner chooses his investment level. Let q(a) denote the probability that the value of the land in public hands will be greater than a, and let p(y) = q (v(y)). Assume that the state appropriates the land if and only if it is worth more in public bands than in private hands. As before, we
16 Orte might convert this fairness argument into an efficiency argument by extending the analysis to consider why B does not choose to integrate vertically with S. A number of other aspects of contract law bare also been modeled. Hadfield (1994) considers complications created by the inability of courts to observe actions. Hermalin and Katz (1993) examines why contracts do not cover all contingencies. Katz (1990a, 1990b, 1993) has studied doctrines surrounding offer and acceptance, which determine when a contract has been formed. Various authors - e.g., Posner and Rosenfield (1977), White (1988), and Sykes (1992) - have considered the related doctrines of impossibility and impracticability which are, in a sense, the converse of breach as they state conditions under which contractual obligation is discharged. Rasmusen and Ayres (1993) examine the doctrines governing unilateral and bilateral mistake. Polinsky (1983, 1987a) addresses some more general questions of the risk-bearing features of contract that are raised by the mistake and impossibility doctrines. The rule of Hadley v. Baxendale has also received rauch attention as in Perloff (1981), Ayres and Gertner (1989, 1992), Bebchuk and Shavell (1991), and Jolmston (1990). The latter four articles are particularly concerned with the role of the legal rule in inducing parties to reveal information.
J.-P.Benoitand L.A. Kornhauser
2240
consider compensation rules of the form R(y)v(y). Then the landowner chooses y to maximize: - y + (1 - p(y))v(y) + p(y)R(y)v(y).
(7)
Note that (7) is identical to (6), when k = 0 and p is written more generally as
p(x, y). Suppose that the state is benevolent so that its objective function is riet social value: - y + [1 - p(y)]v(y) + E[a[a > v(y)].
(8)
The govemment chooses R (y) to maximize (8), given the landowner's program (7). 17 As a simple example, consider a rule R(y) = a and suppose that the land is either worth more to the state than max v(y) or worth less than v(0) (perhaps a new rail line taust be situated). Thus p1(y) _=O, E1(v(y)) = 0 and efficiency demands that:
v'(y) = 1/[1 - p(y)]. The landowner maximizes by setting:
v'(y) = 1/[1 - p(y)(1 - et)]. Efficiency calls for no compensation, i.e., ot = 0. However, if p(y) is small, then setting « = 1 may be fairer while causing only a small loss in total welfare. It is striking that radically different legal institutions are captured by models that are structurally so similar. W h y do legal institutions vary so much across what seem to be structurally similar strategic situations? The literature does not offer a clear answer; indeed, it has not explicitly addressed the issue. Three suggestions follow. First, the nature of the externality differs slightly across legal institutions. In the accident case, the likelihood of an adverse outcome depends on the care choices of each party. In the contract case, the seUer determines the likelihood of breach while the buyer determines the size of the loss. In the takings context, the landowner determines the market value of the land. Perhaps the shifting judicial approaches reflect important differences in the court's ability to monitor the differing transactions. Second, the differences in institutions may reflect different values that the courts seek to further in the differing contexts. Finally, the judges who developed these common law solutions may not have
17 Aualysesof takings as in Blumeet al. (1984) and Fischeland Perry (1989) are more complexbecausethey are set in a broader frameworkin which the govemmentmust also set taxes in order to financethe takings. In this context orte is able to considera non-benevolentgovernmentas well. This governmentacts in the interest of the majofity; see Fischel and Perry (1989) and Hermalin(1995). Hermalin, whose analysisis explieitly normative, examines a set of non-standardcompensationrules as well. We have ignored these complexities because we are interestedin showingthe doctrinalreaeh of the simplemodel.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal RuIes and Institutions
2241
perceived the common strategic features of these situations and thus may have generated a multiplicity of responses.1 •
3. Is law important? Understanding the Coase Theorem The analysis of accident law in the prior section assumed that the parties could not negotiate or enforce agreements concerning the level of care that each should adopt. The interpretation of the model as orte of accidents between strangers presents a situation in which such a bar to negotiation is plausible; the pedestrian contemplating a stroll rarely has the opportunity to negotiate with all drivers who might strike her during her ramble. Under other interpretations, however, the barriers to negotiation are less. In these contexts, one must confront a seductive, though ill-specified, argument for the irrelevance of certain legal rules. This irrelevance argument is generally attributed to Ronald Coase (1960) who argued through two examples that the assignment of liability would not, in the absence of t r a n s a c t i o n costs, affect the economic efficiency of the behavior of agents because an "incorrect" assignment of liability could always be corrected through private, enforceable agreements. This insight has come to be known as the Coase Theorem. In the context of contract remedies, for example, the parties could negotiate a contingent claims contract specifying the level of reliance that the buyer should undertake. Coase also emphasized that the assignment of liability might indeed matter when transaction costs were present. Coase never actually stated a "theorem" and subsequent scholars have had difficulty formulating a precise statement. Precision is difficult because Coase argued from example and did not clearly define several key concepts in the argument. In particular, "transaction costs" are never defined and the legal background in which the parties act is underspecified. Garne theorists have generally treated the theorem as a claim about bargaining and, as we shall see, have used both the tools of cooperative and non-cooperative garne theory to illuminate our understanding of Coase's examples. The Coase Theorem, however, is also a claim about the importance of legal rules to bargaining outcomes. At the outset, we must thus understand precisely which legal rules are in question so that they may be modeled appropriately. The Coase Theorem implicates two sets of legal rules: the rules of contract and the assignment of entitlements. The rules of contract determine which agreements are legally enforceable and what the consequences of non-performance of a contract are. For the Coase Theorem to hold, the courts should be willing to enforce every contract and the consequences of non-performance should be sufficiently grave to deter non-performance. Absent this possibility, repetition and reputation effects might ensure compliance with contracts in certain situations.
18 We thank a refereefor suggesting this third possibility.
2242
J.-P. Beno'it and L.A. Kornhauser
The entitlement defines the initial package of legal relations over which the parties negotiate. 19 This package identifies the set of actions which the entitlement holder is free to undertake and the consequences to others for interfering with the entitlement holder's enjoyment of her entitlement. The law and economics literature, drawing on Calabresi and Melamed (1972), has generally focused on the two forms of entitlement protection called property rules and liability rules. Under a property rule, all transfers must be consensual; consequently the transfer price is set by the entitlement holder herself. Under a liability rule, an agent may force the transfer of the entitlement; if the parties fall to agree on a price, a court sets the price at which the entitlement transfers. Consider, for example, two adjoining landowners A and B. B wishes to erect a building which will obstmct A's coastal view. Suppose A has an entitlement to her view. Property rule protection of A's entitlement means that A may enjoin B's interfering use of bis land and thus subject B to severe fines or imprisonment for contempt should B erect the building. Put differently, A may set any price, including infinity, for the sale of his view, without regard to the "reasonableness" of this price. Under a liability rule, A's recourse against B is limited to an action for damages. Put differently, should B erect a building against A's wishes, the courts will determine a reasonable "sale" price for the loss of A's view. The Coase Theorem is commonly understood as a claim that, in a world of "zero transaction costs", the nature and assignment of the entitlement does not affect the final allocation of real resources; in this sense, then, legal rules are irrelevant. One might ask two very different questions about the asserted irrelevance of legal rules. First, one might assume a perfect law of contract and specify more precisely what "zero transaction costs" means in order to assure the irrelevance of the assignment of entitlements. Alternatively, one might ask how "imperfect" contract law could be without disturbing the irrelevance of the assignment of the entitlements. Following most of the literature, we investigate the first question. Much controversy revolves around the concept of transaction costs, At the most basic level, transaction costs involve such things as the time and money needed to bring the various parties together and the legal fees incurred in signing a contract. One may
19 An entitlementis actually a complex bundle of vafious types of legal relations. A classificationof legal relations offered by Hohfeld (1913) is useful. He identifiedeight fundamentallegal relations which can be presented as four pairs ofjural opposites: right duty
privilege p o w e r immunity no-right disability liability
When an individualhas a right to do X, she may invokestate power to preventinterferencewith her doing X. By contrast, if she has the privilege to do X, no one else may invoke the state to interfere (though they may be able to "interfere" in other ways). An individualmay hold a privilege without holding a right and conversely. When an individualhas a power, she has the authorityto alter the rights or privileges of another; if the individualholds an irnmunity(withrespect to a particularright or privilege),no one has a power to alter it. Kennedyand Michelman(1980) apply this classificationto illuminatedifferentregimes of property and contract.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2243
go further, however, and, somewhat tautologically, consider a transaction cost to constitute anything which prevents the consummation of efficient trades. Game theory has clarified the different impediments to trade by focusing on two types of barriers: those that arise from strategic interaction per se and those that arise from incomplete information. We might then understand the Coase Theorem as one of two claims about bargaining. 2° First, we might understand the Coase Theorem as a claim that bargains are efficient regardless of the assignment and nature of the entitlement. Call this the Coase Strong Efficient Bargaining Claim. Second, we might understand the Coase Theorem as a claim that, although bargaining is not always efficient, the degree of efficiency is unaffected by the nature and assignment of the entitlement. Call this the Coase Weak Efficient Bargaining Claim. The game-theoretic investigations do provide some support for Coase's valuable insight. 21 However, the bulk of the analysis suggests that both Coase Claims are, in general, false. One set of arguments focuses on the strategic structure of garnes of complete information. A second set considers the problems created by bargaining under incomplete information. A third set circumvents the bargaining problem using cooperative garne theory. The next three subsections discuss each set of arguments in turn.
First, it is worthwhile emphasizing one point. Discussions of the Coase Theorem often characterize it as a claim that, under appropriate conditions, the legal regime is economically irrelevant. This loose characterization obscures an important fact. At most, the Coase Theorem asserts that efficiency may be unaffected by the assignment of the entitlements. There are, of course, other economic considerations. In particular, Coase never asserted that the final distribution of assets would be unaffected by the legal regime. On the contrary, every "proof" of the Coase Theorem relies on the parties negotiating transfers, the direction of which depends on the assignment of the entitlement. Thus, even in circumstances in which the Coase Theorem holds, the choice of a legal rule will certainly matter to the parties affected by its announcement and it may also matter to a policymaker.
3.1. The Coase Theorem and complete information Reconsider the injurer/victim model of Section 2.1. Suppose that I engages in an activity that may cause a fixed amount of damage, L(x, y) -- d, to agent V. Agent I can avoid causing this damage at a cost of c. That is, p(x, y) = 0 if x >~c, p(x, y) = 1 if x < c. Both c and d lie in the interval (0, 1). We assume that the benefit to I of the
20 The literature on the Coase Theorem is vast and offers a variety of characterizations of the claim. For overviews of the literature that offer accounts consistent with that in the text see Cooter (1987) and Veljanovski (1982). 21 Hoffman and Spitzer (1982, 1985, 1986) and Harrison and McAfee (1986) provide experimental evidence in support of the Coase Claims.
2244
z-Æ Beno) and LA. Kornhauser
activity is greater than 1, so that it is always socially desirable for I to undertake the potentially harmful activity. We can view V as being entitled to be free from damage. As previously noted, an entitlement can be protected with a property rule or a liability rule. Consider a compensation rule that specifies a lump sum M that I must pay V for damage. We interpret M ~> 1 as a property rule, since I will only fail to take care if V consents. 22 V's entitlement is protected by a liability rule when 0 < M < 1. Clearly, the larger M the greater the protection afforded V. When M = 0, V has no protection; this can be interpreted as giving I an entitlement to cause damage that is protected by a property rule. A surface analysis suggests that if M = 0, I will not take care since the damage I causes is external to I, whereas if M = 1, I will take care since c < 1. In particular, when M = 0 and c < d, I will cause harm to V, and when M = 1 and c > d I will take care, even though both these outcomes are inefficient. The Coase Theorem holds that this conclusion is unduly negative. For instance, when M = 0 and c < d, V could induce I to take care by offering I a side payment of, say, c + ( d - c ) / 2 . This is possible provided that "transaction costs" are not too high. If making the side payment involved a separate cost greater than (d - c), no mutually beneficial payment could be made. W h e n transaction costs are negligible then, for any values of c and d, and for any value of M, we might expect the firms to negotiate a mutually beneficial transfer which yields the efficient level of care. Note that even if this expectation is correct, it does n o t imply that the legal regime M is irrelevant, as M affects the direction and level of the transfer. While the insight that firms will have an incentive to "bargain around" any legal rule is important, the blunt assertion that they will successfully do so is hasty. Exactly how are the firms to settle on an appropriate transfer? What if, with c < d, V offers to pay c to I , while I insists upon receiving d ? Negotiations could break down, resulting in the inefficient outcome of no care being taken. In any case, Coase did not specify the bargaining game which would permit us to rule out this possibility. Suppose that firms always seek to reach mutually beneficial arrangements and that they can costlessly implement any contract upon which they agree. Consider the polar cases of M = 0, and M = 1. A simple dominance argument shows that in the former case I will never take care when c > d, since it is dominated for V to pay I more than d to take care. Thus, there will never be more than an efficient level of care taken. Similarly, when M ( x , d) = 1 there will never be less than an efficient level of care. Without additional assumptions no more than this can be guaranteed. In particular, the legal regime may affect the level of care taken and the Coase Theorem fails in both its
22 This characterization of a property rule is not wholly satisfactory because the court might enforce a property rule by injunction (and by contempt proceedings should the injunction be violated). Thus this characterization might differ from the operation of such a legal rule should I act irrationally.
Ch. 60: Game-TheoreticAnalysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2245
forms. To establish a Coase Theorem one requires additional structure. Notice that the material facts do not in themselves determine this additional structure. To eväluate the Coase Theorem we taust posit a baxgaining garne and examine how its solufion changes with legal regimes. Consider any legal rule M and a simple garne in which V makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer to I . Then, in the unique subgame perfect equilibrium, when c < d V offers I a side-payment o f max[c - M, 0] to take care and I takes care. Hence I takes care regardless of the legalrule. W h e n c > d, V offers to accept a side-payment of min[c, M] from I if I does not take care, and under every legal rule I does not take care. In both cases, the efficient outcome is reached regardless of the legal rule M(c, d). This is a particulafly simple model of bargalning. Rubinstein (1982) offers a more sophisticated model in which two parfies alternatingly propose divisions of a surplus unfil one of the parties accepts the other's offer. In out present situation, if c < d there is a surplus when care is taken and if c > d there is a surplus when care is not taken, regardless of the rule M(c, d). Suppose that when c < d, in pefiod 1 V offers I a payment to take care. If I rejects the payment, in period 2 1 makes a counterdemand of a payment. If V rejects I ' s proposal he makes a counteroffer in period 3 and so forth. W h e n c > d the garne is the same except that the payments are for not taking care. Each party attaches a subjecfive time cost to delay and the garne ends when an offer is accepted or when I decides to act unilaterally. Rubinstein's results imply thät for all M(c, d) the parties instantly agree upon an efficient transfer. Thus, we have some support for the Coase Strong Efficient Bargaining Claim. However, the result that bargaining will be efficient is delicate. Shaked has shown that with three or more agents bargaining in Rubinstein's model m a y be inefficient. 23 Avery and Z e m s k y (1994) present a unifying discussion of a variety o f bargaining models that result in inefficient bargaining. 24 Perhaps most importantly, we have been assuming complete information. We consider incomplete information in the next section.
3.2. The Coase Theorem and incomplete information Generally, we might expect a firm to possess more information about its costs than outside agents possess. We now modify the model of the previous section in this direction. Specifically, following Kaplow and Shavell (1996), suppose that while ! knows the cost c of taking care, V knows only that c is distributed with continuous positive density f ( c ) on the unit interval. Similarly, while V knows the level o f damage d which I would cause, I knows only that d is distributed with density g(d) on the unit interval.
Shaked's model is discussed in Osborne and Rubinstein (1990). These models, which include Fernandez and Glazer (1991) and Harter and Holden (1990), all have complete information. 23
24
2246
J.-P. Benoft and L.A. Kornhauser
We focus on the two rules M = 0 and M = 1. f a l l these rules M0 and M1, respectively. Notice that to implement M0 and M1 the court only needs to know whether or not damage has occurred. Efficiency requires that I take care whenever c < d. Let Si = { ( c , d ) l l takes care under rule Mi}. The strong efficient bargaining claim asserts that So = Sl = {(c, d)lc <~ d}. 25 Call this set E. The weak efficient bargaining claim could be taken to mean one of two things; that So = S1 7~ E or that, although So 7~ S1, M0 and M1 are equally inefficient (given a measure of the degree of inefficiency of rules). Again consider the simple bargaining procedure in which V makes a take-it-or-leaveit offer to I. Consider first the situation when M0 prevails. Then V m a y seek to bribe I to take care. We calculate how V's offer to buy I ' s right to cause harm varies with V's damage cost d. Suppose V of type d makes an offer of o(d) to I. I accepts if c «. o(d). Thus, when V makes an offer of o(d), he incurs expected costs of F(o(d))o(d) + (1 F(o(d))d. These costs are minimized by that o(d) which satisfies
o(d) = d - F ( o ( d ) ) / f ( o ( d ) ) . Call this value oo(d). Thus: SO = { ( c , d ) I c ~< oo(d)}. Since oo (d) < d efficiency fails in the presence of incomplete information, the strong efficiency claim is false. 26 To check the Weak Efficiency Claim we examine the effect of a change in the legal regime. Consider the situation when M1 prevails. V m a y now offer to sell I the right to cause the harm. Suppose that V offers to forego his damage payment of 1 at a price o(d). I accepts if c > o(d) as it would be cheaper for I to buy the right than to avoid the harm. Thus, when V makes an offer of o (d), he expects profits of (1 - F(o(d))(o(d) - d). These profits are maximized by that o(d) which satisfies
o(d) -- d + [1 - F (o(d) ) ]/ f (o(d) ). Call this value
01 (d).
Thus:
Sl = {(c,d) lc <~ ol(d)}. Since o~(d) > d, again efficiency fails. There is an important difference in regimes M0 and M1, however. Under M0, there are instances when efficiency demands
25 Of course, if c = d efficiencypermits that care either be taken or not taken. Throughout, we will be a little loose as to what happens at degenerate "equality" points. 26 hadeed, Myerson and Satterthwaite (1983) show that, quite generally, bargaining rinder incomplete informarion will be ineflicient.
Ch. 60: Game-TheoreticAnalysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2247
that I take care but he does not. In no case does I take care when he should not. In contrast, under M1, there may be too much care taken, but never too little. 27 F r o m this comparison, we m a y conclude that the Weak Efficiency Claim is false in both its forms. For instance, if F places more weight in the interval [oo(d), d] than in the interval [d, o1(d)] then Mo results in an inefficient level of care more orten than M1 does. 28
3.3. A cooperative game-theoretic approach to the Coase Theorem In the example of the previous section the firms were in a situation of asymmetric information. One might interpret the difficulties imposed by this asymmetric information as an informational transaction cost, thereby rescuing the Coase Theorem. Similarly, orte might interpret the inefficiencies that arise with three or more agents in a Rubinsteintype bargaining model as resulting from strategic transaction costs. On this view, cooperative game theory would seem to provide the best hope for the Coase Strong Efficiency Claim. After all, the characteristic function form of a game simply posits that firms can reach any agreement they choose, effectively assuming away any "bargaining costs". Consider the classic externality problem in which air pollution generated by two factories interferes with the operation o f a nearby laundry. There are two possible assignments of the entitlement: (1) the factories pay for damage caused to the laundry and (2) the factories do not pay for such damage. Each of these assignments yields a game in characteristic function form that derives from the underlying technological interaction between factories and laundry. In this context, orte might formulate the Coase Theorem as a claim either that the (relevant) solution to each of the garnes is the same or that each solution contains only equally efficient allocations. Although there is no general theory that studies (or even formulates) this problem, it is easy to provide examples that contradict each claim. We present here a modification of the examples undeflying Aivazian and Callen ( 1981 ) and Aivazian, Callen, and Lipnowski (1987). There are three firms. Firms 1 and 2 are industrial factories, and firm 3 is a laundry. Each firm can operate at one level or shut down. Firm 3 operating on its own earns a profit of 9. If either firm 1 or 2 operates, however, a pollution cost of 2 is imposed on firm 3. If both firms 1 and 2 operate, independently or jointly, a cost of 8 is imposed on firm 3. Firms 1 and 2 operating independently each earn a profit of 1, regardless of the actions of other firms. Firms 1 and 2 operating together earn joint profits of 7.
27 This is in keeping with a claim from the previous section. 28 Several authors have considered the differential effects of legal rules on the revelation of private information. Ayres and Gertner (1989) argues that this consideration should inform judicial choice of contract default rules. The response to their clalm [Johnston (1990)], their reply [Ayres and Gertner (1992)], and a related analysis [Bebchuk and Shavell (1991)] provide insight into the force of Coase Theorem arguments in contract law. See also Ayres and Talley (1995) and Kaplow and Shavell (1996). Johnston's (1995) study of the effects of blurriness in the entitlement in situations of incomplete information provides related insights.
2248
~ - ~ Beno~ a n d L A . Kornhauser
We must define two characteristic function form games: orte in which the laundry legally bears the pollution cost, and one in which the factories legally bear the cost. In general, defining a characteristic function game from underlying data is not altogether obvious. For instance, in defining the value of a firm operating on its own, should it be assumed that the other firms operate independently or jointly? Should it be assumed that the other firms maximize their profits or that they minirnize the profits of the firm under consideration? Out example has been chosen to circumvent these difficulties. Here, the same game is defined regardless of how these questions are answered. We first derive the characteristic function of the garne in which the laundry bears the pollution costs. We have v(3) = 1; this value of 1 is obtained by taking the 9 that firm 1 earns by operating and subtracting the cost of 8 which is imposed upon it by firms 1 and 2 operating separately or jointly, v(23) = 7 since the best that these firms can do jointly is have firm 2 shut down and firm 3 operate. Their profits are then 9 minus the cost of 2 imposed by firm 1. v(123) = 9; firm 3 alone operates, since having one of the other firms also operate would yield the grand coalition a total of 8 and having all three firms operate would yield it 3. Similar reasoning yields the following characteristic function:
v(1)=v(2)=v(3)=l;
v(12)=v(13)=v(23)=7;
v(123)=9.
Consider now a liability regime in which the court awards damages to the laundry based upon the maximal possible return to any coalition containing the laundry. Under such a regime we have: w(1) = w(2) = w(12) = 0;
w(3) = w(13) = w(23) = w(123) = 9.
The Coase Theorem relates the solutions of the two games v and w. Possibly the most important solution concept for cooperative games is the core. The core of the liability garne w consists of the unique point (0, 0, 9). On the other hand, the no-liability garne v has an empty core. Informal Coase-type reasoning would hold that in the absence of a liability rule, firm 3 will simp]y bribe firms 1 and 2 not to produce, say by offering each of them 3.5. However, such an arrangement is unstable. Firm 1, for instance, could suggest a separate agreement just between itself and firm 3. Since the core is empty, there is in fact no arrangement among the three firms which cannot be blocked by a subset of them. A1though there are no (obvious) transaction costs, it is quite possible that the firms will fall to settle on an efficient outcome. On the other hand, in the liability regime of game w, the efficient outcome in which only firm 3 produces is the obvious stable outcome. Given that the core of v is empty we might want to consider other solution concepts. The Shapley value and nucleolus are both the point (0, 0, 9) for w and the point (3, 3, 3) for v. These solution concepts always exist and are always efficient for superadditive
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and lnstitutions
2249
games so that this Coasean result is not terribly revealing about the validity of the Strong Efficiency Claim. 29 Now consider the bargaining set) ° For the game w the bargaining set still consists of the unique point (0, 0, 9). For v, however, while the efficient outcome (3, 3, 3) with coalitional structure {(123)} is an element of the bargaining set, the inefficient point (1, 3.5, 3.5) with coalitional structure {1, (23)} is also an element of the bargaining set) 1 Note that this inefficient outcome in which firms 2 and 3 form a coalition is better for firms 2 and 3 than the efficient element of the bargaining set (and better than the Shapley value and nucleolus). The complete information, no transaction cost world of cooperative garne theory might seem to be the perfect setting for the Coase Theorem. However, even here the theorem is problematic; the choice of entitlement might very well matter to a legal policymaker concerned solely with efficiency. Clearly, a policymaker with other concerns or faced with a more recalcitrant environment or a policymaker designing the contract regime rather than assigning the entitlement will also need to evaluate the solutions of games defined by different legal rules.
4. Game-theoretic analyses of legal rulemaking Legal controversies arise over broad questions concerning the structure of adjudication and the consequences of specific legal doctrines. Garne theory has played an increasingly important role in illuminating these structural questions. Schwartz (1992), Cameron (1993), Kornhauser (1992, 1996) and Rasmusen (1994), for instance, have analyzed the practice of precedent both within a court and with respect to lower court obedience to higher court decisions. Others have addressed the claim that judicial review of legislative action is countermajoritarian (see, e.g., Ferejohn and Shipan (1990) and the effects of specific decisions of the United States Supreme Court [e.g., Cohen and Spitzer (1995)]. Eskridge and Ferejohn (1992) employs a now standard model to illuminate difficult questions of the interrelation of Congress, administrative agencies and the courts. In principle, under the U.S. Constitution policy is promulgated through Congress, with the policy views of the President accommodated to some extent because of the existence of the presidential veto power. The recent rise of lawmaking promulgated by administrative agencies under the control of the President has shifted additional power
29 The difference in the solutions for the two garnes, however, may be of great significance to a legal policymaker whose social objective extends beyondefficiencyto fainaess or other concerns. 30 See Aumann and Maschler (1964) for a definition of the bargaining set. We are using the definition of M**. 31 Other elements of the bargaining set are (1, 1, 1) for coalitional structure {(1), (2), (3)}, (3.5, 3.5, 1) for coalitional structure {(1, 2), (3)}, and (3.5, 1, 3.5) for coalitional structure {(1, 3)}. See Aivasian, Callen, and Lipnowski (1987) for a derivation (in an equivalent game).
2250
J.-P. Benoft and L.A. Kornhauser
r
J
r
I
I
I
I
r
P
h
tH
s
H
ts
S
SQ
Diagram 1.
to the President. In response, Congress has attempted to redress the balance by assuming the power to veto administrative action. In Immigration and Nationalization Service v. Chadha, the Supreme Court ruled such legislative vetoes unconstitutional. Eskridge and Ferejohn analyze the consequences of these decisions in the following simple model. There are four actors: The House of Representatives, the Senate, the President, and an executive Agency. They play a sequential garne which results in some policy which can be represented as a point along a one-dimensional continuum. Diagram 1 presents a possible distribution of preferences. P is the ideal point of the President; H is the ideal point of the median voter in the House; h is the ideal point of the "2/3rds" house voter; 32 S is the ideal point of the median voter in the Senate; s is the ideal point of the 2/3rds Senate voter; SQ is the status quo. Preferences are spatial so that a person with ideal policy Xi prefers x to y if Ix - Xil < lY - Xi i. Consider the Legislation Game which involves the House, the Senate, and the President. This garne determines whether the United States will shift away from the prevailing status quo policy, SQ. In stage 1 of the Legislation Game, the House chooses some point x in the policy space. If x = SQ the game ends and the policy SQ is maintained. If x ~ SQ the garne continues. In stage 2, the Senate approves or rejects the proposed point x. If the Senate rejects x, the garne ends with SQ. If the Senate approves x, the garne proceeds to stage 3. In stage 3, the President either signs the bill x or vetoes it. If the President signs the bill the garne ends and the bill x becomes law. If the President vetoes the bill, the garne proceeds to stage 4, in which the Senate and the House move simultaneously. If two thirds of each house approves x, the bill is passed and becomes law. If x lacks a two-thirds majority in either house, then SQ prevails. For any specified distribution of ideal points, this garne is easily solved. Consider the pattern displayed in Diagram 1. Since the status quo is to the right of all ideal policies, clearly some new policy will be enacted, ts in Diagram 1 is a point such that Its - S[ = IS - SQ]. The new policy will be no further to the left of S than ts, since the Senate would reject any such proposal in favor of SQ. In fact, in the unique subgalne perfect equilibrium for the configuration of Diagram 1, the House proposes ts and this is approved by both the Senate and the President. Next consider the Delegation Garne in which Congress does not formulate policy, but instead delegates this task to an executive agency (such as the Environmental Protection
32 The 2/3rds voter is the voter such that she and all voters to her right just constitute a 2/3 majority.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2251
Agency). In the Delegation Game, the Agency chooses a policy y in stage 0 and then the above Legislation Game is played with y serving as the new status quo. Since the executive agency is staffed by the President we will assume that its ideal point is that of the President (i.e., P). With the configuration of Diagram 1, the unique subgame perfect equilibrium policy outcome is now h. The delegation of power to the Agency dramatically shifts the equilibrium policy from ts to h. How might Congress moderate Agency's exercise of its discretion? In the Two-House Veto Garne and the One-House Veto Game, Congress intervenes directly. These two garnes model the effects of Chadha, where the Supreme Court ruled such supervision unconstitutional. In the Two-House Veto Garne, Congress delegates decision-making authority to an executive agency but reserves the right to overturn any policy proposal by a majority vote of each house. Specifically, in stage 1 of the Two-House Veto Garne, the Agency chooses a policy y. In stage 2, the House votes on the policy. If a majority approves the policy it is adopted. Otherwise, the game proceeds to stage 3. If a majority of the Senate also approves y, it is adopted. Otherwise, the garne ends with the original status quo SQ remaining in place. Reconsider the ideal point configuration Diagram 1. The point tH is such that ItH -- HI = IH - SQI. Clearly, tH is the equilibrium of the Two-House Veto Garne as any point to the left of tH will be vetoed by both Houses. The Two-House Veto Garne thus moderates the action of the Agency by bringing the equilibrium from h to tH, which is closer to the policy ts that would be enacted directly by Congress (with consent of the President). In the One-House Veto Garne a specific house of Congress has the power to approve or disapprove of the Agency's policy choice. Clearly the outcome will be tH if the House has the veto power and the policy ts if the Senate has the veto power. Thus, Chadha's announcement of a constitutional prohibition on the power of Congress to veto agency decisions dramatically restricts Congress' ability to control power that it statutorily delegates to an executive agency. The previous analysis of the Legislation, Delegation and Veto garnes suggests how one might analyze the way that different institutional structures determine which legal policies prevail. Of course, a complete analysis would compare equilibria across all possible distributions of preferences of the relevant institutional actors.
5. Cooperative game theory as a tool for analysis of legal concepts The prior discussion has examined the use of game theory to understand the behavioral consequences of legal rules. As we have seen, the structure of much legal doctrine can be i!luminated by models of simple games. These models have had an important impact on the legal commentary of cases and legislation. Moreover, courts
2252
J.-P. Beno?t and L.A. Kornhauser
h a v e o c c a s i o n a l l y cited such g a m e - t h e o r e t i c a n a l y s e s in s u p p o r t o f particular d e c i sions. 33 G a m e - t h e o r e t i c tools h a v e also p l a y e d a n o t h e r role in legal analysis, a role that m a y h a v e h a d a m o r e d i r e c t i m p a c t o n legal d e v e l o p m e n t . G a m e theory, particularly c o o p e r ative g a m e theory, p e r m i t s a c o n c e p t u a l analysis o f i d e a s central to s o m e areas o f legal doctrine. This doctrinal a p p r o a c h m a y e x p l i c a t e the social o b j e c t i v e u n d e r l y i n g legal rules. 34 In this section, w e d i s c u s s t w o d o c t r i n a l analyses. W e first e x a m i n e the t r e a t m e n t o f an i n d e x o f v o t i n g p o w e r b y the U n i t e d States' j u d i c i a l s y s t e m . W e t h e n c o n s i d e r a c a s e law p r o b l e m o f fair division. 5.1. M e a s u r e s o f v o t i n g p o w e r
In 1962, the S u p r e m e C o u r t o f the U n i t e d States b e g a n a v o t i n g rights r e v o l u t i o n w h e n it h e l d in B a k e r v. C a r r (1962) that the a p p o r t i o n m e n t o f state legislatures is s u b j e c t to
33 The Supreme Court of the United States has referred to game-theoretic analyses of settlement in at least three of its opiltions. Two of these cases concern settlement under joint and several liability. McDermott, Inc. v. Amclyde et al. (1994) cites Easterbrook, Landes and Posner (1981), Polinsky and Shavell (1980) and Kornhauser and Revesz (1993); Texas Industries v. RadcIiffMaterials (1981) cites Cirace (1980), Easterbrook, Landes and Posner (1981) and Polinsky and Shavell (1980). The dissent in Marek v. Chesny (1985) cites Shavell (1982) and Katz (1987) in a discussion of fee-shifting. The intermediate appellate courts in the federal system and the state courts of the United States also occasionally refer to game-theoretic analyses of setflement or of joint and several liability (or of both). Judge Easterbrook, himself a noted scholar in the field of economic analysis of law, has cited Shavell (1982) and Katz (1987) in Packer Engineering v. Kratville (1992), Easterbrook, Landes and Posner (1981), Polinsky and Shavell (1980) and Kornhauser and Revesz (1989) in In re Oil Spill ofAmoco Cadiz, 954 E2d 1279 (7th Cir. 1991) (per cmiam), Komhanser and Revesz (1989) in Akzo Coatings v. Aigner Corp. (1994), and Shavell (1982) in Premier Electric Construction Company v. National Electrical Contractors Assn. (1987). In addition, Rosenberg and Shavell (1985) were cited by the First Circuit in Weinberger v. Great Northern Nekoosa Corp. (1991) and Easterbrook, Landes and Posner (1981), Polinsky and Shavell (1980) and Kornhauser and Revesz (1993) were cited by the District of Columbia Court of Appeals in Berg v. Footer (1996). In re Larsen (1992) cites Bebchuk (1988) and Rosenberg and Shavell (1985). Again, two economically sophisticated judges, Judge Calabresi and Judge Easterbrook, have cited Ayres and Gegner (1989) on the problems of information revelation in American National Fite Insurance Co. v. Kenealy and Kenealy (1995) and Harnischfèger Corp. v. Harbor Insurance Co. (1991), respectively. Similarly, both Judges Easterbrook (in United States v. Herrera (1995)) and Posner (in In re Hoskins (1996)) have cited Baird, Gertner and Picker (1994) on game theory generally. It is worth noting that Coase (1960), the most cited artäcle in the legal academic literature, is ordy cited 42 times by state and federal courts of the United States. Fifteen of these citations are from United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit. (LEXIS search done on 24 April 2000.) 34 The distinction between the use of garne theory to predict behavior and garne theory to explicate doctrine is sometimes fuzzy. For example, one might rationalize the smacture of product liability doctrine as a set of legal mles that induce efficient behavior on the part of manufactttrers and consumers. This rationalization might use game theory both as a predictive tool (to show that some particular rule in fact induces efficient conduct) and as a conceptual tool (to illuminate the meaning of efficiency, e.g., to distinguish between ex ante, interim, and ex post efficiency).
Ch. 60: Game-TheoreticAnalysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2253
judicial review under the 14th amendment of the U.S. Constitution. In the cases that immediately followed, the Court announced that the U.S. Constitution guarantees each citizen "fair and effective representation" (Reynolds v. Sims (1964)). It enunciated a maxim of "one person, one vote" to guide states in legislative reapportionment. In the context of legislative elections from single-member districts, this slogan had a clear meaning and an immediate impact: it required redistricting when the population discrepancy between the largest and smallest districts was too great. 35 As the Court widened the reach of jurisdictions and governmental bodies subject to judicial oversight it gradually confronted a wider and wider range of election practices which required it to elaborate a more complete theory of fair representation. In particular, the Court encountered systems that weight the votes of legislators to counterbalance population disparities as weil as systems in which larger districts elect proportionately more legislators. Federal and state courts then confronted the question: When do these systems satisfy the requirements of fair and effective representation? In 1954, Shapley and Shubik (1954) offered an interpretation of the Shapley value as an index of voting power. They interpreted the Shapley value as measuring the chance a voter would be critical to the passage of a bill. These ideas influenced John Banzhaf III who, as a law student, proposed a related index in Banzhaf (1965). 36 Banzhaf also interpreted his index as a measure of the chance a voter would be critical. Banzhaf (1965) used this index to analyze weighted voting schemes and Banzhaf (1968) applied the index to the problem of multi-member districts. In each article, Banzhaf acknowledged the influence of the Shapley value on his thinking.37 Banzhaf (1965) had a substantial impact on litigation; even while in draft, it was introduced into the deliberations of the state and federal courts considering a plan for the temporary reapportionment of the New York Legislature in which weighted voting would be used. (For a discussion of the plan see Glinski v. Lomenzo (1965) and WMCA, Inc. v. Lomenzo (1965).) After he published his articles, Banzhaf continued to intervene in reapportionment litigation; the courts thus frequently considered his view. Before we examine Banzhaf's influence on the case law, we define the two power indices mentioned and briefly discuss the relation between them. Straffin (1994) provides a comprehensive survey of the technical literature. Consider a simple, proper voting game (N, v). (v(S) = 0 or 1 for all coalitions S; v(S) = 1 implies v ( N / S ) = 0.) Let Oi be the number of coalitions S in which i is a
35 Of course, as the Court was soon forced to learn, there are many ways to divide a populationinto roughly equal districts. 36 The Banzhafindex is equivalentto measures independentlyproposed by Coleman(1973), Dahl (1957), and Rae (1969). On this equivalence,see Dubey and Shapley (1979). 37 Footnote 32 to Banzhaf (1965) begins, "Althoughthe definitionpresented in this article is based in part on the ideas of Shapley-Shubik,their definitionis rejected because... [it] has not been shownthat the order in which votes are cast is significant;... Likewise it seems unreasonableto credit a legislator with different amounts of voting power depending on when or for what reasons he joins a particular voting coalition". Footnote 55 of Banzhaf(1968) thanks Shapley.
J.-P. Beno?t and L.A. Kornhauser
2254
swing voter; that is, the number of coalitions S such that v ( S ) = 1 and v ( S - {i}) = 0. The unnormalized Banzhaf power index/~i is given by: fli = 0 i / 2 n - I
while the normalized B anzhaf index is: fl; = Oi/ Z
Oi" i
The S h a p l e y - S h u b i k power index is defined as: O-i
Z
(s-
1)!(n-s)!/n!
w h e r e s = IS[.
S is a swing for i
An individual's (unnormalized) Banzhaf index gives the probability that she will be a swing voter under the assumption that all coalitions are equally likely to form. A n individual's S h a p l e y - S h u b i k index gives the probability that she will be a swing voter under the assumption that it is equally likely that a coalition of any size will f o r m Y Although these two indices often give similar measures of power, they need not. Indeed, they m a y differ radically both in the relative weights they assign and in the rank order they place players. (See Straffin (1988) for examples.) Straffin (1988) derives the indices within a probabilistic model in which there are n voters and each voter i has probability Pi of voting "yes" on a given issue, and a probability (1 - Pi) of voting "no" on the issue. Voter i ' s power is given by the probability that her vote will affect the outcome of the election. Thus, a voter's power depends on the joint distribution from which the Pi's are drawn. Straffin shows that (a) ~ri measures i ' s power if Pi = P for all i, and p is drawn from the uniform distribution on [0, 1] while (b) fli measures i ' s power if, for each i, Pi is drawn independently from the uniform distribution on [0, 1]. Equivalently, fli measures i ' s power on the assumption that each voter independently has a 50% chance of voting "yes" on the issue. 39 We turn now to the judicial reception of these ideas. The m a x i m of "one person, one vote" was articulated in the context of a political structure in which legislators are elected from single-member districts and each legislator has one vote within the legislature. The early reapportionment cases therefore identified one political stmcture equal-sized, single-member districts - that satisfies the constitutional requirement that
38 More precisely, the Shapley-Shubik index assumes that it is equally likely that a coalition of any size will form, and that all coalitions of a given size are equally like to form. An equivalent characterization is that the Shapley~Shubikindex gives the probability that as an individualjoins a coalition she will be a swing rinder the assumption that all orders of coalition formation are equally likely. 39 For an axiomatic characterization of the two indices see Dubey and Shapley (1979).
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and lnstitutions
2255
each citizen's vote have equal influence on political outcomes. 4° Other political structures, however, were soon challenged. These challenges required the judiciary to elaborate a conception of "equal voting power". Two political structures were of particular interest. Suppose that districts vary in size. In systems of weighted voting, each district elects one legislator but the elected representatives of larger districts are given more votes within the legislature. What set of voting weights, if any, yield equal influence of each citizen's vote? In the second political structure, larger districts elect more representatives. How should representatives be allocated among the districts to satisfy the constitutional mandate? The Banzhaf index (and Shapley-Shubik index) suggest answers to these questions. Citizens in a representative democracy play a compound voting garne. They elect representatives, and these representatives then pass legislation. There are three ways that the Banzhaf index could be used in this context. First, it could be used to measure the power of the elected representatives voting in the legislature. Second, it could be used to measure the power of citizens when voting for representatives. Finally, it could be used to measure the net power of citizens in the compound voting game. Since the probability that a citizen is a swing voter for the final passage of legislation equals the probability that her vote is crucial to getting her legislator elected times the probability that the legislator's vote is crucial, this last measure of Banzhaf power is simply the product of the first two. From roughly 1967 through 1990 the Banzhaf index served as a judicially accepted criterion for the determination of the power of representatives at the legislative level in weighted voting schemes. The Banzhaf index had particular importance in New York State where many county boards elected supervisors from towns with widely varying populations. 41 Indeed, Banzhaf's first article analyzed the striking case of the Nassau County Board of Supervisors in 1958 and 1964. Voters in different municipalities elected a total of six representatives. Since the municipalities differed in size, the elected representatives were given different voting weights, presumably to equalize the power of the citizens in the different municipalities. Incredibly, the weights were distributed among the representatives in such a way that three representatives had no swings - their votes could never influence the outcome (see Table 1). The weighting schemes masked the fact that in both 1958 and 1964 the six representatives were acmally playing a garne of threeplayer majority rule; three of the representatives had power 1/3 and three had power 0 under both the Shapley and the normalized Banzhaf index.
40 The case law focuses on the formulation of the conception of right articulated in Reynolds v. Sims (1964). There the U.S. Supreme Court stated that "each and every cifizen has an inalienable right to full and effective participation in the political processes of his State's legislative bodies" (at 565). Moreover, "full and effective participation by all citizens in stare govemmentrequires ... that each citizen have an equally effective voice in the election of members of bis state legislature" (at 565). 41 Imrie (1973) and Lucas (1983) providebrief accounts of the use of the Banzhaf index in New YorkState.
2256
J.-P. Benoft and L.A. Kornhauser
Table 1 Board of Supervisors - Nassau County 1958 Municipality
Population
Weight of representative
Hempsteadl Hempstead2 N. Hempstead Oyster Bay Glen Cove Long Beach
618,065
9 9 7 3 1 1
184,060 164,716 19,296 17,999
Unnormalized power
Normalized power
1/2 1/2 1/2 0 0 0
1/3 1/3 1/3 0 0 0
1/2 1/2 0 1/2 0 0
1/3 1/3 0 1/3 0 0
1964 Hempstead1 Hempstead2 N. Hempstead Oyster Bay Glen Cove Long Beach
728,625 213,225 285,545 22,752 25,654
31 31 21 28 2 2
Subsequently, in Iannucci v. Board o f Supervisors o f Washington County (1967) the New York Court of Appeals, the highest court in New York State, endorsed the Banzhaf index as the appropriate standard for determining the weights accorded to representatives of districts of varying sizes. The Court stated that the principle of "one person, one vote" was satisfied as long as the "[Banzhaf] power of a representative to affect the passage of legislation by his vote ... roughly corresponds to the proportion of the population of bis constituency" (at 252). Interestingly, the Court explicitly endorsed the abstract nature of the power calculus, ruling that "the sole criterion [of the constitutionality of weighted voting schemes] is the mathematical voting power which each legislator possesses in theory (emphasis added) ... and not the actual voting power he possesses in f a c t . . . " (at 252). In Franklin v. Kraus (1973), the New York Court of Appeals again approved a weighted voting system that made the Banzhaf power index of each representative proportional to his district's size. In both these cases the court used the Banzhaf index to determine the voting power of the legislators. The courts, however, did not carry the Banzhaf reasoning through to the citizen level. It can be shown that the probability that an individual is a swing voter in the election of her legislator is (approximately) inversely proportional to the square root of the population of her district. Thus, equalizing each citizen's riet Banzhaf power in the compound voting garne would require that a legislator be given power proportional to this square root. Nonetheless, the courts decided that a legislator's power should be proportional to the population itself. How do we account for the failure of the courts to consider the citizen's power in the compound garne? Apparently, the courts adopted a different view of the relation
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and lnstitutions
2257
between representative and citizen than that implicit in Banzhaf. 42 The swing voter analysis assumes that citizens disagree about which candidate would best represent the jurisdiction and that the prevailing candidate acts in the interests of those citlzens w h o v o t e d f o r her. On a different conceptlon of representation, however, once elected a candidate represents the interests of all citizens within her constituency. Each citizen in a district then exerts an equal influence upon the district representative, so that a citizen's influence is inversely proportional to the district populatlon. Hence, under this conception, a representative's power should be proportional to the number of constituents in her district, as the courts ruled. We now consider judicial treatment of multi-member districts. In A b a t e v. M u n d t (1969), the New York Court of Appeals upheld a system of multl-member districts that allocated supervisors to election districts in proportion to district populations. The court again ignored the compound garne analysis. It should be note& however, that unlike Banzhaf's analysis of weighted voting schemes, bis analysis of multi-member districts is seriously flawed. His assertion that voters in districts should be given representatives in proportion to the square root of the size of the population is unwarranted. First of all, it is clear that no recommendation on the number of representatives in a multi-member district can be made independently of the voting method being used to elect these representatives. Is each voter being given one vote or the same number of votes as there are representatives or is some other method in use? Second, if individuals are given many votes, then what is the proper assumption to make on the way these votes are cast? Clearly, the assumption that an individual is casting her own votes independently of each other is absurd. Finally, what assumptlon is being made about the correlation of the voting behavior of representatives voted for by a single individual? If the correlation is perfect, then, in effect, the multl-member districting scheine results in a weighted voting garne in the legislature. Of course, the ratios of voting powers in such a garne are not necessarily equal to the ratlos of voting weights. On the other hand, if these representatives are voting differently from each other, in what sense are they all representing the same individual? There may well be such a sense, but it is ill-captured by the Banzhaf conception, which considers the probability that a voter will be decisive on an issue. A few years after Abate, the United States Supreme Court (in W h i t c o m b v. Chavis (1973)) rejected the Banzhaf index in the judicial evaluatlon of multl-member districts. The Court argued that the index offered only a theoretical measure of the voter's power while constitutional considerations had to rest on disparities in actual voting power. 43 Thus, the theoretical character of the power index which had pleased the New York Court of Appeals, moved the United States Supreme Court to reject the index.
42 Banzhaf (1965) is noncommittal about the relationship between a citizen and bis representative. Banzhaf (1968) explicitly endorses the compoundvoting computation suggested above. 43 Banzhaf was an expert witness for plaintiffs at trial and signed the plaintiff-appellee's brief to the United States Supreme Court. Interestingly, plaintiffs sought single-member districts as a remedy in Whitcomb v. Chavis.
2258
~-~ Beno~ andL.A. Kornhauser
In 1989 the U.S. Supreme Court explicitly carried out a compound voting game analysis when considering the weighted voting scheme used by the Board of Estimate of New York City. 44 The court rejected the Banzhaf index, again citing its "theoretical" nature. On the basis of this decision, orte federal district court struck down as unconstitufional the weighted voting scheme that then prevailed in Nassau County. 45 Two federal district courts have approved a weighted voting system in the New York counties of Roxbury and Schoharie respectively which assigned w e i g h t s proportionally to population. 46 Thus, for the time being at least, the Banzhaf index appears to have been discredited for all United States legislative apportionment purposes. This brief history illustrates both the potential significance and difficulties ofjudicial use of game-theoretic (or other formal) concepts in the articulation of legal rules. The Banzhaf index governed the shape of weighted voting systems for roughly twenty years and partially shaped the judicial treatment of voting systems that consisted of unequal sized districts. Unfortunately, however, the courts and the community of political scientists and game theorists failed to engage in a constructive dialogue that would have enabled the courts to formulate a coherent conception of equal and effective representation for each citizen. The courts never clearly articutated or resolved three important questions. First, as we remarked earlier, the courts had to choose whether to focus attention on the garne constituted by voters electing representatives, the garne played by the elected representatives in the legislature, or the compound garne. The role of citizens in the compound game seems normatively the correct one for the courts to consider, but they were never clear on this point. Second, and as a consequence of their failure to consider the compound game explicitly, the courts did not articulate a theory of representation that would allow analysis of the compound garne. Finally, the courts did not question whether power was the appropriate concept for expressing equality of representation. The indices of voting power measure the probabitity that an individual will be a swing voter under various assumptions; the related concept of safisfaction measures the probability that the outcome will be the one that the roter desires. In a town with like-minded citizens eaeh one will have zero vofing power since decisions will älways be unanimous and no individual roter will be crucial. On the other hand, each cifizen will have a satisfaction of one. The courts should have at least considered whether satisfacfion was a more appropriate concept than power on which to construct the right to fair and effective representation. The anälytic community on the other hand bears some responsibility for the judicial failure to confront these three questions. Neither Banzhaf himself nor other commentators on the judieial efforts clearly framed the quesfion in terms of the compound garne.
44 Morris v. Board of Estimate of New York City (1989). 45 Jackson v. Nassau County Board of Supervisors (1993). The weights at issue in the litigation had been allocated so that the Banzhafpowerof each representativewas proportionalto the populationof the representative's district. 46 Roxbury Taxpayers Alliance v. Delaware County Board of Supervisors (1995) and Reform of Schoharie County v. Schoharie County Bd. of Supervisors (1997).
Ch. 60: Game-TheoreticAnalysis of Legal Rules and lnstitutions
2259
Moreover, discussions of the importance of the concept of representation to the analysis of the garne were sparse. Finally, although a voter's satisfaction is arguably more important than a voter's power, the former concept has received comparatively little attention from garne theorists. 47 5.2. Fair allocation o f losses and benefits Adjudication resolves disputes among parties. Courts are thus offen more concerned, at least superficially, with the fair resolution of the dispute between the parties before the court than with the ex ante behavior that may avoid similar disputes in the fumre (or reshape them). Many classes of disputes, in fact, seem explicitly directed at the fair division of property among disputing claimants. The most obvious area of law in which quesfions of this type arise is bankrnptcy where the court taust allocate the assets of the bankrupt among its creditors in a way that distributes the loss - i.e., the difference between the (valid) claims of creditors and the value of the estate - fairly. 48 Other areas include: the interpretafions o f wills that divide more assets among the heirs than are actually available; the mies of contribution when the share of an insolvent tortfeasor taust be allocated among the remaining joint tortfeasors; rate proceedings for common carriers such as telecommunicafions or electricity providers when the c o m m o n costs of service provision taust be allocated among different classes of customers; and the determinafion of fee äwards to class acfion attorneys when the common costs of representafion must be allocated among different classes of plainfiffs. One might reasonäbly ask what concepfion of fairness is embodied in legal rules governing these allocations? What explains variation, if any, in these mies? In the case of the c o m m o n law, a judge confronted with a dispute consults the decisions in analogous, previously decided cases and attempts to articulate a principle or set of principles that rationalizes these outcomes. Here, answering the above questions is particularly important and difficult. Talmudic law, like A n g l o - A m e r i c a n law, is a form of c o m m o n law adjudication. Aumann and Maschler (1985) and O ' N e i l l (1982) have deployed game-theoretic tools to explicate in part the rules implicit in two areas of Talmudic law that concern the fair allocation of property among disputing claimants. A u m a n n and Maschler consider the following bankruptcy problem from the Talmud. There are three creditors on an estate. Creditor 1 is owed 100; creditor 2 is owed 200, and creditor 3 is owed 300, The estate is worth less than the 600 total claim. The Talmud states that when the estate is valued at 100, the creditors should each receive 33 ½; when
47 On satisfaction see Brams and Lake (1978) and Straffin, Davis, and Brams (1982). 48 In fact bankruptcy law must balance other concems with fairness. In particular,the mles of bankruptcy may affect the pre-bankmptcy behavior of both debtor and creditors. Moreover, even after bartkruptcy, the value of a debtor corporation is generally greater as an ongoing concern than liquidated; captufing this surplus may entail creafiug incentives to some parties such as managers or specific creditors that otherwise seem unfair. Finally, we have ignored concerns about priority of claims of different types of creditors.
Z-R B e n o ) andL.A. Kornhauser
2260
the estate is valued at 200, the creditors should receive, respectively, 50, 75, and 75; when the estate is valued at 300, the allocation should be (50, 100, 150). What principle underlies the prescribed allocations? How should these three examples be extended to other bankruptcy cases? As a preliminary, consider the "contested-garment problem" from the Mishnah: one individual claims an entire garment; a second individual claims one-half of the same garment. The Talmud allocates the garment (3/4, 1/4) to the two claimants respectively. Here, the underlying principle is we11 understood by Talmudic scholars. The second claimant implicitly concedes half the garment to the first, while the first claimant concedes nothing. Each claimant is given the amount that is conceded to hirn, and the remainder is divided equally. However, this principle is articulated only for the case of two claimants. How can this principle for the two-claimant case be extended to the n-claimant case? Define a general claim problem P = (A; Cl, c2 . . . . . cn), where A is the total amount of assets to be distributed and ci is i's claim on A. Aumann and Maschler call a distribution x of the amount A "contested-garment-consistent" if (xi, x j) is the contestedgarment solution to the claim problem (xi + x j; ci, cj) for all claimants i and j. They show that each claim problem has a unique contested-garment-consistent solution. Moreover, this solution gives the allocations prescribed by the Talmud for the above three bankruptcy problems. Note that while the notion of contested-garment consistency does not appear elsewhere in the garne theory literature, this "consistency" approach is certainly gametheoretic in spirit. For instance, Harsanyi has characterized the product solution to the n-person Nash bargaining problem as the unique solution which is Nash-consistent for all pairs of bargainers. As in O'Neill (1982), Aumann and Maschler turn the claim problem into a cooperative garne by associating the following characteristic function garne with it:
v(S)=max(A-Z
ci,O) iEN
for S_CN.
S
This characteristic function is constructed on the assumption that claims are satisfied in full as they arrive and that a coalition can only guarantee itself what it would receive if it were the last to make a claim on the assets A. Alternatively, a coalition's worth is what it obtains when it concedes the claims of the other claimants. Aumann and Maschler demonstrate that the contested-garment-consistent solution (and hence the Talmudic division to the three bankruptcy problems) is the nucleolus of this coalitional garne. 49 While this result is remarkable and Aumann and Maschler's discussion is insightful and revealing, various objections can be raised. These objections pertain to the limitations of the game-theoretic approach in general. 49
See Benoit (1998) for a simple proofof this result.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2261
A difficulty in applying game theory is that "real world" situations are not presented as garnes. Rather a garne must be defined. While the characteristic function Aurnann and Maschler associate with the claim problem is a reasonable one, other specifications are also reasonable. For instance, we could define a coalition's worth to be its expected payment assuming that the other claimants do not form coalitions, that all claimants are paid oft as they arrive, and that all orders of arrival are equally likely. Similarly, while consistency notions are interesting, several can be defined. Thus, call a solution x to a claim problem "CG2-consistent" if for all S C N, (Y~~sxi, Y~~N/Sxi) is the contested-garment solution to (A; Y~.sCi, AS the claim problem
ZN/sCi).
(500; 100,200, 300) shows, there is no CG2-consistent solution. 5° This non-existence might be taken as evidence that CG2-consistency is the wrong notion of consistency, but it might just as well indicate that the contested-garment example should not be extended to more than two people. 51 As noted earlier, two questions arise in the analysis of a body of common law cases. What is the general rule that is to be derived from the disposition of particular cases, and what is the conception of fairness embodied in this law? These two questions are related because a rule that rationalizes a set of cases must both "fit" those cases and offer an attractive rationale for them. After all, many rules will be consistent with the decisions in the set of cases. Aumann and Maschler explicitly address the first question. Implicitly, they address the second as well. The nucleolus of a bankruptcy problem minimizes the maximum loss suffered by any coalition. Thus, it has an egalitarian spirit, but one in which coalitions and not just individuals are taken as objects of concern. O'Neill considers a problem in which a testator bequeaths shares in his estate, valued at 120, that total to more than one. The entire estate is bequeathed to heir 1, onehalf the estate to heir 2, one-third the estate to heit 3 and one-quarter the estate to heir 4. According to O'Neill, the 12th-century scholar Ibn Ezra claimed that the division (97/144, 25/144, 13/144, 9/144) is the appropriate one. Ibn Ezra reasoned that heir 4 lays clairn to a fourth of the estate, but that all four heirs make equal claim to this quarter and so this quarter is split evenly. Next heit 3 claims one third of the estate. He has already received his share of 1/4 of the estate, so now he and the three larger claimants receive an additional 1/3(1/3-1/4) for a total of 13/144. Proceeding in this manner yields the above numbers. In contrast to the earlier bankruptcy problem, here the reasoning underlying the division is given explicitly. O'Neill is interested in both extending this reasoning and proposing alternative, albeit related, solutions. Notice that while each heit only makes a claim for himself, this claim can be taken as implicitly imputing a division of the remainder of the assets to the other heirs. Indeed, given a specific heir's claim and an allocation 50 Solving for xi by taking S = {i} for each claimant one at a time yields (50, 150, 250) as the putative CG2-solufion, but this does not sum to 500. 51 Aumann and Maschler consider a principle similar to CG2-consistency. They show how a modification of this principle can be used to again derive the CG-consistent solution.
2262
Z-~ Beno~ and L.A. Kornhauser
rule, use the rule to impute a division of the remainder of the assets to each of the other heirs. Since no heir has any greater legitimacy than any other, compute the allocation that results from averaging the various divisions obtained in this manner. O'Neill calls a rule consistent if the allocation thus obtained is the same as the allocation the rule prescribed for the initial problem. Ibn Ezra's solution is not consistent in this sense. Again associate the characteristic function v ( S ) = max(A - ~ i e N - S Ci, 0) with this claim problem. The Shapley value yields an allocation which is consistent in O'Neill's sense. Furthermore, the Shapley allocation affords an interesting interpretation. Suppose that each heir is simply paid off in full as he presents his claim until the estate is exhausted. The allocation which results from averaging over all possible orders in which the claims could be presented is the Shapley value. When making allocations, courts might want to balance practical considerations with ethical ones. For instance, courts may not want to give claimants the incentive to combine or split their claims. Thus, they might require that (Xl . . . . . xi . . . . . . x j . . . . . xn) is the solution to (A; cl . . . . . ci . . . . . c j . . . . . cn) if and only if (xl . . . . . xi + x j . . . . . xn) is the solution to (A; cl . . . . . ci + c j . . . . . Cn). The only such rule is proportional allocation. 52 One should note that U.S. law generally does not resolve claims problems similarly to the Talmudic solutions that inspired O'Neill and Aumann and Maschler. In bankruptcy law, the assets A are, in fact, allocated among claimants proportionally to their claims. U.S. law presumably adopts this approach because creditors may freely transfer claims on the debtor-in-bankruptcy. With inheritances the problem is considered one of interpreting the intent of the testator. If no clear intent can be inferred, the will is invalid, the individual dies intestate, and the state's default rules of inheritance govern. Determination of intent depends critically on the precise wording of the document. See, e.g., Estate o f Heisserer v. L o o s (1985), In re Vismar' s Estate (1921), and R o d i s c h v. M o o r e (1913). The shares of insolvent defendants among joint tortfeasors are generally allocated using one of two rules. Under legal contribution, the tortfeasor against whom the plaintiff chooses to execute the judgment must bear the entire share of the insolvent parties. Under equitable contribution, these insolvent shares are divided among the solvent tortfeasors either equally or proportionally to their own shares. (Kornhauser and Revesz (1990) summarizes the law in this area.)
6. Concluding remarks Law pervades daily life. Legal rules structure relations among individuals, institutions, and government. The theory of garnes provides a framework within which to study the effects these legal rules have on the behavior of these agents. In a legal culture that considers law a means to guide behavior to specified goals, this framework will interest
52 See Chun (1988), de Frutos (1994) and O'Neill (1982). Thomson(1997) provides a survey of axiomatic models of bankruptcy.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2263
n o t o n l y legal s c h o l a r s b u t also l a w m a k e r s d i r e c t l y as t h e y a t t e m p t to d e s i g n r u l e s t h a t f o r w a r d t h e i r goals. I n the last d e c a d e , a n a l y s t s h a v e d e p l o y e d i n c r e a s i n g l y s o p h i s t i c a t e d m o d e l s to a n e v e r - w i d e n i n g r a n g e o f legal rules. O u r d i s c u s s i o n h a s m e r e l y s c r a t c h e d t h e surface o f this literature. M a n y a n a l y s e s o f legal rules f o c u s n o t o n t h e b e h a v i o r a l effects o f t h e s e rules b u t o n t h e i r c o n c e p t u a l a n d n o r m a t i v e f o u n d a t i o n s . T h e tools o f g a r n e t h e o r y h a v e also o f f e r e d i n s i g h t s into t h e s e areas.
References Articles Aivazian V.A., and LL. Callen (1981), "The Coase Theorem mad the empty core", Journal of Law & Economics 24:175-181. Aivazian, V.A., J.L. Callan and I. Lipnowski (1987), "The Coase Theorem and coalitional stability", Economica 54:517-520. Arlen, L (1990), "Re-exalnining liability mles when injurers as well as victims suffer losses", International Review of Law and Economics 10:233-239. Arlen, J. (1992), "Liability for physical injuly when injurers as weh as victims suffer losses", Joumal of Law, Economics & Organization 8:411-426. Aumann, R., and M. Maschler (1964), "The bargaining set for cooperative garnes", in: M. Dresher, L.S. Shapley and A.W. Tucker, eds., Advances in Galne Theory (Princeton University Press, Princeton), 443-476. Aumann, R., and M. Maschler (1985), "Game-theoretic analysis of a bankruptcy problem from the Talmud", Journal of Econolnic Theory 36:195-213. Avery, C., and P.B. Zemsky (1994), "Money bulning and multiple equilibria in bargaining", Garnes and Economic Behavior 7:154-168. Ayres, I. and R. Geltner (1989), "Filling gaps in incomplete contracts: An economic theory of default mles", Yale Law Joumal 99:87-130. Ayres, L, and R. Geltner (1992), "Strategic contractual inefficiency and the optimal choice of legal riffes", Yale Law Journal 101:729-772. Ayres, I., and E. Talley (1995), "Solomonic bargaining: Dividing a legal entitlement to facilitate Coasean trade", Yale Law Journal 104:1027-1117. Baird, D., R. Gertner and R. Picker (1994), Garne Theory and the Law (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA). Baird, D., and R. Picker (1991), "A simple non-cooperative bargaining model of corporate reorganization", Journal of Legal Studies 20:311-350. Banzhaf, J.E III (1965), "Weighted voting doesn't work", Rutgers Law Review 19:317-343. Banzhaf, J.F. III (1966), "Multi-member electoral districts', Yale Law Journal 75:1309-1338. Barton, J. (1972), "The economic basis of damages for breach of contract', Joumal of Legal Studies 1:277-304. Beard, T.R. (1990), "Bankruptcy and care choice", Rand Journal of Economics 12:626-634. Bebchuk, L.A. (1984), "Litigation and settlement under impeffect information", Rand Journal of Economics 15:404-415. Bebchuk, L.A. (1988), "Suing solely to extract a setüement offer", Joumal of Legal Smdies 17:437-450. Bebchuk, L.A. (1994), "Efficient and inefficient sales of corporate control", Quarterly Journal of Economics 109:957-993. Bebchuk, L.A., and S. Shavell (1991), "Information and the scope of liability for breach of contract: The rule of Hadley v. Baxendale", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 7:284-312. Becker, G. (1968), "Crime and punishment: An econornic approach", Journal of Political Economy 76:169-217. Benoit, J.-E (1998), "The nucleolus is contested-garment-consistent: A direct proof", Journal of Economic Theory 77:192-196.
2264
J.-P. Beno'it and L.A. Kornhauser
Birmingham, R.L. (1969a), "Damage measures and economic rationality: The geometry of contract law", Duke Law Journal 1969:49-71. Birrningham, R.L. (1969b), "Legal and moral duty in garne theory: Common law contract and Chinese analogies", Buffalo Law Review 18:99-117. Blume, L., D. Rubinfeld and E Shapiro (1984), "The taking of land: When should compensation be paid?", Quarterly Journal of Economics 99:71-92. Brams, S.J., and M. Lake (1978), "Power and satisfaction in a representative democracy", in: RC. Ordeshhook, ed., Garne Theory and Political Science, 529-562. Brown, J.P. (1973), "Toward an economic theory of liability", Journal of Legal Studies 2:323-349. Bulow, J., and R Klemperer (1996), "Auctions versus negotiations", American Economic Review 86:180-194. Calabresi, G. (1961), "Some thoughts on risk distribution and the law of torts", Yale Law Journal 70:499-553. Calabresi, G., and A.D. Melamed (1972), "Property rules, liability rules and inalienability: One view of the cathedral", Harvard Law Review 85:1089-1128. Cameron, C. (1993), "New avenues for modeling judicial politics", University of Rochester Wallis Institute of Political Economy Working Paper. Chun, Y. (1988), "The proportional solution for rights problems", Mathematical Social Sciences 15:231-246. Cirace, J. (1980), "A game-theorefic analysis of contfibution and claim reduction in antitrust treble damages suits", St. John's Law Review 55:42-62. Coase, R. (1960), "The problem of social cost", Journal of Law & Economics 3:1-44. Cohen, L.R., and M.L. Spitzer (1995), "Judicial deference to agency action: A rational choice theory and an empirical test", mimeo. Coleman, J.C. (1973), "Loss of power", American Sociological Review 38:1-17. Cooter, R.D. (1985), "The unity of tort, property and contract", California Law Review 73:1-51. Cooter, R.D. (1987), "Coase Theorem", in: J. Eatwell, M. Milgate and R Newman, eds., The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, Vol. 1 (Macmillan, London) 457-460. Cooter, R.D., L.A. Kornhanser and D. Lane (1979), "Liability rules, limited information, and the role of precedent", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 10:366-373. Cooter, R.D., and D.L. Rubinfeld (1989), "Economic analysis of legal disputes and their resolution", Journal of Economic Literature 27:1067-1097. Cooter, R.D., and T. Ulen (1986), "An economic case for comparative negligence", New York University Law Review 61:1067-1110. Cooter, R.D., and T. Ulen (1988), Law and Economics (Scott, Foresman and Co., London). Cramton E, and A. Schwartz (1991), "Using auction theory to inform takeover regulation", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 7:27-54. Craswell, R. (1988), "Precontractual investigation as an optimal precaution problem", Journal of Legal Studies 17:401-430. Craswell, R., and J.E. Calfee (1986), "Deterrence and uncertain legal standards", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 2:279-303. Dahl, R.A. (1957), "The concept of power", Behavioral Science 2:201-215. Daughety, A., and J. Reinganum (1993), "Endogenous sequencing in models of settlement and litigation", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 9:314-348. De Frutos, M.A. (1994), "Coalitional manipulation in a bankmptcy problem", mimeo. Diamond, RA. (1974a), "Single-activity accidents", Journal of Legal Studies 3:107-162. Diamond, EA. (1974b), "Accident law and resource allocation", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 5:366-405. Diamond, RA. and E. Maskin (1979), "An equilibrium analysis of search and breach of contract I: Steady states", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 10:282-316. Diamond, RA., and J.A. Mirrlees (1975), "On the assignment of liability: The uniform case", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 6:487-516. Dubey, E, and L.S. Shapley (1979), "Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index", Mathematics of Operations Research 4:99-131.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2265
Edlin, A.S. (1994), "Efficient standards of due care: Should courts find more parties negligent under comparative negligence?", International Review of Law and Economics 15:21-34. Eisenberg, T. (1990), "Testing the selection effect: A new theoretical framework with empirical tests", Journal of Legal Studies 19:337-358. Emons, W. and J. Sobel (1991), "On the effectiveness of liability rules when agents are not identical", Review of Economic Studies 58:375-390. Endres, A., and I. Querner (1995), "On the existence of care equilibria under tort law", Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 151:348-357. Eskridge, W.N., and J. Ferej ohn (1992), "Making the deal stick: Enforcing the original constitutional structure of lawmaking in the modern regulatory state", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 8:165-189. Farrell, J. (1987), "Information and the Coase Theorem", Journal of Economic Perspectives 1:113-129. Ferejohn, J., and C. Shipan (1990), "Congressional influence on bureaucracy", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 6:1-20. Fernandez, R., and J. Glazer (1991), "Striking for a bargain between two completely infonned agents", American Economic Review 81:240-252. Fischel, W.A., and P. Shapiro (1989), "A constitutional choice model of compensation for takings", International Review of Law and Economics 9:115-128. Geistfeld, M. (1995), "Manufacturer moral hazard and the tort-contract issue in products liability", International Review of Law and Economics 15:241-257. Glazer, J., and A. Ching-to Ma (1989), "Efficient allocation of a "pilze": King Solomon's dilemma", Games and Economic Behavior 1:222-233. Green, J. (1976), "On the optimal structure of liability rules", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 7:553-574. Grossman, S., and O. Hart (1980), "Disclosure laws and takeover bids", Journal of Finance 35:323-334. Haddock, D., and C. Cttrran (1985), "An economic theory of comparative negligence", Journal of Legal Studies 14:49-72. Hadfield, G. (1994), "Judicial competence and the interpretation of incomplete contracts", Journal of Legal Studies 23:159-184. Haller, H., and S. Holden (1990), "A letter to the editor on wage bargalning", Journal of Economic Theory 52:232-236. Harris, M., and A. Raviv (1992), "Financial contracting theory", in: J.-J. Laffont, ed., Advances in Economic Theory: Sixth World Congress, 64-150. Harrison, G.W., and M. McKee (1985), "Experimental evaluation of the Coase Theorem', Joumal of Law & Economics 28:653-670. Hart, O., and B. Holmstrom (1987), "The theory of contracts", in: T. Bewley, ed., Advances in Economic Theory: Fifth World Congress, 71-155. Hay, B.L. (1995), "Effort, information, settlement, trial", Joumal of Legal Studies 29:29-62. Hermalin, B. (1995), "An economic analysis of takings", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 11:64-86. Hermalin, B. and M. Katz (1993), "Judicial modification of contracts between sophisticated parties: A more complete view of incomplete contracts and their breach", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 9:230-255. Hoffman, E. and M.L. Spitzer (1982), "The Coase Theorem: Some experimental tests", Journal of Law & Economics 25:73-98. Hoffman, E. and M.L. Spitzer (1985), "Entitlements, rights, and faixness: An experimental examination of subjects' concepts of distributive justice", Journal of Legal Studies 14:259-298. Hoffman, E., and M.L. Spitzer (1986), "Experimental tests of the Coase Theorem with large bargaining groups", Journal of Legal Studies 15:149-171. Hohfeld, W,N. (1913), "Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning", Yale Law Journal 23:16-59.
2266
J.-P. Beno?t and L.A. Kornhauser
Holmstrom, B., and J. Tirole (1989), "The theory of the firm", in: R. Schmalensee and R.D. Willig, eds., Handbook of Industrial Organizaüon 1:61-133. Hurwicz, L. (1995), "What is the Coase Theorem?", Japan and the World Economy 7:49-74. Hylton, K.N. (1990), "Costly litigation and legal error under negligence", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 6:433-452. Hylton, K.N. (1993), "Litigation cost allocation rules and compliance with the negligence standard", Joumal of Legal Studies 22:457-476. Hylton, K.N. (1995), "Compliance with the law and the trial selection process: A theoreücal framework", manuscript. Imrie, R.W. (1973), "The impact of the weighted vote on representation in municipal governing bodies in New York State", Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 219:192-199. Johnston, J.S. (1990), "Strategic bargaining and the economic theory of contract defanlt mles", Yale Law Joumal 100:615~64. Johnston, J.S. (1995), "Bargaining under rules vs. standards", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 11:256-281. Kahan, M. (1989), "Cansation and incentives to take care under the negligence mle", Journal of Legal Studies 18:427-447. Kahan, M., and B. Tuchman (1993), "Do bondholders lose from junk bond covenant changes?", Journal of Business 66:499-516. Kambhu, J. (1982), "Optimal product quality under asymmetfic information and moral hazard", Bell Joumal of Economics and Management Science 13:483-492. Kaplow, L., and S. Shavell (1996), "Property rules versus liability rules: An economic analysis", Harvard Law Review 109:713-789. Katz, A. (1987), "Measuring the demand for litigation", Joumal of Law, Economics & Organization 3:143-176. Katz, A. (1990a), "The strategic structure of offer and acceptance: Garne theory and the law of contract formation", Michigan Law Review 89:216-295. Katz, A. (1990b), "Your terms or mine? The duty to read the fine print in contracts", Rand Journal of Economics 21:518-537. Katz, A. (1993), "Transaction costs and the legal mechanics of exchange: When should silence in the face of an offer be construed as acceptance?", Joumal of Law, Economics & Organization 9:77-97. Kennedy, D., and E Michelman (1980), "Are property and contract efficient?", Hofstra Law Review 8:711-770. Kornhauser, L.A. (1983), "Reliance, reputation and breach of contract", Journal of Law and Economics 26:691-706. Kornhauser, L.A. (1986), "An introduction to the economic analysis of contract remedies", University of Colorado Law Review 57:683-725. Komhauser, L.A. (1989), "The new economic analysis of law: Legal rules as incentives', in: N. Mercuro, ed., Developments in Law and Economics, 27-55. Kornhauser, L A . (1992), "Modeling collegial courts. Il. Legal doctrine", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 8:441-470. Komhauser0 L.A. (1996), "Adjudication by a resource-constrained team: Hierarchy and precedent in a judicial system", Southem Califomia Law Review 68:1605-1629. Kornhauser, L.A. and R.L. Revesz (1990), "Apportioning damages among potentially insolvent actors", Journal of Legal Studies 19:617-652. Kornhauser, L.A. and R.L. Revesz (1993), "Settlemants under joint and several liability", New York University Law Review 68:427-493. Komhauser, L.A., and A. Schotter (1992), "An experimental study of two-actor accidents", New York University C.V. Starr Center for Applied Economics Working Paper #92-57. Landes, W., and R. Posner (1980), "Joint and multiple tortfeasors: An economic analysis", Joumal of Legal Studies 9:517-555.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal Rules and Institutions
2267
Leong, A. (1989), "Liability rules when injurers as weil as victims suffer losses", International Review of Law and Economics 9:105-111. Lucas, W.F. (1983), "Measuring power in weighted voting systems", in: S. Brams, W. Lucas and P. Straffin, eds., Political and Related Models, 183-238. Mailath, G.J., and A. Postlewaite (1990), "Asymmetric information bargai~fing problems with many agents", Review of Economic Studies 57:351-367. Moulin, H. (1988), Axioms of Cooperative Decision Making (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Myerson, R.B., and M.A. Satterthwaite (1983), "Efficient mechanisms for bilateral trading", Journal of Economic Theory 29:265-281. Oi, W. (1973), "The economics of product safety", Bell Joumal of Economics and Management Science 4:3-28. O'Neill, B. (1982), "A problem of rights arbitration from the Talmud", Mathematical Social Sciences 2:345-371. Ordover, J.A. (1978), "Costly litigation in the model of single-activity accidents", Journal of Legal Studies 7:243-262. Osborne, M.J., and A. Rubinstein (1990), Bargaining and Markets (Academic Press, San Diego, CA). Perloff, J. (1981), "Breach of contract and the foreseeability doctrine of Hadley v. Baxendale", Journal of Legal Studies 10:39-64. Png, I.P.L. (1983), "Strategic behavior in suit, settlement, and trial", Beil Journal of Economics and Management Science 14:539-550. Png, I.P.L. (1987), "Litigation, liability mad incentives for care", Journal of Public Economics 34:61-85. Polinsky, A.M. (1983), "Risk sharing through breach of contract remedies", Joumal of Legal Studies 12:427-444. Polinsky, A.M. (1987a), "Fixed price vs. spot price contracts: A study in risk allocation", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 3:27-46. Polinsky, A.M. (1987b), "Optimal liability when the injurer's information about the victim's loss is imperfect", International Review of Law and Economics 7:139-147. Polinsky, A.M., and W. Rogerson (1983), "Product liability, consumer misperception, and market power", Bell Joumal of Economics and Management Science 14:581-589. Polinsky, A.M., and D.L. Rubinfeld (1988), "The deterrent effects of settlements and tfials", International Review of Law and Economics 8:109-116. Polinsky, A.M., and S. Shavell (1989), "Legal error, litigation, and the incentive to obey the law", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 5:99-108. Posner, R., and A.M. Rosenfield (1977), "Impossibility and related doctrines in contract law: An economic analysis", Journal of Legal Studies 6:83-118. Priest, G.L., and B. Klein (1984), "The selection of disputes for litigation", Journal of Legal Studies 13:!-56. Rae, D.W. (1969), "Decision rules and individual values in constimtional choice", American Political Science Review 63:40-56. Rasmusen, E. (1994), "Judicial legitimacy as a repeated garne", Joumal of Law, Economics & Organization 10:63-83. Rasmusen, E., and I. Ayres (1993), "Mutual and unilateral mistake in contract law", Journal of Legal Studies 22:309-344. Reinganum, J. (1988), "Plea bargaining and prosecutorial discretion", Americarl Economic Review 78:713-728. Reinganum, J., and L. Wilde (1986), "Settlement and litigation and the allocation of litigation costs", RAND Journal of Economics 17:557-566. Rogerson, W. (1984), "Efficient reliance and damage measures for breach of contract", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 15:39-53. Rosenberg, D., and S. Shavell (1985), "A model in which suits are brought for their nuisance value", International Review of Law and Economics 5:3-13. Rubinfeld, D. (1987), "The efficiency of comparative negligence", Joumal of Legal Studies 16:373-394.
2268
J.-R Beno'it and L.A. Kornhauser
Rubinstein, A. (1982), "Peffect equilibrium in a bargaining model", Econometrica 50:1151-1172. Samuelson, W. (1985), "A comment on the Coase Theorem", in: A.E. Roth, ed., Game-Theoretic Models of Bargaining, 321 339. Schwartz, A. (1989), "A theory of loan priorities", Journal of Legal Studies 18:209-261. Schwartz, A. (1993), "Bankruptcy workouts and debt contracts", Journal of Law and Economics 36:595-632. Schwartz, E.E (1992), "Policy, precedent, and power: A positive theory of supreme court decision-making", Journal of Law, Economics & Organizafion 8:219-252. Sercu, P., and C. van Hulle (1994), "Financing instruments, security design, and the efficiency of takeovers: A note", International Review of Law and Economics 15:373-393. Shapley, L.S., and M. Shubik (1954), "A method for evaluating the distribution of power in a committee system", American Political Science Review 48:787-792. Shavell, S. (1980), "Damage measures for breach of contract", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 11:466-490. Shavell, S. (1982), "Suit settlement and trial: A theoretical analysis under alternative methods for the allocation of legal costs", Journal of Legal Studies 11:55-82. Shavell, S. (1983), "Torts in which victims and injurers move sequentially", Journal of Law & Economics 26:589-612. Shavell, S. (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA). Shavell, S. (1995), "The appeals process as a means of error correction", Journal of Legal Studies 24:379-426. Sobel, J. (1985), "Disclosure of evidence and resolution of disputes: Who should bear the burden of proof?", in: A.E. Roth, ed., Game-Theoretic Models of Bargaining, 341-361. Spier, K. (1992), "The dynamics of pretrial negotiation", Review of Economic Studies 59:93-108. Spier, K. (1994), "Pretrial bargalning and the design of fee shifting rnles", RAND Jottrnal of Economics 25:197-214. Straffin, ED., Jr. (1988), "The Shapley-Shubik and Banzhaf power indices as probabilities", in: A.E. Roth, ed., The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd Shapley, 71-81. Straffin, ED., Jr. (1994), "Power and stability in politics", in: RJ. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 32, 1127-1152. Straffin, ED., Jr., M.D. Davis and S.J. Brams (1982), "Power and satisfaction in an ideologically divided voting body", in: M.J. Holler, ed., Power, Voting, and Voting Power, 239-255. Sykes, A.O. (1990), "The doctrine of commercial impracticability in a second-best world", Journal of Legal Studies 19:43-94. Symposium (1991), "Just winners and losers: The application of garne theory to corporate law and practice", University of Cincinnati Law Review 60:2-448. Thomson, W. (1997), "Axiomatic analyses of bankruptcy and taxation problems: A survey", mimeo. Veljanovski, C.J. (1982), "The Coase theorems and the economic theory of markets and law", Kyklos 35:53-74. Wang, G.H. (1994), "Litigation and pretrial negotiations under incomplete information", Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 10:187-200. Weingast, B., and M. Moran (1983), "Bureaucratic discretion of congressional control? Regulatory policy-making by the Federn Trade Commission", Journal of Political Economy 91:756-800. White, M.J. (1980), "Public policy toward bankrnptcy: Me-first and other priority rules", Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 11:550-564. White, M.J. (1988), "Contract breach and contract discharge due to impossibility: A unified theory", Journal of Legal Studies 17:353-376. White, M.J. (1994), "Corporate bankruptcy as a filtering device: Chapter 11. Reorganization and out-of-court debt resmacturings", Jourual of Law, Economics & Organization 10:268-295. Winter, R. ( 1991 ), "Liability insurance", Journal of Economic Perspectives 5:115 - 1 3 6 . Wittman, D. (1981), "Optimal pricing of sequential inputs: Last clear chance, mitigation of damages, and related doctrines in the law", Jourual of Legal Studies 10:65-92.
Ch. 60:
Game-Theoretic Analysis of Legal RuIes and lnstitutions
2269
Wimnan, D. (1988), "Dispute resolution, bargaining, and the selection of cases for trial: A study of the generation of biased and unbiased data", Journal of Legal Studies 17:313-352. Young, H.P. (1994), Equity: In Theory and Practice (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ). Cases Abate v. Mundt, 25 N.Y.2d 309 (1969) Abate v. Mundt, 403 U.S. 182 (1971) Akzo Coatings, Inc v. Aigner Corp., 30 E3d 761 (7th Cir. 1994) American National Fire Insurance Co. v. Kenealy and Kenealy, 72 E3d 264 (2d Cir. 1995) Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186 (1962) Bechtle v. Board ofSupervisors of County of Nassau, 441 N.Y.S. 2d 403 (2d Dept 1981) Berg v. Footer, 673 A. 2d 1244 (D.C. App., 1996) Board of Estimate of New York City v. Morris, 489 U.S. 688 (1989) Chapman v. Meier, 420 U.S. 1 (1975) Chevron, U.S.A., Inc v. Natural Resources Defense Council Inc, 467 U.S. 837 (1984) Estate of Heisserer v. Loos, 698 S.S. 2d 6 (Mo. Ct. of Appeals 1985) Franklin v. Kraus, 72 Misc.2d (Sup.Ct., Nassau Cty 1972) reversed 32 NY 2d 234 (1973) reargument denied,
motion to amend remittitur granted 33 N.Y. 2d 646 (1973) appeal dismissed for want of a substantial federal question 415 U.S. 904 (1974) Franklin v. Mandeville, 57 Misc.2d 1072 (Sup.Ct. Nassau Cty. 1968) aff'd 299 N.Y.S.2d 953 (2d Dept 1969) modified 26 NY2d 65 (1970) Glinski v. Lomenzo, 16 N.Y.2d 27 (1965) Harnischefeger Corp. v. Harborlnsurance Co., 927 E2d 974 (7th Cir 1991) Holder v. Hall, 114 S.Ct. 2581 (1994) lannucci v. Board of Supervisors of Washington County, 20 N.Y.2d 244 (1967) lmmigration and Nationalization Service v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919 (1983) In re Hoskins, 102 F.3d 311 (7th Cir. 1996) In re Larsen, 616 A.2nd 529 (Pa. S. Ct 1992) In re Oil Spill of Amoco Cadiz, 954 F.2d 1279 (7th Cir 1991) In re Vismar's Estate, 191 NYS 752 (Surrogates Ct 1921) Jackson v. Nassau County Board of Supervisors, 818 E Supp. 509 (EDNY 1993) Kilgarlin v. Hill, 386 U.S. 120 (1966) League ofWomen Voters v. Nassau County Board of Supervisors, 737 F.2d 155 (2d Cir. 1984) cert denied sub nom. Schmertz v. Nassau County Board of Supervisors, 469 U.S. 1108 (1985) Marek v. Chesny, 473 U.S. 1 (1985) McDermott lnc. v. Amclyde et al., 511 S. Ct. 202 at notes 14, 20, and 24 (1994) Packer Engineering v. Kratville, 965 E2d 174 (7th Cir. 1992) Premier Electric Construction Company v. National Electrical Contractors Assn., 814 Ed 358 (7th Cir. 1987) Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533 (1964) Rodisch v. Moore, 101 N.E. 206 (Ill. Sup. Ct 1913) Roxbury Taxpayers Alliance v. Delaware County Board of Supervisors, 886 F. Supp. 242 (NDNY 1995) aff'd, 80 E3d 42 (2d Cir.), cert. denied sub nom. MacDonald v. Delaware County Board of Supervisors, 519 U.S. 872 (1996) Reform of Schoharie County v. Schoharie County Board of Supervisors, 975 E Supp. 191 (NDNY,1997) Texas Industries v. Radcliff Materials, 451 U.S. 630 (1981) United Stares v. Herrera, 70 E3d 444 (7th Cir, 1995) Weinberger v. GreatNorthern Nekoosa Corp., 925 E2d 518 (1st Cir., 1991) Whitcomb v. Chavis, 403 U.S. 124 (1971) WMCA Inc. v. Lomenzo, 246 E Supp. 953 (S.D.N.Y. 1965) affirmed per curiam sub nom Travia v. Lomenzo, 382 U.S. 287 (1965)
Chapter 61
IMPLEMENTATION THEORY THOMAS R. PALFREY* Division of Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA, USA
Contents 1. Introduction 1.1. The basic structure of the implementation problem 1.2. Informational issues 1.3. Equilibrium: Incentive compatibility and uniqueness 1.4. The organization of this chapter
2. Implementation under conditions of complete information 2.1. Nash implementation 2.1.1. Incentive compatibility 2.1.2. Uniqueness 2.1.3. Example 1 2.1.4. Example 2 2.1.5. Necessary and sufficient conditions 2.2. Refined Nash implementation 2.2.1. Subgame perfect implementation 2.2.2. Example 3 2.2.3. Characterization results 2.2.4. Implementation by backward induction and voting trees 2.2.5. Normal form refinements 2.2.6. Example 4 2.2.7. Constraints on mechanisms 2.3. Virtual implememation 2.3.1. Virtual Nash implementation 2.3.2. Virtual implementation in iterated removal of dominated strategies
3. Implementation with incomplete information 3.1. The type representation 3.2. Bayesian Nash implementation 3.2.1. Incentive compatibility and the Bayesian revelation principle
2273 2275 2276 2277 2278 2278 2279 2279 2282 2283 2283 2284 2288 2289 2289 2290 2292 2294 2295 2296 2297 2297 2299 2302 2302 2303 2304
*I thank John Duggan, Matthew Jackson, and Sanjay Srivastava for helpful comments and many enlightening discussions on the subject of implementatiort theory. Suggestions from Robert Aumann, Sergiu Hart and two anonymous readers are also gratefully acknowledged. The financial support of the National Science Foundation is gratefully acknowledged. Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2272 3.2.2. Uniqueness 3.2.3. Example5 3.2.4. Bayesianmonotonicity 3.2.5. Necessary and sufficientcondifions 3.3. Implementationusing refinementsof Bayesianequilibrium 3.3.1. UndominatedBayesianequilibrium 3.3.2. Example6 3.3.3. Example7 3.3.4. Virtualimplementationwith incompleteinformation 3.3.5. Implementationvia sequentialequilibrium 4. Open issues 4.1. Implementationusing perfect informationextensiveforms and votingtrees 4.2. Renegoüationand informationleakage 4.3. Individualrationalityand participationconstraints 4.4. Implementationin dynamicenvironments 4.5. Robustnessof the mechanism References
T.R. Palfrey 2304 2304 2305 2307 2310 2310 2311 2311 2312 2312 2314 2314 2314 2316 2317 2318 2320
Abstract This chapter surveys the branch of implementation theory initiated by Maskin (1999). Results for both complete and incomplete information environments are covered.
Keywords implementation theory, mechanism design, garne theory, social choice
JEL classification: 025,026
Ch. 61:
lmplementation Theory
2273
1. Introduction Implementation theory is an area of research in economic theory that rigorously investigates the correspondence between normative goals and institutions designed to achieve (implement) those goals. More precisely, given a normative goal or welfare criterion for a particular class of allocation problems, or domain of environments, it formally characterizes organizational mechanisms that will guarantee outcomes consistent with that goal, assuming the outcomes of any such mechanism arise from some specification of equilibrium behavior. The approaches to this problem to date lie in the general domain of game theory because, as a matter of definition in the implementation theory literature, an institution is modelled as a rnechanism, which is essentially a non-cooperative game form. Moreover, the specific models of equilibrium behavior are usually borrowed from garne theory. Consequently, many of the same issues that intrigue garne theorists are the focus of attention in implementation theory: How do results change if informational assumptions change? How do results depend on the equilibrium concept governing stabie behavior in the garne? How do results depend on the distribution of preferences of the players or the number of players? Also, many of the same issues that arise in social choice theory and welfare economics are also at the heart of implementation theory: Are some first-best welfare criteria unachievable? What is the constrained second-best solution? What is the general correspondence between normative axioms on social choice functions and the possibility of strategic manipulation, and how does this correspondence depend on the domain of environments? What is the correspondence between social choice functions and voting rules? In order to limit this chapter to manageable proportions, attention will be mainly focused on the part of implementation theory using non-cooperative equilibrium concepts that follows the seminal paper by Maskin (1999). 1 This body of research has its roots in the foundational work on decentralization and economic design of Hayek, Koopmans, Hurwicz, Reiter, Marschak, Radner, Vickrey and others that dates back more than half a century. The limitation to this somewhat restricted subset of the enormous literature of implementation theory and mechanism design excludes four basic categories of results. The first category is implementation via dominant strategy equilibrium, perhaps more familiarly known as the characterization of strategyproof mechanisms. This research, mainly following the seminal work of Gibbard (1973) and Satterthwaite (1975), has close connections with social choice theory, and for that reason has already been treated in some depth in Chapter 31 of this Handbook (Vol. II). The second category excluded is implementation via solution concepts that allow for coalitional behavior, most notably, strong equilibrium [Dutta and Sen (199 lc)] and coalition-proof equilibrium [Bernheim and Whinston (1987)]. The third category involves practical issues in the design of mechanisms. There is a vast literature identifying specific classes of mechanisms such
1 The published article is a revision of a paper that was circulated in 1977.
2274
ZR. Palfrey
as divide-and-choose, sequential majority voting, auctions, and so forth, and studying/characterizing the range of social choice rules that are implementable using such mechanisms. The fourth category is the many applications of the revelation principle to design mechanisms in Bayesian environments. 2 This includes much work in auction theory, bargaining, contracting, and regulation. These other categories are already covered in some detail in several other chapters of this Handbook. Later in this chapter we discuss practical aspects of implementation, as it relates to the specific mechanisms used in the constructive proofs of the main theorems. But a few introductory remarks about this are probably in order. In contrast to the literature devoted to studying classes of"natural" mechanisms, the most general characterizations of implementable social choice rules orten resort to highly abstract mechanisms, with little or no concern for practical application. The reason for this is that the mechanisms constructed in these theorems are supposed to apply to arbitrary implementable social choice rules. A typical characterization result in implementation theory takes as given an equilibrium concept (say, subgame perfect Nash equilibrium) and tries to identify necessary and sufficient conditions for a social choice rule to be implementable, untier minimal domain restrictions on the environment. The method of proof (at least for sufficiency) is to construct a mechanism that will work for any implementable social choice rule. That is, a standard garne f o r m is identified which will implement all such rules with only minor variation across rules. It should come as no surprise that this orten involves the construction of highly abstract mechanisms. A premise of the research covered in this chapter is that to create a general foundation for implementation theory it makes sense to begin by identifying general conditions on social choice rules (and domains and equilibrium concepts) under which there exists some implementing mechanism. In this sense it is appropriate to view the highly abstract mechanisms more as vehicles for proving existence theorems than as specific suggestions for the nitty gritty details of organizational design. This is not to say that they provide no insights into the principles of such design, but rather to say that for most practical applications one could (hopefully) strip away a lot of the complexity of the abstract mechanisms. Thus a natural next direction to pursue, particularly for those interested in specific applications, is the identification of practical restrictions on mechanisms and the characterization of social choice rules that can be implemented by mechanisms satisfying such restrictions. Some research in implementation theory is beginning to move in this direction, and, by doing so, is beginning to bridge the gap between this literature and the aforementioned research which focuses on implementation using very special classes of procedures such as binary voting trees and bargaining rules. 2 The approach based on the revelation principle studies the truthful implementation [Dasgupta, Hammond and Maskin (1979)] of allocation rules [referred to as weak implementation in Palfrey and Srivastava (1993, p. 15)]. That is, an allocation rule is truthfully implementable if there is some equilibrium of some mechanism that leads to the desired allocation rule. This chapter only deals withfull implementation, where the implementing mechanism must have the property that all equilibria of the mechanism lead to the desired allocation rule.
Ch. 61: Implementation Theory
2275
F C
X
M Figure 1. M o u n t - R e i t e r diagram.
Finally, there are other surveys that interested readers would find useful. These include Allen (1997), Jackson (2002), Maskin (1985), Moore (1992), Palfrey (1992), Palfrey and Srivastava (1993), and Postlewaite (1985). 1.1. The basic structure o f the implernentation problem The simple structure of the general implementation problem provides a convenient way to organize the research that has been conducted to date in this area, and at the same time organize the possibilities for future research. Before presenting this classification scheine, it is useful to present one of the most concise representations of the implementation problem, called a Mount-Reiter diagram, a version of which originally appeared in Mount and Reiter (1974). Figure 1 contains the basic elements of an implementation problem. The notation is as foUows: g: The domain of environments. Each environment, e c g, consists of a set offeasible outcomes, A(e), a set of individuals, I(e), and apreferenceprofile R(e), where Ri(e) is a weak order on A(e). 3 X: The outcome space. Note: A(e) c_ X for all e 6 g. F c { f : g --+ X}: The welfare criterion (or social choice set) which specifies the set of acceptable mappings from environments to outcomes. An element, f , of F is called a social choicefunction. M = M1 x • .. x MN: The rnessage space. g : M ~ X: The outcomefunction. B ----(M, g): The mechanism. Z = The equilibrium concept that maps each/z into S~ c {er : g ~ M}. As an example to illustrate what these different abstract concepts might be, consider the domain of pure exchange economies. Each element of the domain would consist of a
3 Except w h e r e noted, w e will a s s u m e that the set of feasible outcomes is a constant A that is independent o f e, a n d the planner k n o w s A. Furthermore, w e will typically take the set o f individuals I = {1, 2 . . . . , N} as fixed.
2276
T.R. Palfrey
set of traders, each of whom has an initial endowment, and the set of feasible outcomes would just be the set of all reallocations of the initial endowment. Many implementation results rely on domain restrictions, which in this illustration would involve standard assumptions such as strictly increasing, convex preferences, and so forth. The welfare criterion, or social choice set, might consist of all social choice functions satisfying a list of conditions such as individual rationality, Pareto optimality, interiority, envyfreeness, and so forth. One common social choice set is the set of all selections from the Walrasian equilibrium correspondence. For this case the message space might be either an agent's entire preference mapping or perhaps his demand correspondence, and the "planner" would take on the role of the auctioneer. An example of an outcome function would be the allocations implied by a deterministic pricing rule (such as some selection from the set of market clearing prices), given the reported demands. Common equilibrium concepts employed in these settings are Nash equilibrium or dominant strategy equilibrium. The arrows of the Mount-Reiter diagram indicate that the diagram has the commutative property that, under the equilibrium concept Z, the set of desirable social choice functions defined by F correspond exacfly to the outcomes that arise under the mechanism/x. That is, F = g o Z#. When this happens, we say that "/z implements F via 27 in g". Whenever there exists some mechanism such that that statement is true, we say " F is implementable via 27 in g". Implementation theory then looks at the relationship between domains, equilibrium concepts, welfare criteria, and implementing mechanisms, and the various questions that may arise about this relationship. The remainder of this chapter summarizes a small part of what is known about this. Because this has been the main focus of the literature, the discussion here will concentrate primarily on the existence question: Under what conditions on F, 27, and g does there exist a mechanism/z such that/z implements F via 27 in g? 1.2. Informational issues To this point, nothing has been said about what information can be used in the construction of a mechanism nor about what information the individuals have about £. A common interpretation given to the implementation problem is that there is a mythical agent, called "the planner", who has normative goals and very limited information about the environment (typically one assumes that the planner only knows g and X). The planner then must elicit enough information from the individuals to implement outcomes in a manner consistent with those normative goals. This requires creating incentives for such information to be voluntarily and accurately provided by the individuals. Nearly all of the literature in implementation theory assumes that the details of the environment are not directly verifiable by the planner, even ex post. 4 Thus, implementation theory characterizes the limits of a planner's power in a society with decentralized information. 4 Thereare someresults on auditing and other expost verificationprocedures. See, for example, Townsend (1979), Chander and Wilde (1998) and the references they cite.
Ch. 61: ImplementationTheory
2277
The information that the individuals have about g is also an important consideration. This information is best thought of as part of the description of the domain. The main information distinction that is usually made in the literature is between complete information and incomplete information. Complete information models assume that e is c o m m o n knowledge among the individuals (but, of course, unknown to the planner). Incomplete information assumes that individuals have some private information. This is usually modeled in the Harsanyi (1967, 1968) tradition, by defining an environment as a profile of types, one for each individual, where a type indexes an individual's information about other individuals' types. In this manner, an environment (preference p r o f l e , set of feasible allocations, etc.) is uniquely defined for each possible type profile. One branch of implementation theory addresses a somewhat different informational issue. Given a social choice correspondence and a domain of environments, how much information about the environment is minimally needed to determine which outcome should be selected, and how close to this level of minimal information gathefing (informationally efficient) do different "natural" mechanisms come? In particular, this question has been asked in the domain of neoclassical pure exchange environments, where the answer is that the Walrasian market mechanism is informafionally efficient [Hurwicz (1977); Mount and Reiter (1974)]. With few exceptions that branch of implementation theory does not directly address questions of incentive compatibility of mechanisms. This chapter will not cover the contributions in that area.
1.3. Equilibrium: Incentive compatibility and uniqueness In principle, the equilibrium concept ~ could be almost anything. It simply defines a systematic rule for mapping environments into messages for arbitrary mechanisms. However, nearly all work in implementation theory and mechanism design restricts attention to equilibrium concepts borrowed from noncooperative garne theory, all of which require the rational response property in one form or another. That is, each individual, given their information, preferences, and a set of assumptions about how other individuals are behaving, and given a set of rules (M, g), adopts a rational response, where rationality is usually based on maximization o f expected utility. 5 The requirement of implementation can be broken down into two components. The first component is incentive compatibility: 6 This is most transparent for the special case of social choice functions (i.e., F is a singleton). If a mechanism <M, g) imPlements a social choice function f , it must be the case that there is an equilibrium strategy profile
5 There are some exceptions, notably the use of maximin strategies [Thomson (1979)] and undominated strategies [Jackson (1992)], which do not require players to adopt expected utifity maximizing responses to the strategies of the other players. 6 This is sometimes referred to as TruthfulImplementability [Dasgupta, Hammond, and Maskin (1979)] because, in the framework where individual preferences and information are represented as "types", if the lnechanism is direct in the sense that each individual is required to report their type (i.e., M = T), then the truthful strategy a (t) = t is an equilibrium of the direct mechanism # = (T, f).
2278
T.R. Palfrey
~r : g --+ M such that g o cr = f . The second component is uniqueness: If a mechanism (M, g) implements a social choice function f , it must be the case, for all social choice functions h ~ f , that there is not an equilibrium strategy profile erI such that g o crI = h. For the more general case of the implementation of a social choice set, F, these two components extend in the natural way. If a mechanism (M, g) implements a social choice set F, it must be the case that, for each f 6 F there is an equilibrium strategy profile cr such that g o cr = f . If a mechanism (M, g) implements a social choice set F, it must be the case, for all social choice functions h ~ F, that there is not an equilibrium strategy profile cr such that g o « = h.
1.4. The organization of this chapter The remainder of this paper is divided into three sections. Section 2 presents characterizations of implementafion under conditions of complete information for several different equilibrium concepts. In particular, the relatively comprehensive characterization for Nash implementation (i.e., implementation in complete information domains via Nash equilibrium) is set out in considerable detail. The partial characterizations for refined Nash implementation (subgame perfect equilibrium, undominated Nash equilibrium, dominance solvable equilibrium, etc.) are then discussed. This part also describes the problem of implementation by games of perfect information, and a few results in the area, particularly with regard to "vofing trees", are briefly discussed. Finally results for virtual implementation (both in Nash equilibrium and using refinements) are described, where social choice functions are only approximated as the equilibrium outcomes of mechanisms. Section 3 explains how the results for complete information are extended to incomplete information "Bayesian" domains, where environments are represented as collections of Harsanyi type-profiles, and players are assumed to have well-defined common knowledge priors about the distribution of types. Section 4 discusses some "difficult" problems in the area of implementation theory that have either been ignored or studied in only the simplest settings. This includes dynamic issues such as renegotiation of mechanisms and dynamic allocation problems, considerations of simplicity, robustness, and bounded rationality, and issues of incomplete control by the planner over the mechanism (side garnes played by the agents, or preplay communication).
2. Implementation under conditions of complete information By complete information, we mean that individual preferences and feasible alternatives are common knowledge among all the individuals. This does not mean that the planner knows these preferences. The planner is assumed to know only the set of pos-
Ch. 61: ImplementationTheory
2279
sible individual preference profiles and the set of feasible allocations. 7 For this reason, we simplify the notation considerably for this section of the chapter. First, we represent the domain by R, the set of possible preference profiles, with typical element R = (R1, R2 . . . . . RN), and the set of feasible alternatives is A. A social choice set can, without loss of generality, be represented as a correspondence F mapping R into subsets of A. We denote the image of F at R by F(R).
2.1. Nash implementation Consider a mechanism # = (M, g) and a profile R. The pair (/z, R) defines an N - p l a y e r noncooperative game. DEFINITION 1. A message profile m* 6 M is called a Nash equilibrium o f # at R il, for all i 6 I , and for all mi ~ Mi
g(m*)Rig(mi,m*_i). Therefore, the definition of Nash implementability is: DEFINITION 2. AsocialchoicecorrespondenceFisNashimplementableinRifthere exists a m e c h a n i s m / z = (M, g) such that: (a) For every R ~ R and for every x ~ F(R), there exists m* E M such that m* is a Nash equilibrium o f / x at R and g(m*) = x. (b) For every R 6 R and for every y q~ F(R), there does not exist m* 6 M such that m* is a Nash equilibrium o f / z at R and g(m*) = y. Alternatively, writing a*(R) as the set of Nash equilibria of # at R, we can state (a) and (b) as: (a ~) F(R) c_ g oa*(R) f o r a l l R ~ R, (b f) g ocr*(R) _c F(R) f o r a l l R 6 R. Condition (a) corresponds to what we have referred to as incentive compatibility and condition (b) is what we have referred to as uniqueness. We proceed from here by characterizing the implications of (a) and (b).
2.1.1. Incentive compatibility Suppose a social choice function f : R --+ A is implementable via Nash equilibrium. Then there exists a mechanism # that implements f via I7 in £. W h a t exactly does this 7 Nearly always, the set of feasible allocations is taken as fixed in implementation theory. A notable exception to this is Hurwicz, Maskin, Postlewaite (1995). In this paper, the mechanism has individuals report endowments as well as preferences to the planner, but it is assumed that it is impossible for an individual to overstate his endowment (although understatements are possible). See Hong (1996, 1998) and Tian (1994) for extensions to Bayesian environments.
T.R. Palfrey
2280
mean? First, it means that there is a Nash equilibrium of/z that yields f as the equilibrium outcome function. With complete information this tums out to have very little bite. That is, examples of social choice functions that are not "incentive compatible" when the individuals have complete information are rather special. How special, you might ask. First, the examples must have only two individuals. This fact is quickly established below as Proposition 3.
In complete information domains with N > 2, every social choice is incentive compatible (i.e., there exists a mechanism such that (a) is
PROPOSITION 3.
function f satisfied).
PROOF. Consider the following mechanism, which we call the agreement mechanism. Let Mi = R for all i 6 I. That is, individuals report profiles. 8 Arbitrarily pick some a0 c A. Partition the message space into two parts, Ma (called the agreement region) and Md (called the disagreement region).
Ma = {m E M [ 3 j E I, R ~ R such thatmi = R for all i s& j}; Md = {m ö M I m q~Ma}. In other words, the agreement region consists of all message profiles where either every individual reports the same preference profile, or all except one individual report the same preference profile. The outcome function is then defined as follows.
g(m)
f(R)
! ao
i f m E Ma, if m E Md.
It is easy to see that if the profile of preferences is R, then it is a Nash equilibrium for all individuals to report mi = R, since unilateral deviations from unanimous agreement will not affect the outcome. Therefore, (a) is satisfied. [] Therefore, incentive compatibility9 is not an issue when information is complete and N > 2. Of course the problem with this mechanism is that any unanimous message profile is a Nash equilibrium at any preference profile. Therefore, this mechanism does not satisfy the uniqueness requirement (b) of implementation. We return to this problem shortly, after addressing the question of incentive compatibility for the N = 2 case. 8 Thismechanismcould be simplifiedfurther by havingeach agentreport a feasibleoutcome. 9 The reader shouldnot confuse this with a numberof negativeresults on implementationof social choice functions via Nash equilibriumwhen mechanismsare restricted to being "direct" mechanisms (Mi = R j). If individualsdo not report profiles, but only report their own componentof the profile (sometimes called privacy-preserving mechanisms),then clearlyincentivecompatibilitycan be a problem.This kind of incentive compatibility is usually called strategyproofness, and is closely related to the problem of implementation under the rauch stronger equilibriumconcept of dominantstrategy equilibrium.See Dasgupta, Hammond, and Maskin (1979).
Ch. 61:
Implementation TheoJ~y
2281
When N = 2 the outcome function of the mechanism used in Proposition 3 is not well defined, since a unilateral deviation from unanimous agreement is not well defined. If m l = R and m2 = R ~, then it is unclear whether g(m) = f ( R ) or g(m) = f(R~). There are some simple cases where incentive compatibility is assured when N = 2. First, if there exists a uniformly bad outcome, w, with the property that, for all a 6 A, and for all R ~ R, aRiw, i = 1, 2. In that case, the mechanism above can be modified so that Ma requires unanimous agreement, and ao = w. Clearly any unanimous report of a profile is a Nash equilibrium regardless of the acmal preferences of the individuals, so this modified mechanism satisfies (a) but falls to satisfy (b). A considerably weaker assumption, called nonempty lower intersection, is due to Dutta and Sen (1991b) and Moore and Repullo (1990). We state a slightly weaker version below, which is sufficient for the incentive compatibility requirement (a) when N = 2. They define a slightly stronger version that is needed to satisfy the uniqueness requirement (b). DEFINITION 4. A social choice function f satisfies Weak Nonempty Lower Intersection 1° if, for all R, R ~ 6 R, such that R 5~ R ~, 3c ~ A such that f ( R ) R l C and f(R~)R~2 c. The definition of social choice correspondences is similar: DEFINITION 5. A social choice correspondence F satisfies Weak Nonempty Lower Intersection if for all R, R ~ 6 R, such that R ¢ R ~, and for all a c f ( R ) and b E f (R~), ~c ~ A such that aRlc and bR~2c. To see that this is a sufficient condition for (a), consider implementing the social choice function f . From Defnition 4, we can define a function c(R, R ~) for R ~ R ~ with the property that f ( R ) R l c ( R , R') and f(R~)R~2c(R, Rt). We can then modify the mechanism above by:
I f(R) g ( m ) = [c(R~,R)
i f m l = m 2 = R,
ifml=Randm2=R
~.
This mechanism is illustrated in Figure 2. It is easy to check that weak nonempty lower intersection guarantees m = (R, R) is a Nash equilibrium when the actual profile is R. There are two interesting special cases where Nonempty Lower Intersection holds. The first is when there exists a universally "bad" outcome [Moore and Repullo (1990)] with the property that it is strictly less preferred than all outcomes in the range of the social choice rule, for all agents, at all profiles in the domain.l 1 This is satisfied by any
I0 The stronger version, called Nonempty Lower Intersection, requires f ( R ) Pl c and f ( R1) P~ c. 11 Notice that this is a joint restriction on the domain and the social choice function.
ZR. Palfrey
2282 Player 2
R
R
R/
f(R)
C(R',R)
Player 1
R' C(R,R')
f(R')
Figure 2. (Weak) Nonempty Lower Intersection: f(R)R1C(R, R/), f(R/)R~2C(R, R/) f(R/)R~C(R/, R), f(R)R2C(R !, R) ~ f(R) c NE(R), f(R/) ~ NE(R/).
and
nonwasteful social choice rule in exchange economies with free disposal and strictly increasing preferences, since destruction of the endowment is a bad outcome. The second special case is any Pareto efficient and individually rational interior social choice correspondence in exchange economies (with or without free disposal) with strictly convex and strictly increasing preferences and fixed initial endowments [Dutta and Sen (1991b); Moore and Repullo (1990)].
2.1.2. Uniqueness Clearly, incentive compatibility places few restrictions on Nash implementable social choice functions (and correspondences) with complete information. The second requirement of uniqueness is more difficult, and the major breakthrough in characterizing this was the classic paper of Maskin (1999). In that paper, he introduces two conditions, which are jointly sufficient for Nash implementation when N 7> 3. These conditions are called Monotonicity and No Veto Power (NVP). DEFINITION 6. A social choice correspondence F is Monotonic iL for all R, R ~ 6 R
(x c F ( R ) , x f~ F(Rt)) ::~ 3i E I, a E A such t h a t x R i a P { x . The agent i and the alternative a are called, respectively, the test agent and the test alternative. Stated in the contrapositive, this says simply that if x is a socially desired alternative at R, and x does not strictly fall in preference for anyone when the profile is changed to R ~, then x must be a socially desired alternative at R ~. Thus monotonic social choice correspondences must satisfy a version of a nonnegative responsiveness criterion with respect to individual preferences. In fact, this is a remarkably strong requirement
Ch. 61: ImplementationTheory
2283
for a social choice correspondence. For example, it rules out nearly any scoring rule, such as the Borda count or Plurality voting. Several other examples of nonmonotonic social choice functions in applications to bilateral contracting are given in Moore and Repullo (1988). One very nice illustration of a nonmonotonic social choice correspondence is given in the following example. It is a variation on the "King Solomon's Dilemma" example of Glazer and Ma (1989) and Moore (1992), where the problem is to allocate a baby to its true mother.
2.1.3. Example 1 There are two individuals in the game (Ms. o~ and Ms. fl), and four possible alternatives: a = give the baby to Ms. «, b = give the baby to Ms. fi, c = divide the baby into two equal halves and give each mother one half, d = execute both mothers and the child. Assume the domain consists of only two possible preference profiles depending on whether « or fi is the real mother, and we will call these profiles R and R' respectively. They are given below:
R~=a»b»c»d,
R~=a»c»b»d,
Rp=b»c»a»d,
R~=b»a»c»d.
The social choice function King Solomon wishes to implement is f ( R ) = a and f ( R ~) = b. This is not monotonic. Consider the change from R to R/. Alternative a does not fall in either player's preference order as a result of this change. However, f (R ~) = b ~ a, a contradiction of monotonicity. Notice however that this social choice function is incentive compatible since there is a universally bad outcome, d, which is ranked last by both players in both of their preference orders. A second examp!e, from a neoclassical 2-person pure exchange environment illustrates the geometry of monotonicity.
2.1.4. Example 2 Consider allocation x in Figure 3. Suppose x ~ f ( R ) where the indifference curves through x of the two individuals are labelled R1 and R2 respectively in that figure. Now consider some other profile R / where R2 = R~, and RI1 is such that the lower contour set of x for individual 1 has expanded. Monotonicity would require x ~ f (R/). Put another way (formally stated in the definition), if f is monotonie and x ¢ f ( R ~) for some R ~~ R, then one of the two individuals must have an indifference curve through x that either crosses the R-indifference
T.R. Palfrey
2284
Agent 2
Rll [R; R2 =
R~ R2 =
Agent 1 Figure 3. Illustration of monotonicity: x c F(R) ~ x ~ F(R~). curve through x or bounds a strictly smaller lower contour set. Figure 4 illustrates the (generic) case in which the R~-indifference curve of one of the individuals (individual 1, in the figure) crosses the R-indifference curve through x. Thus, in this example agent 1 is the test agent. One possible test alternative a ~ A (an alternative required in the definition of monotonicity which has the property that xRiaP/x) is marked in that figure.
2.1.5. Necessary and sufficient conditions Maskin (1999) proved that monotonicity is a necessary condition for Nash implemenration. THEOREM 7. If F is Nash implementable then F is monotonic. PROOF. Consider any m e c h a n i s m / z that Nash implements F and consider some x E F(R) and some Nash equilibrium message, m*, at profile R, such that g(m*) = x. Define the "option set ''12 for i at m* as
Oi(m*; # ) = {a E A [ 3m I ~ Mi such that «(ml,m*_i) = a } . 12 This is similar to the role of option sets in the strategyproofnessliteramre.
Ch. 61: lmplementation Theory
2285 Agent 2 !
R2 = R~
2 R 2 = R~ Agent 1 Figure 4. Illustrationof tests agentand test allocation: x R la P~x.
That is, fixing the messages of the other players at m ' i , the range of possible outcomes that can result for some message by i under the mechanism # is Oi(m*; I~). By the definition of Nash equilibrium, x*Ria for all i and for all a ~ Oi (m*; #). Now consider some new profile R ~ where x ~ F(R~). Since/~ Nash implements F , it must be that m is not a Nash equilibrium at R'. Thus there exist some i and some alternative a e Oi(m*; #) such that aPz(x. Thus a is the test alternative and i is the test agent as required in Definition 6, with the property that x Ria P/x. [] The second theorem in Maskin (1999) was proved in papers by Williams (1984, 1986), Saijo (1988), McKelvey (1989), and Repullo (1987). 13 It provides an elegant and simple sufficient condition for Nash implementation for the case of three or more agents. This is a condition of near unanimity, called No Veto Power (NVP). DEFINITION 8. A social choice correspondence F satisfies No Veto Power (NVP) if, for all R ~ R and for all x ~ A, and i ~ I,
[ x R j y for all j 5~ i, for all y e Y] ~ x ¢ F ( R ) . 13 Groves (1979) credits Karl Vind for some of the ideas underlyingthe now-standardconstructiveproofs of sufficiency,and writes down a version of the theorem that uses these ideas in the proof. That version of the theorem, as weh as the version of the theorem proved by Williams (1984, 1986), imposes stronger assumptionsthan in Maskin (1999).
T.R. Palfrey
2286
THEOREM 9. If N >~ 3 and F is Monotonic and satisfies NVP,, then F is Nash implementable. PROOF. The proof given here is constructive and is similar to one in Repullo (1987). A very general mechanism is defined, and then the rest of the proof consists of demonstrating that the mechanism implements any social choice funcfion that satisfies the hypotheses of the theorem. This is usually how characterization theorems are proved in implementation theory. Consider the following generic mechanism, which we call the agreement/integer mechanism:
~=R×A×{O,
1,2 . . . . }.
That is, each individual reports a profile, an allocation, and an integer. The outcome function is similar to the agreement mechanism, except the disagreement region is a bit more complicated, and agreement must be with respect to an allocation and a profile.
Ma = {m ~ M [ 3j, R ~ R, a ~ F ( R ) such that mi = (R, a, zi), where zi = 0 for each i 7~ j };
Md = { m c M ] m q ~ M a } . The outcome function is defined as follows. The outcome function is constructed so that, if the message profile is in Ma, then the outcome is either a or the allocation announced by individual j , which we will denote aj. If the outcome is in Md, then the outcome is ag where k is the individual announcing the highest integer (fies broken by a predetermined rule). This feature of the mechanism has become commonly known as an integer garne (although in actuality, it is only a piece of the original garne form). Formally,
{
a
g(m) =
aj ak
if m ~ Ma and aj Pja, i f m E Ma a n d a R j a j , i f m c Md and k = max{i ~ I ] zi >~zj for all j e I}.
Recall that we must show that F ( R ) c_ N E # ( R ) and NE u (R) c_ F ( R ) for all R, where NEIz(R ) = {a E A [ 3m ~ M such that a = g ( m ) R i g ( m l , m - i ) for all i ~ I, m I c Mi} is the set of Nash equilibrium outcomes to/x at R. (1) F ( R ) c_ N E ~ ( R ) . At any R, and for any a 6 F ( R ) , there is a Nash equilibrium in which all individuals report mi ----(R, a, 0). Such a message lies in Ma and any unilateral deviafion also lies in Ma. The only unilateral deviation that could change the outcome is a deviation in which some player j reports an alternative aj such that a R j a j . Therefore, a is a R j-maximal element of Oj (m;/~) for all j 6 I, so m = (R, a, O) is a Nash equilibrium.
Ch. 61: lmplementation Theory
2287
(2) N E u ( R ) c_ F ( R ) . This is the more delicate part of the proof, and is the part that exploits Monotonicity and NVP. (Notice that part (1) of the proof above exploited only the assumption that N >~ 3.) Suppose that m ~ N E u ( R ) and g(m) = a q~ F ( R ) . First notice that it cannot be the case thät all individuals are reporting (R I, a, 0) where a 6 F ( R I) for some R' 6 R. This would put the o u t c o m e i n Ma and Monotonicity guarantees the existence of some j ~ I, b 6 A such that a R ) b P j a , so pläyer j is bettet oft changing to a message (., b, .) which changes the outcome from a to b. Thus mi ~ m j for some i, j . Whenever this is the case, the option set for at least N - 1 of the agents is the entire alternative space, A. Since a ~ F ( R ) and F satisfies NVP, it taust be that there is at least one of these N - 1 agents, k, and some element c a A such that cPka. Since the option set for k is the entire alternative space, A, individual k is better oft changing his message to (., c, Zk) ~ m j where z~ > z j, j ~ k, which will change the outcome from a to c. This contradicts the hypothesis that m is a Nash equilibrium. [] Since these two results, improvements have been developed to make the characterization of Nash implementation complete and/of to reduce the size of the message space of the general implementing mechanism. These improvements are in Moore and Repullo (1990), Dutta and Sen (1991b), Danilov (1992), 14 Saijo (1988), Sjöström (1991) and McKelvey (1989) and the references they cite. The last part of this section on Nash implementation is devoted to a simple application to pure exchange economies. It turns out the Walrasian correspondence satisfies both Monotonicity and NVP under some mild domain restrictions. First notice that in private good economies with strictly increasing preferences and three or more agents, NVP is satisfied vacuously. Next suppose that indifference curves are strictly quasi-concave and twice continuously differentiable, endowments for all individuals are strictly positive in every good, and indifference curves never touch the axis. It is well known that these conditions are sufficient to guarantee the existence of a Walrasian equilibrium and to further guarantee that all Walrasian equilibrium allocations in these environments are interior points, with every individual consuming a positive amount of every good in every competitive equilibrium. Finally, assume that "the planner" knows everyone's endowment. 15
14 Of these, Danilov(1992) establishes a particularlyelegantnecessary and sufficientcondition(with three or more players), which is a generalizationof the notion of monotonicity,called essential monotonicity. However, these results are limited somewhat by this assumptionof universaldomain. Nash implementable social choice correspondences need not satisfy essential monotonicityunder domain restrictions. Yamato (1992) gives necessary and sufficientconditionson restricted domains. 15 This assumption can be relaxed. See Hurwicz, Maskin, and Postlewaite (1995). The Walrasian correspondence can also be modified somewhat to the "constrainedWalrasiancorrespondence" which constrains individual demands in a particular way. This modifiedcompetitive equilibriumcan be shown to be implementable in more general economicdomainsin which Walrasianequilibriumallocationsare not guaranteed to be locallyunique and interior. See the surveyby Postlewaite (1985), or Hurwicz (1986).
2288
T.R. Palfrey
Since the planner knows the endowments, a different mechanism can be constructed for each endowment profile. Thus, to check for monotonicity it suffices to show that the Walrasian correspondence, with endowments fixed and only preferences changing, is monotonic. If a is a Walrasian equilibrium allocation at R and not a Wah-asian equilibrium allocation at R ~, then there exists some individual for whom the supporting price line for the equilibrium at R is not tangent to the R~ indifference curve through a. But this is just the same as the illustration in Figure 4, and we have labelled allocation b as a "test allocation" as required by the monotonicity definition. The key is that for a to be a Walrasian equilibrium allocation at R and not a Walrasian equilibrium allocation at R ~ implies that the indifference curves through x at R and R ~ cross at x. As mentioned briefly above, there are many environments and "nice" (from a normative standpoint) allocation rules that violate Monotonicity, and in the N = 2 case ("bilateral contracting" environments) NVP is simply too strong a condition to impose on a social choice function. There are two possible responses to this problem. Orte possibility, and the main direction implementation theory has pursued, is that Nash equilibrium places insufficient restrictions on the behavior of individuals. 16 This leads to consideration of implementation using refinements of Nash equilibrium, or refined Nash implementation. A second possibility is that implementability places very strong restrictions on what kinds of social choice functions a planner can hope to enforce in a decentralized way. If not all social choice functions can be implemented, then we need to ask "how close" we can get to implementing a desired social choice function. This has led to the work in virtual implementation. These two directions are discussed next.
2.2. Refined Nash implementation More social choice correspondences can be implemented using refinements of Nash equilibrium. The reason for this is straightforward, and is easiest to grasp in the case of N ~> 3. In that case, the incentive compatibility problem does not arise (Proposition 3), so the only issue is (ii) uniqueness. Thus the problem with Nash implementation is that Nash equilibrium is too permissive an equilibrium concept. A nonmonotonic social choice function fails to be implementable simply because there are too many Nash equilibria. It is impossible to have f ( R ) be a Nash equilibrium outcome at R and at the same time avoid having a ~ f ( R ) also be a Nash equilibrium outcome at R. But of
16 One might argue to the contrary that in other ways Nash equilibriumplaces too strong a restriction on individualbehavior.Both directionsare undoubtedlytrue. Experimentalevidencehas shownthat both of these are defensible.On the one hand, some refinementsof Nash equilibriumhave received experimentalsupport indicating that additionalrestrictions beyond mutual best response have predictive value [Banks, Camerer, and Porter (1994)]. On the other hand, manyexperimentsindicatethat players are at best imperfectlyrational, and even violate simplebasic axioms such as transitivityand dominance.Thus, from a practical standpoint, it is very importantto explore the implementationquestionunder assumptionsother than the simplemutual best responsecriterionof Nash equilibrium.
Ch. 61: lmplementationTheory
2289
course this is exactly the kind of problem that refinements of Nash equilibrium can be used for. The trick in implementation theory with refinements is to exploit the refinement by constructing a mechanism so that precisely the "bad" equilibria (the equilibria whose outcomes lie outside of F) are refined away, while the other equilibria survive the refinement. 17
2.2.1. Subgame perfect implementation The first systematic approach to extending the Maskin characterization beyond Nash equilibrium in complete information environments was to look at implementation via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium [Moore and Repullo (1988); Abreu and Sen (1990)]. They find that more social choice functions can be implemented via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium than via Nash equilibrium. The idea is that sequential rationality can be exploited to eliminate certain bad equilibria. The following simple example in the "voting/social choice" tradition illustrates the point.
2.2.2. Example 3 There are three players on a committee who are to decide between three alternatives, A = {a, b, c}. There are two profiles in the domain, denoted R and R t. Individuals 1 and 2 have the same preferences in both profiles. Only player 3 has a different preference order under R than under R ~. These are listed below:
Rl=R]=a»b»c, R3=c»a»b,
R2=R~=b»c»a, R~=a»c»b.
The following social choice function is Pareto optimal and satisfies the Condorcet criterion that an alternative should be selected if it is preferred by a majority to any other alternative:
f(R) =b,
f(R') =a.
This social choice function violates monotonicity since b does not go down in player 3's rankings when moving from profile R to R ~ (and no one else's preferences change). Therefore it is not Nash implementable. However, the following trivial mechanism (extensive form game form) implements it in subgame perfect Nash equilibrium:
17 Earlier work by Farquharson (1957/1969), Moulin (1979), Crawford (1979) and Demange (1984) in specific applications of multistage games to voting theory, bm'gaining theory, and exchange economies foreshadows the more abstract formulation in the relatively more recent work in implementation theory with refinements.
T.R. Palfrey
2290 1
Outcome
Outcome = a
Outcome = c
Figure 5. Garne tree for Example 2.
Stage 1: Player 1 either chooses alternative b, or passes. The game ends if b is chosen. The garne proceeds to stage 2 if player 1 passes. Stage 2: Player 3 chooses between a and c. The game ends at this point. The voting tree is illustrated in Figure 5. To see that this garne implements f , work back from the final stage. In stage 2, player 3 would choose c in profile R and a in profile R/. Therefore, player l ' s best response is to choose b in profile R and to pass in profile Rq Notice that there is another Nash equilibrium under profile R ~, where player 2 adopts the strategy of choosing c if player 1 passes, and thus player 1 chooses b in stage 1. But of course this is not sequentially rational and is therefore ruled out by subgame perfection.
2.2.3. Characterization results Abreu and Sen (1990) provide a nearly complete characterization of social choice correspondences that are implementable via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, by giving a general necessary condition, which is also sufficient if N ~> 3 for social choice functions satisfying N V E This condition is strictly weaker than Monotonicity, in the following way. Recall that monotonicity requires, for any R, R' and a ~ A, with a = f ( R ) , a ~ f(R'), the existence of a test agent i and a test allocation b such that aRibR;a. That there is some player and some allocation that produces a preference switch with f ( R ) when moving from R to Rq The weakening of this resutting from the sequential rationality refinement is that the preference switch does not have to involve f ( R ) directly. Any preference switch between two altemätives, say b and c, will do, as long as these alternatives can be indirectly linked to f ( R ) in a particular fashion. We formally stare this necessary condition and call it indirect monotonicity,18 to contrast it with the 18 Abreu and Sen (1990) call it Condition«.
Ch. 61: ImpIementationTheory
2291
direct linkage to f ( R ) of the test alternative in the original definition of monotonicity. DEFINITION 10. A social choice correspondence F satisfies indirect monotonicity if there 3B _c A such that F(R) c_ B for all R c 7~, and if for all R, R r and a c A, with a ~ F(R), a ~ F(R~), 3L < oc, and ~ a sequence of agents {j0 . . . . . iL} and 3 sequences of alternatives {a0 . . . . . aL+l}, {b0 . . . . . bL} belonging to B such that: (i) akRjkak+l, k = O, 1. . . . . L; (il) aL+IP~LaL; (iii) bkP'jkak, k = 0 , 1 . . . . . L; (iv) (a L+IRjLb ' Vb E B) ::=}(L = 0 or JL-1 -= jL). The key parts of the definition of indirect monotonicity are (i) and (ii). A less restrictive version of indirect monotonicity consisting of only parts (i) and (ii) was used first by Moore and Repullo (1988) as a weaker necessary condition for implementation in subgame perfect equilibrium with multistage games. The main two general theorems about implementation via subgame perfect implementation are the following. The proofs [Abreu and Sen (1990)] are long and tedious and are omitted, although an outline of the proof for the sufficiency result is given. Similar results, but slightly less general, can be found in Moore and Repullo (1988). THEOREM 1 1 (Necessity). If a social choice correspondence F is implementable via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, then F satisfies indirect monotonicity. THEOREM 12 (Sufficiency). If N >~3 and F satisfies NVP and indirect monotonicity,
then F is implementable via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium. PROOF. This is an outline of the sufficiency proof. Since F safisfies indirect monotonicity, there exists the required set B and for any (R, R I, a) such that a c F(R) and a ~ F ( R r) there exists an integer L and the required sequences {jk(R, R', a)}k=0,1 ..... L and {ak(R, R ~, a)}k=0,1 ..... L+I that satisfy (i)-(iv) of Definition 6. In the first stage of the mechanism, all ag ents announce a triple of the form (m i 1, m i 2, m i 3 ) where m i 1 C R , mi2 E A, and mi3 E {0, 1 . . . . }. The first stage of the game then conforms faMy closely to the agreemenffinteger mechanism, with a minor exception. If there is too much disagreement (there exist three or more agents whose reports are different) the outcome is determined by mi2 of the agent who announced the largest integer. If there is unanimous agreement in the first two components of the message, so all agents send some (R, a, zi) and a ~ F(R), then the game is over and the outcome is a. The same is true if there is only orte disagreeing report in the first two components, unless the dissenting report is sent by io(R, miol, a), in which case the first of a sequence of at most L "binary" agreement/integer garnes is triggered in which either some agent gets to choose bis most preferred element of B or the next in the sequence of binary agreemenffinteger
2292
T.R. Palfrey
games is triggered. If the game ever gets to the (L + 1)st stage, then the outcome is aL+l and the game ends. The rest of the proof follows the usual order. First, one shows that for all R 6 T~ and for all a ~ F ( R ) there is a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium at R with a as the equilibrium outcome. Second, one shows that for all R 6 7~ and for all a ~ F(R) there is no subgame perfect Nash equilibrium at R with a as the equilibrium outcome. [] In spite of its formidable complexity, some progress has been made tracing out the implications of indirect monotonicity for two well-known classes of implementation problems: exchange economies and voting. Moore and Repullo (1988) show that any selection from the Walrasian equilibrium correspondence satisfies indirect monotonicity, in spite of being nonmonotonic. There are also some results for the N = 2 case that can be found in Moore (1992) and Moore and Repullo (1988) which rely on sidepayments of a divisible private good. The case of voting-based social choice rules contrasts sharply with this. Abreu and Sen (1990), Palfrey and Srivastava (1991a) and Sen (1987) show that many voting rules fail to satisfy indirect monotonicity, as do most runoff procedures and "scoring rules" (such as the famous Borda rule). However, a class of voting-based social choice correspondences, including the Copeland rule, is implementable via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium [Sen (1987)]. Some related findings are in Moulin (1979), Dutta and Sen (1993), and the references they cite. There are a number of applications that exploit the combined power of sidepayments and sequential mechanisms. See Glazer and Ma (1989), Varian (1994), and Jackson and Moulin (1990). Moore (1992) also gives some additional examples. 2.2.4. ImpIementation by backward induction and voting trees In general, it is not possible to implement a social choice function via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium without resorting to games of imperfect information. At some point, it is necessary to have a stage with simultaneous moves. Others have investigated the implementation question when mechanisms are restricted to games of perfect information. In that case, the refinement implied by solving the garne in its last stage and working back to earlier moves, generates similar behavior as subgame perfect equilibrium. 19 Example 3 above illustrates how it is possible for nonmonotonic social choice functions to be implemented via backward induction. The work of Glazer and Ma (1989) illustrates how economic contracting and allocation problems similar in structure to Example 1 (King Solomon's Dilemma) can be solved with backward induction implementation if sidepayments are possible. Crawford's work (1977, 1979) on bargaining 19 In fact, it is exactly the same if players are assumed to have strict preferences. Much of the work in this area has evolved as a branch of social choice theory, where it is commonto work with environments where A is finte and preferences are linear orders on A (i.e., slxict).
Ch. 61:
Implementation Theory
2293
mechanisms 2° proves in fairly general bargaining settings that games of perfect information can be used to implement nonmonotonic social choice functions that are fair. The general problem of implementation by backward induction has been studied by Hererro and Srivastava (1992) and Trick and Srivastava (1996). The characterizafions, unfortunately, are quite cumbersome to deal with, and the necessary conditions for implementation via backward induction are virtually impossible to check in most settings. But some useful results have been found for certain domains. Closely related to the problem of implementation by backward induction is implementation by voting trees, using the solution concept of sophisticated voting as developed by Farquharson (1957/1969). Sophisticated voting works in the following way. First, a binary voting tree is defined, which consists of an initial pair of alternatives, which the individuals vote between. Depending on which outcome wins a majority of votes, 21 the process either ends or moves on to another, predetermined pair and another vote is taken. Usually one of the alternatives in this new vote is the winner of the previous vote, but this is not a requirement of voting trees. The tree is finite, so at some point the process ends regardless of which alternative wins. Sophisticated voting means that one starts at the end of the voting tree, and, for each "final" vote, determines who will win if everyone votes sincerely at that last stage. Then one moves back one step to examine every penultimate vote, and voters vote taking account of how the final votes will be determined. Thus, as in subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, voters have perfect foresight about the outcomes of future votes, and vote accordingly. The problem of implementation by voting trees was first studied in depth by Moulin (1979), using the concept of dominance solvability, which reduces to sophisticated voting [McKelvey and Niemi (1978)] in binary voting trees. There are two distinct types of sequential voting procedures that have been investigated in detail. The first type consists of binary amendmentprocedures. In a binary amendment procedure, all the altematives (assumed to be finite) are placed in a fixed order, say, (al, a z . . . . . alAi). At stage 1, the first two alternatives are voted between. Then the winner goes against the next alternative in the list, and so forth. A major question in social choice theory, and for that matter, in implementation theory, is how to characterize the set of social choice functions that are implementable by binary amendment procedures via sophisticated voting. This work is closely related to work by Miller (1977), Banks (1985), and others, which explores general properties of the majority-mle dominance relation, and following in the footsteps of Condorcet, looks at the implementability of social choice correspondences that satisfy certain normative properties. Several results appear in Moulin (1986), who identifies an "adjacency condition" that is necessary for implementation via binary voting trees. For more details, the reader is referred to the chapter on Social Choice Theory by Moulin (1994) in Volume II of this Handbook.
20 This includes the divide-and-choose m e t h o d a n d generalizations o f it. 21 It is c o m m o n to a s s u m e an o d d n u m b e r of voters for obvious reasons. Extensions to permit even numbers o f voters are usually possible, but the occurrence of ties clutters up the analysis.
2294
T.R. Pa~rey
More recent results on implementation via binary voting trees äre found in Dutta and Sen (1993). First, they show that implementability by sophisticated voting in binary voting trees implies implementability in backward induction using games of perfect information. They also show that several well-known seleetions from the top-cycle set 22 are implementable, but that certain selections that have appealing normative properties are not implementable. Z Z 5. Normal form refinements There are some other refinements of Nash equilibrium that have been investigated for mechanisms in the normal form. These fall into two categories. The first category relies on dominance (either strict or weak) to eliminate outcomes that are unwanted Nash equilibria. This was first expióred in Palfrey and Srivastavä (1991a) where implementation via undöminated Nash equilibrium is characterized. Subsequent work that explores this and other vätiations of dominänce-based implementation in the normal form includes Jackson (1992), Jackson, Palfrey, and Srivastava (1994), Sjöström (1991), Tatamitani (1993) and Yamato (1993). Using a different approach, Abreu and Matsushima (1990) obtain results for implementation in iteratively weakly undominated strategies, if randomized mechanisms can be used and small fines can be imposed out of equilibrium. The work by Abreu and Matsushima (1992a, 1992b), Glazer and Rosenthal (1992), and Duggan (1993) extends this line of exploiting strategic dominance relations to refine equilibria by looking at iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies and also investigating the use of these dominance arguments to design mechanisms that virtually imptement (see Section 2.3 below) social choice functions. The second category of refinements looks at implementation via trembling hand perfect Nash equilibrium, The main contribution here is the work of Sjöström (1993). The central finding of the work in implementation theory using normal form refinements is that essentiatly anything can be implemented. In particular, it is the case that dominance-based refinements are more powerful than refinements based on sequential rationality, at least in the context of implementation theory, A simple result is in Palfrey and Srivastava (1991a), for the case of undominated Nash equilibrium. DEFINITION 13. Consider a mechanism/z = (M, g). A message profile m* E M is called an undominated Nash equilibrium of lz at R if, for all i E I, for all mi E Mi, g(m*)Rig(mi, m*_i) and there does not exist i c I and mi E M such that
g(mi, m_i ) Rig(m *, m-i) g(mi, m-i)Pig(m~, m-i)
m-i E M-i and s o m e m-i E M-i.
for all for
22 The top-cycleset at R is the minimalsubset, TC, of A, with the propertythat for all a, b such that a ~ TC and b ~ TC, a majorltystrictly prefersa to b. This set has a very prominentrole in the theory of voting and committees.
Ch. 61: ImplementationTheory
2295
In other words, m* is an undominated Nash equilibrium at R if it is a Nash equilibrium and, for all i, m* is not weakly dominated. THEOREM 14. Suppose R contains no profile where some agent is indifferent between
all elements of A. If N ~ 3 and F satisfies NVP, then F is implementable in undominated Nash equilibrium. PROOF. The proof of this theorem is quite involved. It uses a variation on the agreement/integer garne, but the general construction of the mechanism uses an unusual technique, called tailchasing. Consider the standard agreement/integer garne,/x, used in the proof of Theorem 9. If m* is a Nash equilibrium o f / z at R, but g(m*) q~ f ( R ) , then one can make m* dominated at R by amending the garne in a simple way. Take some player i and two alternatives x, y such that xPiy. A d d a message m I for a player i and a message for each of the other players j ¢ i, m j, such that
g(m~,m_i)=g(mti,m_i) g(m*,mI_i) = y,
f o r a l l m _ i 7~m~_i ,
g(m~,mt_i)=x.
Now strategy m* is dominated at R. Of course, this is not the end of the story, since it is now possible that (m~, m*_i) is a new undominated Nash equilibrium which still produces the undesired outcome a ~ f ( R ) . To avoid this, we can add another message for i, m "i and another message for the other players j --/:i, mj~~ and do the same thing again. If we repeat this an infinite number of times, we have created an infinite sequence of strategies for i, each one of which is dominated by the next one in the sequence. The complication in the proof is to show that in the process of doing this, we have not disturbed the "good" undominated Nash equilibria at R and have not inadvertently added some new undominated Nash equilibria. [] This kind of construction is illustrated in the following example.
2.2.6. Example 4 This example is from Palfrey and Srivastava (1991a, pp. 488--489).
A={a,b,c,d}, RI ~- R2 a b cd
N=2,
R = { R , Rt}:
Rtl = R; a
b c d F ( R ) = {a, b}, F(R') = {a}.
2296
T.R. Palfrey
It is easy to show that there is no implementation with a finite mechanism, and any implementation taust involve an infinite chain of dominated strategies for one player in profile R t. One such mechanism is: Player 2
mI
a
c
c
c
...
Player
m2
c
b
d
d
...
1
m~
c
b
c
d
...
m4
c
b
c
c
...
2.2.7. Constraints on mechanisms Few would argue that mechanisms of the sort used in the previous example solve the implementation problem in a satisfactory manner. 23 This concern motivated the work of Jackson (1992) who raised the issue of bounded mechanisms. DEFINITION 15. A mechanism is bounded relative to R iL for all R E R, and mi E Mi, if mi is weakly dominated at R, then there exists an undominated (at R) message mli ~ Mi that weakly dominates mi at R. In other words, mechanisms that exploit infinite chains of dominated strategies, as occurs in tailchasing constructions, are ruled out. Note that, like the best response criterion, it is not just a property of the mechanism, but a joint restriction on the mechanism and the domain. Jackson (1992) 24 shows that a weaker equilibrium notion than Nash equilibrium, called "undominated strategies", has a similar property to undominated Nash implementation, namely that essentially all social choice correspondences are implementable. He shows that if mecbanisms are required to be bounded, then very restrictive results reminiscent of the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem hold, so that almost no social choice function is implementable via undominated strategies with bounded mechanisms. However, these negative results do not carry over to undominated Nash implementation.
23 In fact, few would argue that any of the mechanismsused in the most general sufficiencytheorems are particularly appealing. 24 That is also the first paper to seriouslyraise the issue of mixed strategies. All of the results that have been described so far in this paper are for pure strategy implementation. Only very recently have results been appearing that expficitly address the mixed strategy problem. See for exarnple the work by Abreu and Matsushima (1992a) on virtualimplementation.
Ch. 61: lmplementationTheory
2297
Following the work of Jackson (1992), Jackson, Palfrey, and Srivastava (1994) provide a characterization of undominated Nash implementation using bounded mechanisms and requiring the best response property. They find that the boundedness restriction, while ruling out some social choice con'espondences, is actually quite permissive. First of all, all social choice correspondences that are Nash implementable are implementable by bounded mechanisms [see also Tatamitani (1993) and Yamato (1993)]. Second, in economic environments with free disposal, any interior allocation rule is implementable. Furthermore, there are many allocation rules that fall to be subgame perfect Nash implementable that are implementable via undominated Nash equilibrium using bounded mechanisms. Boundedness is not the only special property of mechanisms that has been investigated. Hurwicz (1960) suggests a number of criteria for judging the adequacy of a mechanism. Saijo (1988), McKelvey (1989), Chakravorti (1991), Dutta, Sen, and Vohra (1994), Reichelstein and Reiter (1988), Tian (1990) and others have argued that message spaces should be as small as possible and have given results about how small the message spaces of implementing mechanisms can be. Related work focuses on "natural" mechanisms, such as restrictions to price-quantity mechanisms in economic environments [Saijo et al. (1996); Sjöström (1995); Corchon and Wilkie (1995)]. Abreu and Sen (1990) argue that mechanisms should have a best response property relative to the domain for which they are designed. Continuity of outcome functions as a property of implementing mechanisms has been the focus of several papers [Reichelstein (1984); Postlewaite and Wettstein (1989); Tian (1989); Wettstein (1990, 1992); Peleg (1996a, 1996b) and Mas-Colell and Vives (1993)]. 2.3. Virtual implementation 2.3.1. Virtual Nash implementation A mechanism virtually implements a social choice function 25 if it can (exactly) implement arbitrarily close approximations of that social choice function. The concept was first introduced by Matsushima (1988). It is immediately obvious that, regardless of the domain and regardless of the equilibrium concept, the set of virtually implementable social choice functions contains the set of all implementable social choice functions. What is less obvious is how much more is virtually implementable compared with what is exactly implementable. It turns out that it makes a big difference. One way to see why so rauch more is virtually implementable can be seen by referring back to Figure 3. That figure shows how the preferences R and R' must line up in order for monotonicity to have any bite in pure exchange economies. As can readily
25 The workon virtual implementation limits attention to single-valuedsocial choicecorrespondences.Since the results in this area are so permissive (i.e., few social choicefunctionsfall to be virtually implementable), this does not seemto be an importantrestricdon.
2298
T.R.Palfrey
be seen, this is not a generic picture. Rather, Figure 4 shows the generic case, where monotonicity places no restrictions on the social choice at R ' if a = f(R). Virtual implementation exploits the nongenericity o f situations where monotonicity is binding. 26 It does so by implementing lotteries that produce, in equilibrium at R, f ( R ) with very high probability, and some other outcomes with very low probability. In finite or countable economic environments, every social choice function is virtually implementable if individuals have preferences over lotteries that admit a von N e u m a n n Morgenstern representation and if there are at least three agents. 27 The result is proved in Abreu and Sen (1991) for the case of strict preferences and under a domain restriction that excludes unanimity among the preferences of the agents over pure alternatives. They also address the 2-agent case, where a nonempty lower intersection property is needed. A key difference between the virtual implementation construction and the Nash implementation construction has to do with the use of lotteries instead of pure alternatives in the test pairs. In particular, virtual implementation allows test pairs involving lotteries in the neighborhood (in lottery space) of f (R) rather than requiring the test pairs to exactly involve f(R). It turns out that by expanding the first allocation of the test pair to any neighborhood of f(R), one can always find a test pair of the sort required in the definition of monotonicity. There are several ways to illustrate why this is so. Perhaps the simplest is to consider the case of von N e u m a n n - M o r g e n s t e m preferences for lotteries. If an individual maximizes expected utility, then his indifference surfaces in lottery space are parallel hyperplanes. For the case of three pure alternatives, this is illustrated in Figure 6. For this three alternative case, consider two preference profiles, R and R I, which differ in some individual's von N e u m a n n - M o r g e n s t e r n utility function. This means that the slope o f the indifference lines for this individual has changed. Accordingly, in every neighborhood of every interior lottery in Figure 6, there exists a test pair of lotteries such that this agent has a preference switch over the test pair of lotteries. Now consider a social choice function that assigns a pure allocation to each preference profile, but that fails to satisfy monotonicity. In other words, the social choice function assigns one of the vertices of the triangle in Figure 6 to each profile. We can perturb this social choice function ever so slightly so that instead of assigning a vertex, it assigns an interior lottery, x, arbitrarily close to the vertex. This "approximation" of the social choice function satisfies monotonicity because there exists agent i (whose von N e u m a n n - M o r g e n s t e m utilities have changed), and a lottery y such that xRiyR~x. In this way, every (interior)
26 This fact that monotonicity holds generically is proved formally in Bergin and Sen (1996). They show for classica[ pure exchange environments with continuous, strictly monotone (but not necessarily convex) preferences there exists a dense subset of utility functions that always "cross" (i.e., there are never tangencies of the sott depicted in Figure 2). 27 In fact, more general lottery preferences can be used, as long as they satisfy a condition that guarantees individuals prefer lotteries that place more probability weight on more-preferredpure altematives.
Ch. 61: Implementation Theory
2299
C
a
b
Figure 6. Vertices a, b, and c represent pure alternatives, with all other points representing lotteries over those alternatives. The indifference curves passing through lottery x for agent i under two von NeumannMorgenstern utility functions are labelled R i and R~, with the direction of preference marked with arrows. Lottery y satisfies xRiyR~x.
approximation of every pure social choice function in this simple example is monotonic and hence (if veto power problems are avoided) implementable. Abreu and Sen (1991) prove that this simple construction outlined above for the case of von Neumann-Morgenstem preferences and lA[ -- 3 is very general. The upshot of this is that moving from exact to virtual implementation completely eliminates the necessity of monotonicity.
2.3.2. Virtual implementation in iterated removal of dominated strategies An even more powerful result is established in Abreu and Matsushima (1992a). They show that if only virmal implementation is required, then in finite-profile environments one can find mechanisms such that not only is there a unique Nash equilibrium that approximately yields the social choice function, but the Nash equilibrium is strictly dominance solvable. They exploit the fact that for each agent there is a function h from his possible preferences to lottery space, h, such that if Ri 5~ R~, t h e n h ( R i ) R i h ( R ~ ) and h(R~)R;h(Ri). The message space of agent i consists of a single report of i's own preferences and multiple (ordered) reports of the entire preference profile, with the final outcome patching together pieces of a lottery, each piece of which is determined by some portion of the reported profiles. The payoff function is then constructed so that falsely reporting one's own type as R I at R will lead to individual i receiving the g(R ~) lottery instead of the g(R) lottery with some probability, so this false report is a strictly
2300
T.R. Palfi'ey
dominated strategy. Incentives are provided so that subsequent 2s reports of the profile will "agree" with earlier reports in a particular way. The first defection from agreement is punished severely enough to make it unprofitable to defect from the truthful selfreports of the first component of the message space. The degree of approximation can then be made as fine as one wishes simply by requiring a very large number of reported profiles. Formally, a message for i is a K + 1 vector mi = (m O, m~ . . . . . mK), where the first component is an element of i ' s set of possible preferences and the other K components are each elements of the set of possible preference profiles. The outcome function is then pieced together in the following way. Let e be some small positive number. With probability e/I (where I is the number of players), the outcome is based only on m/°, and equals h(m°i), so i is strictly better oft reporting m/° honestly. With probability e2/I agent i is rewarded il, for all k = 1 . . . . . K, m/k = m ° whenever mj = m ° for all j f = i for all h < k. That is, i gets a small reward (in expected terms) for honestly revealing his preference, and then gets an order of magnitude smaller reward for always agreeing with the vector of first reports (including his own). These are the only pieces of the outcome function that are affected by m °. Clearly, for e small enough the first order loss overwhelms any possible second order gain from falsely reporting m °. Thus messages involving false reports of m ° are strictly dominated. The remaining pieces of the outcome function (each of which is used with probability (1 - e - e2)/K) correspond to the final K components of the messages, where each agent is reporting ä preference profile. If everyone agrees on the kth profile, then that kth piece of the outcome function is simply the social choice function at that commonly reported profile. For K large enough, the gain one can obtain from deviating and reporting m/~ ~ m ° in the kth piece can be made arbitrarily small. But the penalty for being the first to report m/k ~ m ° is constant with respect to K , so this penalty will exceed any gain from deviating when K is large. Thus deviating at h = k + 1 can be shown to be dominated once all strategies involving deviations at h < k + 1 have been eliminated. Variations on this "piecewise" approximation technique also appear in Abreu and Matsushima (1990) where the results are extended to incomplete information (see below) and Abreu and Matsushima (1994) where a similar technique is applied to exact implementation via iterated elimination of weakIy dominated strategies. 29 This kind of construction is quite a bit different from the usual Maskin type of construction used elsewhere in the proofs of implementation theorems. It has a number of attractive features, one of which is the avoidänce of any mixed strategy equilibria. 28 The term "subsequent" should not be interpreted as meaning that the profiles are reported sequentially, since the garne is simultaneous-move.Rather, the vector of reported profiles is ordered, so subsequent refers to the reported profile with the next index number. Glazer and Rubinstein (1996) show that there is a similar sequential garne that can be constructed which is dominance solvable following sirnilar logic. 29 Glazer and Perry (1996) show that this mechanism can be reconstructed as a multistage mechanism which can be solved by backward induction. Glazer and Rubinstein (1996) propose that this reduces the computational burden on the players.
Ch. 61: ImpIementation Theory
2301
In other constructions, mixed strategies are usually just ignored. This can be problematic as an example of Jackson (1992) shows that there are some Nash implementable social choice correspondences that are impossible to implement by a finite mechanism without introducing other mixed strategy equilibria. A second feature is that in finite domains one can implement using finite message spaces. While this is also true for Nash implementation when the environment is finite, there are several examples that illustrate the impossibility of finite implementation in other settings. Palfrey and Srivastava (1991a) show that sometimes infinite constructions are needed for undominated Nash implementation, and Dutta and Sen (1994b) show that Bayesian Nash implementation in finite environments can require infinite message spaces. Glazer and Rosenthal (1992) raise the issue that in spite of the obvious virmes of the implementing mechanism used in the Abreu and Matsushima (1992a) proof, there are other drawbacks. In particular, Glazer and Rosenthal (1992) argue that the kind of game that is implied by the mechanism is precisely the same kind of game that game theorists have argued as being fragile, in the sense that the predictions of Nash equilibrium are not a priori plausible. Abreu and Matsushima (1992b) respond that they believe iterated strict dominance is a good solution concept for predictive 3° purposes, especially in the context of their construction. However, preliminary experimental findings [Sefton and Yavas (1996)] indicate that in some environments the Abreu-Matsushima mechanisms perform poorly. This is part of an ongoing debate in implementation theory about the "desirability" of mechanisms and/or solution concepts in the constructive existence proofs that are used to establish implementation results. The arguments by critics are based on two premises: (1) equilibrium concepts, or at least the ones that have been explored, do not predict equally well for all mechanisms; and (2) the quality of the existence result is diminished if the construction uses a mechanism that seems unattractive. Both premises suggest interesting avenues of future research. An initial response to (1) is that these are empirical issues that require serious study, not mere introspection. The obvious implication is that experimenta131 work in game theory will be crucial to generating useful predictive models of behavior in games. This in turn may require a redirection of effort in implementation theory. For example, from the garne theory experiments that have been conducted to date, it is clear that limited rationality considerations will need to be incorporated into the equilibrium concepts, as will statistical (as opposed to deterministic) theories of behavior. 32
30 In implementation theory, it is the predictive value of the solution concept that matters. One can think of the solufion concept as the planner's model for predicting outcomes that will arise under different mechanisms and in different environments, ff the model predicts inaccurately, then a mechanism will fall to implement the planner's targeted social choice function. 31 The use of controlled experimentation in setfling these empirical questions is urged in Abreu and Matsushima's (1992b) response to Glazer and Rosenthal (1992). 32 See, for example, McKelvey and Palfrey (1995, 1996, 1998).
2302
T.R. Palfrey
Possible responses to (2) are more complicated. The cheap response is that the implementing mechanisms used in the proofs are not meant to be representative of mechanisms that would actually be used in "real" situations that have a lot of structure. These are merely mathematical techniques, and any mechanism used in a "real" situation should exploit the special structure of the situation. Since the class of environments to which the theorems apply is usually very broad, the implementing mechanisms used in the construcfive proofs must work for almost any imaginable setting. The question this response begs is: f o r a specißc problem o f interest, can a " reasonable" mechanism be f o u n d ? The existence theorems do not answer this question, nor are they intended to. That is a question of specific application. So far, even with the alternative mechanisms of Abreu-Matsushima, the mechanisms used in general constructive existence theorems are impractical. However, some nice results for familiar environments exist [e.g., Crawford (1979); Moulin (1984); Jackson and Moulin (1990)] that suggest we can be optimistic about finding practical mechanisms for implementation in some common economic settings.
3. Implementation with incomplete information This section looks at the extension of the results of Section 2 to the case of incomplete information. Just as most of the results above are organized around Nash equilibrium and refinements, the same is done in this section, except the baseline equilibrium concept is Harsanyi's (1967, 1968) Bayesian equilibrium. 33 3.1. The type representation
The main difference in the model structure with incomplete information is that a domain specifies not only the set of possible preference profiles, but also the information each agent has about the preference profile and about the other agents' information. We adopt the "type representation" that is familiar to literature on Bayesian mechanism design [see, e.g., Myerson (1985)]. An incomplete information domain 34 consists of a set, I, of n agents, a set, A, of feasible alternatives, a set of types, Tl, for each agent i E I, a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function for each agent, ui : T x A -+ T~, and a collection of conditional probability distributions {qi(t-i [ti)}, for each i E I and for each ti E Ti. There area variety of familiar domain restrictions that will be referred to, when necessary, as follows: (1) Finite types: ITil < oo. (2) Diffusepriors: qi (t-i Iti) > 0 for all i E I, for all ti ~ Ti, and for all t-i E T - i .
33 This should come as no surprise to the reader, since Bayesian equilibrium is simply a version of Nash equilibrium, adapted to deal with asymmetries of information. 34 Myerson (1985) calls this a Bayesian Collective Decision Problem.
Ch. 61: lmplementation Theory
2303
(3) Private values: 35 ui(ti, t-i, a) = ui(ti, t!_i , a) for all i, ti, t_i, t!_i , a. (4) Independent types: qi (t-i Iti) = qi (t-i [t;) f o r all i, ti, tl_i , t - i , a. (5) Value-distinguished types: For all i, tl, t; ~ Ti , ti ~ t; , ~a, b such that u i ( ti , t-i, a) > ui(ti, t-i, b) and ui(t;, t-i, b) > ui(t;, t-i, a) for all t-i ~ T-i. A social choicefunction (or allocation rule) f ; T --+ A assigns a nnique outcome to each type profile. A social choice correspondence, F, is a collection of social choice functions. The set of all allocation rules in the domain is denoted by X, so in general, we have f E F _c X. A mechanism # = (M, g) is defined as before. A strategy for i is a function mapping 7~ into Mi, denoted ai : Ti -+ Mi. We also denote type ti of player i's interim utility of an allocation rule x 6 X by: Ui(x, ti) • E t { u i (x(t), t) lt i }, where Et is the expectätion over t. Similarly, given a strategy profile a in a mechanism/z, we denote type ti of player i's interim utility ofstrategy a in IZ by:
vi («, ti)= ~,/ùi(«(««)), 01,i}. 3.2. Bayesian Nash implementation The Bayesian approach to full implementation with incomplete information was initiated by Postlewaite and Schmeidler (1986). Bayesian Nash implementation, like Nash implementation, has two components, incentive compatibility and uniqueness. The main difference is that incentive compatibility imposes genuine restrictions on social choice functions, unlike the case of complete information. When ptayers have private information, the planner must provide the individual with incentives to reveal that information, in contrast to the complete information case, where an individual's report of his information could be checked against another individual's report of that information. Thus, while the constructions with complete information rely heavily on mutual auditing schemes that we called "agreement mechanisms", the constructions with incomplete information do not. 36 DEFINITION 16. ti~Ti Ui (dr, tl) ~ Ui
A strategy « is a Bayesian equilibrium of # if, for all i and for all
!
(o-i,
~r_i, t i)
!.
for all O-i
. ~/~ ~
M i.
35 In this case, we simply write u i (ti, a), since i's utility depends only on his own type. 36 There are special exceptions where mutual auditing schemes can be used, which include domains in which there is enough redundancy of information in the group so that an individual's report of the state may be checked against the joint report of the other individuals. This requires a condition called Non-Exclusive Information (NEI). See Postlewaite and Schmeidler (1986) or Palfrey and Srivastava (1986). Complete information is the extreme form of NEI.
T.R.Palfrey
2304
DEFINITION 17. A social choice function f : T ~ A (or allocation rule x : T --+ A) is Bayesian implementable if there is a m e c h a n i s m / z = (M, g) such that there exists a Bayesian equilibrium o f / x and, for every Bayesian equilibrium, « , of M, f ( t ) = g(«(t)) for all t 6 T. Implementable social choice sets are defined analogously. For the rest of this secfion, we restrict attention to the simpler case of diffuse types, defined above. Later in the chapter, the extension of these results to more general information strnctures will be explained.
3.2.1. Incentive compatibility and the Bayesian revelation principle Paralleling the definition for complete information, a social choice function (or allocation rule) is called (Bayesian) incentive compatible if and only if it can arise as a Bayesian equilibrium of some mechanism. The revelation principle [Myerson (1979); Harris and Townsend (1981)] is the simple proposition that an allocation rule x can arise as the Bayesian equilibrium to some mechanism if and only if trnth is a Bayesian equilibrium of the direct 37 mechanism,/z = (T, x). Thus, we state the following. DEFINITION 1 8.
A n allocation rule x is incentive compatible if, for all i and for all
Ui(x, Ii) ~ Et{ui(x(~,t-i),t)lti}. 3.2.2. Uniqueness Just as the multiple equilibrium problem can arise with complete information, the same can happen with incomplete information. In particular, direct mechanisms often have this problem (as was the case with the "agreement" direct mechanism in the complete information case). Consider the following example.
3.2.3. Example 5 This is based on an allocation rule investigated in Holmstrom and Myerson (1983). There are two agents, each of whom has two types. Types are equally likely and statistically independent and individuals have private values. The alternative set is A = {a, b, c}. Utility functions are given by (Uij denotes the utility to type j of player i): U l l ( a ) = 2 u l l ( b ) = lull(C)---- 0,
Ul2(a) = 0Ul2(b) = 4u12(c) z 9,
u21 (a) = 2u21 (b) ---=lu21 (c) mm0,
u22(a) = 2u22(b) = lu22(c) z - 8 .
37 A mechanism is directif Mi = T1 for all i 6 I.
Ch. 61: ImplementationTheory
f/j
2305
The following social choice function, f , is incentive compatible and efficient (where denotes the outcome when player 1 is type i and player 2 is type j):
fll = a ,
f12 = b ,
f21 = c ,
f22 = b .
It is easy to check that for the direct revelation mechanism (T, f ) , there is a "truthful" Bayesian equilibrium where both players adopt strategies of reporting their actual type, i.e., f is incentive compatible. However, there is another equilibrium of (T, f ) , where both players always report type 2 and the outcome is always b. We call such strategies in the direct mechanism deceptions, since such strategies involve falsely reported types. Denoting this deceptive strategy profile as «, it defines a new social choice function, which we call f«, defined by f«(t) =-- f(oe(t))t. This illustrates that this particular allocation rule is not Bayesian Nash implementable by the direct mechanism. However, it turns out to be possible to add messages, augmenting 38 the direct mechanism into an "indirect" mechanism that implements f . One way to do this is by giving player 1 another pair of messages, call them "truth" and "lie", one of which must be seht along with the report of his type. The outcome function is then defined so that g(m) = f ( t ) if the vector of reported types is t and player one says "truth". If player 1 says "lie", then g(m) = f ( q , t~) where tl is player l's reported type and t~ is the opposite of player 2's reported type. This is illustrated in Figure 7. It is easy to check that if the players use the o~ deception above, then player 1 will announce "lie", which is not an equilibrium since player 2 woutd be better oft always responding by announcing type 1. In fact, simple inspection shows that there are no longer any Bayesian equilibria that lead to social choice functions different from f , and (truth, "truth") is a Bayesian equilibrium 39 that leads to f .
3.2.4. Bayesian monotonicity Given that the incentive compatibility condition holds, the implementation problem boils down to determining for which social choice functions it is possible to angment the direct mechanism as in the example above, to eliminate unwanted Bayesian equilibria. This is the so-called method ofselective elimination [Mookherjee and Reichelstein (1990)] that is used in most of the constructive sufficiency proofs in implementation theory. Again paralleling the complete information case, there is a simple necessary condition for this to be possible, which is an "interim" version of Maskin's monotonicity condition (Definition 6), called Bayesian monotonicity. DEFINITION 19. A social choice correspondence F is Bayesian monotonic iL for every f 6 F and for every joint deception o~: T -+ T such that f« ~ F, ~i ~ I, ti E Tl,
38 The terminology"angmented"mechanismis due to Mookherjeeand Reichelstein (1990). 39 There is anotherBayesianequilibrium that also leads to f. See Palfreyand Srivastava(1993).
T.R. Palfrey
2306
tl
Player 2 t2
(tl, "truth")
a
b
(t2, "truth")
c
b
(tl, "lie")
b
a
(te, "lie")
b
c
Player 1
Figure 7. Implementingmechanismfor Holmstrom-Myersonexample.
and an allocation rule y: T -+ A such that Ui(f~, ti) < Ui(y~, ti) and, for all t[ e Tl,
Ui (f, t[) >~ Ui (y, t[). The intuition behind this condition is simpler than it looks. In particular, think of the relationship between f and f« being roughly the same in the above definition as the relationship between R and R', the difference being that with asymmetric information, we need to consider changes in the entire social choice function f , rather than limiting attention to the particular change in type profile from R to R' ( o r t to t', in the type notation). So, if f~ ~ F (analogous to a ~ F(R') in the complete information formulation), we need a test agent, i, and a test allocation rule y (analogous to test allocation, in the monotonicity definition), such that i's (interim) preference between f and y is the reverse of his preference between f« and y,~ (with the appropriate quantifiers and qualifiers included). Thus the basic idea is the same, and involves a test agent and a test allocation rule.
Ch. 61: lmplementationTheory
2307
3.2.5. Necessary and sufficient conditions We are now ready to state the main result regarding necessary conditions4° for Bayesian implementation. THEOREM 20. If F is Bayesian Nash implementable, then F is Bayesian monotonic, and every f ~ F is incentive compatible. PROOF. The necessity of incentive compatibility is obvious. The proof for necessity of Bayesian monotonicity follows the same logiß as the proof for necessity of monotonicity with complete information (see Theorem 7). [] As with complete information, sufficient conditions generally require an allocation rule to be in the social choice correspondence if there is nearly unanimous agreement among the individuals about the "best" allocation rule. This is the role of NVP in the original Maskin sufficiency theorem. There are two ways to guarantee this. The first way (and by far the simplest) is to make a domain assumption that avoids the problem by ruling out preference profiles where there is nearly unanimous agreement. The prototypical example of such a domain is a pure exchange economy. In that case, there is a great deal of conflict across agents, as each agent's most preferred outcome is to be allocated the entire societal endowment, and this most preferred outcome is the same regardless of the agent's type. Another related example includes the class of environments with sidepayments using a divisible private good that everyone values positively, the best-known case being quasi-linear utility. We present two sufficiency results, one for the case of pure exchange economies, and the second for a generalization. We assume throughout that information is diffuse and n ~> 3. Consider a pure exchange economy with asymmetric information, E, with L goods and n individuals, where the societal endowment41 is given by w = (wa . . . . . wL). The alternative set, A, is the set of all nonnegative allocations of w across the n agents. 42 The set of feasible allocation rules mapping T into A are denoted X. THEOREM 2 1. Assume n >~ 3 and information is diffuse. A social choice function x ~ X is Bayesian Nash implementable ifand only ifit satisfies incentive compatibility and Bayesian monotonicity.
40 There are other necessary conditions.For example, F must be closed with respect to commonknowledge concatenations.See Postlewaite and Schmeidler (1986) or Palfrey and Srivastava(1993) for details. 41 We will not be addressing questionsof individualrationality,so the initial allocationof the endowmentis ler unspecified. 42 One couldpermit fi'eedisposal as well, but this is not needed for the implementationresult. The constructions by Postlewaite and Schmeidler (1986) and Palfrey and Srivastava(1989a) assume free disposal. We do not assume it here, but do assume diffuse information.Free disposabilitysimplifiesthe constructionswhen informationis not diffuse, by permittingdestructionof the entire endowment(i.e., all agents receive 0) when the joint reported type profile is not consistentwith any type profile in T.
T.R. Palfrey
2308
P~ooê. Only if follows from Theorem 20. It is only slightly more difficult. Once again, we use a variation on the agreement/integer garne, adapted to the incomplete information framework. Notice, however, that there is always "agreement" with diffuse types, since each player is submitting a different component of the type profile, and all reported type profiles are possible. Each player is asked to report a type and either an allocation rule that is constant in his own type (but can depend on other players' types) or a nonnegative integer. Thus: M i = Tix{X_ i
U {0, 1 . . . . }}
where X i denotes the set of allocation rules that are constant with respect to ti. The agreement region is the set of message profiles where each player sends a reported type and "0". The unilateral disagreement region is the set of message profiles where exactly orte agent reports a type and something other than "0". Finally, the disagreement region is the set of all message profiles with at least two agents failing to report "0". In the agreement region, the outcome is just x (t), where t is the reported type profile. In the unilateral disagreement region the outcome is also just x (t), unless the disagreeing agent, i, sends y ~ X - i with the property that Ui (x, t~) ». Ui (y , t[) for all t~ c Tl. In that case, the outcome is y (t). In the disagreement region, the agent who submits the highest integer 43 is allocated w and everyone else is allocated 0. Notice how the mechanism parallels very closely the complete information mechanism. The structure of the unilateral disagreement region is such that if all individuals are reporting truthfully, no player can unilaterally falsely report and/of disagree and be bettet oft. By incentive compatibility it does not pay to announce a false type. The fact that y does not depend on the disagreer's types implies that it doesn't pay to report y and a false (or true) type. Therefore, there is a Bayesian equilibrium in the agreement region, where all players truthfully report their types. There can be no equilibrium outside the agreement region, because there would be at least two agents each of whom could unilaterally change his message and receive w. Thus the only possible other equilibria that might arise would be in the agreement region, where agents are using a joint deception oe. But the Bayesian monotonicity condition (which f satisfies by assumption) says that either x~ = x or there exists a y, and i, and a ti, such that Ui (x, t~) ~~. U i (y, t~) for all t~ 6 7) but Ui(y«, tl) > Ui(x«, ti). Since it is easy to project y onto X - i [see Palfrey and Srivastava (1993)] and preserve these inequalities, it follows that i is bettet oft deviating unilaterally and reporting y instead of "0". [] The extension of the above result to more general environments is simple, as long as individuals have different "best elements" that do not depend on their type. For each i, suppose that there exists an alternative bi such that U/(bi, t) >/ Ui (a, t) for all a E A
43 In this region, if a player sends an allocation instead of an integer, this is counted as "0". Ties are broken in favor of the agent with the lowest index.
Ch. 61: ImplementationTheory
2309
and t E T, and further suppose that for all i, j it is the case that Ui (bi, t) > Ui (b j, t) for all t 6 T. If this condition holds, we say players have distinct best elements. THEOREM 22. If n ~ 3, information is diffuse and players have distinct best elements,
then f is Bayesian implementable if and only if f is incentive compatible and Bayesian monotonic. PROOF. Identical to the proof of Theorem 21, except in the disagreement region the outcome is bi, where i is winner of the integer garne. [] Jackson (1991) shows that the condition of distinct best elements can be further weakened, and their result is summarized in Palfrey and Srivastava (1993, p. 35). An even more general version that considers nondiffuse as well as diffuse information structures is in Jackson (1991). That paper identifies a condition that is a hybrid between Bayesian monotonicity and an interim version of NVR called monotonicity-no-veto (MNV). The earlier papers by Postlewaite and Schmeidler (1986) and Palfrey and Srivastava (1987, 1989a) also consider nondiffuse information structures. Dutta and Sen (199 lb) provide a sufficient condition for Bayesian implementation, when n ~> 3 and information is diffuse, that is even weaker than the M N V condition of Jackson (1991). They call this condition extended unanimity, and it, like MNV, incorporates Bayesian monotonicity. They also prove that when this condition holds and T is finite, then any incentive compatible social choice function can be implemented using a finite mechanism. They do this using a variation on the integer garne, called a modulo garne, 44 which accomplishes the same thing as an integer garne but only requires using the first n positive integers. Dutta and Sen (1994b) raise an interesting point about the size of the message space that may be required for implementation of a social choice function. They present an example of a social choice function that fails their sufficiency condition (it violates unanimity and there are only two agents), but is nonetheless implementable via Bayesian equilibrium. Bnt they are able to show that any implementing mechanisms must use an infinite message space, in spite of the fact that both A and T are finite. Dutta and Sen (1994a) extend their general characterization of Bayesian implementable social choice correspondences when n ~> 3 to the n = 2 case, using an interim version of the nonempty lower intersection property that they used in their n = 2 characterization with complete information [Dutta and Sen (1991a)]. This complements some earlier work on characterizing implementable social choice functions by Mookherjee and Reichelstein (1990). Dutta and Sen (1994a) extend these results to characterize
The modulo game is due to Saijo (1988) and is also used in McKelvey (1989) and elsewhere. A potential weakness of a modulo garne is that it typically introduces unwanted mixed s~ategy equilibria that could be avoided by the familiar greatest-integer garne.
44
2310
T.R.Palfrey
Bayesian implementable social choice correspondences for the n ----2 case, for "economic environments".45 All of the results described above are restricted (either explicitly or implicitly) to finite sets of player types. Obviously for many applications in economics this is a strong requirement. Duggan (1994b) provides a rigorous treatment of the many difficult technical problems that can arise when the space of types is uncountable. He extends the results of Jackson (1991) to very general environments, and identifies some new, more inclusive conditions that replace previous assumptions about best elements, private values, and economic environments. The key assumption he uses is called interiority, which is satisfied in most applications.
3.3. ImpIementation using refinements of Bayesian equilibrium Just as in the case of complete information, refinements permit a wider class of social choice functions to be implemented. These fall into two classes: dominance-based refinements using simultaneous-move mechanisms, and sequential rationality refinements using sequential mechanisms. In both cases, the results and proof techniques have similarities to the complete information case.
3.3.1. Undominated Bayesian equilibrium The results for implementation using dominance refinements in the normal form are limited to undominated Bayesian implementation, where a nearly complete characterization is given in Palfrey and Srivastava (1989b). An undominated Bayesian equilibrium is a Bayesian equilibrium where no player is using a weakly dominated strategy. There are several results, some positive and some negative. First, in private value environments with diffuse types and value-distinguished types, any incentive compatible allocation rule satisfying no veto power is implementable via undominated Bayesian equilibrium. The proof assumes the existence of best and worst elements 46 for each type of each agent, but does not require No Veto Power. They also show that with nonprivate values, some additional very strong restrictions are needed, and, moreover, the assumption of value distinction is critical. 47
45 The term economicis vague. "Inforrrlallyspeaking, an economicenvh-onmentis one where it is possible to make some individualstrictly better oft from any given allocationin a rnannerwhich is independentof her type. This hypothesis, while strong, will be satisfied if there is a transferable private good in which the utilities of both individualsare strictlyincreasing". [Dutta and Sen (1994a, p. 52).] 46 Nofice that if A is finite or more generallyif A is compact and preferences are continuous,then best and worst elementsexist. The proof can be extended to cover some special environmentswhere best elementsdo not exist, such as the qnasi-linearutilitycase. 47 The assumptionof value distinctionis stronger than might appear. It mies out environmentswhere two types of an agent differ only in their beliefs about the other agents. One can imagine some natural environments where value distinctionmightbe violated, such as tinancialtradingenvironments,where a key feature of the informationstmcture involveswhat agents know about what other agents know.
Ch. 61: ImplementationTheory
2311
Two simple voting public goods examples illustrate both the power and the limitations (with c o m m o n values) of the undominated refinement. 3.3.2. Example 6 There are three agents, two feasible outcomes, A = {a, b}, private values, independent types, and each player can be one of two types. Type « strietly prefers a to b and 1 type/3 strictly prefers b to a, and the probability of being type ot is q, with q2/> ~" The "best solution" according to almost any set of reasonable norrnative criteria is to choose a if and only if at least two agents are type «. Surprisingly, this "majoritarian" solution, while incentive compafible, is not implementable via Bayesian equilibrium. It is fairly easy to show that for any mechanism that produces the majoritarian solution as a Bayesian equilibrium that mechanism will have another equilibrium in which outcome b is produced at every type profile. However, it is easy to see that the majoritarian solution is implementable via undominated Bayesian equilibrium, since it is the unique undominated Bayesian equilibrium 48 outcome in the direct mechanism. 3.3.3. Example 7 This is the same as Example 6 (two feasible outcomes, tb_ree agents, two independent types and type ot occurs with probability q2 > ½), except there are common values. 49 The common preferences are such that if a majority of agents are type of, then everyone prefers a to b, and if a majority of agents are type/~, then everyone prefers b to a. We call these "majoritarian preferences". Obviously, there is a unique best social choice function for essentially any non-malevolent welfare criterion, which is the majoritarian (and unanimous, as well!) solution: choose a if and only if at least two agents are type «. First observe that because of the common values feature of this example, players no longer have a dominant strategy in the direct game for agents to honestly report their true type. (Of course, truth is still a Bayesian equilibrium of the direct garne.) One can show [Palfrey and Srivastava (1989b)] that this social choice function is not even implementable in undominated Bayesian equilibrium. In particular, any mechanism which produces the majoritarian solution as an undominated Bayesian equilibrium always has another undominated Bayesian equilibrium where the outcome is always b. The point of Example 7 is to illustrate that with common values, using refinements may have only limited usefulness in a Bayesian framework. We know from the work in complete information that implementation requires the existence of test agents and test
48 Notice that it is actually a dominantstrategy equilibrium of the direct mechanism. This example i11ustrates how it is possible for an allocation rule to be dominant strategy implementable (and strategy-proof),but not Bayesian Nash implementable. 49 By common values we mean that every agent has the same type-contingentpreferences. A related mechanism design problem is explored in more depth by Glazer and Rubinstein (1998).
2312
ZR. Palfrey
pairs of allocations that involve (often delicate) patterns of preference reversal between preference profiles. Analogously, in the Bayesian setting such preference reversals must occur across type profiles. With private values, such preference reversals are easy to find. With common values and/or non-value-distinguished types, such preference reversals often simply do not exist, even in very natural examples of social choice functions that satisfy No Veto Power and N > 2.
3.3.4. Virtual implementation with incomplete information For virtual implementation, Abreu and Matsushima have an extension of their complete information paper on the use of iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies [Abreu and Matsushima (1990)] for implementation in incomplete information environments. They show that, under a condition they call measurability and some additional minor restrictions on the domain, any incentive compatible social choice function defined on finite domains can be virtually implemented by iterated elimination of stricfly dominated strategies. Abreu and Matsushima (1994) conjecture that with some additional assumptions (such as the ability to use small monetary transfers) one may be able to obtain exact implementation via iterated elimination of weakly dominated strategies in finite incomplete information domains. Duggan (1997) looks at the related is sue of virtual implementation in B ayesian equilibrium (rather than iterated elimination of dominated strategies). He shows that the measurability of Abreu and Matsushima (1990) is not necessary for virtual Bayesian implementation, and uses a condition called incentive consistency. Serrano and Vohra (1999) have recently shown that both measurability and incentive consistency are stronger conditions than originally implied in these papers. Results and examples in that paper provide insight into the kinds of domain restrictions that are required for the permissive virtual implementation results. In a sequel to that paper, Serrano and Vohra (2000) identify a useful and easy-to-check domain restriction, called type diversity. They show that any incentive-compatible social choice function is virtually Bayesian implementable as long as the environments satisfy this condition. Type diversity requires that different types of an agent have different interim preferences over pure alternatives. In private-values models, it reduces to the familiar condition of value-distinguished types [Palfrey and Srivastava (1989b)].We mrn next to the question of implementation using sequential rationality refinements, where results parallel (to an extent) the results for subgame perfect implementation.
3.3.5. Implementation via sequential equilibrium There are some papers that partially characterize the set of implementable social choice functions for incomplete information environments using the equilibrium refinement of sequential equilibrium. The main idea behind these characterizations is the same as the ideas behind the results for subgame perfect equilibrium implementation under conditions of complete information. Instead of requiring a test pair involving the social choice
Ch. 61: lmplementation Theory
2313
function, x, as is required in Bayesian monotonicity, all that is needed is some (interim) preference reversal between some pair of allocation rules, plus an appropriate sequence of allocation rules that indirectly connect x with the test pair of allocation rules. The details of the conditions analogous to indirect monotouicity for incomplete information are messy to state, because of quantifiers and qualifiers that relate to the posterior beliefs an agent could have at different stages of an extensive form garne in which different players are adopting different deceptions. However, the intuition behind the condition is similar to the intuition behind Condition • in Abreu and Sen (1990). As with the necessary and sufficient results for Bayesian implementation, results are easiest to state and prove for the special case of economic environments, where No Veto Power problems are assumed away and where there are at least three agents. Bergin and Sen (1998) have some results for this case. They identify a condition which is sufficient for implementation by sequential equilibrium in a two-stage garne. That paper also makes the point that with incomplete information there exist social choice functions that are implemeutable sequentially, but are not implementable via undominated Bayesian equilibrium (or via iterated dominance), and are not even virtually implementable. This contrasts with the complete information case, where any social choice function in economic environments that is implementable via subgame perfect Nash equilibrium is also implementable via undominated Nash equilibrium. They are able to obtain these very strong results by showing that the "consistent beliefs" condition of sequential equilibrium can be exploited to place restrictions on equilibrium play in the second stage of the mechanism. Baliga (1999) also looks at implementation via sequential equilibrium, limited to finite stage extensive games. His paper makes additional restrictions of private values and independent types, which lead to a significant simplification of the analysis. A more general approach is taken in Brusco (1995) who does not limit himself to stage garnes not to economic environments. He looks at implementation via perfect Bayesian equilibrium and obtains the incomplete information equivalent to indirect monotonicity which he calls "Coudition fl+". This condition is then combined with No Veto Power in a manner similar to Jackson's (1991) monotonicity-no-veto condition to produce sequential monotonicity-no-veto. His main theorem 5° is that any incentive-compatible social choice function satisfying SMNV is implementable in perfect Bayesian equilibrium. He also identifies a weaker condition than fl+ (called Condition fi), which he proves is necessary for implementation in perfect Bayesian equilibrium. However, Brusco's (1995) results are weaker than Bergin and Sen (1998) because his conditions on the requisite sequence of test allocations include a universal quantitier on beliefs that makes it rauch more difficult to guarantee existence of the sequence. Bergin and Sen show that the very tight condition of belief consistency can replace the universal quantifier. Loosely speaking, Brusco's results exploit only the sequential
50 The main theorem is stated more generally. In particular he allows for social choice correspondences, whichmeansthat the additionalrestriction of closureunderthe commonknowledgeconcatenationis required.
2314
T.R. Palfrey
rationality part of sequential equilibrium, while Bergin and Sen exploit both sequential rationality and belief consistency. This seemingly minor distinction actually rnakes quite a difference in proving what can be implemented. Duggan (1995) focuses on sequentially rational implementation 51 in quasi-linear environments where the outcomes are lotteries over a finite set of public projects (and transfers). He shows that any incentive-compatible social choice function is implementable in private-values environments with diffuse priors over a finite type space if there are three or more agents. He also shows that these results can be extended, with some modifications, in a number of directions: two agents; the domain of exchange economies; infinite type spaces; bounded transfers; nondiffuse priors; and social choice correspondences. He also shows how a "belief revelation mechanism" can be used if the planner does not know the agents' prior beliefs, as long as these prior beliefs are common knowledge among the agents.
4. Open issues Open problems in implementation theory abound. Several issues have been explored at only a superficial level, and others have not been studied at all. Some of these have been mentioned in passing in the previous sections. There are also numerous untied loose ends having to do with completing full characterizations of implementability under the solution concepts discussed above.
4.1. Implementation using perfect information extensive forms and voting trees Among these uncompleted problems is implementation via backward induction and the closely related problem of implementing using voting trees. If this class of implementation problems has a shortcoming, it is that extensions to the more challenging problem of implementation in incomplete information environments are limited. The structure of the arguments for backward induction implementation fails to extend nicely to incomplete information environments, as we know from the literature on sophisticated voting with incomplete information [e.g., Ordeshook and Palfrey (1988)].
4.2. Renegotiation and information leakage Many of the above constructions have the feature that undesirable (e.g., Pareto inefficient, grossly inequitable, or individually irrational) allocations are used in the mechanism to break unwanted equilibria. The simplest examples arise when there exists a universally bad outcome that is reverted to in the event of disagreement. This is not necessarily a problem in some settings, where the planner's objective function may conflict 51 Duggan (1995) defines sequentially rational implementation as implementation simultaneously in Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium and Sequential Equilibrium.
Ch. 61:
Implementation Theory
2315
with Pareto optimality from the point of view of the agents (as in many principal-agent problems). However, in some settings, most obviously exchange environments, one usually thinks of the mechanism as being something that the players themselves construct in order to achieve efficient allocations. In this case, one would expect agents to renegotiate outcomes that are commonly known among themselves to be Pareto dominated. 52 Maskin and Moore (1999) examine the implications of requiring that the outcomes always be Pareto optimal. This approach has the virtue of avoiding mixed strategy equilibria and also avoiding implausibly bad outcomes oft the equilibrium path. It has the defect of implicitly permitting the outcome function of the mechanism to depend on the preference profile, which makes the specification of renegotiation somewhat arbitrary. Ideally, one would wish to specify a bargaining game that would arise in the event that an outcome is reached which is inefficient. 53 But then the bargaining game itself should be considered part of the mechanism, which leads to an infinite regress problem. More generally, the planner may be viewed directly as a player, who has statecontingent preferences over outcomes, just as the other players do. The planner has prior beliefs over the states or preference profiles (even if the players themselves have complete information). Given these priors, the planner has induced preferences over the allocations. This presents a commitment problem for the planner, since the outcome function must adhere to these preferences. This places restrictions both on the mechanism that can be used and also on the social choice functions that can be implemented. Several papers have been written recently on this subject, which vary in the assumptions they make about the extent to which the planner can commit to a mechanism, the extent to which the planner may update his priors after observing the reported messages, and the extent to which the planner participates direcfly in the mechanism. The first paper on this subject is by Chakravorti, Corchon, and Wilkie (1994) and assumes that the social choice function must be consistent with some prior the planner might have over the states, which implies that the outcome function is restricted to the range of the social choice function. The planner is not an active participant and does not update beliefs based on the messages of the players, nor does he choose an outcome that is optimal given his beliefs. Baliga, Corchon, and Sjöström (1997) obtain results with an actively participating planner, 54 who acts optimally, given the messages of the players and cannot commit ex ante to an outcome function. Thus, the mechanism consists of a message space for the players and a planner's strategy of how to assign messages to outcomes. This strategy replaces the familiar outcome function, but is required to be sequentially rational. Thus, the mechanism is really a two-stage (signalling) garne, and an equilibrium of the mechanism must satisfy the conditions of Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium. Baliga and Sjöström (1999) obtain further results on interactive implementation with an
52 One doesn't have to look very hard to find counterexamples to this in the real world. Institutional structures (such as courts) are widely used to enforce ex post inefficient allocations in order to provide salient incentives. Some forms of criminal punishments, such as incarceration and physical abuse, fall into this category. 53 See, for example, Aghion, Dewatripont, and Rey (1994) or Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1992). 54 That is, the planner also submits messages. They call this "interactive implementation".
2316
T.R. Palfrey
uninformed planner who can commit to an outcome function, and who also participates in the message-sending stage. Another sort of renegotiation arises in incomplete information settings if the social choice function calls for allocations that are known by at least some of the players to be inefficient. In particular, for certain type realizations, some players may be able to propose to replace the mechanism with a new orte that all other types of all other players would unanimously prefer to the outcome of the social choice function. This problem of lack of durability 55 [Hollnstrom and Myerson (1983)] opens up another kind of renegotiation problem, which may involve the potential leakage of information between agents in the renegotiation process. Related issues are also addressed in Sjöström (1996), and in principal-agent settings by Maskin and Tirole (1992) and in exchange economies by Palfrey and Srivastava (1993). Also related to this kind of renegotiation is the problem of preplay communication among the agents. It is well known that preplay communication can expand the set of equilibria of a game, and a similar thing can happen in mechanism design. This can occur because information can be transmitted by preplay communication and because communication opens up possibilities for coordination that were impossible to achieve with independent actions. In nearly all of the implementation theory research, it is assumed that preplay communication is impossible (i.e., the message space of the mechanism specifies all possible communication). An exception is Palfrey and Srivastava (1991 b), which explicitly looks at designing mechanisms that are "communicationproof", in the sense that the equilibria with arbitrary kinds of preplay communication are interim-payoff-equivalent to the equilibria without preplay communication. They show that for a wide range of economic environments orte can construct communicationproof mechanisms to implement any interim-efficient, incentive-compatible allocation rule. Chakrovorti (1993) also looks at implementation with preplay communication.
4.3. Individual rationality and participation constraints A close relative to the renegotiation problem is individual rationality. Participation constraints pose similar restrictions on feasible mechanisms as do renegotiation constraints, and have similar consequences for implementation theory. In particular, individual rationality gives every player a right to veto the rinal allocation, which restricts the use of unreasonable outcomes oft the equilibrium path, which are often used in constructive proofs to knock out unwanted equilibria. Jackson and Palfrey (2001) show that individual rationality and renegotiation can be treated in a unified structure, which they call
voluntary implementation. Ma, Moore, and Turnbull (1988) investigate the effect of participation constraints on the implementability of efficient allocations in the context of an agency problem of
55 Closely related to this are the notions of ratifiability and secure allocations [Cramton and Palfrey (1995)] and stable allocations [Legros (1990)].
Ch. 61: lmplementationTheory
2317
Demski and Sappington (1984). 56 In the mechanism originally proposed by Demski and Sappington (1984), there are multiple equilibria. Ma, Moore, and Turnbull (1988) show that a more complicated mechanism eliminates the unwanted equilibria. Glover (1994) provides a simplification of their result. 4.4. Implementation in dynamic environments
Many mechanism design problems and allocation problems involve intertemporal allocations. One obvious example is bargaining when delay is costly. In that case both the split of the pie and the time of agreement are economically important components of the final allocation. Recently, Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1992) looked at the renegotiationproof problem in implementation theory by appending an infinite horizon bargaining garne with discounting to the end of each inefficient terminal node. This is an alternative approach to the same renegotiation problem that Maskin and Moore (1999) were concerned about. However, like the rest of implementation theory, their interest is in implementing static allocation rules (i.e., no delay) in environments that are (except for the final bargaining stages) static. This is true for all the other sequential game constructions in implementation theory: time stands still while the mechanism is played out. Intertemporal implementation raises additional issues. Consider, for example, a setting in which every day the same set of agents is confronted with the next in a series of connected allocation problems, and there is discounting. A preference profile is not an infinite sequence of "one shot" profiles corresponding with each time period. A social choice function is a mapping from the set of these profile sequences into allocation sequences. Renegotiation-proofness would impose a natural time consistency constraint that the social choice function would have to satisfy from time t onward, for each t. With this kind of structure one could begin to look at a broader set of economic issues related to growth, savings, intertemporal consumption, and so forth. Jackson and Palfrey (1998) follow such an approach in the context of a dynamic bargaining problem with randomly matched buyers and sellers. Many buyers and sellers are randomly matched in each period, and bargain under conditions of complete information. Those pairs who reach agreements leave the market, and the unsuccessful pairs are rematched in the following period. This continues for a finite number of periods. The matching process is taken as exogenous, and the implementation problem is to design a single bargaining mechanism to implement the efficiently dynamic allocation rule (wbich pairs of agents should trade, as a function of the time period), subject to the constraints of the matching process and individual rationality. They identify necessary and sufficient conditions for an allocation rule to be implemented and show that it is often the case that constrained efficient allocations are not implementable under any bargaining game. 56 There is a large and growing literamre on implementationtheoretic appficationsto agencyproblems.The tectmiques used there apply many of the ideas surveyedin this chapter. See, for example,Arya and Glover (1995), Arya, Glover,and Rajan (2000), Ma (1988), and Duggan (1998).
2318
T.R. Palfrey
There are some very simple intertemporal allocation problems that could be investigated as a first step. One example is the one-sector growth model of Boylan et al. (1996) which compares different political mechanisms for deciding on investments. As a second example, Bliss and Nalebuff (1984) look at an intertemporal public goods problem. There is a single indivisible public good which can be produced once and for all at any date t = 1, 2, 3 . . . . . and preferences are quasilinear with discounting. The production technology requires a unit of private good for the public good to be provided. Thus, an allocation is a time at which the public good is produced and an infinite stream of taxes for each individual, as a function of the profile of preferences for the public good. Bliss and Nalebuff (1984) look at the equilibrium of a specific mechanism, the voluntary contribution mechanism. At each point in time an individual must decide whether or not to privately pay for the public good, depending on their type. The unique equilibrium is for types that prefer the public good more strongly to pay earlier. Thus the public good is always produced by having the individual with the strongest preference for the public good pay for it, and the time of delay before production depends on what the highest valuation is and on the distribution of types. One could generalize this as a dynamic implementation problem, which would raise some interesting questions: What other allocation rules are implementable in this setting? Is the Bliss and Nalebuff (1984) equilibrium allocation rule interim incentive efficient? 57 4.5. Robustness of the mechanism The approach of double implementafion looks at robustness with respect to the equilibrium concept. For example, Tatamitani (1993) and Yamato (1993) both consider implementation simultaneously in Nash equilibrium and undominated Nash equilibrium. The idea is that if we are not fully confident about which equilibrium concept is more reasonable for a certain mechanism, then it is better if the mechanism implements a social choice function via two different equilibrium concepts (say, one weak and one strong concept). Other papers adopting this approach include Peleg (1996a, 1996b) and Corchon and Wilkie (1995). The constructive proofs used by Jackson, Palfrey, and Srivastava (1994) and Sjöström (1994) also have double implementation properties. A second approach to robustness is to require continuity of the implementing mechanism. This was discussed briefly earlier in the chapter. Continuity will protect against local mis-specification of behavior by the agents. Duggan and Roberts (1997) provide a formal justification along these lines. 58 On the other hand, the preponderance of discontinuous mechanisms in real applications (e.g., auctions) suggests that the issue of mechanism continuity is of little practicäl concern in many settings. Related to the continuity requirement is dynamical stability, under various assumptions of the adjustment
57 Noficethat it is not ex post efficientsince there is alwaysdelay in producing the public good. 58 Corchon and Ortufio-Ortin (1995) consider the qUestion of robustness with respect to the agents' prior befiëfs.
Ch. 61: lmplementationTheory
2319
path, See Hurwicz (1994), Cabrales (1999), Kim (1993). Chen (2002) and Chen and Tang (1998) have experimental results demonstrating that stability properties of mechanisms can have significant consequences. Theré is also the issue of robustness with respect to coalitional deviations. Implementation via strong Nash equitibrium [Maskin (1979); Dutta and Sen (1991 c); Suh (1997)] and coalition-proof equilibrium [Boylan (1998)] are one way to address these issues. The issue of collusion among the agents is related to this [Baliga and Brusco (2000); Sjöström (1999)]. These approaches look at robustness with respect to profitable deviations by coalitions~ Eliaz (1999) has looked at imptementation via mechanisms where the outcome function is robust to arbitrary deviations by subsets of players, a rauch stronger requirement. An alternative approach to robustness, which is related to virtual implementation, involves considerations of equilibrium models based on stochastic choice, 59 so that social choice functions may be approximated "on average" rather than precisely. 6° Implementätion theory (even the relaxed problem of virtual implementation) so rar has investigated special deterministic models of individual behavior. The key assumption for obtaining results is that the equifibrium model that is assumed to govern individual behavior under any mechanism is exactly correct. Many of the mechanisms have no room for error. One would generally think of such fragile mechanisms as being nonrobust, Similarly (especially in the Bayesian environmentsL the details of the environment, such as the common knowledge priors of the players and the distribution of types, are known to the planner precisely. Often mechanisms rely on this exact knowledge. It should be the case that if the model of behavior or the model of the environment is not completely accurate, the equilibrium behavior of the agents does not lead to óutcomes too far from the social choice function orte is trying to implement. This problem suggests a need to investigate mechanisms that either do not make special use of detailed information about the environment (such as the distribution of types) or else look at models that permit statistical deviation from the behavior that is predicted under the equilibrium model. In the latter case, it may be more natural to think of social choice functions as type-contingent random variables rather than as deterministic functions of the type profile. Related to the problem of robustness of the mechanisms and the possible use of statistical notions of equilibrium is bounded rationality. The usuat defense for assuming in economic models that all actors are fully rational, is that it is a good first cut on the problem and orten captures rauch of the reality of a given economic situation. In any case, most economists regard the fully rational equilibrium as an appropriate benchmark in most situations. Unfortunately, since implementation theorists and mechanism designers get to choose the economic garne in very special ways, this
59 Orte such approach is quantal respotlse equilibrium [McKelvey and Palfrey (1995, 1996, 1998)]. 60 Note the subtle difference between this and virtual implementation, In the virtual implementation approach, something is vlrtually implementable if a nearby social choice function can be exactly implemented. The playèrs do not make choiees stochastica]ly~ although the outcome functions of the mechanisms may use lottèries.
2320
T.R. Palfrey
r a t i o n a l e loses r a u c h o f its p u n c h . It m a y well b e that the g a r n e s w h e r e r a t i o n a l m o d e l s p r e d i c t p o o d y are p r e c i s e l y t h o s e g a r n e s t h a t i m p l e m e n t a t i o n t h e o r i s t s are p r o n e to designing. I n t e g e r garnes, m o d u l o garnes, " g r a n d l o t t e r y " g a r n e s like t h o s e u s e d in v i r t u a l i m p l e m e n t a t i o n proofs, a n d the e n o r m o u s m e s s a g e s p a c e s e n d e m i c to all the g e n e r a l c o n s t r u c t i o n s w o u l d s e e m for the m o s t p a r t to b e g a r n e s that w o u l d c h a l l e n g e the limits o f e v e n the m o s t b r i l l i a n t a n d e x p e r i e n c e d g a r n e player. I f s u c h c o n s t r u c t i o n s are u n a v o i d a b l e w e r e a l l y n e e d to start to l o o k b e y o n d m o d e l s o f p e r f e c t l y r a t i o n a l b e h a v i o r . E v e n i f s u c h c o n s t r u c t i o n s are a v o i d a b l e , w e h a v e to b e a s k i n g m o r e q u e s t i o n s a b o u t the m a t c h (or m i s m a t c h ) b e t w e e n e q u i l i b r i u m c o n c e p t s as p r e d i c t i v e tools a n d l i m i t a t i o n s o n the r a t i o n a l i t y o f t h e players.
References Abreu, D., and H. Matsushima (1990), "Virtual implementation in iteratively undominated strategies: Incomplete information", mimeo. Abreu, D., and H. Matsushima (1992a), "Virtual implementation in iteratively undominated strategies: Complete information", Econometrica 60:993-1008. Abreu, D., and H. Matsushima (1992b), "A response to Glazer and Rosenthal", Econometrica 60:1439-1442. Abreu, D., and H. Matsushima (1994), "Exact implementation", Journal of Economic Theory 64:1-20. Abreu, D., and A. Sen (1990), "Subgame perfect implementation: A necessary and almost sufficient condition", Journal of Economic Theory 50:285-299. Abreu, D., and A. Sen (1991), "Virtual implementation in Nash equilibrium", Econometrica 59:997-1021. Aghion, E, M. Dewatripont and E Rey (1994), "Renegotiation design with unverifiable information", Econometrica 62:257-282. Allen, B. (1997), "Implementation theory with incomplete information", in: S. Hart and A. Mas-Colell, eds., Cooperation: Garne Theoretic Approaches (Springer, Heidelberg). Arya, A., and J. Glover (1995), "A simple forecasting mechanism for moral hazard settings", Journal of Economic Theory 66:507-521. Arya, A., J. Glover and U. Rajan (2000), "Implementation in principal-agent models of adverse selection", Journal of Economic Theory 93:87-109. Baliga, S. (1999), "Implementation in economic environments with incomplete information: The use of multistage games", Garnes and Economic Behavior 27:173-183. Baliga, S., and S. Brusco (2000), "Collusion, renegotiation, and implementation", Social Choice and Welfare 17:69-83. Baliga, S., L. Corchon and T. Sjöström (1997), "The theory of implementation when the planner is a player", Journal of Economic Theory 77:15-33. Baliga, S., and T. Sjöström (1999), "Interactive implementation", Garnes and Economic Behavior 27:38-63. Banks, J. (1985), "Sophisticated voting outcomes and agenda controF', Social Choice and Welfare 1:295-306. Banks, J., C. Camerer and D. Porter (1994), "An experimental analysis of Nash refinements in signalling garnes", Garnes and Economic Behavior 6:1-31. Bergin, J., and A. Sen (1996), "Implementation in generic environments", Social Choice and Welfare 13:467448. Bergin, J., and A. Sen (1998), "Extensive form implementation in incomplete information environments", Journal of Economic Theory 80:222-256. Bemheim, B.D., and M. Whinston (1987), "Coalition-proof Nash equilibrium, II: Applications", Journal of Economic Theory 42:13-29. Bliss, C., and B. Nalebuff (1984), "Dragon-slaying and ballroom dancing: The private supply of a public good", Journal of Public Economics 25:1-12.
Ch. 61: lmplementation Theory
2321
Boylan, R. (1998), "Coalition-proof implementation", Journal of Economic Theory 82:132-143. Boylan, R., J. Ledyard and R. McKelvey (1996), "Political competition in a model of economic growth: Some theoretical results", Economic Theory 7:191-205. Brusco, S. (1995), "Perfect Bayesian implementation", Economic Theory 5:419 444. Cabrales, A. (1999), "Adaptive dynamics and the implementation problem with complete information", Journal of Economic Theory 86:159-184. Chakravorti, B. (1991), "Strategy space reductions for feasible implementation of Wakasian pefformance", Social Choice and Welfare 8:235-246. Chakravorti, B. (1993), "Sequential rationality, implementation and pre-play communication", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 22:265-294. Chakravorti, B., L. Corchon and S. Wilkie (1994), "Credible implementation", mimeo. Chander, E, and L. Wilde (1998) "A general characterization of optimal income taxation and enforcement", Review of Economic Studies 65:165-183. Chen, Y. (2002), "Dynamic stability of Nash-efficient public goods mechanisms: Reconciling theory and experiments", Garnes and Economic Behavior, forthcoming. Chen, Y., and F.-E Tang (1998), "Learning and incentive-compatible mechanisms for public goods provision: An experimental study", Journal of Political Economy 106:633-662. Corchon, L., and I. Ortufio-Ortin (1995), "Robust implementation under alternative information structures", Economic Design 1:157-172. Corchon, L., and S. Wilkie (1995), "Double implementation of the ratio correspondence by a mm'ket mechanism", Economic Design 2:325-337. Cramton, R, and T. Palfrey (1995), "Ratifiable mechanisms: Learning from disagreement", Garnes and Economic Behavior 10:255-283. Crawford, V. (1977), "A garne of fair division", Review of Economic Smdies 44:235-247. Crawford, V. (1979), "A procedure for generating Pareto-efficient egalitarian equivalent allocations", Econometrica 47:49-60. Danilov, V. (1992), "Implementation via Nash equilibrium", Econometrica 60:43-56. Dasgupta, P., P. Hammond and E. Maskin (1979), "The implementation of social choice mles: Some general results on incentive compatibility", Review of Economic Studies 46:185-216. Demange, G. (1984), "Implementing efficient egalitarian equivalent allocations', Econometrica 52:11671177. Demski, J., and D. Sappington (1984), "Optimal incentive contracts with multiple agents", Joumal of Economic Theory 33:152-171. Duggan, J. (1993), "Bayesian implementation with infinite types", mimeo. Duggan, J. (1994a), "Virmal implementation in Bayesian equilibrium with infinite sets of types", mirneo (California Institute of Technology, CA). Duggan, J. (1994b), "Bayesian implementation", Ph.D. dissertation (Califomia Institute of Technology, CA). Duggan, J. (1995), "Sequentially rational implementation with incomplete information", mimeo (Queens University). Duggan, J. (1997), "Virtual Bayesian implementation", Econometrica 65:1175-1199. Duggan, J. (1998), "An extensive form solution to the adverse selection problem in principal/multi-agent environments", Review of Economic Design 3:167-191. Duggan, J., and J. Roberts (1997), "Robust implementation", Working paper (University of Rochester, Rochester). Dutta, B., and A. Sen (1991a), "A necessary and sufficient condition for two-person Nash implementation", Review of Economic Studies 58:121-128. Dutta, B., and A. Sen (1991b), "Further results on Bayesian implementation", mimeo. Dutta, B., and A. Sen (1991c), "Implementation under strong equilibrium: A complete characterization", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 20:49-67. Dutta, B., and A. Sen (1993), "Implementing geueralized Condorcet social choice functions via backward induction", Social Choice and Welfare 10:149-160.
2322
T.R. Palfrey
Dutta, B., and A. Sen (1994a), "Two-person Bayesian implementation", Economic Design 1:41-54. Dutta, B., and A. Sen (1994b), "Bayesian implementation: The necessity of infinite mechanisms", Jottmal of Economic Theory 64:130-141. Dutta, B., A. Sen and R. Vohra (1994), "Nash implementation through elementary mechanisms in exchange economies", Economic Design 1:173-203. Eliaz, K. (1999), "Fault tolerant implementation", Working paper (Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv). Farquharson, R. (1957/1969), Theory of Voting (Yale University Press, New Haven). Gibbard, A. (1973), "Manipulation of voting schemes", Econometrica 41:587-601. Glazer, J., and C.-T. Ma (1989), "Efficieut allocation of a 'pilze' - - King Solomon's dilemma", Garnes and Economic Behavior 1:222-233. Glazer, J., and M. Perry (1996), "Virtual implementation by backwards induction", Garnes and Economic Behavior 15:27-32. Glazer, J., and R. Rosenthal (1992), "A note on the Abreu-Matsushima mechanism", Econometrica 60:14351438. Glazer, J., and A. Rubinstein (1996), "An extensive garne as a guide for solving a normal garne", Journal of Economic Theory 70:32-42. Glazer, J., and A. Rubinstein (1998), "Motives and implementation: On the design of mechanisms to elicit opinions", Journal of Economic Theory 79:157-173. Glover, J. (1994), "A simpler mechanism that stops agents from cheating", Journal of Economic Theory 62:221-229. Groves, T. (1979), "Efficient collective choice with compensation", in: J.-J. Laffont, ed., Aggregation and Revelation of Preferertces (North-Holland, Amsterdam) 37-59. Harris, M., and R. Townsend (1981), "Resource allocation with asymmetric information", Econometrica 49:33-64. Harsanyi, J. (1967, 1968), "Garnes with incomplete information played by Bayesian players", Management Science 14:159-182, 320-334, 486-502. Hererro, M., and S. Srivastava (1992), "Implementation via backward induction", Journal of Economic Theory 56:70-88. Holmstrom, B., and R. Myerson (1983), "Efficient and durable decision rules with incomplete information", Econometrica 51:1799-1819. Hong, L. (1996), "Bayesian implementation in exchange economies with state dependent feasible sets and private information", Social Choice and Welfare 13:433-444. Hong, L. (1998), "Feasible Bayesian implementation with state dependent feasible sets", Journal of Economic Theory 80:201-221. Hong, L., and S. Page (1994), "Reducing informational costs in endowment mechanisms", Economic Design 1:103-117. Hurwicz, L. (1960), "Optimality and information efficiency in resource allocation processes", in: K. Arrow, S. Karlin mad P. Suppes, eds., Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences (Stanford University Press, Stanford) 27-46. Hurwicz, L. (1972), "On informationally decentralized systems", in: C.B. McGuire and R. Radner, eds., Decision and Organization (North-Holland, Amsterdam). Hurwicz, L. (1973), "The design of mechanisms for resource allocation", American Economic Review 61:130. Hurwicz, L. (1977), "Optimality and informational efficiency in resource allocation problems", in: K. Arrow, S. Karlin and P. Suppes, eds., Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences (Stanford University Press, Stanford) 27-48. Hurwicz, L. (1986), "Incentive aspects of decentralization", in: K. An'ow and M. Intriligator, eds., Handbook of Mathematieal Eeonomies, Vol. III (North-Holland, Amsterdarn) 1441-1482. Hurwiez, L. (1994), "Economic design, adjustmeut processes, mechanisms, and institutions', Economic Design 1:1-14.
Ch. 61: Implementation Theory
2323
Hurwicz, L., E. Maskin and A. Postlewaite (1995), "Feasible Nash implementation of social choice correspondences when the designer does not know endowments or production sets", in: J. Ledyard, ed., The Economics of Information Decentralization: Complexity, Efficiency, and Stability (Kluwer, Amsterdam). Jackson, M. (1991), "Bayesian implementation", Econometrica 59:461-477. Jackson, M. (1992), "Implementation in undominated strategies: A look at bounded mechanisms", Review of Economic Studies 59:757-775. Jackson, M. (2002), "A crash course in implementation theory", in: W. Thomson, ed., The Axiomatic Method: Principles and Applications to Garne Theory and Resource Allocation, forthcoming. Jackson, M., and H. Moulin (1990), "Implementing a public project and distributing its cost", Joumal of Economic Theory 57:124-140. Jackson, M., and T. Palfrey (1998), "Efficiency and voluntary implementation in markets with repeated pairwise bargaining", Econometrica 66:1353-1388. Jackson, M., and T. Palfrey (2001), "Voluntary implementation", Joumal of Economic Theory 98:1-25. Jackson, M., T. Palfrey and S. Srivastava (1994), "Undominated Nash implementation in bounded mechanisms', Garnes and Economic Behavior 6:474-501, Kalal, E., and J. Ledyard (1998), "Repeated implementation", Joumal of Economic Theory 83:308-317. Kim, T. (1993), "A stable Nash mechanism implementing Lindahl allocations for quasi-linear environments", Joumal of Mathematical Economics 22:359-371. Legros, E (1990), "Strongly durable allocations", CAE Working Paper No. 90-05 (Comell University). Ma, C. (1988), "Unique implementation of incentive contracts with many agents", Review of Economic Smdies 55:555-572. Ma, C., J. Moore and S. Tumbull (1988), "Stopping agents from cheating", Journal of Economic Theory 46:355-372. Mas-Colell, A., and X. Vives (1993), "Implementation in economies with a continuum of agents", Review of Economic Studies 10:613-629. Maskin, E. (1999), "Nash implementation and welfare optimality", Review of Economic S tudies 66:23-38. Maskin, E. (1979), "Implementation and strong Nash equilibrium", in: J.-J. Laffont, ed., Aggregation and Revelation of Preferences (North-Holland, Amsterdam). Maskän, E. (1985) "The theory of implementation in Nash equilibrium", in: L. Hurwicz, D. Schmeidler and H. Sonnenschein, eds., Social Organization: Essays in Memory of Elisha Pazner (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Maskin, E., and J. Moore (1999), "Implementation with renegotiation", Review of Economic Studies 66:3956. Maskin, E., and J. Tirole (1992), "The principal-agent relationship with an informed principal, II: Common values", Econometrica 60:1-42. Matsushima, H. (1988), "A new approach to the implementation problem", Journal of Economic Theory 45:128-144. Matsushima, H. (1993), "Bayesian monotonicity with side payments", Journal of Economic Theory 59:107121. McKelvey, R. (1989), "Garne forms for Nash implementation of general social choice correspondences", Social Choice and Welfare 6:139-156. McKelvey, R., and R. Niemi (1978), "A multistage garne representation of sophisticated voting for binary procedttres", Joumal of Economic Theory 81 : 1-22. McKelvey, R., and T. Palfrey (1995), "Quantal response equilibria for normal form garnes", Garnes and Economic Behavior 10:6-38. McKelvey, R., and T. Palfrey (1996), "A statistical theory of equilibrium in games", Japanese Economic Review 47:186~09. McKelvey, R., and T. Palfrey (1998), "Quantal response equilibria for extensive form garnes", Experimental Economics 1:9-41. Miller, N. (1977), "Graph-theoretic approaches to the theory of voting", American Journal of Political Science 21:769-803.
2324
T.R. Palfrey
Mookherjee, D., and S. Reichelstein (1990), "Implementation via augmented revelation mechanisms", Review of Economie Studies 57:453-475. Moore, J. (1992), "Implernentation, contracts, and renegotiation in environments with complete information", in: J.-J. Laffont, ed., Advances in Economic Theory, Vol. 1 (Cambfidge University Press, Cambridge). Moore, J., and R. Repullo (1988), "Subgame perfect implementation", Economelrica 46:1191-220. Moore, J., and R. Repullo (1990), "Nash implementation: A full characterization", Econometrica 58:10831099. Moulin, H. (1979), "Dominance-solvable voting schemes", Econometrica 47:1337-1351. Moulin, H. (1984), "Implementing the Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solution", Joumal of Economic Theory 33:32-45. Moulin, H. (1986) "Choosing from a toumament", Social Choice and Welfare 3:271-291. Moulin, H. (1994), "Social choice", in: R.J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds., Handbook of Garne Theory, Vol. 2 (North-Holland, Amsterdam) Chapter 31,1091-1125. Mount, K., and S. Reiter (1974), "The informational size of message spaces", Journal of Economic Theory 8:161-192. Myerson, R. (1979), "Incentive compatibility and the bargaining problem", Econometrica 47:61-74. Myerson, R. (1985), "Bayesian equilibrium and incentive compatibility: An introduction", in: L. Hurwicz, D. Schmeidler and H. Sonnenschein, eds., Social Goals and Organization: Essays in Memory of Elisha Pazner (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) 229-259. Ordeshook, E, and T. Palfrey (1988), "Agendas, strategic voting, and signaling with incomplete information", American Journal of Political Science 32:441-466. Palfrey, T. (1992), "Implementation in Bayesian equilibrium: The multiple equilibrium problem", in: J.-J. Laffont, ed., Advances in Economic Theory, Vol. 1 (Cambridge University Press, Cambfidge). Palfrey, T., and S. Srivastava (1986), "Private information in large economies", Journal of Economic Theory 39:34-58. Palfrey, T., and S. Srivastava (1987), "On Bayesian implementable allocations", Review of Economic Smdies 54:193-208. Palfrey, T., and S. Srivastava (1989a), "hnplementation with incomplete information in exchange economies", Econometrica 57:115-134. Palfrey, T., and S. Srivastava (1989b), "Mechanism design with incomplete information: A solution to the implementation problem", Joumal of Political Economy 97:668-691. Palfrey, T., and S. Srivastava (1991a), "Nash implementation using undominated strategies", Econometrica 59:479-501. Palfrey, T., and S. Srivastava (1991b), "Efficient trading mechanisms with preplay communication", Jottmal of Economic Theory 55:17-40. Palfrey, T., and S. Srivastava (1993), Bayesian Implementation (Haxwood Academic Publishers, Reading). Peleg, B. (1996a), "A continuous double implementation of the constrained Walrasian equilibrium", Economic Design 2:89-97. Peleg, B. (1996b), "Double implementation of the Lindahl equilibrium by a continuous mechanism", Economic Design 2:311-324. Postlewaite, A. (1985), "Implementation via Nash equilibfia in economic environments', in: L. Hurwicz, D. Schmeidler and H. Sonnenschein, eds., Social Goals and Organization: Essays in Memory of Elisha Pazner (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) 205-228. Postlewaite, A., and D. Schmeidler (1986), "Implementation in differential information economies", Journal of Economic Theory 39:14-33. Postlewaite, A., and D. Wettstein (1989), "Feasible and continuous implementation", Review of Economic Studies 56:603~11. Reichelstein, S. (1984), "Incentive compatibility and informational requirements", Journal of Economic Theory 34:32-51. Reichelstein, S., and S. Reiter (1988), "Garne forms with minimal strategy spaces", Econometrica 56:661692.
Ch. 61: Implementation Theory
2325
Repullo, R. (1987), "A simple proof of Maskin's theorem on Nash implementation", Social Choice and Welfare 4:39-41. Rubinstein, A., and A. Wolinsky (1992), "Renegotiation-proof implementation and time preferences", American Economic Review 82:600-614. Saijo, T. (1988), "Strategy space reductions in Maskin's theorem: Sufficient conditions for Nash implementation", Econometrica 56:693-700. Saljo, T., Y. Tatamitani and T. Yamato (1996), "Toward natural implementation", International Economic Review 37:949-980. Satterthwaite, M. (1975), "Strategy-proofness and Arrow's conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedure and sociai welfare functions", Journal of Economic Theory 10:187-217. Sefton, M., and A. Yavas (1996), "Abreu-Matsushima mechanisms: Experimental evidence", Garnes and Economic Behavior 16:280-302. Sen, A. (1987), "Two essays on the theory of implementation", Ph.D. dissertation (Pfinceton University). Serrano, R., and R. Vohra (1999), "On the impossibility of implementation under incomplete information", Working Paper #99-10 (Brown University, Department of Economics, Providence) (forthcoming in Econometrica). Serrano, R., and R. Vohra (2000), "Type diversity and virtual Bayesian implementation", Working Paper #00-16 (Brown University, Department of Economics, Providence). Sjöström, T. (1991), "On the necessary and sufficient conditions for Nash implementation", Social Choice and Welfare 8:333-340. Sjöström, T. (1993), "Implementation in perfect equilibria", Social Choice and Welfare 10:97-106. Sjöström, T. (1994), "Implementation in undominated Nash equilibrium without integer garnes", Garnes and Economic Behavior 6:502-511. Sjöström, T. (1995), "Implementation by demand mechanisms", Economic Design 1:343-354. Sjöström, T. (1996), "Credibility and renegotiation of outcome functions in implementation", Japanese Economic Review 47:157-169. Sjöström, T. (1999), "Undominated Nash implementation with collusion and renegotiation", Garnes and Economic Behavior 26:337-352. Suh, S.-C. (1997), "An algorithm checking strong Nash implementability", Journal of Mathematical Economics 25:109-122. Tatamitani, Y. (1993), "Double implementation in Nash and undominated Nash equilibrium in social choice environments", Economic Theory 3:109-117. Thomson, W. (1979), "Maximin strategies and elicitation of preferences", in: J.-J. Laffont, ed., Aggregation and Revelation of Preferences (North-Holland, Amsterdam) 245-268. Tian, G. (1989), "Implementation of the Lindahl correspondence by a single-valued, feasible, and continuous mechanism", Review of Economic Studies 56:613-621. Tian, G. (1990), "Completely feasible continuous implementation of the Lindahl correspondence with a me ssage space of minimal dimension", Joumal of Economic Theory 51:443-452. Tian, G. (1994), "Bayesian implementation in exchange economies with state dependent preferences and feasible sets", Social Choice and Welfare 16:99-120. Townsend, R. (1979), "Optimal contracts and competitive markets with costly stare verification", Journal of Economic Theory 21:265-293. Trick, M., and S. Srivastava (1996), "Sophisticated voting mles: The two tournaments case", Social Choice and Welfare 13:275-289. Varian, H. (1994), "A solution to the problem of externalities and public goods when agents are wellinformed", American Economic Review 84:1278-1293. Wettstein, D. (1990), "Continuous implementation of constrained rational expectations equilibria", Journal of Economic Theory 52:208-222. Wettstein, D. (1992), "Continuous implementation in economies with incomplete information", Garnes and Economic Behavior 4:463-483. Williams, S. (1984), "Sufficient conditions for Nash implementation", mimeo (University of Minnesota).
2326
T.R. Palfrey
Williams, S. (1986), "Realization and Nash implementation: Two aspects of mechanism design", Econometrica 54:139-151. Yamato, T. (1992), "On Nash implementation of social choice correspondences", Garnes and Economic Behavior 4:484-492. Yamato, T. (1993), "Double implementation in Nash and undominated Nash equilibria", Journal of Economic Theory 59:311-323.
Chapter 62
GAME THEORY AND EXPERIMENTAL GAMING MARTIN SHUBIK* Cowles Foundation, Yale Universiß; New Haven, CT, USA
Contents 1. Scope 2. Garne theory and gaming 2.1. The testable elementsof garnetheory 2.2. Experimentationand representationof the game 3. Abstract matrix garnes 3.1. Matrixgarnes 3.2. Gamesin coalitionalform 3.3. Other games 4. Experimental economics 5. Experimentation and operational advice 6. Experimental social psychology, political science and law 6.1. Socialpsychology 6.2. Politicalscience 6.3. Law 7. Game theory and military gaming 8. Where to with experimental gaming? References
*I would like to thank the Pew Charitable Trustfor its generoussupport, Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 3, Edited by R.Z Aumann and S. Hart © 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved
2329 2330 2331 2332 2333 2333 2336 2338 2339 2344 2344 2344 2344 2345 2345 2346 2348
2328
M. Shubik
Abstract
This is a survey and discussion of work covering both formal game theory and experimental gaming prior to 1991. It is a useful preliminary introduction to the considerable change and emphasis which has taken place since that time where dynamics, learning, and local optimization have challenged the concept of noncooperative equilibria.
Keywords experimental gaming, game theory, context, minimax, and coalitional form
JEL classification: C71, C72, C73, C90
Ch. 62:
GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
2329
1. Scope This article deals with experimental garnes as they pertain to garne theory. As such there is a natural distinction between experimentation with abstract games devoted to testing a specific hypothesis in garne theory and garnes with a scenario from a discipline such as economics or political science where the garne is presented in the context of some particular activity, even though the same hypothesis might be tested. 1 John Kennedy, professor of psychology at Princeton and one of the earliest experimenters with garnes, suggested 2 that if you could tell hirn the results you wanted and give hirn control of the briefing he could get you the results. Context appears to be critical in the study of behavior in garnes. R. Simon, in his Ph.D. thesis (1967), controlled for context. He used the same two-person zero-sum game with three different scenarios. One was abstract, one described the garne in a business context and the other in a military context. The players were selected from majors in business and in military science. As the garne was a relatively simple two-person zero-sum game a reasonably strong case could be made out for the maxmin solution concept. The performance of all students was best in the abstract scenario. Some of the military science students complained about the simplicity of the military scenario and the business students complained about the simplicity of the business scenario. Many experiments in garne theory with abstract garnes are to "see what happens" and then possibly to look for consistency of the outcomes with various solution concepts. In teaching the basic concepts of garne theory, for several years I have used several simple garnes. In the first lecture when most of the students have had no exposure to game theory I present them with three matrices, the Prisoner's Dilemma, Chicken and the Battle of the Sexes (see Figures 1a, b and c). The students are asked if they have had any experience with these games. If not, they are asked to associate the name with the garne. Table 1 shows the data for 1988. There appears to be no significant ability to match the words with the matrices. 3 There are several thousand articles on experimental matrix garnes and several hundred on experimental economics alone, most o f which can be interpreted as pertaining to garne theory as well as to economics. Many of the business games are multipurpose and contain a component which involves garne theory. War gaming, especially at the tactical level and to some extent at the strategic level, has been influenced by garne theory [see Brewer and Shubik (1979)]. No attempt is made here to provide an exhaustive review of the vast and differentiated body of literature pertaining to blends of operational, experimental and didactic gaming. Instead a selection is made concentrating on
1 For example, one might hypothesize that the percentage of points selected in an abstract garne which lie in the core will be greater than the points selected in an experiment repeated with the only difference being a scenario supplied to the garne. 2 Personalcommunication, 1957. 3 The rows and colnmns do not all add to the same number becanse of some omissions among 30 students.
2330
M. Shubik
A
B
C
1
2
1
2
1
2
5,5
-9,10
-10,-10
5,-5
2,1
0,0
10,-9
0,0
-5,5
0,0
0,0
1,2
Figure 1. Table 1 Guessed name
Chicken Battle of the Sexes Prisoner's Dilemma
Actual garne Chicken
Battle of the Sexes
7 9 10
11 12 7
Prisoner's Dilemma 8 8 9
the modeling problems, formal structures and selection of solution concepts in garne theory. Roth (1986), in a provocative discussion of laboratory experimentation in economics, has suggested three kinds of activities for those engaged in economic experimental garning. They are "speaking to theorists", "searching for facts" and "whispering in the ears of princes". The third of these activities, from the viewpoint of society, is possibly the most immediately useful. In the United States the princes tend to be corporate executives, politicians and generals or admirals. However, the topic of operational gaming merits a separate treatment, and is not treated here.
2. Game theory and gaming Before discussing experimental garnes which might lead to the confirmation or rejection of theory, or to the discovery of "facts" or regularities in human behavior, it is desirable to consider those aspects of garne theory which might benefit from experimental garning. Perhaps the most important item to keep in mind is the fundamental distinction between the garne theory and the approach of social psychology to the same problems. Underlying a considerable amount of game theory is the concept of external symmetry. Unless stated otherwise, all players in garne theory are treated as though they are intrinsically symmetric in all nonspecified attributes. They have the same perceptions, the same abilities to calculate and the same personalities. Much of garne theory is devoted to deriving normative or behavioral solution concepts to garnes played by personality-free players in context-free environments. In particular, oue of the impressive achievements
Ch. 62: GameTheory and Experimental Gaming
2331
of formal game theory has been to produce a menu of different solution concepts which suggest ingeniously reasoned sets of outcomes to nonsymmetric garnes played by externally symmetric players. In bold contrast, the approach of the social psychologists has for the most part been to take symmetric games and observe the broad differences in play which can be attributed to nonsymmetric players. Personality, passion and perception count and the social psychologist is interested to see how they count. A completely different view from either of the above underlies much of the approach of the economists interested in studying mass markets. The power of the mass market is that it turns the social science problem of competition or cooperation among the few into a nonsocial science problem. The message of the mass market is not that personality differences do not exist, but that in the impersonal mass market they do not matter. The large market has the individual player pitted against an aggregate of other players. When the large market becomes still larger, all concern for the others is attenuated and the individual can regard himself as playing against a given inanimate object known as the market. 2.1. The testable elements of game theory Before asking who has been testing what, a question which needs to be asked is what is there to be tested concerning garne theory. A brief listing is given and discussed in the subsequent sections. Context: Does context matter? Or do we believe that strategic structure in vitro will be treated the same way by rational players regardless of context? There has been much abstract experimental gaming with no scenarios supplied to the players. But there also is a growing body of experimental literature where the context is explicitly economic, political, military or other. External symmetry and limited rationality: The social psychologists are concerned with studying decision-makers as they are. A central simplification of garne theory has been to build upon the abstract simplification of rational man. Not only are the players in garne theory devoid of personality, they are endowed with unlimited rationality, unless specified otherwise. What is learned from Maschler's schoolchildren, Smith's or Roth's undergraduates or Battaglio's rats [Maschler (1978), Smith (1986), Roth (1983), Battaglio et al. (1985)] requires considerable interpretation to relate the experimental results with the game abstraction. Rules of the garne and the role of time: In much garne theory time plays little role. In the extensive form the sequencing of moves is frequently critical, but the cardinal aspects of the length of elapsed time between moves is rarely important (exceptions are in dueling and search and evasion models). In particular, one of the paradoxes in attempting to experiment with garnes in coalitional form is that the key representation the characteristic functions (and variants thereof) - implicitly assumes that the bargaining, communication, deal-making and tentative formation of coalitions is costless and timeless. Whereas in actual experiments the amount of time taken in bargaining and discussion is offen a critical limiting factor in determining the outcome. -
2332
M. Shubik
Utility and preference: Do we carry around utility functions? The utility function is an extremely handy fiction for the mathematical economist and the garne theorist applying garne theory to the study of mass markets, but in many of the experiments with matrix garnes or market garnes the payoffs have tended to be money (on a performance oi" hourly basis or both), points or grades [see Rapoport, Guyer and Gordon (1976)]. For example, Mosteller and Nogee (1951) attempted to measure the utility function of individuals with little success. In most experimentalwork little attempt is made to obtain individual measures before the experiment. The design difficulties and the costs make this type of pre-testing prohibitively difficult to perform. Depending on the specifics of the experiment it can be argued that in some experiments all orte needs to know is that more money is preferred to less; in others the existence of a linear measure of utility is important; in still others there are questions concerning interpersonal comparisons. See however Roth and Malouf (1979) for an experimental design which attempts to account for these difficulties. 4 Even with individual testing there is the possibility that the goals of the isolated individual change when placed in a multiperson context. The maximization of relative score or status [Shubik (1971b)] may dominate the seeking of absolute point score. Solution concepts: Given that we have an adequate characterization of the garne and the individuals about to play, what do we want to test for? Over the course of the years various garne theorists have proposed many solution concepts offering both normative and behavioraljustifications for the solutions. Much of the activity in experimental gaming has been devoted to considering different solution concepts. 2.2. Experimentation and representation of the garne The two fundamental representations of garnes which häve been used for experimentation have been the strategic and cooperative form. Rarely has the formal extensive form been used in experimentation. This appears to be due to several fundamental reasons. In the study of bargaining and negotiation in general we have no easy simple description of the garne in extensive form. It is difficult to describe talk as moves. There is a lack of structure and a flexibility in sequencing which weakens the analogy with garnes such as chess where the extensive form is clearly defined. In experimenting with the garne in matrix form, frequently the experimenter provides the same matrix to be played several times; but clearly this is different from giving the individual a new and considerably larger matrix representing the strategic form of a multistage garne. Shubik, Wolf and Poon (1974) experimented with a garne in matrix form played twice and a much larger matrix representing the strategic form of the two-stage garne to be played once. Strikingly different results were obtained with considerable emphasis given in the first version to the behavior of the opponent on his first trial. 4 Unfortunately,giveu the virtual duality betweeu probability and utility, they have to introduce the assumption that the subjective probabilities are the same as those presented in the experiment. Thus one difficulty may have been traded for another.
Ch. 62: GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
2333
How big a matrix can an experimental subject handle? The answer appears to be a 2 x 2 unless there is some form of special structure on the entries; thus for example Fouraker, Shubik and Siegel (1961) used a 57 x 25 matrix in the study of triopoly, but this matrix had considerable regularities (being generated from continuous payoff functions from a Cournot triopoly model).
3. Abstraet matrix games 3.1. Matrix games
The 2 x 2 matrix game has been a major source for the provision of didactic examples and experimental games for social scientists with interests in garne theory. Limiting ourselves to strict orderings there are 4! x 4! = 576 ways in which two payoff entries can be placed in each of four cells of a 2 x 2 matrix. When symmetries are accounted for there are 78 strategically different games which remain [see Rapoport, Guyer and Gordon (1976)]. If ties are considered in the payoffs then the number of strategically different garnes becomes considerably larger. Guyer and Hamburger (1968) counted the strategically different weakly ordinal garnes and Powers (1986) made some corrections and provided a taxonomy for these garnes. There are 726 strategically different garnes. O'Neill, in unpublished notes dating from 1987, has estimated that the lower bound on the number of different 2 x 2 x 2 games is (8!)3/(8 • 6) = 1,365,590,016,000. For the 3 x 3 game we have (9!)2/((3!) 2. 2) = 1,828,915,200. Thus we see that the reason why the 2 x 2 x 2 and the 3 x 3 garnes have not been studied, classified and analyzed in any generality is that the number of different cases is astronomical. Before considering the general nonconstant-sum garne, the first and most elementary question to ask concerns the playing of two-person zero- and constant-sum games. This splits into two questions. The first is how good a predictor is the saddlepoint in twoperson zero-sum games with a pure strategy saddlepoint. The second is how good a predictor is the maxmin mixed strategy of a player's behavior. Possibly the two earliest published works on the zero-sum garne were those of Morin (1960) and Lieberman (1960) who considered a 3 x 3 garne with a saddlepoint. He has 15 pairs of subjects play a 3 x 3 for 200 times each at a penny a point. He used the last 10 trials as his statistic. In these trials approximately 90% selected their optimal strategy. One may query the approach of using the first 190 trials for learning. Lieberman (1962) also considered a zero-sum 2 x 2 garne played against a stooge using a minimax mixed strategy. Rather than approach an optimal strategy the live player appeared to follow or imitate the stooge. Rapoport, Guyer and Gordon [(1976, Chapter 21)] note three ordinally different games of pure opposition. Using 4 to stand for the most desired outcome and 1 for the least desired, Garne 1 below has a saddlepoint with dominated strategies for each player, Garne 2 has a saddlepoint but only one player has a dominated strategy and Garne 3 has no saddlepoint.
2334
M. Shubik
1
2
1
2
2
4
3
4
1
3
2
1
1
2
1
2
4
2
3
1
Figure 2. Column Player
Row Player
1
2
3
J
1
0
1
1
0
2
1
0
1
0
3
1
1
0
0
J
0
0
0
1
Figure 3.
They report on one-shot experiments by Frenkel (1973) with a large population of players with reasonably good support for the saddlepoints but not for the mixed strategy. The saddlepoint for small games appears to provide a good prediction of behavior. Shubik has used a 2 x 2 zero-sum garne with a saddlepoint as a "rationality test" prior to having students play in nonzero-sum games and one can bet with safety that over 90% of the students will select their saddlepoint strategy. The mixed strategy results are by no means that clear. More recently, O'Neill (1987) has considered a repeated zero-sum garne with a mixed strategy solution. The O'Neill experiment has 25 pairs of subjects play a card-matching garne 105 times. Figure 3 shows the matrix. The ÷ is a win for Row and the - a loss. There is a unique equilibrium with both players randomizing using probabilities of 0.2, 0.2, 0.2, 0.4, each. The value of the garne is 0.4. The students were initially given $2.50 each and at each stage the winner received 5 cents from the loser. The aggregate data involving 2625 joint moves showed high consistency with the predictions of minimax theory. The proportion of wins for the row player was 40.9% rather than 40% as predicted by theory. Brown and Rosenthal (1987) have challenged O' Neill' s analy sis but his results are of note [see also O' Neill (1991)]. One might argue that minimax is a normative theory which is an extension of the concept of rational behavior and that there is little to acmally test beyond observing that naive players do not necessarily do the right thing. In saddlepoint games there is reasonable evidence that they tend to do the right thing [see, for example, Lieberman (1960)] and as the results depend only on ordinal properties of the matrices this is doubly comforting. The mixed strategies however in general require the full philosophical
2335
Ch. 62: GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
mysteries of the measurement of utility and choice under uncertainty. One of the attractive features of the O'Neill design is that there are only two payoff values and hence the utility structure is kept at its simplest. It would be of interest to see the O'Neill experiment replicated and possibly also performed with a larger matrix (say a 6 x 6) with the same structure. It should be noted, taking a cue from Miller's (1956) classical article, that unless a matrix has special structure it may not be reasonable to experiment with any size larger than 2 x 2. A 4 x 4 with general entries would require too rauch memory, cognition and calculation for nontrained subjects. One of the most comprehensive research projects devoted to studying matrix garnes has been that of Rapoport, Guyer and Gordon (1976). In their book entitled The 2 x 2 Garne, not only do they count all of the different garnes, but they develop a taxonomy for all 78 of them. They begin by observing that there are 12 ordinally symmetric garnes and 66 nonsymmetric garnes. They classify them into games of complete, partial and no opposition. Garnes of complete opposition are the ordinal variants of two-person constant-sum garnes. Garnes of no opposition are classified by them as those which have the best outcome to each in the same cell. Space limitations do not permit a full discussion of this taxonomy, yet it is my belief that the problem of constructing an adequate taxonomy for matrix games is valuable both from the viewpoint of theory and experimentation. In particular, although much stress has been laid on the noncooperative equilibrium for games in strategic form, there appears to be a host of considerations which can all be present simultaneously and contribute towards driving a solution to a predictable outcome. These may be reflected in a taxonomy. A partial list is noted here: (1) uniqueness of equilibria; (2) symmetry of the garne; (3) safety levels of equilibria; (4) existence of dominant strategies; (5) Pareto optimality; (6) interpersonal comparison and sidepayment conditions; (7) information conditions. 5 Of all of the 78 strategically different 2 x 2 garnes I suggest that the following one is structurally the most conducive to the selection of its equilibrium point solution. 6 The cell (1, 1) will be selected not merely because it is an equilibrium point but also because it is unique, Pareto-optimal, results from the selection of dominant strategies, 1
2
1
4,4
3,2
2
2,3
1,1
5 In an experiment with several 2 x 2 games played repeatedly with low information where each of the players was given only his own payoff matrix and information about the move selected by his competitorafter each of a sequence of plays, the ability to predict the outcome depended not merely on the noncooperative equilibrium hut on the coincidence of an outcomehaving several other properties [see Shubik (1962)]. 6 Wherethe conventionis that 4 is high and 1 low.
2336
M. Shubik
is symmetric and coincides with maxmin (P1 - P2). Rapoport et al. (1976) have this tied for first place with a closely related no-conflict garne, with the oft-diagonal entries reversed. This new garne does not have the coincidence of the maxmin difference solution with the equilibrium. The work of Rapoport, Guyer and Gordon (1976) to this date is the most exhaustive attempt to ring the changes on conditions of play as well as structure of the 2 x 2 game. 3.2. Garnes in coalitional forrn If one wishes to be a purist, a game in coalitional or characteristic function form cannot actually be played. It is an abstraction with playing time and all other transaction costs set at zero. Thus any attempt to experiment with garnes in characteristic function form must take into account the distinction between the representation of the game and the differences introduced by the control and the time utilized in play. With allowances made for the difficulties in linking the actual play with the characteristic function, there have been several experiments utilizing the characteristic function especially for the three-person game and to some extent for larger garnes. In particular, the invention of the bargaining set by Aumann and Maschler (1964) was motivated by Maschler's desire to explain experimental evidence [see Maschler (1963, 1978)]. The book of Kahan and Amnon Rapoport (1984) has possibly the most exhaustive discussion and report on garnes in coalitional form. They have eleven chapters on the theory development pertaining to games in coalitional form, a chapter on experimental results with three-person games, a chapter 7 on garnes for n/> 4, followed by concluding remarks which support the general thesis that the experimental results are not independent of normalization and of other aspects of context; that no normative game-theoretic solution emerges as generally verifiable (often this does not rule out their use in special context-rich domains). It is my belief that a fruitful way to utilize a game in characteristic function form for experimental purposes is to explore beliefs or norms of students and others concerning how the proceeds from cooperation in a three-person garne with sidepayments shouId be split. Any play by three individuals of a three-person game in characteristic function form is no longer represented by the form but has to be adjusted for the time and resource costs of the process of play as well as controlled for personality. In a normafive inquiry Shubik (1975a, 1978) has used three characteristic functions for many years. They were selected so that the first garne has a rather large core, the second a single-point core that is highly nonsymmetric and the third no core. For the most part the subjects were students attending lectures on game theory who gare their opinions on at least the first garne without knowledge of any formal cooperative solution. Gamel:
v(1)=v(2)=v(3)=0; v(123) = 4.
v(12)=l,v(13)=2,
v(23)=3;
7 Thesetwo chapters provide the most comprehensivesummaryof experimental results with garnes in characteristic form up until the early 1980s.These include Apex garnes, simple games, Selten's work on the equal division core and market games.
Ch. 62:
2337
Game Theory and Experimental Gaming
Table 2 Percentage in core Garne 1 1980 1981 1983 1984 1985 1988
86 86.8 87 89.5 93 92
Game 2 28.3 5 21.8 19 20 11
Percentage even split Garne 3 36 32.5 7.5 5
Garne2:
v(1)=v(2)=v(3)=0; v(123) =-4.
v(12) = 0, v(13) = 0, v(23) = 4;
Game3:
v(1)=v(2)=v(3)=0; v(123) = 4 .
v(12) = 2.5, v(13) = 3, v(23) = 3.5;
Table 2 shows the percentage of individuals selecting a point in the core for games 1 and 2. The smallest sample size was 17 and the largest was 50. The last column shows the choice of an even split in the garne without a core. There was no discernible pattern for the garne without a core except for a selection of the even split, possibly as a focal point. There was little evidence supporting the value or nucleolus. When the core is "flat" and not too nonsymmetric (garne 1), it is a good predictor. When it is orte point but highly skewed, its attractiveness is highly diminished (garne 2). Three-person garnes have been of considerable interest to social psychologists. Caplow (1956) suggested a theory of coalitions which was experimented with by Gamson (1961) and later the three-person simple majority game was used in experiments by Byron Roth (1975). He introduced a scenario involving a task performed by a scout troop with three variables: the size of the groups considered as a single player, the effort expended, and the economic value added to any coalition of players. He compared both questionnaire response and actual play. His experimental results showed an important role for equity considerations. Selten, since 1972, has been concerned with equity considerations in coalitional bargaining. His views are surnmarized in a detailed survey [Seiten (1987)]. In essence, he suggests that limited rationality must be taken into consideration and that normalization of payoffs and then equity considerations in division provide important structure to bargaining. He considers and compares both the work by Maschler (1978) on the bargaining set and his theory of equal division payoff bounds [Selten (1982)]. Selten defines "satisficing" as the player obtaining his aspiration level which in the context of a characteristic function garne is a lower bound on what a player is willing to accept in a genuine coalition. The equal division payoff bounds provide an easy way to obtain aspiration levels, especially in a zero-normalized three-person game. The specifics for the calculation of the bounds are lengthy and are not reproduced hefe. There are however
2338
M. Shubik
three points to be made. (1) They are chosen specifically to reflect limited rationality. (2) The criterion of success suggested is an "area computation", i.e., no point prediction is used as a test of success, but a fange or area is considered. (3) The examination of data generated from four sets of experiments done by others "strongly suggests that equity considerations have an important influence on the behavior of experimental subjects in zero-normalized three-person garnes". This also comes through in the work of W. Güth, R. Schmittberger and B. Schwartz (1982) who considered one-period ultimatum bargaining garnes where one side proposes the division of a sum of money M into two patts, M - x and x. The other side then has the choice of accepting or rejecting the split with both sides obtaining 0. The perfect equilibrium is unique and has the side that moves first take all. This is not what happened experimentally. The approach in these experiments is towards developing a descriptive theory. As such it appears to this writer that the structure of the garne and both psychologicat and socio-psychological (actors must be taken into account explicitly. The only way that process considerations can be avoided is by not actually playing the garne but asking individuals to state how they think they should or they would play. The characteristic function is an idealization. The coalitions are not coalitions, they are cosfless coalitionsin-being. Attempts to experiment with playing garnes in characteristic function form go against the original conception of the characteristic form. As the results of Byron Roth indicated both the questionnaire and actual play of the garne are worth utilizing and they give different results. Much is still to be learned in comparing both approaches. 3.3. Other games
One important but somewhat overlooked aspect of experimental gaming is the construction and use of simple paradoxical garnes to illustrate problems in garne theory and to find out what happens when these games are played. Three examples are given. Hausner, Nash, Shapley and Shubik (1964) in the early 1950s constructed a garne called "so long sucker" in which the winner is the survivor; in order to win it is necessary, but not sufficient, to form coalitions. At some point it will pay someone to "doublecross" his partner. However, to a garne theorist the definition of doublecross is difficult to make precise. When John McCarthy decided to get revenge for being doublecrossed by Nash, Nash pointed out that McCarthy was "being irrational" as he could have easily calculated that Nash would have to do what he did given the opportunity. The dollar auction garne [see Shubik (1971a)] is another exarnple of an extremely simple yet paradoxical garne. The highest bidder pays to win a dollar, but the secondhighest bidder taust also pay but receives nothing in return. Experiments with this garne belong primarily to the domain of social psychology and a recent book by Tegler (1980) covers the experimental work. O'Neill (1987) however has suggested a game-theoretic solution to the auction with limited resources. The third garne is a simple game attributed to Rosenthal. The subjects are confronted with a game in extensive form as indicated in the game tree in Figure 4. They are told that they are playing an unknown opponent and that they are player 2 and have been given the move. They are required to select their move and justify the choice.
2339
Ch. 62: GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
Pt
12,3
3,4
2
P2
2
P1
2,3 Figure 4.
The paradox cornes in the nature of the expectations that player 2 must form about player l ' s behavior. If player 1 were "rational" he would have ended the game: hence the move should never have come to player 2. In an informal 8 classroom exercise in 1985 17 out of 21 acting as player 2 chose to continue the game and 4 terminated giving reasons for the most part involving the stupidity or the erratic behavior of the competition.
4. Experimental economics The first adequately documented running of an experimental garne to study competition among firms was that of Chamberlain (1948). It was a report of a relatively inforrnal oligopolistic market run in a class in economic theory. This was a relatively isolated event [occurring before the publication of the Nash equilibrium (1951)] and the general idea of experimentation in the economics of competition did not spread for around another decade. Perhaps the main impetus to the idea of experimentation on econonfic competition came via the construction of the first computer-based business garne by Bellman et al. (1957). Within a few years business games were widely used both in business schools and in many corporations. Hoggatt (1959, 1969) was possibly the earliest researcher to recognize the value of the computer-based garne as an experimental tool. In the past two decades there has been considerable work by Vernon Smith primarily using a computer-based laboratory to study price formation in various market structures. Many of the results appear to offer comforting support for the virtues of a cornpetitive price system. However, it is important to consider that possibly a key feature in the functioning of an anonymous rnass market is that it is designed implicitly or explicitly to minimize both the socio-psychological and the more complex game-theoretic aspects of strategic human behavior. The crowning j o y of economic theory as a social science is its theory of markets and competition. But paradoxically markets appear to work the best
8 The meaning of "informal" here is that the students were not paid for their choice. I supplied them with the garne as shown in Figure 4 and asked them to write down what they would do, if as player 2 they were called on to move. They were asked to explain their choice.
2340
M. Shubik
when the individuals are converted into nonsocial anonymous entities and competition is attenuated, leaving a set of one-person maximization problems. 9 This observation is meant not to detract from the value of the experimental work of Smith and many others who have been concerned with showing the efficiency of markets but to contrast the experimental program of Smith, Plott and others concerned with the design of economic mechanisms with the more general problems of game theory. 10 Are economic and game-theoretic principles sufficiently basic that one might have cleaner experiments using rats and pigeons rather than humans? Hopefully, animal passions and neuroses are simpler than those of humans. Kagel et al. (1975) began to investigate consumer demand in rats. The investigations have been primarily aimed at isolated individual economic behavior in animals, including an investigation of risky choice [Battaglio et al. (1985)]. Kagel (1987) offers a justification of the use of animals, noting problems of species extrapolation and cognition. He points out that (he believes that) animals unlike humans are not selected from a background of political, economic and cultural contexts, which at least to the garne theorist concerned with external symmetry is helpful. The Kagel paper is noted (although it is concerned only with individual decisionmaking) to call attention to the relationship between individual decision-making and game-playing behavior. In few, if any, garne experiments is there extensive pre-testing of one-person decision-making under exogenous uncertainty. Yet there is an implicit assumption made that the subjects satisfy the theory for one-person behavior. Is the jump from one- to two-person behavior the same for humans, sharks, wolves and rats? Especially given the growth of interest in garne theory applications to animal behavior, it would be possible and of interest to extend experimentation with animals to two-person zero- and nonconstant-sum games. In much of the experimental work in garne theory anonymity is a key control factor. It should be reasonably straightforward to have animals (not even of the same species) in separate cages, each with two choices leading to four prizes from a 2 x 2 matrix. There is the problem as to how or if the animals are ever able to deduce that they are in a two-animal competitive situation. Furthermore, at least if the analogy with economics is to be carried further, can animals be taught the meaning and value of money, as money figures so prominently in business games, rauch of experimental economics, experimental garne theory and in the actual economy? I suspect that the answer is no. But how far can animal analogies be made seems to be a reasonable question. Another approach to the study of competition has been via the use of robots in computerized oligopoly garnes. Hoggatt (1969) in an imaginative design had a live player play two artificial players separately in the same type of garne. One artificial player
9 But even here the dynamics of social psychology appears in mass markets. Shubik (1970) managed to run a simtdated stock market with over 100 individuals using their own money to buy and sell shares in four corporations involved in a business game. Trading was at four professional broker-operated trading posts. Both a boom and a panic were encountered. l0 See the research series in experimental economicsstarting with Smith (1979).
Ch. 62: GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
2341
was designed to be cooperative and the other competitive. The live players tended to cooperate with the former and to compete with the latter. Shubik, Wolf and Eisenberg (1972), Shubik and Riese (1972), Liu (1973), and others have over the years run a series of experiments with an oligopolistic market game model with a real player versus either other real players or artificial players [Shubik, Wolf and Lockhart (1971)]. In the Systems Development Corporation experiments markets with 1, 2, 3, 5, 7, and 10 live players were run to examine the predictive value of the noncooperative equilibrium and its relationship with the competitive equilibrium. The average of each of the last few periods tended to lie between the beat-the-average and noncooperative solution. A money pilze was offered in the Shubik and Riese (1972) experiment with 10 duopoly pairs to the firm whose profit relative to its opponent was the highest. This converted a nonzero-sum garne into a zero-sum garne and the predicted outcome was reasonably good. In a seiles of experiments run with students in garne theory courses the students each first played in a monopoly garne and then played in a duopoly game against an artificial player. The monopoly game posed a problem in simple maximization. There was no significant correlation in performance (measured in terms of profit ranking) between those who performed well in monopoly and those who performed well in duopoly. Business garnes have been used for the most part in business school education and corporate training courses with little or no experimental concern. Business garne models have tended to be large, complex and ad hoc, but garnes to study oligopoly have been kept relatively simple in order to maintain expeilmental control as can be seen by the work of Sauermann and Selten (1959); Hoggatt (1959); Fouraker, Shubik and Siegel (1961); Fouraker and Siegel (1963); Friedman (1967, 1969); and Friedman and Hoggatt (1980). A difficulty with the simplificafion is that it becomes so radical that the words (such as firm production cost, advertising, etc.) bear so little resemblance to the complex phenomena they are meant to evoke that experience without considerable ability to abstract may actually hamper the players. 1i The first work in cooperative garne experimental economics was the prize-winning book of Siegel and Fouraker (1960) which contained a series of elegant simple experiments in bilateral monopoly exploring the theories of Edgeworth (1881), B owley (1928) and Zeuthen (1930). This was interdisciplinary work at its best with the senior author being a quantitatively oriented psychologist. The book begins with an explicit statement of the nature of the economic context, the forms of negotiation and the information conditions. In game-theoretic terms the Edgeworth model leads to the no-sidepayment core, the Zeuthen model calls for a Nash-Harsanyi value and the Bowley solution is the outcome of a two-stage sequential garne with perfect information concerning the news.
11 Two examples where the same abstract game can be given different scenarios are the Ph.D. thesis of R. Simon, already noted, and a student paper by Bulow where the same business garne was ran calling the same control variable advertising in one tun and product development in another.
2342
M. Shubik
In the Siegel-Fouraker experiments subjects were paid, instructed to maximize profits and anonymous to each other. Their moves were relayed through an intermediary. In their first expeilments they obtained evidence that the selection of a Pareto-optimal outcome increased with increasing information about each others' profits. The simple economic context of the Siegel-Fouraker experiments combined with care to maintain anonymity gave interesting results consistent with economic theory. In contrast the imaginative and ilch teaching games of Raiffa (1983) involving face-to-face bargaining and complex information conditions illustrate how far we are from a broadly acceptable theory of bargaining backed with experimental evidence. Roth (1983), recognizing especially the difficulties in observing bargainers' preferences, has devised several insightful experiments on bargaining. In particular, he has concentrated on twoperson bargaining where failure to agree gives the players nothing. This is a constantthreat game and the various cooperative fair division theories such as those of Nash, Shapley, Harsanyi, Maschler and Perles, Raiffa, and Zeuthen can all be considered. Both in his book and in a perceptive article Roth (1979, 1983) has stressed the problems of the game-theoretic approach to bargaining and the importance of and difficulties in linking theory and experimentation. The value and fair division theories noted are predicated on the two individuals knowing their own and each others' preferences. Abstractly, a bargaining game is defined by a convex compact set of outcomes S and a point t in that set which represents the disagreement payoff. A solution to a bargaining game (S, t) is a rule applied to (S, t) which selects a point in S. The garne theorist, by assuming external symmetry concerning the personalities and other particular features of the players and by making the solution depend just upon the payoff set and the no-agreement point, has thrown away most if not all of the social psychology. Roth's experiments have been designed to allow the expected utility of the participants to be determined. Participants bargained over the probability that they would receive a monetary pilze. If they did not agree within a specified time both received nothing. The experiment of Roth and Malouf (1979) was designed to see if the outcome of a binary lottery game 12 would depend on whether the players are explicitly informed of their opponent's pilze. They experimented with a partial and a complete information condition and found that under incomplete information there was a tendency towards equal division of the lottery tickets, whereas with complete information the tendency was towards equal expected payoffs. The experiment of Roth and Murnighan (1982) had one player with a $20 prize and the other with a $5 pilze. A 4 x 2 factorial design of information conditions and common knowledge was used: (1) neither player knows his competitor's prize; (2) and (3) one does; (4) both do. In one set of instances the state of information is common knowledge, in the other it is not common knowledge. The results suggested that the effect of information is primarily a function of whether the player with the smaller prize is informed about both. If this is common knowledge 12 If a playerobtained 40% of the lottery tickets he would have a 40% chance of winning his personal prize and a 60% chance of obtaining nothing.
2343
Ch. 62: GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming P2
.1///~
E
"'E
//J
I
B
!i \ C
Pl
Figure 5. there is less disagreement than if it is not. Roth and Schoumaker (1983) considered the proposition that if the players were Bayesian utility maximizers then the previous results could indicate that the effect of information was to change players' subjective beliefs. The efforts of Roth and colleagues complement the observations of Raiffa (1983) on the complexities faced in experimenting with bargaining situations. They clearly stress the importance of information. They avoid face-to-face complications and they bring new emphasis to the distinction that must be made between behavioral and normative approaches. Perhaps one of the key overlooked factors in the understanding of competition and bargaining is that they are almost always viewed by economists and garne theorists as resolution mechanisms for individuals who know what things are worth to themselves and others. An alternative view is that the mechanisms are devices which help to clarify and to force individuals to value items where previously they had no clear scheme of evaluation. In many of the experiments money is used for payoffs possibly because it is just about the only item which is clearly man-made and artificial that exists in the economy in such a form that it is normatively expected that most individuals will have a conscious value for it even though they have hardly worked out valuations for most other items. Schelling (1961) suggested the possible importance of "natural" focal points in garnes. Stone (1958) performed a simple experiment in which two players were required to select a vertical and a horizontal line respectively on a payoff diagram as shown in Figure 5. If the two lines intersect within or on the boundary (indicated by ABC) the players receive payoffs determined by the intersection of the lines (X provides an example). If the lines intersect outside o f A B C then both players receive nothing. Stone's results show a bimodal distribution with the two points selected being B, a "prominent point" and E, an equal-split point. In class I have tun a one-sided version of the Stone experiment six times. The results are shown in Table 3 and are bimodal. A more detailed discussion of some of the more recent work 13 on experimental gaming in economics is to be found in the survey by Roth (1988), which includes the consid13 A bibliography on earlier work together with commentarycan be found in Shubik (1975b). A highly useful source for game experiment literature is the volumesedited by Sauermann starting with Sauermann (1967-78).
2344
M, Shubik
Table 3
1980 1981 1983 1984 1985 1988
E
B
Other offers*
9 10 12 8 8 24
16 11 8 6 10 15
13 11 4 5 7 7
*These are scattered on several other points. erable work on bidding and auction mechanisms [a good example of which is provided by Radner and Schotter (1989)].
5. Experimentation and operational advice Possibly the closest that experimental economics comes to military gaming is in the testing of specific mechanisms for economic allocation and control of items involving some aspects of public goods. Plott (1987) discusses policy applications of experimental methods. This is akin to Roth's category of "whispering into the ears of princes", or at least bureaucrats. He notes agenda manipulation for a flying club [Levine and Plott (1977)], rate-filing policies for inland water transportation [Hong and Plott (1982)] and several other examples of institution design and experimentation. Alger (1986) considers the use of oligopoly garnes for policy purposes in the control of industry. Although this work is related to the concerns of the game theorist and indicates how much behavior may be guided by structure, it is more directly in the domain of economic application than aimed at answering the basic questions of game theory.
6. Experimental social psychology, political science and law 6.1. Social psychology
It must be stressed that the same experimental garne can be approached from highly different viewpoints. Although interdisciplinary work is often highly desirable, rauch of experimental gaming has been carried out with emphasis on a single discipline. In particular, the vast literature on the Prisoner's Dilemma contains many experiments strictly in social psychology where the questions investigated include how play is influenced by sex differences or differences in nationality. 6.2. Political science
We may divide much of gaming experiments in political science into two parts. One is concerned with simple matrix experiments used for the most part for analogies to situations involving threats and international bargaining. The second is devoted to experimental work on voting and committees.
Ch. 62: GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
2345
The gaming section of Conflict Resolution contains a large selection of articles heavily oriented towards 2 x 2 matrix garnes with the emphasis on the social psychology and political science interpretations. Much of the political science gaming activities are not of prime concern to the game theorist. The experiments dealing with voting and committees are more directly related to strictly game-theoretic concerns. An up-to-date survey is provided by McKelvey and Ordeshook (1987). They note two different ways of viewing much of the work. One is a test of basic propositions and the other an attempt to gain insights into poorly understood aspects of political process. In the development of game theory at the different levels of theory, application and experimentation, a recognition of the two different aspects of gaming is critical. The cooperative form is a convenient fiction. In the actual playing of games, mechanisms and institutions cannot be avoided. Frequently the act of constructing the playable garne is a means of making relevant case distinctions and clarifying ill-specified models used in theory. 6.3. Law
There is little of methodological interest to the garne theorist in experimental law and economics. A recent lengthy survey article by Hoffman and Spitzer (1985) provides an extensive bibliography on auctions, sealed bids, and experiments with the provision of public goods (a topic on which Plott and colleagues have done considerable work). The work on both auctions and public goods is of substantive interest to those interested in mechanism design. But essentially as yet there is no indication that the intersection between law, garne theory and experimentation is more than some applied industrial organization where the legal content is negligible beyond a relatively simplistic misinterpretation of the contextual setting of threats. The culmral and academic gap between game theorists and the laissez-faire school of law and economics is typified by virmally totemistic references to "The Coase Theorem". This theorem, to the best of this writer's understanding, amounts to a casual comment by Coase (1960) to the effect that two parties who can harm each other, but who can negotiate, will arrive at an efficient outcome. Hoffman and Spitzer (1982) offer some experimental tests of the Coase so-called theorem, but as there is no well-defined context-free theorem, it is somewhat difficult to know what they are testing beyond the proposition that if people can threaten each other but also can make mutually beneficial deals they may do so.
7. Garne theory and military gaming The earliest use of formal gaming appears to have been by the military. A history and discussion of war gaming has been given elsewhere [Brewer and Shubik (1979)]. The expenditures of the military on games and simulations for training and planning purposes are orders of magnitude larger than the expenditures of all of the social sciences on
2346
M. Shubik
experimental gaming. Although the garnes devoted to doctrine, i.e., the actual testing of overall planning procedures, can in some sense be regarded as research on the relevance and viability of overall strategies, at least in the open literature there is surprisingly little connection between the considerable activity in war gaming and the academic research community concerned with both game theory and gaming. War games such as the Global War Game at the U.S. Naval War College may involve up to around 800 players and staff and take many weeks spread over several years to play. The compression of garne time as compared to clock time is not far from one to one. In the course of play threats and counterthreats are made. Real fears are manifested as to whether the simulated war will go nuclear. Yet there is little if any connection between these activities and the scholarly game-theoretic literature on threats.
8. Where to with experimental gaming? Is there such a thing as context-free experimental gaming? At the most basic level the answer must be no. The act of running an experimental game involves process. Games that are run take time and require the specification of process rules. (1) In spite of the popularity of the 2 x 2 matrix garne and the profusion of cases for the 2 x 2 x 2 and 3 x 3, several basic theoretical and experimental questions remain to be properly formulated and answered. In particular with the 2 x 2 game there are many special cases, games with names which have attracted considerable attention. What is the class of special garnes for the larger examples? Are there basic new phenomena which appear with larger matrix games? What, if any, are the special garnes for the 2 x 2 x 2 and the 3 x 3? (2) Setting aside game theory, there are basic problems with the theory of choice under risk. The critique of Kahneman and Tversky (1979, 1984) and various explanations of the Allais paradox indicate that our understanding of orte-person reaction to risk is still open to new observations, theory and experimentation. It is probable that different professions and societies adopt different ways to cope with individual risk. This suggests that studies of fighter pilots, scuba divers, high rise construction workers, demolition squads, mountaineers and other vocations or avocations with high-risk characteristics is called for. The social psychologists indicate that group pressures may influence corporate risktaking [Janis (1982)]. In the economics literature it seems to have been overlooked that probably over 80% of the economic decisions made in a society are fiduciary decisions with someone acting with someone else's money or life at stake. Yet no experimentation and little theory exists to account for fiduciary risk behavior. A socialized individual has a far better perception of the value of money than the value of thousands of goods. Yet little direct consideration has been given to the important role of money as an intermediary between goods and their valuation. (3) The experimental evidence is overwhelming that one-point predictions are rarely if ever confirmed in few-player games. Thus it appears that solutions such as the value
Ch. 62:
Garne Theory and Experimental Gaming
2347
are best considered as normative or as benchmarks for the behavior of abstract players. In mass markets or voting much (but not all) of the social psychology may be wiped out: hence chances for prediction are improved. For few-person garnes more explicitly interdisciplinary work is called for to consider how much of the observations are being explained by game theory, personal or social factors. (4) Game-theoretic solutions proposed as normative procedures can be viewed as what we should teach the public, or as reflecting what we believe public norms to be. Solutions proposed as reflecting actual behavior (such as the noncooperative theory) require a different treatment and concern for experimental validation. The statement that individuals should select the Pareto-optimal noncooperative equilibrium if there is one is representative of a blend of behavioral and normative considerations. There is a need to clarify the relationship between behavioral and normative assumptions. (5) Little attention appears to have been paid the effects of time. Roth, Murnighan and Schoumaker (1988) have evidence concerning the importance of the end effect in bargaining. But both at the level of theory and experimentation clock time seems to have been of little concern, even though in military operational gaming questions concerning how time compression or expansion influences the garne are of considerable concern. (6) The explicit recognition that increasing numbers of players change the nature of communication and information 14 requires more exploration of numbers between 3 and say 20. How many is many has game-theoretical, psychological and socio-psychological dimensions. One can study how game-theoretic solutions change with numbers, but at the same time psychological and socio-psychological possibilities change. (7) Game-theoretic investigations have cast light on phenomena such as bluff, threat and false revelation of preference. All of these items at one time might have been regarded as being almost completely in the domain of psychology or social psychology, yet they were susceptible to game-theoretic analysis. In human conflict and cooperation words such as faith, hope, charity, envy, rage, revenge, hate, fear, trust, honor and rectitude all appear to play a role. As yet they do not appear to have been susceptible to gametheoretic analysis and perhaps they may remain so if we maintain the usual model of rational man. It might be different if a viable theory can be devised to consider contextrational m a n who, although he may calculate and try to optimize, is limited in terms of capacity constraints on perception, memory, calculation and communication. It is possible that the instincts and emotions are devices that enable our capacity-constrained rational man to produce an aggregated cognitive map of the context of bis environment simple enough that he can act reasonably well with his limited facilities. Furthermore, actions based on emotion such as rage may be powerful aggregated signals. The development of garne theory represented an enormous step forward in the realization of the potential for rational calculation. Yet paradoxically it showed how enormous the size of calculation could become. Computation, information and communication
14 Aroundthirtyyearsago at MITthere was considerableinterest in the structureof communicationnetworks. None of this material seems to havemade any mark on game-theoreticthought.
2348
M. Shubik
c a p a c i t y c o n s i d e r a t i o n s s u g g e s t that at b e s t in situations o f a n y c o m p l e x i t y w e h a v e common context rather than common knowledge. T h e r e is c o n s t a n t f e e d b a c k b e t w e e n theory, o b s e r v a t i o n a n d e x p e r i m e n t a t i o n . E x p e r i m e n t a l g a r n e t h e o r y is o n l y at its b e g i n n i n g b u t a l r e a d y s o m e o f t h e r n e s s a g e s are clear. C o n t e x t m a t t e r s . T h e g a m e - t h e o r e t i c m o d e l o f r a t i o n a l m a n is n o t a n i d e a l i z a t i o n h u t a n a p p r o x i m a t i o n o f a far m o r e c o m p l e x c r e a t u r e w h i c h p e r f o r r n s u n d e r s e v e r e c o n s t r a i n t s w h i c h a p p e a r in the c o n c e r n s o f t h e p s y c h o l o g i s t s a n d social p s y c h o l o g i s t s m o r e t h a n in the g a m e - t h e o r e t i c literature.
References Alger, D. (1986), Investigating Oligopolies within the Laboratory (Bureau of Economics, Federn Trade Commission). Aumann, R.J., and M. Maschler (1964), "The bargaining set for cooperative garnes", in: M. Dresher, L.S. Shapley and A.W. Tucker, eds., Advances in Garne Theory (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ), 443-476. Battaglio, R.C., J.H. Kagel and D. McDonald (1985), "Animals' choices over uncertain outcomes: Some initial experimental results", American Economic Review 75:597-613. Bellman, R., C.E. Clark, D.G. Malcolm, C.J. Craft and EM. Ricciardi (1957), "On the construction of a multistage multiperson business garne", Joumal of Operations Research 5:469-503. Bowley, A.L. (1928), "On bilateral monopoly", The Economic Journal 38:651-659. Brewer, G., and M. Shubik (1979), The War Garne (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA). Brown, J.N., and R.W. Rosenthal (1987), Testing the Minimax Hypothesis: A Re-Examination of O'Neill's Garne Experiment (Department of Economics, SUNY, Stony Brook, NY). Caplow, T. (1956), "A tbeory of coalitions in the triad", American Sociological Review 21:489-493. Chamberlain, E.H. (1948), "An experimental imperfect market", Journal of Political Economy 56:95-108. Coase, R. (1960), "The problem of social cost", The Journal of Law and Economics 3:1-44. Edgeworth, EY. (1881), Matbematical Psychics (Kegan Paul, London). Fouraker, L.E., M. Shubik and S. Siegel (1961), "Oligopoly bargaining: The quantity adjuster models", Research Bulletin 20 (Department of Psychology, Pennsylvania State University). Partially reported in: L.E. Fouraker and S. Siegel (1963), Bargaining Bebavior (McGraw Hill, Hightstown, NJ). Frenkel, O. (1973), "A study of 78 non-iterated ordinal 2 x 2 garnes", University of Toronto (unpublished). Friedman, J. (1967), "An experimental study of cooperative duopoly", Econometrica 33:379-397. Friedman, J. (1969), "On experimental research on oligopoly", Review of Eeonomic Studies 36:399-415. Friedman, J., and A. Hoggatt (1980), An Experiment in Noncooperative Oligopoly: Research in Experimental Economics, Vol. 1, Supplement 1 (JAI Press, Greenwich CT). Gamson, W.A. (1961), "An experimental test of a theory of coalition formation", American Sociological Review 26:565-573. Goldstick, D., and B. O'Neill (1988), "Tmer", Philosophy of Science 55:583-597. Güth, W., R. Schmittberger and B. Schwartz (1982), "An experimental analysis of ultimatum bargaining", Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 3:367-388. Guyer, M., and H. Hamburger (1968), "A note on a taxonomy of 2 x 2 garnes", General Systems 13:205-219. Hausner, M., J. Nash, L.S. Shapley and M. Shubik (1964), "So long sucker: A four-person garne", in: M. Shubik, ed., Game Theory and Related Approaches to Social Behavior (Wiley, New York), 359-361. Hoffman, E., and M.L. Spitzer (1982), "The Coase Theorem: Some experimental tests", Journal of Law and Economics 25:73-98. Hoffman, E., and M.L. Spitzer (1985), "Experimental law and eeonomics: An introduction", Columbia Law Review 85:991-1031.
Ch. 62:
GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
2349
Hoggatt, A.C. (1959), "An experimental business game", Behavioral Science 4:192-203. Hoggatt, A.C, (1969), "Response of paid subjects to differential behavior of robots in bifurcated duopoly garnes", Review of Economic Studies 36:417-432. Hong, J.T., and C.R. Plott (1982), "Rate-filing policies for Inland watet transportation: An experimental approach", Bell Journal of Economics 13:1-19. Kagel, J.H. (1987), "Economics according to the rats (and pigeons too): What have we learned and what can we hope to learn?" in: A.E. Roth, ed., Laboratory Experimentation in Economics: Six Points of View (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 155-192. Kagel, J.H., R.C. Battaglio, H. Rachlin, L. Green, R.L. Basmann and W.R. Klemm (1975), "Experimental stndies of consumer demand behavior using laboratory animals", Economic Inquiry 13:22-38. Kagel, J.H., and A.E. Roth (1985), Handbook of Experimental Economics (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ). Kahan, J.E, and A. Rapoport (1984), Theories of Coalition Formation (L. Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ). Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky (1979), "A prospect theory: An analysis of decisions under risk", Econometrica 47:263-291. Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky (1984), "Choices, values and frames", American Psychologist 39:341-350. Kalish, G., J.W. Milnor, J. Nash and E.D. Nering (1954), "Some experimental N-person garnes", in: R.H. Thrall, C.H. Coombs and R.L. Davis, eds., Decision Processes (John Wiley, New York), 301-327. Levine, M.E., and C.R. Plott (1977), "Agenda influence and its implications", Virginia Law Review 63:561604. Lieberman, B. (1960), "Human behavior in a strictly determined 3 x 3 matrix garne", Behavioral Science 5:317-322. Lieberman, B. (1962), "Experimental studies of conflict in some two-person and three-person garnes", in: J.H. Criswell et al., eds., Mathematical Methods in Small Group Processes (Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA), 203-220. Liu, T.C. (1973), "Gaming and oligopolistic competition", Ph.D. Thesis (Department of Administrative Sciences, Yale University, New Haven, CT). Maschler, M. (1963), "The power of a coalition", Management Science 10:8-29. Maschler, M. (1978), "Playing an N-person garne: An experiment", in: H. Sauermann, ed., Coalition-Forming Behavior: Contributions to Experimental Economics, Vol. 8 (Mohr, Tübingen), 283-328. McKelvey, R.D., and EC. Ordeshook (1987), "A decade of experimental research on spatial models of elections and committees", SSWP 657 (Califomia Institute of Tectmology, Pasadena, CA). Miller, G.A. (1956), "The magic number seven, plus or minus two: Some limits on out capacity for processing information", Psychological Review 63:81-97. Morin, R.E. (1960), "Strategies in garnes with saddlepoints", Psychological Reports 7:479-485. Mosteller, E, and R Nogee (1951), "An experimental measurement of utility", Journal of Political Economy 59:371-404. Murnighan, J.K., A.E. Roth and E Schoumaker (1988), "Risk aversion in bargaining: An experimental study", Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 1:95-118. Nash, J.E, Jr. (1951), "Noncooperative garnes", Annals of Mathematics 54:289-295. O'Neill, B. (1986), "International escalation and the dollar auction", Conflict Resolution 30:33-50. O'Neill, B. (1987), "Nonmetric test of the minimax theory of two-person zero-sum garnes", Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA 84:2106-2109. O'Neill, B. (1991), "Comments on Brown and Rosenthal's reexamination", Econometrica 59:503-507. Plott, C.R. (1987), "Dimensions of parallelism: Some policy applications of experimental methods", in: A.E. Roth, ed., Laboratory Experimentation in Economics: Six Points of View (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) 193-219. Powers, I.Y. (1986), "Three essays in garne theory", Ph.D. Thesis (Yale University, New Haven, CT). Radner, R., and A. Schotter (1989), "The sealed bid mechanism: An experimental study", Journal of Economic Theory 48:179-220. Raiffa, H. (1983), The Art and Science of Negotiation (Harvard University Press, Cämbridge, MA).
2350
M. Shubik
Rapoport, A., M.J. Guyer and D,G. Gordon (1976), The 2 x 2 Garne (University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor). Roth, B. (1975), "Coalition formation in the triad", Ph.D. Thesis (New School of Social Research, New York~ NY). Roth, A,E. (1979), Axiomatic Models of Bargaining, Lecture Notes in E¢onomics and Mathematical Systems, Vol. 170 (Springer-Verlaß, Berlin). Roth, A.E. (1983), "Toward a theory of bargaining: An experimental study in economics", Scienee 220:687691. Roth, A.E. (1986), "Laboratory experiments in economies", in: T. Bewely, ed., Advances in Eeonomie Theory (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge), 245-273. Roth, A.E. (1987), Laboratory Experimentation in Economics: Six Points of View (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Roth, A.E. (1988), "Laboratory experimentation in economies: A methodological overview', The Economic Jouma198:974-1031. Roth, A.E., and M. Malouf (1979), «Oame-theoretic models and the role of information in bargaining', Psyehological Review 86:574-594. Roth, A.E., and J.K. Murnighan (1982), "The role of information in bargaining: An experimental study", Econometrica 50:1123-1142. Roth, A.E., J.K. Murnighan and E Schoumaker (1988), "The deadline effect in bargaining: Some experimental evidence", American Economic Review 78:806-823. Roth, A.E., and E Schoumaker (1983), "Expectations and reputations in bargaining: An experimental study", American Economic Review 73:362-372. Sanermann, H. (ed.) (1967-78), Contributions to Experimental Economics, Vols. 1-8 (Mohr, Tübingen). Sauermann, H., and R. Selten (1959), "Ein Oligopolexperiment', Zeitschrift für die Gesamte Staatswissensehaft 115:427471. Schelling, J.C. (1961), Strategy and Conflict (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA). Selten, R. (1982), "Equal division payoff bounds for three-person characteristic function experiments', in: R. Tietz, ed., Aspiration Levels in Bargaining and Economic Decision-Making, Lecture Notes in Economics and Mathematieal Systems, Vol. 213 (Springer-Verlag, Berlin), 265-275. Selten, R. (1987), "Equity and coalition bargaining in experimental three-person garnes", in: A.E. Roth, ed., Laboratory Experimentation in Economics: Six Points of View (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA), 42-98. Shubik, M. (1962), "Some experimental non-zero-sum garnes with lack of information about the rules", Management Science 8:215-234. Shubik, M. (1970), "A note on a simulated stock market", Decision Sciences 1:129-141. Shubik, M. (1971a), "The dollar auction game: A paradox in noneooperative behavior and escalation", The Journal of Conflict Resolution 15:109-111. Shubik~ M. (1971b), "Games of status", Behavioral Sciences 16:117-129. Shubik, M. (1975a), Garnes for Society, Business and War (Elsevier, Amsterdam). Shubik, M. (1975b), The Uses and Methods of Gaming (Elsevier, Amsterdam). Shubik, M. (1978), "Opinions on how one should play a three-person nonconstant-sum garne", Simulation and Garnes 9:301-308. Shubik, M. (1986), "Cooperative garne solutions: Australian, Indian and U.S. opinions", Joumal of Conflict Resolution 30:63-76. Shubik, M., and M. Reise (1972), "An experiment with ten duopoly garnes and beat-the-average behavior", in: H. Sanermann, ed., Coutributions to Experimental Economics (Mohr, Tübingen), 656-689. Shubik, M., and G. Wolf (1977), "Beliefs about eoalition formation in multiple-resource three-person situations", Behavioral Science 22:99-106. Shubik, M., G. Wolf and H.B. Eisenberg (1972), "Some experiences with an experimental oligopoly business garne", General Systems 17:61-75.
Ch. 62:
GarneTheory and Experimental Gaming
2351
Shubik, M., G. Wolf and S. Lockhart (1971), "An artificial player for a business market garne", Simulation and Garnes 2:27-43. Shubik, M., G. Woff and B. Poon (1974), "Perception of payoff structure and opponent's behavior in repeated matrix garnes", Journal of Conflict Resolution 18:646-656. Siegel, S., and L.E. Fouraker (1960), Bargaining and Group Decision-Making: Experiments in Bilateral Monopoly (Macmillan, New York). Simon, R.I. (1967), "The effects of different eneodings on complex problem solving", Ph.D. Dissertation (Yale University, New Haven, CT). Smith, V.L. (1965), "Experimental auction markets and the Walrasian hypothesis", Journal of Political Economy 73:387-393. Smith, V.L. (1979), Research in Experimental Economics, Vol. 1 (JAI Press, Greenwich, CT). Smith, V.L. (1986), "Experimental methods in the political economy of exchange", Science 234:167-172. Stone, J.J. (1958), "An experiment in bargaining garnes', Econometrica 26:286-296. Tegler, A.I. (1980), Too Much Invested to Quit (Pergamon, New York). Zeuthen, F. (1930), Problems of Monopoly and Economic Warfare (Routledge, London).
AUTHOR INDEX
n indicates citation in footnote. 2175, 2180-2182, 2189, 2192, 2196, 2200, 2249n, 2259,2263,2336,2348 Austen-Smith, D. 2207n, 2211,2217,2218, 2222, 2224, 2227 Ausubel, L.M. 1905,1910,1913, 1913n, 1915, 1918-1920, 1922,1928-1930, 1932-1936, 1941, 1942 Avenhaus, R. 1952, 1955,1956,1962,1965, 1969, 1972,1974,1980,1983,1984 Avery, C. 2245, 2263 Avis, D. 1743,1756 Axeh'od, R. 2016,2021 Ayres, I. 1908, 1942, 2239n, 2247n, 2252n, 2263,2267
Abreu, D. 1881,1893, 2289,2290,2290n, 2291, 2292, 2294,2296n, 2297-2301,2301n, 2312, 2313,2320 Admati, A. 1922,1923,1935,1938,1941 Aggarwal, V. 1734,1756 Aghion, E 2315n, 2320 Aivazian, V.A. 2247,2249n, 2263 Aiyagari, R. 1790n, 1797 Akerlo~ G.A. 1588,1589,1905,1941 Alge~ D. 2344, 2348 Allen, B. 1680,1685,1794n, 1795n, 1798, 2275, 2320 Altmann, J. 1952, 1984 Amer, R. 2074, 2075 Ami~ R. 1813, 1829 Anderson, R.M. 1787n, 1790n, 1791n, 1798, 2171,2179,2182 Anscombe, EJ. 1951,1984 Arcand, J.-L.L. 2016n, 2021 Areeda, E 1868, 1893 Arlen, J. 2234n, 2236,2263 Armbruster, W. 1679,1685 Arrow, K.J. 1792n, 1795n, 1798,2189, 2200 Artstein, Z. 1771n, 1785n, 1792n, 1794n, 1798, 2136,2162 Arya, A. 2317n, 2320 Ash, R.B. 1767n, 1769n, 1798 Aubin, J. 2162 Audet, C. 1706, 1718, 1745, 1756 Aumann, R.J. 1524, 1530, 1531, 1537, 1539, 1544, 1571, 1576, 1577, 1585, 1589, 1590, 1599-1601, 1603, 1606-1609, 1613, 1614, 1636,1654,1655, 1657, 1671,1673,1675, 1676, 1680-1682, 1685, 1690,1709, 1711, 1713, 1714, 1718, 1763n, 1764, 1765, 1765n, 1766n, 1770,1771n, 1774n, 1775n, 1780n, 1784,1787, 1789n, 1793n, 1797n, 1798, 2028, 2039, 2040, 2044, 2052, 2072, 2075, 2084-2088, 2095, 2117, 2118, 2128-2131, 2135,2136,2140,2141,2145,2150,2152, 2158, 2159, 2161-2163, 2171-2173, 2173n,
Backhouse, R. 1992n, 2021 Bag, EK. 2049, 2052 Bagwell, K. 1566, 1590, 1861n, 1867n, 1872n, 1893 Baiman, S. 1953, 1984 Bain, J. 1859n, 1893 Baird, D. 2231n, 2232, 2252n, 2263 Balder, E.J. 1783n, 1793n, 1794, 1795, 1795n, 1796-1935 Baliga, S. 1996n, 2012, 2021, 2313, 2315, 2319, 2320 Balkenborg, D. 1565, 1568-1572, 1590 Banks, J.S. 1565, 1590, 1635, 1657, 2207, 2207n, 2210, 2217-2220, 2222, 2222n, 2224, 2227, 2288n, 2293, 2320 Banzhaf III, J.E 2052, 2070, 2075, 2253, 2253n, 2257n, 2263 B~r~ny, L 1606, 1658 Baron, D. 2218, 2219, 2227 Barton, J. 2263 Barut, Y. 1790n, 1799 Ba~gi, E. 1799 Basmann, R.L. 2340, 2349 Bastian, M. 1734, 1756 Baston, V.J. 1956, 1973, 1984 Basu, K. 1527, 1528, 1544, 1590, 1622, 1658 I-1
I-2 Battaglio, R.C. 2331, 2340, 2348, 2349 Battenberg, H.E 1969, 1980, 1984 Battigalli, E 1542, 1590, 1627, 1658 Baye, M.R. 1873n, 1893 Beard, T.R. 2236, 2263 Bebchuk, L.A. 2232n, 2239n, 2247n, 2252n, 2263 Becker, G. 2263 Bellman, R. 1622, 1658, 2339, 2348 Ben-Porath, E. 1544, 1566, 1590, 1605, 1622, 1658 Bennett, C.A. 1952, 1985 Benoit, J.-E 2260n, 2263 Benson, B.L. 2000, 2021 Berbee, H. 2127, 2136, 2140, 2163 Berge, C. 1773n, 1799 Bergin, J. 1793n, 1799, 2298n, 2313, 2320 Bernhardt, D. 1793n, 1799 Bemheim, B.D. 1527, 1585, 1586, 1590, 1601, 1658, 2273, 2320 Besley, T. 2013n, 2021 Bewley, T.F. 1781n, 1799, 1822, t830 Bierlein, D. 1951, 1983, 1984 Bikhchandani, S. 1904n, 1918, 1918n, 1942 Billera, L.J. 2163 Billingsley, E 1767n, 1777n, 1789n, 1799 Binmore, K. 1544, 1590, 1623, 1658, 1899n, 1941n, 1942 Bird, C.G. 1954, 1985 Birmingham, R.L. 2231, 2231n, 2264 Black, D. 2205, 2227 Blackwell, D. 1813, 1821, 1830 Bliss, C. 2318, 2320 Block, H.D. 2062, 2075 Blume, A. 1571, 1590 Blume, L.E. 1550, 1590, 1629, 1658, 2240n, 2264 B6ge, W. 1679, 1685 Bollob~s, B. 1771n, 1799 Bomze, LM. 1745, 1756 Bonnano, G. 1658 Borch, K. 1952, 1953, 1985 Borenstein, S. 1872n, 1893 B6rgers, T. 1542, 1590, 1605, 1658 Borm, EE.M. 1593, 1660, 1700, 1719, 1750, 1756, 1757 Bostock, EA. 1956, 1973, 1984 Bowen, W.M. 1952, 1985 Bowley, A.L. 2341, 2348 Boylan, R. 2318, 2319, 2321
Author Index
Brains, S.J. 1799, 1952, 1985, 2259n, 2264, 2268 Brandenburger, A. 1524, 1544, 1590, 1601, 1608, 1609, 1613, 1654, 1657, 1658, 1681, 1685, 1713, 1718 Brander, J.A. 1855, 1893, 2015, 2021 Brewer, G. 2329, 2345, 2348 Brezis, E. 2016n, 2021 Brown, D. 2163, 2181, 2183 Brown, G.W. 1707, 1719 Brown, J.N. 2334, 2348 Brown, J.P. 2231, 2231n, 2233, 2264 Brusco, S. 2313, 2319-2321 Budd, J.W. 1939, 1942 Bulow, J. 1858n, 1894, 2232n, 2264 Bums, M.R. 2010, 2021 Butnariu, D. 2163, 2181, 2183 Cabot, A.V. 1813, 1832 Cabrales, A. 2319, 2321 Calabresi, G. 2231, 2242, 2264 Calfee, J.E. 2236, 2264 Callen, J.L. 2247, 2249n, 2263 Calvo, E. 2042, 2052 Camerer, C. 2017n, 2021, 2288n, 2320 Cameron, C. 2249, 2264 Cameron, R. 2009, 2021 Canty, M.J. 1952, 1974, 1984 Caplow, T. 2337, 2348 Card, D. 1936, 1940, 1942 Carlos, A.M. 1997, 1998n, 2021 Carlsson, H. 1579, 1584, 1590 Carreras, F. 2050, 2052, 2074, 2075 Carmthers, B.E. 1999n, 2021 Castaing, C. 1773n, 1780n, 1782n, 1799 Chakrabarti, S.K. 1769n, 1770n, 1793n, 1794n, 1799 Chakravorti, B. 2297, 2315, 2316, 2321 Chamberlain, E.H. 2339, 2348 Chamberlin, E. 1799 Champsaur, P. 1795n, 1799, 2163, 2171, 2172, 2181, 2183, 2200 Chander, P. 2276n, 2321 Charnes, A. 1729, 1755, 1756, 1813, 1830 Chatterjee, K. 1905, 1934, 1942 Chen, Y. 2319, 2321 Cheng, H. 2163, 2181, 2183 Chin, H.H. 1531, 1591, 1697, 1700, 1701, 1719 Citing-to Ma, A. 2265 Chipman, J.S. 1796n, 1799 Chiu, Y.S. 2049, 2052
I-3
Author Index
Cho, I.-K. 1565, 1591, 1635, 1651, 1658, 1862, 1894, 1904n, 1918, 1918n, 1921, 1935, 1942 Chun, Y. 2036, 2037, 2052, 2262n, 2264 Chv~ital, V. 1728, 1756 Cirace, J. 2252n, 2264 Clark, C.E. 2339, 2348 Clark, G. 1999n, 2021 Clarke, E 2107, 2118 Clay, K. 2004, 2021 Coase, R.H. 1908, 1917, 1930, 1937, 1942, 2231, 2241, 2252n, 2264, 2345, 2348 Coate, S. 2013n, 2021 Cochran, W.G. 1968, 1985 Cohen, L.R. 2249, 2264 Coleman, J.C. 2253n, 2264 Condorcet, M. 2205, 2227 Conklin, J. 2009, 2021 Constantinides, G.M. 1796n, 1799 Cooter, R.D. 2232, 2236, 2237, 2243n, 2264 Corchon, L. 2297, 2315, 2318, 2318n, 2320, 2321 Cordoba, J.M. 1795n, 1799 Cottle, R.W. 1731, 1749, 1756 Coughlan, E 2225n, 2227 Coughlin, E 2222, 2227 Coulomb, J.M. 1813, 1830, 1847-1849 Cournot, A.A. 1599, 1658, 1764n, 1794, 1795n, 1799 Craft, C.J. 2339, 2348 Cramton, E 1901n, 1906, 1907, 1934, 1935, 1938-1940, 1942, 1943, 2232n, 2264, 2316n, 2321 Craswell, R. 2236, 2264 Crawford, V.E 1899n, 1943, 1998n, 2013, 2021, 2226, 2227, 2289n, 2292, 2302, 2321 Cremer, J. 1943 Cunningham, W. 1992n, 2021 Curran, C. 2236, 2265 Cutland, N. 1787n, 1799, 1802, 1804 da Costa Werlang, S.R. 1663 Da Rin, M. 2012, 2021 Dab1, R.A. 2253n, 2264 Dalkey, N. 1646, 1659 Danilov, V. 2287, 2287n, 2321 Dantzig, G.B. 1730, 1757 Dasgupta, A. 2049, 2052 Dasgupta, R 1530, 1591, 1716, 1719, 1795n, 1799, 1905, 1943, 2274n, 2277n, 2280n, 2321 d'Aspremont, C. 1717, 1719 Daughety, A. 2232n, 2264
David, EA. 1992n, 1997, 2020n, 2021 Davis, E.L. 1997, 2021 Davis, M.D. 1952, 1985, 2259n, 2268 De Frutos, M.A. 2262n, 2264 Debreu, G. 1533, 1591,1612,1659,1766n, 1773n, 1787n, 1795n, 1798-1800 Dekel, E. 1566,1590,160l, 1605,1658, 1659 Demange, G. 2289n, 2321 Demski, J. 2317,2321 Deneckere, R.J. 1910, 1913,1913n, 1915,1916, 1918-1920, 1922-1924, 1928-1930, 1932-1936, 1941-1943 Denzau, A. 2216,2227 Derks, J. 2044,2052 Derman, C. 1974, 1985 DeVfies, C. 1873n, 1893 Dewatripont, M. 2315n, 2320 Dhillon, A. 1659 Diamond, D.W. 2010, 2021 Diamond, H. 1974-1976,1985 Diamond, EA. 2231, 2231u, 2234n, 2264 Dickhaut, J. 1706,1719,1742,1757 Dierkec E. 1533,1591,1797n, 1800 Diestel, J. 1780n, 1781-1784,1784n, 1785, 1786,1786n, 1787-1975 Dincleanu, N. 1782n, 1800 Dixit, A. 1860, 1894 Dold, A. 1535,1591 Doob, J.L. 1790, 1791n, 1800 Downs, A. 2220,2227 Dresher, M. 1528, 1553, 1591, 1689, 1719, 1951,1952,1955, 1956,1969,1972,1985 Dr~ze, J.H. 2028, 2039, 2040, 2052, 2072, 2075, 2192, 2196, 2200 Dfiessen, T. 2109, 2118 Dubey, E 1585,1591,1794n, 1795,1796, 1796n, 1797-1975, 2037,2038,2038n, 2052, 2067-2071, 2075, 2126, 2152-2154, 2163, 2181,2183,2253n, 2254n, 2264 Duffle, D. 1821, 1830 Duggan, J. 2219, 2220, 2222n, 2227, 2294, 2310, 2312,2314,2314n, 2317n, 2318,2321 Duma, B. 2273, 2281,2282, 2287, 2292,2294, 2297,2301,2309, 2310n, 2319,2321,2322 Dutta, E 1813,1830 Dvoretsky, A. 1765,1765n, 1800,2144, 2163 Dye, R.A. 1953, 1985 E~on, J. 1857,1894 Eaves, B.C. 1742, 1745, 1757 Edgeworth, EY. 1800,2341, 2348
I-4 Edlin, A.S. 2236, 2265 Eichengreen, B. 1997, 2021 Einy, E. 2071, 2075 Eisele, T. 1679, 1685 Eisenberg, H.B. 2341, 2350 Eisenberg, T. 2232n, 2265 Eliaz, K. 2319, 2322 Ellison, G. 1580, 1591, 2011, 2022 Elmes, S. 1646, 1659 Emons, W. 2236, 2265 Endres, A. 2234n, 2265 Eskridge, W.N. 2249, 2265 Evangelista, E 1712, 1719 Evans, R. 1923, 1924, 1943 Everett, H. 1830, 1836n, 1840, 1849 Fagin, R. 1681,1682,1684,1685 Falkowski, B.J. 1969,1980,1984 Falmagne, J.C. 2062, 2075 Fan, K. 1612, 1659, 1766n, 1767, 1800 Farber, H.S. 2013,2022 Farquharson, R. 2208,2227, 2289n, 2293,2322 Farrell, J. 1585, 1591, 1907, 1943, 2265 Feddersen, T. 2224,2225, 2227 Federgruen, A. 1830 Fedzhora, L. 2050, 2052 Feichtinger, G. 1956, 1985 Feinberg, Y. 1676, 1676n, 1677, 1685 Feldman, M. 1790n, 1800 Fellner, W. 1882n, 1894 Fer~ohn, J. 2212, 2219, 2227, 2249, 2265 Ferguson, T.S. 1813,1830,1831,1956,1972, 1985 Fernandez, R. 1899n, 1943, 2245n, 2265 Fershtman, C. 2016,2022 Filar, J.A. 1813,1814,1825,1830-1832,1956, 1985 Fiofina, M. 2212,2227 Fischel, W.A. 2240n, 2265 Fishburn, RC. 1609, 1659 Fleming, W. 2105,2118 Flesch, J. 1843,1849 Fogelman, E 2136, 2163 Fohlin, C.M. 2012n, 2022 Forges, F. 1591,1606,1659,1680,1685,1813, 1820,1830 Forsythe, R. 1941n, 1943 Fouraker, L.E. 2333,2341,2348,2351 Fragnelli, V. 2051, 2052 Frenkel, 0.2334,2348
Author Index
Friedman, J. 1882n, 1894,2341,2348 Fudenberg, D. 1524, 1542, 1551, 1591, 1592, 1605,1623,1634,1653,1659,1680,1685, 1774n, 1796n, 1800,1858n, 1861n, 1868n, 1882, 1894, 1910-1912, 1914, 1926, 1943, 1994n, 2022 Fukuda, K. 1743, 1756 Gabel, D. 2010, 2010n, 2022, 2023 Gabszewicz, J.J. 1717, 1719, 1795n, 1800, 2182, 2183 Gal, S. 1949, 1985 Gale, David 1796n, 1800 Gale, Douglas 1956, 1985 Gamson, W.A. 2337, 2348 Garcia, C.B. 1749, 1757 Garcfa-Jurado, I. 2050-2052 Gardner, R.J. 2162, 2163, 2182, 2183 Gamaev, A.Y, 1956, 1985 Geanakoplos, J. 1659, 1821, 1830, 1858n, 1894 Geistfeld, M. 2232n, 2265 Gertner, R. 2232, 2239n, 2247n, 2252n, 2263 Gibbard, A. 2273, 2322 Gibbons, R. 190In, 1907, 1942, 1943 Gilboa, I. 1745, 1756, 1757, 2062, 2075, 2163 Gilette, D. 1830 Gilles, C. 1790n, 1800 Gilligan, T. 2225, 2227 Glazer, J. 1566, 1592, 1899n, 1943, 2245n, 2265, 2283, 2292, 2294, 2300n, 2301, 2301n, 231 ln, 2322 Glicksberg, I.L. 1530, 1592, 1612, 1659, 1717, 1719, 1767, 1767n, 1800 Glover, J. 2317, 2317n, 2320, 2322 Golan, E. 2050, 2053 Goldman, A.J. 1952, 1956, 1985 Goldstick, D, 2348 Gordon, D.G. 2332, 2333, 2335, 2336, 2350 Gorton, G. 2010, 2022 Govindan, S. 1534, 1535, 1565-1567, 1592, 1600, 1640, 1648, 1659 Green, E.J. 1775n, 1793n, 1800, 1877, 1894, 2008, 2010, 2022 Green, J.R. 2177n, 2183, 2236, 2265 Green, L. 2340, 2349 Greenberg, J. 1954, 1985 Greif, A. 1991n, 1994n, 1995, 1995n, 1996, 1996n, 1999n, 2000, 2001, 2003n, 200411, 2005, 2007, 2012n, 2014, 2014n, 2016, 2016n, 2017, 2018, 2018n, 2019, 2020n, 2022, 2023
Author Index
Gresik, T.A. 1789n, 1795n, 1800, 1904, 1905, 1905n, 1906n, 1943 Gretlein, R. 2208, 2227 Grossman, G. 1857, 1894 Grossman, S.J. 1659, 1918n, 1943, 2265 Groves, T. 2285n, 2322 Gu, W. 1940, 1944 Guesnefie, R. 1797n, 1800, 2163, 2182, 2183 Guinnane, T.W. 2013n, 2021 Gul, E 1528, 1534,1566,1592,1659,1676, 1685, 1796n, 1800, 1910-1912, 1913n, 1914, 1915, 1917, 1923, 1927-1929, 1943, 2046, 2047,2052 Gunderson, M. 1936,1939, 1942,1943 G~th, W. 1584,1587-1589,1591,1592,1595, 1955,1985,2338, 2348 Guye~M.J. 2332,2333, 2335,2336,2348,2350 Haddock, D. 2236, 2265 Hadfidd, G. 2239n, 2265 HNmanko, O. 2150, 2155, 2156, 2160, 2163, 2164 HNle~H. 1796n, 1797n, 1800, 1801, 1899n, 1944, 2245n, 2265 HNmos, RR. 1771, 1801 HNpern, J.XL 168L 1682, 1684, 1685 HNfiwangec J. 1872n, 1894 Hamburge~ H. 2333, 2348 Hammers~in, R 1524, 1592, 1659, 1797n, 1801 Hammond, RJ. 1660, 1783n, 1791n, 1795, 1795n, 1796n, 1799,1801,2274n, 2277n, 2280n, 2321 Hansen, R 1706,1718, 1745,1756 Harrington, J. 1867n, 1872n, 1894 Harris, C. 1545, 1592 Harris, M. 2232,2265,2304,2322 Harrison, A. 1936,1940, 1944 Harrison, G.W. 2265 Harsanyi, J.C. 1523,1524,1530,1532-1534, 1537,1538,1547,1567,1572, 1574, 1576-1579, 1583-1587, 1589, 1592, 1593, 1599,1606-1608,1618,1619,1636,1660, 1678-1681, 1685, 1694-1696, 1704, 1719, 1750, 1757,1773,1801,1873,1875,1894, 2034,2042,2045,2052,2084,2091,2117, 2118,2171,2172,2175,2180,2183,2200, 2277,2302,2322 Hart, O.D. 1796n, 1801, 1899, 1917, 1937, 1940,1944,2232,2265 Hart, S. 1531,1541, 1543,1593,1600,1615, 1660,1710,1714,1719,1725,1757,1768n,
I-5 1770n, 177ln, 1775n, 1781n, 1792n, 1793n, 1798, 1801, 1843, 1849, 2033-2035, 2035n, 2039-2042, 2046, 2047, 2047n, 2048, 2052, 2064, 2073-2075, 2094-2096, 2098, 2102-2111, 2113-2115, 2118, 2131, 2157-2160, 2164, 2171, 2172, 2175, 2178, 2178n, 2179n, 2180, 2180n, 2181, 2181n, 2183 Hartwell, R.M. 1991n, 2023 Hauk, E. 1566, 1593 Hausner, M. 2338, 2348 Hay, B.L. 2232n, 2265 Heath, D.C. 2163 Heifetz, A. 1673, 1673n, 1675, 1676n, 1677, 1682, 1684n, 1685, 1686, 1798 Hellmann, T. 2012, 2021 Hellwig, M. 1545, 1593, 1795n, 1798 Hererro, M. 2293, 2322 Herings, EL-J, 1581, 1593, 1660 Hermalin, B. 223 ln, 2239, 2239n, 2240n, 2265 Herv6s-Beloso, C. 1795n, 1801 Heuer, G.A. 1697, 1700, 1719, 1744, 1757 Hiai, E 1785n, 1801 Hildenbrand, W. 1770n, 1771n, 1775n, 1777n, 1780n, 1781n, 1789n, 1793n, 1801, 1802 Hillas, J. 1553, 1564, 1565, 1593, 1632, 1634, 1647, 1651, 1660, 1719, 1725, 1757 Hinich, M. 2221, 2227 Hintikka, J. 1681, 1686 Hoffman, E. 1997, 1998n, 202l, 2243n, 2265, 2345, 2348 Hoffman, RT. 2011, 2020, 2023 Hoggatt, A.C. 2339-2341, 2348, 2349 Hohfeld, W.N. 2242n, 2265 Holden, S. 1899n, 1944, 2245n, 2265 Holmstrom, B. 2232, 2265, 2266, 2304, 2316, 2322 Hong, J.T. 2344, 2349 Hong, L. 2279n, 2322 HiSpfinger, E. 1954, 1970, 1972, 1985 Housman, D. 1789n, 1793n, 1802 Howson Jr., J.T. 1535, 1594, 1696, 1701, 1702, 1720, 1725, 1731, 1734, 1739, 1740, 1745, 1757, 1758, 1953, 1985 Hughes, J. 1997, 2024 Hurd, A.E. 1787n, 1802 Hurkens, S. 1566, 1571, 1591, 1593 Hurwicz, L. 1795n, 1802, 2266, 2277, 2279n, 2287n, 2297, 2319, 2322, 2323 Hylton, K.N. 2236, 2266
I-6 IAEA 1982,1985 Ichiishi, T. 2116-2118 Imm, H. 2092, 2109, 2118, 2164 Imrie, R.W. 2255n, 2266 Irwin, D.A. 2015,2023 IsbeH, J. 2164 Isoda, K. 1716,1720 Jackson, M. 2275,2277n, 2292,2294,2296, 2297,2301,2302,2309,2310,2313, 2316-2318, 2323 Jacobson, N. 1821, 1830 Jaech, J.L. 1952, 1986 Jamison, R.E. 1780n, 1802 Jansen, M.J.M. 1531, 1565, 1593, 1647, 1660, 1662,1663,1696,1700,1719,1721,1744, 1745,1750,1756,1757,1759 Jaumard, B. 1706,1718,1745,1756 Jaynes, G. 1795n, 1802 Jehid, R 1905,1944 Jia-He, J. 1663,1696,1721 Johnston, J.S. 2239n, 2247n, 2266 Jovanovic, B. 1793n, 1796n, 1797n, 1802 Judd, K.L. 1802,2016,2022 Jurg, A.R 1593,1660,1700,1719,1750,1757 Kadiy~i,V. 1867n, 1894 Kage1, J.H. 2331,2340,2348,2349 Kahan, J.E 2336, 2349 Kahan, M. 2232n, 2235n, 2266 Kahneman, D. 2346, 2349 Kakutani, S. 1611,1660 K ~ , E. 1568, 1569, 1571, 1593, 1660, 1745, 1757,2039, 2052,2063,2064,2066,2075, 2082,2083,2090,2099-2102,2118,2119, 2323 K~ish, G. 2349 Kalkofen, B. 1588,1589,1592 Kambhu, J. 2232n, 2266 Kandofi, M. 1580,1593 Kaneko, M. 1796n, 1802 Kannm, Y. 1775n, 1777n, 1802,2126,2136, 2164 Kanodia, C.S. 1953, 1986 Kantor, E.S. 1993n, 2023 Kaplan, R.S. 1952,1986 Kaplan, T. 1706,1719,1742,1757 Kaplansky, I. 1697, 1719 Kaplow, L. 2245, 2247n, 2266 Karfin, S. 1689, 1719, 1720, 1975, 1986 Karni, E. 1797n, 1802
Author Index
K~z,A. 2239n, 2252n, 2266 Katz, M. 2231n, 2239n, 2265 K~znelson, Y. 1539,1590,1774n, 1789n, 1798 Keiding, H. 1743,1757 Keislec H.J. 1787n, 1791n, 1802 Kelsey, D. 1796n, 1802 Kemperman, J.H.B. 2164 Kennan, J. 1899, 1899n, 1936, 1937, 1939, 1940, 1941n, 1943,1944 Kennedy, D. 2242n, 2266 Kern, R. 2085,2087,2088,2117,2119 Kervin, J. 1936,1939,1943 Khan, M.A. 1767n, 1769n, 1770,1771,1771n, 1772-1777, 1777n, 1778, 1778n, 1779-1781, 1781n, 1782,1782n, 1783-1785,1785n, 1786, 1786n, 1787-1789, 1789n, 1790-1793, 1793n, 1794, 1794n, 1795-1797,1797n, 1798-2101 Kihls~om, R.E. 1796n, 1803,1804 Kilgouc D.M. 1952,1954,1985,1986 Kim, S.H. 1804 Kim, T. 1793n, 1794n, 1804, 2319, 2323 Kinghorn, J.R. 2012n, 2023 Klages, A. 1953, 1986 Klein, B. 2232n, 2267 Klemm, W.R. 2340, 2349 Klemperer, R 1858n, 1894, 1901n, 1907, 1942, 2232n, 2264 Knez, M. 2017n, 2021 Knuth, D.E. 1745,1757 Kohlberg, E. 1531,1532,1551, 1553,1554, 1561, 1562,1593,1600,1613,1627, 1631, 1634, 1635, 1640, 1641, 1644-1646, 1649, 1660,1719,1725,1745,1746,1757,1771n, 1775n, 1781n, 1793n, 1801,1813,1822, 1830, 1848,1849,1921,1944,2161, 2164 Kojima, M. 1756,1757 KoHec D. 1725,1750,1752-1757 Komhausec L.A. 2231n, 2232,2234n, 2236, 2237n, 2249,2252n, 2262,2264, 2266 Koaanek, K.O. 1954,1985 Kovenock, D. 1873n, 1893 Krame~ G. 2215-2217, 2221,2227 Krehbiel, K. 2225, 2227 Kreps, D.M. 1540-1542, 1544, 1549-1551, 1560,1565,1567,1591,1593,1618,1623, 1627,1629,1634,1635,1645,1651,1653, 1658-1661, 1680,1686,1858n, 1862,1868n, 1894, 1918,1921,1942 Kreps, V.L. 1697,1720 Kripke, S. 1681,1686
I~7
Author Index
Krishna, V. 1708, 1720, 1900, 1944 Krohn, I. 1704, 1720, 1740, 1757 Kuhn, H.W. 1541, 1593, 1616, 1661, 1699, 1701,1720,1743,1751, 1752,1754,1758, 1763,1763n, 1804,1951,1972,1986, 2164 Kuhn, E 1940, 1944 Kumar, K. 1789n, 1804 Kttrz, M. 2040-2042, 2052, 2073-2075, 2095, 2117-2119, 2162, 2180, 2182, 2189, 2192, 2200 Laffond, G. 2220n, 2228 Laftbnt, J.J. 1796n, 1803,1804 Lake, M. 2259n, 2264 Landes, W. 2236, 2266 LandsbergegM. 1954,1986 Lane, D. 2236, 2264 Laroque, G. 1795n, 1799 Lasaga, J. 2042,2052 Lasliec J. 2220n, 2228 Laver, M. 2217,2218,2228 Le Breton, M. 2220n, 2228 Ledyard, J. 2221,2227,2318,2321,2323 Lefvre, E 2164 Legros, E2316n, 2323 Lehmmm, E.L. 1961, 1986 Lehre~ E. 1829,1830,2070,2075 LNninge~W. 1545, 1593, 1813, 1830 Lemke, C.E. 1535,1594,1696, 1701,1702, 1720,1725,1731,1734, 1739,1740,1742, 1749,1755,1758 Leong, A. 2236,2267 Leopold(-Wildburge0, U. 1587,1594,1595 Levens~in, M.C. 1995n, 2011, 2023 Levhari, D. 1813, 1830 Leviatan, S. 2181, 2183 Levin, D. 1797n, 1802 Levin, R.C. 2010, 2020n, 2024 Levine, D.K. 1524, 1542, 1591, 1592, 1623, 1634, 1653, 1659, 1796n, 1800, 1804, 1882, 1894,1911, 1912,1914,1926,1943 Levine, M.E. 2344,2349 Levy, A. 2074, 2075, 2090, 2091, 2095, 2117, 2119 Levy, Z. 2046, 2047, 2052 Lewis, D. 1671,1681,1686,2020,2023 Liang, M.-Y. 1923,1924,1943 Lieberman, B. 2333, 2334, 2349 Lindbeck, A. 2222, 2228 Linds~om, T. 1787n, 1804 Linial, N. 1756,1758
Lipnowski, I. 2247, 2249n, 2263 Littlechild, S.C. 2051,2052 Liu, T.C. 2341, 2349 Lockhart, S. 2341, 2351 Loeb, EA. 1780n, 1787, 1787n, 1802, 1804, 2163, 2181, 2183 Lo6ve, M. 1767n, 1769n, 1804 Lucas, R.E.,Jr. 1796n, 1804 Lucas, W.E 1752,1758,2075,2076,2255n, 2267 Luce, R.D. 1607, 1661,1678,1686 Lyapuno~A. 1780n, 1804, 2164 Ma, C.-T. 2283, 2292, 2316, 2317, 2317n, 2322, 2323 Ma, ZW. 1766n, 1804 Mackay, R. 2216,2227 MacLeod, W.B. 2001n, 2023 Madrigal, V. 1551,1594 MNlath, G.J. 1553,1554,1580,1593,1594, 1632, 1661, 1796n, 1804, 2267 MN~a, A. 1829-1831,1848,1849 M~umdar, M. 1785n, 1803 Makowsld, L. 1795n, 1804, 1900, 1944 MNcolm, D.G. 2339,2348 MNcomson, J.M. 2001n, 2023 MNou~M. 2332,2342,2350 Mangasarian, O.L. 1701, 1706, 1720, 1742, 1744,1745,1758 Mann, I. 2050,2052 Marschak, J. 2062, 2075 Martin, D.A. 1829, 1831, 1848, 1849 Marx, L.M. 1661 Mas-Colell, A. 1763, 1763n, 1775, 1775n, 1781n, 1785n, 1788,1789n, 1793n, 1794n, 1795,1795n, 1796,1797,1797n, 1798-1830, 1821, 1830, 2033-2035, 2035n, 2039, 2040, 2047, 2047n, 2048, 2052, 2064, 2075, 2098, 2103-2110, 2114, 2115, 2118, 2131,2157, 2164,2172,2175,2177n, 2179n, 2180,2181, 2181n, 2183,2297,2323 Maschle~M. 1537, 1590, 1657, 1680, 1685, 1690, 1718,1951,1954,1972,1973,1977, 1980, 1986, 2110-2112, 2114, 2119, 2181, 2183,2249n, 2259,2263,2331,2336,2337, 2348, 2349 Maskin, E. 1530, 1591, 1680, 1685, 1716, 1719, 1882, 1894, 1905, 1911, 1943, 1944, 2264, 2272, 2273,2274n, 2275,2277n, 2279n, 2280n, 2282, 2284, 2285, 2285n, 2315-2317, 2319, 2321, 2323
I-8 Maskin, M. 1585, 1591 Mass6, J. 1793n, 1805 Matsuo, T. 1904, 1944 Matsushima, H. 2294, 2296n, 2297, 2299-2301, 2301n, 2312, 2320, 2323 Maurer, J.H. 1996n, 2016, 2023 Maynard Smith, J. 1524, 1594, 1607, 1661 McAfee, R.E 1904, 1907, 1944 McCardle, K.E 1662, 1676n, 1686, 1713, 1720 McCloskey, D.N. 1991n, 2020, 2023 McConnell, S. 1936, 1944 McDonald, D. 2331, 2340, 2348 McGarvey, D. 2209, 2228 McGee, J. 1868, 1894 McKee, M. 2265 McKelvey, R.D. 1706, 1720, 1725, 1756, 1758, 2207-2209, 2212, 2227, 2228, 2285, 2287, 2287n, 2293, 2297, 2301n, 2309n, 2318, 2319n, 2321, 2323, 2345, 2349 McKenzie, L.W. 1796n, 1805 McLean, R.R 1943, 2074-2076, 2090, 2091, 2095, 2117, 2119, 2164, 2165, 2171, 2174, 2183 McLennan, A. 1566, 1594, 1659, 1661, 1706, 1720, 1725, 1743, 1756, 1758, 1821, 1830, 2066, 2076 McMillan, J. 1796n, 1805 McMullen, E 1743, 1758 Megiddo, N. 1725, 1750, 1752-1758 Meier, M. 1674n, 1682n, 1686 Meilijson, I. 1954, 1986 Melamed, A.D. 2242, 2264 Melino, A. 1936, 1939, 1943 Melolidakis, C. 1956, 1972, 1985 Mertens, J.-E 1531, 1532, 1548, 1553, 1554, 1559-1562, 1564, 1566, 1570, 1572, 1593, 1594, 1600, 1629, 1631, 1634, 1635, 1636n, 1638-1641, 1644-1651, 1654, 1659-1661, 1669, 1673, 1675, 1679, 1680, 1682, 1686, 1745, 1746, 1757, 1758, 1809, 1813, 1816, 1818-1823, 1823n, 1828, 1831, 1835, 1840, 1843, 1847, 1849, 1921, 1944, 2131, 2133, 2141, 2146-2148, 2160, 2165, 2180, 2182-2184, 2201 Mezzetti, C. 1900, 1944 Michelman, E 224211, 2266 Milchtaich, I. 2165 Milgrom, RR. 1529, 1539, 1544, 1594, 1661, 1680, 1686, 1709, 1720, 1773, 1774n, 1775n, 1781n, 1789n, 1805, 1861, 1868n, 1894,
Author Index
1994n, 1995n, 1999n, 2005, 2012n, 2014, 2023 Miller, G.A. 2335, 2349 Miller, N. 2210, 2228, 2293, 2323 Millham, C.B. 1697, 1700, 1719, 1720, 1744, 1757, 1758 Mills, H. 1701, 1720, 1745, 1758 Milne, E 1796n, 1802 Milnor, J.W. 1764n, 1805, 1831, 2165, 2349 Minelli, E. 1680, 1685 Mirman, LJ. 1813, 1830, 2165 Mirrlees, J.A. 1795n, 1805, 1944, 2231n, 2264 Mitzrotsky, E. 1969, 1986 Miyasawa, K. 1708, 1720 Modigliani, F. 1859n, 1894 Mokyr, J. 2011, 2023 Moldovanu, B. 1905, 1944 Moltzahn, S. 1704, 1720, 1740, 1757 Monderer, D. 1528, 1529, 1594, 1708, 1709, 1720, 1829, 1830, 2053, 2060, 2062, 2065, 2066, 2069, 2075, 2076, 2130, 2131, 2151, 2157, 2158, 2164, 2165 Mongin, P. 1682, 1686 Mookherjee, D. 1900, 1944, 2305, 2305n, 2309, 2324 Moore, J. 2275, 2281-2283, 2287, 2289, 2291, 2292, 2315-2317, 2323, 2324 Moran, M. 2268 Morelli, M. 2049, 2053 Moreno-Garcia, E. 1795n, 1801 Morgenstem, O. 1523, 1526, 1543, 1594, 1606, 1609, 1646, 1663, 1681, 1686, 1689, 1721, 1763, 1790n, 1808, 2036, 2053 Moriguchi, C. 2013, 2023 Morin, R.E. 2333, 2349 Morris, S. 1676, 1686 Moses, M. 1681, 1682, 1685 Mosteller, F. 2332, 2349 Moufin, H. 1531, 1543, 1594, 1604, 1614, 1661, 1711, 1714, 1715, 1720, 2209, 2228, 2267, 2289n, 2292, 2293, 2302, 2323, 2324 Mount, K. 2275, 2277, 2324 Mukhamediev, B.M. 1701, 1720, 1745, 1758 Mtiller, H. 2196, 2200 Mulmuley, K. 1743, 1758 Murnighan, J.K. 2342, 2347, 2349, 2350 Murphy, K. 2012, 2023 Murty, K.G. 1749, 1758 Mutuswami, S. 2049, 2053 Myerson, R.B. 1531, 1540, 1547, 1552, 1553, 1594, 1619, 1628, 1631, 1640, 1661, 1680,
Author Index
1686,1700,1720,1795n, 1805, 1900, 1903-1905, 1934, 1944, 1998n, 2023, 2036, 2042, 2044, 2048, 2052, 2053, 2066, 2072, 2074-2076, 2117, 2119, 2246n, 2267, 2302, 2302n, 2304, 2316, 2322, 2324 Nakamura, K. 2206,2228 NNebuff, B. 2318,2320 NashJr.,J.E 1523,1524,1528,1531,1534, 1586,1587, 1594,1599,1606,1607,1611, 1662,1690,1720,1727,1734, 1758,1764, 1764n, 1766, 1767n, 1771n, 1772, 1783, 1785, 1805, 1855, 1894, 2045, 2053, 2083, 2119,2180,2184, 2189,2201,2338,2339, 2348,2349 Nau, R.E 1662,1676n, 1686,1713,1720 NeN, L. 1998, 2023 Neegn, J. 1941n, 1944 Nefing, E.D. 2349 Neumann, J. yon, see yon Neumann, J. Neyman, A. 1529,1594,1662,1823,1830, 1831,1835,1849,2038,2039, 2053, 2067-2069, 2075, 2117, 2118, 2126, 2131, 2133-2137,2139,2148,2151-2153, 2162-2166,2171,2174,2181,2183,2184, 2192,2200 Niemi, R. 2208, 2209, 2228, 2293, 2323 Nikaido, H. 1716, 1720 Nisgav, Y. 1955,1956,1973,1986 Nishikofi, A. 1954, 1986 Nitzan, S. 2222,2227 Nix, J. 2010n, 2023 Nogee, E 2332, 2349 N61deke, G. 1551,1595,1662 Noma, T. 1756,1757 Norde, H. 1529,1589,1595,1694,1720,2051, 2052 North, D.C. 1993n, 1995n, 1997,1999,2005, 2012n, 2016n, 2020n, 2021,2023 Novshek, W. 1794n, 1795n, 1805 Nowak, A.S. 1817,1821,1831 Nti, K. 1796n, 1805 Nye, J.V. 1998n, 2012n, 2023 Ochs, J. 1941n, 1944 Oi, W. 2232n, 2267 Okada, A. 1569,1595, 1662,1980,1983,1984 Okada, N. 1954, 1986 Okuno, M. 1795n, 1802 O'Neill, B. 1805,1949, 1986,2259,2260, 2262n, 2267,2334,2338,2348,2349
I-9 Ordeshook, EC. 2221, 2227, 2314, 2324, 2345, 2349 Ordovel; J.A. 2236,2267 Orshan, G. 2112, 2119 O~ufio-Ortin, I. 2318n, 2321 Osborne, M.J. 1565,1595,1662,1899n, 1942, 1944, 2117, 2119, 2166, 2245n, 2267 Os~om, E. 1955,1987 Os~oy, J. 1795n, 1804 Owen, G. 2028, 2040-2042, 2050-2053, 2062, 2063,2069,2073, 2074, 2075n, 2076,2094, 2096-2100, 2110-2112, 2114, 2119, 2144, 2166,2181,2183 Pacios, M.A. 2050, 2052 Page, S. 2322 Palfrey, T. 1805, 2274n, 2275, 2287n, 2292, 2294, 2295, 2297, 2301, 2301n, 2303n, 2305n, 2307n, 2308-2312, 2314, 2316, 2316n, 2317, 2318, 2319n, 2321, 2323, 2324 Pallaschke, D. 2166 Pang, J.-S. 1731, 1749, 1756 Papadimitriou, C.H. 1745, 1756-1758 Papageorgiou, N.S. 1785n, 1793n, 1794n, 1803, 1805 Park, I.-U. 1743, 1758 Parthasarathy, K.R. 1767n, 1789n, 1805 Parthasarathy, T. 1531, 1591, 1689, 1697, 1700, 1701, 1716, 1719, 1720, 1725, 1758, 1814, 1818-1820, 1830, 1831 Pascoa, M.R. 1785n, 1789n, 1793n, 1795n, 1796n, 1801, 1805, 1806 Patrone, E 2051, 2052 Pazgal, A. 2166 Pearce, D.G. 1527, 1528, 1534, 1542, 1566, 1592, 1595, 1601, 1604, 1662, 1881, 1893 Pearl, M.H. 1956, 1985 Peleg, B. 1529, 1530, 1585, 1590, 1595, 1767n, 1768, 1768n, 1806, 2119, 2297, 2318, 2324 Perea y Monsuw6, A. 1662 Perez-Castfillo, D. 2048, 2053 Perles, M. 2163 Perloff, J. 2239n, 2267 Perry, M. 1659, 1900, 1904n, 1905, 1918n, 1922, 1923, 1935, 1935n, 1938, 1941, 1943-1945, 2300n, 2322 Pesendorfer, W. 1796n, 1800, 1804, 2224, 2225, 2227 Peters, H. 2044, 2052 Pethig, R. 1955, 1985 Pfeffer, A. 1756, 1757
I-lO Picker, R. 2231n, 2232, 2252n, 2263 Piehlmeie~ G. 1969, 1984, 1986 Plo~, C.R. 2207, 2228, 2344, 2349 Png, I.RL. 2236, 2267 Polak, B. 1662,1996n, 2012,2021 Polinsky, A.M. 2232n, 2236,2239n, 2267 Ponssard, J.-E 1565,1595 Poon, B. 2332,2351 Po~e~ D. 2288n, 2320 Po~er, R.H. 1877, 1877n, 1894,1995n, 2010, 2022,2024 Posner, R. 2236,2239n, 2266,2267 Pos~l-Vinay, G. 2011, 2023 Posflew~,A.W. 1795n, 1796n, 1800, 1804, 1806,2267,2275,2279n, 2287n, 2297, 2303, 2303n, 2307n, 2309,2323,2324 Potters, J.A.M. 1564,1589,1593,1595,1647, 1660,1663,1700,1719,1750,1756 Powers, I.Y. 2333,2349 Prakash, E 1806 Prescott, E.C. 1796n, 1804 Price, G.R. 1524, 1594, 1607, 1661 Priest, G.L. 2232n, 2267 Pfikry, K. 1793n, 1794n, 1798, 1804 Quemer, I. 2234n, 2265 Quint, T. 1743, 1758 Quinzii, M. 2136,2163 Raanan, J. 2163,2165 Rachlin, H. 2340,2349 Radner, R. 1539, 1590, 1595, 1773, 1774n, 1789n, 1792n, 1798,1806,1882n, 1894, 1941n, 1945,2344,2349 Radzik, T. 1716,1717,1720 Rae, D.W. 2253n, 2267 Raghavan, T.E.S. 1531, 1591, 1595, 1689, 1697, 1700, 1701, 1712,1716,1719-1721, 1725, 1730,1758,1759,1814,1821,1825,1831, 1832,1846,1850 RNffa, H. 1607,1661,1678,1686,2342,2343, 2349 Rajan, U. 2317n, 2320 Ramey, G. 1551,1566,1590,1593,1627,1661, 1861n, 1867n, 1893 Ramseyer, J.M. 2010n, 2024 Rapoport, Amnon 2050, 2053 Rapoport, An~o12332,2333,2335, 2336,2349, 2350 Rashid, S. 1780n, 1787n, 1789n, 1790n, 1804, 1806
Author Index
Rasmusen, E. 1994n, 2024, 2239n, 2249, 2267 Rath, K.R 1771n, 1774n, 1776n, 1777, 1777n, 1778, 1778n, 1781n, 1785n, 1786, 1786n, 1793n, 1794n, 1803, 1806 Rauh, M.T. 1766n, 1779n, 1796n, 1807 Raut, L.K. 2166 Ravindran, G. 1717, 1720 Raviv, A. 2232, 2265 Ray, D. 1585, 1590 Reichelstein, S. 1900, 1944, 2297, 2305, 2305n, 2309, 2324 Reichert, J. 2131, 2166 Reid, F. 1936, 1939, 1943 Reijnierse, H. 1589, 1595 Reinganum, J.E 1954, 1986, 2232n, 2264, 2267 Reise, M. 2341, 2350 Reiter, S. 1997, 2024, 2275, 2277, 2297, 2324 Reny, EJ. 1544, 1545, 1551, 1557, 1592, 1593, 1595, 1613, 1622, 1623, 1627, 1634, 1646, 1654, 1659, 1660, 1662, 1904, 1905, 1944, 1945 Repullo, R. 2281-2283, 2285-2287, 2289, 2291, 2292, 2324, 2325 Revesz, R.L. 2236, 2252n, 2262, 2266 Rey, E 2315n, 2320 Ricciardi, EM. 2339, 2348 Riley, J. 1915, 1945 Rinderle, K. 1973, 1986 Ritzberger, K. 1532, 1533, 1595, 1650, 1662 Rob, R. 1580, 1593, 1796n, 1806 Roberts, J. 1529, 1544, 1594, 1661, 1680, 1686, 1709, 1720, 1794n, 1795n, 1806, 1861, 1867, 1868n, 1894, 2318, 2321 Roberts, K. 1795n, 1806 Robinson, J. 1707, 1721, 1806 Robson, A.J. 1545, 1566, 1592, 1593, 1659 Rogerson, W. 223 ln, 2232n, 2237n, 2267 Romanovskii, I.V. 1725, 1750, 1755, 1759 Root, H.L. 1999, 2024 Rosenberg, D. 1849, 1850, 2252n, 2267 Rosenfield, A.M. 2239n, 2267 Rosenmtiller, J. 1534, 1595, 1696, 1702, 1704, 1720, 1721, 1740, 1757, 2166 Rosenthal, J.-L. 1995n, 1996n, 2008n, 2011, 2012, 2020n, 2023, 2024 Rosenthal, R.W. 1539, 1544, 1590, 1595, 1662, 1711, 1712, 1721, 1745, 1757, 1773, 1774n, 1789n, 1793n, 1796n, 1797n, 1798, 1799, 1802, 1805, 1806, 1873n, 1894, 2162, 2166, 2294, 2301, 2301n, 2322, 2334, 2348 Rotemberg, J.J. 1870, 1877, 1895, 2011, 2024
Author Index
Roth, A.E. 1941n, 1944, 2031,2032,2053, 2067n, 2070,2076,2083,2095, 2119,2181, 2184, 2330-2332, 2342, 2343, 2347, 2349, 2350 Roth, B. 2337,2350 Rothblum, U. 2163,2166 Rothschild, M. 1796n, 1805 Royden, H.L. 1781n, 1806 Rubinfeld, D.L. 2232, 2236,2240n, 2264,2267 Rubinstein, A. 1537,1542,1579,1595, 1662, 1882n, 1895,1899n, 1904n, 1909,1910, 1918,1929,1933,1938,1942,1944,1945, 1954,1986,2245,2245n, 2267,2268,2300n, 2311n, 2315n, 2317,2322, 2325 Ruckle, W.H. 1952,1986,2165,2166 Rudin, W. 1767n, 1781n, 1807 Russen, G.S. 1955,1986 Rusfichini, A. 1782n, 1793n, 1794n, 1799,1803, 1807,1906,1945 Saari, D. 2207, 2228 Saaty, T.L. 1951, 1986 S~jo, Z2285, 2287, 2297, 2309n, 2325 Sakaguchi, M. 1956,1972,1986 S~kovics, J. 1909n, 1945 SNone~ G. 1870,1877,1895,2011,2024 Samet, D. 1568,1569,1571,1593,1660,1662, 1673,1673n, 1675-1677, 1686, 2039,2052, 2053,2063-2066,2075,2076,2082, 2090, 2099, 2100,2102,2103,2118,2119, 2165, 2167 Samudson, L. 1524,1553, 1554, 1594, 1595, 1632, 1661,1662 Samuelson, EA. 1796,1796n, 1807 Samuelson, W. 1905,1908,1923n, 1934,1942, 1945,2268 Santos, J.C. 2167 Sappington, D. 2317, 2321 SateKhwaite, M.A. 1789n, 1795n, 1800, 1804, 1807,1900,1903,1904,1906,1906n, 1934, 1943-1945, 2246n, 2267, 2273,2325 Sauermann, H. 2341, 2343n, 2350 Savard, G. 1706,1718,1745,1756 Schanuel, S.H. 1583, 1595 Scheinkman, J. 1858n, 1894 Schelling, J.C. 2343, 2350 Schelling, T. 2020, 2024 Schl~cher, H. 1954, 1986 Schmeidler, D. 1531, 1593, 1660, 1710, 1719, 1765,1766,1768n, 1770n, 1779n, 1780n,
1-11 1785,1785n, 1795n, 1797n, 1801,1802, 1806, 1807, 2303, 2303n, 2307n, 2309, 2324 Schmi~berger, R. 2338,2348 Schofield, N. 2206,2207,2228 S c h o t ~ A . 1941n, 1945, 2234n, 2266, 2344, 2349 Schoumaker, E 2343,2347,2349,2350 Schrijver, A. 1728,1759 Schroede~ R. 1813,1830 Schwartz, A. 2231n, 2232n, 2264, 2268 Schwartz, B. 2338,2348 Schwartz, E.E 2249, 2268 Schwarz, G. 1721, 1807 Secci~ G. 1796n, 1807 Seflon, M. 2301,2325 Seidmann, D. 2050,2053 Sela, A. 1708,1720 Selten, R. 1523,1524,1530,1539-1544, 1546, 1547, 1549, 1567, 1572, 1574, 1576-1578, 1583-1589, 1592,1593,1595,1600,1618, 1619, 1621,1622,1625,1628,1636,1640, 1645,1659,1660, 1662,1691,1721,1725, 1748, 1750,1755, 1757,1759,1797n, 1801, 1854, 1895,2117, 2118,2337,2341, 2350 Sen, A. 2273, 2281,2282,2287, 2289,2290, 2290n, 2291,2292,2294,2297,2298,2298n, 2299, 2301, 2309,2310n, 2313,2319-2322, 2325 Sercu, E 2268 Se~ano, R. 2312, 2325 Se~el, M.R. 1799,1806 Shafer, W. 1795n, 1796n, 1807, 2095,2119, 2181, 2184 Shaked, A. 1941n, 1942 Shannon, C. 1529,1594 Shap~o, C. 2003, 2024 Shap~o,N.Z. 1763, 1807, 2167 Shap~o, E 2240n, 2264, 2265 Shapley, L.S. 1528,1529,1535,1537,1594, 1596 1704,1708,1709,1720,1721,1725, 1731 1734,1740,1759, 1763,1764n, 1800, 1805 1807,1812,1816,1831,2027-2030, 2039 2044, 2050, 2052, 2053, 2060, 2062, 2063 2065, 2066, 2069-2071, 2075, 2076, 2082 2084, 2102, 2116-2119, 2128-2131, 2135 2136,2140,2141,2145,2150,2152, 2158 2159, 2161-2163, 2165, 2167, 2171, 2172 2173n, 2174, 2175, 2180-2182, 2184, 2201 2253,2253n, 2254n, 2264,2268,2338, 234~ Sharke 4W.W. 2116, 2119,2165
1-12 Shave11, S. 2231n, 2232, 2232n, 2235, 2236, 2237n, 2239n, 2245, 2247n, 225211, 2263, 2266-2268 Shephard, A. 1872n, 1893 Shepsle, K. 2210, 2216-2218, 2228 Shieh, J. 1793n, 1807 Shilony, Y. 1873n, 1895 Shipan, C. 2249, 2265 Shitovitz, B. 2182, 2183 Shleifer, A. 2012, 2023 Shubik, M. 1596, 1743, 1758, 1794n, 1795, 1796, 1796n, 1797-2217, 1813, 1831, 2030, 2053, 2070, 2076, 2167, 2171, 2184, 2253, 2268, 2329, 2332, 2333, 2335n, 2336, 2338, 2340n, 2341, 2343n, 2345, 2348, 2350, 2351 Siegel, S. 2333, 2341, 2348, 2351 Simon, L.K. 1530, 1548, 1583, 1595, 1596 Simon, R.I. 2329, 2351 Simon, R.S. 1843, 1850 Sj6str6m, T. 1708, 1720, 2287, 2294, 2297, 2315, 2316, 2318-2320, 2325 Smith, V.L. 2331, 2340n, 2351 Smorodinski, R. 2137, 2166 Sobel, J. 1550, 1560, 1565, 1590, 1591, 1593, 1635, 1657, 1658, 1917, 1921, 1926, 1942, 1945, 2226, 2227, 2236, 2265, 2268 Sobel, M.J. 1813, 1832 Sobolev, A.I. 2035, 2053 Solan, E. 1840, 1843, 1846, 1846n, 1850 Sonnenschein, H. 1794n, 1795, 1796, 1796n, 1797-2319, 1910-1912, 1913n, 1914, 1915, 1917, 1923, 1927-1929, 1941n, 1943, 1944 Sopher, B. 1941n, 1943 Sorin, S. 1571, 1576, 1590, 1596, 1657, 1662, 1680, 1681, 1685, 1686, 1721, 1809, 1816, 1823n, 1827, 1829-1832, 1835, 1846, 1849, 1850, 2201 Spence, M. 1588, 1596, 1859, 1895 Spencer, B.J. 1855, 1893, 2015, 2021 Spiegel, M. 1941n, 1944 Spier, K. 2232n, 2268 Spiez, S. 1843, 1850 Spitzer, M.L. 2243n, 2249, 2264, 2265, 2345, 2348 Srivastava, S. 1805, 2274n, 2275, 2292-2295, 2297, 2301, 2303n, 2305n, 2307n, 2308-2312, 2316, 2318, 2322-2325 Sroka, J.J. 2167 Stacchetti, E. 1528, 1534, 1592, 1881, 1893 Staiger, R. 1872n, 1893 Stanford, W. 1528, 1596
Author Index
Stem, M. 1814, 1831 Stewart, M. 1936, 1940, 1944 Stigler, G. 1869, 1895 Stiglitz, J.E. 2003, 2024 Stinchcombe, M.B. 1548, 1596 Stokey, N.L. 1915, 1926, 1927, 1930, 1945 Stone, H. 1745, 1758 Stone, J.J. 2343, 2351 Stone, R.E. 1731, 1749, 1756 Straffin Jr., P.D. 2030, 2053, 2070n, 2076, 2253, 2254, 2259n, 2268 Strnad, J. 2206, 2228 Sudderth, W. 1829-1831, 1848, 1849 Sudh61ter, P. 1704, 1720, 1740, 1757 Suh, S.-C. 2319, 2325 Sun, Y.N. 1770n, 1771-1776, 1776n, 1777, 1777n, 1778, 1778n, 1779-1781, 1781n, 1782, 1782n, 1783-1785, 1785n, 1786, 1786n, 1787-1790, 1790n, 1791, 1791n, 1792-1794, 1794n, 1795-1830 Sundaram, R. 1813, 1830 Sutton, J. 1941n, 1942, 1993n, 2024 Swinkels, J.M. 1553, 1554, 1594, 1627, 1632, 1661, 1662 Sykes, A.O. 2268 Takahashi, I. 1917, 1926, 1945 Talagrand, M. 1782n, 1807 Talley, E. 1908, 1942, 2247n, 2263 Talman, A.J.J. 1704, 1706, 1721, 1725, 1726, 1745, 1749, 1750, 1755, 1759 Tan, T.C.-C. 1551, 1594, 1663 Tang, E-E 2319, 2321 Tarski, A. 1527, 1596 Tatamitani, Y. 2294, 2297, 2318, 2325 Tanman, Y. 1714, 1719, 2131, 2133, 2137, 2151, 2152, 2161, 2165-2167 Tegler, A.I. 2338, 2351 Telser, L. 1998, 2024 Thisse, J. 1717, 1719 Thomas, M.U. 1955, 1956, 1973, 1986 Thomas, R.E 1999, 2023 Thompson, EB. 1646, 1663 Thomson, W. 2119, 2262n, 2268, 2277n, 2325 Thuijsman, E 1827, 1832, 1837, 1843, 1844, 1846, 1849, 1850 Tian, G. 1793n, 1808, 2279n, 2297, 2325 Tijs, S.H. 1529, 1530, 1595, 1700, 1717, 1719, 1721, 1750, 1756, 1825, 1832, 2051, 2052 Tirole, J. 1551, 1592, 1659, 1774n, 1800, 1853n, 1858n, 1861n, 1868n, 1878n, 1894, 1895,
Author Index
1-13
1899, 1910-1912, 1914, 1926, 1943, 1944, 1994n, 2022,2232,2266,2316,2323 Todd, M.J. 1734, 1759 Tomlin, J.A. 1756,1759 Topkis, D. 1529,1596 Torunczyk, H. 1843, 1850 Touss~nt, S. 1783n, 1793n, 1808 Townsend, R. 2276n, 2304, 2322, 2325 Tracy, J.S. 1938-1940, 1942, 1943, 1945 Treble, J. 1995,2013,2024 Tnck, M. 2293,2325 Tsitsiklis, J.N. 1745,1757 Tuchman, B. 2232n, 2266 Tucker, A.W. 1763, 1763n, 1804,2164 Turnbull, S. 2316, 2317, 2323 Turner, D. 1868, 1893 Tversky, A. 2346, 2349
Vincent, D.R. 1899, 1923,1937,1945 Vishny, R. 2012, 2023 Vives, X. 1529,1596,1789n, 1795n, 1797n, 1805, 1808, 2297,2323 Vohra, R. 1680,1685,1793n, 1795n, 1796n, 1803, 2297,2312,2322,2325 von Neumann, J. 1523,1526, 1543, 1594, 1606, 1609, 1646,1663,1681, 1686, 1689,1721, 1763, 1787n, 1790n, 1808, 2036, 2053 von Stackelberg, H. 1977,1986 yon Stengel, B. 1725,1726,1740,1743,1745, 1749, 1750, 1752-1757, 1759, 1972-1974, 1984,1986 Vorobiev, N.N. 1699,1701,1721,1743,1759 Vfieze, O.J. 1825-1827, 1831, 1832,1837, 1843, 1844,1849, 1850 Vroman, S.B. 1936,1945
UhlJE, J.J. 1780n, 1781-1784, 1784n, 1785, 1786,1786n, 1787-1939 Ulen, T. 2236, 2264 Umegaki, H. 1785n, 1801
Wald, A. 1765, 1765n, 1800, 1808, 2144, 2163 Wallmeier, H.-M. 1704, 1720, 1740, 1757 Wang, G.H. 2268 Weber, M. 1992n, 2024 Weber, R.J. 1539, 1594, 1773, 1774n, 1775n, 1781n, 1789n, 1805, 2045, 2053, 2060, 2061, 2066-2069, 2069n, 2070, 2075, 2076, 2081, 2116, 2120, 2152, 2153, 2163, 2167 Weibull, J. 1524, 1527, 1528, 1590, 1596, 2222, 2228 Weiman, D.E 2010, 2020n, 2024 Weingast, B.R. 1994n, 1995n, 1999, 1999n, 2005, 2012n, 2014, 2023, 2024, 2210, 2228, 2268 Weinrich, G. 1796n, 1808 Weiss, A. 1566, 1592 Weiss, B. 1539, 1590, 1774n, 1789n, 1798 Weissing, E 1955, 1987 Wen-Tstin, W. 1663 Werlang, S. 1551, 1594 Wettstein, D. 2048, 2053, 2297, 2324, 2325 Whinston, M.D. 1585, 1586, 1590, 2177n, 2183, 2273, 2320 White, M.J. 2231n, 2239n, 2268 Whitt, W. 1813, 1831 Wieczorek, A. 1797n, 1808 Wilde, L.L. 1954, 1986, 2232n, 2267, 2276n, 2321 Wilkie, S. 2297, 2315, 2318, 2321 Williams, S.R. 1789n, 1795n, 1807, 1900, 1902, 1906, 1906n, 1945, 2285, 2285n, 2325, 2326 WiUiamson, S.H. 1991n, 2024 Wilson, C. 1588, 1596
V~adier, M. 1773n, 1780n, 1782n, 1794n, 1799, 1808 van Damme, E.E.C. 1524, 1529, 1533, 1548, 1550-1553,1565,1566,1571,1576, 1579, 1584, 1585,1588,1590, 1591,1595, 1600, 1606,1608,1628,1631,1640,1648,1663, 1691,1693,1695,1721,1725,1740,1759 van den Elzen, A.H. 1704, 1721, 1725, 1726, 1739,1745,1749, 1750,1755, 1759 van Hulle, C. 2268 Vannetelbosch, V.J. 1660 Vardi, M.Y. 1681,1682,1684,1685 Varian, H. 1873,1873n, 1895,2292,2325 Varopoulos, N.Th. 1771n, 1799 Vaughan, H.E. 1771, 1801 Vega-Redondo, E 1524,1596 Veitch, J.M. 1998,2024 VeUanovski, CJ. 2243n, 2268 Vermeulen, A.J. 1564, 1565, 1589, 1593, 1595, 1647, 1660,1662,1663, 1721,1745, 1750, 1757,1759 Veronesi, R 1658 Vial, J.-E 1531, 1594, 1614, 1661, 1711, 1714, 1715,1720,1795n, 1800 Vickrey, W. 1795n, 1808 Vieille, N. 1717, 1718, 1721, 1827, 1832, 1836, 1839, 1842,1846, 1846n, 1849,1850 Vinas-Boas, J.M. 1875n, 1895
1-14 Wilson, R.B. 1534, 1535, 1540-1542, 1544, 1549,1550,1565-1567, 1592,1593,1596, 1618,1627,1629, 1645,1659,1661,1663, 1680,1686,1696,1721,1725,1739,1742, 1745-1748,1750,1752,1755,1759,1862, 1868n, 1894, 1899n, 1906n, 1910,1912, 1913n, 1914, 1915,1917,1923,1927,1928, 1936,1937,1939,1943-1945 Winkels, H.-M. 1701,1706,1721,1744,1759 Winston, W. 1813,1832 Winter, E. 2040-2043, 2048, 2049,2052, 2053, 2075, 2076,2095, 2120, 2171,2184 Winter, R. 2236,2268 Wittman, D. 2232n, 2236,2268,2269 Woff, G. 2332,2341,2350, 2351 Wolfowitz, J. 1765,1765n, 1800,1808, 2144, 2163 Wofinsky, A. 1542,1595,2315n, 2317,2325 W611ing, A. 1961, 1987 Wooders, M.H. 1796n, 1802,2167,2181,2184 Wu, W.-T. 1696, 1721 Yamashige, S. 1776n, 1777,1777n, 1806,1808 Yamato, T. 2287n, 2294,2297,2318,2325,2326
Author Index
Yang, Z. 1706,1721 Yannelis, N.C. 1785n, 1793n, 1794,1795, 1795n, 1796-2042 Yanovskaya, E.B. 1745, 1755, 1759 Yavas, A. 2301, 2325 Ye, T.X. 2075,2076 Yoshise, A. 1756,1757 Young, H.E 1580, 1596, 2033, 2051, 2054, 2113, 2120, 2167,2269 Zame, W.R. 1530, 1550, 1583, 1590, 1595, 1596, 1629, 1658, 2167, 2181, 2184 Zamir, S. 1661, 1669, 1673, 1675, 1679, 1680, 1682, 1686, 1809, 1813, 1816, 1823n, 1828, 1830, 1831, 1843, 1850, 1980, 1984 Zang, I. 2167 Zangwill, W.I. 1749, 1757 Zarzuelo, J.M. 2167 Zeckhauser, R. 1915, 1945 Zemel, E. 1745, 1756, 1757 Zemsky, RB. 2245, 2263 Zermelo, E. 1543, 1596 Zeuthen, E 2341, 2351 Ziegler, G.M. 1727, 1736, 1759
SUBJECT INDEX
allocation, 2051 allocation core, 2218 almost complementary, 1701 almost completely labeled, 1733 almost strictly competitive games, 1711 alternating offer, 1918, 1921, 1925, 1926, 1929, 1933 alternating-offer game, 1909, 1920 amendment procedure, 2212 amendment voting procedure, 2210 AN, 2128 animal behavior, 2340 APE, 1920 arms control, 1950 Arms Control and Disarmament Agency (ACDA), 1951 artificial equilibrium, 1733 assuredly perfect equilibrium, 1918 ASYMP, 2124 ASYMP*, 2134 ASYMP*(~), 2154 ASYMP(~), 2154 asymptotic ~-semivalue, 2154 asymptotic value, 2124, 2135, 2152, 2174 atomless vector measure, 1780 atoms, 1765 attribute sampling, 1951 auction mechanisms, 2344 auctions, 1680, 1908 auditing, 1952 augmented semantic belief system, 1670 Aumann, 2039, 2040, 2044, 2172 Aumann and Shapley, 2172 Aumann-Shapley value, 2151 Ausubel, 1910, 1933-1935 axiom, 2027, 2029 axiomatic characterization, 2181
v-path extension, 2155 K-committee equilibrium, 2216 /x-measure-preserving automorphism, 2157 /x-symmetric, 2157 /x-value, 2125, 2157, 2180 w-potential function, 2064 7r random order coalitional structure value, 2074 7r-coalitional structure value, 2073 Jr-coalitional symmetry axiom, 2073 rr-efficient, 2072 re-symmetric, 2072, 2155, 2156 rr-symmetric value, 2155 ~-value, 2072 a-additive, 1682 a-field, 1669 Abreu-Matsushima mechanisms, 2301 absolute certainty, 167 l absolutely continuous, 2161 absorbing state, 1812, 1814, 1843 AC, 2161 additive, 2058 additivity, 2029 additivity axiom, 2058 adjudication, 2249 Admati, 1922, 1923, 1938 Admati-Perry, 1935 administrative agencies, 2249 admissibility, 1619-1621, 1653 affinely independent, 1727 agency relations, 2002 agenda independence, 2213 agenda manipulation, 2344 agenda-independent outcome, 2211, 2212, 2214 agendas, 2207, 2210 agent normal form, 1541 Agreement Theorem, 1676 agreement/integer mechanism, 2286 airport, 2051 Akerlof, 1905, 1906 Akerlof's lemons problem, 1588 alarm, 1957
backward induction, 1523, 1621-1634, 1650-1653, 1682 backward induction implementation, 2292 backward induction procedure, 1543 1-15
Subject Index
1-16 balanced contribution, 2036 Banach space, 1781 bankruptcy, 2259-2262 banks, 2012 Banzhaf, 2253 Banzhaf index, 2031, 2254-2258 bargaining, 1899, 2046, 2047, 2342 bargaining games, 2338 bargaining mechanisms, 1899, 1934 bargaining problems, 1587 bargaining set, 2249 bargaining with incomplete information, 1680 basic solution, 1737 basic variables, 1737 basis, 1737 battle of the sexes, 1553, 1567, 1689 Bayesian, 1875 Bayesian monotonicity, 2305 Bayesian rational, 1713 beat-the-average, 2341 behavior strategy, 1616, 1753, 1910 behavior strategy si, 1541 belief hierarchies, 1669 belief morphism, 1674 beliefs, 1667 Bertrand, 1857, 1858, 1870, 1878, 1879, 1882, 1886 best elements, 2308 best reply, 1525 best-reply correspondence, 1525 best-response function, 1777 best-response region, 1731 best-response-equivalent, 1711 big match, 1814 bilateral monopoly, 2341 bilateral reputation mechanism, 2014 bimatrix game, 1689 binary amendment procedures, 2293 binary voting tree, 2208 binding inequality, 1727, 1736 bluff, 2347 Bochner integral, 1782 Borel determinacy, 1829 bounded edges, 1702 bounded mechanisms, 2296 bounded variation, 2128 breach of contract, 2237 bromine industry, 2011 budget balancing, 1901 business games, 2339 buyer-offer, 1921, 1926
buyer-offer game, 1909 BV, 2128 bv1FA, 2130, 2147 briM, 2124, 2130 bvINA, 2123, 2130 canonical, 1672 Caratheodory's extension theorem, 1787 Carreras, 2050 carrier, 1691, 2030 cartier axiom, 2059 Cauchy distributions, 2142 cautiously rationalizable strategy, 1604 cell and truncation consist, 1574 cell in, 1574 centroid of, 1574 chain store paradox, 1543 Champsanr, 2172 chaos theorems, 2207 characteristic functions, 2331 Chatterjee, 1905, 1934 cheap talk, 2225 Chiu, 2049 Cbo, 1935 Chun, 2036, 2037 cliometrics, 1991 closed, 1674 closed rule, 2225, 2226 coalition, 2000, 2041-2043, 2058, 2127 coalition of partners, 2063 coalition structure, 2039, 2041, 2072, 2155 coalition-proof Nash equilibrium, 1585 coalitional, 2028 Coase, 1908, 1917, 2241 Coase Conjecture, 1917, 1921, 1924, 1927, 1928, 1935, 1937 Coase Strong Efficient Bargaining Claim, 2243, 2245 Coase Theorem, 2241-2245, 2247-2249 Coase Theorem and incomplete information, 2245 Coase Weak Efficient Bargaining Claim, 2243 coherent, 1674 collectivist equilibrium, 2017 collusion, 1869-1872, 1877, 1879-1882, 1884, 1885, 2011 combinatorial standard form, 1828 commitment, 1908 commitment power, 1977 common interest games, 1571 common knowledge, 1576, 1671, 1713, 2342 common knowledge of rationality, 1624, 1656
Subject Index common prior, 1675 communication and signalling, 1680 community responsibility system, 2005 compact, 1677 comparative negligence, 2234, 2236 comparison system. 2113 complementary pivoting, 1736, 1738 complementary slackness, 1730 complete, 1674 complete information, 2342 completely consistent, 2112 completely labeled, 1731, 1743 completely mixed, 1697 completeness assumption, 1613 CONs, 2 150 conjectural assessment, 1713 conjectural variations, 1872, 1882-1885 connected sets of equilibria, 1644 consastency. 1529, 1589, 2034, 2047, 2109 consistency conditions, 1669 consistent, 1549, 1679. 2035, 2065 consistent beliefs, 2313 consistent NTU-value, 2181 consistent probabilities, 1828 consistent solution payoff configuration, 2113 consistent system of beliefs, 1626 consistent value, 2111, 2113 consistent with n, 2074 constant-sum game, 2189 contestable market, 1882 contested-garment problem, 2260 contested-garment solution, 2261 contested-garment-consistent, 2260 context, 2329 context independence, 1573 context-specific model, 1994, 1996, 2000 continuity, 2128.2151 continuum of agents. 2172, 2192 contract, 1938, 1939, 2238 contract enforcement, 1999 contract negotiations, 1940 contraction mapping, 1816 contraction principle, 1816 controlling player, 1826 convex, 2049 cooperation, 2028 cooperation index, 2074 cooperation structures, 2039 cooperative game, 2027, 2123 cooperative refinements, 1586 Copeland rule, 2292
1-17 core, 2116, 2159, 2179, 2200. 2205, 2248, 2336 correlated equilibrium, 1530, 1600, 1612-1615. 1681. 1690, 1710 correlated strategy, 1709 correlatedly rationalizable strategy, 1601 costs, 2051 counteroffers, 1908 Cournot, 1855, 1858, 1877, 1878, 1881-1883, 1886 Cottrnot-Nash equilibrium distribution, 1775 Cramton, 1907, 1934, 1935 cultural beliefs, 2017 culture, 2016 curb sets, 1527 Dasgupta, 2049 data verification, 1965 debt repudiation, 1998 deceptions, 2305 delegation game. 2250 demand commitment, 2049 democracy, 2189 Deneckere, 1910, 1933-1935 Derks, 2044 D1AG, 2136, 2147 diagonal, 2152 diagonal formula, 2141, 2151 diagonal property, 2125, 2151 DIFF, 2147 DIFF(y). 2155 differentiable case, 2173 diffuse types, 2304 diffused characteristics, 1773 dimension, 1727 direct evidence, 1995, 2010 disagreement region, 2308 disarmament, 1950 discontinuity of knowledge, 1685 discount factor, 1811, 2046 discounted game, 1811 dispersed characteristics, 1773 dissolution of partnerships, 1907 dissolved, 1907. 1908 distribution of a correspondence, 1771 distributive pofitics, 2212 dividend equilibrium, 2197 dividends, 2034, 2197 dollar auction game, 2338 dominance-solvable, 1529 dominated strategy, 1600 domination, 1693 double implementation, 2318
1-18 Downsian model, 2220 Dr~ze, 2039, 2040 duality theorem of linear programming, 1728 Dubey, 2037, 2038 duel, 1975 dummy, 2029, 2040, 2058 dummy player axiom, 2058, 2128 duopolistic competition, 2015 durability, 2316 durable goods monopoly, 1899, 1930 duration, 1936 dynamic, 1934 dynamic bargaining, 2317 dynamic bargaining game, 1906 dynamic programming, 1824 East India Company, 2015 economic mechanisms, 2340 economic-political models, 2187 edge, 1701 Edgeworth's 1881 conjecture, 1764 efficiency, 1900-1902, 2123, 2124, 2151 efficiency axiom, 2059 effÉcient, 1908, 1934, 2059, 2128, 2188 Egalitarian solution, 2100, 2102, 2108 Egalitarian value, 2100, 2101 elaborates, 1673 elbow room assumption, 2197 Electors, 2049 elementary cells, 1574 elimination of strictly dominated strategies, 1604 emotion, 2347 empirical, 1941 empirical evidence, 1936 endogenous expectation, 1572 endogenous institutional change, 2018, 2019 entitlement, 2242, 2244 entry deterrence, 1680, 1853, 1859-1861, 1867, 1868, 1885 epistemic conditions for equilibrium, 1654-1657 epistemology, 1681 equal treatment, 2197 equicontinuous family, 1778 equilibrium enumeration, 1742 equilibrium payoff, 1835 equilibrium refinement, 1617, 1619 equilibrium selection, 1524, 1572, 1619, 1691, 1996 equilibrium set, 1827 ergodic theorem, 1815, 1829 error of the second kind, 1958
Subject Index ESBORA theory, 1588 essential monotonicity, 2287 European state, 2006 event, 1667 evolutionary game theory, 1607 ex post efficient, 1903 ex post efficient trade, 1903 exact potential, 1529 exchangeable, 1700 existence of equilibrium, 1611, 1612 expectation, 2238 experimental law, 2345 experimental matrix games, 2329 experiments, 1941 extended solution, 2065 extended unanimity, 2309 extension operator, 2141 extensive form, 2332 extensive form correlated equilibria, 1820 extensive form games, 1523, 1615 extensive games, 1681 external symmetry, 2331
FA, 2128 face, 1727 facet, 1727 fair, 2072 fair allocation rule, 2072 fair ranking, 2037 false alarm, 1957 false alarm probability, 1960 Fatou's lemma, 1772 fear of rnin, 2191 Fedzhora, 2050 fiduciary decisions, 2346 financial systems, 2011 finite extensive fon'a games with perfect recall, 1540 finitely additive, 2128 finitely additive measure, 1770 First Theorem of Welfare Economics, 2196 fixed points, 1534 fixed prices, 2196 fixed-price economies, 2187 focal points, 2343 Folk Theorem, 1565, 1910, 1925, 1933 formation, 1575 forward induction, 1524, 1554, 1566, 1634, 1635, 1645, 1648-1653 Fourier transform, 2142 Fragnelli, 2051 Fubini's theorem, 1767
Subjectlndex fully stable set of equilibria, 1561 fully stable sets, 1646 gains from trade, 1902 game form, 1541 game in normal form, 1525 game in standard form, 1573 game over the unit square, 1975 game theory, 1523 game with common interests, 1576 game with private information, 1773 games in coalitional form, 2336 games of survival, 1823 games with perfect information, 1543 games with strategic complementaries, 1529 gang of four, 1680 gap, 1914, 1915, 1917, 1923, 1925, 1926, 1928, 1933 Garcia-Jurado, 2050 Gelfand integral, 1781 general case, 2173 general claim problem, 2260 general existence theorem, 1827 general minmax theorem, 1829 (general) semantic belief system, 1670 generalized solution function, 2105 generalized value, 2097, 2098 generic, 1740 generic equivalence of perfect and sequential equilibrium, 1629 generic insights, 1993, 1996 geometry of market games, 2178 Gibbons, 1907 globally consistent, 2112 Golan, 2050 good correlated equilibrium, 1711 Groves mechanism, 1901 Gul, 2046 H I, 2159 ! H+, 2159 H-stable set of equilibria, 1564 Hadley v. Baxendale, 2239 Hahn-Banach theorem, 1683 Harsanyi, 2042, 2045, 2180 Harsanyi and Selten, 1574 Harsanyi doctrine, 1606 Harsanyi NTU, 2092 Harsanyi NTU value, 2175 Harsanyi NTU value payoff, 2091 Harsanyi solution, 2093
1-19 Harsanyi solution correspondence, 2093 Harsanyi-Shapley NTU value, 2193 Hart, 2034, 2035, 2040, 2046-2048, 2172, 2180 hierarchy, 2043 historical context, 1993 history, 1910 holdouts, 1938-1940 holds in, 1670 homogeneous, 2058 homotopy, 1749 Hurwicz, 2273 hyperplane game, 2110, 2111, 2113 hyperplane game form, 2107 hyperstable set, 1646 hyperstable set of equilibria, 1561 i's expected payoff, 1541 ideal coalitions, 2124 ideal games, 2141 idiosyncratic shocks, 1790 amperfect competition, 2182 imperfect monitoring, 1846, 1877, 1878 amplementation theory, 2273 Impossibility, 2239 mcentive compatibility, 1900, 1904, 2277 incentive compatible, 1900 mcentive consistency, 2312 incomplete information, 1665, 1843, 1899, 1980, 2117 mcomplete information domain, 2302 incredible threats, 1523 independence hypothesis, 1769 independence, statistical, 1602 index of power, 2069 indirect evidence, 1995, 2010 indirect monotoincity, 2290 individual rationality, 1901, 2316 individualist equilibrium, 2017 inefficiency, 1905 inferior, 1575 infinite conjunctions mad disjunctions, 1685 infinite regress, 1679 infinite repetition, 1689 infinitely repeated games, 2020 infinitesimal minor players, 1764 infinitesimal subset, 2187 infinitesimally close, 1788 informal contract enforcement, 2000 informal contract enforcement institution, 2004 information partition, 1671 information set, 1671, 1750 mspectee, 1949
1-20 inspection, 1680 mspection games, 1949 inspector, 1949 institutional foundations of exchange, 2000 institutional trajectories, 2017 ansurance, 1953 mteger games, 2320 interactive analysis, 1994 interactive belief systems, 1654 interactive implementation, 2315 interdependent, 1905 interdependent values, 1909, 1923, 1924 interim utility, 2303 interiority, 2310 internal, 2130 International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA), 1950 international relations, 2016 international trade, 2014 intuitive criterion, 1862 invariant cylinder probabilities, 2148 issue-by-issue procedure, 2213, 2214 iterated dominance, 1600-1604, 1619-1621 iteratively undominated strategy, 1601 Jackson (1991), 2309 Japan, 2013 joint continuity, 1817 judicial review, 2249 Kakutani's fixed point theorem, 1767 Kalai, 2039 Karl Vind, 2285 King Solomon's Dilemma, 2283 Klemperer, 1907 Knesset, 2051 knowledge, 1671 Kuhn's theorem, 1616 Kurz, 2040 label, 1731 labor, 1938 labor relations, 2013 large non-anonymous games, 1773 law, 2012 Law Merchant system, 2005 leadership, 1977, 1980, 1981 learning, 2333 legislation game, 2250 Lemke's algorithm, 1749 Lemke-Howson algorithm, 1535, 1733, 1739, 1748
Subject Index level structure, 2043 Levy, 2046 lexico-minimum ratio test, 1741, 1747, 1748 lexicographic method, 1741 liability rules, 2242, 2244 liability with contributory negligence, 2235 limit price, 1859-1861, 1865, 1866 limit pricing, 1859, 1861, 1867 limited rationality, 2331 limiting values, 2123, 2133 limits of sequences, 2181 LINs, 2150 linear, 2058 linear complementarity problem (LCP), 1731 linear tracing procedure, 1580, 1581 linear-quadratic, 1927 linearity, 2124, 2151 linearity axiom, 2058 Lipschitz condition, 1914 Lipschitz potential, 2105, 2107 local strategy, 1541 Loeb counting measure, 1789 Loeb measure spaces, 1787 logarithmic trace, 1583 logarithmic tracing procedure, 1580, 1583 long-distance trade, 2014 losing coalition, 2069 LP duality, 1730 Lyapunov, 1820 Lyapunov's theorem, 1780 M, 2128 M-stability, 1564 Maghribi traders, 2001 majoritarian preferences, 2311 majority, 2031 majority rule, 2224 marginal contributions, 2033, 2059, 2111 marginal worth, 2187 marginality, 2113 market, 2173 market clearance, 2196 market entry games, 1587 market games, 2125 market structure, 1996, 1997, 2009 Markov, 1811 Markov decision processes, 1824 marriage lemma, 1771 Mas-Colell, 2034, 2035, 2047, 2048, 2172 Maskin, 2273 mass competition, 1763
1-21
Subject Index mass markets, 2331 material accountancy, 1951, 1962 Material Unaccounted For (MUF), 1951 maximal Nash subsets, 1744 maxmin, 1690, 1847 measurability, 2312 measurable selection, 1771 measure-based values, 2157, 2180 measurement error, 1962, 1966 mechanism continuity, 2318 mechanism design, 1899, 1908 memory, 2335 merchant guild, 2015 Mertens value, 2180 Milnor axiom, 2059 Milnor operator, 2059 minimal curb set, 1568, 1570 minimax theory, 2334 minimum ratio test, 1737, 1741 missing label, 1734 M/X, 2124 mixed extension, 1609-1611 mixed strategy, 1525, 1680, 1690, 1726, 2334 mixed-strategy equilibrium, 1766, 1873, 1875, 1876 mixing value, 2124, 2140, 2152 modal logic, 1681 model, 1670 modularity, 2038 modulo game, 2309 monopoly, 2010 monotone, 2058 monotonic, 2128 monotonicity, 2033, 2282 monotonicity-no-veto, 2309 moral hazard, 1952 Morelli, 2049 Mount-Reiter diagram, 2275 multi-member districts, 2253, 2257 multilateral reputation mechanism, 2014 multilinear extension, 2096, 2144 multiple equilibria, 1524, 1610 mutual knowledge, 1681, 1685 Myerson, 1903, 1904, 1907, 1934, 2036, 2044, 2048
~NA, 2123 NA, 2128 Nakamura number, 2205 Nash, 2045 Nash Bargaining Solution, 2083, 2099, 2l 14
Nash equilibrium, 1523, 1528, 1599, 2279 Nash equilibrium in pure strategies, 1689 Nash implementation, 2278, 2279 Nash product property, 1587 Nash-Harsanyi value, 2341 natural sentences, 1670, 1674 negligence, 2233, 2235 negligence with contributory negligence, 2233, 2234, 2236 negligible, 1763 neutrality, 2032 Neyman, 2039 Neyman-Pearson lemma, 1961, 1963-1965, 1983 no delay, 1929 no free screening, 1928, 1929 no gap, 1925-1927, 1929, 1933 no veto power, 2282, 2285 Non-Proliferation Treaty (NPT), 1951 nonatomic, 1820, 2123 nonbasic variables, 1737 noncooperative games, 1523, 2045 nondegenerate, 1701, 1732, 1739-1741 nondetection probability, 1959 nondifferentiable case, 2178 nonempty lower intersection, 2281 nonexclusive information, 2303 nonexclusive public goods, 2195 nonmarket institutions, 1992 nonstationary equilibria, 1930 nonsymmetric values, 2154 nonzero-sum, 1818 nonzero-sum games, 1842 norm-continuity, 1821 normal form, 1524, 1541, 1814 normal form perfect equilibrium, 1628, 1653 normative procedures, 2347 normative theory, 1523 NP-hard, 1756 NTU game, 2079 NTU game form, 2105 NTU value, 2194 nuclear test ban, 1950 nucleolus, 2248 null, 2058 null hypothesis, 1957, 1966 null player axiom, 2058, 2123 offer/counteroffer, 1910, 1911 offers, 1908 Old Regime France, 20l 1, 2013 one person, one vote, 2253, 2254, 2256
1-22 One-House Veto Game, 2251 open rule, 2225, 2226 operator, 2058 optimal threat, 2189 ordinal potential, 1528 ordinal vs. cardinal, 2182 ordinality, noncooperative, 1636-1638 organizations, 2017 origin of the state, 2006 outcome, 1541 Owen, 2040-2042, 2050, 2051 Owen's multilinear extension, 2153 ownership, 1908 p-Shapley NTU value payoff, 2090 p-Shapley correspondence, 2091 p-Shapley value, 2081, 2116 p-type coalition, 2063 Pacios, 2050 parallel information sets, 1752 parliamentary government, 2008 partially symmetric values, 2125, 2154 participation constraints, 1900 partition, 2043 partition value, 2151, 2152 partitional game, 2073 partnership, 1907, 1908 partnership axiom, 2063 path, 2155 path value, 2057 payoff configuration, 2091 payoff dominance, 1577 payoff dominance criterion, 1585 Perez-Castrillo, 2048 perfect, 1748, 1756 perfect Bayesian equilibrium, 1550 perfect equilibrium, 1523, 1547, 1618, 1628-1634, 1692, 2338 perfect information, 1824 perfect recall, 1541, 1616, 1752 perfect sample, 2190 perfectly competitive, 2172 permutation, 2058 Perry, 1922, 1923, 1938 persistent equilibrium, 1524, 1569, 1571 persistent rationality, 1544 persistent retracts, 1568 personal (or non-pecuniary) injury, 2236 perturbation, 1681 Peters, 2044 pFA, 2129
Subject Index pivot, 2070 pivotal, 2030 pivotal information, 2224 pivoting, 1736, 1737 planning procedures, 2346 player set, changes in, 1639, 1640 players, 2058, 2127 pNA, 2123, 2129 pNA I, 2159 pNAO~), 2156 pNAee, 2123, 2130 pM, 2129 podest~t, 2007 political games, 2044 political value, 2044 pollution control, 1955 polyhedi'on, 1727, 1734 polytope, 1727, 1743 pooling equilibrium, 1863, 1865-1867 populous games, 1763 positive, 2059, 2128 positively weighted value ~0c°, 2063 positivity, 2123, 2124, 2151 positivity axiom, 2059 potential, 2034, 2103 potential games, 1528 pre-play communication, 1585, 2316 pre-play negotiation, 1606 predation, 1860, 1861, 1866-1868, 1882, 1886 preferences, 2031, 2332 price formation, 2339 price rigidities, 2196 price wars, 1870, 1871, 1877, 1878, 1881 primitive formations, 1575 principal-agent problems, 1680, 1953 prior expectations p, 1584 prisoner's dilemma, 1690 private values, 1909, 1912 probabilistic values, 2057, 2059 probability space, 1681 Prohorov metric, 1778 projection, 2058 projection ~iom, 2058, 2151 prominent point, 2343 proper equilibrium, 1523, 1552, 1619, 1629-1634 proper Nash equilibrium, 1700 property rights, 1908, 1996, 1998, 2008, 2014 property rules, 2242, 2244 proportional solution, 2101
Subject Index public, 2051 public goods, 2187 public goods economy, 2192 public goods without exclusion, 2192 public signals, 1820 Puiseux-series, 1821 pure bargaining problem, 2080 pure equilibrium, 1689 pure exchange economy, 2173 pure strategies, 1525 pure strategy Nash equilibrium, 1768 purely atomic, 1820 purification, 1537, 1765, 1875 purification of mixed strategies, 1608 purification of mixed strategy equilibria, 1539 quantal response equilibrium, 2319 quasi-concave, 1716 quasi-perfect equilibrium, 1548, 1628, 1630 quasi-strict, 1693 quasi-strict equilibria, 1529 quasivalues, 2057, 2154 quitting games, 1844 railroad cartel, 2010 random variable, 1770 random-order value, 2057, 2061, 2081 randomization, 1765 Rapoport, 2050 rational, 1713 rationalizability, 1600-1605 rationalizable strategy, 1601 rationalizable strategy profiles, 1527 reaction functions, 1856, 1859 reaction to risk, 2346 realization equivalent, 1541, 1754 realization plan, 1753, 1754 recursive games, 1823, 1828 recursive inspection game, 1969, 1971, 1973 redistribution, 2187, 2189 reduced game, 2035, 2109 reduced strategic form, 1751 refined Nash implementation, 1523 refinements of Nash equilibrium, 1523, 2288 regular, 1675 regular equilibrium, 1532, 1608, 1695 regular map, 1695 regular semantic belief system, 1675 regulations, 1996, 1997, 2013 relative risk aversion, 2192 relatively efficient, 2072
1-23 reliance, 2237, 2238 remain silent, 1929 renegotiation, 1586, 2314 renegotiation-proof equilibrium, 2014 repeated game, 1689, 1843, 1869, 1870, 1872, 1873, 1877-1879, 1882, 1884 repeated game with incomplete information, 1680, 1813 repeated prisoner's dilemma, 1680 replacement, 1939 replicas, 2181 representative democracy, 2220 reproducing, 2130 reputation, 2010 reputational price strategy, 1931 restrictable, 2131 retract R, 1568 revelation principle, 2304 risk, 2032 risk aversion, 2192 risk dominance, 1524, 1576-1578, 1580 robots, 2340 robust best response, 1569 robustness, 2318 Roth, 2031, 2032 Rubinstein, 1909, 1933, 1938 S-allocation, 2188
sINA, 2162 saddlepoint, 2333 Samet, 2039 sample space, 1681 Samuelson, 1905, 1934 satiation, 2196 Satterthwaite, 1903, 1904, 1907, 1934 scalar measure game, 2161 screening, 1936-1938, 1940 searching for facts, 2330 Seidmarm, 2050 selective elimination, 2305 self-enforcing, 1523 serf-enforcing agreement, 1540 self-enforcing assessments, 1608, 1609 self-enforcing plans, 1607, 1608 self-enforcing theory of rationality, 1526 seller-offer, 1917, 1925, 1933 seller-offer game, 1909, 1912, 1914 semantic, 1667 semantic belief system, 1667 semi-algebraic, 1821 semi-reduced normal form, 1541 semivalues, 2057, 2060, 2125, 2152
1-24 separable, 2215 separable preferences, 2214 separate continuity, 1817 separating equilibrium, 1863, 1865-1867 separating intuitive equilibrium, 1865 sequence form, 1750, 1753, 1755 sequential bargaining, 1909 sequential equilibrium, 1523, 1549, 1618, 1626-1628, 1910, 2312 sequential monotonicity-no-veto, 2313 sequential rationality, 1626 sequentially rational, 1549 set of best pure replies, 1691 set-valued solutions, 1642-1645 settlement, 1936 Shapley, 1731, 2027, 2172, 2180 Shapley correspondence, 2085 Shapley NTU value, 2092, 2174 Shapley NTU value payoff, 2084 Shapley value, 2114, 2123, 2187, 2248, 2253, 2262 Shapley value and nucleolus, 2249 Shapley-Shubik, 2027, 2254 Shapley-Shnbik index, 2254, 2255 Shapley~Shubik power index, 2254 sidepayments, 2336 signaling, 1918, 1921, 1936-1938, 1940 signaling games, 1565, 1571, 1588 signals, 1813 Silence Theorem, 1929 simple, 2058 simple games, 2030 simple polytope, 1727, 1740 simply stable, 1747 simply stable equilibrium, 1745 sincere voting, 2209 single crossing property, 1864 smuggler, 1955 so long sucker, 2338 social psychology, 2344 social utility function, 2187 solution T, 1558 solution concept, 1558 solution function, 2105, 2109 sophisticated sincerity, 2211 sophisticated voting, 2207, 2208 sophisticated voting equilibrium, 2215 Spanish Crown, 2008 speaking to theorists, 2330 stability, 1745 stability concepts, 1524
Subject Index stable equilibrium, 1696 stable set of equilibria, 1561 Stackelberg, 1882 stag hunt, 1576, 1579, 1603 standard form of a game, 1573 state of nature, 1811 state of the world, 1667 state space, 1667, 1811 state variable, 1912 states, 1667, 1933 static, 1909, 1934 static bargaining game, 1906 statiouarity, 1911, 1925, 1928, 1933 stationary, 1811, 1927, 1929 stationary equilibrium, 1840, 1910, 1914 stationary sequential equilibrium, 1929 statistical test, 1958 stochastic game, 1811, 1835 strategic complements, 1859 strategic equilibrium, 1599, 1606, 1679 strategic form, 2332 strategic form game, 1561 strategic stability, 1558, 1640-1653 strategic substitutes, 1859 strategically zero-sum games, 1711 strategy with finite memory, 1815 strategyproofness, 2280 strict equilibria, 1529 strict liability, 2233 strict liability with contributory negligence, 2233 strict liability with dual contributory negligence, 2234 strictly positive, 2063 strictly stable of index 1, 2142 strikes, 1899, 1936, 1937, 1939, 1940 strong efficiency claim, 2249 strong equilibrium, 1585 strong law of large numbers, 1683 strong positivity, 2128, 2151 strong-Markov, 1927 strongly positive, 2151 structure-induced equilibrium, 2216 sub-classes, 2037 subgame, 1541, 1572 subgame perfect, 1977, 2047 subgame perfect equilibrium, 1523, 1545, 1625, 1817 subgame perfect implementation, 2289 subsidy, 1739 subsolution, 1531 sunspot equilibria, 1820
Subjectlndex superadditive, 2058 supermodular, 2116 support, 1726, 1742, 2129 swing, 2070 switching control, 1825 symmetric, 2059, 2128 symmetric information, 1813 symmetrized, 1775 symmetry, 2029, 2040, 2124, 2151 symmetry axiom, 2059 syntactic, 1667 syntactic belief system, 1669 syntactically commonly known, 1677 system of beliefs, 1549 tableau, 1737 taking of property, 2239 takings, 2240 Tarski's elimination theorem, 1821 tax inspection, 1954 tax policy, 2191 taxation, 2187, 2189 taxonomy, 2335 test allocation, 2288 test statistic, 1963 theorem of the maximum, 1913 theory of rational behavior, 1523 timeliness games, 1974 tracing procedure, 1524, 1580, 1748 transaction costs, 2241, 2242, 2244, 2247, 2336 transfer, 2057, 2069 transition probability, 1811 triviality, 2037 truncation, 1910, 1911 truthful implementation, 2274 TU game, 2079 TU game form, 2106 Two-House Veto Game, 2251 two-house weighted majority game, 2136 two-person zero-sum game, 2329 two-sided incomplete information, 1934 type diversity, 2312 type structure, 1679 Uhl's theorem, 1784 ultimatum, 2338 unanimity rule, 2224 unbounded edge, 1702 underdevelopment trap, 2012 undiscounted game, 1822 undominated Nash equilibrium, 2294
1-25 unemployment, 2196 Uniform Coase Conjecture, 1928, 1929, 1932 uniform equilibria, 1827 uniformly discount optimal, 1824 uniformly perfect equilibria, 1547 uniformly perturbed game, 1574 union, 1899, 1937-1940, 2042 union contract negotiations, 1936 United States, 2049 universal, 1672, 1674 universal beliefs space, 1828 universal type space, 1828 utility function, 2031 value, xii, 2027, 2028, 2185, 2337 value allocations, 2187 value equivalence, 2171, 2175, 2188 value equivalence principle, 2117 value function, 1926 value inclusion, 2175 value principle, 2172 variable sampling, 1951 variation, 2128 variational potential, 2106, 2107 vector measure games, 2161 verification, 1950, 1982 via strong Nash equilibrium, 2319 violation, 1957 virtual implementation, 2297 voluntary implementation, 2316 voting, 2030, 2345 voting game, 2193 voting measure, 2193 voting power, 2253, 2256, 2258 voting system, 2256 w-Egalitarian solution, 2100 w-Egalitarian solution payoff, 2103 w-Egalitarian value payoff, 2100 w-Shapley correspondence, 2089, 2090 w-Shapley value, 2090 w-potential, 2104 wage negotiations, 2013 weak asymptotic ~-semivalue, 2153 weak asymptotic value, 2134, 2152 weak correlated equilibrium, 1714 weak efficiency claim, 2246 weak-Markov, 1927 weakly dominated, 1548 Weber, 2045 weight system, 2063 weight vectors, 2063
Subject Index
1-26 weighted majority game, 2136, 2162 weighted Nash Bargaining Solution, 2083 weighted Shapley NTU, 2088 weighted Shapley values, 2057, 2081 weighted value ~0w, 2064 weighted values, 2157 weighted voting, 2255, 2257, 2258 Wettstein, 2048 Williams, 2285
winning coalition, 2069 Winter, 2041-2043, 2049 Young, 2033, 2051 Young measures, 1794 zero transaction costs, 2242 zero-sum game, 1531, 1729, 1960, 1968