de Gruyter Series in Logic and Its Applications 1 Editors: Wilfrid A. Hodges (London) Steffen Lempp (Madison) Menachem Magidor (Jerusalem)
W. Hugh Woodin
The Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, and the Nonstationary Ideal
Second revised edition
De Gruyter
Mathematics Subject Classification 2010: 03-02, 03E05, 03E15, 03E25, 03E35, 03E40, 03E57, 03E60.
ISBN 978-3-11-019702-0 e-ISBN 978-3-11-021317-1 ISSN 1438-1893 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Woodin, W. H. (W. Hugh) The axiom of determinacy, forcing axioms, and the nonstationary ideal / by W. Hugh Woodin. ⫺ 2nd rev. and updated ed. p. cm. ⫺ (De Gruyter series in logic and its applications ; 1) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-3-11-019702-0 (alk. paper) 1. Forcing (Model theory) I. Title. QA9.7.W66 2010 511.3⫺dc22 2010011786
Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. 쑔 2010 Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin/New York Typesetting: Da-TeX Gerd Blumenstein, Leipzig, www.da-tex.de Printing and binding: Hubert & Co. GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ⬁ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com
Contents
1 Introduction 1.1 The nonstationary ideal on !1 . . . . . . . . . . . 1.2 The partial order Pmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1.3 Pmax variations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1.4 Extensions of inner models beyond L.R/ . . . . . 1.5 Concluding remarks – the view from Berlin in 1999 1.6 The view from Heidelberg in 2010 . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
1 2 6 10 13 15 18
2 Preliminaries 2.1 Weakly homogeneous trees and scales 2.2 Generic absoluteness . . . . . . . . . 2.3 The stationary tower . . . . . . . . . 2.4 Forcing Axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.5 Reflection Principles . . . . . . . . . 2.6 Generic ideals . . . . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
21 21 31 34 36 41 43
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
3 The nonstationary ideal 51 3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51 3.2 The nonstationary ideal and CH . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108 116 4 The Pmax -extension 4.1 Iterable structures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 116 4.2 The partial order Pmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 136 5 Applications 5.1 The sentence AC . . . . . . . . . . . 5.2 Martin’s Maximum and AC . . . . . 5.3 The sentence AC . . . . . . . . . . . 5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5.5 Pmax 0 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5.6 Pmax 5.7 The Axiom . . . . . . . . . . . . 5.8 Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . .
184 184 187 192 199 221 232 238 274
6 Pmax variations 6.1 2 Pmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals 6.2.1 Qmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.2.2 Qmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
. . . .
287 288 306 306 334
vi
Contents
6.3
6.2.3 2 Qmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.2.4 Weak Kurepa trees and Qmax . . . . 6.2.5 KT Qmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.2.6 Null sets and the nonstationary ideal Nonregular ultrafilters on !1 . . . . . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
. . . . .
370 377 383 403 421
7 Conditional variations 426 7.1 Suslin trees . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 426 7.2 The Borel Conjecture . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 441 8 | principles for !1 493 8.1 Condensation Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 496 |NS 8.2 Pmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 501 C CC 8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 577 9 Extensions of L.; R/ 9.1 ADC . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/ . . . . 9.2.1 The basic analysis . . . . . . 9.2.2 Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ . . 9.3 The Qmax -extension of L.; R/ . . . . 9.4 Chang’s Conjecture . . . . . . . . . . 9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles 9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture . . . . . . 9.7 Ideals on !2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
609 610 617 618 622 633 637 651 667 683
10 Further results 10.1 Forcing notions and large cardinals . . . . . 10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 // . . . . . . . . . . . 10.2.1 Coding by sets, SQ . . . . . . . . . . 10.2.2 Q.X/ max . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .;/ 10.2.3 Pmax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .;;B/ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.2.4 Pmax 10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum . . . 10.4 -logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis . . 10.6 The Axiom ./C . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.7 The Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
694 694 701 703 708 739 768 784 807 813 827 835
. . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . .
11 Questions
840
Bibliography
845
Index
849
Chapter 1
Introduction
As always I suppose, when contemplating a new edition one must decide whether to rewrite the introduction or simply write an addendum to the original introduction. I have chosen the latter course and so after this paragraph the current edition begins with the original introduction and summary from the first edition (with comments inserted in italics and some other minor changes) and then continues beginning on page 18 with comments regarding this edition. The main result of this book is the identification of a canonical model in which the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) is false. This model is canonical in the sense that G¨odel’s constructible universe L and its relativization to the reals, L.R/, are canonical models though of course the assertion that L.R/ is a canonical model is made in the context of large cardinals. Our claim is vague, nevertheless the model we identify can be characterized by its absoluteness properties. This model can also be characterized by certain homogeneity properties. From the point of view of forcing axioms it is the ultimate model at least as far as the subsets of !1 are concerned. It is arguably a completion of P .!1 /, the powerset of !1 . This model is a forcing extension of L.R/ and the method can be varied to produce a wide class of similar models each of which can be viewed as a reduction of this model. The methodology for producing these models is quite different than that behind the usual forcing constructions. For example the corresponding partial orders are countably closed and they are not constructed as forcing iterations. We provide evidence that this is a useful method for achieving consistency results, obtaining a number of results which seem out of reach of the current technology of iterated forcing. The analysis of these models arises from an interesting interplay between ideas from descriptive set theory and from combinatorial set theory. More precisely it is the existence of definable scales which is ultimately the driving force behind the arguments. Boundedness arguments also play a key role. These results contribute to a curious circle of relationships between large cardinals, determinacy, and forcing axioms. Another interesting feature of these models is that although these models are generic extensions of specific inner models (L.R/ in most cases), these models can be characterized without reference to this. For example, as we have indicated above, our canonical model is a generic extension of L.R/. The corresponding partial order we denote by Pmax . In Chapter 5 we give a characterization for this model isolating an axiom . The formulation of does not involve Pmax , nor does it obviously refer to L.R/. Instead it specifies properties of definable subsets of P .!1 /.
2
1 Introduction
The original motivation for the definition of these models resulted from the discovery that it is possible, in the presence of the appropriate large cardinals, to force (quite by accident) the effective failure of CH. This and related results are the subject of Chapter 3. We discuss effective versions of CH below. Gdel was the first to propose that large cardinal axioms could be used to settle questions that were otherwise unsolvable. This has been remarkably successful particularly in the area of descriptive set theory where most of the classical questions have now been answered. However after the results of Cohen it became apparent that large cardinals could not be used to settle the Continuum Hypothesis. This was first argued by Levy and Solovay .1967/. Nevertheless large cardinals do provide some insight to the Continuum Hypothesis. One example of this is the absoluteness theorem of Woodin .1985/. Roughly this theorem states that in the presence of suitable large cardinals CH “settles” all questions with the logical complexity of CH. More precisely if there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals then †21 sentences are absolute between all set generic extensions of V which satisfy CH. The results of this book can be viewed collectively as a version of this absoluteness theorem for the negation of the Continuum Hypothesis (:CH).
1.1
The nonstationary ideal on !1
We begin with the following question. Is there a family ¹S˛ j ˛ < !2 º of stationary subsets of !1 such that S˛ \ Sˇ is nonstationary whenever ˛ ¤ ˇ? The analysis of this question has played (perhaps coincidentally) an important role in set theory particularly in the study of forcing axioms, large cardinals and determinacy. The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated if there is no such family. This statement is independent of the axioms of set theory. We let INS denote the set of subsets of !1 which are not stationary. Clearly INS is a countably additive uniform ideal on !1 . If the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated then the boolean algebra P .!1 /=INS is a complete boolean algebra which satisfies the !2 chain condition. Kanamori .2008/ surveys some of the history regarding saturated ideals, the concept was introduced by Tarski. The first consistency proof for the saturation of the nonstationary ideal was obtained by Steel and VanWesep .1982/. They used the consistency of a very strong form of the Axiom of Determinacy (AD), see .Kanamori 2008/ and Moschovakis .1980/ for the history of these axioms.
1.1 The nonstationary ideal on !1
3
Steel and VanWesep proved the consistency of ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated” assuming the consistency of ZF C AD R C “‚ is regular ”: AD R is the assertion that all real games of length ! are determined and ‚ denotes the supremum of the ordinals which are the surjective image of the reals. The hypothesis was later reduced by Woodin .1983/ to the consistency of ZF C AD. The arguments of Steel and VanWesep were motivated by the problem of obtaining a model of ZFC in which !2 is the second uniform indiscernible. For this Steel defined a notion of forcing which forces over a suitable model of AD that ZFC holds (i. e. that the Axiom of Choice holds) and forces both that !2 is the second uniform indiscernible and (by arguments of VanWesep) that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. The method of .Woodin 1983/ uses the same notion of forcing and a finer analysis of the forcing conditions to show that things work out over L.R/. In these models obtained by forcing over a ground model satisfying AD not only is the nonstationary ideal saturated but the quotient algebra P .!1 /=INS has a particularly simple form, P .!1 /=INS Š RO.Coll.!;
4
1 Introduction
more general problem of computing the effective size of the continuum. This problem has a variety of formulations, two natural versions are combined in the following: Is there a (consistent) large cardinal whose existence implies that the length of any prewellordering arising in either of the following fashions, is less than the least weakly inaccessible cardinal? – The prewellordering exists in a transitive inner model of AD containing all the reals. – The prewellordering is universally Baire. The second of these formulations involves the notion of a universally Baire set of reals which originates in .Feng, Magidor, and Woodin 1992/. Universally Baire sets are discussed briefly in Section 10.3. We note here that if there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals then a set A R is universally Baire if and only if it is 1 -weakly homogeneously Suslin which in turn is if and only if it is 1 -homogeneously Suslin. Another relevant point is that if there exist infinitely many Woodin cardinals with measurable above and if A R is universally Baire, then L.A; R/ AD and so A belongs to an inner model of AD. The converse can fail. More generally one can ask for any bound provided of course that the bound is a “specific” !˛ which can be defined without reference to 2@0 . 1 For example every † 2 prewellordering has length less than !2 and if there is a measurable cardinal then every †13 prewellordering has length less than !3 . A much deeper theorem of .Jackson 1988/ is that if every projective set is determined then every projective prewellordering has length less than !! . This combined with the theorem of Martin and Steel on projective determinacy yields that if there are infinitely many Woodin cardinals then every projective prewellordering has length less than !! . The point here of course is that these bounds are valid independent of the size of 2@0 . The current methods do not readily generalize to even produce a forcing extension of L.R/ (without adding reals) in which ZFC holds and !3 < ‚L.R/ . Thus at this point it is entirely possible that !3 is the bound and that this is provable in ZFC. If a large cardinal admits an inner model theory satisfying fairly general conditions then most likely the only (nontrivial) bounds provable from the existence of the large cardinal are those provable in ZFC; i. e. large cardinal combinatorics are irrelevant unless the large cardinal is beyond a reasonable inner model theory. For example suppose that there is a partial order P 2 L.R/ such that for all transitive models M of ADC containing R, if G P is M -generic then .R/M ŒG D .R/M , .ı13 /M ŒG D .!3 /M ŒG , L.R/ŒG ZFC,
1.1 The nonstationary ideal on !1
5
where ı 13 is the supremum of the lengths of 13 prewellorderings of R. The axiom ADC is a technical variant of AD which is actually implied by AD in many instances. Assuming DC it is implied, for example, by AD R . It is also implied by AD if V D L.R/. By the results of .Woodin 2010b/ if inner model theory can be extended to the level of one supercompact cardinal then the existence of essentially all large cardinals is consistent with ı 13 D !3 . It follows from the results of .Steel and VanWesep 1982/ and .Woodin 1983/ that such a partial order P exists in the case of ı12 , more precisely, assuming L.R/ AD; there is a partial order P 2 L.R/ such that for all transitive models M of ADC containing R, if G P is M -generic then .R/M ŒG D .R/M , .ı12 /M ŒG D .!2 /M ŒG , L.R/ŒG ZFC. Thus if a large cardinal admits a suitable inner model theory then the existence of the large cardinal is consistent with ı12 D !2 . We shall prove a much stronger result in Chapter 3, showing that if ı is a Woodin cardinal and if there is a measurable cardinal above ı then there is a semiproper partial order P of cardinality ı such that V P ı12 D !2 : This result which is a corollary of Theorem 1.1, stated below, and Theorem 2.64, due to Shelah, shows that this particular instance of the Effective Continuum Hypothesis is as intractable as the Continuum Hypothesis. Foreman and Magidor initiated a program of proving that ı 12 < !2 from various combinatorial hypotheses with the goal of evolving these into large cardinal hypotheses, .Foreman and Magidor 1995/. By the (initial) remarks above their program if successful would have identified a critical step in the large cardinal hierarchy. Foreman and Magidor proved among other things that if there exists a (normal) ı 12 < !2 . In !3 -saturated ideal on !2 concentrating on a specific stationary set then Chapter 9 we improve this result slightly showing that this restriction is unnecessary; if there is a measurable cardinal and if there is an !3 -saturated (uniform) ideal on !2 then ı 12 < !2 . An early conjecture of Martin is that ı 1n D @n for all n follows from reasonable 1 1n prewellorderings. hypotheses. ın is the supremum of the lengths of The following theorem “proves” the Martin conjecture in the case of n D 2. Theorem 1.1. Assume that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that there is a measurable cardinal. Then ı 12 D !2 and further every club in !1 contains a club constructible from a real. t u
6
1 Introduction
As a corollary we obtain, Theorem 1.2. Assume Martin’s Maximum. Then ı 12 D !2 and every club in !1 contains a club constructible from a real. t u Another immediate corollary is a refinement of the upper bound for the consistency strength of ZFC C “For every real x; x # exists.” C “!2 is the second uniform indiscernible.” Assuming in addition that larger cardinals exist then one obtains more information. For example, Theorem 1.3. Assume the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that there exist ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above them all. (1) Suppose that A R, A 2 L.R/, and that there is a sequence hB˛ W ˛ < !1 i of borel sets such that A D [¹B˛ j ˛ < !1 º: 1 Then A is † 2 .
(2) Suppose that X is a bounded subset of ‚L.R/ of cardinality !1 . Then there exists t u a set Y 2 L.R/ of cardinality !1 in L.R/ such that X Y . We note that assuming for every x 2 R, x # exists, the statement (1) of Theorem 1.3 1 implies that ı 12 D !2 ; if ı12 < !2 then every † 3 set is an !1 union of borel sets.
1.2
The partial order Pmax
Theorem 1.3 suggests that if the nonstationary ideal is saturated (and if modest large cardinals exist) then one might reasonably expect that the inner model L.P .!1 // may be close to the inner model L.R/. However if the nonstationary ideal is saturated one can, by passing to a ccc generic extension, arrange that P .R/ L.P .!1 // and preserve the saturation of the nonstationary ideal. Nevertheless this intuition was the primary motivation for the definition of Pmax . The canonical model for :CH is obtained by the construction of this specific partial order, Pmax . The basic properties of Pmax are given in the following theorem. Theorem 1.4. Assume ADL.R/ and that there exists a Woodin cardinal with a measurable cardinal above it. Then there is a partial order Pmax in L.R/ such that; (1) Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous (in L.R/), (2) L.R/Pmax ZFC.
1.2 The partial order Pmax
7
Further if is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i and if hH.!2 /; 2; INS i then Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
:
t u
The partial order Pmax is definable and thus, since granting large cardinals Th.L.R// is canonical, it follows that Th.L.R/Pmax / is canonical. Many of the open combinatorial questions at !1 are expressible as …2 statements in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i and so assuming the existence of large cardinals these questions are either false, or they are true in L.R/Pmax . In some sense the spirit of Martin’s Axiom and its generalizations is to maximize the collection of …2 sentences true in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i Indeed MA!1 is easily reformulated as a …2 sentence for hH.!2 /; 2i. By the remarks above, assuming fairly weak large cardinal hypotheses, any such sentence which is true in some set generic extension of V is true in a canonical generic extension of L.R/. The situation is analogous to the situation of †12 sentences and L. By Shoenfield’s absoluteness theorem if a †12 sentence holds in V then it holds in L. The difference here is that the model analogous to L is not an inner model but rather it is a canonical generic extension of an inner model. This is not completely unprecedented. Mansfield’s theorem on †12 wellorderings can be reformulated as follows. Theorem 1.5 (Mansfield). Suppose that is a …13 sentence which is true in V and there is a nonconstructible real. Then is true in LP where P is Sacks forcing .defined in L/. t u Of course the …13 sentence also holds in L so this is not completely analogous to our situation. :CH is a (consistent) …2 sentence for hH.!2 /; 2i which is false in any of the standard inner models. Nevertheless the analogy with Sacks forcing is accurate. The forcing notion Pmax is a generalization of Sacks forcing to !1 . The following theorem, slightly awkward in formulation, shows that any attempt to realize in H.!2 / all suitably consistent …2 sentences, requires at least †12 Determinacy.
8
1 Introduction
Theorem 1.6. Suppose that there exists a model, hM; Ei, such that hM; Ei ZFC and such that for each …2 sentence if there exists a partial order P such that hH.!2 /; 2iV then
P
;
hH.!2 /; 2ihM;E i :
Assume there is an inaccessible cardinal. Then V †12 -Determinacy:
t u
One can strengthen Theorem 1.4 by expanding the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i by adding predicates for each set of reals in L.R/. This theorem requires additional large cardinal hypotheses which in fact imply ADL.R/ unlike the large cardinal hypothesis of Theorem 1.4. Theorem 1.7. Assume there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri and that hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri Then
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
:
t u
We note that since Pmax is !-closed, the structure Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/ is naturally interpreted as a structure for the language of hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri: The key point is that this strengthened absoluteness theorem has in some sense a converse. Theorem 1.8. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose that for each …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri if
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
then hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG for some G Pmax which is L.R/-generic.
t u
1.2 The partial order Pmax
9
If one assumes in addition that R# exists then Theorem 1.8 can be reformulated as follows. For each n 2 ! let Un be a set which is †1 definable in the structure hL.R/; hi W i < ni; 2i where hi W i < ni is an increasing sequence of Silver indiscernibles of L.R/, and such that Un is universal. Theorem 1.9. Assume ADL.R/ and that R# exists. Suppose that for each …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; Un I n < !i if Pmax hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; Un I n < !iL.R/ then hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; Un I n < !i : Then L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG for some G Pmax which is L.R/-generic. t u Thus in the statement of Theorem 1.9 one only refers to a structure of countable signature. These theorems suggest that the axiom: ./ AD holds in L.R/ and L.P .!1 // is a Pmax -generic extension of L.R/; is perhaps, arguably, the correct maximal generalization of Martin’s Axiom at least as far as the structure of P .!1 / is concerned. However an important point is that we do not know if this axiom can always be forced to hold assuming the existence of suitable large cardinals. Conjecture. Assume there are ! 2 many Woodin cardinals. Then the axiom ./ holds in a generic extension of V . t u Because of the intrinsics of the partial order Pmax , this axiom is frequently easier to use than the usual forcing axioms. We give some applications for which it is not clear that Martin’s Maximum suffices. Another key point is: There is no need in the analysis of L.R/Pmax for any machinery of iterated forcing. This includes the proofs of the absoluteness theorems. Further The analysis of L.R/Pmax requires only ADL.R/ . For the definition of Pmax that we shall work with the analysis will require some iterated forcing but only for ccc forcing and only to produce a poset which forces MA!1 . In Chapter 5 we give three other presentations of Pmax based on the stationary tower forcing. The analysis of these (essentially equivalent) versions of Pmax require no local forcing arguments whatsoever. This includes the proof of the absoluteness theorems.
10
1 Introduction
Also in Chapter 5 we shall discuss methods for exploiting ./, giving a useful reformulation of the axiom. This reformulation does not involve the definition of Pmax . We shall also prove that, assuming ./, L.P .!1 // AC: This we accomplish by finding a …2 sentence which if true in the structure, hH.!2 /; 2i; implies (in ZF C DC) that there is a surjection W !2 ! R which is definable in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i from parameters. This sentence is a consequence of Martin’s Maximum and an analogous, but easier, argument shows that assuming ADL.R/ , it is true in L.R/Pmax . Thus the axiom ./ implies 2@0 D @2 . Actually we shall discuss two such sentences, AC and AC . These are defined in Section 5.1 and Section 5.3 respectively.
1.3 Pmax variations Starting in Chapter 6, we shall define several variations of the partial order Pmax . Interestingly each variation can be defined as a suborder of a reformulation of Pmax . The and it is the subject of Section 5.5. A slightly more general reforreformulation is Pmax 0 mulation is Pmax and in Section 5.6 we prove a theorem which shows that essentially any possible variation, subject to the constraint that 2@0 D 2@1 0 in the resulting model, is a suborder of Pmax . The variations yield canonical models which can be viewed as constrained versions of the Pmax model. Generally the constrained versions will realize any …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i which is (suitably) consistent with the constraint; i. e. unless one takes steps to prevent something from happening it will happen. This is in contrast to the usual forcing constructions where nothing happens unless one works to make it happen. One application will be to establish the consistency with ZFC that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. This also shows the consistency of the existence of an !1 dense ideal on !1 with :CH. Further for these results only the consistency of ZFCAD is required. This is best possible for we have proved that if there is an !1 -dense ideal on !1 then L.R/ AD: More precisely we shall define a variation of Pmax , which we denote Qmax , and assuming ADL.R/ we shall prove that L.R/Qmax ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense”:
1.3 Pmax variations
11
Again ADL.R/ suffices for the analysis of L.R/Qmax and there are absoluteness theorems which characterize the Qmax -extension. Collectively these results suggest that the consistency of ADL.R/ is an upper bound for the consistency strength of many propositions at !1 , over the base theory, ZFC C “For all x 2 R, x # exists” C “ı12 D !2 ”: However there are two classes of counterexamples to this. Suppose that R# exists and that L.R# / AD. For each sentence such that L.R/ ; the following: There exists a sequence, hB˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i, of borel sets such that [ \ R# D B˛;ˇ ; ˛
ˇ >˛
and L.R/ AD C , can be expressed by a †2 sentence in hH.!2 /; 2i which can be realized by forcing with a Pmax variation over L.R# /. There must exist a choice of such that this †2 sentence cannot be realized in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i of any set generic extension of L.R/. This is trivial if the extension adds no reals (take to be any tautology), otherwise it is subtle in that if L.R/ AD then we conjecture that there is a partial order P 2 L.R/ such that L.R/P ZFC C “R# exists”: The second class of counterexamples is a little more subtle, as the following example illustrates. If the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense and if Chang’s Conjecture holds then there exists a countable transitive set, M , such that M ZFC C “There exist ! C 1 many Woodin cardinals”; (and so M ADL.R/ and much more). The application of Chang’s Conjecture is only necessary to produce X †2 H.!2 / such that X \ !2 has ordertype !1 . The subtle and interesting aspect of this example is that L.R/Qmax Chang’s Conjecture; but by the remarks above, this can only be proved by invoking hypotheses stronger than ADL.R/ . In fact the assertion, L.R/Qmax Chang’s Conjecture, is equivalent to a strong form of the consistency of AD. This is the subject of Section 9.4.
12
1 Introduction
The statement that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense is a †2 sentence in hH.!2 /; 2; INS i: This is an example of a (consistent) †2 sentence (in the language for this structure) which implies :CH. Using the methods of Section 10.2 a variety of other examples can be identified, including examples which imply c D !2 . Thus in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i there are (nontrivial) consistent †2 sentences which are mutually inconsistent. This is in contrast to the case of …2 sentences. It is interesting to note that this is not possible for the structure hH.!2 /; 2i; provided the sentences are each suitably consistent. We shall discuss this in Chapter 8, (see Theorem 10.159), where we discuss problems related to the problem of the relationship between Martin’s Maximum and the axiom ./. The results we have discussed suggest that if the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 saturated, there are large cardinals and if some particular sentence is true in L.P .!1 // then it is possible to force over L.R/ (or some larger inner model) to make this sentence true (by a forcing notion which does not add reals). Of course one cannot obtain models of CH in this fashion. The limitations seem only to come from the following consequence of the saturation of the nonstationary ideal in the presence of a measurable cardinal: Suppose C !1 is closed and unbounded. Then there exists x 2 R such that ¹˛ < !1 j L˛ Œx is admissibleº C: This is equivalent to the assertion that for every x 2 R, x # exists together with the assertion that every closed unbounded subset of !1 contains a closed, cofinal subset which is constructible from a real. Motivated by these considerations we define, in Chapter 7 and Chapter 8, a number of additional Pmax variations. The two variations considered in Chapter 7 were selected simply to illustrate the possibilities. The examples in Chapter 8 were chosen to highlight quite different approaches to the analysis of a Pmax variation, there we shall work in “L”-like models in order to prove the lemmas required for the analysis. It seems plausible that one can in fact routinely define variations of Pmax to reproduce a wide class of consistency results where c D !2 . The key to all of these variations is really the proof of Theorem 1.1. It shows that if the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated then H.!2 / is contained in the limit of a directed system of countable models via maps derived from iterating generic elementary embeddings and (the formation of) end extensions. Here again there is no use of iterated forcing and so the arguments generally tend to be simpler than their standard counterparts. Further there is an extra degree of freedom in the construction of these models which yields consequences not obviously
1.4 Extensions of inner models beyond L.R/
13
obtainable with the usual methods. The first example of Chapter 7 is the variation, Smax , which conditions the model on a sentence which implies the existence of a Suslin tree. The sentence asserts: Every subset of !1 belongs to a transitive model M in which ˘ holds and such that every Suslin tree in M is a Suslin tree in V . If AD holds in L.R/ and if G Smax is L.R/-generic then in L.R/ŒG the following strengthening of the sentence holds: For every A !1 there exists B !1 such that A 2 LŒB and such that if T 2 LŒB is a Suslin tree in LŒB, then T is a Suslin tree. In L.R/ŒG every subset of !1 belongs to an inner model with a measurable cardinal (and more) and under these conditions this strengthening is not even obviously consistent. The second example of Chapter 7 is motivated by the Borel Conjecture. The first consistency proof for the Borel Conjecture is presented in .Laver 1976/. The Borel Conjecture can be forced a variety of different ways. One can iterate Laver forcing or Mathias forcing, etc. In Section 7.2, we define a variation of Pmax which forces the Borel Conjecture. The definition of this forcing notion does not involve Laver forcing, Mathias forcing or any variation of these forcing notions. In the model obtained, a version of Martin’s Maximum holds. Curiously, to prove that the Borel Conjecture holds in the resulting model we do use a form of Laver forcing. An interesting technical question is whether this can be avoided. It seems quite likely that it can, which could lead to the identification of other variations yielding models in which the Borel Conjecture holds and in which additional interesting combinatorial facts also hold.
1.4
Extensions of inner models beyond L.R/
In Chapter 9 we again focus primarily on the Pmax -extension but now consider extensions of inner models strictly larger than L.R/. These yield models of ./ with rich structure for H.!3 /; i. e. with “many” subsets of !2 . The ground models that we shall consider are of the form L.; R/ where P .R/ is a pointclass closed under borel preimages, or more generally inner models of the form L.S; ; R/ where P .R/ and S Ord. We shall require that a particular form of AD hold in the inner model, the axiom is ADC which is discussed in Section 9.1. It is by exploiting more subtle aspects of the consequences of ADC that we can establish a number of combinatorially interesting facts about the corresponding extensions. Applications include obtaining extensions in which Martin’s Maximum holds for partial orders of cardinality c, this is Martin’s Maximum.c/, and in which !2 exhibits some interesting combinatorial features.
14
1 Introduction
Actually in the models obtained, Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ holds. This is the assertion that Martin’s MaximumCC holds for partial orders of cardinality c where Martin’s MaximumCC is a slight strengthening of Martin’s Maximum. These forcing axioms, first formulated in .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/, are defined in Section 2.5. Recasting the Pmax variation for the Borel Conjecture in this context we obtain, in the spirit of Martin’s Maximum, a model in which the Borel Conjecture holds together with the largest fragment of Martin’s Maximum.c/ which is possibly consistent with the Borel Conjecture. Another reason for considering extensions of inner models larger than L.R/ is that one obtains more information about extensions of L.R/. For example the proof that L.R/Qmax Chang’s Conjecture; requires considering the .Qmax /N -extension of inner models N such that .R \ N /# 2 N and much more. Finally any systematic study of the possible features of the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i in the context of ZFC C ADL.R/ C “ı12 D !2 ” requires considering extensions of inner models beyond L.R/; as we have indicated, there are (†2 ) sentences which can be realized in the structure, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i, of these extensions but which cannot be realized in any such structure defined in an extension of L.R/. The results of Chapter 9 suggest a strengthening of the axiom ./: Axiom ./C : For each set X !2 there exists a set A R and a filter G Pmax such that (1) L.A; R/ ADC , (2) G is L.A; R/-generic and X 2 L.A; R/ŒG. This is discussed briefly in Chapter 10 which explores the possible relationships between Martin’s Maximum and the axiom ./. One of the theorems we shall prove Chapter 10 shows that in Theorem 1.8, it is essential that the predicate, INS , for the nonstationary sets be added to the structure. We shall show that Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture together with all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/i does not imply ./. We shall also prove an analogous theorem which shows that “cofinally” many sets from P .R/ \ L.R/ must be added; for each set Y0 2 P .R/ \ L.R/, Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture
1.5 Concluding remarks – the view from Berlin in 1999
15
together with all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; Y0 ; 2i does not imply ./. Finally, we shall also show in Chapter 10 that the axiom ./ is equivalent (in the context of large cardinals) with a very strong form of a bounded version of Martin’s MaximumCC .
1.5
Concluding remarks – the view from Berlin in 1999
The following question resurfaces with added significance. Assume ADL.R/ . Is ‚L.R/ !3 ? The point is that if it is consistent to have ADL.R/ and ‚L.R/ > !3 then presumably this can be achieved in a forcing extension of L.R/. This in turn would suggest there are generalizations of Pmax which produce generic extensions of L.R/ in which c > !2 . There are many open questions in combinatorial set theory for which a (positive) solution requires building forcing extensions in which c > !2 . The potential utility of Pmax variations for obtaining models in which !3 < ‚L.R/ is either enhanced or limited by the following theorem of S. Jackson. This theorem is an immediate corollary of Theorem 1.3(2) and Jackson’s analysis of measures and ultrapowers in L.R/ under the hypothesis of ADL.R/ . Theorem 1.10 (Jackson). Assume the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that there exist ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above them all. Then either: (1) There exists < ‚L.R/ such that is a regular cardinal in L.R/ and such that is not a cardinal in V , or; (2) There exists a set A of regular cardinals, above !2 , such that a) jAj D @1 , b) jpcf.A/j D @2 .
t u
One of the main open problems of Shelah’s pcf theory is whether there can exist a set, A, of regular cardinals such that jAj < jpcf.A/j (satisfying the usual requirement that jAj < min.A/). Common to all Pmax variations is that Theorem 1.3(2) holds in the resulting models and so the conclusions of Theorem 1.10 applies to these models as well. Though,
16
1 Introduction
recently, a more general class of “variations” has been identified for which Theorem 1.3(2) fails in the models obtained. These latter examples are variations only in the sense that they also yield canonical models in which CH fails, cf. Theorem 10.185. I end with a confession. This book was written intermittently over a 7 year period beginning in early 1992 when the initial results were obtained. During this time the exposition evolved considerably though the basic material did not. Except that the material in Chapter 8, the material in the last three sections of Chapter 9 and much of Chapter 10, is more recent. Earlier versions contained sections which, because of length considerations, we have been compelled to remove. This account represents in form and substance the evolutionary process which actually took place. Further a number of proofs are omitted or simply sketched, especially in Chapter 10. Generally it seemed better to state a theorem without proof than not to state it at all. In some cases the proofs are simply beyond the scope of this book and in other cases the proofs are a routine adaptation of earlier arguments. Of course in both cases this can be quite frustrating to the reader. Nevertheless it is my hope that this book does represent a useful introduction to this material with few relics from earlier versions buried in its text. By the time (May, 1999) of this writing a number of papers have appeared, or are in press, which deal with Pmax or variations thereof. P. Larson and D. Seabold have each obtained a number of results which are included in their respective Ph. D. theses, some of these results are discussed in this book. Shelah and Zapletal consider several variations, recasting the absoluteness theorems in terms of “…2 -compactness” but restricting to the case of extensions of L.R/, .Shelah and Zapletal 1999/. More recently Ketchersid, Larson, and Zapletal .2007/ isolate a family of explicit Namba-like forcing notions which can, under suitable circumstances, change the value of ı 12 even in situations where CH holds. These examples are really the first to be isolated which can work in the context of CH. Other examples have been discovered and are given in .Doebler and Schindler 2009/. Finally there are some very recent developments (as of 1999) which involve a generalization of !-logic which we denote -logic. Arguably -logic is the natural limit of the lineage of generalizations of classical first order logic which begins with !-logic and continues with ˇ-logic etc. We (very briefly) discuss -logic (updated to 2010) in Section 10.4 and Section 10.5. In some sense the entire discussion of Pmax and its variations should take place in the context of -logic and were we to rewrite the book this is how we would proceed. In particular, the absoluteness theorems associated to Pmax and its variations are more naturally stated by appealing to this logic. For example Theorem 1.4 can be reformulated as follows. Theorem 1.11. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i and that ZFC C “hH.!2 /; 2; INS i ”
1.5 Concluding remarks – the view from Berlin in 1999
is -consistent, then
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
:
17
t u
In fact, using -logic one can give a reformulation of ./ which does not involve forcing at all, this is discussed briefly in Section 10.4. Another feature of the forcing extensions given by the (homogeneous) Pmax variations, this holds for all the variations which we discuss in this book, is that each provides a finite axiomatization, over ZFC, of the theory of H.!2 / (in -logic). For Pmax , the axiom is ./ and the theorem is the following. Theorem 1.12. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Then for each sentence , either (1) ZFC C ./ ` “H.!2 / ”, or (2) ZFC C ./ ` “H.!2 / :”.
t u
This particular feature underscores the fundamental difference between the method of Pmax variations and that of iterated forcing. We note that it is possible to identify finite axiomatizations over ZFC of the theory of hH.!2 /; 2i which cannot be realized by any Pmax variation. Theorem 10.185 indicates such an example, the essential feature is that ı12 < !2 but still there is an effective failure of CH. Nevertheless it is at best difficult through an iterated forcing construction to realize in hH.!2 /; 2iV ŒG a theory which is finitely axiomatized over ZFC in -logic. The reason is simply that generally the choice of the ground model will influence, in possibly very subtle ways, the theory of the structure hH.!2 /; 2iV ŒG . There is at present no known example which works, say from some large cardinal assumption, independent of the choice of the ground model. -logic provides the natural setting for posing questions concerning the possibility of such generalizations of Pmax , to for example !2 , i. e. for the structure H.!3 /, and beyond. The first singular case, H.!!C /, seems particularly interesting. There is also the case of !1 but in the context of CH. One interesting result (but as of 2010, this is contingent on the ADC Conjecture), with, we believe, potential implications for CH, is that there are limits to any possible generalization of the Pmax variations to the context of CH; more precisely, if CH holds then the theory of H.!2 / cannot be finitely axiomatized over ZFC in -logic. Acknowledgments to the first edition. Many of the results of the first half of this book were presented in the Set Theory Seminar at UC Berkeley. The (ever patient) participants in this seminar offered numerous helpful suggestions for which I remain quite grateful. I am similarly indebted to all those willingly to actually read preliminary versions of this book and then relate to me their discoveries of mistakes, misprints and relics. I only wish that the final product better represented their efforts. I owe a special debt of thanks to Ted Slaman. Without his encouragement, advice and insight, this book would not exist.
18
1 Introduction
The research, the results of which are the subject of this book, was supported in part by the National Science Foundation through a succession of summer research grants, and during the academic year, 1997–1998, by the Miller Institute in Berkeley. Finally I would like to acknowledge the (generous) support of the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation. It is this support which enabled me to actually finish this book. Berlin, May 1999
1.6
W. Hugh Woodin
The view from Heidelberg in 2010
In the 10 years since what was written above as the introduction to the first edition of this book there have been quite a number of mathematical developments relevant to this book and I find myself again in Germany on sabbatical from Berkeley working on this book. This edition contains revisions that reflect these developments including the deletion of some theorems now not relevant because of these developments or simply because the proofs, sketched or otherwise, were simply not correct. Finally I stress that I make no claim that this revision is either extensive or thorough and I regret to say that it is not – I feel that the entire subject is at a critical crossroads and as always in such a situation one cannot be completely confident in which direction the future lies. But it is this future that dictates which aspects of this account should be stressed. First and most straightforward, the theorems related to ˘! .!2 /, such as the theorem that Martin’s Maximum implies ˘! .!2 /, have all been rendered irrelevant by a remarkable theorem of .Shelah 2008/ which shows that ˘! .!2 / is a consequence of 2!1 D !2 . Shelah’s result shows that assuming Martin’s Maximum.c/, or simply assuming that 2!1 D !2 , then the nonstationary ideal at !2 cannot be semi-saturated on the ordinals of countable cofinality. It does not rule out the possibility that there exists a uniform semi-saturated at !2 on the ordinals of countable cofinality. On the other hand, the primary motivation for obtaining such consistency results for ideals at !2 in the first edition was the search for evidence that the consistency strength of the theory ZF C ADR C “‚ is regular” was beyond that of the existence of a superstrong cardinals. Dramatic recent results .Sargsyan 2009/ have shown that this theory is not that strong, proving that the consistency of this theory follows from simply the existence of a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Therefore in this edition the consistency results for semisaturated ideals at !2 are simply stated without proof. The proofs of these theorems are sketched at length in the first edition but based upon an analysis in the context of ADC of HOD which is open without requiring that one work relative to the minimum model of ZF C ADR C “‚ is Mahlo” but of course the sketch in the case of obtaining the consistency that JNS is semisaturated is not correct – that error was due to a careless misconception regarding
1.5 The view from Heidelberg in 2010
19
iterations of forcing with uncountable support. As indicated in the first edition the analysis of HOD in the context of ADC is not actually necessary for the proofs, it was used only to provide a simpler framework for the constructions. Ultimately of far more significance for this book is that recent results concerning the inner model program undermine the philosophical framework for this entire work. The fundamental result of this book is the identification of a canonical axiom for :CH which is characterized in terms of a logical completion of the theory of H.!2 / (in logic of course). But the validation of this axiom requires a synthesis with axioms for V itself for otherwise it simply stands as an isolated axiom. This view is reinforced by the use of the Conjecture to argue against the generic-multiverse view of truth .Woodin 2009/. I remain convinced that if CH is false then the axiom ./ holds and certainly there are now many results confirming that if the axiom ./ does hold then there is a rich structure theory for H.!2 / in which many pathologies are eliminated. But nevertheless for all the reasons discussed at length in .Woodin 2010b/, I think the evidence now favors CH. The picture that is emerging now based on .Woodin 2010b/ and .Woodin 2010a/ is as follows. The solution to the inner model problem for one supercompact cardinal yields the ultimate enlargement of L. This enlargement of L is compatible with all stronger large cardinal axioms and strong forms of covering hold relative to this inner model. At present there seem to be two possibilities for this enlargement, as an extender model or as strategic extender model. There is a key distinction however between these two versions. An extender model in which there is a Woodin cardinal is a (nontrivial) generic extension of an inner model which is also an extender model whereas a strategic extender model in which there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals is not a generic extension of any inner model. The most optimistic generalizations of the structure theory of L.R/ in the context of AD to a structure theory of L.VC1 / in the context of an elementary embedding, j W L.VC1 / ! L.VC1 / with critical point below require that V not be a generic extension of any inner model which is not countably closed within V . Therefore these generalizations cannot hold in the extender models and this leave the strategic extender models as essentially the only option. Thus there could be a compelling argument that V is a strategic extender model based on natural structural principles. This of course would rule out that the axiom ./ holds though if V is a strategic extender model (with a Woodin cardinal) then the axiom ./ holds in a homogeneous forcing extension of V and so the axiom ./ has a special connection to V as an axiom which holds in a canonical companion to V mediated by an intervening model of ADC which is the manifestation of -logic. An appealing aspect to this scenario is that the relevant axiom for V can be explicitly stated now – and in a form which clarifies the previous claims – without knowing the detailed level by level inductive definition of a strategic extender model .Woodin 2010b/: in its weakest form the axiom is simply the conjunction of:
20
1 Introduction
(1) There is a supercompact cardinal. (2) There exist a universally Baire set A R and < ‚L.A;R/ such that V .HOD/L.A;R/ \ V for all …2 -sentences (equivalently, for all †2 -sentences). As with the previous scenarios this scenario could collapse but any scenario for such a collapse which leads back to the validation of the axiom ./ seems rather unlikely at present. Acknowledgments to the second edition. I am very grateful to all of those who sent me lists of errata for the first edition or otherwise offered valuable comments, I wish this edition better reflected their efforts. I would also like to thank Christine Woodin for an extremely useful python script for finding unbalanced parentheses in very large LATEX files. Heidelberg, March 2010
W. Hugh Woodin
Chapter 2
Preliminaries
We briefly review, without giving all of the proofs, some of the basic concepts which we shall require, .Foreman and Kanamori (Eds.) 2010/ covers most of what we need and obviously quite a bit more. In the course of this we shall fix some notation. As is the custom in Descriptive Set Theory, R denotes the infinite product space, ! ! . Though sometimes it is convenient to work with the Cantor space, 2! , or even with the standard Euclidean space, . 1; 1/. If at some point the discussion is particularly sensitive to the manifestation of R then we may be more careful with our notation. For example L.R/ is relatively immune to such considerations, but Wadge reducibility is not. We shall require at several points some coding of sets by reals or by sets of reals. There is a natural coding of sets in H.!1 / (the hereditarily countable sets) by reals. For example if a 2 H.!1 / then the set a can be coded by coding the structure hb [ !; a; 2i where b is the transitive closure of a. A real x codes a if x decodes sets A ! and E ! ! such that hb [ !; a; 2i Š h!; A; Ei; where again b is the transitive closure of a. Suppose that M 2 H.c C / and let N be the transitive closure of M . Fix a reasonable decoding of a set X R to produce an element of P .R/ P .R R/ P .R R/: A set X R codes M if X decodes sets A R, E R R and R R such that is an equivalence relation on R, A R, E R R, A and E are invariant relative to , and such that hN; M; 2i Š hR=; A=; E=i: We shall be interested in sets M which are coded in this fashion by sets X R such that X belongs to a transitive inner model in which the Axiom of Choice fails.
2.1
Weakly homogeneous trees and scales
For any set X , X
22
2 Preliminaries
(1) s 2 !
Tx D [¹Txjk j k 2 !º:
Thus for each x 2 ! , Tx is a tree on . We let !
ŒT D ¹.x; f / j x 2 ! ! ; f 2 ! ; and for all k 2 !; .xjk; f jk/ 2 T º denote the set of infinite branches of T and we let pŒT D ¹x 2 ! ! j .x; f / 2 ŒT for some f 2 ! º: Thus pŒT ! ! , it is the projection of T , and clearly pŒT D ¹x 2 ! ! j Tx is not wellfoundedº: A set of reals, A, is Suslin if A D pŒT for some tree T . Of course assuming the Axiom of Choice every set is Suslin. One can obtain a more interesting notion by restricting the choice of the tree. This can done two ways, by definability or by placing combinatorial constraints on the tree. The first route is the descriptive set theoretic one. A pointclass is a set P .! ! /. Suppose that is a pointclass and that for any continuous function F W !! ! !! if A 2 then F 1 ŒA 2 ; i. e. suppose is closed under continuous preimages. Then has an unambiguous interpretation as a subset of P .X / where X is any space homeomorphic with ! ! . The point of course is that this does not depend on the homeomorphism. We shall use this freely. Similarly if in addition, is closed under finite intersections and contains the closed sets, then has an unambiguous interpretation as a subset of P .X / where X is any space homeomorphic with a closed subset of ! ! . If is a pointclass closed under preimages by borel functions then has an unambiguous interpretation as a subset of P .X / where X is any space homeomorphic with a borel subset of ! ! . If the borel set is uncountable, i. e. if X is uncountable, then the pointclass, , is uniquely determined by this interpretation. More generally if X is a topological space for which there is an isomorphism W hX; .Z.X //i ! h! ! ; B.! ! /i where .Z.X // is the -algebra generated by the zero sets of X , and B.! ! / is the -algebra of borel subsets of ! ! , then again has an unambiguous interpretation as a subset of P .X / which again uniquely determines . This includes any space we shall ever need to interpret in. We shall almost exclusively be dealing with pointclasses closed under preimages by borel functions.
2.1 Weakly homogeneous trees and scales
23
Suppose that is a pointclass. Then : denotes the pointclass obtained from complementing the sets in , : D ¹! ! n A j A 2 º: Clearly if is closed under continuous preimages then so is the dual pointclass, :. Moschovakis introduced the fundamental notion in descriptive set theory of a scale, (see .Moschovakis 1980/). We recall the definition. Definition 2.1. Suppose that is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages. (1) Suppose that A 2 . The set A has a -scale if there is a sequence hi W i 2 !i of prewellorderings on A such that the following conditions hold. a) The set ¹hi; x; yi j i 2 !; x i yº belongs to . b) There exists Y 2 : such that Y ! !! !! and such that for all i < !, i D Yi \ .R A/: where Yi D ¹.x; y/ j .i; x; y/ 2 Y º is the section given by i . c) Suppose that hxi W i < !i is a sequence of reals in A which converges to x. Suppose that for each i there exists i such that xj i xi and xi i xj for all j i . Then x 2 A and for all i < !, x i x i : (2) The pointclass has the scale property if every set in has a -scale.
t u
The notion of a scale is closely related to Suslin representations. Remark 2.2. (1) If the pointclass is a -algebra closed under continuous preimages and if contains the open sets then a set A 2 has a -scale if and only if there is a sequence hi W i < !i of prewellorderings on A such that each belongs to and the condition (c) of the definition holds. (2) If is a -algebra closed under both continuous preimages and continuous images then a set A 2 has a -scale if and only if A D pŒT for some tree T which is coded by a set in . t u
24
2 Preliminaries
Recall that a set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ is †21 -definable in L.R/ if and only if it is †1 definable in L.R/ with parameter R. Assuming the Axiom of Choice fails in L.R/, then it is easily verified that there must exist a set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/, such that R n A is †21 -definable in L.R/ and such that A is not Suslin in L.R/. The following theorem of Martin and Steel .1983/ shows that assuming .AD/L.R/ , 2 L.R/ the pointclass .† has the scale property. By the remarks above this is best pos1 / sible. In fact it follows by Wadge reducibility that, assuming .AD/L.R/ , every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ 2 L.R/ . which is Suslin in L.R/, is necessarily .† 1 / This theorem will play an important role in the analysis of the Pmax extension of L.R/. Theorem 2.3 (Martin–Steel). Suppose that L.R/ AD: 2 Then every set A R which is †1 -definable in L.R/ has a scale which is †21 -definable in L.R/. t u Suppose that X is a nonempty set. We let m.X / denote the set of countably complete ultrafilters on the boolean algebra P .X /. Our convention is that is a measure on X if 2 m.X /. As usual for 2 m.X / and A X , we write .A/ D 1 to indicate that A 2 . Suppose that X D Y
1 if k1 < k2 and, for all A Y k1®, 1 .A/ D 1 if and only ¯ if 2 .A / D 1 where k2 A D s 2 Y j sjk1 2 A : We write 1 < 2 to indicate that 2 projects to 1 . For each 2 m.X / there is a canonical elementary embedding j W V ! M where M is the transitive inner model obtained from taking the transitive collapse of V X = . Suppose that 1 2 m.Y
k1 < k2 . The tower, h k W k 2 !i, is countably complete if for any sequence hAk W k 2 !i such that for all k < !, k .Ak / D 1, there exists f 2 Y ! such that f jk 2 Ak for all k 2 !. It is completely standard that if h k W k 2 !i is a tower of measures on Y
2.1 Weakly homogeneous trees and scales
25
We come to the key notions of homogeneous trees and weakly homogeneous trees. These definitions are due independently to Kunen and Martin. Definition 2.4. Suppose that is an ordinal and ¤ 0. Suppose that T is a tree on ! . (1) The tree T is ı-weakly homogeneous if there is a partial function W !
t u
Any tree on ! ! is ı-weakly homogeneous for all ı and similarly any tree on ! 1 is ı-homogeneous for all ı. In each case the associated measures are principal. The definition of a weakly homogeneous tree has a simple reformulation which is frequently more relevant to the process of actually verifying that specific trees are weakly homogeneous. This reformulation is given in the following lemma which we leave as an exercise.
26
2 Preliminaries
Lemma 2.6. Suppose that T is a tree on ! . Then T is ı-weakly homogeneous if and only if there exists a countable set m.
k .Txjk / D 1. Homogeneity is a rather restrictive condition on a tree, weak homogeneity, however, is not. For example if ı is a Woodin cardinal and T is a tree on ! for some then there exists an ordinal ˛ < ı such that if G Coll.!; ˛/ is V -generic then in V ŒG, T is <ı-weakly homogeneous. Another example is the theorem of Martin that ADR implies that every tree is weakly homogeneous. A set of reals which can be represented as the projection of a weakly homogeneous tree or as the projection of a homogeneous tree has special regularity properties and this is the primary reason for considering these trees. Definition 2.7. Suppose that A ! ! . (1) The set A is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin if A D pŒT for some tree T which is ı-weakly homogeneous. The set A is ı-homogeneously Suslin if A D pŒT for some tree T which is ı-homogeneous. (2) The set A is <ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin if A is ˛-weakly homogeneously Suslin for all ˛ < ı. The set A is <ı-homogeneously Suslin if A is ˛- homogeneously Suslin for all ˛ < ı. (3) The set A is weakly homogeneously Suslin if A is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin for some ı. The set A is homogeneously Suslin if A is ı-homogeneously Suslin for some ı. t u The connection between the notions of being weakly homogeneously Suslin and being homogeneously Suslin is given in the following lemma. Lemma 2.8. Suppose that A R. Then A is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin if and t u only if A is the continuous image of a set B which is ı-homogeneously Suslin. Homogeneously Suslin sets are determined and as a consequence have strong regularity properties. Weakly homogeneously Suslin sets share some of these regularity properties, for example weakly homogeneously Suslin sets have all the regularity properties that correspond to forcing notions. These include the properties of being Lebesgue measurable etc. Other regularity properties include the following, due to Kechris. Lemma 2.9 (Kechris). Suppose that A !1 and that A is weakly homogeneously Suslin where A D ¹x 2 R j x codes A \ ˛ for some ˛ < !1 º: Then A is constructible from a real.
t u
2.1 Weakly homogeneous trees and scales
27
Definition 2.10. (1) ıWH is the set of all A R such that A is ı-weakly homoWH is the set of all A R such that A is < ı-weakly geneously Suslin. <ı WH homogeneously Suslin. 1 is the set of all A R such that A is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin for all ı. H (2) ıH is the set of all A R such that A is ı-homogeneously Suslin. <ı is the H set of all A R such that A is <ı-homogeneously Suslin. 1 is the set of all A R such that A is ı-homogeneously Suslin for all ı. t u
The next lemma gives the elementary closure properties for these pointclasses. Lemma 2.11. tions.
(1) ıH is closed under continuous preimages and countable intersec-
(2) ıWH is closed under continuous preimages, continuous images, countable intersections and countable unions. (3) ıH ıWH . (4) If ı1 < ı2 then ıWH ıWH 2 1 and ıH2 ıH1 :
t u
If ı is a limit of Woodin cardinals then much stronger closure conditions hold. WH . Theorem 2.12. Suppose that ı is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that A 2 <ı Then WH P .R/ \ L˛ .A; R/ <ı
where ˛ is the least ordinal such that L˛ .A; R/ ZF :
t u
We shall need the following theorem, .Koellner and Woodin 2010/. This theorem can be used in place of the Martin-Steel theorem on scales in L.R/, Theorem 2.3, in the analysis of L.R/Pmax . Theorem 2.13. Suppose that ı is a limit of Woodin cardinals and that there a measurable cardinal above ı. Suppose that A R and that A 2 L.R/. Then A is <ı weakly homogeneously Suslin. t u The basic machinery for establishing that sets are weakly homogeneously Suslin is developed in Larson .2004/. An important application is given in the following theorem of Steel.
28
2 Preliminaries
Theorem 2.14 (Steel). Suppose that ı0 < ı1 are Woodin cardinals and A 2 WH C: ı1
t u
WH Then A has a scale in <ı . 0
The fundamental theorem of .Martin and Steel 1989/ implies that if ı is a Woodin cardinal then H ıWH C <ı : An immediate corollary to this is the following theorem which is extremely useful in developing the elementary theory of these pointclasses. Theorem 2.15. Suppose that ı is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Then WH H <ı D <ı :
and further there exists ˛ < ı such that WH H D <ı : ˛WH D <ı
t u
Putting everything together we obtain the following theorem. H is a -algebra Theorem 2.16. Suppose that ı is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Then <ı H closed under continuous preimages and continuous images. Further every set in <ı H admits a scale in <ı . t u
Remark 2.17. (1) Suppose that 0 1 are pointclasses which are closed under continuous preimages. Suppose that 1 is a -algebra and is closed under continuous images. Suppose every set in 1 is the continuous image of a set in 0 . Suppose every set in 1 is determined. Then 0 D 1 . Therefore if ı is a limit WH H and <ı follows abstractly from of Woodin cardinals, the equivalence of <ı WH . the determinacy of the sets in <ı (2) Suppose that is strongly compact. Then by the results of .Larson 2004/ the pointclass WH is a -algebra with the property that every set in WH admits a scale in WH . Further WH has very strong closure properties. For example, 2 assuming CH, then if A 2 WH then every set which is † 1 definable from A is in WH . An interesting open question is the following. Suppose that is strongly compact. Must WH D H ? This is equivalent to the question of whether every -weakly homogeneously Suslin set is determined (given that is strongly compact). t u It is convenient in many situations to associate with a pointclass P .! ! / a transitive set M . Roughly M is simply the set of all sets X which are coded by a set in . For technical reasons we actually define M to be a possibly smaller set, though in practice this distinction will never really be important to us. It does however raise an interesting question.
2.1 Weakly homogeneous trees and scales
29
Definition 2.18. Suppose that is a pointclass which is a boolean subalgebra of P .R/ and that is closed under continuous preimages and under continuous images. (1) N is the set of all sets X such that hY; X; 2i Š hR=; P =; E=i where a) Y is the transitive closure of X , b) is an equivalence relation on R, c) P R and E R R, d) ; P; E are each in . (2) M is the set of all X 2 N such that the following holds where Y is the transitive closure of X . a) Suppose that 0 W R ! N and 1 W R ! N are functions in N . Then ¹.x; y/ 2 R R j 0 .x/ D 1 .y/ and 0 .x/ 2 Y º 2 :
t u
Clearly M and N are each transitive. With our coding conventions N is simply the set of all sets X which are coded by a set in . Remark 2.19. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass as in Definition 2.18. (1) Suppose that Y 2 N is transitive and that hY; 2i Š hR=; E=i where a) is an equivalence relation on R, b) E is a binary relation on R, c) ; E are each in . Let W R ! Y be the associated surjection. Then 2 N . (2) M is a transitive set which is closed under the G¨odel operations. Even with t u determinacy assumptions on we do not know if this is true of N . Remark 2.20.
(1) If D P .R/ then M D N D H.c C /:
30
2 Preliminaries
(2) If D P .R/ \ L.R/ then M D N D L‚ .R/ where ‚ is as computed in L.R/; i. e. where ‚ is the least ordinal such that in L.R/ there is no surjection WR!‚ t u
of the reals onto ‚.
The following theorems summarize some of the relationships between M and N . Theorem 2.21. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass such that for each A 2 , L A .A; R/ \ P .R/ where for each A 2 , A is the least ordinal admissible relative to the pair .A; R/. Then u t M D N D [¹L A .A; R/ j A 2 º: Assuming AD one obtains some nontrivial information in the general case (weaker closure on ), using various generalizations of the Moschovakis Coding Lemma. Theorem 2.22. Suppose that is a pointclass which is a boolean subalgebra of P .R/ and that is closed under continuous preimages and under continuous images. Suppose that every set in is determined. Then: (1) M \ Ord D N \ Ord. (2) Suppose that T 2 N is a wellfounded subtree of R
t u
Remark 2.23. (1) We do not know if one can prove that M D N , assuming either every set in is determined or even assuming L.; R/ AD: (2) Note that if 0 1 are each (boolean) pointclasses closed under continuous images and preimages then N0 N1 : However the relationship between M0 and M1 is less clear, even with determinacy assumptions.
2.2 Generic absoluteness
31
(3) Generally we shall only be interested in M \ P .Ord/ unless in fact satisfies the closure requirements of Theorem 2.21. Thus the distinction between M and N will never really be an issue for us. Given a pointclass with the closure properties of Definition 2.18 we define a new 2 pointclass † 1 ./. Definition 2.24. Suppose that is a pointclass which is a boolean subalgebra of P .R/ and that is closed under continuous preimages and under continuous images. 2 † 1 ./ is the set of all Y R such that Y is †1 definable in the structure hM \ V!C2 ; ¹Rº; 2i t u
from real parameters.
It is easily verified that the pointclass †21 ./ is closed under finite unions, intersections, continuous preimages and continuous images. It is not closed under complements and further it is R-parameterized; i. e. it has a universal set. If M D N then 2 † 1 ./ is the set of all Y R such that Y is †1 definable in the structure hM ; ¹Rº; 2i from real parameters. We generally will only consider †21 ./ when satisfies the closure conditions of Theorem 2.21; i. e. when M D N . WH Definition 2.25. (1) Suppose ı is an ordinal and that the pointclass <ı is closed 2 2 under complements. A set of reals Y is †1 .< ı-WH/ if it belongs to † 1 ./ WH where D <ı . WH (2) Suppose that the pointclass 1 is closed under complements. A set of reals Y 2 1 2 WH . WH/ if it belongs to †1 ./ where D 1 . t u is † 1
2.2
Generic absoluteness
Suppose A R is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then the set A has an unambiguous interpretation in V ŒG where G is V -generic for a partial order in Vı . The interpretation is independent of the choice of the representation of A as the projection of a tree which is ı-weakly homogeneous. This is an immediate consequence of the next two lemmas. Lemma 2.26. Suppose T is a tree on ! and T is ı-weakly homogeneous. Then there is a tree S on ! .2 /C such that if P 2 Vı is a partial order and G P is V -generic then t u .pŒT /V ŒG D RV ŒG n .pŒS /V ŒG :
32
2 Preliminaries
Lemma 2.27. Suppose T1 is a tree on ! 1 , T2 is a tree on ! 2 , and pŒT1 D pŒT2 : Suppose T1 and T2 are ı-weakly homogeneous. Then .pŒT1 /V ŒG D .pŒT2 /V ŒG where G P is V -generic for a partial order P 2 Vı .
t u
Suppose A R and let D ¹B R j B is projective in Aº: Suppose every set in is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. Suppose .x1 ; x2 / is a formula in the language of the structure hH.!1 /; A; 2i and a 2 R. Let
B D ¹t 2 R j hH.!1 /; A; 2i Œt; aº:
Thus B 2 . Suppose P 2 Vı is a partial order and that G P is V -generic. Let AG and BG be the interpretations of A and B in V ŒG. Then ® ¯ BG D t 2 R j hH.!1 /V ŒG ; AG ; 2i Œt; a : This is an easy consequence of Lemma 2.26 and Lemma 2.27. Alternate formulations are given in the next two lemmas. Lemma 2.28. Suppose A R and let B R be the set of reals which code elements of the first order diagram of the structure hH.!1 /; 2; Ai: Suppose S and T are trees on ! such that (1) S and T are ı-weakly homogeneous, (2) A D pŒS and B D pŒT . Suppose P 2 Vı and G P is V -generic. Let AG D pŒS and let BG D pŒT , each computed in V ŒG. Then in V ŒG, BG is the set of reals which code elements of the first order diagram of the structure hH.!1 /V ŒG ; 2; AG i:
t u
Lemma 2.29. Suppose A R and suppose that each set B R which is projective in A, is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. Suppose Z V˛ is a countable elementary substructure such that ı C ! < ˛, ı 2 Z and such that A 2 Z. Let MZ be the transitive collapse of Z and let ıZ be the image of ı under the collapsing map. Suppose P 2 .MZ /ıZ is a partial order and that g P is MZ generic.
2.2 Generic absoluteness
33
Then (1) A \ MZ Œg 2 MZ Œg, (2) hV!C1 \ MZ Œg; A \ MZ Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i. Suppose further that A 2 .ıWH /V˛ : Then A \ MZ Œg 2 .ıWH /MZ Œg : Z
t u
Suppose that A R and that every set B 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/ is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then .A; R/# is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. This is easily verified by noting that .A; R/# is a countable union of sets in L.A; R/. This observation yields the following generic absoluteness theorem. Theorem 2.30. Suppose that A R and that every set in P .R/\L.A; R/ is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. Suppose that T is a ı-weakly homogeneous tree such that A D pŒT and that P 2 Vı is a partial order. Suppose that G P is V -generic. Then there is a generic elementary embedding jG W L.A; R/ ! L.AG ; RG / such that (1) jG .A/ D AG D pŒT V ŒG , (2) RG D RV ŒG , (3) L.AG ; RG / D ¹jG .f /.a/ j a 2 RG ; f W R ! L.A; R/ and f 2 L.A; R/º. Further the properties (1)–(3) uniquely specify jG .
t u
One corollary of Theorem 2.30 is the following generic absoluteness theorem which we shall need. Theorem 2.31. Suppose that ı is a limit of Woodin cardinals and that there a measurable cardinal above ı. Suppose that GP is V -generic where P is a partial order such that P 2 Vı . Then L.R/V L.R/V ŒG : Proof. By Theorem 2.13, each set X 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ is <ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. The theorem follows from Theorem 2.30.
t u
34
2 Preliminaries
The next theorem shows, in essence, that the key property of weakly homogeneous trees given in Lemma 2.26 is equivalent in the presence of large cardinals to weak homogeneity. Theorem 2.32. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal. Suppose that S and T are trees on ! such that if G Coll.!; ı/ is V -generic then, .pŒT /V ŒG D RV ŒG n .pŒS /V ŒG : Then S and T are each <ı-weakly homogeneous.
2.3
t u
The stationary tower
We briefly review some of the basic facts concerning the stationary tower forcing. Definition 2.33.
(1) A nonempty set a is stationary if for any function f W .[a/
there exists b 2 a such that f Œb
t u
2.3 The stationary tower
35
Definition 2.34 (Stationary Tower). Suppose a and b are stationary sets. Then a b if [b [a and ¹ \ .[b/ j 2 aº b: (1) For each ordinal ˛, P<˛ , is the partial order given by, P<˛ D ¹a 2 V˛ j a is stationaryº: (2) For each ordinal ˛, Q<˛ , is the partial order given by, Q<˛ D ¹a 2 V˛ j a is stationary and a P!1 .[a/º:
t u
Remark 2.35. This generalization of the notion of a stationary set appears in Woodin .1985/, where it is exploited in this generality and where the stationary tower is introduced. The idea for generalizing the notion of a stationary set in this fashion originates in work of Shelah. The motivation for some of the key definitions relating to the stationary tower is from consideration of the results of Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah .1988/. An expanded treatment can be found in .Larson 2004/. t u There are numerous variations of P<˛ . The partial order Q<˛ is one such example. The others are defined in a similar fashion as suborders of P<˛ . Except in the proof of Theorem 9.68, we shall need to use only Q<˛ . Suppose G Q<˛ is V -generic. For each a 2 G, G defines in V ŒG an ultrafilter Ua on V \ P .a/. The ultrafilter is simply Ua D G \ ¹b a j b 2 G and [ b D [aº: This in turn yields an elementary embedding ja W V ! .Ma ; Ea / where Ma D Ult .V; Ua /. If a < b and a 2 G then there is a natural embedding jb;a W Mb ! Ma and this defines a directed system. The verification relies on (i). Let .M; E/ be the limit and let j W V ! .M; E/ be the resulting embedding. It is straightforward to verify the following, each of which is a consequence of (ii). (1) For all x 2 V˛ , there exists y 2 M such that ¹t 2 M j t E yº D ¹j.a/ j a 2 xº: (2) For all a 2 Q<˛ , a 2 G if and only if there exists y 2 M such that y E j.a/ and such that ¹t 2 M j t E yº D ¹j.b/ j b 2 [aº:
36
2 Preliminaries
Suppose .M; E/ is wellfounded and let N be the transitive collapse of .M; E/. In this case (1) asserts that for each x 2 V˛ , j Œx 2 N . Therefore for each ˇ < ˛, j jVˇ 2 N and so by (2), G \ Vˇ 2 N . If .M; E/ is not wellfounded these conclusions still hold. (1) implies that for each ˇ < ˛, Vˇ belongs to the wellfounded part of .M; E/ and so by (2), G \ Vˇ also belongs to the wellfounded part of .M; E/. The next theorem indicates a key influence of large cardinals. Theorem 2.36. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal and that G Q<ı is V -generic. Let j W V ! .M; E/ be the induced generic elementary embedding. Then .M; E/ is wellfounded and further N <ı N in V ŒG where N is the transitive collapse of .M; E/.
t u
Remark 2.37. (1) Theorem 2.36 holds for P<ı and this leads to a variety of unusual forcing effects. For example if ı is a Woodin cardinal and if is a measurable cardinal below ı, then in a forcing extension of V which adds no new bounded subsets to , it is possible to collapse C to and preserve the measurability of . (2) Theorem 2.36 can be proved from a variety of large cardinal assumptions. For example it follows from the assumption that ı is strongly compact. t u
2.4
Forcing Axioms
We briefly survey some of the forcing axioms which we shall be interested in. Suppose that P is a partial order, 2 V P is a term, and that G P is a V -generic filter. Then IG . / denotes the interpretation of in V ŒG given by G. Definition 2.38 (Shelah). Suppose that P is a partial order. (1) P is proper if for all sufficiently large ; if X H. C / is a countable elementary substructure with P 2 X , then for each p0 2 P \ X there exists p1 2 P such that p1 p0 and such that for each term 2 V P \ X; if G P is V -generic with p1 2 G then either IG ./ … Ord or IG ./ 2 X .
2.4 Forcing Axioms
37
(2) P is semiproper if for all sufficiently large ; if X H. C / is a countable elementary substructure with P 2 X , then for each p0 2 P \ X there exists p1 2 P such that p1 p0 and such that for each term 2 V P \ X; if G P is V -generic with p1 2 G then either IG ./ … !1V or IG ./ 2 X .
t u
Remark 2.39. (With notation as in Definition 2.38.) (1) Definition 2.38(1) asserts simply that if p1 2 G then X can be expanded to an elementary substructure X H. C /ŒG such that G 2 X and such that X \ C D X \ C . For sufficiently large
this in turn is equivalent to requiring that X \ H. C / D X . (2) Definition 2.38(2) asserts that if p1 2 G then X can be expanded to an elementary substructure X H. C /ŒG such that G 2 X and such that X \ !1 D X \ !1 .
t u
There are several equivalent definitions of proper partial orders. One elegant version is given in the next lemma. Lemma 2.40 (Shelah). Suppose that P is a partial order. The following are equivalent. (1) P is proper. (2) For all stationary sets a such that a P!1 .[a/, V P “a is stationary”:
t u
Definition 2.41. (1) (Baumgartner, Shelah) Proper Forcing Axiom .PFA/: Suppose that P is a proper partial order and that D P .P / is a collection of dense subsets of P with jDj !1 : Then there exists a filter F P such that F \D ¤; for all D 2 D.
38
2 Preliminaries
(2) (Shelah) Semiproper Forcing Axiom .SPFA/: Suppose that P is a semiproper partial order and that D P .P / is a collection of dense subsets of P with jDj !1 : Then there exists a filter F P such that F \D ¤; for all D 2 D.
t u
Definition 2.42 (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah). Suppose that P is a partial order. The partial order P is stationary set preserving if .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\ V:
t u
Definition 2.43 (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah). Martin’s Maximum: Suppose that P is a partial order which is stationary set preserving. Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of dense subsets of P with jDj !1 : Then there exists a filter F P such that F \D ¤; for all D 2 D.
t u
In fact Martin’s Maximum is equivalent to SPFA. Theorem 2.44 (Shelah). The following are equivalent. (1) Martin’s Maximum. t u
(2) SPFA.
There are several variations of these forcing axioms which we shall be interested in. We restrict our attention to variations of Martin’s Maximum. Definition 2.45 (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah). (1) Martin’s MaximumC : Suppose that P is a partial order which is stationary set preserving. Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of dense subsets of P with jDj !1 ; P
and that 2 V is a term for a stationary subset of !1 . Then there exists a filter F P such that: a) for all D 2 D, F \ D ¤ ;; b) ¹˛ < !1 j for some p 2 F ; p ˛ 2 º is stationary in !1 .
2.4 Forcing Axioms
39
(2) Martin’s MaximumCC : Suppose that P is a partial order which is stationary set preserving. Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of dense subsets of P with jDj !1 ; and that h W < !1 i is a sequence of terms for stationary subsets of !1 . Then there exists a filter F P such that: a) For all D 2 D, F \ D ¤ ;; b) For each < !1 , ¹˛ < !1 j for some p 2 F ; p ˛ 2 º t u
is stationary in !1 .
The following lemma notes useful consequences of these axioms which are quite relevant to the themes of this book. These consequences of Martin’s Maximum and of Martin’s MaximumCC are not equivalences; however they are equivalences for bounded versions of these forcing axioms, see Lemma 10.93 and Lemma 10.94 of Section 10.3. Lemma 2.46. Suppose that P is a partial order which is stationary set preserving. (1) (Martin’s Maximum) Then P
hH.!2 /; 2i †1 hH.!2 /; 2iV : (2) (Martin’s MaximumCC ) Then P
hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i †1 hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iV :
t u
Definition 2.47 (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah). (1) Martin’s MaximumC .c/: Martin’s MaximumC holds for partial orders P with jP j c. (2) Martin’s MaximumCC .c/: Martin’s MaximumCC holds for partial orders P with jP j c. t u Remark 2.48. One can naturally define SPFA.c/. One subtle aspect of the equivalence of Martin’s Maximum and SPFA is that Martin’s Maximum.c/ is not equivalent to SPFA.c/; Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies that INS (the nonstationary ideal on !1 ) is !2 -saturated whereas SPFA.c/ does not. One strong indication of the difference follows from the results of Section 9.5: Assume Martin’s Maximum.c/. Then Projective Determinacy holds. The consistency of SPFA.c/ can be obtained from that of the existence of a strong t u cardinal and so SPFA.c/ does not imply even 12 -Determinacy.
40
2 Preliminaries
We end this section with the definition of a somewhat technical variation of Martin’s Maximum.c/. For many applications where Martin’s Maximum.c/ is used, this variation suffices. For example, it implies that INS is !2 -saturated. However we shall see in Section 9.2.2 that this forcing axiom is (probably) significantly weaker than Martin’s Maximum.c/. We require the following definition. Definition 2.49. Suppose P D .R;
t u
Remark 2.50. As we have suggested, many (but not all) of the partial orders to which one applies Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ are in fact absolutely stationary set preserving. These include the partial orders for sealing antichains in .P .!1 / n INS ; /, which are defined immediately before Definition 2.56. t u Definition 2.51. Martin’s Maximum ZF .c/: Martin’s Maximum holds for partial orders P such that: (1) jP j c. (2) P is absolutely stationary set preserving.
t u
We shall prove, in Section 9.5, that Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies that for every A !2 , A# exists. The following lemma is an immediate corollary of this. Lemma 2.52 (Martin’s Maximum .c/). Suppose that A !2 is such that H.!2 / LŒA: Then LŒA Martin’s MaximumZF .c/:
t u
2.5 Reflection Principles
2.5
41
Reflection Principles
Forcing axioms generalizing MA!1 to various classes of partial orders are inherently reflection principles in the spirit of supercompactness but for !2 . In the presence of large cardinals these forcing axioms can be viewed as assertions that !2 is generically supercompact. Suppose be a collection of partial orders. MA!1 ./ holds if for every partial order P 2 and for every set X of dense subsets of P if X has cardinality !1 then there exists a filter F P which is X -generic. Theorem 2.53. Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Let be a collection of partial orders. Then the following are equivalent. (1) MA!1 ./. (2) For every poset P 2 and for every there exists a generic elementary embedding j W V ! M V P Q such that cp.j / D !2 and such that M M in V P Q . Proof. We first show that (1) implies (2). This is a straightforward consequence of the existence of the generic elementary embeddings associated to the stationary tower. See Theorem 2.36 and Remark 2.37. We shall use the version of Theorem 2.36 which concerns P<ı . Fix P 2 and 2 Ord. Let ı be a Woodin cardinal such that < ı and such that P 2 Vı . Let D be the set of d P such that d is dense in P . Let ˛ < ı be a limit ordinal such that P 2 V˛ and let a be the set of X V˛ such that (1.1) !1 X , (1.2) jX j D !1 , (1.3) there is a filter F X such that F is X -generic. We claim that a is stationary in P!2 .V˛ /. Fix a function H W V˛
X V˛ ;
42
2 Preliminaries
H ŒX
such that: a) X Y and jY j D !1 ; b) Z \ P!1 .Y / is stationary in P!1 .Y /.
2.6 Generic ideals
43
(2) (Todorcevic) (Strong Reflection Principle; SRP): Suppose that !2 , Z P!1 . / and that for each stationary set T !1 , ¹ 2 Z j \ !1 2 T º is stationary in P!1 . /. Then for all X of cardinality !1 there exists Y
such that: a) X Y and jY j D !1 ; b) Z \ P!1 .Y / contains a set which is closed and unbounded in P!1 .Y /. u t Remark 2.55. (1) The principle WRP was introduced in .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ as Strong Reflection. It implies the (weaker) assertion that for any partial order P , P is semiproper if and only if forcing with P preserves stationary subsets of !1 , see .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/. Interestingly, Todorcevic had previously proved that a special case of WRP implies that c @2 . The results of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ show that WRP is consistent with CH. (2) The principle SRP was formulated in .Todorcevic 1984/ and is based on Shelah’s proof that Martin’s Maximum is equivalent to SPFA. The precise formulation given in Definition 2.54(2) is the principle of Projective Stationary Reflection of Feng and Jech .1998/. Feng and Jech proved that Projective Stationary Reflection is actually equivalent to Todorcevic’s principle. (3) SRP implies WRP and many of the consequences of Martin’s Maximum follow from it. For example, SRP implies the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated and that 2@1 @2 see .Todorcevic 1984/. It will follow from the principal results of Chapter 3, that SRP implies that ı12 D !2 and so SRP implies that c D @2 . Theorem 9.79 shows that a fairly weak fragment of SRP suffices. (4) Both WRP and SRP follow from SPFA. (5) One can show that SRP is consistent with the existence of a Suslin tree on !1 and so SRP does not imply Martin’s Maximum. u t
2.6
Generic ideals
One of the main results of Chapter 3 is that if the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 saturated and if there is a measurable cardinal, then there is an effective failure of CH. The force of this result is greatly amplified by the results of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ and Shelah .1987/ which show that if suitable large cardinals exist then there is a semiproper partial order P such that in V P , the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated.
44
2 Preliminaries
Combining these results yields that the effective version of the Continuum Hypothesis is as intractable a problem as the Continuum Hypothesis itself. We review briefly the results of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ and .Shelah and Woodin 1990/. We begin with the key definition. Suppose that A P .!1 / n INS is nonempty. Let PA denote the following partial order. Conditions are pairs .f; c/ such that (1) for some ˛ < !1 , f W ˛ ! A, (2) c !1 is a countable closed subset such that for each ˇ 2 c, if ˇ 2 dom.f / then ˇ 2 f ./ for some < ˇ, and such that c ¤ ;. The ordering on PA is by extension. Suppose that .f1 ; c1 / 2 PA and that .f2 ; c2 / 2 PA . Then .f2 ; c2 / .f1 ; c1 / if f1 f2 and c1 D c2 \ .max.c1 / C 1/. We note that if .f; c/ 2 PA then necessarily sup.c/ 2 c. This is because c is closed in !1 and not cofinal. One of the key theorems of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ is that if A P .!1 / n INS is predense in .P .!1 / n INS ; / then forcing with PA preserves stationary subsets of !1 . It is not difficult to show that PA is proper if and only if there exists a sequence hA˛ W ˛ < !1 i of elements of A and a closed cofinal set C !1 such that for all ˛ 2 C, ˛ 2 Aˇ for some ˇ < ˛. The question of when the partial order PA is semiproper is more interesting. This isolates a fundamental combinatorial condition on the predense set A which we define below. This condition is implicit in .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/. Definition 2.56. Suppose that A P .!1 / n INS : Then A is semiproper if for any transitive set M such that M P .H.!2 // M; if X M is a countable elementary substructure such that A 2 X , then there exists a countable elementary substructure Y M
2.6 Generic ideals
45
such that (1) X Y , (2) X \ !1 D Y \ !1 , (3) Y \ !1 2 S for some S 2 Y \ A.
t u
The selection of name semiproper in Definition 2.56 is explained in the following lemma. Lemma 2.57 (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah). Suppose that A P .!1 / n INS is nonempty. Then the following are equivalent. (1) A is semiproper. (2) The partial order PA is semiproper.
t u
The nonstationary ideal on !1 is presaturated if for any A 2 P .!1 / n INS and for any sequence hAi W i < !i of maximal antichains in P .!1 / n INS there exists B A such that B … INS and such that for each i < !, ¹X 2 Ai j X \ B … INS º has cardinality at most !1 . Theorem 2.58 (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah). Suppose that for each predense set A P .!1 / n INS ; A is semiproper. Then the nonstationary ideal on !1 is precipitous.
t u
Theorem 2.59 (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah). Suppose that is a supercompact cardinal and that G Coll.!1 ; < / is V -generic. Then in V ŒG, (1) each predense set A P .!1 / n INS is semiproper, (2) the nonstationary ideal on !1 is presaturated.
t u
The large cardinal hypothesis of Theorem 2.59 can be reduced, this yields the following theorem. Theorem 2.60. Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal and that G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic. Suppose that hA W < ıi 2 V ŒG is a sequence such that in V ŒG, for each < ı, A P .!1 / n INS and A is predense.
46
2 Preliminaries
Then there exists a < ı such that is strongly inaccessible in V , such that hA W < i 2 V ŒGj ; and such that in V ŒGj , for each < , A P .!1 / n INS ; A is predense, and A is semiproper.
t u
The conclusion of Theorem 2.60 is weaker than that of Theorem 2.59, nevertheless it is sufficient to prove INS is presaturated in V ŒG. Theorem 2.61. Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal and that G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic. Then in V ŒG, INS is presaturated.
t u
Suppose that A P .!1 / n INS and that A is predense and not semiproper. Let TA be the set of countable X P .H.!2 // such that there does not exist Y P .H.!2 // such that X Y , X \ !1 D Y \ !1 , and such that Y \ !1 2 S for some S 2 Y \ A. Since A is not semiproper, the set TA P!1 .P .H.!2 /// is stationary in P!1 .P .H.!2 ///. Shelah has generalized Theorem 2.60 obtaining the following theorem. For the statement of this theorem we require a definition. Suppose N M are transitive models of ZFC such that !1N D !1M : Then M is a good extension of N if for each set A 2 N such that in N , A P .!1 / n INS ; A is predense and not semiproper; the set .TA /N is a stationary set in M . Theorem 2.62 (Shelah). Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal and that P Vı is a ı-cc partial order such that: (1) There is a cofinal set S ı such that if 2 S then is a strongly inaccessible cardinal such that if G P is V -generic then G \ V is V -generic for P \ V , and V ŒG is a semiproper extension of V ŒG \ V .
2.6 Generic ideals
47
(2) There exists a closed unbounded set C ı such that for all 2 C , if is strongly inaccessible and if G P is V -generic then a) !1V D !1V ŒG , b) G \ V is V -generic for P \ V , c) D !2 in V ŒG \ V , d) V ŒG is a good extension of V ŒG \ V . Suppose that G P is V -generic and that hA W < ıi 2 V ŒG is a sequence such that in V ŒG, for each < ı, A P .!1 / n INS and A is predense. Then there exists < ı such that is strongly inaccessible in V , such that (1) G \ V is V -generic for P \ V , (2) hA W < i 2 V ŒG \ V , (3) in V ŒG \ V , for each < , A P .!1 / n INS ; A is predense, and A is semiproper.
t u
One corollary of Lemma 2.57 is the following. Lemma 2.63. Let PD
Y
PA
be the product with countable support of all the partial orders PA such that A P .!1 / n INS and such that A is semiproper. Then the partial order P is semiproper. Suppose that G P is V -generic. Then V ŒG is a good extension of V . Proof. Let M be a transitive set such that M H./ M where is a regular cardinal such that jP .P .!1 //j < : Suppose that A0 P .!1 / n INS and that A0 is predense and not semiproper. Since A0 is not semiproper, the set TA0 is stationary in P!1 .P .H.!2 ///. Therefore there exists X0 M
48
2 Preliminaries
such that X0 2 TA0 . The key point is the following. Suppose that X M is a countable elementary substructure such that X0 X and such that X \ !1 D X0 \ !1 : Then X 2 TA0 . By constructing an elementary chain, there exists X M such that (1.1) X0 X , (1.2) X \ !1 D X0 \ !1 , (1.3) for each predense set A P .!1 / n INS such that A 2 X and such that A is semiproper, there exists S 2X \A with X \ !1 2 S . Now suppose that g X \ P is a filter which is X -generic. By (1.3) it follows that there is a condition p 2 P such that p
t u
A corollary of Theorem 2.60 is the following theorem of .Shelah and Woodin 1990/.
2.6 Generic ideals
49
Theorem 2.65. Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal and that G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic. Then in V ŒG there is a normal, uniform, ideal I on !1 such that I \ V D .INS /V and such that I is !2 -saturated in V ŒG. Proof. We sketch the proof. The ideal I is rather easy to define, it is the normal ideal (in V ŒG) generated by the following set. Let I0 2 V ŒG be the set of A !1 such that for some f W !1 ! P .!1 / n INS ; (1.1) A D ¹ˇ < !1 j ˇ … f .˛/ for all ˛ < ˇº, (1.2) if A D ¹f .˛/ j ˛ < !1 º then for some < ı, is strongly inaccessible in V , A 2 V ŒG \ V ; and A is semiproper in V ŒG \ V . Let I be the normal ideal generated by I0 . The only difficulty is to verify that I is a proper ideal. Granting this, it is easy to prove using Theorem 2.60 that I is a saturated ideal in V ŒG. Suppose that A0 P .!1 / n I is a maximal antichain. Let A D A0 [ .I n INS /: Clearly A P .!1 / n INS and A is predense. By Theorem 2.60, there exists < ı such that is strongly inaccessible in V , such that A \ V ŒG \ V 2 V ŒG \ V ; and such that A \ V ŒG \ V is semiproper in V ŒG \ V . Let f W !1 ! A \ V ŒG \ V be a surjection with f 2 V ŒG. Thus A 2 I where A D ¹ˇ < !1 j ˇ … f .˛/ for all ˛ < ˇº: Since I is a normal ideal it follows that A0 A \ V ŒG \ V ; and so jA0 j D !1 in V ŒG. Thus the ideal I is a saturated ideal, provided it is a proper ideal. To show that I is proper we work in V . Let M D H.ı C /, thus M Vı M: By constructing an elementary chain one can show that there exists a countable elementary substructure, X M; and a condition p 2 Coll.!1 ; <ı/ such that the following hold.
50
2 Preliminaries
(2.1) p is X -generic; i. e. the set ¹q 2 X \ Coll.!1 ; <ı/ j p < qº is X -generic. (2.2) Suppose that 2 X \ ı, is strongly inaccessible and that 2 V Coll.!1 ;</ \ X is a term for a semiproper subset of P .!1 / n INS . Then there is a term for a subset of !1 such that 2 X , p 2 and such that p X \ !1 2 : Now suppose G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic and that p 2 G. Since ¹q 2 X \ Coll.!1 ; <ı/ j p < qº is X -generic it follows that there exists Y M ŒG such that X D Y \ M . By (2.2), for each set A 2 Y \ I0 , Y \ !1 … A: This implies that the normal ideal generated by I0 is proper. Finally by modifying the choice of .X; p/ it is possible to require p < p0 for any specified condition and given a stationary set S !1 , it is also possible to arrange that S 2 X and that X \ !1 2 S: Thus I \ V D .INS /V .
t u
Chapter 3
The nonstationary ideal
We consider in this chapter some combinatorial consequences of the assumption that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. We prove that if one assumes in addition that there is a measurable cardinal, then CH is false and moreover there is a projectively definable prewellordering of the reals of length !2 . The precise result is that if the nonstationary ideal is saturated and if P .!1 /# exists then !2 is the second uniform indiscernible. This result is really a special case of a more general covering lemma which we shall prove. We also prove that some additional assumption is necessary showing that it is consistent for the nonstationary ideal to be saturated together with !2 is not the second uniform indiscernible. At the heart of these results is an equivalence which does not involve the saturation of the nonstationary ideal. This equivalence centers on the study of (transitive) models which are iterable with respect to the process of forming generic ultrapowers. Many of the definitions and results of this chapter will be used throughout this book.
3.1
The nonstationary ideal and ı 12
We shall be concerned with transitive models of a fragment of ZFC which is rich enough to be preserved by the generic ultrapowers which we shall need to use. It is convenient to work with a variety of structures and for each of these there is an obvious fragment of ZFC which works. We give a single fragment which works uniformly. For our purposes it suffices to consider transitive sets M such that: (1) M is closed under the G¨odel operations. (2) Suppose that
M
R M
is a nonempty subset which is definable in M (with parameters from M ) such that for all f 2 R, f j˛ 2 R for all ˛ < dom.f /. Then there exist ˛ !1M and a function f W˛!M such that
52
3 The nonstationary ideal
a) f 2 M n R, b) for all ˇ < ˛, f jˇ 2 R; c) if ˛ D C 1 then for all g 2 R, if f j g then f j D g. We let ZFC be the corresponding fragment of ZFC. Remark 3.1. (1) The second condition is a form of “!1 -DC” which is stronger than “!1 -replacement ”. (2) At first glance, (2c) might seem strange in its formulation. Suppose though that M is simply a transitive set closed under the G¨odel operations and that R 2 M . Suppose that hW!!M is an element of R. Then there exists f W!C1!M such that f extends h and such that f … R. (3) Assuming ZFC, if is an ordinal of cofinality > !1 then V ZFC . Also, t u assuming ZFC, L.P .!1 // ZFC as does the transitive set H.!2 /. The following lemma is a standard variation of Łos’ theorem. Lemma 3.2. Suppose M is a transitive model of ZFC and that U is an ultrafilter on P .!1M / \ M . Let hN; Ei be the model obtained from the M -ultrapower, .M !1 /M =U where
® ¯ .M !1 /M D f W !1M ! M j f 2 M :
Then hN; Ei ZFC and the natural map j WM !N is an elementary embedding from the structure hM; 2i into hN; Ei.
t u
Let S be the set of stationary subsets of !1 . The partial order .S; / is not separative. It is easily verified that RO.S; / D RO.P .!1 /=INS /: Definition 3.3. Suppose M is a model of ZFC . (1) .P .!1 / n INS /M denotes the partial order .S; / computed in M . (2) A filter G .P .!1 / n INS /M is M -generic if G \ D ¤ ; for all predense sets D 2 M.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
53
(3) M “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 saturated ” if in M every predense subset of .P .!1 / n INS /M contains a predense subset of t u cardinality !1M in M . Remark 3.4. (1) “The nonstationary ideal is saturated” has several possible formulations within ZFC and they are not in general equivalent. (2) H.!2 / “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 saturated ”. (3) Suppose the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated, M is a transitive set, M ZFC , and P .!1 / M . Then M “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 saturated”: (4) Suppose that M is a transitive model of ZFC , .P .!1 //M 2 M; and that G .P .!1 / n INS /M is a filter such that G \ D ¤ ; for all dense sets D 2 M . Then G is M -generic. t u Definition 3.5. Suppose that M is a countable model of ZFC . A sequence hMˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of M if the following hold. (1) M0 D M . (2) j˛;ˇ W M˛ ! Mˇ is a commuting family of elementary embeddings. (3) For each C 1 < , G is M -generic for .P .!1 / n INS /M , M C1 is the M ultrapower of M by G and j ; C1 W M ! M C1 is the induced elementary embedding. (4) For each ˇ < if ˇ is a (nonzero) limit ordinal then Mˇ is the direct limit of ¹M˛ j ˛ < ˇº and for all ˛ < ˇ, j˛;ˇ is the induced elementary embedding. If is a limit ordinal then is the length of the iteration, otherwise the length of the iteration is ı where ı C 1 D . A model N is an iterate of M if it occurs in an iteration of M . The model M is iterable if every iterate of M is wellfounded. t u Remark 3.6. (1) In many instances a slightly weaker notion suffices. A model M is weakly iterable if for any iterate N of M , !1N is wellfounded. For elementary substructures of H.!2 / weak iterability is equivalent to iterability. (2) Suppose M is a countable iterable model of ZFC. Then: M “The nonstationary ideal is precipitous ”:
54
3 The nonstationary ideal
(3) It will be our convention that the assertion, j W M ! M is an embedding given by an iteration of M of length , abbreviates the supposition that there is an iteration hMˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < C 1i of M such that M D M and such that j D j0; : (4) Suppose M is a countable model of ZFC . Then any iteration of M has length at most !1 . (5) The assertion that a countable transitive model M is iterable is a …12 statement about M and therefore is absolute. (6) Suppose M is iterable and N M is an elementary substructure then in general N may not be iterable. This will follow from results later in this section. In fact here are two natural conjectures. a) Suppose there is no transitive inner model of ZFC containing the ordinals with a Woodin cardinal. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC and that M is iterable. Suppose X M . Then the transitive collapse of X is iterable. b) Suppose there is no transitive inner model of ZFC containing the ordinals with a Woodin cardinal for which the sharp of the model exists. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC and that M is iterable. Suppose M “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 saturated”: Suppose X M , NX 2 M and NX is countable in M where NX is the transitive collapse of X , 2 M and where M ZFC . Then NX is not iterable. t u Remark 3.7. We shall usually only consider iterations of M in the case that in M , INS is saturated. We caution that without this restriction it is possible that M be iterable but that H.!2 /M not be iterable. If in M , INS is saturated and if M is iterable then H.!2 /M is also iterable. This is a corollary of the next lemma. The correct notion of iterability for those transitive sets in which INS is not saturated is slightly different, see Definition 4.23. t u The next two lemmas record some basic facts about iterations that we shall use frequently. These are true in a much more general context. Lemma 3.8. Suppose that M and M are countable models of ZFC such that
(i) !1M D !1M ,
(ii) P .!1 /M D P .!1 /M .
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
55
Suppose that either
(iii) P 2 .!1 /M D P 2 .!1 /M , or (iv) M The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 saturated; and that hMˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of M . Then there corresponds uniquely an iteration W ˛ < ˇ < i hMˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ
of M such that for all ˛ < ˇ < : Mˇ
(1) !1
M
D !1 ˇ ;
(2) P .!1 /Mˇ D P .!1 /Mˇ ; (3) G˛ D G˛ . .M / 2 Mˇ and there is Suppose further that M 2 M . Then for all ˇ < , j0;ˇ an elementary embedding .M / kˇ W Mˇ ! j0;ˇ jM D kˇ ı j0;ˇ . such that j0;ˇ
Proof. This is immediate by induction on .
t u
Remark 3.9. The Lemma 3.8 has an obvious interpretation for arbitrary models. We shall for the most part only use it for wellfounded models. t u For the second lemma we need to use a stronger fragment of ZFC. There are obvious generalizations of this lemma, see Remark 3.11. Lemma 3.10. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC C Powerset C AC C †1 -Replacement in which the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Suppose hMˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of M such that M \ Ord. Then Mˇ is wellfounded for all ˇ < . Proof. Let .0 ; 0 ; 0 / be the least triple of ordinals in M such that: (1.1) M “cof. 0 / > !1 ”; (1.2) 0 < 0 ;
56
3 The nonstationary ideal
(1.3) there is an iteration, of V0
hNˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < 0 C 1i; \ M such that j0;0 .0 / not wellfounded.
Choose .0 ; 0 ; 0 / minimal relative to the lexicographical order. Thus 0 and 0 are limit ordinals. Let hNˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < 0 C 1i be an iteration of V0 \ M of length 0 such that j0;0 .0 / is not wellfounded. Choose ˇ < 0 and such that < j0;ˇ .0 / and such that jˇ ;0 . / is not wellfounded. Let hMˇ ; G˛ ; k˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < 0 C 1i be the induced iteration of M . By the minimality of 0 it follows that Mˇ is wellfounded for all ˇ < 0 . The key point is that for any ˇ 2 M \ Ord if G Coll.!; ˇ/ then the set M ŒG is 1 -correct. Thus .0 ; 0 ; 0 / can be defined in M . More precisely .0 ; 0 ; 0 / is least † 1 such that: (2.1) M “cof. 0 / > !1 ”; (2.2) 0 < 0 ; (2.3) there exist an ordinal ˇ 2 M , an M -generic filter G Coll.!; ˇ/, and an iteration, W ˛ < ˇ < 0 C 1i 2 M ŒG; hNˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ of V0 \ M of length 0 such that j0;0 .0 / not wellfounded. Further since Mˇ is wellfounded the same considerations apply to Mˇ and so .j0;ˇ .0 /; j0;ˇ . 0 /; j0;ˇ .0 // must be the triple as defined in V for Mˇ . However the tail of the iteration hNˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < 0 C 1i starting at ˇ is an iteration of j0;ˇ .V0 \ M / of length at most 0 and 0 C 1 j0;ˇ .0 / C 1: Further the image of by this iteration is not wellfounded. This is a contradiction t u since < j0;ˇ .0 /. Remark 3.11. Lemma 3.10 can be easily generalized to any iteration of generic elementary embeddings. A generic elementary embedding is an elementary embedding j WV !M VP where M is the transitive collapse of the ultrapower, Ult.V; E/ of V by E where E is a V -extender in V P . As usual, this ultrapower is computed using only functions in V . t u
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
57
Lemma 3.12. Let M be a transitive set such that M ZFC and such that P .!1 / M . Suppose the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated in M , X M and that X is countable. Let ˛ D X \ !1 and let Y D ¹f .˛/ j f 2 X º: Let NX D collapse.X /, let NY D collapse.Y /, and let j W NX ! NY be the induced ® ¯ embedding. Finally let G D A j A 2 NX ; and !1NX 2 j.A/ . Then (1) Y M . (2) j is an elementary embedding. (3) G is NX -generic for P .!1 / n INS .computed in NX /. (4) NY is the generic ultrapower of NX by G and j is the corresponding generic elementary embedding. Proof. This is straightforward. Since M ZFC it follows that Y M . The rest of the lemma follows provided we can show the following: Claim: Suppose A P .!1 / is a set of stationary subsets of !1 which defines a maximal antichain in P .!1 / n INS . Suppose A 2 X . Then X \ !1 2 S for some S 2 X \ A. Since the nonstationary ideal is saturated in M , every antichain has cardinality at most !1 . Thus suppose A D ¹S˛ j ˛ < !1 º is a maximal antichain of stationary subsets of !1 and A 2 X . Since A is a maximal antichain, the diagonal union 5¹S˛ W ˛ < !1 º contains a set C which is a club in !1 . Since X M , we can choose C such that t C 2 X in which case X \ !1 2 C . Therefore X \ !1 2 Sˇ for some ˇ < X \ !1 . u Corollary 3.13. Let M be a transitive set such that M ZFC and such that P .!1 / M . Suppose the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated in M , X M and that X is countable. Let NX be the transitive collapse of X and let !1X D X \ !1 . Then there is a wellfounded iteration j W NX ! N of NX such that j.!1X / D !1 and such that for all A 2 X \ H.!2 / j.AX / D A where AX is the image of A under the collapsing map.
58
3 The nonstationary ideal
Proof. Define an !1 sequence hX˛ W ˛ < !1 i of countable elementary substructures of M by induction on ˛: (1.1) X0 D X ; (1.2) for each ˛ < !1 , X˛C1 D ¹f .X˛ \ !1 / j f 2 X˛ ºI (1.3) for each limit ordinal ˛ < !1 , X˛ D [¹Xˇ j ˇ < ˛º: Let X!1 D [¹X˛ j ˛ < !1 º. For each ˛ !1 let
N˛ D collapse.X˛ /
and for each ˛ < ˇ !1 let j˛;ˇ W N˛ ! Nˇ the elementary embedding obtained from the collapse of the inclusion map X˛ Xˇ . Thus N0 D NX and by induction on ˛ !1 using Lemma 3.12, it follows that for each ˛ < !1 , N˛C1 is a generic ultrapower of N˛ and j˛;˛C1 W N˛ ! N˛C1 is the induced embedding. Therefore j0;!1 W N0 ! N!1 is obtained via an iteration of length !1 . Finally !1 X!1 . Hence j0;!1 .!1X / D !1 and j0;!1 .AX / D A for each set A 2 X \ H.!2 /.
t u
Lemma 3.14. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Let M be a transitive set such that M ZFC and such that P .!1 / M . Suppose M # exists. Then ¹X M j X is countable and MX is iterable º contains a club in P!1 .M /. Here MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. Fix a stationary set S P!1 .M /: It suffices to find a countable elementary substructure X M such that X 2 S and such that MX is iterable. Fix a cardinal such that M 2 V and such that V ZFC : Thus M # 2 V . Let Y V be a countable elementary substructure with M 2 Y and such that Y \ M 2 S . Let X D Y \ M . We claim that MX is iterable. To see this let
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
59
NY be the transitive collapse of Y and let W Y ! NY be the collapsing map. X D Y \ M and M # 2 Y and so .M # / D .MX /# . NY ZFC . Let G Coll.!; MX / be NY -generic. Let xG 2 R be the code of MX given by G, this is the real given by ¹.i; j / j p.i / 2 p.j / for some p 2 Gº: # Thus xG 2 NY ŒG and so NY ŒG is correct in V for …12 statements about xG . Therefore if MX is not iterable then MX is not iterable in NY ŒG. Assume toward a contradiction that ˇ 2 NY and that there is an iteration in NY ŒG of MX of length ˇ which is not wellfounded. Then by Lemma 3.8 this defines an iteration of NY of length ˇ t u which is not wellfounded, a contradiction since ˇ 2 NY . The next lemma gives the key property of iterable models. For this we shall need some mild coding. There is a natural partial map W R ! H.!1 / such that: (1) is onto; (2) (definability) is 1 -definable; (3) (absoluteness) If x 2 dom./ and .x/ D a then M “.x/ D a” where M is any ! model of ZFC containing x and a; (4) (boundedness) if A dom./ is †11 then ¹rank..x// j x 2 Aº is bounded by the least admissible relative to the parameters for A. For example one can code a set X 2 H.!1 / by relations P ! and E ! ! where h!; P; Ei Š hY [ !; X; 2i, Y is the transitive closure of X . Lemma 3.15. Suppose M is an iterable countable transitive model of ZFC . Suppose N is an iterate of M by a countable iteration of length ˛. Suppose x is a real which codes M and ˛. Then rank.N / < where is least ordinal which is admissible for x. Proof. Let x 2 R code M and let y 2 R code ˛. Then by the properties of the coding map , the set of z 2 dom./ such that .z/ is an iteration of M of length ˛ is t u †11 .x; y/. The result now follows by boundedness. Theorem 3.16. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. The following are equivalent. (1) ı 12 D !2 . (2) There exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / whose transitive collapse is iterable.
60
3 The nonstationary ideal
(3) For every countable X H.!2 /, the transitive collapse of X is iterable. (4) If C !1 is closed and unbounded, then C contains a closed unbounded subset which is constructible from a real. Proof. We fix some notation. Suppose x is a real and x # exists. For each ordinal let M.x # ; / be the model of x # . (1 ) 3) Fix X H.!2 /. Fix an ! sequence hi W i < !i of ordinals in X \ !2 which are cofinal in X \ !2 . For each i < ! let zi 2 X be a real such that i < rank.M.zi# ; !1 C 1//. Let N be the transitive collapse of X . For each i < ! let iN be the image of i under the collapsing map. Thus ¹iN j i < !º is cofinal in N \ Ord. Suppose j W .N; 2/ ! .M; E/ is an iteration of N . Then ¹j.iN / W i < !º is cofinal in OrdM . The first key point is the following. Suppose that j.!1N / is wellfounded. Then for each i < !, j.M.zi# ; !1N C 1// is wellfounded since by absoluteness: j.M.zi# ; !1N C 1// Š M.zi# ; j.!1N C 1//: Thus: (1.1) For any iterate .M; E/ of N if !1M is wellfounded then M is wellfounded. By assumption the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated. Thus if G P .!1 / n INS is V -generic for the partial order .P .!1 / n INS ; / and if j W H.!2 / ! M is the induced embedding then j.!1 / D !2 D OrdH.!2 / . This is expressible in H.!2 / as a first order sentence. This is the second key point. Thus: (2.1) If M is a wellfounded iterate of N and if M is a generic ultrapower of M then M is wellfounded. From (1.1) and (2.1) it follows that N is iterable. (2 ) 4) Fix X H.!2 / such that NX is iterable where NX is the transitive collapse of X . It suffices to show that if C 2 X and if C !1 is closed and unbounded then C contains a closed unbounded subset which is constructible from a real. This is because if (4) fails then there must be a counterexample in X . Fix C 2 X such that C is a club in !1 . Let z be a real which codes NX . Let CX D C \ X . By Corollary 3.13 there is an iteration of length !1 j W NX ! N such that j.CX / D C .
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
61
By Lemma 3.15, if ˛ is admissible relative to z and if k W NX ! M is any iteration of length ˛ then k.!1NX / D ˛. Therefore if ˛ < !1 is admissible relative to z then ˛ 2 C . Thus D D ¹˛ < !1 j L˛ Œz L!1 Œzº is a closed unbounded subset of C and D 2 LŒz. (4 ) 1) This is a standard fact. The only additional hypothesis required is that for all x 2 R, x # exists and this is an immediate consequence of the assumption that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated. Suppose !1 < ˛ < !2 . Fix a wellordering <˛ of !1 of length ˛. Choose a club C !1 such that for all 2 C ,
rank.<˛ j / <
where is the least element of C greater than . Let D C be a closed unbounded subset such that D 2 LŒz for some real z. We can assume by changing z if necessary that D is definable in LŒz from z and finitely many indiscernibles of LŒz greater than or equal to !1 . Further by replacing z by z # we can assume that D is definable in LŒz from z and !1 . Thus for each 2 D rank.<˛ j / < rank.M.z # ; C 1// and so ˛ < rank.M.z # ; !1 C 1//: Hence
!2 D sup¹rank M.z # ; !1 C 1/ j z 2 Rº:
t u
Theorem 3.17. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that ı 12 D !2 . P .!1 /# exists. Then Proof. P .!1 /# exists and so H.!2 /# exists. By Lemma 3.14, there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / whose transitive collapse is iterable. The theorem follows by Theorem 3.16. t u There is a version of Theorem 3.16 which does not require the hypothesis that the nonstationary ideal is saturated. Remark 3.18. The proof that (2) follows from (4) in Theorem 3.19 plays a fundamental role in the analysis of the Pmax -extension and its generalizations. This analysis is of course the main subject of this book. t u Theorem 3.19. The following are equivalent. (1) There exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / whose transitive collapse is iterable. (2) For every countable X H.!2 /, the transitive collapse of X is iterable.
62
3 The nonstationary ideal
(3) For all reals x, x # exists and if C !1 is closed and unbounded, then C contains a closed unbounded subset which is constructible from a real. (4) If C !1 is closed and unbounded, then there exists x 2 R such that ¹˛ < !1 j L˛ Œx is admissibleº C: Proof. This is similar to the proof of Theorem 3.16. (1 ) 3). As in the proof of Theorem 3.16 it follows that if C !1 is closed and unbounded, then C contains a closed unbounded subset which is constructible from a real. It remains to show that for every z 2 R, z # exists. Since X H.!2 / we need only show this for z 2 X . Fix z 2 X \ R. Let M be the transitive collapse of X . We prove that every uncountable cardinal of V is a regular cardinal in LŒz. From this it follows that z # exists by Jensen’s Covering Lemma. In fact we prove the following claim. Claim: Suppose N is a countable transitive model of ZFC and that N is iterable. Suppose that t is a real in N . Then !1N is a regular cardinal in LŒt . The proof of the claim is straightforward. Let S be the set of < !1N such that is singular in L! N Œt . Assume toward a 1 contradiction that S is stationary in N . Let j W N ! N be an iteration of N of length !1 . Thus j.!1N / D !1 . Let G be V -generic for Coll(!; !1 ). In V ŒG let U .P .!1 / n INS /N be N -generic with j.S / 2 U: Let N be the generic ultrapower of N by U and let k W N ! N be the corresponding elementary embedding. Thus !1V 2 k.j.S // and so !1V is singular in L! N Œt a contradiction. 1
Thus there exists club C !1N such that C 2 N and such that for all 2 C , is a regular cardinal in L! N Œt . Finally suppose that !1N is not a regular cardinal in LŒt . 1
Choose ˇ < !1 such that !1N is singular in Lˇ Œt . Let j W N ! N
be an iteration of N of length ˇ. Thus ˇ !1N and so !1N is singular in L! N Œt . 1 However L! N Œt D j.L! N Œt /: 1
1
This is a contradiction since 2 j.C / and this proves the claim. From the claim it follows easily that every uncountable cardinal in V is a regular cardinal of LŒz. Let be an uncountable cardinal in V . Let V ŒG be a generic extension of V in which is countable. In V ŒG let j W M ! M be an iteration of !1N
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
63
M of length . By Lemma 3.15, it follows that j.!1M / D . By absoluteness M is iterable in V ŒG and so M is iterable in V ŒG. Hence, by the claim, is a regular cardinal in LŒz. (3 ) 4). This is immediate. (4 ) 2). This is quite similar to the argument that (1 ) 3) in the proof of Theorem 3.16. Suppose that X H.!2 / is a countable elementary substructure and let N be the transitive collapse of X . There are two key claims.
(1.1) Suppose that N is an iterate of N such that !1N is wellfounded. Then N is wellfounded. (1.2) Suppose that N is a wellfounded iterate of N and that N is a generic ultrapower of N . Then .!1 /N D N \ Ord: For each x 2 R and for each ˛ !1 let .x; ˛/ be the least ordinal such that L Œx is admissible and such that ˛ < . Let Ax D ¹˛ < !1 j L˛ Œx is admissibleº: It follows from (3) that ¹.x; !1 / j x 2 Rº is cofinal in !2 . Suppose that x 2 R, y 2 R and that .x; !1 / < .y; !1 /. Then by reflection there must exist a closed unbounded set C !1 such that for all ˛ 2 C , .x; ˛/ < .y; ˛/: By (3) there exists z 2 R such that Az C . Since X H.!2 /, there exists a sequence hxi W i < !i of reals such that (2.1) ¹.xi ; !1 / j i < !º is cofinal in X \ !2 , (2.2) for each ˛ 2 Axi C2 , .xi ; ˛/ < .xiC1 ; ˛/: N is the transitive collapse of X and so by absoluteness it follows that for each i < !, .xi ; !1N / is the image of .xi ; !1 / under the collapsing map. Thus if j W N ! .M; E/ is an iteration, ¹j..xi ; !1N // j i < !º is cofinal in OrdM . We prove (1.1). Let j W N ! N be the given iteration.
64
3 The nonstationary ideal
Let be the wellfounded part of OrdN . Thus for each x 2 N \ R, L Œx is admissible. However !1N is wellfounded and so for each x 2 N \ R, L! N Œx is 1 admissible. Therefore by (2.2), for each i < !,
.xi ; !1N / < : Thus by absoluteness, for each i < !,
j..xi ; !1N // D .xi ; !1N /
and so D OrdN . This proves (1.1). (1.2) follows from the following consequence of (4). Suppose that f W !1 ! !1 . Then there exists x 2 R such that for all ˛ 2 Ax , f .˛/ < .x; ˛/: This is a first order property of H.!2 / and so it must hold in N . The second property of N that we shall need is that for each x 2 R \ N , .x; !1N / 2 N ; i. e. N 9Œ > !1 and L Œx is admissible: Again this (trivially) holds in H.!2 / and so it must hold in N . Let j W N ! N be an iteration of length 1. Thus Ord \ N is an initial segment of OrdN function f W !1N ! !1N
. Fix a
such that f 2 N . It suffices to prove that
j .f /.!1N / < Ord \ N :
Let x 2 R \ N be such that for all ˛ 2 Ax \ !1N , f .˛/ < .x; ˛/: By the remarks above,
.x; !1N /
2 N . Thus by absoluteness,
.x; !1N / D ..x; !1N //N
:
Therefore by the elementarity of j ,
j .f /.!1N / < .x; !1N / < Ord \ N : This proves that
j .!1N / D Ord \ N
and this proves (1.2). The iterability of N is an immediate consequence of (1.1) and (1.2). This proves (2). t u We shall need the following theorem of .Shelah 1987/ which is discussed in Section 2.4.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
65
Theorem 3.20 (Shelah). Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal. Then there is a semiproper partial order P such that; (1) P is homogeneous and ı-cc, (2) V P “INS is saturated”.
t u
Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal and that ı 12 D !2 in V P where P is the partial order indicated in Theorem 3.20. Then since P is homogeneous it follows that if j is the generic elementary embedding of V P corresponding to the nonstationary ideal then j jı 2 V . We shall need the following technical lemma which is a minor improvement of the analogous result in .Hjorth 1993/. Suppose that for all x 2 R, x # exists. For each n !, n > 0, let un be the th n uniform indiscernible. We define a set Z of bounded subsets of u! and a map W Z ! V as follows. Suppose X um for some m < !. Then X 2 Z if and only if for all y 2 R, if A !1 and if A 2 LŒX; y then A is constructible from a real. Thus Z \ P .!1 / is the set of subsets of !1 which are constructible from a real. Suppose X !1 and X 2 Z. Let t 2 R be such that X 2 LŒt . We can choose t such that X is definable in LŒt from !1V and indiscernibles above !1V . .X / D j.X / where j W LŒt ! LŒt is any elementary embedding with critical point !1V and such that j.!1V / D u2 . It is easily verified that .X / is unambiguously defined. The definition does not depend on the choice of either j or t . For the general case we define .X / by induction on sup X . Suppose X ˛, ˛ < unC1 and X 2 Z. Let t 2 R be such that in LŒt there is a bijection f W un ! ˛: Let Y D f 1 .X /. Then Y 2 Z. We define .X / D .f /..Y //: It is straightforward to show that this is unambiguously defined. Suppose X unC1 and X 2 Z. Then .X / D [¹.X \ ˛/ j ˛ < unC1 º: Note that if ADL.R/ holds then Z contains all the bounded subsets of u! which are in L.R/. Lemma 3.21. Suppose that for all x 2 R, x # exists and that u2 D !2 . Suppose X 2 Z. Then .X / 2 Z. Proof. This is by the key argument of .Hjorth 1993/. The proof is included in the proof of Lemma 3.23. t u
66
3 The nonstationary ideal
We shall need the following theorem due independently to Martin and Welch. Theorem 3.22 (Martin, Welch). Suppose that ı 12 D !2 and that for every x 2 R, x # exists. Then for every x 2 R, x exists. u t Theorem 3.22 can be improved, obtaining much more than for every x 2 R, x exists. It should be the case that the hypothesis implies 12 -Determinacy but this is still an open question. For each t 2 R let LŒ; t denote the smallest transitive inner model N of ZFC containing the ordinals and t such that N is closed under and such that \ N 2 N . Lemma 3.23. Suppose that for all x 2 R, x # exists and that u2 D !2 . Suppose x 2 R. (1) For each n < !, P .un / \ LŒ; x Z: (2) There is an elementary embedding j W LŒ; x ! N such that for all X 2 Vu! \ LŒ; x, j.X / D .X /, and such that j j L˛ Œ; x 2 LŒ; x for all ˛ 2 Ord. Proof. We first prove (1). Suppose F is a function and t 2 R. For each ordinal ˛ define J˛ ŒF; t by induction on ˛. J˛C1 ŒF; t is the closure of J˛ ŒF; t [ ¹J˛ ŒF; t º [ ¹J˛ ŒF; t \ F º [ ¹F .X / j X 2 dom.F / \ J˛ ŒF; t º under the G¨odel operations. By the definitions, we prove (1) if we prove the following claim. Claim: Suppose t 2 R, ˛ is an ordinal and for all n < !, P .un / \ J˛ Œ; t Z: Suppose m < !, y 2 R, B um and that B 2 J˛C1 Œ; t . Then every set A !1 such that A 2 LŒB; y is constructible from a real. The argument for this is similar to the proof of Theorem 2.3 in .Hjorth 1993/. We sketch the argument. Since ı12 D !2 (and for all x 2 R, x # exists), by Theorem 3.22, for all x 2 R, x exists. Suppose the claim fails. Fix t 2 R and ˛ 2 Ord for which the claim fails. Fix a ordinal such that V ZFC and ˛ < . Let X V be an elementary substructure such that X has cardinality !1 , !1 X and such that X \ !2 has cofinality !. The latter condition is the key condition. Let M be the transitive collapse of X . Choose an ! sequence, hzk W k < !i, of reals in M such that !2M D sup ¹k j k < !º where for each k < !, k is the least indiscernible of LŒzk above !1 . The point of course is that !2M D uM 2 and so this sequence exists.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
67
Let z 2 R code the pair .hzk W k < !i; t /. z exists and so F \ LŒz; F is an ultrafilter in LŒz; F where F is the club filter on !1 . Let ˛ M be the image of ˛ under the transitive collapse of X . Let .J˛ Œ; t /M be the image of J˛ Œ; t under the collapsing map and let M be the image of . Thus .J˛ Œ; t /M D J˛M Œ M ; t : The key point is that J˛M Œ M ; t 2 LŒz; F and that M jJ˛M Œ M ; t 2 LŒz; F : The verification that M jJ˛M Œ M ; t 2 LŒz; F follows from the fact that for all m < !, P .um / \ J˛ Œ; t Z together with the observation that there is a map e 2 LŒz; F such that for all B 2 Z \ X , e.BM / D M .BM /. Here BM is the image of B under the collapsing map. The latter observation is easily verified as follows. By the choice of X , !1 X and so M is uniquely determined by the map W Z \ X \ P .!1 / ! V M where .B/ D .B/ \ uM 2 and u2 is the image of u2 under the collapsing map. The M map is computed from exactly as and Z are computed from the set of B !1 such that B is constructible from a real. For this one uses the sequence hzi W i < !i. It is straightforward to verify that for B 2 Z \ X \ P .!1 /, M .B/ D j.B/ \ uM 2 where j W LŒz; F ! LŒz; j.F /;
is the ultrapower embedding as computed in LŒz; F . Fix m < !, B um , A !1 and x 2 R such that B 2 J˛C1 Œ; t , A 2 LŒB; x and A … Z. We may assume that ¹A; B; xº X . Let BM be the image of B under the collapsing map and let AM be the image of A. Since !1 X , A D AM . Thus BM 2 J˛M C1 Œ M ; t and A 2 LŒBM ; x. But J˛M C1 Œ M ; t 2 LŒz; F and LŒz; F LŒz . Therefore A 2 LŒz , a contradiction since A … Z and so A is not constructible from a real. We now prove (2). The key is to represent as the embedding derived from an ultrapower. For each x 2 R we abuse notation slightly and let Q LŒ; x!1 D [¹LŒ; x!1 \ LŒ; y j y 2 Rº: By (1) we can form the ultrapower Q LŒ; x!1 =F where F is the club filter on !1 . The point of course is that by (1), F is an ultrafilter on [¹P .!1 / \ LŒ; y j y 2 Rº: The filter F is countably complete and so the ultrapower is wellfounded.
68
3 The nonstationary ideal
For each x 2 R let
jx W LŒ; x ! Mx
be the induced elementary embedding. It follows that for all X 2 Z \ LŒ; x, jx .X / D .X /. For each x 2 R let Ex be the .u1 ; u! / extender derived from jx . Thus Ex 2 LŒ; x. Let Nx D Ult .LŒ; x; Ex / and let jx0 W LŒ; x ! Nx be the corresponding embedding. The ultrapower Ult .LŒ; x; Ex / is wellfounded since it embeds into Mx . Since Ex 2 LŒ; x it follows that jx0 j L˛ Œ; x 2 LŒ; x for all ˛ 2 Ord. Further by the definition of Ex it follows that jx D jx0 when restricted t u to Vu! \ LŒ; x. The proof of part 2 of Lemma 3.23 shows that assuming that u2 D !2 , the map is obtained from a restricted ultrapower. Theorem 3.24. Assume the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Then the following are equivalent. (1) ı12 D !2 . (2) There is an inner model N of ZFC containing the ordinals and an elementary embedding k W N ! N such that if G .P .!1 / n INS ; / is V -generic and if j WV !M is the associated generic elementary embedding then a) kjN˛ 2 N for all ˛; b) j jN! D kjN! . where ! D sup ¹ n j n < !º and h n j n < !i is the critical sequence of k. Proof. (1) implies (2) by the previous lemma. We now prove that (2) implies (1). Fix a cardinal such that jVı j D ı and such that cof.ı/ > !1 . Thus Vı ZFC and .N! ; kjN! / 2 Vı : Let X Vı be a countable elementary substructure such that N! ; kjN! 2 X . We show that X \ H.!2 / is iterable. The relevant point is that .N! ; kjN! / is naturally a structure that can be iterated and further all of its iterates are wellfounded. Let k! D kjN! . The fact that .N! ; k! / is iterable is a standard fact. k N and
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
69
N contains the ordinals, therefore .N; k/ is iterable; i. e. any iteration of set length is wellfounded. The image of .N! ; k! / under an iteration of .N; k/ of length ˛ is simply the ˛ th iterate of .N! ; k! /. Let MX be the transitive collapse of X . Let NX! be the image of N! under the collapsing map and let kX! be the image of k! . We claim that .NX! ; kX! / is iterable. This too is a standard fact. Any iterate of .NX! ; kX! / embeds into an iterate of .N! ; k! / which is wellfounded since .N! ; k! / is iterable. The image of .NX! ; kX! / under any iteration of MX is an iterate of .NX! ; kX! /. This is an immediate consequence of the definitions and the hypothesis, (2), of the lemma. Therefore the image of !2 under any iteration of MX is wellfounded and so by Lemma 3.8, the transitive collapse of X \H.!2 / is iterable. But then by Theorem 3.16, ı12 D !2 . t u Combining Shelah’s theorem with Theorem 3.17 yields a new upper bound for the consistency strength of ZFC C “For every real x, x # exists” C “ı12 D !2 ”: With an additional argument the upper bound can be further refined to give the following theorem. One corollary is that one cannot prove significantly more than 12 -Determinacy from the hypothesis of Theorem 3.22. It is proved in .Koellner and Woodin 2010/ that 1 3 -Determinacy implies that there exists an inner model with two Woodin cardinals. Therefore Theorem 3.22 cannot be improved to obtain 13 -Determinacy. Theorem 3.25. Suppose ı is a Mahlo cardinal and that there exists ı < ı such that: (i) ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı /; (ii) Vı Vı . Then there is a semiproper partial order P such that V P ZFC C “For every real x, x # exists” C “ı12 D !2 ”: If in addition ı is a Woodin cardinal then V P “INS is !2 -saturated”: Proof. The partial order is simply the partial order P defined by Shelah in his proof of Theorem 3.20. We shall need a little more information from this proof which we sketched in Section 2.4. The partial order P is obtained as an iteration of length ı, hP˛ W ˛ < ıi, such that: (1.1) hP˛ W ˛ < i V for all < ı such that jV j D ; (1.2) hP˛ W ˛ < i is definable in V for all < ı such that jV j D ; (1.3) For each < ı, if is strongly inaccessible then P D [¹P˛ j ˛ < º:
70
3 The nonstationary ideal
By (1.2) the definition of hP˛ W ˛ < i for suitable is absolute, more precisely suppose that N is a transitive model of ZFC, < ı and that N D V : Suppose that jV j D . Then hP˛ W ˛ < i is the iteration of length as defined in N . We note by (1.3), since ı is a Mahlo cardinal, the partial order P is ı-cc. Thus if GP is V -generic then H.!2 /V ŒG D Vı ŒG: Let ı < ı be least such that ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı / and such that Vı Vı . Since Vı# exists it follows that ı has cofinality !. Therefore we can construct in V an L.Vı /-generic filter H Q where Q is the poset for adding a generic subset of ı . The point is that since ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı / it follows that <ı -DC holds in L.Vı /. Thus L.Vı /ŒH ZFC and standard arguments show that ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı /ŒH . Suppose that G P is V -generic and let Gı D G \ Pı : Thus Gı is L.Vı /ŒH -generic and so since Pı is P as defined in L.Vı /ŒH it follows that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated in L.Vı /ŒH ŒGı . Further since Vı Vı and since the iteration for P is locally definable it follows that H.!2 /L.Vı /ŒH ŒGı H.!2 /V ŒG : This is because H.!2 /L.Vı /ŒH ŒGı D Vı ŒH ŒGı and H.!2 /V ŒG D Vı ŒG: Let Y L.Vı /ŒH ŒGı be a countable elementary substructure containing infinitely many indiscernibles for L.Vı /ŒH ŒGı above ı . Let X D Y \ H.!2 /L.Vı /ŒH ŒGı : Let N be the transitive collapse of Y and let M be the transitive collapse of X . Thus N “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated ” and further N is a rank initial segment of L.N / and so by Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.10, N is iterable. However M D H.!2 /N and so M is iterable. Finally X H.!2 /V ŒG and so by Theorem 3.16, ı 12 D !2 in V ŒG. t u This upper bound is somewhat technical. It does follow from more natural assumptions. For example if ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı /, Vı# exists and if cof.ı/ D !1 then in L.Vı /, ı satisfies all the necessary requirements.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
71
Note that this upper bound is strictly stronger than the assumption that ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı / and Vı# exists. This is because (with notation as in the statement of the theorem) ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı / and Vı# exists. Remark 3.26. We do not know if the hypothesis needed to obtain ı 1 D !2 2 can be weakened below that of Theorem 3.25. A natural question is whether the assumption that ı is Mahlo can be reduced to the assumption that ı is inaccessible. To obtain both ı 1 D !2 2 and that INS is !2 -saturated, the hypothesis indicated in Theorem 3.25 is plausibly optimal. t u The next theorem has been considerably improved by G. Hjorth. One of the main theorems of .Hjorth 1993/ shows that the hypothesis that the nonstationary ideal is saturated in unnecessary and that the conclusion can be strengthened to include all of the usual regularity properties. In fact Hjorth’s theorem is an immediate consequence of Lemma 3.23. The point is that the Martin-Solovay tree T2 is easily seen to be in LŒ. Lemma 3.23 is simply a mild strengthening of Hjorth’s result. We include our original proof. Theorem 3.27. Assume that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that !2 D ı 12 : 1 Then every uncountable †3 set contains a perfect subset.
Proof. The key point is that if M is a countable transitive model of ZFC which is iterable then †13 statements with parameters from M which are true in M are true in V. Suppose that A R is an uncountable †13 set. Choose X H.!2 / such that X is countable and such that X contains the parameters for the †13 definition of A. Let M be the transitive collapse of X . By Theorem 3.16, M is iterable. Suppose G is M -generic for .P .!1 / n INS /M . Let N be the generic ultrapower of M by G. Let AM be A as computed in M . M is iterable hence AM D A \ M . Similarly let AN be A as computed in N . M is iterable and so N is iterable. Hence AN D A \ N . Since A is uncountable it follows that there exists an injective function f W !1 ! A such that f 2 X . Let fM be the image of f under the collapsing map. Thus fM D f j˛ where ˛ D !1M . Let hSk W k < !i be an enumeration of .P .!1 / n INS /M . For each x 2 2! let Gx D ¹Sk j x.k/ D 1º. By a routine construction there is a perfect set Z 2! such that: (1.1) Gx is M -generic for each x 2 Z; (1.2) tx ¤ ty for all x 2 Z, y 2 Z such that x ¤ y.
72
3 The nonstationary ideal
where for each x 2 Z, tx is the real in the generic ultrapower of M by Gx which is given by fM . The map F W Z ! R defined by F .x/ D tx is continuous and by the remarks above tx 2 A for each x 2 Z. Thus ¹tx j x 2 Zº is a perfect set contained in A. t u As a corollary to the previous theorem we obtain the following theorem which ı 12 from the shows that some additional assumption is required to prove that !2 D saturation of the nonstationary ideal. Theorem 3.28. Assume that ZFC C “There is a Woodin cardinal ” is consistent. Then so is ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated” C “ı12 ¤ !2 ”: Proof. A wellordering of the reals is a good 13 wellordering of the reals if the wellordering has length !1 and the set of reals which code proper initial segments of the wellordering is a †13 set. By the results of .Martin and Steel 1994/, if ZFC C “There is a Woodin cardinal ” is consistent then so is ZFC C “There is a Woodin cardinal ” C “There is a good 13 wellordering of the reals ”: Therefore we may assume that ı is a Woodin cardinal in V and that there is a good 13 wellordering of the reals. Let P be the partial order defined by Shelah in his proof of Theorem 3.20. Again we shall need a little more information from this proof. What is required is easily verified from the sketch provided in Section 2.4. The partial order P is semiproper and it is obtained as an iteration of length ı, hP˛ W ˛ < ıi, such that for all ˛ < ı, jP˛ j < ı. Let G P be V -generic. Then it follows that †13 statements are absolute between V and V ŒG. Let be a good 13 wellordering of the reals in V . Let be a †13 formula which in V defines the set of reals which code initial segments of . Let A be the set defines in V and let AG be the set which defines in V ŒG. By absoluteness A AG . By absoluteness again, every real in AG codes a countable sequence of reals and further if x; y 2 AG then the sequences coded by x and y are equal or one is an initial segment of the other. Therefore since A AG , every real in AG codes an initial segment of and so R \ V is a †13 set in V ŒG. The nonstationary ideal is saturated in V ŒG. If ı 1 D !2
2
in V ŒG then by Theorem 3.27, in V ŒG every uncountable †13 contains a perfect set. 1 t u This is a contradiction since R \ V is a †3 set in V ŒG.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
73
Remark 3.29. Theorem 3.28 does not really seem optimal. For example consider the following question. Suppose the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that AD holds in L.R/. Is ı 12 D !2 ? The proof of Theorem 3.28 does not generalize to answer this question. One really seems to need a deeper analysis of when the forcing iteration to make the nonstationary ı 12 D !2 . A typical question is the following. ideal on !1 saturated necessarily forces Suppose V is a core model and that ı is the least ordinal satisfying that ı is a Woodin cardinal in L.Vı /. Let G be L.Vı /-generic for the iteration which forces the nonstationary ideal saturated. Is ı 12 D !2 in L.Vı /ŒG? At this point there is not even a good understanding of how the forcing iteration for making the nonstationary ideal saturated adds any reals. For example (for the specific iteration indicated in Section 2.4) does the iteration add any reals which are V -generic for proper forcing? t u We shall need a slight variation on the notion of iterability. Definition 3.30. Suppose A R and M is a countable transitive iterable model of ZFC . The model M is A-iterable if for all iterations j WM !N j.A \ M / D A \ N where j.A \ M / D [¹j. / j 2 M and Aº:
t u
Remark 3.31. (1) This is really a strengthening of the notion of weak iterability. Suppose A is the complete …11 set. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC and that for any iteration j W M ! N , j.A \ M / D A \ N . Then M is weakly iterable. (2) In most (but not all) cases when we are considering M which are A-iterable we shall also have that A \ M 2 M . t u One easy consequence of the definition of A-iterability is the following theorem which in some sense generalizes the theorem of AD which states that every !1 union 1 of borel sets is † 2 . We require the following definition. Suppose that A R. A set B R is †11 .A/ if it is †1 definable in the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i †11 .A/
if it †1 definable in this structure (without from parameters. The set B is parameters). Note that it is our convention that R n A is †11 .A/.
74
3 The nonstationary ideal
Theorem 3.32. Suppose that A R and that there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that hX; A \ X; 2i hH.!2 /; A; 2i and such that the transitive collapse of X is B-iterable for each set B which is †11 .A/. Suppose that there exists a sequence hB˛ W ˛ < !1 i of borel sets such that A D [¹B˛ j ˛ < !1 º: 1 Then A is † 2 . Proof. Fix a †11 set universal for all
1 † 1
Similarly fix a
U RR sets. For each x 2 R let
†11 .A/
Ux D ¹y 2 R j .x; y/ 2 U º: set UA R R
1 x 2 R let universal for all † 1 .A/ sets. For each ¯ ® A Ux D y 2 R j .x; y/ 2 U A : Fix a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that hX; A \ X; 2i hH.!2 /; A; 2i and such that the transitive collapse of X is U A -iterable. Thus there exists a set R of cardinality @1 such that 2 X and such that A D [¹Ux˛ j x 2 º: Let M be the transitive collapse of X and let M be the image of under the collapsing map. Thus M D \ M . Let be the union of all sets j. M / such that j W M ! M is a countable iteration of M . Thus since, by Corollary 3.13, there exists an iteration j W M ! M
of length !1 such that j. M / D . Let A D [¹Ux j x 2 º: 1 Clearly A is † 2 . Further since , A A . Finally since M is U A -iterable it follows that for each x 2 , Ux A and so A D A : 1 Thus A is † t u 2 .
Theorem 3.34 is the generalization of Theorem 3.19 to the case of A-iterability. We require a minor variation of Corollary 3.13. The proof is identical to that of Corollary 3.13, using an appropriately modified version of Lemma 3.12.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
75
Lemma 3.33. Suppose X †2 H.!2 / is a countable †2 -elementary substructure and let M be the transitive collapse of X . Suppose that M ZFC : Let N D ¹f .s/ j f 2 X; s 2 !1
76
3 The nonstationary ideal
By Lemma 3.33, the embedding jX is given by an iteration of MX . Therefore there exists a sequence hXi W i < !i of elements of X such that for all i < !, .Xi ; jXi ; NXi / 2 XiC1 \ X and such that X D [¹Xi j i < !º: We now fix a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that hX; A \ X; 2i hH.!2 /; A; 2i: We must prove that the transitive collapse, MX , of X is A-iterable. For each i < ! let Ni be the image of NXi under the transitive collapse of X and let ji W MXi ! Ni the image of jXi . Thus for all i < !, (2.1) .MXi ; ji ; Ni / 2 NiC1 , (2.2) Ni †2 NiC1 , (2.3) ji W MXi ! Ni is an iteration map, and further MX D [¹Ni j i < !º: By Theorem 3.19, MX is iterable. Suppose j W MX ! M is a countable iteration. Then for each i < !, j.ji / W MXi ! j.Ni / is an iteration and so for each i < !, j jNi W Ni ! j.Ni / is an iteration. For each i < !, Ni is an iterate of MXi and MXi is A iterable. Hence Ni is A-iterable. Finally M D [¹j.Ni / j i < !º; and for each i < !, Ni 2 NiC1 . Hence M D ¹j.Ni / j i < !º: Therefore j.A \ MX / D [¹j.A \ Ni / j i < !º D [¹A \ j.Ni / j i < !º D A \ M: This verifies that MX is A-iterable.
t u
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
77
Lemma 3.35. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Suppose A R and that B is weakly homogeneously Suslin for each set B which is projective in A. Let M be a transitive set such that M ZFC , P .!1 / M , and such that M # exists. Then ¹X M j X is countable and MX is A-iterableº contains a club in P!1 .M /. Here MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. We recall that if N is a countable transitive model of ZFC and if j W N ! N is a countable iteration then j.A \ N / is defined to be the set j.A \ N / D [¹j.Z/ j Z 2 N; and Z Aº: We first prove the lemma in the case that M D H.!2 /. Set M0 D H.!2 /. Let G be V -generic for the Levy collapse of 2!1 to !. Thus M0 is countable in V ŒG. Let T be a weakly homogeneous tree in V such that A D pŒT . Define AG to be the projection of T in V ŒG. It is a standard fact that AG does not depend on the choice of T . Let T be a tree in V such that in V ŒG, pŒT D R n pŒT : The tree T exists since T is weakly homogeneous in V and since G is generic for a partial order of size less than the least measurable cardinal. Finally let S be a weakly homogeneous tree in V such that B D pŒS where B is the set of reals which code A-iterable transitive models of ZFC . Since B is projective in A, the tree S exists. Further we have that in V ŒG, BG is the set of reals which code AG -iterable transitive models of ZFC where BG is the projection of S in V ŒG. We claim that M0 is AG -iterable in V ŒG. Let j0 W M0 ! N0 be a countable iteration of M0 in V ŒG. Then by Lemma 3.8, there corresponds an iteration j W V ! .N; E/ V ŒG such that N0 D j.M0 / and j jM0 D j0 . By Lemma 3.10, .N; E/ is wellfounded and we identify N with its transitive collapse. Note that j.A/ D pŒj.T / \ N and that j0 .A/ D j.A/. It suffices to show that in V ŒG, pŒT D pŒj.T /. However in V ŒG; (1.1) pŒT pŒj.T /, (1.2) pŒT pŒj.T /, (1.3) pŒT D R n pŒT , (1.4) pŒj.T / \ pŒj.T / D ;.
78
3 The nonstationary ideal
Condition (1.4) holds by absoluteness since by elementarity of j it must hold in N . From these conditions it follows immediately that pŒT D pŒj.T / in V ŒG. Thus M0 is AG -iterable in V ŒG. Let x0 be a real in V ŒG which codes M0 . Thus x0 2 BG and so x0 2 pŒS . In V fix a set Z P!1 .M0 / such that Z is stationary. Let be large enough such that T; S 2 V and such that V is admissible. Let X V be a countable elementary substructure such that T 2 X , S 2 X and such that X \ M0 2 Z. Let NX be the transitive collapse of X and let SN be the image of S under the collapsing map. Finally let GN be N -generic for the Levy collapse of .2!1 /N . Thus by the argument above we have that there exists a real xN 2 N ŒGN such that xN 2 pŒSN and xN codes H.!2 /N . Therefore xN 2 pŒS and so H.!2 /N is A-iterable. However H.!2 /N is the transitive collapse of X \ H.!2 / and X \ M0 2 Z. This proves the lemma in the case that M D H.!2 /. The general case follows using Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.14. The point is that if N is a countable transitive iterable model of ZFC in which the nonstationary ideal is saturated and if A is any set of reals then N is A-iterable if and only if H.!2 /N is A-iterable. t u The covering theorems are more easily proved using the following theorem which is a routine generalization of the (correct) results of .Woodin 1983/ from the setting of L.R/ to that of L.A; R/. We shall only need parts (2) and (3). For the sake of completeness we include a sketch of the proof. Theorem 3.36. Suppose A R, L.A; R/ AD and that G Coll.!;
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
79
It is a standard fact that AD implies **uniformization and that **uniformization implies that every set of reals has the property of Baire. Assume **uniformization and that V D L.A; R/ where A R. Then **AC holds; i. e. if F W R ! V n ¹;º is a function then there exists a function H WR!V such that ¹x j H.x/ 2 F .x/º is comeager in R. This easily generalizes as follows. Suppose Q is a partial order with a countable dense set and let 2 V Q be a term for a real. For each condition p 2 Q define an ideal I p as follows. Let S be the Stone space of Q. I p D ¹Z R j ¹G Q j p 2 G; IG ./ 2 Zº is meager in Sº where if G Q is a filter then IG is the associated (partial) interpretation map. For a comeager collection of filters G Q, IG ./ is defined; i. e. for each n 2 ! there exists m 2 ! such that for some q 2 G, q .n/ D m: p We say Z R is I -positive if Z … I p . The set Z is I p -large if X 2 I p where X D R n Z. The following facts are easily verified. The ideals I p are countably complete and for all Z R, Z is I p -positive if and only if there exists q < p such that Z is I q -large. Now assume Q is a partial order with a countable dense set, is a term for a real, p 2 Q, V D L.A; R/ and **uniformization. Suppose F W R ! V n ¹;º is a function. Then there is a function H WR!V such that ¹x j H.x/ 2 F .x/º is I p -large. Suppose g Q is L.A; R/-generic and let z 2 L.A; R/Œg be the interpretation of by g. Let Ug D ¹Z R j Z 2 L.A; R/; Z is I p -large for some p 2 gº and so Ug is an L.A; R/-ultrafilter on L.A; R/ \ P .R/. Let N D Ult.L.A; R/; Ug /. It is easily verified that N is wellfounded (use DC in L.A; R/) and we identify N with its transitive collapse. Let j W L.A; R/ ! N be the associated generic elementary embedding. It follows that j is the identity on the ordinals, RN D RL.A;R/Œz , and that j .A/ D [¹X V Œz j X 2 V; X is borel and X Aº where if X 2 V is a borel set then X V Œz denotes its interpretation in V Œz.
80
3 The nonstationary ideal
Now suppose that G Coll.!;
X \ S˛
is comeager in S˛ , (1.2) for all x 2 X , .x; f .x// 2 Z, 1 (1.3) f is … 1 in the codes. It is straightforward to show that AD implies !1 -**uniformization. Assume !1 -**uniformization and that V D L.A; R/ where A R. Then !1 **AC holds; i. e. if F W H.!1 / ! V n ¹;º
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
81
is a function then there exists X H.!1 / and there exists a function H WX !V such that for all g 2 X , H.g/ 2 F .g/ and such that for each ˛ < !1 ,
X \ S˛
is comeager in S˛ . In fact, both assertions (1) and (2) in the statement of theorem follow simply from the assumption that !1 -**uniformization holds in L.A; R/ and we shall prove (1) and (2) from only this weaker assumption. Let S be the following partial order. Conditions are triples .N; g; ˛/ such that (2.1) N !1 , (2.2) ˛ < !1 , (2.3) g 2 S˛ . Suppose .N1 ; g1 ; ˛1 / 2 S and .N2 ; g2 ; ˛2 / 2 S. Then .N2 ; g2 ; ˛2 / < .N1 ; g1 ; ˛1 / if N1 2 LŒN2 , ˛1 < ˛2 , g1 g2 and g2 \ Q˛1 ;˛2 is LŒN1 -generic. We will need the following consequences of !1 -**AC and **uniformization. Suppose X H.!1 / and that ˛ < !1 . Suppose that for each ˇ < !1 , X \ S˛;ˇ is comeager in S˛;ˇ . Then there exists N !1 such that for all ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ then ¹g Q˛;ˇ j g is LŒN -genericº X: By **uniformization, every set of reals has the property of Baire and so for every set N !1 and for every ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ then ¹g Q˛;ˇ j g is LŒN -genericº is comeager in S˛;ˇ . We first prove the following. Suppose .N; g; ˛/ 2 S and D0 S is a set which is dense below .N; g; ˛/. Let D be the set of p 2 S such that for some q 2 D0 , p q 2 G where G is the term for the generic filter. We claim there exist N !1 and ˇ < !1 such that ˛ < ˇ and such that .N ; g h; ˇ/ 2 D for all h Q˛;ˇ which are LŒN -generic. By !1 -**AC, there exists X H.!1 / and there exists a function F W X ! P .!1 / such that for all ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ then (3.1) X \ S˛;ˇ is comeager in S˛;ˇ , (3.2) if h 2 S˛;ˇ \ X and if there exists M !1 such that .M; g h; ˇ/ 2 D then .F .h/; g h; ˇ/ 2 D.
82
3 The nonstationary ideal
Let T be the set of triples .ˇ; q; / such that (4.1) ˛ < ˇ < !1 , (4.2) q 2 Q˛;ˇ , (4.3) < !1 , (4.4) ¹h 2 S˛;ˇ j 2 F .h/º is comeager in the open subset of S˛;ˇ given by q. Let X be the set of h Q˛;ˇ such that ˛ < ˇ < !1 and such that h is LŒT generic. Define F W X ! P .!1 / by
F .h/ D ¹ j .ˇ; q; / 2 T for some q 2 hº
where ˇ < !1 is such that h is LŒT -generic for Q˛;ˇ . Let X D ¹h 2 X \ X j F .h/ D F .h/º: Since every set of reals has the property of Baire, for every ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ then X \ S˛;ˇ is comeager in S˛;ˇ . Let S be the set of pairs .ˇ; p/ such that (5.1) ˛ < ˇ < !1 , (5.2) p 2 Q˛;ˇ , (5.3) ¹h 2 S˛;ˇ j .F .h/; g h; ˇ/ 2 Dº is comeager in the open subset of S˛;ˇ given by p. For each ˇ < !1 such that ˛ < ˇ let Yˇ D ¹h 2 S˛;ˇ j .F .h/; g h; ˇ/ 2 D $ .ˇ; p/ 2 S for some p 2 hº: Thus for each ˇ, Yˇ is comeager in S˛;ˇ . Let Y D [¹Yˇ j ˛ < ˇ < !1 º: Let N !1 be a set such that .g; S; T / 2 LŒN and such that for all ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ then ¹g Q˛;ˇ j g is LŒN -genericº X \ Y: Suppose ˇ < !1 and ˛ < ˇ. Suppose h Q˛;ˇ is LŒN -generic and that there exists M !1 such that .M; g h; ˇ/ 2 D. h is LŒN -generic and so h 2 X . Therefore .F .h/; g h; ˇ/ 2 D and further F .h/ D F .h/. However T 2 LŒN and so F .h/ 2 LŒN Œh. Thus .N ; g h; ˇ/ .F .h/; g h; ˇ/ 2 G and so
.N ; g h; ˇ/ 2 D:
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
83
Let E D ¹p j .ˇ; p/ 2 S for some ˇ < !1 º: We claim that E is predense in Coll.!;
84
3 The nonstationary ideal
where Gp0 D g0 .G \ Q˛0 ;!1 / is the perturbation of G to extend g0 . We prove that FGp0 \ jG .D/ ¤ ; for all D S such that D is dense. Suppose D S is dense. We may assume that for all p 2 S, if p q 2 G for some q 2 D then p 2 D. Since every set of reals has the property of Baire and since !1 -**AC holds, it follows by the remarks above, that there exists ˛ < !1 such that ˛0 < ˛ and there exists N1 !1 such that .N1 ; g0 h; ˛/ 2 D for all h Q˛0 ;˛ such that h is LŒN1 -generic. Thus .N1 ; g0 G˛0 ;˛ ; ˛/ 2 jG .D/ and .N1 ; g0 G˛0 ;˛ ; ˛/ < jG .p0 /. Clearly G \ Q˛;!1 is LŒN1 -generic. Thus .N1 ; g0 G˛0 ;˛ ; ˛/ 2 jG .D/ \ FGp0 : This proves that FGp0 \ jG .D/ ¤ ; for all D S such that D is dense. It now follows that FG \ D ¤ ; for all D 2 L.AG ; RG / such that D jG .S/ and such that D is dense. The point is that any set in L.AG ; RG / is the image of a set in L.AG˛ ; RG˛ / for some ˛ and so genericity follows by relativizing the previous argument, with a suitable choice of p0 , to L.AG˛ ; RG˛ / V ŒG˛ : Finally we prove (2). It suffices to show that if F S is L.A; R/-generic then !1 -AC holds in L.A; R/ŒF . We work in L.A; R/. Suppose is a term, .N; g; ˛/ 2 S and .N; g; ˛/ ¤ ;: We prove that there exists N
!1 and a term such that .N ; g; ˛/ 2 :
Let D be the set of q < .N; g; ˛/ such that q 2 for some term . Therefore D is open and D is dense below .N; g; ˛/. By the claim proved above, there exists N !1 and there exists ˇ < !1 such that ˛ < ˇ and such that .N ; g h; ˇ/ 2 D for all h Q˛;ˇ which are LŒN -generic. By **AC there exists a set X which is comeager in S˛;ˇ and a function F W X ! L.A; R/ such that for all h 2 X , F .h/ is a term and .N ; g h; ˇ/ F .h/ 2 :
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
85
Let N !1 be a set such that N 2 LŒN and such that if h Q˛;ˇ is LŒN generic then h 2 X . F defines a term and .N ; g; ˛/ 2 : Now suppose 2 L.A; R/S is a term, .N; g; ˛/ 2 S, and .N; g; ˛/ W !1 ! V n ;: Let hˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i be a sequence of terms such that for all ˇ < !1 , .N; g; ˛/ ./ D ˇ : where ˛ C 1 C D ˇ. By !1 -**AC and by **uniformization and by the result proved above, there exists X H.!1 / and two functions, F0 W X ! P .!1 / and F1 W X ! L.A; R/ with the following properties. For all ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ then X \ S˛;ˇ is comeager in S˛;ˇ and for all h 2 X \ S˛;ˇ , F1 .h/ is a term and .F0 .h/; g h; ˇ/ F1 .h/ 2 ˇ : As we did above we extract the term defined by F0 . Let T be the set of triples .ˇ; q; / such that (7.1) ˛ < ˇ < !1 , (7.2) q 2 Q˛;ˇ , (7.3) < !1 , (7.4) ¹h 2 S˛;ˇ j 2 F0 .h/º is comeager in the open subset of S˛;ˇ given by q. For each ˇ < !1 such that ˛ < ˇ let Yˇ be the set of h 2 X \ S˛;ˇ such that F0 .h/ D ¹ < !1 j .ˇ; q; / 2 T for some q 2 hº: Thus Yˇ is comeager in S˛;ˇ . Let Y D [¹Yˇ j ˛ < ˇ < !1 º:
Finally let N !1 be such that .N; T / 2 LŒN and such that for all ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ then ¹h 2 S˛;ˇ j h is LŒN -genericº X \ Y: Suppose h Q˛;ˇ and that h is LŒN -generic. Therefore h 2 X and so .F0 .h/; g h; ˇ/ F1 .h/ 2 ˇ : The genericity of h relative to LŒN also implies that h 2 Yˇ . Therefore F0 .h/ 2 LŒT Œh:
86
3 The nonstationary ideal
However T 2 LŒN and so .N ; g h; ˇ/ .F0 .h/; g h; ˇ/ 2 G where G is the term for the generic filter. Thus for all ˇ < !1 , if ˛ < ˇ and if h 2 S˛;ˇ is LŒN -generic then .N ; g h; ˇ/ F1 .h/ 2 ˇ : The function F1 yields a term 2 L.A; R/S such that .N ; g; ˛/ “ is a choice function for ”:
t u
Remark 3.37. (1) As indicated in the proof, one does not need AD for this. For example, (3) follows assuming only that **uniformization holds in L.A; R/. See .Woodin 1983/. (2) The partial order S, defined in the proof of Theorem 3.36, is equivalent to the forcing notion of .Steel and VanWesep 1982/. Assuming AD, ¹.N; g; ˛/ 2 S j N !º is dense in S and the order on S can be refined to make the partial order !-closed; i. e. S is !-strategically closed. (3) With additional requirements on the inner model, L.A; R/, one in fact gets !1 DC in L.AG ; RG /ŒG. The additional assumption is ADC , it is implied by AD if V D L.R/. !1 -choice is sufficient for our purposes. A brief survey of ADC is given in the first section of Chapter 9. t u As a corollary to Theorem 3.36 we obtain the following theorem. Theorem 3.38. Suppose A R, L.A; R/ AD and that G Coll.!;
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
of subsets of !1 such that
87
5¹S˛ j ˛ < !1 º
contains a club and such that for each ˛ < !1 , there is a club C on which f j.S˛ \ C / D g for some g 2 L.AG ; RG /. (4) Suppose X ı is a set of size !1 in L.AG ; RG /ŒG. Then there is a set Y ı in L.AG ; RG / of size !1 such that X Y . Proof. (1) follows immediately from Theorem 3.36(3) noting that the club filter on !1 is an ultrafilter in L.A; R/ and that the ultrapower Ord!1 =U is wellfounded in L.A; R/ where U is the club filter on !1 . (2) is an elementary consequence of the fact that the partial order, Coll.!;
88
3 The nonstationary ideal
Let T D ¹.p; ˛; / j p 2 Coll.!;
kQy0 .g˛ /.!1V / D ˛ :
For each ˛ < !1 let S˛ D ¹ < !1 j f . / D g˛ . /º: It suffices to show that in L.AG ; RG /ŒG, S D 5¹S˛ j ˛ < !1 º contains a closed unbounded subset of !1 . Suppose E !1 is a stationary subset of !1 in L.AG ; RG /ŒG. Let be a term for E and let S D ¹.p; / j p “ 2 ”º: S 2 L.A; R/ and so there exists y 2 R such that S 2 LŒy. We may suppose that 1 “ is a stationary subset of !1 ”:
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
89
Fix z 2 R such that S 2 LŒz and such that y 2 LŒz. Thus ¹S; Eº LŒzŒG: Let SQ D kz .S /: Thus SQ is a term for a subset of ı12 in the forcing language for Coll.!; <ı12 /. Let Z !1 be the set of < !1 such that for all q 2 Coll.!; < / there exists .p; / 2 S such that p < q. Thus Z 2 LŒz. A key point is the following. Since 1 “ is a stationary subset of !1 ”; it follows that in L.A; R/, Z contains a club in !1 . Otherwise, working in L.A; R/, there exists a closed, unbounded, set C !1 and a condition q0 2 Coll.!;
E \ S ¤ ;: Therefore in L.AG ; RG /ŒG, S contains a closed unbounded subset of !1 .
t u
Lemma 3.39. Suppose A R, L.A; R/ AD and that for all B 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº is stationary where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Suppose G Coll.!;
90
3 The nonstationary ideal
Proof. Suppose G Coll.!;
B D f 1 ŒCG
for some continuous function f W RG ! RG with f 2 V ŒG. Thus it suffices to prove that for all C 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/, the set ® ¯ X hH.!2 /V ŒG ; CG ; 2i j MX is CG -iterable and X is countable is stationary. Fix C 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/. Let U RR 1 be a universal † 1 set. For each z 2 R let
Uz D ¹y 2 R j .z; y/ 2 U º: If M is a transitive model of ZFC we let U M D U \ M . By absoluteness U M is defined in M by the same †11 formula which defines U in V . Suppose X hH.!2 /; C; 2i is a countable elementary substructure in V such that MX is D-iterable and MX is E-iterable where D D ¹z j Uz C º and E D ¹z j Uz R n C º: Let Y D X ŒG and let N be the transitive collapse of Y . Therefore N D MX ŒG \ Coll.!;
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
Suppose in V ŒG,
91
k W N ! N
is a countable iteration of N . Let g D G \ Coll.!;
N D k.MX /Œk.g/
and k.g/ is k.MX /-generic for Coll.!; <ı/ where ı D .!1 /k.MX / : Note that CG D [¹UzV ŒG j z 2 Dº and RG n CG D [¹UzV ŒG j z 2 Eº: Therefore CG \ N D [¹UzN j z 2 D \ MX º and .RG n CG / \ N D [¹UzN j z 2 E \ MX º: This implies that k.CG \ N / D [¹Uzk.N / j z 2 k.D \ MX /º D [¹Uzk.N / j z 2 DG \ k.MX /º; and k.N \ .RG n CG // D [¹Uzk.N / j z 2 k.E \ MX /º D [¹Uzk.N / j z 2 EG \ k.MX /º; since k.D \ MX / D DG \ k.MX / and k.E \ MX / D EG \ k.MX /: Suppose z 2 DG . Then UzV ŒG CG (by applying j ). Therefore [¹Uzk.N / j z 2 DG \ k.MX /º CG since for each z 2 RG \ k.N /, Uzk.N / UzV ŒG :
92
3 The nonstationary ideal
Similarly [¹Uzk.N / j z 2 EG \ k.MX /º RG n CG : This implies k.N \ CG / CG and k.N \ .RG n CG // RG n CG : Therefore k.N \ CG / D k.N / \ CG and k.N \ .RG n CG // D k.N / \ .RG n CG /: This proves that N is CG -iterable in V ŒG. Finally suppose Z P!1 .H.!2 // is stationary in P!1 .H.!2 //. Then ¹X ŒG j X 2 Zº V ŒG . is stationary in .P!1 .H.!2 /// Therefore in V ŒG, the set ® ¯ X hH.!2 /V ŒG ; CG ; 2i j MX is CG -iterable and X is countable is stationary.
t u
To prove the first of the two covering theorems we need the following theorem of Steel which is a corollary of the results of .Steel 1981/. Theorem 3.40 (Steel, (AD + DC)). Suppose that < ‚ and cof./ > !. Suppose that Y R R is a prewellordering of length . Then there exists a set X R and a surjection WX ! such that 1 (1) for each † 1 set Z X ,
sup¹.t / j t 2 Zº < ;
(2) the set ¹.x; y/ j .x/ .y/º X X 1 is † 1 .Y /.
Proof. Suppose that there exists .; X / which satisfies (1). Then by the Moschovakis Coding Lemma there exists .; X / satisfying both (1) and (2). We prove (1). We fix some notation. Suppose A R. Let A be the least ordinal such that LA .A; R/ ZF n Powerset and let A D P .R/ \ LA .A; R/:
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
93
It is useful to note that A B if and only if A B , (by Wadge). Let P .! ! / be such that (1.1) for each A 2 ,
A ;
(1.2) ordertype¹ A j A 2 º D . These conditions uniquely specify . Let ı D sup¹ A j A 2 º: By (1.2), cof.ı / D cof./ and so cof.ı / > !. We shall assume the basic facts concerning Wadge reducibility in the context of AD, see the discussion after Definition 9.25. One such fact is that there exists a set B ! ! of minimum Wadge rank such that B … . Fix B0 and let D ¹B ! ! j B is a continuous preimage of B0 º: Let
O D ¹! ! n A j A 2 º
be the dual pointclass. By the choice of B0 , O D \ ; this is the second basic fact we require. In fact we shall use a slightly stronger form of this. Let L.! ! ; ! ! / denote the set of continuous functions f W !! ! !! such that for all x 2 ! ! , for all y 2 ! ! , and for all k 2 !, if xjk D yjk then f .x/jk D f .y/jk. It follows from the determinacy of the relevant Wadge games, the closure properties of , and the definition of , that: (2.1) Suppose B ! ! . Then ¹B; ! ! n Bº ¹f 1 ŒB0 j f 2 L.! ! ; ! ! /º if and only if B 2 . By the results of .Steel 1981/: (3.1) is closed under finite unions or O is closed under finite unions. (3.2) Suppose that is closed under finite unions. Then for each †11 set Z ! ! and for each A 2 , A \ Z 2 :
94
3 The nonstationary ideal
It is the latter claim, which requires that cof./ > !; which is the key claim. Without loss of generality we can suppose that is closed under finite unions. Fix a surjection W ! ! ! L.! ! ; ! ! / such that the set ¹.x; y; z/ j .x/.y/ D zº is borel; i. e. a reasonable coding of L.! ! ; ! ! /. Fix A0 2 n and let R be the set of pairs .x0 ; x1 / such that (4.1) ..x0 //1 ŒA0 \ ..x1 //1 ŒA0 D ;, (4.2) ..x0 //1 ŒA0 [ ..x1 //1 ŒA0 D ! ! . Note that by the definition of , for each .x0 ; x1 / 2 R, ..x0 //1 ŒA0 2 : Define W R ! ı by .x0 ; x1 / D B where B D ..x0 //1 ŒA0 . Thus by (1.2), defines a prewellordering of R with length and ı D sup¹.x0 ; x1 / j .x0 ; x1 / 2 Rº: Finally we show that if ZR is
1 † 1
then sup¹.x0 ; x1 / j .x0 ; x1 / 2 Zº < ı :
This is where we use (3.2). Since the range of has ordertype , this boundedness property will suffice to prove (1). Let Z D ¹.x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / j .x0 ; x1 / 2 Z; .x0 /.y/ D z0 ; and .x1 /.y/ D z1 º: 1 Thus Z is † 1 . Let
A D ¹.x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / j .x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / 2 Z and z0 2 A0 º D Z \ ¹.x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / j z0 2 A0 º: Then because is closed under intersections with †11 sets (and closed under continuous preimages), A 2 :
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
95
But ! ! n A D ¹.x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / j .x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / … Z or z0 … A0 º D ¹.x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / j .x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / … Z or z1 2 A0 º D .! ! n Z / [ ¹.x0 ; x1 ; y; z0 ; z1 / j z1 2 A0 º and so since is closed under finite unions (and contains all …11 sets), ! ! n A 2 :
Therefore
A 2 \ O D :
But for each .x0 ; x1 / 2 Z, ..x0 //1 ŒA0 is a continuous preimage of A and so B A < ı where B D ..x0 //
1
ŒA0 . Therefore
sup¹.x0 ; x1 / j .x0 ; x1 / 2 Zº A < ı ; t u
and so Z is bounded. We begin with a technical lemma. Lemma 3.41. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model such that M ZF C DC C AD; and such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) for all A 2 M \ P .R/, the set ¹X hH.!2 /; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº is stationary where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Suppose ı < ‚M , S !1 is stationary and f W S ! ı. Suppose that g W !1 ! ı is a function such that g 2 M and such that f .˛/ g.˛/ for all ˛ 2 S . Then there exists a sequence h.T ; g / W < !1 i such that S D 5¹T j < !1 º and such that for all < !1 , (1) T is stationary, (2) g 2 M ,
96
3 The nonstationary ideal
(3) either f jT D gjT ; or for all ˛ 2 T ,
f .˛/ g .˛/ < g.˛/:
ı 12 D !2 and so we can assume that !2 < ı. Proof. Fix ı < ‚M . By Theorem 3.19, Fix f W S ! ı such that S !1 and such that S is stationary. For notational reasons we assume that the range of f is bounded in ı. Fix a set A R such that A 2 M and such that A codes a prewellordering of length ı. Suppose G Coll.!;
f .˛/ gi .˛/ < g.˛/:
By Theorem 3.38(3) the lemma follows from this claim. We work in V ŒG. We may suppose without loss of generality that for all ˛ 2 S , f .˛/ < g.˛/: We first divide S into three parts. Let S0 D ¹˛ 2 S j g.˛/ is a successor ordinalº; let and let
S1 D ¹˛ 2 S j cof.g.˛// D !º; S2 D ¹˛ 2 S j cof.g.˛// > !º:
Clearly we may suppose that S D S0 , S D S1 or S D S1 ; for if the claim holds for each of S0 ; S1 , and S2 then it trivially holds for S . If S D S0 then the claim is trivial.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
97
We next suppose that S D S1 . Note that for ordinals less than ı, L.AG ; RG /ŒG correctly computes the cofinality if the ordinal has countable cofinality in V ŒG. Since !1 -choice holds in L.AG ; RG /ŒG, there exists a sequence hhˇi˛ W i < !i W ˛ 2 S1 i 2 L.AG ; RG /ŒG such that for each ˛ 2 S1 , hˇi˛ W i < !i is an increasing cofinal sequence in g.˛/. For each i < ! define a function gi W !1 ! ı by gi .˛/ D ˇi˛ : For each i < ! let Ti D ¹˛ 2 S1 j f .˛/ gi .˛/ < g.˛/º: Clearly S D [¹Ti j i < !º: This proves the claim holds for .g; f; S1 /. We finish by proving that the claim holds for the triple .g; f; S2 /. Let Y ı be a set in L.AG ; RG / of cardinality !1 in L.AG ; RG / such that the range of g is a subset of Y . Y exists by Theorem 3.38 (3). Fix in L.AG ; RG / a function h W !1 ! Y which is onto. Let U RG R2G be a universal set for the relations 1 2 which are † 1 .AG /. Let P RG be the set of pairs .x; y/ such that: (2.1) x codes a countable ordinal ˛; (2.2) Uy is a prewellordering y of length h.˛/ with the property that if Z field.y / and Z is
1 † 1
then Z is bounded relative to y .
By Theorem 3.40, dom.P / is exactly the set of x 2 R such that x codes a countable ordinal. The key point is that !1 -choice holds in L.AG ; RG /ŒG and so we can find a sequence h.x˛ ; y˛ / W ˛ < !1 i 2 L.AG ; RG /ŒG of elements of P such that for each ˛ < !1 , x˛ codes a countable ordinal such that h. / D g.˛/. Choose in V ŒG an !1 sequence of reals hz˛ W ˛ < !1 i such that for each ˛ < !1 , z˛ 2 field.y˛ / and such that for each ˛ 2 S2 , f .˛/ is the rank of z˛ relative to y˛ . Let S D h.x˛ ; y˛ / W ˛ < !1 i and let T D hz˛ W ˛ < !1 i. Choose a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 /V ŒG containing the sequences S and T and such that MX is P -iterable where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Let SX and TX be the images of S and T under the collapsing
98
3 The nonstationary ideal
map. Thus SX D Sj!1MX and similarly for TX . By Corollary 3.13, there is an iteration j W MX ! N of length !1 such that j.SX / D S and j.TX / D T : Fix ˛ 2 !1 . Let Z˛ be the set of all z 2 RG such that there is an iteration k W MX ! N of length ˛ C 1 such that k.SX /j.˛ C 1/ D Sj.˛ C 1/ and z D k.TX /.˛/. Thus Z˛ 1 is a † 1 set and z˛ 2 Z˛ . Further since MX is P -iterable we have Z˛ field.y˛ /. Thus this set is bounded. The definition of Z˛ is uniform in Sj.˛ C 1/ and hence hZ˛ W ˛ < !1 i 2 L.AG ; RG /: Therefore there is a function g 2 L.AG ; RG /ŒG such that for all ˛ 2 S2 , f .˛/ g .˛/ < g.˛/. This proves that the claim holds for t u the triple .f; g; S2 /. Lemma 3.41 yields the following theorem as an easy corollary. Theorem 3.42. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model such that M ZF C DC C AD; and such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) for all A 2 M \ P .R/, the set ¹X hH.!2 /; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº is stationary where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Suppose ı < ‚M and that f W !1 ! ı. Then there exists a sequence h.S˛ ; g˛ / W ˛ < !1 i such that !1 D 5¹S˛ j ˛ < !1 º and such that for all ˛ < !1 , (1) S˛ is stationary, (2) g˛ 2 M , (3) f jS˛ D g˛ jS˛ . Proof. By Lemma 3.41 there exists a sequence hFi W i < !i of functions such that for each i < !:
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
99
(1.1) dom.Fi / P .!1 / n INS and jdom.Fi /j D !1 ; (1.2) if ¹S; T º dom.Fi / and if S ¤ T then S \ T 2 INS I (1.3) dom.Fi / is predense in .P .!1 / n INS ; /; (1.4) for each S 2 dom.Fi /, Fi .S / 2 M and either
Fi .S / W !1 ! ı; Fi .S /jS D f jS;
or for all ˛ 2 S , f .˛/ < Fi .S /.˛/I (1.5) for each T 2 dom.FiC1 / there exists S 2 dom.Fi / such that T S ; (1.6) suppose that S 2 dom.Fi /, T 2 dom.FiC1 / and that T ¨ S , then for each ˛ 2 T, FiC1 .T /.˛/ < Fi .S /.˛/I (1.7) for each S 2 dom.Fi / if
Fi .S /jS ¤ f jS
then there exists T 2 dom.FiC1 / such that T ¨ S . Let A be the set of S !1 such that for some i < !, S 2 dom.Fj / for all j > i . By (1.2) and (1.6), for each S 2 A, f jS D gjS for some g 2 M . Let be closed unbounded filter as computed in M . Since M AD C DC;
is an ultrafilter in M and the ultrapower ¹g W !1 ! ı j g 2 M º= is wellfounded. This in conjunction with (1.6) yields the following. Suppose that hSi W i < !i is an infinite sequence such that for all i < j < !, Sj Si and Si 2 dom.Fi /. Then there exists i0 < ! such that for all i > i0 , Si D Si0 : By (1.4) and (1.6), Sj 2 A for all j i0 . Therefore by (1.3), for each T 2 P .!1 / n INS there exists S 2 A such that S \ T … INS :
100
3 The nonstationary ideal
Thus A is predense in .P .!1 / n INS ; /. Finally A [¹dom.Fi / j i < !º t u
and so jAj !1 . We obtain as an immediate corollary the first covering theorem.
Theorem 3.43. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model such that M ZF C DC C AD; and such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) every set A 2 M \ P .R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin in V . Suppose ı < ‚M , S !1 is stationary and f W S ! ı. Then there exists g 2 M such that ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ D g.˛/º is stationary. Proof. By Lemma 3.35, for each A 2 P .R/ \ M , the set ¹X hH.!2 /; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a set closed and unbounded in P!1 .H.!2 //. Therefore the theorem follows from Theorem 3.42. t u Corollary 3.44. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Suppose that ¯ ® !3 sup ‚M where M ranges over transitive inner models such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) M ZF C DC C AD, (iv) every set A 2 M \ P .R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin in V . Suppose G P .!1 / n INS is V -generic and that j WV !M is the induced generic elementary embedding. Then j j˛ 2 V for every ordinal ˛. Proof. By the last theorem j j!3 2 V . It follows on general grounds that j jOrd is a definable class in V . u t
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
101
The second covering theorem is stronger. Again we prove a preliminary version. Theorem 3.45. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model such that M ZF C DC C AD; and such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) for all A 2 M \ P .R/, the set ¹X hH.!2 /; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº is stationary where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Suppose ı < ‚M , X ı and jX j D !1 . Then there exists Y 2 M such that M “jY j D !1 ” and such that X Y . Proof. Fix ı < ‚M and let A 2 M be a prewellordering of the reals of length ı. Fix a set X ı of cardinality !1 . As in the proof of the first covering theorem suppose that G Coll.!;
102
3 The nonstationary ideal
This is easily done. Let N D L .AG ; RG /ŒG. Thus N !1 -choice C !1 -Replacement: By Theorem 3.42, has cofinality !2 in V ŒG, and so V ŒG ZFC , Choose Z V ŒG such that (3.1) Z is countable, (3.2) AG 2 Z, X 2 Z and ı 2 Z, (3.3) the transitive collapse MZ of Z is iterable. Define two sequences hX˛ W ˛ < !1 i and hZ˛ W ˛ < !1 i by induction on ˛ such that: (4.1) X0 D N \ Z and Z0 D Z; (4.2) Xˇ D [¹X˛ j ˛ < ˇº and Zˇ D [¹Z˛ j ˛ < ˇº for all limit ordinals ˇ < !1 ; (4.3) X˛C1 D ¹f .X˛ \ !1 / j f 2 X˛ º; (4.4) Z˛C1 D ¹f .Z˛ \ !1 / j f 2 Z˛ º. Define a sequence hX˛ W ˛ < !1 i by X˛ D Z˛ \ N . Thus for all ˛ < ˇ < !1 : (5.1) Z˛ Zˇ V ŒG ; (5.2) X˛ Xˇ N ; (5.3) X˛ X˛ . It is because !1 -choice and !1 -replacement hold in N that hX˛ W ˛ < !1 i is an elementary chain. The key claim is that for all ˛ < !1 , X˛ \ D X˛ \ and so for all ˛ < !1 , X˛ \ D Z˛ \ . This will follow from the first covering theorem. Once we prove this claim the theorem follows. This is because !1 [¹Z˛ j ˛ < !1 º and so since X 2 Z0 , X [¹Z˛ \ j ˛ < !1 º [¹X˛ j ˛ < !1 º: Further X0 2 L.AG ; RG /ŒG and so hX˛ W ˛ < !1 i 2 L.AG ; RG /ŒG: Thus Y D [¹X˛ \ ı j ˛ < !1 º is the desired cover of X . To finish we must prove that for all ˛ < !1 , X˛ \ D X˛ \ . This follows by induction provided we can prove the following:
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
103
Claim: Suppose X X N , Z V ŒG and that X D Z \N . Suppose that X \ D X \ , Z is countable and that ; AG 2 X . Then for each function f 2 Z where f W !1 ! there exists g 2 X such that f .Z \ !1 / D g.Z \ !1 /: We prove this claim. Fix f W !1 ! . By Theorem 3.42 we have in V ŒG that there is a sequence h.S˛ ; g˛ / W ˛ < !1 i such that: (6.1) hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary sets; (6.2) 5¹S˛ j ˛ < !1 º contains a club in !1 ; (6.3) g˛ W !1 ! and g˛ 2 L.AG ; RG /; (6.4) g˛ jS˛ D f jS˛ . Since L .AG ; RG / L‚ .AG ; RG / and since has cofinality !2 in L.AG ; RG /, ¹g W !1 ! j g 2 L.AG ; RG /º L .AG ; RG /: Thus for each ˛ < !1 , g˛ 2 N . Since Z V ŒG , we can suppose that h.S˛ ; g˛ / W ˛ < !1 i 2 Z : It follows that
f .Z \ !1 / D g .Z \ !1 /
for some function g W !1 ! with g 2 Z \ L .AG ; RG /: Let j W‚!‚ be the ultrapower embedding computed in L.AG ; RG / using the club measure on !1 . Let W ‚!1 \ L‚ .AG ; RG / ! ‚ be the map that assigns to each function the ordinal it represents. By the Moschovakis Coding Lemma j j W ! :
Let D .g / be the ordinal represented by g . Thus since g 2 Z , 2 X and so 2 X . But X N and so since is definable there exists g 2 X \ L .AG ; RG / such that .g/ D . Therefore g D g on a club and so g.Z \ !1 / D g .Z \ !1 / D f .Z \ !1 /: This proves the claim.
t u
104
3 The nonstationary ideal
There is another formulation of Theorem 3.45. Recall P!1 .X / denotes the set of all countable subsets of X . Theorem 3.46. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model such that M ZF C DC C AD; and such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) for all A 2 M \ P .R/, the set ¹X hH.!2 /; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº is stationary where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Suppose ı < ‚M and that f W !1 ! ı: Then there exists a function g W !1 ! P!1 .ı/ such that g 2 M and such that for all ˛ < !1 , f .˛/ 2 g.˛/. Proof. Let X D ¹f .˛/ j ˛ < !1 º: By Theorem 3.45, there exists a set Y ı such that X Y and such that jY jM D !1 : By Theorem 3.19, .!2 /M D !2 and so we may reduce to the case that ı D !1 . Let C D ¹˛ < !1 j f Œ˛ ˛º: The set C is closed and unbounded in !1 . By Theorem 3.19, there exists a closed, cofinal, set D C such that for some x 2 R, D 2 LŒx: Therefore D 2 M . Define g W !1 ! P!1 .!1 / by g.˛/ D min.D n ˇ/; where ˇ D ˛ C 1. Thus g is as required.
t u
The second covering theorem is an immediate corollary of Theorem 3.45. Theorem 3.47. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model such that M ZF C DC C AD;
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
105
and such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) every set A 2 M \ P .R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin in V . Suppose ı < ‚M , X ı and jX j D !1 . Then there exists Y 2 M such that M “jY j D !1 ” and such that X Y . Proof. By Lemma 3.35, for each A 2 P .R/ \ M , the set ¹X hH.!2 /; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a set closed and unbounded in P!1 .H.!2 //. Therefore the theorem follows from Theorem 3.45. t u Corollary 3.48. Assume the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that there exist ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above them all. Let ‚ D ‚L.R/ . (1) Suppose that X is a bounded subset of ‚ of cardinality !1 . Then there exists a set Y 2 L.R/ of cardinality !1 in L.R/ such that X Y . (2) Suppose G P .!1 / n INS is V -generic and that j W V ! M is the induced generic elementary embedding. Let k W ‚ ! ‚ be the map derived from the ultrapower ‚!1 =U computed in L.R/ where U is the club measure on !1 . Then j j‚ D k: Proof. From the large cardinal hypothesis, AD holds in L.R/ and further every set of reals which is in L.R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin. The corollary follows by the covering theorems. t u We end this section with the following theorem which in the special case of L.R/ approximates the converse of Theorem 3.46. Theorem 3.49. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose that for all ı < ‚L.R/ , if f W !1 ! ı then there exists a function g W !1 ! P!1 .ı/ such that g 2 L.R/ and such that for all ˛ < !1 , f .˛/ 2 g.˛/. Let be the least ordinal such that L .R/ †1 L.R/: Then for each set A R such that A 2 L .R/ there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that hX; A \ X; 2i hH.!2 /; A; 2i and such that MX is A-iterable where MX is the transitive collapse of X .
106
3 The nonstationary ideal
Proof. By the definition of , is a regular cardinal in L.R/ and < ‚L.R/ . Therefore since > !2 , cof./ > !1 , and so L .H.!2 // ZFC : Further by the Moschovakis Coding Lemma, for each ˛ < , P .˛/ \ L.R/ 2 L .R/: Let X L .H.!2 // be a countable elementary substructure and let MX be the transitive collapse of X . We prove that MX is A-iterable for each A R such that A 2 X \ L .R/: Fix A. Thus for some t 2 R, A is definable in L .R/ from t . The set A is 21 .t / in L.R/ and so by the Martin–Steel theorem, Theorem 2.3, there exist < , and trees T0 ; T1 on ! such that A D pŒT0 ; such that, R n A D pŒT1 ; and such that .T0 ; T1 / is †1 -definable in L.R/ from .t; R/. Since L .R/ †1 L.R/; it follows that L .R/ \ .HOD t /L.R/ D .HOD t /L .R/ ; and so .T0 ; T1 / 2 .HOD t /L .R/ : Let j W .HOD t /L.R/ ! N t be the elementary embedding computed in L.R/ where N t D .HOD!t 1 /L.R/ = and where is the club filter on !1 . Since DC holds in L.R/, this ultrapower is wellfounded and we identify it with its transitive collapse. It follows that j .HOD t /L.R/ . Since L .R/ †1 L.R/ and since cof./ > !1 , j./ D . The structure .HOD t /L .R/ ; j j.HOD t /L .R/ is naturally iterable and the iterates are wellfounded. The notion of iteration is the conventional (non-generic) one.
3.1 The nonstationary ideal and ı12
107
Let .N; k/ be the image of ..HOD t /L .R/ ; j j.HOD t /L .R/ / under the transitive collapse of X . Thus N and k are definable subsets of MX . Let T0X be the image of T0 under the transitive collapse of X and let T1X be the image of T1 . Suppose j W .N; k/ ! .N ; k / is a countable iteration. Then it follows that there exists an elementary embedding W N ! .HOD t /L .R/ such that .j.T0X // D T0 and such that .j.T1X // D T1 : Thus N is wellfounded, pŒ.j.T0X // pŒT0 and pŒ.j.T1X // pŒT1 : We now come to the key points. By the Moschovakis Coding Lemma, if h W !1 ! and h 2 L.R/ then h 2 L .R/. Thus the hypothesis of the theorem holds in L .H.!2 //. Suppose that jO W MX ! MX is an iteration of MX . Then, abusing notation slightly, jOjN W .N; k/ ! .jO.N /; jO.k// is an iteration of .N; k/ and so MX is wellfounded. Let B D R n A D pŒT1 . Thus jO.A \ MX / pŒjO.T0X / pŒT0 and
jO.B \ MX / pŒjO.T1X / pŒT1 :
Therefore
jO.A \ MX / D A \ MX :
This verifies that MX is A-iterable.
t u
108
3 The nonstationary ideal
3.2
The nonstationary ideal and CH
We still do not know if CH implies that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is not saturated. In light of the results in the previous section this seems likely. Shelah, Shelah .1986/, has proved that assuming CH the nonstationary ideal is not !1 -dense. We prove a generalization of this theorem. It is a standard fact, which is easily verified, that the boolean algebra, P .!1 /=INS , is !2 -complete; i. e. if X P .!1 /=INS is a subset of cardinality at most @1 then _X exists in P .!1 /=INS . Theorem 3.50. Suppose that the quotient algebra P .!1 /=INS is !1 -generated .equivalently !-generated/ as an !2 -complete boolean algebra. Then 2@0 D 2@1 :
t u
We shall actually prove the following strengthening of Theorem 3.50. We fix some notation. Suppose A !1 . For each < !2 such that !1 , let bA 2 P .!1 /=INS be defined as follows. Fix a bijection W !1 ! : Let S D ¹ < !1 j ordertype.Œ/ 2 Aº: Set to be the element of P .!1 /=INS defined by S . It is easily checked that bA is unambiguously defined. We let BA denote the !2 -complete subalgebra of P .!1 /=INS generated by ® A ¯ b j !1 < !2 : bA
Suppose Z P .!1 /=INS is of cardinality @1 . Then there exists a set A !1 such that Z BA : Thus Theorem 3.50 is an immediate corollary of the next theorm. Theorem 3.51. Suppose that for some set A !1 BA D P .!1 /=INS Then
2@0 D 2@1 :
3.2 The nonstationary ideal and CH
109
Proof. The key point is the following. Suppose Y hH.!2 /; 2i is a countable elementary substructure such that A 2 Y . Let N be the transitive collapse of Y and suppose that j W N ! N is a countable iteration such that N is transitive. Then we claim that j is uniquely determined by j.AN / where AN D A \ !1N . To see this let hNˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ j ˛ < ˇ i be the iteration giving j . We first prove that G0 is uniquely determined by j.AN / \ N . This follows from the definitions noting that the property of A, BA D P .!1 /=INS is a first order property of A in H.!2 /. Therefore since Y hH.!2 /; 2i it follows that N Ba D P .!1 /=INS where a D AN . For each 2 N \ Ord with !1N , let .ba /N be as computed in N . Strictly speaking .ba /N is not an element of N , instead it is a definable subset of N . G0 is an N -generic filter and so it follows since N Ba D P .!1 /=INS that G0 is uniquely determined by ¯ ® 2 N j G0 \ .ba /N ¤ ; : Finally
¯ ® 2 N j G0 \ .ba /N ¤ ; D .j.a/ \ N / n !1N :
This verifies that G0 is uniquely determined by j.AN /\N . It follows by induction that j is uniquely determined by j.AN /. Fix B !1 and fix a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / with A 2 X and B 2 X . Let hX W < !1 i be the sequence of countable elementary substructures of H.!2 / generated by X as follows. (1.1) X0 D X . (1.2) For all < !1 , X C1 D X ŒX \ !1 D ¹f .X \ !1 / j f 2 X º:
110
3 The nonstationary ideal
(1.3) For all < !1 , if is a limit ordinal then X D [¹X j < º: Let hM X W < !1 i be the sequence of countable transitive sets where for each < !1 , M X is the transitive collapse of X . Let X!1 D [¹X j < !1 º and let M!1 be the transitive collapse of X!1 . For each < !1 let j; W M ! M be the elementary embedding given by the image of the inclusion map X X under the collapsing map. For each < !1 , .!1 /M is the critical point of j ; C1 and M C1 is the restricted ultrapower of M by G where G is the M -ultrafilter on .!1 /M given by j ; C1 . By Lemma 3.12, hM ; G ; j; W < !1 i is an iteration of M0 . For each !1 let A be the image of A under the collapsing map. Therefore A D A \ .!1 /M and for each < !1 , j ; C1 .A / D A C1 : Similarly for each !1 let B be the image of B under the collapsing map. Thus by Corollary 3.13, j0;!1 .B0 / D B. For all < !1 , j ; C1 .A / D A C1 . By the claim proved above, for all < !1 , G is uniquely determined by j ; C1 .A /. But for each < !1 , j ; C1 .A / D A C1 : Therefore the iteration hM ; G ; j; W < !1 i is uniquely determined by M0 and A. Finally j0;!1 .B0 / D B. This induces a map t u from H.!1 / onto P .!1 /. Remark 3.52. One can also prove Theorem 3.51 using a form of ˘, weak diamond, due to Devlin and Shelah, Devlin and Shelah .1978/. This weakened form of diamond holds whenever 2@0 ¤ 2@1 . t u Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Then for each A !1 there exists A !1 such that A is definable in LŒA and such that the quotient algebra .P .!1 /=INS /=BA is atomless.
3.2 The nonstationary ideal and CH
111
Thus if the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated and CH holds then P .!1 /=INS decomposes as B T where T is a Suslin tree in V B . We now define two weak forms of ˘. We shall see that if ˘ holds in a transitive inner model which correctly computes !2 then these forms of ˘ hold in V . To motivate the definitions we recall the following equivalents of ˘, stating a theorem of Kunen. Theorem 3.53 (Kunen). The following are equivalent. (1) ˘. (2) There exists a sequence hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i of countable sets such that for each A !1 the set ¹˛ j A \ ˛ 2 S˛ º is stationary in !1 . (3) There exists a sequence hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i of countable sets such that for each A !1 the set ¹˛ ! j A \ ˛ 2 S˛ º is nonempty. (4) There exists a sequence hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i of countable sets such that for each countable X P .!1 / the set ¹˛ ! j A \ ˛ 2 S˛ for all A 2 X º is nonempty. Proof. .2/ is commonly referred to as weak ˘. That .3/ is also equivalent to ˘ is perhaps at first glance surprising. We prove that .3/ is equivalent to .2/. Let hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i be a sequence witnessing .3/. For each ˛ < !1 let T˛ D P .˛/ \ L .hSˇ j ˇ < ˛ C !i/ where < !1 is the least ordinal such that L .hSˇ j ˇ < ˛ C !i/ ZF n Powerset: We claim that hT˛ j ˛ < !1 i witnesses .2/. To verify this fix A !1 and fix a closed unbounded set C !1 . We may suppose that C contains only limit ordinals. It suffices to prove that for some ˇ 2 C , A \ ˇ 2 Tˇ . Let B0 D ¹2 ˛ j ˛ 2 Aº: For each 2 C [ ¹0º, let x ! be a set which codes A \ where is the least element of C above . Let B1 D ¹ C 2k C 1 j 2 C and k 2 x º: Let B D B0 [ B1 . Since hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i witnesses .3/, there exists an infinite ordinal ˛ such that B \ ˛ 2 S˛ : If ˛ 2 C then set ˇ D ˛. Thus ˇ is as required since S˛ T˛ . If ˛ … C let be the largest element of C below ˛. Let D 0 if C \ ˛ D ;. Let be the least element of C above ˛. There are two cases. If C ! ˛ then A \ 2 T since x D ¹k < ! j . C 2k C 1/ 2 B \ ˛º: If ˛ < C ! then ¤ 0. Therefore 2 C and since ˛ < C !, A \ 2 T . t u In either case A \ ˇ 2 Tˇ for some ˇ 2 C .
112
3 The nonstationary ideal
Our route toward a weakening of ˘ starts with .4/ which is reminiscent of ˘C . Definition 3.54. Suppose hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of countable sets. Suppose X P .!1 / is countable. Then X is guessed by hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i if the set ¹˛ j A \ ˛ 2 S˛ for all A 2 X º t u
is unbounded in !1 .
Q There exists a sequence hAˇ j ˇ < !2 i of distinct subsets of !1 Definition 3.55. ˘: and there exists a sequence hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i of countable sets such that ¹ˇX j X P .!1 / is countable and hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i guesses X º is stationary in !2 . Here ˇX D sup¹ C 1 j A 2 X º.
t u
We weaken (possibly) still further in the following definition. QQ There exists a sequence Definition 3.56. ˘: hAˇ j ˇ < !2 i of distinct subsets of !1 and a sequence hS˛ j ˛ < !1 i of countable sets such that for a stationary set of countable sets X !2 , there exists ˛ < !1 such that X \ !1 ˛ and such that ¹ˇ j ˇ 2 X \ !2 and Aˇ \ ˛ 2 S˛ º is t u cofinal in X \ !2 . QQ the sequence Remark 3.57. (1) Suppose that 2@1 D @2 . Then in the definition of ˘, hAˇ j ˇ < !2 i can be taken to be any enumeration of P .!1 /. (2) If there is a Kurepa tree on !1 then ˘Q holds. We shall show in Section 6.2.5 that the existence of a weak Kurepa tree is consistent with the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. Therefore ˘QQ is not implied by the existence of a weak Kurepa tree. Recall that a tree T ¹0; 1º
3.2 The nonstationary ideal and CH
113
Let hAˇ W ˇ < !2 i be a sequence of distinct subsets of !1 with hAˇ W ˇ < !2 i 2 M: The key point is that the set M \ P!1 .!2 / is stationary in P!1 .!2 /. To verify this, let F W !2
F Œ
t u
Theorem 3.59. Assume that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Then ˘QQ fails. QQ Proof. Suppose hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i and hAˇ W ˇ < !2 i together witness ˘. Therefore there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!3 / such that (1.1) hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i 2 X , (1.2) hAˇ W ˇ < !2 i 2 X , (1.3) for some ˛ < !1 , X \ !1 < ˛ and ¹ˇ j ˇ 2 X and Aˇ \ ˛ 2 S˛ º is cofinal in X \ !2 .
114
3 The nonstationary ideal
Fix ˛ satisfying (1.3). Let hX W < !1 i be the elementary chain where X0 D X and for all < !1 , (2.1) XC1 D ¹f .X \ !1 / j f 2 X º, (2.2) if is a limit ordinal, X D [¹X j < º: Fix < !1 such that !1 \ X ˛ < !1 \ XC1 : Note that for all < !1 , X \ !2 is cofinal in X \ !2 . Therefore ¹ˇ j ˇ 2 X and Aˇ \ ˛ 2 S˛ º is cofinal in X \ !2 . Thus by replacing X by X if necessary we may assume that D 0; i. e. that !1 \ X ˛ < !1 \ Y where Y D ¹f .X \ !1 / j f 2 X º: Let NX be the transitive collapse of X , let NY be the transitive collapse of Y and let j W NX ! NY be the induced elementary embedding (the image of the inclusion map). However the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and P .!1 / H.!3 /. Therefore by Lemma 3.12, NY is a generic ultrapower of NX and j is the induced embedding. Transferring to V (or equivalently, working in NX ) there exists a stationary set S !1 and ordinal ˛0 such that !1 ˛0 < !2 and such that if G P .!1 / n INS is V -generic with S 2 G then ¹ < !2 j j.A / \ ˛0 2 S˛0 º is cofinal in !2 where
j W V ! N V ŒG
is the induced embedding and hS W < !2 i D j.hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i/: However for all < !2 , j.A / \ !1 D A , and so for all 1 < 2 < !2 , j.A 1 / \ ˛0 ¤ j.A 2 / \ ˛0 : This is a contradiction since S˛0 is countable in V ŒG and !2V D !1V ŒG .
t u
As an immediate corollary to Theorem 3.58 and Theorem 3.59 we obtain the following. Corollary 3.60. Assume that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Then ˘ u t fails in any transitive inner model which correctly computes !2 .
3.2 The nonstationary ideal and CH
115
Related to the question of CH is the following question: Question. Can there exist countable transitive models M; M such that M ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated”;
M is an iterate of M and such that M 2 M ?
t u
Remark 3.61. (1) For this question the fragment of ZFC is important. The answer should be the same for all reasonably strong fragments. But note the answer is yes for ZFC for trivial reasons. (2) It is straightforward to show that the answer is no if the model M is iterable or if M “P .!1 /=INS is countably generated”. (3) Suppose the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated and CH holds. Suppose there exists an inaccessible cardinal. Then the answer is yes. t u One could ask this question for any iteration of generic embeddings. Suppose V is the inner model for one Woodin cardinal. Suppose G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic where ı is the Woodin cardinal. Then in V ŒG there are saturated ideals on !1 . Suppose ı < and that is inaccessible. Let X V ŒG be a countable elementary substructure of V ŒG and let M be the transitive collapse of X . Thus M 2 V . Suppose j W M ! N is an elementary embedding with N transitive and !1 D !1N . Then it follows that R N and so M 2 N . Thus if there is any wellfounded iteration of M of length !1 then the answer to the more general form of the question is yes. An even more general class of iterations is obtained by mixing generic ultrapowers with iteration trees. For this notion of iteration it is possible for a model to be an element of an iterate of itself. We state without proof a theorem which illustrates the possibilities. Theorem 3.62. Suppose there are two Woodin cardinals with an inaccessible above them both. Then there is a sequence hM0 ; M1 ; M2 i of countable transitive models of ZFC such that: (1) M1 is an iterate of M0 by an iteration tree on M0 ; (2) M2 is a generic ultrapower of M1 . for the stationary tower/; (3) M0 2 M2 .
t u
Chapter 4
The Pmax -extension
The results of Chapter 3 suggest that under suitable large cardinal hypotheses, if the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated then the inner model L.P .!1 // may be close to the inner model L.R/. Perhaps the most important clue is given by Corollary 3.13; if the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated and there is a measurable cardinal, then every subset of !1 appears in an iterate of a countable iterable model. Motivated by these considerations we shall define and analyze in Section 4.2 a partial order Pmax 2 L.R/ for which the corresponding generic extension, L.R/ŒG; is an optimal version of L.P .!1 // (assuming ADL.R/ ). First we generalize the notion of iterability slightly to accommodate the definition.
4.1
Iterable structures
We formulate the obvious generalizations of the definitions of iterability from Chapter 3. Definition 4.1. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC . Suppose I 2 M is a set of normal uniform ideals on !1M . (1) A sequence h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of .M; I/ if: a) M0 D M and I0 D I. b) j˛;ˇ W M˛ ! Mˇ is a commuting family of elementary embeddings. c) For all ˇ < , Iˇ D j0;ˇ .I0 /. d) For each C 1 < , G is M -generic for .P .!1 / n I /M for some ideal I 2 I ; M C1 is the generic ultrapower of M by G and j ; C1 W M ! M C1 is the induced elementary embedding. e) For each ˇ < if ˇ is a (nonzero) limit ordinal then Mˇ is the direct limit of ¹M˛ j ˛ < ˇº and for all ˛ < ˇ, j˛;ˇ is the induced elementary embedding.
4.1 Iterable structures
117
(2) If is a limit ordinal then is the length of the iteration, otherwise the length of the iteration is ı where ı C 1 D . (3) A pair .N ; J/ is an iterate of .M; I/ if it occurs in an iteration of .M; I/. (4) .M; I/ is iterable if every iterate is wellfounded.
t u
Remark 4.2. (1) This is the natural definition for iterability relative to a set of ideals. We shall only use it in the case that the set of ideals is finite. (2) Suppose that M is a countable transitive model of ZFC such that .P .!1 //M 2 M: Then .M; ¹.INS /M º/ is iterable if and only if M is iterable in the sense of Definition 3.5. (3) We will often write .M; I / when referring to .M; ¹I º/ in the case where only one ideal is designated. t u We define the corresponding notion of X -iterability where X R. Definition 4.3. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC . Suppose I 2 M is a set of uniform normal ideals on !1M . Suppose .M; I/ is iterable, X R and that X \ M 2 M. Then .M; I/ is X -iterable if for any iteration of .M; I/, j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I / j.X \ M/ D X \ M .
t u
The next two lemmas are the generalizations of Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.10 respectively. The proofs are similar and we omit them. Lemma 4.4. Suppose that M and M are countable models of ZFC such that
(i) !1M D !1M ,
(ii) P 2 .!1 /M D P 2 .!1 /M , (iii) M 2 M . Suppose I 2 M is a set of uniform, normal, ideals on !1M and that h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ j ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of .M; I/. Then there corresponds uniquely an iteration j ˛ < ˇ < i h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ
118
4 The Pmax -extension
of M such that for all ˛ < ˇ < : Mˇ
(1) !1
M
D !1 ˇ ;
(2) P .!1 /Mˇ D P .!1 /Mˇ ; (3) G˛ D G˛ . Further for all ˇ < there is an elementary embedding kˇ W .Mˇ ; Iˇ / ! j0;ˇ ..M; I// such that j0;ˇ jM D kˇ ı j0;ˇ .
t u
Lemma 4.5. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC and that I2M is a set of normal precipitous ideals on !1M . Suppose h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ j ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of .M; I/ of length where M \ Ord. Then Mˇ is wellfounded for all ˇ < . t u We shall need boundedness for iterable structures. Lemma 4.6(1) is proved by an argument analogous to the proof of Lemma 3.15 and Lemma 4.6(2) follows easily from Lemma 4.6(1). Lemma 4.6 (ZFC ). Suppose that x 2 R codes a countable iterable structure, .M; I/. (1) Suppose that j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I / is an iteration of length . Then rank.M / < where is the least ordinal such that < and such that L Œx is admissible. (2) Suppose that j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I / is an iteration of length !1 . Let D D ¹ < !1 j L Œx is admissibleº: Then for each closed set C !1 such that C 2 M , D n C is countable.
t u
As an immediate corollary to Lemma 4.6 we obtain the following boundedness lemma.
4.1 Iterable structures
119
Lemma 4.7 (ZFC ). Assume that for all x 2 R, x # exists. Suppose .M; I/ is a countable iterable structure and that j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I / is an iteration of length !1 . Then rank.M / < ı 12 .
t u
We extend Definition 4.1 to sequences of models. Definition 4.8. Suppose h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is a countable sequence such that for each k, Nk is a countable transitive model of ZFC and such that for all k: (i) Jk 2 Nk and Nk “Jk is a set of normal uniform ideals on !1 ”I N
N
(ii) Nk 2 NkC1 and !1 k D !1 kC1 ; (iii) for each I 2 Jk there exists I 2 JkC1 such that a) I \ Nk D I , N
b) for each A 2 Nk such that A P .!1 k / \ Nk n I , if A is predense in .P .!1 / n I /Nk then A is predense in .P .!1 / n I /NkC1 . An iteration of h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is a sequence hh.Nkˇ ; Jkˇ / W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i such that the following hold. (1) ¹j˛;ˇ W [¹Nk˛ j k < !º ! [¹Nkˇ j k < !º j ˛ < ˇ < º is a commuting family of †0 elementary embeddings. (2) If C 1 < then there exists a sequence hIk W k < !i such that for all k < !, a) Ik 2 Jk ,
b) G \ Nk is Nk -generic for .P .!1 / n Ik /Nk . (3) If C 1 < then Nk C1 is the [¹Nk j k < !º-ultrapower of Nk by G and j ; C1 jNk W Nk ! Nk C1 is the induced elementary embedding. The ultrapower of Nk is computed using all functions f W .!1 /N0 ! Nk such that f 2 [¹Nk j k < !º.
120
4 The Pmax -extension
(4) For each ˇ < if ˇ is a nonzero limit ordinal then for every k < !, Nkˇ is the direct limit of ¹Nk˛ j ˛ < ˇº and for all ˛ < ˇ, j˛;ˇ is the induced †0 elementary embedding. If is a limit ordinal then is the length of the iteration, otherwise the length of the iteration is ı where ı C 1 D . A sequence h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is an iterate of h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i if it occurs in an iteration of h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i. t u The sequence h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is iterable if every iterate is wellfounded. Condition (iii) in Definition 4.8 guarantees that nontrivial iterations exist. Lemma 4.9. Suppose h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is an iterable sequence. Suppose I 2 J0 Then there exist G [¹.P .!1 //Nk j k < !º and a sequence hIk W k < !i such that I0 D I and such that for all k < !, G \ Nk is Nk -generic for .P .!1 / n Ik /Nk : Proof. By condition (iii) in Definition 4.8 there exists a sequence hIk W k < !i such that I D I0 and such that for all k < !, (1.1) Ik 2 Jk , (1.2) IkC1 \ Nk D Ik , N
(1.3) for each A 2 Nk such that A P .!1 k / \ Nk n Ik , if A is predense in .P .!1 / n Ik /Nk then A is predense in .P .!1 / n IkC1 /NkC1 . Let hAk W k < !i enumerate all A 2 [¹Nk j k < !º such that for some k < !, A is predense in .P .!1 / n Ik /Nk . We assume that Ak 2 Nk for each k < !. Let hbk W k < !i be a sequence of subsets of .!1 /N0 such that (2.1) bk 2 Nk , (2.2) bk … Ik , (2.3) bk b for some b 2 Ak .
4.1 Iterable structures
121
The sequence hbk W k < !i is easily constructed by induction on k using the properties (1.1)–(1.3) of the sequence hIk W k < !i. Let G D ¹bk j k < !º: The sequence hAk W k < !i enumerates all the predense sets and so it follows that for all k < !, G \ Nk is Nk -generic for .P .!1 / n Ik /Nk .
t u
We now prove a lemma which we shall use to show that condition (iii) of Definition 4.8 is satisfied by the ! sequences of structures that we shall be interested in. Ultimately we shall apply the lemma within models of only ZFC and so we prove the lemma assuming only ZFC . Suppose that J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 and that A P .!1 / n J has cardinality at most !1 . Suppose that hA˛ W ˛ < !1 i and
hA˛ W ˛ < !1 i
are each enumerations of A possibly with repetition. Then the diagonal unions 5¹A˛ j ˛ < !1 º and
5¹A˛ j ˛ < !1 º
are equal on a club in !1 and so they are equal modulo J . Thus modulo J the diagonal union, 5A is unambiguously defined. The same considerations apply to diagonal intersections. We let 4A denote the diagonal intersection of A. Lemma 4.10 (ZFC ). Suppose M0 is a countable transitive model, I0 2 M0 is a set of normal uniform ideals on !1M0 , and M0 ZFC . Suppose that (i) for all I0 ; I1 2 I0 , if I0 ¹b 2 .P .!1 //M0 j b \ a 2 I1 º for some a 2 .P .!1 //M0 such that !1M0 n a … I1 ; then I0 D I1 . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 and that j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is a wellfounded iteration of length !1 such that J \ M0 D J for some J 2 I0 . Let X be the set of A 2 M0 such that A P .!1 /M0 n J and A is a maximal antichain. Let A D 4¹5A j A 2 Xº:
4 The Pmax -extension
122 Then
(1) !1 n A 2 J ,
(2) B \ A … J for all B 2 P .!1 /M0 n J . Proof. This is immediate from the definitions. Let h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i be the iteration such that j D j0;!1 . The ideal J is an element of I!1 . Hence there exist ˛0 < !1 and I 2 I˛0 such that J D j˛0 ;!1 .I /. Let S D ¹˛ < !1 j G˛ M˛ n j˛0 ;˛ .I /º: By (i) of the hypothesis of the lemma, S is the set of ˛ such that G˛ is M˛ -generic for .P .!1M˛ / n j˛0 ;˛ .I //M˛ : Since J \ M0 D J it follows that !1 n S 2J . This is the key point which we now verify. assume toward a contradiction that !1 n S … J . Then since J is normal there exist ˇ0 < !1 and b0 2 j˛0 ;ˇ0 .I / such that ¹˛ < !1 j jˇ0 ;˛ .b0 / 2 G˛ º … J: This implies jˇ0 ;!1 .b0 / … J . However jˇ0 ;!1 .b0 / 2 j˛0 ;!1 .I / which is a contradiction since j˛0 ;!1 .I / D J and J \ M0 D J . S S S be the ideal defined by INS [ ¹!1 n S º. Thus INS is a normal ideal, INS J Let INS and S \ M D J : INS The lemma follows by the M˛ -genericity of G˛ .
t u
Remark 4.11. (1) The set A in Lemma 4.10 is analogous to a master condition. As a condition in P .!1 / n J it forces that the generic filter is M0 -generic for P .!1 /M0 =J . (2) The requirement (i) in the statement of Lemma 4.10 can be weakened though some assumption is necessary. t u Lemma 4.12 is a version of Lemma 4.10 where the assumption J \ M0 2 I0 is dropped and where no additional assumptions are made about I0 .
4.1 Iterable structures
123
Lemma 4.12 (ZFC ). Suppose M0 is a countable transitive model, I0 2 M0 is a set of normal uniform ideals on !1M0 , and M0 ZFC . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 and that j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is a wellfounded iteration of length !1 . Then there exist J0 2 I0 and S !1 such that (1) S … J , (2) S n A 2 J , where
A D 4¹5A j A 2 Xº:
and X is the set of A 2 M0 such that A P .!1 /M0 n J0 and such that A is a maximal antichain. Proof. Let h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i be the iteration such that j D j0;!1 . For each ˛ < !1 , there is an ideal I 2 I˛ such that G˛ M˛ n I and such that G˛ is M˛ -generic. The ideal I is not necessarily unique however distinct candidates differ in a trivial manner. For each ˛ < !1 let IO˛ be the set of I 2 I˛ such that (1.1) G˛ M˛ n I , (1.2) G˛ is M˛ -generic for
.P .!1 / n I; /M ˛ :
Since J is normal it follows that there exist S !1 , ˛0 < !1 , and I 2 IO˛0 such that (2.1) S … J , (2.2) S .˛0 ; !1 /, (2.3) for all ˛ 2 S ,
j˛0 ;˛ .I / 2 IO˛ :
Let J0 D j˛0 ;!1 .I /. The lemma follows from the definitions. We generalize Definition 4.8 still further in Definition 4.15.
t u
124
4 The Pmax -extension
Definition 4.13. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC . An ultrafilter G .P .!1 //M is M -normal if for any function f W !1M ! !1M such that f 2 M , if ¹˛ < !1M j f .˛/ < ˛º 2 G then for some ˛0 < !1M , ¹˛ < !1M j f .˛/ D ˛0 º 2 G:
t u
Remark 4.14. It is easily verified that if G is M -normal then G\A¤; for any maximal antichain A .P .!1 / n INS /M such that A 2 M and such that A has cardinality !1 in M . Thus M -normal ultrafilters are “weakly generic”. t u Definition 4.15. Suppose hNk W k < !i is a countable sequence such that for each k, Nk is a countable transitive model of ZFC and such that for all k, Nk 2 NkC1
and
N
N
!1 k D !1 kC1 :
An iteration of hNk W k < !i is a sequence hhNkˇ W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i such that ¹j˛;ˇ W [¹Nk˛ j k < !º ! [¹Nkˇ j k < !º j ˛ < ˇ < º is a commuting family of †0 elementary embeddings and such that for all ˛ < ˇ < the following hold. ˛
(1) For all k < !, G˛ \ Nk˛ is an Nk˛ -normal ultrafilter on .P .!1 //Nk . (2) Nk˛C1 is the [¹Nk˛ j k < !º-ultrapower of Nk˛ by G˛ and j˛;˛C1 W [¹Nk˛ j k < !º ! [¹Nk˛C1 j k < !º is the induced †0 elementary embedding. (3) If ˇ is a limit ordinal then for every k < !, Nkˇ is the direct limit of ¹Nk˛ j ˛ < ˇº and for all ˛ < ˇ, j˛;ˇ is the induced †0 elementary embedding. If is a limit ordinal then is the length of the iteration, otherwise the length of the iteration is ı where ı C 1 D . A sequence hNk W k < !i is an iterate of hNk W k < !i if it occurs in an iteration of hNk W k < !i. t u The sequence hNk W k < !i is iterable if every iterate is wellfounded.
4.1 Iterable structures
125
Remark 4.16. Definition 4.15 is really just a slight generalization of Definition 3.5. Suppose hNk W k < !i is an iterable sequence such that for all k < !, jNk jNkC1 D .!1 /N0 : Let N D [¹Nk j k < !º: In general, N is not a model of ZFC , however N is a model of a fragment of ZFC which is rich enough to make it possible to apply Definition 3.5. Iterations of the sequence hNk W k < !i correspond to iterations of N . In virtually every situation in which we consider iterations of hNk W k < !i it will be the case that for all k < !, jNk jNkC1 D .!1 /N0 :
t u
Lemma 4.17. Suppose hNk W k < !i is a countable sequence such that for each k, Nk is a countable transitive model of ZFC and such that for all k, Nk 2 NkC1 and
.!1 /Nk D .!1 /NkC1 :
Suppose that for all k < !: (i) If C 2 Nk is closed and unbounded in !1N0 then there exists D 2 NkC1 such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ NkC1 . (ii) For all x 2 R \ Nk , x # 2 NkC1 . (iii) For all k < !,
jNk jNkC1 D .!1 /N0 :
Then the sequence hNk W k < !i is iterable. Proof. The key point is that if j W hNk W k < !i ! hNk W k < !i is an iteration of length 1 then N
j.!1N0 / D !1 0
D sup¹.!2 /Nk j k < !º D sup¹Ord \ Nk j k < !º D sup¹rank.Nk / j k < !º D ı;
126
4 The Pmax -extension
where ı is the least ordinal such that
ı > .!1 /N0 and such that ı is a Silver indiscernible of LŒx for all x 2 [¹R \ Nk j k 2 !º. From this iterability follows by an argument essentially identical to that given in the proof of Theorem 3.16. There it is proved that assuming ı 12 D !2 and that the nonstationary ideal is saturated then if X H.!2 / is a countable elementary substructure, the transitive collapse of X is iterable. t u Remark 4.18. (1) It is important to note that the assumptions of Lemma 4.17 do not actually imply that any iterations exist; the only implication is that if iterates exist, they are wellfounded. It is easy to construct sequences which satisfy the conditions of Lemma 4.17 and for which no (nontrivial) iterations exist. Lemma 4.19 isolates a condition sufficient to prove the existence of nontrivial iterations. (2) The conditions (i) and (ii) of the hypothesis of Lemma 4.17 are equivalent to the assertions: a) if C 2 Nk is closed and unbounded in !1N0 then there exists x 2 NkC1 such that ¹˛ < !1N0 j L˛ Œx is admissibleº C: b) V!C1 \ NkC1 †2 V!C1 .
t u
Lemma 4.19. Suppose that hNk W k < !i is a sequence of countable transitive sets such that for all k < !, Nk 2 NkC1 , Nk ZFC ; and Nk \ .INS /NkC1 D Nk \ .INS /NkC2 : Suppose that k 2 ! and that a 2 .P .!1 //Nk n .INS /NkC1 : Then there exists G [¹.P .!1 //Ni j i < !º such that a 2 G and such that for all i < !, G \ Ni is a uniform Ni -normal ultrafilter. Proof. Fix
a 2 .P .!1 //Nk n .INS /NkC1 ; by replacing hNi W i < !i with hNiCk W i < !i, we may suppose that a 2 N0 . Let hfi W i < !i enumerate all functions f W !1N0 ! !1N0 such that f 2 [¹Nj j j < !º and such that for all ˛ < !1N0 , f .˛/ < 1 C ˛. (Thus f .˛/ < ˛ for all ˛ > !.)
4.1 Iterable structures
127
We may suppose that fi 2 Ni for all i < !. Construct a sequence hai W i < !i such that a0 a and such that for all i < !, (1.1) ai !1N0 , (1.2) ai is cofinal in !1N0 , (1.3) ai 2 Ni n .INS /Ni C1 , (1.4) fi jai is constant, (1.5) aiC1 ai . The sequence is easily constructed by induction on i . Suppose ai is given. By (1.2) it follows that ai … .INS /Nj for all j i . This is the key point. Thus ai is a stationary subset of !1N0 in NiC2 and so since fiC1 is regressive there exists ˇ < !1N0 such that a D ¹ 2 ai j fiC1 ./ D ˇº … .INS /Ni C2 : since fiC1 2 NiC1 . Therefore a satisfies the requirements for
However a 2 NiC1 aiC1 . Let hai W i < !i be a sequence satisfying (1.1)–(1.4) and let
G D ¹b !1N0 j b 2 [¹Nj j j 2 !º and ai b for some i < !º: It follows that for each j < !, G \ Nj is a uniform Nj -normal ultrafilter. (1.2) guarantees uniformity and (1.4) guarantees normality. t u Lemma 4.17 yields the following corollary. Corollary 4.20. Suppose h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is a countable sequence such that for each k, Nk is a countable transitive model of ZFC and such that for all k: (i) Jk 2 Nk and Nk “Jk is a set of normal uniform ideals on !1 ”I (ii) Nk 2 NkC1 and jNk jNkC1 D !1N0 ; (iii) for each I 2 Jk there exists I 2 JkC1 such that, (1) I \ Nk D I , N
(2) for each A 2 Nk such that A P .!1 k / \ Nk n I if A is predense in .P .!1 / n I /Nk , then A is predense in .P .!1 / n I /NkC1 ;
128
4 The Pmax -extension
(iv) .Nk ; Jk / is iterable; (v) if C 2 Nk is closed and unbounded in !1N0 then there exists D 2 NkC1 such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ NkC1 . Then h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is iterable. Proof. Any iteration of h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i naturally defines an iteration of hNk W k < !i: By Lemma 4.17, the iterates of hNk W k < !i are wellfounded.
t u
Remark 4.21. The previous lemma is also true if condition (iv) is replaced by the condition that for all x 2 R \ .[¹Nk j k 2 !º/; x # 2 [¹Nk j k 2 !º.
t u
We continue our discussion of iterable structures with Lemma 4.22 which is a boundedness lemma for iterations of sequences of structures. Lemma 4.22 which will be used to guarantee that the conditions of Lemma 4.17 are satisfied, is proved by an argument identical to that for Lemma 4.7. Lemma 4.22 (ZFC ). Assume that for all x 2 R, x # exists. Suppose hNk W k < !i is an iterable sequence and that j W hNk W k < !i ! hNk W k < !i is an iteration of length !1 . Let x 2 R code hNk W k < !i. Then (1) for all k < !
rank.Nk / < ı 12 ;
(2) if C 2 [¹Nk j k < !º is closed and unbounded in !1 then there exists D 2 LŒx such that D C and such that D is closed and unbounded in t u !1 . Definition 4.15 suggests the following generalization of Definition 3.5. Definition 4.23. Suppose that M is a countable model of ZFC . A sequence hMˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ j ˛ < ˇ < i is a semi-iteration of M if the following hold.
4.1 Iterable structures
129
(1) M0 D M . (2) j˛;ˇ W M˛ ! Mˇ is a commuting family of elementary embeddings. (3) For each ˇ C1 < , Gˇ is an Mˇ -normal ultrafilter, Mˇ C1 is the Mˇ -ultrapower of Mˇ by Gˇ and jˇ;ˇ C1 W Mˇ ! Mˇ C1 is the induced elementary embedding. (4) For each ˇ < if ˇ is a limit ordinal then Mˇ is the direct limit of ¹M˛ j ˛ < ˇº and for all ˛ < ˇ, j˛;ˇ is the induced elementary embedding. A model N is a semi-iterate of M if it occurs in an semi-iteration of M . The model M is strongly iterable if every semi-iterate of M is wellfounded. t u Clearly if M “INS is saturated” then every semi-iteration of M is an iteration of M . We recall the following notation. Suppose A R. Then †11 .A/ is the set of all BR such that B can be defined from real parameters by a †1 formula in the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i: if both B and R n B are †11 .A/. A set B R is Let ı 11 .A/ be the supremum of the lengths of the prewellorderings of R that are 1 1 .A/. 1 1 .A/
Lemma 4.24. Suppose that A R and that there exists X H.!2 / such that hX; A \ X; 2i hH.!2 /; A; 2i and such that the transitive collapse of X is A-iterable. Suppose that M is a transitive set, H.!2 / M , M ZFC ; and that M \ Ord < ı 11 .A/: Then the set of ¹Y M j Y is countable and MY is strongly iterableº contains a club in P!1 .M /. Here MY is the transitive collapse of Y . Proof. Let D rank.M / and let WR! be a surjection such that 1 ¹.x; y/ j .x/ .y/º 2 1 .A/:
130
4 The Pmax -extension
Let B D ¹.x; y/ j .x/ .y/º: Let N be a transitive set such that N ZFC and such that ¹M; ; Aº [ H.!2 / N . Let Y N be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹; M; Aº Y and let NY be the transitive collapse of Y . Let Y be the image of under the transitive collapse and let Y be the image of . Let X D Y \ M and let MX be the transitive collapse of X . Suppose j W .MX ; 2/ ! .M ; E / is an elementary embedding given by a countable semi-iteration. Since H.!2 /MX D H.!2 /NY ; j lifts to define a semi-iteration k W .NY ; 2/ ! .N ; E /: We identify the standard part of N with its transitive collapse. Thus kjH.!2 /MX W H.!2 /MX ! k.H.!2 /MX / is a countable iteration. By Theorem 3.34, H.!2 /MX is A-iterable. Therefore k.A \ NY / D A \ N 1 and so since B is 1 .A/ in parameters from NY , k.B \ NY / D B \ N :
By elementarity, it follows that k.Y / W R \ N ! k.Y / is a surjection and that B \ N D ¹.x; y/ j k.Y /.x/ k.Y /.y/º: Therefore k.Y / is an ordinal and so k.MX / is wellfounded. Thus j.MX / is wellfounded since j.MX / elementarily embeds into k.MX /. Therefore MX is strongly-iterable.
t u
Definition 4.25. The nonstationary ideal on !1 is semi-saturated if for all generic extensions, V ŒG, of V , if U 2 V ŒG is a V -normal ultrafilter on !1V , then Ult.V; U / is wellfounded. t u
4.1 Iterable structures
131
Lemma 4.26. Suppose INS is not semi-saturated and that G Coll.!; P .!1 // is V -generic. Then there exists U 2 V ŒG such that U is a V -normal ultrafilter on !1V and such that Ult.V; U / is not wellfounded. Proof. Suppose INS is not semi-saturated in V . Then there exists a V -normal ultrafilter U0 such that U0 is set generic over V and such that Ult.V; U0 / is not wellfounded. Let be an ordinal such that ¹f W !1V ! j f 2 V º=U0 is not wellfounded. We work in V ŒG. Let hbi W i < !i be an enumeration of .P .!1 //V and let hgi W i < !i be an enumeration of all functions g W !1V ! !1V such that g 2 V and such that for all ˛ < !1V , g.˛/ < 1 C ˛. Let T be the set of finite sequences h.ai ; fi / W i ni such that for all i < n, (1.1) ai 2 .P .!1 //V n ¹;º, and aiC1 ai , (1.2) ai bi or ai \ bi D ;, (1.3) fi W !1V ! , fi 2 V and for all ˇ 2 aiC1 , fiC1 .ˇ/ < fi .ˇ/; (1.4) gi jai is constant. T is a tree ordered by extension. Any infinite branch of T yields a V -normal ultrafilter, U , such that ¹f W !1V ! j f 2 V º=U is not wellfounded. Conversely if U is a V -normal ultrafilter such that ¹f W !1V ! j f 2 V º=U is not wellfounded, then U defines an infinite branch of T . Therefore U0 defines an infinite branch of T and so T is not wellfounded. By absoluteness, T must have an infinite branch in V ŒG. t u Clearly if INS is !2 -saturated then INS is semi-saturated. Lemma 4.27. Suppose that INS is semi-saturated and that U P .!1 / is a uniform, V -normal ultrafilter which set generic over V . Let j W V ! M V ŒU be the associated generic elementary embedding. Then j.!1 / D !2 .
132
4 The Pmax -extension
Proof. For each ˛ < !2 let
˛ W !1 ! ˛
be a surjection and define f˛ W !1 ! !1 by f˛ .ˇ/ D ordertype.˛ Œˇ/. Suppose that U P .!1 / is a uniform, V -normal ultrafilter which set generic over V . Let j W V ! M V ŒU be the associated generic elementary embedding. Then for each ˛, j.f˛ /.!1V / D ˛I i. e. the function f˛ necessarily represents ˛ (it is a canonical function for ˛). We begin by noting the following. Suppose that I0 P .!1 / is a normal uniform ideal and that h W !1 ! !1 is a function such that for each ˛ < !2 , ¹ˇ < !1 j f˛ .ˇ/ < h.ˇ/º … I0 : Then there is a normal, uniform, ideal I0 P .!1 / such that I0 I0 and such that for each ˛ < !2 , ¹ˇ < !1 j h.ˇ/ f˛ .ˇ/º 2 I0 I simply define I0 to be the ideal generated by I0 [ ¹¹ˇ < !1 j h.ˇ/ f˛ .ˇ/º j ˛ < !2 º: It is straightforward to verify that this is a normal ideal and that it is proper. The point is that for all ˛1 ˛2 < !2 , ¹ˇ < !1 j f˛2 .ˇ/ h.ˇ/º n ¹ˇ < !1 j f˛1 .ˇ/ h.ˇ/º 2 INS : Assume toward a contradiction that the lemma fails. Then it follows that there exists a function h W !1 ! !1 and a normal, uniform, ideal I on !1 such that if U P .!1 / is a V -normal ultrafilter which is set generic over V such that U \ I D ;, then j.h/.!1V / D !2V where j W V ! M V ŒU be the associated generic elementary embedding. Otherwise one can easily construct a V -normal ultrafilter U which is set generic over V and such that Ult.V; U / is not wellfounded. Clearly we can suppose that for all ˇ < !1 , h.ˇ/ is a nonzero limit ordinal. For each ˇ < !1 let hˇk W k < !i be an increasing cofinal sequence in h.ˇ/. For each k < ! define hk W !1 ! !1 by hk .ˇ/ D ˇk .
4.1 Iterable structures
133
For each k < ! there must exist ˛k < !2 such that ¹ˇ < !1 j f˛k .ˇ/ hk .ˇ/º 2 I: Otherwise for some k0 < !1 and for each ˛ < !2 , ¹ˇ < !1 j f˛ .ˇ/ < hk0 .ˇ/º … I: In this case it follows, by the remarks above, that there is a normal ideal I such that I I and such that if U P .!1 / is a V -normal ultrafilter, set generic over V , with U \ I D ;, then j .hk0 /.!1V / !2V where j is the associated generic elementary embedding. This contradicts the choice of h and I . Let ˛! D sup¹˛k j k < !º. Thus ¹ˇ j f˛! .ˇ/ < h.ˇ/º 2 I since for all ˇ < !1 , h.ˇ/ D sup¹hk .ˇ/ j k < !º: This again contradicts the choice of h and I .
t u
Corollary 4.28. Suppose that INS is semi-saturated and that f W !1 ! !1 . Then there exists ˛ < !2 such that the following holds. Let W !1 ! ˛ be a surjection. The set ¹ˇ < !1 j f .ˇ/ < ordertype.Œˇ/º contains a closed, unbounded, subset of !1 . Proof. As in the proof of Lemma 4.27, for each ˛ < !2 let ˛ W !1 ! ˛ be a surjection and define f˛ W !1 ! !1 by f .ˇ/ D ordertype.˛ Œˇ/. Assume toward a contradiction that for each ˛ < !2 , ¹ˇ < !1 j f˛ .ˇ/ f .ˇ/º … INS : Then, arguing as in the proof of Lemma 4.27, there is a normal, uniform, ideal I P .!1 / such that for each ˛ < !2 , ¹ˇ < !1 j f .ˇ/ f˛ .ˇ/º 2 I: Suppose that U P .!1 / is a V -normal ultrafilter such that U is set generic over V and such that U \ I D ;. Let j W V ! M V ŒU be the associated generic elementary embedding. Then !2V j.f /.!1V / which contradicts Lemma 4.27. t u
4 The Pmax -extension
134
We will encounter situations in which the nonstationary ideal on !1 is semisaturated and not saturated cf. Definition 6.11 and Theorem 6.13. Nevertheless the assertion that INS is semi-saturated has many of the consequences proved in Section 3.1 for the assertion that INS is saturated. For example it is routine to modify the proofs in Section 3.1 to obtain the following variations of Lemma 3.14 and Theorem 3.17, together with the subsequent generalization of Theorem 3.47. Clearly, if the nonstationary ideal is semi-saturated in V then it is semi-saturated in L.P .!1 //. Theorem 4.29. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is semi-saturated and that P .!1 /# exists. Suppose that X H.!2 / is a countable elementary substructure. Then the transitive collapse of X is iterable. Proof. Clearly for all x 2 R, x # exists. Let Y L.P .!1 // be a countable elementary substructure containing infinitely many Silver indiscernibles of L.P .!1 //. Let X D Y \ H.!2 /, let N be the transitive collapse of Y and let M be the transitive collapse of X . Thus M D .H.!2 //N and N D L˛ .M / where ˛ D N \ Ord. Since Y contains infinitely many indiscernibles of L.P .!1 //, L˛ .M / L.M /: Finally INS is semi-saturated and so L.P .!1 // “INS is semi-saturated”: Therefore N “INS is semi-saturated” and so L.M / “INS is semi-saturated”: We claim that M is iterable. Suppose M is an iterate of M occurring in an iteration of length ˛. Let < !1 be such that ˛ < and such that L .M / L.M /:
4.1 Iterable structures
135
By an absoluteness argument analogous to the proof of Lemma 3.10, any semiiterate of L .M / occurring in a semi-iteration of L .M / of length less than is wellfounded. The iteration of M of length ˛ witnessing M is an iterate of M induces a semiiteration of L .M / of length ˛ producing a semi-iterate of L .M / into which M can be embedded. Therefore M is wellfounded and so M is iterable. Thus there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / whose transitive collapse is iterable. Thus by Theorem 3.19, if X H.!2 / is any countable elementary substructure, the transitive collapse of X is iterable. t u Theorem 4.30. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is semi-saturated and that ı 12 D !2 . P .!1 /# exists. Then Proof. By Theorem 3.19, the theorem is an immediate corollary of Theorem 4.29. u t The proof of Lemma 3.35 can similarly be adapted to prove the corresponding generalization of Lemma 3.35. Lemma 4.31. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is semi-saturated. Suppose A R and that B is weakly homogeneously Suslin for each set B which is projective in A. Let M be a transitive set such that M ZFC , P .!1 / M , and such that M # exists. Then ¹X M j X is countable and MX is A-iterableº t u contains a club in P!1 .M /. Here MX is the transitive collapse of X . Finally we obtain the generalization of the second covering theorem, Theorem 3.47, to the case when INS is simply assumed to be semi-saturated. Theorem 4.32. Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is semi-saturated. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model such that M ZF C DC C AD; and such that (i) R M , (ii) Ord M , (iii) every set A 2 M \ P .R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin in V . Suppose ı < ‚M , X ı and jX j D !1 . Then there exists Y 2 M such that M “jY j D !1 ” and such that X Y . Proof. This is an immediate corollary of Lemma 4.31, applied to the set, H.!2 /, and Theorem 3.45. t u
136
4 The Pmax -extension
4.2
The partial order Pmax
We now define the partial order Pmax . Definition 4.33. Let Pmax be the set of pairs h.M; I /; ai such that: (1) M is a countable transitive model of ZFC C MA!1 ; (2) I 2 M and M “I is a normal uniform ideal on !1 ”; (3) .M; I / is iterable; (4) a !1M ; (5) a 2 M and M “!1 D !1LŒaŒx for some real x” . Define a partial order on Pmax as follows: h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i if M0 2 M1 ; M0 is countable in M1 and there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that: (1) j.a0 / D a1 ; (2) M0 2 M1 and j 2 M1 ; (3) I1 \ M0 D I0 .
t u
Remark 4.34. (1) Given the results of Section 3.1 it would be more natural to define Pmax as the set of pairs .M; a/ where M is an iterable model in which the nonstationary ideal is saturated. Assuming 12 -Determinacy this yields an equivalent forcing notion. More precisely assuming 12 -Determinacy, the set of conditions h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that I is a saturated ideal in M and such that I is the nonstationary ideal in M, is dense in Pmax . (2) We shall prove that the nonstationary ideal is saturated in L.R/Pmax and that ZFC holds there. Thus Pmax is in some sense converting the existence of models with precipitous ideals (which are relatively easy to find) into the existence of models in which the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated. This is an aspect we shall exploit when we modify Pmax to show the relative consistency that the t u nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. There are equivalent versions of Pmax that do not require that the models which appear in the conditions be models of MA!1 , this is a degree of freedom which is essential for the variations that we shall define. In Chapter 5 we shall give three other (T) 0 , Pmax and Pmax . The first of these will involve presentations of Pmax , denoted by Pmax
4.2 The partial order Pmax
137
using the generic elementary embeddings associated to the stationary tower in place of embeddings associated to ideals on !1 . The second will be closer to Pmax , however the stationary tower will be used to generate the necessary conditions and so certain aspects of the analysis will differ. In fact there are strong arguments to support the 0 is actually the best presentation of Pmax . The third, Pmax , is claim that in the end, Pmax (T) a combination of Pmax and Pmax . In defining two of the variations of Pmax , we shall use these alternate formulations as a template, see Definition 6.54 and Definition 8.30. The following lemma indicates the utility of working with models of MA. We state it in a more general form than is strictly necessary for the analysis of Pmax . Lemma 4.35. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC C MA!1 . Suppose a 2 M, a !1M ; and
M “!1 D !1L.a;x/ for some x 2 R”:
Suppose j1 W M ! M1 and j2 W M ! M2 are semi-iterations of M such that (i) M1 is transitive, (ii) M2 is transitive, (iii) j1 .a/ D j2 .a/, (iv) j1 .!1M / D j2 .!1M /. Then M1 D M2 and j1 D j2 . Proof. This is a relatively standard fact. The key point, which we prove below, is that since both j1 .a/ D j2 .a/ and
j1 .!1M / D j.!2M /;
it follows that j1 .b/ D j2 .b/ for each set b 2 M such that b !1M . From this it follows easily by induction that at every stage the generic filters are the same and so j1 D j 2 . Let hs˛ W ˛ < !1M i be the sequence of almost disjoint subsets of ! where for each < !1M , s is the first subset of ! constructed in L.a; x/ which is almost disjoint from sˇ for each ˇ < . Thus hs˛ W ˛ < !1M i 2 L.a; x/
138
4 The Pmax -extension
and this sequence is definable from a and x. Since j1 ..a; !1M // D j2 ..a; !1M // it follows that
j1 .hs˛ W ˛ < !1M i/ D j2 .hs˛ W ˛ < !1M i/:
Let
ht˛ W ˛ < i D j1 .hs˛ W ˛ < !1M i/
where D j1 .!1M / D j2 .!1M /. Suppose that b 2 M and b !1M . Since M MA!1 it follows that there exists t 2 M such that t almost disjoint codes b relative to hs˛ W ˛ < !1M i; i. e. b D ¹˛ j t \ s˛ is infiniteº. Therefore j1 .b/ D ¹˛ < j t \ t˛ is infiniteº D j2 .b/: Therefore for each b 2 M such that b !1M , j1 .b/ D j2 .b/. The lemma follows. t u The next two lemmas are key to proving many of the properties of the partial order Pmax . Because we wish to apply them within the models occurring in conditions we work in ZFC . Lemma 4.36 (ZFC ). Suppose .M; I / is a countable transitive iterable model where I 2 M is a normal uniform ideal on !1M and M ZFC . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Then there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that: (1) j.!1M / D !1 ; (2) J \ M D I . Proof. Fix a sequence hAk;˛ W k < !; ˛ < !1 i of J -positive sets which are pairwise disjoint. The ideal J is normal hence each Ak;˛ is stationary in !1 . We suppose that Ak;˛ \ .˛ C 1/ D ;. Fix a function f W ! !1M ! P .!1M / \ M n I such that (1.1) f is onto, (1.2) for all k < !, f jk !1M 2 M, (1.3) for all A 2 M if A has cardinality !1M in M and if A P .!1M / n I then A ran.f jk !1M / for some k < !.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
139
The function f is simply used to anticipate subsets of !1 in the final model. Suppose j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is an iteration. Then we define j .f / D [¹j .f jk !1M / j k < !º
and it is easily verified that the range of j .f / is P .!1M /\M nI . This follows from (1.3). We construct an iteration of M of length !1 using the function f to provide a book-keeping device for all of the subsets of !1 which belong to the final model and do not belong to the image of I in the final model. More precisely construct an iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i such that for each ˛ < !1 , if !1M˛ 2 Ak; then j0;˛ .f /.k; / 2 G˛ . The set C D ¹j0;˛ .!1M / j ˛ < !1 º is a club in !1 . Thus for each B !1 such that B 2 M!1 and B … j0;!1 .I / there exists k < !; < !1 such that .C n C 1/ \ Ak; B \ Ak; : Further if B !1 , B 2 M!1 and B 2 j0;!1 .I / then B \ C D ;. Thus J \ M!1 D I!1 .
t u
Lemma 4.37 is the analog of Lemma 4.36 for iterable sequences. The proof is a straightforward modification of the proof of Lemma 4.36. Lemma 4.37 (ZFC ). Suppose h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is an iterable sequence such that Nk ZFC for each k < !. Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Then there exists an iteration j W h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i ! h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i such that: (1) j.!1N0 / D !1 ; (2) J \ Nk D Jk for each k < !.
t u
We analyze the conditions in Pmax in a variety of circumstances. The partial order Pmax is nontrivial under fairly mild assumptions. Lemma 4.38. Assume that for every real x, x exists. Then for each x 2 R the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that x 2 M is dense in Pmax . Proof. Suppose x 2 R and h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax . Let y 2 R code the pair .x; h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i/ so that x 2 LŒy, h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 LŒy and h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i is countable in LŒy. y exists and so there is a transitive inner model N and countable ordinals ı < such that y 2 N , N contains the ordinals, N ZFC C GCH;
140
4 The Pmax -extension
is inaccessible in N , and such that ı is a measurable cardinal in N . Let Q 2 N be a ı-cc poset in N such that; (1.1) N Q MA C :CH, (1.2) N Q ı D !1 , (1.3) Q has cardinality < in N . Let J 2 N be an ideal dual to a normal measure on ı in N . Let G Q be N -generic and let JG be the ideal generated by J in N ŒG. Thus JG is a normal uniform ideal on ı in N ŒG. By .Jech and Mitchell 1983/ JG is a precipitous ideal in N ŒG. Thus by Lemma 4.5, any iteration of .N ŒG; JG / is wellfounded and so by Lemma 4.4, .N ŒG; JG / is iterable. Let j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be an iteration of .M0 ; I0 / such that j 2 N ŒG and such that I0 D JG \ M0 . Let b D j.a0 /. Thus h.N ŒG; JG /; bi 2 Pmax : Finally x 2 N ŒG and h.N ŒG; JG /; bi < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i.
t u
Remark 4.39. Assuming that for every real x, x exists, it follows that the set of conditions h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax for which M ZFC is dense in Pmax . Thus in the definition of Pmax the fragment of ZFC used is not really relevant provided it is strong enough. t u For the analysis of Pmax we need a much stronger existence theorem for conditions. Lemma 4.40. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose that X R and that X 2 L.R/. Then there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; I / is X -iterable, and further the set of such conditions is dense in Pmax . Proof. We work in L.R/. Suppose that for some X R with X 2 L.R/ no such condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax exists. Then by standard reflection arguments in L.R/ we may assume that X is 21 definable in L.R/. By the Martin-Steel theorem, Theorem 2.3, in L.R/ the pointclass 21 definable in L.R/ †21 has the scale property. Thus any set X R R which is is Suslin in L.R/ and so can be uniformized by a function which is 21 definable in
4.2 The partial order Pmax
141
L.R/. Let F W R ! R be a function such that if N is a transitive model of ZF closed under F then hH.!1 /N ; X \ N; 2i hH.!1 /; X; 2i: Let Y R be the set of reals which code elements of F X . Since X is 21 it follows 2 2 that F may be chosen such that F is 1 in which case Y is 1 . Let T; T be trees such that Y D pŒT and R n Y D pŒT . Note that if N is any transitive model of ZF with T 2 N then N is closed under F . Since AD holds, there exists a transitive inner model N of ZFC, containing the ordinals such that T 2 N , T 2 N and such that is a measurable cardinal in N for some countable ordinal . !1 is strongly inaccessible in N and so by passing to a generic extension of N if necessary we can require that the GCH holds in N at . Let Q 2 N be a -cc poset in N such that; (1.1) N Q MA C :CH, (1.2) N Q D !1 , (1.3) jQj D C in N . Let G Q be N -generic. Let I 2 N be a normal ideal on which is dual to a normal measure on . Let IG be the normal ideal generated by I in N ŒG. Thus in N ŒG, IG is a precipitous ideal on !1N ŒG . Let ı < !1 be an inaccessible cardinal in N ŒG. Thus by Lemma 4.4 and Lemma 4.5, it follows that .Nı ŒG; IG / is iterable. Since T 2 N ŒG it follows that hH.!1 /N ŒG ; X \ N ŒG; 2i hH.!1 /; X; 2i: We claim that .Nı ŒG; IG / is X -iterable. Suppose j W Nı ŒG ! M is an iteration of .Nı ŒG; IG /. Then by Lemma 4.4, there corresponds an iteration j W N ŒG ! M of .N ŒG; IG / and an elementary embedding k W M ! j .Nı ŒG/ such that k ı j D j jNı ŒG. (In fact in our situation M D j .Nı ŒG/ and k is the identity.) Let YN ŒG D pŒT \ N ŒG. Thus j .YN ŒG / D pŒj .T / \ M : However (2.1) pŒT pŒj .T /, (2.2) pŒT pŒj .T /.
142
4 The Pmax -extension
Further by absoluteness pŒj .T / \ pŒj .T / D ; and so pŒT D pŒj .T / and pŒT D pŒj .T /. Thus j .YN ŒG / D Y \ M and so j.YN ŒG / D Y \ M . Therefore j.X \ N ŒG/ D X \ M: This proves that .Nı ŒG; IG / is X -iterable. Let a 2 Nı ŒG be such that Nı ŒG a !1
and
!1 D !1LŒa :
h.Nı ŒG; IG /; ai is the desired condition. The density of these conditions follows abstractly. Let h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax . Let z 2 R code h.M; I /; ai. Choose a condition h.N ; J /; bi 2 Pmax such that; (3.1) Y \ N 2 N , (3.2) hH.!1 /N ; Y \ N i hH.!1 /; Y i, (3.3) .N ; J / is Y -iterable, where Y is the set of reals which code elements of X ¹zº. By Lemma 4.36, there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j 2 N and I D J \ M . Let a D j.a/. Thus h.N ; J /; a i 2 Pmax and h.N ; J /; a i < h.M; I /; ai. h.N ; J /; a i is the required condition. t u The entire analysis of Pmax that we give can be carried out abstractly just assuming the following: For each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; I / is X -iterable. This in turn is equivalent to: For each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there exists M 2 H.!1 / such that (1) M is transitive, (2) M ZFC , (3) X \ M 2 M, (4) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (5) .M; I / is X -iterable.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
143
This includes the proof that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated in L.R/Pmax . However we shall see in Chapter 5 that this assumption implies ADL.R/ . This property for a set of reals, X , is really a regularity property which can be established from a variety of different assumptions. For example, it can be established quite easily from just the assumption that every set of reals which is projective in X is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Theorem 4.41. Suppose X R and that every set of reals which is projective in X is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; I / is X -iterable. Proof. Note that since there are nontrivial weakly homogeneously Suslin sets there must exist a measurable cardinal. Let ı be the least measurable cardinal and let I be a normal uniform ideal on ı such that I is maximal; i. e. the dual filter is a normal measure. By collapsing 2ı to ı C if necessary we can assume that 2ı D ı C . The generic collapse of 2ı to ı C preserves the hypothesis of the theorem and it adds no new reals to V . X is weakly homogeneously Suslin and so there exists a weakly homogeneous tree S such that X D pŒS . The tree S is necessarily ı-weakly homogeneous. Let S be a weakly homogeneous tree such that pŒS D R n X . Again S is necessarily ı-weakly homogeneous and so if G P is V -generic where P is a partial order of size less than ı then in V ŒG, pŒS D R n pŒS . Let Y be the set of reals which code elements of the first order diagram of hH.!1 /; X; 2i: Y is weakly homogeneously Suslin since it is a countable union of weakly homogeneously Suslin sets. Similarly R n Y is also weakly homogeneous Suslin since it too is the countable union of weakly homogeneously Suslin sets. Therefore there exist weakly homogeneous trees T and T such that pŒT D Y
and such that pŒT D R n Y . The trees T and T are each necessarily ı-weakly homogeneous. Thus if G P is V -generic where P is a partial order of size less than ı, then in V ŒG, pŒT D R n pŒT . A key point is that ı is measurable and so this also holds if P is a partial order which is ı-cc.
144
4 The Pmax -extension
Let > ı C be a regular cardinal such that ¹S; T; S ; T º H. /. Thus H. / is admissible and if Q 2 H. / is any partial order of cardinality at most ı C then H. /ŒG ZFC and H. /ŒG is admissible, whenever G Q is V -generic. Let Z H. / be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹S; T; S ; T ; I º Z. ; IN be the images of Let N be the transitive collapse of Z and let ıN ; SN ; SN ı; S; S ; I under the collapsing map. Let Q 2 N be a ıN -cc poset in N such that; (1.1) N Q MA C :CH, (1.2) N Q ıN D !1 , C . (1.3) N jQj D ıN
Let G Q be N -generic and let J be the normal ideal in N ŒG generated by IN . Note that pŒSN \ N ŒG 2 N ŒG since N ŒG is admissible. Suppose that j W .N ŒG; J / ! .N ŒG ; J / is an iteration of countable length. Then it follows that j W .N; IN / ! .N ; j.IN // is an iteration. But IN 2 N is the ideal dual to a normal measure in N on ıN and so this is an iteration in the usual sense. Let W N ! Z be the inverse of the collapsing map. Thus by standard arguments there exists Z H. / such that Z Z , N is the transitive collapse of Z and ı j jN D where W N ! Z is the inverse of the collapsing map. / pŒS . Hence Thus pŒj.SN / pŒS . Similarly pŒj.SN pŒj.SN / \ N ŒG D X \ N ŒG and so j.X \ N ŒG/ D X \ N ŒG . This proves that X \ N ŒG 2 N ŒG and that .N ŒG; J / is X -iterable. It remains to show that hH.!1 /N ŒG ; X \ N ŒG; 2i hH.!1 /; X; 2i: A key point is the following. Suppose G P is V -generic where P is a partial order of size less than ı. Then in V ŒG, pŒT codes the diagram of hH.!1 /; pŒS ; 2i. Again ı is measurable and so if G P is V -generic where P is a partial order which is ı-cc, then in V ŒG, pŒT codes the diagram of hH.!1 /; pŒS ; 2i. By elementarity and the remarks above it follows that pŒTN \ N ŒG codes the diagram of hH.!1 /N ŒG ; N ŒG \ pŒSN ; 2i. Thus Y \ N ŒG codes the diagram of hH.!1 /N ŒG ; N ŒG \ X; 2i and so t u hH.!1 /N ŒG ; X \ N ŒG; 2i hH.!1 /; X; 2i:
4.2 The partial order Pmax
145
Remark 4.42. The requirement hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i is important in the analysis of the Pmax -extension. It is also more difficult to achieve. For example if there is a measurable cardinal and if X R is universally Baire then there exists .M; I / which is X -iterable. The proof is identical to that of Theorem 4.41. We do not know if from these assumptions one can find an X -iterable structure .M; I / for which hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i even if one adds the assumption that every set of reals which is projective in X is universally Baire. The notion that a set of reals is universally Baire is defined in .Feng, Magidor, and Woodin 1992/. It has a simple reformulation in terms of Suslin representations which is all that is relevant here: If X is universally Baire then for any partial order P there exist trees T; T such that X D pŒT and such that in V P , pŒT D R n pŒT . Universally Baire sets are briefly discussed in Section 10.3. t u As a corollary to Lemma 4.37 we easily establish that under suitable hypotheses, the partial order Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Lemma 4.43. Assume Pmax ¤ ; and that for each x 2 R the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that x 2 M is dense in Pmax . Then Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Proof. We first prove that Pmax is !-closed. Suppose that hpk W k < !i is a descending sequence of conditions in Pmax and that for each k < !, pk D h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i: Let b D [¹ak j k < !º. For each k < ! there is a unique iteration jk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Nk ; Jk / such that jk .ak / D b. We summarize the properties of the sequence h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i: (1.1) Nk ZFC ; (1.2) Jk 2 Nk and Nk “Jk is a normal uniform ideal on !1 ”I (1.3) .Nk ; Jk / is iterable; (1.4) Nk 2 NkC1 ; (1.5) jNk j D !1 in NkC1 ;
146
4 The Pmax -extension
(1.6) 5A is of measure 1 for JkC1 whenever A 2 Nk , N
A P .!1 k / \ Nk n Jk ; and A is dense; (1.7) JkC1 \ Nk D Jk ; (1.8) if C 2 Nk is closed and unbounded in !1N0 then there exists D 2 NkC1 such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ NkC1 . These properties are straightforward to verify, (1.6) follows from Lemma 4.10 and (1.8) follows from Lemma 4.6. By Corollary 4.20, the sequence h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is iterable. Let z be a real which codes h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i. Thus there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that z 2 M. By Lemma 4.37, there is an iteration j W h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i ! h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i such that: (2.1) j 2 M; (2.2) j.!1N0 / D !1M ; (2.3) I \ Nk D Jk for each k < !. Let a D j.b/. Thus h.M; I /; a i 2 Pmax and h.M; I /; a i < h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i for all k < !. This shows that Pmax is !-closed. We finish by showing that Pmax is homogeneous. Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i are conditions in Pmax . Let z be a real which codes the pair of these conditions. Suppose h.M; I /; ai is a condition in Pmax such that z 2 M. Thus there are iterations j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / and j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / such that: (3.1) j0 2 M and j1 2 M; (3.2) j0 .!1M0 / D !1M D j1 .!1M1 /; (3.3) I \ M0 D I0 and I \ M1 D I1 .
4.2 The partial order Pmax
147
Let a0 D j0 .a0 / and let a1 D j1 .a1 /. The key point is the following. Suppose that h.N ; J /; bi 2 Pmax and h.N ; J /; bi < h.M; I /; ai. Let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the unique iteration such that j.a/ D b. Then h.N ; J /; j.a0 /i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and
h.N ; J /; j.a1 /i < h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i:
Thus the conditions below h.M; I /; ai have canonical interpretations as conditions below h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and as conditions below h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i. These interpretations are unique given j0 and j1 . Now suppose that G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then by genericity there exists a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 G such that z 2 M where z is a real coding both the conditions h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i. From the arguments above it follows that we can define generics G0 Pmax and G1 Pmax such that h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G0 , h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 G1 and such that L.R/ŒG0 D L.R/ŒG1 D L.R/ŒG: This shows that Pmax is homogeneous.
t u
Using the iteration lemmas we prove two more lemmas which we shall use to complete our initial analysis of Pmax . We begin with a definition that establishes some key notation. Definition 4.44. A filter G Pmax is semi-generic if for all ˛ < !1 there exists a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 G such that ˛ < !1M . Suppose G Pmax is semi-generic. Define AG !1 by AG D [¹a j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº: For each h.M; I /; ai 2 G let jG W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the embedding from the iteration which sends a to AG . Let P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 / \ M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº and let
IG D [¹I j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº:
t u
Remark 4.45. (1) Suppose G Pmax is a semi-generic filter. Then Pmax is somewhat nontrivial. Strictly speaking, a filter G Pmax may be, for example, L.R/generic and not be semi-generic. We shall never consider filters in Pmax without assumptions which guarantee that Pmax is nontrivial.
148
4 The Pmax -extension
(2) The iteration jG is uniquely specified by G and the condition h.M; I /; ai 2 G. It is not in general uniquely specified by simply G and .M; I /. A more accurate notation would denote jG by jp;G where p D h.M; I /; ai. However we shall use the potentially ambiguous notation jG , letting the context arbitrate any ambiguities. t u Lemma 4.46 isolates the combinatorial fact which will be used to prove that !1 DC holds in L.R/Pmax . This lemma will be applied within models occurring in Pmax conditions and so the lemma is proved assuming only ZFC . Lemma 4.46 (ZFC ). Assume Pmax ¤ ; and that for each x 2 R, the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that x 2 M is dense in Pmax . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 and that Y H.!1 / is a .nonempty/ set of pairs .p; f / such that: (i) p 2 Pmax ; (ii) for some ˛ < !1 , f 2 ¹0; 1º˛ . Suppose that for all p 2 Pmax , .p; ;/ 2 Y , and suppose that Y satisfies the following closure conditions. (iii) Suppose .p; f / 2 Y and q < p. Then .q; f / 2 Y . (iv) Suppose .p; f / 2 Y and ˛ < dom.f /. Then .p; f j˛/ 2 Y . (v) Suppose .p; f / 2 Y and ˛ < !1 . Then there exists .q; g/ 2 Y such that q < p, f g and such that ˛ < dom.g/. (vi) Suppose p 2 Pmax , ˛ < !1 , ˛ is a limit ordinal and f W ˛ ! ¹0; 1º: Then either .p; f / 2 Y or .p; f jˇ/ … Y for some ˇ < ˛. Then for each q0 2 Pmax there is a semi-generic filter G Pmax and a function f W !1 ! ¹0; 1º such that q0 2 G, IG D J \ P .!1 /G and such that for all ˛ < !1 , .p; f jˇ/ 2 Y for some p 2 G and for some ˇ > ˛.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
149
Proof. Let h.p˛ ; f˛ / W ˛ < !1 i be a sequence such that for all ˛ < ˇ < !1 (1.1) p0 < q0 , (1.2) .p˛ ; f˛ / 2 Y , (1.3) pˇ < p˛ , (1.4) f˛ fˇ , (1.5) ˛ dom.f˛ /, (1.6) J \ M˛ D I˛ , where .M˛ ; I˛ / is defined as follows. Let h.M˛ ; I˛ /; a˛ i D p˛ . Let a D [¹a˛ j ˛ < !1 º: Then for each ˛ there exists a unique iteration j˛ W .M˛ ; I˛ / ! .M˛ ; I˛ / such that j˛ .a˛ / D a . This sequence is easily constructed using the properties of Y and the proof of Lemma 4.36. Let G be the filter generated by ¹p˛ j ˛ < !1 º and let f D [¹f˛ j ˛ < !1 º: Thus G is a semi-generic filter and .G; f / has the desired properties.
t u
The next lemma is simply the formulation of Lemma 4.10 for the special case we are presently interested in. This is the case for structures of the form .M; I /; i. e. when only one ideal is designated. Lemma 4.47 (ZFC ). Suppose .M; I / is a countable transitive model where I 2M is a normal uniform ideal on !1M and M ZFC . Suppose that j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
is a wellfounded iteration of length !1 and that A P .!1 /M n I is a maximal antichain with A 2 M . Let hA˛ W ˛ < !1 i be an enumeration of A in V . Then 5¹A˛ j ˛ < !1 º contains a club in !1 .
t u
150
4 The Pmax -extension
Lemma 4.48 (ZFC ). Assume Pmax ¤ ; and that for each x 2 R, the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that x 2 M is dense in Pmax . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 and that Y H.!1 / is a .nonempty/ set of pairs .p; b/ such that: (i) p 2 Pmax ; (ii) b !1M , b 2 M, and b … I ; where p D h.M; I /; ai. (iii) Suppose .h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i; b0 / 2 Y and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i. Then .h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i; b1 / 2 Y where b1 is the image of b0 under the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends a0 to a1 . (iv) Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax , b0 2 M0 , b0 !1M0 and b0 … I0 . Then there exists .h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i; b1 / 2 Y such that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and such that b1 j.b0 / where j is the embedding given by the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends a0 to a1 . Then for each p0 2 Pmax there exists a semi-generic filter G Pmax such that p0 2 G, J \ P .!1 /G D IG ; jP .!1 /G j D !1 ; and such that
!1 n 5A 2 J
where A is the set of j.b/ such that .h.M; I /; ai; b/ 2 Y , h.M; I /; ai 2 G, and j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the embedding given by the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to AG . Proof. Let S ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ is a limit ordinalº and fix a partition hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i of S into disjoint sets such that S D 5¹S˛ j ˛ < !1 º and such that S˛ … J for each ˛ < !1 . For any uniform normal ideal such a partition exists. We construct a sequence h.q˛ ; b˛ / W ˛ < !1 i of elements of Y such that for all ˛ < ˇ < !1 , qˇ < q˛ < p0 and such that; (1.1) for each ˛ < !1 there is a club C !1 such that S˛ \ C j˛ .b˛ /, (1.2) for each ˛ < !1 and for each d 2 P .!1M˛ / \ M˛ with d … I˛ there exists ˇ < !1 such that ˛ < ˇ and bˇ j˛;ˇ .d /,
4.2 The partial order Pmax
151
where for each ˛ < !1 , h.M˛ ; I˛ /; a˛ i D q˛ , j˛ W .M˛ ; I˛ / ! .M˛ ; I˛ / is the embedding given by the iteration which sends a˛ to [¹aˇ j ˇ < !1 º and where for all ˛ < ˇ < !1 j˛;ˇ W .M˛ ; I˛ / ! .M˛ˇ ; I˛ˇ / is the embedding from the iteration which sends a˛ to aˇ . We construct the sequence h.q˛ ; b˛ / W ˛ < !1 i and at the same time a sequence hd˛ W ˛ < !1 i by induction on ˛ where for each ˛ < !1 , d˛ 2 P .!1M˛ / \ M˛ n I˛ : Suppose h.q˛ ; b˛ / W ˛ < i and hd˛ W ˛ < i have been constructed. If D ˇ C 1 then choose .h.M; I /; ai; b/ 2 Y such that h.M; I /; ai < qˇ and such that b j.dˇ / where j W .Mˇ ; Iˇ / ! .MO ˇ ; IOˇ / is the iteration such that j.aˇ / D a. By (iv), .h.M; I /; ai; b/ 2 Y exists. Let .q ; b / D .h.M; I /; ai; b/ and let d 2 P .!1M / \ M n I . Now suppose that is a limit ordinal and let hk W k < !i be an increasing cofinal sequence of ordinals less than . For each k < ! let .Nk ; Jk / be the iterate of .Mk ; Ik / defined by the iteration which sends ak to [¹aˇ j ˇ < º. Thus h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i satisfies the conditions for Corollary 4.20 and so it is an iterable sequence. This is just as in the proof that Pmax is !-closed. Thus 2 5¹Sˇ j ˇ < º. Let ˇ < be such that 2 Sˇ . Let h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i be the generic ultrapower of h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i by a [¹Nk j k < !º-generic ultrafilter which contains j.bˇ / where j is the embedding from the iteration of .Mˇ ; Iˇ / which sends aˇ to [¹aˇ j ˇ < º. Let a be the image of [¹aˇ j ˇ < º under this iteration. Let x be a real which codes h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i and choose h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that x 2 M. The condition exists since we have assumed that for every real t , t exists. h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i is an iterable sequence and so by Lemma 4.37, there exists an iteration j W h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i ! h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i
in M such that j.!1N / D !1M and such that for all k < !, I \ Nk D Jk . Let a D j.a /. Thus h.M; I /; a i 2 Pmax and for all ˛ <
h.M; I /; a i < q˛ < p0 :
152
4 The Pmax -extension
Thus by property (iii) of Y there exists .q; b/ 2 Y such that q < h.M; I /; a i. Let .q ; b / D .q; b/ and let d 2 P .!1M / \ M n I . This completes the construction of the sequences. Notice that we have complete freedom in the choice of d at each stage . Let G Pmax be the filter generated by ¹q˛ j ˛ < !1 º. We may assume by a routine book-keeping argument that ¹j˛ .d˛ / j ˛ < !1 º D [¹M˛ \ P .!1 / j ˛ < !1 º n IG D P .!1 /G n IG : We claim that G is the desired semi-generic filter. G is generated by a subset of size !1 and so it follows that jAG j D !1 . All that needs to be verified is that 5AG is of measure 1 relative to J and that IG D J \ P .!1 /G . For each ˛ < !1 there is a club C˛ !1 such that C˛ \ S˛ j˛ .b˛ /. Further by definition j˛ .b˛ / 2 AG and so since S D 5¹S˛ j ˛ < !1 º it follows that there is a club C !1 such that S \ C 5AG , take C D 4¹C˛ j ˛ < !1 º. However S is of measure 1 relative to J and J is a uniform normal ideal. Hence C \ S is of measure 1 relative to J . By the choice of hd˛ W ˛ < !1 i it follows that ¹j˛ .d˛ / j ˛ < !1 º D P .!1 /G n IG : .b˛C1 / j˛ .d˛ /. Therefore every set in However for each ˛ < !1 , j˛C1 P .!1 /G n IG is positive relative to J . Further every set in IG is nonstationary and so IG D J \ P .!1 /G :
t u
The lemma follows.
Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. We assume also that for all reals x, x exists so that Pmax is nontrivial. Thus the filter G is semi-generic and so we have defined AG !1 , P .!1 /G P .!1 /, and IG P .!1 /G . The next theorem gives the basic analysis of Pmax . Theorem 4.49. Suppose that for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG !1 -DC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal saturated ideal; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
153
Proof. We claim that for each set X R with X 2 L.R/ the set of such conditions in Pmax which satisfy (i)–(iii) is dense in Pmax . The point here is that given X and a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax define a new set X R as follows. Fix a real z which codes h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and define X to be the set of reals which code a pair .z; t / where t 2 X . We assume X is nonempty. Thus X 2 L.R/ and so there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (1.1) X \ M 2 M, (1.2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (1.3) .M; I / is X -iterable. By (1.2) it follows that z 2 M. Thus by Lemma 4.36, there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / in M such that I D I \ M0 . Thus h.M; I /; j.a0 /i 2 Pmax and h.M; I /; j.a0 /i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i: h.M; I /; j.a0 /i is the desired condition. Therefore by Lemma 4.43, Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. We first prove that if G Pmax is L.R/-generic then !1 -DC holds in L.R/ŒG. Since Pmax is !-closed it follows that DC holds in L.R/ŒG. Every set in L.R/ŒG is definable from an ordinal, a real and G. Therefore to establish that !1 -DC holds in L.R/ŒG it suffices to show that if T ¹0; 1º
154
4 The Pmax -extension
We may assume that M contains a real coding h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i by the remarks above. The following closure properties of Y can be expressed as first order statements in the structure hH.!1 /; X; 2i. (4.1) Suppose .p; f / 2 Y and q < p. Then .q; f / 2 Y . (4.2) Suppose .p; f / 2 Y and ˛ < dom.f /. Then .p; f j˛/ 2 Y . (4.3) Suppose .p; f / 2 Y and ˛ < !1 . Then there exists .q; g/ 2 Y such that q < p, f g and such that ˛ < dom.g/. (4.4) Suppose p 2 Pmax , ˛ < !1 , ˛ is a limit ordinal and f W ˛ ! ¹0; 1º: Then either .p; f / 2 Y or .p; f jˇ/ … Y for some ˇ < ˛. Since it follows that
hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i hH.!1 /M ; Y \ H.!1 /M ; 2i hH.!1 /; Y; 2i:
Further from this it follows that for all x 2M\R there exists h.N ; J /; bi 2 M \ Pmax such that x 2 N and N is countable in M. We can now apply Lemma 4.46 in M to obtain .g; f / 2 M such that the following hold in M. (5.1) f W !1 ! ¹0; 1º. (5.2) g Pmax and g is a semi-generic filter. (5.3) h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 g. (5.4) Ig D I \ P .!1 /g . (5.5) For all ˛ < !1 ,
.p; f jˇ/ 2 Y
for some p 2 g and for some ˇ > ˛. Let ag !1M be the set determined by g. Thus for all p 2 g, h.M; I /; ag i < p: Now suppose that G Pmax is L.R/-generic and that h.M; I /; ag i 2 G. There exists a unique iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.ag / D AG . Let F D j.f /. We claim that for all ˛ < !1 , F j˛ 2 :
4.2 The partial order Pmax
155
To see this fix ˇ < !1 . Choose h.N ; J /; bi 2 G such that h.N ; J /; bi < h.M; I /; ag i and such that ˇ < !1N . Hence there is a unique iteration k W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that k.ag / D b. This iteration is an initial segment of the iteration which defines j , k.f / F , and ˇ < dom.k.f //. .M; I / is X -iterable and so it follows that for all ˛ < !1M , .p; k.f /jˇ/ 2 Y for some p 2 k.g/ and for some ˇ > ˛. Finally for all p 2 k.g/, h.N ; J /; bi < p; and so k.g/ G. Therefore we have that for all ˛ < !1N , k.f /j˛ 2 . Thus k.f /jˇ 2 and so F jˇ 2 . This proves that !1 -DC holds in L.R/Pmax . In fact we have proved something stronger: Suppose that G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Suppose that T 2 L.R/ŒG, T is an !-closed subtree of ¹0; 1º
P .!1 / D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº since given B !1 with B 2 L.R/ŒG let T be the subtree of ¹0; 1º
4 The Pmax -extension
156 where
j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / and j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / are the unique iterations such that j0 .a0 / D AG and j1 .a1 / D AG . Finally we prove that IG is a saturated ideal in L.R/ŒG. For this we prove the following holds in L.R/ŒG. Suppose A P .!1 / n INS is dense. Then there exists A A such that A has cardinality !1 and such that 5A contains a club in !1 . We work in L.R/. Fix a term 2 L.R/Pmax and fix a condition p0 2 Pmax . We assume that 1 P .!1 / n INS and 1
is dense:
Let Y H.!1 / be the set of all pairs .h.M; I /; ai; b/ such that, (7.1) h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax , (7.2) b 2 M and b !1M , (7.3) h.M; I /; ai b 2 , where if G Pmax is L.R/-generic and h.M; I /; ai 2 G then b is the image of b under the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to AG . Observe that because IG is the nonstationary ideal it follows that if .h.M; I /; ai; b/ 2 Y then necessarily b … I . The following properties of Y are easily verified. (8.1) Suppose .h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i; b0 / 2 Y and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i. Then .h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i; b1 / 2 Y where b1 is the image of b0 under the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends a0 to a1 . (8.2) Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax , b0 2 M0 , b0 !1M0 and b0 … I0 . Then there exists .h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i; b1 / 2 Y such that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and such that b1 j.b0 / where j is the embedding given by the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends a0 to a1 .
4.2 The partial order Pmax
157
The second of properties, (8.2), follows from the fact that if G Pmax is L.R/generic then in L.R/ŒG
P .!1 / D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº which we have just proved. We introduce some additional notation. Suppose G Pmax is a semi-generic filter. Let AG be the set of subsets of !1 given by evaluating using G and Y , AG D ¹j.b/ j h.M; I /; ai 2 G and .h.M; I /; ai; b/ 2 Y º; where as above j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the embedding from the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to AG . Let X R be the set of reals which code elements of Y . Let h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 Pmax be a condition such that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < p0 and such that: (9.1) X \ M1 2 M1 ; (9.2) hH.!1 /M1 ; X \ M1 i hH.!1 /; X i; (9.3) .M1 ; I1 / is X -iterable. We shall obtain a condition in Pmax by modifying a1 in the condition h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i. Let Y M1 be the set of elements of Y coded by a real in X \ M1 . Thus Y M1 2 M1 and in M1 has the properties (8.1) and (8.2) stated above for Y . Therefore we may apply Lemma 4.48 within M1 to obtain a semi-generic filter G1 such that p0 2 G1 and such that I1 \ P .!1 /G1 D IG1 and such that
!1 n 5AG1 2 I1
where AG1 is the set of subsets of !1 given by evaluating using G1 and using Y \ H.!1 /M : Let
a10 D A
where A is AG as computed in M1 relative to the filter G1 . By absoluteness .Pmax /M1 D Pmax \ H.!1 /M1 : Further and so
a10 D [¹b j h.N ; J /; bi 2 G1 º h.M1 ; I1 /; a10 i < h.N ; J /; bi
for all h.N ; J /; bi 2 G1 . Note that since p0 2 G1 , h.M1 ; I1 /; a10 i < p0 :
158
4 The Pmax -extension
Now suppose that G Pmax is L.R/-generic and that h.M1 ; I1 /; a10 i 2 G. Let j W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / be the embedding from the iteration which sends a10 to AG . The key point is that since .M1 ; I1 / is X -iterable it follows that j.Y M1 / D Y \ M1 : Further suppose h.M; I /; ai < h.M1 ; I1 /; a10 i and let k W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / be the countable iteration of .M1 ; I1 / which sends a10 to a. By the properties of G1 in M1 it follows that h.M; I /; ai < p for all p 2 k.G1 /. From these facts it follows that j.AG1 / AG : However 5AG1 is of measure 1 in M1 relative to I1 . Therefore 5j.AG1 / is of measure 1 relative to IG and so it contains a club in !1 since IG is the nonstationary ideal in L.R/ŒG. Finally AG1 is of cardinality !1 in M1 and so j.AG1 / has cardinality !1 in L.R/ŒG. Thus j.AG1 / is the desired subset of AG . This proves that IG is a saturated ideal in L.R/ŒG and this completes the proof of the theorem. t u Combining Lemma 4.40 and Theorem 4.49 we obtain as an immediate corollary the following theorem. Theorem 4.50. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG !1 -DC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal saturated ideal; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal.
t u
We continue with our analysis of L.R/Pmax and prove that the conclusion of Corollary 3.48 holds in L.R/Pmax . This theorem can also be proved abstractly by using Corollary 3.48 together with the absoluteness theorem, Theorem 4.64. But a proof along these lines requires stronger hypotheses. Remark 4.51. (1) It is possible to prove that INS is saturated in L.R/Pmax using Lemma 4.52 instead of Lemma 4.48, see the proof of Theorem 10.54. (2) There are Pmax -variations, P 2 L.R/, for which INS is not saturated in L.R/P . However Lemma 4.52 will generalize to these models, yielding the semi-satut u ration of INS in these models, see Section 6.1.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
159
Lemma 4.52. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose that G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG, for every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. From the basic analysis of Pmax summarized in Theorem 4.49 it follows that H.!2 /L.R/ŒG D H.!2 /L.R/ ŒAG : We work in L.R/ŒG. Fix A R with A 2 L.R/. Fix a countable elementary substructure X hH.!2 /; A; G; 2i: Let hXi W i < !i be an increasing sequence of countable elementary substructures of X such that X D [¹Xk j k < !º and such that for each k 2 !, Xk 2 XkC1 . Therefore for each k < !, there exists h.M; I /; ai 2 G \ XkC1 satisfying (1.1) Xk \ P .!1 / M , (1.2) A \ M 2 M, (1.3) .M; I / is A-iterable, where M is the iterate of M given by the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to AG . Let MX be the transitive collapse of X . We claim that MX is A-iterable. Given this the lemma follows. For each k < ! let h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i 2 G \ XkC1 be a condition satisfying the requirements (1.1), (1.2) and (1.3). For each k < ! let k h.Mk˛ ; Ik˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i k be the iteration of .Mk ; Ik / such that j0;! .ak / D AG . Thus for each k < !, 1 k h.Mk˛ ; Ik˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1X i 2 MX
and further
MX D [¹Mk j k < !º;
where D X \ !1 . Suppose j W MX ! N is given by a countable iteration of MX . Let D j.!1MX /: For each k < ! let
.Nk ; Jk / D j..Mk ; Ik //
160
4 The Pmax -extension
where D !1MX D !1X . Therefore for each k < !, .Nk ; Jk / is an iterate of .Mk ; Ik / by an iteration of length which extends the iteration k h.Mk˛ ; Ik˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i:
For each k < ! this is the (unique) iteration of .Mk ; Ik / which sends ak to j.AG \ !1MX /. By induction on , N D [¹Nk j k < !º and so MX is iterable. The argument here is identical to proof that Pmax is !-closed, cf. Lemma 4.43. We finish by analyzing AQ D [¹j.B/ j B A and B 2 MX º: We must show that AQ D A \ N . Let D !1MX . Thus MX D [¹Mk j k < !º. For each k < !, .Mk ; Ik / is A-iterable. Therefore k A \ MX D [¹j0; .A \ Mk / j k < !º:
For each k < ! let AQk be the image of A \ Mk under the iteration of .Mk ; Ik / which sends ak to j.AG \ /. This is the iteration which defines Nk . Thus AQ D [¹AQk j k < !º since for all B 2 MX , B A if and only if B Mk \ A for some k < ! and since for all k < !, k Mk \ A D j0; .A \ Mk /:
The latter equality holds since .Mk ; Ik / is A-iterable. Finally, using the A-iterability of .Mk ; Ik / once more, it follows that for each k < !, AQk D A \ Nk ; and so AQ D A \ N . t u We obtain as a corollary the following theorem. Theorem 4.53. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG the following hold. (1) ı12 D !2 . (2) Suppose S !1 is stationary and f W S ! Ord: Then there exists g 2 L.R/ such that ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ D g.˛/º is stationary.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
161
Proof. (1) is an immediate corollary to Lemma 4.52 and Theorem 3.19. (1) also follows from (2). We prove (2). Let ‚ D ‚L.R/ and suppose f W S ! Ord where S is a stationary subset of !1 . By the chain condition satisfied by Pmax in L.R/, there exists a set X Ord such that X 2 L.R/, f ŒS X and such that jX j < ‚ in L.R/. Therefore we may suppose that f WS !
for some < ‚. (2) now follows from Lemma 4.52 and Theorem 3.42.
t u
We shall prove the following theorem in Section 5.1. Theorem 4.54. Assume ADL.R/ . Then L.R/Pmax ZFC:
t u
Definition 4.55. Suppose that A !1 . The set A is L.R/-generic for Pmax if there exists a filter G Pmax which is L.R/-generic and such that A D AG . t u The following lemma shows that the generic for Pmax can be identified with the subset of !1 it creates. Lemma 4.56. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose that A !1 is L.R/-generic for Pmax . Define in L.R/ŒA a subset F Pmax as follows. h.M; I /; ai 2 F if there exists an iteration
j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
such that (1) j.a/ D A, (2) I D INS \ M . Then F is a filter in Pmax , F is L.R/-generic and A D AF . Proof. Fix a filter G Pmax such that G is L.R/-generic and such that A D AG : Note that for each h.M; I /; ai 2 G, the corresponding iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
162
4 The Pmax -extension
such that j.a/ D A can be computed in L.A; .M; I // and so M 2 L.R/ŒA. Therefore by Theorem 4.50 it follows that P .!1 /L.R/ŒG L.R/ŒA: Thus the set F Pmax is the same computed in L.R/ŒA or L.R/ŒG. Thus it suffices to show that in L.R/ŒG, F D G: By Theorem 4.50, G F and so we need only show that F G, i. e. that the requirement specifying membership in F fails for conditions which do not belong to G. Suppose h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax and h.M; I /; ai … G. We prove that h.M; I /; ai … F : Let z 2 R code h.M; I /; ai. Therefore there is a condition h.N ; J /; bi 2 G such that z 2 N and such that h.M; I /; ai and h.N ; J /; bi are incompatible. First suppose there is no iteration of .M; I / which sends a to b. If there exists an iteration of .M; I / which sends a to A then it is easily verified that there must be an iteration of .M; I / which sends a to b. Therefore there is no iteration of .M; I / which sends a to A and so h.M; I /; ai … F : Therefore we may assume that there is an iteration k W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that k.a/ D b. The iteration k is unique and k 2 N . If I D M \ J then h.N ; J /; bi < h.M; I /; ai which contradicts the incompatibility of these conditions. Therefore I ¤ M \ J in particular there must exist B 2 P .!1N / \ M n I such that B 2 J . Let j W .N ; J / ! .N ; J / be the iteration such that j .b/ D A. Thus j .k/ W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to A. But j .B/ 2 M n I and j .B/ 2 j .J /. Therefore j .B/ is nonstationary in L.R/ŒG since j .J / IG and IG is the nonstationary ideal. Thus h.M; I /; ai … F ; and this proves F D G.
t u
4.2 The partial order Pmax
163
The proof of Lemma 4.59 requires the following technical lemma. Lemma 4.57 (ZFC ). Suppose D !1 and hyk W k < !i is a sequence of reals such that for all k < !, (1) yk# is recursive in ykC1 , (2) every subset of !1 which is constructible from yk and D contains or is disjoint from a tail of the indiscernibles of LŒykC1 below !1 . Then D is constructible from a real. Proof. For each k < ! let Ck be the set of indiscernibles of LŒyk below !1 . First we show that if f W !1 ! !1 is a function in LŒD; yk then there is a function h 2 LŒykC1 such that f D h on a tail of CkC1 . Fix f . For each ˛ < !1 , let ı˛ be the least element of CkC1 above ˛. Thus f .ˇ/ < ıˇ for all sufficiently large ˇ < !1 . This is because every club in !1 which is in LŒD; yk contains a tail of CkC1 . Fix ˇ0 < !1 such that f .˛/ < ı˛ for all ˛ > ˇ0 . For each ı 2 CkC1 if ˇ0 < ı then f .ı/ is definable in LŒykC1 from ı, finitely many elements of CkC1 below ı and finitely many of the !n ’s. Working in V we can find a stationary set S CkC1 , a finite set of ordinals t and a definable Skolem function, , of LŒykC1 such that if ı 2 S then f .ı/ D .ı; t /. Thus we have produced a function h W !1 ! !1 such that h 2 LŒykC1 and such that T D ¹˛ < !1 j f .˛/ D h.˛/º is stationary in !1 . Clearly T 2 LŒD; ykC1 and so T must contain a tail of CkC1 since it cannot be disjoint from a tail of CkC1 . Thus h is as desired. Let X H.!2 / be a countable elementary substructure containing D and ¹yk j k < !º. Let Z D X \ .[¹L!2 ŒD; yk j k < !º/: Define a †0 -elementary chain
hZ˛ W ˛ < !1 i
as follows by induction on ˛ < !1 . Set Z0 D Z and for ˛ a limit ordinal let Z˛ D [¹Zˇ j ˇ < ˛º: Define Z˛C1 D ¹f .Z˛ \ !1 / j f 2 Z˛ º: It is easily verified by induction on ˛ that for every k < !, Z˛ \ L!2 ŒD; yk L!2 ŒD; yk :
164
4 The Pmax -extension
We prove by induction on ˛ < !1 that Z˛ \ !1 is an initial segment of !1 . This is clearly preserved at limits and so we may assume this holds for Z˛ and we prove it for Z˛C1 . Note that since Z˛ \ !1 is an ordinal it follows that it is necessarily an indiscernible of L.yk / for each k < !1 . Let ı D Z˛ \ !1 . Suppose 2 Z˛C1 \ !1 . Then D f .ı/ for some function f W !1 ! !1 with f 2 Z˛ \ LŒD; yk for some k < !. Fix k. Therefore from the remarks above D h.ı/ for some function h W !1 ! !1 with h 2 LŒykC1 \Z˛ . Thus < ı where ı is the next indiscernible of LŒykC1 . But every ordinal less than ı can be generated from finitely many ordinals less ı together with ı and finitely many indiscernibles above !1 for LŒykC1 using definable Skolem functions of LŒykC1 . X contains infinitely many indiscernibles for LŒyi above !1 for every i < ! and so D g.ı/ for some g 2 Z˛ . Let Z D [¹Z˛ j ˛ < !1 º. Thus !1 Z . The key point is the following. For each ˛ < !1 let M˛ be the transitive collapse of Z˛ and let M be the transitive collapse of Z . For each ˛ < ˇ < !1 let j˛;ˇ W M˛ ! Mˇ be the †0 elementary embedding induced by the identity map taking Z˛ into Zˇ and let j W M0 ! M be the embedding induced by the identity map taking Z0 into Z . Let ZFC denote the axioms, ZFC n Powerset. It is useful to note that M˛ is not a model of ZFC , however it is an !-length increasing union of transitive models of ZFC . Let ˛ be the image of !1 under the collapsing map of Z˛ . Then in M˛ the club filter on ˛ is a measure and j W M0 ! M is simply the iteration of length !1 of M0 by the club measure on 0 . This follows easily from the fact that M˛C1 is the ultrapower of M˛ by the club measure on ˛ and j˛;˛C1 is the induced embedding. This fact we verify by induction on ˛. It suffices to prove that the critical point of j˛;˛C1 is ˛ ; i. e. that for every ˛ < !1 , Z˛ \ !1 is an initial segment of !1 and this we proved above. This iteration of M0 is a non-generic analog of the iteration of a sequence of structures as defined in Definition 4.15, cf. Remark 4.16. Note that D 2 M since !1 Z . Let t be a real which codes M0 . Thus D 2 LŒt . t u Lemma 4.57 has the following corollary. Corollary 4.58. Assume ZF C DC and that for all x 2 R; x # exists. The following are equivalent. (1) Every subset of !1 is constructible from a real. (2) The club filter on !1 is an ultrafilter and every club in !1 contains a club which is constructible from a real. t u
4.2 The partial order Pmax
165
For example assume the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated, there is a measurable cardinal and there is a transitive inner model of ZF C DC containing the reals, containing the ordinals, and in which the club filter on !1 is an ultrafilter. Then in L.R/ every subset of !1 is constructible from a real. Lemma 4.59. Assume that for every real x, x exists. Suppose h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax ; d
!1M
and d 2 M.
(i) Let D0 be the set of h.N ; J /; bi 2 Pmax such that a) h.N ; J /; bi < h.M; I /; ai, b) N “!1 D !1L.d
;x/
for some real x”.
(ii) Let D1 be the set of h.N ; J /; bi 2 Pmax such that a) h.N ; J /; bi < h.M; I /; ai, b) N “d is constructible from a real” . Then D0 [ D1 is open, dense in Pmax below h.M; I /; ai. Here d denotes the image of d under the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to b. Proof. Fix a condition p 2 Pmax with p < h.M; I /; ai. There are two cases. First suppose there is a sequence h.pk ; xk / W k < !i such that for all k < !; (1.1) pk 2 Pmax and pkC1 < pk < p, (1.2) xk 2 R \ Mk and xk# is recursive in xkC1 , (1.3) x0 codes p and h.M; I /; ai, M
(1.4) every subset of !1 kC1 which belongs to LŒdkC1 ; xk either contains or is disM joint from a tail of the indiscernibles of LŒxkC1 below !1 kC1 . where for each k < !, pk D h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i, dk D jk .d / and jk is the elementary embedding from the unique iteration of .M; I / such that jk .a/ D ak . Implicit in (1.4) M M is the fact that if A !1 k and if A 2 Mk then every subset of !1 k which is in LŒA # belongs to L˛ ŒA where ˛ D Mk \ Ord. This is because A 2 Mk which in turn follows from the iterability of .Mk ; Jk /. We use this frequently. Choose a condition h.N ; J /; bi 2 Pmax such that for all k < !, h.N ; J /; bi < h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i: For each k < ! let
jk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Jk /
166
4 The Pmax -extension
be the unique iteration such that jk .ak / D b. Let d D jk .dk /. This is unambiguously defined and we may apply Lemma 4.57 in N to obtain that there is a real t 2 N such that d 2 LŒt . The condition h.N ; J /; bi 2 D1 and h.N ; J /; bi < p. The second case is that no such sequence h.pk ; xk / W k < !i exists. Notice that if h.N1 ; J1 /; b1 i < h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i in Pmax and if
j W .N0 ; J0 / ! .N0 ; J0 /
is the unique iteration such that j.b0 / D b1 then for every D 2 J a tail of indiscernibles of LŒx below !1N1 is disjoint from D where x is any real in N1 which codes N0 . Therefore since the sequence h.pk ; xk / W k < !i does not exist it follows that there exist a condition h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i < p; a real x0 2 N0 , and a set D !1N0 , such that (2.1) D 2 LŒx0 ; d0 , (2.2) both D and !1N0 n D are positive relative to J0 , where d0 D j.d / and j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the unique iteration such that j.a/ D b0 . Fix a condition h.N1 ; J1 /; b1 i < h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i: By modifying b1 we shall produce a condition in D1 below h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i. We work in N1 . Fix a real t which codes .N0 ; J0 /. Let C be the set C D ¹ı < !1N1 j Lı Œt LŒt º: Therefore C is a club in !1N1 and C 2 LŒt . Let XC be the elements of C which are not limit points of C and let W !1N1 ! XC be the enumeration function of XC . Fix A !1N1 such that A 2 N1 and !1N1 D !1LŒA . Let A C be the image of A under . Working in N1 construct an iteration j0 W .N0 ; J0 / ! .N0 ; J0 / of length .!1 /N1 such that; (3.1) J0 = J1 \ N0 , (3.2) j0 .D/ \ XC D A .
4.2 The partial order Pmax
167
The iteration exists because the requirements given by (2.1) and (2.2) do not interfere. One achieves (2.1) by working on C n XC as in the proof of Lemma 4.36 and (2.2) is achieved by working on XC . Let b1 D j0 .b0 /, let d1 D j0 .d0 / and let D D j0 .D/. Thus h.N1 ; J1 /; b1 i < h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i and !1N1 D !1LŒt;D since A 2 LŒt; D . However D 2 LŒx; d0 and so D 2 LŒx; d1 . Therefore and so
h.N1 ; J1 /; b1 i
!1N1 D !1LŒx;t;d1 2 D0 .
t u
The next theorem reinforces the analogy between Pmax and Sacks forcing. Theorem 4.60. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose that G Pmax is a filter which is L.R/-generic. Suppose that A !1 and that A 2 L.R/ŒG n L.R/. Then A is L.R/-generic for Pmax and L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒA: Proof. This is immediate, the argument is similar to that for the homogeneity of Pmax together with the analysis provided by Theorem 4.49 and Lemma 4.59. Let G Pmax be L.R/-generic. Fix A !1 , A 2 L.R/ŒG n L.R/. By Theorem 4.49 there exists a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G such that for some d 2 M0 , j .d / D A where j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration which sends a to AG . By Lemma 4.59 we may assume that M0 “!1 D !1L.d;x/ for some real x”: Therefore there exists a real x 2 M0 such that !1 D !1LŒA;x : We first show that L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒA. Since M0 MA!1 it follows, by Lemma 4.35, that there exists a real y 2 M0 with AG 2 LŒA; y: Therefore L.R/ŒA D L.R/ŒAG D L.R/ŒG. To finish we must prove that A is L.R/-generic for Pmax . Let g Pmax be the filter generated by ¹h.N ; J /; A \ !1N i j h.N ; J /; bi 2 G and h.N ; J /; bi < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 iº: It follows that g is L.R/-generic and that A D [¹b j h.N ; J /; bi 2 gºI i. e. that A is the set “AG ” computed from g. t u Therefore A is L.R/-generic for Pmax .
4 The Pmax -extension
168
The next theorem is the key for actually verifying that specific …2 sentences hold in
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
:
Theorem 4.61. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i and that
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
.x/ is a …1 formula in the
9x .x/:
Then there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax and a set b0 !1M0 with b0 2 M0 such that for all h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 Pmax , if h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i; then
hH.!2 /M1 ; 2; I1 i
where b1 D j.b0 / and
Œb1
j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
is the iteration such that j.a0 / D a1 . Proof. Assume V D L.R/ and let G Pmax be generic. For each h.M; I /; ai 2 G let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the iteration such that j.a/ D AG . By Theorem 4.50, in L.R/ŒG
P .!1 / D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº and so
H.!2 /L.R/ŒG D [¹H.!2 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº: t u
The theorem now follows.
The next theorem is simply a reformulation. This theorem strongly suggests that if AD holds in L.R/ and if G Pmax is L.R/-generic then in L.R/ŒG one should be able to analyze all subsets of P .!1 / which are definable in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/ŒG by a …1 formula. Thus while a …2 sentence may fail in L.R/ŒG one can analyze completely the counterexamples.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
169
Theorem 4.62. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose .x/ is a …1 formula in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i: Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic and that hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/ŒG ŒA where A !1 and A 2 L.R/ŒG n L.R/. Let G Pmax be the L.R/-generic filter such that A D AG . Then there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 G such that for all h.M ; I /; a i 2 Pmax ; if h.M ; I /; a i h.M; I /; ai then hH.!2 /M ; 2; I i Œa : Proof. By Theorem 4.60, A is L.R/-generic for Pmax and so the generic filter G exists. As in the proof of Theorem 4.61, H.!2 /L.R/ŒG D [¹H.!2 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 G º; where for each h.M; I /; ai 2 G let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.a/ D AG D A. t u The next theorem we prove gives the key absoluteness property of L.R/Pmax . Using its proof one can greatly strengthen the previous theorems. To prove this we use the following corollary of Theorem 2.61. This theorem is discussed in Section 2.4. An alternate proof is possible using the stationary tower forcing and the associated generic elementary embedding. The choice is simply a matter of taste, working with Theorem 2.61 is more in the spirit of Pmax . In Chapter 6 we shall consider various generalizations of Pmax and for some of the variations we shall prove the corresponding absoluteness theorems which are analogous to the absoluteness theorems proved here for Pmax . There we will have to use the stationary tower forcing cf. Theorem 6.85. Theorem 4.63. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal. Let Q D Coll.!1 ; <ı/ P be an iteration defined in V such that P is ccc in V Coll.!1 ;<ı/ . Then the nonstationary ideal on !1 is precipitous in V Q . Proof. If the nonstationary ideal is precipitous in V then in any ccc forcing extension of V , the nonstationary ideal is precipitous. This is a relatively standard fact. Using this, the theorem follows from Theorem 2.61 t u Theorem 4.64. Assume ADL.R/ and that there is a Woodin cardinal with a measurable above. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i and that hH.!2 /; 2; INS i : Then Pmax : t u hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
170
4 The Pmax -extension
There is a stronger absoluteness theorem that is true and this is the version which we prove. Theorem 4.65. Assume ADL.R/ and that there is a Woodin cardinal with a measurable above. Suppose that J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 , is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; J i; and that hH.!2 /; 2; J i : Then
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
:
Proof. Let .x; y/ be a †0 formula such that D 8x9y: .x; y/ (up to logical equivalence). Assume towards a contradiction that Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
::
Then by Theorem 4.61, there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax and a set b0 2 H.!2 /M0 such that if h.M; I /; ai h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i then
hH.!2 /M ; 2; I i 8y Œb
where b D j.b0 / and j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration such that j.a0 / D a. By Lemma 4.36, there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that: (1.1) j.!1M0 / D !1 ; (1.2) J \ M0 D I0 . Let B D j.b0 /. The sentence holds in V and so there exists a set D 2 H.!2 / such that hH.!2 /; 2; J i : ŒB; D: Let ı be a Woodin cardinal and be a measurable cardinal above ı. Let g be a V -generic enumeration of J of length !1 . The poset is simply J
4.2 The partial order Pmax
171
Let C be a V Œg-generic club in !1 which is disjoint from S . Conditions for C are initial segments and so V is closed under ! sequences in V ŒgŒC . A key point is that V ŒgŒC J D INS \V V ŒgŒC where INS is the nonstationary ideal as computed in V ŒgŒC . This follows from the normality of the ideal J in V . V ŒgŒC is a small generic extension of V and so ı is a Woodin cardinal in V ŒgŒC and is measurable in V ŒgŒC . Let Q D Coll.!1 ; <ı/ P
be an iteration defined in V ŒgŒC such that P is ccc in V ŒgŒC Coll.!1 ;<ı/ , V ŒgŒC Q MA C :CH and such that Q has cardinality ı in V ŒgŒC . Let G Q be V ŒgŒC -generic. Thus by Theorem 4.63, the nonstationary ideal on !1 is precipitous in V ŒgŒC ŒG. Clearly V ŒgŒC ŒG \ V: J D INS Therefore hH.!2 /; 2; INS iV ŒgŒC ŒG : ŒB; D: Further is still measurable in V ŒgŒC ŒG. Let 2 V ŒgŒC ŒG be a measure on . Let X VC2 ŒgŒC ŒG be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹M0 ; j; g; C; G; B; D; º X and let Y D X \ V ŒgŒC ŒG. Let N0 be the transitive collapse of Y and let N1 be the transitive collapse of X . Let X be the image of and let X be the image of under the collapsing map. Thus N0 D VX \ N1 and the pair .N1 ; X / is iterable in the usual sense. Let N D [¹k.N0 / j k is an iteration of k0 º where the union ranges over iterations of arbitrary length and k0 is the embedding given by X . Thus N is a transitive inner model of ZFC containing the ordinals and NX D N0 : Let J0 be the ideal INS as computed in N0 . The ideal J0 is precipitous in N0 and hence it is precipitous in N . Therefore by Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.10, .N0 ; J0 / is iterable in V ŒgŒC ŒG. Let jX be the image of j under the collapsing map. Thus jX 2 N0 and jX W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
4 The Pmax -extension
172
is an iteration of .M0 ; I0 / of length .!1 /N0 and further I0 D J0 \ M0 . The latter holds since I0 D J \ M0 and since in V ŒgŒC ŒG, V ŒgŒC ŒG J D INS \ V:
Thus h.N0 ; J0 /; jX .a0 /i 2 Pmax and h.N0 ; J0 /; jX .a0 /i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i. Finally let BX be the image of B and let DX be the image of D under the collapsing map. Thus hH.!2 /; INS iN0 : ŒBX ; DX and so hH.!2 /; INS iN0 .:8y /ŒBX : However BX D jX .b/. Thus in V ŒgŒC ŒG there is a condition h.M; I /; ai h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i such that
hH.!2 /M1 ; I1 ; 2i 6 8y Œb
where b D j0 .b/ and j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration such that j0 .a0 / D a1 . By absoluteness, noting that V is †13 -correct in the generic extension, V ŒgŒC ŒG, such a condition h.M; I /; ai must exist in V , which is a contradiction. t u Definition 4.66. Suppose X 2 H.!1 /. Let Z be the transitive closure of X . Then Q3 .X / is the set of all Y Z such that the following hold. (1) There exists a transitive inner model M of ZFC such that: a) Ord M; b) X 2 M; c) for some ı < !1 ; X 2 Vı , ı 2 M and ı is a Woodin cardinal in M; d) Y 2 M. (2) Suppose that M is a transitive inner model of ZFC such that: a) Ord M; b) X 2 M; c) for some ı < !1 ; X 2 Vı , ı 2 M and ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. Then Y 2 M.
t u
The operation Q3 .X / has its origins in descriptive set theory. The exact definition is given, and the basic theory is developed in work of Kechris, Martin and Solovay .Kechris, Martin, and Solovay 1983/. The context for the work is 12 -Determinacy. Q3 .!/ is the set of all subsets of ! which are recursive in some real which is a …12 singleton in a countable ordinal .Kechris, Martin, and Solovay 1983/.
4.2 The partial order Pmax
173
We can now provide better versions of the theorems about counterexamples to a …2 statement in L.R/Pmax . Roughly the analysis yields the following. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic and that A !1 has a …1 property in hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/ŒG I i. e. A is a counterexample to a …2 statement. Then there are !1 many stationary subsets of !1 associated to A such that in a very strong sense any attempt to add a witness to make the …1 property of A fail, must destroy the stationarity of one of these sets. We shall again consider this in Chapter 5. See, for example, Theorem 5.67. Theorem 4.67. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose .x/ is a …1 formula in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i: Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic and that hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/ŒG ŒA where A !1 , A 2 L.R/ŒG n L.R/. Let G Pmax be the L.R/-generic filter such that A D AG . Then there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 G such that the following holds. Suppose j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is a countable iteration and let a D j.a/. Let N be any countable, transitive, model of ZFC such that:
(1) .P .!1 //M N ;
(2) !1N D !1M ; (3) Q3 .S / N , for each S 2 N such that S !1N ; (4) If S !1N , S 2 M and if S … I then S is a stationary set in N . Then
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iN Œa :
Proof. Fix a †0 formula, .x; y/ such that .x/ D 8y .x/. By Theorem 4.60, A is L.R/-generic for Pmax and so the filter G exists. By Theorem 4.62, there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G such that for all h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i, hH.!2 /M1 ; 2; I1 i 8y Œa1 : Let h.M; I /; ai < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i be any condition in G . We claim that the condition h.M; I /; ai satisfies the requirements of the theorem. To verify this let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be a countable iteration and let N be a countable, transitive, model of ZFC such that:
4 The Pmax -extension
174
(1.1) M 2 N ;
(1.2) !1N D !1M ; (1.3) Q3 .S / N , for each S 2 N such that S !1N ; (1.4) If S !1N , S 2 M and if S … I then S is a stationary set in N . Let
j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
be the iteration such that j0 .a/ D a . Since h.M; I /; ai < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i, it follows that I0 D I \ M0 D .INS /N \ M0 : We must show that
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iN 8y Œa
where a D j.a/. Assume toward a contradiction that for some b 2 H.!2 /N , hH.!2 /; 2; INS iN : Œa ; b: Choose a transitive set Y †1 N such that (2.1) Y 2 N , (2.2) jY j D !1N in N , (2.3) ¹h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i; a ; bº Y , (2.4) !1N Y , (2.5) hH.!2 /; 2; INS iY : Œa ; b. The structure .M0 ; I0 / is an iterate of .M0 ; I0 / and the iteration is uniquely determined by a . Therefore M0 2 Y . Let Z !1N be such that Z 2 N and Y 2 LŒZ. Let N1 be a transitive inner model of ZFC such that N1 contains the ordinals, Z 2 N1 , Q3 .Z/ D P .!1N / \ N1 ; and such that there exists ı < !1 such that ı is a Woodin cardinal in N1 . We may suppose that N1 D LŒS for some S ı. Y N D INS \ Y and so it follows that Note that INS hH.!2 /; 2; INS iN1 : Œa ; b and that
N1 I0 D INS \ M0 :
4.2 The partial order Pmax
Let
175
P0 D Coll.!1 ; <ı/N1
and let Q D P0 P be an iteration defined in N1 such that P is ccc in N1P0 , N1Q MA C :CH and such that Q has cardinality ı in N1 . Let g Q be N1 -generic with g 2 V . Therefore hH.!2 /; 2; INS iN1 Œg : Œa ; b: N1 Œg and let < !1 be strongly inaccessible in N1 Œg. Since Let I D INS N1 D LŒS for some S ı, it follows that !1 is a limit of indiscernibles of N1 Œg, and so exists. Let M D V \ N1 Œg: By Theorem 4.63, the ideal I is precipitous in N1 Œg and N1 Œg contains the ordinals. Therefore by Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.10, .M ; I / is iterable. Thus h.M ; I /; a i 2 Pmax and hH.!2 /; 2; INS iM :8y Œa : However M0 2 M and I0 D I \ M . Therefore h.M ; I /; a i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and this is a contradiction. t u In the case that the counterexample is actually in L.R/; i. e. is constructible from a real, then a much stronger statement can be made. Theorem 4.68. Suppose that there exists a Woodin cardinal with a measurable cardinal above. Suppose that .x/ is a …1 formula in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i: Suppose that A !1 , x 2 R, and that A 2 LŒx. Suppose that M is a countable transitive model, M ZFC C “There is a Woodin cardinal with a measurable above”; x 2 M and that M †1 V: 3
Then hH.!2 /; 2; INS i ŒA if and only if where AM D A \ !1M .
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iM ŒAM t u
176
4 The Pmax -extension
As a corollary to Theorem 4.67 one obtains the following technical strengthening of Theorem 4.64. Generalizations of this theorem are the subject of Section 10.3. Theorem 4.69. Assume ADL.R/ and that for each partial order P , 1 VP 2 -Determinacy: Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure
hH.!2 /; 2; INS i and that for some partial order P , hH.!2 /; 2; INS iV
P
Then
:
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
:
Proof. The theorem follows by a simple absoluteness argument, noting that from the hypothesis that for every partial order P , 1 VP 2 -Determinacy; it follows that for every partial order P ,
V †1 V P I 4 1 i. e. that †4 statements with parameters from V are absolute between V and V P . It suffices to prove that if is a †2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i and if
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
;
then for each partial order P , hH.!2 /; 2; INS iV
P
:
Fix D 9 .x/ where .x/ is a …1 formula. Thus by Theorem 4.67 there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that the following holds. (1.1) Suppose
j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
is a countable iteration and let a D j.a/. Let N be any countable, transitive, model of ZFC such that:
a) .P .!1 //M N ;
b) !1N D !1M ; c) Q3 .S / N , for each S 2 N such that S !1N ; d) If S !1N , S 2 M and if S … I then S is a stationary set in N .
4.2 The partial order Pmax
Then
177
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iN Œa :
Now assume toward a contradiction that P is a partial order such that hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iV
P
::
Then by the iteration lemmas, (1.1) must fail in V P . But this is a contradiction since (1.1) is expressible as a …14 statement about t where t 2 R codes the condition h.M; I /; ai. t u A stronger form of the absoluteness theorem is actually true. This arises from expanding the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i by adding predicates for each set of reals in L.R/. The expanded structure hH.!2 /; 2 ; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri is a natural one to consider in the presence of suitable large cardinals. In this case each set X R with X 2 L.R/ has a canonical interpretation in any generic extension of V just as borel sets have canonical interpretations. We shall need the following corollary to the results in Section 2.2. Lemma 4.70. Suppose X R and let Y R be the set of reals which code elements of the first order diagram of the structure hH.!1 /; 2; X i: Suppose S and T are trees on ! such that (1) S and T are weakly homogeneous, (2) X D pŒS and Y D pŒT . Suppose P 2 V and G P is V -generic. Let XG D pŒS and let YG D pŒT , each computed in V ŒG. Then in V ŒG, hH.!1 /V ; 2; X i hH.!1 /V ŒG ; 2; XG i: Theorem 4.71. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose language for the structure hH.!2 /; X; 2; INS i
.x/ is a …1 formula in the
where X R is a set in L.R/. Suppose that Pmax
hH.!2 /; X; 2; INS iL.R/
9x .x/:
Then there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax and a set b 2 H.!2 /M such that if h.M ; I /; a i h.M; I /; ai and if .M ; I / is X -iterable then
hH.!2 /M ; X \ M ; 2; I i
t u
Œb
where b D j.b/ and j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.a/ D a .
4 The Pmax -extension
178
t u
Proof. The proof is identical to the proof of Theorem 4.61. We now prove the strong form of the absoluteness theorem. Theorem 4.72. Assume ı is a Woodin cardinal and that every set X 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ C
is ı weakly homogeneously Suslin. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri and that hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
:
Proof. We sketch the argument which is really just a minor modification of the proof of Theorem 4.65. Let .x; y/ be a †0 formula such that D 8x9y: .x; y/ (up to logical equivalence). Clearly we may assume that contains only 1 unary predicate from those additional predicates for the sets of reals we have added to the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i: Let X be the corresponding set of reals. Assume toward a contradiction that Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X iL.R/
::
Then by Theorem 4.71, there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax and a set b 2 H.!2 /M such that: (1.1) For all
h.M ; I /; a i h.M; I /; ai;
if .M ; I / is X -iterable then
hH.!2 /M ; 2; I ; X \ M i 8y Œb where b D j.b/ and j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.a/ D a . By Theorem 4.41, we may assume by refining h.M; I /; ai if necessary, that .M; I / is X -iterable and that X \ M 2 M. By Lemma 4.36, there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that:
4.2 The partial order Pmax
179
(2.1) j.!1M / D !1 ; (2.2) J \ M D I ; (2.3) X \ M D j.X \ M/. Let B D j.b/ and let A D j.a/. The sentence holds in V and so there exists a set D 2 H.!2 / such that hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X i : ŒB; D: Let ı be the least Woodin cardinal and let T be a ı C -weakly homogeneous tree such that X D pŒT . Let Q D Coll.!1 ; <ı/ P be an iteration defined in V such that P is ccc in V Coll.!1 ;<ı/ , V Q MA C :CH; and such that Q has cardinality ı in V . Let G Q be V -generic. By Theorem 4.63, the nonstationary ideal on !1 is precipitous in V ŒG. Since .INS /V D .INS /V ŒG \ V and since
is a †0 formula, it follows that hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; XG iV ŒG : ŒB; D;
where XG D pŒT V ŒG . Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal above ı. For trivial reasons (there are sets which are not †11 and which are ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin) exists C and further X is -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Let IG be the nonstationary ideal on !1 (computed in V ŒG). Let g Coll.!; / be V ŒG generic. Thus by Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.10, .V ŒG; IG / is iterable in V ŒGŒg. Let X.G;g/ D pŒT V ŒGŒg . It follows that .V ŒG; IG / is X.G;g/ -iterable in V ŒGŒg. Therefore in V ŒGŒg, hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; XG iV ŒG : ŒB; D; and so in V ŒGŒg; (3.1) h.V ŒG; IG /; Ai 2 Pmax , (3.2) h.V ŒG; IG /; Ai < h.M; I /; ai, (3.3) h.V ŒG; IG /; Ai is X.G;g/ iterable, (3.4) hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; XG iV ŒG :8y Œj.b/, where j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.a/ D A.
4 The Pmax -extension
180
Finally, in V , every set which is projective in X is C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Therefore by Lemma 4.70, hH.!1 /V ; 2; X i hH.!1 /V ŒGŒg ; 2; X.G;g/ i for sentences with parameters from H.!1 /V . This contradicts (1.1); i. e. the choice of h.M; I /; ai in V . t u We obtain as a corollary the following theorem. Theorem 4.73. Assume that there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri and that hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
:
Proof. Let ı be the least ordinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Let be a measurable cardinal above ı. By the results of .Koellner and Woodin 2010/ if X R and X 2 L.R/ then X is < ı weakly homogeneously Suslin. Therefore the theorem now follows from Theorem 4.72. t u The strengthened absoluteness theorem has in some sense a converse. We first prove a technical lemma which, while not strictly necessary for the proof of Theorem 4.76, does simplify things a little. Lemma 4.74. Assume that for some countable elementary substructure, X0 H.!2 /; MX0 is iterable where MX0 is the transitive collapse of X0 . Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax and that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 Pmax are conditions such that there exist iterations j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / and
j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 /
satisfying (i) j0 .a0 / D j1 .a1 /, (ii) I0 D M0 \ INS , (iii) I1 D M1 \ INS . Then h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i are compatible in Pmax .
4.2 The partial order Pmax
181
Proof. Suppose X H.!2 / is a countable elementary substructure such that ¹h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i; h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i; j0 ; j1 º X: Let MX be the transitive collapse of X . Let .j0X ; j1X / be the image of .j0 ; j1 / and let IX be the image of INS \ X under the collapsing map. By Theorem 3.16, .MX ; IX / is iterable. By Theorem 3.22, for every x 2 R, x exists. Therefore by Lemma 4.38 there exists h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that MX 2 H.!1 /M : By Lemma 4.36, there exists in M an iteration j W .MX ; IX / ! .MX ; IX / such that IX D I \ MX . Let b D j.j0X .a0 //. The iteration j.j0X / witnesses that h.M; I /; bi < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i; and the iteration
j.j1X /
witnesses that h.M; I /; bi < h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i:
t u
Remark 4.75. Lemma 4.74 can be proved under a variety of assumptions. For example it follows from the assumption that there is a Woodin cardinal with a measurable cardinal above. t u Theorem 4.76. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose that for each …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri if
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
then hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG for some G Pmax which is L.R/-generic. Proof. It suffices to show that for all A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/, A is L.R/-generic for Pmax . From this it follows by Theorem 4.60 that L.P .!1 // is a Pmax generic extension of L.R/. Suppose A !1 and A … L.R/. Let FA Pmax be the set of all conditions h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.a/ D A and INS \ M D I .
4 The Pmax -extension
182
We prove that the conditions in FA are pairwise compatible. The statement that for every A !1 , the conditions in FA are pairwise compatible is expressible by a …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; X; 2i where X is the set of reals z such that z codes a pair .p; q/ of elements of Pmax which are incompatible. By Lemma 4.52 and Lemma 4.74 this sentence holds in L.R/Pmax . Therefore it holds in V and so for each A !1 , the conditions in FA are pairwise compatible. If A is L.R/-generic for Pmax then FA D GA where GA is the generic filter given by A. Fix D Pmax such that D is dense and D 2 L.R/. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/generic. Then by Theorem 4.60 the following sentence holds in L.R/ŒG: “For all A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/, FA \ D ¤ ;.” This is expressible by a …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; DiL.R/ŒG and so by the hypothesis of the theorem it holds in V . Therefore for all A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/, the filter FA is L.R/-generic. From this it follows that for each A !1 , if A … L.R/ then L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒA: Hence L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG for some G Pmax which is L.R/-generic.
t u
Remark 4.77. We shall show in Chapter 10 that it is essential for Theorem 4.76 that INS be a predicate of the structure even if one assumes in addition Martin’s Maximum for partial orders of cardinality c, cf. Theorem 10.70. We shall also show that “cofinally” many sets in P .R/ \ L.R/ must also be added, (Theorem 10.90). t u If one assumes in addition that R# exists then Theorem 4.76 can be reformulated so as to refer only to a structure of countable signature; i. e. the structure of a countable language. For each n 2 ! let Un be a set which †1 definable in the structure hL.R/; hi W i < ni; 2i where hi W i < ni is an increasing sequence of Silver indiscernibles of L.R/, and such that Un is universal. Clearly the definition of the set Un depends only on the choice of the universal formula (and not on the choice of hi W i < ni).
4.2 The partial order Pmax
183
Theorem 4.78. Assume ADL.R/ and that R# exists. Suppose that for each …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; Un I n < !i if
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; Un I n < !iL.R/
then hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; Un I n < !i : Then L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG for some G Pmax which is L.R/-generic.
t u
In the Theorem 4.78, the sequence, hUn W n < !i; can be replaced by any sequence, hUn W n < !i, of sets in L.R/ \ P .R/, provided that the sequence is cofinal; i. e. provided that for each set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/, there exists n < ! such that A is a continuous preimage of Un . We end this chapter by stating the following theorem. This theme we shall take up again in Chapter 10. Theorem 4.79. Suppose that there exists a model, hM; Ei, such that hM; Ei ZFC and such that for each …2 sentence if there exists a partial order P such that hH.!2 /; 2iV then
P
;
hH.!2 /; 2ihM;E i :
Assume there is an inaccessible cardinal. Then: (1) For all partial orders P , 1 VP … 1 -Determinacy:
(2) V †12 -Determinacy.
t u
Remark 4.80. (1) It follows from Theorem 4.67 that Theorem 4.79(2) cannot be 1 significantly improved; i. e. † 2 -Determinacy can fail in V . (2) Suppose that for each …2 sentence if there exists a partial order P such that hH.!2 /; 2iV
P
;
then hH.!2 /; 2i : Assume there is an inaccessible cardinal. Must ADL.R/ hold?
t u
Chapter 5
Applications
We give some applications of the axiom: Definition 5.1. Axiom ./: AD holds in L.R/ and L.P .!1 // is a Pmax -generic extension of L.R/. t u We begin by proving that ./ implies that L.P .!1 // AC: We actually give two proofs, the first involves a sentence AC which is the subject of Section 5.1. The second proof works through a variant of AC , this is the sentence AC which is discussed in Section 5.3. In fact the latter approach is much simpler, however the sentence AC introduces concepts which we shall use in Chapter 10. Martin’s Maximum implies both AC and AC and so Martin’s Maximum also implies that L.P .!1 // AC: The main work of the chapter is in Section 5.7 where we give a reformulation of ./ which does not involve the definition of Pmax or the notion of iterable structures.
5.1
The sentence AC
We now prove Theorem 4.54; i. e. that L.R/Pmax ZFC: As we have noted, a second (simpler) proof is given in Section 5.3. First we fix some notation. Definition 5.2. Suppose S !1 . Then SQ is the set of all ˛ < !2 such that !1 ˛ and such that if R is a wellordering of !1 of length ˛ then ¹ j ordertype.Rj / 2 S º contains a club in !1 . u t Thus SQ is the set of ˛ < !2 such that !1 ˛ and 1 B ˛ 2 j.S / where B D RO.P .!1 / n INS / and j W V ! .M; E/ V B is the corresponding generic elementary embedding. Note that !2V is always contained in the wellfounded part of the generic ultrapower .M; E/.
5.1 The sentence AC
185
Definition 5.3. AC : (1) There is an !1 sequence of distinct reals. (2) Suppose hSi W i < !i and hTi W i < !i are sequences of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 . Suppose the Si are stationary and suppose that !1 D [¹Ti j i < !º: Then there exists < !2 and a continuous increasing function F W !1 ! with cofinal range such that F ŒTi SQi t u
for each i < !.
Clearly AC is …2 in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i. The next lemma is immediate. The idea for using subsets of !2 to define a wellordering of the reals in this fashion originates in .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/. They use sets S ¹˛ < !2 j cof.˛/ D !º which are stationary in !2 . The additional ingredient here is using subsets of !1 to generate these sets. This yields a wellordering which is simpler to define. Lemma 5.4 (ZF + DC). Assume AC holds in hH.!2 /; 2i: Suppose hSi W i < !i is a partition of !1 into ! many stationary sets. Then there is a wellordering of the reals which is 1 definable in hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i from hSi W i < !i. Proof. Let hSi W i < !i be a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary sets. An immediate consequence of AC is that for every set x ! with x ¤ ; there exists an ordinal < !2 such that cof. / D !1 and such that x D ¹i j SQi \ is stationary in º: Let x be the least such ordinal. The wellordering of P .!/ n ¹;º is given by x < y if x < y . This wellordering is 1 definable in hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i from hSi W i < !i.
t u
Lemma 5.5. Suppose that for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that
186
5 Applications
(i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG AC : Proof. We work in L.R/ŒG. Necessarily, P .!1 / L.R/ŒG: Suppose hSi W i < !i and hTi W i < !i are sequences of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 . Suppose the Si are stationary and suppose that !1 D [¹Ti j i < !º. Let h.M; I /; ai 2 G be such that hSi W i < !i; hTi W i < !i 2 M where j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.a/ D AG . Let hsi W i < !i; hti W i < !i in M be such that j..hsi W i < !i; hti W i < !i// D .hSi W i < !i; hTi W i < !i/: Thus in M, hsi W i < !i and hti W i < !i are sequences of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1M , the si are not in I , and !1M D [¹ti j i < !º: Let D be the set of conditions h.N ; J /; bi < h.M; I /; ai such that in N there exist < !2N and a continuous increasing function F W !1N ! with cofinal range such that F .tiN / sQiN for each i < ! where tiN D k.ti /, siN D k.si / and k is the embedding of the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to b. For each i < !, sQiN denotes the set AQ as computed in N where A D siN . It suffices to show that D is dense below h.M; I /; ai. We show something slightly stronger. Suppose h.N ; J /; bi < h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i < h.M; I /; ai: Then for some c 2 N , h.N ; J /; ci 2 D and h.N ; J /; ci < h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i < h.M; I /; ai: si0
Let be the image of si under the iteration of .M; I / which sends a to b0 and let ti0 be the image of ti under this iteration. Let x 2 N be a real which codes N0 . Working in N we define an iteration of .N0 ; J0 / of length !1N . Let C be the set of indiscernibles of LŒx less than !1N . Let D C be the set of 2 C such that C \ has ordertype . Thus D is a closed unbounded subset of C . Let h.N˛ ; J˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1N i be an iteration of .N0 ; J0 / in N such that
5.2 Martin’s Maximum and AC
187
(1.1) for all ˛ 2 D and for all < ˛, j0;ˇ .si0 / 2 Gˇ if 2 j0;˛ .ti0 / where ˇ is the th element of C above ˛, (1.2) J! N D J \ N! N . 1
1
The iteration is easily constructed in N , the point is that the requirements given by (1.1) and (1.2) do not interfere. The other useful observation is that if ˛ 2 C and if k W .N0 ; J0 / ! .N0 ; J0 / is any iteration of length ˛ then ˛ D k.!1N0 /. Let be the .!1N C !1N /th indiscernible of LŒx. Let F be the function F W !1N ! given by F .ˇ/ is the th indiscernible of LŒx where D !1N C ˇ. Thus (2.1) 2 N , (2.2) < !2N , (2.3) F 2 N , (2.4) F W !1N ! is continuous and strictly increasing. Let siN D j0;! N .si0 / and let tiN D j0;! N .ti0 /. Let 1
1
c D j0;! N .b0 /: 1
Thus h.N ; J /; ci 2 Pmax and h.N ; J /; ci < h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i. By the definition of the iteration it follows that in N , F ŒtiN sQiN and so h.N ; J /; ci 2 D.
t u
Lemma 5.5 yields, immediately, two corollaries, noting that by Lemma 4.40, the hypothesis of Lemma 5.5 is a consequence of ADL.R/ . Corollary 5.6. Assume ADL.R/ . Then L.R/Pmax ZFC.
t u
Corollary 5.7. Assume ./ holds. Then AC holds in hH.!2 /; 2i.
t u
5.2
Martin’s Maximum and AC
We sketch a proof of the following lemma which we shall use to prove that Martin’s Maximum implies AC . Lemma 5.8. Assume Martin’s Maximum. Suppose that S !1 is stationary. Then ¹˛ j ˛ 2 SQ and cof .˛/ D !º is stationary in !2 .
188
5 Applications
Proof. Assume Martin’s Maximum. Let S0 !1 and S1 !1 be stationary sets. Let P be Namba forcing. Conditions are pairs .s; t / such that (1.1) t !2
5.2 Martin’s Maximum and AC
189
(4.1) ˛0 < ˛1 . (4.2) Suppose 2 Œt2 and let X D ¹f .jk/ j k < !º: Then a) X \ !1 D ˛0 , b) ordertype.X / D ˛1 . To see this suppose that g P is V -generic with .s2 ; t2 / 2 G. Then in V Œg, g 2 Œt2 . Let Xg D ¹f .g jk/ j k < !º: Thus Xg 2 Cg . By absoluteness it follows from (4.2(a)) and (4.2(b)) that Xg \ !1 D ˛0 and that ordertype.Xg / D ˛1 . Therefore Xg 2 Zg ŒS0 ; S1 and so Cg \ Zg ŒS0 ; S1 ¤ ;: To find .˛0 ; ˛1 / and .s2 ; t2 / we associate to each pair .0 ; 1 / 2 S0 S1 with 0 < 1 a game, G .0 ; 1 /, as follows: Player I plays to construct a sequence h.i ; ˇiI / W i < !i of pairs such that .i ; ˇiI / 2 !2 1 . Player II plays to construct a sequence h.bi ; ni ; ˇiII / W i < !i of triples .bi ; ni ; ˇiII / 2 t1 ! 1 . Let hˇi W i < !i be the sequence such that for all i < !, ˇ2iC1 D ˇiI and ˇ2i D ˇiII . The requirements are as follows: For each i < j < !, (5.1) bi biC1 and dom.bi / D i , (5.2) if s1 bi then biC1 D bi _ ı for some ı > i , (5.3) f .b2iC1 / < !1 if and only if ˇi < 0 , (5.4) ni is odd and
f .bi / D f .bni /;
(5.5) f .b2iC1 / f .b2j C1 / if and only if ˇi ˇj . The first player to violate the requirements loses otherwise Player II wins. Thus the game is determined. The key property of the game is the following. Suppose that h.i ; ˇiI / W i < !i and h.bi ; ni ; ˇiII / W i < !i define an infinite run of the game which satisfies (5.1)–(5.5) (and so represents a win for Player II). Let hˇi W i < !i be the sequence such that for all i < !, ˇ2i D ˇiI and ˇ2iC1 D ˇiII . Suppose that 1 D ¹ˇi j i < !º:
190
5 Applications
Let X D ¹f .bi / j i < !º. Then X \ !1 D 0 and ordertype.X / D 1 : We claim that there must exist .˛0 ; ˛1 / 2 S0 S1 such that ˛0 < ˛1 and such that Player II has a winning strategy in the game G .˛0 ; ˛1 /. The proof requires only that INS is presaturated. Let G0 .P .!1 / n INS ; / be V -generic with S0 2 G and let j0 W V ! M0 V ŒG0 be the associated generic elementary embedding. Let G1 .P .!1 / n INS ; /M0 be M0 -generic with j0 .S1 / 2 G1 and let j1 W M0 ! M1 M0 ŒG1 be the generic elementary embedding given by G1 . Thus j1 ı j0 .!2 / D sup¹j1 ı j0 .˛/ j ˛ < !2 º: Further, since !2V D j0 .!1V /, .!1V ; !2V / 2 j1 ı j0 .S0 / j1 ı j0 .S1 /: It follows by absoluteness, using the property (3.2) of f , that in M1 , Player II has a winning strategy in the game G .!1V ; !2V /. Therefore in V there must exist a pair .˛0 ; ˛1 / 2 S0 S1 such that ˛0 < ˛1 and such that Player II has a winning strategy in the game G .˛0 ; ˛1 /. Fix such a pair .˛0 ; ˛1 / and let hˇi W i < !i enumerate ˛1 . Let † be a winning strategy for Player II in the game G .˛0 ; ˛1 /. It is straightforward to construct a condition .s2 ; t2 / .s1 ; t1 / such that if 2 Œt2 is a cofinal branch of t2 then there exists a sequences hi W i < !i and h.bi ; ni / W i < !i such that (6.1) for all i < !, i < !2 , (6.2) h.bi ; ni / W i < !i is the response of † to Player I playing h.i ; ˇi / W i < !i, (6.3) D [¹bi j i < !º.
5.2 Martin’s Maximum and AC
191
Since ˛1 D ¹ˇi j i < !º it follows that if is a cofinal branch of t2 then ¹f .ji / j i < !º \ !1 D ˛0 and that ordertype.¹f .ji / j i < !º/ D ˛1 : Thus .s2 ; t2 / is as required. This proves the claim that if G P is V -generic then in V ŒG, the set ZG ŒS0 ; S1 is stationary in P!1 .!2V /. For each set A !1 and for each ordinal ˛ > !1 let QŒA; ˛ be the partial order defined as follows. Condition are partial functions p W ˛
192
5 Applications
such that: (9.1) D sup¹.i / j i < !º. (9.2) ¹.i / j i < !º . (9.3) C \ is cofinal in . (9.4) Suppose X 2 P!1 . / and that F ŒX
t u
From Lemma 5.8 and the results of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ we obtain the following corollary. Theorem 5.9. Assume Martin’s Maximum. Then H.!2 / AC : Proof. The relevant result of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ is the following. Assume Martin’s Maximum. Suppose hTi W i < !i are pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 and that !1 D [¹Ti j i < !º. Suppose hSi W i < !i are pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !2 such that for all i < !, Si C! where C! D ¹˛ < !2 j cof ˛ D !º: Then there exists an ordinal < !2 and a continuous (strictly) increasing function F W !1 ! with cofinal range such that F ŒTi Si for each i < !. This together with the previous lemma yields that Martin’s Maximum implies AC . t u Thus: Theorem 5.10. Assume Martin’s Maximum. Then L.P .!1 // ZFC:
5.3
The sentence
AC
We prove that ./ implies a variant of AC . This sentence implies L.P .!1 // AC, and in addition it implies 2@0 D 2@1 D @2 .
t u
5.3 The sentence
AC
193
Further this sentence can be used in place of MA!1 in defining Pmax , an alternate approach which will be useful in defining some of the Pmax variations, cf. Definition 6.91. We will also consider, in Section 7.2, versions of this sentence relativized to a normal ideal on !1 . Definition 5.11. AC : Suppose S !1 and T !1 are stationary, co-stationary, sets. Then there exist ˛ < !2 , a bijection W !1 ! ˛; and a closed unbounded set C !1 such that ¹ < !1 j ordertype.Œ/ 2 T º \ C D S \ C:
t u
Thus AC asserts that for each pair .S; T / of stationary, co-stationary, subsets of !1 , there exists an ordinal ˛ < !2 such that ŒS INS D ŒŒ˛ 2 j.T / in V B where B D RO.P .!1 /=INS / and
j W V ! .M; E/ V B
is the corresponding generic elementary embedding. This implies (in ZF) that the boolean algebra P .!1 /=INS can be wellordered (in length at most !2 ). Lemma 5.12 (ZF + DC). Assume
AC
holds in
hH.!2 /; 2i: Suppose hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a partition of !1 into !1 many stationary sets. Then there is a surjection W !2 ! P .!1 / which is 1 definable in
hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i
from hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i. Proof. For each set A !1 let SA D [¹S˛C1 j ˛ 2 Aº and let SA D S0 if A D ;. The key point is that if A !1 , B !1 , and if A ¤ B then SA M SB … INS : Define W !2 ! P .!1 /
194
5 Applications
by .˛/ D A if there is a surjection W !1 ! ˛ and a closed set C !1 such that ¹ < !1 j ordertype.Œ/ 2 S0 º \ C D SA \ C: If no such set A exists then .˛/ D ;. Since AC holds, is a surjection. It is easily verified that is is 1 definable in hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i from hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i.
t u
The proof that Martin’s Maximum implies AC is actually much simpler then the proof we have given that Martin’s Maximum implies AC . The reason is that our approach to proving AC from Martin’s Maximum was through Lemma 5.8 which established quite a bit more than is necessary. Here we take a more direct approach which only requires a special case of the reflection principle, SRP, an observation due independently to P. Larson. The special case is SRP for subsets of P!1 .!2 /, which can be proved from just Martin’s Maximum.c/. This special case is discussed in Section 9.3. Theorem 5.13. Assume Martin’s Maximum.c/. Then H.!2 /
AC :
Proof. Fix stationary sets S0 !1 and T0 !1 . Let Z D ¹X 2 P!1 .!2 / j X \ !1 2 S0 if and only if ordertype.X / 2 T0 º: It suffices to prove that for each stationary set S !1 , the set ZS D ¹X 2 Z j X \ !1 2 S º is stationary in P!1 .!2 /. Let S !1 be stationary. The claim that ZS is stationary in P!1 .!2 / follows by an absoluteness argument using the fact that INS is !2 -saturated. Fix a function H W !2
5.3 The sentence
AC
195
Let X D j0;2 Œ!2V ; the image of !2V under j0;2 . Thus (2.1) ordertype.X / < j0;2 .!1V /, (2.2) j0;2 .H /ŒX
AC
holds for .S0 ; T0 /.
t u
Larson has also noted that the proof of Theorem 5.13 easily adapts to show that Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies AC . We note that Lemma 5.8 cannot be proved from just Martin’s Maximum.c/. Therefore, for the proof that we have given that Martin’s Maximum implies AC , Martin’s Maximum.c/ does not suffice. Finally Larson has proved versions of Lemma 5.8 showing for example that Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies that for each stationary set S !1 , SQ is stationary in !2 and that SQ \ ¹˛ < !2 j cof.˛/ D !º ¤ ;: The sentence, boolean algebra
AC ,
implies that for each stationary, co-stationary, set T !1 , the P .!1 /=INS
is (trivially) generated by the term for j.T /. This fact combined with Theorem 3.51 yields the following lemma as an immediate corollary. Lemma 5.14. Suppose that
AC
holds. Then 2@0 D 2@1 D @2 :
Proof. By Theorem 3.51, 2@0 D 2@1 . By Lemma 5.12, 2@1 @2 .
t u
The next lemma shows that AC serves successfully in place of MA!1 in the definition of Pmax . This lemma is really just a special case of the claim given at the beginning of the proof of Theorem 3.51.
196
5 Applications
Lemma 5.15. Suppose M is a countable transitive set such that M ZFC C Suppose a 2 M,
AC :
a !1M ;
and M “a is a stationary, co-stationary, set in !1 ”: Suppose j1 W M ! M1 and j2 W M ! M2 are semi-iterations of M such that M1 is transitive, M2 is transitive and such that j1 .a/ D j2 .a/: Then M1 D M2 and j1 D j2 . Proof. Fix a and suppose that hMˇ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ j ˛ < ˇ i is a semi-iteration of M such that Mˇ is transitive for all ˇ . We prove that G0 , M1 and j0;1 W M ! M1 are uniquely specified by j0; .a/ \ !2M . We note that since G0 is an M-normal ultrafilter, G0 D ¹b !1M j b 2 M and !1M 2 j0;1 .b/º: Therefore since M
AC
it follows that G0 is completely determined by j0;1 .a/ \ !2M : To see this fix b 2 M such that b !1M . We may suppose that b … .INS /M and that
!1M n b … .INS /M :
Therefore there exist ˛ < !2M , a bijection W !1M ! ˛ and c !1M such that (1.1) 2 M, c 2 M, (1.2) c is closed and cofinal in !1M , (1.3) ¹ < !1M j ordertype.Œ/ 2 aº \ c D b \ c.
5.3 The sentence
AC
197
But this implies that b 2 G0 $ ˛ 2 j0;1 .a/ since ˛ is the ordertype of j0;1 ./Œ!1M . Thus G0 is determined by j0;1 .a/ \ !2M and so M1 and j0;1 are uniquely specified by j0;1 .a/ \ !2M . Finally j0; D j1; ı j0;1 and !2M !1M1 . Therefore j0;1 .a/ \ !2M D j0; .a/ \ !2M and so G0 , M1 and j0;1 are uniquely specified by j0; .a/ \ !2M . By induction on it follows in a similar fashion that for all < , hMˇ ; j˛;ˇ j ˛ < ˇ C 1i and hG˛ j ˛ i M
are uniquely specified by j0; .a/ \ !2 . The lemma follows noting that since j1 .a/ D j2 .a/ it follows that
j1 .!1M /
D
j2 .!1M /.
t u
The proof that ./ implies AC is simplified by first proving the following technical lemma which isolates the combinatorial essence of the implication. Lemma 5.16 (ZFC ). Suppose that x 2 R codes h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax and that x # exists. Let C be the set of of the Silver indiscernibles of LŒx below !1 and let C 0 be the limit points of C . Suppose that ¹s; t º .P .!1 //M n I is such that both !1M0 n s … I and !1M0 n t … I . Suppose J is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 . Then there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / of length !1 such that and such that for all 2 C 0 , if and only if
I D J \ M 2 j.s/ C 2 j.t /
where C is the least element of C above .
198
5 Applications
Proof. We modify the proof of Lemma 4.36 using the notation from that proof. The modification is a minor one. Choose the sequence hAk;˛ W k < !; ˛ < !1 i of J positive, pairwise disjoint, sets such that [¹Ak;˛ j k < ! and ˛ < !1 º C 0 : Following the proof of Lemma 4.36 construct the iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i of .M; I / to satisfy the additional requirement that for all 2 C 0 , 2 j0;C1 .s/ if and only if j0;ˇ .t / 2 Gˇ C
where ˇ D . For each 2 C if h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i is any iteration of length then j0; .!1M / D and so this additional requirement does not interfere with the original requirements indicated in the proof of Lemma 4.36. Thus j0;!1 W .M; I / ! .M!1 ; I!1 / t u
is as desired. Lemma 5.17. Assume ./ holds. Then
AC
holds.
Proof. Fix a filter G Pmax such that G is L.R/-generic. Necessarily, P .!1 / L.R/ŒG: Fix subsets S and T of !1 such that each are both stationary and co-stationary. Therefore there exist h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G; s 2 M0 and t 2 M0 such that j.s/ D S and j.t / D T where j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the (unique) iteration such that j.a0 / D AG . Thus ¹s; t; !1M0 n s; !1M0 n t º \ I0 D ;: Let x0 code M0 , let C be the set of Silver indiscernibles of LŒx0 below !1 and let C 0 be the set of limit points of C . By Lemma 5.16, since G is generic, we may suppose, by modifying the choice of h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i if necessary, that for all 2 C 0 , 2 j.s/
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
199
if and only if
C 2 j.t / where for each 2 C , C denotes the least element of C above . Thus for all 2 C 0 , 2S if and only if C 2 T: Let ˛ be the least Silver indiscernible of LŒx0 above !1 and let W !1 ! ˛ be a bijection. Thus there exists a club D C 0 such that for all 2 D, ordertype.Œ / D C : Therefore ¹ < !1 j ordertype.Œ / 2 T º \ D D S \ D: This proves the lemma.
5.4
t u
The stationary tower and Pmax
We sketch a different presentation of Pmax . This leads to different proofs of the absoluteness theorems. This approach will be useful in proving absoluteness theorems for some of the variations of Pmax that we shall define, cf. Theorem 6.85. Another feature of this approach is that it much easier to show that suitable conditions exist. This is because the generic iterations are based on elementary embeddings associated to the stationary tower and not to an ideal on !1 . Thus no forcing arguments are required to produce conditions. Recall from Section 2.3 the following conventions. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal. Then Q<ı is the partial order given by the stationary tower restricted to Vı and restricted to sets of countable sets. We let I<ı denote the associated directed system of ideals. This is defined as follows. For each ˇ < ı, let Iˇ D ¹a P!1 .Vˇ / j a is not stationary in P!1 .Vˇ /º: If ˛ < ˇ there is a natural map ˛;ˇ W I˛ ! Iˇ given by ˛;ˇ .c/ D ¹ 2 P!1 .Vˇ / j \ V˛ 2 cº: I<ı is the directed system of ideals, hI˛ ; ˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < ıi. A set a 2 Vı is I<ı -positive if a P!1 .[a/ and a is stationary. Thus I<ı can be naturally identified with the set of a 2 Vı such that a P!1 .[ a/ and such that a is not stationary. Q<ı is the set of a 2 Vı such that a is I<ı -positive. We generalize the notions of iterability to the current context.
200
5 Applications
Definition 5.18. Suppose M is a countable model of ZFC and I 2 M is the directed system I<ı as computed in M for some ı 2 M which is a Woodin cardinal in M . (1) A sequence h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of .M; I/ if the following hold. a) M0 D M and I0 D I. b) ¹j˛;ˇ W M˛ ! Mˇ j ˛ < ˇ < º is a commuting family of elementary embeddings. c) For each C 1 < , G is M -generic for .Q<ı /M , M C1 is the M ultrapower of M by G and j ; C1 W M ! M C1 is the induced elementary embedding. Here ı D j0; .ı/ and so .Q<ı /M D j0; .QM <ı /: d) For each ˇ < if ˇ is a nonzero limit ordinal then Mˇ is the direct limit of ¹M˛ j ˛ < ˇº and for all ˛ < ˇ, j˛;ˇ is the induced elementary embedding. (2) If is a limit ordinal then is the length of the iteration, otherwise the length of the iteration is ı where ı C 1 D . (3) A pair .N; J / is an iterate of .M; I/ if it occurs in an iteration of .M; I/. (4) The structure .M; I/ is iterable if every iterate of M is wellfounded. Suppose A R. An iterable structure, .M; I/, is A-iterable if A \ M 2 M and if for all iterations j W .M; I/ ! .N; J /; j.A \ M / D A \ N .
t u
The next lemma, while not strictly necessary for what follows, does simplify some of the definitions. The lemma justifies the identification of an iteration of .M; I/ with the resulting elementary embedding. Lemma 5.19. Suppose M is a countable model of ZFC and I 2 M is the directed system I<ı as computed in M for some ı 2 M which is a Woodin cardinal in M . Suppose h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of .M; I/ of length . Then for each < the sequence h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is uniquely determined by the elementary embedding, j0; W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M ; I /:
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
201
Proof. For each ˇ < < , Gˇ D ¹a 2 Mˇ \ V j jˇ; Œ[a 2 jˇ; .a/º where D j0;ˇ .ı/. This is easily verified by induction on , fixing ˇ.
t u
We extend Definition 5.18 to sequences of models. Definition 5.20. Suppose h.Mk ; Ik ; ık / W k < !i is a countable sequence such that for each k, Mk is a countable transitive model of ZFC. Suppose ık 2 Mk and for all k: (i) ık is a Woodin cardinal in Mk , ık < ıkC1 , Ik 2 Mk and Ik D .I<ık /Mk I Mk
(ii) Mk 2 MkC1 and !1
MkC1
D !1
;
(iii) .Q<ık /Mk D Mk \ Vık \ .Q<ıkC1 /MkC1 . An iteration of h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is a sequence hh.Mkˇ ; Ikˇ / W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i such that ¹j˛;ˇ W [¹Mk˛ j k < !º ! [¹Mkˇ j k < !º j ˛ < ˇ < º is a commuting family of †0 elementary embeddings and such that the following hold for all ˛ < ˇ < . (1) For each k < !, G˛ \ j0;˛ ..Q<ık /Mk / is Mk˛ -generic for j0;˛ ..Q<ık /Mk /. (2) For each k < !, Mk˛C1 is the [¹Mk˛ j k < !º-ultrapower of Mk˛ by G˛ and j˛;˛C1 jMk˛ W Mk˛ ! Mk˛C1 is the induced elementary embedding. The ultrapower of Mk˛ is computed using all functions, f 2 [¹Mi˛ j i < !º, such that f W a ! Mk˛ for some a 2 G˛ . (3) If ˇ is a limit ordinal then for every k < !, Mkˇ is the direct limit of ¹Mk˛ j ˛ < ˇº and for all ˛ < ˇ, j˛;ˇ is the induced †0 elementary embedding.
202
5 Applications
If is a limit ordinal then is the length of the iteration, otherwise the length of the iteration is ı where ı C 1 D . A sequence h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is an iterate of h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i if it occurs in an iteration of h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i. The sequence h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is iterable if every iterate is wellfounded. t u The next two lemmas are the generalizations of Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.10 to iterations based on the stationary tower. We omit the proofs which are straightforward modifications of the previous arguments. Lemma 5.21. Suppose M and M are countable transitive models of ZFC such that M 2 M : . Let I D .I<ı /M Suppose ı 2 M , ı is a Woodin cardinal in M , and MıC1 D MıC1 and suppose h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i
is an iteration of .M; I/. Then there corresponds uniquely an iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i
of .M ; I/ such that for all ˇ < : (1) jˇ .ı/ D jˇ .ı/; (2) jˇ .Mı / D jˇ .Mı /; (3) Gˇ D Gˇ . Further for all ˇ < there is an elementary embedding kˇ W Mˇ ! j0;ˇ .M / such that j0;ˇ jM D kˇ ı j0;ˇ .
t u
Lemma 5.22. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC, ı 2 M and ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . Let I D .I<ı /M and suppose h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i is an iteration of .M; I/ of length where M \ Ord. Then Mˇ is wellfounded for all ˇ < . t u The main lemma for the existence of iterable structures .M; I/ is the routine generalization of Theorem 4.41. We state the lemma in a slightly stronger form, producing M such that if M Œg is a generic extension of M by a partial order in Mı then .M Œg; Ig / is suitably iterable, where ı 2 M is the Woodin cardinal associated to I and Ig D .I<ı /M Œg is the tower of ideals corresponding to .Q<ı /M Œg .
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
203
Lemma 5.23. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal and that is the least strongly inaccessible cardinal above ı. Suppose X V is a countable elementary substructure. Let .M; I/ be the transitive collapse of .X; I<ı \ X / and let ıX be the image of ı under the collapsing map. Suppose that A 2 P .R/ \ X and that every set of reals which is projective in A is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Suppose that P 2 MıX is a partial order and that g P is an M -generic filter with g 2 V . Let Ig D .I<ıX /M Œg : Then: (1) hV!C1 \ M Œg; A \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i; (2) .M Œg; Ig / is A-iterable. Proof. Fix X V such that X is countable. Clearly ı 2 X since ı is definable in V . Let .M; I; ıX / be the image of .V ; I<ı ; ı/ under the collapsing map. Suppose A 2 X , A R and for all B R such that B is projective in A, B is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Let ƒ D ¹B R j B is projective in Aº: Since is the least strongly inaccessible above ı, every set in ƒ is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Therefore if G0 is M -generic for a partial order P0 2 M , with G0 2 V , then A \ M ŒG0 2 M ŒG0 and hH.!1 /M ŒG0 ; A \ M ŒG0 ; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i: This follows by Lemma 2.29. Fix a partial order P 2 MıX and suppose that gP is an M -generic filter with g 2 V . Let Ig D .I<ıX /M Œg : Thus hH.!1 /M Œg ; A \ M Œg; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i; and so (1) holds. Suppose 2 X , ı < and
V ZFC:
204
5 Applications
Let X be the image of under the collapsing map. Let S and T be trees on ! 2 such that if G Coll.!; / then .pŒS /V ŒG D AV ŒG and .pŒT /V ŒG D .R n A/V ŒG : Since 2 X we may suppose that ¹S; T º X: Let .SX ; TX / be the image of .S; T / under the collapsing map. Suppose G Coll.!; X / is M Œg-generic with G 2 V . Therefore by the remarks above, A \ M ŒgŒG 2 M ŒgŒG and hH.!1 /M ŒgŒG ; A \ M ŒgŒG; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i: Suppose
j W .M X Œg; Ig / ! ..M X /Œg ; Ig /
is a countable iteration with j 2 M ŒgŒG. Then by Lemma 5.21, j lifts to define a countable iteration k W .M Œg; Ig / ! .M Œg ; Ig / where kjM˛ Œg 2 M ŒgŒG for all ˛ 2 M \ Ord. By Lemma 5.22, M Œg is wellfounded. Noting A \ M ŒgŒG D pŒSX \ M ŒgŒG we have and so Similarly
k.A \ M Œg/ D k.pŒSX \ M Œg/ D pŒk.SX / \ M Œg pŒSX \ M Œg k.A \ M Œg/: pŒTX \ M Œg k.M Œg \ .R n A//:
However pŒTX \ M ŒgŒG D .R n pŒSX / \ M ŒgŒG and so
k.A \ M Œg/ D pŒSX \ M Œg D pŒSX \ .M X Œg/
since R \ .M X Œg/ D R \ M Œg . Thus in M ŒgŒG, the structure .M X Œg; Ig / is A \ M ŒgŒG-iterable. Finally .M X Œg; Ig /
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
205
is countable in M ŒgŒG and hH.!1 /M ŒgŒG ; A \ M ŒgŒG; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i: Therefore .M X Œg; Ig / is A-iterable in V . The set of 2 M Œg such that M Œg ZFC is cofinal in M Œg and so .M Œg; Ig / is A-iterable.
t u
Remark 5.24. Lemma 5.23 can be proved with weaker requirements on the set A. The approximate converse of this strengthened version of Lemma 5.23 is proved as Lemma 6.59, in Section 6.2.2 where we consider the Pmax -variation, Qmax . t u Definition 5.25. Suppose .M; I/ is a countable iterable structure where I is the directed system of nonstationary ideals, I<ı , for some ı 2 M such that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. Suppose h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i is an iteration of .M; I/ of length !1 . The iteration is full if for all ˛ < !1 and for all a 2 M˛ such that a is I˛ -positive, the set ¹ˇ < !1 j j˛;ˇ .a/ 2 Gˇ º t u
is stationary in !1 . The next lemma accounts in part for the restriction to iterations which are full.
Lemma 5.26. Suppose .M; I/ is a countable iterable structure where I is the directed system of nonstationary ideals, I<ı , for some ı 2 M such that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. Suppose h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i is an iteration of .M; I/ of length !1 . (1) Suppose D 2 M!1 ,
D j0;!1 .QM <ı /;
and that D is dense. Suppose A is stationary in P!1 .M!1 /. Then there exists B A such that B is stationary in A and such that B b for some b 2 D. (2) Suppose that the iteration is full. Then for each ˛ < !1 and for each a 2 M˛ such that a is I˛ -positive, j˛;!1 .a/ is stationary set in V . Proof. The proofs of (1) and (2) are similar. We first prove (1). Fix A and D. Since D 2 M!1 there exists ˛ < !1 and D˛ 2 M˛ such that D D j˛;!1 .D˛ /:
Let A be the set of X 2 P!1 .H.!2 // such that
206
5 Applications
(1.1) X H.!2 /, (1.2) X \ M!1 2 A, (1.3) M˛ 2 X , (1.4) h.M˛ ; I˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i 2 X . Thus A is stationary. Suppose X 2 A . Let ˇ D X \!1 . Gˇ is Mˇ -generic and so Gˇ \j˛;ˇ .D˛ / ¤ ;. Therefore there exist ˛X < ˇ and bX 2 M˛X such that j˛X ;ˇ .bX / 2 Gˇ \ j˛;ˇ .D˛ /: Clearly ˛X 2 X and bX 2 X . A is stationary and so there exist ˛0 and b0 2 M˛0 such that B D ¹X 2 A j ˛X D ˛0 and bX D b0 º is stationary in P!1 .H.!2 //. Let b D j˛0 ;!1 .b0 /. Thus b 2 D. For each X 2 B let bX D j˛0 ;ˇ .b0 / where ˇ D X \ !1 . Thus for each X 2 B, bX 2 Gˇ \ j˛;ˇ .D˛ / where again ˇ D X \ !1 . We claim that B b. To prove this it suffices to show that for each X 2 B, X \ .[b/ 2 b: Fix X 2 B. Let ˇ D X \ !1 and let D ¹jˇ;ˇ C1 .t / j t 2 [bX º: By the properties of the generic elementary embedding associated to the stationary tower and since bX 2 Gˇ , 2 jˇ;ˇ C1 .bX /: Further is countable in Mˇ C1 since jˇ;ˇ C1 .bX / 2 j0;ˇ C1 .QM <ı /: Therefore jˇ C1;!1 . / D ¹jˇ C1;!1 .t / j t 2 º and so ¹jˇ;!1 .t / j t 2 [bX º 2 jˇ;!1 .bX /: However X \ .[b/ D ¹jˇ;!1 .t / j t 2 [bX º since b D j˛0 ;!1 .b0 / D jˇ;!1 .j˛0 ;ˇ .b0 // D jˇ;!1 .bX /:
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
207
Therefore X \ [b 2 b: Thus B b and this proves (1). We now prove (2). Fix ˛0 < !1 and a 2 G˛0 . Let S D ¹ˇ < !1 j j˛0 ;ˇ .a/ 2 Gˇ º: Since the iteration is full, S is a stationary subset of !1 . It suffices to prove that for each function F W H.!2 /
t u
(T) Definition 5.27. We define Pmax by induction on M \ Ord where M is the countable (T) consists of pairs h.M; I/; X i such that transitive model specified in the condition. Pmax the following hold.
(1) M is a countable transitive model of ZFC. (2) I 2 M and I D I<ı as computed in M for some ı 2 M such that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. (3) .M; I/ is iterable. (4) X 2 M and X is a set, possibly empty, of pairs .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 / such that the following conditions hold: a) M0 is countable in M; (T) b) h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i 2 Pmax ;
208
5 Applications
c) j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is an iteration which is full in M; d) j0 .X0 / X ; e) if .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j1 / 2 X then j0 D j1 . (T) The order on Pmax is implicit in its definition. (T) Suppose h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i and h.M2 ; I2 /; X2 i are conditions in Pmax . Then
h.M2 ; I2 /; X2 i < h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i if there exists an iteration j W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / such that .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; j / 2 X2 .
t u
(T) The precise relationship between Pmax and Pmax is given in Theorem 5.39. (T) The analysis of Pmax requires a non-interference lemma.
Lemma 5.28. Suppose (T) h.M; I/; X i 2 Pmax
and that
j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I /
is an iteration of .M; I/ of length !1 . Then M … M . Proof. We argue by contradiction. Let .M0 ; I0 / be a counterexample to the lemma. Let j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be an iteration of length !1 with M0 2 M0 . Therefore M0 is countable in M0 . Let k0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be an iteration such that M0 2 M0 , M0 is countable in M0 and such that M0 \Ord is as small as possible. The key point is that M0 is iterable and therefore it is †12 -correct. Therefore since M0 2 M0 and since M0 countable in M0 it follows that there must exist an iteration k1 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .N ; J / such that M0 2 N , M0 is countable in N and such that k1 2 M0 . This contradicts t u the minimality of M0 \ Ord. A stronger version of Lemma 5.28 is actually true. One can drop the assumption that the iteration is of length !1 ; i. e. one need not require (with notation as in the statement of Lemma 5.28) that M be countable in M . However the weaker version is all that we shall use.
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
209
Lemma 5.28 is really quite general. We state the version for iterable structures .M; I / where I 2 M is an ideal on !1M . This we have already discussed in a different context, see Remark 3.61. This lemma is required for the analysis of any variation of Pmax in which one has dropped all the requirements on the models designed to recover iterations from only the iterates. The proof of Lemma 5.29 is identical to the proof of Lemma 5.28. Lemma 5.29. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC and that .M; I / is iterable. Suppose j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is an iteration of .M; I / of length !1 . Then M … M .
t u
We shall also require a boundedness lemma for iterable structures of the form .M; I/ where I D .I<ı /M and where ı is a Woodin cardinal of M. This lemma is the obvious generalization of Lemma 3.15, and the proof is essentially the same. Lemma 5.30. Suppose M is a countable model of ZFC and I 2 M is the directed system I<ı as computed in M for some ı 2 M which is a Woodin cardinal in M. Suppose that x 2 R codes M. (1) Suppose that
j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I /
is an iteration of length . Then rank.M / < where is the least ordinal such that < and such that L Œx is admissible.
(2) Suppose that
j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I /
is an iteration of length !1 . Let D D ¹ < !1 j L Œx is admissibleº: Then for each closed set C !1 such that C 2 M , D n C is countable.
t u
The boundedness lemma, Lemma 5.30, yields as an immediate corollary the following lemma. (T) (T) Lemma 5.31. Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i 2 Pmax , h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i 2 Pmax , and h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i: Let j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
be the .unique/ iteration such that .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j / 2 X1 : Let x 2 R \ M1 code M0 . Then
210
5 Applications
(1) rank.M0 / < .ı12 /M1 , (2) if C 2 M0 is closed and unbounded in !1M1 then there exists D 2 LŒx such t u that D C and such that D is closed and unbounded in !1M1 . (T) are trivial with the possible The iteration lemmas required for the analysis of Pmax exception of the lemma required for showing (assuming ADL.R/ ) that the partial order (T) (T) is !-closed. This lemma is also required for the proof that the Pmax -extension is Pmax a model of !1 -DC.
Lemma 5.32. Suppose hh.Mi ; Ii /; Xi i W i < !i (T) such that for all i < !, is a sequence of conditions in Pmax
h.MiC1 ; IiC1 /; XiC1 i < h.Mi ; Ii /; Xi i: Let
h.Mi ; Ii / W i < !i
be the sequence such that for each i < !, .Mi ; Ii / is the iterate of .Mi ; Ii / obtained by combining the iterations given by the h.Mj ; Ij /; Xj i for j > i . Then: (1) For each i < !, , a) Mi 2 MiC1
b) .!1 /Mi D .!1 /Mi C1 ,
c) jMi jMi C1 D .!1 /M0 , M0
d) if C 2 Mk is closed and unbounded in !1 D2
then there exists
MkC1
such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and such that D 2 LŒx . for some x 2 R \ MkC1
(2) For each i < ! let Qi be the partial order of Ii -positive sets computed in Mi . For each a 2 [¹Qi j i < !º there exists a sequence hgi W i < !i such that a) a 2 [¹gi j i < !º, b) for each i < !, gi giC1 and gi is Mi -generic. (3) The sequence is iterable.
h.Mi ; Ii / W i < !i
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
211
Proof. For each i < j < ! let kij W .Mi ; Ii / ! .Mij ; Iij / be the iteration of .Mi ; Ii / in Xj . This iteration is the unique iteration k such that .h.Mi ; Ii /; Xi i; k/ 2 Xj : Mj
The iteration has length .!1 / . Suppose i < j1 < j2 . Then since h.Mj2 ; Ij2 /; Xj2 i < h.Mj1 ; Ij1 /; Xj1 i < h.Mi ; Ii /; Xi i it follows that the iteration corresponding to kij1 is an initial segment of the iteration corresponding to kij2 . Let ki be the embedding given by the induced iteration of .Mi ; Ii / of length Mj
M
sup¹kij .!1 i / j i < j < !º D sup¹!1 Thus
j i < j < !º:
ki W .Mi ; Ii / ! .Mi ; Ii /:
Suppose i < j < !. Then (T) h.Mj ; Ij /; Xj i 2 Pmax
and
.h.Mi ; Ii /; Xi i; ki / 2 Xj
where Xj D kj .Xj /. Thus h.Mj ; Ij /; Xj i < h.Mi ; Ii /; Xi i: (1) follows from Lemma 5.31 and the definitions. For each i < j < ! the iteration ki W .Mi ; Ii / ! .Mi ; Ii / is full in Mj . (2) follows from this and Lemma 5.26. (3) follows from (1) by Lemma 4.17. The relevant point is that by (1) and by Lemma 4.17 the sequence hMi W i < !i is iterable in the sense of Definition 4.15. Any iteration of h.Mi ; Ii / W i < !i defines in a unique fashion an iteration of hMi W i < !i and so is iterable.
h.Mi ; Ii / W i < !i t u
212
5 Applications
Remark 5.33. Lemma 5.32 has the following consequence which is really the key to (T) (cf. Theorem 5.39). establishing the relationship between Pmax and Pmax Suppose h.Mi ; Ii / W i < !i is as specified in Lemma 5.32. By Lemma 5.32 (1) and by Lemma 4.17, the sequence hMi W i < !i is iterable in the sense of Definition 4.15. This was noted in the proof of Lemma 5.32 and the observation is the basis for the reformulation of Pmax given in Section 5.5. By Lemma 5.32(2), for each i < !,
.INS /Mi C1 \ Mi D .INS /Mi : Further it follows that iterations of hMi W i < !i correspond to iterations of and conversely, iterations of correspond to iterations of
h.Mi ; Ii / W i < !i h.Mi ; Ii / W i < !i hMi W i < !i:
t u
(T) can be carried in a fashion analogous to Using Lemma 5.32, the analysis of Pmax (T) that for Pmax provided Pmax is sufficiently nontrivial. The proof of Lemma 5.37 requires Theorem 5.34 and Theorem 5.35; these are proved in .Koellner and Woodin 2010/.
Theorem 5.34 (ZF + AD). Suppose Z Ord. For each x 2 R let HODLŒZ;x ¹Zº denote HOD as computed in LŒZ; x with Z as a parameter. Then there exists x0 2 R such that for all x 2 R, if x0 2 LŒZ; x then .!2 /LŒZ;x is a Woodin cardinal in HODLŒZ;x . ¹Zº
t u
Theorem 5.35 (ZF + DC + AD). Assume V D L.R/. Suppose a !1 is a countable set. Then HOD¹aº D HODŒa: t u From Theorem 5.34 and Theorem 5.35 we obtain the following theorem which is quite useful in transferring theorems about weakly homogeneously Suslin sets to theorems about all sets of reals in L.R/ assuming ADL.R/ .
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
213
Theorem 5.36. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose A R and A 2 L.R/. Then for each n 2 ! there exist a countable transitive model M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that the following hold. (1) M ZFC. (2) ı is the nth Woodin cardinal of M . (3) A \ M 2 M and hV!C1 \ M; A \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i: (4) A \ M is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M . Proof. We work in L.R/. Suppose the theorem fails. Then there exists A 2 L.R/ which is a counterexample and such that A is 21 in L.R/. Let B R code the first order diagram of hV!C1 ; A; 2i: is 21
Thus B definable in L.R/. Therefore by the Martin–Steel theorem, Theorem 2.3, there exist (definable) trees S and T in L.R/ such that B D pŒS and R n B D pŒT : Therefore if N L.R/ is any transitive inner model of ZF such that ¹S; T º N then A \ N 2 N , B \ N 2 N and hV!C1 \ N; A \ N; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i: We claim that by Theorem 5.34, there exists a transitive inner model N L.R/ and an increasing sequence hıi W i n C 1i of countable ordinals such that (1.1) ¹S; T º N , (1.2) N ZFC, (1.3) for each i n C 1, ıi is a Woodin cardinal in N . We indicate how to find N in the case that n D 0, in this case there are to be two Woodin cardinals in N . We work in L.R/. Since S; T are definable, ¹S; T º HOD. Let Z0 Ord be such that HOD D LŒZ0 . Choose x0 such that .!2 /LŒZ0 ;x0 is a Woodin cardinal in
0 ;x0 : HODLŒZ ¹Z0 º
214
5 Applications
Let ı0 D .!2 /LŒZ0 ;x0 : Choose a ı0 such that and such that
0 ;x0 a 2 HODLŒZ ¹Z0 º 0 ;x0 \ Vı 0 : LŒa \ Vı0 D HODLŒZ ¹Z0 º
Let y0 2 R be such that for all y 2 R if y0 2 LŒZ0 ; aŒy then
0 ;aŒy0 0 ;aŒy D P .ı0 / \ HODLŒZ : P .ı0 / \ HODLŒZ ¹a;Z0 º ¹a;Z0 º
By Turing determinacy y0 exists and it follows that LŒZ0 ;aŒy0 P .ı0 / \ HOD¹a;Z HOD¹aº : 0º
Therefore by Theorem 5.35, 0 ;aŒy0 P .ı0 / \ HODLŒZ HODŒa ¹a;Z0 º
and so ı0 is a Woodin cardinal in LŒZ0 ;aŒy0 : HOD¹a;Z 0º
By Theorem 5.34, we may assume by increasing the Turing degree of y0 if necessary that .!2 /LŒZ0 ;a;y0 is a Woodin cardinal in
0 ;a;y0 : HODLŒZ ¹Z0 ;aº
Let ı1 D .!2 /LŒZ0 ;a;y0 and let
0 ;a;y0 : N D HODLŒZ ¹Z0 ;aº
N is as required. The general case for arbitrary n is similar. Let D .2ınC1 /N and let S and T be trees on ! such that .S ; T / 2 N and such that if g Coll.!; ınC1 / is N -generic then in N Œg, pŒS D pŒS and
pŒT D pŒT :
The trees S ; T are easily constructed in N by an analysis of terms. Suppose g Coll.!; ınC1 / is N -generic with g 2 L.R/. The generic filter g exists since !1 is strongly inaccessible in N .
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
Thus
215
pŒS \ N Œg D .R n pŒT / \ N Œg;
and so by Theorem 2.32, S and T are <ınC1 -weakly homogeneous in N . Let M D N where < !1 , ınC1 < and N ZFC: Thus .S ; T / 2 M . Further S ; T are <ınC1 -weakly homogeneous in M . Therefore M witnesses the lemma holds for A which contradicts the choice of A. t u As an immediate corollary to Lemma 5.23 and Theorem 5.36 we obtain the exis(T) , from simply assuming ADL.R/ . We state tence of sufficiently many conditions in Pmax (T) the lemma in a more general form than is required for the analysis of Pmax , cf. (4) of the lemma and the reference to generic extensions. Lemma 5.37. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/; (T) such that the following and for each n 2 !, there is a condition h.M; I/; X i 2 Pmax holds. Let ı be the Woodin cardinal of M associated to I and suppose that
g 2 H.!1 / is a filter which is M-generic for a partial order in Mı . Let Ig D .I<ı /MŒg . (1) A \ MŒg 2 MŒg. (2) hH.!1 /MŒg ; A \ MŒgi hH.!1 /; Ai. (3) .MŒg; Ig / is A-iterable. (4) ı is the nth Woodin cardinal of M. (T) Further the set of such conditions is dense in Pmax .
Proof. Let A be given and suppose that (T) : h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i 2 Pmax
Let A be the set of reals which code elements of A ¹h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 iº and let B be the set of reals which code elements of the first order diagram of hH.!1 /; A ; 2i: By Theorem 5.36, there exist a countable transitive set N and a ordinal ı 2 N such that the following hold.
216
5 Applications
(1.1) N ZFC. (1.2) ı is the nth Woodin cardinal in N . (1.3) B \ N 2 N and hV!C1 \ N; B \ N; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i: (1.4) B \ N is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in N . By Lemma 5.23 (applied in N ) there exists a condition (T) h.M; I/; ;i 2 .Pmax /N
such that the following holds where ıM be the Woodin cardinal of M associated to I. Suppose that M Œg is a generic extension of M for a partial order in MıM such that g 2 N . Let Ig D .I<ıM /MŒg : Then (2.1) A \ MŒg 2 MŒg, (2.2) hV!C1 \ MŒg; A \ MŒg; 2i hV!C1 \ N; A \ N; 2i, (2.3) .MŒg; Ig / is A -iterable in N , (2.4) ıM is the nth Woodin cardinal of M. Since hV!C1 \ M; A \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; M; 2i; it follows that h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i 2 H.!1 /M . Let j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be an iteration of .M0 ; I0 / such that j 2 M and such that j is full in M. Let Y D ¹.h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j /º [ j.X0 /. (T) Thus in N ; h.M; I/; Y i 2 Pmax and h.M; I/; Y i < h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i: Finally hV!C1 \ N; B \ N; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i; and so for any choice of g in V , (2.1)–(2.3) hold in V . (T) Similarly in V ; h.M; I/; Y i 2 Pmax and h.M; I/; Y i < h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i: Thus h.M; I/; Y i is as required.
t u
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
217
(T) The analysis of Pmax is now straightforward, following that of Pmax . In many ways (T) the analysis of Pmax is easier than that of Pmax . One reason is that no local forcing arguments are required. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose (T) G Pmax
is L.R/-generic. For each h.M; I/; X i 2 G there exists an iteration j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I / which is defined by combining the iterations k such that .h.M; I/; X i; k/ 2 Y where h.N ; J /; Y i 2 G and h.N ; J /; Y i < h.M; I/; X i: (T) Theorem 5.38. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then
L.R/ŒG ZFC; .P .!1 //
L.R/ŒG
D [¹.P .!1 //M j h.M; I/; X i 2 Gº;
and for all h.M; I/; X i 2 G,
.INS /M D M \ .INS /L.R/ŒG :
t u
(T) We leave the proof of this to the reader and simply prove that Pmax is equivalent in L.R/ to the iteration Pmax .!2
L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒgŒh where g Pmax is L.R/-generic and h .!2
k W .N ; J / ! .N ; J / with k.b/ D A and
J D INS \ N :
218
5 Applications
Fix D Pmax such that D is open, dense in Pmax and such that D 2 L.R/. Assume toward a contradiction that FA \ D D ;: By Theorem 5.38, there exist h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i 2 G and a0 2 M0 such that !1M0 D !1LŒa0 and such that j.a0 / D A where j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / given by G. We work in L.R/ and assume that h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i FA \ D D ;: Let h.N0 ; J0 /; b0 i 2 Pmax be such that M0 2 .H.!1 //N0 and such that
J0 D .INS /N0 :
Let j1 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M1 ; I1 / be an iteration such that j1 2 N0 , j.!1M0 / D !1N0 , and such that j1 is full in N0 . Let a1 D j1 .a0 /. Thus !1LŒa1 D !1N0 and so h.N0 ; J0 /; a1 i 2 Pmax . Since D is open, dense in Pmax , there exists h.N1 ; J1 /; b1 i 2 D such that h.N1 ; J1 /; b1 i < h.N0 ; J0 /; a1 i and such that
J1 D .INS /N1 :
(T) Let h.M2 ; I2 /; X2 i 2 Pmax be such that
N1 2 H.!1 /M2 : Let
k0 W .N0 ; J0 / ! .N0 ; J0 /
be the iteration such that k0 .a1 / D b1 . By Lemma 4.36 there exists an iteration k1 W .N1 ; J1 / ! .N2 ; J2 / such that k1 2 M2 and such that .INS /N2 D J2 D N2 \ .INS /M2 : Let a2 D k1 .b1 /. Thus k1 .k0 .j1 // is an iteration k1 .k0 .j1 // W .M0 ; I0 / ! .k1 .k0 .j1 //.M0 /; k1 .k0 .j1 //.I0 //
5.4 The stationary tower and Pmax
219
which is full in M2 . Therefore (T) h.M2 ; I2 /; X i 2 Pmax
and h.M2 ; I2 /; X i < h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i where X D k1 .k0 .j1 //.X0 / [ ¹.h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; k1 .k0 .j1 ///º: By genericity we may assume h.M2 ; I2 /; X i 2 G: Let j2 W .M2 ; I2 / ! .M2 ; I2 / be the iteration given by G. Thus j2 .k1 / W .N1 ; J1 / ! .N1 ; J1 / is an iteration such that
M
L.R/ŒG .INS /N1 D J1 D N \ INS 2 D N \ INS :
Further A D j0 .a0 / D j2 .k1 .k0 .j1 .a0 //// D j2 .k1 .b1 // D j2 .a2 / and j2 .k1 .b1 // D j2 .k1 /.j2 .b1 // D j2 .k1 /.b1 /: Therefore h.N1 ; J1 /; b1 i 2 FA which contradicts the choice of D and A. Therefore .L.P .!1 ///L.R/ŒG is a Pmax generic extension of L.R/. Fix g Pmax such that g is L.R/-generic and .L.P .!1 ///L.R/ŒG D L.R/Œg: Let P be the following partial order defined in L.R/Œg. (T) P is the set of pairs .h.M; I/; X i; j / such that h.M; I/; X i 2 Pmax and such that O I/ O j W .M; I/ ! .M; is an iteration which is full in L.R/Œg. Suppose .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 / 2 P and that .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; j1 / 2 P . Then .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; j1 / < .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 / if .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 / 2 j1 .X1 /: The two relevant properties of P are the following.
220
5 Applications
(1.1) For each .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 / 2 P and for each B !1 there exists .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; j1 / 2 P such that .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; j1 / < .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 / and such that B 2 j1 .M1 /. (1.2) For each .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 / 2 P there exist .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; j1 / 2 P , .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; k1 / 2 P , and .h.M2 ; I2 /; X2 i; k2 / 2 P such that a) .h.M2 ; I2 /; X2 i; j2 / < .h.M0 ; I0 /; X0 i; j0 /, b) .h.M2 ; I2 /; X2 i; j2 / < .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; j1 /, c) .h.M2 ; I2 /; X2 i; j2 / < .h.M1 ; I1 /; X1 i; k1 /, d) j1 ¤ k1 . By (1.1), the partial order P is .< !2 /-closed in L.R/Œg and by (1.2), RO.P / has no atoms. The partial order P has cardinality 2@1 in L.R/Œg and so since 2@1 D @2 in L.R/Œg, RO.P / Š RO.!2
L.R/ŒG0 D L.R/ŒgŒh0 : By the definability of forcing it follows that there exists h P such that h is L.R/Œg-generic and such that L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒgŒh:
t u
5.5 Pmax
221
5.5 Pmax (T) We define a second reformulation of Pmax . This version is quite closely related to Pmax and it involves a reformulation of the sentence AC .
Definition 5.40. AC : Suppose that hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i and hT˛ W ˛ < !1 i are each sequences of stationary, co-stationary sets. Then there exists a sequence hı˛ W ˛ < !1 i of ordinals less than !2 such that for each ˛ < !1 there exists a bijection
W !1 ! ı˛ ; and a closed unbounded set C !1 such that ¹ < !1 j ordertype.Œ/ 2 T˛ º \ C D S˛ \ C:
t u
If M ZFC then clearly M
AC
M
AC :
if and only if The reason for introducing iterable sequence and that
AC
is the following. Suppose that hMi W i < !i is an
[¹Mi j i < !º
AC :
Suppose that hMi W i < !i is an iterate of hMi W i < !i. Then [¹Mi j i < !º This can fail for
AC :
AC .
Definition 5.41. Pmax is the set of pairs .hMk W k < !i; a/ such that the following hold.
(1) a 2 M0 , a !1M0 , and !1M0 D !1LŒa;x for some x 2 R \ M0 . (2) Mk ZFC . Mk
(3) Mk 2 MkC1 ; !1
MkC1
D !1
.
(4) .INS /MkC1 \ Mk D .INS /MkC2 \ Mk . (5) [¹Mk j k 2 !º
AC .
(6) hMk W k < !i is iterable.
222
5 Applications
(7) There exists X 2 M0 such that M1 , a) X P .!1 /M0 n INS
b) M0 “jX j D !1 ”, M0 . c) for all S; T 2 X , if S ¤ T then S \ T 2 INS is analogous to Pmax . A condition The ordering on Pmax
.hNk W k < !i; b/ < .hMk W k < !i; a/ if hMk W k < !i 2 N0 , hMk W k < !i is hereditarily countable in N0 and there exists an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that: (1) j.a/ D b; (2) hMk W k < !i 2 N0 and j 2 N0 ;
(3) .INS /MkC1 \ Mk D .INS /N1 \ Mk for all k < !. Remark 5.42.
t u
(1) One can strengthen (4) by requiring that for all k < !, Mk MkC1 D Mk \ INS : INS
In this case (7) necessarily holds. is equivalent to the partial order Pmax , assuming that for (2) The partial order Pmax all x 2 R, x exists. is the better presentation of Pmax . The key difference is that one (3) Arguably Pmax without using ideals on !1 . This we can directly construct conditions in Pmax shall do in proving Theorem 5.49. t u
The proof of Lemma 5.15 easily adapts to prove the following lemma which is the analog of Lemma 4.35. . Suppose that Lemma 5.43. Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Pmax
j1 W hMk W k < !i ! hMk1 W k < !i and j2 W hMk W k < !i ! hMk2 W k < !i are wellfounded iterations such that j1 .a/ D j2 .a/. Then hMk1 W k < !i D hMk2 W k < !i and j1 D j2 .
5.5 Pmax
223
Proof. Fix x 2 R \ M0 such that !1M0 D !1LŒa;x : It follows that there exists Z !1M0 such that Z 2 LŒa; x \ M0 M
M
and such that for all k < !, Z … INS kC1 and .!1M0 n Z/ … INS kC1 . Therefore arguing as in the proof of Lemma 5.15, if j1 .Z/ D j2 .Z/ then hMk1 W k < !i D hMk2 W k < !i and j1 D j2 . The sequence hMk1 W k < !i is iterable and so it follows that for all b !1M0 , if b 2 [¹Mk j k 2 !º then b # 2 [¹Mk j k 2 !º: Therefore .x; a/# 2 [¹Mk j k 2 !º. Thus since j1 .a/ D j2 .a/ it follows that t u j1 .Z/ D j2 .Z/ noting that necessarily j1 .!1M0 / D j2 .!1M0 /. The basic iteration lemma required for the analysis of Pmax is a modification of Lemma 4.37. The proof is a minor variation of the proof of Lemma 4.36. . Suppose that Lemma 5.44 (ZFC ). Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Pmax hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 . Then there is an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that for all S !1 , if M
then S˛ n S 2 INS
S 2 [¹Mk j k < !º n [¹INS k j k < !º for some ˛ < !1 .
t u
As a corollary to Lemma 5.44 we obtain the following iteration lemma. It is for the proof of this lemma that the requirement (7) in the definition of Pmax is essential. Lemma 5.45. Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Pmax ; .hNk W k < !i; b/ 2 Pmax ;
and that
hMk W k < !i 2 H.!1 /N0 :
Then there is an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that j 2 N0 and such that M
N1 INS \ .[¹Mk j k < !º/ D [¹INS k j k < !º:
224
5 Applications
Proof. Since
.hNk W k < !i; b/ 2 Pmax
there exists a sequence hS˛ W ˛ < !1N0 i 2 N0 such that for all ˛ < ˇ < !1N0 , S˛ !1N0 ; N1 S˛ … INS ; N0 . and such that S˛ \ Sˇ 2 INS With this sequence the lemma follows by Lemma 5.44.
t u
is a routine generalization of Using the iteration lemmas the basic analysis of Pmax the analysis of Pmax provided suitable iterable structures exist.
Definition 5.46. Suppose that hMk W k < !i is an iterable sequence and that A R. Then the sequence hMk W k < !i is A-iterable if (1) A \ M0 2 [¹Mk j k < !º, (2) for any iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i, j.A \ M0 / D A \ M0 :
t u
. It is (notationally) We prove a very general existence lemma for conditions in Pmax (T) convenient to refer to Pmax in the statements of the two preliminary lemmas that we require; note that the assumption (T) h.M0 ; I0 /; ;i 2 Pmax
simply abbreviates: M0 is a countable transitive model of ZFC, I0 D .I<ı0 /M0 ; and that .M0 ; I0 / is an iterable where ı0 2 M0 is a Woodin cardinal in M0 . Lemma 5.47. Suppose that (T) h.M0 ; I0 /; ;i 2 Pmax :
Let ı0 2 M0 be the Woodin cardinal in M0 associated to I0 and let Q0 D .Q<ı0 /M0 be the associated stationary tower. Suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M0 i 2 M0 is such that ¹S˛ ; T˛ j ˛ < !1M0 º P .!1 /M0 n .INS /M0 : Then there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / of length !1 such that the following hold.
5.5 Pmax
225
(1) .INS /M0 D INS \ M0 . (2) Suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1 i D j.h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M0 i/: Let h˛ W ˛ < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the ordinals 2 !1 n .M0 \ Ord/ such that is a cardinal in L.M0 /. Let C D ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ D ˛ º: Then for all ˛ 2 C and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛ 2 Sˇ if and only if ˛Cˇ 2 Tˇ : Proof. The key point is that for each 2 C , if j0; W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / of length then by boundedness, j0; .!1M0 / D : Let D C be the set of 2 C such that C \ has ordertype . Thus the desired iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i of .M0 ; I0 / of length !1 can easily be construction by induction. By restricting the choice of G for 2 D one can achieve (1). These restrictions place no constraint on t u the choices of G for 2 C n D and so (2) can also easily be achieved. Lemma 5.48. Suppose that (T) h.M0 ; I0 /; ;i 2 Pmax
and that X0 V is a countable elementary substructure such that M0 D MX0 where MX0 is the transitive collapse of X0 . Suppose that a0 !1M0 is a set in M0 such that .!1 /LŒa0 D .!1 /M0 Then there exists
.hMO k W k < !i; a/ O 2 Pmax
226
5 Applications
such that: (1) there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / O such that j.a0 / D a. O
O
(2) for each k < !, .INS /Mk D .INS /MkC1 \ MO k . (3) hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable for each set A 2 X0 such that every set of reals which is projective in A is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. (T) . Proof. Let M be the set of .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / such that h.M; I/; ;i 2 Pmax Let ı 2 X0 be the Woodin cardinal whose image under the transitive collapse of X0 is the Woodin cardinal in M0 associated to I0 . We define by induction on k a sequence
h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i of elements of M together with iterations jk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik / and elements .Fk.S/ ; Fk.T / / 2 Mk as follows. We simultaneously define an increasing sequence hXk W k < !i of countable elementary substructures of V such that for each k < !, Mk is the transitive collapse of Xk . .M0 ; I0 / and X0 are as given. Suppose that Xk and .Mk ; Ik / have been defined. We define .Fk.S/ ; Fk.T / /, jk , XkC1 and .MkC1 ; IkC1 /. Let ık 2 Mk be the Woodin cardinal of Mk corresponding to Ik and let Qk D .Q<ık /Mk ; be the associated stationary tower. Let hk˛ W ˛ < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the ordinals 2 !1 n Mk such that is a cardinal in L.Mk /. Let Ck D ¹˛ j k˛ D ˛º: Choose .Fk.S/ ; Fk.T / / 2 Mk such that (1.1) Fk.S/ W .!1 /Mk ! P .!1 /Mk n .INS /Mk , (1.2) Fk.T / W .!1 /Mk ! P .!1 /Mk n .INS /Mk . By Lemma 5.47 there is an iteration jk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik / of length !1 such that
5.5 Pmax
227
(2.1) .INS /Mk D INS \ Mk , (2.2) for all ˛ 2 Ck and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛ 2 .jk /0;˛C1 .Fk.S/ /.ˇ/ if and only if ˛Cˇ 2 .jk /0;˛CˇC1 .Fk.T / /.ˇ/: Choose a countable elementary substructure XkC1 V such that .Xk ; jk / 2 XkC1 : Let MkC1 be the transitive collapse of XkC1 and let IkC1 be the image of I under the collapsing map. Thus .MkC1 ; IkC1 / 2 M: This completes the definition of (3.1) h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i, (3.2) hjk W k < !i, (3.3) hXk W k < !i, except that we require that ¹jk .Fk.S/ /; jk .Fk.T / / j k < !º is equal to the set, ® ¯ M M [ ¹jk .f / j f W !1 k ! P .!1 k / \ Mk n .INS /Mk and f 2 Mk º j k < ! which is easily achieved. Let X D [¹Xk j k < !º and for each k < ! let .MO k ; YOk / be the image of .Mk ; jk .Yk // under the transitive collapse of X . Let aO D j0 .a0 / \ X: We claim that
.hMO k W k < !i; a/ O 2 Pmax
and is as desired. The verification is straightforward. The sequence hMO k W k < !i satisfies the hypothesis of Lemma 4.17 and so by Lemma 4.17 it is iterable, cf. the proof of Lemma 5.32. u t
228
5 Applications
Combining Lemma 5.48 with Theorem 5.36 we obtain the following fairly general . A more general version is given in Secexistence theorem for conditions in Pmax tion 10.4; cf. Theorem 10.152. The version here suffices for our immediate purposes. Suppose that is a †2 sentence such that it is a theorem of ZFC C “There is a Woodin cardinal ” that there exists a boolean algebra B such that V B : For example could be any of the following. (1) ˘. (2) MA C :CH. (3) MA!1 C “INS is !2 -saturated”. Theorem 5.49. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/; such that there is a condition .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Pmax
M0 ZFC C ; and such that (1) A \ M0 2 M0 , (2) hH.!1 /M0 ; A \ M0 i hH.!1 /; Ai, (3) hMk W k < !i is A-iterable, . and further the set of such conditions is dense in Pmax
Proof. As usual the density of the desired conditions follows on abstract grounds (by changing A and applying the iteration lemma, Lemma 5.44). Fix A and let B0 be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i: Let B1 be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; B0 ; 2i: Thus B1 2 L.R/. By Theorem 5.36, there exist a countable transitive model M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that the following hold. (1.1) M ZFC. (1.2) ı is the second Woodin cardinal in M .
5.5 Pmax
229
(1.3) B1 \ M 2 M and hV!C1 \ M; B1 \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B1 ; 2i: (1.4) B1 \ M is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M . Let ı0 be the least Woodin cardinal of M and let 0 be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal of M above ı0 . Thus since M0 ZFC C “There is a Woodin cardinal”; there exists a partial order P 2 M0 such that M P : Let g P be an M -generic filter (with g 2 V ). Thus: (2.1) M Œg ZFC; (2.2) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M ; (2.3) B0 \ M Œg 2 M Œg and hV!C1 \ M Œg; B0 \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; B0 ; 2iI (2.4) B0 \ M Œg is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M Œg; noting that (2.3) and (2.4) follow from Lemma 2.29. Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal of M Œg above ı. By (2.3), 1 B0 \ M Œg is not † 1 in M Œg and so by (2.4), exists. Let X0 M Œg be an elementary substructure structure such that X0 2 M Œg, B0 \ M Œg 2 X0 , and such that X0 is countable in M Œg. Let M0 be the transitive collapse of X0 . Let a !1 be a set in X0 such that !1 D .!1 /LŒa and let a0 D a \ X0 . By Lemma 5.48 there exists O 2 .Pmax /M Œg .hMO k W k < !i; a/ such that in M Œg, (3.1) there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that j.a0 / D aO and such that M0 D MO 0 ; (3.2) hMO k W k < !i is B0 \ M Œg-iterable.
230
5 Applications
By (3.1), since is a †2 sentence, MO 0 ; and by (2.3), (2.4) and (3.1), hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 \ M Œg; A \ M Œg; 2i: Therefore since hV!C1 \ M Œg; B0 \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; B0 ; 2i: it follows that
hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i; .hMO k W k < !i; a/ O 2 Pmax ;
and that hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable.
t u
A very similar argument proves the following theorem. Theorem 5.50. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose that D0 Pmax is dense in Pmax with D0 2 L.R/. Let D1 be the set of .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Pmax
such that
.INS /M0 D .INS /M1 \ M0
and such that
h.M0 ; .INS /M0 /; ai 2 D0 :
. Then D1 is dense in Pmax
t u
Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. We assume ADL.R/ so that by Theorem 5.49, is nontrivial. We associate to the generic filter G, a subset of !1 , AG and an ideal, Pmax IG . This is just as in case of Pmax .
AG D [¹a j .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 G for some hMk W k < !iº: For each .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 G there is an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that j.a/ D AG . This iteration is unique by Lemma 5.43. Define M
IG D [¹INS 1 \ M0 j .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Gº and let
P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M0 j .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Gº:
The next theorem gives the basic analysis of Pmax .
5.5 Pmax
231
Theorem 5.51. Assume AD L.R/ . Then Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then
L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal saturated ideal; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal.
t u
Theorem 5.51 can be proved following the proof of the analogous theorem for Pmax . One can also obtain the theorem as an immediate corollary of the following theorem together with the analysis of L.R/Pmax . Theorem 5.52. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then there exists a filter H Pmax such that H is L.R/-generic and
L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒH : such that Proof. Let DPmax be the set of .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Pmax
(1) M0 MA!1 , (2) M0 “INS is saturated”, (3) .INS /M0 D .INS /M1 \ M0 . By Theorem 5.50, DPmax is dense in Pmax . Define
H D ¹h.M0 ; .INS /M0 /; a0 i j .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 DPmax \ Gº: We claim that H is a filter in Pmax . This follows from the definition of the order on and the fact that DPmax is dense in Pmax . Pmax Again by Theorem 5.50, D\H ¤; for each dense set D Pmax with D 2 L.R/. Thus H is L.R/-generic. Clearly L.R/ŒH L.R/ŒG: By one last application of the density of DPmax and the definition of the order on Pmax ,
G 2 L.R/ŒH and so L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒH .
t u
232
5 Applications
0 5.6 Pmax 0 0 We define a fourth presentation of Pmax , this is Pmax . The partial order Pmax is essen without the requirement that AC hold in the models associated to the tially just Pmax conditions. This requires that history be added to the conditions as was done in the (T) . definition of Pmax 0 is generalizing the following two theorems which are Our purpose in defining Pmax corollaries of the results of Chapter 3.
Theorem 5.53 (MA!1 ). Assume INS is !2 -saturated and that P .!1 /# exists. Then there is a semi-generic filter G Pmax such that P .!1 /G D P .!1 /. Proof. By Lemma 3.14 and Theorem 3.16, if X H.!2 / is a countable elementary substructure then MX is iterable where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Fix a set A !1 such that !1 D !1LŒA : Following the proof of Theorem 4.76, let FA Pmax be the set of all conditions h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.a/ D A and INS \ M D I . Let G D FA : By Corollary 3.13, for each countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that A 2 X ,
h.MX ; IX /; AX i 2 G
where MX is the transitive collapse of X , AX D A \ !1 \ X and IX D .INS / . It follows that G is a semi-generic filter in Pmax and that MX
P .!1 /G D P .!1 /: A similar argument proves the corresponding theorem for Pmax .
t u
0 5.6 Pmax
233
Theorem 5.54 ( AC ). Assume INS is !2 -saturated and that P .!1 /# exists. Then there is a semi-generic filter G Pmax such that P .!1 /G D P .!1 /.
t u
We shall prove the following theorem in Section 9.5. Theorem 5.55. Assume Martin’s Maximum.c/. Then for each set A !2 , A# exists.u t Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies that 2@1 D @2 and so we obtain the following corollary. Corollary 5.56. Assume Martin’s Maximum.c/. Then there is a semi-generic filter G Pmax such that P .!1 /G D P .!1 /. Proof. By the results of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/, Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies that 2@0 D 2@1 D @2 . Therefore by Theorem 9.69, Martin’s Maximum implies that P .!1 /# exists. The theorem follows from Theorem 5.53. t u 0 Definition 5.57. We define Pmax by induction on
[¹Mk \ Ord j k < !º where hMk W k < !i is the countable sequence transitive models specified in the 0 consists of pairs .hMk W k < !i; X / such that the following hold. condition. Pmax (1) Mk ZFC . Mk
(2) Mk 2 MkC1 ; !1
MkC1
D !1
.
(3) .INS /MkC1 \ Mk D .INS /MkC2 \ Mk . (4) hMk W k < !i is iterable. (5) X 2 M0 and X is a set, possibly empty, of pairs ..hNk W k < !i; X0 /; j0 / such that the following conditions hold: a) hNk W k < !i is countable in M0 ; 0 b) .hNk W k < !i; X0 / 2 Pmax ;
c) j0 W hNk W k < !i ! hNk W k < !i is an iteration such that for all k < !,
.INS /M1 \ Nk D .INS /NkC1 \ Nk I
234
5 Applications
d) j0 .X0 / X ; e) if ..hNk W k < !i; X0 /; j1 / 2 X then j0 D j1 . 0 is defined as follows. Suppose The order on Pmax 0 : ¹.hMk W k < !i; X /; .hNk W k < !i; Y /º Pmax
Then .hMk W k < !i; X / < .hNk W k < !i; Y / if there exists an iteration j W hNk W k < !i ! hNk W k < !i such that ..hNk W k < !i; Y /; j / 2 X .
t u
0 (T) is a combination of the definitions of Pmax and Remark 5.58. The definition of Pmax Pmax . One important item in the definition of Pmax has been eliminated, this is clause 0 is such that X ¤ ; (7). The relevant observation is that if .hMk W k < !i; X / 2 Pmax then (7) holds, i. e. there exists a set Z 2 M0 such that M1 (1) Z P .!1 /M0 n INS ,
(2) M0 “jZj D !1 ”, M0 . (3) for all S; T 2 Z, if S ¤ T then S \ T 2 INS
t u
0 extension of L.R/, assuming ADL.R/ , is a routine modifiThe analysis of the Pmax (T) extension. As for the analysis of the Pmax -extension, cation of the analysis of the Pmax a non-interference lemma is required. The proof is similar to that of Lemma 5.28 which (T) . is the corresponding lemma for Pmax
Lemma 5.59 (ZFC ). Suppose 0 .hMk W k < !i; X / 2 Pmax
and that j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is an iteration of hMk W k < !i of length !1 . Then hMk W k < !i … M0 .
t u
Definition 5.60. Suppose that for each x 2 R there exists a condition 0 .hMk W k < !i; X / 2 Pmax
such that x 2 M0 . 0 (1) A filter G Pmax is semi-generic if for each ˛ < !1 there exists 0 such that ˛ < .!1 /M0 . .hMk W k < !i; X / 2 Pmax
0 5.6 Pmax
235
0 (2) Suppose that G Pmax is a semi-generic filter. Then for each p 2 G, with p D .hMk W k < !i; X /,
jp;G W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is the iteration of length !1 given by G. 0 (3) Suppose that G Pmax is a semi-generic filter. Then
P .!1 /G D [¹jp;G .P .!1 /.p;0/ / j p 2 Gº 0 where for each p 2 Pmax with p D .hMk W k < !i; X /,
P .!1 /.p;0/ D .P .!1 //M0 :
t u
0 The existence of conditions as required for the analysis of the Pmax extension is an . immediate corollary of Theorem 5.49 which is the corresponding theorem for Pmax
Theorem 5.61. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/; 0 such that there is a condition .hMk W k < !i; X / 2 Pmax (1) A \ M0 2 M0 , (2) hH.!1 /M0 ; A \ M0 i hH.!1 /; Ai, (3) hMk W k < !i is A-iterable, 0 . and further the set of such conditions is dense in Pmax
t u
0 The basic analysis of Pmax is given in the following two theorems. The second 0 , the proof is similar. theorem is the version of Theorem 5.39 for Pmax 0 Theorem 5.62. Assume AD L.R/ . Then Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. 0 Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then
L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal saturated ideal; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal.
t u
0 Theorem 5.63. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then
L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒgŒh where g Pmax is L.R/-generic and h .!2
t u
236
5 Applications
The generalization of Theorem 5.53 and Theorem 5.54 that we seek is the following. Theorem 5.64. The following are equivalent. (1) 2@0 D 2@1 and there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that the transitive collapse of X is iterable. (2) There exists a semi-generic filter 0 G Pmax
such that P .!1 /G D P .!1 /. Proof. Let D .2@1 /C . Fix a wellordering, <, of H. /. We fix some notation. Suppose that X hH. /; <; 2i is a countable elementary substructure. For each !1 let X Œ D ¹f .s/ j s 2
0 5.6 Pmax
237
a) For some a0 2 Zi
By Lemma 3.12, the map j specified in (2.2(d)) is an iteration. Let Z0 D [¹Zk j k < !º: 0 which satisfies the It follows, since jZ0 j < 2@0 , that Z0 generates a filter F0 Pmax conditions (1.1)–(1.2). This proves our claim and (2) follows. To finish we assume (2) holds and prove (1). First we must prove that (2) implies that 2@0 D 2@1 . But 0 j 2@0 jGj jPmax
and for each condition p 2 G, there is a unique iteration jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i
given by G where p D .hM.p;k/ W k < !i; X.p/ /i. By the definition of P .!1 /G , P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 / \ M.p;0/ j p 2 Gº;
and so by (2), 2@0 D 2@1 . To finish we must prove that (2) implies that there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that the transitive collapse of X is iterable. By (2), for every x 2 R there exists an iterable sequence, hNk W k < !i; such that x 2 N0 . Thus arguing as in the proof of Theorem 3.19, for every x 2 R, x # exists. Thus the existence of X H.!2 /, countable and with iterable transitive collapse, is essentially an immediate corollary of Lemma 4.22 and Theorem 3.19. u t
238
5 Applications
5.7
The Axiom
We prove that the Pmax -extension can be characterized by a certain kind of generic homogeneity. This property generalizes to L.P .!1 // a well known property which characterizes L.R/ in the case that L.R/ is computed in LŒG where G is L-generic for adding uncountably many Cohen reals to L. This is the symmetric extension of L given by infinitely many Cohen reals. Suppose that L.R/ is a symmetric extension of L for adding infinitely many Cohen reals. Then the following hold. (1) There is an L-generic Cohen real. (2) Let X R be a nonempty set which is ordinal definable in L.R/. Then there exists a term 2 L such that for all L-generic Cohen reals c, .c/ 2 X; where .c/ is the interpretation of by the generic filter given by c. It is straightforward to show that the converse is also true: If (1) and (2) hold then L.R/ is a symmetric extension of of L for adding infinitely many Cohen reals. The point is that (1) and (2) imply that for every x 2 R n L, LŒx D LŒc for some c 2 R which is an L-generic Cohen real. Further (1) and (2) also imply that for every x 2 R, there is an LŒx-generic Cohen real. We generalize this to L.P .!1 // in Theorem 5.67. This gives a reformulation of the axiom ./ which seems more suited to the investigation of the consequences of this axiom. As we have indicated above, this property characterizes the Pmax -extension. We fix some notation. Recall that the partial order Coll.!;
t u
5.7 The Axiom
239
Remark 5.66. The sequence hS˛g W ˛ < !1 i, defined in Definition 5.65, can be defined using any reasonable sequence h˛ W ˛ < !1 i of terms for pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 . The only important requirement is that h˛ W ˛ < !1V i 2 L:
t u
Theorem 5.67. Assume ./ holds. Suppose X P .!1 /, X 2 L.P .!1 //; X ¤ ;, and that X is definable in L.P .!1 // from real and ordinal parameters. Then there exist t 2 R and a term !1 Coll.!;
M
M0 D ¹j.hi /.˛/ j ˛ < !1 0 ; i < !º: Let t 2 R code M0 . Suppose g Coll.!;
240
5 Applications
(1.1) j 2 LŒt Œg, (1.2) j.!1M0 / D !1 , (1.3) for all if S D j.hi /.˛/ then
S 2 P .!1 / \ M0 n I0 ; Sg n S 2 INS
where D ! ˛ C i (i. e. is the image of .i; ˛/ under a reasonable bijection of ! !1 with !1 ). The iteration j is easily constructed in LŒt Œg. Let be a term for j . We may suppose that the interpretation of by any LŒt generic filter yields an iteration satisfying (1.1)–(1.3). Let 0 be a term in LŒt for j.a0 / and let D ¹.˛; p/ j ˛ < !1 ; p 2 Coll.!;
t u
5.7 The Axiom
241
We isolate the conclusion of Theorem 5.67 in defining the following axiom. Definition 5.68. Axiom : For all t 2 R, t # exists. Suppose X P .!1 /, X ¤ ;, and that X is definable from real and ordinal parameters. Then there exist t 2 R and a term !1 Coll.!;
t u one need only consider sets
X P .!1 / which are definable (without parameters). Lemma 5.69 (For all t 2 R, t # exists). The following are equivalent. (1) . (2) Suppose X P .!1 /, X ¤ ;, and that X is definable by a †2 formula. Then there exist t 2 R and a term !1 Coll.!;
242
5 Applications
where z D A \ ! and where A D ¹˛ < !1 j ! C ˛ 2 Aº:
If fails then X ¤ ;. Assume toward a contradiction that X ¤ ;. X is definable by a †2 formula. Therefore by (2) there exist t 2 R and a term !1 Coll.!;
Since t exists we may suppose, by replacing t if necessary, that is definable in LŒt from t and !1 . Let 0 be the least Silver indiscernible of LŒt and let g0 Coll.!; 0 / be an LŒt -generic filter. Fix t0 2 LŒt Œg0 \ R such that LŒt Œg0 D LŒt0 and define 0 !1 Coll.!;
5.7 The Axiom
243
Thus for all ˛ < !1 , S˛g is stationary. Let A D Ig . /. Therefore A 2 X and so A 2 Xz where as above, z D A \ ! and A D ¹˛ < !1 j ! C ˛ 2 Aº: Since is definable in LŒt from t and !1 , it follows that A\! is completely determined by g \ Coll.!; <0 / g0 : Therefore z 2 LŒt0 and z does not depend on h. Finally by the definition of 0 , Ih .0 / D A and so Ih . / 2 Xz . Therefore t0 and 0 witness that Xz is not a counterexample to , which is a contradiction. t u Many of the consequences of ./ are more easily proved using . We begin with a straightforward consequence which concerns !1 -borel sets. A set A R is !1 -borel if it can be generated from the borel sets by closing the borel sets under !1 unions and intersections. Clearly if CH holds then every set of reals is !1 -borel. The following lemma gives a useful characterization of the !1 -borel sets. Lemma 5.70. Suppose A R. The following are equivalent. (1) A is !1 -borel. (2) There exist S !1 , ˛ < !2 , and a formula .x0 ; x1 /, such that !1 < ˛ and such that t u A D ¹y 2 R j L˛ ŒS; y ŒS; yº: Lemma 5.70 can fail if one does not assume AC, the difficulty is that it is possible for a set A R to be !1 -borel but not effectively !1 -borel. With the latter notion, Lemma 5.70 is true in just ZF. A set A R is effectively !1 -borel if it has an !1 borel code. The !1 -borel codes are defined by induction as subsets of !1 in the natural fashion generalizing the definition of borel codes as subsets of !. Lemma 5.71 (ZF). Suppose A R. The following are equivalent. (1) A is effectively !1 -borel. (2) There exist S !1 , ˛ < !2 , and a formula .x0 ; x1 /, such that !1 < ˛ and such that t u A D ¹y 2 R j L˛ ŒS; y ŒS; yº:
244
5 Applications
1 It is not difficult to show, assuming AD, that every !1 -borel set is 3 . This is an immediate consequence of the fact that assuming AD, the 13 sets are closed under !1 unions. In fact, Lemma 5.70 can be proved assuming AD, and so, assuming AD, the following are equivalent:
(1) A is !1 -borel, (2) A is effectively !1 -borel, (3) there exist x 2 R, ˛ < !2 , and a formula , such that !1 < ˛ and such that A D ¹y 2 R j L˛ Œx; y Œx; yº:
t u
Theorem 5.72. Assume . Suppose that A R and that A is definable from ordinal and real parameters. Then the following are equivalent. (1) A is !1 -borel. 1 (2) A is † 3 and
L.R/ A is !1 -borel:
(3) There exist x 2 R, ˛ < !2 , and a formula , such that !1 < ˛ and such that A D ¹y 2 R j L˛ Œx; y Œx; yº:
t u
Proof. (2) trivially implies (1) and by Lemma 5.70, (3) also implies (1). We assume (1) and prove (3). By Lemma 5.70 there exist S0 !1 , ˛0 < !2 , and a formula 0 .x0 ; x1 /, such that !1 < ˛0 and such that A D ¹y 2 R j L˛0 ŒS0 ; y 0 ŒS0 ; y; !1 º: Clearly we can suppose that ˛0 is less than the least ordinal such that !1 < and such that L ŒS0 is admissible. Fix ˛0 and 0 . Let X P .!1 / be the set of S such that (1.1) A D ¹y 2 R j L˛0 ŒS; y 0 ŒS; yº, (1.2) ˛0 < where is the least ordinal above !1 such that L ŒS is admissible. Thus X ¤ ; and since A is definable from ordinal and real parameters, so is X . By there exist x 2 R and a term !1 Coll.!;
5.7 The Axiom
245
if g is LŒx-generic and if for each < !1 , S g is stationary, then Ig ./ 2 X: Let ˛ < !2 be least such that ˛0 < ˛ and such that L˛ .x/ ZFC: Note that for each y 2 R, if g Coll.!;
such that G is L.R/-generic and such that L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG: Thus assuming L.R/ AD; and that
V D L.P .!1 //;
it follows that ./ and are equivalent. In fact we shall also prove that assuming , the nonstationary ideal has a homogeneity property which can be shown to imply that L.R/ AD: Thus if
V D L.P .!1 //;
then ./ and are equivalent. The proof that implies that L.P .!1 // is a Pmax -extension of L.R/ requires the following theorem and subsequent lemma. These combine to prove Corollary 5.78. Theorem 5.73 gives more than we need however it does give some interesting consequences of ./.
246
5 Applications
Theorem 5.73. Assume
holds. Then:
(1) ı12 D !2 . (2) Every club in !1 contains a club which is constructible from a real. (3) Suppose A !1 is cofinal. There is a wellordering
5.7 The Axiom
247
Let p0 and q0 be the LŒt0 -least such conditions relative to the canonical wellordering of LŒt0 given by t0 . Since Ig0 .0 / 2 X0 , ˛0 , p0 and q0 exist. Since 0 is definable in LŒt0 from t0 and !1 , ¹˛0 ; p0 ; q0 º L 1 Œt0 where 1 is the least indiscernible of LŒt0 above 0 . Let h W < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the indiscernibles of LŒt0 below !1 . For each < !1 let j W LŒt0 ! LŒt0 be the canonical elementary embedding such that j.0 / D and such that LŒt0 D ¹j .f /.s/ j f 2 LŒt0 ; s 2 Œ
248
5 Applications
(3.1) ¹p W ! ¹ º ! j p 2 g0 º g, (3.2) ¹i 2 ! j ˛CiC1 2 Ig .0 /º codes g0 \ Coll.!; <C! /, (3.3) g \ Coll.!; < / 2 LŒt0# Œg0 \ Coll.!; < /. This is easily done. There are two relevant points. (4.1) For each < !1 if is a limit ordinal and if h0 Coll.!; <Ci / is LŒt0 -generic then the filter h0 can be enlarged to an LŒt0 -generic filter h1 Coll.!; <CiC1 / with either pCi 2 h1 or qCi 2 h1 as desired. (4.2) The are strongly inaccessible in LŒt0 . Therefore if < ! is a limit ordinal and h Coll.!; < / is a filter such that for all ˇ < , h \ Coll.!; <ˇ / is LŒt0 -generic, then h is LŒt0 -generic. With these observations in hand we sketch the inductive step. The limit steps are immediate, the uniformity of the construction at successor steps ensures that (3.3) holds. Suppose < !1 , is a limit ordinal and that g \ Coll.!; < / is given. Since g \ Coll.!; < / 2 LŒt0# Œg0 \ Coll.!; < /; we can define g \ Coll.!; / satisfying (3.1) and preserving LŒt0 -genericity. For each i ! let i D C2Ci : Thus for each i < !, .pCiC1 ; qCiC1 / 2 L i Œt0 : We work in LŒt0# Œg0 \ Coll.!; <! /. Let x ! be such that x 2 LŒt0# Œg0 \ Coll.!; <! / and such that x codes g0 \ Coll.!; <! /. We choose x to be the LŒt0# Œg0 \ Coll.!; <! /-least such set in the canonical wellordering of LŒt0# Œg0 \ Coll.!; <! / given by .t0# ; g0 \ Coll.!; <! //. It is straightforward to construct, using (4.1), g \ Coll.!; <i / by induction on i < ! such that ¹i < ! j pCiC1 2 gº D x and such that ¹i < ! j qCiC1 2 gº D ! n x:
5.7 The Axiom
By (4.2)
249
[¹g \ Coll.!; <i / j i < !º
is LŒt0 -generic. Thus
[¹g \ Coll.!; <i / j i < !º
is as desired. We define
g \ Coll.!; <! /
to be the LŒt0# Œg0 \ Coll.!; <! /-least such extension of g \ Coll.!; < /: Let g Coll.!;
g D ¹pj.! Œ! ; !1 // j p 2 gº
This contradicts Ig .0 / 2 X0 and so X0 D ;. This proves (5).
t u
Remark 5.74. (4) can be generalized to give the following. Suppose T !1
250
5 Applications
The following theorem which we shall prove in Section 6.2.4 shows that the axiom implies that there are no weak Kurepa trees. The relevant theorem of Section 6.2.4 is Theorem 6.124 and is actually a little stronger than Theorem 5.75. Note that by Theorem 5.73(5), implies that for every B !1 , B # exists. Therefore implies that for every B !1 , jP .!1 / \ LŒBj D !1 : Theorem 5.75. Assume that
. Suppose that A !1 . Then there exists B !1 such
(1) A 2 LŒB, (2) for all Z !1 if
Z \ ˛ 2 LŒB
for all ˛ < !1 then Z 2 LŒB.
t u
Remark 5.76. (1) The first 4 consequences of given in Theorem 5.73 follow from Martin’s Maximum though the proofs seem more involved. (2) We do not know if (5) of Theorem 5.73 can be proved from Martin’s Maximum. This problem seems very likely related to the problem of the relationship of Martin’s Maximum and the axiom ./. Similarly we do not know if Theorem 5.75 can be proved from Martin’s Maximum. The two problems are likely closely related. Note that if B !1 satisfies the condition (2) of Theorem 5.75 and if t u B # exists then there must exist x 2 LŒB \ R such that x # … LŒB. Lemma 5.77. Assume
. Suppose that y 2 R and that M 2 H.!2 /
is definable from y and ordinal parameters. Then M 2 LŒz for some z 2 R. Proof. This is an immediate consequence of . Fix y 2 R and suppose that M 2 H.!2 / is ordinal definable from y. Let X be the set of A !1 such that M 2 LŒA: Thus is ordinal definable from y (and X ¤ ;). X By , there exist z 2 R and !1 Coll.!;
S˛g
is stationary for each ˛ < !1 then Ig ./ 2 X:
5.7 The Axiom
251
Let g1 Coll.!;
t u
Lemma 5.77 has the following corollary. This is also a corollary of Theorem 5.73 and Theorem 3.22, but the proof we give is more direct. Corollary 5.78. Assume
. Then for all x 2 R, x exists.
Proof. Fix x 2 R. By Theorem 5.73(2) and Lemma 5.77, F \ P .!1 / \ HODx is an HODx -ultrafilter where F is the club filter on !1 . Therefore !1 is a measurable cardinal in HODx and F \ P .!1 / \ HODx is a normal measure on !1 . Let N D LŒF ; x: Since !1 is a measurable cardinal in N , jV!1 \ N j D !1 and so by Lemma 5.77 there exists y0 2 R such that V!1 \ N 2 LŒy0 : Since y0# exists, for all A !1 , if A \ ˛ 2 LŒy0 for all ˛ < !1 then A 2 LŒy0 .
252
5 Applications
Thus P .!1 / \ N LŒy0 and so jP .!1 / \ N j D !1 : Hence by Lemma 5.77 again there exists y1 2 R such that P .!1 / \ N 2 LŒy1 and such that F \ P .!1 / \ N 2 LŒy1 : Thus N LŒy1 #
y1#
and so N exists since exists. Therefore x exists.
t u
By Theorem 4.59 and Corollary 5.78, assuming trivial. Lemma 5.79. Assume
, the partial order Pmax is non-
. Suppose A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/:
Then A is HODR -generic for Pmax . Proof. For each A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/; let FA be the set of
h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax
for which there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.a/ D A and such that I D INS \ M : By Theorem 3.19 and Theorem 5.73(2), there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that MX is iterable where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Thus by Lemma 4.74 the elements of FA are pairwise compatible. Therefore it suffices to show that FA \ D ¤ ; for each D Pmax such that D is dense and such that D 2 HODR . Assume toward a contradiction that A0 2 P .!1 / n L.R/;
5.7 The Axiom
253
D0 Pmax is dense, D0 2 HODR , and that D0 \ FA0 D ;: By Theorem 5.73(5), there exists t0 2 R such that !1 D .!1 /LŒt0 ;A0 : Let X P .!1 / n L.R/ be the set of all A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/ such that (1.1) FA \ D0 D ;, (1.2) !1 D .!1 /LŒA;t0 . Since D0 2 HODR ; X is definable with parameters from R [ Ord. Further A0 2 X and so X ¤ ;. Therefore by there exist t 2 R and !1 Coll.!;
254
5 Applications
and let I0 2 N Œg be the ideal generated by ¹a ı j ı n a 2 º: It follows that .N ŒgŒh; I0 / is iterable. Thus h.N ŒgŒh; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax and so, since D0 is dense, there exists h.M; I /; ai 2 D0 such that h.M; I /; ai < h.N ŒgŒh; I0 /; a0 i: Let
j0 W .N ŒgŒh; I0 / ! .N Œg Œh ; I0 /
be the iteration such that j0 .a0 / D a. By Lemma 4.36, there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / of length !1 such that Let A D j.a/. By elementarity,
I D INS \ M :
j.g / Coll.!;
g is LŒt -generic and A D Ij.g / ./: Moreover for each ˛ < ı, .S˛g /N ŒgŒh … I0 : Thus, by the elementarity of j ı j0 , for each ˛ < !1 , S˛j.g Since
/
… I :
I D INS \ M ;
it follows that for each ˛ < !1 , S˛j.g / is stationary. Thus implies that A 2 X . However the iteration, j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / witnesses h.M; I /; ai 2 FA : t u
This is a contradiction. Corollary 5.80. Assume . Then MA!1 . Proof. Let A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/ code a pair .P ; D/ 2 H.!2 / such that
5.7 The Axiom
255
(1.1) P is a ccc partial order, (1.2) D is a collection of dense subsets of P . By Lemma 5.79, A is L.R/-generic for Pmax . In particular there exists h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax and an iteration
j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
such that
I D INS \ M
and such that j.a/ D A. By elementarity,
M MA!1 :
Therefore since A 2 M we have that .P ; D/ 2 M : This implies that there is a filter F P such that F 2 M and such that F \d ¤; for all d 2 D.
t u
We recall the following notation. Suppose G Pmax is a semi-generic filter. P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 / \ M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº where for each h.M; I /; ai 2 G, j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the unique iteration such that j.a/ D AG D [¹a j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº: Of course the filter G is uniquely specified by AG . Theorem 5.81. Assume
. Suppose A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/:
Then exists a filter G Pmax such that G is HODR -generic and such that the following hold. (1) A D AG . (2) P .!1 / D P .!1 /G . (3) HODP .!1 / D HODR ŒG.
256
5 Applications
Proof. Suppose A 2 P .!1 / n L.R/: Fix x 2 R such that
!1 D .!1 /LŒA;x :
By Lemma 5.79 there is a filter G Pmax such that G is HODR -generic and such that A D AG : Suppose B !1 . By Corollary 5.80, MA!1 holds and so B 2 L!1 C1 ŒA; x; y for some y 2 R. By genericity there exists, h.M; I /; ai 2 G such that .x; y/ 2 M. Let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the unique iteration such that A D j.a/. It follows that L!1 C1 ŒA; x; y 2 M and so B 2 M ; i. e.
B 2 P .!1 /G :
Therefore P .!1 / D P .!1 /G and so G satisfies (2). We finish by proving that HODP .!1 / D HODR ŒG: Let P be the predicate defined as follows. .A; ; ˛; b/ 2 P if (1.1) ˛ 2 Ord and ˛ > !2 , (1.2) b 2 R Ord, (1.3) A 2 P .!1 /, (1.4) is a formula in the language for set theory, (1.5) V˛ ŒA; b. It is an elementary fact that HODP .!1 / D L.P; P .!1 //: Therefore it suffices to show that for all ı 2 Ord, P \ Vı 2 HODR ŒG: Let Q be the following predicate. .t; ; ; ˛; b/ 2 Q if
5.7 The Axiom
257
(2.1) ˛ 2 Ord and ˛ > !2 , (2.2) b 2 R Ord, (2.3) t 2 R, !1 Coll.!;
and this proves the theorem.
Using the results of the next section, Section 5.8, the assumption in the Corollary 5.82 that L.R/ AD can be eliminated; i. e. if then ./ and
V D L.P .!1 //; are equivalent.
Corollary 5.82. Assume L.R/ AD: Then the following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) L.P .!1 //
We next prove that of P .!1 /.
.
t u implies that a perfect set theorem holds for definable subsets
258
5 Applications
Theorem 5.83. Assume holds. Suppose X P .!1 / and that X is definable in L.P .!1 // from real and ordinal parameters. Suppose there exists A 2 X such that A … L.R/. Then there exists a function W 2
˛ 2 .s/
if and only if s.˛/ D 1I and such that for all F 2 2!1 , [¹.F j˛/ j ˛ < !1 º 2 X: Proof. The proof is quite similar to the proof of Theorem 5.73(5). Let X0 D X n L.R/. Thus X0 is definable from ordinal and real parameters, and X0 ¤ ;. By there exist t0 2 R, 0 !1 Coll.!;
5.7 The Axiom
259
(1.3) p “˛0 2 Ig0 .0 /”. (1.4) q “˛0 … Ig0 .0 /”. Let p0 and q0 be the LŒt0 -least such conditions relative to the canonical wellordering of LŒt0 given by t0 . Since Ig0 .0 / 2 X0 , ˛0 , p0 and q0 exist. Since 0 is definable in LŒt0 from t0 and !1 , ¹˛0 ; p0 ; q0 º L 1 Œt0 where 1 is the least indiscernible of LŒt0 above 0 . Let h W < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the indiscernibles of LŒt0 below !1 . For each < !1 let j W LŒt0 ! LŒt0 be the canonical elementary embedding such that j.0 / D and such that LŒt0 D ¹j .f /.s/ j f 2 LŒt0 ; s 2 Œ
˛ D j .˛0 /;
let p D j .p0 /; and let q D j .q0 /: Suppose that g 2 F t0 and that g \ Coll.!; <0 / D g0 \ Coll.!; <0 /: Then for each < !1 , the elementary embedding j lifts to an elementary embedding jO W LŒt0 Œg0 \ Coll.!; <0 / ! LŒt0 Œg \ Coll.!; < /: Thus (2.1) p j.! / 2 g, (2.2) q j.! / 2 g, (2.3) p “˛ 2 Ig .0 /”, (2.4) q “˛ … Ig .0 /”.
260
5 Applications
Let T D ¹˛C1 j < !1 º: For each < !1 let
F t0
be the set of filters h Coll.!; < /
such that h is LŒt0 -generic. For each h 2 F t0 and for each ˛ < let S˛h D ¹ˇ j for some p 2 h; p.0; ˇ/ D ˛º: Similarly for each h 2 F t0 let Ih .0 / D ¹˛ < j .˛; p/ 2 h for some p 2 hº: Suppose g 2 F t0 . Then for each < !1 , Ih .0 / D Ig .0 / \ and for each ˛ < , S˛h D S˛g \ where h D g \ Coll.!; < /. Define a function W 2
2 S˛ .s/
where ˛ is such that 2 S˛g0 , (3.5) if ˛C1 2 dom.s/ then pC1 2 .s/ if s.˛C1 / D 1; and qC1 2 .s/ if s.˛C1 / D 0: By the remarks above involving the embeddings j , the requirements (3.4) and (3.5) do not interfere. Define W 2
5.7 The Axiom
261
Suppose F 2 2!1 and let g D [¹.F j / j < !1 º: For each < !1 , .F j / 2 F t0 and so g is LŒt0 -generic. For each ˛ < !1 , S˛g M S˛g0 2 INS and so for each ˛ < !1 , S˛g is stationary. Therefore Ig .0 / 2 X . Finally Ig .0 / D [¹.F j˛/ j ˛ < !1 º t u
and so is as desired.
Remark 5.84. Thus subsets of 2!1 which are definable in L.R/Pmax are either in L.R/ t u or contain copies of 2!1 . The reformulation of ./ as taken together with the results of Chapter 4 strongly suggests that, assuming ./, one should be able to analyze sets X P .!1 / which are definable in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i by a …1 formula. We explore the possibilities for classifying specific definable subsets of P .!1 /. For this we assume that the axiom ./ holds and we focus on attempting to classify partitions W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º for which there is no homogeneous rectangle for 0, of (proper) cardinality @1 . Here we adopt the convention that if Z D A B !1 !1 is a rectangle, then Z has proper cardinality @1 if both A and B have cardinality @1 . This is related to the following variation of a question of S. Todorcevic. Is it consistent that for any partition W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º; either there is a homogeneous rectangle for for 0, of (proper) cardinality @1 , or there is no such homogeneous rectangle in any generic extension of V which preserves !1 ?
262
5 Applications
Remark 5.85.
(1) Suppose that W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º;
and for each ˛ < !1 define B˛ D ¹ˇ < !1 j .˛; ˇ/ D 0º: The partition has a homogeneous rectangle of (proper) cardinality @1 if and only if there exists a countably complete, uniform, filter F P .!1 / such that j¹˛ < !1 j B˛ 2 F or !1 n B˛ 2 F ºj D @1 ; similarly the partition has a homogeneous rectangle for 0 of (proper) cardinality @1 if and only if there exists a countably complete, uniform, filter F P .!1 / such that j¹˛ < !1 j B˛ 2 F ºj D @1 : Thus one is really attempting to classify the sequences hB˛ W ˛ < !1 i of subsets of !1 for which there exists a uniform countably complete filter on !1 which contains uncountably many of the sets. (2) The problem of whether it consistent for every partition W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º to have a homogeneous rectangle of (proper) cardinality @1 , has been solved negatively Moore .2006/. t u We fix some more notation. Suppose a 2 H.!1 / and that L.a/ ZFC: Let D jcj
L.a/
where c is the transitive closure of a, Then M3 .a/ D .H.j jC //L.Q3 .a// :
Let b be a set in L.a/ which codes a. One can show that M3 .a/ is precisely the set of all sets, c, which can be coded by a set z such that z 2 Q3 .b/. 1 Definition 5.86 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that
W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º: (1) Suppose that X !1 . Let E .3/ ŒX be the set of < !1 such that there exists Z1 Z2 such that
5.7 The Axiom
263
a) Z1 and Z2 each have ordertype , b) .˛; ˇ/ D 0 for all .˛; ˇ/ 2 Z1 Z2 with ˛ < ˇ, c) Q3 .Z1 Z2 .X \ / jŒ2 / ¤ ;, d) M3 .Z1 Z2 .X \ / jŒ2 / D !1 . (2) Suppose that X !1 and that A D hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of stationary subsets of !1 such that for each ˛ < !1 , S˛ 2 LŒX : Let E .3/ ŒX; A be the set of < !1 such that there exists Z1 Z2 such that a) Z1 and Z2 each have ordertype , b) .˛; ˇ/ D 0 for all .˛; ˇ/ 2 Z1 Z2 with ˛ < ˇ, c) Q3 .a/ ¤ ;, d) M3 .a/ D !1 , e) for each ˛ < , S˛ \ 2 M3 .a/ and S˛ \ is a stationary set within M3 .a/, where a D Z1 Z2 .X \ / jŒ2 :
t u
Assume there exists a Woodin cardinal with a measurable cardinal above. Then 1 by .Martin and Steel 1989/, 2 -Determinacy holds and so Definition 5.86 applies. If the partition given by has a homogeneous rectangle for 0, of (proper) cardinality @1 , then necessarily E .3/ ŒX; A contains a club in !1 . Another trivial observation is that if for some .X; A/ the set E .3/ ŒX; A is nonstationary then there exists Y !1 such that E .3/ ŒY; A D ;: With the notation as above we have the following lemma. Lemma 5.87. Assume there is a Woodin cardinal with a measurable above. Then (1) E .3/ ŒX contains a closed unbounded set or E .3/ ŒX is nonstationary, (2) E .3/ ŒX; A contains a closed unbounded set or E .3/ ŒX; A is nonstationary.
264
5 Applications
Proof. We prove (1), the proof of (2) is similar. Suppose E .3/ ŒX is stationary. We show that E .3/ ŒX contains a closed unbounded set. Let ı be a Woodin cardinal and let S ı be a set such that Vı 2 LŒS #
and such that S exists. By the hypothesis of the lemma, ı and S exist. Let N D LŒS : Let Y N be a countable elementary substructure containing infinitely many Silver indiscernibles of N . We prove that Y \ !1 2 E .3/ ŒX : Let NY be the transitive collapse of Y . Let SY be the image of S under the collapsing map and let ıY be the image of ı. Let ˛ D NY \ Ord. Thus NY “ıY is a Woodin cardinal” and NY D L˛ ŒSY : Since Y contains infinitely many indiscernibles of N , L˛ ŒSY LŒSY : The key points are that .E .3/ ŒXY /NY D E .3/ ŒX \ Y \ !1 Y and that ŒXY is stationary”; NY “E .3/ Y where XY and Y are the images of X and under the collapsing map. By elementarity, .E .3/ ŒXY /LŒSY D E .3/ ŒX \ Y \ !1 Y and ŒXY is stationary”: LŒSY “E .3/ Y Let a D .E .3/ ŒXY /LŒSY and let D !1LŒSY D Y \ !1 . Y Let G .Q<ıY /LŒSY be an LŒSY -generic filter for the stationary tower such that a 2 G.
5.7 The Axiom
Let
265
j W LŒSY ! LŒSY
be the induced elementary embedding. Since ıY is a Woodin cardinal in LŒSY , the generic ultrapower is wellfounded, since a 2 G, 2 j.a/: Further j.Y /jŒ2 D jŒ2 and similarly j.XY / \ D X \ . Therefore there exists Z 1 Z2 such that (1.1) Z1 and Z2 each have ordertype , (1.2) .Z1 ; Z2 / 2 LŒSY , (1.3) j.Y /.˛0 ; ˛1 / D 0 for all .˛0 ; ˛1 / 2 Z1 Z2 with ˛0 < ˛1 ,
(1.4) .M3 .Z jŒ2 .X \ ///LŒSY “ D !1 ”. However LŒSY is a transitive inner model containing the ordinals and so it follows that for each transitive set b 2 .H.!1 //LŒSY ; such that L.b/ ZFC,
M3 .b/ .M3 .b//LŒSY : Therefore the set Z1 Z2 witnesses that 2 E .3/ ŒX and so Y \ !1 2 E .3/ ŒX . This proves (1).
t u
Theorem 5.88. Assume ./. Suppose that A !1 . Then there exists a transitive inner model M containing the ordinals and the set A such that M ZFC C “There exist ! many Woodin cardinals”: Proof. We sketch the argument. We require the following strengthening of Theorem 5.73(5). For each x 2 R let Nx D HODxL.R/ : Suppose A !1 . Then there exist x 2 R and G Coll.!;
266
5 Applications
We prove this. By Theorem 5.67, L.P .!1 //
:
Let X be the set of A !1 for which x and G do not exist satisfying (1.1) and (1.2). By there exist t 2 R and 2 LŒt such that (2.1) !1 Coll.!;
t u
5.7 The Axiom
267
Theorem 5.89. Assume ./. Suppose that W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º; X !1 and that A D hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of stationary subsets of !1 . Then (1) E .3/ ŒX contains a closed unbounded set or E .3/ ŒX is nonstationary, (2) E .3/ ŒX; A contains a closed unbounded set or E .3/ ŒX; A is nonstationary. u t Lemma 5.90 is in essence just Theorem 4.67 adapted to our current context. Lemma 5.90. Assume ./. Suppose W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º is a partition with no homogeneous rectangle for 0 of .proper/ cardinality @1 . Then there exist X !1 and a sequence A D hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i of stationary sets such that A 2 LŒX and such that E .3/ ŒX; A D ;: Proof. Fix a filter G Pmax such that G is L.R/-generic. Let h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G be such that 0 2 M0 and such that j0;!1 .0 / D where h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i is the unique iteration such that j0;!1 .a0 / D AG and 0 D jŒ!1M0 2 : By Theorem 4.67 we can suppose that for all countable iterations, j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M; I / if N is a countable, transitive, model of ZFC such that; (1.1) .P .!1 //M N , (1.2) !1N D !1M , (1.3) Q3 .S / N , for each S 2 N such that S !1N , (1.4) if S !1N , S 2 M and if S … I then S is a stationary set in N ,
268
5 Applications
then N “ j.0 / has no homogeneous rectangle for 0, of (proper) cardinality @1 ”. Let A D hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i be an enumeration of .P .!1 //M!1 n I!1 : Since I!1 D INS \ M!1 ; for each ˛ < !1 , S˛ is a stationary subset of !1 . Let X !1 be a set which codes M!1 . Suppose Y H.!2 / is a countable elementary substructure with h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i 2 Y and let D Y \ !1 . Then
¹S˛ \ j ˛ < º D .P .!1 //M n I
and X \ codes M . Suppose that N is a countable transitive model of ZFC such that !1N D and such that X \ 2 N . Then .P .!1 //M N : Therefore by the choice of h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i, … E .3/ ŒX; A and so E .3/ ŒX; A D ;.
t u
There is a version of Lemma 5.90 for dealing with the existence of homogeneous sets for partitions W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º: This requires the obvious adaptation of Definition 5.86. 1 Definition 5.91 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that
W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º: (1) Suppose that X !1 . Let F .3/ ŒX be the set of < !1 such that there exists Z such that a) Z has ordertype , b) .˛; ˇ/ D 0 for all .˛; ˇ/ 2 Z Z with ˛ < ˇ, c) Q3 .Z .X \ / jŒ2 / ¤ ;, d) M3 .Z .X \ / jŒ2 / D !1 .
5.7 The Axiom
269
(2) Suppose that X !1 and that A D hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of stationary subsets of !1 such that for each ˛ < !1 , S˛ 2 LŒX : Let F .3/ ŒX; A be the set of < !1 such that there exists Z such that a) b) c) d) e)
Z has ordertype , .˛; ˇ/ D 0 for all .˛; ˇ/ 2 Z Z with ˛ < ˇ, Q3 .a/ ¤ ;, M3 .a/ D !1 , for each ˛ < , S˛ \ 2 M3 .a/ and S˛ \ is a stationary set within M3 .a/,
where a D Z .X \ / jŒ2 :
t u
The proof of Lemma 5.90 is easily modified to yield a proof of Lemma 5.92. Assume ./. Suppose W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º is a partition with no homogeneous set for 0 of cardinality @1 . Then there exist X !1 and a sequence A D hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i of stationary sets such that A 2 LŒX and such that F .3/ ŒX; A D ;: u t For the problem of finding homogeneous sets, Lemma 5.92 is essentially the strongest possible result. This is a consequence of the following theorem of Todorcevic. Theorem 5.93 (Todorcevic). Assume ./ and suppose S !1 is a stationary, costationary, subset of !1 . Then there exists a partition W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º such that: (1) F O.3/ Œ; D ;; (2) For all X !1 , F .3/ ŒX is contains a closed unbounded set; (3) Let A D hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i be any sequence of stationary sets which contains S , then F .3/ ŒX; A is nonstationary; where O W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º is the partition; .˛; O ˇ/ D 0 if and only if .˛; ˇ/ D 1.
t u
270
5 Applications
Remark 5.94. Todorcevic’s theorem is actually stronger, Theorem 5.93 is simply the version relevant to our discussion. Note that Theorem 5.93(1) asserts in effect that t u cannot have a homogeneous set of cardinality @1 for 1. By combining Theorem 5.67 and Lemma 5.90 we obtain the next theorem. Suppose g Coll.!;
g Coll.!;
if g is LŒt -generic and if
¹S˛g j ˛ < !1 º P .!1 / n INS ; then a) W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º, b) E .3/ ŒX ; Ag D ;,
where D Ig . / and where X !1 is such that LŒt Œg D LŒX :
5.7 The Axiom
271
Proof. Assuming , this follows easily from Lemma 5.90. By Theorem 5.67, u t holds in L.P .!1 //. The key question is the following. Assume ./. Suppose
W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º
is a partition with no homogeneous rectangle for 0 of (proper) cardinality @1 . Must there exist a set X !1 such that E .3/ ŒX D ;? The point here is the following. By Lemma 5.90, if W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º is a partition with no homogeneous rectangle for 0 of (proper) cardinality @1 , and if ./ holds, then the nonexistence of the homogeneous rectangle is coupled to the stationarity of certain subsets of !1 . The question we are asking is if this is really possible, perhaps the nonexistence of the homogeneous rectangle can only be coupled to the preservation of !1 as is the case in all of the currently known examples (assuming ./). In contrast to the situation concerning homogeneous rectangles, is that of the existence of homogeneous sets. Todorcevic has proved that given a stationary set S !1 there exists a partition S W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º such that if V ŒG is a set generic extension of V such that !1V D !1V ŒG , V ŒG PFA.c/, then in V ŒG: (1) The partition S has no homogeneous set for 1 which is of cardinality !1 ; (2) The partition S has a homogeneous set for 0 of cardinality !1 if and only if the set S is nonstationary. The requirement, V ŒG PFA.c/; can be weakened substantially. It is a version of this theorem which we state as Theorem 5.93. If the answer to the question stated above is yes, then the hypothesis of the next theorem, Theorem 5.96, can be reduced to the hypothesis of Theorem 5.95 giving a strong version of Lemma 5.90. The key difference in the statement of this theorem is that all LŒt -generic filters are allowed, the requirement that the sets S˛g each be stationary is not necessary.
272
5 Applications
Theorem 5.96. Assume ./. Suppose W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º is a partition such that for some X !1 , E .3/ ŒX D ;: Then there exist t !, L!1 Coll.!;
g Coll.!;
if g is LŒt -generic then a) W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º, b) E .3/ ŒX D ;,
where D Ig . / and where X !1 is such that LŒt Œg D LŒX : Proof. The theorem is a straightforward consequence of
in L.P .!1 //.
t u
The connection with the question of Todorcevic is given in the Theorem 5.97 and Theorem 5.98 below. We state these without giving the proofs for they require some additional machinery which is beyond the scope of this presentation, particularly in the case of Theorem 5.98. The proof of Theorem 5.97 is completely straightforward given that (in the notation of the theorem) .E .3/ ŒX /V D .E .3/ ŒX /V ŒZ which is true by an absoluteness argument. The proof of Theorem 5.98 requires some inner model theory and genericity iterations. Theorem 5.97. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal, there is a measurable cardinal above ı, and that W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º: Suppose Z1 !1 and Z2 !1 are cofinal sets such that
5.7 The Axiom
273
(i) .Z1 ; Z2 / is V -generic for a partial order P 2 Vı , (ii) .¹˛; ˇº/ D 0 for all .˛; ˇ/ 2 Z1 Z2 such that ˛ < ˇ, (iii) !1V ŒZ1 ;Z2 D !1V . Then in V , for all X !1 , E .3/ ŒX is stationary.
t u
Theorem 5.98. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal, there is a measurable cardinal above ı, and that W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º: Suppose that for all X !1 , E .3/ ŒX is stationary. Then for each ˛ < ı there exists a transitive inner model N and a partial order P 2 N such that the following hold. (1) Ord N . (2) N ZFC C ı is a Woodin cardinal. (3) V˛ 2 N . (4) Suppose G P is N -generic. Then !1 D !1N ŒG and there exist cofinal sets Z1 !1 and Z2 !1 such that .Z1 ; Z2 / 2 N ŒG and such that .¹˛; ˇº/ D 0 for all .˛; ˇ/ 2 Z1 Z2 such that ˛ < ˇ.
t u
In Chapter 7 we shall consider Pmax -extensions of inner models other than L.R/; i. e. inner models satisfying stronger determinacy hypotheses. Using these results one can show, for example, that if ZFC C “There are ! 2 many Woodin cardinals ” is consistent then ZFC C
C “There are ! 2 many Woodin cardinals ”
is consistent. In particular it is consistent for ./ to hold and for there to exist a Woodin cardinal with a measurable above. Therefore by Theorem 5.97 if ./ implies that for all partitions W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º either there is a homogeneous rectangle for 0 of (proper) cardinality !1 or there exists a set X !1 such that E .3/ ŒX is nonstationary, then the answer to Todorcevic’s question is yes.
274
5 Applications
Remark 5.99. (1) There is no evidence to date that Todorcevic’s question involves large cardinals at all. (2) One can define other versions of E .3/ ŒX . For example define E .1/ ŒX modifying the definition of E .3/ ŒX by replacing M3 .a/ by M1 .a/ where for each transitive set a 2 H.!1 /, M1 .a/ D L .a/ where is the least ordinal such that L .a/ is admissible. E .2/ ŒX is defined using M2 .a/ D LŒa: (3) Assume ./. Suppose W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º is a partition such that for some X !1 , E .3/ ŒX is nonstationary. Is E .2/ ŒX nonstationary for some X !1 ? Is E .1/ ŒX nonstationary for some X !1 ?
5.8
t u
Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
Assume ./ holds. We shall show in Section 6.1 that it does not necessarily follow that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated in V . This suggests that the structure of the quotient algebra P .!1 /=INS is necessarily somewhat complicated. The following lemma, which is well known, shows that assuming MA!1 , if I is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 which is !2 -saturated then the boolean algebra, P .!1 /=I is rigid. Lemma 5.100 (MA!1 ). Suppose that I0 ; I1 are are normal, uniform, saturated ideals on !1 and that G0 .P .!1 / n I0 ; / is V -generic. Suppose that G1 .P .!1 / n I1 ; / is a V -generic filter such that G1 2 V ŒG0 . Then G0 D G1 .
5.8 Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
275
Proof. Fix a sequence h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i of (infinite) pairwise almost disjoint subsets of !. For each set A !1 , let †A be the set of all ! such that A D ¹˛ < !1 j \ ˛ is infiniteº: Since MA!1 holds, for each A !1 , †A ¤ ; Let j0 W V ! M0 V ŒG0 be the generic elementary embedding corresponding to the generic ultrapower given by G0 and let j1 W V ! M1 V ŒG1 be the generic elementary embedding corresponding to G1 . Thus RV ŒG0 M0 and G1 2 V ŒG0 . Let D ! V where 1
h˛ W ˛ < !1M1 i D j1 .h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i/: Thus, by the elementarity of j1 , for all A !1V , with A 2 V , and for all 2 †A , A 2 G1 if and only if \ is infinite. However 2 M0 since RV ŒG0 M0 and G1 2 V ŒG0 . Let f 2 V be a function such that j0 .f /.!1V / D ; i. e. a function that represents . We can suppose that for all ˛ < !1V , f .˛/ ! and that f .˛/ is infinite. Thus for all A 2 P .!1 /V , and for all 2 †A , A 2 G1 if and only if ¹˛ j f .˛/ \ is infiniteº 2 G0 : We work in V . Let Z D ¹[¹ ˛ j ˛ 2 sº j s 2 Œ!1
a0 \ ˇ
276
5 Applications
We return to V ŒG0 . If B0 2 G0 then ; 2 G1 since a0 2 †; , and so C0 2 G0 . Again we work in V . Define W C0 ! Œ!1
¹ˇ < !1 j f .˛/ \ ˇ is infiniteº
is finite and so .˛/ 2 Œ!1
5.8 Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
277
Thus there exists an elementary embedding k0 W M1 ! M0 such that j0 D k0 ı j1 . But j1 .!1V / D !2V D j0 .!1V / and so k0 must be the identity. Therefore j0 D j1 and so G0 D G1 .
t u
A natural reformulation of Lemma 5.100 is given in the following corollary. Corollary 5.101 (MA!1 ). Suppose that I is a normal, uniform, saturated ideal on !1 and that G .P .!1 / n I; / is V -generic. Suppose that U 2 V ŒG is a normal, uniform, V -ultrafilter on !1V . Then U D G: Proof. Let be a term for U and fix a set S 2 G such that S “ is a normal, uniform, V -ultrafilter”: Working in V , define J D ¹T !1 j S “T … ”º: Thus in V , J is a normal, uniform ideal on !1 . Since .P .!1 / n I; / is !2 -cc, J is a saturated ideal. Thus U .P .!1 / n J; / and U is V -generic. By Lemma 5.100, U D G:
t u
By Corollary 5.101, if ./ holds then P .!1 /=INS is not homogeneous. In this section we show that if ./ holds then the boolean algebra P .!1 /=INS has a property which approximates homogeneity. This we define below. A key point is that this property can be proved just assuming , which is how we shall proceed.
278
5 Applications
Definition 5.102. Suppose I is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 . The ideal I is quasihomogeneous if the following holds. Suppose that X0 P .!1 / is ordinal definable with parameters from ¹I º [ R. Suppose that there exists A0 2 X0 such that ¹A0 ; !1 n A0 º \ I D ;: Then for all A 2 P .!1 / n I if !1 n A … I there exists B 2 X0 such that A M B 2 I:
t u
Remark 5.103. (1) The condition that an ideal I is quasi-homogeneous is a very strong one, particularly when the ideal is also saturated. We note the following consequence. Suppose that G P .!1 / n I is V -generic and let j W V ! M V ŒG be the associated generic elementary embedding. Suppose that B Ord and that B is ordinal definable in V . Then for each ordinal ˛, j jL˛ ŒB 2 V: (2) It is easily seen that if I is a normal !1 dense ideal on !1 then the ideal I is not necessarily quasi-homogeneous. Combining the constructions of Qmax and M Qmax which are given in Section 6.2.1 and in Section 6.2.6, respectively, one can construct a partial order Q 2 L.R/ such that if AD holds in L.R/ and if GQ is L.R/-generic then L.R/ŒG ZFC C “V D L.P .!1 //”; and in L.R/ŒG the following hold. a) INS is !1 dense. b) INS is not quasi-homogeneous.
t u
A key consequence of the existence of a quasi-homogeneous saturated ideal is given in the following theorem. This seems to be the simplest route to establishing that implies ADL.R/ , see Remark 5.111. Nevertheless the proof requires the core model induction and so is beyond the scope of this book. Theorem 5.104. Suppose that I is a saturated, normal, ideal on !1 and that I is quasi-homogeneous. Then L.R/ AD: t u The first step in showing that implies ./ is to establish that implies that INS is quasi-homogeneous.
5.8 Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
Theorem 5.105.
279
The nonstationary ideal on !1 is quasi-homogeneous.
Proof. The theorem follows from the following claim which is an immediate corollary of Lemma 4.36. Suppose .M; I / is iterable, b !1M , b 2 M, b … I and that !1M n b … I . Suppose S !1 is stationary and co-stationary. Then there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / of .M; I / of length !1 such that C \ S D C \ j.b/ for some club C !1 and such that for all d !1 , if d 2 M n I then d is stationary. Suppose that X0 P .!1 / n INS and that X0 is ordinal definable from x where x 2 R. We suppose that X0 is nonempty and that for all A 2 X0 , A is co-stationary. Let Z0 be the set of pairs .t; / such that (1.1) t 2 R, !1 Coll.!;
h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i Pmax AG 2
where is the term for the subset of P .!1 / given by Z0 . Suppose S !1 is stationary and co-stationary. By the claim above there exists an iteration j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / of .M0 ; I0 / of length !1 such that
280
5 Applications
(2.1) C \ S D C \ j0 .a0 / for some club C !1 , (2.2) I0 D M0 \ INS . Let A1 D j0 .a0 /. Thus A1 is stationary and co-stationary. Again by Theorem 5.81, there is a filter G1 Pmax such that G1 is HODR -generic and such that HODP .!1 / D HODR ŒG1 and such that A1 D AG1 . The embedding, j0 , witnesses that h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G1 and so HODR ŒG1 AG1 2 XG1 ; where XG1 is the interpretation of by G1 . However AG1 D A1 and X G1 X0 ; and so A1 2 X0 . Finally by (2.1) and (2.2), S M A1 2 INS ; and this proves the theorem.
t u
Remark 5.106. An immediate corollary of Theorem 5.105 and Theorem 5.67 is that assuming ./, the nonstationary ideal is quasi-homogeneous in L.P .!1 //. This shows that MA!1 is consistent with the existence of a saturated ideal on !1 which is quasi-homogeneous. In Chapter 7, we shall improve this result, replacing t u MA!1 by Martin’s MaximumCC .c/. By Theorem 4.49, the basic analysis of the Pmax extension can be carried out just assuming that for each set B R such that B 2 L.R/, there exists a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (1) B \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; B \ Mi hH.!1 /; Bi, (3) .M; I / is B-iterable. We now prove that this in fact holds, assuming . Our goal is to show that assum ing , the nonstationary ideal is saturated in L.P .!1 //. By Theorem 5.104 it will follow that implies ADL.R/ . We first prove that the conclusion of Lemma 4.52 follows from .
5.8 Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
Lemma 5.107. Assume
281
. Suppose B R and B 2 HODR . Then the set
¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. By Theorem 5.81, there exists a filter G Pmax such that G is HODR -generic and such that P .!1 / D P .!1 /G : The lemma is a straightforward consequence of this fact. This is more transparent if one reformulates it as follows. Let H.!2 /G D [¹H.!2 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº where for each h.M; I /; ai 2 G, j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the (unique) iteration such that j.a/ D AG . Since P .!1 / D P .!1 /G ; it follows easily that H.!2 / D H.!2 /G : We now fix G. Let F W H.!2 /
282
5 Applications
Since !1 N0 , for each k < !, Nk is transitive. Since H.!2 /G D H.!2 /; there exist sequences hh.Mk ; Ik /; ak i W k < !i; hbk W k < !i; and htk W k < !i such that for all k < !, (2.1) h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i 2 G \ NkC1 \ X , (2.2) h.MkC1 ; IkC1 /; akC1 i < h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i, (2.3) bk 2 Mk , (2.4) for all p 2 Zk \ Pmax , h.MkC1 ; IkC1 /; akC1 i < p; (2.5) jk .bk / D Nk , (2.6) jk .tk / D sk , where Zk is the closure of ¹bk º under F and where jk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik / is the iteration such that jk .ak / D AG . For each k < ! let Xk D jk Œbk D ¹jk .c/ j c 2 bk º: Thus for each k < !, Xk X and further X D [¹Xk j k < !º: We note that for each k < !, since jk .bk / D Nk , jk .B \ bk / D B \ Nk : For each k < ! and let Dk be the set of h.M; I /; ai < h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i such that
j .B \ bk / D B \ j .bk /
and such that for all countable iterations j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
5.8 Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
283
it is the case that j.B \ j .bk // D B \ j.j .bk //, where j W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik / is the iteration such that j .ak / D a. We claim that for each k 2 ! there exists q 2 G such that ¹p < q j p 2 Pmax º Dk : Assume toward a contradiction that this fails for k. Then for all q 2 G there exists p 2 G such that p < q and p … Dk . However G is HODR -generic and so there must exist h.M; I /; ai 2 G and an iteration
j W .M; I / ! .M0 ; I 0 /
such that (3.1) h.M; I /; ai < h.Mk ; Ik /; ak i, (3.2) j.B \ j .bk // ¤ B \ j.j .bk // where j W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik / is the iteration such that j .ak / D a, (3.3) h.M0 ; I 0 /; a0 i 2 G where a0 D j.a/. But this contradicts the fact that jk .B \ bk / D B \ Nk . Therefore for each k < ! there exists qk 2 G such that ¹p < qk j p 2 Pmax º Dk : Note that Dk is definable in the structure hH.!2 /; B; G; 2i from bk . Therefore we can suppose that qk 2 Zk , for such a condition must exist in Zk . This implies that h.MkC1 ; IkC1 /; akC1 i 2 Dk : For each k < n < !, let jk;n W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mkn ; Ikn / be the iteration such that jk;n .ak / D an and let jk;! W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk! ; Ik! / be the iteration such that jk;! .ak / D [¹an j n < !º:
284
5 Applications
Thus for all k < !, ! Mk! 2 MkC1 :
The key points are that MX D [¹Mk! j k < !º D [¹jk;! .bk / j k < !º: and that for each k < !, jk;! .bk / D NkX where NkX is the image of Nk under the collapsing map. These identities are easily verified from the definitions. Finally suppose jO W MX ! MO X is a countable iteration. For each k < !,
! ! ; IkC1 // jO..MkC1
is an iterate of .MkC1 ; IkC1 /. Further for each k < !, h.MkC1 ; IkC1 /; akC1 i 2 Dk : Therefore for each k < !, jO.B \ NkX / D jO.jkC1;! .B \ jk;kC1 .bk /// D B \ jO.jkC1;! .jk;kC1 .bk /// D B \ jO.NkX /: X However for each k < !, NkX is transitive and NkX 2 NkC1 . Therefore
MO X D [¹jO.NkX / j k < !º and so
jO.B \ MX / D B \ MO X : t u
Therefore MX is B-iterable. As a corollary to Lemma 5.107 we obtain that of Pmax . Theorem 5.108. Assume
implies the requisite nontriviality
. Suppose B R and that B 2 HODR . Then there exists h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax
such that (1) B \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; B \ Mi hH.!1 /; Bi, (3) .M; I / is B-iterable.
5.8 Homogeneity properties of P .!1 /=INS
285
Proof. Fix G Pmax such that G is HODR -generic and such that P .!1 /G D P .!1 /: Suppose 2 Ord,
L .B; R/ŒG ZFC ;
and that < ‚L.B;R/ : By Corollary 5.80, L .B; R/ŒG MA!1 : Let A R be such that A 2 HODR and such that < ı 11 .A/: By Lemma 5.107, there exists a countable elementary substructure X H.!2 / such that hX; A \ X; 2i hH.!2 /; A; 2i and such that the transitive collapse of X is A-iterable. Therefore by Lemma 4.24, there exists a countable elementary substructure Y L .B; R/ŒG such that ¹B; AG º Y and such that MY is strongly iterable where MY is the transitive collapse of Y . Since B 2 Y , it follows by Theorem 3.34, that H.!2 /MY (which is the transitive collapse of Y \ H.!2 /) is B-iterable. MY . Thus the structure .MY ; IY / is B-iterable. Let a be the image of Let IY D INS AG under the collapsing map. Thus h.MY ; IY /; ai 2 Pmax t u
and is as required. Corollary 5.109. Assume
. Then
(1) L.P .!1 // ZFC, (2) INS is saturated in L.P .!1 //. Proof. By Theorem 5.108, Theorem 5.81, and Lemma 5.5, H.!2 / AC and so (1) follows. Similarly (2) follows from Theorem 5.108, Theorem 5.81 and Theorem 4.49.
t u
Combining Theorem 5.104, Theorem 5.105 and Corollary 5.109(2), yields the equivalence of ./ and the assertion that holds in L.P .!1 //.
286
5 Applications
Theorem 5.110. The following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) L.P .!1 //
.
t u
Remark 5.111. In fact the proof that: (1) For each set A R with A 2 L.R/ there exists h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that .M; I / is A-iterable; (2) There is a normal (uniform) saturated ideal on !1 which is quasi-homogeneous; together imply ADL.R/ is somewhat simpler than the proof of Theorem 5.104.
t u
Chapter 6
Pmax variations In this chapter we define several variations of Pmax . These yield models which, like those defined in the next chapter, are conditional versions of the Pmax -extension. The models obtained in this chapter condition the Pmax -extension by varying the structure, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i; relative to which the absoluteness theorems are proved. One of these is the Qmax -extension which we shall define in Section 6.2.1. This extension has two interpretations as a conditional extension. By modifying the structure, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i; the Qmax -extension is the Pmax -extension conditioned on a form of ˘. A very interesting feature of the Qmax -extension is that in it the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. Further it also can be interpreted as the Pmax -extension conditioned by this, i. e. the Qmax -extension realizes every …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i which is (suitably) consistent with proposition that the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense. CH fails in the Qmax -extension so we also obtain as a corollary consistency of an !1 -dense ideal on !1 together with :CH. Finally the Qmax -extension is a generic extension of L.R/ and ADL.R/ is sufficient to prove things work. This substantially lowers the upper bound for the consistency strength of the existence of an !1 -dense ideal on !1 and in fact provides the optimal upper bound, the two theories are equiconsistent. Previous unpublished results of Woodin required the consistency of the existence of an almost huge cardinal or the consistency of ZF C ADR C “‚ is regular”; see Foreman .2010/ for a survey of results related to saturated ideals and generic elementary embeddings. There is an important difference in the results here. The previous methods produced models in which there is an !1 -dense ideal on !1 and in which CH holds. In the context of CH the consistency of the existence of an !1 -dense ideal on !1 is quite strong, much stronger than that of AD. This provides an example of a combinatorial proposition whose consistency strength varies depending on whether one requires that CH holds. We also prove that the existence of an !1 -dense ideal on !1 implies that there is a nonregular ultrafilter on !1 without assuming CH, this is a theorem of Huberich .1996/. Combining these results also gives a new upper bound for the consistency strength of the existence of a nonregular ultrafilter on !1 .
288
6 Pmax variations
6.1
2
Pmax
The nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated in L.R/Pmax . Suppose that L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG where G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Does it follow that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated (in V )? We define another variation on Pmax in order to answer this question. With this variation we can maximize the …2 sentences true in the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; J; 2i where J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 and J is not the nonstationary ideal. The analysis of the 2 Pmax -extension yields an interesting combinatorial fact true in the Pmax -extension. One version of this is given in Lemma 6.2 which is an immediate corollary of Lemma 6.16. These lemmas concern a certain partial order which we define below. We fix some notation. Suppose that I is a uniform, normal, ideal on !1 and that S !1 is a set such that !1 n S … I: We let I _ S denote the normal ideal generated by I [ ¹S º. It is easily verified that I _ S D ¹T !1 j T \ .!1 n S / 2 I º: We define a partial order PNS which is the natural choice for creating, by forcing, a nontrivial normal ideal J such that J ¤ INS _ S for any S !1 . Definition 6.1. Let PNS be the partial order defined as follows. Conditions are pairs .X; S / such that (1) X P .!1 /, (2) jX j !1 , (3) S and !1 n S are stationary. The order is given by .X1 ; S1 / .X0 ; S0 / if X0 X1 , S0 S1 and if .INS _ S1 / \ X0 D .INS _ S0 / \ X0 :
t u
Suppose G PNS is V -generic. Let IG D ¹S j .;; S / 2 Gº: If PNS is .!1 ; 1/-distributive then IG is a normal ideal on !1 . If G … V , i. e. if G contains no elements which define atoms in RO.PNS /, then IG ¤ INS _ S for any S !1 . It is easily verified that if .X; S / 2 PNS then .X; S / defines an atom in RO.PNS / if and only if the set, ¹.T n S / n A j T 2 X; A 2 INS º n INS ; is dense in the partial order, .P .!1 n S / n INS ; /.
6.1
2P
max
289
Lemma 6.2. Assume ./. (1) The partial order, PNS , is .!1 ; 1/-distributive in L.P .!1 //. (2) Suppose G PNS is L.P .!1 //-generic. Then IG is a normal saturated ideal in L.P .!1 //ŒG and IG ¤ INS _ S for any set S !1 . t u
Proof. See Theorem 6.17.
This shows that in L.R/Pmax the quotient algebra P .!1 /=INS is not absolutely saturated and it answers the question above. The point here is that if the nonstationary ideal is saturated then every normal ideal on !1 is of the form INS _ S for some S !1 . Remark 6.3. It may seem strange that PNS could ever be nontrivial and yet be .!1 ; 1/distributive, or more generally that by forcing with an .!1 ; 1/-distributive partial order it is possible to create a saturated ideal on !1 . However suppose that P .!1 /=INS Š RO.B Coll.!; !1 // where B is a complete boolean algebra which is .!1 ; 1/-distributive and !2 -cc. Then it is not difficult to show that RO.PNS / Š B: Further if G PNS is V -generic then in V ŒG, P .!1 /=IG Š RO.Coll.!; !1 //I i. e. in V ŒG, IG is an !1 -dense ideal. One can show it is relatively consistent P .!1 /=INS Š RO.B Coll.!; !1 // where B is a complete, nonatomic, boolean algebra which, as above, is !2 -cc and .!1 ; 1/-distributive; i. e. where B is the regular open algebra corresponding to a Suslin tree on !2 . This can be proved by constructing a Qmax variation where Qmax is the partial order constructed in Section 6.2.1. However the example indicated in Lemma 6.2 is more subtle. t u Remark 6.4. In Chapter 9 we shall consider the Pmax -extensions of inner models of AD strictly larger than L.R/. We shall prove that if P .R/ is a pointclass such that L.; R/ ADR C “‚ is regular”; then if G Pmax Coll.!2 ; !2 / is L.; R/-generic, L.; R/ŒG ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/: The proof of Lemma 6.2 easily generalizes to show both that
290
6 Pmax variations
L.; R/ŒG “PNS is .!1 ; 1/-distributive”. Suppose H PNS is L.; R/ŒG-generic, then L.; R/ŒGŒH “IH is !2 -saturated”: This shows that Martin’s Maximum.c/ is consistent with the assertion that PNS is .!1 ; 1/-distributive. Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies that !2 has the tree property and so, in L.; R/ŒG, PNS cannot be embedded into P .!1 /=INS . Recall that !2 has the tree property if every .!2 ; !2 / tree of rank !2 has a (rank) cofinal branch. t u Definition 6.5. Let 2 Pmax be the set of pairs h.M; I; J /; ai such that: (1) M is a countable transitive model of ZFC C MA!1 ; (2) M “ I; J are normal uniform ideals on !1 ”; (3) I J and I ¤ J ; (4) .M; ¹I; J º/ is iterable; (5) a !1M ; (6) a 2 M and M “!1 D !1LŒaŒx for some real x” . The ordering on conditions in 2 Pmax is as follows: h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i if M0 2 M1 ; M0 is countable in M1 and there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ such that: (1) j.a0 / D a1 ; (2) M0 2 M1 , M0 is countable in M1 ; (3) M0 2 M1 and j 2 M1 ; (4) I0 D I1 \ M0 and J0 D J1 \ M0 . The analysis of the partial order that for Pmax .
2
t u
Pmax can be carried out in a fashion similar to
Lemma 6.6 (ZFC ). Suppose that I J are normal uniform ideals on !1 and that I ¤ J . Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i 2 2 Pmax . Then there is an iteration j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ such that j.!1M0 / D !1 , I0 D I \ M0 and J0 D J \ M0 .
6.1
2P
max
291
Proof. The proof is quite similar to the proof of Lemma 4.36, which is the analogous lemma for Pmax . Fix a set X !1 such that X 2 J n I . Fix a sequence hAk;˛ W k < !; ˛ < !1 i of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 such that the following conditions hold. (1.1) If ˛ < !1 is an even ordinal then Ak;˛ X and Ak;˛ is I -positive. (1.2) If ˛ < !1 is an odd ordinal then Ak;˛ !1 n X and Ak;˛ is J -positive. Fix a function
f W ! !1M0 ! M0
such that (2.1) f is onto, (2.2) for all k < !, f jk !1M0 2 M0 , (2.3) for all A 2 M0 if A has cardinality !1M0 in M0 then A ran.f jk !1M0 / for some k < !. The function f is simply used to anticipate subsets of !1 in the final model. Suppose j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ is an iteration. Then we define j .f / D [¹j .f jk !1M / j k < !º and it is easily verified that the range of j .f / is M0 . This follows from (2.3). We construct an iteration of .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ of length !1 using the function f to provide a book-keeping device for all of the subsets of !1 which belong to the final model. More precisely construct an iteration h.Mˇ ; ¹Iˇ ; Jˇ º/; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i such that for each ˛ < !1 , if ˛ is even and if for some < !1 , (3.1) !1M˛ 2 Ak; , (3.2) < !1M˛ , (3.3) j0;˛ .f /.k; / !1M˛ , (3.4) j0;˛ .f /.k; / … I˛ , then G˛ is M˛ -generic for P .!1M˛ / \ M˛ n I˛ and j0;˛ .f /.k; / 2 G˛ . If ˛ is odd and if for some < !1 ,
6 Pmax variations
292
(4.1) !1M˛ 2 Ak; , (4.2) < !1M˛ , (4.3) j0;˛ .f /.k; / !1M˛ , (4.4) j0;˛ .f /.k; / … J˛ , then G˛ is M˛ -generic for P .!1M˛ / \ M˛ n J˛ and j0;˛ .f /.k; / 2 G˛ . The set C D ¹j0;˛ .!1M / j ˛ < !1 º is a club in !1 . Thus for each B !1 such that B 2 M!1 and B … j0;!1 .I0 / there exist k < !; < !1 such that C \Ak; B\Ak; . Further if B !1 , B 2 M!1 and B 2 j0;!1 .I0 / then B \ C D ;. Thus I \ M!1 D I!1 . t u Similarly J \ M!1 D J!1 . The analysis of the 2 Pmax -extension requires the generalization of Lemma 6.6 to sequences of models. The proof of Lemma 6.7 is a straightforward adaptation of the proof of Lemma 6.6. We state this lemma only for the sequences that arise, specifically those sequences of structures coming from descending sequences of conditions in 2 Pmax . There is of course a more general lemma one can prove, but the generality is not necessary and the more general lemma is more cumbersome to state. Suppose that hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in 2 Pmax such that for all k < !, pkC1 < pk : We let hpk W k < !i be the associated sequence of conditions which is defined as follows. For each k < ! let h.Mk ; Ik ; Jk /; ak i D pk and let
jk W .Mk ; ¹Ik ; Jk º/ ! .Mk ; ¹Ik ; Jk º/
be the iteration obtained by combining the iterations given by the conditions pi for i > k. Thus jk is uniquely specified by the requirement that jk .ak / D [¹ai j i < !º: For each k < !
pk D h.Mk ; Ik ; Jk /; ak i:
We note that by Corollary 4.20, the sequence h.Mk ; ¹Ik ; Jk º/ W k < !i is iterable (in the sense of Definition 4.8). Lemma 6.7 (ZFC ). Suppose I J are normal uniform ideals on !1 such that I ¤ J . Suppose hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in 2 Pmax such that for
6.1
2P
max
293
each k < ! pkC1 < pk . Let hpk W k < !i be the associated sequence of 2 Pmax conditions and for each k < !, let h.Mk ; Ik ; Jk /; ak i D pk : Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; ¹Ik ; Jk º/ W k < !i ! h.Mk ; ¹Ik ; Jk º/ W k < !i M
such that j.!1 0 / D !1 and such that for all k < !, Ik D I \ Mk and
Jk D J \ Mk :
Proof. By Corollary 4.20 the sequence h.Mk ; ¹Ik ; Jk º/ W k < !i is iterable. The lemma follows by an argument similar to that used to prove Lemma 6.6.
t u
The next lemmas record some of the relevant properties of the partial order 2 Pmax . First we note that the nontriviality of Pmax immediately gives the nontriviality of 2 Pmax . Lemma 6.8. Assume that for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Then for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I; J /; ai 2 2 Pmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; ¹I; J º/ is X -iterable. Proof. This is immediate by the following observation. Suppose h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax : !1M
Let S be such that S 2 M, S … I , and !1M n S … I . Let J 2 M be the ideal generated by I [ ¹S º. Then h.M; I; J /; ai 2 2 Pmax . The point is that any iteration of .M; ¹I; J º/ is an iteration of .M; I /. t u
294
6 Pmax variations
As a corollary we obtain the following lemma. Lemma 6.9. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose X R and that X 2 L.R/. Then there is a condition h.M; I; J /; ai 2 2 Pmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; ¹I; J º/ is X -iterable. Proof. This is immediate by the previous lemma and Lemma 4.40.
t u
Remark 6.10. The analysis of 2 Pmax can be carried out abstractly just assuming: For each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I; J /; ai 2 2 Pmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; ¹I; J º/ is X -iterable.
t u
Suppose that I is a normal ideal on !1 and that S 2 P .!1 / n I . We let I jS denote the normal ideal generated by I [ ¹!1 n S º. We define an operation on normal ideals. Definition 6.11. Suppose that I is a normal ideal on !1 and that I is not saturated. Let t u sat.I / D ¹S 2 P .!1 / j S 2 I or I jS is a saturated idealº: Lemma 6.12. Suppose that I is a normal ideal on !1 and that I is not saturated. Then sat.I / is a normal ideal on !1 . Proof. This lemma is an elementary consequence of the definition of sat.I /.
t u
Theorem 6.13. Suppose that INS is saturated or that sat.INS / is saturated. Then INS is semi-saturated. Proof. Clearly we may suppose that INS is not saturated and so sat.INS / is saturated. Suppose V ŒG is a generic extension of V and that U 2 V ŒG is a V -normal ultrafilter on !1V . If U .P .!1 / n sat.INS //V
6.1
2P
max
295
then U is V -generic since .sat.INS //V is saturated in V . In this case Ult.V; U / is wellfounded. Therefore we may suppose that U 6 .P .!1 / n sat.INS //V : Thus for some S 2 .P .!1 / n INS /V ; S 2 U and
S 2 .sat.INS //V :
Necessarily .INS jS /V is saturated in V and so U is V -generic. Therefore again we have that Ult.V; U / is wellfounded. This proves the theorem. u t Assume ADL.R/ and suppose G 2 Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then as in the case for Pmax the generic filter G can be used to define a subset of !1 and we denote it by AG . Thus AG D [¹a j h.M; I; J /; ai 2 G for some M; I º: However now the generic filter can also be used to define two ideals which we denote by IG and JG . For each h.M; I; J /; ai 2 G there is an iteration j W .M; ¹I; J º/ ! .M ; ¹I ; J º/ such that j.a/ D AG . This iteration is unique because M is a model of MA!1 . Let IG D [¹I j h.M; I; J /; ai 2 Gº; let and let
JG D [¹J j h.M; I; J /; ai 2 Gº;
P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I; J /; ai 2 Gº:
The next lemma gives the basic analysis of 2 Pmax . It shows that IG is the nonstationary ideal, JG is a saturated ideal in L.R/ŒG and JG D sat.IG /. This implies that the ideal IG is presaturated in a very strong sense. Recall that a normal ideal I on !1 is presaturated if for any sequence hAi W i < !i of antichains of P .!1 / n I and for any A 2 P .!1 / n I , there exists B A such that B … I and such that for each i < !, j¹X 2 Ai j X \ B … I ºj !1 : Lemma 6.14. Assume ADL.R/ . Then 2 Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Suppose G 2 Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG !1 -DC and in L.R/ŒG:
296
6 Pmax variations
(1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (3) JG is a normal saturated ideal on !1 ; (4) JG is nowhere the nonstationary ideal; i. e. for all stationary sets S !1 there exists a stationary set T S such that T 2 JG ; (5) JG D sat.IG /. Proof. The proof that 2 Pmax is !-closed is immediate by applying Lemma 6.7 within the relevant condition. With the possible exception of (3)–(5) the remaining claims are proved by simply adapting the proofs of the corresponding claims for Pmax , using Lemma 6.6, Lemma 6.8, and Lemma 6.9. (3) is proved following the proof that the nonstationary ideal is saturated in L.R/Pmax . (4) follows by an easy density argument. (5) is also proved by using the proof that INS is saturated in the Pmax -extension. The relevant observation is that one can seal antichains corresponding to IG on sets t u which are IG -positive and in JG . Part (4) of the previous lemma provides another example of how forcing notions like Pmax can be devised to achieve something from very weak approximations. There is a dense set of conditions h.M; I; J /; ai 2 2 Pmax such that ideals I; J differ in a trivial way. J is obtained from I by adding one set. This is how we argued for the nontriviality of 2 Pmax given the nontriviality of Pmax . However in the generic extension the ideal JG is not trivially different from the ideal IG ; it is nowhere equal to IG . One consequence of the next lemma is that if G 2 Pmax is L.R/-generic then L.R/ŒG AC and so L.R/ŒG ZFC: One can show directly that L.R/ŒG AC and we shall do this for the remaining variations of Pmax that we shall define. Lemma 6.15. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose G L.R/ŒG: (1) AG is L.R/-generic for Pmax ; (2) P .!1 / L.R/ŒAG .
2
Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then in
6.1
2P
max
297
Proof. In L.R/ŒG let F be the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.a/ D AG and such that I D INS \ M : By Lemma 6.14(1), in L.R/ŒG every club in !1 contains a club which is constructible from a real. Therefore by Theorem 3.19, if X H.!2 / is a countable elementary substructure then the transitive collapse of X is iterable. Thus by Lemma 4.74, the conditions in F are pairwise compatible in Pmax . Therefore we have only to show that F \D ¤; for all D Pmax such that D is dense and D 2 L.R/. Suppose h.M; I; J /; ai 2 G and that D Pmax is an open, dense set with D 2 L.R/. Let h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax be such that M 2 H.!1 /M0 : Let B0 !1M0 be a set in M0 such that both B0 and !1M0 are I0 -positive. Let J0 2 M0 be the uniform normal ideal on !1M0 defined by I0 [ ¹B0 º. By Lemma 6.6 there exists an iteration j W .M; ¹I; J º/ ! .M ; ¹I ; J º/ such that j 2 M0 , I D I0 \ M , and J D J0 \ M . Thus h.M0 ; I0 /; j.a/i 2 Pmax . Let h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 D be a condition such that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i and let j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be the iteration such that j0 .j.a// D a1 . Thus h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i 2 2 Pmax and h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i where J1 2 M1 is the (normal) ideal on !1M1 defined by I1 [ ¹j0 .B0 /º. Note that B0 and !1M0 n B0 are I0 -positive, and so j0 .B0 / and !1M1 n j0 .B0 / are I1 -positive. By genericity we may suppose that h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i 2 G: But then h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 F and so F \D ¤; for all D Pmax such that D is dense and D 2 L.R/. This proves (1). The second claim of the lemma follows from Lemma 6.14(1). t u
6 Pmax variations
298
The next lemma gives the basic relationship between Pmax and 2 Pmax . Lemma 6.16. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose G L.R/ŒG:
2
Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then in
(1) L.P .!1 // is a generic extension of L.R/ for Pmax ; (2) sat.INS / is saturated; (3) There is a filter H0 PNS such that H0 is L.P .!1 //-generic, such that L.P .!1 //ŒH0 D L.R/ŒG and such that IH0 D JG D sat.INS /: Proof. (1) is immediate from Lemma 6.15. (2) follows from Lemma 6.14. Let g Pmax be the L.R/-generic filter such that AG D Ag . Let PNS be the partial order PNS as computed in L.R/Œg. Conditions are pairs .X; S / such that (1.1) X P .!1 /, (1.2) jX j !1 , (1.3) S and !1 n S are stationary. The order is given by .X1 ; S1 / .X0 ; S0 / if X0 X1 , S0 S1 and if .INS _ S1 / \ X0 D .INS _ S0 / \ X0 where for each S !1 such that !1 n S is stationary, INS _ S is the normal ideal generated by INS [ ¹S º. Suppose h0 PNS is L.R/Œg-generic. In L.R/ŒgŒh0 define G0 .2 Pmax /L.R/ as follows. h.M; I; J /; ai 2 G0 if h.M; I /; ai 2 g and if for some d 2 M the following two conditions are satisfied. (2.1) J is the ideal generated by I [ ¹d º. (2.2)
..P .!1 //M ; j.d // 2 h0 where j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.a/ D Ag .
6.1
2P
max
299
We prove that G0 is an L.R/-generic filter for 2 Pmax . Suppose .X0 ; S0 / 2 h0 and that D 2 Pmax is open, dense with D 2 L.R/. Since jX0 j !1 , there exist h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 g and .t0 ; b0 / 2 .PNS /M0 M0 such that I0 D INS and such that
j0 ..t0 ; b0 // D .X0 ; S0 / where
j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
is the iteration such that j0 .a0 / D Ag . We work in L.R/. Let h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 Pmax be such that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i M1 and such that I1 D INS . Let J0 be the normal ideal in M0 generated by I0 [ ¹b0 º. Let .t1 ; b1 / be the image of .t0 ; b0 / under the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends a0 to a1 . Let J0 be the image of J0 under this iteration. Thus
.t1 ; b1 / 2 .PNS /M1 and b1 … I1 . In M1 , let J1 be the normal ideal on !1M1 generated by I1 [ ¹b1 º. Thus and J1 \ t1 D J0 \ t1 . J1 ¤ I1 and so h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i 2 2 Pmax . Therefore there exists h.M2 ; I2 ; J2 /; a2 i 2 D such that h.M2 ; I2 ; J2 /; a2 i < h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i and such that J2 is the ideal defined by I2 [ ¹d0 º for some d0 2 .P .!1 //M2 : By Lemma 6.6, the set of conditions h.M; I; J /; ai 2 2 Pmax such that J is obtained by adding a single set to I is dense. Thus h.M2 ; I2 ; J2 /; a2 i exists. Let 1 W .M; ¹I1 ; J1 º/ ! .M1 ; ¹I1 ; J1 º/ be the iteration which sends a1 to a2 . An important point is the following. Since J1 is the ideal in M1 generated by I1 [ ¹b1 º, is also an iteration of .M1 ; I1 /. Thus h.M2 ; I2 /; a2 i < h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i: By genericity we may assume that h.M2 ; I2 /; a2 i 2 g: Let b2 D .b1 /, let t2 D .t1 / and let d1 D d0 [ b2 . Since J1 D M1 \ J2
6 Pmax variations
300
it follows that b2 2 J2 and
J2 \ t2 D J1 \ t2 :
Therefore .t2 ; d1 / .t2 ; b2 / in .PNS /M2 . Let j2 W .M2 ; I2 / ! .M2 ; I2 / be the iteration such that j2 .a2 / D Ag and let .X1 ; S1 / D j2 ..t2 ; d1 //. In L.R/Œg, .INS _ S0 / \ X0 D .INS _ S1 / \ X0 and so .X1 ; S1 / .X0 ; S0 / in PNS . By genericity we may assume that .X1 ; S1 / 2 h0 . This implies that h.M2 ; I2 ; J2 /; a2 i 2 G0 and so G0 \ D ¤ ;. It remains to show that G0 is a filter. Since G0 \ D ¤ ; for each dense set D 2 Pmax , it suffices to show that elements of G0 are pairwise compatible in 2 Pmax . Suppose h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i 2 G0 and h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i 2 G0 : Let d0 2 M0 be such that J0 is the ideal in M0 generated by I0 [ ¹d0 º and similarly let d1 2 M0 be such that J1 is the ideal in M1 generated by I1 [ ¹d1 º. Let j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / and
j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 /
be the iterations such that j0 .a0 / D AG D j1 .a1 /. Since J0 is generated from I0 by adding one set, j0 is also an iteration of .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ and similarly j1 is an iteration of .M1 ; ¹I1 ; J1 º/. Let B0 D j0 .d0 / and let B1 D j1 .d1 /. Thus j0 .J0 / D .INS _ B0 / \ M0 and
j1 .J1 / D .INS _ B1 / \ M1 : Let S0 D B0 , S1 D B1 ,
and let
X0 D P .!1 / \ M0 X1 D P .!1 / \ M1 :
Since h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i 2 G0 , it follows .X0 ; S0 / 2 h0 :
6.1
2P
max
301
Similarly .X1 ; S1 / 2 h0 . Let S D S0 [ S1 and let X D X0 [ X1 . Since h0 is a generic filter, .X; S / 2 h0 . Let h.M2 ; I2 /; a2 i 2 g be such that .M0 ; M1 / 2 H.!1 /M2 and such that I2 D .INS /M2 . Thus j0 2 M2 and j1 2 M2 where j2 W .M2 ; I2 / ! .M2 ; I2 / is the iteration such that j2 .a2 / D AG . Let k0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .MO 0 ; IO0 / and
k1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .MO 1 ; IO1 /
be the iterations such that k0 .a0 / D a2 D k1 .a1 /. Thus k0 2 M2 and j0 D j2 .k0 /: Similarly j1 D j2 .k1 /. Let b0 D k0 .d0 /, b1 D k1 .d1 /, O
y0 D .P .!1 //M0 and let
O
y1 D .P .!1 //M1 :
Let b D b0 [ b1 and let y D y0 [ y1 . Note that (3.1) j2 ..y0 ; b0 // D .X0 ; S0 /, (3.2) j2 .y1 ; b1 / D .X1 ; S1 /, (3.3) j2 .y; b/ D .X; S /. Now both .X0 ; S0 / .X; S / and .X1 ; S1 / .X; S / in PNS . Therefore both M2 . .y; b/ .y0 ; b0 / and .y; b/ .y1 ; b1 / in PNS Let J2 be the normal ideal in M2 generated by I2 [ ¹bº. Thus J2 \ MO 0 D JO0 and J2 \ MO 1 D JO1 where JO0 D k0 .J0 / and JO1 D k1 .J1 /. Finally .MO 0 ; ¹IO0 ; JO0 º/ is an iterate of .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ as witnessed by k0 and similarly .MO 1 ; ¹IO1 ; JO1 º/ is an iterate of .M1 ; ¹I1 ; J1 º/ as witnessed by k1 . This is because in M0 , J0 is the normal ideal generated by I0 [ ¹d0 º and because in M1 , I1 is the normal ideal generated by J1 [ ¹d1 º. Thus h.M2 ; I2 ; J2 /; a2 i 2 2 Pmax , h.M2 ; I2 ; J2 /; a2 i < h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i; and h.M2 ; I2 ; J2 /; a2 i < h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i: Therefore h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i and h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i are compatible and so G0 is L.R/-generic.
6 Pmax variations
302
By the genericity of G0 and its definition it follows that L.R/ŒgŒh0 D L.R/ŒG0 : By the homogeneity of 2 Pmax it follows that there exists h PNS such that h is L.R/Œg-generic and such that L.R/ŒgŒh D L.R/ŒG: Finally since PNS has cardinality !2 in L.R/Œg and since .P .!1 //L.R/Œg D .P .!1 //L.R/ŒG ; PNS is .!1 ; 1/-distributive in L.R/Œg.
t u
As an immediate corollary to Lemma 6.16 we obtain the following theorem. Theorem 6.17. Assume ./ and that V D L.P .!1 //. Then PNS is .!1 ; 1/-distributive. Further, suppose G PNS is V -generic. Then in V ŒG; (1) IG is a normal saturated ideal, (2) IG D sat.INS /.
t u
There are absoluteness theorems for 2 Pmax analogous to those for Pmax . The proofs are straightforward modifications of those for the Pmax theorems. We prove the absoluteness theorem for 2 Pmax which corresponds to Theorem 4.64. The proof is quite similar to that of Theorem 4.64. Of course in this theorem the ideal I could be simply the nonstationary ideal. Theorem 6.18. Assume ADL.R/ and that there is a Woodin cardinal with a measurable above. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; I; J; 2i where I J are normal uniform ideals on !1 and I ¤ J . Suppose hH.!2 /; I; J; 2i : Then
2P max
hH.!2 /; INS ; JG ; 2iL.R/
:
Proof. Let .x; y/ be a †0 formula such that D 8x9y: .x; y/ (up to logical equivalence). Assume towards a contradiction that hH.!2 /; IG ; JG ; 2i
2P max
::
Then by Lemma 6.14, there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i 2 2 Pmax and a set b0 2 H.!2 /M0
6.1
such that if
2P
max
303
h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i
then
hH.!2 /M0 ; 2; I0 ; J0 i 8y Œb0 ;
where b0 D j.b0 / and where j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ is the iteration such that j.a0 / D a0 . By Lemma 4.36, there is an iteration j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ such that: (1.1) j.!1M0 / D !1 ; (1.2) I0 \ M0 D I0 ; (1.3) J0 \ M0 D J0 . Let B0 D j.b0 /. The sentence holds in V and so there exists a set D0 2 H.!2 / such that hH.!2 /; 2; I; J i : ŒB0 ; D0 : Let ı be a Woodin cardinal and be a measurable cardinal above ı. Suppose that G Coll.!1 ; P .!1 // is V -generic. Let hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i be an enumeration of I in V ŒG, and let hT˛ W ˛ < !1 i be an enumeration of J . Let S D ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ 2 Sˇ for some ˇ < ˛º and let T D ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ 2 Tˇ for some ˇ < ˛º: The key points are the following. We work in V ŒG. First S is co-stationary and .INS _ S /V ŒG \ V D I: This is easily verified by an analysis of terms in V ; since I is a normal ideal in V , for each set A !1 such that A 2 V and A … I , A \ .!1 n S /
304
6 Pmax variations
is a stationary subset of !1 . This follows from the observation that in V , for each set A 2 P .!1 / n I , ZA P!1 .H.!2 // is stationary in P!1 .H.!2 // where ZA is the set of countable X H.!2 / such that X \ !1 2 A and such that for all B 2 X \ I , X \ !1 … B. If B 2 I then B \ .!1 n S / is countable. Similarly T is co-stationary and .INS _ T /V ŒG \ V D J Since I J , it follows that .INS _ S /V ŒG .INS _ T /V ŒG ; and since I ¤ J ,
.INS _ S /V ŒG ¤ .INS _ T /V ŒG :
V ŒG is a small generic extension of V and so ı is a Woodin cardinal in V ŒG and is measurable in V ŒG. Let Q D Coll.!1 ; <ı/ P be an iteration defined in V ŒG such that P is ccc in V ŒGColl.!1 ;<ı/ , V ŒGQ MA C :CH and such that Q has cardinality ı in V ŒG. Let H Q be V ŒG-generic Thus by Theorem 4.63, the nonstationary ideal on !1 is precipitous in V ŒGŒH . Further, .INS /V ŒG D .INS /V ŒGŒH \ V ŒG and so hH.!2 /; 2; INS _ S; INS _ T iV ŒgŒC ŒG : ŒB0 ; D0 : Clearly is still measurable in V ŒGŒH . Let 2 V ŒGŒH be a measure on . Let X VC2 ŒGŒH be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹M0 ; S; T; j; G; H; B0 ; D0 ; º X and let Y D X \ V ŒGŒH . Let NY be the transitive collapse of Y and let NX be the transitive collapse of X . Let X be the image of and let X be the image of under the collapsing map. Thus NY D VX \ NX and the pair .NX ; X / is iterable in the usual sense. Let N D [¹k.NY / j k is an iteration of k0 º
6.1
2P
max
305
where the union ranges over iterations of arbitrary length and k0 is the embedding given by X . Thus N is a transitive inner model of ZFC containing the ordinals and NX D NY : Let IY be the image of .INS _S /V ŒGŒH under the collapsing map and let JY be the image of .INS _T /V ŒGŒH . Since INS is precipitous in V ŒGŒH , it follows that .INS /NX is precipitous in NX . Therefore .INS /N is precipitous in N . Thus by Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 3.10, the structure .NY ; .INS /NY / is iterable in V ŒGŒH . Therefore the structure .NY ; ¹IY ; JY º/ is iterable. Let jY be the image of j under the collapsing map. Thus jY 2 NY , jY W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ is an iteration of .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ of length .!1 /NY , I0 D IY \ M0 and J0 D JY \ M0 : The latter two identities hold since, I0 D I \ M0 D .INS _ S /V ŒGŒH \ M0 and J0 D J \ M0 D .INS _ T /V ŒGŒH \ M0 : Thus h.NY ; IY ; JY /; jY .a0 /i 2 2 Pmax and h.NY ; IY ; JY /; jY .a0 /i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i: Finally let BY be the image of B0 under the collapsing map and let DY be the image of D0 . Thus hH.!2 /NY ; IY ; JY ; 2i : ŒBY ; DY and so hH.!2 /NY ; IY ; JY ; 2i .:8y /ŒBY : However BY D jY .b0 /. Thus in V ŒGŒH there is a condition h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i h.M0 ; I0 ; J0 /; a0 i such that hH.!2 /M1 ; I1 ; J1 i 6 8y Œb1 where b1 D j0 .b0 / and j0 W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ is the iteration such that j0 .a0 / D a1 . By absoluteness, noting that V is †13 -correct in the generic extension, V ŒGŒH ; t u such a condition h.M1 ; I1 ; J1 /; a1 i must exist in V , which is a contradiction.
306
6 Pmax variations
6.2
Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
6.2.1 Qmax We shall be concerned with !1 -dense, normal, uniform ideals on !1 . Recall that if I P .!1 / is a normal, uniform, ideal, then the ideal I is !1 -dense if the set of nonzero elements of the boolean algebra, P .!1 /=I; contains a dense subset of cardinality @1 . We have previously proved using the core model induction that the existence of such an ideal on !1 implies ADR and so we obtain the equiconsistency, see Theorem 6.149 and the subsequent corollary. We define our next variation on Pmax which we shall call Qmax . This we shall use to show that it is consistent that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. The first proof we give here will require the consistency of a huge cardinal. We do this version first because it is relatively easy and it illustrates the basic method which can be used to obtain a variety of results. We then reduce the hypothesis to simply the consistency of AD by modifying the definition of Qmax . This version, which is somewhat more technical to define, we shall denote by Qmax . The definition of Qmax is analogous to . that of Pmax In summary, we shall define a partial order Qmax . Assuming the existence of an huge cardinal we shall prove that L.R/Qmax ZFC and L.R/Qmax “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 dense”: In fact we shall prove that if there is a normal, uniform, !1 -dense ideal on !1 and there exist infinitely many Woodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above; then L.R/Qmax ZFC and L.R/Qmax “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 dense”: Thus we abstractly obtain the consistency that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 dense from the consistency that there is an !1 -dense, normal, uniform ideal on !1 (together with the appropriate large cardinals). After the initial analysis of L.R/Qmax we shall define Qmax and complete the anal ysis of L.R/Qmax assuming only ADL.R/ . Finally we shall obtain as a corollary that, assuming only ADL.R/ , RO.Qmax / D RO.Qmax /: We shall also prove several absoluteness theorems for L.R/Qmax . One of these, (Theorem 6.85), shows that the Qmax extension is simply the Pmax -extension conditioned on a form of ˘. Another, Theorem 6.87, is a related theorem which shows that satisfies a restricted form of the homogeneity condition, formalized the Qmax -extension in axiom , that characterizes the Pmax -extension. We fix some notation.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
307
Definition 6.19. Suppose I is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 . Then YColl .I / denotes the set of functions f W !1 ! H.!1 / such that for all ˛ < !1 , f .˛/ is a filter in Coll.!; 1 C ˛/ and such that the following conditions are satisfied. For each p 2 Coll.!; !1 / let Sp D ¹˛ j p 2 f .˛/º: (1) For each p 2 Coll.!; !1 /, Sp … I . (2) For each S 2 P .!1 / n I , Sp n S 2 I for some p 2 Coll.!; !1 /.
t u
The functions in YColl .I / correspond to boolean isomorphisms W P .!1 /=I ! RO.Coll.!; !1 //: One manifestation of this correspondence we shall use frequently. Suppose G Coll.!; !1 / is V -generic. Let H D ¹S !1 j S n Sp 2 I for some p 2 Gº be the corresponding V -generic filter in .P .!1 / n I; /. The filter H induces a generic elementary embedding j W V ! M V ŒH : It is easily verified that j.f /.!1V / D G. Definition 6.20. Qmax is the set of pairs h.M; I /; f i where: (1) I; f 2 M. (2) M ZFC . (3) I is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 in M. (4) .M; I / is iterable. (5) f 2 .YColl .I //M . The ordering on Qmax is analogous to Pmax . h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i if M0 2 M1 ; M0 is countable in M1 , and there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that: (1) j.f0 / D f1 ; (2) M0 2 M1 and j 2 M1 ; (3) I0 D I1 \ M0 .
t u
308
6 Pmax variations
Remark 6.21.
(1) Suppose that ¹h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i; h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 iº Qmax
and that
j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
is an iteration of length !1M1 such that: a) j.f0 / D f1 ; b) M0 2 M1 and j 2 M1 . Then necessarily,
I0 D I1 \ M0 ;
and so (3) in the definition of the order on Qmax is implied by the other conditions. (2) If we modify the definition of Qmax to require that M ZFC we obtain an equivalent forcing notion provided for each real x there exists a condition h.M; I /; f i with x 2 M (and M ZFC). This is true under mild assumptions. For example if AD holds in L.R/ and there is an inaccessible then it is true. Unlike the situation for Pmax , the fragment of ZFC that the models occurring in the conditions satisfy is important insofar as what theory one needs to work in to prove existence of conditions. The underlying point is that the existence of a precipitous ideal on !1 is weak in terms of consistency strength, whereas the existence of an t u !1 -dense ideal on !1 is equiconsistent with AD. Lemma 6.22. Suppose h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax . Suppose j1 W .M; I / ! .M1 ; I1 / and j2 W .M; I / ! .M2 ; I2 / are iterations of .M; I / such that j1 .f / D j2 .f /. Then M1 D M2 and j1 D j2 . Proof. This lemma is the analogue of Lemma 4.35 and the proof is a routine adaptation of the proof of Lemma 4.35. The function f plays the role of the set a. We first examine an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / corresponding to a single generic ultrapower. We prove that j is completely determined by j.f /.!1M /. The lemma follows by induction on the length of the iteration. Let U .P .!1 //M be the M-ultrafilter corresponding to j . Thus U D ¹a !1M j a 2 M and !1M 2 j.a/º:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
309
Let g D j.f /.!1M /. Since f 2 .YColl .I //M , g Coll.!; !1M / and g is an M-generic filter. Again since f 2 .YColl .I //M , U can be recovered from g as follows. A set a belongs to U if and only if there exists p 2 g such that .!1M n a/ \ ¹ˇ < !1M j p 2 f .ˇ/º 2 I: Thus j is recoverable from j.f /.!1M /.
t u
The next lemma is the basic iteration lemma for conditions in Qmax . Because we wish to apply it within the models occurring in conditions we assume only the relevant fragment of ZFC. Lemma 6.23 (ZFC ). Suppose that I is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 and that f 2 YColl .I /: Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 Qmax : Then there is an iteration k W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M ; I / such that: (1) k.!1M0 / D !1 ; (2) I \ M D I ; (3) k.f0 / D f modulo I . Proof. This lemma corresponds to Lemma 4.36, however the proof in this case is easier. First we note that (1) and (2) follow from (3). We prove (3). Let h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; k˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i be any iteration of .M0 ; I0 / such that for all ˇ < !1 if k0;ˇ .!1M0 / D ˇ and if f .ˇ/ is an Mˇ -generic filter for Coll.!; ˇ/ then kˇ;ˇ C1 is the corresponding generic elementary embedding. We claim that h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; k˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i is as desired. Suppose A !1 and A codes the iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; k˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i: Then the set of < !1 such that h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; k˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i 2 LŒA \
310
6 Pmax variations
contains a club in !1 . Further the set of < !1 such that k0; .!1M0 / D also contains a club. Because of the relationship between f and I , ¹˛ < !1 j f .˛/ is not a LŒA \ ˛-generic filter for Coll .!; ˛/º 2 I: This is easily verified by using the generic elementary embedding corresponding to I , noting that if j is the generic elementary embedding then j.A/ \ !1V D A. Therefore !1 n ¹ j f ./ is M -genericº 2 I: Let X !1 be the set of < !1 such that f ./ is an M -generic filter for Coll.!; / and such that k0; .!1M0 / D . Thus !1 n X 2 I . However by the properties of the iteration, X ¹ j k0; C1 .f0 /./ D f ./º and so k0;!1 .f0 / D f modulo I . This proves (3). t u The analysis of the Qmax -extension requires the generalization of Lemma 6.23 to sequences. Here (unlike for 2 Pmax ) we state the general lemma cf. Lemma 6.7. The reference in the hypothesis to conditions in Qmax is simply a device to shorten the statement of the lemma. Lemma 6.24 (ZFC ). Suppose I is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 and that f 2 YColl .I /: Suppose hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in Qmax such that for each k < ! pk D h.Mk ; Ik /; fk i and for all k < ! (i) pk 2 MkC1 , (ii) jMk jMkC1 D .!1 /MkC1 , Mk
(iii) !1
MkC1
D !1
,
(iv) fk D f0 , (v) IkC1 \ Mk D Ik , (vi) if C 2 Mk is closed and unbounded in !1M0 then there exists D 2 MkC1 such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ MkC1 . Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i such that j.!1M0 / D !1 , such that ¹˛ < !1 j f .˛/ ¤ j.f0 /.˛/º 2 I; and such that for all k < !, Ik D I \ Mk :
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
311
Proof. By Corollary 4.20 the sequence h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is iterable. The lemma follows by a construction essentially the same as that given in the proof of Lemma 6.23. t u Remark 6.25. Lemma 6.23 and Lemma 6.24 can both be proved without the requirement that the ideal I be !1 -dense. Instead one requires that the function f satisfy a diamond-like condition relative to the ideal, as indicated in the proof. For the nonstationary ideal this condition is given in Definition 6.37. t u Lemma 6.26 is a simple variation of Lemma 5.23. Lemma 6.26. Suppose J is a normal precipitous ideal on !1 and that is the least strongly inaccessible cardinal. Suppose X V is a countable elementary substructure. Let M be the transitive collapse of X and let I be the image of J under the collapsing map. Then .M; I / is A-iterable for each set A 2 X such that every set of reals which is projective in A is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Proof. Suppose A 2 X , A R and for all B R such that B is projective in A, B is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Let ƒ D ¹B R j B is projective in Aº: Since is the least strongly inaccessible, every set in ƒ is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Therefore if g is M -generic for a partial order P 2 M then A \ M Œg 2 M Œg and hH.!1 /M Œg ; A \ M Œg; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i: This follows as in the proof of Lemma 5.23, by Lemma 2.29. Suppose 2 X and that V ZFC. Let X be the image of under the collapsing map. Let S and T be trees on ! 2 such that if G Coll.!; / then .pŒS /V ŒG D AV ŒG and .pŒT /V ŒG D .R n A/V ŒG : Since 2 X , we may suppose that ¹S; T º X: Let .SX ; TX / be the image of .S; T / under the collapsing map. Suppose g Coll.!; X / is M -generic. Therefore by the remarks above, A \ M Œg 2 M Œg
6 Pmax variations
312 and
hH.!1 /M Œg ; A \ M Œg; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i: Let N D .M / X and suppose j W .N; I / ! .N ; I / is a countable iteration with j 2 M Œg. Then by Lemma 3.8, j lifts to define a countable iteration k W .M; I / ! .M ; I / where kjM˛ 2 M Œg for all ˛ 2 M . By Lemma 3.10, M is wellfounded. Noting A \ M Œg D pŒSX \ M Œg we have
k.A \ M / D k.pŒSX \ M / D pŒk.SX / \ M
and so
pŒSX \ M k.A \ M /:
Similarly
pŒTX \ M k.M \ .R n A//:
However pŒTX \ M Œg D .R n pŒSX / \ M Œg and so
k.A \ M / D pŒSX \ M D pŒSX \ N
since R \ N D R \ M . Thus in M Œg, the structure .N; I / is A \ M Œg-iterable. Finally .N; I / is countable in M Œg and hH.!1 /M Œg ; A \ M Œg; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i: Therefore .N; I / is A-iterable in V . The set of 2 M such that
M ZFC
is cofinal in M and so .M; I / is A-iterable.
t u
Lemma 6.26 can be used to obtain the existence of suitably nontrivial conditions in Qmax . Theorem 6.27. Suppose there is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 . Suppose there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above them all. Suppose X R and that X 2 L.R/.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
313
Then there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; I / is X -iterable. Proof. From the large cardinal hypothesis, AD holds in L.R/ and further every set of reals which is in L.R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin. The theorem follows from Lemma 6.26. t u The following is proved in .Foreman 2010/. It shows that starting with a huge cardinal one can force to obtain a model in which there are normal saturated ideals on !1 for which P .!1 /=I can up to isomorphism be any complete boolean algebra satisfying the obvious necessary conditions. Theorem 6.28. Suppose that 0 is 1 huge. Suppose G0 Coll.!; < 0 / is V -generic and that G1 Coll. 0 ; < 1 / is V ŒG0 -generic where the poset Coll. 0 ; < 1 / is computed in V ŒG0 . Suppose that B 2 V ŒG1 is a complete, !2 -cc boolean algebra in V ŒG1 such that V ŒG1 B j!1V ŒG1 j D !: Then in V ŒG1 there is a normal uniform ideal I on !1 such that P .!1 /=I Š B: As an immediate corollary we get: Corollary 6.29. Assume there exists an huge cardinal. Then for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; I / is X -iterable.
t u
314
6 Pmax variations
Proof. Suppose 0 is 1 -huge. Therefore 1 is a measurable cardinal and 1 is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Let be a normal measure on 1 and let j WV !N be the associated elementary embedding. N is closed under 1 sequences in V . Suppose G0 Coll.!; < 0 / is V -generic and that G1 Coll. 0 ; < 1 / is V ŒG0 -generic where the poset Coll. 0 ; < 1 / is computed in V ŒG0 . Since N is closed under 1 -sequences in V it follows that N ŒG1 is closed under 1 sequences in V ŒG1 . However 1 D .2@1 /V ŒG1 : Therefore by Theorem 6.28, in N ŒG1 there is an !1 -dense normal ideal on !1 . j. 1 / is a limit of Woodin cardinals in N and so it follows that j. 1 / is a limit of Woodin cardinals in N ŒG1 . j. 1 / is a measurable cardinal in N and hence it is a measurable cardinal in N ŒG1 . By Lemma 6.26, the conclusion of the Corollary 6.29 holds in L.R/N ŒG1 since in N ŒG1 , every set of reals which belongs to L.R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin. One could also use Theorem 6.27 for this. Finally by Theorem 2.31, L.R/N L.R/N ŒG1 since N ŒG1 is a generic extension of N by a partial order in N of cardinality less than t u j. 1 / in N . The conclusion of the corollary holds just assuming ADL.R/ . As is the case for Pmax the analysis of Qmax can be carried out just assuming: For each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; I / is X -iterable. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Let fG D [¹f j h.M; I /; f i 2 G for some M; I º:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
315
For each condition h.M; I /; f i 2 G there is a unique iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.f / D fG . Let IG D [¹I j h.M; I /; f i 2 G for some M; f º; and let
P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; f i 2 Gº:
The next theorem gives the basic results concerning Qmax . It shows that IG is an ideal, it is !1 -dense, and it is the nonstationary ideal in L.R/ŒG. Theorem 6.30. Suppose for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Then Qmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG !1 -DC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal. Proof. The only claim here that does does not have a counterpart in the Pmax case is (2). The other claims are proved by simply adapting the proofs of the corresponding claims for the Pmax -extension. As in the case for 2 Pmax , the proof that Qmax is !-closed requires proving Lemma 6.23 for the sequences that arise. Again the sequences satisfy the conditions of Corollary 4.20 and so are iterable in the sense of Definition 4.8. To prove (2) we work in L.R/ŒG. Suppose A 2 P .!1 / n IG : By (1) and the definitions, there exists h.M; I /; f i 2 G such that A 2 M n I ; where .M ; I / is the image of .M; I / under the iteration which sends f to fG . Therefore by the properties of .I ; fG / in M , there exists p 2 Coll.!; !1 / such that ¹ˇ < !1 j p 2 fG .ˇ/º … I
6 Pmax variations
316
and such that
.!1 n A/ \ ¹ˇ < !1 j p 2 fG .ˇ/º 2 I :
However I D M \ IG . Therefore for each set S 2 P .!1 / n IG there exists p 2 Coll.!; !1 / such that ¹ˇ < !1 j p 2 fG .ˇ/º n S 2 IG : t u
This verifies (2).
There remains the question of whether the axiom of choice holds in L.R/Qmax . We show that it does and in fact for the same reason it holds in L.R/Pmax . Recall that AC is the …2 sentence for hH.!2 /; 2i which we used to show that AC holds in L.R/Pmax . Theorem 6.31. Suppose for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Then
Qmax
hH.!2 /; 2iL.R/
AC :
Proof. The proof is a minor modification of the proof that AC holds in L.R/Pmax . Fix G Qmax such that G is L.R/-generic. Suppose hSi W i < !i and hTi W i < !i are sequences of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 . Suppose the Si are stationary and suppose that !1 D [¹Ti j i < !º: Let h.M; I /; f i 2 G be such that hSi W i < !i; hTi W i < !i 2 M where j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.f / D fG . Let hsi W i < !i; hti W i < !i in M be such that j..hsi W i < !i; hti W i < !i// D .hSi W i < !i; hTi W i < !i/: Thus in M, hsi W i < !i and hti W i < !i are sequences of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1M , the si are not in I , and !1M D [¹ti j i < !º:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
317
Let D be the set of conditions h.N ; J /; gi < h.M; I /; f i such that in N there exists < !2N and a continuous increasing function F W !1N ! with cofinal range such that F .tiN / sQiN for each i < ! where tiN D k.ti /, siN D k.si / and k is the embedding of the iteration of .M; I / which sends f to g. For each i < !, sQiN denotes the set AQ as computed in N where A D siN . It suffices to show that D is dense below h.M; I /; f i. We show something slightly stronger. Suppose h.N ; J /; gi < h.N0 ; J0 /; g0 i < h.M; I /; f i: Then for some h 2 N , h.N ; J /; hi 2 D and h.N ; J /; hi < h.N0 ; J0 /; g0 i < h.M; I /; f i: si0
Let be the image of si under the iteration of .M; I / which sends f to g0 and let ti0 be the image of ti under this iteration. Let x 2 N be a real which codes N0 . Working in N we define an iteration of .N0 ; J0 / of length !1N . Let C be the set of indiscernibles of LŒx less than !1N . Let D C be the set of 2 C such that C \ has ordertype . Thus D is a closed unbounded subset of C . Let h.N˛ ; J˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1N i be an iteration of .N0 ; J0 / in N such that (1.1) For all ˛ 2 D and for all < ˛, j0;ˇ .si0 / 2 Gˇ if 2 j0;˛ .ti0 / where ˇ is the th element of C above ˛, (1.2) J! N D J \ N! N . 1
1
(1.3) j0;! N .g0 /jD D gjD for some club D D. 1
Condition (1.3) is the additional requirement special to the case of Qmax . The condition (1.3) is satisfied by constructing the iteration using g. / to define the generic ultrafilter at stage whenever possible provided 2 D. The iteration is easily constructed in N , the point is that the requirements given by (1.1), (1.2), and (1.3) do not interfere. The other useful observation is that if ˛ 2 C and if k W .N0 ; J0 / ! .N0 ; J0 / is any iteration of length ˛ then ˛ D k.!1N0 /. Let be the ˇ th indiscernible of LŒx where ˇ D !1N C!1N . Let F be the function F W !1N ! given by F .ˇ/ is the th indiscernible of LŒx where D !1N C ˇ. Thus (2.1) 2 N , (2.2) < !2N , (2.3) F 2 N , (2.4) F W !1N ! is continuous and strictly increasing.
6 Pmax variations
318
Let siN D j0;! N .si0 / and let tiN D j0;! N .ti0 /. Let 1
1
h D j0;! N .g0 /: 1
Thus h.N ; J /; hi 2 Qmax and h.N ; J /; hi < h.N0 ; J0 /; g0 i. By the definition of the iteration it follows that in N , F .tiN / sQiN and so h.N ; J /; hi 2 D.
t u
As a corollary to the previous theorems we obtain the following consistency result which we shall improve considerably in Corollary 6.82. Theorem 6.32. Assume ZFC C “There is an huge cardinal ” is consistent. Then so is ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense”:
t u
The analysis of Qmax yields the absoluteness theorem corresponding to Qmax . There are several absoluteness theorems that one can prove. The absoluteness results hold if one expands the structure hH.!2 /; I; 2i by adding predicates for each set of reals which is in L.R/. One can also add a predicate for ŒF I H.!2 / where ŒF I is the set of all functions h W !1 ! H.!1 / such that ¹˛ j F .˛/ ¤ h.˛/º 2 I . Theorem 6.33. Suppose there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above them all. Suppose J is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 and that F 2 YColl .J /: Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; J; ŒF J ; A; 2 W A R; A 2 L.R/i and that hH.!2 /; J; ŒF J ; A; 2 W A R; A 2 L.R/i : Then
Qmax
hH.!2 /; IG ; ŒfG IG ; A; 2 W A R; A 2 L.R/iL.R/
:
Proof. Let ı be the supremum of the first ! Woodin cardinals and let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal above ı. Since there is a measurable cardinal above ı, every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ is <ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. Therefore by Theorem 6.27, for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
319
(1.1) X \ M 2 M, (1.2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (1.3) .M; I / is X -iterable. Thus the basic analysis of Qmax as given in Theorem 6.30 and Theorem 6.31 applies. Suppose X V is a countable elementary substructure containing I and f . Let hMX ; JX ; FX i be the image of hX; J; F i under the transitive collapse. Then .MX ; JX / is iterable. Further for each A 2 X \ P .R/ \ L.R/, .MX ; JX / is A-iterable. Thus hMX ; JX ; FX i 2 Qmax . The theorem follows from an argument similar to the absoluteness theorem for Pmax . The situation here is actually simpler since no forcing over V is required. The only other relevant point is that if h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax then there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.!1M / D !1 and such that ¹˛ j j.f /.˛/ ¤ F .˛/º 2 J:
t u
As with the case for Pmax this expanded absoluteness theorem has a “converse”. This requires two preliminary lemmas the first of which is a very weak analogue of Lemma 4.60. Lemma 6.34. Assume that for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Suppose that G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Suppose h 2 L.R/ŒG and that in L.R/ŒG; h is a function such that h W !1 ! H.!1 / and such that the set ¹˛ j fG .˛/ D h.˛/º contains a club in !1 . Then there is a filter G Qmax such that G is L.R/-generic, fG D h and such that L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒG :
320
6 Pmax variations
Proof. For each q 2 Qmax let Qmax jq D ¹p 2 Qmax j p < qº: By Theorem 6.30(1), there exist h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 G and h0 2 M such that j0 .h0 / D H where j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration such that j0 .f0 / D fG . Since I0 D IG \ M0 , ¹ˇ < !1M0 j f0 .ˇ/ ¤ h0 .ˇ/º 2 I0 : Therefore h.M0 ; I0 /; h0 i 2 Qmax . Define a map W Qmax jh.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i ! Qmax jh.M0 ; I0 /; h0 i as follows. Suppose h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax and h.M; I /; f i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i. Let k W .M0 ; I0 / ! .MO 0 ; IO/ be the iteration such that k.f0 / D f . Then h.M; I /; k.h0 /i 2 Qmax and h.M; I /; k.h0 /i < h.M0 ; I0 /; h0 i: Let h.M; I /; k.h0 /i D .h.M; I /; f i/: Now suppose h.M; I /; hi 2 Qmax and h.M; I /; hi < h.M0 ; I0 /; h0 i. Let k W .M0 ; I0 / ! .MO 0 ; IO/ be the iteration such that k.h0 / D h. Then h.M; I /; k.f0 /i 2 Qmax and h.M; I /; k.f0 /i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i: Further h.M; I /; hi D .h.M; I /; k.f0 /i/: Thus is a bijection from Qmax jh.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i to Qmax jh.M0 ; I0 /; h0 i. Clearly preserves the order. Thus ¹.p/ j p 2 G and p < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 iº generates a filter G Qmax which is L.R/-generic. The filter G is as desired.
t u
Lemma 6.35. Assume that for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Suppose that G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒfG :
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
321
Proof. Let F be the set of h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.f / D fG . The iteration j is unique and j 2 L.fG ; h.M; I /; f i/: Thus F 2 L.R/Œfg and G F . It remains to show that the conditions in F are pairwise compatible in Qmax . This follows easily from Theorem 6.30(1). Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 F and that h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i 2 F . Then by Theorem 6.30(1) there exists h.M; I /; f i 2 G such that .M0 ; M1 / 2 H.!1 /M and such that there exist iterations k0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .MO 0 ; IO0 / and
k1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .MO 1 ; IO1 /
with k0 .f0 / D f D k1 .f1 /. Necessarily, .k0 ; k1 / 2 M. Therefore h.M; I /; f i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i and h.M; I /; f i < h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i and so F D G.
t u
Theorem 6.36. Suppose there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above them all. Suppose I is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 and that F 2 YColl .I /: Suppose that for each …2 sentence, , in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; I; ŒF I ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/i if
Qmax
hH.!2 /; IG ; ŒfG IG ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/iL.R/ then
hH.!2 /; I; ŒF I ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/i : Then there exists G Qmax such that: (1) G is L.R/-generic; (2) P .!1 / L.R/ŒG; (3) fG D F ; (4) IG D I .
322
6 Pmax variations
Proof. Suppose that h 2 ŒF I . Let Fh Qmax be the set of all conditions h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.f / D h. Thus INS \ M D I . We claim that the conditions in Fh are pairwise compatible. Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 F and that h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i 2 F . Let be the least strongly inaccessible and let X V be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹I; h; h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i; h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 iº 2 X: Let MX be the transitive collapse of X and let .IX ; hX / be the image of .I; h/ under the collapsing map. It follows that .MX ; IX / is iterable and so h.MX ; IX /; hX i 2 Qmax . Since h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 F and h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i 2 F , there exist iterations k0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .MO 0 ; IO0 / and
k1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .MO 1 ; IO1 /
with k0 .f0 / D hX D k1 .f1 /. Thus h.MX ; IX /; hX i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i and h.MX ; IX /; hX i < h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i and so the conditions in F are pairwise compatible in Qmax . If G is L.R/-generic for Qmax then in L.R/ŒG, Fh D G. Fix D Qmax such that D is dense and D 2 L.R/. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then by Theorem 4.60 the following sentence holds in L.R/ŒG: “For all h 2 ŒfG IG , Fh \ D ¤ ;.” This is expressible by a …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; ŒfG IG ; DiL.R/ŒG and so by the hypothesis of the theorem it holds in V . Therefore for all h 2 ŒF I , Fh is an L.R/ŒG-generic filter for Qmax . For each B !1 there trivially exists hB 2 ŒF I such that B 2 L.hB /. Combining Lemma 6.34 and Lemma 6.35 we obtain P .!1 / L.R/ŒFh for each h 2 ŒF I and this proves the theorem.
t u
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
323
The absoluteness theorems suggest that in the model L.R/Qmax one should have all the consequences of the largest fragment of Martin’s Maximum which is consistent with the existence of an !1 -dense ideal on !1 . This seems to generally be the case and we shall prove a theorem along these lines. However in Section 6.2.4 we shall prove that there is a weak Kurepa tree on !1 in L.R/Qmax . By varying the order on Qmax we shall also produce a model in which the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense and in which there are no weak Kurepa trees, this is the subject of Section 6.2.5. Many of the combinatorial consequences of the existence of an !1 -dense ideal can be factored through a variant of ˘. We define three such variants, the first is ˘.!1
is stationary in !1 . Definition 6.38. ˘+ .!1
t u
The next two lemmas give useful reformulations of ˘.!1
324
6 Pmax variations
It suffices to prove that there exists a countable elementary substructure, X H.!2 / such that H ŒX X and such that f .˛/ is MX -generic. Let N H.!2 / be an elementary substructure of cardinality @1 such that
!1 N and such that H ŒN N . Clearly N is transitive. Let hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i enumerate the dense subsets of Coll.!; !1 / which belong to N. Let S D ¹˛ < !1 j f .˛/ \ Dˇ ¤ ; for all ˇ < ˛º:
Since f witnesses ˘.!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
325
Lemma 6.41. Suppose that for every A !1 , A# exists and that f W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function such that for all ˛ < !1 , f .˛/ is a filter in Coll.!; ˛/. (1) Suppose f witnesses ˘.!1
t u
Related to the reformulations of ˘.!1
326
6 Pmax variations
Lemma 6.43. Suppose that for every A !1 , A# exists and that f W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function such that for all ˛ < !1 , f .˛/ is a filter in Coll.!; ˛/. Then following are equivalent. (1) f witnesses ˘.!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
327
(5) for all ˛ 2 c with ˛ a limit point of c, f .˛/ is a filter in Coll.!; ˛/ and f .˛/ is LŒAh \ ˛ ˛; c \ ˛ generic for Coll.!; ˛/ where Ah D ¹.ˇ; / j 2 h.ˇ/º: The order on P .f / is given by extension: .h2 ; c2 / .h1 ; c1 / if h1 h2 , c1 c2 and
c2 \ .˛ C 1/ D c1
where ˛ D [c1 . Suppose is an ordinal and f W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function. Let P .f; / denote the countable support iteration where for all ˛ < , P .f; ˛ C 1/ D P .f; ˛/ P .f / and P .f / is as computed in V P .f;˛/ . We note that P .f; / is not in general a semiproper partial order. Lemma 6.44. Suppose that for all A !1 , A# exists, and that f W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function which witnesses ˘.!1
328
6 Pmax variations
Let Y D X \ V and let MY be the transitive collapse of Y . Thus MY 2 L.MX /: Let PY be the image of P .f; / under the collapsing map. Let F W ! ! MY be a surjection such that g is L.MY ; F /-generic where g D f .Y \ !1 /. To see that F exists let z 2 R code the pair .MY ; g/. z # exists and so !1 is inaccessible in LŒz. Therefore there exists a filter G Coll.!; MY / such that G is LŒz-generic. Let F be the function determined by G. Thus F is a surjection and further g is L.MY ; F /-generic. Let GY be MY -generic for PY with GY 2 L.MY ; F /. Choose GY such that pY 2 GY where pY is the image of p under the collapsing map. Let W Y ! V be the inverse of the collapsing map. It follows that there is a condition q 2 P .f; / such that q < .p/ for all p 2 GY . The relevant points are that GY 2 L.MY ; F / and that f .Y \ !1 / is L.MY ; F /-generic for Coll.!; MY \ !1 /.
t u
Lemma 6.45. Suppose f W !1 ! H.!1 / is V -generic for Coll.!1 ; H.!1 //. Then f witnesses ˘.!1
t u
Lemma 6.46. Suppose 0 is 1 huge. Suppose V ŒG0 Œf ŒG1 is a generic extension of V such that (i) G0 is V -generic for Coll.!; < 0 /, (ii) f is V ŒG0 -generic for Coll.!1 ; H.!1 // as computed in V ŒG0 , (iii) G1 is V ŒG0 Œf -generic for P .f; 1 / as computed in V ŒG0 Œf . Then in V Œf; G1 , ˘ holds, f witnesses ˘++ .!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
329
Proof. It is straightforward to show that the sequence h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i witnesses ˘ in V Œf ŒG1 where for each ˛ < !1 , ˛ D f .˛ C 1/: The lemma now follows by a straightforward modification of the proof of Theorem 6.28. t u Lemma 6.47 gives a property of Qmax which is a consequence of the existence of (suitable) large cardinals and yet which cannot be proved simply assuming ADL.R/ . The difficulty is (4). Let ZFC be ZFC together with a finite fragment of ZFC. Lemma 6.47. Suppose there is an huge cardinal. Then for every set A R with A 2 L.R/ there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (1) A \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i, (3) .M; I / is A-iterable, (4) ˘ holds in M, (5) f witnesses ˘++ .!1
330
6 Pmax variations
Proof. Let f W !1 ! H.!1 / be a function which witnesses ˘.!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
331
containing
332
6 Pmax variations
Proof. It suffices to show that there must exist a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 . This is a relatively standard fact. Let I be a uniform, countably complete, !1 -dense ideal on !1 . Then P .!1 /=I Š RO.Coll.!; !1 //: Therefore I defines a boolean-valued elementary embedding j WV !M VB where B D RO.Coll.!; !1 //. Define W P .!1 / ! B V by .A/ D [[!1 2 j.A/]]. Let I0 be the set of A such that .A/ D 0. Thus I0 is a normal saturated ideal on !1 and induces a boolean isomorphism of P .!1 /=I0 with a complete subalgebra of B. It follows that I0 is a normal !1 -dense ideal. t u Lemma 6.52 (ZFC ). Suppose I is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 . Let f W !1 ! H.!1 / be such that f induces a boolean isomorphism W P .!1 /=I ! RO.Coll.!; !1 //: Suppose c is Cohen generic over V and in V Œc let I.c/ be the normal ideal generated by I . Then in V Œc, I.c/ is normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 and f induces a boolean isomorphism .c/ W P .!1 /=I ! RO.Coll.!; !1 //: Proof. Suppose G Coll.!; !1 / is V Œc-generic. Then G is certainly V -generic and so there exists a generic elementary embedding j W V ! M V ŒG V such that j.f /.!1 / D G. Since c is Cohen generic over V ŒG and since Cohen forcing is ccc, the embedding j lifts to a generic elementary embedding j W V Œc ! M Œc V ŒGŒc: The induced ideal is easily verified to be I.c/ . The generic elementary embedding j shows that I.c/ and f have the desired properties. t u Theorem 6.53. Assume that for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (i) X \ M 2 M, (ii) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (iii) .M; I / is X -iterable. Then the following hold in L.R/Qmax . (1) Every set of reals of cardinality !1 is of measure 0. (2) The reals cannot be decomposed as an !1 union of meager sets.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
333
Proof. (1) follows from (2). We prove (2). Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. We work in L.R/ŒG. (2) is equivalent to the assertion that for each A !1 there exists an LŒA-generic Cohen real. Suppose that A 2 L.R/ŒG and that A !1 . We prove that there exists an LŒAgeneric Cohen real. By Theorem 6.30(1), there exists h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 G and a0 2 M0 such that j0 .a0 / D A where j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration such that j0 .f0 / D fG . Let h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i 2 Qmax be such that h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i and let
k0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .MO 0 ; IO0 /
be the iteration in M1 such that k0 .f0 / D f1 . Let c be a real which is Cohen generic over M1 and let I1.c/ be the normal ideal generated by I1 in M1 Œc. It is easily verified that M1 Œc ZFC . By Lemma 6.52, it follows that h.M1 Œc; I1.c/ /; f1 i 2 Qmax noting that if k W .M1 Œc; I1.c/ / ! .k.M1 Œc/; k.I1.c/ // is an iteration of .M1 Œc; I1.c/ / then kjM1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .k.M1 /; k.I1 // is an iteration of .M1 ; I1 /. Therefore .M1 Œc; I1.c/ / is iterable. By genericity we may assume that h.M1 Œc; I1.c/ /; f1 i 2 G: Since c is Cohen over M1 it follows that c is Cohen generic over .LŒk0 .a0 //M1 . Let j1 W .M1 Œc; I1.c/ / ! .M1 Œc; .I1.c/ / / be the iteration such that j1 .f1 / D fG . Therefore c is Cohen generic over .LŒj1 .k0 .a0 ///M1 . However j1 .k0 .a0 // D j0 .a0 / D A and by condensation,
.R/LŒA D R \ .LŒA/M1 : Thus c is Cohen generic over LŒA.
t u
6 Pmax variations
334
6.2.2 Qmax We define the variant of Qmax for which the analysis can be carried out assuming just ADL.R/ . The modification is obtained by replacing the model M in a condition with an ! sequence of models. With this we can improve Theorem 6.32 to obtain the consistency of ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 dense” from simply the consistency of ZF C AD. This is best possible. The definition of Qmax is motivated by the proof that Qmax is !-closed and the definition is closely related both to Definition 4.15 and to the definition of Pmax . In fact there is a dense subset of Qmax which is a suborder of Pmax . Suppose hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in Qmax such that for all k < !, pkC1 < pk . Suppose that for each k < !, pk D h.Mk ; Ik /; fk i: Let
ı D sup¹.!1 /Mk j k < !º
and let f D [¹fk j k < !º. For each k < ! let .Mk ; Ik / be the image of .Mk ; Ik / under the iteration of .Mk ; Ik / which sends fk to f . It follows that iterations of hMk W k < !i in the sense of Definition 4.15, correspond to iterations of h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i in the sense of Definition 4.8. The relevant point is that for each k < !,
Ik D .INS /MkC1 \ Mk : Thus if
G [¹P .ı/ \ Mk j k < !º
is a filter such that G \ Mk is Mk -normal for all k < !, then for all k < !, G \ Mk is Mk -generic. The same point applies to iterates of hMk W k < !i. Therefore hMk W k < !i is iterable. Definition 6.54. Qmax is the set of pairs .hMk W k < !i; f / such that the following hold. (1) f 2 M0 and
f W !1M0 ! M0
is a function such that for all ˛ < !1M0 , f .˛/ is a filter in Coll.!; ˛/. (2) Mk ZFC .
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals Mk
(3) Mk 2 MkC1 ; !1 (4) .INS /
MkC1
MkC1
D !1
.
\ Mk D .INS /
MkC2
335
\ Mk .
(5) hMk W k < !i is iterable. (6) For each p 2 Coll.!; !1M0 /, ¹˛ < !1M0 j p 2 f .˛/º … .INS /M1 : (7) Suppose that a !1M0 , k 2 ! and that a 2 Mk n .INS /MkC1 : Then there exists such that
p 2 Coll.!; !1M0 /
¹˛ < !1M0 j p 2 f .˛/º \ .!1M0 n a/ 2 .INS /MkC1 :
The ordering on Qmax is analogous to Qmax . A condition .hNk W k < !i; g/ < .hMk W k < !i; f / if hMk W k < !i 2 N0 , hMk W k < !i is hereditarily countable in N0 and there exists an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that: (1) j.f / D g; (2) hMk W k < !i 2 N0 and j 2 N0 ;
(3) .INS /MkC1 D .INS /N1 \ Mk for all k < !.
t u
As in the definition of the order on Qmax , clause (3) in the definition of the order on Qmax follows from clauses (1) and (2). The next lemma clarifies the effect of (6) and (7) in Definition 6.54. Lemma 6.55. Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax . (1) Suppose that
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i
is an iteration of length 1. Then j.f /.!1M0 / Coll.!; !1M0 / and j.f /.!1M0 / is a filter which is generic relative to [¹Mk j k < !º. (2) Suppose that
g Coll.!; !1M0 /
is a filter which is generic relative to [¹Mk j k < !º. Then there is a unique iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i of length 1 such that g D j.f /.!1M0 /.
6 Pmax variations
336
Proof. The lemma is an immediate consequence of the definitions.
t u
Definition 6.56. Suppose .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax and suppose X R. Then hMk W k < !i is X -iterable if (1) X \ M0 2 [¹Mk j k < !º, (2) for any iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hNk W k < !i of hMk W k < !i, j.X \ M0 / D X \ N 0 .
t u
If Qmax is sufficiently nontrivial then Qmax and Qmax are equivalent as forcing notions. More precisely if for every real x there exists a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that x 2 M and such that I D .INS /M then RO.Qmax / Š RO.Qmax /: The proof of this is implicit in what follows. We shall need a slight variant of iterability. Definition 6.57. Let A R and .M; I; ı/ 2 H.!1 / be such that (i) M is a transitive model of ZFC, (ii) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M and I D .I<ı /M is directed system of ideals associated to .Q<ı /M , (iii) .M; I/ is iterable, (iv) A \ M 2 M and hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i. The pair .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable if for all countable iterations j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I /I (1) j.A \ M / D A \ M ,
(2) hH.!1 /M ; A \ M ; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i.
t u
The notion that .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable is simply a convenient abbreviation.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
337
Lemma 6.58. Let A R and .M; I; ı/ 2 H.!1 / be such that (i) M is a transitive model of ZFC, (ii) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M and I D .I<ı /M is directed system of ideals associated to .Q<ı /M , (iii) .M; I/ is iterable, (iv) A \ M 2 M and hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i. The following are equivalent. (1) .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable. (2) .M; I/ is B-iterable for each set B R which is definable in hV!C1 ; A; 2i: Proof. This is immediate from the definitions. We prove a lemma that approximates a converse to Lemma 5.23. Lemma 6.59. Let A R and .M; I; ı/ 2 H.!1 / be such that (i) M is a transitive model of ZFC, (ii) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M and I D .I<ı /M is directed system of ideals associated to .Q<ı /M , (iii) .M; I/ is A-iterable. Then there are trees T and T on ! ı such that: (1) .T; T / 2 M ; (2) Suppose that g Coll.!; <ı/ is an M -generic filter. Then pŒT \ M Œg D A \ M Œg and pŒT \ M Œg D .R n A/ \ M Œg:
t u
338
6 Pmax variations
Proof. This is a special case of the general theorem for producing Suslin representations from various forms of generic absoluteness and correctness in the context of a Woodin cardinal. We briefly sketch the argument which involves elementary aspects of the stationary tower. The key point is the following. Let R0 be the set of triples .P ; ; p/ such that (1.1) P 2 Mı is a partial order, (1.2) 2 MıP is a term for a real, (1.3) for all M -generic filters g P; if p 2 g then Ig . / … A, where Ig ./ is the interpretation of by g. Similarly let R1 be the set of triples .P ; ; p/ such that (2.1) P 2 Mı is a partial order, (2.2) 2 MıP is a term for a real, (2.3) for all M -generic filters g P; if p 2 g then Ig . / 2 A. Then for each partial order P 2 Mı and for each term 2 MıP , ¹p j .P ; ; p/ 2 R0 [ R1 º is dense in P . Further .R0 ; R1 / 2 M . The verification is a routine consequence of A-iterability noting that if P 2 Mı is a partial order and if g P is an M -generic filter then there exists an M -generic filter h .Q<ı /M such that g 2 M Œh. We now work in M . Let AM D A \ M and fix R0 and R1 as specified above. Fix a strongly inaccessible cardinal, , of M which is below ı. A countable elementary substructure X M is AM -good if for each partial order P 2 X the following holds. Suppose 2 X \ M P is a term for a real and that g X \P is an X -generic filter; i. e. g is a filter such that if D P is a dense set such that D 2 X then g \ D ¤ ;: Let x 2 R be the interpretation of by g. Then x 2 AM
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
339
if and only if for some p 2 g, .P ; ; p/ 2 R1 , and x … AM if and only if for some p 2 g, .P ; ; p/ 2 R0 . Suppose that G .Q<ı /M is M -generic and let j W M ! N M ŒG be the corresponding generic elementary embedding. Then it is easily verified that ¹j.a/ j a 2 M º is j.AM /-good in N . Therefore the set ¹X M j X is AM -goodº contains a closed unbounded subset of P!1 .M /. In fact one can show that every countable elementary substructure which contains A as an element, is AM -good. t u It is now straightforward to construct the trees T and T as desired. Remark 6.60. The next lemma isolates a consequence of .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable. This consequence is all that we shall actually require. The lemma refers to iterations j W .M; / ! .M ; / where 2 M is a normal measure in M . This notion of iteration is the conventional (non-generic) one. t u Lemma 6.61. Let A R and .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / be such that .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable. Let ı 2 M be the Woodin cardinal associated to I. Suppose that T 2 M is a tree on ! ı such that for all M -generic filters, g Coll.!; <ı/; pŒT \ M Œg D A \ M Œg. Let < ı be a measurable cardinal in M and let 2 M be a normal measure on . (1) The structure .M; / is iterable. (2) Suppose that
j W .M; / ! .M ; /
is a countable iteration and that G Coll.!; <j.ı//
is M -generic. Then a) A \ M ŒG D pŒj.T / \ M ŒG, b) hH.!1 /M
ŒG
; A \ M ŒG; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i.
6 Pmax variations
340
Proof. For each n 2 ! let An be the set of x 2 R which code an element of the †n diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i: Thus for each n 2 !, .M; I/ is strongly An -iterable. For each n 2 ! let Tn 2 M be a tree on ! ı such that for all M -generic filters, g Coll.!; <ı/; pŒTn \ M Œg D An \ M Œg. The trees Tn exist by Lemma 6.59. We first prove that for any countable iteration k W .M; / ! .M ; /; for each n 2 !,
pŒk.Tn / An :
Fix the iteration k. Suppose that the iteration is of length ˛. Let Q kQ W .M; I/ ! .MQ ; I/ be a countable iteration of length ˛. Thus for each < ı, Q ¹k.a/ j a 2 M º 2 MQ : Thus
Q Q \¹k.a/ j a 2 º 2 k. /:
Therefore there exists an elementary embedding W M ! MQ Q such that ı k D k. This implies that
Q n /: pŒk.Tn / pŒk.T Finally k.Tn / is countable in MQ and hMQ \ V!C1 ; A \ MQ ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i:
Therefore if pŒk.Tn / 6 An then there must exists x 2 pŒk.Tn / n An Q n / and this contradicts that Q such that x 2 M . But then x 2 pŒk.T Q n \ M / D An \ MQ : k.A This proves that for each n, pŒk.Tn / An : Finally let
j W .M; / ! .M ; /
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
341
be the given countable iteration and let G Coll.!; <j.ı//
be M -generic. Let A D pŒj.T / \ M ŒG and for each n < ! let An D pŒj.Tn / \ M ŒG. By the elementarity of j it follows that in M ŒG, for each n < !, the set An is the set of x 2 R which code an element of the †n -diagram of hV!1 \ M ŒG; A ; 2i: Further A A and for each n < !, An An . Therefore A D A \ M ŒG and
hV!1 \ M ŒG; pŒj.T / \ M ŒG; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i:
t u
As an immediate corollary to Lemma 5.37 we obtain the following theorem which we shall use to produce suitable conditions in Qmax . Theorem 6.62. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/, there exists .M; I; ı/ 2 H.!1 / such that (1) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M , (2) I D .I<ı /M , (3) .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable. Proof. Let B R be the set of x 2 R which code an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i: By Lemma 5.37 there exists .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / such that .M; I/ is B-iterable. It follows that .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable.
t u
We now come to the main theorem for the existence of conditions in Qmax . First we fix some notation and prove an easy preliminary lemma. This lemma is really the technical key for producing conditions in Qmax from our assumptions. Suppose S Ord is a set of ordinals. Then Coll .!; S / is the partial order of finite partial functions p W ! S ! Ord such that p.i; ˛/ < 1 C ˛. The order is by extension and so Coll .!; S / is the natural restriction of the Levy collapse. 1 1 We also fix some coding. A partial function f W H.!1 / ! H.!1 / is … 1 if it is … 1 1 in the codes. More precisely f is …1 if the set ¹x 2 R j x codes .a; b/ and b D f .a/º
is
1 … 1.
342
6 Pmax variations
Lemma 6.63 (For all x 2 R, x # exists). Suppose N is a transitive model of ZFC of height !1 and A !1 is a cofinal set such that A\˛ 2N for all ˛ < !1 . Suppose B !1 , B A and that .N; A; B/ is constructible from a 1 real. Then there is … 1 function f such that for all ˛ 2 B, if .g; h/ 2 H.!1 / and; (1) g is N -generic for Coll .!; A \ ˛/, (2) h is N Œg-generic for Coll .!; ¹˛º/, then f .g; h/ is an N ŒhŒg-generic filter for Coll .!; S / where S D A \ ¹ j ˛ < < ˇº and ˇ is the least element of B above ˛. Proof. Let z 2 R be such that .A; B; N / 2 LŒz. Define f as follows. Suppose .g; h/ is given. Then f .g; h/ D G where G 2 LŒz # , G is N ŒhŒg-generic for Coll .!; S /, S D ˇ \ A n .˛ C 1/ and ˇ is the least element of B above ˇ and G is the least such in LŒz # in the natural wellordering by constructibility. It is easy to verify that 1 G 2 L Œz # where is the least admissible relative to .g; h; z # / and so f is … 1 on its domain. This proves the lemma. t u Theorem 6.64. Suppose X R and that for each z 2 R there exists .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / such that (i) z 2 M , (ii) .M; I/ is strongly X -iterable. Then there is a condition .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax such that (1) X \ M0 2 M0 , (2) hH.!1 /M0 ; X \ M0 i hH.!1 /; X i, (3) hMk W k < !i is X -iterable. Proof. We first prove that for every set Y R such that Y is projective in X and for every real z there exists .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / such that .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable and such that z 2 M . This is immediate. Fix Y R such that Y is projective in X and fix z 2 R. Choose t 2 R and such that Y is definable from t in the structure hV!C1 ; X; 2i:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
343
Let .M; I/ be strongly X -iterable with .z; t / 2 M . It follows that .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable. For every real z there exists .M; I/ such that .M; I/ is strongly X -iterable and such that z 2 M . In particular, .M; I/ is iterable and so for every z 2 R, z # exists. We next prove that every subset of !1 which is coded by a set projective in X is constructible from a real. Suppose A !1 be such that A is coded by a set which is projective in X . Let Y R be the set of reals which code elements of A. Therefore Y is projective in X . Let .M; I/ be such that .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable. Let z be a real which codes M . Thus by absoluteness it follows that A 2 LŒz. We now prove the theorem. Fix X R. We are assuming that there exists .M; I/ such that .M; I/ is strongly X -iterable. We define sequences hNk ; fk ; Ck ; xk I k < !i and hMk ; k ; k I k < !i as follows. Set C0 D !1 . Choose .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / such that .M; I/ is strongly X -iterable and let ı be the Woodin cardinal of M associated to I. Let T0 2 M be a tree on ! ı such that for all M-generic filters g Coll.!; <ı/; pŒT0 \ MŒg D X \ MŒg. The existence of the tree T0 follows from Lemma 6.59. Let M0 D M and let 0 2 M be a normal measure on 0 < ı. Let N0 be the image of .M0 /0 under the !1th iteration of .M0 ; 0 /. Let C1 be the critical sequence of this iteration. Thus (1.1) N0 ZFC, (1.2) Ord \ N0 D !1 , (1.3) C1 is a club in !1 consisting of inaccessible cardinals of N0 . Further for any ˛ < ˇ with ˛; ˇ 2 C1 there exists a canonical elementary embedding j W N0 ! N 0 1 such that cp.j / D ˛ and j.˛/ D ˇ. Let y0 2 R be an index for a … 1 function f0 with the following property. If .˛; g; h/ is such that;
(2.1) ˛ 2 C1 , (2.2) g is N0 -generic for Coll .!; <˛/, (2.3) h is N0 Œg-generic for Coll .!; ¹˛º/, then f0 .˛; g; h/ is an N0 ŒhŒg-generic for Coll .!; S / where S is the interval .˛; ˇ/ and ˇ is the least element of C1 above ˛. Let x0 be a real such that N0 ; M0 ; y0 ; C1 2 LŒx0 with M0 countable in LŒx0 .
344
6 Pmax variations
We continue to define hNk ; fk ; Ck ; xk I k < !i and hMk ; k ; k I k < !i simultaneously by induction on k. Suppose Nk ; fk ; xk ; Mk ; k ; k and CkC1 are given. Choose .MkC1 ; kC1 / 2 H.!1 / such that .MkC1 ; kC1 / is iterable and such that xk 2 MkC1 . Let kC1 2 MkC1 be the measurable cardinal supporting kC1 . Let NkC1 be the image of .MkC1 /kC1 under the !1th iteration of .MkC1 ; kC1 /. Let CkC2 be the critical sequence of this iteration. Thus (3.1) NkC1 ZFC, (3.2) Ord \ NkC1 D !1 , (3.3) CkC2 is a club in !1 consisting of inaccessible cardinals of NkC1 , (3.4) kC1 is the least element of CkC2 , (3.5) Ni NkC1 for all i k, (3.6) Ci CkC2 for all i k C 1, (3.7) Ci \ 2 NkC1 for all i k C 1 and < !1 . Further for any ˛ < ˇ with ˛; ˇ 2 CkC2 there exists a canonical elementary embedding j W NkC1 ! NkC1 such that (4.1) cp.j / D ˛ and j.˛/ D ˇ, (4.2) j.Ni / D Ni for all i k, (4.3) j.Ci / D Ci for all i k C 1. where j.Ni /; j.Ci / are defined in the natural fashion; j.Ni / D [¹j.a/ j a 2 Ni º; Let ykC1 2 R be an index for a .˛; g; h/ is such that;
1 … 1
j.Ci / D [¹j.Ci \ / j < !1 º: function fkC1 with the following property. If
(5.1) ˛ 2 CkC2 , (5.2) g is NkC1 -generic for Coll .!; CkC1 \ ˛/, (5.3) h is NkC1 Œg-generic for Coll .!; ¹˛º/, then fkC1 .˛; g; h/ is an NkC1 ŒhŒg-generic for Coll .!; .˛; ˇ/ \ CkC1 / where ˇ is the least element of CkC2 above ˛. Let xkC1 be a real such that ¹NkC1 ; MkC1 ; ykC1 ; CkC2 º LŒxkC1 and such that MkC1 countable in LŒxkC1 .
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
345
This completes the definition of the sequences hNk ; fk ; Ck ; xk I k < !i and hMk ; k ; k I k < !i. Let 0 be the minimum element of \¹Ck j k < !º and let 1 be least element of \¹Ck j k < !º above 0 . Thus 0 D sup¹ k j k < !º. Choose generics gk ; hk for k < ! such that (6.1) gk Coll .!; Ck \ k / is Nk -generic and gk 2 NkC1 , (6.2) hk Coll .!; ¹ k º/ is Nk Œgk -generic and hk 2 NkC1 . We now define a sequence of generics hGk W k < !i using the functions fk . This definition is really the key to what is going on. We wish to define Gk Coll .!; Ck \ 0 / such that Gk is Nk -generic and such that Nk ŒGk NkC1 ŒGkC1 . There are of course other key properties, these we shall discuss after giving the definition. The generics hGk W k < !i are defined such that the following conditions are satisfied, these conditions uniquely specify the generics. (7.1) Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ k / D gk . (7.2) Gk \ Coll .!; ¹ k º/ D hk . (7.3) For all ˛ 2 CkC1 \ 0 , Gk \ Coll .!; .˛; ˇ// D fk .˛; g; h/ where g D Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ ˛/, h D GkC1 \ Coll .!; ¹˛º/, and ˇ is the least element of CkC1 above ˛. It is straightforward to show the following by induction on . For all k < !, if 2 CkC1 then Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ / is Nk -generic. The key point is that every element of CkC1 is strongly inaccessible in Nk and so the genericity of Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ / follows from the genericity of Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ ˛/ for all ˛ < . This enables one to argue for the genericity of Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ / for
which are limit points of CkC1 . Now suppose that G Coll .!; ¹ 0 º/ is Nk ŒGk -generic for all k < !. Using G we can prolong the generics Gk and define a sequence hGk W k < !i of generics such that: (8.1) Gk Coll .!; Ck \ 1 / and Gk is Nk -generic; (8.2) Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ 1 / D Gk ; (8.3) Gk \ Coll .!; ¹ 1 º/ D G;
6 Pmax variations
346
(8.4) for all ˛ 2 CkC1 \ 1 , Gk \ Coll .!; .˛; ˇ// D fk .˛; g; h/ where g D Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ ˛/, h D GkC1 \ Coll .!; ¹˛º/, and ˇ is the least element of CkC1 above ˛.
For each k < ! let k be the least element of CkC1 above 0 . Thus k is strongly inaccessible in Nk and 1 D sup ¹k j k < !º. Since 1 D sup ¹k j k < !º, for all k < !, Gk is Nk -generic. This follows by an argument similar to that for the genericity of Gk . We now come to the key points. For each k < ! let jk W Nk ! N k be the canonical embedding with critical point 0 and such that jk . 0 / D 1 . Thus for all k < m < !; (9.1) jm .Nk / D Nk and jm .Ck / D Ck , (9.2) jm jNk D jk , (9.3) jk j.Nk /k 2 Nm , where as above jm .Nk / and jm .Ck / are defined in the obvious way. For each k < ! the embedding jk lifts to define an embedding jk W Nk ŒGk ! Nk ŒGk : It follows that for all k < m < !; (10.1) jm jNk ŒGk D jk , (10.2) jk j.Nk ŒGk /k 2 Nm ŒGm ŒG. For each k < ! let Uk be the Nk ultrafilter on 0 which is the image of k under the iteration of .Mk ; k / which sends k to 0 . It is straightforward to show that for all k < !, Uk 2 NkC1 and that Uk D F \ Nk where F is the club filter on 0 as computed in NkC1 . The ultrapower of h.Nk ; Uk / W k < !i is defined as follows. Let U D [¹Uk j k < !º and for each k < ! let where
Nk D Nk0 =U Nk0 D ¹h W 0 ! Nk j h 2 [Ni º
Let h.Nk ; Uk / W k < !i be the ultrapower of h.Nk ; Uk / W k < !i and let j W [¹Nk j k < !º ! [¹Nk j k < !º be the induced embedding. Thus j is a †0 -embedding whose restriction to Nk is fully elementary for each k < !. It follows that for each k < !, j jNk D jk .
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
347
Iterations of h.Nk ; Uk / W k < !i are defined in the natural fashion. As in the case of iterating !-sequences of models (see Definition 4.8) the embeddings that arise j W [¹Nk j k < !º ! [¹Nk j k < !º are †0 elementary embeddings whose restrictions to Nk are fully elementary. It is easy to verify that h.Nk ; Uk / W k < !i is iterable and in fact for all k < !, Nk is the image of Nk under any countable iteration of h.Nk ; Uk / W k < !i. For each k < ! let Ik D INS \ Nk ŒGk where INS is the nonstationary ideal on !1 .D 0 / as computed in NkC1 ŒGkC1 . Thus for all k < !: (11.1) Nk ŒGk ZFC; N ŒGk
(11.2) Nk ŒGk NkC1 ŒGkC1 ; !1 k
N
D !1 kC1
ŒGkC1
D 0 ;
(11.3) Ik P .!1N0 ŒG0 / \ Nk ŒGk is a uniform ideal which is normal relative to functions in Nk ŒGk ; (11.4) Ik 2 NkC1 ŒGkC1 ; (11.5) IkC1 \ Nk ŒGk D Ik . Iterations of hNk ŒGk W k < !i lift iterations of h.Nk ; Uk / W k < !i and so hNk ŒGk W k < !i is iterable in the sense of Definition 4.15. Thus by the definition of hNk ŒGk W k < !i the following hold, (12.1) X \ N0 ŒG0 2 N0 ŒG0 , (12.2) hH.!1 /N0 ŒG0 ; X \ N0 ŒG0 i hH.!1 /; X i, (12.3) If
j W hNk ŒGk W k < !i ! hNk ŒGk W k < !i
is a countable iteration of hNk ŒGk W k < !i then j .X \ N0 ŒG0 / D X \ N0 ŒG0 : We note that (12.3) follows from Lemma 6.61. Define f W !1N0 ŒG0 ! H.!1 /N0 ŒG0 as follows. Suppose ˛ < !1N0 ŒG0 . Then f .˛/ D ¹p 2 Coll.!; ˛/ j p 2 G0 º where for each p 2 Coll.!; ˛/, p is the condition in Coll .!; ¹˛º/ such that dom.p / D dom.p/ ¹˛º and such that p .k; ˛/ D p.k/ for all k 2 dom.p/. For each k < !, let Mk D .Nk ŒGk /k : Thus .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax and .hMk W k < !i; f / is the desired condition.
t u
348
6 Pmax variations
The following theorem is now an immediate corollary. Theorem 6.65. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set X R with X 2 L.R/, there is a condition .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax such that (1) X \ M0 2 M0 , (2) hH.!1 /M0 ; X \ M0 i hH.!1 /; X i, (3) hMk W k < !i is X -iterable.
t u
As a corollary to Theorem 6.64 we obtain Lemma 6.68 which in some weak sense corresponds to Lemma 6.47. As we have already noted, Lemma 6.47 cannot be proved just assuming ADL.R/ . The basic method for proving Lemma 6.68 can be used to prove many similar results, it is also related to additional absoluteness theorems we shall prove for Qmax cf. Theorem 6.85. We need two preliminary lemmas. The first is a corollary of Lemma 6.40. Lemma 6.66. Suppose .M; I/ is a countable iterable structure such that (i) M ZFC, (ii) I 2 M and I is the tower of ideals I<ı as computed in M where ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . Suppose f 2 M , f witnesses ˘+ .!1
t u
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
349
The second lemma we need is a corollary of Theorem 5.23, Lemma 6.44, Lemma 6.45 and the transfer theorem, Theorem 5.36. Lemma 6.67. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose A R and A 2 L.R/. Then there is a countable, A-iterable structure .N; I/ such that (1) N ZFC C ˘ C ˘++ .!1
350
6 Pmax variations
such that if g P is MZ -generic then MZ Œg ˘ C ˘++ .!1
M Œg B0 \ MZ Œg 2 WH Z ;
C MZ / . where D .ıZ C Thus in MZ Œg every set projective in A \ MZ Œg is ıZ -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Let 2 MZ Œg be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal above ıZ . By standard arguments, ıZ is a Woodin cardinal in MZ Œg. Let Y .MZ Œg/ be an elementary substructure such that A \ MZ Œg 2 Y , Y 2 MZ Œg and Y is countable in MZ Œg. Let N be the transitive collapse of Y and let I be the image of .I<ıZ /MZ Œg under the collapsing map. Thus
N ZFC C ˘ C ˘++ .!1
t u
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
351
Proof. Fix A R such that A 2 L.R/. By Lemma 6.58 and Lemma 6.67 there exists a countable, A-iterable, structure .N; I/ such that (1.1) N ZFC C ˘ C ˘++ .!1
Here we use Lemma 6.66 to show that Gˇ exists as required. Let S D ¹ˇ < !1M0 j f .ˇ/ D j0;ˇ C1 .f0 /.ˇ/º: Since .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax , it follows that !1M0 n S 2 .INS /M1 : Let
j W .N; I/ ! .N ; I /
be the limit embedding of the iteration. Let f D j.f0 /. Thus !1N D !1M0 and S D ¹ˇ < !1M0 j f .ˇ/ D f .ˇ/º: Let M0 D N and for each k > 0 let Mk D Mk .
6 Pmax variations
352
Since N 2 M0 ,
.INS /M1 \ N D .INS /M2 \ N ;
and so for all k 2 !,
.INS /MkC1 \ Mk D .INS /MkC2 \ Mk : Thus
.hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax t u
and is as required.
With Theorem 6.65 the analysis of Qmax can easily be carried out as in the case of Qmax . We summarize the results of this in the next two theorems. First we prove the main iteration lemmas for conditions in Qmax . Lemma 6.69. Suppose .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax . Suppose j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i and
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i
are iterations such that j .f / D j .f /. Then hMk W k < !i D hMk W k < !i and j D j . Proof. The proof is identical to the proof of Lemma 6.22 which is the corresponding lemma for Qmax . To illustrate we examine an iteration k W hMk W k < !i ! hMO k W k < !i of length 1 so that k corresponds to a weakly generic ultrapower. Let U [¹.P .!1 //Mk j k < !º be the [¹Mk j k < !º-ultrafilter corresponding to k. Let g D k.f /.!1M0 /. By conditions (6) and (7) in the definition of Qmax , g Coll.!; !1M0 / and g is [¹Mk j k < !º-generic. Again by the definition of Qmax , a set a belongs to U if and only if there exists p 2 g and k 2 ! such that .!1M0 n a/ \ ¹˛ j p 2 f .˛/º 2 .INS /Mk : Thus the iteration k is completely determined by k.f /.!1M0 /. The lemma follows by induction on the length of iterations.
t u
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
353
Lemma 6.70. Suppose h W !1 ! H.!1 / and that I P .!1 / is a normal (uniform/ ideal such that for all A !1 , ¹˛ j h.˛/ is not L.A \ ˛/-generic for Coll.!; ˛/º 2 I: Suppose .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax . Then there is an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that: (1) j.!1M0 / D !1 ;
(2) for all k < !, I \ Mk D INS \ Mk D .INS /MkC1 \ Mk ; (3) j.f / D h modulo I . Proof. This lemma corresponds to Lemma 6.23. Let hhMkˇ W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i be any iteration of hMk W k < !i such that for all ˇ < !1 if j0;ˇ .!1M0 / D ˇ and if h.ˇ/ is an [¹Mkˇ j k < !º-generic filter for Coll.!; ˇ/ then jˇ;ˇ C1 is the corresponding generic elementary embedding. We claim that hhMkˇ W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i is as desired. Suppose A !1 . By assumption ¹˛ < !1 j h.˛/ is not a LŒA \ ˛-generic filter for Coll.!; ˛/º 2 I: Suppose A !1 and A codes the iteration hhMkˇ W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i Then the set of < !1 such that hhMkˇ W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i 2 LŒA \ contains a club in !1 . Further the set of < !1 such that j0; .!1M0 / D also contains a club. Let X !1 be the set of < !1 such that h./ is an [¹Mkˇ j k < !º-generic filter for Coll.!; / and such that j0; .!1M0 / D . Thus !1 n X 2 I . However by the properties of the iteration, X ¹ j j0; C1 .f /./ D h./º and so j0;!1 .f / D h modulo I .
t u
354
6 Pmax variations
Lemma 6.70 can be reformulated as follows. Lemma 6.71. Suppose that p 2 Qmax , .hNk W k < !i; g/ 2 Qmax and that
p 2 .H.!1 //N0 :
Then there exists h 2 N0 such that (1) .hNk W k < !i; h/ 2 Qmax , (2) .hNk W k < !i; h/ < p, (3) ¹˛ < !1N0 j h.˛/ ¤ g.˛/º 2 .INS /N1 . Proof. Since p 2 .H.!1 //N0 , p 2 .Qmax /N0 . For each a 2 .P .!1 //N0 let a be the set of ˛ < !1N0 such that g.˛/ is LŒa \ ˛-generic for Coll.!; ˛/. Let I 2 N0 be the normal ideal generated by the set ¹a j a 2 .P .!1 //N0 º: The key point is that
I .INS /N1 ;
which is easily verified since .hNk W k < !i; g/ 2 Qmax . Let .hMk W k < !i; f / D p: Applying Lemma 6.70 within N0 , there exists an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that: (1.1) j.!1M0 / D !1N0 ;
(1.2) for all k < !, I \ Mk D .INS /N0 \ Mk D .INS /MkC1 \ Mk ; (1.3) j.f / D g modulo I . Let h D j.f /. Thus .hNk W k < !i; h/ 2 Qmax and .hNk W k < !i; h/ < p:
t u
As a corollary to Lemma 6.71 and Lemma 6.68, we obtain the set of conditions specified in Lemma 6.68 is dense in Qmax .
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
355
Corollary 6.72. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose that A R, A 2 L.R/; and that p 2
Qmax .
Then there exists .hNk W k < !i; g/ 2 Qmax
such that: (1) A \ N0 2 N0 ; (2) hH.!1 /N0 ; A \ N0 ; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i; (3) hNk W k < !i is A-iterable; (4) ˘ holds in N0 ; (5) g witnesses ˘++ .!1
t u
356
6 Pmax variations
Proof. This is one theorem about Qmax that is actually much simpler than the corresponding theorem about Qmax or Pmax . The !-closure of Qmax is essentially built into its definition. Suppose hpi W i < !i is a strictly decreasing sequence of conditions in Qmax and that for each i < !, pi D .hMki W k < !i; fi /: Let fO D [¹fi j i < !º. For each i < ! let ji W hMki W k < !i ! hMO ki W k < !i be the iteration such that ji .fi / D fO. This iteration exists since hpi W i < !i is a strictly decreasing sequence in Qmax . By Lemma 4.22, hMO kk W k < !i satisfies the hypothesis of Lemma 4.17 and so by Lemma 4.17, hMO kk W k < !i is iterable. Let O0 M Mi ı D !1 0 D sup ¹ !1 0 j k < !º: For q 2 Coll.!; ı/ let Sq D ¹˛ < ı j q 2 fO.˛/º: Then for each q 2 Coll.!; ı/, Sq 2 MO 00 ; and further
Ok
Sq … .INS /Mk
for each k 2 !. Fix k 2 !. Suppose that A ı and that O kC1
A 2 MO kk n .INS /MkC1 : Then for some q 2 Coll.!; ı/, O kC1
Sq n A 2 .INS /MkC1 : Finally if q1 q2 in Coll.!; ı/ then Sq1 Sq2 . It follows that .hMO kk W k < !i; fO/ 2 Qmax . Further if q 2 Qmax and q < .hMO kk W k < !i; fO/; then q < pi for all i < !. By Corollary 6.72 there exists q 2 Qmax such that q < .hMO kk W k < !i; fO/; and so there exists q 2 Qmax such that q < pi for all i < !.
t u
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
357
We adopt the usual notational conventions. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Let fG D [¹f j .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 G for some hMk W k < !iº: For each condition .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 G there is a unique iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that j.f / D fG . This is the unique iteration such that j.f / D fG . Let IG D [¹.INS /M1 j .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Gº and let
P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M0 j .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Gº:
The basic analysis of Qmax is straightforward, the results are given in the next two theorems. Theorem 6.74. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG !1 -DC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal. Proof. The proof is essentially the same as the proof of Theorem 6.30. Here one uses Lemma 6.70 and the proof of Theorem 6.73. t u Theorem 6.75. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then L.R/Qmax AC : Proof. The proof for Qmax naturally generalizes.
t u
Theorem 6.76. Assume ADL.R/ . Let G Qmax be L.R/-generic and let fG W !1 ! H.!1 / be the function derived from G. Then fG witnesses ˘++ .!1
P .!1 / D [¹P .!1 /M0 j .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Gº where for each .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 G, j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is the (unique) iteration such that j.f / D fG . The theorem is an immediate corollary of Corollary 6.72.
t u
358
6 Pmax variations
As a corollary to the basic analysis of Qmax we obtain Theorem 6.80 which shows that ADL.R/ implies that Qmax is nontrivial in the sense required for the basic analysis summarized in Theorem 6.30. We require a preliminary lemma. Lemma 6.77. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG, for every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. This is the Qmax version of Lemma 4.52. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. From the basic analysis of Qmax summarized in Theorem 6.73 and Theorem 6.74, it follows that H.!2 /L.R/ŒG D H.!2 /L.R/ ŒG: We work in L.R/ŒG. Fix A R with A 2 L.R/. Fix a stationary set S P!1 .H.!2 // and fix a countable elementary substructure X hH.!2 /; A; G; 2i such that X \ H.!2 / 2 S . Let hXi W i < !i be an increasing sequence of countable elementary substructures of X such that X D [¹Xi j i < !º and such that for each i 2 !, Xi 2 XiC1 . Therefore for each i < !, there exists .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 G \ XiC1 satisfying (1.1) Xi \ P .!1 / j.M0 /, (1.2) A \ M0 2 M0 , (1.3) hMk W k < !i is A-iterable, where
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i
is the iteration such that j.f / D fG . Let MX be the transitive collapse of X . We claim that MX is A-iterable. Given this the lemma follows. For each i < ! let .hMki W k < !i; fi / 2 G \ XiC1 be a condition satisfying the requirements (1.1), (1.2) and (1.3). For each i < ! let ji W hMi W k < !i ! hMO i W k < !i k
k
be the iteration of hMki W k < !i such that ji .fi / D fG j.X \ !1 /.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
359
Thus for each i < !, ji 2 MX and MX D [¹ji .M0i / j i < !º: Suppose j W MX ! N is an iteration of MX such that j.!1MX / D and < !1 . For each i < ! let hNki W k < !i D j.hMO ki W k < !i/: Therefore for each i < !, hNki W k < !i is an iterate of hMki W k < !i and the iteration is the unique iteration which sends fi to j.fG jX \ !1 /. By induction on N D [¹N0i j i < !º and so MX is iterable. We finish by analyzing C D [¹j.B/ j B A and B 2 MX º: We must show that C D A \ N . Since MX D [¹ji .M0i / j i < !º it follows that C D [¹j.ji .A \ M0i // j i < !º This is because A \ M0i 2 M0i for each i < !. However for each i < !, hMki W k < !i is A-iterable and so for each i < !, j.ji .A \ M0i // D A \ N0i : This implies that C D A \ N .
t u
As a corollary to Lemma 6.77 and Lemma 4.24 we obtain the following theorem which easily yields a plethora of conditions in Qmax . Theorem 6.78. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG the following holds. Suppose 2 Ord, L .R/ŒG ZFC ; and that L .R/ †1 L.R/: Suppose X L .R/ŒG is a countable elementary substructure with G 2 X . Let MX be the transitive collapse of Y and let IX D .INS /MX : Then for each A R such that A 2 X \ L.R/, .MX ; IX / is A-iterable.
6 Pmax variations
360
Proof. By an analysis of terms L .R/ŒG †1 L.R/ŒG: We prove that for each ˛ < , if L˛ .R/ŒG ZFC then the set ¹Y 2 P!1 .L˛ .R/ŒG/ j MY is iterableº contains a club in P!1 .L˛ .R/ŒG/, where MY is the transitive collapse of Y . Assume toward a contradiction that this fails for some ˛ and let ˛0 be the least such ˛. It follows that ˛0 < ‚L.R/ . This contradicts Lemma 4.24 and Lemma 6.77. Now suppose X L .R/ŒG is a countable elementary substructure with G 2 X . Let Z D ¹˛ 2 X \ j L˛ .R/ŒG ZFC º: Thus Z is cofinal in X \ . Further since L .R/ŒG †1 L.R/ŒG; for each ˛ 2 Z there exists a function F W L˛ .R/ŒG
MX
is A-iterable. Thus MX is A-iterable.
t u
Another corollary of Lemma 6.77 is the following lemma. Lemma 6.79. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG the following hold.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
361
(1) !3 D ‚L.R/ . (2) ı12 D !2 . (3) Suppose S !1 is stationary and f W S ! Ord: Then there exists g 2 L.R/ such that ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ D g.˛/º is stationary. Proof. (2) follows from Theorem 3.16 and Lemma 6.77. By Theorem 6.75, ‚L.R/ !3 in L.R/ŒG since c D !2 in L.R/ŒG. Qmax satisfies the following chain condition in L.R/. Suppose W Qmax ! ‚ is a function. Then the range of is bounded in ‚. This is because there is a map of the R onto Qmax . The usual analysis of terms shows that ‚L.R/ is a cardinal in L.R/ŒG. By Theorem 6.74(1), !1L.R/ and !2L.R/ are cardinals in L.R/ŒG. Therefore (1) follows. Similarly for (3) one can reduce to the case that for some ı < ‚, f W !1 ! ı: and so (3) follows from Theorem 3.42, Lemma 6.77, and Theorem 6.74(2).
t u
As an immediate corollary to Theorem 6.78 we obtain that, assuming ADL.R/ , Qmax is suitably nontrivial as required for the analysis of the Qmax -extension. Let ZFC be any finite fragment of ZFC together with ZFC . Theorem 6.80. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (1) M ZFC , (2) I D .INS /M , (3) A \ M 2 M, (4) hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i, (5) .M; I / is A-iterable, (6) f witnesses ˘++ .!1
6 Pmax variations
362
Proof. Let G Qmax be L.R/-generic. We work in L.R/ŒG. Fix 2 Ord such that L .R/ŒG ZFC ; cof ./ > !1 and such that L .R/ †1 L.R/: Let X L .R/ŒG be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹A; fG º X . Let MX be the transitive collapse of X and let fX be the image of fG under the collapsing map. Let IX D .INS /MX which is the image of INS under the collapsing map. By Theorem 6.78, .MX ; IX / is A-iterable. Therefore h.MX ; IX /; fX i 2 Qmax : By Theorem 6.76, fg witnesses ˘++ .!1
t u
The analysis of L.R/Qmax given by the assumption of the existence of a huge cardinal can now be carried out just assuming ADL.R/ . For example we obtain the following theorem as an immediate consequence of Theorem 6.80, Theorem 6.30, Theorem 6.31, and Theorem 6.53. Theorem 6.81. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 / D P .!1 /G and IG D INS ; (2) every set of reals of cardinality !1 is of measure 0; (3) the reals cannot be decomposed as an !1 union of meager sets; (4) the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense; (5) the function fG witnesses ˘++ .!1
t u
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
363
Corollary 6.82. Assume ZF C AD is consistent. Then so is ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense”:
t u
We continue our analysis of Qmax by proving another absoluteness theorem which suggests that the Qmax model is simply a conditional form of the Pmax model. In Chapter 7 we shall consider other conditional variations of Pmax . The proof of this absoluteness theorem uses the generic elementary embedding associated to the stationary tower forcing. The argument can be adapted to prove the absoluteness theorems for Pmax without using Theorem 2.61. See the remarks preceding Theorem 4.63. Remark 6.83. The most general absoluteness theorem for Qmax requires a restriction on the …2 formulas. With this restriction we shall obtain an absoluteness theorem where only ˘+ .!1
t u
Definition 6.84. Suppose A is an alphabet for a first order language and that A contains 2 and a unary predicate U . A formula of L.A/ is a U -restricted …2 formula if there is a †0 -formula .x; y; z/ in L.A n ¹U º/ such that D 8x8y9zŒ.x/ !
.x; y; z/
where .x/ is the atomic formula U.x/.
t u
Theorem 6.85. Suppose there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above them all. Suppose F W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function which witnesses ˘+ .!1
364
6 Pmax variations
and that hH.!2 /; ŒF INS ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/i : Then
Qmax
hH.!2 /; ŒfG IG ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/iL.R/
:
Proof. From the large cardinal assumptions, AD holds in L.R/. Therefore by Theorem 6.80, Qmax is nontrivial in the sense required for the analysis of Qmax . Fix A R with A 2 L.R/. is a ŒF INS -restricted …2 sentence and so D 8x8y9zŒ.x/ !
.x; y; z/
where is the atomic formula expressing x 2 ŒF INS and is a †0 formula in the language for hH.!2 /; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/i: We assume that the only unary predicate occurring in corresponds to A. Let ı0 be the least Woodin cardinal and let 0 be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal above ı0 . Thus by Theorem 2.13, the set A is <ı0C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. We shall need the following from Section 5.4. Let Q<ı0 be the (countably based) stationary tower defined up to ı0 . Let I<ı0 be the associated directed system of nonstationary ideals. Suppose X V0 is a countable elementary substructure with A 2 X . Let .MX ; IX / be the transitive collapse of .X; I<ı0 /. Then by Lemma 5.23, .MX ; IX / is A-iterable. Assume toward a contradiction that Qmax
hH.!2 /; ŒfG IG ; A; 2iL.R/
::
Then by Theorem 6.30, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax and a pair .h; b/ 2 H.!2 /M such that if h.N ; J /; gi < h.M; I /; f i
then h 2 ŒgJ and hH.!2 /N ; A \ N ; 2i 8z: Œh ; b where .h ; b / D j..h; b// and j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.f / D g. By the proof of Lemma 6.23, there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
365
such that: (1.1) j.!1M / D !1 ; (1.2) INS \ M D I ; (1.3) ¹˛ j j.f /.˛/ D F .˛/º contains a club in !1 . Let f D j.f /, H D j.h/ and let B D j.b/. The sentence holds in V and so there exists a set D 2 H.!2 / such that hH.!2 /; A; 2i
ŒH; B; D:
Choose a countable elementary substructure X V 0 such that
¹M; A; b; h; F; f ; M º X:
Let .MX ; IX / be the transitive collapse of .X; I/, let .fX ; BX ; HX ; DX / be the image of .f ; B; H; D/ under the collapsing map. Thus fX D f jX \ !1 ; HX D H jX \ !1 and
BX D B \ X \ !1 :
Similarly DX D D \ X \ !1 . Let h.N ; J /; gi 2 Qmax be a condition such that MX 2 N and such that MX is countable in N . Choose an iteration, k W .MX ; IX / ! .MQ X ; IQX /; in N of length .!1 /N such that ¹˛ j k.fX /.˛/ ¤ g.˛/º 2 J: The iteration exists by Lemma 6.66 since g 2 .YColl .J //N . Thus h.N ; J /; k.fX /i 2 Qmax and h.N ; J /; k.fX /i < h.M; I /; f i: Since X V0 , hH.!2 /; A \ X; 2iMX
ŒHX ; BX ; DX ;
and so by elementarity Q
hH.!2 /; k.A \ X /; 2iMX
Œk.HX /; k.BX /; k.DX /: The structure .MX ; IX / is A-iterable and so k.A \ X / D A \ MQ X . The formula has only bounded quantifiers and so hH.!2 /; A \ N ; 2iN
Œk.HX /; k.BX /; k.DX /:
Finally k..HX ; BX // is the image of .h; b/ under the iteration of .M; I / which t u sends f to k.fX / and this contradicts the choice of h.M; I /; f i and b.
6 Pmax variations
366
This absoluteness theorem also has a “converse”. Theorem 6.86. Suppose AD holds in L.R/ and that F W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function which witnesses ˘ .!1
¹˛ < !1 j p 2 F .˛/º is stationary. Suppose that for each ŒF INS -restricted …2 sentence, , in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; ŒF INS ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/i if Qmax
hH.!2 /; ŒfG IG ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/iL.R/
:
then hH.!2 /; ŒF INS ; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/i : Then there exists G Qmax such that: (1) G is L.R/-generic; (2) P .!1 / L.R/ŒG; (3) fG D F . Proof. By Theorem 6.80, Qmax is nontrivial in the sense required for the analysis of Qmax . Suppose g 2 ŒF NS : We associate to the function g a filter Fg Qmax defined to be the set of h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that the set
¹˛ < !1 j F .˛/ D j .f /.˛/º
is closed and unbounded in !1 . Suppose g is generic for Qmax ; i. e. that there is an L.R/-generic filter G0 Qmax such that g D fG0 . Then as in the proof of Lemma 6.35, Fg D G0 . Fix D Qmax such that D is dense and D 2 L.R/. Suppose G Qmax is L.R/generic. Then by Lemma 6.34 and by Lemma 6.30(1) the following sentences holds in L.R/ŒG:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
367
(1.1) For all g 2 ŒfG INS , Fg \ D ¤ ;. (1.2) For all g 2 ŒfG INS , Fg is a filter in Qmax . (1.3) For all g 2 ŒfG INS , for all a !1 , a 2 L.g; x/ for some x 2 R. The first sentence is expressible by a ŒfG INS -restricted …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; ŒfG INS ; DiL.R/ŒG ; the second sentence is expressible by a ŒfG INS -restricted …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; ŒfG INS ; Qmax iL.R/ŒG ; and the third sentence is expressible by a ŒfG INS -restricted …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; 2; ŒfG INS iL.R/ŒG : Thus by the hypothesis of the theorem the three sentences hold in V . Therefore for all g 2 ŒF INS , the filter Fg is L.R/-generic and further ŒgINS L.R/ŒFg : For any A !1 there exists g 2 ŒF INS such that A 2 L.F; g/. Let G D FF . Thus it follows that L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG and this proves the theorem.
t u
The next theorem shows that the Qmax -extension satisfies a restricted version of the homogeneity condition satisfied by the Pmax -extension (cf. Theorem 5.67). We fix some notation. Suppose t 2 R and that g Coll.!;
368
6 Pmax variations
Theorem 6.87. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG where G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Suppose X P .!1 / is a nonempty set such that X 2 L.P .!1 //; and such that X is ordinal definable in L.P .!1 // with parameters from R [ ¹ŒfG INS º: Then there exist t 2 R and a term !1 Coll.!;
A D j.a/ j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
is the iteration such that j.f / D fG . By genericity we can suppose that in L.R/, h.M; I /; f i Qmax Œ ; w; ; ŒfG INS where is the term for j.a/. Let t 2 R code h.M; I /; f i. Suppose g Coll.!;
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
369
be the iteration of h.M; I /; f i such that for all ˇ < !1 jˇ;ˇ C1 .j0;ˇ .f //./ D Fg ./ where
M
D !1 ˇ : This uniquely specifies the iteration. We note that for each ˇ < !1 , hM˛ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i 2 LŒt Œg \ Coll.!; </ M !1 ˇ .
where D Therefore by the genericity of g, it follows by induction on ˇ that for each ˇ < !1 , Fg ./ is Mˇ -generic and so jˇ;ˇ C1 exists as specified. A key property of the iteration is that ¹˛ j j0;!1 .f /.˛/ D Fg .˛/º contains
Mˇ
¹!1
j ˇ < !1 º
and so it contains a club in !1 . Let !1 Coll.!;
L.R/ŒG ŒA ; w; ; ŒfG INS : t u
370
6.2.3
6 Pmax variations 2
Qmax
We define and briefly analyze a variant of Qmax which is analogous to 2 Pmax . We denote this partial order by 2 Qmax . We give this example to illustrate how extensions with various ideal structures can be easily obtained by modifying Pmax . Assuming AD holds in L.R/ we shall prove that if G 2 Qmax is L.R/-generic then in L.R/ŒG, INS is not saturated, sat.INS / is !1 -dense and further for each S 2 sat.INS / n INS INS jS is !1 -dense. Before defining 2 Qmax we prove that AC holds in the Qmax -extension of L.R/. Lemma 6.88 is the analog of Lemma 5.16, used to prove that AC holds in the Pmax -extension. Here the situation is even simpler. Lemma 6.88. Suppose that h.N ; J /; gi < h.M; I /; f i in Qmax and let x0 2 N \ R code M Let C be the set of of the Silver indiscernibles of LŒx below !1N and let C 0 be the limit points of C . Suppose that ¹s; t º .P .!1 //M n I is such that both !1M0 n s … I and !1M0 n t … I . Then there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j 2 N ,
¹˛ j j.f /.˛/ ¤ g.˛/º 2 J; 0
and such that for all 2 C , if and only if
2 j.s/ C 2 j.t /
where C is the least element of C above . Proof. The proof is essentially a trivial modification of the proof of Lemma 6.23. Construct the iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1M1 i; in N , by induction such that for all 2 C 0 if g. / is M -generic for Coll.!; / then j;C1 .j0; .f //. / D g. / 0
and such that for all 2 C ,
j0; .s/ 2 G
if and only if j0;ˇ .t / 2 Gˇ C
where ˇ D .
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
371
By the boundedness lemma, Lemma 4.6, for all 2 C , if k W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is given by any iteration of length then k.!1M / D : Therefore the requirements do not interfere with each other. As in the proof of Lemma 6.23, ¹˛ j j.f /.˛/ ¤ g.˛/º 2 J; and so j0;omega1 W .M; I / ! .M!1 ; I!1 / t u
is as desired.
As a corollary to Lemma 6.88 and the basic analysis of L.R/Qmax we obtain the following lemma. The proof is essentially identical to that of Lemma 5.17, using Lemma 6.88 in place of Lemma 5.16. Lemma 6.89. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG
AC :
t u
Lemma 6.89 combined with Theorem 6.78 yields the following variation of Theorem 6.80. Corollary 6.90. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (1) M ZFC C
AC ,
(2) A \ M 2 M, (3) hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i, (4) .M; I / is A-iterable.
t u
Definition 6.91. 2 Qmax is the set of finite sequences hM; I; J; f; Y i which satisfy the following. (1) M ZFC C
AC .
(2) In M, I and J are normal !1 -dense ideals on !1 with I J . (3) .M; I / is iterable. (4) h.M; J /; f i 2 Qmax . (5) Y J n I and jY j !1 in M.
372
6 Pmax variations
(6) For each a; b 2 Y , a M b 2 I or a \ b 2 I . (7) For each a 2 Y , h.M; Ia /; f i 2 Qmax where Ia is the ideal I ja as computed in M. The ordering on 2 Qmax is analogous to Qmax . hM1 ; I1 ; J1 ; f1 ; Y1 i < hM0 ; I0 ; J0 ; f0 ; Y0 i if M0 2 M1 ; M0 is countable in M1 and there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ such that: (1) j.f0 / D f1 ; (2) M0 2 M1 and j 2 M1 ; (3) I0 D I1 \ M0 and J0 D J1 \ M0 ; (4) j.Y0 / Y1 . Remark 6.92.
t u
(1) The requirement (2) of Definition 6.91 implies that J D I ja
for some a 2 P .!1 /M n I . Necessarily, by (5), a \ b 2 I for all b 2 Y . Further iterations of .M; ¹I; J º/ correspond to iterations of .M; I / and so (3) implies that .M; ¹I; J º/ is iterable. (2) Given (3) of Definition 6.91, (4) and (7) become first order conditions on M. For example (4) simply asserts that J is an !1 -dense ideal and g is a function t u related to J in the usual fashion; i. e. g 2 YColl .J /. Lemma 6.93. Suppose that hM; I; J; f; Y i 2 2 Qmax : Suppose that j1 W .M; ¹I; J º/ ! .M1 ; ¹I1 ; J1 º/ and j2 W .M; ¹I; J º/ ! .M2 ; ¹I2 ; J1 º/ are iterations of .M; ¹I; J º/ such that j1 .f / D j2 .f /. Then M1 D M2 and j1 D j2 .
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
Proof. Let
373
a D ¹˛ < !1M j .0; 0/ 2 f .˛/º:
Since h.M; J /; f i 2 Qmax , it follows that a…J and that
!1M n a … J:
Therefore M “a is a stationary, co-stationary, subset of !1 .” Since j1 .f / D j2 .f / it follows that j1 .a/ D j2 .a/. The lemma follows by Lemma 5.15.
t u
Using Corollary 6.90 we trivially obtain the nontriviality of 2 Qmax as required for the analysis of the 2 Qmax -extension. Lemma 6.94. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/; there is a condition hM; I; J; f; Y i 2 2 Qmax such that (1) jY =I j D !1 in M, (2) A \ M 2 M, (3) hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i, (4) .M; I / is A-iterable. Proof. By Corollary 6.90, there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 Qmax such that .M0 ; I0 / satisfies (2)–(4). We may suppose, by modifying f0 is necessary, that for all ˛ < !1M0 , f0 .˛/ is a maximal filter in Coll.!; ˛/. For each ˇ < !1M0 let Sˇ D ¹˛ < !1M0 j ˇ < 1 C ˛ and .0; ˇ/ 2 f0 .˛/º: Define
f W !1M0 ! H.!1 /M0
as follows. Suppose ˛ < !1M0 . Let ˇ be such that ˛ 2 Sˇ . Then f .˛/ D ¹p 2 Coll.!; ˛/ j .0; ˇ/a p 2 f0 .˛/º: Let (1.1) M D M0 , (1.2) Y D ¹Sˇ j ˇ > 0º,
374
6 Pmax variations
(1.3) I D I0 , (1.4) J D I0 jS0 . It follows that hM; I; J; f; Y i 2 2 Qmax and is as required.
t u
The iteration lemmas for 2 Qmax are proved by minor modifications in the arguments used to prove the iteration lemmas for Qmax . The only difference is that the iteration lemmas for 2 Qmax are more awkward to state. Lemma 6.95. Suppose that hM0 ; I0 ; J0 ; f0 ; Y0 i 2 2 Qmax ; hM1 ; I1 ; J1 ; f1 ; Y1 i 2 2 Qmax ; and that hM0 ; I0 ; J0 ; f0 ; Y0 i 2 .H.!1 //M1 : Suppose that Y Y1 , Y 2 M1 and that M1 jY =I1 j D !1 : Then there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ such that j 2 M1 and such that the following hold. (1) ¹˛ < !1M1 j j.f0 /.˛/ ¤ f1 .˛/º 2 I1 . (2) I0 D M0 \ I1 and J0 D M0 \ J1 . (3) j.Y0 /=I1 Y =I1 . Proof. The key point is the following. Suppose jQ W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .MQ 0 ; ¹IQ0 ; JQ0 º/ is a countable iteration and that Q
g Coll.!; !1M0 / is MQ 0 -generic. Then (1.1) there exists an iteration kQ W .MQ 0 ; JQ0 / ! .MQ 1 ; JQ1 / such that
Q kQ ı jQ.f0 /.!1M0 / D g;
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
375
(1.2) for each S 2 jQ.Y0 / there exists an iteration kQS W .MQ 0 ; IQ0 / ! .MQ 1 ; IQ1 / such that
Q kQS ı jQ.f0 /.!1M0 / D g
and such that
Q !1M0 2 kQS .S /:
With this simple observation, the desired iteration, j , is easily constructed in M1 by the usual book-keeping arguments used in the proofs of the earlier iteration lemmas, cf. the proof of Lemma 4.36. The point is that one must associate elements of j.Y0 /, as they are generated in the course of the iteration, to elements of Y . t u We require two other lemmas. The proofs are easy variations of the proofs of Lemma 6.94 and Lemma 6.95. We again leave the details to the reader. Lemma 6.96. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose that hM0 ; I0 ; J0 ; f0 ; Y0 i 2 2 Qmax and that a0 2 J0 . Then there exists hM1 ; I1 ; J1 ; f1 ; Y1 i 2 2 Qmax such that hM1 ; I1 ; J1 ; f1 ; Y1 i < hM0 ; I0 ; J0 ; f0 ; Y0 i and such that
j.a0 / n 5Y1 2 I1
where j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M1 ; ¹I1 ; J1 º/ is the .unique/ iteration such that j.f0 / D f1 .
t u
Lemma 6.97. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose that hM0 ; I0 ; J0 ; f0 ; Y0 i 2 2 Qmax and that a0 2 P .!1 /M0 n J0 . Then there exists hM1 ; I1 ; J1 ; f1 ; Y1 i 2 2 Qmax and b j.a0 / such that hM1 ; I1 ; J1 ; f1 ; Y1 i < hM0 ; I0 ; J0 ; f0 ; Y0 i; b 2 J1 n I1 , and such that
b \ a 2 I1
for all a 2 j.Y0 /, where j W .M0 ; ¹I0 ; J0 º/ ! .M1 ; ¹I1 ; J1 º/ is the .unique/ interation such that j.f0 / D f1 .
t u
376
6 Pmax variations
Using the proof of Lemma 6.95 and of its generalization to sequences of conditions, the analysis of the 2 Qmax extension can be carried out in a manner quite similar to that for the Qmax -extension. The results are summarized in the next theorem where we use the following notation. Suppose G 2 Qmax is L.R/-generic. Let fG D [¹f j hM; I; J; f; Y i 2 Gº: For each condition hM; I; J; Y; f i 2 G there is a unique iteration j W .M; ¹I; J º/ ! .M ; ¹I ; J º/ such that j.f / D fG . We let Y denote j.Y /. Let (1) P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 / \ M j hM; I; J; Y; f i 2 Gº, (2) IG D [¹I j hM; I; J; f; Y i 2 Gº, (3) JG D [¹J j hM; I; J; f; Y i 2 Gº, (4) YG D [¹Y j hM; I; J; f; Y i 2 Gº. Theorem 6.98. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose G 2 Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 / D P .!1 /G ; (2) IG D INS ; (3) for each set A 2 JG there exists Y YG such that jY j D !1 and such that A n 5Y 2 IG I (4) YG is predense in .P .!1 / n IG ; /; (5) For each S 2 P .!1 / n JG , ¹˛ j p 2 fG .˛/º n S 2 JG for some p 2 Coll.!; !1 /; (6) For each S 2 YG and for each T S such that T … IG , ¹˛ j p 2 fG .˛/º n T 2 IG for some p 2 Coll.!; !1 /; (7) JG D sat.IG /.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
377
Proof. The proofs that P .!1 / D P .!1 /G , IG D INS and that L.R/ŒG AC are routine adaptations of earlier arguments. (3) follows from (1), Lemma 6.96, and the genericity of G. (4) follows from (3) given that JG n IG is predense in .P .!1 / n IG ; / which in turn follows from (1), Lemma 6.97, and the genericity of G. (5) and (6) are immediate consequence of (1) and the definition of 2 Qmax . It remains to prove (7). By (1), Lemma 6.97, and the genericity of G, for all A 2 P .!1 / n JG and for all Y YG such that jY j D !1 , there exists B A such that B 2 YG and such that B \ S 2 IG for all S 2 Y . Thus for all A 2 P .!1 / n JG , IG jA is not saturated. Therefore sat.IG / is defined and sat.IG / JG : We finish by calculating sat.IG /. By (6), YG sat.IG /. However by (3), any normal ideal containing YG [ IG must contain JG . Therefore JG sat.IG / and so JG D sat.IG /:
t u
As an immediate corollary to Theorem 6.98 be obtain the following theorem. Theorem 6.99. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose that G 2 Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG: (1) INS is not !2 -saturated, (2) sat.INS / is !1 -dense, (3) for each S 2 sat.INS /, the ideal INS jS is !1 -dense.
t u
6.2.4 Weak Kurepa trees and Qmax The absoluteness theorems suggest that in the model L.R/Qmax one should have all the consequences for hH.!2 /; 2i which follow from the largest fragment of Martin’s Maximum which is consistent with the existence of an !1 -dense ideal on !1 .
378
6 Pmax variations
It is therefore perhaps curious that there is a weak Kurepa tree on !1 in L.R/Qmax . This is the principal result of this section. This result together with the results of the next section show that the existence of a weak Kurepa tree is independent of the proposition that the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense. See Remark 3.57. The following holds in the extension obtained by any Pmax -variation unless one explicitly prevents it: For each A !1 there exists x 2 R such that x # … L.A; x/: For the Pmax -extension this is a corollary of Theorem 5.73(5). 1 Lemma 6.100 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that for each A !1 there exists x 2 R such that x # … L.A; x/:
Suppose that A !1 and let A D sup¹.!2 /LŒZ j Z !1 ; A 2 LŒZ; and RLŒA D RLŒZ º: Then A < !2 . Proof. We first prove the following. (1.1) Suppose that !2 is a countable set. Then !1 is inaccessible in L. /. Choose A0 !1 such that (2.1) 2 LŒA0 , (2.2) !1 D .!1 /LŒA0 , 1 (2.3) LŒA0 2 -Determinacy.
By Jensen’s Covering Lemma, if A !1 and x 2 R are such that x # exists and x … L.A; x/, then A# exists. Therefore, by the hypothesis of the lemma, A#0 exists and so !2 is an indiscernible of LŒA0 . We work in LŒA0 . Let 2 LŒA0 be a countable set of uniform indiscernibles of LŒA0 such that for some x0 2 R \ LŒA0 , #
2 L.; x0 /: Let ˛ be the ordertype of . We can suppose that ! ˛ D ˛ by increasing if necessary. Let M 2 LŒA0 be a countable transitive set such that (3.1) x0 2 M , (3.2) ˛ < !1M , (3.3) M ZFC C “There exist ˛ measurable cardinals ”, (3.4) M is iterable (by linear iterations using the normal measures in M ).
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
379
Since 1 LŒA0 2 -Determinacy;
the transitive set M exists. It follows that there exists an iteration by the normal measures in M , j W M ! M ; such that is M -generic for product Prikry forcing. Thus !1 is inaccessible in M . However x0 2 M and so 2 M Œ : This proves (1.1). Fix A and fix x 2 R such that x # … L.A; x/: Assume toward a contradiction that A D !2 : Then for every set B !1 ,
.A;B/ D !2
where .A;B/ D sup¹.!2 /LŒZ j Z !1 ; .A; B/ 2 LŒZ; and RLŒAŒB D RLŒZ º: Thus we can assume that !1 D .!1 /LŒA and that .A;x/ D !2 . Let 0 be an infinite set of indiscernibles of LŒx with 0 !2 n !1 . Let Z !1 witness that .A;x/ > sup. 0 /. Thus there exists a countable set 2 LŒZ such that (4.1) !2LŒZ , (4.2) 0 , (4.3) x 2 LŒ , (4.4) is countable in LŒ . By (1.1), !1 is inaccessible in LŒ and so by Jensen’s Covering Lemma, x # 2 LŒ LŒZ: This contradicts that RLŒZ D RLŒAŒx .
t u
This (essentially) rules out one method for attempting to have weak Kurepa trees in L.R/P where P is any Pmax variation we have considered so far. Remark 6.101. (1) There are Pmax -variations which yield models in which any previously specified set of reals is !1 -borel in the simplest possible manner, given
380
6 Pmax variations
X R with (say) X 2 L.R/, one obtains in L.R/P that [ \ XD B˛;ˇ ˛
ˇ >˛
for some sequence hB˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i of borel sets. 1 If X is the complete † 3 set then in such an extension there exists A !1 such # that for all t 2 R, t 2 LŒAŒt . Simply choose A such that hx˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i 2 LŒA where for each ˛ < ˇ < !1 , x˛;ˇ 2 H.!1 / is a borel code of B˛;ˇ .
(2) There is an interesting open question. Suppose that INS is !2 -saturated and that P .!1 /# exists. For each A !1 let A be as defined in Lemma 6.100. Must t u A < !2 ? To prove that there are weak Kurepa trees in L.R/Qmax , it is necessary to to find a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax and a tree T 2 M of rank !1 in M such that if h.N ; J /; gi is a condition in Qmax and M 2 N with M countable in N then there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / in N with the following properties. (1) J \ M D I . (2) j.f / D g modulo J . (3) There is a cofinal branch b of j.T / such that b … M . The next lemma identifies the requirements which we shall use. Lemma 6.102 (ZFC ). Suppose that f is a function which witnesses ˘+ .!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
381
(6) For each limit ˛ < !1 , ¹ˇ < !1 j xˇ˛ 2 T º contains a club in !1 where xˇ˛ D [¹h˛ .s/ j s f .ˇ/º: Proof. This is a routine construction.
t u
The role of g in the conditions specified in Lemma 6.102 is simply to control the sets T˛ , for example it follows that T˛ Tˇ whenever ˛ < ˇ. Let T be the set of hM; I; f; .T; g; h/i such that (1) h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax , (2) f witnesses ˘++ .!1
382
6 Pmax variations
The following is the key to the construction. Suppose j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M; I / is a countable iteration of .M0 ; I0 / and that b is a M-generic branch of j.T0 /. Suppose G is MŒb-generic for Coll.!; !1M / and let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the corresponding generic elementary embedding. Then there exists G such that G is M -generic for Coll.!; !1M / and such that b 2 j .j .j.T0 /// where j W .M ; I / ! .M ; I /; where M is the generic ultrapower of M given by G , and where j is the corresponding elementary embedding. In this we are identifying generic ultrapowers with their transitive collapses (as usual). Given this the construction is straightforward. The existence of G follows from the mutual genericity of b and G relative to M and the properties of j.T0 ; g0 ; h0 / D .T; g; h/ in M. There are two relevant points. (2.1) .T; g; h/ satisfies in M the conditions (1)–(6) of Lemma 6.102 and further .T ; g ; h / satisfies these conditions in M where .T ; g ; h / is the image of .T; g; h/ under the iteration associated to the generic ultrapower given by G. (2.2) T 2 M and
g D g j!1M :
Thus by the mutual genericity of b and G, it follows that b is a M -generic branch of T . Therefore by clause (5) of the conditions set forth in Lemma 6.102, there exists an M -generic G such that b D ¹h˛ .s/ j s 2 G º where ˛ D !1M .
t u
From the previous lemmas and the basic analysis of Qmax it follows that there is a weak Kurepa tree in L.R/Qmax . Recall that if G Qmax is L.R/-generic then the associated function fG witnesses ˘++ .!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
383
Proof. (2) is an immediate consequence of (1). We prove (1) which really is an immediate consequence of Lemma 6.103 and the basic analysis of L.R/ŒG given in Theorem 6.30. By Theorem 6.30 (and Theorem 6.80) there exist ¹.T0 ; g0 ; h0 /; D0 º 2 M0 and h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 G; such that j0 ..T0 ; g0 ; h0 // D .T; g; h/ and j0 .D0 / D D where j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration such that j0 .f0 / D fG . By Theorem 6.80 there exists a condition h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i such that f1 witnesses ˘++ .!1
6.2.5
KT
Qmax
As our next example of a variant of Qmax we define a partial order KT Qmax . The partial order KT Qmax is obtained from Qmax by simply changing the definition of the order. Our goal is to produce a model in which the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense and in which there are no weak Kurepa trees on !1 . By Lemma 6.51, if there is an !1 -dense ideal on !1 then there is a Suslin tree. Thus one cannot obtain a model in which there is an !1 -dense ideal on !1 and in which there are no weak Kurepa trees, by sealing trees. We shall also state as Theorem 6.121, the absoluteness theorem for the KT Qmax extension which is analogous to the absoluteness theorem (Theorem 6.84) which we proved for the Qmax -extension.
384
6 Pmax variations
Definition 6.105. Let KT Qmax be the partial order obtained from Qmax as follows: KT
Qmax D Qmax ;
but the order on KT Qmax is the following strengthening of the order on Qmax . A condition h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i if h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i relative to the order on Qmax and if addition the following holds. Let j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the (unique) iteration such that j.f0 / D f1 . Suppose b !1M1 , b 2 M1 and b \ ˛ 2 M0 for all ˛ < !1M1 . Then b 2 M0 .
t u
The iteration lemmas necessary for the analysis of KT Qmax are an immediate corollary of the following lemmas. Lemma 6.106 (ZFC + ˘+ .!1
of length !1 such that: (1) F D j.f / on a club in !1 ; (2) if b !1 is a set such that b \ ˛ 2 M for all ˛ < !1 , then b 2 M : Proof. For each a 2 H.!1 / let M.a/ D L˛ .b [ ¹aº/ where b is the transitive closure of a and ˛ is the least ordinal such that L˛ .b/ is admissible. Since F witnesses ˘+ .!1
(1.1) Gˇ is M.Mˇ ; h ˛ W ˛ < ˇi/-generic for Coll.!; !1 ˇ /,
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
385
(1.2) if j0;ˇ .!1M0 / D ˇ and if M
F .ˇ/ Coll.!; !1 ˇ / is a filter which is M.Mˇ ; h ˛ W ˛ < ˇi/-generic then Gˇ D F .ˇ/: This iteration is easily constructed. Since F witnesses ˘+ .!1
t u
386
6 Pmax variations
Lemma 6.107 (ZFC + ˘+ .!1
(iii) !1
MkC1
D !1
,
(iv) IkC1 \ Mk D Ik , (v) fkC1 D fk , (vi) if C 2 Mk is closed and unbounded in !1M0 then there exists D 2 MkC1 such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ MkC1 . Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i of length !1 such that: (1) F D j.f0 / on a club in !1 ; (2) if b !1 is a set such that b \ ˛ 2 [Mk for all ˛ < !1 , then b 2 [Mk :
t u
Suppose G KT Qmax is L.R/-generic. Let fG D [¹f j h.M; I /; f i 2 G for some M; I º: For each condition h.M; I /; f i 2 G there is a unique iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.f / D fG . Let IG D [¹I j h.M; I /; f i 2 G for some M; f º and let P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; f i 2 Gº: Using Lemma 6.106 and Lemma 6.107 the analysis of Qmax generalizes to yield the analogous results for KT Qmax . However for this we assume the existence of a huge cardinal so that Lemma 6.47 holds. This gives a suitably rich collection of conditions h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that ˘ holds in M. Within these conditions Lemma 6.106 and Lemma 6.107 can be applied. We note that the conclusion of Lemma 6.106 is false in L.R/Qmax . This shows that some additional assumption is required, in particular Lemma 6.106 cannot be proved from just ˘+ .!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
Theorem 6.108. Assume there is a huge cardinal. Then mogeneous. Suppose G KT Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then
KT
387
Qmax is !-closed and ho-
L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) there are no weak Kurepa trees; (5) for every A !1 there exists B !1 such that A 2 LŒB and such that for all S !1 if S \ 2 LŒB for all < !1 then S 2 LŒB. Proof. By Lemma 6.47, for every set A R with A 2 L.R/ there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that (1.1) A \ M 2 M, (1.2) hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i, (1.3) .M; I / is A-iterable, (1.4) ˘ holds in M, (1.5) f witnesses ˘++ .!1
6 Pmax variations
388
Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 G and let j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be the iteration such that j0 .f0 / D fG . Suppose b !1 and that b \ ˛ 2 M0 for all ˛ < !1 . Then b 2 M0 . Choose h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i 2 G, and b1 2 M1 such that h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i and such that j1 .b1 / D b where j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / is the iteration such that j1 .f1 / D fG . Let k W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M; I / be the iteration such that k.f0 / D f1 . Thus k 2 M1 and j1 .M/ D M0 . Further b1 \ 2 M !1M .
for all < Therefore by the definition of the order in KT Qmax , b1 2 M. This implies that b 2 M0 . We now prove (5). Fix X0 !1 with X0 2 L.R/ŒG. By (1) there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 G and a set b0
!1M0
such that b0 2 M0 and j.b0 / D X0 where j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
is the unique iteration such that j.f0 / D fG . We work in L.R/ and we assume that the condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i forces that X0 D j.b0 / is a counterexample to (5). Let z 2 R be any real such that M0 2 LŒz and M0 is countable in LŒz. For each i !, Let i be the i th Silver indiscernible of LŒz. Let k W L! Œz ! L! Œz be the canonical embedding such that cp(k) = 0 and let L! Œz D ¹k.f /.0 / j f 2 L! Œzº: Let U be the L! Œz-ultrafilter on 0 given by k, U D ¹A 0 j A 2 L! Œz; 0 2 k.A/º: Thus L! Œz Š Ult.L! Œz; U / and k is the associated embedding. For each X P .0 / \ L! Œz if X 2 L! Œz and jX j 0 in L! Œz then U \ X 2 L! Œz. Therefore .L! Œz; U / is naturally iterable.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
389
Let g Coll.!; <0 / be L! Œz-generic. Let N D L! ŒzŒg. Therefore 0 D !1N and the ultrafilter U defines an ideal I on !1N with I N . Further for each X 2 N if jX j !1N in N then I \ X 2 N . As in the proof of Theorem 6.64, if S then Coll .!; S / the restriction of Coll.!; < / to S . Thus if ˛ < ˇ then Coll.!; <ˇ/ Š Coll.!; <˛/ Coll .!; Œ˛; ˇ//: Suppose that k W .L! Œz; U / ! .k.L! Œz/; k.U // is a countable iteration and that h Coll .!; Œ0 ; k.0 /// is k.L! Œz/Œg-generic. Then k lifts to define an elementary embedding kQ W N ! NQ where NQ D k.L! Œz/ŒgŒh. kQ is naturally interpreted as an iteration of .N; I /. We abuse our conventions and shall regard .N; I / as an iterable structure restricting to elementary embeddings arising in this fashion. For any set S !1N , if S is stationary in N then ˘ holds in N on S . Let Fg W !1N ! N be the function such that for all ˛ < !1N , Fg .˛/ is the filter in Coll.!; 1 C ˛/ given by g and ˛. Thus Fg .˛/ D ¹p 2 Coll.!; 1 C ˛/ j p 2 gº where for each p 2 Coll.!; 1 C ˛/, p 2 Coll.!;
p .k; ˛/ D p.k/:
For each ˇ < !1N let Tˇ D ¹˛ j .0; ˇ/ 2 Fg .˛/º: !1N i
2 N and hTˇ W ˇ < !1N i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint Thus hTˇ W ˇ < sets which are positive relative to I . Fix a set S 0 such that S 2 L! Œz, S is stationary in L! Œz and S … U . Thus S !1N , S 2 N , S is stationary in N , and S … I . For each or each ˇ < !1N , let Sˇ D Tˇ n S . Thus hSˇ W ˇ < !1N i is a sequence in N of pairwise disjoint I -positive sets each disjoint from S . By the proof of Lemma 7.7, there is an iteration j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M1 ; I1 / such that j0 2 N and such that:
390
6 Pmax variations
(2.1) for each s !1M1 , if s … I1 then S˛ n s 2 INS for some ˛ < !1 ; (2.2) if b !1M1 is a set in N such that for all ˛ < !1M1 , b \ ˛ 2 M1 ; then b 2 M1 . Thus I \ M1 D I1 . Let f1 D j0 .f0 / and let b1 D j0 .b0 /. We come to the key points. First, N D L! Œy1 where y1 !1N and second, the proof Lemma 6.106 can be applied to .N; I /. Let h.M2 ; I2 /; f i be any condition in KT Qmax such that N 2 M2 , N is countable in M2 and such that ˘ holds in M2 . Then there is an iteration k W .N; I / ! .N ; I / in M2 such that (3.1) k .!1N / D .!1 /M2 , (3.2) I2 \ N D I , (3.3) if b !1M2 is a set in M2 such that b \ ˛ 2 N for all ˛ < !1 , then b 2 N : Let f2 D k .f1 /, b2 D k .b1 / and let y2 D k .y1 /. Thus (4.1) h.M2 ; I2 /; f2 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i, (4.2) b2 D j.b0 / where j is the embedding given by the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends f0 to f2 , (4.3) b2 .!1 /M2 , (4.4) y2 .!1 /M2 , (4.5) b2 2 .LŒy2 /M2 , (4.6) if b !1M2 is a set in M2 such that for all ˛ < !1M2 , b \ ˛ 2 LŒy2 ; then b 2 LŒy2 . Now suppose G KT Qmax is L.R/-generic and that h.M2 ; I2 /; f2 i 2 G. Let X0 D j0 .b0 / where j0 is the elementary embedding given by the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends f0 to fG . Similarly let j2 W .M2 ; f2 / ! .M2 ; I2 / be the iteration such that j2 .f2 / D fG . Let Y0 D j.y2 /. Now by the claim proved above, in L.R/ŒG if B !1 is a set such that for all ˛ < !1 , B \ ˛ 2 M2 ;
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
391
then B 2 M2 . By elementarity, since (4.6) holds in M2 , if B !1 , B 2 M2 and if B \ ˛ 2 LŒY0 for all ˛ < !1 , then B 2 LŒY0 . Therefore if B !1 , B 2 L.R/ŒG and if B \ ˛ 2 LŒY0 for all ˛ < !1 , then B 2 LŒY0 . This is a contradiction since X0 2 LŒY0 and Y0 !1 . t u Remark 6.109. Theorem 6.108(5) is a useful approximation to ˘ and this principle serves successfully in place of ˘ in the proofs of Lemma 6.106 and Lemma 6.107 (cf. Lemma 6.118). Theorem 6.108(5) is in some sense a feature of the KT Qmax -extension which is analt u ogous to that of the Pmax extension given in Theorem 5.73(5). Theorem 6.108 can be proved just assuming ADL.R/ . We briefly sketch the argument which in essence involves exploiting Theorem 6.108(5). First one refines the partial order, Qmax , defining a partial order KT Qmax which is the appropriate analog of KT Qmax . Definition 6.110. Let KT Qmax Qmax be the partial order obtained from Qmax as follows. KT Qmax is the set of .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax such that for all a 2 [¹Mk j k < !º if a
!1M0
and if a \ ˛ 2 M0
!1M0 ,
for all ˛ < then a 2 M0 . The order on KT Qmax is the following strengthening of the order from Qmax . A condition .hNk W k < !i; g/ < .hMk W k < !i; f / if .hNk W k < !i; g/ < .hMk W k < !i; f / relative to the order on Qmax and if the following holds. Let j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i M
be the (unique) iteration such that j.f / D g. Suppose b !1 0 , b 2 [¹Nk j k < !º and
b \ ˛ 2 M0 M
for all ˛ < !1 0 . Then b 2 M0 . Lemma 6.106 easily generalizes to the following lemma.
t u
392
6 Pmax variations
Lemma 6.111 (ZFC + ˘+ .!1
of length !1 such that: (1) F D j.f / on a club in !1 ; (2) if b !1 is a set such that b \ ˛ 2 M0 for all ˛ < !1 , then b 2 M0 :
t u
The analysis of Qmax generalizes to KT Qmax using the proof of Lemma 6.111 and using Theorem 6.113 to obtain the necessary conditions. One obtains Theorem 6.113 by modifying the proof of Theorem 6.64. (6) is the key requirement, the other requirements are automatically satisfied by the condition produced in the proof of Theorem 6.64. The modification of the proof of Theorem 6.64 involves proving the following strengthening of Lemma 6.63. Lemma 6.112 (For all x 2 R, x # exists). Suppose N is a transitive model of ZFC of height !1 and A !1 is a cofinal set such that A\˛ 2N for all ˛ < !1 . Suppose B !1 , B A and that .N; A; B/ is constructible from a real. Let z 2 R be such that .N; A; B/ 2 LŒz and such that .N; A; B/ is definable from .!1V ; z/ in LŒz. Then there exist x 2 R and a function f W H.!1 / ! H.!1 / such that f is …11 .x/ and such that the following hold. (1) For all ˛ 2 B, if .g; h/ 2 H.!1 / and if a) g is N -generic for Coll .!; A \ ˛/, b) h is N Œg-generic for Coll .!; ¹˛º/, then f .g; h/ is an N ŒhŒg-generic filter for Coll .!; S / where S D A \ ¹ j ˛ < < ˇº and ˇ is the least element of B above ˛.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
393
(2) Suppose ı is an indiscernible of L.x/ and ı < !1 . Suppose H Coll .!; B \ ı/ is L.x/-generic and g Coll .!; A \ ı/ is N -generic. Suppose that for all ˛ 2 B \ ı, gjColl .!; S / D f .g; h/ where h D H jColl .!; ¹˛º/, S D A \ ¹ j ˛ < < ˇº and ˇ is the least element of B above ˛. Finally, suppose b ı, b 2 L.x/ŒH and b \ 2 N Œg for all < ı. Then b 2 N Œg. Proof. Let x 2 R with z recursive in x and let f W H.!1 / ! H.!1 / …11 .x/
be any definable function which satisfies (1). These exist by Lemma 6.63. It follows that f must satisfy (2).
t u
Using Lemma 6.112 in the proof of Theorem 6.64 yields the requisite strengthening of Theorem 6.65. Theorem 6.113. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for every set A R with A 2 L.R/ there is a condition .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax such that the following hold. (1) A \ M0 2 M0 . (2) hH.!1 /M0 ; A \ M0 ; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i. (3) hMk W k < !i is A-iterable. (4) ˘ holds in M0 . (5) f witnesses ˘+ .!1
t u
6 Pmax variations
394
We illustrate the use of Theorem 6.113 in the analysis of KT Qmax . Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax , .hNk W k < !i; g/ 2 Qmax , .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 .H.!1 //N0 and that .hNk W k < !i; g/ satisfies the conditions (1)–(6) of Theorem 6.113 with A D ;. By Lemma 6.111, there exists in N0 an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that in N0 on a club in
!1N0
j.f / D g and such that if b !1N0 is a set in N0 satisfying b \ 2 M0
for all < !1N0 then b 2 M0 . Suppose b !1N0 , and that
b 2 [¹Nk j k < !º; b \ 2 M0
for all < !1N0 . Then by condition (6), b 2 N0 and so b 2 M0 . Thus .hMk W k < !i; f / < .hNk W k < !i; j.f // in KT Qmax . The basic analysis of KT Qmax is easily carried out. This yields the following theorem. Suppose G KT Qmax is L.R/-generic. Let fG D [¹f j .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 G for some hMk W k < !iº: For each condition .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 G there is a unique iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i: such that j.f / D fG . This is the unique iteration such that j.f / D fG . Let IG D [¹.INS /M1 j .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Gº and let
P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; f i 2 Gº:
Theorem 6.114. Assume ADL.R/ . Then KT Qmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Suppose G KT Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
395
(1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) fG witnesses ˘++ .!1
t u
This suffices for the consistency result. With just a little more work one can easily prove the following lemmas which are the relevant versions of Lemma 6.77 and Lemma 6.79. This in turn leads to absoluteness theorems for the KT Qmax -extension of L.R/. Lemma 6.115. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose G KT Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG, for every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº t u
contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X .
The proof of Lemma 6.116 follows that of Theorem 6.78 using Lemma 6.115 in place of Lemma 6.77. Lemma 6.116. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose G Then in L.R/ŒG the following holds. Suppose > !2 , L .R/ŒG ZFC ;
KT
Qmax is L.R/-generic.
and that L .R/ †1 L.R/: Suppose X L .R/ŒG is a countable elementary substructure with G 2 X . Let MX be the transitive collapse of Y and let IX D .INS /MX : Then for each A R such that A 2 X \ L.R/, .MX ; IX / is A-iterable.
t u
Putting everything together we obtain Theorem 6.117 which is a strengthening of Theorem 6.80. The additional property (7) comes from Theorem 6.114(5).
396
6 Pmax variations
Theorem 6.117. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/, there is a condition h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax such that the following hold. (1) M ZFC . (2) I D .INS /M . (3) A \ M 2 M. (4) hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i. (5) .M; I / is A-iterable. (6) f witnesses ˘++ .!1
ha˛ W ˛ < !1 i
of countable transitive sets with the following property. For all A !1 there exists a set C !1 , closed and unbounded in !1 , such that for all ˛ 2 C if ˛ is a limit point of C then .A \ ˛; C \ ˛/ 2 a˛ : Lemma 6.118 (ZFC + ˘+ .!1
of length !1 such that:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
397
(1) F D j.f / on a club in !1 ; (2) if b !1 is a set such that b \ ˛ 2 M for all ˛ < !1 , then b 2 M : Proof. As in the proof of Lemma 6.106 we use the following notation. For each a 2 H.!1 / let M.a/ D L˛ .b [ ¹aº/ where b is the transitive closure of a and ˛ is the least ordinal such that L˛ .b/ is admissible. Let B !1 be such that (1.1) .F; M/ 2 LŒB, (1.2) for all S !1 if
S \ 2 LŒB
for all < !1 then S 2 LŒB. Since F 2 LŒB, !1LŒB D !1 and so ˘+ holds in LŒB. Let ha˛ W ˛ < !1 i 2 LŒB be a sequence which witnesses ˘+ in LŒB. Let h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i 2 LŒB be an iteration of .M; I / of length !1 such that for all ˇ < !1 , M
(2.1) Gˇ is M.Mˇ ; ha˛ W ˛ < ˇi/-generic for Coll.!; !1 ˇ /, M
(2.2) if F .ˇ/ is M.Mˇ ; ha˛ W ˛ < ˇi/-generic for Coll.!; !1 ˇ / and if then Gˇ D F .ˇ/.
j0;ˇ .!1M0 / D ˇ
This iteration is easily constructed in LŒB. A key property of the iteration is the following one. Suppose ˇ < !1 and that t 2 aˇ . Then t 2 Mˇ C1 or t … M!1 : This follows the genericity requirement of (2.1). Since F witnesses ˘+ .!1
398
6 Pmax variations
(3.1) A \ 2 a . (3.2) F ./ is M.A \ /-generic for Coll.!; /. (3.3) j0; .!1M0 / D and .b \ ; h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i/ 2 M.A \ /: By (2.1) and (2.2), for each such , G D F ./ and so b\ 2 M or b\ … M C1 . But if b \ … M C1 then b \ … M!1 which is a contradiction. Hence b \ 2 M . Thus for a stationary set of < !1 , b \ 2 M and so b 2 M!1 . In summary we have proved that if b !1 , b 2 LŒB and if b \ 2 M!1 for all < !1 , then b 2 M!1 . Now suppose b !1 , b 2 V , and that b \ 2 M!1 for all < !1 . Then
b \ 2 LŒB
for all < !1 since M!1 2 LŒB. Therefore b 2 LŒB by the key property of B, and so b 2 M!1 . Therefore the iteration has the desired properties in V . t u There are absoluteness theorems corresponding to the details to the reader. Theorem 6.121 corresponds to Theorem 6.85.
KT
Qmax . We state one, leaving
Definition 6.119. ˆ˘ : For all X !1 there is a sequence ha˛ W ˛ < !1 i of elements of H.!1 / such that for all Y !1 if Y \ ˇ 2 L.X; ha˛ W ˛ < !1 i/ for all ˇ < !1 then contains a club in !1 .
¹˛ < !1 j Y \ ˛ 2 a˛ º t u
The sentence ˆ˘ is a weakening of the principle used in place of ˘ in Lemma 6.118. It is also sufficient to prove the requisite iteration lemmas for KT Qmax . ˆ˘ is implied by ˘+ . The absoluteness theorem for KT Qmax requires the following iteration lemma which is easily proved using Lemma 6.66 and the proof of Lemma 6.118.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
399
Lemma 6.120 (ˆ˘ ). Suppose F W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function which witnesses ˘ .!1
(i) M ZFC, (ii) I 2 M and I is the tower of ideals I<ı as computed in M where ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . Suppose f 2 M , f witnesses ˘+ .!1
t u
Recall that a tree T ¹0;1º
KT Q
hH.!2 /; ŒfG IG ; B; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/iL.R/
max
:
t u
400
6 Pmax variations
We end this section with a sketch of the proof of Theorem 5.75. For this it is convenient to make the following definition. A tree T ¹0;1º
t u
It follows, by absoluteness and reflection, that the set of weakly special trees of cardinality !1 is †1 definable in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i using !1 as a parameter. This leads to a strengthening of the sentence ˆ˘ . Definition 6.123. ˆC ˘ : For all A !1 there exists B !1 such that (1) A 2 LŒB, (2) the tree TB is weakly special where TB D ¹0;1º
t u
is provably equivalent to the assertion that a certain …2 By the remarks above, sentence holds in the structure, hH.!2 /; 2i:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
401
Therefore by the absoluteness theorem, Theorem 4.64, ˆC ˘ (if appropriately consistent) is a consequence of the axiom ./. Note that while ˆ˘ is consistent with CH, (˘C implies ˆ˘ ); if for all A !1 , A# exists, then ˆC ˘ implies :CH. Theorem 5.75 is an immediate corollary of the following theorem. Theorem 6.124. Assume the axiom ./. Then ˆC ˘ holds. Proof. By Theorem 4.60, it suffices to prove the following. Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 Pmax : Then there exist h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 Pmax and b1 2 .P .!1 //M1 such that (1.1) h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i, (1.2) a1 2 LŒb1 , (1.3) Tb1 is weakly special in M1 where Tb1 D .¹0;1º
!1M
then d 2 LŒb. j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
be an iteration such that j0 2 M and such that I0 D I \ M0 : Let x 2 R code M. By Theorem 5.34 there exist a transitive inner model N containing the ordinals and ı < !1 such that
6 Pmax variations
402
(3.1) N ZFC, (3.2) x 2 N , (3.3) ı is a Woodin cardinal in N . Let g0 be N -generic for the partial order .Coll.!1 ; R//N and let g1 be N Œg0 -generic for Coll.!;
j.j0 / W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
is an iteration in N such that I0 D .INS /N \ M0 : Further there exists b1 2 N such that (5.1) b1 !1N , (5.2) j.j0 /.a0 / 2 LŒb1 , (5.3) if b 2 P .!1 /N is a set such that b \ ˛ 2 LŒb1 for all ˛ < !1N , then b 2 LŒb1 : Let
N
T D ¹0;1º
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
403
N
(6.3) if s 2 ¹0;1º!1 \ N Œg0 Œg1 Œg is a branch of T then s 2 N Œg0 Œg1 . Let g2 P be N Œg0 Œg1 -generic and let g3 .Coll.!1 ; <ı//N Œg0 Œg1 Œg2 be N Œg0 Œg1 Œg2 -generic. Let I1 D .INS /N Œg0 Œg1 Œg2 Œg3 and let M1 D V \ N Œg0 Œg1 Œg2 Œg3 where < !1 is the least strongly inaccessible cardinal in N above ı. ı is a Woodin cardinal in N and so it follows that ı is a Woodin cardinal in N Œg0 Œg1 Œg2 . Thus by Theorem 2.61, I1 is presaturated in N Œg0 Œg1 Œg2 Œg3 . Since N contains the ordinals it follows by Theorem 3.10 that .M1 ; I1 / is iterable. Thus h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i 2 Pmax and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i.
t u
6.2.6 Null sets and the nonstationary ideal One can define variations of Qmax which yield generic extensions of L.R/ in which the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense and in which some of the consequences of CH hold. These include many of the consequences which persist after adding !2 Sacks reals to a model of CH. For example one can arrange that there is a selective ultrafilter on ! which is generated by !1 many sets. We define as our next variation of Qmax a partial order M Qmax . Our goal here is to obtain a model in which the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense and in which there is a set X R of cardinality !1 such that X is not of measure 0. By Theorem 6.81, assuming ADL.R/ , in L.R/Qmax every set of reals which has cardinality !1 is of measure 0. Actually in the model we obtain something much stronger is true. There exists a sequence hB˛ W ˛ < !1 i of borel subsets of Œ0;1 such that (1) for all ˛ < !1 , .B˛ / D 1, (2) if B Œ0;1 and .B/ D 1 then there exists ˛ < !1 such that B˛ B. This implies that the partial order of the borel sets of positive measure is !1 -dense and this is easily seen to hold after adding !2 Sacks reals to a model of CH. We shall also state as Theorem 6.139, an absoluteness theorem for the M Qmax extension which is analogous to the absoluteness theorem, Theorem 6.84, we proved for the Qmax -extension. It is convenient to work with a fragment of ZFC which is stronger then ZFC . Let ZFC denote ZFC C Powerset C †1 -Replacement:
404
6 Pmax variations
We fix some notation. We let A denote the following partial order. This is Amoebaforcing scaled by 1=2. Conditions are perfect sets X Œ0;1 such that .X / > 1=2 and such that .X \ O/ > 0 for all open sets O Œ0;1 with X \ O ¤ ;. The latter condition serves to make A separative. The order on A is by set inclusion. Suppose G A is V -generic and in V ŒG let X D \¹P
V ŒG
j P 2 Gº
V ŒG
where P denotes the closure of P computed in V ŒG. This is P as computed in V ŒG. Then X has measure 1=2 and every member of X is random over V . Suppose I is a uniform, countably complete, ideal on !1 and F W !1 ! P .Œ0;1/: Let YA .F; I / be the set of all pairs .S; P / such that the following hold. (1) S !1 and S … I . (2) P Œ0;1 and P 2 A. (3) Suppose hPk W k < !i is a maximal antichain in A below P . Then ¹˛ 2 S j F .˛/ 6 Pk for all k < !º 2 I: (4) If Q P is a perfect set of measure > 1=2 then ¹˛ 2 S j F .˛/ Qº … I: (5) For all ˛ 2 S , .F .˛// D 1=2. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 and that F is a function such that YA .F; I / is nonempty. Suppose .S1 ; P1 / 2 YA .F; I /, .S2 ; P2 / 2 YA .F; I / and that S1 S2 . Then P1 P2 . Therefore if G P .!1 / n I is a filter in .P .!1 / n I; / then HG D ¹P 2 A j .S; P / 2 YA .F; I / for some S 2 Gº generates a filter in A. Lemma 6.125 (ZFC ). Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 and F W !1 ! P .Œ0;1/ is a function such that YA .F; I / is nonempty. Suppose .S1 ; P1 / 2 YA .F; I /. (1) Suppose P2 is a perfect subset of P1 and P2 2 A. Let S2 D ¹˛ 2 S1 j F .˛/ P2 º: Then .S2 ; P2 / 2 YA .F; I /.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
405
(2) Suppose S2 S1 and S2 … I . Then there exists .S3 ; P3 / 2 YA .F; I / such that S3 S 2 . Proof. We first prove (1). To show that .S2 ; P2 / 2 YA .F; I / we have only to prove that condition (3) in the definition of YA .F; I / holds for .S2 ; P2 /. The other clauses are an immediate consequence of the fact that .S1 ; P1 / 2 YA .F; I /. We may assume that .P2 / < .P1 / for otherwise there is nothing to prove. Let hXi W i < !i be a maximal antichain in A below P2 . Let hZi W i < !i be a maximal antichain in A of conditions below P1 which are incompatible with P2 . The key point is that we may assume that for each i < !, .Zi \ P2 / < 1=2; if .Z \ P2 / D 1=2 then there exists a condition W 2 A such that (1.1) W < Z, (1.2) .W \ P2 / < 1=2. Clearly ¹Xi j i < !º [ ¹Zi j i < !º is a maximal antichain below P1 . Since .S1 ; P1 / 2 YA .F; I /, for I -almost all ˛ 2 S1 , there exists i < ! such that either F .˛/ Xi or F .˛/ Zi . For every ˛ 2 S2 and for all i < !, .F .˛// D 1=2, F .˛/ P2 and .P2 \ Zi / < 1=2. Therefore for I -almost all ˛ 2 S2 , F .˛/ Xi for some i < !. Therefore condition (3) holds for .S2 ; P2 / and so .S2 ; P2 / 2 YA .F; I /: This proves (1). We prove (2). Suppose G P .!1 / n I is V -generic for .P .S1 / n I; /. Let j W V ! .M; E/ be the associated generic elementary embedding. Since the ideal I is normal it follows that !1 belongs to the wellfounded part of .M; E/. Since .S1 ; P1 / 2 YA .F; I / it follows that HG is V -generic for A where HG D ¹Q 2 A j j.F /.!1 / Qº: By part (1) of the lemma this induces a complete boolean embedding W RO.AjP1 / ! RO..P .S1 / n I; // where AjP1 denotes the suborder of A obtained by restricting to the conditions below P1 . Let b D ^¹c 2 RO.AjP1 / j S2 .c/º and let hXi W i < !i be a maximal antichain below b of conditions in A. For each i < ! let Ti D ¹˛ 2 S2 j F .˛/ Xi º: For each i < !, if Ti … I then .Ti ; Xi / 2 YA .F; I /. Therefore it suffices to show that for some i < !, Ti … I . Note that if Q 2 AjP1 and T S are such that T .Q/ then ¹˛ 2 T j F .˛/ 6 Qº 2 I: t u This follows from the definition of HG . Hence Ti … I for all i < !.
6 Pmax variations
406
Lemma 6.126 (ZFC ). The following are equivalent. (1) There is a sequence hP˛ W ˛ < !1 i of perfect subsets of Œ0;1 each of positive measure such that if B Œ0;1 is a set of measure 1 then P˛ B for some ˛ < !1 . (2) There is a sequence hP˛ W ˛ < !1 i of perfect subsets of Œ0;1 each of positive measure such that if P Œ0;1 is a perfect set of positive measure then P˛ P for some ˛ < !1 . (3) There is a sequence hP˛ W ˛ < !1 i of perfect subsets of Œ0;1 each of positive measure such that if P Œ0;1 is a perfect set of positive measure then for each > 0 there exists ˛ < !1 such that P˛ P and .P n P˛ / < . (4) There is a sequence hB˛ W ˛ < !1 i of borel subsets of Œ0;1 such that each B˛ is of measure 1 and such that if B Œ0;1 is of measure 1 then B˛ B for some ˛ < !1 . Proof. These are elementary equivalences. We fix some notation. For each closed interval J Œ0;1 with distinct endpoints let J W J ! Œ0;1 be the affine, order preserving, map which sends J onto Œ0;1. Suppose X .0; 1/. Let XJ D J1 ŒX . Thus XJ is the subset of J given by scaling X to J . Let X D \¹J ŒX \ J j J Œ0;1 is a closed interval with rational endpointsº and let X D [¹XJ j J Œ0;1 is a closed interval with rational endpointsº: It follows that if .X / D 1 then .X / D 1 and if .X / > 0 then
.X / D 1: The fact that X is of measure one is a consequence of the Lebesgue density theorem applied to Œ0;1 n X . We note that if P and B are borel subsets of Œ0;1 such that P B then P B. Let hP˛ W ˛ < !1 i witness (1). For each ˛ < !1 let B˛ D P˛ . Therefore for each ˛ < !1 , .B˛ / D 1. Suppose B Œ0;1 and .B/ D 1. Therefore there exists ˛ < !1 such that P˛ B and so B˛ B since B˛ D P˛ . This proves that (1) implies (4). Trivially, (4) implies (1). We next show that (1) implies (2). Fix hP˛ W ˛ < !1 i. We may assume that for each ˛ < !1 and for each open set O .0; 1/, if O \ P˛ ¤ ; then
.P˛ \ O/ > 0:
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
407
Let Q Œ0;1 be a perfect (nowhere dense) set of positive measure. Since Q has positive measure, Q is of measure 1. Fix ˛ < !1 such that P˛ Q . Q is an F and so there exist closed (proper) intervals I J Œ0;1 with rational endpoints such that P˛ \ I ¤ ; and such that P˛ \ I D QJ \ P˛ \ I D Q \ P˛ \ I: This implies that J .P˛ \ I / D Q \ J .P˛ \ I / and so J .P˛ \ J / \ J .I / Q and .J .P˛ \ J / \ J .I // > 0. There are only !1 many sets of the form J .P˛ \ J / \ J .I / where I J Œ0;1 are closed subintervals with rational endpoints, ˛ < !1 and I \ P˛ ¤ ;. . Therefore these sets collectively witness (2). Finally we show that (2) implies (3). Let hP˛ W ˛ < !1 i be a sequence of perfect subsets of Œ0;1 each of positive measure such that the sequence witnesses (2). Suppose Q Œ0;1 is a perfect set of positive measure. For each ˇ < !1 let Xˇ D [¹P˛ j ˛ < ˇ and P˛ Qº: We claim that for all sufficiently large ˇ, .Q n Xˇ / D 0. This is immediate. Suppose ˇ < !1 and .Q n Xˇ / > 0. Then there exists ˛ < !1 such that P˛ Q n Xˇ and so .Xˇ / < .X / for some < !1 . The claim follows. Let hQ˛ W ˛ < !1 i enumerate the perfect subsets of Œ0;1 which can be expressed as a finite union of the P˛ ’s. Thus hQ˛ W ˛ < !1 i witnesses (3). t u Lemma 6.127 (ZFC ). Assume ˘+ .!1
6 Pmax variations
408
Proof. We first prove that (1) implies (3). Fix F and I . It follows immediately from the definition of YA .F; I / that if B Œ0;1 is a set of measure 1 then F .˛/ B for some ˛ < !1 . The point is that the set ¹Q 2 A j Q Bº is dense in A. Therefore by Lemma 6.126, (3) holds. We finish by proving that (3) implies (2). Let I be a normal ideal on !1 . Let f W !1 ! H.!1 / be a function which witnesses ˘+ .!1 p for some p 2 f .˛/º: Thus on a club in !1 , F .˛/ is a perfect set of measure 1=2. It is straightforward to u t verify that .!1 ; Œ0;1/ 2 YA .F; I /. Definition 6.128. M Qmax consists of finite sequences h.M; I /; f; F; Y i such that: (1) h.M; I /; f i 2 Qmax ; (2) M ZFC ; (3) f witnesses ˘++ .!1
F W !1M ! P .Œ0;1/I
(5) Y 2 M is the set YA .F; I / as computed in M, and .!1M ; Œ0;1M / 2 Y . The order on M Qmax is given as follows. Suppose that ¹h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 ; F1 ; Y1 i; h.M2 ; I2 /; f2 ; F2 ; Y2 iº M Qmax : Then h.M2 ; I2 /; f2 ; F2 ; Y2 i < h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 ; F1 ; Y1 i if h.M2 ; I2 /; f2 i < h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i in Qmax and if j W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 /
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
409
is the corresponding iteration, (1) j.F1 / D F2 , (2) j.Y1 / D Y2 \ M1 .
t u
We prove the basic iteration lemmas for M Qmax . There are two iteration lemmas, one for models and one for sequences of models. The latter is necessary to show that M Qmax is !-closed. As usual its proof is an intrinsic part of the analysis of M Qmax . We need a preliminary lemma. Lemma 6.129 (ZFC ). Suppose h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 M Qmax and Q Œ0;1 is a perfect set with measure greater than 1=2. Suppose .S; P / 2 Y and
.Q \ P / > 1=2: Suppose that A 2 M,
A .P .!1 / n I /M ;
and A is open, dense in .P .!1 / n I; /M below S . Then there exists .S ; P / 2 Y such that
.Q \ P / > 1=2 and such that S 2 A. Proof. Fix .S; P / 2 Y and fix Q Œ0;1 such that
.Q \ P / > 1=2: The key point is that by Lemma 6.125, the set D D ¹P j .S ; P / 2 Y for some S 2 Aº is open dense in AM below P . Let hPi W i < !i 2 M be maximal antichain of conditions below P such that Pi 2 D for all i < !. M is wellfounded and so by absoluteness hPi W i < !i is a maximal antichain in A below P . Therefore for some i < !,
.Q \ Pi / > 1=2 t u
and the lemma follows.
With this lemma the main iterations lemmas are easily proved. As usual it is really the proofs of these iteration lemmas which are the key to the analysis of M Qmax . Lemma 6.130 (ZFC C ˘+ .!1
410
6 Pmax variations
Suppose g W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function which witnesses ˘+ .!1
M˛C1
j˛C1;˛C2 .F˛C1 /.!1
/ P˛
where for each ˇ < !1 , Fˇ D j0;ˇ .F /. The iteration is easily constructed by induction on ˛. Lemma 6.129 guarantees that (1.2) can be satisfied at every stage. The use of Lemma 6.129 is as follows. Fix < !1 and suppose h.M˛ ; I˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ C 1i is given. Let fC1 ; FC1 , and YC1 be the images of f; F , and Y under j0;C1 . Thus h.MC1 ; IC1 /; fC1 ; FC1 ; YC1 i 2 M Qmax : Suppose .S; P / 2 YC1 and .P \ P / > 1=2. Suppose A 2 MC1 and A is open dense in the partial order .P .!1 / n IC1 ; /M C1 : By Lemma 6.129, there exists .S ; P / 2 YC1 such that S S , S 2 A and
.P \ P / > 1=2: The model MC1 is countable and so there exists GC1 P .!1 / n IC1 such that GC1 is MC1 -generic for .P .!1 / n IC1 ; /M C1 and such that for all .S; P / 2 YC1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
411
if S 2 GC1 then .P \ P / > 1=2. The filter GC1 is MC1 -generic and so G D ¹P 2 AM C1 j .S; P / 2 YC1 for some S 2 GC1 º is a filter in AM C1 which is MC1 -generic. (Clearly G generates a generic filter which is all we require. By Lemma 6.125, G literally is the filter it generates since .!1 ; Œ0;1/M C1 2 YC1 .) However for each P 2 G,
.P \ P / > 1=2: It follows that \¹P j P 2 Gº P : This is an elementary property of the generic for Amoeba forcing. Let XG D \¹P j P 2 Gº: Then .XG / D 1=2 and .X \P / D 1=2. But if O Œ0;1 is open and O \XG ¤ ; then .XG \ O/ ¤ 0. Therefore XG D XG \ P : Finally
M C1
/ XG
M C1
/ P :
jC1;C2 .FC1 /.!1 and so
jC1;C2 .FC1 /.!1
This verifies that condition (1.2) can be met at every relevant stage. We consider the effect of condition (1.1). Since g witnesses ˘+ .!1
412
6 Pmax variations
(2.1) Suppose hQk W k < !i is a maximal antichain in A below P . Then ¹˛ 2 S j j0;!1 .F /.˛/ 6 Qk for all k < !º 2 J: (2.2) If Q P is a perfect set of measure > 1=2 then ¹˛ 2 S j j0;!1 .F /.˛/ Qº … J: The other requirements .S; P / must satisfy follow by absoluteness. We first prove (2.1). The key point is that there exists a club C0 !1 such that for all ˛ 2 C0 , D˛ D ¹P 2 AM˛ j P Qk for some k < !º is dense in AM˛ . The existence of C0 follows from clause (1.2) in the construction of the iteration. Let X H.!2 / be a countable elementary substructure such that h.M˛ ; I˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i and such that D 2 X where D D ¹P 2 AM!1 j P Qk for some k < !º: Let ˛ D X \ !1 and let MX be the transitive collapse of X . g witnesses ˘+ .!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
413
Lemma 6.131 (ZFC C ˘+ .!1
(iii) !1
MkC1
D !1
,
(iv) Fk D F0 and fk D f0 , (v) IkC1 \ Mk D Ik , (vi) Yk D YkC1 \ Mk , (vii) if C 2 Mk is closed and unbounded in !1M0 then there exists D 2 MkC1 such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ MkC1 . Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i such that (1) ¹˛ j j.f0 /.˛/ D g.˛/º contains a club in !1 , (2) YA .j.F0 /; J / \ Mk D j.Yk /. Proof. By Corollary 4.20 the sequence h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is iterable. Given this the proof of the lemma is essentially identical to the proof of Lemma 6.130. Let hP˛ W ˛ < !1 i be a sequence of conditions in A which is dense. Let hh.Mk˛ ; Ik˛ / W k < !i; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i be an iteration of h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i such that the following hold.
414
6 Pmax variations M˛
(1.1) For all ˛ < !1 if ˛ D !1 0 and if g.˛/ is [¹Mk˛ j k < !º-generic for Coll.!; ˛/ then G˛ is the corresponding generic filter. (1.2) For all ˛ < !1 , M0˛C1
j˛C1;˛C2 .F0˛C1 /.!1
/ P˛ :
where for each ˛ < !1 , F0˛ D j0;˛ .F0 /. This is the iteration analogous to that specified in the proof of Lemma 6.131. Given this iteration the remainder of the proof is the same. In constructing this iteration the only point to check here is that Lemma 6.129 can still be applied. It suffices to show the following. Suppose j0;ˇ W h.Mk0 ; Ik0 / W k < !i ! h.Mkˇ ; Ikˇ / W k < !i is a countable iteration of h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i D h.Mk0 ; Ik0 / W k < !i and suppose Q 2 A. Then there exists an iteration jˇ;ˇ C1 W h.Mkˇ ; Ikˇ / W k < !i ! h.Mkˇ C1 ; Ikˇ C1 / W k < !i of length 1 such that ˇ
M0
jˇ;ˇ C1 .Fˇ /.!1
/Q
where Fˇ D j0;ˇ .F0 /. We verify this in the special case that ˇ D 0; i. e. given Q 2 A we construct an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i of length 1 such that j.F0 /.!1M0 / Q. The general case is identical. Fix Q and construct by induction on k a sequence h.Sk ; Pk / W k < !i such that for all k 2 !, (2.1) .Q \ Pk / > 1=2, (2.2) .Sk ; Pk / 2 Yk , (2.3) SkC1 Sk , (2.4) The set ¹S 2 .P .!1 //Mk j Si S for some i 2 !º is Mk -generic for .P .!1 / n Ik ; /Mk .
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
415
Lemma 6.129 is used in the construction as follows. Suppose .Sk ; Pk / 2 Yk and A 2 MkC1 is a dense open set in .P .!1 / n IkC1 ; /MkC1 : Suppose .Q \ Pk / > 1=2. YkC1 \ Mk D Yk and so .Sk ; Pk / 2 YkC1 . Therefore by Lemma 6.129 applied to MkC1 , there exists .SkC1 ; PkC1 / 2 YkC1 such that
.Q \ PkC1 / > 1=2, SkC1 Sk and such that SkC1 2 A. For each k 2 !, h.Mk ; Ik /; fk i 2 Qmax and fk D fkC1 . This is a key point for it implies that if A 2 Mk is a dense open set in .P .!1 / n Ik ; /Mk ; then A is predense in .P .!1 / n IkC1 ; /MkC1 : Therefore the genericity conditions (2.4) are easily met and so the sequence h.Sk ; Pk / W k < !i exists. For each k 2 ! let Gk D ¹S 2 .P .!1 //Mk j Si S for some i 2 !º and let Hk D ¹P 2 AMk j .S; P / 2 Yk for some S 2 Gk º: Thus for each k 2 !,
Hk D ¹P 2 AMk j P \ MkC1 2 HkC1 º and for all P 2 Hk , .Q \ P / > 1=2. For each k < !, Gk is Mk -generic and so for each k < !, Hk is Mk -generic for AMk . Let j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i
be the iteration given by [¹Gk j k < !º and let X D \¹P j P 2 H0 º D \¹P j P 2 [¹Hk jk 2 !ºº: Therefore j.F0 / X Q and so the iteration is as desired. We make the usual associations. Suppose G M Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then (1) fG D [¹f j h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 Gº, (2) FG D [¹F j h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 Gº, (3) IG D [¹j .I / j h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 Gº, (4) YG D [¹j .Y / j h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 Gº, (5) P .!1 /G D [¹M \ P .!1 / j h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 Gº, where for each h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 G, j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the (unique) iteration such that j.f / D fG .
t u
416
6 Pmax variations
The basic analysis of M Qmax follows from these lemmas in a by now familiar fashion. The results of this we give in the following theorem. The analysis requires that M Qmax is suitably nontrivial. More precisely one needs that for each set A R with A 2 L.R/ there exists h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 M Qmax such that hH.!1 /M ; A \ H.!1 /M ; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i and such that .M; I / is A-iterable. By Lemma 6.47 and Lemma 6.127, this follows from the existence of a huge cardinal. Theorem 6.132. Assume that for each set A R with A 2 L.R/ there exists h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 M Qmax such that (i) hH.!1 /M ; A \ H.!1 /M ; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i, (ii) .M; I / is A-iterable. Then M Qmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Suppose G M Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG !1 -DC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal !1 -dense ideal on !1 ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) YG D YA .FG ; INS /; (5) fG witnesses ˘++ .!1
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
417
Proof. The proof that M Qmax is !-closed follows closely the proof that Qmax is !closed. Suppose hpk W k < !i is a strictly decreasing sequence of conditions in M Qmax and that for each k < !, pk D h.Mk ; Ik /; fk ; Fk ; Yk i: Let f D [¹fk j k < !1 º and let F D [¹Fk j k < !1 º: For each k < ! let and let
jk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik / pk D h.Mk ; Ik /; f; jk .Fk /; jk .Yk /i
where jk is the iteration such that j.fk / D f . By boundedness it follows that hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in M Qmax which satisfies the conditions (i)–(vi) of Lemma 6.131. By the nontriviality of M Qmax there exists a condition h.N ; J /; g; G; Y i 2 M Qmax such that
hpk W k < !i 2 .H.!1 //M :
By Lemma 6.131 there exists an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i such that j 2 N and such that in N , (1.1) ¹˛ j j.f /.˛/ D g.˛/º contains a club in !1 , (1.2) for all k < !,
YA .j.F /; J / \ Mk D j.Yk /:
Thus h.N ; J /; j.f /; j.F /; Zi 2 M Qmax and for all k < !, h.N ; J /; j.f /; j.F /; Zi < pk where
Z D .YA .j.F /; J //N :
In a similar fashion the other claims are proved by just adapting the proofs of the corresponding claims for Qmax . Because of the requirement (2) in the definition of M Qmax , (5) is immediate from (1). (4) is an immediate consequence of (1) and the definition of the order on M Qmax . (6) follows from (4) by the definition of YA .FG ; INS /. t u
418
6 Pmax variations
There is a version of M Qmax analogous to Qmax for which the analysis can be carried out just assuming ADL.R/ . This version is a little tedious to define and we leave the details to the reader. The net effect of this is the following theorem that M Qmax is suitably nontrivial just assuming ADL.R/ . This is analogous to Theorem 6.80. Theorem 6.133. Assume ADL.R/ . Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/ there exists h.M; I /; f; F; Y i 2 M Qmax such that (1) hH.!1 /M ; A \ H.!1 /M ; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i, t u
(2) .M; I / is A-iterable. Combining the two previous theorems we obtain the following theorem. Theorem 6.134. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose G M Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense; (2) ˘++ .!1
(3) there is a sequence hB˛ W ˛ < !1 i of borel subsets of Œ0;1 such that each B˛ is of measure 1 and such that if B Œ0;1 is set of measure 1 then B˛ B for t u some ˛ < !1 . There are absoluteness theorems for M Qmax analogous to the absoluteness theorems for Qmax . These require the following preliminary lemmas. With these lemmas in hand the proof of the absoluteness theorem, Theorem 6.139, is an easy variation of the proof of the corresponding theorem for Qmax , Theorem 6.85. We leave the details as an exercise. We generalize the definition of YA .F; INS / to the setting of the stationary tower. Suppose that ı is strongly inaccessible and that F W !1 ! P .Œ0;1/: Let YA .F; ı/ be the set of all pairs .S; P / such that the following hold. (1) S 2 Q<ı and !1 [S . (2) P Œ0;1 and P 2 A.
6.2 Variations for obtaining !1 -dense ideals
419
(3) Suppose hPk W k < !i is a maximal antichain in A below P . Then ¹a 2 S j F .a \ !1 / 6 Pk for all k < !º is not stationary in S . (4) If Q P is a perfect set of measure > 1=2 then ¹a 2 S j F .a \ !1 / Qº is stationary in S . (5) For all a 2 S , .Q/ D 1=2 where Q D F .a \ !1 /. The relationship between YA .F; INS / and YA .F; ı/ is summarized in the following lemma which is an immediate consequence of the definitions. Lemma 6.135. Suppose that ı is strongly inaccessible and that F W !1 ! P .Œ0;1/: Then YA .F; INS / D ¹.S; P / j .S; P / 2 YA .F; ı/ and S !1 º:
t u
The next two lemmas, Lemma 6.136 and Lemma 6.137, are used to prove the iteration lemma, Lemma 6.138, just as Lemma 6.125 and Lemma 6.129 are used to prove the basic iteration lemmas for M Qmax , Lemma 6.130. Lemma 6.136. Suppose ı is strongly inaccessible F W !1 ! P .Œ0;1/ is a function such that YA .F; ı/ is nonempty. Suppose .S1 ; P1 / 2 YA .F; ı/. (1) Suppose P2 is a perfect subset of P1 and P2 2 A. Let S2 D ¹a 2 S1 j F .a \ !1 / P2 º: Then .S2 ; P2 / 2 YA .F; ı/. (2) Suppose that S2 S1 in Q<ı . Then there exists .S3 ; P3 / 2 YA .F; ı/ such that S3 S 2 . Proof. This is the analog of Lemma 6.125. The proof is similar. For (2) one uses the generic ultrapower associated to Q<ı in place of the generic ultrapower associated to t u P .!1 /=I . Lemma 6.137. Suppose .M; I/ is a countable iterable structure such that (i) M ZFC, (ii) I 2 M and I is the tower of ideals I<ı as computed in M where ı is a Woodin cardinal in M .
420
6 Pmax variations
Suppose f 2 M is a function such that .YA .f; ı//M ¤ ; and let Y D .YA .f; ı//M . Suppose .S; P / 2 Y and
.Q \ P / > 1=2: Suppose that A 2 M ,
A .Q<ı /M ;
and A is open, dense in .Q<ı /M below S . Then there exists .S ; P / 2 Y such that
.Q \ P / > 1=2 and such that S 2 A. Proof. Fix .S; P / 2 Y and fix Q Œ0;1 such that
.Q \ P / > 1=2: By Lemma 6.136, the set D D ¹P j .S ; P / 2 Y for some S 2 Aº is open dense in AM below P . Let hPi W i < !i 2 M be maximal antichain of conditions below P such that Pi 2 D for all i < !. M is wellfounded and so by absoluteness hPi W i < !i is a maximal antichain in A below P . Therefore for some i < !,
.Q \ Pi / > 1=2:
Since Pi 2 D, there exists S 2 A such that .S ; Pi / 2 Y:
t u
Using Lemma 6.137 the basic iteration lemma is easily proved. The proof follows that of Lemma 6.130 using Lemma 6.137 in place of Lemma 6.129. Lemma 6.138. Suppose F W !1 ! P .Œ0;1/ is a function such that .!1 ; Œ0;1/ 2 YA .F; INS /. Suppose H W !1 ! H.!1 / is a function which witnesses ˘ .!1
(i) M ZFC, (ii) I 2 M and I is the tower of ideals I<ı as computed in M where ı is a Woodin cardinal in M .
6.3 Nonregular ultrafilters on !1
421
Suppose f 2 M is a function such that .!1M ; Œ0;1M / 2 .YA .f; INS //M : Suppose h 2 M , h witnesses ˘+ .!1
t u
Theorem 6.139 is an absoluteness theorem for M Qmax . Again the proof is an easy adaptation of earlier arguments and stronger absoluteness theorems can be proved. For this theorem one uses the iteration lemma, Lemma 6.138, modifying the proof of the corresponding absoluteness theorem for Qmax , Theorem 6.85. The situation here is simpler since there are no restricted …2 sentences to deal with. Theorem 6.139 (˘+ .!1
MQ
hH.!2 /; X; 2 W X R; X 2 L.R/iL.R/
6.3
max
:
t u
Nonregular ultrafilters on !1
We consider ultrafilters on !1 . Definition 6.140. Suppose that U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 . (1) The ultrafilter U is nonregular if for each set W U of cardinality !1 there exists an infinite set Z W such that \Z ¤ ;:
422
6 Pmax variations
(2) The ultrafilter U is weakly normal if for any function f W !1 ! !1 ; either ¹˛ j ˛ f .˛/º 2 U or there exists ˇ < !1 such that ¹˛ j f .˛/ < ˇº 2 U:
t u
We begin with the basic relationship between the existence nonregular ultrafilters on !1 and the existence of weakly normal ultrafilters on !1 . This relationship is summarized in the following theorem of Taylor .1979/. This theorem is the analog for !1 of the theorem that if is measurable then there is a normal measure on . Theorem 6.141 (Taylor). Suppose that U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 . (1) Suppose that U is weakly normal. Then U is nonregular. (2) Suppose that U is nonregular. Then there exists a function f W !1 ! !1 such that U is weakly normal where U D ¹A !1 j f 1 ŒA 2 U º:
t u
The relative consistency of the existence of nonregular ultrafilters on !1 first established by Laver. Laver proved that if there exists an !1 -dense uniform ideal on !1 and ˘ holds, then there exists a nonregular ultrafilter on !1 . Huberich improved Laver’s theorem proving the theorem without assuming ˘. Thus in L.R/Qmax there is a nonregular ultrafilter on !1 . The basic method for producing nonregular ultrafilters on !1 is to produce them from suitably saturated normal ideals on !1 . The approach is due to Laver and involves the construction of indecomposable ultrafilters on the quotient algebra, P .!1 /=I: Definition 6.142. Suppose that B is a countably complete boolean algebra. An ultrafilter U B is indecomposable if for all X B, _X 2 U if and only if _Y 2 U for some countable set Y X .
t u
The fundamental connection between normal ideals on !1 and nonregular ultrafilters on !1 is given in the following lemma due to Laver.
6.3 Nonregular ultrafilters on !1
423
Lemma 6.143 (Laver). Suppose I P .!1 / is a normal uniform ideal. Let B D P .!1 /=I: (1) Suppose that U B is an ultrafilter which is indecomposable. Let W D ¹A !1 j ŒAI 2 U º: Then W is a weakly normal ultrafilter on !1 . (2) Suppose that W is a weakly normal ultrafilter on !1 such that W \ I D ;. Let U D ¹ŒAI j A 2 W º: Then U is an indecomposable ultrafilter on B.
t u
The following theorem was first proved by Laver assuming ˘ and then by Huberich, .Huberich 1996/, without any additional assumptions. Theorem 6.144 (Huberich). Let B D RO.Coll.!; !1 //: Then there is an ultrafilter U on B which is indecomposable.
t u
We prove the following stronger version. Suppose ı is an ordinal. Then Add.!; ı/ is the Cohen partial order for adding ı many Cohen reals. Theorem 6.145. Let ı be an ordinal and let B D RO .Coll.!; !1 / Add .!; ı// : Then there is an ultrafilter U on B which is indecomposable. Proof. Let P D Coll.!; !1 / Add .!; ı/. More formally P is the set of pairs .f; g/ such that f is a finite partial function from ! to !1 and g is a finite partial function from ! ı to ¹0;1º. For each q D .f; g/ in P let ˛q be the largest ordinal in the range of f . Fix a cardinal such that !1 ; ı < . For each countable elementary substructure X V such that P 2 X let PX D P \ X . Thus PX is a countable partial order. For each such X V let FX D ¹_D j D PX and D is dense º where the join, _D, is computed in B. Let F D [¹FX j X V ; X 2 P!1 .V / and P 2 X º: We prove that if S F is finite then ^S ¤ 0 in B. Suppose hb0 ; : : : ; bn i is a finite sequence of elements of F . For each i n let Xi V be a countable elementary substructure containing P and let Di PXi be a dense subset such that bi D _Di . By
424
6 Pmax variations
reordering if necessary we may assume that Xi \ !1 Xj \ !1 : for all i j . The key point is the following. Suppose X V , X is countable and P 2 X . Suppose q 2 P and ˛q < X \ !1 . Here ˛q is the ordinal defined above. Then there is a condition q0 2 PX such that if q1 < q0 and q1 2 PX then there is a condition p 2 P such that p < q, p < q1 and ˛p < X \ !1 . Using this it is straightforward to construct a sequence h.p0 ; q0 /; : : : ; .pn ; qn /i of pairs of conditions in P such that for all i j : (1.1) pi < qi ; (1.2) qi 2 Di ; (1.3) ˛pi < Xi \ !1 ; (1.4) pj pi . Thus pn ^¹bi j i nº. Let F be the filter in B generated by the finite meets of elements of F . Let U be an ultrafilter on B extending F . We prove that U is indecomposable. Suppose X B and _X 2 U . Let Y be the set of conditions q 2 P such that q b for some b 2 X. Let W be the set of conditions q 2 P such that q ^ b D 0 in B for all b 2 X. Let D D Y [ W . Thus D is dense in P . Let Z V be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹P ; Dº Z. Let D D D \ Z. Thus D is dense in PZ and so _D 2 F U . Let b D _.Y \ Z/ and let c D _.W \ Z/ Thus _D D b _ c. Further c _W and ._W /^._X/ D 0. Thus c … U and so b 2 U . But b D _.Y \Z/ and Z is countable. Therefore b _X for some countable set X X. Thus U is indecomposable. t u An immediate corollary of Lemma 6.143 is the following theorem of .Huberich 1996/.
Theorem 6.146 (Huberich). Assume there is an !1 -dense ideal on !1 . Then there is a t u nonregular ultrafilter on !1 . Corollary 6.147. Assume there is an !1 -dense ideal on !1 . Suppose ı is a cardinal and that G Add .!; ı/ is V -generic. Then in V ŒG there is a nonregular ultrafilter t u on !1 .
6.3 Nonregular ultrafilters on !1
425
The following theorem is now immediate. Theorem 6.148. Assume ZF C AD is consistent. Then so are (1) ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense”. (2) ZFC C “There is a nonregular ultrafilter on !1 ”. (3) ZFC C “There is a nonregular ultrafilter on !1 ” C “ 2@0 is large”.
t u
The following theorem, in conjunction with Theorem 6.148, completes the analysis of the consistency strength of the assertion that there exists an !1 -dense ideal on !1 . The proof of this theorem involves the core model induction which is also the method used to prove Theorem 5.111 and as noted is beyond the scope of this book. Theorem 6.149. Suppose that I is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 such that I is !1 dense. Then L.R/ AD: t u Corollary 6.150. The following are equiconsistent: (1) ZF C AD. (2) ZFC C “INS is !1 -dense”. (3) ZFC C “There is a normal, uniform, !1 -dense ideal on !1 ”.
t u
The consistency strength of the existence of a nonregular ultrafilter on !1 is not known.
Chapter 7
Conditional variations In this chapter we define two conditional variations of Pmax . The models obtained are in essence simply conditional versions of the Pmax -extension, i. e. the models maximize the collection of …2 sentences which can hold in the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i given that some specified sentence holds. The Qmax -extension is an example of such a variation. It conditions the extension on the assertion that the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense. There is an analogy for these conditional variations with variations of Sacks forcing. Suppose is a …13 sentence which is true in V and that there is a function f W ! ! ! which eventually dominates all those functions which are constructible. Then is true in LP where P is Laver forcing. This can be proved by a modification of Mansfield’s argument. Thus the Laver extension of L realizes all possible …13 sentences conditioned on the existence of fast functions. These variations of Pmax also yield models in which conditional forms of Martin’s Maximum hold. For example we shall define a variation Bmax such that in L.R/Bmax the Borel Conjecture holds together with a large fragment of Martin’s Axiom.
7.1
Suslin trees
Throughout this section, a tree, T , is a Suslin tree if T is an !1 -Suslin tree; i. e. if T is an .!1 ; !1 /-tree which satisfies the countable chain condition. We define a variation of Pmax which we shall denote Smax . Our goal is to have that Suslin trees exist in the resulting generic extension of L.R/. We give the sentence relative to which we shall condition the final model. Definition 7.1. ˆS : For all X !1 there is a transitive model M such that (1) M ZFC , (2) ˘ holds in M , (3) X 2 M , (4) for every tree T 2 M , if T is a Suslin tree in M then T is a Suslin tree in V . u t The sentence ˆS is implied by ˘ and it will hold after any (sufficiently long) forcing iteration where cofinally often ˘ holds and Suslin trees are preserved. In the model which we obtain, a strong form of ˆS actually holds.
7.1 Suslin trees
427
Definition 7.2. ˆC S : For every set X !1 there exists Y !1 such that X 2 LŒY and such that every tree T 2 LŒY which is a Suslin tree in LŒY is a Suslin tree in V. t u This strong version of ˆS seems quite subtle in the context of large cardinals. For example assuming for all A !1 , A# exists; it is not obvious that it can even hold. We prove that if for all A !1 , A# exists then ˆC S implies :CH. Lemma 7.3. Suppose that A !1 is a set such that R LŒA and such that A# exists. Then there is a tree T 2 LŒA such that T is a Suslin tree in LŒA and such that T has a cofinal branch. Proof. We naturally view any .!1 ; !1 / tree as an order on !1 ! such that for each ˛ 2 !1 , ¹˛º ! is the set of nodes in T on the ˛ th level. We restrict our considerations to trees with only infinite levels and which are splitting. We may suppose that for all ˛ < !1 , ˛ !1LŒA\˛ : Let T D .!1 !;
ˇ D .!1 /LŒ.A\ˇ;T<ˇ / :
428
7 Conditional variations
It follows that T<ˇ is a Suslin tree in LŒA \ ˇ; T<ˇ and that there is a cofinal branch b T<ˇ such that p 2 b and such that b 2 LŒ.A \ ˇ; T<ˇ /# : However T<ˇ is a Suslin tree in LŒA \ ˇ; T<ˇ and so the branch b is necessarily LŒA \ ˇ; T<ˇ -generic. This verifies the claim and so it follows that the tree T exists. Necessarily T is a Suslin tree in LŒA and repeating the argument for the claim, T has a cofinal branch in t u LŒA# . We now define the partial order Smax . It in essence is just Pmax with a more restrictive ordering though we modify the fragment of MA which is to hold in the models occurring in the conditions. Recall that a partial order P is -centered if P is the countable union of sets, S P , with the property that if a S is finite then there exists q 2 P such that q p for all p 2 a. For example if P the union of countably many filters then P is -centered. MA!1 . -centered/ is the variant of Martin’s Axiom which asserts that if P is -centered and if D is a collection of dense subsets of P with jDj !1 then there is a filter F P which is D-generic. We note that Lemma 4.35 holds for countable transitive models M such that M ZFC C MA!1 . -centered/: Thus if .M; I / is iterable and if a !1M is such that a 2 M and such that !1M D .!1 /L Œa where D M \ Ord, then iterations of .M; I / are uniquely determined by the image of a. Definition 7.4. Let Smax be the set of pairs h.M; I /; ai such that: (1) M is a countable transitive model of ZFC C MA!1 . -centered/; (2) I 2 M and M “I is a normal uniform ideal on !1 ”; (3) .M; I / is iterable; (4) a !1M ; (5) a 2 M and M “!1 D !1LŒaŒx for some real x”. Define a partial order on Smax as follows. h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i if M0 2 M1 ; M0 is countable in M1 and there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that: (1) j.a0 / D a1 ; (2) M0 2 M1 and j 2 M1 ; (3) I1 \ M0 D I0 ; (4) For any T 2 M0 , if T is a Suslin tree in M0 then T is a Suslin tree in M1 .
t u
7.1 Suslin trees
429
Lemma 7.7 is the iteration lemma that essentially allows the proofs for Pmax to generalize in a straightforward fashion. As usual it is really the proof of the lemma that is important. Before proving Lemma 7.7 we prove two useful technical lemmas. Lemma 7.5. Suppose that I is a normal uniform ideal on !1 , S !1 is I -positive and that T is a Suslin tree. Suppose that f WS !T is a function such that for all for all ˛ 2 S , f .˛/ 2 T˛ ; where T˛ denotes the with a < b,
˛ th
level of T . Then there exists a 2 T such that for all b 2 T ¹˛ 2 S j b < f .˛/º
is I -positive. Proof. For each b 2 T let Sb D ¹˛ 2 S j b < f .˛/º; and let D D ¹b 2 T j Sb 2 I º: For each ˛ < !1 let T<˛ be the subtree of T obtained by restricting T to the first ˛ many levels of T ; i. e. T<˛ D [¹Tˇ j ˇ < ˛º: Let S D ¹˛ 2 S j ˛ … Sb for all b 2 D \ T˛ º: Since the ideal I is normal it follows that S n S 2 I: Assume toward a contradiction that D is dense in T . Suppose ˛ < !1 and that a 2 T˛ . Let ba be the cofinal branch of T<˛ defined by a. Since T is a Suslin tree it follows that ¹˛ < !1 j for all a 2 T˛ ; D \ ba ¤ ;º contains a club in !1 . Therefore there exists ˛ 2 S such that bf .˛/ \ D ¤ ; which is a contradiction. Therefore D is not dense and this proves the lemma. t u
430
7 Conditional variations
As an immediate corollary to Lemma 7.5, we obtain the following iteration lemma. Lemma 7.6. Suppose .M0 ; I0 / is a countable iterable model of ZFC , T 2 M0 , T is a Suslin tree in M0 , and that T is dense. Then there is an iteration of length 1 .i. e. a generic ultrapower/, j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M1 ; I1 / such that is predense in j.T /. Proof. The key point is the following which is an immediate consequence of Lemma 7.5. Suppose A 2 M0 , A !1M0 and A is I0 -positive. Suppose that 2 M0 is a term for a node of j.T / above !1M0 . Then there is B A such that B is I0 -positive and there is t 2 such that B t < . From this the lemma easily follows. Construct the M0 -generic filter in ! steps ensuring that every node of j.T / above !1M0 is above some element of . This proves the lemma. t u Lemma 7.7 (ZFC). Assume ˘. Suppose .M; I / is a countable transitive iterable model where I 2 M is a normal uniform ideal on !1M and M ZFC . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Then there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that the following hold. (1) j.!1M / D !1 . (2) J \ M D I . (3) Suppose T 2 M and T is a Suslin tree in M . Then T is a Suslin tree. Proof. Note there is a stationary set S !1 such that ˘.S / holds and such that !1 n S is J -positive. The relevant point here is that assuming ˘ if !1 D S1 [ S2 then ˘.S1 / holds or ˘.S2 / holds. Fix S and let h ˛k W ˛ 2 S i be a diamond sequence on S . We modify the proof of Lemma 4.36. The proof of the lemma is simply a dovetailing of the construction of the iteration given in the proof of Lemma 4.36 together with the construction of a Suslin tree using ˘. This is straightforward using Lemma 7.6. Let x be a real which codes M and let C !1 be a closed unbounded set of ordinals which are admissible relative to x.
7.1 Suslin trees
431
Fix a sequence hAk;˛ W k < !; ˛ < !1 i of J positive sets which are pairwise disjoint and disjoint from S . The ideal J is normal hence each Ak;˛ is stationary in !1 . Fix a function f W ! !1M ! M such that (1.1) f is onto, (1.2) for all k < !, f jk !1M 2 M, (1.3) for all A 2 M if A has cardinality !1M in M then A ran.f jk !1M / for some k < !. The function f is simply used to anticipate elements in the final model. Suppose j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is an iteration. Then we define j.f / D [¹j.f jk !1M / j k < !º and it is easily verified that M is the range of j.f /. This follows from (1.3). We construct an iteration of M of length !1 using the function f to provide a book-keeping device for all of the subsets of !1 which belong to the final model and do not belong to the image of I in the final model. Implicit in what follows is that for ˇ 2 C if j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is an iteration of length ˇ then j.!1M / D ˇ. This is a consequence of Lemma 4.6(1). More precisely construct an iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i such that for each ˇ < !1 , if (2.1) ˇ 2 Ak; \ C , (2.2) < ˇ, (2.3) j0;ˇ .f /.k; / ˇ, (2.4) j0;ˇ .f /.k; / … Iˇ , then j0;ˇ .f /.k; / 2 Gˇ . These requirements place no constraint on the choice of Gˇ for ˇ 2 S \ C . For ˇ 2 C \ S choose Gˇ such that if ˇ codes .k; ; T; / where (3.1) < ˇ, (3.2) T is a Suslin tree in Mˇ , (3.3) j0;ˇ .f /.k; / D T , (3.4) is dense in T , then is predense in jˇ;ˇ C1 .T /. Lemma 7.6 shows Gˇ exists.
432
7 Conditional variations
Thus J \ M!1 D I!1 as in the proof of Lemma 4.36. Further since h ˛ W ˛ 2 S i is a diamond sequence it follows that if T 2 M!1 and T is a Suslin tree in M!1 then T is a Suslin tree. t u Corollary 7.8. Assume ˆS . Suppose .M; I / is a countable transitive iterable model where I 2 M is a normal uniform ideal on !1M and M ZFC . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Then there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that the following hold. (1) j.!1M / D !1 . (2) J \ M D I . (3) Suppose T 2 M and T is a Suslin tree in M . Then T is a Suslin tree. Proof. Let .T0 ; T1 / be a partition of !1 into J -positive sets and let hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i be a sequence of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 such that for ˛ < !1 , T 0 \ S˛ … J and T1 \ S˛ … J: By ˆS there exists a transitive model M such that (1.1) M ZFC , (1.2) ˘ holds in M , (1.3) M 2 M , (1.4) hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i 2 M , .T0 ; T1 / 2 M , and !1M D !1 , (1.5) for every tree T 2 M , if T is a Suslin tree in M then T is a Suslin tree in V . Thus in M , either ˘.T0 / holds or ˘.T1 / holds. Suppose that ˘.T0 / holds in M . Fix a bijection g W !1 ! ! !1 such that f 2 M . Let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the iteration constructed in M as in the proof of Lemma 7.7, with S D T0 and with Ak;˛ D T1 \ Sˇ where ˇ D g.k; ˛/. Thus if T 2 M is a Suslin tree in M , then T is a Suslin tree in M . Hence by the choice of M , T is a Suslin tree in V . Suppose a 2 M is I -positive. Then there exists a club C !1 such that C \ Ak;˛ a for some .k; ˛/ 2 ! !1 . t u Therefore J \ M D I .
7.1 Suslin trees
433
The analysis of the Smax -extension requires the generalization of Corollary 7.8 to sequences of models. This in turn requires the generalization of Lemma 7.6 to sequences of models. Lemma 7.9 (ZFC). Suppose h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is an iterable sequence of countable structures such that for all k < !; (i) Mk is a countable transitive model of ZFC, (ii) Mk 2 MkC1 , (iii) jMk jMkC1 D .!1 /MkC1 , Mk
(iv) !1
MkC1
D !1
,
(v) IkC1 \ Mk D Ik , (vi) suppose Ak 2 Mk ,
M
Ak P .!1 k / \ Mk n Ik and that Ak is predense, then Ak is predense in .P .!1 / n IkC1 ; /MkC1 : Suppose that T 2 [¹Mk j k < !º is a Suslin tree in [¹Mk j k < !º, and that T is a dense subset of T . Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i of length 1 such that is predense in j.T /. Proof. We suppose that T 2 M0 . For each ˛ < !1M0 let T˛ denote the ˛ th level of T . Let hxk W k < !i be an enumeration of [¹Mk j k < !º such that for all k < !, xk 2 Mk . By successive applications of Lemma 7.5 there exists a sequence hsk W k < !i such that for each k < !, (1.1) skC1 sk ,
434
7 Conditional variations
(1.2) sk !1M0 , (1.3) sk 2 Mk n Ik , (1.4) if xk !1M0 then sk D xk or sk D !1M0 n xk , (1.5) if xk is a predense subset of then sk s for some s 2 xk , (1.6) if xk is a function
f W !1M0 ! T
such that for all ˛ < !1M0 , then for some b 2 ,
.P .!1 /Mk n Ik ; /
f .˛/ 2 T˛ ;
sk ¹˛ < !1M0 j f .˛/ > bº:
Let G D ¹sk j k < !º: By (1.4) and (1.5), for each k < !, G \ Mk is Mk -generic for .P .!1 / n Ik /Mk . Since the sequence, h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i, is iterable, G defines an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i of length 1 where for each k < !, Mk is transitive. By (1.6), is predense in j.T /.
t u
Lemma 7.10 (ZFC). Assume ˆS . Suppose J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Suppose that h.M; Ik / W k < !i is a sequence such that for each k < !, Mk is a countable transitive model of ZFC, Ik 2 Mk and such that in Mk , Ik is a uniform normal ideal M on !1 k . Suppose that for all k < !, (i) Mk 2 MkC1 , (ii) jMk jMkC1 D .!1 /MkC1 , Mk
(iii) !1
MkC1
D !1
,
(iv) IkC1 \ Mk D Ik , (v) .Mk ; Ik / is iterable, (vi) suppose Ak 2 Mk ,
M
Ak P .!1 k / \ Mk n Ik and that Ak is predense, then Ak is predense in .P .!1 / n IkC1 ; /MkC1 ; (vii) if C 2 Mk is closed and unbounded in !1M0 then there exists D 2 MkC1 such that D C , D is closed and unbounded in C and such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ MkC1 .
7.1 Suslin trees
435
Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i such that the following hold. (1) j.!1M0 / D !1 . (2) For all k < !,
J \ Mk D Ik :
(3) Suppose that T 2 [¹Mk j k < !º and that for all k < !, if T 2 Mk then T is a Suslin tree in Mk . Then T is a Suslin tree. Proof. By Corollary 4.20 the sequence h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is iterable. The lemma follows by a construction essentially the same as that given in the proof of Corollary 7.8. For this proof the construction uses Lemma 7.9 in place of Lemma 7.6. t u As we have indicated, the nontriviality of Smax is an immediate corollary to nontriviality of Pmax . However we shall need a slightly stronger version of this. The reason is simply that the iteration lemmas for Smax require additional assumptions. The situation here, though much simpler, is reminiscent of that in Section 6.2.5 where we analyzed KT Qmax . Smax is a refinement of Pmax which is analogous to KT Qmax as a refinement of Qmax . Lemma 7.11. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose X R and that X 2 L.R/: Then there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Smax such that (1) M ˆS , (2) X \ M 2 M, (3) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (4) .M; I / is X -iterable, and further the set of such conditions is dense in Smax . Proof. The proof is identical to the proof of Lemma 4.40 with one slight change. We use the notation from that proof. The modification concerns the choice of the partial order Q 2 N . For this proof one chooses Q 2 N such that N Q ZFC C MA!1 . -centered/:
436
7 Conditional variations
and such that Q D Coll.!; < / P where P 2 N Coll.!;</ and in N Coll.!;</ , P is obtained as the result of an iteration of -centered partial orders of cardinality !1 (with finite support). We claim that N Q ˆS : Suppose g Coll.!; < / is N -generic and that h P is N Œg-generic. is measurable in N and so ˘ holds in N ŒgŒa for any a such that a 2 N ŒgŒh. Finally suppose a and that a 2 N ŒgŒh. Then there exists b such that a 2 N ŒgŒb and such that N ŒgŒh is a -centered forcing extension of N ŒgŒb. This is because P is an iteration of -centered partial orders. Therefore Suslin trees in N ŒgŒb remain Suslin trees in N ŒgŒh. This verifies that N Q ˆS : With this choice of Q the construction of the proof of Lemma 4.40 will yield the desired condition. t u Suppose G Smax is L.R/-generic. We assume ADL.R/ so that Smax is nontrivial. We associate to the generic filter G a subset of !1 , AG , and an ideal, IG . This is just as in case of Pmax . AG D [¹a j h.M; I /; ai 2 G for some .M; I /º: For each h.M; I /; ai 2 G there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.a/ D AG . This iteration is unique because M MA. -centered/. We let I D j.I /. Define IG D [¹I j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº and let
P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº:
Finally define a set A !1 to be L.R/-generic for Smax is there exists an L.R/-generic filter G Smax such that A D AG . The next theorem gives the basic analysis of Smax . Theorem 7.12. Assume AD L.R/ . Then Smax is !-closed and homogeneous. Suppose G Smax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) IG is a normal saturated ideal;
7.1 Suslin trees
437
(3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) the sentence AC holds; (5) the sentence ˆC S holds; (6) suppose A !1 and A … L.R/, then A is L.R/-generic for Smax and L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒA: Proof. The proof that Smax is !-closed is a routine adaptation of the proof of Lemma 4.37 to prove the analog of Corollary 7.8 for iterable sequences of models. The !-closure of Smax then follows from the fact that for all x 2 R there exists a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Smax such that x 2 M and ˆS holds in M. This fact is an immediate corollary of Lemma 7.11. With the exception of part (5) the remaining claims of the theorem are proved by arguments essentially identical to those used to prove the corresponding claims about Pmax . We leave the details to the reader and just sketch the proof for (5). This proof is quite similar to the proof of Theorem 6.108(5). Fix X0 !1 with X0 2 L.R/ŒG. By (1) there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G and a set b0
!1M0
such that b0 2 M0 and j.b0 / D X0 where j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
is the unique iteration such that j.a0 / D AG . We work in L.R/ and we assume that the condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i forces that X0 D j.b0 / is a counterexample to (5). Let z 2 R be any real such that M0 2 LŒz and M0 is countable in LŒz. For each i ! let i be the i th Silver indiscernible of LŒz. Let k W L! Œz ! L! Œz be the canonical embedding such that cp(k) = 0 and let L! Œz D ¹k.f /.0 / j f 2 L! Œzº: Let U be the L! Œz-ultrafilter on 0 given by k, U D ¹A 0 j A 2 L! Œz; 0 2 k.A/º: Thus L! Œz Š Ult.L! Œz; U / and k is the associated embedding. For each X P .0 / \ L! Œz if X 2 L! Œz and jX j 0 in L! Œz then U \ X 2 L! Œz. Therefore .L! Œz; U / is naturally iterable. Let g Coll.!; <0 / be L! Œz-generic. Let N D L! ŒzŒg. Therefore 0 D !1N and the ultrafilter U defines an ideal I on !1N with I N . Further for each X 2 N if jX j !1N in N then I \ X 2 N .
438
7 Conditional variations
As in the proof of Theorem 6.64, if S then Coll .!; S / the restriction of Coll.!; < / to S . Thus if ˛ < ˇ then Coll.!; <ˇ/ Š Coll.!; <˛/ Coll .!; Œ˛; ˇ//: Suppose that k W .L! Œz; U / ! .k.L! Œz/; k.U // is a countable iteration and that h Coll .!; Œ0 ; k.0 /// is k.L! Œz/Œg-generic. Then k lifts to define an elementary embedding kQ W N ! NQ where NQ D k.L! Œz/ŒgŒh. kQ is naturally interpreted as an iteration of .N; I /. We abuse our conventions and shall regard .N; I / as an iterable structure restricting to elementary embeddings arising in this fashion. This situation here is identical to that in the proof of Theorem 6.108(5). For any set S !1N , if S is stationary in N then ˘ holds in N on S . We view the generic filter g as a function g W !1N ! N such that for all ˛ < !1N , g.˛/ W ! ! 1 C ˛ is a function with range ˛. For each ˇ < !1N let Tˇ D ¹˛ j g.˛/.0/ D ˇº. Thus hTˇ W ˇ < !1N i 2 N and hTˇ W ˇ < !1N i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets which are positive relative to I . Fix a set S 0 such that S 2 L! Œz, S is stationary in L! Œz and S … U . Thus S !1N , S 2 N , S is stationary in N , and S … I . For each ˇ < !1N , let Sˇ D Tˇ n S . Thus hSˇ W ˇ < !1N i is a sequence in N of pairwise disjoint I -positive sets each disjoint from S . By the proof of Lemma 7.7, there is an iteration j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M1 ; I1 / such that j0 2 N and such that: (1.1) for each s !1M1 , if s … I1 then S˛ n s 2 INS for some ˛ < !1 ; (1.2) if T 2 M1 is a Suslin tree in M1 then T is a Suslin tree in N . Thus I \ M1 D I1 . Let a1 D j0 .a0 / and let b1 D j0 .b0 /.
7.1 Suslin trees
439
We come to the key points: (2.1) N D L! Œy1 where y1 !1N ; (2.2) Suppose that .N ; I / is an iterate of .N; I /. Suppose that T 2 N is a Suslin tree (in N ), S 2 .P .!1 //N n I and that f WS !T
is a function such that f 2 N and such that for all for all ˛ 2 S , f .˛/ 2 T˛ ; where T˛ denotes the b 2 T with a < b,
˛ th
level of T . Then there exists a 2 T such that for all ¹˛ 2 S j b < f .˛/º
is I -positive. Thus the proof Lemma 7.7 can be applied to .N; I /. Let h.M2 ; I2 /; ai be any condition in Smax such that N 2 M2 , N is countable in M2 and such that ˘ holds in M2 . Then there is an iteration k W .N; I / ! .N ; I / in M2 such that (3.1) k .!1N / D .!1 /M2 , (3.2) I2 \ N D I , (3.3) if T 2 N and if T is a Suslin tree in N then T is a Suslin tree in M2 . Let a2 D k .a1 /, b2 D k .b1 / and let y2 D k .y1 /. Thus (4.1) h.M2 ; I2 /; a2 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i, (4.2) b2 D j.b0 / where j is the embedding given by the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends a0 to a2 , (4.3) b2 .!1 /M2 , (4.4) y2 .!1 /M2 , (4.5) b2 2 .LŒy2 /M2 , (4.6) if T 2 LŒy2 is a Suslin tree in LŒy2 then T is a Suslin tree in M2 .
440
7 Conditional variations
Now suppose G Smax is L.R/-generic and that h.M2 ; I2 /; a2 i 2 G. Let X0 D j.b0 / where j is the elementary embedding given by the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / which sends a0 to AG . Similarly let Y0 D j.y2 / where j is the embedding given by the iteration of .M2 ; I2 / which sends a2 to aG . It follows by part (1) of the theorem that if T 2 LŒY0 and T is a Suslin tree in LŒY0 then T is a Suslin tree in L.R/ŒG. t u This is a contradiction since X0 2 LŒY0 and Y0 !1 . Remark 7.13. (1) ˆC S is a very strong version of ˆS and it is analogous to the consequence of the axiom ./ given in part (5) of Theorem 5.73. As we have noted, # ˆC S is not obviously consistent with any large cardinals (above 0 ), however by forcing with Smax over stronger models of AD one can show that it is consistent with existence of measurable cardinals and quite a bit more. By Lemma 7.3, if there is a measurable cardinal then ˆC S implies :CH. (2) Suppose A !1 and that ˛0 is least such that L˛0 ŒA T0 and such that !1 < ˛0 , where T0 ZFC. Then by an argument similar to the proof of Lemma 7.3, there exists a tree T 2 L˛0 ŒA such that T is a Suslin tree in L˛0 ŒA and such that T has a cofinal branch (in LŒA). Thus Theorem 7.12(5) cannot really be strengthened. t u The absoluteness theorem corresponding to Smax is the natural variation of the absoluteness theorem for Pmax . Using Corollary 7.8, the proof is a straightforward modification of the proof of Theorem 4.73. We leave the details to the reader noting one key difference in the present situation. We now add to the structures an additional predicate identifying the Suslin trees. We shall let T denote the set of .T; / 2 H.!2 / such that .T; / is a Suslin tree. Theorem 7.14. Assume ˆS holds and that there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; T ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri where T is the set of .T; / 2 H.!2 / such that .T; / is a Suslin tree. Suppose that hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; T ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then
Smax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; T ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
:
t u
As in the case of Pmax the converse also holds in the sense of Theorem 4.76. The proof requires the version of Lemma 4.74 for conditions in Smax . Theorem 7.15. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose that for each …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; T ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
if
Smax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; T ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
441
then hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; T ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG for some G Smax which is L.R/-generic.
7.2
t u
The Borel Conjecture
We define a variation of Pmax to produce a forcing extension of L.R/ in which both the Borel Conjecture holds and the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. We denote this variation Bmax . We shall use Bmax to obtain the consistency of the Borel Conjecture with a large fragment of Martin’s Axiom. The relative consistency of the Borel Conjecture with ZFC is due to R. Laver, .Laver 1976/. We shall require that the models occurring in the Bmax conditions be models of ZFC instead of the usual requirement that they simply be models of ZFC . The iteration lemmas necessary for the analysis of the Bmax extension are most easily proved assuming CH. Therefore we shall require that the models appearing in the conditions satisfy CH. We must as a consequence either add to the conditions (T) , use sequences of models as we did historical record as we did in the definition of Pmax in the definition of Pmax , or impose some condition which enables the iterations to be recovered uniquely from the iterates. The latter course is how we shall proceed. The only penalty for adopting this option is that the existence of suitable iterable structures is slightly more difficult to establish. The additional condition is AC relativized to an ideal. Definition 7.16.
AC .I /:
(1) I is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 . (2) Suppose S !1 and T !1 are such that ¹S; !1 n S; T; !1 n T º \ I D ;: Then there exist ˛ < !2 , a bijection W !1 ! ˛; and a set A !1 such that
!1 n A 2 I
and such that ¹ < !1 j ordertype.Œ/ 2 T º \ A D S \ A: Remark 7.17. though is that
AC .I / AC .I /
is the obvious relativization of is consistent with CH, unlike AC .
AC
t u
to I . A key difference t u
442
7 Conditional variations
The following theorem is a slight variation of Theorem 2.65. We shall use Theorem 7.18 to construct conditions in Bmax . Theorem 7.18. Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal and that G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic. Then in V ŒG there is a normal, uniform, ideal I on !1 such that (1) I \ V D .INS /V , (2) I is !2 -saturated in V ŒG, (3) V ŒG
AC .I /.
Proof. The proof is quite similar to that of Theorem 2.65. We sketch the argument. As before the ideal I is rather easy to define. Suppose that G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic. For each ˛ < ı let G˛ D G \ Coll.!1 ; <˛/: Let mc.Vı / be the set of < ı such that is a measurable cardinal in V . For each 2 mc.Vı / we define a normal ideal I 2 V ŒGC1 as follows by induction on . Fix a wellordering, in V , of Vı . There are two cases. We first suppose that 2 mc.Vı / and that is not a successor element of mc.Vı /. In this case we define J 2 V ŒGC1 to be the set of A !1 such that for some f W !1 ! P .!1 / n INS ; (1.1) A D ¹ˇ < !1 j ˇ … f .˛/ for all ˛ < ˇº, (1.2) if A D ¹f .˛/ j ˛ < !1 º then A 2 V ŒG ; and A is semiproper in V ŒG . I is the normal ideal in V ŒGC1 generated by J [ I< where I< D [¹I j 2 \ mc.Vı /º: The second case is that 2 mc.Vı / and that mc.Vı / \
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
443
has a maximum element, . If V ŒG C1
AC .I /
then I is the normal ideal in V ŒG generated by I so that in this (vacuous) subcase the ideal I is easily defined. Otherwise let .S; T / 2 V ŒG C1 be the least counterexample to
AC .I /
and let
f W !1 ! be a surjection with f 2 V ŒGC1 . The pair .S; T / is chosen using the wellordering of Vı ŒG induced by the chosen wellordering of Vı . Let A D A0 [ A1 where A0 D ¹˛ 2 !1 j ˛ 2 S and ordertype.f Œ˛/ … T º and A1 D ¹˛ 2 !1 j ˛ … S and ordertype.f Œ˛/ 2 T º: We define I to be the normal ideal in V ŒGC1 generated by I [ ¹Aº: Let I be the normal ideal generated in V ŒG by [¹I j 2 mc.Vı /º: Here as in the proof of Theorem 2.65, the only difficulty is to verify that I is a proper ideal. If I is a proper ideal then arguing as in the proof of Theorem 2.65, I is a saturated ideal and further it follows easily that V ŒG
AC .I /:
To show that I is proper we work in V . Let M D H.ı C /, thus M Vı M: Fix 0 2 mc.Vı / [ ¹ıº such that for any V -generic filter G Coll.!1 ; <ı/; and for any 2 mc.Vı / \ 0 ; the normal ideal generated by I in V ŒGC1 is a proper ideal. By the construction of an elementary chain there exists a countable elementary substructure (containing the designated wellordering of Vı ), X M; and a condition p 2 Coll.!1 ; <0 C 1/ such that the following hold.
444
7 Conditional variations
(2.1) p is X -generic; i. e. the set ¹q 2 X \ Coll.!1 ; <0 C 1/ j p < qº is X -generic. (2.2) Suppose that 2 X \ .0 C 1/ \ mc.Vı / and that \ mc.Vı / has no maximum element. Suppose that 2 V Coll.!1 ;</ \ X is a term for a semiproper subset of P .!1 / n INS . Then there is a term for a subset of !1 such that 2 X , p 2 and such that p X \ !1 2 : (2.3) Suppose that 2 X \mc.Vı /, < 0 and that is the least element of mc.Vı / above . Suppose that q 2 X \ Coll.!1 ; < C 1/, p < q, and that . S ; T / is a pair of terms in V Coll.!1 ;< C1/ \ X such that if g Coll.!1 ; < C 1/ is V -generic and q 2 g then V Œg :
AC .I /
and in V Œg, .S; T / is the least counterexample to AC .I / where S is the interpretation of S by g and T is the interpretation of T by g. Then either a) p X \ !1 2 S and p ˛ 2 T , or b) p X \ !1 … S and p ˛ … T , where ˛ D ordertype.X \ /. One constructs .X; p/ by defining a chain hX W 2 X \ .0 C 1/ \ mc.Vı /i of elementary substructures of M and a decreasing sequence hp W 2 X \ .0 C 1/ \ mc.Vı /i of conditions in Coll.!1 ; <0 C 1/ such that for all 2 X \ .0 C 1/ \ mc.Vı /, (3.1) 2 X , (3.2) for all 2 X \ .0 C 1/ \ mc.Vı /, if > then X \ D X \ ;
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
445
(3.3) p 2 Coll.!1 ; < C 1/, (3.4) the set ¹q 2 Coll.!1 ; < C 1/ j p < qº is X -generic, (3.5)
a) if \ mc.Vı / has no maximum element then (2.2) is satisfied by X at , otherwise, b) (2.3) is satisfied by X at .
For the construction of this elementary chain we note that the requirements corresponding to the desired properties, (3.5(a)) and (3.5(b)), do not conflict. The requirement which yields (3.5(a)) is easily handled using the definition of a semiproper subset of P .!1 / n INS . The requirement for (3.5(b)) is handled using the following observation. Suppose Y M is a countable elementary substructure and that 2 Y \ ı is a measurable cardinal. Then there exists a closed unbounded set C !1 such that for each ˛ 2 C there exists Y M such that Y Y , such that Y \ is an initial segment of Y \ and such that Y \ has ordertype ˛. Now suppose that 2 V Coll.!1 ;< C1/ is a term for a stationary, co-stationary subset of !1 and that q 2 Coll.!1 ; < C 1/: Then for cofinally many ˛ 2 C there is a condition q < q such that q ˛ 2 and for cofinally many ˛ 2 C there is a condition q < q such that q ˛ … : With this observation (3.5(b)) is easily achieved. Now suppose Gı Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic and that p 2 Gı . Since ¹q 2 X \ Coll.!1 ; <0 C 1/ j p < qº
446
7 Conditional variations
is X -generic it follows that there exists Y M ŒG0 C1 such that X D Y \ M . By (2.2) and (2.3) it follows that for each set A 2 I0 , Y \ !1 … A: This implies that I0 is a proper ideal in V ŒG0 C1 and so the normal ideal in V ŒG generated by I0 is also proper. Finally by modifying the choice of .X; p/ it is possible to require p < p0 for any specified condition and given a stationary set S !1 , it is also possible to arrange that S 2 X and that X \ !1 2 S: Thus in V ŒG, I0 \ V D .INS /V . Therefore it follows that I \ V D .INS /V ; t u
and so the ideal I is as required.
We prove that AC .I / does allow one to recover iterations from iterates. The proof is quite similar to that of Lemma 5.15. We state the lemma only in the special form that we shall need. Lemma 7.19. Suppose M is a countable transitive set such that M ZFC C where I 2 M is in M, a normal ideal on
!1M .
AC .I /
Suppose a 2 M,
a !1M ; and for some x 2 M \ R, M “!1 D !1LŒa;x ”: Suppose j1 W .M; I / ! .M1 ; I1 / and j2 W .M; I / ! .M2 ; I2 / are iterations of M such that M1 is transitive, M2 is transitive and such that j1 .a/ D j2 .a/: Then M1 D M2 and j1 D j2 . Proof. Fix a and x. Clearly we may suppose that either j1 or j2 is not the identity. Therefore since M contains precipitous ideals, M “For every set A !1 , A# exists”:
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
Therefore
447
sup.a/ D !1M
and so, since j1 .a/ D j2 .a/, j1 .!1M / D j2 .!1M /. Let N be the transitive set N D L! M .a; x/: 1
Thus N 2 M,
!1M D !1N
and j1 .N / D j2 .N /: Let b
!1M
be a set such that b is definable in N from parameters; i. e. b 2 L! M .a; x/; 1
and such that both b … I and !1M n b … I . Since j1 .N / D j2 .N / it follows that j1 .b/ D j2 .b/: Arguing exactly as in the proof of Lemma 5.15, it follows that M1 D M2 and that j1 D j 2 : t u We recall the basic definitions. Definition 7.20. A set X .0;1/ is a strong measure 0 set if for any sequence hzk W k < !i of positive reals there is a sequence hIk W k < !i of open intervals such that X [¹Ik j k < !º and such that .Ik / < zk for all k < !. t u The Borel Conjecture asserts that every strong measure 0 set is countable. Definition 7.21. (1) Suppose h 2 ! ! . A set X .0;1/ is h-small if there is a sequence hIk W k < !i of open intervals such that X [¹Ik j k < !º and such that for all k < !, .Ik / < 1=.h.k/ C 1/. (2) Suppose Z ! ! . A set X .0;1/ is Z-small if X is h-small for all h 2 Z. u t Lemma 7.22. Suppose Z ! ! is such that for all h 2 Z there exists f 2 Z with the property that for all k 2 !, h.n/ < f .k/ for all n 2k . Then
¹X .0;1/ j X is Z-small º
is an ideal and the ideal is closed under countable unions.
448
7 Conditional variations
Proof. Fix h 2 Z and a sequence hXi W i < !i of Z-small sets. Let hhi W i < !i be a sequence of functions in Z such that h0 D h and such that for all i < !, for all k < !, hi .n/ < hiC1 .k/ for all n 2k . The key point is that if X and Y are hiC1 -small then X [ Y is hi -small. This is easily verified by merging the two sequences of intervals, witnessing X is hiC1 -small and Y is hiC1 -small. A similar, though slightly more complicated merging, shows that [¹Xi j i < !º t u
is h0 -small.
The definition of the partial order Bmax is motivated by the following reformulation of the Borel Conjecture: Suppose X .0;1/ is uncountable, then there exists h W ! ! ! and there exists a function f W !1 ! X such that if O .0;1/ is open and h-small then ¹˛ j f .˛/ … Oº is stationary. That this is a reformulation of the Borel Conjecture is a corollary to the following theorem due to J. Zapletal. Theorem 7.23 (Zapletal). Suppose that I P .Œ0;1/ is a -ideal and that X Œ0;1 is a set of cardinality @1 such that X … I . Then there exists a function f W !1 ! X such that for all Y 2 I
¹˛ 2 !1 j f .˛/ … Y º
is stationary. Proof. Fix a surjection W !1 ! X and define W !1 ! P!1 .X / by .˛/ D ¹.ˇ/ j ˇ ˛º: Thus since X … I , for all Y 2 I , ¹˛ 2 !1 j .˛/ Y º is countable.
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
449
Choose functions fi W !1 ! X for each i < !, such that for all ˛ < !1 , .˛/ D ¹fi .˛/ j i < !º: We claim that one of the functions fi is as desired. Otherwise for each i < ! there exist Yi 2 I and a club Ci !1 such that Ci ¹˛ < !1 j fi .˛/ 2 Yi º: Let C D \¹Ci j i < !º; and let Y D [¹Yi j i < !º: Since I is a -ideal, Y 2 I . However for each ˛ 2 C , .˛/ Y . Therefore X Y t u
which is a contradiction. A similar argument proves the following theorem.
Theorem 7.24. Suppose X .0;1/ is of cardinality !1 and not of strong measure 0. Then there exists a function f W !1 ! X and there exists h W ! ! ! such that if O .0;1/ is open and h-small then ¹˛ 2 !1 j f .˛/ … Oº is stationary. Proof. The proof is quite similar to the proof of Theorem 7.23. Fix a surjection W !1 ! X and define W !1 ! P!1 .X / by .˛/ D ¹.ˇ/ j ˇ ˛º: Fix a countable set Z ! such that X is not Z-small and such that !
I D ¹Y Œ0;1 j Y is Z-smallº is a -ideal. The set Z exists by Lemma 7.22. Thus since X … I , for all Y 2 I , ¹˛ 2 !1 j .˛/ Y º is countable.
450
7 Conditional variations
Choose functions fi W !1 ! X for each i < !, such that for all ˛ < !1 , .˛/ D ¹fi .˛/ j i < !º: Let hhj W j < !i enumerate Z. We claim that for some i; j 2 ! the pair .fi ; hj / is as desired. Otherwise for each .i; j / 2 ! ! there exist Yi;j Œ0;1 and a club Ci;j !1 such that Ci;j ¹˛ < !1 j fi .˛/ 2 Yi;j º and such that Yi;j is hj -small. For each i < ! let Ci D \¹Ci;j j j < !º; and let Yi D \¹Yi;j j j < !º: Thus for each i < !, Yi is Z-small and Ci ¹˛ < !1 j fi .˛/ 2 Yi º: Finally let C D \¹Ci j i < !º; and let Y D [¹Yi j i < !º: Since I is a -ideal, Y 2 I and so Y is Z-small. However for each ˛ 2 C , .˛/ Y . Therefore X Y which is a contradiction since X is not Z-small.
t u
Remark 7.25. We originally proved Theorem 7.24 with the additional hypothesis that t u the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated. Suppose h 2 ! ! . Let ŒhE be the set of functions f 2 ! ! such that for some i; j 2 !, h.i C k/ D f .j C k/ for all k 2 !. Thus X Œ0;1 is ŒhE -small if and only if X is ¹h.m/ j m < !º-small where for each m < !, h.m/ .k/ D h.m C k/ for k < !. Definition 7.26. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . ZBC .I / is the set of all pairs .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / such that the following hold.
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
451
(1) For all i < n, fi W !1 ! .0;1/ and hi W ! ! !. (2) S !1 and S … I . (3) If hOi W i < ni is a sequence of open subsets of .0;1/ such that for all i < n, Oi is hi -small then ¹˛ 2 S j fi .˛/ … Oi for all i < nº … I: (4) For all i < n if B is a borel set such that B is Œhi E -small then ¹˛ 2 S j fi .˛/ 2 Bº 2 I:
t u
We thin ZBC .I / and define YBC .I /. Definition 7.27. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . YBC .I / is the largest subset of ZBC .I / such that if .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I / then: (1) For each i < n there exists g 2 ! ! such that .h.fi ; g/i; S / 2 YBC .I / and such that for sufficiently large k 2 !, g.j / hi .k/ k
for all j < 5 ; (2) For some p 2 ! ! ,
.h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I /
where: a) p.0/ D 0 and p.k/ < p.k C 1/ for all k < !; b) for some m 2 !, m > 1 and p.k/ D k m for all sufficiently large k < !; c) for all i < n and for all j < !, hi .j / D hi .k/ where k < ! is such that p.k/ j < p.k C 1/.
t u
We define a slightly weaker refinement as follows. .I / is the largest Definition 7.28. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . YBC subset of ZBC .I / such that if .I / .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC
then for some p 2 ! ! , .I / .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC
452
7 Conditional variations
where: (1) p.0/ D 0 and p.k/ < p.k C 1/ for all k < !; (2) for some m 2 !, m > 1 and p.k/ D k m for all sufficiently large k < !; (3) for all i < n and for all j < !, hi .j / D hi .k/ where k < ! is such that p.k/ j < p.k C 1/.
t u
Remark 7.29. In Definition 7.27, condition (2) can be replaced by for each m 2 ! there exists p 2 ! ! such that: (1) p.0/ D 0 and p.k/ < p.k C 1/ for all k < !; (2) p.k/ D k m for all sufficiently large k < !; (3)
.h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I /; where for all i < n and for all j < !, if k 2 ! and p.k/ j < p.k C 1/ then hi .j / D hi .k/:
The analogous remark applies to Definition 7.28. We record in the following lemma sufficient conditions for membership in YBC .I /. Lemma 7.30. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . Suppose that .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 ZBC .I / is such that (1) for all i < n, .h.fi ; hi /i; S / 2 YBC .I /, (2) .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I /.
Then .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I /: Proof. Define for each ordinal ˛, a subset ˛ ZBC .I /
as follows. 0 ZBC .I / D ZBC .I / and if ˛ is a limit ordinal then ˛ ˇ .I / D \¹ZBC .I / j ˇ < ˛º: ZBC ˛C1 Finally for each ordinal ˛, ZBC .I / is the set of ˛ .h.fOi ; hO i / W i < ni; O SO / 2 ZBC .I /
t u
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
453
such that: ˛ .I / and such (1.1) for each i < nO there exists g 2 ! ! such that .h.fOi ; g/i; SO / 2 ZBC that for sufficiently large k 2 !,
g.j / hO i .k/ for all j < 5k ; (1.2) for some p 2 ! ! ,
˛ O SO / 2 ZBC .I / .h.fOi ; hO i / W i < ni;
where: a) p.0/ D 0 and p.k/ < p.k C 1/ for all k < !; b) for some m 2 !, m > 1 and p.k/ D k m for all sufficiently large k < !; c) for all i < nO and for all j < !, hO i .j / D hO i .k/ where k < ! is such that p.k/ j < p.k C 1/. Thus for for sufficiently large ˛, ˛ .I / D YBC .I /: ZBC
Fix .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 ZBC .I / satisfying the conditions of the lemma and assume toward a contradiction that .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / … YBC .I /: Thus for some ordinal ˛, ˛ .I /: .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / … ZBC
We may suppose that the choice of .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / minimizes ˛. Thus ˛ is a successor ordinal. Let ˛0 be such that ˛ D ˛0 C 1. Let p 2 ! ! be a function such that .I / .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC
where: (2.1) p.0/ D 0 and p.k/ < p.k C 1/ for all k < !; (2.2) for some m 2 !, m > 1 and for all sufficiently large k < !;
p.k/ D k m
454
7 Conditional variations
(2.3) for all i < n and for all j < !, hi .j / D hi .k/ where k < ! is such that p.k/ j < p.k C 1/. We claim that for all i < n, .h.fi ; hi /i; S / 2 YBC .I /: Fix i < n. Since
.I / .h.fi ; hi /i; S / 2 YBC
it follows that the elements of YBC .I / which witness .h.fi ; hi /i; S / 2 YBC .I / can be used to witness that .h.fi ; hi /i; S / 2 YBC .I /: Thus .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / satisfies the conditions of the lemma and so, ˛0 .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 ZBC .I /:
But this implies that ˛0 C1 .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 ZBC .I /;
t u
a contradiction.
Definition 7.31. Bmax consists of finite sequences h.M; I /; a; Y i such that the following hold. (1) M is a countable transitive model of ZFC. (2) M CH. (3) I 2 M and M “I is a normal uniform ideal on !1 ” . (4) M
AC .I /.
(5) .M; I / is iterable. (6) Y 2 M is the set YBC .I / as computed in M. (7) a 2 M, a !1M and M “!1 D !1LŒaŒx for some real x”. The order on Bmax is defined as follows. Suppose that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i and h.M2 ; I2 /; a2 ; Y2 i are conditions in Bmax . Then h.M2 ; I2 /; a2 ; Y2 i < h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i if
M1 2 H.!1 /M2
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
455
and there exists an iteration j W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / such that (1) j.a1 / D a2 , (2) I1 D I2 \ M1 , (3) j.Y1 / D Y2 \ M1 .
t u
Remark 7.32. (1) The only reason for requiring that the models occurring in the Bmax conditions actually be models of ZFC instead of ZFC is so that (6) in the definition of Bmax is unambiguous. The trivial point is that ZFC does not prove that YBC .I / exists. (2) There is actually a parameterized family of generalizations of Bmax . Fix a function h 2 ! ! . Let Bmax .h/ be the suborder of Bmax consisting of those conditions h.M; I /; a; Y i such that if g 2 ! ! and g occurs in Y then for sufficiently large i 2 !, h.i / < g.i /. t u We prove the basic iteration lemmas for Bmax . There are two iteration lemmas, one for models and one for sequences of models. The latter is necessary to show that Bmax is !-closed and its proof is an intrinsic part of the analysis of Bmax just as in the case of Pmax . We need several preliminary lemmas. For all m 2 ! and for all h 2 ! ! , let h.m/ be the function obtained by shifting h, h.m/ .k/ D h.m C k/ for k 2 !. Thus a set X Œ0;1 is ŒhE -small if and only if X is ¹h.m/ j m < !º-small. We note that if .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 ZBC .I / then for all m 2 !,
.h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < ni; S / 2 ZBC .I /:
This is immediate from the definition of ZBC .I /. We claim that if .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I / then for all m 2 !,
.h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I /:
This is easily verified noting the following. Suppose g 2 ! ! and h 2 ! ! are such that for all k m0 , g.j / h.k/
456
7 Conditional variations
for all j < 5k . Then for any m 2 !, g .m/ .j / h.m/ .k/ for all j < 5k and for all k max¹m0 m; 0º. One reason for thinning ZBC .I / to obtain YBC .I / is the following. Suppose that .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I / and fix i < n. Fix g 2 ! ! such that .h.fi ; g/i; S / 2 YBC .I / and such that for sufficiently large k 2 !, g.j / hi .k/ for all j < 5k . Fix m0 such that for all k > m0 , g.j / hi .k/ if j < 5k . For each m 2 ! let Hm 2 ! ! be such that for all j 2 !, Hm .j / D hi .k C m/ where k is such that 2 j C 1 < 2kC1 . Suppose that for each m 2 !, Om is Hm -small. For each m1 > m0 let k
Xm1 D [¹Om j m > m1 º: Then Xm1 is g .m1 / -small. This observation, which we prove in the next lemma, is the key to proving the subsequent lemmas. Lemma 7.33. Suppose g 2 ! ! , h 2 ! ! , and h.k/ g.j / for all j < 5k . For each m 2 ! let Hm 2 ! ! be such that for all j 2 !, Hm .j / D h.k C m/ where k is such that 2k j C 1 < 2kC1 . Suppose that for each m 2 !, Om is Hm -small. For each n 2 ! let Xn D [¹Om j m > nº: Then for each n 2 !, Xn is g .n/ -small. Proof. For each m 2 ! let hIjm W j < !i be a sequence of open intervals which witnesses that Om is Hm -small, so that for each m 2 !,
.Ijm / < 1=.Hm .j / C 1/; for each j 2 !.
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
457
Fix n 2 !. It suffices to show that ¹Ijm j m > n; j 2 !º witnesses that Xn is g .n/ -small. We note that for each a 2 ! with a > n, X
2k D
kCmDa;am>n
a.nC1/ X
2k D 2an 1 2aC1 n
kD0
and so for each a 2 !, j¹Ijm j 2k j C 1 < 2kC1 where k D a m and a m > nºj 2aC1 n: For each a 2 ! such that a > n let Ja D ¹Ijm j 2k j C 1 < 2kC1 where k D a m and a m > nº: Thus [¹Ja j a 2 !; a > 0º D ¹Ijm j m > n; j 2 !º: Each interval I 2 Ja has length at most 1=.h.a/ C 1/. For each a 2 ! such that a > n, g .n/ .j / h.a/ for all j such that 5a1 n C j < 5a . If a > n, j¹j j 5a1 n C j < 5a ºj 4 5a1 n and so jJa j j¹j j 5a1 n C j < 5a ºj; noting that since a > n, jJa j 2aC1 n: Thus ¹Ijm j m > n; j 2 !º t u
witnesses that Xn is g .n/ -small. Lemma 7.34. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 , g 2 ! ! , and .h.f; h/i; S / 2 ZBC .I /; where for all j 2 !, if k 2 ! and 2k j C 1 < 2kC1 then h.j / D g.k/: Then
.I /: .h.f; g/i; S / 2 YBC
Proof. This is immediate from the definitions.
t u
458
7 Conditional variations
Lemma 7.35. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . Suppose .h.f0 ; h0 /i; S / 2 YBC .I /; and that T S is a set such that T … I . Then there exists m < ! such that .h.f0 ; h.m/ 0 /i; T / 2 YBC .I /: Proof. For each m 2 ! let Hm 2 ! ! be such that for all j 2 !, Hm .j / D h0 .k C m/ k where k is such that 2 j C 1 < 2kC1 . We first prove that for some m 2 !, .h.f0 ; Hm /i; T / 2 ZBC .I /: If this fails then there is a sequence hOm W m < !i of open sets such that (1.1) T n ¹˛ 2 T j f0 .˛/ 2 Om º 2 I , (1.2) for all m < !, Om is Hm -small. Let g 2 ! ! be such that (2.1) .h.f0 ; g/i; S / 2 ZBC .I /, (2.2) for sufficiently large k 2 !, g.j / h0 .k/ if j < 5k . By Lemma 7.33, for sufficiently large k 2 !, [¹Om j m > kº .k/ is g -small. Let B D \¹[¹Om j m > kº j k 2 !º and so B is ŒgE -small. However by (1.1) ¹˛ 2 T j f0 .˛/ 2 Bº … I which is a contradiction since T S . Fix m0 2 ! such that .h.f0 ; Hm0 /i; T / 2 ZBC .I /: By Lemma 7.34, 0/ .h.f0 ; h.m /i; T / 2 YBC .I /: 0 For each h 2 ! ! and for each s 2 !
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
459
For each m 2 ! let Gm 2 ! ! be such that for all j 2 !, Gm .j / D g0 .k C m/ where k is such that 2 j C 1 < 2kC1 . We prove that there exists s 2 !
.h.f0 ; s Gm0 /i; T / 2 ZBC .I /: Fix g1 2 ! ! such that .h.f0 ; g1 /i; S / 2 YBC .I / and such that for sufficiently large k 2 !, g1 .j / g0 .k/ if j < 5k . Arguing as above there exists m1 2 ! such that .h.f0 ; Gm1 /i; T / 2 ZBC .I /: By increasing m1 if necessary we may suppose that for all k m1 , g1 .j / g0 .k/ if j < 5k . Let m2 D 2m1 C2 . For each n 2 ! let sn 2 ! m2 be the constant function taking value n. We claim that .h.f0 ; sn Gm0 /i; T / 2 ZBC .I / for some n 2 !. If not then for each n 2 ! there exists an open set Un such that Un is sn Gm0 -small and such that ¹˛ 2 T j f0 .˛/ … Un º 2 I: Each set Un can be partitioned into open sets Un0 and Un1 such that Un0 is sn -small .m2 / -small. and such that Un1 is Gm 0 Thus for sufficiently large n, Un is g1 -small. This contradicts .h.f0 ; g1 /i; S / 2 YBC .I /: Therefore there exists n such that (3.1) .h.f0 ; sn Gm0 /i; T / 2 ZBC .I /, (3.2) .h.f0 ; sn .g0.m0 / //i; T / 2 YBC .I /.
Thus for each g 2 ! ! such that h.f0 ; g/; S i 2 YBC .I / there exists s 2 !
such that h.f0 ; s .g .m0 / //; T i 2 YBC .I /:
460
7 Conditional variations
Let Z be the set of .h.f0 ; s .h.m0 / //i; T / such that (4.1) .h.f0 ; h/i; S / 2 YBC .I /, (4.2) s 2 !
The elements of Z provide the witnesses necessary to show that 0/ .h.f0 ; h.m /i; T / 2 YBC .I /: 0
t u
Lemma 7.36. Suppose I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . Suppose .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 YBC .I /; .h.fn ; hn /i; S / 2 YBC .I /; and that T S is a set such that T … I . Then there exists m < ! such that .h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < n C 1i; T / 2 YBC .I /: Proof. For each .i; m/ 2 .n C 1/ ! define Hi;m 2 ! ! by Hi;m .j / D hi .k C m/ where k is such that 2 j C 1 < 2kC1 . By Lemma 7.35, we can suppose that for each i < n C 1, and for each m < !, k
.h.fi ; h.m/ i /i; T / 2 YBC .I /: Assume the lemma fails. Thus by Lemma 7.30, for each m 2 !, .h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < n C 1i; T / … YBC .I /: .I / as a refinement of ZBC .I /, Therefore as a consequence of the definition of YBC for each m 2 ! there exists a sequence
hOim W i < n C 1i of open sets such that (1.1) T n ¹˛ 2 T j fi .˛/ 2 Oim for some i < n C 1º 2 I , (1.2) for all i < n C 1, Oim is Hi;m -small. The ideal I is countably complete and so there is a set T1 T such that T nT1 2 I and such that for all m 2 ! and for all ˛ 2 T1 , fi .˛/ 2 Oim for some i < n C 1.
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
461
For each i < n C 1 let gi 2 ! ! be such that (2.1) .h.fi ; gi /i; S / 2 ZBC .I /, (2.2) for sufficiently large k 2 !, gi .m/ hi .k/ if m < 5k . By Lemma 7.33, for each i < n C 1 and for sufficiently large k 2 !, [¹Oim j m > kº is gi.k/ -small. For each i < n C 1 let Bi D \¹[¹Oim j m > kº j k 2 !º and so for each i < n C 1, Bi is Œgi E -small. Therefore, since for each i < n C 1, .h.fi ; gi /i; S / 2 ZBC .I /; there is a set T2 T1 such that T1 n T2 2 I and such that for all i < n C 1 and for all ˛ 2 T2 , fi .˛/ … Bi . Fix ˛ 2 T2 . Then ˛ 2 T1 and so for all m 2 !, fi .˛/ 2 Oim for some i < n C 1. Thus for some i < n C 1, the set ¹m 2 ! j fi .˛/ 2 Oim º is infinite and so fi .˛/ 2 Bi which is a contradiction. Therefore for some m 2 !, .h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < n C 1i; T / 2 YBC .I /.
t u
Lemma 7.36 can be recast as follows. This reformulation is in essence what is required to prove the iteration lemmas. Lemma 7.37. Suppose that h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Bmax , .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 Y , .h.fn ; hn /i; S / 2 Y , and that hOi W i < ni is a finite sequence of open sets such that each Oi is hi -small. For each i < n let hIki W k < !i be a sequence of open intervals in .0;1/ with rational endpoints such that the sequence witnesses that Oi is hi -small. Suppose A 2 M, A .P .!1 / n I /M ; and A is dense below S in .P .!1 / n I; /M . Suppose m0 2 !. There exists m > m0 and there exists T 2 A such that (1) T S , (2) .h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < n C 1i; T / 2 Y , (3) fi .˛/ … Iki for all k < m, for all i < n, and for all ˛ 2 T . Proof. This follows from Lemma 7.36 by absoluteness. Fix m0 2 !. Let T be the tree of attempts to build the sequences hIki W k < !i to refute the lemma. So T is the set of hti W i < ni such that for some m > m0 :
462
7 Conditional variations
(1.1) For all i < n, ti D h.rki ; ski / W k < mi where for all k < m, a) 0 rki < ski 1, b) rki 2 Q, c) ski 2 Q, d) .ski rki / < 1=.hi .k/ C 1/. (1.2) For all T S with T 2 A, either .h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < n C 1i; T / … Y; or for some i < n and for some ˛ 2 T , fi .˛/ 2 [¹.rki ; ski / j k < mº: The ordering on T is by (pointwise) extension, hsi W i < ni hti W i < ni if ti si for all i < n. Clearly T 2 M. Suppose T has an infinite branch. Then by absoluteness, T has an infinite branch in M. We work in M and assume toward a contradiction that T has an infinite branch. Any such branch yields for each i < n a sequence h.rki ; ski / W k < !i of open intervals in .0;1/ with rational endpoints such that for all i < n and for all k < !, jski rki j < 1=.hi .k/ C 1/: These sequences have the additional property that for all T 2 A such that T S and for all m < ! either .h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < n C 1i; T / … Y; or for some i < n and for some ˛ 2 T , fi .˛/ 2 [¹.rki ; ski / j k < mº: For each i < n let OQ i D [¹.rki ; ski / j k < !º: Thus for each i < n, OQ i is hi -small. Let T0 D ¹˛ 2 S j fi .˛/ … OQ i for all i < nº: Since .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 Y ,
T0 … I:
A is dense below S and so there exists T 2 A such that T T0 . By Lemma 7.36, there exists m < ! such that .h.fi ; h.m/ i / W i < n C 1i; T / 2 Y: This is a contradiction and so T is wellfounded in M. Hence T is wellfounded in V . t u
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
463
The iteration lemmas are proved using the following lemmas which in turn follow rather easily from the previous lemmas. Lemma 7.38. Suppose h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Bmax . Suppose .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / is an element of Y and suppose h.fi ; hi ; Si / W i < !i is a sequence extending h.fi ; hi ; S / W i < ni such that for each i < ! if i n then .h.fi ; hi /i; Si / 2 Y . Suppose hBi W i < !i is a sequence of borel sets such that each i < !, if i < n then Bi is hi -small and if i n then Bi is Œhi E -small. Then there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / of length 1 such that (1) for all i < !, if !1M 2 j.Si / then j.fi /.!1M / … Bi , (2) !1M 2 j.S /. Proof. Let hAi W n i < !i enumerate the sets in M which are dense in .P .!1 / n I /M . Using Lemma 7.37 it is straightforward to build sequences hTi W i < !i;
hIji W i; j < !i;
and
hNi W i < !i
such that for all i < ! the following hold. Let Z D ¹i < ! j Si \ Ti ¤ ;º: (1.1) Ni D 0 and Ti D S for i < n. (1.2) If i n then Ti 2 Ai and either Ti Si or Ti \ Si D ;. (1.3) If i n then TiC1 Ti S , Ni 2 ! and Ni < NiC1 . (1.4) Iji is an open interval with rational endpoints and
.Iji / < 1=.hi .Ni C j / C 1/: (1.5) Bi [¹Iji j j < !º. .Ni /
(1.6) .h.fj ; hj
/ W j 2 Z \ i i; Ti / 2 Y .
(1.7) If i < n then for all ˛ 2 Tn , for all j < i , fj .˛/ … [¹Ikj j k < Nn º: (1.8) If i n then for all ˛ 2 TiC1 , for all j < i , if j 2 Z then fj .˛/ … [¹Ikj j k < NiC1 º:
464
7 Conditional variations
We first construct hTi W i ni;
hIji W i < n; j < !i;
and
hNi W i ni:
For this we need only specify hIji W i < n; j < !i; Tn and Nn . For each i < n let hIji W j < !i be a sequence of open intervals with rational endpoints such that Bi [¹Iji j j < !º and such that for all j < !,
.Iji / < 1=.hi C 1/: By Lemma 7.37, there exist L0 2 ! and T 0 2 An such that (2.1) T 0 Sn or T 0 \ Sn D ;, (2.2) T 0 S , 0
(2.3) .h.fi ; hi.L / / W i < ni; T 0 / 2 Y , (2.4) for all k < L0 , for all i < n, fi .˛/ … Iki for all ˛ 2 T 0 . Let Tn D T 0 and let Nn D L0 . We next suppose m n and that hTi W i mi;
hIji W i < m; j < !i;
and
hNi W i mi
i are given. For each i < m and k < ! let Jki D IkCN . Therefore m m/ / W i 2 Z \ mi; Tm / 2 Y .h.fi ; h.N i
and for each i < m, the sequence hJki W k < !i witnesses that Oi is .hi.Nm / /-small where Oi D [¹Jki j k < !º: By Lemma 7.37, there exist L0 2 ! and T 0 2 AmC1 such that (3.1) T 0 SmC1 or T 0 \ SmC1 D ;, (3.2) T 0 Tm , 0
m / .L / / / W i 2 Z \ mi; T 0 / 2 Y , (3.3) .h.fi ; .h.N i
(3.4) for all k < L0 , for all i 2 Z \ m, fi .˛/ … Jki for all ˛ 2 T 0 .
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
465
By Lemma 7.37 again, there exist L00 2 ! and T 00 2 AmC1 such that (4.1) T 00 T 0 , 00
m / .L / / / W i 2 Z \ m C 1i; T 00 / 2 Y , (4.2) .h.fi ; .h.N i
(4.3) for all k < L00 , for all i 2 Z \ m, fi .˛/ … Jki for all ˛ 2 T 00 . Of course if T 0 \ SmC1 D ; then one can simply let T 00 D T 0 and L00 D L0 . Set TmC1 D T 00 and NmC1 D Nm C L00 . Choose a sequence hJk W k < !i such .N / that hJk W k < !i witnesses that Bm is hm mC1 -small. The sequence exists since Bm is Œhm E -small. For each k < ! set Ikm D Jk . Therefore by induction the sequences exist. Let G be the filter generated by ¹Ti j i < !º. Thus G is M-generic. Let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the associated iteration of length 1. It follows from (1.5), (1.7), and (1.8) that for all t u i < !, if !1M 2 j.Si / then j.fi /.!1M / … Bi . There is an analogous version of the previous lemma for sequences of models. We shall apply this lemma only to sequences which are iterable. However the lemma holds for sequences which are not necessarily iterable and it is this more general version which we shall prove, (for no particular reason). Lemma 7.39. Suppose that h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is a sequence such that for each k < !, Mk is a countable transitive model of ZFC, Ik 2 Mk and such that in Mk , Ik M is a uniform normal ideal on !1 k . For each k < ! let Yk D .YBC .Ik //Mk : Suppose that for all k < !, (i) Mk 2 MkC1 , (ii) jMk jMkC1 D .!1 /MkC1 , Mk
(iii) !1
MkC1
D !1
,
(iv) IkC1 \ Mk D Ik , (v) Yk D YkC1 \ Mk , M
(vi) for each A 2 Mk such that A P .!1 k / \ Mk n Ik , if A is predense in .P .!1 / n Ik /Mk then A is predense in .P .!1 / n IkC1 /MkC1 .
466
7 Conditional variations
Suppose .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / is an element of Y0 and suppose h.fi ; hi ; Si / W i < !i is a sequence extending h.fi ; hi ; S / W i < ni such that for each i < ! if i n then .h.fi ; hi /i; Si / 2 Yi . Suppose hBi W i < !i is a sequence of borel sets such that each i < !, if i < n then Bi is hi -small and if i n then Bi is Œhi E -small. Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i of length 1 such that (1) for all i < !, if !1M0 2 j.Si / then j.fi /.!1M0 / … Bi , (2) !1M0 2 j.S /. Proof. Let hAi W n i < !i enumerate the sets A 2 [¹Mk j k 2 !º such that if A 2 Mk then
A .P .!1 / n Ik /Mk
and A is predense in
.P .!1 / n Ik ; /Mk :
By (vi) in the hypothesis of the lemma we can suppose that for each i < !, Ai 2 Mi : Following the proof of Lemma 7.38 it is straightforward, using Lemma 7.37 and (v), to build sequences hTi W i < !i, hIji W i; j < !i and hNi W i < !i such that for all i < ! the following hold. Let Z D ¹i < ! j Si \ Ti ¤ ;º: (1.1) Ni D 0 and Ti D S for i < n. (1.2) If i n then Ti 2 Ai and either Ti Si or Ti \ Si D ;. (1.3) If i n then TiC1 Ti S , Ni 2 ! and Ni < NiC1 . (1.4) Iji is an open interval with rational endpoints and
.Iji / < 1=.hi .Ni C j / C 1/: (1.5) Bi [¹Iji j j < !º. .Ni /
(1.6) .h.fj ; hj
/ W j 2 Z \ i i; Ti / 2 Yi .
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
467
(1.7) If i < n then for all ˛ 2 Tn , for all j < i , fj .˛/ … [¹Ikj j k < Nn º: (1.8) If i n then for all ˛ 2 TiC1 , for all j < i , if j 2 Z then fj .˛/ … [¹Ikj j k < NiC1 º: We first construct hTi W i ni;
hIji W i < n; j < !i;
and hNi W i ni:
For this we need only specify hIji W i < n; j < !i; Tn and Nn . For each i < n let hIji W j < !i be a sequence of open intervals with rational endpoints such that Bi [¹Iji j j < !º and such that for all j < !,
.Iji / < 1=.hi C 1/: By Lemma 7.37, there exist L0 2 ! and T 0 2 An such that (2.1) T 0 Sn or T 0 \ Sn D ;, (2.2) T 0 S , 0
(2.3) .h.fi ; hi.L / / W i < ni; T 0 / 2 Yn , (2.4) for all k < L0 , for all i < n, fi .˛/ … Iki for all ˛ 2 T 0 . Let Tn D T 0 and let Nn D L0 . We next suppose m n and that hTi W i mi;
hIji W i < m; j < !i;
and
hNi W i mi
i are given. For each i < m and k < ! let Jki D IkCN . m Therefore m/ .h.fi ; h.N / W i 2 Z \ mi; Tm / 2 Ym i
and for each i < m, the sequence hJki W k < !i witnesses that Oi is .hi.Nm / /-small where Oi D [¹Jki j k < !º: By (v), Ym D YmC1 \ Mm and so
m/ .h.fi ; h.N / W i 2 Z \ mi; Sm / 2 YmC1 : i
468
7 Conditional variations
By Lemma 7.37, there exist L0 2 ! and T 0 2 MmC1 such that (3.1) T 0 !1M0 and T 0 a for some a 2 AmC1 , (3.2) T 0 SmC1 or T 0 \ SmC1 D ;, (3.3) T 0 Tm , 0
m / .L / (3.4) .h.fi ; .h.N / / W i 2 Z \ mi; T 0 / 2 Ym , i
(3.5) for all k < L0 , for all i 2 Z \ m, fi .˛/ … Jki for all ˛ 2 T 0 . By Lemma 7.37 once more, there exist L00 2 ! and T 00 2 MmC1 such that (4.1) T 00 T 0 , 00
m / .L / / / W i 2 Z \ m C 1i; T 00 / 2 YmC1 , (4.2) .h.fi ; .h.N i
(4.3) for all k < L00 , for all i 2 Z \ m, fi .˛/ … Jki for all ˛ 2 T 00 . Of course, as in the proof of Lemma 7.38, if T 0 \ SmC1 D ; then one can simply let T 00 D T 0 and L00 D L0 . Set TmC1 D T 00 and NmC1 D Nm C L00 . Choose a sequence hJk W k < !i such .N / that hJk W k < !i witnesses that Bm is hm mC1 -small. The sequence exists since Bm is Œhm E -small. For each k < ! set Ikm D Jk . Therefore by induction the sequences exist. Let G be the filter generated by ¹Ti j i < !º. Thus G is [¹Mi j i < !º-generic. Let j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i be the associated iteration of length 1. It follows from (1.5), (1.7) and (1.8) that for all t u i < !, if !1M0 2 j.Si / then j.fi /.!1M0 / … Bi . With these lemmas the main iterations lemmas are easily proved. As usual it is really the proofs of these iteration lemmas which are the key to the analysis of Bmax . Lemma 7.40 (CH). Suppose h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Bmax and that J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Then there is an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that (1) J \ M D I , (2) j.Y / D YBC .J / \ M .
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
469
Proof. Let hSk;˛ W k < !; ˛ < !1 i be a sequence of pairwise disjoint J -positive sets such that !1 D [¹Sk;˛ j k < !; ˛ < !1 º: Let hs˛ W ˛ < !1 i be an enumeration (with repetition) of all finite sequences of open subsets of .0;1/ such that for each finite sequence s of open subsets of .0;1/, and for each .k; ˛/ 2 ! !1 , ¹ı 2 Sk;˛ j s D sı º is a set which is J -positive. Let hB˛ W ˛ < !1 i be an enumeration of all the borel subsets of .0;1/. Let x be a real which codes M and let C !1 be a closed unbounded set of ordinals which are admissible relative to x. Fix a function F W ! !1M ! M such that (1.1) F is onto, (1.2) for all k < !, F jk !1M 2 M, (1.3) for all A 2 M if A has cardinality !1M in M then A ran.F jk !1M / for some k < !. The function F is simply used to anticipate elements in the final model. Our situation is similar to that in the proof of Lemma 7.7. Suppose j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is an iteration. Then we define j.F / D [¹j.F jk !1M / j k < !º and it is easily verified that M is the range of j.F /. This follows from (1.3). Implicit in what follows is that for ˇ 2 C if j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is an iteration of length ˇ then j.!1M / D ˇ. This is a consequence of Lemma 4.6(1). We construct an iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i of M of length !1 using the function F to provide a book-keeping device for dealing with elements of j0;!1 ..P .!1 / n I /M / and for dealing with elements of j0;!1 .Y /.
470
7 Conditional variations
More precisely construct by induction, an iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i as follows. Suppose ı < !1 and that h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ ıi: Fix .k; / 2 ! !1 such that ı 2 Sk; . If ı … C or if ı then choose Gı to be any Mı -generic filter. If ı 2 C and if < ı there are three cases. We first suppose that j0;ı .F /.k; / D .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / and that .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 j0;ı .Y /. Suppose sı D hOi W i < ni is a sequence of length n such that for each i < n, Oi is hi -small. Let h.fi ; hi ; Si / W i < !i be a sequence extending the sequence h.fi ; hi ; S / W i < ni such that for all i < !, .h.fi ; hi /i; Si / 2 j0;ı .Y / and such that for all
.h.f 0 ; h0 /i; S 0 / 2 j0;ı .Y /;
.h.f 0 ; h0 /i; S 0 / D .h.fi ; hi /i; Si / for infinitely many i < !. Let hBi0 W i < !i be a sequence of borel sets extending hOi W i < ni such that for all i n, Bi0 is Œhi E -small and such that for all ˛ < ı if .h.f 0 ; h0 /i; S 0 / 2 j0;ı .Y / and if B˛ is h0 -small then for some j > n, B˛ D Bj0 and .h.f 0 ; h0 /i; S 0 / D .h.fj ; hj /i; Sj /: By Lemma 7.38, there exists an iteration j W .Mı ; Iı / ! .MıC1 ; IıC1 / of length 1 such that Mı
(2.1) for all i < !, if !1 Mı
(2.2) !1
M
2 j.Si / then j.fi /.!1 ı / … Bi0 ,
2 j.S /.
Let jı;ıC1 D j and let Gı be the associated Mı -generic filter. The remaining cases are similar. Choose j W .Mı ; Iı / ! .MıC1 ; IıC1 /
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
471
of length 1 such that for all .h.f 0 ; h0 /i; S 0 / 2 j0;ı .Y / if
Mı
!1 then
2 j.S 0 / M
j.f 0 /.!1 ı / … B˛
for all ˛ < ı such that B˛ is h0 -small. Let jı;ıC1 D j and let Gı be the associated Mı -generic filter. If j0;ı .F /.k; / 2 .P .!1 / n Iı /Mı ; then choose j such that in addition to the requirement above, Mı
!1
2 j.S /
where S D j0;ı .F /.k; /. In each of these last two cases j exists by Lemma 7.38. This completes the inductive construction of the iteration h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i: It is straightforward to verify that this iteration is as required. The first case of the construction at the inductive step guarantees that j0;!1 .Y / ZBC .J / and this implies that j0;!1 .Y / YBC .J /: The second case guarantees J \ M!1 D I!1 and so j0;!1 .Y / D YBC .J / \ M!1 :
t u
The analysis of the Bmax -extension requires the generalization of Lemma 7.40 to sequences of models. We state this lemma only for the sequences that arise, specifically those sequences of structures coming from descending sequences of conditions in Bmax . Suppose that hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in Bmax such that for all k < !, pkC1 < pk : We let hpk W k < !i be the associated sequence of conditions which is defined as follows. For each k < ! let h.Mk ; Ik /; ak ; Yk i D pk and let
jk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik /
472
7 Conditional variations
be the iteration obtained by combining the iterations given by the conditions pi for i > k. Thus jk is uniquely specified by the requirement that jk .ak / D [¹ai j i < !º: For each k < !, pk D h.M ; Ik /; jk .ak /; jk .Yk /i: We note that by Corollary 4.20, the sequence h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is iterable (in the sense of Definition 4.8). Lemma 7.41 (CH). Suppose hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in Bmax such that for each k < ! pkC1 < pk : Let hpk W k < !i be the associated sequence of Bmax conditions and for each k < ! let h.Mk ; Ik /; ak ; Yk i D pk : Suppose that J is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Then there is an iteration j W h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i ! h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i such that for all k < !; (1) J \ Mk D Ik , (2) YBC .J / \ Mk D j.Yk /. Proof. By Corollary 4.20, the sequence h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i is iterable. The lemma follows by a routine modification of the proof of Lemma 7.40 using Lemma 7.39 in place of Lemma 7.38. t u Theorem 7.43 establishes the nontriviality of Bmax in the sense required for the analysis of L.R/Bmax . The proof requires Theorem 7.18, Theorem 7.42 and the transfer principle supplied by Theorem 5.36.
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
473
Theorem 7.42. Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal. Suppose A R and that every set of reals which is projective in A is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then there is an iterable structure .M; I / such that M ZFC C CH and such that (1) M
AC .I /,
(2) A \ M 2 M, (3) hH.!1 /M ; A \ Mi hH.!1 /; Ai, (4) .M; I / is A-iterable. Proof. Suppose that G Coll.!1 ; <ı/ is V -generic. By Theorem 7.18, in V ŒG there exists a normal uniform saturated ideal IG on !1 such that IG \ V D .INS /V and such that V ŒG
AC .IG /:
Trivially, RV D RV ŒG . Thus in V ŒG every set of reals which is projective in A is weakly homogeneously Suslin. This is witnessed by the trees in V which witness that every set which is projective in A is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal in V ŒG. As usual necessarily exists (otherwise in V ŒG every weakly homogeneously Suslin set is †11 ). Let X V ŒG be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹IG ; Aº X: Let M be the transitive collapse of X and let I be the image of IG under the collapsing map. Thus A \ M 2 M and hH.!1 /M ; A \ Mi hH.!1 /; Ai: By Lemma 6.26, .M; I / is A-iterable. Finally .M; I / 2 V since R D R V
V ŒG
.
As an immediate corollary we obtain the nontriviality of Bmax .
t u
474
7 Conditional variations
Theorem 7.43. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose A R and that A 2 L.R/: Then there is a condition h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Bmax such that (1) A \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; A \ Mi hH.!1 /; Ai, (3) .M; I / is A-iterable, and further the set of such conditions is dense in Bmax . Proof. By Theorem 5.36, there exist a transitive set M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that (1.1) M ZFC, (1.2) A \ M 2 M and hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i; (1.3) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M , (1.4) B is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M for each set B 2 P .R/M such that in M , B is projective in A \ M . By Theorem 7.42 there exists .M; I / 2 H.!1 /M such that (2.1) M ZFC C CH, (2.2) I 2 M and in M, I is a normal uniform saturated ideal on !1 , (2.3) M
AC .I /,
(2.4) A \ M 2 M and hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i; (2.5) .M; I / is A \ M -iterable in M . Thus
hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i hH.!1 /; A; 2i;
and in V , .M; I / is A-iterable. Let
Y D .YBC /M
and let a !1M be any set in M such that !1LŒa;x D !1M for some x 2 R \ M. Thus h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Bmax and is as desired. The density of such conditions follows abstractly by standard argut u ments using the iteration lemmas for Bmax , cf. the proof of Theorem 4.40.
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
475
The analysis of Bmax is now a straightforward generalization of that of Pmax . Suppose G Bmax is L.R/-generic. Then for each h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 G there corresponds a unique iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j .!1M / D !1 . This iteration is constructed by combining the countable iterations of .M; I / given by conditions p 2 G such that p < h.M; I /; a; Y i: Let (1) YG D [¹j .Y / j h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Gº, (2) IG D [¹j .I / j h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Gº, (3) AG D [¹j .a/ j h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Gº,
(4) P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; a; Y i 2 Gº. Theorem 7.44. Assume AD L.R/ . Then Bmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Suppose G Bmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 / D P .!1 /G ; (2) IG is a normal saturated ideal; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) the sentence AC holds; (5) YG D YBC .INS /. Proof. We leave the details to the reader. (1)–(4) follow from the iteration lemmas for Bmax by arguments analogous to those for Pmax . The only difference in the present situation is that the iteration lemmas require the additional assumption of CH. But the models occurring in the conditions of Bmax are required to satisfy CH and so the iteration lemmas for Bmax hold in these models. Finally (5) follows from (1) and the definition of order relation between conditions t u in Bmax . Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose that A !1 . Then the set A is L.R/-generic for Bmax if there exists an L.R/-generic filter G Bmax such that AG D A. The analog of Theorem 4.60 also holds for the Bmax -extension. The proof requires the version of Lemma 4.59 for Bmax . This is easily proved following the proof of Lemma 4.59 and using Lemma 4.57. The proof of Theorem 4.60 then adapts to establish to the case of Bmax , using Lemma 7.19 in place of Lemma 4.35 (these are the lemmas regarding uniqueness of iterations).
476
7 Conditional variations
Theorem 7.45. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose G Bmax is L.R/-generic. Suppose A !1 , A 2 L.R/ŒG n L.R/. Then A is L.R/-generic for Bmax and L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒA:
t u
Lemma 4.52 and Theorem 4.53 also generalize to the Bmax -extension. Theorem 7.46. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Bmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG the following hold. (1) Suppose B R and B 2 L.R/. Then the set ¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . (2) Suppose S !1 is stationary and f W S ! Ord. Then there is a function g 2 L.R/ such that ¹˛ 2 S j g.˛/ D f .˛/º is stationary. Proof. (1) follows by an argument essentially identical to the proof of Lemma 4.52. The application of the argument requires P .!1 /G D P .!1 / which is true by Theorem 7.44. (2) follows from (1) and Theorem 3.42 using a chain condition argument to reduce to the case that f WS !ı for some ı < ‚L.R/ , cf. the proof of Theorem 4.53.
t u
To prove that the Borel Conjecture holds in L.R/Bmax we use the following lemmas. Suppose U is a free ultrafilter on !. Recall that the ultrafilter U is selective if for all partitions h k W k < !i of ! either k 2 U for some k < ! or there exists 2 U such that j \ k j 1 for all k < !. Let PU denote the partial order defined as follows. This is Prikry forcing adapted to U . PU consists of pairs .s; / such that s is a finite subset of ! and 2 U . The order is defined by, .s1 ; 1 / .s0 ; 0 / if s0 s1 , 1 0 and
s1 n s0 0 :
Selective ultrafilters satisfy the following condition. Suppose W Œ!
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
477
is a function where Œ!
t u
Suppose G PU is V -generic. Suppose B .0;1/ is a borel set in V . Let BG denote the borel set defined by interpreting B in V ŒG. Lemma 7.48. Suppose U is a selective ultrafilter on ! and that h 2 ! ! . Suppose p 2 ! ! is such that (1) p.0/ D 0, (2) p.k/ < p.k C 1/ for all k 2 !, (3) limk!1 .p.k C 1/ p.k// D 1. Let h 2 ! ! be the function such that for all j 2 !, h .j / D h.k/ where k 2 ! and p.k/ j < p.k C 1/. Suppose that G PU is V -generic and that O 2 V ŒG is an open set such that O .0;1/ and O is h-small. Then there exists an open set W 2 V such that in V , W is h -small and such that in V ŒG, O WG :
478
7 Conditional variations
Proof. Let 0 be a term for O. We work in V . We may suppose that .;; !/ 0 .0;1/ and that .;; !/ “0 is h-small”: Let 1 be a term for an h-small cover of . Again we may suppose that .;; !/ “1 is an h-small cover of 0 ”: We prove that there exists an open set W .0;1/ such that W is h -small and such that .;; / 0 WG for some 2 U . By homogeneity this suffices. Let I be the set of open subintervals of .0;1/. By Lemma 7.47, for each s 2 Œ!
.Hs .k// 2=.h.k/ C 1/: For each k 2 ! n 0 let Nk 2 ! be such that for all j Nk , p.j C 1/ p.j / > 3 2kC2 : Let N0 D 0. By increasing the Nk , k > 0, if necessary, we may suppose that for all k < !, Nk < NkC1 : For each m 2 ! let m 2 U be such that .t; m / 1 .k/ H t .k/ for all t m C 1 and for all k NmC1 . The ultrafilter U is selective and so there exists 2 U such that for all k 2 !, j \ ŒNk ; NkC1 /j 1; and such that for all s 2 Œ mº m where m D [s. For each k 2 ! let ak be the least element of n Nk . Let J be the set of intervals of the form Hs .j / such that for some k 2 !, Nk j < NkC1 and such that
s .NkC1 \ / [ ¹akC1 º:
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
Let W D [J. We claim that W is h -small and that .;; / 0 WG : We first prove that Suppose
.;; / 0 WG : .s; / .;; /
and that j < [s. Let k 2 ! be such that Nk j < NkC1 : We may suppose that
¹k 2 j k > [sº:
There are two cases. First, suppose that akC1 2 s: Then .s; / 1 .j / H t .j / where t D s \ .akC1 C 1/. However H t .j / 2 J and so .s; / 1 .j / WG : Second, suppose that akC1 … s: Then .s; / 1 .j / H t .j / where t D s \ akC1 . Again H t .j / 2 J and so again .s; / 1 .j / WG : Thus
.;; / 0 WG :
We finish by proving that W is h -small. We note that since for all k 2 !, j \ ŒNk ; NkC1 /j 1; it follows that for all k 2 !, jP . \ NkC1 /j 2kC1 : Suppose m 2 ! and let k 2 ! be such that Nk m < NkC1 : Let Jm be the set of intervals of the form Hs .m/ such that s .NkC1 \ / [ ¹akC1 º: Thus J D [¹Jm j m 2 !º:
479
480
7 Conditional variations
Further for each m 2 !,
jJm j 2kC2
and each interval in Jm has length at most 2=.h.m/ C 1/ where k 2 ! is such that
Nk m < NkC1 :
be the collection of intervals For each m 2 !, let Jm interval .a; b/ 2 Jm , Jm contains the intervals,
.a; .a C b/=2/;
Let J D
[¹Jm
obtained as follows. For each
.a C .b a/=4; b .b a/=4/;
and
..a C b/=2; b/:
j m < !º. Thus W D [J :
Suppose m 2 ! and let k 2 ! be such that Nk m < NkC1 : Each interval in
Jm
has length at most 1=.h.m/ C 1/ and j 3 2kC2 : jJm
For each j 2 ! such that
p.m/ j < p.m C 1/;
we have that h .j / D h.m/. Further since m Nk , p.m C 1/ p.m/ 3 2kC2 : It follows that W is h -small.
t u
Suppose G PU is V -generic. Let aG D [¹s j .s; / 2 Gº and let hG W ! ! ! be the enumeration function of aG . We note the following. Suppose that I is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 and that P is ccc. Suppose that G P is V -generic. Then in V ŒG the ideal I defines three ideals, (1) I0 which is the ideal generated by I , I0 D ¹A !1 j A B for some B 2 I º; (2) I1 which is the -ideal generated by I0 , (3) I2 which is the normal ideal generated by I0 . Under certain circumstances, these three ideals can coincide.
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
481
Lemma 7.49. Suppose U is a selective ultrafilter on ! and that for all X U , if jX j D !1 then there exists 2 U such that n is finite for all 2 X . Suppose I is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Suppose G PU is V -generic. Let I.G/ be the ideal generated by I in V ŒG. Then in V ŒG: (1) I.G/ is a normal uniform ideal on !1 ; (2) suppose f W !1 ! .0;1/ is an injective function such that f 2 V , then V ŒG .h.f; h.n/ G /i; !1 / 2 .YBC .I.G/ //
for some n 2 !. Proof. Suppose F 2 V ŒG is a function, F W !1 ! !1 such that F .˛/ < ˛ for all ˛ > 0. Suppose A !1 , A 2 V ŒG and A … I.G/ . We may suppose 0 … A. We must show that there exists B such that B A, B … I.G/ and such that F jB is constant. Let F 2 V PU be a term for the function F and let A 2 V P be a term for the set A. Fix a condition .s0 ; 0 / 2 G. We may suppose that .s0 ; 0 / A … I.G/ :
We work in V . Let A be the set of ˛ < !1 such that there exists a condition .s; / < .s0 ; 0 / with the property that .s; / ˛ 2 A : Since .s0 ; 0 / A … I.G/ ;
it follows that A … I . For each ˛ 2 !1 choose a condition .s˛ ; ˛ / < .s0 ; 0 / and an ordinal ˛ < ˛ such that .s˛ ; ˛ / .˛/ D ˛ ; and such that if ˛ 2 A then .s˛ ; ˛ / ˛ 2 A ;
and if ˛ … A then
.s˛ ; ˛ / ˛ … A :
Let 2 U be such that for all ˛ 2 A, \ .! n ˛ / is finite.
482
7 Conditional variations
For each ˛ 2 A let n˛ 2 ! be such that n n˛ ˛ . The ideal I is normal. Therefore there exists a set B A such that B … I and there exists .s; n; / 2 Œ!
.s; n n/ .˛/ D :
By the genericity of G we may suppose that .s; n n/ 2 G: This proves (1). We prove (2). Fix a function f W !1 ! .0;1/ such that f 2 V and such that f is injective. Assume that for each n 2 !, V ŒG : .h.f; h.n/ G /i; !1 / 62 .ZBC .I.G/ //
Then for each n 2 ! there exist an open set On and a set An 2 I.G/ such that On is h.n/ G -small and such that ¹˛ < !1 j f .˛/ … On º An : I.G/ is the ideal generated by I and PU is ccc. Therefore there must exist A 2 I such that for all n < ! and for all ˛ 2 !1 n A, f .˛/ 2 On . Let X D ¹f .˛/ j ˛ 2 Aº. Thus X 2 V , jX j D !1 and X is ŒhG E -small in V ŒG. This is a contradiction. Therefore for some n 2 !, V ŒG : .h.f; h.n/ G /i; !1 / 2 .ZBC .I.G/ //
A similar argument shows the following. Suppose that p 2 ! ! \ V and that (1.1) p.0/ D 0, (1.2) p.k/ < p.k C 1/ for all k 2 !, (1.3) limk!1 .p.k C 1/ p.k// D 1. Let hG;p 2 ! ! be the function such that for all j 2 !, hG;p .j / D h.k/ where k 2 ! and p.k/ j < p.k C 1/. Then for some n < !, V ŒG .h.f; h.n/ : G;p /i; !1 / 2 .ZBC .I.G/ //
It follows that for some n 2 !, V ŒG : .h.f; h.n/ G /i; !1 / 2 .YBC .I.G/ //
t u
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
483
Lemma 7.50. Suppose U is a selective ultrafilter on ! and that I is a normal uniform ideal on !1 . Suppose G PU is V -generic. Let I.G/ be the normal ideal generated by I in V ŒG. Then in V ŒG: (1) I.G/ \ V D I ; (2) .YBC .I //V D V \ .YBC .I.G/ //V ŒG ; (3) suppose f W !1 ! .0;1/ is an injective function such that f 2 V , then V ŒG .h.f; h.n/ G /i; !1 / 2 .YBC .I.G/ //
for some n 2 !. Proof. (1) is an immediate consequence of the fact that PU is ccc. We prove (2). Suppose B .0;1/ is a borel set in V . Let BG be the interpretation of B in V ŒG. It suffices to prove that for all .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 .YBC .I //V ; .h.fi ; hi / W i < ni; S / 2 .ZBC .I.G/ //V ŒG : Granting this (2) follows from the definition of .YBC .I.G/ //V ŒG as a subset of .ZBC .I.G/ //V ŒG . The claim that .YBC .I //V .ZBC .I.G/ //V ŒG follows from Lemma 7.48. To illustrate how we suppose .h.f; h/i; S / 2 .YBC .I //V and prove that .h.f; h/i; S / 2 .ZBC .I.G/ //V ŒG : Fix p0 2 ! ! such that .h.f; h /i; S / 2 .YBC .I //V where: (1.1) p0 .0/ D 0 and p0 .k/ < p0 .k C 1/ for all k < !; (1.2) for some m 2 !, m > 1 and p0 .k/ D k m for all sufficiently large k < !;
484
7 Conditional variations
(1.3) for all i < n and for all j < !, hi .j / D hi .k/ where k < ! is such that p0 .k/ j < p0 .k C 1/. Suppose O 2 V ŒG is an open set such that O is h-small. By Lemma 7.48, there exists an open set W 2 V such that W is h -small and such that O WG : In V , ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ … W º is I -positive. Hence in V ŒG, ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ … Oº is I.G/ positive since by (1) I.G/ \ V D I: Therefore .h.f; h/i; S / 2 .ZBC .I.G/ //V ŒG : The general case is similar. Finally we prove (3). Fix f W !1 ! .0;1/ such that f is injective and such that f 2 V . Suppose V ŒG0 is a ccc extension of V such that V ŒG0 MA C “.2@0 /V < 2@0 ”: Let U0 2 V ŒG0 be a selective ultrafilter such that U U0 and such that in V ŒG0 , for all X U0 , if jX j D !1 then there exists 2 U0 such that \ .! n / is finite for all 2 X. Suppose G1 PU0 is V ŒG0 -generic. By Lemma 7.47(2), G1 \ PU is V -generic. Therefore without loss of generality we may suppose that G1 \ PU D G. Let I.G0 / be the normal ideal generated by I in V ŒG0 and let I.G0 ;G1 / be the ideal generated by I.G0 / in V ŒG0 ŒG1 . By Lemma 7.49, there exists n 2 ! such that V ŒG0 ;G1 : .h.f; h.n/ G /i; !1 / 2 .YBC .I.G0 ;G1 / //
Therefore V ŒG .h.f; h.n/ G /i; !1 / 2 .YBC .I.G/ //
since I.G/ I.G0 ;G1 / . Combining Theorem 7.44 and Lemma 7.50 we obtain the following corollary.
t u
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
485
Theorem 7.51. Assume ADL.R/ . Then L.R/Bmax ZFC C Borel Conjecture: Proof. By Theorem 7.44 it suffices to prove the following. Suppose h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i 2 Bmax and that
f0 W !1M0 ! .0;1/
is an injective function such that f0 2 M0 . Then there exists a condition h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i 2 Bmax such that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i and such that for some h 2 M1 , .h.j.f0 /; h/i; !1M1 / 2 Y1 ; where j is the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / such that j.a0 / D a1 . Fix f0 and h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i. Let z 2 R code M0 and let N be a transitive inner model of ZFC C CH such that Ord N , z 2 N and such that for some ı < !1 , N “ı is a Woodin cardinal”: We also require that !1 is strongly inaccessible in N . Since AD holds in L.R/, N exists by Theorem 5.34. By Lemma 7.40, there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that j 2 N and such that (1.1) .INS /N \ M0 D I0 , (1.2) j.Y / D .YBC .INS //N \ M0 . Let U 2 N be a selective ultrafilter on ! and let G0 .PU /N be N -generic. Let G1 .Coll.!1 ; <ı//N ŒG0 be N ŒG0 -generic. By Theorem 7.18, in N ŒG0 ŒG1 there exists a normal ideal I1 such that I1 \ N ŒG0 D .INS /N ŒG0 and such that N ŒG0 ŒG1
AC .I1 /:
Let < !1 be such that ı < and such that N ZFC. Finally let M1 D N ŒG0 ŒG1 ;
486
7 Conditional variations
let, Y1 D .YBC .I1 //N ŒG0 ŒG1 ; and let a1 D j.a0 /: We claim that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i 2 Bmax and is as desired. By Lemma 4.4 and Lemma 4.5, .M1 ; I1 / is iterable. By Lemma 7.50, .YBC .INS //N D .YBC .INS //N ŒG0 \ N; and for some n < !, N N ŒG0 .h.j.f0 /; h.n/ : G0 /i; !1 / 2 .YBC .INS //
Since .Coll.!1 ; <ı//N ŒG0 is !-closed in N ŒG0 , and since I1 \ N ŒG0 D .INS /N ŒG0 ; it follows that .YBC .INS //N ŒG0 D .YBC .I1 //N ŒG0 ŒG1 \ N ŒG0 : Thus and for some h 2 M1 ,
j.Y / D Y1 \ M0 .h.j.f0 /; h/i; !1M1 / 2 Y1 :
This verifies that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i has the desired properties.
t u
We shall use the following lemma to show that in L.R/Bmax , every set X R of cardinality !1 has Lebesgue measure 0. We thank A. Miller for revealing the lemma to us. Lemma 7.52. Suppose that U is a selective ultrafilter on ! and that G PU is V -generic. Then in V ŒG, V \R has Lebesgue measure 0. Proof. We work in V ŒG and prove that V \ 2! has Lebesgue measure 0. For each set a ! let fa W ! ! ¹0;1º
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
487
be the characteristic function of a. Trivially V \ 2! D ¹fa j a 2 P .!/ \ V º \ 2! : Let ! be the set given by the generic filter G, D [¹s j .s; / 2 Gº: For each n < ! let Xn D ¹fa j a ! and either n n a or a \ nº: Both and ! n are infinite and so for each n < !, Xn has Lebesgue measure 0. However by the genericity of G, for each a ! such that a 2 V , either a \ is finite or n a is finite. Therefore V \ 2! [¹Xn j n < !º and so V \ 2! has Lebesgue measure 0.
t u
Combining Theorem 7.44, Lemma 7.50, and Lemma 7.52 we obtain the following additional corollary. The proof is quite similar to that of Theorem 7.51. Theorem 7.53. Assume ADL.R/ . Then L.R/Bmax “Every set of reals of cardinality @1 has measure 0”:
t u
We define the sentence, ˆBC , relative to which the absoluteness theorem for L.R/Bmax holds. Definition 7.54. ˆBC : For all X !1 there is a transitive model M such that (1) M ZFC C CH, (2) X 2 M , (3) .YBC .INS //.M / D M \ YBC .INS /.
t u
Note that (3) is equivalent to the condition .YBC .INS //.M / ZBC .INS /: Theorem 7.55. Assume ADL.R/ . Then L.R/Bmax ˆBC : Proof. This is an immediate consequence of Theorem 7.44(1) and the definition of the t u order on Bmax . The absoluteness theorems for Bmax are analogous to those for Smax . We state one, leaving the proof as an exercise, noting that the main iteration lemmas for Bmax are an immediate consequence of ˆBC .
488
7 Conditional variations
Theorem 7.56. Assume ˆBC holds and that there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; YBC .INS /; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri: Suppose that hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; YBC .INS /; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then
Bmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS ; YBC .INS /; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/
:
t u
Assume ADL.R/ . Then L.R/Bmax satisfies a conditional form of Martin’s Maximum for posets of size !1 . Definition 7.57. that
(1) Let BCFA denote the forcing axiom: Suppose P is a poset such P
YBC .INS / D V \ .YBC .INS //V : Suppose D is a set of dense subsets of P and jDj !1 . Then there exists an D-generic filter F P , i. e. such that F \d ¤; for all d 2 D. (2) Let BCFACC denote the following variation of BCFA: Suppose P is a partial order which satisfies the requirements of BCFA and that 2 V P is a term for a subset of YBC .INS / of cardinality @1 . Suppose D is a set of dense subsets of P and jDj !1 . Then there is an D-generic filter G P which interprets as a subset of YBC .INS /. (3) BCFACC . / denotes the restriction of BCFACC to posets of size .
t u
BCFACC analogous to Martin’s MaximumCC . We note that the preservation condition, YBC .INS / D V \ .YBC .INS //V
P
is equivalent to the requirement, P
YBC .INS / .ZBC .INS //V : The following lemma is an immediate consequence of Lemma 7.50 and the definitions. Lemma 7.58. Assume BCFACC .c/. Then (1) the Borel Conjecture holds, (2) ˆBC holds. We let BC abbreviate Borel Conjecture.
t u
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
489
Theorem 7.59 shows that BCFACC .!1 / holds in L.R/Bmax . An amusing question is whether there are any partial orders in L.R/Bmax satisfying (in L.R/Bmax ) the preservation requirements of BCFA and of cardinality !1 . A natural conjecture is that there are none. It seems likely that in L.R/Bmax , any nontrivial partial order of cardinality !1 adds a Cohen real. Nevertheless the proof of Theorem 7.59 does generalize to prove a non-vacuous version of the theorem, cf. Theorem 9.42. The proof also quite easily adapts to prove, from suitable assumptions, that .c/ L.R/Bmax BCFACC ZF where BCFAZF .c/ is the version of BCFA.c/ analogous to Martin’s MaximumZF .c/, see Definition 2.51. Theorem 7.59. Assume ADL.R/ . Suppose G Bmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC C BC C BCFACC .!1 /: Proof. Suppose that P 2 L.R/ŒG is a partial order satisfying the requirements for BCFA.!1 /. We view P D .!1 ; P /. It suffices to prove the following: Suppose that !1 !1 defines a term for a subset of !1 which codes a subset of YBC .INS / as computed in L.R/ŒGP . For each ˛ < !1 let A˛ D ¹ˇ < !1 j .˛; ˇ/ 2 º: Suppose that !1 !1 is such that for each ˛ < !1 , D˛ is dense in P where D˛ D ¹ˇ < !1 j .˛; ˇ/ 2 º: Then there is a filter F in P such that for all ˛ < !1 , F \ D˛ ¤ ; and such that X codes a subset of YBC .INS / where X D ¹˛ 2 !1 j A˛ \ F ¤ ;º: By Theorem 7.44, there exists a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i 2 G such that where
¹P ; ; º 2 M0 j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
490
7 Conditional variations
is the iteration of .M0 ; I0 / given by G. Thus there exists P0 2 M0 such that j.P0 / D P and there exists . 0 ; 0 / 2 M0 such that j.. 0 ; 0 // D . ; /. By genericity we can suppose that for all h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i 2 Bmax such that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i; if I1 D .INS /M1 then: (1.1) j1 .P0 / satisfies in M1 the preservation requirements for BCFA and further that j1 .0 / is a term for a subset of !1M1 which codes a subset of YBC .INS / as computed in
M1j1 .P0 / ;
(1.2) for each ˛ < !1M1 ,
¹ˇ < !1M1 j .˛; ˇ/ 2 j1 . 0 /º
is dense in j1 .P0 /; where j1 is the (unique) iteration j1 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that j1 .a0 / D a1 . Fix h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i, P0 and . 0 ; 0 /. We work in L.R/. As in the proof of Theorem 7.51, let z 2 R code M0 and let N be a transitive inner model of ZFC C CH such that Ord N , z 2 N and such that for some ı < !1 , N “ı is a Woodin cardinal”: We also require that !1 is strongly inaccessible in N . Since AD holds in L.R/, N exists by Theorem 5.34. Let < !1 be such that ı < and such that N ZFC: By Lemma 7.40, there exists an iteration j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that j0 2 N and such that (2.1) .INS /N \ M0 D I0 , (2.2) j0 .Y / D .YBC .INS //N \ M0 . Thus j0 .P0 / is a partial order on !1N . We claim the following hold in N .
7.2 The Borel Conjecture
491
(3.1) j0 .P0 / satisfies the preservation requirements of BCFA. (3.2) j0 .0 / defines a term in V j0 .P0 / for a subset of !1 which codes a subset of YBC .INS / as computed in V j0 .P0 / . (3.3) For each ˛ < !1 , ¹ˇ < !1 j .˛; ˇ/ 2 j0 . 0 /º is dense in j0 .P0 /. To verify this claim let g .Coll.!1 ; <ı//N be N -generic. We can suppose g 2V. By Theorem 7.18 there exists I1 2 N Œg such that in N Œg, I1 is a normal saturated ideal on !1 , N D I1 \ N; INS and such that N Œg
AC .I1 /:
Let M1 D N Œg , a1 D j0 .a0 /, and let Y1 D .YBC .INS //N Œg : By Lemma 4.4 and Lemma 4.5, since I1 is a saturated ideal in N Œg, the structure .M1 ; I1 / is iterable. Thus h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i 2 Bmax and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i: If (3.1), (3.2) or (3.3) fail in N then they fail in M1 which is a contradiction. Finally let h1 j0 .P0 / be an N -generic filter. Let b !1N be the interpretation of j0 .0 / by h1 . By (3.1), .YBC .INS //N D N \ .YBC .INS //N Œh1 ; and by (3.2), b codes a subset of YBC .INS /N Œh1 . Let Yb be the set coded by b. Let g1 .Coll.!1 ; <ı//N Œh1 be N Œh1 -generic. Let M1 D N Œh1 Œg1 , I1 D .INS /N Œh1 Œg1 , a1 D j0 .a0 / and let Y1 D .YBC .INS //N Œh1 Œg1 : Arguing as above, .M1 ; I1 / is iterable.
492
7 Conditional variations
Thus h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i 2 Bmax : Clearly .YBC .INS //N Œh1 D N Œh1 \ .YBC .INS //N Œh1 Œg1 ; and so by (3.2) and the choice of j0 , j0 .Y0 / D M0 \ .YBC .INS //N Œh1 Œg1 : Thus Yb Y1 and h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 ; Y0 i: By genericity we can suppose that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 ; Y1 i 2 G: Let
k W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 /
be the iteration of .M1 ; I1 / given by G. It follows that in L.R/ŒG, k.h1 / P is a filter and that for each ˛ < !1 , k.h1 / \ ¹ˇ < !1 j .˛; ˇ/ 2 º ¤ ;: Further k.b/ is the interpretation of by k.h1 /, k.b/ codes k.Yb /, and k.Yb / k.Y1 /: However in L.R/ŒG,
k.Y1 / D YBC .INS / \ M1
and so in L.R/ŒG, k.b/ codes a subset of YBC .INS /.
t u
Chapter 8
| principles for !1 For our next example of a Pmax variation, we consider versions of the principle |. Our purpose, in part, is to illustrate degrees of freedom in the analysis of a Pmax variation which we have not yet had to exploit. We fix some notation. Suppose ˛ ˇ are ordinals. Then Œˇ˛ denotes the set of all subsets of ˇ of ordertype ˛ and Œˇ<˛ denotes the set of all subsets of ˇ of ordertype less than ˛. Definition 8.1 (Ostaszewski). |: There is a sequence h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i satisfying the following conditions. (1) For each limit ordinal 0 < ˛ < !1 , ˛ 2 Œ˛! and ˛ is cofinal in ˛. (2) For each cofinal set A !1 , the set ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ Aº is stationary.
t u
The principle | was introduced by Ostaszewski .1975/ as a weakening of ˘. Assuming CH it is equivalent to ˘ and it easily verified that | implies that the nonstationary ideal is not saturated. One natural question, which plausibly can be answered by the techniques of this section, is the following: Assume |. Can INS be semi-saturated? The underlying question is whether | can be obtained in a variation of a Pmax extension. We define two variations of |. Definition 8.2. |0NS : There is a sequence h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i satisfying the following conditions. (1) For each limit ordinal 0 < ˛ < !1 , ˛ 2 Œ˛! and ˛ is cofinal in ˛. (2) For each closed, cofinal set C !1 , the set ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ n C is finiteº contains a closed, cofinal subset of !1 .
t u
494
8 | principles for !1
The principle |0NS weakens | in that only closed, cofinal, subsets of !1 are guessed, and the anticipation is not as strong, being modulo a finite set. However this must happen on a closed unbounded subset of !1 rather than just on a stationary subset of !1 . This requires weakening how sets are guessed. The proof of the forthcoming Lemma 8.25 can easily be modified to prove the following lemma. Lemma 8.3. Suppose that h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence witnessing |0NS . Then there exists a co-stationary set S !1 such that ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ n S is finiteº t u
is stationary in !1 .
We strengthen |0NS by requiring in addition that every subset of !1 is measured by the tail filter associated to ˛ , on a closed unbounded set. Definition 8.4. |NS : There is a sequence h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i satisfying the following conditions. (1) For each limit ordinal 0 < ˛ < !1 , ˛ 2 Œ˛! and ˛ is cofinal in ˛. (2) For each closed, cofinal set C !1 , the set ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ n C is finiteº contains a closed, cofinal subset of !1 . (3) For each set A !1 , there is a closed, cofinal, set C !1 such that for each ˛ 2 C either ˛ n A is finite or A \ ˛ is finite. (4) For each set A !1 , there is a stationary set S !1 such that for each ˛ 2 S either ˛ A or A \ ˛ D ;:
t u
8 | principles for !1
495
It is easily checked that |NS holds in L, though unlike |, |NS is not implied by ˘. |NS seems more closely related to ˘C though we do not know if it is implied by ˘C . Building nontrivial models in which |0NS holds seems difficult using the standard methods of iterated forcing, see .Shelah 1998/ for related results and additional references. In particular a natural question is whether either |0NS or |NS implies that INS is not saturated. |NS and we shall prove that if We shall define a partial Pmax L.R/ AD |NS Pmax
|NS Pmax
then 2 L.R/, is L.R/-generic then
|
|
NS NS is !-closed and Pmax is homogeneous. Further if G Pmax
L.R/ŒG ZFC C |NS : We also shall prove that the nonstationary ideal is saturated in L.R/ŒG. Finally we C CC shall introduce two further refinements of |NS , |NS and |NS , and prove an absolute|
NS ness theorem for the Pmax -extension. The absoluteness theorem we prove is somewhat technical and very likely more elegant versions are possible. |NS -extension will require, as usual, proving several iteration The analysis of the Pmax lemmas. We shall prove these by working in L-like models, i. e. models in which very strong condensation principles hold. This degree of freedom has always been available but until now it has not been particularly useful. One purpose of this chapter is simply to illustrate this approach. There is another potential feature of the Pmax variations which is illustrated by the |NS |NS which we give. It is only after the initial analysis of Pmax that we analysis of Pmax |NS
|
NS are able to prove that INS is !2 -saturated in L.R/Pmax . More precisely if G Pmax is L.R/-generic then as a result of the initial analysis we obtain (assuming ADL.R/ );
L.R/ŒG ZFC, P .!1 /L.R/ŒG D P .!1 /G , where P .!1 /G is defined from the filter G in the usual fashion. |NS |NS , of Pmax , obtaining a new family We then extend this analysis to a variant, Umax of iterable structures, which are generated from countable elementary substructures of |NS is L.R/-generic and L .R/ŒG where G Umax L .R/ŒG ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement: |
NS By considering iterations of these structures we are then able to prove that if G Pmax L.R/ is L.R/-generic then (assuming AD )
L.R/ŒG “INS is !2 -saturated”: In our previous examples, the proof that INS is saturated in the resulting extension has always been possible as part of the initial analysis: the iteration lemmas needed for the initial analysis have always sufficed.
496
8 | principles for !1
8.1
Condensation Principles
We briefly discuss the condensation principle we shall use to prove the iteration lemmas |NS required for the analysis of the Pmax -extension. We begin with the definition of a generalized condensation axiom. Definition 8.5. Suppose that A ı and that F W ı
t u
Theorem 8.7. Suppose that A ı and that F W ı
t u
8.1 Condensation Principles
497
Corollary 8.8. Suppose that M is a transitive model of ZFC and that j WM !N is an elementary embedding of M into a transitive set N . Suppose that M Axiom of Condensation: Then M N .
t u
Corollary 8.9 (Axiom of Condensation). Suppose that j W V ! M V ŒG is a generic elementary embedding. Then V DM t u
and j is the identity. Theorem 8.10. Suppose that A ı and that condensation holds for A. (1) Suppose that B and that B 2 LŒA. Then condensation holds for B. (2) Suppose that P ./ LŒA: j j
Then 2
C
D jj .
t u
Corollary 8.11. Assume the Axiom of Condensation holds in V . Then GCH holds. u t D. Law has improved Corollary 8.11, proving that ˘ follows from the Axiom of Condensation, Law .1994/. The proof yields a different proof of Corollary 8.11; the original proof used Namba forcing. Theorem 8.12 (Law). Assume the Axiom of Condensation holds in V . Then ˘ holds. Proof. Suppose that j WM !N is an elementary embedding such that (1.1) M and N are transitive, (1.2) M ZC C †1 -Replacement, (1.3) N D ¹j.f /.!1M / j f 2 M º, (1.4) .H.!2 //M 2 N .
498
8 | principles for !1
Then M ˘: To see this fix f0 W !1M ! M such that f0 2 M and such that h.H.!2 //M ; <0 i D j.f0 /.!1M / where <0 is a wellordering of .H.!2 //M such that <0 2 N . Working in M , one can define, in the usual fashion using f0 , a ˘ sequence. Now fix 2 Ord such that V ZC C †1 -Replacement; and such that cof./ > !1 . Let X V be a countable elementary substructure. Fix ı < and A ı such that (2.1) ı 2 X , (2.2) A 2 X , (2.3) H.!2 / 2 Lı ŒA. By elementarity there exists a function W ı
8.1 Condensation Principles
499
Let .AX ; X ; ıX / be the image of .A; ; ı/ under the transitive collapse of X . The key point is that j.X / witnesses condensation in N for j.AX / and so by absoluteness, AX 2 N; since ¹j.˛/ j ˛ < ıX º is closed under j.X /. But this implies that .H.!2 //M 2 N since .H.!2 //M 2 LıX ŒAX . Thus .N; M; j / satisfies (1.1)–(1.4) and so M ˘ which implies that ˘ holds in V .
t u
Remark 8.13. The proof of Theorem 8.12 easily adapts to prove directly that the Axiom of Condensation implies that for any (uncountable) regular cardinal ı, ˘ holds at ı on any stationary subset of ı. It is open whether the Axiom of Condensation implies ˘C or whether it implies t u principles such as !1 . Natural models in which the Axiom of Condensation holds are provided by AD. Theorem 8.14. Assume AD holds in L.R/ and let M D H.!1 / \ .HODŒx/L.R/ where x 2 R. Then M ZFC C Axiom of Condensation:
t u
We shall need a strong form of condensation. This we now define. Definition 8.15. Suppose that M is a transitive set closed under the G¨odel operations and that F W Ord \ M ! M is a bijection. The function F witnesses strong condensation for M if for any X hM; F; 2i; FX D F j.Ord \ MX / where FX and MX are the images of F and M under the transitive collapse of X .
t u
We say that strong condensation holds for M if there exists a function F W Ord \ M ! M which witnesses strong condensation for M . The Axiom of Strong Condensation is the axiom which asserts that strong condensation holds for H. / for all uncountable .
500
8 | principles for !1
Remark 8.16. (1) The definition of strong condensation imposes some unnecessary requirements on M . A slightly more general definition could be given by specifying as a witness, a wellordering of M . (2) We shall essentially only be concerned with strong condensation for transitive sets of the form H.ı/ where ı is an uncountable cardinal (actually !3 in most cases). t u We note that in the definition of a witness for strong condensation it is necessary only to consider elementary substructures which lie in V as opposed to the case of witnesses for condensation where it is necessary to consider elementary substructures which are generic over V . This is verified in the following theorem. Theorem 8.17. Suppose that M is a transitive set closed under the G¨odel operations and that F W Ord \ M ! M is a bijection. Suppose that N is a transitive inner model such that (1) N ZC C †1 -Replacement, (2) ¹M; F º N , (3) F witnesses strong condensation for M in N . Then F witnesses strong condensation for M .
t u
As an immediate corollary of Theorem 8.6 and Theorem 8.17 one obtains; Corollary 8.18. Suppose that M is a transitive set closed under the G¨odel operations and that F W Ord \ M ! M is a bijection which witnesses strong condensation for M . Suppose that A Ord and that A 2 M . Then condensation holds for A. t u Suppose that strong condensation holds for H. / for some cardinal > !1 . Then ¹X j ordertype.X / D !1 º is not stationary in P . /. Therefore there are no Ramsey cardinals below . This is in contrast to condensation which can hold below the least measurable cardinal. Theorem 8.19. Assume AD holds in L.R/ and that x 2 R. Let N D HODL.R/ Œx: Suppose that is an uncountable cardinal of N which is below the least weakly comt u pact cardinal of N . Then strong condensation holds for .H. //N in N .
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
501
Remark 8.20. (1) Theorem 8.19 generalizes to other inner models of AD, satisfying “V D L.P .R//”, provided that a particular form of AD is assumed, see Theorem 9.9. (2) Suppose that the Axiom of Condensation holds. Does strong condensation hold for H.!2 /? (3) Suppose that A Ord and that for each uncountable cardinal of LŒA, strong condensation holds in LŒA for H. /LŒA . Suppose that A# exists. Then there exists ˛ < !1 and a set A ˛ such that LŒA D LŒA : (4) Does condensation or strong condensation capture the combinatorial essence of inner models like L? One test question is the following. Suppose that N is a transitive inner model of ZFC containing the ordinals such that for each uncountable cardinal of N , strong condensation holds in N for H. /N . Suppose that covering fails for N in V . Must there exist a real x such that N LŒx‹ Note that if N D LŒA for some A Ord, then by (3) and Jensen’s Covering Lemma, the answer is yes. t u
|
NS 8.2 Pmax |
NS We define Pmax as a variation of Pmax . For this definition and the subsequent analysis we shall use a generalization of the partial orders PU to the case where U is an ultrafilter on !1 , cf. the discussion preceding Lemma 7.47.
Definition 8.21. Suppose that U is an ultrafilter on !1 . PU is the set of pairs .s; f / such that s !1 is finite and such that f W Œ!1
t u
502
8 | principles for !1
Thus PU is a generalization of Prikry forcing to the case of ultrafilters on !1 . The standard properties of Prikry forcing, suitably rephrased, hold for PU . This is summarized in the following lemmas which generalize Lemma 7.47. Lemma 8.22 (Prikry property). Suppose that U is an ultrafilter on !1 . Suppose that .s; f / 2 PU and b 2 RO.PU /. Then there exists .s; f / 2 PU such that .s; f / b t u or such that .s; f / b 0 . Lemma 8.23 (Geometric Condition). Suppose that M is a transitive model of ZC, U 2 M and that M “U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 ”: M Suppose !1 is an infinite cofinal set of ordertype !. Suppose that for all f W Œ!1M
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
503
We note that by Theorem 6.28 it is possible for the following to hold. For each uniform ultrafilter U on !1 there exists a normal saturated ideal I on !1 such that RO.PU / Š P .!1 /=I: The most elegant method for achieving |0NS would be to obtain the following. For some ultrafilter U on !1 , U extends the club filter and RO.PU / Š P .!1 /=INS : Unfortunately this is not possible. Lemma 8.24. Suppose that I is a normal ideal on !1 , U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 and that RO.PU / Š P .!1 /=I: Then I \ U ¤ ;.
t u
A weaker requirement would be that for some ultrafilter U on !1 , U extends the club filter and RO.PU / Š B where B is an !2 -complete boolean subalgebra of P .!1 /=INS . Even this is not possible. Lemma 8.25. Suppose that I is a normal ideal on !1 , U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 and that RO.PU / Š B where B is an !2 -complete boolean subalgebra of P .!1 /=I . Then I \ U ¤ ;. Proof. Fix a function F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! such that F induces the given isomorphism RO.PU / Š B P .!1 /=I: We may suppose that for each limit ordinal ˛ < !1 , F .˛/ is cofinal in ˛. For each ordinal ˛, let F˛ P .˛/ be the tail filter given by F .˛/. Let M D L ŒF; U where is least such that !1 < and such that L ŒF; U ZC:
504
8 | principles for !1
Similarly for each ˛ < !1 let M˛ D L˛ ŒF j˛; F˛ where ˛ is least such that ˛ < ˛ and such that L˛ ŒF j˛; F˛ ZC: Clearly, for all ˛ < !1 , ˛ < !1 . Suppose that G .P .!1 / n I; / is V -generic. Then the generic ultraproduct Y hM˛ ; F˛ i=G Š hM; U i: Thus there exists a set A !1 such that !1 n A 2 I and such that for all ˛ 2 A, (1.1) ˛ < !1 , (1.2) ˛ D .!1 /M˛ . Therefore for any formula .x0 ; x1 /, M ŒF; U \ LŒF; U if and only if ¹˛ j M˛ ŒF j˛; U˛ º … I; where for each limit ordinal ˛ < !1 , U˛ D M˛ \ F˛ : Let F be the filter dual to I . Assume toward a contradiction that F U: Then for any formula .x0 ; x1 /, M ŒF; U \ LŒF; U if and only if ¹˛ j M˛ ŒF j˛; U˛ º 2 U: This contradicts Tarski’s theorem on the undefinability of truth.
t u
These lemmas however do not rule out the following. There is a set Y of triples .U; I; B/ such that (1) U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 which extends the club filter, (2) I is a normal uniform saturated ideal on !1 , (3) B is an !2 -complete boolean subalgebra of P .!1 /=I , (4) RO.PU / Š B,
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
505
and such that Y satisfies the condition, INS D \¹I j .U; I; B/ 2 Y º: If the isomorphisms witnessing (4) are induced by a single function F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! then this function yields a function witnessing |NS . |
NS This is how we shall obtain |NS in the Pmax -extension except the ultrafilters U will be generic over the model, see Theorem 8.84. In fact there will exist an .!1 ; 1/distributive partial order PF (defined from F ) for adding U such that
RO.PF PU / Š B P .!1 /=INS ; see Lemma 8.76 and Corollary 8.88. We continue to fix some notation. Definition 8.26. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! and that U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 . (1) For each function h W Œ!1
t u
506
8 | principles for !1
Suppose that F and U are as in Definition 8.26. In general IU;F is not a proper ideal. Suppose that IU;F is a proper ideal and that F P .!1 / n IU;F is a V -normal ultrafilter (occurring in a set generic extension of V ). Let .M; E/ D Ult.V; F / and let j W V ! .M; E/ be the corresponding elementary embedding. Since IU;F is a normal ideal, !2V OrdM ; i. e. !2V is contained in the wellfounded part of M . Thus j.F /.!1V / 2 Œ!1V ! : The key point is that by Lemma 8.23, it follows that j.F /.!1V / is V -generic for PU . Let GF denote the V -generic filter GF PU determined by
j.F /.!1V /.
Thus GF D ¹p 2 PU j Zp;F 2 F º:
This motivates the next definition. Definition 8.27. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! ; U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 , and that IU;F is a proper ideal. Let RU;F be the set of pairs .S; p/ such that (1) S !1 and S … IU;F , (2) p 2 PU , (3) if G PU is V -generic and p 2 G then there exists a V -normal ultrafilter F P .!1 / n IU;F such that S 2 F , such that F is set generic over V ŒG and such that G D GF :
t u
The following lemma is an immediate consequence of the definitions. Lemma 8.28. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! and U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 such that IU;F is a proper ideal. Suppose that F P .!1 / n IU;F is a V -normal ultrafilter which is set generic over V . Then for each S 2 F there exists p 2 GF such that V : .S; p/ 2 RU;F
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
507
Proof. Fix S 2 F . Since GF PU is V -generic, either there exists p 2 GF as desired or the following must hold, (1.1) if
FO P .!1 / n IU;F
is a V -normal ultrafilter, set generic over V , such that S 2 FO , then GFO ¤ GF : The relevant point is that (1.1) is a first order property of the pair .S; GF /. But F is a counterexample to this.
t u
The next lemma gives a simple characterization of RU;F . Lemma 8.29. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! and U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 such that IU;F is a proper ideal. Suppose that S 2 P .!1 / n IU;F and that p 2 PU . Then .S; p/ 2 RU;F if and only if for all q p,
Zq;F \ S … IU;F :
Proof. The lemma easily follows from the definitions and Lemma 8.23 which gives the geometric condition which characterizes when a cofinal ! sequence in !1V is V -generic for PU . If .S; p/ 2 RU;F then it is immediate that for all q p, Zq;F \ S … IU;F : Now suppose that .S; p/ … RU;F . Then by the definability of forcing, there must exist q0 p such that if G PU is a V -generic filter, with q0 2 G, then G ¤ GF for any V -normal ultrafilter, F , such that (1.1) F .P .!1 / n IU;F /V , (1.2) S 2 F , (1.3) F is set generic over V . It follows that in V , Zq0 ;F \ S 2 IU;F . |
t u
NS We define Pmax . The definition is closely related to that of Pmax which is given as Definition 5.41.
508
8 | principles for !1 |
NS Definition 8.30. Pmax is the set of pairs
.h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / such that hMk W k < !i is iterable and such that the following hold for all k < !. (1) Mk is a countable transitive model of ZFC. Mk
MkC1
(2) Mk 2 MkC1 ; !1
D !1
(3) [¹Mk j k 2 !º
AC .
.
(4) Strong condensation holds in Mk for Mk \ V where is the least inaccessible cardinal of Mk . (5) F 2 M0 and
F W !1M0 ! Œ!1M0 ! :
(6) For each (nonzero) limit ordinal ˛ < !1 , sup.F .˛// D ˛: (7) Yk 2 Mk and Mk
a) for each U 2 Yk , U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 b) for each U 2 Yk , .IU;F /
Mk
in Mk ,
is a proper ideal and
M .!1 k ; p/
2 .RU;F /Mk
where p D .1PU /Mk . (8) Yk D ¹U \ Mk j U 2 YkC1 º. (9) For each U 2 YkC1 , a) .IU;F /MkC1 \ Mk D .IW;F /Mk , b) .RU;F /MkC1 \ Mk D .RW;F /Mk , where W D U \ Mk . (10) \¹.IU;F /Mk j U 2 Yk º D Mk \ .INS /MkC1 . Mk
(11) Let Ik 2 Mk be the ideal on !1
which is dual to the filter,
Fk D \¹U j U 2 Yk º: Then
\¹.IU;F /Mk j U 2 Yk º Ik :
(12) hMk W k < !i is iterable.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
509
|
NS is defined as follows. A condition The ordering on Pmax O O .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; FO / < .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / if hMk W k < !i 2 MO 0 , hMk W k < !i is hereditarily countable in MO 0 and there exists an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i such that:
(1) j.F / D FO ; (2) hMk W k < !i 2 M0 and j 2 M0 ; (3) For all k < !,
j.Yk / D ¹U \ Mk j U 2 YO0 º
and
M
O
INS kC1 \ Mk D .INS /M1 \ Mk I (4) For each U 2 YO0 , O
a) .IU;FO /M0 \ Mk D .IW;FO /Mk , O
b) .RU;FO /M0 \ Mk D .RW;FO /Mk , where W D U \ Mk . Remark 8.31.
t u
(1) Suppose that |
NS .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / 2 Pmax :
Then for all k < !, .INS /MkC1 \ Mk D .[¹.INS /Mi j i < !º/ \ Mk : (2) An immediate consequence of condition (6) is that !1LŒF D !1M0 : Therefore if
|
NS .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / 2 Pmax
and if
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i
is a countable iteration, then j is uniquely determined by j.F /. This is by condition (3) and by Lemma 5.43. u t |
NS is suitably nontrivial assuming ADL.R/ by proving an We shall prove that Pmax iteration lemma for structures of the form .M; I/ where
I D .Q<ı /M for some ı 2 M which is a Woodin cardinal in M. For this we fix some additional notation.
510
8 | principles for !1
Suppose that I is a set of normal uniform ideals on !1 . Let aI be the set of countable elementary substructures X H.!2 / [ I such that for some J 2 I \ X , J \ X ¹A !1 j A 2 X and X \ !1 … Aº: Lemma 8.32. Suppose that I is a set of normal uniform ideals on !1 . Then the set aI is a stationary subset of P!1 .H.!2 / [ I/: Proof. Fix an ideal J 2 I. Since J is a uniform normal ideal it follows that ¹X 2 P!1 .H.!2 // j J \ X ¹A !1 j A 2 X and X \ !1 … Aºº is stationary in P!1 .H.!2 //. The lemma is an immediate consequence of this.
t u
We continue to fix some notation. Again suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! : Suppose that U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 and that IU;F is a proper ideal. Let aU;F be the set of X H.!2 / such that X is countable and such that for all A 2 IU;F \ X , X \ !1 … A. Thus aU;F D ¹X \ H.!2 / j X 2 a¹J º º where J D IU;F . Suppose that p 2 PU and that p D . ; h/. Let ap;U;F be the set of X 2 aU;F such that X \ !1 2 Zp;F . Suppose that Y is a set of uniform ultrafilters on !1 such that for each U 2 Y , the corresponding normal ideal IU;F is a proper ideal. Let I D ¹IU;F j U 2 Y º: Then aI is stationary. Suppose ı is a Woodin cardinal and that G Q<ı is a V -generic filter with aI 2 G. Let j W V ! M V ŒG be the induced generic elementary embedding. Since aI 2 G it follows that aU;F 2 G for some U 2 Y . We come to a key point. From the definition of the ideal IU;F and the geometric criterion for genericity given in Lemma 8.23, j.F /.!1V / is V -generic for PU (in the obvious sense). Let GU PU be the associated generic filter. Then GU D ¹p 2 PU j ap;U;F 2 Gº D ¹p 2 PU j Zp;F 2 Gº:
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
511
|
NS , are of The structures we shall iterate in order to establish the nontriviality of Pmax the form .M; I; a/ where for some ı 2 M, ı is a Woodin cardinal in M, where I is the directed system, .I<ı /M , of ideals associated to the stationary tower .Q<ı /M , and where a 2 .Q<ı /M :
The iterations will be restricted so that the generic filters contain the images of a. Definition 8.33. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC, ı 2 M and that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. Suppose that .M; I/ is iterable where I is the directed system of nonstationary ideals, .I<ı /M and suppose that a 2 .Q<ı /M . A sequence h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i is an iteration of .M; I; a/ if (1) h.Mˇ ; Iˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i is an iteration of .M; I/, (2) a0 D a, (3) for all ˇ , j0;ˇ .a/ D aˇ , (4) for all ˛ < , a˛ 2 G˛ .
t u
We define the collection of structures which are the subject of the first iteration lemma. Definition 8.34. M|NS is the set of triples h.M; I; a/; Y; F i such that the following hold. (1) M is a countable transitive model of ZFC. (2) Strong condensation holds in M for M where is the least inaccessible cardinal of M. (3) I 2 M and I D I<ı as computed in M for some ı 2 M such that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. (4) .M; I/ is iterable. (5) F 2 M and
F W !1M ! Œ!1M ! :
(6) For each (nonzero) limit ordinal ˛ < !1 , sup.F .˛// D ˛:
512
8 | principles for !1
(7) Y 2 M, Y ¤ ;, and for each U 2 Y , U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1M in M. (8) For each U 2 Y , .IU;F /M is a proper ideal and .!1M ; p/ 2 .RU;F /M where p D .1PU /M . (9) Let I 2 M be the ideal on !1M which is dual to the filter, F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then
\¹.IU;F /M j U 2 Y º I:
(10) a D .aI /M where
I D ¹.IU;F /M j U 2 Y º:
t u
We generalize Definition 8.27 to the stationary tower. Definition 8.35. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! ; U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 , and that IU;F is a proper ideal. Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal. .ı/ Let RU;F be the set of pairs .b; p/ such that (1) b 2 Q<ı j ap;U;F , (2) p 2 PU , (3) if G PU is V -generic and p 2 G then there exists a V -generic filter H Q<ı such that b 2 H and such that G D j.F /.!1V / where j W V ! M V ŒH is the generic elementary embedding given by H and G 2 Œ!1V ! is the cofinal t u subset of !1V given by G. The next two lemmas show that if .M; I/ is a countable structure which satisfies (1)–(4) of Definition 8.34, then there exists .a; Y; F / 2 M such that h.M; I; a/; Y; F i 2 M|NS : The proof of the first lemma is the prototype for the proofs of the subsequent iteration lemmas we shall need.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
513
Lemma 8.36. Suppose that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Then there is a function F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! such that for every uniform ultrafilter, U , on !1 , the normal ideal IU;F is proper and .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;F : Proof. Fix a function h W !3 ! H.!3 / which witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 /. For each ˛ < !3 let M˛ D ¹h.ˇ/ j ˇ < ˛º and let h˛ D hj˛: Let S be the set of ˛ < !3 such that (1.1) M˛ is transitive, (1.2) hˇ 2 M˛ for all ˇ < ˛, (1.3) hM˛ ; h˛ ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, (1.4) .!2 /M˛ exists and .!2 /M˛ 2 M˛ . The key point is that for many constructions one can use the sequence h.M˛ ; h˛ / W ˛ 2 S \ !1 i exactly as one uses the sequence h.L˛ ;
514
8 | principles for !1
it will follow that for each 2 S , F j.!1 /M 2 M : Suppose that ˇ < !1 and that F jˇ is defined. Let f D F jˇ: We may suppose that ˇ is a limit ordinal for otherwise we simply define F .ˇ/ D !: There are two cases. First suppose that for each 2 S , if ˇ D .!1 /M ; then f satisfies the requirements of the lemma within the model M . Then F .ˇ/ D h. / where is least such that h. / 2 Œˇ! and such that sup.h. // D ˇ: Now let 0 2 S be least such that ˇ D .!1 /M0 and such that f fails to satisfy the requirements of the lemma in M 0 . Let 0 be least such that h.0 / 2 M 0 witnesses that f fails to satisfy the lemma in M 0 . Let U D h.0 /. Thus in M 0 , U is an ultrafilter on !1 such that either (2.1) IU;f is not a proper ideal, or (2.2) .!1 ; 1PU / … RU;f . Let 0 < !1 be least such that h.0 / 2 Œˇ! and such that (3.1) h.0 / is M 0 -generic for .PU /M0 , (3.2) h.1 / 2 h.0 / where 1 is least such that h.1 / 2 .PU /M0 and such that .Zp;f /M0 2 .IU;f /M0 ;
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
515
where p D h.1 /. Note that by Lemma 8.29, 1 is defined if (2.2) holds. 1 is trivially defined if (2.1) holds. Define F .ˇ/ D h.0 /. This completes the definition of the function F . We verify that F has the desired properties. If this fails then there exist !1 < 0 < 0 < !2 such that (4.1) 0 2 S , (4.2) in M 0 , h.0 / is an ultrafilter on !1 such that either a) .IU;F /M0 is not a proper ideal in M 0 , or b) .!1 ; 1PU /M0 … .RU;F /M0 , where U D h.0 /. We suppose that .0 ; 0 / is as small as possible (with !1 < 0 ) and we set U D h.0 /. In either case, (4.1(a)) or (4.2(b)), there must exist p 2 .PU /M0 such that .Zp;F /M0 2 .IU;F /M0 I if (4.1(a)) holds this is trivial and if (4.2(b)) holds this follows by Lemma 8.29. Let 1 be least such that .Zp;F /M0 2 .IU;F /M0 ; where we set p D h.1 /. We first prove that .IU;F /M0 is a proper ideal in M 0 . The function h witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 / and so it follows from the definition of F that for each function e W Œ!1
!1 n Ze;F 2 INS :
Therefore .IU;F /M0 INS and so .IU;F /M0 is a proper ideal in M 0 . A similar argument shows that !1 n .Zp;F /M0 2 INS which contradicts .Zp;F /M0 2 .IU;F /M0 since .IU;F /M0 INS :
t u
516
8 | principles for !1
Lemma 8.37. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! is a function such that for every uniform ultrafilter, U , on !1 , the normal ideal IU;F is proper. Then there is a normal uniform ideal I on !1 such that I D \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º; where Y is the set of uniform ultrafilters on !1 which are disjoint from I .and so extend the filter dual to I /. Proof. Let ˇ!1 denote the set of all uniform ultrafilters on !1 . We define by induction on ˛ a normal ideal I˛ as follows: I0 D \¹IU;F j U 2 ˇ!1 º and for all ˛ > 0, I˛ D \¹IU;F j U 2 ˇ!1 and for all < ˛, I \ U D ;º: It follows easily by induction that if ˛1 < ˛2 then I˛1 I˛2 : Thus for each ˛, I˛ is unambiguously defined as the intersection of a nonempty set of uniform normal ideals on !1 . The sequence of ideals is necessarily eventually constant. Let ˛ be least such that I˛ D I˛C1 and let I D I˛ . Thus I is a uniform normal ideal on !1 such that I D \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º; where Y is the set of uniform ultrafilters on !1 which extend the filter dual to I .
t u
We note the following lemma which is an immediate corollary of Definition 8.35. Lemma 8.38. Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M|NS and that W 2 Y0 . Let ı0 2 M0 be the Woodin cardinal associated to I0 and let Q0 D .Q<ı0 /M0 : Suppose that 2 Œ!1M0 ! and that is M0 -generic for .PW /M0 . Let g .PW /M0 be the M0 -generic filter given by . Suppose that p 2 g and that .ı0 / M0 .p; b/ 2 .RW;F / : 0 Then there exists an M0 -generic filter G Q0 such that
(1) b 2 G, (2) D j.F0 /.!1M0 /, where j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / is the iteration of length 1 given by G. Suppose a P!1 .[a/
t u
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
517
and b P!1 .[b/: Let X D .[a/ [ .[b/: Then a and b are equivalent if there exists a set C P!1 .X /, closed and unbounded in P!1 .X /, such that for each Z 2 X , Z \ .[a/ 2 a if and only if Z \ .[b/ 2 b: Thus if a and b are stationary then a and b are equivalent if they define the same elements of RO.Q<˛ / where ˛ is any ordinal such that ¹a; bº V˛ : Remark 8.39. Suppose that a P!1 .[a/; and that [a has cardinality !1 . (1) Suppose that a is stationary. Then there is a stationary set S !1 such that S and a are equivalent. Further if T !1 is a stationary set which is equivalent to a then S M T 2 INS : (2) Suppose that a is nonstationary. Then a is equivalent to each set T !1 such t u that T 2 INS . Lemma 8.40. Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M|NS and that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Let ı0 2 M0 be the Woodin cardinal in M0 associated to I0 and let Q0 D .Q<ı0 /M0 be the associated stationary tower. Let J0 D \¹.IU;F /M0 j U 2 Y0 º and suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M0 i 2 M0 is such that ¹S˛ ; T˛ j ˛ < !1M0 º P .!1 /M0 n J0 : Then there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / of length !1 such that the following hold where F D j.F0 /.
8 | principles for !1
518
(1) For each uniform ultrafilter U on !1 if U \ M0 2 j.Y0 / then a) the ideal IU;F is proper, b) .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;F ,
c) suppose that p 2 .PW /M0 , and
.j.ı0 // M0 / ; .p; b/ 2 .RW;F
then b is stationary and .p; S / 2 RU;F M0
where W D equivalent to b.
\ U and where S !1 is a stationary set which is
(2) Suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1 i D j.h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M0 i/: Let h˛ W ˛ < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the ordinals 2 !1 n .M0 \ Ord/ such that is a cardinal in L.M0 /. Let C D ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ D ˛ º: Then for all ˛ 2 C and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛ 2 Sˇ if and only if
˛Cˇ 2 Tˇ :
Proof. The proof is quite similar to the proof of Lemma 8.36. Fix a function h W !3 ! H.!3 / which witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 /. For each < !3 let M D ¹h.ˇ/ j ˇ < º and let h D hj: Let S be the set of < !3 such that (1.1) M is transitive, (1.2) hˇ 2 M for all ˇ < , (1.3) hM ; h ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, M
(1.4) !2
M
exists and !2
(1.5) M0# 2 H.!1 /M .
2 M ,
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
519
Let FS 2 M0 be the function FS W !1M0 ! M0 defined by FS .˛/ D S˛ and let FT be the function FT W !1M0 ! M0 defined by FT .˛/ D T˛ . We define the iteration h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i of .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / by induction, defining hG˛ W ˛ < ˇi by induction on ˇ such that: (2.1) For all ˛ 2 C and for all ˇ < ˛, j0;˛Cˇ .FT /.ˇ/ 2 G˛Cˇ if and only if j0;˛ .FS /.ˇ/ 2 G˛ : The requirement (2.1) guarantees that condition (2) of the lemma will be satisfied. This requirement places no constraint on the choice of G˛ whenever ˛ 2 C and so this requirement places no constraint on the choice of G˛ whenever ˛ D .!1 /M for some 2 S. For each ˛ we let Q˛ D j0;˛ .Q0 /: The definition is uniform and so for each 2 S, M
h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 ij!1
2 M :
Suppose that hG˛ W ˛ < ˛0 i is given. Let h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ ˛0 i be the corresponding iteration. We first suppose that for all 2 S if ˛0 D .!1 /M ; then the iteration h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ ˛0 i satisfies the requirements of the lemma in M .
520
8 | principles for !1
Then G˛0 D h.0 / where 0 is least such that h.0 / Q˛0 ; a˛0 2 h.0 /, h.0 / is M˛0 -generic, and such the corresponding iteration h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ ˛0 C 1i satisfies (2.1). This defines G˛0 in this case (which we note includes the case that ˛0 ¤ .!1 /M for all 2 S). For the remaining cases let 0 2 S be least such that ˛0 D .!1 /M0 and such that the iteration h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ ˛0 i fails to satisfy the requirements of the lemma in M 0 . We shall extend the iteration defining G˛0 , attempting to eliminate the least counterexample. There are several cases depending on how the iteration h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ ˛0 i fails to satisfy the requirements of the lemma within M 0 . Let ı˛0 D j0;˛0 .ı0 /. Because the iteration satisfies (2.1) necessarily requirement (2) of the lemma is satisfied in M 0 . Therefore (1) must fail. Let 0 be least such that: (3.1) h.0 / 2 M 0 ; (3.2) M 0 “h.0 / is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 ”; (3.3) h.0 / \ M˛0 2 j0;˛0 .Y0 /; (3.4) Let U D h.0 /. Either a) .IU;F /M0 is not a proper ideal, or b) there exists .ı˛ /
.p; b/ 2 .RW;F0 /M˛0 such that .p; Sb / … .RU;F /M0 where Sb 2 .P .!1 //M0 , and in M 0 , b and Sb are equivalent, F D j0;˛0 .F0 /, W D h.0 / \ M˛0 .
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
521
Fix (as in (3.4)), U D h.0 / and, F D j0;˛0 .F0 /. Let W D U \ M˛0 . Suppose that (3.4(a)) holds. Then G˛0 D h.0 / where 0 is least such that h.0 / is an M˛0 -generic filter for Q˛0 , containing a˛0 and (4.1) j0;˛0 C1 .F0 /.˛0 / defines an M 0 -generic filter g .PU /M0 where for each ˛ ˛0 , j˛;˛0 C1 W .M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ / ! .M˛0 C1 ; I˛0 C1 ; a˛0 C1 / is the induced generic elementary embedding. Suppose that (3.4(a)) fails and that (3.4(b)) holds. Let 1 be least such that h.1 / D .p; b; Sb / where .p; b; Sb / witnesses that (3.4(b)) holds, and let 2 be least such that h.2 / D q where (5.1) q 2 .PU /M0 , (5.2) q p, (5.3) .Zq;F /M0 \ Sb 2 .IU;F /M0 . Define G˛0 D h.0 / where 0 is chosen to be least such that: (6.1) h.0 / satisfies (4.1), (6.2) b 2 h.0 /, (6.3) q belongs to the induced M 0 -generic filter for .PU /M0 . By Lemma 8.38, in each case 0 exists as desired. This completes the inductive definition of the iteration. It is easily verified that for each 2 S, M
h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 ij!1
2 M
We prove that this iteration satisfies the conditions of the lemma. Clearly this iteration satisfies (2) in the statement of lemma. We prove that (1) is also satisfied. If not let 0 2 S be least such that !1 D .!1 /
M 0
522
8 | principles for !1
and such that the iteration fails to satisfy the conditions of the lemma interpreted in M 0 . There are several cases to consider depending on how the iteration fails to satisfy the requirements of the lemma in M 0 . Let 0 be least such that (3.1)–(3.4) hold; i. e. 0 is least such that h.0 / 2 M 0 and witnesses that the iteration fails to satisfy the (1) of the lemma. Let U D h.0 /. Suppose X hH.!3 /; h; 2i is a countable elementary substructure containing M0 . The iteration is definable in the structure hH.!1 /; hj!1 ; 2i from M0 and so ¹0 ; 0 º 2 X . Let hMX ; hX ; 2i be the transitive collapse of X . Thus hX D hj!1MX D hj.X \ !1 / and MX \Ord 2 S. Let ˛0X D !1MX and let 0X be the image of 0 under the collapsing map. Let UX be the image of U under the collapsing map, thus hX .0X / D h.0X / D UX : X Let X 0 D MX \ Ord. Thus 0 2 S and
MX D M X : 0
Further for each 2 S \ X 0 if .!1 /M D .!1 /
M
X 0
then the iteration M
h.M˛ ; I˛ ; a˛ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 ij!1
2 M
satisfies the requirements of the lemma in M . Therefore G˛X is chosen using M X . Let X D F .˛0X /. Thus
0
0
X D j0;˛X C1 .F0 /.˛0X / 0
MX
and X is MX -generic for .PUX / . This must hold for every countable elementary substructure X hH.!3 /; h; 2i which contains M0 , thus .IU;F / M
M 0
INS :
Therefore .IU;F / 0 is necessarily a proper ideal in M 0 and so (3.4(b)) must hold. Let 1 be least such that h.1 / D .p; b; Sb / where .p; b; Sb / witnesses that (3.4(b)) holds, and let 2 be least such that h.2 / D q
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
523
where (7.1) q 2 .PU /M0 , (7.2) q p, (7.3) .Zq;F /M0 \ Sb 2 .IU;F /M0 . We obtain a contradiction by reflection. Again let X hH.!3 /; h; 2i be a countable elementary substructure and let hMX ; hX ; 2i be the transitive collapse of X . Let 0X be the image of 0 under the collapse. Thus h.0X / D hX .0X /: Let ˛0X D .!1 /MX D X \ !1 and let .UX ; qX ; bX ; qX SX / be the image of .U; p; b; q; Sb / under the collapsing map. Arguing as above, G˛X is chosen using MX and so 0
(8.1) bX 2 G˛X , 0
(8.2) F .˛0X / is MX -generic for .PUX /MX and qX belongs to the corresponding MX generic filter. Further j˛X ;!1 .bX / D b 0
since b 2 M!1 . Therefore b is closed and unbounded in P!1 .[b/. Similarly M !1 n .Zq;F / 0 2 INS and .Zq;F /
M 0
\ Sb 2 .IU;F /
M 0
:
Finally as above, .IU;F /
M
INS :
0
The key point is that b and Sb are equivalent in V since .b; Sb / 2 H.!2 /
M 0
and since R M 0 . This implies that .Zq;F /
M 0
\ Sb
contains a closed unbounded set, which is a contradiction.
t u
As an immediate corollary we obtain the iteration lemma for structures in M|NS .
524
8 | principles for !1
Lemma 8.41. Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M|NS and that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Let ı0 2 M0 be the Woodin cardinal in M0 associated to I0 and let Q0 D .Q<ı0 /M0 be the associated stationary tower. Let J0 D \¹.IU;F /M0 j U 2 Y0 º and suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M0 i 2 M0 is such that ¹S˛ ; T˛ j ˛ < !1M0 º P .!1 /M0 n J0 : Then there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / of length !1 and a set Y ¹U P .!1 / j U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 º such that the following hold where F D j0 .F0 /. (1) For each U 2 Y , U \ M0 2 j.Y0 /. (2) For each U 2 Y , the ideal IU;F is proper and .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;F .
(3) Suppose that U 2 Y , p 2 .PW /M0 , and
.j.ı0 // M0 .p; b/ 2 .RW;F / ;
where W D M0 \ U . Then a) b is stationary, b) .p; S / 2 RU;F where S !1 is a stationary set which is equivalent to b. (4) Let I be the ideal on !1 which is dual to the filter, F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º I: (5) Suppose that U0 is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 such that U0 \ M0 2 j.Y0 /: a) There exists U1 2 Y such that U0 \ M0 D U1 \ M0 : b) Suppose that, in addition, \¹U j U 2 Y º U0 : Then U0 2 Y .
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
525
(6) Suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1 i D j.h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M0 i/: Let h˛ W ˛ < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the ordinals 2 !1 n .M0 \ Ord/ such that is a cardinal in L.M0 /. Let C D ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ D ˛ º: Then for all ˛ 2 C and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛ 2 Sˇ if and only if
˛Cˇ 2 Tˇ :
Proof. Note that (3) implies (2). Let j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / be an iteration of length !1 such that the following hold where F D j.F0 /. (1.1) for each uniform ultrafilter U on !1 if U \ M0 2 j.Y0 / then the ideal IU;F is proper,
suppose that p 2 .PW /M0 , and
b 2 j.Q0 /j.ap;W;F /M0 ; where W D M0 \ U , then – b is stationary, – .p; S / 2 RU;F where S !1 is a stationary set which is equivalent to b. (1.2) Suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1 i D j.h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M0 i/: Then for all ˛ 2 C and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛ 2 Sˇ if and only if
˛Cˇ 2 Tˇ :
The iteration exists by Lemma 8.40. Using the function F the remainder of the proof is essentially identical to that of Lemma 8.37. Let Z be the set of uniform ultrafilters U on !1 such that U \ M0 2 j.Y0 /:
8 | principles for !1
526
We define by induction on ˛ a normal ideal J˛ as follows: J0 D \¹IU;F j U 2 Zº and for all ˛ > 0, J˛ D \¹IU;F j U 2 Z and for all < ˛, J \ U D ;º: It follows easily by induction that if ˛1 < ˛2 then J˛1 J˛2 : Thus for each ˛, J˛ is unambiguously defined as the intersection of a nonempty set of uniform normal ideals on !1 . The sequence of ideals is necessarily eventually constant. Let ˛ be least such that J˛ D J˛C1 and let J D J˛ : Thus J is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . Let Y be the set of U 2 Z such that U \ J D ; and let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º: Then \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º I; t u
and therefore the iteration is as required. |
NS As a corollary to Lemma 8.41, if AD holds in L.R/ then Pmax is suitably nontrivial. For this we require the following refinement of Theorem 5.36.
Theorem 8.42. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Suppose A R and A 2 L.R/. Then there exist a countable transitive model M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that the following hold. (1) M ZFC. (2) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . (3) A \ M 2 M and hV!C1 \ M; A \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i. (4) A \ M is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M . (5) Suppose is the least inaccessible cardinal of M . Then strong condensation holds for M in M . Proof. We sketch the proof which is in essence identical to the proof of Theorem 5.36. We work in L.R/. If the theorem fails then there is a counterexample A R such that A is 21 . Following the proof of Theorem 5.36 there exists a transitive inner model of ZFC such that the following hold.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
527
(1.1) HOD N . (1.2) There exist two Woodin cardinals in N below !1V . (1.3) Let be the least inaccessible cardinal of N . Then P . / \ N D P . / \ HOD: We briefly indicate how to obtain N . For each pair .x; y/ of reals with x 2 HODŒy let Nx be the inner model, 0 Œx HODLŒZ Z0 and let Nx;y be the inner model x Œy HODN : Nx
where Z0 Ord such that
HOD D LŒZ0 :
By the arguments given in the proof of Theorem 5.36, there exists x0 2 R such that for all x 2 R if x0 2 HODŒx then there exists y0 2 R such that for all y 2 R if y0 2 HODŒy then the inner model Nx;y satisfies (1.1)–(1.3). Let ı0 be the least Woodin cardinal of N and let ı1 be the next Woodin cardinal of N . The set A is 21 and so there exist trees S .! ı21 /
t u
In fact the next theorem shows that must less determinacy is required to obtain the |NS nontriviality of M|NS from which the nontriviality of Pmax follows. The first theorem is in essence a “lightface” version of Theorem 8.19.
8 | principles for !1
528
Theorem 8.43. Suppose that x 2 R, y 2 R, x 2 LŒy, and that LŒy 12 .x/-Determinacy: Then: (1) !2LŒy is a Woodin cardinal in HODLŒy . x (2) Let be the least inaccessible cardinal of HODLŒy . Then strong condensation x LŒy LŒy holds for .HODx / in HODx . t u Remark 8.44. The hypothesis For each x 2 R there exists h.M; I; a/; Y; F i 2 M|NS with x 2 M, t u
1 is equivalent to 2 -Determinacy.
From Theorem 8.43 one obtains a little more than just that for every x 2 R there exists h.M; I; a/; Y; F i 2 M|NS with x 2 M. One can require for example that modest large cardinals exist in M, above the Woodin cardinal of M associated to I. 1 Theorem 8.45 ( 2 -Determinacy). For each x 2 R there exists
.M; I; ı/ 2 H.!1 / such that (1) x 2 M, (2) M is transitive and M ZFC C “ı is a Woodin cardinal”, (3) I D .I<ı /M , (4) .M; I/ is iterable, (5) M L.M/, (6) strong condensation holds in M for M where is the least inaccessible cardinal of M. t u As a corollary to the previous lemmas we obtain the following lemma, which is a variation of Lemma 5.23.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
529
Lemma 8.46. Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M|NS and that for some , X0 V is a countable elementary substructure such that M0 D MX0 where MX0 is the transitive collapse of X0 . Then there exists |NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
such that (1) there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / such that j.F0 / D FO and such that .M0 ; j.Y0 // D .MO 0 ; YO0 /; (2) hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable for each set A 2 X0 such that every set of reals which is projective in A is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Proof. Let ı 2 X0 be the Woodin cardinal whose image under the transitive collapse of X0 is the Woodin cardinal in M0 associated to I0 . We define by induction on k a sequence hh.Mk ; Ik ; ak /; Yk ; Fk i W k < !i |NS
of elements of M
together with iterations jk W .Mk ; Ik ; ak / ! .Mk ; Ik ; ak /
and elements .Fk.S/ ; Fk.T / / 2 Mk as follows. We simultaneously define an increasing sequence hXk W k < !i of countable elementary substructures of V such that for each k < !, Mk is the transitive collapse of Xk . h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i and X0 are as given. Suppose that Xk and h.Mk ; Ik ; ak /; Yk ; Fk i have been defined. We define h.MkC1 ; IkC1 ; akC1 /; YkC1 ; FkC1 i .Fk.S/ ; Fk.T / /, jk , and XkC1 . Let ık 2 Mk be the Woodin
cardinal of Mk corresponding to Ik and let Qk D .Q<ık /Mk ;
be the associated stationary tower. Let hk˛ W ˛ < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the ordinals 2 !1 n Mk such that is a cardinal in L.Mk /. Let Ck D ¹˛ j k˛ D ˛º and let
Jk D \¹.IU;F /Mk j U 2 Yk º:
530
8 | principles for !1
Choose .Fk.S/ ; Fk.T / / 2 Mk such that (1.1) Fk.S/ W .!1 /Mk ! P .!1 /Mk n Jk , (1.2) Fk.T / W .!1 /Mk ! P .!1 /Mk n Jk . By Lemma 8.41 there is an iteration jk W .Mk ; Ik ; ak / ! .Mk ; Ik ; ak / of length !1 and a set Y ¹U P .!1 / j U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 º such that the following hold where F D jk .Fk /. (2.1) For each U 2 Y , U \ Mk 2 jk .Yk /. (2.2) For each U 2 Y , a) the ideal IU;F is proper, b) .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;F ,
c) suppose that p 2 .PW /Mk , and .jk .ık // Mk ; .p; b/ 2 RW;F where W D Mk \ U , then b is stationary, .p; S / 2 RU;F where S !1 is a stationary set which is equivalent to b. (2.3) jk .Yk / D ¹U \ Mk j U 2 Y º. (2.4) Let I be the ideal on !1 which is dual to the filter, F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º I: (2.5) For all ˛ 2 Ck and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛Cˇ 2 .jk /0;˛CˇC1 .Fk.T / /.ˇ/ if and only if ˛ 2 .jk /0;˛C1 .Fk.S/ /.ˇ/:
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
Let a D aI where
531
I D ¹IU;F j U 2 Y º:
Choose a countable elementary substructure XkC1 V such that .Xk ; jk ; Y / 2 XkC1 : Let MkC1 be the transitive collapse of XkC1 and let .IkC1 ; akC1 ; YkC1 ; FkC1 / be the image of .I; a; Y; jk .Fk // under the collapsing map. Thus h.MkC1 ; IkC1 ; akC1 /; YkC1 ; FkC1 i 2 M|NS : This completes the definition of (3.1) hh.Mk ; Ik ; ak /; Yk ; Fk i W k < !i, (3.2) h.Fk.S/ ; Fk.T / / W k < !i, (3.3) hjk W k < !i, (3.4) hXk W k < !i, except that we require that ¹.jk .Fk.S/ /; jk .Fk.T / // j k < !º is equal to the set of all possible pairs of functions from the set, [ M M ¹¹jk .f / j f W !1 k ! P .!1 k / \ Mk n Jk and f 2 Mk º j k < !º which is easily achieved. Let X D [¹Xk j k < !º and for each k < ! let .MO k ; YOk / be the image of .Mk ; jk .Yk // under the transitive collapse of X . Let FO D [¹Fk j k < !º: We claim that
|NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
and is as desired. The verification is straightforward. The sequence hMO k W k < !i satisfies the hypothesis of Lemma 4.17 and so by Lemma 4.17 it is iterable, cf. the proof of Lemma 5.32. |NS The remaining conditions of the definition of Pmax , Definition 8.30, are an immediate consequence of the definition of .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO /. The key requirement that for each U 2 YOkC1 , O O .RW;FO /Mk D .RU;FO /MkC1 \ MO k
is guaranteed by (2.2(c)).
t u
532
8 | principles for !1
As an immediate corollary of Lemma 8.46 and Theorem 8.42 we obtain the req|NS . The statement of this uisite theorem regarding the existence of conditions in Pmax . The reason is that we have not theorem is weaker than that of its counterpart for Pmax |
NS yet established the iteration lemmas for Pmax and so we cannot conclude that the set |NS . of conditions indicated in Theorem 8.47 is dense in Pmax
Theorem 8.47. Assume AD holds in L.R/. Then for each set A R with A 2 L.R/; there is a condition |NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax such that (1) A \ MO 0 2 MO 0 , O
(2) hH.!1 /M0 ; A \ MO 0 i hH.!1 /; Ai, (3) hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable. Proof. Fix A and let B be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i: Thus B 2 L.R/. By Theorem 8.42, there exist a countable transitive model M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that the following hold. (1.1) M ZFC. (1.2) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . (1.3) B \ M 2 M and
hV!C1 \ M; B \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i:
C
(1.4) B \ M is ı -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M . (1.5) Suppose is the least inaccessible cardinal of M . Then strong condensation holds for M in M . Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal of M above ı. By .1:3/, B \ M is 1 not † 1 in M and so by (1.4), exists. Let X0 M be an elementary substructure structure such that X0 2 M , B \ M 2 X0 , and such that X0 is countable in M . Let M0 be the transitive collapse of X0 . By Lemma 8.36 and Lemma 8.37, there exists .a0 ; Y0 ; F0 / 2 M0 such that h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 .M|NS /M : By Lemma 8.46 there exists |NS M / .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 .Pmax such that in M ,
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
533
(2.1) there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / such that j.F0 / D FO and such that .M0 ; j.Y0 // D .MO 0 ; YO0 /; (2.2) hMO k W k < !i is B \ M -iterable. By (1.3), (1.4) and (2.1), hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 \ M; A \ M; 2i: Therefore since hV!C1 \ M; B \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i: it follows that (3.1) hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i, |NS , (3.2) .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
(3.3) hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable.
t u |
NS The next iteration lemma we shall prove concerns conditions in Pmax . This involves iterating sequences of models. We shall need the following lemma.
Lemma 8.48. Suppose that |
NS : .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / 2 Pmax
Suppose that hUk W k < !i is a sequence such that for each k < !, (1) Uk 2 Yk , (2) Uk UkC1 . Suppose that
2 Œ!1M0 !
and that for each k < !, is Mk -generic for .PUk /Mk . Then there exists an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i of length 1 such that
Proof. For each k < ! let
D j.F /.!1M0 /: Gk .PUk /Mk
be the Mk -generic filter corresponding to . The key point is the following. Fix k < !.
534
8 | principles for !1
Suppose that
.S0 ; p0 / 2 .RUk ;F /Mk
and that p0 2 Gk . Suppose that f W !1M0 ! !1M0 is a function such that f 2 Mk and such that f .˛/ < 1 C ˛ for all ˛ <
!1M0 .
Then there exist p1 2 Gk and ˛ < !1M0 such that .S1 ; p1 / 2 .RUk ;F /Mk ;
where S1 D f 1 .˛/. Otherwise there must exist q0 2 Gk such that q0 < p0 and q0 M forces that this fails; i. e. for all ˛ < !1 k , .f 1 .˛/; q1 / … .RUk ;F /Mk for any q1 q0 . However q0 < p0 and so .S0 ; q0 / 2 .RUk ;F /Mk : This is a contradiction; let U be a Mk -normal ultrafilter such that U .P .!1 / n RUk ;Fk /Mk and such that q0 2 gU where
gU .PUk /Mk
is the associated Mk -generic filter. Since .S0 ; q0 / 2 .RUk ;F /Mk ; we can choose U such that S0 2 U , and since U is Mk -normal there must exist ˛0 < .!1 /Mk such that f 1 .˛0 / 2 U . By Lemma 8.28, there must exist q 2 gU such that q < q0 and such that .f 1 .˛0 /; q/ 2 .RUk ;F /Mk ; which contradicts the choice of q0 . Let hfk W k < !i enumerate all functions f W !1M0 ! !1M0 such that f 2 [¹Mk j k < !º and such that f .˛/ < 1 C ˛ for all ˛ < !1M0 . We also assume that for all k < !, fk 2 Mk . Define by induction on k a sequence h.Sk ; pk / W k < !i such that for all k < !, (1.1) .Sk ; pk / 2 .RUk ;F /Mk , (1.2) fk jSk is constant, (1.3) pk 2 Gk , (1.4) SkC1 Sk . By the remarks above this sequence is easily defined.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
535
For each k < ! let Fk D ¹S !1M0 j S 2 Mk and Si S for some iº: Thus Fk is an Mk -normal ultrafilter. The sequence hFk W k < !i defines an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i of length 1 such that
D j.F /.!1M0 /:
t u
As an easy corollary to Lemma 8.48 and to the proof of Lemma 8.40 we obtain the generalization of Lemma 8.40 to sequences of structures. We leave the details to the reader. Lemma 8.49. Suppose that strong condensation holds for H.!3 / and that |
NS : .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / 2 Pmax
Then there is an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i of length !1 such that for each uniform ultrafilter U on !1 if U \ Mk 2 j.Yk / for each k < !, then: (1) the ideal IU;j.F / is proper; (2) .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;j.F / ; (3) for each k < !,
a) IU;j.F / \ Mk D .IW;j.F / /Mk ,
b) RU;j.F / \ Mk D .RW;j.F / /Mk , where W D U \ Mk .
t u |
NS , The next lemma when combined with Lemma 8.49 yields the !-closure of Pmax |NS with the appropriate assumptions on the nontriviality of Pmax .
Lemma 8.50. Suppose that |
NS .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / 2 Pmax
and that
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i
is an iteration of length !1 such that for each uniform ultrafilter U on !1 if U \ Mk 2 j.Yk /
536
8 | principles for !1
for each k < !, then (i) the ideal IU;j.F / is proper, (ii) .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;j.F / , (iii) for each k < !,
IU;j.F / \ Mk D .IW;j.F / /Mk and
RU;j.F / \ Mk D .RW;j.F / /Mk ;
where W D U \ Mk . Then there exists a set Y of uniform ultrafilters on !1 such that (1) for any sequence hUk W k < !i such that for all k < !, Uk 2 j.Yk / and Uk UkC1 , there exists U 2 Y such that U \ Mk D Uk for all k < !, (2) let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;j.F / j U 2 Y º I; (3) if U0 is an ultrafilter on !1 such that \¹U j U 2 Y º U0 ; and such that for all k < !, U0 \ Mk 2 j.Yk /; then U0 2 Y . Proof. Using the function j.F / the proof is essentially identical to that of Lemma 8.37. Let Z be the set of uniform ultrafilters U on !1 such that for all k < !, U \ Mk 2 j.Yk /: We define by induction on ˛ a normal ideal J˛ as follows: J0 D \¹IU;j.F / j U 2 Zº and for all ˛ > 0, J˛ D \¹IU;j.F / j U 2 Z and for all < ˛, J \ U D ;º: It follows easily by induction that if ˛1 < ˛2 then J˛1 J˛2 :
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
537
Thus for each ˛, J˛ is unambiguously defined as the intersection of a nonempty set of uniform normal ideals on !1 . The sequence of ideals is necessarily eventually constant. Let ˛ be least such that J˛ D J˛C1 and let J D J˛ : Thus J is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . Let Y be the set of U 2 Z such that U \ J D ; and let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º: Thus \¹IU;j.F / j U 2 Y º I; and so Y satisfies the second requirement. The third requirement is an immediate consequence of the definition of Y . Finally it follows by induction that for each ˛, the ideal J˛ has the property: (1.1) For any sequence hUk W k < !i such that for all k < !, Uk 2 j.Yk / and Uk UkC1 , there exists U 2 Z such that U \ J˛ D ;; and such that U \ Mk D Uk for all k < !. t u
Therefore the set Y satisfies the first requirement. |
NS We introduce the following notation for the constituents of a condition p 2 Pmax : p D .h.M.p;k/ ; Y.p;k/ / W k < !i; F.p/ /:
|
|
NS NS 1 Corollary 8.51 ( 2 -Determinacy). For each p0 2 Pmax there exists p1 2 Pmax such that p1 < p0 and such that for each sequence hWk W k < !i 2 M.p1 ;0/ ; if 2 j.Y.p0 ;k/ / Wk \ M.p 0 ;k/
for all k < !, then there exists U 2 Y.p1 ;0/ such that for all k < !, I Wk D U \ M.p 0 ;k/ where W k < !i j W hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p 0 ;k/ is the .unique/ iteration such that j.F.p0 / / D F.p1 / . Proof. Let x 2 R code p0 and let .M; I; ı; / 2 H.!1 /
538
8 | principles for !1
be such that (1.1) x 2 M, (1.2) M is transitive and M ZFC C “ı is a Woodin cardinal”, (1.3) I D .I<ı /M , (1.4) .M; I/ is iterable, (1.5) ı < and M M, (1.6) strong condensation holds in M for M where is the least inaccessible cardinal of M. The existence of .M; I; ı; / follows from 12 -Determinacy, by Theorem 8.45. |
NS M Thus p0 2 .Pmax / and so by Lemma 8.49, there exists an iteration j0 W hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i ! hj0 .M.p0 ;k/ / W k < !i with j0 2 M and such that the following hold in M.
(2.1) j0 has length !1 . (2.2) For each uniform ultrafilter U on !1 if U \ j0 .M.p0 ;k/ / 2 j0 .Y.p0 ;k/ / for each k < !, then: the ideal IU;j0 .F.p0 / / is proper; .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;j0 .F.p0 / / ; for each k < !,
j .M / – IU;j0 .F.p0 / / \ j0 .M.p0 ;k/ / D IW;j0 .F.p0 / / 0 .p0 ;k/ , j .M / – RU;j0 .F.p0 / / \ j0 .M.p0 ;k/ / D RW;j0 .F.p0 / / 0 .p0 ;k/ ,
where W D U \ j0 .M.p0 ;k/ /. By Lemma 8.50, there exists Y 2 M such that in M, Y is a set of uniform ultrafilters on !1 and (in M), (3.1) for any sequence hUk W k < !i such that for all k < !, Uk 2 j0 .Y.p0 ;k/ / and Uk UkC1 , there exists U 2 Y such that U \ j0 .M.p0 ;k/ / D Uk for all k < !, (3.2) let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;j0 .F.p0 / / j U 2 Y º I;
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
539
(3.3) if U0 is an ultrafilter on !1 such that \¹U j U 2 Y º U0 ; and such that for all k < !, U0 \ j0 .M.p0 ;k/ / 2 j0 .Y.p0 ;k/ /; then U0 2 Y . Thus there exists a 2 M such that h.M; I; a/; Y; j0 .F.p0 / /i 2 M|NS : Let X0 M be an elementary substructure such that (4.1) X0 2 M, (4.2) jX0 jM D !, (4.3) ¹ı; p0 ; a; Y; j0 º 2 X0 , let M0 be the transitive collapse of X0 and let ¹I0 ; a0 ; Y0 ; F0 º be the image of ¹I; a; Y; j0 .F.p0 / /º under the collapsing map. Thus h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 .M|NS /M Thus by Lemma 8.46, there exists |NS M .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 .Pmax /
such that in M there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / satisfying (5.1) j.F0 / D FO , (5.2) .M0 ; j.Y0 // D .MO 0 ; YO0 /. Let
p1 D .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO /: |
|
NS M NS Thus, since p1 2 .Pmax / , p1 2 Pmax . By the properties of j0 and by (5.1) and (5.2),
p1 < p0 and satisfies the requirements of the lemma.
t u
540
8 | principles for !1
1 Corollary 8.52 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that hpk W k < !i is a sequence of ele|
NS ments of Pmax such that for all k < !,
pkC1 < pk : Then there exists p 2
|NS Pmax
such that for all k < !, p < pk :
Proof. For each k < ! let .h.Mik ; Yik / W i < !i; Fk / D pk : Let F D [¹Fk j k < !º and for each k < ! let jk W hMik W i < !i ! hMO ik W i < !i be the iteration such that jk .Fk / D F: By Lemma 5.43, since [¹Mik j i 2 !º
AC ;
the iteration jk is unique. Let q D .h.MO kk ; jk .Ykk // W k < !i; F /: It follows from the definitions that if hMO kk W k < !i |
NS is iterable then q 2 Pmax . k O The sequence hMk W k < !i satisfies the hypothesis of Lemma 4.17 and so it is iterable, cf. the proof of Lemma 5.32. |NS such that p < q. It follows that By Corollary 8.51 there exists p 2 Pmax
p < pk for each k < !.
t u
For each of the previously considered Pmax variations the proof that !1 -DC holds in the extension has been a routine adaptation of the proof for the Pmax -extension using |NS this is Lemma 8.49 the appropriate analogs of Lemma 4.36 and Lemma 4.37; for Pmax |NS combined with Lemma 8.50. The situation for the Pmax -extension is different. Our third iteration lemma establishes what is required to prove that !1 -DC holds in the |NS -extension. Pmax |NS It is convenient to adapt Definition 4.44 to Pmax .
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
541
|
NS is semi-generic if for all ˛ < !1 there exists a Definition 8.53. A filter G Pmax condition p2G
such that ˛ < .!1 /M.p;0/ . |NS is semi-generic. Define FG by Suppose G Pmax FG D [¹F.p/ j p 2 Gº For each p 2 G let W k < !i jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ is the (unique) iteration such that j.F.p/ / D FG . Let (1) P .!1 /G D [¹P .!1 / \ M.p;0/ j p 2 Gº,
(2) IG D [¹M.p;0/ \ .INS /M.p;1/ j p 2 Gº,
(3) YG be the set of uniform ultrafilters on !1 such that 2 jp;G .Y0 / U \ M.p;0/ for all p 2 G.
t u
We note that in Definition 8.53, if P .!1 /G D P .!1 / |
NS -extension) then the definition of YG is the natural choice. (which will hold in the Pmax |NS We caution though that for an arbitrary semi-generic filter G Pmax , the set YG is in most cases empty. For example, we shall see that if ADL.R/ holds and
|
NS G Pmax is L.R/-generic then in L.R/ŒG the set YG is empty. The possibility that YG D ;
|
NS -extension is not simply a routine is one reason that the proof of !1 -DC in the Pmax application of our current iteration lemmas. For the proof of Lemma 8.55 it is useful to make the following definition.
Definition 8.54. Suppose that hpk W k < !i is a sequence of conditions in
|NS Pmax
such that for all k < !, pkC1 < pk . Let FO D [¹F.pk / j k < !º
and for each k < !, let W i < !i jk W hM.pk ;i/ W i < !i ! hM.p k ;i/ be the (unique) iteration such that jk .F.p / / D FO . Then k
; jk .Y.pk ;k/ // W i < !i; FO / .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / D .h.M.p k ;k/ is the condition associated to the sequence hpk W k < !i.
t u
542
8 | principles for !1
Thus the condition associated to the sequence hpk W k < !i is precisely the condi|NS is !-closed. tion constructed in the proof of Corollary 8.52; i. e. that Pmax 1 Lemma 8.55 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that
hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i |
|
NS NS is a sequence of dense subsets of Pmax and that q0 2 Pmax . Suppose that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Then there is a semi-generic filter
|
NS G Pmax
such that the following hold where for each p 2 G, jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i
is the iteration given by G. (1) q0 2 G. (2) For each ˛ < !1 ,
G \ D˛ ¤ ;:
(3) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 G !. For each W 2 jp;G .Y.p;k/ /, there exists U 2 YG such that D W: U \ M.p;k/ (4) For each U 2 YG , the normal ideal IU;FG is proper. (5) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 G !. For each U 2 YG ,
D .IW;FG /M.p;k/ , a) IU;FG \ M.p;k/
b) RU;FG \ M.p;k/ D .RW;FG /M.p;k/ , . where W D U \ M.p;k/ |
NS Proof. Since Pmax is !-closed, we can easily build a decreasing sequence
hp˛ W ˛ < !1 i of conditions in associated filter
|NS Pmax ,
below q0 , such that p˛ 2 D˛ for each ˛ < !1 . Thus the |
NS G D ¹p 2 Pmax j p˛ < p for some ˛ < !1 º
|
NS is a semi-generic filter in Pmax . The minor problem is that the set YG may be empty; there may be no ultrafilters on !1 such that
U \ M.p;0/ 2 jp;G .Y.p;0/ /
for all p 2 G.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
543
The solution is to ensure that for each nonzero limit ordinal ˛, the set Y.p˛ ;0/ is suitably large. Conditions (4) and (5) will be achieved by consideration of “least counterexamples” as in the proofs of Lemma 8.40 and Lemma 8.49. Fix a function f W !3 ! H.!3 / which witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 /. Define a function h W !3 ! H.!3 / as follows. Let X be the set of t ! such that t codes a pair .ˇ; p/ where ˇ < !1 and |NS . p 2 Pmax For each ˛ < !3 let ˛ D ! ˛. Thus h˛ W ˛ < !3 i is the increasing enumeration of the limit ordinals (with 0) less than !3 . Suppose ˛ < !3 then for each k < !, h.˛ C k C 1/ D f .˛/: Suppose ˛ < !3 and f .˛/ … X . Then h.˛ / D f .˛/: Suppose ˛ < !3 and f .˛/ 2 X . Let .ˇ; p/ be the pair coded by f .˛/. Then h.˛ / D f .˛ / where ˛ is least such that f .˛ / 2 Dˇ and such that f .˛ / p. Since f witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 / it follows that h also witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 /. The verification is straightforward, note that f is trivially definable from h in H.!3 /. For each < !3 let M D ¹h.ˇ/ j ˇ < º and let h D hj: Let S be the set of < !3 such that (1.1) M is transitive, (1.2) hˇ 2 M for all ˇ < , (1.3) hM ; h ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, M
(1.4) !2
M
exists and !2
2 M ,
(1.5) q0 2 H.!1 /M , M
(1.6) H.!1 /M D ¹h.ˇ/ j ˇ < !1 º.
544
8 | principles for !1
The reason for modifying f to obtain h is in order to achieve the following. Suppose 2 S. Then M
(2.1) hDˇ \ H.!1 /M W ˇ < !1 i 2 M , |
M
|
NS M NS M (2.2) for each ˇ < !1 , Dˇ \ .Pmax / is dense in .Pmax / .
We define by induction on ˛ < !1 a (strictly) decreasing sequence hp˛ W ˛ < !1 i |
NS of conditions in Pmax below q0 such that for all ˛ < !1 , p˛ 2 D˛ . The filter generated by the set ¹p˛ j ˛ < !1 º will have the desired properties. By (2.1) and (2.2) it will follow that for each 2 S,
hp˛ W ˛ < .!1 /M i 2 M : Suppose hp˛ W ˛ < ˇi has been defined and that ˇ is a nonzero limit ordinal. The case that ˇ D 0 or that ˇ is a successor ordinal is similar. We first suppose that for all 2 S, ˇ ¤ .!1 /M : We define three ordinals 0 , 1 and 2 . These will depend on ˇ. Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D h˛k W k < !i where h˛k W k < !i is an increasing cofinal sequence in ˇ. Let 0 < !1 be least such that (3.1) M 0 is transitive, (3.2) h 2 M 0 for all < 0 , (3.3) hM 0 ; h 0 ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, M0
(3.4) !1
M0
exists and !1
2 M 0 , M0
(3.5) H.!1 /M0 D ¹h./ j < !1
º,
(3.6) hp˛k W k < !i 2 H.!1 /M0 . |
|
NS NS be the condition in Pmax which is associated to the sequence Let q 2 Pmax hp˛k W k < !i.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
545
|
NS and such that the following hold where Let 1 be least such that h.1 / 2 Pmax p D h.1 /:
(4.1) M 0 2 H.!1 /M.p;0/ ; (4.2) p < q and for each increasing sequence hWk W k < !i 2 M.p;0/ ; if Wk 2 j.Y.q;k/ / for all k < !, then there exists U 2 Y.p;0/ such that for all k < !, ; Wk D U \ M.q;k/
where
W k < !i j W hM.q;k/ W k < !i ! hM.q;k/
is the (unique) iteration such that j.F.q/ / D F.p/ . Finally let 2 be least such that h.2 / 2 Dˇ and such that h.2 / < h.1 /: We finish the definition of pˇ setting pˇ D h.2 /: In the case that ˇ D 0 or ˇ D ˛ C 1, we define pˇ in a similar fashion using q0 or p˛ in place of q. The remaining case is that for some 2 S, ˇ D .!1 /M : Let
|
NS Mˇ / j p˛ < p for some ˛ < ˇº; g D ¹p 2 .Pmax
let Fg D [¹F.p/ j p 2 gº and for each p 2 g let W k < !i jp;g W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/
be the unique iteration such that j.F.p/ / D Fg . Let H.!1 /g D [¹M.p;0/ j p 2 gº: For each 2 S with the property that ˇ D .!1 /M ; |
NS M / . This is because for each such , g is a semi-generic filter in .Pmax
H.!1 /M D Mˇ D H.!1 /g : Let 0 2 S be least such that
ˇ D .!1 /M0
8 | principles for !1
546
and such that g fails to satisfy the requirements of the lemma as interpreted in M 0 relative to the sequence hD˛ \ Mˇ W ˛ < ˇi: If 0 does not exist then choose pˇ as above. Similarly if .Yg /M0 D ; then again choose pˇ as above. In fact it will follow by induction that .Yg /M0 ¤ ; and further that g satisfies (3) in M 0 . Therefore g fails to satisfy (4) or (5). Otherwise let .0 ; 1 / be least such that h.0 / 2 .Yg /M0 ; h.1 / 2 g !, and such that either (5.1) .IU;F /M0 is not a proper ideal, or (5.2) .p; k/ 2 g ! and either
a) .IW;F /M.p;k/ ¤ .IU;F /M0 \ M.p;k/ , or
b) .RW;F /M.p;k/ ¤ .RU;F /M0 \ M.p;k/ ,
where we set F D .Fg /M0 ; U D h.0 /; W D h.0 / \ M.p;k/ ; and .p; k/ D h.1 /. We shall again define three ordinals 0 , 1 and 2 . These will depend on ˇ. Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D h˛k W k < !i where h˛k W k < !i is an increasing cofinal sequence in ˇ. Let 1 < !1 be least such that hp˛k W k < !i 2 H.!1 /M1 : Let q D .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / |
NS be the condition in Pmax associated to the sequence hp˛k W k < !i. We shall define an iteration of hMk W k < !i as follows. There are three cases. Suppose first that (5.1) holds. Let 2 be least such that h.2 / D j where
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is an iteration of length 1 such that j.F /.ˇ/ is M 0 -generic for .PU /M0 .
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
547
Next suppose that (5.1) fails. Then (5.2) holds. If (5.2(a)) holds then let 0 be least such that n .IW;F /M.p;k/ : h.0 / 2 .IU;F /M0 \ M.p;k/ Let 2 be least such that h.2 / D j where j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is an iteration of length 1 such that j.F /.ˇ/ is M 0 -generic for .PU /M0 and such that !1M0 2 j.h.0 //: If (5.2(a)) fails then (5.2(b)) holds. Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .S0 ; .s0 ; f0 /; .s1 ; f1 // where
.S0 ; .s0 ; f0 // 2 .RW;F /Mk ; .s1 ; f1 / 2 .PU /M0 ; .s1 ; f1 / < .s0 ; f0 / in .PU /M0 , and S0 \ .Z.s1 ;f1 /;F /M0 2 .IU;F /M0 : The existence of 0 follows from Lemma 8.29. Let 2 be least such that h.2 / D j where j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is an iteration of length 1 such that j.F /.ˇ/ is M 0 -generic for .PU /M0 , .s1 ; f1 / belongs to the corresponding M 0 -generic filter, and such that !1M0 2 j.S0 /: This defines the iteration j D h.2 / in each case. Let q D .h.Mk ; j.Yk // W k < !i; j.F // The definition of 1 and of 2 is as above with q in place of q: Let 1 be least |NS and such that the following hold where p D h.1 /: such that h.1 / 2 Pmax (6.1) M 1 2 H.!1 /M.p;0/ ; (6.2) p < q and for each increasing sequence hWk W k < !i 2 M.p;0/ ; if Wk 2 j.Y.q0 ;k/ / for all k < !, then there exists U 2 Y.p;0/ such that for all k < !, Wk D U \ M.q ;k/ ;
where
j W hM.q ;k/ W k < !i ! hM.q ;k/ W k < !i
is the (unique) iteration such that j.F.q / / D F.p/ .
8 | principles for !1
548
Let 2 be least such that h.2 / 2 Dˇ and such that h.2 / < h.1 /: Finally we finish the definition of pˇ setting pˇ D h.2 /: This completes the inductive definition of the sequence hp˛ W ˛ < !1 i: Let
|
NS G D ¹p 2 Pmax j p˛ < p for some ˛ < !1 º
|
NS be the associated filter. Thus q0 2 G, G is a semi-generic filter in Pmax , and for each ˛ < !1 , G \ D˛ ¤ ;. We next prove that the set YG is nonempty. This is a consequence of the following property of the sequence we have defined. For each ˛ < !1 let
.h.M˛;k ; Y˛;k / W k < !i; F˛ / D p˛ and for each ˛ < ˇ < !1 let ˇ W k < !i j˛;ˇ W hM˛;k W k < !i ! hM˛;k
be the unique iteration such that j˛;ˇ .F˛ / D Fˇ . Suppose ˇ < !1 , ˇ is a limit ordinal, ˇ ¤ 0 and that ˇ D sup¹.!1 /M j 2 S \ ˇº: Let ˇ be least (7.1) M ˇ is transitive, (7.2) h 2 M ˇ for all < ˇ , (7.3) hM ˇ ; h ˇ ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, Mˇ
(7.4) !1
Mˇ
exists and !1
2 M ˇ , Mˇ
(7.5) H.!1 /Mˇ D ¹h./ j < !1 Mˇ
(7.6) ˇ < !1
º,
.
Suppose hU˛ W ˛ < ˇi 2 M ˇ and that (8.1) all ˛ < ˇ, U˛ 2 Y.p˛ ;0/ , (8.2) for all ˛0 < ˛1 < ˇ, j˛0 ;˛1 .U˛0 / U˛1 :
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
549
Then there exists U 2 Y.pˇ ;0/ such that for all ˛ < ˇ, U \ j˛;ˇ ŒM.p˛ ;0/ D j˛;ˇ .U˛ /: Using this property of the sequence it is straightforward to prove that for each p 2 G, if W 2 jp;G .Y.p;0/ / then there exists U 2 YG such that U \ jp;G .M.p;0/ / D W: We now prove that (4) and (5). The argument is by reflection and is quite similar to that given in the proof of Lemma 8.40. We note that for all 2 S such that > !1 , G 2 M and in M , G satisfies all of the requirements of the lemma except possibly (4) or (5). If either (4) or (5) fail let 0 2 S be least such that M0
!1
D !1
and such that in M 0 , (4) or (5) fails to be satisfied by G. We prove that G satisfies (4) and (5) in M 0 . Assume otherwise. Let ˛0 be least such that h.˛0 / 2 .YG /M0 and such that h.˛0 / witnesses in M 0 the failure of either (4) or (5) for G. Set U D h.˛0 /. Arguing as in the proof of Lemma 8.40 using countable elementary substructures of hM 0 ; hj0 ; 2i it follows that .IU;FG /M0 INS and so (4) must hold for .U; G/ in M 0 . Therefore (5) fails for .U; G/ in M 0 . Let ˛1 be least such that h.˛1 / 2 G ! and such that either
¤ .IW;FG /M.p;k/ , or (9.1) .IU;FG /M0 \ M.p;k/
¤ .RW;FG /M.p;k/ , (9.2) .RU;FG /M0 \ M.p;k/
where .p; k/ D h.˛1 / and where jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i
is the iteration given by G. We first assume that (9.1) holds. Let 0 be least such that
h.0 / 2 .IU;FG /M0 \ M.p;k/ n .IW;FG /M.p;k/ :
550
8 | principles for !1
Using countable elementary substructures of hM 0 ; hj0 ; 2i it follows that !1 n h.0 / 2 INS ; cf. the proof of Lemma 8.40. This is a contradiction since .IU;FG /M0 INS . Finally we assume that (9.2) holds. Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .S0 ; .s0 ; f0 /; .s1 ; f1 // where .S0 ; .s0 ; f0 // 2 .RW;F /M.p;k/ ; .s1 ; f1 / 2 .PU /M0 ; M0 .s1 ; f1 / < .s0 ; f0 / in .PU / , and S0 \ .Z.s1 ;f1 /;F /M0 2 .IU;F /M0 : The existence of 0 follows from Lemma 8.29. Again using countable elementary substructures of hM 0 ; hj0 ; 2i it follows that !1 n S0 2 INS and that !1 n .Z.s1 ;f1 /;F /M0 2 INS : This contradicts .IU;FG /M0 INS . Thus G satisfies (4) and (5) in M 0 and so the semi-generic filter G satisfies the requirements of the lemma. t u 1 Lemma 8.56 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that |
NS G Pmax
is a semi-generic filter and that Y0 YG is a set such that the following hold where for each p 2 G, W k < !i jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ is the iteration given by G. (i) For each .p; k/ 2 G !, and for each W 2 jp;G .Y.p;k/ /, there exists U 2 Y0 such that D W: U \ M.p;k/ (ii) For each U 2 Y0 , a) the ideal IU;FG is proper, b) for each .p; k/ 2 G !, .IW;FG /M.p;k/ D IU;FG \ M.p;k/ and ; .RW;FG /M.p;k/ D RU;FG \ M.p;k/ where W D M.p;k/ .
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
551
(iii) Suppose that U0 2 YG , U1 2 Y0 and that U0 \ P .!1 /G D U1 \ P .!1 /G : Then U0 2 Y0 . Then there exists a set Y Y0 such that: (1) for each U 2 Y0 there exists U 2 Y such that for all .p; k/ 2 G !, D U \ M.p;k/ I U \ M.p;k/
(2) let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;FG j U 2 Y º I: Proof. The proof is essentially identical to that of Lemma 8.50. We define by induction on ˛ a normal ideal J˛ as follows: J0 D \¹IU;F j U 2 Y0 º and for all ˛ > 0, J˛ D \¹IU;F j U 2 Y0 and for all < ˛, J \ U D ;º: It follows easily by induction that if ˛1 < ˛2 then J˛1 J˛2 . Thus for each ˛, J˛ is unambiguously defined as the intersection of a nonempty set of uniform normal ideals on !1 . The sequence of ideals is necessarily eventually constant. Let ˛ be least such that J˛ D J˛C1 and let J D J˛ . Thus J is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . Let Y be the set of U 2 Y0 such that U \ J D ; and let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º: Then \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º I; and so Y satisfies the second requirement. Finally it follows by induction that for each ˛, the ideal J˛ has the property: For each U0 2 Y0 there exists U1 2 Y0 such that U1 \ J˛ D ;; and such that U0 \ P .!1 /G D U1 \ P .!1 /G : Therefore the set Y satisfies the first requirement.
t u
As a corollary to Lemma 8.55 and Lemma 8.56 we obtain the following lemma with |NS which the basic analysis of the Pmax -extension is easily accomplished. Lemma 8.57 is analogous to Lemma 4.46, though this formulation is more efficient.
8 | principles for !1
552
Lemma 8.57 (ADL.R/ ). Suppose that A R and that A 2 L.R/. Then for each |NS |NS there exists p0 2 Pmax such that p0 < q0 and such that: q0 2 Pmax (1) hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i is A-iterable; (2) hV!C1 \ M.p0 ;0/ ; A \ M.p0 ;0/ ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i; |
NS (3) Suppose that D Pmax is a dense set which is definable in the structure hH.!1 /; A; 2i M.p0 ;0/ from parameters in H.!1 / . Then D \ ¹p > p0 j p 2 M.p0 ;0/ º ¤ ;:
Proof. Fix A and let B be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i: Let B be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; B; ¹q0 º; 2i: Thus B 2 L.R/. By Theorem 8.42 applied to B , there exist a countable transitive model M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that the following hold. (1.1) M ZFC. (1.2) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . (1.3) B \ M 2 M and hV!C1 \ M; B \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B ; 2i. (1.4) B \ M is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M . (1.5) Suppose is the least inaccessible cardinal of M . Then strong condensation holds for M in M . |
NS M / . (1.6) q0 2 .Pmax
Let hD˛ W ˛ < !1M i |
NS M enumerate all the dense subsets of .Pmax / which are first order definable in the structure hH.!1 /M ; A \ M; 2i:
By Lemma 8.55 there exists a filter |
NS M g .Pmax / such that the following hold in M where for each p 2 g, jp;g W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i is the iteration given by p.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
553
(2.1) q0 2 g. (2.2) For each ˛ < !1M ,
g \ D˛ ¤ ;:
(2.3) Suppose that p 2 g. For each W 2 jp;g .Y.p;k/ /, there exists U 2 Yg such that U \ M.p;k/ D W:
(2.4) For each U 2 Yg , the normal ideal IU;Fg is proper. (2.5) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 g !. For each U 2 Yg ,
a) IU;Fg \ M.p;k/ D .IW;Fg /M.p;k/ ,
D .RW;Fg /M.p;k/ , b) RU;Fg \ M.p;k/ . where W D U \ M.p;k/
By Lemma 8.56, there exists Y 2 M such that Y Yg and such that in M : (3.1) For each U 2 Yg there exists U 2 Y such that for all .p; k/ 2 g !, U \ M.p;k/ D U \ M.p;k/ I
(3.2) Let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;Fg j U 2 Y º I: Let a D .aI /M where I D ¹.IU;Fg /M j U 2 Y º: Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal of M above ı. By .1:3/, B \ M 1 is not † 1 in M and so by (1.4), exists. and let X0 M
be an elementary substructure such that X0 2 M , X0 is countable in M and such that ¹B \ M; Y; gº 2 X0 : Let M0 be the transitive collapse of X0 . Let .a0 ; Y0 ; F0 ; g0 / be the image of .a; Y; Fg ; g/ under the collapsing map and let I0 be the image of .I<ı /M . Thus h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 .M|NS /M : By Lemma 8.46 there exists |NS M .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 .Pmax /
such that in M ,
554
8 | principles for !1
(4.1) there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / such that j.F0 / D FO and such that .M0 ; j.Y0 // D .MO 0 ; YO0 /; (4.2) hMO k W k < !i is B \ M -iterable. By (1.3), (1.4) and (4.1), hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 \ M; A \ M; 2i: Therefore since hV!C1 \ M; B \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i: it follows that
hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i; |NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax ;
and that hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable. Let p0 D .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO /: By (4.1) it follows that for each p 2 j.g0 /, p0 < p. |NS Suppose that D Pmax is a dense set which is definable in the structure hH.!1 /; A; 2i O
from parameters in H.!1 /M0 . Then again by (4.1) it follows that there exists p 2 j.g/ such that p 2 D. Therefore p0 is as desired. t u |
NS The basic analysis of Pmax -extension follows easily from the iteration lemmas by the usual arguments.
|
NS Theorem 8.58. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then
L.R/ŒG !1 -DC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) the sentence
AC
holds;
(3) FG witnesses |NS .
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
555
|
NS is !-closed. By Theorem 8.47, for each x 2 R, there Proof. By Corollary 8.52, Pmax |NS exists p 2 Pmax such that x 2 M.p;0/ ;
|
NS by Corollary 8.51, these conditions are dense in Pmax . Fix q0 2 G. |NS
Suppose that 2 L.R/Pmax is a term for a subset of !1 . Let Z be the set of triples .p; a; ˛/ such that p a D \ ˛: Let A be the set of reals x which code an element of Z . |NS By Lemma 8.57 there exists there exists p0 2 Pmax such that p0 < q0 and such that: (1.1) hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i is A-iterable; (1.2) hV!C1 \ M.p0 ;0/ ; A \ M.p0 ;0/ ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i; |
NS (1.3) Suppose that D Pmax is a dense set which is definable in the structure
hH.!1 /; A; 2i from parameters in H.!1 /
M.p0 ;0/
. Then
D \ ¹p > p0 j p 2 M.p0 ;0/ º ¤ ;: By genericity we may suppose that p0 2 G. Let B !1 be the interpretation of by G, The key point is that |
NS \ M.p0 ;0/ j p0 < pº 2 M.p0 ;1/ ¹p 2 Pmax
and so by (1.2) and (1.3),
M.p0 ;0/
B \ !1 Let
2 M.p0 ;1/ :
jp0 ;G W hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p W k < !i 0 ;k/
be the iteration given by G. By (1.1)–(1.3), again using the fact that |
NS ¹p 2 Pmax \ M.p0 ;0/ j p0 < pº 2 M.p0 ;1/
it follows that B D jp0 ;G .b/ M.p
;0/
where b D B \ !1 0 . This proves (1). A similar argument shows that L.R/ŒG !1 -DC: The remaining claims, (2) and (3), are immediate consequences of (1) and the defini|NS tion of the order on Pmax . t u
556
8 | principles for !1 |
NS We now begin the analysis of the nonstationary ideal on !1 in the Pmax -extension. Our goal is to show that the ideal is saturated. We begin with the following lemma |NS -extension. which is the analog of Lemma 6.77 for the Pmax
Lemma 8.59. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose |
NS G Pmax
is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG, for every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. The proof is identical to that of Lemma 6.77 using the basic analysis provided by Theorem 8.58 (i. e. using Theorem 8.58 in place of Theorem 6.74) and using the |NS is !-closed (Corollary 8.52 in place of Theorem 6.73). t u fact that Pmax Remark 8.60. An immediate corollary of Lemma 8.59 is the following. Assume AD |NS is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG, INS is semiholds in L.R/ and that G Pmax saturated. The verification is a routine application of Lemma 4.24. t u Assume AD holds in L.R/ and that |
NS G Pmax
is L.R/-generic. Then it is not difficult to show that in L.R/ŒG, the set YG is empty. However one can force over L.R/ŒG to make YG nonempty. The resulting model is |NS . We shall define and briefly itself a generic extension of L.R/ for a variant of Pmax |NS analyze this variant which we denote Umax . |NS The basic property of Umax is the following. Suppose that AD holds in L.R/ and that |NS G Umax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒgŒY where in L.R/ŒG; |
NS is L.R/-generic, (1) g Pmax
(2) L.R/Œg is closed under !1 sequences in L.R/ŒG, (3) Y D Yg , (4) INS D \¹IU;Fg j U 2 Y º, (5) for all U 2 Y , INS \ U D ;. |
NS . We now define Umax
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
557
|
NS is the set of pairs .p; f / such that Definition 8.61. Umax
|
NS , (1) p 2 Pmax
(2) f 2 M.p;0/ and f W .!3 /M.p;0/ ! Y.p;0/ is a surjection. |
NS The ordering on Umax is defined as follows:
.p1 ; f1 / < .p0 ; f0 / |
NS if p1 < p0 in Pmax and for all ˛ 2 dom.f0 /,
j.f0 .˛// D f1 .j.˛// \ M.p 0 ;0/
where j W hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i is the unique iteration such that j.F.p0 / / D F.p1 / .
t u
|
|
NS NS Suppose that G Umax is a filter. Then G projects to define a filter FG Pmax . |NS The filter G is semi-generic if the projection FG is a semi-generic filter in Pmax . We |NS is a semi-generic filter. Let fix some more notation. Suppose that G Umax
fG D ¹jp;FG .f / j .p; f / 2 Gº: Thus fG is a function with domain, dom.fG / D sup¹!2LŒA j A 2 P .!1 /FG º: For each ˛ 2 dom.fG /,
fG .˛/ P .!1 /FG
and fG .˛/ is an ultrafilter in P .!1 /FG . |
NS -extension of L.R/ is a routine generalization of the analThe analysis of the Umax |NS ysis of the Pmax -extension of L.R/. We summarize the basic results in the next theorem the proof of which we leave as an exercise for the dedicated reader.
|
NS Theorem 8.62. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Umax is L.R/-generic. F D FFG and let Y D .YFG /L.R/ŒG :
Then in L.R/ŒG: |
NS ; (1) FG is L.R/-generic for Pmax
(2) P .!1 /FG D P .!1 /; (3) dom.fG / D !2 ; (4) for all ˇ < !2 , f .ˇ/ 2 Y ;
Let
558
8 | principles for !1
(5) for each U 2 Y , IU;F is a proper ideal and .!1 ; p/ 2 RU;F where p D 1PU ; (6) INS D \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º; (7) for each U 2 Y , INS \ U D ;.
t u |
NS Suppose that for each x 2 R there exists p 2 Pmax such that
x 2 M.p;0/ : We fix some more notation. Suppose that |
NS G Pmax
is a semi-generic filter. Then
IG D [¹M.p;0/ \ .INS /M.p;1/ j p 2 Gº
where for each p 2 G, jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i
is the iteration given by G. A set |
NS Pmax H.!1 /
defines a term for a dense subset of .P .!1 /G n IG ; / if the following conditions are satisfied. (1) is a set of pairs .p; b/ such that M.p;0/
b !1 and such that
b 2 M.p;0/ n .INS /M.p;1/ : |
NS (2) For each .p0 ; b0 / 2 Pmax H.!1 / such that
M.p0 ;0/
b0 !1 and such that
b0 2 M.p0 ;0/ n .INS /M.p0 ;1/ ;
there exists .p1 ; b1 / 2 such that p1 < p0 and such that b1 j.b0 / where j W hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p W k < !i 0 ;k/
is the (unique) iteration such that j.F.p0 / / D F.p1 / . |
NS is a semi-generic filter. Then Suppose G Pmax
G D ¹jp;G .b/ j p 2 G and .p; b/ 2 º: If the filter G is sufficiently generic then G is dense in the partial order, .P .!1 /G n IG ; /:
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
559
|
NS 1 Lemma 8.63 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that Pmax H.!1 / defines a term
|
NS for a dense subset of .P .!1 /G n IG ; / and that q0 2 Pmax . Suppose that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Then there is a semi-generic filter
|
NS G Pmax
and a set Y0 YG such that the following hold where for each p 2 G, W k < !i jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/
is the iteration given by G. (1) q0 2 G. (2) For each U 2 Y0 ,
G n IU;FG
is dense in .P .!1 /G n IU;FG ; /. (3) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 G !. For each W 2 jp;G .Y.p;k/ /, there exists U 2 Y0 such that D W: U \ M.p;k/ (4) For each U 2 Y0 , the normal ideal IU;FG is proper. (5) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 G !. For each U 2 Y0 ,
D .IW;FG /M.p;k/ , a) IU;FG \ M.p;k/
b) RU;FG \ M.p;k/ D .RW;FG /M.p;k/ , where W D U \ M.p;k/ .
(6) Suppose that U0 2 YG , U1 2 Y0 and that U0 \ P .!1 /G D U1 \ P .!1 /G : Then U0 2 Y0 . Proof. Fix a function f W !3 ! H.!3 / which witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 /. Define a function h W !3 ! H.!3 / as follows. Let hD˛ W ˛ < !i
8 | principles for !1
560
|
NS enumerate all the dense subsets of Pmax which are first order definable in the structure
hH.!1 /; ; 2i: We require that for each limit ordinal ˛, ¹Dˇ j ˇ < ˛º contains all the dense sets which are definable with parameters from ¹f .ˇ/ j ˇ < ˛º: Let X be the set of t ! such that t codes a pair .ˇ; p/ where ˇ < !1 and |NS . p 2 Pmax For each ˛ < !3 let ˛ D ! ˛. Thus h˛ W ˛ < !3 i is the increasing enumeration of the limit ordinals (with 0) less than !3 . Suppose ˛ < !3 then for each k < ! h.˛ C k C 2/ D f .˛/: Suppose ˛ < !3 and f .˛/ … X . Then h.˛ / D f .˛/: Suppose ˛ < !3 and f .˛/ 2 X . Let .ˇ; p/ be the pair coded by f .˛/. Then h.˛ / D f .˛ / where ˛ is least such that f .˛ / 2 Dˇ and such that f .˛ / p. Finally for each ˛ < !3 , ² 1 if f .˛/ 2 ; h.˛ C 1/ D 0 otherwise. Just as in the proof of Lemma 8.55, h witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 /. The additional feature we have obtained here is that (using the notation from the proof of Lemma 8.55) for each 2 S, \ M 2 M : Let hp˛ W ˛ < !1 i be as constructed in the proof of Lemma 8.55 using the function h and the sequence hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i: Let G
|NS Pmax
be the filter, |
NS j for some ˛ < !1 ; p˛ < pº: G D ¹p 2 Pmax
Thus G is a semi-generic filter, YG ¤ ;, and the following hold. (1.1) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 G !. For each W 2 jp;G .Y.p;k/ /, there exists U 2 YG such that D W: U \ M.p;k/
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
(1.2) For each U 2 YG , the normal ideal IU;FG is proper. (1.3) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 G !. For each U 2 YG ,
D .IW;FG /M.p;k/ , a) IU;FG \ M.p;k/
D .RW;FG /M.p;k/ , b) RU;FG \ M.p;k/ . where W D U \ M.p;k/
Let Y0 be the set of U 2 YG such that G n IU;FG is dense in .P .!1 /G n IU;FG ; /. Y0 satisfies the requirements of the lemma provided for each p 2 G, jp;G .Y.p;0/ / D ¹U \ M.p;0/ j U 2 Y0 º:
For each < !3 let
M D ¹h.ˇ/ j ˇ < º
and let h D hj: Let S be the set of < !3 such that (2.1) M is transitive, (2.2) hˇ 2 M for all ˇ < , (2.3) hM ; h ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, M
(2.4) !2
M
exists and !2
2 M ,
(2.5) q0 2 H.!1 /M , M
(2.6) H.!1 /M D ¹h.ˇ/ j ˇ < !1 º. Let Q D [¹jp;G .Y.p;k/ / j .p; k/ 2 G !º: Define a partial order on Q by W1 < W2 if W2 W1 . Suppose that U 2 YG . Then ¹W 2 Q j W U º is a maximal filter in Q. Suppose that 2 S and !1 < < !2 . Then Q 2 M :
561
562
8 | principles for !1
Suppose that F Q is a filter which is M -generic and let U D UF . We shall prove that G n IU;FG is dense in .P .!1 /G n IU;FG ; /. We first prove that the relevant filters exists. More precisely suppose that D P .Q/ is set of dense subsets of Q such that jDj !1 . We prove that there exists a filter F Q such that W 2 F and such that F is D-generic. The proof is essentially the same as the proof that YG ¤ ;. Fix D and let X hH.!3 /; h; 2i be the elementary substructure of elements which are definable in the structure with parameters from !1 [ ¹Dº. For each ˛ < !1 let X˛ D ¹f .s/ j f 2 X and s 2 ˛
|NS M .Pmax / ˛
hX˛ ; h; 2i Š hM ˛ ; h ˛ ; 2i; be the filter generated by the set, ¹p j < ˛º. C D ¹X˛ \ !1 j ˛ < !1 º
and for each ˛ < ˇ < !1 , let ˛;ˇ W M ˛ ! M ˇ be the elementary embedding which corresponds to the inclusion map, X˛ Xˇ . Finally for each ˛ < !1 let ˛ be least such that (3.1) M ˛ is transitive, (3.2) h 2 M ˛ for all < ˛ , (3.3) hM ˛ ; h ˛ ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, M
(3.4) !1
˛
M
exists and !1
(3.5) H.!1 /
M
˛
M
(3.6) ˛ < !1
˛
˛
2 M ˛ , M
D ¹h./ j < !1 .
˛
º,
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
563
Clearly C is a closed unbounded subset of !1 . The key point is that if is a limit point of C then hM ˛ W ˛ < i 2 M and h˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < i 2 M : For each ˛ < ˇ !1 let and let
Y˛ D Y.p˛ ;0/ .ˇ / j˛;ˇ W M.p˛ ;0/ ! M.p ˛ ;0/
be the elementary embedding corresponding to the iteration which witnesses pˇ < p˛ . If ˇ D !1 then j˛;!1 D jp˛ ;G jM.p˛ ;0/ : Thus if hW˛ W ˛ < i is any sequence such that: (4.1) hW˛ W ˛ < i 2 M ; (4.2) for each ˛ < ˇ < , j˛;ˇ .W˛ / Wˇ ; (4.3) for each ˛ < , W˛ 2 Y˛ : Then there exists W 2 Y.p / such that j˛; .W˛ / W for all ˛ < . It is now straightforward to construct a sequence hW˛ W ˛ < !1 i such that: (5.1) for all ˛ < ˇ < !1 ,
W˛ 2 Y˛
and j˛;ˇ .W˛ / Wˇ ; (5.2) the filter F Q generated by the set ¹jp˛ ;G .W˛ / j ˛ < !1 º is D-generic. Clearly one can require that any given element of Q belong to F . Let 0 2 S be least such that !1 < 0 . Thus G 2 M 0 . Suppose that F0 Q is a filter which is M 0 -generic and let U0 2 YG be such that [F0 U0 : We prove that G n IU0 ;FG is dense in .P .!1 /G n IU0 ;FG ; /. This is an immediate consequence of the genericity of F0 . To see this suppose that p 2 G, W 2 jp;G .Y.p;0/ / and that W 2 F0 . The key point is that INS \ P .!1 /G D .\¹IU;FG j U 2 YG º/ \ P .!1 /G :
8 | principles for !1
564
Let A be the diagonal union of .IW;FG /M.p;0/ where jp;G W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i:
The set A is unambiguously defined modulo a nonstationary set. By modifying the choice of A we can suppose that A 2 P .!1 /G . Suppose that U 2 YG . Then for some W1 2 jp;G .Y.p;0/ /,
W1 D U \ P .!1 /M.p;0/ : If W 6 U then W ¤ W1 and it follows that for each U 2 YG either W U or .!1 n A/ 2 IU;FG . Now suppose that B 2 P .!1 /G , B \ A D ;, and that B is stationary; i. e. that B … .\¹IU;FG j U 2 YG º/ \ P .!1 /G : Let U 2 YG be such that B … IU;FG . The ultrafilter U must exist since INS \ P .!1 /G D .\¹IU;FG j U 2 YG º/ \ P .!1 /G : Necessarily W U . Therefore there exists q 2 G such that (6.1) q < p,
(6.2) B 2 P .!1 /M.q;0/ , where W k < !i: jq;G W hM.q;k/ W k < !i ! hM.q;k/ . Thus W1 2 jq;G .Y.q;0/ / and W W1 . Suppose that Let W1 D U \ M.q;0/ F Q is any M 0 -generic filter containing W1 and that U 2 YG is any ultrafilter such that [F U . It follows that B … IU;FG . It follows by the M 0 -genericity of F0 that
G n IU0 ;FG is dense in .P .!1 /G n IU0 ;FG ; /. Thus Y0 satisfies the requirements of the lemma. u t Lemma 8.63 yields the following variation of Lemma 8.57. |
NS H.!1 / defines a term for a dense Lemma 8.64 (ADL.R/ ). Suppose that Pmax subset of P .!1 / n IG and that 2 L.R/:
|
NS Let A be the set of x 2 R which code an element of . Then for each q0 2 Pmax there |NS exists p0 2 Pmax such that p0 < q0 and such that:
(1) hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i is A-iterable; (2) hV!C1 \ M.p0 ;0/ ; A \ M.p0 ;0/ ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i;
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
565
|
NS \ M.p0 ;0/ such that g0 2 M.p0 ;0/ , such that (3) There exists a filter g0 Pmax
p0 < p for each p 2 g0 , and such that in M.p0 ;0/ ; a) g0 is semi-generic and F D Fg0 , b) for each U 2 Y.p0 ;0/ , . \ H.!1 /M.p0 ;0/ /g0 n IU;F is dense in .P .!1 /g0 n IU;F ; /, where F D F.p0 / . Proof. The proof is in essence identical to the proof of Lemma 8.57, using Lemma 8.63 in place of Lemma 8.55. Let B be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i: Let B be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of the first order diagram of the structure hV!C1 ; B; ¹q0 º; 2i: Thus B 2 L.R/. By Theorem 8.42 applied to B , there exist a countable transitive model M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that the following hold. (1.1) M ZFC. (1.2) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . (1.3) B \ M 2 M and hV!C1 \ M; B \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B ; 2i. (1.4) B \ M is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M . (1.5) Suppose is the least inaccessible cardinal of M . Then strong condensation holds for M in M . |
NS M / . (1.6) q0 2 .Pmax
By Lemma 8.63 there exist, in M , a filter |
NS M / g .Pmax
and a set Y0 .Yg /M such that the following hold where for each p 2 g, W k < !i jp;g W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/
is the iteration given by g. We let . /M D \ H.!1 /M :
566
8 | principles for !1
(2.1) q0 2 g. (2.2) Suppose that p 2 g. For each W 2 jp;g .Y.p;k/ /, there exists U 2 Y0 such that D W: U \ M.p;k/
(2.3) For each U 2 Y0 , the normal ideal IU;Fg is proper. (2.4) For each U 2 Y0 ,
../M /g n IU;Fg
is dense in .P .!1 /g n IU;Fg ; /. (2.5) Suppose that .p; k/ 2 g !. For each U 2 Y0 ,
D .IW;Fg /M.p;k/ , a) IU;Fg \ M.p;k/
D .RW;Fg /M.p;k/ , b) RU;Fg \ M.p;k/ . where W D U \ M.p;k/
(2.6) Suppose that U0 2 Yg , U1 2 Y0 and that U0 \ P .!1 /g D U1 \ P .!1 /g : Then U0 2 Y0 . By (2.2)–(2.6), g and Y0 satisfy (in M ) the requirements of the hypothesis of Lemma 8.56 and so by Lemma 8.56 there exists Y 2 M such that Y Y0 and such that in M , (3.1) for each U0 2 Y0 there exists U1 2 Y such that for all .p; k/ 2 g !, D U1 \ M.p;k/ ; U0 \ M.p;k/
(3.2) let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;Fg j U 2 Y º I: Let a D .aI /M where I D ¹.IU;Fg /M j U 2 Y º: Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal of M above ı. By .1:3/, B \ M 1 is not † 1 in M and so by (1.4), exists. and let X0 M
be an elementary substructure such that X0 2 M , X0 is countable in M and such that ¹B \ M; Y; gº 2 M:
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
567
Let M0 be the transitive collapse of X0 . Let .a0 ; Y0 ; F0 / be the image of .a; Y; Fg / under the collapsing map and let I0 be the image of .I<ı /M . Thus h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 .M|NS /M : By Lemma 8.46 there exists |NS M / .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 .Pmax
such that in M , (4.1) there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / such that j.F0 / D FO and such that .M0 ; j.Y0 // D .MO 0 ; YO0 /; (4.2) hMO k W k < !i is B \ M -iterable. By (1.3), (1.4) and (4.1), hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 \ M; A \ M; 2i: Therefore since hV!C1 \ M; B \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i: it follows that (5.1) hV!C1 \ MO 0 ; A \ MO 0 ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i, |NS , (5.2) .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
(5.3) hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable. Let
p0 D .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO /:
By (4.1) it follows that for each p 2 j.g/, p0 < p. Finally j is an elementary embedding and j.A \ M0 / D A \ MO 0 : Therefore for each U 2 YO0 , we have that in MO 0 ; O
../M0 /j.g/ n IU;FO is dense in .P .!1 /j.g/ n IU;FO ; /, where O
O
. /M0 D \ H.!1 /M0 : Let g0 D j.g/. Thus p0 and g0 are as required.
t u
As a corollary to Lemma 8.64 we obtain the following theorem which we shall use |NS to prove that the nonstationary ideal is !2 -saturated in the Pmax -extension of L.R/.
568
8 | principles for !1
Theorem 8.65. Assume AD L.R/ and that V D L.R/ŒG where G
|NS Umax
|
NS is L.R/-generic. Let FG be the induced filter on Pmax and let
F D FFG : Suppose that D 2 L.R/ŒFG is dense in .P .!1 / n INS ; /: Then for each ultrafilter U 2 YFG ; the set D n IU;FG is dense in .P .!1 / n IU;FG ; /: Proof. This is immediate. Let |
NS H.!1 / Pmax
be a set in L.R/ which defines a term for D. Let A be the set of x 2 R which code an element of . Fix U 2 YFG and fix a set S 2 P .!1 / n IU;FG : By Theorem 8.62, there exists a condition .p; f / 2 G such that for some s 2 M.p;0/ and for some u 2 Y.p;0/ , S D jp;FG .s/ and where
jp;FG .u/ D U \ M.p;0/ ; jp;FG W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i
is the iteration given by FG . By Lemma 8.64 and the genericity of G we can suppose that: (1.1) A \ M.p;0/ 2 M.p;0/ ; (1.2) hM.p;k/ W k < !i is A-iterable; |
NS (1.3) There exists a filter g0 Pmax \ M.p;0/ such that g0 2 M.p;0/ , such that
p
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
569
c) for each U0 2 Y.p;0/ , ../M.p;0/ /g0 n IU0 ;F0 is dense in .P .!1 /g0 n IU0 ;F0 ; /, where F0 D F.p/ and where . /M.p;0/ D \ H.!1 /M.p;0/ : Let
d D ../M.p;0/ /g0 n Iu;F0
as computed in M.p;0/ with F0 D F.p/ . By (1.3c) there exists b 2 d such that b a. Since p 2 FG , jp;FG .g0 / FG : Finally hM.p;k/ W k < !i is A-iterable and
.Iu ;F /M.p;0/ D IU;F \ M.p;0/
where u D jp;FG .u/. Therefore jp;FG .d / D n IU;F which implies that jp;FG .b/ 2 D n IU;F : However b a and so
jp;FG .b/ A:
t u
To apply Theorem 8.65 we need the following lemma which is an immediate corollary of Lemma 8.59. Lemma 8.66. Assume ADL.R/ and suppose |
NS G Umax
is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG, for every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . |
NS Proof. Let FG Pmax be the L.R/-generic filter given by G. By Theorem 8.62(2),
H.!2 /L.R/ŒG D H.!2 /L.R/ŒFG : Using this, the lemma is an immediate corollary of Lemma 8.59. It is convenient to introduce some more notation. |
Definition 8.67. M0 NS is the set of finite sequences h.M; I/; g; Y; F i such that the following hold.
t u
570
8 | principles for !1
(1) M is a countable transitive set such that M ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement: (2) L.R/M AD. |
NS (3) g Umax \ M, g is L.R/M -generic and M D L.R/M Œg:
(4) F D .Fg /M . (5) Y D .Yg /M . (6) I D ¹.IU;F /M j U 2 Y º. (7) .M; I/ is iterable.
t u |
The fundamental iteration lemma (Lemma 8.41) generalizes to structures in M0 NS . Lemma 8.68. Suppose that |
h.M0 ; I0 /; g0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS and that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Then there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / of length !1 and a set Y ¹U P .!1 / j U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 º such that the following hold where F D j0 .F0 /. (1) For each U 2 Y , U \ M0 2 j.Y0 /. (2) For each U 2 Y , the ideal IU;F is proper,
.RW;F /M0 D RU;F \ M0 ; and
.IW;F /M0 D IU;F \ M0 ;
where W D M0 \ U . (3) Let I be the ideal on !1 which is dual to the filter, F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º I: (4) Suppose that U0 is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 such that U0 \ M0 2 j.Y0 /: a) There exists U1 2 Y such that U0 \ M0 D U1 \ M0 : b) Suppose that \¹U j U 2 Y º U0 : Then U0 2 Y .
t u
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
571
Lemma 8.68 combined with Lemma 8.46 easily yields the following version of | Lemma 8.46 for M0 NS . Theorem 8.69. Assume AD holds in L.R/ and that A R is a set in L.R/. Suppose that | h.M0 ; I0 /; g0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS : Then there is a condition |NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax and an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that (1) hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable, (2) j 2 MO 0 , (3) j.F0 / D FO , (4) j.Y0 / D ¹U \ M0 j U 2 YO0 º, (5) for each U 2 YO0 , and where W D M0 \ U .
.RW;FO /M0 D RU;FO \ M0 ;
.IW;FO /M0 D IU;FO \ M0 ; t u
Lemma 8.66 yields the following strengthening of Lemma 8.64. The difference is in the statement of (3b). |
NS Lemma 8.70 (ADL.R/ ). Suppose that Pmax H.!1 / defines a term for a dense subset of P .!1 / n IG . Let A be the set of x 2 R which code an element of . Then for |NS |NS there exists p0 2 Pmax such that p0 < q0 and such that: each q0 2 Pmax
(1) hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i is A-iterable; (2) hV!C1 \ M.p0 ;0/ ; A \ M.p0 ;0/ ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i; |
NS (3) There exists a filter g0 Pmax \ M.p0 ;0/ such that g0 2 M.p0 ;0/ , such that p0 < p for each p 2 g0 , and such that in M.p0 ;0/ ;
a) g0 is semi-generic and F D Fg0 , b) for each U 2 Y.p0 ;0/ , ../M.p0 ;0/ /g0 n IU;F is predense in .P .!1 / n IU;F ; /, where F D F.p0 / and where ./M.p0 ;0/ D \ H.!1 /M.p0 ;0/ .
572
8 | principles for !1 |
|
NS NS Proof. Fix q0 2 Pmax . Suppose G Umax is L.R/-generic such that
q0 2 FG |NS Pmax
where FG is the induced L.R/-generic filter. We work in L.R/ŒG. Let be least such that L .R/ŒG †2 L.R/ŒG and let N D L .R/ŒG. We claim that by Lemma 8.66 and Lemma 4.24, the set ¹X N j X is countable and NX is strongly iterable º is stationary in P!1 .N /. Here NX is the transitive collapse of X . To see this note that in L.R/ŒG, ‚L.R/ D !3 : Therefore by Lemma 4.24, if M is a transitive set of cardinality !2 such that M ZFC ; and such that H.!2 / M , then the set ¹X M j X is countable and MX is strongly iterable º contains a club in P!1 .M / where for each X M , MX is the transitive collapse of X. Now fix a function H W N
MX D MX
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
573
where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Therefore MX is strongly iterable and so the set ¹X N j X is countable and NX is strongly iterable º is stationary in P!1 .N /. Let X0 N be a countable elementary substructure such that (1.1) ¹q0 ; G; Aº X0 , (1.2) N0 is strongly iterable, where N0 is the transitive collapse of X0 . Let Z0 D X0 \ H.!2 / and let M0 be the transitive collapse of Z0 . Thus M0 D .H.!2 //N0 : Let S D ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countable º where MX is the transitive collapse of X . By Lemma 8.66 there exists a function W H.!2 /
D n IU;FG
is dense in .P .!1 / n INS ; /. Let J D ¹IU;FG j U 2 YFG º:
8 | principles for !1
574 Thus:
(2.1) INS D \¹I j I 2 Jº. (2.2) Suppose that I0 2 J, I1 2 J and that for some A !1 , a) I0 ¹B !1 j B \ A 2 I1 º, b) !1 n A … I1 . Then I0 D I1 . Let ¹G0 ; F0 ; F0 ; J0 ; Y0 º be the image of ¹G; FG ; FG ; J; YFG º under the transitive collapse of X0 . |NS The partial order Umax is !-closed and so ¹N0 ; F0 ; G0 ; F0 ; D0 ; Y0 º 2 L.R/: Further
|
h.N0 ; J0 /; G0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS : We now work in L.R/. By Theorem 8.69 there exists a condition |
NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
and an iteration
j W .N0 ; J0 / ! .N0 ; J0 /
such that (3.1) hMO k W k < !i is A-iterable, (3.2) j 2 MO 0 , (3.3) j.F0 / D FO , (3.4) j0 .Y0 / D ¹U \ N0 j U 2 YO0 º, (3.5) for each U 2 YO0 ,
.RW;FO /N0 D RU;FO \ N0
and
.IW;FO /N0 D IU;FO \ N0 ;
where W D N0 \ U . Let
p0 D .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO /
and let g0 D j.F0 /. We claim that p0 and g0 satisfy the requirements of the lemma. We verify (3(b)), the other requirements are immediate.
|
NS 8.2 Pmax
575
Suppose that U 2 YO0 and let W D U \ N0 : Since
|
h.N0 ; J0 /; G0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS ; it follows that
|
h.N0 ; J0 /; G0 ; Y0 ; FO i 2 M0 NS
where hG0 ; Y0 i D j.hG0 ; Y0 i/. |
By the definition of M0 NS , in N0 , . \ N0 /g0 n IW;FO is dense in .P .!1 / n IW;FO ; /. Let
D0 D ../N0 /g0 n IW;FO ;
where as usual, . /N0 D \ H.!1 /N0 . We work in MO 0 . .N0 ; J0 / is an iterate of .N0 ; J0 / and IU;FO is a normal uniform ideal on !1 such that IU;FO \ N0 2 J0 : Therefore by (2.2) and Lemma 4.10, !1 n .5D0 / 2 IU;FO : t u
This verifies (3b). |
NS is L.R/-generic. Then in Theorem 8.71. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Pmax L.R/ŒG,
(1) IG is !2 -saturated, (2) INS D IG . Proof. By Theorem 8.58, P .!1 / D P .!1 /G and IG D INS . Therefore it suffices to show that if D P .!1 /G n IG is dense then there exists a set D0 D such that D0 is predense in .P .!1 /G n IG ; / and such that jD0 j !1 . |NS Let Pmax H.!1 / be a set in L.R/ which defines a term for D. Let A R be the set of x 2 R such that x codes an element of .
8 | principles for !1
576
By Lemma 8.70 and genericity there exists p0 2 G such that: (1.1) hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i is A-iterable; (1.2) hV!C1 \ M.p0 ;0/ ; A \ M.p0 ;0/ ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i; |
NS (1.3) There exists a filter g0 Pmax \ M.p0 ;0/ such that g0 2 M.p0 ;0/ , such that for each p 2 g0 , p0 < p;
and such that in M.p0 ;0/ ; a) g0 is semi-generic, b) F.p0 / D Fg0 , c) for each U 2 Y.p0 ;0/ , ../M.p0 ;0/ /g0 n IU;Fg0 is predense in .P .!1 / n IU;Fg0 ; /, where ./M.p0 ;0/ D \ H.!1 /M.p0 ;0/ : A key point is that in M.p0 ;0/ ; for each U 2 Y.p0 ;0/ , j../M.p0 ;0/ /g0 j !1 ; and so (1.3c) asserts that !1 n A 2 IU;Fg0 where Let
A D 5¹S j S 2 ../M.p0 ;0/ /g0 n IU;Fg0 º: jp0 ;G W hM.p0 ;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p W k < !i 0 ;k/
be the iteration given by G. It follows that jp0 ;G .g0 / G and that in L.R/ŒG, jp0 ;G .g0 / is a semi-generic filter. Let g0 D jp0 ;G .g0 / and let D0 D g0 \ M.p : 0 ;0/
Thus D0 D and
jD0 j !1 :
By (1.3) it follows that
5D0
contains the critical sequence of the iteration defining jp0 ;G and so D0 is necessarily predense in .P .!1 /G n IG ; / since .P .!1 /G n IG ; / D .P .!1 / n INS ; /:
t u
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
577
As an immediate corollary of Theorem 8.71 we obtain the following. |
NS Corollary 8.72. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then in L.R/ŒG, YG D ;:
Proof. We note that the following must hold in L.R/ŒG. Suppose that S !1 is stationary. Then there exists a set A !1 such that both ¹˛ 2 S j A n F .˛/ is finiteº and ¹˛ 2 S j A \ F .˛/ is finiteº are stationary. Suppose YG ¤ ; and let U 2 YG . Thus, since P .!1 / D P .!1 /G ; it follows that IU;FG is a proper ideal. But INS is !2 -saturated and so for some stationary set S !1 , IU;FG D INS jS D ¹T !1 j T n S 2 INS º: t u
This contradicts the claim above. | PmaxNS
. This lemma will We end this section with one last lemma regarding the L.R/ be relevant to the absoluteness theorem we shall prove, see Theorem 8.99. |
NS Lemma 8.73. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Let F D FG . Then in L.R/ŒG the following holds. There exists a co-stationary set S !1 such that for all ultrafilters U P .!1 /, if p 2 PU and
Zp;F … INS ; then Zp;F \ S … INS :
8.3
C
t u
CC
The principles, |NS and |NS |
|
NS NS The Umax -extension of L.R/ is a generic extension of the Pmax -extension. The relevant partial order is a product of a partial order PF which is defined in Definition 8.75. The definition of PF is closely related to two refinements of |NS one of which we |NS now define. These refinements in turn yield an absoluteness theorem for the Pmax extension. It is not clear if the version we prove is optimal and as we have indicated, more elegant versions are likely possible.
578
8 | principles for !1
We first fix some notation. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! is a function witnessing that |NS holds. For each S 2 P .!1 / n INS let FS;F denote the set of A !1 such that there exists a club C !1 such that for all ˛ 2 C \ S , F .˛/ n A is finite. Clearly FS;F is a filter on !1 which extends the club filter. The definition of C |NS involves Zh;F which is defined in Definition 8.26. C
Definition 8.74. |NS : There is a function F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! such that the following hold. (1) F witnesses |NS . (2) Suppose X P .!1 / has cardinality !1 and that S !1 is stationary. Then there exists a stationary set T S and an ultrafilter U such that: a) FT;F \ X D U \ X . b) Suppose that h W Œ!1
t u
Definition 8.75. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! is a function witnessing that |NS holds. Let PF be the partial order defined as follows. Conditions are sets X P .!1 / such that jX j !1 and such that X FS;F for some S 2 P .!1 / n INS . Suppose X; Y 2 PF . Then X Y if Y X .
t u
The partial order PF is analogous to the partial order PNS which we defined in Section 6.1. There is however an interesting difference. It is not difficult to show that assuming ./, the partial order PNS is not !2 -cc. However if INS is !2 -saturated, which |NS
is the case in L.R/Pmax , then PF is trivially !2 -cc for any function F which witnesses |NS . More is actually true.
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
579
Lemma 8.76. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! is a function which witnesses that |NS holds and that INS is !2 -saturated. Then there exists a complete boolean subalgebra B P .!1 /=INS such that RO.PF / Š B: Proof. Define W PF ! P .!1 /=INS as follows. Suppose X 2 PF . It follows from the !2 -saturation of INS that there exists a stationary set SX !1 such that (1.1) X FSX ;F , (1.2) for all S 2 P .!1 / n INS , if
X FS;F
then S n SX 2 INS . Define .X / D b where b 2 P .!1 /=INS is the element given by SX . The element b is unambiguously defined. The function induces the required isomorphism of RO.PF / with a complete t u boolean subalgebra of P .!1 /=INS . We also note the following reformulation of Corollary 8.72. |
NS Lemma 8.77. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Pmax is a semi-generic filter such that G is L.R/-generic and such that
P .!1 / D P .!1 /G : Then RO.PF / has no atoms where F D FG .
t u C
Lemma 8.76 and Lemma 8.77 suggest the following refinement of |NS . CC
Definition 8.78. |NS : There is a function F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! such that the following hold. C
(1) F witnesses |NS . (2) PF is !2 -cc. (3) RO.PF / has no atoms.
t u
580
8 | principles for !1
Remark 8.79. As we have already remarked, the most elegant manifestation of |NS would be to have for some ultrafilter U on !1 , (1) U extends the club filter, (2) the boolean algebra RO.PU / is isomorphic to a complete boolean subalgebra of P .!1 /=INS . Any function F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
inducing the isomorphism for (2), witnesses that |NS holds. However by Lemma 8.25, CC
(1) and (2) cannot both hold for any ultrafilter U . |NS in some sense gives the best possible approximation to (1) and (2); cf. Corollary 8.88. t u There is an interesting question. Suppose that
F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! C
is a function which witnesses that |NS holds. Can the boolean algebra, RO.PF /; be atomic? |
NS -extension easily yields, The basic analysis of the Pmax
|
NS Theorem 8.80. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then CC
L.R/ŒG |NS : |
NS , the function FG Proof. By Theorem 8.58 and the definition of the order on Pmax witnesses that L.R/ŒG |NS
and in L.R/ŒG; P .!1 / D P .!1 /G : |
NS that the function FG witnesses that It follows from the definition of Pmax C
L.R/ŒG |NS : By Theorem 8.71, the nonstationary ideal is !2 -saturated in L.R/ŒG and so by Lemma 8.76, the function FG witnesses that CC
L.R/ŒG |NS : |
t u |
NS NS -extension of L.R/, identifying the Umax We continue our analysis of the Pmax |NS extension of L.R/ as a generic extension of the Pmax -extension of L.R/. The relevant partial order, as we have indicated, is simply a product of PF .
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
581
Definition 8.81. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! is a function witnessing that |NS holds. Let QF be the product partial order: Conditions are functions p W ˛ ! PF such that ˛ < !2 . The order is defined pointwise: Suppose that p1 and p2 are conditions in QF . Then p2 p1 if (1) dom.p1 / dom.p2 /, (2) for all ˇ 2 dom.p1 /,
p2 .ˇ/ p1 .ˇ/ t u
in PF . Lemma 8.82. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function which witnesses that |NS holds. Then the partial order PF is .!1 ; 1/distributive. Proof. Suppose that g Coll.!2 ; P .!1 // is V -generic. Since g is V -generic for a partial order which is .< !2 /-closed in V , it follows that in V Œg, F witnesses that CC |NS holds. Therefore we may assume without loss of generality that 2@1 D @2 . Suppose that G PF is V -generic. Then, by reorganizing G as a subset of !2 , V ŒG D V ŒA where A is a set such that A \ ˛ 2 V for all ˛ < !2V . This is a consequence of C the fact that F witnesses |NS in V ŒG, see Definition 8.74(2). Since PF is !2 -cc in V t u it follows that V is closed under !1 -sequences in V ŒG. !2V
|
|
NS NS The next four theorems detail the relationship between Pmax and Umax . We shall not need these theorems, we simply state them for completeness. The proofs are not difficult and we leave the details to the reader.
|
NS is L.R/-generic. Let Theorem 8.83. Assume AD L.R/ . Suppose that G Umax F D FFG and let
H D ¹p 2 .QF /L.R/ŒFG j for all ˇ 2 dom.p/; p.ˇ/ fG .ˇ/º: Then H is an L.R/ŒFG -generic filter and L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒFG ŒH :
t u
8 | principles for !1
582
Theorem 8.84. Assume ADL.R/ and that V D L.R/Œg |NS Pmax
where g is L.R/-generic. Let F D Fg be the function witnessing |NS given by g. Then PF is .!1 ; 1/-distributive and further suppose G PF is V -generic. Then in V ŒG; (1) IU;F is a proper ideal, (2) INS is not saturated, (3) IU;F D sat.INS /, (4) IU;F is a saturated ideal, where U D [G.
t u
Theorem 8.84 combined with Theorem 8.58 yields the following theorem. Theorem 8.85. Assume ADL.R/ and that V D L.R/Œg |NS Pmax
where g is L.R/-generic. Let F D Fg be the function witnessing |NS given by g. Suppose p 2 g and let j W hM.p;k/ W k < !i ! hM.p;k/ W k < !i
of length !1 such that j.F.p/ / D F . Suppose that G PF is V -generic and let U P .!1 / be the ultrafilter, U D [G, given by G. Then in V ŒG the following hold where : W D U \ M.p;0/ (1) W 2 j.Y.p;0/ /.
(2) .IW;F /M.p;0/ D IU;F \ M.p;0/ .
(3) .RW;F /M.p;0/ D RU;F \ M.p;0/ .
t u
Theorem 8.86. Assume ADL.R/ and that V D L.R/Œg |NS Pmax
where g is L.R/-generic. Let F D Fg be the function witnessing |NS given by g. Then QF is .!1 ; 1/-distributive. Suppose G QF is V -generic and for each ˛ < !2 let U˛ D [¹p.˛/ j ˛ 2 dom.p/ and p 2 Gº; and let Y D ¹U˛ j ˛ < !2 º:
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
583
Then in V ŒG: (1) Y D Yg ; (2) For each U 2 Y , a) IU;F is a proper ideal, b) IU;F is a saturated ideal; (3) INS D \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º; (4) For each U 2 Y , INS \ U D ;.
t u CC
One corollary of Lemma 8.82 is that |NS cannot hold in L. More generally, strong CC
condensation for H.!2 / implies :|NS . CC
Corollary 8.87. Assume that strong condensation holds for H.!2 /. Then |NS fails. Proof. The proof is a modification of the proof of Lemma 8.25. We sketch the argument under the additional hypothesis that V D L. The proof from strong condensation for H.!2 / is essentially the same. Suppose that G PF is V -generic and let U 2 V ŒG be the ultrafilter on !1 given by G; U D ¹X j X 2 Gº: Since F witnesses |NS in V it follows that U is a V -ultrafilter on !1V . However F CC witnesses |NS in V and so by Lemma 8.82, PF is .!1 ; 1/-distributive in V . This implies .P .!1 //V D .P .!1 //V ŒG and so U is an ultrafilter on !1 in V ŒG. Let < !2 be least such that (1.1) F 2 L , (1.2) L ZC, CC
(1.3) F witnesses |NS in L . The key point is that G \ L is L -generic for .PF /.L / . This implies that U \ L is generic over L . Let C D ¹X \ !1 j X L ; F 2 X and jX j D !º and for each ˛ 2 C let
X ˛ L
be the (unique) elementary substructure X L such that F 2 X and ˛ D X \ !1 .
584
8 | principles for !1
For each ˛ 2 C let ˛ be the image of under the transitive collapse of X˛ . Therefore, since U extends the club filter on !1 , for each formula .x0 ; x1 / and for each ˇ < !1 , L ŒF; ˇ if and only if ¹˛ j ˇ < ˛ and L˛ ŒF j˛; ˇº 2 U: Finally by the definition of , every element of L is definable in L from paramt u eters in !1 [ ¹F º. But this contradicts that U \ L is generic over L . A second corollary of Lemma 8.82 is the following improvement of Lemma 8.76. The proof, which we leave to the reader, is an easy consequence of the definitions, cf. the proof of Lemma 8.76. Corollary 8.88. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function which witnesses that |NS holds and that INS is !2 -saturated. Then there exists a complete boolean subalgebra B P .!1 /=INS such that RO.PF PU / Š B; where U 2 V PF is the ultrafilter on !1 given by the generic filter for PF .
t u
|
NS We now come to the absoluteness theorem for the Pmax -extension. We first prove |NS a strong version of the homogeneity of Pmax . This is a corollary of the following iteration lemma.
Lemma 8.89. Suppose that |
h.M0 ; I0 /; g0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS ; |
h.M1 ; I1 /; g1 ; Y1 ; F1 i 2 M0 NS ; and that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Then there exist iterations j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / and j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / of length !1 and a bijection W j0 .Y0 / ! j1 .Y1 / such that: (1) !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j j0 .F0 /.˛/ D j1 .F1 /.˛/º 2 INS . (2) Suppose that W0 2 j0 .Y0 / and W1 D .W0 /. Then for all A0 2 W0 and for all A1 2 W1 , A0 \ A1 … INS :
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
585
(3) Suppose that U P .!1 / is an ultrafilter such that U \ M0 2 j0 .Y0 / and such that U \ M1 2 j1 .Y1 /: a) The ideal IU;F is proper. b) For each i 2 ¹0;1º,
.RW;F /Mi D RU;F \ Mi ; and
.IW;F /Mi D IU;F \ Mi ;
where W D Mi \ U and where F D ji .Fi /. Proof. The proof is quite similar to that of Lemma 8.40 except we do not need to . enforce AC Fix a function h W !3 ! H.!3 / which witnesses strong condensation for H.!3 /. For each < !3 let M D ¹h.ˇ/ j ˇ < º and let h D hj: Let S be the set of < !3 such that (1.1) M is transitive, (1.2) hˇ 2 M for all ˇ < , (1.3) hM ; h ; 2i ZFC n Powerset, M
(1.4) !2
M
exists and !2
2 M ,
(1.5) M0# 2 H.!1 /M . We construct j0 as the limit of an iteration 0 W ˛ < ˇ !1 i h.M0˛ ; G˛0 /; j˛;ˇ
and j1 as the limit of an iteration 1 W ˛ < ˇ !1 i: h.M1˛ ; G˛1 /; j˛;ˇ
Simultaneously we construct a sequence h˛ W ˛ !1 i of bijections 0 1 .Y0 / ! j0;˛ .Y1 / ˛ W j0;˛ 0 such that for all ˛ < ˇ !1 , and for all W 2 j0;˛ .Y0 /, 0 1 ˇ .j˛;ˇ .W // D j˛;ˇ .˛ .W //:
586
8 | principles for !1
Thus everything is completely determined by h.G˛0 ; G˛1 ; ˛ / W ˛ < !1 i. We say that this sequence satisfies the conditions of the lemma if the corresponding iterations 0 1 and j0;! ) together with the map !1 satisfy the requirements of the lemma. (j0;! 1 1 Similarly if 2 S then h.G˛0 ; G˛1 ; ˛ / W ˛ < .!1 /M i 0 1 satisfies the requirements of the lemma in M if both .j0; ; j0; ; / 2 M and 0 1 .j0; ; j0; ; / satisfies the requirements of the lemma interpreted in M where D .!1 /M . We construct h.G˛0 ; G˛1 ; ˛ / W ˛ < ˇi by induction on ˇ, following the proof of Lemma 8.40, eliminating potential counterexamples. The construction is uniform and so for each 2 S, h.G˛0 ; G˛1 ; ˛ / W ˛ < .!1 /M i 2 M :
Suppose that h.G˛0 ; G˛1 ; ˛ / W ˛ < ˛0 i is given. If ˛0 is a successor ordinal then .G˛00 ; G˛10 ; ˛0 / D h.0 / where 0 is least such that h.0 / satisfies the minimum necessary conditions. Thus we may suppose that ˛0 is a (nonzero) limit ordinal. The function ˛0 is uniquely specified. We must define G˛00 and G˛10 . This we do by cases. The first case is that for all 2 S, either ˛0 ¤ .!1 /M ; 0 1 ; j0;˛ ; ˛0 / satisfies the requirements of the lemma interpreted in M . or .j0;˛ 0 0 There are two subcases. If for all 2 S,
˛0 ¤ .!1 /M ; then let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and 0 .I0 /, (2.1) for some I 2 j0;˛ 0
g0 .P .˛0 / \ M0˛0 n I / and g0 is M0˛0 -generic, 1 .I1 /, (2.2) for some I 2 j0;˛ 0
g1 .P .˛0 / \ M1˛0 n I / and g1 is M1˛0 -generic. Let .G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /: Otherwise let 0 2 S be least such that ˛0 D .!1 /M0 : Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
587
0 (3.1) for some I 2 j0;˛ .I0 /, 0
g0 .P .˛0 / \ M0˛0 n I / and g0 is M0˛0 -generic, 1 .I1 /, (3.2) for some I 2 j0;˛ 0
g1 .P .˛0 / \ M1˛0 n I / and g1 is M1˛0 -generic, 0 1 .F0 /.˛0 / D j0;˛ .F1 /.˛0 /. (3.3) j0;˛ 0 C1 0 C1 0 1 Since .j0;˛ ; j0;˛ ; ˛0 / satisfies the requirements of the lemma interpreted in M 0 , 0 0 0 exists. Let
.G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /: Finally let 0 2 S be least such that ˛0 D .!1 /M0 ; 0 1 and .j0;˛ ; j0;˛ ; ˛0 / fails to satisfy the requirements of the lemma interpreted in 0 0 M 0 . As in the analogous stage of the proof of Lemma 8.40, we shall extend the iterations, defining .G˛00 ; G˛10 /, attempting to eliminate the least counterexample, ignoring the requirement (1). We first suppose (2) fails. There are two subcases. First suppose that there exists .W0 ; W1 / 2 ˛0 such that for some A0 2 W0 and for some A1 2 W1 ,
A0 \ A1 D ;: Let 0 be least such that h.0 / is such a pair .W0 ; W1 / 2 ˛0 and let 1 be least such that h.1 / D .A0 ; A1 / with A0 2 W0 , A1 2 W1 and A0 \ A1 D ;: Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and (4.1) (2.1)–(2.2) hold, (4.2) A0 2 g0 and A1 2 g1 . Let .G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /:
588
8 | principles for !1
Otherwise let 0 be least such that for some .W0 ; W1 / 2 ˛0 , (5.1) h.0 / D .W0 ; W1 /, (5.2) there exist A0 2 W0 , A1 2 W1 , such that A0 \ A1 … .INS /M0 : Let 1 be least such that h.1 / D .A0 ; A1 / witnessing (5.2). Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and (6.1) (2.1)–(2.2) hold, 0 1 .F0 /.˛0 / D j0;˛ .F1 /.˛0 /, (6.2) j0;˛ 0 C1 0 C1
(6.3) A0 2 g0 and A1 2 g1 . We can ensure (6.2) holds because in M 0 , W0 [ W1 can be extended to an ultrafilter. Let .G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /: 0 1 Finally we suppose that in M 0 , (3) fails for .j0;˛ ; j0;˛ ; ˛0 /. 0 0 Let 0 be least such that:
(7.1) h.0 / 2 M 0 ; (7.2) M 0 “h.0 / is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 ”; 0 (7.3) h.0 / \ M0˛0 2 j0;˛ .Y0 /; 0 1 (7.4) h.0 / \ M1˛0 2 j0;˛ .Y1 /; 0
(7.5) Let U D h.0 /. Either a) .IU;F /M0 is not a proper ideal, or b) there exists
˛0
.p; S / 2 .RW0 ;F /M0 such that .p; S / … .RU;F /M0 where 0 F D j0;˛ .F0 /, 0
W0 D h.0 / \ M0˛0 , c) there exists
˛0
.p; S / 2 .RW1 ;F /M1 such that .p; S / … .RU;F /M0 where 1 F D j0;˛ .F1 /, 0
W1 D h.0 / \ M1˛0 .
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
589
Let (8.1) U D h.0 /, (8.2) W0 D U \ M0˛0 , ˛0
0 (8.3) I0 D .IW0 ;F /M0 where F D j0;˛ .F0 /, 0
(8.4) W1 D U \ M1˛0 , ˛0
0 (8.5) I1 D .IW1 ;F /M1 where F D j0;˛ .F1 /. 0
There are several subcases. First suppose that (7.5(a)) holds. Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and (9.1) g0 .P .˛0 / \ M0˛0 n I0 / and g0 is M0˛0 -generic, (9.2) g1 .P .˛0 / \ M1˛0 n I1 / and g1 is M1˛0 -generic, 0 1 (9.3) j0;˛ .F0 /.˛0 / D j0;˛ .F1 /.˛0 /, 0 C1 0 C1 0 .F0 /.˛0 / is M 0 -generic for .PU /M0 . (9.4) j0;˛ 0 C1
Let .G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /: Otherwise (7.5(a)) fails. Hence either (7.5(b)) holds or (7.5(c)) holds. We next suppose that (7.5(b)) holds. Let 1 be least such that h.1 / D .p; S / witnessing (7.5(b)). Let 2 be least such that h.2 / D q and (10.1) q 2 .PU /M0 , (10.2) q p, (10.3) .Zq;F /M0 \ S 2 .IU;F /M0 , 0 where F D j0;˛ .F0 /. 0 Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and
(11.1) (9.1)–(9.4) hold, (11.2) S 2 g0 , (11.3) q belongs to the M 0 -generic filter for .PU /M0 given by 0 , where 0 1 0 D j0;˛ .F0 /.˛0 / D j0;˛ .F1 /.˛0 /: 0 C1 0 C1
Let .G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /: The final case is that both (7.5(a)) and (7.5(b)) fail. In which case (7.5(c)) holds. This is essentially the same as the case that (7.5(b)) holds: Let 1 be least such that h.1 / D .p; S / witnessing (7.5(c)). Let 2 be least such that h.2 / D q and
8 | principles for !1
590
(12.1) q 2 .PU /M0 , (12.2) q p, (12.3) .Zq;F /M0 \ S 2 .IU;F /M0 , 1 where F D j0;˛ .F1 /. 0 Let 0 be least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and
(13.1) (9.1)–(9.4) hold, (13.2) S 2 g0 , (13.3) q belongs to the M 0 -generic filter for .PU /M0 given by 0 , where 0 1 0 D j0;˛ .F0 /.˛0 / D j0;˛ .F1 /.˛0 /: 0 C1 0 C1
Let .G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /: This completes the inductive definition of h.G˛0 ; G˛1 ; ˛ / W ˛ < !1 i. Let .j0 ; j0 ; / D .j00;!1 ; j10;!1 ; !1 /: We claim that .j0 ; j0 ; / satisfies the requirements of the lemma. We prove (1) holds. For this we first prove that for all .W0 ; W1 / 2 , if A0 2 W0 and if A1 2 W1 then A0 \ A1 ¤ ;: Suppose this fails. Let 0 be least such that h.0 / is such a pair .W0 ; W1 / 2 and let 1 be least such that h.1 / D .A0 ; A1 / with A0 2 W0 , A1 2 W1 and A0 \ A1 D ;: Suppose X hH.!3 /; h; 2i is a countable elementary substructure with 2 X . Let ˛0 D X \ !1 and let MX be the transitive collapse of X . Thus MX D M where D MX \ Ord and so 2 S. Let .0X ; 1X / be the image of .0 ; 1 / under the collapsing map. Thus h.1X / D .X \ A0 ; X \ A1 /: It follows that .G˛00 ; G˛10 / was defined at stage ˛0 using .0X ; 1X / choosing 0 least such that h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 / and (14.1) (2.1)–(2.2) hold, (14.2) A0 \ X 2 g0 and A1 \ X 2 g1 ,
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
591
and defining .G˛00 ; G˛10 / D h.0 / D .g0 ; g1 /: Thus A0 \ X 2 G˛00 and A1 \ X 2 G˛10 . But this implies ˛0 2 A0 \ A1 which is a contradiction. This proves that for all .W0 ; W1 / 2 , W0 [ W1 has the finite intersection property. Therefore there is a closed unbounded set C !1 to which this reflects; if ˛0 2 C then for all .W0 ; W1 / 2 ˛0 , W0 [ W1 has the finite intersection property. Therefore, by inspection of the inductive construction, for all ˛0 2 C , if there exists 2 S such that ˛0 D .!1 /M ; then 0 1 j0;˛ .F0 /.˛0 / D j0;˛ .F1 /.˛0 /: 0 C1 0 C1
This proves (1). The verification that (2) and (3) hold is by similar reflection arguments. These arguments are essentially identical to arguments for the analogous claims given at the end of the proof of Lemma 8.40. t u Lemma 8.90. Suppose that |
h.M0 ; I0 /; g0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS ; |
h.M1 ; I1 /; g1 ; Y1 ; F1 i 2 M0 NS ; and that strong condensation holds for H.!3 /. Then there exist iterations j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / and
j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 /
of length !1 and a set Y ¹U P .!1 / j U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 º such that !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j j0 .F0 /.˛/ D j1 .F1 /.˛/º 2 INS and such that for each i 2 ¹0;1º, the following hold. (1) For each U 2 Y , U \ Mi 2 j.Yi /. (2) For each U 2 Y , the ideal IU;ji .Fi / is proper,
.RW;ji .Fi / /Mi D RU;ji .Fi / \ Mi ; and where W D Mi \ U .
.IW;ji .Fi / /Mi D IU;ji .Fi / \ Mi ;
592
8 | principles for !1
(3) Let I be the ideal on !1 which is dual to the filter, F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;ji .Fi / j U 2 Y º I: (4) j.Yi / D ¹U \ Mi j U 2 Y º. Proof. Let
j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 /
and
j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 /
be iterations of length !1 , and let W j0 .Y0 / ! j1 .Y1 / be a bijection such that : (1.1) !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j j0 .F0 /.˛/ D j1 .F1 /.˛/º 2 INS . (1.2) Suppose that W0 2 j0 .Y0 / and W1 D .W0 /. Then for all A0 2 W0 and for all A1 2 W1 , A0 \ A1 … INS : (1.3) Suppose that U P .!1 / is an ultrafilter such that
U \ M0 2 j0 .Y0 /
and such that
U \ M1 2 j1 .Y1 /:
a) The ideal IU;F is proper. b) For each i 2 ¹0;1º,
.RW;F /Mi D RU;F \ Mi ; and
.IW;F /Mi D IU;F \ Mi ;
where W D Mi \ U . By Lemma 8.89, .j0 ; j1 ; / exists. Let F D j0 .F0 /. The desired set of ultrafilters Y is obtained just as in the proof of Lemma 8.41. Let Z be the set of uniform ultrafilters U on !1 such that U \ M0 2 j0 .Y0 /
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
and such that
593
U \ M1 2 j1 .Y1 /:
We define by induction on ˛ a normal ideal J˛ as follows: J0 D \¹IU;F j U 2 Zº and for all ˛ > 0, J˛ D \¹IU;F j U 2 Z and for all < ˛, J \ U D ;º: It follows easily by induction that if ˛1 < ˛2 then J˛1 J˛2 : Thus for each ˛, J˛ is unambiguously defined as the intersection of a nonempty set of uniform normal ideals on !1 . The sequence of ideals is necessarily eventually constant. Let ˛ be least such that J˛ D J˛C1 and let J D J˛ : Thus J is a uniform normal ideal on !1 . Let Y be the set of U 2 Z such that U \ J D ; and let I be the ideal dual to the filter F D \¹U j U 2 Y º: Then it follows that \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º I: Similarly and
j0 .Y0 / D ¹U \ M0 j U 2 Y º j1 .Y1 / D ¹U \ M1 j U 2 Y º: |
t u
NS is an immediate corollary. We isolate the relevant fact The homogeneity of Pmax in the following lemma.
Lemma 8.91. Suppose that for each x 2 R, there exists |
h.M; I/; g; Y; F i 2 M0 NS |
|
NS NS such that x 2 M. Suppose that p0 2 Pmax and p1 2 Pmax . There exist
|
NS .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F / 2 Pmax
and functions F0 , F1 such that |
NS (1) .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F0 / 2 Pmax and .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F0 / < p0 ,
|
NS (2) .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F1 / 2 Pmax and .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F1 / < p1 ,
(3) ¹˛ < !1M0 j F0 .˛/ ¤ F1 .˛/º 2 .INS /M0 .
594
8 | principles for !1
Proof. Let x 2 R code the pair .p0 ; p0 / and let |
h.M; I/; g; Y; F i 2 M0 NS be such that x 2 M. Thus
|
NS M / : ¹p0 ; p1 º .Pmax
Let N D .L.R//M and for i 2 ¹0;1º let |
NS N / gi .Umax
be N -generic with pi 2 Fgi where |
NS N / Fgi .Pmax
|
NS N is the induced N -generic filter on .Pmax / . Let hYi ; Fi i D hYgi ; Fgi iN Œgi
and let Ii D ¹.IU;Fi /N Œgi j U 2 Yi º: A key point is that since .M; I/ is iterable it follows by Lemma 8.66 and Theorem 3.46, that for each i 2 ¹0;1º, the structure .N Œgi ; Ii / is also iterable and so |
h.Mi ; Ii /; gi ; Yi ; Fi i 2 M0 NS ; where Mi D N Œgi . Strictly speaking Lemma 8.66 and Theorem 3.46 cannot be applied in N Œg since we have only N Œg ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement; but both are easily seen to hold in this case. Let y 2 R code .N ; g0 ; g1 / and let O I; O ı; / 2 H.!1 / .M; be such that O (1.1) x 2 M, (1.2) MO is transitive and MO ZFC C “ı is a Woodin cardinal”, O (1.3) IO D .I<ı /M ,
O I/ O is iterable, (1.4) .M; O (1.5) ı < and MO M, (1.6) strong condensation holds in MO for MO where is the least inaccessible cardiO nal of M.
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
595
O I; O ı; / follows from 1 -Determinacy, by Theorem 8.45. We The existence of .M; 2 note that since for each x 2 R, there exists |
h.M; I/; g; Y; F i 2 M0 NS such that x 2 M, necessarily 12 -Determinacy holds. This follows by absoluteness. Thus |
O
¹h.M0 ; I0 /; g0 ; Y0 ; F0 i; h.M1 ; I1 /; g1 ; Y1 ; F1 i; º .M0 NS /M O and so by Lemma 8.90, Then there exist iterations in M, j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / and
j1 W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / O
of length !1M and a set O
Y ¹U P .!1 / j U is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 ºM O such that Y 2 M, O
O
O
!1M n ¹˛ < !1M j j0 .F0 /.˛/ D j1 .F1 /.˛/º 2 .INS /M ; O and such that for each i 2 ¹0;1º, the following hold in M. (2.1) For each U 2 Y , U \ Mi 2 j.Yi /. (2.2) For each U 2 Y , the ideal IU;ji .Fi / is proper,
.RW;ji .Fi / /Mi D RU;ji .Fi / \ Mi ; and
.IW;ji .Fi / /Mi D IU;ji .Fi / \ Mi ;
where W D Mi \ U . (2.3) Let I be the ideal on !1 which is dual to the filter, F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;ji .Fi / j U 2 Y º I: (2.4) j.Yi / D ¹U \ Mi j U 2 Y º. Let F D j0 .F0 /. Thus there exists a 2 MO such that O I; a/; Y; F i 2 M|NS : h.M; Let
X0 MO
be an elementary substructure such that
8 | principles for !1
596
O (3.1) X0 2 M, O
(3.2) jX0 jM D !, (3.3) ¹ı; a; Y; j0 ; j1 º 2 X0 , let MO X0 be the transitive collapse of X0 and let ¹ IOX0 ; aX0 ; YX0 ; FX0 ; FX10 º O a; Y; F; j1 .F1 /º under the collapsing map. Thus be the image of ¹ I; O h.MO X0 ; IOX0 ; aX0 /; YX0 ; FX0 i 2 .M|NS /M
Therefore by Lemma 8.46, there exists |NS M O / .h.MQ k ; YQk / W k < !i; FQ / 2 .Pmax
such that in MO there exists a countable iteration j W .MO X0 ; IOX0 ; aX0 / ! .MO X 0 ; IOX 0 ; aX 0 / satisfying (4.1) j.FX0 / D FQ , (4.2) .MO X 0 ; j.YX0 // D .MQ 0 ; YQ0 /. Let
p D .h.MQ k ; YQk / W k < !i; FQ /:
Thus, since p 2
|NS M O / , .Pmax
|
NS p 2 Pmax . Clearly
p < p0 Q (since F D j.FX0 / and F D j0 .F0 /.) Let FQ1 D j.FX10 /: Then |NS , (5.1) .h.MQ k ; YQk / W k < !i; FQ1 / 2 Pmax
(5.2) .h.MQ k ; YQk / W k < !i; FQ1 / < p1 , Q
Q
(5.3) ¹˛ < !1M0 j FQ .˛/ ¤ FQ1 .˛/º 2 .INS /M0 . t u
This proves the lemma. The following corollary is immediate from Lemma 8.91. Corollary 8.92. Suppose that for each x 2 R, there exists |
h.M0 ; I0 /; g0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS |
NS such that x 2 M0 . Then Pmax is homogeneous.
t u
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
597
Lemma 8.91 combined with Theorem 8.69 yields the following theorem. |
NS Theorem 8.93. Assume ADL.R/ and that V D L.R/Œg where g Pmax is L.R/generic. Let F D Fg be the function witnessing |NS given by g. Suppose that
|
h.M0 ; I0 /; g0 ; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M0 NS : Then there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / of length !1 such that:
(1) .INS /M0 D INS \ M0 . (2) !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j j.F0 /.˛/ D F .˛/º 2 INS . (3) Suppose that G PF is V -generic and let U P .!1 / be the ultrafilter, U D [G, given by G. Then in V ŒG the following hold where W D U \ M0 . (1) W 2 j.Y0 /.
(2) .IW;j.F0 / /M0 D IU;F \ M0 .
(3) .RW;j.F0 / /M0 D RU;F \ M0 . Proof. By Theorem 8.69 there exists a condition |
NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
and an iteration j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .j0 .M0 /; j0 .I0 // such that (1.1) j0 2 MO 0 , (1.2) j0 .F0 / D FO , (1.3) j0 .Y0 / D ¹U \ j0 .M0 / j U 2 YO0 º, (1.4) for each U 2 YO0 ,
.RW;FO /j0 .M0 / D RU;FO \ j0 .M0 /
and .IW;FO /j0 .M0 / D IU;FO \ j0 .M0 /; where W D j0 .M0 / \ U . Let
p0 D .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO /:
By Lemma 8.91 there exists an L.R/-generic filter |
NS g0 Pmax
such that
598
8 | principles for !1
(2.1) L.R/Œg0 D L.R/Œg, (2.2) p0 2 g0 , (2.3) ¹˛ < !1 j Fg .˛/ ¤ Fg0 .˛/º 2 .INS /L.R/Œg . Let
j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be the iteration of length !1 such that j.FO / D Fg0 . It follows from Theorem 8.85 that j is as required. t u Theorem 8.93 suggests the following definition. Definition 8.94. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function which witnesses |NS . The function F is universal if for each .M; f / 2 H.!1 / such that (i) M is transitive and CC
M ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement C |NS ; (ii) M is iterable, CC
(iii) f witnesses |NS in M, there exists an iteration
j W M ! M
of length !1 such that:
(1) .INS /M D INS \ M . (2) !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j j.f /.˛/ D F .˛/º 2 INS . (3) Suppose that G PF is V -generic and let U P .!1 / be the ultrafilter, U D [G, given by G. Then in V ŒG the following hold where W D U \ M :
a) .IW;F /M ŒW D IU;F \ M ŒW . b) .RW;F /M ŒW D RU;F \ M .
t u
Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function which witnesses |NS . With the following iteration lemma, several equivalent formulations for the notion that F is universal are easily identified. There may well be fairly natural combinatorial properties of F which imply that F is universal. If |NS . so this would lead to more elegant absoluteness theorems for Pmax
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
599
Lemma 8.95. Suppose that .M; f; Ff / 2 H.!1 / and that (i) M is transitive and CC
M ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement C |NS ; (ii) M is iterable, CC
(iii) f witnesses |NS in M, (iv) Ff D ¹a 2 .P .!1 //M j !1M n a … z for all z 2 .Pf /M º. Suppose that strong condensation holds for H.!3 / and that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M i 2 M is such that
¹S˛ ; T˛ j ˛ < !1M º P .!1 /M n .INS /M :
Then there is an iteration
j W M ! M
of length !1 and a set Y of uniform ultrafilters on !1 such that the following hold where F D j.f / and where Y be the set of filters W .P .!1 //M such that
¹z 2 .Pj.f / /M j z W º
is M -generic. (1) Y D ¹U \ M j U 2 Y º. (2) For each U 2 Y : a) The ideal IU;F is proper. b) .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;F . c) Let W D M0 \ U . Then
.IW;F /M D IU;F \ M and
.RW;F /M D RU;F \ M :
(3) Let I be the ideal on !1 which is dual to the filter, F D \¹U j U 2 Y º; then \¹IU;F j U 2 Y º I .
600
8 | principles for !1
(4) Suppose that U0 is a uniform ultrafilter on !1 such that U0 \ M 2 Y : a) There exists U1 2 Y such that U0 \ M D U1 \ M . b) Suppose that, in addition, \¹U j U 2 Y º U0 . Then U0 2 Y . (5) Suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1 i D j.h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M i/: Let h˛ W ˛ < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the ordinals 2 !1 n .M \ Ord/ such that is a cardinal in L.M/. Let C D ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ D ˛ º: Then for all ˛ 2 C and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛ 2 Sˇ if and only if ˛Cˇ 2 Tˇ : Proof. Following the proof of Lemma 8.40 there exists an iteration j W M ! M of length !1 such that the following hold where F D j.f / and where Y is the set of filters W .P .!1 //M such that
¹z 2 .Pj.f / /M j z W º is M -generic. (1.1) Suppose that U is an ultrafilter on !1 such that U \ M 2 Y . Then: a) The ideal IU;F is proper. b) .!1 ; 1PU / 2 RU;F . c) Let W D M0 \ U . Then
.IW;F /M D IU;F \ M and
.RW;F /M D RU;F \ M :
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
601
(1.2) Suppose that h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1 i D j.h.S˛ ; T˛ / W ˛ < !1M i/: Let h˛ W ˛ < !1 i be the increasing enumeration of the ordinals 2 !1 n .M \ Ord/ such that is a cardinal in L.M/. Let C D ¹˛ < !1 j ˛ D ˛ º: Then for all ˛ 2 C and for all ˇ < ˛, ˛ 2 Sˇ if and only if
˛Cˇ 2 Tˇ :
We note the following. Suppose that k W M ! M is an (arbitrary) iteration of length !1 . Then for each z 2 .Pk.f / /M filter g .Pk.f / /M
there exists a
such that z 2 g and such that g is M -generic. To see this note that if g0 .Pf /M is an M-generic filter (which must exist since M is countable) then ¹k.t / j t 2 g0 º
generates an M -generic filter. Clearly we can suppose that z D k.t / for some t 2 M by passing to a countable iterate of M if necessary. Thus we can choose g0 with t 2 g0 in which case the M -generic filter generated by the image of g0 contains z as desired. Thus for the iteration specified above, necessarily j.Ff / D \Y : This combined with the usual thinning arguments, as in the proof of Lemma 8.41, yields the set Y as required. t u Lemma 8.95 combined with Lemma 8.46 yields the following lemma. 1 Lemma 8.96 ( 2 -Determinacy). Suppose that
.M; f / 2 H.!1 /
and that (i) M is transitive and CC
M ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement C |NS ; (ii) M is iterable, CC
(iii) f witnesses |NS in M.
602
8 | principles for !1
Then there is a condition |
NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
and an iteration j W M ! M such that: (1) j 2 MO 0 . (2) j.f / D FO . (3) Let Y be the set of W 2 MO 0 such that
a) W .P .!1 //M and W is a filter,
b) the set ¹z 2 .PFO /M j z W º is M -generic. Then Y D ¹U \ M j U 2 YO0 º. (4) For each U 2 YO0 ,
O
.RW;FO /M D .RU;FO /M0 \ M ; and
O
.IW;FO /M D .IU;FO /M0 \ M ;
where W D M \ U .
t u
Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function witnessing |NS . We give in the next two lemmas, universality properties of F which are each equivalent to the property that F is universal. Lemma 8.97 (ADL.R/ ). Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function witnessing |NS . The following are equivalent. (1) F is universal. (2) Suppose that
h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M|NS :
Let ı0 2 M0 be the Woodin cardinal in M0 associated to I0 , and let Q0 D .Q<ı0 /M0 be the associated stationary tower. Then there is an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / of length !1 such that the following hold. a) Suppose b 2 j.Q0 ja0 /. Then b is stationary. b) !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j j.F0 /.˛/ D F .˛/º 2 INS .
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
603
c) Suppose that G PF is V -generic and let U P .!1 / be the ultrafilter, U D [G, given by G. Then in V ŒG the following hold where W D U \ M0 : (i) W 2 j.Y0 /. (ii) Suppose that p 2 .PW /M0 , and
.j.ı0 // M0 / ; .p; b/ 2 .RW;F
then .p; S / 2 RU;F where S !1 is a stationary set which is equivalent to b. Proof. We first prove that (1) implies (2). Fix h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M|NS : Let ı0 2 M0 be the Woodin cardinal in M0 associated to I0 , and let Q0 D .Q<ı0 /M0 be the associated stationary tower. By Lemma 8.46, there exists |
NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
such that (1.1) there exists a countable iteration j W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / such that j.F0 / D FO and such that .M0 ; j.Y0 // D .MO 0 ; YO0 /: Let
|
h.M; I/; g; Y; f i 2 M0 NS be such that
.h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Fg |
NS M where Fg .Pmax / is the associated .L.R//M -generic filter. The existence of h.M; I/; g; Y; f i follows from the assumption of ADL.R/ . To see this suppose that |NS G Umax
is L.R/-generic with
.h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 FG
|
NS where FG Pmax is the induced L.R/-generic filter. Let be least such that
L .R/ŒG ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement:
604
8 | principles for !1
By Lemma 8.66 and Lemma 4.24, the set of countable elementary substructures, X L .R/ŒG such that MX is iterable where MX is the transitive collapse of X , is closed and unbounded in P!1 .L .R/ŒG/: Choose such an elementary substructure with ¹.h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO /; Gº 2 X: The transitive collapse of X yields |
h.M; I/; g; Y; f i 2 M0 NS as required. Since F is universal there exists an iteration jO W M ! M of length !1 such that the following hold.
(2.1) .INS /M D INS \ M . (2.2) !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j jO.f /.˛/ D F .˛/º 2 INS . (2.3) Suppose that G PF is V -generic and let U P .!1 / be the ultrafilter, U D [G, given by G. Then in V ŒG the following hold where W D U \ M : a) .IW;jO.f / /M
ŒW
b) .RW;jO.f / /M Finally let
ŒW
D IU;F \ M ŒW . D RU;F \ M .
jg W hMO k W k < !i ! hMO k W k < !i
be the iteration (in M) such that jg .FO / D f . Thus jO.jg .j // W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / is an iteration of length !1 , which is as required. The proof that (2) implies (1) is similar. Given .M; f / 2 H.!1 / and that (3.1) M is transitive and CC
M ZFC C ZC C †1 -Replacement C |NS ; (3.2) M is iterable, CC
(3.3) f witnesses |NS in M.
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
there exists, by Lemma 8.96, a condition |
NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; FO / 2 Pmax
and an iteration
j W M ! M
such that: (4.1) j 2 MO 0 . (4.2) j.f / D FO . (4.3) Let Y be the set of W 2 MO 0 such that
a) W .P .!1 //M and W is a filter, b) the set
¹z 2 .PFO /M j z W º
is M -generic. Then
Y D ¹U \ M j U 2 YO0 º:
(4.4) For each U 2 YO0 ,
O
.RW;FO /M D .RU;FO /M0 \ M ; and
O
.IW;FO /M0 D .IU;FO /M0 \ M0 ;
where W D M0 \ U . By Lemma 8.49 and Lemma 8.50, there exists h.M0 ; I0 ; a0 /; Y0 ; F0 i 2 M|NS and an iteration
jO W hMO k W k < !i ! hMO k W k < !i
such that (5.1) jO.FO / D F0 , (5.2) for each k < !, jO.YOk / D ¹U \ MO k j U 2 Y0 º, (5.3) for each U 2 Y0 , for each k < !,
.IWk ;F0 /Mk D .IU;F0 /M0 \ Mk and
.RWk ;F0 /Mk D .RU;F0 /M0 \ Mk ;
where for each k < !, Wk D U \ Mk .
605
606
8 | principles for !1
Let j0 W .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / ! .M0 ; I0 ; a0 / be as given by (2). The induced iteration j0 .jO.j // W M ! M is of length !1 and is easily verified to witness that F is universal.
t u
The proof of Lemma 8.97 easily adapts to prove Lemma 8.98 which gives another CC characterization of when a function witnessing |NS is universal. This characterization |
NS involves conditions in Pmax .
Lemma 8.98 (ADL.R/ ). Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function witnessing |NS . The following are equivalent. (1) F is universal. (2) Suppose that |
NS : .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; F0 / 2 Pmax
Then there is an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i of length !1 such that:
a) For each k < !, .INS /MkC1 \ Mk D INS \ Mk . b) !1 n ¹˛ < !1 j j.F0 /.˛/ D F .˛/º 2 INS . c) Suppose that G PF is V -generic and let U P .!1 / be the ultrafilter, U D [G, given by G. Then in V ŒG the following hold where for each k < !, Wk D U \ Mk : (i) Wk 2 j.Yk /. (ii) IU;F \ Mk D .IWk ;j.F / /Mk .
(iii) RU;F \ Mk D .RWk ;j.F / /Mk .
t u
Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
is a function witnessing |NS and that F is universal. Then (assuming ADL.R/ ) F must satisfy a number of additional combinatorial facts. For example as a corollary of Lemma 8.73 we obtain that the conclusion of Lemma 8.73 must hold:
C
CC
8.3 The principles, |NS and |NS
607
There exists a stationary set S !1 such that for all ultrafilters U P .!1 /, if p 2 PU and Zp;F … INS ; then Zp;F \ S … INS : Suppose F1 W !1 ! Œ!1 ! and F2 W !1 ! Œ!1 ! . Then we define F1 DE F2 if ¹˛ j F1 .˛/ M F2 .˛/ is infiniteº 2 INS : Let ŒF1 E be the equivalence class of F1 . Theorem 8.99. Suppose that there are ! many Woodin cardinals with a measurable above. Suppose that F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! is a function such that the following hold. CC
(i) F witnesses |NS . (ii) F is universal. Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; ŒF E ; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri and that hH.!2 /; 2; ŒF E ; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X Ri : Then
|NS Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; ŒFG E ; INS ; X I X 2 L.R/; X RiL.R/ Proof. Fix a function F W !1 ! Œ!1 ! CC
witnessing |NS and such that F is universal. There are two relevant claims. First suppose that |
NS .h.Mk ; Yk / W k < !i; f / 2 Pmax :
Then there exists an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i of length !1 such that: (1.1) !1 n ¹˛ j F .˛/ D j.f /.˛/º 2 INS .
(1.2) For each k < !, Mk \ INS D Mk \ .INS /MkC1 .
:
608
8 | principles for !1
(1.3) Suppose that G PF is V -generic. Let U D [G and for each k < ! let Wk D U \ Mk . Then for each k < !, a) Wk 2 j.Yk /,
b) .IWk ;j.f / /Mk D IU;j.f / \ Mk ,
c) .RWk ;j.f / /Mk D RU;j.f / \ Mk . This claim is an immediate corollary of Lemma 8.98. The second claim is the following. Let ı0 be the least Woodin cardinal and let I<ı0 be the directed system ideals associated to stationary tower Q<ı0 . Let 0 be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal above ı0 and suppose that X V0 is a countable elementary substructure. Let M be the transitive collapse of X and let I be the image of I<ı0 under the collapsing map. Let FX D F \ X be the image of F under the collapsing map. By Lemma 5.23, .M; I/ is A-iterable for each set A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/ \ X: By Lemma 8.96 there exist |NS .h.MO k ; YOk / W k < !i; fO/ 2 Pmax
and an iteration
j W .M; I/ ! .M ; I /
such that the following hold. O
(2.1) M 2 MO 0 with jM jM0 D !. (2.2) j 2 MO 0 . O (2.3) .INS /M D M \ I where I D \¹.IW;fO /M0 j W 2 YO0 º.
(2.4) fO D j.FX /. (2.5) Suppose that U 2 YO0 and let W D U \ M . Then
a) W is M -generic for .PW /M ,
O
b) .IW;fO /M D .IU;fO /M0 \ M ,
O
c) .RW;fO /M D .RU;fO /M0 \ M . The remainder of the proof of Theorem 8.99 is a routine adaptation of the proof of Theorem 6.85, the absoluteness theorem for Qmax . There are no restrictions on the …2 formulas here as there are in Theorem 6.85, essentially because of the definition of universality. t u
Chapter 9
Extensions of L.; R/ The main goal in this chapter in the basic analysis of the Pmax and Qmax extensions of models larger than L.R/. One class of examples of models in which we shall be interested are those of the form L.; R/ where P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages. If G Pmax is L.; R/-generic and if, for example, L.; R/ ADR C “‚ is regular”; then .L.P .!1 ///L.;R/ŒG D L.R/ŒG and so L.; R/ŒG ./. Thus by forcing with Pmax over larger models of AD we are creating models of ./ with more subsets of !2 . In this fashion we can create models in which ./ holds and in which P .!2 / is reasonably closed. For a suitable choice of , the Pmax -extension of L.; R/ yields a model in which Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ holds and in which !2 exhibits some interesting combinatorial features. In Section 9.6 we shall consider the Pmax extension of even “larger” inner models which are of the form, L.S; ; R/ where S Ord and where, as above, P .R/. Applications include producing extensions in which ./ holds and in which Strong Chang’s Conjecture holds. One reason we consider the problem of obtaining extensions in which Strong Chang’s Conjecture holds is that since Strong Chang’s Conjecture is not generally expressible in L.P .!2 //, it is not immediately obvious that such extensions can even exist. In the second section of the next chapter, Section 10.2, we shall define several more variations of Pmax and Qmax , and consider the induced extensions of L.S; ; R/. One application will be to show that Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture together with all the …2 sentences true in Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; A W A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/iL.R/
does not imply ./. The analysis of these extensions is facilitated by the assumption that a particular form of AD hold in the inner models, L.S; ; R/. We discuss this refinement of AD in Section 9.1 where we give a brief summary of some of the basic results for ADC . However we note the following theorem which shows that an alternate approach is certainly possible (in some cases). This theorem is an easy corollary of Theorem 4.41 and the analysis of L.R/Pmax .
9 Extensions of L.; R/
610
Theorem 9.1. Suppose that A R and that every set B 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then t u L.A; R/Pmax ZFC C : The following is an interesting open question. Suppose that A R and that every set B 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/ is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Does L.A; R/ ADC ‹
9.1
ADC
We begin with some definitions. Definition 9.2. Suppose A R. The set A is ˛ 2 Ord, and a formula .x0 ; x1 / such that
1
-borel if there exist a set S Ord,
A D ¹y 2 R j L˛ ŒS; y ŒS; yº: There are many equivalent definitions of the formula , for each set S Ord, the set
1
t u
-borel sets, for example given a
A D ¹y 2 R j LŒS; y ŒS; yº; 1
is easily seen to be -borel. Another alternate definition is that a set A R is 1 -borel if A has a transfinite borel code. This definition (though more descriptive) is tedious to formalize. It is important that the transfinite borel code be effective; i. e. that it be a set of ordinals. Assuming AD C DC there is yet another equivalent definition. Lemma 9.3 (AD + DC). Suppose A R. The following are equivalent. (1) A is 1 -borel. (2) There exists S Ord such that A 2 L.S; R/:
t u
Suppose 2 Ord and that A ! . The set A is determined if there exists a winning strategy for Player I or for Player II in the game on corresponding to the set A. The following lemma is an easy exercise. Lemma 9.4 (ZF). There exists a set A !1! such that A is not determined.
t u
9.1 ADC
611
Suppose T is a tree on ! . We use the notation from Section 2.1 and define a set AT ! ! as follows. x 2 AT if Player I has a winning strategy in the game corresponding to Bx ! where Bx D ŒTx D ¹f 2 ! j .x; f / 2 ŒT º: The set AT is easily verified to be 1 -borel. If the set ŒT ! ! ! is clopen in the product space, ! ! ! , we shall say that T is an 1 -borel code of AT . Note that in the case that D !, if ŒT is clopen then AT is borel. Without the 1 requirement that ŒT be clopen, one can only deduce that AT is † 1 . It is not difficult 1 1 to show that every -borel set has an -borel code. One important feature of the 1 -borel sets is that assuming AD the property of being 1 -borel is a local property. One manifestation of this is given in the following lemma. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass which contains the borel sets, such that is closed under continuous preimages, finite unions and complements. Recall from Section 2.1 that we have associated to two transitive sets, M and N , see Definition 2.18. Lemma 9.5 (ZF + AD + DCR ). Suppose A R and that A is 1 -borel. Let be the pointclass of sets which are projective in A. Then there exists T 2 M such that T is an
1
-borel code for A.
t u
Assuming AD many ordinal games are determined and this is closely related to the existence of Suslin representations for sets of reals. We now give the definition of ADC . Recall that ‚ is the least ordinal which is not the range of a function with domain R. The Axiom of Choice implies ‚ D c C . Using the notation above, ‚ is the least ordinal ˛ such that ˛ … M where D P .R/. Definition 9.6 (ZF + DCR ). ADC : (1) Suppose A R. Then A is 1 -borel. (2) Suppose < ‚ and W ! ! ! ! is a continuous function. Then for each t u A R the set 1 ŒA is determined. The next theorem shows that assuming ADC C V D L.P .R// the basic analysis of L.R/ generalizes. Theorem 9.7 (ZF + DCR ). Assume ADC C V D L.P .R//. Then: (1) The pointclass †21 has the scale property. (2) Suppose A R is †21 . Then A D pŒT for some tree T 2 HOD. (3) M2 †1 L.P .R//. 1
t u
9 Extensions of L.; R/
612
Remark 9.8. (1) We note that Theorem 9.7(1) follows from Theorem 9.7(2) and Theorem 9.7(3) just assuming AD C DCR . (2) Over the base theory of AD C DCR , ADC is equivalent to the assumption that Theorem 9.7(2) and Theorem 9.7(3) both hold. t u Also Theorem 8.19 generalizes. Theorem 9.9. Assume ADC C V D L.P .R//. Suppose that x 2 R and let N D HODL.P .R// Œx: Suppose that is an uncountable cardinal of N which is below the least weakly compact cardinal of N . t u Then strong condensation holds for .H. //N in N . One important feature of ADC is that it is downward absolute. Theorem 9.10 (ZF + DCR ). Assume ADC and that M is a transitive inner model of ZF such that R M . Then M ADC : Proof. Suppose ı < ‚M . Then by the Moschovakis Coding Lemma, P .ı/ M: t u
The theorem follows.
At present it is unknown whether or not AD C :ADC is consistent. The axiom AD is analogous to the axiom V D K. Given this analogy it might seem likely that AD C :ADC is consistent. However as indicated by the next theorem, the situation for AD is rather special. C
Theorem 9.11 (ZF + DCR ). Assume AD and that V D L.P .R//: Suppose that A R. Then V D L.A; R/ or A# exists.
t u
Let Uniformization abbreviate the assumption that for all ARR there exists a function F W R ! R such that for all x 2 R, if .x; y/ 2 A for some y 2 R then .x; F .x// 2 A: AD R , which is a strengthening of AD, is the assertion that every real game of length ! is determined. Uniformization is a trivial consequence of AD R .
9.1 ADC
613
Theorem 9.12 (ZF + DC). The following are equivalent. (1) AD C Uniformization. (2) ADR . (3) AD C Every set of reals is Suslin.
t u
Theorem 9.13 (ZF + DC). Assume AD C Uniformization: Then ADC .
t u
Theorem 9.14 (ZF + AD + DCR ). Define D ¹A R j L.A; R/ ADC º Then: (1) L.; R/ ADC ; (2) Suppose that ¤ P .R/ .i. e. that ADC fails/ then L.; R/ ZF C DC C ADR :
t u
Corollary 9.15. Suppose R# exists and that L.R# / AD: Then
L.R# / ADC :
Proof. This is an immediate corollary to Theorem 9.14 and Theorem 9.11.
t u
Remark 9.16. The consequences of ADC given in Theorem 9.7 are abstractly what is needed to generalize the analysis of L.R/Pmax to the analysis of L.; R/Pmax where P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that L.; R/ ADC :
t u
A fundamental notion is that of a Suslin cardinal first isolated by A. Kechris. Definition 9.17 (AD). A cardinal is a Suslin cardinal if there exists a set A R such that (1) A is -Suslin, (2) A is not ı-Suslin for all ı < .
t u
The Suslin cardinals play an important role in descriptive set theory. We note the following two theorems.
614
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Theorem 9.18 (Steel–Woodin, .ZF C DCR C AD/). Let D sup¹ j is a Suslin cardinalº: Then the set of Suslin cardinals is a closed subset of .
t u
Theorem 9.19 (ADC ). The set of Suslin cardinals is a closed subset of ‚.
t u
The strengthening of Theorem 9.19 over Theorem 9.18 is exactly the difference between AD and ADC . Theorem 9.20. The following are equivalent. (1) ZF C DCR C ADC . (2) ZF C DCR C AD C “The set of Suslin cardinals is closed below ‚”.
t u
Remark 9.21. Assume ZF C DCR C AD. Then it is easily verified that the following are equivalent, (1) Every set is Suslin. (2) The Suslin cardinals are cofinal in ‚. Thus the essential content of Theorem 9.20 is simply that if, assuming ZF C DCR C AD there is a largest Suslin cardinal below ‚, then ADC .
t u
Theorem 9.22 (ADC ). The following are equivalent. (1) AD R fails. (2) There exists S Ord such that L.P .R// D L.S; R/:
t u
Suppose that R is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : It is convenient in many situations to define a sequence h‚˛ W ˛ < ˇi of approximations to ‚. The definition, in the context of ADR and in a slightly different form, is due to Solovay. Definition 9.23 (Solovay). Assume ADC and that V D L.P .R//: The sequence h‚˛ W ˛ i is the shortest sequence such that
9.1 ADC
615
(1) ‚0 is the supremum of the ordinals for which there exists map WR! which is onto and ordinal definable. (2) ‚˛C1 is the supremum of the ordinals for which there exists map W P .‚˛ / ! which is onto and ordinal definable. (3) If ˛ is a nonzero limit ordinal then ‚˛ D sup.¹‚ j < ˛º/. (4) ‚ D ‚.
t u
Within the theory of ADC the ordinal and the sequence h‚˛ W ˛ < i are quite important. One example is provided by the next theorem. Theorem 9.24. Assume ADC and that V D L.P .R//. Then ADR holds if and only if is a limit ordinal and > 0. t u The next theorem, Theorem 9.27, is the original motivation for the definition of h‚˛ W ˛ < i: It is due to Solovay. Recall that HODX is the class of sets which are hereditarily ordinal definable from parameters in X [ ¹X º. It is convenient, but not really necessary, to state Theorem 9.27 using the Wadge prewellordering on P .R/. The definition of h‚˛ W ˛ < i in the context of AD (as opposed to ADC ) uses the Wadge prewellordering. This is Solovay’s original definition of h‚˛ W ˛ < i. Definition 9.25. Assume AD. (1) (Wadge) Suppose that A ! ! and that B ! ! . Then A <w B if: A and ! ! n A are each continuous preimages of B. B is not a continuous preimage of A. (2) (Martin) Suppose A ! ! . The Wadge rank of A, denoted w.A/, is the ordinal rank of the relation t u .¹C R j C <w Aº; <w /: It is a theorem of Wadge that, assuming AD, A <w B if and only if A is a continuous preimage of B and B is not a continuous preimage of A. Define for sets of reals, A and B, A w B, if A is a continuous preimage of B, B is a continuous preimage of A.
616
9 Extensions of L.; R/
The induced equivalence classes, ŒAw , are Wadge equivalence classes. Assuming AD, if A is a continuous preimage of B then either (1) A <w B, or (2) A w B, or (3) A w ! ! n B. Thus the relation <w induces a preordering on P .! ! /, the associated equivalence classes are either of the form ŒAw or the (disjoint) union of the two Wadge equivalence classes ŒAw and Œ! ! n Aw , depending on whether the Wadge equivalence class, ŒAw , is closed under complements. It is a theorem of Martin that the relation <w is wellfounded, again assuming AD. This justifies Definition 9.25(2), the definition of the Wadge rank of a set. It follows that assuming AD, ‚ D rank.P .! ! /; <w /: Remark 9.26. (1) Generally we have not been concerned with the various possible presentations of R. However the notion of continuous reducibility is quite sensitive to this. It is easy to see that in the Euclidean space, . 1; 1/, if A and its complement are both dense, then A is not the continuous preimage of any set B which is nowhere dense. For this reason we shall generally, when defining a pointclass using Wadge ranks, explicitly refer to subsets of ! ! . (2) Suppose that 2 Ord is such that the pointclass D ¹A ! ! j w.A/ < º is closed under continuous images. Then is unambiguous (as a function of ) defined on any space which is homeomorphic to an (uncountable) borel subset of ! ! . Further D ¹A ! ! j ı11 .A/ < º; and so the pointclass is easily defined without reference to Wadge rank.
t u
Theorem 9.27. Assume ADC and that V D L.P .R//. Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.P .R//. Suppose that ˛ < and let ˛ D ¹A ! ! j w.A/ < ‚˛ º: Then (1) ‚L.˛ ;R/ D ‚˛ , (2) ˛ D P .R/ \ HOD˛ .
t u
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
617
Remark 9.28. One route to defining strong forms of ADC is through assertions about . The base theory is ZF C ADC C “V D L.P .R//”: Some examples in increasing (consistency) strength: D ‚ and that ‚ is regular. – This is equivalent to the assertion that ADR holds and that ‚ is a regular cardinal. D ‚ and is Mahlo in HOD. is a limit of regular cardinals ı such that ı D ‚ı . D ‚ and is Mahlo. D ı C 1 and ı is the largest Suslin cardinal. – In this case it is necessarily the case that ı D ‚ı .
t u
By the results of .Sargsyan 2009/ all of these strengthenings are very likely fairly weak as measured by the large cardinal hierarchy. This is sharp contrast to what was previously believed. t u
9.2
The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
This section is devoted to the analysis of L.; R/ŒG where (1) P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC ; (2) G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. In Section 9.2.1 we consider the general case. In Section 9.2.2 we consider the case that L.; R/ ADR C “‚ is regular”: The main result is that L.; R/ŒG Martin’s MaximumCC .c/:
618
9 Extensions of L.; R/
9.2.1 The basic analysis Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC and suppose G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. The basic analysis of L.R/ŒG given in Chapter 4 generalizes to L.; R/ŒG. This analysis requires the appropriate existence theorems for conditions. The requisite existence theorem is a corollary to Theorem 9.30. The proof of Theorem 9.30 follows closely the proof of Theorem 5.36 using Theorem 9.7, Theorem 5.34 and the following generalization of Theorem 5.35. Theorem 9.29. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Suppose a !1 is a countable set. Then in L.; R/: HOD¹aº D HODŒa:
t u
Theorem 9.30. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Suppose A R and A 2 L.; R/. Then for each n 2 ! there exist a countable transitive model M and an ordinal ı 2 M such that the following hold. (1) M ZFC. (2) ı is the nth Woodin cardinal in M . (3) A \ M 2 M and hV!C1 \ M; A \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i. (4) A \ M is ı C -weakly homogeneously Suslin in M .
t u
Theorem 9.31. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Then for each set X R such that X 2 L.; R/ there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that (1) X \ M 2 M, (2) hH.!1 /M ; X \ Mi hH.!1 /; X i, (3) .M; I / is X -iterable.
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
Proof. This is a corollary of Theorem 4.41 and Theorem 9.30.
619 t u
The basic analysis of Pmax now easily generalizes to produce the following theorem. Theorem 9.32. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Suppose G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Then in L.; R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) P .!1 / L.R/ŒG; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) for every set B 2 P .R/ \ L.; R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. (2) and (3) are immediate consequences of (1), Theorem 4.50, and the definitions. (1) follows from an analysis of terms using the technical lemma, Lemma 4.46. The proof of (1) is identical to the proof of Theorem 4.49(1) using Theorem 9.31 to obtain the necessary conditions in G. By (1) it follows that in L.; R/ŒG, P .!2 / [¹L.A; R/ŒG j A 2 º: Thus it suffices to prove that for each A 2 , (4) holds in L.A; R/ŒG. Fix A 2 . By (2), L.A; R/ŒG ZFC: The proof that (4) holds in L.A; R/ŒG is identical to the proof of Lemma 4.52.
t u
Theorem 9.32 generalizes to the all of the variations of Pmax that we have discussed. We state the appropriate version for Bmax . We shall consider the Qmax extensions in Section 9.3. Theorem 9.33. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Suppose G Bmax is L.; R/-generic. Then in L.; R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 / L.R/ŒG; (2) for every set B 2 P .R/ \ L.; R/, the set ¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X .
t u
620
9 Extensions of L.; R/
In the special case that L.; R/ D L.A; R/ for some A R one obtains a little more information. Theorem 9.34. Suppose A R and that L.A; R/ ADC : Suppose G Pmax is L.A; R/-generic. Then in L.A; R/ŒG: (1) L.A; R/ŒG ZFC; (2) IG is a normal saturated ideal in L.A; R/ŒG; (3) suppose S !1 is stationary and f W S ! !3 , then there is a function g 2 L.A; R/ such that ¹˛ 2 S j g.˛/ D f .˛/º is stationary. Proof. By Theorem 9.32, .P .!1 //L.A;R/ŒG L.R/ŒG: Therefore by Corollary 5.7, L.A; R/ŒG AC : This proves (1). (2) follows by adapting the proof that IG is a saturated ideal in L.R/ŒG. (3) follows from Theorem 9.32 and Theorem 3.42. u t Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC and that G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. One can show that L.; R/ŒG AC if and only if L.; R/ D L.S; R/ for some S Ord. Theorem 9.35. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Then L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC:
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
621
Proof. If ¤ P .R/ \ L.; R/ then by Wadge determinacy, L.; R/ D L.A; R/ for some A 2 P .R/ \ L.; R/. In this case L.; R/ŒG ZFC. Therefore we may suppose that D P .R/ \ L.; R/; and so L.; R/ “ V D L.P .R// ”: For each set A 2 let w.A/ denote the Wadge rank of A. Let ‚ denote ‚ as computed in L.; R/. Suppose R 2 L.; R/ŒG is a binary relation. Let 2 L.; R/ be a term for R. Fix an ordinal ˛ such that 2 L˛ .; R/ and such that L˛ .; R/ Powerset C †1 -Replacement: For each < ‚ let Z be the set of a 2 L˛ .; R/ such that a is †1 definable in L˛ .; R/ from .; B/ for some set B 2 with w.B/ < . Since L.; R/ ADC + “ ‚ is regular”; there exists < ‚ such that
Z \ ‚ D
and such that in L.; R/, has cofinality !2 . A key point is that for this choice of , Z †1 L˛ .; R/: Since Pmax H.!1 /,
Z ŒG †1 L˛ .; R/ŒG:
Let N be the transitive collapse of Z . Let N be the image of under the collapsing map. Let RN be the interpretation of N . Therefore N ŒG is the transitive collapse of Z ŒG and RN is the image of R under the transitive collapse of Z ŒG. Fix A 2 n Z . Thus w.A/ and it follows that N 2 L.A; R/. By Theorem 9.34(3), has cofinality !2 in L.A; R/ŒG. It follows that N ŒG!1 N ŒG in L.A; R/ŒG. Let W N ŒG ! L˛ .; R/ŒG be the inverse of the collapsing map. is a †1 elementary embedding with cp./ D D .‚/N D .!3 /N :
622
9 Extensions of L.; R/
L.A; R/ŒG ZFC and so either for some ˇ !1 there is an increasing sequence ha˛ W ˛ < ˇi of elements of RN which is not bounded above or there is an increasing sequence ha˛ W ˛ < !2 i. In the first case, ha˛ W ˛ < ˇi 2 N ŒG and so .ha˛ W ˛ < ˇi/ is a ˇ increasing sequence of elements of R which is not bounded above. In the second case, h.a˛ / W ˛ < !2 i t u is an !2 increasing sequence of elements of R. The proof of Theorem 9.35 also yields a proof of the following generalization which we shall require. Theorem 9.36. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages, S Ord, and that L.S; ; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G Pmax is L.S; ; R/-generic. Then t u L.S; ; R/ŒG !2 -DC:
9.2.2 Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ In Theorem 9.39 we examine the Pmax extension of L.; R/ where is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R + “ ‚ is regular”: By Theorem 9.13, L.; R/ ADC and so the previous results apply. The proof of Theorem 9.39 requires the following theorem. Theorem 9.37. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Then in L.; R/ the following holds. Suppose X is a set of ordinals. Then there is a set of ordinals Y such that: (1) X 2 LŒY ; (2) if t is a countable sequence of reals then there is a transitive model N such that, a) N ZFC, b) LŒY; t N , c) N D LŒY; t \ V where is the least .strongly/ inaccessible cardinal of LŒY; t , d) there is a countable ordinal which is a Woodin cardinal in N . t u Theorem 9.37 is easily proved using Theorem 5.34 and the following generalization of Theorem 9.29
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
623
Theorem 9.38. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Suppose X Ord, X 2 L.; R/, and that a !1 is a countable set. Then in L.; R/: HOD¹X;aº D HOD¹Xº Œa:
t u
The forcing axiom Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ is defined in Definition 2.47. It is the restriction of Martin’s MaximumCC to partial orders of cardinality c. Theorem 9.39. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Suppose H0 Coll.!3 ; H.!3 //L.;R/ŒG0 is L.; R/ŒG0 -generic. Then L.; R/ŒG0 ŒH0 ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/: Proof. By Theorem 9.13,
L.; R/ ADC
and so by Theorem 9.32 the following hold in L.; R/ŒG0 .
(1.1) P .!1 / D [¹P .!1 /M j h.M; I /; ai 2 G0 º. (1.2) P .!1 / L.R/ŒG0 . Further by Theorem 9.35, L.; R/ŒG0 !2 -DC: Therefore P .R/L.;R/ŒG0 ŒH0 D P .R/L.;R/ŒG0 and so it suffices to prove that L.; R/ŒG0 Martin’s MaximumCC .c/: Since is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages and since L.; R/ AD R ; it follows that D P .R/ \ L.; R/: It is convenient to work in L.; R/ and so for the remainder of the proof we assume V D L.; R/. Thus V D L.P .R// and by Theorem 9.12, every set of reals is Suslin.
624
9 Extensions of L.; R/
We must show the following. Suppose that G Pmax is L.P .R//-generic. Suppose that P 2 L.P .R//ŒG is a poset of cardinality !2 and that in L.P .R//ŒG, forcing with P preserves stationary subsets of !1 . Suppose that S D hS W < !1 i is an !1 sequence of terms in L.P .R//ŒGP for stationary subsets of !1 and that D D hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of dense subsets of P . Then there is a filter F P such that (2.1) F 2 L.P .R//ŒG, (2.2) for all ˛ < !1 , D˛ \ F ¤ ;, (2.3) for all < !1 , the set ¹˛ j p ˛ 2 S for some p 2 F º is stationary in L.P .R//ŒG. Let P be a term for P , let S be a term for S and let D be a term for D. We may assume that P is a term for a partial order on !2 so that P is a term for a subset of !2 !2 . We then can assume D is a term for a subset of !1 !2 and that S is a term for a subset of !1 !1 !2 . We fix a reasonable coding of elements of H.!2 / by reals. Suppose A 2 H.!2 /: First code A by a set B !1 in the usual fashion. Let x be a real and let be a formula such that B D ¹˛ j LŒx Œx; ˛º: Let y 2 R code the pair .x # ; /. The real y is a code of A.
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
625
Let (3.1) P be the set of x such that x codes .p; ˛; ˇ/ and a) p 2 Pmax , b) .˛; ˇ/ 2 !2 !2 , c) p “.˛; ˇ/ 2 P ”; (3.2) S be the set of x such that x codes .p; ; ˛; ˇ/ and a) .; ˛; ˇ/ 2 !1 !1 !2 , b) p 2 Pmax , c) p “.; ˛; ˇ/ 2 S ”; (3.3) let D be the set of x such that x codes .p; ˛; ˇ/ and a) .˛; ˇ/ 2 !1 !2 , b) p 2 Pmax , c) p “.˛; ˇ/ 2 D ”. Suppose that M is a transitive model of ZF. Suppose that z 2 P \ M and z codes .p; ˛; ˇ/. Then by a simple absoluteness argument M decodes z as a triple .p; ˛ ; ˇ / where ˛ ; ˇ < !2M . If !1M D !1 then ˛ D ˛ and ˇ D ˇ. Similarly suppose that z 2 S \ M and z codes .p; ; ˛; ˇ/. Then M decodes z as a 4-tuple .p; ; ˛; ˇ / where < !1M , ˛ < !1M and ˇ < !2M . Again if !1M D !1 then ˇ D ˇ. Now suppose M is a transitive model of ZF containing !1 so that Pmax \ .H.!1 //M D .Pmax /M : Assume that for all x 2 M \ R, x 2 M . Thus Pmax is nontrivial in M . Suppose that .P S D / \ M 2 M: Then P \ M defines in M a term PM for a subset of !2M !2M . Similarly D \ M defines in M a term for a subset of !1M !2M and S \ M defines in M a term for a subset of !1M !1M !2M . Let SM be the term given by S \ M and let DM be the term given by D \ M . These are terms in the forcing language defined in M for Pmax \ M . If G Pmax \ M is a filter (not necessarily generic) then PM defines a subset of !2M !2M . Similarly DM defines from G a subset of !1M !2M and SM defines from G a subset of !1M !1M !2M . We shall say these are the sets defined by P \ M and G, defined by D \ M and G, and defined by S \ M and G, respectively.
626
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Let T0 be a tree whose projection is the set of reals which code elements of P S D : Let T1 be a tree which projects to the complement of the projection of T0 . We shall use the following. Suppose M is a transitive model of ZF and that T0 ; T1 2 M . Suppose j W M ! M is an elementary embedding of M into a transitive model M . Then the trees T0 and j.T0 / have the same projection in V . By Theorem 9.37 there exists a set of ordinals S such that: (4.1) .T0 ; T1 / 2 LŒS ; (4.2) if t is a countable sequence of reals then there is a transitive model N such that, a) N ZFC, b) LŒS; t N , c) N D LŒS; t \ V where is the least (strongly) inaccessible cardinal of LŒS; t , d) there is a countable ordinal which is a Woodin cardinal in N . Let be the club measure on P!1 .R/. AD R implies is a measure. The normality condition satisfied by is the following. Suppose F W P!1 .R/ ! P!1 .R/ and ¹ j F . / and F . / ¤ ;º 2 : Then there exists x 2 R such that ¹ j x 2 F . /º 2 . Let S be the ultrapower of S by , let T0 be the ultrapower of T0 by and let T1 be the ultrapower of T1 by . By the remarks above the trees T0 ; T0 have the same projection. Further T0 2 LŒS and so ¹P ; S ; D º 2 L.S ; R/: Suppose G Pmax is L.S ; R/-generic. Then in L.S ; R/ŒG: (5.1) ZFC holds; (5.2) the axiom ./ holds; (5.3) P defines a partial order on !2 and forcing with this partial order preserves stationary subsets of !1 ; (5.4) S defines an !1 sequence of terms for stationary subsets of !1 ; (5.5) D defines an !1 sequence of dense subsets of the partial order given by P . The normality condition satisfied by shows Y L.S; /= L.S ; R/ D 2P!1 .R/
and that Łos’ lemma applies. Thus there is a countable set R such that D L.S; / \ R
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
627
and such that if G Pmax \ L.S; / is L.S; /-generic then in L.S; /ŒG: (6.1) ZFC holds; (6.2) the axiom ./ holds; (6.3) P \ L.S; / defines a partial order on !2 and forcing with this partial order preserves stationary subsets of !1 ; (6.4) S \ L.S; / defines an !1 sequence of terms for stationary subsets of !1 ; (6.5) D \ L.S; / defines an !1 sequence of dense subsets of the partial order given by P . Fix such a countable set and fix G Pmax \ L.S; / that is L.S; /-generic. Let t 2 L.S; /ŒG be an enumeration of the reals. Thus L.S; /ŒG D LŒS; t and so there is a transitive inner model N and a countable ordinal ı such that ı is a Woodin cardinal in N , LŒS; t N and N D LŒS; t \ V where is the least strongly inaccessible cardinal of LŒS; t . Fix ı and N . Let aG be the subset of the !1 of L.S; /ŒG defined by G. We are using the notation from Definition 4.44. Let PG !2N !2N be the set in L.S; /ŒG defined by P \ L.S; / and G. Similarly let SG !1N !1N !2N and let DG !1N !2N be the sets in L.S; /ŒG defined by G and S , and by G and D . By the agreement between N and L.S; /ŒG we have, (7.1) PG is a partial order such that .INS /N D .INS /N (7.2) for each < !1N , defines a term in N (7.3) for each ˛ < !1N , is dense in PG .
PG
\ N;
¹.˛; ˇ/ j .; ˛; ˇ/ 2 SG º PG
for a stationary subset of !1N , ¹ˇ j .˛; ˇ/ 2 DG º
9 Extensions of L.; R/
628
Let H P be N -generic and let g Coll.!1N ; <ı/ be N ŒH -generic where !1N is the ordinal !1 as computed in N . Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal in N above ı. Thus is a countable ordinal in V . We now come to the main points. By (7.1) .INS /N D .INS /N ŒH \ N D .INS /N ŒH Œg \ N: Further by Theorem 2.61, .INS /N ŒH Œg is presaturated in N ŒH Œg. Let N ŒH ŒgŒh be a ccc extension of N ŒH Œg in which MA holds and in which is still strongly inaccessible (i. e. use a small poset). Let I D .INS /N ŒH ŒgŒh : Standard arguments show that the ideal I is precipitous in N ŒH ŒgŒh. N ŒH ŒgŒh contains the ordinals and so any countable iteration of .N ŒH ŒgŒh; I / is wellfounded. Suppose .N1 ; I1 / is an iterate of .N ŒH ŒgŒh; I / and let j W N ŒH ŒgŒh ! N1 be the corresponding elementary embedding. .T0 ; T1 / 2 N ŒH ŒgŒh and so it follows that X \ N1 D j.X \ N ŒH ŒgŒh/ where
X D P S D :
Further: (8.1) j.G/ is a filter in Pmax \ N1 ; (8.2) j.PG / is the set of .˛; ˇ/ 2 !2N1 !2N1 such that for some p 2 j.G/, p “.˛; ˇ/ 2 P ”I (8.3) j.SG / is the set of .; ˛; ˇ/ 2 !1N !1N1 !2N1 such that for some p 2 j.G/, p “.; ˛; ˇ/ 2 S ”I (8.4) j.DG / is the set of .˛; ˇ/ 2 !1N1 !2N1 such that for some p 2 j.G/, p “.˛; ˇ/ 2 D ”I (8.5) j.H / is a filter in j.PG /; (8.6) for each < !1N1 , ¹˛ < !1N1 j .; ˛; ˇ/ 2 j.SG / for some ˇ 2 H º is a stationary set in N1 ; (8.7) for each ˛ < !1N1 , j.H / \ ¹ˇ < !2N1 j .˛; ˇ/ 2 DG º ¤ ;:
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
629
Let M D .N ŒH ŒgŒh/ \ V . Thus M is a countable transitive set and M ZFC C MA!1 : Iterations of .M; I / are rank initial segments of iterations of .N ŒH ŒgŒh; I /; this is by Lemma 4.4. By Lemma 4.5, .N ŒH ŒgŒh; I / is iterable and so .M; I / is iterable. Note that since the axiom ./ holds in N it follows that in N , !1 D !1LŒaG ;x for some x 2 R. Since .M; I / is iterable, h.M; I /; aG i 2 Pmax . Suppose that h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 G: There is an iteration (necessarily unique), j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / in M such that j.a0 / D aG and I0 D M \ I . Thus h.M; I /; aG i < p for all p 2 G. Iterations of .M; I / lift iterations of .N ŒH ŒgŒh; I / and so (8.1)–(8.7) hold for countable iterations of .M; I /. We claim that h.M; I /; aG i forces that there is a D -generic filter on P which interprets S as an !1 sequence of stationary sets. This is now straightforward to verify. Suppose G Pmax is L.P .R//-generic and that h.M; I /; aG i 2 G. Let j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the iteration such that j.aG / D AG where AG is the subset of !1 defined by the generic G . Let PG be the partial order (on !2 ) defined by P and G , let SG !1 !1 !2 be the set defined by S and G , and let DG !1 !2 be the set defined by D and G . Finally j.G/ G and I D .INS /L.R/ŒG \ M : Therefore: (9.1) j.PG / PG ; (9.2) j.SG / SG ; (9.3) j.DG / DG ; (9.4) j.H / is a filter in j.PG /; (9.5) For each ˛ < !1 , j.H / \ ¹ˇ < !2 j .˛; ˇ/ 2 j.DG /º ¤ ;I (9.6) For each < !1 , ¹˛ < !1 j .; ˛; ˇ/ 2 j.SG / for some ˇ 2 j.H /º is a stationary subset of !1 .
630
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Thus j.H / is an DG -generic filter on PG which interprets SG as an !1 sequence stationary sets. Finally we can choose M and G such that G contains any given condition. t u The following is an immediate corollary of the proof of Theorem 9.39; the forcing axiom, Martin’s Maximum ZF .c/, is defined in Definition 2.51. Corollary 9.40. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R : Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC C Martin’s Maximum ZF .c/:
t u
The conclusion of Corollary 9.40 follows from significantly weaker assumptions, see Theorem 9.59. These results suggest that perhaps one does not need the full strength of L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”; in order to prove that L.; R/Pmax Martin’s Maximum.c/: However in Section 9.5 we shall sketch the proof of the following theorem. Theorem 9.41. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular” and such that
L.; R/Pmax Martin’s Maximum.c/:
Then L.; R/ AD R :
t u
Combining the arguments for Theorem 9.39 and for Theorem 7.59 one obtains the following generalization of Theorem 7.59. This also requires Theorem 9.33. Recall that BCFACC .c/ denotes the restriction of BCFACC to posets of size c. Theorem 9.42. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADR C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G0 Bmax is L.; R/-generic. Suppose H0 Coll.!3 ; H.!3 //L.;R/ŒG0 is L.; R/ŒG0 -generic. Then L.; R/ŒG0 ŒH0 ZFC C BCFACC .c/:
t u
9.2 The Pmax -extension of L.; R/
631
As a corollary to Theorem 9.39 and Theorem 9.42 we obtain the following consistency result. Theorem 9.43. Assume ZF C ADR C “ ‚ is regular” is consistent. Then the following are consistent. (1) ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/. (2) ZFC C Borel Conjecture C BCFACC .c/.
t u
Another corollary of Theorem 9.39 concerns Martin’s Maximum and the determinacy of sets of reals which are ordinal definable. We first consider the closely related problem of the relationship between Martin’s Maximum and quasi-homogeneous ideals. The proof of Theorem 5.67 easily generalizes to prove the following theorem. Theorem 9.44. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Then L.; R/ŒG :
t u
We obtain as a corollary the consistency Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ with the existence of a quasi-homogeneous saturated ideal. Corollary 9.45. Assume ZF C ADR C “ ‚ is regular” is consistent. Then
ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/
C “The nonstationary ideal is quasi-homogeneous” t u
is consistent. The generic extension L.; R/ŒG0 ŒH0
indicated in Theorem 9.39 is a homogeneous forcing extension of L.; R/ and so the following theorem is an immediate corollary. Theorem 9.46. Assume ZF C ADR C “ ‚ is regular” is consistent. Then
ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/
C “Every set of reals which is ordinal definable from a real is determined” is consistent.
t u
632
9 Extensions of L.; R/
There is an interesting question. Question. Assume Martin’s Maximum. reals?
Is there a definable wellordering of the t u
In .Woodin 2010b/ a strong version of the following conjecture is discussed. A consequence of either conjecture is that Martin’s Maximum does in fact imply the existence of a definable wellordering of the reals, see Remark 9.47(4) below. Conjecture (ZFC). There is a regular cardinal for which there is a definable partition of ¹˛ j ˛ < and cof.˛/ D !º t u
into infinitely many stationary sets.
Remark 9.47. (1) By the previous theorem Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ does not imply there is a definable wellordering of the reals. (2) Suppose P is a partial order such that Martin’s Maximum holds in V P . Suppose forcing with P adds a new subset to !1 . Then P is not homogeneous. This is implicit in .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/. This rules out an obvious approach to producing a model of Martin’s Maximum with no definable wellordering of the reals. (3) Martin’s Maximum + Conjecture implies there is a definable wellordering of the reals. This is by the results of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/. In fact, assuming Martin’s Maximum, the following are equivalent: There is a definable wellordering of the reals. There is a definable partition of ¹˛ j ˛ < !2 and cof.˛/ D !º into infinitely many stationary sets. There is a definable partition of !1 into infinitely many stationary sets. There is a definable !1 -sequence of distinct reals. (4) Todorcevic has proved that assuming the Proper Forcing Axiom then the following are equivalent: There is a definable wellordering of the reals. There is a definable increasing sequence hf˛ W ˛ < !2 i !
in the partial order, .! ;
9.3 The Qmax -extension of L.; R/
633
(5) If the conjecture fails in V then every (uncountable) regular cardinal is measurable in HOD. Thus the consistency strength of the failure of the conjecture is very likely beyond that of the existence of a supercompact cardinal. (6) It looks even harder to obtain the failure of the conjecture in the presence of a supercompact cardinal. Therefore modulo finding a new consistency proof for Martin’s Maximum, the problem of finding a model of Martin’s Maximum in which the conjecture fails looks quite hard. t u
9.3
The Qmax -extension of L.; R/
We examine the Qmax -extension of L.; R/ where P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : As a corollary to Lemma 5.23 and Theorem 9.30 we obtain the following generalization of Theorem 6.62. Theorem 9.48. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Suppose A R and A 2 L.; R/. Then for each n 2 !, there exists .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / such that (1) .M; I/ is strongly A-iterable, (2) the Woodin cardinal of M associated to I is the nth Woodin cardinal of M .
t u
Theorem 9.49. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Suppose A R and A 2 L.; R/. Then there is a condition .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax such that (1) A \ M0 2 M0 , (2) hH.!1 /M0 ; A \ M0 i hH.!1 /; Ai, (3) hMk W k < !i is A-iterable. Proof. This is an immediate by Theorem 6.64 and Theorem 9.48
t u
634
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Using Theorem 9.49, the analysis of L.R/Qmax easily generalizes to the case of L.; R/Qmax where is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Theorem 9.50. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G Qmax is L.; R/-generic. Then L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC and in L.; R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 / L.R/ŒG; (2) for every set B 2 P .R/ \ L.; R/, the set ¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X .
t u
Because of the equivalence of Qmax and Qmax in L.R/ as forcing notions, Theorem 9.50 immediately gives the following version for Qmax -extensions. Theorem 9.51. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G Qmax is L.; R/-generic. Then L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC and in L.; R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 / L.R/ŒG; (2) for every set B 2 P .R/ \ L.; R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X .
t u
As a corollary to Theorem 9.51 we obtain the following generalization of Theorem 6.78. Theorem 9.52. Suppose A R and that L.A; R/ ADC : Suppose G Qmax is L.A; R/-generic. Then in L.A; R/ŒG the following holds. Suppose > !2 , L .A; R/ŒG ZFC ;
9.3 The Qmax -extension of L.; R/
635
and that L .A; R/ †1 L.A; R/: Suppose X L .A; R/ŒG is a countable elementary substructure with G 2 X . Let MX be the transitive collapse of Y and let IX D .INS /MX : Then for each B R such that B 2 X \ L.A; R/, .MX ; IX / is B-iterable. Proof. The proof is essentially the same as that of Theorem 6.78, using Theorem 9.51 in place of Theorem 6.77. t u Another corollary of Theorem 9.51 generalizes Theorem 6.81. Theorem 9.53. Suppose A R and that L.A; R/ ADC : Suppose G Qmax is L.A; R/-generic. Then in L.A; R/ŒG the following hold. (1) L.A; R/ ZFC. (2) IG D INS and IG is is an !1 -dense ideal. (3) Suppose S !1 is stationary and f W S ! Ord: Then there exists g 2 L.A; R/ such that ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ D g.˛/º is stationary. Proof. By Theorem 9.51, .P .!1 //L.A;R/ŒG L.R/ŒG: Therefore by Theorem 6.81, L.A; R/ŒG AC ; IG D INS , and IG is a normal !1 -dense ideal in L.A; R/ŒG. This proves (1) and (2). (3) follows from Theorem 9.51 and Theorem 3.42, by reducing to the case that the t u range of f is bounded in ‚L.A;R/ , cf. the proof of Lemma 6.79(3). Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that
L.; R/ ADC C “‚ is regular”:
We generalize Theorem 9.39, showing that if G Qmax is L.; R/-generic, then in L.; R/ŒG a fragment of Martin’s Maximum holds. As usual this requires some preliminary definitions.
636
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Let Z.˘.!1
.Z.˘.!1
t u
Remark 9.55. As formulated, FA.˘.!1
9.4 Chang’s Conjecture
9.4
637
Chang’s Conjecture
There is a curious metamathematical possibility. Perhaps there is an interesting combinatorial statement whose truth in L.R/Pmax cannot be proved just assuming L.R/ AD; but can be proved from a stronger hypothesis. We recall the statement of Chang’s Conjecture. Definition 9.56. Chang’s Conjecture: The set ¹X !2 j ordertype.X / D !1 º t u
is stationary in P .!2 /. D. Seabold has proved the following theorem.
Theorem 9.57 (Seabold). Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Then L.; R/ŒG Chang’s Conjecture:
t u
A corollary of Seabold’s theorem is that from suitable determinacy hypotheses one obtains that L.R/Pmax Chang’s Conjecture: The proof can be refined to establish the following theorem which identifies a sufficient condition which is first order in L.R/. Theorem 9.58. Suppose L.R/ AD and that there exists a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / \ R D and HODL.R/ . / AD C DC: Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG Chang’s Conjecture: The proofs adapt to prove the following improvement of Corollary 9.40.
t u
638
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Theorem 9.59. Suppose L.R/ AD and that there exists a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / \ R D and HODL.R/ . / AD C DC: Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC C Martin’s Maximum ZF .c/:
t u
Our goal in this section is to sketch the proof of the generalization of Theorem 9.58 to the Qmax -extension; Theorem 9.60. Suppose L.R/ AD and that there exists a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / \ R D and HODL.R/ . / AD C DC: Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG Chang’s Conjecture:
t u
The following theorem, in conjunction with Theorem 6.149, shows that L.R/Qmax Chang’s Conjecture cannot be proved just assuming L.R/ AD: Pmax
The analogous question for L.R/
is open.
Theorem 9.61. Suppose ZFC C “ There is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 which is !1 -dense” C Chang’s Conjecture is consistent. Then ZFC C “ There is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 which is !1 -dense” C “ There are infinitely many Woodin cardinals” is consistent.
t u
Steel has generalized the analysis of scales in L.R/ to iterable Mitchell–Steel modQ i. e. Mitchell–Steel models relativized to R. With this machinels of the form L.R; E/; ery the method of the core model induction used to prove Theorem 6.149 on page 425, generalizes to prove the following theorem.
9.4 Chang’s Conjecture
639
Theorem 9.62. Suppose there is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 which is !1 -dense and that Chang’s Conjecture holds. Then there exists a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / AD C DC:
t u
Corollary 9.63. Suppose there is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 which is !1 -dense and that Chang’s Conjecture holds. Then L.R/Qmax Chang’s Conjecture: Remark 9.64.
t u
(1) The hypothesis of Theorem 9.58 is equiconsistent with ZFC C “There are ! C ! many Woodin cardinals”:
Thus Theorem 9.62 implies that ZFC C “There are ! C ! many Woodin cardinals” is equiconsistent with ZFC C “There is a normal, uniform, ideal on !1 which is !1 -dense” C Chang’s Conjecture: (2) We do not know if Theorem 9.62 can be generalized to ./. More precisely: Suppose that ./ and Chang’s Conjecture hold. Is there a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / AD C DC‹ u t We need a technical lemma which is a variant of Theorem 9.52. Lemma 9.65. Suppose A R and that L.A; R/ ADC : Suppose G Qmax is L.A; R/-generic. Then in L.A; R/ŒG the following holds. Suppose > !2 , L .A; R/ŒG ZFC ; and that L .A; R/ †2 L.A; R/: Then for each a 2 L .A; R/ŒG there exists a countable elementary substructure, X L .A; R/ŒG such that ¹fG ; a; Aº X and such that the following hold: (1) h.MX ; IX /; fX i 2 G; (2) for all ˛ 2 C , fG .˛/ is L.MX ; fG j˛/-generic for Coll.!; ˛/;
640
9 Extensions of L.; R/
where MX is the transitive collapse of X , fX is the image of fG under the collapsing map, IX D .INS /MX ; and where C is the critical sequence of the iteration j W .MX ; IX / ! .MX ; IX / such that j.fX / D fG . Proof. Fix p0 2 G and fix a term 2 L .A; R/ for a. We work in L.A; R/. Fix W R ! L .A; R/ such that ŒR L .A; R/ and such that ¹; Aº ŒR. Let x0 2 R be such that .x0 / D and let x1 be such that .x1 / D A. Let B R code the set of pairs .ha0 ; : : : ; an i; .z0 ; : : : ; zn // such that ha0 ; : : : ; an i 2 R
, is a formula and
L .A; R/ Œ.a0 /; : : : ; .an /: Let T be the theory of L .A; R/; i. e. a reasonable fragment of ZF C AD C DC C “V D L.A; R/”
containing ZFC . By Lemma 9.52 there exists a countable transitive set N and a filter H QN max such that (1.1) N T, (1.2) ¹p0 ; x0 ; x1 º N , (1.3) p0 2 H , (1.4) H is N -generic, (1.5) B \ N 2 N and hH.!1 /N ; B \ N; 2i hH.!1 /; B; 2i, (1.6) .N ŒH ; .INS /N ŒH / is B-iterable. Thus N ŒH /; f i 2 Qmax h.N ŒH ; INS
and N ŒH /; f i < p0 h.N ŒH ; INS
9.4 Chang’s Conjecture
where
641
f D fHN ŒH D [¹f1 j h.M1 ; I1 /; f1 i 2 H º:
By genericity we can suppose that N ŒH h.N ŒH ; INS /; f i 2 G
and that for all ˛ 2 D, fG .˛/ is L.N ŒH ; fG j˛/-generic for Coll.!; ˛/ where D is the critical sequence of the iteration N ŒH j W .N ŒH ; INS / ! .N ; I /
such that j .f / D fG . N ŒH Since h.N ŒH ; INS /; f i 2 G, H G. Let X L .A; R/ŒG be the set of b 2 L .A; R/ŒG such that b is definable in L .A; R/ŒG from parameters in ŒR \ N [ ¹fG º. Thus X L .A; R/ŒG. Further a 2 X since x0 2 N . The key points are that H G and hH.!1 /N ; B \ N; 2i hH.!1 /; B; 2i; for these imply that X \ L .A; R/ D ŒR \ N : Let MX be the transitive collapse of X , let FX be the image of fG under the collapsing map and let IX D .INS /MX . Thus (2.1) .H.!2 //MX D H.!2 /N ŒH , (2.2) IX D .INS /N ŒH , (2.3) f D fX . Therefore by Theorem 9.52, .MX ; IX / is iterable, and so h.MX ; IX /; fX i 2 Qmax : However, N ŒH /; f i 2 G: h.N ŒH ; INS N ŒH /; f i 2 G induces an iteration witTherefore the iteration witnessing h.N ŒH ; INS nessing h.MX ; IX /; fX i 2 G
and this iteration has the same critical sequence, D. Therefore since MX 2 N ŒH , it follows that for all ˛ 2 D, fG .˛/ is t u L.MX ; fG j˛/-generic for Coll.!; ˛/.
642
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Lemma 9.66. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular ”: Suppose G Qmax is L.; R/-generic. Then in L.; R/ŒG the following holds. Suppose N is a transitive set such that N ZFC and such that N !1 N: There exists a function h W !1 ! N such that for all limit ordinals 0 < < !1 , (1) hŒ N , (2) hŒ, (3) fG ./ fG . / is N -generic for Coll.!; fG .// Coll.!; fG . // N
where N is the transitive collapse of hŒ and D !2 . Proof. By Theorem 9.51, L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC: Therefore there exists ZN such that Z Z and such that jZj D !2 . Let NZ be the transitive collapse of Z. Thus we can suppose, by replacing N by NZ if necessary, that jN j D !2 . Fix a bijection F W !2 ! N: !1
Thus for some A R with A 2 L.; R/, .F; N / 2 L.A; R/ŒG: Fix 2 Ord such that
L .A; R/ ZFC
and such that L .A; R/ †2 L.A; R/: By Lemma 9.65 there exists a countable elementary substructure X L .A; R/ŒG such that ¹A; F; N; fG º X and such that the following hold:
9.4 Chang’s Conjecture
643
(1.1) h.MX ; IX /; fX i 2 G; (1.2) for all ˛ 2 C , fG .˛/ is L.MX ; fG j˛/-generic for Coll.!; ˛/; where MX is the transitive collapse of X , fX is the image of fG under the collapsing map, IX D .INS /MX ; and where C is the critical sequence of the iteration j W .MX ; IX / ! .MX ; IX / such that j.fX / D fG . Let hM˛ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i be the iteration of .MX ; IX / such that j0;!1 .fX / D fG . Define a sequence hX˛ W ˛ !1 i of countable elementary substructures by induction on ˛ such that (2.1) X0 D X , (2.2) X˛C1 D ¹f .X˛ \ !1 / j f 2 X˛ º, (2.3) if ˇ !1 is a limit ordinal then Xˇ D [¹X˛ j ˛ < ˇº: For each ˛ !1 let M˛ be the transitive collapse of X˛ , let ˛ W M˛ ! X˛ be the inverse of the collapsing map, and let
G˛ D ¹a 2 .P .!1 //M˛ j X˛ \ !1 2 ˛ .a/º: Thus G˛ is simply the image of ¹S 2 P .!1 / \ X˛ j X˛ \ !1 2 S º in the transitive collapse of X˛ . For each ˛ < ˇ !1 let
j˛;ˇ W M˛ ! Mˇ
be the elementary embedding such that for all a 2 M˛ , .a//: ˛ .a/ D ˇ .j˛;ˇ
Thus
hM˛ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i
is an iteration of .MX ; IX / such that j0;! .fX / D fG . 1 Therefore hM˛ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i D hM˛ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ !1 i:
9 Extensions of L.; R/
644
For each !1 let
NQ D X \ N and let N be the transitive collapse of NQ . Thus N 2 M and NQ D .N /: Further for each !1 ,
N D j0; .N0 /: M
M
Thus for each < !1 , fG .!1 / is L.M0 ; fG j!1 /-generic. However for each < !1 , M
hM˛ ; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i 2 L.M0 ; fG j!1 / MC1
and so for each < !1 , fG .!1
/ is L.N /-generic. Further
MC1
!1
M
D !2
N
D !2 :
Let h W !1 ! N be such that for all limit ordinals < !1 , hŒ D NQ : t u
The function h is as desired. The application of Lemma 9.66 requires the following additional lemma. Lemma 9.67. Suppose L.R/ AD and that R is a countable set such that HODL.R/ . / \ R D and HODL.R/ . / ZF C AD C DC Then
HODL.R/ . / ADC :
Theorem 9.68. Suppose L.R/ AD and that there exists a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / \ R D and HODL.R/ . / AD C DC: Suppose G Qmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG Chang’s Conjecture:
t u
9.4 Chang’s Conjecture
645
Proof. We work in L.R/ŒG. Fix F W !2
!2
˛ < !2 and in L.R/, p Qmax .s/ D ˛:
If Chang’s Conjecture fails in L.R/ŒG then there is a function F and a corresponding term such that F is a counterexample and such that A is 21 in L.R/. This follows by the usual reflection arguments and the fact that the pointclass .†21 /L.R/ has the scale property, Theorem 2.3. Again by the scale property of .†21 /L.R/ there must exist a condition p0 2 Qmax \ HODL.R/ such that p0 forces that is a term for a counterexample to Chang’s Conjecture. Fix a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / \ R D
9 Extensions of L.; R/
646 and
HODL.R/ . / ZF C AD C DC: By Lemma 9.67, we can suppose that HODL.R/ . / ADC : Let S Ord be a set such that LŒS D HODL.R/ : It is easy to see that such a set S exists, essentially by Vopenka’s argument. In fact one can choose S to be a subset of ‚L.R/ . Let N D L.S; / and let D P . / \ N: Thus
L.; / ADC C “ ‚ is regular”
and D R \ L.; /: Let g0 Qmax \ L.; / be L.; /-generic such that p0 2 g0 and let f0 D [¹f j h.M; I /; f i 2 g0 º: Thus g0 is N -generic and P . / \ N Œg0 D P . / \ L.; /Œg0 : Therefore by Theorem 6.81 and Theorem 9.51, the following hold in N Œg0 . (1.1) AC . (1.2) The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. (1.3) f0 witnesses ˘++ .!1
9.4 Chang’s Conjecture
647
By Theorem 5.35, L.R/ HOD¹a D HODL.R/ Œa0 D LŒS; a0 D N Œg0 : 0º
By Theorem 5.34, there exists x0 2 R such that for all x 2 R, if x0 2 LŒS; a0 ; x then
!2LŒS;a0 ;x
is a Woodin cardinal in
0 ;x : HODLŒS;a ¹S;a0 º
However for each < !1 , there exists x1 2 R such that for all x 2 R, if x1 2 LŒS; a0 ; x then 0 ;x HODL.R/ LŒS; a0 ; P ./ \ HODLŒS;a ¹S;a0 º ¹S;a0 º
since HODL.R/ D LŒS . Therefore there exist a transitive inner model M , containing the ordinals, and ı0 < !1 such that M ZFC; ¹S; a0 º M ,
P .!3N Œg0 / \ N Œg0 D P .!3N Œg0 / \ M;
and such that ı0 is a Woodin cardinal in M . Thus (1.1)–(1.4) hold in M . Let M0 D M \ V where is the least ordinal such that > ı0 and such that is strongly inaccessible in M . Since M ZFC and since M L.R/, exists. M0 . Since Ord M , the structure .M0 ; I0 / is iterable where I0 D INS Since (1.1)–(1.4) hold in M , (1.1)–(1.4) hold in M0 . Therefore h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 Qmax and it follows that h.M0 ; g0 /; f0 i < p for all p 2 g0 . By Lemma 6.23 there exists an iteration j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / such that ¹˛ < !1 j j.f0 /.˛/ D fG .˛/º contains a club in !1 . By Theorem 6.34 there is an L.R/-generic filter G Qmax such that fG D fG and such that
L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒG:
9 Extensions of L.; R/
648
Thus it follows that
h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 G :
We now come the key claim, which is a consequence of Lemma 9.66. Let P0 be the partial order given by the stationary tower .P<ı0 /M and let J0 be the associated directed system of ideals. Suppose h0 Coll.!; !1M / is M -generic and that h Coll.!; !2M / is M Œh0 generic. Then there exists a generic filter G0 P0 , such that (2.1) !2M 2 G0 , (2.2) h0 is M1 -generic, (2.3) j.f0 /.!2M / D h where
j W M1 ! M1 M1 Œh0
is the generic elementary embedding corresponding to the generic ultrapower deterM1 . M1 is the generic ultrapower of M determined by G0 . Thus mined by h0 , f0 and INS M1 M ŒG0 and there is a generic elementary embedding j1 W M ! M1 M ŒG0 : Since 2 G0 , the critical point of j1 is !2M and so (1.1)–(1.4) hold in M1 . The verification of this claim is a routine from the definitions, Lemma 9.66 ensures that the requisite set belongs to P0 ; i. e. that this set is stationary. By the choice of and since M0 D V \ M , the claim above holds for M0 . By the definability of forcing, this claim is a first order property of M0 . Again since Ord M , the structure .M0 ; J0 / is iterable where the definition of iterability is the obvious generalization of Definition 5.18. There is a key difference between iterations of .M0 ; J0 / and previously considered iterations. The critical point need not be !1M0 . This is a central point of what follows. Let h0 D fG .!1M0 /. Since !2M
h.M0 ; I0 /; f0 i 2 G ; h0 Coll.!; !1M / and h0 is M0 -generic. Therefore there exists an iteration h.Mˇ ; Jˇ /; G˛ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i such that for all ˇ < !1 , Mˇ
(3.1) !2
2 Gˇ ,
(3.2) h0 is Mˇ C1 -generic,
9.4 Chang’s Conjecture
649
(3.3) if fG ./ is Mˇ C1 Œh0 -generic then j.f0 /./ D fG ./ Mˇ
where D !2
and j W Mˇ C1 ! MˇC1 Mˇ C1 Œh0 M C1
is the generic elementary embedding corresponding to f0 ; INS ˇ
, and h0 .
We note that by (3.1), for all ˛ < ˇ < !1 , the critical point of j˛;ˇ is !2M˛ and so for all ˇ < !1 , j0;ˇ .f0 / D f0 . Let j0 W .M0 ; I0 / ! .MQ 0 ; IQ0 / be the limit embedding of the iteration. Thus Q !2M0 D !1 since
j0 .!2M0 / D !1 :
We come to the final points. First h0 is MQ 0 -generic. Let k0 W MQ 0 ! MQ 0 MQ 0 Œh0 Q
M0 , and h0 . be the generic elementary embedding corresponding to f0 ; INS
¹˛ < !1 j k0 .f0 /.˛/ D fG .˛/º contains a club in !1 . By Theorem 6.34, there is an L.R/-generic filter G Qmax , such that L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒG; and such that k0 .f0 / D fG . We now come the second point. Note f0 D [¹f j h.M; I /; f i 2 j0 .g0 /º since f0 D [¹f j h.M; I /; f i 2 g0 º and so k0 .f0 / D [¹f j h.M; I /; f i 2 k0 ı j0 .g0 /º: Therefore, this is the second point, g0 j0 .g0 / k0 ı j0 .g0 / G : Let
F W !2
650
9 Extensions of L.; R/
be the interpretation of by G . Since g0 G , p0 2 G . Therefore F is a counterexample to Chang’s Conjecture. Let 0 be the interpretation of in M0 . Define F0 W !2M0 ! !2M0 by F0 .s/ D ˛ if for some x 2 R \ M0 , 0 .x/ D .p; s; ˛/ for some p 2 g0 . By the definition of M0 , R \ M0 D D R \ HODL.R/ Œ : Therefore since A is 21 , A \ M0 2 M0 and further hV!C1 \ L.; /; A \ ; 2i hV!C1 ; A ; 2i: Therefore since g0 is L.; /-generic, this definition of F0 does yield a function. Let Q Q Z D k0 Œ!2M0 D ¹k0 .˛/ j ˛ < !2M0 º: Q
Since !2M0 D !1 , Z has ordertype !1 . Further by elementarity, k0 .j0 .F0 //ŒZ
By the choice of and since !1 D !1 0 , k0 ı j0 .0 / D j.R \ MQ 0 /: The final point is that k0 ı j0 .A \ M0 / D A \ MQ 0 and so since k0 ı j0 .g0 / G , k0 ı j0 .F0 / F . But then Z witnesses that F is not a counterexample to Chang’s Conjecture, a contradiction. We verify this final point which amounts to a certain form of A -iterability. Since M0 D V \ M it follows that the elementary embedding j0 lifts to define an elementary embedding j W M ! MQ L.R/: It follows that
MQ 0 D j.M0 / D Vj. / \ MQ :
Therefore the elementary embedding k0 lifts to define an elementary embedding k W MQ ! MQ MQ Œh0 : We must show that k ı j.A \ M / D A \ MQ . The set A is 21 is L.R/. Therefore there exist trees T0 2 HODL.R/ and T1 2 HODL.R/ such that A D pŒT0 and R n A D pŒT1 :
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
651
Since HODL.R/ M , T0 2 M and T1 2 M . Thus k ı j.A \ M / D pŒk ı j.T0 / \ MQ : Clearly pŒT0 pŒk ı j.T0 / and pŒT1 pŒk ı j.T1 /: However by absoluteness pŒk ı j.T0 / \ pŒk ı j.T1 / D ;: Therefore pŒT0 D pŒk ı j.T0 / and so k ı j.A \ M / D A \ MQ as desired.
9.5
t u
Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
A natural question is the following. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that L.; R/ ADC C “‚ is regular”: Suppose that L.; R/Pmax Martin’s Maximum.c/: Must L.; R/ ADR ‹ As we have previously noted (Theorem 9.41), the answer to this question is yes. One goal of this section is to sketch a proof of a stronger theorem, Theorem 9.87. The following theorems show that some condition on is necessary. Theorem 9.69. Assume Martin’s Maximum.c/. Then for each set A !2 , A# exists. t u Theorem 9.70. Suppose that Martin’s Maximum.c/ holds and that P is a partial order of cardinality !2 . Suppose G P is V -generic. Then V ŒG PD: t u We shall obtain Theorem 9.69 as a corollary of a slightly stronger theorem, Theorem 9.75, that involves a specific consequence of Martin’s Maximum.c/. This consequence is a reflection principle for stationary subsets of P!1 .!2 / which is a special case of the reflection principle WRP of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/. This and a generalization formulated in .Todorcevic 1984/ are discussed briefly in Section 2.6, see Definition 2.54. The special cases of interest to us here are given in the following definition. The actual formulation of Definition 9.71(3) is taken from .Feng and Jech 1998/. This formulation is more elegant than the original.
652
9 Extensions of L.; R/
(1) (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah) WRP.!2 /: Suppose that S P!1 .!2 / is stationary in P!1 .!2 /. Then there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S \ P!1 .˛/ is stationary in P!1 .˛/.
Definition 9.71.
(2) (Foreman–Magidor–Shelah) WRP.2/ .!2 /: Suppose that S1 P!1 .!2 / and S2 P!1 .!2 / are each stationary in P!1 .!2 /. Then there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S1 \ P!1 .˛/ and S2 \ P!1 .˛/ are each stationary in P!1 .˛/. (3) (Todorcevic) SRP.!2 /: Suppose that S P!1 .!2 / and that for each stationary set T !1 , the set ¹ 2 S j \ !1 2 T º is stationary in P!1 .!2 /. Then there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S \ P!1 .˛/ contains a closed, unbounded, subset of P!1 .˛/. Lemma 9.72 (Todorcevic). SRP.!2 / holds.
(1) Assume that Martin’s Maximum.c/ is true. Then
(2) Assume SRP.!2 /. Then WRP.2/ .!2 / holds. Lemma 9.73 (Todorcevic).
t u
t u
(1) Assume WRP.!2 /. Then 2@0 @2 .
(2) Assume SRP.!2 /. Then 2@1 D @2 .
t u
Remark 9.74. (1) It is not difficult to show that WRP.!2 / is consistent with 2@1 > @2 and WRP.!2 / is consistent with CH. Thus Lemma 9.73(1) cannot really be improved. (2) We shall prove that SRP.!2 / implies ı12 D !2 and so SRP.!2 / implies c D @2 , see Theorem 9.79. (3) In fact, SRP.!2 / implies AC , as we shall note below. This gives a different t u proof that SRP.!2 / implies c D @2 . At the heart of Theorem 9.69 is the following theorem from which one can obtain Theorem 9.69 as a corollary.
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
653
Theorem 9.75. Assume WRP.2/ .!2 / and that for each set A !1 , A# exists. Then for each set A !2 , A# exists. Proof. Fix a set A !2 . We must prove that A# exists. Clearly we may suppose that A is cofinal in !2 . For each countable set !2 let ı be the ordertype of and let A ı be the image of A under the transitive collapse of . Let W ! ı be the collapsing map. For each i < ! let i D !2Ci . Thus for each bounded set b !2 , i is a Silver indiscernible of LŒb. For each formula .x0 ; y0 ; z0 / and for each pair .s; t / 2 Œ!2
654
9 Extensions of L.; R/
then S.:;s0 ;t0 / \ P!1 .˛/ is not stationary in P!1 .˛/. Similarly if LŒA \ ˛ :ŒA \ ˛; s0 ; t0 : then S.;s0 ;t0 / \ P!1 .˛/ is not stationary in P!1 .˛/. This contradicts the choice of ˛ and so proves our claim. Let T be the set of .; s; t / such that S.;s;t/ contains a closed unbounded subset of P!1 .!2 /. T is naturally interpreted as a complete theory in the language with additional constants for A, the ordinals less than !2 , and for the i . It follows easily that this theory is A# since every countable subset of this theory can be embedded into A# for almost all (in the sense of the filter generated by the closed unbounded subsets t u of P!1 .!2 /). Magidor has noted the following: Suppose that is weakly compact and that G Coll.!1 ; < / is V -generic. Then (by reflection) V ŒG WRP.2/ .!2 /: Thus WRP.2/ .!2 / does not imply, for example, that 0# exists. Lemma 9.76 (Todorcevic). .SRP.!2 // INS is !2 -saturated.
t u
One corollary of Lemma 9.76 and the proof of Theorem 5.13 is that SRP.!2 / implies AC . This result, obtained independently by P. Larson, gives yet another proof that SRP.!2 / implies c D @2 . Corollary 9.77 (SRP.!2 /).
AC
holds.
t u
Theorem 9.69 is an immediate consequence of the following corollary of both Lemma 9.76 and Theorem 9.75. Corollary 9.78. Assume SRP.!2 /. Then for each set A !2 , A# exists. Proof. By Lemma 9.72(2), WRP.2/ .!2 / holds. By Lemma 9.76, for every set A !1 , t u A# exists. Therefore by Theorem 9.75, for every set A !2 , A# exists. Another corollary is the following theorem which shows that SRP.!2 / implies that ı12 D !2 . Theorem 9.79. Assume SRP.!2 /. Then ı12 D !2 . Proof. We have by Lemma 9.76 and Corollary 9.78 the following. (1.1) INS is !2 -saturated and that for each A !2 , A# exists.
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
655
We claim that (1.1) implies that ı 12 D !2 . This is an immediate corollary of Theorem 3.17 if one assumes in addition that 2@1 D @2 which in fact is a consequence of SRP.!2 /. However this additional assumption is unnecessary. Choose A !2 such that (2.1) .!2 /LŒA D !2 , (2.2) .H.!2 //LŒA H.!2 /. This is easily done, it is theorem of ZFC that such a set A exists. Thus (by (2.2)) for all ˛ < !2 , .A \ ˛/# 2 LŒA and so P .!1 / \ LŒA D P .!1 / \ LŒA# : Therefore
#
.H.!2 //LŒA H.!2 /; which implies that LŒA# “INS is !2 -saturated” #
since !2 D .!2 /LŒA . But LŒA# “P .!1 /# exists”. Thus by Theorem 3.17, which can be applied in the inner model LŒA# , LŒA# “ı12 D !2 ” and so ı 12 D !2 .
t u
Corollary 9.78 can be strengthened considerably, for example if SRP.!2 / holds then for every set A !2 , A exists. Another generalization of Theorem 9.75 is given in the following theorem whose proof is closely related to the proof of Theorem 9.87. Theorem 9.80. Suppose that WRP.2/ .!2 / holds and that if g Coll.!; !1 / is V -generic then in V Œg: (i) L.R/ AD; (ii) R# exists. Suppose that G Coll.!; !2 / is V -generic. Then in V ŒG: (1) L.R/ AD; (2) R# exists.
t u
656
9 Extensions of L.; R/
An easier version of Theorem 9.80 is the following theorem. Recall that PD is the assertion that all projective sets are determined. Theorem 9.81. Suppose that WRP.2/ .!2 / holds and that if g Coll.!; !1 / is V -generic then V Œg PD: Suppose that G Coll.!; !2 / is V -generic. Then V ŒG PD:
t u
The method of proving Theorem 9.81 amplified by some of the machinery behind the proof of Theorem 5.104 yields the following improvements of Theorem 9.81. Theorem 9.82. Suppose that WRP.2/ .!2 / holds and that INS is !2 -saturated. Suppose that G Coll.!; !2 / is V -generic. Then V ŒG PD:
t u
Corollary 9.83. Suppose that SRP.!2 / holds and that P is a partial order of cardinality !2 . Suppose G P is V -generic. Then V ŒG PD:
t u
Remark 9.84. Theorem 9.82, and therefore Corollary 9.83, can be be strengthened to obtain more determinacy. The main results of Steel and Zoble .2008/ improve the results by obtaining ADL.R/ . The proof of Theorem 9.82 can be implemented using a weakened version of SRP.!2 /, see Theorem 9.95. This version is defined in Definition 9.88(2). Theorem 9.99 shows that this weakened version together with the assertion that INS is !2 t u saturated cannot imply significantly determinacy significantly past ADL.R/ . WRP.!2 / implies a weak variation of Chang’s Conjecture. Lemma 9.85 (WRP.!2 /). Suppose that F W !2
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
657
Proof. Let S D P!1 .!2 / n CF : Assume toward a contradiction that S is stationary in P!1 .!2 /. Thus by WRP.!2 / there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S \ P!1 .˛/ is stationary in P!1 .˛/. Let Z H.!3 / be a countable elementary substructure such that (1.1) F 2 Z, (1.2) ˛ 2 Z, (1.3) Z \ ˛ 2 S . The requirement (1.3) is easily arranged since S \ P!1 .˛/ is stationary in P!1 .˛/. By (1.2) Z \ ˛ ¨ Z \ !2 : But Z \ !2 is closed under F and so Z \ !2 witnesses that Z \ ˛ 2 CF which contradicts that Z \ ˛ 2 S . t u An immediate corollary of the next lemma is that WRP.!2 / must fail in L.A; R/Pmax where A R is such that L.A; R/ ADC : Lemma 9.86. Suppose that V D LŒA for some set A !2 and that for each set B !1 , B # exists. Then WRP.!2 / fails. Proof. Consider the structure h!2 ; A; 2i: For each countable elementary substructure X h!2 ; A; 2i let AX be the image of A under the transitive collapse. Let S be the set of X 2 P!1 .!2 / such that !1 \ X is countable in LŒAX . We claim that that S is stationary in P!1 .!2 /. If not let Y0 be the set of a 2 H.!3 / such that a is definable in the structure hH.!3 /; A; 2i: Thus Y0 H.!3 / and so S 2 Y0 . Since S is not stationary it follows that Y0 \ !2 … S: Let M0 be the transitive collapse of Y0 and let A0 be the image of A under the transitive collapse. Thus every element of M0 is definable in the structure hM0 ; A0 ; 2i:
658
9 Extensions of L.; R/
However M0 “V D LŒA0 ” and so M0 2 LŒA0 . Therefore M0 is countable in LŒA0 and so Y0 \ !2 2 S , a contradiction. Thus S is stationary in P!1 .!2 /. We now assume toward a contradiction that WRP.!2 / holds. Fix !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S \ P!1 .˛/ is stationary in P!1 .˛/. Thus there exists Z H.!3 / such that (1.1) Z \ ˛ 2 S , (1.2) A \ ˛ 2 Z. However .A \ ˛/# exists and so .A \ ˛/# 2 Z. Let Z0 D Z \ ˛. Let MZ be the transitive collapse of Z and let AZ be the image of A under the transitive collapse. Let AZ0 be the image of A \ ˛ under the transitive collapse of Z0 . Trivially AZ0 is the image of A \ ˛ under the transitive collapse of Z. However Z \ !1 D Z0 \ !1 and so since Z0 2 S ,
V!C1 \ LŒAZ0 6 MZ :
The key point is that since .A \ ˛/# 2 Z; it follows that .AZ0 /# 2 MZ . This in turn implies that V!C1 \ LŒAZ0 MZ ; t u
which is a contradiction.
By Lemma 9.72, Martin’s Maximum.c/ implies WRP.!2 / and so Theorem 9.41 is an immediate corollary of the next theorem. The proof requires more of the descriptive set theory associated to ADC and so we shall only sketch the argument. The proof is in essence a generalization of the proof of Lemma 9.86. Theorem 9.87. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: and such that
L.; R/Pmax WRP.!2 /:
Then L.; R/ AD R :
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
659
Proof. We assume toward a contradiction that L.; R/ 6 AD R : Fix G Pmax such that G is L.; R/-generic. We work in L.; R/ŒG. By Theorem 9.22, since L.; R/ 6 AD R ; there exists a set S Ord such that L.; R/ D L.S ; R/: Thus, since L.R/ŒG ZFC, L.; R/ŒG ZFC: Let .0 ; ˛0 / be the least (lexicographical order) such that (1.1) 0 is a boolean pointclass closed under continuous preimages, (1.2) ˛0 2 Ord and L˛0 .0 ; R/ ZF n Replacement C †1 -Replacement; (1.3) L˛0 .0 ; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”, (1.4) L˛0 .0 ; R/ŒG WRP.!2 /, (1.5) L˛0 .0 ; R/ 6 AD R . It follows that 0 D P .R/ \ L˛0 .0 ; R/; for otherwise L˛0 .0 ; R/ŒG D L˛0 ŒA for some A !2 which, by (1.4), contradicts Lemma 9.86. By (1.5) there is a largest Suslin cardinal (in L˛0 .0 ; R/), ı0 < .‚/L˛0 .0 ;R/ : Let 0 be the pointclass of sets A R such that A is Suslin and co-Suslin in L˛0 .0 ; R/: It follows that there exists a tree T on ! ı0 such that (2.1) T 2 L˛0 .0 ; R/, (2.2) let 0 be the set of A R such that A is †1 -definable in the structure hM 0 ; T; 2i with parameters from R, then T is the tree of 0 -scale on the universal 0 set, (2.3) 0 .HODT .R//L˛0 .0 ;R/ . The key consequence of ADC is the following.
660
9 Extensions of L.; R/
(3.1) Suppose that A 2 0 is definable in L˛0 .0 ; R/ from .T; x/ where x 2 R. Then there is a scale on A (in L.; R/) each norm of which is definable in L˛0 .0 ; R/ from .T; x/. In particular, and this is all we require, (4.1) every set in 0 is Suslin in L.; R/. Consider the structure hM 0 ŒG; T; 2i: For each countable elementary substructure X hM 0 ŒG; T; 2i let NX be the transitive collapse of X . Let S be the set of countable X hM 0 ŒG; T; 2i such that !1 \ X is countable in LŒT; NX . We claim that in L˛0 .0 ; R/ŒG, the set S is stationary in P!1 .M 0 ŒG/. If not let Y0 be the set of a 2 M0 ŒG such that a is definable in the structure hM0 ŒG; 0 ; T; 2i from G. Note that jM 0 ŒGjL˛0 .0 ;R/ŒG D !2 and .H.!3 //L˛0 .0 ;R/ŒG D M0 ŒG: Therefore, by (2.3), there is a wellordering of M0 which is definable in hM0 ŒG; 0 ; T; 2i from G. Thus Y0 M0 ŒG and so it follows that S 2 Y0 . Since S is not stationary it follows that Y0 \ M 0 ŒG … S: Let M0 be the transitive collapse of Y0 and let N0 be the image of hM 0 ŒG; T; 2i under the transitive collapse. The key point is that M0 2 LŒT; N0 : This is another consequence of ADC , it is closely related to the proof of (2.3). Thus N0 is countable in LŒT; N0 which contradicts that Y0 \ M 0 ŒG … S: Therefore S is stationary in P!1 .M 0 ŒG/. We show this contradicts that L˛0 .0 ; R/ŒG WRP.!2 /:
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
661
Fix a bijection W !2 ! M 0 ŒG with 2 L˛0 .0 ; R/ŒG. This exists since jM 0 ŒGj D !2 in L˛0 .0 ; R/ŒG. Therefore, by WRP.!2 /, there exists < !2 such that (5.1) Œ M 0 ŒG, (5.2) !1 Œ, (5.3) ¹X 2 P!1 ./ j ŒX 2 S º is stationary in P!1 ./. The key point is that H.!2 /L.;R/ŒG D H.!2 /L˛0 .0 ;R/ŒG and so in L.; R/ŒG, the set ¹X 2 P!1 ./ j ŒX 2 S º is stationary in P!1 ./. Let B 2 0 be the set of x 2 R such that x codes a triple .˛; a; b/ such that (6.1) ˛ < !1 , (6.2) a ˛, (6.3) b D P .˛/ \ LŒT; a. The set B is Suslin in L.; R/. Let TB 2 M be a tree such that B D pŒTB : Let
TB D ¹f W !1 ! TB j f 2 M º=
be the ultrapower computed in L.; R/ of TB by the measure on !1 generated by the closed unbounded subsets of !1 . Thus if g .P .!1 / n INS ; /L.;R/ŒG is L.; R/ŒG-generic then
TB D j.TB /
where j W L.; R/ŒG ! N L.; R/ŒGŒg is the associated generic elementary embedding. Since in L.; R/ŒG, the set ¹X 2 P!1 ./ j ŒX 2 S º is stationary in P!1 ./, there exists Z hM ŒG; ; 2i such that (7.1) ¹T; TB ; 0 ; ; º 2 Z, (7.2) ŒZ \ 2 S .
662
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Let M0 be the transitive collapse of Z and let N0 be the transitive collapse of ŒZ \ . By (5.2), .!1 /M0 D .!1 /N0 D Z \ !1 : Since TB 2 Z it follows that P .N0 / \ LŒT; N0 M0 : However ŒZ \ 2 S and so this implies that Z \ !1 is countable in M0 , a contradiction. t u There are natural weakenings of the principles, WRP.!2 / and SRP.!2 /. We discuss these briefly and state some theorems. Our purpose is to illustrate how possibly subtle variations are stratified, in the context of Pmax -extensions, by the strength of the underlying model of ADC . Suppose that I P .P!1 .!2 // is an ideal. Recall that the ideal I is normal if for all functions F W !2 ! I; SF 2 I where SF D ¹ 2 P!1 .!2 / j 2 F .˛/ for some ˛ 2 º: The ideal is fine if for each 2 P!1 .!2 /, ¹ 2 P!1 .!2 / j 6 º 2 I: (1) WRP .!2 /: There is a proper normal, fine, ideal I P .P!1 .!2 // such that for all T 2 P .!1 / n INS , ¹X 2 P!1 .!2 / j X \ !1 2 T º … I and such that if S P!1 .!2 /
Definition 9.88.
is I -positive then there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S \ P!1 .˛/ is stationary in P!1 .˛/. (2) SRP .!2 /: There is a proper normal, fine, ideal I P .P!1 .!2 // such that for all T 2 P .!1 / n INS , ¹X 2 P!1 .!2 / j X \ !1 2 T º … I; and such that if S P!1 .!2 / is a set such that for each T 2 P .!1 / n INS , ¹X 2 S j X \ !1 2 T º … I; then there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S \ P!1 .˛/ contains a closed, unbounded, subset of P!1 .˛/.
t u
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
663
Remark 9.89. WRP .!2 / simply asserts that the set of counterexamples to WRP.!2 / t u generates a normal, fine, ideal which is proper on each stationary subset of !1 . One connection between these weakened versions is given in the following lemma. Lemma 9.90. Assume that INS is !2 -saturated and that SRP .!2 / holds. Let I P .P!1 .!2 // be a normal ideal witnessing that SRP .!2 / holds. Suppose that S1 P!1 .!2 / and S2 P!1 .!2 / are each I -positive. Then there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S1 \ P!1 .˛/ and S2 \ P!1 .˛/ are each stationary in P!1 .˛/. Proof. Let J1 P .!1 / be the set of A !1 such that ¹X 2 S1 j X \ !1 2 Aº 2 I: It is easily verified that J1 is a normal (uniform) ideal and so since INS is !2 -saturated, there exists A1 2 P .!1 / n INS such that J1 D ¹A !1 j A \ A1 2 INS º: Similarly there exists A2 2 P .!1 / n INS such that J2 D ¹A !1 j A \ A2 2 INS º; where J2 is the set of A !1 such that ¹X 2 S2 j X \ !1 2 Aº 2 I: Choose stationary sets B1 A1 and B2 A2 such that B1 \ B2 D ;. Define S P!1 .!2 / to be the set of X such that; (1.1) X 2 S1 if X \ !1 2 B1 , (1.2) X 2 S2 if X \ !1 2 B2 . It follows that for each stationary set T !1 , ¹X 2 S j X \ !1 2 T º … I:
Thus since I witnesses SRP .!2 / there exists !1 < ˛ < !2 such that S \ P!1 .˛/ is closed, unbounded, in P!1 .˛/. This implies that both S1 \ P!1 .˛/ and S2 \ P!1 .˛/ t u are stationary in P!1 .˛/. The following lemmas show that while WRP .!2 / is a significant weakening of WRP.!2 /, it is plausible that SRP .!2 / is not as significant a weakening of SRP.!2 /.
9 Extensions of L.; R/
664
Lemma 9.91 (2@1 D @2 ). Assume WRP.!2 / and suppose that A !2 is a set such that H.!2 / LŒA: Then
LŒA WRP .!2 /:
Proof. Let I be the normal ideal defined in LŒA, generated by sets S P!1 .!2 / such that (1.1) S 2 LŒA, (1.2) for all !1 < ˛ < !2 , S \ P!1 .˛/ is not stationary in P!1 .˛/. Since WRP.!2 / holds in V , I is contained in the ideal of nonstationary subsets of P!1 .!2 /. Therefore I is a proper ideal in LŒA and so I witnesses WRP .!2 / in LŒA. t u The proof of Theorem 9.75 easily adapts, using Lemma 9.90 in place of WRP2 .!2 /, to prove the following variation of Theorem 9.75. Lemma 9.92. Assume SRP .!2 / and that INS is !2 -saturated. Then for each A !2 , t u A# exists. As an immediate corollary we obtain a weak version of Theorem 9.87. Corollary 9.93. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular” and such that
L.; R/Pmax SRP .!2 /:
Then for each A 2 P .R/ \ L.; R/, A# 2 L.; R/.
t u
The situation for WRP .!2 / seems analogous to that for Chang’s Conjecture. Theorem 9.94. Suppose L.R/ AD and that there exists a countable set R such that HODL.R/ . / \ R D and HODL.R/ . / AD C DC: Suppose G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG WRP .!2 /:
t u
9.5 Weak and Strong Reflection Principles
665
The proof of Theorem 9.82 actually proves the following theorem. Theorem 9.95. Suppose that SRP .!2 / holds and that INS is !2 -saturated. Suppose that G Coll.!; !2 / is V -generic. Then V ŒG PD:
t u
Some information about SRP .!2 / is provided by Theorem 9.99. This theorem places an upper bound on the consistency strength of the theory ZFC C SRP .!2 / C “INS is !2 -saturated” which is not far beyond the lower bound established by Theorem 9.95, and significantly below the known upper bounds for SRP.!2 /. Theorem 9.99 involves the following determinacy hypothesis: (ZFC) Let F be the club filter on P!1 .R/. Then (1) F jL.R; F / is an ultrafilter, (2) L.R; F / ADC . We note the following corollary of Theorem 9.14. Theorem 9.96. Let F be the club filter on P!1 .R/. Suppose that L.R; F / AD: C
t u
Then L.R; F / AD .
The proof of Theorem 9.99 is relatively straightforward using the following theorem. Theorem 9.97. Let F be the club filter on P!1 .R/. Suppose that F jL.R; F / is an ultrafilter and that L.R; F / AD: Let D
2 L.R;F / . . 1 /
Then:
(1) Suppose A R! and that A 2 M . The real game corresponding to A is determined in L.R; F /. (2) hM ; F \ M ; 2i †1 hL.R; F /; F \ L.R; F /; 2i. Remark 9.98. Theorem 9.97 might seem to suggest that the hypothesis: (ZFC) Let F be the club filter on P!1 .R/. Then (1) F jL.R; F / is an ultrafilter, (2) L.R; F / ADC ;
t u
666
9 Extensions of L.; R/
is very strong, close in strength to ZF C ADR : However the hypothesis is in fact equiconsistent with ZFC C “There are ! 2 many Woodin cardinals” and ADR is considerably stronger; ADR implies there are inner models in which there are measurable cardinals which are limits of Woodin cardinals, and much more. t u Theorem 9.99. Let F be the club filter on P!1 .R/. Suppose that F jL.R; F / is an ultrafilter and that L.R; F / AD: Suppose that G Pmax is an L.R; F /-generic filter. Then L.R; F /ŒG SRP .!2 /:
t u
We conjecture that Theorem 9.87 holds for SRP .!2 /. This conjecture is not refuted by Theorem 9.99. The explanation lies in the subtle, but important, distinction between models of ADC of the form L.; R/ versus models of the form L.S; ; R/ where S is a set of ordinals and is a pointclass (closed under continuous preimages). We discuss below an example which illustrates this point. Let F be the club filter on P!1 .R/. Suppose that, as in Theorem 9.99, F jL.R; F / is an ultrafilter and that L.R; F / AD: Thus L.R; F / “There is a normal fine measure on P!1 .R/”: The basic theory of ADC applied to L.R; F / shows that L.R; F / D HODL.R;F / .R/: Thus L.R; F / is of the form L.S; ; R/ with D ;. However the basic theory of ADC also yields the following theorem. Theorem 9.100. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that L.; R/ ADC and that L.; R/ “There is a normal fine measure on P!1 .R/”: Then L.; R/ ADR : t u Thus to obtain a model of ADC in which there is a normal fine measure on P!1 .R/, the distinction between models of the form L.; R/ and of the form L.S; ; R/ is an important one. We conjecture that the situation is similar for SRP .!2 /. Of course for the other principles (SRP.!2 /, WRP.!2 /, WRP.2/ .!2 /, and WRP .!2 /) the distinction is not important. The reason is simply that these other principles are absolute between V and L.P .!2 //.
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
9.6
667
Strong Chang’s Conjecture
We briefly discuss the following strengthenings of Chang’s Conjecture. One of these is Strong Chang’s Conjecture which is discussed in .Shelah 1998/. Definition 9.101 (ZF C DC).
(1) Chang’s ConjectureC : Suppose that F W !2
Then there exists G W !2
t u
Remark 9.102. In general we shall only consider Strong Chang’s Conjecture in the situation that L.P .!2 // !2 -DC: u t Lemma 9.103 (ZFC). The following are equivalent: (1) Strong Chang’s Conjecture. (2) There exists a function F W H.!3 / ! H.!3 / such that if X H.!3 / is countable and closed under F , then there exists Y H.!3 / such that
668
9 Extensions of L.; R/
a) F ŒY Y , b) X Y , c) X \ !1 D Y \ !1 , d) X \ !2 ¤ Y \ !2 . (3) There exists a function F W H.!3 / ! H.!3 / such that if X H.!3 / is countable and closed under F , then there exists Y H.!3 / such that a) X Y , b) X \ !1 D Y \ !1 , c) X \ !2 ¤ Y \ !2 . (4) There exists a transitive inner model N such that a) P .!2 / N , b) N ZF C DC C Strong Chang’s Conjecture. Proof. It is straightforward to show that (1) implies (2), the relevant observation is the following. Suppose that M is a transitive set such that M H.!3 / M: Then there exist a countable elementary substructure X0 M and a function F0 W H.!3 / ! H.!3 / such that the following holds. Suppose that X H.!3 / is countable, X0 \ H.!3 / X; and X is closed under F0 . Then there exists Y M such that X0 Y and Y \ H.!3 / D X . Thus it suffices to prove that (4) implies (3) and that (3) implies (1). We first prove that (3) implies (1), noting that for this implication one only needs !2 -DC. Let M be a transitive set such that M H.!3 / M and let X M be a countable elementary substructure. Since H.!3 / is definable in M , there exists F W H.!3 / ! H.!3 /
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
669
such that F 2 X and such that F witnesses (3). Let Y H.!3 / be a countable elementary substructure closed under F such that (1.1) X Y , (1.2) X \ !1 D Y \ !1 , (1.3) X \ !2 ¤ Y \ !2 , and let Z D ¹f .a/ j f W !2 ! M; f 2 X; and a 2 ŒY \ !2 jH.!3 /j; and let M D N . Thus M H.!3 / M in N . Let F W H.!3 / ! H.!3 / be a function (in V ) such that if X H.!3 / is a countable set closed under F then there exists X M such that X \ H.!3 / D X . We claim that F witnesses (3). Assume toward a contradiction that this fails and let X H.!3 / be a countable set, closed under F , which witnesses that F fails to satisfy (3). However X 2 N (since H.!3 / N ) and so by absoluteness and the choice of F , there exists a countable elementary substructure X M such that X 2 N and X \ H.!3 / D X . Therefore since N Strong Chang’s Conjecture; there exists a countable elementary substructure Y M such that
670
9 Extensions of L.; R/
(4.1) X Y , (4.2) X \ !1 D Y \ !1 , (4.3) X \ !2 ¨ Y \ !2 . Finally Y \ H.!3 / contradicts the choice of X .
t u
The next lemma is an immediate consequence of the definitions. Lemma 9.104 (ZF C !2 -DC). (1) Assume Strong Chang’s Conjecture holds. Then Chang’s ConjectureC holds. (2) Assume Chang’s ConjectureC holds. Then Chang’s Conjecture holds. Proof. (2) is immediate, we prove (1). Fix a function F W !2
XZ0 \ !2 D X \ !2 GŒX
Finally since Strong Chang’s Conjecture holds, the function G is as required.
t u
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
671
The primary goal of this section is to sketch the construction of a model in which ./ holds and in which Strong Chang’s Conjecture holds. This improvement of Theorem 9.57 will require an even stronger determinacy hypothesis. The formulation involves the sequence h‚˛ W ˛ < i which is discussed at the end of Section 9.1. The proof of Theorem 9.114 requires the following theorems concerning models of ADC . Theorem 9.105. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.; R/. Suppose that either (i) is a limit ordinal, or (ii) if D ˛ C 1 then ˛ < ı where ı D max¹ < ‚ j is a Suslin cardinal in L.; R/º: Then there is a surjection W ‚! \ V‚ ! P .R/ \ L.; R/ such that is †1 -definable in L.; R/ from ¹Rº. Remark 9.106.
t u
(1) We shall only use Theorem 9.105 when L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”:
In this situation D ‚ and so the hypothesis of Theorem 9.105 is satisfied. (2) Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : We do not know if the conclusion of Theorem 9.105 must hold in general. However the assumption that both (i) and (ii) fail; i. e. that D ı C 1 where ı is the largest Suslin cardinal in L.; R/, is far stronger than any determinacy hypothesis we shall require in this book. t u The second theorem we shall require generalizes Theorem 9.29. Note that as an immediate corollary one obtains, with notation from the statement of Theorem 9.107, that .HODa /L.;R/ D .HOD/L.;R/ .a/; for each a 2 P!1 .‚! / \ V‚ :
672
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Theorem 9.107. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Let ‚ D .‚/L.;R/ and suppose that A ‚ ! \ V‚ is ordinal definable in L.; R/. Then there exist a formula .x; y/ and a set b 2 P .‚/ \ HOD such that for all a 2 ‚ ! \ V‚ ; a 2 A if and only if
LŒa; b Œa; b:
t u
Theorem 9.107 easily yields the following corollary which is what we shall require. Corollary 9.108. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC : Let ‚ D .‚/L.;R/ and suppose that a 2 P!1 .‚! / \ V‚ : Suppose that P 2 HODL.;R/ .a/ is a partial order which is countable in V and that X is a comeager set of filters in P such that X is ordinal definable in L.; R/ with parameters from a [ ¹aº. Suppose that g P is a filter which is HODL.;R/ .a/-generic. Then g 2 X . Proof. Fix 2 Ord such that a 2 V , jV j D , and such that X is definable in L .; R/ with parameters from a [ ¹aº. Let Y be the set of all finite sequences ha0 ; b0 ; P0 ; 0 ; g0 i such that: (1.1) a0 2 P!1 .‚! / \ V‚ . (1.2) P0 is a partial order. (1.3) P0 2 H.!1 / \ HODL.;R/ .a0 /. (1.4) b0 2 a0
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
673
Thus Y is ordinal definable and nonempty. Fix a reasonable coding of elements of .P!1 .‚! / \ V‚ / .‚! \ V‚ /
LŒB; s ŒB; s:
and a formula such that X D ¹g j L .; R/ Œa; b; gº:
Now suppose that g P is a filter which is HOD.a/-generic. Since (3.1) B 2 HOD, (3.2) X is a comeager set of filters in P , it follows by the definability of forcing that there must exist a partial order Q 2 HOD.a/Œg \ H.!1 / such that if h Q is HOD.a/Œg-generic then there exists s 2 HOD.a/ŒgŒh such that .s/ D ha; b; P ; ; gi: Thus X must contain all HOD.a/-generic filters.
t u
The next theorem which we shall require generalizes Theorem 9.7. Recall that if P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous images, continuous preimages, and complements, then we have associated to a transitive set M constructed from those sets, X , which are coded by an element of , see Definition 2.18.
674
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Theorem 9.109. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.; R/. For each ˛ < let ı˛ D sup¹ < ‚˛ j is a Suslin cardinalº and let ˛ D ¹A ! ! j w.A/ < ı˛ º. Then M ˛ †1 L.; R/.
t u
Remark 9.110. By Theorem 9.19, the Suslin cardinals are closed below ‚. Thus the essential content of Theorem 9.109 is in the case that ı˛ < ‚ ˛ : This is the case that ı˛ is the largest Suslin cardinal below ‚˛ . For example if ˛ D 0 ı 21 . u t then ı˛ D We shall also need the following theorem concerning generic elementary embeddings. For this theorem it is useful to define in the context of DC, a partial embedding, jU , for each countably complete ultrafilter U . Definition 9.111 (DC). Suppose that X ¤ ; and that U P .X / is a countably complete ultrafilter. Let jU W [¹LŒS j S Ordº ! V be defined as follows: Suppose that S Ord. Then [¹jU .a/ j a 2 LŒS º is the transitive collapse of the ultrapower, ¹f W X ! LŒS j f 2 V º=U; and jU jLŒS W LŒS ! LŒjU .S / is the associated (elementary) embedding.
t u
It is clear from the definition that jU .S / is unambiguously defined. Theorem 9.112. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose that G Coll.!; R/ is L.; R/-generic. Then there exists a generic elementary embedding jG W L.; R/ ! N L.; R/ŒG such that: (1) N ! N in L.; R/ŒG; (2) for each set S Ord with S 2 L.; R/, jG jLŒS D j jLŒS where 2 L.; R/ is the measure on P!1 .R/ generated by the closed unt u bounded subsets of P!1 .R/.
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
675
The last of the theorems which we shall need is in essence a corollary of Theorem 5.34. Theorem 9.113. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.; R/. Then for each ˛ < , HODL.;R/ “‚˛C1 is a Woodin cardinal”:
t u
Theorem 9.114(2) specifies conditions on a pointclass which imply that L.; R/Pmax Chang’s ConjectureC : We do not know if the hypothesis, L.; R/ ADR C “‚ is regular”; of Theorem 9.39 actually suffices. Nevertheless the requirements of Theorem 9.114(2) are implied by a number of much simpler assertions. For example the assertion, L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is Mahlo”; suffices. Theorem 9.114. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.; R/. For each ı < let ı D ¹A ! ! j w.A/ < ‚ı º and let Nı D HODL.;R/ .ı /: Let W be the set of ı < such that (i) ı D ‚ı , (ii) Nı “ı is regular”. Suppose G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic. (1) Suppose that ı 2 W . Then Nı ŒG0 ZF C !2 -DC C Strong Chang’s Conjecture: (2) Suppose that W is cofinal in . Then L.; R/ŒG0 Chang’s ConjectureC :
676
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Proof. By Lemma 9.104, (2) is an immediate corollary of (1). We prove (1). Fix ‚ D .‚/L.;R/ : Let G1 Coll.!; R/ be L.; R/-generic and let j1 W L.; R/ ! L. 1 ; R1 / L.; R/ŒG1 be the associated embedding as given by Theorem 9.112. Thus for each set S Ord with S 2 L.; R/, j1 jLŒS D j jLŒS where 2 L.; R/ is the measure on P!1 .R/ generated by the closed unbounded subsets of P!1 .R/. It is convenient to work in L.; R/ŒG1 . Fix G0 Pmax such that G0 is L.; R/-generic and such that G0 2 L.; R/ŒG1 . We begin by observing that a very weak version of Chang’s ConjectureC does hold. Suppose that F W !2
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
677
such that: (2.1) h 2 L.; R/; (2.2) Suppose 2 P!1 .R/ and hŒ
678
9 Extensions of L.; R/
We let A be the code of . Let † be the set of A 2 ı such that A D A for some term . Fix a surjection W ‚! ! such that is †1 definable in L.; R/, such a function exists by Theorem 9.105. We now come to the first key point. Suppose that A 2 † and that 2 L.; R/Pmax is a term such that A D A . Suppose in addition that s 2 ı ! is such that both A and R n A have scales which are †11 .B/ where B D .s/. Let D R \ HODL.;R/ Œs: The key claim is that for every filter g HODL.;R/ Œs \ Pmax ; if g is HODL.;R/ Œs-generic and if p0 2 Pmax is a condition such that p0 < q for each q 2 g, then there exist a condition p 2 Pmax and a countable set Z !2 such that (4.1) Œ \ !2 ¨ Z, (4.2) Œ \ !1 D Z \ !1 , (4.3) p “ŒZ
p “ ŒZ
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
679
This too follows from Corollary 9.108, using Theorem 9.109 and Theorem 9.105. We now fix ı 2 W . We first apply this last claim in L. 1 ; R1 / where j1 W L.; R/ ! L. 1 ; R1 / L.; R/ŒG1 is the generic elementary embedding associated to G1 . Let HOD1 D j1 .HODL.;R/ / and let
1 D ¹j1 .s/ j s 2 ı ! \ L.; R/º:
Let Y† Mı be the set of all terms 2 Mı \ L.; R/Pmax such that 1 “ W !2
Nı ŒG0 !2 -DC:
Let M0 D ¹f W !2
T P!1 .M0 / 2 P!1 .M0 /
such that there exists Z !2 such that
9 Extensions of L.; R/
680
(7.1) \ !2 ¨ Z, (7.2) \ !1 D Z \ !1 , (7.3) f ŒZ
9.6 Strong Chang’s Conjecture
681
it follows that Nı Œg0 ZFC: Let jS W Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 ! N .S/ Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 ŒGS be the associated generic elementary embedding. Thus since M0 D [S and since S 2 GS , jS ŒM0 2 jS .S/: From the definition of S it follows that the following must hold in jS ŒNı ŒG0 : (8.1) There exists p0 2 jS .G0 / such that p0 < p for all p 2 G0 and such that for all sets Z 2 jS .P!1 .!2 // if a) jS Œ!2L.;R/ ¨ Z, b) !1L.;R/ D Z \ jS .!1L.;R/ /, then there exist p 2 jS .G0 / and 2 Y† such that a) p “jS . /ŒZ
682
9 Extensions of L.; R/
(10.1) B \ N .S/ 2 N .S/ , (10.2) hH.!1 /N
.S/
; B \ N .S/ ; 2i hH.!1 /L.;R/ŒG1 ; B; 2i.
Finally, (6.1) is naturally expressible in the structure hH.!1 /L.;R/ŒG1 ; B; 2i by a formula in the language for this structure involving G0 . This is because G0 2 H.!1 /L.;R/ŒG1 : However (8.1) is expressible in the structure .S/ hH.!1 /N ; B \ N .S/ ; 2i; by the negation of this formula since .S/ G0 2 H.!1 /N : This contradicts (10.2). Thus, in Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 , the set S is not stationary in P!1 .M0 /. This proves that Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 ZFC C Strong Chang’s Conjecture; which is equivalent to (1).
t u
As an immediate corollary of Theorem 9.114, we obtain the following improvement of Theorem 9.39. Theorem 9.115. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.; R/. For each ı < let ı D ¹A ! ! j w.A/ < ‚ı º and let Nı D HODL.;R/ .ı /: Let W be the set of ı < such that (i) ı D ‚ı , (ii) Nı “ı is regular”, (iii) cof.ı/ > !: Suppose that ı 2 W , G0 Pmax is Nı -generic and that H0 .Coll.!3 ; P .!2 ///Nı ŒG0 is Nı ŒG0 -generic. Then (1) Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/, (2) Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 Strong Chang’s Conjecture. Proof. By Theorem 9.114, Nı ŒG0 ZF C Strong Chang’s Conjecture: Further P .!2 /Nı ŒG0 D P .!2 /Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 : There by Lemma 9.103, Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 Strong Chang’s Conjecture:
t u
9.7 Ideals on !2
9.7
683
Ideals on !2
Let JNS be the nonstationary ideal on !2 restricted to the ordinals of cofinality !. We shall consider several potential properties of JNS which approximate !3 -saturation. The first is the property of !-presaturation. This notion (for an arbitrary normal ideal) originates in Baumgartner and Taylor .1982/. Definition 9.116. The ideal JNS is !-presaturated if for all S 2 P .!2 / n JNS and for all sequences hDi W i < !i of subsets of P .!2 / n JNS such that for each i < !, Di is predense in .P .!2 / n JNS ; /I there exists a stationary set T S such that for each i < !, j¹A 2 Di j A \ T … JNS ºj !2 :
t u
For the definition of the second saturation property for JNS that we shall define it is convenient to define the notion of a canonical function. Definition 9.117. Suppose h W !2 ! !2 . Then h is a canonical function if there exists an ordinal ˛ < !3 and a surjection W !2 ! ˛ such that !2 n ¹˛ < !2 j f .˛/ D ordertype.Œ˛/º t u
is not stationary in !2 . Definition 9.118. The ideal JNS is weakly presaturated if for every function f W !2 ! !2
and for every set S 2 P .!2 / n JNS , there exists a canonical function h W !2 ! !2 such that ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ h.˛/º … JNS : t u Remark 9.119. Suppose that JNS is weakly presaturated and that G .P .!2 / n JNS ; / is V -generic. Let j W V ! .M; E/ V ŒG be the associated generic elementary embedding. Then j.!2V / D !3V .
t u
It is a theorem of Shelah that JNS is not presaturated. This is a corollary of the following lemma of .Shelah 1986/.
684
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Lemma 9.120 (Shelah). Suppose that is a regular cardinal and that P is a partial order such that V P cof. / < cof.j j/: Then C is not a cardinal in V P .
t u
Theorem 9.121 (Shelah). JNS is not presaturated. Proof. Let P D .P .!2 / n JNS ; /: Assume toward a contradiction that JNS is presaturated and let G P be V -generic. Let j W V ! M V ŒG be the associated generic elementary embedding. Since JNS is presaturated in V , (1.1) j.!2V / D !3V , (1.2) !1V D !1V ŒG , (1.3) N !1 N in V ŒG. By (1.3), !3V D !2V ŒG : In V ŒG, N is the the V -ultrapower of V by a V -normal, V -ultrafilter disjoint from V JNS and so cof.!2V / D ! in N . Therefore ! D .cof.!2V //V ŒG < .cof.j!2V j//V ŒG D !1V ŒG : By Lemma 9.120, !3V is not a cardinal in V ŒG which is a contradiction.
t u
In contrast, by the results of .Foreman, Magidor, and Shelah 1988/ if is supercompact and if G Coll.!2 ; < / is V -generic then in V ŒG, JNS is !-presaturated. The same theorem is true with only the assumption that is a Woodin cardinal. If GCH holds then JNS is not weakly presaturated. In fact if GCH holds then there is a single function f W !2 ! !2 such that if G .P .!2 / n JNS ; / is V -generic then !3V < j.f /.!2V /. An even easier argument proves the following lemma which shows that Martin’s Maximum does not imply that JNS is weakly presaturated. Lemma 9.122. Assume that JNS is weakly presaturated. Suppose that N is a transitive inner model containing the ordinals such that (i) N ZFC, (ii) !2V is inaccessible in N . Let D !2V . Then . C /N < !3 .
9.7 Ideals on !2
685
Proof. Define f W !2 ! !2 by f .˛/ D .j˛jC /N . Let D ..!2V /C /N . For each < let W ! be a surjection such that 2 N . Define f W !2 ! !2 by f .˛/ D ordertype. Œ˛/. Thus for each < there exists a closed unbounded set C !2 such that f .˛/ < f .˛/ for all ˛ 2 C . Suppose G .P .!2 / n JNS ; / is V -generic and let j W V ! M V ŒG be the associated generic elementary embedding. Thus for each < , D j.f /.!2V / < j.f /.!2V /: Therefore
j.f /.!2V / < j.!2V / D !3V :
t u
We define a natural strengthening of the notion that JNS is weakly presaturated. This we shall define for an arbitrary normal ideal I P .!2 /, though we shall be primarily interested only in those ideals which extend JNS . This definition requires the obvious generalization of Definition 4.13. Definition 9.123. Suppose that U .P .!2 //V is a uniform ultrafilter which is setgeneric over V . The ultrafilter U is V -normal if for all functions f W !2V ! !2V with f 2 V , either
¹˛ < !2V j f .˛/ ˛º 2 U
or there exists ˇ < !2V such that ¹˛ < !2V j f .˛/ D ˇº 2 U:
t u
We now generalize the notion of a semi-saturated ideal to ideals on !2 . Definition 9.124. Suppose that I P .!2 / is a normal uniform ideal. The ideal I is semi-saturated if the following holds. Suppose that U is a V -normal ultrafilter which is set generic over V and such that U P .!2 / n I: Then Ult.V; U / is wellfounded.
t u
686
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Remark 9.125. In light of Shelah’s theorem that no normal ideal extending JNS can be presaturated, semi-saturation (together with !-presaturation) is perhaps the strongest saturation property that such an ideal can have. It implies, for example, that every t u normal ideal which extends JNS is precipitous and much more. The next theorem, which is essentially an immediate consequence of the definitions, shows, in essence, that semi-saturated ideals on !2V in V correspond to semisaturated ideals on !1V Œg in V Œg where g Coll.!; !1V / is V -generic. We state the theorem only for the nonstationary ideal, the general version is similar. Theorem 9.126. Suppose that g Coll.!; !1 / is V -generic. The following are equivalent. (1) V “The nonstationary ideal on !2 is semi-saturated”. (2) V Œg “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is semi-saturated”.
t u
Theorem 9.127 and Lemma 9.128 correspond to Lemma 4.27 and Corollary 4.28 respectively. The proofs are similar, we leave the details to the reader. Theorem 9.127. Suppose that I P .!2 / is a normal uniform ideal such that the ideal I is semi-saturated. Suppose that U is a V -normal ultrafilter which is set generic over V and such that U P .!2 / n I and let j W V ! M V ŒU be the associated embedding. Then j.!2V / D !3V .
t u
The next lemma is an immediate corollary of Theorem 9.127. This lemma shows, for example, that if JNS is semi-saturated then every function f W !2 ! !2 is bounded by a canonical function modulo JNS . Thus ˘! .!2 / implies that JNS is not semi-saturated and so by Shelah’s theorem on ˘! .!2 / .Shelah 2008/, if 2!1 D !2 then JNS is not semi-saturated. Lemma 9.128. Suppose that I P .!2 / is a normal uniform ideal such that the ideal I is semi-saturated. Suppose that f W !2 ! !2 : Then there exists a canonical function h W !2 ! !2 such that ¹˛ < !2 j h.˛/ < f .˛/º 2 I:
t u
9.7 Ideals on !2
687
Corollary 9.129. Assume 2!1 D !2 . Then JNS is not semi-saturated.
t u
If ./ holds then every (normal) semi-saturated ideal on !2 must properly extend JNS . Therefore we shall only be considering ideals which properly extend JNS but we note that there are several obvious questions concerning the general case of arbitrary normal ideals on !2 , with no restriction on 2!1 . (1) Can JNS be semi-saturated? (2) Is is possible for every function f W !2 ! !2 to be bounded by a canonical function pointwise on a closed unbounded set? (3) Can the nonstationary ideal on !2 be semi-saturated? (4) Let I be the nonstationary ideal on !2 restricted to the ordinals of cofinality !1 . Can the ideal I be semi-saturated? (5) Suppose that there exists a normal uniform ideal I P .!2 / such that I is semi-saturated and contains JNS . Suppose that J P .!2 / is a normal uniform semi-saturated ideal. Must JNS J ‹ Remark 9.130. (1) It is plausible that if there is a huge cardinal, then in a generic extension of V one can arrange that every function f W !2 ! !2 is bounded pointwise on an !1 -club by a canonical function. Granting this, a negative answer to the first question would in effect be an interesting dichotomy theorem. (2) The likely answer to the second question is no. Theorem 9.131 shows that if P .!2 /# exists and if the nonstationary ideal on !2 is semi-saturated, then a generalization of Theorem 3.19(4) to !2 must hold. This seems impossible. (3) Let I be the nonstationary ideal on !2 restricted to the ordinals of cofinality !1 . It is not known whether the ideal I can be !3 -saturated. This is a well known problem. Question (3) is a weaker question, possibly significantly weaker as the t u results concerning JNS show. Theorem 9.131. Assume P .!2 /# exists. Let I be the nonstationary ideal on !2 . Suppose that I is semi-saturated and that C !2 is closed and unbounded. Then there exists a set A !1 such that ¹ j !1 < < !2 and L ŒA is admissibleº C:
688
9 Extensions of L.; R/
Proof. Fix C !2 such that C is closed and unbounded in !2 . Suppose that g Coll.!; !1 / is V -generic. Then by Theorem 9.126, V Œg “INS is semi-saturated”: Further since P .!2 /# exists in V , V Œg “P .!1 /# exists”: Thus by Theorem 3.19 and Theorem 4.29, there exists x 2 RV Œg , such that ¹˛ < !1 j L˛ Œx is admissibleº C: Let A !1 code a term for x. It follows that ¹ j !1 < < !2 and L ŒA is admissibleº C:
t u
The next theorem, which is a corollary of Theorem 9.126, shows that if the nonstationary ideal on !2 is semi-saturated then one formulation of the Effective Continuum Hypothesis must hold. Theorem 9.132. Let I be the nonstationary ideal on !2 . Suppose that I is semisaturated. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model containing the reals such that M ZF C DC C AD and such that every set X 2 P .R/ \ M is weakly homogeneously Suslin in V . Then ‚M !2 : Proof. Assume toward a contradiction that ‚M > !2 : Let A 2 P .R/ \ M be such that !2 ı 11 .A/ and let ˛ 2 Ord be least such that L˛ .A; R/ ZF C DC: We note that the existence of ˛ is immediate since (trivially) there must exist a measurable cardinal in V . By the choice of A, !2 < ˛: Fix a partial map W R ! !2 such that: (1.1) 2 L˛ .A; R/; (1.2) ¹.t / j t 2 dom./º D !2 ; 1 (1.3) ¹.x; y/ j .x/ .y/º 2 † 1 .A/; 1 (1.4) Suppose Z dom./ is † 1 , then ¹.t / j t 2 Zº is bounded in !2 .
Such a function exists by Steel’s theorem, Theorem 3.40.
9.7 Ideals on !2
689
By the minimality of ˛, every element of L˛ .A; R/ is definable in L˛ .A; R/ with parameters from ¹Aº [ R. Let B be the set of x 2 R such that x codes a pair ..x0 ; x1 /; t / such that .x0 ; x1 / is a formula, t 2 R and such that L˛ .A; R/ ŒA; t : Thus B naturally codes L˛ .A; R/ and B 2 M . Let TA be a weakly homogeneous tree such that A D pŒTA and let TB be a weakly homogeneous tree such that B D pŒTB . Let T be a weakly homogeneous tree such that dom./ D pŒT . Suppose that g Coll.!; !1 / is V -generic. Then by Theorem 9.126, V Œg “INS is semi-saturated”: Let (in V Œg), Ag D pŒTA and Bg D pŒTB : Let ˛g be the least ordinal such that L˛g .Ag ; Rg / ZF; where Rg D .R/V Œg . In V , every set which is projective in B is weakly homogeneously Suslin. Therefore by Lemma 2.28 it follows that in V Œg, Bg codes L˛g .Ag ; Rg / and that the natural map jg W L˛ .A; R/ ! L˛g .Ag ; Rg / is elementary. Let g D jg ./. Thus g W dom.g / ! jg .!2V / is a surjection and dom.g / D pŒT V Œg . Let X D ¹jg .ˇ/ j ˇ < !2V º: Thus in V Œg, jX j D !1 . However in V Œg: (2.1) L˛g .Ag ; Rg / ZF C DC C AD; (2.2) X is a bounded subset of ‚L˛g .Ag ;Rg / ; (2.3) Every set D 2 P .Rg / \ L˛g .Ag ; Rg / is weakly homogeneously Suslin; (2.4) INS is semi-saturated. Therefore by Theorem 4.32 there exists a set Y 2 L˛g .Ag ; Rg / such that
9 Extensions of L.; R/
690
(3.1) X Y jg .!2V /, (3.2) jY j D !1 in L˛g .Ag ; Rg /. Let D sup.X /: By (3.1) and (3.2), is singular in L˛g .Ag ; Rg / and so since by the elementarity of jg , jg .!2V / is a regular cardinal in L˛g .Ag ; Rg /, it follows that < jg .!2V /: Fix t 2 jg .dom.// such that Let 2 V in V ,
Coll.!;!1 /
g .t / D :
be a term for t . We may suppose without loss of generality that
1 “ 2 dom.g / and g ./ D sup¹jg .ˇ/ j ˇ < !2V º”; which implies that in V , 1 “ 2 pŒT ”: We now work in V . Fix 2 Ord such that V ZFC and such that ¹; TB ; T º 2 V : Let Z0 V be a countable elementary substructure such that ¹; TB ; T º 2 Z0 : For each !1 let Z D ZŒ D ¹f .s/ j f 2 Z0 and s 2
1 † 1
Y D pŒT :
and Y D pŒT pŒT D dom./:
9.7 Ideals on !2
691
Thus by (1.4) there exists < !2 such that .z/ < for all z 2 Y . Therefore there exists t0 2 dom./ such that .z/ < .t0 / for all z 2 [¹Y j < !1 º. However 1 “ 2 dom.g / and g ./ D sup¹jg .ˇ/ j ˇ < !2V º”; and so 1 “g .t0 / < g ./”: Note that !1 Z!1 and so
1 “ 2 pŒT!1 ”:
This is a contradiction for choose Z0 V such that Z0 is countable and such that ¹Z0 ; t0 º 2 Z0 . Thus hM W !1 i 2 Z0 : Let M0 be the transitive collapse of Z0 and let T0 be the image of T!1 under the M
collapsing map and let 0 be the image of . Finally suppose that g Coll.!; !1 0 / is M0 -generic and let tg be the interpretation of 0 by g . Thus tg 2 dom./ and by absoluteness, .t0 / < .tg /: But tg 2 pŒT0 and T0 D T where M0
D !1
D Z0 \ !1 :
Therefore tg 2 [¹Y j < !1 º which contradicts the choice of t0 .
t u
There are three closely related results which improve slightly on the results of .Foreman and Magidor 1995/; these are stated as Theorem 9.134, Theorem 9.135 and Theorem 9.136 below. These theorems are straightforward corollaries of Theorem 10.62, Theorem 10.63, and Lemma 10.65. We leave the details to the interested reader. Remark 9.133. (1) The condition (iii) of Theorem 9.134 is trivially implied by, for example, the hypothesis that 2@2 < @! . (2) The condition (ii), that the ideal I be !-presaturated, is certainly easier to achieve than the condition that I be presaturated. If ı is a Woodin cardinal and G Coll.!2 ; <ı/
692
9 Extensions of L.; R/
is V -generic, then in V ŒG, the nonstationary ideal on !2 is precipitous and JNS is !-presaturated. By Shelah’s theorem, Theorem 9.121, JNS cannot be presaturated and by Theorem 9.136 one cannot hope to provably strengthen (a). For example if ı 12 D !2 in V and there is a measurable cardinal above ı, then in V ŒG there can be no normal, uniform, !-presaturated ideal on !2 which does not contain JNS . In fact if I 2 V ŒG is any normal uniform ideal which contains the set S! .!2 / D ¹˛ < !2 j cof.˛/ D !º; then forcing over V ŒG with the quotient algebra P .!2 /=I must collapse !1 . u t Theorem 9.134. Suppose that I P .!2 / is a normal, uniform, ideal such that (i) ¹˛ < !2 j cof.˛/ D !º 2 I , (ii) I is !-presaturated, (iii) P .!2 /=I is @! -cc. Suppose that M is a transitive inner model containing the reals such that M ZF C DC C AD and such that every set X 2 P .R/ \ M is weakly homogeneously Suslin in V . Then ‚M !2 . t u
Proof. By Lemma 10.65(2) and Theorem 10.63.
Theorem 9.135. Assume that there is a measurable cardinal and that there is a normal, uniform, !3 -saturated ideal on !2 . Then ı12 < !2 . t u
Proof. By Lemma 10.65(1) and Theorem 10.62. Theorem 9.136. Assume that there is a measurable cardinal and suppose that I P .!2 /
is a normal uniform ideal such that ¹˛ < !2 j cof.˛/ D !º 2 I . Suppose that 2@2 D @3 and that .!1 /V D .!1 /V
P
where P D .P .!2 / n I; /. Then ı12 < !2 . Proof. By Lemma 10.65(3) and Theorem 10.62.
t u
9.7 Ideals on !2
693
We end this chapter with two consistency results which can be obtained. As we have previously noted, .Shelah 2008/ proves that ˘! .!2 / follows from 2!1 D !2 and so in particular if 2!1 D !2 then by Theorem 9.127, JNS cannot be semi-saturated. Our original motivation for obtaining the kind of results below concerned the consistency strength of ZF C ADR C “‚ is regular”: The point is that the existence of a !3 -saturated ideal on !2 seems likely to be quite strong – beyond the level of superstrong cardinals – and so obtaining approximations starting from a model of ADR in which ‚ is regular might provide evidence that this theory is also quite strong – with consistency strength beyond that of superstrong cardinals. However recent results of .Sargsyan 2009/ have shown that the consistency strength of ZF C ADR C “‚ is regular” is below that of a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Theorem 9.137. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages, S Ord, and that L.S; ; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose G0 Pmax is L.S; ; R/-generic. Suppose H0 Coll.!3 ; H.!3 //L.S;;R/ŒG0 is L.S; ; R/ŒG0 -generic. Then in L.S; ; R/ŒG0 ŒH0 the following hold. (1) Martin’s MaximumCC .c/. (2) JNS is precipitous. (3) JNS is weakly presaturated.
t u
Theorem 9.138. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages, S Ord, and that L.S; ; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose that G0 Pmax is L.S; ; R/-generic and that H0 Coll.!3 ; H.!3 //L.S;;R/ŒG0 is L.S; ; R/ŒG0 -generic. Then in L.S; ; R/ŒG0 ŒH0 : (1) Martin’s MaximumCC .c/. (2) For each stationary set S ¹˛ < !2 j cof.˛/ D !º there is a normal uniform ideal I P .!2 / such that a) JNS I and S … I , b) I is semi-saturated.
t u
Chapter 10
Further results
One fundamental open question is the consistency of Martin’s Maximum with the axiom ./. The results of Section 10.2 strongly suggest that Martin’s Maximum does not imply ./ even in the context of large cardinal assumptions. The situation for Martin’s MaximumCC seems more subtle, these issues are discussed briefly at the beginning of Section 10.2.4. However we shall also prove in Section 10.2 that the axiom ./ is independent of Martin’s MaximumCC .c/. This will follow from Theorem 9.39 and Theorem 10.70. Nevertheless the axiom ./ can be characterized in terms of a bounded form of Martin’s Maximum, this is main result of Section 10.3. Such variations of Martin’s Maximum were introduced by Goldstern and Shelah. Theorem 2.53 shows that forcing axioms can be reformulated as reflection principles. A natural question therefore is whether Martin’s Maximum is implied by the axiom ./ together with some natural reflection principle such as the principle SRP of Todorcevic. Theorem 10.1 (Larson (Martin’s Maximum)). Suppose that axiom ./ holds. Then there is an .!1 ; 1/-distributive partial order P such that V P ZFC C SRP C :Martin’s Maximum C Axiom./:
t u
A stronger reflection principle is Martin’s Maximum./ where is the class of .!; 1/-distributive partial orders P such that .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\ V:
This special case of Martin’s Maximum has been studied by Q. Feng, he defines this as the Cofinal Branch Principle (CBP). It is easily verified that CBP implies SRP. Theorem 10.2 (Larson (Martin’s Maximum)). Suppose that axiom ./ holds. Then there is an .!1 ; 1/-distributive partial order P such that V P ZFC C CBP C :Martin’s Maximum C Axiom./:
t u
10.1 Forcing notions and large cardinals The question of the relationship between Martin’s MaximumCC and the axiom ./ leads to a deeper question. This concerns what can be (provably) accomplished (using large cardinals) by forcing notions which preserve !1 . If one drops the requirement that
10.1 Forcing notions and large cardinals
695
the forcing notions preserve !1 then once there are Woodin cardinals then essentially anything can be accomplished (at least if V is any of the current inner models). We give some definitions and state without proof some results relevant to this somewhat general question. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC. Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M and that EQ D hE˛ W ˛ < ıi is a weakly coherent Doddage in Mı such that the sequence is in M and the sequence witnesses that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M . More precisely: (1) For each ˛ < ı, E˛ is a set of . ˛ ; ı˛ /-extenders which are ı˛ -strong and of hypermeasure type; i. e. for each E 2 E˛ , cp.jE / D ˛ and jE . ˛ / ı˛ . (2) ı˛ is strongly inaccessible and ı˛ ıˇ < ı if ˛ < ˇ < ı. (3) E˛ 2 Mı and EQ 2 M . Q \ Vı D EQ \ Vı for each E 2 E˛ . (4) (Weak coherence) jE .E/ ˛ ˛ (5) For each A 2 M; A Mı there exists < ı such that for all < ı jE .A/ \ D A \
for some extender E 2 [¹E˛ j ˛ < ıº with cp.jE / D . Here for each extender E 2 M , jE W M ! N is the corresponding elementary embedding. Q is a partial function An iteration scheme for .M; E/ I W H.!1 / ! H.!1 / Q of limit length and if T is consuch that if T is a countable iteration tree on .M; E/ sistent with I then T is in the domain of I and I.T / is a cofinal wellfounded branch for T . T is consistent with I if for every limit ordinal ˛ < length.T /, T j˛ is in the domain of I and I.T j˛/ is the branch defined by T j.˛ C 1/. We also require that for Q which are consistent with I , every model occurring in all iteration trees T on .M; E/ T is wellfounded. Remark 10.3. (1) There are various notions of coherence one can use. The notion used here is a weakening of the conventional notion. (2) Note that if ı is a Woodin cardinal then the trivial Doddage is weakly coherent and witnesses that ı is a Woodin cardinal. For the trivial Doddage h. ˛ ; ı˛ / W ˛ < ıi is the standard enumeration and E˛ is the set of all . ˛ ; ı˛ /extenders which are ı˛ -strong (and of hypermeasure type). The standard enumeration is defined by using the lexicographical order on hmax.˛; ˇ/; ˛; ˇi.
696
10 Further results
(3) We restrict to iteration trees which are nonoverlapping and normal in the sense of .Martin and Steel 1994/. The notion of an iteration scheme is defined there in terms of winning strategies in iteration games. t u We say that an iteration scheme I is < -weakly homogeneously Suslin if the associated set of reals I is < -weakly homogeneously Suslin. The set of reals I is defined by fixing a surjection W R ! H.!1 / which is definable in hH.!1 /; 2i. I is the preimage of I under . The canonical choice for is 1 definable in hH.!1 /; 2i. Definition 10.4. Weakly Homogeneous Iteration Hypothesis (WHIH): (1) There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. (2) There exist a Woodin cardinal ı and a weakly coherent Doddage hE˛ W ˛ < ıi which witnesses ı is a Woodin cardinal such that if > ı and is inaccessible then there exists a countable elementary substructure X V such that Q 2 X, a) ¹ı; Eº b) hM; EQM i has a iteration scheme which is 1 -homogeneously Suslin, where M is the transitive collapse of X and EQM is the image of EQ under the collapsing map. u t WHIH holds in all of the current inner models in which there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. The existence of 1 -weakly homogeneously Suslin iteration schemes for a countQ trivializes the question of what can happen in set generic extenable structure hM; Ei sions of M . If M elementarily embeds into a rank initial segment of V then similarly essentially anything can happen in some generic extension of V . Q is a countable structure where EQ is a weakly coherent Theorem 10.5. Suppose hM; Ei Doddage in M witnessing that ı is a Woodin cardinal for some ı 2 M . Suppose there Q which is 1 -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then is a an iteration scheme for hM; Ei any sentence true in a rank initial segment of V is true in a rank initial segment of a set generic extension of M . t u Theorem 10.6. Suppose there are ! 2 many Woodin cardinals less than . Suppose Q is a countable structure where EQ is a weakly coherent Doddage in M witnesshM; Ei ing that ı is a Woodin cardinal for some ı 2 M . Suppose there is a an iteration scheme Q which is < -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then there is a set R such for hM; Ei that M. / is a symmetric extension of M for set forcing and t u M. / ADC :
10.1 Forcing notions and large cardinals
697
Since the symmetric extension M. / is a model of ADC , the analysis of both Pmax and Qmax can be carried out in M. /. This yields the following corollary. Theorem 10.7. Suppose there are ! 2 many Woodin cardinals less than . Suppose Q is a countable structure where EQ is a weakly coherent Doddage in M witnesshM; Ei ing that ı is a Woodin cardinal for some ı 2 M . Suppose there is a an iteration scheme Q which is < -weakly homogeneously Suslin. Then: for hM; Ei (1) There is a set generic extension of M in which the axiom ./ holds. (2) There is a set generic extension of M in which the nonstationary ideal on !1 is t u !1 -dense. As a corollary we obtain, for example: Theorem 10.8 (WHIH). There exists a partial order P such that V P ./:
t u
We now generalize the notion of an iteration scheme to allow the use of generic elementary embeddings in the construction of the iterations. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC. Suppose that ı0 ; ı1 are Woodin cardinals in M with ı0 < ı1 . Suppose hE˛ W ˛ < ı1 i is a weakly coherent Doddage of sets of extenders in Mı1 such that the sequence is in M and the sequence witnesses that Q is a function ı1 is a Woodin cardinal in M . A mixed iteration scheme for hM; ı0 ; Ei which assigns to each countable generic iteration hMˇ ; Gˇ ; j˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ i an iteration scheme for .M ; EQ / where: (1) M0 D M , G0 is M -generic for the stationary tower forcing P<ı0 defined in M . (2) j˛ˇ W M˛ ! Mˇ is a commuting system of elementary embeddings. (3) G˛ is M˛ -generic for the stationary tower forcing j0;˛ .P<ı0 /. (4) M˛C1 is the generic ultrapower of M˛ given by G˛ and j˛;˛C1 is the corresponding elementary embedding. (5) For each limit ordinal 0 < ˛, M˛ is the direct limit of hMˇ W ˇ < ˛i. Q (6) EQ D j0; .E/. We can view a mixed iteration scheme as a partial function I W H.!1 / ! H.!1 /:
698
10 Further results
We formulate a mixed iteration hypothesis (MIH) in the following definition. Definition 10.9 (MIH).
(1) There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.
(2) There exist a Woodin cardinals ı0 < ı1 and a weakly coherent Doddage EQ D hE˛ W ˛ < ı1 i which witnesses ı1 is a Woodin cardinal such that if ı1 < and if is inaccessible then there exists a countable elementary substructure, X V containing ı0 ; ı1 and EQ such that hM; ı0M ; EQM i has a mixed iteration scheme which is 1 -homogeneously Suslin. Here M is Q under the the transitive collapse of X and .ı0M ; EQM / is the image of .ı0 ; E/ collapsing map. t u A variant of MIH which we denote by MIH is obtained by modifying part (2) replacing ı0 by !1 , adding the assumption that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is precipitous and considering mixed iterations where first one iterates by generic ultrapowers using the nonstationary ideal instead of using the stationary tower. All of the large cardinals within reach of the current inner model theory are (relatively) consistent with the existence of a wellordering of the reals which is †21 .1 -WH/, over the base theory ZFC C “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals”: A natural conjecture is that any large cardinal with an inner model theory is consistent 2 1 with a † 1 . -WH/ wellordering of the reals. This can be proved with certain general assumptions on the inner models. 2 1 t Theorem 10.10 (MIH or MIH ). There is no † 1 . -WH/ wellordering of the reals. u
A weaker requirement is simply that for all x 2 R, ¹xº is OD if and only if there exists A 2 1 such that x is OD in L.A; R/ This, which essentially asserts there is a “good” wellordering of the reals in HOD, is not violated by MIH. It may seem unlikely that any reasonable large cardinal hypothesis will actually imply MIH. Nevertheless one can show that MIH is consistent. In fact there are fairly Q which general circumstances under which there exist countable structures hM; ı0 ; Ei do have mixed iteration schemes that are 1 -homogeneously Suslin. Lemma 10.11. Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Then there is a Q for which there is a mixed iteration scheme which is countable structure hM; ı0 ; Ei 1 -homogeneously Suslin. t u
10.1 Forcing notions and large cardinals
699
A more general version of this is given in the next theorem. Theorem 10.12. Assume there is a proper class of measurable cardinals which are limits of Woodin cardinals. Then for each ordinal ˛ there exists a transitive inner model containing the ordinals such that (1) V˛ N , (2) N ZFC C MIH, WH N WH (3) .1 / 1 .
t u
The existence of 1 -homogeneously Suslin mixed iteration schemes for a countable Q trivializes the question of what can happen in set generic extenstructure hM; ı0 ; Ei sions of M which preserve !1M . Q is a countable structure for which there is a Theorem 10.13. Suppose hM; ı0 ; Ei 1 mixed iteration scheme which is -homogeneously Suslin. Then any sentence true in a rank initial segment of V is true in a rank initial segment of a set generic extension t u of M which preserves stationary subsets of !1M . Thus for example; assuming MIH anything true in a rank initial segment of a set generic extension of V is true in a rank initial segment of a set generic extension of V which preserves stationary subsets of !1 . This also follows from MIH . By Theorem 10.7: Theorem 10.14. Assume MIH or MIH . Then: (1) There is a set generic extension of V preserving stationary subsets of !1 in which the axiom ./ holds. (2) There is a set generic extension of V preserving stationary subsets of !1 in which t u the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. Posets which preserve stationary subsets of !1 are semiproper assuming Martin’s Maximum. Theorem 10.15 (MIH or MIH ). Assume Martin’s MaximumCC . Then the axiom ./ holds. t u We end this section with three more theorems. The first two give fairly general examples of situations where essentially any sentence can be forced to hold by stationary set preserving forcing notions. The third gives a specific situation where this fails. Suppose that S !1 is a stationary set. Let P .S / be the partial order of countable closed subsets of S ordered by extension (Harrington forcing). Suppose that X P .!1 / n INS . Let Y Q.X / D P .S / S2X
700
10 Further results
where the product is computed with countable support. If the normal filter generated by X is proper then Q.X / is .!; 1/-distributive. Theorem 10.16. Suppose that there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that ı is a measurable cardinal, is a normal ultrafilter on ı and that G Coll.!; <ı/ Q. / is V -generic. Suppose that is a †2 sentence and that there exists a partial order P 2 Vı such that V P : Then there exists a partial partial order Q 2 V ŒG such that Q
(1) .INS /V ŒG D V ŒG \ .INS /V ŒG , (2) V ŒGQ .
t u
Theorem 10.17. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ZF C DC C ADR and such that every set in is 1 -homogeneously Suslin. There exists a countable set a0 !1 such that L.;R/ Œa 0 a0 !1HOD and such that the following holds where M D HODL.;R/ Œa0 : Suppose that is a †2 -sentence such that for some partial order P , V P : Then there exists a countable set a !1 such that (1) .INS /M D M \ .INS /M Œa , (2) M Œa .
t u
Note that the set a indicated in Theorem 10.17 is set generic over M (by Vopenka’s Theorem). Theorem 10.18. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ZF C DC C ADR : There exists a †2 -sentence such that the following hold where M D HODL.;R/ and where ı D .‚0 /L.;R/ .
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
701
(1) M Œa for some countable set a !1 . (2) Suppose that G Coll.!; ı/ is V -generic and b ı is a set in M ŒG such that M Œb : Let F be the closed, unbounded, filter on .!1 /M Œb as computed in M Œb. Then for each x 2 .R/M Œb , F \ .M ŒxŒF / t u
is an ultrafilter.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 // In this section we define three Pmax variations for obtaining extensions in which previously specified sets of reals are coded into the structure hH.!2 /; 2i: Q.X/ max ,
One of these variations, is actually a variation of Qmax and in the resulting extension, the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense. This we use to show that it is possible for the nonstationary ideal to be !1 -dense simultaneously with, for example, R# 2 L.P .!1 //: .;/ The second, Pmax , is a special case of the corresponding variation of Pmax . One appli.;/ cation of Pmax will be the construction of a model in which Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ holds and in which the axiom ./ fails; in fact we shall show that
Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture together with all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/i does not imply ./. .;;B/ The third variation, Pmax , involves a parameter B R. The main application of this variation will be to show that given Y0 R with Y0 2 L.R/, Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture together with all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; Y0 ; 2i does not imply ./. These results show that Theorem 4.76, which characterizes when ./ holds in terms of absoluteness, is optimal in that the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/i cannot be simplified in any essential way.
702
10 Further results
One obvious approach to coding information into L.P .!1 // is indicated in the next lemma. Lemma 10.19. Suppose that for each set A R there exists a sequence hB˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i of borel sets such that AD
[ \ ˛
B˛;ˇ :
ˇ >˛
Then: (1) P .R/ L.P .!1 //. (2) For each function f W R ! R there exists a set a !1 such that for all x 2 R, f \ L.a; x/ 2 L.a; x/:
t u
The following theorem is well known. The proof is an easy exercise using Solovay’s method for generically coding information using almost disjoint families in P .!/. Theorem 10.20. There is a -centered boolean algebra B such that if GB is V -generic then in V ŒG the following holds. Suppose A R. Then there exists a sequence hB˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i of borel sets such that [ \ AD t u B˛;ˇ : ˛
ˇ >˛
There is a Pmax version of Theorem 10.20, involving quite different methods. The effect is similar in that one can arrange for example in the resulting extension that there exists a sequence, hB˛;ˇ W ˛ < ˇ < !1 i, of borel sets such that [ \ R# D B˛;ˇ : ˛
ˇ >˛
This, together with the assertion that L.R/ AD C ; is expressible by a †2 sentence in hH.!2 /; 2i. There must exist a choice of such that L.R/ and such that this †2 sentence cannot be realized in the structure P
hH.!2 /; 2iL.R/
for any partial order P 2 L.R/. Of course this is a trivial claim if P is .!; 1/distributive in L.R/. The general case, for arbitrary partial orders P 2 L.R/, is more subtle. It is a plausible conjecture that if L.R/ AD
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
703
then there exists a partial order P 2 L.R/ such that L.R/P ZFC C “R# exists”: It is not difficult to show that if INS is !2 -saturated and if B is any -centered boolean algebra, then INS is !2 -saturated in V B . Thus obtaining models in which INS is !2 -saturated and in which L.P .!1 // is large is straightforward. However if one requires that INS be !1 -dense then the problem appears to be far more subtle. One indication is provided by the theorem of Shelah (see Theorem 3.50); if INS is !1 -dense then 2@0 D 2@1 . Therefore if INS is !1 -dense then necessarily there exists a set A R which is not !1 -borel. Nevertheless one can probably define a variation of Qmax via which one obtains extensions of, say L.R# /, in which INS is !1 -dense and in which R# is !1 -borel. Finally our particular approach to coding sets into L.P .!1 // is chosen with the .;/ .;;B/ particular kind of applications discussed above in mind, (involving Pmax and Pmax ). .;/ .X/ One can easily define the general version of Pmax obtaining Pmax corresponding to .X/ Q.X/ max . Using Pmax one can show that it is possible to realize all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/i and yet have R 2 L.P .!1 //. However suppose that #
L.R/ AD and that for each …2 -sentence , if Pmax
hH.!2 /; INS iL.R/
then hH.!2 /; 2i . Then it is easily verified that R# is not !1 -borel.
10.2.1 Coding by sets, SQ We define our basic coding machinery. For this we recall Definition 5.2, which for each set S !1 defines SQ to be the set of < !2 such that (1) !1 , (2) if h W !1 ! is a surjection then ¹˛ j ordertype.hŒ˛/ … S º 2 INS : Suppose < !2 , !1 and that A . The set A is stationary in if A\C ¤; for each C such that C is closed and cofinal in . Of course if A is stationary in then has cofinality !1 . We caution that this notion that A is stationary in does not coincide with the notion that a is stationary in b as defined in Definition 2.33 unless D !1 .
704
10 Further results
Suppose hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 . For each < !2 let b D ¹i < ! j SQi \ is stationary in º: Given X P .!/, the most natural way to have X definable in H.!2 / would be to have X [ ¹;º D ¹b j < !2 º for a suitable choice of hSi W i < !i. This we cannot quite arrange. For technical reasons we shall thin the sequence hb W < !2 i and, in essence, obtain X [ ¹;º D ¹b j < !2 º for a suitable choice of hSi W i < !i. This thinning will be definable in H.!2 / and more precisely X [ ¹;º D ¹c j < !2 º where for each < !2 ,
c D ¹i j 2iC1 2 b º:
Suppose Y P .!/. An ordinal is a Y -uniform indiscernible if is an indiscernible of LŒa for each a 2 Y . We caution that the Y -uniform indiscernibles are not necessarily Y Y -uniform indiscernibles. However the following lemma is easily proved. Lemma 10.21. Suppose that R is a nonempty set such that for all a 2 !1 º D min¹ 2 S j > !1 º where (i) !1 D sup¹.!1 /LŒx j x 2 º, (ii) S is the set of -uniform indiscernibles, (iii) S is the set of -uniform indiscernibles. Then S n !1 D S .
t u
Definition 10.22. Suppose that hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 and suppose that z !. Let S D hSi W i < !i. We associate to the pair .S; z/ two subsets of P .!/; X(Code) .S; z/ D [¹X j < ıº and Y(Code) .S; z/ D [¹Y j < ıº where S(Code) .S; z/ D h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi is the maximal sequence generated from .S; z/ as follows.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
705
(i) Y0 D ¹zº, X0 D ¹;º, and 0 is the least indiscernible of LŒz above !1 . (ii) For all a 2 Y , a# exists and is the least Y -uniform indiscernible, , such that ˛ < for all ˛ < . (iii) Suppose is not the successor of an ordinal of cofinality !1 . Then X D [¹X˛ j ˛ < º and Y D [¹Y˛ j ˛ < º: (iv) Suppose has cofinality !1 and let b D ¹i < ! j SQi is stationary in º: iC1 2 bº and let d D ¹i < ! j 3iC1 2 bº. Let c D ¹i < ! j 2 a) YC1 D Y [ ¹d º, b) suppose that < where is the least indiscernible of LŒd above !1 , then XC1 D X [ ¹cº; otherwise XC1 D X . (v) < !2 . Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC, S 2 M, and that S D hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets such that for all i < !, Si 2 .P .!1 / n INS /M : Suppose z ! and z 2 M. Let S(Code) .M; S; z/ D .S(Code) .S; z//M ; let X(Code) .M; S; z/ D .X(Code) .S; z//M ; and let
Y(Code) .M; S; z/ D .Y(Code) .S; z//M :
t u
Remark 10.23. (1) It might seem more natural to define the set b ! in (iv) using the first ! many uniform Y -uniform indiscernibles. This would allow the use of single stationary set S in the decoding process instead of a sequence hSi W i < !i of stationary sets. In fact such an approach is possible, the details are quite similar. One advantage is that with further modifications the coded set, X, is †1 definable, from parameters, in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i; instead of the expanded structure, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i. For our applications this feature is at best more difficult to achieve; cf. Theorem 10.55, and there are more elegant ways to achieve this (by simply making the coded set !1 -borel).
706
10 Further results
However one can, by further refinements, arrange in the resulting extension that there exists A !1 such that if N is any transitive set such that A 2 N, .INS /N D INS \ N , N ZFC , then N “2@0 D @2 ”. This yields a †2 sentence in the language of the structure, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i; which if true implies c D !2 . (2) The sequence h W < ıi can be generated in a variety of ways rather just using the Y -uniform indiscernibles. Similarly the condition (iv)(b) can be modified to further thin the sequence. This in effect we shall do in Section 10.2.4, see Definition 10.72 and and the subsequent Remark 10.73. (3) If for every x 2 R, x # exists, then S(Code) .S; z/ has length !2 . (4) The requirement that X0 D ¹;º, rather than X0 D ;, is just for convenience. u t We extend these notions to sequences of models. Definition 10.24. Suppose hMk W k < !i is a sequence such that for all k < !, (1) for each t 2 R \ Mk , t # 2 MkC1 , (2) Mk is countable, transitive and Mk ZFC; (3) Mk MkC1 and
.!1 /Mk D .!1 /MkC1 ;
(4) .INS /MkC1 \ Mk D .INS /MkC2 \ Mk . Suppose S 2 M0 ,
S D hSi W i < !i
and that S is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets such that for all i < !, Si 2 .P .!1 / n INS /M1 : Suppose z ! and z 2 M0 . Let S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ D h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi;
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
707
let X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ D [¹X j < ıº; and let Y(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ D [¹Y j < ıº; where h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi is the maximal sequence such that for all < ı, there exists n 2 ! with h. ˛ ; X˛ ; Y˛ / W ˛ < i D S(Code) .Mk ; S; z/ j t u
for all k > n.
Suppose that hMk W k < !i is a sequence of countable transitive sets satisfying the conditions in Definition 10.24. We note that since for all k < !, .INS /MkC1 \ Mk D .INS /MkC2 \ Mk M
the following holds. Suppose k < !, S 2 .P .!1 //M0 and that ˛ < !2 k . Then for all i > k, Q MkC1 : .SQ /Mi \ ˛ D .S/ This observation yields the following important corollary which concerns the behavior of X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ under iterations. Suppose that j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is an iteration. Then j ŒX(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; j.S/; z/ and
j ŒY(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ Y(Code) .hMk W k < !i; j.S/; z/:
In many situations if one defines j.S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z// [¹j.S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/j / j < ıº: then one actually obtains j.X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z// D X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; j.S/; z/ and
j.Y(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z// D Y(Code) .hMk W k < !i; j.S/; z/:
These claims are easily verified using the properties (1)–(3) of Definition 10.24. It certainly can happen that X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ 2 M0 : Thus if
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i
is an iteration it may be that j.X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z// does not coincide with the definition given above. In the cases we shall be interested in, X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ 2 M0 and the two possible definitions of j.X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z// coincide, cf. Remark 10.27(5).
708
10 Further results
10.2.2 Q.X/ max Suppose the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense and there are infinitely many Woodin cardinals with a measurable cardinal above. The covering theorems show that L.P .!1 // is close to L.R/ below ‚L.R/ . A natural question is whether it must necessarily be the case that L.P .!1 // is a generic extension of L.R/ or whether covering must hold between L.P .!1 // and L.R/. We note that assuming AD L.R/ D L.P .!1 // and so covering trivially holds between these inner models in this case. We focus on the case when the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense since this case is the most restrictive. It eliminates the possibility that sets appear in L.P .!1 // because they are coded into the structure of the boolean algebra P .!1 /=INS : Suppose that X P .!/ is a set such that L.X; R/ ADC : .X/ We define a variation, Q.X/ max , of Qmax such that if G Qmax is L.X; R/-generic then in L.X; R/ŒG, the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense and X 2 L.P .!1 //. In fact in L.X; R/ŒG, X is a definable subset of H.!2 /. Thus, for example, if X codes R# then in L.X; R/ŒG, R# 2 L.P .!1 //: Before defining Q.X/ max it is convenient to define a refinement of Qmax .
Definition 10.25. Q max is the set of .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax for which the following holds. For all k < ! there exists x 2 R \ MkC1 such that for all C !1M0 if C 2 Mk and if C is closed and unbounded in !1M0 , then D \ .!1M0 n C / is bounded in !1M0 where D !1M0 is the set of < !1M0 such that is an indiscernible of LŒx. t u Suppose f W !1 ! H.!1 / be a function such that for all ˛ < !1 , f .˛/ is a filter in Coll.!; ˛/. Let Sf be the sequence hSi W i < !i where for each i < !, Si D ¹˛ < !1 j ¹.0; i /º 2 f .˛/º:
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
709
Definition 10.26. Suppose that X P .!/: Q.X/ max
is the set of triples .hMk W k < !i; f; z/
such that the following hold. (1) .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Q max . (2) For all k < !, Mk ZFC C CH. (3) z ! and z # 2 M0 . (4) Let h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi D S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z/ be the associated sequence. Then there exist sequences hıi W i < !i and hxi W i < !i such that ı D sup¹ıi j i < !º and for all i < ! a) ı0 < !2M0 and ıiC1 D ıi C !1M0 , b) xi !, xi 2 Mi and xi# … Mi , c) S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z/jıi D S(Code) .Mi ; Sf ; z/jıi , d) Ord \ Mi < where is the least indiscernible of LŒxi above !1M0 , e) Xıi D Xı0 , f) Y.ıi C1/ D Yı0 [ ¹xj j j i º. (5) Suppose j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is a countable iteration of .hMk W k < !i; f /. Then j.X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z// X [ ¹;º: The order is defined as follows: .hNk W k < !i; g; y/ < .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ if .hNk W k < !i; g/ < .hMk W k < !i; f / in
Qmax
and y D z.
t u
710
10 Further results
Remark 10.27. (1) There are natural Q.X/ max variations for each Pmax -variation we .;/ have considered. We shall consider Pmax in Section 10.2.3. We analyze the Q.X/ max -extension first because the analysis is a little more subtle than that of the .;/ Pmax -extension. We also shall use the results of this analysis to simplify presen.;/ tation of Pmax , but this of course is not essential. (2) Suppose .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max : Then since .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax it follows that for all x 2 R \ Mk , x # 2 MkC1 . (3) By (4(d)) and (4(f)), [¹Mk \ Ord j k < !º is the least .[¹P .!/ \ Mk j k < !º/-uniform indiscernible above !1M0 . (4) By (4(f)), Ord \ Mi < .ıi C1/ . Thus S(Code) .M0 ; Sf ; z/ D S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/jı0 : (5) By (4(g)), X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z/ 2 M0 and further if j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is an iteration, then the two possible interpretations of j.X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; S; z// coincide.
t u
We note the following corollary to Lemma 10.21. Lemma 10.28. Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max : Let h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi D S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z/ be the associated sequence and let Y D [¹Y j < ıº: Let Z D [¹P .!/ \ Mk j k < !º: Let IY be the set of Y -uniform indiscernibles, , such that !1M0 and let IZ be the set of Z-uniform indiscernibles. Then IY D IZ :
t u Q.X/ max .
We now come to the main theorem for the existence of conditions in This theorem is much weaker than the existence theorems we have proved for the other Pmax variations we have analyzed. The reason for this difference lies in the nature of the Q.X/ max conditions. Suppose .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max :
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
711
Then there must exist x 2 M0 \ R such that x # … M0 . Therefore hH.!1 /M0 ; 2i 6 hH.!1 /; 2i: This rules out the forms of A-iterability which we have used for the analysis of these other Pmax variations. We will of course use A-iterable structures in the analysis of the Q.X/ max -extension, but the actual details of this use will differ slightly when compared to previous instances. One could quite easily develop the analysis of the Pmax -extension along these lines and so these differences are not really fundamental. Theorem 10.29. Suppose that X P .!/ and that for each t 2 R, t # exists. Suppose x0 2 X and x1 2 R. Then there exists .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max such that (1) .x0 ; x1 / 2 LŒz, (2) Gf is LŒz-generic where Gf Coll.!;
1 be the least ¹zk j k < !º-uniform indiscernible above 0 . These are the least two elements of \¹Ck j k < !º. For each k < ! let ık be the least element of CkC1 . Therefore
0 D sup¹ık j k < !º: Construct by induction a sequence hgk ; hk W k < !i of generics such that (1.1) gk Coll .!; Ck \ ık /, gk is LŒzk -generic, and gk 2 LŒzkC1 , (1.2) hk Coll .!; ¹ık º/ hk is LŒzk Œgk -generic, and hk 2 LŒzkC1 . Construct by induction a sequence hGk W k < !i of generics such that the following conditions are satisfied. As in the proof of Theorem 6.64 these conditions uniquely specify the generics. For each k < ! let bk D ¹2iC1 j i 2 x0 º [ ¹3iC1 j i 2 zk º:
712
10 Further results
(2.1) Gk Coll .!; Ck \ 0 / and Gk is LŒzk -generic. (2.2) Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ ık / D gk . (2.3) Gk \ Coll .!; ¹ık º/ D hk . (2.4) For all ˛ 2 CkC1 \ 0 ,
Gk \ Coll .!; .˛; ˇ// is the LŒzkC1 ŒgŒh-least filter, F , such that a) F is LŒzk ŒgŒh-generic, b) for all < ˛ and for all i 2 bkC1 , ¹.0; i /º 2 F jColl .!; ¹ º/ $ ¹.0; i /º 2 G0 jColl .!; ¹ º/; c) for all < ˛ and for all i … bkC1 , ¹.0; !/º 2 F jColl .!; ¹ º/ $ ¹.0; i /º 2 G0 jColl .!; ¹ º/; where g D Gk \ Coll .!; Ck \ ˛/, h D GkC1 \ Coll .!; ¹˛º/, ˇ is the least element of CkC1 above ˛, and for each < ˛, is the th indiscernible of LŒzk above ˛.
Define
f W !1LŒG0 ! H.!1 /LŒG0
as follows. Suppose ˛ < !1LŒG0 . Then f .˛/ D ¹p 2 Coll.!; ˛/ j p 2 G0 º where for each p 2 Coll.!; ˛/, p is the condition in Coll .!; ¹˛º/ such that dom.p / D dom.p/ ¹˛º and such that p .k; ˛/ D p.k/ for all k 2 dom.p/. For each k < ! let Mk D L1 ŒzkC1 ŒGkC1 D L1 ŒzkC1 ŒG0 : Thus just as in the proof of Theorem 6.64, .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Qmax : Let S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z0 / D h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi: Thus ı D 0 !. For each ˛ < 0 , X˛ D ;, Y˛ D ¹z0 º and ˛ is the ˛ th indiscernible of LŒz0 above 0 . Further for each i < ! and for each ˛ < 0 , (3.1) Xˇ D ¹x0 º, (3.2) Yˇ D ¹zk j k i C 1º, (3.3) ˇ is the ˛ th indiscernible of LŒziC1 above 0 , where ˇ D . 0 .i C 1// C ˛. These follow in a straightforward fashion from the definitions of the generics Gk .
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
713
Therefore .hMk W k < !i; f; z0 / 2 Q.X/ max t u
and is as required. Lemma 10.30. Suppose .hNk W k < !i; g; z/ < .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ in
Q.X/ max
and let
j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i
be the .unique/ iteration such that j.f / D g. (1) X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z/ X(Code) .hNk W k < !i; Sg ; z/. (2) Suppose that h 2 M0 is a function such that ¹˛ < !1M0 j h.˛/ ¤ f .˛/º 2 .INS /M1 and suppose that x 2 M0 is a subset of ! such that .hMk W k < !i; h; x/ 2 Q.X/ max : Then .hNk W k < !i; j.h/; x/ 2 Q.X/ max and .hNk W k < !i; j.h/; x/ < .hMk W k < !i; h; x/: Proof. By the definition of the order in Q.X/ max , .hNk W k < !i; g/ < .hMk W k < !i; f / in
Qmax .
Therefore, since .j; hMk W k < !i; hMk W k < !i/ 2 N0 ;
for all k < !,
M
N0 N1 \ Mk D INS \ Mk : INS kC1 \ Mk D INS
From this it follows from the definitions that for all i < !, S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sg ; z/ is an initial segment of S(Code) .Ni ; Sg ; z/. Therefore S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sg ; z/ is an initial segment of S(Code) .hNk W k < !i; Sg ; z/: The first claim of the lemma, (1), follows by the elementarity of j . We prove (2). Note that .hNk W k < !i; j.h/; x/ 2 Q max and .hNk W k < !i; j.h/; x/ < .hMk W k < !i; h; x/ in
Q max .
714
10 Further results
Let h. ˛ ; X˛ ; Y˛ / W ˛ < ıi D S(Code) .Ni ; Sg ; z/: and let ˛0 be such that for all i < !, S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; j.Sf /; z/ D S(Code) .Ni ; j.Sf /; z/j˛0 : Since .hMk W k < !i; h; x/ 2 Q.X/ max it follows that
.hMk W k < !i; j.h/; x/ 2 Q.X/ max :
By an argument similar to that just given, for all i < !, S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; j.Sh /; x/ is an initial segment of S(Code) .Ni ; j.Sh /; x/. Let h. ˛0 ; X˛0 ; Y˛0 / W ˛ < ı 0 i D S(Code) .hNk W k < !i; j.Sh /; x/ and let ˛00 be such that for all i < !, S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; j.Sh /; x/ D S(Code) .Ni ; j.Sh /; x/j˛00 : Let ı0 be such that
Y.ı0 0 C1/ D Yı00 [ ¹t º
for some t 2 M0 such that t # … M0 . This uniquely specifies ı0 as the witness for .hMk W k < !i; j.h/; x/ 2 Q.X/ max to clause (4) in the definition of Q.X/ max . Thus ˛00 D ı0 C !1N0 ! and so ˛00 has cofinality !. Necessarily ı 0 > ˛00 . Let Z D [¹P .!/ \ Mk j k < !º and let
Z D [¹P .!/ \ Mk j k < !º:
Since .hMk W k < !i; j.f // is an iterate of .hMk W k < !i; f / and since .hMk W k < !i; f / 2 Q max ; it follows that the Z -uniform indiscernibles above !1N0 coincide with the Z-uniform indiscernibles above !1N0 . Since .hMk W k < !i; j.h/; x/ 2 Q.X/ max it follows that the Y˛0 0 -uniform indiscernibles above !1N0 coincide with the Z -uniform indiscernibles above !1N0 . Further these coincide with the Y˛0 -uniform indiscernibles above !1N0 .
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
715
Finally j.h/.˛/ D g.˛/ for all ˛ < !1N0 such that ˛ is a Z-uniform indiscernible and such that ˛ > !1M0 . Therefore by induction on it follows that if ˛0 C < ı then 0 Y.˛0 C / n Y˛0 D Y.˛ n Y˛0 0 0 C / 0
and
0
0 X.˛0 C / n X˛0 D X.˛ n X˛0 0 : 0 C / 0
0
t u
(2) follows. Remark 10.31. There is an important difference between Q.X/ max and Qmax . Suppose
.hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max ; and h 2 M0 is a function such that ¹˛ < !1M0 j h.˛/ ¤ f .˛/º 2 .INS /M1 : Then in general .hMk W k < !i; h; x/ … Q.X/ max for any choice of x. This will cause problems in the analysis that follows. This difficulty does not arise in the case of Qmax . t u Lemma 10.32. Suppose that X P .!/. Suppose that .hNk W k < !i; g; x/ 2 Q.X/ max ; .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max ; and t ! codes hMk W k < !i. Suppose t 2 LŒx and G is LŒx-generic where G Coll.!;
716
10 Further results
Proof. (3) is an immediate consequence of (2) and the definition of the order on Q.X/ max . (2) follows from (4) since .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 N0 : To see this suppose k W hNk W k < !i ! hk.Nk / W k < !i is a countable iteration. Then by elementarity it follows that k.X / D k.X(Code) .hNk W k < !i; Sg ; x// [ k.j.X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z/// where X D X(Code) .hNk W k < !i; j.Sf /; z/: Therefore k.X / X. We construct the iteration j to satisfy (1) and (4). Fix c0 2 X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z/ and let b0 D ¹2iC1 j i 2 c0 º [ ¹3iC1 j i 2 xº: Define a function g0 W !1N0 ! N0 by perturbing g as follows. Let C be the set of uniform [¹P .!/ \ Mk j k < !ºindiscernibles below !1N0 and above !1M0 . Let D C be the set of 2 C such that C \ has ordertype . For each ˛ < !1N0 , g0 .˛/ D g.˛/ unless ˛ D C ˇ where 2 D, ˇ < and ˇ is the ˇ th element of C past . In this case g0 .˛/ D g.˛/ if ¹.0; i /º 2 f .ˇ/ and i 2 b0 , otherwise g0 .˛/ D ¹¹.0; !/º _ p j p 2 g.˛/º: Let j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i be the iteration of length .!1 /N0 determined by g0 . Clearly j 2 LŒxŒG. We come to the key claims. Let S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z/ D h ; X ; Y W < ıi; let j.S(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z// D h ; X ; Y W < ı i; and let S(Code) .hNk W k < !i; j.Sf /; z/ D h ; X ; Y W < ı i:
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
717
The claims are the following: (1.1) For all ı ,
. ; X ; Y / D . ; X ; Y /:
(1.2) S(Code) .hNk W k < !i; Sg ; x/ is the sequence, h ı i: C ; Xı C n Xı ; .Yı C n Yı / [ ¹xº W ı C < ı
The first claim is immediate. The point is that [¹j..INS /Mk / j k < !º D .INS /N1 \ .[¹Mk j k < !º/ and that
[¹Mk \ Ord j k < !º
is the least [¹P .!/ \ Mk j k < !º-uniform indiscernible above !1N0 . The latter implies that sup¹ j < ı º D [¹Mk \ Ord j k < !º by clause (4(h)) in the definition of Q.X/ max . We prove the second claim. From the first claim Yı D [¹Y j < ı º
and
ı D [¹Mk \ Ord j k < !º:
Let Y D [¹Y j < ıº: Q.X/ max ,
it follows that the Y -uniform indiscernibles are exactly From the definition of the [¹R \ Mk j k < !º-uniform indiscernibles. For each ˇ < !1N0 , let ˇ be the ˇ th Y -uniform indiscernible above !1N0 . The key point is that the Y -uniform indiscernibles above !1N0 coincide with the Yı -uniform N0 N0 indiscernibles above !1 . Therefore for each ˇ < !1 , if ˇ 0 then ˇ D ı Cˇ : The iteration giving j was constructed using the function g0 , therefore j.f / and g0 agree on the critical sequence of the iteration. However the critical sequence of the iteration is exactly the set of Y -uniform indiscernibles between !1M0 and !1N0 and this is the set C specified above in the definition of g0 . Thus for each ˛ 2 C , g.˛/ D g0 .˛/ D j.f /.˛/: This proves (1). For each i ! let
Si D ¹˛ j ¹.0; i /º 2 g.˛/º
and let Ti D ¹˛ j ¹.0; i /º 2 j.f /.˛/º:
718
10 Further results
For each i !, let SQi be the set computed from Si and let TQi be the set computed from Ti , each computed relative to [¹Nk j k < !º. Thus for each ˇ < !1N0 and for each i < !, if i 2 b0 and if ˇ 2 Ti then ˇ 2 TQi otherwise ˇ 2 TQ! . For each i < !, Ti is stationary in [¹Nk j k < !º and so putting everything together, if D ı C !1N0 then (2.1) YC1 D Yı [ ¹xº, D Xı (2.2) XC1 [ ¹c0 º, (2.3) C1 is the least indiscernible of LŒx above !1N0 ,
(2.4) for each i !,
SQi \ Z D TQi \ Z where Z is the set of indiscernibles of such that is an indiscernible of LŒx and such that 2 [¹Nk j k < !º:
Thus j has the desired properties and this proves the lemma.
t u
The proof of Lemma 10.32 adapts to prove that Q.X/ max is !-closed. Lemma 10.33. Suppose that X P .!/ and that for all t 2 R, t # exists. Then Q.X/ max is !-closed. Proof. Suppose hpi W i < !i is a strictly decreasing sequence of conditions in Q.X/ max and that for each i < !, pi D .hMki W k < !i; fi ; z/: Let f D [¹fi j i < !º. For each i < ! let ji W hMki W k < !i ! hMO ki W k < !i be the iteration such that ji .fi / D f . This iteration exists since hpi W i < !i is a strictly decreasing sequence in Q.X/ max . We note the following properties of .hMO kk W k < !i; f; z/. (1.1) .hMO kk W k < !i; f / 2 Q max . (1.2) Let Then
Y D Y(Code) .hMO kk W k < !i; f; z/: [¹MO kk \ Ord j k < !º 0
is the least Y -uniform indiscernible above .!1 /M0 . (1.3) Suppose that
j W hMO kk W k < !i ! hj.MO kk / W k < !i is a countable iteration, then X(Code) .hj.MO kk / W k < !i; j.f /; z/ X [ ¹;º:
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
719
By Theorem 10.29 there exists .hNk W k < !i; g; x/ 2 Q.X/ max such that x codes hMO kk W k < !i and such that the filter H Coll.!;
The difficulty is that,
k
.hMO kk W k < !i; f; z/ … Q.X/ max :
Nevertheless the properties (1.1)–(1.3) suffice to implement the proof of Lemma 10.32. This yields an iteration j W hMO k W k < !i ! hj.MO k / W k < !i k
k
such that (2.1) j 2 N0 , (2.2) for all k < !,
Ok
.INS /j.Mk / D j.MO kk / \ .INS /N1 ; (2.3) .hNk W k < !i; j.f /; z/ 2 Q.X/ max . Thus .hNk W k < !i; j.f /; z/ < pi t u
for all i < !. One corollary of Lemma 10.30 and Lemma 10.32 is that Q.X/ max is homogeneous.
Lemma 10.34. Suppose that X P .!/ and that for all t 2 R, t # exists. Then Q.X/ max is homogeneous. Proof. This follows by Lemma 10.30(2). Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max and that
.hMk0 W k < !i; f 0 ; z 0 / 2 Q.X/ max :
Let t 2 R code the pair .hMk W k < !i; hMk0 W k < !i/. By Theorem 10.29, there exists .hNk W k < !i; g; x/ 2 Q.X/ max such that t 2 LŒx and such that the filter G Coll.!;
720
10 Further results
By the iteration lemma, Lemma 10.32, there exist iterations j W hMk W k < !i ! hj.Mk / W k < !i and
j 0 W hMk0 W k < !i ! hj 0 .Mk0 / W k < !i
such that .hNk W k < !i; j.f /; z/ 2 Q.X/ max ; such that
.hNk W k < !i; j 0 .f 0 /; z 0 / 2 Q.X/ max ;
and such that for each < !1N0 , if is an indiscernible of LŒt then j.f /./ D g./ D j 0 .f 0 /./: For each q 2 Q.X/ max let .X/ Q.X/ max jq D ¹p 2 Qmax j p < qº:
By Lemma 10.30(2) the partial orders Q.X/ max j.hNk W k < !i; j.f /; z/; 0 0 0 Q.X/ max j.hNk W k < !i; j .f /; z /;
and Q.X/ max j.hNk W k < !i; g; x/ are isomorphic. Finally .hNk W k < !i; j.f /; z/ < .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ and
.hNk W k < !i; j 0 .f 0 /; z 0 / < .hMk0 W k < !i; f 0 ; z 0 /:
t u
We fix some additional notation. Suppose p 2 Q.X/ max and p D .hMk W k < !i; f; z/: Then P .!/.p/ D [¹Mk \ P .!/ j k < !º: Another corollary of Lemma 10.32 is the following lemma. Lemma 10.35. Suppose that X P .!/ and that for all t 2 R, t # exists. Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max and that x0 2 X. Then there exists .hNk W k < !i; g; z/ 2 Q.X/ max such that .hNk W k < !i; g; z/ < .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ and such that x0 2 X(Code) .hNk W k < !i; Sg ; z/.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
721
Proof. Let t 2 R code the pair .hMk W k < !i; x0 /. By Theorem 10.29 there exists a condition .hNk W k < !i; g; x/ 2 Q.X/ max such that (1.1) t 2 LŒz, (1.2) G is LŒz-generic where G Coll.!;
t u
A similar, though easier, argument establishes: Lemma 10.36. Suppose that X P .!/ and that for all t 2 R, t # exists. Suppose that .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max and that y0 !. Then there exists .hNk W k < !i; g; z/ 2 Q.X/ max such that .hNk W k < !i; g; z/ < .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ and such that y0 2 Y(Code) .hNk W k < !i; g; z/.
t u
Lemma 10.37. Suppose that X P .!/. Suppose that hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of dense subsets of Q.X/ max . Let Y R be the set of reals x such that x codes a pair .p; ˛/ with p 2 D˛ . Suppose that .M; T; ı/ 2 H.!1 / is such that: (i) M is transitive and M ZFC. (ii) ı 2 M \ Ord, and ı is strongly inaccessible in M .
722
10 Further results
(iii) T 2 M and T is a tree on ! ı. (iv) Suppose P 2 Mı is a partial order and that g P is an M -generic filter with g 2 H.!1 /. Then hM Œg \ V!C1 ; pŒT \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; Y; 2i: Suppose that hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i is a sequence of conditions in Q.X/ max such that (v) hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i 2 M , (vi) for all ˛ < !1M , p˛ 2 D˛ , (vii) for all ˛ < ˇ < !1M , pˇ < p˛ : Suppose g
Coll.!; !1M /
is M -generic and let Z D [¹Z˛ j ˛ < !1M º where for each ˛ < !1M , Z˛ D P .!/.p˛ / . Suppose is a Z-uniform indiscernible, !1M < < !2M and that hAi W i < !i 2 M Œg is a sequence of subsets of !1M . Then for each q 2 Coll.!; / there exists a condition .hMk W k < !i; h; z/ 2 D! M 1
such that the following hold. (1) .hMk W k < !i; h; z/ 2 M Œg; (2) < !1M0 ; (3) q 2 h./; (4) For each i < !, for each ˛ < !1M , and for each k < !, ˛ 2 Ai if and only if ˛ 2 .SQi /Mk where
Si D ¹ˇ < !1M0 j ¹.0; i /º 2 h.ˇ/º
and where for each ˛ < !1M , ˛ is the ˛ th Z-uniform indiscernible above !1M0 ; (5) h.!1M / D g; (6) For all ˛ < !1M , (7) hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i 2 M0 .
.hMk W k < !i; h; z/ < p˛ I
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
723
Proof. We work in M Œg. For each ˛ < !1M let .hMk˛ W k < !i; f˛ ; z/ D p˛ and let
j˛ W hMk˛ W k < !i ! hMQ k˛ W k < !i
the iteration of hMk˛ W k < !i determined by f D [¹f˛ j ˛ < !1M º: Let h˛k W k < !i be a strictly increasing sequence which is cofinal in !1M such that h˛k W k < !i 2 M Œg: For each k < ! let Thus Let
Nk D MQ 0 k : ˛
.hNk W k < !i; f / 2 Q max : j W hNk W k < !i ! hNOk W k < !i
be a countable iteration, of limit length, such that j.!1N0 / > and such that q 2 j.f /./: The iteration exists since the critical sequence of any iteration of hNk W k < !i is an initial segment of the Z-uniform indiscernibles above !1N0 . Let hi W i < !i be O
an increasing sequence of elements of Z n , cofinal in !1N0 . For each i < ! let ˛ ˛ ki W hM i W k < !i ! hMO i W k < !i k
k
be the (unique) iteration such that ki .f˛i / D j.f /ji , and let ˛ pO˛i D .hMO k i W k < !i; fO˛i ; z/
be the corresponding condition in Q.X/ max . Note that for all ˛ < ˛i < !1M , pO˛i < p˛ : Now choose a condition p 2
Q.X/ max
\ M Œg such that for all i < !, p < pO˛i
and such that hAk W k < !i 2
M0.p/
where we let
.hMk.p/ W k < !i; f.p/ ; z/ D p: Let
˛ Z D [¹P .!/ \ hMO 0 i j i < !º:
724
10 Further results
Let IZ be the class of Z-uniform indiscernibles and let IZ be the class of Z -uniform indiscernibles. Thus N IZ D IZ n !1 0 : Further Z 2 M0.p/ and Z is countable in M0.p/ . The key point is the following. Let M
.p/
h˛ W ˛ < !1 0 i be the increasing enumeration of IZ and let I D ¹˛Cˇ j ˛ D ˛ and 0 < ˇ < !1M º: Suppose that fO 2 M.p/ is a function such that 0
.p/
M (1.1) dom.fO/ D !1 0 , .p/
M0
(1.2) for all ˛ < !1
,
fO.˛/ Coll.!; ˛/
and fO.˛/ is a filter, .p/
M0
(1.3) for all ˛ 2 !1 Then
n I,
f.p/ .˛/ D fO.˛/:
.hMk.p/ W k < !i; fO; z/ 2 Q.X/ max
and for each i < !,
.hMk.p/ W k < !i; fO; z/ < pO˛i :
Since hAk W k < !i 2 M0.p/ , we can choose fO so that requirement (4) of the lemma is satisfied by the condition .hMk.p/ W k < !i; fO; z/ by modifying fOjI if necessary. But this implies that requirement (4) is satisfied by any condition q 2 Q.X/ max such that .p/ O q < .hM W k < !i; f ; z/: k
Let pO D .hMk.p/ W k < !i; fO; z/. Finally by (vi), hM Œg \ V!C1 ; pŒT \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; Y; 2i: and so M Œg \ D! M 1
is dense in
Q.X/ max
\ M Œg. Let .hMk W k < !i; h; z/ 2 D! M \ M Œg 1
be a condition such that O .hMk W k < !i; h; z/ < p: The condition .hMk W k < !i; h; z/ is as required.
t u
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
725
Lemma 10.38. Suppose that X P .!/. Suppose that hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of dense subsets of Q.X/ max . Let Y R be the set of reals x such that x codes a pair .p; ˛/ with p 2 D˛ and suppose that .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / is such that .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable. Let ı 2 M be the Woodin cardinal associated to I. Suppose t !, t codes M and .hNk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max ; is a condition such that t 2 LŒz. Let 2 Mı be a normal .uniform/ measure and let .M ; / be the !1N0 -th iterate of .M; /. Suppose that Gf is LŒz-generic where Gf Coll.!;
j W hNk W k < !i ! hNk W k < !i
is an iteration and let
hp˛ W ˛ < .!1 /N0 i D j.hp˛ W ˛ < !1N0 i/:
Then for all ˛ < .!1 /N0 , p˛ 2 D˛ . Proof. We fix some notation. Suppose that F Coll.!; <˛/ is a maximal filter and that ˇ < ˛. Then F jColl.!; ˇ/ denotes the induced filter, F jColl.!; ˇ/ D ¹p 2 Coll.!; ˇ/ j p 2 F º
726
10 Further results
where for each p 2 Coll.!; ˇ/, p is the corresponding condition in Coll.!; <˛/: dom.p / D dom.p/ ¹ˇº and p .k; ˇ/ D p.k/ for all k 2 dom.p/. Let 2 M be the measurable cardinal associated to . Let 2 M Coll.!;</ be a term such that if G Coll.!; < / is M -generic then defines in M ŒG a sequence hp˛ W ˛ < i such that the following hold where for each ˛ < , .hMk˛ W k < !i; f˛ ; z/ D p˛ ; and Z˛ D [¹P .!/ \ Mkˇ j k < !; ˇ < ˛º: Note that by (1.2), for all ˛ < , ˛ ˛ < .!1 /M0 and so ˛ 2 dom.f˛ /. (1.1) For each ˛ < , p˛ 2 D˛ . (1.2) For each ˛ < ˇ < , pˇ < p˛ . (1.3) For each < such that is strongly inaccessible in M : a) b) c) d)
hp˛ j ˛ < i 2 M ŒGj ; [¹P .!/.p˛ / j ˛ < º D P .!/ \ M ŒGj ; f . / D GjColl.!; /; Suppose that ¹.0; /º 2 GjColl.!; . C /M /; < < . C /M , and that for each ˛ < , is a P .!/.p˛ / -uniform indiscernible. Then < .!1 /M0 and ¹.0; !/º 2 f ./:
(1.4) Suppose that < and that is strongly inaccessible in M . For each i < ! let Ai D ¹˛ < j ¹.0; i /º 2 GjColl.!; ˛ C 1/º: Then for each i < !, for each ˛ < , and for each k < !, ˛ 2 Ai if and only if ˛ 2 .SQi /Mk where M Si D ¹ˇ < !1 0 j ¹.0; i /º 2 f .ˇ/º M
and where for each ˛ < , ˛ is the ˛ th Z -uniform indiscernible above !1 0 .
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
727
Let T 2 M be a tree on ! ı such that for all M -generic filters, g .Q<ı /M ; with g 2 H.!1 /, pŒT \ M Œg D Y \ M Œg and hV!C1 \ M Œg; pŒT \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; Y; 2i The existence of the tree T follows from Lemma 6.58 and Lemma 6.59. By Lemma 10.37, the term is easily constructed in M using the tree T . Let .M ; / be the .!1N0 /th iterate of .M; /. Let j W .M; / ! .M ; / be the iteration yielding M and let D j. /. M 2 LŒt and so Gf is M -generic for Coll.!;
it follows that G0 is M -generic. We further modify G0 to obtain G1 . Let D .!1N0 /C
as computed in M and let
F W !1N0 ! .!1N0 ; /
be the LŒt -least function such that F is onto. Let D C be the set of 2 C such that is the ordertype of C \ . Let E be the set of < !1N0 such that for some ˇ,
728
10 Further results
(2.1) Lˇ Œt ZFC, (2.2) is an inaccessible cardinal in .!1 /Lˇ Œt . Since t codes .M; /, E D. Further E 2 LŒt and in LŒt , E contains a subset which is a club in !1N0 . For each 2 E let ˇ be the least ordinal, ˇ, satisfying (2.1)–(2.2), and let F be the function F as computed in Lˇ Œt . The point of all of this is reflection. Let > be an ordinal such that L Œt ZFC and suppose X L Œt is a countable elementary substructure containing t and F . Let D X \ !1N0 . Then 2 E and F is the image of F under the collapsing map. For each ˇ < ! N0 let Tˇ D ¹ 2 E j ¹.0; ˇ/º 2 f . /º: Thus
hTˇ j ˇ < !1N0 i 2 LŒzŒGf
and for each ˇ < !1N0 , Tˇ … .INS /N1 . We modify G0 to obtain G as follows. For each ˛ < !1N0 , GjColl.!; ˛/ D G0 jColl.!; ˛/; unless ˛ D . C /
M
for some 2 E. In this case GjColl.!; ˛/ D ¹p _ q j q 2 G0 jColl.!; ˛/º:
where p D ¹.0; F .ˇ//º and 2 Tˇ . For each 2 C such that C \ is bounded in , GjColl.!; ˛/ D G0 jColl.!; ˛/ for all but at most one ˛ in the interval Œ ; where is the largest element of C \ . Further for this one possible exception, GjColl.!; ˛/ D ¹p _ q j q 2 G0 jColl.!; ˛/º for some condition p 2 Coll.!; ˛/. Finally G0 j0 D Gj0 where 0 is the least element of C . Thus by induction on 2 C it follows that for all 2 C , Gj is M -generic for Coll.!; < /. Therefore G is M -generic for Coll.!;
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
Let
729
hp˛ W ˛ < !1N0 i
be the interpretation of by G. For each ˛ < !1N0 let .hMk˛ W k < !i; f˛ ; z˛ / D p˛ : For all ˛ < ˇ, pˇ < p˛ . Therefore for all ˛ < ˇ, z˛ D zˇ and f˛ fˇ : Let x D z0 and let h D [¹f˛ j ˛ < !1N0 º. We finish by proving (3.1) .hNk W k < !i; h; x/ 2 Q.X/ max , (3.2) for all ˛ < !1N0 , p˛ 2 D˛ and .hNk W k < !i; h; x/ < p˛ : (3.2) is an immediate consequence of (3.1) and the definitions. We prove (3.1). Let Z D [¹P .!/.p˛ / j ˛ < !1N0 º: Thus by (1.3)(b), Z D P .!/ \ M ŒG: For each k < ! let Ak D ¹˛ < j ¹.0; k/º 2 GjColl.!; ˛ C 1/º and let Sk D ¹˛ < j ¹.0; k/º 2 GjColl.!; ˛/º: Fix k < ! and as above let be the successor cardinal of !1N0 as computed in M . From the definition of G0 , it follows that for each ˛ 2 C , ˛ 2 .SQk /N0 if and only if ˛ 2 Bk where ˛ is the ˛ th Z-uniform indiscernible above . By the modification of G0 to produce G, .SQk /N0 \ .!1N0 ; / D ;: For each ˛ < !1N0 let j˛ W hMk˛ W k < !i ! hMO k˛ W k < !i be the iteration such that j.f˛ / D h. For each ˛ < ˇ < !1N0 , pˇ < p˛ and so S(Code) .hMO k˛ W k < !i; Sh ; x/ S(Code) .hMO kˇ W k < !i; Sh ; x/:
730
10 Further results
For each ˛ < !1N0 , let h ˇ ; Xˇ ; Yˇ W ˇ < ı˛ i D S(Code) .hMO k˛ W k < !i; Sh ; x/ and let
ı D sup¹ı˛ j ˛ < !1N0 º D Ord \ .[¹MO 0˛ j ˛ < !1N0 º/:
Since h D [¹f˛ j ˛ < !1N0 º and since for all 2 C , f . / D h. /; it follows that for each ˛ <
!1N0 ,
S(Code) .hNk W k < !i; Sh ; x/jı˛ D h ˇ ; Xˇ ; Yˇ W ˇ < ı˛ i: Let
h ˇ ; Xˇ ; Yˇ W ˇ < ı i D S(Code) .hNk W k < !i; Sh ; x/:
The key point is that for ˇ D C !1N0 C 1, Yˇ D [¹Y˛ j ˛ < ıº [ ¹zº and ˇ is less than the least indiscernible of LŒz above !1N0 . Note (4.1) f jC D hjC , (4.2) .hNk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max . Thus .hNk W k < !i; h; x/ 2 Q.X/ max . Finally (4) follows from (3). To see this let j W hNk W k < !i ! hNk W k < !i be an iteration and let
hp˛ W ˛ < .!1 /N0 i D j.hp˛ W ˛ < !1N0 i/: By (3) and the elementarity of j , (5.1) j.G/ is j.M /-generic,
(5.2) hp˛ W ˛ < .!1 /N0 i 2 j.M /Œj.G/, N
(5.3) .j.M /; j. // is the !1 0 -th iterate of .M; /. Let
k W .M; / ! .j.M /; j. //
be the iteration map corresponding to (5.3) and let T D k.T / where T 2 M is the tree on ! ı used to define . The key point is that since .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable it follows that hV!C1 \ j.M /Œj.G/; pŒT \ j.M /Œj.G/; 2i hV!C1 ; Y; 2i: The proof of this claim involves noting that if kO W .M; / ! .MO ; / O
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
731
is any (countable) iteration then there exists a countable iteration, j0 W .M; I/ ! .M0 ; I0 / and there exists an elementary embedding k0 W MO ! M0 O i. e. any (countable) iteration of .M; / can be absorbed by an such that j0 D k0 ı k; iteration of .M; I/. Thus (4) follows from (3) and the strong Y -iterability of .M; I/. t u Theorem 10.39. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose that X P .!/ is a set such that X 2 L.; R/: Then for each set Y 2 there exists .M; I/ 2 H.!1 / such that .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable. Proof. The theorem follows from Theorem 9.48.
t u
We adopt the usual notational conventions. Suppose that X P .!/. A filter G Q.X/ max is semi-generic if for each ˛ < !1 there exists .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 G such that ˛ < .!1 /M0 . Suppose that G Q.X/ max is semi-generic. Then (1) zG D z where z occurs in p for some p 2 G, (2) fG D [¹f j .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Gº,
(3) IG D [¹j ..INS /M0 / j .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Gº, (4) P .!1 /G D [¹M0 \ P .!1 / j .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Gº, where for each .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 G, j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is the (unique) iteration such that j.f / D fG . Of course zG must occur in every condition in G.
732
10 Further results
Theorem 10.40. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose that X P .!/ is a set such that X 2 L.; R/: Q.X/ max
is !-closed and homogeneous. Then Suppose G Q.X/ max is L.; R/-generic. Then L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC and in L.; R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) P .!1 / L.X; R/ŒAG ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) IG is !1 -dense; (5) X(Code) .SfG ; zG / D X [ ¹;º and Y(Code) .SfG ; zG / D P .!/; (6)
AC
holds.
.X/ Proof. By Lemma 10.34, Q.X/ max is homogeneous, by Lemma 10.33, Qmax is !-closed. The claim that L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC
follows from (5) since (5) implies that R can be wellordered in L.; R/ŒG. We work in L.; R/ŒG and prove (1)–(5). (1) is immediate, G is the set of .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max such that z D zG , there is an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hj.Mk / W k < !i such that j.f / D fG . This iteration is uniquely specified by fG and the requirement that j.f / D fG . (2) follows from Lemma 10.38, using Theorem 10.39 and Theorem 10.29 to supply the necessary conditions. (3) and (4) follow from (2) and the definitions. Finally by (2)–(4), X(Code) .SfG ; zG / D [¹j .X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z// j .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Gº where as above, for each .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 G, j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is the iteration such that j.f / D fG .
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
733
Therefore X(Code) .SfG ; zG / X [ ¹;º: By the genericity of G and by Lemma 10.35, X [ ¹;º [¹j .X(Code) .hMk W k < !i; Sf ; z// j .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Gº and so X(Code) .SfG ; zG / D X [ ¹;º. A similar argument, using Lemma 10.36, proves that Y(Code) .SfG ; zG / D P .!/. Finally (6) follows by an argument essentially identical to the proof that AC holds t u in the Qmax -extension. Lemma 10.41. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose that X P .!/ is a set such that X 2 L.; R/: Suppose that G Q.X/ max is L.; R/-generic. Then in L.; R/ŒG, for every set A 2 P .R/ \ L.; R/ the set ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Proof. The proof is a modification of the proof of Lemma 5.107. We cannot really use the proof of Lemma 6.77, which is the version of this lemma for Qmax . The minor difficulty is that Q.X/ max Qmax , and so there are no conditions .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Q.X/ max such that hV!C1 \ M0 ; A \ M0 ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i: This fact accounts for the various differences between the presentation of the anal ysis of the Q.X/ max -extension and that of the Qmax -extension. We work in L.; R/ŒG. Let H.!2 /G D [¹H.!2 /M0 j .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 Gº where for each .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 G, j W hMk W k < !i ! hMk W k < !i is the (unique) iteration such that j.f / D fG . By Theorem 10.40(1), P .!1 / D P .!1 /G ;
734
10 Further results
and so H.!2 / D H.!2 /G : This is the key to the proof, just as it was the for the proof of Lemma 5.107. Let F W H.!2 /
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
735
where Zi is the closure of ¹ai º under F and where ji W hMki W k < !i ! hji .Mki / W k < !i is the iteration such that ji .fi / D fG . For each i < ! let Xi D ji Œai D ¹ji .b/ j b 2 ai º: Thus for each i < !, Xi X and further X D [¹Xi j i < !º: We note that for each i < !, since ji .ai / D Ni , ji .A \ ai / D A \ Ni : For each i < ! and let Di be the set of .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ < .hMki W k < !i; fi ; z/ such that
j .A \ ai / D A \ j .ai /
and such that for all countable iterations j W hMk W k < !i ! hj.Mk / W k < !i; it is the case that j.A \ j .ai // D A \ j.j .ai //, where j W hMki W k < !i ! hj .Mki / W k < !i is the iteration such that j .fi / D f . We claim that for some q 2 G, ¹p < q j p 2 Q.X/ max º Di : Assume toward a contradiction that this fails. Then for all q 2 G there exists p 2 G such that p < q and p … Di . However G is L.; R/-generic and so there must exist .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ 2 G and an iteration j W hMk W k < !i ! hj.Mk / W k < !i such that (3.1) .hMk W k < !i; f; z/ < .hMki W k < !i; fi ; z/, (3.2) j.A \ j .ai // ¤ A \ j.j .ai // where j W hMki W k < !i ! hj .Mki / W k < !i is the iteration such that j .fi / D f , (3.3) .hj.Mk / W k < !i; j.f /; z/ 2 G.
736
10 Further results
But this contradicts the fact that ji .A \ ai / D A \ Ni . Therefore for some q 2 G, ¹p < q j p 2 Q.X/ max º Di : Note that Di is definable in the structure hH.!2 /; A; G; 2i from ai . Therefore Di \ Zi ¤ ; and so .hMkiC1 W k < !i; fiC1 ; z/ 2 Di : For each i < n < !, let ji;n W hMki W k < !i ! hji;n .Mki / W k < !i be the iteration such that ji;n .fi / D fn and let ji;! W hMki W k < !i ! hji;! .Mki / W k < !i be the iteration such that ji;! .fi / D [¹fn j n < !º: Thus for all i < !, hji;! .Mki / W k < !i 2 jiC1;! .M0iC1 /: The key points are that MX D [¹ji;! .Mki / j i; k < !º D [¹ji;! .ai / j i < !º: and that for each i < !, ji;! .ai / D NiX where NiX is the image of Ni under the collapsing map. These identities are easily verified from the definitions. Finally suppose jO W MX ! MO X is a countable iteration. For each i < !,
jO.hjiC1;! .MkiC1 / W k < !i/
is an iterate of hMkiC1 W k < !i. Further for each i < !, hMkiC1 W k < !i 2 Di : Therefore for each i < !, jO.A \ NiX / D jO.jiC1;! .A \ ji;iC1 .ai /// D A \ jO.jiC1;! .ji;iC1 .ai /// D A \ jO.NiX /:
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
737
X However for each i < !, NiX is transitive and NiX 2 NiC1 . Further
MX D [¹NiX j i < !º: Therefore and so
MO X D [¹jO.NiX / j i < !º jO.A \ MX / D A \ MO X : t u
Therefore MX is A-iterable.
The motivation for considering Q.X/ max was to investigate whether the assumption that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense implies that the inner model L.P .!1 // is close to the inner model L.R/ as the covering theorems might suggest. The next theorem shows that this is not the case. Note that (5) in the statement of the theorem is marginally stronger than the conclusions of the covering theorems. Theorem 10.42. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose that X P .!/ is a set such that X 2 L.; R/: Q.X/ max
is !-closed and homogeneous. Further, suppose G Q.X/ Then max is L.; R/generic. Then for each A 2 , L.A; X; R/ŒG ZFC and in L.A; X; R/ŒG the following hold. (1) The nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. (2) L.P .!1 // D L.X; R/ŒG. (3) X is a definable (as a predicate) in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i from fG . (4) ı12 D !2 . (5) Suppose S !1 is stationary and f W S ! Ord: Then there exists g 2 L.A; X; R/ such that ¹˛ 2 S j f .˛/ D g.˛/º is stationary.
738
10 Further results
Proof. (1)–(4) follow from Theorem 10.40. (5) follows from (1), Lemma 10.41 and from Theorem 3.42 using the chain condition of Q.X/ max to reduce to the case that f WS !ı where ı < ‚L.A;X;R/ , cf. the proof of Lemma 6.79.
t u
Perhaps our covering theorems do not capture all the covering consequences of the assumption that the nonstationary ideal is !1 -dense, particularly if in addition large cardinals are assumed to exist. Theorem 10.44 is the version of Theorem 10.42 which addresses this question. Theorem 10.43. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADR : Then for each set A 2 there exists an inner model L.S; R/ such that (1) S Ord and A 2 L.S; R/, (2) HODSL.S;R/ “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals”.
t u
Theorem 10.44. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ DC C ADR : Suppose that X P .!/ is a set such that X 2 L.; R/: Suppose that G Q.X/ max is L.; R/-generic. Then there is an inner model N L.; R/ŒG containing the ordinals, R and G such that: (1) N ZFC C “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals”; (2) N “INS is !1 -dense”; (3) X 2 N and X is 1 -weakly homogeneously Suslin in N ; (4) N X 2 L.P .!1 //.
t u
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
739
.;/ 10.2.3 Pmax .;/ We define and briefly analyze Pmax which is the version of Q.X/ max which corresponds to .;/ Pmax but with X D ;. Our interest in Pmax lies in Theorem 10.70. This theorem shows that Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture
together with all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/i does not imply ./. One corollary is that for the characterization of ./ using the “converse” of the absoluteness theorem (Theorem 4.76), it is essential that the predicate INS be added to the structure. For this application we need only consider the case when X D ;; i. e. we are in effect just defining the version of Q.;/ max which corresponds to Pmax . However all the results, including the absoluteness theorem (Theorem 10.55), .X/ in the obvious fashion. We have chosen to concentrate on the special generalize to Pmax .;/ case of Pmax because this case suffices for our primary applications (and the notation is slightly simpler). Strong Chang’s Conjecture is discussed in Section 9.6. .;/ extension of L.R/ are The iteration lemmas necessary for the analysis of the Pmax .;/ actually simpler to prove than those for Qmax . Further the iteration lemmas necessary for the analysis of the Q.;/ max extension of L.R/ are in turn (slightly) simpler than those required for the analysis of the Q.X/ max extensions for general X. We shall use the notation from Section 10.2.1. Suppose that A !1 . Let SA denote the sequence hSi W i < !i where for each i < !, Si is the set of ˛ < !1 such that (1) ˛ is a limit ordinal, (2) ˛ C i C 1 2 A, (3) i D min¹j < ! j ˛ C j C 1 2 Aº. Thus SA is a sequence of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 . .;/ Definition 10.45. Pmax is the set of triples
hM; a; zi such that the following hold. (1) M is a countable transitive set such that M ZFC C ZC: (2) M is iterable. (3) M
AC .
740
10 Further results
(4) Let hSi W i < !i D .Sa /M . For each i < !, Si … .INS /M . (5) Suppose that C !1M is closed and unbounded with C 2 M. Then there exists a closed cofinal set D C such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ M. (6) X(Code) .M; Sa ; z/ D ¹;º. (7) Y(Code) .M; Sa ; z/ D P .!/ \ M. The order is defined as follows: hM1 ; a1 ; z1 i < hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i if z1 D z0 and there exists an iteration j W M0 ! M0 such that (1) j.a0 / D a1 ,
(2) .INS /M0 D .INS /M1 \ M0 .
t u .;/
.;/ The nontriviality of Pmax is an immediate corollary of the analysis of L.; R/Qmax where P .R/
is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “‚ is regular”: Remark 10.46. The use of the analysis of the Q.;/ max -extension (Theorem 10.42) to .;/ .;/ is for expediency. If one defines Pmax using sequences of obtain conditions in Pmax .;/ models (as in the definition of Qmax ) then it is much easier to produce conditions. The conditions can be constructed directly without reference to Q.;/ t u max . Theorem 10.47. Suppose that A R and that L.A; R/ ADC : Then there exists .;/ hM; a; zi 2 Pmax
such that (1) A \ M 2 M and hM \ V!C1 ; A \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i, (2) M is A-iterable, (3) X(Code) .M; a; z/ D ¹;º.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
741
Proof. Let G Q.X/ max be L.A; R/-generic where X D ;. Fix 0 to be least such that L 0 .A; R/ŒG ZFC C ZC; and let B 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/ be such that ı 11 .B/ > 0 . By Theorem 10.40 and Lemma 10.41, L.A; R/ŒG ZFC and further the following hold in L.A; R/ŒG. (1.1) X(Code) .SfG ; zG / D ¹;º. (1.2) Y(Code) .SfG ; zG / D P .!/. (1.3)
AC
holds.
(1.4) The set ¹X hH.!2 /; A; 2i j MX is A-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . (1.5) The set ¹X hH.!2 /; B; 2i j MX is B-iterable and X is countableº contains a club, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . Let SfG D hSi W i < !i and let AG D ¹˛ C i C 1 j ˛ is a limit ordinal and ˛ 2 Si º: Thus SAG D hSi \ C W i < !i where C is the set of countable limit ordinals and so by (1.1), in L.A; R/ŒG, X(Code) .SAG ; zG / D ¹;º: By (1.4) and Lemma 4.24, the set of ¹Y L 0 .A; R/ŒG j Y is countable and MY is strongly iterableº contains a club in P!1 .M /. Here MY is the transitive collapse of Y . Thus, by (1.5), there exists a countable elementary substructure, X L 0 .A; R/ŒG; such that .;/ hM; a; zi 2 Pmax
and satisfies the requirements of the lemma, where (2.1) z D zG , (2.2) M is the transitive collapse of X , (2.3) a D AG \ X \ !1 D AG \ .!1 /M .
t u
742
10 Further results
.;/ It is convenient to organize the analysis of Pmax following closely that of Q.X/ max . The reason is simply that most of the proofs adapt easily to the new context. The next four lemmas summarize the basic iteration facts that one needs. These lemmas are direct analogs of the lemmas we proved as part of the analysis of Q.X/ max . We leave the details to the reader. .;/ , such as the !-closure The first two easily yield elementary consequences for Pmax .;/ and homogeneity of Pmax , the latter two allow one to complete the basic analysis.
Lemma 10.48. Suppose hM1 ; a1 ; z1 i < hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i in
.;/ Pmax
and let
j W M0 ! M0
be the .unique/ iteration such that j.a0 / D a1 . (1) X(Code) .M0 ; Sa0 ; z0 / X(Code) .M1 ; Sa1 ; z1 /. (2) Suppose that b0 2 M0 is such that for each i < !, Sia0 M Sib0 2 .INS /M0 ; where hSia0 W i < !i D .Sa0 /M0 and hSib0 W i < !i D .Sb0 /M0 . Suppose that x0 2 M0 is a subset of ! such that .;/ : hM0 ; b0 ; x0 i 2 Pmax .;/ Then hM1 ; j.b0 /; x0 i 2 Pmax and hM1 ; j.b0 /; x0 i < hM0 ; b0 ; x0 i.
t u
.;/ As we have indicated, the iteration lemmas required for the analysis of Pmax are .;/ .;/ routine generalizations of those for Qmax . The situation for Pmax is actually quite a bit .;/ conditions are simpler and there is more freedom in less complicated since the Pmax constructing iterations.
Lemma 10.49. Suppose that .;/ ; hM1 ; a1 ; z1 i 2 Pmax .;/ hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i 2 Pmax ;
t ! codes M0 , and that t 2 LŒz1 . Let hSia0 W i < !i D .Sa0 /M0 ; hSia1 W i < !i D .Sa1 /M1 ; and let C be the set of < !1M1 such that is an indiscernible of LŒt . Then there exists an iteration j W M0 ! M0 such that j 2 M1 and such that: (1) for each i < !, C \ j.Sia0 / D C \ Sia1 ; .;/ (2) hM1 ; j.a0 /; z0 i 2 Pmax ;
(3) hM1 ; j.a0 /; z0 i < hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i.
t u
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
743
Lemma 10.50. Suppose that hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i .;/ is a sequence of dense subsets of Pmax . Let Y R be the set of reals x such that x codes a pair .p; ˛/ with p 2 D˛ . Suppose that .M; T; ı/ 2 H.!1 / is such that:
(i) M is transitive and M ZFC. (ii) ı 2 M \ Ord, and ı is strongly inaccessible in M . (iii) T 2 M and T is a tree on ! ı. (iv) Suppose P 2 Mı is a partial order and that g P is an M -generic filter with g 2 H.!1 /. Then hM Œg \ V!C1 ; pŒT \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; Y; 2i: .;/ Suppose that hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i is a sequence of conditions in Pmax such that
(v) hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i 2 M , (vi) for all ˛ < !1M , p˛ 2 D˛ , (vii) for all ˛ < ˇ < !1M , pˇ < p˛ : Suppose g Coll.!; !1M / is M -generic and let Z D [¹Z˛ j ˛ < !1M º where for each ˛ < !1M , Z˛ D P .!/ \ M˛ and hM˛ ; a˛ ; z0 i D p˛ . Suppose is a Z-uniform indiscernible, !1M < < !2M and that hAi W i < !i 2 M Œg is a sequence of subsets of !1M . Then for each m < !, there exists a condition hN ; a; zi 2 D! M 1
such that the following hold where hSi W i < !i D .Sa /N ; and where for each ˛ < !1M , ˛ is the ˛ th Z-uniform indiscernible above !1N . (1) hN ; a; zi 2 M Œg. (2) < !1N and 2 Sm . (3) For each i < ! and for each ˛ < !1M , ˛ 2 Ai if and only if ˛ 2 .SQi /N . (4) For all ˛ < !1M , hN ; a; zi < p˛ . (5) hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i 2 N .
t u
744
10 Further results
Lemma 10.51. Suppose that hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i .;/ is a sequence of dense subsets of Pmax . Let Y R be the set of reals x such that x codes a pair .p; ˛/ with p 2 D˛ and suppose that
.M; I/ 2 H.!1 / is such that .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable. Let ı 2 M be the Woodin cardinal associated to I. Suppose t !, t codes M and .;/ hN ; a; zi 2 Pmax ;
is a condition such that t 2 LŒz. Let 2 Mı be a normal .uniform/ measure and let .M ; / be the !1N -th iterate of .M; /. Then there exists a sequence hp˛ W ˛ < !1N i 2 N and there exists .b; x/ 2 N such that .;/ (1) hN ; b; xi 2 Pmax ,
(2) for all ˛ < !1N , p˛ 2 D˛ and hN ; b; xi < p˛ ; (3) there exists an M -generic filter g Coll.!;
t u
.;/ is homogeneous. Lemma 10.53. Suppose that L.R/ ADC . Then Pmax
t u
We adopt the usual notational conventions. A filter .;/ G Pmax
is semi-generic if for all ˛ < !1 there exists a condition hM; a; zi 2 G such that ˛ <
!1M .
.;/ Suppose that G Pmax is a semi-generic filter. Then
(1) zG D z where z occurs in p for some p 2 G, (2) AG D [¹a j hM; a; zi 2 Gº,
(3) IG D [¹.INS /M j hM; a; zi 2 Gº, (4) P .!1 /G D [¹M \ P .!1 / j hM; a; zi 2 Gº, where for each hM; a; zi 2 G, j W M ! M is the (unique) iteration such that j.a/ D AG . Of course, as for Q.;/ max , zG must occur in every condition in G.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
745
Theorem 10.54. Suppose that L.R/ AD: .;/ Pmax
is !-closed and homogeneous. Then Suppose .;/ G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒAG ; (2) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (3) IG is a normal !2 -saturated ideal on !1 ; (4) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (5) X(Code) .SAG ; zG / D ¹;º and Y(Code) .SAG ; zG / D P .!/; (6)
AC
holds.
.;/ .;/ Proof. By Lemma 10.52, Pmax is !-closed and by Lemma 10.53, Pmax is homogeneous. By the usual arguments, (2) and the assertion that
L.R/ŒG ZF C !1 -DC each follow from Lemma 10.51 using Theorem 10.47 to supply the necessary conditions. .;/ . (5) implies (4), (5) and (6) follow from (2) and the definition of the order on Pmax that R can be wellordered in L.R/ŒG and so L.R/ŒG ZFC: By (2), if C !1 is closed, unbounded, then C contains a closed, unbounded, subset which is constructible from a real. Thus .INS /L.R/ŒAG D .INS /L.R/ŒG \ L.R/ŒAG : This implies that .S(Code) .SAG ; zG //L.R/ŒAG D .S(Code) .SAG ; zG //L.R/ŒG ; and so L.R/ŒAg ZFC. The generic filter G can be defined in L.R/ŒAg as the set of all .;/ hM; a; zG i 2 Pmax
such that there exists an iteration j W M ! M satisfying:
746
10 Further results
(1.1) j.a/ D AG , (1.2) j 2 L.M; AG /,
(1.3) .INS /M D .INS /L.R/ŒAG \ M . Note that (1.2) follows from (1.1) since M AC : Finally (3) can be proved by adapting the proof of the analogous claim for Pmax . A slightly more elegant approach is the following. First standard arguments show that in L.R/ŒG, for each set B 2 L.R/ \ P .R/ there exists a countable elementary X hH.!2 /; B; 2i such that MX is B-iterable, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . This implies, by Lemma 3.34 and Lemma 4.24, that for each < ‚L.R/ if L .R/ŒG ZFC then for a closed, unbounded, set of countable elementary substructures, Y L .R/ŒG; the transitive collapse of Y is B-iterable for each B 2 Y \ L.R/ \ P .R/. Now assume toward a contradiction that INS is not saturated in L.R/ŒG. Let 0 be least such that (2.1) L 0 .R/ŒG ZFC C ZC, (2.2) there exists a predense set A P .!1 / n INS of cardinality !2 such that for all S; T 2 A if S ¤ T then S \ T 2 INS . Let 2 L 0 .R/ be a term for A. Let be the set of pairs .hM; a; zi; b/ such that .;/ (3.1) hM; a; zi 2 Pmax ,
(3.2) b 2 .P .!1 / n INS /M , (3.3) hM; a; zi “j .b/ 2 ”. Let B be the set of x 2 R which code an element of . Fix p 2 G such that p forces that is a term for an antichain in .P .!1 / n INS ; / of cardinality !2 . Finally choose a countable elementary substructure Y0 L 0 .R/ŒG; such that (4.1) ¹B; p; Gº 2 Y , (4.2) the transitive collapse of Y0 is B-iterable. Let M0 be the transitive collapse of Y0 and let a0 be the image of AG under the collapsing map. Similarly let A0 be the image of A under the collapsing map.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
747
Thus .;/ hM0 ; a0 ; zG i 2 Pmax
and hM0 ; a0 ; zG i < p. Suppose
.;/ G0 Pmax
is L.R/-generic with hM0 ; a0 ; zG i 2 G0 . We work in L.R/ŒG0 . Let j W M0 ! M0 be the iteration such that j .a0 / D AG0 . Let AG0 be the interpretation of be G0 . Since p 2 G0 , AG0 is an antichain in .P .!1 / n INS ; / of cardinality !2 . However A0 is predense in .P .!1 / n INS ; /M0 ; and so
5j .A0 /
must contain a club in !1 . Since M0 is B-iterable, j .A0 / AG0 ; t u
which is a contradiction. .;/ There is an interesting absoluteness theorem for Pmax .
Theorem 10.55. Suppose that L.R/ AD: Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; Y W Y 2 L.R/; Y Ri; and that
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; Y W Y 2 L.R/; Y RiL.R/ Then
.;/ Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; Y W Y 2 L.R/; Y RiL.R/
: :
Proof. Fix the …2 sentence . We give the proof in the case that none of the predicates for the sets Y occur in . The general case is similar. As usual we may suppose that D .8x0 .9x1 .x0 ; x1 /// where
.x0 ; x1 / is a †0 formula. Fix a condition .;/ hM; a; zi 2 Pmax
and fix a set b0 2 H.!2 /M . We prove there exists a condition O a; hM; O zi O 2 P .;/ max
748
10 Further results O
and a set b1 2 H.!2 /M such that: O a; (1.1) hM; O zi O < hM; a; zi. (1.2) Let
j W M ! M
be the iteration such that j.a/ D a. O Then O
H.!2 /M
Œj.b0 /; b1 :
The theorem follows easily from this. Suppose that G Pmax is a L.R/. We work in L.R/ŒG. Fix a sequence hTk W k < !i of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 and fix < .‚/L.R/ such that
L .R/ ZFC :
.;/ We claim there exists a semi-generic filter F Pmax such that the following hold where hSi W i < !i D SAF :
(2.1) hM; a; zi 2 F . (2.2) There exists Y L .R/ .;/ such that !1 Y and such that F \ Y is Y -generic for Pmax .
(2.3) IF D P .!1 /F \ INS . (2.4) Let P .!/F D P .!1 /F \ P .!/. Let Z be the first !1 many P .!/F -uniform indiscernibles above !1 . a) For each k < !,
hZ; SQi \ Z; 2i Š h!1 ; Ti ; 2i;
b) For each S 2 P .!1 /F n INS , ¹Tk \ S j k < !º P .!1 / n INS : The potential difficulty in constructing F is arranging that (2.4) holds, we deal with this by in effect choosing Z before constructing F . Let X0 L .R/ be a countable elementary substructure with hM; a; zi 2 X0 : Let L 0 . 0 / be the transitive collapse of X0 where 0 D X0 \ R.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
749
.;/ L .0 / Let g0 .Pmax / 0 be an L 0 . 0 /-generic filter with
.hMk W k < !i; a; z/ 2 g0 : Thus
L 0 . 0 /Œg0 ZFC ;
L 0 . 0 /Œg0 is iterable and the critical sequence of any iteration of L 0 . 0 / is an initial segment of the .P .!/ \ X0 /-uniform indiscernibles. We require that X0 is chosen such that L 0 . 0 /Œg0 is A-iterable where A codes the first order diagram of hL .R/; 2i: The existence of X0 follows from the fact that L.R/ AD using Theorem 9.7 and reflection arguments: cf. the proof of Lemma 4.40. It is now straightforward to construct an iteration j W L 0 . 0 /Œg0 ! L 0 . 0 /Œg0 of length !1 such that the semi-generic filter generated by j.g0 / is as desired, noting that with .;/ j p < q for some p 2 j.g0 /º F D ¹q 2 Pmax then (3.1) AF D j.Ag0 /, (3.2) P .!1 /F D P .!1 / \ L 0 . 0 /Œg0 , (3.3) IF D .INS /
L .0 /Œg0 0
,
(3.4) the P .!/F uniform indiscernibles above !1 are exactly the .P .!/ \ X0 /uniform indiscernibles above !1 , where as above, P .!/F D P .!1 /F \ P .!/. .;/ Fix a semi-generic filter F Pmax which satisfies (2.1)–(2.4). Let B0 D j1 .b0 / where
j1 W M ! M
is the (unique) iteration such that j1 .a/ D AF . Choose X1 L .R/ŒG such that X1 is countable, ¹ 0 ; hTk W k < !i; F ; B0 º X1 and such that N is iterable where N is the transitive collapse of X1 . By the remarks above, X1 exists. Let .a0 ; F0 / be the image of .AF ; F / under the collapsing map.
750
10 Further results
Similarly let hTk0 W k < !i be the image of hTk W k < !i under the collapsing map and let B00 be the image of B0 . Fix t0 ! which codes N . Let .;/ O d; zi hM; O 2 Pmax be such that t0 is recursive in z. O Let j2 W N ! N O
be an iteration of length !1M such that O j2 2 M; O and such that the following hold in M where .a0 ; F0 / D j2 ..a0 ; F0 //. (4.1) Let Sa D hSi W i < !i and let
Sa0 D hSi W i < !i:
Then for each i < !,
Si \ C D Si \ C;
O where C is the set of < !1 such that is an indiscernible of LŒz. (4.2) IF0 D P .!1 /F0 \ INS . (4.3) Let be the !1th .X \ P .!//-uniform indiscernible. Then ¹3iC1 j i 2 zO º D ¹i < ! j .Si / \ is stationaryº: O Note that we do not require that Such an iteration is easily constructed in M.
O
.INS /N D .INS /M \ N : We now come to the key points. First .;/ O j2 .a0 /; zi O 2 Pmax hM; and
O j2 .a0 /; zi O < hM; a; zi: hM;
This follows from (4.1)–(4.3). The second key point is that O
where b 2 H.!2 /N
H.!2 /M Œj2 .B00 /; j2 .b/ is such that H.!2 /N ŒB00 ; b:
Note then since X1 L .R/ŒG; the witness b must exist. Thus is as desired. The theorem follows.
O j2 .a0 /; zi O hM; t u
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
751
.;/ As we have indicated, our interest in Pmax lies in Theorem 10.70 which shows that
Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture together with all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; 2i does not imply ./. The failure of ./ in the resulting extension is an immediate corollary of the following lemma. Lemma 10.56. Assume ./. Suppose that S D hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 . Then for each z 2 P .!/, X(Code) .S; z/ D P .!/: Proof. Assume toward a contradiction that X(Code) .S; z/ ¤ P .!/; and fix t 2 P .!/ n X(Code) .S; z/. Fix a filter G Pmax such that (1.1) G is L.R/-generic, (1.2) L.P .!1 // D L.R/ŒG. By the genericity of G there exists h.M; I /; ai 2 G and there exists hsi W i < !i 2 M such that (2.1) I D .INS /M , (2.2) M ZC C †1 -Replacement C ./, (2.3) .z; t / 2 M, (2.4) j.hsi W i < !i/ D hSi W i < !i, where j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / is the iteration such that j.a/ D AG . By Lemma 10.21, the .M \ P .!//-uniform indiscernibles above !1 coincide with the .M \ P .!//-uniform indiscernibles above !1 . Let h˛ W ˛ < !2 i be the increasing enumeration of the .M \ P .!//-uniform indiscernibles above !1 . Let b D ¹i < ! j SQi is stationary in !1 º: Let c D ¹i < ! j 2iC1 2 bº
752
10 Further results
and let d D ¹i < ! j 3iC1 2 bº: By the genericity of G again, we can suppose that c D t and that d codes M. Let S(Code) .S; z/ D h. ; X ; Y / W < !2 i:
Since M ./, 0 D .!2 /M and
.S(Code) .S; z//M D S(Code) .S; z/j0 : Therefore if D !1 ,
(3.1) Y D .Y(Code) .S; z//M , (3.2) D !1 , (3.3) b D ¹i < ! j SQi is stationary in º. Since d codes M, the least indiscernible of LŒd is above . This implies that t 2 XC1 which is a contradiction. t u The proof of Theorem 10.70 requires the following adaptation of Theorem 9.32 and Theorem 9.35, as well as Theorem 10.69 which is the generalization of Theorem 9.39. Among these theorems it is only Theorem 10.69, which concerns obtaining from suitable assumptions on P .R/ that .;/
L.; R/Pmax “Martin’s MaximumCC .c/”; which requires any additional work to prove. Theorem 10.57. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: .;/ .;/ Then Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Further, suppose G Pmax is L.; R/generic. Then L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC
and in L.; R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) P .!1 / L.R/ŒAG ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) X(Code) .SAG ; zG / D ¹;º and Y(Code) .SAG ; zG / D P .!/. The absoluteness theorem, Theorem 10.55 also easily generalizes.
t u
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
753
Theorem 10.58. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”: Suppose is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; Y W Y 2 L.; R/; Y Ri; and that Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; Y W Y 2 L.; R/; Y RiL.;R/
:
Then .;/ Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; Y W Y 2 L.; R/; Y RiL.;R/
:
t u
The proof of Theorem 9.39, which shows that L.; R/Pmax Martin’s MaximumCC .c/; if L.; R/ ADR C “‚ is regular”; .;/ using the following techgeneralizes to to establish the corresponding version for Pmax nical lemma. This lemma is closely related to the results of .Foreman and Magidor 1995/.
Lemma 10.59. Suppose that P is a partial order such that: (i) P is !3 -cc, P
(ii) .!1 /V D .!1 /V . Suppose that jP j D ı and that for each set A ı, A# exists. Then P .ı12 /V D .ı12 /V :
t u
We shall obtain this as corollary of a slightly more general theorem, Theorem 10.62, which requires the following generalization of one of the main definitions of .Foreman and Magidor 1995/. Definition 10.60. Suppose that P is a partial order. P is weakly proper if for every ordinal ˛, .P!1 .˛//V is cofinal in P
.P!1 .˛//V :
t u
754
10 Further results
Remark 10.61. Foreman and Magidor define a partial order P to be reasonable if for every ordinal ˛, .P!1 .˛//V is stationary in P .P!1 .˛//V : It is not difficult to show that this notion is strictly stronger than that of being weakly proper. Recall that P is proper if for every ˛ and for every set S P!1 .˛/, if S is stationary then S is stationary in V P . Foreman and Magidor, .Foreman and Magidor 1995/, prove Theorem 10.62 and (implicitly) a strong version of Theorem 10.63 for reasonable partial orders; this version does not require the hypothesis, L.A; R/ AD: The special case of L.R/; i. e. A D ;, has also been examined by Neeman and Zapletal, but, as here, in the context of the relevant determinacy hypothesis. t u Theorem 10.62. Suppose that P is a partial order such that P is weakly proper. Suppose that jP j D ı and that for each set A ı, A# exists. Then P
.ı12 /V D .ı12 /V : Proof. There exists a tree T on ! 2ı such that if g P is V -generic then in V Œg; pŒT D ¹x # j x 2 Rº: It is convenient to work in V Œg. Since jP jV !2V , !3V is a cardinal in V Œg. Assume toward a contradiction that .ı12 /V < .ı12 /V Œg : Fix x0 2 RV Œg such that .ı12 /V < 0 where 0 is the least ordinal above !1V such that L 0 Œx0 is admissible. Thus x0# 2 pŒT . Since P is weakly proper, there exists a subtree S0 T such that (1.1) S0 2 V , (1.2) jS0 jV D !, (1.3) x0# 2 pŒS0 . Let S be the transitive collapse of S0 so that S is a tree on ! for some countable ordinal, which is isomorphic to the tree S0 . Let x 2 RV code S and for each ˛ !1 let ˇ˛ be the least ordinal above ˛ such that L Œx is admissible. Thus in V the following hold, (2.1) for all t 2 pŒS , t D z # for some z 2 R, (2.2) for all ˛ < !1 and for all t 2 pŒS , rank.M.z # ; ! C ˛// < ˇ˛ where z # D t and where M.z # ; ! C ˛/ is the ! C ˛ model of z # . We note that (2.2) holds by boundedness.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
755
By absoluteness, (2.1) and (2.2) hold in V Œg. Therefore in V Œg, for all ˛ < !1 , rank.M.x0# ; ! C ˛// < ˇ˛ : By reflection rank.M.x0# ; !1 // < ˇ!1 ; which contradicts the choice of x0 since necessarily ˇ!1 < .ı12 /V :
t u
There is a closely related theorem. Recall the following which is formally stated as Theorem 2.30. Suppose that A R is such that every set in P .R/ \ L.A; R/ is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin and that P is a partial order such that P 2 Vı . Suppose that T is a ı-weakly homogeneous tree such that A D pŒT : Finally, suppose that G P is V -generic. Then there is a generic elementary embedding jG W L.A; R/ ! L.AG ; RG / such that (1) jG .A/ D AG D pŒT V ŒG , (2) RG D RV ŒG , (3) L.AG ; RG / D ¹jG .f /.a/ j a 2 RG ; f W R ! L.A; R/ and f 2 L.A; R/º. Further the properties (1)–(3) uniquely specify jG . Theorem 10.63. Suppose that A R, L.A; R/ AD; and that every set in P .R/ \ L.A; R/ is ı-weakly homogeneously Suslin. Suppose that P 2 Vı is a partial order such that P is weakly proper. Suppose that G P is V -generic and let jG W L.A; R/ ! L.AG ; RG / be the associated generic elementary embedding. Then jG .˛/ D ˛ for all ˛ 2 Ord. Proof. Assume toward a contradiction that for some ˛ 2 Ord, jG .˛/ ¤ ˛: Let be the least ordinal ˛ such that jG .˛/ ¤ ˛; i. e. the critical point of jG . Necessarily, < ‚L.A;R/ : Let W dom./ !
756
10 Further results
be a surjection such that (1.1) 2 L.A; R/, (1.2) dom./ R, (1.3) if Z dom./ is †11 then sup¹.t / j t 2 Zº < : The existence of follows from Theorem 3.40 noting that since is the critical point of jG , is an uncountable regular cardinal of L.A; R/, below ‚L.A;R/ . This theorem of Steel was the key to the proofs of the covering theorems. Fix a weakly homogeneous tree such that dom./ D pŒT : Thus pŒT V ŒG D jG .dom.//: By the choice of , jG . / ¤ ; and jG .˛/ D ˛ for all ˛ < . Therefore there exists t0 2 dom.jG .// such that jG ./.z/ < jG ./.t0 / for all z 2 dom./. Thus in V ŒG, t0 2 pŒT . Since P is weakly proper in V , there exists a subtree T0 T such that (2.1) T0 2 V , (2.2) jT0 jV !, (2.3) t0 2 pŒT0 . 1 By (1.3), since in V , pŒT0 is a † 1 set, there exists x0 2 dom./ such that in V ,
.z/ < .x0 / for all z 2 pŒT0 . Therefore by the elementarity of jG , jG ./.z/ < jG ./.x0 / for all z 2 pŒT0
V ŒG
. But t0 2 pŒT0 V ŒG and so jG ./.t0 / < jG ./.x0 /;
which contradicts the choice of t0 .
t u
The technical lemma, Lemma 10.59, which we require for the proof of Theorem 10.69 is an immediate corollary of the next theorem.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
757
Theorem 10.64. Suppose P is a partial order such that P is !3 -cc and such that P .!1 /V D .!1 /V . Then P is weakly proper. Proof. By the chain condition of P , !3V is a cardinal in V P and so both !1V and !3V are cardinals in V P . Therefore by Lemma 9.120, .cof.!2V //V
P
> !:
Again by the chain condition of P , it suffices to prove that .P!1 .˛//V is cofinal in
P
.P!1 .˛//V ; where ˛ D !2V . But this is immediate.
t u
Theorem 9.134, Theorem 9.135, and Theorem 9.136 (these are the theorems of Section 9.7 concerning ideals on !2 ) are immediate corollaries of the boundedness theorems, Theorem 10.62 and Theorem 10.63, together with the next lemma. Lemma 10.65. Suppose that I P .!2 / is a normal uniform ideal such that ¹˛ j cof.˛/ D !º 2 I: Let P D hP .!2 / n I; i. Suppose that either (1) I is !3 -saturated, or (2) I is !-presaturated and that P is @! -cc, or (3) 2@2 D @3 and
P
.!1 /V D .!1 /V : Then P is weakly proper. Proof. (1) is an immediate corollary of Theorem 10.64. The proof of (2) is straightforward. The relevant observation is that since the ideal I is !-presaturated and since ¹˛ < !2 j cof.˛/ D !º 2 I; it follows that for each k < !, V //V .cof.!kC1
P
> !:
Since P is @! -cc, every countable set of ordinals in V P is covered by a set in V of cardinality (in V ) less than @! . This combined with the observation above, yields (2). The proof of (3) is a straightforward adaptation of the proof of Theorem 10.64, again one shows that for each k < !, V .cof.!kC1 //V
P
> !;
and of course one is only concerned with those values of k < ! such that P is not !kC1 -cc; i. e. with cardinals below the chain condition satisfied by P .
758
10 Further results
Since 2@2 D @3 , P is !4 -cc in V and so all cardinals above !3V are preserved. Therefore we need consider only the cases k 2. For k D 0 this is immediate and the case k D 1 follows by appealing to the generic ultrapower associated to the V -generic filter G P . This leaves the case k D 2; i. e. !3V . But this case now follows by Lemma 9.120. t u Lemma 10.68, below, isolates the application of Lemma 10.59 within the proof of Theorem 10.69. This lemma in turn requires the following two lemmas. Lemma 10.66. Suppose that hS˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of stationary subsets of !1 and that h ˛ W ˛ !1 i is a closed increasing sequence of cardinals such that for each ˛ < !1 , ˛C1 is measurable and such that !1 < . Suppose that S !1 is stationary and let Z be the set of X 2 P!1 . / such that (1) X \ !1 2 S , (2) For each ˛ X \ !1 , ordertype.X \ ˛ / 2 S˛ : Then Z is stationary in P!1 . /. Proof. Suppose T !1 is stationary. Let GT be the game played on !1 for T : The players alternate choosing countable ordinals, i , for i < ! with Player I choosing i for i even. Player I wins if sup¹i j i < !º 2 T: Since T is stationary, Player II cannot have a winning strategy. For each ˛ < !1 let G˛ be the game of length ! .1 C ˛/ defined as follows. A play of the game is an increasing sequence h W < ! .1 C ˛/i of countable ordinals. Player I chooses for even and Player II chooses for odd. Player II wins if for some ˇ ˛, sup¹ j < ! .1 C ˇ/º … Sˇ : We claim that for each ˛, Player II cannot have a winning strategy in G˛ . This is easily proved by induction on ˛. Let ˛0 be least such that Player II has a winning strategy in G˛0 and let W !1
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
759
If ˛0 is a limit ordinal then again one can construct a winning strategy for Player II in the game GS˛0 by using an increasing ! sequence cofinal in ˛0 . One constructs a strategy W !1
sup¹ j < ! .1 C ˇ/º 2 Sˇ ;
(1.2) sup¹i j i < !º D sup¹ j < ! .1 C ˛0 /º: The first condition, (1.1), is arranged by appealing to the induction hypothesis; i. e. that Player II does not have a winning strategy in G˛ for any ˛ < ˛0 and for any choice of hS W ˛i. This proves the claim that for each ˛, Player II cannot have a winning strategy in G˛ . Fix a countable elementary substructure X H. C / such that X \ !1 2 S and such that h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i 2 X: We claim there exists
Y H. C /
such that (2.1) X Y , (2.2) X \ !1 D Y \ !1 , (2.3) for each ˛ X \ !1 , ordertype.Y \ ˛ / 2 S˛ : If not then Player II has a winning strategy in G˛ where ˛ D X \ !1 . This follows from the following observation. Suppose Z H. C / is a countable elementary substructure and 2 Z is a measurable cardinal. Let 2 Z be a normal measure on and let 2 \¹A 2 Z j A 2 º: Let ZŒ D ¹f ./ j f 2 Zº:
760
10 Further results
Then (3.1) ZŒ H. C /, (3.2) Z \ V D ZŒ \ V . Using this it is straightforward to prove the claim above; if Y H.!2 / does not exist then Player II has a winning strategy in G˛ where ˛ D X \ !1 . Thus Y H. C / exists as required and the lemma follows. t u Lemma 10.67. Suppose that hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 and that there exist !1 many measurable cardinals. Then there is a partial order P such that P is .!; 1/-distributive and such that if G P is V -generic then .INS /V D .INS /V ŒG \ V and in V ŒG there exists a sequence hTi W i < !i of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1 and an ordinal such that: (1) For each i < !, Ti !1 and for each S 2 P .!1 / \ V n INS , both S \ Ti … INS and S n Ti … INS . (2) !1 < < !2 and cof. / D !1 . (3) There exists a closed cofinal set C such that for each i < !, hC; SQi \ C; 2i Š h!1 ; Ti ; 2i: (4) Suppose that W !1 ! is a surjection and that < . a) Suppose that i < !, S D ¹˛ < !1 j ordertype.Œ˛/ 2 Si º; and that S is stationary. Then for each k < !, both S \ Tk and S n Tk are stationary in !1 . b) Suppose that cof./ D !1 , C is closed and cofinal, S !1 is stationary and that for some i < !, hC; SQi \ C; 2i Š h!1 ; S; 2i: Then for each k < !, both S \ Tk and S n Tk are stationary in !1 .
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
761
Proof. Suppose that is a cardinal and that S !1 is stationary. Let P . ; S / denote the partial order where: (1.1) P . ; S / is the set of pairs .f; c/ such that a) c !1 , c is closed, and c is countable, b) f W max.c/ ! and for all ˛ 2 c, ordertype.f Œ˛/ 2 S: (1.2) .c0 ; f0 / .c1 ; f1 / if a) c0 D c1 \ .max.c0 / C 1/, b) f0 f1 . Suppose that is measurable or a countable limit of measurable cardinals. Suppose that A !1 is stationary and that g P . ; S / is V -generic then in V Œg: (2.1) V ! V . (2.2) 2 SQ . (2.3) A is stationary in !1 . This follows from Lemma 10.66. The key point is that by Lemma 10.66, ¹X 2 P!1 . / j X \ 2 A and ordertype.X / 2 S º is stationary in P!1 . /. More generally suppose h ˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a closed increasing sequence of cardinals such that for each ˛ < !1 , ˛C1 is measurable. Suppose that hA˛ W ˛ < !1 i is a sequence of stationary subsets of !1 and that Y g P . ˛ ; A˛ / ˛
is V -generic where the product partial order is computed with countable support. Then in V Œg: (3.1) V ! V . (3.2) For each ˇ < !1 , ˇ 2 AQˇ . (3.3) For each ˇ < !1 let gˇ D g \
Y
P . ˛ ; A˛ /:
˛<ˇ
Then .INS /V ŒgˇC1 D .INS /V Œg \ V Œgˇ C1 :
762
10 Further results
Again the verification is straightforward using Lemma 10.66. Let D sup¹ ˛ j ˛ < !1 º: The key point is that, by Lemma 10.66, for each stationary set A !1 , SA P!1 . / is stationary in P!1 . / where SA is the set of X 2 P!1 . / such that (4.1) X \ !1 2 A, (4.2) For each ˛ X \ !1 , ordertype.X \ ˛ / 2 A˛ : The first claim, (3.1), follows from this as does .INS /V D .INS /V Œg \ V; which is a weak version of the third claim, (3.3). Note that by (3.1), Y V Y V ŒgˇC1 P . ˛ ; A˛ / D P . ˛ ; A˛ / ; ˛2!1 n
˛2!1 n
where D ˇ C 1, and so V Œg D V Œgˇ C1 Œgˇ C1;!1 where gˇ C1;!1 D g \
Y
V P . ˛ ; A˛ /
;
˛2!1 n
where D ˇ C 1. Thus (3.3) follows by applying Lemma 10.66 in V Œgˇ C1 and arguing as above. Let G0 Coll.!1 ; !1 / be V -generic and in V ŒG0 let for each k < !, Tk D fG1 .k/ 0 where fG0 W !1 ! !1 is the function given by G0 . For each i < ! let i be the i th measurable cardinal. For each (nonzero) limit ordinal ˛ < !1 let ˛CiC1 be the .˛ C i /th -measurable cardinal where i < ! and let ˛ D sup¹ ˇ j ˇ < ˛º: Let Q0 be the product partial order, defined in V ŒG: Y P . ˛ ; Si˛ /; Q0 D ˛2Z
where (5.1) Z D [¹Tk j k < !º, (5.2) for each ˛ 2 Z, i˛ D k where
˛ 2 Tk :
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
763
As above, the product is defined with countable support. Let P D Coll.!1 ; !1 / Q0 : We claim that P is as required. The required properties, (1)–(3), follow from the definitions. We must verify (4). Let G P be V -generic and that V ŒG D V ŒG0 ŒH0 where H0 Q0 is V ŒG0 -generic. For each ˛ < !1 V ŒG0 ŒH0 D V ŒG0 ŒH0˛ ŒH ˛;!1 where D H0 \
H0˛
Y
V ŒG0 P . ˇ ; Siˇ /
ˇ 2Z\˛
and where H0˛;!1
D H0 \
Y
P . ˇ ; Siˇ /
V ŒG0 ŒH0˛ :
ˇ 2Zn˛
The key point is that Y
V P . ˇ ; Siˇ /
ˇ 2Z\˛
D
Y
V ŒG0 P . ˇ ; Siˇ /
ˇ 2Z\˛
since V ! V in V ŒG0 . Therefore it follows that for each ˛ < !1 , G0 is V ŒH0˛ generic for Coll.!1 ; !1 /. Thus for each ˛ < !, if ˛C1
S 2 .P .!1 / n INS /V ŒH0
;
ŒH0˛C1 ŒG0 ,
then in V for each k < !, both S \ Tk and S n Tk are stationary. Both (4(a)) and (4(b)) follow from this. t u Lemma 10.68. Suppose that V D L.S; A; R/ŒG and (i) L.S; A; R/ ADC , (ii) S Ord and A R, .;/ (iii) G Pmax is an L.S; A; R/-generic filter.
Suppose ı 2 Ord, L.S; A; R/ŒG “ı is a Woodin cardinal”; and that L.S; A; R/ŒG “There is a measurable cardinal above ı”: Suppose that 2 Ord is such that ı < , S 2 V , and such that V †2 V:
764
10 Further results
Suppose that Y L .S; A; R/ŒG is a countable elementary substructure with ¹G; S; A; ıº Y , let M0 be the transitive collapse of Y , and let .ı0 ; g0 / be the image of .ı; G/ under the collapsing map. Suppose that P0 2 M0 Œg0 is a partial order such that M0 Œg0 “P0 is !2 -cc and jP0 j D !2 ” and such that M0 Œg0 “ INS D .INS /V
P0
\ V ”:
Let h0 P0 be an M0 Œg0 -generic filter. Then there exists a partial order P1 2 Vı0 \ M0 Œg0 Œh0 such that if h1 P1 is an M0 Œg0 Œh0 -generic filter and if I0 D .I<ı0 /M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 ; then the following hold. (1) .INS /M0 Œg0 Œh0 D .INS /M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 \ M0 Œg0 Œh0 . (2) There exist .;/ hN ; a; zi 2 Pmax
and an iteration j W .M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 ; I0 / ! .M0 Œj.g0 /Œj.h0 /Œj.h1 /; j.I0 // of length !1N such that a) j 2 N , b) j..INS /M0 Œg0 Œh0 / D .INS /N \ M0 Œj.g0 /Œj.h0 /, c) for each p 2 j.g0 /, hN ; a; zi < p. Proof. The key point is that, by Theorem 10.64, M Œg0 “P0 is weakly proper” and so by Lemma 10.67, .ı12 /M0 Œg0 D .ı12 /M0 Œg0 Œh0 : Let a0 D .Ag0 /M0 Œg0 and let z0 D .zg0 /M Œg0 . Thus X(Code) .M Œg0 ; Sa0 ; z0 / D X(Code) .M Œg0 Œh0 ; Sa0 ; z0 / since by Theorem 10.54(5), P .!/ \ M0 D Y(Code) .M0 Œg0 ; Sa0 ; z0 /: Here is the second place we make full use of the thinning requirement, Definition 10.22(iv(b)), the first place was in the proof of Theorem 10.55. Let hsi0 W i < !i D .Sa0 /M0 Œg0
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
765
Note that it is certainly possible that h..si0 / /M0 Œg0 W i < !i ¤ h..si0 / /M0 Œg0 Œh0 W i < !i: Let 0 D .!2 /M0 Œg0 D .ı12 /M0 Œg0 D .ı12 /M0 Œg0 Œh0 : Note that S(Code) .M0 Œg0 ; Sa0 ; z0 / has length 0 . By the preservation properties of P0 , .INS /M0 Œg0 D .INS /M0 Œg0 Œh0 \ M0 Œg0 : Thus S(Code) .M0 Œg0 Œh0 ; Sa0 ; z0 /j0 D S(Code) .M0 Œg0 ; Sa0 ; z0 /: For each ˛ < !1M0 let ˛0 be the ˛ th measurable cardinal of M0 Œg0 Œh0 and let 0 D sup¹ ˛0 j ˛ < !1M0 º: Let P1 2 Vı0 \M0 Œg0 Œh0 satisfy in Vı0 \M0 Œg0 Œh0 the conclusions of Lemma 10.67 relative to hsi0 W i < !i. Let h1 P1 be an M0 Œg0 Œh0 -generic filter. Let hti0 W i < !i 2 M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 be the sequence of subsets of !1M0 given by h1 . Thus the following hold in M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 . (1.1) For each i < !, ti0 !1 and for each S 2 .P .!1 / n INS /M0 Œg0 Œh0 , both S \ tk0 and S n tk0 are stationary in !1 . (1.2) M0 Œg0 Œh0 ! M0 Œg0 Œh0 . (1.3) !1 < 0 < !2 (and so cof.0 / D !1 ). (1.4) There exists a closed cofinal set C 0 such that for each i < !, hC; .si0 / \ C; 2i Š h!1 ; ti0 ; 2i: (1.5) Suppose that W !1 ! is a surjection and that < 0 . a) Suppose that i < !, S D ¹˛ < !1 j ordertype.Œ˛/ 2 si0 º; and that S is stationary. Then for each k < !, both S \ tk0 and S n tk0 are stationary in !1 .
766
10 Further results
b) Suppose that cof./ D !1 , C is closed and cofinal, S !1 is stationary and that for some i < !, hC; C \ .si0 / ; 2i Š h!1 ; S; 2i: Then for each k < !, both S \ tk0 and S n tk0 are stationary in !1 . Fix t ! such that t codes M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 and let .;/ hN ; b; zi 2 Pmax be such that t # 2 LŒz. By Lemma 5.37, .M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 ; I0 / is iterable where I0 D .I<ı0 /M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 : Let j W .M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 ; I0 / ! .M0 Œg0 Œh0 Œh1 ; I0 / be an iteration of length .!1 /N such that j 2 N and such that the following hold in N. (2.1) Let Sb D hSib W i < !i: For each i < !, j.si0 /\C D Sib \C where C .!1 /N is the set of < .!1 /N such that is an indiscernible of LŒz.
(2.2) .INS /M0 Œg0 Œh0 D INS \ M0 Œg0 Œh0 . (2.3) Suppose that W !1 ! is a surjection and that < j.0 /. a) Suppose that i < !, S D ¹˛ < !1 j ordertype.Œ˛/ 2 j.si0 /º; and that S is stationary in M0 Œj.g0 /Œj.h0 /Œj.h1 /. Then S is stationary. b) Suppose that cof./ D !1 , C is closed and cofinal, S !1 is stationary in M0 Œj.g0 /Œj.h0 /Œj.h1 /, and that for some i < !, hC; C \ .si0 / ; 2i Š h!1 ; S; 2i: Then S is stationary. (2.4) ¹3iC1 j i 2 zº D ¹i j j.ti0 / … INS º. By (2.3) and (2.4), ¹3iC1 j i 2 zº D ¹i j ..j.si0 // /N \ j.0 / … .INS /N º: We now come to the essential points. Let j.S(Code) .M0 Œg0 ; Sa0 ; z0 // D h. ; X ; Y / W < j.0 /i; and S(Code) .N ; j.Sa0 /; z0 / D h. ; X ; Y / W < i:
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
767
Then, (3.1) j.0 / < , (3.2) S(Code) .N ; j.Sa0 /; z0 /jj.0 / 2 M0 Œj.g0 /Œj.h0 /Œj.h1 /, D X D ¹;º, (3.3) Xj. 0/ (3.4) Yj. D Yj. [ ¹zº. 0 /C1 0/
Let
S(Code) .N ; Sj.a0 / ; z/ D h. ; X ; Y / W < i:
(4.1) D j.0 / C . . (4.2) For each < , D j. 0 /C1C
(4.3) For each < , .Xj. ; Yj. / D .X [ Xj. ; Y [ Yj. /: 0 /C1C 0 /C1C 0/ 0/
t u
Theorem 10.69. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: .;/ Suppose G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Suppose H Coll.!3 ; H.!3 //L.;R/ŒG0 is L.; R/ŒG0 -generic. Then L.; R/ŒG0 ŒH0 ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/:
Proof. Using Lemma 10.68, the proof is quite similar to the proof of Theorem 9.39. u t Combining Theorem 10.55, Theorem 10.57, Theorem 10.69, and Lemma 10.56 we obtain the following theorem. The proof follows closely that of Theorem 9.114 which is outlined in Section 9.6 where the hypothesis is discussed. This theorem shows that for Theorem 4.76 it is essential that the predicate INS be part of the structure. Theorem 10.70. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.; R/. For each ı < let ı D ¹A ! ! j w.A/ < ‚ı º and let Nı D HODL.;R/ .ı /: Let W be the set of ı < such that ı D ‚ı and such that Nı “ı is regular”. .;/ Suppose that ı 2 W , G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic and that H0 .Coll.!3 ; P .!2 ///Nı ŒG0 is Nı ŒG0 -generic. Let M D Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 . Then:
768
10 Further results
(1) M Martin’s MaximumCC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture; (2) Suppose .x0 / is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/i; and that
Pmax
hH.!2 /; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/iL.R/
:
Then hH.!2 /; Y; 2 W Y R; Y 2 L.R/iM I (3) M :./. Proof. The claim that
M Martin’s MaximumCC .c/
follows by Theorem 10.69 and (2) follows by Theorem 10.55. By Theorem 10.57, X(Code) .SAG ; zG / D ¹;º and so (3) follows from Lemma 10.56. The proof that M Strong Chang’s Conjecture requires adapting the proof of Theorem 9.114. This is straightforward, we leave the details to the reader. u t .;;B/ 10.2.4 Pmax
It is not difficult to prove the following theorem. One uses the proof that Martin’s Maximum implies ˘! .!2 / (Theorem 5.11 from the first edition) together with the fact that, assuming Martin’s Maximum, if G is V -generic for Namba forcing then .ı12 /V < .ı12 /V ŒG : Theorem 10.71. Assume Martin’s Maximum. Suppose that S D hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 . Then for each z 2 P .!/, X(Code) .S; z/ D P .!/:
t u
.S; z/, It is straightforward to define minor variations of X(Code) .S; z/, say X(Code) for which it seems very unlikely that Theorem 10.71 holds; i. e. for which it is unlikely that Martin’s Maximum implies X(Code) .S; z/ D P .!/:
For example one could simply add the requirement, in the calculation of X(Code) .S; z/, that at every stage the stationary subsets of !1 given by SQi \ be independent from all the previous stationary sets (cf. Definition 10.22(iv)). This gives a
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
769
plausible approach to showing that Martin’s Maximum does not imply ./, even if one assumes in addition that large cardinals are present. The situation for Martin’s MaximumCC is more subtle. Indeed the question of whether Martin’s MaximumCC implies ./ assuming some additional large cardinal hypothesis, is in essence the question of whether some large cardinal hypothesis implies that there exists a semiproper partial order P such that V P ./: However there is a natural modification in Definition 10.22 which plausibly yields an approach to showing that Martin’s MaximumCC does not imply ./ outright. This in .;;B/ .;/ turn yields another variation of Q.X/ max which we denote Pmax . As is the case for Pmax , .;;B/ .;/ Pmax is in essence a variation of Qmax , but with a new parameter B R. .;;B/ -extension yields the following result. The analysis of the Pmax Fix B R with B 2 L.R/. Then Martin’s Maximum CC .c/ C Strong Chang’s Conjecture together with all the …2 consequences of ./ for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2i does not imply ./. Thus for the characterization of ./ (Theorem 4.76), using the “converse” of the absoluteness theorem, it is essential that predicates be added for cofinally many sets Y R with Y 2 L.R/. This result complements the results of the previous section which show that the predicate for INS must be added. Definition 10.72. Suppose that hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 Suppose that z ! and that B R. Let S D hSi W i < !i and let ES D ¹˛ C i C 1 j ˛ < !1 ; ˛ is a limit ordinal and ˛ 2 Si º: Let A(Code) .S; z; B/ D [¹A j < ıº where S(Code) .S; z/ D h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi and hA W < ıi is the sequence: (i) A0 D ¹;º. (ii) Suppose is not the successor of an ordinal of cofinality !1 . Then A D [¹A˛ j ˛ < º: (iii) Suppose has cofinality !1 and let b D ¹i < ! j SQi is stationary in º: Let d D ¹i j 3
iC1
2 bº and let a D ¹i j 2iC1 2 bº. Let be least such that L .Y ; B \ L .Y // ZF n Powerset
and let N D L .Y ; B \ L .Y //. Suppose that
770
10 Further results
a) < where is the least indiscernible of LŒd above !1 , b) Y D P .!/ \ N , c) hV!C1 \ N ; B \ N ; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i, d) is the least Y -uniform indiscernible above !1 , e) N ADC and ES is N -generic for Pmax , f) .INS /N ŒES D INS \ N ŒES . Then AC1 D A [ ¹aº. Otherwise AC1 D A .
t u
Remark 10.73. (1) Thus, with notation from Definition 10.72, new elements are added to A(Code) .S; z; B/ only at stages when new elements could be added to X(Code) .S; z/ and various additional side conditions are satisfied. Again this can be modified. For example one could replace (iii(e)) with the condition that N ADC and ES is N -generic for P ; where P D Smax , or P D Bmax etc. More subtle effects can be achieved by modifying (iii(f)). For example if one replaces Pmax by Smax in (iii(e)) then in light of the absoluteness theorem for Smax , it would be natural to make the analogous change in (iii(f)) requiring in addition that Suslin trees be preserved. This is the correct analog of A(Code) .S; z; B/ for Smax . (2) Note that A(Code) .S; z; B/ X(Code) .S; z/. This is because we have defined a D ¹2iC1 j i 2 bº: We could easily decouple A(Code) .S; z; B/ and X(Code) .S; z/ by setting a D ¹5iC1 j i 2 bº: However by adopting the former approach, certain aspects of the analysis of the .;;B/ .;/ -extension can be reduced to the analysis of the Pmax -extension. Pmax (3) By (iii(b)), (iii(e)), (iii(f)), and (essentially) Lemma 10.56, a) !1 D .!1 /N , b) D D .!2 /N , c) S(Code) .S; z/j D .S(Code) .S; z//N ŒES .
t u
Lemma 10.56, which analyzes X(Code) .S; z/ in the context of ./, generalizes to characterize ./ in terms of the behavior of A(Code) .S; z; B/.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
771
Lemma 10.74. The following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) Suppose that hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 and that z !. For each B 2 P .P .!// \ L.R/, A(Code) .hSi W i < !i; z; B/ D P .!/: (3) Suppose that hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 and that z !. For each B 2 P .P .!// \ L.R/, A(Code) .hSi W i < !i; z; B/ ¤ ¹;º: Proof. (1) implies (2) by a straightforward analysis which we leave to the reader. Trivially (2) implies (3). Finally (3) implies (1) essentially from the definitions. To see this fix a set A !1 such that !1 D .!1 /LŒA ; and let hAi W i < !i be an infinite sequence of subsets of !1 with A0 D A. Let hSi W i < !i be a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 such that for each i < !, Ai D ¹˛ j ! 2 ˛ C ! 2 Si º and let ES D ¹˛ C i C 1 j ˛ < !1 ; ˛ is a limit ordinal and ˛ 2 Si º: Fix z ! and B R with B 2 L.R/. Since A(Code) .hSi W i < !i; z; B/ ¤ ¹;º; there exists a transitive set N such that (1.1) N ZF n Powerset, (1.2) B \ N 2 N , (1.3) hV!C1 \ N ; B \ N ; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i, (1.4) N ADC and ES is N -generic for .Pmax /N , (1.5) .INS /N ŒES D INS \ N ŒES . Note that A 2 L!1 C1 ŒES and so by (1.4), A is N -generic for .Pmax /N . By (1.3) and (1.4), L.R/ AD: By varying the choice of hAi W i < !i it follows that if C !1 is closed and unbounded then C contains a closed, unbounded, subset which is constructible from a real. Thus there exists a countable elementary substructure, X hH.!2 /; 2i; such that MX is iterable where MX is the transitive collapse of X .
772
10 Further results
Let FA be the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that (2.1) j .a/ D A,
(2.2) .INS /M D INS \ M . By Lemma 4.74, the elements of FA are pairwise compatible in Pmax . Let GAN .Pmax /N be the N -generic filter given by A. Thus GAN FA and FA \ D ¤ ; for each dense set D Pmax which is definable in the structure hH.!1 /; B; 2i from z. By varying the choice of B it follows that FA \ D ¤ ; for each dense set D Pmax such that D 2 L.R/. Thus FA is a filter in Pmax which is t L.R/-generic; i. e. the set A is L.R/-generic for Pmax . This implies that ./ holds. u Thus the question of whether Theorem 10.71 generalizes to show that Martin’s MaximumCC implies that for each sequence hSi W i < !i of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of !1 and for each z !, A(Code) .hSi W i < !i; z; B/ D P .!/ for each B 2 L.R/; is in essence the question of whether Martin’s MaximumCC implies ./. Definition 10.75. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC, S 2 M, and that S D hSi W i < !i is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets such that for all i < !, Si 2 .P .!1 / n INS /M : Suppose z !, B P .!/ and .z; B/ 2 M. Then S(Code) .M; S; z; B/ D .S(Code) .S; z; B//M :
t u
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
773
Definition 10.76. Suppose that B R: .;;B/ Pmax
is the set of triples hM; a; zi
such that the following hold. (1) M is a countable transitive set such that M ZFC C ZC: (2) M is B-iterable. (3) M
AC .
(4) Let hSi W i < !i D .Sa /M . For each i < !, Si … .INS /M . (5) Suppose that C !1M is closed and unbounded with C 2 M. Then there exists a closed cofinal set D C such that D 2 LŒx for some x 2 R \ M. (6) A(Code) .M; Sa ; z; B \ M/ D ¹;º. (7) Y(Code) .M; Sa ; z/ D P .!/ \ M. The order is defined as follows: hM1 ; a1 ; z1 i < hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i if z1 D z0 and there exists an iteration j W M0 ! M0 such that (1) j.a0 / D a1 ,
(2) .INS /M0 D .INS /M1 \ M0 .
t u
.;/ .;/ Remark 10.77. Let P Pmax be the suborder of Pmax defined by .;/ j M is B-iterableº: P D ¹hM; a; zi 2 Pmax .;;B/ . This is because we have defined A(Code) .S; z; B/ so Then P is a suborder of Pmax that A(Code) .S; z; B/ X(Code) .S; z/:
This observation which we have discussed in Remark 10.73, allows one to infer the .;;B/ .;/ from that of Pmax . u t nontriviality of Pmax
774
10 Further results
Theorem 10.78. Suppose that A R and that L.A; R/ ADC : Suppose that B R and that B 2 L.A; R/. Then there exists .;;B/ hM; a; zi 2 Pmax such that (1) A \ M 2 M and hM \ V!C1 ; A \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i, (2) M is A-iterable.
t u
.;/ .;;B/ As for the analysis of Pmax it is convenient to organize the analysis of Pmax fol.X/ .;/ lowing closely that of Qmax (and Pmax ). Again the reason is simply that the proofs .;;B/ adapt easily to prove the corresponding lemmas for the Pmax analysis. The next four lemmas give the basic iteration facts one needs.
Lemma 10.79. Suppose that B R. Suppose hM1 ; a1 ; z1 i < hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i .;;B/ in Pmax and let
j W M0 ! M0
be the .unique/ iteration such that j.a0 / D a1 : Suppose that b0 2 M0 is such that for each i < !, Sia0 M Sib0 2 .INS /M0 ; where hSia0 W i < !i D .Sa0 /M0 and hSib0 W i < !i D .Sb0 /M0 : Suppose that x0 2 M0 is a subset of ! such that .;;B/ : hM0 ; b0 ; x0 i 2 Pmax .;;B/ and Then hM1 ; j.b0 /; x0 i 2 Pmax
hM1 ; j.b0 /; x0 i < hM0 ; b0 ; x0 i:
t u
.;;B/ are routine The remaining iteration lemmas required for the analysis of Pmax .;/ generalizations of those for Pmax .
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
775
Lemma 10.80. Suppose that B R. Suppose that .;;B/ ; hM1 ; a1 ; z1 i 2 Pmax .;;B/ ; hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i 2 Pmax
t ! codes M0 , and that t 2 LŒz1 : Let hSia0 W i < !i D .Sa0 /M0 , let hSia1 W i < !i D .Sa1 /M1 , and let C be the set of < !1M1 such that is an indiscernible of LŒt . Then there exists an iteration j W M0 ! M0 such that j 2 M1 and such that: (1) for each i < !, C \ j.Sia0 / D C \ Sia1 ; .;;B/ (2) hM1 ; j.a0 /; z0 i 2 Pmax ;
(3) hM1 ; j.a0 /; z0 i < hM0 ; a0 ; z0 i.
t u
Lemma 10.81. Suppose that B R and that hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i .;;B/ is a sequence of dense subsets of Pmax . Let Y R be the set of reals x such that x codes a triple .p; ˛; y/ with p 2 D˛ and y 2 B. Suppose that .M; T; ı/ 2 H.!1 / is such that:
(i) M is transitive and M ZFC. (ii) ı 2 M \ Ord, and ı is strongly inaccessible in M . (iii) T 2 M and T is a tree on ! ı. (iv) Suppose P 2 Mı is a partial order and that g P is an M -generic filter with g 2 H.!1 /. Then hM Œg \ V!C1 ; pŒT \ M Œg; 2i hV!C1 ; Y; 2i: .;;B/ Suppose that hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i is a sequence of conditions in Pmax such that
(v) hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i 2 M , (vi) for all ˛ < !1M , p˛ 2 D˛ , (vii) for all ˛ < ˇ < !1M , pˇ < p˛ .
776
10 Further results
Suppose g Coll.!; !1M / is M -generic and let Z D [¹Z˛ j ˛ < !1M º where for each ˛ < !1M ,
Z˛ D P .!/ \ M˛
and hM˛ ; a˛ ; z0 i D p˛ . Suppose is a Z-uniform indiscernible, !1M < < !2M and that hAi W i < !i 2 M Œg is a sequence of subsets of !1M . Then for each m < !, there exists a condition hN ; a; zi 2 D! M 1
such that the following hold where hSi W i < !i D .Sa /N ; and where for each ˛ < !1M , ˛ is the ˛ th Z-uniform indiscernible above !1N . (1) hN ; a; zi 2 M Œg, < !1N , and 2 Sm . (2) For each i < ! and for each ˛ < !1M , ˛ 2 Ai if and only if ˛ 2 .SQi /N . (3) For all ˛ < !1M , hN ; a; zi < p˛ . (4) hp˛ W ˛ < !1M i 2 N .
t u
Lemma 10.82. Suppose that B R and that hD˛ W ˛ < !1 i .;;B/ is a sequence of dense subsets of Pmax . Let Y R be the set of reals x such that x codes a triple .p; ˛; y/ with p 2 D˛ and y 2 B. Suppose that
.M; I/ 2 H.!1 / is such that .M; I/ is strongly Y -iterable. Let ı 2 M be the Woodin cardinal associated to I. Suppose t !, t codes M and .;;B/ ; hN ; a; zi 2 Pmax
is a condition such that t 2 LŒz. Let 2 Mı be a normal .uniform/ measure and let .M ; / be the !1N -th iterate of .M; /. Then there exists a sequence hp˛ W ˛ < !1N i 2 N and there exists .b; x/ 2 N such that .;;B/ (1) hN ; b; xi 2 Pmax ,
(2) for all ˛ < !1N , p˛ 2 D˛ and hN ; b; xi < p˛ , (3) there exists an M -generic filter g Coll.!;
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
777
From Lemma 10.79 and Lemma 10.80 one easily obtains the homogeneity and the .;;B/ !-closure of Pmax . .;;B/ is Lemma 10.83. Suppose that B R and that L.B; R/ ADC . Then Pmax !-closed. t u .;;B/ Lemma 10.84. Suppose that B R and that L.B; R/ ADC . Then Pmax is homogeneous. t u
We adopt the usual notational conventions. Suppose that B R. A filter .;;B/ G Pmax
is semi-generic if for all ˛ < !1 there exists a condition hM; a; zi 2 G such that ˛ <
!1M .
.;;B/ Suppose that G Pmax is a semi-generic filter. Then
(1) zG D z where z occurs in p for some p 2 G, (2) AG D [¹a j hM; a; zi 2 Gº,
(3) IG D [¹.INS /M j hM; a; zi 2 Gº, (4) P .!1 /G D [¹M \ P .!1 / j hM; a; zi 2 Gº, where for each hM; a; zi 2 G, j W M ! M .;/ is the (unique) iteration such that j.a/ D AG . Of course, as for Pmax , zG must occur in every condition in G. .;;B/ The basic analysis of Pmax is given in the following theorem. The proof is a straightforward adaptation of the arguments for the analysis of Pmax , using Lemma 10.82 and Theorem 10.78.
Theorem 10.85. Suppose that L.R/ AD .;;B/ and that B 2 P .R/ \ L.R/. Then Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Further, suppose .;;B/ G Pmax
is L.R/-generic. Then L.R/ŒG ZFC and in L.R/ŒG: (1) L.R/ŒG D L.R/ŒfG ; (2) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /;
778
10 Further results
(3) IG is a normal !2 -saturated ideal on !1 ; (4) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (5) A(Code) .SAG ; zG ; B/ D ¹;º and Y(Code) .SAG ; zG / D P .!/. Proof. We sketch the argument essentially reproducing the proof of Theorem 10.54. .;/ .;/ is !-closed and by Lemma 10.84, Pmax is homogeneous. By Lemma 10.83, Pmax By the usual arguments, (2) and the assertion that L.R/ŒG ZF C !1 -DC each follow from Lemma 10.82 using Theorem 10.78 to supply the necessary conditions. .;/ . (5) implies that (4) and (5) follow from (2) and the definition of the order on Pmax R can be wellordered in L.R/ŒG and so L.R/ŒG ZFC: By (2), if C !1 is closed, unbounded, then C contains a closed, unbounded, subset which is constructible from a real. Thus .INS /L.R/ŒAG D .INS /L.R/ŒG \ L.R/ŒAG : This implies that .S(Code) .SAG ; zG //L.R/ŒAG D .S(Code) .SAG ; zG //L.R/ŒG ; and so L.R/ŒAg ZFC. The generic filter G can be defined in L.R/ŒAg as the set of all .;;B/ hM; a; zG i 2 Pmax
such that there exists an iteration j W M ! M satisfying: (1.1) j.a/ D AG , (1.2) j 2 L.M; AG /,
(1.3) .INS /M D .INS /L.R/ŒAG \ M . Note that (1.2) follows from (1.1) since M
AC :
Finally (3) can be proved by adapting the proof of the analogous claim for Pmax . As in .;/ the case of Pmax , (3) can also be proved by first proving that for each set Z 2 L.R/ \ P .R/ there exists a countable elementary X hH.!2 /; Z; 2i such that MX is Z-iterable, where MX is the transitive collapse of X . See the proof of Theorem 10.54(3). t u
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
779
Theorem 10.86. Suppose that L.R/ AD .;;B/ is L.R/-generic. Let FG be and that B 2 P .R/ \ L.R/. Suppose that G Pmax the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that in L.R/ŒG there exists an iteration
j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that j.a/ D AG and such that I D .INS /L.R/ŒG \ M : Then (1) FG is a filter in Pmax , (2) FG \ D ¤ ; for each dense set D Pmax which is definable in hH.!1 /; B; 2i from parameters in H.!1 /, (3) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /FG . Proof. By Theorem 10.85, the hypothesis of Lemma 4.74 holds in L.R/ŒG and so by Lemma 4.74, FG is a filter in Pmax . We assume toward a contradiction that (2) fails and we fix t 2 R such that there is a dense set D t Pmax such that (1.1) FG \ D t D ;, (1.2) D t is definable in the structure hH.!1 /; B; 2i from t . Fix a condition hM; a; zi 2 G which forces (1.1). Let M0 be a countable transitive set such that (2.1) M0 ZFC C †1 -Replacement, (2.2) R \ M0 2 M0 , (2.3) B \ M0 2 .L.R//M0 , (2.4) hV!C1 \ M0 ; B \ M0 ; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i, (2.5) M0 is B-iterable, (2.6) M 2 .H.!1 //M0 ; and such that M0 \ Ord is a small as possible.
780
10 Further results
Fix x 2 P .!/ \ M0 such that x codes M and fix a sequence hTi W i < !i 2 M0 of pairwise disjoint subsets of !1M0 such that x D ¹i j T3i C1 … .INS /M0 º: For each ˛ < .!1 /M0 let ˛ be the ˛ th .M \ P .!//-uniform indiscernible above !1M0 . Let C D ¹˛ < .!1 /M0 j is a cardinal in L.M/º n M: Let .Sa /M D hsi W i < !i and let j W M ! M be an iteration such that: (3.1) j 2 M0 and has length .!1 /M0 .
(3.2) .INS /M D .INS /M0 \ M . (3.3) For each ˛ 2 C ,
˛ 2 ..j.si // /M0
if and only if ˛ 2 Ti . Let a D j.a/ and let h. ; X ; Y / W < ıi D .S(Code) .Sa ; z//M0 : It follows from (3.1) and (3.2) that
h. ; X ; Y / W < .!2 /M i D .S(Code) .Sa ; z//M : Since M ./,
.Y(Code) .Sa ; z//M D P .!/ \ M
and so Y0 D P .!/ \ M , where 0 D .!2 /M . Thus for each ˛ < !1M0 , 0 C˛ D ˛ ; and so if 1 D 0 C .!1 /M0 then Y1 D Y0 [ ¹xº: Therefore by the choice of M0 , minimizing M0 \ Ord, .A(Code) .Sa ; z; B//M0 D ¹;º .;;B/ and and so hM0 ; a ; zi 2 Pmax
hM0 ; a ; zi < hM; a; zi: By the genericity of G we can suppose hM0 ; a ; zi 2 G: Let
jG W M0 ! M0
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
781
be the iteration such that jG .a / D AG . Let g0 .Pmax /M0 be the .L.R//M0 -generic filter given by a ; i. e. such that a D .Ag0 /M0 . From the definition of FG and the elementarity of jG , it follows that g0 FG : However D t \ M0 2 .L.R//M0 and D t \ M0 is dense in .Pmax /M0 . Therefore g0 \ D t ¤ ; which implies that FG \ D t ¤ ; this contradicts the choice of D t . Finally a similar argument proves (3). If (3) fails then there exist hM; a; zi 2 G and a set b 2 .P .!1 //M such that jO.b/ … P .!1 /FG where
jO W M ! MO
is the (unique) iteration such that jO.a/ D AG . Clearly we may assume that the condition hM; a; zi forces this. Repeating the construction given above yields a contradiction. t u .;;B/ As an immediate corollary we obtain the desired absoluteness theorem for Pmax .
Theorem 10.87. Suppose that L.R/ AD and that B 2 P .R/ \ L.R/. Suppose is a sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2i and that Pmax
hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2iL.R/
:
Then .;;B/ Pmax
hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2iL.R/
:
.;;B/ Proof. Suppose that G Pmax is L.R/-generic. Let FG be the set of h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that in L.R/ŒG there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
such that j.a/ D AG and such that I D .INS /L.R/ŒG \ M :
782
10 Further results
Then by Theorem 10.86, (1.1) FG is a filter in Pmax , (1.2) FG \ D ¤ ; for each dense set D Pmax which is definable in hH.!1 /; B; 2i from parameters in H.!1 /, (1.3) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /FG . By Theorem 10.85, .P .!1 //L.R/ŒG D P .R/G and so by (1.3), .P .!1 //L.R/ŒG D P .!1 /FG . The theorem follows, in fact one obtains Pmax
hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2iL.R/
Œz
if and only if .;;B/ Pmax
hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2iL.R/
Œz
for all z 2 R and for all formulas . .;;B/
The basic analysis of L.R/Pmax fashion.
t u .;;B/
easily generalizes to L.; R/Pmax
in the usual
Theorem 10.88. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular” .;;B/ and that B 2 \ L.R/. Then Pmax is !-closed and homogeneous. Further, suppose .;;B/ G Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Then
L.; R/ŒG !2 -DC and in L.; R/ŒG: (1) P .!1 /G D P .!1 /; (2) P .!1 / L.R/ŒAG ; (3) IG is the nonstationary ideal; (4) A(Code) .SAG ; zG ; B/ D ¹;º and Y(Code) .SAG ; zG / D P .!/.
t u
The proof of Theorem 10.69 easily adapts to prove the corresponding version for .;;B/ .;;B/ Pmax . One uses Lemma 10.67 to produce the analog of Lemma 10.68 for Pmax in essentially the same manner.
10.2 Coding into L.P .!1 //
783
Theorem 10.89. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular” and that B 2 \ L.R/. .;;B/ Suppose G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Suppose H Coll.!3 ; H.!3 //L.;R/ŒG0 is L.; R/ŒG0 -generic. Then t u L.; R/ŒG0 ŒH0 ZFC C Martin’s MaximumCC .c/: Putting everything together we obtain Theorem 10.90. The proof of Theorem 10.90(2) follows closely that of Theorem 9.114 which is outlined in Section 9.6 where the hypothesis is discussed. This theorem shows that for Theorem 4.76 predicates for cofinally many sets in P .R/ \ L.R/ must be added to the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i. Theorem 10.90. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: Let h‚˛ W ˛ < i be the ‚-sequence of L.; R/. For each ı < let ı D ¹A ! ! j w.A/ < ‚ı º and let Nı D HODL.;R/ .ı /: Let W be the set of ı < such that ı D ‚ı and Nı “ı is regular”. Suppose that .;;B/ B 2 P .R/ \ L.R/, ı 2 W , G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic, and that H0 .Coll.!3 ; P .!2 ///Nı ŒG0 is Nı ŒG0 -generic. Let M D Nı ŒG0 ŒH0 . Then: (1) M Martin’s MaximumCC .c/; (2) M Strong Chang’s Conjecture; (3) Suppose is a sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2i; L.R/Pmax . Then hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2iM ; and that hH.!2 /; INS ; B; 2i (4) M :./. Proof. (1) follows by Theorem 10.89 and as we have indicated above, (2) is proved by the methods of Section 9.6. (3) is an immediate corollary of Theorem 10.87 since P .!1 /M D P .!1 /G : Similarly, by Theorem 10.88, .A(Code) .hSi W i < !i; zg ; B//M D ¹;º where hSi W i < !i D SAG . Therefore (4) follows by the equivalences to ./ given in Lemma 10.74. t u
784
10 Further results
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum Goldstern and Shelah introduced a bounded form of Martin’s Maximum. Definition 10.91 (Goldstern, Shelah). (1) Bounded Martin’s Maximum: Suppose that P is a partial order such that .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\ V:
Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of predense subsets of P , each with cardinality !1 , such that jDj !1 . Then there exists a filter F P such that F \ D ¤ ; for all D 2 D. (2) Bounded Martin’s MaximumC : Suppose that P is a partial order such that .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\ V:
Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of predense subsets of P , each with cardinality !1 , such that jDj !1 . Suppose that 2 V P is a term for a stationary subset of !1 . Then there exists a filter F P such that: a) for all D 2 D, F \ D ¤ ;; b) ¹˛ < !1 j for some p 2 F ; p ˛ 2 º is stationary in !1 . (3) Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC : Suppose that P is a partial order such that .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\ V:
Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of predense subsets of P , each with cardinality !1 , such that jDj !1 . Suppose that h W < !1 i is a sequence of terms for stationary subsets of !1 . Then there exists a filter F P such that: a) For all D 2 D, F \ D ¤ ;; b) For each < !1 , ¹˛ < !1 j for some p 2 F ; p ˛ 2 º is stationary in !1 .
t u
Remark 10.92. It follows from the results of this section and the preceding section that Bounded Martin’s Maximum does not imply Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC . This can easily be strengthened to show both: (1) Bounded Martin’s Maximum does not imply Bounded Martin’s MaximumC ; (2) Bounded Martin’s MaximumC does not imply Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC . t u The following lemmas of Bagaria give useful reformulations of Bounded Martin’s Maximum and of Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC .
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
785
Lemma 10.93 (Bagaria). The following are equivalent. (1) Bounded Martin’s Maximum. (2) Suppose that P is a partial order which is stationary set preserving. Then P
hH.!2 /; 2i †1 hH.!2 /; 2iV :
t u
Lemma 10.94 (Bagaria). The following are equivalent. (1) Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC . (2) Suppose that P is a partial order which is stationary set preserving. Then P
hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i †1 hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iV :
t u
The analysis of the consequences of Bounded Martin’s Maximum seems subtle. For example we shall see that Bounded Martin’s Maximum does not imply (even in the context of large cardinals) that INS is !2 -saturated, see Doebler and Schindler .2009/ and Claverie and Schindler .2010/ for more recent related results. Lemma 10.95 (Bounded Martin’s Maximum). Suppose that either: (i) There is a measurable cardinal, or (ii) INS is precipitous. Then: (1)
AC
holds.
(2) Every function, f W !1 ! !1 , is bounded on a club by a canonical function. Proof. We consider AC , the proofs for (2) are similar. To establish that AC holds in the context of Bounded Martin’s Maximum it suffices to show that for each pair .S0 ; T0 / of stationary, co-stationary subsets of !1 there exists an ordinal such that: (1.1) !1 < . (1.2) For each stationary set S !1 let ZS be the set of X 2 P!1 ./ such that a) X \ !1 2 S , b) X \ !1 2 S0 if and only if ordertype.X / 2 T0 . Then ZS is stationary in P!1 ./. To see this suffices let P be the partial order (conditions are initial segments) which generically creates a surjection W !1 !
786
10 Further results
and a closed, unbounded, set C !1 such that C \ T0 D C \ ¹˛ < !1 j Œ˛ 2 S0 º: Then by (1.2), P is stationary set preserving. Applying Bounded Martin’s Maximum to P yields the necessary witnesses for AC . If is measurable then it is straightforward to show that (1.2) holds. If the nonstationary ideal is precipitous let D jP .P .!1 //jC : We claim that (1.2) holds for . This follows by an absoluteness argument. Fix a stationary set S !1 and fix a function H W
AC
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
787
Corollary 10.96 (Bounded Martin’s Maximum). Suppose that either: (i) There is a measurable cardinal, or (ii) INS is precipitous. Then 2@0 D 2@1 D @2 .
t u
In the presence of large cardinals, Bounded Martin’s Maximum implies that ı12 D !2 . This is an immediate corollary of the results of Chapter 3. Lemma 10.97 (Bounded Martin’s Maximum). Assume there is a Woodin cardinal with a measurable above. Then ı 12 D !2 . Proof. Let ı be the least Woodin cardinal. By Shelah’s theorem, Theorem 2.64, there exists a semiproper partial order P of cardinality ı such that V P “INS is !2 -saturated”: Clearly V P “There is a measurable cardinal ”; and so by Theorem 3.17, V P “ı12 D !2 ”: The lemma follows by applying Bounded Martin’s Maximum to P .
t u
The axiom ./ implies a very strong form of Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC . This is the content of the next theorem, Theorem 10.99, which in essence is simply a reformulation of the fundamental absoluteness theorem, Theorem 4.64, for Pmax . Remark 10.98. The requirement on N , in Theorem 10.99, that for each partial order P 2 N, 1 N P “ 2 -Determinacy”; can be reformulated in terms of large cardinals. In fact, since R N , it is equivalent to the assertion that for each set a 2 N , with a Ord, .M1 .a//# 2 N where M1 .a/ is computed in V . M1 .a/ denotes the minimum (iterable) fine structure model of ZFC C “There is a Woodin cardinal” containing the ordinals and constructed relative to the set a. The formal definition involves the fine structure theory of Mitchell and Steel .1994/. t u Theorem 10.99 (Axiom ./). Suppose that for each partial order P , 1 V P “ 2 -Determinacy”:
788
10 Further results
Suppose that N is a transitive inner model such that (i) P .!1 / N , (ii) N ZFC, (iii) for each partial order P 2 N , 1 N P “ 2 -Determinacy”:
Then N “Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”. Proof. By Lemma 10.94, Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC is equivalent to the following: (1.1) Suppose that P is a partial order such that .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\VI
i. e. such that P is stationary set preserving. Then P
hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iV †1 hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iV : Thus it suffices to show that (1.1) holds in N . In fact this follows by an argument which is essentially identical to that used to prove Theorem 4.69. Fix a …1 formula .x0 / in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i and fix a set A !1 such that hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i ŒA: Clearly we may suppose that A … L.R/ and so by Theorem 4.60, A is L.R/generic for Pmax . Let GA Pmax be the L.R/-generic filter given by A. Thus by Theorem 4.67 there is a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 GA such that the following holds. (2.1) Suppose
j W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
is a countable iteration and let a D j.a/. Let N be any countable, transitive, model of ZFC such that:
a) .P .!1 //M N ;
b) !1N D !1M ; c) Q3 .S / N , for each S 2 N such that S !1N ; d) If S !1N , S 2 M and if S … I then S is a stationary set in N . Then
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iN Œa :
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
789
It follows that (2.1) is expressible as a …13 statement about t where t 2 R codes h.M; I /; ai. The theorem now follows by a simple absoluteness argument, noting that from the hypothesis that for every partial order P , 1 NP 2 -Determinacy; it follows that for every partial order P ,
N †1 N P I 4 1 i. e. that †4 statements with parameters from V are absolute between N and N P . Fix a set E Ord such that E 2 N and such that H. /N 2 LŒE where D .jP [ H.!2 /jCC /N . Suppose that G P is N -generic and assume toward a contradiction hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i .:/ŒA: Let g Coll.!; sup.E// be N ŒG-generic. Then E # together with the iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / which sends a to A, witness that (2.1) fails in N ŒGŒg which contradicts N †1 N ŒGŒg: 4
t u
Remark 10.100. One corollary of Theorem 10.99 is that the consistency of Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC is relatively weak even in conjunction with large cardinal axioms. For example if ZFC C “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals” is consistent then so is ZFC C “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals” C Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC : In contrast, ZFC C “There is a measurable cardinal” C Martin’s Maximum implies the consistency of ZFC C “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals” and much more. The latter is by results of Steel combined with results of Schimmerling. t u Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that
L.; R/ ADC C “ ‚ is regular”:
790
10 Further results 2P max
The basic analysis of L.R/
2P max
generalizes to L.; R/
. In particular,
Theorem 10.101. Suppose A R and that L.A; R/ ADC : Suppose G 2 Pmax is L.A; R/-generic. Then L.A; R/ŒG ZFC and in L.A; R/ŒG, (1) ./ holds, (2) INS is not !2 -saturated.
t u
The next lemma is an immediate corollary of the analysis of Pmax as summarized in Theorem 10.101. 2
Lemma 10.102. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R : Suppose that G 2 Pmax is L.; R/-generic. N L.; R/ŒG containing R [ ¹Gº such that
Then there is an inner model
(1) N ZFC C ./, (2) for all partial orders P 2 N , 1 N P “ 2 -Determinacy”; (3) N “INS is not !2 -saturated”. Proof. By Theorem 9.14 there exists a pointclass 0 such that L.0 ; R/ ADC C AD R : Therefore, and this is all we require, there exists A 2 such that (1.1) L.A; R/ ADC , (1.2) .‚0 /L.A;R/ < .‚/L.A;R/ . Let ı D .‚/L.A;R/ and let M D .HOD/L.A;R/ \ Vı : By Theorem 9.113, ı is a Woodin cardinal in .HOD/L.A;R/ and so M ZFC: It follows that for each partial order P 2 M , 1 M P “ 2 -Determinacy”; and further that M.R/ is a set (symmetric) extension of M . The latter is easily proved by a variation of Vopenka’s argument that every set of ordinals is set generic over HOD. Let N D M.R/ŒG: Thus N is a set generic extension of M . It follows that N is as required.
t u
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
791
By altering the choice of the inner model, N , in the proof of Lemma 10.102, one can also prove the following variation. Lemma 10.103. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R : Suppose that G 2 Pmax is L.; R/-generic. N L.; R/ŒG containing R [ ¹Gº such that
Then there is an inner model
(1) N ZFC C ./, (2) N “There exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals ”, (3) N “INS is not !2 -saturated”.
t u
As an immediate corollary of Theorem 10.99 and Lemma 10.103 it follows that Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC does not imply that INS is !2 -saturated. The basic method can be used to show that a number of consequences of Martin’s Maximum are not implied by Bounded Martin’s Maximum. Two interesting questions are: Assume Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC and that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. – Must INS be semi-saturated? – Must INS be precipitous? Corollary 10.104. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R . Suppose that G 2 Pmax is L.; R/-generic. Then there is an inner model N L.; R/ŒG containing R [ ¹Gº such that (1) N Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC , (2) N “There exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals ”, (3) N “INS is not !2 -saturated”. Proof. By the Martin–Steel Theorem, for all partial orders P 2 N , 1 N P “ 2 -Determinacy”: The corollary follows from this, Theorem 10.99 and Lemma 10.103.
t u
The closure on N , in Theorem 10.99(iii), cannot be significantly weakened, though it can be weakened slightly. We state two closely related theorems which illustrate this. We require a definition.
792
10 Further results
1 Definition 10.105. ZF 2 -Determinacy:
(1) For all x 2 R, x # exists. (2) Suppose 1 .x; y/ and 2 .x; y/ are †12 formulas and a 2 R are such that for all transitive models, M , of ZF, if a 2 M then ¹b 2 R \ M j M 1 Œa; bº D .R \ M / n ¹b 2 R \ M j M 2 Œa; bº: Then the set ¹b 2 R j 1 Œa; bº is determined.
t u
Remark 10.106. Of course, (2) of Definition 10.105 implies (1), and so an equivalent notion is obtained by eliminating (1) from the definition. t u Theorem 10.107. Suppose that for each partial order P , 1 V P “ 2 -Determinacy”: Then there exists a transitive inner model N containing the ordinals such that
(1) P .!1 / N , (2) N ZFC, 1 (3) for each partial order P 2 N ,N P “ ZF 2 -Determinacy”,
(4) N “Bounded Martin’s Maximum fails”. Proof. For each set a Ord let L# .a/ denote the minimum inner model M such that (1.1) M ZFC, (1.2) Ord M , (1.3) a 2 M , (1.4) for all b 2 M , b # 2 M . We prove that N “Bounded Martin’s Maximum fails” where, abusing notation slightly, N D L# .P .!1 //: The proof of the theorem is similar.
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
793
Let G0 Coll.!1 ; H.!2 // be N -generic. Thus there exists A !1 such that A 2 N ŒG0 and such that N ŒG0 D L# .A/: Let
A D ¹˛ < !1 j j˛jL
# .A\˛/
D !º:
The key point is that for each S 2 .P .!1 / n INS /N , A \ S … .INS /N ŒG0 : Let C0 A be N ŒG0 -generic for PA where PA is the partial order of countable subsets of A , which are closed in !1 , ordered by extension (Harrington forcing). Thus in N ŒG0 ŒC0 : (2.1) C0 !1 , and C0 is closed and unbounded. (2.2) For each ˛ 2 C0 , j˛jL
# .A\˛/
D !:
However, for each S 2 .P .!1 / n INS /N , A \ S … .INS /N ŒG0 ; and so .INS /N D N \ .INS /N ŒG0 ŒC0 : Assume toward a contradiction that N “Bounded Martin’s Maximum”: Therefore by Lemma 10.93, hH.!2 /; 2iN †1 hH.!2 /; 2iN ŒG0 ŒC0 : But this implies, by (2.1) and (2.2), that in N there exist AO !1 and CO !1 such that: (3.1) CO !1 , and CO is closed and unbounded. (3.2) For each ˛ 2 CO , j˛jL
# .A\˛/ O
D !:
O exists, which is a contradiction. But by the hypothesis of the lemma, .CO ; A/
t u
The second theorem, Theorem 10.108, is closely related Theorem 9.75 and Theorem 9.81, which show that closure properties of P .!1 / transfer upwards to closure properties of P .!2 /, assuming WRP.2/ .!2 /. Theorem 10.108. Suppose that 1 V Coll.!;!1 / “ 2 -Determinacy”:
794
10 Further results
Suppose that N is a transitive inner model such that (i) P .!1 / N , (ii) N ZFC, (iii) N “Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”. Then for each partial order P 2 N , 1 N P “ ZF 2 -Determinacy”:
Proof. We prove that for each set a Ord, if a 2 N then a# 2 N ; i. e. that for each partial order P 2 N , 1 NP “ … 1 -Determinacy”: The proof of the theorem is similar. Fix a Ord with a 2 N . Assume toward a contradiction that a# … N: Let D sup.a/ and suppose that G0 Coll.!1 ; / be N -generic. Thus there exists A !1 such that A 2 N ŒG0 and such that A# … N ŒG0 . Therefore there exists b0 2 H.!1 / such that in N ŒG0 , ¹˛ < !1 j b0 2 .A \ ˛/# º is stationary and co-stationary in !1 . However .INS /N D .INS /N ŒG0 \ N and so by Lemma 10.94, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iN †1 hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iN ŒG0 since N “Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”. Therefore there exists AO !1 such that AO 2 N and such that ¹˛ < !1 j b0 2 .A \ ˛/# º is stationary and co-stationary in !1 . But by the hypothesis of the lemma, AO# exists and so the set ¹˛ < !1 j b0 2 .A \ ˛/# º cannot be both stationary and co-stationary. This is a contradiction.
t u
Theorem 10.99 can be improved to provide a characterization of ./. First we .;;B/ note the following corollary of the analysis of Pmax which rules out one possible characterization.
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
795
Theorem 10.109. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: .;;B/ Let B R be a set in L.R/. Suppose that G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic and let L.;R/ M D ¹a 2 .HOD/ ŒRŒG0 j j rank.a/ < ‚º where ‚ D .‚/L.;R/ . Then:
(1) For each partial order P 2 M ,
M P ADL.R/ :
(2) M :./. (3) Suppose that N M is a transitive inner model such that a) P .!1 /M N , b) N ZFC, 1 c) For each partial order P 2 N , N P “ 2 -Determinacy”. Then N “Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”.
t u
Definition 10.110 (Feng–Magidor–Woodin). Suppose that A R. Then A is universally Baire if for any compact Hausdorff space X and any continuous function, W X ! R; the set ¹a 2 X j .a/ 2 Aº has the property of Baire in X . t u The next theorem gives a useful characterization of the sets A R which are universally Baire. Theorem 10.111 (Feng–Magidor–Woodin). Suppose A R. equivalent.
The following are
(1) A is universally Baire. (2) Suppose that P is an infinite partial order and let ı D 2jP j : Then there exist trees S; T on ! ı such that A D pŒT and such that if G P is V -generic then in V ŒG, pŒT V ŒG D RV ŒG n pŒS V ŒG : u t Thus if A R is universally Baire and P is a partial order, then A has an unambiguous interpretation in V P . If G P is V -generic then we let AG denote the interpretation of A in V ŒG. It is easily verified that AG D [¹pŒT V ŒG j T 2 V and A D pŒT V º: In the presence of suitable large cardinals, the universally Baire sets are exactly the sets which are 1 -homogeneously Suslin. This is a corollary of Theorem 2.32, Theorem 10.111, and the principal theorem of .Martin and Steel 1989/.
796
10 Further results
Theorem 10.112. Suppose there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that A R. Then following are equivalent. (1) A is universally Baire. (2) A is 1 -weakly homogeneously Suslin. (3) A is 1 -homogeneously Suslin.
t u
The following lemma is an immediate corollary of the definition of a universally Baire set. Lemma 10.113. Let P .R/ be the set of universally Baire sets. Then is a -algebra closed under continuous preimages. u t 1 †12 -sets is answered by Clearly every † 1 -set is universally Baire. The situation for the following theorem of .Feng, Magidor, and Woodin 1992/.
Theorem 10.114 (Feng–Magidor–Woodin). The following are equivalent. (1) For every set X , X # exists. 1 (2) Every † 2 -set is universally Baire.
t u
Corollary 10.115. Suppose A R. Then the following are equivalent. (1) .A; R/# exists and .A; R/# is universally Baire. (2) Each set B 2 L.A; R/ \ P .R/ is universally Baire. Proof. Every set B 2 L.A; R/\P .R/ is a continuous preimage of .A; R/# . Therefore (1) implies (2). Suppose that (2) holds. By Theorem 10.114, .A; R/# exists. Note that .A; R/# is naturally a countable union of sets in L.A; R/ and so by Lemma 10.113, .A; R/# is universally Baire. t u It is open whether the assumption that every projective set in universally Baire implies generic absoluteness for projective statements. The following theorem gives a sufficient condition which is implied in many cases by an appropriate determinacy hypothesis. Theorem 10.116. Suppose that A R and that for each set B R R, if B is definable in the structure hH.!1 /; A; 2i then there exists a choice function f WR!R such that
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
797
(i) for all x 2 R if .x; y/ 2 B for some y 2 R then .x; f .x// 2 B, (ii) f 1 ŒO is universally Baire for each open set O. Suppose that P is a partial order and that G P is V -generic. Then hH.!1 /; A; 2iV hH.!1 /; AG ; 2iV ŒG :
t u
Lemma 10.117 (Feng–Magidor–Woodin). Suppose that for each partial order P , V P ADL.R/ : Then R# is universally Baire.
t u
There are two approximate converses to Lemma 10.117. Theorem 10.118. Assume L.R/ AD and that R# is universally Baire. Then for each partial order P , V P ADL.R/ :
t u
Theorem 10.119. The following are equivalent. (1) For each partial order P , V P ADL.R/ : (2) R# is universally Baire and for each partial order P , if G P is V -generic then .R# /G D .R# /V ŒG :
t u
Remark 10.120. (1) Theorem 10.119 is proved using basic method for proving Theorem 5.104; i. e. the proof uses core model methods. We note that the theorem is false at the projective level. (2) It is open whether the actual converse to Theorem 10.117 holds. We shall need the generalization of Lemma 10.117 to L.R# /. Lemma 10.121. Suppose that for each partial order P , V P ADL.R / : #
Then .R# /# is universally Baire.
t u
798
10 Further results
Definition 10.122. A-Bounded Martin’s Maximum: (1) A R is universally Baire. (2) Suppose that P is a partial order such that .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\ V:
Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of predense subsets of P , each with cardinality !1 , such that jDj !1 . Suppose that h W < !1 i is a sequence of terms for elements of AG . Then there exists a filter F P such that: a) For all D 2 D, F \ D ¤ ;; b) For each < !1 , ¹.i; j / 2 ! ! j for some p 2 F ; p .i; j / 2 º 2 A:
t u
Definition 10.123. A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC : (1) A R is universally Baire. (2) Suppose that P is a partial order such that .INS /V D .INS /V
P
\ V:
Suppose that D P .P / is a collection of predense subsets of P , each with cardinality !1 , such that jDj !1 . Suppose that h W < !1 i is a sequence of terms for stationary subsets of !1 and that h W < !1 i is a sequence of terms for elements of AG . Then there exists a filter F P such that: a) For all D 2 D, F \ D ¤ ;; b) For each < !1 , ¹.i; j / 2 ! ! j for some p 2 F ; p .i; j / 2 º 2 AI c) For each < !1 , ¹˛ < !1 j for some p 2 F ; p ˛ 2 º is stationary in !1 .
t u
As an immediate corollary of Theorem 10.111 we obtain the following. Theorem 10.124. (1) (Martin’s Maximum) Suppose that A R is universally Baire. Then A-Bounded Martin’s Maximum holds. (2) (Martin’s MaximumCC ) Suppose that A R is universally Baire. Then t u A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC holds.
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
799
Theorem 10.127 provides an equivalence to ./ in terms of a strong form of Bounded Martin’s Maximum. We shall prove several versions. Suppose that A R. We denote by †1! .A/ the pointclass of all sets B R such that B is definable in the structure hV!C1 ; A; 2i from real parameters; these are the sets B R which are projective in A. The final theorem we shall need for the proof of Theorem 10.127 is the following. Theorem 10.125. Assume R# exists and that every set which is †1! .R# / is determined. Suppose that A0 R, A0 2 L.R/ and that A0 is definable in L.R/ from x0 and indiscernibles of L.R/. Suppose that M0 is a countable transitive model of ZFC such that: (i) Suppose that g Coll.!; H.!2 /M0 / is an M0 -generic filter with g 2 H.!1 /. Then R# \ M0 Œg D .R# /M0 Œg and hM0 Œg \ V!C1 ; R# \ M0 Œg \ V!C1 ; 2i hV!C1 ; R# ; 2i. (ii) x0 2 M0 . Then there exists .M1 ; I1 ; ı/ 2 H.!1 / such that (1) M1 is transitive and M1 ZFC C “ı is a Woodin cardinal”, (2) I1 D .I<ı /M1 and .M1 ; I1 / is A0 -iterable, (3) H.!2 /M1 D H.!2 /M0 .
t u
The following is an immediate corollary of Theorem 10.12. Theorem 10.126. Assume there is a proper class of measurable cardinals which are limits of Woodin cardinals. Then there exists a transitive inner model containing the ordinals such that (1) P .!1 / N , (2) N ZFC C MIH, WH N WH / 1 . (3) .1
t u
As a corollary of Theorem 10.126 we obtain the following characterization of ./.
800
10 Further results
Theorem 10.127. Assume there is a proper class of measurable cardinals which are limits of Woodin cardinals. Then the following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) Suppose that N is a transitive set such that a) P .!1 / N , b) N ZFC, c) N “Every set which is †1! .R# / is universally Baire”. Then for each set A 2 L.R/ \ P .R/, N “A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”: Proof. We first prove that (2) follows from ./. The proof is a generalization of the proof of Theorem 10.99. Fix A R with A 2 L.R/ and suppose that N is a transitive set such that (1.1) P .!1 / N , (1.2) N ZFC, 1 # (1.3) N “Every set which is † ! .R / is universally Baire”.
We note that
N A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC
if and only if for each partial order P 2 N , if G P is N -generic with .INS /N D .INS /N ŒG \ N then hH.!2 /; INS ; A; 2iN †1 hH.!2 /; INS ; AG ; 2iN ŒG : Fix a …1 formula .x0 / in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; A; INS ; 2i and fix a set B !1 such that hH.!2 /; A; INS ; 2i ŒB: Clearly we may suppose that B … L.R/ and so by Theorem 4.60, B is L.R/generic for Pmax . Let GB Pmax be the L.R/-generic filter given by B. Thus there is a condition h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i 2 GB such that the following holds. (2.1) .M0 ; I0 / is A-iterable. (2.2) A \ M0 2 M0 and hV!C1 \ M0 ; A \ M0 ; 2i hV!C1 ; A; 2i:
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
801
(2.3) Suppose that h.M1 ; I1 /; a1 i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i, .M1 ; I1 / is A-iterable, and that A \ M1 2 M1 . Let j W .M0 ; I0 / ! .M0 ; I0 / be the iteration such that a1 D j.a0 /. Then hH.!2 /; A \ M1 ; I1 ; 2iM1 Œa1 : Now suppose P 2 N is a partial order and that G0 P is N -generic with .INS /N D .INS /N ŒG0 \ N: Let be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal of N such that P 2 N : Let G1 Coll.!; / be N ŒG0 -generic. We work in N ŒG0 ŒG1 D N ŒG. The key point is that since R# is universally Baire in N and since L.R/ AD; it follows, by Theorem 10.118 and by Theorem 10.119, that .R# /N ŒG D .ZG /N ŒG where Z D .R# /N , and so hH.!1 /; A; 2i hH.!1 /; AG ; 2iN ŒG where AG is the interpretation of A in N ŒG; AG D [¹pŒT j T 2 N and A D pŒT \ N º: Thus if N ŒH is a set generic extension of N with H 2 N ŒG, then in N ŒG, .R# /N ŒH D .R# /N ŒG \ N ŒH : We can now apply Theorem 10.125, to obtain in N ŒG a structure .M1 ; I1 ; ı/ 2 H.!1 /N ŒG such that (3.1) M1 is transitive, (3.2) M1 ZFC C “ı is a Woodin cardinal”, (3.3) I1 D .I<ı /M1 , (3.4) .M1 ; I1 / is AG -iterable, (3.5) H.!2 /M1 D H.!2 /N . N ŒG By Lemma 4.40, there exists a condition h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that
(4.1) M1 2 .H.!1 //M , (4.2) AG \ M 2 M, (4.3) .M; I / is AG -iterable.
802
10 Further results
Thus there exists an iteration j W .M1 ; I1 / ! .M1 ; I1 / such that (5.1) j 2 M,
(5.2) I \ M1 D .INS /M1 . However (6.1) hM; I; AG \ M; 2i :Œj.B/, (6.2) h.M; I /; j.B/i 2 .Pmax /N ŒG , (6.3) h.M; I /; j.B/i < h.M0 ; I0 /; a0 i. Thus (2.3) fails in N ŒG for AG . However hH.!1 /; A; 2iN hH.!1 /; AG ; 2iN ŒG which is a contradiction. We finish by proving that (2) implies ./. This implication is an immediate corollary of Theorem 10.126 and Theorem 10.14. By Theorem 10.126 there exists a transitive inner model containing the ordinals such that (7.1) P .!1 / N , (7.2) N ZFC C MIH, WH N WH (7.3) .1 / 1 .
By Theorem 10.14, there exists a partial order P 2 N such that if G P is N -generic then (8.1) .INS /N D .INS /N ŒG \ N , (8.2) N ŒG ./. We work in N ŒG. For each A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/, N “A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”: Thus (9.1) for each A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/, hH.!2 /; INS ; A; 2iN †1 hH.!2 /; INS ; AG ; 2iN ŒG : Fix a set X !1 with X 2 N n L.R/. Let FX Pmax be the set of conditions h.M; I /; ai 2 Pmax such that there exists an iteration j W .M; I / ! .M ; I / such that
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
803
(10.1) j.a/ D X , (10.2) I D INS \ M . By (9.1), X … LŒt for each t 2 RN ŒG and so since N ŒG ./; it follows by Theorem 4.60, that the set X is L.R/N ŒG -generic for .Pmax /N ŒG . Let GX .Pmax /N ŒG be the L.RN ŒG /-generic filter given by X . By (9.1), FX D GX \ N: Suppose that D Pmax is dense with D 2 L.RN /. Let A be the set of t 2 RN such N ŒG that t codes an element of D. Let DG be the set of p 2 Pmax such that there exists # t 2 AG which codes p. Since R is universally Baire in N it follows that .R# /N ŒG D ..R# /G /N ŒG : N ŒG and further, by (9.1), that Thus it follows that DG is dense in Pmax
hH.!2 /; INS ; D; 2iN †1 hH.!2 /; INS ; DG ; 2iN ŒG : Thus FX \ D ¤ ; and so X is L.RN /-generic for .Pmax /N ; i. e. X is L.R/-generic for Pmax . Therefore every set X 2 P .!1 / n L.R/ is L.R/-generic for Pmax . But, as in the proof of Theorem 4.76, this implies ./. t u With slightly more efficient definitions one can improve Theorem 10.127 to the following. Theorem 10.128. Suppose that for each partial order P , V P ADL.R / : #
Then the following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) Suppose that N is a transitive set such that a) P .!1 / N , b) N ZFC, c) N “Every set which is †1! .R# / is universally Baire”. Then for each set A 2 L.R/ \ P .R/, N “A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”: With more work one can further refine the requirements on N .
t u
804
10 Further results
Theorem 10.129. Suppose that for each partial order P , V P ADL.R / : #
Then the following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) Suppose that N is a transitive set and ı 2 Ord \ N are such that a) P .!1 / N , b) N ZFC, c) N “R# is universally Baire”, d) N “ı is a Woodin cardinal”. Then for each set A 2 L.R/ \ P .R/, Nı “A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”:
t u
The requirement on N in Theorem 10.129 can be reformulated in terms of a closure condition which generalizes the closure condition indicated in Remark 10.98. These conditions are each natural generalizations of the requirement that N be closed under sharps (for arbitrary sets), to the realm of Woodin cardinals. Definition 10.130 (Steel). (For every set X , X # exists) For each set a Ord, M! .a/ is the “minimum” Mitchell–Steel fine structure model such that (1) Ord M! .a/, (2) a 2 M! .a/, (3) each extender on the sequence of M! .a/ has critical point above [a, (4) M! .a/ is (transfinitely) iterable.
t u
Theorem 10.131. The following are equivalent. (1) For every partial order P , V P ADL.R/ . (2) For every set a Ord, M! .a/ exists. t u
(3) M! .;/ exists.
The set .M! .a//# , if it exists, is a generalization of 0# , 0 etc. If a !, it is naturally a subset of ! which up to Turing degree is simply the theory of the structure hL.R/; a; k ; 2 W k < !i k th
Silver indiscernible of L.R/. where k is the We caution that, for a !, it is possible for .M! .a//# to exist in V and for there to exist an inner model N containing the ordinals such that
10.3 Bounded forms of Martin’s Maximum
805
N ZFC C “.M! .a//# exists”. .M! .a//# 2 N , .M! .a//# ¤ ..M! .a//# /N . However if, more generally, a Ord and if H.!2 / N; then necessarily .M! .a//# D ..M! .a//# /N . Theorem 10.132. Suppose that for each partial order P , V P ADL.R/ : Suppose that N is a transitive set such that P .!1 / N and N ZFC. Then the following are equivalent. (1) For each set a Ord, if a 2 N then .M! .a//# 2 N . (2) N “R# is universally Baire”.
t u
Thus Theorem 10.129 can be reformulated as follows. Theorem 10.133. Suppose that there exist a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Then the following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) Suppose that N is a transitive set and ı 2 Ord \ N are such that a) P .!1 / N and N ZFC, b) for each set a Ord, if a 2 N then .M! .a//# 2 N , c) N “ı is a Woodin cardinal”. Then for each set A 2 L.R/ \ P .R/, Nı “A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”:
t u
We briefly discuss a slight refinement of Theorem 10.133 which is very likely nearly optimal. The issue is the precise closure necessary on N . Definition 10.134. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that a Ord. Then Q1! .a/ is the set of all b [a such that b 2 N for each transitive inner model N containing the ordinals, such that for some ı 2 Ord, (1) a 2 Nı and N ZFC, (2) for each z Ord, if z 2 N then M! .z/# 2 N , (3) ı is a Woodin cardinal in N , (4) N is a Mitchell–Steel model relative to a which is (transfinitely) iterable. The following theorem shows that for large sets a Ord, a manner analogous to Q3 .a/.
Q1! .a/
t u
can be defined in
806
10 Further results
Theorem 10.135. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that a Ord and that R LŒa: Suppose that b [a. Then the following are equivalent. (1) b 2 Q1! .a/. (2) b 2 N for each transitive inner model of ZFC such that for some ı 2 Ord; a) a 2 Nı , b) for each z Ord, if z 2 N then M! .z/# 2 N , c) ı is a Woodin cardinal in N .
t u
Corollary 10.136. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that N is a transitive inner model of ZFC with P .!1 / [ Ord N: Suppose that ı is a Woodin cardinal in N and that N “R# is universally Baire”: Then for each a 2 Nı \ P .ı/,
Q1! .a/ N:
t u
Theorem 10.137 gives our final characterization of ./. It is quite likely that the closure requirements on N cannot be significantly weakened, more precisely that the requirement: for each set a Ord, if a 2 N then .M! .a//# 2 N , does not suffice. Theorem 10.137. Suppose that there exist a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Then the following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) Suppose that N is a transitive set such that a) P .!1 / N , b) N ZFC, c) for each set a Ord, if a 2 N then Q1! .a/ N . Then for each set A 2 L.R/ \ P .R/, N “A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”:
t u
.;;B/ The following corollary of the analysis of Pmax shows that the equivalences given in Theorem 10.128 and Theorem 10.133 are essentially the best possible.
10.4 -logic
807
Theorem 10.138. Suppose P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ AD R C “ ‚ is regular”: .;;B/ Suppose that B R is a set in L.R/. Suppose that G0 Pmax is L.; R/-generic and let M D ¹a 2 .HOD/L.;R/ ŒRŒG0 j rank.a/ < ‚º
where ‚ D .‚/L.;R/ . Then: (1) For each partial order P 2 M , M P ADL.R / : #
(2) M “There exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals ”. (3) M :./. (4) Suppose that N M is a transitive inner model such that a) P .!1 /M N , b) N ZFC, c) N “Every set which is †1! .R# / is universally Baire”. Then N “B-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC ”.
t u
10.4 -logic The absoluteness theorems associated to Pmax and its variations can more naturally be formulated using -logic – this strengthening of !-logic was introduced in the first edition of this book. The presentation given in this edition reflects a number of expository changes, specifically what was -logic in that edition, is now the logical relation for -logic, T and it is with this definition that we begin. An equivalent definition based on the generic-multiverse generated by V is given in .Woodin 2009/. Definition 10.139. Suppose that: (i) There exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. (ii) T is a theory containing ZFC. (iii) is a sentence. Then T if for all partial orders P and for all ˛ 2 Ord, if V˛P T then t u V˛P .
808
10 Further results
Using the generic elementary embeddings associated to the stationary tower one can prove the following absoluteness theorem. This requires using the full stationary tower, P<ı , rather than the restricted tower, Q<ı , which we have used almost exclusively up to this point. Theorem 10.140. Suppose that there exist a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that T is a theory containing ZFC and is a sentence. Then T if and only if for each partial order P , V P “T ”. The previous theorem strongly suggests that the validities of ZFC in -logic which are …2 -sentences somehow capture the extent of the influence of large cardinals. This intuition leads to the definition of the proof relation for -logic and to the Conjecture. A central aspect of this definition of the proof relation for -logic involves the notion of an A-closed model where A R is universally Baire. Recall that if A R is universally Baire then A has a canonical interpretation, AG , in any set generic extension, V ŒG, of V ; AG D [¹pŒT j T 2 V and A D pŒT V º: The definition we shall give of when a transitive set M is A-closed involves AG . However this can be defined without reference to AG . For example if M ZFC then there is a very natural reformulation using the Stone spaces, XP , defined in V from partial orders P 2 M . Definition 10.141. Suppose that A R and that A is universally Baire. A transitive set M is A-closed if for each partial order P 2 M; P
and for each term 2 M , ¹p 2 P j p V 2 AG º 2 M:
t u
Suppose that M is a countable transitive set such that M ZFC: 1
Suppose that S 2 M is an -borel code. Then, since M is countable, S is a code in V for a borel set A. By absoluteness, M is A-closed. This is the essence of the definability of forcing. Remark 10.142. A-closure can easily be defined for any ! model .M; E/. Note that if .M; E/ ZFC then .M; E/ is wellfounded if and only if .M; E/ is A-closed for each …11 set A.
t u
10.4 -logic
809
We have defined in Definition 4.66, Q3 .a/ for each set a 2 H.!1 /. A similar definition applies to define Q3 .a/ for an arbitrary set a provided for example that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals (much less is required): Let b be the transitive closure of a. Then Q3 .a/ is the set of all Y b such that the following hold. (1) There exists a transitive inner model M of ZFC such that: a) Ord M; b) a 2 M; c) for some ı; a 2 Vı , ı 2 M and ı is a Woodin cardinal in M; d) Y 2 M. (2) Suppose that M is a transitive inner model of ZFC such that: a) Ord M; b) a 2 M; c) for some ı; a 2 Vı , ı 2 M and ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. Then Y 2 M. Remark 10.143. Suppose there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that M is a transitive set such that, M ZFC. Then the following are equivalent: (1) M is A-closed for each †13 set A. (2) For each set a Ord if a 2 M then Q3 .a/ M .
t u
Remark 10.144. Suppose there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that M is a transitive set such that, M ZFC. Then the following are equivalent: (1) M is R# -closed. (2) For each set a Ord if a 2 M then M! .a/# 2 M .
t u
A reformulation of A-closure is given in the following lemma, which we leave as an easy exercise. Lemma 10.145. Suppose that A R is universally Baire and that M is a transitive set such that M ZFC. Then the following are equivalent. (1) M is A-closed. (2) Suppose P 2 M is a partial order and that G P is V -generic. Then in V ŒG; AG \ M ŒG 2 M ŒG:
t u
We shall define T ` only for the language of set theory and for theories T containing the axioms of ZFC. More general definitions are naturally possible.
810
10 Further results
Definition 10.146. Suppose that: (i) There exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. (ii) T is a theory containing ZFC. (iii) is a sentence. Then T ` if there exists a universally Baire set A R such that if M is any countable transitive set satisfying (1) M ZFC, (2) M is A-closed, (3) M T , then M .
t u
We note that the proof relation for -logic can be defined without reference to the universally Baire sets, referring instead to iterable structures. In this approach, A closure, for the relevant universally Baire sets, is reformulated in terms of closure under the (unique) iteration strategies of canonical countable structures. Remark 10.147. One very natural generalization of -logic would allow additional unary predicates to be interpreted by designated universally Baire sets. This in fact will be implicit in some of what follows; cf. Theorem 10.169. t u One application of the basic descriptive set theory of ADC is the following important absoluteness theorem, the relevant theorem of ADC is Theorem 9.7. Theorem 10.148. Suppose that there exist a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that T is a theory containing ZFC and is a sentence. Then T ` if and only if for each partial order P , V P “T ` ”.
t u
The following soundness theorem is easily proved from the definitions using either the generic elementary embeddings associated with the stationary tower, I<ı , where ı is a Woodin cardinal, or by using the closure properties of the pointclass of all universally Baire sets. Theorem 10.149. Suppose that there exist a proper class of Woodin cardinals, is a sentence, and ZFC ` : Then ZFC . The Conjecture is the conjecture that the converse of Theorem 10.149 holds, in effect this is simply the conjecture that the Completeness Theorem holds.
10.4 -logic
811
Definition 10.150 (The Conjecture). Suppose that there is a proper class of Woodin t u cardinals. Then for all sentences , ZFC ` if and only if ZFC . The following theorem shows that the Conjecture is a consequence of iteration hypotheses. Theorem 10.151 (WHIH). Suppose that T is a theory containing ZFC and that is a sentence. Then the following are equivalent: (1) T ` . t u
(2) T .
As we have indicated, many of the theorems relating to Pmax and its variations are more naturally presented in the context of -logic. For example the general existence can be strengthened as follows. theorem, Theorem 5.49, for conditions in Pmax Theorem 10.152. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that A R is universally Baire. Suppose that is a †2 sentence such that ZFC C is -consistent. Then there is a condition .hMk W k < !i; a/ 2 Pmax such that M0 ZFC C ; and such that (1) A \ M0 2 M0 , (2) hH.!1 /M0 ; A \ M0 i hH.!1 /; Ai, (3) hMk W k < !i is A-iterable, and further the set of such conditions is dense in Pmax .
t u
Similarly, we can reformulate the absoluteness theorem for Pmax . Theorem 10.153. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; 2; INS i and that ZFC C “hH.!2 /; 2; INS i ” is -consistent. Then
Pmax
hH.!2 /; 2; INS iL.R/
:
t u
In fact by Theorem 4.76, one has the following equivalence for ./. This reformulation does not involve forcing at all. Of course the definition of -logic that we have given does implicitly involve forcing. However, as we have noted, there is another definition of -logic in terms of iterable structures which does not involve forcing either. Further this equivalence for ./ still holds if one weakens -logic by restricting the collection of “test” models to just R# -closed models. As noted in Remark 10.144, R# -closure has a reformulation purely in fine structural terms.
812
10 Further results
Theorem 10.154. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Then the following are equivalent. (1) ./. (2) For each …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/i; if ZFC C “hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/i ” is -consistent, then hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 P .R/ \ L.R/i :
t u
The discussion of Section 10.1 can also naturally be recast in terms of -logic, for example we note the following reformulation of Theorem 10.17. Theorem 10.155. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ZF C DC C ADR and such that every set in is universally Baire. There exists a countable set a0 !1 such that L.;R/ Œa 0 a0 !1HOD and such that the following holds where M D HODL.;R/ Œa0 : Suppose that is a †2 -sentence such that ZFC C is -consistent. Then there exists a countable set a !1 such that (1) .INS /M D M \ .INS /M Œa , (2) M Œa .
t u
The absoluteness results associated to large cardinal axioms can be reformulated as follows, the key, of course, are the scale theorems of Moschovakis. Theorem 10.156. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Then for each sentence , either (1) ZFC ` “H.!1 / ”, or (2) ZFC ` “H.!1 / :”.
t u
With the analogous results for the universally Baire sets this theorem can easily be generalized to yield the following.
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis
813
Theorem 10.157. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that A R is universally Baire. Then for each sentence , either (1) ZFC ` “L.A; R/ ”, or (2) ZFC ` “L.A; R/ :”.
t u
Thus a natural question arises. To what extent can Theorem 10.156 be generalized to H.!2 /? The limitations imposed by forcing require the some axiom be added to ZFC. Can there exist a sentence ‰ such that for all either – ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or – ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”; and such that ZFC C ‰ is -consistent? Of course, by the results of this book, the answer is yes, the axiom ./ is one example. In fact each (homogeneous) Pmax -variation yields an axiom which also works. Can this happen for H.!3 /? This is an interesting variation of the question, Assume ADL.R/ . Must .‚/L.R/ !3 ? More precisely, Can there exist a sentence ‰ such that for all either – ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!3 / ”, or – ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!3 / :”; and such that ZFC C ‰ is -consistent?
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis There is at least one analog of Pmax for CH. Under suitable assumptions it is simply the partial order Coll.!1 ; R/: We shall make this claim more precise, but first we consider the problem of mutual compatibility for †2 sentences in the structure, hH.!2 /; 2i: This is closely related to mulated as follows.
†21
absoluteness which in the context of WHIH can be refor-
814
10 Further results
Theorem 10.158 (WHIH). Suppose there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals. Then for each †1 sentence , either (1) ZFC C CH ` “hH.!2 /; ¹Rº; 2i ”, or (2) ZFC C CH ` “hH.!2 /; ¹Rº; 2i :”.
t u
We state two theorems though they are not really optimal. The first involves the stationary tower and it is a corollary of a strengthened version of the †21 absoluteness theorem of .Woodin 1985/, which deals with integer games of length !1 . The second theorem involves weakly homogeneous iteration schemes and the conclusion is stronger. Theorem 10.159. Suppose that there is a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals. Then there is a set A !1 such that hH.!2 /; 2iLŒA where is any †2 sentence such that ZFC C “hH.!2 /; 2i ” t u
is -satisfiable. Theorem 10.160. Suppose that there exits a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose M is a countable transitive model of ZFC and hE˛ W ˛ < ıi 2 M is a weakly coherent Doddage in M such that; (i) ı is a Woodin cardinal in M , (ii) hE˛ W ˛ < ıi Mı , (iii) hE˛ W ˛ < ıi witnesses that ı is a Woodin cardinal in M ,
(iv) there exists 2 M such that ı < and such that is a measurable Woodin cardinal in M . Q has an iteration scheme in V which is Suppose .M; E/ Suslin. Then there is a set A 2 .P .!1 //M
1
-weakly homogeneously
such that hH.!2 /; 2iLŒA where is any †2 sentence such that ZFC C “hH.!2 /; 2i ” is -consistent.
t u
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis
815
These theorems shows that under fairly general circumstances there cannot be (nontrivial) consistent †2 sentences for hH.!2 /; 2i which are mutually inconsistent. The correct version of these theorems is given in the following conjecture: Conjecture: Suppose there exists a measurable Woodin cardinal and CH holds. Then there exists A !1 such that for all B !1 , if A 2 LŒB then Th.LŒA/ D Th.LŒB/:
t u
This conjecture is a corollary of a slightly more general conjecture which asserts that if there exists a measurable Woodin cardinal then a wide class of integer games of length !1 are determined. A brief discussion of this is given in Section 10.6 where the axiom ./C is introduced, see Remark 10.195 and Theorem 10.196. Remark 10.161. By Theorem 5.73(5), if ./ holds then the conclusion of the conjecture must fail; if ./ holds then for all A !1 there exist B0 !1 and B1 !1 such that (1) A 2 LŒB0 and A 2 LŒB1 , (2) there exists x 2 R \ LŒB0 such that x # … LŒB0 , (3) for all x 2 R \ LŒB1 , x # 2 LŒB1 . Thus the assumption of CH in the statement of the conjecture is important.
t u
Theorem 10.166 supports our claim that the partial order Coll.!1 ; R/ is an analog of Pmax for CH. The theorem requires the notion of weakly A-good iteration schemes. Definition 10.162. Suppose that Q ı/ 2 H.!1 / .M; E; and that (1) M ZFC, (2) EQ 2 M is a weakly coherent Doddage (in M) witnessing ı is a Woodin cardinal in M. Suppose that A is universally Baire and that M is A-closed. Q ı/ is weakly A-good if every iterate of M conAn iteration scheme, I , for .M; E; structed according to I , is A-closed. t u
816
10 Further results
Remark 10.163. Implicit in Definition 10.162 is the definition of an A-good iteration scheme. One requires in addition that if j W M ! M is an elementary embedding obtained from the iteration strategy, then j is elementary with respect to the predicates witnessing A-closure of M and M . In many (but not all) cases this in fact must be the case. t u Definition 10.164. Weakly Homogeneous Iteration HypothesisC (WHIHC ): (1) There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. (2) Suppose A is universally Baire. There exist a Woodin cardinal ı and a weakly coherent Doddage hE˛ W ˛ < ıi which witnesses ı is a Woodin cardinal such that if > ı and is inaccessible then there exists a countable elementary substructure X V Q Aº such that hM; EQM i has a weakly A-good iteration scheme containing ¹ı; E; 1 which is -homogeneously Suslin. Here M is the transitive collapse of X and t u EQM is the image of EQ under the collapsing map. The following theorem shows that in many cases, WHIH implies WHIHC . Recall that if there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals then a set A R is universally Baire if and only if it is 1 -homogeneously Suslin. Theorem 10.165. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that Q ı/ 2 H.!1 / .M; E; and that (i) M ZFC, (ii) EQ 2 M is a weakly coherent Doddage (in M) witnessing ı is a Woodin cardinal in M, (iii) there exist 2 Ord and X V such that M is the transitive collapse of X . Q ı/ which is universally Baire. Suppose that I is an iteration scheme for .M; E; Suppose that A R is universally Baire and that B R is 21 -definable in L.A; R/ with parameters from M. Then the iteration scheme, I , is weakly B-good. t u Having made the requisite definitions we can now state the first theorem regarding Coll.!1 ; R/ as an analog of Pmax in the context of CH.
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis
817
Theorem 10.166. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Let be the set of A R such that A is universally Baire. Suppose that 0 is a pointclass such that: (i) L.0 ; R/ \ P .R/ D 0 . (ii) For each A 2 0 there exists
Q ı/ 2 H.!1 / .M; E;
such that a) M ZFC, b) EQ 2 M is a weakly coherent Doddage (in M) witnessing ı is a Woodin cardinal in M, c) in M there is a measurable Woodin cardinal above ı, d) M is A-closed, Q has an iteration scheme in M which is weakly A-good. e) .M; E/ 0 Suppose that is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 0 i and that Coll.!1 ;R/ ” ZFC C “hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 0 iV is -consistent. Suppose that G Coll.!1 ; R/ is V -generic. Then hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 0 iL.0 ;R/ŒG :
t u
Remark 10.167.
(1) In Theorem 10.166, if in addition one requires L.0 ; R/ ADR C “‚ is regular”; then L.0 ; R/ŒG !1 -DC, and so one can further force over L.0 ; R/ŒG to obtain ZFC without adding new subsets of !1 .
(2) It seems quite likely that if there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals then the pointclass of the universally Baire sets necessarily satisfies the requirement (ii) of Theorem 10.166. t u We note the following theorem. Theorem 10.168. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and Q ı/ 2 H.!1 / such that that A R is universally Baire. Then there exists .M; E; (1) M ZFC and M is A-closed, (2) EQ 2 M is a weakly coherent Doddage (in M) witnessing ı is a Woodin cardinal in M, Q has a weakly A-good iteration scheme in M where P .R/ is the (3) .M; E/ pointclass of all universally Baire sets. u t
818
10 Further results
Another, though weaker, version of Theorem 10.166 is: Theorem 10.169. Suppose that there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals and that for each partial order P , V P WHIHC : Let be the set of A R such that A is universally Baire and suppose that L.; R/ \ P .R/ D : Suppose that is a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 i and that ZFC C “hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 iV
Coll.!1 ;R/
”
is -consistent. Suppose that G Coll.!1 ; R/ is V -generic. Then hH.!2 /; INS ; 2; A W A 2 iL.;R/ŒG :
t u
The requirement in Theorem 10.169 that L.; R/ \ P .R/ D where is the pointclass of all universally Baire sets is not difficult to achieve. With additional (substantial) large cardinal assumptions one can also require, L.; R/ ADR C “‚ is regular”; see Remark 10.167. Theorem 10.170. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that is an inaccessible limit of strong cardinals. Suppose that G Coll.!; < / 1 be the pointclass of all universally Baire sets as defined in V ŒG. is V -generic. Let G Then in V ŒG:
(1) There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. 1 1 ; RG / \ P .RG / D G . (2) L.G
(3) Suppose that in V , is the critical point of an elementary embedding j W VC1 ! VC1 : Then (in V ŒG) 1 ; RG / ADR C “‚ is regular”: L.G
We note the following theorem which is a variation of Theorem 4.79.
t u
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis
819
Theorem 10.171. Suppose that there exists a model hM; Ei such that hM; Ei ZFC C CH; and such that for each …2 sentence if there exists a partial order P such that hH.!2 /; 2iV VP
where Q D .Coll.!1 ; R//
P Q
;
, then hH.!2 /; 2ihM;E i :
Assume there exists a proper class of inaccessible cardinals. Then for all partial orders P , V P ADL.R/ : u t Remark 10.172. The proof of Theorem 10.171 uses the core model induction, this is the machinery used to prove Theorem 5.104 and Theorem 6.149; and the conclusion can be strengthened. A plausible upper bound in the consistency strength of the hypothesis is an inaccessible limit of Woodin cardinals which are limits of Woodin cardinals. Of course without the assumption that hM; Ei CH; the hypothesis is relatively weak, the upper bound, eliminating the inaccessibles, being the consistency strength of 1 ZFC C ./ C “For all P , V P 2 -Determinacy”; by Theorem 4.69.
t u
We generalize the notion of a mixed iteration scheme to weakly A-good mixed iteration schemes, and similarly we formulate the analogous mixed iteration hypothesis. These definitions allow us to state Theorem 10.175 which is the corresponding generalization of Theorem 10.12. With the version of Theorem 10.12 given here, it is possible to prove various generalizations of Theorem 10.128. But this we shall not do. Definition 10.173. Suppose that Q ı1 / 2 H.!1 / .M; ı0 ; E; and that (1) M ZFC, (2) ı0 < ı1 and each is a Woodin cardinal in M, (3) EQ 2 M is a weakly coherent Doddage (in M) witnessing ı1 is a Woodin cardinal in M. Suppose that A is universally Baire and that M is A-closed. Q ı1 / is weakly A-good if every iterate A mixed iteration scheme, I , for .M; ı0 ; E; of M constructed according to I , is A-closed. t u
820
10 Further results
Definition 10.174 (MIHC ).
(1) There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.
(2) There exist a Woodin cardinals ı0 < ı1 and a weakly coherent Doddage EQ D hE˛ W ˛ < ı1 i which witnesses ı1 is a Woodin cardinal such that if ı1 < and if is inaccessible then there exists a countable elementary substructure, X V containing ı0 ; ı1 and EQ such that hM; ı0M ; EQM ; ı1M i has a mixed iteration scheme which is 1 -homogeneously Suslin and weakly A-good for each universally Baire set A 2 X . Here M is the transitive collapse Q ı1 / under the collapsing map. u t of X and .ı0M ; EQM ; ı1M / is the image of .ı0 ; E; Theorem 10.175. Assume there is a proper class of measurable cardinals which are limits of Woodin cardinals. Then for each ordinal ˛ there exists a transitive inner model containing the ordinals such that (1) V˛ N , (2) N ZFC C MIHC , WH N WH (3) .1 / 1 .
t u
There are two natural candidates for canonical models of the form, L.P .!1 //, in the context of CH. (I) Suppose that 0 is 1 -huge. Suppose that G0 Coll.!; < 0 / is V -generic and that G1 .Coll.!1 ; < 1 //V ŒG0 is V ŒG0 -generic. The first candidate is L.P .!1 //V ŒG1 : (II) Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that L.; R/ ZF C ADR C “‚ is regular”: Suppose that G Coll.!1 ; R/ is L.; R/-generic. The second candidate is L.P .!1 //L.;R/ŒG : The first class of models, or at least the background models V ŒG1 , have two interesting features. These models were the subject of Theorem 6.28, which shows that a much stronger version of (1) below actually holds.
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis
821
(1) In V ŒG1 there is a normal, uniform, !1 -dense ideal on !1 . (2) There is a stationary set S !1V ŒG1 such that if C !1V ŒG1 is a V ŒG1 -generic club contained in S then hH.!2 /; 2iV ŒG1 ŒC where is any †2 -sentence such that ZFC C CH C “hH.!2 /; 2i ” is -satisfiable in V1 . A very interesting question is: Can ODR -Determinacy hold in L.P .!1 //V ŒG1 ? The second class of models have strong homogeneity properties and also a plethora of saturated ideals. (1) Suppose that H Coll.!2 ; /L.;R/ŒG is L.; R/ŒG-generic. Then in L.; R/ŒGŒH , there is a normal, uniform, !1 dense ideal on !1 . (2) .INS /L.;R/ŒG is quasi-homogeneous in L.; R/ŒG. (3) Suppose that P 2 L.; R/ŒG is an .!; 1/-distributive partial order, in L.; R/ŒG, of cardinality !1 . Suppose that g P is L.; R/ŒG-generic. Then .L.P .!1 ///L.;R/ŒG .L.P .!1 ///L.;R/ŒGŒg : An appealing conjecture is that these models, with the proper choices of the underlying ground models, do yield generalizations of ./ to the context of CH. Theorem 10.166 and Theorem 10.169 offer some evidence for this in the case of the second class of models. We end this section by stating several theorems which impose a rather fundamental limit on possible generalizations of Pmax to the context of CH. These theorems are conditioned on the following conjecture from .Woodin 2010b/. Definition 10.176 (ADC Conjecture). Suppose that L.A; R/ and L.B; R/ each satisfy ADC . Suppose that every set X 2 .L.A; R/ [ L.B; R// \ P .R/ is !1 -universally Baire. 2 L.A;R/ 2 L.B;R/ 2 L.B;R/ 2 L.A;R/ Then either . . or . . . 1 / 1 / 1 / 1 / There is a stronger version of this conjecture.
t u
822
10 Further results
Definition 10.177 (Strong ADC Conjecture). Suppose that L.A; R/ and L.B; R/ each satisfy ADC . Suppose that every set X 2 .L.A; R/ [ L.B; R// \ P .R/ is !1 -universally Baire. Then either A 2 L.B; R/ or B 2 L.A; R/.
t u
Theorem 10.178. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Let 1 be the pointclass of all A R such that A is universally Baire and let T D Th.H.!2 // Then following are equivalent. (1) There exists a sentence ‰ such that V ZFC C ‰ for some , and such that for each sentence , either a) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or b) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”. (2) T is is †1 definable (equivalently 1 -definable) in the structure hM 1 ; 2; ¹Rºi:
t u
Remark 10.179. (1) First order logic is definable in V! and as a result the theory of V! cannot be finitely axiomatized over ZFC in first order logic. This of course is the essence of the incompleteness theorems of G¨odel. The key question raised by Theorem 10.178 concerns the intrinsic complexity of -logic; i. e. of the set: 0 D ¹ j ZFC ` º for this places a limit on how large a fragment of V one can consistently assert has a theory which is finitely axiomatized over ZFC in -logic. The only immediate upper bound is Vı where ı is the second Woodin cardinal, noting that Wadge determinacy holds in this case for the sets A R which are homogeneously Suslin for each < ı. Neeman has proved that if there is a Woodin cardinal then all universally Baire sets are determined and using this result, the set 0 is definable in Vı0 C1 where ı0 is the least Woodin cardinal. The set 0 cannot be defined in H.!1 / and assuming ./ it cannot be defined in H.!2 /. (2) Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Let 1 be the pointclass of all A R such that A is universally Baire. Then 0 has the same Turing degree as the †1 -theory of the structure hM 1 ; 2; ¹RºiI in fact each is recursively reducible to the other. Thus the complexity of -logic t u is the same as that of the complete †21 . 1 / subset of !.
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis
823
Theorem 10.180 (CH C ADC Conjecture). Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Let 1 be the pointclass of all A R such that A is universally Baire. Let T be the †1 theory of hM 1 ; 2; ¹Rºi. Then either (1) T is †2 definable in the structure; hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i; or (2) T is …2 definable in the structure; hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i:
t u
There is a version of Theorem 10.180 which is not dependent on the ADC Conjecture. This theorem is proved using the core model induction. Theorem 10.181. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that either Martin’s Maximum.c/ holds or there is an !1 -dense ideal on !1 . Let 1 be the pointclass of all A R such that A is universally Baire and let T t u be the †1 theory of hM 1 ; 2; ¹Rºi. Then T is definable H.c C /. As a corollary of Theorem 10.180, using Tarski’s theorem on the undefinability of truth, one obtains the first theorem regarding CH. This theorem shows that the most optimistic possibility of a version of Pmax for CH must fail. Theorem 10.182 (ADC Conjecture). Suppose that there exist a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that ‰ is a sentence such that V ‰ for some strongly inaccessible cardinal, . Suppose that for each sentence , either (i) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or (ii) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”. t u
Then CH is false.
The axiom ./ is a natural example of an axiom which axiomatizes the theory of H.!2 / in -logic. An immediate consequence of ./ is that there exists a surjection W R ! !2 such that the induced prewellordering, ¹.x; y/ j .x/ .y/º is 13 . Let ˆ express: There exists a surjection W R ! !2 such that is 2 -definable in the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i; (without parameters),
824
10 Further results
if there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals then – the relation R D ¹.x; y/ j .x/ < .y/º is universally Baire, moreover – there exists a universally Baire set A such that R is .21 /L.A;R/ . We require the following generalization of Theorem 10.180. Under a variety of additional assumptions, alternative (2) can be eliminated. For example if either of the following hold: There is a normal, uniform, !2 -saturated ideal on !1 ; Chang’s Conjecture; then it can be eliminated. Theorem 10.183 (ADC Conjecture). Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Let 1 be the pointclass of all A R such that A is universally Baire. Let T be the †1 theory of hM 1 ; 2; ¹Rºi. Then either (1) T is †2 definable in the structure, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iI or (2) T is …2 definable in the structure, hH.!2 /; INS ; 2iI or (3) there exists a universally Baire set A R and a surjection W R ! !2V such that is 2 -definable in the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i and such that the prewellordering R D ¹.x; y/ j .x/ .y/º t u
is .21 /L.A;R/ .
The second theorem regarding CH generalizes the fact that ./ implies ı 12 D !2 . It is a corollary of Theorem 10.183. Theorem 10.184 (ADC Conjecture). Suppose that there exist a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that ‰ is a sentence such that V ‰ for some strongly inaccessible cardinal, . Suppose that for each sentence , either (i) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or (ii) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”. Then ˆ holds.
t u
10.5 -logic and the Continuum Hypothesis
825
We note the following theorem which shows that Theorem 10.184 is essentially the strongest possible. This theorem was independently proved by Neeman. Theorem 10.185. Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that A R is universally Baire, 0 is sentence and (i) L.A; R/ 0 , (ii) for all B 2 L.A; R/ \ P .R/, either L.B; R/ D L.A; R/, or L.B; R/ :0 . Let ‚A D .‚/L.A;R/ . Then there exists a sentence ‰ such that: (1) For each sentence , either a) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or b) ZFC C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”. (2) ZFC C ‰ is -consistent. t u
(3) ZFC C ‰ ` ‚A < !2 :
In the fall of 2009, Aspero, Larson, and Moore showed that there are …2 -sentences 1 and 2 such that both 1 and 2 can be forced to hold with CH but .1 ^2 / implies the :CH. The main question which remains is: Question. Can there exist a sentence ‰ such that for all †2 sentences, , either (1) ZFC C CH C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or (2) ZFC C CH C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”; and such that ZFC C CH C ‰ is -consistent?
t u
Remark 10.186. (1) A natural conjecture is that if the answer to the question above is yes, then under suitable large cardinal hypotheses, or suitable determinacy hypotheses, the witness for ‰, is simply the sentence: H.!2 / †2 H.!2 /V
Coll.!1 ;R/
;
which is a generic form of ˘, see Theorem 10.198. (2) As indicated in Remark 10.194 of the next section, one of the statements (Version III) preceding Remark 10.194 gives an example of a …2 sentence in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i which looks quite difficult to obtain (together with CH) except by forcing over a suitable model of ZF C ADC .
826
10 Further results
(3) We note the following corollary of Theorem 10.171. Suppose that CH holds in V and that if is a …2 sentence for which there exists a partial order P such that hH.!2 /; 2iV
P
CH C ;
then H.!2 / . Assume there exists a proper class of inaccessible cardinals. Then for all partial orders P , V P ADL.R/ :
t u
Finally if the Conjecture is false (and there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals) then a very interesting question is the following. Question. Can there exist a sentence ‰ such that for all either (1) ZFC C CH C ‰ “H.!2 / ”, or (2) ZFC C CH C ‰ “H.!2 / :”; and such that ZFC C CH C ‰ is -satisfiable?
t u
The next theorem, in conjunction with Theorem 10.184, shows that this question must have a negative answer in any sufficiently iterable model provided that ZFC C CH C ‰ is -consistent in V . Theorem 10.187. Suppose that there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that Q ı/ 2 H.!1 / .M; E; is such that: (i) M is transitive and M ZFC C “There exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals”: (ii) M “ı is a Woodin cardinal”. (iii) E 2 M and in M is a weakly coherent Doddage witnessing that ı is a Woodin cardinal. Q has an iteration scheme which is universally Baire. (iv) .M; E/ Suppose that T 2 M is a theory containing ZFC, is a sentence and that M “T ”: Then T ` .
t u
10.6 The Axiom ./C
827
10.6 The Axiom ./C The results of Section 9.2 suggest the following variations of the axiom ./. Definition 10.188. Axiom ./C : For each set X R there exists a set A R such that (1) L.A; R/ ADC , (2) there is an L.A; R/-generic filter, g Pmax , such that X 2 L.A; R/Œg:
t u
Definition 10.189. Axiom ./CC : There exists a pointclass P .R/ and a filter g Pmax such that (1) L.; R/ ADC , (2) g is L.; R/-generic, (3) P .R/ L.; R/Œg.
t u
The successful extension of the fine structural analysis of HODL.R/ to the analysis of HODL.A;R/ for all sets A R such that L.A; R/ ADC should yield a proof of the following conjecture. Definition 10.190 (The Cofinality Conjecture). Suppose that L.A; R/ and L.B; R/ are Wadge incomparable inner models of ADC . Let ı D sup¹‚L.C;R/ j C 2 P .R/ \ L.A; R/ \ L.B; R/º: t u
Then cof.ı/ D !1 .
Assuming Cofinality Conjecture an argument using the core model induction and which is quite similar to the proof of Theorem 10.181 yields the following theorem and it is a corollary of this theorem that the two axioms, ./C and ./CC , are equivalent. The statement of the theorem involves the following notation – for each set A R, ./A abbreviates: (1) L.A; R/ ADC , (2) L.P .!1 /; A/ D L.A; R/ŒG, for some L.A; R/-generic filter G Pmax . Theorem 10.191 (Cofinality Conjecture). Let be the pointclass of sets A R such that ./A holds and suppose that A and B are in . Then L.A; B; R/ ADC :
t u
828
10 Further results
Related to the problem of Martin’s Maximum vs. ./ is the following question: Is ZFC C Martin’s Maximum C ./CC consistent? A simpler question concerns the value of ı 12 in V Œg where g is V -generic for Namba forcing. Note that if ı 1 D !2 2 then necessarily, .ı12 /V < .ı12 /V Œg : A bound for .ı12 /V Œg is provided by the following theorem. Theorem 10.192. Assume that for all A !2 , A exists. Suppose that g is V -generic for Namba forcing. Then in V Œg: (1) For all x 2 R, x # exists; (2) ı12 !3V . Proof. We sketch the proof. Let P be the Namba partial order. The elements of P are pairs .s; t / such that (1.1) t !2
10.6 The Axiom ./C
829
and such that x D [¹.gjk/ j k < !º: Let A Ord be a set such that (3.1) .!2 /LŒA D !2 , (3.2) ¹; .s; t /º 2 LŒA, (3.3) !3 is a measurable cardinal in LŒA. Let PA D P \ LŒA. By (3.1), PA is simply the partial order for Namba forcing as defined in LŒA. defines a term A 2 LŒAPA for a real. Since there is a measurable cardinal in LŒA, LŒAPA “For all y 2 R, y # exists”: Let ı be the least strongly inaccessible cardinal in LŒA. Thus ı < !3V : Fix a tree T 2 LŒA on ! ı such that if g PA is LŒA-generic then in LŒAŒg ,
pŒT D ¹.y; y # / j y 2 RLŒAŒg º: As usual we regard the infinite branches of T as triples .y; z; f / where y 2 ! ! , z 2 ! ! and f 2 ı ! . Thus working in LŒA there exists a condition .s ; t / .s; t / in PA and a function
W t ! T
such that if b is an infinite branch of t then [¹ .bjk/ j k < !º is an infinite branch .y; z; f / of T such that y D [¹.bjk/ j k < !º. The condition .s ; t / 2 PA and the function are constructed by a fusion argument, analogous to the construction of .s; t / and . Here though one cannot require that is length preserving. We return to V Œg. By genericity we may suppose that .s ; t / 2 g. We now prove that in V Œg, x # exists and further that !3V is an indiscernible of LŒx. Since .s ; t / 2 g, there exists z 2 RV Œg such that .x; z/ 2 pŒT . By absoluteness it follows that z D x# for otherwise in LŒA there must exist .x ; z / 2 pŒT such that z ¤ .x /# contradicting the choice of T . This proves x # exists in V Œg. We finish by proving that !3V is an indiscernible of LŒx. In fact a simple boundedness argument shows that for each ordinal , the . C 1/th indiscernible of LŒx is below the least ordinal above which is admissible relative to T , cf. the proof of Theorem 10.62. However !3V is a cardinal in LŒT so it follows that !3V is an indiscernible of LŒx.
830
10 Further results
In summary we have proved that in V Œg, for all x 2 RV Œg , x # exists and that !3V is an indiscernible of LŒx. However !1V Œg D !1V and so it follows that .ı12 /V Œg !3V .
t u
Theorem 10.193 (Axiom ./CC ). Suppose that for each A !2 , A exists. Suppose that g is V -generic for Namba forcing. Then .ı12 /V Œg D .!3 /V : Proof. Clearly !3 D .‚/L.;R/ : Recall that AG denotes the set [¹a j h.M; I /; ai 2 Gº. By modifying G if necessary we can suppose that !1 D .!1 /LŒAG and so, since AC holds, there exists a surjection W !2 ! R which is †1 definable in the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i from AG . Fix an ordinal ˛ 2 !3 n !2 and fix a set B 2 such that B codes a a surjection W R ! ˛: Let F G be the set of
h.M; I /; ai 2 G
such that (1.1) M ZFC C ./, (1.2) B \ M 2 M, (1.3) .M; I / is B-iterable, (1.4) hV!C1 \ M; B \ M; 2i hV!C1 ; B; 2i. By Lemma 4.52 and Lemma 4.56, F is dense in G. Suppose that h.M; I /; ai 2 F and let jG W .M; I / ! .M ; I / be the (unique) iteration such that jG .a/ D AG : It follows from (1.1)–(1.4) that hV!C1 \ M ; 2i hV!C1 ; 2i
10.6 The Axiom ./C
831
and so by (1.1) it follows that hH.!2 /M ; 2i hH.!2 /; 2i: Therefore j.!2 /M 2 M . Now suppose that hh.Mk ; Ik /; ak i W k < !i is a decreasing sequence in F and for each k < ! let jGk W .Mk ; Ik / ! .Mk ; Ik / be the (unique) iteration such that jGk .ak / D AG : Let x 2 R code hh.Mk ; Ik /; ak i W k < !i. Then (2.1) Œsup¹Mk \ Ord j k < !º D [¹R \ Mk j k < !º, (2.2) ordertype.¹ ı .ˇ/ j ˇ 2 [¹Mk \ Ord j k < !ºº/ x where x is the least ordinal, , above !1 such that L Œx is admissible. The theorem easily follows. Define f W !2
Then s 2 M where
jG W .M; I / ! .M ; I /
is the iteration such that j.a/ D AG . (3.2) Suppose s 2 !2
t u
832
10 Further results
There are three analogs of ./C in the context of CH: Version I: Suppose that X !1 . Then there exists a set A R such that L.A; R/ ADC , there is a filter g Coll.!1 ; R/ such that (1) g is L.A; R/-generic, (2) X 2 L.A; R/Œg.
t u
Version II: Suppose that X !1 . Then there exists a pointclass P .R/ such that L.; R/ ZF C DC C ADR , there is a filter g Coll.!1 ; R/ such that (1) g is L.; R/-generic, (2) X 2 L.; R/Œg.
t u
Version III: Suppose that X !1 . Then there exists a pointclass P .R/ such that L.; R/ ZF C DC C ADR , there is a filter g Coll.!1 ; R/ such that (1) g is L.; R/-generic, (2) X 2 L.; R/Œg, (3) .INS /L.;R/Œg D INS \ L.; R/Œg.
t u
Remark 10.194. Clearly, assuming CH, (Version I) and (Version II) are each expressible by a …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; 2i: Further (Version III) is expressible by a …2 sentence in the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i: It is a corollary of the proof of Theorem 10.180 that (Version III) cannot be implied by CH in -logic. In fact one can show that the sentence “There exists a partial order P such that RV D .R/V V cannot be a validity of -logic.
P
P
and such that
(Version III)” t u
10.6 The Axiom ./C
833
We conjecture that (Version I) is implied by CH if there exists a measurable Woodin cardinal. This conjecture is implied by the following stronger conjecture for which we make the following definition. Suppose that G H.!1 /:
Let G be the set of b 2 H.!2 / such that for all countable X hH.!2 /; G ; 2i; if b 2 X then bX 2 G where bX is the image of b under the transitive collapse of X . The stronger conjecture is: (Long Game Conjecture) Assume that ı is a measurable Woodin cardinal and that AR is ı-homogeneously Suslin. Suppose that G H.!1 / and that G 2 L.A; R/. Then there exists a set B R such that (1) B is ı-homogeneously Suslin, (2) A 2 L.B; R/, (3) in L.B; R/Pmax , the integer game of length !1 given by G is determined t u where G is as defined in L.B; R/Pmax . Remark 10.195. (1) It is not difficult to show that assuming ./, there is definable integer game of length !1 which is not determined. (2) It is a corollary of Long Game Conjecture that if ı is a measurable Woodin cardinal then for every set A R, if A is ı-homogeneously Suslin and if G 2 P .H.!1 // \ L.A; R/; then the integer game of length !1 given by G is determined (no assumption concerning CH is made). The Long Game Conjecture is true if this corollary is provable from the existence of a measurable Woodin cardinal, provided certain iterability assumptions hold in V . (3) Neeman has shown that if there is a measurable Woodin cardinal then the Long Game Conjecture follows directly from iterability assumptions for V , Neeman .2004/. t u Theorem 10.196 (Long Game Conjecture). Assume there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals. Then there exists a universally Baire set A R such that the following holds. Suppose that X !1 , Y !1 and that !1 D .!1 /LŒX D .!1 /LŒY : Suppose that A \ LŒX 2 LŒX and that A \ LŒY 2 LŒY . Then LŒX LŒY :
t u
834
10 Further results
Theorem 10.197 (Long Game Conjecture, CH). Assume there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals. Suppose that X !1 . Then there exists a set A R such that (1) L.A; R/ ADC , (2) there is a filter g Coll.!1 ; R/ such that a) g is L.A; R/-generic, b) X 2 L.A; R/Œg.
t u
We now consider the problem of obtaining (Version II) from CH. This is closely related to the question concerning CH, listed at the end of the previous section: Does there exist a sentence ‰ such that ZFC C CH C ‰ is -consistent and such that for all †2 sentences, , either – ZFC C CH C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or – ZFC C CH C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”? It is convenient to define a slight strengthening of (Version II). (Version II)C : Suppose that X !1 and that A R is universally Baire. Then there exists a pointclass P .R/ such that A 2 , L.; R/ ZF C DC C ADR , there is a filter g Coll.!1 ; R/ such that (1) g is L.; R/-generic, (2) X 2 L.; R/Œg.
t u
We remark that the assumptions (i)–(iii) of Theorem 10.198 should hold in any fine structural inner model in which there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals. Further it seems quite plausible that (i), (iii) and a sufficient fragment of (ii) are provable consequences of the existence of a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals; i. e. that the stronger theorem, obtained by eliminating the assumptions (i)– (iii), is actually true. Theorem 10.198. Assume there exists a proper class of measurable Woodin cardinals and that: (i) Long Game Conjecture holds; (ii) WHIHC holds;
10.7 The Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis
835
(iii) For each universally Baire set, A R, there exists Q ı/ 2 H.!1 / .M; E; such that a) M ZFC, b) EQ 2 M is a weakly coherent Doddage (in M) witnessing ı is a Woodin cardinal in M, c) in M there is a measurable Woodin cardinal above ı, d) M is A-closed, Q has a universally Baire iteration scheme which is weakly A-good. e) .M; E/ Then the following are equivalent. (1) ZFC C CH (Version II)C . (2) For each †2 sentence, , either a) ZFC C CH C “H.!2 / †2 H.!2 /V b) ZFC C CH C “H.!2 / †2 H.!2 /
Coll.!1 ;R/
V Coll.!1 ;R/
” ` “H.!2 / ”, or ” ` “H.!2 / :”.
t u
Suppose that LŒE is a Mitchell–Steel inner model with a superstrong cardinal, and a proper class of Woodin cardinals, in which the countable initial segments of LŒE are -iterable for every . Then one can show that in LŒE, the †2 theory of H.!2 / is not finitely axiomatized over ZFC in -logic. With additional assumptions one can also show that in LŒE, (Version II) must fail. Thus any attempt to prove (Version II) from CH would seem to require large cardinals beyond superstrong.
10.7 The Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose is an uncountable cardinal and that g Coll.!; / is V -generic. Suppose in V Œg there exists a prewellordering .RV Œg ; g / such that in V Œg: (1) g is 1 -homogeneously Suslin; (2) g has length !2 . Must there exist in V an 1 -homogeneously Suslin prewellordering of length CC ? By Theorem 9.132, if there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and if the nonstationary ideal on !2 is semi-saturated then the answer is no, with D !1 . The case when is a singular strong limit cardinal seems particularly interesting. A positive answer is an effective form of the Singular Cardinals Hypothesis.
836
10 Further results
Definition 10.199. Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis: Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose that is a singular strong limit cardinal and that g Coll.!; / is V -generic. Suppose that M V Œg is a transitive inner model such that in V Œg: (1) R M ; (2) M ZF C AD; (3) Every set A 2 P .R/ \ M is 1 -homogeneously Suslin. Then ‚M < . CC /V .
t u
Remark 10.200. There are two natural variations of the Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis: (1) One could require that GCH holds below , or (2) that the Effective Generalized Continuum Hypothesis holds below . The Effective Generalized Continuum Hypothesis is the obvious variation of Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis: Suppose that is an infinite cardinal and that g Coll.!; / is V -generic. Suppose that M V Œg is a transitive inner model such that in V Œg: – R M; – M ZF C AD; – Every set A 2 P .R/ \ M is 1 -homogeneously Suslin. Then ‚M < . CC /V .
t u
We give a brief summary of a few relevant results and which are proved in Chapter 7 of .Woodin 2010b/. These results are primarily concerned with the following related problem. Suppose is a singular strong limit cardinal and that 2 V Coll.!;/ 1
is a term for an -homogeneously Suslin set of reals. Must be equivalent to a term which is definable from parameters in H. C /? It is convenient to introduce the notion of a term relation. Definition 10.201. Suppose that is a cardinal and that 2 V Coll.!;/ is a term for a subset P .!/. The term relation of is the set of pairs .p; / such that
10.7 The Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis
837
(1) ! Coll.!; /, (2) p 2 Coll.!; /, (3) p x 2 , where x 2 V Coll.!;/ is the term for a subset of ! given by ; ŒŒn 2 x D _¹q 2 Coll.!; / j .n; q/ 2 º:
t u
The case when has uncountable cofinality is easily dealt with. Theorem 10.202. Suppose that is a strong limit cardinal of uncountable cofinality. Suppose that 2 V Coll.!;/ is a term for an 1 -homogeneously Suslin subset of P .!/. Then the term relation for is definable, from parameters, in the structure hH. C /; 2i: Proof. Without loss of generality we may suppose that H. C /. Let T be a term for a weakly homogeneous tree in V Coll.!;/ with projection and let F be term for a function which witnesses that T is weakly homogeneous. Since every every countably complete measure in V Coll.!;/ which concentrates on finite sequences of ordinals extends uniquely a measure in V , there exists (uniquely) a partial function W ¹.s; t; q/ j s 2 !
838
10 Further results
Let G be the set of countably generated filters g Coll.!; /. Thus G 2 H. C / as is the function W G ! P .R/ defined by .g/ D A g . Let R be the term relation for . Then is is easily verified that .p; / 2 R if and only if S is stationary in P!1 .H. // where S is the set of countable elementary substructures Y hH. /; 2i such that for some set D Y \ Coll.!; /, (1.1) p 2 Y , (1.2) D is dense in Y \ Coll.!; /, (1.3) if g 2 G , p 2 g, and D \ g ¤ ;, then Ig . / 2 A g : Thus R is definable in H. C / from .G ; /.
t u
As one might expect, the case when has cofinality ! is more subtle. Theorem 10.203. Let be a singular strong limit cardinal of cofinality !. Suppose that there exists an elementary embedding j W L.VC1 / ! L.VC1 / with critical point below . Then there exists a closed cofinal set C such that: (1) j.C / D C ; (2) Suppose 2 C and cof. / D !. Then jV j D and there exists a term 2 V Coll.!;/ for a subset of P .!/ such that, a) is a term for a set which is < -weakly homogeneously Suslin, b) every set in L .VC1 / \ P .VC1 / is †1 definable from parameters in the structure, hH. C /; R ; 2i; where R is the term relation of . Remark 10.204. The large cardinal hypothesis: There exists an elementary embedding j W L.VC1 / ! L.VC1 / with critical point below ,
t u
10.7 The Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis
839
yields a structure theory for L.VC1 / which in many aspects is analogous to the structure theory for L.R/ in the context of ADL.R/ . Note that by Kunen’s theorem on the nonexistence of an elementary embedding of V to V , must be the ! th element of the critical sequence of j . The next theorem shows that from this hypothesis one obtains a weak failure of the Effective Singular Cardinals Hypothesis. The proof of this theorem and of related theorems can be found in Chapter 7 of .Woodin 2010b/. t u Theorem 10.205. Suppose that there exists an elementary embedding j W L.VC1 / ! L.VC1 / with critical point below and that g Coll.!; / is V -generic. Then in V Œg there exists a transitive inner model M L.VC1 /Œg such that (1) RV Œg M , (2) M ZF C ADC , (3) . CC /L.VC1 / < ‚M .
t u
Remark 10.206. It is a natural conjecture that the inner model M of Theorem 10.205 can be chosen such that .‚/L.VC1 /Œg D ‚M : It is immediate that .‚/L.VC1 /Œg is simply the least ordinal such that in L.VC1 /, is not the surjective image of VC1 . We denote this ordinal by ‚L.VC1 / , this is the natural generalization of ‚L.R/ to L.VC1 /. This in turn suggests the following problem. Suppose there exists an elementary embedding j W L.VC1 / ! L.VC1 / with critical point below . Must ‚L.VC1 / < CC ‹
t u
Chapter 11
Questions
The following is a list of questions, including many which have appeared in earlier chapters. The order simply reflects roughly the place within the book where the question is discussed, either explicitly or implicitly, and there is significant overlap among various of these questions. Comments have been asserted in italics for those questions which either have been solved or otherwise affected by developments of which I am aware since the first edition. (1) Assume L.R/ AD. Must ‚L.R/ !3 ? (2) Can there exist countable transitive models M and M such that M ZFC C “The nonstationary ideal on !1 is saturated”;
M is an iterate of M , and such that M 2 M ? (3) Suppose that the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !2 -saturated and that L.R/ AD: Must ı12 D !2 ? (4) Suppose that N is a transitive inner model containing the ordinals such that N ZFC and such that for each countable set N there exists a set 2 N with jjN D ! and such that . a) Suppose that for each set X , X # exists. Must ı 1 D .ı12 /N ‹
2
b) Suppose that for each partial order P , V P ADL.R/ : Must .HOD/L.R/ D .HOD/L.R
N/
‹
(5) Suppose that INS is !2 -saturated and that P .!1 /# exists. Suppose that A !1 and let A D sup¹.!2 /LŒZ j Z !1 ; A 2 LŒZ; and RLŒA D RLŒZ º: Must A < !2 ?
11 Questions
841
(6) Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Do either of the following imply :CH? a) Every function f W !1 ! !1 is bounded on a closed cofinal subset of !1 by a canonical function. b) Suppose that A R is universally Baire and that f W !1 ! A: Then there exists a tree T on ! !1 such that that A D pŒT and such that ¹˛ < !1 j f .˛/ 2 pŒT j˛º contains a closed cofinal subset of !1 . Solved by Larson and Shelah: The answer is no. (7) Suppose the nonstationary ideal on !1 is !1 -dense. a) Must c D !2 ? b) Must ı 12 D !2 ? c) Must ‚L.R/ !3 ? (8) Assume Martin’s Maximum.c/. Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass, closed under continuous preimages, such that a) L.; R/ ADC , b) !3 D .‚/L.;R/ . Suppose that G Pmax is an L.; R/-generic filter such that G 2 V and such that P .!1 / D P .!1 /G : Must L.; R/ŒG ADR ‹ (9) Assume ./. Suppose W Œ!1 2 ! ¹0;1º is a partition with no homogeneous rectangle for 0 of (proper) cardinality @1 . Must there exist a set X !1 such that E .3/ ŒX is nonstationary in !1 ? Justin Moore has proved that the associated partition relation is false .Moore 2006/, but the status of this question remains unclear. (10) Assume . a) Must INS be semi-saturated? b) Must HODR AD?
842 (11)
11 Questions
a) Suppose that the Axiom of Condensation holds. Does strong condensation hold for H.!2 /? b) Suppose that N is a transitive inner model of ZFC in which the Axiom of Strong Condensation holds and that covering fails for N . Must N LŒx for some x 2 R?
(12) (Conjecture) The following are equiconsistent. a) ZFC C Martin’s Maximum.c/ C “JNS is weakly presaturated”. b) ZFC C CH C “INS jS is !1 -dense for a dense set of S 2 P .!1 / n INS ”. c) ZF C ADR C “‚ is regular”. (13) Assume there is a measurable cardinal. a) Is is possible for every function f W !2 ! !2 to be bounded by a canonical function pointwise on a closed unbounded set? b) Can the nonstationary ideal on !2 be semi-saturated? c) Let I be the nonstationary ideal on !2 restricted to the ordinals of cofinality !1 . Can the ideal I be semi-saturated? d) Suppose that there exists a normal uniform ideal I P .!2 / such that I is semi-saturated and contains JNS . Suppose that J P .!2 / is a normal uniform semi-saturated ideal. Must JNS J ‹ The motivation for this question is rendered irrelevant by Shelah’s theorem on ˘! .!2 /. The natural conjecture now is that the answer to (a)–(c) is negative. (14) Is Martin’s Maximum + MIH consistent? (15) Assume Martin’s Maximum. a) Can ./C hold?
? c) Can L.P .!! // ?
b) Can L.P .!3 //
11 Questions
843
(16) (Conjectures) a) There exists a regular (uncountable) cardinal and a definable partition of ¹˛ < j cof.˛/ D !º into infinitely many stationary sets. b) Suppose that there is a proper class of supercompact cardinals. Then (a) holds. c) Assume Martin’s Maximum. There is a definable wellordering of the reals. These conjectures are all implied by the HOD-Conjecture of .Woodin 2010b/ where a number of relevant results are proved. (17) Suppose that P .R/ is a pointclass closed under continuous preimages such that L.; R/ ADC and let M D .HOD/L.;R/ . Suppose that a !1 is a countable set such that M Œa ./: Must .!1 /
M
< .!1 /
M Œa
?
(18) Assuming the existence of some large cardinal: a) Must there exist a semiproper partial order P such that V P ./‹ b) Must there exist a semiproper partial order P such that V P “ INS is !1 -dense ”‹ (19) Suppose that 1 and 2 are †2 sentences such that both ZFC C 1 and ZFC C 2 are each -consistent. Is ZFC C 1 C “V P 2 for some semiproper P ” -consistent? (20) Suppose that 0 is 1 huge. Suppose that G0 Coll.!; < 0 / is V -generic and that G1 .Coll.!1 ; < 1 //V ŒG0 is V ŒG0 -generic. Can ODR -Determinacy hold in L.P .!1 //V ŒG1 ?
844
11 Questions
(21) Suppose that 1 and 2 are …2 sentences (in the language for the structure hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i) such that both ZFC C CH C “hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i 1 ” and ZFC C CH C “hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i 2 ” are -consistent. Let D .1 ^ 2 /. Is ZFC C CH C “hH.!2 /; INS ; 2i ” -consistent? Solved by Aspero, Larson, and Moore in fall, 2009: The answer is no. (22) Can there exist a sentence ‰ such that for all †2 sentences, , either ZFC C CH C ‰ ` “H.!2 / ”, or ZFC C CH C ‰ ` “H.!2 / :”; and such that ZFC C CH C ‰ is -consistent? The reformulation with CH C ‰ replaced by either generic-˘ or ˘, is also open and discussed in Woodin .2003/. (23) (Conjecture) Assume there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Let be a †2 sentence. Then the following are equivalent. a) ZFC C is -consistent. b) There exists a partial order P such that V P . This is the Conjecture. (24) Are the following mutually consistent? a) .ZF C DC/ There exists a cardinal such that for every cardinal , there exists an elementary embedding j WV !V with cp.j / D and j. / > . b) .ZF C DC/ For all x 2 R, ¹xº is OD if and only if for some A 2 1 , x is OD in L.A; R/. (25) Assume there exists an elementary embedding j W L.VC1 / ! L.VC1 / with critical point below . Define ‚L.VC1 / to be; sup¹˛ 2 Ord j there exists a surjection, f W P . / ! ˛, with f 2 L.VC1 /º: Must
‚L.VC1 / < CC ‹
Bibliography
Baumgartner, J. E. and A. D. Taylor (1982). Saturation properties of ideals in generic extensions. I. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 270, 557–574. Blass, A. (1988). Selective ultrafilters and homogeneity. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 38, 215–255. Claverie, B. and R. Schindler (2010). Woodin’s axiom ./, bounded forcing axioms, and precipitous ideals on !1 . Preprint. Devlin, K. and S. Shelah (1978). A weak version of ˘ which follows from a weak version of 2@0 < 2@1 . Israel J. Math. 29, 239–247. Doebler, P. and R. Schindler (2009). …2 consequences of BMM + INS is precipitous and the semiproperness of stationary set preserving forcings. Preprint. Feng, Q. and T. Jech (1998). Projective stationary sets and strong reflection principle. J. London Math. Soc. 58(2), 271–283. Feng, Q., M. Magidor, and W. H. Woodin (1992). Universally Baire sets of reals. In H. Judah, W. Just, and H. Woodin (Eds.), Set Theory of the Continuum, Volume 26 of Mathematical Sciences Research Institute Publications, Heidelberg, pp. 203–242. Springer-Verlag. Foreman, M. (2010). Ideals and generic elementary embeddings. In M. Foreman and A. Kanamori (Eds.), Handbook of Set Theory – volume 2, Volume XIV, pp. 1951– 2120. New York: Springer-Verlag. Foreman, M. and A. Kanamori (Eds.) (2010). Handbook of Set Theory – three volumes, Volume XIV. New York: Springer-Verlag. Foreman, M. and M. Magidor (1995). Large cardinals and definable counterexamples to the continuum hypothesis. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 76, 47–97. Foreman, M., M. Magidor, and S. Shelah (1988). Martin’s maximum, saturated ideals and non-regular ultrafilters I. Ann. of Math. 127, 1–47. Hjorth, G. (1993). The influence of u2 . Ph. D. thesis, U. C. Berkeley. Huberich, M. (1996). A note on Boolean algebras with partitions modulo some filter. Archive of Math. Logic Quarterly. 42, 172–174. Jackson, S. (1988). AD and the projective ordinals. In Cabal Seminar 81–85, Volume 1333 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics, pp. 117–220. Springer-Verlag.
846
Bibliography
Jech, T. and W. Mitchell (1983). Some examples of precipitous ideals. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 24(2), 99–212. Kanamori, A. (2008). The higher infinite. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Large cardinals in set theory from their beginnings; second edition. Kechris, A., D. A. Martin, and R. Solovay (1983). An introduction to Q theory. In Cabal Seminar 79–81, Volume 1019 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. SpringerVerlag. Ketchersid, R., P. Larson, and J. Zapletal (2007). Increasing ı 12 by Nambia-style forcing. JSL 72, 1372–1378. Koellner, P. and W. H. Woodin (2010). Large cardinals from determinacy. In M. Foreman and A. Kanamori (Eds.), Handbook of Set Theory-volume 3, Volume XIV, pp. 1951–2120. New York: Springer-Verlag. Larson, P. (2004). The Stationary Tower: Notes on a Course by W. Hugh Woodin. University Lecture Series (American Mathematical Society). Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press. Laver, R. (1976). On the consistency of Borel’s conjecture. Acta Math. 137, 151–169. Law, D. (1994). An abstract condensation property. Ph. D. thesis, Caltech. Levy, A. and R. Solovay (1967). Measurable cardinals and the continuum hypothesis. Israel J. Math. 5, 234–248. Martin, D. A. and J. Steel (1983). The extent of scales in L.R/. In Cabal Seminar 79–81, Volume 1019 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag. Martin, D. A. and J. Steel (1989). A proof of projective determinacy. J. Amer. Math. Soc. 2, 71–125. Martin, D. A. and J. R. Steel (1994). Iteration trees. J. Amer. Math. Soc. 7(1), 1–73. Mitchell, W. J. and J. R. Steel (1994). Fine structure and iteration trees. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Moore, J. (2006). A solution to the L space problem. J. Amer. Math. Soc. 19(3), 717–736. Moschovakis, Y. N. (1980). Descriptive set theory. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Co. Neeman, I. (2004). The determinacy of long games, Volume 7 of de Gruyter Series in Logic and its Applications. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co. Ostaszewski, A. J. (1975). On countably compact perfectly normal spaces. Journal of the London Mathematical Society 14(2), 505–516.
Bibliography
847
Sargsyan, G. (2009). A tale of hybrid mice. Ph. D. thesis, U. C. Berkeley. Shelah, S. (1986). Around classification theory of models, Volume 1182 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag. Shelah, S. (1987). Iterated forcing and normal ideals on !1 . Israel J. Math. 60, 345–380. Shelah, S. (1998). Proper forcing and Improper Forcing. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Shelah, S. (2008). Diamonds. Shelah archive 922, http://shelah.logic.at. Shelah, S. and W. H. Woodin (1990). Large cardinals imply that every reasonable definable set is Lebesque measurable. Israel J. Math. 70, 381–394. Shelah, S. and J. Zapletal (1999). Canonical models for @1 combinatorics. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 98, 217–259. Steel, J. and R. VanWesep (1982). Two consequences of determinacy consistent with choice. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 272, 67–85. Steel, J. and S. Zoble (2008). Determinacy from strong reflection. Preprint. Steel, J. R. (1981). Closure properties of pointclasses. In A. S. Kechris, D. A. Martin, and Y. N. Moschovakis (Eds.), Cabal Seminar 77–79, Volume 839 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics, pp. 147–163. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Steel, J. R. (1996). The core model iterability problem. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Taylor, A. (1979). Regularity properties of ideals and ultrafilters. Ann. Math. Logic 16, 33–55. Todorcevic, S. (1984). Strong reflection principles. Circulated Notes. Woodin, W. H. (1983). Some consistency results in ZFC using AD. In Cabal Seminar 79–81, Volume 1019 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics, pp. 172–198. Springer-Verlag. Woodin, W. H. (1985, May). †21 absoluteness. Circulated Notes. Woodin, W. H. (2003). Beyond †21 Absoluteness. In Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians, Beijing, 2002, Volume I, pp. 515–524. Higher Education Press. Woodin, W. H. (2009). The Continuum Hypothesis, the generic-multiverse of sets, and the Conjecture. In press. Woodin, W. H. (2010a). The fine structure of suitable extender sequences I. Preprint. Woodin, W. H. (2010b). Suitable extender sequences. Preprint.
Index
A-Bounded Martin’s Maximum, 798 A-Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC , 798 A(Code) .S; z; B/, 769 A-closed structure, 808 ADC Conjecture, 821 ADC , 611 A-iterable model, M , 73 A-iterable structure, hMk W k < !i, 224 Axiom of Strong Condensation, 499 Axiom ./, 184 Axiom ./C , 827 Axiom ./ CC , 827 Axiom , 241 Œˇ˛ , 493 Œˇ<˛ , 493 Bmax , 454 Bounded Martin’s Maximum, 784 Bounded Martin’s MaximumC , 784 Bounded Martin’s MaximumCC , 784 Borel Conjecture, 447 BCFA, 488 canonical function, 683 |, 493 Chang’s Conjecture, 637 |NS , 494 |0NS , 493 C
|NS , 578 CC
|NS , 579 Chang’s ConjectureC , 667 closed set (general), 34 closed, unbounded (general), 34 M|NS , 511 | M0 NS , 569 coding elements of H.!1 /, 21 coding elements of H.c C /, 21
The Cofinality Conjecture, 827 Coll .!; S /, 341 condensation, 496 Axiom of Condensation, 496 condensation-strong, 499 Axiom of Strong Condensation, 499 ı11 .A/, 129 ı-homogeneously Suslin, 26 4, 121 diagonal intersection, 4, 121 5, 121 diagonal union,5, 121 ˘.!1
850
Index
I<ı , 199 I _ S , 288 indecomposable ultrafilter, 422 1 -borel set A, 610 INS , 2 iterable structure, 53 iteration of a structure, h.Nk ; Jk / W k < !i, 119 iteration of a structure, hNk W k < !i, 124 iteration of a structure, h.Mk ; Ik / W k < !i, 201 iteration (full), 205 iteration scheme, 695 iteration scheme (mixed), 697 iterations by stationary tower, 200 iteration of a structure, .M; I; a/, 511 iteration of a structure, .M; I/, 116 IU;F , 505 JNS , 683 Long Game Conjecture, 833 MIH, 698 MIHC , 820 mixed iteration scheme, 697 Martin’s Maximum, 38 Martin’s MaximumZF .c/, 40 Martin’s MaximumC , 38 Martin’s MaximumC .c/, 39 Martin’s MaximumCC , 39 Martin’s MaximumCC .c/, 39 M -normal ultrafilter, 124 M , 29 M3 .a/, 262 M! .a/, 804 nonregular ultrafilter, 421 N , 29 !1 -dense ideals and Suslin trees, 331 -Conjecture, 810
-logic, 807 !1 -dense ideal, 306 -proof, 809 !-presaturated ideal, 683 PF , 578 PFA; Proper Forcing Axiom, 37 AC , 185 ˆBC , 487 ˆ˘ , 398 ˆC ˘ , 400 ˆS , 426 ˆC S , 427 Pmax , 136 0 Pmax , 233 |
NS Pmax , 508 2 Pmax , 290 , 221 Pmax (T) Pmax , 207 PNS , 288 pointclass, 22 projection for measures, 24 proper partial order, 36 Proper Forcing Axiom; PFA, 37 weakly proper partial order, 753 AC , 193 AC .I /, 441 AC , 221 P<˛ , 35 PU , for ultrafilters on !, 476 PU , for ultrafilters on !1 , 501 .;/ , 739 Pmax .;;B/ Pmax , 773
QF , 581 Qmax , 307 KT Qmax , 384 KT Qmax , 391 M Qmax , 408 2 Qmax , 371 Q max , 708 Qmax , 334 Q<˛ , 35 Q3 .X /, 172
Index
quasi-homogeneous ideal, 278 Q.X/ max , 709 R, 21 RU;F , 506 .ı/ , 512 RU;F sat.I /, 294 S(Code) .S; z/, 704 scale, 23 -scale, 23 scale property, 23 Strong Chang’s Conjecture, 667 strong condensation, 499 Axiom of Strong Condensation, 499 semiproper antichain, 44 |NS semi-generic filter, Pmax , 541 semi-generic filter, Pmax , 147 0 semi-generic filter, Pmax , 234 semi-iteration, 128 semi-iterable structure, 128 semiproper partial order, 37 Semiproper Forcing Axiom; SPFA, 38 semi-saturated ideal on !2 , 685 semi-saturated ideal, 130 S˛g , a stationary set associated to g, 238 †11 .A/; †11 .A/, 73 -centered, 428 2 † 1 ./, 31 2 † 1 .< ı-WH/, 31 2 1 † 1 . -WH/, 31 Smax , 428 Suslin cardinal, 613 Suslin sets of reals, 22 SPFA; Semiproper Forcing Axiom, 38 SRP.!2 /, 652 SRP .!2 /, 662 stationary set (general), 34 stationary subset (general), 34 stationary tower, 35 SQ , 184 Strong ADC Conjecture, 822
strongly A-iterable structure, 336 strongly iterable, 129 strong measure 0, 447 SRP, 43 Suslin trees from an !1 -dense ideal, 331 h‚˛ W ˛ i, 614 tower of measures, 24 tower, countably complete, 24 trees for Suslin representations, 21 |
NS Umax , 557 universal function, F , 598 universally Baire set A, 795 U -restricted …2 formula, 363
V -normal ultrafilter on !2 , 685 Wadge order, 615 w.A/, 615 weak Kurepa tree, 112 Weak Kurepa Hypothesis from ./, 401 weakly coherent Doddage, 695 weakly homogeneous tree, 25 ı-weakly homogeneous tree, 25 <ı-weakly homogeneous tree, 25 weakly normal ultrafilter, 422 weakly presaturated; JNS , 683 weakly special tree, 400 weakly proper partial order, 753 WHIH, 696 WHIHC , 816 WRP, 42 WRP.!2 /, 652 WRP.2/ .!2 /, 652 WRP .!2 /, 662 X(Code) .S; z/, 704 X -iterable structure, .M; I/, 117 X -iterable structure, .hMk W k < !i; f /, 336
851
852
Index
YA .F; I /, 404 YA .F; ı/, 418 YBC .I /, 451 YBC .I /, 451 Y(Code) .S; z/, 704 YColl .I /, 307 ZBC .I /, 450 ZFC , 52 ZFC , 404 Zh;F , 505 Zp;F , 505