The balance of power: Stability in international systems
The balance of power Stability in international systems
EME...
52 downloads
611 Views
4MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
The balance of power: Stability in international systems
The balance of power Stability in international systems
EMERSON M. S. NIOU Duke University
PETER C. ORDESHOOK California Institute of Technology
GREGORY F. ROSE North Texas State University
The right of the University of Cambridge to print and sell all manner of books was granted by Henry VIII in 1534. The University has printed and published continuously since 1584.
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge New York Port Chester Melbourne Sydney
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www. Cambridge. org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521374712 © Cambridge University Press 1989 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1989 This digitally printed first paperback version 2006 A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Niou, Emerson M.S. The balance of power : stability in international systems / Emerson M.S. Niou, Peter C. Ordeshook, Gregory F. Rose. p. cm. Bibliography: p. Includes index. ISBN 0-521-37471-5 1. Balance of power. 2. Political stability. I. Ordeshook, Peter C, 1942- II. Rose, Gregory F. III. Title. JX1318.N56 1990 89-9893 327.1'12-dc20 CIP ISBN-13 978-0-521-37471-2 hardback ISBN-10 0-521-37471-5 hardback ISBN-13 978-0-521-37615-0 paperback ISBN-10 0-521-37615-7 paperback
Contents
Acknowledgments
page vii
1
Introduction 1.1 Perspectives 1.2 The dual nature of instability 1.3 Theory in international relations 1.4 Plan of this volume
1 1 22 29 32
2
Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability 2.1 Preliminary assumptions 2.2 Notation and additional assumptions 2.3 Uncertainty 2.4 Stability 2.5 Enforcement of agreements 2.6 Theoretical domain
36 36 42 56 61 67 72
3
System stability and the balance of power 3.1 Some immediate consequences of our assumptions 3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability 3.3 System stability and war 3.4 A note on assumptions 3.5 Appendix: Proof of Theorem 3.2
75 76 85 102 106 111
4
Resource stability and the balance of power 4.1 The relevance of system stability to resource stability 4.2 The nature of resource stability and instability 4.3 A necessary and sufficient condition for resource stability 4.4 General implications 4.5 Some experimental evidence 4.6 Appendix A: Experimental data 4.7 Appendix B: Instructions read to subjects 4.8 Appendix C: Proofs of results
115 115 118 124 127 132 139 142 143
vi
Contents
5
Preventive war 5.1 A dynamic extension 5.2 Preferences 5.3 Equilibria in the first period 5.4 The emergence of a predominant country 5.5 Inessential countries 5.6 The disappearance of stability 5.7 The sources of preventive war 5.8 Appendix: Proofs of results
146 154 160 162 167 174 176 179 182
6
Geography, balancers, and central powers 6.1 Conceptualizing the consequences of geography 6.2 System and resource stability 6.3 Implications: Balancers and central powers 6.4 Balancers and central powers: Some examples 6.5 Appendix: Proofs of results
187 189 197 201 207 212
7
Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914 7.1 Formulating testable hypotheses 7.2 Methodology 7.3 The League of the Three Emperors 7.4 The Austro-German Alliance 7.5 The Triple Alliance 7.6 The Mediterranean agreements 7.7 The Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty 7.8 The Dual Alliance 7.9 The Entente Cordiale and the Triple Entente 7.10 Balance in the alliance system 7.11 Appendix: Data used in the construction of our index
215 216 223 235 244 248 251 254 255 258 259 267
8
European conflict resolution, 1875-1914 8.1 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1875-8 8.2 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1885-8 8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
271 273 279 288
9
Summary and conclusions 9.1 Balance of power reconsidered 9.2 Contemporary implications 9.3 Conclusion
311 311 318 330
References and selected bibliography on European great-power relations, 1871-1914 Index
333 349
Acknowledgments
Valuable assistance in the preparation of this manuscript and in the refinement of our ideas came from several sources, but we would especially like to acknowledge an intellectual debt owed to R. Harrison Wagner. Although we have approached the analysis differently from the way he might have preferred, the early drafts of Harrison's 1986 World Politics essay, and subsequent discussions with him, profoundly influenced our thinking. If he sees his own ideas in our research without citation, it is only because those ideas have become so much part of our own. Second, we want to thank Roy Bridges, Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce Cain, Richard Cupitt, Raymond Duval, David Elliot, Jack Levy, Clifton Morgan, Thomas Schwartz, Duncan Snidal, David Sweet, Dina Zinnes, and the staff of the Public Records Office, London, for their suggestions, encouragement, and assistance. We also want to acknowledge the assistance and encouragement of Bruce Russett who, as editor of The Journal of Conflict Resolution, facilitated the publication of the initial manifestations of our research, as well as the editors of Mathematical Modelling and Simulation and Games, who published follow-up research included in this volume. Finally, we would like to acknowledge our gratitude to the University of Texas at Austin and to the support it provided while we engaged in a considerable portion of the research reported in this volume.
CHAPTER 1
Introduction
Among the depressing features of international political studies is the small gain in explanatory power that has come from the large amount of work done in recent decades. Nothing seems to accumulate, not even criticism. Instead, the same sorts of summary and superficial criticisms are made over and over again, and the same sorts of errors are repeated. Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics (1979, p. 18)
Despite the attention of such intellectual giants as Spinoza, Rousseau, Kant, and Clausewitz, we know little more about international conflict today than was known to Thucydides four hundred years before Christ. Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, The War Trap (1981, p. 2)
1.1
Perspectives
Although the causes of international instability and conflict have been the object of intense scholarly concern, the events of our century are not inconsistent with the supposition that we have made little progress in identifying those causes, that, once identified, we have not adequately applied our research to the discovery of correctives, or that those causes have multiplied at a pace that exceeds our abilities of assimilation and analysis. Some scholars amass and analyze vast arrays of data on diplomatic exchanges, military expenditures, economic indicators, the formation of alliances, and the frequency and severity of wars; others apply the mathematics of decision and game theory with varying degrees of sophistication to the description of international relations processes; and still others reason through the meaning and application of concepts and words such as polarity, power, regime, deterrence, neocolonialism, and the balance of power. If this research has uncovered causes and correctives then, for one reason or another, the corresponding scholarly utterances have been less than compelling. If we reflect upon the considerable literature on the causes of war, one of the chief difficulties is that, on the one hand, so many explanations are offered, we are predisposed to discount them all; on the other hand, 1
2
1 Introduction
since it is so easy to find counterexamples to any particular explanation, a great deal of baggage must be carried to ensure a universal understanding. Such difficulties warn us that true scientific explanation is not being achieved, and that rather than isolating a fundamental cause within a logically consistent theoretical framework, this research appears at best to uncover the varying circumstances sufficient to render conflict an understandable choice by key decision makers. Yet, insofar as uncovering fundamental cause is concerned - uncovering the laws that govern the interactions of people in international affairs and the circumstances under which such interactions yield instability and overt conflict - we are no more likely to infer such cause by the massaging of vast data arrays or from a careful compilation and analysis of historical events than we are to infer the physics of falling objects by observing the flight of leaves from trees. We are not so brazen to suppose that the research we report here resolves all issues. Nevertheless, our goals are immodest: to identify the conditions under which international systems are stable as well as the conditions under which they are unstable, the circumstances in which this instability implies conflict, the objectives that that conflict is intended to serve, and the steps we might take in designing domestic and international institutions to avoid such conflict. Our approach is analytical and abstract, and consists of identifying a structure that is fundamental to all international political processes. Our aim is to formalize the ideas offered by the realist view, in which the dominant force directing international processes is the national pursuit of a single-minded self-interest in an otherwise anarchic system. To achieve this formalization, we make a great many compromises with reality, and the theory we offer is but a preliminary step toward a comprehensive, deductive theory. The measure of this volume's success will be the extent to which other researchers follow our lead by refining our model with alternative and more general assumptions. The necessity for and choice of a paradigm So substantial is the literature on international politics and the causes of war, we should believe that it already contains many of the essential components for a general understanding of our subject. If, as Einstein asserted, "The whole of science is nothing more than the refinement of everyday thinking," then it is unreasonable to suppose that the scholarship of centuries is not replete with insights into the fundamental mechanics of international systems. Nevertheless, we must ask why this scholarship has not formed a generally accepted body of theory with corresponding prescriptions for averting or anticipating wars. Our hypothesis is that this
1.1 Perspectives
3
research too often occurs without reference to any basic paradigm of explanation, or to paradigms that are only dimly perceived, poorly specified, and that do not lend themselves to the rigorous derivation of conclusions so that we can see clearly the underlying premises. Without an explicitly defined and formally organized conceptual scheme identifying general concepts and the relationships of these concepts to the observed world, an empirical literature, no matter how well-informed and scholarly, can be little more than an unsystematic mass of insights, conjectures, and stylized facts. Ideas, however insightful, reduce to illdefined constructs held together more by linguistic structure than by a well-understood theory, and understanding and explanation devolve more on familiarity with jargon than on scientific law and generality. A paradigm, or (more properly) a theory based on a paradigm, ensures that our insights and suppositions accumulate, that they can be tested for their generality, and that they can be remembered as part of a coherent structure (Kuhn 1970). Hence, achieving this volume's goal requires that we operate with an explicit paradigm as a guide to our reasoning. A paradigm, however, must do more than merely guide reasoning; it must also organize it in a rigorously deductive way. Human affairs are complex processes, certainly more complex than the situation confronting a natural scientist or engineer who attempts to understand the laws governing airfoils orfluid-flowthermodynamics. Indeed, developing a theory of international processes may entail confronting an even greater complexity than that which confronts us in natural science, which underscores our greater need for theory. Hence, it is essential that we employ a paradigm that permits us to collect our insights in such a way as to ascertain whether seemingly distinct phenomena can be thought of as manifestations of some more general process or whether our intuition requires a fundamental reinterpretation of reality. Our paradigm is that of rational action and methodological individualism, where causal explanation stems from the supposition that all events, save those we attribute to the probabilistic whims of nature, follow from the actions of people pursuing their goals in a world constrained by limited resources, innovative skill, and the actions of others. Explanation, in turn, derives from models in which predicted actions are the only actions that follow logically from hypothesized goals and constraints or that can otherwise be sustained by those goals as equilibria. The mathematics of logical connections - the mechanism we use to ascertain the premises required to sustain our conclusions - are provided by decision and game theory, from which we must recover the appropriate representation of these connections for the substantive task at hand.
4
1 Introduction
The relevance of game theory A fundamental part of our paradigm - the paradigm of rational choice is the supposition that people's preferences over alternative outcomes are "well-defined" and that these preferences can be represented by a measure we call utility. The concept of utility, though, occasions confusing the paradigm and rationality with a mode of decision making in which, after identifying their alternative actions and the likelihood of different consequences given each action, people choose the action that maximizes their utility or expected utility. This model is indeed part of the paradigm, but it is relevant in only highly specialized cases such as voting in mass elections or participating in markets as consumers. Indeed, we must reject the idea that explanation lies in the simple proposition that decision makers choose those actions that maximize their utility or expected utility. Our paradigm admits of more complexity than that, and Jervis (1976, p. 32) identifies the context of that complexity: If he is to decide intelligently how to act, a person must predict how others will behave. If he seeks to influence them, he needs to estimate how they will react to the alternative policies he can adopt. Even if his actions do not affect theirs, he needs to know how they will act in order to tailor his actions accordingly. Snidal (1986, p. 39), in turn, succinctly states the particular problem with which we must deal: [Real international issues lead].. .directly to a strategic rationality which incorporates the realization that pursuit of egoistic interest requires consideration of interactions of one state's choices with other state's choices. No state can choose its best strategy or attain its best outcome independent of the choices made by others... [and] the distinguishing trait of strategic rationality is that actors choose courses of action based on preferences and expectations of how others will behave. International relations, if not most of politics, occurs in an environment of interactive decision making. In this environment, the actions of a single actor determine and are determined by the actions of others. This, of course, seems a trivial proposition, but it leads us to reject approaches that focus exclusively on the motives and beliefs of decision makers taken one at a time. We cannot accept as legitimate propositions such as "actor / chose Y because / preferred Y to Z " unless we are willing to impose some special assumptions. Because a voter's effect on outcomes is so slight in mass elections, it is reasonable to hypothesize that voters ignore interactive effects in deciding how to cast their ballots - each voter ignores the possibility that others will alter their decisions as a function of what the voter in question decides. Hence, we assume that the environment of the voter's decision, including the benefits associated with individual candidates and the competitiveness of the election, is taken as given from
1.1 Perspectives
5
each voter's perspective. Similarly, in microeconomics, when modeling a consumer's decision, we assume that consumers take prices as given, since each consumer's effect on price is imperceptible. For virtually all other social processes, however, we cannot ignore the joint dependency of decisions, in which case our propositions must take the form "/ chose Y because / believed that the other relevant actors, j , k, etc., would choose B, D, etc., and with these other choices, action Y maximizes /'s utility (Y is /'s best response to B, D, and so forth)." Thus, an actor's utility calculations must summarize not merely preferences over outcomes and actions simpliciter, but must also take cognizance of the impact of the actions of others as constraints on that actor's ability to realize his or her objectives. This restatement might seem to represent only a modest revision, or perhaps even just a more complex restatement of the supposition that people act to maximize utility. However, notice that with this perspective we cannot fully explain final outcomes until we utter a parallel statement for person j (as well as for every other relevant decision maker) - that j chose B because, if /, k, etc. choose Y, D, etc., respectively, thenB isj's best response. However, after formulating such sentences, we necessarily confront the problem of higher orders of thinking. If what / chooses is a function of what j , k, etc. choose, and if what j chooses is a function of what /, k, etc. choose, and so on, then how does each decision maker resolve the problem that all decisions are simultaneously determined - that what / does depends on what he believes j believes about him, and so forth? Game theory is the particular branch of decision theory that seeks to disentangle this simultaneity and to discover the logical choices of people in such interdependent contexts; thus, game theory becomes our primary analytic instrument.1 Ours, of course, is not the first study that seeks to apply game theory to the study of international processes. Typically, though, these applications 1
Although we refer to all interdependent decision-making situations as games, game theory identifies three alternative analytic representations of such situations, with each form corresponding to a different degree of abstraction. The first, a game in extensive form, is a representation of the situation that portrays the actions of decision makers, the timing of those actions, and the information of decision makers any time they must act. The key components of a game in extensive form is a list of decision makers, a list of decision nodes, a specification of the decision maker who must act at each node along with the alternatives available at that node, the information about previous choices that that actor possesses at each of his decision nodes, and a list of terminal nodes that specifiesfinaloutcomes and payoffs. The second representation, the normal form, requires a list of decision makers, a specification of the strategies of decision makers - a plan for how to play the extensive-form game that accommodates all possible contingencies - and an outcome function that takes the strategies of all decision makers and specifies a payoff for each decision maker. The final representation is a game in characteristic function form. This representation suppresses the notion of strategy, and focuses instead on the outcomes or
6
1 Introduction
take the form of demonstrating the parallelism between a specific process and a particular game, most notably the Prisoners' Dilemma and Chicken. In their most naive manifestation, we see sentences such as "let China be player 1 with the strategies a and ft,...," and it is difficult to see how such an application can ever lead to a comprehensive theoretical understanding of international processes. Yet, we are not asserting that valuable insights cannot be gained from such an approach. Certainly, our understanding of the possibility of irrational collective action is illuminated by analyses of the Prisoners' Dilemma, the problems of coordination are revealed by Chicken, and recent studies of reputation and deterrence illuminate the profound significance of incomplete information. What we require, though, is a sufficiently general modeling effort that allows for elaboration, admits the possibility of incorporating these earlier studies as subparts, and provides the theoretical structure for an analysis of complete systems at the macro level. The thought to keep in mind is that game theory is but a piece of mathematics and decision theory. Overzealous advocates and unrepentant critics may misinterpret its value and limitations, but game theory in fact offers only the logical connections between abstract concepts. It is not, by itself, a theory of social processes, so that taking a part of it and appending some story to that part does not constitute a theory any more than if we were to append some interpretation to the ;t's and >>'s in the equation (x — y)(*+y) =x2—y2. Knowledge of game theory, however, heightens our sensitivity to the pervasiveness of interactive decision making in politics, and also provides the tools for thinking about such decision making in a logically coherent way. Equilibria as causal explanations Having accepted game theory as the principal analytic component of our paradigm, we are led to our third observation, namely, that concepts of equilibria for both noncooperative and cooperative games are the mechanisms whereby we generate causal explanations. The revision of the notion of utility maximization that requires consideration of best responses is based on the supposition that we can determine the optimal choices for payoffs that can be assured by coordinated action on the part of subsets of decision makers (coalitions). The key elements of such games are again a list of relevant decision makers along with a specification of the "value" of each potential coalition. Ideally, we prefer to model all situations in extensive form, but this is not always possible, and the normal form and the characteristic function form offer representations that are more analytically tractable. For further elaboration of these distinctions and their formal representations, see, for example, Luce and Raiffa (1957), Shubik (1985), and Ordeshook (1986).
1.1 Perspectives
7
people only if we determine all choices simultaneously. And it is the various notions of equilibria in game theory that form the basis for hypothesizing how people solve these simultaneous, interdependent decision problems. Briefly, an equilibrium for a game is a set of actions or outcomes that, given the goals of all decision makers and the structural constraints of the situation being modeled (an identification of relevant decision makers, the actions and information available to each decision maker, and a specification of the relationship between outcomes and joint actions), are the only ones that can endure.2 Hence, we predict certain actions because these actions are in equilibrium. Correspondingly, the cause of a particular outcome is that it follows from actions in equilibrium. This view of causation is important. Cause no longer resides in the mere correlation of events and circumstances or in their temporal ordering. Instead, to specify cause, we must specify the nature of individual goals, the parameters of structural constraints, and the corresponding equilibria. Hence, the attribution of cause to some particular event is moved away from a focus on the events that immediately preceded it; instead, our focus becomes the decision problem confronting all relevant decision makers and the outcomes that follow if those decision makers pursue the goals we assume for them. Insofar as peace and conflict are concerned, we explain one or the other as the consequence of the pursuit of individualistic goals in an environment in which everyone's actions and fates are interdependent; conflict or peace are merely the consequences of a set of individual choices in equilibrium as determined by individual goals and structural parameters. To illustrate, consider the hypothesis that wars are "caused" by a misperception of military capabilities, in particular, by the perceptions of two leaders that they can both win a conflict.3 In this instance, 2
3
Game theory provides a variety of formal definitions of equilibria, so that the choice of a definition depends on the nature of the situation and the particular representation we use as a model. And although a part of contemporary theory seeks to remove the distinction, game theory traditionally divides its subject into two broad categories: noncooperative and cooperative game theory (or, in terms of their analytic representation, games in extensive or normal form versus games in characteristic function form). In noncooperative game theory, we suppose that players are unable to explicitly coordinate their decisions or that, if such coordination is possible, agreements are enforced by wholly endogenous considerations. The names of the equilibrium notions here that are especially relevant to our analysis are Nash equilibria and a refinement called subgame perfect equilibria. In the theory of cooperative games, on the other hand, we submerge the issue of enforcement, assume that coordination is possible, and look for those outcomes to which coordination might lead. In this instance, the relevant equilibrium notions are the core, the von Neumann-Morgenstern solution, the bargaining set, and the competitive solution. We will define each of these notions in this volume as we require them. Although this hypothesis is suggested by Blainey's (1973) argument, it is not intended to be an accurate restatement of that argument (see our discussion in Section 2.3).
8
1 Introduction
however, misperception is merely a precondition, a part of the characterization of the game national leaders play. What remains to be shown (and what is implicit in the hypothesis) is that, given such misperception, one or both parties choosing war describes the equilibrium of that game. This example also serves to illuminate a potential source of confusion in our terminology. Specifically, asserting that an international system is in equilibrium does not mean that there are no conflicts; the equilibrium choices of decision makers may be to war. Indeed, one of the implications of our paradigm is that with an appropriate conceptualization of the game decision makers play, all systems are in equilibrium at all times. It may be that a system is "in transition" - that wars move it from one type of equilibrium state to another - but because the transition path itself is the product of individual "rational" decisions, that path can be described as an equilibrium state. Our task, then, is not to ascertain whether anarchic international systems are in equilibrium; rather, it is to ascertain what kinds of equilibria are attainable under various circumstances. Throughout this book, then, we reserve the word "equilibrium" to denote the actions of decision makers that follow logically from their goals and the other relevant parameters of their environments. We use the word "stability" to describe the international systems in which conflicts of various sorts cannot arise. We should also clarify another source of confusion regarding equilibria. The analysis that follows is in the realist mode to the extent that it focuses on "the struggle for power in an anarchic environment [where] states fend for themselves as they pursue their contradictory interests" (Snidal 1986, p. 39). It is a common mistake to believe, however, that such situations can occasion neither equilibrium nor cooperation. Riker (1980, p. 443), for example, argues that if systems match this conflictual view then equilibria are impossible, in which case "we cannot know much about the future at all." However, in this instance Riker is adopting an especially narrow view of equilibria, one in which a specification of initial conditions determines uniquely the outcome that must prevail. The existence of such equilibria is rare, but the notion of an equilibrium does not refer to a single concept, and game theory offers a variety of definitions of equilibria. Some of these definitions are refinements of others, whereas some treat different classes of games. Although it is true that the conflictual circumstances with which realist thinking is concerned does not typically yield a simple variety of equilibria that occasions unique predictions, prediction in the form of a narrowing of possibilities is still possible. With respect to the issue of cooperation in the conflictual politics envisioned by the realist school, Keohane correctly asserts that
1.1 Perspectives
9
Cooperation takes place only in situations in which actors perceive that their policies are actually or potentially in conflict, not where there is harmony. Cooperation should not be viewed as the absence of conflict, but rather as a reaction to conflict or potential conflict. Without the specter of conflict, there is no need to cooperate (1984, p. 54).
The only qualification we need add is that cooperation is excluded if there are only two parties to the conflict and if the conflict is absolute - if the situation is zero sum. Barring this possibility, which we believe is actually rare in international politics, the various solution hypotheses of game theory (definitions of equilibrium) have as their objective predicting the form of cooperation that ensues. Goals of decision makers We do not suppose that peace requires that international leaders - those who control the destinies of sovereign states - be compelled to act one way or another by idealistic objectives. We cannot assume that a stable or an unstable international system emerges only if decision makers desire such a system. Scenarios such as the Prisoners' Dilemma tell us that even unanimous consent to some objective is no guarantee that people will choose actions that yield the desirable outcome (see, e.g., Olson 1965). Moreover, people may prefer stability to instability or peace to conflict, but these cannot be ultimate objectives. If we wish to assume that nations seek peace or conflict, we must show that such goals are the logical result of the operation of international political systems. Because we do not want to assume our result (that particular systems lead to peace and that others lead to conflict), we must begin with more fundamental objectives and derive the circumstances under which peace or conflict will prevail as the logical consequence of the relationship among states. Ultimate objectives, presumably, might include things such as maintaining one's domestic political power, securing economic benefits for oneself, or even ensuring one's personal survival. Stability (or instability) emerges, then, as a by-product of the pursuit of more fundamental individual objectives. The same argument holds true for balance of power. If a balance of power as we define it later emerges in our analysis, it does so because it can be interpreted as satisfying some more basic objectives of decision makers. It may be true that leaders seek to maintain a balance and that a "balance of power lasts only so long as someone is ready to take risks to maintain it" (Wight 1973, p. 115), but only insofar as a balance serves specific purposes or is the logical result of the pursuit of those purposes. To postulate the pursuit of balance as a primitive objective is to assume what
10
1 Introduction
it is that we are trying to establish: that a balance can emerge in anarchic systems comprised of egoistic decision makers. Domestic versus international politics Theorizing about any phenomenon requires simplification, and in the area of international politics it is often tempting to render our analysis more tractable by ignoring domestic politics. Unfortunately, in specifying the goals of decision makers in international affairs and in identifying their relevant environment, we cannot ignore "mundane" domestic concerns. Certainly, people might be motivated to secure an honorable mention in history's footnotes, and expressions of individual goals may take the form of the lofty rhetoric of international leadership and world peace. However, more commonly, such decision makers are motivated by more immediate concerns such as the establishment or maintenance of a domestic political advantage or, in the case of agents for multinational firms, the pursuit of economic advantage. We need only document those international conflicts that distract attention from domestic problems and thereby undermine domestic political opposition to see how domestic political constraints shape decisions in the international arena. This means that a theoretical dichotomy between international and domestic politics cannot be viable, or at least we must be prepared to formulate an analysis that allows for the eventual bridging of such a dichotomy.4 Rejection of the ultimate viability of such a dichotomy implies that we cannot suppose that conflict is caused by leaders who pursue the "wrong" goals or that peace is secured by more enlightened leaders. Although we cannot discount the influence of a single radical element, the logic of peace and conflict are to be found in the functioning of international systems as leaders react to each other, in the pursuit of their own goals, constrained by domestic politics. We cannot understand the emergence and influence of dominant figures without also exploring the domestic sources of their 4
This is particularly so if the classic grounds for theoretically distinguishing international from domestic politics lies in the "anarchy" of international politics in contradistinction to the "order" of domestic politics. As we argue shortly, the existence or nonexistence of well-defined political rule-systems is a function of the self-interest of political actors. The existence or nonexistence of explicit rule-systems is an endogenous variable, and thus we cannot appeal to the endogeneity of rules to distinguish international from domestic politics. If the international polity is anarchic and the domestic polity archie, it is not because international and domestic politics are categorically different things, but because actors while pursuing essentially equivalent goals in both - generally find strategic advantage in elaborating explicit rule-systems domestically but do not find such advantage in the international arena. Indeed, a study of revolutions and coups d'etat suggests that, in a wide range of cases, domestic politics is as much a Hobbesian state of nature as anything in the international arena.
1.1 Perspectives
11
power and the imperatives of other national leaders with whom they must interact. The problem at hand is raised with particular acuity by Bueno de Mesquita in his discussion of the role of strong leadership in foreignpolicy decision making: We can logically assume, then, that decisions to make war are dominated by a single individual in each state Foreign policies related to war are almost always associated in our minds with individuals such as Richelieu, Metternich, or Bismarck Of course, no leader can afford to ignore completely the desires and interests of those who follow him. Without some support, even the most coercive dictator cannot hope to muster sufficient resources to wage a successful war. Still, it is ultimately the responsibility of a single leader to decide what to do and how to do it (1981a, pp. 27-8).
Although our theoretical analysis, like Bueno de Mesquita's, treats states as unitary actors, the source of our disagreement with this quotation lies in the possibility of confusing institutional arrangements of command and control with the underlying political structure that makes effective leadership possible. The ability of a leader to exercise his institutional authority is determined by a complex set of domestic political games that both constrain and enable such a leader to varying degrees. A model that assumes that such a leader is free to act as he wills cannot explain either why or how a leader acts; it amounts to assuming the explanation. Thus, attention to the constraints imposed by domestic politics is an essential component of any fully comprehensive attempt to predict outcomes in the international system. If domestic politics and these constraints are not incorporated in the analysis, our theory must at least permit us to see how its conclusions are modified when subsidiary analyses identify those constraints. That theory should inform us, moreover, about the forces international politics exert on domestic politics. The issue of the role of domestic politics raises an interesting problem with the "levels-of-analysis" debate in the study of international relations. The paradigm we have embraced provides, if not a complete resolution of the matter, at least a perspective for addressing the issue and organizing our research. Singer poses the problem in the following way: . . . one could, at the systemic level, postulate that when the distribution of power in the international system is highly diffused, it is more stable than when the discernible clustering of well-defined coalitions occurs. And at the subsystemic or national level, the same empirical phenomena would produce this sort of proposition: when a nation's decision makers find it difficult to categorize other nations readily as friend or foe, they tend to behave toward all in a more uniform and moderate fashion. Now, taking these two sets of propositions, how much cumulative usefulness would arise from attempting to merge and codify the systemic proposition from the first illustration with the subsystemic proposition from the second, or vice versa? Representing different levels of analysis and couched in
12
1 Introduction
different frames of reference, they would defy theoretical integration; one may well be a corollary of the other, but they are not immediately combinable. A prior translation from one level to another must take place (1961, p. 92).
Waltz goes further, asserting that systemic and subsystemic explanations are not merely incommensurable, but that systemic explanations alone are the province of the study of international politics and that one cannot expect to obtain precise prediction of specific outcomes through studying international politics: An international political theory does not imply or require a theory of foreign policy any more than a market theory implies or requires a theory of the firm. Systems theories, whether political or economic, are theories that explain how the organization of a realm acts as a constraining and disposing force on the interacting units within it A theory of international politics bears on the foreign policies of nations while claiming to explain only certain aspects of them. It can tell us what international conditions national policies have to cope with. To think that a theory of international politics can in itself say how the coping is likely to be done is the opposite of the reductionist error (1979, p. 72). Waltz, nevertheless, comes closest to our view when he states: Causes at the level of units interact with those at the level of structure, and because they do so, explanation at the unit level alone is bound to be misleading. If an approach allows the consideration of both unit-level and structural-level causes, then it can cope with both the changes and the continuities that occur in a system (1988, p. 618).
The problem for the policy analyst, though, is in the inability to specify precisely the relationship between systemic and subsystemic variables in such a way as to guarantee predictive power over specific outcomes, but a simple example illuminates the contribution our paradigm might make. Assume that three individuals - A, B, and C - bargain, under majority rule, to divide $100. The various approaches in cooperative game theory agree that the structure of this interaction will result in an outcome in which two of the individuals will coalesce to divide the money evenly among themselves, excluding the third participant. In this sense, the structure of the system determines the general character of the outcome - the emergence of a two-person minimum winning coalition that divides the money evenly and excludes the third person. That is, the structure of the system provides a shell that discloses the general form of the outcome. And if we change this structure to, say, one in which persons A and B together can earn $300, A and C can earn $400, and B and C can earn $500, then we can predict that if A and B coalesce, they will divide their winnings $100-200; if A and C coalesce, they will agree to a $100-300 division; and if B and C coalesce, they will split $200-300. In this way, structure sets the constraints on eventual outcomes, and our theory identifies
1.1 Perspectives
13
those constraints. Furthermore, no new theoretical ideas are required to accommodate increases in the number of participants, changes in payoffs, or even alterations in the structure of payoffs from bargaining over dollars to bargaining over, say, policy in some multidimensional issue space. If, on the other hand, we want to predict which particular two-person coalition will emerge in a specific instance - in our example, the alternatives are {A,B}, [A, C}, {B, C] - then we must know a great deal about the details of perception and preference for A, B, and C and the priors they bring to the bargaining process before we can make any accurate prediction. Does A feel more secure dealing with Bl Are there cultural barriers to C s dealing with Al What are the subsidiary games A, B, and C will play that we have thus far ignored in the analysis? Are there domestic political imperatives that we have also ignored that render particular coalitions difficult to enforce? Indeed, it is our experience, after observing hundreds of sessions of undergraduates confronting theoretically equivalent decision tasks in experimental environments, that it may be impossible to determine precisely which coalition will form ultimately. Girlfriends coalesce against boyfriends and classmates against each other; quiet negotiators prevail, as do hard bargainers; and age, sex, and race, if they predict anything at all, predict with minimal significance. Nevertheless, despite the great variety of factors that seem to influence outcomes, the coalitions that emerge and the outcomes that form the basis of agreements nevertheless fit (or closely approximate) the macropattern proscribed by theory. Thus, these and similar considerations pour content into the shell provided by the structural variables our analysis identifies. Prediction of actual coalition behavior in specific instances must be predicated on identifying both the shell and its contents. Our paradigm thus elucidates the relationship between systemic and subsystemic variables in the analysis of international politics. This relationship and the role of the paradigm is illustrated further by an analysis of the general structure of the European great-power alliance system in the last quarter of the nineteenth century. Without attention to the domestic political constraints impinging on international actors, we would be at a loss to predict which nations will ally with which others, that is, we would be unable to predict specific outcomes from either the shell or the content alone. Thus, when examining European great-power alliance formation and conflict resolution, 18711914, in Chapters 7 and 8, we consider some general constraints on action that model the effects of their bargaining in the international arena. However, with Waltz's observation in mind, we also remain sensitive to the modification of domestic constraints by the imperatives of international forces.
14
1 Introduction
Problems uncovered by the theory of social choice Another way in which our paradigm highlights the importance of the interaction of systemic and subsystemic variables in international relations is related to the problems associated with treating aggregates such as the nation-state as individual actors. Any attempt to view nations as unitary actors - as decision makers with well-defined (consistent) goals and preferences - is an abstraction we can apply only with great care. Here we must follow the logic of Kenneth Arrow's (1957) classic theorem, which tells us that regardless of the social and political construction of a state, circumstances may arise in which the actions implemented by political leaders and the heads of multinational firms may not be consistent with any identifiable goal (see Bueno de Mesquita 1981a, pp. 12-18). Although it is convenient from time to time to speak of countries as maximizing their power, resources, and so forth, or offirmsmaximizing market shares and profits, we must be cognizant that such actions are themselves the product of domestic political and economic processes, and that those processes need not be consistent with any identifiable objective for any collectivity. Arrow's theorem and subsidiary results appear to pose a dilemma for any theory that treats collectivities, such as nation-states, as unitary actors. Among the subsidiary results causing the greatest concern is McKelvey's proof (1976,1979) that if decisions are made by majority rule and if we can characterize outcomes as concerning some multidimensional issue space, then even the slightest intransitivity in the social preference order (which occurs whenever every feasible outcome can be upset by some other outcome) requires that the intransitivity encompass the entire issue space. This, in turn, implies that a skillful agenda setter, by the judicious ordering of a sequence of pairwise voting comparisons, has the opportunity to choose from a considerable range of outcomes which outcome will eventually prevail. McKelvey's result might seem to merely open the door to the assumption that any collectivity's preference ought to be reducible, ultimately, to some agenda setter's preference - that an implicit dictatorship cannot be avoided. However, another result of Gibbard (1973) and Satterthwaite (1975) establishes that all procedures of social decision are potentially manipulable. Regardless of the procedure used - be it a simple one such as majority rule with an agenda, or a complex one such as the description we might give to congressional-presidential decision making - that procedure is subject to the strategic revelation of preferences by as few as one and as many as all participants in the decision process. McKelvey's result and Gibbard and Satterthwaite's theorem, taken together, appear to imply the impossibility of imputing a simple discernible preference for any collectivity. Indeed, they suggest that such preferences
1.1 Perspectives
15
emerge only in the context of complex strategic calculation and manipulation. This causes one scholar familiar with this literature to conclude that social decision processes are not merely complex - a fact we already know - but also that imponderable and unpredictable considerations, such as the relative strategic skills of individuals and the precise timing of events, can profoundly affect social decisions and, thus, the implied social preference order over outcomes (Riker 1982). We do not require such theorems to learn that social processes are complex or that the flow of history often turns on critical events. Yet, these theorems are important because they prove and generalize our intuition; and, just as importantly, the research they stimulate yields insight into the potential sources of greater predictability and coherence of social decisions. We have learned, for example, that such coherence does not require even an approximate social consensus over what outcomes ought to be selected. Instead, coherence is supplied in majority-rule systems, for example, if there is unanimity merely over the criteria used to evaluate outcomes (Black 1958) or if the correlation of preferences is "sufficiently great" (Niemi 1969). In this instance, then, we can think of coherence as being supplied by socialization, shared values, and a common perception of the issue under consideration at any point in time. Coherence can also be supplied by various institutional constraints. Although theoretical analysis here has just begun, one apparent implication is if the rules and procedures of social decision are exogenous - if the mechanisms used by a collectivity for aggregating individual preferences and choice into a social choice are not subject simultaneously to reconsideration and change then it is possible to constrain decisions so as to vitiate the implications of intransitive social preferences. Because we cannot survey a vast subfield in a few pages, we cannot delve deeply into the details of abstract theoretical reasoning so as to uncover fully the insights provided by that reasoning. However, the preceding discussion points to two general sources of coherence in social decision: coherence emerging from the constraints of socialization, and coherence emerging from the constraints of institutions when coupled with a consensus on the legitimacy of those institutions. Interestingly, middle-range theory assessing foreign-policy decision making in terms of domestic political variables follows, tacitly, the lines suggested by this analysis of coherence in social decision. The operational-code approach (Leites 1951; George 1969; Holsti 1970; McClellan 1971; Walker 1977; Campbell, Darvich, and Rose 1983) focuses on the consequences of value socialization for preference formation. The bureaucratic politics (Lindblom 1965; Allison 1971; Allison and Halperin 1971) and organization process (Snyder, Bruck, and Sapin 1962; Cyert and March 1963; Allison 1971) approaches focus on the consequences of various institutional arrangements for preference
16
1 Introduction
formation. These results, in turn, permit us to understand more accurately the role of the assumption that we introduce in the next chapter: that nation-states are unitary actors seeking to ensure their continued sovereignty and to maximize their resources. We do not make this assumption because we believe that such a coherent objective necessarily characterizes all the decisions of national leaders. Nor do we make this assumption because we accept Bueno de Mesquita's (1981a) judgment about the dominance of key decision makers in the determination of a country's foreign policy. Rather, we impose it because it is analytically convenient. It permits us to establish the implications for anarchic international systems of states that act, for whatever internal domestic reasons, in a proscribed way. We can then use this model to understand the implications of nationstates that do not act in accordance with our assumption, relating possible violations of our assumptions to the domestic factors suggested by the previous discussion. In this way, we can begin to build into our analysis a consideration of domestic politics and social processes. We emphasize, on this score, that taking cognizance of Arrow's theorem does not require that our models be reducible immediately to an analysis of individual decisions. The assumption of methodological individualism does not require a reductionist approach. Even economists hypothesize that certain collectivities such asfirmsact with a single objective (the maximization of profit), despite the fact that Arrow's theorem applies to any organization and despite the empirical evidence that key decision makers in firms are not always motivated primarily by the profit margins of their employers. What makes this assumption legitimate, however, is the subsequent demonstration that although the goals of the members of a firm need not concern profit, those firms that do not act as unitary agents in the pursuit of profit will disappear, supplanted by those that do. It is the Darwinian force of competitive markets, then, that assures that the consequences of Arrow's theorem will not vitiate the logic of subsequent deductions. Of necessity, then, we will assume that various collectivities in international affairs (specifically, nation-states) act as unitary agents. In doing so, however, we must give good arguments why the process of their internal politics ensures that outcome; or, minimally, why a collectivity that does not act as if it holds a collective goal will either be supplanted by some other form or will otherwise adapt to its exigencies. General adequacy of the paradigm Many students of international affairs might believe that the "rationalchoice" paradigm is inappropriate for their subject. After all, despite
1.1 Perspectives
17
Blainey's (1973, p. 249) conclusion that "no wars are unintended or 'accidental,'" and despite the lessons learned from games such as the Prisoners' Dilemma, wars nevertheless give the appearance of being the consequence of seemingly irrational actions by persons with clear incentives to act rationally. And it is reasonable to suppose that the next great war, if it occurs, will be the penultimate irrational act for our species - in which case, our fear of it seems to be an admission of the possibility of irrational choice. Before turning to our substantive focus, then, we should comment on the adequacy of our paradigm for the study of politics in general and international relations in particular. Such discussions are, of course, already extensively represented in the literature (see, e.g., Harsanyi 1969, and Riker and Ordeshook 1973). Stating our position briefly, the assumption of rational action or the hypothesis that people maximize utility is not subject to direct empirical test. Arguing whether people are rational or not makes little sense, at least within the confines of the paradigm. We judge a person "rational" if that person's decisions are understandable to us or appear that they might be rendered understandable with some attribution of goals and perceptions, imbedded in a tractable model of the decision environment; we judge people "irrational" only if we choose to relegate their actions to the world of the inexplicable. Understanding, on the other hand, is provided by the models we develop for the specific substantive issue before us. Thus, rationality is not an empirical hypothesis like others we might derive from it; rather, its "test" consists of ascertaining whether and to what extent the models based on it (and their corresponding explanations) possess any advantage over other approaches. Naturally, we cannot use the efforts of a single researcher as a basis for any definitive evaluation of the paradigm: it can always be said that we failed to achieve worthwhile insights because of the researcher's deficiencies. Nevertheless, the course of much of the recent theorizing about why people vote gives us some insight into the paradigm's promise as well as the problems we encounter with it. Nearly any representation of the decision to vote suggests that if people are concerned solely with the instrumental benefit of voting versus abstaining - defined in terms of which candidate wins and which loses - then few if any citizens should vote. Thus, it appears that people vote merely because they are socialized to do so, in which case the decision-theoretic structure of our paradigm must be augmented somehow to secure an understanding of this fundamental political act. This does not mean, however, that people are irrational, or that they do not maximize expected utility, or that this application of the paradigm fails to provide valuable insights. Rather, it suggests (but does not prove) that much of the voting decision is determined by considerations exogenous to the particular
18
1 Introduction
election being considered, that expected utility calculations focusing on the parameters of a particular election may be largely irrelevant to the voting act, and that the greater explanatory power in this case is promised by a study of the origins of taste and of the affective (as against instrumental) value people place on the act of voting. This example should also dispel the misperception that our paradigm assumes a world populated by egoists who cannot be motivated by altruism or other "socially conscious" objectives. Admittedly, our analysis assumes an egoism of the sort in which decision makers are unconcerned with the welfares of other states aside from how those welfares affect, via the selection of strategies, the resources and sovereignty of their state. However, this assumption is a hypothesis; it is not a requisite part of the paradigm. The analysis of voting reveals that if we cannot explain the decision to vote by motives that focus on a single voter's influence of the outcome of who wins and who loses, then we must entertain speculations in which the act of voting itself has affective value. Similarly, we may find that people's decisions in contexts that concern us here must also be modified. The point is that we cannot learn whether a modification is required until we explore the implications of a pure form of egoism; furthermore, the possibility of a modification that admits of altruism is not precluded a priori. To be more specific, we could, of course, assume that some national leaders maximize the prospects for world peace, whereas others seek conflict; but because such actions are "close" to the outcomes we want to understand, this attribution of goals threatens a vacuous tautology - one that fits historical facts well but, because of its specificity, yields little generalized predictive power. Thus, we substitute more remote goals instead, in this instance, the desire to maximize a country's relative resources, tempered by the constraint of ensuring its sovereignty. Admittedly, though, even this goal is removed from what geneticists tell us is a more fundamental individual motivation, the maximization of one's "fitness." However, although such a goal promises more generality, the necessity for translating it into predictions about actions requires models that we are not yet equipped to develop. Thus, research within the paradigm necessarily entails a trade-off between generality and tractability, and much of the researcher's art consists of reaching an acceptable balance within the domain of these two dimensions, a balance that must always be prepared to give way to new theoretical developments. The issue as to whether people are "rational" continues nevertheless to arise in political theory, largely because some people believe that simple constructs and words can adequately label and convey the meaning of
1.1 Perspectives
19
complex ideas. Rationality is not a simple elementary concept in our paradigm. It not only embodies a set of axioms about preferences (that they are complete and transitive), but, in addition, much of what game and decision theorists do can be interpreted as the discovery of the meaning of this word in different contexts. Thus, rationality in noninteractive environments may mean choosing actions that can be interpreted as maximizing utility or expected utility; in noncooperative games, it may mean the selection of strategies that are consistent with one definition of equilibrium or another; and in a cooperative game, it may mean the selection of outcomes and the formation of coalitions that are consistent with some solution hypothesis. Indeed, the meaning of rationality is sufficiently complex that very little would be lost if we simply banished the word altogether from our vocabulary. As afinalnote of caution, we should guard against prematurely rejecting our paradigm whenever the complexity of reality seems to defy the development of tractable models based on its precepts. Because we want to use the precise language of mathematics to deduce our hypotheses, thereby ensuring that those hypotheses follow logically from explicitly stated assumptions, we simplify our representations of reality to ensure tractability. This bothers many scholars who see and appreciate politics in all of its complexity. For these scholars, mathematical tractability seems a hinderance to understanding. To some extent this criticism is fair, but only if we abide by a naive view of the role of formal theory. Certainly, it should not be used to judge the paradigm as inappropriate to our subject. The pursuit of scientific understanding is more an art than it is the application of some mechanical formula for proving theorems or conducting empirical research. Because international systems are much too complex to be adequately summarized by any single model, theorem, or set of regression equations, the expression of that art is a coherent combination of whatever theoretical structures we possess, dictated by our general understanding of our subject - an understanding that informs our application of rigorously derived results, which in turn refine that understanding. Applications of the simple Prisoners' Dilemma game to politics provide a useful example. Briefly, such games reveal how sometimes the simple structuring of decisions by circumstance can decisively effect outcomes, in particular, the inability of people to achieve mutually beneficial (Paretooptimal) outcomes. It is hardly profound, however, to assert that little of the real world fits comfortably into the simple structure of a 2 x 2 game. Nevertheless, although we might deem such models imperfect reflections of reality owing to their simplicity, our general understanding of social processes tells us that an important component of those processes is that
20
1 Introduction
politics is a continuing sequence of social interaction and that our actions today are dictated, in part, by how they affect the play of future games. Thus, as we become more technically sophisticated and consider multiperiod versions of the dilemma (Taylor 1976 and Axelrod 1984), or dilemmas in which players possess incomplete information about the game (Kreps and Wilson 1982), our ability to explain additional patterns of action (such as cooperation, threats, and the selection of alternatives that minimize utility in the short run) increases. At this point, however, further analysis requires the mathematical complexity some prefer to avoid. Yet, even at this stage, we can begin to glean important lessons about the precise role of reputation and commitment in circumstances as diverse as terrorist threats, nuclear deterrence, military intervention, and revolution (e.g., Rose 1986; Powell 1987, 1988; Alt, Calvert, and Humes 1988; and Wagner 1988). Even if we stop here, commonalities in empirical phenomena are revealed, so that what was originally seen as diverse phenomena are now known to be manifestations of common theoretical principles. The anarchy of international systems The theory of international systems set forth in this book does not attribute conflict or peace to the presence or absence of various types of international organizations. Indeed, we begin with the supposition that international systems are anarchic in the sense that there exists no exogenously determined organization or structure, save the primitive rule that countries with greater resources can defeat countries with fewer resources. That is, referring to the concept of regimes rather than systems, we follow Keohane (1984, p. 98), citing Young (1979, p. 35), observing that international regimes are decentralized institutions. Decentralization does not imply an absence of mechanisms for compliance, but it does mean that any sanctions for violation of regime principles or rules have to be enacted by the individual members.
The particular issue we address is the emergence of stability, of implicit cooperation, when systems are anarchic. Again, this issue is defined by Keohane: The puzzle of compliance is why governments, seeking to promote their own interests, ever comply with the rules of international regimes when they view these rules as in conflict with what I will call their "myopic self-interest." Myopic selfinterest refers to governments' perception of the relative costs and benefits to them of alternative courses of action with regard to a particular issue, when that issue is considered in isolation from others (1984, p. 99).
Insofar as identifying the specifics of our task, it is tempting to suppose that what differentiates domestic politics from international politics is the
1.1 Perspectives
21
existence in domestic affairs of specific institutional structures that ameliorate the sources of conflict in society, and their absence in international politics. In its simplest form, this argument views the state as an agency authorized to resolve various social Prisoners' Dilemmas such as the provision of public goods, including domestic order and tranquility. Since no such agency exists in international affairs to resolve the dilemmas there for example, arms races that everyone prefers to avoid (see Waltz 1959, Jervis 1978, and Wagner 1983) - then achieving a goal of international peace and tranquility merely requires the establishment of supranational institutions.5 The argument in support of the proposition that peace can be secured via the establishment of "appropriate" supranational organizations supposes, as we do, that the structure of international political systems is anarchic. However, it also assumes, contrary to our approach, that this anarchy is the fundamental cause of conflict. This view is most clearly stated by Riker (1962) in his critique of Kaplan's (1957) analysis of the balance of power. Briefly, on the basis of his application of game theory to the balance-of-power literature, Riker concludes that international systems are inherently unstable, and that there are "only two ways of moderating instability, and only two": the method of moral restraint and the method of institutional constraint (p. 174). Thus, Riker abandons the possibility that simple self-interest can yield stability and argues, instead, that such stability must arise because of exogenous factors. Although our analysis differs significantly from Kaplan's, we cannot accept Riker's conclusion. If stability is to occur at all, it must arise from wholly endogenous considerations of self-interest. We do not dispute that such organizations could play an important role in reducing the costs of information and the likelihood of miscalculation. However, our argument is that an international system is not distinguishable from a domestic system simply by the presence or absence of specific types of institutions, procedural rules, behavioral norms, and the like. Nor do we suppose that supranational organizations per se are a prerequisite 5
As we suggested earlier, the enterprise of explaining the differences between international and domestic political systems in terms of an anarchy/hierarchy dichotomy is questionable. Specifically, it assumes that the ordering principle that determines whether a system is hierarchical or anarchic is exogenous to the system. If, however, the ordering principle is endogenous (i.e., arises from interactions of actors in the system), then differentiating between international and domestic political systems in terms of an ordering principle merely typologizes rather than explains. The endogeneity of rule formation within systems arising from the nonexludability of strategizing is one of the more important implications of our paradigm, and such a result is suggestive of a more fundamental explanation for behavior at both the systemic and subsystemic levels than the anarchy/hierarchy dichotomy provides.
22
1 Introduction
for stability. With respect to the character of domestic versus international systems, we agree that it may be easier to establish mechanisms for the enforcement of agreements in thefirstthan it is in the second, but it is easier only to the extent that decision makers find it in their interest to maintain the features of those institutions that regulate enforcement. We take the view that rules, procedures, and norms are endogenous to political systems: that they are established and maintained only to the extent to which they serve the interests of those who participate in them, and that their existence is governed by the same forces that govern the existence or nonexistence of stability itself. Thus, the objectives of a social or political institution primarily reflect the interests of its more powerful members. When these interests or the relative powers of individuals. . .change, there will be attempts to change the nature of the institution and its objectives in order to reflect significant changes in interests and power (Gilpin 1981, p. xi).
For the specific context of this volume, "if, for example, the equilibrium of the balance of power is maintained through states abiding by rules, then one needs to explain how agreement on the rules is achieved and maintained" (Waltz 1979, p. 121), in which case, for the issue of cooperation, using rational choice theory for the study of international cooperation implies that the relevant decisions of governments, and other actors, about whether to cooperate can be treated as if they were voluntary (Keohane 1984, pp. 70-1).
This argument leads to the view that supranational organizations are merely mechanisms for the implementation of agreements. It is not a gun that kills the victim, nor is it the availability of a gun that "causes" a killing. Rather, it is the person pulling the trigger who commits the homicide, and the gun is merely the mechanism he or she chose to implement an action. Similarly, supranational organizations may facilitate implementation, but we cannot say that they cause peace. They may be facilitating agents, but understanding their function and identifying the benefits that are believed to follow from their formation require that we understand them as the product of more fundamental processes. In short, we cannot use institutions to explain stability or vice versa; both must be understandable from the same source. 1.2
The dual nature of instability
Because this book is fundamentally about stability in international systems, it is essential that we understand this concept's dual nature, for it is that nature that often distinguishes between domestic and international politics. It is also here that we can begin to draw the outlines of the elementary forces that operate in and define international political systems.
1.2 The dual nature of instability
23
To see the dual nature of stability and instability most simply, let us proceed from a rudimentary bargaining game. Imagine that three people, whose initial wealth holdings are $20 each, must use majority rule in deciding how to divide an additional $90. One resolution, suggested by the majority-rule criterion and assuming that each person has an equal vote, is that two people coalesce to divide the sum evenly among themselves, excluding the third from any increment. Thus, persons 1 and 2 might propose to allocate the $90fifty-fifty,and to exclude 3 from any gains. However, person 3 could then offer 2 a "better deal," such as a proposal to divide the amount sixty-forty between 2 and 3, respectively. Person 1 could then respond by offering 3 thefifty-fiftydeal at the expense of 2. Clearly, this cycle continues indefinitely. Notice now that if we repeat this game several times in succession, using an additional $90 each time in the sequence, we could observe any number of possibilities, such as multiperiod coalitions that are periodically broken up by an "irresistible" offer of the excluded player, or the "complete instability" of constantly shifting allegiances and coalitions. An important feature of this scenario to remember, however, is that unless one or more of the participants feels compelled by ethical considerations - if, to properly describe motivations, we must augment the simple objective of maximizing one's wealth with the assumption that people also prefer to avoid "inequitable" distributions of income - the current holdings of a player should be irrelevant to how the next $90 is divided. That is, regardless of the current distribution of income, each person retains his one-third share of the "vote" in deciding how to divide the next $90. Each redistributive opportunity in this sequence corresponds to what game theorists refer to as a simple constant-sum cooperative game that has no core.6 It is constant-sum because our three decision makers cannot 6
Briefly, the core of a cooperative game consists of all outcomes such that, once at one of them, no person or no collection of persons who might coordinate their choices (a coalition) has the desire or the wherewithal to unilaterally move to some other outcome. The definition of the core, then, parallels the definition of (Nash) equilibria for noncooperative games - games that do not permit players to explicitly coordinate choices. Such a noncooperative equilibrium corresponds to a conjunction of strategies, one for each player, such that no player has the incentive to shift to any other available strategy. The core can be viewed as such an equilibrium if we substitute coalitions for players and the outcomes they can secure as strategies. Thus, a cooperative game without a core can, in principle, cycle endlessly as one coalition supplants the outcome proposed by a previous agreement. This does not mean, however, that we cannot predict outcomes if the core is empty. The solution theory of cooperative game theory, although relinquishing the goal of identifying a unique outcome as its prediction, seeks to identify limits on the range of outcomes that can prevail. For example, in a three-person divide-the-dollar game, we can in principle cycle endlessly through all possible divisions, but most variants of solution theory limit the eventual outcome to those three in which two players divide the dollar evenly between themselves.
24
1 Introduction
create or destroy wealth, only redistribute it. It does not have a core because, regardless of what redistribution is proposed, there is another distribution that a majority strictly prefer and that they can secure if they coalesce. Furthermore, if we look at each game in the sequence in isolation from the rest, then the various solution hypotheses treating games without cores all render an identical prediction that accords with our intuition: the formation of a minimal winning majority coalition that evenly divides the $90 among its members. Stated in the formal notation of the game theorist: the value of a coalition C in the first play of this game, v(C), is $20 if C consists of a single member, is $90 plus $20 plus $20 if C contains two members, and equals $90 plus $60 if C contains three members.7 Game theory then predicts that an outcome such as ({1,2}, {3), $65, $65, $20) will prevail in thefirstperiod - that a coalition such as [1,2) will form against {3}, add $45 to the wealth of each of its members, and leave 3 with his initial holding. If the game is repeated a second time with a new $90 subject to redistribution, then f(l) = f(2) = $65, y(3) = $20, v(l, 2) = $220, v(l, 2) = v{29 3) = $175, and u(l, 2,3) = $240. Again, we would predict that some minimal winning coalition will form to divide the next $90 evenly between its members. Notice now that the players in this scenario need not be concerned about the existence of future games in the sequence when deciding how to play a current game. Although the outcome of the current game determines each person's relative wealth, it in no way affects future strategic possibilities. In each game of the sequence, there is precisely $90 to be divided and every person shares one-third of the total vote. In fact, even if we let the current wealth of each person (in addition to the $90) be subject to redistribution, so that the situation is a pure redistributive game, the nature of the instability remains unchanged, as do the strategic considerations of the players. The value of a "single-member coalition" is now zero since it cannot ensure itself anything, the value of a two-member coalition in the first round is $150 since it can reallocate all available wealth, and 7
The notation v(C) is called the characteristic function value of the coalition C. Briefly, v(C) is commonly defined as the set of payoffs the members of C can guarantee for themselves by appropriately coordinating their strategies - the security level of C. There are, however, a variety of alternative definitions of the characteristic function, depending on whether the game concerns a freely transferable resource (games with side payments, such as when some form of exchange is possible), and whether all individual utility functions over this resource are linear (transferable utility, such as when money is equated with utility). If both assumptions are satisfied, then v(C) can be summarized by a single number the amount of resources, money, etc. that C can guarantee for its members and that it can ensure will be at the disposal of its members for distribution. Notice that this definition, because it is based on the notion of a coalition's security value, admits the possibility that the players excluded from C act irrationally in holding C down to its security level. However, in Chapter 4 we modify the definition of v(C) to take account of the rational responses of those countries excluded from the coalition.
1.2 The dual nature of instability
25
a typical predicted outcome is ((1,2), (3);$75, $75, $0). If this game is played a second time, with an additional $90 subject to redistribution,
v(l) = v(2) = v(3) = $0, v(l, 2) = v(l, 3) = v(2,3) = v(l, 2,3) = $240. Although we may witness wider swings in wealth as coalitions form and dissolve in a repeated play of this game, each person "remains in the game," someone to be reckoned with as a potential coalition partner in the game's next redistributive round. The preceding scenario is not much different from the one which Riker (1962) uses to argue that international political systems are inherently unstable. Specifically, if ru r2, and r3 are the resources controlled by persons 1, 2, and 3, respectively, and if K equals the resources added to the current round for redistribution (in addition to the sum R = r{ + r2 + A*3), then v(C) =R+K if the coalition C is any majority; otherwise, if C is losing, i>(C) = 0. In this case, an empty core means that, regardless of what coalition proposes to form and how it intends to distribute its payoff, there always exists some other coalition and proposed redistribution that members of the new coalition can secure and unanimously prefer. Put differently, the set of feasible coalitions and alternative redistributions is an all-encompassing cycle that leads from any distribution to any other distribution, and back again. Now suppose we modify the situation in the following way: although majority rule continues to be the decisive criterion, let each person's "voting weight" be endogenous and equal the resources he or she presently controls relative to all others. If this game is played once, then the players' strategic considerations are not much different from what wefindin a single play of the game in our first scenario. Although voting weights are no longer equal, if there are only three players, if no player's weight is zero, and if no player already controls a majority share of weight, then (as with equal weights) any two players can form a minimal winning coalition that expropriates all available resources. On the other hand, if this game is repeated several times, then the participants' strategic considerations and actions should be quite different from what we anticipate in our previous scenario. Now current holdings play a critically important role since, for example, if any player secures a majority share then he or she becomes dictator in all subsequent games. That is, the existence of future games affects one's thinking about the current game; so, by rendering voting weight endogenous rather than exogenous, the game becomes one of survival in which one or two players can be permanently "retired," rather than a game that is merely concerned with the allocation of money. In summary, then, our two scenarios - thefirstwith exogenous and equal voting weights and the other with endogenous weights - are equivalent if they are played once. However, strategic considerations differ markedly if the players know that the game will be repeated a succession of times.
26
1 Introduction
Thus, combining endogenous weights with repeated play yields a situation that differs significantly from the game Riker uses to analyze international conflict and the balance of power. We draw this distinction for two reasons. First, we want to emphasize the different character of the instabilities in each game and the corresponding differences in the players' strategic considerations. Second, although features of both situations can be found in international political processes, the first situation is more frequently found in domestic politics - at least in reasonably stable democracies - whereas the second is especially germane to the study of international relations. With respect to strategic considerations, notice that in thefirstscenario, players may be quite willing to let a coalition partner secure an advantage since part of the pie is better than none at all. Further, even if everyone knows that the situation will be repeated more than once, each can still concentrate on the current round. Long-term multitrial coalitions are no more stable than single-trial agreements and, because a player retains his or her vote regardless of what coalitions form, agreements in the current round have no bearing on strategic possibilities in future rounds. The second scenario, though, is profoundly different. There participants must guard against agreements in which one person secures a majority of the wealth, since such a person is predominant and can expropriate all available resources. Everyone must guard against having his wealth reduced to zero, since that outcome permanently removes a person from the game. For example, I might agree in the first scenario to let you be the principle beneficiary of a decision to expropriate the resources from a third party. Although I prefer other outcomes, I may feel compelled to this outcome in order to forestall expropriation of my own resources. However, with endogenous voting weights measured by resources, such an agreement may only temporarily postpone my eventual elimination from the game. I will merely become your next victim if I permit you to secure a majority of the resources from the third player. Correspondingly, negotiation strategies and the attention participants pay to multiperiod consequences are likely to be significantly different in the second scenario than in the first. This view of strategic possibilities is perhaps no more forcefully illustrated than by this example from Kennedy (1987, p. 139): The Russian general Kutusov, wishing to halt his army's westward advance in 1812, once the Grand Army had been driven from the homeland, may have spoken for more than himself when he doubted the wisdom of totally destroying Napoleon, since the "succession would not fall to Russia or to any other continental power, but to the power which already commands the sea, and whose domination would be intolerable." Thus, although the first scenario presents us with those instabilities we commonly associate with zero- or constant-sum cooperative games, the
1.2 The dual nature of instability
27
second scenario adds an additional consideration. Not only might we cycle indefinitely as we renegotiate the resources each of us controls, but there is also a potential instability in the number of viable participants. One or more of the players may be so weak - either because of initial inequities in the distribution of resources or because he or she previously agreed to outcomes that were inappropriate to his or her welfare - that he or she may be incapable of securing existence through negotiation and reallocation. Thus, whereas the first scenario offers us a view of what we might term the "microinstability" of shifting alliances and coalitions in constant-sum games, the second scenario adds the possibility of the "macroinstability" of the game's viable participants. The second scenario, moreover, alerts us to the possibility of observing macrostable, but microunstable, systems. The second reason for distinguishing between our two scenarios is the different purposes to which they can be applied in politics. Insofar as domestic politics are concerned, we might use our second scenario to characterize such politics when the forces of economic competition and governmental regulation threaten the economic viability of firms, or when economic status fully measures political influence. For example, if votes are irrelevant because net wealth determines and measures political power, then "voting weights" are endogenous and can be set permanently to zero. This scenario also is obviously relevant to the study of regimes characterized by revolution and armed unrest, where the measure of each competing interest's political influence is its military capability. Of course, the first scenario is also relevant to the study of domestic politics, especially in constitutional democracies with constitutional guarantees to enfranchisement and representation. Legislators may negotiate the reallocation of public resources, but, barring radical political change and subject only to the laws of population variability, legislative districts and the representation of citizens is best treated as exogenous. Despite the fact that we might use both scenarios to model various aspects of domestic politics, only the second seems relevant to the representation of international political processes. Because there are no supranational authorities capable of guaranteeing the representation or sovereignty of countries, "voting weights" are necessarily endogenous. "Power" or economic and military resources, endogenously determined by the vitality of an economy or determined by a country's success at expropriation from others in earlier games, becomes the sole determinant of who can defeat whom and who can expropriate further from whom. It is this endogeneity that gives international politics its special role in human affairs while at the same time rendering organizations such as the League of Nations in the past and the United Nations today largely irrelevant to the central flow of events.
28
1 Introduction
It is the central premise of this volume, then, that the second of our two scenarios describes, albeit in highly simplified and abstract form, a basic process of politics - both domestic and international - and one of our tasks is to elaborate on this scenario so that it becomes a better approximation of reality, an approximation from which we can derive specific and testable hypotheses. At this point, however, we should note the special complications associated with analyzing multiperiod situations modeled after this scenario. In the case of thefirstscenario, an analysis is simplified considerably because we can treat each period as an isolated event. Because the outcome of one period does not prejudice strategic position in the next, we can simply look at optimal or stable decisions that take cognizance only of current factors. However, with the second scenario, the choices of decision makers in one period affect profoundly all future decisions, including even who will be relevant decision makers in the future. Because we do not want to assume initially that decision makers are stupid or naive, we must suppose that they take future conequences into account in deciding what to do now. In the lexicon of game theory, decision makers are playing a potentially unlimited extensive-form game, so strategies must tell them what to do under all possible contingencies, both present and future. Thus, by adopting the second scenario as our basic structural scheme, we must learn to accommodate complex, time-dependent, interactive decision making. Notice also that if we accept the proposition that the second scenario models international political processes, then quite directly, the concept of balance of power becomes the focus of our discussion. Indeed, having accepted the idea that stability, if it arises at all, must arise from wholly endogenous sources, we arrive at a conclusion wholly in accord with Harsanyi's (1969) argument that social processes and their dynamics can be understood only "in terms of the balance of power among the various social groups [nations] pressing for the arrangements most favorable to their own interests" (p. 535). However, in theorizing about international relations, perhaps no idea causes more difficulty or is a greater source of confusion than that of balance of power. Scholars are uncertain about whether this term refers to a theory of conflict and coalitions, to a description of international systems, to the goals of key decision makers, or to a normative prescription about how international systems ought to achieve peace. It should be evident from what we have said thus far, of course, that we reject the notion of balance of power as a goal or as a normative prescription: if balance in the form of system or resource stability prevails, it must do so regardless of whether all, some, or none of the states in the international system consciously aim to maintain a balance or profess balancing as their policy.
1.3 Theory in international relations
29
Nevertheless, even with this narrowing of definitions, the literature's theoretical disarray makes it virtually impossible to identify what ought to be a theoretical primitive and what ought to be a deduction. Should we assume that nations act to oppose other nations that seek to dominate the system, or should such assertions be deduced from more basic assumptions about national interest? What are the indicators of a system out of balance? Is a system unbalanced because the resources of specific countries or alliances do not satisfy certain equations (Zinnes 1967, 1970), or must we observe overt aggressive acts? Indeed, even those who approach the subject from our perspective of nations seeking to advance their own self-interest infer different conclusions as to the meaning of balance of power. To the extent that we rely on our second scenario as a starting point for modeling international relations processes, then quite directly we must formulate our own theory of the balance of power. Despite the confusion in the literature about its precise formulation, it is evident that such a theory ought to be concerned with identifying viable as against unviable alliances (coalitions), with identifying the conditions under which one set of countries will attempt to expropriate resources from another, and the conditions under which one or more countries will be eliminated, or at least rendered irrelevant to the strategic calculations of the remaining countries. However, these are precisely the questions the game theorist tries to answer when studying the games our scenario describes, so a theory of the balance of power becomes our primary product. 1.3
Theory in international relations
We noted earlier that the phenomena that concern social scientists are considerably more complicated than the phenomena treated by natural science, and thus we cannot suppose that a small set of assumptions and mathematical expressions can accommodate anything more than the broad outlines of the forces guiding events. Thus, aside from the obvious fact that our theories must remain abstractions, the models we construct with these theories are of necessity incomplete. For example, despite its continuous development and refinement over two centuries, a review of that most powerful of social theories - classical microeconomics - tells us that our ability to describe and predict even a very special class of social interactions is severely limited. Even today research continues into the causes of market failure, the mechanisms for accommodating uncertainty and incomplete information, and the interface between private and public sectors in areas such as regulation, tax policy, and international trade. Because markets are a component of international affairs, our task entails
30
1 Introduction
the same difficulties (on perhaps an even large scale) as those confronting our colleagues in other branches of the social sciences. We offer these comments so that the reader can properly interpret what follows in this volume. Our assumptions and deductions should not be taken as modeling any specific international process or historical eras, nor should we presume that our analysis is intended to be comprehensive of all possible considerations. Indeed, we acknowledge the fact that the particular assumptions that form the basis of our analysis are chosen not only because we believe that they lead to an understanding of substantively important and general features of international political affairs, but also because they facilitate deduction and analysis. Correspondingly, we do not regard as a criticism the comment that the use of mathematics and explicit assumptions renders the limitations of our analysis apparent. Such comments assure us that we have avoided, at least to some degree, a scientifically unacceptable sloppiness of thinking. As Waltz (1979, p. 11) observes: In international politics, whether because theories are contradictory or weak, discussion and argument about many important matters... are made difficult or useless because the participants are talking about different things while using the same terms for them. Movement towards a remedy is impeded by disinclination to treat the question of meaning as a problem that can be solved only through the articulation and refinement of theories.
To the extent that the forces our analysis uncovers can be interpreted as guiding us to other features of international systems we do not consider, then that fact merely points to the potential profitability of formally incorporating these other features into our analysis and thereby refining further the theory we offer. To illustrate the way in which this incorporation process might proceed, consider once again the "levels-of-analysis" issue. At the first level, we see history driven by the personality or skill of specific individuals. Germany is unified only because of Bismarck, the outbreak of World War II requires a Hitler, Churchill's intransigence keeps Germany from overwhelming Russia, a resurgence of Islam can be led only by a Khomeini, and the Cold War emerges as the result of Stalin's paranoia. At the second level, events are driven by more general features of domestic politics. Great Britain establishes an empire to feed its industrial growth, Germany and Japan's aggression is encouraged by the belief that the United States has not the will to engage its economy in war, and the notion of the nationstate will prove subservient to that of class. At the third and final level, international affairs are dictated by general forces that operate on nationstates. Britain sides with France to block the German threat of preponderance, and the United States seeks a rapprochement with China to forestall a hegemonic coalition between China and the Soviet Union.
1.3 Theory in international relations
31
The theory we offer coincides most closely with the third view, but the potentially devastating error we can make as analysts is to suppose that these views are in conflict - that to adopt one necessarily implies a rejection of the others. Indeed, it is foolhardy to disagree with the proposition that powerful personalities often change the course of history or that domestic politics are relevant to international affairs. Generally, the theory of cooperative games (as we have already noted) merely narrows the range of potentially observable coalitions, so that the specific coalition that forms in some circumstances may be dictated by chance, by the timing of ephemeral events, or by the relative bargaining skills of people. Thus, our "macrotheory" narrows down the range of outcomes, and we must appeal to some "microtheory" to refine those predictions further. Our paradigm, as we have argued, provides a particularly satisfying methodology for uniting these macro- and microtheories. Ideally, our microtheories should employ the same paradigm as our macrotheories. However, in the initial stages of theorizing, which describe the present circumstances of international relations theory, we must often proceed on a more ad hoc basis, and "patch" reality in from time to time. Still, we are confident that the apparently ad hoc flavor of the constraints assumed to operate at the microlevel is, in part, deceptive; they follow from the empirical results of theoretically driven research within the paradigm we have embraced. The fact that our theory is primitive also means that, in reviewing our assumptions, the reader should resist the temptation to begin mapping reality into the analysis, with the search for examples and counterexamples. These comments should not be interpreted as an argument against the empirical application of our theory, since we attempt such an application in the chapters following that theory's development. We are merely offering the caution that in any application or test, we must make a number of compromises. We must temper certain possibilities, for example, with our suppositions about the imperatives of domestic politics, the perceptions and beliefs of key decision makers, and the fact that national leaders are often involved in a complex nexus of games. And to these problems we can add the operationalization or measurement of key concepts. Despite our goal of deductive rigor, this problem remains with our analysis because, rather than grapple with the meaning of such words as power, we merely substitute abstract notation and a different word - resources. We do this, however, with the understanding that such concepts are primitive only at the macrolevel of our analysis and that, depending on substantive context, the analyst has some flexibility in choosing their meaning and measurement. Thus, applying our paradigm and the abstract propositions of our analysis to a complex reality is necessarily more an art than a science. Whether we have executed our art satisfactorily is left to the reader's judgment.
32
1 Introduction
1.4
Plan of this volume
We begin in Chapter 2 with a more extensive discussion of our second scenario, and, in particular, we explore its alternative manifestations and interpretations in politics. Simultaneously, we offer an initial elaboration of this scenario with the politics of international relations specifically in mind. It is here that we present our key assumptions about goals, capabilities, and the alternative actions available to decision makers, and it is here as well that we discuss in detail the specific abstractions we require for tractable analysis. It is also in this chapter that we define more carefully the notions of stability suggested by our second scenario - system and resource stability - and judge the extent to which they capture the meaning of stability in the literature. In Chapters 3 and 4, we turn to an analysis of our scenario, and it is here that we attempt to resolve directly the confusion in the balance-ofpower concept. We do this by reconceptualizing this concept in terms of our two notions of stability. In the case of system stability, we focus on each nation's ability to ensure its survival against every possible contingency threatening its sovereignty. However, even if system stability prevails, this does not mean that some country cannot force others to cede it some of their resources. Hence, a system is resource stable if no one, acting alone or in coalition with others, seeks to upset the current distribution of resources among nations. With these two notions of stability and with the supposition that national leaders are sophisticated decision makers who are cognizant of the ultimate consequences of their actions, we deduce necessary and sufficient conditions in Chapters 3 and 4 for the existence of system stability and resource stability, respectively, in ncountry systems. There are several avenues open for testing the model developed in Chapters 3 and 4, the most obvious being a survey of historical events and the data others use to test similar ideas. However, our theoretical analysis involves a number of assumptions about how people bargain and form coalitions in a specific structured situation. Because other assumptions may be plausible, a focus on the data history alone provides would not allow us to distinguish between a failure of the general theoretical perspective as against the necessity for revising our analysis of bargaining; that is, the general theoretical approach may be correct, but other bargaining assumptions may be more suitable. Thus, Chapter 4 concludes with an experimental test of the predictive accuracy of our assumptions and of the necessary and sufficient conditions for system and resource stability. Our experimental results are encouraging, although of necessity not definitive. Nevertheless, it is evident that regardless of whatever empirical
1.4 Plan of this volume
33
support we can gather for the model in Chapters 3 and 4, there are two essential missing elements. The first such element concerns the subject of preventive wars. We must confront the possibility that neither system nor resource instability is attributable wholly to some current "imbalance" in military position. Rather, such instability may result from the projections of future imbalances and from the corresponding perceived necessity for preventive wars (see Fay 1938; Brodie 1973; Organski and Kugler 1980; and Levy 1987). This dynamical view is reflected also in the debate over domestic versus defense spending and the issue of whether a country should invest resources optimally to maximize economic growth rather than appropriating those resources to maximize current military strength. Indeed, this debate shows why a simple static analysis based on some current distribution of national resources or power cannot capture all relevant aspects of the "balance-of-power" concept in general and the causes of war in particular. In response to such realities, the analysis in Chapter 5 extends the model from Chapters 3 and 4 by adding investment and resource growth as part of the decision criteria of national leaders, who must then judge coalitions and resource reallocations in terms of longer-term as well as immediate consequences. Such an extension, moreover, is natural to our model in that both system and resource stability seem to be precisely the issue involved in the debate over current versus future defense needs. Using these two concepts, the extended model accommodates resource growth as a determinant factor of system or resource stability, and provides an analysis of preventive wars in two ways. First, we let growth be a function of exogenous factors, summarized by a growth rate and an initial distribution of resources. Second, we let national leaders affect growth endogenously. As part of a sequential cooperative and noncooperative game, such leaders can vary the current and future military capabilities of countries by choosing investments into the future, hence the proportion of resources subject to growth. In this way, national leaders do more than simply try to anticipate future events. In choosing their investments and in deciding whether to engage in a preventive war, they must also anticipate the anticipations of others, the actions of others based on those anticipations, and so on, with the understanding that everyone is doing the same. To learn the conditions under which countries can invest and maintain their sovereignty, and when they might contemplate a preventive war because they cannot do so, the analysis in Chapter 5 describes the necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of system and resource stability in this interactive, dynamic setting. The second element missing from our analysis concerns geography and the asymmetrical role resources play with respect to this factor. History
34
1 Introduction
tells us that, although land armies may be effective for attacking a continguous adversary, they may be useless against one with even a modest water barrier; and a tenet of today's strategic thinking is that modern technology fundamentally changes the implications of such barriers and distance. This argument's implication is that formulations of balance of power in which resources are treated symmetrically, although providing an initial understanding of the problem as well as the basic structure for theoretical refinements, may mislead us as to the necessary and sufficient conditions for stability, and that they may be inappropriate for interpreting historical events and processes. Indeed, profoundly important questions cannot be answered adequately unless geography is taken explicitly into account (cf. Spykman 1944, Dehio 1962). For example, should we attribute England's role as "balancer" in the nineteenth century to the motives and diplomatic skills of key decision makers or to its unique geographical position with respect to the Continental powers? What precisely are the advantages of geographical distance? Should we attribute the unification of China at the end of the Warring States Period in 221 B.C., for example, at the hands of a geographically "peripheral" as against central power as mere happenstance brought about by the fortuitous combination of military and diplomatic skill, or is it reasonable to hypothesize that such peripheral powers have an advantage over central ones? What are the implications for international stability of a decline in geography's importance, as occasioned by advances in the technologies of weapons systems? Can the removal of natural barriers to warfare disadvantage individual states, but make international systems more stable? In Chapter 6, then, but only for the special case of three-country systems, we extend the model that we offer in Chapters 3 and 4 to accommodate geography, and in doing so we are able to specify precisely the roles and special advantages and disadvantages of balancers and central powers. In Chapters 7 and 8, we move toward applying our model to the dynamics of alliance formation and conflict resolution in the classical period of the European balance of power, 1871-1914. Chapter 7 focuses on the dynamics of alliance formation using a valuation of coalitions deduced from our theory and markedly different from one assumed by earlier game-theoretic treatments. Chapter 8 is concerned with conflict resolution in three crises: the two Near Eastern Crises of 1875-8 and 1885-8, and the July Crisis of 1914. Our objective is to show the operation of similar forces in all three crises, but to explain why the third erupted into war. Most interestingly, our treatment of World War I as a preventive war uncovers an important set of factors underlying Russian precipitation of the war that had hitherto escaped analytical notice.
1.4 Plan of this volume
35
Finally, in Chapter 9, we offer a brief review of our analysis, and then we turn to a discussion of the contemporary implications of our analysis. The particular issues that concern us there are the relevance of our theory to a world with nuclear weapons and the theoretical extensions to our analysis that modern technology requires. In this way, we highlight the future research directions to which our analysis points.
CHAPTER 2
Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability International relations continue to be a recurring struggle for wealth and power among independent actors in a state of anarchy. Robert Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics (1981, p. 7)
Classic balance-of-power theory can be interpreted as an hypothesis that in a more-than-two-Power world there are no non-autonomous causes of systemic change;... the purely political aspect of the system's powerpolitical process always tends to produce a stable equilibrium which can be upset, if at all, only by autonomous changes. Arthur L. Burns, Of Powers and their Politics (1968, p. 249)
The balance's underlying principle...was that all the nth disengaged powers would tend to intervene on the side that seemed in danger of losing any ongoing war, to ensure that such a loser was not eliminated from the system and absorbed into an emerging colossus. George H. Quester, Offense and Defense in the International System (1977, p. 64)
2.1
Preliminary assumptions
Our objective in this chapter is to elaborate our second scenario of resource competition and survival - a game wherein the only explicit rule defining its structure is that any player can overcome a weaker adversary so that it more clearly constitutes a model of international conflict and alliances. At the same time, we want to render the concept of equilibrium, implicit in the preceding quotations, analytically precise so that the full implications of egoistic choice in anarchic systems can be uncovered. Before we proceed too far, though, we must be certain that this scenario can model a process as complex as the relations among sovereign states. We have already tried to indicate why we believe that this scenario in particular relates to some fundamental processes of international politics; but even if we accept the proposition that abstract theory can contribute to our understanding of international affairs, it is admittedly difficult to see how a simple three-person bargaining situation in which a single 36
2.1 Preliminary assumptions
37
commodity is the negotiable item can serve as a model of much of anything in politics. Indeed, as we noted earlier, too often the applications of decision and game theory to politics take the form of simple stories or scenarios based on the Prisoners' Dilemma and Chicken games, which, although interesting and informative, fail to provide any general structure for understanding fundamental processes. Hence, before we can become convinced that any one scenario can provide such a model, we must interpret its component parts and structure substantively. First, we must address the issue of the identities of the fundamental decision makers in our analysis. Holding in abeyance our earlier discussion of the implications of Arrow's Impossibility Theorem, our assumption is that countries are unitary actors, or, equivalently and in accordance with Bueno de Mesquita's (1981a) approach, that they are led by a single decision maker. This assumption must confront several objections. Anyone familiar with democratic processes understands the consequences of a Congress with foreign-policy objectives distinct from those of the President, and is thereby cognizant of the fact that the foreign-policy objectives of a state need not be readily identifiable. Indeed, even less democratic governments often speak with a discordant voice, one that is made all the less coherent as policy preferences shift over time and as other elements of the society act in contrary ways. In short, "The existence of transgovernmental policy networks leads to a different interpretation of one of the standard propositions about international politics - that states act in their own interest [T]his conventional wisdom begs two important questions: which self and which interest?" (Keohane and Nye 1977, p. 34). Nevertheless, our assumption plays an important and informative role. Just as we study frictionless planes in physics and the abstraction of competitive markets in economics in order to discern fundamental laws, the assumption of unitary decision makers serves to reduce "friction" in our analysis. We base our assumption of the state as a unitary decision maker on the prior assumption of a relatively complex set of domestic political games the outcome of which is to endow the state, or a single leader of that state, with the effective power of a unitary decision maker. Later, we explore the implications of decision makers who fail to satisfy our assumptions to see what effect such failures might have on our conclusions. Second, we should understand that the identification of key decision makers, and our associating them with nation-states, is more an analytic convenience than it is a theoretical necessity. We do not suppose that nation-states are always the primary actors in international systems, nor do we preclude the possibility of applying our analysis to historical periods in which the concept of the nation-state is irrelevant. Because we are attempting to formulate a general theory of interaction in anarchic
38
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
political systems, the definition and identification of key decision makers is left to the requirements of the analyst. Thus, although we use the word "country" to identify a key decision-making entity, we could just as easily refer to the city-states of medieval Italy. Indeed, although one of our primary objectives is to study the alliances that form among decision makers, it may be useful from time to time to treat certain alliances as constraints on the system and to suppose that a particular alliance is a unitary actor, especially if that alliance exists more for domestic political reasons that we choose to interpret as exogenous to the immediate study. It may be convenient, for example, to treat Japan, Canada, and the United States as a single entity as long as we focus on immediate military capabilities, as long as Japan and Canada forego the development of independent military capabilities, and as long as Japan in particular continues its indirect support of America's military spending and our corresponding budget deficits. However, if our attention turns to economic conflict and to the competition for control of economic resources, then Japan at least should clearly be entered into the analysis as a differentiated decision-making entity. The point is that the definition or identification of "key decision maker" is for the analyst's analytical convenience. Third, before we can accept the abstraction of assuming that countries are unitary actors, we must satisfactorily specify the objectives of these decision makers. Again, this forces us to confront Arrow's theorem and the possibility that, although countries may act as if they are unitary decision makers, they may also act "incoherently" in the sense of not revealing complete or transitive preferences. In this event, it may be impossible to argue that any collection of persons is acting as if it were pursuing an identifiable goal. Nevertheless, we assume that the unitary decision makers in our model, qua national leaders, act as if they share a readily discernible goal - increasing their countries' resources, provided that the survival of their respective countries is not thereby threatened. We find support for such an egoistic assumption about goals in Kennedy's (1987, p. 73) observation that "The most significant feature of the Great Power scene after 1660 was the maturing of a genuinely multipolar system of European states, each one of which increasingly tended to make decisions about war and peace on the basis of 'national interests' rather than for transnational, religious causes." With a more direct reference to our assumption, we can cite the following observation about the Ch'un Ch'iu period in China: the ultimate aim of political actions was the expression of the sovereignty of the individual states. This became the standard for judging the measures of the rulers and the various officers of the states. The moral code of the former Chou feudal age had meaning only when it added to the power and prestige of the state which
2.1 Preliminary assumptions
39
claimed to adhere to it Thus, major policies were security policies. Security and power were the concern of the day. Such actions as rounding out frontiers, joining leagues, transferring alliances, treaty arrangements, fomenting civil war elsewhere can all be interpreted in terms of the quest for security (Walker 1953, pp. 99-100). Even this quote understates the generality of the assumption of egoism, and of Morgenthau's (1959, p. 5) boldly stated proposition that "statesmen think and act in terms of interest defined as power." Waltz succinctly states the cause for such generality: Because some states may at any time use force, all states must be prepared to do so - or live at the mercy of their militarily more vigorous neighbors. Among states, the state of nature is a state of war. This is meant not in the sense that wars constantly occur but in the sense that, with each state deciding for itself whether or not to use force, war may break out at any time (1979, p. 102). Several important issues, however, arise with our assumption about objectives. Among them is the question of whether the objectives of all nation-states or their agents can be summarized by a single, unidimensional measure. That is, what of the seemingly self-evident fact that Security in traditional terms, is not likely to be the principle issue facing governments. Insofar as military force is ineffective on certain issues, the conventional notion of power lacks precision. In particular, different power resources may be needed to deal with different issues The notion of national interest - the traditionalists' lodestar - becomes increasingly difficult to use effectively. Traditional maxims of international politics - that states will act in their national interest or that they will attempt to maximize their power - become ambiguous (Keohane and Nye 1977, p. 8). In approaching this debate, however, we should keep in mind that the simplification that we adopt from the realist view parallels the simplification that underlies the attractiveness of contemporary economic theory: One important reason for the remarkably great explanatory power of classical economic theory lies precisely in the extreme simplicity of its motivational assumptions, which make economic self-interest virtually the only motivating force of human behavior, at least in economic activities (Harsanyi 1969, p. 518). Morgenthau (1959, p. 12) makes an equivalent argument: if I want to understand "religious man" I must for the time being abstract from the other aspects of human nature and deal with its religious aspect as if it were the only one. Furthermore, I must apply to the religious sphere the standards of thought appropriate to it, always remaining aware of the existence of other standards and their actual influence upon the religious qualities of man. What is true of this facet of human nature is true of all others. No modern economist, for instance, would conceive of his science and its relations to other sciences of man in any other way. It is exactly through such a process of emancipation from other
40
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
standards of thought, and the development of one appropriate to its subject matter, that economics has developed as an autonomous theory of the economic activities of man. To contribute to a similar development in the field of politics is the purpose of political realism.
Correspondingly, such a simplification has proven to be powerful in previous attempts to model diverse political processes at the domestic level, such as in Niskanen's (1971) model of bureaucratic-congressional relations (viz., his assumption that public bureaucrats maximize their budgets), Fiorina (1977) and Mayhew's (1974) studies of congress (viz., their assumption that legislators maximize their probabilities of reelection), in Downs's (1957) seminal study of elections (viz., the assumption that political parties maximize their chances of election), and in microeconomic theory (viz., the assumption that firms maximize profit). Each of these models posits a simple and readily operationalized objective for decision makers with the view that the adequacy of the assumption is tested by observing the adequacy of predictions. If the abstraction leads to a model that predicts well in diverse situations, then we regard it as an acceptable abstraction; otherwise, we must find an alternative specification of objectives or an alternative specification of the system's key actors. If we find, for example, that domestic politics preclude coherent national goals, then we may have to revise our description of international systems so that various domestic actors are explicitly identified and given an appropriate role in the analysis. The potential for disagreement about the identity of key decision makers and their goals characterizes many of the differences in views of international politics. A classical Marxist perspective prescribes class and class leaders as relevant actors, whereas others look at significant economic entities such as multinational corporations, and still others prefer a classic nation-state conceptualization, augmented by the force of powerful personalities. Our approach most closely parallels the traditional realist view, but even acceptance of the criticisms of that view does not vitiate an analysis based on its precepts. If, in fact, "Survival is the primary goal of all states" and "in the worst situations, force is ultimately necessary to guarantee survival" (Keohane and Nye 1977, p. 27), and if "In international affairs, force remains thefinalarbiter" (Waltz 1979, p. 180), then our analysis - like classical microeconomic theory, spatial theories of elections, and analyses of legislatures based on the assumption that legislators maximize the probability of reelection - describes the shell in which all other forces must operate, and provides the broad outlines of international politics that help us discern the meaning and the impact of these other considerations. There remains, nevertheless, one difficulty with applying a perspective in which we hypothesize the goal of maximizing resources or maintenance of sovereignty: no natural unidimensional commodity suggests itself for
2.1 Preliminary assumptions
41
measuring the performance or preference with respect to that goal. We could, for example, try to make our assumption seem more reasonable by substituting the word "power" for resources, but this merely replaces one word with another - one whose definition is even more problematical. What we must do, then, is recognize that the resources to which we refer in our assumption can mean a number of things, depending on context. Thus, at a minimum, we shall use it to refer to territory, at other times to military manpower, and at other times to economic capacity. And we must admit that even these simplifications are often difficult to formulate - witness, for example, the issue of defining and measuring a country's economic capacity in today's complex world market economy. At this point, however, we must emphasize that the assumption that each national leader is motivated to secure resources while guarding his or her country's sovereignty is not necessarily equivalent to the supposition that nations (or their agents) simply pursue the maximization of power or of resources alone. Although the proponents of realpolitik typically equate this goal with "rational" action itself, we must keep in mind our view that international politics does not consist of the single "play" of a simple game; rather, it consists of a successive play of a sequence of games. In this context, if national leaders are concerned with final outcomes or with some view of the future, and hence with what their actions imply about the ultimate, overall distribution of resources, then this interpretation of rationality is not a basic assumption but, at best, a deduction from some model that posits more fundamental goals. If we assume instead that the ultimate goal of national leaders is the survival of their nations as sovereign entities, then those leaders must evaluate a decision to attack another nation, to join a particular coalition, or to cede resources, not in terms of immediate benefits, but in terms of what an action implies ultimately about the likelihood that its survival will be endangered. Echoing Kutusov's strategic dilemma in his pursuit of Napoleon, Kaplan (1979, p. 70) makes a similar observation: "the weakest player, by joining a nearly predominant strong player, only creates a condition in which he will be the next victim." Correspondingly, we can cite Wagner's observation that the basic question that concerns us is whether states will act so as to eliminate other states. If one state is eliminated from a four-actor game, for example, the result is to precipitate a three-actor subgame. If a value can be assigned to such a subgame for each player, it is possible to determine whether any players have an incentive to eliminate other players (1986, p. 551).
So, assuming that international actors are cognizant of the sequential game they are playing, we must check whether immediate objectives (maximizing resources) are consistent with ultimate goals (survival, defined in terms of territorial or economic sovereignty).
42
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
Next, we must specify the rules under which national leaders pursue their objectives - the actions that they may take and the consequences of these actions. Actually, this is a more difficult task than we might otherwise suppose, and there are two alternative approaches. In the terminology of the game theorist, thefirstapproach consists of specifying a game's extensive form. This requires that we model reality by identifying the specific actions available to decision makers, the order in which those actions can be taken, the constraints that specific decisions place on subsequent actions, and the consequences of all possible permutations of actions. In the current context, these actions would include decisions to cede territory or resources to another country, to threaten countries with invasion, to invade, to sue for peace, to negotiate a coalition with someone, to establish mechanisms for enforcing agreements, and decisions about the timing of each of these actions. The advantage of such a method is the empirical verisimilitude of the model it produces. However, the difficulty with such an approach is that it yields a monstrously complex model of reality that defies both specification and analysis. Our solution to this problem is traditional to cooperative game-theoretic analysis: we abstract from the substantive content of actions and focus instead on their consequences. For example, we can look at the decision to transfer resources from one country to another and assess whether such a transfer is dictated by the current situation, ignoring for the time being whether such a transfer occurs via the actual cessation of territory, whether it requires armed conflict, or whether it requires simply that some new tariff be implemented that reorders the economic advantages afforded to the industries of one country versus another. With this approach, we also deliberately ignore the precise sequencing of events, the nuances of bargaining, and the precise mechanisms players might use to enforce agreements. Thus, referring to our first scenario, we can try to decide whether a two-person coalition will form and divide the available resources equally between its members without specifying the details of the negotiation process. In summary, then, our basic scenario consists of a set of decision makers who are confronted with a sequence of situations in which each, without threatening one's future viability, tries to maximize resources via the judicious formation of coalitions as either threats or counterthreats. 2.2
Notation and additional assumptions
The assumptions in the previous section about unitary actors, the identity of those actors, the maximization of resources, and the substantive content of actions permit us to maintain someflexibilityin the substantive interpretation of our formal results. This is important and useful.
2.2 Notation and additional assumptions
43
Although our analysis seeks to be rigorous, we do not want to become constrained by its mathematics when we are required to give it substantive meaning. First, this flexibility permits us to avoid becoming embroiled too quickly in issues of operationalization, such as the definition of sovereign states, measures of relative military capabilities, the specific identities of key decision makers, and definitions of war. Too often discussions of the causes of conflict and the nature of international systems focus prematurely on such issues; but it is precisely these issues that cannot be resolved until general theoretical paradigms and essential concepts are specified. Second, because we are searching for fundamental causes in the structure of international political systems, we prefer to avoid the task of ascertaining the variety of ways in which those causes might become manifest in reality. We cannot know that falling leaves and falling rocks are manifestations of the common phenomena of gravity and friction until the concept of gravity itself is hypothesized. So here, until a general theoretical paradigm is at hand, we cannot be certain in the retelling and comparison of events whether differences are theoretically fundamental or are merely equivalent manifestations of the same phenomena. To elaborate our second scenario, then, we proceed abstractly and as generally as possible by first introducing some formal notation. This notation may be distasteful to many students of international affairs, but it will permit us to state some requisite assumptions rigorously. Keeping in mind that the essential components of that scenario are a specification of the players in the game and an initial endowment of resources for the players that measures their "voting weight," we then require the following notation: S = {1,2,...,«}, the set of all countries in the international system under consideration. C = a subset of S (written C<=S), denoting a specific collection of countries in S that typically corresponds to a coalition or an alliance in our analysis. r = (^I* ri> -->rn)> a n fl-tuple of resources, where rt denotes the resources of country /. We assume that A*;>0 for all /, and (for convenience) that the resources of the countries are ordered rx > R = 2?=i /"/, the total resources controlled by all countries in the system under consideration. r(C) — S/ e c f/> the total resources controlled by the collection of countries C. (S; r) = an outcome or a state of the world specifying the countries that constitute the system under consideration and the resources they control individually.
44
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
Merely supposing that we can model international political processes with this notation means that we accept a number of implicit assumptions, including (as we have already stated) that the principal decision makers are unitary actors, that there exists some finite, controllable resource, and that we can specify how much of that resource each country controls. This notation also supposes that we can unambiguously identify the set of countries relevant to the analysis. This, of course, is not always the case since we may be uncertain about which countries are relevant and which countries are mere satellites of another, without true sovereignty in the sense that they cannot express an independent foreign policy. Despite such operationalization problems, we should be prepared to beflexiblein empirical applications of our model. We may prefer, for example, to exclude certain countries from an analysis as a temporary convenience, as when we exclude smaller countries to study superpower relations, or when we ignore the role of the superpowers in the relations among smaller countries in studying, for example, regional matters. Our analysis of European great-power relations, for example, excludes Ottoman Turkey as an actor, since it is more convenient to treat the resources contributed to conflict resolution by that declining empire as merely a means for rendering conflict a nonconstant sum game among the European powers. Alternatively, we may decide that the superpowers have no conflicting interests in a situation, or that their resources are not of a type that impacts on local conflicts, in which case we may choose to apply the analysis only to smaller countries [cf. Walt's (1987) analysis of the Middle East]. Finally, to understand the constraints imposed by domestic politics, we might leave the arena of international affairs and instead associate the members of S with key domestic political interests within a state. Although free to define the set S of relevant countries in a number of ways, depending on research intent, we have already noted that the supposition that a country's resources can be represented by a single number is problematical. Indeed, even if we accept the proposition that nationstates act as unitary decision makers concerned primarily with maintaining their sovereignty, and that military capacity provides the ultimate guarantee, it is clearly the case that a great many things such as geographical advantages, population, size and robustness of an economy, and the degree of domestic political stability are relevant resources; and each of these components even is difficult to measure by a single index. Later, in Chapters 7 and 8, we operationalize this variable in terms of factors especially relevant to the historical period under consideration - namely, a country's military age male population, its ability to mobilize that population for conflict, its production of commodities (e.g., coal, iron, and steel) that are key to any war effort, and its ability to project its military forces
2.2 Notation and additional assumptions
45
offensively and defensively. And although variables such as GNP should correlate with the ones we use, the fact that we do not use economic measures yields a bias in our analysis for measuring directly military capability rather than potential value to an adversary of successful threats. This bias, in turn, reveals an ambiguity in our assumptions. In the analysis that follows, we implicitly equate military capability and the resources a country might lose to an adversary in a conflict. In reality, however, a country with an inferior economy but with a superior armed force might overwhelm its adversary and force the transfer of economic resources that greatly exceed the costs of overcoming the current disparity in strength. Nevertheless, our argument about the conditions for stability and instability can be more clearly developed if we assume that the concept of resources is unidimensional and unemcumbered by complex substantive qualification (for further discussion of this issue, see Section 2.6). This ambiguity in the meaning and operationalization of resources is not much different from the problems we encounter in giving the concept of power theoretical and substantive meaning.1 Of course, these problems are well known, and for those reasons we agree that "power" cannot usefully be a primitive concept in any adequate theory. Nevertheless, because we suppose that "resources" not only measure what it is that countries seek, but that it also measures their abilities to secure additional resources from adversaries, then our use of the word "resources" is synonymous with much of the intuition that underlies the concept of power. To a certain extent, then, we are free to interchange these words, provided that we keep in mind the fact that the notion of resources gains its substantive meaning only through the particular operationalization we supply to it an operationalization we must be prepared to alter, depending on the particular historical period under consideration. Before we can proceed, however, we require two additional assumptions about resources that allow certain mathematical manipulations. The first assumption is that the total of resources held by all countries is constant: Al. R is a constant. 1
For discussion of the plethora of problems associated with operationalizing the concept of "power," see Knorr (1956,1970), Hart (1976), Baldwin (1979), and Organski and Kugler (1980). Despite these problems, however, there is a common theme to attempts at conceptualizing and operationalizing power - namely, the replacement of a complex, multifaceted reality with a simple, unidimensional measure. Our notion of resources seeks this same objective. The resources one country can bring to bear to overcome an opponent or to defend against an adversary are varied and complex, but in order to theorize about fundamental imperatives (as against, say, the specific tactics nations employ) we submerge consideration of the ways in which resources can be combined and transformed, and of the functional relationships between resources of different types and the capacity to resist or engage in aggression.
46
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
An equivalent alternative to Al is the following: Al'. For all / in 5, rt (and thus R) grows at the same rate. Al and Al' are equivalent since rt can be interpreted as country /'s proportion of resources, measured against the total. If a country's resources and R grow at the same rate, then the proportion of those resources to R is a constant. Despite the fact that Al is consistent with the supposition that if resources and power are synonymous then (because power is a relative concept) it ought to be in fixed supply, the most evident limitation of Al, as is made apparent by Al', is that it does not permit us to consider an important class of hypotheses that refer to differential growth rates in national capabilities as a source of conflict in international politics. Put differently, Assumption Al precludes consideration of the causes of preventive wars, those wars that occur in anticipation of some country securing a resource advantage in the future owing to a differential growth rate. That this limitation is serious is underscored by Gilpin's (1981, p. 13) observation that "the most destabilizing factor is the tendency in an international system for the powers of member states to change at different rates because of political, economic, and technological developments." Echoing a consistent theme in the literature, however, Chatterjee states the distinction that outlines our analysis:2 In an international system there are two methods by which stability is sought to be maintained. One method is direct - it involves adjustments of the individual capabilities of the nation... mainly by changes in their armaments levels The other method is the adjustment of alliance configurations among the various nations in the system, including the neutralization of certain actors... (1975, p. 44).
Initially, we concern ourselves with identifying the consequences of the second method - alliance formation and the resource adjustments that the formation of alliances might necessitate - in a world of constant capabilities. We merely postpone until Chapter 5 consideration of the effects of differential growth rates and investment strategies, their importance as a general determinant of stability, and their consequences for alliance formation. Our second assumption is that a country is "eliminated" if its resources equal zero, and that once eliminated it is forever precluded from becoming a member of the international system. That is, 2
Similarly, Waltz (1979, p. 118) remarks that "states, or those who act for them, try in more or less sensible ways to use the means available...[that] fall into two categories: internal efforts (moves to increase economic capability, to increase military strength, to develop clever strategies) and external efforts (moves to strengthen and enlarge one's own alliances or to weaken or shrink an opposing one)."
2.2 Notation and additional assumptions
47
A2. Country / in S is eliminated if r, = 0, so that in all subsequent states of the world (S'; r'), / cannot be a member of S'. If we interpreted our theory as one that concerns the disappearance of countries, we would have to admit that it is a theory more appropriate to those historical epochs in which we witness the evolution of nationstates from the more basic material of feudal systems than it is to relations among states in an established nation-state system. However, even if states today rarely disappear, assumption A2 admits more general interpretations. First, we can think of the situation in which rt = 0 as corresponding to that in which / has ceased to be an "effective" actor. Thus, if we choose to interpret our model as concerning only "great powers," then elimination can merely refer to the removal of a country from great-power status. Alternatively, elimination can refer to those situations in which, although a country retains its technical sovereignty, it is merely a satellite of some neighboring power, one that controls its foreign policy. These alternative interpretations of the condition rt = 0, then, reflect the flexibility we allow in the specification of 5, the relevant states in the system. For purposes of fully analyzing the nature of conflict resolution and alliance-formation processes, we require one additional assumption about national resources: A3. R is infinitely divisible and freely transferable among the countries in 5. If resources refer to territory, then we can see how A3 might be theoretically viable, but it may not be viable in any practical sense. Although the United States can transfer "ownership" of Hawaii to Japan, of Maine to Canada, and of Texas to Mexico, any elected official held responsible for such a transfer will have served his last term in public office. In short, the transfer of certain types of resources may be impossible owing to domestic political considerations. Alternatively, if resources refer to (say) industrial capacity, it may be technologically impossible to effect certain transfers. We might move a steel mill, but the effective transfer of technological expertise may require the development of entire economic infrastructures. The Soviet Union may be able to steal the technology of microcomputers, but what of that part of the American economy in mail order catalogues, shopping malls, and universities that services these computers with spare parts, software, and programming skills?3 3
Assumption A3 places some technical constraints on resources that warrant emphasis. Aside from the fact that infinite divisibility merely facilitates mathematical manipulation, if we measure r, as a percent of R - that is, if we transform all measures of resources to relative terms - then unless the total resources in the system are constant or unless Al' is satisfied, A3 can be violated. If, for example, relative resources are changed only by a
48
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
Despite its implausibility in certain respects, A3 is nevertheless useful.4 First, we should not suppose that resource transfers require the physical movement of troops, money, or international boundaries. Again, we can be flexible and, thus, we can interpret as a transfer one country ceding some part of its sovereignty to another, as when Poland, acting as a buffer state for the Soviet Union, permits the Kremlin to dictate domestic policy with respect to labor unrest. Second, Assumption A3 is valuable because it corresponds, for us, to our "frictionless model" of international political processes. With it we can understand the types or directions of transfers national leaders might seek. And if such transfers are revealed to be essential for stability, then we can interpret technological or domestic political impediments as impediments to stability, or vice versa. In this way, then, we can begin to understand some of the implications of domestic politics and technological limitations for conflict and stability in international systems. Assumption A3 also permits us to confront the following characterization of balance-of-power theories: the major [adjustment] mechanism... [of balance-of-power theory] is the making and unmaking of alliances. The reason for this dependence on coalitions in order to change the distribution of power is that the power resources of each member of the system are viewed as inelastic. There is no way a nation can increase its own strength very much except by adding its allies' strength to its own, or by decreasing its adversaries' strength by separating it, through persuasion, bribery, or subversion, from its allies (Organski and Kugler 1980, p. 16).
Organski and Kugler offer this characterization as a way to introduce their argument for the necessity of considering endogenous resource growth, but their argument highlights the necessity for Assumption A3, which, by explicitly allowing for an "elastic" shifting of resources across members of the system, brings our analysis in line with previous ideas about the operation of balance-of-power politics.
4
country increasing or decreasing its absolute resources, then any change between two countries necessarily alters the percentage of resources controlled by all other countries and thus free transferability is violated. Any assertion that Assumption A3 diminishes the generality of our analysis must, however, contend with the fact that we have merely made explicit an assumption that is implicit in previous research. Most balance-of-power theorists tacitly make the same assumption (Kaplan 1957, Morgenthau 1959, Claude 1962, Waltz 1979) and their ability to discuss transfers of power and redistributions of capability among national actors rests precisely upon the tacit assumption that power (or resources or capability) is infinitely divisible and perfectly transferable among nations. Moreover, A3 seems more acceptable as an assumption in an era when the measure of military capability can be based more on technology and economic productivity and control than on territory and the counting of bodies available for military service.
2.2 Notation and additional assumptions
49
Now we must specify the actions available to the decision makers in our analysis. Because this analysis uses concepts from the theory of ^-person cooperative games, in which a representation of the game that explicitly defines the alternative actions of people (the extensive or the normal form) is reformulated to define a function (the characteristic function) that identifies the relative values of alternative coalitions, of necessity we must abstract away people's specific substantive acts and talk instead of coalition possibilities. Nevertheless, having some sense of available actions is important so that we can more clearly see the substantive implications of our analysis. Briefly, we distinguish these five actions: al: a2: a3: a4: a5:
negotiate to cede resources to other countries, aggressively act to secure resources from other countries, negotiate to secure resources from other countries, aggressively oppose the actions of other countries, act neither to secure nor to cede resources.
We deliberately leave the words "negotiate" and "aggressively" ambiguous. Our purpose is not to distinguish sharply between war and alternative acts of aggression, nor do we want to enter the debate over what constitutes a war and what constitutes an extension of diplomatic posturing for securing a more advantageous bargaining position. Instead, we intend simply to provide a means whereby we might interpret the theoretical results in terms of actions that are more or less peaceful or conflictual. With respect to the preferences of national leaders for alternative allocations of resources, we follow a lead that is implicit in the quotation from Quester (1977) and that also anticipates the logic of our concept of system stability: • A country prefers greater resources to less, unless securing greater resources leads, ultimately, to an outcome in which its resources are reduced to zero, and, in particular, it prefers having some resources to having no resources - survival is preferred to elimination. That is, A4. / prefers the resource distribution r to the distribution r' if rt > r[, provided that / can ensure that no distribution r" results from r in which r" — 0, and, in particular, / prefers any r in which r,- > 0 to a distribution in which its resources are zero. A4 is not inconsistent with the supposition that leaders seek to maximize the resources of their countries, but because we suppose that people look to the future consequences of their actions, it adds a necessary
50
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
qualification: namely, that they seek actions that guarantee the existence of their countries as sovereign entities, or, in the case of "great powers," that guarantee that they remain so. Thus, as we show subsequently, A4 admits the possibility that national leaders might choose to transfer some of their country's resources to another country in the event that such transfers are perceived as necessary to ensure survival. Nevertheless, if a nation's survival is not threatened, its leaders will act, whenever possible, to increase their resources.5 One issue that ought to concern us, however, is that countries do not maximize resources at all - that the goals we attribute to these collectivities are of a different sort. One plausible speculation is that, at least for those countries capable of sustaining prosperity among their inhabitants, maintenance of the status quo is the primary goal and that the maximization of resources or power is merely a by-product or is an objective that is shunned if it interferes with prosperity. This view, summarized by Gilpin (1981, p. 7) as the belief that "peaceful evolution has replaced military conflict as the principle means of adjusting relations among nation states ... [so that] economic and welfare goals have triumphed over the traditional power and security objectives." For example, numerous commentators today characterize the United States as a "status quo power," filling a role once occupied by Britain, and thereby is less interested in the aggrandizement of military power than it is in the maintenance of stable relations among states so that it can pursue purely economic goals. Because we do not suppose, however, that there exists any clean separation between military and economic resources, our assumption matches Gilpin's assertion, as quoted earlier, that "international relations continue to be a recurring struggle for wealth and power," and is reflected in contemporary events by a popular press replete with statements of concern that the strategic position of the United States is threatened by its relative decline in the world economy. Implicit in such concerns, we suspect, is the view that if the maximization of resources or of their proportion - both military and economic - play no role in strategic considerations, then a single country with maximization in mind should find little resistance to its becoming hegemonic. Because hegemonic goals have been pervasive in the past, and because we believe it is only reasonable to anticipate resistance 5
Notice that an apparent alternative to the assumption that resources are maximized is the assumption that national leaders maximize proportion of resources. In fact, to the extent that resources serve the same purpose as power in previous analyses, and since power is (if anything at all) a relative concept, then maximization of proportion seems more nearly consistent with previous research. However, since we assume that total resources in the system are constant, maximization of proportion and maximization of absolute level are equivalent, and we need not concern ourselves with this distinction until we consider, in Chapter 5, the consequences of growth.
2.2 Notation and additional assumptions
51
to such goals, then maximization must of necessity play a role in everyone's strategic thinking. Turning now to our next assumption, we must proceed with the realization that the processes of international relations are dynamic and the formal representation of these processes is possibly more complicated and laden with strategic possibilities than any game political scientists study. Part of this complexity arises because nations cannot war or transfer resources instantaneously, and decisions to do so leave open the possibility that other nations can respond before final consequences prevail. Unfortunately, formulating an appropriate extensive form so that it is tractable and yields generalizable results is currently beyond our capabilities. Hence, we substitute an analysis in which responses are instantaneous. In particular, we suppose that individually or in coalition, decision makers can choose actions such as a2 and that other countries can be mobilized immediately and their leaders choose al or a4. If these latter countries are defeated, their resources are transferred to the victors unspoiled. The next two assumptions concern the actual play of the game. First, we suppose that: • A coalition of countries can defeat another coalition if and only if the amount of resources held by the first coalition exceeds that of the second coalition. Furthermore, if thefirstcoalition defeats the second, the resources of the second are transferred to the first in a distribution agreed upon by that first coalition. In formal notation, this amounts to the assumption: A5. For the two disjoint collections of countries C and C'^S, C can defeat C" if and only if the resources that C controls, r(C), exceed the resources that C" controls, r(C'), and if no larger coalition attacks C If C defeats C", r(C') is transferred to C as specified by the members of C so that C's resources become r(C) + r(C'). Thus, chance events play no role in determining who can defeat whom. Later, when we interpret historical events in light of our analysis, we must of course make allowances for the uncertainty that confronts decision makers. We discuss this problem further in the next section, although an obviously valuable theoretical extension of the analysis we offer here is to incorporate uncertainty formally. A more serious limitation of our assumption concerns the special role of geography in international affairs. Briefly, our assumption requires that X units of resources be as effective in attacking one country as they are in attacking another, and that those resources can counter an attack by a country possessing X units or less.
52
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
Geography, however, introduces obvious asymmetries in the value of resources. Germany's land army in 1939 may have been just short of adequate for attacking and defeating Russia, but it could not be applied with equal effectiveness against England. This assumption also precludes studying certain kinds of technological change, such as the development of the railroad and the advantages this transportation gave to Germany and Russia. For the present, though, we will ignore this complication, postponing until Chapter 6 a treatment of geography and the asymmetries it occasions. Assumption A5 imposes an additional restriction. By supposing that the resources controlled by C equal r(C) + r(C) after C" is defeated by C, we require that choosing an action such as a2 (as against, say, a3) is costless. It is, of course, silly to suppose that securing resources by aggressive action, including war, takes no more effort than securing those resources by negotiation. We are interested in international instability precisely because of the costs to all of us that wars threaten. Nevertheless, we want to be certain that stability does not prevail in our analysis merely because we have made war and, thus, instability costly. Although this argument (as well as arguments about preserving analytic tractability) rationalizes Assumption A5, Rosecrance's (1986, p. 37) hypothesis that "If war is to be avoided, its cost must be high.. .but it must not be so high as to prevent others from even considering the need to stop an expansive power," forces us to consider the possibility that stability is maximized for some intermediate cost. To see how we might incorporate war costs and thereby determine the logical validity of this hypothesis, an alternative to A5 is to suppose that, after C defeats C , the resources C controls equal [r{C) + r(C')\[\-*r{C')/r{C)]\
(2.1)
that is, the resources destroyed by conflict increase as the strengths of opposing coalitions approach equality. A5 sets a equal to zero. On the other hand, if a = 1 and r(C) = r ( C ) , C is left with nothing - in a contest between equal powers, the resources of both are destroyed. Since even the defeated powers in both World Wars maintained considerable industrial capacity (and ignoring the consequences of nuclear weapons), this possibility seems too extreme, and we might limit a to values between 0 and 1. Throughout most of our analysis, though, we suppose that a = 0, because this allows us to explore balance of power in a "frictionless" world and because such an assumption greatly facilitates the analysis of such issues as preventive war and geography. However, the sensitivity of our conclusion about system stability to the war cost parameter - and, thus, the sensitivity of the fundamentals of balance-of-power politics - are examined in Chapter 3, and are shown not to depend on this assumption.
2.2 Notation and additional assumptions
53
Regardless of whether we set a equal to zero or not, however, it is still reasonable to suppose that if the same outcome can be obtained through either means, negotiation ought to be preferred to conflict. That is, A6. If securing resources through conflict (a2) and securing resources through negotiation (a3) lead to otherwise identical outcomes, a decision maker strictly prefers a3. Of course, A6 is reasonable only to the extent that the preferences of decision makers somehow match those of the people they purportedly represent. Indeed, A6 precludes the leader who values conflict positively because it draws domestic attention away from his or her own deficiencies and solidifies his or her domestic base of political support. Thus, our analysis may model poorly an Argentine junta. Indeed, Riker (1964) tells us that federalist governments are almost always formed as a response to some external military threat. Hence, if someone sees private political advantage from the formation of such a government, then that person may positively prefer conflict, regardless of casualties or wasted resources. The approach to war and its costs embodied by A6, however, has nevertheless one distinct disadvantage: negotiation and war are barely distinguishable and thus we cannot differentiate sharply between transfers that occur through actions such as negotiation, the mobilization of troops, and skirmishes designed to test or display one's resolve as against those actions in which lives are lost, industrial plants are destroyed, and cities laid waste. If war merely is "diplomacy conducted by other means," then our assumption that wars are costless fails to differentiate among these alternative means. We see later, however, that our analysis of stability in an environment of costless wars applies also to those circumstances in which national leaders and those they lead must confront the costs A6 ignores. Another issue that our assumptions to this point leave unresolved is the consequence of simultaneous moves by several decision makers. In particular, one of the important features of international conflict is the fact that hostilities between any pair of countries leave open the possibility that a third country can enter the fray to its own advantage. Historically, the Soviet Union has been especially attuned to this possibility: Germany attacks Poland, and Stalin reacts to Poland's vulnerability; the United States verges on the unconditional surrender of Japan, and the Soviets declare war on Japan. The next assumption removes some of the ambiguity about how countries can use their resources to attack (a2) or defend (al or a4), and specifies some of the consequences of simultaneous conflicts: • If a coalition attacks and defeats a second, smaller coalition that itself had attacked a third, smaller coalition, then the resources
54
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
of the second coalition are absorbed by the first, but the third coalition is unaffected. That is, A7. If for the three disjoint "coalitions" C, C", and C", C attacks C" and C" attacks C", with r(C) > r(C') > r(C")9 then the larger coalition, C, absorbs C , whereas the target of the attack of C", coalition C", is unaffected. Hence, if r = (150,100,50) describes the initial distribution of resources, and if 1 attacks 2 and 2 attacks 3, then, if no further countermoves arise, (250,0,50) prevails. Actually, A7 is stronger than we require, and any number of assumptions can be substituted provided that they satisfy the following property: If two nations war, then a third more powerful nation can take advantage of the conflict. More formally, for example, we could suppose that C absorbs r(C') as well as some part of r(C")9 or that C absorbs some proportion of r(C') + r(C") and C" absorbs some part of r(C"). Our next assumption merely serves to emphasize the multiperiod context of our second scenario. Briefly, this assumption is driven by the fact that international relations occur in a dynamic setting that cannot be modeled adequately as a "one-shot" game, and that any wholly static description of international political processes abstracts away essential features of reality: • Countries interact over a sequence of periods. The beginning of any period is characterized by a particular distribution of resources over the countries. If at the beginning of any period a country's resources are zero, it is eliminated from interaction for all ensuing periods. Furthermore, the interaction of countries in each period in accordance with assumptions A1-A7 determines the initial resource distribution for the following period. Equivalently: A8. The game consists of a sequence, (1,2, ...,y, ...,m}, of periods. The beginning of period j is characterized by (Sy; r y ). If rj = 0, then / is not a player in the game and i$Sk for all k >y. In each period, countries attempt to redistribute resources in accordance with A1-A7, and the result characterizes the beginning of the next period. The important feature of this assumption is that it implies that decision makers must be concerned with a sequence of plays, rather than with a single negotiation period. Thus, decision makers must look ahead to the
2.2 Notation and additional assumptions
55
future consequences of their actions in deciding how to play the game in the current period. One question we should raise with respect to this formulation concerns the calculation of payoffs. Normally, when analyzing a repeated game in which each person receives a stream of payoffs, it is assumed that a person's current payoff equals the discounted value of the stream. However, here payoffs are merely the resources that a country controls: /*/, r/ +1 , etc., and do not necessarily correspond to a recurring stream. Consequently, we interpret Assumption A4 to refer to the resources that a country controls in the next period, and we say that / can ensure its existence if it can pursue a strategy in which no rj in the sequence equals zero. Notice, however, that A8 leaves the details of the game's negotiation process, and thus its full extensive form, deliberately obscured (aside from the requirement that this process consists of the selection of actions al through a5). Rather than specify the process whereby outcomes are negotiated, in the next chapter we introduce a proposition that tells us how resources are actually distributed in a period. Thus, although our analysis up to this point is nearly identical to Wagner's (1986) model of balance of power, it is here that we depart from his approach.6 Wagner proposes to specify an extensive-form negotiation game and to deduce equilibrium bargaining outcomes for that game. Although this is theoretically sound, not only is the analysis of games in this form difficult, but the relationship between cooperative and noncooperative game theory presently is only imperfectly understood. Consequently, general results elude Wagner. The approach we take, which consists of formulating a cooperative solution hypothesis that models the situation at hand without reference to the details of the bargaining process, permits the derivation of general results (but see footnote 8, Chapter 3). Yet, our approach is not without its disadvantages. Like much of cooperative ^-person solution theory and the arguments for the applicability of concepts such as the core and the von Neumann and Morgenstern solution, there is an ad hoc flavor to the analysis that cannot be avoided without resorting to a full extensive-form treatment of the situation.7 Of course, even an extensive-form treatment of a 6
7
One critical difference to this point is that Wagner does not allow countries to transfer resources. As our view of the European great-power relations in Chapters 7 and 8 reveals, however, such transfers, whether implicit or explicit, are an important part of international processes. Moreover, denying the possibility of such transfers, given the flexibility possible in the operationalization of resources, merely denies Blainey's (1973, p. 115) observation that "In peace time the relations between two diplomats are like relations between two merchants. While the merchants trade in copper or transistors, the diplomats' transactions involve boundaries, spheres of influence, commercial concessions and a variety of other issues which they have in common." For a discussion of the core, see footnote 6 in Chapter 1. The von Neumann-Morgenstern solution, on the other hand, can be interpreted as a generalization of the core, and is
56
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
situation must make countless ad hoc assumptions about the sequencing of events and the actions available to decision makers.8 Nevertheless, if we keep our assumptions about bargaining as general as possible, the advantages of a traditional cooperative game-theoretic approach - the ability to deduce general propositions about coalitions and the outcomes they impose - outweigh its disadvantages. 2.3
Uncertainty
Our final assumption concerns the information that decision makers possess about their situation: A9. There is no uncertainty about the resources controlled by each country; and all decision makers have complete information about the game. Game theory admits of two types of uncertainty. The first is statistical and can arise because of the probabilities nature creates, unavoidable measurement error, and ambiguities in the meaning of key concepts. National leaders, for example, may be uncertain about how the various measures of national resources should best be combined into an overall assessment of a country's relative strength and its likelihood of winning a war. Nature may also play a role, as when it dictates the winner of a war as the result of uncontrollable factors such as a storm that sinks an armada or overcast skies that preclude aerial cover of ground troops. Nevertheless, in keeping with our objective of developing an ideal-type model, we assume that this type of uncertainty does not exist. The exclusion of statistical
8
designed, in particular, to treat games for which the core is empty. Briefly, if X is the set of all feasible outcomes then Y, a subset of X, is a von Neumann-Morgenstern solution to the cooperative game over X if Y satisfies two conditions. First, no element of Ydominates another element of Y: if, whenever some coalition has the ability to force a move between elements of 7, the members of that coalition do not unanimously favor such a move; and if they do favor such a move, they do not have the ability to realize it. Second, every element of X not in Y is dominated by some element of Y: if a feasible outcome not in Y is considered, then there exists at least one coalition that has the unanimous preference and the wherewithal to shift the outcome to some element of Y. Notice that in this definition, no allowance is made for the mechanisms whereby coalitional agreements are enforced - the definition of the V set refers merely to what coalitions prefer and can feasibly secure. Thus, the application of such solution notions presupposes the exogenous existence of mechanisms whereby coalitional agreements are enforced. (We emphasize, however, that focusing our discussion at this time on the von Neumann-Morgenstern solution should not be interpreted to mean that we regard it as a wholly satisfactory idea. Indeed, we regard other [albeit related] ideas as more appropriate models of cooperative bargaining and agreements [see, e.g., Ordeshook 1986]. However, we postpone further discussion until Chapter 3, where we must modify solution theory to fit the specific problem at hand.) Aside from the issues of complexity and tractability, the special problem of an extensiveform representation is the timing of moves. The usual structure of an extensive-form
2.3 Uncertainty
57
uncertainty necessarily gives our results a "knife-edged" quality that never exists in reality. Assumption A5, for example, implies that country / can defeat j if /'s resources exceedy's by even the slightest amount. It is never the case, however, that we can assert that one more tank, one more aircraft, or one more dollar of GNP renders one country winning over another. Ideally, we would prefer a model in which we begin with sentences of the form "/'s probability of defeating j is..." and in which we deduce sentences that include phrases such as ".. .makes conflict less likely...," or "... increases the chances that...," or "... leads to conflict with a probability of p, where 0 < p < 1 " Hence, we must learn to temper the interpretations of our abstract results with the realization that reality rarely affords decision makers the luxury of the certainty assumed by our model, and that attitudes toward risk may play a role not found in our analysis (see, e.g., Bueno de Mesquita 1981a). We should not anticipate, however, that the knife-edged quality of our assumptions necessarily implies that our conclusions will be knife-edged as well. Indeed, one of the important conclusions about international stability that we derive from these assumptions is that the necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability at least are not knife-edged, and that the extent to which this form of stability characterizes systems is likely to prove insensitive to the different ways in which we might incorporate statistical uncertainty into the analysis. It is also important to note that the assumption of a certain world does not preclude the study of miscalculation or error as a source of conflict any more than the inclusion of probabilities permits it. Presumably, miscalculation refers to the choice of actions based on factually incorrect beliefs (Jervis 1976), and one can miscalculate in a certain world as well as in a world that one believes is uncertain. Perhaps the presumption that we cannot study miscalculation from a rational-choice perspective derives from the mistaken view of some researchers that "'rational' models of conflict [are] based on the assumption that statesmen accurately perceive external threats and opportunities.. ." (Levy 1983b, p. 76). Yet, there is nothing in our paradigm that game supposes that the sequence with which players implement their decisions, including the possibility of simultaneous decisions, is determined exogenously. Although it is theoretically possible to model sequencing endogenously, this typically yields an extensive-form representation of such complexity that analysis becomes intractable. In most bargaining situations, of course, timing is endogenous, and the only practical solution to this dilemma to date has been to impose ad hoc assumptions on timing and move sequencing. It can be argued, of course, that the theory underlying cooperative solution notions such as the core, the von Neumann-Morgenstern solution, the bargaining set, and the competitive solution merely obscures this issue of timing and that any ultimate theoretical justification for any solution hypothesis must be an extensive-form representation of the moves and countermoves that bargaining allows. Here, though, we must take the tools currently provided by game theory, with the understanding that any analysis based on that theory may have to be modified as our understanding of our paradigm's fundamental elements is refined.
58
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
supposes that individual beliefs, probabilistic or otherwise, are factually correct. We assume simply that people act "optimally," conditional on their beliefs. Thus, as our analysis becomes more sophisticated, we can explore the implications of a world with miscalculation in it. There is, however, a second and potentially more profound type of uncertainty in political processes, which concerns the beliefs of decision makers, and which arises when decision makers are not fully informed about various parameters of the game and when information is asymmetrically distributed. Traditionally, game theory assumes that all players are fully informed about relevant parameters, including the strategies available to an opponent and the opponent's preferences - or at least that they all share the same "imperfect" view - and that each knows that the other knows that the other knows, and so on (this is generally referred to as the "assumption of common knowledge"). Suppose, however, that although person / knows the amount of resources he possesses, he is uncertain about person y's resources, and vice versa. That is to say, / knows y's resources only up to some probability distribution, whereas in fact these resources are determined. Player / could, of course, treat this problem in the usual expected utility way by substituting the expected value of ry into his or her calculations. However, what are we to make of the situation in which j's actions reveal something about ry? In this event, we have a doubly complex strategic situation. If j knows that / may learn something about Tj from j's actions, then j may prefer to take actions that either better reveal or disguise ry-; and if i is aware of j's strategic options, then / must attempt to infer ry-, knowing that j is choosing an action that takes /'s inferences into account. In other words, the usual he-thinks-that-Ithink regress found in noncooperative games extends now to beliefs as well as to strategies. An especially relevant example of the role of such uncertainty includes the analysis of terrorist acts and responses to them. A terrorist, who has seized hostages, may be uncertain about a particular national leader's resolve, just as that leader may be uncertain about the willingness of the terrorist to kill the hostages. If the leader gives in to the terrorist's demands and secures the release of the hostages, this reveals that the leader's resolve is not great, which increases the likelihood of future attacks. If the leader refuses to negotiate, the hostages may die (depending on the terrorist's decision), but the likelihood of future attacks may be reduced. Similarly, if the terrorist kills the hostages whenever his demands are not met, he will certainly die, but he will also strengthen the future viability of this strategy for his compatriots. If he releases the hostages even though his demands are not satisfied, he lives, but this action decreases the viability of this terrorist tactic.
2.3 Uncertainty
59
Presently, we can imagine circumstances in which countries are uncertain not merely about the resources of others, but also about what others believe about capabilities. Thus, actions may be taken to probe the likely responses to others, with the hope that these responses will reveal something about beliefs. Of course, if everyone is aware of everyone else's uncertainty and if everyone knows the purpose of these probes, we are led to formulate a considerably more complicated description of the strategic problem confronting decision makers than the one formulated in this volume. We are only now learning how to treat games with this form of uncertainty and strategic complexity (see, e.g., Kreps and Wilson 1982; Austen-Smith and Riker 1987; Powell 1987,1988; Alt, Calvert, and Humes 1988; Ordeshook and Palfrey 1988), and it is far too complex to incorporate into our analysis, at least until we have identified the basic structure of international relations. We note it here, however, to serve as a warning that a type of uncertainty remains outside of our analysis, and that this type may be especially important for a full understanding of events. Even though we do not consider the strategic imperatives occasioned by this second type of uncertainty, the analysis this volume offers is nevertheless relevant to inferring the consequences of such uncertainty for war. Specifically, a thesis that our analysis supports is that such uncertainty is a necessary condition for war. The argument is as follows: we begin with the first part of Blainey's hypothesis that When nations prepare to fight one another, they have contradictory expectations of the likely duration and outcome of the war. When those predictions, however, cease to be contradictory, the war is almost certain to end (Blainey 1973, pp. 246-7).
Second, such contradictory expectations cannot prevail in the usual setting of game theory - a special form of misperception is required. Finally, because our model precludes this type of misperception, if wars do not arise in our analysis - if a balance of power implies peace - then war requires the misperception that that uncertainty permits, thereby confirming the second part of Blainey's hypothesis. The critical part of this argument is its second step. Suppose, then, that rx and r2 measure the military capabilities of two potential belligerents and that both belligerents, prior to receiving any contemporaneous information about capabilities, share a common subjective prior about the distribution of rx — r2. Of course, if rx — r 2 > 0 then country 1 can defeat country 2, whereas if the inequality is reversed then 2 can defeat 1. Before choosing whether or not to initiate hostilities, however, suppose that each decision maker is privately informed about his own capability, which necessarily causes both decision makers to revise their beliefs that they can win a war. Presumably, the first part of Blainey's hypothesis requires that
60
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
each decision maker believes that he or she can win, but if these revised beliefs are common knowledge - if each person knows the other's belief, if each knows that the other knows, and so on - then probability theory dictates that these posterior beliefs cannot be contradictory (Aumann 1976). Common priors and common knowledge preclude both persons from believing that they can each win against the other. To ascertain the potential sources of such contradictory beliefs, Harsanyi (1968) argues persuasively that the critical condition is the assumption of common knowledge as against the assumption of common priors, since different subjective probabilities ought to be traceable to different experiences - to different observations about the real world. It follows that Blainey's precondition for war requires either a miscalculation of beliefs based on private information or a breakdown of the commonknowledge assumption.9 Game theory, including its application in this volume, generally imposes the common-knowledge assumption (in the form of presuming that all players know the game being played, all know that the others know, etc.), and so, barring miscalculation, the precondition in the second part of Blainey's hypothesis is satisfied by our analysis. Support for the hypothesis is then provided by a balance-of-power analysis that precludes war. If the common-knowledge assumption is critical, then we ought to ask how such knowledge is assured. Knowledge of each other's posterior beliefs is not sufficient - each must also know that the other knows, and so on - and public revelation of one's posteriors is not sufficient either since neither side can be assured that the other is not lying. Indeed, establishing an institutional framework whereby truthful revelation is assured remains one of the difficult design issues of the incentive-compatibility lit9
The common-knowledge assumption does not require merely that each person know the other's posterior beliefs - they must also know that the other knows, etc. - and the validity of the hypothesis that communication facilitates peace may lie here. For those unaccustomed to the jargon of game theory, we offer the following distinctions about the different types of information that players in a game might possess. In a game of perfect and complete information (illustrated by games such as chess and tic-tac-toe), each player is fully aware not only of all aspects of the game, but also of the previous choices of everybody else. In games of imperfect and complete information (that part of game theory made familiar by such expositions as Luce and Raiffa 1957), players are fully aware of all aspects of the game, but the previous choices of some players may be hidden from view, as when decisions are made simultaneously. Finally, in games of incomplete information, players are uninformed about some aspect of the game. In the most interesting case, this information is distributed asymmetrically, as when each person knows his preferences but not the preferences of others. Analyses of games of this last type assume, however, that the basis of preferences is common knowledge. For example, if we suppose that each person's preferences have a random component and that informational asymmetry arises because each person "sees" the result of the draw with respect to their preferences, then it is assumed that the densities governing preferences are common knowledge. Inconsistent beliefs in this instance can arise only if the common-knowledge assumption is violated.
2.4 Stability
61
erature in economics and game theory (for a theoretical discussion, see de Groot 1974 and McKelvey and Page 1986). We can speculate, however, that the appropriate institution is a bargaining format, which leads to the further speculation that the post-World War II argument that peace is fostered by increased communication (by increased trade, cultural exchanges, and the like) is more than simple utopianism. Keohane (1984) restates this argument in a more sophisticated way that hints directly at our argument: regimes are important not because they constitute centralized quasi-governments, but because they.. .increase the symmetry and improve the quality of the information that governments receive. By clustering issues together in the same forums over a long period of time, they help bring governments into continuing interaction with one another, reducing incentives to cheat and enhancing the value of reputation (pp. 244-5). What remains for this volume is establishing the consequences for international stability of "symmetric information" in a form that satisfies the common-knowledge assumption, which is of "high quality" in the sense that there is no statistical uncertainty about capabilities. 2.4
Stability
With our nine assumptions as preliminaries, we must now distinguish between two notions of stability. To see why we need two notions, recall our two scenarios from the previous chapter. In the first scenario, on the one hand, the existence (voting weight) of the players is not an issue. In the event that existence is thus assured exogenously, then the only form of instability that concerns decision makers is instability in the current distribution of resources. In the second scenario, on the other hand, alternative redistributions of resources can threaten existence or at least the opportunity to continue as a relevant participant. In other words, decision makers have a dual (but not independent) concern: securing a more advantageous distribution of resources and securing a distribution that ensures their own survival. Thus, we can speak of two forms of stability. The first notion concerns the instabilities in the distribution of resources among countries that threaten the sovereignty of some countries. In this instance, stability is of a particularly profound sort and means that no country can be eliminated from the game. The second notion concerns instabilities in the distribution of resources that do not threaten sovereignty. Morgenthau (1959), in his description of the operation of balance of power, suggests this distinction: So long as the balance of power operates successfully... [i]t creates a precarious stability in the relations between the respective nations, a stability that is always in danger of being disturbed and, therefore, is always in need of being reestablished.
62
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
This is, however, the only stability obtainable under the assumed conditions of the power pattern. For we are here in the presence of an inevitable inner contradiction of the balance of power [B]alance of power is supposed to [establish].. .stability in the power relations among nations; yet these relations are...by their very nature subject to continuous change. They are essentially unstable. Since the weights that determine the relative position of the scales have a tendency to change continuously by growing either heavier or lighter, whatever stability the balance of power may achieve must be precarious and subject to perpetual adjustment in conformity with intervening changes (pp. 161-2).
Similarly, although not abiding by our convention of distinguishing between the concepts of equilibrium and stability, Gilpin (1981) offers this hint at the necessity for identifying two separate notions of stability: In every international system there are continual occurrences of political, economic, and technological changes that promise gains or threaten losses for one or another actor. In most cases these potential gains and losses are minor, and only incremental adjustments are necessary in order to take account of them. Such changes take place within the existing international system, producing a condition of homeostatic equilibrium. The relative stability of the system is, in fact, largely determined by its capacity to adjust to the demands of actors affected by changing political and environmental conditions. In every system, therefore, a process of disequilibrium and adjustment is constantly taking place. In the absence of large potential net benefits from change, the system continues to remain in a state of equilibrium (p. 13).
Distinguishing between two forms of stability is important not merely because our scenarios suggest it, but also because it clarifies much of the confusion in the balance-of-power literature. In our view, balance of power is neither a goal of decision makers nor a necessary property of international systems, but is instead a property that results when conditions lead decision makers to conclude that certain actions but not others are in their interests. Briefly, notice that our second scenario, as elaborated by Assumptions Al through A9, satisfy Waltz's conditions for balanceof-power politics: that "the [international] order be anarchic and that it be populated by units wishing to survive" (1979, p. 121). Given an anarchic system - a system in which no organizations or constraints on action are imposed exogenously - composed of decision makers whose principal objective is to maximize their resources, provided that their existence is not threatened, then our two notions of stability taken together define a balance of power.10 Later, we provide formal definitions in terms of some game-theoretic concepts, but for now, informal definitions of our two types of stability 10
Of the quotations that introduce this chapter, Quester clearly has system stability in mind when referring to balance of power; Burns, however, is more ambiguous, but we can read into it the necessity for considering both forms of stability.
2.4 Stability
63
will suffice. First, if in fact "Whenever conflict between organized groups occurs, some question of sovereignty is involved" (Walker 1953) and if "there seems to be little disagreement.. .that a fundamental objective of creating a system of balance of power is to protect the security and independence of the participant nations" (Chatterjee 1975), then the following definition of the first type of stability - system stability - is central: System stability. The set S of countries in conjunction with the resource distribution r, where rt is strictly greater than 0 for all / in S, is system stable if no country or coalition of countries will be eliminated by some other country or coalition of countries. Notice that this definition avoids any reference to the "ability" of countries or of alliances to eliminate others in terms of specific equations or inequalities relating the resources of one set of players to that of another set. Insofar as ability is concerned, simple algebra tells us that if no country controls a majority of resources then, in any three-country system, for example, some two-country alliance controls more resources than the third. So some coalition always has the ability to eliminate someone else.11 However, until we formally link objectives, actions, and consequences, we cannot suppose that the mere fact that any two countries outweigh the third country implies that some pair of countries will in fact act to eliminate the third. We avoid specific algebraic relationships in the preceding definition, because such relationships ought to be deductions from the model as necessary and sufficient conditions for the selection of certain actions as against others, and not as theoretically primitive propositions. System stability focuses on final consequences and actions, and not on theoretical capabilities, and our second notion of stability - resource stability - takes a similar view. Later, we restate the definition of this second type of stability in terms of a particular solution concept for a cooperative ^-player game in characteristic function form called the core: the set of 11
Bull (1977, p. 113) states the situation correctly: "To speak of a complex or multiple balance among... three or four powers is not to imply that they are equal in strength. Whereas in a system dominated by two powers a situation of balance... can be achieved only if there is some rough parity of strength between the powers concerned, in a system of three or more powers balance can be achieved without a relationship of equality among the powers concerned because of the possibility of combination of the lesser against the greater." As simple as the algebra of three powers is concerned, however, its consequences have escaped universal notice. Specifically, if stability requires "a delicate balance among the relative capabilities of competing, fluctuating coalitions" (attributed to Claude 1962 by Wallace 1973), then three-country systems cannot be stable except in the unlikely event that one power controls precisely half the resources. Hence, even if it were true, as Jervis (1986, p. 60) asserts, that a balance of power requires that "there must be several actors of relatively equal power," or [as Blainey (1973, p. 110) states in his survey of the literature] that balance "now usually signifies equality and equilibrium," equality cannot ensure balance among alliances.
64
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
feasible outcomes that no coalition has the means or the unanimous inclination to upset in favor of some other outcome.12 However, referring to the possibility that countries will not act to redistribute resources to one country at the expense of another, the following definition is adequate for now: Resource stability. The system (S; r), with r, strictly greater than 0 for all / in 5, is resource stable if for no coalition C^S will the members of C redistribute resources to some new distribution r', where r\ is strictly greater than rt for all / in C. Thus, a resource-stable system is one in which no individual country or coalition of countries has an incentive and the means to alter the current distribution of resources. There is, of course, a close relationship between both types of stability. First, notice that if (S; r) is resource stable, then it is system stable: countries can be eliminated only by transferring resources. However, the opposite need not be true. As we show later, although countries may choose to force a redistribution of resources, the corresponding system may nevertheless be system stable in that no coalition will seek a redistribution in which some subset of countries is eliminated. Second, we can distinguish one form of stability from the other by noticing that a system is system stable if no redistribution of resources yields rt = 0 for any /, whereas resource stability implies that no redistribution whatsoever occurs. Despite the simplicity of this distinction, the two notions of stability are often confused in the literature, or the possibility or the necessity for a distinction goes unnoticed. For example, Rosecrance (1986, p. 45) argues that "A power relationship determined at a prior period may be undermined if a rising state transforms its position through industrialization. Then the balance of... responsibilities and rewards.. .will no longer correspond to power realities, and the new challenger will seek a redistribution of the spoils, usually through war." What this argument fails to specify, however, is the circumstances under which the instability takes the extreme form of system instability in which survival is threatened, as against the circumstances in which a more modest redistribution results in which no country's position of sovereignty is altered. 12
If a game has a core, then that core is necessarily a subset of any von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. A core is especially attractive as a solution hypothesis because of the type of stability its definition captures - once at the core, no coalition has the unilateral incentive or means to force any other outcome. Generally, however, most n-person («>3) games of political interest do not have cores, such as all games in which the players must divide a finite, fixed amount of some commodity or resource. It is, of course, this fact that Riker (1962) uses to assert his conclusion that balance-of-power politics is necessarily unstable.
2.4 Stability
65
For another example, Claude (1967, pp. 49-50) catalogues those scholars who define balance specifically in terms of the equality of power or resources. However, this equating perhaps best illustrates the confusion that our two definitions try to resolve. Is equality a necessary condition for, say, the absence of war? Is it a sufficient condition for peace? Is equality a definition of "balance" or is it the product of a balance of power and an indicator that some sort of "balance" prevails? The definitions of system and resource stability do not provide answers to such questions directly, since answers must be deduced from assumptions and from the interpretations we give words such as "negotiate" and "aggressive." Yet, the distinction between the two forms of stability permit us to avoid certain ambiguities. Because (S;r) can be system stable without being resource stable, then, unless proper distinctions are made, we are likely to confuse one sort of instability with another.13 With respect to war, for example, if (S; r) is not system stable, and if we interpret the choice of action a2 to imply the overt use of force, then some form of international conflict seems inevitable - some country will be absorbed or have its status as a great power altered. An important question, then, is: What distributions of resources imply system stability? Regardless of how we interpret various words, system stability does not mean that countries will not seek reallocations of resources by some means. Indeed, if (S;r) is system but not resource stable, reallocations are predicted. Those reallocations can occur in many ways, including the renegotiation of fishing rights and the actual transfer of territory from one nation to another. Thus, system stability does not presuppose that wars cannot occur, since it does not specify how resources might be transferred. Presumably, though, wars will take a limited form if system stability prevails, since each country, by definition, has a strategy that precludes its complete elimination from the game. Indeed, we can imagine 13
We note in passing that Organski's and Kugler's critique of balance-of-power theory (1980, pp. 14-17) rests on such a confusion. The problem is compounded by a non sequitur arising from their attempt to use a citation from Organski's (1968) work on world politics to show that "the 'balance' must represent an equal distribution of power" (p. 16). The passage in question simply asserts: "This is how the power system is supposed to work:... Given large numbers of nations with varying amounts of power each one striving to maximize its own power, there is a tendency of the entire system to be in balance. That is to say that the various nations group themselves together in such a way that no single nation or group of nations is strong enough to overwhelm the others, for its power is balanced by that of some opposing group. As long as the balance can be maintained, there is peace and the independence of small nations is maintained" (p. 274). As we see shortly, the situation Organski describes is realized under both equal and unequal distributions of power among nations; how he moves from the relative equality of potential coalitions to an equal distribution of power among national actors, we cannot fathom except insofar as he conflates system and resource stability.
66
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
circumstances in which countries might "voluntarily" agree to a transfer of resources so as to ensure system stability, or at least their survival in a system, and one of the issues that we will study in this volume is an elucidation of the circumstance under which such transfers might occur. Resource stability, on the other hand, implies not only that the system is stable, but also that no subsequent reallocations of resources are possible. Resource stability implies the unanimous choice of alternative a5 and, certainly, the absence of wars. It remains to be seen, though, whether equality of resources is either a necessary or a sufficient condition for such stability. In any event, we should anticipate that the circumstances under which a system can be resource stable are likely to be exceedingly fragile and easily upset by changes in technology and changes in the capabilities of countries through the natural evolution of domestic markets. A number of theoretical issues arise immediately with these two definitions of stability. First and foremost, of course, is a specification of the necessary and sufficient conditions for either form of stability to prevail. Burns (1968), Kaplan (1957), and Wright (1942), for example, argue that systems with fewer states are more stable than systems with a larger number of states, whereas Waltz (1979) argues the opposite. Are large systems favored over smaller ones? The contradictory and at times confusing assertions about the relationship between stability and the distribution of resources occasion a second important question: Must resources be distributed uniformly, and, if not, how great can the asymmetry in the distribution become before instability prevails? Are there nontrivial conditions of a country's resources that guarantee its survival? What types of coalitions and alliances are we likely to see? Will the ebb and flow of events more nearly correspond to balance as against bandwagoning behavior (cf. Waltz 1979 and Walt 1987)? That is, will smaller states join the smaller alliance to keep a large alliance or country from becoming predominant, or will they seek alliance with the larger member, hoping to gain some share of the spoils? If a system is not system stable, can it become stable, and, if so, what will the configuration of countries look like? If a system is system but not resource stable, can it ever become wholly stable, and, if not, what can we say about the likely pattern of redistributions? When we allow for growth, are states with the greatest growth rate advantaged? Do coalitions that initiate a preventive war necessarily exclude the threatening country? What patterns of investment and of alliances are we likely to see when resources grow at exogenously determined rates? And when we allow for the asymmetries occasioned by geography, are peripheral or central powers advantaged? Are system and resource stability more or less difficult to achieve when all countries are contiguous or when one country is central and others are peripheral? Is it necessarily
2.5 Enforcement of agreements
67
true, as Waltz (1979) maintains, that "the notion of a balancer is more a historical generalization than a theoretical concept" (p. 164)? That is, can we generalize the role of, say, Britain in the nineteenth century to its special geographic character relative to continental powers? 2.5
Enforcement of agreements
Seeking answers to the preceding questions is our preoccupation in the next four chapters. Before beginning, though, we should comment on the important issue of the logic of cooperative action and the mechanisms countries might use for enforcing agreements. Understanding cooperative action and the approaches game theory offers for modeling such action requires, first, that we abandon viewing simplistic games as models of political processes. For example, because international systems are anarchic, it is commonplace to believe that their processes occasion Prisoners' Dilemmas that cannot be resolved or that can be resolved only with great difficulty. Simple analogies appealing to the Prisoners' Dilemma or to a single play of any simple 2x2 game, however, are problematical. Political processes are a never-ending sequence of games, and even so simple a game as this one, if played sequentially, offers quite different strategic incentives than the dilemma played once. For example, Wagner (1983) shows how the imperatives of the dilemma are changed if we merely give players a chance to detect defections from cooperation, as well as the opportunity to respond, and if we make these facts common knowledge. Similarly, Prisoners' Dilemmas, such as those that occasion various economic market failures, pervade our existence, and their resolution with and without appeals to exogenous forces, when the stakes become sufficiently great, is not uncommon. The history of human affairs attests to the considerable degree of imagination and invention - including the invention of the state itself - that has occurred in response to the problems such dilemmas occasion. There is no reason to suppose a priori, unless other factors operate, that with the stakes as great as they are today in international affairs, invention cannot occur here as well. Merely acknowledging the complexity of political processes, however, sidesteps a complex facet of cooperation, which we can best consider in the context of a simple two-person Prisoners' Dilemma. The usual context for the dilemma is to suppose that, regardless of whatever communication occurs beforehand, each player must choose his or her strategy without knowing the strategy selected by the other, in which case the joint selection of dominant actions for all participants leads to an outcome they unanimously prefer to avoid. Alternatively, suppose this game is played in a cooperative context that allows the players a completely free hand in determining the outcome, so that the issue of whether choices must be
68
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
made simultaneously, or whether binding contracts between the players are feasible, is wholly endogenous to the situation. At this point, we have two alternative ways in which we can proceed with our analysis: (1) model the complex game that unrestricted negotiation allows, including the mechanisms that might be employed to enforce contracts; or (2) simply ascertain what contracts we are likely to observe if binding agreements are possible, ignoring the mechanisms whereby enforcement of agreements is assured. Because modeling endogenously determined games, as well as the mechanisms players might implement, is exceedingly difficult, cooperative game theory traditionally focuses on the second mode of analysis. Hence, if confronted with a Prisoners' Dilemma, cooperative game theory, without specifying precisely how agreements are implemented, simply predicts that a Pareto-optimal outcome will prevail, as against the Pareto-inefficient outcome that results from noncooperative (simultaneous and uncoordinated) choice. In particular, if lotteries are precluded, the prediction is the outcome that obtains when both persons cooperate, because, in the terminology of game theory, this outcome is the unique element of the core. This is the approach we take in this volume. Thus, our analysis seeks to specify the agreements and outcomes that prevail if decision makers have at their disposal mechanisms for the enforcement of agreements: for committing to one alliance rather than another, and for implementing the actual tranfer of resources. (However, see footnote 8 in Chapter 3 for the outline of an extensive-form model that rationalizes our analysis as a noncooperative equilibrium and that thereby assures the endogenous enforcement of the agreements our analysis otherwise circumvents.) Questions nevertheless remain as to whether we can design such mechanisms, whether they are likely to arise "naturally" in anarchic systems, and whether feasible mechanisms admit the sorts of agreements that are part of system-stable systems. There are at present two seemingly distinct, but in fact closely related approaches to this issue, both of which take cognizance of the fact that any such mechanism must correspond to a noncooperative game (in order that we not solve the problem of cooperation by assuming it away) and in which the actions sufficient to yield the prespecified cooperative outcomes are dominant choices or, minimally, equilibrium choices.14 The 14
There is a third approach, introduced in population genetics and recently popularized in political science (Axelrod, 1984). Using the notion of evolutionary stable strategies (ESS) - strategies that cannot be "invaded" by mutant strategies (see, especially, Maynard-Smith 1974) - the approach here is to establish various strategies that yield cooperative outcomes as ESS. One difficulty with this approach, however, is illustrated by the fact that the commonly cited source of cooperation in repeated Prisoners' Dilemmas, tit-for-tat, is not ESS (Boyd and Lorderbaum 1987).
2.5 Enforcement of agreements
69
first approach seeks to identify the specific institutional structures that guide and constrain individual choices and that are thereby sufficient to yield the desired outcomes as the consequence of dominant or equilibrium choices. Although research to date has focused on mechanisms that use some type of taxation device for solving a market failure, there is no reason to suppose that this approach cannot have a broader application. The theoretical difficulty with implementation of cooperation in anarchic international systems by relying only on institutional design, however, is that institutions survive only if they serve the purposes of those whose actions they seek to regulate. If they are to serve the purpose of inducing cooperation then, excepting the existence of some exogenous "higher" authority that enforces their rules, they themselves must ultimately be viewed as the product of noncooperative choices in anarchic systems. To reiterate a point made earlier, if "the equilibrium of a balance is maintained through states abiding by rules, then one needs an explanation of how agreement on the rules is achieved and maintained" (Waltz 1979, p. 121). This view compels us, then, to regard institutions more as facilitating agents, and less as the fundamental source of cooperation or the primary explanation for cooperation.15 The second approach takes cognizance of the fact that the "games" nations and national leaders play entail sequences of moves - indeed, even repetitions of the same game - and it explores the circumstances under which such repetition solves the problem of cooperation that recourse to institutional design alone cannot solve. In particular, what repetition allows is the possibility that players can retaliate subsequent to an "uncooperative" choice, and that retaliation renders cooperative action an equilibrium. For example, one mechanism for inducing such action in the Prisoners' Dilemma is to require that the two participants play the game repeatedly, without knowing which game in the sequence will be the last. In this instance, a Pareto-efficient, cooperative outcome (via the joint selection of a strategy such as tit for tat) corresponds to an equilibrium (Taylor 1976). Thus, it is tempting to assert that this view of politics as a repeated game rationalizes the existence and durability of fundamental political institutions such as constitutions, and indeed this hypothesis about the source of cooperation and the enforcement of contracts is especially appealing in international systems.16 We can discern, for example, the incentives to abide by one's treaty obligations in the fact that by pursuing such a strategy, one secures a reputation that becomes an asset in 15
16
A debate of the issues surrounding this view is offered, for example, in Shepsle and Weingast's (1984) response to McKelvey and Ordeshook (1984). For a discussion of these issues in the context of international relations theory, see Snyder and Diesing (1977), Axelrod and Keohane (1985), and Oye (1986). The citations in Oye's essay, in particular, are a good starting point for review of the relevant literature.
70
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
subsequent negotiations - in subsequent repetitions of the "international politics game." Similarly, institutions themselves are rendered viable because they become part of the technology for playing a repeated game. At this point, however, game theory poses an especially perplexing problem. Regardless of the particular definition adopted, infinitely repeated games generally possess a great many equilibria, and a variety of "folk theorems" establish that nearly any outcome, including Pareto-inefficient ones, can be sustained by some equilibrium of strategies.17 In the infinitely repeated Prisoners' Dilemma, for example, both players always defecting remains an equilibrium: anyone playing a strategy that cooperates some of the time against someone who always defects would do better by defecting all of the time as well. This multiplicity of equilibria occasions two difficulties. First, it leaves unanswered the question of why Paretoefficient (cooperative) as against -inefficient outcomes prevail. What precisely is the process that allows players to implicitly coordinate in order to achieve efficient (cooperative) as against inefficient (noncooperative) equilibria? Second, if (#, b) and (c, d) are both equilibrium strategy pairs then it is not necessarily the case (unless the game is two-person and zerosum) that (#, d) or (c, b) are equilibria, in which case we must still ascertain how players implicitly coordinate to achieve any equilibrium in the fundamental noncooperative game we employ to explain cooperation. There is a second problem. Our analysis assumes not only perfect information (and thus the absence of uncertainty), but also complete information (and thus common knowledge of all aspects of the game). However, games of incomplete and asymmetric information, like their infinitely repeated counterparts, also typically possess multiple equilibria, and the nature of these equilibria is sensitive not only to the initial beliefs of participants but also to the institutional details governing the sequential revelation of information. Even seemingly innocuous features of a situation, such as a nonbinding straw poll taken prior to a formal vote, can profoundly affect outcomes. Unfortunately, we have only just begun to understand the analysis of such games, and we are no better here at resolving the problems occasioned by multiple equilibria than we are in repeated games in general. 17
See, for example, Fudenberg and Maskin (1986) and the literature they cite. To appreciate the consternation that multiplicity of equilibria occasion, see also Harsanyi and Selten (1988). One solution to this problem, which we adopt in the model outlined in footnote 8 of Chapter 3, is to assume that strategies are stationary - that players make the same choices whenever they find themselves in identical circumstances, regardless of whatever events have transpired (assuming that those events do not alter beliefs or capabilities). Such an assumption greatly facilitates analysis and reduces the number of equilibria with which we must contend. However, aside from appeals to cognitive capabilities, stationarity is itself an ad hoc hypothesis.
2.5 Enforcement of agreements
71
Thus, whether through an explicit institutional structure, through the strategic imperatives of repeated play, or through combination of the two, ensuring cooperative action and the enforcement of agreements is not simple. It is probably the case, of course, that by looking for the sources of cooperation in systems that are anarchic "in the extreme," we have pushed the problem to too fundamental a level: no event or negotiation occurs in an environment in which there does not exist some institutional structure and some historically based expectations about what others will do. Although the meaning of words such as "culture" and "tradition" await definition and operationalization in these formal analyses, it is perhaps here, in the context of the issue of equilibrium selection, that we see a role for such notions. In any event, it is the recognition of problems of this sort that helps explain the difficulty nations confront in resolving the details of agreements, which, although appearing inconsequential when compared to the scope of the general issues under consideration, can nevertheless undermine their ability to ensure that abiding by the agreement is in the complete interest of both persons. And to the extent that countries cannot implement agreements in a timely fashion, conflict can occur even if all of our assumptions are otherwise satisfied. This fact not only makes the issue of implementation and the study of the sources of cooperative action a primary concern, it also provides, if not an argument against the theory this volume offers, then an argument for requiring that we regard the conditions we subsequently establish for system and resource stability as merely necessary but not sufficient. Our analysis assumes the feasibility of implementing agreements, but if technology or the details of international processes preclude this, then self-interest may imply instability. There is, then, no obligatory conflict between realist arguments and those regarding institutions as essential to the maintenance of stability and peace. On the one hand, we must accept the fact that, unless there exist mechanisms for the implementation and enforcement of agreements, the forces for stability described in this volume can be ineffectual. On the other hand, mechanisms alone cannot ensure stability unless there are incentives for their maintenance and their use, incentives such as the ones this volume seeks to describe in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions for stability. Thus, it is prudent to maintain the hypothesis that Nonhegemonic cooperation is difficult, since it must take place among independent states that are motivated more by their own conceptions of self-interest than by a devotion to the common good The importance of regimes for cooperation supports the Institutionalist claim... that international institutions help to realize common interests in world politics. An argument for this view has been made here... by relying on Realist assumptions that states are egoistic, rational
72
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
actors operating on the basis of their own self interest. Institutions are necessary, even on these restrictive premises, in order to achieve state purposes Realism should not be discarded, since its insights are fundamental to an understanding of world politics... but it does need to be reformulated to reflect the impact of information-gathering institutions on state behavior, even when rational egoism persists (Keohane 1984, pp. 245-6).
2.6
Theoretical domain
The preceding discussion helps identify the context and limitations of our analysis. Within this context, Assumptions Al through A9 define our theory's domain: the class of phenomena to which it can be legitimately applied. Not all assumptions, however, perform this task equally well. The assumption that decision makers are rational merely places our theory in a particular paradigm - in this instance, a paradigm that is not intended to study only part of social reality but all of it. Other assumptions, such as that information is complete, are intended to facilitate initial formulations, and we can only hope that they will be weakened if the theory appears promising. However, our assumptions about resources, Al, A3, A4, and A5, together define the domain of our theory, if not all balanceof-power theories. Assumption A4 requires that national leaders maximize /•/, which to this point we have ambiguously referred to as country /'s national resources, whereas A5 requires that whatever rt measures also determines a state's capability of securing rt in conflict, its military capability. Furthermore, A4 requires that all countries share a common maximand, and A5 requires that the capability of countries is also measured by a common variable. Finally, Al and A3 suppose that whatever r measures is transferable across countries on a one-to-one basis and in finite supply. The consequence of these assumptions, then, is that our theory concerns those international systems in which readily identifiable sovereign entities (countries) maximize the same 'thing,9 which is in limited but transferable supply, and which translates directly into a measure of a country's capacity for securing its ends and maintaining its security. It is tempting in this context to relabel rt as country /'s power and to assert that countries maximize power. After all, whatever power is, there is likely to be some consensus that it is relative and therefore must be in finite supply at least to the extent that an increase in one person's power decreases someone else's; and assuming that decision makers maximize power seems only reasonable if the alternative is to suppose that they minimize it or deem it irrelevant to their goals. In theories of rational choice, however, the concept of power is afictionas a theoretically primitive idea it is at best a derivative notion (e.g., market power in microeconomics) -
2.6 Theoretical domain
73
and relabeling rt as /'s power merely replaces notation with a theoretically undefined word. In any event, such a relabeling takes us no closer to an operational definition of rt than does the notation itself, and theories of politics that pretend otherwise are doomed to ambiguity. If, on the other hand, we operationalize resources less ambiguously, as Organski and Kugler (1980) do by basing their analysis on measures of GNP or GNP per capita, the empirical limitations of the consequence of our three assumptions become more apparent. Assuming that all countries maximize some measure of their per-capita wealth is not an unreasonable basis for theorizing about international politics. Such an assumption is not inconsistent with a variety of views about international politics ranging from a belief that private entrepreneurs in search of profits direct the destinies of states to the hypothesis that national leaders are motivated simply by the median welfare of their populations. However, to assert that GNP also translates directly into an ability to wrest such resources from another sovereign state (i.e., a military capability) is problematical. Organski and Kugler argue that GNP and military capability are closely related - that GNP correlates highly with the measures of capability that others offer - but clearly such a relationship is at best imprecise. Even if we could convert every component of GNP into wealth with which we might purchase military capability, and even if every aspect of military capability had a monetary antecedent, time lags in the conversion of one resource into the other would render the correspondence imperfect. Evaluating any particular operationalization of the thing we call resources, then, reveals that even if we sidestep the social preference problem defined by Arrow, the things countries maximize may not be immediately convertible into a capacity for resisting aggression or for otherwise securing those ends. Thus, it is also tempting to view the consequence of Al, A3, A4, and A5 as a limitation of the theory that some theoretical refinement ought to rectify. Whether the theory requires rectification, however, is a matter of judgment based on an empirical assessment of the limits of the theory's domain relative to the variety of domains offered by nature. Clearly, some restriction on our theory is required. For example, suppose national leaders and the populations they represent maximize "spiritual contentment" as measured by the logical consistency of a common religious dogma. Because the means to such an end will not set nations in conflict - indeed, it may render the issue of sovereignty itself moot - the theorems we offer in subsequent chapters will be irrelevant to an understanding of international relations in such a system. If only international systems of this type exist, then our theory would be little more than an exercise in logical thinking. Alternatively, if a national leader seeks to maximize colonial territory and if the ability to secure and defend that
74
2 Basic elements of a model and definitions of stability
territory and one's sovereignty depends on a wholly unrelated military capability, then once again our theory will prove irrelevant (although we suspect that such a leader will enjoy a brief tenure). To the extent, though, that territory and military capability correlate, then the relevance of our theory increases and we should begin to detect the operation of the forces our theory describes. And if that correlation becomes 1, then the forces our theory describes should be the only forces that operate. The particular difficulty with which we must contend, then, is the possibility that this correlation is low and that the discrepancies between the two aspects of resources - goals and means - occasion forces that render the balance of power an insignificant or otherwise minor consideration in the relations of states. We ought not to try to resolve this empirical issue, however, without reference to the empirical verisimilitude of the theory's implications. Perceptions about motives can be deceptive, and the relationship between means and ends - between, say, a country's economic status, the living standard of its inhabitants, and its ability to influence (if not militarily overcome) other countries - may be obscure even to astute observers; witness the contemporary debate over the implications of deficit spending and balance of payments. Detailed diplomatic histories, for example, might provide valuable insights into the motives and perceptions of key decision makers, but we cannot take such histories as definitive: if events (e.g., the pattern of alliances, the outbreak of war, and changes in sovereignty) corroborate the theory, but if motives as revealed by public utterances, private correspondences, and public and secret treaties are distinct from the motives required to apply the theory, then we ought to suspect the interpretation of those histories. On the other hand, if events fail to corroborate the theory's predictions, then we should use those histories (as well as any other data at our disposal) to infer the motives of decision makers and to guide the development of an appropriate theory.
CHAPTER 3
System stability and the balance of power
The balance of power is a system designed to maintain a continuous conviction in every state that if it attempted aggression, it would encounter an invincible combination of the others. Quincy Wright, A Study of War (1942, p. 254)
The aspiration of power on the part of several nations, each trying either to maintain or overthrow the status quo, leads necessarily to a configuration that is called the balance of power and to policies that aim at preserving it The balance of power and policies aimed at its preservation are not only inevitable but are an essential stabilizing factor in a society of sovereign nations. Hans Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations (1973, p. 161)
In this chapter and the next, we analyze the consequences of the assumptions offered in Chapter 2 by ascertaining the conditions under which both system and resource stability prevail in ^-country systems. In doing so, we are able to resolve much of the confusion between assumptions and conclusions found in earlier attempts to theorize about balance of power. And although our model differs significantly in form from the verbal models that others before us formulate, our principal conclusion accords with the scholarly intuition underlying balance-of-power theories: stability of both sorts is possible. We contest Riker's (1962) hypothesis, then, that international systems are characterized by the instabilities of cooperative zero-sum games. Self-interest, we show, does not lead necessarily to the formation of minimal winning coalitions that expropriate all from the losers. These conclusions suggest that wars, especially those that yield significant changes in great-power resources, are occasioned by matters we shall consider in Chapters 5 and 6 (differential growth rates of resources and the asymmetries occasioned by geography) or by the "frictions" we have not explicitly operationalized as part of our analysis (such as those arising from the constraints imposed by domestic politics, or because of the technological infeasibility of actually transferring resources from one country to another). 75
76
3 System stability and the balance of power
3.1
Some immediate consequences of our assumptions
Although a number of other assumptions might be employed to constrain and define an international system, Al to A9 not only yield a set of consequences that are consonant with much of the scholarly thinking about balance of power, but also many of these consequences often have been taken as theoretically primitive assumptions in other balance-of-power theories or as descriptions of systems "in or out of balance." We begin with one consequence, which, although a trivial implication of our assumptions, is nevertheless an important component of our analysis: • If any single country controls a majority of the resources available to all countries in the system, then that country will eliminate all others and expropriate all the available resources. Formally: Remark 3.1. If rt>R/2 for some / in S, then / will eliminate all others, and ({/};/?) prevails as the final outcome. This consequence is obvious, given the assumptions, and it asserts that any state securing hegemony becomes a dictator.1 This remark, however, once again underscores the "knife-edged" nature of our assumptions. Because our model does not consider uncertainty and because it, of necessity, supposes that imprecise concepts can be represented precisely, the results depend on the specific values of parameters. That is, if a country secures more than exactly half the resources, it becomes dominant, with certainty. In reality, of course, and as we noted earlier in our discussion of uncertainty, we can never say that a particular dollar added to the GNP or a resource unit added to some index renders a country dominant and capable of eliminating the sovereignty of the rest. We are especially interested in learning, then, whether the conditions for stability in international systems require certainty or uncertainty. If these conditions are similarly knife-edged, then we can infer that stability, if it exists at all in reality, can exist only if constraints exogenous to our analysis impinge on international affairs or if the statistical uncertainty associated with the measurement of resources and military capabilities, coupled with assumptions about attitudes toward risk of key decision makers, preclude the 1
The literature offers a variety of definitions of a hegemon (Aron 1973, Keohane and Nye 1977, Gilpin 1981, Modelski 1983, and Keohane 1984), but throughout this text, a hegemon or (equivalently) a predominant country simply refers to a country that controls more than half of the system's resources. A near-predominant country is one that controls precisely half the resources. In Chapter 6, we generalize these definitions to accommodate the discounting of resources occasioned by geography.
3.1 Some immediate consequences of our assumptions
77
choice of aggressive acts. However, if these conditions are not knife-edged (which they are not), then our confidence that such stability can prevail in reality is increased. Aside from this issue, the maxim embodied in Remark 3.1 nevertheless retains a considerable degree of empirical plausibility: namely, that states (or, more properly, their policy makers) are sensitive to resource thresholds that enable or constrain potential opponents from achieving hegemony. The resources in question may take the form of political prestige and military might, or, more straightforwardly, economic forms. In the former case, and although the example refers to an alliance rather than a single country, we find it difficult to explain the vigor with which the Quay d'Orsai sought in the early 1890s to dislodge Czarist Russia from its alliance with Wilhelmine Germany except in terms of the strategic perception that the resources amassed by a German/Austro-Hungarian/Russian coalition would establish it as hegemonic on the European continent, and thereby threaten not only the ability of France to amass resources from colonial possessions and protectorates in the Near East and South Asia, but its eventual sovereignty as well. Indeed, the same concerns preoccupy the Triple Entente with respect to potential Germanic hegemony over the Balkans and the Straits. The diplomatic archives are replete with documentation of this shared perception that the perseverance of this alliance would permit its members to breach some resource threshold and achieve eventual hegemony. The classic statement of this perception is Sir Eyre Crowe's 1907 memorandum in which he observed: History shows that the danger threatening the independence of this or that nation has generally arisen, at least in part, out of the monetary predominance of a neighboring State at once militarily powerful, economically efficient, and ambitious to extend its frontiers or spread its influence, the danger being directly proportionate to the degree of its power and efficiency, and to the spontaneity or "inevitableness" of its ambitions. The only check on the abuse of political predominance derived from such a position has always consisted in the opposition of an equally formidable rival, or of a combination of several countries forming leagues of defence. The equilibrium established by such a grouping of forces is technically known as the balance of power, and it has become almost an historical truism to identify England's secular policy with the maintenance of this balance by throwing her weight in this scale and now in that, but ever on the side opposed to the political dictatorship of the strongest single State or group at a given time (Gooch and Temperley 1926, pp. iii, 403). Note also a little later in the same document where he suggests as an explanation of Germany's weltpolitik that Germany is definitely aiming at a general political hegemony and maritime ascendancy, threatening the independence of her neighbors and ultimately the existence of England... (Gooch and Temperley 1926, pp. iii, 417; emphasis added).
78
3 System stability and the balance of power
Similar views, albeit focused on Russia and Great Britain, were current in German military and diplomatic circles (Conrad 1922, pp. iii, 597; and Fischer 1961, pp. 59ff). In another case, wefindconsiderable evidence that Imperial Japanese planners from the late 1920s onward perceived United States policy in Asia and the Pacific as aimed at diminishing Japanese access to economic resources - particularly vital raw materials - so as to prevent the resource threshold necessary for the Asian hegemony Japan envisioned in its Greater East Asian Co-Prosperity Sphere. Although Remark 3.1 may state the maxim with a "knife-edged" precision that only imperfectly obtains in empirical cases, it merely renders explicit an intuition upon which statecraft has been predicated since the emergence of states. Indeed, if one understands the "elimination" of a nation to consist not in its destruction and the extermination of its people, but rather in deprivation of its freedom of political, military, and economic action, in its subsumption by the political dictatorship of another state, the vassal or satellite of which it becomes while technically retaining national existence, then Remark 3.1 - even with its knife-edged precision - captures an essential element of both the strategic thinking of statesmen and the theorizing of balance-of-power theorists. Another consequence of Remark 3.1 bears directly on the debate over the greater stability of bipolar versus multipolar systems, since it asserts that the only system- and resource-stable two-country (bipolar) system is one in which resources are exactly evenly divided. Again, the empirical meaning of such a consequence must be tempered by those features of reality we do not consider. It nevertheless would follow straightforwardly from almost any reasonable probabilistic adaptation of our model that "as the expected values of the resources of two countries in a two-country system become equal, the probability that one country will succeed in any attempt to become a hegemon will decrease." For example, suppose rx and r2 are both random variables, so that we must speak of the probability that one exceeds the other and vice versa. Notice, however, that as random variables, they have two interpretations. First, we might be referring to the decision maker's uncertainty about parameter values; second, we might be referring to our (the analyst's) uncertainty as to what a decision maker will believe about parameter values. This is an important distinction. Consider the first possibility, and let p denote the probability that /*! exceeds r2, which is a probability we can deduce directly from the presumed joint distribution of rx and r2. If p also measures a decision maker's perception of the probability with which an attack by 1 on 2 will be successful, then 1 need only perform the appropriate expected utility calculation in deciding what to do. That is, attack if pu + (l— p)u'> w",
3.1 Some immediate consequences of our assumptions
79
f
where u is the utility of success, u is the utility of failure, and u" is the utility of the status quo; otherwise do not attack. Here again, the analysis will be knife-edged in that if the expected utility of an attack exceeds u" by however small an amount, then we will predict an attack; otherwise not. Still, even if reality is knife-edged, we are not likely to be able to measure the parameters of decision criteria with perfect accuracy, in which case the uncertainty is ours as analysts. In this event, we can only utter predictions of the form "an attack by 1 on 2 is more likely as rx increases relative to r2."2 The implications of Remark 3.1 should affect profoundly the decisions of national leaders when they choose whether or not to form alliances. If, in an /7-country system, the elimination of (say) country j leads to the eventual elimination of country / in subsequent plays of any of the n-1, n-2, « - 3 , etc., country games, then / will act to block y's elimination (if such action is feasible). Hence: • If the resources of each country in an international system are less than or equal to half the resources available to all countries in the system, no country will act to increase the resources of any other to a majority of the available resources. That is: Remark 3.2. If r^R/2 for all /, no country will act to increase the resources of another country in excess of R/2. By permitting another country to control over half the resources, each country knows that the only stable system and stable resource distribution that can prevail ultimately is the unique outcome in which the dominant country eliminates all others. Thus, Remark 3.2 helps "fill in" each country's preference order over alternative outcomes this way: / strictly prefers any 77-tuple of resources r in which rt > 0 and r7 < R/2 for all jeS to any ^-tuple r' in which rj>R/2, j^i; that is, every country prefers a resource distribution that prevents the preponderance of any other. 2
Remark 3.1 also reveals one possibility that our model does not incorporate: the breakup of sovereign entities into two or more independent decision makers, that is, civil wars. Clearly, we could use our analysis to model internal wars simply by reconceptualizing the elements of S as, say, the significant factions in a country. Throughout our analysis, though, we suppose that once / "absorbs" j , i can be forced to cede resources to another country only by considerations that are external to it. Further, once the number of countries reduces to n, it cannot increase later to n +1 or more owing to the division of a country. If such a division occurs, we must assume that it does so because of circumstances endogenous to that country. We could certainly analyze the resulting (n — l)-country system (assuming that our results are general and do not depend on the number of countries in a system), but we cannot predict its emergence.
80
3 System stability and the balance of power
Our third remark takes us closer to establishing a necessary and sufficient condition for system stability: Remark 3.3. If rt = R/2 for some country / in S (if some country is near-predominant), then no member of S—{/} will attack another member of S— {/}. If CcS—[i] attacks some C'CS— {/}, then, by Assumption A7, / will attack C and absorb all of its resources, in which case, by Remark 3.1, the final outcome will be ({/};/?). That is, aggressive choices among the members of S— [i] create opportunities for the near-predominant country, /, to become predominant. Remark 3.3 demonsrates the critical nature of Assumption A7 for our analysis. With it, countries must guard against the possibility that third parties can take advantage of "localized" conflicts. This has the important consequence of keeping such conflicts from occurring, especially if a third country is close to becoming hegemonic. Without this assumption, on the other hand, we might anticipate that even if r; = R/2 for some /, that some members of S— [i] could attack other members of this set. Yet, this could only occur if all the members of S— {/} agree to "terminate hostilities" the minute / attacks one of them, and it is indeed difficult to envision such an agreement among warring parties. We can find no such case of prior agreement to terminate hostilities in the eventuality of attack by a third party in recorded history; however, some examples of such agreements after a third party's attack can be found - for example, Constantius' agreement to Sassanid Persia's peace terms to permit redeployment of the Eastern Roman armies against the then-usurper Julian's eastward march on Constantinople from Gaul in A.D. 361. However, even here, despite the Persians' clear preference for the relatively ineffectual Constantius as opposed to the more militarily gifted Julian as Roman Emperor, the Sassanid Shah imposed draconian terms - terms that undermined Constantius' support among his generals - on the very party whose victory in the battle for the throne he sought to ensure. This example suggests that the existence of sufficient self-interest to impel countries into war militates against sufficient prescience to prepare before the fact for peace so as to face other threatening contingencies. Nevertheless, such agreements may be theoretically possible, and, as such, they lead to a violation of our assumption, in which case Remark 3.3 is no longer valid. Nonetheless, we find little reason to dispute the general plausibility of our assertion that states with sufficient self-interest to form coalitions against other (potentially hegemonic) states will be unlikely to wage war within that coalition for fear of enabling their common enemy's predominance.
3.1 Some immediate consequences of our assumptions
81
Remark 3.4. If r; = R/2, then / has no means for increasing its resources. Country / can increase its resources in only two ways (keeping in mind that our assumptions do not yet permit differential internal resource growth across countries): by attacking or threatening to attack a weaker country or coalition, or by forming a coalition with other countries to attack countries not in the coalition. By Remark 3.3, no country in S— [i] will attack another country in S— {/}. Thus, all countries in S— [i] are free to attack / either individually or collectively, but if / attacks some country or coalition and wins, it becomes dominant. Thus, all members of S— [/}, whose total resources necessarily equal rh have action a4 as a dominant choice, which in this instance is "attack / if / attacks anyone in S— [/}." Hence, / cannot increase its resources by attacking. Similarly, since no country has an incentive to relinquish any resources to / as a consequence of any coalition, / knows that no coalition is possible in which it can secure additional resources. An important consequence of this discussion, then, is this: Remark 3.5. If r( = R/2 for some / in S, then (S;r) is system stable and resource stable. From Remark 3.3, no member of S— [i] will attack another member of S— {/}; from Remark 3.4, / has no means of increasing its resources. Thus, no country's resources will be redistributed to other countries and no country will be eliminated. Remark 3.5, then, provides a sufficient condition for system and resource stability. Notice also that if we keep Remarks 3.3 and 3.4 in mind, then Remark 3.5 summarizes the intuition that a balance-of-power system protects the survival of small states (see Morgenthau 1973 and Hertz 1959). In Remark 3.3, such states are protected from larger but not predominant ones by the threat that warfare poses to all but the largest state, whereas in Remark 3.4, smaller states are protected from attack by a predominant one because no one can permit the largest state to become predominant. 3 Herein, then, is the basis for Crowe's observation on the July 1914 crisis that Our interests are tied up with those of France and Russia in this struggle, which is not for the possession of Serbia, but one between Germany aiming at a political dictatorship in Europe and the Powers who desire to retain individual freedom (Gooch and Temperley 1926, pp. iv, 101). Herein also is the basis for Morgenthau's (1973, p. 167) insistence that 3
Following both Morgenthau and Herz, we are tacitly assuming here that smaller states are less resource-abundant than larger states. Empirical reality may violate this assumption under a number of conditions, including differential distribution of technologies over states.
82
3 System stability and the balance of power
the international balance of power is only a particular manifestation of a general social principle to which all societies composed of a number of autonomous units owe the autonomy of their component parts; that the balance of power and policies aimed at its preservation are not only inevitable but are an essential stabilizing factor in a society of sovereign nations...
and for Waltz's characterization of the balance of power as a "self-help system" (1979, p. 118). Remarks 3.3, 3.4, and 3.5, then, reveal a profoundly important feature of the balance of power, which students of international affairs such as Morgenthau and Waltz appreciate; namely, the balance of power is not merely the equating of one combination of resources against another combination. Rather, the balance of power necessarily embodies, implicitly or explicitly, a nexus of "mutual security" relationships among states, enforced by the understanding that hegemonic dominance threatens more than a single state. To reiterate an earlier point, notice that Remark 3.5 depends critically on Assumption A7 (by way of its dependence on Remark 3.3). If countries can somehow agree to localize their conflicts with the guarantee that they will jointly move against the intervention of external parties, then the condition that rt = R/2 is not sufficient to ensure either system or resource stability. However, with such a guarantee, the countries party to it simply become a new subsystem, and Remarks 3.1 through 3.5 apply to this subsystem. This leads to an interesting speculative question: Is (5; r) system stable whenever all of its subsystems are system stable? And, conversely, if all subsystems are system stable, is (S;r) system stable? The hint that such relationships need not exist, but that any such relationship is important, is offered by Bull (1977, pp. 116-17) in his summary of the meaning of balance of power: First, the general balance of power serves to prevent the system of states from being transformed by conquest into a universal empire Second, local balances of power - where they exist - serve to protect the independence of states in particular areas from absorption or domination by a locally preponderant power Third, both the general balance of power, and such local balances as exist at present, help to provide the conditions in which other institutions on which international order depends are able to operate.
We cannot answer our two queries until we identify the necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability. However, notice that all subsystems are system stable if and only if every two-country subsystem is system stable. It follows from Remark 3.1, then, that every subsystem can be system stable only if resources are uniformly distributed across all n countries in S. And, as we see shortly, this is sufficient to ensure that (S; r) is itself system stable. The converse of this proposition, however, is not true. Suppose in particular that 5= {1,2,3} and that rx = R/2>r2>r3.
3.1 Some immediate consequences of our assumptions
83
Remark 3.5 tells us that the system is system and resource stable. However, subsystem ([2,3 j ; (r2, r3)) is not stable since 2 is predominant in it. Our next remark, which follows directly from the preceding remarks, moves us closer to a condition that is both necessary and sufficient for system stability: Remark 3.6. If rt Tj and rt + rj > R/2, then one or more of the remaining countries should coalesce withy to defend j ; otherwise / will dominate all countries. On the one hand, since /*;?/2, / cannot defeat S - { / } . On the other hand, if / seeks to form a coalition to defeat some other set of countries, then, from Remark 3.2, no country will join / if this permits / to secure more resources than R/2. To a considerable extent, Remark 3.6 captures much of the intuition about the implications of the balance of power, the intuition summarized by Castlereagh's reference to the balance as "the maintenance of such a just equilibrium between the members of the family of nations as should prevent any of them becoming sufficiently strong to impose its will upon the rest" (quoted in Claude 1962, pp. 13-14). Remark 3.6 asserts that if no country controls more than half the resources and (as an implicit assumption) if the resources of the countries are not growing at differential rates, then no country will be permitted to become a hegemon. Thus, we must attribute the occasional historical emergence of a hegemony to specific violations of our assumptions: to the fact that not all growth rates are equal, and to decision makers who suffer from a human failing we do not accommodate - an inability to perfectly foresee the consequences of their actions (or inactions). Because we ultimately want to learn how system stability is assured by our assumptions and how it can be undermined in reality, an illustration of the preceding remarks is useful. Suppose that, in a three-country system, resources are distributed (140,100,60), and suppose that country 1 attacks 2. Although l's resources are greater than 2's, country 3 knows that if it does nothing then: l's attack will be successful, 1 will absorb all of 2's resources, 1 will become dominant, 3 will be the next victim, and the outcome ({l};300) will prevail. Thus, in accordance with Remark 3.2, country 3 must join with 2 to defend against l's attack, regardless of what difference might otherwise divide countries 2 and 3. Churchill has long ago told us that in the power-politics game of survival, a coalition with
84
3 System stability and the balance of power
the devil may indeed be an acceptable alternative; herein lies the motive of the grand coalition against Napoleon (detailed by Gulick 1955), as well as against Hitler. Alternatively, suppose that 1 and 2 coalesce to attack 3 and agree to the resource distribution (150,150,0). Notice that in this agreement 1 receives only 10 units of additional resources, which, by Remark 3.6, is the most it can anticipate under any scenario in which 2 and 3 respond in ways that are appropriate to their interests. Country 3, however, can guarantee this outcome for 1 by simply transferring 10 units to 1. Country 1, by Assumption A6, prefers attaining the ten additional units in that way rather than through conflict, after which no one will have an incentive to coalesce with 1 (Remark 3.4), nor will 2 attack 3 (Remark 3.3). At this point in our example we might try to model how 2, in anticipation of this transfer by 3 that forestalls 2 achieving 150, responds with, say, a better offer to 3 - an attack, say, on 1 by 2 and 3. Notice then the emergence of a circular logic, in which one country's proposal is countered by some new proposal, which is countered by yet another proposal, and so on. To judge whether such a process can ever settle down to some definitive outcome requires an appropriate solution hypothesis to the cooperative game described by our assumptions, much like the theorizing about cooperative solution concepts in characteristic function form games. We shall shortly provide such a hypothesis (see Assumption A10), whereby a country's sovereignty is secured only if, for every threat against its existence, it possesses an "appropriate" counterthreat or if it can initiate some transfer of resources that moves one country to control half the resources, in which case, by Remark 3.5, system stability is assured. This discussion, though, demonstrates the importance of another assumption, A6, to our analysis. Notice that what allows 3 to formulate a useful counterthreat to a coalition between 1 and 2 is 3's willingness to cede ten units of resources to 1, and, by Assumption A6, l's preference for receiving those resources "freely" rather than by force. Without this assumption - without there being some cost to conflict, however slight the best that 3 can do is render 1 indifferent between the transfer and an attack, in which case it is unclear what 1 will choose. Thus, in applying our model to real data, ascertaining whether Assumption A6 is satisfied warrants special attention. As we note earlier, for example, decision makers may not consider conflicts costly, especially if such conflict serves to strengthen that decision maker's domestic position. Hence, and only logically, we see that whatever system stability we deduce from our model requires there not being a player in the game who positively prefers conflict to peace when the same international outcome can be guaranteed by either. This is, however, not necessarily a serious impediment for the study of many situations arising in international relations. Indeed, we believe
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
85
it is precisely such a strategic consideration as that outlined in our discussion of the three hypothetical countries before that contributed to the general absence of armed conflict among the great powers over colonial possessions in the last quarter of the nineteenth century. It is not without good reason that scholars have characterized this period as the golden age of balance-of-power politics. 3.2
Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
Our model thus far sets the stage for threats, bargaining, and coalition formation among countries, and identifies some sufficient conditions for system stability; but it does not tell us what outcomes prevail from this complex process. The specific possibility that we have not yet excluded is that ultimately two countries coalesce to subjugate all others, dividing resources equally so that a stable bipolar world emerges. That is, although the preceding remarks tell us that no country can secure more than half the resources in the system to become predominant, those remarks do not exclude the hypothesis that a succession of majority coalitions form to eventually whittle down the list of countries until only two prevail. This hypothesis is, of course, the one which Riker (1962) offers, and it is the one implicit in those balance-of-power discussions that posit two-country systems as especially stable. We have two alternative analytic approaches to studying this issue. First, we can try to model the bargaining process directly, carefully mapping out the feasible sequences of moves by the decision makers in S, and solving the resulting game description for equilibria. Unfortunately, pursuing this possibility with an analytically tractable yet general model eludes us. The alternative approach is to specify, in the form of a solution hypothesis that tries to accommodate the sequential character of international relations, the properties that predicted outcomes might reasonably be expected to satisfy. Because we do not map out the game's full form, this hypothesis has an ad hoc flavor to it (although not necessarily more ad hoc than any specific model of bargaining among national leaders). Yet, with it we can more easily derive general hypotheses. This second approach is the one we take here, and to proceed we require some additional notation and definitions: W=the set of winning coalitions, coalitions that control more than half of the resources in the system, W= {C^S\r(C)>R/2 and rt
86
3 System stability and the balance of power E = the set of essential countries in 5; the set of countries that are individually a member of at least one minimum winning coalition,
E= UceW*C. C = (C 1 ,C 2 ,...,C / ), a coalition structure that partitions the members of S into / exhaustive and disjoint coalitions (as a linguistic convenience, we refer to S as the "coalition of the whole," {1,2, (r, C) = a proposal consisting of a distribution of resources and a particular coalition structure. Perhaps no part of this notation is more important than the concept of an essential country. Typologies of states are implicit in most accounts of international affairs: great powers, satellite states, hegemonic powers, status quo powers, states within a sphere of influence, and so on. The preceding notation offers another but exceedingly important distinction: states that are members of at least one minimal winning coalition and, hence, critical to that coalition; and states that are not members of any such coalition. In the lexicon of game theory, then, essential countries have a power index greater than zero - they can pivot at least once so as to convert a losing coalition to a winning one - whereas inessential countries have indexes of zero - they can never individually convert a losing coalition to a winning one.4 Next, to analyze the process whereby coalitions form, we must define three new concepts: threats, counterthreats, and viable counterthreats. Before proceeding, though, we should note that the definitions and the conditions for system stability that we are about to offer parallel the development of the bargaining set in cooperative game theory. Briefly, bargaining set theory asks whether a particular distribution of payoffs to the various players in a game, in conjunction with a specific coalition structure, is a reasonable prediction. It is deemed reasonable if every person 4
The power index [or, more appropriately, the Shapley-Shubik (1954) power index] measures the probability that an individual player will, by joining, convert a losing coalition into a winning one if all possible sequences of coalition construction are equiprobable. For example, if 5 = {1,2,3] then there are six possible sequences leading to the coalition of the whole: (1,2,3), (3,1,2), (1,3,2), (2,1,3), (2,3,1), and (3,2,1). If the resources of all three countries are equal, then 2 is the pivotal player in two of these sequences: (1,2,3) and (3,2,1) - that is, 2 is pivotal when it joins 1 or 3 - and 2's power index is 2/6 = 1/3. The important feature of the power index, however, is that its value need not be proportional to a player's weight. For instance, in any set of weights in a three-person situation in which no player controls half or more of the resources, every player's "power" equals one-third. Similarly, for a six-player situation with weights (27,27,24,18,2,2), the corresponding power indexes are 1/3, 1/3, 1/3, 0, 0, and 0, respectively. Application of the power index to politics is widespread, but a good introduction to the literature is provided in Brams (1975).
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
87
has a counter to every threat against what he or she receives in the prediction - if everyone can "defend" his or her payoff. Although there are several theoretical variants of this set that place different limits on who can make threats and who must counter them, the bargaining set is the collection of all such reasonable predictions.5 For our purposes, however, we must modify this view. Because we are concerned here with the notion of system stability and the ability of countries to defend their sovereignty, which requires only that each country be assured of some positive amount of resources, we are less interested in the ability of countries to defend a specific resource distribution. Rather, we are interested in the ability of countries to ensure against elimination. Thus, we modify the definitions of threat and counterthreat to ask whether, given an initial distribution of resources, each country can ensure against having its resources set equal to zero. With respect now to the notion of a threat, the reader should understand that our use of the word "threat" does not mean that negotiations, the process whereby alliances are formed, and the actions leading to one country increasing its resources at the expense of another necessarily presuppose explicit hostile action. Threats can be implicit and unstated, as when one country recognizes the consequences of potential alliances in the form of trade and cultural exchange agreements. A threat against the Soviets may be merely an agreement between, say, Syria and the United States to "normalize" diplomatic relations, whereas decision makers in the United States perceive the negotiation of fishing rights in the South Pacific as a Soviet threat. Similarly, the Anglo-French entente of 1904 5
To see better how the bargaining set relates to our analysis, we offer here a definition in abbreviated form. Suppose we are asking whether the coalition structure and distribution of resources (r,C) = ((0.5,0.5,0), ({1,2], (3))) in a simple divide-the-dollar game can prevail. Bargaining set theory seeks to answer this question by first ascertaining the objections that individual players have against their coalition partners. In our example, the only relevant coalition is (1,2), and suppose that player 2 demands more. In particular, suppose 2 threatens 1 with the objection ((0,0.7,0.3), ({2,3], {1])). Thus, 2 proposes to join instead with 3, take seventy cents for himself, and give 3 the remaining thirty cents. This certainly improves the welfare of 2 and 3, and thus 1 might be tempted to accede to 2's threat. However, 1 has a counterthreat: he can merely propose ((0.5,0,0.5), ((1,3], {2})). This counter allows 1 to "defend" what he is getting in the original proposal with 2 while simultaneously bettering 2's offer to 3. Seeing this consequence, 2 relents and withdraws his threat. However, suppose we begin with ((0.7,0.3,0), ({1,2}, {3))) instead. If 2 objects with ((0,0.5,0.5), ({2,3), [1])), player 1 has no counter that continues to award him 0.7 while simultaneously giving 3 anything as good as 2's offer. Thus, because there is an objection (a threat) to which there is no counter, a proposal to form the coalition {1,2) and to disproportionately reward 1 is excluded as a prediction. Indeed, in this example, the only proposals we predict are those that divide the dollar evenly between two players. For further formal discussion of the bargaining set and its several variants, see Aumann and Maschler (1964), Owen (1982), and Ordeshook (1986).
88
3 System stability and the balance of power
merely concerned colonial disputes and nowhere mentioned Europe, "Yet Europe was inevitably and profoundly affected, and beyond a doubt this was in the back of the minds of the experienced diplomatists who negotiated the agreement" (Schmitt 1934, p. 61). The definition of a threat that follows, then, seeks not only to make this idea mathematically precise, but also to render it general. More specifically, a threat is a "proposal" by one or more countries to reduce to zero the resources of one or more other countries it outweighs. This should not be interpreted to mean, however, that we suppose that international discourse and the jockeying for advantage characterizing international affairs consists solely of such "total-war" maneuvers. Our concern here, though, is with the ability of countries or regimes to ensure their existence, and to study this problem we mustfirstassume that threats take an extreme form. Later, in Chapter 4, we explore the more limited forms of negotiation and instability that, although perhaps more commonly descriptive of international politics, must occur within the constraints set by the ability of countries to secure their sovereignty. Thus, presently a threat, implicitly understood or explicitly made, is the ultimate aggressive action in that it is in effect a proposal to eliminate the threatened countries from the system or, depending on our interpretation of the circumstance rt = 0, to exclude a country as a relevant power in the system. Formally, we define such a threat as follows: Threat, (r', C ) is a threat by Cj against Q with respect to (5; r), the current status quo, if i. Cj,C'keC\ both coalition Cj and coalition Ck must be disjoint elements of some coalition structure C ; ii. r(Cj) > r(C'k), the resources of the members of coalition Cj are greater than those of the members of coalition Cjc; iii. rj = 0 for all / e C'k, the resource allocation for all countries in coalition Ck will be zero if the threat is not countered; iv. r'j > rj for all j e Cj, the resource allocation for each country in coalition Cj will be greater if the threat is carried out. We say that (r',C) is a threat against / in particular if / is a member of the threatened set of countries, Ck. Surveying this definition, condition (i) requires that Cj and Ck both be disjoint coalitions in the coalition structure C . This is only reasonable, of course, since if i attacks j9 we can hardly say that / and j have coalesced to coordinate their strategies. Admittedly, though, this condition ignores the sort of complexity that characterizes the role of different states in many conflicts, as illustrated by the United States' role in mediating between the disputes of its allies or those it seeks as allies (e.g., Britain versus Argentina, Israel versus Egypt).
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
89
Condition (ii) is borrowed from the presumption that countries will attack others only if they anticipate the possibility of victory, hence the requirement that the resources of Cj exceed the resources of C'k. Condition (iii) requires that a threat is a proposal to eliminate attacked countries. Generally, of course, threats are aimed merely at securing some portion of a country's resources, but as we have just noted, this extreme form of a threat is part and parcel of our current focus on system stability (as against resource stability, in which threats can have more limited aims). Finally, condition (iv) states that the members of Cj will coalesce to attack others only if, individually, each anticipates some immediate gain in terms of increased resources from such an act. The threat, in other words, must be profitable for all participating countries. Clearly, only near-predominant or predominant countries - countries controlling half or more of the resources in a system - are immune to threats. Thus, system stability prevails only if all countries also possess counterthreats - threats against one or more of those who are making the original threat or a proposal that induces some of those countries into joining a new coalition. This view, then, merely reiterates the previously cited observation of Waltz (1979, p. 102) that all states must at all times be prepared to use force, if only to counter the ambitions of others. Of course, just as threats need not be explicit hostile acts, counterthreats can similarly exist merely in the minds of decision makers: Counterthreat. (r",C") is a counterthreat to (r',C) by the collection of countries K^ CfkDC^ if i. either Cj g C£ or Cj DCj^^Q, where C^ and C"h are both elements of the coalition structure C"; ii. (r", C") is a threat to C"h by C£; iii. r'( > r\ for all i in C£, and r'( > rt for all / in K if C"h * 0. Thus, a counterthreat by the collection K is, according to conditions (i) and (ii), a proposal in which K is in both Cjc (the coalition which is being attacked) and C^ (the coalition that is formulating the counter), as well as a proposal that either threatens all the members of Cj (the originally threatening coalition) or coopts one or more members of Cj. In addition, condition (iii) requires that all countries in the countercoalition C^ prefer the counter to the original threat. Notice now that condition (iii) is the feature of counterthreats that differs from the notion of a counter offered in bargaining set theory. Because bargaining set theory asks whether a particular distribution is "stable," those making the counter must prefer it to the original proposal. Here, though, we allow two types of counters. First, one or more countries can transfer resources directly to another so as to render it near-predominant
90
3 System stability and the balance of power
(in which case C# is empty). Such a counter reduces the threatened players' resources below what they have in r; if successful, such a ploy, in accord with Remarks 3.3 to 3.6, "freezes" the system and thereby secures their sovereignty. We justify this modification of the original idea offered by Aumann and Maschler (1964) because we are merely interested in whether countries can counter to ensure their existence. The second type of counter allows one or more of the threatened countries to formulate an alternative threat directed at members of the originally threatening coalition. However, because the new threat does not freeze the system, these members must be concerned that their resources will be whittled away in repeated action; so, in this instance, we require that members of the new threat who were targets of the old threat defend, as in the bargaining set, their original payoffs. Counterthreats are available to nearly all players for the game we are presently considering. Yet, for a smaller country, say /, counters may require the assistance of others and we must be certain that these other countries have some incentive to join / - that they have some incentive, in Quester's words cited earlier, "to ensure that... a loser was not eliminated from the system and absorbed..." (1977, p. 64). Thus, we require an additional refinement, which we call a viable counterthreat.6 Viable Counterthreat. The counterthreat (r", C") is viable for / in K if there is no subset Co of C^ that excludes / (i.e., no Co <=; C^ - {/}) such that Co has a threat (r0, Co) against C"h or C£+ {/}, with roj preferred to rj for all jeCoeCo. Hence, a counterthreat is viable for a threatened member of C'k if /'s coalition partners in the counter have some incentive to coalesce with /, in the sense that whenever they exclude / (to form C^ —{/}, or some subset if they also exclude others in addition to /) they cannot formulate a counterthreat that they all prefer to the counter they can form by including / in their coalition. The notion of a viable counterthreat, then, merely formalizes the notion of self-help that Waltz (1979) asserts is an essential 6
We noted earlier the similarity of our analysis of threats and counters to Aumann and Maschler's bargaining set. Correspondingly, the notion of a viable counter is similar to their concept of a coalitionally rational payoff configuration - a configuration in which no subset of any coalition has an incentive to split off from the coalition of which it is currently a member and "go its own way." We cannot use exact restatements of their definition, however, because we do not assume the prior existence of any coalition structure, except for the structure ({1,2,...,«}). We adopt this convention because we want to maintain the view that exclusionary coalitions form here (if they form at all) only to make threats and to defend against threats. Also, because we are more interested in a country's ability to ensure its survival as against its ability to protect a specific resource level, we impose condition (iii) in the definition of the counter rather than requiring that r" > rj.
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
91
component of stability in international politics, and formally incorporates the notion of collective security as a central component of our analysis. We emphasize that our introduction of the notions of threat and counterthreat admits of an important dynamic in balance-of-power systems. As will become clear from our application of the model to the case of the European great powers, 1871-1914, in Chapters 7 and 8, it is not always the formal existence of alliances that drives the balance of power or maintains system stability, but the potential alliances embodied in threats and counterthreats. For example, from 1873 to 1892, the actual alliances observable within the system were: Austria-Hungary, Germany, and Russia (1873-87); Austria-Hungary and Germany (1879-1918); Austria-Hungary, Italy, and Germany (1882-1914); and Germany and Russia (1887-90). However, the real balancing dynamic from the early 1870s onward was between the potential threat of a Russo-French alliance (which did not actually materialize until 1892-4) and the potential counterthreat of an Austro-Italo-German alliance (which was not actually consummated until 1882). Indeed, the potential threat of the Russo-French alliance did not become actual until Russia was left with no better option than the alliance with France. The particular hypothesis we offer now about the properties of outcomes to our game is the following: A10. Country / in S will not be eliminated if and only if it possesses a viable counterthreat to every threat. Implicit in this assumption, of course, is the supposition that if / is vulnerable - if there exists some threat it cannot counter - then that fact will be known to all other participants whether or not the threat is explicitly made, and they will take advantage of the situation to eliminate i.1 Thus, our next remark follows immediately from Assumption A10: Remark 3.7. (5; r) is system stable if and only if, for all i in S and for every threat against /, / has a viable counterthreat. The coalition Cj might pose a threat to C'k because it outweighs C'k, so threatened countries must devise viable counterthreats in order to survive. The definition of a counterthreat is weak and excludes few countries from 7
By basing our formulation of balance of power on the notion of threats and counterthreats, it might seem that our analysis conflicts with Walt (1987), who argues for a distinction between a balance of power and a balance of threat. Walt, however, is primarily interested in explaining observed alliances and thus, consistent with our assumptions, he asserts that alliances will necessarily be responses to perceived or actual threats. Thus, his analysis is compatible with ours. Because we are concerned with the general issue of survival, we do not want to place any ad hoc constraints on potential threats, and thus we assume that survival is ensured if and only if all threats can be effectively countered.
92
3 System stability and the balance of power
having one in any specific contingency. Most of the work is done by the notion of a viable counter. Briefly, a counter is viable for / in K if /'s partners in the counter have some incentive to coalesce with /, if C^ — {/} cannot also threaten CjJ (or C# joined by /) so that they prefer this counterthreat to the counter that includes /.8 8
We prefer deducing A10 and its primary implication (Theorem 3.2) from more primitive assumptions, since we can often rationalize cooperative predictions as noncooperative equilibria (Roth 1985, Binmore and Dasgupta 1987, Harsanyi and Selten 1988). To see how we can do this in the present context, let nature choose country / to make a threat (failing to threaten or the refusal of /'s partners to unanimously approve the threat leads to the selection of another player). If /'s threat of r' by C against C is approved by C— {/], nature chooses a y e C to counter. If the counter, (r", C"), is not unanimously accepted by the new proposed coalition, nature chooses another member of C , and so on until all members of C have the chance to counter. If no counter is approved, the threat is implemented; if a counter is a mutually agreed-to transfer, the transfer is implemented; if an approved counter involves involuntary transfers, it becomes the new threat, etc. Nodes in which a player receives R/2 resources are terminal. But because some branches repeat earlier nodes, we can have infinite play, and the method of solution is to posit continuation values, v(Tr>), for the subgames beginning with each threat and to assume "stationary strategies" that posit the same action whenever a node is repeated, where strategies and continuation values are simultaneously consistent. To illustrate the analysis of this game if all players are essential and can buy stability, let r = (120,100,80), so no sequence of decisions can yield less than 70 to 1 and 2 and 50 to 3 since each can avoid lower payoffs by buying stability. Simplifying the discussion, consider only the threats (150,150,0), (0,150,150), and (150,0,150), and the transfer outcomes (150,70,80), (150,100,50), and (70,150,80). Letting t;(r (150 , 0 , iso)) = (150,70,80), v(T{0> 150,150)) = (70,150,80), and v(T{i50,150,0)) = ^(r(i5o,0,150))/2 + t;(F (0)150) 150))/2 = (110,110,80), suppose 1 threatens (150,0,150) and let 3 accept. If 2 counters with (0,150, 150) then 3 rejects, because the original threat is worth more to 3 than v(F(o, 150, iso))- Similarly, 1 rejects a counter of (150,150,0); so 2 must transfer to 1, which is consistent with f(r(i5o,o,i5O))- On the other hand, if 1 or 2 threatens (150,150,0) then 3 can counter with (150,0,150) or (0,150,150). Both counters are certain to be accepted, but since 3 is indifferent between them, let 3 choose each with equal probability, which is consistent with the value f(F(i5o, i5o,o)) w e previously posited. Notice now that if we posit an equilibrium in which no country participates in an initial threat if it does not gain from doing so, then no threats are made, whereas if we suppose that countries participate in initial threats if they do not lose, then either 1 transfers to 2 or 2 transfers to 1. In either case, system stability prevails. To see the general structure of this example, notice that with the presumed continuation values for (150,0,150) and (0,150,150), neither threat is a counter to the other, but one or the other serves as a counter to any other threat if we posit continuation values similar to the one we choose for (150,150,0). This construction, in turn, implies that the presumed continuation values are consistent with subgame perfect strategies. Hence, although our game is noncooperative, these continuation values make {(150,150,0), (0,150,150)] look like a core: neither distribution "dominates" the other in that neither is a counter to the other, all other threats are "dominated" by (150,0,150) or (0,150,150) since one or the other counters any other threat, and no other threat "dominates" (150,150,0) or (0,150,150). For four-country systems, if all countries are essential and can buy stability, as with r = (110,80,60,50), the analysis proceeds as in the three-country case except that the particular threats that have "corelike" stability are (150,85,65,0), (150,85,0,65), (150,0,75,75),
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
93
To illustrate A10 and Remark 3.7 in combination with earlier assumptions, consider again the three-country example with the resource distribution (140,100,60), and suppose that countries 1 and 2 propose to coalesce in order to attack 3. We noted earlier that 3 might try to oppose this threat by offering to transfer 10 units of resources to country 1, which yields a distribution both 1 and 3 strictly prefer to anything {1,2} might agree to. To see how this proposalfitsour definitions, notice that {1,3] can be interpreted as a coalition that threatens C#. Thus, condition (ii) in the definition of a counter is satisfied. Condition (i) is satisfied since C\ DC* = {l,2}n{l,3j = {l}, which is not empty, as is condition (iii), since 1 prefers securing 150 units of resources "peacefully" rather than aggressively (Assumption A6), and since 3 prefers any resource level in which it is not eliminated to one in which it is (Assumption A4). The counter is viable for 3, because player 1 cannot secure a better outcome than "150 units without aggression" (Assumption A6 and Remark 3.6). and (0,150,75,75), where y(r(i50,85,65,0)) = (150, 80,60,10), u(r(i5Of 85,o,65)) = (150,80, 20, 50), y(r(150, o, 75,75)) = (150, 40, 60, 50), and y(r(0,150,75,75)) = (40,150, 60, 50). So suppose 4 is inessential as with r = (110,90,70,30), and let 1, 2, or 3 threaten (120,100, 80,0). If 4 merely offers any two countries more than 10 units each, keeping part of r$ for itself, then even if its offer is accepted, 4 is merely postponing its day of reckoning and will eventually have its resources reduced to zero. So suppose instead that 4 counters with (150,150-e,0,e), which, if accepted, is countered by 3 with either (150,0,150,0) or (0,150,150,0). If the continuation values are as in the three-country case with zero payoffs for 4, then 2 must transfer to 1 or 1 to 2; and if 3 chooses each of its counters with equal probability then 1 and 2 prefer avoiding this lottery by rejecting 4's counter in favor of (120,100,80,0), in which case 4 is eliminated. Similarly, if 4 counters with (150,0, 150 — e, e) then 2 must transfer to 1; but then 3 is left with a payoff of 70, so 3 rejects 4's counter and again 4 is eliminated. In this way an inessential country cannot maintain its sovereignty. Concluding that this noncooperative model fully rationalizes our cooperative approach requires a general analysis, which follows our treatment of three-country systems. First, letting max[C] denote the largest member of C, we identify type-1 threats as those in which a winning coalition C threatens S— C, where S—C can render max[C] near-predominant. Second, we isolate a particular set 7"of such threats, where every country that might be the largest member of a winning coalition is represented by some threat in T, and where the members of Tall satisfy two properties: (1) for no two coalitions Cand C" represented by threats in T'\s it the case that max[C] and max[C"] = CflC"; (2) there does not exist a CoeWsuch that C o flC = max[Co] ^max[C]. Threats in Tare assigned a continuation value in which the largest member of the coalition becomes near-predominant and its partners maintain their current allocation; all other threats are assigned values in which no one becomes near-predominant and all but the largest coalition members are confronted with the possibility of a resource loss. In certain circumstances (as when resources are not uniformly distributed and no country can buy stability), we add the assumption that countries threaten to cede their resources to the largest country when confronted with elimination (because such threats preclude others from taking actions that lead to such possibilities), and we suppose that, ceterisparibus, threatened countries prefer to coalesce with themselves in formulating counterthreats. These values and such assumptions give Tits "corelike" stability, render those values consistent, and imply that a stationary equilibrium supports AlO's implications (Niou and Ordeshook 1989c).
94
3 System stability and the balance of power
This argument is not a formal proof, but it suggests why A10, together with the previous assumptions, implies the following result (which is a corollary of the central theorem, Theorem 3.2). Theorem 3.1. All three-country systems are system stable provided that rt < R/2 for / = 1,2, 3; and only those distributions in which rt = R/2 for some / are resource stable. Although we generally relegate the proofs of our results to appendices, we discuss the logic of this theorem here so as to illuminate the role of our assumptions. We begin with the observation that, in any three-country system in which 0 < rt < R/2 for all / in 5 (in which no country is predominant), for any pair of countries / and j in S it must be the case that r{ + rj exceeds or equals R/2 (otherwise, rk>R/2). Hence, rt>R/2 — rj. This inequality means, however, that /'s resources, rh necessarily exceed the amount of resources required to render j near-predominant, R/2 — rj, in which case (by Remark 3.5) the system becomes both system and resource stable. At the very worst, then, i can seek to counter any threat to its existence and freeze the system by transferring R/2 — rj of its resources to j . Such a counter is clearly viable since it thwarts the elimination of /, and since, by Remark 3.6, j knows that it can never hope to form a coalition that promises it more than R/2, and since, by Assumption A6, j prefers a voluntary transfer that secures R/2 to a coalition with k to eliminate / for the same end. Thus, the system is system stable. To show that the system is resource stable if and only if rt = R/2 for some country /, Remark 3.3 establishes that rt = R/2 is sufficient for resource stability. Necessity is established by observing that if rt < R/2 for all /, then for any / and j in S it must be the case that rz + rj > R/2, so that / and j together can threaten the third country and force it to cede resources. Despite the fact that this result deals with only the special three-country case, a number of substantively important conclusions follow from it. First, with regard to the relative stability of two- versus three-country systems, although the only two-country system that is system or resource stable is one in which both countries have identically equal resources, all three-country systems without a predominant country are system stable, even ones in which the distribution of resources is "inequitable " As long as decision makers maximize relative resources, and as long as our other assumptions are satisfied, instability is inevitable in two-country systems unless perfect equality of resources is maintained; but it is anything but inevitable in three-country systems. This does not mean that we should interpret Theorem 3.1 as implying that wars cannot occur in such systems, since we have shown that not all three-country systems are resource stable and since we have not specified the mechanisms nations use to effect a
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
95
transfer of resources. Yet, the key feature of a three-country system is that no nation will be eliminated. This conclusion differs markedly from Waltz's that "smaller systems are more stable" (1979, p. 136) and, specifically, that bipolar systems are more stable than multipolar ones (1979, pp. 170-6). However, Waltz's conclusions do not follow in any rigorous way from his assumptions. Although it may be true that "the costs of bargaining increase at an accelerating rate as the number of parties becomes larger" or that "the diversity of parties increases the difficulty of reaching agreements" (1979, pp. 1356), the opportunities for stabilizing counterproposals also increases as number and "diversity" increase. Indeed, if a system is truly bipolar, so that the resources of all other countries are irrelevant, then arguments about the costs of negotiation, diversity, and the like are irrelevant. All that is relevant is who can defeat whom and at what cost. In a three-country system, on the other hand, everyone can be defeated by some combination of resources, in which case either this mutual interdependence is recognized and system stability prevails, or someone errs. Whether error is more likely as the number of countries increase, we cannot say, but Waltz's conclusion about relative stability does not follow because he ignores or misconstrues the full consequences of his prior observations about the self-help nature of international systems. Theorem 3.1, moreover, disconfirms the supposition that equality of resources is required to achieve balance, and thus supports Morgenthau's (1959) belief that exact parity is not a necessary condition for peace {qua stability). However, excepting the circumstance in which some country's resources exceed R/2, it fails to support his corresponding supposition that rough equality is necessary. Theorem 3.1 also contradicts the supposition that ensuring (system) stability requires precise measurement of capabilities. Such a supposition is correct in two-country systems, but not in three-country systems. It is perhaps not surprising, then, that the literature seems to lead to an ambiguous conclusion about the relationship between power inequities and the frequency of war.9 In any event, this feature of three-country versus two-country systems suggests an issue that we elaborate on in Chapter 9, namely, that negotiations for disarmament are more likely to be successful when there are three powers rather than when there are only two. In bipolar systems, negotiators must be especially 9
Ferris (1973), Sabrosky (1975), and Siverson and Tennefoss (1984), for example, argue that equality correlates with peace; Garnham (1976) finds the opposite; Singer, Bremer, and Stuckey (1972) argue that the relationship depends on the characteristics of states; and Healey and Stein (1973), Karsten, Howell, and Allen (1984), Maoz (1982), and Wolf (1978) find no relationship whatsoever. Although our analysis has not yet taken rates of resource growth and geography into consideration, these studies taken as a whole can be interpreted as supporting the implication of Theorem 3.1: there is no relationship.
96
3 System stability and the balance of power
careful that agreements do not inadvertently give a slight advantage to one side or the other, whereas in three-country systems, the consequences of miscalculation and error are less severe - all three countries will remain necessarily essential. A further implication of Theorem 3.1 is that, although three-country systems may see shifting alliances as resources change, we need not witness meaningful permanent coalitions. If alliances are "commitments.. .which bind two or more states to concert their policies in time of crisis" (Singer and Small 1966, p. 5), we must reject the supposition that alliances are the sole measure of the operation of balance of power. Indeed, it is not merely coalitions that prevent wars, but also the threat of coalitions that performs this function. At the distribution (140,100,60), the coalition of 2 and 3 should never actually form to eliminate 1. If such a coalition intends to eliminate 1, 1 can forestall this possibility by relinquishing resources to 2. The threat of 1 and 2 coalescing does not yield a war of total absorption either, since 3 can cede 10 units to 1. Thus, with three countries, we do not predict merely that we should observe "minimal winning coalitions," but instead we should allow for the possibility that no explicit coalitions will be observed, and that the implicit threats and counterthreats of coalitions may be as important to the dynamics of the system as the explicit coalitions revealed to us in the form offormal treaties and agreements. This is not to say that we would not want to understand those treaties and agreements in the context of balance-of-power politics, but only that implicit as well as explicit possibilities should be considered. Consider now the presumption that Theorem 3.1 and its consequences are known to all decision makers, or at least that its logic is implicitly understood by them, in which case the leaders of nations who might otherwise seek to be predominant know that they cannot succeed and therefore that it is fruitless to try (at least with the instruments we have thus far allowed). We infer from these comments, then, that those who view the explicit formation and dissolution of alliances as an essential part of a balance-of-power system (Wright 1942, Claude 1962, Organski 1968) generally have something other than system stability in mind (or that they are merely failing to distinguish between system and resource stability). Insofar as system stability is concerned, the threat of alliances and not their actual formation is sufficient for a three-country system to be system stable. Finally, and despite the fact that it deals with a special case, perhaps the most profound implication of Theorem 3.1 is that it establishes the possibility of system stability without appeal to exogenous institutions or constraints, or to an analysis that posits balance as a goal. Balance in the form of system stability emerges wholly endogenously as the consequence of self-interest and a recognition of the interdependence that describes the
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
97
system. This theorem, then, is a counterexample not only to Riker's view of balance of power, but also to Utopian schemes that see world government (however established) as the sole guarantee of stability. Self-interest alone provides such a guarantee in anarchic three-country systems, and Utopian schemes are merely accessories. The importance of what we have just said is greatly diminished, of course, if we cannot generalize Theorem 3.1 to larger systems in the form of necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability. Before we proceed in this direction, however, we must consider a potentially confounding strategic possibility arising in systems with more than three countries. Specifically, because the possibility cannot arise in three-country systems, we have not ruled out a strategy whereby inessential countries are eliminated and their resources absorbed in such a way as to render a previously essential country inessential. In fact, though, if an inessential country is eliminated, the survivability of essential countries is not threatened in subsequent games, as indicated by the following result that simplifies considerably the strategic planning of countries contemplating the possibility of expropriating resources from someone else. Remark 3.8. If any or all members of S—E (the set of countries that are not essential) are eliminated then, regardless of how the resources of S—E are reallocated, all members of E remain essential. Suppose, as a worst case, that j receives no resources from the eliminated countries. Since j is essential before some or all of the inessential countries (those in the set S-E) are eliminated, there is by definition a minimum winning coalition C such that C— {j} is no longer winning. But C augmented by all inessential countries, the coalition CU(S-E), is also winning (although not minimal winning), and, since S—E is not essential, CU(S—E— {j}) is not minimal winning either.10 Therefore, even if C-[j] absorbs any or all of S-E's resources, j remains essential to C and therefore is essential in the new game.11 10
11
This assertion requires that, if 5—E is the set of all countries that cannot individually render a losing coalition winning, then S—ii combined into a single entity cannot do so either. To see that this is true, suppose the contrary, that C is losing but that C plus the members of S-E are winning. In this case, we should be able to delete each member of S—E one at a time from C plus S—E until what remains is losing, in which case that member is essential - a contradiction. Note, however, that this result is true only when the internal rate of resource growth for all essential countries in the system is held constant; as we shall see in Chapter 5, treating differential internal rates of resource growth as endogenous to the model makes the absorption of the resources of inessential countries very troublesome to essential countries.
98
3 System stability and the balance of power
Remark 3.8 has an important substantive implication that permits us to make some predictions about superpower relations. Namely, a country should be unconcerned about the attempts of other countries to absorb the resources of inessential countries unless, for reasons exogenous to the present analysis (e.g., differential rates of internal resource growth among the essential countries), such an absorption is part of a strategy by the absorbing country to become predominant. Perhaps we should not be surprised, then, to find the major Western powers agreeing to the absorption of a Latvia or an Estonia. The usual argument for explaining acquiesence to this absorption is that countries like Latvia and Estonia are within the "sphere of influence" of the Soviets or that they have a "historical attachment" to Russia. Yet, this leaves open the question of how spheres of influence are arrived at in specific cases and defined in general. Indeed, such spheres are artificial concepts and commonly are proved to be ephemeral in the face of dominant military capabilities. In the terms of our analysis, countries are allowed spheres of influence since the explicit addition of resources of entities within those spheres does not materially affect the stability of the international system. Similarly, although each superpower can make useful propaganda out of the other's military involvements in Vietnam and Afghanistan, neither truly perceives the outcomes there as threats to international stability. The United States, however, should take a far different view of a Soviet invasion of, say, the People's Republic of China, just as the Soviets might react to an American decision to occupy by force the oilfieldsof the Middle East. In such cases, it is precisely the changes in resources implied by such acquisitions that make them matters of considerable concern to the parties involved. Despite their substantive import, Theorem 3.1 and Remark 3.8 are nevertheless but preliminaries to the central result of this chapter, which provides the necessary and sufficient condition for system stability. Theorem 3.2. (S; r) is system stable if and only if all countries in 5 are essential (i.e., if and only if S = E). We relegate the formal proof of this result to an appendix, but the principles that underlie it are straightforward. Each country knows that everyone else will oppose it if it threatens to become predominant, and therefore that the best outcome it can secure is control of precisely half of the system's resources. The condition that S equals E merely guarantees that every country possesses, either individually or in combination with some other set of similarly vulnerable countries, enough resources to render someone near-predominant. Since every country prefers to become nearpredominant in this way, the recipient of such an offer has a clear incentive to accept it, which, in accordance with our earlier remarks, freezes the system. The formal proof of Theorem 3.2, then, merely ensures that
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
99
the result is consistent with our assumptions and that all essential countries can meet every threat with a viable counterthreat. As long as we maintain the assumption that countries maximize "power" in the form of maximizing their proportion of resources in the system (subject to the constraint, of course, that their sovereignty is not threatened), it is straightforward to see, moreover, that this theorem does not depend on our assumption that wars are costless, where a costly war or threat means that resources for the loser as well as perhaps the winner are lost in the conflict [as expression (2.1) in Chapter 2 illustrates]. First, suppose that all countries can form viable counterthreats by transferring resources to the largest country that might threaten them so as to render that country near-predominant. The same must be true, of course, if wars are costly, since that cost is irrelevant to the transfer. Now suppose that all countries are essential, but that some cannot individually buy stability, and, in particular, suppose that the target C" of a threat made by C does not have enough resources to buy stability. Notice that we can suppose that C=S—C; even if C does not explicitly include all of S—C\ the members of S— C — C are implicitly parties to the threat since, with the destruction of any of the resources of C, their share will increase. And because every / in C" is essential, it must be the case that some Kri.n Finally, if C" is inessential, its "coalition partners" can always increase their proportion of resources by dropping C" from the counter - even, perhaps, adding C" to a counterthreat's target - in which case an inessential C" cannot form a viable counter. Returning to the assumption that wars are costless, to illustrate the logic of Theorem 3.2 further, especially the operation of threats and counters, we consider the following five-country examples:13 12
13
Suppose, for example, that r = (100, 80,60,40,20) and suppose that (1,2) threatens 4, in which case 3 and 5 also gain in proportion from any destroyed resources on the part of 1, 2, and 4. But 4 can counter with, say, {2, 3,4] threatening (1, 5 j . Since the proportion that {2, 3,4] controls after 1 and 5's resources are reduced to zero also equals 100 percent, and since 4's partners are fewer in number than the number of members of the original threat, those partners can be assured of gaining more, proportionately, in the counter than in the threat. An interesting sidelight to this theorem is its relationship to the Shapley-Shubik power index (1954). Originally designed to measure a person's "power" in formal voting systems (see footnote 5), notice that a country is essential if and only if, after interpreting the r/'s as voting weights, the power index is nonzero. Hence, we can interpret our analysis as showing that only those countries with positive power indexes can survive.
100
3 System stability and the balance of power
Example 3.1. Let r = (120, 50, 50,40,40), which corresponds to Case 1 in the theorem's proof. Although there are a variety of potential threats against different countries, even the smallest (4 or 5) has enough resources to "buy" stability when threatened. At the very worst, 5 can form a viable counterthreat by offering to transfer 30 units to 1. In this event, 5's coalition partner can do no better than have its total resources increased to 150, and the distribution (150,50,50,40,10) serves as the basis for a viable counter. Example 3.2. Let r = (100, 80,50,35,35), in which case countries 4 and 5 cannot individually form viable counters by "buying off" the largest player; hence, this illustrates the second case in the proof. If 1 and 2 threaten 5, notice that the maximum gain to C= [1,2} is 35, so country 2 can at best realize the resource level 115. But if 5 coalesces with 2 to attack 1, 2 can be made strictly better off (even securing 150 units of resources), but 2 cannot do better by acting alone. It is interesting to note that, except for the number of countries, the strategic considerations in this example are identical to those that prevailed in Europe between 1871 and 1914. At the time of the second Near Eastern Crisis in 1885, for example, resources were distributed on a percentage basis approximately (5,35,14,21,6,19) across Austria-Hungary, Great Britain, France, Germany, Italy, and Russia, respectively (see our discussion of resources in Chapter 7). To see that all countries are essential, if we ignore the geographical imperatives of the period, notice that although Austria-Hungary, Italy or France did not possess sufficient resources to render Britain near-predominant, any two of them together could do so in the form of a minimum winning coalition. Hence, all countries are essential. Example 3.3. Let r = (110,80,50,50,10), in which case country 5 cannot "buy off" any other country, nor is it essential to any coalition for the implementation of a threat. For instance, the coalition {2,3,4} can attack 5, and although 5 might counter with, say, {2,5} threatening 4, 2 does not require 5 to make such a threat. Hence, the counter is not viable. Example 3.4. Let r = (60,60,60,30,30), and suppose that {1,2, 3} threatens 4 and 5. Notice that, although countries 4 and 5 are essential, and although they have enough resources to ensure their sovereignty by setting one country's resources equal to half the total, such a move reduces their resource holding to zero. Thus, it appears that countries 4 and 5 can, paradoxically, secure
3.2 Necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability
101
survival only by eliminating themselves. However, 4 and 5 can coalesce with 2 and 3 so that the coalition's gain is also 60. Since 4 and 5, by the definition of a counterthreat, are not required to gain more than what they have in the original distribution, 2 and 3 can divide the gain in such a way that they are better off in the counter than in the threat. These examples reveal an important component of balance-of-power politics that is not always fully appreciated. In Examples 3.1, 3.2, and 3.4, in particular, the country in question secures its existence by forming a viable counterthreat that transfers resources to someone else so as to render the target of the transfer near-predominant (thereby freezing the system in accordance with Remark 3.3). Thus, although students of international affairs such as Morgenthau and Waltz, as we noted earlier, make us sensitive to the mutual-security aspects of balance-of-power politics, we see here that the threat of counteralliances is only part of the process whereby system stability is assured - the other part being the ability to transfer resources (territory, spheres of influence, money, etc.).14 Theorem 3.2 and its proof confirm the intuition expressed by Gilpin that "Territorial, political, and economic adjustments among states in response to conflicting interests and shifting power relationships function to relieve pressure on the system, thereby preserving it intact" (1981, p. 46). Although it is far from clear that Gilpin has in mind the resource transfers we formalize as part of viable counterthreats, the logic of Theorem 3.2 quite directly shows how the possibility of such adjustments secures system stability. It is interesting to speculate, then, why theorists pay such modest heed to this feature of counterthreats as a mechanism for ensuring balance (Claude 1962 and Organski 1968). However, aside from observing that resource transfers are a feature of international politics (witness Franco-British and Russo-British negotiations prior to the formation of the Entente Cordiale as well as the resolutions of the Near Eastern Crises of 1875-7 and 1885-8) and aside from noting the subtlety possible in a transfer (granting of trade concessions, replacing a hostile minister with one who is likely to be subservient to the threatening power), such speculation is premature. Just as our theory does not require the actual implementation of a threat and counter, our theory does not suppose that such transfers invariably occur so as to secure system stability. Rather, it is the potential for such transfers that renders a system system stable. Predicting 14
Wagner (1986) argues that such transfers are not essential to system stability and that it is unclear how such transfers are enforced, although he implicitly admits such transfers by allowing countries to absorb the resources of others. As we note earlier, the issue of enforcement is a legitimate concern, but what is unclear at this point is whether transfers are more difficult to enforce than other types of agreements.
102
3 System stability and the balance of power
the transfers that we might actually observe requires the analysis we offer in the next chapter on resource stability. 3.3
System stability and war
If there is a serious ambiguity in our analysis, it is the one between reallocations that might occur through the choice of some aggressive act (a2) and reallocations that, although requiring coercion, occur through negotiation (a3). Assumption A6 presumes the feasibility of making this distinction, but such assumptions must eventually give way to ones in which countries are presented with a greater diversity of alternative actions, where each one imposes different costs on decision makers. Although the present theoretical structure gives us a clear sense of empirical possibilities, it is probably impossible to classify acts into two such abstract categories. Of course, there is always a gap between abstract concepts and their empirical operationalization. What we are suggesting here, then, is that because the primary outcomes that concern us - peace and war - manifest themselves in varying degrees, it would ultimately be useful to extend our analysis so that it better incorporates this variety. It should also be apparent that the failure of the analysis in this chapter to consider several factors limits its ability to discuss alternative sources of conflict. Consider the following remark, which merely lays out formally our earlier discussion of subsystem stability: Remark 3.9. If S' is a subset of S and if r' is the distribution of resources within S', then even if (5;r) is system stable, (S";r') may or may not be system stable. For example, (S; r) = ({1,2,3,4, 5,6], (100, 80, 30, 30, 30, 30)) is a systemstable system, but (S';r') = ({2, 3,4), (80,30,30)) is not. Thus, if - for reasons presently exogenous to the analysis, such as geography - countries 1,5, and 6 will not attack those in S\ then we might anticipate a war in which 2 attacks and absorbs 3 and 4. Hence, the formal results of this analysis do not accommodate "local conflicts" such as ones between Iran and Iraq or between Great Britain and Argentina. To summarize, then, the particular import of Theorem 3.2 is that it reaffirms much of what we said about Theorem 3.1. In particular, we find that there is no magic number for achieving a balance of power, nor is there any magic formula relating the distribution of resources to system stability. Nevertheless, because in a bipolar (two-country) system, system stability requires a precise equality of resources, and because system stability in multicountry systems exists under a broad range of resource distributions, we can only conclude that such stability is much more likely
3.3 System stability and war
103
to be retained in multipolar systems. Thus, Waltz (1979) is probably correct to argue that miscalculation presents special dangers in bipolar systems. We do not concur, however, with his assertion that "systems of three [countries] have distinctive and unfortunate characteristics," as compared to multipolar systems because "two of the powers can easily gang up on the third" (p. 163). Theorems 3.1 and 3.2 offer no reason for supposing that three is less secure than four, or that five is "the lowest number that promises stability." In addition to the empirical counterexample that, for 200 years, seven conflictual states co-existed in ancient China (the Warring States Period, 453-221 B.C.), we find no theoretical basis for Waltz's assertions. If the simple counting of powers cannot explain the likelihood of war, then we should ask: What are the sources of conflict and war in our analysis? Despite the relatively broad circumstances for stability identified by Theorem 3.2, wars do occur, including wars between great powers that in no way can be conceptualized as inessential. The opponents of those who have attempted to secure hegemony - of the Habsburg realms under Charles V and Phillip II, France under Louis XIV and Napoleon, and Germany under the Kaiser and Hitler (Dehio 1962) - were clearly not inessential, as evidenced by the outcomes of the wars themselves (Wright 1942 and Dehio 1962). And if a hegemonic war is one that involves "a direct contest between the dominant power or powers in an international system" and in which "the fundamental issue at stake is the nature and governance of the system" and in which nations use "unlimited means" to secure their ends (Gilpin 1981, p. 199; see also Levy 1984), then Theorem 3.2 cannot provide an answer to our question. A partial answer is provided, however, by Blainey's (1973, pp. 111-12) observation that we possess not an axiom for peace but an axiom for national independence. And that in fact was the main virtue of a balance of power in the eyes of those who originally practiced it Gulick.. .was adamant that its clearest theorists and practitioners - the Metternichs and Castlereaghs - "all thought of war as an instrument to preserve or restore a balance of power." In essence, a balance of power was simply a formula designed to prevent the rise of a nation to world dominance. It merely masqueraded as a formula for peace. Although we would add that a balance is also a formula designed to prevent the elimination of essential countries in addition to the rise of a hegemon, the point of this argument is that because system-stable systems are not necessarily resource stable, we cannot preclude the possibility that resource instability implies armed conflict that stops short of the elimination of essential actors. We should not preclude the possibility, however, that conflict nevertheless occurs also because one or more of the assumptions of our model are
104
3 System stability and the balance of power
violated. Ignoring for the moment the issues of resource growth and decline and of geography, notice first that our model presupposes that all countries possess complete freedom to bargain and to threaten, and that counterthreats to transfer resources are believable. Clearly, then, we can hypothesize that in systems described by constant resources for all countries, system instability and the wars they occasion are caused by inflexibilities and constraints on bargaining. Inflexibility can arise from a great many sources, and this is perhaps the reason why scholars can so readily cite different reasons for a particular war or for all wars. Domestic politics provides perhaps the most evident constraint on a national leader's flexibility. Few if any such leaders, except those who are absolute dictators and who rule by military force, are afforded the luxury of being able to transfer resources to another country in the form, say, of territory. If particular allocations are regarded as infeasible, then Theorem 3.2 no longer applies, system stability may no longer hold, and even essential countries may be unable to invent the viable counterthreats that secure their existence. However, following the dictates of the literature as well as common sense, we postulate survival as a supreme goal, which suggests that inflexibilities that are allowed to threaten sovereignty must have profound sources and the inflexibilities themselves must be of an extreme sort. Simple disputes over, say, colonial possessions, tariffs, and the like should fall before the goal of survival. Thus, impediments to formulating viable counters to a threat may be a contributory factor to war, but wars to eliminate essential countries are likely to have a different source. As we suggest in Chapter 1, that source is most likely uncertainty and misperception. Even if domestic politics plays no role, resources cannot be readily measured and transferred. Hence, even reasonable negotiators can fail to agree on what specific transfers (such as the assignment of spheres of influence) will ensure their sovereignty and thus maintain balance. Naturally, the uncertainty and misperception that our assumptions exclude can play critical roles as well. The impact of uncertainty, in fact, can be profound, at least for the determination of final outcomes. Without it, essential countries can ensure, with certainty, that no country becomes predominant. Yet with uncertainty, the "luck of the draw" may yield such predominance. Also, essential countries can in our model ensure against the possibility that they in particular become inessential. Still, again, probabilistic events may dictate otherwise, regardless of what steps are taken by decision makers beforehand. Thus, even though uncertainty is precluded by our assumptions, breakdowns of system stability and outbreaks of war need not be taken always as refutations of the forces our analysis uncovers; such outbreaks can be the result of chance events. This, of
3.3 System stability and war
105
course, requires that in any empirical test or application of our analysis, we distinguish between those conflicts that arise because of chance events, those that arise because leaders have misjudged each other's capabilities, and those that arise because our model is simply in error. An additional source of difficulty, discussed in Chapter 2 but warranting reemphasis, concerns the enforcement of agreements. Throughout this analysis, we have assumed that countries need merely to share some mutual interest to render coordination toward the attainment of that interest feasible. Diplomats and foreign-policy analysts alike, however, know that the sticky details of an agreement - designed to assure that those who are party to it abide by its terms - often derail otherwise mutually beneficial outcomes. The perception that an agreement in one coalition is more readily enforced than an agreement in another can, of course, introduce important asymmetries. Particular threats or counters may be unbelievable owing to factors such as ideology and domestic politics, whereas other threats and counters may play a more significant role because factors we do not consider reenforce mutual self-interests. Finally, we should not ignore two major empirical violations of our initial assumptions as a likely cause of war: the absence of resource growth among countries and the failure to discount offensive capabilities for geography. As we attempt to make clear in Chapter 5, where we explicitly add the dimension of differential rates of growth among countries, and in Chapter 8, where we discuss the conflict-resolution implications of our model, much of the observed conflict between essential countries arises from differential rates of resource growth. Similarly, as we show in Chapter 6, where we add geographical considerations, and in Chapter 7 as well as 8, where we illustrate how geography shapes the strategic environment, wefindthat geography can place differential burdens on the resources required to render a country essential. At this point, we should not belabor particularistic sources of instability and conflict, since what we want to emphasize is that, although results such as Theorem 3.2 point the way to abstract principles and to the conclusion that the anarchic order of international relations does not necessarily yield instability and conflict, these results are not an end to theorizing. We ought not to interpret the analysis offered in this chapter as providing any definitive conclusion about whether the realist perspective necessitates the conclusion that balance (system stability) precludes war. Indeed, we have not yet considered a second type of stability, resource stability; to better understand the possible sources of conflict in international systems, as well as the necessity for distinguishing between system and resource stability, in the next chapter we shall focus on whatever reallocations are likely to arise when no country's existence or sovereignty is threatened.
106
3 System stability and the balance of power
3.4
A note on assumptions
We can debate any assumption ad infinitum without necessarily resolving whether it is reasonable or unreasonable; the most valuable means of assessing an assumption is by gaining an understanding of its critical function in the analysis. Aside from the model of bargaining (which we offer in this chapter in the form of A10), two assumptions introduced earlier are especially critical to this chapter's conclusions: Assumptions A6 and A7. First, Assumption A6 states that countries prefer to secure additional resources without conflict. Intended to model the costs of wars without introducing new parameters, this assumption plays a profound role in the specification of necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability. Indeed, without it or some equivalent assumption, only two-country systems are system stable. To see why this assertion is true, consider the threecountry system (120,100,80). In our analysis, country 3 protects its sovereignty by the threat that it can transfer 30 units to 1. Assumption A6, in turn, ensures that 1 prefers to accept this transfer over any forced feasible reallocation of resources. But without A6, a proposal by 1 and 2 to attack 3 so as to secure the distribution (150,150,0) cannot be countered by 3. At first glance, it might seem that we should add a stronger assumption to accommodate the costs of wars and, in particular, to accommodate the fact that conflicts destroy resources. Nevertheless, our assumption that wars are costless to the extent that they do not destroy resources does not affect our primary result about system stability (Theorem 3.2): if countries maximize proportion of resources (power), then S = E remains a necessary and sufficient condition for system stability. Thus, if potential combatants maximize proportion - if strategic planners in the United States and the Soviet Union view a conflict in which the United States retains a population of 25 million compared to 10 million for Russia as a "victory" for the United States - it is perhaps somewhat comforting to learn that balance-of-power politics, although not aiding inessential countries, will nevertheless ensure the sovereignty of essential ones. Although this result is consistent with Organski and Kugler's (1980) assertion that "nuclear weapons have not modified [the rules of international political processes], they have instead reinforced them" (p. 217), we might have conjectured that war costs would make system stability more pervasive by rendering otherwise inessential countries essential. This intuition, though, seems to have in mind decision makers who maximize the absolute level of resources rather than their proportion, or at least decision makers who perceive a tradeoff between "power" and absolute resource levels.15 15
Another way in which such costs can induce stability, of course, is if the technology of modern warfare (nuclear weapons and their delivery systems in particular) assures that
3.4 A note on assumptions
107
We suspect, then, that the issue of war costs as a deterrent to conflict arises whenever national leaders are implicitly assumed not to be concerned merely with proportion of resources, but with the absolute level of resources as well. To see this, suppose that (conditional on maintaining their sovereignty) countries maximize absolute level, and that absolute level and proportion are decoupled because threats, if implemented, destroy resources. If we otherwise maintain A6 and if all countries are not merely essential but can individually "buy" stability with a resource transfer to the largest threatening country, then the system remains system stable since, as before, all countries can freeze the system with such a transfer. What changes here, however, are the conditions under which stability can be bought. To see this, suppose war costs are described by expression (2.1) - suppose that the resources of C after implementing an uncountered threat against C" equal [r(C) + r(C')][l-ar{C')/r(C)] in which case ({1,2}; (200,100)) is system stable whenever a > 2/3, since any attack by 1 against 2 leaves 1 with fewer than 200 units of resources. This example, in fact, seems to correspond to the balance of power that existed between the United States and the Soviets. Despite the considerable resource advantage enjoyed by the United States and its allies over the Soviet bloc, the destructiveness of nuclear weapons allowed an otherwise unstable system to remain stable. However, before we infer from this example that war costs are stabilizing, notice that if (in a three-country system) r = (120,100,80) then country 3 cannot buy stability unless it cedes all of its resources to 1 - our analysis of the two-country system shows that 1 can hold up to 200 units of resources before it dominates all others. Indeed, some simple algebra establishes that country 3 is inessential in this instance - it cannot formulate a viable counterthreat against a threat by 1 and 2.16 We should not interpret this example to imply that war costs destabilize otherwise stable systems or that there is any simple monotonic relationship between war costs and system stability whenever national leaders maximize absolute resources. For example, in the system ({1,2, 3,4]; (90,90,90,30)), if a = 0 then country 4 is not essential; if a = 1/2 then 4 is essential; and if a — 2/3 then 4 is inessential once again.
16
any two coalitions are effectively of equal size - in which case, with a = r(C)/r(C')> expression (2.1) implies that any two antagonists destroy each other totally. In such a world, of course, any reasonable attribution of preferences to a world in which r = (0,0,0,...) is necessarily the consequence of any threat would imply that no coalition will ever threaten another. For additional discussion of war costs in the context of the present model, especially as the effect of those costs are mediated by alternative national goals, see Niou and Ordeshook (1989b). By using expression (2.1), the gain of (1,2) attacking 3 is positive, whereas the gains of counters by 3 (coalescing with either 1 or 2 to attack the remaining member of the system) are not positive. Thus, 3 has no viable counterthreat either in the form of a direct resource transfer to render one country near-predominant or in the form of an attacking counter.
108
3 System stability and the balance of power
The general implication of this discussion, then, is that the relationship between war costs and stability are mediated by goals. If leaders pursue power, defined in relative terms, then such costs are irrelevant to stability. On the other hand, if those leaders maximize absolute levels of resources, then war costs can either stabilize or destabilize systems - and the precise nature of the consequence of such costs depends on their magnitude (as well as on the functional relationship between those costs and the resources of potential combatants). The impact of war costs on the stability of international systems, then, may depend profoundly on domestic political matters that influence the weight given by national leaders to relative versus absolute resource levels. A concern with relative resources is relevant to decision makers who are concerned primarily with international issues and state sovereignty; a concern with absolute resources is perhaps more relevant to decision makers concerned about their domestic bases of support and with the survival of their regimes. Hence, the analysis in this chapter merely opens the door to a more comprehensive theoretical treatment of the relationship among stability, war costs, and the tradeoffs national leaders perceive between goals. Assumption A7 is no less important for our analysis, its critical feature being the supposition that any larger country or coalition of countries not a party to some conflict can secure resources from that conflict. Consider again the distribution (120,100,80), and consider country 3's reasoning as it contemplates a possible attack by 1 or 2. Everyone knows that in the event of such an attack, 3 could offer to transfer 30 units to 1 and 1 would be predisposed to accept the transfer. But moving the system to the distribution (150,100,50) does 3 little good if it is then attacked by 2. What keeps this attack from materializing, though, is Assumption A7: country 2 know that if it attacks 3 then 1 can profit from the conflict, securing the extra resources or proportion of resources required to become predominant. Thus, reasoning backwards, everyone knows that if 1 controls exactly half the resources then 2 cannot attack 3, in which case everyone also knows that a 30-unit transfer by 3 to 1 establishes system stability. Again, reality need not correspond to A7. This is most easily seen by noting that A7 can imply that third parties to a conflct can secure small gains from a conflict among other states. Clearly, geography and other impediments to effective military mobilization lead to violations of this presumption, and if third parties cannot anticipate gains that outweigh costs then regional conflicts precluding the emergence of system stability are possible. Thus, multicountry systems are system stable only if regional conflicts are "policed" in the international system by the threat that larger countries will take advantage of such conflict. If this threat is not present then the stability of subsystems must be analyzed independently.
3.4 A note on assumptions
109
Our last critical assumption is A10, which models the bargaining that occurs among countries insofar as that bargaining pertains to the ability of countries to survive. Readers familiar with game theory might wonder why we do not directly graft to our analysis the reasoning that defines any one of the several cooperative solution hypotheses offered by game theory. Indeed, applying the reasoning of the V-set or the bargaining set yields quite different predictions than the ones produced by A10. Consider the bargaining set, the motivation of which closely parallels our assumption, and consider the distribution (150,150,0), which we suppose is the result of a coalition of 1 and 2 against 3. Bargaining set theory asks whether this distribution is "stable" in the sense that it can endure once arrived at. To see that this distribution is in fact stable according to that theory's logic, suppose 1 objects with the proposal (150,100, 50), which is to say that 1 demands receiving 150 units through negotiation rather than through conflict. This is a legitimate objection since, by Assumption A6,1 prefers his payoff in (150,100,50) to his payoff in (150,150,0). Further, only objections of this form are possible, since objections in which 1 or 2 receives more than 150 units are implausible; everyone knows that no coalition partner would agree to such an arrangement. However, 2 can now counter with (0,150,150). Indeed, there is a counter objection to every objection, and (150,150,0) with the coalition structure ({1,2), {3}) is in the bargaining set. Conversely, the distribution that results whenever 3 implements a transfer so as to secure its existence, (150,100,50), is not in this set. Presumably, this distribution should be associated with the coalition structure ({1,3}, {2}), so consider an objection by 3 against 1 in the form of the proposal (0,150,150), which is to say that 3 threatens a coalition with 2 in which 2 and 3 attack 1. But A6 implies that 1 has no counterobjection. A counter, according to the definitions of bargaining set theory, must be a distribution that 1 likes at least as much as (150,100,50) and that its coalition partner(s) like as much as (0,150,150). That is, with the counter, country 1 must be able to "defend" whatever payoff is received in the particular proposal under scrutiny, (150,100,50) in this instance. Since this distribution is the best possible outcome for 1 (the maximum possible resources secured through negotiation), any other distribution in which 2 or 3 secures as much as it is offered in the objection, 150, cannot be obtained without conflict if 1 also gets 150, in which case 1 likes this 150 less than the 150 in (150,100,50). Since 1 thus cannot defend the 150 units it gets in (150,100, 50), this distribution is not in the bargaining set. Indeed, in the present three-person situation, bargaining set theory predicts that only outcomes of the form (150,150,0), (0,150,150), and (150,0,150) prevail - one of the three countries will be eliminated.
110
3 System stability and the balance of power
The application of traditional solution hypotheses to our problem, then, predicts that all systems ultimately reduce to two-country systems. Yet such applications are ill-suited to our purposes. Traditionally, these hypotheses are designed to be applied to games "in characteristic function form," which represents the advantages and disadvantages of players in terms of what outcomes can be enforced by the different coalitions. These applications presume, in effect, that aside from the constraints represented by the characteristic function form, bargaining occurs in a "state of nature" - there are no additional constraints on what is possible. Abstractly, all advantages and disadvantages, if they exist, derive from individual preferences and the structure of the bargaining situation. The application we have just reviewed takes account of preference, but it ignores structure. We have not tried to model the structure of bargaining among countries, but notice that the purpose of A10 is not to render a prediction about payoffs. Rather, A10 is designed to aid in predicting which countries can and which countries cannot survive given a current distribution of resources. Thus, the status quo [the distribution (120,100, 80) in the example] plays an especially important role here, and all objections that propose a change must be objections to it. With this in mind, A10 proposes some simple modifications of the objection-counterobjection process detailed in the bargaining set literature. For example, we do not require that those countries being objected to recover to their original position. Bargaining set theory imposes this constraint on counter objections because it seeks to predict payoffs; but here we are trying to predict survival, and survival merely requires that a country is assured of retaining some resources. However, one might object to this rationale for A10 with the argument that the initial resource distribution serves merely to identify winning coalitions, and that bargainers can otherwise ignore it. However, there is another view that justifies A10. Suppose countries threatened with attack can make "one last move" to transfer resources. Hence, if everyone knows that an attack on an essential country can be thwarted by a transfer, then the possibility of such a transfer should be taken as a constraint on whatever bargains are reached. Bargaining environments that support A10, then, are those in which negotiators have some certainty that transfers can be implemented as a blocking response to the decision to attack and to eliminate countries (see Footnote 8). As with our other assumptions, though, this justification for A10 suggests how its violation yields a second class of environments in which conflict and the eventual emergence of a bipolar system might become a reasonable prediction. If, in our example, 3 misreads 1 and 2's intentions and thereby fails to initiate the transfer to 1, then the attack will occur and
3.5 Appendix: Proof of Theorem 3.2
111
3 will be eliminated. In this instance, imperfect information and miscalculation preclude the certainty of "last moves," in which case we should not presuppose that countries can guarantee their survival with resource transfers. There is, then, a second class of bargaining environments, in which there is no assurance that responses of a particular type are possible. Although it is uncertain what solution is appropriate in such a context (bargaining set theory seems irrelevant since it presumes, in effect, that players negotiate with the assumption that counter objections can always be implemented as a last move), hypotheses such as the main simple V-set (which completely forgoes a bargaining rationale) predict minimal majority coalitions that eliminate maximal minority coalitions. Which class better models international systems is subject to speculation and the character of the particular system under discussion. If the system is characterized by imperfect information, by barriers to communication, and by domestic politics that inhibit the timely implementation of appropriate counterproposals, then the second class seems more appropriate. Yet, if there is a time lag between the decision to war and the actual first attack, and if there are no impediments to the implementation of an appropriate response, then we ought to use A10. Minimally, then, our analysis identifies conditions appropriate for A10 as sufficient for multicountry system stability, and the appropriateness of classical solution hypotheses as sufficient for predicting the eventual emergence of bipolar systems.
3.5
Appendix: Proof of Theorem 3.2
To establish sufficiency, we will show that (S; r) is system stable if / is essential for all i 6 5. Remark 3.5 shows that if rt = R/2 for some / in S then (S; r) is system stable. Thus, suppose that rt < R/2 for all / in S. First, we let g(C'h Ck) = r(Ck) denote the resources that C\ can secure from Ck if it defeats Ck, assuming, of course, that Q g S - C / . Let (r',C) be a threat against Ck by C'h ieC'k9 and let y = arg max [rk], keS-{i]
which means that j is the country with the greatest resources in 5— {/} (if j is not unique, then we can arbitrarily choose one such j). There are now two cases to be considered. Case 1: ieE
and rt>—2
max [rj\. jeS-U)
112
3 System stability and the balance of power
Suppose that jeCj, so j is the country with the greatest resources in S— {/} and j is part of the threatening coalition. By assumption, / has enough resources to transfer the amount R/2 — Tj to j , thereby setting j's resources equal to R/2, From A6 and Remark 3.6, R/2 is the maximum most preferred outcome possible for j . And since / prefers any outcome in which rt > 0 to one in which rt = 0, then / and j both prefer the transfer to the outcome of the attack. Hence, letting C"m= [ij] and Q' = 0, K = {i} has a counter to the threat (r', C ) . The counter is viable since, again from Remark 3.6 and A6, j most prefers the transfer to any other feasible outcome, and therefore j cannot be better off by excluding / from [/, j}. Now suppose that j $ Cj, and let C^ = {/, j} and C/J = Cj. We know that rt + rj>R/2, so (r",C") is a threat against Q' by C^, which also implies that r">ri. By Remark 3.6, j can secure at most R/2 — rj additional resources. Hence, (r", C") is a counter to (r', C ) by K= {/}. And, as before, the counter is viable, since j cannot do better than secure R/2 by acting alone. Case 2: ieE
but
/*/<— - max [ry-]. 2
JeS-{i}
In this event, there are two possibilities: letting (r', C ) be a threat by Cj against C'k, ieC'k9 then either f - max [ 0 ]
(3.A1)
or "< " holds in this inequality. In thefirstpossibility, if (r', C ) is a threat against C'k by C'h then (r',C') is a threat to at least one other country in addition to /, because / has fewer resources than the assumed lower bound on g(Cj, C'k). That is, {/} C C'k. If the country with the most resources in S— {/}, country j , is in Cj, then the members of Ck can transfer the amount R/2 — rj to j and develop a viable counterthreat. Similarly, if j $ Cj then K (ieK) can coalesce with j to form an appropriate counterthreat. To see this, note that (since ieE) there exists a C^ such that je C^e W* and AT is a subset of C"m. [This assertion follows if, whenever / is a member of some C e W*, then / is a member of some minimal winning coalition containing j , the largest member of S. To see that this is necessarily true, suppose ieCe W*, in which case C— {/'} is losing, S— C is losing, and S— C+ {/} is winning. If / is the smallest country in 5— C+ {/}, then clearly S- C+ {i} e W*9 since the deletion of / or of any larger member renders the coalition losing. If / is not the smallest such country, notice that we can delete the smallest member of S - C+ {/}, say k> and check whether S - C+ [i}-{k] is losing. If it is losing, then S - C+ {/) must be
3.5 Appendix: Proof of Theorem 3.2
113
minimal winning. If not, we can repeat the process on S— C + [i} — {k] until either / is the smallest country or the resulting coalition becomes losing with the deletion. That coalition contains / and y, and is minimal winning.] Let M= {C£ \ i,jeC£ and C;'e W*}. Then we choose C^ such that
In this case, r(C^- {j}) < r(C'k) = g(C'h C'k). And since j $ C'h the maximum resources Cj can secure, g(Cj, Cjc), is less than (R — rj)/2. Next, we must show that g(C^, S- C£) > g(C'h Ck). If the opposite is true, then
or (equivalently) from the right and left sides of this inequality,
However, r(Cj^-{j])
1
^
which yields an inequal-
R-r; 0
So it must be that g(C^, S- C^) ^ g(Q, Ck). Because resources are infinitely divisible and transferable, all members of C% can be made better off with an appropriate and feasible specification of (r", C") than in (r', C ) for all /e C^ and r'( > rt for all ie K. Thus, (r", C") is a counterthreat by K against Cj. To see that this is a viable counterthreat for / e K, notice that C^ e W*, (r0, Co) might be a threat against C% but not against C*h + {/}. Therefore, if r'{ = rt and if r(C0) > r(C;)9 then g(C0, C"h) =
g(C^, eft), which implies that roj > rf for all jeC0 is impossible. Accordingly, (r", C") is a viable counter for /. The second possibility is that the inequality in expression (3.A1) becomes " <." Since / e E, it follows that there exists a C ^ e W*, such that ^ 1
max [rj\>g(C'hC'k). j S U )
To show this, let g(C£, CD = r(S- C^). Suppose that g(C"m,C*h)<^-
max [rj], 2
in which case
JeS-{i}
114
3 System stability and the balance of power
r(S-C'^)+ max [/•;]<£. However, since C^eW* 9 C^-{i]i W*, so r(C^-{/})?/2. thatr(S-C£ + {/})>/?/2. Since
(3.A2) This means
r/< max [ry], we have r ( 5 - C ^ ) + max [ r y ] > ^ . ye5-{/}
z
But this contradicts expression (3.A2), so it must be that g(C^, C£)> g(C/, C'k). Consequently, as before, (r", C") is a viable counter for / e K. To prove necessity, we will show that if S ^ E then there is at least one / e S such that, for some threat against /, / does not have a viable counter. Suppose that there is an i$E such that, for every threat (r',C) by C\ against /, / has a viable counterthreat (r", C/r). Assume that C^ = C0U {/}, Co e Pr*. From the definition of a viable counterthreat and the notation introduced there, no Co can have a threat (r0, Co) against CjJ or against Q' U {/} with roJ > /*/, for all jeC0. However, since Coe W*, r(Co) > r(CJU(/)), which implies that (r0, Co) is a threat to Q'U {/}. Moreover, g(C0, C^U{/}) > g(C^, C£), and since resources are infinitely divisible and transferable, all members of Co can make themselves better off in (ro, Co) than in (r", C"), which contradicts the conditions of a viable counterthreat. Q.E.D.
CHAPTER 4
Resource stability and the balance of power
... disagreements about how benefits should be distributed permeate the relations among actors and persist because bargains are never permanently valid Furthermore, this struggle to make others adjust is played repeatedly. Apparent victory can be illusory or defeat ephemeral, for political bargaining and maneuver result not in definitive choices conferring power on some people rather than others, but in agreements that may in the future be reversed or in discord that signals a continuation of bargaining and maneuver. Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony (1984, p. 18)
This discovery of instability. ..points up sharply the contrast between economic activity, most of the models for which are self-equilibrating or assume some kind of "dynamic" equilibrium, and political activity, where fundamental instability seems inherent and ineradicable. William H. Riker, The Theory of Political Coalitions (1962, pp. 173-4)
4.1
The relevance of system stability to resource stability
Hitherto, our analysis has focused simply on the first part of the game, which concerns international actors. This focus is especially important because it deals with the fundamental issue of sovereignty and the survival of regimes, and it shows how such survival is ensured in anarchic systems. The central thesis of this volume, however, is that there are two types of instability, and we should also be concerned about the possibility that the second type - resource instability - can also upset systems and lead to conflict. Echoing the observation from Keohane, Gilpin (1981, p. 13) hints not only at the necessity for distinguishing between system and resource stability, but also at the pervasiveness of resource instability in systems that are otherwise stable: In every international system there are continual occurrences of political, economic, and technological changes that promise gains and threaten losses for one or another actor. In most cases these potential gains and losses are minor, and only incremental adjustments are necessary in order to take account of them. Such changes take place within the existing international system, producing a condition 115
116
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
of homeostatic equilibrium. The relative stability of the system is, in fact, largely determined by its capacity to adjust to the demands of actors affected by changing political and environmental conditions. In every system, therefore, a process of disequilibrium and adjustment is constantly taking place. In the absence of large potential net benefits from change, the system continues to remain in a state of equilibrium.
In a similar vein, Kennedy (1987, p. 73), referring to the period 1519-1659 as one of "short-term, shifting alliances," suggests the "microinstability," encapsulated by our notion of resource instability, which seems an inevitable part of "macrostable" systems, that is, system-stable systems. Despite such tantalizing hints in the literature, system and resource stability, by and large, have not been analytically distinguished. Consequently, some scholars believe that cooperative game theory, whenever applied to situations in which the total of resources isfixed,yields a constant-sum game in which no balance of power is possible, and in which dominant alliances war on and absorb the rest. This supposition not only runs contrary to our argument that the forces of self-interest can ensure essential countries against absorption by other essential countries and, hence, elimination, but if the argument presented in the previous chapter is genuinely compelling then our attention must be drawn to a further implication: the dynamics of system stability affect the set of feasible redistributions. To see what we mean by this, notice that our analysis thus far can be interpreted as modeling the contemplations of actors prior to anyone actually making a threat or initiating a transfer of resources. Although it does not tell us what alliances, if any, will form, or what specific reallocations of resources will be implemented by the various coalitions, if everyone has complete information about the situation, so that everyone knows that essential countries cannot be eliminated, then this act should be reflected in any subsequent negotiations and resource transfers. Thus, the baseline of negotiations should not be the elimination of essential countries; that is, it should not include setting rt = 0 for any country / in E. Instead, that baseline should be the amount of resources countries can ensure for themselves, given that they will not be eliminated. To illustrate this implication using some elementary notation from cooperative game theory, if the initial distribution of resources is $50 to each of three players, and if all resources are subject to expropriation and redistribution, then the "value" of a single player, v(i) - /'s security level if it joins no coalition - equals zero since an individual can guarantee nothing under simple majority rule, whereas the value of any winning coalition is $150, the total of all available resources. Thus, the "negotiable range" - the set of feasible payoffs to any individual player - varies theoretically from zero to $150. In this instance, we can appeal to any
4.1 The relevance of system stability to resource stability
117
number of solution hypotheses to predict that a minimal winning coalition will form and "split the difference": its two members will divide the $150 evenly (assuming that we can equate the measure of a player's utility with the measure of how much money he or she possesses). Of course, if the distribution (75,75,0) appears imminent then player 3 could propose (0,80,70), which 2 and 3 unanimously prefer to the original proposal. However, now 1 could counter with (75,0,75), to which 2 counters with (0,70,80), and so on, ad infinitum. Thus, in this instance, the game is both system and resource unstable: players are threatened with elimination, and no resource distribution is immune from challenge. However, the assignment of "value" to alliances in this example, the corresponding prediction about coalitions, and the arguments about the game's inherent instabilities are legitimate only if players can secure more than half the resources and if the players are indifferent about how they secure their resources. If, as in our model, a player prefers to receive resources through negotiation rather than through conflict, and if everyone acts on the presumption that no one can secure more than half the total, then if any player agrees to cede half of his or her initial endowment of $50 to another, the game ends in the sense that no further reallocations are possible. Hence, rather than setting the security value of /, v(i), equal to 0, we should set this value equal to $25, which is what any player will be left with in the event that it must cede half of his or her initial endowment to counter a threat and forestall elimination. This change in the representation of the implicit and explicit bargaining game that affects nations is fundamental to our understanding of international political processes, since it is no longer evident that such a game is necessarily resource unstable. Instead, we must analyze this new game to learn its properties with respect to resource stability. Hence, in the next section we discuss situations that are system stable but that may not be resource stable: systems in which the distribution of resources remains the subject of negotiation, but in which each country is initially essential and can thereby ensure its own survival. Our analysis will establish the necessary and sufficient conditions for resource stability and predict what distribution of resources will arise from an initial distribution. As we note in the previous chapter, researchers offer a variety of speculations about the details of balance-of-power systems, including assertions that relate to the relative stability of large versus small systems, and the question of whether equality or inequality of resources among countries best fosters stability. Chapter 3 addresses such issues in the context of system stability, and we find no necessary relationship between the number of countries and system stability, or between the precise distribution of resources and this type of stability. This chapter, then, will also address
118
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
these same issues in the context of resource stability, and we seek answers to the following questions: Are three-country systems more resource stable than ^-country systems? Is there any "magic" number of countries that ensures resource stability? Does such stability require equality or near equality in the distribution of resources? Finally, to be certain that our model makes sense in the context of cooperative bargaining processes, we shall conclude with an experimental test of the ideas presented in this chapter and Chapter 3. 4.2
The nature of resource stability and instability
Suppose that all nations are essential, so that the survival of regimes or countries is not an issue and the purpose of alliances is simply to coerce a more advantageous position with respect to the overall distribution of resources. What we now wish to consider is the bargaining that might occur within an alliance if it seeks to extract resources from some other set of countries. The literature on bargaining and experimental games contains a great many ad hoc hypotheses about how an alliance's members might divide their "winnings," such as that those winnings accrue to the largest member of the alliance, that members divide winnings in proportion to their relative weight, that these winnings are divided on the basis of a player's likelihood of being the pivotal member of a winning coalition, or that equitable (i.e., equal division) outcomes prevail. Here, however, we take a more game-theoretic view, and we suppose instead that those resources are redistributed among the alliance's members on the basis of what each member might have received if some other coalition had formed. To transform this somewhat imprecisely stated idea into a formal analysis, there are at least four important theoretical questions a game theorist would ask about the situation. First, how in general can we represent cooperative games that take account of the analysis given in our previous chapter? That is, how do we formally represent a cooperative game among essential countries that reflects Assumptions Al through A10? Second, will such games have cores? This question is merely a technical way of asking whether there are any equilibrium resource distributions - resource distributions that naturally suggest themselves to negotiators and that, once arrived at, cannot be upset by any other proposal. Negotiations in cooperative games without cores, though, can cycle endlessly through an indefinite (possibly finite, possibly infinite) series of proposals as each proposal on the table is upset successively by some coalition with a new proposal. Third, if no core exists, but if alternative distributions are arrived at by some sequential recontracting process, then what are the end
4.2 The nature of resource stability and instability
119
points, if any, of this process? That is, if there is no natural "sticking point" to which negotiations among essential countries might converge, will negotiations in fact proceed endlessly or will certain types of outcomes emerge? Finally, might essential countries become inessential in the process of negotiation? To illustrate how we can go about answering these questions, suppose that the set of countries is S= {1,2,3 j and that the initial distribution is r = (120,100,80). In accordance with Theorem 3.1, this system is system stable. Suppose now that the coalition {1,2} tentatively forms with the intention of threatening 3 with elimination or at least in order to coerce 3 out of some of its resources. Notice that one possible response is that 3 offers to cede 30 units to 1, at which point a resource-stable distribution (150,100,50) results. However, we certainly should take some account of the fact that country 2 could form an alliance with 3 instead to expropriate 50 units from 1, in which case 1 can respond by noting that it can coalesce with 3 to expropriate 30 units from 2. Thus, each country has bargaining advantages and disadvantages of different sorts. Country 3 is disadvantaged in that none of these coalitions permit it to secure additional resources. Yet, if 3 is excluded from any coalition, so that only {1,2} is feasible, then country 2 cannot secure additional resources either. Thus, 3 (being essential) can place some demands on 1 or 2 in the event either approaches it to form an alliance. Although it is still too early to suggest that the situation we model here is precisely reflected in the empirical world, what we seek to model in this situation are the systemic bargaining implications of the bargaining position of a weaker (here, the weakest) but essential power in an international system. Abstracting for a moment from the number of essential members of such a system, the situation we have in mind is similar to that of, say, Austria-Hungary with regard to the other great powers (particularly Germany) in the last quarter of the nineteenth century, or England in its dealings with Spain, Portugal, France, and the Holy Roman Empire at the dawn of the sixteenth century. The three-country situation we have described corresponds to a threeperson cooperative bargaining game that we can model in the usual characteristic function form representation of ^-person cooperative games. However, for reasons we have already noted, some care must be taken in defining that function. Traditionally, a coalition's value is set equal to whatever it receives if the excluded players act in the coalition's worst interests, even if that means that these players act irrationally. If, for example, coalition {2,3} forms and 1 must play alone as a "single-member" coalition, then 1 cannot ensure against the possibility of being eliminated by {2,3), in which case it seems appropriate that we set v(l) = 0. Yet, we
120
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
already know that in this circumstance, country 1 should offer to cede 50 units of resources to country 2. Country 2 now has a dominant choice accept the offer. This strategy ensures l's continued sovereignty and gives 2 its most preferred feasible outcome. This argument leads to the conclusion that we should set v(\) equal to 120, less the 50 units it may be required to cede in order to exist; that is, v(l) = 70. Continuing with this definition of the characteristic function, we set v(2) = 70 (acting alone, it must cede 30 units to 1), and v(3) = 50 (acting alone, it must cede 30 units to 1). With respect to coalition [1,2), although it has the ability to absorb 3, in evaluating ^(1,2) we should be cognizant that 3 can disrupt the coalition by ceding 30 units to 1. Thus, if {1,2} assumes that 3 responds rationally to its formation (and recall that responses can be made instantaneously in our model), its members know that the coalition can expropriate at most 30 units from 3. Thus, v(l, 2) = 220 (the resources it controls originally) plus 30 (the resources it can secure from 3), which totals 250. By a similar argument, we should set v(l, 3) and v(2,3) each equal to 230. Finally, we set v(l, 2,3) equal to 300, since the system's resources are constant and we assume that resources cannot be destroyed (or, equivalently, that countries are concerned solely with proportion of resources controlled). It is evident that the corresponding characteristic function, based on the idea that countries respond rationally to offers and counteroffers, yields a zero-sum cooperative game that has no core. As before, outcomes can cycle endlessly. If the distribution (150,100,50) is proposed, 2 can offer 3 (70,150, 80) instead, to which 1 can counter with (150,70,80), to which 3 might demand (50,100,150), and so on. Notice, however, that this instability is of a different sort than what Riker (1962) asserts characterizes international systems. Specifically, it does not support the conclusion that balance of power is a fiction, at least insofar as the existence of sovereign countries is concerned, since the survival of countries is not an issue in this game. That is, the results of our previous chapter justify the assumption that essential countries will not be eliminated, and this fact has been incorporated into the definition of v(C). Instead, we are now focusing on ascertaining final distributions of resources that can be arrived at through negotiation and through the "threat" of war as against its actual implementation. With respect to the general idea of international instability and conflict, then, the direct manifestations of resource instability are likely to correspond less to overt conflict than will manifestations of system instability. System instability threatens sovereignty; resource instability merely implies that all countries are positioned to lose as well as win resources from each other. This does not mean, though, that resource instability is not dangerous to peace. On the contrary, the tactics whereby countries seek
4.2 The nature of resource stability and instability
121
to extract economic and military advantage from others are the threats and counterthreats defined in the previous chapter, and thus, in a resourceunstable world, countries are necessarily in a state of muted conflict and competition. The complexity this instability occasions is well articulated by Waltz (1979, pp. 165-6): With more than two states, the politics of power turn on the diplomacy by which alliances are made, maintained, and disrupted. Flexibility of alignment means both that the country one is wooing may prefer another suitor and that one's present alliance partner may defect. Flexibility of alignment narrows one's choice of policies. A state's strategy must please a potential or satisfy a present partnerf,] ... strategy is at least partly made for the sake of attracting and holding allies... [and] if pressures are strong enough, a state will deal with almost anyone. In the quest for security, alliances have to be made... by states that have some but not all of their interests in common. The common interest is ordinarily a negative one: fear of other states. To ascertain which specific alliances and distributions might prevail in this complex and competitive environment, we must turn to the various solution concepts offered by game theorists to solve cooperative games in characteristic function form. However, rather than review these hypotheses here as they might pertain to the specific problem at hand, it is merely sufficient to note that each of them takes the view, first, that a unique outcome cannot be predicted. These hypotheses, however, do offer a response to Waltz's rhetorical question: "The three-body problem has yet to be solved by physicists. Can political scientists or policy makers hope to do better in charting the course of three or more interacting states? " (1979, pp. 192-3). The answer is "yes" at least insofar as we can narrow the set of feasible possibilities to a significantly smaller set. This narrowing occurs through the imposition of restrictions on predicted outcomes that seem feasible (e.g., no outcome should prevail in which all of the members of the coalition that bring it about unanimously prefer some other outcome; or, if two coalitions are possible, then those players who pivot between them should not all strictly prefer the proposal of one coalition to the other). Fortunately, despite a seeming plethora of competing hypotheses (e.g., main-simple V-set, strong bargaining set, competitive solution, aspiration bargaining set), each of these solution concepts predicts for the preceding example that one of the following three distributions will prevail: (125,70,105) via coalition {1,3}; (125,125,50) via coalition {1,2); (70,125,105) via coalition {2,3}. As is usual in cooperative games without an equilibrium such as the one defined by the concept of the core, our predictions are not unique,
122
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
but instead take the form "if the alliance C forms, it will establish the new resource distribution..., if the alliance C" forms, it will establish..." and so on. More importantly, notice that, after reflecting the relative bargaining positions of the players, we do not predict that one country will achieve half the total of resources. Instead, we predict that if, say, {1,3} forms then 2 loses the amount it would have to cede to 1 to end the game. However, these 30 units do not all accrue to player 1, because player 2 also has a claim to receiving some resources (such as the threat that {2,3) forms against 1). Hence, 1 and 3 divide these 30 units 5 to 25. Similarly, if 1 and 2 coalesce then 3 loses the 30 units it must cede to ensure survival, but now 1 and 2 divide this amount 5 to 25. Finally, if {2,3} forms then 1 must give up 50 units, which 2 and 3 divide evenly. Notice, however, that these predictions may be valid only in the "short run." For example, if (125,70,105) prevails, then renegotiation can reoccur with a new characteristic function that reflects the new distribution resulting from the previous bargaining round. Based on our previous arguments, then, the corresponding characteristic function is v(l, 2) = 220,
v(l, 3) = 255,
v(2,3) = 220;
That is, country 1 must now cede 45 units to 3 in order to ensure survival, which means that 1 can guarantee itself 80; country 2 must cede 25 to 1, so it can guarantee itself 45; and country 3 must cede 25 to 1, so it is assured of receiving no less than 80. Applying any of the cooperative solution concepts mentioned earlier to this representation of the game yields the following three distributions as predictions: (127.5,92.5,80) via {1,2}; (127.5,45,127.5) via {1,3}; (80,92.5,127.5) via {2,3}. This example leads to several important observations that warrant generalization. First, it follows from a well-known result in game theory about the nonexistence of cores for zero- or constant-sum ^-person cooperative games that since we assume that resources can be neither destroyed nor created, there is no distribution that cannot be upset by some alternative proposal (provided, as in our example, that no country controls precisely half the resources). Put differently, and in accord with the intuition that Waltz reveals in the previously cited quotation: if the survival of all countries is assured, then regardless of which alliance is proposed, there always exists another proposal that the members of some other alliance all prefer and that they can secure.
4.2 The nature of resource stability and instability
123
Second, unless one country can somehow secure one-half the resources in our example, this process of negotiation, dissolution of alliances, and renegotiation will continually change the distribution of resources. The only distribution corresponding here to a resource-stable system is one in which rt = R/2 for some /, so "rt = R/2 for some /" is both a necessary and a sufficient condition for resource stability. That is, in accord with the quotation from Keohane that introduces this chapter, if the existence of all countries is assured, then no alliance is permanent. Instead, we should observe the constant shifting of alliances as countries jockey for more advantageous positions. As Claude observed, "for balance of power, competitive struggle is the general condition, to be dealt with by the realization of cooperative arrangements within limited groups" (1962, p. 145). Indeed, it is precisely this dynamic that led Bismarck to summarize the implications of a balance-of-power system in the dictum that "all politics reduces itself to this formula: Try to be a trois as long as the world is governed by the unstable equilibrium of five Great Powers" (quoted in Joll 1984, p. 37). As well, this remark accounts considerably for the fluidity of the late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century European alliance system. It is exactly this constant shifting and the threats to security it engendered that led to British involvement in "entente" rather than alliance with France and Russia and that reduced Italian participation in the Triple Alliance to "ententelike" behavior. One caveat we offer about this implication is that, because time is not an explicit variable in our analysis, we cannot say anything about the temporal duration of alliances. In reality, of course, they may endure long enough so that technology and the natural growth rates of countries alter the distribution of resources in a way that essentially "resets" the system. Certainly, the economic growth of West Germany, Japan, Korea, and Taiwan - in conjunction with a stagnant Soviet economy and nearly stagnant Eastern European economies - has altered the relative resources of whatever alliances emerged from World War II. The consequences of this change are now being felt as the Soviets try not only to revise the structure of their economy, but also to negotiate a position for themselves that allows them to recoup their lost position. Finally, notice that a fully resource-stable system - one in which one country controls precisely half the total resources - can emerge only in the limit of an infinite sequence of alliances and negotiations. That is, barring differential domestic resources growth (and error on the part of negotiators), in the negotiations for resources among countries, no country emerges as predominant or even near-predominant. Hence, this feature of our example, if it holds true generally, implies that leaders who seek to render their regimes or countries predominant have but two alternative
124
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
courses of action. If they believe that the intelligence of their opponents is flawed, then they can try to secure their objective by nearly any means at their disposal, including the negotiation of successively more advantageous resource allocations; but if stupidity and misinformation do not clear their path, they must rely instead on internal sources of growth - on the dynamism of their economies, on their willingness to sacrifice consumption for military power, and, perhaps, on the inevitability of certain sociopolitical imperatives in which they believe. 4.3
A necessary and sufficient condition for resource stability
To establish the generality of these assertions, which are based on the analysis of a single example, we must first formulate the general form of the resource allocation game's characteristic function: the value of each alternative coalition relative to all others. Letting r be a vector that denotes the initial distribution, we assume first that all countries are essential. That is, we suppose that inessential countries have been eliminated and that their resources have been reallocated to yield r. Letting C be a winning coalition (r(C) > R/2), and letting e be an arbitrarily small positive number, if we take Theorem 3.2 as an operating constraint (assuming that no country in S can have its resources set equal to zero) then we have two possibilities. First, if S—C controls enough resources to render the largest member of C near-predominant, then C cannot guarantee that it receives more than the difference between R/2 and the resources of this member. And since S—C can always "freeze" the system with such a transfer, we set v(S-C) equal to r(S-C) minus the resources it must cede. Second, if S- C hasn't enough resources to render the largest member of C near-predominant, then one or more members of S—C can counter a threat from C only by attracting one or more of the members of C to some new coalition. However, all we know at this point is that, because everyone is essential, no member of S— Cs resources will be set equal to zero (Theorem 3.2). Thus, we set v(S—C) = e and v(C) = R — e since one or more members of S—C may find it necessary to cede an unspecified amount of its resources in forming the counter. Restating this argument in terms of our notation, we have: if ieC
R—e r(S-C)-
r(S-C)>~-msix[ri]i
/
*
ieC
otherwise; 'R \ ( —-max[rt])
if r(S-C)>
/
otherwise;
(4.1) R — -max[rj, 2
ieC
(4.2)
4.3 A necessary and sufficient condition for resource stability
125
v(S) = R; and if C is blocking - if C controls exactly half the resources then S- C is blocking and v(C) = v(S- C) = r(C). Thus, if country / is large enough to render the largest member of S— {/} near-predominant, then v(i) equals rt minus the minimum resources it must cede to render someone near-predominant; on the other hand, if / cannot by itself render anyone near-predominant, then v(i) = e. Notice, moreover, that if we set e = 0 but no longer interpret rt = 0 as implying the elimination of /, then the preceding characteristic function is identical to the usual one used to model a simple majority-rule game, but with the important exception that v(S- C) > 0 if S - C is large enough to "buy" stability. We proceed now by establishing three results about games with this representation of coalitional value. The first result, which follows trivially from expressions (4.1) and (4.2), states simply that the corresponding game is an essential constant-sum game - that v(C) + v(S— C) equals a constant for all C and there is at least one pair of coalitions that gains something by joining. Games of this sort cannot have a core, and because this property of essential is satisfied whenever rt < R/2 for all / (whenever no player controls half or more of the resources), then r{ < R/2 for all / in S implies that (S;r) cannot be resource stable. The second result states that negotiations will necessarily change the distribution of resources unless one country controls exactly half the resources. Thus, rt-=R/2 for some / is a necessary and sufficient condition for resource stability. The last result states that if the agreed-to reallocations of resources correspond to the predictions of any one of several solution hypotheses offered by game theorists about such situations then, regardless of what negotiated outcome prevails, if no country controls half the resources when negotiations begin, no country will control half the resources when negotiations end. Thus, barring changes that are exogenous to the analysis, resource instability is a permanent feature of international political systems. Theorem 4.1. If rt < R/2 for all / e S, then the cooperative «-person game among the essential countries described by expressions (4.1) and (4.2) is an essential constant-sum game, and thus has no core. Theorem 4.1 corresponds to Riker's assertion that "no rules of balance can be formulated for (essential) ^-person zero-sum games" (1962, p. 169) and it reasserts his conclusion about instability cited in the introduction to this chapter. However, it is imperative that we keep in mind that Theorem 3.2 implies that this conclusion does not apply to system stability. That is, resource instability does not imply system instability. Also, Riker fails to consider the possibility that the game among nations becomes inessential whenever one nation is nearly predominant. That is, if one country controls exactly half the resources then no threats are possible, and
126
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
thus no reallocations of resources can occur: systems with a nearly predominant country are both system and resource stable (notice that with a nearly predominant country, all countries are essential). Stated as a formal result with r' denoting the negotiated outcome: Theorem 4.2. For the game in characteristic function form described by expressions (4.1) and (4.2), r] ^ ry- for two or more j e S unless rt = R/2 for some /. Next, we address the issue of whether the condition for resource stability, that rt = R/2 for some /, can ever emerge in a system that is not initially resource stable. In the statement of our next result, Theorem 4.3, we focus on the main-simple V-set as a vehicle for predicting payoffs, since such payoffs correspond to both the competitive solution and to the strong bargaining set (McKelvey, Ordeshook, and Winer 1978).! Theorem 4.3. If r is the initial distribution of resources, if rt< R/2 for all ie S, if r' is the negotiated outcome, and if r' is an element of a main-simple V-set, then r\
For readers unfamiliar with the definition of this solution hypothesis, we offer a brief description. In effect, the main-simple V-set is a refinement of the von Neumann-Morgenstern solution, V. If the vector r of resources describing a system is in a main-simple V-set Vm, and if r' is any other element of Vm - if r' is any other distribution that we include in the set of things that we are predicting as a possible outcome - then there exists a minimal winning coalition C (usually thought of as the coalition that will form to bring r about) such that r, > r\ for all members of C (for all ieC). The idea behind a mainsimple V-set, then, is that if r and r' are two possible outcomes then the coalition that will form to enforce r must not contain any members who strictly prefer some other predicted outcome. Admittedly, the reasonableness of this requirement is debatable since it is merely an ad hoc addendum to the definition of a V-set solution; nevertheless, it has the advantage of restricting predictions to the same outcomes predicted by other solution hypotheses - notably the strong bargaining set and the competitive solution (both of which can be viewed as providing behavioral rationalizations for Vm). Another advantage is that if r and r' are both elements of Km, associated respectively with the minimal winning coalitions C and C", and if / is a member of both of these coalitions, then n = ri. Hence, as seems reasonable, persons who pivot between coalitions must be indifferent between the proposals of those coalitions if both are to have some chance of forming.
4.4 General implications
127
as is presumed by this model, and a great many other factors should intervene to disrupt or redirect the disequilibrium conveyed by this model factors such as the changing leadership of nations and, in violation of assumption Al, differential rates of growth or decline in national resources and power. Short of reaching any limit and ignoring considerations presently exogenous to the model, however, if all countries are essential, but if no country controls exactly half the resources, then the instabilities in the ultimate distribution of resources associated with coalitions in games without cores are necessarily present. 4.4
General implications
The distinction between system and resource stability is profoundly important. Many scholars have hinted at this distinction, but by making it explicit we are able to uncover several hypotheses about balance of power that are at odds with some speculations and in accord with others. First, as a trivial implication of Theorem 4.1 (as well as Remark 3.1), resource stability, like system stability, in two-country systems requires equality of resources. In our model, then, two-country systems are neither system nor resource stable unless a precise equality of resources is maintained. Thus, at this point we ought to ask about the assumptions of those scholars who are led to conclude that bipolar systems are especially stable, or at least more stable than multipolar systems. Briefly, this view (offered by Waltz 1979) supposes that miscalculation is a more serious threat in multipolar systems. This may or may not be true (although it is certainly easier to calculate strategic possibilities when there are only two countries), but recall that uncertainty and hence miscalculation play no role in our analysis. Thus, we might infer that our conclusions about two-country systems and their sensitivity to the relative resources of countries are at odds with an argument that bipolar systems are stable only because that argument is based on different assumptions than the ones we employ.2 Waltz's bipolar world, however, cannot correspond to a two-country system. To suppose otherwise renders inexplicable the presumption that these two powers are greatly concerned with "anything that happens anywhere" (Waltz 1979, p. 171). Thus, bipolarity here must mean something about the distribution of resources, presumably a distribution in which the "lion's 2
Of course, a counterargument to Waltz's conclusion is that uncertainty and a degree of risk aversion will lead decision makers to pursue "more conservative" strategies - strategies that avoid rendering a country nearly predominant - and that it is thereby difficult to say whether increasing uncertainty yields a greater probability of instability (elimination of countries) until we rigorously analyze the trade-off between uncertainty and stability as mediated by the strategies of decision makers.
128
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
share" of resources are controlled by two states. Thus, if we are to find theoretical support for Waltz, it must be that systems in which two countries control more than some critical amount of resources are more stable than systems in which resources are more "equitably" distributed. Theorem 3.2, however, argues against this possibility with respect to system stability, and the hypothesis fares no better with Theorem 4.1. As long as no country controls precisely half the resources, all systems are resource unstable.3 A related conclusion, then, is that if n > 2, a uniform resource distribution is not sufficient for resource stability or necessary for system stability, nor does the emergence of either form of stability produce such uniformity. If we apply any of the usual game-theoretic solution hypotheses to the characteristic functions of our examples, a uniform distribution of resources does not emerge as a predicted outcome. Moreover, even if such a distribution emerges as the result of, say, the dynamics of domestic economic growth, it cannot correspond to a resource-stable outcome. If our assumptions have any empirical validity then coalitions can extract resources from excluded countries, and we should anticipate that unless the costs of international conflict are sufficiently high (and decision makers are concerned with absolute as well as relative resources), countries will maneuver for advantage. A third conclusion we can draw from the analysis is that neither system nor resource stability precludes the possibility that no nation or combination of nations has the ability to defeat some other nation. Clearly, the implied algebraic identity of such a requirement cannot be satisfied in any constant-sum game if the number n of countries in S is greater than or equal to 3. Rather, balance is achieved by a nation's ability either to "buy off" a key member of a threatening coalition or to propose an alternative coalition that makes its members better off than they would otherwise be 3
Alternatively, we might interpret Waltz's hypothesis to mean that the "extent" of the instabilities is less with broadly asymmetric distributions of resources. Of course, the meaning of the word "extent" is ambiguous, but we can give it a formal interpretation. Consider the distribution r and suppose that from any other distribution TQ there exists a path (ri» T2,..., rm) such that there is a winning coalition that prefers ri to ro, a winning coalition that prefers r2 to r i , . . . , and a winning coalition that prefers ro to rm. That is, regardless of where we begin, we can find a way to reach ro. If this is true for any possible resource distribution in the system, then we will say that the "extent of the instability" is total, whereas systems with a smaller set of points that satisfies this property is "less unstable." Unfortunately, it is easy to see that the initial distribution of resources is irrelevant to this degree of instability - if we can get to any distribution from any starting point then any distribution can become a new status quo point. Indeed, as long as no country controls half or more of the resources, then it is a simple corollary of McKelvey's (1979) result, cited in Chaper 1, that all systems are equally unstable: every distribution can be reached from any starting point.
4.4 General implications
129
if the original threat succeeded. To this extent, then, the analysis agrees with the view that system stability is maintained primarily by the skillful formation of alliances and counteralliances, or (more precisely) by the threat of such alliances. Organski and Kugler are thus correct to observe that "the major mechanism through which the balance-of-power system is maintained is the making and unmaking of alliances" (1980, p. 16). However, as we noted in Chapter 2, they offer the wrong explanation for this fact: The reason for this dependence on coalitions in order to change the distribution of power is that the power resources of each member of the system are viewed as inelastic. There is no way a nation can increase its own strength very much except by adding its allies' strength to its own, or by decreasing its adversaries' strength by separating it, through persuasion, bribery, or subversion, from its allies (1980, p. 16). Further, The balance of power...models argue [that]...the units of the system do not change (at least not much): they simply combine in different ways, and different distributions are the result of such combinations (1980, p. 24).
If our theory were thus restricted then Organski and Kugler would be correct in their critique; but, if anything, our analysis allows too much flexibility in the transfer of resources among countries. In any event, allowing such transfers makes the formation of coalitions more, not less, profitable and likely. The preceding discussion thus serves to emphasize that our analysis presumes that all decision makers are cognizant of the game they are playing, including the strategies available to all other decision makers, and that they anticipate and take account of the feasible responses of others to any challenge. Agreements reached among nations should reflect this knowledge, and presumably "skillful negotiation" entails making certain that all other participants are aware of one's advantages and options. Keep in mind, moreover, that our analysis presents decision makers with the simplest environment. If uncertainty takes the form of a lack of perfect information about the situation - about the preferences and perceptions of others - then, as we noted earlier, strategic complexity is increased considerably. This, of course, gives an even greater premium to strategic skills. At this point, it is worth commenting on Morgenthau's (1959, p. 171) observation that "The opposition of two alliances, one or both pursuing imperialistic goals and defending the independence of their members against the imperialistic aspirations of the other coalition, is the most frequent configuration within the system of the balance of power." Morgenthau subsequently qualifies this assertion to include a role for a third,
130
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
balancing country, and indeed we do not find within our analysis reasons for supposing that bipolarity necessarily prevails. Certainly, the various cooperative solution hypotheses to which we have appealed predict that a zero-sum redistribution game, if played once, yields a minimal winning coalition expropriating from those who have been excluded. This establishes at least one force for bipolarity. On the other hand, we prefer to be somewhat more ambiguous in our predictions since the game nations play in system-stable systems is a recurring process of negotiation and renegotiation. Indeed, in this fluid environment it may be difficult to say precisely who is a member of what coalition at any specific point in time, and our impression is that this is often a more accurate characterization of international affairs than one that sees countries cleanly aligned into two opposing alliances. Fourth, if the number of countries exceeds 2, then a uniform distribution implies only system but not resource stability. System stability requires simply that no nation be so weak that it is inessential - a condition that is satisfied if resources are uniformly distributed - whereas a system is both system and resource stable if and only if one country controls exactly half the resources. Hence, aggressive choices are precluded only if r; = R/2 for one country. Otherwise, a system will be either system or resource unstable, in which case wars remain a possibility unless nations can cede resources without armed conflict. This conclusion, then, undermines the equating of the absence of wars with uniform distributions of power (see, e.g., Claude 1962). It is certainly not the case that the balanceof-power theory offered in this volume "suggests that when power is more or less equally distributed among great powers or members of major alliances [that] peace will ensue" (Organski and Kugler 1980, p. 14). Aside from the fact that uniform distributions are sufficient for system but not resource stability, our analysis shows that the precise nature of the resource distribution is largely irrelevant to whether a system is system or resource stable, and thereby it is consistent with the inference Organski and Kugler draw from their data that "power distributions are... not a predicator of the coming of war" (1980, p. 49). Fifth, no "magic" number of countries is required for the attainment of system or resource stability. It is the traditional wisdom that in threecountry systems, two of the powers can easily ally, threaten, and even conquer the third, divide the spoils, and drive the system back to bipolarity. Thus, this argument implies that systems must contain at least four countries to be stable. Yet, our analysis shows that as long as resources are distributed to satisfy the conditions of Theorem 4.2, three-country systems are no more or less resource stable than ^-country systems. What this wisdom seems to have forgotten is that if the third country is capable
4.4 General implications
131
of anticipating threats, it can propose counter alliances to any threat or, at the very worst, offer to cede resources to one of the countries posing a threat. Certainly, the Soviets can anticipate the consequences of an SinoAmerican alliance, just as the United States can anticipate the implications of Soviet hegemony over all of Asia. Just as the United States may be willing to grant various economic benefits to China in order to forestall its moving too closely to the Kremlin, the Kremlin can seek to negotiate its border disputes with China. China, being the willing recipient of this largess, need only be concerned that an American-Soviet rapproachement weaken its pivotal position so as to provide the Soviets with an excuse to reassert their territorial claims and to reduce the United States' desire to aid in China's industrial advancement. We should not, of course, carry the implications of our analysis beyond its limitations. Certainly, as the number of relevant essential countries increases, the transaction costs of negotiating and enforcing agreements will increase as well; and the increasing complexity will make miscalculation more likely. Thus, in reality, smaller systems may have an advantage over larger ones with respect to the ease with which system-preserving negotiations can proceed, which is to say that the intuition that small systems are more stable than larger ones may indeed be correct. Our analysis merely asserts that this differential stability must be explained by considerations that are currently exogenous to our analysis and that our analysis reveals the feasibility of stable systems of any size. Hence, schemes for inducing peace need not rely on the prior existence of any magical number of primary states. Before we review the results of an experimental test of our theoretical structure, we should comment on one aspect of system-stable, resourceunstable systems. It should be evident from what we have said thus far that we regard the outcomes associated with resource instability to be less traumatic from the perspective of wars and armed conflict than those we associate with system instability. This should not be interpreted to mean, however, that resource instability is not dangerous to peace. Threats and counterthreats as a means of securing advantage continue to play a role in resource-unstable systems even if all contries are essential. Although in the perfect and complete information context of our theory these threats will not result in the elimination of such countries, we should anticipate that those informational imperfections that are likely to characterize reality, as well as the constraints on action imposed by domestic political considerations, can upset our calculations. Hence, reality may magnify the consequences of the resource-reallocation game allowed by resource instability and can lead, as a result, to conflict that was otherwise unintended.
132
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
4.5
Some experimental evidence
The distortions of reality occasioned by our assumptions in this and in the previous chapters are apparent. The one assumption that is especially difficult to evaluate, however, is A10 - the imperatives of bargaining that we assume. This is not an assumption that can be readily studied by looking at actual international relations processes. Although evaluating our analysis's performance with respect to the data generated by such processes provides an indirect test, such testing does not permit us to focus on any such specific assumption - the model may fail because other assumptions are inappropriate. And to this point, our justification for A10 is that it is a reasonable extension to the particular problem at hand of bargaining process theory encapsulated by bargaining set theory for cooperative Ai-person games in a context (transferable utility games) in which that theory yields predictions corresponding to the predictions of competing ideas (the main-simple V-set and the competitive solution). What we want to do in this section is provide, via some laboratory experimentation, a bit more confidence in our assumption; thus, we turn to an experimental test of the necessary and sufficient conditions for system and resource stability.4 Here we describe the design of an experimental "balance-of-power" game that we use to test three specific hypotheses about our theory. Section 4.6 reports our data and Section 4.7 offers the instructions read to subjects. Before proceeding, however, a note of caution is in order about how we interpret these experiments. We emphasize that they are not simulations nor are they designed to test the theory, although extreme departures from predictions would certainly be cause for alarm. Our experimental design is not equipped, for example, to accommodate the fact that countries are collectives we have abstractly chosen to treat as a single decision-making entity, because in the experiments we report, the role of countries isfilledby single individuals. Thus, we cannot test the veracity of this anthropomorphic assumption or the effects on our predictions of national decisions being controlled by a collectivity governed by rules of their own creation. Instead, these experiments are designed merely to see if we can have any confidence in a small part of our analysis - Assumption A10 and its implications for bargaining. The experiments use undergraduates at the University of Texas at Austin as subjects. Each experiment begins by randomly assigning numbers to the subjects after seating them face to face at a large conference table. 4
This section and the experimental results we report are taken from Niou and Ordeshook (1988).
4.5 Some experimental evidence
133
The rules of the experiment are as follows: the experimenter begins by revealing to all subjects how 300 divisible and transferable points are initially divided among them, where this division is determined beforehand by the random assignment. Subjects are told that an experiment ends when there is unanimous agreement on the part of the active players (those with positive points) to do so; hence, the duration of an experiment is endogenous (each lasted between one and two hours). 5 Each subject's final dollar payoff from participating is determined by the points he or she controls at the termination of the experiment. To ensure that subjects are motivated solely by the resources they control rather than by, say, the desire to extract as much money as possible from the experimenter, at the end of the experiment each subject converts the points he or she controls at that time into money according to an exchange rate specified in a sealed envelope. Exchange rates differ among subjects, and although everyone is aware of this fact, no one knows his or her own exchange rate or the rate of anyone else. Thus, the dollar value of 10 points depends on which subject controls those points. Also, to minimize the possibility that equity considerations distort the preferences we seek to induce, no discussion of schemes for dividing money after the termination of the experiment is allowed. Each subject is paid in secret, so there is no need for one subject to ever learn how much others earned. The average net payoff to each subject in an experiment was six dollars (no subject was allowed to lose money). An especially critical issue concerns how subjects secure points from others, since here experimental methodologies are fraught with difficulty. On the one hand, we must ensure that subjects play the game addressed by our theory. On the other hand, there is the danger that subjects are so constrained that it is impossible for them to act contrary to the hypotheses under consideration. Since this is the first test of this particular model, we are concerned more with the first consideration than the second, and we proceed under the supposition that if subjects do not act as predicted when constrained, it is unlikely that they would act in accordance with the model when the various rules are wholly endogenous. First, then, in order to secure points from another subject, we require for the allocation resources that one or more of the subjects make a threat that proposes to take all or part of the points held by one or more other players. Those who attempt to expropriate points are called the Attack Group; those who are their target, the Target Group. A threat must satisfy three 5
Although an experiment must end, in actual political processes, of course, there is no end to the game. We are uncertain about the effects of this feature of the experiment, and follow-up research might consider a procedure in which the experiment is terminated at a time unknown to the subjects.
134
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
conditions: (1) it must specify how many points are to be taken away and from whom (the Target Group); (2) it must specify how the points are to be distributed among members of the Attack Group; and (3) the Attack Group must outweigh the Target Group. Our theory presumes that the Target Group can thwart an attack if it can formulate an appropriate counterthreat. In accordance with our definitions, our experimental procedures must allow for two types of counterthreats: Type 1: A proposal by one or more members of the Target Group to give points to some other player or players who are not in the Target Group and that was agreed to by those player (s). Type 2: A new threat, by any subset of the Target Group, that either (i) threatens all members of the original Attack Group, or (ii) includes one or more members of the original Attack Group in the new Attack Group. A Type 2 counterthreat replaces the old threat as the current threat and current threats that are not countered are implemented. The actual bargaining in each experiment uses both informal and formal negotiation procedures. Subjects can freely discuss alternative possibilities among themselves, including the possibility of formulating threats and counters. However, before any reallocation of resources is realized before a player is forced to relinquish points or is eliminated from the game - a threat (or counterthreat) must be made formally byfillingout a 3x5 card that records the distribution of resources among the members of the relevant coalition and that contains the signatures of the members of that coalition. To accommodate our assumption that countries prefer receiving points freely rather than by initiating an attack (Assumption A6), subjects are told that if they receive points because a threat is not countered then those in the Attack Group are charged a fee of two dollars. Also, to accommodate the assumption that if one coalition attacks another then those who are not party to the attack can secure resources from the Attack Group as well (Assumption A7), subjects are informed that members of the Attack Group will be awarded 80% of the points in their proposal (at a fee of two dollars for each member in the group), whereas subjects who are neither in the Attack nor in the Target Group will divide the remaining 20% of the points in the proposal, in proportion to their weight. Subjects who are left with no points are removed from the game. To illustrate these rules with a numerical example, suppose the initial distribution is (100,80,60,30,30). Players 2 and 3 could then threaten players 4 and 5, proposing to divide their gains evenly. If there are no
4.5 Some experimental evidence
135
counters to this threat, then 2 and 3 are awarded 80% of 4 and 5's total 24 points each if their agreement is to divide the spoils evenly - and player 1 is awarded 20%, or 12 points. The result is that players 4 and 5 are removed from the game, the new distribution (112,104,84) is established, and players 2 and 3 are each charged a fee of two dollars. Alternatively, players 4 and 5 might counter with the proposal that they each give 10 points to player 1. If this offer is accepted, then no fees are charged and the distribution (120,80,60,20,20) results. Or, 4 and 5 might counter with a proposal that they, in coalition with 1 or 3, attack 2. If 1 or 3 agrees to this proposal, then it becomes the new current threat. Finally, suppose 1 and 2 attack 3. Notice that 3 cannot counter with an attack on 4 since this leaves the coalition of 1 and 2 unchallenged. But 3 could propose that he and 1 or he and 2 attack someone else. We report here on a total of 15 experiments: seven 5-person games and eight 6-person games. The data generated by these experiments are presented in Section 4.6. Notice that if a subject proposes a Type 1 counter, or if a threat is uncountered, then the initial distribution of points changes and subsequent negotiations must take this new distribution as the status quo (until the distribution is changed again). Each such new distribution, then, can be thought of as a starting point for a new experiment. Hence, Section 4.6 describes the exact sequence of threats, counterthreats, and new starting points for each experiment. Also, "*" denotes a player who has been eliminated, and the points held by inessential players are identified in italic. Aside from the prediction that no player should become predominant, our theory yields several hypotheses with respect to this data, which we can summarize as follows: HI. H2. H3. H4.
No essential player should be eliminated. No essential player should be rendered inessential. Inessential players should be eliminated. No inessential player should become essential.
Looking first at the six experiments with no inessential players (experiments 1, 4, 5, 7, 9, and 11), notice that, except for player 4 in game 5, no player is eliminated. Indeed, if we take the 18 initial or new distributions in which no player is inessential, this is the sole instance of an essential player's elimination. This elimination can be attributed to that subject's refusal to counter a threat against her. When asked afterwards why she did this, she reported that she was angered by the attitude of several of the male subjects and decided to quit playing the game. In fact, if we look at all 31 initial or new distributions, this is the sole instance of the elimination of an essential player. Hypothesis HI, then, appears to be
136
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
well supported by the data. Similarly, Hypothesis H2 is also well supported: although there were proposals to the contrary, no essential player was ever rendered inessential. The support for Hypothesis H3, on the other hand, is more ambiguous. Looking at the experiments with at least one inessential player in the initial distribution (experiments 2, 3, 6, 8, 10, 12, 13, 14, and 15), only 7 of the 13 such players were ultimately eliminated. And if we count each new distribution as a separate experiment, then only 7 of 17 inessential players were eliminated (alternatively, we could say that of 16 initial or new distributions, 5 yielded the elimination of an inessential player). Of course, we could defend Hypothesis H3 with the argument that more inessential players would have been eliminated if the experiments had been allowed to continue, and indeed this possibility is suggested by the striking fact that no inessential player ever gained points. Aside from a simple counting of eliminations, however, the comparison of essential and inessential players is interesting. We might speculate that the seven eliminations of inessential players can be explained more simply by factors not captured by our theory and by the fact that such players had so few points. Notice, though, that subjects with low points are not necessarily inessential, and that when they are essential they are not eliminated. For example, the initial distribution in experiments 9 and 11 is (70,10,10,70,70,70), so that players 2 and 3 (who were essential) have only 10 points each. Experiment 14 offers a similar example. The initial distribution there is (70,15,70,70, 5,70); nevertheless, player 2 with 15 points is essential. Yet, in experiment 9, players 2 and 3 are included twice in a counterthreat; in experiment 11, three times; and player 2 in experiment 14 is included in a counter three times, which suggests that these players are not eliminated because, in accordance with A10, they are valuable in the threat-counterthreat negotiation process. Ambiguity also pervades the data with respect to Hypothesis H4: Of the 17 players who are inessential in an initial or new distribution, 5 such players become essential (experiments 2, 3, and 6). What is interesting to note, however, is that in every such instance, the player is rendered essential while losing points because some essential player gains sufficiently to put them at or near 150. Indeed, it is not altogether clear whether H4 is in fact implied by our theory. This hypothesis is based on the supposition that inessential players will be eliminated first, but our theory does not specify when an essential player will counter a threat with a new threat or will counter by rendering another country near-predominant, thereby freezing the system. And in the event that one country is rendered nearpredominant, all countries, including previously inessential ones, become essential. Our experimental data, then, suggest an important empirical
4.5 Some experimental evidence
137
possibility that does not appear to be without historical precedent: the competition among "major" powers leads to the emergence of a nearpredominant power, in which case "marginal" powers become relevant to balancing the threat of the potential hegemon. Regardless of how we interpret the data with respect to H4, it is important to keep in mind that we should not anticipate a perfect match between experimental data and theoretical predictions. Our subjects are "inexperienced players," and may be more prone to strategic error and to missed opportunities than their counterparts in ongoing political systems. The deviations from H3 and H4 merely alert us to the fact that this volume's theorems and remarks are not "iron-hand, immutable natural laws" - the uncertainties that pervade our understanding of individual decision making, as well as our measurement of preferences and perceptions, can redirect events away from theoretical predictions. The point that warrants emphasis, though, is that we can reject the supposition that the final outcomes will entail a minimum winning coalition expropriating all from the losers. The option of a minimal majority expropriating everything from a maximal minority is available to our subjects, and indeed such proposals permeate our experiments (see, e.g., Game 1, in which every threat is such a proposal). Nevertheless, our data demonstrate clearly that if subjects are cognizant of a dominant player's ability to expropriate all resources, then system stability prevails. Indeed, not only are essential players not eliminated, but six experiments end not with the maximal expropriation from a maximal minority but rather with a resource transfer rendering one subject near-predominant (experiments 1, 2, 3, 4, 7, and 11). For further insight into the mechanics of this equilibration process, notice that all experiments ended with one or more persons transferring points to others so as to reach a unanimous agreement to terminate. Thus, in effect experiments ended with Type 1 counters as against Type 2 counters, which a myopic constant-sum cooperative game model of international processes implies. Notice also that if a country is essential and if it confronts a threat, then we anticipate observing it countering by ceding resources to some country or by proposing a viable counter threat. On the other hand, if a country is inessential then it does not have enough resources to avert elimination, nor is its inclusion in any coalition essential to the formation of a viable counterthreat. With this in mind, consider Table 4.1, which shows the number and types of threats that inessential and essential players confront, the number of times they are included in a Type 1 or Type 2 counter, and the number of eliminations. Briefly, inessential players successfully countered threats 13 times, but in no instance was a Type 2 counter employed - counters always required that the inessential
138
4 Resource stability/ and the balance of power
Table 4.1.
Threat Type 1 Counter Type 2 Counter Elimination
Inessential
Essential
30 13 0 7
76 23 52 1
player cede points. Thus, it appears that subjects recognized that inessential players did not have enough points to ensure stability via participation in viable counterthreats. It also appears that essential players are content to slowly "bleed" an inessential participant - the fact that they could not participate in a Type 2 counterthreat explains why no inessential player ever gained any points. Essential players, however, use Type 2 counterthreats more frequently than Type 1 counters. In the case of essential players, our theory does not state which type of counter should be observed more frequently. The "first instinct" of subjects, however, is to counter a threat with a new threat, and a Type 1 counter seems to be an action "of last resort," an action taken when no other players are willing to join in the formation of a Type 2 counter. Thus, it is not surprising to learn that Type 2 counters are more prevalent than Type 1 counters, which serves to emphasize the argument thatflexibilityin alliance systems is an essential component of the operation of balance-of-power processes. (Generally, a Type 1 counter is used by an essential player to ensure stability when a threat to divide all the points evenly by a two-member attacking group was initiated or when it seemed the easiest route to ending the experiment.) In summary, a static one-period view of anarchic international processes that are characterized by a transferable measure of resources and value implies that system stability is impossible, because some minimal winning coalition will form to eliminate all other players. However, if we take a more dynamical view and if we assume that each country seeks to maximize its resources or proportion thereof, subject to the constraint that its survival is not threatened in the future, then system stability is possible and the resource instability that characterizes constant-sum nperson games takes a more limited form. Our experimental results support this argument, and in particular they support the bargaining assumptions summarized by A10. This does not prove, of course, that the processes of real international systems correspond to our model or that we cannot design experiments to support some alternative bargaining assumption.
4.6 Appendix A: Experimental data
139
Decision makers in international affairs are much more sophisticated than the subjects of our experiments, and reality is far more complicated than the scenario confronted by our subjects. Yet the intent of these experiments is not to show that our model describes reality, but only that if the conditions presumed to operate in our model do in fact operate then anarchic international systems do not necessarily lead to instability and the elimination of essential players. And if our subjects can respond to the strategic imperatives our model purports to represent, and if our model captures an essential part of reality, then it is reasonable to suppose that more sophisticated decision makers respond to those imperatives as well.
4.6
Appendix A: Experimental data Player
Game 1
New
End
Game 2 End
Game 3
New New
End
Game 4 New New
End
6
Description
1
2
3
4
5
Type of Counter
60 100 0 40 0 80 0 23
60 0 90 100 130 0 150 150
60 0 90 60 90 120 150 60
60 100 0 40 80 0 0 23
60 100 120 60 0 100 0 43
Initial distribution 1,4,5 threaten 2,3 2,3,5 threaten 1,4 1,4 cede 40 points to 2 2,3,4 threaten 1,5 1,3,5 threaten 2,4 2,3 threaten 1,4,5 1,4,5 cede 50 points to 2
20 0 10
60 0 40
60 150 60
60 0 40
100 150 150
Initial distribution 3,5 threaten 1,2,4 1,2,4 cede 50 points to 5
IT 1
30 50 0 20 0 15 50 0 100 0 12
30 50 0 20 0 15 50 0 100 0 13
80 0 150 120 150 140 0 60 100 150 150
80 104 0 60 0 50 90 120 0 0 45
80 96 150 80 150 80 110 120 0 150 80
Initial distribution 1,2,4 threaten 3 3,5 threaten 1,2,4 1,2,4 cede 40 points to 3 3,5 threaten 1,2,4 1,2,4 cede 20 points to 3 1,2,4,5 threaten 3 3,4,5 threaten 1,2 1,2,3 threaten 4,5 3,5 threaten 1,2,4 1,2,4 cede 10 points to 3
IT 2 1 IT 1 IT 2 2 2 1
60 0 50 90 50 82 106 0 40
60 0 50 90 50 82 0 0 40
60 100 60 0 35 68 0 75 35
60 100 60 0 35 68 52 75 35
60 100 80 120 130 0 142 150 150
Initial distribution 3,4,5 threaten 1,2 1,2 cede 20 points to 5 1,2,5 threaten 3,4 3,4 cede 50 points to 5 1,2,3,4 threaten 5 1,5 threaten 2,3 3,4,5 threaten 1,2 1,2 cede 20 points to 5
IT 1 IT 1 IT 2 2 1
initial threat (IT) 2 1 IT 2 2 2
140
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
Appendix A (cont.) Player
Game 5
End
Game 6 End
Game 7
New
New End
Game 8
New New
End
Game 9
New End
Game 10
Description
Type of Counter
60 0 0 66
Initial distribution 1,2,4 threaten 3,5 1,3,4 threaten 2,5 2,3 threaten 4, 4 quits
IT 2 1
80 0 58
30 0 11
Initial distribution 1,3 threaten 2,4,5 2,4,5 cede 60 points to 3
IT 1
60 78 0 80 0 60 69 66 100 0 30 0 25
60 72 100 140 150 60 69 66 100 0 30 0 25
60 0 100 0 75 61 108 0 100 100 61 0 40
Initial distribution 2,3 threaten 5 1,4,5 threaten 2,3 2,3,4 threaten 1,5 1,4,5 threaten 2,3 2 cedes 1 point to 5 3,4,5 threaten 1,2 1,2 threaten 5 3,4,5 threaten 1,2 1,2,5 threaten 3,4 3,4 cede 60 points to 2 1,2 threaten 3,4,5 3,4,5 cede 31 points to 2
IT 2 2 2 1 IT 2 2 2 1 IT 1
60 100 0 80 0 68 60 61 100 150 61
60 100 150 0 75 61 70 71 0 75 71
60 0 90 120 0 61 60 61 100 0 56
40 0 60 100 150 42 40 46 0 75 56
20 0 0 0 0 0 10 0 * * *
Initial distribution 1,2,3 threaten 4,5,6 3,4,5 threaten 1,2,6 2,4,5 threaten 1,3,6 1,3,5 threaten 2,4,6 1,2 threaten 6 6 cedes 10 points to 3 5 threatens 6, 6 quits 1,2,4 threaten 3,5 2,3,5 threaten 1,4 1,4 cede 10 points to 5
IT 2 2 2 2 1 IT IT 2 1
70 0 100 0 75 150 0 75 96 70 120 90
10 15 0 20 0 25 50 75 0 8 30 20
10 15 0 20 0 25 38 75 0 8 30 20
70 75 100 0 75 0 106 0 75 70 120 90
70 75 100 120 0 100 0 75 74 70 0 40
70 105 0 140 150 0 106 0 75 74 0 40
Initial distribution 2,6 threaten 1 1,4,5 threaten 2,3,6 2,3,5,6 threaten 1,4 1,4,6 threaten 2,3,5 1,2,3,5 threaten 4,6 2,3,4,6 threaten 1,5 1,2,3,5 threaten 4,6 1,4,6 threaten 2,3 2,3 cede 4 points to 6 1,2,3,4 threaten 5,6 5,6 cede 64 points to 1,2,3,4
IT 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 1 IT 1
60 75 120 0
40 0 60 100
60 75 120 0
20 0 0 0
60 75 0 100
60 75 0 100
Initial distribution 1,3,5,6 threaten 2,4 1,2,3 threaten 4,5,6 2,5,6 threaten 1,3,4
IT 2 2
1
2
3
4
5
60 100 120 66
60 100 0 84
60 0 60 84
60 100 120 0
80 150 80
30 0 11
80 150 140
60 72 100 0 75 60 54 109 0 100 60 150 60
60 78 0 80 0 59 0 59 0 100 119 150 150
60 100 0 0 75 68 60 61 100 0 56
6
4.6 Appendix A: Experimental data
141
Appendix A (cont.) Player
New New End
Game 11
End
Game 12 New End
Game 13 New
End
Game 14
End
Game 15 New New
End
5
6
Description
Type of Counter
0 0 18 0 10 0
150 0 55 56 55 56
0 60 60 61 60 61
1,3,5 threaten 2,4,6 1,3,6 threaten 2,4,5 2,4,5 cede 10 points to 3 2 threatens 4 4 cedes 8 points to 1 2 threatens 4, 4 quits
2 2 1 IT 1 IT
10 0 21 0 40 0 35 10
70 75 0 100 130 0 80 70
70 75 86 100 0 100 0 30
70 75 86 0 90 100 0 30
Initial distribution 1,4,5,6 threaten 2,3 1,2,3,5,6 threaten 4 1,4,5 threaten 2,3,6 2,3,4,6 threaten 1,5 1,5,6 threaten 2,3,4 1,2,3,4 threaten 5,6 5,6 cede 80 points to 1
IT 2 2 2 2 2 1
20 0 * *
20 0 * *
80 100 0 80
20 0 * *
80 100 150 110
Initial distribution 1,4,6 threaten 2,3,5 1,6 threaten 4 4 cedes 20 points to 1,6
IT 2 1
60 61 100 0 80 0 100 63
40 56 100 0 80 0 100 58
60 61 100 150 0 75 100 63
60 61 0 75 140 150 0 58
20 0 * * * * *
60 61 0 75 0 75 0 58
Initial distribution 2 threatens 5, 5 quits 1,2,3 threaten 4,6 3,4,6 threaten 1,2 1,2,4 threaten 3,6 3,4,6 threaten 1,2 1,2,3 threaten 4,5,6 4,6 cede 4 points to 1,2,3
IT IT 2 2 2 2 1
70 75 100 120 0 100 0 0 50 100 0 50
15 0 100 0 60 100 0 50 100 150 0 8
70 75 100 0 100 0 75 150 0 0 100 80
70 75 0 90 140 0 75 100 150 0 100 80
5 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 2
70 75 0 90 0 100 150 0 0 50 100 80
Initial distribution 1,3,4,6 threaten 2,5 1,2,3 threaten 4,5,6 1,4,6 threaten 2,3,5 2,3,4 threaten 1,5,6 1,2,6 threaten 3,4,5 3,4,6 threaten 1,2,5 2,3,4 threaten 1,5,6 1,2,4 threaten 3,5,6 1,2,6 threaten 3,4,5 3,4,6 threaten 1,2,5 1,2,5 cede 90 points to 3,4,6
IT 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 1
60 62 70 71 0 60 150 71
60 61 60 61 80 120 0 60
60 61 60 61 80 120 0 60
50 58 50 51 70 0 75 52
50 58 50 56 70 0 75 57
20 0 10 0 * * * *
Initial distribution 4,5 threaten 6 6 cedes 10 points to 1 5 threatens 6, 6 quits 2,3,4,5 threaten 1 1,2,3 threaten 4,5 1,4,5 threaten 2,3 2,3 cede 2 points to 4,5
IT 1 IT IT 2 2 1
1
2
3
75 120 60 61 68 69
0 0 37 51 37 43
75 120 70 71 70 71
70 75 86 100 0 100 150 150
10 0 21 0 40 0 35 10
80 100 150 110
4
142
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
4.7
Appendix B: Instructions read to subjects
This experiment is designed to model various aspects of conflict, and the amount of money you earn here depends on how carefully you listen to instructions and how well you play the game. The experiment begins by dividing 300 points among you. The precise nature of this division has been predetermined, and it is not necessarily an equal division. Some of you will start with more points than others. At the end of the experiment, each of you can convert the points you have at that time into money according to an exchange rate specified in the sealed envelope before you. Like the initial distribution of points, these rates vary from player to player. Although you cannot open your envelopes until the experiment ends, let me assure that these rates are positive: Thefinalmonetary payoff each of you receives increases as the number of points that you control increases. Notice that although each of your exchange rates is unknown to you, everyone will always know the current distribution of points among you. An important rule concerns how points are secured from other players, which is the only way to increase the points in your possession. First, one or more of you must propose a threat that takes all or part of the points held by one or more other players. I will call those who are attempting to expropriate points the Attacking Group and those who are their target the Target group. I will consider giving those points to the Attacking Group provided that the threat satisfies two conditions: First, the Attacking Group must identify itself and indicate on one of the slips of paper in front of you: (i) how many points are being taken and from whom, and (ii) how those points will be distributed after they are taken. Second, the total points presently held by the Attacking Group must exceed the total number of points held by the Target Group. That is, only bigger coalitions can attack smaller coalitions. Calling this the Current Threat, I will then entertain counteroffers. There are two types of counters. The first is a proposal by one or more members of the target group to voluntarily give points to players who are not being attacked. These other players may or may not include members of the Attacking Group. In the event of such a counter, I will exchange the points as agreed to, recompute the distribution of points among you, and then let negotiations continue by opening the floor to new threats and counters. The second type of counter is a new threat by a new Attacking Group that includes some, but not necessarily all, of the old Target Group. This new Attack Group must either threaten the members of the old Attack Group or it must induce at least one such member to join the new Attack Group. In this event, the counter will replace the old threat as the Current Threat, and I will entertain counters to it.
4.8 Appendix C: Proofs of results
143
Notice that by these rules, if anyone secures over half the points, it is impossible to counter any threat that this person might make. So such a player can secure all the points in the game. Now if neither type of counter is made or otherwise agreed to in response to a threat, I will award the points to the Attacking Group as specified in the Current Threat, but with two provisos: (1) Those who are neither in the Attacking Group nor in the Target Group will divide, according to their current relative points, 20 percent of the points being expropriated from the Target Group. Those who have made the uncountered threat will divide the remaining 80 percent as specified in their agreement; and (2) I will charge each person receiving points a fee of $2.00. At this stage, I will again recompute the distribution of points among you and if any of you are left with no points, you will be removed from the game. Those so removed will be paid $2.00 for their participation. The experiment will end when there is unanimous consent to terminate, and you will then be permitted to open your envelopes to see the exchange rate converting points into money. Each of you will be paid in cash the appropriate amount, subtracting any necessary fees for your actions. 4.8
Appendix C: Proofs of results Theorem 4.1
Consider CeW, so that S—C$W. From the definition of v,
v(C) + v(S- C) = r(C) + ( ^ \
2
ieC
ieC
or v(C) + v(S— C) = R — e + e = R> which defines a constant-sum transferable utility game in characteristic function form. It is well known that such games have no cores if they are essential - if there exist two disjoint subsets of S, say C" and C", such that v(C') + v(C") < v(C'UC"). It is straightforward to see from the definition of v(C) that this game is essential (namely, let C" and C" be losing coalitions, but let C'UC" be winning). Note, incidentally, that if rt = R/2, the game is still constant-sum, but it is now inessential and thus it has a core - the original distribution of resources. Q.E.D. Theorem 4.2 Theorem 4.2 implies that winning coalitions will change the resource distribution unless one country controls R/2, in which case no such coalition
144
4 Resource stability and the balance of power
will form. Suppose to the contrary that rj = r7- for all j . If the winning coalition C forms then - from the definition of v(C) and the fact that regardless of whether we use a solution concept such as the main-simple Vset, the competitive solution, or the strong bargaining set - r' must be Pareto optimal and feasible for C: jeC
But since rj = rj for all j , this equality becomes R r . — = max[r / ], which is impossible since rt
Q.E.D.
Theorem 4.3 Consider a minimal winning coalition C of which /* is a member. From the definition of v(C), it must be that v(C)+/J/2, where equality holds if /* is the largest member of C. Thus, for example, if /* is the largest country, and if it attains R/2 resources through the alliance-formation process in any minimal winning coalition, then the incremental benefit to its partners must sum to zero. And if /* is any smaller country, the incremental benefit to its partners must sum to some negative quantity; otherwise, C is getting more than its value. Furthermore, since /* must (from the property of main-simple V-sets noted earlier) get at least R/2 in every minimal winning coalition of which it is a member, this constraint on the summed resources of its partners must hold for every such coalition. That is, letting rj be what country j gets if it is included in a minimal winning coalition that forms to yield a resource rt-tuple in a main-simple V-set: r / < 0 for all Ce W* when rf > y . Suppose that the maximum payoff to each partner j of i*eC is rj. But again, from the properties of a main-simple V-set, j must receive rj from every coalition in which /* is a partner. Consider now all those minimal winning coalitions that exclude /* and suppose that the maximum payoff to j when it is a member of any one of these coalitions is rj*. Again, though, rj* = rj. But this means that if any coalition C** forms that excludes /*, it cannot get more for its members than they can get individually if they join /* to yield a resource distribution in V. Thus, the previous inequality implies that
4.8 Appendix C: Proofs of results
145
However, except for the case in which /* has R/2 resources to begin with, v(C**) > /*(C**), contradicting the fact that if r** is in a main-simple Vset then it must be Pareto optimal for C**. Hence, if /* begins with less than R/2, no resource distribution in the main-simple V-set gives /* the amount R/2. Q.E.D.
CHAPTER 5
Preventive war
What made the [Peloponnesian] war inevitable was the growth of Athenian power and the fear which this caused in Sparta. Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War (trans. Warner 1954, p. 49)
The great wars of history - we have had a world war about every hundred years for the last four centuries - are the outcome, direct or indirect, of the unequal growth of nations. Halford J. Mackinder, Democratic Ideals and Reality (1962, pp. 1-2)
Whether to invest in additional power resources or to consume some of those that have been accumulated is a perennial issue of foreign policy. Many of the most important choices governments face have to do with the relative weight given to consumption.. .versus investment, and with devising strategies for action that are both viable in the short run and capable of achieving wealth and power objectives in the long run. Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony (1984, p. 24)
Intuition and a considerable theoretical and empirical literature concur with Thucydides' assertion that the cause of international conflict lies as much with differential growth rates in resources as with the relative power or resources countries enjoy at any specific point in time. Hence, conflicts might not be attributable wholly to some current "imbalance" in military position, but also to the projections of future imbalances and to a corresponding perception by some that only a preventive war can guarantee their security.1 Indeed, so compelling is the threat of imbalance owing to the growth of some potential adversary, that even domestic constraints on aggressive action and sentiments for peace can be quickly swept aside. As forcefully argued by McNeill (1982, p. 309): Presumably, as long as sovereign states exist, whenever one of them seems to be growing so powerful as to threaten the continued independence of the others, 1
A great number of sources can be cited for the hypothesis of preventive war, but for a comprehensive general survey, see Levy (1987). 146
5 Preventive war
147
everything tending to encourage hostility to the potential hegemonical power finds congenial conditions within the states that feel threatened. Rapid changes of mood and popular sympathy can and do occur under such circumstances, forming and dissolving alliances in a matter of a few weeks or months. Contrary intentions and conflicting ideals prevailed only when no pressing external threats provoked balance-of-power behavior. This view of international conflict is reflected also in contemporary public debates over, say, domestic versus defense spending and the issue of whether a country should invest resources to maximize economic growth rather than appropriating those resources to maximize current military strength. Kennedy (1987, pp. 539-40) identifies the dilemma clearly in his commentary on contemporary international affairs: To be a Great Power.. .demands a flourishing economic base Yet by going to war, or by devouring a large share of the nation's "manufacturing power" to expenditures upon "unproductive" armaments, one runs the risk of eroding the national economic base, especially vis-a-vis states which are concentrating a greater share of their income upon productive investment for long-term growth Ideally, of course, "profit" and "power" should go hand in hand. Far too often, however, statesmen found themselves confronted with the usual dilemma: between buying military security, at a time of real or perceived danger... or keeping defense expenditures low, but finding one's interests sometimes threatened by the actions of other states The present large Powers... are thus compelled to grapple .. .with the uneven pattern of economic growth, which causes some of them to become wealthier (and usually stronger), relative to others; and... [with the necessity] to choose between a more immediate military security and a longer-term economic security. This debate and contemporary scholarship concerning the issue of "consumption now" versus "greater consumption later" show why a simple static analysis based on some current distribution of national resources or power cannot capture all relevant aspects of balance-of-power reasoning in particular and the causes of war in general. In response, this chapter extends our analysis to include the possibility that the resources that measure a country's capabilities are not static. In so doing, we contest the supposition that a conceptualization of international processes based on "balance of power" is necessarily distinct from one based on "power transition." Indeed, the extension we seek is natural to our analysis, because we assume that decision makers judge coalitions and resource reallocations in terms of future as well as immediate consequences. After all, it is presumably the anticipation of some type of future imbalance and the decisions it implies that leads to preventive war, and we already have adopted the view that national leaders are forwardlooking, that they choose actions in anticipation of what others will do in response to their current decisions. Moreover, the concept of system
148
5 Preventive war
stability seems to define precisely the imbalance that should concern decision makers. The literature recognizes, of course, that the relative resources or power of nations change for various reasons, and that even if we focus exclusively on those resources relevant to the measure of military power, such as technological sophistication and agricultural production, some countries may simply possess advantages of climate, geography, and the like that yield greater growth rates than other countries. To the extent, though, that the same literature offers national leaders only the options of warring or acquiescing to a dominant power, it is inconsistent with the idea that they can also respond to power imbalances by trying to augment their resources. The possibility revealed in the quotation from Keohane that introduces this chapter means that growth rates may vary for endogenous reasons: countries may simply choose to invest their resources differently, with some preferring to invest in the future via additional expenditures on research, education, and a general strengthening of the economy, whereas others act to increase current resources at the expense of the future by way of contemporaneous military hardware expenditures. Spending billions on the procurement of, say, a particular aircraft increases current military preparedness, but at the expense of future resources to the extent that this procurement detracts from expenditures on research and development or on the general strengthening of the economy. Hence, we extend our model in two ways. Taking the idea that growth is a function of both exogenous factors (geography, climate, availability of natural resources) and endogenous factors (vitality of the economy, trade, share of the budget directed to military procurement), we begin by supposing that each country is confronted with an exogenously determined growth rate, which it cannot control. However, we also assume that this rate applies only to those resources countries invest toward the future. As part of a sequential cooperative and noncooperative game, they can vary their current and future military capabilities by choosing the amount of resources to be invested. Since only the proportion invested is subject to growth at the exogenously determined rate, decision makers thereby determine the overall rate at which resources grow. In our extended model, then, national leaders do more than simply try to anticipate future events and choose whether or not to engage in a preventive war. Through alternative investment decisions, they also affect the future. Naturally, in choosing their investments and in deciding whether to engage in a preventive war, they must also anticipate the anticipations of others, the actions of others based on those anticipations, and so on, with the understanding that everyone is doing the same. To learn the con-
5 Preventive war 149 ditions under which countries can invest and maintain their sovereignty, and when they might contemplate a preventive war because they cannot do so, our analysis describes the necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of system and resource stability in this interactive, dynamical setting. Our objective, however, is not merely to extend a particular abstract formulation. It is to answer some specific substantive questions about the preconditions for and nature of preventive wars. The literature on such wars, beginning with Thucydides' observation, provides the perspective for the questions we raise. With respect to definitions, Brodie (1973) defines a preventive war as one in which a country undertakes "to destroy an already strong rival whose power one fears may grow faster than one's own." Fay's (1938) definition is "the waging of war upon a neighbor while he is still weak... to prevent his growing stronger " Implicit in all such definitions is the assumption that preventive wars are not waged simply because some country or coalition acts to take advantage of a current imbalance in the distribution of resources. Rather, preventive wars are designed to overcome a perceived future resource deficit. This view that preventive wars are initiated by a stronger state against an adversary that threatens to grow stronger, however, is not universally accepted. For example, Organski and Kugler (1980), citing Germany and Japan, speculate that the rising power initiates the war. More generally, they observe that "before the nuclear age the great powers, although far stronger than the middle and small powers and very much involved in the diplomatic interchanges that preceded wars, were not the initiators of major wars. They fought when others decided to fight" (p. 56). This dispute reveals the theoretical vacuum that characterizes the debate. It is probably rare for the economic and military capabilities of all countries to grow in wholly parallel fashion, and national capabilities, however measured, almost certainly intersect frequently whenever graphed on a time line (for the case of the great powers of Europe between 1871 and 1914, see Figure 7.1 in Chapter 7). Yet, not all of these positional changes yield preventive wars. Correspondingly, Organski and Kugler suggest that we ought to look solely at the two major contenders: "The fundamental problem that sets the whole system sliding almost irretrievably toward war is the differences in rates of growth among the great powers and, of particular importance, the differences in rates between the dominant nation and the challenger that permit the latter to overtake the former in power" (1980, p. 61). Earlier, however, they observe that "If one looks at the point at which conflicts begin in relation to the point at which the trajectories of the challenger and the dominant nation intersect, it is
150 5 Preventive war clear that conflicts occur after the intersection when the two nations fight alone... but before the coalition of the challenger overtakes the coalition of the dominant country... [which] seems a curious pattern" (p. 60). The notion of system stability, however, offers a view that makes this fact less curious: it is not relative position per se, but whether growth or decline undermines system stability by rendering countries inessential. Quite naturally, then, our theory forces us away from analyzing the situation from the perspective of two countries in isolation, and toward viewing matters from the perspective of complete international systems. Similarly, with respect to the issue of who attacks first and to whether distinctions between preventive wars and preemptive attacks are readily discerned, suppose that there is no uncertainty and thus no possibility of miscalculation or accident; additionally, suppose that all aspects of the situation - growth rates, current resources, etc. - are common knowledge (everyone knows these parameters, everyone knows that everyone knows them, etc.). In this instance, not only is the "declining power" (say A) capable of foreseeing the consequences of its decline if it fails to respond, but those consequences are known to the rising power (say B) as well; and if A concludes that its dominant strategy is to initiate a preventive war, then B also knows this and can respond before A acts - either by offering to bargain away some part of its future advantage so as to dissuade A from attack, by establishing alliances that render it secure until its resources have grown sufficiently, or by launching a "preemptive preventive war" on its own. Thus, even at this level of the analysis, we cannot say who will attack first or, indeed, whether there will be an attack. However, matters can be even more complicated still. If B prefers a preemptive preventive war, then A should know this and can respond with a "preventive preemptive preventive" war; however, B should know that A knows this, and so forth and so on, so that the spiral of conjectural variation continues backward forever. Unless we supply additional structure in the form, for example, of assumptions about bargaining opportunities, about the advantages of different types of attacks, about uncertainty, or about violations of the common-knowledge assumption, we can rationalize any proposition as to who attacks first merely by terminating our conjectural thinking at an appropriate point. That people can anticipate the actions of others, that they will anticipate the anticipation of others, and so on, blurs the theoretical distinctions between preventive and preemptive conflict, so that, regardless of the labels we give to players who choose particular acts, preventive and preemptive attacks must both be understood in the context of the same theoretical structure. Furthermore, unless we elaborate our analysis to include such matters as a specification of the strategic complexity decision makers can
5 Preventive war
151
accommodate, the relative advantages of offensive versus defensive capabilities, and the advantages of first versus second moves, then it is unlikely that we can resolve unambiguously whether the presumed conditions for preventive war imply a preventive strike by a declining power or a preemptive attack by the rising power. In this context, then, we find the source of much of the confusion in the identity of the aggressor in some wars. 2 Was Germany the culprit in World War I with its seeming overzealousness in military expenditures, or was Russia the instigator with its early mobilization? Later, in Chapters 6 and 8, we suggest that Russia's actions and Germany's preemptive thrust into Belgium followed a clear logic dictated by the dynamics of the general resources of the European powers. However, with national leaders able to anticipate the anticipatory moves of others in a game we can only imperfectly model, it can never be clear who has the last move and who has the first. Thus, the distinction between preventive and preemptive actions is more a verbal convenience that helps us summarize general strategic considerations than it is a rigorous theoretical construct. This discussion of the possibility that people might anticipate the actions of others raises additional issues, including the possibility that the growing power, B, might choose to negotiate away its potential advantage so as to avert a war. Levy (1987, p. 96) mentions this strategy, and brings to the forefront the potential for bargaining in the circumstances of threatened war: One might argue that... the problem be conceived as one of bargaining. There is some level of concessions that the challenger would prefer to grant rather than to fight Similarly, there is some level of concessions that the declining state would prefer to accept from the challenger rather than to initiate a war. Levy sets this possibility aside, however, with the conclusion that "It would not be technically incorrect to introduce the defender's calculations... but this would probably add far more complexity than explanatory power" (p. 97). To the contrary, it is impossible to reach definitive conclusions without an analysis that accommodates the reactions and counterreactions of all affected parties, including not only aggressive preemptive moves but less militaristic moves also. To do otherwise relegates the subject of preventive war to a theoretical backwater, and precludes any possibility of ascertaining the circumstances under which countries might seek some 2
See, for example, Allison's (1971, pp. 14-15) discussion and citation of Schmitt's (1930) lament about the disagreements that persist among diplomatic historians over precisely this issue. The problem is that such histories proceed without a well-structured theoretical paradigm, and instead focus on a "cause" that is particular to the circumstance. Such a cause, of course, cannot exist.
152
5 Preventive war
accommodation to differential resource growth other than war.3 Indeed, Levy's argument precludes meeting his goal of identifying "the conditions under which declining states choose to provide for their future security through alliances, an expanded armaments program, or other internal changes rather than through preventive military action" (p. 107). One response to our simple scenario might be to reject it as too abstract and to argue that we ought to appeal to the data. However, although there is ample empirical evidence to support the hypothesis that a necessary condition for wars that we call preventive is differential growth in resources that yields the displacement of one leading power by another, we also know that this condition is not sufficient - witness the failures of Britain to thwart its displacement by the United States, of the Soviets to block the rise of China, of the United States after 1945 to block the Soviet's military expansion (Lebow 1981). Unless we choose to argue that Germany did not begin World War II, we have the additional uncomfortable example of Britain's, France's, and Russia's failure to block the rise of Germany under Hitler. Thus, what we require is an analysis that does more than merely point to circumstances propitious for preventive wars - we should direct our research toward identifying a necessary and sufficient condition. Deducing a necessary and sufficient condition is important because we want to learn whether the cause of preventive war lies in our model, or whether other circumstances must be met as well. Knowing only that differential growth is necessary does not preclude the possibility that these other factors are a contributing source to conflict and that conflict can be avoided if we direct our attention there. Indeed, elaborating on his argument that bargaining is precluded as an alternative, Levy (see also Levy 1983b) hints at the existence of other factors (notably uncertainty): The issue is not a conflict of concrete interests in which each party can easily calculate its gains and losses from different levels of concessions and negotiate accordingly, but a question of future influence over a range of diverse and partly 3
To reiterate our earlier point that we must consider the complete international system before any definitive conclusions can be drawn, it is in fact difficult to see how any of the standard conclusions about preventive wars survive even if we admit the reactions of a second country. If one country is about to be surpassed by another, and if no other countries are relevant so that the country in decline is about to be rendered inessential and its antagonist predominant, then preventive action should have been instigated by the country in decline at an earlier time under the label of a war of conquest. If geography had previously precluded such a war, then it will preclude a successful preventive war as well until the time the country in ascendancy gains predominance. Whether or not wars of conquest occur in this two-country system is not our concern here, but it should be evident that a preventive war is an impossibility. Hence, this chapter only examines systems with three or more countries.
5 Preventive war
153
unpredictable issues that cannot be calculated with any degree of precision and that are not easily amenable to negotiation. Moreover, the very intensity of the conflict tends to generate different perceptions by the adversaries of the stakes, threats, legitimate aims, and acceptable alternatives to war (1987, p. 96).
Thus, one hypothesis we ought to examine is whether factors such as uncertainty must be added to identify sufficient conditions for a preventive conflict as against the hypothesis that our model already contains the seed of such conflict. To these broad issues, we should also add a series of more specific questions. For example, are preventive wars limited necessarily to two adversaries and are such wars initiated by a single large country? What of the possibility that preventive wars are initiated by coalitions to keep some large adversary from becoming predominant? These questions are suggested by the debate over whether it is the declining or rising power who initiates a preventive war. Organski and Kugler (1980) are forced to admit that preventive action is indeed dangerous for the rising power. However, they may be retreating too readily: if several powers are rising or declining simultaneously, those of the same type may coalesce for preventive action (or we may even see mixed coalitions). The debate over who initiates, in fact, seems overly preoccupied with two-country scenarios, and the countries Organski and Kugler cite in support of their proposition hardly corresponded to a unified entity (Germany, Italy, and Japan in World War II). Later in our analysis, then, we distinguish between those situations in which a single country threatens to become predominant and to render all others inessential, and those situations in which no country will become predominant but some subset of countries are threatened nevertheless with becoming inessential. Additional questions that will concern us include: Are preventive wars initiated only when one country grows at a faster rate than someone else or are such wars possible also when all countries grow at the same rate? Are preventive wars predetermined in the sense that, given initial growth rates and resources, there is only one possible resolution to instability? Equivalently, is there a unique and predictable response to a perceived future imbalance in the distribution of resources among countries, or is there a variety of possible responses? Also, despite our treatment of countries as unitary actors and the distribution of resources and their growth as the fundamental determinants of conflict, we must be cognizant of the hypothesis that domestic politics plays an important role in determining whether preventive wars are undertaken (Lebow 1981, 1984). Although we incorporate domestic issues in a limited way by allowing decision makers to determine what share of their countries' resources is to be invested into the future and what share is to be used for strategic maneuver in the current period, because we assume
154
5 Preventive war
that decisions are unconstrained except by their countries' resources and by the imperatives of international politics, we do not take full account of the domestic bases of foreign policy. Nevertheless, to the extent that we define what unconstrained decision makers ought to do, we provide a basis for speculating about the consequences for preventive war of constraints such as those imposed by domestic politics. 5.1
A dynamic extension
To this point, national leaders are forward-looking only in the sense that they will not form coalitions that, although perhaps temporarily useful, disadvantage them in the future by threatening their sovereignty. Now, however, we assume a two-period structure that admits differential resource growth rates among countries and that also permits decision makers to choose the amount of resources they will invest into the second period. Specifically, we suppose that country /'s resources at the beginning of period 1 is rh that / can invest any part of its resources, say pt (0< Pi < A*/), and that the rate of return on an investment is wh so that this investment grows to the amount (W/ + \)pt in period 2, where wt > 0 for all countries / in S. That is, after making this investment, and if nothing else occurs, / will have rt—pt resources available in period 1 and, ceterisparibus, ri-pi-\-{wi-\-\)pi = ri-\-wiplresources in period 2. Of course, we are not asserting with this formulation that a model with only two periods is wholly general. Time is continuous and the temporal horizons of decision makers may vary. If, for example, politicians in democracies "plan only until the next election," then perhaps their opponents in dictatorships plan for what might occur after that election. That is, domestic factors affect time horizons and cause them to vary across decision makers. Nevertheless, a two-period model captures the essential issues confronting people in making any investment decision - the weighing of current against future benefits. Returning to our notation, we emphasize that we are not predicting that country /, after it invests ph realizes AV+W/JP,- resources in period 2. Such a prediction ignores the assumption that everyone's information is complete, and thus the fact that others can anticipate this investment with preemptive moves. To see more clearly what this view implies, we can think of the two-period situation in terms of four stages, where period 1 has three stages and period 2 has a single stage. Assuming that (S;r) emerges as the prevailing state from whatever has transpired beforehand, preventive wars (if they occur at all) occur in the first stage, as do resource reallocations induced by other means in anticipation of the future.
5.1 A dynamic extension
155
Investment decisions are made in the second stage, and in the third stage, with the state being (S;r'), countries can be eliminated unless they are capable of defending their sovereignty. Period 2 consists of a single stage in which the prevailing state is (S'; r"), after which coalition formation, redistribution, and the like reoccur. Summarizing: Period 1 Stage 1: With (5; r) the status quo, and in anticipation of what is to follow, countries form alliances, redistribute resources, or launch a preventive war. Stage 2: Countries choose their investment strategies. Stage 3: With (S;vf) the status quo, countries seek to eliminate inessential players. Period 2 Stage 1: With (S';r") the status quo, countries form alliances, etc., in accordance with the model described in Chapters 3 and 4. Notice now that we cannot predict that r" ultimately equals (rx + wxpl,..., rn + wnpn), since the actual distribution of resources countries use as the basis of their investment decisions may be modified in the first and third stages of period 1. Indeed, even if (ri + w^Pi,..., rn+wnpn) were to prevail ultimately, it would be changed in period 2 as countries begin the negotiation and redistributive process implied by any absence of resource stability. Our objective is not to predict thefinaldistribution of resources per se. Rather, it is to measure the anticipations of decision makers in order to identify the root causes of conflict and, hence, the forces that operate to yield one coalition rather than another in the first period. Consequently, rather than build coalitional considerations directly into the determination of ultimate resource distributions, we initially ignore such considerations, taking r" as the basis whereby countries judge the implications of their investment decisions and the necessity for a preventive war, ceteris paribus. Coalitions and preventive wars may arise to redistribute resources before r" prevails, and it is almost certainly true that the game will continue should r" prevail so as to change this distribution. Yet, it is the anticipation of this particular postinvestment vector, in conjunction with strategic options afforded by the initial distribution of resources, that dictates events. In summary, we suppose that, beginning with (5; r), countries must decide what investment decisions to make under the presumption that there will be two rounds of maneuver, thefirstwith the system (S;r') = (S; (rl— P\,...,rn— pn)) and, if no one is eliminated in the first period, the second with (S;r") = (S; (rx + wxpx, ...,rn+wnpn)).
156
5 Preventive war
Aside from this delineation of a decision problem, we also must add some assumptions about preferences for alternative investment decisions that reflect the decision problem at hand. Because we are interested in the conditions for the emergence of preventive wars and because we suppose that the survival of a country depends on its resources relative to other countries, the following assumption seems a logical one: conditional on being able to defend one's sovereignty in period 1, / maximizes its proportion of resources in period 2, (^• + w / /? / )/2 / 6 5 (^ + wy/?/). Notice that if countries are unconcerned about the possibility of elimination in period 1, such as when investments at the expense of current capabilities can be undertaken in weapons systems that will not become immediately operational because current vulnerabilities can be disguised from an adversary, and if all growth rates are positive, then countries should invest all of their resources. However, the qualification this assumption makes about maintaining the ability to defend one's sovereignty in period 1 implies that, in deciding how much to invest, each country must consider the possible investment decisions of other countries, keeping the following considerations in mind: (1) it cannot invest "too much," or (given the decisions of others) it mightfinditself eliminated in the third stage of period 1, in which case its current and future resources are divided among the remaining countries; and (2) it cannot invest "too little," since that may make it vulnerable to being eliminated in period 2. These two strategic considerations are, of course, the two sides of modern strategic planning and weapons procurement, and they give rise to two important questions. First, under what conditions (in terms of the initial distribution of resources r and the growth rates of countries w) does each country possess an investment strategy that guarantees it will not be eliminated in both periods? Indeed, do such strategies exist? Second, under what conditions will a country find it impossible to ensure being essential in period 2, and thus will prefer - either alone or in concert with others - to initiate a preventive war in period 1? To see why we must ask and answer the first question, notice that the two-period scenario, beginning with stage 2, is in part an ^-person noncooperative game in which each nation's strategy is its investment decision and in which its payoff is 0 if it is eliminated in either stage, and equals the proportion of resources it controls in period 2 otherwise. To illustrate, let the initial distribution be r = (120, 80,60,40) and let the vector of growth rates for this four-country system be w = (1,1,0.5,0.5). Suppose country 1 invests 100 units. Notice that, with 20 units of resources remaining, this country cannot be rendered inessential in the third stage of the first period unless the actions of one or two of the other countries render the remaining country predominant (e.g., countries 3 and 4 invest
5.1 A dynamic extension
157
40 and 20 units, respectively, and country 2 invests nothing). Given current growth rates, this means that in the second period, l's resources total 20 (the amount withheld in the first period) plus 2 times 100, which totals 220. But if country 2 believes that investing 100 units is indeed l's strategy, then it can invest 70 units without fearing the possibility that it will be rendered inessential, short of "irrational actions" by countries 3 and 4. However, if 1 believes that 2 intends to invest 70 units, then it should invest nothing instead and become predominant in the first period. This reasoning corresponds to the familiar "he-thinks-that-I-think" regress, and one of our tasks is to ascertain the conditions under which such regresses terminate because the countries possess dominant strategies or because the game possesses a pure strategy Nash equilibrium - an investment decision for each country such that, even after all choices are revealed, no country unilaterally prefers a different decision.4 We must be cautious, nevertheless, in trying to resolve such regresses, because we must first decide how to accommodate one important feature of reality - namely, that real investment decisions are not made at a specific instant. Rather, investment strategies evolve gradually, during which time other countries can observe decisions and adjust accordingly. The United States, for example, cannot act to shift resources from, say, procurement of weapons (the expenditure of current resources) to research and development (an investment) without the Soviet Union perceiving this shift and adjusting to it, and without the United States anticipating the possibility of making a readjustment, long before any funds are actually spent. Because we have rendered decision points discrete, even a threestage conceptualization of period 1 abstracts from this reality. Unfortunately, a model allowing for the possibility of continuous adjustments and readjustments seems too complex to specify or to analyze. Perhaps a differential game analysis would be appropriate, or a very elaborate 4
By a dominant strategy we mean an investment decision that is best, regardless of what others do. A Nash equilibrium is, as we stated earlier, a set of investment decisions - one for each country - such that no country prefers to change its strategy after all others reveal theirs. Game theory admits the notion of a mixed strategy - a strategy wherein a player chooses his or her investment decision by a lottery - but in the present context such strategies seem unreasonable (for a discussion of why we might prefer to exclude such strategies in other contexts, see Ordeshook 1986, pp. 180-3). Notice, nevertheless, that noncooperative games can have more than one Nash equilibrium (e.g., the game of Chicken), in which case it may be difficult to rationalize the prediction that equilibria prevail as outcomes without some form of preplay communication and coordination. Indeed, the proliferation of equilibria in extensive-form games that attempt to rationalize cooperative action as a noncooperative equilibrium remains as a serious theoretical roadblock to the ultimate integration of noncooperative and cooperative game theory. Thus, throughout this analysis, we will be especially sensitive to the possibility of identifying the circumstances under which equilibria are unique.
158
5 Preventive war
description of an extensive form, but analysis would become unduly heavy without any guarantee that we have achieved generality. Hence, to accommodate the possibilities of secondary, tertiary, etc. adjustments within period 1, we implement a different and simpler approach that uses the notion of a strategy's security value. Game theory traditionally defines the security value of a strategy such as an investment decision in terms of what it guarantees a person should everyone else make decisions in that person's worst interests. Calculated in this way, a security value represents a pessimal view of possibilities. However, suppose instead that we calculate security values under the presumption that other people respond to a particular choice in their own best interest, which presumably should occur if they choose after the person in question acts, or if they are allowed an opportunity to readjust their decisions. To be more specific, consider the following definition of the security value of the period-1 postinvestment resource level for country /, r/, which defines the security value of a strategy after considering certain responses and adjustments by other decision makers. Letting E(r) denote the set of countries in S that are essential when the distribution of resources is r, then: The security value of r/, denoted S;(r-)9 equals 1 if and only if / e E(r° = (rf,..., rl,..., r°n)) for all r° satisfying: for no jeS, j*i9 is it the case that j $ E(r°) but j e E(r*), where r% = r°k for all k ^ j and r} > rf > rf. Otherwise, st(r/) = 0. As formidable as this notation might appear, if we keep in mind that we are only talking about the first period, it is merely the formal representation of some logical ideas. To see what this definition entails and to understand how we can use it to accommodate investment adjustments within a period, notice first that our definition set 5/(r/) = l if, regardless of the investment decisions of others, / is essential. For example, the largest country has at least one strategy with a security value of 1, namely, the strategy of not investing anything. But if country / is inessential at rj, given the particular distribution r, there are two possibilities: everyone else is essential or someone else is inessential. If everyone else is essential, then if attacked, / cannot suppose that its sovereignty will be "protected" by other countries defending themselves because (from the definition of inessential) no other country requires /'s support or existence to ensure its own survival. Hence, in this instance, our definition of security value sets Sj(r-) equal to 0. That is, the security value of r\ is zero if there exists some pattern of investments among the remaining countries that renders / uniquely inessential. For the final possibility, which is the one that our notion of security value is intended explicitly to accommodate, we do not require that / be
5.1 A dynamic extension
159
essential with r' in order to set S;(A*/) equal to 1. Suppose that / is not alone in being inessential, and suppose that whenever one (or more) of these countries responds to make itself essential by reducing its investment, such a move necessarily renders / essential as well. Then we set s^r-) = 1. The rationale for this attribution of security levels is this: if / and j are inessential, but if each is made essential when the other one acts to become essential, then everyone knows that one or both countries cannot be eliminated from the game. Owing to the interdependence of their security, if one country, say j , is attacked, then the other, /, must respond to make itself essential - otherwise / will become the next victim, because without the possibility of any rational response from j , / cannot hope to become essential and maintain its sovereignty. So, to accommodate collapsing a dynamic investment-adjustment process into a static one-shot decision stage, we suppose that countries, if faced with an attack because they are inessential, attempt to adjust their investments so as to render themselves essential, and we further suppose that all countries, in evaluating the security levels of alternative strategies, assume that other countries respond rationally if someone attempts to take advantage of a temporary vulnerability. This definition of security value, then, reformulates Bueno de Mesquita's (1981b, p. 543) assumption that "States act to prevent other states from gaining a preponderance of power" (with which he characterizes Gulick 1955, Kaplan 1957, Claude 1962, Morgenthau 1973, Organski and Kugler 1980, and Singer 1980) to mean that states formulate their strategic plans under the presumption that other states will act to avert their own elimination. Hence, to the extent that this notion is critical to our analysis of systems with dynamical resources (which it is), we see quite directly how the idea of collective security is an essential part of the balance-ofpower theory. Morgenthau (1959, p. 175) sought to distinguish balance of power from the notion of collective security: Balance of power alliances are formed by certain individual nations... on the basis of what those individual nations regard as their separate national interests. The organizing principle of collective security is the respect for the moral and legal obligation to consider an attack by any nation upon any member of the alliance as an attack upon all members of the alliance. Consequently, collective security is supposed to operate automatically; that is, aggression calls the counter-alliance into operation at once and, therefore, protects peace and security with the greatest possible efficiency. Our formulation, though, argues that this distinction is meaningless, and it presumes that whatever "moral and legal" imperatives exist, their basis lies in the egoistic motives of individual states. Put simply, our definition of security value presumes that countries invest even if such action renders
160
5 Preventive war
them vulnerable in the short run, provided that others have the incentive and the means, however indirect, to render them essential should the need arise for them to do so.5 Aside from rendering the notion of collective security explicit within a balance-of-power framework, our concept of security value has the technical advantage of associating a single number with each strategy that is independent of the actions of all others. If we are able then to justify the supposition that this number indexes preferences (i.e., denotes the utility that a person associates with each strategy), then we can reduce a gametheoretic problem to a simple decision-theoretic one in which people simply choose strategies that maximize their security value. In the theory of two-person, noncooperative games, that justification is provided by showing that if both persons maximize their security values then their choices are necessarily in equilibrium - neither person has any incentive to alter his or her choice unilaterally after the fact. This justification does not extend to all games in general, but in the next section we use it to model preferences over alternative investment decisions.6 5.2
Preferences
We are now in a position to specify the investment game extension of our basic model. Recall that a noncooperative game has three characteristics: the set of players, the strategies available to each player, and a payoff 5
6
At this point, however, we should emphasize that our analysis makes critical use of the preceding definition of security value, and thus, if it is invalid, then our conclusions about stability and preventive war may be invalid as well. The critical aspect of this definition, clearly, is the presumption that the short-term viability of some countries is established by a mutual vulnerability and, subsequently, by the assumption that everyone acts in their own self-interest. If, however, uncertainty and misperception cloud the picture and if others cannot be relied upon to act in their own self-interest (defined, in part, by the assumption that everyone else is doing the same), then investment poses a risk that national leaders may rationally choose to avoid. Before we use this notion of security value to define preferences over alternative investment decisions, we must first consider the possibility that everyone computes the security value to them of their strategy in r' to be 1, but if everyone adopts the strategy specified by r' then a subset of S finds itself inessential and unable, owing to the strategies of the remaining countries, to extricate itself from this situation. If this possibility arises then there may be no basis for supposing, as we do shortly, that countries maximize their investments subject to the constraint that, whenever possible, they not choose strategies with a security value of 0. To see, then, that this situation cannot arise, notice that / alone cannot be inessential; otherwise, / cannot be certain that, if attacked, no one offers assistance out of their own self-interest, in which case s,(r/) = 0. So suppose that all countries / e XC S are inessential with r', that all countries / e S—Xarc essential, and that £,(/"/) = 1 for all / e S. That the strategies of the countries in S—Xcannot "trap" two or more countries in X, say the subset Y, into being inessential follows because, by setting 5/(r/) = l,
5.2 Preferences 161 function, which either specifies the utility to / from each vector of joint strategy choices or which specifies ordinal preferences over these vectors. The set of players is 5, and z's strategy is the amount of resources it fails to invest, rft = ri—ph so its strategy space is Rt = {r- |0
7
we require that for every j e Y there exists an adjustment by Y— {j} that renders all members of Y essential. Hence, by definition, the members of X cannot be so "trapped." To restate these assumptions about preference formally as a bookkeeping convenience, let «/(•) denote a utility function for country / that summarizes its preferences (i.e., / prefers r' to r* if and only if «,(r') > W/(r*)). Then our assumption about preference is: Given an initial distribution that, via any sequence of unilateral moves on the part of countries in S, allows a unilateral move to either r' or r*, then
162 5 Preventive war This concludes the extension to our model. In formulating this extension, we have had to make several compromises. Some compromises, such as the restriction to two discrete periods, are mere analytic conveniences subject in the future to generalization. The consequences of other compromises, however, are less clear. We refer here to the definition of security value and to the specification of preferences in terms of this value. We prefer a more careful modeling of the dynamics of adjustment that occur within one of our periods as each country's pattern of investment and procurement unfolds. We have assumed that countries can rely on the selfinterest of others who confront a similar fate - elimination because they are inessential. However, we have not considered the possibility that the game is even more complicated than this, that essential countries might try to deal with subsets of inessential countries and that enforceable contracts can be established among them to eliminate the remaining inessential countries. Once again, then, we must learn to appreciate the strategic complexity of politics and why some decision makers appear to learn to "play" better than others. Minimally, our analysis should illuminate this complexity and thereby reduce our propensity to assume that people's motives should be self-evident or that optimal choices are readily apparent. 5.3
Equilibria in the first period
To derive conclusions from our model, we take our cue from the methods of noncooperative game analysis and try to answer three questions. The first is whether the game possesses an equilibrium - a set of strategies such that once the players qua countries have chosen those strategies, no one has any incentive to make a different choice unilaterally. The second concerns the uniqueness or nonuniqueness of equilibria. If equilibria are unique, then generally we are confident that they provide good predictions or at least reasonable hypotheses about choice. However, if the equilibria are not unique, then their existence may be irrelevant to prediction All. tt/(r')>M/(r*)if: (1) 5/(r/) = land5 / (rf) = 0or (2) 5/(r/)=5/(rf) = 0and ieE{r') and i w,(r')>w,(r*)if: (3) Si(ri) =st(rf) = 1 and r\
5.3 Equilibria in the first period
163
(as in the Chicken and the Battle of the Sexes games). Finally, the third question asks about the properties of equilibria, if any exist - a specification of the actions they imply. We answer these questions first by searching for period-1 investment equilibrium strategies, followed by a review of the circumstances under which these equilibria lead to resource distributions in the second period in which no one becomes inessential, as compared to those circumstances in which someone becomes inessential and thereby has an incentive to initiate a preventive war in period 1 prior to making an investment. This approach, then, assumes that countries proceed down that branch of the game in which they make no allowances for preventive wars, or coalitions in anticipation of a preventive war, or coalitions to thwart a preventive war. After we have reviewed these consequences of period-1 equilibria, however, we can then try to determine likely responses. Ourfirsttheorem, then, answers the first and second questions, and establishes the base for our subsequent analysis. Theorem 5.1. If (S; r) is system stable, then there exists a unique period-1 equilibrium of resource investment. The most direct way to convey the meaning of this result is with some numerical examples and ancillary remarks. Example 5.1. Consider the three-country system (S; r) = ({1,2,3}; (120,100, 80)). To see that the unique period-1 equilibrium is the distribution r' = (20,40,20), notice that even if country 1 reduces its investment to 0 so that (120,40,20) prevails, both countries 2 and 3 are inessential. But the definition of security value and the requirement that countries prefer to choose a strategy with a security value of 1 whenever possible require that 2 need only consider those distributions in which no other country acts to render itself inessential, given what everyone else does. In this instance, country 3 can respond by reducing its investment also, and at (120,40,80), 2 is essential. That is, at 40, country 2 remains essential by supposing that everyone else responds rationally to each others' decisions. But if 2 increases its investment further so that (20,30,20) prevails, then even if 3 responds to a decision by 1 to not invest by also not investing, 2 remains inessential in (120,30, 80). Similarly, to see that country 1 would not increase its investment above 100 units, notice that if 1 increases its investment to 110 so that the distribution (10,40,20) prevails, then 1 becomes inessential, and no rational response by anyone else will render it essential.
164
5 Preventive war
Although the identity of (20,40,20) as the unique equilibrium that results from the distribution (120,100, 80) is anything but obvious, the following remark generalizes our example (recall our convention of assuming that Remark 5.1. For any system-stable three-country system (S; r) = ({1,2,3}; (ru r2, r3)), the equilibrium values of/?/, /= 1,2,3, satisfy px = rx + r3 - r2 and p2 = p3 = r2 + r3 - rx.
Reexamining our example now not only illustrates this remark, but it also clarifies the definition of security value and its implications. Notice that with the distribution (20,40,20), country 2 (indeed, all countries) could be rendered inessential if any other country reduces its investment to zero. Nevertheless, we set the security value of r2 = 40, for example, equal to 1 because, in the event that 1 retains, say, 70 units of resources in the first period, country 3, because it also is inessential, must increase the amount that it retains; and if 3 becomes essential, then so does 2. Thus, our concept of security value permits countries to "place themselves in jeopardy," in the sense that an opponent can unilaterally render them inessential. But, to reiterate our earlier comments about how the notion of collective security is reflected in our analysis here, our supposition is that a country can evaluate its strategy on the premise that other countries will make whatever and as many adjustments as they feel are necessary to ensure their survival, that this fact is common knowledge, and thus that no one will be able to take advantage of the country's vulnerability. Notice that this extreme form of Waltz's "self-help" notion finds its empirical reflection in, for example, Japan as well as those Western European countries that underinvest in their own military capabilities, knowing that the United States cannot afford their domination by the Soviets. As Gilpin observes: "First, in an alliance between a great power and a lesser power there is a tendency for the former to overpay in the long run... [T]he great power increases its commitments without a commensurate increase in the resources devoted by its allies tofinancethose commitments" (1981, p. 193).8 It is also evident, however, that our analysis does not apply if there are impediments to strategic readjustments, such as those that are occasioned by an inability to detect a country's investment strategy. Certainly, decision makers should then proceed much more 8
Olson and Zeckhauser (1966) argue that we should attribute such underinvestment to a Prisoners' Dilemma that occasions free riding on the part of smaller countries. We do not disagree, but the present analysis points the way to an explanation that accommodates the fact that the surplus of resources these countries enjoy as a result of their failure to contribute toward their defense in the same proportion as the United States is not all directed to current consumption, but is instead invested in, for example, plant modernization and personal savings.
5.3 Equilibria in the first period
165
cautiously. Indeed, any country capable of disguising its strategy from others possesses a considerable advantage, primarily because if other countries invest too much, it can launch a preemptive strike in the first period. Thus, at least one source of war, obvious without our model, is the failure to detect or measure current military resources. Another suggestion of our example is that we should not suppose that the largest country, defined in terms of resource potential in the first period, will be the largest country in period 1 after making its investment decision. It is interesting to speculate, of course, on the extent to which this corresponds to contemporary events. Arguably, the United States (along with its allies) could be interpreted as investing more in the future (by its emphasis on research and technology), whereas the Soviet Union, by spending a considerably greater proportion of its resources on current procurement of weapons, is foregoing future growth. Certainly, the Soviets' concern over an American Strategic Defense Initiative (Star Wars) is consistent with this interpretation despite their public assertions to the contrary. Notice that one implication of Remark 5.1 is that if resources are distributed evenly across the three countries, then the countries invest all of their resources. This result, however, does not generalize to larger systems, either for n even or n odd [e.g., with r = (60,60,60,60,60) as the initial distribution, 5 is uniquely inessential in (60, 30,30,30,0) - the security value of investing everything is not 1 as it is in the three-country case]. Beyond this, however, we can see that matters are a bit different if n is even. To begin our exploration of this case, though, we consider the following example: Example 5.2. Suppose (S;r) = ({1,2,3,4}; (120,80,60,40)). To see that r' = (40,40,40,40) is the unique period-1 equilibrium, so that again the smallest country does not appear disadvantaged and the largest does not appear advantaged in the first period, notice first that if 1 alone invests only to reduce its period-1 resources to 80, then 4 is uniquely inessential in (80, 80, 60, 40). Since 4 is inessential if it controls any lesser total of resources, since 4 is essential in r', and since everyone else is essential in (80,80,60,40) - and thus they have no incentives to adjust in a way that might make 4 essential - and since the security value to 4 of every strategy is zero, 4 prefers r' to any strategy in which it invests. On the other hand, 5/(40) = 1 for / = 1,2,3, whereas 5;(r/<40) = 0 otherwise [e.g., 1 is inessential in (30,40,40,40), but no one else is inessential and thus 1 cannot be assured that it will be rendered essential by the rational responses of others]. Hence, r' is the unique period-1 equilibrium.
166
5 Preventive war
This example should not be interpreted to mean that, in four-country systems, everyone always invests down to the smallest country. The following remark provides a basis for formulating a counter to that hypothesis. Remark 5.2. If (5; r) is a system-stable four-country system, then the period-1 equilibrium investments satisfy two conditions: (1) pi 5, the unique period-1 equilibrium is one in which the countries, after making their investments, are left with (10,70,55,5). Notice now that Remark 5.2 distinguishes between three- and fourcountry systems in the following way: although an equitable distribution of resources with three countries implies that all countries invest everything, an equitable distribution among four countries implies that no one invests anything, a result that generalizes to any even-number-size system. Aside from this fact, though, the number of possible cases we must consider grows geometrically with n, so stating general results that parallel Remarks 5.1 and 5.2 for systems with more than four countries requires unwieldy algebra. We conclude this section with a single five-country example to illustrate the method of analysis: Example 5.4. Let (5; r) = ({1,2,3,4,5}; (100,80,60,30,30)), in which case the unique equilibrium is (30,30,30,30,30). Notice
5.4 The emergence of a predominant country
167
first that every country remains essential, regardless of the actions taken by the remaining countries. For example, if 1 and 2 reduce their investments to zero, countries 3, 4, and 5 are essential in (100,80,30,30,30). To see that no country can invest more, suppose 1 invests down to 20. But then at (20,70,40,30,30), 1 is inessential while everyone else is essential. 5.4
The emergence of a predominant country
Theorem 5.1 is important because it tells us that as long as a system is initially system stable, there is a unique investment pattern and hence a unique system in period 2 that national leaders can anticipate. Nevertheless, it does not tell us anything about whether countries will prefer a preventive action of some kind in stage 1 to forestall the realization of this equilibrium. However, having accepted the proposition that preventive wars, if they occur at all, are caused by the threat that one or more countries will be rendered inessential in period 2, there are (as noted earlier) two ways in which this precondition can be met: (1) one country, because it is able to invest proportionately more resources or because it is advantaged in its growth rate, threatens to become predominant in the second period; and (2) because they can invest little or because their growth rates are low, one or more countries (but less than n — 1) are faced with becoming inessential. In exploring these possibilities, we can make important use of Theorem 5.1 and the two remarks that follow it. Notice that neither the existence nor the properties of equilibria depend on the w/s; that is, the pattern of investment is independent of the exogenously determined parameter.9 Several conclusions follow from this fact. First, barring the possibility that no one invests or that everyone invests the same, there exists some pattern of growth rates such that one country becomes predominant and 9
Indeed, it is straightforward to show that the invariance of investment strategy with w, holds generally. Briefly, because equilibrium strategies are also dominant (because we can compute security values directly without reference to the investment decisions that other countries make), we can compute them without reference to the strategic choices of other countries. It follows that if investing /?, maximizes period-2 resources when resources grow at the rate wit it maximizes those resources regardless of w/'s value. This result might seem perverse since we commonly think of investment decisions as choices between consumption now and consumption later - choices that are reasonably affected by rates of return. Presently, however, current resources enter one's utility today only to the extent that they facilitate one's security and once that security is assured, all remaining resources ought to be invested. It seems evident, then, that this independence between investment strategy and growth rate would change were we to introduce risk in one form or another into the analysis.
168
5 Preventive war
patterns such that some subset becomes inessential.™ Hence, if growth rates differ significantly enough, the equilibrium investments may lead directly to the necessity for preventive action. Consider Example 2 again, where (5; r) = ({1,2,3,4}, (120,80,60,40)), and where the respective investments corresponding to a period-1 equilibrium (40,40,40,40) are 80, 40, 20, and 0. If w2 = 20 and wx = w3 = w4 = 4, then the period-2 distribution becomes (440, 880,140,40), and 2 is predominant. However, taking a case in which all w,'s are equal, say to 4, then (440,240,140,40) prevails in period 2, and country 1 is predominant, which establishes another fact: differential growth rates are not a necessary precondition for the emergence of a predominant country. Conditions for a threatened predominance The preceding analysis tells us that the preconditions for preventive action of some sort, conditions (1) and (2), can be met whenever some subset of countries has an advantage in growth rates or can invest more because it begins with more. Both factors, moreover, can operate independently and simultaneously to set the stage for preventive action. However, since we can meet the presumed preconditions if the discrepancies in the W/'s are sufficiently great, we should ask whether there are systems that are immune to the second method: Are there systems in which countries render others inessential merely because they can invest more? We approach the problem by negating the differential effect of the w/s and suppose that they are all equal and by dividing the analysis into the two parts described before. Letting / denote the total resources invested by all countries in period 1, and after assuming that a period-1 equilibrium prevails, the following result defines the necessary and sufficient condition for meeting or avoiding the first precondition, that one country threatens to become predominant: Theorem 5.2. If wt = w for all ieS, and if a period-1 equilibrium prevails, then no country is predominant in period 2 if and only if, for all / e 5, (i) pf < 1/2; (ii) otherwise, w < {R/2-ri) -s(Pi-I/2). Theorem 5.2 is tantalizing, because by defining a necessary and sufficient condition for precluding the possibility of the first precondition for 10
In three-country systems, if rj
5.4 The emergence of a predominant country
169
preventive war, it appears to have delivered us to the doorstep of understanding the causes of such wars. However, we cannot easily interpret this result substantively since it treats the /?z's and the rfs as independent, whereas because the investments of countries are functions of the initial distribution of resources, the p / s are functions of the rfs. Remarks 5.1 and 5.3 nevertheless allow us to interpret and illustrate Theorem 5.2 for three- and four-country systems. First, with respect to three-country systems, we have the following result: Remark 5.3. For wf = w for all /, (S= {1,2,3);r) is system stable, and, following a period-1 equilibrium, no country emerges as predominant if and only if rx < r2 + r 3 /3 or if w < (r2 + r 3 — r{) -s(3r1-3r2-r3). Notice that although this remark provides a convenient algebraic interpretation of Theorem 5.2, the first inequality merely provides a sufficient condition for avoiding the emergence of a predominant country. Yet, if the precondition of the remark is violated [i.e., if r = (140,100,60) so that r1 = 140 > r2 + r 3 / 3 = 120] then condition (ii) of Theorem 5.2, in conjunction with Remark 5.1, shows that the period-1 equilibrium does not yield a predominant country if w < (r2 + r 3 - /*i)/(3r1 - 3r2 - r3). In threecountry systems, then, no country emerges as predominant if and only if r j < r 2 + r 3 / 3 or if w < (r 2 + r 3 — A*1)/(3r1 — 3r2 — r 3 ). What is especially interesting about these inequalities is that their right-hand sides both increase as r2 or r3 increases. Hence, in three-country systems, iftheexogenously determined factor in growth is identical for all countries, then the more nearly equal in size are the countries, the more difficult it is for the largest to threaten predominance. Turning now to four-country systems, we use Remark 5.2 and Theorem 5.2 to establish the following result: Remark 5.4. If wz = w for all /, and if (S; r) is system stable, then the only four-country system that never occasions a predominant country following a period-1 equilibrium, regardless of w, is one in which ri = R/4 for all /. Thus, four-country systems differ from their three-country counterparts in that with n = 4, we can be certain of avoiding the possibility that one country becomes predominant, regardless of the growth rate w, only if all countries are equal in resources. However, four-country systems in which all resources are equal is a relatively uninteresting case, because no country should make any investment in this event. For example, if r = (75,75,75,75), and if any country invests anything, then that country is inessential, whereas all others remain essential. Thus, r is itself the unique
170 5 Preventive war period-1 equilibrium. Suppose then that this restrictive equality condition is not satisfied. In particular, let r = (120, 80,60,40), which corresponds to Example 5.2 in Section 5.2. The period-1 equilibrium is (40,40,40,40), so country l's investment, 80 units, exceeds the combined investments of 2, 3, and 4 - 6 0 units - and 1 becomes predominant if w is sufficiently large. Specifically, from condition (ii), country 1 becomes predominant if w> (150-120)/(80-70) = 3 [e.g., if w = 4 then the resource distribution in the second period is (440,240,140,40), and 1 is predominant]. Notice now that the qualitative implications of Remarks 5.3 and 5.4 are germane to the debate over whether stability requires an equitable or inequitable division of resources. In Chapter 3 we show that, without resource growth and investment, there is no necessary relationship between system stability and the symmetry or asymmetry of the resource distribution. Here, however, we find that the most stable three-country system is one in which resources are evenly divided across the three countries. That is, with uniform growth rates and a uniform distribution of resources, no preventive wars are anticipated, and, more generally, three-country systems can avoid the preconditions for preventive war regardless of growth rates if the two smaller countries are not "too small."11 At least with respect to three-country systems, then, we find support in our theory for those who argue that a symmetric distribution is more conducive to peace as well as for those who argue that there is no relationship; but our theory does make clear that this debate must be made more precise by specifying whether or not resource growth and investment are relevant considerations. On the other hand, by establishing that only four-country systems in which resources are distributed uniformly are guaranteed not to occasion the rise of a predominant country, Remark 5.4 provides some basis for arguing that equitable resource distributions are more conducive toward peace. This discussion of four-country systems also leads us back to the debate over whether smaller systems are more stable than larger systems. 11
Moreover, with three countries, if resources are uniformly distributed, then Remark 5.1 also shows that all countries invest all resources, leaving none for conflict in period 1. Hence, if we can imagine our game being played successively, we might speculate that, with all vv/'s equal, countries will continually reinvest and thereby forever preclude the possibility of conflict. Precisely the opposite is true, however, in four-country systems. From condition (1) of Remark 5.2, we see that if all resources are equal then /?, = 0 for all countries. This difference between three- and four-country systems suggests that the issue of the role of resource distribution in avoiding conflict depends on whether we believe that investment or noninvestment is more conducive to peace, and on this point the debate is unresolved. Star wars (an investment that precludes current military as well as civilian expenditures) is viewed by opponents, including the Soviets, as destabilizing; on the other hand, increased military expenditures on currently available technologies (that directly preclude investment) are also seen as destabilizing.
5.4 The emergence of a predominant country
171
Without growth and investments, all countries are essential in three-country systems, whereas this is not true for larger systems. Aside from this fact, though, we find no relationship between the number of countries and the conditions that ensure system stability. Here, however, three-country systems are relatively immune to the possibility that the largest country can invest so much that it becomes predominant, whereas four-country systems are necessarily immune only if resources are distributed uniformly. Hence, as a qualitative conclusion, we find support for both sides of this debate; but, as with the argument over the relationship between stability and the asymmetry of resources, we see that the debate over the relationship between system size and stability must be made precise by specifying whether or not resource growth and investment are considerations. Indeed, since we can find no simple linear relationship between system size and stability, we are forced to conclude that the debate over the possible nature of this relationship is too poorly structured to possess either empirical or theoretical content, and that the search should end for a few variables and simple relationships that might account for conflict. Responses to a threatened predominance To this point our analysis relies exclusively on the properties of period-1 equilibria and the postinvestment resource distributions they imply directly, and the only adjustment we permit in the process is the elimination of countries that are inessential in the third stage of period 1. Thus, we have not yet considered the other possible responses of countries in that stage to the threat of predominance. The particular possibility that should concern us is if a country's investment strategy renders it predominant in period 2, then what of the response of the remaining countries in stage 3? Is the emergence of a dominant country avoidable, and is the formation of specific coalitions such as {2,3,4] in the previous four-country example required to avoid it? Dropping the assumption that all w,'s are equal, we proceed by addressing the first part of this question, beginning with the following remark that specifies an additional property of period-1 equilibrium investments: Remark 5.5. If (S; r) is system stable and if rt — R/2 for only one / in 5, then the unique period-1 equilibrium satisfies rj = ry for all
and ri
172
5 Preventive war
the issue of whether any country will become predominant, given our assumptions. Remark 5.6. If (5; r) is system stable, if rt = R/2 for some / in S, and if / avoids investing whenever such action necessitates a preventive action against / by S— {/}, then no country invests, and (S; r) is resource (and system) stable in both periods. Hence, just as the condition that rt = R/2 for some / yields both resource and system stability in Chapters 3 and 4, we find that this condition establishes stability in our two-period extension. As we shall see shortly, however, this result is critical for showing that, in general, system stability can prevail in international systems even if resource growth threatens the sovereignty of one or more countries. However, our final result takes us the rest of the way to answering the central question about the possibility that a country can pursue an investment strategy whereby it becomes predominant in the second period. Remark 5.7. If (S; r) is system stable and if there are no impediments to coalition formation in stage 3 of period 1, then no country in S can become predominant in period 2. Although stated formally, this result is based on an argument about the nature of cooperative games rather than the manipulation of algebraic identities. So, instead of relegating the argument to the appendix, we offer it here. First, Remark 5.6 handles the case in which ri = R/2 for one / in S. Suppose then that rt
Because the cooperative game in question involves transferable utility, the main-simple V-set exists and corresponds to both the strong bargaining set and the competitive solution (McKelvey and Ordeshook 1977). Hence, regardless of which solution hypothesis we choose, we reach the same conclusion.
5.4 The emergence of a predominant country
173
such predominance is not an equilibrium strategy. Moreover, even if such a country sought to become predominant by investing less, what we have said about cooperative action in stage 3 applies equally well to the first stage. If a country threatens predominance in period 2, and if all countries can anticipate this eventuality, then coalitional countermoves can block this possibility in period 1 of stage 1. Remark 5.7, then, follows less from the formal structure of our analysis and more from the cooperative view in which this analysis is placed, but what is especially interesting is that if there are no impediments to coalitions and to the transfer of resources in stage 1, then S— [j] is not the only coalition that can forestall the threatened predominance of j . Indeed, j can be a member of some coalition that arises in response to its threat. Recall our earlier example in which r = (120,80,60,40) and w = 4, so that r" = (440,240,140,40) and country 1 is predominant. To see that since no country controls precisely half the resources, {2,3,4} is not the only possible coalition that can block this threatened predominance, notice that countries 1, 2, and 3 can coalesce against 4, eliminate 4, and agree to a redistribution that results in the new distribution (120, 100, 80,0). Now the period-1 equilibrium is (20,40,20,0) and the period-2 distribution is (520,340,320,0). Clearly, country 1 prefers this alternative since it is not forced to cede any resources - indeed, it averts the possibility of a preventive war by {2,3,4) against it - and countries 2 and 3 meet their objective of remaining essential in period 2. It is because of this possibility that earlier we referred to the anticipated rise of a predominant country as a "presumed" precondition for preventive war. This new possibility, then, admits some indeterminacy into the analysis. First, notice that a coalition of 1, 2, and 3 against 4 in which 2 and 3 share 4's resources is feasible because w is not so great as to imply that 2 and 3 nevertheless become inessential. Even if w is much larger than 4, 1 can transfer resources to 2 and 3 in period 1 in the coalition {1,2,3} against 4. Indeed, in nearly any circumstance, 1, 2, and 4, or 1, 3, and 4, as well as 1, 2, and 3 can coalesce. Thus, in its present form, this "cooperative" game does not have a core and any number of outcomes might prevail (as predicted by a cooperative concept such as the V-set or the competitive solution). This example suggests that if the largest country threatens to become predominant in period 2, then in general any number of coalitions is possible, including coalitions in which the largest country is a member. Despite the fact that this role for a country threatening predominance seems wholly unanticipated in the preventive war literature, we can find historical precedents. During the Warring States Period of China, Ch'in, the most powerful state, sought in 302 B.C. to overcome the state of Ch'u
174
5 Preventive war
(Ssuma 80 B.C.). However, rather than permit the balance-of-power policy of Ho Tsung to assert itself in the form of a coalition of Ch'u and some number of the other five states, Ch'in judiciously ceded territory to negotiate a temporary coalition with the states of Wei and Han in its ultimately successful campaign against Ch'u. Indeed, owing to a combination of diplomatic and military skill, it was not for another 55 years, until 247 B.C., that the armies of Wei, Han, Chao, Ch'u, and Yen, reasserting the Ho Tsung policy for the last time, blocked Ch'in. But by then it was too late to halt the eventual unification of China in 221 B.C. under its first emperor, Ch'in Wang Cheng. The rationale for anticipating any of several coalitions, in fact, follows from our model generally. Specifically, if C is winning, then the characteristic function value for C, v(C), is given by expression (4.1), whereas v(S— C) is given by (4.2). The earlier rationale for this characteristic function is that if one or more countries are threatened with becoming inessential and if r(S-C)>R/2-maxieCrh then S-C could transfer resources to the largest country, set rx = R/2, and ensure both resource and system stability. Remark 5.6 implies that the same rationale applies here: S—C can increase the resources of country 1 to R/2, in which case no country can invest, and country l's incentive for accepting the transfer is that it is assured of half the system's resources, which is the greatest proportion it can secure. However, for this characteristic function, there is no core unless rx = R/2, so, as asserted, any number of coalitions is possible. Despite the unification of China that occurred under Ch'in, if the assumptions of this theory are satisfied (perfect divisibility and transferability of resources, complete information, and the ability to fully anticipate and react to the choices of others), predominant countries ought not arise. On the other hand, imperfect information, miscalculation, and the rigidities imposed by domestic politics can individually and together preclude those coalitional adjustments required to avoid the emergence of a predominant state. 5.5
Inessential countries
Thus far, our discussion focuses on the first of our two presumed preconditions for preventive war: the threatened emergence of a predominant country in the second period. Yet, there is another possibility - namely, that some but not all countries find that the period-1 equilibrium renders them inessential in period 2.13 13
It is possible to state a necessary and sufficient condition for all countries to be essential in period 2. Unfortunately, this condition is clumsy and does not lend itself to any simple
5.5 Inessential countries
175
To illustrate this possibility, let (5; r) = ({1,..., 5); (60,60,60,30,30)), so the period-1 equilibrium is (30,30,30,30,30): countries 1, 2, and 3 invest 30 units each, and countries 4 and 5 invest nothing. If wt = 2 for all /, then the distribution in period 2 becomes (120,120,120,30,30), in which case countries 4 and 5 are inessential. Before we can conclude, however, that this circumstance is sufficient for countries to foment a preventive war, we ought to ask, just as we did in the previous section, are there any coalitional strategies available to 4 and 5 in stage 1 of the first period that render them essential in the second? Ignoring the e that each country can assure itself in the first period according to expressions (4.1) and (4.2) that is, without assuming that it implies elimination, let e = 0 - suppose, in particular, that 4 and 5 coalesce with 1 and 2 to force 3 to transfer 30 units each to 1 and 2, in which case r becomes (90,90,0,30,30). Then r' = (30,30,0,30,30) and r" = (210,210,0,30,30), and 4 and 5 are essential. Country 3, however, can respond to this threat by proposing that interpretation. Hence, we relegate it to this footnote. First, we offer a result that assures that a specific country, /, is essential. We begin by letting p(C) = £/ 6 cPi be the total investment of coalition C, recalling that / e S is essential if and only if there exists a minimal winning coalition C (i.e., Ce W*) such that / is a member of C. Formally, this requires two conditions: r(C)+wp(C)-rj-wPi<(R+wI)/2; (5.1) r(C)+w/?(C)>(i?+w/)/2. (5.2) Expression (5.1) requires that C - {/) is not winning, and (5.2) requires that C be winning. The terms in these expressions, rearranged, yield w[I/2 -p(C- {/))]>- [R/2 - r(C- {/})], and w[I/2-p{C)]<-[R/2-r{C)]. For simplicity, we will state a result that can be arrived at using some simple algebra in conjunction with the following notation: K— I/2-p(C); M=I/2-p(C-li}); L = R/2-r(C); and N=R/2-r(C-{i}). Then, if w = w/ for all / e 5, ieS is essential in period 2 if and only if there exists a C c S . / e C , such that: 1. if 7V<0, thenM>0and -L/K<w<-M/N\ 2. if 7V=0, then A:<0 and w>-L/K, or K>0, L<0, and w<-L/K, or A>0, L<0, and w > - l ; 3. if 7V>0, then K>0, L<0, and -L/K>w>-M/N, or AT=O, L < 0 , and w > - l , or A:<0, W>-L/K,
and w>-M/N.
Consider now the coalition C of which / is a member, and let w/(C) denote the range of values of w associated with C such that C is minimal winning in period 2, thereby rendering / essential in period 2 (the preceding result establishes the parameters of wf-(C)). Letting W* denote the set of minimal winning coalitions of which / is a member, then / is essential if and only if w is in the union of Wi(C), taken over all C in W* - if and only if w renders some coalition of which / is a member minimal winning in period 2. For the system to be system stable, this condition must be true for all / e 5, which establishes this result: If w = Wj for all / e 5, then a system is system stable in period 2 if and only if
176 5 Preventive war {2,3,4} attack {1,5] so that the preinvesment distribution becomes (0,80, 80,80,0). In this case the eventual outcome is (0,240,240,240,0), which 2 and 4 prefer to any previous proposal and 3 prefers to the threat established by 4 and 5's proposal. Thus, rather than a preventive war in which 4 and 5 secure their survival, 5 is ultimately rendered inessential and eliminated, which is to say that although countries becoming inessential might seek coalitions that avoid this possibility, there is no guarantee that they will be successful in the attempt.14 Indeed, the discussion in the previous section, which extends the relevance of the characteristic function given by expressions (4.1) and (4.2) to the current model, pertains here as well. The cooperative game that national leaders play in anticipation of the consequences of period-1 equilibria does not, in general, have a core: any number of coalitions are possible, including ones in which some but not all of the countries threatened with becoming inessential are included. 5.6
The disappearance of stability
Throughout this chapter, we have assumed that, ceteris paribus, countries maximize the proportion of resources they control in period 2, which seems unexceptional if we interpret resources as a measure of military capabilities, since such capabilities ought to have no intrinsic value other than the security they provide. However, an alternative assumption, which we introduce in Chapter 3 in the context of discussion of the costs of war, is that national leaders maximize the absolute magnitude of resources. Indeed, it is possible to imagine that goals are multidimensional, and that decision makers confront a trade-off between maximizing relative shares of resources and maximizing the absolute level of those resources. Of course, if resources are neither created nor destroyed, maximizing proportion and maximizing absolute level are equivalent objectives. But in the present context, the imperatives of coalitional maneuver and strategy in stage 1 depend critically on such details of preference. In particular, system stability requires not only that countries have the capability of transferring resources so as to make someone near-predominant, but it also supposes that the recipient country has an incentive to accept the transfer. The goal of maximizing proportion retains this incentive, whereas the goal of maximizing absolute magnitude can destroy it when there is resource growth. 14
It might seem that this process could continue until 1 and 2 each control 120 units of resources, freezing the system at (120,120,0,0,0). Notice, though, that any number of proposals accomplish this purpose, such as (120,60,20,20,20).
5.6 The disappearance of stability
177
To see this, recall our earlier example in which r = (120,80,60,40) and w = 4 so that r" = (440,240,140,40). One response to the threatened predominance of 1 is for country 4 (or any other country) to transfer 30 units of resources to 1. If 1 maximizes proportion of resources, it accepts the offer and freezes the system in accordance with Remark 5.6. However, 1 has no incentive to accept the offer if it ignores shares and maximizes final resources. For example, countries 1, 2, and 3 could agree to coalesce and eliminate 4, agreeing to a new distribution (120,100,80,0). Now the period-1 equilibrium is (20,40,20,0) and the period-2 distribution is (520,340,320,0), which 1 prefers (as do 2 and 3). Thus, both the rising and some of the declining powers join to eliminate another declining power so as to institute a new three-country game that does not threaten any survivor's sovereignty. Counters exist to this proposal, but the surprising result here is that this game has a core consisting of the four possible period-1 preinvestment distributions in which three countries each hold 100 units of resources and the fourth country is eliminated. With a uniform distribution of resources among three countries, everyone invests fully, so that the final outcome in period 2 is one in which the three surviving countries each hold 500 units of resources, and no other feasible outcome - no other feasible reallocation of resources among a winning coalition in the four-country system and allowable investment strategy dominates an outcome such as (500,500,500,0). Some important conclusions emerge from this example. First, notice that the modification of national goals destroys system stability, and leads ultimately to the absorption of one country - or at least to its removal from "great-power"status. Moreover, the core of the corresponding game consists of four distinct outcomes, one of which includes the elimination of the country with a potential for predominance, whereas other outcomes lead to the elimination of powers that are in relative decline. The instability in this example, however, does not depend on whether one country threatens predominance or others are threatened with becoming inessential, since our example merely illustrates the following remark: Remark 5.8. If wt = w>0.5 for all / in S= (1,2,3,4}, and if all countries maximize resources in period 2, then, unless rt = R/2 for some /, (S; r) is system unstable and the corresponding cooperative game has a nonempty core in which any three countries divide R evenly among themselves, eliminate the fourth, and invest all resources. It would, of course, be interesting to know whether such a remark generalizes for larger systems, and therefore whether, if countries maximize the absolute magnitude of their resources as against the proportion of
178
5 Preventive war
resources relative to other countries in the system, wars that eliminate one country or another (and that might otherwise appear as preventive wars) can arise regardless of whether one country threatens predominance or some countries are threatened with becoming inessential. Our conjecture is that the result does not generalize to establish that any system is unstable and thus that all systems ultimately can reduce to a three-country system. Nevertheless, Remark 5.8 establishes the sensitivity of our conclusions about system stability to the way in which we formalize goals. This sensitivity, however, is not new to models of political processes. Similar issues arise in the construction of election models (do candidates or parties maximize votes, expected plurality, probability of winning, proportion of the vote?) and in models of firm behavior (do firms maximize profits, per-share earnings, growth rate, market share?). The best that can be done in these circumstances is to identify those conclusions that are sensitive to assumptions and those that are not. Without the possibility of growth, the specific assumption we make is, of course, irrelevant; whereas with such growth, only our conclusions about coalitional maneuvering and its effects on system stability depend on the formalization of goals that we choose. Which assumption is most appropriate? Unfortunately, the literature provides little guidance, largely because the critical nature of the assumption was not previously understood. Organski and Kugler (1980), for example, criticize Singer, Bremer, and Stuckey's (1972) measure because it normalizes each country's index by the total of all countries. Their criticism - which is that "when the relative power of one nation declines, one cannot determine whether this is because the particular nation is doing worse or whether the average growth of the sample as a whole is improving" (p. 36) - is discussed, however, purely as a problem of operationalizing the concept of power, and nowhere do they address the issue of goals. Many students of international politics are comfortable with the assumption that nations maximize power, which suggests our second assumption, but those same persons argue that power is a relative concept, which is more nearly consistent with our first assumption. Although we cannot say whether one assumption is unambiguously best, if we nevertheless allow ourselves the luxury of speculation, at least one interesting interpretation follows. In the European competition for empire, although the attendant colonial resources surely had military consequences on the Continent, the demand for empire arose from domestic political forces for expanding markets and securing new materials for domestic consumption and production. In this context, attributing the goal of resource maximization seems appropriate, and we are struck by the fact that the main contenders generally numbered three: Spain, Portugal,
5.7 The sources of preventive war
179
and the Netherlands in the sixteenth century; Spain, France, and Britain in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries; and Britain, France, and Germany in the nineteenth century. Ignoring as it does the role of so many other factors, including the geographically remote participation of the United States and the fact that a variety of colonial entanglements persisted long after the countries in question experienced their decline, we had best not make too much of such crudely drawn facts. However, in taking the long view and a global perspective, the Continental system of colonial powers is clearly system unstable, and in an approximate way its history is consistent with Remark 5.8. Yet, if we take a shorter and more myopic view - one in which the relevant system consists only of European states and in which colonial possessions have modest short-term military consequences on the Continent - relative resource maximization seems the more appropriate assumption. In this circumstance, we find periods of system stability embracing a larger number of countries that persist until some exogenous factor comes into play, such as one country's unanticipated industrial growth, an alternation in warfare's technology, or a decision maker who miscalculates and invests too heavily in military strength. Both assumptions about goals, then, may have their use, with one assumption yielding implications for one system and the other for a coexistent overlapping system. 5.7
The sources of preventive war
Even if a review of historical events were to support much of what has been outlined, we have offered at least one seemingly counter factual conclusion, Remark 5.7. Despite the prediction that countries threatened by the predominance of another possess coalitional strategies to counteract this threat, countries have succeeded in gaining hegemony. One possible explanation, of course, is that we have applied the word "hegemony" too broadly. Keohane (1984) argues that following World War II the United States became a hegemon, but if the American hegemony was a predominant one, it lasted but a few years. Thus, although we use predominant and hegemon interchangeably, hegemon must refer to something less than a country that is able to impose its will on all countries relevant to its welfare. Nevertheless, the unification of China under Ch'in, Rome at its peak, and the United States in the Western hemisphere all illustrate predominant hegemonies, whereas Germany in 1914 and 1941 nearly succeeded in establishing a Continental predominance, only to be blocked ultimately by a peripheral power from the other side of the Atlantic. We can attribute the American example to the circumstances of geography and to an economic growth rate that overcame the half-hearted opposition of
180 5 Preventive war Britain, as well as that of Spain and Mexico. The remaining examples, though, should be viewed as important "exceptions" to our analysis, and thus we should look to their sources. However, before examining those sources, we should insert a cautionary note about attempting to interpret our analysis (and Remark 5.7 in particular) as implying the possibility of avoiding preventive wars - of avoiding the outbreak of wars waged against the potential hegemon by some coalition of other states. Remark 5.7 merely emphasizes the possibility that voluntary transfers can avert the necessity for preventive conflict. Nevertheless, conflict of some degree may be required to effect such transfers - indeed, conflict may be the mechanism whereby transfers are enforced. In addition, our discussion of this remark reveals that coalitions against the potential hegemon are not the sole possible instruments of adjustment - winning coalitions that include the potential hegemon are viable alternatives. And because we have not specified the mechanisms whereby other coalitions effect transfers, those coalitions may employ conflict as well, in which case the preconditions for preventive war can yield not only conflict that is traditionally labeled preventive, but also conflict in which the potential hegemon is a member of the majority coalition. The rise of Athenian power may have set the stage for war between Athens and Sparta, but it did not make it inevitable - inevitability followed because other adjustments were somehow infeasible. Turning now to those circumstances that might occasion the emergence of a hegemon, as well as those that might require the choice of conflict to effect a resource adjustment, the most likely candidate (as with the disruptions of the forces that yield system stability in a world without growth and investment) concerns the transferability of resources and Assumption A2. Even if we take full cognizance of McNeilPs conclusion that international politics shapes domestic politics, the opposite must be true as well, and we know that domestic considerations often preclude such transfers and thereby preclude the efficient formation of coalitions. Indeed, this is perhaps one of the great tensions between international and domestic politics. Certainly, the rigidities of domestic politics frequently strengthen the hand of political leaders when negotiating agreements, as when one leader tries to convince another that certain actions are impossible and that unusual compromises are required. Yet, frequent also are those instances in which negotiators cannot modify commitments, such as the United States' relationship with Israel, which sometimes appear inconvenient from the perspective of international politics but not from the perspective of domestic politics. In addition to transfers, we also suppose that there are no domestic constraints that apply to investment decisions. It seems self-evident, however,
5.7 The sources of preventive war
181
that although the planning horizons of some decision makers may extend far into the future, the horizons of others extend only to the next election or meeting of stockholders; and internal political considerations play a significant role in the debate between expenditures on military procurement as against general research and development. It may not even be clear, moreover, whether an expenditure ought to be treated as an investment or as current consumption. A decision to develop a new weapons system has obvious short-term implications; but to the extent that this development yields new technology, it is also an investment. This blurred distinction occasions uncertainty and debate over the consequences of policy, which, by precluding certain investment patterns and requiring others, both inhibits and exacerbates the forces leading to preventive wars. This argument points the way to another previously discussed violation of our assumptions, namely, that information is complete. This assumption incorporates a number of "sins," such as the supposition that national leaders can calculate resources with precision and that they can identify exactly which coalitions are winning and which are losing. It certainly does not take much historical research to uncover dramatic instances of miscalculation, especially when it comes to estimating current and future resources of countries. We also assume implicitly that the countries in S are well-defined, so that we can judge whether there are n, or JZ + 1, or n — 1 players in the game. Geography, of course, blurs the relevance of countries, but this is a consideration that we shall try to accommodate in the next chapter. Even so, we cannot always judge whether a country is an independent actor or an extension of some larger state (recall the quip during its recent period of labor unrest that Poland would certainly fight in any NATOWarsaw Pact confrontation; the question was "who?"). Such knowledge is not window dressing to the planning of strategies. Knowing whether a country is an independent actor tells us something about political repercussions in other states when threats are made. This threat may be formulated to secure certain concessions, concessions that are impossible because of unbreakable linkages among countries. If the threat unexpectedly becomes a commitment, then the central premise upon which we have built our analysis - the wholly fluid nature of actions and compromises - is violated. Thus, a variety of considerations exogenous to the model determines the ultimate implications of a threatened predominance or a fear of becoming inessential. If the coalitional flexibility that our model assumes exists, hegemony as well as preventive wars are avoidable; but if that flexibility is absent then, barring the conditions of remarks such as 5.3 and 5.4, explicit conflict may be the only alternative. Some students of international
182
5 Preventive war
relations may wish for less ambiguous conclusions. The statistical literature on wars, after all, seems predicated on the supposition that there exists some simple linear relationship between "appropriately operationalized" independent variables and military conflict - that if "power" could somehow be defined and measured better, the R2in our regressions would increase. However, we cannot assert trivial relationships if those relationships have no theoretical basis, and those who try to simplify a complex reality by pretending that a simplicity pervades international affairs that does not characterize even the macroeconomics operating within the shell of those affairs and that decision makers are inherently less sensitive than the analyst to strategic complexity, are bound to failure. To reiterate what we have said throughout this text: our analysis, if anything, oversimplifies reality and thus it can merely uncover basic forces. If those forces operate at a level of complexity that is disconcerting to some, then the only tactic available for deducing a simple structure is the imposition of even more restrictive, less empirically valid assumptions. Finally, we should comment on the definition of security value and the assignment of preferences upon which our analysis in this chapter is based. In order to sidestep the necessity for modeling the sequential adjustment processes of investment and arms procurement, our assumption requires that a form of collective security operate to such a degree that decision makers take its operation as an unquestioned basis for their strategic calculations. Certainly, then, we sweep a great many issues under the rug, including the presumed reliability of other decision makers. In particular, our assumption requires that the operation of balance of power as we describe it in previous chapters is common knowledge. Such a supposition, though, may be less than compelling to those who direct the fates of regimes or nations, and we must leave the door open for refinements of the model, for alternative formulations, and for conclusions different from ours.
5.8
Appendix: Proofs of results Theorem 5.1
The validity of the result follows directly from our definitions. Let r /min be the minimum resource level that country / can choose such that S/(r/min) = 1. That is, s z (r /min ) = 1, whereas st(q < rimin) = 0 for all q satisfying r /min > q > 0. Temporarily, let rimin = rt whenever no such level exists for /. By definition, then, r' = (A-/min,..., rnmin) exists. It follows from this specification of A*/min and the description of preferences embodied in the definition
5.8 Appendix: Proofs of results
183
of a period-1 equilibrium that / will not invest more. Further, / will not invest less since this only reduces its resources in period 2 without increasing its security value in period 1. Finally, for those countries for which S;(q) = 0, for all qeRh i is either inessential in r', in which case we reset r imm equal to 0, or / can find a maximum investment (0, if necessary) such that it is essential in r'. Q.E.D.
Remark 5.1 It follows from the definition of essential that either all countries are essential in a three-person situation or only one country is essential and predominant. Since (S;r) is system stable, all countries are essential. To invest, country 1 must ensure that the next largest country, 2, cannot become predominant, which requires that (rx — /71) + r 3 >r 2 . To maximize /?!, we let equality hold, which implies the first equality in the remark. The remaining equalities follow in the same way. Q.E.D. Remark 5.2 There are three possibilities: (i) / invests too much so that it alone becomes inessential; (ii) i invests too much and renders one country predominant; and (iii) / invests too much and renders two countries, including itself, inessential. Condition (1) avoids the first possibility. If the inequality is reversed, then the other three countries can invest down to r4f in which case / is inessential, and none of the other countries has any incentive to change its strategy because they are all essential. Condition (2) avoids the second possibility. In the case of country 1, country 2 can become predominant unless [rx—p\] + r3 + r4 > r2. Algebraic manipulation yields the constraint on px that condition (2) specifies, and a parallel argument establishes the remainder of the condition. Suppose now that case (iii) applies. If 3 is the country in question, then 4 must be inessential also, as must 3 and 4 if they combine. But this can occur only if 1 is predominant, and condition (1) avoids that possibility. On the other hand, if the country in question is 2, it cannot be that only 2 and 4 are inessential, so suppose that 2 and 3 are inessential. But again, this means that 4 is inessential and that 1 is predominant. Hence, case (iii) is indistinct from (ii), and condition (2) avoids this possibility. Q.E.D. Theorem 5.2 No country is predominant if and only if no country controls more than half the resources. Formally, this means that, for all / e S, rt + wpt < (R+wI)/2, which, after some manipulation, is equivalent to
184
5 Preventive war
f "^
(5 A1)
*
To prove the sufficiency of the remark's first inequality, notice that because (S;r) is stable in the first period by assumption, R/l — r^O. So if pi < 7/2, since w>0, expression (5.A1) is satisfied. Condition (ii) is simply a restatement of expression (5. Al) when pt —7/2 > 0. That the conditions are necessary follows since, if/7/ —//2<0, then expression (5.A1) is satisfied automatically, whereas if condition (ii) is violated, then the inequality in (5.A1) is reversed and the system is unstable in period 2. Q.E.D. Remark 5.3 From Remark 5.1, / = 3r3 4-r2 — rx. Then no country is predominant for all w [condition (i) of Theorem 5.2] if rx < r2 + r3/3, if r2 < rx + r3, and if r3 > r2-rl. The last two inequalities are obviously always satisfied since rx> r2 > r3. Hence, all three-country systems that are system stable (that do not have a predominant country) cannot give rise to a predominant country after investment if rx < r2 + r 3 /3. Now suppose that rx > r2 + r 3 /3, in which case, by Theorem 5.2, no country is predominant if w<(r2 + r3-rx) + (3rl-3r2-r3). Necessity is implied by Theorem 5.2. Q.E.D. Remark 5.4 First, to show that if rt = R/4 for all / e S, notice that from the symmetry of (S; r) and the fact (from Theorem 5.1) that the period-1 equilibrium is unique, we must have pt = pj for all / and j , in which case r'{ — rj for all / and j . Hence, no one is predominant in period 2. Second, to show that the only four-country system in which the period-1 equilibrium necessarily implies a stable system in period 2 regardless of w, notice that, from Remark 5.2 and from the definition of 7, I=R — 4r4. Thus, from Theorem 5.2, no country becomes predominant regardless of w if and only if /•/ < R / 2 - r4, i = 1,2,3. Summing for / = 1, 2, and 3 yields 2 rt = R- r4 < 3R/2-3r4, which requires that R/4 0, then rt > r'(S— {/}). Soy, by investing any positive amount, renders itself inessential and the result cannot be a period-1 equilibrium. Now, to show that / can invest, we first establish this lemma: If ry- > rk and j is inessential in
5.8 Appendix: Proofs of results
185
(S; r ) , then k is inessential in (S; r ) . If k is essential, then by definition there
exists a CeW* such that keC, r(C-{k}) + rk>R/2 and r(C)-rk< R/2. Because rj>rk, it must be the case that r(C-{k}) + rj>R/2 and r(C) — Tj < R/2. So j is essential, which contradicts the assumption of the lemma that j is inessential. Turning to the proof of the remark, it must be true that ry < R/2, for all j ^ /. It follows from the lemma just stated that / can invest to reduce its resources in period 1 to r2, the second largest country: If / becomes inessential, all countries are inessential, which is impossible, so by All, the unique period-1 equilibrium is an r' in which / invests at least rt-r2. Q.E.D. Remark 5.6 From Remark 3.5, if rt = R/2 for some / e S, then (S; r) is resource stable and thus system stable. By Remark 5.5, no country can invest except /. But if w > 0 , then r" > 2 " = I A / / 2 in period 2, which is to say that / becomes predominant. Hence, S— {/} can threaten / in stage 3 of period 1 if / invests. Since r(S— {/}) = rt > /*/, S— {/} can force some reallocation, but in no case will / be allowed to secure more than half the resources in period 2. Since / is assured of controlling half by not investing, it prefers not to invest, in which case (S; r) describes period 2. Q.E.D. Remark 5.7 To prove sufficiency, we must specify the range of w such that expressions (5.1) and (5.2) in footnote 13 are satisfied: (i) If N< 0 (which means that the members of C except / invest more than half of the total investment), which implies that K< 0, and if M > 0, then to satisfy (5.1) and (5.2), the range of w is -L/K<w< -M/N; (ii) if N= 0, and (1) if K< 0, to be essential, w>-L/K, (2) if K > 0, L < 0, then w < -L/K, (3) \fK=0, L < 0 , then w > - l ; and (iii)if A/>0, and (1) if K< 0, then w > -L/K and w > -M/N, (2) if K>0, L < 0 , then -M/N<w<-L/K, (3) if AT = O, L < 0 , then w > - l . To prove necessity, notice that when the condition on w is not satisfied, ceterisparibus, conditions (5.1) and (5.2) are not satisfied, and / is not essential. Next consider the cases that are not included in the previous: (i) If N<0
and M < 0 , then r(C- [i}) + wp(C - { / } ) > (R + wI)/2.
In other
186 5 Preventive war words, coalition C— {/} possesses more than or exactly half of the total resources at period 1, and invests more than half of the total investment. Hence, Ce Wbut C$ W*, and / is not essential; (ii) if Af>0, K>0, and L > 0, then r(C) + wp(C) < (R + wI)/2. In other words, coalition C possesses exactly or less than half of the total resources at period 1 and invests exactly or less than half of the total investment, which implies that C$W; hence, / is not essential. Q.E.D. Remark 5.8 Because rt < R/2 for all /, any three-person coalition is winning. Consider now the allocation (R/3, R/3, R/3,0) in the presumed set of core points, Co. From Remark 5.1, all three countries invest everything to yield the postinvestment outcome ((l+w)R/39 (l+w)R/3, (l+w)R/3,0). Because the equivalent outcomes in which we permute the identity of the countries do not dominate each other, to prove that such a set is a core we must show that no alternative outcome dominates any outcome in Co. We have three cases: (i) (1,4} is winning and they divide all resources evenly between themselves (since an uneven distribution renders one of them predominant). Since 1 and 4 cannot invest in this event, such an allocation dominates what results from r in Co if and only if both countries prefer R/2 to what they get from r, and, in particular, if one of them prefers R/2 to (l + w)R/3. But this inequality requires that w<0.5; (ii) all four countries choose the allocation r' = (r[,r2,r'3,r'A), where r->0 for all /. To establish that r' cannot dominate any element of Co, say r, it suffices to show that this allocation cannot dominate the element of Co that eliminates 4, and, in particular, it suffices to show that country 2 prefers R/3 to r2. From Remark 5.3, p2 ^ R- 2r[. But also, since 1 is the largest country, r2 < r{, which implies that p2 is maximized at r[ — R/3. The question then becomes whether an increase in r{ over R/3 (and thus on the allowable values of r[ and r'2) compensates for the decreased investment that 2 can make. Country 2's maximum feasible postinvestment resources equal r[+w(R — 2r{), and the derivative of this quantity with respect to r{ is negative whenever w>0.5; and (iii) consider any allocation of the form r' = (r{, A*2, /"3,0). Once again, we need only show that 2 prefers r to rr. As before, 2's maximum postinvestment resources are, from Remark 5.1, r{ + w(r2 + A*3 - r[) = r{+w(R -2r[), the derivative of which is negative as r[ increases if w > 0.5. Q.E.D.
CHAPTER 6
Geography, balancers, and central powers
The geographic location of a state in the world is of basic importance in defining its problems of security. It conditions and influences all other factors... [and] regional location defines potential enemies and allies and perhaps even the limits of a state's role as a participant in a system of collective security. Nicholas J. Spykman, The Geography of the Peace (1944, pp. 22-3)
If a Soviet strategic planner could be granted one wish, it should be to move his country somewhere else. Stephen M. Walt, The Origins of Alliances (1987, p. 277)
A fundamental difficulty with formulating a fully comprehensive theory of stability in anarchic international systems lies in conceptualizing a country's resources so that we adequately summarize the strategic imperatives of a decision maker seeking to ensure a country or a regime's sovereignty. In his early work on coalitions, the size principle, and the application of cooperative game theory to a formulation of the concept of balance of power, for example, Riker (1962) assumes that such systems are constantsum games in which winning coalitions are those that control a majority of resources. Much of the formal theorizing in the balance-of-power literature, including our analysis thus far, follows Riker's lead of assuming that resources are additive across a coalition's members and that any coalition can defeat a coalition with fewer resources. This formulation supposes implicitly that resources to attack one country can be used equally well to defend against an attack, or that those resources can be directed with equal effectiveness at any country. Yet, such assumptions are not wholly general. History tells us that even inferior land armies may be effective for defending against a more powerful adversary if that adversary has not the technology for supply far from its home base, and that even if an army can defeat a contiguous adversary, it may be useless against one with even a modest water barrier. Although the United States had perhaps the most technologically advanced and powerful army in the world during the Civil War, we can generally ignore its influence in nineteenth 187
188
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
century European great-power diplomacy simply because of its geographic remoteness. Indeed, although a tenet of today's strategic thinking is that modern technology fundamentally changes the implications of such barriers and distance, Morganthau's (1959) assertion that "[t]he most stable factor upon which the power of a nation depends is obviously geography" (p. 102) and his more specific argument that the geographical location of the United States remains a fundamental factor of permanent importance which the foreign policies of all nations must take into account, however different its bearing upon political decisions might be today from what it was in other periods of history (p. 103) finds contemporary support in Pearson's (1974, p. 455) reasoning that "even in the post-World-War-II technologically advanced environment, geographic distance seems to represent a cost in the movement of troops which all but the most powerful states are unable or unwilling to pay," and in Bueno de Mesquita's (1981b, p. 44) assertion that modern technology does not eliminate the necessity for discounting capabilities among even today's great powers. This argument's implication is that formulations of balance of power in which resources are treated symmetrically, although valuable for an initial understanding of the problem, may mislead us about the necessary and sufficient conditions for stability, and may be inappropriate for interpreting a broad range of historical events and processes. Indeed, profoundly important questions cannot be answered adequately unless geography is taken explicitly into account. Should we, for example, attribute Britain's role as "balancer" in the nineteenth century to the motives and diplomatic skills of key decision makers or to its unique geographical position with respect to the Continental powers? Waltz (1979, p. 164) correctly observes that "the notion of a balancer is more a historical generalization than a theoretical concept," but he goes further to assert that "balance of power theory cannot incorporate the role of balancer because the playing of the role depends on such narrowly defined and historically unlikely conditions" (1979, p. 164). Is this view justified, or is there a general theoretical explanation for, in Churchill's words, "the wonderful unconscious tradition of British foreign policy"? What precisely are the advantages and disadvantages of geographical distance? For example, should we attribute the unification of China at the end of the Warring States Period in 221 B.C. at the hands of a geographically "peripheral," as against central, power as mere happenstance brought about by the fortuitous combination of military and diplomatic skill, or is it reasonable to hypothesize that such peripheral powers have an advantage over central ones? Can that part of Germany's special, threatening role in European power
6.1 Conceptualizing the consequences of geography
189
politics from 1871 to 1945, which is seen as a consequence of its geographically central position, be understood theoretically and generally? What are the implications for international stability of any decline in geography's importance, as occasioned by advances in the technologies of weapons systems? Can the removal of natural barriers to warfare disadvantage individual states, but nevertheless make international systems more stable? Finally, to the extent that nuclear weapons neutralize the great powers and render them unable or unwilling to play anything but a peripheral role in regional conflicts, what are the strategic imperatives in particular regions such as the Middle East, where conventional weapons and resources, and thus geography, follow a classical logic? To answer such questions, this chapter extends our earlier analysis to include the asymmetries occasioned by geography in the use of resources. In formulating this extension, however, we must make certain compromises. First, our analysis focuses on the model that Chapters 3 and 4 detail, and it forgoes any treatment of differential resource growth and preventive wars. Second, we only treat three-country systems. Naturally, we prefer a general ^-country model, but even the analysis of a special case is enlightening, since many of our results are unanticipated. We identify, for example, the circumstances under which one country is uniquely positioned to play the role of "balancer." We find that "central powers" countries that are contiguous to two noncontiguous powers - are at a disadvantage in terms of the resources they must possess to be essential and to maintain system stability. We also find that if geography discounts the offensive capabilities of all countries (but not "too much"), then no threecountry system can be system stable. Thus, although we might disagree as to whether war is made less likely by modern technology because that technology increases the costs of conflict to mutually unacceptable levels, our analysis shows that even with this consideration aside, those features of modern weapons technology that have the effect of removing the barriers of geography among all great powers simultaneously make international systems more stable. 6.1
Conceptualizing the consequences of geography
The essential feature of geography that we seek to capture in our analysis is that resources may be especially advantageous for defense as against offense, and they may be especially advantageous or disadvantageous when used to attack one country as compared to another. Germany's army in 1940 might be well suited for overwhelming France but not England, even though France certainly had a more powerful army than England. Yet,
190
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
even if ill-suited for attacking across the Channel, that army was sufficient for repelling a counterinvasion by England alone. Spain once held an advantage over England in colonizing the world and even dominated the Continent, but it could not extend its power to invading England; and a relatively minor "power" in the New World, led by an oft-defeated general, could secure its independence from a state that was almost certainly the most powerful in Europe. On the other hand, if we conceptualize resources not in terms of direct military capabilities, but instead as economic control, this special asymmetry between offense and defense remains relevant. Aside from the obvious advantages of language and familiarity with legal institutions, countries can erect barriers to investment by foreigners so that domestic entrepreneurs can more readily secure economic control of industrial capacity within their own countries than they can of capacity elsewhere. In whatever way we choose to conceptualize and measure resources, then, it seems only reasonable to suppose that defense has an advantage over offense - that a "unit" of resource mobilized for defense can at least counter a unit of resource mobilized by a second country for offense against the first. Hence, to accommodate the imperatives of geography, we first reinterpret the resource vector r a s a summary of the defensive capabilities of countries. Next, we suppose that a country's resources, say country /, can be applied offensively against another country, say j , but only after they are discounted by some parameter dtj, where 0 < dtj < 1. Thus, we let r/rf/y denote /'s offensive capabilities with respect to j , and as a modification of Assumption A6, which posits complete symmetry in offensive and defensive capability, we assume instead that 1 A6'. Country / can defeat j (/ can unilaterally absorb all of y's resources but not vice versa) if and only if r/rf/y- > rj9 and j can defeat / if and only if rjdjt > rh 1
Assumption A6' differs from the way in which Wright (1942, pp. 1389-91) tries to incorporate distance. Wright assumes that the ability to resist aggression equals the "degree of separation" minus the disparity in power. Although /'s "ability to resist aggression" on the part of country j is not a theoretical primitive in our analysis, we can roughly take it to be measured by /•,• — ry djt, so that (in Wright's notation) ry djt = 5// — Pi. Boulding (1962) assumes that offensive capabilities decline monotonically with distance, as does Bueno de Mesquita (1981b); however, because we treat countries as discrete and stationary entities, all such accommodations for distance are equivalent as long as we assume that geography discounts offensive but not defensive capability. Admittedly, though, our assumption is a problematical abstraction for a country such as Russia in which the discounting that ought to be applied with respect to other European powers should differ from the one that should be applied even today for the Asian powers of China and Japan. For additional discussion of the results this chapter reports, see Niou and Ordeshook (1989a).
6.1 Conceptualizing the consequences of geography
191
Notice that even if resources as represented by the r's are not equal, neither country may be able to defeat the other if the d's are sufficiently small. An immediate implication of this fact concerns the number and nature of winning coalitions. Recall that if all d's equal 1 in a three-country system, then either one country is predominant (if it controls more than half the resources) or all two-country coalitions are winning in the sense that they can overwhelm the third. With discounting for geography, however, we must generalize the definition of the set W* of two-country winning coalitions as W*=\
CCS, |C| = 2, 2 ieC
So if the d's are sufficiently small, then W* is empty, whereas with an appropriate selection of discount factors, only one or two coalitions may be winning. The comparison of the results in this chapter with those we offer in Chapters 3 and 4 is especially important. For example, we can interpret du = dji = 1 as meaning that / and j are contiguous, at least from the perspective of the technology of offensive resources. If resources can be converted into weapons systems that can render geographical barriers irrelevant, then even if countries are not geographically contiguous, they ought to be treated as contiguous. Theorem 3.1 tells us that if all d's equal 1, then all three-country systems are system stable. Hence, the results we obtain in this chapter tell us what effect such modern technologies have on international stability. To deduce results formally so that we can make such comparisons, however, we must impose a simplifying assumption about a particular type of asymmetry in the discount variables that reduces the complexity of the conditions for stability that we offer later. Specifically, any asymmetry in the d's of the form d;j > djt means that / has a technological advantage over j - that /'s resources are more effective for attacking j than are j's resources for attacking / (viz., the United States' short-lived advantage over the Soviet Union following World War II). If no such asymmetric superiority exists, then A12. dtj = dji for all / and j in S. Keeping in mind that A12 implies nothing about the relation between dtj and dik or between d^ and djk, we use this assumption to facilitate analysis, although it is not required by all of our results. We should emphasize that we do not suppose that this assumption models all historical circumstances. Certainly, asymmetric investments in navies generated asymmetric offensive and defensive capabilities among European powers throughout
192
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
modern history, just as the Mongol hordes and barbarians of the Steppes could invade and replace established empires because of the special advantages of mobility afforded them by their horsemanship. To illustrate now how our analyses in Chapter 3 and 4 are altered with the preceding reformulation of resources, consider the three-country system with the initial resource distribution (140,120,40). If all rf's equal 1, then this system is system but not resource stable. Suppose, however, that dn-1> ^13 = ^23 = 0-2. Then 2 cannot absorb 3, nor can 1 absorb 3. But 1 can attack 2 without 3 being able to assist 2 in a viable counter - 3 cannot transfer sufficient resources to 2 so that 2 can defend against 1 nor can 3 divert sufficient resources from 1 by attacking it. Thus, 1 absorbs 2, and, with 260 units of resources, it subsequently absorbs 3. Hence, even though it initially controls less than half the resources, country 1 is in fact predominant. Alternatively, (160,80,60) is wholly stable if dl2 = dn = 2/3 and d23 = 0.7. To see this, notice that if 1 threatens to absorb 2 and become predominant, then 3 can join 2 in a viable counter by attacking 1. If 3 attacks 1 then 1 must hold r3rf31= 40 resources in reserve to counter 3's attack, leaving it with insufficient resources to threaten 2. And because 2 cannot threaten 3, (160,80,60) is resource and thus system stable. This simple example, then, illustrates a fact that we might have suspected was true, namely, that with geographical considerations taken into account, countries can become predominant even if they do not initially control a majority of resources, and countries with a majority of resources need not be predominant. Proceeding further to generalize the implications of this example requires that we choose between two alternative assumptions about how countries can use the resources of other countries. Previously, we assume that if country / defeats country j and absorbs all of y's resources (Assumption A5), then / can target rt + rj resources at k. However, now we must choose between these two assumptions: A13. If / absorbs y, then / can target (rt + rj)dik resources at k, and A13'. If / absorbs y, then / can target ridik + rjdjk resources at k. Choosing between these two assumptions entails asking whether, in the case of A13', it is merely the sovereignty of resources that are transferred (in the same way as the United States used its strategic position following World War II to target the resources of both Japan and Germany at the Soviets) or whether, in the case of A13, / absorbs y's resources into its own territory (in much the same way as the Soviet Union absorbed
6.1 Conceptualizing the consequences of geography
193 2
Germany's captured industrial plant after that same war). If resources refer to territory and the population it holds, then the second assumption is appropriate. A13', for example, fits the scenarios of the early development of empires in which, because of the poor technology of transport, armies had to rely for their food, and even for their personnel, on indigenous, conquered populations. If, on the other hand, resources are readily transportable (such as when the resource is wealth), then we should impose the first assumption. Thus, both assumptions are plausible. A13, though, seems more consonant with an analysis that conceptualizes resources and international conflict in terms of economic wealth and control of industrial capabilities. Thus, all of the results we offer in this text employ A13. However, when we come to the central result about stability, notably Theorem 6.1, we indicate a parallel condition that assumes A13'. Before proceeding further with the clarification of some definitions and with our formal results, let us preview the broad outline of the results we establish. In general, we learn that, at least for three-country systems, geography profoundly affects the circumstances under which system stability prevails. We know from Theorem 3.2, of course, that if dtj — dik = djk = 1, then ({/, j , k]; r) is system stable. Theorem 6.1, on the other hand, establishes that if none of these d's is equal to 1 - if no two countries are contiguous - then the system cannot be system stable. Stability requires either that two countries be both contiguous to a third or that two countries be contiguous to each other. The possibility that two countries are contiguous to a third but not to each other gives rise to the notion of a "central power," and our analysis shows that central powers are disadvantaged if the discounting of resources between the two "peripheral powers" is sufficiently great - the central power must control more resources than either peripheral power in order to ensure its sovereignty. The possibility that two countries are contiguous but not to a third, on the other hand, gives rise to the notion of a balancer - the sole peripheral power - who, as we shall see, enjoys the advantage of being able to ensure that it is near-predominant. We cannot establish these substantively tantalizing results, however, unless we render certain ideas more precise. In particular, we turn now to the issue of when a country can become predominant - when it can threaten the sovereignty of others without confronting any viable counterthreats. Without considering geography, the corollary to Theorem 3.1 tells us that in three-country systems, any attack by one country on a 2
A third possibility allows a country to choose the portion of its resources to target via djk and djk. This possibility yields a somewhat more complicated analysis, but the conclusions we offer do not appear to be qualitatively altered.
194
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
smaller one threatens the third (unless the attacking country already controls over half the resources in the system), and, correspondingly, any attack by a country on another can be countered by a viable counter. However, with geographical considerations, a country, say /, can become predominant, first, only if, upon the absorption of, say y's resources, it can overcome the third, k. Second, predominance requires that k cannot effectively assist j in formulating a viable counterthreat by transferring resources to j. The final requirement for the predominance of / is that k cannot participate in a viable counterthreat by attacking / directly (thereby causing / to divert some share to defending against k while attacking j). Formally, this yields the following revised definition of predominant: Country / is predominant if and only if neither j nor k, acting alone or in concert, can formulate a viable counterthreat to a threat by / that renders / predominant - if and only if there exists a jeS-{i] such that: (1) (ri + rj)dik>rk (i.e., if / absorbs j9 i can defeat k); (2) ridij>rkdkj + rj (i.e., / can defeat j even if k transfers all of its resources to j); and (3) r/C^- > rkdkidiJ + rJ (i.e., / can defeat j even if k tries to aid j by attacking / directly). Correspondingly, recall that, without any consideration given to geography, country / is near-predominant if rt = R/2 - if the addition of e resources, however small e might be, renders i predominant. This idea can be generalized by removing the reference to the specific number R/2 and by saying simply that / is near-predominant with rh first, if / is not predominant, and, second, if it is rendered predominant whenever its resources are increased to rt + e, where e is any number that exceeds 0.3 Before proceeding further, it is important that we first verify that a two-country (bipolar) system can be system and resource stable. For the model offered in Chapters 2 and 3, two-country systems are system stable if and only if both countries control an equal share of resources. As we have previously noted, however, such a "knife-edged" stability condition is the by-product of our mathematics - of the fact that we have not incorporated the momentum of existing alliances and the constraints of domestic politics, and of our failure to consider the uncertainty confronting real decision makers in their assessments of resources and their attitudes toward risk in their assessments of strategic options. We should make 3
Under A13', we say that / is predominant if and only if there exists a j in S- [i j such that (1) ndik + rjdjk >rk- that is, after / eliminates and absorbs all of j , k can be eliminated; (2) ndy > rj + rkdjk - that is, / can defeat j even if k aids j by transferring resources to j ; and (3) (ri — rkdkj)dij > rj - that is, / can defeat j even if k aids j by attacking / directly. The definition of near-predominance is unchanged with this alternative assumption.
6.1 Conceptualizing the consequences of geography
195
certain, however, that incorporating geography does not destroy so fragile a condition, and, in the process, check whether our formulation of geography renders bipolar systems more stable. The following remark, which does not require that dtj = djh answers our query: Remark 6.1. In two-country systems, either one country is predominant or the system is both system stable and resource stable. Neither country is predominant if and only if 1/(1 + dtj) > rt/R >
This remark follows from our assumptions and some simple algebra. First, suppose that country / has no threat against j (i cannot defeat j ) , in which case we must have rtdij rt >Rdjt/{\ + tfy7), which implies the inequality in the remark. To see how this result relates to our analyses in Chapters 3 and 4, notice that if dij = dji = 1, then the inequality becomes 1/2 > rt/R > 1/2, or simply rt = R/2. More generally, the inequalities in Remark 6.1 can be satisfied by an appropriate choice of rt only if the first term is at least as great as the third; otherwise we have a contradiction and system stability is impossible. Some simple algebraic manipulation shows, however, that l/(l + djj)>dji/(l + dji) if and only if l>rfy7d/y-, which is an inequality that is necessarily satisfied, given the constraints on the rf's that they not exceed 1. Thus, system stability is possible in two-country systems (as is resource stability since both forms of stability are equivalent in such systems). And not only is system stability possible in two-country systems after we take geography into consideration, but Remark 6.1 establishes that stability no longer requires a "knife-edged" equality of resources. For example, even if country 1 has twice the resources of country 2, the system ({1,2}; (200,100)) is stable and country 2 is essential as long as tf12<0.5. We might be led to infer from this discussion of the two-country case that the discounting of offensive resources occasioned by geography renders both system and resource stability more likely - that the constraints on the r's required to ensure a country's sovereignty are weakened. However, this implication is an illusion that illustrates the necessity for a more complete analysis. To see the nature of this illusion, we proceed by proving two lemmas. Our first lemma concerns only the issue of technological possibilities in the context of the viable counterthreats that countries can make, and it does not constitute a prediction about final outcomes. Letting S= {/, y, k}9 and letting C= {/, j} be any two-country coalition in the set of minimum winning coalitions W*9 we define the function gj(C) to
196
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
equal the maximum amount of resources that / can gain either from k alone or from k and j together, such that i is not rendered predominant.4 Lemma 6.1. For {i9j} in W*, ridu
R l
'
To see first that this lemma is consistent with our previous analysis, let the d's equal 1, in which case gz({/, j}) = (rJ-{-rk — ri)/2. So, for example, if r = (120,100,80) then g1({l,2j) = g1({l,3}) = 30, which is to say that country 1 can expect to win at most 30 units of resources, since 2 and 3 can block 1 from winning more and becoming predominant. Similarly, gidh 2}) = g2({2,3}) = 50 and g3({l, 3}) = g3({2,3}) = 70. (Notice that Lemma 6.1 does not depend on the assumption that dtj = djt for all / and j.) Lemma 6.1 extends this reasoning to establish the maximum transfer a country can anticipate when another country, using the transfer as part of a viable counter, takes careful account of geographical considerations so as to merely render the recipient near-predominant and not predominant. Lemma 6.1, however, does not inform us about the circumstances under which a country is assured of having viable counterthreats that guarantee its existence and stability. Indeed, since one type of counter is a transfer that renders another country near-predominant, we must first learn what near-predominance requires. Without geography taken into consideration, we know that a country is near-predominant if and only if it controls precisely half the resources. Our next lemma establishes necessary and sufficient conditions for a country to be near-predominant when the d's in our model are taken into account.5 4
The statement of Lemma 6.1 is considerably more complicated with Assumption A13', owing to the possibility that after j loses its sovereignty, some of / and k's resources will be contiguous (their shares of j). To prove a parallel lemma, then, we also need to establish the following: If / threatens j , to join in a viable counter with j that maximizes the geographically discounted resource disparity between {/} and {j, k], k should transfer resources to j if dkj > dtj dik, and k should target its resources directly at / if this inequality is reversed. The result using A13', which parallels Lemma 6.1, now establishes that
if djk
5
otherwise,
These formidable expressions lack, to our eye at least, any intuitive meaning, and since we do not require them in the proof of our central results, we spare the reader their derivation, as well as the equally cumbersome proof of the alternate form of Lemma 6.2 that follows. The lemma that parallels Lemma 6.2 using Assumption A13' is as follows: If {/,y) and {/, k] are winning, then / is near-predominant if and only if
6.2 System and resource stability
197
Lemma 6.2. For any / e 5, / is near-predominant if and only if (1) r^j = rtdik = rj + rk\ and (2) either dkj = 1 or dki = du = 1. The conditions of this lemma are substantively important. If we suppose that dkj — 1 means that k and j are contiguous (and, therefore, that dJk = l), then a country can be near-predominant only if the other two countries in the system are contiguous (dkJ = 1) or if / is contiguous to both other countries (dki = dy = 1). Hence, if we imagine Russia and China as the sole contiguous adversaries in the three-country system {China, Russia, United States}, then only the United States can become near-predominant. If, however, the United States and Russia are "contiguous" as well (which is one interpretation of the technology of nuclear deterrence), then only Russia can become near-predominant. Of course, if technology renders all three countries "contiguous," then any one of the three can become near-predominant. Similarly, with respect to the latter part of nineteenth century, if we ignore Britain, then in the Continental system {France, Germany, Russia}, only Germany has the potential to become near-predominant. On the other hand, if we treat Russia and France as a single entity that is contiguous to Austria-Germany, then only Britain can be nearpredominant in the system {Britain, France-Russia, Austria-Germany}.6 To the extent, then, that system and resource stability depend on the ability of countries to form viable counterthreats by rendering another country near-predominant, it is in this way that the stability of systems depends directly on geography or on the technology of resources. 6.2
System and resource stability
Before stating the necessary and sufficient conditions for both system and resource stability, we ought to keep in mind that without geographical considerations, all three-country systems are system stable (provided that no country controls more than half the resources), since, if no country is near-predominant, every country necessarily controls enough resources to render someone else near-predominant. With geography taken into account, a new possibility emerges, namely, that the discount factors are so
6
m2Lx[ridij-rj-rkdikdij,ridik-rk-ridijdik]=0 whenever djk
198
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
great that no two-person coalition is winning. However, barring this possibility, we must follow the same logic as before with respect to a viable counter in order to establish the conditions for system stability. That is, a three-country system is system stable if and only if (1) geography renders the three countries irrelevant to each other's security; or (2) one country is near-predominant; or (3) each country can, as a viable counterthreat, render another near-predominant by the transfer of some appropriate sum of resources. The formal statement of these conditions - in particular, identifying formally the circumstances under which every country has a viable counter to every threat - provides us with the necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability that we seek.7 Theorem 6.1. A three-country system is system stable if and only if (1) W* is empty; or (2) for some ie 5, / is near-predominant; or (3) for any ieS such that {j,k}eW*, then there exists a C = {/, j) such that (a) (rt + rj)dJk > rk, (b) du = djk, and (c) either d ij = djk = \ or dik = \. A straightforward corollary to this theorem, then, is as follows: Corollary. If [i,j], {j,k}, and {/,/:} are all winning coalitions, then (5; r) is system stable if and only if all the tf's equal 1 (if all countries are contiguous). One way to interpret this theorem is to consider the following result about systems that violate condition (3): Remark 6.2. If there are only two winning coalitions, say {/,yj and {j, k] in a three-country system, if dtj > djk, and if j is not predominant when it absorbs either / or k, then the system cannot be system stable. In particular, a stable two-country system will emerge without /. To see the logic of this remark, suppose j is not predominant over / even if j controls ry -I- rk resources and that it is not predominant over k 7
Under assumption A13', condition (3) becomes simply: if every country is in some minimum winning coalition. This follows since if {/, k) is winning, then by the result in footnote 4, a = gi({ij}) rki and by the result in footnote 5, k does not control sufficient resources to render / nearpredominant.
6.2 System and resource stability
199
8
even if j controls rt + rj resources. Notice from Lemma 6.1 and from the definition of gj that j gains something from each winning coalition. Since j is the sole pivot between minimal winning coalitions, it follows that there cannot be any viable counter to a threat by {/, j) to eliminate k or by {j, k] to eliminate /. It follows from Lemma 6.1 that #,•({/, j})< gj({j, k}) if and only if djk < dij9 so, in particular, j prefers a coalition with k if and only if djk 133.33. Suppose now that 1 and 2 threaten 3. 8
So as not to confuse the assumption about predominance with the assumption that {/, j] and {/, k] are winning, the assumption that i is not predominant even if it absorbs the resources of the third power requires that (r/ + r^dy < ry and (r, + rj)dik ^ rk, whereas the supposition that [itj] and [i,k] are winning requires that r / ^ + r ^ ^ y >O anc* rjdJk>rk.
200
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers Country 3 can respond by transferring 46.66 to 1. Since 2 and 3 are contiguous, and since t/13 = rf12, it matters little, from l's perspective, how resources are distributed between 2 and 3 - 1 cannot overcome {2,3}, and the system is "frozen." On the other hand, suppose that d23 = 0.$ as well. As before, 1 cannot be allowed to control more than 166.66 resources. The problem for 3, however, is that it cannot now "buy" stability with a transfer to 1. If 3 proposes to transfer 46.66 resources as before to 1 then, due to the discount between 2 and 3,1 can attack 3 and {2,3} cannot provide an effective counter: 0.8(166.66) > 0.8(100)+ 80-46.66. Indeed, we see here that 0.8(166.66) exceeds x( 100) + 80-46.66 for any value of x less than 1 - for any degree of noncontiguity between 2 and 3.
The conditions of Theorem 6.1 are important since they imply substantively meaningful results about the special role of countries that balance in international systems and countries that we call central powers. However, postponing the interpretation of this theorem for the moment, let us first use it to define, in conjunction with the definitions of predominant and near-predominant, a reformulation of the characteristic function for the cooperative three-person game among countries; thus: v(S) = R and v(i, j) = rt + rj and v(k) = rk if W* is empty or if / or j are near-predominant.
(6.1)
Clearly, if W* is empty, no threats are possible, so, trivially, there is a valid counter to every threat in which no country has to transfer resources to others. If some / is near-predominant, then, as in our earlier model, j and k cannot threaten each other for fear that / can become predominant (Assumption A6), nor will / join in a coalition to threaten a third country since it knows that it will not be allowed to gain any resources in that coalition. Next, and if either / or j is near-predominant if / or j controls 6 additional resources, d
(6.2)
If / is not near-predominant, but if it can join with j to eliminate k (if {/, j) e W*), then, by Theorem 6.1, k can ensure that it loses no more than 5 by ceding 5 to /. Finally, v(C) = R and v(i, i $ C) = 0 otherwise.
(6.3)
Having thus defined the characteristic function for a constant-sum threeperson game, and assuming (as before) that a system is resource stable
6.3 Implications: Balancers and central powers
201
if and only if that three-person game has a core, we then have the following: Theorem 6.2. A three-country system is resource stable if and only if W* is empty or if there is an ieS such that / is nearpredominant. Thus, a three-country system is resource stable if and only if the d's are sufficiently small so as to render each country essentially irrelevant to the others, or if the conditions of Lemma 6.2 are satisfied - which excludes systems of three noncontiguous but nevertheless jointly relevant countries. 6.3
Implications: Balancers and central powers
Perhaps the most important implication that we can draw from our analysis is that once we take geography into account, not all three-country systems are necessarily system stable. Theorem 6.1 leaves open the possibility that whenever all d's are not equal to 1 - whenever geography matters - system stability depends on the specific character of geographical dissimilarities. Indeed, part (3) of that theorem tells us that whenever there is discounting between all pairs of countries owing to geography, then as long as that discounting is not so great as to render each country a separate "system,"system stability among three countries is impossible. With this in mind, it is reasonable to speculate that World War II ended the applicability of the logic of the diplomatic imperatives that dictated great-power international politics in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. The histories of those centuries, as well as the first half of ours, are commonly described as a constant process of negotiation and balancing, in which stability, if it existed at all, existed because of the diplomatic skills of key decision makers. To the extent that negotiation and balancing, as well as the striving for advantage, were conscious objectives, we can surmise that participants perceived no natural stability to their systems and that negotiation, threat, and counterthreat were understood as essential components of any periods of stability. If there was a natural and easily attained stability, then certainly it should not have been so difficult to achieve, nor so fragile that it led to major wars. The preceding analysis - in particular, the conclusion that geographical considerations can undermine system stability - suggests that we ought to look toward geography as a key component of any discussion of history. With our attention focused in Europe, it is interesting to see also how our analysis explains why Britain in particular is credited with playing the role of balancer in earlier centuries. It is tempting to attribute this role to the goals of its leaders and its business elite. Yet, if that is our
202
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
explanation, then we must also explain those goals. Short of pursuing a complete theory of history, we note simply that Britain alone is separated from the continent by any meaningful natural barrier, whereas the remaining key actors at the several important historical periods are essentially contiguous. (Napoleon's drive on Russia was not with a contiguous adversary, as his defeat reveals, but it is only when he challenged Britain's security by challenging contiguous adversaries that Britain became a balancing actor). So if we look at Lemma 6.2, we see that only Britain can be a near-predominant country - explicitly or implicitly ceding resources to any other country cannot ensure stability (Russia, which we might also conceptualize as being noncontiguous, was simply too economically backward and too weak to play Britain's role of becoming near-predominant). This is not to say that other countries cannot become predominant through technology or by the miscalculation of others. However, Britain's special geography rendered it a particularly distinctive coalition partner: it alone could be rendered near-predominant (which, in reality, owing to uncertainty and the like, is a less precise concept than that which our theory presumes) without fear that miscalculation could render it predominant. This discussion, though, goes only part of the way to a direct contradiction of Waltz's assertion, noted earlier, that the role of a balancer cannot be formally incorporated into a balance-of-power analysis (although Waltz can be defended with the supposition that his argument applied only to the then-existent balance-of-power models). However, to see that this assertion is incorrect, consider the following definition of a balancer that incorporates three ideas: first, the country in question, /, must be capable of determining which of the two coalitions of which it can be a member is winning (it must be able to ensure the defeat of either potential aggressor); second, the system must be system stable so as to preclude the possibility that / is not merely a potentially predominant country; and, finally, the system should not be resource stable in order to assure that there are some incentives for the formation of coalitions. Country / is a balancer in (S = {/, j , k]; r) if and only if {/, j} and [i,k] are winning and (S;r) is system but not resource stable. Without geography as a consideration, of course, every country in a system-stable three-country system is a balancer. What we are particularly interested in, though, are the circumstances, owing to geography, which place one country uniquely in this role - the circumstances under which, barring an opportunity to become predominant, the optimal strategy for one country is to side with one side and then the other as circumstances dictate so as to ensure its own survival, with system stability as the byproduct. The following theorem, which follows almost as a corollary to Theorem 6.1, establishes this condition:
6.3 Implications: Balancers and central powers
203
Theorem 6.3. Country / in S = {/, j , k] is the unique balancer in (5; r) if and only if (1) djk = 1 (countries j and k are contiguous); (2) dij = dik = d<\ (country / is not contiguous to either j or k)\ (3) d(rj + rk) < rt (the coalition {j,k} cannot defeat /); and (4) d{rt + rj)>rk and d(rj + rk)>:rj (coalitions [i,j] and [i9k] are winning). The theorem, then, reveals that Britain's role as balancer was not the mere accident of skillful diplomacy or the realization of a particular diplomatic stance that other countries could have adopted as well. Instead, Theorem 6.3 suggests that Britain was uniquely positioned to play its role, and thus - to contradict Waltz - it provides a theoretical explanation for that role (we say "suggests" since our analysis presumes three countries rather than the six or so major powers that played on the stage of nineteenth-century European politics). This theorem also permits us to respond to the speculation that Britain played its role merely because it was "a status quo power" or that a tradition begun by Cardinal Wolsey's policies toward the Habsburg monarchies was a mere accident of leadership. Rather, Theorem 6.3 turns the "causal arrow" around and suggests that it was such a power and that it enjoyed such leadership as a result of its unique natural position. The rise of Germany's navy, Britain's involvement in a continental war, and technology destroyed the uniqueness of this position, but it established a new peripheral power, the United States, which played its role in two successive world wars. Theorem 6.3 is consistent with some of the intuition about balancing that we find in the literature, but not all of it. Waltz (1979, p. 164), for example, argues that Britain met this role because she satisfied three conditions: The first of these was that the margin of power on the side of the aggressor not be so large that British strength added to the weaker side would be insufficient to redress the balance... [T] he second condition was that Britain's ends on the continent remain negative, for positive ends help to determine alignments Finally ... Britain required a status in power at least equal to that of the mightiest. Waltz's first condition corresponds to (4) in the theorem; the meaning of his second condition is unclear, except perhaps to require geographical remoteness - condition (2); but Waltz's last condition is clearly incorrect. Morgenthau (1966, p. 340), however, comes closer to tapping the intuition behind Theorem 6.3: Britain was capable of making its beneficial contributions to peace and stability only because it was geographically remote from the centers of friction and conflict, because it had no vital interests in the stakes of these conflicts as such, because it had the opportunity of satisfying its aspirations for power in areas beyond the seas which generally were beyond the reach of the main contenders of power.
204
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
Although only Morgenthau's first condition concerns Theorem 6.3, his observations about European politics in general reach the other conditions of the theorem: "Both naval supremacy and virtual immunity from foreign attack for more than three centuries enabled great Britain to perform this function [condition (3)] Air power h a s . . . put an end to [this] invulnerability..." (p. 337). "France under Louis XIV and Italy in the decade before the First World War attempted to play this r o l e . . . but France was too deeply involved... lacking in commanding superiority [in violation of conditions (2) and (4)]. Italy on the other hand had not enough weight to throw around to give it the key position in the balance of power [in violation of condition (4)]" (p. 188). Theorem 6.3 also helps us uncover some of the special advantages enjoyed by a peripheral balancing power. Suppose r = (150,75,75), let dtj — dji for all / and j , and, in particular, let dX2 — dn = 0.5 and d2i = 1. In this instance, 1 and 2 could threaten to divide 3's resources evenly, and 3's only viable counter is to transfer 50 units to 1 so as to make 1 near-predominant. However, neither 2 nor 3, alone or together, can threaten 1. If either coalesces with 1 to attack the third then the third should immediately cede 50 units to 1, since any gain by 2 renders 3 inessential, and vice versa. In this instance, then, the cooperative game has a core that yields the outcome (200,25,75) or (200,75,25). Thus, not only can geographically remote countries such as Britain enjoy a greater level of resources without threatening the stability of the system, they are also the countries to which resources will be ceded when another must ensure its survival. It is evident, moreover, that this argument is wholly general, which establishes the following important result about three-country systems with a unique balancer; namely: Remark 6.3. If / in S is a unique balancer, then the corresponding cooperative game has a core in which / is near-predominant. In Remark 6.3, then, we find the theoretical basis for Morgenthau's (1959, p. 176) observation: The balancer is in a position of "splendid isolation." It is isolated by its own choice; for, while the two scales of the balance must vie with each other to add its weight to theirs in order to gain the overweight necessary for success, it must refuse to enter into permanent ties with either side Its isolation is "splendid"; for, since its support or lack of support is the decisive factor in the struggle for power, its foreign policy, if cleverly managed, is able to extract the highest price from those whom it supports. The position Britain enjoyed as a balancer, however, is not the sole asymmetric possibility geography occasions for individual countries, as evidenced by the following observation by McNeill (1982, p. 148):
6.3 Implications: Balancers and central powers
205
States located towards the margins of the European world - Great Britain and Russia in particular - were able to increase their control of resources more rapidly than was possible in the more crowded center. The rise of such march states to dominance over older and smaller polities located near the center where important innovation first concentrated is one of the oldest and best-attested patterns of civilized history [such] states conquered older, smaller polities at least three times in the ancient Near East: Akkad (ca. 2350 B.C.); Assyria (ca. 1000-612 B.C.); and Persia (550-331 B.C.). Mediterranean history offers a similar array of instances: the rise of Macedon (338 B.C.) and then of Rome (168 B.C.) in classical times followed in modern times by the Spanish Dominion over Italy (by 1557) Ancient China (rise of Ch'in 221 B.C.) and ancient India (rise of Magadha, ca. 321 B.C.) as well as Amerindian Mexico (Aztecs) and Peru (Incas) all seem to exhibit a parallel pattern.
To see how this recurring historical pattern finds reflection in our analysis, consider a system in which dn = dn — 1 butrf23< !• Thus, country 1 is central - it is contiguous to two noncontiguous countries, and (again from Lemma 6.2) it is the sole country that can enjoy a position of being near-predominant. However, with Theorem 6.3 in mind, suppose r = (100,100,100) and d23 = 0.5. Although {1,2} can threaten 3 (or, equivalently, {1,3} can threaten 2), 3 can form a viable counter by ceding 50 units of resources to 1 so as to make 1 near-predominant. Yet, if 2 and 3 coalesce to attack 1 with the understanding that they will divide l's resources evenly, 1 cannot form a viable counter: if 1 proposes a coalition with 2 (or 3) that offers 2 more than 150 units of resources at the expense of 3, then 1 has failed to increase its security value since it can now be defeated by 2 alone, and 3 does not have sufficient resources to form a viable counter with 1 against 2 - 2 is predominant. Nor can 1 propose to merely transfer 50 units of resources to 2, since such a transfer cannot make 2 near-predominant so as to render the system resource stable - such a transfer merely weakens 1 further. In this example, then, the central power must control more resources than either adversary in order to secure its survival. Remark 6.4, however, which follows from some simple algebraic manipulations on condition (3) of Theorem 6.1, shows that for the special case in which both such adversaries' (both "peripheral powers'") resources are equal, the resources the central power must control to ensure system stability depend on d, the discount between the two noncentral powers. R e m a r k 6 . 4 . I f rj = rk = r a n d diJ = dik = li t h e n ({i,j,k);r)
is
system stable if and only if 2r > rt > r/djk — r. The proof of this remark is simple enough that we present it here. First, if {j, k] is losing then, because / is contiguous to both j and k, i is predominant. And if {j, k] is winning or blocking, then we must have 2r > rt.
206
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
Condition (3a) of Theorem 6.1, however, requires that (rt + rj)djk > rk for system stability. Substituting r for /*y and rk, and rearranging terms yields rt > r/dJk — r. Combining the two inequalities yields the statement of the remark. Referring back now to our numerical example, if the resources of each of the two peripheral powers is 100 and if the geographical discount between them, d, equals 0.5, then the central power's resources must exceed 100; if d is less than 0.5, then those resources must exceed something greater than 100; and if d is greater than 0.5, then those resources must exceed something less than 100. Thus, the greater the remoteness of the two peripheral powers, the greater are the resources the central power must control to ensure that it is essential. If the resources of each peripheral power are nearly irrelevant to the other (if d <£l), then a central power must do more than match the resources of its potential adversaries; otherwise that power is inessential and its two adversaries can coalesce to eliminate it from the game. The empirical manifestation of this example, then, is almost certainly Bismarck's Germany and the concern it felt about France and Russia: Her location in the centre of the continent gave her [Germany] a great advantage if she wished to exert pressures on the other Powers, and her army... remained the most formidable military machine in the world On the other hand, precisely because of her central location, Germany would be exposed to serious danger if her neighbors to the east and west combined against her (Schmitt 1934, pp. 3-4).
With Britain peripheral, Germany's only effective maneuver at the time was, first, to maintain a strong military tradition, second, to add the resources of Austria-Hungary by alliance, and, third, to industrialize so as to increase its military capability (the League of Three Emperors, bound together by a common fear of democratization, and agreements such as the Russian Reinsurance Treaty can be thus interpreted as part of Germany's strategy for survival, forestalling a Franco-Russia alliance it regarded as inevitable). The quotation from Walt (1987) introducing this chapter is taken from a discussion that suggests that the Soviet Union now confronts the same dilemma as Germany. Indeed, Walt (1987, p. 277) hints at the combination of Theorem 6.3 and Remark 6.4 when he precedes that conclusion with the observation that for the middle-level powers of Western Europe and Asia, the United States is the perfect ally. Its aggregate power ensures that its voice will be heard and its actions felt, and it is driven by its own concern for Soviet expansion to contribute to its allies' defense. At the same time, the United States is far enough away so as not to pose a significant threat to these allies.
6.4 Balancers and central powers: Some examples
207
Our analysis does not apply, of course, if there are more than three essential actors, and thus we must leave it as a conjecture that the advantage of peripheral powers does not disappear as the number of countries increases. We suspect that Remark 6.4 (as well as Theorem 6.3) will generalize, but before we go too far in interpreting as support for our analysis the historical events summarized by McNeill, we ought to keep in mind that if a central power anticipates events, and if the discount between peripheral powers is not too great or if its resources offset geographical disadvantages, then it should be able to meet threats with viable counters. The special danger confronting a central power, nevertheless, is miscalculation. If geographical discounts are low (if the d's are at or near 1), then the central power can ensure its sovereignty with fewer than onethird of the system's resources, but if miscalculation impedes the equilibration process of threats and counters, that power is militarily disadvantaged. Conversely, if the discount between peripheral powers is sufficiently great, if the central power acts to increase its resources accordingly, but if it and its peripheral adversaries take imperfect account of geographical imperatives (such as when the central power's estimate of the discount is greater than the estimates of its adversaries), then the stage may be set for others to contemplate a preventive war. 6.4
Balancers and central powers: Some examples
We conclude this chapter with a general consideration of the applicability of our discussion of balancer and central powers to great power politics since the fifteenth century, c.E. Ideally, we would like to operationalize military power in an index that permits cross-national comparability over the entire period and in terms of which rigorous demonstration of the applicability of our theorems and remarks could be made. However, such an enterprise escapes us for several reasons. First, military technology and with it the interface of the military with society at large - has so developed from the fifteenth to the twentieth century that it is questionable whether a meaningful index covering the entire period under question could be constructed. Second, even assuming that such an index could be constructed, data for the periods before the late eighteenth century are both scanty and unreliable (indeed, for the South German states prior to 1871 and for the Balkan states prior to 1910, the problem remains acute). Thus, failing our more rigorous enterprise, we propose to ask whether our discussion of balancer and central powers in some more cursory, perhaps anecdotal, way both "makes sense" in terms of the great-power politics of these periods and contributes to our understanding of these politics. In
208
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
so doing, we shall be taking severe liberty with the empirical cases. We shall treat each case as a three-actor case, even though it is obvious that through most of the period we have, in fact, four to six national actors. The justification we give for this is simply the analytic convenience afforded by treating coalitions as primary actors, and the fact that, for each of the periods under consideration, the actors nicely aggregate into two conflicting coalitions and a potential balancer; in some of these cases, one of the conflicting coalitions corresponds to a central power. The fifteenth to sixteenth century With the union of the Spanish Throne and the Holy Roman Empire under the House of Habsburg in the person of Charles V, the modern state system may be said to have emerged. The Habsburg realms were opposed by France, the Protestant princes of Germany, and Ottoman Turkey. It is tempting to regard Great Britain as a great power even this early, particularly in light of Cardinal Wolsey's pronouncements on his nation's pursuit of a balance-of-power strategy. However, as Dehio (1962, p. 39) notes: After the election of Charles V, the influence of the island kingdom - not yet playing an intermediary role between the two worlds - was not yet strong enough to support a successful balance of power policy; and for that very reason English leaders could not be expected to pursue it consistently. Characteristically enough, Wolsey had as yet no conception of the importance of a navy to England. And Henry VIII, who had a keen instinct in regard to the future of his country, was not fitted by temperament to steer foreign policy with a steady hand. He relapsed into schemes for Continental conquest and, instead of consistently backing France against the superior strength of the Empire, dreamed from time to time of acquiring the French crown. England's insular position had to be fortified by new circumstances before the island kingdom could become a decisive factor in Continental affairs.
Owing to the contiguity of the Continental powers, the sole candidate for balancer in this period was Ottoman Turkey, which exhibited many of the policies of a unique balancer. Turkey, it is true, was contiguous with the Holy Roman Empire through much of this period, but - because the real population base and center of military power for the Ottoman empire (as well as its administrative center) were considerably to the east, in Constantinople and Anatolia - the expanse of territory separating these centers from the other continental powers imposed no insignificant discount on the forces of these powers. The particular difficulty with asserting that Ottoman Turkey was a unique balancer concerns the possibility that it failed to meet our third criterion in the requirements of that role: that the coalition of the opposition not be winning, collectively, when its discounted resources are matched to the undiscounted resources of the
6.4 Balancers and central powers: Some examples
209
balancer - that is, d{rj + rk)
210
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
of naval superiority Spain possessed over its adversaries. Thus, on closer examination, we can say that England was able to play the balancer role in roughly the same way and for the same reasons as Ottoman Turkey in the previous century. This dynamic almost certainly continues to explain England's success in balancing off Holland and the Holy Roman Empire against France in the seventeenth century. However, as France learned at La Hogue, Britain increasingly approximated fulfillment of the third criterion of a unique balancer set forth in Theorem 6.3. Certainly, Britain does not completely fulfill this role until near the end of the eighteenth century, but its increasing strength was heralded in its role in the Wars of Spanish and Austrian Succession and the Seven Years' War: in each case, it more closely approximated the behavior predicted of a unique balancer. Furthermore, the pressure for French expansion may best be understood in terms of its role as a central power and its need to maintain at least twice as many resources as its contiguous opponents, the Holy Roman Empire and Holland; the same is true in the mideighteenth century for Prussia. The eighteenth to twentieth century With the rise of Napoleon in France in the late eighteenth century, C.E., Britain emerges as the unique balancer of the European great-power system. From 1798 to 1814, France ranged itself against a coalition that, at various times, included Prussia, Austria, and Russia; its constant opponent, however, was Great Britain. Great Britain's naval power, colonial empire, and burgeoning industrial might gave it the capacity to fulfill all the criteria set forth in Theorem 6.3. Indeed, it was only limits of demography and geography that prevented Britain, after the Congress of Vienna, from becoming predominant. By our index of national resources (see Chapter 7), ignoring the effects of geography, Britain was predominant until 1857, although the British score on this index must be discounted to reflect British perceptions of the effects of geography on potential continental operations. However, after 1857, the minimum discount that must be applied to forces attacking Great Britain in order for Britain to continue to meet the third criterion of Theorem 6.3 grows quite rapidly: in 1871, djb = dkb = 0.82, if d(rj + rk)
6.4 Balancers and central powers: Some examples
211
of its central position between France and Russia. Chapter 7 examines these dynamics at some length in terms of their impact on alliance formation in this period, and Chapter 8 does so with attention to conflict resolution. The twentieth century Although Britain's eclipse as unique balancer occurred prior to World War I, it retained its role and this, as much as anything, made British intervention in the war inevitable. However, it was the United States that arose as unique balancer and, finally, ended the carnage. There is virtually no question that the United States from 1916 to 1945 fulfills the criteria by which we define a unique balancer. This was demonstrated in 1916-18 and, again, in 1941-5. Indeed, it is precisely in those periods when the United States could have acted as unique balancer but chose not to do so (for domestic political reasons that fall outside the purview of our analysis) -1921-40 - that the most egregious disturbances of international equilibrium took place. Since 1945, a bipolar system has, by and large, emerged, albeit this system is exhibiting increasing tendency toward multipolarity. However, it is unclear exactly to what degree the United States could be said to be a unique balancer within a multipolar system in the nuclear age. The existence of nuclear weapons and intercontinental delivery systems for such weapons renders our discussion of geographical contiguity and noncontiguity moot; if one can deliver several thousand megatons of nuclear destruction to any country on the globe within half an hour - and this is the case for the United States and the Soviet Union, and somewhat less so for China, Great Britain, and France - there seems to be little relevant sense in which geography introduces discount parameters for force projection by any nuclear power. If such a system is, however, system stable - and whether it is or can be system stable is outside the purview of our current discussion - then the role of the balancer, if not the unique balancer, remains of crucial importance. Alternatively, if we ignore the role of nuclear technology with the supposition that international politics must proceed with the assumption that such weapons cannot be used, thereby bringing our analysis in line with Pearson's previously cited conclusion about geography's continuing relevance, then it is tempting to assert the following analogy to the nineteenth century: the Soviet Union substitutes for Germany as the central power, Western Europe for France (with East Germany its Alsace-Lorraine?), China (allied with Japan?) plays Russia's earlier role, and the United States plays Britain's role of balancer. Thus, this analogy and Remark 6.4 formalize Walt's observation, cited in the beginning of this chapter, about
212
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
the probable desires of Soviet strategic planners, and we might even speculate that it is in this geographical configuration and its intuitive understanding of that remark, as much as its historical experience, that we find the source of the Soviet Union's paranoia about the military capabilities of others. The extent to which this analogy fits contemporary circumstances is a subject we explore in more detail in Chapter 9.
6.5
Appendix: Proofs of results Lemma 6.1
Since {/, j} e W*, i and j together can defeat k. But before / and j divide rk, j must make certain that / does not control enough resources to defeat j subsequently. Suppose / and j divide rk into a and rk — a, respectively. Then it must be the case that (ri + a)dij 0 to /*, so that (ri + e)diJ>rj + rk-e, for anyyeS-}/} and keS—{i,j], then / is predominant. Thus, to prove sufficiency, we must show that if the conditions of the lemma are satisfied then / is not predominant without the addition of e - that every threat by / can be countered with a viable counterthreat - whereas / becomes predominant with e. Notice, first, that if ridij = rldik = rj-\-rk then,by Lemma 6.1, g/(C) = 0 for all C in JV*9 ie C. Thus, i cannot gain resources by coalescing with either j or A: in a threat against the third country, so / cannot be predominant. However, if we add e resources to /, then (ri + e)dij = (ri + e)dik> rj + rk — e, and / is predominant. Second, if / threatens j and k together, let rf be the resources / allocates against j . If ridij = ridik = rj + rk then dij = diki in which case (rt — rf)dik + rfdy = rtdij = Tj + rk. So / cannot overcome j and k simultaneously, nor can it overcome one without rendering itself vulnerable to the other. Thus, / is not predominant, but if we add e resources to /, the previous equality becomes ">," and / becomes predominant, which means that it is near-predominant without e. Finally, suppose / threatens j alone. If dkJ = 1, then rj + rkdkj = rj + rk = rjdjj, k can join j in a counter by transferring resources to y, and thus / is not predominant. But if e is added to /'s resources, the last equality becomes" < " and k cannot join j in a viable counter by attacking / or by transferring
6.5 Appendix: Proofs of results
213
resources to j . An attack yields a viable counter only if (r, + e — rkdki)dij < r7, or, equivalently, (rt + e)dij- 0 , this requires that rt djj < rj + rk dik dtj. We know that dik dtj < 1, so this inequality cannot hold. Nor can k form a counter by transferring its resources to j . Such a transfer yields a viable counter only if ry + rk > r^dy + edtj. Since e > 0, this requires that ry + A^ > rt dtj, which violates the assumption of the lemma. So again, / is near-predominant. Suppose, on the other hand, that dki = dtj - 1. Then, if / threatens j , k can join j in a viable counter by attacking /. Country / must target more than /y of its resources at j and at least rk at k. If rt = rj + rk, this is impossible, whereas if e is added to fs resources then / has sufficient resources to defeat j and k. To prove necessity, we already know by definition that if r^dy > rj + rk, then / is predominant; so suppose that " < " holds. By Lemma 6.2, g;(C) > 0 for some C in W*9 i e C. But / cannot subsequently gain enough to eliminate its coaliion partner, since such a coalition agreement violates our model's rationality assumptions. Suppose then that " = " holds. We are left with two cases. First, if dkJ< 1 andd k i <\forsomeyeS-{/},thenr/rf^->rj + rkdkj and rt dtj > /y 4- rkdki dtj, in which case / is predominant. Second, if dkj < 1 and djj<\ for some jeS—[i], then again ridij>rj + rkdkj and rjdij> rj + rkdkidu. Q.E.D. Theorem 6.1 It is evident that conditions (1) and (2) are sufficient. To show that (3) is sufficient, suppose (rr, ({j, k], {/))) is a threat against /. From the definition of a threat, this requires that {j,k}eW*9 rjdjj + rkdki>rh r- = 0, and r]>rj, and r'k>rk. But if, as (3) assumes, /, when threatened by (rr, ([j9k], {/})), is in some winning coalition, say {/,./}, such that the conditions of (3) are satisfied, then / can transfer gy({/, j}) resources toy. In this case, by Lemma 6.2, j becomes near-predominant and the transfer is a counter. That / can transfer gy({/, j}) resources to j without setting its resources to 0 follows because (r;+rj)djk > rk, which implies that gjdjj k})< ri - otherwise, j is predominant when it secures gj([j9 k}), in contradiction of Lemma 6.1. It is a viable counter since, by A6, j prefers the transfer to securing an equivalent amount of resources by eliminating /, and since, by Lemma 6.1, j cannot gain more than gj([i9 j}). To prove that the conditions of the theorem are necessary, suppose (5;r) is not system stable, W* is not empty, and no country in the system is nearpredominant. Then, if dtj ^ djk9 or if dik ^ 1 and dtj or djk ^ 1, by Lemma 6.2, / cannot render j near-predominant. Finally, if (rt + rj)djk
214
6 Geography, balancers, and central powers
Theorem 6.2 The conditions of the theorem are clearly sufficient. To establish necessity, notice that if W* is not empty and if no i is near-predominant, then the corresponding constant-sum game is essential. Referring to (6.2), v(i, j) = ri + rj + b>v(i) + v(j) = ri + rj-2b. But if W* is not empty and no / is near-predominant, there exists a b > 0 that renders some / predominant, so the game is essential. It follows, because only inessential constant-sum ^-person games have nonempty cores, that the core is empty for situations described by the characteristic function in (6.2), and that the system is not resource stable. Q.E.D. Theorem 6.3 For sufficiency, by Theorem 6.1 and the definition of a balancer, conditions (1), (2), and (4) imply that / is a balancer and the system is system stable, whereas (3) implies that neither j nor k can be balancers. To prove necessity, if (4) is violated, then {/, j] and {/, k] cannot be winning and / cannot be a balancer. If d(rj + rk) > rh then / is not the unique balancer. Specifically, {j, i] and {j, k) are winning: {j, k] is winning from the assumption that (3) is violated; and condition (4) implies that /y +tfr,-> rki so {j, /} is winning. Third, if (2) is violated and dtj = dik = 1, then, ceteris paribus, by (3), rj-\-rk<:ri. In the case of strict inequality, / is predominant and the system is not system stable; if equality holds then, by Theorem 6.2, the system is resource stable and no country is a balancer. If (1) is violated and djk is not equal to 1 then, ceteris paribus, the system is not system stable, by condition (3) of Theorem 6.1. Q.E.D.
CHAPTER 7
Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
The Balance of Power worked with calculation almost as pure as in the days before the French Revolution. It seemed to be the political equivalent of the laws of economics, both self-operating. If every man followed his own interest, all would be prosperous; and if every state followed its own interest, all would be peaceful and secure. A. J. P. Taylor, The Struggle for Mastery in Europe, 1848-1918 (1954, p. xx)
To give meaning to the factual raw material of foreign policy... we put ourselves in the position of a statesman who must meet a certain problem of foreign policy... and we ask ourselves what the rational alternatives are from which a statesman may choose... and which of these rational alternatives this particular statesman, acting under these circumstances, is likely to choose. It is the testing of this rational hypothesis against the actual facts and their consequences that gives meaning to the facts of international politics and makes a theory of politics possible. Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations (1959, p. 5)
It is one thing to formulate a set of assumptions and to deduce consequences; it is another thing to relate those assumptions and deductions to reality in such a way that they facilitate our understanding of events. This is an especially important consideration in the present context since any set of abstract assumptions used to model complex macropolitical processes must be at odds to some extent with what we believe to be true about reality. Our theoretical development assumes that a singular objective characterizes the foreign policy of each state; it presupposes that a single unidimensional variable measures the capabilities of countries to war and to coerce others and that this variable also measures what countries win and lose in international conflict; and it fails to take account of the fact that commonalities and differences in language, culture, and social organization both facilitate and impede the processes whereby countries reach agreements. Our theory embodies certain assumptions because they facilitate formal reasoning and because we do not yet know how to formulate more 215
216
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
empirically satisfactory ones in ways that admit the derivation of general results. Yet, we can also justify our approach by noting that theories are rarely developed by constructing an analysis that incorporates all salient aspects of reality in a single parsimonious structure. What we have supplied is a "frictionless" theory of international systems that is intended as a guide to our thinking about events and that can slowly be generalized by replacing one assumption with another - a process illustrated in Chapters 5 and 6. This means, however, that we cannot test our theory with data from a world characterized by frictions in a simple way. We hypothesize that our theory is true for the stated conditions, but, just as we know that objects in our experience never uniformly fall according to the law s = at2/!, we also know that our theory, like all theories, is "false" in the sense that it does not identically model international systems. Again, we cannot turn to some historical record of falling objects and test the hypothesis that in a vacuum all objects fall according to the same law. We gain confidence in our theories, though, when we find that heavy objects approximate this law and that objects of similar shape behave similarly. This is our approach in the rest of this volume. We proceed by reviewing an historical record, trying to detect the operation of the forces that our analysis uncovers. Minimally, this approach should give us a clearer sense of what is involved in mapping our theory to the real world, and whether expanding its empirical relevance is likely to prove worthwhile. 7.1
Formulating testable hypotheses
The first issue we must confront concerns the goals served by the formation of alliances. First, notice that our model predicts that, barring particular asymmetries in resource growth and the geographical discounting of offensive capabilities, we will not observe coalitions to eliminate essential countries (Theorem 3.2). In a world in which coalitions can be formed and dissolved effortlessly, everyone will foresee the futility of attempts to eliminate essential players - they will see that for every such threat there is a viable counter. Results such as Theorem 3.2, however, do not preclude the possibility that coalitions and alliances will emerge that threaten essential players so as to effect a resource reallocation. System stability does not imply resource stability, and the condition for resource stability - that one country be near-predominant - is special and fragile. Thus, if the imperatives described in Chapters 5 and 6 that might otherwise destabilize systems do not apply, then the coalitions and alliances we observe will have the limited aim of effecting reallocations of resources, not the elimination of essential countries.
7.1 Formulating testable hypotheses
217
A second feature of our theory is that it does not permit us to predict precisely which coalitions will form. As we state in Chapter 4: "If the survival of all countries is assured, then regardless of what alliance is proposed, there exists another proposal that the members of some other alliance all prefer and that they can secure." At first glance, then, it might seem that we have an ill-conceived theory, one which fails to predict the coalitions that will pose a threat to others. However, although we cannot predict precisely which coalitions will form, we can identify certain coalitions as possibilities while excluding others, since the coalitions and alliances that can form to effect reallocations must share certain properties. First, given the constant-sum character of the situation in conjunction with the fact that Riker's (1962) "size principle" is implied by our definition of a viable counterthreat, we can hypothesize that such coalitions are minimal-winning - that only coalitions large enough to win will form. Second, as Theorem 4.3 establishes, regardless of what coalition or alliance forms, no country will be rendered near-predominant by whatever success that coalition or alliance enjoys. In this context, we should add that rational-choice models are often viewed as antithetical toward explanations based on "culture" or "historical accident," but this is a misperception. With respect to coalitions, formal analysis permits us to narrow the range of possibilities, but the specific coalition that emerges is often determined by factors exogenous to the analysis, such as the accidental timing of events. Thus, Germany and Austria may find it easier to coalesce because of a common culture and language, and France's strategic options may be restricted by fading recollections of Napoleonic grandeur. So just as those who seek to understand events in terms of culture and accident should take cognizance of the general forces uncovered by formal theory, formal theorists must take cognizance of the limitations of their theory and the role those limitations grant to "ad hoc" variables. Before we can commence interpreting our results in the context of historical events, then, we must accommodate the frictions that accompany coalition formation in international systems. These include the imperatives of domestic politics, the time that must be spent mobilizing resources and negotiating agreements, miscalculation, and the differential benefits of negotiation occasioned by cultural differences and historical animosities. The particular danger that confronts a country is that if others form a coalition, these frictions may give coalitions a degree of permanence that confounds attempts to dissolve them with better offers. Alternately, if decision makers are alert to these frictions, they may try to take advantage of them so as to render an essential country inessential. For example,
218
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
if the initial distribution of resources in a seven-country system is (50,50, 50,40,40,35,35), then all countries are essential. However, if countries 1 and 2, 3 and 4, and 5 and 6 coalesce, and if we treat these coalitions as new "players" so that the four-actor system (100,90,75,35) emerges, then country 7 is no longer essential. Confronted with this possibility, country 7 should anticipate events and propose coalitions that ensure its survival. Since 7 is essential in the original distribution, viable counters are available so as to yield an ebb and flow of actual or threatened alliances in which essential countries act to ensure against the possibility that other alliances will form that threaten to render them inessential. In Chapter 3, we define a counterthreat as a proposal that either threatens all the members of the originally threatening coalition or that coopts one or more members of that coalition, and in which all countries party to the counterthreat prefer the counter to the original threat. We also define a viable counterthreat as one in which each of the threatening members of the coalition in the counter has some incentive to coalesce in the sense that whenever the coalition excludes any member, it cannot make a counterthreat that its remaining members all prefer to the counter formed by including the excluded member. Using these definitions, we assume (A10) that a country will not be eliminated if and only if it possesses a viable counterthreat to every threat, from which we derive that system stability prevails if and only if all countries are essential. Thus, if any system of alliances emerges, then that system ought to provide essential actors with at least one viable counter to any potential threat. Another way to express this equilibration process is to suggest that each country will examine the potential configurations available in each coalition in terms of all potential threats and pursue the formation of a feasible coalition that is the best guarantee against any threat. We qualify this coalitional activity in terms of feasibility because of two types of constraints that operate on the abilities of countries to obtain coalitions. First, there are those constraints that arise directly from the assumptions of our analysis. For example, Assumptions A4 and A10 imply that no essential country will join in any coalition in which the conditions for forming include abrogation of its national sovereignty. Second, there are constraints exogenous to the analysis but that nevertheless are operant. The particular type that concerns us arises out of an ambiguity in our accounting of a country's resources, its military potential, and the value of resources that might be transferred to another country voluntarily or involuntarily. The specific example is the Franco-German dispute over Alsace-Lorraine. The effective value of this territory, which entailed a nexus of domestic political considerations foreclosing any effective Franco-German coalition, far exceeded the military value of the territory (which is not to say,
7.1 Formulating testable hypotheses
219
of course, that such value was insignificant). Excluding the possibility of a Franco-German alliance, then, accommodates many of the effects of domestic politics on coalition formation. More generally, much of the conflict in the period 1871 to 1914 concerns extra-European possessions, maintenance of spheres of influence, and access to markets. Thus, the index of resources we offer shortly, intended to measure the relative military strengths of coalitions, misspecifies what countries might actually lose or gain from a failed or a successful alliance. Placing ad hoc constraints on coalitional feasibility, then, should be interpreted as a "stopgap" measure that alerts us to such considerations when attempting to give our model substantive meaning. We emphasize, though, that such constraints ought to be treated with care. When regimes or sovereignty are threatened, populations and their leaders can doubtlessly find excuses for surmounting traditional impediments to a coalition. "If pressures are strong enough, a state will deal with almost anyone" (Waltz 1979, pp. 166), which is an idea best evidenced by Churchill's (1950, p. 370) famous assertion that "if Hitler invaded Hell, I should at least make a favorable reference to the Devil in the House of Commons." Thus, the United States might be portrayed as the great evil in human affairs in one year by China, whereas soon thereafter it is advertised as the partner in an implicit alliance to maintain its borders against the Soviet Union. One implication of our analysis of resource stability is that nearly any essential country can coalesce with any other such country for advantage. Thus, whenever we deem a coalition infeasible, we should make certain that its members have counters to whatever threats they might perceive. That is, because our theory requires an essential country to have a viable counter to any threat, admitting ad hoc constraints on feasibility leads to the following hypothesis: HI. If a coalition is deemed an infeasible counter to some threat, then each threatened country will have or will actively seek an alternative feasible and viable counter to that threat. With Waltz and Churchill in mind, however, we should add this corollary to HI: HI'. To the extent that an infeasible alliance is the sole viable counter to some threat, then countries will act to eliminate the relevant feasibility constraint. In reality, the pace of events is slowed by an environment sticky with ideology and misperception, and diplomatic maneuver is characterized by simultaneous negotiations, with the understanding that treaties may have no binding effect. The only constraint that binds ultimately is self-interest,
220
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
and in the environment of redistributive politics, such interest leads to no unique prediction about ultimate coalition structures. In such environments, people can only guess at the threats that will confront them, and a prudent course appears to imply that countries ought to seek to become members of the strongest feasible coalition. The notion of "strongest feasible," however, is imprecise. If the intent of coalitions is to defeat and thereby remove essential countries and if uncertainty characterizes any such venture, then it is not unreasonable to hypothesize that national leaders will seek to establish alliances with overwhelming military capability. However, if in a system-stable environment, coalitions have the more limited aim of effecting advantageous redistributions of resources in the form of access to colonial markets, territory, and trade routes, then we should anticipate a different type of coalition, because forming an overly large coalition removes countries from which one may expropriate. With respect to threats, the constant-sum character of redistribution, the characteristic function representation of value embodied by expressions (4.1) and (4.2), and the implicit use of the minimum winning coalition hypothesis predict that the coalitions that form to effect a redistribution will not contain unnecessary members - that no member of such a coalition can be excluded without rendering the coalition losing and, thus, vulnerable against feasible opponents. If we suppose further that coalition members share gains in proportion to their relative size within a coalition, as measured by their resources, then we can refine this prediction. If g(C) equals the potential gains from forming C and if r(C) is the resources C controls, then a decision maker prefers the minimum winning coalition that maximizes g(C)/r(C).1 1
If a coalition's gains (and losses) are apportioned among its members in proportion to their relative sizes, and if g(C) is C's maximum potential gain, then rjg(C)/r(C) is member I'S gain, and i prefers C to C" if g(C)/r(C) >g{C')/r{C). It is important to note, however, that solution notions such as the V-set and the bargaining set do not imply proportionality. If r = (120,100,80), so that, as we show in Chapter 4, the main-simple V-set is {(125,125,50), (125,70,105), (70,125,105)], then country 1 is indifferent between coalescing with 2 and with 3 since 1 gains 5 in both instances. On the other hand, if gains are distributed proportionally, then 1 receives 14 in {1,2} as against 15 in {1,3}. In effect, then, hypothesizing proportionality supposes not only that countries prefer to be members of minimal winning coalitions, but also that they prefer coalitions of minimal weight. Despite the disjuncture between the proportional-gains hypothesis and solution theory, there is some intuitive rationale arguing for proportionality. Diplomatic maneuver and resource adjustments in international politics are almost certainly characterized by frictions disallowing the fine adjustment of gains presumed by classical solution theory, and it seems plausible to suppose that, conditional on being winning, decision makers prefer as significant a role as possible in their coalition. Nevertheless, in evaluating the relative attractiveness of two minimal-winning coalitions, we ought to keep in mind the ad hoc character of the proportionality hypothesis and the fact that, rather than being a direct implication of our analysis, it is an addendum that takes us beyond the supposition that minimum winning coalitions are preferred to larger coalitions.
7.1 Formulating testable hypotheses
221
With respect to viable counterthreats, our theory distinguishes between two types: those in which a subset of countries cedes resources and those in which the counter is itself a threat. Certainly, national leaders prefer counters of the second type, and if the proportionality rule operates, such counters should also be of minimum weight and winning. Uncertainty about the resolve and strengths of countries may temper this idea to yield larger coalitions, but we should not interpret "strongest feasible" to mean the largest coalition possible. Thus, we are led to hypothesize: H2. Countries forming coalitions to make a threat or to counter a threat without ceding resources will form coalitions only large enough to win, and, in particular, they will seek coalitions that
maximize g(C)/r(C). Admittedly, our theory is merely sufficient to assert H2, and we can imagine many other rationalizations for it, but the particular contribution of our theory is its specification of g(C). The usual approach to the evaluation of coalitions is to suppose that if a coalition C is winning, then its incremental value is R minus whatever resources its members currently control, r(C); whereas if C is losing, g(C) equals —r(C). Expression (4.1), though, says that if C is winning then g(C) = v(C) — r(C), and that this difference equals the resources that must be ceded to C's largest member to render that member near-predominant [or, if insufficient resources are available from S-C, all of r(S- C)]. We can make a similar calculation for losing coalitions, except that now, in accordance with expression (4.2), we must subtract from the total controlled by such a coalition the resources that its members must cede to ensure system stability. Our evaluation of H2, then, focuses on the extent to which we can interpret observed coalitions as attempts to maximize this particular measure of gain. Turning to alliance configurations, the literature is, of course, replete with ideas: contrast Organski and Kugler's (1980, p. 14) contention that "the balance-of-power model suggests that when power is more or less equally distributed among great powers or members of major alliances peace will ensue" with Claude's (1962, pp. 42-3) assertion that opposing alliances must balance in strength, and with Bull's (1977, p. 113) argument that "in a system of three or more powers balance can be achieved without a relationship of equality among the powers concerned because of the possibility of combination of the lesser against the greater." Organski and Kugler, then, see balance as implying a static system in which only alliances of equally powerful members can endure; Claude sees balance as implying a bipolarity of equals; and Bull offers no specific prediction, although his idea is more in keeping with a view in which the mere threat of alliances maintains balance (i.e., stability). Our theory is more consonant
222
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
with Bull's view. If we viewed international political processes as a sequence of well-defined cooperative redistributive games, we might then postulate a sequence of minimal-winning coalitions successively redistributing resources - that is, we would postulate bipolarity, but neither balance nor stability. The complex and dynamic processes of international politics, however, are not likely to fit this simple abstract scenario. First, countries are not merely seeking to redistribute resources, they are also seeking to maintain their sovereignty. Second, countries can strive to remain neutral in conflicts, using theflexibilityof their neutrality to extract the largest possible gains from the system and to forestall others from securing gains. In any event, a full mapping of coalitional dynamics is not part of our analysis. Despite the fact that we cannot make definitive predictions about the alliance structures that emerge, Remark 3.1 and Hypothesis HI give credence to the supposition that if a bipolar alliance system - either formally specified or informally understood - encompasses all of S, then both alliances must have approximately equal resources. On the other hand, although there is nothing in our analysis presupposing an all-encompassing bipolar alliance structure, it does preclude the possibility of a hegemonic alliance that can dictate its will on all excluded members. Thus, we can detect within our analysis forces that operate to keep imbalances from becoming permanent. Consider, then, the following hypothesis: H3. If a bipolar alliance system has one alliance significantly more powerful than the other, then either some member of the larger alliance will be attracted to the smaller, or there must exist other countries not formally associated with either alliance capable of offsetting the advantage of the larger alliance. In short, because we predict that system stability prevails if all countries are essential, majority alliances can exist only for temporary advantage and not for hegemonic domination. System stability requires flexibility in the alliance system, so that members of an alliance should be willing to listen to any overture, in which case it may be impossible to determine, at any point in time, precisely who is a member of an alliance or the commitment of its members to it. The ebb andflowof diplomacy should then exhibit some tendency toward balance of resources among competing alliances, especially in bipolar systems, but the fluidity of coalitional processes does not permit us to predict that this balance will at any specific time take on the qualities of mathematical equality. To these hypotheses we can add others, several of which are supported by even a cursory review of the historical record. These hypotheses include the predictions that no essential country will be eliminated (Theorem 3.2), and that essential countries will seek to disrupt patterns of alliances that
7.2 Methodology
223
render them inessential. To this point, however, our discussion largely ignores the implications of our analysis in Chapters 5 and 6, especially the role of geography and the results we offer there about balancers (Theorem 6.3) and central powers (Remark 6.4). Because these results, a priori, ought to apply to Britain and Germany, respectively, throughout the period 1871-1914, we cannot test them in any statistical way (i.e., the entire period constitutes a single observation). However, we can predict that they should color everybody's strategic thinking, not just the policies of Britain and Germany. With this in mind, we use them in the interpretation of our results to gauge their contribution to the analysis. 7.2
Methodology
We reemphasize that, because our model cannot capture all of the forces operating in an international system, our empirical aims must be limited to judging the extent to which that model provides a framework for theorizing about international affairs. Hence, what we seek is an assessment of the model's validity in terms of how easily we can discern historically the forces it describes and the extent to which those forces appear to operate despite the frictions characterizing reality. We select as the venue for evaluation the great powers of Europe - Austria-Hungary, Britain, France, Germany, Italy, and Russia - in the period 1871-1914. We are drawn to this period not merely by the relative reliability of the data, although this is not an inconsequential concern, but also by the contention of historians and social scientists of such varied inclinations as Schmitt (1934), Taylor (1954), Holborn (1957), Morgenthau (1959), and Claude (1962) that this period encapsulates archetypically the operation of balance-of-power politics. Although few scholars might be willing to accept uncritically the view that events of the period reflected balance-of-power politics in a pure form, if our model fails to shed light upon this period then we have definite grounds for rejecting it as useful. We begin in this chapter by examining the relevant coalition formation activity of the great powers, and the particular coalitions that concern us are: 1. the League of the Three Emperors (Austria-Hungary, Germany, and Russia), 2. the Austro-German Alliance, 3. the Triple Alliance (Austria-Hungary, Germany, and Italy), 4. the First and Second Mediterranean Agreements (Austria-Hungary, Great Britain, and Italy), 5. the Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty, 6. the Dual Alliance (France and Russia), 7. the Entente Cordiale (Britain and France), and 8. the Triple Entente (Britain, France, and Russia).
224
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
We proceed under the assumption that these agreements reflected the dominant forces of great-power politics of the era, and our approach can be viewed as an assessment of the extent to which an exceedingly simplified view can nevertheless explain preferences as reflected by formal agreements and treaties. If we call the theory earlier chapters offer a theory of the balance of power, then it is tempting to interpret each resource measure rt as a measure of power and that it is power that countries gain and lose in international conflict and that simultaneously determines who wins and loses. However, devising an appropriate theoretical treatment of power and providing a meaningful operationalization remains one of the most intractable problems in political analysis (cf. Baldwin 1979 and Hart 1976). Indeed, the concept of power, as a theoretically primitive notion, is bogus it is at best a derivative idea (such as, for example, the notion of market power in microeconomic theory). Hence, we prefer not to debate appropriate conceptualizations of power. Nevertheless, the empirical application of our theory, in its present form, requires that we operationalize rt for each / in the international system under consideration. As indicated earlier, we prefer a theory that incorporates a careful analysis of the relationship between military capabilities and what countries gain and lose in international relations, or that allows for two jointly determined measures. Without such an analysis, however, we are left with two options: develop a measure of military capability and assume that it correlates with potential gains and losses, or develop a measure of potential gains and losses and assume that it correlates with military capabilities. Thefirstapproach is illustrated by Singer, Bremer, and Stuckey (1972) and the correlates-of-war project; the second approach is illustrated by Organski and Kugler's (1980) analysis based on GNP. Although we are sympathetic with Organski and Kugler's arguments, we operationalize r{ more in the spirit of Singer et al., but with significant modification. GNP seeks to measure the magnitude of a society's economy and thus it is an important indicator of what countries can gain and lose. Moreover, it is clearly not irrelevant to a society's military capability, and in the long run it may be the primary indicator of such capability. In the "short run," however, it can seriously misinform us about military imperatives and, thus, the imperatives guiding the decisions of national leaders who are concerned with the survival of their regimes or with the concessions they must make when confronting an immediate threat. Furthermore, although no measure escapes the problem, GNP also suffers from extremely unreliable measurement, especially in the nineteenth century.2 2
For a discussion of the problems associated with measuring economic variables in the period and with dealing with such issues as currency-conversion rates, see Deane and Cole (1962), Crafts (1983), and Fremdling (1985).
7.2 Methodology
225
Focusing then on military capability, the measurement of which should nevertheless take serious account of economic resources, we operationalize our index according to the following formula: ry = {[(MAMP7 x MOBF,) + PCL/+ PIOZ + PPI/+ PSLJ x FP,)/100, where MAMP is the military-age male population in thousands; MOBF is a mobilization factor; PCL, PIO, PPI, and PSL are (respectively) the annual production of coal, iron ore, pig iron, and steel in hundreds of thousands of standard tons; and FP is a force-projection factor. The raw product of the operations is divided by 100 to facilitate simple representation of the result for intercountry comparisons. Figures 7.14 through 7.20 in Section 7.11 summarize, for each country, the data from which we derive our national-resources index.
MAMP In view of the reasonable contention that military capability depends on the number of people in a country who can directly fight or indirectly support those who fight by economic production, it should not be surprising that we begin with the military-age male-population variable. It is an annual tally from census data of the male population in thousands of persons in the cohort 15-45 years of age; for those years in which census data are unavailable, we interpolate using available data.3 Although interpolation has the effect of smoothing variations between census data points, it preserves the more important demographic trends. We select this maleage cohort for two reasons. First, it is this cohort that is the pool from which military forces were recruited or conscripted by all the European great powers during this period and, thus, sets directly the upper boundary of manpower availability. Second, this cohort contains the majority of productive laborers in the economies of these great powers throughout the period and, thus, sets the upper boundary of manpower availability for the economy.4 3
4
There is no systematic census data for Imperial Russia for any year other than 1897. Official estimates by the Czarist government provide us with data points for 1851, 1858, and 1885. However, Khromov (1950) uses Czarist archival materials to estimate census data at ten-year intervals from 1800 to 1910. We have employed Khromov, the official estimate for 1885, and the census of 1897 to establish our data points and then have applied the demographic estimation techniques outlined in the text to generate the annual estimates. Although female and child labor were characteristic of all economies in agriculture and most of them in industry, there is little reliable data for any country except Britain for the period. Furthermore, the large-scale entry of women into the industrial workforce was a phenomenon more associated with World War I than the preceding period. We prefer a measure that includes the entire manpower pool, but MAMP seems an adequate approximation. Footnote 7 describes our demographic data sources.
226
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
MOBF The mobilization factor measures a country's ability to mobilize (1) military forces for deployment and (2) manpower for economic production in support of military operations. We define MOBF by the formula MOBF = (0.5[(RR/LA)/£]) x SEE, where RR/LA is the ratio of railway track length in kilometers to land area in square kilometers for the country under consideration, B is the standardization value assigned to the ratio of railway track length in kilometers to land area in square kilometers of Great Britain, and SEE is the staff-efficiency estimate.5 We select the ratio of railway track length to land area as an index of mobilization capacity for several reasons. First, there is ample evidence that this index in fact measures directly the ability of military forces to mobilize throughout the period in question (Pratt 1916; Napier 1920a, 1920b; Villate 1927; Meinke 1938; Shaw 1938; Ritter 1958; Williamson 1969; Showalter 1976; and Van Creveld 1977). Second, it is equally true that the level of development of a country's lines of communication and transportation infrastructure is a significant index of that country's ability to logistically support war. To obtain a standard for comparison, we have selected the country with the best railway-to-land-area ratio through the period, Great Britain, and set its value arbitrarily at 0.5. By dividing the other countries' railway-to-land-area ratio by that of Great Britain, we obtain a comparative ranking of the effects of transportation infrastructure on mobilization capability. SEE estimates the efficiency of a country's military-staff system as a force and mobilization multiplier. Although we prefer a direct index of such an intangible as the multiplier effect of staff efficiency, we are unable to discover a satisfactory one. This variable is, then, a judgment call based on contemporary evaluations of staff efficiency by the intelligence services and military establishments of the great powers and evaluations by military historians.6 We 5
6
We deviate from this procedure in the Russian case by using the land area in square kilometers of European Russia (i.e., west of the Urals) because the vast majority of the Russian population was concentrated in this land area and, with the exception of the TransSiberian railway, the entire Russian rail network was confined to this area. To use any other land-area standard for Russia would badly underestimate its already low mobilization capacity. We have particularly relied on estimates by the British War Office and Admiralty, both published (Great Britain, War Office, Intelligence Division, 1873, 1875, 1877, 1882, 1886, 1888, 1889, 1890, 1891, 1894, 1897, 1898, 1900, 1901, 1905, and 1913) and in archival form at the Public Records Office in London, as well as estimates of the German and French military establishments in the state archives of those countries. Among the relevant military historical studies are Maurice (1888), Von Kuhl (1920), Fuller (1926), Florinsky (1927), Villate (1927), Tyler (1938), Richmond (1941), Perry (1949), Askew (1951), Goerlitz (1953),
7.2 Methodology
227
set the lower boundary of the MOBF at 0.1 to reflect the minimum ability of any country in the period to mobilize military forces; this reflects empirical evidence from the archival materials cited in Footnote 6. PCL, PIO, PPL and PSL These variables are selected as the index of the contribution of economic production to logistical support because production of these commodities - coal, iron ore, pig iron, and steel - was the conditio sine qua non of military technology in the period.7 Note that for 1914, we extrapolate annual production from production figures for the first two quarters, thus avoiding contamination of the index with the consequences of decision making after the initiation of World War I. In measuring the production of these commodities in hundreds of thousands of standard tons, we are implicitly suggesting some comparability in effective military power between 1,000 men and 100,000 tons of a commodity. This seems an odd comparison at first glance, but in so doing we are attempting to reflect the military reality of the period. Between 1871 and 1914, a gradual, unevenly distributed, and incomplete transition between labor intensity and capital intensity in warfare began that fundamentally changed the nature of warfare. However, this transition was only dimly and incompletely perceived by military strategists in the period.8 Because we seek to index military
7
8
Perkins (1953), Challener (1955), Schurman (1955), Walsh (1957), Ritter (1958), Hittle (1961), Von Geyr (1962), De La Gorce (1963), Preston (1964), Gordon (1965), Turner (1965), Flammer (1966), Von Wahlde (1966), Ralston (1967), Gardiner (1968), Moon (1968), Williamson (1969), D'Ombrain (1970,1974), Gooch (1970), Summerton (1970), Addington (1971), Bond (1972), Walder (1973), Warner and Warner (1974), Alfoldi (1975,1976), Rothenberg (1975, 1976a, 1976b), Campion (1976), Murphy (1976), and Whittam (1976). The primary sources for both our economic and demographic data are Mitchell (1975) and statistical abstracts published by the governments of the countries under consideration. These abstracts include for Austria-Hungary: Nachrichten ueber Industrie, Handel und Verkehr (1873-1908), Oesterreichisches Statistisches Handbuch (1880-1914), Statistisches Jahrbuch der Oesterreichischen Monarchie (1871-81), and Magyar Statistikai Evkoeyv (1881-1914); for France: Annuaire Statistique de la France (1878-1914); for Germany: Statistisches Jahrbuch fuer das Deutsches Reich (1880-1914) and Statistik des Deutsches Reich (1873-1914); for Great Britain: Statistical Abstract for the Principal and Other Foreign Countries (1872-1912) and Statistical Abstract of the United Kingdom (1871-1914); for Italy: Annali di Statistica (1871-1914), Annuario Statistico Italiano (18781914), and Sommario de Statistiche Storiche Italiane, 1861-1955; for Russia: Annuaire de la Russie (1904-11) and Statistika Rossieskoie Impede (1887-1904). For example, the implications of Jean de Bloch's (1899) prophetic study of the intersection between technology, economics, and politics were almost universally ignored by contemporary professional military analysts. Indeed, the universal expectation of a short decisive campaign in 1914, shared by the general staffs of all the European powers, was a direct result of an underestimation of the role of the increasing capital and technology intensity of the modern battlefield. Cf. De Negier (1905), Henderson (1905), Kuropatkin (1909), Balck (1911), Von Bernhardi (1912), Altham (1914), and Foch (1903).
228
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
capability in terms relevant to the strategic decision making of military and political actors in this period, the relationship of manpower to economic production built into the index is a reflection of the tension between the labor-intensive preoccupations of contemporary strategists and the increasingly capital-intensive reality. FP By force projection, we do not merely mean the ability to move troops from place to place; if this were our meaning, there is no clear sense in which a naval power would have any advantage over a land power with a good railway network. Rather, we follow accepted military parlance in defining force projection as the ability to select the venue in which confrontation will take place. In an increasingly global economy, the ability to keep open sea-lanes of commerce - vital sources of raw materials on which the national economy of each great power depends - by either deterring potential opponents or, alternatively, crushing their attempts to interdict such commerce largely determines the sustainability of such a power in war. Where the force-projection variable assumes a low value, as with Russia after 1905, we would anticipate grave problems for such a country in sustaining its resource levels when at war with countries with higher-valued force-projection variables precisely because the ability to choose the field of battle permits a country to avoid those combat venues that most threaten its resource viability. Thus, we operationally define the force-projection variable in terms of the formula: FP = 1.5(NTC/NT^), where NTC is the naval tonnage of the country under consideration, NT^ is the naval tonnage of Great Britain, and 1.5 is the maximum force-projection multipier.9 We define the force-projection multiplier in terms of a comparison of naval tonnage for several reasons. First, force projection is significantly enhanced by the ability to deploy troops abroad by sea; this ability is a function of (1) the availability of troops to be transported (measured in the MAMP x MOBF variables), (2) the availability of sea transport,10 and (3) the availability of warships to defend that transport and to support it with naval bombardment. Second, the ability to project 9
10
We obtained the empirical data on naval tonnage primarily from Admirality archives in the Public Records Office in London. See also Maurice (1888), Stevens (1896), McHardy (1897), Clarke (1898), Herzfeld (1926), Hallmann (1927), Michalik (1931), Jouan (1932), Kehr (1933), Von Schonberg (1933), Woodward (1935), Marder (1940, 1961, 1964), Graham (1965), Steinberg (1965), and Gardiner (1968). In the absence of good direct data on the availability of sea transport, we estimate it indirectly through the naval-tonnage figure on the assumption that naval tonnage reflects shipbuilding capacity generally and, thus, implicitly permits ranking and comparison of the sea-transport capacity of each country.
7.2 Methodology
229
force is also dependent on the ability of a country to sustain its economic production by guaranteeing access to raw material abroad; this is to a significant degree a function of naval assets available for commitment to defending sea lines of communication, again measurable in terms of naval tonnage. Third, the ability to project force consists in part of the ability to engage opposing naval forces offensively, again a function of naval tonnage. To facilitate cross-national comparison, we standardize the measure by using the ratio of a country's naval tonnage to that of the premier naval power of the period, Great Britain. We set the maximum force projection multiplier at 1.5 in accordance with evidence from the archival materials cited in Footnote 9.11 Of the various components of our index, FP is perhaps the most problematic, since it is most sensitive to the endogenous forces of the theory. We prefer a measure of resources that explains alliance activity as well as the attempts of countries to increase their military capability, but with FP, we include a variable in which capability becomes an independent variable. Clearly, it is impossible to devise an adequate measure of military capability that does not have endogenous components - to assert otherwise is to deny Chapter 4's theoretical perspectives. FP, however, has advantages over variables others use, notably military expenditures, in that it is less subject to problems associated with currency conversion and it responds more slowly to the year-to-year strategic considerations of national leaders. Comparing the construction of our index to earlier efforts, wefindthat its general philosophy is in accord with Taylor's (1954, pp. xxiv-xxxii) discussion of population and coal, pig iron, and steel production as indicators of national power. We do not follow Taylor in including military expenditures and general manufacturing production as indicators for a number of reasons, among them the difficulty of obtaining accurate annual military-expenditure data and comparing over fluctuating currencyconversion and inflation rates, and our belief that the production factor indicators we survey encapsulate more precisely the impact of economic production variables on the ability to wage war than do general manufacturing totals. A contemporary alternative index is Singer, Bremer, and Stuckey's (1972), which they describe thus: 11
Assigning the maximum force-projection multiplier to Great Britain throughout the period might underestimate the effects of manpower constraints on British force-projection capability. However, MAMPxMOBF should compensate for any overestimation of force projection, and the ability to deploy troops is only one of the ways in which force projection multiplies military capability. With respect to the other two areas of force projection - sea-lane defense and offensive engagement of enemy naval forces - we feel justified in assigning the maximum multiplier to Great Britain. See Beckett (1974) for further data on British force projection.
230
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
We... combine [six separate indicators] into... a single power base or war potential ... score for each nation every half-decade. The six fall into three groupings of two dimensions each. The demographic dimension includes, first, the nation's total population, and second, the number of people living in cities of 20,000 or larger. The industrial dimension embraces both energy consumption (from 1885 on) and iron or steel production. The energy may come from many sources, but it is converted into coal ton equivalents, and the iron /steel production is based on the former only until 1895, at which time we shift to steel alone. The third pair of measures are military expenditures and armed forces size, excluding reserves. As to the more obvious validity questions, we carefully considered the need for separate indicators of social organization, national unity and motivation, and technical skills, but concluded that each of those was adequately reflected in one or more of the six specific indices. Closely related to the choice of indices and subindices is the matter of their relative contributions to a nation's power base [We] treat them as equally important, and additive in their effect. In line with these tentative assumptions, we first compute the total score (in people, tons, dollars, etc.) for the system, and then ascertain each nation's percentage share. This has the virtue of normalizing all of our data, reduces the computational problems associated withfluctuatingcurrency conversion rates, avoids that of changes in purchasing power, and puts the figures into ideal form for the computation of our concentration-distribution scores... (pp. 25-6).
This index offers a more conservative assessment of German resources and a greatly magnified assessment of Russia's than does our measure. Aside from the fact that our measure is more consistent with the qualitative assessment of Russian resources offered by Wohlforth (1987), there are other reasons why we reject this particular operationalization. First, the demographic indices seem more remote from the effects of demography on military power than our MAMP variable and ignore the relationship between demography and mobilization capability. Second, the industrial indices are problematic on two counts: the treatment of energy consumption in terms of coal-equivalent tons ignores the significance of differential rates of conversion from wood- to coal-based economies for the relative distribution of economic power among the European powers; and the shift between iron and steel indices blurs the significant differential between the premier industrial nations of Europe - Britain, Germany, and France - and those industrially less advanced - Austria, Italy, and Russia - which can only be seen in sufficient detail by comparing production along both iron and steel indices simultaneously. Third, the military indices are problematic on several grounds: (1) archival data on military expenditures refutes their claim of the relative ease of obtaining accurate figures, in part because of systematic concealment of expenditures by various budgetary devices employed by the great powers in this period, and suggests that the result of employing the published expenditure figures is to systematically underestimate the expenditures of Germany, Austria,
7.2 Methodology
231
150 -
100-
50-
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 —~— A u s t r i a - H u n g a r y
-&-
Great B r i t a i n
~^~
—B- Germany
~&-
Italy
—0— Russia
Figure 7.1
France
Great-power resources.
and Italy in particular; (2) even if the gross expenditurefigureswere reliable, their index fails to take into account differential rates of conversion of expenditure into capability (it fails to take into account the fact that, e.g., each German unit of expenditure would go farther toward enhancing capability than each Italian unit because of differences in the military and economic structures), because the normalizing procedure they follow addresses none of the structural sources of purchasing-power differentials between countries; (3) the use of military-force totals excluding reserves ignores the most fundamental military reality of the period - the conviction held by both military and political strategists that mobilization was the basis for waging land warfare - and, thus, distorts almost completely the real distribution of forces by inattention to differential rates of mobilization arising from differentials in mobilization capability; and (4) the use of military expenditures fails to resolve the problem of the endogeneity of the index. Fourth, we fail to see the way in which the normalization procedure they describe in fact reduces the serious problems of comparability across fluctuating currency-conversion rates and rates of inflation. Figures 7.1 and 7.2 summarize our operationalization of resources for the six great powers relevant to our analysis in absolute magnitude and as a percent of the total. These data suggest important questions, such as how other nations accommodated Britain's virtual near-predominance in the early period and how Britain accommodated the growth of Germany.
232
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
100%
75%-
50%-
25%-
0%
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 Austria-Hungary
Great Britian
Illlll France
Germany
Italy
I
Figure 7.2
I Russia
Great-power resources by percent.
Quick calculation also reveals that despite decline in France's relative position and the small relative sizes of Austria and Italy, no country is inessential in this period, and so World War I, which we must treat as more than an attempt to secure a modest reallocation of resources, must be explained. When comparing our index against alternative measures of power and resources, if our measure differs significantly from what others suggest, it does so in two respects. First, it attributes a considerably smaller share of resources to Russia as compared to Germany than does an index based on GNP or military personnel (as against indices based on per-capita GNP); indeed, it reveals a trend in which this disparity is increasing. Hence, our index cannot sustain viewing World War I as a preventive war launched by a Germany threatened by a Russian predominance. Rather than portraying Russia as a potential hegemon or even as an emerging threat, we see exactly the opposite: it is Russia that is declining relative to a German state that, early in the period, is more than a match against every power except Britain. This aspect of our index, then, is consistent with Wohlforth's (1987) qualitative assessment of Russian resources and strength, as well as Kennedy's (1987, pp. 209-42) evaluations of Germany and Russia. Second, our index sees Germany surpassing Britain in the early 1900s, whereas even a per-capita GNP calculation gives Britain the edge (albeit, a rapidly diminishing one). Our index, on the other hand, corresponds
7.2 Methodology
233
- © - British Mfg. Output ~~0— German Mfg. Output -*K- French Mfg. Output -S-
Russian Mfg. Output
"O-
British Resources
..$.. Q e r m a n Resources •••^- French Resources "Q-
1880
1900
Russian Resources
1913
Source: Kennedy (1987:202)
Figure 7.3 Comparison of manufacturing output and resource index by percent for Britain, Germany, France, and Russia.
closely to Kennedy's (1987, p. 202) assessment based on Bairoch's (1976) calculation of the relative shares of manufacturing output among the great powers. Figure 7.3 compares our index to this measure and reveals the parallelism in trends and magnitudes. To apply such data, however, we must do more than measure the resources of individual countries; we must also measure the value of potential coalitions from each country's view. And although, as we indicated earlier, expressions (4.1) and (4.2) provide the means for evaluation, we must nevertheless reduce some computational complexity and accommodate the fact that not all coalitions are feasible for reasons exogenous to our formal analysis. With six countries, there are 63 possible coalitions, and each country can be a member of 32 coalitions (including being unaligned); moreover, 31 coalitions can be aligned against any unaligned country, 15 against any two-country coalition, 7 against any three-country coalition, and so on. However, we deem a coalition involving both France and Germany as infeasible since to suppose otherwise severely misrepresents the strategic options of these two countries as well as the threats other countries might reasonably anticipate. This fact, for example, greatly diminishes British incentives to ally formally with any Continental power, at least until Germany's resources grow sufficiently. So a coalition that
234
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
fails to control half the resources may nevertheless be foreseen as winning by national leaders against feasible opponents, and, thus, defensively, as valuable as any other alliance. To accommodate such realities, we calculate g(C)/r(C) only for coalitions we deem feasible, with the understanding that the issue of feasibility must be treated carefully (as per our discussion of Hypotheses HI and HI'). The particular substantive constraints we consider are (1) France and Germany's inability to ally; (2) Britain's desire not to ally militarily with any continental power (although the logic of this "constraint" is assumed to follow the analysis offered in Chapter 6); and (3) the disruptive influences of the Balkans on Russia's and Austria's ability to forge an effective alliance. We can imagine other possible restrictions, but our method will be to consider the implications of these constraints in particular, exploring simultaneously the implications of an international system in which virtually no constraints operate. At this point, we should admit that the calculation of a coalition's value based on the characteristic function specified by our analysis has several disadvantages that must be kept in mind when we apply it. First, this calculation is more appropriate for evaluating offensive as against defensive coalitions (i.e., threats versus counterthreats). Although it tells us whether a coalition is winning or losing against feasible opponents, in the case of defensive coalitions - coalitions formed merely to maintain the status quo resource distribution - the ranking of coalitions based on what each coalition can expropriate from others that this calculation provides may be irrelevant. Second, this calculation ignores the fact that the historical record is one of human events in motion and of coalition formation in a world with uncertainty and incomplete information. Coalitions are commonly "stop-gap" measures to counter potential threats that are themselves not certain to materialize. Germany might ally with Russia or with Austria-Hungary so that it can consolidate its nationhood against potential threats by France and Britain, but Bismarck, as well as nearly everyone else, understood the fragility of such an alliance, its questionable value as a defensive agreement, and its virtual irrelevance as an offensive threat. Thus, reality lacks the "knife-edged" property that is part of a characteristic function's calculation in which small changes in resources render a losing coalition winning and vice versa. Finally, small resource changes can render a coalition winning or losing and, thus, yield sharp swings in relative value. A coalition that is barely losing may have to cede a great deal, whereas one that is barely winning may be credited with a substantial resource transfer to render its largest member near-predominant. Unfortunately, our resource index is but a highly imperfect measure of strategic capabilities, and this fact necessitates a careful interpretation of, and healthy skepticism toward, numbers.
7.3 The League of the Three Emperors
7.3
235
The League of the Three Emperors
The League of the Three Emperors, defensively used by Bismarck to isolate France and to thereby allow the consolidation of the polity and economy of the new German state, arose from three diplomatic agreements negotiated between May and October 1873. The first of these, the St. Petersburg Military Convention between Russia and Germany, signed on May 6,1873, specified that "if one of the two Empires should be attacked by a European Power, it shall be aided with the least possible delay by an army of 200,000 men of effective troops" (Lepsius, Mendelssohn-Bartholdy, and Thimme 1922-1927, Vol. I, p. 203). The second, the Convention of Schoenbrunn, signed by Austria-Hungary and Russia on June 6, 1873, revealed the defensive posture of the League: Their Majesties mutually promise, even though the interests of their States should present some divergences respecting special questions, to take counsel together in order that these divergences may not be able to prevail over the considerations of a higher order which preoccupy them. Their Majesties are determined to prevent anyone from succeeding in separating them in the field of the principles which they regard as alone capable of assuring, and, if necessary, of imposing the maintenance of the peace of Europe against all subversions, from whatsoever quarter they may come In case an aggression coming from a third Power should threaten to compromise the peace of Europe, Their Majesties mutually engage to come to a preliminary understanding between themselves, without seeking or contracting new alliances, in order to agree as to the line of conduct to be followed in common If, as a result of this understanding, a military action should become necessary, it would be governed by a special convention to be concluded between Their Majesties (Lepsius et al. 1922-1927, Vol. I, pp. 206-7). The third agreement of October 22, 1873 announced German adherence to the Convention of Schoenbrunn, which accorded treaty status by all three parties. The League was reinforced on June 18, 1881 in a joint convention - the Three Emperor's Alliance - that again reasserted the largely defensive posture of the contracting parties: In case one of the High Contracting Parties should find itself at war with a fourth Great Power, the two others shall maintain towards it a benevolent neutrality and shall devote their efforts to the localization of the conflict. This stipulation shall apply likewise to a war between one of the three Powers and Turkey, but only in the case where a previous agreement shall have been reached between the three Courts as to the results of this war. In the special case where one of them should obtain a more positive support from one of its two Allies, the obligatory value of the present Article shall remain in all its force for the third Russia, in agreement with Germany, declares her firm resolution to respect the interest arising from the new position assured to Austria-Hungary by the Treaty of Berlin The three Courts, desirous of avoiding all discord between them, engage to take account of their respective interests in the Balkan Peninsula. They further promise one another that any new modifications in the territorial status quo of Turkey in
236
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
Europe can be accomplished only in virtue of a common agreement between them. ... The three Courts recognize the European and mutually obligatory character of the principle of the closing of the Straits of the Bosphorus and of the Dardanelles ... (Lepsius et al. 1922-1927, Vol. Ill, pp. 176-8).
To this convention was appended an Austro-Hungarian protocol to which both Germany and Russia agreed reserving for Austria-Hungary the right to annex the Turkish provinces of Bosnia and Herzegovina, the administration of which had been granted to Austria-Hungary by the Treaty of Berlin, and establishing that "the three Powers will not oppose the eventual reunion of Bulgaria and Eastern Rumelia within the territorial limits assigned to them by the Treaty of Berlin" (Lepsius et al. 1922-1927, Vol. Ill, p. 179). Additionally, Russia accepted the Austro-German ministerial declaration of May 18, 1881, which reasserted the status of the AustroGerman alliance. The League remained in effect until its expiration in June 1887. In summary, then, from 1881-7, if Britain attacked Russia then Germany and Austria committed to neutrality, and if either France attacked Germany or Italy attacked Austria then Russia committed to neutrality.12 While some might suggest that these amendments to the original agreement make the Three Emperor's Alliance qualitatively different from the earlier League, it is precisely our argument that the underlying strategic dynamic that rendered the League only partially effective accounts for its evolution into the Alliance and the Alliance's eventual demise. Our first concern now is ascertaining the sense in which the League might be considered an optimal coalition from the perspective of its members, despite Taylor's assessment that "[t]he league was supposed to keep Europe at peace; in reality it could exist only so long as Europe remained pacific A new conflict between France and Germany, a new twist of the Eastern question, would destroy it" (1954, p. 221). Examining the potential coalitions and alliances for Germany from 1871 to 1887, in light of French revanchist ambitions arising from the Franco-Prussian War - for example, the demand for return of Alsace-Lorraine as a condition of negotiation - and the role of Franco-German rivalry in the emergence of the German state, we eliminate as infeasible any coalitions that include France.13 12
13
Skazkin (1928) provides a detailed history of the League, including important Russian archival material. Rupp (1941) provides an analysis of Austro-Russian relations in the context of the League, concentrating on the increasing conflict of basic interests that emerge in the context of the First Near Eastern Crisis. Gauld (1927) also discusses the role of intra-League conflicts of interest in this crisis. For the intra-League politics after the Congress of Berlin, see Gorianov (1918), Muller (1927), Medlicott (1929,1938,1945), and Leidner (1936). We assume that a Franco-German coalition was infeasible, but Franco-German relations were not uniformly hostile throughout the period. As John Keiger (1983, p. 68) argues:
237
7.3 The League of the Three Emperors
-50
-100 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911
-*-
BG~ABG~ABGI"
AG~GI
AGI
AGIR
GR
AGFTGIR
Figure 7.4 q(C)/r(C) for Germany, S — C as opposition.
With France excluded as an alliance partner, for the period 1871 to 1887, Figure 7.4 portrays g(C)/r(C) (times 100) for various German coalitions and suggests that the strongest and most preferred coalition is AGIR when it is winning (throughout this text, we use the abbreviations G = Germany, The major obstacle to any lasting improvement in Franco-German relations was the treaty of Frankfurt, by which Germany annexed Alsace and Lorraine. Yet France's attitude towards Germany fluctuated between 1871 and the First World War, partly as a result of who held power in France and partly as a result of Berlin's attitude. From a threatening stance between 1871 and 1875, Bismarck moved to a more conciliatory one for the next ten years, enthusiastically encouraged by the "peaceful" Republicans. The rise of Boulanger ended the detente, which was not fully resumed until 1894. Seven years of rapprochement were followed by four years of hostility under Delcasse, only to be followed by a further seven years of detente fostered by Ambassador Jules Cambon. The zig-zagging policy drew to a close with Poincare's desire to go back to Delcasse's old policy, which was bound to conflict with the Berlin incumbent Ambassador's ideas. The fate of Jules Cambon's policy reveals that Poincare's more pessimistic view of Germany was shared generally by policy-makers in France in 1912. Scholarly opinion is virtually unanimous in identifying the same impediments to such a coalition. The most authoritative study of French strategic perceptions is Carroll (1931); Challener (1975) provides a general survey of French national security policy and its constraints, as does Liddell-Hart (1967). An excellent diplomatic history of Franco-German relations may be had in Gooch (1923). The best general treatment of the influence of revanchist military elements on French foreign policy is Ralston (1967), and Contamine (1957) exhaustively examines la revanche in French society throughout the period. For the period immediately after the Franco-Prussian War, Benjamin (1932) is useful, as is Seager (1969) for the Boulanger affair; Langer (1929) and Irvine (1934) discuss French
238
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
A = Austria-Hungary, B = Britain, F = France, I = Italy, R = Russia),14 which adumbrates the Triple Alliance of 1882 in including Austria-Hungary and Italy and reflects German preferences had the maintenance of a coalition including both Austria-Hungary and Russia involved less serious differences in national interests. It is undoubtedly these underlying differences in interests, especially interests eventually amounting for Austria-Hungary to questions of national sovereignty, which account for the specific military convention Russia negotiated with Germany but not with Austria-Hungary. Further, Italian objections to Russian ambitions in the Ottoman Empire, although not fully warranting an ad hoc constraint on coalitions, seem to have militated against Italian participation in any coalition with Russia.15 We cannot, of course, discount the value of an alliance with Britain. AGIR is tenuously balanced against BF in the early years of the League's
14
15
strategic perceptions of Germany that occasioned the Dual Alliance. Leaman (1942) argues for domestic political concerns, particularly revanchist sentiment, influencing foreign policy in the period immediately preceding the First Moroccan Crisis. Christopher Andrew's (1968) study of Delcasse and the origins of the Entente Cordiale is a groundbreaking reappraisal for French foreign policy in that period. For the period of the Triple Entente, especially with regard to military influence on French policy makers, see Stuart (1921) and Cairns (1953). The exacerbation of Franco-German hostility between the two Moroccan crises is discussed in Smyser (1947) and Poidevin and Bariety (1977). Carroll (1938) does for Germany nearly as thorough a study as his study of French policy. Mitchell (1935) deals exhaustively with Bismarck's conciliatory policy toward France in the aftermath of the war, reaching, however, conclusions like our own regarding the feasibility of a Franco-German coalition. Wienefeld (1929) takes an even less sanguine view in his analysis of Franco-German relations in the late Bismarckian period; although he concentrates on the German army, Seaton (1973) reaches similar conclusions. Campion (1976) covers the period immediately after Bismarck's dismissal, focusing on the German military's strategic perceptions of France; Craig's (1955) study of the German armed forces carries the analysis forward to World War I. D'Ombrain (1970) discusses German military strategy and the formation of policy toward France during the Second Moroccan Crisis. Kitchen (1968), although focusing on the German officer corps in the Wilhelmine period, provides corroboration of military perceptions of strategic impediments to such a coalition. If, as a sensitivity check or as an accommodation for Britain's geographical remoteness, we increase German resources or decrease British resources by 10 percent, AGIR is winning from 1876 onwards. Salvemini (1944) analyzes Italian foreign policy throughout the period, and Bosworth (1979) improves on this work by virtue of access to previously unavailable Italian archival materials. Cardella (1928) provides a general survey of Italian policy on the Mediterranean and the Eastern Question, pointing out the conflicts between Italian and Russian and Italian and French interests, as does Castagno (1957) and Donaudy's (1937) study of Italian colonial policy from Cavour to Crispi. See D'Agostino (1969) for a discussion of Italy's economic interests in Ottoman North Africa, as well as Askew (1942) and Barclay (1973). Whittam's (1976) study of the politics of the Italian army sheds some light on military concerns underlying Italian perceptions of Russian threats to Italy's strategic interest in the Ottoman Empire. Brunschwig (1966) is good background to Franco-Italian rivalry in North Africa.
7.3 The League of the Three Emperors
239
existence, whereas a British coalition is uniformly winning. Indeed, if we depend on Figure 7.4 alone, we are left with the problem of explaining the emergence of AGR, the League, as an alliance based on an unviable counter (against S—C) put forward by members with fundamentally conflicting interests. The approximate balance between BF and AGIR, however, is but one possible basis for German strategy. There is ample evidence that German strategic thinking could, with careful diplomacy, take as an assumption Britain's preference for neutrality, provided that its interests were not directly threatened.16 Indeed, our accounting of British resources distorts matters by failing to accommodate the fact that Britain could not militarily intercede on the continent without a continental ally.17 More theoretically, it seems reasonable to suppose that the conditions of Theorem 6.3 are satisfied for this part of the nineteenth century so that, as we show later, Britain's strategic interests are best served by remaining neutral, provided that Germany pursued policies that did not directly threaten British economic interests. To see German motives for acting accordingly, Figure 7.5 recalculates g(C)/r(C) under the assumption of an unaligned Britain (except possibly in coalition with Germany itself). In this instance, the logic of the League becomes apparent: first, the League is one of three viable (winning) coalitions that do not involve Britain as a member, and, second, because of Germany's larger proportionate role in a winning coalition that excludes Britain, if we assume proportional allocation of gains, then Germany prefers AGR (as well as GR and AGIR) and an unaligned Britain. Thus, with Britain unaligned, AGR serves its purpose of meeting feasible threats, it is among the coalitions that are optimal as a threat, and it thereby renders the addition of Italy or a coalition with Britain unnecessary. 16
17
For a discussion of British interests in neutrality in this period, see Liebold (1930) and Bourne (1970). German appreciation of the advantages of British neutrality is analyzed in Rachfahl (1920), Fuller (1926), Pribram (1931), Carroll (1938), Israel (1938), Sonntag (1938), Langer (1950), and Medlicott (1956). The problem of British force projection onto the continent in the absence of a continental ally has been analyzed from several perspectives. The most acute difficulty appears to have been manpower procurement in the light of contending colonial and continental demands on British ground forces; the Card well reforms and their impact have been examined in detail by Allen (1960), Bond (1960, 1961, 1962a, 1962b), and Tucker (1963). See also Fuller (1926), Richmond (1941), Schurman (1955), Preston (1964), Cunningham (1975), and Skelley (1977). Lowe (1967b) provides documentary evidence for the policy implications of force-projection constraints. Gordon (1965) examines the extent to which dominion forces could amplify limited British ground resources in a Continental war. Fortescue's (1899-1930) history of the British army reveals the military and political dynamics underlying British force-projection capabilities throughout the period. Tyler (1938) and Williamson (1969) focus on the problem after the formation of Entente Cordiale, but comment on the earlier period. Merrill (1956) analyzes the strictly military problems arising from the coordination of British and allied naval and ground forces, which colored British perceptions in the ensuing period, and Anderson (1967) sheds light on the tensions between industrial and military demands on manpower.
240
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914 100
50 -
-1001 ' ' • I • ' ' I 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 G
- + - AG~GI
BG~ABG~ABGI~^ AGIR
AGi
-B-
AGFTGIR
GR
Figure 7.5 q(C)/r(C) for Germany, Britain unaligned.
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 AG
AGI
AB
ABGI
AGIR
AGR
AIR
ABF
Figure 7.6 q(C)/r(C) for Austria, S—C as opposition.
Examining the potential coalitions and alliances for Austria-Hungary in this period, we again eliminate any coalitions which ally France with Germany, as well as coalitions containing both France and Italy (for reasons we discuss in connection with the Triple Alliance). Figure 7.6 shows g(C)/r(C) for the most logical possibilities for Austria-Hungary. As in
241
7.3 The League of the Three Emperors 100
-80
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 AG
AGI
AB
ABGI
AGIR
AGR
AIR
ABF
Figure 7.7 q(C)/r(C) for Austria, FG infeasible, Britain unaligned.
the German case, although AGIR, when it is winning, affords the greater potential gain, ABF renders the League irrelevant from the Austro-Hungarian perspective and serves as a legitimate option to any alliance with Germany. It is tempting to speculate that it is the threat of such a coalition that binds Germany to its alliance with Austria, but if we apply the same reasoning in the Austrian case as we did for Germany by assuming an unaligned Britain, and if we also exclude any opposing coalition containing both France and Germany, then we obtain the evaluation Figure 7.7 portrays - an evaluation showing the commonality of German and Austro-Hungarian interests. Not only is AGR winning against feasible opponents, but it is Austria's most preferred coalition for the life of the League and, contrasting Figures 7.6 and 7.7, shows that, like Germany, Austria prefers AGR and an unaligned Britain to any coalition with Britain. To view matters from the Russian perspective, we ought to keep in mind the internal conflicts of an Austro-German-Russian coalition. In particular, it is the complex of interests relating to Austro-Hungarian national sovereignty that crucially affected the ability of the League to function. The Danube constituted the Austro-Hungarian Empire's economic lifeline; free navigation of the Danube and the maintenance of Turkish or other polities undominated by competing great powers (or dominated by Austria-Hungary) along this river was a necessary condition for the maintenance of Austria-Hungary's rate of domestic resource growth.
242
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
60 40
20f 0 20) 4U 60 80
I I I
I
I
I
1 1 I 1 1 1
I
I
1
1 1 1
1 1 1 1 1
1
I
I
I
I
I
I I
I
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 GR
FR
BR
AGIR
GIR~AGR
FIR~AFR
- B - BFR
Figure 7.8 q(C)/r(C) for Russia, S~C as opposition.
Indeed, severance of this Danubian lifeline would have resulted in Austria-Hungary's rapid economic collapse. Thus, Russian ambitions in the Balkans and, most importantly, its interest in dominating the Ottoman Turkish regime ran directly counter to Austria-Hungary's most vital interests and threatened that nation's national sovereignty. To the extent that these Russian ambitions could be curbed or that Russian incursions in the Balkans were paralleled by concessions to Austria-Hungary, as in the 1878 Treaty of Berlin, Austria-Hungary's entry into a coalition including Russia would be more likely. The difficulty arises from the inability of Austria-Hungary to grant sufficient concessions in the Balkans to appease Russian ambitions without compromising its national sovereignty. This problem arose in connection with the Near Eastern Crises of 1875-8 and 1885-7. These crises are discussed in detail in Chapter 8; however, it suffices for our purposes here to note that the expiration of the League results directly from this contradiction of interests.18 Indeed, the changes in League obligations outlined in the original 1873 and 1881 renewal agreements differed precisely to the extent that this fundamental difference in Austro-Hungarian and Russian interests obtain. 18
For the role of these conflicting interests in the demise of the League, see Gorianov (1918), Gauld (1927), Skazkin (1928), Medlicott (1938), Stojanovic (1939), Langer (1950), and May (1961). Summer (1937) examines Russia's interests in the Balkans and the problems these posed for the League. Blaisdell's (1929) study of European financial control in the Ottoman Empire reveals the economic stake both Austria-Hungary and Russia had in realizing distinct scenarios in the Ottoman Balkans.
243
7.3 The League of the Three Emperors 1 UU
!
50 t 0
-50
100
tf)
w
1 1
1 1
LTLX I I I
I
I
I
I
I
II I I
i
i
I I
i
i
I I
i
i
I I
371 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 GR
FR
BR
BFR
AGIR
GIR~AGR
FIR~AFR
FR + 5%
Figure 7.9 q(C)/r(C) for Russia, FG infeasible, Britain unaligned.
With this in mind, if we eliminate coalitions that include Britain, France and Germany, and any direct alliance with Britain (which seems only reasonable when we add Russian-British conflicts in Ottoman Turkey, Southwest Asia, and the Far East to British incentives for neutrality), the evaluations portrayed in Figures 7.8 and 7.9 demonstrate, as in the German and Austrian cases, the reasonableness of a coalition with these two countries. Yet, this analysis fails to answer questions about the viability of Russian threats to coalesce with France - a coalition that is losing against Britain and AGI. Such a threat was directed, of course, against an Austro-German alliance, and it is evident that it presumed British neutrality. We should keep in mind, though, the imprecision of our index. If we conduct a minimal-sensitivity analysis by modifying our accounting of Austrian, German, and British resources in various ways (by inflating or deflating those resources by, say, 5%) then our conclusions about Austrian and German imperatives remain largely unchanged. However, Figure 7.9 shows that even though FR is losing with Britain unaligned (against B and AGI), if we augment French and Russian resources by 5 percent then FR becomes winning in the period 1886-95. Indeed, if we add Italy to the coalition (witness French overtures to Italy from 1888 to 189019) then FIR is 19
We know, retrospectively, that such overtures were stillborn; however, as Dethan (1936) points out, French interest in dislodging Italy from the Triple Alliance rested on France's appreciation of the new strategic situation arising from the demise of the League.
244
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
winning without any augmentation. Thus, if strategic planning assumes our index, any reasonable accounting of uncertainty and the imperfection in that index as a measure of military capabilities renders a FrancoRussian threat credible.20 7.4
The Austro-German Alliance
Despite agreements between Germany and Russia, Germany clearly favored Austria in its formal alliances, as expressed by the Austro-German treaty signed by both powers on October 7, 1879. Among the key provisions of this treaty were the following: Should... one of the two Empires be attacked by Russia, the High Contracting Parties are bound to come to the assistance of the other with the whole strength of their Empires, and accordingly only to conclude peace together and upon mutual agreement Should one of the High Contracting Parties be attacked by another power, the other High Contracting Party binds itself not only not to support the aggressor against its high Ally, but to observe at least a benevolent neutral attitude towards its fellow Contracting Party Should, however, the attacking party in such case be supported by Russia, either by an active cooperation or by military measures which constitute a menace to the Party attacked, then the obligation stipulated in... this Treaty, for reciprocal assistance with the whole fighting force, becomes equally operative, and the conduct of this war by the two High Contracting Parties shall in this case also be in common until the conclusion of a common peace (Pribram 1920, pp. 25-6).
This treaty was renewed in 1883 and 1902, in the latter case for an indefinite period. In summary, then: if France attacked Germany, Austria committed to neutrality; if Russia attacked Germany or Austria, or if any combination of Russia with another great power attacked Germany or Austria, then Germany and Austria would respond. Were we to focus solely on the relative size of an alliance, this alliance in particular seems odd since the size rankings of potential single-paired alliances for Germany for the period 1879 to 1914 is BG > GR > AG = GI. 20
The interests of Russia in the Balkans and the Ottoman Empire generally related directly to its ability to maintain its rate of domestic resource growth and its rate of growth relative to the other great powers. The Austro-Hungarian need to resist such Russian ambitions accounts for the collapse of the League. However, this argument in no way mitigates Russia's general preference for a coalition with Germany to a coalition with France in the event of Austria-Hungary's nonavailability - especially at the point in which the League becomes irrelevant (1887), and a Russian-German coalition becomes winning (see Figure 7.4). Although Russia was able to credibly threaten a potential coalition with France against German interests in an effort to preempt German support for AustriaHungary, the underlying validity of our analysis is suggested by the Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty of 1887 and the stillborn 1905 Treaty of Bjoerko.
245
7.4 The Austro-German Alliance
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911
BR
BF
AB
BG~ABG~ABGI •
BFR
-B-
ABI
Figure 7.10 q(C)/r(C) for Britain, and FG, AR, and GR infeasible.
Thus, the apparent German preference for an alliance with Austria-Hungary (as evidenced by its formal treaty obligations) over alliances with Russia and Great Britain is unwarranted if we assume that size dictates the preferences of national leaders for coalition partners. However, a more detailed examination serves to emphasize that we cannot explain individual pairings within an alliance without reference to the alliance structure that characterizes the full system. First, to ascertain whether a German alliance with Austria over one with Britain violates our model, we ought to keep in mind that alliances must be mutually beneficial. Germany, as we have already seen, prefers a coalition with Austria, Italy, and Russia, or Austria and Italy as long as Britain remains neutral to any Continental conflicts. A preference for a coalition with Britain emerges only in the event of the unavailability of AGIR or of British willingness to coalesce with France or Russia against Germany. If we suppose, though, that a Franco-German as well as Austro-Russian rapprochement is impossible, and that by coalescing with Austria, Germany signals to Britain its unwillingness to side with Russia, thereby precluding a Russo-German threat to British interests, Britain's optimal strategy, as Figure 7.10 shows, is to remain unaligned, at least up to 1899. It also is apparent that by 1886, Anglo-German competition for economic markets had emerged as an important political-economic dynamic that characterized the period
246
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
through 1914.21 The repeated attempts of Great Britain and Germany to reach a rapprochement and their repeated failures to do so suggests that we are dealing with marginal considerations, but considerations which nonetheless color strategy. The problem of Germany's failure to ally with Russia on terms equivalent with its alliance with Austria-Hungary, however, remains. Although our analysis in Chapter 6 of geography's role applies only to three-country systems, geography seems relevant nonetheless. Given a Russo-German alliance in the absence of an Austro-German alliance, we must look at the countermoves available to Austria. Militarily, its most viable counter is an Austro-French coalition, which at some point would almost certainly involve the British as well. Germany would be faced with a multifront war threat - a war in which the proximity of Austria and France to the primary fields of battle would discount Austro-French resources to a lesser degree than Russian resources (see Heller 1926). In addition, we can view an Austro-German alliance as fulfilling the conditions for system stability that Remark 6.4 describes. With Russia an ineffectual military force against France (i.e., dRF
This is a matter of some controversy. Taylor (1954, p. 599) debunks the importance of economic factors in the failure of Anglo-German rapprochement, but see the evidence presented by Ibbeken (1928), Sonntag (1938), Anderson (1939), Hale (1940), Erusalimskii (1954), and Hoffmann (1964). For the British view of Anglo-German colonial rivalry in economic terms, see Veal (1917), Adams (1937), Imlah (1950), Cairncross (1953), Court (1965), and Gifford and Louis (1967); for the German view, see Aydelotte (1937), Henderson (1938, 1948), and Bald (1970). Even Taylor (1967) gives greater weight to economic factors in his discussion of the origins of Anglo-German colonial rivalry. For discussion of the attempts at Anglo-German rapprochement, see Meinecke (1927), Ehringhaus (1929), Ritter (1929), Roloff (1929), and Hilbert (1954).
7.4 The Austro-German Alliance
247
-100 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911
BR
BF
AB
BG~ABG~ABGI-
BFR
-a-
ABI
Figure 7.11 q(C)/r(C) for Britain, FG and AR infeasible.
1909. From 1879 to 1886, we have no problem in excluding Britain as a feasible coalition partner (it can do at least as well unaligned), but after 1886, we cannot apply this argument. Our problem once again is that we cannot use our model to explain single pairings of countries in an alliance without reference to the full alliance structure that characterizes a system. For example, if Russia is excluded because of Austro-Russian and Anglo-Russian conflicts,22 and if the presumption of an unaligned Britain no longer serves as a legitimate basis for strategy (i.e., if Figures 7.7 and 7.5 are irrelevant), then Austrian and German preferences for a coalition with Britain coincide (Figures 7.4 and 7.6). Indeed, the Mediterranean agreements might be seen as a harbinger of such a realignment. Such a realignment was nevertheless largely stillborn, and we suspect that once again geographical considerations, as well as a successful strategy to keep Britain neutral, play the decisive role. The proximity of Germany to Russia certainly discounted German resources counterbalancing Russian aggression against Austria-Hungary to a lesser degree than those of Great Britain. Despite Britain's force-projection capability, it could not have transported military forces of the same size or larger than those 22
For discussions of the conflicting interests between Britain and Russia in Ottoman Turkey, Southwest Asia, and the Far East, see Maurice (1905), Rachfahl (1920), Liebold (1930), Harris (1936, 1939), Israel (1938), Sumner (1942), Wheeler (1956), Walsh (1957), Pierce (1960), Becker (1969), and Morris (1975). See also Martens (1879) for a contemporary account of British perceptions of the Russian threat in Central Asia.
248
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
of Germany to face a Russian threat to Austria-Hungary. Furthermore, given Anglo-German economic rivalry, such a coalition might well have prompted Germany to side with Russia. Thus, the apparent advantages of an Anglo-Austro-Hungarian coalition seem to have been evanescent. Additionally, factors of timing exogenous to the model may have played a role. The renewal of the Austro-German Alliance in 1883 antedates British interest in coalition partners and tied Austria-Hungary to its German alliance for twenty years. The 1902 renewal came at a point of serious British overtures to Germany, and, thus, considerations arising from faulty Austro-Hungarian perceptions of the likelihood of Anglo-German rapprochement may have to be taken into account.23 7.5
The Triple Alliance
The Triple Alliance first emerged in a treaty concluded between AustriaHungary, Germany, and Italy on May 20, 1882 in Vienna and in joint ministerial declarations issued by the allies on May 22,1882.24 The treaty specified the following: The High Contracting Parties... will enter into no alliance or engagement directed against any one of their States... and they further promise... mutual support within the limits of their own interests In case Italy, without direct provocation on her part, should be attacked by France for any reason whatsoever, the two other Contracting Parties shall be bound to lend help and assistance with all their forces to the Party attacked If one, or two, of the High Contracting Parties, without direct provocation on their part, should chance to be attacked and to be engaged in a war with two or more Great Powers nonsignatory to the present Treaty, the casus foederis will arise simultaneously for all the High Contracting Parties In case a Great Power nonsignatory to the present Treaty should threaten the security of the states of one of the High Contracting Parties, and the threatened Party should find itself forced on that account to make war against it, the two others bind themselves to observe towards their Ally a benevolent neutrality If the peace of any of the High Contracting Parties should chance to be threatened... the High Contracting Parties shall take counsel together in ample time as to the military measures to be taken with a view to eventual cooperation. They engage henceforward, in all cases of common participation in a war, to conclude neither armistice, nor peace, nor treaty, except by common agreement among themselves (Lepsius et al. 1922-1927, Vol. Ill, pp. 245-7).
That France was perceived as the principal threat and that the Alliance sought to neutralize Britain's attitude toward it is underscored by the ministerial declaration, adopted at Italian insistence, that specified that "the 23 24
For a detailed discussion of Anglo-Austro-Hungarian relations, see Pribram (1923,1931, 1951), Wedel (1932), Leidner (1936), May (1961), Birch (1966), and Jelavich (1969). Useful histories of the Alliance include Heller (1925), Coolidge (1926), Medlicott (1929, 1938), Leidner (1936), Carroll (1938), Salvemini (1944), Langer (1950), and Taylor (1954).
7.5 The Triple Alliance
249
provisions of the secret Treaty concluded May 20, 1882, between Italy, Austria-Hungary, and Germany, cannot, as has been previously agreed, in any case be regarded as being directed against England" (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, p. 69). In summary, then, if France attacked Italy, AGI would respond; if France attacked Germany, GI would respond; and if any combination of Britain, France and Russia attacked Germany, Austria, or Italy, then AGI would respond. The Alliance was first renewed on February 20, 1887 in the form of a joint protocol, a treaty renewing the 1882 treaty, and separate treaties between Italy and Germany and Italy and Austria-Hungary. The ItaloGerman treaty focused specifically on France and, more in the spirit of a threat, provided the following: The High Contracting Parties, having in mind only the maintenance, so far as possible, of the territorial status quo in the Orient, engage to use their influence to forestall, on the Ottoman coasts and islands in the Adriatic and Aegean Seas, any territorial modification which might be injurious to one or the other of the Powers signatory to the present Treaty If it were to happen that France should make a move to extend her occupation, or even her protectorate or her sovereignty, under any form whatsoever, in the North African territories... and that in consequence thereof Italy, in order to safeguard her position in the Mediterranean, should feel that she must herself undertake action in the said North African territories, or even have recourse to extreme measures in French territory in Europe, the state of war which would thereby ensue between Italy and France would constitute ipso facto, on the demand of Italy and at the common charge of the two Allies, the casus foederis with all the effects foreseen by... the aforesaid Treaty of May 20, 1882, as if such a eventuality were expressly contemplated therein If the fortunes of any war undertaken in common against France should lead Italy to seek for territorial guarantees with respect to France for the security of the frontiers of the Kingdom and of her maritime position, as well as with a view to the stability of peace, Germany will present no obstacle thereto; and if need be, and in a measure compatible with circumstances, will apply herself to facilitating the means of attaining such a purpose (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 111-15). The key provision of the separate Italo-Austro-Hungarian treaty specified the following: The High Contracting Parties, having in mind only the maintenance, so far as possible, of the territorial status quo in the Orient, engage to use their influence to forestall any territorial modification which might be injurious to one or the other of the Powers signatory to the present Treaty. They shall communicate to one another all information of a nature to enlighten each other mutually concerning their own dispositions, as well as those of other Powers. However, if, in the course of events, the maintenance of the status quo in the regions of the Balkans or of the Ottoman coasts and islands in the Adriatic and in the Aegean Sea should become impossible, and if, whether in consequence of the action of a third Power or otherwise, Austria-Hungary or Italy shouldfindthemselves under the necessity of modifying it by a temporary or permanent occupation on their part, this occupation
250
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
shall take place only after a previous agreement between the two Powers aforesaid, based upon the principle of a reciprocal compensation for every advantage, territorial or other, which each of them might obtain beyond the present status quo, and giving satisfaction to the interests and well founded claims of the two Parties (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 107-8).
The Alliance was renewed on May 6, 1891 in a treaty that contained the provisions of the 1882 treaty and the separate Italo-German and ItaloAustro-Hungarian treaties, plus an additional article that sought once again to dissuade Britain from perceiving the alliance as a threat to her interests with the clause "[i]t is understood that in such an eventuality the two Powers would seek to place themselves likewise in agreement with England" (Lepsius et al. 1922-1927, Vol. VII, p. 102). The Triple Alliance in this form was renewed again in 1902 and 1912. The rationale for such clauses is evident. With British opposition joined to a Franco-Russian threat, AGI is a losing coalition (see Figure 7.4), but with Britain unaligned, AGI from 1889 to 1904 is Germany's most profitable coalition and is essentially as profitable as any other thereafter (see Figure 7.5). Moreover, for the period 1876-88, AGI is losing by so slight a margin (less than 2% of the resources involved), and given the ambiguities inherent in our index of resources, we should deem AGI with Britain neutral as at worst a blocking coalition. After 1908, of course, Germany's most serious threat is BFR and its only counter is the Triple Alliance. An equivalent analysis applies for Austria and Italy.25 In the approximate period, 1882-7, we can regard the participation of Austria-Hungary in the Triple Alliance as insurance against the evident unviability of the League owing to its conflicts with Russia. And in the period 1889-1904, Austria's most potentially profitable strategy is to form AGI and keep Britain neutral to any conflict (Figure 7.7) or to align with Germany and Britain (Figure 7.6). Indeed, as in the previous period (1871-88), the observed alliance with Britain neutral is preferred. And although our analysis implies a weakening of British reticence to coalesce fully with continental powers after 1887, the imperatives for maintaining AGI that Figure 7.7 describes are not vitiated. Owing to the parallelism in our data between Austrian and Italian resources, the rankings and strategic imperatives for Italian coalitions match those for Austria. Thus, if coalitions with France or Russia are infeasible, our previous argument about AGI's viability pertain. Indeed, the policy of French support for the Papacy at the time of the unification of Italy, as well as territorial adjustments demanded of the Sardinian throne by 25
For background on the particular Italian concern for Great Britain, Glanville's (1934) study, while concentrating on a later period, is useful.
7.6 The Mediterranean agreements
251
France, colors Italian perceptions of a French threat to Italian national sovereignty (cf. Curatulo 1915, Bourgeois 1926, Case 1932, and Halperin 1939). Furthermore, French preemption of Italian colonial aspirations in North Africa - a colonial expansion Italy regarded as a necessary condition for national survival in the international arena - also tended to reinforce this Italian perception. Finally, this attempted preemption of colonial expansion had serious domestic economic consequences for Italy.26 The Italo-Russian case is similar to the French in that realization of Russian aspirations at hegemony over the Ottoman Empire would have the same preemptive colonial effect as French policy in North Africa. 7.6
The Mediterranean agreements
The first Mediterranean agreement was initiated at German prompting in a communication from the Italian Foreign Ministry to the British Foreign Office on February 12, 1887: The status quo in the Mediterranean as well as the Adriatic, the Aegean Sea, and the Black Sea shall be maintained so far as possible. Care must be taken... to prevent any change, which.. .would affect the present situation to the detriment of the two Powers If the maintenance of the status quo becomes impossible, they shall so act that no modification whatsoever shall occur except after a previous agreement between the two Powers Italy is entirely ready to support the work of Great Britain in Egypt. Great Britain... is disposed, in case of encroachments on the part of a third Power, to support the action of Italy at every point whatsoever of the North... and to the extent that circumstances shall permit, Italy and England promise one another mutual support in the Mediterranean in every difference which may arise between one of them and a third Power (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 95-6). The British Foreign Secretary endorsed these principles on the same date. On March 24, 1887, the Austro-Hungarian ambassador communicated his government's adherence to these principles to the British Foreign Office. The second Mediterranean agreement was embodied in a communication between the Austro-Hungarian and British governments on December 12, 1887: [T]he Government of His Imperial and Royal Apostolic Majesty has come to an agreement with the Government of Italy to pose to the Government of Great Britain the adoption of the following points, intended to confirm the principles... [of the first Mediterranean agreement] and to define the common attitude of the three Powers in prospect of the eventualities which might occur in the Orient The 26
For discussions of this issue, see Curatalo (1915), Cardella (1928), Donaudy (1937), McKay (1939), Askew (1942), Salvemini (1944), Ling (1955), Castagno (1957), D'Agostino (1969), Barclay (1973), and Bosworth (1979).
252
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
maintenance of peace and the exclusion of all policy of aggression The maintenance of the status quo in the Orient, based on the treaties, to the exclusion of all policy of compensation The maintenance of the local autonomies established by the same treaties The independence of Turkey, as guardian of important European interests..., of all foreign preponderating influence Consequently, Turkey can neither cede nor delegate her suzerain rights over Bulgaria to any other Power, nor intervene in order to establish a foreign administration there, nor tolerate acts of coercion undertaken with this latter object Likewise, Turkey, constituted by the treaties guardian of the Straits, can neither cede any portion of her sovereign rights, nor delegate her authority to any other Power in Asia Minor The desire of the three Powers to be associated with Turkey for the common defence of these principles In case of Turkey resisting any illegal enterprises... the three Powers will immediately come to an agreement as to the measures to be taken for causing to be respected the independence of the Ottoman Empire and the integrity of its territory, as secured by previous treaties Should the conduct of the Porte, however,... assume the character of complicity with or connivance at such illegal enterprise, the three Powers will consider themselves justified by existing treaties in proceeding, either jointly or separately, to the provisional occupation by their forces, military or naval, of such points of Ottoman territory as they may agree to consider it necessary to occupy in order to secure the objects determined by previous treaties (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 125-7).
The Mediterranean agreements differ somewhat from the cases we have hitherto analyzed as a result of the motivations of the participants, notably Britain.27 As Figure 7.12 shows, even if we make no accounting for the special advantages of British geography, prior to 1876, Britain could successfully meet any threat if it were aligned with any other power (Austria or Italy in the figure, the two smallest powers), regardless of the feasibility of alternative threats. From 1871 to 1883, Britain held the balance between France and the remaining continental powers (i.e., BF is either winning in the period or barely losing), and from 1871 to 1895, it holds the balance between Russia and other continental powers. The pessimism Figure 7.12 assumes about feasible opponents, however, seems unwarranted, and, referring back to Figure 7.11, we see that the critical juncture in Britain's unique position as a balancer occurs between 1891 and 1899. Specifically, if we exclude simultaneous threats from France and Germany, as well as from Austria and Russia, Britain can counter feasible opponents unaligned until 1873, and aligned with France, Germany, or Russia until 1891. From that point forward, however, Britain was increasingly confronted with the prospect of needing multiple coalition partners to form threats and viable counterthreats. In short, its special position as balancer erodes. 27
For a general discussion, see Medlicott (1926, 1929, 1938, 1956), Cardella (1928), Liebold (1930), Israel (1938), Birch (1966), Lowe (1967a), Bourne (1970), and Seton-Watson (1972).
253
7.6 The Mediterranean agreements
-100 h 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907
BR
BF
AB
BG~ABG~ABGI-
BFR
-a-
1911
ABI
Figure 7.12 q(C)/r(C) for Britain, S-C as opposition. A sensitivity analysis shows, of course, that any relative increase in British resources pushes ahead the year at which various coalitions are no longer winning. For example, a 10 percent increase renders BF winning until 1900, and if we assume that a Russo-German threat is infeasible, then Britain can counter any threat unaligned until 1900 (see Figure 7.10). Nevertheless, our analysis rebuts Rosecrance's assertion that "Theoretically, Britain should not have departed from her policy of 'splendid isolation' to ally with continental powers..." (1963, p. 142). Britain's participation in the Mediterranean agreements reflects her increasing need, and the Russian threat to Ottoman autonomy presented in the second Near Eastern Crisis was the proximate occasion for this coalition's forming. Although it is true that Britain alone could have defeated Russia in absolute resource terms, we suspect that the discounting dynamic identified in our discussion of geographical factors in balance-of-power politics underlies Britain's willingness to enter the coalition: Britain's distance from Turkey's Balkan possessions discounted its resources, despite its forceprojection capacity, to such a degree that the lesser discounting arising from Russia's proximity to Turkey's Balkan possessions resulted in at least parity, if not Russian superiority, in any confrontation in the region. As Figure 7.11 shows, if joint threats from France and Germany and from Austria and Russia are unlikely, then ABI is Britain's optimal coalition from 1886 to 1899; and if a Russo-German threat is also deemed infeasible, then, as Figure 7.10 shows, ABI is optimal until even the outbreak
254
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
of World War I. The cases of Austria and Italy's participation in this agreement have been addressed earlier. 7.7
The Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty
We turn, then, to the Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty, which arose in direct response to the collapse of the League in 1887.28 The treaty, signed on June 18, 1887, provided that: In case one of the High Contracting Parties should find itself at war... the other would maintain a benevolent neutrality towards it, and would devote its efforts to the localization of the conflict. This provision would not apply to a war against Austria or France in case this war should result from an attack directed against one of these two latter Powers by one of the High Contracting Parties Germany recognizes the rights historically acquired by Russia in the Balkan Peninsula, and particularly... in Bulgaria and Eastern Rumelia. The two Courts engage to admit no modification of the territorial status quo of the said peninsula without a previous agreement between them, and to oppose, as occasion arises, every attempt to disturb this status quo or to modify it without their consent (Lepsius et al. 1922-1927, Vol. V, pp. 253-4). Appended to the treaty was a secret protocol that specified: Germany, as in the past, will lend her assistance to Russia in order to reestablish a regular and legal government in Bulgaria In case His Majesty the Emperor of Russia should find himself under the necessity of assuming the task of defending the entrance of the Black Sea in order to safeguard the interests of Russia, Germany engages to accord her benevolent neutrality and her moral and diplomatic support to the measures which His Majesty may deem it necessary to take to safeguard the key of His Empire (Lepsius et al. 1922-1927, Vol. V, pp. 254-5). The treaty expired after three years and was not renewed. As our discussion of the League suggests, Germany's willingness to entertain such a treaty arises from the value of the coalition GR compared to AG in the absence of AGR, the League. The dissolution of the League in 1887 as a result of intractable conflicts of interest in the Balkans between Austria-Hungary and Russia opened Germany to the threat presented by a potential Russo-French alliance. The Reinsurance Treaty retained for Germany the effects of the League by ensuring Russian neutrality in the event of French aggression. The corollary German pledge of neutrality in case of an Austro-Hungarian attack on Russia was meaningless in light of Austro-Hungarian assurances that it would take no action without prior consultation. Indeed, with Russia and Britain neutral, Germany could counter any French threat short of an unlikely coalition of France, 28
This treaty has been of particular interest to German scholars. See especially Rachfahl (1920), Raab (1923), and Muller (1927). Also useful is Campion (1976).
7.8 The Dual Alliance
255
Italy, and Austria. Thus, Germany made no real concession to obtain its maximum feasible benefit. Russia's interest in the Treaty arises from the failure of the League. The greater strength of the coalition GR than the coalition FR predisposed Russia to seek continuation of its relationship with Germany for as long as Germany could be guaranteed to restrain Austria-Hungary or to remain neutral in the event of Austro-Hungarian aggression. With Germany neutral, Russian resources very nearly equaled even those of France and Austria combined, and geography discounted French resources to the extent that Russia achieved predominance on any feasible region of its primary interests. The potential Russo-French alliance remained as a lever to guarantee German adherence to the treaty or an alternative if the treaty failed. 7.8
The Dual Alliance
The Dual Alliance commenced in the form of a military convention between France and Russia, signed on August 17, 1892. This convention specified that: France and Russia... and having no other aim than to prepare for... a defensive war, provoked against either of them by an attack by the forces of the Triple Alliance, have agreed upon the following provisions: [1] If France is attacked by Germany, or Italy supported by Germany, Russia shall employ all her available forces to fight Germany. If Russia is attacked by Germany, or by Austria supported by Germany, France shall employ all her available forces to fight Germany. [2] In case the forces of the Triple Alliance or one of the Powers which compose it should be mobilized, France and Russia, at the first indication of the event, and without a previous agreement being necessary, shall mobilize all their forces immediately and simultaneously, and shall transport them as near to the frontiers as possible. [3] The forces available which must be employed against Germany shall be for France, 1,300,000 men; for Russia, from 700,000 to 800,000 men. These forces shall begin complete action with all speed, so that Germany will have to fight at the same time in the east and the west. [4] The Staffs of the armies of the two countries shall constantly plan in concert [5] France and Russia shall not conclude peace separately. [6] The present Convention shall have the same duration as the Triple Alliance (Pribram 1920, Vol. II, pp. 215-17). This military convention was accorded treaty status by the Russian government on December 27,1893 and by the French government on January 4, 1894.29 29
A considerable literature on the formation and history of the Dual Alliance exists. Langer's (1929) survey is marred only by the unavailability of important French and Russian archival material at the time of its publication. Renouvin (1934, 1955), Taylor (1954), Bovykin (1979), and Girault (1979) remedy this deficiency. Viner (1929), Poidevin (1970), and Girault (1973) point out the importance of Franco-Russian economic relations,
256
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
The treaty obligations established between France and Russia are not, of course, optimal for either country: FR is not even a winning coalition. However, if we eliminate those coalitions and alliances including AustriaHungary (1893-1914), Italy (1893-1914), Great Britain (1893-1907), and Germany (1893-1914) as infeasible or otherwise unavailable owing to the interests of these countries, then the only coalition remaining to France and Russia is FR. The Russo-French alliance illustrates a simple fact: not all countries can be members of minimum winning coalitions simultaneously. We have already discussed the reasons for which the Austro-Hungarian and Italian coalitions are infeasible. A formal alliance with Britain fails for similar reasons. Figure 7.11 shows the advantages to Britain of a coalition with Russia, especially in the period 1902-11, but conflicts over Ottoman Turkey, Persia, Afghanistan, and Tibet are part and parcel of a struggle for colonial expansion that pitted Russian interests in the Near East and Asia against British interests in safeguarding its lines of communications to India and in the security of its colonial interests in the East.30 Moreover, given the inaccessibility of other regions for Russian colonial ambitions and the importance of colonial expansion to national survival among the great powers in this period, Russian compromises accompanying such a coalition could well have threatened its sovereignty or at least the stability of the regime. However, in addition, Figure 7.11 shows a plethora of British options. As long as Russian dalliances with Germany do not cement the Austro-German-Italian alliance, Britain can choose between a coalition with Russia, with Russia and France, with Austria and Italy, and with Germany. The availability of these options, in accordance with Hypothesis HI, lessens considerably British incentives to render an alliance with Russia politically feasible.
30
particularly French financing of Russian economic development. Irvine (1934) analyzes the military aspects of the alliance from a French perspective, as does Von Wahlde (1966) for the Russian. The literature on Anglo-Russian conflicts of interest in the Ottoman Empire, Central Asia, and the Far East is extensive. Allen and Muratoff (1953) survey the Russian military presence on the Turco-Caucasian border, and Wheeler (1956), Pierce (1960), Becker (1969), and Morris (1975) examine Russian interests in Central Asia. Cowles (1969) provides an interesting perspective in a treatment of Anglo-Russian relations as a "cold war." Liebold (1930) and Stojanovic (1939) investigate the role of these antagonisms in British policy toward the Near Eastern Crisis of 1875-8, and Lowe (1967a) surveys Anglo-Russian relations in the context of Liberal foreign policy, as does Medlicott (1956) and Seton-Watson (1972). Martens (1879) provides a contemporary account of these antagonisms during the Near Eastern Crisis. Sumner (1942) examines Russian imperialist ambitions in the Middle East and East Asia, and Walsh (1957) discusses the importance of India in Russian military planning.
7.8 The Dual Alliance
257
With regard to the feasibility of a Russo-German coalition, notice that GR is stronger than the coalitions AG, AGI, and FR. These relationships are pertinent, however, only to the extent that the stronger coalition can be trusted and that both members perceive mutual gains from alliance. First, a reputational dynamic undermines German willingness to align with Russia in the face of Russian willingness to align with France. In the Near Eastern Crises of 1875-8 and 1885-8, Russia attempted to threaten a Russo-French alliance to force Germany to apply pressure on Austria-Hungary for concessions in the Balkans. In neither case was this strategy successful, owing (as we have argued) to Germany's need for Austria as a partner to offset its vulnerability as a central power. In any event, the repeated threats from an ally of an alliance with Germany's chief enemy undermined German trust in any alliance with Russia. Conversely, German unwillingness to apply pressure on Austria-Hungary, even in the face of threats of a Russo-French alliance, no doubt led Russia to question the utility of a strong alliance incapable of producing favorable outcomes for Russia. However, to argue that the infeasibility of a Russo-German alliance arises wholly from these reputational considerations ignores the fact that reputation, like feasibility itself, is more an effect than a cause (cf. Hypothesis HI'). Notice in particular that if the coalition GR forms, then the basis for a counterthreat (and thus a threat) from ABF is established. This basis is established, moreover, at a time when Britain is no longer near-predominant, and GR's value exists only with Britain neutral. That is, Germany's optimal policy in this period is maintaining British neutrality and allying to form either AGI or AG (Figure 7.5). In short, the formation of GR poses real dangers to both participants, especially for Germany in the form of reduced reliability in the availability of Austria's resources and in the form of incentives for Britain to seek formal counter alliances. With respect to French participation in the alliance, it is evident that the rivalry of France and Great Britain for colonial possessions and markets, particularly in Central and Eastern Africa and Southeast Asia, provided an impediment to any formal alliance including both countries. Important to the failure to immediately resolve these disputes is the fact that throughout the period of 1886-1900, British resources are approximately equal to those of FR and exceed those of AG. With Russia split off from Germany, Britain could counter any feasible threat to its interests - especially its interests in Asia and India - and, consequently, has little incentive to resolve its disputes with France to form BFR. French acceptance of an FR alliance, then, reflects the character of that alliance as the strongest option available to it.
258
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
7.9
The Entente Cordiale and the Triple Entente
Members of losing coalitions should seek to expand their coalition until it becomes winning or can counter feasible threats, and the Entente Cordiale between France and Britain reflects such strategic necessities. On March 20,1899, France conceded de facto British control of Egypt in exchange for British recognition of a French sphere of influence in the region of Eastern Sahara. Although this Fashoda Agreement did not immediately result in an effective Anglo-French coalition, it set the pattern of cooperation resulting in the three joint declarations of April 8,1904 from which the Entente Cordiale is usually dated.31 These declarations resolved standing disagreements over Egypt and the Sahara, Morocco, West and Central Africa, and Newfoundland, as well as coordinated Anglo-French policy in Morocco. Military coordination followed from this coordination of Moroccan policy32 and, as a participant in that coordination, Lieutenant Colonel C. A'Court Repington reported that "the Anglo-French military conversations, officially begun in January 1906, continued uninterruptedly till the outbreak of war in 1914" (1920, p. 14). However, neither the Entente Cordiale nor its successor, the Triple Entente, enjoyed the diplomatic status of alliances. Recall that until at least 1886, Britain had little incentive to seek coalition partners. After 1886, it sought the ABI coalition in the form of the Mediterranean agreements in the face of specific Russian threats (or implicitly, ABGI, given German treaties with Austria and Italy). Interestingly, however, Britain is largely indifferent between ABGI and BFR up to about 1906 (see Figure 7.12), but develops a preference for BFR over ABGI thereafter. Indeed, this preference materializes regardless of whether we place feasibility constraints on the opposition to British coalitions (compare Figures 7.11 and 7.10). What Figures 7.11 and 7.12 also make clear is that over time, owing to Germany's increased military potential, strategic coalitional alternatives disappear. AB, then BF, then ABI, and then BR become losing coalitions, and Britain is left with a choice between joining the Triple Alliance on progressively unequal terms with 31
32
For discussions of the role of the Fashoda Agreement in setting the stage for the Entente Cordiale, see Stuart (1921), Giffen (1930), Mathews (1939), Hargreaves (1953), Brown (1970), Goode (1971), and Wright (1972). See Guillen (1968) for the effects of the colonial accords; see Tyler (1938), Wadman (1939), Hargreaves (1951), Williamson (1969), Summerton (1970), D'Ombrain (1974), and Kennedy (1979) for the question of military coordination. Andrew (1971) provides a strategic evaluation of the Entente Cordiale from its formation to World War I, and his study of Delcasse and the Entente (1968) remains an essential guide to Anglo-French relations in the period, as does Monger (1963) for British policy.
7.10 Balance in the alliance system
259
Germany, or forming BFR to balance AGI. It is no coincidence, then, that the BF coalition, as a precursor to BFR, becomes feasible. Indeed, it is precisely this dynamic that we identify as the reason for which both Anglo-French and Anglo-Russian colonial conflicts of interest become surmountable. Like the Entente Cordiale, the Triple Entente had its origins in a set of agreements resolving outstanding disputes that had hitherto impeded any cooperation. In this case, three agreements were signed by Great Britain and Russia on August 31, 1907 concerning, respectively, Persia, Afghanistan, and Tibet, resolving longstanding Anglo-Russian rivalry on the periphery of India.33 These agreements, while facilitating an Anglo-Russian rapprochement, did not lead to military coordination between Great Britain and Russia until 1912, despite the ongoing coordination of France separately with both Britain and Russia. Consulting Figure 7.12 again, we see that, as with the Entente Cordiale, and short of splitting Austria and Italy from Germany, Great Britain exhibits maximizing behavior in entering BFR. Indeed, the formation of BFR follows shortly after the conversion of BF and ABI to losing coalitions and precedes by only a few years the rendering of BR losing. Figures 7.8 and 7.9 show that, with the possible exception of reaffirming a coalition with Germany, Russia is likewise exhibiting maximizing behavior in entering the BFR coalition, and the same is true for France. 7.10
Balance in the alliance system
We have eight general cases over which we have examined ourfirsttwo hypotheses, and the data appear to be consistent with them. However, we have also argued that the events of the period reflect the operation of two results from our analysis: Theorem 6.3 (which specifies the necessary and sufficient condition for a country to be a unique balancer) and Remark 6.4 (which identifies the special strategic problem of a central power); now we can offer an overview of the dilemma these results posed for German decision makers in particular. Briefly, the alliances of the period are best understood by realizing that Germany (and, to a degree, Austria-Hungary) is a central power on the continent, separating two noncontiguous powers, France and Russia. To the extent that we can suppose that the resource discount between Russia and France was substantial (although not zero, as the Napoleonic invasion of Russia established), Germany was essential on the continent only if it controlled more resources than 33
See Churchill (1939) and Williams (1966) for a discussion of the Anglo-Russian accords.
260
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
either Russia or France. This, in part, accounts for the necessity of an Austro-German alliance and for Germany's perceived need for military superiority. Within this framework, the analysis of the preceding sections demonstrates that German interests were best served by a neutral Britain. However, ensuring that Germany remains essential endangers Britain's role as balancer, because (with Theorem 6.3 in mind) that role existed only insofar as the resources required to ensure German security did not threaten Britain directly. Thus, Germany was presented with the task of forming alliances and increasing its resources so as not to undermine Britain's neutral position and strategy. Schmitt (1934, pp. 91-2) nicely summarizes the dilemma that Theorem 6.3 and Remark 6.4 together posed: The British wished to limit armaments The Germans said: Situated as we are between France and Russia, we cannot discuss a limitation unless Britain will abandon the Triple Entente. To this the British replied: We cannot abandon the Entente if you continue to add to your navy, for you have the Triple Alliance. Tirpitz might have yielded on the fleet in return for a promise of unconditional neutrality. Such a promise Grey could not give... partly because British interests would not permit giving Germany a free hand to deal with France. Great Britain insisted on her naval superiority and her diplomatic combinations, which maintained the balance in her favor. To restore the balance, Germany had to retain her freedom in armaments or break up the Entente. The problem was as Bethmann said "insoluble."
Whether this task was insoluble, or merely too difficult for the likes of a Tirpitz, we cannot say. We suspect but cannot prove that the military armament policies Germany pursued after Bismarck were in fact a colossal blunder, and that - because Britain could no more tolerate a French or Russian hegemony than a German one - the extension of Bismarck's policies to the twentieth century would have done as much to ensure the survival of the German state. In any event, the outbreak of war in 1914 reveals that the task was not accomplished. Before we turn to the specific military conflicts of the period and to World War I in particular, we must consider our third hypothesis, H3, which focuses on the forces moving alliances to approximate resource parity. What concerns us here is the logic underlying the emergence of coalitions at specific points in history. Ideally, we would wish for a model that would isolate the exact moment in history when the distribution of resources over an alliance system requires its reconfiguration, but we cannot pretend that such an ideal is even remotely within our grasp. However, our model does disclose the causes of coalition formation, as well as rough time parameters within which these causes operate.
7.10 Balance in the alliance system
261
1873-93 From 1874 until well past its dissolution in 1887, the League not only provided its members with a counterthreat to any feasible threat, but it also was approximately balanced vis-a-vis any opponent and winning against opponents we might reasonably deem likely to provide a threat (notably Britain, France, and Italy alone, or Britain and Italy). Had Germany, Russia and Austria-Hungary collectively chosen to impose any resource allocation that did not simultaneously threaten British and French interests to the extent of causing a coalition between Britain and France to become feasible, our analysis suggests that they could have prevailed. Yet, it unilaterally imposed no resource allocations. Indeed, the only explicit threats of the period emerged from within it directed against other members of the alliance, and viable counters were obtained only by stepping outside the League. Still, it persevered for fourteen years. It is in analyzing this seeming contradiction that the underlying dynamics of greatpower relations in this period can be elucidated and explained in terms of the requirements of balance-of-power politics. The League of the Three Emperors emerged from the Holy Alliance of Prussia, Austria-Hungary, and Russia, formed in the aftermath of the struggle against Napoleon and revolutionary France. Although this alliance had been notably inept as a threat or counterthreat to the ambitions of other European powers (e.g., as evidenced by Prussian and AustroHungarian behavior during the Crimean War), its chief efficacy had been in suppressing revolutionary and democratic activism. In 1849, it had been Russian arms that restored the Habsburgs to their Hungarian throne.34 This concern for the stability of monarchist absolutism no doubt played a role in the League's establishment and perseverance - its enunciated purpose, "[to maintain] the peace of Europe against all subversions, from whatsoever quarter they may come," suggests this - but it seems unlikely that this alone accounts for it. Furthermore, the conflicting interests of Austria-Hungary and Russia in the Balkans emerged first in the mid18508, well before the League's founding, and the League's existence contributed virtually nothing toward a resolution of these conflicts. The question we must ask, then, is: What can account for the emergence of an offensively and defensively inept alliance that includes at least two members at permanent odds over vital interests? We begin by reviewing the threats underlying Russo-Austrian conflict in the Balkans. Russia was clearly able to prevail against Austria-Hungary 34
For the Russian role in repressing the revolutionary tide in 1848, see Rath (1957), Young (1957), Fasel (1970), Lincoln (1973), and Stearns (1974).
262
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
alone, and this drove Austria-Hungary to seek an ally. Alliance with France would likely produce a Russo-German alliance against which a FrancoAustrian alliance could not prevail. Alliance with Italy would be ineffectual even against Russia alone. Britain was unavailable, for reasons previously outlined. Thus, it was toward Germany that Austria-Hungary was propelled by the Russian threat. Although Germany and Austria could defeat Russia alone, that alliance could not defeat a Franco-Russian alliance. In the face of such a threat, Germany has three options: (1) cede resources in some form to Russia or France such as Alsace-Lorraine; (2) expand its alliance with Austria-Hungary to include Italy or Britain; or (3) obviate any Franco-Russian alliance by allying with Russia and, simultaneously, obviate a Russian defeat of Austria-Hungary by allying with Austria-Hungary. The first option almost certainly would have led to the demise of the nascent German state; coalition with Britain at this time was, at best, problematical owing to British reticence and the questionable relevance of British resources in a continental conflict; and alliance with Italy did not yield a coalition capable of overcoming FR until 1889 (see Figure 7.7). The Russian advantage in allying with Germany rested in the counter provided to any potential threat to its interests in the Near East or Southwest Asia from Britain. Thus, the League provided Germany with security against a Franco-Russian alliance, Austria with security against Russia, and Russia with security against Britain, all while Germany, in the eyes of Russia, restrained Austrian freedom of action in the Balkans and, in the eyes of Austria-Hungary, Russian freedom of action in the same region. However, this edifice was held together only by the credibility of Russia's threat of an alliance with France, and therein lies the seeds of its demise. In the Near Eastern Crisis of 1875-8, the League initially performed its function (see Section 8.1). In the Budapest conventions, Germany restrained both Russia and Austria-Hungary, guaranteeing roughly equal gains for each in the Balkans. However, Russia repeatedly sought to lever Germany with the French threat into imposing terms on Austria-Hungary more favorable to Russia and, when the Treaty of San Stefano repudiated the agreement and gave Russia virtual hegemony over Ottoman Turkey's Balkan possessions, Russia expected that the French threat would allow it to present Austria-Hungary with a fait accompli. In this case, the interests of Great Britain in preserving the independence of the Ottoman buffer state permitted Germany to obviate Russia's threat of a French alliance by an insurmountable Anglo-Austro-German coalition, which imposed the terms of the Treaty of Berlin on Russia. A similar turn of events
7.10 Balance in the alliance system
263
in the Near Eastern Crisis of 1885-8 extinguished the League's paltry life (see Section 8.2). However, the demise of the League did not diminish the underlying dynamic that sustained it. The Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty of 1887 represented continuing efforts by Germany to lessen the insecurity that accompanies a central power by obviating the French threat, and by Russia to persuade Germany to restrain Austria-Hungary. However, the Russian willingness to pose this threat, although perhaps a bluff, remained credible to Germany in light of Russia's willingness to sacrifice the League to its Balkan interests. The failure of the League to procure favorable outcomes for Russia impelled it toward more sincere overtures to France. In this situation, as our hypothesis predicts, the inadequacy of the Austro-German alliance in the face of a potential Franco-Russian alliance required both Germany and Austria-Hungary to seek alliance partners to meet this contingency. The Triple Alliance emerges from this Austro-German search for allies. Thus, the struggle to augment the resources of the central powers in the direction of parity characterizes the diplomatic maneuvering of the period, screened from view by formal agreements, but sustained by the ever-present Russian threat of alliance with France. This contention is supported by the German willingness to allow the Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty to lapse. Some have suggested that this was in fact a German blunder, but our data indicates good reasons for the German decision. Figure 7.13 graphs the resource differences between several pairs of opposing coalitions, and shows that from about 1889 onward, Germany was able to call Russia's bluff precisely because a Franco-Russian alliance was increasingly resource-inferior to the Triple Alliance. It was the resource superiority of a threatened Franco-Russian alliance to the Austro-German alliance that sustained the League and that later propelled Germany and Austria-Hungary toward Italy and the Triple Alliance to achieve resource parity. Once the Franco-Russian alliance was resourceinferior, Germany no longer needed to placate Russia: Germany could choose the second of its three options, and the search for allies was pressed upon Russia and France, not Germany and Austria-Hungary. Discarding Russia in favor of AGI, moreover, aided in ensuring Britain's neutrality, which rendered AGI Germany's most potentially profitable coalition from 1889 to 1904. If the primary antagonists of the period are AG versus FR, AGI versus FR, or AGR versus F, then there is little incentive for Britain to make the system or itself rigid with formal alliances: In all three cases, Britain can render either side winning. After about 1896, however, BF is no longer winning against AGR, and after 1907, BF is no longer winning against
264
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 AGR-BF
AG-FR
AGI-FR
AG-BFR
AG-BF
AGI-BF
-£-
AGI-BFR
Figure 7.13 Alliance differences as a percentage of total resources. AGI, so we should suppose that relations between Russia and Britain (or between Britain and some member of AGI) should change from what they were in the period 1871-96. These facts are largely in accord with Hypothesis H3. 1894-1914 From 1894 to 1907, the struggle of Russia and France for allies to overcome the resource inferiority of their alliance vis-a-vis the Triple Alliance dominates great-power relations. French financial overtures to Italy in the 1890s - albeit ineffective, particularly in light of French colonial policy in North Africa - were certainly aimed at providing incentives for Italian defection from the Triple Alliance. However, such overtures were peripheral to the real requirements of French and Russian security. Unable to offset Germany, owing to the relative stagnation of French resources and the growth of German resources, Britain became the only effective guarantor of both France and Russia. Those who argue that balance of power necessarily implies a bipolarity of approximately equally powerful alliances ought to feel uncomfortable, nevertheless, with the fact that although Britain was resource-inferior to its strongest feasible opposition from 1887 onwards (AGI, see Figure 7.10),
7.10 Balance in the alliance system
265
it was twelve years before the colonial disputes that divided Britain and France were significantly negotiated and seventeen years before the Entente Cordiale was consummated. Certainly, Britain exhibited behaviors consistent with such an hypothesis: the Naval Defence Act of 1889 and the Spencer Programme of the 1890s were obvious attempts to increase Britain's resources by domestic means.35 However, even recognizing that any operationalization of resources is too gross an instrument to predict alliance formation with temporal precision, we find the length of time between Britain's need for coalition partners and the formal consummation of such coalitions interesting. Our analysis in Chapter 6 suggests, in fact, that the Entente Cordiale and the Triple Entente find their logic in the anticipation of events, not as reactions to transpired events. To put matters simply, the growth of German resources in this period is not so great as to wholly undermine the conditions of Theorem 6.3 and Britain's role as a balancer. Certainly, British concerns increased after the commencement of Germany's naval construction program in 1897 and, again, after the increase in Germany's naval construction in 1906. Because AGI is winning only as long as Britain remains unaligned, the straightforward British calculation would be that the coalition FR and its preoccupation with AGI forestalled any Russian threat to British interests - it was, after all, Russia and France and not Britain that were directly threatened by AGI in this period - and should those interests become threatened by the Triple Alliance, Britain merely required the availability of BFR. Hence, the agreements Britain negotiated with France and then Russia need not be viewed as a move toward resource parity as much as simple insurance that, with FR unable to offset AGI (see Figure 7.13), BFR was available. Further insight into Britain's reluctance to ally formally is provided by considering the nature of both the Entente Cordiale and the Triple Entente and asking: Why did the parties involved prefer an entente to a formal alliance? As British Prime Minister H. H. Asquith (1923, p. 99) vigorously asserted, "The Entente, I repeat, was never converted into an Alliance. While working cordially with France and Russia to secure the international equilibrium, we kept ourselves free to decide, when the occasion arose, whether we should or should not go to war." However, as 35
For detailed discussions of British naval policy in this period, see Woodward (1935), Marder (1940, 1961, 1964), Grenville (1964), Graham (1965), Lowe (1967a, 1967b), Gardiner (1968), and Kennedy (1976). For contemporary, if polemical, views, see Stevens (1896) and McHardy (1897). Hallmann (1927), Michalik (1931), Kehr (1933), Von Schonberg (1933), and Steinberg (1965) provide exhaustive detail on the interaction of British and German naval policies throughout the period.
266
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914
Morley (1928, p. 17) notes, the decision not to advance from entente to alliance was not without peril: An entente was evidently something even more dangerous for us than an alliance. An alliance has definite covenants. An entente is vague, rests on point of honour, to be construed by accident and convenience. The Prime Minister and Grey had both of them assured the House of Commons that we had no engagements unknown to the country. Yet here we were confronted by engagements that were vast indeed, because indefinite and undefinable. It is important to an understanding of the structure of the international system to inquire as to the motivations that underlay this British refusal to covenant unambiguous obligations. The distinction between an entente and an alliance precisely resides in the ad hoc character of the threats and counterthreats coalitions pose. As we discussed in Chapter 5, the possibility of an offensive hegemonic alliance's emergence is likely to induce those threatened by that alliance to wage preventive war. The Entente Cordiale and Triple Entente, had they been alliances, would have met the criteria for a hegemonic alliance. Had the Triple Alliance been certain that either the Entente Cordiale or the Triple Entente had offensive intentions, a preventive war by Germany and Austria to forestall the solidification of a BFR alliance would have become considerably more likely. The ability of Britain, and to a lesser extent Russia, to convince particularly Germany that their intentions in these coalitions were defensive was predicated on the uncertainty of each country's participation in any threat originated by its coalition partners. Open, explicit alliance would have diminished this uncertainty and enhanced considerably the likelihood of war. Thus, the uncertainty that some authors suggest contributed to World War I (cf. Holsti and North 1966; Singer, Bremer, and Stuckey 1972) may in fact havfe delayed the war by more than a decade. And British concerns about such possibilities may have postponed her full response to AGI as well. In summary, Germany and Austria recruited Italy in the face of a Franco-Russian threat in a period in which British invulnerability rendered Germany vulnerable; Britain became especially involved in continental affairs when its own position eroded and the rough balance between AGI and FR disappeared; Britain resolved its disputes with France and Russia when AGI became clearly predominant over FR and threatened continental stability. What we have not satisfactorily explained yet, however, is the outbreak of World War I itself. That question we shall address in Chapter 8.
7.11 Appendix: Data used in the construction of our index
7.11
267
Appendix: Data used in the construction of our index 0
0 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 —— Austria-Hungary •
Germany
Great Britain
France
Italy
Russia
1911
Figure 7.14 Mobilization factor (MOBF).
Thousands
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887
1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911
—— Austria-Hungary
Great Britain
France
"9-
Italy
Russia
Germany
Figure 7.15 MAMP x MOBF.
268
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914 Tons (x 1000)
3500
0 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 ~^~
Austria-Hungary
Great Britain
France
-s~
Germany
Italy
Russia
Figure 7.16 Coal production (PCL).
Tons (x 1000) 350
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 ~*~
Austria-Hungary
~G~ Germany
Great Britain
France
Italy
Russia
Figure 7.17 Iron ore production (PIO).
7.11 Appendix: Data used in the construction of our index
269
Tons (x 1000) 200
150 -
100 -
1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 Austria-Hungary
Great Britain
France
Germany
Italy
Russia
Figure 7.18 Pig iron production (PPI).
200
Tons (x 1000)
150 -
100 -
0: 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 Austria-Hungary
Great Britain
France
Germany
Italy
Russia
Figure 7.19 Steel production (PSL).
270
7 Great-power alliance formation, 1871-1914 1.6 I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I 1.4
0.8 I ' • ' I ' • • I ' ' ' I • • • I • ' ' I ' ' ' I ' • • I ' ' ' I ' • ' I • • • I' 1871 1875 1879 1883 1887 1891 1895 1899 1903 1907 1911 Austria-Hungary
Great Britain
France
Germany
Italy
Russia
Figure 7.20
Force projection (FP).
CHAPTER 8
European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
Should equilibrium be attained at one point, it would immediately be wiped out by the search for slight superiority. Ernest B. Haas, "The Balance of Power: Prescription, Concept or Propaganda?" (1953, p. 450)
[A] system of flexible alliance arrangements can only maintain stability if the core powers can jointly increase their capabilities at the expense of peripheral actors. Partha Chatterjee, Arms, Alliances, and Stability (1975, p. 126)
In Chapter 7, we examined the general applicability of our model to alliance formation, concluding that European alliances between 1871 and 1914 are consistent with a calculation of coalitional value derived from the concept of system stability, and consistent as well with the respective roles of Germany and Britain as central power and balancer. However, system stability does not imply resource stability, which leaves room at a more microlevel for threats and counterthreats to be directed at achieving, if not the "slight superiority" to which Haas refers, at least some advantage. This view of instability within stability leads us to different predictions about conflict resolution than others offer. Translating his assertion into our terms, Chatterjee sees resource instability yielding system stability only if the game is not constant-sum - if members of the system can expropriate from external entities. We argue, though, that alliance flexibility allows wholly endogenous adjustments, but only if those adjustments are consistent with the requirements of such stability. We must check, then, whether we can interpret actual resource adjustments as being constrained if not dictated by system stability, and subsidiarily to see what insights we can gain about alliance formation and maintenance. We approach this issue by focusing on three cases of conflict resolution: the Near Eastern Crises of 1875-8 and 1885-8 and the July Crisis of 1914. The Near Eastern Crises highlight equilibration within systemstable systems and elucidate two patterns of conflict resolution. In the first pattern, alliances are unaffected whereas the opposite is true in the 271
272
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
second, owing, we argue, largely to the fact that the first crisis was more nearly consonant with Chatterjee's (1975) precondition of nonconstantsum conflict, whereas the second was constant-sum. Despite their differences, we discern within the events of both conflicts the operation of those constraints on action imposed in systems that are system stable. The third case, the July Crisis of 1914, permits us to examine some implications of our analysis of preventive war, which shed light on the causes of World War I. Our analysis here, then, does not embrace all explicit conflicts in the period; but the cases we select are exemplary of great-power conflict resolution throughout the period. Moreover, detailed examination of these three crises allows us to address an important and frequently overlooked issue: Why are some crises resolved without armed conflict, whereas others erupt in war? If we were to look merely at the July Crisis - if, for our data, we were to follow a research tradition that looks only at events immediately preceding a war - we would forego the warning about the ichthyologist "who examined fish collected after the seining of a lake. He arrived at the interesting conclusion that allfishliving in the lake were more than four inches long. The moral, of course, is that one must examine the seine as well as the fish..." (Adair 1987, p. 3). If our theory has general applicability, then we should be able to detect the operation of the same forces in all three crises; but we should also be able to isolate those special circumstances and, presumably, the violations of our assumptions in the last crisis resulting in war. Before proceeding, we emphasize that the international system in each of these three crises cannot be characterized merely by a description of resource distributions. As we suggested in the last section of Chapter 7, any comprehensive analysis of events must also accommodate three facts. The first fact is a growth trend that worked uniformly throughout the period to Germany's advantage (see Figure 7.1), which cannot have escaped the notice and strategic calculations of decision makers. Hence, the role that this growth trend played in all three crises, especially the last, tempers, in the manner of the analysis in Chapter 5, any static view of resources. Second, if we envision the continent as being roughly divided into two camps - Austria and Germany versus France and Russia - then Britain's unique role as balancer (Theorem 6.3) is apparent. This fact, when grafted onto the condition for system stability presented in Theorem 6.1, is essential for understanding British motives. Third, if we focus on the continent, then German strategy is dominated necessarily by consideration of its position as a central power and, hence, by the special strategic disadvantages that accompany that position (Remark 6.4). An equivalent concern motivates Austrian strategy, which emphasizes the
8.1 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1875-8
273
general relevance of geography and the results in Chapter 6 for an analysis of conflict in the period. 8.1
The Near Eastern Crisis, 1875-8
Historical overview In July 1875, the largely Slavic Christian population of Herzegovina revolted against their Ottoman Turkish overlords; they were joined by their coreligionists in Bosnia in August of the same year. These uprisings occurred for long-standing reasons of Slavic nationalism and in response to the economic and political burdens imposed by Turkish rule. However, the immediate spark was applied to the Balkan tinderbox by the Austrian Emperor Francis Joseph I in May, when he toured the bordering province of Dalmatia, proclaiming himself the protector of Ottoman Turkey's western Slavs and, despite contrary advice from his foreign minister, encouraged these Slavic populations to expect Austrian assistance. This Austrian precursor of the crisis was noted with some alarm in St. Petersburg. Despite his monarch's pretensions, the Austrian foreign minister, Andrassy, sought to dampen the Bosnian-Herzegovinan revolt with a proposal that the Austrian, German, and Russian consuls in the area mediate a settlement between the local population and the Turkish government. Mindful of the Austrian emperor's role in sparking the uprising and fearful of a German-Austrian conspiracy to establish Austrian hegemony over the Balkans, the Russian foreign minister, Gorchakov, insisted that the French be included, which forced invitations to the two remaining European powers, Britain and Italy. Italy, eager for recognition as a power, accepted. Britain, irked at not being consulted initially, accepted at the request of Turkey. In light of Russian insistence on the involvement of France, the failure of Andrassy's mediation proposal - rejected out of hand by the insurgents - was greeted with relief in Vienna and Berlin. Undaunted, Andrassy proposed a set of political and economic reforms to be imposed on Turkey by the League as a precondition of settlement. Again, Russia insisted on French participation and the Andrassy Note of December 30, despite Turkish acceptance, failed to gain the rebels' support. In a meeting in Berlin on May 11, 1876, Bismarck sought to bring Andrassy and Gorchakov to a modus vivendi. Gorchakov sought great-power intervention against Turkey; Andrassy rejected partition of the Balkans and counterproposed a set of Turkish reforms to which Gorchakov gave way, albeit with a provision that if the reforms failed, "effective measures" would be taken. France and Italy endorsed the Berlin Memorandum, but Britain, suspecting that the Russians aimed at dismemberment
274
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
of Ottoman Turkey, declined and dispatched a fleet to Besika Bay, just beyond the Dardanelles. Such a deployment, as noted in St. Petersburg, prefaced the Crimean War. To forestall the emergence of the 1854 coalition, Gorchakov invited the French to deploy a fleet in Turkish waters; the French, fearful of war with Britain, declined. The inability of Turkey to suppress the Bosnian-Herzegovinan uprising brought down the Sultan, who abdicated on May 29, 1876, as the revolt spread to Bulgaria. Sensing Turkish weakness, Serbia and Montenegro declared war on Turkey in June, coming to the assistance of the insurgents. Andrassy and Gorchakov met at Reichstadt in July to discuss the impending Turkish defeat. Their agreement specified: if Turkey were defeated, Russia would receive Bessarabia and Austria would receive Bosnia; if the Ottoman state collapsed, Istanbul would become a free city and independent or autonomous states would be carved from its Balkan possessions. However, the reports of Turkey's demise were premature, and by August, Serbia and Montenegro had been defeated by the new Turkish Sultan, Abdul-Hamid II. The Slavic uprising, however, continued. Pan-Slavic agitation within the Russian court for Russian intervention in support of the uprising eventually converted the Czar, Alexander II, to its position, despite the contrary pleading of Gorchakov, and Russia moved to neutralize Austria's opposition. A series of meetings in early 1887 culminated in the Budapest conventions with the results that Austria would be neutral in any Russo-Turkish War; Austria would be permitted to occupy Bosnia-Herzegovina; Serbia and Montenegro would be recognized by both parties as buffer states between their forces; and Russia guaranteed that "no great, compact state, Slav or other" would be created in the Balkans as a result of the war. On April 24, 1877, Russia declared war on Turkey. The British, outraged at the prospect of Turkey's defeat and dismemberment, demanded a Russian guarantee not to occupy Istanbul and a limitation of its territorial gains. Gorchakov accepted these demands, but the Czar repudiated them on June 14. The British again dispatched a fleet to Besika Bay and announced that its neutrality would not survive a Russian occupation of Istanbul and the straits. The likelihood of a British-Russian confrontation over Turkey was diminished, however, by the difficulties encountered by Russia at Plevna. The four-month siege of Plevna, eventually taken by Russia on December 11, depleted both sides, and the Russian army, pummeled by Turkish resistance to an unexpected degree, staggered to the gates of Istanbul by the end of December. Nevertheless, the Turks had exhausted their ability to resist and an armistice was concluded. The Treaty of San Stefano was signed on March 3,1878. This treaty provided that: an autonomous principality of Bulgaria - a "Greater Bulgaria," consisting
8.1 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1875-8
275
of Bulgaria proper, Macedonia, Eastern Rumelia, and part of southern Rumania - would be established under a prince selected by the Russian Czar; Turkey would cede Batum and additional territory in Asia Minor to Russia; and Turkey would pay a war indemnity to Russia while recognizing the independence of Rumania, Serbia, and Montenegro. To the Austrians, the treaty violated the Budapest conventions by ignoring the agreement to its occupation of Bosnia-Herzegovina and by creating a "Greater Bulgaria" under Russian hegemony. To the Germans, the treaty increased Russian power at the expense of Turkey and Austria, a particularly dangerous eventuality in light of Russian overtures to the traditional Germany enemy, France. To the British, the treaty placed Russia within striking distance of Istanbul and the straits through its Bulgarian surrogate. It is therefore unsurprising that these powers demanded an adjustment of terms, and this threat resulted in Russian repudiation of "Greater Bulgaria" in an Anglo-Russian agreement signed on May 30, 1878. Britain exchanged an agreement to defend Asiatic Turkey against the Russians for occupation of Cyprus in June, providing Britain with a forward base for conducting such operations. Under these circumstances, Russia accepted German offers of mediation and the Congress of Berlin, in which Austria, Germany, Britain, and Russia participated, was convened in June. Negotiations in the Congress produced an agreement marginally acceptable to all the parties: Russia received Bessarabia, lost in the Crimean War, from Rumania, as well as Batum in Asia Minor, and agreed to forego other annexations in Asia Minor granted under the Treaty of San Stefano; "Greater Bulgaria" was reduced to "Lesser Bulgaria" with the return of Macedonia and Eastern Rumelia to Turkey and the southern portion of Rumania to Rumania; the powers confirmed the British occupation of Cyprus and Britain's de facto right to transit the straits; and Austria was permitted to occupy and administer Bosnia-Herzegovina. Interpretation In the Spring of 1875, the status quo embodied a rough balance between the resources of the German-Austrian alliance and the yet unallied, but friendly Italy and the resources of a potential Russo-French alliance, and a general growth trend that continued to strengthen AGI against FR.1 This status quo, however, posed special dangers to Germany and Austria, which made them sensitive to any reversal of trends. As central powers, both were especially vulnerable to the possibility of a Franco-Russian 1
Although no treaty as yet bound Italy to Germany and Austria, both Berlin and Vienna believed that any augmentation of French power, as through an alliance with Russia, would swing Italy to their camp.
276
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
alliance. German strategy, though, could rely on British opposition to any Continental alliance that threatened British interests, and presently Russia was the more direct threat. Bismarck could strive, then, for the maintenance of the status quo with some concessions to Russia in the Balkans, which would forestall a Russo-French alliance, and reinvigorate the dormant League, all the while maintaining its alliance with Austria, which continued to be driven by the geographic position of both countries. The various diplomatic exchanges were essentially proposals to maintain this status quo, as was the British dispatch of afleetto Besika Bay in the Summer of 1876. The first Russian proposal, embodied in the Budapest conventions, essentially maintained this status quo by taking advantage of the fact that Turkish weakness rendered the game "positive-sum" from a European view in terms of the absolute level of resources. It offered an increase in Austrian resources, through permitting Austrian occupation of BosniaHerzegovina, while simultaneously increasing Russian resources, through obtaining territory from Turkey and the creation of small satellite states among the insurgent Slavs. Hence, both countries gained at Turkey's expense from this proposal in 1877, which we summarize as (10.3, 72.2, 25.0,40.0,11.2, 37.1) = (5.3%, 36.9,12.8,20.4,5.7,19.0)? From an Austro-German perspective, acquiescence to this proposal forestalled a Russo-French alliance, while differential growth rates continued to narrow the gap between AG and FR. The benefit to Russia was that Britain's position was made more difficult by obviating an Anglo-Austrian alliance that would have enabled Britain to more effectively impose demands on Russia. Russian military success against Turkey, however, led to the threat of a different outcome. With the creation of a "Greater Bulgaria" under Russian suzerainty and increased Russian-inspired pan-Slavic agitation along Austria's borders and among its Slavic subjects, Russia threatened Austria: both the free navigation of the Danube, which was essential to Austria's economy, and the demographic base from which it recruited its 2
This estimate of resource acquisitions by Austria-Hungary and Russia is based on a calculation of resource totals for Bosnia-Herzegovina and Bulgaria; the military-age, male populations of each were extrapolated for 1876 from later census data, assuming average rate of cohort growth as constant. Since both areas lacked significant infrastructure and economic development, and possessed no force-projection capability, this MAMP figure was multiplied by the minimum mobilization factor (MOBF) 0.1 to arrive at a conservative estimate of resource total. This process was repeated for each year relevant to this case and the Second Near Eastern Crisis. Recall, also, that variation in these figures, as well as the resource totals for the great powers, is largely a function of endogenous growth.
8.1 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1875-8
277
armed forces were imperiled. The immediate resource distribution implied for 1878 in the Treaty of San Stefano, (8.6,72.4,26.8,42.2,11.6,40.2) = (4.3%, 35.9,13.3,20.9,5.7,19.9),3 not only threatened Austrian interests in a way not wholly reflected in these numbers, but directly threatened the Austro-German central power alliance with the reduction of Austrian resources and increase in Russia's. Even if Italy actively supported Germany and Austria, this threat posed a danger to the central-power Austro-German alliance by reversing a trend that promised increased Austro-German security against a Franco-Russian threat (Remark 6.4). Turkey's resources were diminished by territorial losses and the indemnity imposed by the Treaty of San Stefano, and this weakening, although not immediately diminishing Britain's resources, placed it at future disadvantage with respect to its Asian possessions and threatened the role of Ottoman Turkey as a buffer against Russian expansion in Asia and the Near East. A memorandum from General Simmons to the War Office, July 26, 1878, suggests the degree to which Britain perceived its position imperiled: By obtaining possession of the Turkish provinces adjoining Persia, Russia would acquire the means of applying pressure on the whole of the northern & western frontiers of Persia which would be irresistible and render the latter power a passive if not an active ally in the extension of her influence and territory towards India By the eventual and almost certain extension of her influence and power... it would be difficult to arrest her progress to the Straits of the Dardanelles and the Bosphorus... [and] she would obtain the power of raising and provisioning armies which by the aid of conscription would become so powerful that no European power dependent upon the sea for its communications could expect to maintain an army in the field at such a distance from home sufficiently strong to resist further conquests. Syria would t h e n . . . come under the control of the Power that had obtained possession of the resources of Asia Minor and eventually the Suez Canal & Egypt might feel its influence... [I]f the progress of Russia through Asia to the Dardanelles and the Mediterranean is to be checked at all it must be before she has acquired the means of forming and maintaining larger armies The best metho d . . . is to resist all progress... [and] Britain in the event of Russia again attacking Turkey in Asia Minor would be compelled to take measures and eventually to go to war to prevent the extension of Russia on this side (PRO/FO/78/2893). 3
We estimate that closure of the Danube to Austro-Hungarian commerce would have had the effect of immediately reducing Austria-Hungary's resources to 16 percent. We base this judgment on the effects of diminution of the commodity production variables in our resource calculation by elimination of over half of Austria-Hungary's foreign trade. This estimate is conservative and, hence, the actual effects would almost certainly have been more drastic. We do not, however, argue that the results of the Treaty of San Stefano would have included closure of the Danube; rather, we argue that among these results was the emergence of a Russian capability to close the Danube and that Austria-Hungary had to take such a worst-case scenario into strategic account.
278
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
It was thus logical for Germany, Britain, and Austria to seek Russian concessions, and the emergence of such a coalition was compelling to Russia, alone or in alliance with France. Russia agreed to the Congress of Berlin, out of which emerged a counterproposal, (10.3,72.4,26.8,42.2, 11.6,37.7) = (5.1%, 36.0,13.3,21.0,5.8,18.8), which differed only marginally from the status quo ante, Austria gained Bosnia-Herzegovina and ensured free navigation of the Danube with Russia's abandonment of "Greater Bulgaria." Russia gained Bessarabia, Batum, and "Lesser Bulgaria," while conceding its other conquests in Asia Minor, the dream of a "Greater Bulgaria," and the Turkish indemnity. The British gained Cyprus and asserted its rights of passage through the Straits. The short-term gain for Austria and Russia, measured by our index, was marginal and corresponded to what was provided for in the Budapest conventions. The implication of this new resource distribution for the potential AustroItalo-German and Russo-French alliances was virtual parity, which eased German concerns. Only Turkey, unable to face down the coalition of European powers at the Congress of Berlin, sustained a net loss. This case elucidates a pattern we observe in other conflicts of the period. The crisis centered on the way in which the threat embodied in the Treaty of San Stefano repudiated trends that ensured German and Austrian security and British economic interests. The Franco-Russian alliance never materialized explicitly, but if the threats and counterthreats in the form of potential alliances are as important as the actual existence of alliances, then the significance of this aspect of the crisis is apparent and its resolution understandable. First, the general growth trend within the alliance system operating to ensure Austro-German security was maintained. Second, both Austria and Russia secured gains in the Balkans. Although the game remained zero-sum when payoffs are expressed in terms of proportion of resources controlled, it is not unreasonable to suppose that maintenance of a trend advantageous to Austria and Germany and positive absolute gains to Austria and Russia account for the acceptance of the outcome arising from the Congress of Berlin. Although Russia was dissatisfied with the failure to pressure Austria into full acquiescence, the outcome inclined it to persevere in the League in the hopes of further incremental gains, rather than repudiate the League and opt for an explicit alliance with France - an alliance Britain was certain to counter if Russia sought from it significant gains at Austria's expense. The positive gain for Austria, coupled with the growth trend of the incipient Triple Alliance, provided sufficient incentive for it to support the status quo, particularly in light of the likelihood that the alliance system might provide a brake on Russian ambitions in the Balkans.
8.2 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1885-8
8.2
279
The Near Eastern Crisis, 1885-8 Historical overview
In September 1885, Eastern Rumelia proclaimed its union with the Principality of Bulgaria, repudiating the "Lesser Bulgaria" guaranteed by the Congress of Berlin. Austria responded to this repudiation of the Balkan status quo by calling for Turkish intervention to return Eastern Rumelia to the Ottoman suzerainty. Interestingly, Russia concurred in Austria's desire for a restoration of the status quo, for the realization that a large portion of the "Greater Bulgaria" for which Russia had been prepared to go to war with Turkey in 1877 in fact represented a danger to Russian interests, in light of the refusal of Alexander of Battenberg, Bulgaria's prince, to acquiesce in Bulgaria's entry into a Russian sphere of interest. The British, fearing a joint Austrian and Russian plan to partition the Ottoman Empire and consequent loss of the buffer state for which it had been prepared to risk war in the first Near Eastern Crisis, refused to support the Austrian initiative. Failing to obtain a consensus to restore the status quo, Austria's Serbian ally4 demanded compensation for the Bulgarian unification and declared war in November when this demand was rejected. The Serbian army was routed by Bulgaria in less than two weeks. Fearing a Bulgarian march on Belgrade, the Austrian foreign minister, Kalnoky, coupled his demand for a cessation of hostilities with a secret pledge to Alexander of Battenberg to assist him in his domestic struggle against Czarist interests. Britain then mediated a temporary solution in the form of Turkish appointment of the Prince of Bulgaria as governor in perpetuity of the Ottoman province of Eastern Rumelia, effecting the unification of Bulgaria in the Prince's person, but retaining the formal distinction of Bulgaria proper and Eastern Rumelia. Both Austria and Russia accepted this formula in April 1886. Russia unilaterally repudiated the Salisbury accord in August, when Alexander of Battenberg was abducted by Bulgarian officers acting on Russian instructions. Although he was returned to the throne in September, Czar Alexander III ordered him to abdicate or face Russian military intervention. He meekly acquiesced in the demand. General Kaulbars, 4
Austria-Hungary and Serbia concluded a treaty of alliance on July 28, 1881, in which both parties pledged "to follow mutually a friendly policy" and in which they pledged "friendly neutrality" toward each other in the event of either party going to war. Under Article IV of the treaty, Austria-Hungary pledged to "use her influence with the other European Cabinets to second the interests of Serbia" and Serbia agreed to "not admit to her territory a foreign armed force, regular or irregular, even as volunteers" (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 51-3).
280
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
a serving Russian officer, was appointed regent, but Bulgaria's civilian government refused to deal with him and relations between Bulgaria and Russia were severed in November, with Russia threatening invasion. Kalnoky, determined to resist Russian hegemony over Bulgaria, appealed to Germany. Bismarck replied that the Austro-German alliance was defensive and that, if Austria desired to wage offensive war against Russia, it would be necessary to enlist the backing of Britain. Britain, while equally outraged at the Russian coup in Bulgaria, was sensitive to the problems presented by war with Russia if Germany were not committed: Russia could then threaten Persia or India, regardless of the results in the Balkans. Furthermore, British uncertainty as to French intentions weighed in Salisbury's decision. France offered to support Britain in the Balkans in exchange for British evacuation of Egypt, and the Wolff mission was dispatched to Constantinople to negotiate such an eventuality with Turkey. Germany, seeking to aid Austria without openly offending Russia and eager to increase its strength against rising French revanchisme, proposed revisions in the soon-to-expire Triple Alliance. In the face of Austrian objections to according Italy a role in the Balkans beyond its claims in Albania, the basic text of the treaty was renewed without change on February 20, 1887. However, an additional Italo-German treaty committed Italy to support the maintenance, so far as possible, of the territorial status quo in the Orient,... [and to] forestall, on the Ottoman coasts and islands in the Adriatic and Aegean Seas, any territorial modification (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 111-12) in exchange for a German pledge that if it were to happen that France should make a move to extend her occupation, or even her protectorate or her sovereignty, under any form whatsoever, in the North African territories... [and if] to safeguard her position in the Mediterranean, [Italy] should feel that she must undertake action in the said North African territories, or even have recourse to extreme measures in French territory in Europe, the state of war which would thereby ensue between Italy and France would constitute ipso facto, on the demand of Italy and at the common charge of the two Allies, the casus foederis with all the effects foreseen by Articles II and V of the aforesaid Treaty of May 20, 1882, as if such an eventuality were expressly contemplated therein... [and that] if the fortunes of any war undertaken in common against France should lead Italy to seek for territorial guarantees with respect to France for the security of the frontiers of the Kingdom and of her maritime position ... Germany will present no obstacle (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 113-15). Thus, in exchange for Italian support for the status quo in the Balkans, Germany pledged to make expansion of French domains in North Africa at Italian expense a sufficient cause for launching the Triple Alliance into war with France (and this without Austria's knowledge) and to guarantee
8.2 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1885-8
281
Italy's acquisition of France's North African empire in the aftermath of such a war, as well as the possibility of Italian recovery of Savoy and Nice from metropolitan France in the event of war. If it were designed to counter a possible Franco-Russian alliance, the German threat was meaningless without British participation, and so Germany also prompted a set of communications between Italy and Britain, which came to fruition in the first Mediterranean agreement. On February 12,1887, an Anglo-Italian accord was signed in which Austria joined on March 24. This agreement tied Britain to support Italian interests in North Africa in exchange for Italian support of the status quo in the Mediterranean, Adriatic, Aegean, and Black seas. As Taylor observes: The notes of February and March 1887 created a Triple Entente which protected British interests in Egypt, Italian interests in Tripoli, and the interest of all three at Constantinople There was a solid majority against the French in Egypt; and, except for the French, the "Crimean coalition" had been re-created at Constantinople. But it was the Crimean coalition with a difference. That had followed the outbreak of war; this was designed to prevent it. Salisbury's real concern was to improve his bargaining position with the French and perhaps even with the Russians (1954, pp. 313-14).
Thus, while Germany sought to build a coalition that could meet the Russian threat, Britain employed these German initiatives to guarantee its balancer role while pursuing its colonial self-interest. Germany assiduously sought to prevent consummation of a FrancoRussian alliance. The expiration of the League of Three Emperors in June of 1887 was not mourned by Austria and Russia in light of the continuing Bulgarian crisis, but Germany remained interested in its Russian ties, and the Reinsurance Treaty embodied this interest. However, Germany gave little to obtain much (see Chapter 7): in exchange for promising not to do what was not in its self-interest, nor to do what it had obviated by subterfuge, it defused temporarily the threat of a Franco-Russian alliance. The Wolff mission - Britain's ploy toward France through Turkey - concluded a convention governing British withdrawal from Egypt with the Turkish government in May. However, Boulangerist agitation led France to reject the convention and join the Russians in urging the Turkish sultan to void the agreement (in the form of a French threat to occupy Syria and a Russian threat to occupy Armenia), thus forestalling an AngloFrench rapprochement.5 The collapse of the British initiative could not 5
As Taylor pithily expresses it, "immediately the French repented of their success and offered to help England in negotiating a new convention" (1954, p. 314). However, the intensifying crisis in Bulgaria gave little time for negotiation of a new convention and Salisbury appeared to have what might best be called "reputational" reservations about the French government's ability to pursue a consistent policy.
282
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
have come at a worse time. On July 7, the Bulgarian national assembly elected Ferdinand of Saxe-Coburg - a Hungarian nobleman and serving Austrian officer - as their new prince. Russia threatened invasion and began massing troops along the Austrian border by late August. The crisis persisted into the winter with Austria demanding German support in a preemptive war against Russia. Bismarck refused to countenance such a plan and initiated a set of steps aimed at blocking Russia short of war. Bismarck struck at Russia's financial base. In November 1887, he promulgated the Lombardverbot, which forbad acceptance of Russian securities as collateral in German financial markets. Hitherto Germany had served as Russia's principal lender, as well as largest investor and trade partner. As Geyer notes: Until the 1880s the political relationship between Berlin and St. Petersburg was kept on an even keel, despite mutual irritation, by strong commercial and financial relations between the two countries. German portfolios contained about 2,000 million marks in Russian securities in 1885, including most of the credits for the war of 1877-8. German capital financed the construction of railways in Russia, German heavy industry was the largest supplier of industrial raw materials, equipment and technical know-how, and Germany offered the largest market for Russian exports of grain (1987, p. 150). The short-term effect of the Lombardverbot, coupled with the tariff increases of May 1885 and December 1887, was to throw the Russian economy into chaos.6 The longer-term effect was to drive the Russian Finance Ministry to the French bourse.1 Second, Germany brokered an Italian initiative, coordinated with Austria, to expand the purview of the original Mediterranean entente to the Balkans. This resulted in the second Mediterranean agreement. Italy, Austria, and Britain pledged "to be associated with Turkey in the common defense of" the Balkan status quo. More important, the signatories agreed that should the conduct of the Porte... assume the character of complicity with or connivance at any such illegal enterprise, the three Powers will consider themselves justified... to the provisional occupation by their forces, military or naval, of such points of Ottoman territory as they may agree to consider it necessary to occupy [e.g., the Straits at Constantinople] in order to secure the objects determined by previous treaties (Pribram 1920, Vol. I, pp. 126-7). 6
7
Note also that these measures coincided with a general depression of the price of cereals on international markets; the preeminent Russian hard currency export was, of course, grain. For detailed discussion of the economic aspects of the crisis, see Kashkarov (1896), Schulze-Gaevernitz (1899), Crisp (1976), and Geyer (1987). Bismarck appears to have been aware of this possible consequence and, while he found it unpalatable from the perspective of the Russo-French threat, regarded it as acceptable to deter a Russian offensive against Austria. See Kumpf-Korfes (1968), Wehler (1970), and Mueller-Link (1977).
8.2 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1885-8
283
The importance of Bismarck's success in brokering this agreement is underscored by Taylor's observation that this agreement was more nearly an alliance with a group of Great Powers than any Britain had ever made in time of peace and more formal than any agreement made with France or Russia twenty years later. Salisbury might still insist that Austria had le beau role - "y°ii lead, we follow you." In fact he had made an alliance with Austria and Italy for the defence of Bulgaria and Asia Minor The new agreement was a preliminary to a possible military action, directed solely against Russia (1954, p. 321).
Germany had maneuvered the balancer of the European alliance system into a necessary, if reluctant, reprise of its balancing role. Third, Bismarck published the text of the Austro-German Treaty of Alliance, secret since 1879, on February 3,1888, followed on February 6 with his last major speech to the Reichstag in which, while offering the Czar the sop of public support for his Bulgarian policy, he proclaimed that Germany was prepared to meet its treaty obligations to Austria, for "we Germans fear God and nothing else in the world." Russia, which had yet to repay the loans through which the war of 1877-8 was funded, was suitably intimidated. Having faced down Russia indirectly through the Mediterranean entente (and directly through his financial machinations and endorsement of the Austro-German alliance), Bismarck seconded a face-saving denouement to the crisis in supporting a Russian demand on the Ottoman sultan that he declare the election of Ferdinand of Saxe-Coburg illegal.8 The sultan complied; Russian pride was salvaged. Yet Ferdinand remained Prince of Bulgaria despite the sultan's proclamation, and Russia perceived, facesaving gestures notwithstanding, a serious strategic loss for its Balkan policy. Interpretation In September 1885, the resources of the great powers were (12.3, 80.6, 32.4, 48.3,13.4, 42.9) = (5.4%, 35.1,14.1, 21.0, 5.8,18.7). Although the League of the Three Emperors increasingly showed the attentuating consequences of the conflict between Austria and Russia in the Balkans, through it Germany sought to wedge itself between the potential alliance of Russia and France. To this extent, then, the status quo appeared little different from that which existed at the time of the first Eastern Crisis. The unification of Bulgaria and Eastern Rumelia, however, threatened to set 8
France also supported the Russian demand, albeit carefully couching it in terms of seconding Germany's support. Austria, Italy, and Britain opposed the demand, but did nothing to prevent the sultan's action, an interesting indication of the extent to which the Mediterranean entente's policy was driven by Germany.
284
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
in motion forces that could adversely and profoundly affect Austrian and hence German interests. A hostile power capable of controlling navigation of the Danube or a large Slavic nationalist state capable of rallying anti-Habsburg Slavic agitation endangered both the economic stability and integrity of the Austrian monarchy. Thus, we represent the unification of Bulgaria and Eastern Rumelia as a threat of the form (10.3,80.6, 32.4,48.3,13.4,42.9) = (4.5%, 35.4,14.2,21.2, 5.9,18.8).9 The logic of Austria's demand for restoration of the status quo is evident; Russia's reversal from its stand in the previous Near Eastern crisis results from the refusal of Bulgaria to act as an instrument of Russian policy, depriving Russia of effective use of the resources awarded it in the Congress of Berlin. The disastrous Serbian defeat, however, necessitated a revised Austrian policy. The ultimatum issued by Kalnoky threatened direct Austrian intervention if the Bulgarian army were not halted; at the same time, he secretly pledged his government's support for Alexander of Battenberg against pro-Russian elements in Bulgaria. Bulgarian acceptance of this offer obviated the implicit threat posed by the unification, insofar as it rendered Bulgaria not a hostile but rather a friendly state to Austria. The British mediation, based on its preference for maintenance of Ottoman Turkey as a buffer state and for Austrian hegemony in the Balkans in the event that Turkey could not be maintained, presented Russia with a potential Anglo-Austrian coalition against which a RussoFrench coalition was unlikely to prevail. Thus, Russia officially accepted the British proposal while secretly scheming to replace Alexander with a more compliant Bulgarian prince. Russia's subsequent unilateral repudiation of the Salisbury accord arises from Bismarck's two objectives: maintenance of his alliance with Austria and avoidance of an actual Russo-French alliance. The uncertainty produced by the pursuit of these objectives contributed to the Russian belief that Germany would not stand behind Austria over Bulgaria; it also forced Salisbury to constantly take into account the possibility that, despite Bismarck's private assurances, his at best noncommittal and at worst supportive policy in public toward Russia adumbrated a potential outcome in which Germany would jettison its secret partners for open, military support of Russia.10 9
10
We calculate that closure of the Danube to Austrian commerce would have the immediate effect of an almost 16 percent reduction in its resources, and that continuation of that closure would permanently reduce it to below 8 resource units in less than two years. Our analysis suggests the extreme unlikelihood of Germany's repudiation of its treaty with Austria in favor of Russia, for reasons suggested by Remark 6.4. Rather, we believe that German policy was really driven by its desire to balance the necessary alliance with Austria, with the objective of preventing a Russo-French alliance. However, the means by which Bismarck pursued this policy certainly appeared to Salisbury as potentially duplicitous and, after the fact, to Alexander III as positively perfidious.
8.2 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1885-8
285
The Russian-inspired kidnapping of Alexander of Battenberg, his forced abdication, the appointment of Kaulbars as regent, and the threat of Russian military occupation of Bulgaria implied the following threat to Austria: (10.5, 80.7, 35.2, 50.2,14.3,47.4) = (4.4%, 33.9,14.8,21.1,6.0,19.9), which reduced Austria's resources via the ability of a Russian-occupied Bulgaria to close the Danube to Austrian commerce, and increased Russia's resources via its control of a unified Bulgaria and from its hegemony over European Ottoman Turkey and Asia Minor. Austria responded by proposing war. Germany, hoping to avoid conflict with Russia and thus a Russo-French alliance, demurred, counting on its ability to draw Italy and, through Italy, Britain into support for the Balkan status quo (Austria's position) without antagonizing Russia. Cedric Lowe summarizes Britain's dilemma in this situation: "The danger to Salisbury was not France, or even Russia, but one or both supported by the Triple Alliance" (1967a, p. 112). Thus, while Britain had to meet the Russian threat in the Balkans and Ottoman Turkey, it had to do so while taking into account the possibility that Germany would be forced to ally with Russia against it. The sensible strategy for Britain in this instance was three-tracked: (1) seek a coalition with Italy and Austria to meet the potential Russo-French threat; (2) seek a coalition with France to meet the potential Russo-German threat; (3) seek a coalition with Italy, regardless, for its ability to help meet both threats. Strategies (1) and (3) intersected German interests in supporting Austria and thus led to German brokering of the Mediterranean entente. Bismarck pretended to be nonchalant about strategy (2), in part because he thought it unlikely to be successful. The difficulty in deterring Russian policy by these means was the belief in St. Petersburg that Germany was wavering in its commitment to Austria and could be persuaded to support Russia in exchange for repudiation of any Russian overtures to France. The Reinsurance Treaty, which explicitly promised German support for Russian policy in the Balkans, directly contributed to this belief. Thus, Russian strategists believed that Germany would control Austria (perhaps on the basis of a partitioning of the remainder of the Balkans) and that Germany and Russia together could block British countermoves. Although the Reinsurance Treaty from Bismarck's perspective merely prevented a Franco-Russian alliance, from Alexander Ill's perspective it cemented Russian and German interests in the Balkans. The consequences of German policy were brought to a head in the summer of 1887 by Austria's support for the election of Ferdinand of SaxeCoburg as Prince of Bulgaria. Russia immediately threatened invasion of both Austria and Bulgaria, and Germany could no longer stand on the sidelines. Furthermore, although the potential alliance of Britain and
286
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
France failed with the demise of the Wolff mission, France was increasingly interested in reopening such a possibility.11 Bismarck was determined to prevent such an outcome. The Lombardverbot had the immediate effect of reducing Russia's ability to wage war by at least 10 percent (indeed, the data on Russian state expenditures suggest closer to 30-35 percent); it implemented the distribution (12.9,82.0,37.3,52.5,15.9,40.2) = (5.4%, 34.1,15.5,21.8,6.6,16.7). When juxtaposed with Bismarck's publication of the Austro-German Treaty of Alliance, it had the further effect of persuading Britain that no active Russo-German alliance was likely and thus prompted Britain to join more directly in a second Mediterranean entente aimed at meeting the original Russian threat. Thus, Russia was again presented with the Austrian demand for acceptance of Ferdinand of SaxeCoburg, only now backed by the Mediterranean entente against which it could at best mount a losing Russo-French counter. Germany's support for a face-saving overture to the Ottoman sultan brought the crisis to a close. Like the Crisis of 1875-8, this second crisis can be given an interpretation consistent with the requirements of resource instability in a systemstable context. The conduct of the crisis was driven, first, by two German objectives - prevention of a Franco-Russian alliance and maintenance of the Austro-German alliance - and, second, by Britain's attempt to gain maximum strategicflexibilityin light of uncertainty about Germany's ultimate policy. Austria struggled successfully to avoid the crippling resource loss embodied in Russia's threat. Russia, on the other hand, was dealt a stinging defeat, whether judged against the gain embodied in its original threat, or against its position prior to the Lombardverbot. The outcome of the crisis, moreover, differed from its predecessor in that the alliance system witnessed a major revision. The League met its demise, while the Russo-German alliance was revealed to be a sham - the mere holdover of an earlier defense of monarchy. The Triple Alliance was materially strengthened, and the incentives for a Russo-French alliance were advanced. In this case, the situation could not accommodate the dual interests of Germany. It could not have both an Austro-German and a Russo-German alliance, and, unlike its predecessor, it yielded a direct and uncompensated loss for a principal actor, Russia. The events of the second crisis bear directly on our formal analysis. Our assumptions model a system in which nations first seek to guarantee 11
We would prefer a model-driven explanation for French rejection of the Wolff mission's convention with Turkey. Unfortunately, although such an alliance was in France's interest, domestic political variables exogenous to our model - in the form of Boulanger's rabidly nationalist following - intervened to prevent its consummation. This is, however, the only such case we can identify among the conflict-resolution events of the period.
8.2 The Near Eastern Crisis, 1885-8
287
their survival as essential actors and, second, consistent with thisfirstimperative, to maximize their resources or proportion thereof. Alliances, and the threats and counters of which they are a part, are instruments for realizing this self-interest. Both crises were occasioned by disputes over the second kind of interest - they were resource-instability-related events that nevertheless threatened system stability. In the second crisis, however, events impinged on the alliance structure when the associated reallocation threatened one or more essential actors, and the alliance system could accommodate no settlement other than (1) the elimination of an essential actor or (2) an absolute decrease in the threatening actor's resources to a level sufficient to guarantee that the threatened actor is not eliminated. System stability implies that the second outcome prevails, and indeed Germany's Lombardverbot amounted to this option, both by reducing the Russian resource level and by rendering infeasible a RussoGerman potential coalition upon which Russian planners had counted. Any other German course would result in Austria's eventual elimination, and even (for the reasons suggested in Remark 6.4) to the elimination of Bismarck's Germany as well. The difference between the two crises is that in 1878 Germany could broker an agreement meeting Russia's demands without threatening Austria, whereas in 1888 it could not. The corollary is Russia's decision to abandon maneuvering within the system - to abandon pressuring Germany to pressure Austria for concessions in favor of an alliance with France to guarantee that Russian interests would be no further sacrificed to those of Austria in the Balkans. In this way, the unspoken threat of a RussoFrench alliance, which drove the alliance system prior to 1888, soon thereafter became a fact. In short, then, the second crisis restructured alliances so that they were more nearly consistent with the geopolitical roles of countries: Austria and Germany together as central powers; France and Russia as the peripheral threats to the center; and Britain as balancer (in this case, in favor of the weaker Austro-German coalition). In thefirstcrisis, no such change was necessitated by system stability. The "availability" of the European remnants of the Ottoman Empire rendered the first case nonconstantsum, whereas, as long as Britain regarded any further incursion a threat to its empire, the second was constant-sum. In the first case, then, the existing alliance system - ostensibly designed to ensure the essentiality of at least Germany, Austria, and Russia and to refrain from infringing on British interests - served its purpose by proving itself irrelevant. In the second case, however, exogenous events (the "turn" of Greater Bulgaria) precipitated a crisis that the existing alliance system (the League) could not resolve. To grant concessions to Austria while "buying off" Russia
288
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
with further gains (the Dardenelles and more) would lead to war with Britain, if not with Britain and France allied. However, Germany and Austria could secure their objectives in coalition with Italy by swinging Britain temporarily to their side. Correspondingly, a new alliance system arose, not necessarily with the conscious purpose of maintaining stability, but system stability was nonetheless its product. Chatterjee's (1975) observation captures part of the truth: alliance flexibility fosters stability; but the qualification we add is that suchflexibilitycan ensure system stability without peripheral actors from whom to expropriate. There remains one unanswered question. If Remark 6.4 and Theorem 6.3 are indeed compelling in these instances, why did Russia (or at least the Czar) believe it possible that Bismarck could abandon Austria? As a central power, Germany must either augment its resources to exceed those of Russia and France, taken individually - which requires alliance with Austria - or it must blunt the Russian threat with a secure RussoGerman alliance. Between these two alternatives, Germany has but one logical choice: the first, since the second yields a direct confrontation with Britain, France, and Austria. The answer to our question, then, seems to lie in the historical basis for the League's existence: three nations joined by a common fear of revolt against their monarchies. With the uncertainties inherent in judging the relative salience of issues, the Czar might suppose that this concern transcended other matters (as it almost certainly did for him) and that the League could endure; but Bismarck's actions were consistent with an appreciation of the requirements for Germany's survival as a sovereign entity, and this dictated a course that led away from Russia to Austria and Britain. 8.3
The July Crisis of 1914 Historical overview
On June 28, 1914, a Bosnian political activist with connections to officers of the Serbian intelligence service assassinated Archduke Francis Ferdinand, the heir to the Austrian throne, and his wife in Sarajevo.12 The Austrian government was almost immediately divided between a faction that regarded the assassination as a fitting pretext for the subjugation of Serbia and the assertion of Austrian hegemony over the Balkans, and a 12
Gavrilo Princip, the assassin, and his five coconspirators received the weapons for the attack from the Serbian military arsenal at Kragujevac, from agents of Ujedinjenje Hi Smrt (Union or Death), a clandestine Serbian political organization, headed by Colonel Dimitrijevic, the chief of Serbian military intelligence. See Remak (1959) and also Dedijer (1967).
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
289
faction that regarded the pressing of demands on Belgrade as likely to involve Austria in a war with Serbia's Russian ally.13 The Austrian Chief of Staff, Baron Conrad, proposed immediate mobilization of the armed forces against Serbia to force an end to perceived Serbian encouragement of Slavic dissident groups within the empire. Fear of the Russian reaction and opposition within the cabinet, as well as conflicting signals from Berlin,14 led Foreign Minister Berchtold to propose seeking German guarantees of support for Austrian policy against the Serbs in the event of Russian opposition. Count Hoyos was dispatched to Berlin with a letter from Francis Joseph to Wilhelm II. Ambassador Szoegyeny presented the letter to the Kaiser on the following day at lunch and received a virtual "blank check" from Wilhelm; Szoegyeny's cable to the Foreign Ministry conveyed a message welcome to the hardliners in Vienna; "inform our gracious Majesty that we might in this case, as in all others, rely upon Germany's full support" (Bittner et al. 1930, doc. 10058). It is almost certain that the Kaiser did not envision himself as committing Germany to war with the Triple Entente; in meetings with senior military and political officials later in the afternoon of July 5 and on the morning of July 6, he repeatedly asserted that war with Russia or France over Austria's demands on Serbia was unlikely given the lack of readiness in St. Petersburg and 13
14
The "war party" consisted of Chief of the General Staff Baron Conrad, Austrian Prime Minister Stuergkh, War Minister von Krobatin, Count Hoyos, Count Forgaech, Count Bilinski, and Baron Macchio; the "peace party" consisted of Hungarian Prime Minister Tisza and a few junior ministers. Foreign Minister Berchtold sought to mediate between the two parties, but sympathized with the war party. On June 30, the German ambassador to Austria advised against any precipitous action against Serbia, and Zimmerman, the acting head of the German Foreign Office, suggested to the Austrian ambassador in Berlin on July 4 that Vienna should exercise a prudent caution in dealing with Serbia, particularly in not making humiliating demands on Belgrade. Conversely, on July 1, Victor Naumann, a confidante of the Bavarian Prime Minister, confided to Count Hoyos that the Kaiser and the German military were prepared to completely support Austria-Hungary, regardless of her policy. Several factors contributed to this German ambivalence. First, German and Austrian interests had grown apart since the early years of the century; this increasing distance in interests contributed materially to the German decisions during the Bosnian annexation crisis (19089) and the First and Second Balkan Wars (1912-13) to restrain Austrian policy and work with other powers, most notably Britain, to mediate disputes. Several German Foreign Office officials anticipated continuation of this policy. Second, officials in the Chancellor's office were worried that a failure to support Austria in this instance, coupled with a failure to support it's initiatives in 1908-9 and 1912-13, would lead to Austrian repudiation of the Dual Alliance; indeed, Bethmann-Hollweg complained to his staff, "in that case, they will draw close to the Western powers, whose arms are open, and we will lose our last powerful ally" (quoted in Remak 1967, p. 107). Although this was not the principal factor in Germany's decisions, it certainly played a role. Finally, the internal structure of German decision making, limited to a small, extraconstitutional group around the Kaiser, lent itself to the proliferation of speculation on state policy in the absence of the Kaiser's expression of preference over an issue.
290
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
Paris. As Remak argues, "The Emperor apparently thought that the Austrians would now proceed to act without further delay, and that, given the merits of their case against Serbia and Russia's relative unreadiness for war, whatever fighting there might be would be confined to Austria and Serbia" (1967, p. 106). On July 6, the Kaiser departed for Kiel to begin a three-week vacation cruise off Norway, hardly the act of a man who has decided to thrust the world into war.15 German policy toward the crisis from July 6 until July 24 consisted, on the one hand, of urging quick action on Austria and, on the other hand, seeking to localize the conflict to Austria and Serbia. Among the reasons for urging quick action, three seem paramount. First, it would present the Triple Entente with a fait accompli against which their protestations but not military action could be expected. Second, it would limit the extent to which the Triple Entente could coordinate its diplomatic response before the fact. Third, a proposal from the Turkish War Minister, Enver Pasha, on behalf of his government for a military alliance with Germany was forwarded by the German ambassador in Constantinople on July 22. Such an alliance had been mooted earlier in the month and presented Germany with the opportunity to reverse the considerable danger of a Turkish rapprochement with Russia.16 Quick Austrian action against Serbia and its consequences for Austrian hegemony in the Balkans could only reinforce Ottoman Turkey's resolve to ally with Germany and Austria.17 Reinforced by the German commitment, the hard-line faction of the Austrian cabinet pressed for the presentation of an ultimatum to Serbia. Tisza's opposition at the July 7 Ministerial Council prevented adoption of a proposed text, although by July 14 the Hungarian Prime Minister had yielded to pressure and agreed to a preliminary text, the details of which were approved by the Ministerial Council on July 19. The Austrian cabinet agreed to delay presentation of the ultimatum to Serbia until 15
16
17
A similar inference might be made from the failure until July of Chief of the General Staff von Moltke to end his "cure" at Carlsbad (begun on June 28), and of Navy Minister von Tirpitz to return from his holiday in the Schwartzwald. Whereas the Austrians sent officers on leave during the crisis to allay speculation of its intentions, such was not the case for Germany, as suggested by the Kaiser's notation on a cable from Tschirschky in Vienna that this Austrian stratagem was "childish." Such a rapprochement was almost consummated in May during the Czar's holiday at Livadia, when only Sazonov's refusal to believe that Talaat Pasha, the Turkish Interior Minister and confidante of the Grand Vizier, was authorized to conduct such negotiations prevented Pasha's discussions with the Czar (Weber 1970, pp. 47-54). Indeed, such an alliance promised Germany control of the Straits and the ability, as we shall see, to blackmail Russia into submission to any German demands by denying it the ability to export commodities from its Black Sea ports.
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
291
the departure of French President Poincare from his state visit to Russia on the evening of July 23 to impede Russo-French coordination in the event of Russian support for Serbia.18 In what remains as one of the unique documents of unsubtle diplomatic correspondence, the ultimatum demanded that [Serbia]... publish the following declaration on the first page of its official pressorgan ...: "[Serbia] condemns the propaganda directed against Austria, that is the entirety of the ambitions, whose ultimate aim is to disjoin parts of the territory belonging to the Austrian Monarchy [Serbia] regrets that Serbian officers and officials have taken part in the propaganda above-mentioned and thereby imperilled the friendly and neighborly relations, which [Serbia]... had solemnly promised to cultivate in its declaration of 31 March 1909. [Serbia].. .which condemns and rejects every thought and every attempt to interfere in behalf of the inhabitants of any part of Austria, considers it a duty... that it will in future use great severity against such persons, as will be found guilty of similar doings, which [Serbia] ...will make every effort to suppress [Serbia].. .will overmore pledge itself to the following: To suppress every publication likely to inspire hatred and contempt against the Monarchy or whose general tendencies are directed against the integrity of the latter; To begin immediately dissolving the society called Narodna Odbrana; to seize all its means of propaganda and to act in the same way against all the societies and associations in Serbia, which are busy with the propaganda against Austria;... To eliminate without delay from public instruction everything that serves or might serve the propaganda against Austria, both where teachers or books are concerned; To remove from military service and from the administration all officers and officials who are guilty of having taken part in the propaganda against Austria, whose names and the proofs of whose guilt [Austria] will communicate to [Serbia]; To consent that [Austrian]... officials assist in Serbia in the suppressing of the subversive movement directed against the territorial integrity of the Monarchy; To have a judicial enquiry instituted against all those who took part in the plot of 28 June, if they are to be found on Serbian territory; ... To arrest [those]... compromised by the results of the enquiry; To take effective measures so as to prevent the Serbian authorities from taking part in the smuggling of weapons and explosives across the frontier; to dismiss from service and severely punish those organs of the frontier service... who helped the perpetrators of the crime of Sarajevo to reach Bosnia in safety; To give [Austria]... an explanation of the unjustified remarks of high Serbian functionaries in Serbia as well as in foreign countries, who... did not hesitate to speak in hostile terms of Austria in interviews given just after the event of 28 June; To inform [Austria]... without delay that the measures summed up in the above points have been carried out (Bittner et al. 1930, doc. 10395). A Serbian reply was demanded within forty-eight hours, and the Austrian minister in Belgrade was instructed to sever diplomatic relations in 18
When the German Foreign Office advised Vienna that Poincare would not be leaving until 11, rather than 10 p.m. as originally planned, the Austrian ambassador in Belgrade was instructed to delay his presentation of the ultimatum by an hour.
292
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
the event of any response other than unconditional acceptance of the demands. Serbia, in the midst of an internal political crisis, was unable initially to respond. When Prime Minister Pasic returned to Belgrade in the early hours of July 24, he importuned the Prince Regent to telegraph a personal appeal to the Russian Czar for assistance. The Austrian ultimatum and the Serbian appeal galvanized the Russian government into action. Although Russian Foreign Minister Sazonov had been apprised of reports that Austria was preparing for action against Serbia, assurances to the contrary by the Austrian foreign ministry had prepared him for a peaceful settlement of the crisis. His reaction to the ultimatum was described in the Foreign Ministry's official diary: "Towards 10 a.m. S. D. Sazonov arrived from Tsarskoe Selo, when Baron Schilling immediately communicated the above-mentioned information [the Austrian ultimatum] to him, which created a very strong impression upon the Minister, who at once exclaimed: 'C'est la guerre europeene'" (Hoetzsch 1931, pp. 5, 25). Sazonov conferred with British and French ambassadors about the ultimatum in the early afternoon of July 24, at which meeting he received advice from Paleologue to take a tough stance against Germany and Austria. Indeed, the more cautious British ambassador reported to Foreign Secretary Grey that "[f]rom the French Ambassador's language it almost looked as if France and Russia were determined to make a strong stand even if we declined to join them" (Gooch and Temperley 1926, Vol. I, p. 101). At 3:00 p.m., the Russian Council of Ministers met to discuss responses to the Austrian ultimatum. Sazonov posed the problem for his fellow ministers not in terms of the Austrian ultimatum, but rather in terms of the threat of German hegemony over the Balkans and the Near East, which an Austrian success in Serbia foreshadowed and for which the ultimatum constituted one of a set of "systematic preparations, which were calculated to increase her power in Central Europe in order to enable her to carry out her wishes, not only as regards matters in the Near East, but in all international questions, without taking into consideration the opinion and influence of the powers not included in the Triple Alliance" (quoted in Lieven 1983, p. 141).19 Indeed, Sazonov argued, failure to stand firm in support of Serbia and, thus, against German hegemony would mean the eventual demise of Russia as a great power. While he counseled firmness, 19
Our discussion of the July 24 Council of Minister's meeting is based on the unpublished memoirs of Finance Minister P. A. Bark; they are particularly remarkable for the extensive detail with which they recount the minister's conversations, suggesting that Bark may well have had access to official minutes of the meeting. The Bark Manuscript is held by the Bakhmetev Archive of Columbia University.
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
293
he also recognized that such a stand would likely lead to war with Germany and Austria. However, he insisted that the remaining members of the Triple Entente must also be persuaded to join in that stand and, thus, if Serbia should be invaded, the Serbians should be counseled to fall back in the face of superior force and appeal to the powers for assistance, thus inducing Britain in particular to support Serbia. Sazonov's argument was seconded by the Agriculture Minister, Krivoshein, who insisted that concession would only endanger "Russia's vital interests," whilefirmopposition might deter Germany (which he also saw as the author of the crisis) from its course, even if such firmness might lead to war. Sukhomlinov, Grigorovich, and Bark, ministers for defense, the navy, and finance (respectively) spoke in support of Sazonov's position. The Council of Ministers forwarded to the Czar its resolutions: [T]he Foreign Minister... should make contact with the Cabinets of the Great Powers in an effort to persuade the Austrian Government to grant Serbia a temporary postponement of her reply to the ultimative demands set by the Austrian Government in order to give the Governments of the Great Powers the opportunity to inspect and study the documents on the crime committed in Sarajevo To endorse the proposal of the Foreign Minister that the Serbian Government should be advised that, in the event of Serbia's position being such that she is not strong enough to defend herself unaided against a possible Austrian attack, it should offer no resistance to armed invasion of Serbian territory, if such attack of this kind were to take place. Rather should it declare that Serbia would yield to superior force and entrust her fate to the judgment of the Great Powers. To charge the War and Naval Ministers... with the task of entreating [your]... assent... to a proclamation of mobilization of the four military districts of Kiev, Odessa, Moscow and Kazan, and of the Baltic and Black Sea Fleets, should the subsequent course of events so require. To charge the War Minister without delay to speed up the stockpiling of war materials for the army. To charge the Finance Minister to make measures for the immediate reduction of sums belonging to the Finance Department at present deposited in Germany and Austria (Hoetzsch 1931, pp. 5, 19).
Accompanying the Council's resolutions, Sazonov forwarded a report to the Czar in which he stated the reason for opposition to the Austrian ultimatum: "The demands posited by Austria in Belgrade bear no relation either in form or content to those omissions for which a measure of blame might possibly be imputed to the Serbian Government The clear aim of this procedure - which is apparently supported by Germany - is the total annihilation of Serbia and disturbance of the political equilibrium in the Balkans" (Hoetzsch 1931, pp. 5, 47). The implication of the Council's resolutions were spelled out by Sazonov in a meeting with Buchanan the following morning: "Russia cannot allow Austria to crush Serbia and become [the] predominant Power in the Balkans, and, secure of support
294
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
of France, she will face all the risks of war (Gooch and Temperley 1926, p. 125). On July 25, the Czar chaired a meeting of the Council of Ministers at which this implication was reinforced by his approval of the Council's decision "from 26 July of this year to enforce throughout the entire Empire the order for the period preparatory to war..." (Hoetzsch 1931, pp. 5, 42). Yanushkevich, the Chief of the General Staff, briefing officers on their tasks in light of the decree, went further still, instructing them to begin preparations directly related to mobilization that went beyond the decree's scope. Reinforced by Sazonov's assurance of Russian support, given to Serbia's ambassador on the evening of July 24, the Belgrade government ordered general mobilization, while responding to Austria its willingness to accept all those portions of the ultimatum that did not involve the operation of Austrian officials on Serbian territory. The Austrian ambassador, following his government's instructions, rejected the Serbian reply and severed diplomatic relations. Austria's ambassador in Berlin reported even as relations were being severed that "here the general belief is, that if Serbia gives an unsatisfactory answer our declaration of war and war operations will follow immediately. Here every delay in the beginning of war operations is regarded as signifying the danger, that foreign powers might interfere. We are urgently advised to proceed without delay and to place the world before a fait accompli" (Bittner et al. 1930, doc. 10656). In such circumstances, Conrad issued the order for mobilization to begin on July 28. German support of Austria now focused on attempting to localize the conflict, while mediating between Vienna and St. Petersburg. At Germany's suggestion, the Austrian Foreign Office publicly repudiated any territorial claims. At the same time, Germany sought to neutralize Britain and France if Russia could not be persuaded to stand aside on the Serbian question. As the Russian decree of the period preparatory to war went into effect, Sazonov appeared reassured by Austria's insistence that Serbian rejection of the ultimatum would not immediately result in war and the German ambassador's intimation that Austria might reduce its demands. Despite these signals that the firm stand might deter the Central Powers, the Russian foreign minister seemed troubled by a cable from the Russian ambassador to Turkey, who reported the likelihood - based on reports of an impending Turko-German alliance - that both Turkey and the Balkan states would fall under German hegemony, "resulting] in the total destruction of our prestige and of our position in the Near East" (Krasniy Arkhiv, USSR, 1933, vol. 5, pp. 168-70). The Austrian declaration of war on Serbia on July 28 and the shelling of Belgrade the following day
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
295
stripped Sazonov of his illusions. The Austrian declaration persuaded the Czar to order the mobilization of the Odessa, Kiev, Moscow, and Kazan Districts. However, as Danilov (the Quartermaster-General) insisted, partial mobilization would disastrously imperil Russia's ability to wage war. Lieven summarizes these difficulties: A major problem about partial mobilization was that Russian regiments did not draw their reserves from a single military district. This was largely the result of the multi-racial nature of the Empire. The government wished Poles to serve in Asia and Caucasians in Europe. A rule existed that units should be three-quarters Slav and, if possible, one-half Great Russian, which, together with the need to distribute evenly scarce skilled cadres often living in a very few urban centres, ensured that units drew their recruits from a wide area Many reservists from the Moscow and Kazan districts went to units deployed against Germany. Either these reservists must be sent to the Austrian front or remain milling about at the mobilisation centres. Meanwhile of course the Kiev and Odessa districts drew some of their reservists and relied on the concentration of their front of units from outside the four mobilised regions. If for instance the Guards Corps, situated in the Petersburg military district and recruited from the entire Empire, was neither to be mobilised nor to be deployed in the Kiev district then a large gap would immediately exist on the Russian south-western frontier. Finally, the Warsaw military district, which faced both Germany and Austria, was both the key to military operations and the area whose railways had to carry much the greatest number of troop trains. Delay or confusion here would not merely cripple Russia's planned offensives but also might render impossible an effective response to the Austrian main attack northwards from Galicia, of whose details the Russian General Staff was well aware (1983, pp. 149-50). Sazonov joined in persuading the Czar on July 29 to order full mobilization, despite the German ambassador's conveyance of a curt message from Berlin: "further continuation of Russian mobilization would force us to mobilize, and in that case a European war could scarcely be prevented" (Schuecking and Montgelas 1919, Vol. I, p. 342).20 However, almost as soon as the order was issued, the Czar rescinded it and reverted to partial mobilization following a conciliatory cable from Wilhelm II. The Kaiser's appeal to the Czar stemmed, in part, from the failure of German efforts to neutralize France and Britain; Germany seemed willing to step back from the precipice and counseled Austria to halt its army at Belgrade. Sazonov, however, would not be deterred. The events of the next day reveal the roles of key Russian decision makers, and the account of the Foreign Ministry's official diary is worth examining at length: Between 9 and 10 a.m. the Minister for Foreign Affairs spoke to the Minister for Agriculture by telephone. Both of them were greatly disturbed at the stoppage of 20
It seems likely that Sazonov was influenced by the reinforcement his ambassador in Sofia, A. A. Savinsky, gave to Giers' insistence that German hegemony in the Balkans and Turkey was imminent.
296
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
the general mobilization Sazonov advised A. V. Krivoshein to beg an audience of the Czar in order to represent to His Majesty the dangers called forth by the change General Yanushkevich requested the Minister that in the event of his succeeding in persuading the Czar he would telephone him to that effect from Peterhof, in order that he might immediately take the necessary steps "After that," said Yanushkevich, "I shall go away, smash my telephone and generally adopt measures which will prevent anyone from finding me for the purpose of giving contrary orders which would again stop our general mobilization."... Meanwhile A. V. Krivoshein informed S. D. Sazonov that in reply to his request that the Czar would receive him he was told that His Majesty was so extremely occupied today that he could not see him. Krivoshein then expressed a desire to see S. D. Sazonov before the latter went to Peterhof Krivoshein expressed the hope that S. D. Sazonov would succeed him persuading the Czar, as otherwise, to use his own words, we should be marching towards a certain catastrophe During the course of nearly an hour the Minister [Sazonov] attempted to show that war was becoming inevitable The firm desire of the Czar to avoid war at all costs, the horrors of which filled him with repulsion, led His Majesty in his full realization of the heavy responsibility which he took upon himself in this fateful hour to explore every possible means for averting the approaching danger Finally the Czar agreed that under the existing circumstances it would be very dangerous not to make timely preparations for what was apparently an inevitable war, and therefore gave his decision in favor of an immediate general mobilization. Sazonov requested the Imperial permission to inform the Chief of the General Staff of this immediately by telephone, and this being granted, he hastened to the telephone on the ground floor of the palace. Having transmitted the Imperial order to General Yanuschkevich, who was waiting impatiently for it, the Minister, with reference to the conversation that morning added, "Now you can smash your telephone" (Hoetzsch 1931, pp. 5, 284).
The Russian decision to proceed with general mobilization forced Germany and Austria to a decision. From the German perspective, "Here he [the Kaiser] had been trying to mediate, and what had the Russians done but use his efforts as a cover for obtaining a five days' start in military preparations" (Remak 1967, p. 118). Indeed, [t]he Germans, when they heard the news, were close to panic. Earlier that day, July 30, when he had heard of Russia's partial mobilization, the Kaiser's first anguished comment had been, "That means I have got to mobilize as well." The situation now was infinitely worse. The Russians were moving against them, the Germans, not just against the Austrians. And what would France do but support her Eastern ally? Here it was, the old nightmare of a two-front war, and it was real. There was only one possibility, the Germans had long thought, of winning such a war. It lay in offsetting the overwhelming advantage in men and material that France and Russia held with speed. If they, the Germans, were to move quickly against France and to defeat them in a matter of at most six weeks, they might then be able to rush their troops to the east just before the Russians had fully brought their forces into position. To allow the Russians to proceed with their general mobilization and thereby let Germany's only chance of victory slip away seemed intolerable (Remak 1967, pp. 124-5).
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
297
Austria proclaimed general mobilization effective from July 31. Also on July 31, the German government proclaimed the Kriegsgefahr - the "state of imminent war" - which necessarily preceded mobilization, and dispatched an ultimatum to St. Petersburg: In spite of the still pending negotiations for mediation and although we ourselves have up to the present hour taken no mobilization measures of any kind, Russia has mobilized her entire army and navy, thus against us also. For the security of the Empire, we have been compelled by these Russian measures, to declare a state of threatening danger of war, which does not yet mean mobilization. Mobilization must follow, however, in case Russia does not suspend every war measure against Austria and ourselves within twelve hours and make us a distinct declaration to that effect (Schuecking and Montgelas 1919, Vol. I, p. 490).
The German proclamation of general mobilization and declaration of war followed the next day. We have, thus far, concentrated on the actions of Austria, Germany, and Russia, in large part because it was they who drove events until the German declaration of war. However, before recounting the course of events resulting from the German declaration of war, in which both France and Britain play major roles, it is useful to review their activities up to the German declaration. As Keiger (1983) argues, for the French government, as well as for the French public at large, until the Austrian ultimatum, the crisis occurred not in the Balkans, but in a French courtroom, where the fate of the Poincare government hung in the balance as the wife of its former Finance Minister, Caillaux, stood trial for murder (pp. 139-40, 145-50). In fact, "in France during the first three weeks of July the subjects dealt with in diplomatic correspondence were by and large the same as before 28 June. Indeed, compilers of the collection of French Diplomatic Documents decided to advance the ending of their work to 23 July precisely because the assassination [of Ferdinand] did not have the effect on French politics which has so often been attributed to it" (pp. 146-7). Although growing indications of the likelihood of Austrian demands against Serbia were a topic of discussion during the visit of Poincare and Prime Minister Viviani to Russia from July 20 to July 23 (as Poincare's diaries attest), and though Poincare's encounter with Szapary, the Austrian ambassador to St. Petersburg, included a cautionary reminder of Serbia's friendship with Russia and Russia's alliance with France,21 there is no indication of the Russo-French "conspiracy" to launch a revanchist 21
This cautionary reminder was prefaced by some considerable ambivalence over just how important the impending crisis might be. Poincare's remark, as reported by Remak (1967), was: "With a little good will, this Serbian business is easy to settle. But it can just as easily become acute. Serbia has some very warm friends in the Russian people. And Russia has an ally, France" (p. 112).
298
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
war against Germany, which was popularized by some historians and journalists in the early 1920s.22 Poincare and Viviani almost certainly went no further in dealing with the Balkans crisis than is suggested in the remarks of Sazonov and Paleologue to Buchanan, reported to Grey in a cable on July 24: Minister for Foreign Affairs and French Ambassador told me confidentially that [the] result of [Poincare's visit]... had been to establish the following points: Perfect community of views on the various problems with which the Powers are confronted as regards the maintenance of general peace and balance of power in Europe, most especially in the East; Decision to take action at Vienna with a view to prevention of a demand for explanations or any summons equivalent to an intervention in the internal affairs of Serbia which the latter would be justified in regarding as an attack on her sovereignty and independence; Solemn affirmation of obligations imposed by the alliance of the two countries (Gooch and Temperley 1926, Vol. I, p. 101).
The Austrian strategy of waiting for the French delegation's departure before delivering the ultimatum to Serbia appears to have precluded serious coordination between the French and Russian heads of state. When the delegation, at sea, learned of the ultimatum, the response was restrained. Viviani radioed the French embassy in St. Petersburg to cable the Foreign Office in Paris instructions to advise Serbia to accept as many Austrian demands as possible, to seek extension of the ultimatum's deadline by twenty-four hours, and to propose an international inquest into the assassination in place of the one demanded in the ultimatum. The French Foreign Ministry took this as a cue to vacillate. Indeed, until Poincare's return to France on July 29, the French government could give few definitive answers to any foreign enquiries. The Russian military attache, alarmed by the vacillation, was moved to ask of the Chief of Staff, JofFre, whether France would honor its commitments by mobilizing in the event of a German mobilization against Russia. While Paleologue was insistent in his assurances to Sazonov that France would support Russia, a similar note was not sounded in Paris until Poincare's and Viviani's return. Even then, as Paris was apprised of the German threat to mobilize, Viviani cabled his ambassador in St. Petersburg to impress on Sazonov that "in taking any precautionary measures of defense which Russia thinks must go on, she should not immediately take any step which may offer to Germany a pretext for a total or partial mobilization" (France 1936, Vol. XI, p. 305). 22
It seems more unlikely still that Poincare and Viviani should have conspired with the Russian government to launch a war of aggression and then wait until four days later, leisurely sailing the Baltic, to decide to cancel their state visits to Denmark and Norway and return to France.
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
299
France was especially uneasy about the absence of clear assurance from Britain that it would honor the understandings France regarded as implicit in the Triple Entente, that it would come to the defense of France in war. Only the German declaration of war on Russia on August 1 prompted French general mobilization. The response of the Asquith government in Britain to the events of the crisis was, if anything, more hesitant than that of France. The Liberal cabinet was split between the Imperial Liberals - Asquith, Grey, Churchill, and Haldane - and a faction opposed to entanglement with continental powers - Morley, Burns, Lloyd George, and Harcourt - with a pacifically inclined majority formally aligned with neither faction. Certainly there was support within the Foreign Office for a more belligerent stand by the first group. As early as 1907, Sir Eyre Crowe, Senior Clerk in the Foreign Office, predicted an eventual clash between British interests and German aspirations. Indeed, as Crowe argued, above and beyond the argument of impending German hegemony: It is clear that France and Russia are decided to accept the challenge thrown out to them. Whatever we may think of the merits of the Austrian charges against Serbia, France and Russia consider that these are the pretexts, and that the bigger cause of Triple Alliance versus Triple Entente is definitely engaged Should the war come, and England stands aside, one of two things must happen: (a) Either Germany and Austria win, crush France, and humiliate Russia. With the French fleet gone, Germany in occupation of the Channel, with the willing or unwilling co-operation of Holland and Belgium, what will be the position of a friendless England? (b) Or France and Russia win. What would then be their attitude towards England? What about India and the Mediterranean? Our interests are tied up with those of France and Russia in this struggle, which is not for the possession of Serbia, but one between Germany aiming at a political dictatorship in Europe and the Powers who desire to retain individual freedom (Gooch and Temperley 1926, p. 101).
Under-Secretary of State Nicholson shared similar views and Churchill and Haldane became their most avid advocates in the Cabinet. Anti-interventionist sentiment was equally strong within the Liberal Party itself and it was believed in the Cabinet that public opinion would not tolerate British participation in a European war over Serbia. Much of Foreign Secretary Grey's maneuvering was dictated by this split within the government. Second, until Germany's rejection on July 27 of his proposal for mediation of the Serbian crisis, Grey had been hopeful of enlisting Germany into the role it had played in the Bosnian annexation and Balkan War crises and had downplayed the significance of the current crisis. Indeed, it was not until after the Austrian ultimatum, on July 24, that Grey raised the issue for discussion. It was only after the July 29 overture by Germany
300
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
to procure British neutrality in the event of war with France and Russia that Grey became convinced that a Continental war was inevitable. This conviction came to Grey as the realization dawned in Paris of the precarious position in which France would be placed if war came with Germany as a result of its alliance commitments to Russia and Britain adopted neutrality in that conflict. France had concentrated its fleet in the Mediterranean in accordance with the interpretation it had given to the joint naval agreements of 1912, leaving its Channel coast open to German threat. While it is not certain that even the British naval negotiators who had participated in the 1912 agreements intended to commit to defense of the French coast, the arguments were compelling. Asquith summarized his and a majority of the Cabinet's - position in the light of this development: We have no obligation of any kind either to France or Russia to give them military or naval help. The dispatch of the Expeditionary force to help France at this moment is out of the question & wd serve no object. We mustn't forget the ties created by our long-standing & intimate friendship with France. It is against British interests that France shd be wiped out as a Great Power. We cannot allow Germany to use the Channel as a hostile base. We have obligation to Belgium to prevent her being utilised & absorbed by Germany (quoted in Hazlehurst 1971, p. 96). It was in this obligation to Belgium that a device for circumventing public trepidation at and, more important, anti-interventionist Cabinet opposition to, Britain's involvement in a Continental war was found. Belgium was Britain's casus belli as a result of German plans for a twofront war. The Schlieffen Plan and its modifications called for a German sweep through Belgium to encircle the French army within forty days, thereby freeing the bulk of the German army for commitment against Russia in the east as Russian mobilization was concluding. Britain had been a chief guarantor of the 1839 treaty ensuring Belgian neutrality. The German ultimatum to Belgium on August 2, followed by its invasion on August 4, provided the prowar faction of the Cabinet with a pretext for war. Despite his membership in the opposing faction, Morley's account of Belgium's role in British deliberations is supported by the evidence: "the precipitate and peremptory blaze about Belgium was due less to indignation at the violation of a Treaty than to natural perception of the pleas that it would furnish for intervention on behalf of France, for expeditionary force, and all the rest of it. Belgium was to take the place that had been taken before, as pleas for war, by Morocco and Agadir" (1928, p. 14). The Cabinet issued an ultimatum to Germany to respect Belgian neutrality; but Grey withheld its dispatch until German troops crossed the Belgian frontier on August 4. With the expiration of the ultimatum's deadline at 11:00 p.m., the war's participant list was essentially complete.
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
301
Interpretation The central question that confronts us is: Why did this, but not earlier crises, result in war? Before seeking an answer, though, we should first dispense with one hypothesis - that the war was a preventive war launched by Germany against the Triple Entente - the Fischer (1961, 1964, 1977) thesis. Fischer elaborates upon the argument first put forward by Albertini (1952-7), placing primary responsibility on Germany for instigating the war. The argument, briefly stated, suggests that Germany's decline relative to the Triple Entente, particularly Russia, forced German policy makers to seek to establish continental hegemony before the growing strength of the Entente would obviate that possibility.23 As a result of this situation, Germany pressured Austria into war with Serbia so as to ignite a general European war in which the central powers could serially vanquish the Entente. Although we cannot dispute Germany's aggressive actions and military buildup, there are problems with this hypothesis. If preventive wars are instigated by a declining power in anticipation of its being overtaken by another, then our resource index (indeed, the trends of nearly any index) suggests that this view is untenable on grounds similar to those put forward by Taylor in his argument that "in fact, peace must have brought Germany the mastery of Europe within a few years" (1954, p. 528). Projecting resource growth, based on average growth for the period 1910-14, the resources of the Triple Alliance exceed those of the Triple Entente by 1918; the resources of the Austro-German alliance exceed those of the Triple Entente by 1921 and of the Triple Entente plus Italy by 1923; German resources exceed those of the Triple Entente by 1923 and of the Triple Entente plus Italy by 1925. Even if we accept the imprecision of our index and speculate about the implications of geography, it is difficult to see how any preventive war hypothesis that posits Germany as a threatened power in relative decline can be sustained.24 Indeed, the first difference, then, between this crisis and the two crises we 23 24
For a comprehensive review of the literature that is generally sympathetic to the Fischer hypothesis, see Levy (1988). For a critical discussion of the Fischer thesis, see Ritter (1962a, 1962b) and Zechlin (1964); for a summary of the Fischer-Ritter debate, see Epstein (1966) and Mommsen (1966). The numerical case for German decline relative t o Russia is offered in Doran and Parsons (1980). Unfortunately, their logistics analysis, based on a suspect "theory" of cycles, does not factor out the effects of war, World War I in particular. If, on the other hand, we examine their data from 1871 t o 1914, we see the same general pattern as in our resource index: declining resources for Austria, Britain, France, and Italy; a stagnant Russia; and, with the exception of some data points that deviate inexplicably from the trend at the end of the period, the growth of Germany.
302
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
reviewed earlier is that Germany possessed or was about to possess the strategic advantage. Despite Germany's objective strategic advantage - disclosed by our resources index - it is possible to argue that German policy makers failed to perceive this advantage and subjectively believed that their nation would soon become increasingly resource-inferior to the Entente. Thus, Germany might be thought to have launched a preventive war as a result of misperception of strategic asymmetries. Certainly there is documentary evidence that some German planners, particularly in the military, grossly overestimated Russian capabilities. However, equally strong documentary evidence points to relatively realistic estimations of Russian and Entente strength on the part of civilian policy makers, particularly in the Foreign Ministry and around the Chancellor, Bethmann-Hollweg. While we find stronger evidence for Russian instigation of a preventive war against Germany, we do not reject the argument about German overestimation of Russian capability. Instead, as will become clearer shortly, we see an intersection of Russian interest in preventing German continental hegemony (and the reduction of Russia to a second-class power) with German interest in preempting the Entente for grand tactical advantage, once it became clear that the result of Russian mobilization meant war. Thus, the evidence Fischer cites regarding German perceptions of a Russian threat becomes sound grounds for accepting German interest in preempting the Entente in the actual deployment of troops into battle once war seemed inevitable, rather than German interest in launching a preventive war. That Germany did place considerable pressure on Austria-Hungary to deal with Serbia militarily is unquestionable. However, the argument that Germany did so with full recognition - or at least anticipation - that such a course would ignite a general European war seems unfounded. Indeed, careful examination of the diplomatic correspondence suggests that German policy makers believed that expeditious Austro-Hungarian action would successfully localize the conflict, presenting the Entente with a. fait accompli. Szoegyeny's cable to Berchtold makes this clear: I should like to remark that here [Berlin] the general belief is, that if Serbia gives an unsatisfactory answer our declaration of war and [sic] war operations will follow immediately. Here every delay in the beginning of war operations is regarded as signifying the danger, that foreign powers might interfere. We are urgently advised to proceed without delay and to place the world before a fait accompli (Geiss 1967, p. 201).
Our analysis suggests that the German objective was to gain hegemony in the Balkans and Turkey - and, thus, to gain an impregnable position from which to threaten Russia with elimination from the ranks of the great powers - without a general, Continental war. Thus, our rejection of
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
303
that part of the Fischer hypothesis that interprets the war as a preventive rather than preemptive one launched by Germany is driven by the existence of a plausible alternative consistent with our analysis, and by the extent to which our explanation accords more closely with the documentary record and the trends our resource index reveals. Now, the particular decisions leading to war, upon which our analysis should focus, are (1) German support for Austrian policy toward Serbia; (2) Austrian willingness to threaten Russia by threatening Serbia; (3) Russian willingness to mobilize despite the knowledge that such a decision would lead to war with Germany; (4) German willingness to go to war in the face of Russian mobilization; and (5) the British decision to enter the war. The conclusions we draw point to World War I as a preventive war instigated by Russia, but anticipated by a German preemptive attack. Germany's culpability for the war consisted of an overzealous attempt to ensure against its vulnerability as a central power in a constant-sum resource-allocation game being played by the European powers - the same game that had been played since 1871, but now absent Bismarck's diplomatic skill. An externality of this German attempt to evade systemic constraints was to threaten Russia's continuation as a great power; it was this dynamic from which the war emerged. Chapter Five modeled nations as maximizing resource growth, subject to the constraint that investment not render them uniquely vulnerable in the current period. Although these objectives are not necessarily contradictory, they had increasingly become so in the circumstance in which Germany found itself in the first two decades prior to the war. Germany's relative growth would guarantee, ceteris paribus, if not its eventual predominance, then at least a Continental hegemony; but maintenance of this growth was an artifact of an investment strategy that jeopardized its current share of resources in any period and thus jeopardized its ability to meet threats from the Triple Entente - threats that it perceived as the natural consequence of its geographically central position. The only alternative was to evade these constraints. The German race for colonial possessions from the 1880s is symptomatic of this attempt, and equally important was its attempt to obtain control of Ottoman Turkey's resources by economic assistance and concessionary arrangements. Austrian motives are equally important. As we indicated earlier, the Austro-German alliance was driven largely by the mutual necessity for these central powers to secure resources exceeding those of contiguous powers (Remark 6.4) - France and Russia. For Austria in particular, the need to subjugate the Serbian threat was driven by its general insecurity vis-a-vis Russia. It is interesting to speculate, nevertheless, about the danger to Austria of German growth - the likelihood that Germany would
304
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
no longer require Austria to ensure its sovereignty. Indeed, Austria itself might be threatened by a more powerful German state in that, by being the smallest of the great powers, it faced the danger of becoming uniquely inessential. Dissolution of the Dual Alliance and coalition with Britain and its allies offered Austria no greater guarantee - if anything, dissolution of the alliance would move Britain and Germany together to block Austrian ambitions. German fears of a simultaneous two-front war against France and Russia, aided by Britain, reveals a perception that Germany did not yet have resources sufficient to achieve a complete hegemony, but it was nevertheless prudent for Austria to augment its own resources in the Balkans while it was still in Germany's interests to support such a policy. Austria's desire to subjugate the perceived Serbian threat to its multiethnic empire in the aftermath of the assassination in Sarajevo provided Germany with an opportunity to continue its strategy of augmenting the resources of the center. If Austria were to render Serbia effectively a satellite state, Austrian hegemony in the Balkans would be guaranteed. The resources of the Balkan states would fall under Austrian control and thus be added to those of the Triple Alliance and, by implication, to Germany. Also, Austrian hegemony in the Balkans would provide a powerful incentive for Turkey to carry forward its proposed alliance with Germany and Austria. It is this "scavenging" of resources that lies at the basis of Germany's encouragement of Austria's hard line toward Serbia. This hypothesis is consistent with the documentary evidence that Germany had no intentions of igniting a general European war; however, its policy of supporting Austria had great impact on Russia. In examining the impact of German policy on Russia, we begin with an explanation of Russia's willingness to mobilize despite the certainty that mobilization meant war with Germany. What, in fact, were the consequences for Russia of German control of the Balkans and Ottoman Turkey? Coupled with the German fleet's control over exit from the Baltic, these German gains would provide a virtual stranglehold over Russian exports and imports. Approximately 95 percent of Russian exports and 98 percent of Russian imports passed through the ports of the Black or Baltic seas. An average of 45 percent of Russian export income derived from grain (averaged over the period 1905-13); 98 percent of this grain departed Russia from the Black Sea ports and passed through the Dardanelles. Also, an average of 26 percent of Russian nongrain export income came from exports to Germany (see Table 8.1). Thus, if Germany's Balkan and Turkish objectives were realized, Germany could, at will, threaten to deprive Russia of not less than two-thirds of its export earnings.
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
305
Table 8.1. Income from all grain and from nongrain exports to Germany as a percentage of Russian export income Year
Grain
Other
Total
1905 1906 1907 1908 1909 1910 1911 1912 1913
52.75 43.10 40.90 38.03 52.50 51.50 46.47 36.30 39.11
22.13 29.95 29.46 27.83 21.33 21.78 26.04 30.26 26.92
74.88 73.05 70.36 65.86 73.83 73.28 72.51 66.56 66.03
Sources: Bontwesch (1975, pp. 282, 289), Khromov (1950, pp. 474, 486-93), and Zuckerman (1915, Tables I and II).
The Russian economy, moreover, was especially sensitive to variation in export earnings and capital-intensive imports.25 Between 1905 and 1913, an average of 9.5 percent of Russian state expenditures consisted of interest, dividend, and principal payments on outstanding foreign debt, and an additional average of 20 percent of state expenditures consisted of militaryrelated outlays (see Table 8.2). All debt-related, and approximately half of the military-related, expenditures required hard foreign currencies. We can gain some sense, moreover, of the probable results of such a decline in export earnings and capital-intensive imports for the Russian economy by noting what did occur as a result of the German blockade of the Baltic and the Straits in the War. On average between 1914 and 1917, Russian coal production was reduced by 45 percent, iron ore by 60 percent, pig iron by 32 percent, and steel by 39 percent. Russian rail capacity was reduced by over half as a result of the lack of imported spare parts for locomotives and rolling stock. The Czarist government managed to avoid default on its foreign indebtedness only by generous refinancing and subsidies from its allies. In terms of our resource index, the consequence was reduction of Russia's resources by 60 percent and of its growth rate by 25
For a contemporary British estimate of Russian sensitivity to variation in grain export earnings and the importance of the Straits to Russian export capacity, see P R O / F O / 371/2094/69-70.
306
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
Table 8.2. Debt and military-related expenditures as a percentage of Russian state expenditures Year
Debt*
Military6
Total
1905 1906 1907 1908 1909 1910 1911 1912 1913
8.28 9.00 10.13 10.23 10.12 10.44 9.60 8.71 8.50
33.49 30.32 17.60 15.86 13.76 13.78 16.76 19.05 16.74
41.77 39.32 27.73 26.09 23.88 24.22 26.36 27.76 25.24
a
Includes interest, dividends, and principal payments on state credit and railway debts. b Includes Ministries of War and the Navy and the Extraordinary Expenses Account. Sources: Khromov (1950, pp. 524-9) and Gatrell (1986).
68 percent. Under such conditions, Russia would verge on loss of its greatpower status.26 On the face of it, Austro-German hegemony over the Balkans and Ottoman Turkey, coupled with German naval strength in the Baltic, presented an extraordinary threat to Russia's survival as a great power. And although we cannot say that Russia was strictly threatened with becoming inessential, it is likely that the Russian regime perceived its survival as being threatened. Certainly, the documentary evidence suggests as much. Russian attention had been drawn to Germany's influence in Ottoman Turkey by the Liman von Sanders mission early in 1914. Russian intelligence possessed German documents disclosing Germany's intention to seize the Straits in the event of the Ottoman Empire's collapse and Turkey's agreement to modernize the shore batteries at Constantinople and to give command of these installations to German officers.27 Furthermore, 26
27
Indeed, this is precisely what happened from 1917 until the early 1930s. While it is possible t o argue that the economic consequences of the German blockade did not alone cause the revolution and the devastation that followed, it is incontrovertible that it contributed mightily to it. For Russian intelligence reports on these documents, see Krasniy Arkhiv, USSR, 1934, vol. 62, pp. 91-3.
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
307
Sazonov received reports from his mission in Constantinople of the impending German-Turkish alliance and, from his embassy in Sofia, of the consequences of Austrian subjugation of Serbia for the Balkan states. Sazonov himself, both in his remarks to the Council of Ministers on July 24 and his report to the Czar, justified Russian intransigence in the face of the Austrian ultimatum to Serbia precisely in terms of the threat that potential German hegemony in the Balkans and Turkey posed to Russia's survival as a great power. That a coalition of the foreign minister, the ministers of agriculture, finance, war, and the navy, and the chief of the general staff - that is, of those officials whose duties most intimately familiarized them with the economic and military consequences of German hegemony in the Balkans and Ottoman Turkey - should be the chief advocate of Russian opposition to such hegemony, even at the price of war, is simply not accidental. This construal of the evidence explains Krivoshein's frantic calls to Sazonov when the Czar rescinded the mobilization order on July 29 and Sazonov's relieved dictum to Yanushkevich when the order for mobilization had been finally reinstated on July 30: "Now you can smash your telephone." War was a sacrifice to be embraced if the alternative was the demise of the regime or of the state itself as a great power. The second distinguishing characteristic of this crisis, then, is that it threatened a great power not merely with a reduction of resources or of growth, but for the first time (with the continuing exception of Austria) threatened its removal from great-power status as well as the survival of its regime. Events suggest moreover that the threat to Russia that began the war was no chimera; the Czarist regime was swept away and Russia's status as a great power stripped from it for more than ten years. Russia's actions are thus consistent with the hypothesis that, threatened with becoming inessential, it sought a preventive war as its counterthreat - or a German preemptive attack that would force the issue before Germany achieved hegemony. However, before we can argue such an hypothesis, we must confront three questions. First, given the fact that Germany declared war on Russia, how can we say that Russia in fact launched it? Second, why were there no alternatives available to Russia, short of war? Finally, why did France and Britain join Russia? The Russian decision to mobilize was taken with the full recognition that it would prompt German countermobilization and that German war plans made war the automatic consequence. The much-discussed pressure of "timetables" was real in Berlin, given the necessity, if war broke out, of fighting a two-front war. The need to defeat France within forty days and then shift forces to face Russia meant that failure to declare war immediately after a Russian announcement of mobilization would only reduce the time available in which to defeat France and turn to face the
308
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
mobilized Russian army. Russian mobilization made war inevitable and Russian planners knew it. Second, given the uncertain obligations imposed by the Triple Alliance and, indeed, the explicit text of the RussoFrench Alliance, Russia could count on the support of France and Britain only if they were called to Russia's defense after a German declaration of war. This accounts for Russia's adopting a strategy of provoking Germany into the first declaration by taking steps that Russia knew made the declaration inevitable. That the sensitivity of the Liberal government to public opinion made Britain hesitate, even with the German declaration on Russia, suggests the wisdom of Russian strategy. What, then, of options? In particular, what of the coalitional countermoves Theorem 5.3 presumes are feasible for averting conflict? Given German near-predominance, and referring to our discussion of Theorem 5.3, the only alternative to war is the extraction of resources from the Austro-German alliance or the imposition of a permanent brake on German growth. Implementation of either possibility, however, required a reversal of a German policy that had nourished the nation since its inception - a policy dictated by its geographic position. Even if German planners ignored the uncertainties associated with estimating military capabilities, reversal of this policy was almost certainly domestically untenable. Indeed, we can speculate that, as a result of its long-term commitment to securing resources as a function of its special strategic vulnerability as a central power, Germany policy evolved to one that sought not merely to maximize its proportion of resources but also to maximize the absolute level of those resources - in which case, by Remark 5.8, the European system had been transformed into an unstable one. These German motives rendered coalitional countermoves untenable. German alliance with Russia could not, for reasons we described earlier, provide Germany with any permanent guarantee of security; and German alliance with France remained infeasible. Despite this, Germany thought for a moment (particularly on July 30) to pull back from the brink; but, having reconsidered, pushed forward. How do we explain this? Our resource calculations - which are evidently paralleled by German intelligence estimates - suggest the reason. If Germany made good on its threat to reduce Russian resources by blockade, gaining thereby the resources of the Balkan states and Ottoman Turkey, then Germany could be confident (if Italy shouldered its obligations) that the Triple Alliance would prevail and that, given luck with the vagaries of war and German confidence in its martial proficiency, the Austro-German alliance would prevail as well. Thus, the risk of continental war was one that Germany might well shoulder.
8.3 The July Crisis of 1914
309
The French decision to join Russia was, of course, trivialized by German strategy; but even prior to the attack, France had few options but to ensure the solidarity of its alliance with Russia. Britain's decision to enter the war was a logical extension of the balancer role it had played throughout the period, but with one profound difference. Without British participation, the Russo-French alliance was doomed, regardless of Italy's ultimate decision. Even without the reduction of Russian resources threatened by Austro-German policy in the Balkans, the Russo-French alliance was unsustainable. Without Britain, the Triple Entente was dead and Germany was predominant on the continent. Belgian neutrality provided the pretext that international power politics required. And given the stalemate that ensured, it is evident that Britain "balanced" just in time. With any further delay in the war's outbreak, the addition of British resources to those of France and Russia would not have achieved even a stalemate, owing to Germany's relative growth. Thus, the third distinguishing characteristic of this crisis is that Britain's role as balancer had eroded to the point of it being able to ensure only stalemate for one side; and with further delay, even that role would disappear. We can attribute the outbreak of war, then, to (1) German resource growth, which threatened a Continental hegemony; (2) the Austrian need for resources to maintain its position as an essential component of the German alliance; (3) the threat to Russian sovereignty implied by these first two factors; and (4) the undermining of Britain's ability to play the role of balancer owing to German growth. Taken together, the sole alternative to war was a coalitional adjustment that imposed a decrease on Austro-German resources and growth - such as a transfer of Balkan sovereignty to Russia - which would have required dissolution of the AustroGerman alliance and which was not to be preferred by Germany or Austria to war. Germany, then, first among the European powers as a result of the strategic imperatives of its position, confronted Russia with the necessity of formulating a counterthreat in the form of its mobilization, which, to no one's surprise, Germany anticipated with a preemptive strike. The stalemate that followed suggests that both sides to the dispute could reasonably anticipate a 50-50 chance of success. The consequences to Russia, France, and Britain of acceding to German policy was a German continental hegemony and an inessential Russia. The consequences to Germany and Austria of accommodating their opponents was a decrease in resources and growth, both of which fundamentally threatened the security of their states and regimes. Thus, as events reveal, even odds was an acceptable bet to both sides. Nevertheless, if we prefer to say that some miscalculation or judgmental error led to war (aside from the failure to
310
8 European conflict resolution, 1875-1914
anticipate the defensive advantages of a soldier sitting in a trench armed with a machine gun), we must look to events preceding the July crisis in particular, to the failure of the Triple Entente to impose a resource reallocation on Germany and Austria before the Dual Alliance was positioned to secure a stalemate. Just as the American Civil War accomplished an end to slavery that normal politics could not secure, World War I secured a (temporary) resource adjustment (and, its extension, World War II, a permanent one vis-a-vis Germany's status as a great power) otherwise unattainable through negotiation and diplomacy. To this view of World War I as a preventive war instigated by Russia in light of the Austro-German threat, we must add an important qualification. Given the objective insecurity of Austria, we might argue that Austria forced the issue, preemptive of its own demise owing to its economic and political stagnation relative to the remaining powers. Indeed, the trends leading to the July crisis explicitly threatened two countries: Russia via its decline relative to Germany, and Austria via its decline relative to all the powers. Hence, whose actions we prefer to label the provoking preventive move is somewhat arbitrary. We might prefer focusing on Russia since its actions were directed explicitly against the rising power, Germany; on the other hand, we cannot exclude the view that Austria sought to provoke a conflict between Germany and Russia before its regime met a fate that, in retrospect, seems inevitable. The games within games that nations play in a world in which countries can anticipate the actions of others, and in which devious calculations can escape notice, make distinctions between preventive and preemptive moves theoretically meaningless. What is important is that coalitional countermoves were unavailable for implementing the resource adjustments required to maintain system stability.
CHAPTER 9
Summary and conclusions
9.1
Balance of power reconsidered
Much of what we say in this volume agrees with scholarly intuition about international stability, instability, and the nature of the balance of power. In particular, the idea that the pursuit of narrowly defined national interests can occasion a form of stability that ensures national sovereignty in anarchic systems has been shown to possess both theoretical and empirical foundation. These basic correspondences, however, between our analysis and the intuition the literature offers should not be surprising. We have endeavored to match our assumptions as closely as possible to what others before us identify as the building blocks of a theory of anarchic international systems. Indeed, our analysis matches in its most basic assumption what Waltz (1988, p. 616) cites as the critical component of neorealism: "Because power is a possibly useful means, sensible statesmen try to have an appropriate amount of it. In crucial situations, however, the ultimate concern of states is not for power but for security." To this outline we have added some formalism and game-theoretic reasoning borrowed from the theory of cooperative games, so if we have done our job well then our conclusions should strike a chord of recognition and understanding. Because we have deliberately sought to uncover the circumstances in which stability emerges in anarchic systems populated by states pursuing a singular objective, our analysis stands forthrightly in the realist tradition, and it should be unsurprising that much of what we have done here parallels the thinking of those whose appreciation of world politics was shaped by such scholars as Claude, Morgenthau, and Taylor. Correspondingly, a significant portion of our contribution to the study of the balance of power has been to develop what was already present within this tradition, albeit only dimly seen, imprecisely formulated, and frequently attended by contradictory conclusions. However, by formalizing the realist intuition with explicit definitions and assumptions, we are able to resolve several disputes, revise some of that intuition, and (presumably) bring new ambiguities to light. Most importantly, the conclusion, drawn from earlier game-theoretic arguments, that multipolar anarchic systems are inherently unstable can 311
312
9 Summary and conclusions
be traced to a confusion between instabilities that threaten sovereignty and instabilities that seem universally to characterize international affairs but concern only the constant jockeying for relative advantage among states whose sovereignty is assured. This second type of instability, resource instability, is dangerous, since the processes by which nations negotiate and seek advantage entail the implicit or explicit use of threats, which, if not handled skillfully, can lead to war. Nevertheless, although international systems may be inherently resource unstable (Theorems 4.1 and 4.2) and dangerous, they are not inherently system unstable (Theorems 3.1 and 3.2). This conclusion holds true, moreover, regardless of war's costs, provided that national leaders are concerned with maximizing their countries' relative as against absolute resources. Thus, although he refers only to eighteenth-century Europe and although it is more an empirical generalization than a theoretical one, we can echo Rosecrance's (1963, p. 30) comment that "[t]he balance of power mechanism [does] not prevent military contests, but it [does] prevent them from getting out of hand." To this conclusion, though, we must add several qualifications. First, if resources grow and if countries are flexible in their ability to allocate their resources between current capabilities and investing for future capabilities, the presumed preconditions for preventive wars are readily satisfied (Theorem 5.2 and Remarks 5.3 and 5.4). Such wars, however, are not inevitable if leaders can negotiate beforehand (Theorem 5.3) and implement resource adjustments, without domestic politics constraining agreements that might be reached. Nevertheless, stability in such circumstances is predicated on decision makers appreciating the benefits of a form of collective security that allow some countries to render themselves vulnerable in the short run (viz., the definition of security value employed in Chapter 5). Also, stability becomes much more tenuous if decision makers fail to perceive fully the imperatives for survival and, accordingly, if they maximize the absolute magnitude of resources at their disposal in an environment of expanding national resources without due consideration given to the resources controlled by other powers. Although we do not provide a general analysis, the result (Remark 5.8) that four-country systems in an environment of resource growth are inherently system unstable demonstrates the significant difference between systems in which decision makers maximize relative versus absolute resources. At a minimum, this result points to the necessity for a careful specification of goals when forming conclusions about international stability. Our analysis also reveals the profound role of geography, since, in systems with noncontiguous adversaries, it alone can preclude the possibility of system stability (Theorem 6.1 and Remark 6.2). Geography, moreover,
9.1 Balance of power reconsidered
313
gives rise to two important general types of countries: balancers (Theorem 6.3) and central powers (Remark 6.4), each with a critical and distinctive role in maintaining system stability in international affairs. Balancers can fulfill their role only if they possess a leadership that perceives the benefit of forming no permanent alliance, and if they are capable of discarding the view that one side or the other is morally superior or ideologically objectionable. By fulfilling this role, balancers can reap the greatest rewards from the status quo (Remark 6.3). The especially difficult role is that of the central power, which, in order to ensure system stability and its viability in that system, may have to maintain a military capability exceeding that of each of its contiguous adversaries (Remark 6.4). We saw how Germany, in response to this fact, upset Britain's role as balancer, threatened the security of the Triple Entente, and thereby precipitated World War I. In fact, we argue that much of the tension and conflict that existed in Europe between 1871 and 1914 can be attributed to two contradictory German aims: increasing its resources so as to remain essential on the Continent, but not increasing those resources to such an extent that its military capabilities threatened Britain. Bismarck successfully navigated this difficult path (albeit with a weaker Germany), but his successors proved less adept at the task. Although we accord Bismarck's skills with due credit, we are inclined to view the failure of his successors as less a product of deficient leadership than the inherent intractability of Germany's problem as a central power. To this broadly drawn picture, we can add some details that relate directly to the balance-of-power literature. First, with the exception of twocountry systems, system stability pervades under a wide range of resource distributions. Hence, if we equate system instability with conflict and stability with peace (which is not an implication of our model, but rather an implicit assumption made by others), those empirical analyses that posit or otherwise test the hypothesis that inequitable distributions or equitable distributions yield a greater probability of conflict should find no relationship. Second, aside from the implications of Remark 5.8, our analysis finds no simple relationship between the number of countries in a system and the likelihood with which that system is system stable. If large systems are more or less stable than small systems, they must be that way for reasons exogenous to our analysis. A third and related conclusion is that wefindlittle reason to suppose that systems necessarily tend toward bipolarity. With eyes focused on U.S.-Soviet relations or on thefinalmoves of great-power politics in Europe, bipolarity might seem inevitable, but such a focus ignores, for example, the Warring States period of China in which seven "players," over a period of 200 years, aligned themselves in virtually every conceivable combination. We disagree, then, with Waltz's
314
9 Summary and conclusions
(1979, p. 163) assertion that "[s]ystems of three have distinctive and unfortunate characteristics [in particular] Two of the powers can easily gang up on the third, divide the spoils, and drive the system back to bipolarity." Such an assertion neglects to consider the tenuous relationship between those who might so coalesce, and the countermoves by the third. And although the resource instability that is likely to be a pervasive feature of anarchic systems generates obvious incentives for the formation of minimal winning coalitions (assuming that conflict is costless or that countries maximize relative resources), the same instability implies that no coalition is permanent, and that international affairs should be characterized by a constant shifting of alliances as different coalitions form or whose formations are threatened in order to secure advantages for one or more of their members.1 A phenomenon that fails to find reflection in our analysis is bandwagoning - the hypothesis that weaker states attach themselves to an already winning coalition or alliance (Waltz 1979, p. 126; Walt 1987). The motives on the part of inessential or small states for seeking such alliances are evident; what is more difficult to discern is the incentive for larger states and winning coalitions to accommodate them. Indeed, if we take as our cue those studies of Congressional coalition formation that attempt to explain larger than minimal winning and, in particular, universalistic coalitions on redistributive legislation (see, e.g., Weingast 1979; Niou and Ordeshook 1985), we must conclude that no such incentive is possible, barring the uncertainties inherent in an accurate accounting of resources and the corresponding uncertainties associated with the determination of winning coalitions, and barring an inability to predict which coalitions will form to force redistributions in a perennially resource-unstable environment. That is, if states are uncertain that they will be included in a dominant coalition, then they may prefer to form larger coalitions in order to reduce risk. Our analysis does not consider such uncertainty, so bandwagoning does not occur in it; however, if uncertainty is the cause of such behavior, then we see it not as an alternative to balance-of-power processes, but merely as a phenomenon that arises in a more general model. 1
We must be careful, however, in our interpretation of this conclusion and in the empirical inferences we draw from it. Our analysis says very little about the actual processes whereby coalitions form and dissolve; and, in particular, it says nothing about the actual timing of events. Hence, although we predict that, in resource-unstable systems, no coalition minimal winning or otherwise - is stable in the sense that it cannot be upset by some other winning coalition, the pace of international affairs and diplomacy may be such that even unstable alliances can persist for lengthy periods. Although a Triple Alliance, a Triple Entente, or a coalition of the United States, Western Europe, and Japan may be unstable, our analysis does not say whether that coalition ought to dissolve in four or forty years. Instead, all we can offer is the prediction that there will be forces, constantly operating on such alliances, which threaten some alternative configuration.
9.1 Balance of power reconsidered
315
With respect to war and its costs, if we preclude the extreme form of costs threatened by nuclear weapons (namely, the elimination of the system in its entirety), then we find that so long as countries maximize relative resources, such costs make systems neither more nor less system stable. On the other hand, if decision makers maximize the absolute level of resources, then such costs can render otherwise inessential countries essential and vice versa. This finding, then, draws our attention to the necessity for securing a more comprehensive understanding of goals and of their determinants. Finally, our analysis in Chapters 7 and 8 is germane to two frequently stated assertions about war. Thefirstis that lesser countries "drag" major powers into conflict. The second is that treaties in and of themselves have profound effects on stability. Both assertions are summarized by German Chancellor von Bethmann-Hollweg, who, upon the realization that Britain in 1914 would honor its commitments to Belgium, stated incredulously: "Just for a scrap of paper, Great Britain is going to make war." If anything, the Chancellor's statement underscores the potential for and importance of miscalculation and misperception, but it does not lend credence to the assertions that treaties are a cause of war and that small countries drag major powers to the precipice. Treaties reflect self-interest, and although minor powers can precipitate action in the same way as a speck of dirt can begin the formation of a snowflake or a pearl, our priors should be that such powers are dragged only in the direction of their interests. It was not only that Belgium was strategically valuable to Britain or that Britain appeared to operate with a laudable code of honor - a commodity that suffered considerable depreciation in the 1930s but also that Britain could not tolerate a hegemonic Continental power. Just as the sinking of the Maine, the invasion of Poland, the bombing of Pearl Harbor, and the Gulf of Tonkin incident each served the useful purpose of overcoming domestic resistance to policy, the German invasion of Belgium offered Britain the excuse to defend a self-interest that the mothers of men sent to die might not otherwise perceive. We cannot, with a single data point and without a comprehensive study of international conflict, assert that honor and solemnly signed documents are unimportant, but the hypothesis that simple self-interest, defined by the imperatives of balance of power and the requirements of system stability, is determinative of policy ought to be considered as well. Thus, it is not von Bethmann-Hollweg who provides the explanation for events that is consistent with our analysis, but rather Duff Cooper (quoted in Jervis 1976, p. 105): "It was not for Serbia that we fought in 1914. It was not even for Belgium We were fighting then... in order that one Great Power should not be allowed... to dominate by brutal force the continent of Europe."
316
9 Summary and conclusions
Despite the close relation, however, between our analysis and the realist view of international politics, our formalization of balance of power differs in several important respects from earlier formulations. First, rather than viewing balance of power in terms of some simple algebraic identities that relate the relative resources of explicit alliances, we assume that the underlying dynamics of the balance of power are driven also by a complex set of potential threats and counterthreats of alliance. To this extent, we concur with Walt's (1987, p. 263) conclusion that "when there is an imbalance of threat (i.e., when one state or coalition appears especially dangerous), states will form alliances or increase their internal efforts in order to reduce their vulnerability."2 To this we should add, however, that threats and counters need not be explicit, but merely understood in the minds of decision makers. Hence, for the first twenty years of the period 1871-1914, balance in the European alliance system was held intact by Russia's willingness to feign affinity for France and Germany's unwillingness to test Russia's mettle over this threat. The fact that threats and counters need not be explicitly embodied in formally signed agreements is important. It provides a theoretical framework more subtle and supple for dealing with the constant give-and-take that characterizes diplomatic history. Correspondingly, though, it makes empirical analyis more difficult, since it implies that we can understand the operation of balance of power not merely in terms of the alliances we observe, but also in terms of all feasible alliances. Second, our analysis helps disentangle the concept of war from that of the balance of power - in particular, we do not require the treatment of peace as an epiphenomenon of system stability and war as one of system instability. War can be an extension of the conflictual processes underlying the jockeying for position inherent in resource instability and, specifically, the consequence of those features of reality that create a fundamental intractability in the diplomatic give-and-take that usually characterizes resource-unstable systems. Furthermore, conflict may be a mechanism for enforcing the transfer of resources, and thus was (limited to the extent that it does not seek to eliminate sovereign entities) may be part of the process whereby system stability is maintained. This is not to say, however, that war and system stability are unrelated, but rather that other preconditions must be satisfied before system instability implies armed 2
Walt seeks to distinguish between the balance-of-power theory and the balance-of-threat theory: in the balance-of-power theory, "states will react to imbalances of power," whereas in the balance-of-threat theory, states react to imbalances of threats. Walt, though, clearly has in mind a version of the balance of power denned in terms of algebraic identities, and thus we interpret our analysis as conforming to his (by Assumption A10) or as establishing a framework in which the distinction is meaningless.
9.1 Balance of power reconsidered
317
conflict. System instability merely implies some adjustment in the definition of national boundaries and in the identity of sovereign entities. Because wars may arise in system-stable but resource-unstable systems, system instability is not a necessary condition for war. And although resource instability may be a necessary condition for conflict, there is nothing in our analysis that identifies it as a sufficient condition. Thus, in order to identify those factors that together comprise a necessary and sufficient condition requires the extension of our analysis to the consideration of topics with which our analysis fails to grapple - notably, uncertainty and imperfect information. On this score, Blainey's (1973) argument seems compelling: war and peace, as instrumentalities of the pursuit of selfinterest, must be understandable in the same theoretical terms, and that war in particular arises when two or more countries hold contradictory assessments of their capabilities. By treating war and peace as derivative concepts - as consequences and instrumentalities of the more private dynamics of national self-interest - rather than identifying them with elements of system structure, we provide hopefully a framework for analyzing the empirical conditions making war more or less likely. Our analysis, nevertheless, does identify some specific sources of system instability that may greatly increase the chances for conflict. Specifically, the dynamics of economies, technology, and domestic politics undermine the stability of systems and thereby necessitate profound resource adjustments. Preventive war is a direct consequence of equilibrium investment strategies among states and the threat that such strategies present for the emergence of a predominant, hegemonic actor or for the decline of some essential countries. Technology can change the requirements geography establishes for stability as peripheral powers become central and balancers become contiguous, and each such change, unless accompanied by a corresponding adjustment in resources, renders one or more countries inessential. And domestic politics, which turns the attention of decision makers far away from the goal of relative resource maximization to that of absolute resource maximization, can have a similarly destabilizing influence. We must also admit, however, that our analysis entails several ambiguities that preclude us from asserting that our conclusions stand without the possibility of challenge. Perhaps the most important ambiguity concerns our assumptions about bargaining, and A10 in particular. Footnote 8 in Chapter 3 offers an extensive-form model of bargaining that rationalizes A10, but we cannot fully understand how agreements are enforced, nor can we identify precisely those features of reality that might undermine this assumption's validity until we explore alternative models. Second, we remain bothered by the possibility of alternative formulations of goals (absolute versus relative resource maximization) and by the fact
318
9 Summary and conclusions
that we have merely analyzed the stability of systems assuming one goal or the other. In particular, because we do not model the source of goals, we do not take account of the possibility that the relative importance of alternative goals is itself derivative of domestic and balance-of-power politics. Finally, although we formulate an admittedly crude measure of resources for the period 1871-1914, we offer little guidance about how to operationalize the r/s for other periods. This ambiguity impacts on the second since there now is a greater (but obviously not total) disjuncture between military and economic capability (to the extent that today's technology allows wars to be "played out" before nonmilitary economic resources can be brought to bear on the conflict), and to the fact that although any measure of military capability is necessarily relative, measures of economic capability as a component of national goals - such as percapita income and rates of GNP growth, for example - may be stated in both absolute and relative terms. 9.2
Contemporary implications
It is a mistake, of course, to suppose that any single analysis or model can resolve all issues, and we must remind ourselves that the subject of international relations is far more complex and less structured than most. Hence, despite the ambiguities that remain, we ought to judge our analysis by the extent to which it reveals the utility of our paradigm as a basis for formalizing realist thinking, for rendering explicit a research agenda to extend and elaborate that thinking, and, perhaps most importantly, for organizing our thoughts about contemporary affairs. With respect to this last criterion, then, we now turn to an assessment of the relevance of our analysis in a nuclear age - to an age in which we might hypothesize that the balance-of-power politics of the nineteenth and earlier centuries provide an irrelevant guide to the conduct of international affairs. We begin by returning once again to the sources of conflict in our model, and we note that - beyond the hypothesis that armed conflict is a manifestation of the adjustment of an international system to an existent or anticipated system instability, a manifestation of the resource instability that seems inherent in such systems, or the consequence of a negotiation process that does not match our assumptions - the sources of conflict can lie also in the specific violation of one or more of our assumptions that precede A10. In this regard, the assumptions that ought to concern us especially are that resources are readily calculated, one-dimensional, and transferrable, and, as we have just noted, that everyone's information is complete. The argument that violations of assumptions lead to conflict is, of course, a triviality and takes us no closer to an understanding of
9.2 Contemporary implications
319
conflict than before. We can, nevertheless, use our analysis to identify those situations in which violations are likely to be important and when they are likely to be unimportant, and in the process we can try to gauge the contemporary relevance of our analysis. Consider the inherent uncertainty pervading the measurement of capabilities and the specification of how various dimensions of capability translate to some overall measure. In a bipolar world fixated on military capabilities, such uncertainties play a key role - systems are system stable in only one circumstance, namely, that each major power controls half the resources. Hence, even though the costs of war associated with nuclear weapons and the concern of national leaders with maximizing or at least preserving absolute resource levels (as against maximizing purely relative resources) may have, in combination with geographical realities, perturbed the equation, we can speculate that the United States and the Soviet Union had for so long been unable to negotiate arms reduction treaties out of an honest fear that no one knew the precise implications of any bargain, and miscalculation threatened disastrous consequences (Remark 3.1). Beginning in the 1970s, however, bipolarity and whatever remained of the United States' hegemony over Western affairs dissipated in an obvious way. China is now a third player, and Japan (even without a military presence) as well as Western Europe are key actors whose ties to the United States we should not assume are forever written in stone, especially when viewed in the context of today's economic competition and in the context of the strident nationalism (even xenophobia) that sometimes characterizes trading partners. This fact of increasing multipolarity helps us understand recent efforts to secure arms reduction when no reduction seemed feasible earlier. It is commonplace to view contemporary initiatives for strategic arms agreements as emanating from domestic political and economic considerations - from the desire for a president to earn an honorable footnote in history or from the need of a premier to remove the burdens of excessive military expenditures in a stagnating society. Yet these domestic forces operate and are sustained in an international context, and if the imperatives of that context preclude such agreements, it is unlikely that purely domestic forces can establish contrary incentives. Presidents have won elections, after all, by playing general as well as by playing statesman, and premiers in despotic regimes have held power even though millions of countrymen died as a consequence. We offer here, then, an explanation for why domestic politics seem especially propitious for strategic arms limitation: agreements and the inherent uncertainty associated with them are less dangerous in a multipolar world than in a bipolar one (Theorem 3.2 versus Remark 3.1); whereas, because resource stability is unlikely and thus the
320
9 Summary and conclusions
incentives to seek advantage by threats and counterthreats pervade (Theorem 4.1), a failure to agree is more dangerous. This conjectured explanation for recent U.S.-USSR movement on strategic arms reduction is complemented, of course, by other considerations, and since both sides have such a surplus of delivery systems, a cynic could argue that negotiators are merely making room in overfilled warehouses. Attempting to ascertain the most important consideration is, at this point, impossible; we offer the explanation provided by our theory not because we believe that it is the dominant factor, but rather because we merely wish to emphasize that any other relevant considerations are today operating in the context of a favorable macrostrategic environment. The issue of assessing resources so that we can apply our analysis generally, however, raises more profound questions. We noted in Chapter 6 the temptation to assert an analogy, which is not original to us,3 in which we see a repeat of nineteenth-century European great-power politics, with the Soviet Union substituted for Germany as the central power, Western Europe for France, China playing Russia's earlier role, and the United States (with Japanese funding?) playing Britain's role of balancer. This analogy and identification of power centers, though, brings into question the validity of our attribution of power. If we speak of military capabilities, then the relevant system concerns only two or three countries (the United States, the USSR, and, by virtue of its size and potential, mainland China); whereas if we also consider economic capabilities, then we ought to add Western Europe and Japan. As we note in the previous section, in earlier times this distinction between economic and military capabilities was blurred by the fact that, because wars took years or decades to fight, material and industrial resources could be converted from other purposes and directed at the conflict. Nuclear weapons and their associated technology arguably change this equation. In a war that takes days to fight, the fact that one country produces twenty times the number of personal computers as the other may be irrelevant to the outcome, so that if we focus on military capability, we arrive at a different accounting of power than if we focus on economic resources. The measure of military capabilities is complicated, moreover, because nuclear weapons seem qualitatively different from conventional ones. A country with 10,000 tanks can resist aggression better, ceteris paribus, than a country with 1,000 such vehicles, and if overcome, some proportion of the defeated foe's resources automatically are transferred to the victor. Yet a country with 3
See Liska (1977). For a contemporary analysis of the analogy between today's strategic environment and that which immediately preceded World War I, and (in particular) for an analogy that equates Russia and Germany's role as well as the roles of Britain and the United States, see Kagan (1987).
9.2 Contemporary implications
321
1,000 ICBMs may be no less powerful than one with 10,000, and in the event of war, no resources may remain for the loser or the "victor." Moreover, contrary to Assumption A7, no third parties may gain from such a conflict, and they too may lose as much as the principal combatants. Throughout this volume, we have assumed that resources of any type are not merely desired objectives, but that they can be translated into the capacity for overcoming an adversary. If, however, Organski and Kugler (1980, pp. 213-14) are correct to assert that "due to the incredible explosive power of nuclear weapons, military strength no longer moves within the narrow limits imposed by economic productivity and governmental capacity to extract resources," then we must ask whether the implications of our theorems about the necessary and sufficient conditions for system stability remain valid. To see, then, how our analysis can be applied (with appropriate assumptions) in a contemporary context, we must consider two issues associated with nuclear weapons. The first issue concerns the costs of war, and the second, the treatment of the concept of sovereignty. With respect to war costs, much of our analysis excludes considering such costs in order to render the study of preventive wars and geography tractable, although we can show that war costs do not affect the conditions for system stability if the relevant goal is the maximization of relative resources; whereas, in the event of absolute resource maximization, these costs, if sufficiently great, can significantly change the requirements for system stability and render even highly asymmetric bipolar systems system stable. Regardless of which objective we postulate, however, it is not unreasonable to suppose that, historically, the parameter a in expression (2.1) has been low - that regardless of a war's destruction, the material substratum upon which a country's resources are predicated (population, natural resources, geographic position) have remained essentially intact. This certainly seems true for the most intense and widespread war of this century, World War II, as evidenced by the resilience of the German, Japanese, and Russian economies despite the considerable damage inflicted upon them by weapons of great technological sophistication and immense destructive power. Britain may have lost an empire and France its position as a great power, but their relative decline seems inevitable in retrospect, even without war. Although wars may be costly in other ways, they have not proven to be especially so in terms of the long-term objectives of the victorious combatants: the assimilation of the resource-production capabilities of opponents and the maintenance, even the extension, of industrial capacity. Thus, one possibility is that modern technology has merely increased the parameter a in expression (2.1) from values near 0 to values that allow for the destruction of the material substratum upon which resource
322
9 Summary and conclusions
production is predicated, and that the stability of the postwar bipolar system, despite the U.S. advantages over the Soviets, has merely reflected this cost.4 It is arguably the case, though, that nuclear weapons open a new possibility that is not accommodated by this expression - namely, that any nation or coalition possessing them is blocking and capable of the destruction of an opponent (or, if not its destruction, at least the imposition of such costs as to render the possibility of a nuclear exchange unacceptable as an alternative to any outcome). Put differently, nuclear weapons may not be an additive or transitive resource as our analysis and expression (2.1) presume: if / can eliminate j , then / can eliminate j regardless of what additional resources are added to j ; moreover, j can eliminate / as well. This alternative view of nuclear weapons implies that the contexts in which the analysis of the preceding chapters is relevant is either a world disarmed of such weapons or a world in which no one would dare use them, unless otherwise threatened with elimination.5 Since the first possibility is a mere Utopia, let us consider a world in which deterrence works. By "works" we mean that each state possessing such weapons has "an infrangible guarantee of its independence and physical integrity" (Smart 1975, p. 458, quoted in Gilpin 1981, p. 215), in which case threats against state sovereignty - threats that, in Rosecrance's (1986) terminology, are manifestations of the competition of purely territorial states - are unbelievable, and any extreme form of system instability is precluded as well. This fact might seem to augur well for the course of international politics, but we must once again emphasize that system stability does not imply resource stability, so the viability of the nuclear threat does not inhibit countries from vying with each other for control over global resources. 4
5
Wars, of course, have always been costly, but it is not unreasonable to suppose that those costs weigh more heavily today than in earlier ages. A satisfactory accounting of war costs, though, must accommodate the fact that such costs differ, depending on the point of view. From one view, a battlefield casualty is merely a decrement in a nation's labor supply; from another view (that of the casualty), this cost may be the utter termination of the game. In an earlier age, national leaders might ignore the second view. Excepting the decision of a Napoleon to lead his own troops or of a Hitler to choose suicide over public humiliation and execution, kings, emperors, prime ministers, presidents, and dictators (as well as the governmental infrastructure that served them and much of the noncombative civilian population) might hope to avoid their personal destruction. Wars need not even change the world very much and might even leave open opportunities to regain control after a period of exile. Such is not the case today. The consequences of a nuclear exchange would be visited on all, and this certainly alters the thinking of today's strategic planners. Some strategists would argue that there is an advantage in terms of second-strike capabilities to possessing more nuclear warheads than an opponent, or that such weapons are like all others. If we accept this view, however, then we merely revert to the previous interpretation of our analysis.
9.2 Contemporary implications
323
In fact, resource instability here is doubly dangerous. Such instability implies a continual process of subtle or explicit threat and counterthreat, but now errors in judgment may be supremely costly; and, there is no natural limit to the resources to which nations might aspire. Moreover, if sovereignty for all states possessing such weapons is guaranteed, then there is no systemic constraint that acts to prevent countries from seeking and successfully securing a preponderance of resources, and the resource instability that prevails looks more like the one Riker (1962) describes than the one we deduce from our assumptions. This observation, then, merely reiterates Gilpin's (1981, p. 216) concern that "insofar as [modern man]... makes the world safe from total nuclear war through arms control and an effective system of deterrence, he also makes the world that much safer for limited wars and the calculated exploitation of nuclear threats." Minimally, we can hypothesize that any guarantee of sovereignty offered by nuclear weapons leaves the field open for dangerous local, resource-instability-related conflicts, which error and misjudgment might move to an unintended apocalyptic level. Such an argument would seem to imply that the deterrence provided by nuclear weapons would lead national leaders to fear only miscalculation, but such an inference relies on too narrow an interpretation of the concept of sovereignty. Sovereignty comes in different forms. It was probably of small consolation to the Romanovs, for example, to know that, both before and after World War I, Russia approximated Waltz's (1979) requirement that it be able to decide "for itself how it will cope with its internal and external problems" (p. 96). Indeed, this example compels us, in the context of the effective deterrence scenario, to treat sovereignty as applying to regimes within states rather than to states themselves. If we keep in mind the assumption of methodological individualism underlying the rational-choice paradigm, and if we keep in mind as well that it is merely a convenient abstraction to suppose that collectivities such as states have an existence that is independent of those who lead them, then the idea of regime survival provides a more justifiable basis for asserting the relevance of our analysis. And once we make this adjustment in terminology, we see little reason for supposing that nuclear weapons provide regimes with an infrangible guarantee of survival. Thus, if we turn our attention to the regimes that direct the affairs of individual states, we can find a basis for agreeing with Organski and Kugler's (1980, p. 217) assertion that "If nuclear weapons have influenced the rules of international politics inherited from pre-nuclear times, the influence has not operated in the expected direction: the weapons have not modified these rules, they have instead reinforced them," and with Gilpin's (1988, p. 611) conclusion that "The fundamental characteristics of international
324
9 Summary and conclusions
affairs unfortunately have not been altered and, if anything, have been intensified by the nuclear revolution. International politics continues to be a self-help system."6 Waltz's requirement for sovereignty and our application of this concept to domestic regimes, nevertheless, reveals a potential confusion between the definitions of sovereignty and the role various national resources play in ensuring sovereignty. Although some ambiguities remain when we restrict the notion of sovereignty to the control of territory, if we suppose (as we must) that economic resources are an important component of a state's or regime's ability to "cope with its internal and external problems," then the ambiguity of definitions increases considerably in an economically interdependent world community. Is the United States less sovereign today than a decade ago when it relied less on the investments of foreign powers for maintenance of employment and on banks in Japan and Germany for maintaining the stability of the dollar's relative value, or should we treat current trends in the world economy "merely" as an erosion of U.S. resources? We cannot offer here a satisfactory answer to this question since such an answer requires a precise definition of the multifaceted notion of sovereignty and a more careful modeling of the relationship between domestic politics, goals, and international politics. Clearly, though, such concerns bring into question our sharp distinction between essential and inessential countries, as well as the methodologies we ought to use in applying our analysis in contemporary affairs. Our analysis, of course, is built on a sequence of such distinctions that only imperfectly characterize international politics - a characterization that approximates reality when countries are autonomous self-contained entities - but the contemporary world economy muddies the waters considerably. We now see a form of international competition in which territorial sovereignty takes a back seat at times to sovereignty based on economic control. The concept of economic control or economic power in a world market economy is, of course, no easier to operationalize than any classical notion of power. Compounding the difficulty is that the nuclear threat in combination with a world economy forces us to consider the possibility that we may have to adjust our assumption about national goals - that, however measured or defined, the maximization of power or of economic control no longer summarizes a viable hypothesis about 6
However, we should note that, for reasons we discuss subsequently, we disagree with the conclusion Gilpin (1988) offers at the conclusion of his essay, namely that "All of the nuclear states seek to avoid nuclear war at the same time that they are attempting to safeguard more traditional interests. The result has been ... the creation of a new basis for international order. In contrast to the balance of power system ... order in the nuclear age has been built on the foundation of mutual deterrence" (p. 612).
9.2 Contemporary implications
325
objectives. Earlier, we justified imposing this objective as an assumption of our theory with the Darwinian argument that nations that failed to pursue this goal would soon become inessential, to be absorbed subsequently by more powerful neighbors. However, if the nuclear threat and a workable deterrence alters this calculus then perhaps it can alter goals as well, and perhaps some different maximand will supplant the one we assume throughout most of this volume. Gilpin (1981) cites the possible source of a change in incentives that the nuclear threat may accelerate: Since the advent and spread of industrialism... groups and states have been able to maximize their mutual gains through international cooperation and the establishment of an efficient economic organization both domestically and internationally. The gradual creation of the world market economy over the past century and a half reflected this global commitment to efficiency and growth (p. 219). Correspondingly, particularly among industrialized, pluralist countries, the perceived margin of safety has widened: fears of attack in general have declined, and fears of attacks by one another are virtually nonexistent. France has abandoned the tous azimuts (defense in all directions) strategy that President de Gaulle advocated Canada's last war plans for fighting the United States were abandoned half a century ago. Britain and Germany no longer feel threatened by each other. Intense relationships of mutual influence exist between these countries, but in most of them force is irrelevant or unimportant as an instrument of policy (Keohane and Nye 1977, p. 27). Although the share of the world's resources must still total one hundred percent, the possibility of a world in which competition among nations is no longer viewed as a constant-sum game dictated by relative economic and military capabilities suggests that a country's share of that percentage need not be the measure we use to evaluate policies. If nuclear deterrence forces us to focus on regime rather than nation-state sovereignty, and if absolute rather than relative wealth determines the domestic viability of regimes, then the maximization of military power or even maximization of shares of economic wealth may become tempered by the goal of maximizing the efficiency of global markets. The ambiguities characterizing the application of our analysis to contemporary circumstances, however, should not be interpreted as undermining the relevance of the realist view of international affairs embodied by our analysis. We should keep in mind that even though nuclear weapons may give the appearance of ensuring the identity of a state, and even though there may be considerable mutual gains from economic cooperation, neither consideration guarantees economic vitality and sovereignty. And, ultimately, the loss of economic vitality and sovereignty - with or without nuclear weapons - undermines political (regime) sovereignty
326
9 Summary and conclusions
regardless of whether we take a narrow view of sovereignty in terms of territorial control or of the broader view offered by Waltz. Hence, if it is in fact true that "all of the major shifts in the world's military-power balances have followed alterations in the productive balances" (Kennedy 1987, p. 439), if "through the exercise of economic power, each center of the world economy will seek to increase the benefits of interdependence and decrease the costs" (Gilpin 1975, p. 261), and if a "balance in world military politics is necessary to permit a trading system to function" (Rosecrance 1986, p. ix), then we are compelled to the view that the fundamental character of international politics today is not effectively different from the past. The change wrought by nuclear weapons may be only apparent, and a focus on immediate military capabilities at the expense of other dimensions of national power may merely have caused us to temporarily fail to see that the arena in which we must compete includes not only the Soviets for advantage in military technology, but also other powers for economic advantage. "The direction of financial flows, the inevitable shifts in comparative advantage, and the international distribution of productive activities are preoccupations of modern statecraft" (Gilpin 1987, p. 5). Hence, the Bismarck of the late twentieth century will not be concerned merely with the Balkans or with other parts of the globe of which we remain dimly aware, but also with rates of industrial productivity, with foreign investment, and with market share; and here, too, the balance of power as we have analyzed it, albeit operationalizing the notion of resources somewhat differently, will hold true. The realist intuition rests less on the strict predominance of military power and military security issues in international affairs than on the perception that a single set of conflictual dynamics underlie these affairs, whether the question is a Soviet naval base in the Pacific or a Japanese tariff policy. Returning now to the geopolitical analogy with the nineteenth century, it must of course be true that any shift in emphasis from military to economic competition and from territorial to regime sovereignty decreases the relevance of geography. However, such a shift cannot eliminate geography as an important variable. Although economic resources may be more fungible than military resources, military capability continues to play an obviously important role - to assume otherwise requires explanation for the difficulties confronting the major powers in reaching accords on conventional-arms limitation. Thus, with geography remaining relevant, we see the inherent conflict between the Soviets and the United States. From the Russian perspective, the United States - by virtue of its alliances with Western Europe and Japan, in conjunction with the maintenance of a stable relationship with a mainland China that pays mere
9.2 Contemporary implications
327
lip service to Marxist dogma - plays less the role of balancer and more a threatening power that augments the resources of Russia's contiguous adversaries. The Soviets may, by virtue of their nuclear arsenal, ensure the survival and identity of their country, but this does not preclude threats to the viability of their regime. The special danger to the Soviet Union is that by virtue of the explicit and implicit dimensions of their alliance with the United States - regardless of whether this alliance takes the form of a hegemony dominated by the United States or one dominated merely by a capitalist ideology - Russia's potential adversaries to the East and West are effectively joined as an economic and military colossus, completing a contemporary form of the Franco-Russian alliance Germany feared. One solution is to split off parts of the American alliance and either neutralize those parts or attach them to its own. A second alternative is a reconciliation with mainland China and a reformation of an alliance of Communist states. The third possibility is to alter the arena of conflict to economic competition, thereby rendering geography less relevant. The hope (from the Soviets' view) embodied in the first alternative is that not all elements of a factious Western Europe will maintain their role as essential actors and their abilities to resist Soviet pressures. On the other hand, today we see a resurgence of national and ethnic identity among not only Russia's Eastern European allies, but also among component parts of the Soviet state itself, which raises the possibility that a united Europe's boundaries will not correspond nicely to the division between East and West established after World War II. The problem of the second alternative is that China today seems well aware of its potential role and of the necessity for maintaining flexible commitments within the constraints established by its desire to modernize its society. Indeed, Russia now confronts the growth not merely of mainland China, but of the mainland coupled with the economic power of Japan, Korea, Taiwan, and Malaysia. Although these Pacific-rim countries are unlikely to become an international military force, their resources (technology, money, and managerial skills) will augment the mainland's development, thereby rendering China both an economic and a military threat. With respect to the possibility of economic competition and the concomitant reduction of the role of geography, this, of course, is the arena in which the United States and its allies hold the advantage. Augmenting Russia's economic resources and power is at best problematical, given a bureaucratically centralized economic structure that works no better today than it did in Czarist times. There remains, in fact, the reasonable possibility that the Soviets can find themselves with an economy not even ranked third among the world's major economic conglomerates, and that it will thereby confront
328
9 Summary and conclusions
a threat even Germany did not contemplate. Thus, the mere readjustment of alliances in the form of a weakening of America's hegemony seems inadequate to meet the demands on Russian security. Although there is no reason to suppose that the Soviets must pursue one strategy at the expense of all others, it seems reasonable to suppose that economic competition holds the ultimate key to national security and that to escape the dilemma of the central power - to, in Walt's words quoted earlier, "move their country somewhere else" - the Soviets must learn to rely more on economics and on the development of their immense natural resources. The solution to the security dilemma for those who sit behind the Kremlin's walls, then, contradicts their autocratic rule and their dreams of a Russo-communist world hegemony: in a process that has only just begun, and that may yet fail because of an entrenched bureaucracy unable to act on the basis of macrogeopolitical considerations, the Kremlin must remove the inefficient shackles of a centralized command economy based on an outdated and discredited theory of socioeconomic processes. The strategic imperatives for the United States are equally clear. Briefly, the United States cannot become overly concerned if some portion of its "alliance" moves closer to neutrality, thereby reducing Russian anxiety. That is, in purely military matters, the United States should demand of neither Western Europe nor mainland China an inflexible commitment to one side or the other, lest Russia perceive a real threat to a status quo in which she is essential. The American relationship with the mainland in particular ought not to be approached as a potential addition to any well-defined military alliance; rather, it should be based on more informal mutual economic interests and on the necessity for augmenting China's incentives and ability to act as an independent, essential player in a multipolar system. Similarly, the "cost" to the United States of an integrated and independent Europe - of an Eastern Europe that moves from the shadow of Soviet military dominance - may be a weakening of the military component of its alliance with Western Europe and a more explicit reliance on the shared ideology of the nature of the social contract between citizen and state and on mutual economic interests. Because we see system stability more easily assured in a multipolar than in a bipolar world, we would reverse Waltz's (1979, p. 172) concern that "[miscalculation... is the source of danger in a multipolar world; overreaction ... is the source of danger in a bipolar world." In any event, the conclusions we draw from this view supports Kennedy's (1987, p. 515) argument about the strategic trap that the United States ought to avoid, namely:
9.2 Contemporary implications
329
the United States now runs the risk, so familiar to historians of the rise and fall of previous Great Powers, of what might roughly be called "imperial overstretch": that is to say, decision-makers in Washington must face the awkward and enduring fact that the sum total of the United States' global interests and obligations is nowadays far larger than the country's power to defend them all simultaneously.
There is no reason to suppose that a declining American hegemony is necessarily destabilizing. Looking, for example, to the trends and events preceding World War I, we see that it was not merely the relative decline of British military and economic power that destabilized Europe. Rather, it was the threatened German predominance on the continent that led to conflict. Were the French capable of maintaining a comparable rate of growth, then it is not unreasonable to suppose that German growth would have merely required the British to engage in more delicate diplomatic maneuver. Correspondingly, if we can imagine a circumstance in which China (broadly defined) and Western Europe each becomes responsible for its military security and sovereignty, then a unique balancing role for the United States, unencumbered by the necessity forfinancingthe security needs of countries who are increasingly able to not only compete economically with the United States but to even dominate specific markets, becomes apparent. There is, though, one complicating factor in this discussion - the possibility that the competition for economic resources characterizing the relationships of the major industrial states will be transformed to a more traditional territorial-military form - "the dangers inherent in the tendencies toward mercantilistic competition, economic regionalism, and sectoral protectionism should not be minimized" (Gilpin 1987, p. 405). Thus, although today we might treat Japan as a contributor to America's military resources, we cannot exclude the possibility that the competition between these two countries, with racism and Japanese xenophobia serving as catalysts, can take a bitter turn. Once again, though, America's role is evident in a variety of reasonable scenarios. With memories of Nanking having a long half-life, we cannot discount the potential conflict between China and Japan, and even if we add the Soviet Union to the equation, so that China is viewed as a central power caught between a Russia seeking to ensure its regime's sovereignty by dominating all of Asia and a Japan seeking to control the mainland's natural and human resources, America's role remains one of flexible commitments - as a supporter of China's sovereignty and, following the development of China's industrial potential, as traditional balancer. In addition, despite the trend toward increasing great power preoccupation with economic sovereignty, there remains an explicitly military and
330
9 Summary and conclusions
territorial character to regional conflicts and, here, our analysis of nineteenth-century Europe appears particularly apt. Two Middle Eastern examples make the point unmistakably: Iraq and Israel. Both face the dilemma imposed by a central power's security requirements. Iraq, bordered by a hostile Iran and Syria, sought in 1980 to break free of this central power's dilemma by attacking Iran when it seemed, to outside observers, at its weakest. The initial feature of this stratagem forced Iraq to search for external resources in the form of Saudi, Kuwaiti, and French loans and Soviet and French weapons. This process parallels German attempts earlier in the century to gain resources from Turkey and the Balkans to avoid the straightjacket that would be imposed on its ability to meet its security requirements, although the German dilemma was compounded by the fact that no superpower existed to tilt the balance decisively in its favor. The situation facing Israel is similar and the security requirements of a central power are the most important considerations in Israeli strategic thinking. Here, too, the central power's strategy is to ensure its sovereignty by obtaining external resources; however, its position is enormously better than that of Iraq in that it enjoys a uniquely privileged relationship with one of the superpowers, which is prepared to transfer resources at levels higher than can be matched by any of Israel's Arab neighbors for the foreseeable future. We can attribute the special instabilities of the region and the periodic outbreak of war, then, to the fact that, without the intervention of exogenous states, neither Israel nor Iraq resides in a system-stable subsystem. What these examples suggest is that regional politics will continue, in many respects, to structurally resemble the military power-driven politics of nineteenth-century Europe. 9.3
Conclusion
We cannot conclude this volume with definitive predictions. At best, our analysis offers a starting point for a more comprehensive theoretical development, a mechanism whereby we can question the conclusions of others, and a framework for guiding the application of common sense and intuitive understanding. In this spirit, and because we have relied so much on his insights throughout this volume, let us review the five factors Gilpin (1981, pp. 235-7) outlines as potentially destabilizing in the modern international system. The first factor, based on the premise that the current world order is bipolar, is that one power or the other allows its position to deteriorate. That such a possibility is destabilizing in a bipolar world is unquestionably true (Remark 3.1), but, as we have just argued, it is far from clear
9.3 Conclusion
331
whether the current order is bipolar. If the United States is indeed a declining hegemon, it is not declining necessarily to the Soviet's benefit, but more to that of its post-World War II allies - Germany, Japan, and the other burgeoning economic powers. This trend leads us directly to the second factor Gilpin cites: "the danger of the rise of a third party to upset the bipolar balance." If anything, however, we find such an eventuality stabilizing, at least from the perspective of system stability, although not from that of resource stability. The view that the rise of third parties is destabilizing fails to take these two distinct notions of stability into account, and thus it fails to accommodate the contrary forces of balanceof-power processes in a transition from bipolar to multipolar systems. The third factor, in which Gilpin draws an analogy to World War I, concerns "the danger of polarization of the international system as a whole into two hostile camps." Gilpin is correct to express this concern to the extent that it refers to, say, the domestic political constraints that make the formation of advantageous alliances difficult. However, we ought to interpret carefully the appearance of inflexibility that historical events provide and the conclusions we draw from those events, because we want to avoid the error of attributing particular manifestations of the imperatives of balance of power to inflexibility. Our analysis in Chapter 8, for example, suggested that, aside from the presumed infeasibility of a FrancoGerman alliance, the events leading to World War I are better understood as arising from a set of theoretically well-defined geopolitical concerns than they are from a consideration of the constraints on action imposed by treaty commitments and the like. Of course, to the extent that nuclear technology and a world economy render geopolitical factors irrelevant, the lessons of that war may have little relation to the problems confronting us today; but even if those factors remain relevant, it is not the inflexibility of treaty obligations per se that ought to concern us as a possible source of conflict, but rather the root causes of inflexibility: contradictions between alliance adjustments required to sustain system stability and domestic politics.7 The fourth factor is "the danger of entanglement of the major powers in the ambitions and difficulties of minor allies." Again, too much of a 7
It is tempting to argue, in this context, that political ideology can play the same role in establishing inflexibilities as did the issue of Alsace and Lorraine. This may indeed be true to the extent that domestic politics restrict a country's ability to act in accordance with geopolitical strategic imperatives in mind, but Alsace and Lorraine concerned territory and resources, whereas the U.S. rapprochement with mainland China illustrates the dominating influence of these strategic imperatives when the issue is security and sovereignty. Ideology, in short, may color short-term dynamics and it may yield biases in favor of one coalition as against another, but it cannot wholly subvert strategic imperatives.
332
9 Summary and conclusions
lesson is being drawn from one reading of European events. Our analysis suggests that Germany did not launch its attack on France because it was "entangled" with Austria any more than Britain entered the war on the Franco-Russian side because it was "entangled" with Belgium. The entanglement of both followed logically from balance-of-power considerations, and to the extent that those considerations do not imply a loss of sovereignty for one or more of the major powers, then as long as the assumptions of our analysis hold, relations with minor allies are unlikely to cause major conflicts. The fifth and final destabilizing factor is "the loss of control over economic, political, and social developments [that]... lead political elites in great powers to miscalculate." This factor - uncertainty and incomplete information - is, as we have already indicated, doubtlessly of profound importance. Our sole qualification of Gilpin's concern is to emphasize that we see little reason to assume that the shift from a political-territorialeconomic maximand to a more exclusively economic maximand will intrinsically change the balance-of-power dynamics of international systems. Certainly, the pace of economic, technological, political, and social change has been accelerating since the Industrial Revolution. Yet, the underlying structure of the system - the maximizing behavior of self-interested actors intent on maintaining the viability of their regimes - has remained constant. Assuming that nuclear weapons play only the role of deterrence, then, as we said in Chapter 2: our assumptions about resources... define the domain of our theory, if not all balance-of-power theories. Assumption A4 requires that national leaders maximize ri9 which to this point we have ambiguously referred to as country /'s national resources, whereas A5 requires that whatever r, measures also determines a state's capability of securing rt in conflict, its military capability. Furthermore, A4 requires that all countries share a common maximand, whereas A5 requires that the capability of countries is also measured by a common variable. Finally, Al and A3 suppose that the thing that the r's measure is transferable across countries on a one-to-one basis and infinitesupply. The consequence of these assumptions, then, is that our theory concerns those international systems In which readily identifiable sovereign entities (countries) maximize the same "thing/' which is in limited but transferable supply, and which translates directly into a measure of its capacity for securing its ends and maintaining its security.
Despite the evident integration of economies, and the mutual gains that advanced industrial technology affords those economies, we are not prepared to reject the hypothesis that this balance-of-power dynamic will apply for the foreseeable future.
References and Selected Bibliography on European Great-Power Relations, 1871-1914
Adair, R. K. (1987). The Great Design. New York: Oxford University Press. Adams, M. (1937). "The British Attitude to German Colonization, 1880-1885," Bulletin of the Institute of Historical Research XV: 190-3. Addington, L. H. (1971). The Blitzkrieg Era and the German General Staff, 1865-1941. New Brunswick (NJ): Rutgers University Press. Albertini, L. (1952-7). The Origins of the War of 1914. 3 vols. London: Oxford University Press. Alfoldi, L. M. (1975). The Armies of Austria-Hungary and Germany, 1740-1914: A Bibliography. Carlisle Barracks (PA): U.S. Army War College. (1976). "The Prussian General Staff, 1804-1919," in Essays in Some Dimensions of Military History: Volume Four, pp. 28-47. Carlisle Barracks (PA): U.S. Army War College. Allen, F. S. (1960). "The British Army, 1860-1900: A Study of the Cardwell Manpower Reforms." Ph.D. dissertation, Harvard University. Allen, W. E. D., and P. Muratoff (1953). Caucasian Battlefields: A History of the Wars on the Turco-Caucasian Border, 1828-1921. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Allison, G. (1971). Essence of Decision. Boston: Little, Brown. Allison, G., and M. Halperin (1972). "Bureaucratic Politics: A Paradigm and Some Policy Implications," in Theory and Policy in International Relations, edited by R. Tanter and R. Ullman. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Alt, J. E., R. L. Calvert, and B. D. Humes (1988). "Reputation and Hegemonic Stability: A Game Theoretic Analysis," American Political Science Review 82(2): 445-66. Altham, E. A. (1914). The Principles of War Historically Illustrated. London: Macmillan. Anderson, D. P. (1968). The Balkan Volunteers. London: Hutchinson. Anderson, O. (1967). "Early Experiences of Manpower Problems in an Industrial Society at War: Great Britain, 1854-1856," Political Science Quarterly LXXXII: 526-45. Anderson, P. (1939). The Background of Anti-English Feeling in Germany, 1890-1902. New York: American University Press. Andrew, C M . (1968). Theophile Delcasse and the Making of the Entente Cordiale. New York: St. Martin's Press. (1971). "The Entente Cordiale from its Origins to 1914," in Troubled Neighbours: FrancoBritish Relations in the Twentieth Century, edited by N. Waites. London: Weidenfeld. Aron, R. (1973). Peace and War, translated by R. Howard and A. B. Fox. Garden City (NY): Doubleday. Arrow, K. (1957). Social Choice and Individual Values. New Haven: Yale University Press. Askew, W. C. (1942). Europe and Italy's Acquisition of Libya, 1911-1912. Durham (NC): Duke University Press. (1951). "Russian Military Strength on the Eve of the Franco-Prussian War," Slavonic and Eastern European Review XXX: 185-205. Asquith, H. H. (1923). Genesis of the War. London: Cassell. Aumann, R. J. (1976). "Agreeing to Disagree," The Annals of Statistics 4(6): 1236-9. Aumann, R. J., and M. Maschler (1964). "The Bargaining Set for Cooperative Games," in Advances in Game Theory, edited by M. Dresher, L. S. Shapley, and A. W. Tucker. Princeton: Princeton University Press. 333
334
References and selected bibliography
Austen-Smith, D., and W. H. Riker (1987). "Asymmetric Information and the Coherence of Legislation," American Political Science Review 81(3): 897-918. Axelrod, R. (1984). The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books. Axelrod, R., and R. O. Keohane (1985). "Achieving Cooperation Under Anarchy," World Politics 38(1): 226-54. Aydelotte, W. O. (1937). Bismarck and British Colonial Policy. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Bairoch, P. (1976). "Europe's Gross National Product: 1800-1975," Journal of European Economic History 5. Balck, W. (1911). Tactics. Ft. Leavenworth (KS): U.S. Cavalry Association. Bald, D. (1970). Deutsch-Ostafrika, 1900-1914: Eine Studie ueber Verwaltung, Interessengruppen und wirtschaftliche Erschliessung. Munich: Weltforum Verlag. Baldwin, D. A. (1979). "Power Analysis and World Politics," World Politics 31(1): 161-94. Barclay, G. (1973). The Rise and Fall of the New Roman Empire: Italy's Bid for World Power, 1890-1943. New York: St. Martin's Press. Becker, S. (1969). Russia's Protectorates in Central Asia: Bukhara and Khiva, 1865-1924. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Beckett, I. F. W. (1974). Victoria's Wars. Aylesbury, UK: Shire Publications. Benjamin, H. C. (1932). "Official Propaganda and the French Press During the FrancoPrussian War," Journal of Modern History IV: 214-30. Binmore, K., and P. Dasgupta (1987). The Economics of Bargaining. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Birch, R. C. (1966). Britain and Europe, 1871-1939. Oxford: Pergamon Press. Bittner, L., H. Uebersberger, A. F. Pribram, and H. R. von Srbik, eds. (1930). OesterreichUngarns Aussenpolitik von der Bosnischen Krise 1908 bis zum Kriegsausbruch 1914. Wien and Leipzig. 9 vols. Black, C. E. (1943). The Establishment of Constitutional Government in Bulgaria. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Black, D. (1958). Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Blainey, G. (1973). The Causes of War. New York: The Free Press. Blaisdell, D. C. (1929). European Financial Control in the Ottoman Empire. New York: Columbia University Press. Bond, B. (1960). "The Effect of the Cardwell Reforms on Army Organization, 1878-1904," Journal of the Royal United Service Institution CV: 515-24. (1961). "The Late Victorian Army," History Today XI: 616-24. (1962a). "Edward Cardwell's Army Reforms," Army Quarterly LXXXIV: 108-17. (1962b). "Recruiting the Victorian Army, 1870-1892," Victorian Studies V: 331-8. (1972). The Victorian Army and the Staff College, 1854-1914. London: Eyre Methuen. Bontwesch, B. (1975). "Handelspolitik und Industrialisierung. Zur aussenwirtschaftlichen Abhaengigheit Russlands," in Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft im vorrevolutionaeren Russland, edited by D. Geyer. Koeln: Kiepenheur und Witsch. Bosworth, R. J. B. (1979). Italy, the Least of the Great Powers: Italian Foreign Policy before the First World War. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Boulding, K. (1962). Conflict and Defense: A General Theory. New York: Harper. Bourgeois, E. (1926). "Les Origines de la Triple Alliance et la question romaine," Revue de Paris 33: 37-58. Bourne, K. (1970). The Foreign Policy of Victorian England, 1830-1902. London: Oxford University Press. Bovykin, V. I. (1979). "The Franco-Russian Alliance," History 64(210): 20-35. Boyd, R., and J. P. Lorderbaum (1987). "No Pure Strategy is Evolutionary Stable in the Repeated Prisoners' Dilemma," Nature 327: 58-9. Brams, S. (1975). Game Theory and Politics. New York: Free Press. Brodie, B. (1973). War and Politics. New York: Macmillan. Brown, R. G. (1970). Fashoda Reconsidered: The Impact of Domestic Politics on French Policy in Africa, 1893-1898. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
References and selected bibliography
335
Brunschwig, H. (1966). French Colonialism, 1870-1914: Myths and Realities, translated by W. G. Brown. New York: Pall Mall Press. Bueno De Mesquita, B. (1981a). The War Trap. New Haven: Yale University Press. (1981b). "Risk, Power Distributions, and the Likelihood of War," International Studies Quarterly 25(4): 541-68. Bull, H. (1977). The Anarchical Society. New York: Columbia University Press. Burns, A. L. (1968). Of Powers and Their Politics. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall. Cairncross, A. K. (1953). Home and Foreign Investment, 1870-1913. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cairns, J. C. (1953). "International Politics and the Military Mind: The Case of the French Republic, 1911-1914," Journal of Modern History XXV: 273-85. Cameron, R. (1966). France and the Economic Development of Europe, 1800-1914. Chicago: Rand McNally. Campbell, W. R., D. Darvich, and G. F. Rose (1983). "An Inquiry into the Values Structuring the Islamic Revolution," Hamdard Islamicus 6(4): 66-115. Campion, L. K. (1976). As Bismarck Fell: The Restive Mind of the German Military. Greenville (NC): East Carolina University Press. Cardella, G. P. (1928). "Crispi e la Politica Mediterranea e Coloniale," Politico XXIX: 150-79; XXXI: 350-80. Carroll, E. M. (1931). French Public Opinion and Foreign Affairs, 1870-1914. New York: Appleton-Century. (1938). Germany and the Great Powers, 1866-1914. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall. Case, L. M. (1932). Franco-Italian Relations, 1860-1865: The Roman Question and the Convention of September. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Castagno, A. A. (1957). The Development of the Expansionist Concepts in Italy (18611896). Ann Arbor (MI): University Microfilms. Challener, R. D. (1965). The French Theory of the Nation in Arms, 1866-1939. New York: Russell and Russell. (1975). "French National Security Policies, 1871-1939," in New Dimensions in Military History, edited by Russell F. Weigley, pp. 92-121. San Rafael (CA): Presidio Press. Chatterjee, P. (1975). Arms, Alliances and Stability. New York: Wiley. Churchill, R. P. (1939). The Anglo-Russian Convention of 1907. London: The Torch Press. Clarke, G. S. (1898). Russia's Sea-Power, Past and Present. London: Murray. Claude, I. (1962 and 1967). Power and International Relations. New York: Random House. Contamine, H. (1957). La Revanche, 1871-1914. Paris: Berger-Levrault. Coolidge, A. C. (1926). The Origins of the Triple Alliance. New York: Scribners. Cornelius, J. (1977). Military Forces of France: A Bibliography. Carlisle Barracks (PA): U.S. Army War College. Court, W. H. B. (1965). British Economic History, 1870-1914: Commentary and Documents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cowles, V. S. (1969). The Russian Dagger: Cold War in the Days of the Czars. London: Collins. Crafts, N. F. R. (1983). "Gross National Product in Europe, 1870-1910: Some New Estimates," Explorations in Economic History 20: 387-401. Craig, G. (1955). The Politics of the Prussian Army, 1640-1945. New York: Oxford University Press. Crisp, O. (1976). Studies in the Russian Economy Before 1914. London: Macmillan. Cunningham, H. (1975). The Volunteer Force: A Social and Political History, 1859-1908. London: Croom Helm. Curalto, G. E. (1915). Francia e Italia, 1849-1914. Turin: Fratelli Bocca. Cyert, R., and J. March (1963). A Behavioral Theory of the Firm. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall. D'Agostino, G. (1969). Vltalia in Africa, 1869-1896. Florence: La Nuova Italia. De Bloch, J. (1899). Is War Now Impossible? London: The Russian Library. De La Gorce, P. M. (1963). The French Army: A Military-Political History. New York: G. Braziller.
336
References and selected bibliography
Deane, P., and W. A. Cole (1962). British Economic Growth, 1688-1959. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dedijer, V. (1967). The Road to Sarajevo. London: MacGibbon Kee. Degroot, M. H. (1974). "Reaching a Consensus," Journal of the American Statistical Association 69: 118-21. Dehio, L. (1962). The Precarious Balance: The Politics of Power in Europe, 1494-1945, translated by Chalres Fullman. New York: Vintage. De Negier, F. (1905). Lessons From the Russo-Japanese War. London. Dethan, G. (1936). "Le Rapprochement Franco-Italien apres la Chute de Crispi, 18961904," Revue d'Historie Diplomatique LXX: 323-39. Deutsch, K. (1967). The Analysis of International Relations. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall. D'Ombrain, N. J. (1970). "The Imperial General Staff and the Military Policy of a 'Continental Strategy' During the 1911 International Crisis," Military Affairs XXXIV: 88-93. (1974). War Machinery and High Policy: Defence Administration in Peacetime Britain, 1902-1914. London: Oxford University Press. Donaudy, A. (1937). Da Cavour a Crispi (La Storia delVEspansione Coloniale Italiana). Milan: Edizione da Tempo. Doran, C. F., and W. Parsons (1980). "War and the Cycle of Relative Power," American Political Science Review 74(4): 947-65. Downs, A. (1957). An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row. Dupuy, T. N. (1977). A Genius for War: The German Army and General Staff, 1807-1945. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall. Ehringhaus, F. (1929). "Die Ergebnisse der englischen Akten ueber die deutsch-englischen Buendnisverhandlungen, 1899-1901," Vergangenheit und Gegenwart XIX: 471-80. Epstein, K. (1966). "Gerhard Ritter and the First World War," Journal of Contemporary History 1(3): 198. Erusalimskii, A. S. (1954). Die Aussenpolitik und die Diplomatic des deutschen Imperialismus ende des 19. Jahrhunderts. Berlin: Dietz Verlag. Faber, R. (1966). The Vision and the Need: Late Victorian Imperialist Aims. London: Faber. Fasel, G. W. (1970). Europe in Upheaval: The Revolutions of 1848. Chicago: RandMcNally. Fay, S. B. (1938). The Origins of the World War, 2nd Ed. New York: Macmillan. Feis, H. (1930). Europe: The World's Banker, 1870-1914. New Haven: Yale University Press. Ferris, W. (1973). The Power Capabilities of Nation States. Lexington (MA): Lexington Books. Fiorina, M. P. (1977). Congress: Keystone of the Washington Establishment. New Haven: Yale University Press. Fischer, F. (1961). Griff nach der Weltmach. Dusseldorf: Droste. (1964). "Weltpolitik, Weltmachstreben, und deutsche Kriegsziele," Historische Zeitschrift 199(2): 265-364. (1977). Der Erste Weltkrieg und das deutsche Geschichtsbild. Dusseldorf: Droste. Flammer, P. M. (1966). "The Schlieffen Plan and Plan XVII: A Short Critique," Military Affairs XXX: 207-12. Florinsky, M. (1927). "The Russian Mobilization of 1914," Political Science Quarterly XLII: 203-27. Foch, F. (1903). Des principes de la guerre. Paris: Berger-Levrault. Fortescue, J. W. (1899-1930). A History of the British Army. London: Macmillan. France. Commission de Publication des Documents Relatif aus Origines de La Guerre de 1914 (1929- ). Documents Diplomatiques Francais, 1871-1914. Paris: Imprintes Nationale. Fremdling, R. (1985). "Commodity Output in Great Britain and Germany 1855-1913." Mimeo. Berlin: Freie Universitaet Berlin. Fudenberg, D., and E. Maskin (1986). "Folk Theorems for Repeated Games with Discounting or with Incomplete Information," Econometrica 54: 533-54. Fuller, J. F. C. (1926). Imperial Defence, 1588-1914. London: Praed. Fuller, J. V. (1922). Bismarck's Diplomacy at Its Zenith. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.
References and selected bibliography
337
Gardiner, L. (1968). The British Admiralty. Annapolis (MD): U.S. Naval Institute. Garnham, D. (1976). "Dyadic International War, 1816-1965: The Role of Power, Parity, and Geographic Proximity," Western Political Quarterly 29: 231-42. Gatrell, P. (1986). The Tsarist Economy, 1850-1917. New York: St. Martin's Press. Gauld, W. A. (1927). "The 'Dreikaiserbund' and the Eastern Question, 1877-1878," English Historical Review XLII: 561-8. Geiss, I., ed. (1967). July 1914: The Outbreak of the First World War - Selected Documents. New York: Scribners. George, A. (1969). "The Operational Code: A Neglected Approach to the Study of Political Decision-Making," International Studies Quarterly 13: 190-222. Geyer, D. (1987). Russian Imperialism: The Interaction of Domestic and Foreign Policy, 1860-1914, translated by B. Little. New Haven: Yale University Press. Gibbard, A. (1973). "Manipulation of Voting Schemes," Econometrica 41: 587-601. Giffen, M. B. (1930). Fashoda: The Incident and Its Diplomatic Setting. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Gifford, P., and R. Louis. (1967). Britain and Germany in Africa: Imperial Rivalry and Colonial Rule. New Haven: Yale University Press. Gilpin, R. (1975). U.S. Power and the Multinational Corporation. New York: Basic Books. (1981). War and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (1987). The Political Economy of International Relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (1988). "The Theory of Hegemonic War," The Journal of Interdisciplinary History XVIII(4): 591-614. Girault, R. (1973). Emprunts russe et investissements francais en Russie, 1887-1914. Paris: A. Colin. (1979). Diplomatic europeene et imperialismes, 1871-1914. Paris: Masson. Glanville, J. L. (1934). Italy's Relations with England, 1896-1905. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Goerlitz, W. (1953). History of the German General Staff, 1657-1945, translated by B. Battershaw. New York: Praeger. Gooch, G. P. (1923). Franco-German Relations, 1871-1914. New York: Longmans, Green. Gooch, G. P., and H. Temperley, eds. (1926). British Documents on the Origin of the War, 1898-1914. 11 vols. London: H.M.S.O. Gooch, J. (1970). "The Origin and Development of the British and Imperial General Staffs to 1916." Ph.D. dissertation, University of London. Goode, J. H. (1971). "The Fashoda Crisis: A Survey of Anglo-French Imperial Policy on the Upper Nile Question, 1882-1899." Ph.D. dissertation, North Texas State University. Gordon, D. C. (1965). The Dominion Partnership in Imperial Defence, 1870-1914. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Gorianov, S. (1918). "The End of the Alliance of the Emperors," American Historical Review XXIII: 324-50. Gosses, F. (1948). The Management of British Foreign Policy Before the First World War, Especially During the Period 1880-1914. Leiden: Sijthoff. Graham, G. S. (1965). The Politics of Naval Supremacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Great Britain, War Office, Intelligence Division (1873,1882,1886). The Armed Strength of Russia. London: H.M.S.O. (1875). The Armed Strength of Italy. London: H.M.S.O. (1877). The Armed Strength of France. London: H.M.S.O. (1888). The Armed Strength of the German Empire. London: H.M.S.O. (1889, 1894, 1898, 1905). Handbook of the Russian Army. London: H.M.S.O. (1890). Handbook of the Russian Troops in Asia. London: H.M.S.O. (1891 and 1913). Handbook of the Italian Army. London: H.M.S.O. (1897 and 1900). Handbook of the German Army. London: H.M.S.O. (1901). Handbook of the French Army. London: H.M.S.O. Grenville, J. A. (1964). Lord Salisbury and Foreign Policy at the Close of the 19th Century. London: Athlone.
338
References and selected bibliography
(1968). "Les Accords coloniaux Franco-Anglais de 1904 et la Naissance de l'Entente Cordiale," Revue d'Histoire Diplomatique LXXXII: 315-57. Gulick, E. V. (1955). Europe's Classical Balance of Power. New York: Norton. Haas, E. (1953). "The Balance of Power: Prescription, Concept or Propaganda?" World Politics 5(4): 442-77. Hale, O. J. (1940). Publicity and Diplomacy. New York: Appleton-Century. Hallmann, H. (1927). Krugerdepesche und Flottenfrage. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer. Halperin, S. W. (1939). Italy and the Vatican at War. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Harcave, S. S. (1964). First Blood: The Russian Revolution of 1905. New York: Bodley Head. Harfield, A. G. (1978). "British Military Presence in Cyprus in the 19th Century," Journal of the Society for Army Historical Research LVI: 160-70. Hargreaves, J. D. (1951). "The Origins of the Anglo-French Military Conversations in 1905," History XXXVI: 244-8. (1953). "Entente Manquee: Anglo-French Relations, 1895-1896," Cambridge Historical Journal XI: 65-92. Harris, D. (1936). A Diplomatic History of the Balkan Crisis of 1875-1878: The First Year. Stanford (CA): Stanford University Press. (1939). Britain and the Bulgarian Horrors of 1876. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Harsanyi, J. (1968). "Games of Incomplete Information Played By Bayesian Players," Management Science 14: 486-502. (1969). "Rational Choice Models of Political Behavior vs. Functionalist and Conformist Theories," World Politics 21(4): 513-38. Harsanyi, J., and R. Selten (1988). A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games. Cambridge (MA): The MIT Press. Hart, J. (1976). "Three Approaches to the Measurement of Power in International Relations," International Organization 30: 289-305. Hazlehurst, C. (1971). Politicians at War, July 1914 to May 1915. New York: Knopf. Healey, B., and A. Stein (1973). "The Balance of Power in International History," Journal of Conflict Resolution 17: 1. Heller, E. (1925). Das Deutsch-Osterreichisch-ungarische Bundniss in Bismarcks Aussenpolitik. Berlin: E. S. Mittler & Sohn. (1926). "Bismarcks Stellung zur Fuehrung des Zweifrontenkrieges," Archiv fuer Politik und Geschichte VII: 677-98. Henderson, G. F. R. (1905). The Science of War. London: Longmans, Green. Henderson, W. O. (1938). "Germany's Trade with Her Colonies, 1884-1914," Economic History Review IX: 1-16. (1948). "German Economic Penetration in the Middle East, 1870-1914," Economic History Review XVIII: 54-64. Herz, J. H. (1959). International Politics in the Atomic Age. New York: Columbia University Press. Herzfeld, H. (1926). "Der deutsche Flottenbau und die englische Politik," Archiv fuer Politik und Geschichte VI: 97-146. Hilbert, L. W. (1954). "The Role of Military and Naval Attaches in the British and German Service, with Particular Reference to those in Berlin and London and their effect on Anglo-German Relations, 1871-1914." Ph.D. dissertation, Cambridge University. Hirschman, A. (1945,1980). National Power and the Structure of Foreign Trade. Berkeley (CA): University of California Press. Hittle, J. D. (1961). The Military Staff: Its History and Development. Harrisburg (PA): U.S. Army War College. Hoetzsch, O., ed. (1931). Die Internationalen Beziehungen im Zeitalter des Imperialisms. Berlin: R. Hobbing. Hoffman, R. J. S. (1964). Great Britain and German Trade Rivalry, 1875-1914. London: Oxford University Press. Holborn, H. (1926). Deutschland und die Tuerkei, 1878-1890. Berlin: Deutsche Verlagsgesellschaft fuer Politik und Geschichte. (1957). The Political Collapse of Europe. New York: Knopf.
References and selected bibliography
339
Holsti, K. J. (1967). International Politics: A Framework for Analysis. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall. Holsti, O. C. (1970). "The 'Operational Code' Approach to the Study of Political Leaders: John Foster Dulles' Philosophical and Instrumental Beliefs," Canadian Journal of Political Science 3(1): 123-57. (1972). Crisis, Escalation, and War. Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press. Holsti, O. C , and R. C. North (1966). "Comparative Data from Content Analysis: Perceptions of Hostility and Economic Variables in the 1914 Crisis," in Comparing Nations, edited by R. L. Merritt and S. Rokkan. New Haven: Yale University Press. Ibbeken, R. (1928). Das Aussenpolitische Problem in Staat und Wirtschaft in derdeutschen Reichspolitik, 1880-1914. Schleswig: J. Ibbeken. Imlah, A. H. (1950). "The Terms of Trade of the United Kingdom, 1798-1913," Journal of Economic History X: 170-94. Irvine, D. D. (1934). "French Military Policy and the Russian Alliance of 1891." Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania. Israel, L. (1938). England und der orientalische Dreibund, 1887-1896. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer. Jelavich, B. (1969). The Habsburg Empire in European Affairs, 1814-1918. Chicago: Rand McNally. Jervis, R. (1976). Perception and Misperception in International Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (1978). "Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma," World Politics 30: 167-214. (1986). "From Balance to Concert: A Study of International Security Cooperation," in Cooperation Under Anarchy, edited by K. A. Oye. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Joll, J. (1984). The Origins of the First World War. London: Longman. Jouan, R. (1932). Histoire de la Marine Francaise. Paris: Payot. Kagan, D. (1987). "World War I, World War II, World War III," Commentary (March): 21-40. Kaplan, M. (1957). "Balance of Power, Bipolarity, and Other Models," American Political Science Review 51: 3. (1969). Macropolitics: Selected Essays on the Philosophy and Science of Politics. Chicago: Aldine. (1979). Towards Professionalism in International Theory: Macrosystem Analysis. New York: The Free Press. Karsten, P., P. D. Howell, and A. F. Allen (1984). Military Threats: A Systematic Historical Analysis of the Determinants of Success. Westport (CN): Greenwood Press. Kashkarov, M. P. (1896). Denezhnoye Obrashcheniye v Rossii. St. Petersburg: Gosudarstvennaya Tipographiya. Kehr, E. (1933). Schlachtflottenbau und Parteipolitik. Berlin: E. Ebering. Keiger, J. F. V. (1983). France and the Origins of the First World War. New York: St. Martin's Press. Kennedy, P. M. (1976). The Rise and Fall of British Naval Mastery. New York: Scribners. (1979). The War Plans of the Great Powers, 1880-1914. London: Allen and Unwin. (1987). The Rise and Fall of the Great Powers. New York: Random House. Keohane, R. O. (1984). After Hegemony. Princeton: Princeton University Press, ed. (1986). Neorealism and Its Critics. New York: Columbia University Press. Keohane, R. O., and J. S. Nye (1977). Power and Interdependence. Boston: Little, Brown. Khromov, P. A. (1950). Ekonomicheskoe razvitie Rossii v XIX-XX vekakh, 1800-1917. Moscow: Gospolitizdat. Kitchen, M. (1968). The German Officer Corps, 1890-1914. New York: Clarendon Press. (1973). "Army and Society in the Wilhelmine Era," Laurentian University Review V: 49-65. Knorr, K. (1956). The War Potential of Nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (1970). Military Power and Potential. Cambridge (MA): D. C. Heath. Kosev, K. (1976). "The Uprising of April 1876 in Bulgaria," Bulgarian Historical Review IV: 24-46.
340
References and selected bibliography
Kreps, D., and R. Wilson (1982). "Sequential Equilibrium," Econometrica, 50: 863-94. Kuhn, T. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kumpf-Korfes, S. (1968). Bismarcks "Draht nach Russland." Berlin, GDR: AkademieVerlag. Kuropatkin, G. N. (1909). The Russian Army and the Japanese War. London: J. Murray. Langer, W. L. (1929). The Franco-Russian Alliance, 1890-1894. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. (1950). European Alliances and Alignments, 1871-1890. New York: Knopf. (1951). The Diplomacy of Imperialism, 1890-1902. New York: Knopf. Laqueur, W. (1965). Russia and Germany: A Century of Conflict. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Leaman, B. R. (1942). "The Influence of Domestic Policy on Foreign Affairs in France, 1898-1905," Journal of Modern History 4(14): 449ff. Lebow, R. N. (1981). Between War and Peace. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. (1984). "Windows of Opportunity: Do States Always Jump Through Them?" International Security 9(1): 147-86. Lee, D. W. (1934). Great Britain and the Cyprus Convention. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Leidner, F. (1936). Die Aussenpolitik Osterreich-Ungarns, 1870-1879. Halle: Akademischer Verlag. Leites, N. (1951). The Operational Code of the Politburo. New York: McGraw-Hill. Lepsius, J., A. Mendelssohn-Bartholdy, and F. Thimme (1922-1927). Die Grosse Politik der Europaischen Kabinette, 1871-1914. 40 vols. Berlin: Deutsche Verlagsgesellschaft fuer Politik und Geschichte. Levy, J. S. (1983a). War in the Modern Great Power System, 1495-1975. Lexington (KY): The University of Kentucky Press. (1983b). "Misperception and the Causes of War: Theoretical Linkages and Analytical Problems," World Politics 36: 76-99. (1984). "Theories of General War," Mimeo. University of Texas at Austin. (1987). "Declining Power and the Prevention Motivation," World Politics 40: 82-107. (1988). "The Role of Crisis Management in the Outbreak of World War I," paper delivered at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Washington, D.C. Liddell-Hart, B. H. (1967). "French Military Ideas Before the First World War," in A Century of Conflict, 1850-1950: Essays for Alan J. P. Taylor, edited by Martin Gilbert, pp. 133-48. New York: Atheneum. Liebold, R. (1930). Die Stellung Englands in der russich-tuerkischen Krise von 1875-1878. Wilkau: Buchdruckerei F. K. Zschiesche. Lieven, D. C. B. (1983). Russia and the Origins of the First World War. New York: St. Martin's Press. Lincoln, W. B. (1973). "Russia and the European Revolutions of 1848," History Today XXIII: 53-9. Lindblom, C. (1965). The Intelligence of Democracy. New York: Free Press. Ling, D. L. (1955). "The French Occupation and Administration of Tunisia, 1881-1892." Ph.D. dissertation, University of Illinois. Liska, G. (1977). International Equilibrium: A Theoretical Essay on the Politics and Organization of Security. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Lowe, C. J. (1967a). The Reluctant Imperialist: British Foreign Policy, 1878-1902. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (1967b). The Reluctant Imperialist: The Documents. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Luce, R. D., and H. Raiffa (1957). Games and Decisions. New York: Wiley. Mac kinder, H. J. (1962). Democratic Ideals and Reality. New York: Norton. Manchester, W. (1964). The Arms of Krupp, 1587-1968. Boston: Little, Brown. Maoz, Z. (1982). Paths to Conflict: International Disputes Initiation: 1816-1976. Boulder (CO): West view Press.
References and selected bibliography
341
(1983). "Resolve, Capabilities, and the Outcome of Interstate Disputes, 1816-1976," Journal of Conflict Resolution 27(2): 195-230. Marder, A. J. (1940). British Naval Policy, 1880-1905. London: Putnam. (1961). From Dreadnought to Scapa Flow: The Royal Navy in the Fisher Era, 1904-1919. London: Oxford University Press. (1964). The Anatomy of British Sea Power: A History of British Naval Policy in the PreDreadnought Era, 1880-1905. London: Cass. Marriott, J. A. (1956). The Eastern Question. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Martens, T. T. (1879). Russia and England in Central Asia. London: Ridgeway. Mathews, J. J. (1939). Egypt and the Formation of the Anglo-French Entente. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Maurice, F. B. (1905). The Russo-Turkish War, 1877: A Strategical Sketch. London: S. Sonnenschein. Maurice, J. F. (1888). The Balance of Military Power in Europe: An Examination of the War Resources of Great Britain and the Continental States. London: Tauchnitz. May, A. (1961). The Habsburg Monarchy, 1867-1914. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Mayer, A. J. (1969). "Internal Causes and Purposes of War in Europe, 1870-1956: A Research Assignment," Journal of Modern History XLI: 291-303. Mayhew, D. R. (1974). Congress: The Electoral Connection. New Haven: Yale University Press. Maynard-Smith, J. (1974). "The Theory of Games and the Evolution of Animal Conflicts," Journal of Theoretical Biology 47: 209-21. McClellan, D. (1971). "The 'Operational Code' Approach to the Study of Political Leaders: Dean Acheson's Philosophical and Instrumental Beliefs," Canadian Journal of Political Science 4(1): 52-75. McDermott, J. (1974). "The Revolution in British Military Thinking from the Boer War to the Moroccan Crisis," Canadian Journal of History IX: 159-78. McHardy, C. M. (1897). The British Navy for 100 Years. London: The Navy League. McKay, D. V. (1939). "The French Acquisition of Tunis." Ph.D. dissertation, Cornell University. McKelvey, R. D. (1976). "Intransitivities in Multidimensional Voting Models and Some Implications for Agenda Control," Journal of Economic Theory 45: 472-82. (1979). "General Conditions for Global Intransitivities in Formal Voting Models," Econometrica 47(5): 1085-1112. McKelvey, R. D., and P. C. Ordeshook (1977). "Competitive Coalition Theory," in Game Theory and Political Science, edited by P. Ordeshook. New York: New York University Press. (1984). "An Experimental Study of the Effects of Procedural Rules on Committee Behavior," Journal of Politics 46: 182-205. McKelvey, R. D., P. C. Ordeshook, and M. Winer (1978). "The Competitive Solution for Az-Person Games Without Transferable Utility With an Application to Committee Games," American Political Science Review 72: 599-615. McKelvey, R. D., and T. Page (1986). "Common Knowledge, Consensus, and Aggregate Information," Econometrics 54(1): 109-27. McNeill, W. H. (1982). The Pursuit of Power: Technology, Armed Force, and Society Since A.D. 1000. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Medlicott, W. N. (1926). "The Mediterranean Agreements of 1887," Slavonic Review V: 66-88. (1929). "Diplomatic Relations After the Congress of Berlin," Slavonic Review VIII: 66-79. (1938). The Congress of Berlin and After. London: Metheun. (1945). "Bismarck and the Three Emperor's Alliance, 1881-1887," Transactions of the Royal Historical Society XXVII: 61-83. (1956). Bismarck, Gladstone and the Concert of Europe. London: Athlone. Meinecke, F. (1927). Geschichte des deutsch-englischen Buendnisproblems, 1890-1901. Munich: Oldenbourg.
342
References and selected bibliography
Meinke, B. (1938). "Beitraege zur fruehesten Geschichte des Militaereisenbahnwesens/Mrchivfuer Eisenbahnwesen, 293-319. Merrill, J. N. (1956). "British-French Amphibious Operations in the Sea of Azov, 1855," Military Affairs XX: 16-27. Michalik, B. (1931). Probleme des deutschen Flottenbaues. Breslau: Marcus. Midlarsky, M. (1981). "Equilibria in the Nineteenth-Century Balance of Power System," American Journal of Political Science 25: 270-96. Mitchell, B. R. (1975). European Historical Statistics, 1750-1970. New York: Columbia University Press. Mitchell, P. B. (1935). The Bismarckian Policy of Conciliation with France, 1875-1885. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Modelski, G. (1983). "Long Cycles of World Leadership," in Contending Approaches to World System Analysis, edited by W. R. Thompson. Beverly Hills (CA): Sage Publications. Mommsen, W. (1966). "The Debate on German War Aims," Journal of Contemporary History 1(3): 47-72. Monger, G. W. (1963). The End of Isolation: British Foreign Policy, 1900-1907. New York: Nelson. Moon, H. R. (1968). "The Invasion of the United Kingdom: Public Controversy and Official Planning, 1888-1918." Ph.D. dissertation, University of London. Morgenthau, H. J. (1959, 1966, 1973). Politics Among Nations. New York: Knopf. Morley, J. Viscount (1928). Memorandum on Resignation, August 1914. London: Macmillan. Morris, P. (1975). "The Russians in Central Asia, 1870-1887," Slavonic and Eastern European Review LIII: 521-38. Muller-Link, H. (1977). Industrialisierung und Aussenpolitik: Preussen-Deutschland und das Zarenreich, 1860-1890. Goettingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht. Muller, M. (1927). Die Bedeutung des Berliner Kongresses fuer die deutsche-russichen Beziehungen. Leipzig: R. Noske. Murphy, J. (1976). "The Evolution of the General Staff Concept," Defense Management Journal XII: 34-9. Myatt, F. (1974). The Soldier's Trade: British Military Developments, 1660-1914. London: MacDonald and Jane's. Napier, C. S. (1920a). "Strategic Movement by Rail in 1914," Journal of the Royal United Service Institute LXXX: 69-93, 361-80. (1920b). "Strategic Movement over Damaged Railways in 1914," Journal of the Royal United Service Institute LXXXI: 315-46. Niemi, R. (1969). "Majority Decision Making with Partial Unidimensionality," American Political Science Review 63: 489-97. Niou, E. M. S., and P. C. Ordeshook (1985). "Universalism in Congress "American Journal of Political Science 29(2): 246-58. (1986). "A Theory of the Balance of Power in International Systems," Journal of Conflict Resolution 30(4) (December): 685-715. (1987). "Preventive War and the Balance of Power: A Game Theoretic Analysis," Journal of Conflict Resolution 31(3) (September): 387-419. (1988). "An Experimental Test of a Theory of the Balance of Power," Simulation and Games 19(4): 415-39. (1989a). "The Geographical Imperatives of the Balance of Power in 3-Country Systems," Mathematical and Computer Modelling 12(4/5): 519-31. (1989b). "Stability in International Systems and the Costs of War," in Models of Strategic Choice in Politics, edited by P. Ordeshook. Ann Arbor (MI): The University of Michigan Press, in press. (1989c). Stability in Anarchic International Systems. Mimeo, California Institute of Technology. Niskanen, W. (1971). Bureaucracy and Representative Government. Chicago: Aldine.
References and selected bibliography
343
Olson, M. (1965). The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Olson, M., and R. Zeckhauser (1966). "An Economic Theory of Alliances," The Review of Economics and Statistics 48: 266-79. Ordeshook, P. C. (1986). Game Theory and Political Theory. New York: Cambridge University Press. Ordeshook, P. C , and T. Palfrey (1988). "Strategic Voting, Incomplete Information, and Signaling in Agendas," American Journal of Political Science 32(2): 441-66. Organski, A. F. K. (1968). World Politics. New York: Knopf. Organski, A. F. K., and J. Kugler (1980). The War Ledger. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Owen, G. (1982). Game Theory. Orlando (FL): Academic Press. Oye, K. A. (1986). Cooperation Under Anarchy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Pearson, F. S. (1974). "Geographic Proximity and Foreign Military Intervention," Journal of Conflict Resolution 18(3): 432-60. Perkins, E. J. (1953). "The Military Staff: Its History and Development," Canadian Army Journal VII: 25-35. Perry, E. W. (1949). "The General Staff System," Canadian Army Journal III: 27-30. Pierce, R. A. (I960). Russian Central Asia, 1867-1917: A Study in Colonial Rule. Berkeley (CA): University of California Press. Platt, D. C. M. (1968). Finance, Trade and Politics in British Foreign Policy, 1815-1914. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Poidevin, R. (1970). Finances et relations internationales, 1887-1914. Paris: A. Colin. Poidevin, R., and J. Bariety (1977). Les relations franco-allemandes, 1815-1975. Paris: A. Colin. Powell, R. (1987). "Crisis Bargaining, Escalation, and MAD" American Political Science Review 81(3): 717-35. (1988). "Nuclear Brinksmanship with Two-Sided Incomplete Information," American Political Science Review 82(1): 155-78. Pratt, E. A. (1916). The Rise of Rail-Power in War and Conquest, 1833-1914. London: P. S. King & Son. Preston, A. W. (1964). "British Military Thought, 1856-1890," Army Quarterly LXXXIX: 57-74. Pribram, A. F. (1920). The Secret Treaties of Austria-Hungary. 2 vols. London: Oxford University Press. (1923). Austrian Foreign Policy, 1908-1918. London: Allen & Unwin. (1931). England and the International Policy of the European Great Powers, 1871-1914. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (1951). Austria-Hungary and Great Britain, 1908-1914. London: Oxford University Press. Quester, G. (1977). Offense and Defense in the International System. New York: Wiley. Raab, G. (1923). Der deutsch-russische Ruckversicherungsvertag in dem System der Bismarckschen Politik, vornehmlich des Jahres 1887. Wetzlar. Rachfahl, F. (1920). "Der Ruckversicherungsvertag, der 'Balkandreibund' und das angebliche Buendnisangebot Bismarcks an England vom Jahre 1887," Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv XVI: 28-81. Ralston, D. B. (1967). The Army of the Republic: The Place of the Military in the Political Evolution of France, 1871-1914. Cambridge (MA): The MIT Press. Rath, R. J. (1957). The Viennese Revolution of 1848. Austin (TX): University of Texas Press. Ray, J. (1979). Global Politics. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Remak, J. (1959). Sarajevo. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. (1967). The Origins of World War 1,1870-1914. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Renouvin, P. (1934). "Les Engagements de l'Alliance Franco-Russe: Leur Evolution de 1891 a 1914," Revue d'Historie de la Guerre Mondiale XII: 297-310.
344
References and selected bibliography
(1955). Histoire des relations Internationales, Vol. VI: 1871-1914. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Repington, C. A. (1920). The First World War, 1914-1918. London: Constable and Co. Richmond, H. W. (1941). The Invasion of Britain: An Account of Plans, Attempts and Countermeasures from 1586 to 1918. London: Methuen. Riker, W. H. (1962). The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press. (1964). Federalism: Origin, Operation, Maintenance. Boston: Little, Brown. (1980). "Implications from the Disequilibrium of Majority Rule for the Study of Institutions," American Political Science Review 74: 432-46. (1982). Liberalism Against Populism. San Francisco: W. Freeman. Riker, W. H., and P. Ordeshook (1973). An Introduction to Positive Political Theory. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall. Ritter, G. (1929). Die Legende von der Verschmahten englischen Freundschaft. Freiburg: Universitaetsbuchdruckerei E. Gross. (1958). The Schlieffen Plan: Critique of a Myth, translated by A. and E. Wilson. London: O. Wolff. (1962a). "Griff nach der Weltmacht?" Luebecker Nachrichten (May 20). (1962b). "Eine neue Kriegsschuldthese? Zu Fritz Fischers Buch 'Griff nach der Weltmacht,'" Historische Zeitschrift 194(4): 646-68. Roloff, G. (1929). "Die Buendnisverhandlungen zeischen Deutschland und England, 18981901," Berliner Monatshefte, 1167-1222. Rose, G. F. (1986). "Revolution, Culture and Collective Action," Journal of Political Science XIV: 25-32. Rosecrance, R. N. (1963). Action and Reaction in World Politics. Boston: Little, Brown. (1986). The Rise of the Trading State. New York: Basic Books. Rosecrance, R. N., A. Alexandroff, B. Healy, and A. Stein (1974). Power, Balance of Power, and Status in Nineteenth Century International Relations. Beverly Hills (CA): Sage Publications. Roth, A. E. (1985). Game-theoretic Models of Bargaining. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rothenberg, G. E. (1975). "The Army of Austria-Hungary, 1868-1918: A Case Study of a Multi-Ethnic Force," in New Dimensions in Military History, edited by Russell F. Weigley, pp. 242-54. San Rafael (CA): Presidio Press. (1976a). The Army of Francis Joseph. West Lafayette (IN): Purdue University Press. (1976b). "Nobility and Military Careers: The Habsburg Officer Corps, 1740-1914," Military Affairs XL: 182-6. Rupp, G. H. (1941). A Wavering Friendship: Russia and Austria, 1876-1878. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Sabrosky, A. N. (1975). "From Bosnia to Sarajevo: A Comparative Discussion of Interstate Crisis," Journal of Conflict Resolution 19: 57-74. Salvemini, G. (1944). La Politica Estera delVItalia, 1871-1914. Florence: G. Barbera. Satterthwaite, M. A. (1975). "Strategy-Proofness and Arrow's Conditions: Existence and Correspondence Theorems for Voting Procedures and Social Welfare Functions," Journal of Economic Theory 10(2): 187-217. Schmitt, B. E. (1930). The Coming of the War. 2 vols. New York: Scribners. (1934). Triple Alliance and Triple Entente. New York: Holt. Schroeder, P. W. (1977). "Quantitative Studies in the Balance of Power: An Historian's Reaction," Journal of Conflict Resolution 21(1): 1-22. Schuecking, W., and M. Montgelas, eds. (1919). DieDeutschen Dokumente zum Kriegsausbruch. 2 vols. Berlin: Deutsche Zerlagsgesellschaft fuer Politik und Geschichte. Schulze-Gaevernitz, G. (1899). Volkswirtschaftliche Studien aus Russland. Leipzig: Duncker und Humbolt. Schurman, D. M. (1955). "Imperial Defence, 1868-1887." Ph.D. dissertation, University of London. Seager, F. H. (1969). The Boulanger Affair: Political Crossroad of France, 1886-1889. Ithaca (NY): Cornell University Press.
References and selected bibliography
345
Seaton, A. (1973). The Army of the German Empire, 1870-1888. Reading (UK): Osprey. Seton-Watson, H. (1967). The Russian Empire, 1801-1917. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Seton-Watson, R. W. (1972). Disraeli, Gladstone and the Eastern Question. New York: Norton. Shapely, L., and M. Shubik (1954). "A Model for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System," American Political Science Review 48: 787-92. Shaw, G. C. (1938). Supply in Modern War. London: Faber and Faber. Shepsle, K., and B. Weingast (1981). "Structure-Induced Equilibrium and Legislative Choice," Public Choice 37(3): 503-19. (1984). "When Do Rules of Procedure Matter," Journal of Politics 46(1): 206-23. Showalter, D. E. (1976). Railroads and Rifles: Soldiers, Technology, and the Unification of Germany. Hamden (CN): Archon Press. Shubik, M. (1985). Game Theory in the Social Sciences. Cambridge (MA): The MIT Press. Simowitz, R. (1982). The Logical Consistency and Soundness of the Balance of Power Theory. Denver (CO): University of Denver Press. Singer, J. D. (1961). "The Level of Analysis Problem," World Politics 14(1): 77-92. (1980). The Correlates of War, Vol. II. 2 vols. New York: Free Press. Singer, J. D., S. A. Bremer, and J. Stuckey (1972). "Capability Distribution, Uncertainty, and Major Power War, 1820-1965," in Peace, War, and Numbers, edited by B. M. Russett, pp. 19-48. Beverly Hills (CA): Sage Publications. Singer, J. D., and M. Small (1966). "Formal Alliance, 1815-1939: A Quantitative Description," Journal of Peace Research 3: 1-32. (1972). The Wages of War, 1816-1969: A Statistical Handbook. New York: Wiley. Siverson, R. M., and M. Sullivan (1983). "The Distribution of Power and the Onset of War," Journal of Conflict Resolution 27: 473-94. Siverson, R. M., and M. R. Tennefoss (1984). "Power, Alliance, and the Escalation of International Conflict: 1815-1965," American Political Science Review 78: 1057-69. Skazkin, S. (1928). Konets Avstro-Russko-Germanskogo Soiuza: 1879-1884. Moscow: Ranion. Skelley, A. R. (1977). The Victorian Army at Home: The Recruitment and Terms and Conditions of the British Regular, 1859-1899. London: Croom Helm. Small, M., and J. D. Singer (1970). "Patterns in International Warfare, 1816-1965? Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Sciences 391: 145-55. Smart, I. (1975). "The Great Engines: The Rise and Decline of a Nuclear Age," International Affairs 51: 544-53. Smyser, W. M. (1947). "Algeciras to Agadir: Franco-German Antagonism Before the First World War." M.A. thesis, Georgetown University. Snidal, D. (1986). "The Game Theory of International Politics," in Cooperation Under Anarchy, edited by K. A. Oye. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Snyder, G. H., and P. Diesing (1977). Conflict Among Nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Snyder, R. C , H. W. Bruck, and B. Sapin (1962). Foreign Policy Decision-Making. New York: Free Press. Sonntag, R. J. (1938). Germany and England: Background of Conflict, 1848-1894. New York: Appleton-Century. Spykman, N. J. (1944). The Geography of the Peace. New York: Harcourt, Brace. Ssuma, C. (80 B.C.). The Historical Records. Shih Chi. Stearns, P. N. (1974). 1848: The Revolutionary Tide in Europe. New York: Norton. Steinberg, J. (1965). Yesterday's Deterrent: Tirpitz and the Birth of the German Battle Fleet. New York: Macmillan. Steiner, Z. (1970). The Foreign Office and Foreign Policy, 1898-1914. New York: Cambridge University Press. Stevens, G. W. (1896). Naval Policy. London: The Naval League. Stojanovic, M. D. (1939). The Great Powers and the Balkans, 1875-1878. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
346
References and selected bibliography
Stone, N. (1966). "Army and Society in the Habsburg Monarchy, 1900-1914," Past and Present XXXIII: 95-111. Stuart, G. H. (1921). French Foreign Policy from Fashoda to Serajevo, 1898-1914. New York: Century. Summerton, N. W. (1970). "The Development of British Military Planning for a War Against Germany, 1904-1914." Ph.D. dissertation, University of London. Sumner, B. H. (1937). Russia and the Balkans, 1870-1880. Hamdem (CN): Archon Books. (1942). Tsardom and Imperialism in the Far East and Middle East, 1880-1914. London: H. Milford. Taylor, A. J. P. (1941). The Habsburg Monarchy, 1809-1918: A History of the Austrian Empire and Austria-Hungary. London: H. Hamilton. (1954). The Struggle for Mastery in Europe, 1848-1918. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (1967). Germany's First Bid for Colonies, 1881-1885: A Move in Bismarck's European Policy. Hamden (CN): Archon Press. Taylor, M. (1976). Anarchy and Cooperation. New York: Wiley. Thucydides (1954). The Peloponnesian War, translated by R. Warner. London: Cassell. Towle, P. (1974). "The European Balance of Power in 1914," Army Quarterly 104: 332-42. (1971). "The Russo-Japanese War and British Military Thought," Journal of the Royal United Service Institute CXVI: 64-8. Trainor, L. (1969). "The Liberals and the Formation of Imperial Defence Policy, 18921895," Bulletin of the Institute of Historical Research XLII: 188-200. (1975). "The European State System and the Origins of the First World War, 1903-1915," New Zealand Journal of History IX: 171-8. Tramond, J. M., and A. Reussner (1924). Elements d'Histoire Maritime et Coloniale Contemporaine. Paris: Societe d'editions geographiques, maritimes etcoloniales. Tucker, A. (1963). "Army and Society in England, 1870-1900: A Reassessment of the Cardwell Reforms," Journal of British Studies II: 110-41. Turner, L. C. F. (1965). "The Role of the General Staffs in July 1914," Australian Journal of Politics and History XI: 305-23. Tyler, J. A. (1938). The British Army and the Continent, 1904-1914. London: E. Arnold. Van Creveld, M. (1977). Supplying War: Logistics from Wallenstein to Patton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Veal, D. A. E. (1917). "British and German Imperialism Compared," Empire Review XXXI: 299-307. Villate, R. (1927). "L'Etat materiel des armees allemandes en Aout et Septembre 1914," Revue d'Histoire de la Guerre Mondiale IV: 310-26. Viner, J. (1929). "International Finance and Balance of Power Diplomacy, 1880-1914," Southwestern Political and Social Science Quarterly IX: 407-51. Von Bernhardi, F. (1912). On War Today. London: H. Rees. Von Geyr, L. (1962). "The German General Staff. Part I: The Imperial Period," Military Review XLII: 19-32. Von Kuhl, H. (1920). Der deutsche Generalstab in Vorbereitung und Durchfuehrung des Weltkrieges. Berlin: E. S. Mittler & Sohn. Von Schonberg, A. F. (1933). Um den Twopowerstandard: Englische Flottenpolitik, 18801895. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer. Von Wahlde, P. (1966). "Military Thought in Imperial Russia." Ph.D. dissertation, Indiana University. Wadman, D. C. (1939). "The Anglo-French and Anglo-Belgian Military and Naval Conversations from the 'Entente' to the Great War." M.A. thesis, University of Wales. Wagner, R. H. (1983). "The Theory of Games and the Problem of International Cooperation," American Political Science Review 77(2): 330-46. (1986). "The Theory of Games and the Balance of Power," World Politics 38(4): 546-76. (1988). Uncertainty, Rational Learning, and Bargaining in the Cuban Missile Crisis. Mimeo. University of Texas at Austin. Walder, D. (1973). The Short Victorious War: The Russo-Japanese Conflict, 1904-1905. New York: Harper & Row.
References and selected bibliography
347
Walker, R. L. (1953). The Multi-State System of Ancient China. Hamden (CN): The Shoe String Press. Walker, S. G. (1977). "The Interface Between Beliefs and Behavior: Henry Kissinger's Operational Code and the Vietnam War," Journal of Conflict Resolution 21(1): 129-68. Wallace, M. D. (1973). War and Rank Among Nations. Lexington (MA): Lexington Books. Walsh, W. B. (1957). "The Imperial Russian General Staff and India," Russian Review XVI: 53-8. Walt, S. M. (1987). The Origins of Alliances. Ithaca (NY): Cornell University Press. Waltz, K. (1959). Man, the State, and War. New York: Columbia University Press. (1979). Theory of International Politics. Reading (MA): Addison-Wesley. (1988). "The Origins of War in Neorealist Theory," The Journal of Interdisciplinary History XVIII(4): 615-28. Warner, D., and P. Warner (1974). The Tide at Sunrise: A History of the Russo-Japanese War. New York: Charterhouse. Weber, F. G. (1970). Eagles on the Crescent: Germany, Austria, and the Diplomacy of the Turkish Alliance, 1914-1918. Ithaca (NY): Cornell University Press. Wedel, O. H. (1932). Austro-German Diplomatic Relations, 1908-1914. Stanford (CA): Stanford University Press. Wehler, H. U., ed. (1970). Krisenherde des Kaiserreiches, 1871-1918. Goettingen:Berg. Weingast, B. R. (1979). "A Rational Choice Perspective on Congressional Norms," American Journal of Political Science 25: 96-111. Wheeler, G. (1956). "The Russians in Central Asia," History Today VI: 172-80. Whittam, J. R. (1976). The Politics of the Italian Army, 1861-1918. Hamden (CN): Archon Press. Wienefeld, R. H. (1929). Franco-German Relations, 1878-1885. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Wight, M. (1973). "The Balance of Power and International Order," in The Bases of International Order, edited by A. James. London: Oxford University Press. Williams, B. J. (1966). "The Strategic Background to the Anglo-Russian Entente of August 1907," Historical Journal IX: 360-73. Williamson, S. R. (1969). The Politics of Grand Strategy: Britain and France Prepare for War, 1904-1914. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Wohlforth, W. C. (1987). "The Perception of Power," World Politics 39(3): 353-81. Wolf, P. (1978). "International Social Structure and the Resolution of International Conflicts, 1920-1965," in Research in Social Movements, Conflicts and Change, edited by L. Kreisberg, Vol. 1. Greenwich (CN): JAI Press. Woodward, E. L. (1935). Great Britain and the German Navy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Wright, P. (1972). Conflict on the Nile: The Fashoda Incident of 1898. London: Heinemann. Wright, Q. (1942). A Study of War. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Young, I. (1957). "The Russians in Hungary, 1849," History Today VII: 236-42. Young, O. (1979). Compliance and Public Authority. Washington, D.C.: Resources for the Future. Zechlin, E. (1964). "Deutschland zwischen Kabinettskrieg und Wirtschaftkrieg: Politik und Kriegfuehrung in den ersten Monaten des Weltkrieges 1914," Historische Zeitschrift 199(2): 247-458. Zinnes, D. (1967). "An Analytical Study of the Balance of Power Theories," Journal of Peace Research 4: 270-88. (1970). "Coalition Theories and the Balance of Power," in The Study of Coalition Behavior, edited by S. Groennings, E. W. Kelley, and M. Leiserson. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Zuckermann, S. (1915). Der Warenaustausch zwischen Russlands und Deutschland. Berlin: Russische Kurier.
Index Adair, R. K.,272 Adams, M., 246n Addington, L.H., 227n agenda setter, 14 Albertini, L., 301 Alfoldi, L. M., 227n Alexander of Battenberg, 279, 284 Allen, A. F., 95n Allen, F. S., 239n Allen, W. E. D., 256n, 333 alliance, see coalitions Allison, G., 15, 151n Alsace-Lorraine, 211, 218, 236 Alt, J., 20, 59 Altham, E. A.,227n altruism, 18 anarchy: and cooperation, 20-1, 68-72, 92-3n; and domestic politics, lOn, 20-2; in international politics, lOn, 16, 20-2, 187, 311-12 Anderson, D. P., 333 Anderson, O., 239n Anderson, P., 246n Andrassy, Hungarian prime minister, 273-4 Andrew, C. M., 238n, 258n Aron, H., 76n Arrow, K., 14-16, 37-8 Arrow's Theorem, 14, 37-8, 73 Askew, W. C , 226n, 238n, 251n Asquith, British prime minister, 265, 299-300 attack group, 133 Aumann, R. J., 60, 87n, 90 Austen-Smith, D., 59 Austria (also Austria-Hungary): 77, 91, 100, 119, 197, 217, 235-66, 272-310, 332; conflicts with Russia, 234, 241-2, 247, 250, 254, 261-3, 276-7, 279-80, 284-6, 289-97; and Dual Alliance, 256-7; importance of Danube, 241-2, 276-8, 284-5; as instigator of war, 310; League of Three Emperors, 240-1, 261-2; mobilization of, 297; resources of, 230-2, 241; ultimatum to Serbia, 291-4, 297-8 Austro-German Alliance: 206; Austrian incentives, 246-8; and British neutrality, 245, 247; and France, 244-6; German incentives, 244-6; and geography, 246-7; and Great Britain, 245-8; intent,
244, 303-4; relative resources of, 264; and Russia, 244-8 Axelrod, R., 20, 68n, 69n Aydelotte, W. O., 246n Bairoch, P., 233 balance of power: and alliances, 48, 91, 96, 123, 129, 159, 221-2, 259-66, 314-16; and balance of threats, 91n, 316; and balancer, 188-9, 202, 207-12; and bandwagoning, 66, 314; bipolar systems, 78-9, 85, 94-6, 102-3, 107, 127-30, 194-5, 211, 221-2, 264-5, 313-14; and coalitions, 39, 46-8, 63, 66, 96, 129, 172-4,187, 221-3, 259-66; and collective security, 159-60; and common knowledge, 182; conditions for, 63n, 65, 72-3, 94-9; and cooperation, 21-3; and the core, 64n, 75, 125; definitions, 28-9, 36, 48, 75, 77, 82, 97, 117; differences with, 316; and economic goals, 326, 332; European, 22, 34, 85, 215, 223-4, 253, 259-66, 271, 298; general relevance, 28, 123; and geography, 188-9, 331; as a goal, 9-10, 28-9, 96; and investment, 147; local, 83-4; and number of countries, 95,102; and peripheral powers, 193, 206-7; policy of Ho Tsung in China, 174; and power transition, 147; and resource stability, 61-7,115-17,127, 222; and resource transfers, 48n, 55n, 101-2, 129; and resources, 64-5,123, 130,187-8, 221, 313, 316; and rules, 21-3; and self-help systems, 82,164; and small states, 81; and sovereignty, 61-3,106, 120; and stability, 20-3; and systemstability, 21-7, 29, 32-4, 61-7, 81-4, 91-9, 101, 127, 313-17, 331-2; and threats, 91,147, 221, 316; and uncertainty, 59-61; and war, 103,116, 201, 312, 316-17; and war costs, 52 balance of threats, 91n, 316 balancer: 34, 66-7,188-9, 200-4, 207-12, 252-3, 259-60, 263, 265, 271-2, 281-3, 287, 309, 320, 327, 329; advantages of, 204, 313; and balance of power, 188-9, 202, 207-12; and Britain, 34, 188, 197, 201-4, 208-11, 223, 252-3, 260, 263, 265, 271-2, 281, 283, 287, 309; conditions for, 193, 200-3; and the core, 204; examples,
350
Index
balancer (cont.) 207-12; and geography, 201-11, 252, 313; and United States, 197, 203, 206, 211-12, 320, 327-9; uniqueness of, 202-3; and war, 103, 116, 201, 316-17 Balck, W., 227n Bald, D., 246n Baldwin, D. A., 45n, 224 Balkans, 207, 234-5, 242, 244n, 249, 253-4, 257, 261-3, 273-6, 278-9, 280, 282-5, 287-95, 299, 304-9, 326, 330 bandwagoning, 66, 314 Barclay, G., 238n, 251n bargaining set, 7n, 86-7, 89-90, 109 bargaining, 118-19 Bariety, J.,238n Bark, Russian finance minister, 292-3 Batum, 275, 278 Becker, S., 247n, 256n Beckett, I. F. W., 229n Belgium: 151, 299-300, 315, 332; neutrality of, 300, 309 beliefs, 58-9 Benjamin, H. C , 237n Berchtold, Austrian foreign minister, 289, 302 Berlin Memorandum, 273 Besika Bay, 274, 276 Bessarabia, 274-5, 278 best response, 5-6 Bethmann-Hollweg, German chancellor, 289n, 302, 315 Binmore, K., 92n bipolar systems: 111, 211, 319; and alliances, 221-2, 264-5, 313-14; and balance of power, 78-9, 85, 94-6, 102-3, 107, 127, 130, 194-5, 211, 221-2, 264-5, 31314; and current world order, 330-1; and geography, 195, 198-9; relative stability of, 78-9, 85, 102-3, 314, 329; and resource stability, 78-9, 127-8; and system stability, 95, 102-3, 110-12, 127-8, 194-5, 319, 321-2, 328, 331 bipolarization of systems, 130, 313 Birch, R. C , 248n, 252n Bismarck, Otto, 30, 123, 206, 234-7, 260, 273, 276, 280, 282-8, 303, 313, 326 Bittner, L., 289, 291, 294 Black, D., 15 Blainey, G., 7n, 17, 55n, 59-62, 63n, 103, 317 Blaisdell, D. C , 242n Bond, B., 227n, 239n Bontwesch, B., 305 Bosnia, 236, 273-6, 278, 291 Bosworth, R. J. B., 238n, 251n Boulding, K., 190n
Bourgeois, E., 251 Bourne, K., 239n, 252n Bovykin, V. I., 255n Boyd, R.,68n Brams, S., 86 Bremer, S. A., 95n, 178, 224, 229-30, 266 Bridges, R., vii Britain, see Great Britain Brodie, B., 33, 149 Brown, R. G., 258n Bruck, H.W.,15 Brunschwig, H., 238n Budapest conventions, 262, 274-6, 278 Bueno de Mesquita, B., vii, 1, 11, 14-16, 37, 57, 159, 188, 190 Bulgaria, 236, 252, 254, 274-6, 278-85, 287 Bull, H., 63n, 82, 221-2 Burns, A. L., 36, 62n, 66 Cain, B., vii Cairncross, A. K., 246n Cairns, J. C , 238n Calvert, R. L., 20, 59 Campbell, W. R., 15 Campion, L. K., 227n, 254n Cardella, G. P., 238n, 251n, 252n Cardwell reforms, 239n Carroll, E. M., 237n, 239n, 248n Case, L. M., 251 Castagno, A. A., 238n, 251n central power: 34, 66, 189, 193, 200-11, 223, 288, 301, 308, 313, 320, 328-30; disadvantages of, 205-7, 246; and geography, 205-6, 313; and Germany, 188-9, 192-3, 197, 203-10, 246, 257, 259-60, 263, 271-2, 275, 277, 287-8, 303, 308, 313; and preventive war, 207; and sovereignty, 193, 207; and Soviet Union, 211-12, 327-9 Challener, R. D., 227n, 237n characteristic function, 5-6n, 24n, 117, 119-22, 123-5, 200, 220, 234 Charles V, 103, 208-9 Chatterjee, P., 46, 63, 271-2, 288 Chicken, 6, 37,157n China: 98, 152, 219; and contemporary balance of power, 30, 132, 190n, 197, 211, 319-20, 326-9, 331n; and United States, 131, 329; and Warring States Period, 34, 38-9, 103, 173-4, 179, 188, 205, 313 Churchill, R. P., 259n Churchill, Winston, 30, 83-4, 219, 299 city states, 38 civil wars, 79n Clarke, G. S., 228n Claude, I., 48n, 63n, 65, 83, 96, 123,130, 159, 221, 223, 311
Index coalition structure, 86 coalitions: and balance of power, 39, 46-8, 63, 66, 96, 172-4, 187, 221-3, 259-66; bargaining in, 118-22, 125; duration, 123, 147; enforcement, 105, 110; and entanglements, 331-2; gains from, 99-101,195-6, 220-1, 234; notation, 43, 85-6; prediction of, 13, 19, 23, 68, 74, 109-10, 121-2, 217-23; and preventive war, 152-3, 155, 163, 171-7; purposes, 42, 51, 77, 79, 118, 216-17; and resource stability, 23-6, 64, 118-30, 155, 219; restrictions on, 38, 126, 217-19, 233-4, 238, 256; role, 129-31, 172-3, 180; and system stability, 46, 63-4, 75, 80, 94, 96, 101, 117,129, 221-2, 271-310; and threats, 53-4, 81-4, 87-91, 101, 278, 287; universalistic, 314; value of, 49, 52, 99-101, 116-24, 191, 220-1, 233-4; winning, geography and, 191, 198 Cole, W. A., 224n collective security, 91, 159-60, 164, 187, 312 colonies, 179, 256-7, 259, 264-5, 303 common knowledge, 58-61, 70, 150, 182 competitive solution, 7n, 121, 132, 172n, 173 Congress of Berlin, 236, 275, 278-9, 284 Congress of Vienna, 210 Conrad, Austrian chief-of-staff, 78, 289 Contamine, H., 237n continuation value, 92n Convention of Schoenbrunn, 235 Coolidge, A. C , 248n Cooper, Duff, 315 cooperation: and anarchy, 20-2; and conflict, 8-9; in games, 55-6, 67-8, 86-7, 121; and enforcement, 7n, 67-72, 92n cooperative games: 7,12; and resource transfers, 24n core: 7n, 23-4, 55-6, 63-4, 68, 214; and balance of power, 64n, 75, 125; and balancers, 204; and investments, 173-4, 176-7, 186; and majority rule, 126; and resource stability, 64, 118-23,125, 127, 143, 200-1; and stability, 23-5; and systern stability, 176-7,199; and the V-set, 55-6n, 64n Cornelius, J., 335 counterthreat, definition, 89-91 Court, W. H. B., 246n Cowles, V. S., 256n Crafts, N. F. R., 224n Craig, G., 238n Crimean War, 261, 274-5 Crisp, O., 282n Crowe, Eyre, 77, 81, 299 Cunningham, H., 239n
351 Cupitt, R., vii Curatulo, G. E., 251 Cyert, R., 15 Cyprus, 275, 278 D'Agostino, G., 238n, 251n Danube: importance to Austria, 241-2, 276-8, 284-5; and Russia, 241-2 Dardanelles, 274, 288 Darvich, D., 15 Dasgupta, P., 92n De Block, J., 227n De La Gorce, P. M., 227n Deane, P., 224n decision makers, identity of, 37-8 Dedijer, V., 288n DeGroot, M. H., 15 Dehio, L., 34, 103, 208 De Negier, F., 227n deterrence, 6, 20, 107, 197, 228, 322-3, 324n, 325, 332 Dethan, G., 243n Deutsch, K., 336 Diesing, P., 69n D'Ombrain, N. J., 227n, 238n, 258n domestic politics: 27, 75-6; and anarchy, lOn, 20-2; and coalitional flexibility, 217-19, 286n, 308; and goals, 10, 14, 312; and impediments to stability, 180-2; levels-of-analysis, 11-12, 30; relevance to international politics, 10-13, 319-20 dominant strategy, 157n Donaudy, A., 238n, 251n Doran, C. F., 301n Downs, A., 40 Dual Alliance, see Franco-Russian alliance Dupuy, T. N., 336 Duval, R., vii economic competition: 27, 38, 42, 47, 50, 72, 78, 101, 121, 193, 319, 326-9, 332; and European powers, 239, 241-2, 245, 248, 251, 278, 284, 307, 310, 329; and investment decisions, 33,147; and measuring resources, 41-2, 43-6, 73, 76-7, 104, 190, 225-31, 318, 319, 320-1, 324-6 economic growth, 123, 128,149,179 economic production and resources, 78, 227-9, 326 egoism, 18, 38-9 Ehringhaus, F., 246n Einstein, A., 2 Elliot, D., vii enforcement, 7n, 21-2, 67-72 England, see Great Britain Entente Cordiale, 101, 223, 239n, 258-9, 265-6
352
Index
entente versus alliance, 265-6 Epstein, K., 301n equilibrium: alternative definitions, 7n, 77; as cause, 3, 6-9; and dominant strategies, 157n; and enforcement, 68-71; and investment strategies, 157,160, 162-5, 177, 183-5; multiplicity of, 70-1, 162-3; Nash, 7n, 23n, 157n; and rationality, 19; and stability, 8, 36, 62; stationary, 92n; subgame perfect, 7n Erusalimskii, A. S., 246n essential countries: definition, 86; and power index, 86, 99n European balance of power, 22, 34, 85, 215, 223-4, 253, 259-66, 271, 298 European great powers, resources of, 22434, 238-41, 243-4, 246-7, 253-5, 25961, 263-5, 267-8, 276-8, 283-6 evolutionary stable strategy, 68n experimental evidence, 132-43 extensive form: 5-6n, 28, 42, 51-2, 66, 158; and system stability, 92-3n; and timing of moves, 56-7n Faber, R., 337 Fasel, R., 261n Fashoda Agreement, 258 Fay, S. B., 33,149 Ferdinand of Saxe-Coburg, 282-6 Feis, H., 336 Ferris, W., 95n Fiorina, M. P., 40 Fischer, F., 78, 301 Fischer thesis, 300-3 Hammer, P. M., 227n Florinsky, M , 226n Foch, F., 227n force projection: 228-9, 239n, 247, 248, 270; and geography, 211, 253; and resources, 228-9 Fortescue, J. W., 239n France: 30, 77, 81, 91, 100, 103, 119,123, 152,179, 189, 197, 204, 206, 208-11, 21719, 253-66, 272-89, 292-4, 307-9, 316, 319-21, 325, 332; and Austro-German Alliance, 244-6; conflicts with Britain, 257-8; conflicts with Italy, 251; and the League of Three Emperors, 235-6, 243; resources of, 230-4; and Triple Alliance, 249-50 Franco-German alliance, feasibility, 21819, 233-4, 236-8, 256 Franco-Prussian War, 236, 237n Franco-Russian alliance: 206, 223, 237, 243-4, 246, 250, 255-9, 262-6, 275-8, 281, 284-7, 289, 291, 297, 304, 308-10, 327, 332; and Austria, 256-7; French
incentives, 256-8, 264; relative resources of, 264; Russian incentives, 256, 263-4; as a threat, 244, 254-5, 257, 262-3, 266, 287 Fremdling, R., 224n Fudenberg, D., 70n Fuller, J. F. C , 226n, 239n Fuller, J. V., 338 game theory: and cooperation, 42; and equilibria, 6-9; relevance of, 4-6 games: Chicken, 6, 37, 157n; constantsum, 23,125; cooperative, 7n, 23-4, 69; noncooperative, 7n, 92-3n; Prisoners' Dilemma, 6, 9, 19-21, 37, 67-70, 164n; repeated, 20, 26-7, 69-71, 85; with transferable utility, 24n, 132,143; zero-sum, 75,125-6, 278 Gardiner, L., 227n, 228n, 265n Garnham, D., 95n Gatrell, P., 306 Gauld,W. A.,236n, 242n Geiss, I., 302 geography: 187-214; Austro-German Alliance and, 246-7; and balance of power, 188-9, 331; and balancers, 201-11, 252, 313; and bipolar systems, 195,198-9; and central powers, 205-6, 313; defense vs. offense, 189-92; discounting for, 190-1, 246-7, 253, 255, 259; and force projection, 211, 253; and Mediterranean Agreements, 252; and miscalculation, 202, 207; and peripheral powers, 205, 207; and power, 182; and predominance, 194,196-7; relevance, 33-4, 44, 51-2, 66, 75, 104-5, 108, 187-9, 211, 246, 253, 273, 312-13, 327-8; and resource stability, 195,197-201; and resource transfers, 192-4; and resources, 187-94, 312-13; and security value, 205; and system stability, 189,193-5,198-209, 246, 312; and technology, 188-9, 193, 197, 203, 210, 227n, 317; and threats, 192, 197-9; and war, 105, 189; and winning coalitions, 191, 198 George, A., 15 Germany: 30, 52-3, 77-8, 81, 91, 100, 103, 119, 123, 149, 151-3, 179, 211, 217-19, 223, 235-66, 271-310, 316, 320, 324, 327-8, 331-2; as central power, 188-9, 192-3, 197, 203-10, 246, 257, 259-60, 263, 271-2, 275, 277, 287-8, 303, 308, 313; and Dual Alliance, 256-7; and League of Three Emperors, 237-9, 261-2; mobilization of, 297-8, 307; resources of, 230-4, 272, 301, 309 Geyer, D., 282
353
Index Gibbard, A., 14 Giffen, M. B., 258n Gifford, P., 246n Gilpin, R., 22, 36, 46, 50, 62, 76n, 101-3, 115,164, 322-3, 324n, 325-6, 329-32 Girault, R., 255n Glanville, J. L., 250n GNP and resources, 45, 57, 73, 76, 224, 232 goals: 9-10,16,18,129, 201-2; and Arrow's Theorem, 37-8; assumptions, 38-41, 156, 215-16, 317-18, 324-5; alternative assumptions, 50-1; and domestic politics, 10,14; and equilibria, 19; and explanation, 3; and payoffs, 55,156,161-2n; and power, 39-41,124; and rational choice, 18-19; and resources, 41-51, 72-4,106-8,156,176, 312; and security value, 159-62; and sovereignty, 38-41, 49-51,104,107-8,154,156; and system stability, 106-8, 176-9, 312, 315, 321; and theoretical domain, 72-4; and war, 104; and war costs, 107-8 Goerlitz, W., 226n Gooch, G. P., 77-8, 81, 292, 294, 298-9 Gooch, J., 227n Goode, J. H., 258n Gorchakov, Russian prime minister, 273-4 Gordon, D. C , 227n, 239n Gorianov, S., 236n, 242n Gosses, F., 337 Graham, G. S., 228n, 265n Great Britain: 30, 50, 52, 67, 78, 88, 91, 100,102,119,123, 151,179-80, 223, 22566, 271-89, 293-301, 304, 307-9, 315, 320-1, 332; and Austro-German aliiance, 245-8; as balancer, 34, 188, 197, 201-4, 208-11, 223, 252-3, 260, 263, 265, 271-2, 281, 283, 287, 309; conflicts with France, 257-8; conflicts with Russia, 243, 247, 253, 256, 256n, 259, 262, 265, 274-7; and Dual Alliance, 256; force projection, 228-9, 248; and the League of Three Emperors, 236, 238-9, 243; and Mediterranean Agreements, 252-3, 285; neutrality of, 239, 241, 243, 245-7, 250, 253-4, 257, 260, 263, 265, 274, 300; predominance of, 257; resources of, 225n, 226, 226n, 229n, 229-34; and Triple Alliance, 249-50 Grenville, J. A., 265n Grey, British foreign secretary, 260, 266, 292, 298-300 Gulick, E. V., 84,103, 159 Haas, E., 271 Hale, O. J., 246n
Hallmann, H., 228n, 265n Halperin, M., 15 Halperin, S. W., 251 Harcave, S. S., 338 Harfield, A. G., 338 Hargreaves, J. D., 258n Harris, D., 247n Harsanyi, J., 17, 28, 39, 60, 70n, 92n Hart, J., 45n, 224 Hazlehurst, C , 300 Healey, B., 95n hegemonic war, 103 hegemony, 76-8,179-80, 329 Heller, E., 246, 248n Henderson, G. F. R., 227n Henderson, W. O., 246n Herz, J. H., 81 Herzegovina, 236, 273-8 Herzfeld, H., 228n Hilbert, L. W., 246n Hirschman, A., 338 Hitler, Adolph, 30, 84,103,152, 219 Hittle, J. D., 227n Ho Tsung, policy of, 174 Hoetzsch, O., 292-4, 296 Hoffman, R. J. S., 246n Holborn, H., 223 Holsti, K. J., 339 Holsti, O. C , 15, 266 Holy Roman Empire, 119, 208-10 Howell, P. D., 95n Humes, B. D., 20, 59 Ibbeken, R., 246n Imlah, A. H., 246n incomplete information, 29 India, 256-9, 277, 280, 299 inessential countries, 86,174-6 instability, see stability interdependent choice, 4-5,18-19 international politics, anarchy in, lOn, 16, 20-2,187, 311-12 international systems: assumptions about, 36-56,154-62,189-93; notation for, 43, 154-5,190 intransitivity, 14 investment strategy: 154-61; and dominant strategies, 157n; equilibrium of, 157, 162-7; invariance with, 167; and preferences, 156,160-2; and security value, 158-60 Irvine, D. D., 237n, 256n Israel, L., 239n, 247n, 252n Italy: 91, 100, 123, 153, 236, 238n, 239-40, 243, 245, 248-66, 273, 275, 277-85, 288, 301, 308-9; conflicts with France, 251; conflicts with Russia, 238, 251; and the
354
Index
Italy (cont.) League of Three Emperors, 238; Near Eastern Crises, 273; resources of, 230-2 Japan: 30, 38, 47, 53, 78, 123, 149, 153, 164, 190n, 192, 314n, 319-20, 324, 326-7, 329, 331 Jelavich, B., 248n Jervis, R., 4, 21, 63n, 315 Joll, J., 123 Jouan, R.,228n July Crisis of 1914, 271-2, 288-310 Kagan, D., 320n Kalnoky, Austrian foreign minister, 27980, 284 Kaplan, M , 21, 41, 48n, 66, 159 Karsten, P., 95n Kashkarov, M. P., 282n Kaulbars, Russian general, 279, 285 Kehr, E., 228n, 265n Keiger, J. F. V., 236n, 297 Kennedy, P. M., 26, 38, 116, 147, 232-3, 258n, 265n, 326, 328-9 Keohane, R. O., 8, 20, 22, 37-40, 61, 69n, 72, 76n, 115, 146, 148, 179, 325 Khromov, P. A., 225n, 305-6 Kitchen, M.,238n Knorr, K., 45n Kosev, K.,341 Kreps, D., 20, 59 Krivoshein, Russian agriculture minister, 293, 296, 307 Kugler, J., 33, 45n, 48, 65n, 73, 106, 12930, 149-50, 153, 159, 178, 221, 224, 321, 323 Kuhn,T., 3 Kumpf-Korfes, S., 282n Kuropatkin, G. N., 227n Langer, W. L., 237n, 239n, 242n, 248n, 255n Laquer,W.,342 League of Nations, 27 League of Three Emperors, 206, 223, 23544, 250, 254-5, 261-3, 273, 276, 281, 283, 286-8; Austrian incentives, 240-1, 261-2; and British neutrality, 239, 241, 243, 262; and France, 235-6, 243; German incentives, 237-9, 261-2; and Great Britain, 236, 238-9, 243; intent, 236; and Italy, 238; Russian incentives, 241-4, 261-2, 278 Leaman, B. R., 238n Lebow, R. N., 152-3 Lee, D.W.,340 Leidner, F.,236n, 248n Leites, N., 15
Lepsius, J., 235-6, 248, 250, 254 levels of analysis, 11-12 Levy, J., vii, 33, 57, 103, 146n, 151-3, 301n Liddell-Hart, B. H., 237 Liebold, R., 239n, 247n, 252n, 256n Lieven, D. C. B., 292, 295 Liman von Sanders mission, 306 Lincoln, W.B.,261n Lindblom, C , 15 Ling, D. L., 251n Liska, G., 320n Lorderbaum, J. P., 68n Louis XIV, 103, 204 Louis, R., 246n Lowe, C. J., 239n, 252n, 256n, 265n Lowe, Cedric, 285 Luce, R. D.,6n, 60n Mackinder, H., 146 majority rule: 12, 14-15, 23, 117; and resource stability, 126; and system stability, 25 Manchester, W., 340 manipulability, 14-15 Maoz, Z., 95n March, J. G., 15 Marder, A. J., 228n, 265n Marriott, J. A., 341 Martens, T. T., 247n, 256n Maschler, M., 87n, 90 Maskin, E., 70n Mathews, J. J., 258n Maurice, F. B., 247n Maurice, J. F., 226n, 228n May, A., 242n, 248n Mayer, A. J., 341 Mayhew, D., 40 Maynard-Smith, J., 68n McClellan, D., 15 McDermott, J., 341 McHardy, C. M., 228n, 265n McKay, D. V., 251n McKelvey, R. D., 14, 61, 69n, 126, 128n, 172n McKelvey Theorem and social choice, 14 McNeill, W. H., 146-7,180, 204-5, 207 Mediterranean Agreements: 223, 238, 247, 249, 251-3, 258, 277, 280-3, 285-6, 299300; British incentives, 252-3, 285; and geography, 252; and Russia, 252-3 Medlicott, W. N., 236n, 239n, 242n, 248n, 252n, 256n Meinecke, F., 226, 246n Mendelssohn-Bartholdy, A., 235 Merrill, J. N., 239n methodological individualism, 3
355
Index Michalik, B.,228n, 265n Middle East, 44, 88, 98, 102, 189, 197n, 330 Midlarsky, M , 342 minimum winning coalitions: 12, 97,100, 112, 135, 256; and minimum weight, 221; notation for, 12; and viable counters, 220 misperception, 7-8, 58-9, 302 Mitchell, B. R., 227n Mitchell, P. B.,238n mixed strategy, 157n mobilization: 225-6, 230-1, 276, 289, 293300, 302-4, 307-9; of Austria, 297; of Germany, 297-8, 307; and resources, 225-7, 229; of Russia, 293-6, 300-4, 307-8 Modelski, G., 76n Mommsen, W., 301n Monger, G. W., 258n Montgelas, M., 295, 297 Moon, H. R.,227n Morgan, C , vii Morgenthau, H. J., 39, 48n, 61, 75, 81, 95, 101, 129-30, 159, 188, 203-4, 215, 223, 311 Morley, British cabinet minister, 266, 299, 300 Morris, P., 247n, 256n Mueller-Link, H., 282n Muller, M., 236n, 254n multipolarity and arms reduction, 319-20 MuratofT, P., 256n, 333 Murphy, J., 227n mutual security, 82 Myatt, F., 342 Napier, C. S., 226 Napoleon Bonaparte, 26, 41, 84, 103, 202, 210, 217, 261, 332 Nash equilibrium, 7n, 23n, 157n Naval Defense Act of 1889, 265 Near Eastern Crisis of 1875-8, 34, 101, 236n, 242, 262, 271-8 Near Eastern Crisis of 1885-8, 34,100-1, 242, 271, 279-88 near predominant, definition, 80-1 Nicholson, British diplomat, 299 Niemi, R., 15 Niou, E. M. S., 93n, 107n, 132n, 314 Niskanen, W., 40 noncooperative games, 7n normal form, 5-6n, 49 North, R. C , 266 nuclear weapons: 52, 106-7, 315, 318-26, 332; and national goals, 324-5; and resource stability, 323; and resources, 320-2; and sovereignty, 322-3, 325-6; and war, 52, 321
Nye, J., 37, 39, 40, 76n, 325 Olson, M . , 9 , 164n operational code, 15 Ordeshook, P. C , 6n, 17, 56n, 59, 69n, 87n, 93n,107n,126, 132n, 157n, 172n, 314 Organski, A. F. K., 33, 45n, 48, 65n, 73, 96, 106, 129-30, 149-50,153,159, 178, 221, 224, 321, 323 Ottoman Turkey, 44, 208-10, 235-6, 238, 241-3, 244n, 247n, 249, 251-3, 256, 262, 273-87, 290, 294-5, 302-8, 330 Owen, G., 87n Oye, K. A.,69n Page, T., 61 Paleologue, French ambassador, 292, 298 Palfrey, T., 59 paradigms: necessity for, 2-3, 151n; and rational choice, 3-4, 16-20 Parsons, W., 301n payoffs, 55 Pearson, F. S., 188, 211 peripheral powers, 188-9,193, 203, 205-7 Perkins, E . J . , 2 2 7 n Perry, E.W.,226n Phillip II, 103, 209 Pierce, R. A., 247n, 256n Platt, D. C. ML, 343 Plevna, battle of, 274 Poidevin, R., 238n, 255n Poincare, French president, 237, 291, 297-8 polarization, 331 Powell, R., 20, 59 power: of agenda setter, 14; and geography, 182; and goals, 39-41, 124; measurement of, 27, 31, 40-1, 72,182, 224, 320-1; and rational choice, 41; and resources, 41, 45-6, 48, 50n, 72-4, 99 power index, 86, 99n power transition, 147 Pratt, E. A., 226 predominant country: definition, 76, 80-1, 194; emergence of, 167-74 preemptive war, 150-1, 154, 165, 282, 303, 307, 309-10 preferences, see goals Preston, A. W., 227n, 239n preventive war: 33-4, 46,146-86, 189, 207, 232, 266, 312, 317; anticipation of, 14852, 155; causes, 146-53,155, 179-82, 312; and central powers, 207; and coalitions, 152-3, 155, 163, 171-7; and collective security, 159-60, 312; and common knowledge, 150; definition of, 149; preconditions for, 167; and preemptive war, 150-1, 154,165, 282, 303, 307, 309-10;
356
Index
preventive war (cont.) and resource transfers, 173,175-7,180; and system stability, 150; and technology, 181; and World War 1,14, 232, 272, 301-3, 307, 310; and World War II, 152-3 Pribram, A. F., 239n, 244, 249-52, 255, 279n, 280, 282 Prisoners' Dilemma: 6, 9,19-21, 37, 67-70, 164n; and cooperative games, 68 proposal, 86 Quester, G. H., 36, 49, 62n, 90 Raab, G., 254n Rachfahl, F., 239n, 247n, 254n Raiffa, H., 6n, 60n Ralston, D. B., 227n, 237n Rath, R. J.,261n rational choice: adequacy of, 16-20; definition, 18-19; as an empirical hypothesis, 17; and goals, 18-19; and voting, 17-18; paradigm of, 3-4,16-20; and power, 41; and war, 17 Ray, J., 343 realism, 2, 8-9, 39, 40, 48n, 71-2, 105, 311, 316, 318, 325 regime, 20, 27,115, 256, 319, 323-7, 329, 332 Remak, J., 288n, 289n, 290, 296, 297n Renouvin, P., 255n Repington, C. A., 258 resource absorption, 192-3 resource distribution and system stability, 82, 95, 102, 127-8, 130, 170-1, 313 resource growth: anticipation of, 75,14950; and Germany, 230-4, 272, 301, 309; and goals, 41-51, 72-4,106-8,156, 176, 312; instability, 167-79; notation for, 154; sources, 148; and system stability, 150,167-79, 312; and war, 105 resource stability: and alliances, 116,118, 121-3,126, 219, 271; and balance of power, 61-7,115-17,127, 222; and bipolar systems, 78-9,127-8; and coalitions, 23-6, 64, 118-30,124-30,155, 219; conditions for, 66-7, 82, 94, 115-32, 172, 195,197-201; and the core, 64,118-23, 125, 127,143, 200-1; definition, 63-4, 312; geography and, 195,197-201; and majority rule, 126; and nuclear weapons, 323; and number of countries, 130-1; and sovereignty, 115,120-1; and system stability, 63-5, 81, 89, 94, 96,103, 105, 115-16,125, 127-30, 216, 271, 287, 312; and threats, 120-1; and Von NeumannMorgenstern Set, 126; and war, 66, 120-1,131, 317
resource transfers: 42, 51, 218, 234, 309; anticipations of, 116; assumption about, 47-8, 51, 55n; and balance of power, 48n, 55n, 101-2,129; in balance-ofpower theory, 48,129; and the characteristic function, 124,144; and cooperative games, 24n; in experiments, 132,135-6; geography and, 192-4; limitations on, 75-6; and preventive war, 173,175-7, 180; and stability, 48; and system stability, 65-7, 84, 89, 92-3n, 93-5, 99-102, 104-13,173-7,180,192-205, 212-13 resources: additivity of, 187; assumptions, 44-8; and balance of power, 64-5,123, 130,187-8, 221, 313, 316; and economic production, 78, 227-9, 326; of European great powers, 224-34, 238-41, 243-4, 246-7, 253-5, 259-61, 263-5, 267-8, 276-8, 283-6; and force projection, 228-9; and geography, 187-94, 312-13; and GNP, 45, 57, 73, 76, 224, 232; and goals, 41-51, 72-4, 106-8, 156, 176, 312; of Italy, 230-2; measurement, 41-2, 43-6, 73, 76-7,104, 190, 225-31, 318, 319, 320-1, 324-6; and military capability, 224-5, 229-31; and mobilization, 225-7, 229; notation for, 43; and nuclear weapons, 320-2; operationalization, HA-IA, 318; and population, 225; and power, 41, 45-6, 48, 50n, 72-4, 99; and preferences, 49, 50, 53,156; of Russia, 225n, 226n, 230-2, 243; and sovereignty, 324-6; and stability, 64; and theoretical domain, 72-4 Richmond, H. W., 226n, 239n Riker, W. H., 8,15,17, 21, 26, 53, 59, 64n, 75, 85, 97, 115, 120, 125,187, 217, 323 Ritter, G., 226, 227n, 246n, 301n Roloff, G., 246n Rose, G. F., 15, 20 Rosecrance, R., 52, 64, 253, 312, 322, 326 Roth, A. E., 92n Rothenberg, G. E., 227n rules, endogeneity of, 21-2, 69 Rumelia, 236, 254, 275, 279, 283-4 Rupp, G. H.,236n Russett, B., vii Russia: 26, 52, 77-8, 81, 91, 98, 100, 106, 123,151-2, 190n, 197, 202, 205-6, 210-11, 223, 225-8, 230, 232, 234-6, 238, 24266, 272-310; and Austro-German Alliance, 244-8; conflicts with Austria, 234, 241-2, 247, 250, 254, 261-3, 276-7, 27980, 284-6, 289-97; conflicts with Great Britain, 243, 247, 253, 256, 256n, 259, 262, 265, 274-7; conflicts with Italy, 238, 251; and Danube, 241-2; exports, 241-2,
Index 282, 304-6; force projection, 228; and League of the Three Emperors, 241-4, 261-2, 278; and Mediterranean Agreements, 252-3; mobilization of, 293-6, 300-4, 307-8; predominance of, 232, 255; resources of, 225n, 226n, 230-2, 243; threats to sovereignty, 307; and Triple Alliance, 249-50; see also Soviet Union Russo-German Reinsurance Treaty, 206, 223, 244n, 254-5, 263, 281, 285; German incentives, 254, 263; Russian incentives, 255, 263 Russo-Turkish War, 274 Sabrosky, A. N., 95n Salvemini, G., 238n, 248n, 251n Salisbury accord, 279, 284 Sapin, B., 15 Sarajevo, 288, 291, 293, 304 Satterthwaite, M., 14 Sazonov, Russian foreign minister, 290n, 292-6, 298, 307 Schmitt, B. E., 88, 151n, 223, 260 Schroeder, P. W., 347 Schuecking,W.,295, 297 Schulze-Gaevernitz, G., 282n Schurman, D. ML, 227n, 239n Schwartz, T., vii Seager, F. H., 237n Seaton, A., 238n Seaton-Watson, H., 348 Seaton-Watson, R. W., 252n, 256n security value: 24n, 116-17, 158-65, 182-3; and geography, 205; and investment strategy, 158-60; and preferences, 160-2; and utility, 160-1, 161-2n Selten, R., 70n, 92n Serbia, 274-5, 279, 284, 288-94, 297-304, 307, 315 Shapley, L., 99n Shaw, G. C , 226 Shepsle, K.,69n Showalter, D. E., 226 Shubik, M., 6n, 99n Simowitz, R., 345 Singer, J. D., 11, 95n, 96, 159, 178, 224, 229-30, 266 Siverson, R. M., 95n size principle, 187, 217 Skazkin, S., 236n, 242n Skelley, A. R., 239n Small, M., 96 Smart, I., 322 Smyser,W. M.,345 Snidal, D., vii, 4, 8 Snyder, G. H., 69n
357 Snyder, R. C , 15 social choice: 14-16; influence of socialization, 15; and McKelvey Theorem, 14; and unitary actors, 14, 16, 38 social preference order, 14 solution theory, 23 n Sonntag, R. J., 239n, 246n sovereignty: 32, 38, 46-8, 73-4,106, 181, 311-12, 321-6, 329-32; and balance of power, 61-3,106,120; of central powers, 193, 207; and collective security, 158-9; definitions, 323-4; and economic resources, 324-6; and goals, 38-41, 4951, 104, 107-8, 154, 156; and nuclear weapons, 322-3, 325-6; and regimes, 115, 323-6; and resource stability, 115, 120-1; Russian, threats to, 307; and system stability, 32, 64, 77, 84, 87-102,115, 120, 317; and threats, 91, 106, 154, 219, 224, 256 Soviet Union: 30, 47-8, 53, 106-7, 131, 151, 157,164-5, 170n, 191-2, 206, 219, 316, 319-22; as central power, 211-12, 327-9; contemporary strategic problems, 326-9; see also Russia Spain, 119, 178-80, 190-2, 211-12 Spencer Programme, 265 spheres of influence, 98,101 Spykman, N., 34, 187 Ssuma, 174 St. Petersburgh Convention, 235 stability: and balance of power, 20-3; and common knowledge, 58-61; and the core, 23-5; definitions, 63-4; domestic, 44, 48; dual nature of, 22-9, 61-2, 64-6, 115-16; and equilibrium, 8-9; forms, 61-7; and goals, 106-8, 176-9, 312, 315, 321; instability and resource growth, 167-79; and resource transfers, 48; and resources, 64; and war, 65-6, 84, 99, 102-8, 131, 312, 316-17 Stalin, 30, 53 stationary equilibrium, 92n Stearns, P. N., 251n Stein, A., 95n Steinberg, J., 228n, 265n Steiner, Z., 345 Stevens, G. W., 228n, 265n Stojanovic, M. D., 242n, 256n Stone, G. H., 346 strategic defense initiative, 165, 170n strategy, 5n Stuart, G. H., 258n Stuckey, J., 95n, 178, 224, 229-30, 266 subgame perfect equilibrium, 7n Summerton, N. W., 227n, 258n Sumner, B. H., 242n, 247n, 256n
358
Index
Sweet, D., vii system stability: and alliance flexibility, 104, 129, 136, 172, 181, 222, 271, 287-8; and assumptions, 106-11; and balance of power, 21-7, 32-4, 61-7, 81-4, 91-9, 101, 127, 313-17, 331-2; and bipolar systems, 95, 102-3, 110-12, 127-8, 194-5, 319, 321-2, 328, 331; and coalitions, 46, 63-4, 75, 80, 94, 96, 101, 117, 129, 221-2, 271, 310; conditions for, 45, 57, 66-7, 75-114, 128-30, 163-79, 193-5, 197-210, 218; and the core, 176-7,199; definition, 49, 62-3, 312; and endogenous voting weights, 25; and enforcement, 71, 92-3n, 105; and extensive form, 92-3n; and geography, 189, 193-5, 198-209, 246, 312; and goals, 106-8, 176-9, 312, 315, 321; and investment equilibrium, 163-6; and majority rule, 25; and miscalculation, 57, 95, 104, 313, 319, 328; and number of countries, 102, 117, 171, 313; and the power index, 99n; and resource distribution, 82, 95, 102, 127-8, 130, 170-1, 313; and resource growth, 150,167-79, 312; and resource stability, 63-5, 81, 89, 94, 96, 103, 105, 115-16, 125, 127-30, 216, 271, 287, 312; and resource transfers, 65-7, 84, 89, 923n, 93-5, 99-102, 104-13, 173-7,180, 192-205, 212-13; and sovereignty, 32, 64, 77, 84, 87-102, 115, 120, 317; in subsystems, 80, 82-3, 102, 108, 330; and technology, 110, 191, 201, 203; and threats, 84, 87-102, 104-10, 129, 193-201, 204-5, 207, 212-13, 216, 322; and three-country systems, 93-7; and war, 102-5, 131, 312, 316-17; and war costs, 52-3, 99, 106-8, 314-15, 319, 321 Szapary, Austrian ambassador, 297 Szoegyeny, Austrian ambassador, 289, 302 target group, 133 Taylor, A. J. P., 215, 223, 229, 236, 246n, 248n, 255n, 281, 283, 301, 311 Taylor, M., 20, 69 Temperley, H., 77-8, 81, 292, 294, 298-9 Tennefoss, M. R., 95n theory: and balance of power, 28-9; current inadequacies, 1-2; in economics, 37, 39-40, 61, 67, 182, 224; in international relations, 12,19, 29-31; and paradigms, 2-3; testing, 19 theoretical domain, 72-4 Thimme, F., 235 threats: and balance of power, 91, 147, 221, 316; counterthreat, definition, 89, 218;
differences in European crises, 287, 307; and geography, 192, 197-9; of predominance, 168-74; and resource stability, 120-1; and sovereignty, 91, 106, 154, 219, 224, 256; and system stability, 84, 87102, 104-10, 129, 193-201, 204-5, 207, 212-13, 216, 322; types, 86-91; viable counterthreat, definition, 90, 218 Thucydides, 146, 149 Towle, P., 346 Trainor, L., 346 Tramond, J. M., 346 transferability of resources, 47, 55 Treaty of San Stefano, 262, 274-5, 277-8 Treaty of Berlin, 242, 262 Treaty of Bjoerko, 244n Triple Alliance: 123, 223, 238, 240, 243n, 248-51, 255, 258, 260, 263-6, 278, 280, 285-6, 292, 299, 301, 304, 308, 314n; France and, 249-50; and Great Britain, 249-50; incentives for, 250-1, 266; predominance of, 266; relative resources of, 264; and Russia, 249-50 Triple Entente: 77, 223, 237, 258-60, 265-6, 281, 289-90, 293, 299, 301, 303, 309-10, 313, 314n; incentives for, 258-9, 265-6; relative resources of, 264 Tucker, A., 239n Turner, L. C. F., 227n Tyler, J. A., 226n, 239n uncertainty, 56-61, 76, 152-3 United Nations, 27 United States: 30, 38, 47, 50, 53, 78, 87-8, 98, 106-7, 131, 152, 157,164-5, 179-80, 187-8, 191-2, 219, 313, 314n, 319-20, 322, 324-9, 331; as balancer, 197, 203, 206, 211-12, 320, 327-9; and China, 131, 329; strategic imperatives, 328-9 utility, 4-6, 17-20, 78-9, 92, 117; and security value, 160-1, 161-2n; transferable, 24n,132, 143 VanCreveld, M.,226 Veal, D. A. E., 246n viable counterthreat, definition, 90, 208 Villate, R., 226 Viner, J., 255n Viviani, French prime minister, 297-8 Von Neumann-Morgenstern Set, 7n, 557n, 109, 173; and the core, 55-6n, 64n; main-simple, 111, 121, 132, 172n; and resource stability, 126 Von Bernhardi, F., 227n VonGuyer, L., 227n VonKuhl, H.,226n
359
Index Von Schonberg, A. F., 228n, 265n Von Wahlde, P., 227n, 256n voting, 17-18 Wadman, D. C , 346 Wagner, R. H., vii, 20-1, 41, 55, 67, lOln Walder, D.,227n Walker, R. L., 39, 63 Walker, S. G., 15 Wallace, M. D., 63n Walsh, W. B., 227n, 247n, 256n Walt, S. M , 44, 66, 91n, 187, 206, 211, 314, 316, 328 Waltz, K., 1, 12-13, 21-2, 30, 39, 40, 46n, 48n, 62, 66-9, 82, 89, 90, 95, 101-3, 121-2, 127-8, 164, 188, 202-3, 219, 311, 313-14, 323-4, 326, 328 war: and alliance flexibility, 104; and balance of power, 103, 116, 201, 316-17; causes, 7-8, 21, 33, 59-60, 75, 80, 102-5, 151, 165, 309-10, 317; civil, 79n; costs of, see war costs; Franco-Prussian, 236, 237n; and geography, 105, 189; and goals, 104; hegemonic, 103; and nuclear weapons, 52, 321; preventive, see preventive war; and rational choice, 17; and resource growth, 105; and resource stability, 66, 120-1, 131, 317; and stability, 65-6, 84, 99, 102-8,131, 312, 316-17; and system stability, 102-5, 131, 312, 316-17, and theory in international relations, 1-2 war costs: 52-3, 99, 106-8, 176, 189, 321-2, 322n; and balance of power, 52; representation of, 52-3; and system stability, 52-3, 99, 106-8, 314-15, 319, 321; and goals, 107-8 Warner, D., 146, 227n Warner, P., 146, 227n
Warring States, 34, 38-9, 103, 173-4, 188, 205, 313 Weber, F. G., 350 Wedel, O. H.,248n Wehler, H. U., 282n Weingast, B., 69n, 314 Wheeler, G., 247n, 256n Whittam, J. R., 227n, 238n Wienfeld, R. H., 238n Wight, M., 9 Williams, B. J., 259n Williamson, S. R., 226, 227n, 239n, 258n Wilson, R., 20, 59 Winer, M., 126, 172n Wohlforth, W. C , 230, 232 Wolf, P., 95n Wolff mission, 280-1, 286 Wolsey, Cardinal, 203, 208 Woodward, E. L., 228n, 265n World War I: 34, 151, 204, 211, 226, 232, 254, 258n, 260, 301, 303, 310, 313, 320, 323, 329, 331; as preventive war, 14, 232, 272, 301-3, 307, 310; and Fischer thesis, 300-3 World War II: 123, 179, 188, 191-3, 201, 232, 254, 260, 266, 310, 327; as preventive war, 152-3 Wright, P., 258n Wright, Q., 66, 75, 96, 103, 190n Yanushkevich, Russian Chief of General Staff, 294, 296 Young, I., 261n Young, O., 20 Zechlin, E.,301n Zeckhauser, R., 164n Zinnes, D., vii, 29 Zuckermann, S., 305