GOD AND THE
FUTURE
This page intentionally left blank
GOD AND THE
FUTURE Wolfhart Pannenberg's Eschatological Doctrine of God
CHRISTIAAN MOSTERT
T8.T C L A R K
A Continuum imprint LONDON
•
NEW YORK
T&T CLARK LTD A Continuum imprint 59 George Street Edinburgh EHi iLQ Scotland
370 Lexington Avenue New York 10017-6503 USA
www.tandtclark.co.uk
www.continuumbooks.com
Copyright © T&T Clark Ltd, 2002 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of T&T Clark Ltd. First published 2002 ISBNo 56708821 9 HB ISBNo 56708850 2 P B British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Typeset by Fakenham Photosetting Ltd Printed and bound in Great Britain by MPG Books, Bodmin
In memoriam Marijke Mostert 1944-1993
This page intentionally left blank
Contents Foreword Preface Abbreviations
ix xi xv
1. Eschatology in twentieth-century theology Introduction A shocking discovery Eschatology in non-historical form Eschatology in the key of promise Pannenberg's comprehensive eschatology
i 6 9 14 19
2. The appeal of apocalyptic Theology and apocalyptic The emerging picture of apocalyptic The kingdom of God in the message of Jesus The resurrection of Jesus from the dead Conclusion
27 32 38 43 53
3. An ontology of the whole Introduction The inter-disciplinary responsibility of theology Ontology - common province of theology and philosophy Reality as temporality Can there be a universal history?
55 58 62 69 79
4. The ontological priority of the future Introduction Being and appearance Contingency and connection Time and eternity The present as anticipation of the future
89 93 97 104 112
GOD AND THE FUTURE
5. The God of the future Introduction Early ideas about God God's futurity and eternity God and time Creation from the future An all-determining or determinist God?
127 129 141 152 161 175
6. The reign of the triune God Introduction A decisive turn to the Trinity The triune God The economic and the immanent Trinity The seal of God's futurity
183 187 201 213 225
Postscript
237
Bibliography
239
Index of Subjects
257
Index of Authors
261
Vlll
Foreword Concerning oneself with Christian doctrine, with its history and its conceptual ramifications, is one of the most fascinating intellectual adventures, not to speak of its profound spiritual depth. It is the satisfaction of teaching theology and of publishing on Christian doctrine to convey this enthusiasm to others. I hope that this book may succeed in achieving such an appreciation of studying Christian doctrine, as I experienced it myself through decades. It is a document of such an experience. The book describes impressively how basic issues of biblical exegesis like Jesus' teaching on the kingdom of God and the proclamation of his resurrection suggest the idea of God's kingdom, power and life to be future as well as eternal. It shows how this had to be elaborated with the help of hermeneutical and philosophical reflection. It also shows how the idea of God in terms of the power of the future requires for its explication a reinterpretation of the trinitarian doctrine of the church. I feel particularly satisfied to see this connection being highlighted as it is done in this book, and I am grateful for this contribution of the author. Wolfhart Pannenberg
IX
This page intentionally left blank
Preface The eschatological theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg has excited me and baffled me for over three decades. I have learnt important things from a wide range of theologians, but no influence has been greater than that of Pannenberg. I have only met him once, during a visit to Miinchen in January 1995, when, together with Philip Clayton, we had what Pannenberg described as 'eine intensive theologische Unterhaltung' in his study and over lunch in a restaurant. However, I do remember vividly the thrill I experienced when first reading his work on Christology, Jesus - God and Man, in Cambridge in the summer of 1971. Over the years, back in Australia and while teaching in Korea, I read other works by Pannenberg, mainly the volumes of essays. The three volumes of Systematic Theology were eagerly awaited and, though not the easiest to read and understand, they continue to illuminate many a theological problem. I have attempted to understand Pannenberg's theology, both in its development through four decades and in its most carefully formulated systematic form. Two things struck me particularly about it: the fact that the whole range of Christian doctrine must be understood as an expanded doctrine of God and that eschatology shapes the structure of every doctrine. The consequence of this is that eschatology must also have a decisive influence on the doctrine of God in the narrower sense. It is no accident that the idea of the reign (kingdom) of God and the understanding of God as Holy Trinity coincide exactly in Pannenberg's theology. Methodologically, I am drawn to Pannenberg's approach. Despite his recognition that all theological work is historically and geographically (as well as culturally and ecclesially) contextual, he does not abandon the question of the truth-claims inherent in theological statements. The question about the truth of Christian XI
GOD AND THE FUTURE
claims is assuredly not the only important question, but it is, in my view, the first question to ask. Pannenberg's theology exemplifies the way this question can become a significant part of constructive (systematic) theology. I am also drawn to his engagement with philosophy and the natural sciences, though these are never invested with the authority of establishing or refuting truth-claims in the province of theology. However, there are philosophical (ontological) implications in making theological assertions, and some of Pannenberg's most interesting work is in the clarification of his ontological ideas, notably the priority of the future over the other modes of time. I have questions about some of Pannenberg's ideas, but I find them powerful and persuasive. Part of the reason for seeking to make this work more widely available in published form is to offer students who want to learn from Pannenberg a key that may give access to some major currents in his thought. It is also intended as a modest contribution to the serious discussion of issues raised by his theology for those already familiar with it. It had been my intention to bring Pannenberg's theology into relation with the concerns of postmodernism (in its varying forms). This would certainly have made for either a much longer work or a very different work. However, the pressure to do so was substantially lessened by the recent appearance of F. L. Shults's book, The Postfoundationalist Task of Theology: Wolfhart Pannenberg and the New Theological Rationality. He argues that Pannenberg may be regarded - contrary to popular perception of him - as an ally in the postfoundationalist task of theology, without turning him (impossibly) into a postfoundationalist. This is a welcome and important contribution to the discussion of Pannenberg's theology. A note about language: I have tried to avoid the use of the third person masculine pronoun to refer to God, even though this sometimes results in clumsy and repetitive constructions. To me this is preferable to using gender-specific language for God. However, if the decision is made to speak of the Trinity as Father, Son and Holy Spirit, it is impossible to avoid the use of pronouns and artificial to avoid 'he', 'him' and 'his', at least for the Father and the Son. Until an acceptable convention establishes itself in theology, none of the available options is problem-free. I owe a debt of gratitude to many people for their support and xii
PREFACE
encouragement over the years. In Sydney I could not fail to mention Gordon Dicker, Stephen Pickard, Allan Loy, James Tulip, Paul Crittenden, Graham Hughes and Doug Purnell, as well as the staff of the Camden Library. In Melbourne I have received invaluable support from Dorothy Lee, Peter Matheson, Rufus Black, Harry Wardlaw, Eric Osborn, and from the staff of the Joint Theological Library. Help and encouragement in one form or another have also come from overseas scholars: Philip Clayton (USA), Colin Gunton (UK), Martien Brinkman and Bram van de Beek (The Netherlands). I owe my assistant, Lisa Stewart, a debt of gratitude for her help with the proofs and indices. I am most grateful to the publishers for their helpful approach and their meticulous attention to detail. My children are not theologians in the normal sense of the word, and have not helped directly with the writing of this book. However, in indirect ways, too numerous to mention, they have given me 'heaps' of inspiration and helped me more than they know. I cannot exaggerate the debt of gratitude to my late wife, Marijke, who lived with this work in most of its first stage but did not live to see its completion. Her encouragement to 'get on with it' has stayed with me throughout the second stage. In so many ways she was a tower of strength and an example of faith expressed more in deed than in word. I cannot think of God and the future without also thinking of her, and it is to her memory that I dedicate this work. CHRISTIAAN MOSTERT Melbourne Advent 2001
xin
This page intentionally left blank
Abbreviations for works by Wolfhart Pannenberg ATP
Anthropology in Theological Perspective
BQTi Basic Questions in Theology, Vol. i BQTz Basic Questions in Theology, Vol. 2, BQTj
Basic Questions in Theology, Vol. 3
GSTz
Grundfragen systematischer Theologie, Bd 2
1ST
An Introduction to Systematic Theology
JGM
Jesus - God and Man
MIG
Metaphysics and the Idea of God
RAH
Revelation as History
STi
Systematic Theology, Vol. i
STz
Systematic Theology, Vol. 2
STj
Systematic Theology, Vol. 3
TKG
Theology and the Kingdom of God
TPS
Theology and the Philosophy of Science
TTN
Toward a Theology of Nature
WM
What Is Man?
xv
This page intentionally left blank
I
Eschatology in twentieth-century theology
Introduction olfhart Pannenberg is widely regarded as one of the foremost systematic theologians in the world, with a readership in W many countries. His publications number in excess of six hundred
works. Until his retirement in 1994 he was Professor of Systematic Theology in the University of Munich, having been appointed to the newly formed Protestant faculty there in 1968. Through his writings, culminating in his magnum opus, the three-volume Systematic Theology', he has gained a reputation for wide learning and deep insight, sharp powers of analysis and unusual capacity to relate Christian theology to other fields of enquiry. He is a consummate Systematiker, an original thinker, a theologians' theologian. His ecclesiastical roots are Lutheran, but his theological engagement is with the full breadth of the Christian tradition. For many years he was engaged in theological work on behalf of the World Council of Churches (Faith and Order) aimed at promoting the unity in faith of all Christians. He writes, of course, as a European, but does not set out to write a European theology. In the face of sometimes stridently 'contextual' theologies, Pannenberg's concern is with 'the truth of Christian doctrine and the Christian confession',1 for the doctrines of Christianity, in his view, make truth-claims about objective states of affairs, essentially about God and God's activity in the world. 1 W. Pannenberg, Systematic Theology, Vol. i (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1991), xiii; hereafter STi.
I
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Theology is essentially a Gotteswissenschaft, a doctrine of God; it is fundamentally about God and all things in their relation to God. This book is about Pannenberg's elaboration of the Christian doctrine of God, which is as formidable as any in recent theology. In Christian theology no other concern could displace the concern with God. This does not imply a narrow view of the subject, however. If the Christian claim about God is true, everything that exists has some relation to God, which makes theology the most all-encompassing of fields of enquiry. This also makes theology a very concrete discipline, for it is concerned with things in the (socalled) 'real' world. However, our concern here is with the way Pannenberg thinks about the God of Christian faith, which - and here lies its novelty - does rather more with the notion of the future than most other theologies. Hence the title of this book, God and the Future. Putting it more technically, this way of thinking about God gives more prominence to eschatology than has usually been the case in theology. Indeed, I call Pannenberg's doctrine of God eschatological. The whole of this book is an explanation of what this means and the difference it makes to thinking about God. Not everyone thinks that theology is primarily about God. It can easily be argued that Christian theology is about the Christian religion or about Christian beliefs. It can also be construed as an explanation (or exploration) of Christian life and faith, both in its individual and socio-political aspects. But Pannenberg argues against such views, claiming that theology - any theology - must be about God, whether God is named as such or not. In his view, the Christian doctrine of God must be an unfolding of the divine 'economy' of creation and redemption. It is an elaboration of the biblical statement that God is love, an idea that includes both the relations between the three Persons of the Trinity and the relationship between the triune God and created reality. The cosmos has its origin in the divine love; all the works of God are an expression of the love of God. In fact, God has determined not to be God without a creaturely counterpart. The sending of the Son and the Spirit are also the manifestation of the love of God. This divine love is expected finally to reach its fulfilment in the eschatological consummation of this finite, temporal creation and its participation in God's eternal (trinitarian) life. This consummation 2
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
will mean at the same time the glorification of God by created beings and their glorification by God.2 Pannenberg is by no means alone in his insistence that the Christian doctrine of God, both narrowly and broadly conceived, must be a doctrine of the Trinity. His three-volume Systematic Theology is one of the strongest and most nuanced examples of a trinitarian doctrine of God. However, he is also acutely aware that the word 'God' has become highly problematic and in need of rational explanation in a culture which has marginalised it or is unable to rise above the scepticism or agnosticism sown by modern atheism.3 One of the tasks taken up in the first volume of Systematic Theology is that of investigating the ground on which God-talk might gain at least a preliminary plausibility; certainly no 'proofs' are available. This is an unavoidably rational task, for which fervent appeal to faith and commitment is no substitute. In the wake of the breakdown of classical metaphysical assumptions, speaking plausibly about God is far from simple. In Pannenberg's view, nothing less than a new understanding of reality - a new metaphysics - is required for this task. Pannenberg's early writing on the subject of God largely served this purpose. His search for a new metaphysics, a new ontology, converged with the growing conviction that Jesus' proclamation of the coming of God's kingdom had to occupy a central place in Christian theology. More likely, this new conviction, and especially Pannenberg's acceptance of the view that Jesus' understanding of the kingdom of God was radically eschatological, provided the stimulus for the new ontological explorations. Although Earth and Bultmann had, in their very different ways, given a certain prominence to eschatology, Pannenberg regarded this as inadequate. His own approach was ground-breaking: the starting point for theology had to be 'the Kingdom of God understood as the eschatological future brought about by God himself'.4 The imminent kingdom of God, the central idea in the message of Jesus, had to become the key to Christian theology as a whole. The 2 W. Pannenberg, Systematic Theology, Vol. 3 (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1998), 625; hereafter ST3. 3 STi, 6 3 f. 4 W. Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, ed. Richard J. Neuhaus (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1969), 53; hereafter TKG.
3
GOD AND THE FUTURE
important place which the idea of the future came early to occupy in both Pannenberg's theological work and his ontological ideas can be traced back to the central place he gave to the eschatological message of Jesus about the kingdom of God. Closely connected with this was his view of the resurrection of Jesus from the dead as an eschatological reality that had proleptically made its appearance within time and space.5 Clearly, the idea of the future was fundamental, fundamental for Jesus' own message and fundamental for the understanding of time.6 The prominence of eschatology in Pannenberg's thought gave rise to the impression of a certain convergence between his work and that of Jiirgen Moltmann. Almost exact contemporaries, they were briefly colleagues at the Kirchliche Hochschule in Wuppertal in the late 19505. However, their intellectual background and their personal history differed considerably and they found their theological and philosophical inspiration in very different figures. Although it is likely that there was some cross-fertilisation of ideas, the directions their work took were, in the main, divergent. Although Earth remained one of Pannenberg's principal sources of influence, Pannenberg moved further away from him in his theological method than did Moltmann. Moltmann's work is predominantly a theology of hope - as the title of his first major published work suggests7 - though his later work culminates in a theological discussion of the future for which Christians hope.8 Pannenberg's work is much more a theology of the future, although he has written about hope.9 They are in strong agreement about the central importance of eschatology in Christian faith and theology; for neither is it merely the last item on the theological agenda. On the contrary, for each of them Christian theology as a whole and in all its parts acquires its shape from eschatology. However, despite some points of similarity 5
See Pannenberg's discussion of the resurrection in Jesus - God and Man (London: SCM Press, 1968), ch. 3, esp. 74-88; hereafter/GM. 6 The priority of the eschatological future which determines our present demands a reversal also in our ontological conceptions.' TKG, 54. 7 J. Moltmann, Theology of Hope (London: SCM Press, 1967). 8 J. Moltmann, The Coming of God (London: SCM Press, 1996). 9 See e.g. The God of Hope' Basic Questions in Theology, Vol. 2. (Philadelphia: Westminster Press; London: SCM Press, 1971), ch. 8; hereafter BQTi. See also the discussion of hope in STj, 173-81.
4
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
between them formally speaking, materially their theologies differ significantly. In Pannenberg's view, we cannot think of God's being apart from God's rule (kingdom). God's being is God's rule; 'the deity of God is his rule'.10 God's rule is an expression of God's power, and the idea of power is implicit in the very idea of deity. If the kingdom of God does not come, God cannot be God! But how is God powerful? How does God rule in and over the cosmos? Obviously, in a Christian frame of reference we have to speak about God's power in close connection with God's love, for God is love as much as God is power. Another strong element in the discussion of God's power and rule is its trinitarian form. God works (rules) in the cosmos in a trinitarian way because God is the Holy Trinity, Father, Son and Holy Spirit. It cannot be otherwise if God's being and God's rule are one and the same. The other major characteristic of God's being and rule that will be highlighted in this discussion of Pannenberg's theology is its eschatological form. God is associated primarily with the future, even when God's action in the past or the present is under consideration. Indeed, God is the power of the future. What this means will require detailed discussion. Eschatology and Trinity belong together, and Pannenberg's promise of a strongly eschatological doctrine of God is eventually materialised in the articulation of a very strong doctrine of the Trinity, orthodox in its basic structure, yet full of new variations on the old themes. Ultimately the theology of the eschatological kingdom of God and the doctrine of the Trinity coincide. The present work begins with a focus on eschatology and ends with a discussion of Pannenberg's doctrine of the Trinity. It also reflects the indissoluble unity of theological and ontological ideas which is characteristic of Pannenberg's work. We begin with the theological, move to the ontological, and return to the theological. There is a certain artificiality about this structure, for the trinitarian theology fully articulated at the end is already more than hinted at in Pannenberg's early writing. We begin, then, with a focus on the eschatological shape of Pannenberg's theology, and this itself must be put in its historical context. 10
TKG, 55.
5
GOD AND THE FUTURE
A shocking discovery Pannenberg has a positive view of the adoption of the categories of Greek philosophy in early Christian theology, but acknowledges that a price was paid for this, notably the loss from view of the eschatological character of the Christ event.11 The finality of the Christ event - the message that Jesus Christ was the eschatological revelation of God and thus one with the very 'essence' of God was expressed in terms of the doctrine of the incarnation.12 Although this form of the fundamental Christian claim was persuasive in a culture which found apocalyptic ideas alien, it rests, in Pannenberg's view, on essentially eschatological ideas about God's self-revelation. The loss of truly eschatological thinking in the theological mainstream - as distinct from ideas about the life of the soul after death - is beyond dispute. It was not until the development of modern historiography in the nineteenth century, with its sharp focus on the history of Jesus, including his message of the kingdom of God, that there was a rediscovery of its eschatological character. A huge step in modern biblical scholarship was taken by Johannes Weiss in 1892. In Die Predigt Jesu vom Reiche Gottes^ Weiss broke decisively with the prevailing thinking about Jesus' understanding of the kingdom of God. When we bracket out our modern understandings of the kingdom of God, Weiss argued, we end up with the view that Jesus understood it as wholly future. During the nineteenth century the kingdom of God was understood as a spiritual community of people joined together by obedience to the will of God. As Albert Schweitzer puts it, for Weiss, there could be 'no question of a founding and development of the Kingdom within the hearts of men'.14 Schweitzer provided a ringing endorsement of Weiss's conclusions in his survey of the 'lives' of Jesus during the nineteenth century. Along with a sweeping condemnation of all attempts to 11 W. Pannenberg, The Appropriation of the Philosophical Concept of God as a Dogmatic Problem of Early Christian Theology', BQT2, ch. 5. IZ See Pannenberg's sixth thesis on revelation in Revelation as History (New York: Macmillan, 1968), 149-52; hereafter RAH. 13 Leander Keck (ed.), Jesus' Proclamation of the Kingdom of God (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1971). 14 A. Schweitzer, The Quest of the Historical ]esus (New York: Macmillan, 1955), 240.
6
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
picture Jesus in terms of the prevailing ideal of human personhood, Schweitzer declared, 'Jesus of Nazareth will not suffer Himself to be modernised'.15 It could no longer be maintained that the kingdom was something Jesus founded; there could be no doubt that for Jesus the kingdom of God was an eschatological reality. But this was a discovery hardly to be welcomed! For 'the historical Jesus will be to our time a stranger and an enigma'.16 Theology in the modern world could do little with the 'historical Jesus'. Not as an eschatological prophet but only as the source of a mighty spiritual force was Jesus significant for the modern world. Great scholar though he was, Schweitzer had 'no eschatological sense at all'.17 A desire for 'eschatological sense' was not high on the agenda of Protestant culture-Christianity and its theology. Harnack, whose confidence in the relevance of 'scientific' history and theology exceeded that of Schweitzer, had no trouble putting aside Jesus' eschatological ideas; he saw the kingdom of God as 'a still and mighty power in the hearts of men'.18 The principle of selection was the priority of what was original to Jesus over what he shared with his contemporaries. Harnack was a true son of the Ritschlian theology which saw Christianity as the perfect practical (moral) religion. The kingdom of God, of which Jesus is the founder, is to be understood as the moral society of nations. For Harnack, as for Ritschl, Christianity authenticated itself by its moral insights and ideals. Ritschl can be excused for not seeing that this understanding of the kingdom bore no relation to Jesus' view of the kingdom,19 but Harnack cannot. His view of the history of Jesus was clouded by his convictions about Christianity's place in Western civilisation and its universal importance. Another issue with some bearing on the discussion is the relation between historical knowledge and faith. Ritschl had no reason to doubt that his view of Jesus was based on solid historical 15
Schweitzer, The Quest of the Historical Jesus, 312. Schweitzer, The Quest of the Historical Jesus, 399. 17 The phrase is Moltmann's: Theology of Hope, 38. 18 A. Harnack, What Is Christianity?, 2nd edn. (London: Williams & Norgate, 1901), 54. 19 He died in 1889, and Johannes Weiss, who was his son-in-law, did not publish Die Predigt Jesu vom Reiche Gottes until 1892. 16
7
GOD AND THE FUTURE
fact.20 Weiss showed that the evidence of the New Testament forced a very different judgment. But this raised the broader question of the relation between historically ascertainable facts about Jesus and what might be accepted in faith. We should briefly consider the view of another contemporary, Wilhelm Herrmann, if only because of their influence on his most influential pupils, Earth and Bultmann. Herrmann accepted a solid core of facts, known from the New Testament, including the inner ideas of Jesus and his work of establishing the kingdom of God. But faith is not interested in a historical figure; it is the living Christ who is central for faith. The historian may not determine what a person can believe. Faith needs a surer foundation than historical research can provide, namely, one's own experience. Herrmann, as well as Martin Kahler (whose views were close to Herrmann's),21 did not want faith to be vulnerable to the changing verdicts of scientific (historical) investigation. Pannenberg is highly critical of this 'flight' from history. For him it is axiomatic that if Christian faith lives from a real past event, it follows that the object of faith cannot be immune to the results of historical research.21 The fatal problem with the views of Herrmann and Kahler was that they made faith rest upon itself instead of being built upon a historical foundation. With Herrmann and Kahler one cannot quite speak of a 'loss of history', but in the theology of their successors, Earth and Bultmann, there is a severance of the Gospel from its foundation in history. For Pannenberg this renders the Kerygma 'autonomous over against its historical correlate'.23
20
Ritschl had 'still upheld' the historical truth of the ground of faith, i.e. the historical Jesus; see 'Redemptive Event and History', Basic Questions in Theology, Vol. i (Philadelphia: Westminster Press; London: SCM Press, 1970), 57; hereafter BQTi. 21 It was Kahler who said, 'the real Christ is the Christ who is preached'; The So-called Historical Jesus and the Historic, Biblical Christ, ed. Carl E. Braaten (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1964), 66. Zi Faith is not a second way to knowledge of the past. 'In no case is theology ... in the position of being able to say what was actually the case regarding contents which remain opaque to the historian'; BQTi, 50. 2 3 BQTi, 8 5 f. 8
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
Eschatology in non-historical form The development of Pannenberg's view of the relation between history and faith was influenced to a significant extent by his rejection of the approaches of Bultmann and Earth to this issue. Both were theologians of the Word of God: Earth with his concept of the threefold form of the Word of God, and Bultmann with his focus on the kerygma as it addresses people in the present moment. For Pannenberg the Word must be understood as witnessing to the acts of God; 'the Word alone with its sheer claim to truth, taken abstractly by itself, is not yet sufficient ground for faith'.24 It is the events which the Word proclaims that have to be examined for their inherent meaning as redemptive. Troeltsch's failure to find the final revelation of God in the relative events of history dissuaded Earth and Bultmann from repeating the attempt. The only ways left open were to abandon the claim of an absolute revelation of God in Jesus Christ or to retain it but ground it in something other than what can be historically investigated. Pannenberg criticises Bultmann and Earth for taking the latter course: Bultmann by dissolving history into the historicity of existence and Earth by holding that the real content of faith is supra-historical.25 Arguably, no-one exercised a greater influence on Bultmann's view of history than R. G. Collingwood, from whom Bultmann learnt that 'historical knowledge is "existential" knowledge'; history is '/or human self-knowledge'.26 History is no objective study of self-contained events in the past, which explains why Bultmann had no interest in trying to recover the details of Jesus' life. Jesus Christ addresses people only through the church's kerygma. From Karl Jaspers, on the other hand, Bultmann took the point that history serves the human task of being 'responsible for the future'.27 This complements Heidegger's insistence that 'man, if he is willing to exist in a full personal sense, must be open to the future'.28 The study of history serves the responsibility of actualising our historicity. So Bultmann goes to the New 2 2
« BQTi, 85.
5 BQTi, i 5 f. R. Bultmann, History and Eschatology (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1957), 133, 134. 27 Bultmann, History and Eschatology', 130. 28 Bultmann, Jesus Christ and Mythology (London: SCM Press, 1960), 77. 26
9
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Testament asking what it has to say about possibilities for our existence. Pannenberg criticises this as too narrow a concern. Bultmann strips 'what happened then [das DamaligeY of its thenness [Damaligkeit], and fails to let the New Testament speak about 'God and his works in the events of the world and its history', which is its first concern.19 These views about history have implications for Bultmann's understanding of eschatology. He accepts that eschatological expectation and hope is the core of New Testament preaching, but he does not think that there will actually be an 'end of history'.30 With the non-arrival of the eschaton and the continuation of history, the church's eschatological hope experienced a crisis, resulting in a shift of emphasis to the way Jesus had already effected the transition from the old age to the new. For those who are in Christ 'the decisive event has already happened'. Christians must become what they already are. Pannenberg agrees that the eschatological decision takes place already in the encounter with Jesus (or as he is preached in the kerygma), so that in a sense the end of history is already here. However, this end is provisional; within history it is only 'anticipated'. It can be understood only within the framework of an apocalyptic view of history.31 Moreover, if Paul speaks of the gift of the Spirit as a first instalment (i Cor. 1:22), the question of the remainder cannot be bypassed. At the very least, Bultmann is selective in what he includes in his eschatology; it may be more accurate to say that what he excludes seriously distorts biblical eschatology.32 Bultmann's eschatology is the prisoner of his existentialist philosophy. This puts his eschatology in the same situation as every other doctrine of God. Any objective talk about God, salvation, eschatology or whatever is ruled out. Theology is not a set of general truths. We can speak of God only from the situation of knowing our existence to be 'determined' by God. Likewise, we Z
9 BQTi, nof.
3° See H. Ott, 'Rudolf Bultmann's Philosophy of History', in C. W. Kegley (ed.), The Theology of Rudolf Bultmann (London: SCM Press, 1966), 58. Bultmann's reply is on p. 264 of the same work. 3* BQTi, 36. 32 As Paul S. Minear argues on the grounds of the absence of any cosmological considerations; 'Rudolf Bultmann's Interpretation of New Testament Eschatology', in Kegley (ed.), The Theology of Rudolf Bultmann, 82,. IO
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
can speak about the end of the world only from the situation of having come to the end of our life on our own terms. This is the situation of faith, which is 'the affirmation of God's action upon us, the answer to his Word directed to us'.33 Pannenberg is dissatisfied with the 'formalism' of Bultmann's existentialist interpretation, which 'reduces the rich content of tradition to the thinness of [the] single fundamental act of existence'.34 It is the result of making humankind the bearer of history instead of God. Strangely, as it seems to him, we now have history grounded in the historicity of humankind instead of the converse. Pannenberg is less strident, though nonetheless serious, in his criticism of Karl Earth, who is a constant discussion-partner. He sees Earth as extending Kahler's view that the content of faith is supra-historical rather than historical. Ordinary history is more or less avoided. What he finds in Earth is a 'theology of redemptive history [which] fled into a harbor supposedly safe from the critical-historical flood-tide, the harbor of a suprahistory - or with Earth, of pre-history'.35 Earth is a theologian of the Word of God; his starting-point is the great fact of Deus dixit. God's great Word - and act - is the incarnation of the Logos, which is the self-revelation of God. How does this relate to history? In the Romerbrief we find the classic sentences responsible for the charge that, for Earth, self-revelation is not truly or consistently historical. Here we find the great phrases about the meeting of two worlds, the Gospel and human history; but they meet only on the point of intersection. The name 'Jesus' defines an historical occurrence, but in so far as our world is touched by the other world, it can no longer be directly observed as history.36 Who and what Jesus is is beyond historical definition. The divine and human worlds touch 'as a tangent touches a circle, that is, without touching it'. Similarly, the resurrection is both 'an occurrence in history' and 'not an event in history at all'. 11 R. Bultmann, 'What Does it Mean to Speak of God?', Faith and Understanding, Vol. i, ed. R. W. Funk (London: SCM Press, 1969), 61-3. 34 W. Pannenberg, Theology and the Philosophy of Science (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1976), 172; hereafter TPS. 35 BQTi, 15, 16. 36 K. Barth, The Epistle to the Romans, ed. Edwyn C. Hoskyns (London: Oxford University Press, 1933 & 1972), 29. The next several quotations are from the same and the following page. II
GOD AND THE FUTURE
In a section of the Romerbrief entitled 'Concerning the Value of History', Earth speaks of 'the Primal History which conditions all history', namely, 'the light of the LOGOS of all history and of all life', and of the incapacity of history to give any assurance at all of the non-historical.37 The history of Jesus, as the self-revelation of God, is 'not a point among other points'.38 It cannot be understood on the analogy of other events, for here our normal judgments meet their judgment (krisis). Jesus appeared as the Christ within the same flux of time as that in which we live, but that aspect is of no interest to us.39 Elsewhere Earth says that 'the history of Deus dixit has, as qualified history, no ... links with the rest of history'.40 If it is not understood in its own terms, it will not be understood at all. Earth is, as so often, elusive, wanting to utter both a yes and a wo; there is continuity', but there is an even more important discontinuity. That the Logos was made flesh in a particular time and place is certainly of the greatest importance. But in themselves the details are not of any great interest. Thus the investigation of this particular piece of history with the tools of historical-critical scholarship is, at best, irrelevant and, at worst, misleading, bound to miss the true identity of Jesus. This may not quite be a repudiation of ordinary history, but one can agree with Pannenberg's criticism that it amounts to a depreciation of real history. The sphere of the historically ascertainable and the sphere of revelation touch without really touching.41 What accounts for this? The reason for Earth's ambiguous attitude toward ordinary history is his doctrine of the hiddenness of God. God is utterly different from finite beings, and can never be the object of their cognitive grasp, except in so far as God creates this possibility. Revelation is always God's revelation, and Earth emphasises that 'precisely in his revelation God is the hidden God'.41 This is because God is the living, utterly free God. Earth will not allow us to think even for a moment that, armed with historical skills and 37
Earth, The Epistle to the Romans, 140, 144. Barth, The Epistle to the Romans, 91. 3 9 Barth, The Epistle to the Romans, 498. 40 K. Barth, The Gottingen Dogmatics: Instruction in the Christian Religion, Vol. i, ed. Hannelotte Reiffen (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1991), 6of. 4' BQTi, 16, 58. ^ Barth, The Gottingen Dogmatics, 135. 38
12
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
careful attention to Jesus' life, we can penetrate what God keeps in concealment. Yet he insists that Jesus' space and time were of the same kind as ours. Pannenberg's criticism of Earth, similar to his criticism of Bultmann, is equally justified. The overshadowing of ordinary history by the non-historical radiance of a primal history is no less a withdrawal from history than is Bultmann's concentration on the historicity of personal existence. Pannenberg does not discuss in detail the implications for eschatology of Earth's ambiguous concern with history. Earth certainly saw the importance of eschatology, as indicated by the celebrated remark in the Romerbrief that 'if Christianity be not altogether thoroughgoing eschatology, there remains in it no relationship whatever with Christ'.43 But everything hinges on what Earth meant by 'thoroughgoing eschatology'. Doubtless, he meant something more substantial than liberal Protestantism's understanding of it. Nevertheless, the impression is strong that Earth pressed eschatology into the service of his theology of revelation, with the result that it becomes a way of bearing witness to the transcendence of God. Earth speaks of a 'timeless age to which all men belong', a life that is final and non-historical,44 in which we shall live. But it is doubtful that this is a real future. The eschatological reality is more like a boundary between the finite and the infinite. For the power and deity of God, having entered our world, has 'set a boundary against everything in our world', and manifests itself at that boundary.45 Earth speaks also of a 'Moment', the eternal Moment, which is the 'now' of revelation, which 'always is, and yet is not'. It is the parousia, but it is no temporal event. It is simply not clear from Earth's early work whether the 'Moment' can be any 'Now' in which the eternal is present in time - between the past and the future - or whether it is truly ('thoroughly') eschatological. The suspicion is that eschatology, for Earth, is another form of the eternity, the transcendence, the timelessness of God, which meets us as a 43
Earth, The Epistle to the Romans, 314. Earth, The Epistle to the Romans, 249. 4 5 Earth, The Epistle to the Romans, 314. Gerhard Sauter endorses the idea that for dialectical theology 'eschatology' became 'a boundary marker (Grenzbegriff)'; What Dare We Hope? Reconsidering Eschatology (Harrisburg: Trinity Press International, 1999), 68. Eschatology points to the limitation or the boundary of all human speech about God; ySf. 44
13
GOD AND THE FUTURE
boundary to our existence.46 In effect, this means the collapse of eschatology into the doctrine of revelation. If there is no eschatological 'end', and the revelatory 'moment' can be any moment, Earth's eschatology is less than thoroughgoing, no matter how strong and rich his doctrine of God in relation to time may have been. Is the kingdom of God merely 'above' or also 'before' us? The young Earth was as elusive as ever on this point. Later he admits that his view of eternity was not adequate. Referring to his earlier interpretation of a passage such as Rom. 13:1 if., he says that he saw it as referring 'only to the moment which confronts all moments in time as the eternal "transcendental meaning" of all moments in time'.47 As early as 1967 Pannenberg expressed strong criticism of such an eschatology: for Bultmann and for the young Earth, Jesus' eschatology is timeless and deprived of its temporal meaning. Dialectical theology disregarded Jesus' message about the Kingdom of God as an expectation regarding the concrete future ... And where Jesus' words about the future have a clearly temporal meaning, these were modified by means of Christological or anthropological interpretations.48
Eschatology in the key of promise In his excellent survey and analysis of types of eschatology in the last couple of centuries, Gerhard Sauter speaks of 'the third "eschatological storm" ', which broke out in the 19605 in Europe and North America.49 This 'storm' was a new movement in theology which related the Christian hope not to the details of the 'last things', the eschata, which will follow this world and this age, but to the whole process of the history of the world, especially its future. It was - as the title of Jiirgen Moltmann's theological classic symbolises50 - a theology of hope, but a hope which is 46 This is the view of Moltmann, who thinks that for Barth, no less than Bultmann, 'revelation and the eschaton coincide'; Theology of Hope, 46. If the eschaton is the transcendental boundary between time and eternity, the end is always near. ^ K. Barth, Church Dogmatics, II/i (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1957), 716. Barth remarks that he was serious about 'the far-sidedness of the coming kingdom of God' but was not confident to discuss its actual coming. 48 TKG, 52.. 4 ? Sauter, What Dare We Hope?, 119. 50 Moltmann, Theology of Hope.
14
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
related very concretely to the social, economic and political conditions in which the majority of people in the world live. This makes it - at least in Moltmann's version of it - a political theology, which in turn played some part in the development of 'liberation' theologies in various parts of the 'two thirds' world. Hope should lead to (hopeful) action for the transformation of socio-economic conditions that are contrary to the will of the God who takes up especially the cause of the poor and the marginalised. Pannenberg and Moltmann were the leading figures in the articulation of an eschatological theology of history. In this section we will briefly consider the main features of Moltmann's theology, in order to help us to see where Pannenberg's thought both converges with it and diverges from it. For Moltmann, as we shall see, the key idea is that of 'promise',51 the promise of God, for the historical realisation of which we hope. In a brief autobiographical piece Moltmann speaks about the importance of hope in the period of internment in a British POW camp, a hope which 'rubbed itself raw on the barbed wire'.52 Clearly, it had to be a hope that could conquer the awful experience of personal despair as well as the cultural collapse which World War II symbolised to a devastating degree. It was a hope at once grounded in the cross and the resurrection. Christian faith must know the basis on which it can have something to say - and something to hope in - in the face of the incalculable suffering that has resulted in 'protest atheism'.53 Like Pannenberg, Moltmann was a student of Gerhard von Rad, who showed that the understanding of revelation found in the traditions of the Old Testament connected it closely with historical events. Against Bultmann's existentialist view of revelation, both Moltmann and Pannenberg saw that revelation requires a theology of history. However, they did so with different 51
Sauter remarks that 'promise is the basic category of eschatology ... , the category for perceiving God's faithfulness in God's sayings and doings'; What Dare We Hope?, 219. 52 J. Moltmann, 'Foreword' in M. Douglas Meeks, Origins of the Theology of Hope (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1974), x. 53 J. Moltmann, The Crucified God: The Cross of Christ as the Foundation and Criticism of Christian Theology (London: SCM Press, 1974), ch. 6, esp. 2.19-27, 249-56. 15
GOD AND THE FUTURE
emphases. For Pannenberg, God is revealed in history, but this revelation will be complete only at the end of history, when God will be seen unambiguously to be the unifying power of all finite reality. Revelation is a predicate of history. Moltmann, on the other hand, saw history as a predicate of revelation.54 History is the fulfilment of the word of promise which God has spoken. The Bible is 'the history book of God's promises', 'the story of the anticipations of God's future in the past'.55 It is a dangerous book, especially on account of the subversive memory of the cross. The hope it generates is not one that turns people away from the problems of their time, but a hope from which to challenge things that fall short of God's promises. Those who live in this hope 'can no longer put up with reality as it is, but begin to suffer under it, to contradict it',56 and to initiate change. Moltmann's view of history is closely connected with the concept of promise, and is premised on the distinction between 'epiphany' religion and the religion of promise.57 Epiphany religion focuses on the times and places where the deity manifests itself, which then become sacred. For Israel God's appearing is connected with the uttering of a word of promise, but the promise points away from the appearances to the yet unrealised future which it announces.58 This is how the sense of history arises in human experience. 'Beneath the star of the promise of God it becomes possible to experience reality as history.'59 The stories of the past are interpreted as stories of the promises of God, which have a future fulfilment in view. The past matters because it becomes the basis of the call for on-going confidence in the God of the promises. The future matters because the fulfilment of the promises is a future reality. The present, the time between the promises and their fulfilment, matters as the time of orientation 54
For a clear comparison see Meeks, Origins of the Theology of Hope, 67-73. Moltmann says, 'it is not that consummated history reveals God, but God's universal revelation in the coming of the fulness of his glory brings history to its consummation'; Theology of Hope, 115. 55 J. Moltmann, The Experiment Hope, ed. M. Douglas Meeks (London: SCM Press, 1975), 45. 56 Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 2.1. 57 Moltmann, Theology of Hope, ch. 2. 58 Moltmann, Theology of Hope, yyL 59 Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 106.
16
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
toward the fulfilment. Historical events point forward and receive their truth 'from the goal that has been promised by God and is to be expected from him'.60 This makes history the creation of the promises of God. In Moltmann's view, God is revealed in the fulfilment of the ancient promises. Here an important area of disagreement with Pannenberg comes into view. For Moltmann the context of the doctrine of revelation is not the problem of God's non-provability: that is a philosophical issue. God reveals Godself in order that humankind might be able to identify God, know who God is, not merely that God is. God is identifiable where God identifies Godself with historical acts of faithfulness. With Pannenberg in mind, Moltmann says, 'In proving his faithfulness in history, [God] reveals himself. For the essence and the identity of the God of promise lies not in his absoluteness over and beyond history, but in the constancy of his freely chosen relation to his creatures, in the constancy of his electing mercy and faithfulness.'61 It is not history as such which reveals God, but only the history initiated by promise and expected as a result of it. Moltmann is critical of Pannenberg's theology of history, especially the idea of 'universal history'. The main problem with it, for Moltmann, is that revelation is too much a predicate of history as a whole. Pannenberg's argument proceeds from a view of history in its totality to God as the ground of its unity. Although this is understood eschatologically, it is an attempt to demonstrate God's existence from the world, albeit in its future totality. Moltmann sees this as a form of the old cosmological argument, in which God's existence is inferred empirically from the existence of the world. This is essentially an attempt to improve on Greek cosmic theology, and is not significantly different from the 'epiphany' religion from which he strongly distinguishes his own theology of promissory history.62 This history begins with Abraham and the patriarchs and is both validated and set off in a new direction in Jesus Christ. For Moltmann the cross and the resurrection - the resurrection of the crucified one - have to be given their due already now, in giving humankind knowledge of 60 61 6z
Moltmann, Theology of Hope', 108. Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 116. Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 79. 17
GOD AND THE FUTURE
God. In his view, Pannenberg puts too much emphasis on the finality and completeness of revelation at the end of history and reduces the significance of what can be known about God in the midst of history. This knowledge 'moves within the horizon of remembrance and expectation opened up by the promise5.63 It is an anticipatory knowledge, as Moltmann and Pannenberg both say. The difference between them is that for Pannenberg the notion of anticipatory knowledge is part of a rich, theoretical epistemology, in which the issue of (eschatological) confirmation is an important element, while for Moltmann it is a knowledge of the future of God, in the sense of a knowledge of what God will do in the world, a knowledge gained on the basis of the past faithfulness of God. This is not the knowledge about which theories of knowledge are written, but the knowledge of pilgrims on the way. How does eschatology arise in Moltmann's view of history? The promises of God can be termed eschatological when they are directed 'towards a historic future in the sense of the ultimate horizon'.64 Thus eschatology arose in the context of promise; the novum of promise became eventually the novum ultimum^ when expectations of salvation within the course of history no longer seemed capable of fulfilment and a new decisive action of God beyond the present age was envisaged. This implied a radical universalising of the action of God, which Moltmann expresses brilliantly: On its political deathbed Israel brings the nations, as it were, into the hands of its God and into his future. By this very means Yahweh's threats and promises for the future are set free from their restriction to the one specific people and its particular future in history, and become eschatological.65
This is the Day of Yahweh, when God's faithfulness to the divine promises reaches its fullest expression. In the light of the resurrection of Jesus, this promised future is unthinkable apart from Jesus Christ. He is the validation of the promise of God and thus of the God of promise. But hope for the future cannot go around the cross. The cross is a standing challenge to 'fulfilment ecstasy', 63
Moltmann, Theology of Hope', 118. 4 Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 12.5. 65 Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 12.9.
6
18
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
a warning not to look away from the pain and suffering of the world as it exists now. Nevertheless, from the resurrection of Jesus we know that God has begun a history 'whose goal is the annihilation of death in the victory of the life of the resurrection, and which ends in the righteousness in which God receives in all things his due and the creature thereby finds its salvation'.66 It is clear that in the theology of hope eschatology has been vigorously put back into the centre of systematic theology. It is an eschatology in the key of promise, for God is the giver and the fulfiller of the promise of life and salvation. From the promises of God history is created, as human beings respond in hope to the promises and reach out for the fulfilment. The promises of God can be expressed in different metaphors, but the overarching one is that of the kingdom of God; here is the heart of eschatology. Here the universal horizon of promise and hope is connected with the theology of the lordship of God; God will be 'all in all' (i Cor. 15:28). The world and everything in it will become God's. To speak of the kingdom of God is to bring out 'the all-embracing eschatological breadth of [God's] future', to which people are already related through promise and hope.67 Despite some notable differences between the theologies of Moltmann and Pannenberg, they are nowhere closer than at this point. Pannenberg's comprehensive eschatology If Moltmann's theology is best described as a theology of hope, Pannenberg's is more accurately characterised as theology of the future, though this is an ambiguous phrase.68 Moltmann's theology has ontological implications, but he does not pursue these in detail.69 Pannenberg has devoted many years to working out a detailed onto-theological account of the eschatological world-view of the Old and New Testaments, and Jesus' view of the kingdom of God. He spoke early of the 'priority of the eschatological 66
Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 163. Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 2.2.0. 68 See P. Hefner, Theological Reflections (4): Questions for Moltmann and Pannenberg', Una Sancta, 2,5.3, 1968, 38. 69 Moltmann speaks of the need for an 'ontology of the future' (or the 'notyet') as a counterpart to the 'anthropology of hope'; cf. 'Where There Is Hope, There Is Religion', The Experiment Hope, 20, 2,5^ But he himself does not go into such matters. 67
19
GOD AND THE FUTURE
future', a fundamental feature of Jesus' message of God's kingdom, which demands a reversal in our ontological conceptions.70 Among other things, the doctrine of God, the concept of history (time), anthropology and epistemological issues need to be reshaped in the light of the priority of the future. His approach to eschatology is nothing if not comprehensive. Pannenberg was not the first to undertake a detailed treatment of the theme of the future in contemporary theology. There were others whose work is significant.71 But Pannenberg's retrieval of eschatology into the centre of the theological agenda is unmatched in contemporary theology. There are six main reasons for this. First, it is demanded by the Christian faith itself. The originating events and traditions cannot be properly understood in a noneschatological way. Second, the Christian understanding of salvation requires it. Without such an eschatological understanding the old objection that the world looks too unredeemed to believe that the Messiah has come could not be met. Third, the importance of the theme of futurity in modern European thought requires it. Whether the focus is on the problem of history or on individual existence - thus whether Hegel, Marx and Bloch or Kierkegaard and Heidegger are held to raise the critical issues - the theme of the future cannot be avoided.72 Fourth, Pannenberg's interest in anthropology also adds impetus to his exploration of the idea of the future. Human existence is not conceivable apart from an 'unending movement into the open'.73 Our identity is not given 70
TKG, 54, and BQTi, xv, xvi. Mention should especially be made of Gerhard Sauter, Zukunft und Verheissung: Das Problem der Zukunft in der gegenwdrtigen theologischen und philosophischen Diskussion (Zurich: Zwingli Verlag, 1965). Sauter has been a critic of both Pannenberg's and Moltmann's understanding of eschatology. He doubts that a theology of history can really grasp the reason for Christian hope; What Dare We Hope?, xiif. and Eschatological Rationality: Theological Issues in Focus (Grand Rapids: Baker Books, 1996), esp. 149. 7Z John Macquarrie suggests that the theology of hope as a whole is indebted to the Hegel-Feuerbach-Marxist line in philosophy, as opposed to the Kierkegaard-Heidegger-Bultmann line; see Theologies of Hope: A Critical Examination', Expository Times 81, 1970-71, 100-5. In Pannenberg's case, this is an over-simplification. 73 W. Pannenberg, What Is Man? Contemporary Anthropology in Theological Perspective (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1970), 54; hereafter WM 71
2,0
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
to us by the past but from the future, an idea that certainly requires ontological clarification. A fifth reason is the need for a contemporary articulation of the doctrines of Christianity. Pannenberg early saw the potential of an eschatological understanding of the doctrine of God, and an eschatological framework has progressively proved fruitful in expressing the meaning of other doctrines. Sixth, there is a political reason, called such because it concerns a person's basic stance in the public world. An eschatological understanding of the kingdom of God encourages realism in what can be achieved in political, social and economic change. We shall briefly consider these six factors in Pannenberg's development of an eschatological theology. First, the restoration of eschatology is demanded by a proper understanding of the Christian faith. It is no longer possible to doubt that the idea of the kingdom of God, central in the ministry of Jesus, is an eschatological notion. Theology cannot ignore eschatology, for eschatology is 'no longer a marginal problem of theology, which one could leave to the last chapter of dogmatics, but the basis upon which everything in Christian tradition is built'.74 If this is ignored, or if eschatology is reduced to a nontemporal phenomenon, violence is done to the core of the faith-tradition. Furthermore, the resurrection of Jesus from the dead, understood in terms of Jewish eschatological expectation, is the sine qua non of Christian faith: The basis of the knowledge of Jesus' significance remains bound to the original apocalyptic horizon of Jesus' history ... If this horizon is eliminated, the basis of faith is lost; then Christology becomes mythology and no longer has true continuity with Jesus himself and with the witness of the apostles.75
In other words, if the resurrection is central to Christianity, an axiomatic point, the same must be said about eschatology. It is not possible to understand Christian faith properly without it. Second, the doctrines of reconciliation and salvation also demand an eschatological understanding. These cannot be 74
W. Pannenberg, 'Can Christianity Do Without an Eschatology?', in G.B. Caird et al., The Christian Hope (London: SPCK, 1970), 31. 75 /GM, 83. 21
GOD AND THE FUTURE
understood adequately in terms of the forgiveness of sins but require much fuller articulation. To say without qualification that reconciliation between God and the world is already established in Christ is to lose the crucial 'already-not yet' tension inherent in Christian existence. It ignores the fact that the world is not yet fully redeemed. The modern preoccupation with the concept of alienation implies that Christian talk of reconciliation must include the eschatological proviso. The reconciliation of the world, accomplished proleptically, does not yet characterise the empirical course of events in history. As Pannenberg puts it, the decisive reason why Christianity cannot do without an eschatology is that the reconciliation of the world, the presence of God, and his kingdom through Christ, have taken place only in the form of an anticipation of a future which in its fullness has not yet materialized. Therefore, the belief in the reconciliation of the world in Christ is itself based upon eschatology while at the same time it corroborates the Christian trust and hope in the future of God.76
Christian claims about reconciliation must be abandoned if they are not understood in an eschatological sense. The 'already-not yet' tension in every aspect of Christian existence can only be articulated in eschatological terms. The third set of reasons is philosophical. In Pannenberg's view the Gospel has its foundation in history, and God's relation to the creation must be understood in terms of 'history'. This requires a view of history in its totality, not a special stream of 'salvationhistory'; nothing else would be adequate to the universality of God.77 Pannenberg believes that the idea of a single history is meaningful; that everything in history must be understood in terms of continuities which, in principle, have no limit. Of course, history, not yet complete, requires the idea of an open future. This has been made the theme of philosophical inquiry, particularly by Ernst Bloch. Bloch has 'recovered the biblical tradition's eschatological mode of thought as a theme for philosophical reflection'.78 Bloch has done much to explore 'the ontological priority of the future' in relation to the mystery of the human being. Pannenberg believes Bloch has not really succeeded in finding an ontological 76 77 78
Pannenberg, 'Can Christianity Do Without an Eschatology?', 30. BQTi, 67. BQT2, 2.38. 2,2,
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
ground for the primacy of the future, and that his non-theistic eschatology needs a theological dimension. Heidegger, too, explored the importance of the future for human existence, though very differently. Dilthey had asserted that the meaning of any individual event (or life) could be determined only in the light of what still lies in the future. To understand the parts one must know the whole. Heidegger developed this not in relation to the whole of history but individual existence; yet here too the idea of the future plays a major role.79 Pannenberg is critical of Heidegger's restriction of this to the sphere of human existence - in which form it was taken up by Bultmann - but it has potential for much broader application. Pannenberg's interest in the broader ontological implications is an important factor in developing an eschatological theology. The fourth factor is Pannenberg's anthropological interest. Developments in modern anthropological thought were a strong stimulus toward modern atheism, and Pannenberg believes that the most promising way of creating space today for the Godhypothesis must take place 'on the terrain of the interpretation of human existence'.80 The human person is characterised by the quality of self-transcendence or 'exocentricity',81 but this must be seen in relation to the question of an ultimate destiny, in which an individual's identity is first truly established, and an ultimate fulfilment in which all the ambiguities of human existence within history are overcome. This is to set out in an eschatological direction in anthropological thought. A decisive impetus comes from the New Testament, where Paul re-orients the concept of the human person in an eschatological direction.82 A historical understanding of the human being first emerged in Christian thought, but such an understanding has to include openness to the future, for the meaning of anything includes its outcome, which, at the time of its happening, is 'still hidden in the womb of the future'. 83 79
BQTi, 166. ('Historicness' is not a very attractive word.) W. Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1985), 15; hereafter ATP. 81 ATP, 62-6. On exocentricity see also 37. ^ ATP, 497. 8 3 ATP, 506. 80
23
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Thus theological anthropology is a further fruitful field for the development of an eschatological theology. Fifth, the need to find the most persuasive articulation of Christian doctrine is a factor in Pannenberg's pursuit of an eschatological theology, especially the doctrine of God; this is at the heart of his entire theological work. In the message of Jesus, God is a God of the coming kingdom. This is the basis for developing both an eschatological ontology and an eschatological doctrine of God. Without this, an eschatological form of other doctrines would be of little interest, since their foundation lies in the concept of God.84 The biblical God is God 'only in the execution of [God's] lordship', and this can be fully accomplished only in the future.85 In an early essay Pannenberg said that the question of God must now be 'concerned exclusively with the possibility of a God "with futurity as a quality of being" '.86 The completion of the Systematic Theology gives this understanding of God its most developed expression. Working out an understanding of God consistent with Jesus' proclamation of the 'God of the coming kingdom' has been the major factor in constructing a consistent and comprehensive eschatological theology. Finally, Pannenberg also argued for a critical and constructive function of eschatology in the public realm.87 Although eschatology has at times taken 'other-worldly' forms, resulting in a 'world-denying' stance, there is a positive element in this 'otherworldliness' that is of some political relevance. Eschatology provides a challenge to the self-sufficiency of an entirely secular view of the world. The consummation of human existence lies beyond death, and eschatology challenges the illusory hopes of secular world-views - political and cultural - about the attainability of unambiguous happiness in this world. 'Eschatology exposes secular man's illusions about the possibilities of self-realisation in this world, and therefore eschatology is at the heart of a Christian realism in appraising the conditions of human existence in the present world.'88 This is not an excuse for a negative attitude 8 4 8 5 86 87
BQTi, xvi. BQT2,140. BQT2, 241.
W. Pannenberg, 'Constructive and Critical Functions of Christian Eschatology', Harvard Theological Review 77.2., 1984, 119-39. 88 Pannenberg, 'Constructive and Critical Functions of Christian Eschatology', 124. 24
ESCHATOLOGY IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY THEOLOGY
toward the affairs of the world. Rather, it makes possible a realistic involvement in the world's struggles, since one can operate with hope but without illusions. There is a positive counterpart to this critical function of eschatology, for it can reinforce the sense of the dignity and meaning of human experience, by relating it to an eternal and transcendent source of meaning. 'Hope in a transcendent completion of human existence in communion with God illumines the present existence in spite of its shortcomings.'89 To accept this is not to diminish the significance of life in the world now. On the contrary, this life is enriched and deepened when it is understood as an 'anticipation' of that fuller existence that in part is already known and in part is still awaited from the future. To show the relevance of an eschatological theology is not yet to establish its truth; that requires a detailed examination of Pannenberg's theology. So far we have traced in outline the fluctuating fortunes of eschatology in modern theology, and given an indication of the nature and extent of Pannenberg's commitment to eschatological theology. We now begin the task of investigating major elements in Pannenberg's recovery of eschatology for the Christian doctrine of God.
89 Pannenberg, 'Constructive and Eschatology', 124.
2-5
Critical Functions of Christian
This page intentionally left blank
2,
The appeal of apocalyptic Theology and apocalyptic
T
he shape of Pannenberg's theology is determined by the message and resurrection of Jesus, by 'the peculiar, eschatological character of [his] history'.1 He understands Jesus' message of the kingdom of God and his resurrection from the dead in the closest relation to second Temple Jewish apocalyptic thought. The question is whether he is on solid ground here. This is an important exegetical question. However, in view of his appeal to some key ideas in apocalyptic literature, it is also important to ask whether these ideas are significant within the world of apocalyptic and whether they can bear the weight of the theological system Pannenberg builds on them. It is - as he recognises - a world that is strange to us,2 and whilst the ideas of apocalyptic literature have fascinated many people they have not played a very prominent role in contemporary theology. That Pannenberg - rather against the stream - should find these ideas challenging and illuminating bears investigation.3 In April 1960 Ernst Kasemann made the now famous remark that apocalyptic was 'the mother of all Christian theology'.4 Jesus 1
W. Pannenberg, 'On Historical and Theological Hermeneutic', BQTi,
175.
2
BQTi, 144^; cf. also 146. A. D. Galloway says that Pannenberg (and Moltmann) take 'this unwanted child of faith unhesitatingly into the bosom of their theology'; The New Hegelians', review article, Religious Studies 8, 1972, 369. 4 E. Kasemann, 'The Beginnings of Christian Theology', in Robert W. Funk (ed.), Apocalypticism, Journal for Theology and the Church 6 (New York: Herder & Herder, 1969), 40. 3
2-7
GOD AND THE FUTURE
himself, in Kasemann's view, preached a message of the kingdom of God which was not constitutively stamped by apocalyptic, his emphasis being on the nearness of God. But Easter and Pentecost caused primitive Christianity to 'resort again to apocalyptic terms as a means of responding to, and in a certain sense supplanting, Jesus5 preaching of the nearness of God9.5 Pannenberg agrees that the origins of Christianity cannot be understood in isolation from the eschatological expectations of Judaism. In his view, Jesus' message too 'can only be understood within the horizon of apocalyptic expectations', which is not to say that Jesus can be described as simply an apocalyptic figure.6 Various members of the so-called 'Pannenberg circle' that met in Heidelberg and published Revelation as History in 1961 discussed the influence of apocalyptic on Jesus and on early Christianity. Ulrich Wilckens saw apocalyptic thought as 'the native soil for the proclamation of Jesus',7 and Dietrich Rossler had earlier written about 'history in its entirety' or 'the unity of history' as a basic theme of Jewish apocalyptic,8 a theme that Pannenberg would make central in his theology of history. In the last fifty years the question of the influence of apocalyptic ideas on Jesus has been vigorously debated. Kasemann's essay was criticised by Gerhard Ebeling and Ernst Fuchs, which prompted an even stronger essay on the theme from Kasemann.9 If Jesus was not an apocalyptic figure, what would need to be explained is the double discontinuity between Jesus and John the Baptist and between Jesus and the early church. When Jesus is confessed as the Son of Man, the bringer of the last judgment, we are in the realm of apocalyptic, though a modified apocalyptic. Kasemann speculated why early Christianity may only have found it possible to respond to Jesus in apocalyptic terms. 'In Jesus the world is confronted by ultimate promise', the promise of 'the kingdom of freedom', which cannot have been qualitatively ultimate without 5
Kasemann, The Beginnings of Christian Theology', 40. /GM, 32, 2,17. 7 U. Wilckens, The Understanding of Revelation Within the History of Primitive Christianity', RAH, 71. 8 D. Rossler, Gesetz und Geschichte: Untersuchungen zur Theologie der judischen Apokalyptik und der pharisdischen Orthodoxie (Neukirchener Verlag, 1960). 9 See the contributions of Kasemann, Ebeling and Fuchs in Funk (ed.), Apocalypticism. 6
2,8
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
also being temporally ultimate. By breaking the power of death and bringing in a new age of freedom Jesus had abiding and universal significance.10 However, by way of contrast, Marcus Borg, a member of the Jesus Seminar, writing more than forty years after Kasemann, argues that 'Jesus' message and mission were non-eschatological' and that the eschatological expectations of the early church were not central to its life and belief.11 The matter is clearly still contentious. Stimulated more by developments in Old Testament studies (notably von Rad's work on the connection between faith and history in the Old Testament), Pannenberg and his friends discovered something like a total view of history in the literature of apocalyptic, particularly in the period between 200 BCE and 100 CE. Their own work led them to conclude that history is the most comprehensive horizon of Christian theology. All theological questions and answers are meaningful only within the framework of the history which God has with humanity and through humanity with his whole creation - the history moving toward a future still hidden from the world but already revealed in Jesus Christ.12
Jewish apocalyptic had a view of history that covered the whole course of the world from its beginning to its end. Pannenberg found in Jewish apocalyptic the continuation of a strong historical consciousness and a view of the cosmos as a whole. It is unnecessary and artificial to separate the cosmological and the historical, although, as we shall see, there are different streams within apocalypticism. What is most striking for Pannenberg about apocalyptic is its universal scope. The history of all the nations is included within its compass. This is the necessary correlate to his idea that the deity of God (God's reality and power) can establish itself only with reference to the whole of reality. 'Speaking about God and speaking about the whole of reality are not two entirely different matters, but mutually condition each other.' J 3 10 E. Kasemann, 'On the Topic of Primitive Christian Apocalyptic', in Funk (ed.), Apocalypticism, 118. 11 Marcus J. Borg, Jesus in Contemporary Scholarship (Valley Forge, PA: Trinity Press International, 1994), 89.
" BQTi, 15. '3 3QTi, 156.
29
GOD AND THE FUTURE
The legitimacy and relevance of apocalyptic thought for theology lies, in Pannenberg's view, in its contribution to a theology of revelation, since revelation is not to be understood primarily in terms of the concept of the Word of God, but in relation to history. For Israel the evidence of Yahweh's power and deity lies in what God does in history. God's self-revelation takes place as a reflex of this activity in history.14 Pannenberg means God's action in its totality, for a series of unrelated revelatory events is incompatible with revelation understood as God's selfrevelation. It is the totality of God's action that is revelatory, and it is this that requires a notion of history in its totality. Only the last event will finally and fully disclose the power and glory of God. This finds its exact parallel in the theme of salvation. In the great future act of judgment and salvation God's self-disclosure will be final and complete.15 The hidden meaning of the present will be disclosed and God's vindication will be clear for all to see. God's power over all things will be confirmed, and God's glory will be revealed. In taking key apocalyptic ideas into the centre of his theology, Pannenberg is not without his critics. Moltmann contrasts apocalyptic thought unfavourably with the prophetic outlook on the future. There is insufficient basis for hope and promise, and in place of the faithfulness of God there is only the plan of God which has been fixed from the beginning of time.16 Moltmann is struck more by the differences between prophetic, historical thinking and apocalyptic ideas than by the similarities. While he sees much that is theologically important in apocalyptic thought 'the New Testament did not close the window which apocalyptic had opened for it towards the wide vistas of the cosmos'17 - his interest is in the political implications of the theology of hope rather than, as Pannenberg, in the potential of apocalyptic thought to throw new light on ontological questions. Gerhard Sauter also makes less than enthusiastic reference to apocalyptic. What interests him is not apocalyptic ideas about the future, but the capacity of apocalyptic thought to challenge every world-view that *4 RAH, 13. 15 16 17
See Pannenberg's second thesis on revelation; RAH, 131-5. Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 135. Moltmann, Theology of Hope, 138. 30
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
is self-contained. Preoccupation with the details of the future can be a form of escape from the troubles of the present. Theology should focus on the ground of our hope rather than the end of all things. Sauter calls for a clear distinction between eschatology and adjacent concepts such as apocalyptic: The concept of eschatology must be pointed up as talk of God which is determined by God's coming. God's coming means adventus and futurum, God's coming to be present both today and in what still lies ahead. Eschatology would then be extricated from the almost explosive profusion of reflections on the nature of time, conceptions of history ..., hermeneutical questions of the interpretation of biblical expectations and linguistic aporia. It would concentrate on the eschatos rather than on the eschata: on Jesus Christ... as 'the first and the last and the living one'.18
Sauter, in explicit opposition to Pannenberg, does not think that theology has any obligation to determine what the end of history is or means.19 The sharpest critique of Pannenberg's appeal to Jewish apocalyptic has come from William R. Murdock and Hans Dieter Betz. Betz disputes the contention that in apocalyptic writings history is understood as a universal process, proceeding according to a kind of divine master plan.20 Not only do some apocalyptic writings make no reference to history, but universal history is not the central theme in apocalyptic. Apocalyptic is not the climax of a theology of salvation-history, but contradicts it. Most serious is the criticism that one cannot look to apocalyptic for a view of universal history. It is supported by Murdock, who says that the apocalyptic schemata often do not even cover the whole of history. They do not intend to present a theology of history.21 If there is an implicit understanding of history, it is dualistic; history is not only the working out of the divine plan, but also, in part, of the demonic will. The eschaton means the termination of the process of history, not its culmination, 18
Sauter, Eschatological Rationality, 145f.; Sauter's emphasis. Sauter, Eschatological Rationality, 149. 20 See H. D. Betz, The Concept of Apocalyptic in the Theology of the Pannenberg Group', in Funk (ed.), Apocalypticism, 192-207, esp. 195-7, 20 if. 21 William R. Murdock, 'History and Revelation in Jewish Apocalypticism', Interpretation 21.2, April 1967, 167-87. 19
31
GOD AND THE FUTURE
and the alleged eschatological revelation cannot be interpreted as 'the final brilliant burst of light ... at the end of a history-long candlelighting service'. In Murdock's view, Pannenberg's claim of continuity between history and the eschaton cannot be supported. Rather, his scheme is a form of German idealism.22 It remains to consider whether these criticisms hit their mark. Pannenberg continues to think that apocalyptic eschatology provides an important foundation for his systematic theology.13 In an essay on the relation between concepts and truth he refers again to the significance of the biblical experience of reality, especially Jewish apocalyptic, for philosophical reflection.24 However, while remaining convinced of the validity of his position, he is open to the possibility of a more differentiated view of apocalyptic.25 Although he himself has not pursued this task in detail, the last few decades have seen the appearance of important work on apocalyptic, which must be briefly considered. The emerging picture of apocalyptic The word 'apocalyptic' is used to mean a variety of distinct (though related) things. It is not clear whether the word is a noun or an adjective; it is used as both. In the recent study of apocalyptic terminological clarity and understanding both increased. In popular speech 'apocalyptic' can simply mean 'violent' or 'cataclysmic'. It also suggests speculation about the future of the world. It is also associated with 'fanatical millenarian expectation', and the apocalypse of Daniel has often been used by millenarian groups.26 Since the term comes from apokalypsis, meaning 'revelation' or 'disclosure', it denotes for some the 'revelation of the divine mysteries through visions or some other form of immediate disclosure of heavenly truths'.27 22
Murdock, 'History and Revelation in Jewish Apocalypticism', 187. 3 See the 'Postscript to the Second Edition' of RAH, 192. See also STi, 207-11, 227. 24 W. Pannenberg, Metaphysics and the Idea of God (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1990), 109; hereafter MIG. 25 /GM, znd edn., 1977, 401. 26 John J. Collins, The Apocalyptic Imagination: An Introduction to the Jewish Matrix of Christianity (New York: Crossroad, 1984), i. 27 Christopher Rowland, The Open Heaven: A Study of Apocalyptic in Judaism and Early Christianity (New York: Crossroad, 1982), 70. 2
32,
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
Paul Hanson suggests that the term should be understood at three distinct levels.28 First, it refers to a particular genre of literature, through which apocalyptic writers typically conveyed their messages. Second, it can refer to apocalyptic eschatology as a religious perspective, a way of viewing divine plans in relation to events in the world. Third, the term can also refer to 'the symbolic universe in which an apocalyptic movement codifies its identity and interpretation of reality'. Apocalyptic is not systematic or uniform; it includes ideas, symbols and themes, all 'highly eclectic in nature and characterized by the esoteric, the bizarre, and the arcane'. An apocalypse is a genre of revelatory literature with a narrative framework, in which a revelation is mediated by an otherworldly being to a human recipient, disclosing a transcendent reality which is both temporal, insofar as it envisages eschatological salvation, and spatial insofar as it involves another, supernatural world.29
This is the core of the genre, describing works like i Enoch, Daniel, 4 Ezra, 2 Baruch, Apocalypse of Abraham, 3 Baruch, 2 Enoch, Testament of Levi 2-5, the Apocalypse of Zephaniah and, in part, Jubilees and the Testament of Abraham. In the New Testament the book of Revelation (an 'apocalypse of Jesus Christ', 1:1) is the clearest example of apocalyptic literature. In some apocalypses ('historical') there is a review or summary of history. In others there are details of other-worldly regions. Collins differentiates between two streams of Jewish apocalypses: one is characterised by visions and has an interest in the development of history; the other is marked by other-worldly journeys and has an interest in cosmological speculation.30 Common to both streams, however, is a view of the world as mysterious. Therefore, as Collins puts it, revelation must be transmitted from a supernatural source, through the mediation of angels; there is a hidden world of angels and demons z8
Paul D. Hanson, 'Apocalypticism', The Interpreter's Dictionary of the Bible, Supplementary Volume (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1976), 18-34, esp. 2,9-30. Z9 Collins reports some of the findings in The Apocalyptic Imagination, ch. i. The quotation and some of the material that follows is on ^L 30 Rowland, The Open Heaven, 5.
33
GOD AND THE FUTURE
that is directly relevant to human destiny; and this destiny is finally determined by a definitive eschatological judgment. In short, human life is bounded in the present by the supernatural world of angels and demons and in the future by the inevitability of a final judgment.31
This view of the world is not restricted to works that are technically 'apocalypses'. Other types of literature are related to this genre. It is important to distinguish apocalyptic from eschatological material, though there is overlap. Apocalyptic literature is not just a sub-group of eschatology; it deals in the categories of space as well as time. On the other hand, there are eschatological writings which do not belong to the genre of apocalyptic. Rowland restricts the term 'apocalyptic' to works which 'purport to offer disclosures of the heavenly mysteries, whether as the result of vision, heavenly ascent or verbal revelation5.32 There is no consistent eschatology in apocalyptic literature. Scenarios of the end of history are typical of historical apocalypses, such as Daniel. However, the fact that such scenarios do not feature in other types of apocalypse does not imply that there is no recognisable apocalyptic eschatology.33 In some there is a focus on the judgment of individuals after their death; Collins concludes that there is a clear hope of transcending death in late post-exilic Judaism.34 Belief in two spheres of life, not necessarily in temporal succession as two aeons but also as two storeys in the universe, is common to many apocalypses. In Collins's view, the idea of a transition from one sphere of life to another was more prominent in second-century Judaism than ideas such as the resurrection of the body or the transformation of the earth.35 However, the details of the heavenly sphere, which are prominent in the nonhistorical apocalypses, would be of great interest to those who believed that the transition from this sphere of life to the heavenly 31
Rowland, The Open Heaven, 7. Rowland, The Open Heaven, yof. 33 Collins, The Apocalyptic Imagination, 9. 34 J. J. Collins, 'Apocalyptic Eschatology as the Transcendence of Death', in Paul D. Hanson (ed.), Visionaries and Their Apocalypses (Philadelphia: Fortress Press; London: SPCK, 1983), 78. 3 5 Collins, 'Apocalyptic Eschatology as the Transcendence of Death', 73. He says that the idea of a resurrection of the body, although clearly in view in Daniel 12:2, 'was hardly envisaged at the time.' Note that Collins is here restricting himself to material from the znd century BCE: see p. 69. 32
34
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
one would occur at the end of the present age. Thus even in the different types of apocalyptic there are probably common elements. The picture that emerges from recent study of apocalyptic is one of considerable heterogeneity; it has become much less monochrome.36 Boundaries are fluid; there is some continuity between the post-exilic prophetic movement - perhaps 'the dawn of apocalyptic' - and the apocalyptic movement as such. Isaiah 56-66 already sees the need of divine intervention, in the form of a new heaven and a new earth. What is not found in these prophetic writings is interest in the heavenly world and the eschatological judgment. Yet post-exilic prophecy provided some of the raw materials for later apocalypses.37 One can also no longer speak of the apocalyptic movement, for there were various movements. Some texts appear to belong to a common tradition; others reveal very different theological traditions. The situations which were being addressed also varied greatly. In view of these differences, generalisations are risky. Nonetheless, Collins ventures the following summary of a distinctive apocalyptic perspective, from which any problem is viewed. It is framed spatially by the supernatural world and temporally by the eschatological judgment. The problem is not viewed simply in terms of the historical factors available to any observer. Rather it is viewed in the light of a transcendent reality disclosed by the apocalypse. The transcendent world may be expressed through mythological symbolism or celestial geography or both. It puts the problem in perspective and projects a definitive resolution to come.38
This perspective governs both of the basic types of apocalyptic referred to earlier, despite the differences between them. If caution is necessary in making general statements about apocalyptic, criticisms also require an awareness of its pluriform nature. Pannenberg's early critics of his understanding of apocalyptic can now be seen as standing on less solid ground in their criticisms. Murdock's criticism that Pannenberg fails to see the antithetical relation between history and eschatology and that he sees the 36 P. Hanson, The Dawn of Apocalyptic (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1979, revised edn.). 37 Collins, The Apocalyptic Imagination, 2.0. 38 Collins, The Apocalyptic Imagination, 32.
35
GOD AND THE FUTURE
eschaton as a telos rather than a terminus is not substantiated by the research of recent decades. Whether there is a new age or a new space, apocalyptic views God as inaugurating a new sphere of existence. On the more difficult issue of basing a concept of universal history on apocalyptic, there is a balance of opinion. Some writers discern a strong interest in history in apocalyptic; others see a rejection of history. Hanson regards an abdication of responsibility to the historical realm as a feature of Jewish apocalyptic, but he does not see this as the collapse of the notion of the historical.39 Does this leave Pannenberg's claim that history is seen as a universal process in Jewish apocalyptic secure? The claim really requires more detailed substantiation. On the other hand, it has not been convincingly refuted. Perhaps the idea of universal history as an explicit theme is less prevalent in apocalyptic thought than Pannenberg supposed, but it does not need to be explicitly thematised on a major scale. David Polk, who does not see this as a major theme in apocalyptic thought, makes the decisive point: 'history as a whole is embraced for the first time when an envisioning of its anticipated consummation arises'.40 On this basis Pannenberg might well think he can 'rest his case'. We should consider the place of the concept of God's kingdom or rule in apocalyptic thought. The term 'kingdom of God' is uncommon outside the Synoptic Gospels. It occurs in the Old Testament only once (i Chron. 28:5). There are several references to 'his' or 'your' kingdom, where the meaning must be God's kingdom. In Daniel it is said that God will set up a kingdom that shall never be destroyed; it will 'crush all these kingdoms and bring them to an end' (1:44). God will not set up a kingdom like other kingdoms; God's kingdom is God's kingship, God's kingly rule. The idea of God as king is not uncommon in the Old Testament. Sometimes God's kingship is seen as present, especially in the Psalms. In the prophets, a day is envisaged when God will establish God's rule, not merely in Israel but over the whole world.41 39 P. Hanson, 'Old Testament Apocalyptic Reexamined', in Hanson (ed.), Visionaries and Their Apocalypses, 57 (note 19) & 59!:. 4° D. Polk, On the Way to God (Lanham: University Press of America, 1989), 169. 41 See G. E. Ladd, The Presence of the Future: The Eschatology of Biblical Realism (London: SPCK, 1974), 46-59.
36
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
In the course of time God's rule is thought of in eschatological terms. The Gentiles will be included in those who live under God's kingship. There will be peace and justice for all people, and evil will be overcome. As king, God is judge of all the earth, but the end result will be God's salvific presence in the world. As the political fortunes of Israel sank to their lowest ebb, the expression of God's kingly power is more and more awaited in a final act of judgment, beyond what is generally envisaged by the postexilic prophets. This is on the way to an apocalyptic view of the future. There are few explicit references to the kingdom of God in the literature of the inter-testamental period. Its use in Dan. 2:44 has been noted. The clearest use of the term occurs in the Wisdom of Solomon (10:10) and the Psalms of Solomon (17:3). In other passages the rule of God is referred to. In the Apocalypse of Baruch there is a vision about the consummation of all things in a messianic kingdom through which God's reign on earth will be established (53-77). This is the culmination of history, which will open up a glorious future in the form of a resurrection.42 There are other passages from inter-testamental literature in which the idea of God's kingdom occurs in connection with God's decisive intervention in history and the final state of the redeemed.43 However, the relative paucity of explicit references to the kingdom or rule of God in intertestamental literature is an insufficient basis for a judgment that God's sovereign rule is a matter of indifference to the apocalyptic writers.44 Whilst their focus may be on particular themes or images, such as details of the heavenly world, there is an overarching concern with God's victory over all that resists God's will. As Rowland says, 'the dominion of the barbarian power will only be temporary and the vindication of the righteous [is] assured'.45 To speak of this expectation is to voice the hope of the victory of the kingly rule of God. If the idea of God's rule or kingship were rare in the expression 4Z
This was probably written in the first century BCE, and may thus be influenced by Christian usage. 43 See N. Perrin, The Kingdom of God in the Teaching of Jesus (London: SCM Press, 1963), 168-85. 44 Pannenberg acknowledges that the idea of the divine rule is 'relatively rare' in apocalyptic; STz, 326. 45 Rowland, The Open Heaven, 179.
37
GOD AND THE FUTURE
of eschatological hope in the inter-testamental period, especially in apocalyptic movements or groups of that time, the centrality of the kingdom of God in the message of the Baptist and Jesus would require explanation. The Baptist was certainly an apocalyptic figure. In his preaching the imminence and consequences of the conflict between those who were faithful to God and those who were not, were sounded forth in the wilderness of Judea; this conflict was but the visible aspect of a truly cosmic battle between 'the sons of light' and 'the sons of darkness'.46 However, the argument cannot be settled by counting the number of occurrences of the term 'kingdom of God'. The paucity of explicit references to the 'kingdom of God' in apocalyptic literature is not easily explained. However, the confident expectation of God's decisive intervention and judgment cannot be separated from the confidence that God's rule will be decisively established. When we turn to the preaching of John the Baptist and Jesus we find no paucity of reference to the kingdom of God. The kingdom of God in the message of Jesus The kingdom of God is central in Pannenberg's theology. We must now examine Pannenberg's understanding of Jesus' message of the kingdom of God, looking in particular for points of continuity and discontinuity between Jesus' understanding of it and that of apocalyptic thought. As the integrating theme of Jesus' preaching, the kingdom of God has been the subject of close scrutiny by New Testament scholars. In Pannenberg's view, the proclamation of the imminent kingdom of God was at the centre of Jesus' message; he announced its dawning in his own activity.47 This is not controversial. What is a matter of dispute is how Jesus understood the rule of God. Pannenberg regards Jesus' view of the kingdom of God as eschatological, and much closer to the apocalyptic expectation of God's decisive intervention in the world than to rabbinic views. The rabbinic view did not lack eschatological content, for a sense of the eschatological future was part of all the streams of Jewish religious thought. However, for rabbinic Judaism 'the eschaton 46 See the Dead Sea Scroll, The War of the Sons of Light and the Sons of Darkness'. 47 STi, 2.59; 5T2, 311.
38
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
cannot give more than the Law is able to give'.48 The revelation of God in the Torah will not be surpassed. In apocalyptic the focus is on the final act of salvation and judgment in which God will demonstrate conclusively God's kingly power and rule. The apocalyptic world of ideas was the environment in which Jesus lived. His attitude toward the Torah sets him apart from a rabbinic way of thinking. But it would be saying too much to describe Jesus as an apocalyptic visionary. Jesus' message can only be understood within the horizon of apocalyptic expectations - a view for which Pannenberg had plenty of support49 but Jesus is profoundly different from apocalyptic visionaries; he was 'not an apocalyptic seer nor a collector of apocalyptic traditions'.50 The crucial difference, apart from the scarcity of apocalyptic visions in his preaching, is that he understood the kingdom's coming as imminent and as the work of a 'fatherly' God, whilst apocalyptic thought typically emphasises the judgment of God and details of the heavenly world. The contrast should not be overdrawn, for Jesus cannot be understood in isolation from apocalyptic ideas. What, then, is new in Jesus' understanding of the kingdom of God? Some light is thrown on this by the fact that Jesus, having been in the circle of John the Baptist, goes his own way. The Baptist is more typical of the movement of apocalyptic expectation, notably in his emphasis on the imminent judgment of God. This is not absent from Jesus' preaching, as Mark 1:15 shows; the present is a time for receiving good news, but also a time for repentance. But the message of Jesus and the message of the Baptist are very different. Kasemann says that the Baptist's message of the distant God who is coming as judge recedes strangely into the background, and the legal rigorism of the Pharisees and the people of Qumran ... is broken through, while 48
Wilckens, The Understanding of Revelation Within the History of Primitive Christianity', RAH, 61. 49 See e.g. G. Bornkamm, Jesus of Nazareth (London: Hodder &: Stoughton, 1960), 66. E. P. Sanders describes the world-view of first-century Judaism as 'eschatological (or apocalyptic)', and adds that 'Jesus obviously shared it'; Jesus and Judaism (London: SCM Press, 1985), 124, 375^, note 3. 50 /GM, 61; The Revelation of God in Jesus of Nazareth', in J. M. Robinson and J. B. Cobb (eds.), Theology as History (New York: Harper & Row, 1967), 112. 39
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the latter's apocalyptic dreams of a holy war inevitably appear as sheer absurdity. Jesus ... speaks of the coming of the basileia in a different sense from the Baptist and contemporary Judaism, namely, not exclusively, or even only primarily, in relation to a chronologically datable end of the world.51
Pannenberg bluntly says, 'Jesus not only issued a call to repentance, but with full authority he granted to the [people] he met the salvation expected in the future.'52 This was a clear departure from apocalyptic thought; it also implies much about the messenger. For Pannenberg, Jesus' message of the kingdom of God is closely connected with his view of God as the 'Father' in heaven. Jesus' addressing God as abba expresses a unique sense of God's immediacy, but the nearness to God that is expressed in this form of address is identical with the eschatological nearness of God's kingdom.53 God is to be trusted as one trusts a parent, both in respect of the necessities of every day and in relation to God's kingdom, for which people must strive but which it is also the Father's pleasure to give to his 'little flock' (Luke 12:31-32). The Father knows what his people need (Luke 11:30). As Wilckens says, 'In the view of Jesus, to entrust oneself to God's everyday care and to direct oneself totally with intense expectation toward the approaching Kingdom of God coincide.'54 The point of connection is the immediacy or nearness of God. Pannenberg sees here the most striking modification of the apocalyptic tradition which forms the general framework of Jesus' thinking. The nearness of God's kingdom is the basis for knowing God's nearness in the events of ordinary life. The nearness of God raises the question of the relation between God's kingdom as present in the ministry of Jesus and as a still future reality. This question, as Sanders shows, is not easily settled.55 51 E. Kasemann, 'On the Topic of Primitive Christian Apocalyptic', in Funk (ed.), Apocalypticism, 104. 5 Z /GM, 2,17; see also STz, 317. U. Wilckens says, 'the radical nearness of the eschatological judgment, as it was presupposed in the preaching and conduct of the Baptist, was transformed by Jesus into the message of the radical nearness of salvation in the inbreaking reign of God'; RAH, 7i53 /GM, 2.Z9-32. 54 /GM, 2.30; cf. Wilckens, RAH, 117, note 35. 55 Jesus and Judaism, 133-6.
40
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
There are six clear types of 'kingdom' sayings attributed to Jesus.56 Complete clarity about whether the kingdom of God in Jesus' message is mainly future or mainly present is impossible. However, if forced to choose between a future and a present meaning, Sanders will say that it is 'immediately future'. 57 Jesus indeed believed the power of God to be working in his own ministry, that is, in the present, but the kingdom of God as such is a future reality. Jesus teaches his disciples to pray for its coming (Matt. 6:10). Clearly, Jesus did not speak of the kingdom of God with the conceptual precision of a philosopher. But the problem is perhaps not linguistic as much as ontological. We do not understand how something can be both future and present at the same time. As we shall see, it is the notion of time that is under challenge here. Given this problem, we must be content with a series of cameos when thinking about the kingdom of God.58 This should come as no surprise, given that Jesus spoke of the kingdom in parables, enacting it as much as proclaiming it. Only a very nuanced statement is likely to come near the truth. B. Chilton and J. McDonald suggest that if Jesus' initial proclamation is of the 'imminence' of the Kingdom, the performance of the message, both in his preaching and teaching, effects the present 'crisis' in time, the 'moment of truth', the encounter with the Kingdom. The language of imminent approach subtly shades into that of present invitation. The Kingdom that intersects time is 'at hand' in the sense that it may be entered.59
R. Funk thinks that we have to transcend our normal understanding of temporality; if we have to ask 'When?' we have already misunderstood. 'The kingdom arrives as both the "out of which" and the "into which" of existence that is caught up in the transition from man's present to God's future.'60 The present and 56 Sanders, Jesus and Judaism, 141-50. The difficulty is knowing where the emphasis should be placed; cf. 156. 57 Sanders, Jesus and Judaism, 152. 58 B. Chilton and J. McDonald, Jesus and the Ethics of the Kingdom (London: SPCK, 1987), 61. 59 Chilton and McDonald, Jesus and the Ethics of the Kingdom, 61. 60 R. W. Funk, 'Apocalyptic as an Historical and Theological Problem in Current New Testament Scholarship', Apocalypticism, 182.
41
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the future cannot be separated; 'authentic temporality means the coincidence of the horizons of time5. For Pannenberg, too, language has to be stretched to express the kingdom's presence and its futurity. But the fact remains that in Jesus' proclamation of the kingdom of God future and present are 'inextricably interwoven'.61 Jesus' sense of God's immediacy is beyond question. For those who 'have no other hope than God's future' and 'who long for the nearness of God proclaimed by Jesus', salvation is already present.62- But the kingdom of God is present as the coming kingdom. The futurity of the kingdom of God is primary. In an early essay Pannenberg makes this finely nuanced statement: in the ministry of Jesus the futurity of the Reign of God became a power determining the present. For Jesus, the traditional Jewish expectation of the coming Reign of God on earth became the decisive and all-encompassing content of one's relation to God, since the coming Reign of God had to do with the coming of God himself. Thus, obedience to God ... became turning to the future of the Reign of God. But wherever that occurs, there God already reigns unconditionally in the present, and such presence of the Reign of God does not conflict with its futurity but is derived from it and is itself only the anticipatory glimmer of its coming. Accordingly, in Jesus' ministry, in his call to seek the Kingdom of God, the coming Reign of God has already appeared, without ceasing to be differentiated from the presentness of such an appearance.63
As we have seen, Pannenberg's view of the ministry and message of Jesus is not so unusual. What is new about his theology is the key role played by the theme of the kingdom of God, and especially its eschatological character. This is what Pannenberg makes foundational for Christian doctrine, and what necessitates a 'reversal' in our ontological conceptions.64 However, it is not only Jesus' message of the presence of the coming kingdom of God that turns our thinking about everything else upside down. The resurrection of Jesus from the dead is also understood by Pannenberg in a way that brings a future (eschatological) reality 61 6i
TKG, 53. /GM, 2,2,8.
W. Pannenberg, 'Appearance as the Arrival of the Future', TKG, 133. * TKG, 53-5.
63
42-
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
into the present of human experience. It is important, therefore, to look closely at Pannenberg's discussion of the resurrection, which is the bridge between the ministry of Jesus and the proclamation of the church. The resurrection of Jesus from the dead Jesus' sense of the immediacy of God in ordinary experience was grounded in his belief in the eschatological nearness of God. However, it cannot be overlooked that Jesus' expectation of the kingdom's imminent arrival was not fulfilled; not as Jesus envisaged it. This problem of the non-appearance of the eschatological events that would end this age cannot be minimised. But it was not a problem for long; Pannenberg claims that the resurrection of Jesus was understood by the earliest Christians in relation to the coming of God's kingdom. The question is whether Jesus' resurrection can be taken as a fulfilment of his expectation about the kingdom's coming, as Pannenberg holds.65 The resurrection of Jesus is of fundamental importance in Pannenberg's theology. Its foundational role in his Christology is clear from the structure of Jesus - God and Man. For other doctrines too, especially the doctrine of the Trinity, everything depends on establishing Jesus' unity with God, and this can be done only through the resurrection. The most striking aspect of Pannenberg's discussion of the resurrection is his defence of its historical facticity, which he has maintained in the face of much criticism.66 It is a position not compromised, he argues, by the fact that the resurrection is an eschatological reality - and thus different from the reality of this world - for the overcoming of death implied in this idea has nonetheless taken place in this world and in our history.67 Although the historicity of the resurrection is basic for Pannenberg, we need not consider it further here. We do need to examine Pannenberg's interpretation of the resurrection, in particular his claim that it was understood in relation to the general resurrection. Only in this way can it be shown that the resurrection of Jesus was the fulfilment of Jesus' 65 Pannenberg, The Revelation of God in Jesus of Nazareth', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History', 114. 66 /GM, ch. 3, esp. 98-106; STz, 359-63. 67 STz, 36of.
43
GOD AND THE FUTURE
expectation of the imminent arrival of the kingdom of God. Was the resurrection of Jesus the arrival of the rule of God? This is a big claim to make, as Pannenberg acknowledges, since the resurrection of an individual was not part of the apocalyptic tradition.68 There are three parts to the problem. First, we consider Pannenberg's claim that the resurrection of Jesus was the beginning of the end of the world. Second, we examine whether the expectation of a general resurrection was a significant part of apocalyptic expectation. Finally, we look at Pannenberg's response to the problem of the delay of the parousia. i. The beginning of the end of the world? Those who accepted that Jesus had been raised from the dead would have had a particular understanding of that extraordinary 'event'. This understanding was shaped in part by the nature of the event and in part by the cultural and theological horizon of the first believers, which included apocalyptic eschatology. Pannenberg argues that for Jesus' Jewish contemporaries, insofar as they shared the apocalyptic expectation, the occurrence of the resurrection did not first need to be interpreted, but for them it spoke meaningfully in itself: If such a thing had happened, one could no longer doubt what it meant.69
If Jesus had indeed been raised from death it would have meant the beginning of the end of the world.70 Jesus' resurrection was taken as the beginning of the resurrection of others, at least those for whom he was the Christ. Paul declared him the first of many brothers, the first fruits of those who have died (Rom. 8:19; i Cor. 15:10). As long as the time-gap between Jesus' resurrection and that of others was not felt to be a problem, the resurrection of Jesus was understood as the beginning of the (eschatological) end of the world. The resurrection of Jesus would also have meant the beginning 68 Pannenberg, The Revelation of God in Jesus of Nazareth', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, ii4f. 69 /GM, 67. Pannenberg's claim here is feasible. However, strictly speaking, intrinsic meaning and the act of interpretation belong together. Even when the meaning of an event is clearly determined by the event itself, the element of interpretation is never absent. 7° /GM, 67.
44
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
of eschatological salvation. For Pannenberg 'the resurrection as such already has saving character'.71 The first Christians saw salvation as restricted to those who were Christian. In Israel resurrection was sometimes thought of as the reward of the righteous, especially the martyrs (Isa. 26:19). For some the resurrection would mean everlasting shame, while for the obedient it would be the beginning of salvation (Dan. 12:1-3 and 2 Enoch 22). Furthermore, if the resurrection of Jesus meant the beginning of the eschatological end of the world, it also meant the confirmation of the pre-Easter activity of Jesus.71 This is a key point for Pannenberg, for it means that the problem of Jesus' claim to authority, which the crucifixion had thrown wide open, is resolved.73 Implied in this is the endorsement of Jesus' views on the Torah, as against those of the recognised authorities. This is not to say that everything Jesus had said and done receives explicit confirmation, but it means that he is vindicated in the things for which he was accused of blasphemy, mainly in respect of his role in God's dealings with humankind (e.g. Mark 2:7). Most significant, this confirmation of what Jesus had said and done also implies God's endorsement of Jesus' understanding of the imminent reign of God, in particular his claim that it was already dawning in his own ministry. So Pannenberg concludes that the resurrection fulfilled Jesus' expectation of the kingdom of God: Without the resurrection of Jesus his message would have turned out to be a fanatical audacity. But ... the resurrection did justify Jesus' expectation of the near End. It was in himself that it was fulfilled. Admittedly, this happened otherwise than Jesus and his disciples probably had imagined the announced future. But it is true of every 'fulfilment' that it only rarely corresponds to the announcement prior to it. Nevertheless, in view of the resurrection of Jesus and the eschatological quality of that event, we cannot be satisfied with the simple judgment that Jesus' expectation of the near End remained unfulfilled.74
71
/GM, 78. /GM, 67f. 7 3 /GM, 53-66. 74 Pannenberg, The Revelation of God in Jesus of Nazareth', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 116; cf. STz, 345. 72
45
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Nothing has been said yet about the meaning of the phrase 'the end of the world'. Pannenberg sees it mainly in terms of the resurrection of the dead, understood as the transformation from an old life to a new life. He recognises the problem of speaking about an event that ends history in language applicable to events within history. The end of the world (or of history75) is something in which the meaning of every event is finally established, the destiny of every creature is attained, and the hypothesis of God's reality is established beyond doubt. It must also mean the final establishment of God's kingdom. Can anything concrete be said about what 'the end' means for the world and its history. What is the relation between the old world and the new reality of God's kingdom? Pannenberg has discussed the problem of the idea of the end of history in more detail in later writings.76 Does the end of the world mean the end of everything? If not, is the idea of something taking place after the end of history not self-contradictory? At issue here is the problem of time. Suffice it for now to say that 'the end of history' is an expression of the finite nature of time. Time borders on eternity, which is not the abolition of time but the overcoming of its finitude, the overcoming of the separation of temporal moments from those before and after.77 To say that time borders on eternity is to say that God is the end of time and the final future of created reality is in the kingdom of God. When time ends, temporal history is brought into the eternal presence of God, where creaturely separation from God - but not the distinction of Creator and creature - is overcome.78 Notwithstanding the difficulty of the idea of the end of the age, 75 J. J. Collins warns against a simple equation of the idea of the end of the world (a cosmological idea) and the idea of the end of history (a temporal, historical idea); see 'Apocalyptic Eschatology as the Transcendence of Death', 64f. 76 W. Pannenberg, 'Constructive and Critical Functions of Christian Eschatology', Harvard Theological Review 77.1, 1984, 119-39, esp. 136-9. In 5X3 there is a discussion of the end of time and the end of history. The chapter is entitled The Consummation of Creation in the Kingdom of God'. Pannenberg has in mind both the sense of 'end' and 'completion'; STj, 586. 77 Pannenberg, 'Constructive and Critical Functions of Christian Eschatology', 137. 78 STj, 580-607, esp. 586-95. We shall return to this theme in later chapters.
46
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
it is not difficult to see that the resurrection would have been understood as the end of the aeon, at least as the beginning of the end. It presupposes the inseparability of Jesus' resurrection from the general resurrection. It could not have been otherwise. Paul understood it in this way. Without the language of the eschatological resurrection of the dead, the earliest believers would not have known how to speak of Jesus' making himself known to them after his death.79 It was only for the second generation of New Testament witnesses that the resurrection of Jesus was 'not yet the beginning of the immediately continuous sequence of the eschatological events but was a special event that happened to Jesus alone'.80 We will consider shortly the problem of the delay of the general resurrection of the dead. However, it is clear that for the first Christians the resurrection of Jesus would have meant the beginning of the end of the age. 2. The resurrection in apocalyptic expectation The resurrection of Jesus could not have been understood as such if the idea of resurrection had not had a certain currency at the time. But how much currency, and how prominent was the expectation of a resurrection of the dead within the general climate of ideas? Pannenberg argues that the resurrection of Jesus did not occur in a vacuum; prior to Paul there was already 'a tradition in which the expectation of the resurrection of the dead was cultivated'.81 Belief in some form of existence beyond death was certainly current several centuries before the time of Jesus, even if it was not of ancient provenance in Israel.82 C. F. Evans says that Christians 'did not invent the idea of resurrection'; it arises only within apocalyptic eschatology, and cannot be understood apart from that context.83 Was the idea of the resurrection of the dead as prominent in the period up to the life of Jesus as is usually assumed? It is not the only way in which the idea of a life beyond death was expressed. 79
ST2. 349. /GM, 66. 81 /GM, 78. 8z C. Rowland, Christian Origins: From Messianic Movement to Christian Religion (Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1985), 188. 83 C. F. Evans, Resurrection and the New Testament (London: SCM Press, 1970), 2,0. 80
47
GOD AND THE FUTURE
But it was a significant way, as Pannenberg shows from references in the Old Testament and apocalyptic literature.84 There can be little doubt that the idea of the resurrection of the dead was cin the air', for the resurrection of Jesus could not have been understood as such at all if the idea of resurrection had not been around. Pannenberg argues that 'if the message of the resurrection of Jesus arose against the background of such an expectation, we [can] assume a priori a connection between this message and that expectation'.85 However, if the idea of the resurrection of the dead enjoyed a reasonable currency, Pannenberg's case becomes stronger. Yet the extent of the expectation of the resurrection of the dead in the time of Jesus is difficult to determine; scholarly opinion varies considerably. Some scholars do not regard the idea of the resurrection of the dead as particularly prevalent in apocalyptic Judaism. Collins sees it as only one idea among others. He says that the physical resurrection of the body was 'hardly envisaged at the time'. The most significant aspect of the future hope of second-century Judaism was the transition from one sphere of life to another.86 Was this envisaged without reference to death? His judgment does seem particularly cautious. However, he has support from C. F. Evans, who thinks Pannenberg may be claiming too much. For Evans the general resurrection from the dead was not a 'sufficiently fixed theologoumenon in Jewish tradition ... to provide the necessary context from which the resurrection of Jesus would be immediately read off',87 though he thinks it may lie behind the original Easter faith. Other scholars see belief in the resurrection of the dead as more prominent in late Jewish apocalyptic. L. J. Greenspoon claims that a belief in the resurrection arose early in Israel. By the time of Jesus there was a division over the issue between Sadducees and Pharisees. He thinks it probable that, from at least the second century BCE, the majority of Jews held the Pharisaic view.88 He 8
< /GM, 74f. 5 RAH, Postscript to ind edn., 191. 86 Collins, 'Apocalyptic Eschatology as the Transcendence of Death', in Hanson (ed.), Visionaries and their Apocalypses, 73. 87 Evans, Resurrection and the New Testament, 180. 88 Leonard J. Greenspoon, The Origin of the Idea of Resurrection', in Baruch Halpern and Jon D. Levenson (eds.), Traditions in Transformation: Turning Points in Biblical Faith (Winona Lake: Eisenbrauns, 1981), 247. 8
48
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
regards Daniel 11:2, often regarded as the single undisputed evidence that the resurrection of the dead is known in the Old Testament, as 'the end product of countless generations of speculation concerning man's place in the afterlife'.89 He does qualify the point: belief in resurrection first received 'more than isolated expression' only in the inter-testamental period.90 George W. E. Nickelsburg looks at a smaller range of texts, beginning with Daniel 12:1-3 and concluding with material from the Qumran scrolls, and shows that belief in resurrection, together with belief in immortality and eternal life, is well established in inter-testamental Jewish theology.91 The context of belief in the resurrection is typically that of religious persecution and the need of the righteous to be vindicated. There are many variations in detail in the stories and in the kind of resurrection that is envisaged. Where the situation addressed does not include people being put to death for their faith, there is no need to mention resurrection; 'The malady is not present. The remedy is not necessary.'9Z The different situations from which these eschatological ideas originate explains the prominence or absence of the idea of resurrection in different texts. There are other ways of describing people's share in the eschatological life. Although the matter is to some extent controversial, Pannenberg's claim that there was in the time of Jesus a general expectation of the resurrection of the dead at the end of the age has good support. It does not seem to have been merely marginally there, in the background. Clearly, sense could be made of the resurrection of Jesus from the expectation of the resurrection of the dead in general. However, 89 Greenspoon, The Origin of the Idea of Resurrection', 249. See also part 5 of the essay, 2.81-318. 'A concept of the bodily resurrection of the dead is expressed in Biblical material that ranges in date of composition from the ninth to the second centuries BCE'; 319. 90 Greenspoon, The Origin of the Idea of Resurrection', 3 20. 91 George W. E. Nickelsburg, Resurrection, Immortality, and Eternal Life in Intertestamental Judaism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972). 92 Nickelsburg, Resurrection, Immortality, and Eternal Life in Intertestamental Judaism, 151. Gerhard Hasel, looking at Old Testament apocalyptic material, confirms the view that the idea of a physical resurrection of the dead is a constituent part of apocalyptic eschatology; G. F. Hasel, 'Resurrection in the Theology of Old Testament Apocalytic', Zeitschrift fur die Alttestamentliche Wissenschaft 92.2, 1980, 267-84.
49
GOD AND THE FUTURE
with time apocalyptic ideas had to be recast in the light of the resurrection of Jesus.93 3. The delay of the parousia Jesus' resurrection was not at first understood as separate from the general resurrection at the end of the age. Several decades after Jesus' death Paul still expected the imminent, ultimate arrival of the resurrected Jesus for judgment, accompanied by the universal resurrection of the dead, possibly within his life-time.94 Only when the expected 'day of the Lord Jesus' did not arrive did the resurrection of Jesus take on a more independent meaning. With the parousia of Christ and the general resurrection of the dead still outstanding, does the increasing distance from the resurrection of Jesus adversely affect our interpretation of Jesus' resurrection as integrally related to the general resurrection? Does the delay of the parousia jeopardise the apocalyptic framework of the resurrection, and can the resurrection of Jesus still mean the end of the age? Does Pannenberg's view of the resurrection remain tenable in the light of the parousia's delay? At one level, the question may be answered simply. The church has never, in fact, allowed the increasing length of time between Jesus' resurrection and his eschatological return to cause it to abandon its belief in his coming again 'in glory to judge the living and the dead'. The tension between the 'already' of his life, death and resurrection and the 'not yet' of his coming in glory remains, although it is always at risk of being broken, either through indifference to the future expectation or through excessive preoccupation with it. Pannenberg is right in his observation that 'it no longer presses itself upon us so irresistibly that the resurrected Jesus is the eschatological judge'.95 We have only the witness of the early church to keep this before us. But will the problem of the delay of the parousia become sharper if an interval of two thousand years should become two or three times as long? Pannenberg's view is that it should not; the length of the interval between Jesus' resurrection and the eschatological end of the world is irrelevant. What counts is 'the material analogy of 93 RAH, postscript to znd edn., 192. See also STz, 349-51. 94 /GM, 66. 95 /GM, 107. 50
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
what has already happened in and with Jesus and that for which the apocalyptic expectation hopes from the ultimate future'.96 If they are essentially the same, the length of time between them cannot change their qualitative identity. The difference between the resurrection of Jesus and the general resurrection of the dead is quantitative, not qualitative.97 Thus if Jesus really was raised from death it can be said that 'the general human destiny has occurred in Jesus'.98 Then he is truly 'the first of many'. If the decisive point is indeed the material identity of Jesus' resurrection and the general resurrection - and it is hard to see how Pannenberg's point can be refuted - the delay of the parousia presents no insurmountable problem for Christian faith. This, in turn, underscores the eschatological interpretation of Jesus' resurrection. However, an account must be given of this 'material identity' across this large (and potentially much larger) temporal gap. Pannenberg expresses the material identity of Jesus' resurrection and the eventual resurrection of others by the term 'anticipation' or 'prolepsis', which are equivalent.99 Pannenberg sees prolepsis as 'a new systematic category', to describe the place of Jesus' history and especially his resurrection within the framework of the philosophy of history.100 He is as emphatic about the proleptic character of the resurrection as about its historical facticity. For the resurrection is at once an event in history and the eschatological salvation-event, a past event and one that remains before us as our ultimate future.101 The resurrection of Jesus is an anticipation, 'a pre-realization of the future'.102 Only in this sense can 96
JGM, 107. 97 BQTi, 17998 Pannenberg, The Revelation of God in Jesus of Nazareth', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 114. 99 Pannenberg tends to use prolepsis in connection with the eschaton. Thus the resurrection of Jesus is a prolepsis of the general eschatological resurrection; see STi, 56. The term anticipation generally has a wider use, including the discussion of language, concepts and meaning. However, statements about God are also said to have a proleptic character; see BQTi, 204$. 100 w. Pannenberg, 'God's Presence in History', The Christian Century, n March 1981, 262. 101 Pannenberg, RAH, Postscript to znd edn., 193-5. 102 Pannenberg, The Revelation of God in Jesus of Nazareth', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 113.
51
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the final self-revelation of God, which can only occur at the end of history, have already taken place in the history of Jesus. The delay of the parousia does not jeopardise the Christian understanding of Jesus' resurrection because it is the proleptic occurrence of the final eschatological event, namely, the resurrection of the dead. Of course, the whole idea remains disputable until then, for 'the ultimate divine confirmation of Jesus will take place only in the occurrence of his return'.103 The idea of the return of Christ keeps alive the tension between the resurrection of Jesus and the general resurrection. It is the necessary counterpart to the present hiddenness of Christ in the world.104 Only then will the presence of the kingdom of God in him be finally disclosed, just as the coming of God's kingdom in its fulness also depends on that event. Christians await both as one and the same occurrence; the return of Christ brings with it the completion of God's rule.105 From what has been said in this section it appears that the resurrection of Jesus (as the proleptic occurrence of the eschatological event) is closely connected with the reality of the rule of God. The final coming of God's kingdom and its presence in Jesus' ministry and resurrection are ultimately indistinguishable. Moreover, neither can be understood - in both their meaning and their connection - apart from the general apocalyptic framework of late Judaism, which Jesus shared but modified in some significant ways, and which Pannenberg has made central in his theology. With the concept of prolepsis or anticipation Pannenberg has linked Jesus' resurrection with the eschatological events which will establish God's rule in its fulness. God's kingdom, which will come in its fulness with the 'return' of Jesus, has already come proleptically in the ministry of Jesus and in his resurrection. Differently from the way he may have expected, Jesus' message of the coming kingdom of God received its confirmation in his resurrection, inasmuch as the eschatological rule of God made its appearance there in a definitive and unsurpassable way. 10
3 /GM, 108. 104 w. Pannenberg, 'Die Auferstehung Jesu und die Zukunft des Menschen', Grundfragen Systematischer Theologie, Bd ^ (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck &c Ruprecht, 1980), 117; hereafter GSTz. This essay has not, as far as I know, been translated into English. The return of Jesus Christ is also dealt with in STj, ch. 15, part 4, 608-30. 10 5 GSTi, 117.
52-
THE APPEAL OF APOCALYPTIC
Conclusion We have now looked at Pannenberg's understanding of the history of Jesus, notably his message of the kingdom of God and his resurrection from the dead, in which he finds the basis for his eschatological theology. This message of the coming rule of God is inseparable from the ideas of Jewish apocalyptic which, though strange to our ears, are important for our understanding of existence in the world. No other major theologian has made this as central and fruitful for theology as Pannenberg. His understanding of the eschatology of Jewish apocalyptic, although in need of further differentiation, is substantially accurate. Recent research vindicates his position against some of his earlier critics. It is clear that the idea of the kingdom of God, as proclaimed by Jesus, with its interweaving of presence and futurity, is foundational for Pannenberg's theology. God is God only in the execution of God's lordship, the full expression of which lies in the future. God's being and God's kingdom cannot be separated, 'since the being of God is his lordship'.106 Jesus' references to the kingdom of God are not easily reduced to a systematic formulation, but Pannenberg holds in dynamic tension the contrasting elements implicit in Jesus' own view. The resurrection of Jesus is the basis for all Pannenberg's Christological claims and it clearly has an enormously important role in his theology. The critical question is the relation between it and the kingdom of God. This depends on the relation between Jesus' resurrection and the general resurrection at the end of the age, which has been shown to be inseparable from the final establishment of the kingdom of God. Pannenberg is clearly justified in his view that a sufficient tradition of belief in the resurrection of the dead existed around the time of Jesus to provide the interpretative framework for his followers' experience of Jesus as alive and present after his death. Jesus' resurrection was therefore understood in connection with the end of the age, and thus with the kingdom of God. The eschatological kingdom, which Jesus also proclaimed as elusively but truly present in his ministry, can thus be seen as proleptically present in Jesus' resurrection. On this basis, but obliquely, Jesus' resurrection can be understood as the fulfilment of his expectation of the imminence of the kingdom of God. 106
BQTz, 240. 53
GOD AND THE FUTURE
It may be concluded, then, that Pannenberg has laid the foundations for his system of eschatological theology in his analysis of the ministry and message of Jesus and his resurrection from the dead. With the publication of the three volumes of Systematic Theology it is abundantly clear what a substantial and internally consistent theological system it is. On the whole, the exegetical and theological foundations are solid, although here and there they might be strengthened in the light of new findings in the field of apocalyptic. Pannenberg has been so preoccupied with the detailed laying out of his theological system - the writing of his magnum opus - that there was in all likelihood no time to carry out the modifications to the foundations which he himself hinted might be desirable or necessary.107 In the next two chapters we shall see how Pannenberg applies the principle of future-oriented thinking to the areas of ontology and history, giving particular attention to the idea of the priority of the future.
107
/GM, and edn., 401. 54
3
An ontology of the whole Introduction
I
n this chapter we shall look at Pannenberg's discussion of ontological questions, in particular noting the effect of his eschatological grounding principles. It goes without saying that Pannenberg is emphatically a theological thinker, but he also wants to relate his theology to philosophical reflection on the nature of that which 'is' in its totality (alles Seiende). Theologically, the doctrine of creation demands that the relation of God to all created reality be considered. But Pannenberg also thinks it important to interact with philosophical thought about God; this was influential in the formative period of Christian theology. Early in his career he wrote a good deal about the relation between philosophy and theology, and more recently he returned to some important metaphysical themes.1 In 1965 Pannenberg offered a lecture-course on 'Ontology and Eschatology'. In the programmatic essay, 'Theology and the Kingdom of God', he said that the eschatological understanding of the kingdom of God has ontological implications which cannot be left unexplored; indeed, they are such that the 'priority of the eschatological future which determines our present demands a reversal ... in our ontological conceptions'.2- In a later edition of his Christology, he postulated an 'eschatological ontology' based on the 'eschatological logic' of the history of Jesus, which would 1 TPS and M/G. Pannenberg remarks on this in 'An Autobiographical Sketch', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 17.
> TKG, 54.
55
GOD AND THE FUTURE
be a distinctively Christian contribution to the understanding of reality and call for a revision of prevailing philosophical presuppositions.3 The notion of an 'eschatological ontology' is unusual but it accurately describes what Pannenberg sets out to achieve.4 Jesus' proclamation of the kingdom of God, seen in the light of his resurrection, shapes Pannenberg's view of the structure and nature of the whole of finite reality. The heart of this ontological vision is this: just as in Jesus' preaching the future kingdom of God already determines the present, without ceasing to be a future reality, so the future is ontologically prior to the present and is in some sense determinative of the present - and thus of the past. What Pannenberg means by this bold proposal will occupy us in this and the following chapter. For some years - despite a strong intention to work out the ontological implications of his theological programme - he gave priority to the more strictly theological (or 'dogmatic') task, leading to the detailed working out of his theological 'system'. In his 1973 work, Theology and the Philosophy of Science,5 he did set out his view of the relation of theology to philosophy and other fields of knowledge. But a decade later the systematic presentation of the alternative ontology implied in Pannenberg's theology was still outstanding.6 Only with the publication of Metaphysics and the Idea of God,7 which appeared the same year as Volume i of the Systematic Theology, has Pannenberg gone some way in offering an account of his alternative ontology, at least in essay form. Pannenberg's ontology is indeed an eschatological ontology, in /GM, znd edn., 1976, 410. B. J. Walsh locates such an ontology on the side of 'geneticist' rather than 'structuralist' ontology; Christian Scholar's Review 11.3, 1982, 2.2.9-49, esp. 134-75 Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1976; a translation of Wissenschaftstheorie und Theologie (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1973). In English this title is misleading. 'Theology and Theories of Knowledge' would have been a more accurate title. 6 P. Clayton, 'The God of History and the Presence of the Future', Journal of Religion 65.1, January 1985, 106. 7 Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1990; Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1991; a translation of Metaphysik und Gottesgedanke (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988). 3 4
56
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
which the future has ontological priority. But there is a more fundamental feature of his thought, which should be discussed first. This is his determination to think about reality as a whole. This phrase, against the stream of much recent philosophy, immediately identifies the background of Pannenberg's philosophy. It suggests speculation on the grandest possible scale. But Pannenberg endorses D. Henrich's call for a 'counter-move to the empirical consciousness'.8 Philosophy cannot consistently avoid considering the idea of the totality of reality, since it is presupposed by any particular experience; and theology cannot avoid the same idea as the correlate of understanding God as 'the alldetermining reality'.9 Theology and metaphysics should not, in Pannenberg's view, be done in isolation from each other: More than anything else, theological discourse about God requires a relationship to metaphysical reflection if its claim to truth is to be valid. For talk of God is dependent on a concept of the world, which can be established only through metaphysical reflection.10
It is important for both philosophers and theologians to understand 'the world', by which Pannenberg means not simply the world in its 'finite givenness' but 'the whole within which each individual object receives its place'.11 For theologians to speak of God implies a view of the world. For philosophers to speak of the world requires, in Pannenberg's view, a critical view of 'every form of consciousness that limits itself to perceptions of finite objects'.12 Despite the differences between them, both disciplines should rise above an everyday understanding of the world and press toward the One or the whole which is the ground both of the unity of everything that exists and of its differentiation into the multiplicity of finite things. There is no easy way from this quest for broader horizons to a plausible case for God, but Pannenberg sees in this quest a point of convergence between philosophy and theology. Whilst unable to prove the existence of God, metaphysical thought 8
M/G, 5, 15. Pannenberg is not unaware of the difficulty of the idea of 'reality as a whole', but regards it as necessary; cf. TPS, 304-10. ^ TPS, 305, 3o9f. 10 M/G, 6. Pannenberg takes heart from the signs that philosophy is again taking 'its great metaphysical tradition' seriously. 11 M/G, i6. IZ M/G, i4f.; Pannenberg's italics. 57
GOD AND THE FUTURE
can achieve significant results; negatively, it can provide a corrective to theological ideas and religious images of God, and positively, it can build useful bridges between philosophical concepts such as 'the absolute' or 'the infinite' and theological understandings of God. Pannenberg's agenda, in part, is the age-old problem of the one and the many. When philosophy wrestles with the question of what is common to all existing things, which found its classical form in Aristotle, no area of experience can in principle be excluded. When propositions of extreme generality are advanced about what it is to 'be', assumptions about reality as a whole are unavoidable. Pannenberg believes that every kind of philosophy has, at least implicitly, a theory of reality in general. Philosophy may decline to deal with this problem explicitly, just as it may ignore the question of that which unifies all existing things. But if it wishes to be consistent, philosophy must not shirk the question of reality as a whole.13 This implies a holistic approach to addressing this question. So we begin with Pannenberg's understanding of the relation between theology, philosophy and science. The inter-disciplinary responsibility of theology Pannenberg emphasises the public character of theology. Theology may not seek to occupy some privileged ground, away from the scrutiny of those who investigate other areas of human experience or study the nature of the cosmos. Nor may theology concern itself only with religious or moral experience. In so far as theology makes claims about the world, it is accountable before other sciences; it has to make good its assertions before the court of reason as it functions in the community of 'scientific' discussion. 'Every theological statement must prove itself on the field of reason, and can no longer be argued on the basis of unquestioned presuppositions of faith.'14 This view marks a break with two major positions in modern Protestant theology on the relation between theological truth and other truth. As one observer remarks: With Troeltsch, over against Earth and Bultmann, Pannenberg sees the necessity of relating the Christian faith to the whole of reality. But over '3 TPS, 304. 14 Pannenberg, 'Faith and Reason', BQTz, 54, note 15.
58
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
against Troeltsch, he does not interpret Christianity in subjection to the prevailing world-view of modern man, but rather interprets the whole of reality theologically, submitting his argumentation before the bar of human judgement, being convinced that a Christian interpretation of the whole of reality is more rational than any other.15
This is a position which transcends the division in contemporary theology between 'post-liberal' (Yale) and 'revisionist' (Chicago) views of theological method.16 Pannenberg has often been accused of being too 'rationalist', even 'foundationalist', in his theology, but these criticisms have been shown to be superficial, most recently in a monograph by F. L. Shults.17 Shults makes a persuasive case for regarding Pannenberg as a 'postfoundationalist' thinker, defining postfoundationalism as a model of theological rationality that 'charts a course ... between the Scylla of foundationalist dogmatism and the Charybdis of nonfoundationalist relativism'.18 If foundationalism is the search for certain knowledge, based on self-evident foundational experiences or a priori propositions, and nonfoundationalism is the denial of this possibility and is the strategy of justifying belief in terms of coherence with other beliefs in one's particular context or web,19 postfoundationalism involves two major commitments, outlined by van Huyssteen: First, it fully acknowledges contextuality, the epistemologically crucial role of interpreted experience, and the way that tradition shapes the epistemic and nonepistemic values that inform our reflection about God ... At the same time, however, a postfoundationalist notion of rationality in theological reflection claims to point creatively beyond the confines of the local community, group or culture towards a plausible form of interdisciplinary conversation.20 15 Richard Rhem, 'A Theological Conception of Reality as History - Some Aspects of the Thinking of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Reformed Review 26, Autumn 1972., esp. 181. 16 For an account of these terms see J. Webster and G. P. Schner (eds.), theology after Liberalism (Oxford: Blackwell, 2.000), especially the essays by Webster, D. Tracey and G. A. Lindbeck. 17 F. LeRon Shults, The Postfoundationalist Task of Theology: Wolfhart Pannenberg and the New Theological Rationality (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1999). See also J. Wentzel van Huyssteen, Essays in Postfoundationalist Theology (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1997), ch. 3. 18 Shults, The Postfoundationalist Task of Theology, 26. 19 Shults, The Postfoundationalist Task of Theology, 31. zo van Huyssteen, Essays in Postfoundationalist Theology, 4.
59
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Pannenberg has not directly entered into the discussion of those issues in theological methodology that have recently become prominent; he has not argued a case directly for foundationalism, nonfoundationalism or postfoundationalism. For some this would count as a regrettable gap in his theological system. Nevertheless, he has certainly not identified himself with a strict foundationalist or nonfoundationalist position. Shults regards his theological method as 'consonant with the postfoundationalist model', not least by showing a way of bringing the Christian concept of God into relation with the interdisciplinary dialogue about rationality.11 We shall briefly consider the terms in which Pannenberg has sought to do so. In Pannenberg's view, the task of systematic theology cannot be reduced to the exposition of Scripture, although this will always be a significant element in Christian theology. There can be no retreat to the 'authority of the Bible' as an unquestionable authority guaranteeing the truth of its message. If the task of theology includes the necessary particularity of its relation to a given religious tradition, it also includes the necessary universality of engaging with truth in its totality. Both tasks have to be taken up, difficult though it may be to reconcile them: Systematic theology always takes place within the tension between two tendencies. On the one hand, it is concerned about the faithfulness of theology itself ... to its origin, the revelation of God in Jesus Christ as this is attested in Scripture. On the other hand, however, the task of theology goes beyond its special theme and includes all truth whatever.2Z
Theology has nothing to lose and everything to gain from the decision to bring theological truth and other truth into relation. The question of the truth of Christianity is 'concerned ... with truth itself, which in essence can only be one',Z3 This conviction has two roots: the Greek idea of the unity of truth and the Hebrew idea that the truth of God embraces all other truth. Faith cannot be its own foundation. 'My truth cannot be mine alone. If I cannot in principle declare it to be truth for all ... then it pitilessly ceases to be truth for me also.'24 Shults, The Postfoundationalist Task of Theology, 2.39-43. " BQTi, i. Z 3 W. Pannenberg, 'What is Truth?', BQTz, i. *4 STi, sof.
ZI
60
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
The claim that the truth of the Christian message is a universal truth can only be advanced by open, cogent argumentation. Pannenberg is confident that the truth of the Gospel can speak for itself, without needing 'preceding guarantees', even though the question of the truth of the Christian message is nothing less than the question of the reality of God.25 His theological work is driven by the desire to show that the hypothesis that God exists as the power determining all things offers the most cogent account of the nature of reality as a whole. Statements about God are not verifiable by inspection of their subject matter. However, 'statements about divine reality and actions are testable by reference to their implications for the understanding of finite reality insofar as God is maintained to be the all-determining reality'/6 Theology, in Pannenberg's view, proceeds by a constant dialectic of the particular and the universal. For Christian theology, universal meaning requires grounding in the historical particularity of Jesus of Nazareth himself, but this particularity is not rightly understood until its universal meaning is articulated. This can only be done by speaking of the Christ-event as an act of God. Moreover, 'statements about God refer essentially to the totality of reality and imply an understanding of this whole'.27 This is consistent with Pannenberg's understanding of theology as being essentially about God and all things in their relation to God. 'It belongs to the task of theology to understand all being ... in relation to God, so that without God [it] simply could not be understood. That is what constitutes theology's universality.'28 This gives theology no option but to be open to the contributions of other disciplines of knowledge. A brief look at the range of Pannenberg's theological and philosophical concerns shows the scope of his theological vision. The desire to engage with the concerns of contemporary culture places him, in Louis Dupre's view, in the same 'integralist' movement as Bultmann, Earth and Tillich earlier in the twentieth century.29 Z
5 STi, 52, 60.
26
W. Pannenberg, The Nature of a Theological Statement', Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science 7.1, 1972,, 12. 27 BQTi, 200. 28 BQTi, i. 29 L. Dupre, The Dissolution of the Union of Nature and Grace at the Dawn of the Modern Age', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolf hart Pannenberg, $6L
61
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Before finding the confidence to develop the doctrine of God, he felt obliged to 'acquire a systematic account of every other field, not only theology, but also philosophy and the dialogue with the natural and social sciences'.30 Philip Hefner analyses Pannenberg's interaction with the natural sciences; the 'secular5 description of natural phenomena is taken as merely a provisional version of the matter in question, the theologian having the further task of making explicit a theological dimension which is already implicit in it.31 The attempt to span the worlds of science and theology is significant, given the history of suspicion. There is a good number of scientists who have taken a deep interest in theology. It is rarer to find a theologian of note who also has a sufficiently sophisticated understanding of the sciences for fruitful dialogue, but Pannenberg is one such. He wants to overcome all dualistic thinking between the sciences and theology or philosophy and biblical thought. The idea of God cannot, in principle, tolerate a division between segments of reality. For the same reason, Pannenberg has constantly fought against the privatisation of theology and the subjectivisation of truth. Theology, philosophy and the sciences cannot ultimately operate in isolation from each other. Despite the particularity of their focus, there is a fundamental convergence in their concern not with isolated bodies of truths but with the truth, understood comprehensively and in its unity. Pannenberg 'asks how theology might become more scientific and how science might become more theological'.3Z However, theology's traditional relationship is with philosophy, and it is to Pannenberg's view of that relationship that we now turn. Ontology - common province of theology and philosophy Theologians and philosophers have been discussion partners for many centuries. The relationship has almost always been close. 3° W. Pannenberg, 'An Autobiographical Sketch', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 16. 31 P. Hefner, The Role of Science in Pannenberg's Theological Thinking', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 166-86. 32 - W. Pannenberg, Toward a Theology of Nature, ed. Ted Peters (Louisville: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1993), editor's introduction, 6. 62,
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
From its earliest beginnings, philosophy has stood in a critical relation to religious traditions. Pannenberg says: The origin of philosophy seems to be associated with a discontent at the fact that religious conceptions did not provide what they claimed to provide with regard to the understanding of existence as a whole ... Philosophy, with its conjectures, steps into the gaps in religious tradition and rejects its assertions as inadequate to the nature of the divine, and therefore as failing to do justice to its function.33
The critical task of philosophy in relation to religious traditions has been carried out with great effect, particularly in the modern world, in which the idea of a divine origin of the world has been rejected in much philosophical thought as sheer projection. In Pannenberg's view, theology should welcome the critical function of philosophy. It is not the task of philosophy to generate a sense that the universe is a coherent and meaningful whole; that is part of a religious apprehension of reality.34 The contribution of philosophy is first to submit such a view of the world to critical scrutiny. If it is the nature of religion to assert 'totalities of meaning', philosophy has rightly assumed the task of evaluating such claims against experiences in which wholeness of meaning is yet far from realised.35 Philosophy tests for 'reality'. It has also been critical of theological appeal to authority, insisting that the question of the truth of what is held to be revealed must be an open question.36 But philosophy can also adopt a constructive role in relation to theology. Philosophy can help with 'the thinkability of God'.37 It can help theology to be clearer about its use of language, its forms of argument, its use of concepts shared with other areas of enquiry, and the criteria for determining what is true and untrue.38 One area in which theology particularly relies on philosophical support is in the provision of a philosophy of religion. Pannenberg 33 W. Pannenberg, 'Christian Theology and Philosophical Criticism', BQT3, i 33 f. 34 Pannenberg, 'Christian Theology and Philosophical Criticism', 142. Here Pannenberg acknowledges indebtedness to the young Schleiermacher, author of the Speeches on Religion. ^ BQT3, i42,f, 133. 36 See also STi, ch. i, esp. §5. 37 J. O'Donnell, review of STi, Gregorianum 72/1, 1991, 77. 38 BQT3, izif.
63
GOD AND THE FUTURE
argues that the theology of revelation 'implicitly assumes an understanding of revelation and religion, that is, a philosophy of religion. At this point theological thinking which is self-critical has no alternative but to deal explicitly with philosophical problems.'39 The clarification of the phenomenon of religion is of great importance for theology, but it is fundamentally a philosophical problem, helped in the modern period by the 'sciences' of religion. Pannenberg intends to lay such theological claim to the categories of the philosophy of religion as is consistent with his own theological vision. In the discussion of religion Pannenberg's philosophical and theological interests coincide. Influenced by T. Luckmann and others, Pannenberg describes religion in terms of comprehensive, integrating systems of meaning or 'specific historical institutionalisations of symbolic universes'.40 Such systems of meaning need not be religious in the normal sense, but where the ground of meaning or unifying structure of meaning becomes a matter of explicit concern we are in the realm of religion or the religions. Their essence is the higher or deeper perception of the actual reality of things and states of affairs. Religions are concerned with the most comprehensive framework of meaning, 'a final, allembracing totality of meaning in which all individual meanings are linked to form a semantic whole'.41 In theological terms, this is inseparable from the postulate of a divine reality, which is believed to ground and complete 'the meaning totality of the natural and social world'.42 The task of theology is to offer a justification of such a belief, tested by reference to the world as it is experienced. In Christian terms, God is the ground and guarantor of meaning in the cosmos; this is implied in the doctrines of creation and redemption. The idea of God is 'an answer to the question of the meaning of reality as a whole. Whoever wishes to 39
BQT3, in. See also the early essay, Toward a Theology of the History of Religions', especially part 2, dealing with the phenomenology of religion, BQT2, 71-80. In STi, ch. 3 Pannenberg incorporates a discussion of religion into the structure of his discussion of God. 4° The quotation is from T. Luckman; cf. TPS, 31 if, note 616. On the concept of 'meaning' see Pannenberg's important discussions in TPS, 206-24 and in MIG, ch. 8, 153-70. 41 TPS, 216. 4Z M/G, 167. 64
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
exclude this question must also forbid that religious consciousness through which we honor God as the creator of ourselves and the world.'43 Thus, in religion an ultimate, all-embracing totality of meaning is affirmed. In the great monotheistic religions the reality of God is accepted as a form of the same conviction. Pannenberg rejects the modern secular reduction of religion to a purely anthropological phenomenon. Religion is two-sided: it 'embraces deity and humanity, but in such a way that in the relation deity emerges as preeminent, awe-inspiring, absolutely valid, inviolable'.44 Rejecting Heidegger's view that the idea of God has (wrongly) been imported into philosophy, Pannenberg takes 'God' to have been a theme within philosophy from the beginning, in the question of the ultimate beginning, the prote arche.45 In any case, philosophy's character as unrestricted reflection will drive it toward the articulation of a comprehensive ground of being and meaning. For most of its history philosophy has produced models of meaning. Pannenberg sees the fundamental concern of philosophy as being with 'reality in general, the ti en einai of things',46 the essence of a thing, what in truth it is and what it means. To look at the semantic context of every phenomenon, philosophy must concern itself with the total context of human experience, the whole of reality. His view is that the ultimate truth or meaning of anything can only be seen in this total context. This sounds impossibly ambitious, but Pannenberg says that this totality is accessible to us only in anticipation. Philosophy can provide models of this totality which are like hypotheses, and these can be 'tested for coherence ..., the efficiency of their interpretative components ... and the degree of simplicity and subtlety they achieve in their interpretations of reality'.47 In this way the many areas of human experience can be integrated. This may now seem an unusual use of the term 'philosophy', but mostly when Pannenberg uses it he means 'metaphysics'; he 43 M/G, 170. 44 STi, 142. 45 W. Pannenberg, The End of Metaphysics and the Idea of God', M/G, 12. 46 TPS, 68-70. 47 TPS, 6
65
GOD AND THE FUTURE
uses the two terms more or less interchangeably. Even philosophies that deny a place to metaphysics imply some theory of reality. His meaning is clear from the following: Philosophical enquiry is not concerned with this or that being in its particularity, or with one area of reality which can be separated from others; it is concerned with the being of beings, or in other words with reality in general. This is clearest in the traditional fundamental philosophy of ontological metaphysics, which received its classical form from Aristotle.48
In recent writing Pannenberg speaks not just about the relation of theology to philosophy, but about the need for theological discourse to have 'a relationship to metaphysical reflection', that is, if its claim to truth is to be made good.49 When Pannenberg describes philosophy as 'an inquiry into what exists as such', he has in mind metaphysics; others might use 'ontology', but Pannenberg uses this noun infrequently. Theology and philosophy share a common ontological concern inasmuch as each intends to probe below the surface of what we experience in the world. Pannenberg describes the philosopher's approach as a 'requalifying of the objects that we encounter in our consciousness of the world, rethinking them from the perspective that is achieved by going beyond the finite givenness of the world'.50 What he really wants philosophers to do is to speak of the absolute or the infinite, as a condition of the finite itself. Appealing to Hegel, Schleiermacher and Descartes, Pannenberg argues that the very idea of the finite (implying an ending in space and time and differentiation from other things) logically implies something beyond the finite. It is another matter, of course, to establish that reality actually is what we suppose it to be.51 The concept of the infinite (the actual infinite rather than the mathematical infinite) has played an important part in theology as well as in philosophy. The religious consciousness equates the idea of the infinite with the concept of God. This is easier for the theologian than for the philosopher. There is a gap between 48
TPS, 303. ? M/G, 6; my italics. 5° M/G, 16. 51 This is the problem Pannenberg addresses in The Problem of the Absolute', M/G, ch. z. 4
66
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
philosophical discussion of the infinite and theological discourse about God. For one who believes in God, infinity and absoluteness suggest transcendence, self-sufficiency and ontological priority, and are thus easily associated with God. If the idea of God is already accepted, especially the idea of the one God, it necessarily implies the elements of infinity, absoluteness, perfection and necessary existence. Thus, as Pannenberg says, the concept of the infinite, rather than being a synonym for the divine, functions as a criterion for making theological statements about God.52- For philosophy it is less easy to slide between the concepts of God and the infinite. There is a difference between the philosophical idea of the infinite, which is essentially negative, and the (positive) theological idea of 'an existing being [Wesen] that possesses infinity, absolute perfection, and necessary existence'.53 However, despite the differences between theology and philosophy, there is also continuity between them. For theology the divine must stand at the centre. We do not expect this in philosophy. But philosophical discussion of the infinite, which is presupposed by the existence of finite things, can create a space in which the idea of God can be discussed. There cannot be an unbridgeable gap between someone who looks into a starry sky and is overawed by a sense of the infinite and one who looks at the heavens and sees the work of God's fingers. Is there not in common the sense that the multiplicity of finite things is somehow held together by a unifying power and that, no matter how difficult it is to conceptualise it, each thread of meaning is part of an immeasurably vast and complex fabric of meaning? This is indeed a religious sense, but it is precisely this that was a stimulus in ancient times for the emergence of philosophy.54 Philosophers generally prefer to investigate things that are more manageable. But the larger questions have always been fascinating, and Pannenberg believes that many other philosophical issues depend greatly on how one views the larger ones. Pannenberg regards philosophy as 'an endless process of * M/G, 34. " M/G, 37.
54 Michael Hollis says, 'Wonder is as old as the sight of the stars from the mouth of the cave - wonder about what there is and how it moves and why the gods have ordered it so'; Invitation to Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985), 2. 67
GOD AND THE FUTURE
examining the unexpressed semantic context of experiences .. ,'.55 Its results are never beyond criticism and thus never final. It is concerned with the essence and meaning of experiences and phenomena, assuming that they have an 'unexpressed semantic context'. Whether they do or do not is part of the exploration. The hunch that there may be such a semantic context is not peculiar to theologians. Theology must go further, in Pannenberg's view, than philosophy. In seeking to articulate the 'unexpressed semantic context' of what exists and what happens, theology reaches the question of God, and must speak of God. For God is the 'determiner' of all things in the universe and must therefore be the final 'determiner' of their meaning. The 'semantic whole' which gives meaning to the tiniest things in the cosmos cannot be separated from God. Everything in the world must be seen in relation to God (sub ratione Dei).56 Philosophy does not have this responsibility. It does have the task, Pannenberg thinks, of seeking to understand reality as a whole. This means wrestling with 'the double question of what the unity of existing things consists of, i.e. what is common to all existing things, and what it is that makes all that exists a unity as a single reality'.57 But this is the question of God; it is the question about the power that ultimately determines all things. This is an ultimate question which philosophy may avoid without ceasing to be philosophy, although it is always there in the background. But the foreground of philosophy is occupied by questions which do not absolutely require the idea of God.58 It is clear that Pannenberg regards theology and philosophy as close partners. He has made his case for this with considerable force and clarity, and many will find his argument persuasive on the ground of the unity of truth. There is a field of ultimate questions, ontological and metaphysical, which are the common province of theology and philosophy. Many - both in theology and philosophy - will see these questions as being in the 55 TPS, 2,2,2,. 5 6 M/G, 12,. 57 TPS, 58
303.
TPS, 304. Pannenberg cannot suppress the opinion that philosophy, while free to refuse to address the question of God explicitly, involves itself in a certain contradiction if it refuses to do so. Pannenberg shows that metaphysics is more resilient than was thought in various philosophical movements in the twentieth century. 68
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
background of their respective discipline; they are regarded as too difficult or abstract to engage us concretely. However, in so far as philosophers seek to engage these questions, they are closer to the question about God's existence than perhaps they know. Where philosophers and theologians diverge is on the optional or obligatory nature of explicit speech about God. However, since the concern of this chapter is primarily ontological, we now turn to consider Pannenberg's understanding of the idea of 'reality as a whole' or 'the unity of everything that exists'. Reality as temporality The idea of 'reality as a whole' plays a major role in Pannenberg's philosophical and theological work. It is, of course, an extremely general and imprecise idea, which many would not find philosophically usable or theologically interesting. Pannenberg is well aware of its problematic nature. Perhaps the major problem with the idea of 'reality as a whole' lies in its implied completeness and closedness. Related to this is the problem of the knowledge of this 'reality as a whole'. It is no longer possible, Pannenberg argues, to think of the unity of that which is as 'a totality existent here and now' and to think of the unity which unites this totality as likewise 'existent here and now'.59 It is no longer possible to think of anything that exists here and now as the totality of what exists, for this would contradict the inconclusiveness of reality. Reality is a process, not a fixed structure; the element of time cannot be left out of it. Using the phrase which Heidegger used for his famous title, Pannenberg says that being and time must be considered in their intimate relationship to one another, and the processes which belong to everything that is are never definitively concluded ... When what exists here and now is represented as a totality complete in itself, the points in which changes in it originate are neglected and disguised ... The gaps and absurdities in what now exists, which call for change in the direction of some other possible totality, are concealed or at least passed over by the illusion of a world which is whole and sound. What exists here and now, taken as a totality ... can only be untruth.60
This is an important passage, on which three comments may be 59 BQT3,i3i. BQT3, 131.
60
69
GOD AND THE FUTURE
made. First, there is a recognition that the philosophy of time is an indispensable part of a metaphysics of 'reality as a whole5. The 'historically' of reality is a basic element in Pannenberg's ontology of the whole.61 'Being' cannot be discussed in isolation from 'time'. Pannenberg recognises the importance of Heidegger's insights about the historicity of existence. It is important in this connection also to look at the basic contrast between Greek metaphysical thought and the biblical understanding of reality. Second, Pannenberg underscores the importance of the category of 'process'. Everything that is is in process, and the processes that comprise finite reality are 'never definitively concluded'. The term 'process' raises the question of Pannenberg's view of 'process theology'. In fact, no European theologian has given the philosophy of Whitehead and process thought such detailed consideration as Pannenberg.6z Third, the passage reveals an aspect of Pannenberg's theology which is often not noticed. His refusal to understand 'reality as a whole' merely in terms of the here and now, and his view of 'gaps and absurdities in what now exists, which call for change in the direction of some other possible totality', point to a 'practical' agenda, not only a theoretical one. His concern is not only to understand the world but also to change it. His ethics is an ethics of change or transformation.63 Jesus' message was about the power of God's future on the present. Christianity's concern is not with a 'counter-world of faith' but with the real world, which is the world God creates and reconciles.64 God intends the transformation of this world. 61
Pannenberg says, 'History is reality in its totality'; BQTi, n. MIG, 4. In ch. 6 Pannenberg discusses his major disagreement with process thought: 'Atomism, Duration, Form: Difficulties with Process Philosophy', 113-2.9. See also some of the contributions to Braaten and Clayton, The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, esp. that of John B. Cobb, 'Pannenberg and Process Theology', 54-74, and Pannenberg's response, 32,1-3. There has been an important dialogue between Lewis S. Ford and Pannenberg. Ford's essay, The Nature of the Power of the Future' in the same volume (see esp. 89-94), is a reply to Pannenberg's essay referred to above. Pannenberg's disagreement with process theology will be commented on further in ch. 5. 6 3 W. Pannenberg, 'Sanctification and Polities', in Christian Spirituality and Sacramental Community (London: Darton, Longman & Todd, 1984), ch.643 . W. Pannenberg, Christianity in a Secularized World (London: SCM Press, 1989), 57. 6z
70
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
Two points are especially in need of clarification. The first is the historical understanding of 'reality as a whole'. This point marks a fundamental division between the classical tradition of metaphysics and contemporary ontological proposals. It is also a point of great difference between the biblical view of reality and Greek philosophy. The second point is the coincidence of 'reality as a whole' and the unity of meaning which incorporates but also transcends that which exists now. This point takes up the incompleteness of the process of reality and its openness to the future, and brings together the concepts of the totality of being and the totality of meaning. i. The historical understanding of reality It is a truism that human life takes concrete form in history, but the implications of this were not seen until comparatively recently.65 For many centuries the human being was thought to have a universal and essential nature, which remains constant throughout human history and throughout the course of an individual life. Christian theology associated this with the imago Dei. Only within the horizon of modern historical thought did the essence of the human being come to be seen as a destiny to be attained in the course of time. Human essence is not above time; it is historical. History does not illustrate a constant human essence, but determines, even constitutes it. Pannenberg writes that the Christian view of the human race as a history that runs from the first Adam to the new and final Adam replaced the philosophical concept of an essential human nature that is independent of time with a concept of the human being as historical or, rather, as caught up in the movement of that concrete history.66
It is largely to Herder that Western thought owes this insight.67 Dilthey and Heidegger also radically influenced the consciousness 6
5 ATP, ch. 9,485-532.
66
ATP, 499. One may ask, exactly what is 'caught up in the movement of [its] concrete history'. P. Clayton argues that Pannenberg is committed to having 'some trans-historical things to say as a theologian' about the human person. Structures implicit in human being 'do not disappear in Pannenberg's view, as they do under a fully temporalized ontology' (in private correspondence to me, June 1994). 67 ATP, ch. 2, esp. 47-60. 71
GOD AND THE FUTURE
of historical reality and the historicity of the human being in Western thought. Pannenberg disagrees with Heidegger's idea that the historicity of the human being precedes all historical experience. He argues for an inversion of Heidegger's thesis; our historicity is grounded in the experience of reality as history.68 What is at stake here is not just a new kind of anthropology, but a new way of perceiving the world. The experience of reality as history led to a new model of reality in which the static ontological categories of antiquity and medieval Europe were displaced. R. G. Collingwood remarks that since the time of Descartes and Kant humankind has 'acquired a new habit of thinking historically', with a technique of its own, 'no less definite in its character and certain of its results than its elder sister, the technique of natural science'. This change has transformed every area of thought.69 The historical nature of reality includes the historical character of reason. Pannenberg regards this as the most important direction taken in the understanding of reason after Kant.70 Rather than being seen as having a fixed structure (Kant), reason came to be seen as a process which moves from one stage to the next (Fichte and Hegel). It was Dilthey who wrestled most productively with the historical character of reason. Everything, from institutions to ideas and the interpretation of experience, is the product of historical growth and thus historically conditioned. For Dilthey, historical understanding is not a quest for understanding cause and effect, but for understanding facts and events in terms of 'structures, systems, connections, and coherences - in short ... Zusammenh'dnge\7* Where Hegel saw everything in history in terms of a purposeful and rational process, Dilthey located the meaning of events by reference to their context, immediate and wider. Every event has its meaning in connection with other events, and ultimately with the totality of events. The flow of time will always give rise to new understanding. Historical meaning is ATP, 491, note 18, and BQTi, 35. R. G. Collingwood, The Historical Imagination', The Idea of History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1946, 131-49; reprinted in H. Meyerhoff (ed.), The Philosophy of History in Our Time: An Anthology (New York: Doubleday, 1959), 66-7. 7° W. Pannenberg, Taith and Reason', BQT2, 59. 71 T. Plantinga, Historical Understanding in the Thought of Wilhelm Dilthey (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1980), 130. 68
69
72,
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
therefore always provisional. Understanding reality as history implies openness to the future. As a paradigm for thinking about the world, this historical approach was new, but Pannenberg sees strong continuities between this way of understanding reality and the historical mode of thought in the literature of Israel. He sees biblical faith not as the 'temporary, accidental presupposition of the Western consciousness of historical reality, but the origin to which this consciousness remains essentially bound'.72 His fear that the loss of any sense of God as the agent of history would result in the loss of the sense of the unity of history and its replacement by a multiplicity of cultural and individual perspectives73 has proved to be justified. Pannenberg sees three distinct views of reality at work in the ancient world, together with corresponding views of truth. First, there is the mythological orientation to primordial time.74 Myth is to be distinguished from saga and fairy tale; 'its subject is the events of the primal age, that is, those things which happened at the "beginning" of the present ordering of life, which constitute this ordering of life and manifest their continuing power in it'.75 The real and the true are identified by reference to the mythical beginning. There is a good deal of mythical material in the Old Testament, but its view of reality is not mythical. Second, there is the historical view of reality, which is found in the Bible. On the whole, biblical thought does not expect the future to be a return to the 'first things', but expects the future to surpass everything that has been experienced till now.76 This is the difference between the mythical and biblical views of reality. The biblical view of reality is inseparable from belief in God. For Israel, the reality of God is not exhausted by causing the world to come into being at the beginning. Rather, this God can 'break into the course of his 7* BQTi, 33W. Pannenberg, The Biblical Understanding of Reality', Faith and Reality, 16; also BQTi, 33. 74 Pannenberg discusses myth in The Later Dimensions of Myth in Biblical and Christian Tradition', ch. i in BQTj, 1-79, and in a later essay, 'Zeit und Ewigkeit in der religiosen Erfahrung Israels und des Christentums', GSTz, 188-206, esp. 190-4. 75 BQT3, 3. * BQT3, 61. 73
73
GOD AND THE FUTURE
creation and initiate new events in it in an unpredictable way'.77 Israel understands the world in terms of a linear history which moves toward a goal. The real and the true are associated with the future which God is believed to have in store for the creation; the truth and essential nature of things will appear conclusively at the end of the historical process. The third view of reality is the philosophical view of the Graeco-Roman world. Here being and time, truth and history, belong to different realms. The truth and essence of things are grasped by cognitive effort behind the historical appearance of things. Truth is timeless; it 'underlies the fleeting succession of phenomena', as in Plato's doctrine of the forms.78 Reality and appearance never coincide. The truly real was not that which came at the beginning but that which is everlasting and underlies the fleeting succession of things. Pannenberg comments that philosophical thinking shared with mythical thought a reserve toward history. Historical change was regarded as unimportant, identifying the essential with the abiding.79 The biblical view of reality as history has been significant in Christian history. But its radical implications, especially in the importance it gives to the future, were not seen until the flourishing of historical thinking in the nineteenth century. It was expressed by some theologians and philosophers in the form of a concept of universal history, either in a theistic or non-theistic form. Israel 'not only discovered history as a particular sphere of reality; it finally drew the whole of creation into history. History is reality in its totality.'80 It is striking that this biblical approach to reality should have found new prominence precisely at the time when the notion of divine providence as the determining force of history came under challenge. Clearly, in a significant sense human beings are the makers of history. Nevertheless, the loss of a sense that history is also God's has resulted in the fragmented sense of history that Pannenberg described, namely, as a collection of many histories, with little or no connection between them. Pannenberg has a strong sense of the unity of history, and we shall explore in 77
W. Pannenberg, 'Redemptive Event and History', BQTi, 18. See also 'Wahrheit, Gewissheit und Glaube', GSTi, 2.30. 78 ATP, 4977 ? ATP, 497. 80 BQTi, ii.
74
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
the last section of this chapter why he thinks it is indispensable. In the present sub-section we have seen how Pannenberg makes his claim that 'reality as a whole' has to be understood historically. We turn now to the other main point to be clarified. 2. Reality as a whole as an anticipated unity of meaning The great difficulty of the idea of reality as a whole is that the course of history is not yet complete. What exists now is not a totality complete in itself. Therefore the idea of reality as a whole cannot easily be thought of as having the unity of a system. This creates a tension for theology. It cannot equate the unity and totality of the real with anything presently existing; but it cannot give up thinking about the larger unity within which all things have their existence. The question at issue here is whether the nature of reality as a whole can be known. Metaphysicians have always thought it can be known, but they have generally visualised it too much as a closed system. This is the standard criticism of Greek metaphysics; it regarded reality as existing complete in the cosmos. It is also the basis of Pannenberg's criticism of Hegel, with whom he also has important ideas in common. Hegel failed to keep the future truly open, in a way that would permit new things to be continuously brought forth.81 But the more the system is open, the more its incompleteness forces itself on us. How, then, can it be known as a whole? Pannenberg answers this with the help of two concepts which are very important in his thought: the concepts of 'meaning' and 'anticipation': The totality of reality does not exist anywhere complete. It is only anticipated as a totality of meaning. The totality which is an essential framework for any item of experience to have a determinate meaning does not exist at any point as a totality; rather, it can only be imagined by transcending what exists at any point. This anticipation, without which ... no experience is possible at all, always involves an element of hypothesis, of subjective conjecture, which must be confirmed - or refuted - by subsequent experience.82
This means that metaphysics must be done more modestly. We have to remember our finitude and especially 'the historicity of 81 82
BQTi, 134TPS, 310. 75
GOD AND THE FUTURE
every starting point for metaphysical reflection.'83 Our way of thinking about the great metaphysical problems - especially 'the domination of the concept5 - has to be modified. The old secure foundations are no longer there. In contemporary terms, this is a nonfoundational enterprise: Any metaphysics, if it is to be taken seriously, can no longer claim the character of a definitive foundation, constructed of concepts, for being and knowledge. Metaphysical reflection must take on the form of a conjectural reconstruction in relation to its object, one which distinguishes itself from its intended truth while at the same time construing itself as a preliminary form of this truth. Its characteristic reflective form will thus have to be more that of anticipation than that of concept in the sense of classical metaphysics. Put more precisely, the philosophical concept will reveal itself to have the structure of anticipation.84
The key question is the relation between the anticipation and the anticipated reality. We shall look more closely at this problem in the next chapter, but note for now that Pannenberg's use of 'anticipation' is governed by its theological usage in relation to the idea of the kingdom of God. As we saw in the previous chapter, the structure of the kingdom of God is characterised by an 'already' and a 'not yet' element. It is not a case of a present reality extending into a not yet existing future. Pannenberg sees it as the presence of the future (the 'not yet') in the present (the 'already'). The future remains future, and it must provide confirmation of what is claimed to be already present in the anticipation. But when the confirmation is given, the anticipation will turn out to be 'a real instance of something's occurring in advance'.85 The anticipated future is thus already present in its anticipation. But the anticipation will be ambiguous. Until its true nature is confirmed, the 'anticipation' may as plausibly be understood as something altogether different. Until its confirmation in the resurrection, Jesus' ministry could as easily have been understood as prophetic enthusiasm. The idea of anticipation, as we saw, has a wider application. Pannenberg speaks of an anticipation of meaning, the meaning of 8
3 W. Pannenberg, 'Concept and Anticipation', MIG, 93. M/G, 93f. Pannenberg's italics. 8 5 M/G, 96.
84
76
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
the whole of reality. Because of the incompleteness of reality as a whole, what it all means cannot be definitively known; it can only be anticipated. If it turns out that there is an intrinsic coherence and unity of meaning in reality as a whole - as distinct from the bits of it which we invest with meaning - there will have been grounds for calling our intuitions of meaning anticipations of the real meaning of things. So Pannenberg thinks the meaning of the whole of reality can be anticipated in the present. For some this way of discussing the question of meaning will be foreign. Why, they might ask, should we suppose that there is any such meaning? For Pannenberg, just as the problem of truth must not be narrowed down to the truth of assertions,86 the problem of meaning must not be reduced to the meaning of statements. Every event in history has meaning, depending on the context in which it occurs. For Pannenberg, then, 'reality as a whole' is not only the totality of what 'is'; it is also the largest possible 'semantic whole'. The whole of reality is thus 'the semantic context' of all phenomena in creation (in history), past, present and future;87 it has a semantic character. Thus reality as a whole is to be approached hermeneutically. Here Pannenberg was strongly influenced by Dilthey's project. Dilthey advocated the autonomy of the 'human' or 'cultural' sciences (Geisteswissenschaften], their difference from the 'natural' sciences. The natural sciences aim at the formulation of general laws about phenomena. The human sciences are sciences of the individual and the unique. They are 'value-related' sciences.88 In the latter every event has its meaning as part of a larger semantic whole. This is important for understanding Pannenberg. Dilthey adopted the historical framework of Hegel's thought and his view of truth and reality as the final whole of experience. But, as one commentator puts it, 'the appeal to final coherence works better as a semantics than as a logic'.89 Thus it makes sense to speak of a hermeneutics of totality, which moves from the individual to the whole. 86
W. Pannenberg, 'Die Einengung des Wahrheitsbegriffs auf die Aussagewahrheit'; GSTz, 2.35. 8 ? TPS, 68. 88 The phrase is T. Plantinga's; Historical Understanding in the Thought of Wilhelm Dilthey, 2.7. 89 P. Clayton, in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 134.
77
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Pannenberg's metaphysics of the whole is best seen as an ontology of 'final coherence', in which reality as a whole is understood as a totality of meaning. Pannenberg's theory of meaning owes most to Dilthey's contextual view of meaning. The concept of meaning is not only about the relation of the sign to what it signifies, but also about 'the relation between the parts of a semantic whole and their relation to this whole'.90 This applies to words within the 'semantic whole' of sentences, and to sentences within the larger whole of a discourse. A sentence has a relative autonomy of meaning, but it also exists as 'the anticipation of an indefinite semantic whole which transcends it'.91 We understand texts in the same way, by seeing the whole in terms of the parts and the parts in the context of the whole. But the same semantic structure is inherent in the life of individuals and social groups: The individual life-moments, the experiences undergone by an individual, have their meaning in the context of the course of his life. But the individual is himself, in turn, a part of life-forms and nexuses of meaning that transcend individualized human existence. These, in turn, are coordinated within still more encompassing totalities of historical life - such as peoples and states - and refer beyond all of them to the totality of mankind and universal history. Thus, 'the relationship between whole and parts' exists everywhere in society and in history.92
As one would expect, the discernment of meaning is a complex and tentative task. Connections between events will run in every direction. We do not arrive at a final determination of meaning, but with time we discover further complexes of meaning. New experiences confirm or challenge the perceived meaning. The interpretation of meaning always moves concurrently in opposite directions: from parts to whole and from whole to parts. New experiences produce adjustments to a semantic whole, while a comprehensive system of meaning will also cause revisions in the way in which individual experiences are understood. This is the unavoidable circularity of hermeneutics. We have been considering Pannenberg's ontology of the whole, notably his belief that 'reality as a whole' must be understood in 9° TPS, 115. TPS, 2,17. ? BQTi, 161. 91 2
78
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
historical terms. Just as, in his view, the experience of finite things presupposes the infinite, so events in history presuppose larger semantic wholes. Dilthey said that we cannot know the meaning of a person's life until she or he has died, until there is a whole in which to understand the parts.93 Neither can we conclusively understand the meaning of history until we have arrived at its end But this meaning can be 'anticipated' in the course of history.94 Given the incompleteness of the course of history, the idea of the whole of reality becomes understandable when it is regarded as a semantic whole, to be approached hermeneutically, which is already present in anticipations of the meaning it confers. Can there be a universal history? Pannenberg placed history at the centre of his theology early in his career,95 and the concept of universal history appears first in 'Hermeneutic and Universal History'. Already in 'Redemptive Event and History' Pannenberg said that when we speak of God's revelation in history we must have 'history as a whole' in mind. A 'universal-historical horizon' must be in view, corresponding to the universality of God.96 Theologically, he was insisting that theology's concern is not only with a special stream of history, the history of Israel and Jesus, but with the whole of history. Historically, he was arguing that, although historians normally deal with small bits of history, historical thought presupposes 'a unity of history'. Everything in history 'stands under over-arching continuities'; no single event can be understood purely in terms of itself. 'It is the horizon of world history which first makes it possible to appreciate the full significance of an individual event.'97 The concept of history with which Pannenberg was working in the early essays was one in which history is tied to God's promises. Later a new perspective took its place, that of 'the history of the 93 BQTi, 163. 94
Pannenberg writes elsewhere, The end of time ... is eternity. It is from the standpoint of this end that the essence of each individual thing, the manner in which it has anticipated eternity, will be decided'; 'Concept and Anticipation', M/G, 109. 95 RAH was published in 1961. The important essay, 'Redemptive Event and History' (BQTi, ch. 2) was first given as a lecture in January 1959. 96 BQTi, 67. ^ BQTi, 6SL
79
GOD AND THE FUTURE
transmission of traditions',98 which gave prominence to hermeneutics in Pannenberg's theology. He saw the historical and hermeneutical concerns of theology as closely related, partly converging and partly in tension with each other." The hermeneutical approach moves back and forth between the text and the present situation of the interpreter. The historical approach goes behind the text for the essential content, in order to interpret it within the broadest context possible, not restricted to the present. The text itself demands that a step back be taken to the subjectmatter of the text, for in the face of a variety of interpretations of the text it is necessary to measure these against the source of the Christian tradition, the historical Jesus or the (already differentiated) primitive Christian proclamation of Christ.100 However, the process of interpretation is an open one; what is to be interpreted is not fixed but 'always contains more than is immediately present in it'. Pannenberg sees the meaning as inherent in the content, not as attached to it in the interpretation. But it 'cannot be expressed exhaustively and definitively within any limited horizon of meaning or in any particular interpretation'.101 So there is never a final meaning. He makes two important points here. First, the meaning of something is intrinsic to it; it is not read into it. Meaning is more than subjective. Second, this meaning has a life of its own and is not confined to any single context. The widest possible context will determine its meaning, and this can be nothing less than universal history. Pannenberg aims to establish the necessity of the idea of universal history. There are four points to be made in support of this endeavour. The first is christological. The Christian claim is that in the life, death and resurrection of Jesus the triune God has disclosed the divine life and purpose and has acted salvifically for the world. In this claim Jesus Christ is related to the being and 'economy' of God, so that he is known as Lord and Son of God. Such christological claims must have the same breadth of reference as all statements about God, and Pannenberg sees language about 98
BQTi, xvii, 81-95.
W. Pannenberg, 'Hermeneutic and Universal History', Part i, BQTi, 96-100. 100 w. Pannenberg, 'On Historical and Theological Hermeneutic', BQTi, 139. 101 BQTi, 140. 99
80
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
God as correlative to the whole of reality.102 If God exists, God is related to reality in its totality, and conversely, everything in the universe is to be understood in its relation to God. The second point is soteriological. The person of Jesus Christ has attracted a peculiar claim to authority, universal in scope. 'The appearance and destiny of Jesus already claims for itself universally decisive meaning. This anticipation of universal meaning inherently presses for confirmation by the totality of man's experience of reality at any time whatever.'103 The missionary expansion of Christianity underscores the early Christian conviction that there is no other name through which people might be saved, and that people in every place should have opportunity to test this conviction in their own experience. While the claim of Christ's universal significance constitutes the scandal of the Christian Gospel, universal history is the only acceptable hermeneutical context for it. The third point is hermeneutical. The concept of universal history is demanded, in Pannenberg's view, not only in the course of a historical approach to theology but also as part of a hermeneutical approach. The historical approach to past events requires that they be grasped 'in the continuity of meaning in which they stand, which connects them with the present age of the historian'.104 This implies the overarching concept of universal history. The hermeneutical approach to theology likewise requires the perspective of universal history. H.-G. Gadamer, a seminal thinker in contemporary hermeneutics, makes the 'claim' of the text on the present-day interpreter the centre of his hermeneutical concern. In the act of interpretation the distance between the then of the text and the now of interpretation is bridged. In the process of understanding, the horizons of the past and present are 'fused',105 and a new horizon is formed: When our historical consciousness places itself within historical horizons, this does not entail passing into alien worlds unconnected in I0i 103
BQTi, 156. Pannenberg, 'On Historical and Theological Hermeneutic', BQTi,
141. IQ 4 BQTi, 100. 105 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, ed. G. Barden and J. Gumming (New York: Crossroad, 1982), 2.58. 81
GOD AND THE FUTURE
any way with our own, but together they constitute the one great horizon that moves from within and, beyond the frontiers of the present, embraces the historical depths of our self-consciousness. It is, in fact, a single horizon that embraces everything contained in historical consciousness.106
This is close to Pannenberg's idea of the all-embracing horizon of universal history. But at the last moment, Pannenberg thinks, Gadamer turns back from the implication of his own insights. The idea of the fusion of horizons moves in the direction of the idea of a universal history, for 'only a conception of the actual course of history linking the past with the present situation and its horizon of the future can form the comprehensive horizon within which the interpreter's limited horizon of the present and the historical horizon of the text fuse together'.107 But Gadamer stops short of this. The fourth point is historiographical. Any subject matter at all undergoes historical development and is historically structured. Truth is not 'a timeless identity of a given essential content'; truth itself is history.108 New words will be spoken on the subject, new understanding will come, and it will be related to many other subjects. This presupposes and contributes to a much more comprehensive hermeneutical 'whole', namely, the totality of tradition. Since no boundaries can be arbitrarily erected, interpreters are engaged in a projection of universal history. This is not to say that a universal history can be achieved, for all our knowledge and understanding are provisional, open to correction and confirmation. Ted Peters differentiates between the idea of a 'whole' and the material content of the whole of history, which is beyond anyone's capacity to see. He goes on to say, 'to posit such a wholeness of truth is not necessarily to claim absoluteness for the one positing, because one's anticipatory acknowledgment of the whole is not knowledge of ... the whole'.109 It is clear from what has been said that Pannenberg's concern is 106
Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2,71. ? BQTi, 12.9. 108 BQTi, 131. 109 Ted Peters, Truth in History: Gadamer's Hermeneutics and Pannenberg's Apologetic Method', Journal of Religion 55.1, January 1975, 51I0
8l
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
with the totality of experience, meaning, truth and reality. Theologians may not settle for a discussion of assorted bits and pieces without taking into account the relation of these matters to the most comprehensive semantic whole, reality in its totality. The fundamental reason is that God acts in relation to all things. Pannenberg argues that the totality of things must be understood historically. 'Reality as a whole' is thus 'history as a whole' or 'universal history'. But Pannenberg is a theologian, not a historian. The concept of universal history is not in great use by working historians. We must look briefly at its provenance and consider the question of its legitimacy. The idea that history, with its myriad events and occurrences, forms a single pattern or 'whole' of some kind, and therefore has some all-embracing meaning, is a hypothesis advanced by some philosophers. The philosophy of history is a modern enterprise, derived from the theology of history, which is older.110 The philosophy of history is a speculative philosophy, which aims at the articulation of precisely such an overall pattern of meaning. Many historians consider such thinking about history to be impossible, but others seek 'less provincial' accounts of historical issues.111 They may look for some general principle by which to explain historical movement. The theories that arise in such speculation are usually part of some metaphysical or anthropological theory.112 Speculative philosophy may be metaphysical, empirical or religious.113 The question with which speculative philosophies of history wrestle is whether, in addition to human action and natural event, there is another level or type of explanation which 110
Karl Lowith, one of Pannenberg's teachers, says that Voltaire invented the term 'philosophy of history', and used it over against the 'theology of history'. Instead of seeing divine providence as the leading principle, Voltaire made human will and reason the central category. 'Philosophy of history' meant a 'systematic interpretation of universal history in accordance with a principle by which historical events and successions are unified and directed toward an ultimate meaning'; Meaning in History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949), i. 111 The phrase is used by W. H. Dray, Philosophy of History, Foundations of Philosophy Series (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964), 64. 112 See W. H. Walsh, Philosophy of History: An Introduction, quoted by Dray, Philosophy of History, 65. 113 Dray uses these terms. He regards Hegel, Toynbee and R. Niebuhr as representative of these various types; cf. chs 6-8 in his book.
83
GOD AND THE FUTURE
offers a fuller, richer account of history. Hegel saw it in terms of the human movement toward freedom, which he saw as part of the self-development of the Absolute Spirit. Toynbee studied the rise and fall of civilisations but ended up with a religious view of the fulfilment of transcendent purposes. Others see the world of human affairs within the framework of the purpose of a sovereign God, who alone gives unity to history. In the light of such speculative philosophy of history, Pannenberg's concept of universal history is understandable. He was very likely influenced in this by Hans von Campenhausen, who described Augustine as 'the first universal theologian of history in Western civilisation5, and who urged his students to undertake a comprehensive theology in the spirit of Augustine.114 On the whole, historians are critical of their peers who play the philosopher or the prophet in their historical work.115 Hegel was aware of the ambiguity of history, describing it as 'the slaughterbench at which the happiness of peoples, the wisdom of States, and the virtue of individuals have been victimized';116 yet he asked about the final purpose for which these sacrifices are made time and again. If we ask why this question should be asked at all, the answer can only be that it simply arises in our minds, at least in any culture which does not accept the idea of fate. In Hegel's terms, history is a history of the Absolute Spirit. For Pannenberg, 'history has a unity only in the form of a divine history, a history of revelation ... History cannot be secularized without disintegrating, without losing its unity.'117 The necessity to see history in such terms is a theological one. Is it also a historical necessity? Most historians would deny it; and it cannot be a requirement on historians that they provide us with theories of universal meaning. The historian qua historian will think long before confusing her or his role with that of the philosopher or theologian. At the same time, writing history within larger semantic wholes will appeal to some. Pannenberg "4 J. M. Robinson 'Revelation as Word and as History', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History^ 7-10. "5 In Australia this is evident in the very mixed response among academic historians to the work of Manning Clark. 116 This quotation is from Lowith, Meaning in History-, 53. 117 W. Pannenberg, Toward a Theology of Law', Anglican Theological Review 55, October 1973, 404.
84
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
would challenge the historian's veto on grand frameworks of meaning. His source of inspiration in this was Dilthey, who was certainly no theist. Dilthey did not understand history theologically, yet he considered the theme of universal history to be unavoidable. Pannenberg comments: In the hermeneutic of the historical school and in Dilthey the theme of universal history is intimately related to the old hermeneutical principle that in the process of interpreting a text, the whole and its parts reciprocally illumine each other. The result of the application of this principle to historical knowledge was, for Dilthey ... that 'basically, there can be no other history than universal history because the meaning of the individual itself is determined only from the standpoint of the whole'.08
Heidegger applied Dilthey's key insights to the sphere of human existence and historicity, rather than to history as a whole. Pannenberg finds contemporary support from the Gottingen historian, R. Wittram, who is reserved about the idea of universal history but makes the interesting observation that the unity of history is the 'presupposition' without which it is scarcely possible to think historically.119 Likewise, W. Mommsen, who regards the achievement of a total view of the historical world as impossible in practice, takes the idea of universal history to be important as a guiding principle.120 Pannenberg expresses his position with some care: All historical study remains oriented to the problem of universal history. If this ... assertion is correct, then one may conjecture that the theme of the totality of history is a strictly common frame of reference for both historical and theological work. The historian as such may not usually speak explicitly of God, but his work nevertheless remains oriented toward that theme which on its part, justifies speaking about God, viz., the problem of universal history.121 us BQTi, 162. Pannenberg quotes here from Gadamer's Truth and Method. 119 Wittram's position is ambiguous; in addition to remarks in BQTi, 160 (note 19) and 69 (note 136), see W. Pannenberg, 'Response to the Discussion', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 244. IZO Pannenberg, 'Response', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 243f.
"' BQTi, 159-
85
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Pannenberg is swimming against a very strong tide. If it is acceptable for historians not to speak explicitly about God, there can hardly be a historical necessity for them do so, whether explicitly or in some veiled way. To do so would turn them into philosophers or theologians of history. However, for theologians a theological view of history - history in its relation to God - is not an optional extra but an unavoidable responsibility. It raises several difficult challenges. First, what is at issue here is whether the secular reality of life can be understood 'theonomously'.IZZ This is a form of the question about the relation between the finite and the infinite. Pannenberg does not equate God with the historical process; even Hegel did not do so.113 There is no static 'presence of the infinite in the finite' in Pannenberg's thought. The relation between the finite and the infinite is mediated negatively. The infinite puts the finite in crisis, but also preserves and transforms it: History is not the field of a finitude which is enclosed within itself, an 'immanence' to which one could and indeed would have to oppose a 'transcendence'. History is far rather the ongoing collapse of the existing reality which is enclosed in its own 'immanence' (because centred on itself). The power of the infinite is active and present in this collapse of the finite. Thus the infinite expresses itself in the first place negatively. But because the finite lives not by clinging to itself, but only in transformation of itself ... insofar as the power of the infinite expresses itself also positively, as reconciliation and preservation of the finite in the midst of its collapse.IZ4
Here is the essence of Pannenberg's theology of history. History in its length and breadth and in all its secularity is not merely the sum of human finitude. It is constituted by the presence of God, who discloses God's deity through history. God does this both by affirming the finite and by negating it, by enabling it to transcend itself and become more splendid than it already is and by standing in judgment over the finite, even to the point where the finite IZi
The term is Tillich's. W. Hamilton describes Pannenberg's view of history as 'theonomous'; 'The Character of Pannenberg's Theology', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 186. Pannenberg replies on 148-50. IZ 3 W. Pannenberg, 'The Significance of Christianity in the Philosophy of Hegel', in BQTj, esp. 160-5. 124 Pannenberg, in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 2,5if. 86
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE WHOLE
perishes. In this way God reveals who God is, establishing the divine rule (the kingdom of God) in and over the finite creation.125 Pannenberg no more ignores history's 'slaughter-bench' than Hegel did. God has to be seen in connection with the negative, the evil, and the tragic. Human use of power comes under judgment in the 'perishing' of the finite. Thus the second important issue in respect of God's relation to history is the problem of theodicy. Pannenberg does not regard theodicy as the critical problem some writers take it to be; it should not be given an exaggerated importance on the theological agenda.126 Every doctrine of the faith has the task of substantiating the truth claims of Christian discourse about God. 'The entire process of divine economy leading to [the] final consummation amounts to a self-demonstration of God's existence.'127 Yet it is only in relation to the Christian hope for the glorification of God in the perfection of creation that the problem of suffering finds its proper theological context. In discussing theodicy theologians must avoid another trap. Pannenberg says that I do not think it the task of theology to exculpate God theoretically for the evil in the world. In the face of the horrors of evil every theoretical theodicy would function as an ideological device. There can be only one valid answer to the reality of evil: the eschatological reconciliation of God with his world by that glorification of his suffering creatures which alone will finally prove his true divinity. iz8
Theoretical argument cannot solve this problem; only the practice of faith. Human misery and suffering cannot be alleviated by rational argument, no matter how cogent. There is no solution on this level. Pannenberg insists that the answer must be seen in connection with God's victory over evil through the cross and resurrection, expressed in trinitarian terms.129 Not just the problem of evil and suffering, but the entire 125
Pannenberg, in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 25 3 f. W. Pannenberg, 'Christianity as the Legitimacy of the Modern Age', BQT3, 184, note 4. See also STz, ch. 7, part 3 & STj, ch. 15, part 5. 127 W. Pannenberg, Introduction to Systematic Theology, 12. 128 W. Pannenberg, 'Postscript', in E. F. Tupper, The Theology ofWolfhart Pannenberg (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1973), 3°4129 W. Pannenberg, 'Vom Nutzen der Eschatologie fur die christliche Theologie', Kerygma und Dogma 25, April-June 1979, 93. We shall return to the trinitarian point in the final chapter. 126
87
GOD AND THE FUTURE
problem of God's relation to history in its totality, is susceptible only to an eschatological solution. The reason for this is that history, in Pannenberg's view, gains its unity only from God's faithfulness in God's historical acts,130 that is, through time, and this will not be finally evident until the eschaton. It follows that the concept of universal history has its fullest meaning only in a theological view of reality. This is not to suggest that the idea of universal history is theologically problem-free; it has the same problems as any statement about the biblical God. But it is suggested that the notion of universal history has a justifiable place within the framework of any theology that encompasses the course of history - natural history no less than human history - from beginning to end, from the creation of the heavens and the earth to their consummation. In this chapter we have considered Pannenberg's fundamental ontological vision of a differentiated totality, 'reality as a whole', understood as history in its universal dimensions and in its relation to God, its 'determiner', that is, its creator, redeemer and perfecter. This ontology of the whole is, as we have seen, the single subject of Pannenberg's scientific, philosophical and theological work. The scope of his vision is vast, as is his view of the task of theology, in partnership with philosophy and the sciences. But at the end of the day, all explanations and solutions call for eschatological confirmation, for only then will we know what at present we see dimly. In the meantime we have to see everything in the framework of larger semantic wholes. However, for Pannenberg the future is far more than a confirming reality at the end of time. He sees it as having an ontological priority over present time and past time. This truly innovative aspect of his ontology we take up in the next chapter.
T
3° W. Pannenberg, The God of History', The Cumberland Seminarian 19.2-3, 1981, 30. This essay is a translation of 'Der Gott der Geschichte', GST2, II2.-2.8.
88
4
The ontological priority of the future Introduction
I
n this chapter we shall consider the nature of Pannenberg's distinctive eschatological ontology. The key points of focus will be the ontological priority of the future and its relation to the present, and here the concept of anticipation is central; indeed, without it the future can have no relation to the present. We shall also examine Pannenberg's view of time. In this chapter we are still concerned with ontology, but his ontological ideas are closely connected with his ideas about God. Certainly there has to be consistency between them. Pannenberg thinks of the ultimate future as the eschatological rule of God, in which all things will have their right relation to God. God is the future, and if God truly /s, the ultimate future is inconceivable apart from the reality and power of God. The genesis of Pannenberg's fascination with the future as ontologically significant is not simple. We saw in the early chapters how the idea of the kingdom of God and the resurrection of Jesus were decisive in shaping Pannenberg's entire theological vision. However, this eschatological theology also has other roots. His preoccupation with modern atheism also pushed him in the direction of a view of God as not simply an 'existing' being; God must transcend everything that is real at present. As he said in an early essay, God is 'not among the beings existing in the world, but is the Lord of the future, toward whose coming the world is moving'.1 An idea of increasing importance is the association of God with the 1
W. Pannenberg, The Question of God', BQTz, 2.33.
89
GOD AND THE FUTURE
future of God's reign, and its effect on the present. In a word, 'the deity of God is his rule'.z The influence of the neo-Marxist philosopher, Ernst Bloch, on the theology of Moltmann is well known, and the question of a possible influence on Pannenberg's idea of God as future is worth asking. Bloch's great work on hope, The Principle of Hope,3 was published in 1959, but Pannenberg does not regard it as influential on his own thinking. In 1965 he wrote 'The God of Hope' for a Festschrift for Bloch's eightieth birthday.4 He writes in glowing terms of Bloch's contribution to the recovery of the category of eschatology in understanding biblical thought, but is critical of Bloch's 'ontology of the not-yet'. Bloch has recovered the biblical tradition's eschatological mode of thought as a theme for philosophical reflection (and for Christian theology!) but the primacy of the future is not properly established.5 Bloch has not protected the Utopian hope from the possibility that it is merely the symbolic expression of our psychological strivings. The heart of the matter is Bloch's atheism. Bloch finds the idea of God dispensable. He is interested in messianic thinking, but finds this incompatible with theism. 'The place that has been occupied in individual religions by what is conceived as God ... has not itself ceased after it has ceased to be ostensibly filled'.6 We project what we long for onto the future, but there is a metaphysical correlate of this projection, which is at once utterly mysterious and real. It does not disappear with the loss of the god-hypothesis. The kingdom remains when God has gone. '... the kingdom, even in secularized form ... remains as a messianic Front-space even without any theism, indeed it can only remain at all ... without theism'.7 Atheism is not the enemy of religious Utopia but its precondition. z 3
TKG, 55-
Das Prinzip Hoffnung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag). It appeared in English in three volumes, trans. N. Plaice, S. Plaice and P. Knight (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986). 4 BQT2, 134-49. 5 BQTi, 138-40. 6 E. Bloch, The Principle of Hope, Vol. 3, 1199. See further pp. 1183-311. 7 Bloch, The Principle of Hope, Vol. 3, 12.00 (Bloch's italics). The religious kingdom-intention as such involves atheism, at last properly understood atheism7 (1199). 90
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
For Pannenberg, the grounds of Bloch's utopianism are tenuous. Human hope for a better future is no foundation for the Utopia of the kingdom. For Pannenberg the kingdom is inseparable from the God whose rule it is. 'When the coming kingdom is designated in biblical terms as the kingdom of God, that is out of concern for the ontological primacy of the future of the kingdom over all present realities, including, above all, psychological states.'8 Despite the service which Bloch has rendered to theology, his treatment of the idea of God is unconvincing. Human fulfilment can indeed only come from the future; and this deep conviction of Bloch is a form of the ontological priority of the future. But in Pannenberg's view, human misery and hope for a better future require not only the Utopia of the kingdom but the hidden God who is the kingdom's ground. Is Bloch's influence on Pannenberg then only marginal? Probably, his reading of Bloch came at an important time, but there is little dialogue with Bloch's ideas. Pannenberg found in Bloch a notion of the ontological primacy of the future, in terms of which he could develop his own ideas about the futurity of God,9 but it is clear that Pannenberg was already on the track of eschatological theology by the time he read Bloch. It is probably more correct to think of 'a provocative confluence with Pannenberg's own eschatological vision of universal history'.10 Pannenberg claims that the influence of Bloch was never as strong as some commentators suggested.11 The influence of others Dilthey for example - was much stronger. Nevertheless, Bloch has helped theology by changing the shape of the question about God. By turning the question of the most perfect being into a question about 'the highest Utopian problem', Bloch has created space for thinking again about God as 'the power of the future', even though he himself did not think in such theistic terms. Yet Pannenberg sees 8 9
5QT2, 240.
This is suggested by Polk, On the Way to God, 255. 10 As suggested by Tupper, The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 26. 11 W. Pannenberg, 'Providence, God, and Eschatology', in Donald W. Musser and Joseph L. Price (eds.), The Whirlwind in Culture: Frontiers in Theology (in honor of Langdon Gilkey; Bloomington, IN: Meyer Stone Books, 1988), 181, note 16. In personal conversation, Pannenberg confirmed this opinion and spoke instead of a 'convergence' of Bloch's thought and his own. 91
GOD AND THE FUTURE
rich possibilities for thinking about God in relation to the future, a God 'with futurity as a quality of being'.11 Already in the early essay to honour Bloch, Pannenberg speculates that ontological questions, too, may have to be seen in a new way; that 'being itself is perhaps to be understood as 'the power of the future'.13 Pannenberg is primarily a theologian. But the theologian cannot work in isolation from philosophy. Theological talk about God 'requires a relationship to metaphysical reflection if its claim to truth is to be valid',14 for only such reflection can establish a concept of the world, which is correlative with the idea of God. Over the years Pannenberg has written various essays on philosophical subjects. In 1988, coinciding with the first volume of Systematic Theology, he published Metaphysics and the Idea of God. Not only is the concept of the future to be given its proper place in theology, but Pannenberg also applies himself to the task of developing 'a new way of understanding the structure of reality',15 an understanding in which the idea of futurity is determinative. Even in early writing Pannenberg had something radical in mind, a reversal of the normal relation between present and future.16 Leaving aside the implications of such a reversal for thinking about God - to which we return in the next chapter - it is clear that the concept of time, especially the idea of the future, requires major rethinking. In the programmatic essay, 'Theology and the Kingdom of God', Pannenberg argues for a view of the future that is concrete and existential, not abstract and formal. The future is actually experienced as a power; it confronts humankind sometimes as 'a dark and uncertain power', sometimes as a power that promises fulfilment.17 But does the future actually have any such power? In Pannenberg's view, the future is not simply the prisoner of the past and the present. Rather, one must speak of 'the unpredictable new thing that is hidden in the womb of the future'.18 This is poetic language, to be sure, but can * BQTi, 24if. 3 BQTi, 242. 4 MIG, 6. 5 So Richard J. Neuhaus, 'Wolfhart Pannenberg: Profile of a Theologian', TXG, 12. 16 TKG, 5417 TKG, 56. 18 WM, 42,. 92
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
ontological sense be made of such an idea? The basic issue is the sense in which the future can be said to exist at all.19 A distinction has to be made between the ordinary sense of future and Pannenberg's theological understanding of it. Ordinarily, the future is seen as an extension of the past and present. In theology the emphasis is on the novelty of the future; it confronts and runs counter to the present world.20 In the everyday perception of the future, it is not quite 'real'. It exists only in thought or imagination. Its reality is at least of a very different order from that of the present. Since it has not happened yet, it is thought not yet to exist. There are grounds for questioning this 'everyday' understanding of the future; the revolutions in physics in the last century have made the 'ordinary' perception of space and time quite inadequate. Pannenberg ascribes a very definite reality to the future. The division of time into past, present and future is unavoidable in a finite world, but it has its limitations. If we could imagine a standpoint outside of time this division would be meaningless.21 If we were able to see the world sub speciae aeternitatis, time would appear very different. As we shall see, Pannenberg thinks that time participates in eternity. From such a standpoint the future will appear very different. In close connection with the idea of God, who is the future of humankind and of the entire universe, the future is seen by Pannenberg as 'a reality in its own right'.22 However, his view of the future should be argued on grounds that do not require the concept of God, even though they may be more compelling within a theistic framework. In fact, his arguments for the ontological priority of the future do not presuppose the truth of the God-hypothesis. Being and appearance We observed in the last chapter that Pannenberg's ontology is a thoroughly temporal ontology; our ideas about what 'is' are 19
Philip Hefner early said that the crucial question about Pannenberg's thought is whether futurity is viable as a basic ontological category. 'Theological Reflections (4)', Una Sancta 25.3, 1968, 44. 20 W. Pannenberg, 'Future and Unity', in E. H. Cousins (ed.), Hope and the Future of Man (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1972.), 60. 21
22
WM, 70.
Pannenberg, 'Future and Unity', 6z. 93
GOD AND THE FUTURE
irreducibly historical. Pannenberg has a correspondingly temporal view of being and appearance. This is a subject he addresses in 'Appearance as the Arrival of the Future',*3 an essay from 1967. There is a long history in philosophy of the distinction between what something is in and for itself and what it is for us or how it appears to us. Pannenberg argues that Greek philosophy tended to separate being and appearance, sometimes strongly, sometimes less strongly. Self-sufficient ideas or substances were ontologically prior to the world of phenomena and sense experience. Centuries later, Hegel saw the relation between essence and existence (or appearance) in more reciprocal terms, but the realm of appearance is still in effect 'reduced to the status of the nonessential'.24 With Kant the understanding is explicitly related to appearance, that is, the phenomenal world. Following Kant and German Idealism, philosophy gave priority to existence (appearance) over essence. It was at the heart of Kierkegaard's reaction to Hegel. Pannenberg endorses Heinrich Earth's view that the idea of appearance includes both 'the act of coming-into-appearance' and 'the "something" that appears', which is not exhausted in the act of appearing.25 Being (or essence) and appearance may not be separated, for they belong together; nor may they be equated, for there is a difference between them. Precisely this antinomy Pannenberg seeks to penetrate further. What guides his thinking is the point that what appears is not exhausted in the appearance; the appearance is only a partial realisation of the possibilities of what appears in it.z6 What he seeks to articulate more adequately is the unity of identity and difference between being (or essence) and the form in which it appears. He turns to theology for examples that throw light on the general problem. In Jesus' teaching about the kingdom of God, opening oneself to the coming kingdom makes it already a present reality, yet without abolishing its futurity. The kingdom of God is expressed in the present but not exhausted by its presence in that *3 TKG,ch. 4, 127-43. 24 Pannenberg is aware that for Hegel 'essence' and 'being' are not the same, and that the concept of essence underwent significant changes in the centuries between Plato and Aristotle and Hegel. But Hegel accepted 'the ontological precedence of essence over its appearance'; TXG, 130. 2 5 TKG, 131. z6 TKG, 132. 94
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
time and space. Such presence of the kingdom of God, says Pannenberg, is 'derived from [its futurity] and is itself only the anticipatory glimmer of its coming'.27 There is both identity and differentiation. The example presupposes a religious background very different from the Platonic view of the world. The ontological issue which Pannenberg wants to explore with the help of this example is the difference the introduction of temporality makes to our understanding of the relation between identity and difference. Does the problem of identity and difference in the relation of being and appearance reflect the relation between future and present in general? 'Does that which appears in the appearance . . . present itself in the mode of futurity?' 28 In answering this question, Pannenberg first argues that such a view is not, contrary to popular opinion, completely foreign to classical ontology, at least from Plato on. He claims to find it in Plato's quest for the good, which is not a possession but something sought, striven for, which implies the idea of the future.29 The idea is not strong enough in Plato to transform his view of the relation between the forms and the empirical world, but it is not completely absent. Pannenberg argues that Aristotle's notion of entelechy, too, can be taken in a futurist sense. 'The essence of a thing, its eidos, is the goal of its movement - at least of its natural, unforced movement.'30 This teleological view of the world is, of course, different from the eschatological view Pannenberg espouses.31 But the idea of a thing's essence as future is implied in what Aristotle says about movement. None of this by itself makes Pannenberg's futurist ontology compelling, but he is justified in finding some indirect support in Plato and Aristotle. In modern philosophy there has been, as Pannenberg notes, a TKG, 133. TKG, 136. TKG, 137. TKG, 139. 31 Pannenberg says that 'the concept of prolepsis, especially as anticipatory occurring of the end . . . forms exactly the counterconcept to a "protologically" founded teleology . . .'; Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 261. The entelechy is not the anticipation of the not yet attained goal, but is the already present . . . germ, out of which the goal unfolds itself; TKG, 139.
* ^ ^ 3°
95
GOD AND THE FUTURE
sharper focus on the 'appearance' itself, rather than on that which 'appears' in the appearance. Pannenberg speaks of the dissolution of Aristotelian metaphysics of substance into appearance. 'Philosophy no longer succeeded in thinking of what appears independently of the way in which it appears.'3Z Since Kant the cognitive faculty itself has been the subject of interest. The imagination goes beyond what is immediately given in experience in order to give shape to experience. This puts the focus on the subject's relation to the world. Pannenberg suggests that the subject thus goes beyond the given and alters it, making itself into the future of its world. It does this through technology or through the constructions (projections) of the imagination. But what is to be made of such projections? Pannenberg rejects any one-sided understanding of these. They are indeed projections of the imagination, but they are more; their anticipatory nature also has to be taken seriously: Do we not ... have to understand the synthetic constructions of the productive imagination ... as anticipations of the essential future of what is given in appearance? Is it not only with this presupposition that we can possibly understand the miracle of the correspondence to objective reality and of the readability of spontaneous human constructions?33
I have referred at length to this early essay because it shows the beginnings of Pannenberg's futurist ontology. It contains hints and suggestions rather than systematic developments. In later work the vision is expanded and clarified, though it is never the kind of thing for which 'knock-down' arguments can be produced. Seen in the context of other proposals that move 'beyond static conceptualisations of being',34 it invites serious consideration. An ontology which gives an integral place to the temporal process surely has advantages which make it prima fade attractive. The choice in considering the relation between being and appearance is between two options. The appearing reality can be understood as 'the appearance of something that always is' - as held in classical ontology - or, in Pannenberg's phrase, as 'the arrival of what is 3* TKG, 140.
33 TKG, i4of.; Pannenberg's italics. 34 Cf. the discussion by Philip Clayton in 'Being and One Theologian', The Thomist 52.4, October 1988, 650!. 96
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
future'."* The first way has the force of history behind it, but it has one great weakness which Pannenberg thinks is overcome by the second way. The first way, which 'sees what appears in the appearance only as a timeless universal, will inevitably underestimate ... the importance for our experience of reality, of the contingently new, of the individual, and of time'.36 The endless repetition of a fixed structure of being in the infinite multiplicity of events, attractive though it may have been, is not able to account for the experience of contingency and genuine novelty which are an undeniable feature of existence in the world. Pannenberg's conviction has been that appearance is better seen as an anticipatory arrival of the future, and that an ontology of the future gives a better account of contingency and freedom. Contingency and connection We shall see in this section how Pannenberg understands the contingency of events and the part it plays in articulating an ontology of the primacy of the future. There is no doubt about the element of contingency in nature and history. Events have an 'essential indeterminateness', for which there are both theological and scientific grounds.37 Theologically, the first point is the contingency of the cosmos itself. The world has its origin in the free decision of God in God's impenetrable eternity; in this its contingent character is grounded.38 The biblical view of reality presupposes the divine freedom and the contingent nature of events in the world. In Israel new and unforeseen events take place constantly and are understood as the work of God. If there is a 'necessity' about the course of events, it is not as a result of some immutable law but on account of the free, sovereign action of God in the world. 35 TKG, 141. 36 TKG, 141.
37 Science and theology discuss the notion of contingency in different but complementary ways. S. Grenz says, 'science speaks about regularities in temporal sequences, presupposing contingency, whereas theology discusses the contingency of events, representing their consequences as history'; Reason for Hope, 87. R. J. Russell has noted the importance of the notion of contingency as a bridge between a theological doctrine of creation and the scientific understanding of the universe in Pannenberg's theology; cf. 'Contingency in Physics and Cosmology; A Critique of the Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Zygon 23.1, March 1988, 23-43. 3* STz, 9.
97
GOD AND THE FUTURE
In science there has been a gradual move away from a teleological view of nature to one in which chance plays a major role.39 Often this is not adequately recognized, when the observed regularities are uncritically described in terms of law. But there is increasing recognition that each scientific hypothesis of law describes uniformities in the behavior of the object of such affirmations. The object itself, however, is contingently given in relation to its hypothetical description as a case where the affirmed law obtains ... However, the applicability of scientific formulas to concrete cases of natural processes requires initial and marginal conditions that are contingent in relation to the uniformity affirmed in the equation as such.40
With the replacement of a mechanistic view of the world with the principles of modern physics - notably relativity and indeterminacy - the place of contingency in the system is secure. Pannenberg regards the contingent nature of the world as the highest priority in the dialogue between scientists and theologians. Even where processes in the world of nature can be discussed in terms of natural law, they must also be considered as events 'in the course of the contingent sequence itself'.41 Theology is interested particularly in the contingent. This is not to deny theology's interest in the connectedness of events which science describes in terms of law. As noted in the last chapter, Pannenberg regards history not as a collection of contingent, disconnected events. There is a continuity in the sequence of events, without which historical narrative would be impossible. But the continuity is not sought in unchanging structures of reality. It is found in the fidelity of the creator and perfecter of all finite reality,42 which does not compromise the See W. Pannenberg, The Doctrine of the Spirit and the Task of a Theology of Nature' and Theological Questions to Scientists', TTN, chs 5 & i. Other chapters are also pertinent. 40 W. Pannenberg, The Doctrine of Creation and Modern Science', TTN 36. See Theology and Science', The Princeton Seminary Bulletin 13.3, 1992., esp. 3o3f. 41 TTN, 36. Elsewhere Pannenberg writes, '... in every new stage or research, the total process of natural events presents itself again as a mesh of contingency and regularities'. TTN, 78. 4Z Cf. W. Pannenberg, Toward a Theology of Law', Anglican Theological Review 55, October 1973, 401. 39
9«
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
contingency of events. In fact, the continuity and contingency of historical events - including events in nature - have a common root; both are grounded in something which transcends history, namely, God.43 God is the origin of the contingent and of the unity which constitutes contingent events as history. God is the ground of contingency by virtue of God's transcendent freedom, but this is a freedom exercised in faithfulness. God maintains the cosmos in being at every moment and is the power that will bring it to its perfection. Pannenberg links God's faithfulness with both contingent events and the uniformities of nature: In the theological perspective such uniformities ... as well as the enduring forms of natural reality are considered as contingent in the same way as any single event. The laws of nature appear to the theologian as contingent products of the creative freedom of God. The unity of contingency and continuity in the creative activity of God as well as in its products is rooted ... in God's faithfulness.44
God's faithfulness is God's constancy in relation to the created world. It refers both to creation and redemption. Faithfulness also implies duration; it can only be expressed over time. Creation will reach its eschatological completion through the faithful love of God, the ground of both the contingency and the connectedness of events. How does this discussion of contingency offer support to a futurist ontology? Pannenberg understands the continuity of historical events in terms of a movement from the present to the past, not the reverse. If the new is genuinely contingent, it cannot have had to come into being. The new is accounted for by something more than antecedent causes. It is received, as it were, from the future and brought into relation with past events, which have come into being in the same way: If ... the connection of events is grounded in the faithfulness of the free God, then we do not have to conceive a continuity of something enduring from the past into the future after the manner, say, of a development. Rather, we have to think of events which are in themselves contingent, as being at the same time linked backward and « BQTi, 74. «« TTN, 37. 99
GOD AND THE FUTURE
referred to what has happened. By means of such backward linking the continuity of history is constantly re-established. This is the way in which the faithfulness of God expresses itself. Only in this way ... can the primary connection of history be conceived without losing its contingency.45
Pannenberg's point is that if the new can only be accounted for as an outcome of past events, there is no genuine freedom and contingency; no escape from determinism. There can be no simple account of causality; certainly, future acts cannot be deduced simply from antecedent events.46 The link between new events and the past is created retroactively. If the new cannot be adequately accounted for simply as the effect of past causes, the only alternative is to see it as coming in some way from the future. Pannenberg sees this in terms of the creative activity of God, the power of the future. But can this be expressed in a non-theistic form? Is there an adequate ontological basis for such a view? Do events in fact spring from the future? Pannenberg hints how this might be so. The whole of reality may be divided into the sum of individual contingent events and indeterminate, unpredictable future events. This future is full of ambiguity; it is 'not yet ... decided upon'. It is open; it does not yet exist: In every event the infinite future separates itself from the finite events which until then had been hidden in this future but are now released into existence. The future lets go of itself to bring into being our present. And every new present is again confronted by a dark and mysterious future out of which certain relevant events will be released. Thus does the future determine the present.47
This is unusual language to describe what we regard as natural. The initiative lies with the future; it 'separates itself from what comes into existence and 'releases' it into existence. Pannenberg does not say how the metaphor of release and separation is related to the image of decision, nor what makes the image of decision appropriate. In a theistic context, where the power that operates in contingent events is personal, this language has some justification. In more recent work Pannenberg seeks to clarify his earlier 45 46 47
W. Pannenberg, 'Redemptive Event and History', BQTi, 75^ See TTN, 2,2,. TKG, 59. IOO
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
ideas. The future is 'the field of the possible', and 'the basis of the openness of creation to a higher consummation and the source of what is new, i.e., of contingency in each new event'.48 In discussing the priority of the future, as the field of the possible, with philosophers and physicists, Pannenberg proposes that the concept of 'field' might function as a mediating term between theology and science.49 The triune God may be thought of as a dynamic 'field', with a trinitarian structure. In particular, the work of the Holy Spirit in creation has the character of a dynamic field of force.50 More precisely, the power of the future, understood as a field of the possible, is the sphere in which the dynamic of the Spirit expresses itself in creation.51 This is a bold move, for which he offers some reasons. Theologically, it restores the link between pneumatology and eschatology. The enlivening work of the Spirit, directed to all creatures, is the proleptic effect of the Spirit's eschatological reality. In the life-giving activity of the Spirit in creation we see an anticipation of the eschatological consummation; it is an expression of the power of the future. Scientifically, Pannenberg draws on some implications of quantum theory, as outlined by H.-P. Diirr. Diirr connects quantum indeterminacy with the concept of possibility, which presupposes the future. He leans strongly in the direction of affirming the primacy of the future; it has greater power than the factual, that is, the past.52 He certainly wants to overturn the 'everyday' view, namely, that the future is determined by what is actual. This, of course, calls into question the predictability of the future. But far too much is read into the notion of the predictability, in principle, of future events, given established 48
49
ST2, 9 7 f.
Pannenberg's use of the 'field' concept has been criticized as insufficiently nuanced by Jeffrey S. Wicken, Theology and Science in the Evolving Cosmos: A Need for Dialogue', Zygon 2.3.1, March 1988, esp. 51-3. Pannenberg's response is in Theological Appropriation of Scientific Understandings: Response to Hefner, Wicken, Eaves, and Tipler', Zygon 14.2, June 1989, 2,55-71, esp. 156-8. 50 See ST2, 83^; this is discussed further in chapter six. *' SeeSTi, 98. 52 STz, 99. Pannenberg thinks it is better to speak of 'the power of the realm of the future being given concrete form by the event that takes place in the present'. 101
GOD AND THE FUTURE
starting conditions. Essentially, predictability has no firmer ground than statistical probability. Pannenberg argues for pressing the question whether interest in predictability has not implicated scientific thought in an inversion of the real relation between the actual and the possible. Rather than regarding an ontology in which primacy lies with the future as false, may it not be the conventional ontology, in which primacy lies with the given, that is mistaken? It has to be asked whether there is adequate recognition of contingency in the 'everyday' view of the relation between the actual and the possible. At least, a much less simple account of causality should be offered, to take account of factors beyond what is immediately given. Pannenberg draws support for his futurist ontology from new directions of thought which find the orthodoxies of the past in science and philosophy unsatisfactory.53 It may well be that a 'paradigm shift' is underway. If so, only time will tell whether this new ontological proposal will make better sense of old problems. Reference has been made several times to the 'power' of the future, or to the greater power of the possible over the actual. Clearly, the notion of power is indispensable in this discussion. However, as Lewis Ford says, 'the real problem ... lies in the difficulty of understanding how the future can exert power upon the present'.54 What kind of power, if any, do possibilities have? Ford says that in many accounts of causation there is no effective role for possibilities.55 This is because the ontological status of possibility is far from clear. The conventional wisdom is that possibilities have power only if they are real; but what does 'real' mean here? Pannenberg turns this upside down: only by virtue of its power to shape the present can (future) possibilities be said to be 'real'. In effect, they can be 'real' without (yet) 'existing'. Pannenberg severs the usual connection between what 'exists' and what is 'real'. 53 Pannenberg gives an example in STz, 100. His arguments on the basis of new conceptions in modern physics require detailed evaluation from those familiar with the field. I claim no detailed acquaintance with it. A step in this direction, but without reference to STz, was taken by D. Z. Nowell in ch. 4 of his unpublished thesis, 'Futurity and contingency: An alternative paradigm', submitted to Baylor University in 1991. 54 Lewis S. Ford, The Nature of the Power of the Future', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolf hart Pannenberg, 75. 55 Ford, The Nature of the Power of the Future', 76.
IO2,
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
Pannenberg is searching for 'an alternative to an understanding of the real which is concentrated entirely upon what is existent'.56 What is 'real' is not restricted to what 'exists' at present. Both the past (which has existed) and the future (which is not yet existent) are 'real', because they are 'effective in the present moment'. Something may be said to be 'real' if it is 'effective' in the present:57 What belongs to the future is not yet existent, and yet it already determines present experience, at least the present experience of beings who ... are orientated towards the future and always experience their present and past in the light of a future which they hope for or which they fear. Thus the future is real, although it does not yet exist.58
The future is 'real' because it has an effect upon the present. The present could not come into being without its 'determination' by the future. The present is dependent on what the future releases. Freedom is inconceivable without the reality of the future, for it operates in a realm of possibilities not yet realized. When certain possibilities are grasped and become actual, the future is powerful over the present. The future and freedom thus belong together; neither 'exists' as such, but each has 'power over what exists here and now'.59 The idea of power is one of three ideas that are central and inseparable in Pannenberg's ontology; the others are unity and the future. The key term is that of power; only through power is unity established out of unrelated, contingent events. At this point Pannenberg slides over into speech about God's power. God is the power of the future. Only in the future, and by the all-determining power that is God, does the cosmos receive its unity and coherence: The coming of God to his sovereignty over the world is his gift to the world, unifying its scattered events. The coming of God also means that God has the power over the future of those who are under his rule. Thus the circle is closed. Jesus' message of the Kingdom of God implies that the unity of the world is to be expected from the future.60 no. D. Polk points out that the German words for 'real' and 'effective' (wirklich and wirksam) have 'an essential parallelism'; On the Way to God, 258. 58 BQT3, 110 59 BQT3, in. 60 TKG, 59 f. 56
57
BQt3,
103
GOD AND THE FUTURE
The impetus for such an ontology is the biblical idea of the kingdom of God. But the idea of a unity existing at the heart of all finite events is a fundamental religious idea. The search for a unifying principle or power is at once the question reaching for God and the fundamental ontological question. Pannenberg has transposed an eternal transcendent unity into an eternal eschatological unity, for the unity of all things is a future reality. We have been examining the major elements of Pannenberg's future-oriented ontology. His ontology and his understanding of God are intertwined. He sets out to bring theological ideas about God and the understanding of the cosmos into dialogue. To speak of God is, at least implicitly, to speak of the future of the cosmos. But the converse is also true. From a theological standpoint, to speak of the future is, at least indirectly, to speak of God. 'Every event in which the future becomes finitely present must be understood as a contingent act of God, who places that finite reality into being by distinguishing it from his own powerful future.'61 How God creates the present from the future must be further considered in the next chapter. So far we have looked at some of the ontological implications of Pannenberg's eschatological theism. Much has been said about the future, but we have yet to consider Pannenberg's understanding of time. The ontological primacy of the future has its basis in the eternity of God. Time and eternity The problem of time, especially its relation to eternity, has long preoccupied Pannenberg. In an early essay he wrote, 'The truth of time lies beyond the self-centeredness of our experience of time as past, present, and future. The truth of time is the concurrence of all events in an eternal present.'62 Twenty-five years later he published his view of the relation between time and eternity in an important essay and in his Systematic Theology.6"63 The importance 61
TKG, 61. In 'Contingency and Natural Law' Pannenberg considers several scientific models of the universe, exploring how they might be compatible with the theological notion of 'creation'. Some models are particularly open to the idea of a creation from the future of the world; cf. TTN, 102-5. 62 WM, 74. Eternity is 'the truth of time, which remains hidden in the flux of time'. 63 W. Pannenberg, 'Being and Time', published in M/G, ch. 4, 69-90 & 5T2, ch. 7, part z, 84-102. 104
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
of the problem is indicated in his discussion with scientists, where he says that 'without an answer to the question regarding time and eternity, the relation of God to this world remains inconceivable'.64 He raises the question of the possibility of relating the extension of time and space to a mathematical model of eternity, a problem not irrelevant to the question of God's existence. Most characteristically, he argues that dividing time into past, present and future presupposes c an undivided whole of time', comprising all temporal distinctions; this is what a contemporary concept of eternity denotes: 'not as timeless, but as infinite unity of life'.65 Here we are at the heart of Pannenberg's view of time. A key issue is that of God's relation to time. Pannenberg takes a middle way between two incompatible forms of theism: classical theism, developed by the early patristic theologians, and a later form of theism which rejects major elements of classical theism.66 A key feature of classical theism is 'the denial that God is in any literal sense temporal or really related to the world'; it can be called 'nontemporalistic theism'.67 This is rejected in many other types of theology, including recent contextual and narrative theologies. These also have in common a rejection of metaphysics in theology. Ogden claims that Heidegger, in one of few references to God, proposes a thesis of the temporality of God which is ontologically well substantiated.68 Ogden observes 6
4 TTN, 15-28, esp. 24. W. Pannenberg, 'Theology and Science', in The Princeton Seminary Bulletin 13.3, 1992,, 305. 66 In an astute study of a footnote in Heidegger's Sein und Zeit, Schubert Ogden has described these two types of theism. The crucial issue is the relation of God to time and temporality; see The Temporality of God', The Reality of God (London: SCM Press, 1967), ch. 5, esp. 158-63. 67 Ogden, The Temporality of God', 158. 68 The footnote reads: 'It requires no extensive discussion to show that the traditional concept of eternity, in the sense of the "stationary now" (nunc stans), is drawn from the vulgar understanding of time and is limited by an orientation to the idea of "constant" presence-on-hand. If the eternity of God would admit of being "construed" philosophically, it could be understood only as a more primal and "infinite" temporality ...'; M. Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), 499, note xiii. (The British edition, London: SCM Press, 1961, has the quotation in slightly different words.) The quotation is found in Ogden's essay on p. 145. 65
105
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the familiar spectacle of classical theists trying to adjust to the demands of temporality, and of modern temporalists inconsistently appealing to the God of traditional theism. In neither case are we offered anything like a real third alternative, but are left to choose either the sacrifice of time and man to God's eternity or the abandonment of God and infinity for the temporality of man.69
Heidegger's view of God as essentially temporal is a major advance. Pannenberg provides just the third option that Ogden calls for. In his discussion of time there are two fundamental aspects: the contrast between biblical views of God in relation to time and the view of time typically found in Greek philosophy, and the challenge to the received philosophical wisdom about the concept of time. First, the contrast between biblical and philosophical ideas about God and time.70 The major difference is that the God of the Bible, though eternal, does things. The god of Greek philosophy is not capable of doing anything. Tn order to act, God would have to pass from rest into movement and thus would lose his eternity along with his constancy.'71 The eternal is the utterly constant and unchanging, the utterly simple and undifferentiated; Aristotle's 'unmoved mover' exemplifies this. In Pannenberg's view, 'the eternity of the Greek God is that of the empty, eternal being'.72 The eternity of the biblical God is God's presence to every time; 'his action and power extend to everything past and future as to something that, for him, is present'.73 God's eternity is God's omnipresence. The biblical God allowed the boundless diversity of his creative possibilities to take form in creation, and remains the unity of this richness. However, God is not bound to the world as it is; neither to a primordial ordering of events such as is celebrated in myth and cult, nor to an unbreakable chain of cause and effect describable in scientific terms. God confronts the course of events with the 69
S. Ogden, The Temporality of God', 160. See Pannenberg's essay on time and eternity in the religious experience of Israel and Christianity, 'Zeit und Ewigkeit in der religiosen Erfahrung Israels und des Christentums', in GSTz, 188-206. This essay has not been translated. For a concise account of this contrast see WM, 74-6. 71 WM,757* WM, 75. 73 WM, 74; also ST2, 9if. 70
106
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
new. Israel's sense of time was governed by its orientation to the future. 74 The sense of the past remained strong, but with the prophets Israel slowly learnt to expect its salvation from the future and to relate in trust and hope to the God in whose hands this future lay. In the preaching of Jesus the reality of God becomes inextricably linked to the future of God's rule; if there were to be no completion of God's rule there could be no God! This future has a strong bearing on the present. In the early Christian community, the experience of the Spirit signified the presence already now of the future salvation reality. But how could this 'present' be understood? In Pannenberg's view, it was understood as the presence of eternity.75 In one sense, God's eternity and human temporality stand over against each other. The difference between the infinite and the finite is never dissolved, even in the eschaton. In another sense, they also coincide. Here Pannenberg appeals to the idea in apocalyptic thought that those things which belong to the end-time already exist in heaven. This does not dissolve the distinction between future and present; the future provides the meaning of the present. But the 'not yet' of the future is anticipated already in the present. In apocalyptic thought - and in the New Testament there is a remarkable interweaving of time and eternity; this is very different from the Greek opposition between a timeless eternity and all things temporal and transitory. Pannenberg describes the future of God as 'the parousia of his eternity', and it is this that constitutes the dimension of depth in the present.76 Conversely, the present has its place in the eternity of God and finds its meaning therein. Eternity is the presence of life in its totality; the whole is already present in the part.77 However, the coincidence of eternity and time is mediated temporally. The present has its relation to the hidden dimension of the eternal only via the future. Without this temporal mediation 74 Pannenberg says that in ancient Israel there was no concept of time as such. Israel knew the course of days, months and years by which what we now call 'time' was measured, and it knew the time which God determines for the events of life; cf. 'Zeit und Ewigkeit in der religiosen Erfahrung Israels und des Christentums', GSTi, 193. 7 5 GST2, 199. 76
77
GST2,
202.
See STi, 403 & STz, 92. 107
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the eternal and the present would become polarised in a stark dualism, as seen already in some of the New Testament writings, notably the Fourth Gospel.78 For Pannenberg the true point of the coincidence of time and eternity is the eschaton. This is part of his third option, over against the focus on the primordial past, which remains normative in mythology, and the Neoplatonist idea of the circular movement of origin from, and return to, God. The second important aspect of Pannenberg's discussion of time is his challenge to the received philosophical understanding of time. He believes that the early Christian sense of the presence of God's eschatological future was displaced by other influences as Christianity spread beyond the sphere of Judaism. The sense of the future was retained only indirectly; it lost its place as the linchpin of the Christian understanding of time. Significant in the shift was the Platonist antithesis of the eternal and the temporal, part of the close connection between Christian thought and Platonism.79 For Plato time was the image of eternity; temporal reality copied the eternal forms. For Augustine time was the creature of God, and as such he could view it more positively. As the fall of humankind had taken place in time, the conversion of the will also had to take place in time. Pannenberg sees a 'historicisation of time' in Augustine's thought. With his view of a comprehensive future salvation, he broke out of the framework of Platonist thought, especially its cyclical idea of reincarnation. He asserted the irreversibility of the history that has its goal in God. But he was not consistent in this 'historicisation' of reality; in some respects he remained closer to Neoplatonism.80 Pannenberg is more positive about Plotinus, who broke with earlier philosophers in refusing to define time in relation to motion. Time is presupposed by the idea of motion.81 Plotinus developed his theory of time from a 78
GSTz, 203. See W. Pannenberg, The Appropriation of the Philosophical Concept of God as a Dogmatic Problem of Early Christian Theology', BQT2, ch. 5; also 'Christentum und Platonismus'. In both articles Pannenberg makes clear that Christian thinkers also challenged Platonist ideas. 80 Pannenberg, 'Christentum und Platonismus', 160. He expresses surprise at how little Augustine's view of God, in contrast to his anthropology, was affected by his 'historical' outlook. 81 In 5T2, 93 Pannenberg describes in more detail the positions against which Plotinus developed his theory of time; see also M/G, 76. 79
108
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
consideration of the nature of the soul, which he uses as a mediating concept. Time is related to eternity; in fact, derived from it. The soul is tied to the eternal, but it is also the principle that brings about the moving apart of the various moments of life within the flow of time. The soul, while participating in the One, also experiences the succession of moments. But it grasps these moments in their connectedness.81 The key point for Pannenberg is time's relation to eternity. We saw in the previous chapter that understanding the part in relation to the whole is the driving force of Pannenberg's ontological thought. Everything historical, every moment in history, can be understood only within the 'semantic whole' that constitutes history in its totality. Similarly, time can only be understood in the framework of eternity. But eternity is the fulness of time, not its antithesis. For Augustine there was no time in God's eternity; time and eternity stand in antithesis. But Plotinus had a different view; he defined eternity as 'the presence of the totality of life'.83 For him the eternal is 'the whole of life, namely, of "life that is fixed within Sameness, because the whole is always present in it - not now this, then another, but all simultaneously" in the sense of "completion without parts" '.84 For Plotinus eternity is not opposed to time but is the presupposition of understanding it. The Platonist antithesis of time and eternity does remain in Plotinus's thought to some extent; time is understood as 'the dissolution of the unity of life into a sequence of separate moments'. But it is also 'constituted a sequence by the reference to the eternal totality'.85 This is the line of thought taken by Boethius, who regards eternity as 'the simultaneous and perfect presence of unlimited life'; in other words, authentic duration.86 There is, then, a discontinuity between time and eternity, in Plotinus's view; but this is only one side. Eternity is also the unity and perfection of time; that is the other side. Time arises in the fall of the soul from eternity. The soul participates in the eternal, and 82
M/G, 76, quoting from Enneads; see also STz, 93. 3 571,403. 8 « MIG, 7 6f. 85 STi, 403, 404. It is clear that the relation between eternity and time in Plotinus' understanding requires fairly nuanced statement. Can time and eternity be 'not opposed' but at the same time be 'antithetical'? 86 STi, 404. 8
109
GOD AND THE FUTURE
thus longs for its wholeness, but it suffers a 'fall' from eternity, which breaks the perfect wholeness of eternity. The result (paraphrasing Plotinus) is the separation of the moments and parts of life, the diastasis ... zoes, and along with the independence of the finite or the many, time arises. Time is characterized as the manner in which the many remains bound, even in its independence, to the whole. Given the nature of temporal moments as parts, the whole is present only in the sense that it hovers over the parts as the future whole .. .8?
Elsewhere Pannenberg speaks of the time-spanning presence of eternity. 'A present can be eternal only if it is not separate from the future and if nothing sinks for it into the past.'88 The reference to the future comes from Plotinus himself. Pannenberg concludes that 'when the theory of time is oriented toward the eternal totality, the consequence is a primacy of the future for the understanding of time'.8? Pannenberg credits Plotinus, not Heidegger, with first affirming the primacy of the future in the philosophy of time. However, for both the totality of existence is possible only in the light of its future. The part can only be understood against the whole, and the whole can be understood only as a future reality. The future therefore shapes the present and its meaning, and this gives the future its reality, despite the fact that it does not yet 'exist'. Totality includes the whole of the past, present and future, and is thus indistinguishable from the idea of eternity. This was the context of Plotinus's view of time. Heidegger's thought is focussed on the wholeness that an individual person may experience in his or her existence, and is thus much narrower in scope. The Western understanding of time has been shaped by the christianised Neoplatonism of Augustine rather than by the thought of Plotinus, which has resulted, in Pannenberg's view, in the loss of something important. There is no parallel in Augustine to Plotinus's notion of the primacy of the future. Biblical eschatology could have provided the impetus for such a move, but Augustine was more concerned with the origin of time as the creation of God than with time from 8
? MIG, 77.
88 8
ST2, 92. 9 MIG, 77. no
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
the standpoint of its future. In his analysis of the experience of time Augustine moved beyond Plotinus, and here his work has remained definitive. The present is a bridge between the remembered past and the expected future. The soul is extended beyond the present and gives unity to what is remembered, experienced and expected. It creates the sense of duration, which is the way into the experience of time. Whereas Plotinus derives time from the experience of the separation of the moments of life, Augustine's emphasis is on bringing these moments of life together through the soul's extension. Plotinus goes deeper here, in Pannenberg's view, because he sees finite being, with its disjunctive experience of time, as grounded in eternity, by which he means the eternal being of God.90 Decisive for Pannenberg is the connection of the analysis of time with the idea of eternity. In so far as Augustine failed to make such a connection, his analysis of time, whilst psychologically sharp, is ontologically inferior to that of Plotinus. The same criticism applies to Heidegger. There is a narrowing of vision here which can be attributed to Kant. What Kant did in the first Critique, according to Pannenberg, was to derive the unity of time from the unity of the ego. Pannenberg finds this a serious flaw. Kant saw time as 'the form ... of the intuition of ourselves and of our inner state'.91 However, there is more to his view, for there is a background to this subjectivist view which stands in tension with it. What is prominent in Kant is his 'anthropocentrically oriented intention', but he also sees differentiated time as presupposing 'a constant unity of time'.92 For Pannenberg, if time is given in intuition as an infinite whole, it cannot be derived from the ego, for the ego is not an infinite whole. The conclusion is that the awareness of time cannot be based on the self-intuition of the ego.93 Thus Plotinus's derivation of time from eternity is superior to Kant's reduction of everything to the transcendental subject. Pannenberg's insistence that time should be viewed against the horizon of the eternal makes him as critical of Heidegger as he is of 9° M/G, 8if. 91 M/G, 83.
9Z 5T2, 94. Pannenberg cites the Critique of Pure Reason, §A, 3 if. [See the Transcendental Aesthetic', Section II, §4, part 4 & 5, p. 75 in the Norman Kemp Smith edition (London: Macmillan, 1933).] 93 M/G, 83.
in
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Kant. In grounding the notion of time, Kant replaces eternity with the subjectivity of the ego. Heidegger replaces it with individual human existence (Dasein). Pannenberg argues against Heidegger that the wholeness of human existence is not experienced in the face of death, for death fragments existence. 'We will need another light than the one that death throws on a life, if we are to recognize in that life some sort of totality.'94 Pannenberg concludes that the leading role in our consciousness of time belongs to the future understood as the source of possible completion, as can be clearly seen in Plotinus. Working outward from this perspective, the present and the past can then be interpreted as participating in the future totality, or as falling short of it.95
This quotation underscores the point that being and time belong together. The future, understood as the field of the possible and the source of life's unity and of its discrete moments and events, is the source of possible completion of our existence. If this is so, the essence of an individual's existence is determined by its future. On this basis Pannenberg speculates whether beings are to be conceived as the anticipation of their essences, indeed whether 'everything that exists is what it is only as the anticipation of its future, in which ... the wholeness of each being might be established'.96 Pannenberg concludes that eternity represents the possibility that finite beings will have their being completed, that all temporal moments participate in eternity, and that the future is to be seen as the source of the wholeness of finite being.97 The present as anticipation of the future If the future is the source of the completion and meaning of individual being, how is the present to be understood? Does Pannenberg - as some critics think - devalue the present?98 The answer to this depends on the capacity of Pannenberg's concept of 94 M/G, 86. 95 M/G, 87.
96 M/G, 88; Pannenberg's italics. 97 M/G, 88f. 98 See e.g. P.C. Hodgson's criticism (based only on Jesus - God and Man) that in an apparent over-reaction to existentialism Pannenberg emphasizes the future at the expense of the present; 'Pannenberg on Jesus: A Review Article', Journal of the American Academy of Religion 36, December 1968, 374. See 112
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
'anticipation' to link, yet differentiate, the present and the future. The concept of 'anticipation' (or 'prolepsis') plays a role in his discussion of many subjects. Its use, especially when equated with 'prolepsis', has a long history, not only in theology but in philosophy." However, Pannenberg has given it an importance in systematic theology unparalleled by any other theologian. It reflects his unparalleled elevation of the concept of the kingdom of God to theological importance. He writes: The category of anticipation or prolepsis, which was originally introduced to describe the distinctive structure of the history of Jesus, especially of his resurrection, ... shows itself to be a fundamental structural element both of cognition and of language, and of the being of beings in their temporality.100
Pannenberg has himself described its importance in terms of its correlation with the notion of eschatology. If Christianity cannot do without an eschatology, the present experience of salvation has to be connected with it. For Pannenberg it is not a question of realised eschatology; the eschaton is still future. But it has come proleptically, by anticipation. If Weiss was right about Jesus' proclamation of the kingdom of God, it follows that the final salvation, the presence of the eschaton, was not yet at hand except by anticipation. Then it is also the case that the reconciliation of the world 'has been accomplished - but by anticipation'.101 The concept of anticipation has its meaning in the framework of the Christian experience of the already and the not yet. Present Christian experience is that salvation is already truly experienced, but not yet in its fulness. There is continuity between this present experience and the future reality of salvation, but they are not identical. Salvation has been given and the kingdom of God has
also H. Burhenn, Tannenberg's Doctrine of God', Scottish Journal of Theology 2,8.6, 1975, 547. 99 A detailed history of the concept of anticipation was traced by L. Kugelmann, Antizipation; Eine begriffsgeschichtliche Untersuchung (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1986). D. Polk lists some theologians and biblical scholars in whose work the idea can be found some decades before Pannenberg; On the Way to God, 2.30, note 72. 100 Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, 2,60. 101 W. Pannenberg, 'Can Christianity Do Without an Eschatology?', 29. 113
GOD AND THE FUTURE
come, but 'only in the form of an anticipation of a future which in its fulness has not yet materialized'.102 The concept of anticipation serves not only to describe the connection between present and future salvation but also to make intelligible the 'scandal' of the Christian claim that in a particular event in history something of universal significance has taken place. It provides a way of seeing how the particular and the universal can coincide. It establishes an essential connection between a historical event and the eschatological event which Christians believe will determine the eternal destiny of all people. How can so much be claimed for a single event in history? Responding to G. Klein, who thinks that the 'once for all' claim of Christianity is at risk in his theology, Pannenberg argues that it is 'only through the idea of the prolepsis of this "once and for all" that the unsurpassability of the Christ-event becomes clear ... since this event, although it took place once in the past at a definite time, still remains before us as our ultimate future'.103 For Pannenberg everything hinges on the eschatological nature of the Christ event, since 'absolute meaning' could be claimed for nothing less than such an event. The same holds true for its 'once for all-ness'. But the Christ-event also takes place in ordinary time. Hence it can be an eschatological event only proleptically or in an anticipatory way. Speaking of revelation, Pannenberg writes: While it is only the whole history that demonstrates the deity of the one God, and this result can only be given at the end of all history, there is still one particular event that has absolute meaning as the revelation of God, namely, the Christ event, insofar as it anticipates the end of history.104
As an eschatological event, it is impossible for any other event to surpass it as the demonstration of God's deity. Neither can the Christ-event be surpassed as the salvation-event, because it is the prolepsis of the eschatological event, which remains before us as our ultimate future. IOZ
Pannenberg, 'Can Christianity Do Without an Eschatology?', 30. The terms 'anticipation' and 'prolepsis' are also scattered throughout the Systematic Theology. The basis for it is 'the proleptic presence of the salvation of the divine rule in the message and work of Jesus'; STz, 402.. 103 RAH, postscript to the ind edition, 194. 104 RAH, 144. 114
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
Pannenberg believes that without the Christ-event's proleptic structure the claim of absoluteness, 'once for all-ness' or universality is no more than a bare assertion. It could only be asserted fideistically. But by means of the concept of anticipation this central Christian claim can be seen to have an objective basis, namely, in the relation that always pertains between the present and the future. The concept of anticipation thus provides a way out of relativism in theology; it is Pannenberg's attempt to overcome the problem that defeated Troeltsch.105 If Troeltsch was unable to echo the traditional affirmation of the Christ-event as 'absolute', Hegel failed to do justice to the irreducible finitude of experience and to recognise 'the impossibility of taking account of the contingent and the individual by means of the universal'.106 For Pannenberg the way through this Scylla and Charybdis is by a proper appreciation of eschatology and its correlative notion of anticipation. This requires moving beyond both Hegel and Troeltsch, keeping the horizon of the future open and preserving the finitude of human experience, yet not succumbing to a relativism which surrenders the claim of Christ's universal significance. The history of Jesus, in its relation to the Israelite-Jewish tradition, gives us an understanding of history in which its totality is already established by the fact that its end has become accessible in a provisional and anticipatory way. The appeal to eschatology and the concept of anticipation open up a view of history which, in Pannenberg's view, makes the Christian claim defensible. Whether one has in mind Jesus' proclamation of the kingdom of God or the resurrection of Jesus, the concept of anticipation connects yet differentiates present experience and future 105 Pannenberg has many positive things to say about Troeltsch, e.g. TPS, 103-16. But there are two great problems in his thought: the one-sided emphasis on the kingdom of God as a future reality, 'at the expense of the presence of this future in the history of Jesus', and the location of the absolute as a final goal 'totally beyond present experience'. TPS, no. Thus present experience in Troeltsch's view has no room for the absolute. The concept of anticipation was intended to overcome these problems. L. Allen says that Pannenberg, more than any other, has taken up Troeltsch's tasks in the late twentieth century. 'From Dogmatik to Glaubenslehre: Ernst Troeltsch and the Task of Theology', Fides et Historia n.z, Spring 1980, 54. 106 BQTi, 134-
H5
GOD AND THE FUTURE
fulfilment. Jesus' claim about God's judgment and salvation in his own ministry and the Christian claim of the presence of eschatological life through the risen Christ both imply 'an anticipation of a confirmation that is to be expected only from the future'.107 Both claims have an anticipatory or proleptic structure. A claim is made which, if it receives eschatological confirmation, will be shown to have been not mere wishful thinking but the accurate perception of the future reality as already present. The concept of anticipation thus has a 'strictly theological' root, as Pannenberg confirms.108 Anticipation has an epistemological and an ontological aspect. Epistemologically, it calls for confirmation from the future. It looks to the prospect of overcoming the present contestability of Christian claims about the Christ-event and about God. Until then anticipation includes 'the eschatological reservation that applies to all Christological conclusions drawn from Jesus' resurrection'.109 The ontological aspect is more radical. Assuming that there will be a future confirmation (and everything depends on this), the future reality already appears proleptically in the present, although it remains future. What happens in the present already has the character of the future reality. Such a view presupposes the reality of the future - indeed its primacy over the present and the past even though it does not yet exist. To make matters even more difficult, Pannenberg also sees the relation between future and present from the other side. Pannenberg insists that an event in time - the resurrection of Jesus from the dead - has determined the ultimate future. Without the resurrection of Jesus, the ultimate future of the general resurrection of the dead could not be what, in the light of Jesus' resurrection, it will be. There is certainly a reciprocal relation here, but where then does the priority lie? Pannenberg accepts Clayton's description of this paradoxical state of affairs as meaning that 'the gist of the final outcome has been decided (ontologically) in Jesus' resurrection'.110 Of course, we do not yet know this with certainty; it all depends on the actual IQ
7 JGM, 58.
108 w Pannenberg, 'A Response to my American Friends', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 319. I0 ? /GM, 397. 110 Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 131. Pannenberg's endorsement of this is on p. 32.0. 116
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
arrival of that final outcome in the parousia of Jesus. This is certainly a 'robust' ontological doctrine.111 Wherever Pannenberg uses the concept of anticipation this same condition applies: unless the future of which something is said to be an anticipation actually arrives, that event will not have been an anticipation of the supposed future reality. But the concept of anticipation is not used only in relation to events; it plays a key role in Pannenberg's discussion of other subjects. In a discussion of the nature of theological language, Pannenberg reflects on the proleptic element of dogmatic statements (about God).112 Dogmatic statements 'rest entirely on an anticipation of the eschaton', for they make reference to 'something that will fully appear only in a future which is inconceivable for us, but which has already happened in Jesus at a specific time'.113 Language 'lags behind' the reality which it seeks to express. It is always provisional. But Pannenberg asserts more than the provisionality of theological statements. That to which theological language refers will only be finally disclosed by the arrival of the eschaton. Theological language points ahead to its referent, and relies on confirmation from the eschatological future. Theological models 'have the function of an anticipatory presentation of the truth of God, for the conclusive revelation of which in the world faith is waiting'.114 Pannenberg extends his view of the proleptic character of theological language to the concept of truth. In both Greek and Hebrew understanding, truth is something that can be experienced, but it is characteristic of the Israelite notion of truth that its full disclosure is expected from the future. Truth 'always proves itself for the first time through the future. Therefore it is accessible now only by trusting anticipation of the still-outstanding proof, and that means precisely, by faith.'115 Truth is not the correspondence of thought to reality. It is not simply 'available' to those who open their eyes to the inner structure of things. Truth is historical, 111
C. Braaten's phrase; Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolf hart Pannenberg^ 129. 112 See esp. part 6 of 'What is a Dogmatic Statement?', BQTi, 201-5. IJ 3 BQTi, 204, 205. 114 STi, 60. (Here I have slightly changed Bromiley's translation; cf. the German original, p. 71.) IJ 5 W. Pannenberg, 'What is Truth?', BQTz, 7. 117
GOD AND THE FUTURE
proving itself in the course of history. It is given from the future, says Pannenberg; it is ultimately the truth of God, whose mode of being is future. 'All constancy, whether it be in the orders of nature, in the life of nations, or in the individual, is embraced by the truth of God and is grounded in it.'116 Pannenberg works with a view of truth not usually found in philosophical discussion. His concern is neither with the narrow question of the truth of propositions nor with the modern subjectivisation of truth.117 The two aspects of the problem of truth which are paramount for Pannenberg are the unity of truth and its historicity. In the modern (post-Enlightenment) discussion of truth these two aspects coincide. The unity of truth can only be thought of as the history of truth. Truth itself is historical; the essence of truth is the process of its history.118 Hegel tried to articulate a theory of reality on this basis. He saw truth as a process that runs its course, and saw that the unity of the process, which is full of contradictions, can only be seen from the standpoint of its end. The higher stage will always synthesise into a unity the contradictions of the previous stage. The highest stage is that of the Absolute, which Hegel understood theistically. But the key point at which Hegel failed, in Pannenberg's view, was his incapacity to see the Absolute in its futurity. He thus associated the Absolute with his own thought, rather than with an open future. Pannenberg, often criticised for being too Hegelian, moves away from Hegel here, adopting the biblical view that truth must be understood eschatologically. Only at the end, understood eschatologically, not as some timeless Absolute, will truth - the truth of all things and the truth about God - disclose itself. This raises the question of the status of present truth-claims; what is the relation of present truth to this final, eschatological truth? The issue is not one of the adequacy of concepts for the reality to which they are supposed to correspond. Truth becomes a matter of anticipation, of openness to its future disclosure. Pannenberg sees this as the same as trust in God, whose reality awaits its verification from the same future. The problem of truth can therefore never be only a philosophical matter; it is as much 116 ZI
BQTz, 9.
7 BQT2, 18. See also 'Wahrheit, Gewissheit und Glaube', GSTz, 2.2.9. 118 BQT2, zof. 118
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
theological. In particular, it is christological; the Christian claim is that Jesus Christ is the ultimate, unsurpassable revelation of God, and thus embodies the truth of God. But this itself is to be understood proleptically. The truth that appeared in Christ is an appearance of the eschatological truth in the form of anticipation. Its truth can only be definitively established in the eschatological future, but it is nonetheless an anticipatory form of the same truth. Pannenberg understands not only the concept of truth but the nature of reflection in this anticipatory, eschatological way. In his discussion of the 'concept' and its place in philosophy he takes up Dilthey's criticism of 'the domination of the concept'.119 Again, Hegel's view of philosophical truth as a higher form of religious or theological truth exemplifies the problem. This is not intended as a veto on metaphysical thought or conceptual clarity. But any metaphysical statement - and it is no less true for theological statements - is unavoidably limited by the historicity of its starting point. What follows, then, for metaphysics and philosophical thought generally? Metaphysical reflection must ... take on the form of a conjectural reconstruction in relation to its object, one which distinguishes itself from its intended truth while at the same time construing itself as a preliminary form of this truth. Its characteristic reflective form will have to be more that of anticipation than that of concept in the sense of classical metaphysics. Put more precisely, the philosophical concept will reveal itself to have the structure of anticipation.120
Beyond recognizing the anticipatory structure of all assertions, and especially of hypothetical assertions concerning reality as a whole, Pannenberg sees it as the task of metaphysics to investigate 'the structure of anticipations'.121 The relation between the anticipation and the content toward which it is directed may be seen either as external, that is, accidental, or as intrinsic. Pannenberg argues for a more than accidental connection between an anticipation and its content. On the one hand, the truth of the anticipation 'hinges on the still-absent future'; on the other hand, the anticipation is 'a real instance of something's occurring in 119 120 121
W. Pannenberg, 'Concept and Anticipation', M/G, 92. M/G, 93f. Pannenberg's italics. M/G, 94. 119
GOD AND THE FUTURE
advance'.122 An anticipation is unavoidably ambiguous. Its truthcontent will always depend on a future verification. But if there should be no future confirmation of the truth-claim implicit in the anticipation, it will turn out to be wrong, mere 'prophetic enthusiasm'. We can never have final certainty about the truth of our assertions in philosophy, theology or any science that is empirical and predictive. As we have seen, the notion of 'anticipation' is of major importance in Pannenberg's theology and has its applicability across an almost unlimited field of experience. The breadth of its scope is accounted for by the fact that the forms of anticipation of final reality are many and varied; there is no concept, no statement, no historical being of which it cannot be said that it is an anticipation of final reality, either ontically or noetically. This, of course, is more obvious in respect of some things than others. In everyday speech or experience we are more or less unaware of the reality or truth of which a particular thing or statement is an anticipation. Pannenberg describes these kinds of anticipation as 'broken'.123 In thinking about people, for example, we are more likely to regard them as the product of their past history than as the anticipation of their final identity or essence. In other experiences - Pannenberg suggests things like peace, spirit, love and life - there is a greater continuity between the present experience and its full eschatological reality. He calls these examples of 'unbroken' or 'pure' anticipation, even though our participation in these realities is not actually pure. When Christians speak of 'life in the Spirit' or 'abiding in Christ' they speak of an anticipation of an essentially eschatological reality; Pannenberg would regard this a case of 'pure' anticipation. The same would be true in the Christian experience of holy communion as a foretaste of the heavenly banquet. The terms 'broken', 'unbroken' and 'pure' are probably not the clearest, but they intend to point to varying degrees of obvious continuity between the present experience and the future reality which it anticipates. It should be emphasised, however, that Pannenberg sees the truth of every statement and the truth of every creature from the standpoint of its final, eschatological 122
M/G, 96.
12.3 w. Pannenberg, 'Response to the Discussion', in Robinson and Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, z6zL 12O
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
truth or being. There is nothing created that does not have some relation to God's eschatological rule over the whole creation. The concept of anticipation permits the predication of both identity and difference between something that exists now and its final essence. Consider human persons, to whom we readily attribute a unique set of attributes which, together with a unique history, make them what they are. But what are they? Are they what they are becoming, or are they becoming what they are? If the latter, how is this so? It cannot be disputed that they change with time, that what they are changes over time.114 Only at their death - and in an important sense not even then - is their identity established finally and fully. Pannenberg writes, 'Not only our knowing but also the identity of things themselves [is] not yet completely present in the process of time.'115 What something is changes with time, as it becomes part of new contexts of meaning; thus its essence appears only at the end. But at the same time it has to be said that this had been its essence all along. This is a paradoxical state of affairs, which Pannenberg illustrates from the field of horticulture: A zinnia is already a zinnia as a cutting and remains one during the entire process of its growth up to blossoming, even though the flower bears its name on account of its blossom. If there were only a single such flower, we could not determine its nature in advance; and yet over the period of its growth it would still be what it revealed itself to be at the end. It would possess its essence through anticipation, though only at the end of the developmental process would one be able to know that this was its essence.126
Pannenberg makes both a noetic and an ontological point here. We cannot know the essence of something until it is fully disclosed at the end of its existence; this is not a controversial remark. It is the ontological point that is the heart of his claim. What he claims here is that the essence or identity of something is not determined until its end; if the end were to be different its essence would also be different; yet by anticipation it already possesses its essence. Pannenberg describes this as the retroactive constitution of the 124
Pannenberg argues that there is no supra-historical identity that persists through time; ATP, 240, 513-15. IZ 5 MIG, 104. Ii6 M/G, 105. IZI
GOD AND THE FUTURE
essence of a thing from the future.12-7 Technically, he proposes a modification of Aristotle's concept of substance by allowing 'time and becoming [to be] the medium that constitutes the whatness of things'. Then things would 'be what they are ... retroactively from the outcome of their becoming on the one hand, and on the other in the sense of anticipating the completion of their process of becoming, their history'.128 This is an important statement for understanding the notion of anticipation and the primacy of the future. What is most difficult here is the idea of the retroactive establishment of essence or identity. From the standpoint of the present it is established from the future; yet this future is anticipated already in the present. What endures through time is a series of changing (enriching or diminishing) anticipations of the identity that is established retroactively from the future. It may be objected that there must be some ontic structure that exists in and through historical change,129 but Pannenberg would not see any such constant structure or element as non-temporal. Nor would he see the need for it to avoid the structure of anticipation.130 Pannenberg's ontology of the future sounds unfamiliar and counter-intuitive. But it is also strangely attractive. He has been developing his theological-philosophical vision with great consistency for several decades now, and shown it to be comprehensive and far-reaching. He has mounted strong criticisms of alternative ontological positions.131 A major strength of his position is its emphasis on the openness of being to the new. It is immensely liberating, for example, to think of human persons as not simply the outcome of their past history but as the anticipation of their future identity. Similarly, Pannenberg's view of truth, of concepts, and of the relation between thought and reality is thoughtprovoking and challenging. The whole proposal, in its breadth and detail, is breathtaking in its originality. In contrast to the school of I2 7 Ii8 IZ9
M/G, 107. M/G, 107.
P. Clayton, 'Being and One Theologian', 668. '3° ATP, 514. 131 R. Olson says that Tannenberg's critiques of ... other metaphysical concepts of God and the world are extremely cogent. His historical and logical analyses meticulously reveal their inner aporias'; Review of M/G in Journal of Religion 72.2, April 1992., 2,86. 12,2
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
process thought, to which many thinkers have contributed, Pannenberg has single-handedly developed an alternative ontological vision which is fully a match for process thought in its sophistication.132 Pannenberg's ontological proposals have generated a good deal of interest. But have they - especially the idea of anticipation been persuasive? P. Clayton, a friendly critic, is not satisfied that Pannenberg's concept of anticipation has been shown to work. There have been five areas of criticisms. First, ever since Pannenberg moved away from a theology of hope and began to develop a theology of the future it has been claimed that his ontological ideas lack substantiation, and such claims continue to be made. However, whether this was ever a fair criticism or not, it can no longer be made after the publication of three volumes of Systematic Theology and Metaphysics and the Idea of God. This is a criticism which cannot be substantiated, and it is easily dismissed. Second, a related criticism, not deserving of any more attention than the first, is that Pannenberg's theology is too much concerned with ontological questions. Thirty years ago H. Obayashi made the criticism that Pannenberg's ontology 'ultimately succumbs to an ontological totalitarianism'.133 R. Ahlers suggests that, in attending too closely to the metaphysical questions of modern philosophy, a theologian may not only fail at that level but also surrender his/her proper theological obligations.134 These criticisms are mainly methodological; about the proper business of theology. Pannenberg is unwilling to do theology in isolation from other areas of thought, especially philosophy and the natural sciences. He is indeed a strongly philosophical theologian, but no reader of the Systematic Theology could fail to discern a very theological theologian. This, too, is not a serious criticism. I3Z
See J. B. Cobb, 'Pannenberg and Process Theology', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 55. P. Hefner has described the magnitude of his programme as 'stunning'; p. 2.83 of the same volume. 133 H. Obayashi, 'Future and Responsibility: A Critique of Pannenberg's Eschatology', Sciences Religieuses/Studies in Religion i, 1971, 198f. 134 R. Ahlers, Theory of God and Theological Method', Dialog 2.2, Summer 1983, 2,39. 113
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Third, another criticism, deserving of serious consideration, is that Pannenberg is (consciously or not) a 'determinist'. This criticism is prompted by his understanding of God as the all-determining reality, which, on the face of it, might be incompatible with any real human freedom. For Pannenberg to make God's alldetermining power a matter of the future does not, it is alleged, overcome the problem.135 This criticism continues to be made; several contributors to The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg refer to the matter.136 But Pannenberg, in his response, speaks of 'the supposed peril of determinism';137 he has consistently denied the charge. However, the criticism warrants careful consideration, and this is best done in discussing God's action from the future in the next chapter. Fourth, Pannenberg is also criticised for accepting the idea of a future consummation of history. If this idea is rejected, the whole notion of the anticipation of the eschatological future must be rejected with it. What does 'the end of history' or 'the consummation of creation' mean? Some regard the idea of the end of the world as a hermeneutical necessity, but it is a horizon that is never actually reached; perhaps a vestige of apocalyptic thought which now needs to be abandoned.138 Process theologians, committed to the idea of a completely open future, question the validity of the idea of a temporal consummation of history. J. B. Cobb, while accepting the idea of human survival, cannot connect this with an assured consummation of history.139 L. Ford says that process theologians do not think of history or time as having an end.140 However, Pannenberg has consistently argued for the necessity of a final consummation of all things in history, although he postulates no simple series of events corresponding to the symbols of 135 This is the criticism of David McKenzie in Tannenberg on God and Freedom', The Journal of Religion 60.3, July 1980, esp. 319-19. 136 See the essays by Clayton (140!.), Polk (152-68), Ford (75-89) and Cobb (68-70). It is also a major issue discussed in D. Polk, On the Way to God, esp. ch. 8. 137 Pannenberg, 'A Response to my American Friends', 321; italics added. 138 W. Logister, 'Het Eschatologisch Probleem bij Wolfhart Pannenberg: Analyse en Kritiek', Nederlands Theologisch Tijdschrift 24, April 1970, 283-6. 139 Cobb, Tannenberg and Process Theology', 67. 140 L. Ford, The Divine Activity of the Future', Process Studies 11.3, Fall 1981, 178.
124
THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY OF THE FUTURE
eschatological expectation.141 He has devoted the last chapter of his theological system to a discussion of many aspects of the Christian expectation of the end, including the idea of the kingdom of God as the entry of eternity into time.142 This is a criticism which, if it had validity, would apply to almost all theology claiming to be Christian. Fifth, Pannenberg is criticised for not being consistent in his use of the concept of anticipation. This criticism is made most carefully by P. Clayton, who claims that Pannenberg uses the term in two different senses, one of which would make him a determinist. The first sense (anticipation^ implies an ontologically determinate view of history; the second (anticipationJ has a more open view of history.143 The question is whether the totality of meaning anticipated in a particular event is thereby unalterably and invariably set in place - in which case a 'determinist' reading of history is warranted - or whether there is a real possibility that the end which is purportedly anticipated may turn out to be different from what is expected - in which case the event will not have been correctly understood as that anticipation. Clayton is justified in claiming that there is such a discrepancy in Pannenberg's use of 'anticipation' and in insisting that the tension between the two senses of the concept must be resolved. It is not enough to say that 'the two belong together'.144 There is no detailed response to Clayton's criticism in Metaphysics and the Idea of God. While the concept of anticipation is in many ways remarkable, a fuller discussion of it, focussing especially on the tension between an open and a determinate view of history, would be helpful. In this chapter we have surveyed the major aspects of 141 W. Pannenberg, 'Can Christianity Do without an Eschatology?', in G. B. Caird, The Christian Hope, 3 zf. These things are finally a matter of hope. They also exceed all our concepts, as does the divine reality itself; STj, 52.7. 142 STj, 595-607. Pannenberg says, The relation between time and eternity is the crucial problem in eschatology'; 595. Many theological problems can only be clarified on the basis of an adequate view of the relation between time and eternity. I4 ^ P. Clayton, 'Anticipation and Theological Method', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 137^ 144 Clayton, 'Anticipation and Theological Method', 138. Pannenberg's response is on p. 311.
125
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Pannenberg's eschatological ontology. From the beginning he was fascinated with the ontological implications of Jesus' understanding of the kingdom of God and Jesus' resurrection from the dead. In the course of developing these implications in both the noetic and ontic realms, Pannenberg overturned some standard ontological assumptions, such as the priority of the past over the present and the future, and argued for the priority of the future. What he proposes might well be the beginning of a 'paradigm shift' which, if the problems with it can be resolved, may throw new light on old ontological questions. We have made frequent reference to God. Pannenberg is right to insist that ontology and theology cannot properly be separated. The focus in this chapter has been on ontological issues; in the next chapter the focus will be on the understanding of God which Pannenberg develops in tandem with his ontology. For him the point is unquestionably theology, and theology is essentially the 'science' of God. The ontology has a supportive role, though it is intended to make a contribution in its own distinctive realm. The next two chapters will investigate Pannenberg's understanding of the being and action of God in relation to the cosmos. In particular, we shall ask what kind of God has the futurist ontology we have been considering as its correlate.
12,6
5
The God of the future Introduction
A
good deal has already been said about Pannenberg's understanding of God in the previous two chapters, since his ontological and theological thought cannot be separated. We now have to see how the eschatological perspective shapes the doctrine of God. This will first be done in a general way and then in the final chapter quite explicitly in a trinitarian way. In particular, we must show what Pannenberg means by the idea that God is the power of the future or that the future is God's mode of being, and what this means both for God's being and God's action in the world. This will involve a comparison of Pannenberg's view of God with that of some other theologians, notably process thinkers. The underlying issue will be the relation of God to the course of history. Critics have pointed to the danger of falling into a Hegelian equation of God and history, but Pannenberg steers well clear of such a confusion.1 The question about God's being and God's relation to created reality must be posed on the tension between God as the all-determining reality - Pannenberg's working definition of God - and as the world's future which gives freedom to the world to go its own way. Indeed, Pannenberg argues that it is precisely the freedom of human beings and the contingency of events in the world that 1 Grenz defends Pannenberg on this point; Reason for Hope, 71. T. Bradshaw regards Pannenberg's theology as 'a Hegelian doctrine of quite a pure strain', with an ultimate identification of the divine and the historical; see 'God's Relationship to History in Pannenberg', Scottish Bulletin of Evangelical Theology, Special Study 3, 1989, 59, 61.
127
GOD AND THE FUTURE
require an understanding of God as future. This does not mean that God is only future; as the future of every past, God's action can be described in all three tenses. However, this tension gives rise to two important questions. First, if God is related to the world primarily as its future, how does God create from this future? This question, already raised in the previous chapter, must be pressed further. It represents a point of significant interaction with process theology. Second, can Pannenberg survive the criticism that he is a crypto-determinist in his view of history?2 Prima facie, understanding God as the 'all-determining' reality or power stands in tension with other things Pannenberg claims about God's relation to created reality. This alleged determinism needs to be substantiated or refuted. Before considering these questions, it will be useful to see how the idea of God's futurity originates and develops in Pannenberg's thought. Here three essays are of particular importance: 'The Question of God',3 'The God of Hope'4 and 'Theology and the Kingdom of God'.5 These essays, together with the view of God Pannenberg was expressing in his work on Christology,6 show clearly the direction in which his theology was heading. Their discussion of God's futurity forms a foundation for his later articulation of the doctrine of God. Pannenberg can hardly have foreseen in the early 19605 how these ideas would find their systematic shape,7 but he saw already then that there would be radical implications. These early ideas about God contain the seed of his developed theological thought, culminating in the Systematic z To my knowledge, this term has not actually been used of Pannenberg. I use it because the criticism that he is a determinist is made despite his vigorous denials. 3 First given as a lecture in Gottingen in July 1964, published in Evangelische Theologie, 2,5, 1965; see BQTz, ch. 7. 4 First published in the Festschrift, Ernst Block zu Ehren, ed. S. Unseld (Frankfurt, 1965); see BQTz, ch. 8. 5 First published in Una Sancta 2,4.2, 1967, 3-19; later in TKG, ch. i, 51-71. 6 W. Pannenberg, Grundzuge der Christologie (JGM) was published in 1964. 7 He refers to the 'many years' it took him to fit the many topics of theology into a systematic whole, the doctrine of God being the most difficult. 'An Autobiographical Sketch', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 16.
12,8
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
Theology. Their importance cannot be overstated, for there is a very clear continuity between his early and his later theological thought. Early ideas about God Pannenberg was driven in his early work on reformulating the doctrine of God by two main concerns: a positive and a negative one. The positive concern, discussed already, was the conviction that in both Jesus' proclamation of the kingdom of God and in his resurrection a thoroughly eschatological reality is in view. It is a matter of the ultimate future of God and God's power over all things. This gives rise to a simple theological syllogism: 1i) The concept of God cannot be detached from the idea of the kingdom of God. (2) The kingdom of God is unquestionably an eschatological reality. (3) Therefore God must be understood in an eschatological way. Years later Pannenberg spoke of reformulating the doctrine of God 'on the basis of eschatology' or 'from the point of view of Jesus' eschatological message'.8 As we noted in chapter two, Pannenberg regards Jesus' proclamation of the kingdom of God as strongly influenced by apocalyptic thought. God can be thought of only in relation to the coming of God's eschatological rule. 'God's being and existence cannot be conceived apart from his rule.'9 The negative concern is equally important: dissatisfaction with the classical philosophical understanding of God in theology. There are clearly serious difficulties with this understanding of God, as both theological critics and atheist observers have pointed out. Pannenberg's own view is that 'the classical Christian concept of God, if rigorously developed, could result in unacceptable, deterministic consequences'.10 Pannenberg was driven to his doctrine of God, negatively, by his dissatisfaction with the reformulations of the concept of God in German Idealism (especially 8
Pannenberg, 'Providence, God, and Eschatology', 175. TKG, 55. 10 Pannenberg, 'Providence, God, and Eschatology', 175; cf. 'Speaking about God in the Face of Atheist Criticism', BQTj, ch. 3, esp. 107-15. 9
129
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Hegel) and by process thinkers, beginning with Whitehead and Alexander.11 The combined force of these influences resulted in the initially very surprising idea that God's reality is essentially future. The key phrase Pannenberg used in respect of God was 'the power of the future'; it is found in certain key essays, after which it recedes into the background.12 The reason is probably twofold. First, Pannenberg later developed a much fuller account of the problem of time, in which the priority of the future was given a more solid ontological foundation.13 Second, Pannenberg was also developing his doctrine of the Trinity in the 1970S,14 and one of the key elements in such a doctrine is the relation of God to history. For Pannenberg, the doctrine of the Trinity provides the key to understanding how God can be 'absolute in His relation to the world and not restricted by it, but fulfilled ... through that relationship'.15 The details of this discussion will be considered in the final chapter, but his doctrine of the Trinity is a more differentiated attempt to articulate the Christian belief that God acts on the present (and thus has acted on what is now the past) from the future. However, this is to anticipate the culmination of Pannenberg's doctrine of God. The initial moves in this direction develop the idea of God as 'the power of the future', especially in the essays referred to. In the even earlier monograph on Christology there are already strong hints of such a view of God. In the discussion of Jesus' participation in the lordship of God, Pannenberg links the futurity of God's lordship with God's eternity.16 Eternity is not to be understood as timelessness but as inclusive of time and as its source and goal. However, from the standpoint of time this fulness can only be sought in the future.17 In the early work the idea of the 11
Pannenberg, 'Providence, God, and Eschatology', 175. It still occurs in 'Eschatologie und Sinnerfahrung' (1972.), published in Gottesgedanke und menschliche Freiheit and GSTz; ET in BQTj, ch. 7; see esp. 2.10. 13 Pannenberg, 'Being and Time', in MIG, ch. 4, 77-84: '... when the theory of time is oriented toward the eternal totality, the consequence is a primacy of the future for the understanding of time'. 14 See the three important essays on the Trinity in GST2, chs 3-5. 15 Pannenberg, The God of History', 35. A translation of 'Der Gott der Geschichte', GSTz, 12.2. 16 /GM, 368. J 7 STi, 408. 12
130
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
creation of all things from the future also appears but is not developed. Creation takes place out of the ultimate future, from the eschaton, for 'only from the perspective of the end are all things what they truly are'.18 In this early work Pannenberg does not develop the idea of God as future. For this we must look at the three important essays mentioned above. i. 'The Question of God' In this first essay the issue is the justification of speech about God in a secular climate of thought. Pannenberg agrees that the question of God arises primarily in the context of the (religious) experience of a power that can bring human existence to its wholeness and grant it coherence and meaning.19 It is especially important to defend the personal nature of this power,20 that is, its non-manipulability and concrete claim upon individuals. In the personhood of Israel's God lay his freedom and faithfulness, experienced in a history of ever new events. God's reality and faithfulness can only be finally established in the future. Given the difficulty - in the modern world - of speaking about God, the key point is God's future, 'the future of his reign, which will be the definitive revelation of his deity'.21 The future of God is thus critical for the knowledge that God is and who God is. But God is known precisely in God's rule, as the history of the world is given its coherence and meaning in relation to God; and this rule will be conclusively real in the future. Only the coming God is Lord over all things. The same point is made anthropologically. On the one hand, belief in God precipitates the question of what it means to 18
/GM, 2,30. See also TKG, 70. See BQTz, 222-7. The framework within which speech about God can take place in the modern world, in Pannenberg's view, is that of anthropology. 20 This is a major task Pannenberg sets himself; cf. BQTz, 2.2.6-32. Pannenberg argues that thinking about God as personal is not a projection on the basis of the 'personal' character of human existence, but that 'the modern concept of the personal has arisen out of Christian theology; indeed from the problems of Christology and the doctrine of the Trinity'; 229. The claim is substantiated in Pannenberg's article, 'Person', in Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, Vol. 5, 3rd edn., 1961, cols 230-5. The key point, contra Fichte, is that the infinity of God is not a barrier to God's personhood, but actually underscores it; BQTz, 231. Pannenberg returns to this theme in 'The God of Hope', BQTz, esp. 245. " BQTz, 232. 19
131
GOD AND THE FUTURE
be human; on the other hand, understanding the human being includes the question about God. This question, too, reaches its goal only 'in the eschatological future of God's public reign'.22 Thus, in this early essay, Pannenberg claims that in both an ontological and epistemological sense God can only be thought of in connection with the future. The future of God's rule will prove who and what God is, and will confirm that the human quest for God, now so ambiguous, has a solid ground and a sure goal. 2. 'The God of Hope' In this second essay, more important than the first, Pannenberg asks whether there are new possibilities for speaking of God in the wake of modern atheism's rejection of the idea of the highest being or the omnipotent deity who leaves no room for human freedom.23 His argument is that the biblical God is the God of the promises, 'the God who leads history into a new future', 'the God of the coming kingdom', and that in this light all reality is to be understood as eschatologically oriented.24 This focus on the future received unparalleled sharpness in the life and teaching of Jesus, with the result that God's future was seen as determinative of the present. As we saw in chapter four, there are points of connection here with Bloch, who had shown the power of the still-open future and of the hope that reaches out to it. Bloch would have the eschatological kingdom without the God of the kingdom, which for Pannenberg makes the kingdom ontologically precarious. There is neither a kingdom without God nor a God without the kingdom. This has radical implications for the way we understand God: from the biblical standpoint the being of God and that of the kingdom are identical, since the being of God is his lordship. He is God only in the execution of this lordship, and this full accomplishment of his lordship is determined as something future. To this extent, the God to whom the hope of the kingdom refers is characterized in a radical and exclusive sense by 'futurity as a quality of being'/5
In this essay we see a more developed view of God's being and encounter ideas of great originality. In a few pages he sets out ideas ^ Z 3 n 2 5
5QT2, 2,32,. The God of Hope', JBQT2, 235. JBQT2, 237. BQTz, 240. 132
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
which will become foundational in his doctrine of God. Six points are particularly salient.26 First, the accent shifts to God's futurity. Pannenberg makes a significant modification to the classical doctrine of God. God is still to be thought of as transcendent, but not in the usual way. With encouragement from Bloch's thought, the question of God as the most perfect being now assumes a temporal form and becomes a question about 'the end' of all things.27 God is not to be thought of as 'a self-contained being alongside other beings'. It is no longer credible to think of God as 'a thing at hand, even as a thingified person, or a "reified hypostasis" '. God as 'absolute in the mode of being present at hand' is no longer thinkable, because all existing things can be superseded. God cannot be superseded by a greater reality or power. If the idea of God is to have meaning, it can only be a God with futurity as a quality of being. Pannenberg sees this as a move away from 'the God of theism'.28 Pannenberg was reluctant to predicate existence of God - a point to which we shall return - and the emphasis on God's being as essentially future appealed as a way out of the problem. Second, God's being is God's rule. The emphasis on God's futurity goes hand in hand with a move from a static to a dynamic conception of God. On the basis of the centrality of the kingdom of God in the preaching of Jesus, Pannenberg discusses the connection between God's deity and God's kingdom. Is the kingdom of God, the future of God's lordship, integral to God's deity or incidental to it? For him God is God 'only in the accomplishment of his lordship over the world', and God's lordship will be fully apparent only when the kingdom comes.29 So God's deity - God's being God - and God's kingdom or rule are inseparably connected. Without God's rule God could not be God. God's being implies God's rule; and if God's rule is not complete till the eschaton, God's being, too, cannot be already complete.30 Third, God is powerful as the future is powerful. The answer to 26
See BQTz, esp. pp. 240-9. BQT2, 24if. The following quotations come from the same pages. i8 BQTz, 242. Pannenberg does not explain this phrase, but he must mean the God of classical theism, essentially above or beyond time. 2 9 BQTz, 242. 30 'Does this not mean that God is not yet, but is yet to be?' BQTz, 242. This raises difficult questions which we shall consider. 27
133
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the question whether God already is or is yet to be is that God 'exists only in the way in which the future is powerful over the present'.31 God does not exist as something that is at hand in the present; God is not an object in the world. God is not 'the quiescent background of all beings, the timeless being underlying all objects', but 'the power of the future'. 32 The future 'decides' over the present; everything that has ever happened has been brought about by the power of the future, confronting every present. God has existed 'as the future that has been powerful in every present'.33 God's futurity implies God's eternity, but not as timelessness or as mere endurance. God's eternity has to be thought of as the power of the future over the present. It is not clear from this early essay what all this means; what it means that God determines or decides the present, or how God is active in the world. Pannenberg does offer this suggestion: 'God, through the realization of the historical future at a given time, pushed this away from himself as power of the ultimate future and in this way mediated himself to it in his own eschatological futurity.' 34 This requires a good deal of elucidation and development, but the key point is that the immediate historical future of any event - not its past - is the point at which God is causally active in relation to it. Fourth, God creates from the future. A God who is the power of the future cannot be thought of as creator along conventional lines, as 'first cause' of all things in the universe. As Pannenberg expresses it, the God of the coming kingdom had to become the occasion for an eschatological reversal of the idea of creation as soon as he was recognized ... as the one who by the future of his lordship is alone powerful over the present world and decisive for its meaning, its essence.35
We will consider the nature and extent of this 'eschatological 31 BQT2, 242. 3- BQT2, 242. 3a3 BQT2, 244. The theme of eternity as futurity is not further developed here. 34 BQT2, 2.44. The idea of an event's participation in God's immediate historical future and the correlative idea of God's self-mediation (as the power of the ultimate future) to the immediate historical future stand in need of considerable elucidation. 35 BQT2, 243. 134
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
reversal' in due course, but it is clear from this quotation that the idea of creation includes the determination of its essence and its meaning, which has to wait until the future. How God is causally involved in creation is not yet clear, nor the way in which the present gets its shape. We have only a first intimation of ideas which receive more detailed attention in subsequent works, notably the second volume of Systematic Theology. What is clear is its orientation to the future rather than to the past. God is the future that is powerful in every present. Fifth, the seal of God's futurity is the Trinity. Especially striking in this early essay is the trinitarian note on which it ends. The issue is the future of God, the fulfilment of all that has been promised, which involves the participation of the world in the glory of God. This can be understood on the analogy of the relation between the Son and the Father.36 Their unity presupposes Jesus' self-differentiation from God, but in thinking of the future lordship of God the emphasis is on the unity of the Son with the Father, which, in Pannenberg's view, can only be consistently thought in trinitarian terms. He wants to show the nature of the relation between what presently exists and the future of God's lordship and appeals to the doctrine of the Trinity to show that the Son is one with the Father by dedicating himself completely to the Father's coming kingdom. His point is that participation in the glory of God requires openness to God's future and acknowledging its primacy over everything that exists now. This does not require a negative attitude to the present but the recognition that every given state of affairs must be left behind, in order that it may be transformed. This transformation is the expression of God's love and the power of its future over the present, through which the present is transformed toward the glory of God. The doctrine of the Trinity reinforces the priority of God's future over everything that 36
At the time of writing there was no question about the appropriateness of using the term 'Father' for God. In later writings Pannenberg has defended the traditional terminology. He finds it 'unacceptable that a revision should be called for in addressing God as Father on the grounds of our changed views about the position of woman in society'; Christianity in a Secularized World, 54. He leaves himself open to sharp criticism in saying that 'the exchange of this name inevitably results in turning to another God'; 1ST, 31. A fuller discussion may be found in STi, 159-64; also 'Feminine Language About God?', Asbury Theological Journal 48.2, Fall 1993, 2.7-9, esP- 27-
*35
GOD AND THE FUTURE
presently exists. Pannenberg describes it as 'the seal of the pure futurity of God'.37 It prevents us from reducing the relation between present creaturely reality and the future reality of God's rule to that of a stark antithesis. As the Father draws the Son to himself in love, so the future of God draws present created reality, with its negativity and pain, into itself.38 Sixth, God's futurity safeguards human freedom. Pannenberg sees a direct connection between the idea of God as the power of the future and the establishment of human freedom. If God were both omnipotent and 'a being presently at hand', human freedom would amount to nothing. What he means by freedom is 'the freedom to transcend every present state of affairs'. 39 Human power and freedom and divine omnipotence each have to be given their due. Far from threatening human freedom, God as the power of the future reinforces it. The power of the future 'frees man from his ties to what presently exists in order to liberate him for his future, to give him his freedom'.40 This is part of Pannenberg's notion of creation from the future, which preserves the contingency of each event in history. Just as God, as a personal agent, is free in the sense of not being bound by the present, so the human person is similarly free, not bound to the present and not bound by the past. Human beings are free because they have a future to which they can be open. So, freedom is 'the power that transforms the present'. But freedom itself has futurity as a condition of its possibility. Thus, freedom and future are correlative ideas, both in respect of the human being and (a fortiori) of God. Freedom is the capacity to transcend the present. Having a future which is not just the outcome of the past and the present is what makes room for a real notion of freedom. God, the power of the future, does not erode human freedom but gives it its possibility. With these major themes running through this essay - albeit not developed - it is clearly of importance.
37 BQT2, 249. 38
39
terms. 40
BQTz, 249. These ideas are developed in STz, ch. n, esp. §§4 & 5. BQTz, 141. Pannenberg will not discuss freedom in purely formal BQT2, 243. Pannenberg's italics. 136
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
3. 'Theology and the Kingdom of God' By contrast with this essay, the better-known 'Theology and the Kingdom of God' breaks little new ground. It has the appearance of a summary essay, presenting in outline and less technical language points argued more fully elsewhere. It does, however, highlight two methodological commitments. Pannenberg argues the case for the Gospel of God's coming rule on premises which are publicly accessible. Second, the point of departure for his thought is the Christian Gospel. Pannenberg's understanding of reality is shaped by the idea of the future kingdom of God, which already impinges on the present.41 In addition, there are four points in this essay that throw light on Pannenberg's understanding of God as future. First, God's being is God's rule. This point, which already appeared in the previous essay, is one of Pannenberg's key theological ideas. Here he puts it in a way that gained him a certain notoriety. It begins with the familiar observation that God's being and existence cannot be conceived apart from God's rule. In the language of the philosophy of religion, 'the being of the gods is their power'.42 God's power does not require there to be a created cosmos over which to have power, but once there is a created world God must have power over it; this belongs to the very idea of God. However, if God's rule is a future reality rather than an existent one, does this mean that the being of God is also a future rather than a present reality? Pannenberg gives the following answer: it is necessary to say that, in a restricted but important sense, God does not yet exist. Since his rule and his being are inseparable, God's being is still in the process of coming to be. Considering this, God should not be mistaken for an objectified being presently existing in its fullness ... Obviously, if the mode of God's being is interlocked with the coming of his rule, we should not be surprised or embarrassed that God cannot be 'found' somewhere in present reality.43
41
Neuhaus, describing Pannenberg's theology, says, 'the truth about the universe, Christian theology contends, is that the Kingdom of God is at hand'; TKG, 23. 42 TKG, 5543 TXG, 56. Polk describes it as a 'cryptic observation, widely quoted and almost as widely misunderstood'; On the Way to God, 2,50. 137
GOD AND THE FUTURE
The idea that 'God does not yet exist' is carefully qualified; it is true in a restricted sense. There is a sense in which it is not true; no denial of God's reality is implied. But there is also a sense in which the proposition is true. The issue is whether it is possible, within the context of a history that is not yet complete, to speak of the full reality of God. If this is not possible, then what is the appropriate way to speak of the present reality of God?44 The underlying question is about God's relation to history. Specifically, how is God affected by time? We will return to this question in due course. Second, God, the unity of all things, is essentially a future reality. If God's being is inseparable from God's rule, and if that rule reaches its fulness only in the eschatological future, then God's being must be in process of becoming. This fundamental point, to be further elucidated, is now reinforced by a second argument. Pannenberg asserts that a meaningful sequence of events requires not only the character of contingency, but also a unity. This unity may be supplied by a chain of cause and effect, as in a deterministic view of the world, but events describable as personal acts can never be reduced to such a sequence. Personal acts are characterised by both contingency and a unity that makes them the expression of a particular individual. Pannenberg proposes that God be regarded as the personal power at work in the infinitely complex series of contingent events that constitutes the universe. It is God who constitutes - or will constitute - these events as a unity. There is no simple step from postulating the unity of all things to the idea of God as the creator of all things, but from ancient times these ideas have been connected. 'The quest for the ultimate unity which integrates and thus unifies everything is the question reaching for God, as that question has been asked since the beginning of Greek philosophy.'45 Any concept of God which could not account for the unity of all reality would be inadequate. However, this unity is not apparent as a presently-existing reality. Neither is it any longer an option to think of it as existing in an eternal realm above the world of changing phenomena. Being 44 Polk astutely identifies three connected concerns out of which these early remarks of Pannenberg can be seen to arise; On the Way to God, 2,52,.
4
5 TKG, 60.
138
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
cannot be thought of apart from time. Pannenberg adopts an eschatological approach: the unity of all things can only be expected from the future, as 'something to be achieved by a process of reconciling previous schisms and contradictions'.46 Again, the implication is that God provides this unity - brings about completeness or closure, and therefore acts from - the future. This has implications for God's being. Third, God exercises power from the future. For Pannenberg, the idea of the future is not an abstract one; it is not an empty category.47 While we tend consciously to think of the future as created out of the present, we also experience it as a powerful reality moving toward us with either threat or promise. Does the future then actually have power over against the present? In the previous chapter we saw how Pannenberg sees the future as a powerful field of the possible, the sphere in which the Spirit expresses itself in creation.48 We noted already that the concept of power is closely tied up with the idea of the future. Now it becomes for Pannenberg a mediating idea between the future and God. Theologically speaking, God is powerful over the present as the future is powerful over the present. As we confront the future we confront God. The power of the future is the power of God. 'In every present we confront the infinite future, and in welcoming the particular finite events which spring from that future, we anticipate the coming of God.'49 There is no possibility of an argument which shows that the power of the future must be understood as the power of God. But if Jesus' message about the kingdom of God is true, God must be the future of the world. Then it follows that 'all experience of the future is, at least indirectly, related to God himself. In this case every event in which the future becomes finitely present must be understood as a contingent act of God .. .'5° In later years Pannenberg refines his ideas on how God creates from the future. 51 It has to be remembered that Pannenberg's 46 47
TKG, 60.
TKG, 56. It is 'neither empty category nor bundle of chances', 59. See ch. 4, 'Contingency and connection', above pp. yji. ^ TKG, 59. 5° TKG, 61. 51 See STi, ch. 7. On p. 98 Pannenberg refers to ideas presented in the essay under discussion as 'a first sketch'; see note 256. 48
139
GOD AND THE FUTURE
purpose in this early essay is not to justify speaking about God. He is exploring the implications of Jesus' message of the kingdom of God for the understanding of God. Thinking of God as the power of the future is an implication of accepting the reality of the coming kingdom of God. To see how Pannenberg grounds 'Godtalk' more generally we would have to look at his discussion of anthropology.52 Fourth, the power of the future is the power of love. Most striking in this essay is the identification of the power of the future with love. This, too, has its basis in the message of Jesus. 'It was possible for Jesus to interpret life comprehensively and exclusively in terms of eschatology only because Jesus discovered God's love in the imminence of the Kingdom.'53 The power of the coming kingdom of God already manifests itself as love in the forgiveness of sins and in the offer of salvation. Wherever new life is given, the power of the kingdom has already come in the form of love. In the Christian view of the world it is not possible to separate power and love. But love has its ontological grounding in the future: The creative character of love is linked to the power of the future ... The idea of power by itself is ambiguous, making possible both destruction and life. But creative love is unambiguous in asserting that the present is set free to life. Love is the only real answer we have to the startling question, Why should there be anything at all rather than nothing? Love grants existence and grants it contingently. This means that love grants new existence, in spite of the self-asserting arrogance of that which already is. In love we recognize the intrinsic dynamic at work in the eventuating of contingent events from the future and releasing them in the process of time.54
Only because the rule of God comes in love rather than sheer power can humankind participate in God's future. There would be no future for us if God were not a loving, reconciling God. Creation itself has its origin in the divine love. In the last chapter 52 Pannenberg believes that the ground on which the battle between theology and atheism is to be fought is anthropology; cf. 'Speaking about God in the face of Atheist Criticism', BQT$, esp. 106. Pannenberg later stated that 'theologians will be able to defend the truth precisely of their talk about God only if they first respond to the atheistic critique of religion on the terrain of anthropology'; ATP, 16. 53 TXG, 64. 54 TXG, 65. Cf. STi, ch. 6, §7, entitled The Love of God'.
140
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
of his theological 'system' Pannenberg also sees the eschatological consummation as the revelation of the love of God.55 But these ideas are already intimated in this early essay. Christian speech about God begins and ends with the love of God. The grammar of this speech is trinitarian, a point Pannenberg already emphasises at the end of this essay. 'The trinitarian doctrine describes the coming God as the God of love whose future has already arrived and who integrates the past and present world, accepting it to share in his own life forever.'56 We have looked at some of Pannenberg's early ideas about God. From these a view of God has begun to emerge which is a correlate of the eschatological ontology outlined in the previous chapter. Already it is apparent what far-reaching implications are contained in the idea that God's being is inseparable from God's rule. As God's rule is an eschatological reality, God's being must be such as to accommodate this. There must be a sense in which God is as well as a sense in which God is becoming. What this means for God's relation to time will have to be considered. Before doing this, however, we shall consider the way Pannenberg sees the relation between God's futurity and eternity. God's futurity and eternity The theme of the future is as prominent in Pannenberg's thought as it is perplexing. To understand Pannenberg's view of its ontological status requires a shift from familiar patterns of thought. The future is 'the "place" ... for the eternal presence that ancient Greek thought conceived as timeless'. This future is 'the point where time and eternity coincide'.57 This calls for some comment on the relation between God's eternity, which is an aspect of God's non-finite reality, and what might be called God's 'futurity'. Fundamental to this discussion is the redefinition of the notion of eternity. We saw in the previous chapter that the major element in this revision was the rejection of the notion of eternity as 55 56
ST3, 645.
TKG, 71. Pannenberg's trinitarian theology is the subject of ch. 6 below. 57 Pannenberg, 'Providence, God, and Eschatology', 178; see also the 'Response' in Braaten and Clayton, The Theology of Wolf hart Pannenberg, 321. 141
GOD AND THE FUTURE
timelessness. Eternity is the totality of life; the 'infinite unity of life'.58 Early Christian views of God's eternity were influenced by Plato's concept of the Forms or Ideas, which was itself influenced by Parmenides' notion of 'the One' which neither was nor will be but which is now all at once, a single whole.59 Pannenberg found in Plotinus the bridge between the antithesis of eternity and time and eternity as the fulness of time.60 Boethius developed this view into the classical line that eternity is 'authentic duration' and not just the negation of time.61 Time remains in relation to eternity, for the many moments of time remain bound to the fulness of time. The 'whole', however, is present 'only in the sense that it hovers over the parts as the future whole', toward which all finite things strive in time.62 The whole is indistinguishable from eternity. As the fulness of time, eternity implies duration, but not in the brokenness of separated moments which characterises time. Pannenberg claims that a theory of time oriented toward the eternal totality will give priority to the future. 63 But what is the relation between futurity and eternity? Does God's futurity constitute God's eternity, or does God's eternity include God's futurity? Is anything significant at stake in this question? It is interesting to see where the continuity lies between Pannenberg's earlier writings, dominated by the notion of God as the power of the future, and his later writings, in which he more typically speaks of God's eternity. In particular, is Pannenberg's discussion of God's eternity (in the Systematic Theology) still shaped by the understanding of God as the power of the future? In one of the early essays we looked at, Pannenberg clearly sees God's eternity in the light of God's futurity/ 4 Pannenberg wants to say that the future is not a mode but the mode of God's being. The future of God's lordship is integral to God's deity. Speaking directly about the relation between God's futurity and eternity, he 58
W. Pannenberg, Theology and Science', The Princeton Seminary Bulletin, 13.3, 1992., 305. 59 See e.g. W. Kneale, Time and Eternity in Theology', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 61, 1961, 87-108. 60 See ch. 4, Time and eternity', above pp. iO4f. 61 STi, 404. 6i MIG, 77. 63 This is attributed to Plotinus. See M7G, jji. 64 W. Pannenberg, The God of Hope', BQTz, esp. 242-4. 142
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
argues that 'the futurity of God implies his eternity'.65 God's eternity is included in God's futurity, for God has been the future of every past moment, no matter how far back in time. Thus God has been active 'before our present and before every present', precisely 'as the future that has been powerful in every present'. God's eternity is thus predicated upon God's being 'the power of the future over every present'.66 To use spatial categories, instead of imagining God to be behind every moment in the past and the present, pushing the present into the future, God is better thought of as being in front of every past and present moment, allowing it to participate in that part of God's future that is most immediate to it. In a later essay on time and eternity in the experience of Israel and Christianity, Pannenberg starts from the concept of God's eternity but understands it as the future of the world.67 He also speaks of the future of God as the parousia of God's eternity.68 God's futurity is not a matter only of distant futurity; it spans the whole of time. In fact, the time-spanning presence of God's future is God's eternity. God's eternity is then constituted by God's futurity, which is already present, not merely for Godself but also for the person who lives in faith, who already now trusts this future. In the early essays, when the notion of God's futurity is high on Pannenberg's theological agenda, God's eternity is described as an implication of God's futurity. It is not a question of reducing the former to the latter, but of showing their identity. In Pannenberg's mature, systematic account of God's being, found especially in the first volume of Systematic Theology, God as Holy Trinity is discussed first, followed by God's unity and attributes.69 Eternity is one of the attributes ascribed to God on the basis of what the concept of God implies; other attributes are ascribed to God on the basis of God's self-revelation in history. Thus to speak of God's eternity is a form of speaking about God's infinity. Pannenberg says that 'eternity, omnipotence, and omnipresence may be viewed as concrete manifestations of [God's] 6
5 BQT2, 244. BQT2, 244-
66 67
W. Pannenberg, 'Zeit und Ewigkeit in der religiosen Erfahrung Israels und des Christentums', GSTz, 201. 68
6
GST2,
202.
9 STi, chs 5 & 6. 143
GOD AND THE FUTURE
infinity from the standpoints of time, power, and space'.70 To predicate eternity of God is to assert that God embraces all time; that all time is present to God.71 It is clear from the later work that Pannenberg's agenda is no longer shaped by the concerns of his earlier writings. These concerns have not disappeared; he still insists on 'the constitutive significance of [the eschatological] consummation [of the kingdom] for the eternity of God'.72 But the focus is now on the eternity of God rather than on God as the power of the future. This is best explained as the replacement of a programmatic line of thought with a more careful, systematic working out of the Christian understanding of God. This systematic account coincides with the fuller exploration of the problem of time and eternity in Metaphysics and the Idea of God. There is no equivocation about including God's futurity in the attribute of eternity. Eschatology must colour our understanding of God's eternity. The future of the divine rule and God's eternity coincide; they come together in the eschaton. Thus the change of focus does not indicate a material change in Pannenberg's theology. But God's eternity must have priority over God's futurity because God's being encompasses all the modes of time. As Pannenberg says, 'all time is before the eyes of God as a whole'.73 For God everything past, present and future is simultaneously present; this is implied in God's eternity. Only in relation to the temporal process may priority be ascribed to the future. To speak of God as the power of the future is appropriate from within the temporal process. As far as God's being is concerned, God's futurity is not set over against God's eternity. To conclude this discussion, three points may be made. First, Pannenberg's focus on the eternity of God and his dropping of the phrase 'power of the future' does not represent any substantial change in his thought. The key point remains constant in his entire work, viz. the qualification of God's being (God's deity and eternity) by God's eschatological rule. Second, it may be surmised that Pannenberg's earlier suggestion that God's futurity is God's eternity was largely a strategic device intended to deflect the 70
STi, 397-
71STi, 403
7* STi, 33 i. 73 STi, 401. Cf. STi, 91, & ST3, 598. 144
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
charge that he was replacing the traditional doctrine of God's eternity with a new doctrine of God's futurity. To speak of God as the power of the future presupposes the experience of time. It does not stand in conflict with God's eternity. If it stands in competition with anything, it is the view that God is related to the created cosmos only as its beginning.74 Third, great care is needed with the abstract term 'futurity'. While it is well established to speak of God's eternity, one cannot speak of 'futurity' as an attribute of God, and Pannenberg does not really do so.75 To say that God is eternal implies that what in our experience is past, present and future is present to God simultaneously.76 Thus it includes the future of God's rule. We are on safer ground simply to speak of the future, though ultimately we must mean God's future. However, the concept of the future is by no means a straightforward one. The process theologian Lewis Ford - who has explored the possibilities of convergence between process theology and Pannenberg's trinitarian theology - differentiates the future as that which will be from that which might be; the latter does greater justice to the realm of indeterminate possibility which marks the future.77 Pannenberg contrasts the view of the future found in secular futurology and theology; the latter is characterised by 'an emphasis on the novelty of the future'. 78 However, there is a firm line between theological views developed 'on the basis of the exegetical rediscovery of early Christian eschatology' and the Whiteheadian view, in which 'the idea of a future confronting and not just prolonging the present' is uncharacteristic.79 In particular, the idea that the future culminates in something that we designate the end of time is integral to Pannenberg theology, but attracts some strong criticism. The review of Pannenberg's early essays left no doubt about the 74
See STz, 140, 143. Pannenberg speaks mainly of God as 'the power of the future' and of the future or futurity as 'God's mode of being'. 76 STi, 401. Lewis Ford says that for Pannenberg God is 'the compresence of all times'; 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', Encounter 38, 1977, 312.. 77 L. S. Ford, 'Creativity in a Future Key', in Robert C. Neville (ed.), New Essays in Metaphysics, 179. 78 Pannenberg, 'Future and Unity', 60. 79 Pannenberg, 'Future and Unity'. As we shall see, Lewis Ford modifies this Whiteheadian line of thought considerably. 75
J
45
GOD AND THE FUTURE
importance of the idea of the kingdom of God for his theology in general and his doctrine of God in particular. The kingdom of God or the establishment of God's rule is an expectation which Christians have on the basis of the nature of the God revealed by Jesus. Jesus' message revolved around the coming of this kingdom, and Pannenberg aims to work out the implications of this eschatological concept. The kingdom of God is the eschatological future, which will establish the unity of all things. Its coming will finally reveal the reality and identity of God before the whole creation and bring the cosmos to its completion.80 Pannenberg regards this eschatology as central to the Christian faith; it may neither be secularised nor demythologised. Christianity cannot leave the question of eschatology undecided, for belief in reconciliation through Christ and in the presence of God and his kingdom depends on it.81 The two major symbols of God's own ultimate reality and the (individual and social) realisation of human destiny are the kingdom of God and the resurrection of the dead.8* There can be no doubt that Pannenberg thinks of the eschaton as an end. In the final chapter of the Systematic Theology he provides a detailed account of his understanding of this matter. The future of the kingdom of God - for which Christians pray in the words of Matt. 6:ioa - is the essence of Christian hope.83 In 'The Kingdom of God and the End of Time' Pannenberg describes the content of this hope. First, it means the perfection of human society. 'Because God is the Creator of the world, where he reigns his creatures attain to the goal of the destiny that is constitutive of their nature.'84 The framework for this is the renewal of the whole world. Second, the kingdom of God means the end or consummation of history. Pannenberg accepts the basic apocalyptic conviction that the series of world empires will come to an end in the kingdom of God, an idea that has become problematical in the modern world. Pannenberg regards the consummation of the world as implied in the view that reality is an all-encompassing process; that human experience is characterised fundamentally 80 81 82 83
8
These ideas come from Theology and the Kingdom of God. W. Pannenberg, 'Can Christianity do without an Eschatology?', 30. See e.g. W. Pannenberg, 'Future and Unity', esp. yof. ST3, 5*7-
4 5T3, 580.
146
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
by its historicity; and that the idea of a meaning of history presupposes its completeness, and thus its end.85 But the end of the world is expected as God's act. Obviously, it makes a great difference whether God or nothingness is regarded as the end of time.86 Third, the coming of the kingdom of God means the entry of eternity into time. Here the relation between time and eternity is pivotal. But the central conviction is that only through the coming of eternity into time is it possible to attain life in its fulness, and thus its true essence.87 This involves the participation of creatures in God's eternity, which necessitates a radical transformation. In connection with this, Pannenberg also discusses the judgment and the return of Christ. The theme of the coming of God's rule in its fulness is not complete without some final comments on theodicy, for it also means the vindication of God in relation to evil. As the consummation of the creation, it is also the revelation of God's love. Pannenberg's approach to this theme has a double foundation. First, there is the eschatological thrust of Jesus' message of the kingdom of God, influenced by Jewish apocalyptic thought but also at variance with it in some ways. Closely allied with this is the reality of Jesus' resurrection, understood as a fulfilment of Jesus' message about the kingdom of God. It cannot be understood apart from the general framework of apocalyptic expectation. Second, there is the philosophical principle that the meaning of the part is determined by its place in the whole, understood as ca semantic whole'. Within such a whole there are various levels of 'meaning totalities', all 'related to each other as parts and wholes'.88 For Pannenberg the notion of the whole of finite reality, understood as a historical process, requires the idea of its end, just as for Dilthey the meaning of an individual existence can only be determined from its end.89 85
ST3, 591ST3, 594. 87 ST3, 603. The future of consummation is the entry of eternity into time. For it has the content that characterizes eternity but that is lost in the disintegration of time, namely, the totality of life and therefore also its true and definitive identity.' 88 W. Pannenberg, Theology and the Categories "Part" and "Whole" ', M/G, 139. 89 The key passage is in 'On Historical and Theological Hermeneutic', BQTi, esp. 162-4. 86
147
GOD AND THE FUTURE
The idea of an end to history is not viewed equally positively by all theologians and has come under criticism in several ways.90 At the end of chapter four this criticism was mentioned in relation to the concept of anticipation. One criticism is that the idea of the end of the world cannot be understood literally; no particular event will instantiate it. It is rather a horizon against which to understand the course of history. This would make it a regulative idea; its existence cannot be demonstrated, but it is a condition for thinking meaningfully about the present. It could also be regarded as a 'hermeneutical necessity', a horizon that is never actually reached.91 Pannenberg is not unaware of the difficulty of the idea of the end of the world. Scientific cosmology lends some support to it, since it generally favours the idea of a universe which had a beginning and will have an end. But Pannenberg has in mind an eschatological reality, which is different from an event in time and space which physicists may project on the basis of a present understanding of the universe.92 These criticisms have in common the unthinkability or unspecifiability of the end of history or the world. A different kind of criticism comes from process theologians, who find the idea of the end of history in conflict with their understanding of God. On the grounds of an inevitable plurality in being and the view that if God is love God must have a world to love and respond to, Daniel Day Williams regards the idea of an end of the world as untenable. The idea of a 'final event' is a contradiction 'because God's creative action does not end'.93 John B. Cobb extends this criticism and offers two models to illustrate how differently Pannenberg and process theologians see the God-world relation. For Pannenberg God is 'the power of a temporally remote future' who, as its end, gives unity and meaning to the whole cosmic process. For Whitehead God was 'the everlasting companion through whom relevant aspects of eternal 90
S. J. Grenz has summarized the criticisms; Reason for Hope, 204-7. W. Logister, 'Het Eschatologisch Probleem bij Wolfhart Pannenberg: Analyse en Kritiek', Nederlands Theologisch Tijdschrift 24, April 1970, 183-6. 92 ST3, 589^ See also Theological Questions to Scientists', TTN, 18, 2,4-7. 9 3 D. D. Williams, 'Response to Wolfhart Pannenberg', E. H. Cousins (ed.), Hope and the Future of Man, 86f. 91
148
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
possibilities become effective in each moment'.94 For process thinkers the future is indeterminate, and 'since there will be no end to the arising of new occasions, there will be no final definitive meaning of the occasion'. Its ultimate meaning is conferred on it by the fact that God values it.95 In part, this disagreement has its basis in a difference of fundamental intuition. Pannenberg does not accept that God needs an 'other' to love, to act upon and respond to. The creation of the cosmos takes place out of the plenitude of the divine being, the richness of the mutual love of the persons of the Trinity. Once such a world is in existence, God is in relation to it, but it is not ontically necessary to God.96 God's decision to bring a universe into being is an act of freedom and love: The contingency of the world as a whole and of all individual events, things, and beings has its basis in the omnipotent freedom of the divine creating. Precisely by this freedom of origin, that things are or are not becomes an expression of divine love. God had only one reason to create a world ... namely, that God graciously confers existence on creatures, an existence alongside his own divine being and in distinction from him.97
Ultimately, this problem is settled along trinitarian lines, which highlights a major difference between Pannenberg and process theologians. Pannenberg writes out of the classical tradition of Christian orthodoxy, in which the doctrines of the Trinity and the incarnation are accepted as the legitimate theological outcome of biblical faith. Process theologians do not on the whole find anchorage in this tradition, though some may see their theology as compatible with it. Pannenberg is struck by their freedom vis-a-vis the theological tradition. In a dialogue with Lewis Ford, he is troubled that for process theologians the movement between theological tradition and process philosophy is only one-way. This entails a reduction of the intentionality of the Christian faith. He 94
J. B. Cobb, 'Pannenberg and Process Theology', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolf hart Pannenberg, 60. 95 Cobb, 'Pannenberg and Process Theology', 60. 96 The point is that God could in principle exist without a cosmos. This remains true even though, once such a cosmos exists, God's rule over it is ultimately integral to God's deity. 97
5T2, 20.0.0.
149
GOD AND THE FUTURE
looks for a greater concern for 'the Christian identity' of the concepts used within the theological tradition.98 The immediate issue which prompted this criticism was the meaning of the phrase, 'the power of the future', and whether it could be reconceived in terms of 'process' categories. Ford has developed a Whiteheadian sense of Pannenberg's idea of God as the power of the future, in which God as the power of the future is necessarily effective in all things, but nowhere as the sole agent." This makes the apocalyptic hope for an unambiguous display of God's power 'an idle dream, resting upon a misconception as to how God acts'.100 This would make the expectation of a cosmic end similarly untenable. It follows from an axiomatic Whiteheadian point that it is the fundamental postulate of Whitehead's metaphysics that every finite act of synthesizing the past in a fresh act of becoming adds one more item to be synthesized by subsequent acts of becoming, ad infinitum. Time can have no end, and it is highly unlikely that world history should have an end either. If so, God's everlasting synthesis of temporal acts cannot come to some final end.101
For Ford, God can be said to be in the future, but this is not a future which will someday be present. The infinite futurity of God cannot merge with the finite actualities of the present. So God can be seen as the dynamic completion and unification of time, incorporating each temporal moment as it occurs, but only by being forever future.102 Pannenberg expects precisely the meeting of eternity and time, the infinite and the finite. God is the God of the coming kingdom, not the synthesizer of a temporal process in which God is as much 98 W. Pannenberg and L. S. Ford, 'A Dialogue About Process Philosophy', Encounter 38, 1977, 3i8f. 99 See L. S. Ford, 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', Encounter 38, 1977, 307-17; 'God as the Subjectivity of the Future', Encounter 41, 1980, 287-91; 'The Divine Activity of the Future', Process Studies n, Fall 1981, 169-79; 'Creativity in a Future Key', in R. C. Neville (ed.), New Essays in Metaphysics, 179-97; and 'The Nature of the Power of the Future', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 75-94. TOO pord, 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', 315. ioi por(j?
150
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
controlled as controlling. We see here a fundamental difference between two views of the meaning of the Christian Gospel, reinforced by two largely incompatible philosophical traditions, idealism and process thought. As observed by Philip Clayton, deciding between alternative metaphysical systems is not a simple matter.103 Pannenberg argues strongly for the viability of a view of the world which is the correlate of the triune God. This includes providing support for the apocalyptic view of the end of history and the resurrection of the dead. Despite its strangeness, it can provide the key, in Pannenberg's view, for seeing how the whole of reality and its meaning can be conceived.104 His Diltheyan hermeneutics push him hard in this direction. 'Each individual experience presupposes as a condition of its definite nature an end of history that makes of the history of the universe as well as humanity a total process.'105 We have considered God's eternity, which must be understood not as timelessness but as including the whole of time before God simultaneously. God's eternity is not set over against God's being the world's future. In his early work Pannenberg introduced the idea of God as the power of the future, but this located God's being and power in relation to the world of finite experience. It tells us from where God acts on the world, viz. from the eschatological future. Pannenberg sees this as a basic element in the Christian faith and the condition of a coherent and comprehensive Christian world-view. If Jesus' message of the coming kingdom of God is taken seriously, our view of God must include God's power over all finite reality, which can only be awaited from the future. This is the key point for any theology which intends to do justice to eschatology. God's eternity is not compromised by the idea of God as the power of the future. Rather, it denotes an important quality of God's eternity. Before considering the implications of this for God's action in history, we must look at God's relation to time and the question of development in God. 103
P. Clayton, 'Recent Classical/Process Dialogue on God and Change', Process Studies 18, Fall 1989, 2.oif. He compares Whitehead's atomism and Pannenberg's trinitarian theology. I0 « BQTi, 181; also STz, 157-61. IQ 5 ST3, 59 of. I5i
GOD AND THE FUTURE
God and time How is the relation between God and time to be understood? In particular, how is God affected by time? Some important points were noted in chapters three and four, especially on the understanding of reality as history, the inseparability of being and time and the relation of time and eternity. I suggested that Pannenberg provides a middle way between the sacrifice of temporality to the requirement of God's eternity and the sacrifice of God to the requirement of temporality.106 It presupposes the view of time as the creation of God; Christian theology (notably Augustine) held this view over against earlier philosophical opinion that time did not have a beginning.107 Pannenberg has clarified his view of time, both in relation to eternity and in relation to the being of God, in recent work.108 The Christian view of God's relation to time contrasts with that of Platonism, in which the divine could not be related to time. In accordance with the understanding of God as transcendent and immanent, both above creation and present to it, a view of God has to be developed which expresses this truth in relation to the problem of time. In this task Pannenberg develops further some aspects of Earth's view of God's temporality.109 He is guided by the biblical view of 'God's transcendence over changing time' but nevertheless of 'a real relation of God to time'.110 This follows from the fact that God is the creator of time and time is part of God's creation. Pannenberg supports Augustine's teaching that the world was created not in time but with time; time is posited with the existence of created things.111 God willed it as the form of the existence of created things, for these can act independently only in the sequence of time.112 Time is present before God in its three modes, but for God it is an unlimited present. 'God's present 106
See ch. 4, The present as anticipation of the future', above pp. inf. 7 See STz, 146-57. 108 See M/G, ch. 4, 'Being and Time', STi, 401-10, and ST2, ch. 7, parts z (§zc) & 3 (Si)109 Earth spoke of a 'before' and an 'after' in the trinitarian life of God, which has to be seen as part of the essence of God, since God's act is God's being; Church Dogmatics, II/i, 615. Pannenberg refers to this in STi, 405. 110 STi, 405. He credits Th. Haering with this idea. 111 ST2, 38f. 111 STz, 9 5 f.; cf. ST3, 580. 10
152
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
embraces the past as well as the future.' 113 This follows from God's transcendence over time. Since God is the creator of time, it also follows that God has a real relation to time. Here again we encounter an intense form of the paradox of God's transcendence and immanence in relation to creation. Like Earth, Jiingel and Moltmann, Pannenberg thinks that this paradox can only be properly considered in trinitarian terms.114 Some initial things can be said now about God's relation to time. Pannenberg holds that God's relation to the world of space and time is a constitutive part of God's being; 'we cannot set God's relations to the world in antithesis to his essence, as though this were unaffected by the relations.'115 He goes on, 'in God's own immeasurability itself distinctions are posited and permitted that go with the existence of creaturely finitude'.116 Everything finite, whether past, present or future, is present to God simultaneously, yet without setting aside their difference in time.117 This raises the question of time's effect on God. Does God experience change in time? Is there a becoming in God? The key point is that the concept of God's essence must be conceived as relational. This is independent of the intra-trinitarian relations in God, though in harmony with it; the doctrine of the Trinity is not derived from the idea of relationality in God.118 The concept of relation belongs in the idea of God as such. As an infinite, eternal being, God is transcendent, existing beyond the world, 'high above the perishability of created things'.119 However, God is also 'an active presence in the reality of the world'. Even before we know God as such, God is present in all human life. God is there 'as the undefined infinite which is formed "3 5Ti, 4 03114 This will be considered in detail in the final chapter. See W. Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', Dialog 26.4, 1987, 251. 115 ST2, 85. Pannenberg also says that 'the concept of essence is itself ... relationally structured'; 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 253. 116 ST2, 86. "7 STi, 405. 118 Pannenberg seeks to demonstrate that 'relation as a category is ... constitutive for the concept of essence as it is for the understanding of the trinitarian persons'. 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 253. 119 STi, 357. The following quotation comes from the same page. 153
GOD AND THE FUTURE
by the primal intuition of our awareness of reality, as the horizon within which we comprehend all else by limitation'.I2-° We only know this as God, however, when the idea of God - the idea of an infinite, eternal, all-determining being - is introduced to us through religious traditions of one kind or another. Thus God's essence presupposes God's existence in the world of human experience, even when God is not yet named as such. On the other hand, God's existence is known as such only when the question of God's essence is made explicit. Thus the essence of God and the existence of God in our world of experience are reciprocally related.121 This philosophical point is reinforced by an explicitly theological one: the significance of the incarnation and the crucifixion of the Son for the eternal being of God. How is the essential being of God affected by what took place in the life of Jesus on earth, most sharply on the cross? Referring to the ways in which Rahner, Jiingel and Moltmann had grappled with this question, Pannenberg recalls an earlier discussion in which he had answered the question in trinitarian terms: The reciprocity in the relationship of the divine persons makes room for the constitutive significance of the central salvation-historical events for the Godhood of God and thus for the significance of time and change for the divine eternity. And it is not just the sending of the Son and especially the resurrection of the Crucified One which are to be understood as constitutive for the divinity of the Father, but also the work of the Spirit who is the dynamic realization of the kingdom of God in the world, a kingdom without which God could not be God.122
The radical point being made here is that the essence of God's being, the Godhood of God, the deity of the Father, is constituted by what happens in the history of Jesus and by the work of the Spirit. The eternal God is constituted by what happens in time. The transcendent God is also immanent in the created world. 120 121
STi, 356.
The essence, on the one hand, is the actual content and basis of the existent, yet, on the other hand, it remains tied to the existent because it is only what it is as the essence of this existent* Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 253; Pannenberg's italics. 122 Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 2,52,. The reference is to The God of History', originally published in 1977 and later in GSTz, iiz-zS. 154
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
Given the existence of a finite, temporal universe, the eternal God cannot be thought of apart from God's relation to it. Why this extraordinary state of affairs requires a trinitarian articulation will be considered in the final chapter. The Christian claim is that the eternal God is present in the world of time and space. The grammar of speech about this presence is trinitarian in form. God is involved in the world as Father, Son and Holy Spirit. First, God is present in the world as its creator; it owes its existence to God. Second, in a creation headed for death, God's Godhood as creator is maintained by God's presence as reconciler; for this purpose the Son is sent into the world. Third, God is present in the activity of the Spirit, who raised Jesus from the dead and who will bring the whole of humankind to resurrected life; the Spirit is already now the power of the new life of believers. But is God truly present in the world? There is reason enough to doubt it. The world sometimes seems to be anything but the work of a loving creator. The cross could as easily be a sign of the absence of God as of God's loving presence. And the life of believers is so inconsistent, to say the least, that it scarcely constitutes a reason to believe and trust in a present, active God. Given the world as we experience it, God's existence and power cannot be regarded as settled unless and until that deity is established in relation to precisely this world. Everything capable of honouring God as its creator must do so, and everything that casts doubt on God's goodness or power must be resolved. This can only be awaited from the eschatological consummation. If it then becomes clear who and what God is it can be concluded that God was present and involved in the world all along and that God's essence is what it had been supposed to be. But this is to anticipate the outcome; for now the reality, goodness and power of God are radically debatable. God has not made God's presence in the world indisputably obvious. Pannenberg concludes that God, 'through the creation of the world, made himself radically dependent on this creation and on its history'.123 To recapitulate briefly, Pannenberg's main point was that God's 123
Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 2,55. In a letter to Timothy Bradshaw, Pannenberg says, 'I consider the eternal reality of God itself dependent on the outcome of history - although such dependence occurs only on the condition that there is a world. It is possible 155
GOD AND THE FUTURE
essence should not be thought of in isolation from the world. The very essence of God includes God's relatedness to the world that is God's creation. God's relation to the world takes the form of creation, reconciliation and consummation. In each of these God's existence is at issue. Until the eschatological consummation of the world, the coming of the rule of God in its fulness, the existence of God is disputable. The issue is epistemological and ontological. We cannot yet know beyond doubt that the world is God's creation. But God's being, the nature of God's deity, is also at issue. Pannenberg is arguing not only that God is affected by time, but that the eternal essence of God is constituted by what happens in time, by the creation, reconciliation and perfection of the world in time. Paradoxically, time is the creature of God, yet God allows what takes place in time to be constitutive of God's own being. This is the content of Pannenberg's insistence that there is a real relation between the eternal God and time. There is an important sense, then, in which God depends for God's deity on the historical completion of God's activity in the world. God's being is inseparable from God's rule, as Pannenberg insists repeatedly. This view of God's relation to history owes a great deal to Hegel, although Pannenberg has reservations about Hegel's thought. Nevertheless, Hegel provides his basic model for seeing the problem of God's relation to the world of time and history. Hegel too spoke about a history of God, in such a way that God's essence and God's activity could be thought together. But there has always been a fear that in Hegel's view of the relation between God and history the being of God is absorbed in the history of the world process. There is no such danger in Pannenberg's theology. Hegel needs modification in his failure to see the relation in eschatological terms. Confident in his own system of thought, Hegel did not need an eschatological resolution. For Pannenberg the eschatological resolution of all questions about God is central, as is God's dependence on history's consummation for the constitution of God's own eternal being. and even necessary to think of God that he could very well do without a world. But that is mere fancy, since there is a world'. See T. Bradshaw, Trinity and Ontology: A Comparative Study of the Theologies of Karl Earth and Wolfhart Pannenberg, Rutherford Studies in Contemporary Theology, Vol. i (Lewiston: Edwin Mellen Press, 1988), 402..
i56
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
To state the truth about God's relation to history, two requirements have to be met. As Pannenberg expresses it, 'one must be able to think of God as absolute in His relation to the world and not restricted by it, but fulfilled Himself through that relationship'.124 Pannenberg is one of a number of contemporary theologians who have expressed this in trinitarian terms. His way of doing so - as we shall see - is to make the deity of each Person of the Trinity thematic in the historical process. Jiingel and Moltmann had already done so in relation to Jesus Christ, asking what the cross and resurrection imply for the being of God. As Pannenberg puts it, 'the history of the Son has to do with the divinity of the Father Himself. For the divinity of the Father is mediated to Him through the Son who is revealed in the history of Jesus.'115 Something similar must be said about the Holy Spirit. The point is to show that God is fulfilled through God's relationship with the world, indeed constituted by it. We must now ask whether God's dependence on the course of history implies a development or a 'becoming' in God. Pannenberg has had a strong aversion to the idea of change or development in God. Already in the essay 'Theology and the Kingdom of God' he contrasted his own view of God's essence as implying time with the way in which Whitehead and Hartshorne incorporated time into the idea of God. He cannot agree with Whitehead's suggestion that the futurity of God's rule implies a 'development' in God.126 As Lewis Ford says, Pannenberg can accept divine temporality, but only by distinguishing it sharply from 'development'.127 This difference between Pannenberg and process theologians is more than terminological; it is fundamental, involving both ontological and theological principles. The ontological difference reduces to a difference about the priority of being over becoming or the reverse. Whereas in classical metaphysics the fundamental category is that of being, in Whiteheadian metaphysics it is that of becoming. Being depends IZ4
Pannenberg, The God of History', 35. Pannenberg, The God of History', 36. 116 TKG, 62,. 117 Ford, The Nature of the Power of the Future', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 78. 115
157
GOD AND THE FUTURE
on becoming. It is clear that Pannenberg, by emphasizing temporality as part of the divine essence, is not opposed to an element of 'becoming' in God. 'On the level of the economic trinity, there is undoubtedly an element of development and history within the divine reality itself.'128 Whitehead and Hartshorne did incorporate time into the idea of God, but in such a way as to imply development in God. But the ontological principle of 'retroactive permanence' overrules the principle of development or becoming.129 For Pannenberg, like Whitehead, the movement of time contributes to deciding what the definite truth is going to be, also with regard to the essence of God. But - and here is the difference from Whitehead - what turns out to be true in the future will then be evident as having been true all along. This applies to God as well as to every finite reality.130
This principle of retroactive permanence derives, at least in part, from Dilthey. The essence of a being is not decided till the final moment of its existence. But when that time is reached it may then be said that such was its essence all along. Only the whole incomplete till the end - can determine the essence of something or someone. We cannot apply the idea of the 'end' to God, but the eschatological consummation of God's rule over all finite reality is the point at which God's essential being will be both constituted and unambiguously known. What will then turn out to be the case about God will have been God's essence all along. The essence of something requires wholeness, and wholeness requires closure of some kind. In the Whiteheadian universe there is no closure. The process of achieving concreteness, in which God provides ever new possibilities, goes on and on. There is no room here for an eschatological end of the historical process. In Pannenberg's view, there is a point of closure, the eschatological consummation of all things. At this point God's essence is decided, constituted as what iz8 W. Pannenberg, 'A Response to my American Friends', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 313. A similar statement about 'a becoming' taking place in God is found already in /GM, 157. In The God of History' Pannenberg justifies the idea of a 'becoming' in God on the grounds that God is 'altered' by the incarnation, i.e. God is not God in the same way after it as before it; 33. 129 Pannenberg, 'A Response to my American Friends', 32.3. J 3° TKG, 63.
158
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
it is eternally. This is the point at which time and eternity meet; the point of unity of the immanent and economic Trinity. While there is a becoming in God's being at the level of the economic Trinity, this has to be brought into relation with God's eternal being as the immanent Trinity. This implies God's 'eternal enjoyment of the fullness of [God's] life'.131 In Pannenberg's view, this rules out the idea of 'development' in God. For any statement about God must finally take into account the unity of the eternal (essential) Trinity and the economic Trinity. God's being is in becoming, not in developing,132 a distinction which may not be observed in ordinary speech but which must apply to speech about God. The eschatological unity of the economic and immanent Trinity - which is not just arrived at in the eschatological consummation of history but also becomes from that point retroactively the truth about the divine essence all along - expresses, in respect of God, the reconciliation of being and becoming. For Pannenberg it is not possible to think of God as 'an infinity of becoming' or 'perfect becoming'.133 But it is also not acceptable to Pannenberg to think of a universe in which there is a final dualism of being and becoming. 'Can there be a final dualism of being and becoming ...? Or should the philosopher rather conceive of being itself in terms of becoming, or at least as integrating the aspect of becoming?'134 Ontologically, Pannenberg sees 'being' as the fundamental category. In respect of God, even a 'becoming' God is becoming. The theological difference between Pannenberg and process theologians can be stated more briefly. Pannenberg makes clear his dislike of the way Whitehead and some process theologians conceive of the being of God. He complains that the God of process thought is far removed from the God of the Bible and Christian tradition. In the first place, this is evident in the doctrine 131
Pannenberg, 'A Response to My American Friends', 323. Italics added. I3Z Recalling the sub-title of E. Jiingel's famous work on the Trinity, The Doctrine of the Trinity: God's Being is in Becoming (Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press, 1976). The statement assumes a distinction between becoming and developing. 133 Pannenberg, 'A Response to my American Friends', 326. Cf. Ford, The Nature of the Power of the Future', 81. 134 Pannenberg, 'A Response to my American Friends', 326. 159
GOD AND THE FUTURE
of creation. Pannenberg writes, 'From the point of view of theology, it must be said that Whitehead thinks of God only as one factor among others in the system of the universe, not as the creator of the world.'135 There a wide gulf between God as the creator of heaven and earth, in the biblical sense, and the God who creates by providing to every event its ideal possibility for selfrealisation.136 Pannenberg regards the idea of creation in process thought as really self-creation. The God of process thought is too small, too finite: If we conceive of God as finite, we have not conceived of God at all. My question concerning the Whiteheadian doctrine of God ... is whether he has really spoken of God at all. I'm very uncertain about that. I agree ... that Whitehead has not conceived of God as creator in the sense of the Jewish and Christian traditions. He didn't want to, but of course the Whiteheadian theologians do.137
There may indeed be points of similarity, but these do not obscure the fundamental difference which Pannenberg sees between the views of God found in process thought and in classical Christian theology. The place of the doctrine of the Trinity in these respective systems is an indication of deep differences, for it is by means of the doctrine of the Trinity that Pannenberg is able to take temporality seriously in his view of God's being. This commits him to attributing a 'becoming' in God, which he finds acceptable. However, he finds the 'process' idea of 'development' in God, based on a Whiteheadian metaphysics, alien to a Christian understanding of God. In conclusion, the problem of God's relation to time may be expressed in terms of the idea of self-actualisation. In terms of the economic Trinity, it may be said that God is involved in a process of self-actualisation, which operates in relation to the world. On the premise that God's being is God's rule, this self-actualisation is identical with the coming of the kingdom of God, the Z
35 W. Pannenberg, 'God and Nature', TTN, 58. He means by this 'the strict sense of a creatio ex nihilo; see 'Future and Unity', 64. 136 Pannenberg, 'The God of History', 32. Here Pannenberg is describing J. B. Cobb's view of God's creativity. 137 w. Pannenberg, 'A Theological Conversation with Pannenberg', Dialog n, Fall 1972., 292. 160
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
establishment of God's rule in and over all things. In terms of the immanent Trinity, which as eternal is already in the eschatological 'position' in relation to the process of history, as it were, there can be no self-actualisation in God. For God, as causa sui, owes God's being to nothing else, neither past, present nor future; God is already fully actual. In traditional ontological terms, God is actus purus; there is in God no potentiality still to be made actual. But God's 'being' is not a simple 'being there' (Dasein). The divine essence is more than 'simple identity with itself or sheer naked facticity/38 God's being may be understood as a 'becoming', a 'coming to be' (zu sich Werden), in the sense of a becoming fully what one already is. This is a becoming which is self-created and in which one remains what one already essentially was. Such a becoming does not contradict God's aseity inasmuch as God's being is self-created (sich selbst hervorbringend) and does not become something other than what it was before. No new self is created.139 However, the way God does this is through the economy of creation and redemption, through the creation of an 'other' which God reconciles to Godself and brings to its perfection as 'other'. Thus God actualises Godself in relation to, and through, this 'other'.140 Thus, only in a very qualified sense, based on the distinction (but ultimate identity) of the immanent and economic Trinity, could one speak of 'development' in God. Creation from the future We shall now think more specifically about God's action. Here too God's relation to history is basic to the discussion. If the historical 138 I owe these ideas to Joachim Ringleben, 'Gottes Sein, Handeln und Werden', in Jan Rohls and Gunther Wenz (eds.), Vernunft des Glaubens: Wissenschaftliche Theologie und Kirchliche Lehre (Festschrift zum 60. Geburtstag von Wolfhart Pannenberg; Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988), 457-87, esp. 479-84139 Ringleben, 'Gottes Sein, Handeln und Werden', 482.. Ringleben is seeking to express the idea that God is causa sui in terms of 'becoming' (zu sich Werden). 140 Pannenberg once spoke in my hearing about the world in relation to God as 'das Andere seiner Selbst', through which God comes to a full actualisation of God's being. What prevents Pannenberg from making the 'other' necessary to God is his emphasis on the freedom of God as the immanent Trinity.
161
GOD AND THE FUTURE
process affects God's being, it is no less the sphere in which God acts. The purpose of this section is to see how Pannenberg understands God's action in history. A basic presupposition is that for those who accept God's reality history must be in some significant sense God's; it is the history of God's self-actualisation in relation to the 'other' that is the cosmos. He is critical of the modern abandonment of the Augustinian view that the real agent in history is God. 'History is not made up ... solely of human actions':141 it is essential to think also in terms of divine agency or the guidance of divine providence. How is this to be understood? First, it is not to be understood as 'a determination of events prior to the actual course of history'.142 Second, it does not preclude participation of human action in the process of history. These points have to be substantiated, in view of persistent criticisms that Pannenberg is a determinist in his understanding of God as 'the all-determining reality'. We shall have to look carefully at Pannenberg's view of God's action and creation of the world, in particular his claim that God acts and creates from the future. The idea of God's action is, of course, intrinsically difficult. Divine agency is both like and unlike human agency, and we cannot avoid thinking of God's actions on the analogy of human action. But we have then to ask, as Thomas Tracy puts it, 'whether the theistic modifications of the way we think about persons as agents leave us with a coherent concept of the divine agent'.143 All agency involves intentionality, but there are features of human agency - blindness to real intentions, ignorance of the consequences of actions and the need to reconsider intentions - which cannot apply to God. Human agency involves a separation of the goal and the execution of an action, and this too cannot apply to God.144 The limited freedom of human agents in relation to their intentions cannot be a model for God's freedom as agent, for God's capacity to achieve what God intends, as well as the range of things God can intend, is 1 '4 ATP, 504. J 2 4 ATP, 515.
14 3 Thomas F. Tracy, God, Action, and Embodiment (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1984), 109. 144 Purposive action can be 'attributed to God only metaphorically, because in the instance of eternity there is no separation between goal and execution'; Pannenberg, 'Providence, God, and Eschatology', 178.
162,
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
unlimited.145 What can then be said about God's action in the world? Already in his early writings, Pannenberg foreshadows ideas about God's creation which become central in later thinking. The idea that creation is from the future is first seen very early, in several different contexts. If eschatology is the key in which all theology is written, there are clear implications for the doctrine of creation: ... in Jesus' proclamation the true nature of creation is revealed for the first time in the light of the approaching end. This has fundamental significance also for the understanding of creation itself. Creation is not to be understood as an act that happened one time, ages ago, the results of which involve us in the present. Rather, the creation of all things, even including things that belong to the past, takes place out of the ultimate future, from the eschaton, insofar as only from the perspective of the end are all things what they truly are.146
Here Pannenberg turns the doctrine of creation back-to-front; the end is more significant than the beginning. Even earlier, he contrasts the Greek understanding of the divine as the ground of the present world with the biblical view that 'the creation is still underway to its proper reality' and that the definitive future selfrevelation of God will also be the moment that 'decides' the essence of all things. 'The creation occurs from the side of the end.'147 The insistence that the whole notion of creation should undergo an 'eschatological reversal', occurs again in 'The God of Hope'. The new idea of creation will be 'oriented not toward a primeval event in the past but toward the eschatological future'. In this essay there is the first hint of how God creates from the future. As the power of the ultimate future, God 'pushes' the historical future away from Godself and lets it become the present.148 Once the vision of an eschatological doctrine of creation is firmly crystallised, Pannenberg begins to articulate such an understanding 145
This has to be qualified. Tracy says, 'God faces no limitation upon his activity that is not either logically or circumstantially necessary'; God, Action, and Embodiment, 142,. 146 /GM, 2,30. Pannenberg's italics (published in 1964). 147 W. Pannenberg, 'Analogy and Doxology', BQTi, 2.37 (first published in 1963). 148 BQTz, 135-49; see esp. 243^ (published in 1965). 163
GOD AND THE FUTURE
more explicitly in relation to scientific thought. The fact that scientific views of the world and a theological doctrine of creation will differ significantly is suggested early. In scientific understanding an event will usually be seen as 'a consequence of past events or of invariable laws'. A theological view will be different: The idea of the love of God as the origin of all reality does not violate scientific descriptions of natural processes. Each event will be understood primarily as something in itself, as a work of creative love and not simply as a consequence of past events or of invariable laws. The laws of causation have their own overwhelming significance, but do not plumb the depths of reality's foundation.149
Clearly, the idea of the 'laws' of the universe is a highly useful and important principle of explanation, but they are not allexplanatory; much remains unexplained by them. Already in this early essay Pannenberg is fascinated by Whitehead's idea that the new is not merely the outcome of what already exists but enters into relation with what already is. 'Thus the continuity of nature is no longer understood as the irresistible dynamic of the already existing pushing forward, but as the building of bridges to the past that save the past from getting lost.'150 Pannenberg later writes in greater detail about nature and scientific subjects.151 What emerges here is the conviction that nature, like history, should not be understood only in a modern, secular way. Too much is ignored in such a view. Elsewhere he writes that the theologian cannot in good conscience simply accept as exhaustive the description of nature given us by the natural scientist. There is more to nature than simply what the scientist ... has been able to report. The reality of God is a factor in defining what nature is, and to ignore this fact leaves us with something less than a fully adequate explanation of things.151 *49 TKG, 67. J 5° TKG, 67. 151 Three early essays, published with others in TTN, are 'Contingency and Natural Law' (1970), 'Spirit and Energy' (1971), and The Doctrine of the Spirit and the Task of a Theology of Nature' (1972,). 152 W. Pannenberg, The Doctrine of Creation and Modern Science' (1987), TTN, 48. His view of the sciences and the relation between them and theology has been well stated by Philip Hefner, The Role of Science in Pannenberg's Theological Thinking', in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, ch. n, 266-86. 164
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
This is illustrated in Pannenberg's connection of the theological concept of 'spirit' and the scientific notion of 'field'. Influenced by the Eastern Orthodox theology of the Spirit, Pannenberg emphasises the work of the Spirit in creation, not just redemption, as is more typical of Latin theology.153 The identification of spirit with mind - the intellectualisation of the Spirit - was a further obstacle to overcome. To create room for the concept of Spirit in discussing nature, Pannenberg had to overcome the gulf that divides biblical thought (with its view of an origin of life that transcends the living being) and the modern understanding of life (which sees life as a function of the living cell that reproduces itself). There is room here for rapprochement: On the one hand, the biblical perspective is quite open for the idea of independent existence which constitutes the very essence of the concept of a living being: it has life in itself. On the other hand, modern biology does not exclude everything that transcends the living cell from the analysis of life. Although life is taken as the activity of the living cell or of a higher organism, that activity itself is conditioned. It is conditioned particularly by the requirement of an appropriate environment. When kept in isolation, no organism is fit for life.154
In Pannenberg's view, the idea of the ecological self-transcendence of life and the biblical idea of a spiritual origin of life correspond to each other. Organisms depend on a field of energy; this selftranscendence is both 'an activity of the organism and ... an effect of a power that continuously raises the organism beyond its limitations and thereby grants it its life.'155 Thus self-creation depends on this process of self-transcendence. The term 'spirit' denotes the power on which life depends and the broader context for the self-transcending dynamic of organic life.156 The idea of the self-transcendence of life implies their orientation to the future; this is an important element in Pannenberg's doctrine of creation. Aware of it or not, every organism is related 153
W. Pannenberg, The Doctrine of the Spirit and the Task of a Theology of Nature', TTN, 127. Pannenberg appreciates the efforts of Tillich and Teilhard de Chardin in this area; cf. 118-37. See also 'Spirit and Energy', TTN, 138-47. 154 TTN, 133. 155 TTN, 135. *56 TTN, 135. 165
GOD AND THE FUTURE
to its own future and that of its species. This is both an act of selfcreation and the result of a power or field of energy without which there could be no self-creation. This field of energy is itself creative; creative of the lives of individuals which are also selfcreative.157 There is a human mode of this self-transcendence, far beyond the physical and including the spiritual. This expresses itself in the capacity to think in abstract terms, the capacity for trust, love and hope, the quest for personal identity, social life and social institutions, and the creation of a world of meaning through language and culture. All these are examples of both self-creation and receptivity to a power that draws us beyond ourselves. In artists and poets we see exceptional examples of spiritual freedom and creativity, but they illustrate what is true of humankind in general.158 We do not experience this self-transcendence in an unbroken way; our orientation to the future comes up against its limit in death, which threatens the sense of the meaning of life. In the Christian account of the spiritual power that enables creativity despite this ambiguity there is a promise of union with this power beyond death, of 'being united to the future of God', which is both the goal and the source of our existence.159 The other idea of great importance first developed in detail at this time is that of contingency.160 In the last chapter we saw the importance of this notion in connection with Pannenberg's argument for the priority of the future. If that which arises is in some sense new and contingent (not necessary), it cannot be accounted for in terms of antecedent causes alone. It must be seen, he contends, as arising from an open future. The connection between the present and the past can be seen only in retrospect. Take the example of the emergence of the human being. In the usual explanation the appearance of the human being is purely the outcome of antecedent causes. As Pannenberg sees it, the present, released from the future, creates the past by letting it appear in a different light from what it would have appeared in if the human being had not come on the scene. This type of 157 7TN, i34*58 SeeTTN, i 3 6f. 159 TTN, 137. 160 Hefner describes Pannenberg's work as 'a theology of contingency and field'; The Role of Science in Pannenberg's Theological Thinking', 266. 166
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
explanation does not exclude the other, for the new that arises depends also on the old forms that already exist. It complements scientific explanation and suggests another form of connection between the present and the past: Only with the origin of the human being and with the appropriation of nature by human consciousness does the world process as a whole, retroactively on the basis of the human being, attain its connection in itself. That takes place through human knowledge of nature just as through any alleged domination over it. Only in this sense is it possible to speak of a history of nature. This is not a history of nature by itself apart from the human being; rather, it is a history of nature directed to the human being.161
However, it is not the human being who constitutes the history of nature as a unity. Historical connection is provided by God, who brings new events into connection with earlier ones and lets the new throw their light on the old. In ancient Israel there developed the idea of a divine reality which gives unity to the historical process. On this basis it is possible to say that God has 'ordained the contingent sequence of forms toward the human being so that this sequence can be conceived as a meaningful connection of occurrences backward, a sequence that is shaped and perfected by human recognising and acting'.162 The emphasis on contingency can be explained by a twofold concern that is evident in Pannenberg's writings on scientific matters, beginning around 1970. First, there is a concern to overcome the hiatus between thinking about nature and thinking about God, which has become standard in the modern world. The principle of inertia was taken to imply the independence of the natural order from God.163 However, Pannenberg considers the principle of inertia to be at least less self-evident than it is usually taken to be, partly because the 'solid' bodies of the universe are actually thinkable as events and their regularities, and these 161
i6z
W. Pannenberg, 'Contingency and Natural Law', TTN, inf. TTN? I I 2
163 See TTN, 109. Cf. also 'Theological Questions to Scientists', TTN, 19-21. and The Doctrine of Creation and Modern Science', TTN, esp. 3of. The principle of inertia removed the philosophical demand for the constant cooperation of a first preserving cause for the preservation of the conditions of bodies and especially also of their movement'; TTN, 109.
i67
GOD AND THE FUTURE
themselves have a contingent character. If physical phenomena depend on a combination of contingent conditions, there are grounds for thinking that inertia itself may 'imply the framework of a field of force to provide the conditions for such a phenomenon to exist'.164 Scientific explanation is much less closed than it was formerly thought to be, and therefore the possibility of a harmonisation of theological speech about God and scientific description of nature is again quite strong. In Pannenberg's view, the contingency of events could well be 'a point of departure on the basis of which talking about a personality of divine action could become again a meaningful element in the frame of a presently relevant understanding of reality'.165 A second concern underlying Pannenberg's focus on contingency is the challenge to the determinism of scientific explanation. The concept of contingency challenges an uncritical use of the principle of regularity in scientific explanation. The old form of determinism has gone; modern physics is more modest in its view of physical and scientific law. Only statements of probability can be made concerning micro-events, not because of limits to our knowledge but because of the nature of the universe. In every scientific problem the relation of contingency and regularity is again an open question. Pannenberg regards the total process of natural events as 'a mesh of contingency and regularities'.166 Pannenberg's developed theology of creation is found in Volume 2, of the Systematic Theology, supplemented by parts of the final chapter of Volume 3. Many of his early ideas are found in the completed material on creation. It is beyond the scope of this chapter to present an outline of this material; the focus is on the idea of creation from the future. However, two general points should be made. First, Pannenberg defends the use of current scientific knowledge of the cosmos in a theological doctrine of creation. Theologians are free, as the biblical writers were, to use contemporary knowledge;167 they are not required to preserve ideas which have been superseded in science. More positively, cosmological thought gives some support to a model of the cosmos 1*4 TTN, 2.1. 165 TTN, 115, note 10. 166
l6
TTN^
78>
? 5T2, 117. 168
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
which converges with the idea of 'the future of God as the creative origin of the universe'.168 Second, Pannenberg has produced a theology of creation without parallel at the present time. It is important to note the trinitarian grounding of this doctrine, because the idea of creation from the future is developed in connection with the work of the Spirit. The idea of creation from the future is more implicit than explicit in his doctrine of creation, but it is integral to it by virtue of the strongly pneumatological shape of this doctrine. Thus the idea of creation from the future is articulated in a pioneering way by its connection with both the doctrine of the Trinity and contemporary scientific thought. For Pannenberg, creation is the free, loving act of the triune God. The Father, the Son and the Spirit act together but distinctively in creation. 'With the creation of a world all the persons, acting together, move out of what they have together, namely, the divine essence.'169 The work of creation is constituted a unity by the fact that it has both a beginning and an end; it embraces the themes of creation, reconciliation, redemption and consummation. Each of the persons of the Trinity plays a key part in the act of creation, beginning with the Father. 'God is Father as the origin of creatures in their contingency by granting them existence, caring for them, and making possible their continued life and independence.'170 This is an expression of the goodness of God, based in the love of the Father for the Son. The Father's turning to a world of creatures is mediated through the Son and they in turn are objects of the Father's love as they are drawn into his eternal love for the Son. The Father creates through the Son; the Son, as 'the origin of all that differs from the Father', is 'the origin of the existence of creaturely reality'.171 Just as the Spirit unites the Father and the Son even in their distinction from each other, so the Spirit enables creatures in their independent existence to transcend their finitude and to participate in the divine life.172According to the witness of Scripture, all creatures owe life and movement to the Spirit. Thus the Son establishes the creaturely 168 16
STz, 161.
9 5T2,
5.
170
STz, 2,1.
171
ST2, 2-9, 2,2,.
^ 5T2, 33 .
169
GOD AND THE FUTURE
forms in their distinctiveness and distinction from God, while the Spirit is the creative force by which the new comes into being. These two aspects of the divine act of creation belong together: The idea of a vital creative dynamic is not sufficient to make intelligible to us the uniqueness of creaturely existence ... in its distinction from all else and its relation to it. For this we need a principle of distinction such as we find in the self-distinction of the Son from the Father, i.e. of the divine Logos. Whereas the creative dynamic in the events of creation relates to the Spirit, the Logos is the origin of the distinguishing form of the creature in the totality of its existence and in the ensemble of distinctions and relations of creatures in the order of nature.173
Pannenberg's account of the Spirit's action in creation is closely related to new cosmological insights. Whereas classical physics related force or energy to bodies in space, modern physics sees bodies in terms of force or energy. Faraday regarded bodies as forms of forces that are independent realities, 'fields that occupy space'.174 Pannenberg traces the idea of a field of force to preSocratic philosophy or the Stoic idea of pneuma. The latter idea influenced the early patristic writers in their view of the Spirit in creation. He regards this relation between the doctrine of pneuma and modern field theory as closer than that between Christian thought and the Aristotelian theory of motion: The renewing of the thought of the primacy of force in Leibniz (with Newton as a precursor) and the development of field theories in physics have made it possible again to relate the function of the divine Spirit in the creation of the world to the way in which physics describes nature. We may refer especially to the concept of all material, bodily phenomena as manifestations of force fields and finally of the one cosmic force field that Faraday had in view.175
This is a modest claim; there is no blurring of the boundaries between theology and physics. But the underlying metaphysical assumptions are similar and their roots in ancient thought are identical. He does not claim that the Spirit is 'the field'; that would be another version of the God of the gaps. Field theories are only I7
I7
3 5T2, 1
« STz, So. 175 ST2, 82,.
170
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
'approximations' of the divine reality we call 'Spirit'. The Holy Spirit is 'a unique manifestation (singularity) of the field of the divine essentiality'.176 The Spirit may be thought of as 'a dynamic field that is structured in trinitarian fashion'. The Spirit is one of the personal concretions of the essence of God as Spirit. The Spirit is the Person in the Trinity who relates what is distinct, both within the being of God and between God and created things. Without denying the personhood of the Spirit, the Spirit's work in creation has something of the character of dynamic field operations. In the previous chapter we looked at Pannenberg's view of the primacy of the future as part of his ontology. We must now link this view of the future with his doctrine of the Spirit. He does this under the heading of 'The Spirit of God and the Dynamic of Natural Occurrence'.177 The broad point is that space and time are aspects of the Spirit's working. God gives the creatures space and time; space over against God's own being and time because succession in time is a condition of their independence in relation to God and each other.178 Creatures who are in time are oriented to the future and relate to it ambivalently; it is full of threat (the threat of the end of their existence) and full of promise (the promise of the fulfilment of their existence). The future is the field of the possible and the source of the new, and precisely as such is the sphere par excellence of the Spirit's operations.179 Theologically, the Spirit is the eschatological reality, the power of creation's consummation; thus not only the origin of all life but especially the origin of the new eschatological life. The Spirit's lifegiving work at creation is preparatory to the Spirit's bringing forth of the new life of the eschaton. But then 'we have to regard the dynamic of the Spirit in creation from the very outset in terms of the coming consummation, i.e., as an expression of the power of his future'.180 In other words, the Spirit acts on created reality from the future, as the power of the future that introduces the new into the world of existing things. As suggested in the previous 176
STz, pages. J 77 STz, 178 ST2, I7 ? STz, 180 ST2,
83f. (cf. STi, 372-4); the following quotations are from the same ch. 7, Part II, §2, 76-115. 86, 95. 98. 98. 171
GOD AND THE FUTURE
chapter, Pannenberg gives priority to the possible over that which is actual; the realm of the possible is 'the force field' of future possibility. From this the new comes into being. Pannenberg sees this operating especially at the level of microevents, but something similar may happen at the level of macro-events. If so, we may speak of 'a creative dynamic of the field in relation to the phenomena that take place in it'. Within such a framework Pannenberg sees the increase in complexity of natural structures in the history of evolution. As a whole, the process of nature tends toward the dissolution of creatures through entropy. Yet 'within the force field of future possibility' nature also 'offers space for the rise of new structures of increasing differentiation and complexity'.181 This is what actually took place in the evolution of life. Pannenberg believes not only that there is empirical support for his understanding of the Spirit as working in all events as the power of the future, but also that scientific description by itself is incomplete and needs revision. Here he sees a convergence between scientific and theological discourse, without confusing the two. Pannenberg argues that a view of creation from the future safeguards the contingent character of the universe better than a more conventional view of creation from the past. Indeed, a proper recognition of contingency in history and nature requires the primacy of the future or, in theistic terms, God's creation from the future. However, this is not its only advantage. The Spirit is not only the source of the new; it is also the Spirit of unity, who integrates, reconciles and unites, and who brings the cosmos to its consummation in the eternity of God: The emergence of contingent individual events from the possibility field of the future constitutes ... only the elementary aspect in the creative dynamic of the Spirit, the beginning of its development. It culminates in the integration of events and moments into a unity of form. Within worldly time it appears as a time-bridging present in the duration of forms. In this duration of creaturely forms ... we have a kind of inkling of eternity. The goal of the Spirit's dynamic is to give creaturely forms duration by a share in eternity and to protect them against the tendency to disintegrate that follows from their independence.l8z 181
STz, loof.
I8i
ST2, 102.
172
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
In Christian theology the Spirit is understood as an eschatological power or force, who brings the power of the new, a redeemed and reconciled existence, into the present, though this is experienced only in a fragmentary way. Christians understand their present existence precisely in this way, whether they call it 'life in the Spirit' or 'life in Christ'. Already now, as an anticipation of what awaits them in the eschatological future, they experience - though incompletely - unity with God, with other people, and the rest of creation. This is the life of the future already present, ahead of its time, as it were; life that is the gift of the Spirit. Pannenberg presents his proposal that God should be understood as acting creatively from the future rather than the past in an impressive way, especially in his Systematic Theology. It is a proposal with such far-reaching implications for the way we view the cosmos that it may one day be judged to be the beginning of a major paradigm shift. In terms of Lakatos's idea of a 'research programme', with its 'hard core' of assertions that provide 'dramatic, stunning, and unexpected' interpretations of the world as well as auxiliary hypotheses which need various kinds of validation, P. Hefner describes Pannenberg's work as precisely such a programme.183 Hefner lists a number of 'auxiliary hypotheses' which summarize major aspects of Pannenberg's thought. The 'hard core' of assertions that would create a paradigm shift are the following: (i) God is the all-determining reality which constitutes the field from which everything that exists derives its being and in which all the contingencies of nature and history have their origin. (2) The medium in which God's alldetermining work has been cast is that of an eschatological historical continuum; its meaning is in the yet incomplete totality of reality. (3) The fulfilment of the eschatological continuum is part of the all-determining work of God.184 The idea of creation from the future might well constitute another auxiliary hypothesis. None of these auxiliary hypotheses are capable of instantaneous adjudication. The idea of creation from the future is counterintuitive, despite Pannenberg's argument; the traditional 183
Hefner, The Role of Science in Pannenberg's Theological Thinking', esp. 281-4. 184 Hefner, The Role of Science in Pannenberg's Theological Thinking', 282.
*73
GOD AND THE FUTURE
understanding of causation from past to future is strongly entrenched. Pannenberg's challenge is to do greater justice to the complexity of the concept of causality: From the standpoint of creatures the continued event of creation proceeding from the power of the future of God suffers a temporal inversion whereby it seems to be a process moving from the past to the future. From this angle, it is marked by tension between increasing entropy on the one side and ever higher structuring on the other. In its independence all creaturely reality is subject to the fate of destructuring, of dissolution according to the law of entropy. Because of the openness of process structures to future events, however, new structures are constantly formed, since processes take place in open rather than closed systems.185
The tension remains. Entropy and the rise of new structures (whether the formation of matter or the higher structuring of life forms, for example) both have to be taken into account. The development of structures of increasing complexity was not inevitable; it was an open possibility. 'Thermodynamics has to do only with possibilities and probabilities.'186 At the heart of the problem of assessing Pannenberg's 'programme' is the question whether a world-view characterized by contingency, chance and indeterminacy is more consistent with an account of causality as moving from the future or from the past. The inexhaustible wealth of God's creative power in bringing about the multiplicity of forms of life can be maintained on either view, but can each view do equal justice to the irreducible element of contingency and creaturely freedom? Pannenberg believes that this element of indeterminacy coheres better with his view of creation from the future. He has some support for his view of creation from process thinkers. In particular, Lewis Ford has endeavoured to show the viability of the idea of God as creating from the future. Ford argues that if future causation makes no sense 'purely past causation is likewise impossible'. 'Causation is ... shared by the events ordinarily labelled as cause and effect, rather than being exercised solely by prior events.'187 Indeed, 'if we accept the ideal of complete causal explanation, as seems reasonable, the traditional 185 186
187
STz, 112; see also icz. ST2, 114. Ford, 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', 313. 174
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
understanding of causation inevitably entails causal determinism'.188 This is in line with Pannenberg's argument. Causation is a complex phenomenon, involving past fact, present activity and future possibility. The future is not an efficient cause, since it is not actual. But, following Whitehead, Ford sees God as 'the ultimate power of the future, rescuing the world from degeneration into chaos by the relentless provision of ever-new creative possibilities for the world to actualise.'189 God is not the only causal agent, but as the power of the future God is effective in all things. There is even a sense in which God is 'the ultimate determiner of all things'.190 This is not to suggest a greater convergence between process thought and Pannenberg's theology than actually exists. But Ford's argument adds weight to the idea of causation (and creation) from the future, as part of a more complex view of causation. An all-determining or determinist God? We return to the question whether Pannenberg's view of creation from the future makes him vulnerable to the charge of determinism. It should be clear now that his most important concepts are compatible only with a completely non-determinist view of the cosmos. In particular, his emphasis on contingency, freedom and indeterminacy makes clear his challenge to the deterministic prejudice of Newtonian physics. Moreover, his uneasiness about the deterministic implications of the classical Christian concept of God make the suggestion that he is a determinist more perplexing. In an early essay he insisted that the doctrine of God must include both the idea of God as 'the reality which determines everything' and 'the reality of freedom, of human subjectivity'.191 What God 188 porci? 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', 313. Ford, 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', 314. See also the qualification in note 13 on the same page. For Ford the future does not actually exist, i.e. objectively. But it does have its subjective dimension; it exists for itself, and as such is the source of the possibilities that lure the world to greater complexity. God is 'the subjectivity of the future'; see Ford, 'God as the Subjectivity of the Future', esp. z89f. Elsewhere Ford defines God as the 'future activity creating the conditions of the present'. God's future activity influences the present by presenting it with 'real' possibilities; see 'The Divine Activity of the Future', esp. 172, 175. See also 'Creativity in a Future Key', i86f. 190 Ford, 'The Nature of the Power of the Future', 86. 191 W. Pannenberg, 'Speaking about God in the Face of Atheist Criticism', BQT3, 109. 189
175
GOD AND THE FUTURE
'determines' must include the contingency and freedom of created reality. This 'determination' must then include a realm of possibilities,, only some of which are realised. Creation is an open system, open to the new, including a higher consummation.192 There can be no suggestion of any determinism here, that is in the hard sense of the term. Pannenberg concedes the partial determination of events (and the consequent limitation of the field of possibilities) by the past and present. This is compatible with the theological idea of creaturely independence in relation to the creative work of the Spirit. But it is not to be confused with the almost complete determinism of classical physics.193 On the face of it, the idea that Pannenberg is a determinist is most improbable. However, the suggestion to this effect has persisted. D. McKenzie, has strongly criticised Pannenberg's understanding of freedom and God as the power of the future.194 Pointing out the ambiguity of the word 'determine' (and the German bestimmen), McKenzie found neither an adequate explanation of 'the future principle' nor an acceptable notion of human freedom in Pannenberg's work. He concluded that Pannenberg was too committed to preserving the idea of God's omnipotence, in a more or less traditional sense,195 and infers that the idea of God as 'the Reality that determines everything' needs to be abandoned in favour of a 'process' view of God. In another early criticism, L. Gilkey suggests that Pannenberg's view of causation from the future is equally problematical to a traditional view of divine causality. He sees Pannenberg as adopting 'a kind of Calvinism set into temporal reverse gear',196 but does not think that a shift in the temporal locus of God's being and work would change much. On the basis of Pannenberg's later work these criticisms could not be sustained. D. Polk considers that the idea of God as the all-determining power of the future can be understood non-deterministically, though only at the cost of losing the notion 191
SeeSTi, 971. 3 STz, 108. 194 D. McKenzie, 'Pannenberg on God and Freedom', The Journal of Religion 60.3, July 1980, 307-19. r 95 D. McKenzie, 'Pannenberg on God and Freedom', 32.8-9. 196 L. B. Gilkey, 'Pannenberg's Basic Questions in Theology: A Review Article', Perspective 14, Spring 1973, 53f. 19
i76
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
of divine immutability.197 Polk is not confident that Pannenberg has a solution to the problem, but Pannenberg's discussion of the economic Trinity suggests otherwise. J. Cobb refers to 'a determinism based on the causal efficacy of the future', as if it is a simple alternative to 'a determinism based on the causal efficacy of the past'.198 L. Ford considers the connection between God and human freedom to be at least ambiguous in Pannenberg's theology, and suggests that it could be construed as a kind of 'futuristic deism'.199 There is no lack of criticism! But do these accusations of determinism stick? Pannenberg is adamant that they do not. In his view it makes an enormous difference whether past events determine some future outcome or whether the future is determinative of the present. For him there can only be a deterministic system if past events determine the future. If the future has power in some way to 'determine' the present, a very different sense of 'determine' must be implied. It is simply a mistake on the part of the critics to apply the idea of determinism to his very different conception of the power of the future on the assumption that it is of the same structure.200 The key question for Pannenberg is whether a particular theoretical scheme leaves significant room for human freedom and contingency. He regards his own view of the future as 'determining' the present quite safe in this respect.201 The reality of human freedom is guaranteed by the divine 'determination'; where there is truly a freedom to decide between possibilities there can be no possibility of a deterministic system. Correspondingly, the openness of the historical process is not compromised by the promised coming of the kingdom of God, nor even by its 'proleptic inauguration' in the person of Jesus.202 What is the effect on the openness of the historical process of the fact that there will be an eschatological closure, that the coming of 197
D. Polk, The All-determining God and the Peril of Determinism', in Braaten and Clayton, The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 153. 198 J. B. Cobb, 'Pannenberg and Process Theology', in Braaten and Clayton, The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 68. Pannenberg strongly repudiates such a simple equation; 'Response', 322,. 199 Ford, 'The Nature of the Power of the Future', 85. 200 Pannenberg, 'A Response to My American Friends', 322.. 201 See Pannenberg, 'A Response to My American Friends', 322 and 'Speaking About God in the Face of Atheist Criticism', BQTj, esp. 107-13. 202 Pannenberg, 'A Response to My American Friends', 322. 177
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the eschaton is already set? In terms suggested by P. Clayton, if 'the eschatological rule of God has already been decided in Jesus' resurrection',203 does this not suggest a closed and 'determined' course of history? Pannenberg concedes that 'the gist of the final outcome has been decided ... in Jesus' resurrection', but strictly on the condition that we 'presuppose the advent of that future, which is still open in our actual experience.'204 Only the coming of God's rule in its fulness will make the resurrection of Jesus what it claims to be, namely, the anticipation of this advent. If the presupposition should turn out to be justified - if the consummation of creation under the rule of God is what the future will indeed bring - does this make the charge of determinism more difficult for Pannenberg to refute? Can the future still be truly open? Clayton thinks that in this case the 'openness' of the future in our experience can only be epistemological, for the matter has essentially ('the gist' of it) been decided. Pannenberg disagrees with this and claims the significance of the work of the Spirit in the period between Jesus' resurrection and the coming of God's rule in its fulness. This is undoubtedly important in many respects, but it does not clearly touch the issue of determinism. Pannenberg can be cleared of the charge of determinism on a different ground. If God is truly God - if God's being is God's rule - God's reign in the created universe must eventually be complete. But this coming of the kingdom of God is something other than the natural outcome of a historical process. It is compatible with any course of events, precisely because it will come from the future as something new. God is able to connect the fulness of the divine rule with any historical course of events; it will come 'in the fulness of time' as God determines it, just as in the fulness of time God sent the Son into the world (Gal. 4:4). This eschatological outcome does not imply that events in history are determined - not even from the future. As L. Ford says - speaking of Whitehead's God, but the point is general - God is 'the ultimate determiner of all things, not as determining each act individually, but as determining its role and significance in the unity of the final whole'.20* 103
P. Clayton, 'Anticipation and Theological Method', Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, 131. 104 Pannenberg, 'A Response to My American Friends', 320. z °5 Ford, The Nature of the Power of the Future', 86. 178
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
The heart of the matter is whether the postulates of human freedom and the openness of history are compatible with the reality of God, understood as the power of the future. Pannenberg has addressed this problem in his description of God's relation (as the Spirit) to the dynamics of natural occurrence. As we saw, his argument is that the Spirit is the power of the future, working creatively in all events at both micro and macro level as a field of force, and that the contingency of present events is not compromised by their coming into existence from a 'possibility field of future events'.206 In the final chapter of his Systematic Theology, on the consummation of creation in the kingdom of God, Pannenberg reiterates his understanding of God's future as the creative origin of all things and all events in the contingency of their existence.207 Two further points support the contention that Pannenberg is no determinist, despite the language which may suggest it. First, it has to be stressed that the future does not yet exist and cannot therefore be thought of as an 'efficient' cause.208 If the future is powerful over the present, this does not mean that it acts on the present in the same way as the past acts on it. It is 'the field of the possible'; it is only part of the complex phenomenon of causation. This should suffice to answer the criticism that Pannenberg is a determinist. Second, in Pannenberg's view God does not 'rule' the cosmos by naked power, but by love. The unambiguous manifestation of God's power belongs to the eschaton, but 'God is already ruling the world from the hiddenness of heaven.'209 God's power, exercised from the future, already has an effect on the present, but it is to be understood as love.210 He has elaborated this idea in his Systematic Theology. The chapter on the divine attributes ends 206
STz, loo-z. The German edition was published after the last suggestions of determinism of which I am aware, viz. in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg. 20 ? ST3, 531. 208 This point is made by Ford, 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', 313. 209 W. Pannenberg, 'Future and Unity', in E. H. Cousins (ed.), Hope and the Future of Man, 72. 210 W. Pannenberg confirms this in a comment on D. Folk's article in Braaten and Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg, referring to his 'own understanding of the Christian interpretation of God's "alldetermining power" in terms of love'; see Pannenberg's 'Response', 323. 179
GOD AND THE FUTURE
with a discussion on the love of God.211 This is preceded by his presentation of the doctrine of God's omnipotence, which, 'can be thought of only as the power of divine love and not as the assertion of a particular authority against all opposition.'212 The supreme expression of God's omnipotence is the incarnation of the Son. The love of God is to be understood in a trinitarian way; 'as infinite love it is divine love only in the trinitarian riches of its living fulfilment'.213 In this form it has a direct bearing on the question of determinism: Only the doctrine of the Trinity permits us so to unite God's transcendence as Father and his immanence in and with his creatures through Son and Spirit that the permanent distinction between God and creature is upheld. The same holds good for an understanding of God's omnipotence. The power of God over his creation as the transcendent Father finds completion only through the work of the Son and Spirit because only thus is it freed from the one-sided antithesis of the one who determines and that which is determined, and God's identity in his will for creation is led to its goal/14
God rules the universe not by a power abstractly understood as absolute but by love.215 What God has 'determined' (decided on) is the creation of a reality different from Godself; it is a 'determination' of love. The entire relation of God to the world is governed by love. Having created the world, God does not have God's own existence in isolation from the world, but both over against it and in it as it moves toward its consummation in the kingdom of God. It can be confidently concluded that the theological system Pannenberg has created is not deterministic. Phrases such as 'the all-determining reality' will always raise the suspicion of determinism, especially among English-speaking readers. Pannenberg adopted it as a linguistic convention (nominal and incomplete), as he explained long ago.216 The reason for using it is the conviction, shared by Jewish monotheism and Greek philosophical monotheism, that everything that exists has its being by virtue of this z z
5Xi, ch. 6, §7, 412-48. 5Xi, 2.422. 5X6.1,446. 5X1,445.5. 5X1,4477.. 166 See XP5, 302
* 3 4 5
180
THE GOD OF THE FUTURE
reality or power and must ultimately be unintelligible except in relation to it. A theological implication of this formal definition of God is 'the idea that this all-determining power is itself determined only by itself and not subject to determination by anything else, unless it determines that it should be determined by something else'.217 In addition, the divine essence as love decisively colours the nature of God as 'the all-determining reality'. All the divine attributes are an expression of this love. God's all-determining power is further conditioned by God's determination to create a cosmos as the object of this love, a cosmos which God desires, in its own proper freedom and independence from God, to turn to God and to find its fullest life in union with God.218 Such a God, whilst 'all-determining', cannot be a determinist. In this chapter we have investigated the theological side of Pannenberg's ontology of the future, namely, his eschatological doctrine of God. Both God's being and God's action upon created reality have been in focus. In the background throughout the chapter has been Pannenberg's formal definition of God as 'the alldetermining reality', a phrase that needed some clarification. The consistency of Pannenberg's early and later ideas on the futurity of God is remarkable.219 In more recent writings Pannenberg has clarified his understanding of time in relation to eternity, thus providing a basis for a systematic account of God's relation to time. Of particular interest was his trinitarian articulation of the way in which God is affected by what takes place in time. This leads to a rich notion of a 'becoming' in God, an idea which Pannenberg greatly prefers to the idea of 'development' in God. In particular, we looked at Pannenberg's view of God's action, notably the idea that God creates from the future. Of fundamental importance here is the 'eschatological reversal' of the doctrine of creation, for which Pannenberg in later work draws on contemporary scientific argument. He brings together ideas from cosmology and physics (especially the notion of 'field of force') and the classical doctrine of the Trinity (especially the concept of ZI7
TPS, 302.
^ STi, 42of. 219 J. O'Donnell says that Pannenberg is 'thoroughly consistent in the fundamental intuition which has guided his reflections during the past thirty years'; Tannenberg's Doctrine of God', in Gregorianum 71.1, 1991, 94. 181
GOD AND THE FUTURE
'the Spirit'). Increasingly, the doctrine of the Spirit has become prominent in his work, notably in essays on science and nature and in the final volume of his Systematic Theology, with the accent on the role of the Spirit in creation. Pannenberg's doctrine of creation from the future is not easy to understand, but we have found it to be highly innovative and coherent. Finally, we found the criticism that he is a determinist, though understandable, unconvincing. It remains now, in the final chapter, to consider how Pannenberg's radical eschatological and orthodox trinitarian ideas coincide. It will be a further unfolding of Pannenberg's axiom that the being of God is God's rule, for the kingdom of God - the central theme of Jesus' proclamation - is nothing other than the rule (monarchy) of the Father through the Son and the Spirit.
181
6
The reign of the triune God Introduction
T
he final chapter of this book is concerned with Pannenberg's trinitarian articulation of his eschatological doctrine of God. The previous chapter explored Pannenberg's understanding of God's being and interaction with the created cosmos. Reference was made to the trinitarian solution to the problem of God's transcendence and immanence, that is, how God is and is not affected by what happens in time and space. We also noted the trinitarian form of Pannenberg's doctrine of creation. In this chapter the focus will be on the doctrine of the Trinity as such. Pannenberg's doctrine of the Trinity is not an addendum to a largely philosophical theology; it is the backbone of the whole system.1 Its full articulation appears only in the third volume of the Systematic Theology, though chapters five and six of Vol. i lay the foundations. The particular interest guiding our investigation is the relation of Pannenberg's trinitarian thought to his major principle that God's being is God's rule. God cannot be God without God's rule in and over all things; once there is a cosmos the very idea of God requires that God's power or rule be established over it. 'Only the god who proves himself master over all is true.' 2 The deity of God as creator is inconceivable without God's rule in this world and without the praise and gratitude by which the creatures honour 1
Already in 1981 Pannenberg said that his development of the doctrine of God would be 'more thoroughly trinitarian than any example I know of; see 'God's Presence in History', The Christian Century, n March 1981, 2.60. 2
TKG, 55.
183
GOD AND THE FUTURE
God as their creator.3 This rule, which must include the removal of all doubt concerning God's reality, is eschatological; it is incomplete in the present order of things. God is 'the God of the coming rule'.4 How then does Pannenberg bring together the idea of the kingdom of God, central in Jesus' ministry, and the doctrine of the Trinity, central in Christian faith? He early described the doctrine of the Trinity as 'the seal of the pure futurity of God'.5 The Son reconciles us with the Father by drawing us into his sonship and making us open to God's future, God's coming rule, which the Father establishes through the Son and the Spirit. It is more usual for theologians to focus on Jesus' message of the rule of God, to the exclusion of the Trinity, or to write a trinitarian theology without serious engagement with the heart of Jesus' message. Pannenberg sees them in the closest relation. In this chapter we will look especially at the way he superimposes the doctrine of the Trinity on his early principle of God's being as God's rule.6 The chapter begins with a survey of early references to the Trinity, followed by an analysis of the more crystallised trinitarian theology found in three major essays of the second half of the 1970s.7 We then consider Pannenberg's systematic account of the doctrine of the Trinity in his Systematic Theology, mainly in the first volume. This includes his approach to some key issues in trinitarian theology, in particular the relation between the economic and the immanent Trinity. This study culminates in a close look at the way in which, like two overlapping circles which come together to become concentric, the doctrine of the Trinity becomes the theological framework for understanding the eschatological completion of the divine project of creation. Although few published criticisms of Pannenberg's doctrine of the Trinity 3
Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 255. 4 TKG, 56. 5 W. Pannenberg, The God of Hope', BQTz, 149. 6 Colin Gunton also calls for 'a truly trinitarian eschatology'; The Promise of Trinitarian Theology (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1991), 157. 7 These are all published in GSTz: 'Person und Subjekt' (1976), 80-95; 'Die Subjektivitat Gottes und die Trinitatslehre' (1977), 96-111; and 'Der Gott der Geschichte' (1977), u.2,-2.8. Only the last of these is translated into English (by M. B. Jackson) as 'The God of History', The Cumberland Seminarian, 19.2-3, Winter & Spring 1981, 2.8-41. 184
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
reveal a close knowledge of his most recent writings on the Trinity, the major criticisms are considered. Pannenberg's fundamental ontological principle is that the essence of something is determined only by its end, but - on the principle of retroactive permanence - is then constituted as its essence throughout. Its essence is fully known only in relation to its full historical context, but it is anticipated in the course of its history. This holds true for Pannenberg's theology; the centrality of the doctrine of the Trinity in his theological system is fully clear only from his later writings but turns out to have been the real centre of the system all along. There were clear anticipations of it in earlier writing, but they were not so striking that the future shape of the system could be clearly foreseen. To review briefly, there is a reference to the Trinity already in Revelation as History. It their context the following lines are quite remarkable: In the fate of Jesus, the God of Israel is revealed as the triune God. The event of revelation should not be separated from the being of God himself. The being of God does not belong just to the Father, but also to the Son. The Holy Spirit also shares in the being of God by virtue of his participation in the glory of God that comes to life in the eschatological congregation.8
The Trinity plays no further part in the argument of this early work. It is unavoidable to raise it in the framework of Christology; the claim of Jesus' deity forces the question of the relation of that deity to the deity of God the Father. Thus we find more developed trinitarian ideas in Jesus - God and Man, in the section 'The Origin of the Doctrine of the Trinity and the Problem of the Logos Christology'.9 The basis of the doctrine of the Trinity is the relation and the distinction between the Son and the Father; both belong to the essence of God.10 The heart of the trinitarian problem is already described as the unity of God, given the distinctiveness of Father, Son and Spirit in God's self-revelation and thus in the divine essence.11 Already Pannenberg is drawn to the idea of 8
RAH, 143. This was published (in the German original) in 1961. See also/GM, 130 (1964). 9 /GM, ch. 4, part 3, 158-83. 10 /GM, 159, 169. This idea recurs virtually unchanged in STi, 2.64. 11 /GM, 180. This foreshadows the sequence of chs 5 & 6 in STi; see 334-6. i85
GOD AND THE FUTURE
perichoresis (the 'complete reciprocal dedication') of the three persons of the Trinity as the solution to the problem of the unity of the trinitarian God.12 The exploration of trinitarian ideas, driven by the pursuit of christological questions, is already foreshadowed in the mid-1960s. However, there are very few references to the doctrine of the Trinity in the essays collected in the first volume of Grundfragen; it appears to have been extraneous to Pannenberg's major concerns in these essays, despite his stated concern with the understanding of God.13 In 'The Appropriation of the Philosophical Concept of God as a Dogmatic Problem of Early Christian Theology', there is a reference to the doctrine of the Trinity, but only to illustrate the point that 'the metaphysics of the history of revelation' was not swamped by philosophical concerns alien to the Gospel.14 A major issue in these early essays is God's relation to the world, but this is not yet described in trinitarian terms. The essay 'The God of Hope', about the futurity of God, ends by describing the doctrine of the Trinity as 'the seal of the pure futurity of God'.15 In the programmatic essay 'Theology and the Kingdom of God' we see a clearer hint that Pannenberg proposes to develop the idea of God's futurity and relation to the historical process in trinitarian terms: In his creative, redeeming, and sustaining arrival, God's future demonstrates his power. This can be clarified by reference to the trinitarian language about God that is common in the Christian community. In Jesus this life of divine love is revealed in a trinitarian form. God is not an existing entity but is the future of his coming Kingdom. As this future, he was and is present through that man, Jesus, who testified to the coming Kingdom of God ... The trinitarian distinctions are based on the difference between future and present. As we have seen, future and present - and consequently the 'persons' of the Trinity - are comprehended in the unity of God. " /GM, 183. 13 These essays, translated in the two English volumes entitled Basic Questions in Theology, Vols i &; 2,, were written between 1959 and 1967. See the Foreword to BQTi, xv. There is a reference to the Trinity in connection with the concept of 'the person' in 'The Question of God', 2,2,9. '< BQT2, 179. '5 BQT2, 249. 186
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
... The trinitarian concept [of God] describes the particular unity of the living God ... The trinitarian doctrine describes the coming God as the God of love whose future has already arrived and who integrates the past and present world, accepting it to share in his own life forever ... The trinitarian doctrine is the ultimate expression for the one reality of the coming God whose Kingdom Jesus proclaimed.16
From the standpoint of Pannenberg's mature trinitarian theology, these ideas were to undergo enormous development. But it is clearly signalled that the idea of God's futurity, which is so innovative, will be expressed in traditional trinitarian terms. It is clear that some significant anticipations of the theme of the Trinity appear in these early essays, in which Pannenberg argued for a philosophically and theologically defensible understanding of God and God's relation with the cosmos. But we have little more than hints. This changes in three major essays from the mid-1970s. A decisive turn to the Trinity Pannenberg writes in the Foreword of Grundfragen Systematischer Theologie, Vol. 2, that the three studies on the doctrine of the Trinity connect the doctrine of the Trinity and God's relation to history in a way which had hitherto remained open. In these essays the doctrine of the Trinity moves to the centre of the stage.17 In the first of these Pannenberg distinguishes the concepts of 'person' and 'subject', which is of particular importance in trinitarian theology.18 Personhood consists essentially in relationality. If the modern concept of 'subject', with its overtones of absoluteness, is applied to the persons of the Trinity, one ends up dangerously close to tritheism.19 The Persons of the Trinity - and no less human persons - are constituted by their relations. Human beings have their human essence through their relations with other human beings, and the Persons of the Trinity have their deity only in relation to the other trinitarian Persons. The Father and the Son do not have their deity in isolation from each other, but only in relation to each other; through the communion of the Spirit who 16
TKG, 7of. GSTz, ji. Philip Clayton rightly describes these essays as 'the backbone of Grundfragen', Vol. 2; The God of History and the Presence of the Future', The journal of Religion 65.1, January 1985, 103. 18 W. Pannenberg, 'Person und Subjekt', GSTz, 80-95. *9 GST2, 86. 17
187
GOD AND THE FUTURE
unites them. For each Person of the Trinity the divine essence appears only in and through the other two.20 Two points are worth noting. First, Pannenberg takes the idea of the mutuality of the trinitarian persons further than usual; the Father receives his deity as much from the Son and the Spirit as they receive theirs from the Father. Pannenberg sees the trinitarian relations not only as relations of origin, in which the Son and the Spirit receive their deity from the Father.11 In volumes two and three of Systematic Theology he elaborates on the correlative idea of the Father's dependence on the Son and Spirit for his deity. God's deity includes God's rule over all created things, and this is achieved only through the Son and the Spirit. Thus the relation of the Father with the Son and the Spirit involves a mutual dependence, which requires seeing the trinitarian relations not only as relations of origin but also as eschatological relations. This is an enrichment of our understanding of the intra-trinitarian relations.22 Second, Pannenberg insists, against Earth, that it is possible to describe God as personal only by means of the doctrine of the Trinity. To regard God as 'a person' apart from the Trinity makes the doctrine of the Trinity superfluous. It leaves no room for the 'Persons' of the Father and the Son, and reduces the Spirit to the impersonal power of the one God. Rather, God is personal because the Father, the Son and the Spirit are 'Persons' in the fullest sense. Pannenberg sees no other way to understand God's being as personal. Likewise, the divine unity can be seen only in the trinity of the divine Persons. This is not only a matter of how it appears to us; the trinitarian Persons themselves have the divine essence mediated through each other.23 In other words, this is predicated of the immanent Trinity, not just the economic Trinity. Whilst the major focus of this first essay is terminological, the discussion includes implications for the doctrine of the Trinity per se, especially the intra-trinitarian relations. In the second of these essays the focus is on the trinitarian relations and distinctions as the basis for understanding God's relation to the 20
GST2, 93. An expanded form of this understanding is found in STi, esp. 310-17. 21 Cf. STi, 320-7. 22 Contra J. O'Donnell, who criticises this departure from the patristic idea of unilateral relations of origin; Tannenberg's Doctrine of God', 96. 2 3 GST2, 95. 188
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
cosmos.14 Pannenberg traces some problems in Earth's doctrine of the Trinity to its Hegelian foundations. Earth's indebtedness to the Hegelian I. Dorner is well-known. Like Dorner, Earth thought of God as 'a person', an absolute person, and thus regarded the three Persons of the Trinity as three 'modes of being' (Seinsweisen) of the one God. In Pannenberg's view, this is unsatisfactory. However, the importance of the essay goes beyond its historical insights. We will focus on three points: Pannenberg's critique of the Hegel-Earth line of grounding the Trinity in the subjectivity of God, his own way of making the Trinity integral to the doctrine of God, and the importance of the doctrine of the Trinity for understanding God's relation to the world. i. The critique of Earth and Hegel In keeping with his emphasis on the concept of the person in trinitarian theology, Pannenberg rejects the grounding of the doctrine of the Trinity in the idea of God's subjectivity, that is, understanding God as Subject. He sees this not only in Hegel, where God or Spirit is the subject of a necessary self-development in the 'other' of itself, but also in Earth, where the doctrine of the Trinity is developed out of the simple proposition that God reveals Godself as Lord.25 The main problem with Hegel, according to Pannenberg, is that there is too ready an equation of God with Spirit/Subject and an emphasis on the Subject's necessary selfdifferentiation, while yet remaining essentially itself. By predicating of the infinite God a process of self-development (in which God becomes truly Godself), Hegel describes God in terms which belong to finite reality. Self-development presupposes a self to be developed, and this implies the idea of the successiveness of cause and effect. This is unacceptable in a Christian doctrine of God, because God, as eternal, is all that God is in a single present.26 Understanding God principally as Subject or in terms of Self-consciousness leads to a very problematic view of God. 24
W. Pannenberg, 'Die Subjektivitat Gottes und die Trinitatslehre' (The Subjectivity of God and the Doctrine of the Trinity'), GST2, 96-111. 25 As Clayton points out, Falk Wagner has criticised Pannenberg's interpretation of Hegel's view of the person; The God of History and the Presence of the Future', 103. 26 GSTz, 107. Here, in a nutshell, is the basis of Pannenberg's opposition to the idea of development in God, as distinct from a 'becoming' in God. 189
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Earth, similarly to Hegel, develops his view of the Trinity on the basis that God is the Subject of God's self-revelation; God determines to be Father, Son and Holy Spirit. This implies that God exists as Subject prior to the differentiation of the trinitarian 'modes of being'. Earth understands God first as a single Subject; God's unity is the unity of a thinking and willing T.27 In Pannenberg's view, the doctrine of the Trinity cannot be grounded in the idea of the divine subjectivity expressing itself in revelation; nor in the concept of revelation per se. This fails to do justice to the three trinitarian Persons. They become 'modes of being' of the one God, moments in the revelation of God, and personhood is predicated of this one God.28 The result is the subordination of the Son and the Spirit to the Father. The irony is that Earth, so critical of Hegel's idea of a necessary self-development in God (since this implies a denial of the freedom of God), establishes his doctrine of the Trinity in essentially the same way. We will return to the serious consequences of this. 2. God's deity is dependent upon the deity of the three trinitarian persons In Hegel's work there is another way of grounding trinitarian theology, in which the unity of God is constituted by the communion of love which unites the Father and the Son. Here the plurality of the divine persons is primary; God's oneness exists only in this plurality of divine persons.19 This accords with a major point in the first of these essays, that God is personal only because the Father, the Son and the Spirit are each divine Persons. Pannenberg insists that the Persons of the Trinity are not divine in isolation, but in relation to each other. There is thus no danger of bi-theism or tri-theism, for the Persons of the Trinity do not have their being or deity independently, but only in relation to the other two. This highlights the major difference between the concepts of subject and person. In Hegel's sense, the subject sees the 'other' as an alienation from itself, through which, however, it comes to know itself. But its subjectivity is not gained through the 'other'. 17
'... als die Einheit eines denkenden und wollenden Ich'; GSTz, 100. GST2, 100. 2 9 GST2, 108.
18
190
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
The person, on the other hand, does not have its self a priori, but receives its personhood from something which transcends itself.30 In Pannenberg's view, the doctrine of God must be developed from the deity of the three Persons, which is established from the New Testament and subsequent theological clarification. It cannot be based on some extraneous concept of the divine, of revelation (Earth) or the Subject (Hegel). Pannenberg's developed thought on the Trinity is consistent with this principle.31 3. God's relation to the world Only if the doctrine of the Trinity is properly grounded in what the three Persons of the Trinity do in the economy of creation and salvation is it possible to express the relation between God and the world in adequate terms. Pannenberg supports Moltmann in differentiating between a proper trinitarian Christian theism (in which God is personal only as three Persons) and a spurious Christian theism, in which God is one divine Person.32 This latter understanding of God leads to one of two views of the relation between God and the cosmos. Either it sees God as completely 'other', beyond (even in opposition to) the world (Earth), or it sees a self-development in God for which the cosmos is a necessary condition (Hegel). These two views lead to an extreme emphasis respectively on God's transcendence or God's immanence. Pannenberg steers a course between these extremes. He criticises Earth for wanting to have a concept of God totally removed from the world. Earth's God neither depends on any relation with the world nor is arguable on the basis of any worldly reality; we must 'begin with God', a position Pannenberg always regarded as unacceptably fideistic.33 Earth's God is, of course, a God of grace, who has made an 'other' to be a counterpart. But 30
GSTz, 109. 'Personalitat ... hat das Ich nicht schon von sich aus. Person zu sein, kommt dem Ich erst zu von einem das Ich iibersteigenden Lebensinhalt, der sein wahres Selbtsein allererst begriindet.' I understand the word Personalitat to mean 'personhood'. 31 STi, 299. 3Z GSTz, nof., note 34. 33 GSTz, 105. See also TPS, 265-76, esp. 2.73: 'Earth's apparently so lofty objectivity about God and God's Word turns out to rest on no more than the irrational subjectivity of a venture of faith with no justification outside itself.' 191
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Earth will tolerate no idea of a God who might need the cosmos; a God who exists only over against some other is not God.34 On this point Pannenberg is more in sympathy with Hegel, who argued that the idea of the finite and the infinite are unavoidable correlates. Belief in God must have some reference to the cosmos. In Hegelian terms, the infinite must not only be seen in its opposition to the finite; it must also be seen to annul and transcend the opposition between finite and infinite.35 For Pannenberg it is not just the being of God but also the rule of God over the cosmos that is at stake. God's sovereignty, so much Earth's concern, can only be established in relation to the world that God has created. That relation includes both God's transcendence over the world and God's immanence in it. Pannenberg recalls Bonhoeffer's dictum that God is the other, the beyond, in the midst of our life.36 Both the 'beyondness' and the 'in the midst' have to be recognised. Pannenberg believes that this can only be adequately expressed in trinitarian terms. We come now to the third (and the most important) essay on the Trinity in this first volume of Grundfragen, entitled 'The God of History'.37 Among the most tightly argued of Pannenberg's writings, the essay consists of three parts. j. God's relation to history For Pannenberg history has its coherence or unity 'from the faithfulness of God's activity which initially guarantees stability and continuity to and for God's people'.38 In biblical thought all events are seen in relation to God. For believers in God, history cannot be regarded as an autonomous realm, independent of God's reality. It would deprive God of God's deity, for it 'mitigates the power of God which is seen in the fact that each and all events are equally the work of God.'39 The view of history 34
GSTi, 104, where Pannenberg quotes Barth.
35 GST2, I0 5 . 36
GST2, in. 'Gott 1st ... "mitten in unserem Leben jenseitig".' 37 W. Pannenberg, 'Der Gott der Geschichte'; GSTi, 112-2.8. References are given to the English translation by M. B. Jackson. 38 Pannenberg, The God of History', 30. 39 Pannenberg, The God of History', 30. The word 'equally' for zugleich is misleading. The point is not that all events are equally the work of God, but that each event is equally (at the same time) an event within the chain of cause and effect and an act of God. 192
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
as autonomous reduces God to a 'more or less impotent spectator'.40 But what is the nature of God's involvement in history? How is history the work of God, and how can history have its unity and its meaning in God? How can the claim of a theological meaning of history be justified? The claim that history is in some sense a divine project comes under great pressure from the reality of evil and the magnitude of suffering, but Pannenberg sees history as both a history of judgment and a history of salvation.41 He argues that the assertion of our emancipation from God is no more self-evidently true than the claim that history has its meaning in God. It remains to be seen whether God's reality will be definitively established. But if it is to be established, it will have to be in relation to the whole course of history. This is what Pannenberg means by the statement that 'God's divinity is at stake in history.'42 Only the completion of God's activity in the coming of God's kingdom will remove the question-mark. 2. With Hegel, not Kierkegaard How is God's relation to the course of history to be understood? In particular, how are God's acts related to God's being? In the second part of the essay Pannenberg rejects any help that might come from process theology, with its idea that God becomes God in the history of the divine action.43 While such an understanding of God may help to make sense of evil and suffering, it finally manages to 'lose the concept of God, as absolute, by reducing him to one factor among others in the universe and to reciprocal action with them'.44 Pannenberg also wants to go beyond Kierkegaard's impasse between the necessary timelessness of God ('the Eternal alone has absolutely no history') and the corollary of the incarnation, 'that something is decided for the being of God Himself in the continuous change of 40
Pannenberg, The God of History', 31. Pannenberg, The God of History', 31. ^ Pannenberg, The God of History', 32. 43 In this essay Pannenberg criticises Process theology's notion of a 'becoming' God. As we saw in the last chapter Pannenberg later distinguishes a 'developing' God, which he sees in Process theology, from a 'becoming' God, which he can accommodate in his own theology. 44 Pannenberg, The God of History', 33. 41
193
GOD AND THE FUTURE
historical development5.45 Kierkegaard could not find room in his understanding of God for any historical becoming. At this point, Pannenberg leans strongly toward Hegel's idea that God has a history within God's own being, rather than adopting Kierkegaard's position. To express such a view, Hegel drew on the Christian doctrine of the Trinity. His understanding of the Trinity as 'the one history of God within Himself was taken up by Earth, who once (in the Christian Dogmatics) described the Trinity as 'the eternal history of God'.46 Pannenberg is sympathetic with Earth's desire to avoid Hegel's blurring of the distinction between the being of God and the course of the world's history. Earth sees that God's self-revelation in history must disclose God's eternal essence, but he appealed to a Platonist notion of correspondence to express the relation between what happens in history and God's being as Trinity. Pannenberg comes back to the sharp statement of the problem by Hegel and Kierkegaard. Hegel understands God's being and the history of God's activity as a unity - with the result that the idea of God as prior to history was put at risk - while Kierkegaard went to great pains to preserve the ontological distinction between God and created reality.47 In an important footnote Pannenberg traces the impasse to a paradox in the idealist concept of the subject: does the subject already exist as subject prior to its self-deployment - in which case the self-deployment is not a condition of the identity of the subject as subject - or is the process of self-deployment constitutive for the essence of the subject - in which case the process precedes the subject and produces the subject within the process itself.48 Pannenberg takes the first option; the problem must be approached in the following way, along modified Hegelian lines.49 Theology has to work out 45 Pannenberg, The God of History', 33. 'If God were not altered by the incarnation and is God in the same way after as before it, then the notion of God's incarnation and the idea of His historical self-revelation would be abolished. On the other hand, should the concept of incarnation be taken seriously, then the being of God is not absolutely redeemable from history.' 46 Pannenberg, The God of History', 33, 34 (note 2.1). 47 Pannenberg, The God of History', 34. 48 Pannenberg, The God of History', 34, note 2.6; the footnote is on 4of. 49 'In spite of these uncertainties (Aporien), which established the justification for Kierkegaard's critique, Hegel's effort remains admirable as an
194
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
the implications of the biblical language about God as the truth of God's historical activity, without implying that God has no reality apart from that activity: The solution to the task of conceiving the being of God and the history of His activity is conditioned by the fact that one must be able to think of God as absolute in his relation to the world and not restricted by it, but fulfilled Himself through that relationship. As Hegel surmised, the doctrine of the Trinity offers a key to the solution of this task.50
3. Outline of the doctrine of the Trinity The third part of this essay is Pannenberg's outline of the doctrine of the Trinity. In his view, the doctrine of the Trinity has its basis not merely in the history of salvation, but in the relation of that history to the entire work of creation, from beginning to end.51 The Logos Christology of the early church secures this relation of redemption to creation. It also opens the way for an immanent doctrine of the Trinity. The trinitarian distinctions apply not only to the divine economy but also to the eternal being of God. However, this distinction has made the relation of the triune God to history problematic: Since the immanent Trinity is conceived of as preceding all God's historical relations to the world, all these relations (even the incarnation) now appear as something subsequently added and external to the eternal life of the triune God. The God of the classical doctrine of the Trinity then remains the God of history and historical revelation only in a secondary sense.52
The result is the hypostasisation of the Trinity prior to all history. Pannenberg sees this as the great problem of the doctrine of the Trinity throughout its history. Hegel's instinct, if not his solution, was right; he sought to relate the (triune) being of God more closely to God's action in the created cosmos. The problem was attempt to conceive the being of God and the history of His activity as a unity'; The God of History', 34f. 50 Pannenberg, The God of History', 35. 51 'Only in a dual relationship to the origin of the world and its future fulfillment is the God revealed in the unique history of Jesus truly God'; The God of History', 35. 52 GSTz, 123. I have slightly changed Jackson's translation of these sentences; The God of History', 35. 195
GOD AND THE FUTURE
that he did it in a speculative and non-eschatological way. Pannenberg proposes to do it in a more thoroughly trinitarian and eschatological way: the deity of each of the Persons of the Trinity has to be explicitly considered in relation to the course of history. Such a procedure has consequences for the articulation of the doctrine of the Trinity and of God's relation to history. As mentioned in the last chapter, Pannenberg emphasises the mutuality and reciprocity of the trinitarian relations; the Father depends on the Son for his deity as much as the Son depends on the Father. The significance of the crucifixion for our knowledge of God, indeed for God's being, has been given prominence in recent theology especially by Moltmann and Jiingel.53 Pannenberg sees this in the closest connection with Jesus' resurrection. Together they profoundly affect the very being of God: Above all, the crucifixion of Jesus placed in question the divine authority claimed by Him, which was decided in light of His resurrection. But in that case, the crucifixion placed the divinity of the Father in question also. In this way the resurrection of Jesus is just as constitutive for the divinity of the Father as for the Sonship of Jesus. For apart from Jesus' resurrection, the Father proclaimed by him would not be God.54
We should note, first, that the issue is ontological, not epistemological. If God is defined by the cross and resurrection of Jesus, this means not only that our knowledge of God is channelled through the cross and resurrection, but that they are determinative of the being of God. This is a radical departure from the doctrine of God's immutability. Second, even more radically, Pannenberg insists that not only the deity of the Son is determined by the cross and resurrection of Jesus, but also the deity of the Father. This is a major modification of the old doctrine of the priority of the Father over the Son and the Spirit. It goes hand in hand with Pannenberg's view of God's being as constituted by God's eschatological rule over the world, rather than as abstracted from the divine work of creation. This is a major shift in thought. Each of the Persons of the Trinity gains his deity through the other Persons. As we will see, the Father gains his deity through 53 Pannenberg elaborates on this in a later essay, 'Problems of a Trinitarian God', Dialog 2,6.4, FaH *9%7> esp. 2.51-2.. 54 Pannenberg, The God of History', 36.
196
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
the Son and the Spirit. The Son gains his deity by his obedient service to the Father (with whom he is one and from whom he also distinguishes himself) and from the Spirit, who raises him from the dead and glorifies him. Correspondingly, the Spirit is glorified as divine in so far as it is the Spirit who glorifies the Father and the Son in their union. None of the trinitarian Persons is a divine subject in his own right and in isolation from the other two. Reiterating what he emphasises in the earlier two essays, Pannenberg says: The model of a self-static subjectivity has no place in the trinitarian life of God, as it actualises itself in God's historical revelation and thus also in God's eternity. The Father is not the truly divine Subject who produces the other so-called modes of being; nor is the Spirit, and certainly not the Son. The construction of the Trinity as the self-development of a divine Subject unavoidably violates the co-eternity of the divine Persons and reduces their plurality to mere modes of being which are subordinated to the divine Subject. 55
This requires a detailed treatment of the work of each of the persons of the Trinity, which Pannenberg does not attempt in this essay. He gives only an indication of how it might be done: through the old doctrine of appropriation (Attributionenlehre}. According to this doctrine, the divine acts ad extra are the acts of the one God, although they are attributed to one Person of the Trinity in particular. However, the other Persons are also involved. Pannenberg wants to develop this involvement of the other two Persons in greater detail, especially its implications for God's being. He speaks of an />z£r<2-trinitarian attribution, corresponding to the attribution of divine acts ad extra to one Person of the Trinity. What he means is the attribution of deity (the divine essence common to the three) to each of the trinitarian Persons through the other two. Thus the deity of the Father, the reality of his kingdom or rule, is dependent on the work of the Son and the Spirit. For the Person to whom a given divine act in the economy of salvation is attributed, God is represented by the other two. In the work of salvation attributed to the Son, the Father, present through the Spirit, is the one God. In the work of creation the Father depends on the Son and the Spirit who will glorify him as 55
Pannenberg, The God of History', 36.1 have altered the translation; cf. GSJ2, 12.4. 197
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the creator of all things. The Spirit, in completing the work of redemption, is glorified only through the glorification of the Father and the Son in their mutual fellowship. The result of such a reshaping of the doctrine of the Trinity is not clearly apparent in this essay, but the implications are major. The implications for the relation between God and history are equally significant. Pannenberg argues for the unity of God's being and God's action in history. Such a view requires the doctrine of the Trinity. Each of the Persons of the Trinity effects something in the economy of creation, redemption and perfection, and in this way contributes something to the intra-trinitarian relations which constitute God's being, while also receiving something from the other two Persons. The reciprocity of these relations does not exclude the first Person of the Trinity, who also receives from the other two. What the second and third Persons experience in their work in the world of time and space is brought into the very life of God. This brings God into an intimately close relation with the world, so much so that what takes place in the history of creation must be said to affect God in God's very being. As Pannenberg wrote much later, 'the reciprocity in the relationship of the divine persons makes room for the constitutive significance of the central salvation-historical events for the Godhood of God and thus for the significance of time and change for the divine eternity'.56 At issue here is the relation between eternity and time, the impact of what takes place in time on the eternal being of God. Pannenberg makes the extraordinary statement that, although the (ontological) difference between God and the creation remains, it is also transcended or modified from the side of God.57 The point is that God is open to, and involved in, the course of historical events, notably through the experience and activity of the three Persons of the Trinity. God's being is constituted by what each of the trinitarian Persons does in the whole economy of creation, redemption and consummation. 'The triune God is the God of history';58 conversely, the God of history is none other than 56
Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 2.52.. Pannenberg, The God of History', 37. Pannenberg's actual words are, '... wobei die Differenz zwischen Gott und Geschopf sowohl gesetzt als auch von Gott her immer schon iibergriffen ist'; G5T2, 12.5. Here Jackson's translation is inaccurate. 58 GSTz, 125. 57
198
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
the triune God. But in what way is God open to, and involved in, history? The view of God in which the Son's experience of suffering and death, together with his resurrection, is constitutive for God's very being must include some reference to the reality of suffering and evil, since this most sharply calls into question the claim that history is the realm of God's action and involvement. At the end of the essay Pannenberg turns to the question of theodicy. The key point for him is that room is made for a creaturely reality, different from God, by the fact that each person of the Trinity differentiates himself from the one God.59 Created beings, though dependent on their creator, have the opportunity to establish a relatively independent existence before God. However, their vocation is to live in partnership with God. Only through the Son and the Spirit can human beings attain the perfection of human existence. Only in fellowship with God, in the relationship of sonship to God mediated by the Spirit, can the perfection of this relatively independent existence be achieved. The ambiguity and tragedy of the human situation is the fact that the independence of human beings that has its basis in their self-differentiation from God contains the possibility of a perversion of the 'independence in partnership' that is their vocation. Creaturely difference from God degenerates into a division between Creator and creature. This happens in the space between the creative activity of the Father and that of the Son and the Spirit. But this is also the space in which occur the evil and suffering that give rise to the problem of theodicy. Pannenberg argues for the potential of a trinitarian theology to throw new light on the problem of theodicy, seeing advantages over the usual kenotic theories, which involve a self-restriction on the part of God. Pannenberg offers a more differentiated view of God's activity in creation, which finds fuller expression in the second volume of Systematic Theology. The doctrine of creation includes both the origins of the cosmos and its eschatological end. The work of creation, traditionally 'appropriated' to the Father, includes the original creative act of the Father in giving existence to the cosmos, 59
Pannenberg, The God of History', 37; cf. GST2, 115. In the Systematic Theology Pannenberg explicitly grounds the existence of an 'other' reality, differentiated from God, in the self-differentiation of the Son from the Father; cf. ST2, 22. 199
GOD AND THE FUTURE
the Son's provision of a basis for self-differentiation from God, and the perfecting, consummating work of the Spirit. In addition, this trinitarian view of God's history with the world suggests how God experiences and deals with the reality of evil and suffering in the Son and how God is active in overcoming it through the Spirit. The Spirit's work is to bring about true partnership between creatures and the creator. Through the Spirit this eschatological reality already shapes present experience, transforming those who are open to fellowship with the Son. Finally, the Spirit will grant the creation a share in the glory of God, which has shone in Jesus Christ. The strength of a trinitarian understanding of creation is that it is fully in harmony with the eschatological structure of the Christian understanding of the world and of life in its relation to God. It does so in the eschatological tension which it sees between the creative work of the Father - the already of the past - and the Father's dependence on the work of the Son and the Spirit for the realisation of the kingdom of God - the not yet of the future. In this tension lies the explanation of the sense which we have both of God's presence and God's absence in the world. Already the world gives evidence - not unambiguous - of having its existence in God; at the same time the magnitude of evil and the prevalence of injustice are reason enough to doubt it, leaving the question to be resolved - if at all - in the future that has not yet come. This 'paradoxical absence and presence of God' and the associated paradox of 'the future and present of His kingdom in creation' are implied in 'the paradox of unity and difference in the intratrinitarian relationships'.60 The three Persons of the Trinity are one in essence, and the creation of the cosmos is the work of the one God. But the life of the one God is constituted by the complementary but different activity of the three Persons. In the space between the work of the Father and that of the Son and the Spirit the world has its history of glory and misery. The creation is on the way to its full communion with God but also experiences its alienation from God and from its vocation. Pannenberg closes this essay with the following words: In the tension between the Creator's power and powerlessness, in the death of his Son and with the glorification of both through the Spirit, 60
Pannenberg, The God of History', 39; GSTz, 137. Pannenberg's term for 'paradox' here is 'das Ineinander'. 2OO
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
the triune God takes upon himself the suffering of his creation. In this way God is the God of history and its truth. 61
This is a remarkable essay. Together with the other two considered in this section, it shows Pannenberg's deliberate turn to the classical trinitarian theology of the church. Many ideas are introduced which are later developed in the Systematic Theology. Since the doctrine of the Trinity becomes the centre of the theological system, the major features of Pannenberg's account of it must now be considered. The triune God The decade between the essays we have considered and the appearance of the first volume of Pannenberg's Systematic Theology in 1988 was devoted largely to working out the details of the trinitarian theology already outlined. Pannenberg was not alone in this endeavour. Other theologians, notably Moltmann, Jiingel and Jenson, were engaged in a similar project. Pannenberg published no new work on the Trinity between 1977 and 1987, when 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God' came out.62 This article, highlighting some major questions Pannenberg was working on in preparing his magnum opus, was especially helpful for non-German speakers, who had to wait several years for a translation of the major work. In this short article the doctrine of the Trinity is presented as 'an inexhaustible resource which allows Christian theology to make constructive use of antimetaphysical and atheistic criticisms of the concept of God'.63 Pannenberg finds the basis for the doctrine of the Trinity in the Christian conviction that Jesus, as Son of God, was in the most intimate union with the God he addressed as 'Father', and yet differentiated himself from this God.64 The use of the title Kyrios for Jesus gives further impetus to trinitarian theology, for it implies the full deity of the Son. In addition, since these are not a sufficient basis for a trinitarian understanding of God, the Spirit is 61
Pannenberg, 'The God of History', 39, slightly altered; cf. GSTz, 128. Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 250-7. A translation of 'Probleme einer trinitarischen Gotteslehre', in W. Baier et al., Weisheit Gottes - Weisheit der Welt (St Ottilien, 1987), Vol. i, 329-41. 63 Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 250. 6 « STi, 263f. 62
2,01
GOD AND THE FUTURE
understood in early Christian experience as 'the medium of the communion of Jesus with the Father and the mediator of the participation of believers in Christ'/5 It is the Spirit who enables Jesus to do the work of God, and it is by the Spirit that Christian believers have a share in the sonship of Jesus. The impetus for trinitarian theology and worship comes especially from these influential factors. In the early centuries of Christian theology the relations between the Persons of the Trinity was a particularly difficult issue. Origen distinguished the three Persons according to their distinctive sphere of operation. Athanasius and the Cappadocians, on the other hand, held the three hypostases to be involved in all the divine activity, thus requiring a different basis for the distinctions between them. They found it in the relations of the Son/ Logos to the Father and the Spirit. The Logos doctrine of the early centuries was at times developed in a way that linked the unity of the Father and the Son with the Son's originating from the Father. Seeing the intratrinitarian relations primarily as relations of origin - the Son and the Spirit receiving their deity from the Father - always carried with it the risk of falling into subordinationism. Pannenberg regards the subordination of the Son and the Spirit to the Father as particularly problematic. In Basil, for example, the idea of the mutual defining of the distinctiveness of the persons does not lead to the thought of an equally mutual ontological constitution of their personhood but is interpreted in terms of relations of origin, of which it can be said that strictly they are constitutive only for the personhood of the Son and Spirit if the Father is the origin of deity.66
The distinctiveness and the unity of the Persons of the Trinity is in need of a firmer theological footing, and a significant part of Pannenberg's discussion of the doctrine of the Trinity is devoted to this task. There is a strong tendency in the history of trinitarian theology - epitomised by Thomas Aquinas - to derive the three Persons of the Trinity from the divine unity.67 This is in contrast 6
5 STi, 266.
66
STi, 2,80. STi, z88. The arrangement of themes gives appropriate expression to the basic structure: the existence of the one God, his substance, his substantial attributes, the Trinity'. 67
202
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
with the pattern of the East, in which it is the triune God who is the subject of everything else predicated of God. The major problem with the Western approach, however, is that it makes the doctrine of the Trinity superfluous or merely an external addition to the doctrine of God.68 This was one factor in the strong critique of the doctrine in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, with biblical scholarship and historical criticism adding further weight. For Pannenberg there is only one way forward; theology must try to show that the doctrine of the Trinity is 'a full and self-consistent presentation of the unity of the God who reveals himself in Christ', something which is 'only indicated in the NT witness but implicitly present materially in the faith of primitive Christianity'.69 Some of the key ideas of the earlier essays reappear in the Systematic Theology. Pannenberg rejects Hegel's attempt to derive the Trinity from the idea of the self-differentiation of Spirit in the process of its self-awareness; this is 'to subsume the threeness of the persons into the concept of a single personal God'.70 Such an approach is passed on, via Dorner, to Earth, for whom - as Pannenberg sees it - 'there is no room for a plurality of persons in the one God but only for different modes of being in the one divine subjectivity'.71 Such an approach inevitably attracts the charge of modalism, and Pannenberg views it as failing to do justice to the three Persons of the Trinity. The failure is compounded by the subordination of two of the Persons of the Trinity to the first Person. Even where the Trinity is derived from the concept of love - as in Richard of St Victor - the problem is not overcome. Such an approach does presuppose a plurality of persons, but in Pannenberg's view it still operates with a primary subject of love, leaving the other persons as its objects. The Trinity must be constituted by love; God is love. Anything less is subordinationism. Anything that puts the personhood of the three Persons at risk is damaging to the doctrine of the Trinity. Too often God is primarily identified with the Father,72 which is a travesty of the Christian doctrine of God. 68 69
70 71 72
STi, 183. STi, 291. STi, 294. STi, 196. STi, 198. Pannenberg criticises Jiingel for this. 203
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Pannenberg's way forward, anticipated in 'The God of History', is to focus on the actual history of revelation: To find a basis for the doctrine of the Trinity we must begin with the way in which Father, Son, and Spirit come on the scene and relate to one another in the event of revelation. Here lies the material justification for the demand that the doctrine of the Trinity must be based on the biblical witness to revelation or on the economy of salvation.73
In this way, Pannenberg believes, the doctrine of the Trinity is restored to the centre of the Christian understanding of God, rather than being reduced to an after-thought. Christian 'God-talk' always presupposes some prior understanding of God, but this is provided not by philosophy but by the Jewish understanding of God, hammered out in the struggle between the theologies of Israel and the surrounding nations. The Christian, trinitarian understanding is a reconstitution of the Jewish view of God, impelled by the words and deeds, the death and resurrection of Jesus. The Christian doctrine of God has to be presented as intrinsically trinitarian, not optionally so. It is the task of the Christian theologian to demonstrate this. For Pannenberg this has two major consequences, one methodological, the other material. Methodologically, it requires a discussion of the Trinity before God's unity, the consideration of the trinitarian Persons and relations before the divine essence and attributes. Materially, Pannenberg goes to considerable lengths to emphasise the reciprocity in the relations between the Persons of the Trinity. Three major points should be made. i. The basis for the doctrine of the Trinity in the divine selfrevelation in Jesus Christ Pannenberg applauds Earth for connecting the doctrine of the Trinity with revelation, though he criticises him for discussing it in the prolegomena of his theology rather than in the context of the doctrine of God. Pannenberg shares Earth's commitment to deal with the question: who is the God who is revealed in Jesus Christ? The basis for the Trinity can no longer be sought simply in Scripture.74 Nor can the doctrine of the Trinity be derived from the 73 STi, 299. 7 « STi, 3oif.
204
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
concept of revelation rather than from its content, as he criticises Earth for doing:75 To base the doctrine of the Trinity on the content of the revelation of God in Jesus Christ we must begin with the relation of Jesus to the Father as it came to expression in his message of the divine rule. The NT statements about the deity of Jesus all presuppose his divine sonship and are ultimately grounded in his relation to the Father. The relation of his message and work to the Father forms the foundation of the confession of the divine sonship of Jesus by the Christian community in the light of the divine confirmation of his fulness of power by the Easter event.76
The distinct personhood of the Spirit has also to be considered in accounting for the emergence of trinitarian theology, but the starting-point is the Son's relation to, and self-differentiation from, the Father. The Spirit is closely related to the Father and the Son and differentiated from both; indeed the differentiation of the Spirit from the Son is an extension of the differentiation of the Son from the Father. The patristic theologians went to great lengths to express the relation of the Spirit to the Father in different terms from those in which the Son's relation to the Father was described. They also made a careful distinction between the eternal procession of the Son and the Spirit from the Father, as well as between the Father's sending of the Son and gift of the Spirit to the world in the economy of salvation. Pannenberg regards some of these distinctions as over-stated and having little exegetical justification.77 His point is not that the consubstantiality of the Son with the Father, as the fourth-century theologians put it, is an unwarranted doctrine, but that it cannot be based on distinctions between begetting and sending, or begetting and breathing. It has to be based instead on the actual historical relation of Jesus to the Father. The starting-point is in history, the sending of the Son and the Spirit to the world in the economy of salvation. 7
5 Pannenberg suggests that Barth, though criticising Augustine's notion of the vestigia trinitatis, bases his doctrine on 'the supreme vestige, the image of the Trinity in the human soul'; STi, 304. 76 STi, 304. 77 5Ti, 305-8. 205
GOD AND THE FUTURE
2. Reciprocity in the trinitarian relations One of Pannenberg's greatest contributions to the doctrine of the Trinity is his argument that the relations between the Persons of the Trinity must be understood as reciprocal. They should not only be seen as relations of origin.78 The argument begins with Jesus, who serves the God he knows as Father and announces the nearness of the Father's lordship. God's lordship is to be honoured, and all other concerns are to be subordinated to the kingdom of God, which is imminent. Jesus subordinates himself to God, even in Gethsemane, and thus shows himself to be the Son who serves the Father's will: Precisely by distinguishing himself from the Father, by subjecting himself to his will as his creature, by thus giving place to the Father's claim to deity as he asked others to do in his proclamation of the divine lordship, he showed himself to be the Son of God and one with the Father who sent him (John 10:30). He is the Son of God as in his own person he at the same time honors on behalf of all others the claim of the first commandment by giving God the lordship that he demands in his proclamation. For in this way he glorifies the Father, and this is the object of his sending into the world.79
This becomes the basis of a trinitarian argument inasmuch as Jesus' oneness with the Father is so deep that the eternal God is God only in relation to Jesus. How is this so? There are several steps in this argument.80 First, in his human life Jesus differentiates himself from the God whom he addresses as Father. Yet, second, he glorifies the Father as no-one else has done; certainly not the first Adam, who in wanting to be as God succeeded only in separating himself from God. This is the basis of the confession that Jesus is Son of the Father. He is Son of God in a unique sense; all other human beings have their fellowship with the Father only through Jesus' fellowship with the Father. Third, in the life, death and resurrection of Jesus God is revealed as Father; God is Father only as in relation to this Son. The Son is therefore the eternal counterpart of the Father. There is a transition in this argument 78 He speaks of 'a defect which plagues the trinitarian theological language of both East and West, namely, that of seeing the relations among Father, Son, and Spirit exclusively as relations of origin'; STi, 319. 79 STi, 310. 80 See esp. the concentrated passage on STi, 310.
206
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
from what is predicated of Jesus, the man who was close to the God he called Father, to what is predicated about the eternal Son of the Father. This distinction - between a divine and a human aspect of Jesus - eventually becomes crystallised in the 'two natures' distinction of classical Christology. Pannenberg bases such a distinction - within the person of Jesus - on what is implied in God's eternity: what is true of God must be true of God eternally: The eternal God cannot be directly thought of as from eternity related to a temporal and creaturely reality unless this is itself eternal, as a correlate of the eternal God, and thus loses its temporal and creaturely nature. A distinction has thus to be made between the relation of Jesus to God's eternal deity, as the correlate of the Father, and his human, creaturely reality.81
Thus without displacing the creaturely reality of Jesus, the entire phenomenon of his appearance, his mission, his death and resurrection has its ontological ground in the being of God. We know about this only through the story of Jesus, which becomes the index of the story of God. Ontologically, however, it becomes the ground of this human story. This is the mystery of the incarnation. Thus there is within the being of God from eternity a counterpart to the Father, the Son, who is of the same being as the Father. Through him the Father's kingdom comes and through him the Father is glorified. As Christian tradition has maintained, God is Father only in relation to the Son. All others who name God 'Father' share in the Son's relation to the Father. This raises for Pannenberg the question of what is implied in the claim that the Father is Father only in relation to the Son. If the Son receives his deity from the Father, can anything comparable be said about the Father in relation to the Son? The matter has traditionally not been seen in such terms. The Father is said to be without origin; he is the origin and fount of deity for the Son and the Spirit. The dependence is one-way. However, Pannenberg argues that a greater degree of reciprocity should be acknowledged. Appealing to Athanasius's argument against the Arians, he emphasises that the Father is not the Father without the Son: Does that not mean that in some way the deity of the Father has to be dependent on the relation to the Son, although not in the same way as 81
STi, 311. 2,07
GOD AND THE FUTURE
that of the Son is on the relation to the Father? The Father is not begotten of the Son or sent by him. These relations are irreversible. But in another way the relativity of fatherhood that finds expression in the designation 'Father' might well involve a dependence of the Father on the Son and thus be the basis of true reciprocity in the trinitarian relations.82
Among the biblical material Pannenberg draws on to support such a view,83 particular emphasis is placed on the handing over of rule to the Son and the Son's handing of it back to the Father. This, and the glorification of the Father that results from it, is the purpose of the sending of the Son into the world. All power and authority have been given to the Son, but this is placed in the service of the glorification of the Father. The Son's lordship is not exercised for his own benefit but to complete the lordship or rule of the Father. Each gives to, and receives from, the other. Pannenberg takes this to characterise the intra-trinitarian relations between the Father and the Son; the relation between them is reciprocal: In the handing over of lordship from the Father to the Son, and its handing back from the Son to the Father, we see a mutuality in their relationship that we do not see in the begetting. By handing over lordship to the Son the Father makes his kingship dependent on whether the Son glorifies him and fulfils his lordship by fulfilling his mission. The self-distinction of the Father from the Son is not just that he begets the Son but that he hands over all things to him, so that his kingdom and his own deity are now dependent upon the Son.84
If the lordship of God means lordship over the cosmos, we must also make reference to the third Person of the Trinity. The death of Jesus calls into question Jesus' identity as Son of God, but even more the deity of the Father, the proclamation of whose kingdom has brought Jesus to trial and crucifixion. However, if it is the Spirit who raised Jesus from death, it is the Spirit who settles the question of the deity of the Son and the Father. To this extent they depend on the Spirit. This task of the Spirit is not yet complete with this, but in the resurrection it is already anticipated that death does not have the last word. The Johannine writings 8z
STi, 312.. At least one would speak of a co-dependence between the Father and the Son. 8 3 E.g. Matt 28:18, Luke 10:2.2, Matt 11:27, John 5: 23-7, i Cor 15:24^ 84 STi, 313. 2,08
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
throw a further light on the role of the Spirit with their idea of glorification. As it is the task of the Son to glorify the Father (Jn 17:4), so it is the task of the Spirit to glorify the Son (Jn 16:14). Therefore, in Pannenberg's view, the Spirit 'completes the revelation of the Father by the Son, since the Father is known only through the Son . . . Glorifying the Son, the Spirit also glorifies the Father and their indissoluble fellowship'.85 This is the 'selfdistinction' through which the Spirit is a distinct Person from the Father and the Son, while in intimate union with both. Like the Son, who serves not his own cause but that of the Father, the Spirit does not serve his own glorification but that of the Son. In glorifying the Son, the Spirit glorifies him in his relation to the Father, and so glorifies the Father in the Son. Pannenberg discusses the activity of the Spirit in more detail in the third volume of Systematic Theology. What has been said in the foregoing paragraphs demonstrates his point about reciprocity in the relations between the Persons of the Trinity, and this applies no less to the Spirit. Although he accepts the Western view of the Spirit as the bond of union between the Father and the Son, he also accepts the Eastern criticism that this weakens the personhood of the Spirit. The Spirit is not only the communion of the Father and the Son but is also differentiated from them. Without this it would be impossible to speak of mutuality. In his discussion of the filioque (in which he takes the Eastern view), Pannenberg sees the Son as first receiving the Spirit. In the economy of salvation he gives the Spirit to people, thus drawing them into his own fellowship with the Father. This justifies the description of the Spirit as 'the Spirit of Christ', but it does not alter the fact that the Spirit proceeds from the Father. He is received by the Son.86 It is clear then that in Pannenberg's view the fellowship of the Persons of the Trinity should not be described only in terms of relations of origin. To do so obscures the mutuality of the trinitarian relations, which can be inferred from the economy of salvation, culminating in the eschatological lordship of God over all finite things. Each of the Persons of the Trinity receives from the other two. Even the Father depends for his lordship (and thus his deity) on the Son and the Spirit. However, this conclusion can 85 86
STi, 315. STi, 3 i 7 f. 209
GOD AND THE FUTURE
be reached only within an eschatological frame of reference; only at the end will the Father's lordship be established and his glory permeate all things. Pannenberg's discussion of the reciprocal nature of the trinitarian relations underscores his conviction that eschatology is integral to the doctrine of God. 3. The monarchy of the Father through the Son and the Spirit Pannenberg has a distinctive view of the relation between the three Persons of the Trinity and the one God. Christian faith is uncompromisingly monotheistic, yet insists that the God revealed in Jesus Christ must be spoken of in terms of the trinitarian distinctions. Pannenberg accepts the idea of the simplicity of God; the divine unity is 'absolutely simple, without composition'.87 He acknowledges that holding the simplicity of God's being together with the three Persons of the Trinity is difficult. However, the unity of the divine being is not a unity without distinctions, though these cannot imply separation. 'As regards the Trinity it is plain that distinction does not vanish in unity but that the unity of the living God is a unity in distinction.'88 In short, the simplicity of God's being rules out the separation of the divine Persons from each other, but not their distinction from each other. This safeguards the unity of God. We have noted that Pannenberg is opposed to the idea that God is a single divine subject existing in three modes of being. On the contrary, the three Persons of the Trinity must be understood as 'living realizations of separate centers of action'.89 Each is active in his own way, though in complete harmony with the other two. Pannenberg regards the idea of person as implying a centre of action. (It is less clear whether he sees the persons of the Trinity also as centres of consciousness.90) When it comes to God's action, 87
STi, 2,84. He adds, 'Any idea of composition would dissolve the concept of God itself, for then we would have to seek a cause for the composition, and what is composite could not be the first and supreme cause.' See also STi, 346f. 88 STi, 3478 ? STi, 319. 90 STi, 319. This depends on how we can apply the idea of consciousness to God. Pannenberg seems to allow the possibility of each person of the Trinity having his own centre of consciousness, on the ground that the notion of self-consciousness, derived from the realm of human experience, can be applied to the divine persons in a modified way; STi, 32.0, 377!". 210
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
Pannenberg says that the subject of the divine action cannot be the divine essence itself, for the essence of God is not a subject alongside the three Persons. 'Only the three persons are the direct subjects of the divine action.'91 The Cappadocians, with their idea of the working together of the three persons ad extra, attracted the charge of tritheism. Pannenberg proposes that the tension between three acting subjects and one acting God may be resolved by means of the idea of the Spirit as a dynamic field of force. The Spirit is both the divine essence common to the three Persons and the third Person of the Trinity. Here he applies field theory to the idea of God from modern physics. The idea of the divine life as a dynamic field sees the divine Spirit who unites the three persons as proceeding from the Father, received by the Son, and common to both, so that precisely in this way he is the force field of their fellowship that is distinct from them both.'92 The Persons of the Trinity are not derived from a divine essence that differs from them, but they are centers of action of the one movement which embraces and permeates all of them - the movement of the divine Spirit who has his existence only in them. The persons are not first constituted in their distinction, by derivation from the Father, and only then united in perichoresis and common action. As modes of being of the one divine life they are always permeated by its dynamic through their mutual relations ... The commonality of action of Father, Son, and Spirit can be only a manifestation of the unity of life and essence by which they are always linked already.93
The one God, then, exists and acts in the Persons of the Father, the Son and the Spirit. The one divine essence exists in these distinctions and the one action of God is the cooperative action of the three Persons of the Trinity. But how does this affect the idea of the kingdom or rule of God? Pannenberg sees this as the reign (monarchy) of the Father. He repudiates any monarchianist (subordinationist or modalist) understanding of this. The sole rule (monarchia) of God is the rule or lordship of the Father in the economy of salvation by means of the Son and the Spirit, whose equal deity is not undermined by this. Keeping in view the 91
STi, 384. ** STi, 383. 93 STi, 385. 211
GOD AND THE FUTURE
eschatological consummation of God's rule, Pannenberg sees the monarchy of the Father not as the presupposition but the result of the common activity of the three Persons. It is 'the seal of their unity'.94 It implies no ontological primacy of the Father, nor the subordination of the Son and the Spirit. Pannenberg affirms the monarchy of the Father by reconstituting it in terms of eschatology: [T]hrough the work of the Son the kingdom or monarchy of the Father is established in creation, and through the work of the Spirit ... the kingdom or monarchy of the Father in creation is consummated. By their work the Son and Spirit serve the monarchy of the Father. Yet the Father does not have his kingdom or monarchy without the Son and Spirit, but only through them.95
There is thus no contradiction between the mutual communion of the Persons of the Trinity with each other and the monarchy of the Father, which reaches its goal in relation to the universe only through the Son and the Spirit.96 The concept of the monarchy of the Father, understood in this trinitarian way, is the bridge between Jesus' proclamation of the coming kingdom of God and the church's doctrine of the Trinity.97 The need to bring these together is occasioned by the once popular view that Jesus proclaimed only the Father, and not the Son.98 However, in Pannenberg's view there is no division between the God whom Jesus knew as Father and the triune God because the communion of the persons finds its content in the monarchy of the Father as the result of their common activities. Thus 'the trinitarian God is none other than the God whom Jesus 94
95 96
ST1, 325. ST1, 324.
See also STi, 389, where the monarchy of the Father is described as God's absolute lordship, which is served by the Son and the Father and mediated by them. Yet it is the action of the one God. 97 This rich trinitarian understanding of 'monarchy' is not vulnerable to Moltmann's criticism of the divine monarchic for he associates it with a nontrinitarian monotheism, which obliges us to think of God without Christ; J. Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God (London: SCM Press, 1981), 131. 98 Pannenberg refers to this; STi, 315. He agrees with Harnack's famous statement to this effect, but adds that we cannot know the Father apart from the person of Jesus, 'for the reign of the Father dawns [near] only in his coming and in belief in him. It is thus that he is the Son.' 212
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
proclaimed, the heavenly Father whose reign is near, dawning already in the work of Jesus'." However, a full Christian articulation of this God's being and action is trinitarian in form. What God does in the economy of salvation is the harmonious action of the Father, the Son and the Spirit. This brings us to another major issue in Pannenberg's discussion of the Trinity, the relation between the economic and the immanent Trinity. The economic and the immanent Trinity At issue here is the relation of God to history. The relation of God's transcendence over the course of history and God's immanence in historical reality is basically a problem about the relation between the eternal God (the immanent Trinity) and the God of revelation (the economic Trinity). How is the eternal, essential God related to the history of the created cosmos and, more sharply, how is God affected by what takes place in it? In particular, what is the relation between God as perfectly fulfilled in the mutual relations of the three Persons of the Trinity (the essential, immanent Trinity) and God as self-revealing, selfcommunicating and salvifically active in the world (the economic Trinity)?100 Since for Christian faith there is only one God - and therefore only one Trinity - the answer must be that the economic and the immanent Trinity are one and the same. This changes the question: how is the identity and unity of the immanent and the economic Trinity to be understood? It might well be asked why a disjunction ever occurred between these two ways of thinking about the Trinity. In a formative stage of the development of the doctrine of the Trinity the eternal and essential Trinity 'broke loose from its historical moorings' and came to be regarded as 'untouched by the course of history on account of the eternity and immutability of God, and therefore also inaccessible to all creaturely knowledge'.101 The need to 99
100
ST1,
32.5.
Robert Jenson, echoing Earth's statement that God's deity is event, says, 'God is what happens between Jesus and his Father in their Spirit' and 'God is what happens to Jesus and the world.' R. W. Jenson, Systematic Theology, Vol. i (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 2,2,1. See also The Triune God', in C. E. Braaten and R. W. Jenson (eds.), Christian Dogmatics (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1984), 164-9. 101 STi9 332. 213
GOD AND THE FUTURE
counter the Arian separation of the Son from the Father caused Athanasius to accentuate the difference of the Son (and the Trinity) from the realm of change. Pannenberg regards this whole development as having a decisive and unfortunate impact on the doctrine of God. 'The immanent Trinity became independent of the economic Trinity and increasingly ceased to have any function relative to the economy of salvation.'101 For a long time such a view was not felt to be unduly problematic, but today it is felt to be incompatible with a view of God based on the Scriptures. The problem is how to put together again what had been sundered: God in God's eternal self-identity and God active and revealed in Jesus Christ. In the middle part of the twentieth century both Earth and Rahner made important contributions to solving this problem. Rahner's proposal that 'the economic Trinity is the immanent Trinity and the immanent Trinity is the economic Trinity'103 is an important milestone, but it does not yet address the question of the nature of this identity. It cannot mean absorption of the immanent Trinity in the economic Trinity, for God cannot be absorbed by history, however much God is affected by it.104 If the economy of salvation is the work of God, then it is Godself who is disclosed in it. Pannenberg acknowledges the contribution of Jungel and Moltmann in going beyond Rahner. Jungel stays close to Earth. For him the problem is how to relate God's essence - God's determining in divine freedom to be Father, Son and Spirit - and God's work, which reveals who God is. Jungel says that 'in revelation there comes a precise correspondence of the involution and convolution of the three modes of being in the work of God to "the involution and convolution of the three modes of being in the 102 STi, 332,f. Catherine Mowry LaCugna speaks of an increasing focus on theologia per se, i.e. the interrelationship among the divine persons, and a decreasing attention to the oikonomia, i.e. the whole scheme of God's redemption of created reality, which originally radically altered the way God was thought of; God For Us: The Trinity and Christian Life (San Francisco: Harper, 1991), 2.09^ 103 K. Rahner, The Trinity (London: Burns & Gates, 1970), 2,2.. 104 STi, 33of. Pannenberg here acknowledges the contribution of W. Kasper. A good discussion of the nature of the issue is found in LaCugna, God For Us, 2.16-32..
214
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
essence of God" V 05 God is shown to be a God for whom relationality is part of God's essence. In the history of Jesus Christ God has set Godself in relationship, and this is not extrinsic to God's being.106 Elsewhere Jlingel expresses his agreement with Rahner's Rule: 'God himself takes place in Jesus' God-forsakenness and death.'107 Pannenberg's thinking runs along similar lines. He also finds a lot to agree with in Moltmann. In The Crucified God and later in The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, Moltmann declares his opposition to an 'apathetic' God. Given the conventional understanding of God, he had to speak paradoxically about 'the sufferings of the God who cannot suffer'.108 But he will not think of God apart from the cross; 'the meaning of the cross of the Son on Golgotha reaches right into the heart of the immanent Trinity. From the very beginning, no immanent Trinity and no divine glory is conceivable without "the Lamb who was slain".'109 God is from all eternity the crucified God; 'the pain of the cross determines the inner life of the triune God from eternity to eternity'.110 This radical view leads Moltmann to an ambiguous position. His inclination is to give up the distinction between the immanent and the economic Trinity altogether, for there is no Christian justification for separating a God who is alone and selfsufficient from a God who loves and reconciles a world that is estranged: 'if God is love, then his liberty cannot consist of loving or not loving. On the contrary, his love is his liberty and his liberty is his love.'111 It makes no sense to Moltmann to distinguish the immanent and the economic Trinity in any way in which the first nullifies what the second says. When he adds that the two are on a continuum and merge into each other112 he comes close to dissolving the distinction between them. But he does not quite abandon the two terms, insisting only that there are not two 105
E. Jiingel, The Doctrine of the Trinity: God's Being is in Becoming (Edinburgh Academic Press, 1976), 39; Jiingel's italics. He quotes Earth here. 106 Jiingel, The Doctrine of the Trinity, 61-4, 68, 83. IQ 7 E. Jiingel, God as the Mystery of the World (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1983), 370. 108 Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 2.2. 109 Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 159. 110 Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 161. 111 Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 151. 112 Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 152.. 215
GOD AND THE FUTURE
different Trinities. There is only one, single, divine Trinity and one, single divine history of salvation. The triune God can only appear in history as he is in himself.'113 However, the distinction between the two terms is required by the fact that 'God's relationship to the world has a retroactive effect on his relationship to himself .. .'.II4 Moltmann understands the relation between the immanent and the economic Trinity eschatologically; 'the economic Trinity completes and perfects itself to immanent Trinity when the history and experience of salvation are completed and perfected'.115 Moltmann does not say how this will be so. Nevertheless, on this point his ideas and Pannenberg's coincide closely. A comparison with the trinitarian theology of Robert Jenson may also be useful.116 Like Pannenberg, Jenson sees the disastrous consequences of keeping the immanent Trinity and the economic Trinity apart, in particular the dismissal of the doctrine of the Trinity as abstraction.117 Jenson has several proposals for reshaping the doctrine of the Trinity.118 First, it must be freed from 'captivity to antecedent interpretation of deity as timelessness'. Second, the relation between the immanent and the economic Trinity must be reconsidered, and here he expresses support for Rahner and Jiingel in their identification of the two. However, this identity must be seen as eschatological. The Trinity is 'simply the Father and the man Jesus and their Spirit as the Spirit of the believing community', and this "economic" Trinity 'is eschatologically God "himself", an "immanent" Trinity'. Indeed, 'God is himself only eschatologically, since he is Spirit'. This somewhat puzzling statement is explained by Jenson's view of the Spirit as 'God coming to us from the last future; ... God coming from and as the Kingdom'.119 For Jenson God is not only the agent of the world's transformation, but also the event of its transformation. 113
Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 153. Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, i6of. IJ 5 Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 161. 116 See esp. Robert Jenson, The Triune Identity: God According to the Gospel (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1982.) and The Triune God', 79-191. 117 Jenson, The Triune God', 143^ 118 Jenson, The Triune God', 154-7. The following quotations come from these pages. 119 Jenson, Systematic Theology, Vol. i, 219. 114
216
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
The Spirit effects this event eschatologically. Third, the relations of Father, Son and Spirit must be seen as two-way rather than oneway; Jenson complains of an 'asymmetry' in the trinitarian relations.120 What the Son and the Spirit do has to be seen as 'God-constituting' as much as the work of the Father. Where Pannenberg calls for 'mutuality' in the trinitarian relations, Jenson asks for symmetry. Thus 'future-to-past active relations' must be posited together with the traditional 'past-to-future' active relations. The Spirit's witness to the Son is equally God-constituting with the traditional relations, and the same is true of the Son's and the Spirit's joint reality as 'the openness into which the Father is freed from mere persistence in his pretemporal transcendence'.111 There is much here that is congruent with Pannenberg's ideas. Like Moltmann, however, Jenson is not interested in seeking a philosophical basis for theological claims. He makes no appeal to ideas like the ontological priority of the future or retroactive permanence. Neither Jenson nor Pannenberg thinks that theological claims can be made secure by ideas or principles whether from philosophy or science, or indeed from theology prior to discussing the actual content of the Gospel,111 but Pannenberg, as we noted in chapter three, is more interested in a mutually critical dialogue between theology and philosophy. Pannenberg also acknowledges Jenson's (and Moltmann's) hints of an eschatological solution to the problem of the identity of the immanent and economic Trinity.113 But he wants to show how it is possible to connect 'the eternal self-identity of God with a becoming in time',114 the need for which Rahner and Earth had already seen. It is not enough to speak about a kenosis on the part of God (Rahner), nor simply of the self-definition of God in the death of Jesus (Jiingel) or the grief of the Father at the death of the Son (Moltmann). At the heart of the problem, as Jenson also sees, is the relation between eternity and time, between the eternal triune being of God and the history of the world. For both, the IZO
Jenson, The Triune God', 156. Jenson, The Triune God', 156. I2i Jenson, Systematic Theology, Vol. i, 5, 2.1; Pannenberg, STi, 47. "3 STi, 330. 124 Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 251. 121
217
GOD AND THE FUTURE
reciprocal nature of the trinitarian relations is a critical factor. Without it, what happens in the history of the world can have no effect on the being of God, in spite of faith's sense that God must be affected by what transpired on the cross. For Pannenberg the reciprocal relationships between the Persons of the Trinity give the central salvation-historical events a constitutive significance for God's being, and thus make time and change significant for it. As we saw in the last section, the deity or rule of the Father is not achieved without the Son's incarnate existence and work in the world and the Spirit's activity of bringing the cosmos to its completion. In this connection, Pannenberg's argument that God should not be thought of as a single subject (in three modes of being) but as three Persons - three distinct subjects acting in a 'unity of reciprocal self-dedication'115 - has additional force. Pannenberg's understanding of the concept of 'essence' adds further weight to his argument for the identity of the immanent and the economic Trinity. As eternal, God must be 'high above the perishability of created things'. But God must also be 'an active presence in the reality of the world'.126 Such a claim is grounded in the association of 'essence' with 'relation', notably in Kant and Hegel. For Hegel the concept of relation is implied in the essence of a particular entity. The consequence for theology, in Pannenberg's view, is that 'the divine essence can no longer be thought of as unrelated identity outside the world ... the idea of transcendence itself expresses a relation'.127 This still leaves open the question of the nature of this relation, which has been conceptualised very differently by different thinkers. However, once a world exists God must be in a real relation to it, for it is part of the essence of divine being to be related to that which it transcends. It is still necessary, since God is understood as eternal, to think of God as existing before the world - the corollary of the conclusion that the world owes its existence to the free decision and act of God - but any idea about God's essence and attributes 125 This phrase was coined by Pannenberg quite early to describe Hegel's view of the Trinity. He regards it as an idea of the greatest profundity and vitality;/GM, 182. »« STi, 357 . "7 STi, 367.
2,18
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
as the eternal God must be derived from, and based on, the way God is present in the world.128 This already establishes a significant connection between God's eternal essence and God's salvific activity in the world, which calls for the bringing together of the immanent and the economic Trinity. Pannenberg makes a further point about the concept of 'essence' which has a bearing on the trinitarian identity of God. He argues that the essence of any existing entity can be seen in its unity only in the totality of the moments of its existence; it cannot be discerned fully at any particular moment of its existence. For example, the meaning of a life cannot be determined before its end. In a finite series the last member of the series will determine the essence. In the case of God it means that the essence of God is finally determined only eschatologically. Only at the eschaton will God's eternal essence as Father, Son and Spirit be determined to be identical with the God of the kingdom, announced and anticipated in Jesus and perfected and completed by the Spirit. In other words, the identity of the immanent and the economic Trinity is eschatological. To say that the immanent and the economic Trinity are one and the same means that the eternal God - the same from eternity to eternity - is none other than the God who, in the three trinitarian Persons, is active in the world. Before looking more closely at how this identity is an eschatological reality, let us note what a radical idea this is. At issue is the existence (and essence) of God in relation to the world. In creating the world God has made Godself 'radically dependent on this creation and on its history'.129 The Christian claim is that God is present and active in the world in three modes. God is present in creation as its creator but God does not compel the acknowledgement of this; indeed, creaturely independence turns the creator to a large extent into 'a mere background divinity'.130 In a world marked by brokenness (fallenness) God's deity is upheld in the sending of the Son who effects renewal and reconciliation. In the crucifixion of the Son, I2 8
- Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 2.54. God's existence must be thought of primarily as God's powerful presence in creation; 255. 129 Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 2.55. 130 Pannenberg, 'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', 2.55. 219
GOD AND THE FUTURE
however, that deity is again called into question: where is God in Jesus' God-forsakenness? In the resurrection of Jesus the presence and power of God is once again affirmed. However, redemption is clearly not yet an empirical reality, except - and even here in ambiguity - in the new life of the community that is called into being by the crucified risen Christ and energised by the Spirit. This new life is understood as the Spirit's instalment of the eschatological existence associated with the reign of God in its fulness. If there were to be no such eschatological consummation of God's rule in the world, we would be forced to say that the God who is held to have been revealed in the history of Israel and the life, death and resurrection of Jesus Christ has, after all, no reality. The final outcome will determine the matter; to this extent God has made Godself dependent on the creation and its ultimate end. Only the eschaton can establish the unity of the God who is active in creation and the eternal God, the unity of the economic Trinity and the immanent Trinity. What does this eschatological determination mean? Pannenberg has two answers to this. The first is epistemological; the eschaton will establish the existence of God, which up till then is contestable. We will then see face to face and know fully, as we are fully known (i Cor. 13:12). It will mean the answer to many questions and the end of many doubts. It will also establish the essence of God, what God is like, what God is and does in relation to the world. That God is and what God is will become unambiguously clear. This first point is neither difficult nor controversial. It does, of course, presuppose that God exists. The second sense in which Pannenberg postulates eschatological determination is ontological, and this answer is more problematic. At issue here is the relation of eternity and time and thus the relation of the immanent and the economic Trinity. Here we come up against an antinomy. If, as Pannenberg holds, the events of history 'in some way bear on the identity of [God's] eternal essence',131 God's essence must still be open, at least from the standpoint of temporal reality. But how can God's essence simultaneously be still open and be the eternal divine essence? On the face of it, this is impossible. But there is a crucial qualification: God's essence must be said from within the realm of time to be 131
STi, 334. 2,20
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
open. Yet, in keeping with his determination to avoid the idea of a 'developing' God, a God who becomes God in the course of history, Pannenberg insists that the trinitarian God cannot be 'the result of history'.132 How can these two claims about God - that God is eternally what God is and that the events of history have a bearing on God's being - be held together? How or when or where do they become compatible? For Pannenberg they coincide eschatologically. In other words, the eschaton becomes the 'place' or time at which what is the case in time coincides with what is the case in eternity. As we noted in chapter five, he sees the eschaton as the entrance of God's eternity into time.133 Pannenberg's meaning is indicated in the following key passage: In our historical experience it might seem as if the deity of the God whom Jesus proclaimed is definitively demonstrated only with the eschatological consummation. It might also seem as if materially the deity of God is inconceivable without the consummation of his kingdom. But the eschatological consummation is only the locus of the decision that the trinitarian God is always the true God from eternity to eternity. The dependence of his existence on the eschatological consummation of the kingdom changes nothing in this regard. It is simply necessary to take account of the constitutive significance of this consummation for the eternity of God.134
These lines are as problematic as they are important. Pannenberg is juxtaposing two sets of statements which do not fit together easily. He has been arguing the constitutive importance of the Trinity of salvation history, which culminates in the consummation of the kingdom of God. It is surprising, then, to find him suggesting in the first two sentences of the passage that this is a matter of how it appears to us from our place in history. The point of contrast is not, however, between appearance and reality but between the realms of time and eternity. In the third and fourth sentences the accent is placed on what is eternally the case about God. In reality the triune God is always, from eternity to eternity, the true God; the eternal essence of God does not change. Pannenberg does not see this as negating 'the constitutive I3Z
STi, 331-
'« SeeST 3 ,ch. 15, § 3 ,c. '3<> STi, 331221
GOD AND THE FUTURE
significance' of the eschaton, which he underscores in the final sentence. The eschatological consummation is 'the locus of the decision' that the triune God is the true God, has been all along and will be always. By extension it is the 'locus' of the unity of the Trinity of salvation history and the eternal Trinity. Something is 'decided' in this moment in which eternity and time are connected. The notion of 'decision' is figurative; something is settled or determined; something becomes clear: the God who is 'constituted' by events that take place in history is eternally as so constituted. The sentences that follow the passage quoted show that Pannenberg relies here on the principle of retroactive permanence. The resurrection of Jesus is a parallel case; it not only enables us to know that Jesus of Nazareth was Son of God, but decides that he was Son of God, retroactively.135 Similarly, the deity of God is 'definitively and irrefutably manifested' by the eschatological consummation of God's kingdom,136 with repercussions for all eternity. The essence of God that is established by this event will have been God's essence all along, not simply from that moment on. The reason for this is that God is by definition eternal. The eschaton will not merely make clear that the God of salvation history is the eternal triune God, but will also constitute this identity, and do so retroactively. Without it this would not be God's essential being, but because of it this is God's being from all eternity to all eternity. The principle of retroactive permanence is very important in Pannenberg's argument for the eschatological identity of the economic and the immanent Trinity. Together with his view of the relational nature of the essence of things, this principle is the ontological basis for the claim of the unity of the Trinity of salvation history (in which God's being is dependent on the course of history) and the eternal, immanent Trinity (which is the same through all eternity). Pannenberg relies on this principle in respect of things both human and divine. He first uses it in his discussion of the resurrection of Jesus, but points out that it does 'not involve 135
See also STz, 365, esp. note 12.2,, and 303, note 92.. In the latter note Pannenberg explains the idea of 'retroactive force' or 'retroactive change of significance (and nature)'. 136
STi, 331.
222
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
something unique about the Christ event that would be ontologically incomprehensible' but that it involves 'a matter of universal ontological relevance'.137 The principle comes from Dilthey's 'hermeneutics of historical experience'.138 For Pannenberg the essence of something (its ti en einai) is 'not independent of the events in the light of whose (provisional) conclusion we look back upon it'.139 Thus he moves from his Diltheyan view of the retroactive force of an event at the end of a historical series to conclusions about the eternal essence of Jesus as Son of God (through the resurrection) and the identity of the economic and the immanent Trinity (through the eschaton). Pannenberg argues (plausibly, in my view) that the essence of a finite entity is determined by its future, but can it be extended to God? If it is a fundamental ontological principle it should apply to God no less than to finite beings. However, it is even more true of God, as eternal, that what is God's being at any time is God's being at all times. Notwithstanding the force of the argument, Pannenberg's claim that the eternal being of God is dependent on what happens in the history of the world is no ordinary claim. He does not want a God who 'develops' in history; nor a God who is untouched by events in time. He argues for a view of God whose eternal being is established retroactively from the point where eternity and time meet. The underlying issue is again the relation between eternity and time. As against the popular idea that time is the realm of change and eternity is changelessness, Pannenberg sees their relation differently; eternity is 'the presence of the totality of life'.140 It is presupposed by the disjunction of moments of time, not its opposite. As eternal, God must be present to every moment in time, as well as having the whole of time present to Godself. In his criticism of Nelson Pike's God and Timelessness, Pannenberg puts his finger on an idea which is a barrier to understanding his own thought. We may think that God 'takes up a temporal position' even though God is immortal and imperishable.141 This would 137
138
/GM, I 3 6 .
STi, 303, note 92. 5T2, 303. See also 'Being and Time', M/G, esp. 71-7. *4° STi,4o3. *** 5TT, 4 o 5 . 139
223
GOD AND THE FUTURE
make God different before and after an event in history which affects God, as happens with finite beings. But this would ignore the eternity of God, in which all events affecting God are present to God all at once. Thus, if God as the Trinity of salvation history is involved in contingent historical events which affect God's very being, such events will affect God's eternal being, the immanent Trinity. The Christian doctrine of God must do equal justice to God's transcendence and immanence, to God's eternity and God's relation to time. For God to be God, God's being must be thought of as infinite, the antithesis of all that is limited and transitory. God is not part of a finite series of entities, but their creator. Two aspects of God's relation to the world of time and space should be differentiated yet kept together, God's difference from creaturely temporality and the incorporation of creatures into God's eternal present.142 The unity-in-distinction of the immanent and the economic Trinity enables each of these aspects to receive its due. The immanent Trinity is the essential deity of God, the God who does not need a cosmos in order to be more fully God. The economic Trinity is God working as the trinitarian Persons in the economy of salvation, with a view to incorporating the cosmos into the glory of God, granting it eternal life, and establishing the rule of God in it through the overcoming of all evil and suffering. When this salvific, 'divinising' work is complete, the identity of the immanent Trinity and the Trinity active in the economy of salvation will be established and unambiguously known. Then will it be clear that the God of salvation, the economic Trinity, is the eternal triune God, who created and permeates all things. It will be clear beyond doubt that the world is the creation of God, redeemed by God from its brokenness and brought to its consummation in God's kingdom. Pannenberg concludes his discussion of God, in the first and third volumes of Systematic Theology, with a focus on the love of God. The doctrine of the Trinity is an articulation of the statement that God is love. This denotes first the mutual love of the Persons of the Trinity, but extends to the unfolding of this trinitarian love in the economy of salvation.143 The entire work ends on the same '4* STi, 407. x
*3 STi, 446-8.
224
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
note; from the beginning of creation to its eschatological consummation the economy of salvation manifests the divine love. From this love God moves beyond the divine self-sufficiency to the creation, reconciliation and perfection of a finite 'other', and grants it participation in the unity of God's trinitarian life. As Pannenberg says at the end of the concluding paragraph, not without poetic flair, 'the distinction and unity of the immanent and economic Trinity constitute the heartbeat of the divine love, and with a single such heartbeat this divine love encompasses the whole world of creatures'.144 The seal of God's futurity Before concluding this chapter we shall consider some criticisms of Pannenberg's trinitarian theology and ask whether the doctrine of the Trinity is the culmination of his entire future-oriented theological system. Most of the criticisms predate the publication of the full three volumes of Systematic Theology. In his outline of Pannenberg's system, Stanley Grenz raises some questions about the doctrine of the Trinity and about eschatology.145 Pannenberg's emphasis on the three Persons of the Trinity was bound to attract the charge of tritheism. This criticism has more merit than the opposite criticism that for Pannenberg God is not three Persons but one.146 Pannenberg avoids tritheism by his emphasis on reciprocity in the trinitarian relations and by his belief that none of the persons of the Trinity is a divine subject in isolation from the other two.147 Similarly, the criticism that Pannenberg's view of the Trinity is an extreme form of the Latin view is demonstrably 144
ST3, 646. S. J. Grenz, Reason for Hope (Oxford University Press, 1990), esp. chs 5 &; 6. The work predates the publication of Vols 2 & 3 of Systematic Theology and is based on earlier drafts. 146 Grenz, Reason for Hope, 70; cf. 231, note 40 in respect of W. J. Hill's criticism, expressed in The Three-personed God (Washington: Catholic University Press, 1981), 162-6. No-one reading the Systematic Theology could come to Hill's conclusion. 147 R. Olson seems to support Pannenberg's emphasis on the distinct personhood of each of the trinitarian Persons, but questions 'the reservation of God's perfect unity to the final future'; 'Wolfhart Pannenberg's Doctrine of the Trinity', Scottish Journal of Theology 43.2, 1990, 202. This is a misunderstanding. The eschatological reality is the unity of the economic and the immanent Trinity. 145
22.5
GOD AND THE FUTURE
ill-founded.148 Pannenberg's view of the Trinity is much closer to the Eastern view, which has its starting-point in the three Persons of the Trinity. On the question of Pannenberg's closeness to Hegel in his trinitarian thinking, Grenz rightly points out that Pannenberg's appreciation of Hegel's trinitarian thought is finely differentiated, that one may legitimately speak of a link between history and God without implying a fusion between them, and that Pannenberg never relies on Hegel's thought alone.149 C. Venema criticises Pannenberg for making God's reality 'dependent upon the existence of the world',150 but Pannenberg makes it quite clear that such a statement can only be made in the light of creation. Only once a universe exists does God's lordship necessarily mean God's lordship in relation to it. The same writer's charge that Pannenberg 'does not so much as consider the significance of the Christian tradition's understanding of God's trinitarian being' is not only nullified by the Systematic Theology but was already untrue when it was made. Much of the criticism of Pannenberg's trinitarian thought is discounted by his subsequent published work, but this does not apply to all criticisms. There are three main areas of criticism or question. The first of these is about the consistency of Pannenberg's doctrine of God. Does he work with a single, coherent concept of God? This cannot be a question about the compatibility of a trinitarian and a monotheistic view of God. Pannenberg recognises well enough the need to do justice to both. He sees the doctrine of the Trinity as 'concrete monotheism in contrast to notions of an abstract transcendence of the one God and abstract notions of a divine unity that leaves no place for plurality'.151 Several commentators have felt a degree of tension between two different concepts of God. A. Glasser speaks of two concepts of God which compete with each other in Pannenberg's theology: the triune God of Christian faith and the God who is the power of the future or of history, who brings all things together in a totality of the 148
See Grenz, Reason for Hope, 2,31, note 42. 49 Grenz, Reason for Hope, 72.. 150 C. P. Venema, 'History, Human Freedom and the Idea of God in the Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Calvin Theological Journal 17, April 1982,75. <5' STi, 335 f. X
216
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
divine.152 This criticism is not justified, and the critic makes no reference at all to the Systematic Theology. It is clear from the second and third volumes, particularly in the discussion of creation and eschatology, that it is precisely the triune God who works in creation and brings all things into unity. Grenz and Olson see a different tension in Pannenberg's doctrine of God, between a general philosophical view of God and a theological view of God as personal. 'Does the imagery of God as the divine field working upon the world from the future allow us to conceive of God as truly personal?'153 This is a fair question, but the answer is clear. In Pannenberg's view of the Trinity, God is personal by virtue of the personhood of the three Persons of the Trinity; indeed, they are persons in the highest sense. In addition, in Pannenberg's view the divine essence, when viewed as a 'field', 'can find equal manifestation in all three persons'.154 Thus there need be no incongruity between the idea of God as 'field' and the idea of God as personal; the doctrine of the Trinity is the mediating idea. Pannenberg holds that the Spirit is both a Person of the Trinity and 'the force field of their fellowship that is distinct from them both'.155 As a field, the Spirit would be impersonal, but the Spirit 'also stands over against the Father and the Son as his own center of action'.156 This presupposes the Spirit's nature as personal. Although the question is reasonable, there is no equivocation in Pannenberg's position. Perhaps, on the analogy of human persons, it is not difficult to see how a person may be the centre of a considerable field of force. A second area of criticism concerns the relation between God and the world. Grenz and Olson voice a concern whether Pannenberg's theology of the freedom of God in relation to the world is adequately conceived.157 This may be related to the charge that Pannenberg is too much the pupil of Hegel, to which reference 152
A. Glasser, Verweigerte Partnerschaft? (Regensburg: Verlag Friedrich Pustet, 1991), 169. 153 S. J. Grenz and R. E. Olson, 'The Transcendence of the Future: The Theology of Hope', ch. 6 of Twentieth Century Theology: God and the World in a Transitional Age (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1992,), 199. "< STi, 3 8 3 . '« 5X1,383. *56 5Ti, 3 8 3 f. 157 Grenz and Olson, The Transcendence of the Future', 199. 227
GOD AND THE FUTURE
was made before. T. Bradshaw, while accepting that what happens within history has an impact on God, is critical of the idea of a God too closely involved in this realm of change. For him God must be 'complete and wholly stable in his identity'; otherwise God cannot be the Lord of history. His criticism is that Pannenberg's 'historicised trinitarianism' subjects God to too much change.158 But how much change is 'too much'? And how much room for change in God can there be if God must be 'wholly stable in his identity'? Bradshaw compares God's presence in creation to an artist's presence in a work of art,159 but artists can be profoundly affected by interaction with their work. Bradshaw misses the real issue. One of Pannenberg's achievements is the creation of an ontology in which temporality is integral. His doctrine of the Trinity, particularly the relation between the economic and immanent Trinity, enables him to do justice to God's freedom in relation to history and God's involvement in it. In addition, his axiom that once there is a cosmos God's deity can only be established in relation to it - while affirming that God was under no necessity to create a world - is, in my view, incontrovertible. This criticism concerns Pannenberg's view of the relation between the economic and the immanent Trinity. This distinction enables us to hold together God's transcendence and immanence. It safeguards God's oneness with the divine action in history and God's being as more than the process of this action. J. O'Donnell acknowledges Pannenberg's endeavour to 'avoid the Scylla and Charybdis of a becoming God a la Hegel and an eternal immutable God a la St Thomas', but finds Pannenberg 'dangerously close to process theology with its finite God'.l6° Since Pannenberg explicitly rejects such a view of God, the criticism must be that he falls into this despite his best intentions. The key issue for O'Donnell is the nature of God's essence. He opts for a more classical view, in which God's essence has nothing to do with the fulfilment of God's history with the world.161 For Pannenberg, however, relationality is an inextricable part of God's being. Z 8
5 T. Bradshaw, 'God's Relationship to History in Pannenberg', Scottish Bulletin of Evangelical Theology', Special Study 3, 1989, 66. *59 Bradshaw, 'God's Relationship to History in Pannenberg', 66f. 160 J. O'Donnell, 'Pannenberg's Doctrine of God', Gregorianum 72.1, 1991, 95f. 161 O'Donnell, 'Pannenberg's Doctrine of God', 96.
2,28
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
R. Olson's criticism that Pannenberg reserves God's perfect unity to the final future also fails.162 This is to misunderstand the principle of retroactive permanence. To speak of God's eternal essence at all is to see all time as simultaneously present to God. If the eschaton establishes God's rule over the creation, God's being will turn out to have been eternally what it is then, from a standpoint in time, established to be. What will be established at the eschaton is the unity of the immanent and the economic Trinity. The third area of criticism concerns the trinitarian relations. Some critics are uneasy about Pannenberg's emphasis on the reciprocal nature of the relations between the Persons of the Trinity. O'Donnell thinks that he has gone too far; these relations must be seen (as the Fathers saw them) as 'relations of origin'. He acknowledges the reciprocity between the Persons of the Trinity but 'some relationships are unilateral'. The Son receives his hypostasis from the Father, not the converse. He concludes that 'neither the scriptures nor the tradition warrant an unrestricted mutuality of relationships in the Trinity'.163 Several things can be said about this criticism. First, Pannenberg is not opposed to the idea of relations of origin in the Trinity. What he opposes is the exclusive view of the trinitarian relations in terms of relations of origin.164 Against the traditional view of the Father as the origin and fount of deity for the Son and the Spirit, he takes up Athanasius' view that the Father cannot be the Father without the Son. 'Does that not mean that in some way the deity of the Father has to be dependent on the relation to the Son, although not in the same way as that of the Son is on the relation to the Father? The Father is not begotten of the Son or sent by him. These relations are irreversible.'165 Pannenberg does not assert that the relations between the trinitarian Persons are symmetrical. But it is one-sided to consider only the dependence of the Son and the Spirit on the Father, as when the focus is exclusively on the relations of origin. Account must be taken of the Father's handing over of power and rule to the Son, since this also defines the relation between the Father and the Son. The Father 162
See note 147 above. O'Donnell, 'Pannenberg's Doctrine of God', 96. 4 STi, 319. 16 5 STi, 312. 16 3 16
22,9
GOD AND THE FUTURE
not only begets the Son, but also makes himself dependent on the Son. Second, O'Donnell sees the root of the problem in Pannenberg's way of relating the eternal and the temporal, in particular 'his proclivity to make the immanent Trinity dependent on the economic'.166 This is at the core of Pannenberg's understanding of God, together with a good many of his contemporaries. O'Donnell's loyalty to Aquinas makes him unwilling to see God as being in too close a relation to history. At issue here is a fundamental conflict of philosophical and theological vision. The whole of Pannenberg's philosophical and theological thought is devoted to the articulation of a different view of the relation of time and eternity. Finally, it must be asked whether the doctrine of the Trinity really constitutes the fullest expression of the eschatological theology that was Pannenberg's hallmark from his earliest writings. Is the doctrine of the Trinity the culmination of this eschatological theology or is there a theological gap between his early and late work? At the beginning of this chapter a significant sentence from an early essay was quoted: 'the doctrine of the Trinity is the seal of the pure futurity of God'.167 This futurity has to do with the drawing of the creation into the reign of the Father through the Son and the Spirit. This future, the kingdom of God, into which the whole creation is to be taken up, is described in trinitarian terms. It is the rule of the Father, through the obedient service of the Son, who hands back to the Father what has been committed to him, and through the Spirit, who works in the world to bring it to its consummation and its reconciliation with God. This trinitarian vision was hinted at in the 1965 essay. The trinitarian theology of the Systematic Theology is the development of the same vision. The earlier theology of the coming kingdom of God and the later theology of the eschatological unity of the economic and the immanent Trinity are essentially of a piece. This continuity can be briefly illustrated. The material identity of the theology of the kingdom of God and the trinitarian doctrine of God is clear in Pannenberg's system, particularly in the second and third volumes of Systematic Theology. In a fine phrase Grenz describes the kingdom of God, which he sees as foundational for 166 O'Donnell, 'Pannenberg's Doctrine of God', 96. 167 See note 5 above. 230
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
Pannenberg, as 'the glory of the Trinity demonstrated in God's rulership over creation'.168 This divine rule is the work of the three Persons of the Trinity, as the chapters of Systematic Theology make clear. It is particularly clear in the doctrine of creation itself, which includes the creation of the cosmos, its preservation and consummation. The rule of God also includes the reconciliation of the world and the election of a people with whom to have fellowship; this is discussed under the doctrine of reconciliation and the doctrine of the church. Finally, the rule of God over the world includes the consummation of creation in the kingdom of God, which is discussed in explicitly trinitarian terms under the doctrine of the end, or eschatology in its narrower sense. We shall amplify these observations and look briefly at the major doctrines, in terms of their relation to the kingdom of God and their trinitarian articulation. First, the kingdom of God, God's rule over creation, presupposes the creation of the universe itself. As we noted in chapter five, Pannenberg sees the work of creation as the work of the three Persons of the Trinity, while remaining the action of the one God. This action of God in relation to the world is 'not wholly different from the action in his trinitarian life. In his action in relation to the world the trinitarian life turns outward, moves out of itself, and becomes the determinative basis of relations between the Creator and the creatures.'169 The creation of the cosmos derives from Gods freedom in the trinitarian life, which is nothing other than the expression of the love of God. At its core, this love is the love of the Father for the Son, in whom he loves all creatures. They are 'objects of the Father's love as they are drawn into his eternal turning to the Son'.170 The independence of creaturely existence has its basis in the self-distinction of the Son from the Father. However, creatures are not only distinct from each other and from God; they are also related to each other and to God. It is the Spirit's work to grant them fellowship with God, which looks beyond present possibilities. 'When the divine action produces finite creatures that are subject to temporal and temporally limited relations, it produces finite events and beings in the nexus of a 168 16
Grenz, Reason for Hope, 2.16.
9 5T2,
170
5.
ST2, 21.
231
GOD AND THE FUTURE
temporal sequence in which their existence is referred to a future fulfilment.'171 This foreshadows the eschatological consummation of creation which is nothing other than the kingdom of God. We may conclude, then, that Pannenberg's doctrine of creation is developed in concert with the idea of the eschatological rule of God and explicitly articulated in trinitarian terms.172 Second, the doctrine of reconciliation is presented as an action of the three Persons of the Trinity, not simply as the mediatorial action of Jesus Christ.173 Reconciliation is not restricted to the history of Jesus but extends to what happens in the present. It has its basis in the action of the Father, who intends the reconciliation of a world which, in its separation from God, experiences brokenness. According to the New Testament, the Father 'gave up' his Son, but there is also a self-giving on the part of the Son. The action of the Father does 'not make the Son a mere object but implies his active cooperation'. Neither does the action of the Son 'rule out the fact that the initiative in the event lies with the Father'.174 What the Son does for the reconciliation of the world to God is at the centre of the work of reconciliation. It includes the historical work and fate of Jesus, who proclaims the coming kingdom of God and goes to the cross for it. But this history is also the work of the eternal Son, who becomes human in the person of Jesus. Finally, reconciliation is the work of the exalted Lord who is active in the apostolic proclamation of this history as salvific. However, reconciliation has an anticipatory structure, for the world is not yet fully reconciled with its creator. Whilst reconciliation has its centre in the ministry and death of Jesus, it includes the eschatological reconciliation of all things with God, in which the kingdom of God comes to its fulness. This is the realm of the Spirit, in whose activity the world is given a share. 'Through the Spirit reconciliation with God no longer comes upon us solely from outside. We ourselves enter into it.'175 In this participation the Spirit enables us to enter into the relation of Jesus to the Father, which liberates us from sin and frees us for a new 171
ST2, 7 The trinitarian form of the doctrine of creation is clearest in STz, ch.y, esp. I.§3~4 & II.§2. z ?3 See ST2, 437-54. I7Z
'74 ST2, I7
439.
5 5X2,450.
232
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
relationship with God, who thus becomes our Father. The Spirit completes our reconciliation with God by enabling us through faith in Jesus Christ to accept our own finite existence before God.'176 This is already in part the experience of those who live 'in Christ'. But its full measure is the eschatological reality awaited from the future, when God reigns in and over all things. Again, from this overview of the doctrine of reconciliation it is clear that the kingdom of God and the work of the Trinity are inseparable. Third, the doctrine of the church is seen in the same terms. The kingdom of God is not only a reality in the future; it is already anticipated in communities in which there is koinonia with God and with other people. Such fellowship 'provisionally and symbolically represents the world-embracing fellowship of the kingdom of God that is the goal of reconciliation'.177 This is to speak of the church, which signifies and provisionally expresses the humanity that is reconciled in the kingdom of God. Just as the work of creation involves both the Son and the Spirit, so the creation of the church is the work of the Son and the Spirit. 'The christological and pneumatological constitution of the church do not exclude each other but belong together, because the Son and the Spirit mutually indwell one another as trinitarian persons.'178 The church has its ground in Jesus Christ, not itself. However, it is inadequate to see the existence of the church solely in his will and direct action; it requires pneumatological mediation. The church is thus the creation of the Spirit in so far as it is the creation of the exalted Christ through the word of the Gospel. The link between the Spirit and the church refers not only to the church's origin, but also to the eschatological future of the kingdom of God. The church is the anticipation of the kingdom of God, its provisional representation.179 No doctrine of the church is adequate if it does not have in view the new humanity, the renewed people of God, which shares in the Son's relation to the Father. The church should see itself more as the eschatological community, the anticipatory sign of the coming kingdom of God. The sacraments strongly express this eschatological character, '* <77 '78 '7»
STz, 454. 5T2, 4 6af. 5T3, i6f. 573,10,31. 2-33
GOD AND THE FUTURE
especially the eucharist. The church is the people of God, the body of Christ, the community of the Spirit, the provisional sign of the kingdom of God. Again, as in the doctrines of creation and reconciliation, the Trinity and the eschatological rule of God are inextricably connected in the doctrine of the church. Finally, we would expect the unity of the themes of the Trinity and the kingdom of God to be most clearly evident in the doctrine of the end, the eschatological consummation of all things. For the kingdom of God is nothing other than the glory of the Trinity, demonstrated in God's rule over the whole creation. From the eschaton we await the coming of God to the fulness of divine rule over the creation.180 The kingdom of God is the completion and perfection of the creation. The divine economy of salvation, centred on the Son, is not yet complete with the sending and death of the Son, but arrives at its goal only with the work of the Spirit. For the Spirit witnesses to, and glorifies, the Son in the hearts of believers, and with the Son the Father who acts through him. In the eschaton the Spirit will transform our mortal lives into the new life of the resurrection of the dead. Finally, the life-giving Spirit will overcome the transience of the cosmos and transform it into the new creation.181 The Spirit does not work in isolation from the Son; he will 'come in glory to judge the living and the dead'.182 The return of Christ signifies his lordship. This lordship, in turn, is not in competition with that of the Father but serves to establish it.183 The work of the Spirit can be encapsulated in the notion of glorification.184 The creation is glorified in its participation in God's glory, and God is glorified in the new resurrection life of the creation; both are the Spirit's work. The same Spirit who grants believers a participation in Jesus' relation to the Father 'draws them into the eternal fellowship of the Father and the Son'.185 The kingdom of God is thus the glorification of the triune God in the cosmos. This implies the vindication of God in the face of evil and suffering. Only the eschatological consummation of creation can 180 181 182
ST3, 517-
ST 3 ,55i. Pannenberg discusses the judgment and the return of Christ in ch. 15, §4 608-30. 183 5T3, 608. 184 ST , 623f. 3 185
ST3, 3, 626.
234
THE REIGN OF THE TRIUNE GOD
provide the conclusive demonstration of the existence of God, the nature of God, and God's ways of working in the world. Only this will establish incontestibly the deity of God, and only then will the creation of the universe be seen unambiguously as an expression of the love of God, with which God has accompanied creation every step of the way and in which God will finally grant it participation in the divine glory. Thus the kingdom of God and the glory of the Trinity coincide exactly. The focus of this chapter has been on Pannenberg's strongly trinitarian doctrine of God, articulated comprehensively in the three volumes of Systematic Theology. The roots of this trinitarian theology go back to his early writings. An explicitly trinitarian theology makes its appearance in the three important essays of the mid-1970s. We then noted major elements of Pannenberg's doctrine of the Trinity, in particular the points on which he develops a position of his own. Notable among these is the emphasis on reciprocity in the intratrinitarian relations. Without losing sight of the divine activity as the work of one God, Pannenberg consistently describes this as the activity of the three Persons of the Trinity, steering clear of the peril of tritheism. A major theme is God's relation to the course of history and its effect on God's being. In comparing Pannenberg's distinctive approach to this theme - in terms of the distinction but ultimate identity of the immanent and the economic Trinity - with those of major contemporary theologians, his innovative and penetrating theological work became evident. The principle of retroactive permanence, on which his argument for the eschatological identity of the immanent and the economic Trinity depends, bears a good deal of the weight of his whole system. In considering the main criticisms of Pannenberg's doctrine of the Trinity - many of which do not take into account its completed presentation Pannenberg's position was able to be defended. Finally, crucial to the whole book, we asked whether the doctrine of the Trinity puts the seal on Pannenberg's entire eschatological theology, or whether it is related to his theological system only extrinsically. It is clear, from a brief survey of several key areas of doctrine, that the theology of the eschatological kingdom of God and the theology of the Trinity coincide. Though the former is the keynote of Pannenberg's early theology and the latter is the central theme of the later work, he has skilfully 235
GOD AND THE FUTURE
superimposed the trinitarian theology on to his theology of the divine futurity. This is not to suggest that the trinitarian theology is an afterthought. Perhaps it is more accurate to say that he has fused together two aspects of the Christian doctrine of God which are more typically kept apart: the principle that God's being is God's rule and the belief that God is a community of three divine Persons, yet one God. The kingdom of God is indeed the glory of the Trinity, demonstrated in God's eschatological rule over all created things.
z36
Postscript
I
t is clear from the foregoing chapters that I regard Pannenberg as a theologian of great stature, fully deserving the attention which his work has attracted over the past four decades. I have considered the impact on Pannenberg's doctrine of God of his belief that God cannot properly be thought of apart from God's rule over all created things, that is, apart from the kingdom of God. His principle that 'God's being is God's rule' is far-reaching. God does not need a world of finite entities, but if there is such a world God must ultimately have power over it; this belongs to the very notion of 'God' in monotheistic religion. The world does not yet show itself unambiguously to be the creation of such a God or as a world over which such a God has power. If such power is to be both established and incontestably clear - when all things are subjected to God and God is 'all in all' (i Cor. 15:28), and when we shall know fully as we are fully known (i Cor. 13:11) - it must come from the eschatological future. Pannenberg arrives at this conclusion on the basis of his study of Jesus' message of the kingdom of God, supported by considerations from the philosophy of religion. Jesus' message was about an eschatological salvation which had already come within reach. It was truly a case of the future having arrived! But the tension between a reality that is 'already' present and one that has 'not yet' arrived remains an ineradicable feature of the Christian gospel. Through the six chapters of the book I have identified some major streams in Pannenberg's thought, beginning with his approach to eschatology and its decisive role in shaping his whole theology. I concluded that Pannenberg is on firm ground in his view of apocalyptic and in his assessment of its importance for understanding the message and ministry of Jesus and his resurrection from the dead. One of the aspects of apocalyptic that has abiding value is its idea that history forms a whole. This idea was then explored in terms of Pannenberg's 'ontology of the whole', which is the basis for his far-reaching thinking about the priority of the future. Although this is the most speculative part of the book, Pannenberg sees this speculation as implied in Jesus' 237
GOD AND THE FUTURE
understanding of God's coming rule and his resurrection from the dead. The speculation is nothing if not bold, and it defies easy assessment. In the final chapters this thinking about the future was explicitly related to God's being and action, which led to an examination of Pannenberg's thinking about God and time and the counter-intuitive idea of creation from the future. These themes were finally articulated in the powerful trinitarian terms that characterise Pannenberg's major work, Systematic Theology. In this area he has made, by any standards, a very important contribution to the current discussion of trinitarian theology. Like any writer, I have explored Pannenberg's work through the lens of my own interests, generally describable under the heading of eschatology. Many important areas of theology have not been considered, in particular the theological ethics that are based on this theological system. Whilst I cannot hope to have done justice to the range and depth of Pannenberg's thought, I do hope to have demonstrated why he is regarded as one of the leading theologians of his time and why his work has attracted attention from scholars in every tradition and every part of the world. In my view, he exemplifies the role of the public theologian. The entire body of his writing is devoted to the task of unfolding and explaining the Christian confession of God's triune being and works, grounded in the history of Jesus and opening up new possibilities for the world in the Spirit. He supports this confession by showing its coherence with claims made by thinkers ancient and modern and in many fields of enquiry. He is a theologian formed by the great tradition of Christian thought, who defends it, sometimes criticises it, and offers exciting reformulations of major issues within it. He would be the first to acknowledge the provisionality of his (and all) theology. The price of boldness in thinking is that some will think it too daring or too conjectural. Indeed, it is not without its problems, and it is too early to tell whether its ideas about the priority of the future might be the beginning of an eventual paradigm shift. It is not hard to believe that seeing things as the anticipation of their future essence, rather than as merely the outcome of their past, might throw new light on old habits of thought. The gaps and problems in Pannenberg's work do not, however, diminishes its importance. It is innovative and comprehensive in unusual degree. It is likely that he will be recognised as one of the great teachers and defenders of the Christian faith of the twentieth century. 238
Bibliography Works by Wolfliart Pannenberg /. Books
Anthropology in Theological Perspective. Trans. Matthew J. O'Connell. Philadelphia: Westminster; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1985. A translation of Anthropologie in theologischer Perspektive. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1983. The Apostles' Creed in the Light of Today's Questions. Trans. Margaret Kohl. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1972. A translation of Das Glaubensbekenntnis ausgelegt und veranttvortet vor den Fragen der Gegenwart. Hamburg: Siebenstern Taschenbuch Verlag, 1972. Basic Questions in Theology. Vol. i. Trans. George H. Kehm. Philadelphia: Westminster Press; London: SCM Press, 1970. A translation of pages i-201 of Grundfragen systematischer Theologie, Bd i. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1967. Basic Questions in Theology. Vol. 2. Trans. George H. Kehm. Philadelphia: Westminster Press; London: SCM Press, 1971. A translation of pages 202-398 of Grundfragen systematischer Theologie, Bd i. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck &t Ruprecht, 1967. Basic Questions in Theology. Vol. 3. Trans. R. A. Wilson. London: SCM Press, 1973. A translation of material from Terror und Spiel: Problems der Mythenrezeption. Wilhelm Fink Verlag, Miinchen, 1971, and Gottesgedanke und Menschliche Freiheit. Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, Gottingen, 1972. Also published as The Idea of God and Human Freedom. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1973. Christian Spirituality and Sacramental Community. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1983. Christianity in a Secularized World. Trans. John Bowden. London: SCM Press, 1988. Translated from Christentum in einer sakularisierten Welt. Freiburg: Verlag Herder, 1988. The Church. Trans. Keith Crim. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1983. A translation of Part 2 of Ethik und Ekklesiologie. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1977.
239
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Ethics. Trans. Keith Grim. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1981. A translation of Part i of Ethik und Ekklesiologie. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1977. Faith and Reality. Trans. John Maxwell. London: Search Press, 1977. A translation of Glaube und Wirklichkeit. Miinchen: Chr. Kaiser Verlag, 1975Grundfragen systematischer Theologie, Band 2,. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1980. Human Nature, Election, and History. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1977. An Introduction to Systematic Theology. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1991. Jesus - God and Man. Trans. Lewis L. Wilkins and Duane A. Priebe. London: SCM Press, 1968. A translation of Grundzuge der Christologie. Giitersloh: Gerd Mohn, 1964. The znd English edn. of 1976 is a translation of the 5th German edn. The only difference is an afterword, 399-410. Metaphysics and the Idea of God. Trans. Philip Clayton. Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1990; Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1991. A translation of Metaphysik und Gottesgedanke. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988. Revelation as History, with Rolf Rendtorff, Trutz Rendtorff, & Ulrich Wilkens. Trans. David Granskou. New York: Macmillan, 1968. A translation of Offenbarung als Geschichte. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1961. Systematic Theology. Vol. i. Trans. Geoffrey W. Bromiley. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1991. A translation of Systematische Theologie, Band i. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988. Systematic Theology. Vol. z. Trans. Geoffrey W. Bromiley. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1994. A translation of Systematische Theologie, Band 2. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1991. Systematic Theology. Vol. 3. Trans. Geoffrey W. Bromiley. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1998. A translation of Systematische Theologie, Band 3. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1993. Theology and the Kingdom of God, ed. Richard John Neuhaus. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1969. Theology and the Philosophy of Science. Trans. Francis McDonagh. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1976. A translation of Wissenschaftstheorie und Theologie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1973240
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Toward a Theology of Nature: Essays on Science and Faith, ed. Ted Peters. Louisville, Kentucky: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1993. What Is Man? Contemporary Anthropology in Theological Perspective. Trans. Duane A. Priebe. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1970. A translation of Was ist der Mensch? Die Anthropologie der Gegenwart im Lichte der Theologie, 2. Auflage, Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1964. ii. Articles and Chapters 'An Autobiographical Sketch', Carl E. Braaten, and Philip Clayton (eds.), The Theology ofWolfhart Pannenberg. Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1988, 11-18. 'Analogic', Galling, Kurt et al. Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, Band I, 3. Auflage. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 1957, cols 350-3. 'Antwort auf G. Sauters Uberlegungen', Evangelische Theologie 40.2, March-April 1980, 169-81. 'Appearance as the Arrival of the Future', Journal of the American Academy of Religion 35, 1967, 107-18. Also published in M. E. Marty and D. G. Peerman, (eds.), New Theology No. 5. New York: Macmillan, 1968, 112-29, and m Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, ed. R. J. Neuhaus. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1969, ch. 4. 'Atom, Duration, Form: Difficulties with Process Philosophy', trans. J. C. Robertson and G. Vallee, Process Studies, 14.1, Spring 1984, 21-30. 'Die Auferstehung Jesu und die Zukunft des Menschen', Kerygma und Dogma 24, 1978, 104-17. Trans. M. B. Jackson, The Cumberland Seminarian 19.2 and 3, Winter and Spring 1981, 41-51. 'Ein Briefwechsel zwischen Wolfhart Pannenberg und Gerhard Ebeling' [with G. Ebeling], Zeitschrift fur Theologie und Kirche, 70.4, 1973, 448-73. 'Can Christianity Do Without an Eschatology?', in G. B. Caird et al. The Christian Hope. Theological Collections 13, London: SPCK, 1970, 2-5-34'Christentum und Platonismus; Die kritische Platonrezeption Augustins in ihrer Bedeuting fur das gegenwartige christliche Denken', Zeitschrift fur Kirchengeschichte 96.2, 1985, 147-61. 'The Christological Foundation of Christian Anthropology', in Claude Geffre (ed.), Humanism and Christianity (Concilium 6.9), New York Herder & Herder, 1973, 86-100. The Church and the Eschatological Kingdom', in W. Pannenberg, Avery Dulles and Carl E. Braaten, Spirit, Faith, and Church. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1970, ch. 6. 241
GOD AND THE FUTURE
'Constructive and Critical Functions of Christian Eschatology', Harvard Theological Review 77.2, 1984, 119-39. 'A Dialogue About Process Philosophy' [with Lewis S. Ford], Encounter 38, 1977, 318-24. The Doctrine of Creation and Modern Science', East Asian Journal of Theology 4, 1986, 33-46. A version of this is also in Ted Peters (ed.), Cosmos as Creation: Theology and Science in Consonance. Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1989, ch. 4, 152-76. It is also ch. 2 in Toward a Theology of Nature, 1993. 'The Doctrine of the Spirit and the Task of a Theology of Nature', Theology 75.619, January 1972, 8-21. A translation of this by John Maxwell, entitled 'The Spirit of Life', is ch. 3 of Faith and Reality, 1977. It is also published as ch. 5 in Toward a Theology of Nature, 1993. 'Facts of History and Christian Ethics', Dialog 8, 1969, 287-96. 'Feminine Language About God?', The Asbury Theological journal 48.2, Fall 1993, 27-9. 'Future and Unity', in Ewert H. Cousins (ed.), Hope and the Future of Man. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1972, 60-78. 'Geist gegen Zeitgeist: Gesprach mit dem Theologen Wolfhart Pannenberg', Evangelische Kommentare 5/95. 'God's Presence in History', The Christian Century, March u 1981, 260-3. 'Gott (Theologiegeschichtlich)', in Kurt Galling et al. Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, Band II, 3. Auflage. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 1958, cols. 1717-32. 'Der Gott der Geschichte: Der trinitarische Gott und die Wahrheit der Geschichte', Kerygma und Dogma 23.2, 1977, 76-92. Trans. M. B. Jackson, The Cumberland Seminarian 19.2-3, Winter and Spring 1981, 28-41. 'Hermeneutics and Universal History', in History and Hermeneutic (Journal for Theology and the Church) 4, ed. Robert W. Funk and Gerhard Ebeling; New York: Harper & Row, 1967, 122-52. Also published in a slightly different translation in Basic Questions in Theology, Vol. i, 1970, 96-136. 'Jesus' History and Our History', Perspectives in Religious Studies, i, Fall 1974, 134-42,. 'A Liberal Logos Christology: The Christology of John B. Cobb', in David Ray Griffin and Thomas J. J. Altizer, John Cobb's Theology in Process. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1977, 133-49. 'Macht der Mensch die Religion oder macht die Religion den Menschen?', in Trutz Rendtorff (ed.), Religion als Problem der Aufkldrung. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1980, 151-7. 242
BIBLIOGRAPHY
The Nature of a Theological Statement', Zygon 7.1, 1972-, 6-19. 'Person', in Kurt Galling et al., Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, Band V, 3. Auflage. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 1961, cols 230-5. Trans. D. Coffey (unpublished). 'Postscript by Wolfhart Pannenberg', in E. Frank Tupper, The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1973, 3 O 3~5'Problems of a Trinitarian Doctrine of God', Dialog 26.4, Fall 1987, 250-7. Trans. P. Clayton from 'Probleme einer trinitarischen Gotteslehre', in W. Baier, et al.9 Weisheit Gottes - Weisheit der Welt, Vol. i, St Ottilien, 1987. 'Providence, God, and Eschatology', ch. 8 of D. W. Musser and J. L. Price, The Whirlwind in Culture: Frontiers in Theology (in honor of Langdon Gilkey). Bloomington, IN: Meyer Stone Books, 1988. 'The Question of God', Interpretation 21, 1967, 289-314. 'The Religions from the Perspective of Christian Theology and the Selfinterpretation of Christianity in Relation to the Non-Christian Religions', Modern Theology 9.3, July 1993, 285-97. 'A Response to my American Friends', in Carl E. Braaten and Philip Clayton (eds.), The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg. Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1988, 313-36. 'Response to the Discussion', in J. M. Robinson and J. B. Cobb (eds.), Theology as History (New Frontiers in Theology, Vol III). New York: Harper & Row, 1967, 221-76. 'Revelation in Early Christianity', in G. R. Evans (ed.), Christian Authority: Essays in Honour of Henry Chadwick. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988, ch. 5, 76-85. 'The Revelation of God in Jesus of Nazareth', in J. M. Robinson and J. B. Cobb (eds.), Theology as History, New Frontiers in Theology, Vol III. New York: Harper & Row, 1967, 101-33. 'The Significance of the Categories "Part" and "Whole" for the Epistemology of Theology', Journal of Religion 66.4, October 1986, 369-85. This is also published as ch. 7 of Metaphysics and the Idea of God, 1990. 'Die Subjektivitat Gottes und die Trinitatslehre: Ein Beitrag zur Beziehung zwischen Karl Barth und der Philosophic Hegels', Kerygma und Dogma 23, January-March 1977, 25-40. 'Theological Appropriation of Scientific Understandings: Response to Hefner, Wicken, Eaves, and Tipler', Zygon 24.2, June 1989, 255-71. 'A Theological Conversation with Wolfhart Pannenberg', Dialog n, Fall 1972, 286-95. 'Theological Questions to Scientists', Communio: International Catholic Review 15.3, Fall 1988, 319-33. This is also published as ch. i in Toward a Theology of Nature, 1993. 243
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Theology and Science', The Princeton Seminary Bulletin 13.3, 1992, 299-310. 'A Theology of Death and Resurrection', Theology Digest 23.2, Summer i975> 143-8. 'Toward a Theology of Law', Anglican Theological Review 55, October 1973. 395-42.0. 'Vom Nutzen der Eschatologie fur die christliche Theologie: Eine Antwort', Kerygma und Dogma, 25, April-June 1979, 88-105. 'The Working of the Spirit in the Creation and in the People of God', in W. Pannenberg, Avery Dulles and Carl E. Braaten, Spirit, Faith, and Church. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1970, ch. i. Works on Wolfhart Pannenberg's theology /. Books
Albright, Carol R. and Haugen, Joel (eds.). Beginning with the End: God, Science and Wolfhart Pannenberg. Chicago: Open Court Publishing, 1997. Braaten, Carl E. and Clayton, Philip (eds.). The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg. Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1988. Bradshaw, Timothy. Trinity and Ontology: A Comparative Study of the Theologies of Karl Earth and Wolfhart Pannenberg^ Rutherford Studies in Contemporary Theology i. Lewiston: Edwin Mellen Press, 1988. Colombo, J. A. An Essay on Theology and History: Studies in Pannenberg, Metz, and the Frankfurt School, American Academy of Religion Studies in Religion 61. Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1990 (Part I). Galloway, Allan D. Wolfhart Pannenberg. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1973. Glasser, Alfred. Verweigerte Partners chaft? Anthropologische, konfessionelle und okumenische Aspekte der Theologie Wolfhart Pannenbergs. Eichstatter Studien, Neue Folge, Band 31. Regensburg: Verlag Friedrich Pustet, 1991. Greiner, Sebastian. Die Theologie Wolfhart Pannenbergs, Bonner Dogmatische Studien. Wiirzburg: Echter Verlag, 1988. Grenz, Stanley J. Reason for Hope: The Systematic Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990. McKenzie, David. Wolfhart Pannenberg and Religious Philosophy. Washington: University Press of America, 1980. Murphy, Nancey. Theology in the Age of Scientific Reasoning. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990. Olive, Don. Wolfhart Pannenberg. Waco, Texas: Word Books, 1973. Polk, David P. On the Way to God: An Exploration into the Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg. Lanham, MD.: University Press of America, 1989. 244
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Robinson, James M. and Cobb, John B. (eds.). Theology as History, New Frontiers in Theology, Vol. 3. New York: Harper & Row, 1967. Rohls, Jan and Wenz, Gunther (eds.). Vernunft des Glaubens: Wissenschaftliche Theologie und Kirchliche Lehre (Festschrift zum 60. Geburtstag von Wolfhart Pannenberg). Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988. Shults, F. LeRon. The Postfoundationalist Task of Theology: Wolfhart Pannenberg and the New Theological Rationality. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1999. Tupper, E. Frank. The Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1973. Worthing, Mark W. Foundations and Functions of Theology as Universal Science: Theological Method and Apologetic Praxis in Wolfhart Pannenberg and Karl Rahner. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 1996. /'/'. Articles and Chapters Ahlers, Rolf. Theory of God and Theological Method', Dialog 22, Summer 1983, 235-40. Apczynski, John V. Truth in Religion: A Polanyian Appraisal of Wolfhart Pannenberg's Theological Program', Zygon 17.1, March 1982,48-73. Bellinger, Gary. 'Pannenberg's Theology of the Religions and the Claim to Christian Superiority', Encounter 43, Summer 1982, 273-85. Braaten, Carl E. The Current Controversy on Revelation: Pannenberg and His Critics', The Journal of Religion XLV, 1965, 225-37. 'Wolfhart Pannenberg', in M. E. Marty and D. G. Peerman, A Handbook of Christian Theologians. Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1965 & 1984 (enlarged), 639-59. Bradshaw, Timothy. 'God's Relationship to History in Pannenberg', Scottish Bulletin of Evangelical Theology', Special Study 3, 1989, 48-67. Burhenn, Herbert. 'Pannenberg's Doctrine of God', Scottish journal of Theology 28.6, 1975, 535-49Clark W. Royce, 'Christian Images of Fulfillment: Healing Within Anticipation', Religion in Life 46.2, Summer 1977, 186-97. Clayton, Philip. 'Being and One Theologian', The Thomist 52.4, October 1988, 645-71. The God of History and the Presence of the Future', The journal of Religion 65.1, January 1985, 98-108. 'Recent Classical/Process Dialogue on God and Change', Process Studies 18, Fall 1989, 194-203. Cobb, John B. Jr. 'A New Trio Arises in Europe', in M. E. Marty and D. G. Peerman, New Theology No. 2. New York: Macmillan, 1965, 257-63. M5
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Corduan, Winfried. 'Hegelian Themes in Contemporary Theology', Journal of the Evangelical Theological Society 12.4, 1979, 351-61. Ford, Lewis S. 'Creativity in a Future Key', in Robert C. Neville (ed.), New Essays in Metaphysics. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1986. 'A Dialogue About Process Philosophy' [with Wolfhart Pannenberg], Encounter 38, 1977, 318-24. 'The Divine Activity of the Future', Process Studies 11.3, Fall 1981, 169-79. 'God as the Subjectivity of the Future', Encounter, 41, Summer 1980, 287-92. 'A Whiteheadian Basis for Pannenberg's Theology', Encounter 38, 1977, 307-17. Fuller, Daniel P. Easter Faith and History. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1965, esp. 177-87Galloway, Allan D. 'The New Hegelians', a review article on J. Moltmann, Hope and Planning, and W. Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology, Vols i & 2, Religious Studies, 8, 1972, 367-71. 'Wolfhart Pannenberg', The Expository Times 92.3, December 1980, 69-73. Gilkey, Langdon. 'Pannenberg's Basic Questions in Theology: A Review Article', Perspective 14, Spring 1973, 34-56. Grenz, Stanley J. 'The Irrelevancy of Theology: Pannenberg and the Quest for Truth', Calvin Theological Journal 27, November 1992, 307-11. 'Pannenberg and Evangelical Theology: Sympathy and Caution', Christian Scholar's Review 20.3, 1991, 272-85. 'Sacramental Spirituality, Ecumenism, and Mission to the World: Foundational Motifs of Pannenberg's Ecclesiology', Mid-Stream 30, January 1991, 20-34. 'Wolfhart Pannenberg turns 60', Christianity Today, September 2 1988, 22-4. and Olson, Roger E. 'The Transcendence of the Future: The Theology of Hope', Ch. 6 in Twentieth Century Theology: God and the World in a Transitional Age. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1992, 170-99. Hagenaars, P. 'Anticipatie en Rationaliteit', in H. J. Adriaanse and H. A. Krop, Theologie en Rationaliteit: Godsdienstwijsgerige Bijdragen. Kampen, Netherlands: J. H. Kok, 1988, 162-95. Halsey, Jim S. 'History, Language, and Hermeneutic: The Synthesis of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Westminster Theological Journal 41, Spring 1979, 269-90. Hefner, Philip. 'Theological Reflections (4)', Una Sancta 25.3, 1968, 32-51. 2,46
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Henry, Carl F. H. The Theology of Zigzags', Christianity Today, September u 1970, 36-7. Hick, J. 'A Note on Pannenberg's Eschatology', Harvard Theological Review 77.3-4, July/October 1984, 421-3. Hill, William J. The Historicity of God', Theological Studies 45, June 1984,320-33. Hinton, Rory A. A. 'Pannenberg on the Truth of Christian Discourse: A Logical Response', Calvin Theological Journal 27, November 1992, 312-18. Hodgson, Peter C. Tannenberg on Jesus: A Review Article', Journal of the American Academy of Religion 36, December 1968, 373-84. Hogan, John P. The Historical Imagination and the New Hermeneutic: Collingwood and Pannenberg', in Robert Masson (ed.). The Pedagogy of God's Image. Chico, CA: Scholars Press, 1982, 9-30. Jackson, M. B. 'How True is God-language? W. Pannenberg', The Cumberland Seminarian 19.2-3, Winter and Spring 1981, 21-7. Jentz, Arthur 'Personal Freedom and the Futurity of God: Some Reflections on Pannenberg's "God of Hope" ', Reformed Review 31, Spring 1978, 148-54Johnson, Elizabeth A. The Ongoing Christology of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Horizons 9.2, Fall 1982, 237-50. The Right Way to Speak About God? Pannenberg on Analogy', Theological Studies 43.4, December 1982, 673-92. Knitter, Paul. 'What is German Protestant Theology Saying About the Non-Christian Religions?', Neue Zeitschrift fur Systematische Theologie 15.1, 1973, 38-64. Koch, Kurt. 'Gottes Handeln in der Geschichte und die Bestimmung des Menschen; Zur geschichtstheologischen Neuinterpretation des christlichen Erwahlungsglaubens bei Wolfhart Pannenberg', Catholica 33-3, i979? 2.20-39. Logister, W. 'De Dimensie van God: Een Studie in Pannenberg's Theologie', Tijdschrift voor Theologie n, 1971, 159-78. 'Het Eschatologisch Probleem bij Wolfhart Pannenberg: Analyse en Kritiek', Nederlands Theologisch Tijdschrift 24, April 1970, 263-90. Lonning, Per. 'Zur Denkbarkeit Gottes - ein Gesprach mit Wolfhart Pannenberg und Eberhard Jiingel', Studia Theologica 34, 1980, 39-71. Macquarrie, John. Theologies of Hope: A Critical Examination', Expository Times 82, 1970, 100-5. McGrath, Alister E. 'Pannenberg', in A. E. McGrath (ed.), The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Modern Christian Thought. Oxford: Blackwell, 1993. McKenzie, David. 'Pannenberg on Faith and Reason', Dialog 18, Summer 1979, 222-4. 147
GOD AND THE FUTURE
'Pannenberg on God and Freedom', The Journal of Religion 60.3, July 1980, 307-29. Meyers, Alan G. The Divine Incompleteness: Two Alternative Theisms'. Unpublished PhD thesis, Union Theological Seminary, Virginia, 1987. Murdock, William R. 'History and Revelation in Jewish Apocalypticism', Interpretation 21.2, April 1967, 167-87. Neuhaus, Richard J. 'Pannenberg Jousts with the World Council of Churches', The Christian Century, 17 February 1982, 74-6. 'Reason Public and Private: The Pannenberg Project', First Things 21, March 1992, 55-60. Nicol, Iain G. 'Facts and Meanings: Wolfhart Pannenberg's Theology as History and the Role of the Historical-Critical Method', Religious Studies 12, June 1976, 129-39. Nobuhara, Tokiyuki. 'Analogia Actionis: A New Proposal for Christology "From Below" ', Union Seminary Quarterly Review 39.4, 1984, 269-85. Nowell, David Z. 'Futurity and Contingency: An Alternative Paradigm'. Unpublished PhD thesis, Baylor University, 1991. Obayashi, Hiroshi. 'Future and Responsibility: a Critique of Pannenberg's Eschatology', Sciences Religieuses/Studies in Religion 1.3, 1971, 191-203. Oden, Thomas C. 'The Human Potential and Evangelical Hope', Dialog 13, Spring 1974, 121-8. O'Donnell, J. 'Pannenberg's Doctrine of God', Gregorianum 72.1, 1991, 73-98. Olson, R. 'The Human Self-Realization of God: Hegelian Elements in Pannenberg's Christology', Perspectives in Religious Studies 13.3, Fall 1986, 207-23. 'Trinity and Eschatology: The Historical Being of God in Jiirgen Moltmann and Wolfhart Pannenberg', Scottish Journal of Theology 36.2, June 1983, 213-27. 'Wolfhart Pannenberg's Doctrine of the Trinity', Scottish Journal of Theology 43.2, 1990, 175-206. Olthuis, James H. 'God as True Infinite: Concerns about Wolfhart Pannenberg's Systematic Theology, Vol. i', Calvin Theological Journal 27, November 1992, 318-25. Pailin, David. 'Lessing's Ditch Revisited: The Problem of Faith and History', in Ronald H. Preston (ed.), Theology and Change: Essays in Memory of Alan Richardson. London: SCM Press, 1975, ch. 6, 78-103, esp 93-9. Park, Aaron P. The Christian Hope According to Bultmann, Pannenberg, and Moltmann', Westminster Theological Journal 33, May 1971, I53-74248
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Pasquariello, Ronald D. 'Pannenberg's Philosophical Foundations', The Journal of Religion 56.4, October 1976, 338-47. Peters, Ted. 'Jesus' Resurrection: An Historical Event Without Analogy', Dialog 12, Spring 1973, 112-16. Truth in History: Gadamer's Hermeneutics and Pannenberg's Apologetic Method', Journal of Religion 55.1, January 1975, 36-56. The Use of Analogy in Historical Method', Catholic Biblical Quarterly 35, 1973, 475~ 82 Pinnock, Clark H. 'Pannenberg's Theology: Reasonable Happenings in History', Christianity Today, 5 November 1976, 19-22. 'No-Nonsense Theology: Pinnock Reviews Pannenberg', Christianity Today, 19 November 1976, 14-16. Placher, William C. The Present Absence of Christ: Some Thoughts on Pannenberg and Moltmann', Encounter 40, Spring 1979, 169-79. Rhem, Richard A. 'A Theological Conception of Reality as History Some Aspects of the Thinking of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Reformed Review 26, Autumn 1972, 178-88, 212-23. Ringleben, Joachim. 'Gottes Sein, Handeln und Werden', in J. Rohls and G. Wenz (eds.), Vernunft des Glaubens: Wissenschaftliche Theologie und Kirchliche Lehre (Festschrift zum 60. Geburtstag von Wolfhart Pannenberg). Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988. Ritter, A. M. This or That Theology: Reflections upon "The reception of the philosophical notion of God as a dogmatic problem of early Christian Theology" in memory of Heinrich Doerrie', Studia Patristica 18.2, 1989, 121-31. Russell, John M. 'Pannenberg on Verification in Theology: An Epistemic Response', Iliff Review 43.1, Winter 1986, 37-55 Russell, Robert J. 'Contingency in Physics and Cosmology: A Critique of the Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Zygon 23.1, March 1988, 23-43. Sauter, Gerhard. 'Uberlegungen zu einem weiteren Gesprachsgang iiber "Theologie und Wissenschaftstheorie" ', Evangelische Theologie 40.2, March/April 1980, 161-8. Schott, Faye. 'Comparing Eberhard Jiingel and Wolfhart Pannenberg on Theological Method and Religious Pluralism', Dialog 31, Spring 1992, 129-35. 'God Is Love: The Contemporary Theological Movement of Interpreting the Trinity as God's Relational Being'. Unpublished ThD thesis, Lutheran School of Theology, 1990. Schwobel, Christoph. 'Wolfhart Pannenberg', in F. David Ford (ed.), The Modern Theologians, Vol. I. Oxford: Blackwell, 1989, ch. 13, 257-92. Simpson, Gary. 'Whither Wolfhart Pannenberg? Reciprocity and Political Theology', Journal of Religion 67.1, January 1987, 33-49. 2,49
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Steiger, Lothar. 'Revelation-History and Theological Reason: A Critique of the Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg', History and Hermeneutic (Journal for Theology and the Church 4), ed. Robert W. Funk and Gerhard Ebeling; New York: Harper & Row, 1967, 81-106. Turner, Geoffrey. 'Wolfhart Pannenberg and the Hermeneutical Problem', Irish Theological Quarterly 39.2, April 1971, 107-19. Van den Brom, L. J. 'Dogmatiek een Wetenschap: Een Contradictie?', Nederlands Theologisch Tijdschrift 40.1, 1986, 53-81.-81. Venema, Cornelis P. 'History, Human Freedom and the Idea of God in the Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg', Calvin Theological Journal 17, April 1981, 53-77Walsh, Brian J. 'Pannenberg's Eschatological Ontology', Christian Scholar's Review 11.3, 1982, 229-49. (ed.). 'Pannenberg's Systematic Theology', Vol. i: A Symposium', Calvin Theological Journal 27, November 1992, 304-25. Wicken, Jeffrey S. 'Theology and Science in the Evolving Cosmos: A Need for Dialogue', Zygon 23.1, March 1988, 45-55. Wilken, Robert L. 'Who is Wolfhart Pannenberg?', Dialog 4, 1965, 140-2. Wood, Laurence W. 'Defining the Modern Concept of Self-Revelation: Toward a Synthesis of Barth and Pannenberg', Asbury Theological Journal 41.2, Fall 1986, 85-105. 'History and Hermeneutics: a Pannenbergian Perspective', Wesleyan Theological Journal 16, Spring 1981, 7-22. Other works Barth, Karl. Church Dogmatics, I/i. 2nd edn., trans. G. W. Bromiley. Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1975. A translation of Die Kirchliche Dogmatik: Die Lehre vom Wort Gottes, I. Zurich: Evangelischer Verlag. Church Dogmatics, II/i. Trans. T. H. L. Parker et al. Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1957. The Epistle to the Romans, 6th edn., trans. Edwyn C. Hoskyns. London: Oxford University Press, 1933 & 1972. The Gottingen Dogmatics: Instruction in the Christian Religion, Vol. i, ed. Hannelotte Reiffen; trans. G. W. Bromiley. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1991. A translation of Unterricht in der christlichen Religion. Theologischer Verlag Zurich, 1990. Bloch, E. The Principle of Hope, 3 vols. Trans. N. Plaice, S. Plaice and P. Knight. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986. A translation of Das Prinzip Hoffnung. Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp Verlag, 1959. Borg, Marcus J. Jesus in Contemporary Scholarship. Valley Forge: Trinity Press, 1994.
250
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Braaten, C. E. and Jenson, R. W. (eds.), Christian Dogmatics, Vol. i. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1984. Braaten, C. E. (ed.). Our Naming of God. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989. The Future of God. New York: Harper &; Row, 1969. Buckley, Michael J. At the Origins of Modern Atheism. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1987. Bultmann, Rudolf. Faith and Understanding, Vol. i, ed. R. W. Funk. London: SCM Press, 1969. A translation of Glauben und Verstehen, Bd. i, 6th edn. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck). History and Eschatology. The Gifford Lectures, 1955. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1957. -Jesus Christ and Mythology. London: SCM Press, 1960. Caird, G. B. (ed.), The Christian Hope. London: SPCK, 1970. Chilton, B. and McDonald, J. I. H. Jesus and the Ethics of the Kingdom. Biblical Foundations in Theology. London: SPCK, 1987. Clayton, P. God and Contemporary Science. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, I997Coffey, D. Deus Trinitas: The Doctrine of the Triune God. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Collingwood, R. G. The Idea of History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1946. Collins, John J. The Apocalyptic Imagination: An Introduction to the Jewish Matrix of Christianity. New York: Crossroad, 1984. Cousins, Ewert H. (ed.). Hope and the Future of Man. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1972,. Dray, W. H. Philosophy of History. Foundations of Philosophy Series. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964. Ebeling, Gerhard. The Nature of Faith. Trans. Ronald Gregor Smith. London: Collins, 1961. A translation of Das Wesen des Christlichen Glaubens. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1959. Word and Faith. Trans. James W. Leitch. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1963. A translation of Wort und Glaube. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1960. Evans, C. F. Resurrection and the New Testament, Studies in Biblical Theology, Second Series 12. London: SCM Press, 1970. Funk, Robert W. (ed.). Apocalypticism, Journal for Theology and the Church 6. New York: Herder & Herder, 1969. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Truth and Method. Trans. G. Barden and J. Cumming et al. New York: Crossroad, 1982. A translation of Wahrheit und Methode, znd edn. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 1965. Gale, Richard M. (ed.). The Philosophy of Time. New York: Doubleday (Anchor Books), 1967. 251
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Gardiner, P. The Nature of Historical Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961. Grenz, Stanley J. and Olson, Roger E. Twentieth Century Theology: God and the World in a Transitional Age. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1992. Gunton, Colin E. The Promise of Trinitarian Theology. Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1991. Hanson, Paul D. The Dawn of Apocalyptic, revised edn. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1979. (ed.). Visionaries and their Apocalypses. Issues in Religion and Theology 4. Philadelphia: Fortress Press; London: SPCK, 1983. Harnack, Adolf von. What Is Christianity? 2nd edn., trans. T. B. Saunders. London: Williams & Norgate, 1901. A translation of Das Wesen des Christentums. 1900. Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. New York: Harper & Row; London: SCM Press, 1962. A translation of Sein und Zeit, yth edn. Tubingen: Neomarius Verlag, 1953. Hill, William J. The Three-personed God. Washington: Catholic University Press, 1982. Jenson, Robert W. The Triune Identity: God According to the Gospel. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1982. Systematic Theology, Vol. i. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997. Jiingel, Eberhard. The Doctrine of the Trinity: God's Being is in Becoming. Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press, 1976. A translation of Gottes Sein ist im Werden. Verantwortliche Rede vom Sein Gottes bei Karl Barth, Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 1964. God as the Mystery of the World. Trans. Darrell L. Guder. Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1983. A translation of Gott als Geheimnis der Welt, 3rd revised edn. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1977. Kahler, Martin. The So-called Historical Jesus and the Historic, Biblical Christ, ed. and trans. Carl E. Braaten. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1964. A translation of Der sogenannte historische Jesus und der geschichtliche, biblische Christus. Leipzig, 1892. Klein, E. and Lachieze-Rey, M. The Quest for Unity: The Adventure of Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Koch, Klaus. The Rediscovery of Apocalyptic, Studies in Biblical Theology, Second Series 22. Trans. M. Kohl. London: SCM Press, 1972. A translation of Ratios vor der Apokalyptik. Giitersloher Verlagshaus Gerd Mohn, 1970. Kugelmann, Lothar. Antizipation: Eine begriffsgeschichtliche Untersuchung. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1986. 252
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Kiing, Hans. The Incarnation of God. Trans. J. R. Stephenson. Edinburgh: T&cT Clark, 1987. Translated from Menschiverdung Gottes. Freiburg: K. G. Herder, 1970. LaCugna, Catherine M. God For Us: The Trinity and Christian Life. San Francisco: Harper, 1991. Ladd, G. E. The Presence of the Future: The Eschatology of Biblical Realism. London: SPCK, 1974. Lindbeck, G. A. The Nature of Doctrine. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1984. Lowith, Karl. Meaning in History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949. Macquarrie, John. In Search of Deity: An Essay in Dialectical Theism. London: SCM Press, 1984. Marty, Martin E. and Peerman, Dean G. (eds.). New Theology No. 2. New York: Macmillan, 1965. Meeks, M. Douglas. Origins of the Theology of Hope. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1974. Meyerhoff, H. (ed.). The Philosophy of History in Our Time: An Anthology. New York: Doubleday, 1959. Moltmann, J. The Coming of God. Trans. Margaret Kohl. London: SCM Press, 1996. A translation of Das Kommen Gottes: Christliche Eschatologie. Giitersloh: Chr. Kaiser Verlag, 1995. The Crucified God: The Crucified Christ as the Foundation and Criticism of Christian Theology. Trans. R. A. Wilson and J. Bowden. London: SCM Press, 1974. A translation of Der gekreuzigte Gott, znd edn. Munich: Chr. Kaiser Verlag, 1973. The Experiment Hope, ed. M. Douglas Meeks. London: SCM Press, 1975. Theology of Hope. Trans. James W. Leitch. London: SCM Press, 1967. A translation of Theologie der Hoffnung. Munich: Chr. Kaiser Verlag, 1965. The Trinity and the Kingdom of God. Trans. Margaret Kohl. London: SCM Press, 1981. A translation of Trinitdt und Reich Gottes. Munich: Chr. Kaiser Verlag, 1980. Neville, Robert C. (ed.). New Essays in Metaphysics. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1986. Nickelsburg, George W. E. Resurrection, Immortality, and Eternal Life in Intertestamental Judaism. Harvard Theological Studies 26. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972. O'Donnell, J. J. The Mystery of the Triune God. Heythrop Monographs 6. London: Sheed & Ward, 1988. Trinity and Temporality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983. Ogden, Schubert M. The Reality of God. London: SCM Press, 1967. 253
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Perrin, Norman. The Kingdom of God in the Teaching of Jesus. London: SCM Press, 1963. Peters, Ted. God as Trinity: Relationality and Temporality in Divine Life. Louisville: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1993. God - the World's Future. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1992.. Plantinga, T. Historical Understanding in the Thought of Wilhelm Dilthey. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1980. Rahner, K. The Trinity. London: Burns & Gates, 1970. Rickman, H. P. (ed.). Meaning in History. London: Allen & Unwin, 1961. Wilhelm Dilthey: Pioneer of the Human Studies. London: Paul Elek, 1979. Robinson, J. M. and Cobb, J. B. (eds.). Theology as History (New Frontiers in Theology, Vol. III). New York: Harper & Row, 1967, 101-33. Rowland, Christopher. Christian Origins: From Messianic Movement to Christian Religion. Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1985. The Open Heaven: A Study of Apocalyptic in Judaism and Early Christianity. New York: Crossroad, 1982.. Sanders, E. P. Jesus and Judaism. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1985. Sauter, G. Eschatological Rationality: Theological Issues in Focus. Grand Rapids: Baker Books, 1996. What Dare We Hope? Reconsidering Eschatology. Harrisburg: Trinity Press International, 1999. Zukunft und Verheissung: Das Problem der Zukunft in der gegenwdrtigen theologischen und philosophischen Diskussion. Zurich: Zwingli Verlag, 1965. Schleiermacher, Friedrich. On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers. Trans. J. Oman. New York: Harper &: Row, 1958. A translation of the 3rd edn. of Uber die Religion, 1821. Schlink, Edmund. The Coming Christ and the Coming Church. Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd, 1967. A translation of Der kommende Christus und die kirchlichen Traditionen. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck 6c Ruprecht, 1961. Schweitzer, Albert. The Quest of the Historical Jesus: A Critical Study of its Progress from Reimarus to Wrede. Trans. W. Montgomery. New York: Macmillan, 1955. A translation of Von Reimarus zu Wrede: Eine Geschichte der Leben-Jesu-Forschung, ist edn. 1906. Thiselton, Anthony C. The Two Horizons: New Testament Hermeneutics and Philosophical Description with Special Reference to Heidegger, Bultmann, Gadamer and Wittgenstein. Exeter: Paternoster Press, 1980. Tillich, Paul. Systematic Theology, Vol. i. London: Nisbet, 1953. Torrance, Thomas F. Theological Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969. 254
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Tracy, David. The Analogical Imagination: Christian Theology and the Culture of Pluralism. London: SCM Press, 1981. and Cobb, John B. (eds.). Talking About God: Doing Theology in the Context of Modern Pluralism. New York: Seabury, 1983. Tracy, Thomas F. God, Action, and Embodiment. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1984. Travis, Stephen H. Christian Hope and the Future of Man. Leicester: Inter-Varsity Press, 1980. Urs von Balthasar, Hans. The God Question and Modern Man. Trans. Hilda Graef. New York: Seabury Press, 1967. A translation of Die Gottesfrage des Heutigen Menschen. Wien & Miinchen: Verlag Herold, 1958. Previously published in English as Science, Religion and Christianity. Westminster: Newman Press, 1958. Weinandy, Thomas G. Does God Change? The Word's Becoming in the Incarnation. Still River, MA: St Bede's Publications, 1985. Weiss, Johannes. The Preaching of Jesus about the Kingdom of God, ed. L. Keck, trans. R. H. Hiers and D. L. Holland. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1971. Wiles, M. God's Action in the World. London: SCM Press, 1986.
*55
This page intentionally left blank
Index of Subjects Anthropology 20, 23, 7 if., 121, 1 66, 187 Anticipation (seetf/soProlepsis) 18, 22, 5if.,75f., 79,96, 112-26, 173 Apocalyptic 2, 27-54, 147, 150 Jesus' relation to 28, 39 kingdom of God in 36-8, 53 types of 32-5 Atheism 3, 89^, 132, 201 Being 69, 94, 112, i38f., 159 and becoming 121-3, I 38, 157^5 159
Bible, scripture authority of 60
113, 115, 117, 144, 146, 151, 156, 219, 221, 231, 237^ Barth on i3f. Bultmann's understanding of 10 centre of theology 20, 146, 209 consummation 2f., 88 eschatological confirmation 1 8 loss, rediscovery of 6, 90 ontological implications 55-8 political relevance 24 Eternity presence of 107 and time, see Time Ethics 70
Determinism 124^, 128, 162, 168, i74f-» *75~*5 Duration 142
Finite, see Infinite Foundationalism 59f. Freedom 100, 103, 124, 132, 136, 175, 177, 179 Future concept of 93, 100, 145 eschatological 3, 89 field of the possible 101 God as power of 5, 91, 100, 104, 127-30, 134-6, 139, 143-6, 148, 150, 175, 226 openness of 9, 100, 178 power of 70, 92, 102, 139, 150, 177 (ontological) priority of I9f., 22f., 56-8, 88-126, 135 reality of 103, 179 theology of 4, 19
Economy 161, 191, 195, 198, 204, 224 Eschatology, eschaton 5, 21-5, 108,
God action 162-6, 181, 197, 2iof., 231
Cause, causality 100, 164, i74f., 179
Church 23 3f. Contingency 97-100, 115, 127, 138, 149, 166-9, i73 f -> i?5> J 77> 179 Cosmos, cosmology 103, 126, 148, i68f., 170, 181, 199, 224 Creation i68f., 176, 179, 181, 183, 197, i99f., 224, 23 if., 234 from the future 104, i2if., 128, i3if., 134-6, 139^, 161-75, 178
257
GOD AND THE FUTURE
God (cont.) all-determining 68, iz4f., izyf., 154, 173, 175-82, becoming, development 153, i57f., 159-61, 193^, 2.2.1, 223 doctrine of 21, 127, 204 existence 134, i37f., 154-6, 186 futurity 24, 89-92, 128, 130-4, 136, 138, 141-51, 150, 184, i86f., 216, 225-7, 230 glory, glorification 3, 135, 198, 200, 206, 2o8f., 234^ God's being as God's rule 5, 90, 129, 133, 137, 141, 144, 156, 160, 182, 183, 196, 222,
236,
237
lordship 24, i32f., 142, 206, 2o8f., 211, 226 personhood 131, 138, 187-91, 227 plausibility 3 power of 5, 131, 133, 155, 174, 179, 181 proofs of 17, 57f., 137 reign of, see Kingdom of God subject, subjectivity 189^, 197, 218 God, attributes of aseity 161 eternity 130, 134, 141-51, J 54> 172, 197, 207,
221-4
faithfulness 99, 131 immanence 153, 183, i9if., 2.13, 224
immutability 177, 196 infinity 143, 154, 224, 228 love 2, 5, 135, i4of., i48f., 164, i79f., 181, 187, 203, 224f., 231 omnipotence 136, 143, 149, 176, 180 simplicity 210 transcendence i52f., 183, 19 if., 195, 213, 224 unity 190, 200, 202, 210, 215 Hermeneutics 8 if.
Historical thinking 71-5 History concept of 79, 83 end of 10, 124, 146, 148, i5of., 155, 158, 173, lyyf. flight from 8, 9, n, 12 God's relation to 73, 84, 86, 88, 98, i27f., 130, 132, 148, i56f., i6if., 180, 186, 191-201, 213-16, 2i8f., 226, 228, 230, 235 and revelation 16, 17 theology of 15, 17, 83, 86 totality, universal history 17, 29^, 36, 79-88, 151 unity of 21, 28, 74, 104, 167 Hope 15, 1 6 Humanity see Anthropology Incarnation 154, 207 Infinite, the 66f., 86, 192 Jesus, Christ cross, crucifixion i54f., 157, 196, 199, 2o6f., 208, 215, 2171"., 219 finality of 6 resurrection, see Resurrection return of 147 self-distinction from Father 135 Son of God 206 Kingdom of God 7, 125, 132, 139^, 146, i78f., 180, 184, 210-13, 219,231-4, 236 as eschatological 3, 19, 21, 76, 91, 107, 137, 184, 212, 219, 230, 233 as future and present 42f., 53, 94, 115, 200 Jesus' understanding of 6f., 20, 38-43, 53, 129, 151, 212, 237 Logos 202 Meaning 7if., 75, yyf., 80 as anticipated 751"., 125 158
INDEX OF SUBJECTS
Salvation 21, 45, 81, ii3f., 205, 209, 2i3f., 221, 237 Science, scientists 164^, 169 theology and 58-62, 101, 105, 164, 168, 172, 217 Soul 109, in Spirit (Holy) 101, 165, i78f., 2oif.,
Metaphysics (see also Ontology) 3, 57, 65f., 71, 75f., 78, 92, 96, 105, 119, 160 Nature, laws of nature 99, 164, 167 Ontology 3, 20, 55^, 62-9, 78, 89, 95f., 102, 104, 122, 126, 185 principle of retroactive permanence i58f., 216,
205, 208f., 2l6, 220, 233
as eschatological 101, 173 as field 165^, 170-4, 179, 181, 211, 227
222f., 229, 235
in creation 101, 169-72, 182, 234
Parousia 143 delay of 50-2 Philosophy (see also Metaphysics, Ontology) 65, 67f. Greek 6, 70, 106, 180 and theology 55-64, 66-9, 92 of time 70-2 Physics 93, 98, 168, 170, 175^, 181 Possibility 102 Process 69-71 Process thought 70, 123^, 130, 148-51, 159-61, 174, 2.28 Prolepsis (see also Anticipation) 5if., 113-15 Promise 15, 16, 18 Reality, the real 103 and appearance 74, 93 f. as a whole, see Whole as historical 71-3, 108 openness of 75, 177, 179 unity of i38f., 146, 148, 178 views of 73-5, 98 Reconciliation 2if., 23 2f. Religion 63-5 Resurrection 146 and apocalyptic 27, 47-50 and end of the world 44-7, 52 foundational for theology 43, 53 and kingdom of God 44-6, 52 general 51, 53, 116, 151 of Jesus 4, i8f., 21, 43-52, ii5f., 129, 147, 196, 199, 2o6f., 2O8,
Temporality 69-79, 95, 152 Theodicy 87, 147, 199!". Theology 2 as Gottesivissenschaft 2, 61 of history, see History of hope 4, 14 relation to philosophy 55-64, 66-9 Time, 69, 92, 122, 152-61, 229 and eternity 46, 93, 104-12, 130, 141, 147, 150, 181, 198, 217, 22of., 230
God's relation to 105-8, 151, 152-61, 193^ relation between present and future 92-7, no, 112-26, 132, i66f., 217 Trinity, triune God 101, 127, 135, 141, 143, 151, 153, 155, 159, i69f., i8of., 183-236 appropriation, attribution 197 doctrine of 130, 149, 160, i8of., 203, 230 immanent and economic 159-61, 177, i84f., 188, 195, 213-25, 228 intra-trinitarian relations i35f., 149, 153^, 157, 185, 187-91, 196, 198, 202, 204-13, 2i7f., 229f., 235 perichoresis 186 Persons 149, 155, 157, 169^,
22O, 222, 237f.
187, 191, 196, 200, 202,
Revelation 12, 30, 87, 114, 119, 143, 190, 204, 205
209, 224, 227, 236
processions 205 259
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Truth, truth-claims i, 74, 77, 117-2.2. Whole, 142 reality as 571"., 61, 64^, 69-71, 77, 81, 83, 147
as semantic, hermeneutical 77-9, 82 Word of God 9, u World end of 46f., 148 God's relation to, see History
260
Index of Authors Ahlers, R. 123 Allen, L. 115 Alexander 130 Aquinas, Thomas 202, 228, 230 Aristotle 58, 94!"., 106, 122 Athanasius 202, 207, 214, 229 Augustine 84, 108-11, 152, 205
Dorner, I. 189, 203 Dray, W. H. 83 Dupre, L. 61 Durr, H.-P. 101
Earth, H. 94 Earth, K. 31"., 8-14, 58, 61, 1521"., 188-92, 194, 203-5, 213-15, 217 Easil 202 Eetz, H. D. 31 Bloch, E. 20, 22, 90-2, 132-3 Boethius 109, 142 Bonhoeffer, D. 192 Borg, M. 29 Bornkamm, G. 39 Braaten, €.117 Bradshaw, T. 127, i55f., 228 Bultmann, R. 3, 8-14, 23, 58, 61 Burhenn, H. 113
Faraday, M. 170 Fichte, J. G. 72 Ford, L. S. 70, 102, 124, 145, 149^, 157, i74f., 177-9 Fuchs, E., 28 Funk, R.W., 41
Campenhausen, H. von 84 Cappadocian Fathers 202, 211 Chilton, B. 41 Clark, M. 84 Clayton, P. 56, 71, 77, 96, 116, 122-5, J5 1 . 178* 187, 189 Cobb, J. B. 70, 123^, i48f., 160, 177 Collingwood, R. G. 9, 72 Collins, J. J. 32-5, 46, 48 Descartes, R. 66, 72 Dilthey, W. 23, yif., 77-9, 85, 91, 119, 147, 158, 223
Ebeling, G. 28 Evans, C. F. 471".
Gadamer, H.-G. 8 if., 85 Galloway, A. D. 27 Gilkey, L. 176 Glasser, A. 226f. Greenspoon, L. J 48f. Grenz, S. 97, 127, 148, 225-7, 230-1 Gunton, C. 184 Haering, Th. 152 Hamilton, W. 86 Hanson, P. D. 33-6 Harnack, A. 7, 212 Hartshorne, C. 157!". Hasel, G. F. 49 Hefner, P. 19, 62, 93, 123, 164, 166, 173 Hegel, G. W. F. 20, 66, 72, 75, 77, 83f., 86f., 94, 115, n8f., 130, 156, 189-95, 2-°3? 2I 8, 226-8 Heidegger, M. 9, 20, 23, 65, 69-72, 85, 105^, 110-12 Henrich, D. 57 Herder, J. G. 71 261
GOD AND THE FUTURE
Herrmann, W. 8 Hill, W. J. 225 Hodgson, P .C. 112 Hollis, M. 67 Huyssteen, J. W. van 59
Parmenides 141 Perrin, N. 37 Peters, T. 82, Pike, N. 2.2,3 Plantinga, T. 72, 77 Plato 74, 94^, 108, 142. Plotinus 108-12, 142 Polk, D. 36, 91, 103, 113, 124, i37f., i76f., 179
Jaspers, K. 9 Jenson, R. 201, 213, 2i6f. Jiingel, E. 1531"., 157, 159, 196, 201, 203,
214-17
Rad, G. von 15 Rahner, K. 154, 114-17 Rhem, R. 59 Richard of St Victor 2.03 Ringleben, J. 161 Ritschl, A. 7-8 Robinson, J. M. 84 Rossler, D. 28 Rowland, C. 32-4, 37, 47 Russell, R. J. 97
Kahler, M. 8, n Kant, I. 72, 94, 96, inf., 218 Kasemann, E. 27, 29, 39f. Kasper, W. 214 Keck, L. 6 Kierkegaard, S. 20, 94, i93f. Klein, G. 114 Kneale, W. 142 Kugelmann, L. 113
Sanders, E. P. 39-41 Sauter, G. i4f., 20, 3of. Schleiermacher, F. 63, 66 Schner, G. P. 59 Schweitzer, A. 6-7 Shults, F. L. x, 591".
LaCugna, C. M. 214 Ladd, G. E. 36 Lakatos 173 Leibniz 170 Lindbeck, G. 59 Logister, W. 124, 148 Lowith, K. 83f. Luckman, T. 64 Macquarrie, J. 20 Marx, K. 20 McDonald, J. 41 McKenzie, D. 124, 176 Meeks, M. D. 16 Minear, P. S. 10 Moltmann, J. 4, 14-19, 3°> 9°> T 53^ 5 157, 191, 196, 201, 212, 214-17 Mommsen, W. 85 Murdock,W. R. 3 if., 35 Neuhaus, R. J. 92, 137 Nickelsburg, G. W. E. 49 Niebuhr, R. 83 Nowell, D. Z. 102 Obayashi, H. 123 O'Donnell, J. 63, 181, 188, 228-30 Ogden, S. io5f. Olson, R. 122, 225, 227, 229
Teilhard de Chardin, P. 165 Tillich, P. 6 1, 86, 165 Toynbee, A. J. 831". Tracey, D. 59 Tracy, T. F. i62f. Troeltsch, E. 9, 581"., 115 Tupper, E. F. 87, 91 Venema, C. 226 Voltaire 83 Wagner, F. 189 Walsh, B.J. 56 Walsh, W. H. 83 Webster, J. B. 59 Weiss,]. 6, 8, 113 Whitehead, A. 70, 130, 148, 1501"., 157-60, 164, 175, 178 Wicken, J. S. 101 Wilckens, U. 28, 39f. Williams, D. D. 148 Wittram, R. 85
262