This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
.
2.
Case
That
completes
the d e f i n i t i o n s
in Case
I.
u 6 R.
lemma
element <J
<j-least
-definable
J
Y
be the
2.2,
let q(m)
of Jp(m)
be the
<j-least
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
q 6 Jp(~)
from parameters
such
that
every
in a m U {q}
in
p(~) ,A(m)>. Set ]
>,
[
,
This The
completes following
Lemma
the d e f i n i t i o n two
lemmas
are
if Y < p(~),
if ~ : p(V).
in Case
2.
clear:
2.4 J
<<8(~) ,P(q) ,A(~) ,p(n)>
I q 6 S
n v> is u n i f o r m l Y ~ l
~ 6 S.[3
Lemma
2.5
L e t ~,~ 6 S,
and
suppose
o: <Jp(v) ,A(v)> is such Then
that
o(p(~))
o is u n i q u e l y
(i)
~ 6 P ++ T 6 P;
(ii)
~(~
(iii)
V < p(m)
(iv)
~ < 0(~)
(v)
~6P
(vi)
o(q(v))
) = ~ ;
÷
++ T
o(y(~))
p(~) ,A(T)>
= p(T).
determined
÷ 0(~)
= T; :
= q(T). [3
y(T);
by o ~ e
• Moreover:
~({~
}) for
of
Lemma Let
2.6
m 6 S, ~ _< p(v) , A _ c J ~ ,
o: where
p(~) 6 r a n ( o ) .
that
~ = p(~);
Proof:
Notice
and
<J[,A>
Then
A(~)
= #, so A = ~,
each
~ < ~,
~I
there
A : h(~). first
suppose
<Jp(m),A(~)>,
is
a
(necessarily
Moreover,
o(p(5))
that
<J~,A>
amenable.
and
if m 6 R,
is
<Jp(v),A(v)>
then
~
3x
unique)
5 6 S such
= p(m). For
llm(p(v)),
if
~ 6 P,
so
lim
then
(~),
and
for
(x = A(~) N J o ( q ) ) ,
SO
<J~,A> Set
~ = e
Case Set J
b
Bx
(x = A N J
).
, ~ = 8(~) , n = n(~) , p = p(v) , A = A(m) , p = p(~) , q = q(u) .
I. ~ 6 P y = y(v).
. Since
Thus
B = P = Y + i, A = A = ¢,
p 6 ran(O),
we
have
q,y,~,~
6 ran(o).
and
~ is r e g u l a r
Let
over
q = -l(q),
Y = d-l(y), and
q 6 ran
Claim
A:
Proof: ~(~)
=
~.
B:
Proof:
Claim
5 6 S and
from
~ = o I J ~.
Thus
~:
J~
Jy
= ~. immediately
5 is r e g u l a r ~:
J~
q is the
Let
q,~.
Let
from
~:
J~
41 Jp
and
o(~)
= ~,
[]
is J ~ - d e f i n a b l e
Proof:
~
follows
Since
C:
~ = -i(~).
(~).
This
Claim
J~
~ = o-i(~),
x 6 J~. Set
over
~ Jy
and
<j-least from Then
s = <~>.
J~. ~ = ~ + v = y and
element
parameters ~(x) 6 Jy, Let
~ be
of J~
such
v ~ y ÷ ~(5)
that
every
= ~.~
element
of
in ~ U {2}so for
a formula
some of
~ 6 e, ~(x)
is J - d e f i n a b l e
set
such
theory
that
(i)
J
~ Vz By Vy'
[y'
: y ÷÷
%(y',z,q)];
Y (ii)
J
~ Vz Vy
[~(y,z,q)
÷
(B~)
(z = <~>)];
Y (iii)
(Vy6 J
) [y = ~(x)
+÷ J
Y Let
t be
the
<j-least
~ %(y,s,q)]. Y
elemen{
of J
such
that
J
~ ~(~(x),t,q). Then Y t is J - d e f i n a b l e f r o m ~(x) ,q. But ~(x) ,q 6 r a n ( ~ ) < J . H e n c e Y Y t6ran(~). By c h o i c e of t,t _<js , so t 6 J . Thus t = <~> for some Y
~6~. By
(i) above, (Vy 6 J ) 7 --i q
Applying
and
[ = o
7
u
$ 6 [,
this m e a n s
~(x)
++ J
~ %(y,t,q)]. Y
----1
setting
(Vy6 J:) Since
[y =
(t) = <~>,
we get
[y : x ÷÷ J- b ~ ( y , t , q ) ] . Y
that x
is J - - d e f i n a b l e Y
from
parameters
in
{~}. Hence
U {q}. and
We
let q'
every show
element that
<j p h a v e
of J- is J - - d e f i n a b l e Y Y q is < j - m i n i m a l w i t h this
property.
this
in p a r t i c u l a r ,
property
also.
are $ C ~ such that { is J--definable Y
_
and s e t t i n g from
~,q'.
Hence
Then,
from ~,~'.
w
q' : o(q
) ' ~ = $(~),
every
we h a v e
q'
Applying
in
Suppose
not,
there
~: J-< J
Y Y <j q and q is J y - d e f i n a b l e
is J - d e f i n a b l e f r o m p a r a m e t e r s Y Y in ~ U {q'}, s i n c e in any J - d e f i n i t i o n of an e l e m e n t f r o m p a r a m e t e r s Y in [ U {q} we can r e p l a c e q by its d e f i n i t i o n from ~,q . This c o n t r a dicts
the d e f i n i t i o n
Claim
D:
Proof:
~ is not
For Xm =
of J
of q - D
El-regular
e a c h m6~, {x 6 J~
element
from parameters
over
J~l"
set
I x is E m + l - d e f i n a b l e
from parameters
in ~ U {q} in
J-}. Y Then
X m "~m J~
is the
largest
and
there
c~rdinal
is a J--definabley in J~
and
map
~ c X m "(i J~'
of ~ onto
Xm.
Since
Xm D ~ is t r a n s i t i v e ,
so
10
set
~
= X
m
map of
m
n ~.
e onto
Since
~m'
we
~ is r e g u l a r have
~ m < ~"
s u pm_ ~< " ~
= ~.
Clearly,
Claim
8(~)
: ~ + i, n(~)
E:
Proof:
By
Claim
F:
Proof:
claims
q([)
By
: q and
completes
Case
2. ~ £ R.
By t h e
unique
B A @ such
°:
J~ ~n
Claim
J~
G:
Proof: o(])
such
so
H:
Proof:
find
now
two
into using
So by
<J m<~
X
= J-,
so we
m
are
: ~ + i, y(~)
claims
= p(v).
lemma
Set
] = o-i(~)
theory
~
~-
= [.
not.
cases
to
so
done.
[]
: ~.
E,
p(])
=
D
in C a s e
([De
A and
].
if ~ < p 1],
A = Ag n-l,
page
and
and 100)
set
5 = ~ if
there
is
a
an e m b e d d i n g
~.
~ = ~ and J]<J
O:
J~
. Moreover,
o(~)
And = ~.
if ~ < p, The
claim
then follows
Then,
o:
J~ is
map
over since
f such
J~. ~ is that
the f[[]
largest is
cardinal
cofinal
in ~.
in J~, There
we are
consider.
first
v, w h i c h G~del's
p(~)
the
that
a En_l(J~)
applying
P,
: q.
o(p(~))
of
~ is Z n _ l - r e g u l a r
Suppose by
C,
a J--definable y
m
Suppose
can
q(~)
p = p n-l,
(oIJ~):
immediately,
E,
that
If v = p , t h e n
claim
is
: p(v).
structure
~ 6 S and
= ~,
Claim
fine
by
there
[]
~ = o-i(~).
~ = p.
J- and y
is E l ( a n,+ ly)
: i, ~ 6
o(p([))
proof
But
I m < w>
implies
the
q = o-l(q),
D.
C and
which
That
Set
B and
claims
=,
<[m
over
that
~ < p. T h u s
pairing
see
that
since
function
~ < @ and
we
~(f)
~ is can
o(~)
maps
a subset
regular code
= ~.
f as
in J~.
If f £ J~,
then
of e c o f i n a l l y Thus
f { J~.
By
a E n _ l ( J ~)
subset
of
11
[, now,
to c o n c l u d e
that
~)(~) D E n _ l ( J ~) { J [ .
Thus
p n-l<~,
contrary
n-i to p~ = p>~. Suppose partition
now that u = p. Thus ~ = ~. In J~,
of [ into [ m a n y
let k ~ 6 J~ be the < j - l e a s t Clearly,
k is a En_l(J{)
= ~ = p~-i Claim
sets map
of A~ onto
function
and c < ~, so this
I: q is the < j - l e a s t
J~ is E l - d e f i n a b l e
of c a r d i n a l i t y
such
from p a r a m e t e r s
~ 6 dom(f),
Set k = U { k ~ l ~ 6
that k[~]
of J~ such
I ~ <~> be a
~. For each
f(~).
is impossible.
element
let < A ~
dom(f)}.
= [. But
[] that e v e r y
element
of
in [ U {q} in <J~,A>.
Proof:
Let x 6 J-. Then o ( x ) 6 J , so for some ~ 6 e, o(x) is E l - d e f i n a b l e P P from q,~ in <J ,A>. Set s = <~>. Let % be a E o - f O r m u l a such that: P (i)
<J
(ii)
<J
(iii)
( V y 6 J ) [y = o ( x ) P
P P
,A> b Vz 3y Vy'
[y' = y ÷÷ 3 u % ( u , y ' , z , q ) ] ;
,A> b Vz V y [ 3 u # ( u , y , z , q ) ÷÷
<J
P
+
(~)
,A> ~
(z = <~>)];
Hu%(u,y,s,q)].
Let <~ be the l e x i c o g r a p h i c o r d e r i n g on L × L i n d u c e d by <j. C l e a r l y J L <~ is A 1 and u n i f o r m l y £ 1 p for all limit p> O. Letbe the <~-least
pair
such
that
<Jp,A> Then < t , U o >
b ~(Uo,~(x),t,q).
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
a(x),q 6 ran(d)
~ i < J p ' A > ' t ' U o 6 ran(o).
t = <~> for some ~ 6 a. By (Vy 6 Jp) Applying
-i,
The m i n i m a l i t y
So as
t ~ j s, t 6 Je.
(i) above,
~ = o-l(t),
[y = x ÷+ <J~,A>
x is E l - d e f i n a b l e
in <Jp,A>. Since
[y = d(x\) ÷÷ <Jp,A>
and s e t t i n g
(Vy~J~) Hence
from o ( x ) , q
we have = 3u¢(u,y,[,q)].
from p a r a m e t e r s
of q is p r o v e d
b 3u¢(u,y,t,q)].
in [ U {q} in <J~,A>.
just as in C l a i m C.
[]
Thus
12
Claim
]
J:
Proof:
By
is n o t Claim
J-
In-regular
"(w × (J- x { q } ) ) .
P,A
In particular,
there
Since
~ = p~-l,
Claim
K:
is
{ = B(]), claims
n = n(~),
By
lim(B)
+
lim(~).)
[]
L:
q = q(~)
and
Proof:
By
a II(<J~,A>)
~ : A ~n - i , t h i s
Proof:
Claim
H and
claims
J.
so o ( p ( ~ ) )
o(~)
:~.
then
That
=
completes
Lemma
Let
p(~).
5 6 S[,
such
Let
~'
that
Case
the
[ onto
~.
~ : p(~), notice
A : A(]). that
~:
JB
~i JB'
so
: p(~). If
: p(v)
~ : ~ and
proof
of
v < p,
by
p(~)
lemma
p(C),
and
suppose
<Jp(~) ,A([)> ~i
~[[].
then
claims
v < p and we
G and
=,
the so
fact
again
have that we
get
2.6.
] is
a limit
point
of S-.e L e t
<Jp(~),A(v)>
: p(u).
Then
v'e
<Jp(~) ,A(~)>
c~J-cd' v -
Set
a < a,
o(p(~))
= sup
that
Proof: =
of
[]
~ 6 S,
o':
such
a subset
2.7
o:
be
map
q : q(~).
=,
from
is I n (S~).
~ 6 R,
o(p(~))
I a n d K,
If u = p,
map
(For ~ 6 R,
p(5)
o(p(~))
J~.
I,
: h-
P
over
S
~i
o'(p(~))
and
and
there
is
an e m b e d d i n g
<Jp(~') ,A(~')>
: p(m').
B : B(~) , n = n(v) , p = p(v) , A = A(m) , q = q(~) , p : p(~) , ~
= A(~),
I. ~ 6 P.
Set
~
:
q(]), ~ : p(]).
y = y(v) .
13
For each m £ ~, set X m = {x 6 J
Y
I x is E m + l - d e f i n a b l e
from parameters
in ~ U {q} in
J } Y Thus X m ~ m
Jy.
S i n c e @ is the l a r g e s t
X m @ ~ is t r a n s i t i v e , a Jy-definable
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
t_] X = J¥, m<~ m
f r o m p in Jp,
so as v is r e g u l a r so S U P m < ~ m
Jy'
over Jy, m m < ~ .
= ~. But for each m,
m
so ~m 6 ran(o).
m. Thus 9' = ~ and the l e m m a is t r i v i a l l y
2. ~ 6 R. JS~ n ~ is E 1 ~({~})
in Jm and ~c_ X m < i
so let Um = X m N ~. T h e r e is, by its d e f i n i t i o n ,
m a p of e o n t o Xm,
B u t by c h o i c e of q,
cardinal
Hence
oil]
m
is c o f i n a l
in
valid.
Case
as
J and S~ N ~ is ~I ~({~})
(°IJ~) : J~ ~l J~ and o(~)
= ~, ~' = sup(S
c l o s e d in sup(So) , we h a v e ~' 6 S Let ~ = sup(o[~]),
~ = An J
by the same d e f i n i t i o n . A ~').
So,
S i n c e S~ is
I
. S i n c e ran(u) c- J
~
, p, ~ £ J q . By
E 0-
absoluteness,
o: < J ~ ' A > ~ O So,
as o is c o f i n a l
<J
,A>.
in q,
Set
X = hn, ~ "(~ x <Ja × {q}}).
Let
~: <Jy,B> ~ <X,~A X>.
Thus
~: < J y , B > 4 1 <Jn,A>.
%
C l a i m A: ran(u) c X . Proof:
L e t x 6 ran(6).
T h e n x is E l - d e f i n a b l e
from parameters
U {q} in <J
in
,A>. Let x = o-l(x). A n a r g u m e n t as in c l a i m I of P l e m m a 2.6 shows t h a t x is E l - d e f i n a b l e f r o m p a r a m e t e r s in ~ U {q} in <J~,A>.
So for some i 6 w, z 6 J~, x = h ~ , ~ ( i , < z , q > ) .
Applying
14
e:
<J~,A>
x
= h
<J~'A>
9(i,). A-
Claim
B:
Proof:
xn
Let
: h
and
setting
Hence
x 6 X.
z = o(z) , w e
get
[]
v : ~' ~ 6 X ng.
Then
,~(i,).
= hT,A~n J
for
Since
(i,)
some
lim(~)
. Since
z 6 J
there
and is
somc
i 6 w,
a T < u with
n = sup(e[~])
we
can
pick
here
T
so
that
T
= e(~)
T
for
some
~ < ~.
@ = sup
=
Set
[in h
T
~ ,ANJ
[~ N h-
sup
"(w × (J
× {q}))],
,,(~× <J[× {~}>)3.
-
T,ANJ-
~u
Now,
AN
= AN
J
J
N J
= AN
J
T
T
, so
h
~ T,ANJ
6 J
@
by
amenability.
So
as
T
< ~ and
~
is
regular
in J
, @ < m.
Similarly
@ < ~.
But
clearly,
P e(~)
= @.
Hence
< @ = ~a([)
Thus Now
XA
< sup(e[[])
: ~'
~ c v' .
let
~ 6 ~'.
For
some
[ < ~,
~ < 6 = e([).
~ 6 j5 ' f:
~ o~to
~.
Since
(gIJ~) : J~ ~ O
f:
6.
by
claim
A,
Thus
a o~to ~' c X N Now,
ran(o)
But ~.
suffices By
~1 <J
ran(o)
B,
<J~,A>
-i~,
now
to
Eo-absoluteness ~:
as
f = e(f)6
~cX,
J
is
, and
~ = f[e] c X .
,A>, X M1 <J ,A>, and r a n ( o ) ~ X .
<1 < x , ~ n x>. s o ,
claim
So
~ < ~ there
Hence
D
e':
By
f 6 X.
J~'
Since
41
setting
that y=
,
<Jy,B>
= ~ 1o e , we h a v e
<Jy,B>.
= idly' , so prove
e'
Hence
4 0 <Jp,A>.
e' IJ~ p(~'),
= idIJs, B = A(~'),
giving and
eIJ~ce' -l(p)
It = p(v,).
~ 6 X.
15
So by
the
fine
structure
theory
n-i Y = PR'~ , B = An-16' ' a n d q,
= -l(q)
,
p,
there
a mapping
z:
-i
-i
=
= e,
Suppose
=.
By
the
-l(q)
Claim
C:
Just
Claim
D:
Then
Js, < n
is n o t
claim
So,
~:
<J
v'
~'.
Claim
E:
Proof:
Claim
By
F:
Proof:
But
8'
2.6
lemma
~
such
such that
that w c_ ~.
Set
~'
q'
over
Js'"
,A> a n d × {q'})).
= 6(~'),
n : n(v'),
C and
D.
Hence
as
.
Hence
= o(~')
it
suffices
to
show
J6'"
over
41 < J
: v'.
= q(v').
In-regular
: v' n h q , ~
p =
-l(p)
2.6.
~'
(v)
= 7-
that
that
-i
Hence
v' < y.
[]
"(~ × ( J
~' c X Thus
x {q})).
= ran(~), there
n-I 871 y = PS' ' B = A , so this
we
is
map
have
a II(<Jy,B>) is E n
~' 6 R, y : p ( ~ ' ) ,
(J6
,).
map
of
[]
B = A(~').
[]
= q(~').
"(~ x ( J
parameters
lemma
B,
lemma
"(~ × ( J
claims
q'
B,
B,
to s h o w
i.e.
claim
H in
By definition,
= h¥, B
from
The
,B>
= ~' n hy, B
onto
Jy
y
J6
6'
p =.
p =,
claim
in Claim
By
by
e>,
Moreover,
is I n _ l - r e g u l a r
Proof: as
using
in o r d e r
as
~'
But
[ : ~ and
= q(Y'),
~'
)>.
=.
And,
above,
that
, -i (~
p'
~ = p.
p'
Proof:
(v)
a unique
~ -i ( p ) .
=
Suppose v < @. T h e n ~ < @ a n d p = < q , ~ p'
is
X = h
× {q'})).
in a U [q'}
completes
is p r o v e d .
the
[]
,~ "(~ × (J~ × { q } ) ) . Hence
every
in < J y , B > .
proof,
u
member
And
an
So, of J y
argument
applying
~
-i
,
is E l - d e f i n a b l e as
in C l a i m
C in
18
Suppose iff for
now
that
v is a limit
all T o - f O r m u l a s
¢(Vo,Vl)
ordinal
and X c J
of set theory,
. We w r i t e
with
X 4Q J
parameters
from
X,
X ~
(¥~)
Clearly,
(B8 > ~)
if X
unbounded
in v,
We w r i t e Define
ole
, then
then
~: J~ ~ Q J~
Jv ~
(V~)
Conversely,
iff ran(T)
~: < J p ( m ) , A ( ~ ) > ~ = p(T)
~Q
most
one ~ y
bedding J
P(~
~:
= h
ran(o) mined
It s u f f i c e s
iff e
1 <J
such
,A(T)> (o~J):
J
~
p(~),A(T)
< ~
and
T
there
is
that
4Q J T
partial
to show
that
= ~. Let
<Jp(v) ,A(v)>
0(Y) ,A(~)
= h by
with
and X N v is
J~.
~ on S by ~ T
and
~ is a w e l l - f o u n d e d
is a tree.
$(8,J8).
if X
'
Clearly,
( B S > e)
.
relation
= idI~ ~, o(p(v))
iff
X ~i J~"
X ~Q J
a binary
an e m b e d d i n g
$.(8,J 8)
ordering if ~ 6 S
~ ,
~
~i <J0(T) 'A(T)>
"(~ × ( J - × {p(~)})),
p(~)
2.5,
the m a p
show
and [ < e,
that
there
= [. T h e n
there
as above.
Now,
is at
is a E l - e m -
so
"(w × (J- × {p(~)})).
T a n d [. H e n c e
on S. We
Thus
is c o m p l e t e l y
ran(0)
is e n t i r e l y
determined
by
deter-
~ and ~. H e n c e
so is ~.
By
lemma
if v ~ T ,
so we m a y
denote
{0 T I ~ T }
and
Lemma
if by ~ T
{~ T I v ~ T }
o which
. Set are
~ ~r :
testifies
this
fact
(a ~T Iv) U {}.
is u n i q u e ,
The
systems
commutative.
2.8
Let ~ T .
Then
maps
S
~ (v+l)
into
S
N(T+I)
in an o r d e r - p r e s e r v -
T ing f a s h i o n (i)
such
that:
if y = m i n ( S
) , then
z T(y)
= min(Se
); T
(ii)
if y i m m e d i a t e l y
succeeds
6 in S
n (~+i) , then V
immediately
succeeds
~
(6)
in S
N (T+l); T
~
~T
(y)
17 (iii)
if y is a l i m i t
point
of S
point
of S
A (m+l),
then
z
(~) is a limit
~ (~+1). T
Proof:
This
following We wish
follows
case.
trivially
Suppose
to s h o w
that
from
lemma
~ is a limit
T : z
(~)
2.1
point
is a limit
(vi),
except
of S
and
point
of S
in the
that
~ = p(~).
. This
follows
T
easily
from t h e
fact
that
where
the Q - e m b e d d i n g
Lemma
2.9
T ~T,
Let
~ 6 S~_~
(g
~J ) : J
condition
4Q J ~ .
This is
is r e q u i r e d .
T, ~ : ~--T~(~). T h e n
the only point
[]
~ ~,
~-
I~ = ~-~T I~' and
g-
(A(~))
T
By
Proof:
lemma
2.4,
-
(p(]))
= p(y)
UTT
~
(p(~))
Lemma
= p(~).
The
~
lemma
follows
= A(Y)
and
TT
'
immediately.
2.10
If T 6 S is a limit
point
of 4, then
T =
k_]
~[~]
and p
J
=
p(T)
Proof: and
t_]
o
v~T We
<X
Iv ~ T >
~:
lemma
o(p(~)) since
X
p(m)
commence
<Jp(T),A(T)>.
2.6
I~ ~ T }
•~
that
Set X = U{X
<J~,A>
there
in < J p ( T ) , A ( T ) > . T)
Iv ~ < } .
~ = sup
for
all
Then Pick
~ such {~
V~T
let X
Suppose = ran(o
Z 1 submodels
not,
T) •
of
X K1 <Jp(T) 'A(T)>"
v-~T,
some
we
we h a v e
Let
with
~i <Jp(z) 'A(T)>'
~6 e
clearly
A = A(~), have
X A JT ~ Q JT"
contrary ~ 6 ~T,
~ = p(~),
that
I~)-~T],
5 in ~ ,
for
~ ~T
of
Thus
[~\~I~ ~ T ) .
X>.
is a u n i q u e
T succeeds
let x 6 Jp(T).
chain
= <X,A(T)N
Since
a T : sup
. For e a c h
is an i n c r e a s i n g
N JT
~,p(T) 6 r a n ( o
].
by p r o v i n g
{e
= p(~).
• = ~- . Thus VT NOW
[J
let [ = sup
Thus
By
vT
to the
(by the
we have
T).
And
~-~T
assumption
above).
x 6ran(o
~£S~.
Hence
x is E l - d e f i n a b l e
and
and
on T.
from
p(T),
Then,
since
This
shows
18
that
J
once.
T is
not Let
~ ~T
Now
]. T h e ~T [J p ( ~ )
maximal
in
~ = sT,
such
corresponding
result
for
that
S
and e
, then
pick
~ 8.
T is
I 6 S
We
a limit
, I > T.
place
point
Given
ourselves
in
of
~ follows
at
~.
8 < e we
show
that
Jl"
X be
the
Let
e l e m e n t a r y submodel o f < J p ( T ) , A ( T ) > c o n t a i n i n g
smallest such
~
2.1 1
Proof: is
~~
o
Lemma If
=
p(T)
that
X n a is
return
to
the
transitive. real
Since
world. Let
a = ~i'
q:
<J
,A>
X n ~ 6 ~.
p(T)
Let
= <X,A(T)
there
and 8,
~ = X N ~.
n X>.
By
lemma
2.6
P there q
is
= o.
a unique
~ 6 S-
Since
= ~ > 8, w e
~
such
that are
p =
p(~),
done.
A
= A(~).
of
S
. Let
~
[~]
Then
~ ~T
and
[]
~T
Lemma Let
2.1 2
~ ,
Then
and
]~'
Proof:
and
Clearly,
Hence
(q~IJ]):
now.
[]
suppose a~,
~ is
limit
point
~'
= sup(~[-~]).
~J~ = o ] ~ I J ~ .
(o~IJ~): J~
a
J
J~
4° J
,. T h e
,. B u t
lemma
follows
is
easily
cofinal from
in lemma
~' 2.7
~9
§ 3.
We assume
tree
use
A New
the
V = L
Construction
above
theory
of
a Souslin
to
construct
on
T,
%-Tree
a Souslin
~2-tree
in
L.
We
throughout•
We
define,
of
height
by
recursion
trees
T T , T 6 S . T T will
be
a normal
N T), and we shall use the members of S N T T T to index the levels of T ~ (so T ~ = U{T ~ ] u 6 S N T)) • If T < ml' TT v ~ T w i l l h a v e w i d t h ~ l , a n d if T 6 S i, T T w i l l h a v e w i d t h ~2" O u r f i n a l
~2-tree,
T,
For if
otp(S
will
~ 6 S,
~ ~ max(S We
carry
be we
a subtree
denote
of
by
s(~)
), w i t h
s(~)
out
construction
the
the
tree
the
immediate
undefined
if so
U{T <
I T E S 1}. successor
v = max(S
as
to
of
~
in
S
,
).
preserve
the
following
conditions: (PI)
If ~ 6 S
N T,
T T will
be
an
end-extension
of
T~
(i.e.
we
shall
T have
T ~ = U{TTy
I Y E S~
N ~}); T
(P2)
T~
:
S(7)
- Y;
Y (P3
If
~ ~,
~ = ~T
and
The position
~T~ (~)
definition of
T in
embeds
~.
T ~ into
then
•
of
~T[T
T T falls
We
T T so
that
whenever
~ 6 Sa_N T
T-~ ] c T T ~" into
consider
three
these
cases,
cases
in
depending order
of
upon
the
increasing
complexity.
Case In
I.
T is
a limit
this
case
we
normal
tree
of
set height
point
TT =
in
~
~)~
otp(S
T~)].
N ~)
on
By
lemma
T such
2.10,
that
this
~ TI~
defines
embeds
a
T ~ into
T
T T
-5.
(to
satisfy
(P3))for
each
~ ~T.
We
must
check
that
if
n 6 S
N T, T
then
point
T T is
of
3,
an e n d - e x t e n s i o n
and
by
lemma
of
2.]0•
T n.
if
But
by
~)--.l~c i s
lemma
2•11,
sufficiently
~ is
a limit
large,
20
D
: zmT ({)
and
the
Case
for
some
result
~6
follows.
2. T is m i n i m a l
There
are
three
Case
2.1
T is
Then
we must
Case
2.2
S~
D ~,
There
whence
by
lemma
is n o t h i n g
2.9,
further
o~T
~-
to
check•
to
check.
= omT
T~ '
in ~ .
subcases
initial
to
consider.
in S T
set
T is
T ° = @.
a limit
There
point
is n o t h i n g
of
for
us
S T
Set
T T = U{TVI~ 6 S
D T~ There
is n o t h i n g
to
check.
T
Case
2.3
There
Case
T = s(~).
are
three
2.3.1
~ is
subcases
to
consider.
initial
in S Y
TT
Set
= T -
Case
2.3.2
Using
the
member
of
~.
There
is
nothing
to
check.
~ = s(~). ordinals T~
of
T -~,
to f o r m
T TV,
appoint and
set
infinitely
many
T T = T ~ U T T~.
extensions
There
of e a c h
is n o t h i n g
to
check.
Case
2.3.3
~ is
a limit
point
of
S T
First
that
note
by
lemma
2.11,
T is
maximal
in
S
,
so
by
2.1
(iii),
T
• ¢ S 1
Hence
~ is
a
a countable
limit
through
containing
point The
T~,
extensions
actual
following of
the
choice case.
countable
ordinal, x.
of e a c h of
the
Suppose
countability
of
and
limit for
Using branch
each
the
Hence
x 6 T ~ we
ordinals
in
b x to obtain
branches
b
T v 6 Jp(~). the
ordinal.
ordinals
X
is
not
(Notice in
otp(S
can
pick
T - ~,
we
T T~,
Whence
important that
TN U)
S D ~ ± in o r d e r
a branch appoint
to
b
x
one-
T T = T~ U TT.
except
we make
is
in
the
extensive construct
use the
21
trees
T T,
J p(m)
in
J
However,
•
case,
T £ S n ~i'
let
p(v)"
to
certainly
the
Q
countable
is
set
disjoint
completes
of
will
all so
'
from
the
only
each
is
in
as w e
that
show
T~
later.)
segments
of
easy
to
pick
branches
of
Q.
this
case.
the
lies In
initial
member
definition
"accidental"
occur,
thin it
be
this
T ~ which
There
is
nothing
check
is
that
b
in
lie to be
x
for
us
check.
Case As
it w i l l
Q be
eventually That
it
so
3.
in
Case
T immediately
Case
3.1
2,
T is
there
succeeds are
initial
{ in
three
in
~.
subcases.
S T
T T = @. T h e r e
Set
Case
3.2
T is
is
nothing
a limit
to
point
check.
of
S T
TT :
Set
embeds
U{T~I~ 6 S
T~ into
=
The only
thing
that
whenever
~ 6 S~T n T and
T T s o~
~T[TT~]c_ T T. ~T[~
n T}.
Now, b y
U{~TI5
lo~una 2 . 8 ,
] ~ 6 Sa
n ~}.
The
to
~ will
be
result
follows
u
~T~
= ~- (~), TT
a limit
point
then
of
S T,
so
immediately
using
subcases
consider.
% Lemma
2.9.
Case
3.3
T =
Then
~ =
s(5),
Case
3.3.1
s(~). where
~ is
~T(~)
initial
= ~.
in
There
are
three
to
S T
Let
TT
= T - v.
Case
3.3.2
Then
~ = s(~),
x 6 T T-D % -
where
Y £ TTS'
TY
D
2). has
are
no
non-trivial
checks
to
be
made.
v = s(~) .
(~ U ~ { T [ T ~ 5 ] )
section of
n
There
Use
and is the
infinitely
~(~) x
=
< T y'
let
infinite ordinals many
~.
For n~T(y)
(this in
each
pair
extend
is
clear
this
set
extensions
in
x,y 6 T ~ such ~T(x)
from
the
to e n s u r e TY
in
. There
that
T T ~.
Now
t
construction
that
every
is
nothing
of
element of
a
22
non-trivial
Case
nature
3.3.3
which
~ is a limit
needs
point
to be
checked.
of S T
There
Case
are two
3.3.3.1
subcases
~-
[~]
to c o n s i d e r .
is c o f i n a l
in ~.
YT
For e a c h
through
x 6 T{~,
let 7-TT(X)
T~ d e t e r m i n e d set
infinite
~ -
by extending Firstly,
by { ~ T ( y )
l y
(~ U ~ r [ T ~ ] )
two further
if y ~
be an e x t e n s i o n
using
the
ordinals
we now c o m p l e t e
the
definition
collections
and y # m a x ( S
in T T~ of the b r a n c h
of branches
) and ~y~[Y]
through
in
the o f T~
T ~.
is c o f i n a l
in ~,
and
if
Y x 6 T s(Y)Y , we e n s u r e onto
that
for
and d i s t i n c t
each from
each
rules
laid
There
are no n o n - t r i v i a l
out
3.3.3.2
lemma
lemma
2.9),
n I ~N
in c a s e
Tu e x t e n d s
checks
X
through
extended
of the b
x
T ~,
above,
is m a d e
containing
x,
and e x t e n d
according
to the
to be made.
and
Let
o~iIJ5
~ = s(1).
successor
Io,I 1 is a limit
o ~Ioli o
b
< ~.
~ ~I,
= ~TI~.
of
a branch
2.3.3.
an i m m e d i a t e Each
choice
~[~]
I 6 Sa~,
~II~
be
= ~IiI
T T . The
I = sup
2.12,
~i = S(ll)" ~I
{ ~ y ~ ( y ) [y
of the b r a n c h e s
branch
Case
onto
x 6 T ~ we pick
that
Let
branch
TT
Secondly,
By
the
~io,
= a-~vIJ~. Choose
~o ~ ~ w i t h
of qo in ~ . point
Let
of its
so in p a r t i c u l a r
Moreover,
~o
~o = S(lo)'
level.
~ioli[Io]
(using
Moreover,
is c o f i n a l
in
n1 1 I. H e n c e Let x E there
Case
T{_.
3.3.3.1
By the
is a p o i n t
applied
construction
y(x)
in the d e f i n i t i o n in C a s e
in T ~i ii w h i c h
3.3.3.1
extends
all
of T for T
. D1
, we k n o w
the p o i n t s
that
~ i I (z)
23
for
z
points
z~
(z)
y' (x)
= ~ 1
(= ~ l ( z )
for
each
(y(x)).
Then
y' (x) 6 T ~ I
= ~ii ~ o ~l(z))
T ~ , containing
dx through
Also,
Let
y' (x),
x 6 TV , pick
and
a branch
for
b
all
Pick
a branch
z
let ~
extends
extend
through
the
d x o n T T ~"
T ~ , containing
x,
and
X
distinct
from
the
branches
d
T -
(~ U ~ [ T T ~ ] )
to extend
The
choice
branches
of t h e
Case
2.3.3.
There
are
That
no non-trivial
completes
the
just
x
these dx,
extended, branches
x 6 T~,
checks
and onto
use TT
a n d b x,
the
ordinals
in
.
x 6 T ~,
is m a d e
as
in
to be m a d e .
construction.
Let
T = U{TTIT 6 S
}. T is
clearly
an ~ 2 - t r e e .
Lemma
3. I
T has
at m o s t
Proof:
Suppose
e2-branches b y N T~.
Let
M be
tive.
Let z(U) that
countably
Let
7: M
otherwise,
of T. Let
the
U =
Let
v = Mn
= Jl"
e 2.
Then,
let
~ < e 2 be
{b
least
. Clearly,
M<Je3
such
Clearly,
zI~
I~ < e l} be such U is
that
81 m a n y
that
~ < T < eI ÷ b
a thin
distinct
initial
N T6
segment
6 M a n d M n e 2 is
of T.
transi-
v 6 e 2.
= id~,
It is e a s i l y
T D ~ = T ~,
e2-branches.
and
~-/ b ~<e I
smallest
= U N ~.
many
seen
z ( e 2) that
= ~,
~ is
U N ~ = U N T ~. M o r e o v e r ,
~(T)
= T n ~,
a limit U D ~ is
point a thin
and
of S
, and
e1 initial
segment
of T ~ .
Claim.
8(~)
Proof:
Since
Jl"
show~ t h a t
We
=
I + 1 and z
-i
: Jl~ v is
n(~)
Je3
and
= i. M o r e o v e r , -i
El-singular
(~)
= e2,
over
I +
cf(~) v is i,
= e.
clearly
and
that
regular cf(~)
over
= e.
24
Let X ° be the s m a l l e s t
X ~l Jl such that6 X, and set
Vo = s u p ( X o N ~). N o t i c e regular
that since X ° is d e f i n a b l e
in Jl'
and v is
over Jl' we m u s t h a v e Vo < ~"
Now suppose
X n ~n+l
Jl and Vn < ~ are d e f i n e d .
Let Xn+ 1 be the s m a l l e s t
X ~n+2 Jl such that6 X and ~ n -c X, and set Vn+l = s u p ( X n + i N
~)" S i n c e Xn+ 1 is J l - d e f i n a b l e
and ~ is r e g u l a r
over
Jl and Vn < ~' we h a v e Vn+l < m" Let X = n<~k-] Xn. xn ~ = SUPn<~
Clearly,
Vn
X < Jl and6 X, and
(which is t r a n s i t i v e ,
Jl is the s m a l l e s t
elementary
and has Thus,
in p a r t i c u l a r
are E l - d e f i n a b l e
By the claim,
submodel
a transitive
we have,
since
through
v>6,
there
U. We o b t a i n
our c o n s t r u c t i o n U N v extend By lemmas Jp(v) T~
U N V 6
contains
clearly,
in p a r t i c u l a r ,
ensures
= 6(v)
[]
= I + i. H e n c e
as
p(v)" in T
contradiction
t h a t only
< X n [ n < w> and < V n l n < ~>
the claim.
p(v)
are ~I m a n y p o i n t s our d e s i r e d
w i t h v. Thus X = Jl"
which
extend
a branch
by d e m o n s t r a t i n g
countably many branches
that
through
onto T
2.1
= vy~
of Jl w h i c h
This p r o v e s
T N v, U N v 6 Ji' we h a v e T V, U D v 6 J
Now,
B u t s i n c e Jl ~ M,
intersection
S U P n < v n = v. But
over Jl+l"
of course).
(iii),
2.11,
and 2.10,
d ~ o ~ [ J p ( ~ o ) ]. So we
d~OV[Jp
can pick Vo h e r e
(~o) ]
can p i ~ k V o ~ V
Moreover,
large e n o u g h
~ is a limit p o i n t
by our above
for ~
in ~ and
large e n o u g h claim,
cf(~)
v [ V o ] to be c o f i n a l
to h a v e =
w, so we
in v. N o t i c e
O
-I(TV)
that if Vo - ~ I ~ ~' then
= T vl and ~
VlV
-I(uN~) Vl v
v1 initial
segment
of T
~Vlv[T
] = TVN ran(~
(because iv)) .
~VlV:
J p ( v l ) ~i Jp(v)
and
is a t h i n
25
Let
C =
{~JVoI~
branches
# max(S
through
_)},
T [ which
that
B is c o u n t a b l e .
only
branches
and
extend
We p r o v e
through
o
for ~ 6 C let B~ be on T$(5)
that
-I(uNv)
ticular
The
for
proof
~i' ~ Vl"
Case
I.
Then
T
~VoVl[b]^ for
v I = v, this
T 1 = S(ml).
YI is a l i m i t
TI
= T2~T I<-]
are e x t e n d e d
2.
complete
There
T2]
are
Since
is true
of the
the r e s u l t cases
), the
on T s(vl) ~i
this
our p r o o f
three
Notice
in par-
lemma.
holds
for
all
to c o n s i d e r •
in 3 . , and
the r e s u l t
follows
easily
from
the
hypothesis.
T I is m i n i m a l
In this
case,
Case
T I succeeds
3.
b 6 B.
on v I. S u p p o s e
point
~ T 2 T I IT
some
will
is by i n d u c t i o n Let
induction
Case
form
all
~ ~ and v I # m a x ( S
VlV are of the
set of
Let B = ~6C BS"
if Vo ~ I which
the
in ~ .
__90 b r a n c h
through
OVl v
-i
(UNv)
is e x t e n d e d
TI Tvl.
onto
T 2 in 4 . T1
Notice
that
T 1 falls
under
Case
3.3.3.1
in the d e f i n i t i o n
T1 Suppose
that
z 6 T
~i e x t e n d s
construction
of T
branches
since
which
bx,
is a t h i n
a branch
, the b r a n c h these
initial
maining
possibilities.
Suppose
first
that
are
all
segment
z = ~
by
eventually of T
-i ~ o V2Vl
a
-i v2 v
of the
- l ( u n v ) , we
from
in J p ( ~ l ) . T h e r e
(x) t w h e r e
x 6 T
By our
z is n o t o n e
disjoint
T2
Since
of the o 1~
are
~ 2~
-i
(Un~),
two re-
-i
(UNv)
~2
T2T I = o
~ 1 ~ -I(uD~).
through
extended
of T
see
that
x must
extend
a branch
through
Vl v
(UN~). form
So,
by i n d u c t i o n
~ ov2[b]^for
some
hypothesis,
the b r a n c h
extended
by x is
b 6 B. H e n c e
the b r a n c h
extended
by
z is
26
of
the
form
~
[b] ^ = ~ Vom I
Now
suppose
that
. ~ ~2~i
for
some
[b] ^
(for this
that
y ~ max
b).
~o~i
y ~ml
such
(S)
and
~7m [Y] 1
7 is
cofinal
Y J~o'
in ml'
then
y 6 C,
~O ~ Y' in w h i c h and by the
z extends
where
x 6 T s(Y)Y
[YlY
case
{y]y
hypothesis
at y,
~ o~i [b]^
z extends
are done.
If
so
induction
b 6 B, w h e n c e
{~y~l (y) Iy
{YlY
(= YY~I
Otherwise,
: ~ oy[b]^
~ z ~o~i [b]^),
and
for
some
again
we
are done.
By
lemma
3.1 we
can find
contains
x. We
to avoid
carrying
assume
that
generality
Lemma
show
that
a point
x of T such
{y 6 TIx
6.1, y}
x along
T already
no ~ 2 - b r a n c h
is a s o u s l i n
as a p a r a m e t e r ,
is A r o n s z a j n .
that
This
however, clearly
~2-tree. we
shall
causes
no
of T
In o r d e r simply loss
of
in our proof.
3.2
T is S o u s l i n . Proof:
Suppose
not.
L e t X be
an a n t i c h a i n
of T of
cardinality
~2"
Let U = {x 6 Xlx It is e a s i l y U
"splits"
seen
within
that x
IU N T6I
~ > 6 such contrary higher
U
~2 m a n y
IUI
= ~2"
(i.e.
z, and ht(y)
U N (TI~)
to the
fact
of T.
that
at m o s t
x 6 U there
as in
lemma
countably
each member
in 2}.
T is A r o n s z a j n ,
= ht(z)) . Thus
exactly
has
successors
Since
for e a c h
= '~I" A r g u i n g
that
levels
that
has
of U has
each member
are d i s t i n c t there 3.1 many
of
y,z 6 U such
is a ~ < ~2 such now,
we
can
extensions
extensions
find a in T
,
in U on all
27
§ 4. A N e w
We need if it h a s
some
Lemma
preliminaries.
the p r o p e r t y
o n all h i g h e r distinct
Construction
levels,
points
that
on a limit
a Kurepa
A tree will
each
but does
of
point
not
level
has
be
called
infinitely
necessarily
have
~2-Tree
distinct
almost many
normal
extensions
have
the p r o p e r t y
that
sets
of p r e d e c e s s o r s .
4.1
Suppose
T is
~3 many
~2-branches.
tO e<~ 2 Te+l
Proof:
=
an a l m o s t
Then
t r e e T ° of h e i g h t every
extensions
tree
there
of h e i g h t
is
a Kurepa
~2
and width ~2'
~2-tree
T'
such
having
that
tU T' e<~ 2 e+l"
By discarding
e < ~2'
normal
all
~2
limit
levels
and w i d t h
~2
of T ° ~
which
e-branch
on T ° . N o t e
of T, w e
such
obtain
an a l m o s t
normal
that
for e v e r y
limit
ordinal
extends
on T °~ h a s
infinitely
many
that
e
T° =
For which
each
limit
is e x t e n d e d
the p o i n t s defines
4.1
quired
and
T'
above,
Kurepa
below
such
that
a tree
trees
3. T T w i l l
We
T° =
element
T'
4.1
which
of T ° w h i c h Since
is c l e a r l y
of a K u r e p a
lemma
e-branch,
<J T' e<~ 2 e+l"
T satisfying
assume
T T, T 6 S, be
a new
= e<~2qJ T +i,
and r e l y u p o n
tree.
and e a c h
all points
construction
construct
construct
section
lies
~ < ~2 n o w
introduce
e<w2<-] T ' ~ + I
s o to t h e
f a c t d o is lemma
o n T e, °
an ~ 2 - t r e e
And
ordinal
of b and
cO2-branches
We
t/ e < ~ 2 Ta+l"
the
tree
b,
extends extend
This
H3 m a n y
Kurepa.
(in L).
all
b.
T has
[]
What we
requirements
itself
of T ° I ~
to e x t r a c t
in
specified the re-
V = L f r o m n o w on. in a m a n n e r
an a l m o s t
normal
similar
tree
to that employed
of h e i g h t
otp(S e
n T) T
in
in
28
whose
levels we s h a l l
index by the o r d i n a l s
in S
~ T. T ~ w i l l have T
width be
N1 f o r
the
~ G S ~ ml
ordinals
in
and
s(y)-y
width
' ~2
(for
y 6 S
for
~ 6 S 1 n ~).
"
The
elemen~of
We s h a l l
carry
T~7 w i l l
out
the
T
construction (i)
so as to p r e s e r v e
If v 6 S
the f o l l o w i n g
n T, T T is an e n d - e x t e n s i o n
conditions: of T ~.
T
(ii)
If ~ T ,
z~I~
embeds
T ~ into T T in such a w a y
J6 S~_N T - and ~-TT (~) = ~'
then ~
T[T ~
]]
that w h e n e v e r
c_ T T~.
T
(iii)
Suppose
T = s(~), w h e r e
~ is a limit p o i n t
of S
, and t h a t T ~ T
is E l - d e f i n a b l e Tm which (iv)
is
over < J D ( ~ ) , A ( ~ ) > .
~l-definable
Suppose
T,~ are as in
Suppose
further
(iii),
through
<JD(v),A(~)>.
Since every
of ~
~,~ of ~(A)
u6B
Suppose
U {p(~)}
idI~
and ~
c l e a r l y have,
u
Define B~JD(~)
u6B It is e a s i l y
~ = s(]),
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
element
of JP(m)
in <Jp(v) ,A(~)>, x÷ , y÷ 6 ~
is
= ~. Let
there
from
are E l - f o r m u l a s
such that for all u , v 6 Jp(~),
~-m~: <JP(~) , A ( ] ) >
iff
~T(~)
~l-definable
<J p(~) ,A(v)> b ~ ( u , y 'p(~)) .
= p(m)
o n t o T T.
over
iff
(P(~))
through
over < J p ( m ) , A ( ~ ) > .
<Jp(~) ,A(v)> ~ % ( u , v , x , p ( v ) )
for u , v 6 J p ( ] )
extends
iff
x , y 6 e-.~ S i n c e =
,A(~) >
and T ~ T ,
T ~ which
and e l e m e n t s
u
p(v)
t h a t T m is E l - d e f i n a b l e
B be a b r a n c h
elements
over < J
Then every branch
and ~
~i <Jp(m) ,A(~)> and IT ~)] = T m
N ran(~5~),
we
'
<Jp(~) ,A(m)> ~ ~ ( u , v , x , p ( m ) ) .
by
iff
<JD(~),A(~)>
s e e n t h a t B is a b r a n c h
b %(u,y,p(5)) . through
T 5 and that ~L~[B] _cB.
29
Now,
the b r a n c h
there
is
shall
ensure
B just
defined
(by c o n d i t i o n that
~-
(iii)
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
above)
(x) e x t e n d s
a point
B on T T.
over
<Jp(5),A([)>,
x 6 T ?- e x t e n d i n g (This
is w h e r e
so
B. We
we
lose
the
TT
full
normality
with
El-definitions
tions
as if they
not be
As
the
Case
~
T~T
rise
to
not w i t h
and we m u s t
"different"
branches handle
so m u c h
different
branches,
though
as defini-
this m a y
of course.)
construction
a limit
T T = _kJ
We d e a l
of b r a n c h e s ,
3, the
I. T is
trees.
gave
case,
in s e c t i o n
Set
of our
point
[TT].
prpceeds
by
cases.
in ~ .
Conditions
(i)
and
(ii)
are v e r i f i e d
as in
TT
section
3. W e
Suppose
then
cheek that
(iii)
and
Y = s(m),
(iv)
where
simultaneously. ~ is a limit
point
of S
, and that T
T ~) i s
71-definable
which
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
qb,t) o f
over
<Jp(x)),A(~))>.
over ÷
o~(A) a n d e l e m e n t s
Let
<Jp(~),A(~)>. ÷
x , y 6 cry s u c h
B be a branch Then
that
for
there
all
are
through
El-formulas !
u,VEJp(,~)
u
iff
<Jp(m),A(m)>
~ %(u,v,x,p(~)),
u 6 B
iff
<Jp(~),A(~)>
b ~(,m,y,p(~)).
T ~)
÷
Pick
~o ~ T
with
x÷ , y÷ 6 a~
. Let
~o = S(~o) " S u p p o s e
To ~
~T,
and
let
O
= S(5).
Define
Then,
u
iff
B 5~Jp(~)
by
ueB~ Thus
iff
-
~J T
o
~T~T
for u , v £ J
<Jp(~),A(~o)>
<Jp(5),A(~)>
B 5 is a b r a n c h
z--V~. [Bs] B
clearly,
through
T~
•
= B~, n r a n ( z s ~ , ) . Also, ~~
[B ] ~
By "
condition
p (5) '
b %(u,v,X,p(5)).
~ ~(u,~,p(~)).
Moreover, ~sv[Bs] (iii)
for
~o
~T~TI~T,
= B n ran(~L~) , and
below
T, let x- e x t e n d M
B- on
30
T .f x
By
condition
= 7-YY (x ~
(iii).
Case There
T,
~TT'-- (X~)
any
T 'To 4T
~T.
Clearly
the
method
of
T Is m i n i m a l
are
Case
below
for
And
2.
(iv)
2.1
three
T is
in
proof
~
for
To ~ T
x extends
establishes
~T'
B on
~T.
Let
T T.This
proves
(iv).
.
subcases
initial
= X~,
to
consider.
in
S
no
checks
T
T T = ~.
Set
Case
2.2
There
T is
are
a limit
point
to
of
be
made.
S T
TT = U{T~I~ 6 S
Set
N T}.
There
is
nothing
to
check.
T Case
2.3
Y = s(~).
There
are
three
Case
2.3.1
subcases
~ is
to
initial
consider.
in S T
Set
T Y = T -m
Case Use of
2.3.2 the
~ =
member
2.3.3
~
finish.
s(D).
ordinals
each
Case
and
of of
is
T -mto
T ~. n
provide
There
a limit
is
point
infinitely
nothing
of
to
many
extensions
on
TT
check.
S T
For use
x 6 T~,
each the
ordinals
branches This
let
In
Zl-definable
over
extensions branches
be
and
this
possibily only
case
distinct
definitions
may, have
more
than
through
to p r o v i d e
arises
we
other
when
extend
branches,
one
than
of
thereby
actual
We s h a l l
of
these
many)
through
distinct
and
x.
Zl-definable
branch
extension.)
each
(countably
T ~ is
each
treating
rather
T~ containing
extensions
some
<Jp(~),A(~)>,
produced with
a branch
T - v
possibility
<Jp(~),A(~)>.
they
x
from
b x on T T
latter
though
b
over
T ~ which
Zl-definitions
is as
associating
branches.
There
branches.
are
(Hence, no
checks
some to
31
be
made.
Case As
3.
in
Case
T immediately
Case
3.1
2 there
T is
succeeds
~ in
three
subcases.
are
initial
in
~.
S T
Set
TT = $
Case
3.2
and
T is
be
done.
a limit
point
of
S T
Set
TT =
U{T~I~ 6 S
N T}.
The
only
non-trivial
check
to
be
made
T
concerns
condition
(ii).
Case
3.3
T = s(v).
Then
~ = s(~),
where
This
z-
([)
is
handled
= v.
There
as
are
in
section
three
3.
subcases
to
consider.
TT
Case
3.3.1
~ is
initial
in
S T
Let
T T = T -m.
Case
3.3.2
Then
~ = s(~)
There
are
q
, y 6 T_, ~
ordinals has
where
checks
to
be
made.
~-(~)
in
3.3.3
= n.
For
each
pair
x,y 6 T ~ such
that
T%
and
T -
infinitely
Case
non-trivial
~ : s(q).
'
x 6 T
no
x
_
let
(~ U ~?7[T~])~ many
~ is
~- (y) TT to
extensions
a limit
point
extend
ensure on
of
now
~- (x) TT that
on
every
M
. Use
member
the of
Tv q
TT.
S T
There
Case For
are
two
3.3.3.1 each
subcases
to
consider.
~-
[5]
is
cofinal
x 6 T~,
let
7-
(x)
be
in
v.
an e x t e n s i o n
on
T T of
the
ordinals
of
branch
through
TT
T ~ determined T
-
by
(v U ~ T [ T ~ ] ) ,
through Firstly,
{~T(y) we
ly
extend
up
to
Using
the
three
further
collections
of
branches
Tv . if
y ~
and
y ~ max(S
) and Y
z7
[y]
is
cofinal
in
v,
then
for
32
each
x 6 T s(Y)Y we e n s u r e
extends
on
Secondly, every
that
branch
through
T ~ which
on T ~, T regarding branches,
as in C a s e
Finally,
we ensure
that
The
only
T,T.
But
problem
T ~ which
Case
3.3.3.2
Then
I 6 S
case we
point
a few m o m e n t s here,
each
is e x t e n d e d
significant
so we
2.3.3
point
we e n s u r e
over
that
<Jp(v),A(v)>
El-definitions
as if they
has
an
defined
above.
of T ~ lies
on at least
one b r a n c h
on T T.
to c h e c k
not
<Jp(~),A(m)>,
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
reflection
shall
i = sup
over
distinct
distinct
through
Tv
TT. if T ~ is E l - d e f i n a b l e
extension
{~y~(Y) IY
the b r a n c h
is c o n d i t i o n
suffice
give
the
(iv)
to s h o w
simple
for
that
the p a i r
there
is no
details.
~5~[~] < ~.
, ~ X, and ~ 5 ~ J ~ T can e a s i l y s h o w that
= d ~ I J ~. And, for e a c h
as in s e c t i o n
x 6 T_ t h e r e
3 in this
is a p o i n t
y' (x) in
T1 which e x t e n d s t h e b r a n c h {x~T(z) Iz
first
x 6 e~ such
that
that
there
iff
for u , v 6 J p ( ~ ) ,
u
Suppose
further
B is a b r a n c h
through
B is a b r a n c h uCB
<Jp(~) ,A(~)> b
and o r d i n a l s
iff
<Jp(~) ,A(~)> ~
~ is a E l - f o r m u l a T V, w h e r e
.
B c- J
of
%(u,v,~,p(~)).
~A)
and y 6 ~
are
p(m) is d e f i n e d by
<Jp(m) ,A(~)> ~- ~ ( u , y , p ( ~ ) ) .
through iff
%(u,v,x,p(m))
we h a v e
iff
that
u 6B
Then
% of ~(A)
for u , v 6 Jp(v) ,
U
Thus,
is a E l - f o r m u l a
T ~, w h e r e
<Sp(~),A(])>
BC_Jp(~)
is d e f i n e d
b ~(u,y,p(~)).
by
such
that
33
We k n o w with
the a b o v e
being
We
t h a t B has
the
not
definition.
one n o w
complete
an e x t e n s i o n ,
to be
above,
let z- (x) e x t e n d TT
in case
ensure
usual,
that branch
T m is E l - d e f i n a b l e
over
we regard
the
above
over
distinct
<J p(~) ,A(~)>
definitions
(this
extension
definition
of B). T x 6 T_
T ~ containing
y' (x)
each
the r e m a i n i n g
an e x t e n s i o n
<Jp(~),A(~)>,
associated
point
For
using
of T ~ has
on T_,
B on T T
through
on T T. Now,
point
is E l - d e f i n a b l e
with
a branch
each
T ~ which
it w,
of T T as f o l l o w s .
choose
that
call
~- (w) e x t e n d TT
associated
the d e f i n i t i o n
considered
in T - V,
Let
let us
every
extends
as if they
ordinals
o n T T and
branch onto
defined
and
that
through
T ~' T where,
as
distinct
branches.
There
The
are no n o n - t r i v i a l
construction
checks
is c o m p l e t e .
to be made.
Clearly,
T =
[J T6S
T T is an a l m o s t
nor-
e1 mal
tree
of h e i g h t
~2
Suppose
not,
branches. branches
case
~2-branch.
one,
this
Define
of the Since
will
exhaust
submodels
NI~
show
transitive.
Set
L e t N I + I < J~3 transitive.
'
argument
sequence
T has ~3 m a n y
as f o l l o w s , such
all
the
~2~2-
that
T has
not need
at least to be o n e -
that
for
I < m2"
el U {T,B}c_ No.
Clearly
N o A ~2
is
mo = No A ~2"
be s m a l l e s t
Set ~ l + l
let N I =
~I = s u p n < l
shows
< b ~ l ~ < ~2 > does
such
t h a t N 1 U {N I} ~ N I + I. T h e n N X + 1 n e2 is
= N I + I A ~2"
n<-7
N
. Thus
NI~ J
and N 1 N ~2 = s u p ~ < l ~3
Set
that
all p o s s i b i l i t i e s . )
Jm3
be s m a l l e s t
lim(1)
We
let B = < b ~ l ~ < ~2 > e n u m e r a t e
following
the
L e t N o ~ J~3
If
and
~2"
of T.
(A s p e c i a l one
and w i d t h
~"
~"
34
Let
Pl:
easily and
We
NI
-- J < ( l )
seen
that
PI(B)
shall
of b~,
Then
"
vl
point
pl(~2)
of S 1
= ~l
It is
Moreover,
Pl (T)
T
I~ < ~i >-
attempt
~ < w2"
= idI~ 1 and
is a limit
=
now
plp~l
to d e f i n e
If we
succeed,
least
ordinal
an w 2 - b r a n c h
we
shall
have
of T, d i s t i n c t arrived
from
each
at our d e s i r e d
contradiction•
L e t x ° be
the
let xl+ 1 be
the
least
in T o not
ordinal
in b o.
in T
such
If xl 6 T i is d e f i n e d ,
that
xl
and
~I+i xl+ 1 { b I ordinal
. If lim(l) in T i w h i c h
otherwise each
T distinct
Lemma For
q
-I
over
the
breaks
sequence
from each
each
of xq,
down.
< x l ] A < w2>
of b6,
I~ < X> is d e f i n e d ,
~ < e2"
then
q
let x I be the
if s u c h
Providing
clearly
So, we m u s t
x I is also
an x I exists;
x I is d e f i n e d
defines show
least
for
an e 2 - b r a n c h that
if
of
lim(1)
defined.
4.2
each
Proof: Pl
extends
the d e f i n i t i o n
i < ~2'
and <x
and <Xq[q < I> is d e f i n e d ,
I < w 2, T I is E l - d e f i n a b l e
Let
I < ~2'
(~) = ~2" JB(1)
and
Hence
set m = ml"
m is r e g u l a r
(by d e f i n i t i o n
= pI(T) 6 J<(l)"
Thus
(with p a r a m e t e r s )
of
Js(~)"
Now, over
But
A(~),
T ~ is E l - d e f i n a b l e
By the
above
lemma
and
it s u f f i c e s
definable above,
over
now
to s h o w
follow
at o n c e
: J<(1)<
J<(1) • But
that And
and
m is not
•
<J
for
can
regular T~ =
T ~ is ~ n ( ~ ) - d e f i n a b l e Thus,
by
the p r o p e r t i e s
p(~) ,A(~)>, as r e q u i r e d •
(in p a r t i c u l a r ,
by the
if we
J~3
<(I) < B(~) • But
over
construction
<Jp(~l),A(~l)>.
this w i l l
-i
T ~ c J p(~)
codes
(iii)),
Q{
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
of the
our
<Jp(~l),A(~l)>.
~(~)) . H e n c e
T ~ £ JB(~)"
over
over
lim(1) , <x
condition
I~ < I> is E l-
same
considerations
show
that
as
o
35
<x
n
lq < I> 6 J8
from now on) We know
(v~)
. It clearly
suffices
to show that
T v, ,
already
that T v 6 JB(v) " Also,
(setting
v = vl
6 as(v)"
= < b [ N TVI~ < v>II
and = pI(B) 6 J~(1) ~ Js(v)"
So it r e m a i n s
to show that
6 Oh(v). Define
Nq',
n < I, from JK(I) ,~l,TV,just
were defined
n
from J ~ 3 ! ~ i ,T,B.
' In < I> 6 J B ( v ) '
(Recall
that
so <m' n
~(I) < 8(~)-)
as Nq
Set vq' = Nq' N v for each
,q < w 2 ,
q < I. Then,
lq < l> 6 J s ( v ) " But we may r e p l a c e
definition
of Nq for q < I. So,
shows
that
(pl IN n) : Nq ~ N q ', and hence
Hence
<mqlv < I> 6 JB(v)'
J~3 by N 1 in the o r i g i n a l
as Pl: N1 = J~(1)'
and we are done.
that
a simple_ i n d u c t i o n
v q = v'q
, for all q < I.
38
References
[Del].
K.J. Notes
Devlin, Aspects of C o n s t r u c t i b i l i t y . 354
Springer Lecture
(1973).
[De2].
........... , C o n s t r u c t i b i l i t y .
[Je].
T.J.Jech.
Trees.
Springer,
to appear.
Journal of S y m b o l i c Logic 36,
(1971),
1-14.
[La].
R. Laver & S. Shelah.
[Mi].
W.J. Mitchell, A r o n s z a j n Trees and the Independence of the Transfer Property.
[Si].
J.H.
Silver,
The
~2-Souslin Hypothesis.
Annals of Math. Logic 5,
(1972), 21-46.
The Independence of Kurepa's C o n j e c t u r e
Two-Cardinal Conjectures
in Model Theory.
Pure Maths. XIII, Part I, 383-390.
AMS Proc.
and Symp.
i~
COARSE MORASSES I N Hans-Dieter
Donder
Mathematisches Universitat
Introduction several retic
Higher-gap
years
transfer
definition morasses Jensen
ago
(see
in
of h i g h e r - g a p
exist in
noticed
L
morasses
that w e a k e r
his notes,
J e n s e n gave
Our a p p r o a c h
son for
treatment
the simple
the
can be f o u n d uses
questions
morass
structure
can be o b t a i n e d
L
This
treatment We
restriction
In addition,
w h i c h do not
the n a t u r a l
rial
questions
some
direct
in
in § 2 that u s i n g properties. gap-1 torial using
L
which
application
the morass
result w h i c h an a p p r o p r i a t e
can b e more
O-principle. one
We also give some
coarse m o r a s s e s
other
to be new.
easily v i s u a l i z e d .
coarse
can get K u r e p a
~-principle
In
just define
the
One reaout
the
is not n e c e s s a r y some proper-
from the axioms
methods
b u t not
direction,
we show
trees with a d d i t i o n a l
prove
result
but we think
that
combinato-
In § 1 we only deal
things This
the r e a d e r
to a n s w e r
In this
applications.
and among
seems
tool
can be p r o v e d b y
of a
L.
of these struc-
seem to f o l l o w
is to try to c o n v i n c e
are
But
for fine m o r a s s e s .
coarse m o r a s s e s
L
that
easily
in
we use
The m a i n aim of this p a p e r in
but a
L.
rather
arguments
different.
of
that J e n s e n has only w o r k e d
gaps.
false
model-theo-
and use its p r o p e r t i e s .
we deal with.
are a c t u a l l y
strong
in [6]. The p r o o f
the fine
axiomatic
in
is the fact
for small
ties of the natural a n d some w h i c h
to prove
is still u n p u b l i s h e d
in § 2 is s l i g h t l y morass
by Jensen
them
and c o n d e n s a t i o n
a thorough
coarse
this a p p r o a c h
axiomatic for
global
introduced
work
structures
coarse d e f i n a b i l i t y
"natural"
This
essentially
BRD
have b e e n
He u s e d L.
just u s i n g
tures.
Institut
Bonn,
morasses
[5]).
theorems
L
a simple
with
combina-
could also be p r o v e d
that
the m o r a s s
proof
38
I.
Coarse Gap-1
for
gap-1
morasses
the m o m e n t
define
coarse
axioms V=L,
have b e e n d e s c r i b e d b y D e v l i n
that the r e a d e r has gap-1
(M0) -
(see
a copy of that b o o k
as a s t r u c t u r e
[I], p.149).
such a structure
in his book.
which
We first
available
satisfies
show
Assuming we can
the m o r a s s
that a s s u m i n g
can be o b t a i n e d very
easily.
There-
we give some a p p l i c a t i o n s .
Assume
V=L.
Let
L
is a model of Y In addition, set S+ =
For
morasses
(M5)
of course,
after,
morasses
ZF-.
Iv~ S I L v ~ v~ S +
~
be
the
Let
S
"there
class be
of all o r d i n a l s
T
such
the class of l i m i t points
is a l a r g e s t
uncountable
that
of
S.
cardinal"~
set
av =
the l a r g e s t
Lv-cardinal
a n d let
S ~v:=C~ ~
=
Now let
~
S+
such
v* = the least
that
v~ S
and for some
~v
in
aVUI,~}
To see Since onto
v ~.
mvUlf}.
set
~
is not a cardinal
Let
M
be
p if
I:
Let
v
and
qv = P v
let
~>v
be
exists, there
is some
the e l e m e n t a r y
M ~ I~v.
Then
~
The same k i n d of a r g u m e n t Remark
x~ L ~
from parameters
such
such a
We define
v
every
qv = <~v "v}
that
Let
that
pC L~
L~-definable
In a d d i t i o n
is not a cardinal.
such
is
= the
v
vg S ~ ~.
of
is as required. yields
Then
v*
a regular
f~ L
submodel
otherwise. cardinal.
w h i c h maps L
~v
generated by
39 The following basic definability Lemma I : Let
h : Lp -----~Zm Lv.
h(~)=v,
if
v~v*,
or
~,~
a relation
iff there exists such that
~v
V,v.
and
f
otherwise.
~( on
S#
rng(h).
Then
~
8 + , ~=~*
and
as follows~
f~L~.
Obviously,
f • L~. - - - ~
f~
= id~
be as above.
So we may set
denote
~=-p
q~
S+~ ~ $ v
~v
Let
such that
o
We now define Let
verified by standard
arguments.
Let
h (q~)=q~
lemma is immediately
We also set ~
f
qv ~ rng(f)
is uniquely
Sometimes
~v(~)
is a tree,
and
Then
HVv = f ~ .
Lv.
determined
we also use
H~v
by
to
= v.
is a commutative
system and
we have
Now let us fix a regular points
in
cardinal
~
and restrict
our attention
to
S + n ~ +. @
Set ~ : I ~ , ~ l ~
s~
,
~:~,
L W
"~
is regular"!
S ~ = I~rll3o~¢ ~ , V ) ~ Note
that
The following (MO)
(a)
S
properties
are immediately
is closed for
verified.
~<~; +
B~ Ca++1 ; (b)
Sa
is bounded
~ = max S ~ = sup(S°~K); S ~C
is club in
in
a ,
if
~
is not a cardinal
40
(MI)
If
vgx,
then
nv~(~ v) = a
Hvx~v=
id~v,
and ~
~v~ ' < v + l " < ' S ~ v
(M2) ¥ ~
and ~ s~¥, ~
fh~V~v (M3)
~v[v<~l
(M~)
~
and
is closed
~vlV~r} [To prove
this,
Choose
~*
in
where
Ly
and
q~
in
in S in
p~ S
such that m
n~(;)
:
unbounded take
<~+I , < , S
= HT~
HgvlV
not maximal
z~
such that L¥~
is regular
ZF-. some
q:
Given any X~L .
-~*
Then ~
by Remark
we find working
such that
Bg X ~ a ~
~
X.
But then collapsing v-4~
such that
(MS)
I~ v IV ~ }
X
and applying
Lemma I
we get
~v = Xna~] unbounded
in
~
~t
=
U v~c
H v'c
v
We now turn to some applications. restrict
ourselves
trary successor
to the case
cardinals
will be discussed
work with
(MO) - (M5). In particular, morass
to arbi-
cardinals
gap-1
morass
defined
which are not given by the axioms
we essentially
use the fact
that our
is universal.
We first
introduce
A V = l~[~vl not a cardinal get
Inaccessible
we
chapter.
the natural
i.e. we use some properties
simplicity
The generalizations
will be obvious.
at the end of this
We shall actually above
~=~.
For notational
some notations.
and B v = Iv[v
Lb
and
For
Note that
v~ 8 +
set
Bv,Av~
6.. is closed enough.
1.
L~
when
So especially
v
is we
41 Lemma 2~
v~ S +, ~¢~, ~
The f o l l o w i n g
SeuS~-~Av,Bv~
strengthening
of
L
~ +
was introduced by D e v l i n i~
[5]. 0 @'
there is a sequence
(i) N
is ~ countable,
(ii) if
X~m~
[~<m,)
whenever
is a
H~-sentence
]m '~ •
#
&<~
is true in
p.r.
C Om~
H~-reflecting
then there is an
s.t.
transitive
there is a club
(iii)
N
s.t.
for
n<~
Let
e<~,.
~4,
and set
Set
C~X~I,
Cn~
N
Which means: <m,,~,(A~)i(
},
s.t. <~,~(AL~)i<
~e now show that a natural s.
~
is true in a structure
[Actually, D e v l i n only requires
moras
closed set containing
)" H~-reflection]
~ #- sequence
~(~) = max(S u[~l)
5(a) = min(S~-(a+1 ))
if
b(~)
is contained
in the
is not a limit point in
otherwise.
By Lemma 2 we have
Lemma 3~ Proof:
satisfies
We have to v e r i f y (ii) Let
some ~Kv
X~ rng H~v
(iii) Let
~ = <~01,Z,(A~)i<
which is true in v~
So~ I
and
~
s.t.
~
Lv
~/. ~
"~
~
"~
Choose
• Then >
Since
is a successor LV
But
(i) - (iii) in the d e f i n i t i o n _ I. XC~
(i) is obvious. s.t.
0 #
be given and let
S
is club in ~/".
-< . Since
is true in
~/la~ "
is a successor in -4 . Hence
H~v
~
~2
Choose
~ ~.
Xg L v . There is
A V -~_v
(*) shows that
is true in in
s.t.
v~ S
of
is as required.
be a
H~-sentencen
there is some ~
: L~ ~
'Z Lv to
s.t.
N
~-v
=
Lv
rng [I~v
we clearly have
" ~ = max S v
So
~
qued
42
D e v l i n showed in [3] that
~ ~
tree w i t h o u t A r o n s z a j n subtrees. the morass gives us a "natural"
implies
the e x i s t e n c e of a K u r e p a
~ e v e r t h e l e s s we shall show now that tree of that kind. We shall use this
fact in § 2, where we shall show that the c o r r e s p o n d i n g = k+>~
has a d d i t i o n a l nice p r o p e r t i e s .
not good enough,
for there are p o i n t s
i m m e d i a t e successors. K u r e p a family. For of
B
(i.e.
L e m m a 4s Proof:
let
gv I m v
v,~
w h i c h have
$
,v~.
~ , 2
F~a
is
Row let T
6~ ~ ) .
Set
Let
~=a~. T
I:~Ig~
T1
shows that
b r a n c h of
~
=
~ = <~,~>
Ta~L ~ So
is an
T U
is an T
~-tree.
Choose
is a s u c c e s s o r in g ~-tree
for
and and
(since g~ L ~
.
~
a.
We h a v e
v~ 8 1 s.t. HVv(~ HVv
So there is some
is u n b o u n d e d in
v = m a x Sa).
IBvlv~ S 1
countable.
Since
ly have
Bv~B~
F =
we h a v e
has an u n c o u n t a b l e branch.
v ~ v s.t.
is a
tree w h i c h c o n t a i n s no A r o n s z a j n subtree.
a<~
T C _ T s.t.
let
~
many
be the c h a r a c t e r i s t i c f u n c t i o n
It is easy to see that
But for
~
I~ Iv~ S
For the first p a r t it suffices to show that
Hence
that
iff
is a K u r e p a
is a K u r e p a family.
tree itself is
take the tree a s s o c i a t e d w i t h that family.
g~(6) = 0
T
v~ S ~
But it is easy to see that
We shall
v~ S ~
The morass
tree for
) = ~
~
and T
.
is e l e m e n t a r y we clear-
gg T
s.t.
is a s u c c e s s o r in ~ , Hvv(g )
Lv
for some
But our d e s c r i p t i o n of
But then
to show
T
above
hence
d e s c r i b e s an u n c o u n t a b l e
~. qued.
As we said before, s u c c e s s o r cardinals.
Lemma 3 and 4 have obvious g e n e r a l i z a t i o n s
For i n a c c e s s i b l e
~
to
the s i t u a t i o n is different.
43 The reason is that we have show that for many the
Sa
(~<~)
[Sa[=a+
inaccessible
to approximate
~
if
a
is a cardinal. But we shall
we only need small segments of
Sg:.
This argument is due to Jensen.
~e first recall a familiar definition. Definition:
~>~
there is some Now let the
is ineffable
A_C~ s.t. ~
iff for every
I~<~IA~=An~I
s.t.
is stationary.
be regular but not ineffable. Let
~ =
= Iv~ S~ I ~
L v, L
~
"~a
Aa_Ca
sho~,~ tb~t c
~_~
be
set
is not ineffable"l
and ~ : ~ , ~ : t ~ ~ t A ~ L I ( ~ = ) . + Clearly, I~[~_~ For
is closed for
S for
v, v~ ~
Let
v
and
hence
Proof:
We clearly have
L~.
v--~ S~, Now set
is club in
~
and
AIav~ rng H~v
v--~v, v~ ~
v~ ~g,
~
~
set
iff
Lemma 5:
and
~. U ~
~
~<~
s.t.
X~
ring H~v,
and set
~=~v"
Then
~v.
So assume
Hpv(~I~) = A~a.
~
L w.
there is a club
We shall derive a contradiction. Since
CC~, C~ L
C = H~v(~), A = Hpv(AK).
elementary embedding
H~v
So we only have to show that
s.t. Then
AB~, ~
C
also gives us that
8
for all
8g ~.
and
~=-/~a"
But the
AnS@A8
for all
BE C.
Contradiction. qued. Lemma 5 shows that the previous arguments go through for
.< . So
we get Lemma 6~ holds i.e.
(V=L).
Let
K
be regular but not ineffable. Then
there is a sequence
CN I~<~)
s.t.
~ ~
Ic
44 (i)
N
is a transitive
(ii)
if
X_~
(iii)
p.r.
closed set containing
there is a club is
C_~
H~-reflecting
It is well known that
~ ~
s.t.
~
for all
~
C~>X~m,
and
IN~I<_~
Cna~ N
n~
is already false for ineffable
~.
IC
So the lemma above gives various dinals
in
L.
Proposition
if
7:
(V=L)
A _ ~ +,
and Proof:
Let
h.
S ~ ~
be regular b u t not ineffable. 2
Then
(vc~ +) s.t.
there is a club
C _ C ~ s.t.
Vm~ C 3 v , ~
A(fv(~):0
and
A~Lv
for some
a<~
set
v~ Sa~ we can define
s.t. 3v,~
v~ ~
be defined as above. For
So by an easy d i a g o n a l i z a t i o n
...., 2
VA~ G For
~
: ~ ~
IAi=Iml
IG~I¢~.
s ~
fv
IA[=~,
= ~A~I_
Then
car-
f (~)=I) Let
G
of ineffable
We now give another one.
there are partitions (*)
characterizations
A(h
(v)=0
now define
f
and
h (~)=I)
s r ---~ 2
V
by
fv(~) 0 Note that given Choose
~
S
~
s.t.
C ~ ~a~l~'~4~. satisfies
if there is no such there is at most one such
~.
A~ L~ .
Let
~
Then
is club in
C
the requirements
for
~'~ ~
s.t. K.
Let
A ~
s.t.
rug H~,~
and set
It is immediate
that
A. qued.
The p r o o f shows that if if
AC~ +,
IAI>_k,
then
K=k ÷
we can s t r e n g t h e n
(*) to~
... +
Actually,
Jensen has shown a long time ago that for
strengthen V~
~-5
morass..
(*) to:
if
~v,~g A ( f v ( ~ ) = 0
A C ~ + , IAl=k, and
there is some
fv(~)=1).
~z=-k 8<~
IAI=~.
one can s.t.
But the p r o o f uses a fine
C
45
For inaccessible Wolsdorf Let some
K
the situation
and Choodnovsky ~
be weakly
A _ ~ +,
IAI=~,
~v~ A
have shown
compact.
Let
~
B
Proposition there
is some
i~2
let
of
stationary"
IAI=~,
V~
A
and
if
intersection
NOW set
W =
~_
and
~ DP and
D
fA (V)'l I~ [ O l ~
let
immediately
s.t. find
s.t. for some
G~ ~(~)
s.t.
IGI~_~
of some enumeration "A G
is
to find some
s.t.
for some
= n IAh( and
A G h
D_CA t
for some
Now observe
is stationary (I),
l
Ai
for some
i,vl
and
~.
w.l.o.g,
satisfying
v~ B,
ACB,
that
g=gD s.t. l)(i. A1v-g(v)
[Ag(v) Iv~ ID-P ~ . D~ W
For
It suffices
D_CAh(~)
IWI_~-~, we may assume
Now given
E~
Then
is stationary
I D = ~v<~+II~-A~ Since
in ZFC.
on the choice of the enumeration.
h : B ---~ 2
IDI<~
s to A
is proved
fv : ~ ---* 2 (v<~+).
some notation.
For then it is easy to construct
IAI=
Let
result
7 characteri-
It is easy to see that the statement
IAh(V)l
(2)
is
i<2
fv(a)=i
Atv = [~<~Ifv(~)=il"
IBI=~,
(I)
GuI~l.
Then there
s.t. for some
and some stationary
does not depend
Now set
and
A_C~+,
_~
The following
be ineffable.
be the diagonal
: ~ --~ 2 (v<~+).
we now show that Lemma
L.
We first introduce
& G
_~+,
in
~
Vv~ E
Proofs
fv
f~(a)=i
cardinals
8: Let
different. Namely,
(see [8]):
and some unbounded
For the sake of completeness zes ineffable
is slightly
IIDI=~ +
for
~
ID
for all and set
that if there is some for every
D~ W.
p~+
GC_~DP , IGI(~,
(2). So we may assume
we
that this
46 is not the case. Hence we find for every ~
÷
(6<~) s.t.
(where
I
g=gD).
I-~
and
No~ set
h : B ---* 2
(see
then
(2),
pairwise
disjoint
A IA vg(v) ~ v~ GD6 ~ is not stationary
B = U ~ID~
there is some
DE W
s.t.
W, 6 < ~ .
Since
A IA~ (v) I ~
B~
K
is ineffable,
is stationary
for every
h
satisfies
too. qued.
2.
The ~lobal Assume
Let
V=L
~a(a<~) ~
T~=
~
~
=
function
of
T~
more
remark
closely.
~v
I:
gB : ~---~ 2
as in § I. Set For
and set
~
T~=
k-tree
By = I ~ l ~ v l
let
~
gv
is a tree
for
be the charac-
Igv~alv~ ~ a < ~
For this we introduce
Let
~>~
be regular
be the characteristic
T = T F = IgB~aiB~ F, ~<ml
and
is called a rich ~-tree
1
and
is to investigate
a definition.
First
T
k
of height
the trees let us
s.t.
ITal
IFI =
(ii)
for all
where let
XC~,
function
_~(K). of
D.
For
BE F
let
Set
T =
iff the following
conditions
are satisfied.
~IXI<:~
: IF~XI ~
IXI
F~X = I~,~,X I BE FI T
be a subtree
is regular. Clearly,
and let
+
(i)
for
~.
be regular but not ineffable.
a~k.
Definition
(iii)
~>~
be defined Iv~
L
Our main aim im this chapter
that for us a
for all
in
again and let
and
and let
teristic
coarse morass
Then
~
of
~
s.t.
has a branch
T
is a
k-tree
of length
this is not a very elegant definition,
where
k~
k.
but it is good enough
our purposes. We shall prove:
Theorem
I:
Assume
V=L.
Let
~>~
be regular hut ~ot ineffable.
Then
47
there is a rich
~2-tree.
In fact, we shall show that for rich.
Of course,
m~T
we now have
m
as above
we have already
shown this for
to investigate
small subtrees
the tree ~=-~ of
ning.
So we introduce
the "global introduced
set
Since
~
this
in the begin-
now the general f r a m e w o r k which might be called
coarse morass in
L".
~e use the notations
in the context of his higher-gap
we do not give an axiomatic Let
is
in § I. But for
T ~.
will be done in a u n i f o r m way, we do not have to fix
T~
S, S +, S , v~' Pv'
~(v) = m a x ~ S I L
~
morasses
Jensen has
(see
[5]), but
treatment. qv
"v
be defined as in § I. For
is a cardinal"~.
v~ S+-Card
We note that
~(v)
can
also be found as follows. Define
<~(v,i)li
~(v,o)
=
by
v
~(v,E+1)
~t(v,k) = SUD t~(v,~)
Then
~ ( v , k v) = ~(v)
if
v
Then and
q~
since the d e f i n i t i o n
~(v)~v*,
in
V , v ~ S+-Card
) v
f : v
~undefined otherwise
lim(k)
is not a cardinal Let
Defini tion,
S~(v,~)
•
We obviously have tees that
= ~f m a x S ~ ( v ' E ) i f
iff
f
Lv.+2
and
of
v*
guaran-
.
f : ~(V) ----* ~(v).
has an extension
f*
s.t. f* =L~. ---*2 Lv*
rng f*.
An easy argument d e t e r m i n e d by f : v ===~ v
f~
shows and
f*(q~) = qv"
that
H~v
(E I) Let
f = ~==>
f(~(~,i))
= ~
v, v.
if Then
= ~(~f(i))
f*
is u n i q u e l y
So, by slight abuse of notation,
V,v.
we do not d i s t i n g u i s h
Note that
So
~v.
f
and
We also set
We clearly have
f(k~) = k v for
f*.
i(_k~v .
and
given
f(~*)=v*.
48 We now introduce another notation. Let
f : ~ ~
~
and
f(~)s ~(~) --~ ~(~)
~
~+ s.t. ~(~) ~ ~(~).
by
f(~
= f~(~).
Set
~ = f(~).
Define
We have
(E 2) f(¥) , ¥ = = ~ Proof:
Since
~'¢v*
we get
~(~) & ~(~), f(<~*,q~})
the claim is immediate.
it is easy to see that
= <~,q~)
So assume
so we only have to show that Then
p~
is the
parameters I~-
from
since
~L-least a u~p~,
~ = v ~.
f
Now if
is elementary.
Then
We immediately get
~Wg rng(f).
~ = v ~.
Assume first that
pC Lv, s.t. Pv
is definable
and the corresponding
Hence an easy argument shows that
~"~v ~.
in
av~_a~. Lv.
with
statement is true for
f(p~)=~.
If
a~
proof is similar. qued. (E 3)
Let
Then
f : ~
~
~
and
~g S ~ ( V + I ),
where
[=a~.
Let
~ .
f(~)~f(~).
Proof:
By (E 2) we may assume w.l.o.g,
we can consider
f~)
.
Now set
that
~=-v, since otherwise
~ = a~, G = f(~)
and
D = f(~)"
Set X = the Skolem hull of
8~[q~]
in
Lv~
= the Skolem hull of
~ulq~l
in
L
By § I, Lemma I we only have to show that But be know that by applying
f,
X~a v =6 since
and
Lv~
Xnav=5
otp (~[n~)-~.
has definable
and
otp
(Xnv)--~.
So the conclusion follows
Skolem functions. qued.
We now introduce Definition:
Let
some special maps.
v~ S+-Card, a~v
X = the Skolem hull of Let
~ : Lp
~(~)=v.
Set
~--*
X.
and
aulx,qvl
in
x~ L (v). Lv~
•
By ~ I, Lemma I we know that
f = ~I~(~).
Then
f : ~ ~>
Let
v.
L =L~. , where
We set
f(a,x,v)
:= f"
49
Obviously, (E 4)
the characteristic
Let
f(a,x~)
: ~ ~
Then there is some we
property ~
and
of
f(a,x,v)
g : x ~
is
~ s.t. a u l X l ~ rng(g).
h : ~ ~-~ ~ s.t. f(a,x,v) = g-h.
In addition,
IVI~I~I+~.
have
We now come to the main p r o p e r t y ion. Let
4~(Ir)JT(p>
iff there is some (E 5)
Let
where
lim(p)
By
Let
We say that
for all
<~(Y)IY(P>
conver~es
l'(P. be a convergent
R(T) = f ( ~ ( T ) ) ( Y < P ) .
Then
-~-chain
(~(T)IY
is
-(-chain.
(E 2)
<
Choose
v.
and let
(E 3) we know that
easy to see that Now let
-~-chain.
~ s.t. ~(I") -~ D
f : ~ ~
a convergent Proof:
be a
for which we need another definit-
(~(T~)IY(P>
is a
H (T)~R(6>) = f(H~(7~),~(~ ) ) f o r , H T)
be the direct
~ s.t. D(%-)-~ q
tary embedding
for all
limit of
y
h :
4-chain.
ycS~p
It is
.
We can then define an elemens "t.
the f o l l o w i n g
diagrams
commute
L q (y),
Ln(T)
But then
,
where
:
....
(U,E~
(U,E~ = LG,~> 8=~--*,
~
y
L11*
- ;
(U,E~
is well-founded, for some
h(:)=~.
8.
hence we may assume w.l.o.g,
We clearly have
Clearly,
:(7)~<~
__q~ rng(h).
for all
that
But then
1~(Pqued.
To illustrate +
Set
We recall
our methods
we consider
~k(~) = ~a_Ocl lal(kl. the following
definition
For
the two-cardinal
a~ ~k(r)
(see [I])
set
v e r s i o n of
® (a) = ua
.
.
50 ~,k
i There is a sequence whenever
XC~
a~ ~k(~),
if
x~,
a
~ x
@ = @(a)
~
sequence
we used to define
and set
x = x(a) = ~ a , @ , ~ . Note that
N a = rng(f a)
Assume
Bna,
then
Let
finable
in
Claim I~
If
We first
a
and
~
~
and let
f(~(6)) Hence
~
~ ~(6)
(E 2),
(E 3)
counterexample.
L + ,
since
~Na~
Then is de-
We shall show
is a limit point of
B na~
S®
X.
® = @(a). s.t. ~
-~
that
Since ~ .
v.
for
®
is a limit point of
We only have to show
f(~@) : @. and
X~®
~(6)18~p~ 4~(8)18~p~
f(~)~ ~@ .
f(~) Hence
Na
is definable ~
is c l o u d in
~
rng(fa).
• Set
be the increasing C rng(f).
(ES). So let
4~(8)~
and let
is a successor f(~) = ~
enume-
So let
is a convergent
-4-chaln by
of the sequence
But then
and
(~(~) I!~P~
is a convergent
-<-successor
= ~
to show that
Let
8<:p. Now
B~®
that
By definition,
(~(8~)~
Obviously,
lal+~-
0
of
We also know
f : ~ ~
~a.
the minimal
where
Na
---~ B o
ration of
rng(f a) ~
® = @(a)
We now prove Claim 2. We have f=fa
@ = @(a)
fa = f(lal,x,w)
s.t. L - < L K + o
To see this, first observe under
and let
be the
Na
be given and set
Claim 2:
~
the definition
there is some
set
and
he the
~
X~®, ~
This contradicts So let
XC~
Choose
a~ ~ ( ~ )
then
~ =
a~ ~ ( ~ )
(without parameters)
L + •
Let
•
not. Let
is definable
B~a
is a limit point of
satisfies
Proof:
and
for any
.
set
lal+m, s.t.
a ~ rng(f a)
emma
X
<
INal ~ B~
be regular but not ineffable.
: min S o
s.t.
there is an unbounded
Now let
We set
of
-~-chaln. ~
be
@ = ~.
(~18~ by qued
51 The same method if
k
can be used to prove
We now turn to Theorem
~ +,k
for any regular
#c,
I which was stated at the beginning
of this chapter. Proof of Theorem Let
~
I:
be given.
We shall
show that
TK
is a rich
K-tree,
where
T ~ =
is the tree given by the family F K = IBvlv~ ~ i ÷ IF~I = ~ • Now observe that in the proof of Lemma 2 we
Clearly, implicitly Let B~na,
showed:
~
~.
then
If
~@~
have to show
a~ ~ ( ~ ) N a.
(iii).
So
For
and F
® = ®(a)
satisfies
k=~
we proved
It is easy to see that it suffices for the tree
(T',
~CT'
-~ )
s.t. <~,
branch
of length
-<
)
is a
k.
Choose Since
k~
hence s.t. ~
S
f
= f
Let
f(T) = ~. ~d TS"
D(8)~ ~8. convergent of
<~(8)}.
Hence B ~
IPl
f
-~-chain by
~--(~, since is a "cofinal"
to show that = kl.
~
has a
Clearly,
let
there is some
~
s.t. k~ rng(f
"
~.
Then
is elementary
~(8)
(E 5). Let ~
L~W
So let
~
f(~(~))=
Clearly,
.
v
I ~Pl
cf(p)=k.
8~ "~
branch
where
for ~
and
T
T
8<~.
and
is a
-<-chain Then
f(~) = p
and
So let
(of cardinality
"
) = m. fla = id~m.
k-tree,
we get
<~(8)l~<~a)
s.t.
<~(8)I~<~>
is a
be the minimal
is singular". of
f ~ = f (a,T,~)
f(~) = k
But there is a convergent
So let
B
For
f : ~ ~
Since
U
v~ ~
statement
~o
L -~ -~ L ~+
and let
k~.
is singular.
is regular,
Set
f"~ =
p
I. So we only
this in § I o So let
We have
p = min
that
(ii) in Def.
to show the corresponding
T' =
k-tree.
Let
We may assume w.l.o.g, Case I:
where
is a limit point of
~
-<-successor "~
~ = f(~). k).
is regular". Then
52 Case 2:
k=p
In this case,
the argument
is essentially
the same as in the proof of
Lemma 4, § I, so we only indicate
the proof.
T, A [ k ~ L v,
is the sequence
~
.
where
Let
~v
"cofinal" Hence
be minimal
in
B ~
A =
~
for some
s.t. ~
is "cofinal"
~,
~k~
SEn~,
in
T
Choose
v~ 8 k s.t.
we used
rng H~v.
where
where
~=~
Then and
to define ~
is
H~v(~ ) = T.
~ = nvv(~). qued.
We now give an application Proposition
3s
H :
Assume
, ~, Let
X_~ +
and
h(~)})
Proofs
Let
~_C~(~).
v = max where
where
g : k
)~
T
has a branch
whenever
~tree.
g t k
Then there is some
Let
Then
) X s.t.
~-tree
given by the
)T by
FCF
having
S(~B,B~)
family
the analogous
= gB~v
be given and let It suffices
where IF[ =
to shows
k enumeration
so that for every
E~) = g(v).
is regular.
v<~
be the increasing
,F
k
h : k
~ = H"[~] 2 .
of length
h : k
and
and
)T
Now let
, ~
~k<~
H ~ [F] ~
H : IF] ~
is regular.
s.t. H(lh(v),
Clearly,
vck
~(~h(v),
of such a
there h(:)~)
is some = g(v)
v<~
We now prove ~
~--tree hence
to find
We define
Define
every
be a rich
k<_~
branch.
all
for
~ =
For then let
E~ ~
= g(v)
Ip<~[Bnp = ~ I .
Claim:
is a rich
iXl=k,
It suffices
property.
~-trees.
which satisfies:
there are injective H(Ih(v),
there
of rich
the claim.
We show by induction
Then the claim follows
~.
So let
IDl
(ii) for
T.
g,g~ T a,
g~g.
~.
Set
by induction But simple Hence
[~
from condition
D = {dom f[f: T0
hypothesis.
tree arguments [
Hence
that
for
(iii) for the rich for some
[F~DI:k
show that
[~a[
8<m~,
by condition
g~D $ :~D, ~edo
if
53
Corollar~: Hn
: [ +]n+~
and
~
Assume
IX I
,
there is a rich [~]n(1~<~)
A-tree.
s.t.:
is r e g u l a r there is some
Then there are
for every YC_~ s.t.
X C ~ + s.t. ~ I X [ < _ K
IXI =
}YI
and
IX] n+' 2 [YI n
Proof:
Let
H
be d e f i n e d as above and set
qued. This result gives a rather general s t e p p i n g - u p lemma in v a r i o u s kinds of n e g a t i v e p a r t i t i o n relations.
For example,
L
for
recall
the d e f i n i t i o n of the s q u a r e - b r a c k e t relation. DefinitionL XC ~
and
, [kv] ~n
~
v<~ s.t.
iff for all
]XI = k v
and
f[~]n ___+ ~
there is some
v~f"[X] n .
The f o l l o w i n g result gives a p a r t i a l a n s w e r to P r o b l e m 17 in [4] u n d e r the a s s u m p t i o n
V=L.
the s t a t e m e n t
(see [7~).
P r o p o s i t i o n 4:
Assume
regular,
V=L.
~_~v~
kv
Proof:
We may assume that
left side is false. corollary. Then
Let
f ~ Hn
T o d o r e v i c has p r o v e d the c o n s i s t e n c y of
Let
n~1.
80 let
~-~
be r e g u l a r and
~(_~,
Then:
~
is not ineffable,
Hn
s [~+]n+~
f : [~]n ____. ~
since o t h e r w i s e
~ [~]n
the
be as in the
give the r e l a t i o n on the left side.
gives the r e l a t i o n on the right side. qued.
Note that we could also treat finite (.
be the l e x i c o g r a p h i c a l
o r d e r i n g on
k~s ~2.
above. Finally, For
g=~
let
the f o l l o w i n g
result was p r o v e d b y D e v l i n in [2]. P r o p o s i t i o n 5: ir rich. Let
Let M =
F~(~)
[gB]Bg F~.
be a f a m i l y s.t. the ~ree given b y T h e n given any
X(IM S.to
[X[~.~, ]X[
F
regular, there is some by
(.
or
Y__CX s.t.
~.
Proofs
or
and
Y
is wellordered
~, •
(Recall that there is no by
IYI = IXI
X_C~2 s.t.
IXI = K +
and
X
ls wellordered
~,).
This follows immediately from the proof of Proposition 3. qued.
References [I]
KoJ. Devlin,
Aspects of constructibllity,
Springer Lecture Notes in Mathematics 354 (1973) [2]
KoJ. Devlln, 0rder-t~pes,
trees, and a problem of Erdos and
Hajnal,
Periodlca Math. Hungarica 5 (1974), pp.15J-160 [3]
K.J. Devlln, The combinatorial principle
~ @ ,
to appear [4]
P. Erd~s and Ao Hajnal, Unsolved problems in set theory, ln: Axiomatic Set Theory, Proc.Symp.Pure Math.Vol.23,
Part I(1971)
pp. I 7-48 [5]
R.B. Jensen~ The
[~]
L.J. Stanley,
(~,G)-morass
(unpublished
manuscript)
"L-11ke" models of set theory~ forcing,
comblnatorlal
principles and morasses, Thesis, Berkeley (1977) [7]
St.B. Todorevlc, Some results In set theory If, Notices of the AMS (1979), A 440
[8]
K. Wolfsdorf, Der Beweis elnes Satzes yon G. Choodnovsky~ Arch.Math.Loglk 20 (1980), pp. 161-171
[9]
F.G° Abramson, L.A. Harrington, E.M. Kleinberg, W.S. Zwlcker, Flipping properties: a unifying thread in the theory of large cardinals, Ann~of Math.Loglc 12 (1977), pp. 25-58
SOME APPLICATIONS
D.
Donder,
Bonn,
In § I, § 2 a n d questions
about
In § 3 w e p r o v e
R.B.
Jensen,
§ 4 of this
partition
OF THE CORE MODEL
Oxford,
paper we
properties
an a n a l o g u e
a n d B.J.
apply
the
of c a r d i n a l s
of Schoenfield's
Koppelberg,
core model and
Berlin.
K to
ultrafilters.
absoluteness
theorem
for
K.
In that,
[10] M i t c h e l
if < is R a m s e y ,
it h a s
the p r o p e r t y .
Theorem Erd~s
Ramsey
there
In § I w e
K be
cardinals
is a s m a l l e s t
improve
e-Erd~s,
are
inner model
Mitchell's
where
absolute
cf(e)
result
>~.
in K a n d
in w h i c h
to:
Then
< is ~-
in K.
Corollary
Mitchell,
2: L e t
inner model
then
conjecture. lative
that
then
I (Jensen) : L e t
Following
We
proved
< be
in w h i c h
we
e-Erd~s, it h a s
use o w n m e t h o d s Silver
then
showed
to the ~ x i s t e n c e
get:
where
cf(e) > w .
There
is a s m a l l e s t
the p r o p e r t y .
to d e t e r m i n e that
Chang's
o f an ~ 1 - E r d ~ s
the e x a c t conjecture cardinal.
strength
of Chang's
is c o n s i s t e n t We
show
the
re-
converse:
56
Theorem Then
3
< is
In
~-Erd~s
§ 2 we
weakly no
(Donder) : Assume
Theorem every
4
Ketonen is
Theorem Then
on
no
Jensen
and
(Since
results,
proving
filters
are
The
main
Theorem
6
a e,
M ~L[a].
B.J.
existence the
of
non
statement
regular
that
and
there
is
K be
an
infinite
cardinal.
Then
(<,~-regular.
result
under
~L H.
Let
on
the
in
K be
assumption
the
on
~O ~.
Our
written,
assumption
proved
Ketonen's Donder of
such
that
2~
= <.
K.
originally
the wake of was
regular
ultrafilter
Koppelberg
paper
theorem
of
( J e n s e n ) : If then
7
e : ~I"
work has
V = K
this on
(K,<+)-regu
vastly
that
result
extended
all
uniform
these
ultra-
regular).
K
a corollary
Theorem
K is
normal
~O ~,
this
K = ~2'
method.
weakly
assumption
larity
As
this
his
Let
+
[ 8 ] proved
(Jensen) : Assume is
Let
cardinal.
IL ~. on
on
the
~L ~ b e
a measurable
ultrafilter
based
there
the
real
in
5
R.B.
with
to
Let
(Jensen) : Assume
uniform
proof
ourselves
ultrafilters.
model
conjecture.
K.
address
normal
inner
in
Chang's
is
3 reads
0~
does
not
exist
but
a#
exists
for
every
I
E3-absolute.
of
the
(Sensen) : Let Then
§
Ba 6 L [ M ]
proof
we
obtain:
1
A be~ (A(a)) .
2.
Let
M be
a mouse.
Assume
A(a),
where
57
§
4 contains
In
[12]
two
I) ( J e n s e n , Assume
Koppelberg's
V
uniform
results K.
Prikry
= L. over
Let <
(Proposition
Silver)
there
is
s.th.
~ < I < < .
These
results
an
ultrafilter all
Let
~ ~ <
regular
be
Theorem filter
on
some
methods
filters been to
on
written,
theorem
to
not
weakly for
strongly is
compact.
all
i ~ ~
Let
U be
.
inaccessible
l-indecomposable
following
Assume
regular
~ L~
cardinal
cardinal
<
for
l
all
and
let
LCH
~,<
~ ~ cfl < i are
Assume
for
~ ~ K .
all to
these
cardinals
Donder
<
two
theorems:
and
let
. Then
U
U be
is
a uniform
~-decomposable
6 ~ < .
cardinal
D.
4.3.
the
regular
singular
some
< which
Koppelberg)
leading
and
0 @ exists.
i < < s.th.
(B.
for
over
cardinals
6-decomposable The
that
cardinals
4.7.
presented:
20).
Koppelberg)
some
are
l-decomposable
theorem
Then
decomposability.
Silver)
regular
is
generalize
on
cardinals
U
ultrafilter
(B.
J.
be
Suppose
4.3.
for
~ ~w
I and
on
decomposability
and
. Then
2) (J.
Theorem
on
work
has
<
results
be the statement
strong
7L ~ Assume
left
impregnable. obtained
limit
and
U be
LCH
But
a result
limit
cardinals.
let
the
that all
a uniform . Then
case
of
since for
U
uniform the
this
is
ultra-
paper
case
ultra-
has
analogous
58
5 1.
Partition
In
Cardinals
in K
[ I ] Baumgartner
introduces
the
following
useful
defini-
tion.
Let
~ ~ e ~ < .
subset
of
such
(Concerning
the
IA[
our
the
the
< ~
then
subtle
It
and
In core
Theorem
M
mention
type
of A.
(i.e.f(~)
that, On
unbounded
<min($))
for
if A
the
Being
a pleasant
f.
is a s e t
other
there
hand,
of o r d i -
~ denotes
~-Erd6s
<~
K.
We
that
countable
there
is
M = L[f].
Since
~
for
is o b v i o u s l y
some
facts
a strengthening
(~)<w ordinal So
and
~ is
the
especially
property
showed
improve
< be
< be
paper
of
least
~ such
< is R a m s a y
a-Erd~s
cardinals
that
iff
< is
that
they
are
inaccessible.
Mitchell
Let
Let
Baumgartner's
< is ~ - E r d ~ s .
following
such
a closed
D is h o m o g e n e o u s
us
to
a limit
therefore
model
necessary.
order
reader
d is
[ 10]
The
model
is
l.l:
let
relation
if
<-Erd~s.
~ e and
cardinals.
partition
(~)<~,
C is
o f X).
Conversely,
the
the
iff w h e n e v e r
• < is r e g r e s s i v e
notation
refer
e-Erd~s
IDI
that
cardinality
about
~-Erd~s
f:[C] <~
denotes
We
of
is
< and
is a D ~ C
nals,
<
this
~-Erd~s
example ~l-Erd~s
< is
that
an L - g e n e r i c is c o u n t a b l e
cf(~)
shows
~-Erd~s
cardinals
are
Ramsay
Then
~-Erd~s
in
to:
and
and
Ramsay
that
set
> ~.
some
~ = w~.
in M b u t
not
collapsing
~ is
assumption We
construct
in K M. map
in M a w e l l - k n o w n
about
f:~
an
Since~L(e) , ~.
argument
in K.
~ is inner is
Let due
to
59
Silver
yields
that
ric extension
o f L.
It is w e l l - k n o w n reformulated that
this
Therefore
that
can
in M.
of
for
I ~ < is a g o o d
8 <<
relation
~-Erd~s
L e t A I , . . . , A n c < and
KM = L b e c a u s e
be a-Erd~s
indiscernibles
a l s o be d o n e
= C~I LB [ ~ ] for
But
~ cannot
the p a r t i t i o n
in t e r m s
Definition. ~B
< is a - E r d ~ s
set
for
<
M is a g e n e -
in K M.
, (a)<~ c a n b e
structures.
We
show now
cardinals.
Ol=
6 ,~ > ,
.
set o f i n d i s c e r n i b l e s
for O~ (or g o o d
for (}/) iff
for all ¥ 6 I: (G i) ~ y
< C~
(G 2)
I-y
is set o f
Lemma
1.2:
Let ~ ~ e be a limit
model
~=
type
Let
< be a - E r d ~ s .
T h e n C is c l o s e d of t h e
formulas
parameters
ordinal.
a good
< is a - E r d ~ s
set of
indiscernibles
that
f([$,~})
numbers
= O,
if
and otherwise
. Then
in <. L e t
for
a counterexample.
II = a
G i v e n Ot as a b o v e
unbounded
from X have
gives
6 ,~ > h a s
for
iff e v e r y of o r d e r
~.
Proof:
such
indiscernibles
Let
I is g o o d
The opposite
I qC
. Define
the
is t h e
same
be homogeneous
f:[C] <~ --~ <
type
number
with
over
of a f o r m u l a
for
f such
which
that
for Cry.
direction
It is n o w c l e a r is a s t r e n g t h e n i n g
f({~,~})
< ~ }"
for X £ C formulas
than ~
realize
{X < < [ ~ X
I B < <> b e an e n u m e r a t i o n
such that
less
$,~
< ~
set C =
that
is o b v i o u s .
the
of Theorem
following
i.i.
indiscernibility
lemma
60
Lemma Let
1.3:
I be g o o d
that
I'
Proof:
is good
in 0%.
6 E OZ
that
~y
{(~
Using
for
we
This
, 6 , D N <,A>.
there
is I' 6 K such
y 6 I is i n a c c e s -
is a m o d e l
of ZFC.
y E I and n < w
to the
y < Y1 < .... < Y n
so ~ny
'r in the
as
follows.
set of x E % +
which
are
in y U { y , y l , . . . , y n ]
' Yi 6 I.
= C~6 (y,n)
replace
for a 6(y,n)
" CO%-definable"
definition
above
where
by
Yn+l 6 I , Yn+l > Y n "
yields (i) ~ n
6
O~ n+l Y
Y Set
each
that OZ
from parameters
see t h a t we can
. Then
arguments
of OZ
OZy--n is t r a n s i t i v e ,
(GI)
> w
. Set ( ~ =
(6+)Oz.
(~-definable
Clearly,
cf(IIl)
it f o l l o w s
restriction
where
[A] c K
I cI'
O~y--n ~ y +
= the
L
indiscernibility
~+ =
models
~ny
that
for O% and
Since
set
We d e f i n e
such
for OL such
By s t a n d a r d
sible
For
Let A ~ <
C~y =
Czy--n . It is o b v i o u s
U
that
n<w
Let h ~
(i 6 w) be a c o m p l e t e
set of d e f i n a b l e
Skolem
functions
for
O~
1
Since
n YY'
I
satisfies
--n : CZy
(G2)
~ ~ n y~|
(h
~
as
parameters
for from
define
for y ~ y'
(7,y,yl,.
where Arguing
,
we can
..
elementary
by:
,yn )) =
h.m~ 1
$ < y ~ y' < y l ..... Yn
(i) we I. N o w
see
that
set ~yy,
embeddings
n
(7 ' y
,
'Yl
' " "
"'Yn )
' yj 6 I
6 (~Z and is O Z - d e f i n a b l e y7' = nE~ ~_] ~ YY' n U s i n g (2) we get
in n+3
.
81
(3} ~yy, :~.y It is c l e a r
that
J
for
on y in < ~ y
, Uy >
is o b v i o u s .
and ~yy, (y) = y'. N o w d e f i n e
~ y
y 6 ~yT, (X)
=
is n o r m a l
and < ~ y Normality
~ y = id
yy'
X 6 U7 (4) Uy
f~ ~,,
, Uy >
is a m e n a b l e
To p r o v e
y < y'
.
amenability
set U n = U
•
T
It s u f f i c e s
to s h o w t h a t U n 6 ~ But this T Y" O Z - d e f i n a b l e from ~yy, and U nY 6 0 ~ y ÷ .
Since
that z yy'
~
7,
: < ~
N O W set <%,
, Uy, >
< < o Z y , Uy >
Y
is i m m e d i a t e
since U n is Y
n = U ny, of U n is u n i f o r m we get ~yy, (Uy) Y is c o f i n a l we have:
the d e f i n i t i o n
So o b s e r v i n g
(5)
N ~n Y
, Uy>
,
T* = sup I ,
, < ~yy.
, ,
U
, >
I* = I U {y*}. C l e a r l y , O~y, ~ O ~
[ y £ I >
I Y 6 I > , < Zyy,
since ef(IIl)
<~
be the d i r e c t , y,y
_ y' ]y <
> e, and m a y t h e r e f o r e
(3) - (5) go t h r o u g h
. Let
l i m i t of
6 I > . ~y.
is w e l l
be t a k e n as t r a n s i t i v e .
founded, It is
clear
that
for y,T' 6 I* .
<~T'
U U U Let M Y = J T = ~{ j Y [ j T 6 ~y} for y 6 I* ~X ~+i Uy Uy > is r u d c l o s e d we see t h a t J ~ 6 ~y implies
Since Uy J ~ + l ~ O~y
So MY
is a p r e m o u s e
We n o w show:
and we k n o w M T c
~7
' M7
~ ~Y
(6) M Y is i t e r a b l e .
Noting
t h a t ~yy,
iterable.
This
r M Y : MY ----~o M Y*
in t u r n w i l l
follow
it s u f f i c e s f r o m the
to s h o w t h a t M Y* is
fact t h a t U
is Y*
e-complete.
But this
is c l e a r
since
cf(y*)
> ~ and:
62
X 6Uy~
Our
next
.
aim
~ X 6 ~y
is to s h o w
(7) ? (y) D
and
that
M Y { ~n
3 y< y*
I -yc_X
(gZy 6 M Y
for
. We n e e d
first:
y 6 I ,n <
Y Suppose model
not
of ZFC
is a l e a s t But My
and
then
set
satisfying
T < <
such
T 6 ~y
= J U8
6
,
It s u f f i c e s
N ~y
by
~
(y) fl J T + l
~y
< OZy+
c_ ~
this
, since
T _>y
such
Let N 8 be the
that
be the m o u s e iteration
get a 6 M.
T h e n ?(y) (7).
a 6N.
Using
= ~(y)
proves
(8) let
Clearly,
to
So a s s u m e
we m a y
assume
Hence ~y
~y
N M 0 c_~(y)
we be
are the
ready least
order
since
~(Y)
formulas
and
n
such
that
n N O c N c_ Ozy--n , w h i c h
~ < By
Then,
Let
at a
N 6 ~y
8 > <
satis-
is a b s o l u t e
N 6 (~7+
assume
IN to a r e g u l a r
Since
t h e n (~
of m o u s e
we m a y
to f i n i s h
, hence
+l
iterable.
But
is a m o u s e
M@ c_ N 8 a n d c h o o s e
= O~,
Y of a s u b s e t
there
D ~y
. let M 0
8 . T h e n M@ c N 8 or N@ c M 8. If N 8 c M 8 ,
~yy, ( ~ y )
Ny = j U y
the n o t i o n
~ C~y+ of
(y)
a ~L.
B < T < y+
N 6 (~6y--n contradicts
(8).
Eventually,
map
So let a 6 ~
there
and
y 6 I
iteration
of M Y
N MY
This
Since
B 6 ~y
D MY
for y 6 I.
~l -< Y~ < < "
" Clearly,
observation.
for
Since O g is a
in L [< . H e n c e
an e a r l i e r
(y)
iterability,
normal
f~yn
~
• Hence
ZFC + V = K + V • L . M o r e o v e r
in 05
we
that
since
to s h o w
D L~M Y
fies
V = K, U 6 0 L is not
, contradicting
(8) ~ ( y )
~(y)
B = By , U = U nY . T h e n M Y = J ~ .
of y o n t o
< ~i I i < ~ > for (~.
NY .
the p r o o f
such
~yy, (~y)
= ~y, .
fl j U y ~ J~Y ~+i Hence
Set
there
methods
is a
Z l(NY)
since
it is
'
N Y is a m o u s e ,
be a r e c u r s i v e
By s t a n d a r d
that
of L e m m a 1.3. U O~y 6 J~+l ¥ "
enumeration (cf.
the
of the proof
of
first
63
Lemma and C~y
1.2),
if ~
By
one
v 6X i Y
, ~
~i(~'~)
the
for
Now
I'
set
f o r C Tt,
~
=
' (]rAy b
< ~>
X i 6 N Y such Y
that
Xi £ U Y Y
, < ~ >
6 [ X i - ~ in Y
, then
~ i ( ~' T%) "
choice
i i~< ~ X Y*
is
O~y~
we
"
have
Then
~
OZ.
a mouse.
So
Before is
and
choose
Zyy,(X$)
=
X y, i
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
y < y'
since
N Y~
canonically
< v
canonical
y 6 x y, i
since
may
But
I'
and was
I' 6 K is
proceeding
a natural
I ~I'
further
prewellordering
is
defined
the
let
of
I'
the
set
us
good
for
OZy~
from
N Y*
and
we
were
remind
mice
is
hence
N Y*
£ K,
looking
for.
reader
that
the
which
,
defined
there
as
follows
M
It
is
~ N
shown
iff
in
M 8 6 N8
[4
] that
where
~
@ >M,N
restricted
is
to
regular.
the
core
mice
is
a well-
ordering. We
often
use
Let ~
(¥)
M
D
Our = K.
(cf.
the
HM
= KM
<
K
for M
where
aim
a mouse
proof and M.
of HM
simple
M,N
every
=~(y)
next
Call
following
~ N,
D M c N
Then~(y)
V
the
are
y ~ ~,T
fact.
mice
at
To
prove
.
D
M@
c
is
to
describe
M
at
~(y)
4.9
~
Moreover
ZF.
in
K
Lemma
inner
be
an
inner
let
8 > ~,T
is
1
Then be
regular.
of
if an
which
It
M
is
is
satisfy
easily
seen
critical,
iterative
of
M
then at
M,
. Hence
model
models
H M< 6 M .
that,
if M. '
W
this
iff
M.
HM < H i <
Let
all
[ 4])
<. , t h e n H i £ M. and ±
1.4.
respectively.
n N e c N.
< critical
Lemma
<,T
ZF.
~J H I i 6 0 n ~i
is
an
inner
Suppose
KW
% K.
Let
N
84
be
the
Then
4-1east
N
is
core
critical
mouse and
such
Kw
=
that
~J i60n
N{
H 1
W. where
'
N
are
the
~ L and
let
A6~(K
that
M.
i
iterates
of
N
a t K.. l
Proof: (I)
We
first
show:
~ (Ki) N K W c iN _
This
is
there
clear,
is
if K W
a mouse
M6
= L. KW
So
at
assume
a T > <. --
KW such
A6
Since
i) D K W . T h e n M~N,
we
get
1
A6N.. 1
H Ni c K W Ki-
(2)
Let
H Ni
a6
and
let
JU . A s s u m e
Ni =
w.l.o.g,
acy
Ki
a~ and
L.
Then
a6
Z
for
some
y < K.
-
a6 (M)
3U.~+I - sU~ f o r (see
[4
],
some
K.I < ~ < ~"
Corollary
But
and
i
then
5.2.1).
But
M4N,
critical.
Let
Ac<
M
= 3y
hence
is M6
a mouse K W which
W
implies
It the
A6
a 6 KW . This
remains
bounded
to
proves
show
subsets
N.
But
by
As
a corollary
that
of
(2) w e
N
is
K which
know
of
(2).
that
Lemma
are A6
1.4,
in
N.
K W . So
we
It A6
get
is N
the
recursively
enough
follows
to
show
from
following
code that
(I).
result
of
Mit-
chell.
Lemma
1.5:
Assume ~)
L e t ~ (~)
~(~).
such
Then
be
we
a
can
formula define
such an
that
inner
ZFI- V ~
model
W
(~ (~) - - - ~ < ~t~)). = W~
(uniformly
in
that
(a) ~ ( ~ )
holds
in W
(b)
If Q
is
inner
(Hence
W
the
Proof:
If
is
there
an
smallest
is
model inner
a critical
and ~(~) model
core
holds in w h i c h
mouse
in Q, ~(~)
N such
then
W
= WQ
holds).
that
~(~)
holds
in
65
N.
~]
i60n
H Ni
set
<.'
ih6i0 n
W =
H K 'i
set W
= K.
Corollary inner
The
now
Chang
conclusion
1.6:
model
We
Let
turn
~=
= ~I"
to
an
the
Silver
N is
the
~-least
such.
Otherwise
with
that
Chang's
this
and
an
~-Erd@s
be is
the
Then
there
is
a smallest
~-Erd~s.
of
the
indiscernibility
strong
two
cardinals
~A',B',...~
of
of C h a n g ' s
cardinal. implies
On
the
assumption
the
length ~'
with
= ~I
conjecture
other
lemma.
conjecture.
countable
such t h a t
~ ~
consistency
the
cf(~) > w.
a structure
w1-Erd~s
that
and
application
conjecture
show
immediate.
following
there
proved
is
< is
Then
a model
r be
in w h i c h
proposed
Let
where
1
1
hand
and
~ = w2, ~'
= ~.
starting Kunen
from
showed
existence
of O #.
We
strengthen
in S i l v e r ' s
result
cannot
be
weakened.
Theorem
1.7:
Assume
~-Erd~s
in K.
Proof:
Let
A6~(~)
a good
set
of
fice,
Chang's
N K
and
conjecture.
set
indiscernibles
since
there
will
then
<+
(<+)K
and
choose
0[=
<
Let
,£,DNK,A>.
for O t h a v i n g be
such
< = ~2'
It
order
a set
e = w1"
is o u r
type
in K b y
6.
the
Then
aim
This
< is
to
find
will
suf-
indiscernibility
lemma.
Let choose
a set
countable jecture
=
Ec p such -
cardinals there
is ~ ' ~
that
in L [ E ] . P ~such
p < ~+ such K
cL
p-
Set
p
[E]
t h a t 016 KQ
and
~ =
6,<
are
[E],E,K P
t h a t ~'
= ~I'
and the
,Dp>.
K < K ~+" P first By
two
un-
Chang's
P e n~'
Then
is c o u n t a b l e
and
con-
6B
6 ~'.
L e t b':
~-~
~
where ~
a n d b' (~) = ~ .
Our
choice
b' (e) = <. S e t
~ = ~ n ~'.
s e t b = b' ~K. C l e a r l y , For
later
We
Case
K
=
two
transitive.
of E p r o v i d e s so ~ is the
b:---~
use, n o t e t h a t ~ = < K A K
consider
I:
is
Let ~ =P
that
first
e n ~
is t r a n s i t i v e
point
moved
b y b'.
and
Now
. ,SN~,A>
where
Ac_ ~ a n d b: ~ - - ~
~.
cases.
K_.
P S e t ~ = s u p b"s theorem the
of
first
[4 ] s h o w s point
by another
on e. B u t
can be
iterated
~6 K~L[U<] ~.
Case
2: K # K-. P
Then
there
would
first
in MS,
K, w e
( +)L[U] U
normal
that
N 6 K,
In a d d i t i o n ,
hence
since
8 for
also
get ~7£6.
b(~)
for ~.
for ~ of o r d e r
type
But ~,
that
since
@ > 5. B u t also know
@ large
points
( + ) K < <. H e n c e
U
K. B u t
since
then
of o r d e r
iterate
is a m o u s e
b: K---~m K +. <
union
o f the m i c e w h i c h
iteration
that
e is the
points
of
largest
M6 K
enough.
is a g o o d
b: ~ - - g Z w O .
S o we
AM, 6
B u t t h e n ~ 6 M~.
of M up to ~. T h e n
then b"C
Hence U
otherwise
the
L[U]
But
with
on
= <. S o w e h a v e
M e for
iteration
=
the ~ - t h
K is t h e
in K. W e
in K,
C of C is g o o d
cernibles
mouse
KcM
~ is r e g u l a r .
set of i n d i s c e r n i b l e s
M@ K such
for e v e r y
let C = C M ~ be the
segment
a good
with
So a
K ---}El K.
an i n n e r m o d e l
show that M6 K s • Recall
of K. H e n c e
cardinal
Since ~6 Now
has
is t h e n
U
to a ~:
to e, w h e r e
to see t h a t
to <, y i e l d i n g
g i v e M 6 K.
regular
regular
[ 3 ], t h e r e
it is e a s y
that N ~M
are e l e m e n t s M are
of
is a c o r e m o u s e
at a y < 5- W e
which
b y b is t a k e n
certainly
type
----~i K ~ c o f i n a l l y .
K
t h a t b ° c a n be e x t e n d e d
moved
theorem
normal
observe
a n d b ° = b ~K . T h e n bo:
some
final
s e t of i n d i s -
67
§ 2
Regularity
We Let
first
U be
quence
such is
for
6 U
for
have
U
Let Then
f"YcT
W6
definitions.
I~ £ X > s u c h U
is
u
all
some
cardinal
< y
for
closed
U and
X
6 U
this,
define
for
m 6 X.
unbounded
~ < <.
U
W
for
It
is
subsets
=
f:
of for
{~ 6 W I ~
there
normal
< ~
clear
In
weakly
= sup
U
bounded
a weakly
addition, normal
we
U:
{~ < ~ I d 6 X ~ } } .
W 6 U.
To ~ U,
see f is
regressive
{~If(d)
< y} 6 U.
f:
W ~
mod But
U.
then
< by
f(e)
= sup
Hence
there
is
Y D X
= ~ which
{~ < a l e 6 X
y < < such
}.
We
now
state
statement
Theorem weakly
weakly
Assume
normal
a uniform
contradicts
X
non
is
theorem no
model
on
chapter.
with
a regular
ultrafilter
on
< is
(y,K)-regular
Ketonen
(<,
showed
<+)'-regular
Assume
I L ~.
(see
<
is
[ 6 ])
ultrafilter
with
Let
the
same
< > ~ be
(<,<+)-regular.
Let
cardinal.
that on
nL ~ abbreviate
a measurable
< be
+ ultrafilter
this
Let
ultrafilter
2.2:
of
inner
6 U. T
~L ~.
and
normal
Corollary
main
"There
2.1:
Kanamori
the
Assuming
that
T
the
is
iff
< is
that
<.
se-
~ 6 X and
iff
is w e a k l y
principle
Set
a regularity
c_~
u
function
T < u).
diagonalisation
By
(y,<)-regular
(mod U)
Y 6 U,
u.
X c_~ ,
that called
regressive
for
following
Ultrafilters
a regular
q < <.
every
contains
the
on
all
of
familiar
satisfying
and
(i.e.
normal
Y =
mean
a sequence
U
some
ultrafilter U we
uniform
mod
Normality
recall
an
{ v l q 6 u v}
and
for
if
a cardinal.
Then some
every
~ < <.
< > ~ and
<+ , then
property.
cardinal".
there
< + carries
Hence
Then
we
is a
get:
every
uniform
68
In
[8]
Ketonen
O ~ does filter into
not can
two
exist. be
itself.
actually
get
need
used We
new not
Theorem
He
showed
to
find
make
such
entirely
lemma
proved
an
under
that
an
the
stronger
irregular
a non-trivial
elementary
use
of
his
ideas
embedding
for
K.
But
we
arising
true
for
from
K and
the
we
assumption
weakly
extensive
cases
be
2.1
facts
cannot
ultra-
embedding
to
also
normal
show have
that
exclude
of
that to
that
we
L can
consider
the
condensation
the
possibility
(K+) K = K +.
Proof
Let
of
Theorem
K be
which
a regular
is
not
shall
show
We
first
remark
~(<)
tions tary
N K
f 6 K)
that
with
6.12
such
now
sential
carrying
it
for is
of
the
of
[ 4].
So
to
find
some
of
this
a theorem
with
of
several
K by
V
us
[ 3]
sets Set
each
a system
the
whole
K < m < K
IK < m < < + > {T <
ultrafilter
(restricted
M.
there
But is
of
structures
and
to
an
M
Q~
the
in
K
model
is
es-
code
the
proof.
pick and
IK
which
and
DN
f
Y
mapping
<
onto
m.
_Ac
Let
+ <
~+ T
[A],ANT>
~
~ < < set
_0
}.
Then
E
is
+ unbounded
= K by
inner
. For
smallest
QW
T 6 E, QT
such
that
e~Q.
=
>
and
V
func-
elemen-
then
embeddings
+ For
cardinal.
a non-trivial
class
U
cases,
a measurable
a non-trivial
gives
transitive
ultrafilter
Considering
model
ultrapower For
by
y < <.
normal
cardinal.
build
for
into
a weakly
inner
suffices
that
K
any
an
is w e l l f o u n d e d .
a measurable
We
there
that
embedding
Lemma
cardinal
(y,K)-regular
we
over
2.1
closed
6g Then
C T := {~ <
= < N Q~
x 6 Qy { e 6 C Ix6 Q~}
is a final
~Y:
QY ~ ~T
Finally
where
set T
We o f t e n
of C~.
Q~ is t r a n s i t i v e .
Q~
= O n ~ Q~, K T~ = K ~ and T~ : ~ T ~ K T. H e n c e
use the
= ~IQ~e
To v e r i f y
(hence K ~ =
this
The
so the rest
following
2.3:
{a£WN
6 Q~
Qn"
Since
every
Q < Q
in QT
from ~, hence
is u n i q u e l y
= ~Te n Q . But ~T~ is an end e x t e n s i o n
deterof
is a key e l e m e n t
in our proof.
there
is T 6 E such that
}6 U.
-
Suppose
Proof:
that Qn is d e f i n a b l e
+ Let W 6 U, f 6 6~T W = ~ . Then
T
(~)-I(Q)
is clear.
sublemma
C If(a) < T
YT : { ~ 6 W ~ C T Our e a r l i e r gT~ h a s
regressive,
not. IT
For ~ 6 W let h
< f(~)}
Fact
shows
and define
that
inject
f(e)
gT 6 6T~T~ by gT(~)
the gT are p a i r w i s e
< many p r e d e c e s s o r s
(mod U) gT~
in fact gT~(~) < a, there
into ~. For T 6 E set = h~(T~).
distinct
(~ < < ) "
is a c a r d i n a l
mod U. Hence
Since
gT~ i s
y < < such
that
-
Y = {~IgTm(~) <
y}6U.
Choose
$ 6 E such that
T > T ,T { and set
for
~ 6 Y N C- =: Y: T
u
= {~ < ~i , , T ~ £
Then < u Hence
K<+.
( 7)-~ ( K ) £ K ~, K ~ ~ K ~ and ~a = T ~ K ~ a )"
just note
m i n e d by Q N K, we get ~e ~T Q~ N Q~,
z~:~ K ~ - - ~
following
Q~ n Q~ ~ But then ~T
QU 6 QT"
some
segment
in < and for e v e r y
Let ~ £ C , U 6 E N T, ~ 6 rng ~ T. Then ~ £ C , Q~ =
and ~
Lemma
unbounded
Q~, ~ ~ for ~ 6 E, e 6 C T by:
Define
Fact:
is c l o s e d
[ a 6 Y> i s
U is
rug T ~ and g ~
a regularity
(y,~)-regular.
(~) < gT,(~)}.
sequence
Contradiction!
for
U and ~
< ~
for
~ 6 Y.
70
We model T s
return
to
of
+ V = K and
ZF-
: KT s
Case
the
main
Hence ~
I:
is
the
T 6 E
such
of
our
notion
KT c K S T
~ K +"
There
line
proof. of
We
mouse
note
is
that
absolute
KT
is
a
in
KT t
since
s
that
{s 6 C
IK T
J KT
} 6 U.
T Let
~
Set
W
be
be
tion
L e m m a
s Y i -> T
such
KT S
{aE
7s
and
Let
T 6 E,
. Then
~(~)
let
:+ 7~ < ~
2.4:
> T
Suppose -
M.. 1 that
KT
M
= M ~,
2.5: WN C
for
L,
a
since
are
IT 6 r n g
s
since
mouse
KT N s
7~ < ~
There T
K ~
AM, cy.
at
C
set
since
iterate
WN
and
otherwise
ME K { , ~
, s6
all
N
since
for
for
have
a6
the
Hence
and
Bi
7
S
T £ rng
KT ~
at
a
Let
M s with
if
T > T.
a c-~ ,
itera-
M is
= 7~}
, such ~
T: S
KT ~
6 >- ~ , y .
Let
N =
the
large
Let
~ < T
Since
since
contradicts
S
~T
a N f M i . Hence
and
T
of
.
= y s.
M 6K T
arbitrarily
~T S
and
~ < ~
a 6~(~)
- This
iterate
M exists.
N6
K
i-th
:+ i < s
~ l
not
We
M~ be 1
n K TmM ~ - -
then
Lemma
at
Then
N ~ M
~-th
that
7~-
AM, 6 Nc But
}. T h e n for each ~ £ W there is a core mouse s the ~-th iterate of M s is a mouse at a 7 < T . Let s
point
follows Then
such.
J K~
a mouse
Proof: a6
least
{~IK [ ~
Ms ~ K~ Ms
the
M ~ N.
KT
is
a
unique our
T 6 E
But
choice
such
of
K < +t
core
it
(N).
then
model
core
that
mouse
of
ZF-. with
an
M.
that
E U.
+ Proof: fine
Let T ~ 6 E,
~ < K f
. We
6 sT
show ~+
by
that
there
induction
is on
T > ~ ~ < K
with as
-
T~
=
the
least
{a6 WN CTI
T
such
that
T > T,~,
f~ (s) < T s } 6 U;
SUP ~<~
T
and
the
follows:
property.
De-
71
f
(~)
= y~ where
i = the
Yi > sup
{T
least
I~ < { a n d
i such
~6 C
that
. T
Let
T = sup
T ~ and
= {e6
C I
sup
T h e n C is c l o s e d Z
= {~6
T~ < f f
unbounded
= sum
{~16
(~) h a s
the
On>
NOW
is
Lemma
Set
2.6: that
Let
we
Z 6 U such
(a) T
~ E Z set
the y~
are
X6~(y~) This by
Lemma
We may
Set
Now
;f
let
This
some
shows
T = sum ~<<
Z c C, w e
~ Z
limit
each
ordinal
T is
have
,, t h e n
as
I,
since
remuired.
of T 6 E satisfvin~
the
T ~.
l e t A E ~ ( T ) N K.
Then
there
is y 6 T
T-A.
that for
A6
K
. Argueing
as
in t h e
limit is
cofinal
N ~ = M I~ a n d
Be
= { 7 ~ ] ~ < i} w h e r e
iteration
I,
points
a 6
in p a r t i c u l a r
proof
of
Lemma
2.5,
e 6 Z:
= y~}
is
hence
~ 6 Z }. B u t
that
seauence
Since
~ 6 Z
(~)]{ < e a n d for
Z,Z~ E U,
a 6 Z.
Te ~
N N ~ there
Then
~ < 6' < ~,
T e = Y<
and
{<<.
some
the
applies
for
C and
for
(b){% < ~ ] B i For
that
Z = WN
if
a monotone
I-yc
v6 E such
= y<
= sum
sequence.
3.
or
Proof: get
. But
I = { T ~ I 6 < <}
I-yeA
Set
Z }} 6 U.
Hence
Yi"
l e t < [ 6 L 6 < <> b e of Lemma
such
T
a normal
conclusion
<.
T~}.
f~ (~) < T~}
e 6 Z
Hence
form
= sup ~<~
in
{~ < ~ I ~ 6
< ~ and
,(~) < T%'.
(~T n T) ~
Z[T { 6 r u g ir~ a n d
= {~ 6 Z[~ = sum
set
T,T,A6
zl;
in ~.
of
the
such
to A
rug
that
:=
mouse B~
(~)-I
T
, = y<-
M s.
Hence
for
or
- ~cy<_
-6cX_ (A),
B~
since
we
Remember
that
every
have
A
- X. 6 Ne
2.4.
assume
w.l.o.g,
that
A
contains
a final
segment
of B
for
72
every B
e£
Z.
- Tg(a)
Using
c
the
that
I
We
Using A
for
fact
that
are
A6 is
is
now
can
define
But
a
a6
Z.
Y
=
to
finish
Case
fl K
follows:
ready
V
V
over
iff
~-closed,
then
g
regressive is
{~ 6 ZI~ ~ 6 B
g:
bounded
} 6 U,
it
Z ~
mod
U
<
by
follows
such some
that y < <.
immediately
~(T)
3y < ~ since
I
as
I.
By
Lemma
2.6
we
can
define
an
- y cA.
cf(7)
=
< > ~.
Hence
the
ultrapower
of
K
by
V
wellfounded.
Case
2:
Case
2.1:
Set T
we
- y_cA.
ultrafilter
V
(b)
<' (~')
to U. that
W
=
=
T
(<+)K
= <'
[' <_ ~
Y
fa6 n
K=+.
W
not. K~
T
For .
iff to
To
see
~(e)n
show
T 6 E,
. Then
a'
a
T
~ K
I~
Let < +" = ( +)K, ~ b e l o n g s
( +)K
pick
Y =
{~I~
cardinal
For
~ 6 Y we
in
:+ < ~
@ >6
such
~ }¢u.
K T but
not
in
can
define
a non-trivial
by:
V
yields
for
each
e6
Y
well-known.
~
T
is
some
this,
~'
W
that
that
and
{e6
K
such
show
Then
since
K~ .
( +)K}. K
that
~T(X).
K
T 6 E.
that
~6
not. ~ ~
all
<' < T,
such
T > ~,
rng
WTI~'
over
first
~ 6 W
Pick
T 6
Clearly
. We
=
{~6
f~: n
is
T 6 E.
=
Suppose
gument
e6
for
•
KT ~
suffices
K,
+
: K T} 6 U
T
contradicts
V
fe£ n
IK
T
Fix
for
in
ultrafilter X6
< K
a 6 Y with
K~ w h i c h
Set
C
( +)K.
Suppose
Choose
It
{~6
a wellfounded
there
is
{~ < ~ I f ~ (v) 6 f ~ ( v ) } n+1 n let Then
us
assume
there
is
K
~
L,
a mouse
a
£ V
sequence . But
since N
ultrapower
f~ n
then
we
otherwise
such
that
such
that
may the
{f~In n
of
take ar-
< ~} oN.
K.
73
Let is
N4N
such
that
transitive.
-I
(fn)
is
Then
also
choose
NOW
{ f ~ I n < m} U ~ c N
is
a mouse
a s-descending
=+ < ~
~
such
N
and
of
N
= ~.
Let
cardinality
~,
sequence
that
mod
V
( f ~ I n < ~} c_ K 6
_
6 Z and
>_ ~a} 6 U. set
Xn
:
Then
Z =
{~ 6 Y N
and
,
fn* = ~ ( f
) . Then
~6
Xn
X* = z n
*
=
hence
pick
~
W-TIT 6 rna~ ~
{~If ~ (~) 6 f ~ ( v ) } , n+1 n
N ~ ~
where
N6
K=+.
T ~ T such
--
and
~(Xn )
T~_> @~} 6 U.
Let
and
*
*
{~I fn+1 (~) 6 f n ( V ) } ,
But
.
~
{~[T
that
~:
hence
*
fn+1(~)6
fn(~)
Contradiction!
Case In
2.2:
this
case
we
theorem
of
Un
normal
K
is
+
(K+) K =
K
actually
[ 3 ] it in
show
suffices K.
This
that
to is
U N L[U]
show
that
equivalent
is
normal
in L [ U ] .
By
~,UNK> is a m e n a b l e K the following
a
and
+ Claim:
There
are
arbitrarily
large
T < <
such
that
,UNKT>
is
7
amenable
and
UN
K
T
is
normal
in < K
T
,UnK
T
>.
+ Let For W
T
y < K
the =
moment,
{~ 6 C vT :
We
. We
first
~
shall let
PK T = K } 6 U. ~ T~
{X6~(a)nK
see
that
T 6 E be
T
there
arbitrary.
For
~ 6 W
is
T > y
Recall
satisfying
the
claim.
that
define:
I~(X)}.
show
WT = { ~ 6 WTIVT6 6~K} To
show
this
pick
T 6 E,
U. T ~ T.
Then
Y =
{6 6 W - I T 6 r n g
T}
6 U.
Let
a6
T
Let A
A
=
I~ < c~ 6 K ~
= ~ ~(A)"
Note
that
we
Then
be
an enumeration
of ~(a)
is
now
set
V~ = V ~a N KT.
actually
have
* 6 K. : { A v I ~ 6 A v} a V T 6 K=+ for a 6 ~ • d
It
n KT~ a n d
obvious
that
we
can
T
apply
the
method
of
Lemma
2.5
to
Y.
74 find
T 6 E Y
We
such
that
T > ~,
cf(T)
=
<
and
{~ 6 WTIi s a m e n a b l e } 6 U.
=
shall
show
that
By t h e d e f i n i t i o n
T
satisfies
o f V~, T
we
our
Claim.
obviously
have
for
~ 6 Y:
VT~ i s n o r m a l i n.
For
{~16
that Z6
~ 6 Y choose
U.
For
V~
< T~ } 6 U. ~6
is
Z we
normal
We
need
a
Lemma
2.7:
Let
one
V
satisfying
V
is
=+ < ~
6
Set
have on
final
<
such
Z = VT6 e
that
{~6
YN
K~-~' s o
in < K
T
,V~>
VT 6 K6
Pick
{ 6 E,
W -TI T 6T r n g ~ ~ a n d set
Va
and
T
is
> 6~}.
such Then
Then:
= ~(V~). ,V~>
~
T > T,
amenable.
lemma
+
Let
X6
V
normal
us
V a = V e'
= V
T satisfies
of
amenable.
Claim:
We we
get
N ~ M.
a
There
first
<
in < K
how
every
cf(T)>
T
,V>
this
~,
and
T < K
T
,~
finishes
~ , a ' 6 Z. segment
It
of
. Then
is
our
follows
Z.
But
there
is
at most
amenable.
proof.
We
now
immediately
Z 6 U.
Hence
V
know
that = UN
that
every K
T
. So
Claim.
2.7:
Let
suffices
a mouse
show
that mice
AN, 6 ~ ( < ) N
V be
to
is
distinct Then
and
<+
final
our
It
~ K
show
for
Lemma
T
on
first
contains
Proof
K
on
<
in < K
T
,V>
where
T
,V>
is
show:
N = 3~
the N,M
normal
at
claim at
MeN.
<
< such
implies
such
that
that
the ~(<)N
Contradiction!
~(~) n N
lemma. N
= ~W(<) n K T.
Suppose
= / ~ ( < ) N M.
not. Let
Then e.g.
75
We now prove
the c l a i m .
V V S e t M = ] e = U{]~+II- ]~ 6 K T }"
We
closely
we have
McK
iterable.
~(K) N M ~ K
a least mouse,
We
T < <
that
vide
since
cf(T) > ~.
(8) of the e a r l i e r
proof
we
in the
(using KT <
, we know
but
of T h e o r e m
cannot
argument
is n o w e a k l y
first
in L[V].
Then
Assume
is n o w e a k l y
(a) L e t < u
Hence
the
there
is
is a
claim.
that
normal does
the
ultrafilter.
at l e a s t
normal
assumption
tell
ultrafilter
qL ~
A light
us,
mo-
however,
on r e g u l a r
<
2~ = K.
2.8:
2.9:
M is
get
6 _> ~ a n d N = ~
to u s e
I L ~. L e t n be
normal
ultrafilter
a general
discovered
regular
property
by Ketonen
(see
such
that
Let U be weakly Iv 6 X> b e
normal
a regularity
L e t D ~ ~ be u n b o u n d e d
in <.
25 = <. T h e n
on K.
of w e a k l y [8 ]).
normal
on <, K r e g u l a r . sequence
ultrafilters
For completeness,
a proof.
Lemma
Hence
there,
2.1.
prove,
of a n y w e a k l y
foregoing
IL ~ there
(J~) ~ KT.
1.3 As
a n d t h e n ~ ( < ) ~ M = ~(<~. n K r-
So N s a t i s f i e s
the p r o o f
suspect,
K +) <
t h a t V is n o t n o r m a l
that ~(<) N ~
of the
such
was
. V is o - c l o s e d ,
T
the e x i s t e n c e
assuming
We have
of L e m m a
V is w - c l o s e d .
that
which
+
strongly
Theorem
(7),
completes
dification
there
in
6 such
precludes
proof
for ~ < T
since
This
an a r g u m e n t
but M~ K
T
As
Since
follow
for U.
we
pro-
76
Then (b)
{mlsup(DN
U has
u m)
= m} £ U.
a regularity
lulI 5 c f ( 1 )
for
sequence
all
< u ~ l l < <,
lim(l)>
such
that
I.
Proof: (a)
Suppose
Hence
not.
there
6 6 D - y.
(b) L e t
alc
W
Set
Proof
Theorem
fixed
for
Define now
By
luxl
be
the
~o
=
Then
set ~
2.9
{~6
U has
and
{mIDN
= ~.
lall
mod
u m -c T } .
U.
Let
Contradiction!
: I.
the
Define
qE,q~,f
by
= <.
We
~ < < such For
and
<
that
normal
= I for
as : L
-< Q
<
also
in
is
on
<,
a regularity
where
sequence all
[A]
and
set
~ { C that
~ : < N Q~=
AT : Qa N H<}.
the
_ A ]., A N [
such
~ Co a n d ~oa _ c ~,A,' a .r
AO CTIQa
ul
T [ {o} U E, Q
I.
<
is
regular
< u l I l < <,
Let
this
lim(1)>
sequence
be
proof.
since
2~
Then
a regularity
sup
H
QT
weakly
~T ~,%exactly
smallest
~
ZN W
(k) 6 q E } .
U be
that
~T~ ~
then
Z =
regressive
property.
Let
of
f
however,
[A],AN~>.
fir -~ ~
C'T =
Lemma
rest
of
= the
CT'
2.8:
E,fm,A,QT,
possible,
But
is
I > ~
and
desired
= cf(1)
the
is
a6
the
require,
where
a I = I and
for
{E < lil 6 d o m ( f )
that
U,
(DNu m)
follows.
{~I f- I " ~ 6 U}
with
such
sup
= min
= <.
Z6
sup
q
sequence
2~
that
(a I - ~ )
of
v ~
that
: rain
uI =
and
map
{yI6 6 uy} 6 U.
E < < as
= sup
~
=
i such
on
f6 (I)
the
is y < < s u c h
Then
induction
Then
Now
An
< code
[A] , A N < >
~>~Q
For
u
o.
then
~6
C
2.1.
DN
<.
We
This
and
let
C
we
may
set
o
o
define:
mQ. N
set
that
of T h e o r e m
_ 0 ° =
we
T
proof
for
).
It
is
T 6 {o} U E:
clear
that,
if
oS
[-~
emm~q
]o7
~n~ywsqns
BuiMoiio
7 ~q~
~A~q
~M
(" n 9 9 D
l
"03 D
U~
(~ D
" ~9 D
~ = b~
' ~1
pu~
6ux
~
~X9
U Z9
mbx
x
~oq
(o)
D
= bZ ueq~
b , z,D 9 ~ 7I
(q)
O oM~
~ = ° ~ pu~
:poTii]OA
-M
XITs~
= o M u~q~
ax~
'' D 9
=
D
II
(e)
s~oe 9 5u!MoIIO / eqL
+ (~)7o> o ~ U u0 ~M U u o
= ~
0 = ~ ~
z ~eq~
:]~s
= l~
~ON
£IIeU~ 7 ~M ~ M =
~
z0
pu~
:%~s
'eAT~ISUel]
ST
i0
alaq~ ,D9 ~
"~IOa
IeTOnXo
~q~
£eId
~
s~an~onx~s
~q~
'/ooxd
l~ ~
:1~
1o
'Z ~ {0} 9 i ao 7
~u~s~xd
~q%
uI
o~ 9 x
"g% 3 ]eq~
qons
co> I
sT
~a~N%
pu~
o~9
<'!> u~qm
~ ~sooq0"
ST
qons
~)q
pu~
x ~q~ 96A
1
n3 ql~>
A ~]!uT7 ~)
dns
1
( nuo)dns
e
~eq~
n3
X)
o>
" {~n 3 (~) ~0
•~ 9 { ~ =
I D3
~]
{g ~ [g > @ ( i ~ ) q } l -~no~
e UT
~IqeuTl~p-
= ~ u~q& = X 6"g
(g~)q}
ox~q~ %~S
'~>
oS
M
x u~q~
l~ U
~eq~
"~ uI
"s~Inu~xo7
{(x) T~
70
~ou~ H
= x qons x ~q
II~qs sT
~ ~
~AIS
I<X'T>}
:q
H
~.eq
= g~
:7oo~d
:OL'~
,D
~M
0 uaq&
uoI~ex~mnu~
[V]@q3x
0 ~ eq
H9
~oqs
papunoqun
~q;
~0 p u e O
~Iq~uIT~P-
]eq~
• ~D0
0 s!
" ~1 D ~-X
"X3 ~ ~q
eurmaq £ q
= 0 ~S ~ ~o7
"uo!%o~fIq
l
"F/3
'~umi~q
ZL
78
Lemma
2.11:
{sIT
Let
W 6 U,
f 6 ~6
cf(~) +.
Then
there
is T 6 E s u c h
that
> - f(e) } 6 U .
Proof:
Suppose
set
= {~ 6 W f l C ' I T ~ ~ < f ( ~ ) }
YT
not.
(b) (c)
above,
the
K many
predecessors
For
gT
~ 6W
are
let h and
define
pairwise
(mod U)
g
inject
f(a)
into
gT 6 6 ~ T
distinct
mod
(6 < <) . C h o o s e
cf(~) . F o r
by gT(~) U.
Hence
T 6 E
= h~(T~).
some
T 6 E such
gT*
By
has
that
i
[ >T~,T 6 and v Then
=
set
I~ 6 Y> v
We
now
prove
C
T
<~ f o r
I: T h e r e the
all
but
2.8
Y:
g ~ (~) < g ~ , ( ~ )
sequence This
by
for
U.
contradicts
cases,
} But
v
Lemma
closely
~ gT,(~)
< cf(~) ,
2.9.
imitating
the
proof
of
that
of C a s e
uses
the
{~ 6 C'I K T Te # K T ~ } 6 U.
I
in T h e o r e m
sets
C' a n d T
2.1.
the
The
points
repetition
cf(a)
+ in
is
al-
place
of
.
2: C a s e
Case
2.1 : {~ 6 C W =
by T °
I fails.
o
l~ ° # id rK } ~ U. d
{c~ 6 C o l O r ° # i d ~ K Set
Y =
Suppose not.
{~ 6 W I ~
For
~ 6W
Z = {a 6 (W-Y) n C ' T I K T ~ is r e g u l a r KT = K
m K
For
c~ 6W l e t
a cardinal
- Y there
T:a
be the
in K}
that
We
first
first
point
show
that
that
moved Y 6U
e is n o t
a
{c~}Tc~_> y } 6 U. L e t
Ta >_ ya}.
K~---~K<+
~ is n o t
d
is y e < cf(e) + s u c h
"r s u c h
= KT~ a n d
in KTa' s i n c e . Hence
}.
is
i n Kyc~,. Now p i c k
cardinal
tion.
a 6 Y.
Theorem
argument
Case
Let
6 rng ~ ~ and
is T 6 E s u c h
literal, =+
, ~
=:
2.1.
Repeat most
nC{
is a r e g u l a r i t y
sup
Case
~ 6Y~
{~ < ~ I T * , T ~
hence
Theorem
for
a cardinal
Then and
Z 6U-
Let
z r~(~) = <.
in K T, w h i c h
a 6 Z. T h e n But is a c o n t r a d i c -
79 i
This
proves
define
Y 6U.
a non-trivial
X 6V An
founded
In for
iff
imitation
Case
But
any
of
Case
case y < <.
of
2.1
So
we
ultrafilter
Case
we
a 6Y
clearly
have
(6~) K < ~.
over ~(~
) DK
by:
Hence
we
may
6 T°(X) .
ultrapower
2.2:
this
@
for
2.1,
Theorem
2.1
shows
that
some
V
is
not
yields
a well
K.
fails.
have the
{e < < I s
regular}
conclusion
6U.
follows
Hence
from
U
Theorem
2.1.
(y,<)-regular
80 I § 3. Z 3 - A b s o l u t e n e s s
Shoenfield does
showed
hand,
therefore, the
to Z 3I s t a t e m e n t s ,
not extend
other
case
the
if K is t o o
solution
We
3.1:
since
Within
of S h o e n f i e l d ' s
L e t A be ~ i .
than
Assume
I 1 3.
Clearly
if K = L. N o r
t h a n K - e.g.
in L. H i s
3a a ~ L is i t s e l f
K is z ~ - a b s o l u t e .
- e.g.
condition.
extension
Theorem Then
of a ~
that
small
larger
are a b s o l u t e
I rather Ba a ~ K is Z 4
statement
to conjecture
V is t o o m u c h
modest
I that Z 2 statements
can
On the
It is t e m p t i n g , this
cannot
it b e t h e
if O T e x i s t s ,
since
these
however,
limits,
theorem
I Z3
case
be if
O T is t h e u n i q u e we obtain
a
theorem.
A(a) , w h e r e
a# exists
but
L[a]
~ IL ~.
3a 6 K A(a) .
immediately
Corollary
3.2:
Ba(A(a) A a~
This
get:
Assume
exists)
iO T
•
1
L e t A be ~ 2 "
Then
~ 3a 6 K A(a) .
in t u r n y i e l d s :
Corollary
3.3:
Assume
iO % b u t
that
the r e a l s
are c l o s e d
under ~.
Then
1 K is Z 3 - a b s o l u t e .
As a c o r o l l a r y
Theorem M ~L[a].
3.4: Then
Harrington
of the p r o o f
of T h e o r e m
1 L e t A b e ~ [ 2. L e t ~ b e a m o u s e 3a 6 L [ M ]
and Kechris
3.1,
and
we
shall
assume
obtain:
A(a),
where
A(a). proved
this
for t h e c a s e M = O~
(see
[5 ]).
81
The now
proof
on
wise
of
assume
set
Theorem
A(a),
L[a]
K + = L [ V o]
dinal
which
Lemma
3.5:
3.1
I= nL U,
where
is m e a s u r a b l e
There
(a)
~{6 K +
(b)
Let
M.
is
be
an
the
stretches
over
a # exists.
V°
is
normal
in
an
inner
iterable
iterates
several
K+ = K
K ° and
on
Ko
From
if 7 L H.
is
the
Other-
least
or-
model.
premouse
of
Set
sublemmas.
M
~ with
such
that:
iteration
points
<..
1
Then
l
Mi H
= K L [ a ] 6 M.. Ki i
Ki
Proof: Case
i:
K L[a]
= K.
Since
a # exists,
self,
hence
M
of
there K
Vo 3<+ setting o
=
Case
2:
K L[a]
Then
we
can
that
M~/ L [ a ] .
is
into +
a nontrivial
itself.
Hence
embedding
K + = L [ V o]
of and
L[a] we
can
into
it-
take
(K~)K
~ K.
apply
Lemma
(Note
1.4
that
and
the
H i <.
take
the
~-least
are
the
same
core
whether
mouse
M
such
we r e g a r d
the
1
M.
as
the
iterates
or the
mouse
V M = Ja
be
iterates
of
M).
1
M. l
From now V. = • 1 be
on the
~, i
~... i 3
Set
let
C =
iterates
{K. ! i 6 1
fixed
with
On}.
with
iteration
Finally
set
H
1
=
<, 1
K'
K'
<. 1
(2) ~(K< ) n ~ v
:~(K~
!
•
1
(since <. i
is
1
,'p(K~.) n M i = ~ ( K ~ . ) 1
(3)
) n~
•
1
inaccessible
1
in K'.
normal
points
f!. (1)
V
n~{i+l )
= KL [ a ] .
on K.
i
< in M.
and Then
Let
iteration we h a v e :
maps
82
Not
let I be the c a n o n i c a l
< T i l l < ~> the m o n o t o n e
indiscernibles
enumeration.
L e t bij:
for L[a] L[a]
~i
and L[a]
be de-
fined by: b i j t T i = idtTi, Define
b i j ( r i + a) = Tj+ h.
an u l t r a f i l t e r
X 6 U. l
iff
U i on ~ ( T i) n L[a]
T. 6 b..(X) i i]
U i is o b v i o u s l y
normal
by:
(i < j) .
in < L [ a ] , U i > .
It is k n o w n
that~
is
i
amenable iterate
(setting
Proof:
(T)L[a])
and that < L [ a ] , U i >
of < L [ a ] , U o > , the bij b e i n g
ultrafilters
Lemma
÷=
~i
3.6:
the i t e r a t i o n maps.
We use the
U i to prove.
(r+) K' =
Set rt1 =
is the i-th
(r+)L[a!
(T~)L[a!
is a m e n a b l e
T'i =
' +,K' ~T i) . Suppose
T lI < T~l" Since
we t h e n have U!1 6 L[a], w h e r e
U!1 = U.1 n K'. A
1
standard
argument
shows,
however,
that < K ' . , U ~ > T
over,
cf(Ti)
covering
= T i in L[a],
lemma holds
in L[a] w i t h r e s p e c t
!
in L[a].
of
[ 3 ] t h a t U!l is n o r m a l
U i is m - c o m p l e t e
since
Hence,
is a m e n a b l e .
to K'
in L[a],
in L[U~].
More-
1
i T i is i n a c c e s s i b l e
in L[a]
(see
and the
[3 ]) . But then
we have by a n o t h e r
This contradicts
theorem
our a s s u m p t i o n
that L[a] ~ ~L Z.
Now
set W = ~ ( K ~ ) n K'.
For X 6 W set X :
y
~oi(X) . C l e a r l y
K' = x ~ .
Lemma
3.7:
There
is i
such that if i O
< i < j, then O
-
-
bij (~. N V ) = ~ N Vb. for X 6 W, v 6 On. lj (~))
Proof:
Set
~=
{~I~ = T
class.
Let D 6~.
and cf(~) > <}. C l e a r l y , r
By a F o d e r
type a r g u m e n t
is a s t a t i o n a r y
for e a c h x £ L[a]
there
is
83
< % such
t h a t b..(x) 13
~D < ~ such The m a p ~' ~ .
that
= x for ~ ~ i m j g D-
~D A i s j < D i m p l i e s
~ ~ ~D is r e g r e s s i v e Let
~G = i ° for D 6 ~'.
i o ~ i ~ j, X 6 N , bij(xnv
~)
Corollary (a) D 6C
on ~,
D £ On.
= bij((~NV
3.8: iff
Let
Pick
We
D) n v
) =
bij(X N V
hence show
D £ ?'
Since
) = XA V
constant
that
such
~ < K < cf(~),
there
for all X 6 W .
on a s t a t i o n a r y
i ° is as r e q u i r e d
that
j,~ < D.
( X N V D) n V b . . ( ~ ) 13
Let
Then:
= ~nVb..(~). 13
i o < i N j. T h e n
b. •(D) E C i]
(b) ~. £ C. 1
Proof:
(a)
To p r o v e hence
is i m m e d i a t e
(b) p i c k
T i 6 C by
Every
by
D = T
the L e m m a
= <
such
and C =
that
D ~
. Then
has
the
f o r m ~(~)
for
some ~ 6 C,
f:K n
<. By L e m m a
3.7 b i j ( ~ ( ~ ) )
= ~ (bij (7)
action
of bij
the o r d i n a l s
is d e t e r m i n e d
(see
upon
a version
[ 5 ]) to s h o w
Lemma
3.9:
" bi
(T i) = N 6 C,
(a).
ordinal
We n o w p r o v e
/~ X6V
Let
that
T•
of Paris' this
action
= < . There
1
"patterns
is
by
of
is v e r y
8 such
for
f 6 W such i ° < i g j. its
that Thus
action
the
on C.
indiscernibles"
simple
lemma
indeed.
that
O
(a) Tio+J
= <~+Bj
(b) b i o + i , i o + J ( <
Proof:
Set C 1•
+Bi+~)
= < +~j+
C A'(Ti,Ti+ I)
=
.
.
It s u f f i c e s
to s h o w
that
(*) b" C ij i+h = Cj+h'But
this
follows
from
(**)
b'! .C,
C,
since
then
13 I
=
3
h" C i+h = b i j b i , j + h " Ci = b i , j + h " Ci = C j+h" ;ij
is
for
i°
_
84 (**)
in t u r n (***)
To
see
follows
from
bi,i+l
"C i
this,
assume
The
case
j =i
For
j = k+l,
= Ci+l"
(***) . We
prove
(**)
by
induction
on
j-i.
is t r i v i a l . k>
i we
b i , k + l " Ci = b k , k + l For
j = X such
Cl,
have
b i k "C i
that
= b k , k + l C k = Ck+l"
lim(1) it
i < I>
is e n o u g h
is the
direct
to n o t e
limit
of
that
i < i>,
< b i h [ C i l i o <- i <_ h < l>.
we
now
prove
of < L [ a ] , U i > . for
an
f:
L[a]
We
(***).
Hence
each
T. ~ L [ a ] , 1 ~
not
constant
on
may
take
But
Set = sup n<w
get
let
is
the
the
form
ultrapower
bi,i+l(f)
(T i)
But
then
~n
Since
bi,i+n:
6 U i.
y ~ rn~bi,i+l)
f is m o n o t o n e Set
T i + 2 , we for
~ ~(~(~))}
y 6 C i + 1 - rng (bi,i+l) • L e t
T i ~ Ti+ I.
applying
6 Xn
has
{~ < T i l L [ a ]
So
T i} 6 U i
on
, f is
an X 6 U. a n d 1
fn = b i , i + n ( f )
for
we
n ~ ~.
have:
X 6 V.
xi+ n} £ U i + n
(n < ~ , X 6 V) .
implies
fn+l(Ti+n)
6X6~V x N
Yn = f n + l ( T i + n )' 6 . Then n
@ = sup
of L[a]
)
6 ~n
{v < T i + n l f n ( ~ )
in t u r n (3)
But
we
everywhere.
6 C n Ti+ 2 = x/~ 6v
{m < T i l f ( ~ )
then
This
X 6 U.. 1
it to be m o n o t o n e
fl(Ti)
(2)
any
f:
that
and
by contradiction. (Ti) , w h e r e
(i)
element
(Ti)) (
y = bi,i+l(f)
Since
recall
f 6 L[a]
~(bi,i+l(~)
argue
we
f"
£
n
Ti+~'
E C;
Ti+n+ IWC
(n < ~).
an = bi+n+l,i+m(y hence
since
6 C C since
f W is m o n o t o n e
n)
= f
(Ti+n).
it is a l i m i t and
nsup <~
Ti+n
Finally point
set of C.
: Ti+ ~ . H e n c e
85
cf(~)
= Ti+ ~ in L[a].
L[a]
since
(T+
'
But
)L[a]
lemma
for K'
Now
fails
define
+ w) K' by L e m m a (Ti+
=
i+w
6 is i n a c c e s s i b l e
in L[a].
in K' 3.6
and
~ > Ti+ w in
Hence
the c o v e r i n g
Contradiction!
an e q u i v a l e n c e
relation
~ -
on the
set of
in-
M,e,B
creasing
tupels
<
• '''
f r o m C as follows:
> ~ <<.
30,.--,Jm-1
(a)
ik < ~ ~
ik = Jk
(b)
e_< ik ~
( e < Jk and
(c)
e
(where
<
i k < i h and
y : B"
Corollary
I~,/~),
methods
3.10:
Let
(ik-yB)
=
n
= m and
~k-/B)
k-
[Y//B] +
By s t a n d a r d
iff
>
we
(?B~) < B) •
then
<~>,<~>
get:
6 [C] n such
that
<~> ~ <~>.
Let
f. 6 W, 1
f• :
1
~
L[a]
Now
for
K
4~
=
~ ~(~(~))e-~L[a]
ordinals.
> ~ , B , O n R M such iteration
~
Let
some
n. For
= ~o,~+B
(f)
Now define
(x 6 H)
that
only and
an
.
iterable
L~[M]
premouse
is a d m i s s i b l e .
set C = {Kili < ~}.
~ = ~M,a,B
n ~]<~) £ H.
The
~p(~(~))
Set H = HM,~, ~ = L~[M],
of M and
as b e f o r e .
9or
~
let M be an a r b i t r a r y
arbitrary
(~[C
Then
1 ~ , . . . , m .
= ~+~w"
Set W = W M = the f£W
set ~ =
and < ~ ] f
~ is the
least
Let <Mi,~ij, ~ = ~M,e,B
on
e,B
be
the
[C] <w
~,C n ~ £ H; h e n c e
set of
YZoi(f)
H-language
symbols
an a d d i t i o n a l
Then
where
< and
f 6 M such
and ~
= ~
that
f: <
n
~ K
n. T h e n
6 W> 6 H.
infinitary
predicate
Define
at some
~
= ~M,~,8
of ~ are =,6.
constant
~6 has
~. As a x i o m s
we
as
follows.
constant
names
take
together
ZF-
x
86
with (a) v 6 x<-~z6~X ~ = z (b) ~ _c w
(el L - [ ~ ] K" (d)
~ A(~.)
If < ~ > , < ~ > and
f,
6 [C n 7] <w,
6 W such
1
that
f.
1
:
K
n
~ <
(i = 1 ..... m) , then for e v e r y
An
immediate
Lemma
consequence
3.11:
There
this
gives
But
Corollary
3.12:
K and Z M , ~ , 6
Proof:
Let
lemmas
~.
is
that ~ M , e , 8 is c o n s i s t e n t .
is < M , e , B > 6 K such
that M,a,6
are
countable
in
is c o n s i s t e n t .
<M,~,B>
= b-l(e),
there
foregoing
is < M , e , 8 > 6 K + such
There
M , ~ , B 6 X. L e t b:
But M,~,8
of the
formula
be as in the
H~-~X
6 = b-l(6).
are
countable
is n o t h i n g
<M,~,8> 6 H L[Vo]= K0
where
lemma.
Let
H is t r a n s i t i v e .
Then
H = H~,~,~
in K +. We
claim
to be proved.
Otherwise
K
argument
. The
X ~ H,
same
~ = w in K + such
Set M = b - l ( M ) ,
and~,~,~ that
that
is c o n s i s t e n t .
< M , ~ , B > 6 K.
If K = K +,
K + = L [ V o] and shows
that M , e , 8
are
countable
K0
in K.
We
are n o w
and ~ = ~ M , ~ , 8 theorem part L~[a]
ready be as
to f i n i s h
in C o r o l l a r y
let 0~6 K be a m o d e l
of O i i s b A(a).
the p r o o f
transitive. It s u f f i c e s
Let
of ~ . a be
to show:
3.12. We m a y
of T h e o r e m By
the
assume
3.1.
Let M,~,8
Barwise compactness that
the ( ~ - i n t e r p r e t a t i o n
the w e l l
founded
of ~. T h e n
87
Claim:
L[a] ~ A(a)
Let ~' be the Z F - l a n g u a g e w i t h the c o n s t a n t ~ and ordinal c o n s t a n t s (~ £ On). Define a class S of ~ ' - s e n t e n c e s • Let6 [C] n, fi 6 W, fl: Kn
~
<
(i=l
.....
as follows: m).
Then:
iff
3 < ~ > 6 [C N ~ ] n ~ < ~ > ~ < T > and L~[a] b ~(~(~)))
I n d i s c e r n i b i l i t y a r g u m e n t s show that this is a c o r r e c t d e f i n i t i o n and that (i) S is a consistent, (2)
r~(~)q 6
(3)
rBx ~(x) I 6 S
S
iff
d e d u c t i v e l y closed class of sentences
L~[a] b ~(~) iff
Bt £ T
where T is the class of (4)
rBx 6 On ~(x) I 6 S
Now l e t ~ b e
iff
for ~ <
r~(t)l 6 S L-terms
3~
r~(~)1 6 S
the term model of S. By
the rank of
[t] in 6 ~ is v w h e r e
rrn(t)
equivalence
set of a term t). Hence ~ i s
(4) , 6 ~ is well founded and = _vI 6 S ([t] being the isomorphic
to a t r a n s i t i v e
model Q. But then a is the Q - i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of ~ and L ~ [ a ] < Q by Hence Q = L[a] and L[a] I= A(a).
(2).
This finishes the proof of T h e o r e m
3.1.
In c o n c l u s i o n we prove T h e o r e m 3.4, m e n t i o n e d at the outset. a,M be as in the h y p o t h e s i s of that theorem. Assume w.l.o.g, is the ~-least core mouse. M ~ L[a]. We first show that a Suppose not. Then the c o v e r i n g
lemma holds for L[a].
Let
that M
exists.
But L[a] I= ~L H,
since K L[a] ~
K; hence in L[a]
to K' = K L[a].
Hence the ,covering lemma holds with respect to K'. This
is nonsense,
the c o v e r i n g lemma holds w i t h respect
since the mouse M enables us to c o n s t r u c t a n o n t r i v i a l
88
El-embedding iterable
of K'
premouse
into used
itself.
Thus
in the above
a ~; exists. proof w h i c h
M is then-the shows
3 a 6 L[M]
A(a).
8g
§ 4
At
Decomposability
first we
filters.
repeat
of U l t r a f i l t e r s
some
definitions
L e t U be an u l t r a f i l t e r
and elementary
on some
results
cardinal
K. L e t
for u l t r a -
6 be
a car-
dinal.
U is c a l l e d
Iv < 6 > 6 U 6 s u c h
U is c a l l e d that
~<~6 av 6 U
dingly tions
see
[ 9
An
and
~
for all
uniform
iff
-
with
iff t h e r e A
DA
is a s e q u e n c e
and
~<~6 A
is a p a r t i t i o n
~ <6
~ y6S
a m {U.
6-decomposable.
= ~.
Iv < 6> s u c h
U is
For more
6-descen-
on these
no-
[ 12].
U'
iff
for a l l A , B 6 U
is b e l o w
is a f u n c t i o n
6-decomposable
implies
iff t h e r e
S c6
iff U is cf
] and
ultrafilter
there
that
incomplete
6-decomposable
incomplete
U is c a l l e d
iff
~-descendingly
U in the R u d i n - K e i s l e r - o r d e r i n g
f: K ~ U U '
there
~ = B.
such
is a u n i f o r m
t h a t U'
=
{f"AIA 6 U } .
ultrafilter
U'
on
U'
~RK U
U is
6 below
U in
§ 2 we
call
the R u d i n - K e i s l e r - o r d e r i n g .
Let
! be
a sequence for v 6 X quences
a cardinal.
and
I~ 6 X > {~lq 6 u
for U are
Slightly
extending
a l-regularity } 6U
just
for all
the n o t i o n
sequence
q
Hence
of
for U iff X c < , the
the r e g u l a r i t y
sequences
U is c a l l e d
(y,l)-regular
u
K-regularity
c~ se-
for U in the s e n s e
of § 2.
Let y be a cardinal. set H cU
U is
such
that ~ = I and
(y , l) - r e g u l a r
iff
iff
there
for all H ' c H H ' > y i m p l i e s
there
is a l - r e g u l a r i t y
is a s u b -
DH'
sequence
= ~.
6X>
g0
for U s u c h
t h a t u-- < y
(l,K)-regularity y',l'
be
for all ~ 6 X .
of § 2 c o i n c i d e s
cardinals
such
of U i m p l i e s
the
is
is c a l l e d
just what
that y ~y'<
iff
it is then
y ~cf(6)
~ 6 ~l.
~ R K U be
U is 6 - d e c o m p o s a b l e
of U iff T <<.
The
a uniform
T h e n U is w e a k l y
a weakly
g < f
the
here.
theorey,
of U
see e.g.
for r e g u l a r
~-deocmposable
Let
(~,l)-regularity
(e,l)-regularity
6-decomposable
(mod U)
normal
ultrafilter
following
The
in m o d e l
ultrafilter
iff
If g 6 < < is a f i r s t
normal
of U.
introduced
of
[2
cardinals
for all
6 such
]. I.
that
((y,l)-regular) . Then
(~,l)-regular).
for all g 6 K K
(See § 2).
it is
I = < the n o t i o n
i. T h e n
(l,l)-regular
(y,l)-regular, L e t U'
for
the n o t i o n
l'~
A-regularity
If U is
l e t U be
with
(y',l')-regularity
U is l - d e c o m p o s a b l e
Now
Hence
lemma
on <.
f 6 K K is a f i r s t
implies
idr<
g"y ~T
is a f i r s t
function
of U,
function
for s o m e y 6 U
function
t h e n U' =
and
o f U.
(g"AIA 6U}
is
~ R K U on <.
is a t h e o r e m
of K a n a m o r i
and
is p r o v e d
in
[6]-
Lemma for U.
The
4.1:
T h e n U is
next
f r o m the
Lemma
4.2:
lemma
Let
that O
do~s
cardinals
ultrafilter
is a r e s u l t of
[ 9
for all
of Kunen
] and
6 be a c a r d i n a l
T h e n U is
following
a uniform
(~,l)-regular
theorems
posable.
The
Let U be
on
K without
cardinals
and
function
i
Prikry
the p r e c e e d i n g
first
and
follows
easily
remarks.
a n d U an u l t r a f i l t e r
which
is
6+-decom -
f(6)-decomposable.
result was not exist
(L C H) . In
proved
(,O ~) 1976
in
1974
a n d all
it w a s
under
limit
proved
the
stronger
cardinals
without
are
assuming
assumptions
strong L C H
limit
gl
applying This
results
proof
result
on
now
analogous
gives
with
those
the
of
§ 2 with
stronger
nO ~ i n s t e a d
results
of
§ 2 the
of
~L H
following
decomposability.
Theorem4.3:Assume form
to
7L ~.
ultrafilter
dinals
6 ~K~
Proof:
Evidently
on
U
Let
<.
< be
Then
is n o t
u-decomposable.
Now we
Case
regular
a regular
U is
6-decomposable
a-complete
proceed
cardinal.
by
for
any
for
Let
U be
all
regular
cardinal
induction
on
6 >~
a unicar-
and
hence
K.
+ I: L e t
composable uniform U'
is
all
is
2:
by
Let on
the
U
is
and
6 <<
be
that
y ~d'
show
that
duction
for
But
since
there
is
hypothesis
2.1 Then
the
Then But
by
first
cardinals
Now
U'
(y,<)-regular
is
there
is
regular
a uniform
limit
ultrafilter But
some
hypothesis for
a uniform
Then
by
by
assume
for
then
the
that
some
cardinal
~RK
Lemma
4.2
U has
y
a
U' Now
<< the
on
6',
which
U'
~RK
U
such
now
U 6 ~RK
~RK let
But
U'
ultra-
preceeding
ultrafilter
cardinal. U~,
is
U be
then
normal
a regular
6-decomposable.
let
But
a weakly
there
<+-de-
6-decomposable
function.
is
U is
§ 4 •
and
i <~.
. Then
induction
U is
of
~
all
<
remarks
the
then
cardinal
no
on
preceeding
beginning
limit
for
uniform
there
< is a
is
<.
~ ~<.
U has
all
then
theorem
a cardinal. ~
in
U be the
U on
all
a regular that
let and
l-decomposable
on
by
~RK
for
<. A s s u m e
function.
remarks by
U and
inU
6-decomposable.
Remark: I.
U'
and 4.2
remarks
< be
first
is
Lemma
(~,l)-regular
remarks
~,
by
6-decomposable
filter U
and
ultrafilter
6 ~<+
Case
< be
Clearly
a modification
of
this
argument
also
would
cover
case
92
Case
3:
makes
Set
for
B+
extensive
lowing
use
some
of
singular
the
methods
cardinal of
[8]
8.
and
Here
[12].
We
the
proof
need
the
fol-
iemma:
Lemma
4.4:
filter
Let
on
(i~
8 be
U
is
If
IL ~
cardinal
Then
one
of
and the
U
a weakly
following
normal
ultra-
conditions
holds:
(~I' B + ) - r e g u l a r
U {v~U
Clearly
a singular
S+ . A s s u m e
(ii)
~+.
< =
is
~-decomposabie
this
lemma
U does
not
have
and
so
(~,B)-regular
function,
then
lemma
implies
settles
a
A V regular}
case
3.
first
Let
function,
6-decomposable
there
is
U be
a weakly
all
normal
B-
a uniform
then
for
=
by
ultrafilter
lemma
~ ~ 5+ . If
V ~RK U o n
4.1,
U is
U has
a
Now
(i)
B+ .
on
first
of +
4.4
such
that
that
w1 ~ef(6)
V
and
and
hence
6 = w.
U are
But
(ii)
6-decomposable
and
the
for
induction
all
6 ~ 5
hypothesis +
show
that
The
V
and
proof
U
of
model
results
[12].
For
are
lemma
from
some
6-decomposable
4.4
[13]
is
and
ultrafilter
the
for
crucial
on
results
U on
< let
all
regular
step
and
K.
Prikry
of
6 ~
is
based and
the
on
J.
core
Silver
from
ultrapower
of
<
K mod
U
f mod
U.
Lemma
4.5:
Let
seuqence
and
for
Let
f EK K let
C6 6
Let
6 <<
U be
and
such
the
denote
function
with
a ~-indecomposable
cf(6)
that
[f]u 6 < > / U
=
U q<~
6
~. ~
=
Let
<6
n
equivalence
constant
value
ultrafilter
In < ~ >
6. T h e n
the
in
be
on
q
of
6.
<,
a strictly
K~/'~" u <[C6
class
~ regular increasing
]lq < m >
converges
to
[c6]. This as
lemma
result 6.
The
has
been
next
proved
lemma
is
by
J.
theorem
Silver
and
can
be
5 in
[12]
and
due
found to
K.
in
[12]
Prikry.
93
Lemma
4.6:
Let
< be
a regular
t e r on
K. L e t C ~K/U b e
of the
following
cardinal
closed
conditions
and
{61 [C 6] 6 C } 6 U
(ii)
{~IU is c f ( 6 ) - d e c o m p o s a b l e }
of
in K a n d in K.
lemma
4.4.
6+ =
(8+) K.
B+ =
quence,
there
C 1 6 i ~ cf(1)
(iii)
o t ( C I) < 8
(iv)
I:
Then by
[ida<] U
Then
one
covering
lemma
the
that
oB-sequence
a sequence
arguments there
B is s i n g u l a r
is a ~ - s e q u e n c e
in K is j u s t
< C A l l < 8+ A L i m ( 1 ) >
a DB-se-
such
that
1 =
(ot(X)
is
the o r d e r
type
of X)
• 6 C I ~ C T = C 1 n ~.
Now we have
Case
in
below
ultrafil-
6U.
±t is s h o w n
that
exists
C 1 is c l o s e d
(ii)
[73],
(~+)K i m p l i e s
i.e.
(i)
By standard In
unbounded
normal
holds:
(i)
Proof
and U a weakly
to c h e q u e
{l 6 B+Icf(l) lemm~a 2.9
two cases.
= ~} 6 U .
(b) , U is
(~I' B+ ) - r e g u l a r
a n d the
lemma
4.4
is
proved.
Case Now
2:
{I 6 B+Icf(1)
assume (i)
that
the
>w} 6U. following
condition
{61U is c f ( ~ ) - d e c o m p o s a b l e }
If for all
regular
~<5
cf(~)-decomposable,
then
t h a t t h e r e is a r e g u l a r cf(6)-decomposable 2.9.
(b) U is
such
that
lemma
<~.
(~+, B + ) - r e g u l a r But
6U.
is a 6 < 8+ s u c h 4.4.
v < ~ such
cf(6)
~ + , cf(6).
J {~ < 81v r e g u l a r
there
holds.
But
that
v
is e s t a b l i s h e d .
So a s s u m e
that
for a l l
then
{61cf(6) < ~ } 6 U
and hence
a n d U is
6 < ~+ s u c h
t h a t U is
and by
6-decomposable
(i) and
lemma
for a l l
6 _< B
then
and U v-decomposable}
= B and
the
lemma
is p r o v e d .
94
(Evidently
Now
this
assume
case
that
(i)
(ii) {6 I L i m ( @ ) ^ normal. X =
Hence
Now fine
I
Hence
T < B X
for o t ( C I) >~.
C'
are
[id~B+]U . S i n c e
lemma
of
tensive
>w} 6U
regular
B+ . For
in
~+. For
U is w e a k l y
~ < B. The
set
~ < B+ d e f i n e
each
i < B+, Lim(1)
and X T n C ~
of
the
ultraproduct
U is w e a k l y
B+ and
we
implies,
assume 6U.
de-
= ~ for all
normal,
so o n l y
the
with
limit
C~ : I for
it c o n t a i n s
C~
from
4.4
Since
C'
is c l o s e d
of D,
This
X T is a s t a t i o n a r y
v, t h e r e
and
this
shows
is c o m p l e t e . of K e t o n e n
such
from
that
shows
that
The
set
is a s t r i c t l y
<6qln < ~ >
~ 6D ~X % . But
of ideas
that
{61U is c f ( 6 ) - d e c o m p o s a b l e }
of c o f i n a l i t y
C~ D X T = ~.
lemma use
in
since
all
the m o d i f i e d
important.
implies
contradicts proof
subsets
~ of e l e m e n t s
4.5
to be
< ~ . Since
{~I [C~] 6 C ' }
elements
of type
for some
is a D E - s e q u e n c e
= i<8+]~ C ~
unbounded
4.6 D =
6U,
8+ .
{I 6 B+Jcf(1)
only
Lim(1)>
cardinals
oS-sequence
Then
= u and
Cl\(yX+1)
define
closed
ot(Cyl)
for o t ( C I) < v
I <
nonlimit
is s t a t i o n a r y
T
C
cardinals
(i)) .
= ~}.
that
< C ~ l l < B+A
Now
true.
= v} is s t a t i o n a r y
71 6 C 1 such
C~ :
is not
assuming
U is c f ( 6 ) - i n d e c o m p o s a b l e }
{P 6 X L o t ( C p )
for s o m e
occur,
U is ~ - i n d e c o m p o s a b l e
{p < 8 + I c f ( p ) X~ =
cannot
[8].
~U,
by
lemma
increasing
6 = ~
lemma
sequence
a n 6 X T. N o w 6U
is i m p o s s i b l e
of this
below
containing
{I < B+I6 6 C ~ }
(ii)
proof
unbounded
and a n d the
makes
ex-
gS
LeZ
~ ~K
cardinals
Theorem
be
i ~K
4.7:
cardinal
cardinals
a n d L C H ~K b e
such
H ~cf(1)
Assume
<. A s s u m e
Theorem
4.7
that
~L H. L e t U b e L C H w 2 <. T h e n
follows
immediately
the s t a t e m e n t
are
strong
a uniform U is
that
limit
from theorem
limit
numbers.
ultrafilter
6-decomposable
all
on
a regular
for a l l
4.3 a n d the
6 ~<.
following
two
results.
Lemma
4.8:
Assume
U a uniform
Lemma
4.9:
ultrafilter
on
K such
t h a t U is
of cardinals Then
of Lemma
U is
4.8:
show
28 =
8+ . T h i s
theorem
2.8 U c a n n o t
limit
(~,cf(1))-regular.
t h a t U is an
Let
that
implies
B÷ ~ =
a first
and
(~,8)-regular.
< l _
8 is s i n g u l a r ,
cardinal
standard B÷ B =
function
6 -decomposable
covering
B+
and
for a s e q u e n c e
2@ =
lemma
4.1
lemma
B+.
ar-
T h e n by
shows
that U
(~, 8 ) - r e g u l a r .
Proof
of
lemma
ing sequence
4.9:
of elements we may
H =
that
<6
I such Let
I~ < c f ( 1 ) >
that
/q U v = ~ v6S
be
for e a c h
Iv < c f ( 1 ) >
v
let x
increas-
~
be an injective
for all
~ 6K
a strictly
<6
=
is
sequence
infiniteS ccf(1) H
>
{~ < c f ( 1 ) IH 6 U
W.l.o.g. }. T h e n
and
{y 6 ~ ( c f ( 1 )
cardinality
the m a p p i n g
to
f o r U.
of U such
assume
6~(cf(1))
Let w.l.o.g.
converging
a 6 -decomposition
has
have
such
cf(1)
strong
U 6~ = I u b e v
Since
guments
X
T h e n U is
cardinals,
for ~ < c f ( 1 ) .
is
B+"
K,l be
Iv < c f ( 1 ) >
Proof
on
8 be a s i n g u l a r
Let
ultrafilter <~
7L H. L e t
13H 6 K
K. L e t
H ~ x
H
of
(y = XH) }
K onto
H.
be the p a r t i t i o n Now
let
for e a c h
of x 6H
K generated ~
x
be
the
by common
g8
refinement
of the p a r t i t i o n s
taining
the sets
we
that
show
partition UY N U
some
by
the
{y 6 Y I H q
Y _>I. S i n c e gives
Since
rise
K ~Px"
~ be
for x E H
Let ~ x =
such
that
H 6 UY N U
y 6 ~ x for some
definition <~
> for ~ 6 X
_(U Ny)_c
to a l - d e c o m p o s i t i o n
for U. Then
Since
Clearly
for e a c h
m. H e n c e
U~
con
Next is a
~
y _cpq for
is a ~ - d e c o m p o -
cardinality we o b t a i n
for U.
the p a r t i t i o n
, H is an e l e m e n t
x containing
pq~} has
Ux < _ 6 max(x)
UY 6U.
u 6x
of Ux,
and
{YI~ ~ Y c-P x and y 6 ~ x } .
Ux is a l - d e c o m p o s i t i o n
for e a c h
determined
q <6
sition,
U • = x~
of <. L e t Y c U
6U.
uniquely
P x and
< p ~ I q <~
> 6 v" This
shows
i = ~* = ~ and U*
97
References
[I]
J. Baumgartner, and H i n t i k k a
I n e f f a b i l i t y properties
(eds.), Logic, Found.
87-106, D. Reidel [2]
of Math.
[4]
T. Dodd andR.
[5]
L. H a r r i n g t o n and A. K e c h r i s , ~
[8]
of AMS 220
J. Ketonen,
singletons
Logic
and O ~. Fund. Math.
393-399
47-76 and large cardinals,
Trans.
(1976), 61-73
K. Kunen and K. Prikry, Symb. Logic
W. Mitchell,
[11]
J. Paris, (1974),
filters and i r r e g u l a r ultrafilters,
Nonregular ultrafilters
[10]
36
On d e s c e n d i n g l y
(1971),
incomplete ultrafilters,
650-693
Ramsey cardinals and c o n s t r u c t i b i l i t y ,
Patterns of indiscernibles,
to appear
Bull. London Math.
Soc.
6
183-188
K. Prikry,
On d e s c e n d i n g l y complete ultrafilters,
mer School in Math.
[13]
appear in Ann. Math.
Strong c o m p a c t n e s s and other cardinal sins, Ann.
J. Ketonen,
Journ.
[12]
(1976),
Logic 5 (1972),
of AMS 224 [9]
Jensen, The core model, to
A. Kanamori, W e a k l y normal
Math.
unpublished
167-171
Trans. [7]
Theory,
(1973)
T. Dodd and R. Jensen, The core model,
[6]
and Comp.
Model Theory, North Holland,
[3]
(95),
II, in Butts
(1977)
C.C. Chang and H.J. Keisler, Amsterdam
of cardinals
Logic,
Lecture Notes in Math. Vol.
Springer,
New York
P. Welsh,
C o m b i n a t o r i c a l Principles
thesis, O x f o r d
(1973),
(1979).
C a m b r i d g e Sum337,
459-488 in the core model,
D. Phil.
A LATTICE
STRUCTURE
OF
COMPLETE
ON T H E BOOLEAN
Sabine II.
ISOMORPHISM ALGEBRAS
K o p p e l b e r g I)
Mathematisches
Institut
der
K~nigin-Luise-Str. D-IOOO
For
every
type of
of
B.
complete
B.
Let
Boolean
T(A) ~ T(B)
where
the
order
inherited
of
is
B,
relative
most
for
arbitrary
lattice;
To the
33
(cBA)
B,
up
isomorphism,
to
let
T(B)
be
the
isomorphism
a direct
factor
{T(B
6 B}
B [ b = Ix C B I x ~ B]
B and
hence
ordered
which
r b)]b
has
a cBA. set,
as
(T(B),S), proved
a greatest
is
the
in
element
endowed "type
[13],
T(B)
with
1.31
and
the partial
structure" or
[10],
a smallest
22.6 ele-
• (B ~ O ) .
Our
and
by
1.4),
:
algebra
a partially
also
ment
Berlin
Let
T(B)
(see
is,
FU
24/26
Berlin
algebra if A
TYPES
general
B is
both
Theorem
algebras
Theorem
structure
Stone
space
how
(T(B) ,~)
Heyting get
result
of
R(B)
B we of
=
type
B in its
prove
structure
section dual
satisfying
global
R(B),
and
the
of
(T(B) ,S)
lattice
(a--~b)
in T h e o r e m
sections
2:
(T~B),~) is
(T(B) ,~)
v (b--~a)
A that a sheaf
linear
like
a distributive
are
= 1 for
(T(B) ,~) of
looks
Stone
algebras
arbitrary
is
isomorphic
orders
over
where
{x 6 Blf(x)
=x
for
every
automorphism
f of
B]
I) The author gratefully acknowledges partial support by the Forschungsinstitut fur Mathematik, ETH ZUrich
a,b. to the
99
is the c o m p l e t e
Our
starting
Theorem this of
point
paper.
It s a y s
a homogeneous of
first version this
theorem
section
3.7
version
of
about
the
R = R(B)
[5].
paper,
complete
version
of
B =C I where
such
~c)
Solovay, the
~
T(A) ~
Y(B)
and
then
aware
by Solovay after
and
to t h e
paper
stronger
above)
cBA.
families
in
- More
in
results (where
the
technique
[11]
and u s i n g
established
lattice. this
condition
precisely,
(Ri)i6 1 of
that
R ~B
is a c o m p l e t e
chain
fact
a
seen the first
situation
only
countable
the
is q u o t e d
having
as d e v e l o p e d
answering
finishing
of
of
B is a p o w e r
thus
after
result
cBA's
The
for
and for
Solovay's
and
(ai)i6 1 of
~
,
T(B)
~
proved
reduct
something
isomorphism
types
, is a c a r d i n a l to be
is e x p r e s s i b l e s ~ t
I-~ (ai,<) (Ri) iEI of)
the Boolean
power
of an
a c B A C.
is d e f i n e d
above
became
t h a t T(B)
(.the t w o - v a l u e d
has
T of all
rations
defined
[--~Ri i6I
d w.r.t,
in fact,
class
are
Only
of B d e f i n e d
the present the
order,
was
that
denotes
q-structure
shows
structures
interesting
considerably
forcing
C is a r i g i d
there
the most
Solovay,
B satisfying
at t y p e
[3].
author
subalgebra
of V (R) h e
that
of
obtained
of B.
is w e l l - o r d e r e d ) ,
of T(B) . A p p l y i n g
R ~
where
has
Boolean-valued
shows
T(B)
result
Conversely
structure
ordinals
paper
look
is a l i n e a r
the
algebras
algebras
if T(B)
(and h e n c e
this
elements
is p e r h a p s
of
C inside
Boolean
that
a closer
version
this
preliminary
having
3 which
cBA
invariant
a preliminary
of
is t h e
Theorem
of
is an u n p u b l i s h e d
two-stage
method
for
C in s e c t i o n
a question
of
subalgebra
iff
of
more:
it is w e l l - k n o w n
cBA's,
algebra
endowed
in t h e
T ( A x B) ; h e n c e
the
sense partial
by t = s Q
r
for
some
r 6 T.
with of
that
two
[13].
order
opeHere,
~ of T
100
Now,
for
T(E),
a fixed
where
E is
b 6 B satisfying bra
of
cBA
T the
B,
a cBA
let To(B)
be
such
for
O < d ~ e,
structure
that
E } d ~B
the
~ b.
of w h i c h
has
class
each
isomorphism
e 6 E~{O},
T~(B) been
of
is
then
there
types
are
a cardinal
completely
d 6 E, subalge-
described
by
Solovay.
Another
consequence
without
rigid
remarks
in
quoted
In
factors.
4.6
above
contrast
to
forcing.
proofs
of
R(B)
In
be
that
section
(this
is,
who
the
proof
of T h e o r e m C:
cBA
C such
that
not
too
satisfying Theorem
or
in
apply
more
in
[ 9 ] and
the
some
E in
we
The
on
B
results
paper.
of B o o l e a n -
sometimes
literature.
facts
cBA
elementary
4.
technique
automorphism
to
every
a forthcoming
the
the
for
with
readable,
found with
simple R(B)
course,
the
1.5.
Souslin
in
give
This
group
applies,
of
cardinal
B or
algebras
number
In
in
C,
that,
be
completely
another
condition). in
section
section
compared by
3 we
4 two
embedded
with
countable
into The the
first
these
A
and
give
the
B
a homogeneous
that 2 in chain
a homogeneous second
read
A).
applications
into
Proposition
the
embedded
problem
Theorem
Theorems
B cannot
solves
for
the
a cBA B satisfying
E which
decomposition
2 contains
is
chain
every
4 may
and
of
that
3 and
completely
D ; remember
countable
a product background
in g e n e r a l .
be
mainly
sections
there
the
to
intuitive
above,
B can
showing
rise
Section
(T(B,~)
cBA
(Theorem
gives
interested
to
of
remarks
the
C mentioned
every
large
that
of
1.1
structure
of T h e o r e m
such
not
B e ~B
Theorem
Solovay
paper to be
[7]
some
of
after
that
do
connected
is m a i n l y
about
implies
by
that
together
immediately
we
the
is
[13].
1 we m a k e
immediately
gives
in
of
reader
that
published
facts
decomposition
The
this,
facts
product T(B)
Note
To m a k e
to
in
method
paper,
contained
contained
Solovay's
4.7,
elementary
example,
with
and
will
valued
for
of
of
B,
[I],
V = L
condition cBA
application
version
is
of
is
[3]:
101
if B is nite,
BA's on
a cBA
then
are
a cBA and ~
IAut
that
B1 ~ =
Aut(B) , the
iAut
by
are
by +,-,-,0,1,
denoted write
their
a Sb
automorphism
group
of
B,
is
infi-
B I.
abbreviated
. We
instead
such
underlying
instead
the
of
sets.
The
infinite
a + b if
a,b
finite
joins are
operations
and
meets
disjoint
by
and
~a i i6I call
of
[a i if t h e a i a r e p a i r w i s e d i s j o i n t . If ~b i = I, w e i6I i6I (bi)i6 I a p a r t i t i o n of B. B is t h e n i s o m o r p h i c to t h e p r o d u c t a l g e b r a
(B ~bi) , a n d e v e r y p r o d u c t d e c o m p o s i t i o n of B a r i s e s , u p t o i s o m o r i6I p h i s m , in t h i s w a y . E s p e c i a l l y , w e h a v e t h a t t h e d i r e c t f a c t o r s of B are,
up
set
D of
is
some
We
use
to
isomorphism,
B\{O]
said
to be d e n s e
d 6 D such
that
d ~b.
standard and
The
author
ful
comments
pointing
set-theoretical
IXI
is
on
out
the
of
this
I. D e c o m p o s i t i o n s
B and
B,
C are
in
of
correspondence
B.
A sub-
b 6 B\{O} , t h e r e
the
set
of n o n n e g a t i v e
and
M.Rubin
mostly
his
for
help-
to R . S o l o v a y
for
simplification methods
improving
paper.
automorphism
to be
totally
B ~b
different.
of
R(B)
algebra
into
products
different
~ C ~ c.
group if
x,y 6 B are
of B.
there totally
are
If C is no
a cBA,
b 6 B\{O}
different
and
if B ~x,
Let
R(B) = {r 6 B l f ( r )
the
of
X.
about
the
R instead
each
B ~b
a considerable
B be
totally
of B,
2 and
let A u t
B by
algebra
C - but
T(B)
that
w is
to M . R i c h t e r
and
said
algebras for
a set
R(B)
such
We write
of
Theorem
section
for
if,
of
c 6 C\{O} are
in B
notations;
gratitude
proof
moreover
relative
cardinality
her
an e r r o r
C;
results
a cBA
the
expresses
in T h e o r e m
For
the
is
integers
the
exactly
=r
for
if B is of
every
fixed.
invariant
f 6 Aut Clearly
elements
B}, R is a c o m p l e t e
of B.
sub-
102
1.1. and
Let
a 6 B.
assume
that
interchanging f(a) # a,
a 6 R
O <x
x
and
iff
~ a, y
and
different.
f 6 Aut
So
of
B
each
r i is
1.2.
For
f(a)
such
such
On
~ a and,
totally
a 6 B,
different
is
f(a) of
clear
R which
is
a 6 R iff
1.3.
For
x ~ r. g(x)
=x;
f 6 Aut
greater
Let
g 6 Aut(B
Then
If
g(x)
(ri)i61
rj
are
Fy.
since
There
z ~-(x+y)
hand,
symmetry,
a 6 R. B
or
have B;
proves ~ r).
and
equal
R(B
put
let
f(a)
f(a) = a.
totally
-a
-a
-If
and
hence
f 6 Aut
that
totally
is
i # j,
a parthen
{ r i J i 6 I} ~ R .
6Aut
B}.
Moreover,
if
hence
a ~r.
to
i.e.
a,
r 6 R and
So
a is
a ~r,
the
then
smallest
element
r r) = R ~r:
x 6 R.
To
since
a partition
r r) . S ~ n c e
prove
f 6 Aut
B
the
such
x 6 R.
This
of
we
R,
first,
that
x 6 R(B
g 6 Aut(B
converse,
shows
have
suppose
g ~f
[ r) , w e
let and
~r) . So get
x 6 R ~r ~B f(y) = y f o r
x 6 R(B
~r) .
B =]-~ Bi, iCI
where
Bi~B
f(x) = r r. y ~-r.
~ r i.
Let
R i = R ( B i) . S o R ~
(R [ r i ) i61
i.e. gives
each rise
product to
B
totally
(ri)i61 for
a 6 R
shows
be
are
different
[ rj = - r i , j#±
an
which
a and and
is
let
6RIa_
g = f~(B
Choose
= f(x) = x,
is
• - a = O,
different:
a = a.
f 6 Aut this
B ~x ~B
other
[{f(a)If
a ~ a and
for
r 6 R we
Let
totally
f(z) = z f o r
from
a :Jl{r
and
are
let
that
~ f(r) = r
-a and
the
by
r i and
a =
It
that
B . f(a)
that
a and
O < y ~-a
a contradiction.
different
tition
Then
decomposition
a product
= I~R(B i61
rri)
=]~Ri, i61
B ~ ~-~B i g i v e n b y a p a r t i t i o n i61 decomposition R(B) ~ J J R ( B i ) . i6I
of
R ~B
103
1.4.
For
assume, are
each by
of
cBA
defining
minimal
proper
isomorphism B
hence
a cBA.
i6I If
I={1,...,n},
cardinal
and
we
for
are
For
t 6 T,
(e ® t) Define,
~
~
any
the
means
and
that
of
s_
a cBA
of
T:
t
freely the
of
BA's
isomorphic
that
T(B)
is
a set
sets
and
speak
class
about
of
all
(ti)i6I
where
in
T ( B i)
®
of
B. to
even
we
= t i for
t n instead
of
than
classes
types
define
may
B which
rather
isomorphism T,
We
iI] = ~
associative, e e (s ~
iff
t=s
cBA
the
and
T(B)
Q t i 6 • by i6I
G ti. i6I
If
~ is
t) = (~ ®
and
distributive
s) ~9 (~ ® t) ,
(~B)
laws ~t =
By
of
type
< is
for t has
we
such
the
and that
choose
induction,
x 6T.
a direct
give
reflexive
x,y 6T
some
factor
of
that
< is
proof
transitive. t =x
an,
(D s,
bn,
cn,
Now s =y d n in
type
s.
suppose ~
t. B
bn Pan)
=s,
s,t 6T
Let
such
B be that
_> b o _> a I > b I _> . . . .
= Cn + a n + l T(B
Let
rbn)
e =
=t,
T(B
I-~ an = ~ b n " n6~0 n6w
[Cn)
=x,
NOW
For
a partial
an = d n + b n
ao
a
i 6 I.
I = ao
So
of
i 6 I.
t i = t for
commutative
69 x
reader,
Choose
T(B
a
in ~ ,
each
s.
rank,
~ t i where iEi
clearly,
type
set
type
let
of
t_<s.
isomorphism
etc.
s and
convenience
order
the
t i ~_) ...
® , e.g.
(8 e t)
the
family
write
s_
be
T be
obvious
and
for
be
t i = 4(l--~Bi) i£I we
some
(~ ,
to
may
Let
® t =
There
T(B)
T(B)
types.
is
let
set-theoretical
class;
where
B,
T ( B ~ d n) = y .
104
ao
:
e -~ [
Cn "~ ~ d n
nEa) bo
and
hence
1.5.
= e 4
~ Cn n6w
s =
~(B
be) @ ~
~x
~
~ ®y
t =
T(B
be) +<0 ® x
O
~ ~y
Let
B
is
T has
B be
a fixed
fixed,
cBA; =
T(B)
element
T(b) 6 T t o
b 6 B gives
implies
Suppose
x.b =0.
different
do
1.6. we
We
do
b,
not
identify
clear
know (note
s , t 6 T,
(i.e.,
and
we
different)
is
instead
of
T(B
r b).
-b
R wiht
(T,~)
= 0 Tiff that
element
T : B --~T w h i c h we
Put
Choose
are
x 6 B
totally
a subset
of
which
of
following
is
the
a lattice, not
s,t
imply
are
7(a) = s,
the s O
totally T(b) = t,
onto
a ~b
that x
in
O <x is
we
following t 6 T,
~a
x ~ a.
shall
way.
R
totally
contradicts
diagram
in
that
such
commutative
T
clearly
different,
T,
and
0 T = 0 T.
is
prove
T a) ~ T(b) , w h i c h
s,t 6 T does
such
a smallest
S T(b).
the
T = {t 6 T i t N T(B) },
injective:
a by
R inside
inf(s,t)
if, a , b 6 B
T(b)
Clearly,
a map
and
have
whether that
T. and
~(a)
from
characterize
yet
T [R
Sinceb
hence
sequel,
may
for
x ~-b.
therefore
the
fectly (I)
from
may
in
So
by
I T = T(B)
. Now
T(a) ~ Y ( b ) .
b 6 B write
{~(b) ib 6 B}.
and order preserving
- We
[ dn n->l
for
abbreviate
a greatest
Assigning
but
$
s : t.
T(B)
If
nE<J
always
Although are
per-
generally):
different then
a,b
are
totally
105
(2)
if
s,t 6 T
Call
t 6 T
sup(s,t)
and
inf(s,t)
complemented
: s ~
t : I T. R :
which
follows
t 6 T has
{r 6 T i r
1.1.
a pseudocomplement
t*
which
1.7.
We
proceed
t ^ b
is
is
even
to the
Namely,
in
show
Let
that
define,
for
infimum
t A b ~y
f(x-b)
argument,
that
complemented It
is
in T
also
equals
inf(s,t)
s ~
t.
: 0 T and
in T } ,
not
(i.e.
of
b 6 R and
t and
b
where
x 6B,
is w e l l - d e f i n e d , be
f(x) since
such
and
hard
to
a greatest
see
that
element
every
disjoint
in
t 6T,
an
(T,<),
element
but
we
t ^ b 6 T
will
not
(in
use
let
f : B rx--~B
and
s C T
exists
R.
t Ab=m(x-b) To
is
is
from
t)
this).
there
sup(s,t)
Then
easily
from
fact,
if
= 0 T then
using
an
suppose
isomorphism.
= f(x.b)
re(x) = t . y 6 B
totally
different
f-i
instead
of
f,
that
T (y) = t.
Now
Sf(x.-b):y-b
is
such
%y--b,
from
shows
y.-b,
that
f(x.b)
_
f(x.b)=y-b,
The
hence
same
T(x.b)=
m (y-b) .
I .8.
For
t E T,
let T ~t =
So
if
b 6B
and
decomposition the
product
~(b) : t , of
of
R gives
a family
{s 6 T l s _
~b) = T
rise of
to
partial
order).
i 6 I,
~ b i and
Ti = T ( B i )
Bi = B
We
now
a product
partially
coordinate-wise let
Pt.
Let :T
that
decomposition
ordered (bi) i6I r b i.
prove
sets be
Define
is
each
product
of
(where
T
endowed
a partition
with of
R.
the For
106
%° : T --~ T~i i E I
i£II
t ~-~ (t ^ bi)
F
Since
[ I Ti f o r t 6 T. ~ is o n e - o n e : f o r t 6 T, i61, l e t x 6 B s u c h t h a t r(x) = t. B y x = I x . h i , w e s e e t h a t t = T(x) = i6I ~T(x-b i) = ~ (t ^ b i) m a y b e r e c o n s t r u c t e d f r o m ~(t) . ~ is o n t o : i6I i6I l e t t i 6 T i f o r i 6 I, i.e. t i S b i . C h o o s e , f o r i 6 I, x i 6 B s u c h t h a t
Y(xi)
t A b i ~b i for
= t i and
i 6 I,
x i ~ b i 6 R ~ B.
T ( x o b i) = T ( X i) = ti; Choose
~(t)
x,y 6 B
such
so
~(t)
that
6
Put
x
i xi i6I = ( t i ) i 6 I. -~
T(y) : t,
=
and is
x ~ y and
t = T(x).
For
i 6 I,
order-preserving:
T(x) = s.
Then,
t A bi =
let
for
s ~ t.
i 6 I,
S A b i = T (x'b i) < T (y'b i) : t A b i. Finally,
<0(s)_<%0(t)
(i.e.
s ^bi
_
i E I)
implies
s _< t,
since
s = i ~ i ( s ^ b i) < ~ (t ^ b i) = t . iEI This
shows
that
1.9.
Define,
<0 is
for
our
an
isomorphism
cBA
from
T onto
~-~T(B i61
~ b i)
B,
a =
[
{x 6 B l x
is
an
atom
of
B],
h =
[ {x E B I B
~x
is
atomless
and
homogeneous}
r =
[ {x 6 B I B
~x
is
atomless
and
rigid}
d = -(a+h+r) (a B A
C
every
c 6 C\{O}).
totally
is
called
rigid a,h,r
different.
By
B [a
is
cardinality lyl = Izl. I ~ <.
So
the
T(B
set
~ a)
CI : I a n d
hence
d
are
homogeneous
elements
of
if
R and
C ~C
~ c for
pairwise
1.8.
isomorphic of
IAut
and
T =T(B)
Now,
if
is
~T(B
to of
r a) x T ( B
the
power
atoms
of
isomorphic
~h)
set
x T(B
algebra
rr)
x T(B
P(<)
~d).
where
< is
B~
for
y , z E P(<) , ~(y) = T(z)
to
the
well-ordered
set
of
the iff
cardinals
107
Next,
(see
[7]) ,
TTH
B rh ~
i6I where
e a c h H i is a h o m o g e n e o u s
and H o are t o t a l l y
different.
ordered
chain
structure
number
a greatest
of H.
cBA
and
< a cardinal,
element
It is n o t
T ( H K)
(which d e s c r i b e s
is a w e l l -
fully
the
hard
to p r o v e
that,
for a n y
cardi-
~,B < c(H) .
a cardinal,
by
each
Cj
=
is r i g i d ,
are t o t a l l y
different.
C is r i g i d ,
T ( C <)
itself
greater of
and
one
c(H) ~ ~ ~ ~}.
~ 6 K, w e h a v e
Since, that
for e v e r y
(T(H <) , ~ ) ~
(K,~).
[7], B ~r
a complete
than ~
~C< j j6J 3 <j
is a c a r d i n a l
It c a n be p r o v e d
is a r e t r a c t
of
lattice;
< and (Z(c) d e n o t e s , b y C.
If C s a t i s f i e s
T ( C <) ~ (K,~) (c) . H e n c e on T ( B [d) , w h e r e the existence
1.10.
1.8,
and d-d' : O for d,d' 6 D, d # d ' },
x 6 H K , H K r x ~ H ~ for e x a c t l y
power
i # j, H i
~,~ > O ,
L e t K = {0,I} U {el~
hence
for
atomless
H ~ ~ H B iff
where
and,
J J T(H i ) . i6I
= sup{ Jml+Jm ~ H ,
the S o u s l i n
Again
K i is a c a r d i n a l
of T ( B [ h)) : let
c(H)
nals
with
By
--
T ( B ~ h) ~
If H is a h o m o g e n e o u s
cBA,
of
It is e a s i l y
established
j ~ j', Cj
in an e l e m e n t a r y
complete
lattice
here
K is t h e
set of
for
any
the
countable
the difficulties
algebras
for
the
B ~ d is a c B A w i t h o u t these
and,
was
that
way
that,
if
(K,<) (c) and cardinals
~ not
s t r u c t u r e O6, the B o o l e a n chain
condition,
in d e s c r i b i n g homogeneous
first
the
and Cj,
proved
following
in
T(B)
then
concentrate
or r i g i d
factors
[I].
conditions
on a cBA
-
108
B
are
equivalent:
a)
T =T(B)
b)
T
c)
T = R(B)
d)
T(x) = T(x)
e)
each
is
by
each
for
where
A
is
2.
The
We
assume
bra
B.
But
a cBA
T(B)
notation
Let,
method
of
Stone
P 6 X, We
get
X where
predicate
Theorem global The
of
a quotient
then
over
space
<.
A.
are
clopen
subset
establishes
a cBA
that
hard
not
{~ ®
t-
and
to
see,
t holds
e ® t = t for
the
an
of
R = R(B) the
this
for
each
t : ~(A)
T,~)
a complete
subalge-
element
r 6 R
section,
topology.
of
is
smallest
ultrafilter
usual
(Tp,~)
so
x 6 R is
rest
is
the
I;
and
of
R},
We
shall
define,
a topology
on
logic
one
for
S = U Tp. p£X (as d e f i n e d in [6])
~ is
language
of
first-order
isomorphic
to
(r($) ,<) , t h e
We
is
iff
$ = (S,z,X,~)
the
condition
it
a sheaf
sections
(Tp,<)
is
chain
factors.
x 6 B,
structure
of i - s t r u c t u r e s
with
binary
prove:
(T,<)
essential
R with
a cBA:
yields
section
for
countable
T(B)
X : {p ~ R I p the
the
T(B)
rigid
for
T.
always
that
of
that,
x ~ r.
is
Solovay's without
Recall
in
satisfying
structure
the
satisfying
B
equivalence,
lattice
of
a complement
factors,
t 6 T(B).
algebra
x £ B
a cBA
above
algebra
Boolean
for
t 6 T has
rigid
the
a Boolean
a complete
Moreover, without
is
is
~ -structure
of
all
of ~. point
linear of
in
orders X,
np
this
representation
and, being
for the
s , t 6 T, canonical
of
(T,<)
{p 6 X I ~ p ( S ) map
from
is
that
the
stalks
< ~p(t) } is T to
Tp.
This
a
109
Theorem
B.
and
dual
lattice
the
operation
If
its ~
is
(T,<)
a distributive (T,>) of
algebra
in
2.1.
1.7,
In
T(x) = t.
the
We
R imply
we
of
there
from
B rx.b
from
z.-c ~-c.
2.2.
Let
onto
some
p E X be
s ~
tiff
s ~
~p
a reflexive
Clearly,
is
equivalence s ~pt
iff
s , t E T, zp(t)
is
Heyting
(T,<)
is
algebras. in
a
(T,<)
(T,<) ,
linear
Heyting
t E T,
the
fact
such
such
b E R by that
that
that
t Ab = ~(x.b)
s ^b
~ t Ab
T(x) = s,
z ~y.b and
and
in
T and
T(y) = t.
some
x - c ~ c is
where c ~b
By
isomorphism
totally
t ~
b E p P
such
that
s ^b
~ t A b
s.
and
transitive
relation
on
T,
~p
is
an
and
there
is
some
b E p
such
that
s A b = t ^b.
let = {s' E T I s '
~ p t} '
T p = { z p ( t ) It 6 T} np(s) So
(Tp,~)
and
is
2.3.
s
mapping
ordered and
Tp
set,
has
~p:T
--~Tp
a smallest
is
Z p ( O T)
an
order-preserving
and
a greatest
Wp(IT).
Let
the
iff
a partially
surjective
element
to
s,t ET.
following
In
the
rest
construction
of
Section
and
2,
notations:
we
shall choose
frequently x,y 6 B
f
different
s,t 6 T define
some
t and
relation
Both
~ z.c ~ y.c.
For
there
for
z = z.c $ z.-c
f(x.c)
fixed.
p
and
I.
pseudo-complementation
x,y E T
z E B
s ~p t i f f P
use
Now
Hence,
algebras
O and
[8].
let
B F z.
with
s , t E T - i.e.
sometimes
is
Stone
t A b E T
s A C ~ t ^ C:
~ t Ab
for
defined
shall
s Ab
For
sense
are
lattice
relative
t) V ( t ~ S) = I T h o l d s
(S ~
in
is
such
refer that
110
T(x) = s , maximal T ( y i)
T(y)=t. with
for
Let,
respect
i 6 I;
by
to
for
Zorn's
the
i # j,
XO
=
lemma,
properties:
{ (xi,Yi) li 6 I}
O < x i ~ X,
x i • xj : Yi " Yj = O.
[ Xi i6I
x 1 = X"
F=
-x o
a family
O < Yi ~ Y a n d
T(X
i) :
Put
Yi
Yo
:
Yl
: y " -Yo"
[ i6I
be
So T ( x o) for
some
d 6 T
and
= :(Yo)
x l , y I are,
= d by
maximality
of
F,
totally
in
1.2.
different.
Hence b = xl, disjoint
are
2.4. So
Let
by
p6X
f =-b
6 p
the
be and
definition
fixed.
s ^ f = dA
c ~ p.
proved
So
for
Note
that,
s,t,
the
depend
on
the
d 6 T defined
P
by
is
proved
symmetry
2.3
for
or
c £p.
Assume
that
b {p.
yields = Xo.f ,
b ~ p;
(Tp,_<)
s <_ t or P
choice
that
b £p
=
t ^f
of
by
symmetry,
is a l i n e a r
x,y,F,xo,xl,Yo,y
x,y,F, ....
from
order.
I are
t _< s f o r p
t _
not
every
uniquely
p 6X
Moreover
for
does, each
determined
by
of
not
course,
p 6 X,
the
type
satisfies
~p(d) this
This
given
t.
p 6 X,
that
in
b.c =O,
s _
although
fact
xl,Yl
f = T(yo.f ) S ~(y-f)
that any
of
= Xo.f Sxl.f
s -<
have
By
xl.f =O. x.f
We
c = ~I
the
: min(~p(S) case
c ~ p implies
,Zp(t)) ;
b ~ p by
the
above
d A --C = t A --C.
lines,
and
it
follows
111
2.5.
Let
s,t 6 T be
fixed
u : By
the
want
definition
to
set
show
{p 6 Xl
cl(f) ~ u .
2.1,
as
in
u
f £ p}
of
=
it
is
even for
{a 6 RE
there
2.1
is
that
claim
that
p 6 u,
choose
clear
that
clopen.
f 6 R by
s ^ a ~t
a subset
2.3.
Put
u
an
First,
is
open
subset
of
the
clopen
abbreviating
cl(f) , w e
u = cl(e). f 6 p proves
{p 6 X I ~p(t)
~p(S)
W.l.o.g.,
i.e.
Clearly,
} and
In
{p6X
that
=
see
that
X.
We sub-
s ^ f S t ^ f implies
of
[RM.
M
such
e is
e 6 M,
an
So
in X,
Now
f 6M,
analoguous
p # q
~ =
largest ~u.
I Zp(S)=~p(t)
for
that
the
cl(~)
s ^ f ~ t ^ f.
u ~cl(~).
=
~
that
by
satisfying
suppose S
^ a} ,
{ a i l i 6 I}
s ^ e S t ^ a;
cl(e) , w h i c h
2.6.
X
in
s ~pt}.
~p, is
b , c 6 R as
Let M
By
{p6x{
of
that
and
~ a i. It f o l l o w s i6I element of M. W e
suppose
f ~
way,
} are
we
and
p 6 cl(f)
see
that
clopen
T p N T q = ~.
p 6 u.
subsets
of
By
X.
Put
UTp.
p6x Let
z : S --~X be
defined z(x)
For
t 6 T,
g 6 R
{bt,glt
checked
that
onto
For
by
X.
2.7.
Let
=
6 T , g 6 R} ~ is,
x 6 S there
~ rn
p be
iff
x 6 Tp.
is
the
{ ~ p ( t ) I p 6 cl(g) }. is
a basis
w.r.t,
z homeomorphically
n = bt,iR;
= p
let bt,g
Then
by
an
map
is
this
of
a topology
topology,
an
injective
which
open
n of
subset
continuous
assigns
to
S.
It
a continuous
a neighbourhood
onto
of
of
X:
open
every
x
in
open S which
let, map
p 6 X
is
map
from
is m a p p e d
if x = Zp(t) ,
from
the
easily
n onto
X.
~-structure
S
112
(Tp,<) . T h e x < y in there
underlying
are
sheaf
The
neighbourhoods
of
g(p) 6 T p Since
details
F(~) ~ ~ Tp, p6x
give
2.9.
For
show
F(~)
examples
t 6T,
that
be
(p) . S u p p o s e
show
sense
of y s u c h
that
of
is
~=
[6].
g : X --~S s u c h the
where
s , t 6 t. that
(S,~,
Recall
that
of
all
F(~)
as
a substructure
sections
of
global
an
for
every
X,p) that
and
Then
is a a global
~ o g = idx,
set
(if n o n - e m p t y )
x,y 6 Tp
i.e.
sections
of
~ .
of t h e p r o d u c t
~ -structure.
In 2.9
$ .
be defined
by
= Zp(t) .
g t 6 F($),
bs,g
bt,g
2.7
consider
gt : X - - ~ S
-i
y = Zp(t)
2.5.
the
map
F(~)
and
from
and
X in
of g l o b a l
let
q 6 X satisfying and
2.6
denotes
we may
is T p = z
of x a n d
follows
in
pl61x(Tp,<) ; so
Zp(t) ; l e t
p=q
as
over
~t(p) We
bs,g
proved
p 6 X.
~(p)
x = ~p(s)
@ is a c o n t i n u o u s
for
structure we
< ~q(t)
of ~ - s t r u c t u r e s
section
of
p(p) = (Tp,<) ; e.g.
q 6 cl(g) , Zq(S)
2.8.
set
i.e.
that
g t is
a neighbourhood
g 6q.
By
zp(t)=~p(S).
of x.
Zp(t) = ~ q ( S )
Let,
by
a continuous
map:
let
S o g 6 p a n d x = ~q(S)
and
Tp ~Tq=~
for
p#q
gt(p) for we
= x
some
get
2.5,
v = {p' 6 X I ~ P, (s) : ~p, (t) } = el(B) . So p E v and
g.
of p in X i n t o
~ 6p. the
We
prove
that
neighbourhood
gt m a p s
bs,g
the neighbourhood
of x in S:
and gt(p') since
g E p' .
2.10.
Proof
of T h e o r e m
= ~p, (t)
A.
We
: T -~ F (~)I r t ~--~gt
J
= ~ p, (s) 6 b s , g
prove
that
cl(g.~)
if g • B 6 p' , p ' 6 v
=
113
is
an
isomorphism
of ~ - s t r u c t u r e s .
Since
s ~ t
iff
F(~) :
~(t)
6 F(~)
for
every
for
t 6 T,
F(~) # ~.
Now
if
s ~ t,
in
-i
assume
u = X, are
us ~ ut
Us( p ) = Z p ( S )
Conversely, that
T
~ ~p(t)
that
a = I and,
be
given.
also
Utp(P)
by
s £ M,
that
u ~Up = Utp
~Up.
Since
p E X
By
holds
This
- So
remains
to
choose is
I ~ i ~ n
is
the
of
X,
hence
terminology
that
such
open
p 6 X;
one-one
prove
an
there
bl,...,b n 6 R are
in
~
tp 6 T
compactness
for
means,
s ~ t.
= ~(p) , t h e r e
I R : b I + ... S b n a n d c l ( b i) ~ U p i .
it
For
= np(tp)
= ut(p)
u s ~ ot"
order-preserving;
u E F(X,S)
in
and
~
that
is
exists
and
Let
Up
of
p
such
bl,...,b n 6 R such
Pi E X
pairwise
~
2.5,
~(p) = Z p ( t p ) . S i n c e
neighbourhood
choose
of
both
onto.
u s ~ ot-
that
satisfying
disjoint,
the
isomorphism
type t = is
in
that
T.
We
claim
p 6 Upi
ut(p)
and
: ~p(t)
~_t_!~" P r o o f properties
that
of
resp.
of
Define
B.
largest
u : {p 6 X [ ~ p ( S ) SO u
and
which
v
are
ut;
likewise,
and
with
which
Os
with the
on
v
coincides
docomplement (Tp,<) , b e i n g
with
of
fact,
for
the
other
On
prove B.
that
~(OT)
elements
subsets ~s
on
u
function is
(tpn A bn) p 6 X,
e.g.
hand,
b i 6 p,
we
have
t A b i = tpi A b i and
(F(~) ,<) and
of
~(I T)
F(~) . L e t
is
a lattice
are,
the
and
u s w.r.t,
X.
Clearly,
with
~t
u s v o t 6 F(~)
supremum
UlT
a linear
of
on
u
qt"
order,
and
of
is
v
which
u s and
with
F(~)is
on
the
ot
ut;
is
course, u t be
function the
the is
a distributive
with
the
the
elements
}. u s ^ u t 6 £(~
infimum
coincides
on v ~ u
a distributive
of
o s and
~ ~ p ( t ) }, v : {p 6 X l ~ p ( t ) ~ p ( S )
clopen
coincides
We
in T h e o r e m
the
~
: UtPi(p) .
Theorem
claimed
...
u = u t . In
q(p) = O t p i ( p ) .
: ~p(tpi)
smallest F(~).
(tpl A b I ) ~
with
function the
u s and
ot
on u
~s ~ u t
relative
lattice
lattice
of
and
since
6 F(~ pseuevery
u s A ~t,
114
Os V O t are holds
computed
in e v e r y
gebra:
for
and h e n c e
such
in
that
lattice
structure
(Tp,>)
of
algebra
(F(~) ,<)
of g l o b a l
2.12.
Let
s i in T)
and
of is
(a ~ b )
Moreover,
F(~)
t 6 T,
~t
and
in F(~)
of the
same
v (b ~ a ) = I is a S t o n e
subset
(ot)~(p) = O and
sheaf
(ot)~v is,
up
show
that
of X.
Let
if p ~ w . (ot)~=o
I
T"
to i s o m o r p h i s m ,
(X,n,S,~')
arguments
al-
where
U' (P) =
(F(~) ,>)
is a
algebra.
a family
For
is a c l o p e n
(F(~) ,>) , w h i c h
sections
a Heyting
(si)i6 I b e exists.
F(~).
equation
(ot)~(p) = ] if p 6 w
if U(P) = (Tp,<) . So the
Stone
The
w : {p 6 X I o t ( p ) = O T p }
is the p s e u d o - c o m p l e m e n t
The dual the
(Tp,<)
ot 6 F(~),
(ot)~ 6 F(~) (ot)~
coordinate-wise.
in T s u c h
that
V (t A S i) a l s o i61
V s i (the s u p r e m u m i61
exists
of the
and
t^ k/si = V ( t ^ s i ) , i6I since
(F(f) ,V,A,~)
i6I
is a H e y t i n 9 a l g e b r a .
tv
As
i =
/k (tvsi)~
i6I if
AS i6I
i exists.
~ tij j6J
i6I
since
the of are
as w a s
s,t 6 T
infimum
of
chosen then
let A ~ B cBA's
such
and
of T
(R is the
noticed
in 1.6)
of the
form
can be p r o v e d set of
and
these
for T,
complemented laws d o
not
cBA's.
and
choose
x,y,..,
in 2.11. that
Thus,
× E, A' ~ B ' suppose
different. ThenB~D,
since
in 2.3.
follows
D~D',
Then
b y 2.4
e.g.
T(y) = t, x o _ < x
the
x E' w h e r e C and C'
T(B) = T ( A )
AY(A')
d = T(x o) = T(yo)
is
and the d e s c r i p t i o n
b u t x - - x o, Y ' - Y o
yields
× C' ~ D '
B~B',
as
if T(x) = s,
y(x o) = ~(Yo)
T(x o) = s ^ t. T h i s
× C~D
IJl ~ 2
sublattice already
laws
II, ~ ,
s and t in T w h i c h
Os ^ o t g i v e n
rent,
are
of T,
Let
no distributive
~/ ~ t i f ( i ) for f6J I i6I
in a r b i t r a r y
2.13.
i61
course,
R is a c o m p l e t e
elements hold
:
Of
By duality,
are t o t a l l y
following A,A'
and yo < y
fact:
(and h e n c e
resp. =T(D).
diffe-
E and E'
B,B'...) are t o t a l l y
115
2.14.
Let
(V,A,V,*)
be
a Stone
a subalgebra
of V and
of V in
Let X be the
x
[4].
iff x ^ b _
epimorphism sheaf
over
(a) b o t h algebra
to 2.10
Vp.
which
of
Sk.
to see
{x*Ix 6 V } . is c a l l e d
For
p6X
repeat that
hard
the
Sk is
skeleton
and x , y 6 V ,
the w h o l e
~c
is the
to p r o v e
that
put
construc-
=p : V - - * V / ~ p = V p
and V ~ F ( ~ c) w h e r e It is not
Then
is an
"canonical" the
following
equivalent.
stalk
Vp
lattice
are
Stone
(a~b) v (b~a) = I for of ~ c
is a l i n e a r
= ~ ' (p) } is a c l o p e n
algebras
a,b 6 V;
order
subset
and V is a H e y t i n g
of X
and,
for
(i.e.
~,~' 6 F ( ~ c) ,
Sc = ~ Vp p6X
is a H a u s -
space).
course,
not
isomorphism,
every
the
B A and,
if R(B)
Theorem
C and
3. W e a k l y In this cBA's.
Stone
is finite,
homogeneous
Our m a i n
we define goal
(Solovay).
of a h o m o g e n e o u s
in 3.2
every
cBA B:
stalk
can have,
Sk(T(B))
=R(B)
up
to
is a c o m p l e t e
Tp of ~ is w e l l - o r d e r e d
by
in 3.1
Every
some
3.1.
For
a cBA,
Then
the
following
homogeneity,
a property
of c e r t a i n
weakly
several
of t h e s e
homogeneous
cBA
is, up
to i s o m o r p h i s m ,
cBA.
equivalences
although
weak
is
a power
ty and
some
(a)
cBA's
C
give
for
satisfying
1.9.
section
first
algebra
f o r m T(B)
Theorem
We
space
Sk=
b 6 p. We m a y
algebras
stalks
satisfying
{p 6 X I o ( p )
Of
are
some
and
algebra
Stone
2.6
V a n d its d u a l
(b) e v e r y
dorff
in 2.2,
X with
conditions
a Boolean
for
of S t o n e
algebra
equivalent
to b e i n g
equivalences
let R = R ( B
a power may
and T = T ( B )
conditions
formulations of
a homogeneous
be k n o w n
and
homogeneicBA,
to the reader.
be d e f i n e d
are e q u i v a l e n t
of w e a k
as in S e c t i o n
a cBA
satisfying
I. any
116
of
them
will
a)
R = {0,1}
b)
if
B ~x ~B
c)
(T,5)
d)
if
is
weakly
are
x,y 6 B
(i.e.
a,b
are
~y
a linear
a~b:
if
6 R,
O
O < a ~a
c) : l e t family
and
i ~ j implies
Ix i = a i61
or
not
exists
O < a,b 6 B and ~b
w.r.t,
£ R and By
the
r 6 T
a,b
a b : O,
Zorn's
iYi = b . i6I
d)
~
is
being
3.2.
On
B~H
f)
(T,~)
g)
If
other
< where
H
is w e l l
ITI ~ 2,
Proof.
e)
~
f)
g)
~
e) : l e t
so
H
is
=
@(x
of
i)
is
:
some
different,
R has
let
By
0 < r ~ s,t.
b)
at
least
F = { (xi,Yi)
the
four
Li E I}
0 < Yi ~ b '
and
then elements. be
a maxi-
T ( x i) = T(yi) ,
maximality
of
F,
Then
@T(y
they
i) ~ ( b ) .
the
Then
satisfy
following
r
and
-r
infT(r,-r)
conditions
cBA
and
are
totally
different
= O T.
are
equivalent:
K a cardinal
ordered
then
T has
a
was
shown
in
as
g) . L e t
to 6 T
subset
cardinal
< I.
a homogeneous
homogeneous.
a dense
that
i61
O
T,
hand,
D : is
0 < y ~b,
different)
O < x i ~ a,
~x i = a . i6I
r 6 R and
elements
the
e)
~ a,
trivial.
a) : s u p p o s e
and,
O <x
totally
hence
lemma,
conditions:
Assume
such
are
i61
~ d)
that
totally
x i . xj = Yi " Yj = O.
<(a)
c)
such
order
a , b 6 B.
mal
homogeneous:
there
s,t 6 T~{OT} , there
Proof.
~
called
a,b 6 B\{O},
and
b)
be
of
< such
in Now,
least
by
1.9.
Hence
that
f)
~
H be
g)
element
is
a cBA
to.
trivial. such
that
T(H) = to,
g) ,
{X 6 B ~ { O ~ T B.
positive
(X) : t o } there
x~ 6 D
for
is
a partition
~ < K,
and
B~
(x~)~<<
of
U B~xa~H
<.
B
for
117
3.3.
Trivially,
We
begin
in
3.3
with
to
geneous
(*) and
to
get
cases.
be
uncountable
it
turns
numbers
or
In
out and
that
use
C
A
T
B
is
in
a cBA
3.5
C of
as
but
w.l.o.g,
i.e.
is w e a k l y
Theorem
but
not
T +=T~{OT}
proof
is
Since
C.
homogeneous. So
a power
will
rise
a measure the
type
t.
we
assume
of
a homo-
b = I.
Our
be
easy.
to to
cardinal
the
s ~
In
case
B
unit
element, relative
to
a
split
@ of
(3.5),
up
in
B will
where
interval
positive
6 = ~,
of
real
~-additive
homogeneous.
t = t for
t = t,
will
invariant
a strictly
s ~
every pass
proof
closed
and
smallest
for
that
that
By
holds
frequently
algebra
fact
(*)
no
shall
isomorphic
gives
has
we
a certain
we
may
Cn+l)
= S
s,t 6T choose
implies
~
• s ~ t:
a sequence
(Cn)n6 W
satisfying I = c o ~ c I ~c
7(Cn) This
cBA
homogeneous
well,
(3.4),
T : B--*T
We
shall
b >O,
and the
hence
converse,
ordered,
assume
case
measure;
the
a contradiction.
where
B bb
of
a homogeneous
that
want
B ~b,
of
is w e a k l y
linearly
suitable
in
B
is
algebra
choose
proof
that
i.e.
power
(T,~) we
two
the
3.5
BA,
each
shows
2 ~
= t
... T(c n -
that
* s=~( [c~.-%+~)~(c/=t. n6~
Call
t 6T
a-divisible
such
that
e e s = t and
almost
such
that
e
e ~
t = ~ e s
e s ~ t.
implies
a-divisible,
(where
If
e ® t = e e
then
t is
e is
a cardinal)
a-divisible
and
t is
if
if
there
a-divisible,
(e e s) = e ® s = t.
a-divisible:
there
let
C be
If
a cBA
is
is some
then
some
s E T
s 6 T,
e e t = t,
every
t' ~ t is
of
t.
type
By
assumption, D = {x 6 C ~ { O } I T ( x ) is
a dense
subset
{ c i [ i 6 I} ~ D;
of
suppose
C.
Let
%(ci)
= e e s f o r s o m e s 6 T}
(ci)i6 I be = e e si.
a partition
Then
of
C
such
that
s #OT, for almost
118
t =
Finally, T(c)
if
is
let
joint
that
some
is
factor.
above
of
is
We
3.3.
A:
~ _> e,
joint elements T (b) < t.
By
Let
Zorn's
of
3.5.
B
definition
and
B:
s~gt = t,
Hence,
for
then
and
Note
that
the
more
general
@
last
for
is
we
~ < e we
then
are
k 6 e
n-di-
disjoint
such
that
get
2 k pairwise
and
have
the
n < 2 k. dis-
same
type,
Surely
lemma,
amaximal
~ = II
since
pass
s-divisible then
cardinal
6 >e,
otherwise,
have
show
T (b i
smallest
if
B has
to
~<
such
B ~b
6 but
where
no
t 6T +
~ ® T (b) = T (b) : T h i s w a s
e < el -< 6 a n d
: T(b).
we
6,
the
a n d e I _< 6,
-<e ® T ( b )
start (for
that
t=IT,
family
= t.
contradicting
(bi)i61
Put
b = - [ b i. i£I is s m a l l e r t h a n 6.
<- (~+I) ® t
of
(*)
pairwise
dis-
By maximality This
in
,
yields
=t,
out
with
several
s ~ 0 T would
s =n
such
® s'
and
assertion
is
conditions
remarks:
e ~s
if
s,t 6 T
contradicting
it is e a s i l y
checked
6=e) .
that
s = s'
a,c 6 B
b 6B
simple
imply
T(a)
' implies
exists
t =n
Let
c 6C, argument,
there
non-zero
T(B) = t o ;
t6T+;
r < s < t in T;
if
~O.
6 be
T(b)
~Y(b)
s = OT
=t~gs
there
foregoing
k times, are
~ g s i. i6I
n 6~{O}and
rigid,
dl,d2
let
if O < e < 6
of
We
a < b inB,
if
~ ®
< 6.
6 =~.
t~s
=
the
6-divisible.
satisfying
~ + I <max(e,~) Case
C,
b 6B~{O}
IT=~®t since
which
<~®T(b)
e I <6. by
by
is n o t
and
assume
Moreover,
for
Choose,
si
factors,
device
almost
may
each
T(b) 3.4.Case
= T(d2)
~
hence,
C ~c
Theorem
not
for
6-divisible.
proved
Since
~9~ i6I
rigid
and
splitting
proof
T(b) = t o . SO,
=
s _<2 k e s < T ( c ) .
to 6 T
rigid
i)
without
el,...,e2k n e
the
®~(c i6I
T(dl)
above
Hence
for
no
that
the
Now,
a cBA
c 6 C~{O}.
elements
s.
=
n-divisible
_
Applying
say
is
almost
visible: dl,d2
C
~(c)
but
and that
with
a < c,
~(a) = r ,
a < b < c and
~(c) = t ,
n 6 e\{O},
then
s =s'
proved
[13]
as
a much
in
longer
then
Y(b) = s
2.34
proof.
under The
much
unique
s £ T
119
satisfying
n
e s = t will
be
denoted
by
~ ®
t.
Denote
by
Q the
set
of
n
rational
numbers
q
satisfying
0 Nq N 1.
For
q = ~ 6 Q and
t E T,
let
n
q ®t
1
=k
e ([ ® t ) .
Then (q+q')
® t = (q ~ t) ~
q ® t ~q'
®t
in
(q' ~ t)
Tiff
q
~ q'
if
q+q
in
Q
'EQ
etc. 1
(I)
For
0 T < t 6 T,
let
X = { b l , . . . , b n]
T ( b i) = t where
would
So
1 n+l For
for
get
® I
T
T, By
k 6 {0,I,...,n-I] that It
Define
that
(X h a s
Clearly
~
injective. s , t 6 {q ®
=
to
be
and,
0 T <~_m__ ® n+l
subset
finite
by .
that
by
d
there
that
of
B
and
we
IT < t:
satisfying
6 = w) . So
maximality, .
e t ~ I T = (n ® t) ~
is
q 6 Q 1 [ ~
let
maximal
(n ® t) (~ d = I
t % d.
If
could
conclude
~
d Q
is
t <
®
IT1 q 6 Q} and
~(s Q and
Q
I n+l
®
IT ,
t ~d.
U : B ~ [0,1 ] b y
and ~(q t) = ~(s)
dense
~=~
d < - [1 ®
t = s ~
®
IT;
we
k+l t ~ d" = -" n
IT,
prove ~
I T.
a contradiction.
by
by in
e I T) = q + ~(t)
if
for s ~
monotonicity T resp.
[O,1]
q 6 Q. t 6 T
By
(2),
- this
and
the
fact
for
arbitrary
~
holds
ST
[o,i] O < b
additive
in B, measure
O < p(b) on
B,
follows and
by
(I).
So
p is
a positive
for
s,t 6T.
oT:
B
is
that
T
For
d
Choose
k+l s <-~--
I T and
let
IT_
follows
are
® I T < t:
n E ~{0}.
_
d" = ~ i ®
order-preserving
Moreover,
where
s < q
k e I T ~ s. S o n k l e t ~ ~ I T ~ d' = s,
otherwise,
d'
such
IT
w.r.t,
sup{q 6Qlq
I TI q 6 Q}
Define
such
disjoint
<~ : T ~ [0,I] = {x 6 ]RI 0 _<x _< I} <0(t)
{q ®
n 6 ~
a maximal
(I),
I T < t:
follows
some
< t.
d 6 T.
k+l --6-- ®
is
$ bn)) .
.
(n+1)
s < t in
some
be
I ~ i Sn
d = T(-(b I $
we
(2)
for
there
finitely
120
(3)
T(b)
since We
~ was
show
that
T(C)
iff
~(b)
=
~(c)
one-one.
that
disjoint
=
~
is
o-additive:
elements
of
B
and
let
(an)n6 ~ be
a : ian.
~ ( a ) = s u p ( s o + ... + a n ) . n6~
For
Let
a
sequence
a n = ~(an) ; we
every
of
pairwise
have
to
prove
we
show
n,
s o + ... + a n = ~ ( a o + ... + a n ) ~ ~ ( a ) . Let
~ E [0,1 ] s u c h
z(a) By
S o.
If
not,
induction,
that we
may
choose
by
bo S c
such
that
T(bo)
instead
of
c,o,
~o,ao
~i
Now
We
p(a)
have
let
S ~(c)
thus
o-additive says
that
family
of
Since
B
b
=
B
is,
up
hence B
Corollary.
a power
of
the
Proof.
to
such
get
that
satisfying
T ( a o) S T ( c ) .
~ ( b o) = ~ o "
~ T (b n) n6~
B
is
So
Using
that
~ ( c ) : ~.
p ( b n) = ~ n :
there
c -- b o ,
b I ~ c °- b o
:
is
some
~-~o,
such
~i,
that
al
p ( b I) :
T (b) S T (C)
Theorem
carrying
theorem
Theorem
proves
C
to
which
be
all C,
we
atoms know
cBA.
of
strictly
[14] of
weakly
again
Theorem
~x
in
homogeneous
for
positive these
a finite measure
or
countable
algebras.
homogeneous,
contradicts
algebras
B
is
(*)
in
3.3.
atom
of
R
d)
and
even This
C.
r { R = R ( B ) , r > O.
~{x 6 BIB
a
a product
different
a homogeneous
of
cBA
structure
T + = {I T} and
a
isomorphism,
in
Let
supremum By
c 6 B
bn S c
~ o + ~i S ~ w e
totally
a = is
and
~ T (a n ) = n{~
The
pairwise
Case
get
n C ~;
Then
that
measure.
homogeneous,
is
:
proved
assumed
concludes
ibn. n6(0
we
every
Choose
disjoint
= m(ao) and
for
= o.
is
3.6.
o 6 Q.
z ( a o) = ~ o ~ o = ~ ( c ) ,
T (a)
and
assume
pairwise
first,
etc.
s o + ... + a n S o
Then
r
is
an
a)
through
iff
Moreover
is
homogeneous}
R.
that
conditions
e)
B [r
121
through
g) r
is
by
Theorem
4.
Some
4.1
of an
C.
Then
space
and
atom
The
Let
the
X I is
3.2
of
are
R
second
applications
Theorem.
set.
3.1
X be
algebra
equivalent. ~r)J
iff
IR(B
iff
B ~r
is w e a k l y
iff
B ~r
is
assertion
of
Theorem
an
arbitrary
If
~
: 2
(by
homogeneous
a power
follows
1.3)
of
a homogeneous
cBA
immediately.
C
C = R O ( X I)
homogeneous.
Now,
topological of
is
regular
space
open
a cardinal
and
subsets
such
that
I an of
infinite
the
IUI ~
product
for
set
U of
pairwise
disjoint
open
subsets
of
X,
then
[Vl ~ 2 e f o r
set
V
pairwise
disjoint
open
subsets
of
XI
(so,
if
every
every +
then
of
c(RO(XI))
Proof.
We
regular c ~v.
X i =X
non-void
such
,
prove
that
subsets
of
C
X I.
is w e a k l y Choose
homogeneous.
non-void
basic
Let
u,v
be
open subsets
non-void be_u,
E.g.
where
are
~ ~
~ (2~)+).
first
open
c(RO(X))
for
open
b =
~ Xi x ~ ui i£I o i61 o
C :
~ Xj J~Jo
i 6 I,
subsets
regular
open.
that
I o N 1 1 =~
u.,ik = V j k
for
i ~k
I o and of
Let
x
X
~Vj JEJ o Jo
for
d =
finite
i E Io,
subsets
j 6 Jo"
I o = {il,...,in],
: J o N J1,
_<m,
are
We
for
I Sk
_
and
e =
~ j~(JoUJl
Xj × ~ v j )
j6J o
× ~vj, j6J 1
ui,v j are that
Choose
Jl = {J{ ..... j~}.
Now,
~ Xi × ~ u i × ~ u i, i~ (IoUI I) i61 o i61 I
I and
assume
Jo = {Jl,-'-,Jm}"
Ii : {i~ ..... i ~ } ,
vj~ = Uik
may
of
ui,v j Ii,J 1 ~I Let
122
are
regular
ecc~v.
By
open
subsets
of
C,
C
C ~d
-~ R O ( e )
-~ C 5 e .
is
homogeneous
it
is
(cf.
and
homeomorphic
b is
c(RO(XI)) theorem
product
of
D.
Proof. and
4.3.
by
the
c(C) A ~ 2 . an
ccc
4.4. be I<<
this
if B
d c_bcu,
there
show
that
where
have
open The
Stone
of
4.1
of and
B.
v c_X n a n d
in
cardinal.
is
C
is
of
so
the
a free
Then
C
is
a cardinal
2~
isomorphic
that
b
n 6 ~;
of
e is
ICl _< ( I - I B i )
C
fact
If
each
[2].
infinite
C.
is
for
assertion
3.13
into
C
subset
some
completion
Then
the
open
the
_< (2~) + a n d
to
R O ( X I)
completely
gene-
B.
the
example
B
satisfying
a cBA
an
that
~ u) = c(C)
second
C be
show
basic
see
embeddable
space
by
let
i is
c(C)
c(C
a non-void some
To
completely
in
ccc
embedded
the
other
hand,
cBA
satisfying
[I]
showing (the
into
Martin's ccc,
the
that,
if V = L
countable
chain
a homogeneous
axiom
and
algebra
cBA
condition) C,
e I < 2 ~ hold
C = R O ( X ~)
is
and
satisfies
]CI ~ (w. IBI) W = IBi.
< be
K-closed
an
if, is
dense
<-closed
It
proved
is
on
and
completely
, we
is
contains
a cBA
B,
with
is
infinite
Let
is +
I copies
If,
and
of
follows
there
that,
is
that
cBA.
Erd@s-Rado-theorem;
B be
the
theorem
assumed,
B
X be
Compare
such
B
c(B) _<~
Let
the
rated
and
u
to
5u) _ < c ( R O ( X I ) ) .
the
Let
a homogeneous
to v × X I for
I copies
homogeneous that
But
by
of
sufficient
~b) < c ( C
follows
Theorem
such
1.9).
-~ RO(d)
a power
u 6C~{O}
4.2.
X I such
Hence,
Theorem
even
homeomorphic
infinite for
some
any
d £ D
subset, in
[12]
cardinal. desc@nding
A
subset
sequence
that
d ~d~
then
B
(l,~)-distributive
that,
if
B has
a dense
a cBA
(d~)~
such
is
for
D of
every
in
e < i.
<-closed
for
B
is
said
to
D where If
B has
every
subset
a
I < <.
D then
B
123
may
be
sed
subset.
We
completely
give
4.5.
Moreover,
an
analogue
Theorem.
K-closed
embedded
Let
subset
if of
B.
a rigid
< is r e g u l a r
this
B be
of
into
result
a cBA, Then
cBA
and
and
~ : <.iDI
be
has
a dense
then
<-clo-
c(C) ~ ( ~ ) +
4.2:
< a regular
B may
C which
cardinal
completely
and
D a dense
embedded
into
a homoge+
neous
cBA
some
~
Proof.
and
the
a dense
Z = ~.<,
We may
basis that
C with
we
assume
sets
<-closed
have
that,
if
c(B) ~ ~
for
I B 6 D.
B is
{d 6 D l d ~ e}
for
isomorphic
e 6 D.
Let
to
~ be
RO(D) an
where
infinite
D has
as
cardinal
a such
< ~ 4. L e t
be
endowed
is
a <-closed
dense
with
subset
the
of
C.
We
where
turn
B
the
question
a cBA
and
b,c 6 B and
b ~ c,
then
B ~c
x ~ c .- b. If B ~ cBA's
the
Clearly,
a rigid
presentation If B h a s
that
fb
C : RO(E) ; w e by
analoguous
about
with
order
the
a few
to
of
f to B 5 c
function
(Bi)i61 TAut i6I and
of A u t ( C n)
Bi
interchanges
(see
of
remarks. for
pairwise
a
that
4.1.
of A u t
Firstly, B ~b,
f(x) = x
B if
let
for
totally
different
[7]).
[7].
IBI ~ IAut BI:
b = b I $ b 2 and b I and
E is
proof
in
f 6 Aut
So E
f is o n e - o n e .
given then
that
cardinals
JAut(cn) I = ICJ
in
b y D I.
The
given
satisfying
f to
a family
[2].
that
2 ~ n < w,
factor,
satisfying
is
mapping
assume
in
possible trivial
induced
may
3.13
tAut B ~bl ~ bAut B ~cl:
the
cBA
no rigid
b2 6 B
begin
extension
~B i where i6I then Aut B ~
If C is
b I and
be
Let
completely
is
6 Aut
order.
<<}
partial
c(C) ~ (2~) + f o l l o w s
is
to
l{i~Jxi~IB}l
coordinate-wise
partial
C is h o m o g e n e o u s
such
E such
c(C) S (2~) +.
E : {x~D~[
4.6.
subset
for
follows
from
b 6 B,
choose,
T ( b I) = T(b2) . L e t
b 2 and
fb(x) = x
for
the
fb 6 A u t
x ~-b.
re-
by B
3.3,
124
The
function
mapping
b to fb is o n e - o n e
b = -[{x £ Blfb(y) =y An
arbitrary
c B A B has,
since
for e v e r y
y ~x}.
u p to i s o m o r p h i s m ,
the
form
~i ~j B = A x ~T H i x ~ E j x D i6I j6J = AxH×ExD where
A is a t o m i c ,
ly of p a i r w i s e is a f a m i l y ~j are
cardinals
position
such
of
E.
for
different totally
that
homogeneous
Theorem
(i.e.
totally
A ~P(~)
of p a i r w i s e
cBA without
4.7.
i.e.
E is r i g i d ) ;
atomless
0 < ~i,
or r i g i d
e is f i n i t e , hence
cardinal
different
L e t B be a cBA.
4.6,
some
~j for
a;
(Hi)i{ I is a f a m i -
homogeneous atomless i 6 I,
cBA's;
rigid
j 6 J;
(Ej) j6 J
cBA's;
v i and
D is an a t o m l e s s
factors.
Then Aut
B is f i n i t e i f ~
IH × D I = I and
IAut B I : e!.
~j
If A u t
: I
or
in t h e d e c o m -
IEjl : I for
B is i n f i n i t e
j 6 J
, [Aut BI ~ :
[Aut B I • Proof. (~)
We have Aut
B ~Aut
If e is f i n i t e
A × ~Aut(H i6I and B ~ P ( ~ )
morphism,
the group
and hence
A u t A, A u t ( H × D)
So e < ~.
vi) ~j i x ~ A u t ( E j ) × Aut(D) . j£J x E where
E is r i g i d ,
of all p e r m u t a t i o n s
If 2 ~ Zj a n d
and,
I < IEjl
of ~. C o n v e r s e l y ,
for e v e r y
for
some
A u t B is,
j 6 J, A u t ( E ~ j)
up
to iso-
suppose are
Aut B
finite.
j 6 J,
W ~ IEjl : IAut(E~)I ~ [Aut(E~J) I by
4.6 a n d
factors.
since
So,
E
if
3
is i n f i n i t e .
IH x D I > I, w e
~ 1H × D[ ~ A u t ( H
H x D is an a t o m l e s s
cBA without
get x D)
by 4 . 6 . Now
let A u t
B be
infinite.
By
(~)
it is s u f f i c i e n t
to p r o v e
rigid
125
IAut B1 e = IAut B I for for
some
i 6 I, B ~ = B
the which
A u t ( B e) ~ A u t
B.
3.6,
is a t o m l e s s .
R=R(B)
r 6 R~{O} O
gives
For
=
i.e.
and B = E
to an e m b e d d i n g B has
r 6 R\{O},
from R~{O}
× D. of
If B = H i ± (Aut B) e i n t o
no homogeneous
factor.
By
let
to t h e
= ~(r)
if ~(r'
for
class every
of
cardinals.
r' 6 R s u c h
Call
that
So X : {r 6 R ~ { O } I r
is a d e n s e less,
rise
B : Hi
IAut B ~ r I .
function
~-homogeneous
Sr.
B :A,
So let B = E × D,
~(r) is a m o n o t o n e
cases
subset
we may
of R. L e t
assume
that,
is ~ - h o m o g e n e o u s } P ~X
be a partition
if ~(p) = y
for
of R.
s o m e p 6 P,
Since
R is a t o m -
{p 6 P1~(p) = y}
is
infinite. Now Aut B ~
since
B ~p
and B ~p'
(~)
since
4.8.
IAut Bi
every
Let,
~ Aut(B~p) p6P
factor
are =
totally
~(p) p6P
~(p)
=
for p # p ' .
So
tAut Bi ~
Occurring
in t h e d e c o m p o s i t i o n
in
(~)
occurs
of B g i v e n
E~ : ~ { E ~ J I % = I } , It m a y b e p r o v e d ,
different
by considering
infinitely
often.
in 4.6,
E 2 : ~{E~JI~j
2}.
the
B : H × D and B = E t h a t
cases
B :A,
iB1 ~ iAut BI if iBi = IA ×H ×E2 ×DL and iAut BI ~ .
References [I]
B. and
Balcar,
P.
v
consistency
of S y m b o l i c
v
Stepanek: results
Logic
42
Embedding
theorems
an o r d i n a l
(1977),
64-75.
for B o o l e a n
definable
sets.
algebras
The Journal
126
[2]
[3]
W.W.
Comfort,
S. N e g r e p o n t i s :
Heidelberg-New
York
]974.
E. van Douwen,
J.D.
Monk,
algebras, ETH
preprint
G. Gr~tzer:
[5]
S. Grigorieff:
[9]
Model
J.D.
bras.
Colloquia
nite
and Finite
Rasiowa:
Theory.
questions
Berlin-
about B o o l e a n
f~r M a t h e m a t i k ,
completeness
Monk:
81
sheaves
1978.
extensions
in
447-490. of structures.
73-89.
societatis
groups Janos
of B o o l e a n
Bolyai,
10.
algeInfi-
951-988.
An A l g e b r a i c
Approach
1974.
M.
On the r e c o n s t r u c t i o n
automorphism
for
(1975),
On a u t o m o r p h i s m
Amsterdam Rubin:
and g e n e r i c
101
(1973),
mathematica Sets,
Basel-Stuttgart
submodels
of M a t h e m a t i c s
Mathematicae
R. McKenzie,
H.
Lattice
Intermediate
Annals
A. MacIntyre: Fundamenta
[8]
Some
by the F o r s c h u n g s i n s t i t u t
General
set theory.
[7]
Rubin:
of Ultrafilters.
Z~rich.
[4]
[6]
M.
The T h e o r y
to N o n - C l a s s i c a l
of B o o l e a n
Logics.
algebras
groups,
to appear
in: A r c h i v
Boolean
algebras.
Berlin-Heidelberg-New
from
their
f~r m a t h e m a t i s c h e
Logik. [10]
R. Sikorski:
[11]
R. Solovay, Souslin's
[12]
S. Tennenbaum:
Problem.
P. Stepanek:
Annals
Cardinal
Iterated
Cohen
of M a t h e m a t i c s
collapsing
extensions 94
and o r d i n a l
A. Tarski:
[14]
D.A.
Cardinal
Vladimirov:
Algebras.
Boolesche
New York
Algebren.
definability,
]949.
Berlin
and
(1970), 201-245
preprint. [13]
York
1972.
1964.
PSEUDO REAL CLOSED FIELDS
*) Alexander Fakult~t
Prestel
fur M a t h e m a t i k
Universit~t D-7750
In h i s fields
Ax
famous
considered
ly i r r e d u c i b l e These
fields
by Frey The
The
above
version:
It has b e e n in
pseudo ordered
later
this
[Ba]
real
in
the p r o p e r t y
that
out
(prc) (L,<)
pseudo
, then
fields. if
(K,<)
in w h i c h
K
a
of f i n i t e every
[Jr]
absolute-
K-rational
algebraically
to be v e r y
K
has
by Jarden
extension
characterization
closed
over
of p a c - f i e l d s
L
for o r d e r e d
extension
with
studied
for e v e r y
closed
theory
called
turned
definition
elementary
defined
and e x t e n s i v e l y
algebraically
l ized
been
on the
K
variety
of p a c - f i e l d s
equivalent
[Ax]
fields
affine
have
[Fr]
class
paper
Konstanz
Konstanz
point.
closed
(pac)
and W h e e l e r
[Wh].
interesting.
c a n be p u t field
L
into
of
K
is e x i s t e n t i a l l y
the , if
closed
of p a c - f i e l d s
which
Basarab
an o r d e r e d
calls
is e x i s t e n t i a l l y
Basarab
closed
it is a l g e b r a i c a l l y
following K
is
in
L
genera-
field
(K,<)
in e v e r y
closed~)
*) T h e o r i g i n a l i n t e n t i o n of the a u t h o r h a s b e e n to p u b l i s h in this v o l u m e a s t r a i g h t - f o r w a r d p r o o f of t h e e l i m i n a t i o n of q u a n t i f i e r s for the e l e m e n t a r y t h e o r y of a s p e c i a l c l a s s of p r c - f i e l d s . D u r i n g his s t a y in B r a s i l in s u m m e r 1980 the a u t h o r o b t a i n e d v a r i o u s r e s u l t s on p r c - f i e l d s . T h e r e f o r e he d e c i d e d to g i v e h e r e a comp r e h e n s i v e i n t r o d u c t i o n to the t h e o r y of p r c - f i e l d s . +)
W e h a v e b e e n i n f o r m e d b y S. B a s r a b t h a t t h i s n o t i o n of p s e u d o r e a l c l o s e d f i e l d s h a s a l s o b e e n i n t r o d u c e d b y K . M c K e n n a in his t h e s i s , i n d e p e n t l y of [Ba].
128
One algebraic
which
answer (K,<)
in
. Hence
hand
most
no.
can
be
a prc-field
a problem):
_ a
K
ordering
<
over
closed
K
in
K
of
two
in
squares
in
One every if
field.
we
every
orderings
on
K
Basarab's
and is
irreducible plane
as
poly-
curve
(K,<)
algebraically
is
other
stated
field
Then
(Theorem of
L
of
over
this
sentence:
shows
. In
case
determined
ordering
(3.1))
that
prc
real
a
do
is
not
fix
admits
is
a sum
is
clear
<
this
L
of
K
be
(or one
if
K
is
is all closed.
a certain ordering
the
that
a formally
to which
one
is
a prc-field,
algebraically
from
case
paper
again
(prc)
exactly
This in
closed
K
this
Let
field
in which we
is
suitably:
extension
K
of
a prc-field
pseudo
that
definition.
fact
definable
number) we
that by
come the
an
existen-
sentence: 0
case
the
function
existential
of
in
here
The
< ).
the
closed
On
been
irreducible
(K,<) . T h i s
K'
K
point
tial
in
call
crucial
uniquely
to
has
a prc-
_ a = 0
definition
extend,
to
absolutely
results
K
back
absolutely
an
this
a
Unfortunately, (1.1))
2 orderings.
The
the
also
orderings
of
least
ordered
too,
algebraically
positive.
x 2 +y2
closed
The
is
[B]
by
existentially of
at
~
I).
Theorem
(in
denoted
main
the
Then
(compare
that
a prc-field
Lemma
ordered
extends
extension
extends
is
every
.
the
algebraic
one
real
of
K
such
K
(L,<) , h e n c e
is w h e t h e r
([Ax] ,§ 14,
admits
Obviously,
( B xy)
holds
be
ask
(K,<)
arguments
defines
(again
(L,<).
(/-~)
to
a prc-field
pac-fields
uniquely
a 6
X 2 + y2
curve
of
standard
= K is
Let
questions
constructed
nomial . The
for
By
K'
natural
(K',~)
holds
is
field K
the
extension
property the
of
Extension K'
< a
Theorem
turns
out
iff above
to
be
( B xy) also
a = x
holds
a pac-field.
2
for Thus
+ y
2
non-real we
may
fields drop
the
K'
. In
this
condition
129
of
K
being
are
special
formally cases
real.
Now pac-fields
of p r c - f i e l d s
which
(of c h a r a c t e r i s t i c
seems
to b e n a t u r a l
zero)
in t h i s
approach.
The Extension we
investigate
we deal with rings.
We
having
only
several
also
show
every
real
closure
condition'
of
induce
of
K
closures
that
class
2
(Theorem
has
paper we make
and results.
Keisler
or t h e
We
(2.1))
sufficient on
(1.4)
have that
has
In S e c t i o n
exactly
of K - r a t i o n a l
to g u a r a n t e e K
and t h a t
and
(1.6)).
K
point
points.
that
all
if
in This
orderings
is d e n s e
In s e c t i o n
in all
4 we prove
is e l e m e n t a r y . free use the
thesis
of
standard
reader
[v.d.D]
model
to the b o o k of v a n
den
theoretic
[Ch-K]
of C h a n g -
Dries.
O. P r e l i m i n a r i e s
In t h i s algebraic in t h i s
results
paper
For we deal
. Two
a field
L/K
we give
which
will
only with
extension L
section
will
have
K
linearly
disjoint
integral
domain.
frequently
we denote
fields
of
by
is
K
if t h e
By T h e o r e m
used.
K
its
of
zero,
a common
tensor
2, Ch.
collect
All
some
fields
algebraic
(relatively)
LI, L2
and
considered
zero.
characteristic
if . K
fields over
be
characteristic
regular
extension
some definitions
call
algebraically subfield
product
III of
closure.
we may
LI
K
@ K L2
[La] w e h a v e
2
K
if a n d o n l y
a simple
I
n orde-
a field
is a p r c - f i e l d
an i n f i n i t y
refer
excellent
which
curve which
topologies
3 . In S e c t i o n
of p r c - f i e l d s .
of p r c - f i e l d s
plane
of p r c - f i e l d s
in S e c t i o n
properties
(Propositions
notions
be p r o v e d
of o r d e r i n g s
is a l r e a d y
different
its r e a l
In t h i s
number
irreducible
'curve
the
theory
in S e c t i o n
a finite
abso~ly
will
algebraic
the m o d e l
every
K
Theorem
Since
a field closed
are
in
called
is an
130
(O.1)
L/K
is
a regular
field
extension
if
and
only
if
L @K ~
is
a
field.
From
Theorem
(0.2)
Let
LI/K
are
We
4, Ch. III
linearly
L2
a subset
V
of
of
some
over
K
we
absolutely
is
Of
an
By
By
over
~m
I c
called
absolutely in
and
only
we
a
V
(see
of
K
is
of
a
iff
b - a 6 P
uniquely
denote
the
determined
well-known;
for
(0.4)
Let
V
F(V)
its
ordering
up
an
is
its
irreducible.
In
by
70).
defined
real to
closure
LI is
the
get
and
a regular
set
of
function
field
that
is
I
K[X] this
L2
is
still
case
Hence
we
also
over
K
. From
K
is
say
that
the
give
field
p
extends
are
(K,P)-rational
point
over to
positive, a
P
defined
of
K in
with ~
with
and
K
such
{O}.
if
that
Actually,
respect
. The of
to
following
P
P
. It
is
fact
is
over
K ,
it.
variety
, and
F(V) if
irreducible
by:
a proof
K
of
P = K~
irreducible
function
o_ff) f1' .... fs
absolutely
extension.
P U-
isomorphism we
is
a subset
, and
absolutely
o_ff K
V
a regular
an o r d e r i n g
convenience
be
V
in
Then
, P D - P = ~ cone
we
if
it h a p p e n s
[La] , p.
we mean
positive
L2)
we
get
F(V)/K
P
Q u o t ( L I @K
I
variety
K-variety.
if
, P. Pep
for
[Ja]
Then
. By
generated
absolutely
irreducible
[La]
be
ideal
If
in
arbitrary.
K[XI,...,Xm]
the
is
I, p . 2 0 3
a K-variety
i.e.
V
be and
prime,
V
(K,P)
K
= Quot(K[~]/I).
an o r d e r i n g
is t h e
L2/K
F(V)
Let
P + pep
Corollary
and
some
ideal
definition
discussion
(0.3)
prime
and
mean
then
a field V
disjoint
of
zeros
[La]
regular
extension
call
prime,
be
in
defined
fl .... 'fs 6 K[~]
such only
that if
f1(a),...,fs(a)
(the V
. Then
residue
has
cla~es
a simple
positive.
~1
I31
Proof:
First
F(V). Then
Let the
classes
assume
that
the p r i m e following
of
there
ideal
I
of
statement
X 1 ..... X m
exists
I
where
d
F(V)
K
. Note
an e x i s t e n t i a l the m o d e l
completeness
Conversely, f. (~) 3 F(V)
is p o s i t i v e . of
then
over
A/M
A/M.
is
Since
power the
V
series
ordering
ordering
Q
The
this
local
closed
If
(K,P) its
(K,P)
on
Quot(A)
transcendence
residue
and
of o r d e r e d
fields
of M
denotes
such
(K,P) .
V
such
that
function
its m a x i m a l +M
that
methods
which
field ideal,
are p o s i t i v e
A is i s o m o r p h i c
R
by
in
A
By w e l l - k n o w n on
Hence
by
holds
of
in the
fl + M ' ' ' ' ' f s
to an o r d e r i n g = F(V)
point
of
expressed
fields.
it also
a
completion
(K,P).
degree
can be a c t u a l l y
be a s i m p l e
is r e g u l a r .
over
the
language
A
is r e g u l a r ,
of
the
]
statement
ring
to
R
to
) = m - d
, i.e.
~ £(K,P)
(K,P)
ring
V
of r e a l
'equal'
A
of
in the
let
P
3
that
sentence
of
gl .... 'gr 6 K[XI ....Xm]
(F(V) ,Q) by
~ = O Arank(
is the d i m e n s i o n
over
in
by
Q
:
[i (3 ~)
an e x t e n s i o n
be g e n e r a t e d
is s a t i s f i e d
modulo
r fj (~) £ Q A A gi(2) j:1 i=I
V
such
fl,...,fs
to some
one
then
in
extends
induces
6 Q
an
. q.e.d.
Note over
t h a t we
only
(K,P).
The
next
essentially
van
den
proof
is m o d e l
(0.5)
Let PI'
Consider N
Dries'
and
P
on.
the
K
set
the
fact
will
Lemma we g i v e
L2/K
of o r d e r i n g s
ordering
Proof:
assertion
theoretic,
LI/K P2
used
(2.5),
Ch.
remains
II in one
extensions. resp.,
is a c o m m o n
irreducible
in S e c t i o n
an a l g e b r a i c
LI, L2
, there
V
be u s e f u l
be r e g u l a r on
that
2.
[v.d.D for Then
inducing extension
It is
]. S i n c e
his
convenience. to e v e r y the Q
pair
same to
L I ®K L2"
132
where we
let
we have
Q' + Q ' c Q',
x 6 R
R = L I @K L2
. We have
that
" This
Q' • Q ' c Q',
to p r o v e
only
only
hold
certain
K
we may
PI
and ~
is a s i m p l e (~,~)
point
of
V2
we may
, and
assertion.
, i.e.
x 2 6 Q'
for
It s u f f i c e s
of
P
varieties and P
point
of
with
qi(~)
to
, by
F(V)
and
them
all
to s h o w
L2
V2
there pi(~)
I < i < N
such
implies
o v e r K.
~,~
6(K,P) and Now
V = VI x V2
that
of
functions.
are
. Thus
a
finitely
fields
I < i < N).
variety
= LI ®K L2
are
positive
(for
only
defined
are r e g u l a r
positive
= 0
involves
as f u n c t i o n and
with
all
E(p i ® qi)x~
LI
(0.4),
of the p r o d u c t for
sum
VI
qi
VI
this
that
consider
extend
point
Since
assume
Pi
is p o s i t i v e
Hence
by
(0.4)
all
xi : O
such there
Pi ® qi for
all
.
to an o r d e r i n g extends
PI
We XK
arguments Q
of the
as w e l l
now
as
let
= {P 6 X K becomes
K is c a l l e d
la 6 P}
a totally
[M-H],
is c a l l e d
is s u r j e c t i v e ,
P2
we
can extend
domain
ordering
of K}
where
a 6 K ~ {O}.
or
real
if e a c h
L I ®K L2
Obviously,
Q'
Q
q.e.d.
generated
real
the p r e o r d e r i n g
"
topology,
(2.8),
totally i.e.
integral
disconnected
Lemma
formally
(cf.[Pr])
X K : {PiP
, the Harrison
(compare
L/K
vanish.
1
that
both
is a s i m p l e
By standard
XK
assume
is a s i m p l e
are p o s i t i v e .
x.
irreducible
P2
is an e x t e n s i o n
H(a)
~
R
= 0
. Hence we may
(Pi ® qi ) (~)
1
all
elements
absolutely
such that
that
of
over
Moreover, Since
in c a s e
number
generated
on
third
=
on
N
finite
=
is a p r e o r d e r i n g
Q' D -Q'
the
X (Pi © q i ) x i 2 i=I can
set
Ch.
b y the
compact III or
just
real
if t h e P 6 XK
There
(clopen)
Endowed space,
with the
[PJ, T h e o r e m if
XK # @
restriction extends
is a t o p o l o g y
map
sets
this
order
topology space
(6.5)).
of K
A field
. A field
extension
from
to
to s o m e
XL
ordering
on
XK L
.
133
I. P s e u d o
In
this
vestigate are
section
algebraic
supposed
existentially
K
the
the
holds
is c a l l e d
closed
polynomials
is
L
of with
(1.7))
for
also
~
here
fields.
real
closed
real
means
with
. The
from is
in
P 6 XK
K
parameters
XK
closed
we
in
L
K
extension
L
every
existential
(prc)
if
of
K.
sentence
finite even
# O]
sentence K
. As we this
in t h e
~
is
, i.e. will
pl,...,pr
see
already
a formula are
later
implies
language
in
that
augmented
K
by
predi-
.
observe zero)
that
by
[Wh],
is
also
Theorem
2.2,
a prc-field.
the
real
fields
every
real
every
In t h i s
closed
completeness
of
the
fields:
Let
~
real
of
L
tension
of
sentence
k
infields
regular
from
the m o d e l
fix
all
is
= 0 ^ q(~)
from
us
that
K
that
follows
L
Recall
and
pac-field
case
we
K
have
•
Among
in
of p r c - f i e l d s
zero.
pr(~)
holds
case
(of c h a r a c t e r i s t i c =
such
totally
coefficients in
each
First
X K
existence
pseudo
= O A...A
fields
existentially
cates
of
in e v e r y
closed
[Pl (~)
in
language
(Theorem
the
fields
type
(3xi ..... Xm)
which
closed
characteristic
Existentially of
prove
properties
to h a v e
A field
we
real
the ~
and
be
unique
with hence
some
. Consider
the
field the
ordering
parameters in
K k
closure
. To
with
K
to
from
K
which
together
following
theory
of
obtain with
class
of
field
L
further
ordered
of
is prc.
real
respect
. Then holds
an in
examples
a system
K
(Pi)i£i fields:
closed
to
some
ex-
existential L
of
This
also
holds
prc-fields of
orderings
let of
134
M : { (K,(Pi)i61) It is clear chains. tially then
that
M
Thus ~ere closed,
every
is c l o s e d
are
i.e.
for
hat
K
is prc.
of
Now
(L, (Qi)iCi)
tence
with
We thus
(1.1)
parameters
(linearly
of
M
this
K
which
language
let
M
K
L
(K, (Pi)iC I) augmented holds
[Ch] , Ch.
the
. Hence in
L
by
in
real
ordering
every
Pi
holds
I). reguto
existential
also
,
III,§
be a t o t a l l y
Qi°f
holds
are M - e x i s t e n -
which
(compare
an e x t e n s i Q n to
which
extends
from
ordered)
in
orderings
on
that
K
We w i l l (K, (Pi)i6 I)
If w e
field there
is
prc
see
later
pi }
senK
.
k
and e a c h
is a r e g u l a r
and e v e r y
in g e n e r a l In case
XK
after
need
(Pi)iEl
extension
ordering
(the r e m a r k
system
not
Pi
K
of
k
extends
to
K
Proposition coincide
is finite,
of
(1.6))
such .
that,
with
equality
will
hold
let
but
k = ~ of
does
~
in the
above
, we o b t a i n
not
construction
a prc-field
have
/~-
gives
an a l g e b r a i c
K
as an element.
and
p
be the
which Hence
will K
be u n i q u e -
is not
real
closed.
The n e x t We
in
(1.6)).
ordering
ly o r d e r e d
k
above, X K
extends
(Proposition
fields.
L.
proved
To e a c h
unique
parameters
belongs
from
of
in the
(K,(Pi)i6 I)
. Choose
THEOREM.
{PilPi
in
(even
To p r o v e
lar e x t e n s i o n obviously
K
(K,(Pi)i6 I)
sentence
holds
unions
pi }
(K', (P i' )iCI ) C M
Pi ) w i t h
also
Pi e x t e n d s
under
elements
if some
each
(K',(P i' )i6I ) claim
is r e g u l a r ,
existential
predicates
We
I K/k
could
theorem have
equally
well
taken
characterization
this
as d e f i n i t i o n .
of p r c -
135
(1.2)
THEOREM.
K
is
irreducible
variety
(K,P)-rational
Proof:
Let
K
be
some
gl,...,g r 6
given
by
(B~)
obviously is
absolutely
know
that
the
with
existential
pl,...,pr
holds
in
L
. Fix
F
the
function
prime
ideal
(0.3)
we
fact
know
that
rational
{f
that
point
for
shows
point
= 0
that
of
V
is
(a,b)
^...^
~
P on
pr(~)
also
ideal
regular
real
given
a simply
be
point.
generated
by
sentence
in
pr(~)
I f(x,y)
the
know
6 XK
. Hence, Thus
in
^ bg(~)
. Since (0.4)
in
V
we
K
extension.
Assume
the
. Let
F : K(x,y).
K-variety
that by
V
V F/K By has
we
Obviously
defined is
(0.4)
by
the
regular,
by
and
a simple
assumption,
particular
-
sentence
- I = O]
irreducible.
we
By
holds
also
: O } . Since
real
in
~
K
% 0 ]
. Then
, y 6 L of
(0.3).
regular
: 0 A yq(~)
~ K
L
by
over
by
holds
holds
V
V
Thus
: 0 ^ q(~)
= O
has
a K-rational
of
of
pr(~)
V.
absolutely
existential
F(V)
absolutely
totally each
to
those
6 K[X,Y]
which has
F(V)
is
~
over
every
: O]
a totally
= 0 A...A
field
is
Pl (~)
be
6 K[~]
some
L/K
K-rational
This
I =
L
if
K
XK
the
field
extends
: 0 ^...A
[Pl (2)
prime
F(V)/K
sentence
, q
P 6
Then
function
let
(B~y)
is
gr(~)
P 6 XK
[Pl (~)
the
= O A...A
irreducible,
each
(3x)
let
only
over
each
m]
the
and
defined
for
and
if
K[XI,...,X
in
Conversely, that
V
point
prc
[gl (~)
holds
a prc-field
there
the (K,P)is
a
have
I = 0
K q.e.d.
136
In curves. Z
CK
the
For
: For
following,
convenience
every
zero
f(x,y)
= 0
Z
is of
Theorem
(1.2).
C~
such
ProofS)
:
Consider
f(X,Y)
= abX2y 2 +
inspection
~[Y].
Clearly,
(x,y)
be
for
each
of
that
Let
, i.e.
Easy
the
irreducible
subset
. Note
i__~s c 6 K 6 P
this
criterion
'curve
f(X,Y) P 6
Z
only
to p l a n e
condition'
6 K[X,Y]
, there
which
are
x,y
has
a
6 K
with
.
PROPOSITION.
a,b
apply
introduce
(K,P)
a fixed
instead
(1.3)
in
will
we
absolutely
simple
Here
we
for
plane
f
as
simple
a K-rational
point
K
. For
P 6 XK
defined
zeros of
just
write
satisfies
CK
all
we
by
I = a X 2 ( b y 2 + I)
polynomial
f has
, we
a,b
have
CK by
6 K~
{O}
c 6 P
there
iff
= H(c)
curve
aX 2 + b Y 2 -
of
C KZ
each
N H(b)
Z = XK
prc-field
satisfy
~at
the
. If
every
K
H(a)
XK
in
in
this
X
(K,P) curve,
the
+
polynomial
(bY 2 - I)
proves for
all
i.e.
irreducibility P 6
f(x,y)
over
XK
. Now
let
= 0
. The
ele-
ment c
then is
satisfies
not
~)
assertion
of
the
= ab
- a2b2x2y 2
proposition.
Note
that
possible,
Using that
the
:= a b ( a x 2 + b y 2)
~K
c = 0 q.e.d.
the
language
of
order
implies
K
be
a SAP-field
to
T h i s p r o o f is d u e t o J. thank for many helpful
spaces,
Kr. A r a s o n , discussions
Proposition (see
[Pr],
(1.3)
tells
Proposition
whom the author would on this subject.
like
us
(6.6)).
to
137
(1.4)
PROPOSITION. for
Proof: the It
all
P 6 XK
Given
suffices
the
to
(K,P)
set
also
of
also
g(K)
for
all
x 6 K
fields
there
(ordering) where form
Q 6 XK the
junctive
fact part,
p(~)
holds we
in
find
=
in
such
all
Inspection c 6 Q
may
zero
of
(x,y)
of
f
some
(K,Q).
(O,/~ 2 - c g 2 ( O ) ) . But
for
no
has
[Ka]
K[X] zero
, Theorem such
that
Quantifiers
for
(K,P)
I
for
the
if
g
formula
(K,P)
by
real
.
-6 2
closed
only
positive
the cone
a zero
that
P
g2(x)
in
in d i s j u n c t i v e
implies
(K,P),
. Hence
O
has
in
which has /k in ( K , P ) , t h e n
I)
involving
only
this
qr(~)
in this
proves zero
62
some
(K,Q) , normal
dis-
c 6-
(K,Q).
c 6 Q c
Hence
implies
Proposition
(1.3)
:
6 Q
we
. Now
.
know
that
consider
g
the
has
a zero
polynomial
6 K[X,Y]
f
(K,Q) Q
,
. Iterating
qr(~)
that s 6
H
Q 6 XK
I < P _
6
~ [X]
each
that
that
If
6
6 Q ^...^
+ cg2(X)
K[X]
is
in
g
K
and
in
A...^
such
assume
over
f
if
a zero
ql (~)
= y2
, there
in
induced
g 6
quantifiers
Taking
6 ~
that
Q £ XK
f(X,Y)
dense
contained
monic
g 6 P of
P ' q 1 ' .... q r
iff
We
(see
is
uniformity
a predicate
(K,Q)
has
where
c 6 K
(K,Q).
the
is
without
in
g
0
there
and
A ql (~)
0
(K~P)
for
is
say
c 6 Q
Hence
K
(K,P)
irreducible A in (K,P) . If
arbitrary.
that
that
to
Elimination
g
holds is
respect
Thus
a formula
which
prove
approach
by
of
to
a zero
not.
~
. Then
every
not
. Now
is
coefficients
with
has
does
have
that
does
g2(K)
we
K
show
C. Z
satisfy
K
.
P £ XK
completion
a zero
Let
, we by
is of have C KZ
absolutely g
irreducible.
. Thus
the there
(a,e)
simple is
is
If
a simple
zero
a K-rational
point
138
g
2
(x)
-I • ( 2
=c
_y2)
<
2 P
a contradiction.
(1.5)
q.e.d.
PROPOSITION. is
Proof:
a sum
Let
Hence
of
two
a E ~P P6Z
f(X,Y)
Obviously
Let
= y2
are
squares
in
. Consider
is
6 K
K
. Then
every
element
of ~ P P6Z
.
the
absolutely
irreducible
polynomial
K[X,Y]
a simple
x,y
Z CK
satisfy.
+ X2 _ a 6
(/~a ,0)
there
K
zero
such
of
that
f y2
in
(K,P)
+ x2 :
a
for
each
P 6
Z
. q.e.d.
(1.6.)
PROPOSITION: induce
Let
different
K
Z
..satisfy
topologies
CK
. Then . If
the
on
K
Z
the
same
topology
depends
only
orderings
is
finite
P 6 XK we
get
Z = XK
Proof: (K,P I) By
Assume =
PI,P2
(K,P 2)
Proposition
completion
6 XK
since (1.4)
of
the K
(K,~).
induce
completion
is
dense
Therefore
it
in
(K,PI) . H e n c e
is
real
closed.
on on
K
. Then
the
(K,P I) Let
P
topology. is
also
be
the
the
i
unique
ordering
of
Now
Z
let
Since
P
and
the
logies
on
K
, by
Theorem to a
I
(4.1)), for
is
a sum
all of
(K,P I)
be
. Then
finite
elements the
get
of
Q
. But
square
a 6 K
Z
and
there
Theorem
by
= K N P : P2
induce
which
then
PI
assume
Approximation is
two
and
Q
there 6 Z
we
is
is
pairwise for
be
P 6 XK ~ different
V-Topologies
P-close
Proposition
cannot
some
to
-I
(1.5),
P-close
"
to
Z
.
topo-
(see[Pr-Z], and
a 6 ~-~Q Q6z
O-close . Thus
-1 q.e.d.
Remark: that
If w e
there
is
drop no
finiteness
a 6 K
such
of that
Z
, by H(a)
the
proof
n z : ~
of
. Since
(].6) for
we
obtained
SAP-fields
139
the
sets
tells the
H(a)
us
that
best
we
z = {plp Xk
CKZ
can
a base
get:
Let
satisfies
CK
XK
to
Xk
Xk
implies
with
is
(1.1)
and
Z
topology in
the
is
Choose
the
and
its
is
on
we
this
subset
(Pi)i6i
get
is
where
proper
K
map
the density
of
such
a field
restriction
compact,
, this
k = ~(X)
system
the
XF
. Actually,
a dense
proof
. Since
XK
XK
example
of k}
Z = {Pili6I}
Z % XK
that which
from
of
z
in
.
Let
XK
be
a prc-field
if
and
closed
consider
(9.9)).
is c o n t i n u o u s
THEOREM.
Harrison of
ordering
. By Theorem Z
the
density
us
[Pr] , T h e o r e m
z = {Pili6I}
of
implies
non-archimedean
(compare
(1.7)
form
in e v e r y
finite,
say
only
( K , P I , . . . , P n)
if
extension
X K = {PI,...,Pn}
. Then
K
is e x i s t e n t i a l l y
(L,QI, .... Q n ) s u c h
that
L/K
i_ss
regular.
Note language fixed
of
'existentially
fields
augmented
closed' by
is u n d e r s t o o d
predicates
here
Z1,...,~n
in
for
the
the
n
orderings.
Proof: of
that
Assume
that
(K,PI , . . . , P n)
proof
there
such
is p r c that
that
and
L/K
is an e x t e n s i o n
(L,Q I ..... Q n ) s u c h Consider
K
( L , Q I , . . . , Q n)
is r e g u l a r .
(K',PI' , .... P~)
K'/L
an e x i s t e n t i a l
let
is r e g u l a r
sentence
~
the
an e x t e n s i o n
By Theorem
(1.1)
and
its
of
and
of
be
K'
satisfies
C ~,Ir,~
type
r
(3~)
where
P'qi
holds and
[p(x)
in
: 0 A
6 K[~].
A i=1
qi(~)
6 P
'
Assume
for
all
] ui
~
(K',PI' , .... P n ) . W e
qi(~)
6 ~
holds
choose 1 < i < r
in
(L,Q1,...,Qn).
some
~ E K'
Then
such
. By P r o p o s i t i o n
that
(1.6),
it
also
p(~) P] , . . . .
= O 'Pn
1
induce Theorem
different
topologies
(see p r o o f
of
(1.6))
on
K
for
. Hence each
by
the
I < i < r
Approximation
we
find
-
has
the
same
sign
with
respect
to
P. J
as q i ( 5 )
c
6 K
which
I < j < n
. Thus
1
for
all
140
ciqi(a)
is
a sum o f
existential from
two
sentence
0
squares
in
(in
language
the
K' b y P r o p o s i t i o n of
(1.5).
fields
with
Now t h e
parameters
K) -~
r
(3~) Lp(x) : o ^
-)
A
<3uiv i) ciqi(x) : u 2 +
v 2]
i=1 holds
in
holds
in
K' . S i n c e K
. But
J
K'/K
then
is r e g u l a r
~
clearly
and
holds
K
in
is a p r c - f i e l d ,
9 also
(K,P I ,... ,Pn ) q.e.d.
2. T h e
elementary
In t h i s orderings.
section
Since
characteristic
The
n
theory
we
may
zero)
of p r c - f i e l d s
consider be
0
with
only prc-fields
too,
the
case
n orderings
having
exactly
of p a c - f i e l d s
n
(of
is i n c l u d e d .
structures
under
consideration
now
are of
the
type
(K, P 1 , . . . , p n where
K
called
an
is a f i e l d n-ordered
First expressed
by
of n - o r d e r e d
observe
fields.
slightly
(C) :
every
6 XK
.Such a structure
that
the
curve
set of e l e m e n t a r y
What we will
stronger
actually
'curve
sentences use
there
are
x i , Y i 6 (K,P i) w i t h
(xi,Y i)
# 0
for
are
a,b
be
6
K
with
can b e
in the
in t h i s
language
section
is the
condition'
that
all
{PI ..... mn } CK
condition
irreducible
there
will
field.
absolutely
such ~~y f
P]'''''Pn
a recursive
following
For
and
I < i < n f(a,b)
f(X,Y)
£ K[X,Y]
f ( x i , Y i) = 0
, and e v e r y = 0
, monic
and
h(X) h(a)
Y
and
6 K[X]
% 0
in
.
~
{0}
,
141
The
class
of n - o r d e r e d
mentary
class
express
(C) b y a f o r m u l a
predicates
since
fields
for
HI,...
since
fixed
H '
f ( x i , Y i) = O
The fields
free
next
free
which
theory
class.
of n - o r d e r e d
formula
formula
The
c a n be
and
of
of
f
(C)
and
fields,
is an e l e -
h
we may
augmented
the n o r d e r i n g s .
that
by
This
(2.1)
THEOREM.
Let
set of
shows
of t h i s
is c l e a r
be
(C)
in
K
by
(K,P i) w i t h in
(K,P i) b y
.
that
and
class
We denote
formulas
satisfies
xi,Y i 6
I < i < n
is p r c
(K, P I , . . . , P n )
(K, P I , . . . , P n )
are
expressed
can be expressed
each
K
theory
already
"there
for
prc-fields.
by the recursive
the
class
of n - o r d e r e d
X n = {PI,...,Pn} will
be
called
it b y P R C n
expressing
if and o n l y
if
the
It is a x i o m a -
the
an n - o r d e r e d
is
curve
field. K
condition(C).
Then
is a
prc-field
XK = {P1,...,Pn}
Proof:
First
f
h
and
for
in p a r t i c u l a r
such
tized
and
stand
condition
degree
language
over ~"
theorem
( K , P I , . . . , P n)
an e l e m e n t a r y
in the
~f ~-~ (xi,Y i) # O "
and
some quantifier
(total)
the
n
"f is i r r e d u c i b l e
some quantifier
satisfying
let
K
satisfy
be a p r c - f i e l d
the
assumptions
with
of
(C)
XK = {P1,...,Pn} Then
. Assume
the e x i s t e n t i a l
sentence (Hxy)
holds
in
K,
[f(x,y)
because
Quot(K[X,Y]/(f)) a totally
real
Next, Ci x I ' ' ' ' ' X n } Now
let
certain
L
= O ^ h(x)
# O]
it o b v i o u s l y
of the v a r i e t y regular
assume
(C) h o l d s
for
function
by
over
f
( K , P I , . . . , P n)
from Proposition
be a totally
existential
defined
in the
K
field , and
L = L/K
is
extension.
that
, we know
holds
real
sentence
regular ~ (in the
(1.6)
that
extension language
of
. Since
(C)
implies
XK = {PI,...,Pn} K
. Assume
of fields)
with
that
a
142
parameters
from
subfield L
of
itself
(as
L
is
K~
which and
Xl,...,Xm,X,y
of
L
(i)
Xl,...,Xm,X
(ii)
y
Y
K
over
are
in
in
K
K
to
be
it
is
holds
. Hence
. We
are
extension
we
(K ~,
PI
in
may
going
to
some assume
embed
that L
'''" ,Pn ~ ) of
IKl+-saturated.
possible
such
Then
~
will
find
independent
K ( x I ..... X m , X )
that
to
generators
that
algebraically
, such
already
over
over
K
over
~
.
regular,
algebraic
monic
generated
assume
hence
is
. Then
elementary
we
L/K
L
generated
some
Since
is
in
, finitely
into
( K , P I , . . . , P n) in
holds
finitely
a field)
hold
K
and
f(x,y)
= O
[Sch],
Theorem
over there
und
f
K is
is
f6 K ( X l , . . , x ~ [ X , Y ] ,
irreducible
over
K ( x I ..... x m) (For
a proof
of
now
like
embed
apply
to
the
the
(K~,Pi~) I
we
(C) in
K(~) to
have
let
now
going
Qi' : Qi
to
then
is
to
p(~)
There
is
no
algebraically
^
finally
a simple
be
to
embed
realize
% O
embed
QI,...,Qn
N K(~)
a formula
to
care
~
(K~,PI~
of
non-trivial
every
the
qj(~)
zero
the
the ,
°
.
.
L in
K~
real
of
subset
in
order
closure
too.
into
is
then
irreducible
. However,
each
would
and
PI,...,Pn
diagram
finite
V) . W e
absolutely
of
,Pn ~)
Ch.
into
orderings
extensions
. Consider
there
r /k j=1
of
the
(K(~),QI' , .... Q n , )
(K(~),QI', .... Q n ) . S i n c e have
of
take
l
only
image
on
3D,
= K ( x I .... ,x m)
the
order
assumptions
Hence
where
see
first
f(X,Y)
to verify
are
fact
condition
polynomial
We
this
to
L resp.
( K ~ , P I ~ , . .. ,Pn ~ ) the iKI +
of
structure --
saturated
this
diagram,
we which
type
E vj
equality
independent.
to
Separating
take by
care the
of,
since
index
of
Xl,...,x n Z
and
are
143
replacing
p(~)
@ O
by
m --- ~ ( l ) ^ . . . A
where
each
6 ]1 1
p2(~)
we may
assume
that
m (n)
~(i)
is
of
the
type
(i) (Z) 6 ~ ^ .A p ~ i ) ( Z ) Pl i "" .
6
i
1
Since
( 3 ~ ) ~ (i)
nation
of
Quantifiers
satisfies
(C)
( 3 ~ ) ~ (i)
also
in
(K ~ , P i ~)
(i) for
holds
, by
real
Proposition
. Thus
in for
is n o n - e m p t y .
intersection
(L,Q i)
for
holds
V-Topologies
in
By
holds
closed
fields.
(1.4),
K~
each
I < i < n
[Pr-Z], sets
in Since
~(i) the
(1.6)
Theorem
by
Elimi-
(K~,PI~,...,Pn~) in
(K~,Pi~) . Now
defines
P.~-z o p e n
and
an o p e n set
set
defined
the Approximation
(4.1))we
is n o n - e m p t y
(K~,Pi~)
is d e n s e
(K~,Pi~) , since
Proposition
(see
of t h e s e
it a l s o
too.
may
Theorem
conclude
Hence
~
by
that
the
is r e a l i z a b l e
in
(K~,PI*,...,Pn~)
Now
we
can
( K ~ ' P I ~ .... 'Pn ~) absolutely validity
identify . Finally
irreducible
!
(K(~),QI' , .... Q n )
with
we will
in
apply
polynomial
(C)
f(X,Y).
some
substructure
( K ~ , P I ,. . . ,Pn ~)
This
is p o s s i b l e
of
to t h e
since
the
of
(3xy)
now
carries
for
all
[f(x,y)
over
~f = 0 A ~
from
(x,y)
(L,Q i)
al,...,a N 6 K ~
we
to
find
% O]
(K~,Pi~)
for
a,b
such
£ K~
each
I < i < n
that
f(a,b)
. By
(C),
= O
and
N
h(a)
=
H (a-aj) ~ 0 j=1 therefore assume that
K(x,a,b)
is
isomorphic
. Using a to
again
IKI +-
saturatedness
is t r a n s c e n d e n t a l L
over
K(~)
of
K~
. But
we may
then
. q.e.d.
It s h o u l d the of
above some
proof
be mentioned is
absolutely
the
that
following:
irreducible
the
original
consider
variety
V
L
geometric as
. Find
the
idea
function
a generic
behind field
curve
on
V
144
and
spezialize
spezialized of
K
that
should
Lemma
a decidable
set.
(2.2)
LEMMA. PRC
Let
holds
Proof:
there
is
regular,
and
that
By
(0.5)
tensions
argue
by
K'/K
)
product
we
know
L = Quot(K'
~K
K") is
orderings
of
PI ' '''" 'Pn'
every in
the
sentence
also
i
in
the
closure fact
orderings.
be
of
two
regular
holds
K".
Since
K'
~K
K"
is
PRC
models
field
n
of
which
and
K'
are
K
( K " , P I " , . . . . Pr~')
integral of
ex-
from
in
K'/K
an
extension
K"/K
domain and
K"
common
ex-
resp.
with
) trivially
holds
it
~K
<0
by
parameters
K'
PI '~,... 'P n "
and
(K' 'PI ' ''" " 'Pn
way
if
L
real
theorems
")
are
and only
on
the
substructure
with
aregular
that
each
the
existential
sentence
QI '''" 'Qn
existential
(I .7), <0 t h e n
that
respect
K"/K
is
proof
common
and
if
in
(K",PI,...,Pn
n-ordered
existential
tensor
find
for
that
(0.2)
holds
Theorem
the
we
Now which
an
an
above
to
the
so
point
the
K * had
and
(K',P 1 '''''Pn
in
in
(K',PI',...,Pn')
Then
Consider
are
into
in d o i n g
a simple
that
(K,P I , .... P n ) s u c h tensions.
have
rejected
K(x)
will
difficulty
imply
. Assume
n
is
of
next
The
still
difficulty
embedding
The form
suitably.
curve
. This the
it
parameters
holds
(K",P I
in
'''''Pn
from
K
(L,Q I ,... ,Qn ) . B y ) " Similarly
we
back. q.e.d.
(2.3)
THEOREM.
The
subset
of
PRC
consisting
of
boolean
combinations
n
of
Proof:
existential
Follow
[v.d.D] and
the
essentially
Replace fact
effectively
sentences
that given
OD n it
is
is
the by
proof
PRC n
decidable
algebraic
decidable.
number
of
, and whether
Theorem use
(2.1) , Ch.
Lemma f
6 ~[X]
(2.2), has
II
in
Theorem a zero
(1.1), in
an
field. q.e.d.
145
N o w we which
consider
do not h a v e
an e l e m e n t a r y
among
any
class
the m o d e l s
algebraic
since
( K I , P I , . . . , P n)
extension
we may
of PRC n such
(L,QI,...,Qn)
express
. This
the m a x i m a l i t y
of
ones
again
is
(K,PI,...,P ~
by (A) : E v e r y
monic
each
I < i< n
By the use sees
that
tences,
(A)
The
see
(compare
[v.d.D
are
real
closed
Proof:
OD n
ordered
fields.
companion
Hence
OF
zero
PRC
and
Ch.
closed
= OD
(C) w i l l coincides
n
weaker
fields
one
be d e n o t e d with
sen-
by PRC n-
v a n den
Dries'
of OD n
II). closed
fields
and PRC I-
n model
field n)
companion to s h o w
of OF n, that
(k,Pl,...,pn) in the
(1.1)
is a m o d e l
Then
there
in w h i c h
PRC
the
theory is also
n
of
n-
a model
there
are M - e x i s t e n t i a l l y
class
6 M
we o b t a i n
of PRC
n
is a f i n i t e for
(A) d o e s
(Bx) in
(K,P I ..... Pn ) }
not
extension
irreducible
hold
of
( K , P I , . . . , P n)
algebraic
sentence
it a l s o m u s t
that
. Assume
a certain
the e x i s t e n t i a l
( L , Q I , . . . , Q n)
contradiction.
fo__~r
n
(C) and h e n c e
f 6 K[X]
(K,P i)
axiomatization
algebraically
it s u f f i c e s
of T h e o r e m
( K , P I , . . . , P n)
in
set of e l e m e n t a r y
{(K,P I ..... Pn ) I (k,p] ..... pn ) s u b s t r u c t u r e
(K,PI,...,Pn).
Since
a
fields.
an n - o r d e r e d
in the p r o o f
nomial
(A)
are
extensions(K,P1,...,P
M =
fies
n
by
(1.2),
is the u n i q u e
of
Given
of
], T h e o r e m
PRC
a recursive
a seemingly
PRCo-models
THEOREM.
has
for real
by
theorem
provides
that
(2.4)
As
next
Note models
closed
axiomatized
in the
This
which
of Q u a n t i f i e r s
can be e x p r e s s e d
theory
OD n
f 6 K[X]
is linear.
of E l i m i n a t i o n
As we w i l l theory
irreducible
hold
in
( L , Q I , . . . , Q n)
non-linear
f(x)
satis-
poly-
= 0 holds.
(K,P I , .... Pn ) , a
146
It
remains
(K,P1,...,pn) a regular
c
show
of
sentence
holds
in
that
PRC
(L,QI,...,Qn)
extension
existential also
to
K
with
be
. Now
is m o d e l
n two
models
Theorem
parameters
(K,PI,...,Pn)
. This
complete. of
(1.7)
from
proves
PRC n
. By
implies
K
which
model
Let (A) ,
that holds
L
is
every in
completeness
(L,Q I ..... ~) of
PRC n q.e.d.
In by
[v.d.D
] van
den
Dries
definitions
of
OD n
new
predicates
he
adds
for
the
of
pseudo-finite
showes
theory that
Kiefe's
Quantifiers.we constants
Let
augmented
W
each
for
be
I
there
Elimination
natural
then
fields.
In
do that
not
adding
to
just
sufficient.
elementary
theory
in
c I .... ,c n
, axiomatized
by
(A),
each
I < i<
n
THEOREM.
Proof:
By
PRC
the
K(i)
common
(K(i)
of
PRC
existential R
n
for
holds
in
of
sentence
. If
then
K (2) .
by
(2.16) obtain
n
new
the
and
Kiefe van
., Xm)
[K]
den
Dries of
individual
language
of
(m+1)-ary 6 9.
1
i
admits
~=~(3Y)Xo +xlY
Elimination
criterion
for
situation:
of
n-ordered
predicates ^
/~
c.
6 K.
j$i
±
]
i = K
1,2
(1)
(in t h e ~
holds
in
: O ]
Quantifiers.
elimination
we
have
Let (i) Cn '
. Furthermore
and
+. " "+ x m y m
quantifier
K
(2)
augmented K (I)
t
and
let
language) we
have
(i) (Wm
let
to
(R,...)
be
with show
) )m>1
R : ~
n
The
Elimination
(C) , -c.
_(i) ,p~i) c#i) PI . . . . . . . . . .
'
substructure
from
n
following
=
be m o d e l s
[ Wm(Xo''"
a well-known
consider
OD
, and
(VXo ..... Xm)
(2.5)
extension
used
Example
suffice
an
of Q u a n t i f i e r s .
those
predicates
constants
is
-
for
to
less
show
the
by
m >
m
now
Kiefe's
PRC n
fields,
are
that
admits
predicates
will
makes
which
shows
be
a simple parameters
that
it
also
a
147
Passing field.
Since
f 6 R[X]
K (2)
to
closed c! I) 3
W (1) m
the
algebraic
isomorphic.
and
R sign
Lemma
just
of
that
(By)
To
that
that we
R
is
Hence
the
in
a square
K
K (2)" " . It in
K
(I)
is and
isomorphism
this: we
the
just
of
Then
(I)
a
algebraically
product
negative.
is
polynomials
R
an
R
in
of
such
coincide. be
same
a zero
assure
a square
is
have
can
c is
, the
that
constants
write
those
ac
is
. Thus,
if
in K (2) . H e n c e
a
c. 2
.
c.'s 3
totally a
is
and
~(a)
and We
K(2)/R may
and
atomic
formula
not
an
atomic
assume
regular,
that
unnegated
those
in
are
atomic
formulas involving
~
~
we (Bx)~
formulas.
involving any
are
Wm,
some we
in
the
where
~
If
we
could
predicate
could
is
deduce
W
m
from
R (2)
formula
..... a m ( X ) )
it b y
ao(X)
eliminate
proceed
is
holds
all
+ a1(x)y
the
Wm (ao (x) ..... we
and
a
negated
~
eliminate
replace
(A)
(2.2).
existential
Wm(ao(X)
R
K(1)/R
by
To
to
fact,
R
assume
closures
assume
assume
may
behaviour.
equivalently
(2,2)
. In
, o(ac)
replace
Lemma
K (2)
by
since of
may
whenever
hence
same
can
a £ K (I) . L e t
negative
over
we
belong
some
conjunction
some
If w e
orderings,
c! 2) 3
Now,
the
also
forces
and
situation
on
this
K (I)
the
coincide
that
positive and
have
W (2) m
we
K (I)
in
algebraic
quotients
in
the
are
and
of
a zero
consider
which
field
have
be
respects
the
which
well-known
Now
to
as
+...+
negated
am(X)
follows:
am(X)y m
= 0
formulas
)
First
we
fix
some
x
6 K (1)
which
satisfies
4.
148
Now
-~
= a
Wm(ao(X)
(x)
+...+
a
0
(x)Y m
means
6 K(1) [Y]
that
does
the
not
polynomial
have
any
f(Y)
zero
in
=
K (I)
. We
m
split By
.... , a m ( X ) )
f
into
(A),
each
irreducible of
the
fi's
factors
over
must
without
be
K (1) , s a y
f
zerosin
= fl"'''"
fr
(K(1) ,P (I))
for
"~i some
~.
. By
Elimination
of
Quantifiers
for
real
closed
by some quantifier
free
fields,
this
1
can be
expressed
in
(K (1) , p (x 1) . ) )
formula.
21.
H e n c e we s e e existential
that
we may r e p l a c e
formula
fl,...,fr
such
~
expressing:
that
fi
Wm(ao(X), ....
"there
does
not
are
have
am(X))
(coefficients
a zero
in
by an of)
polynomials
( K ( 1 ) , P (I))~.
and
1
f = fl
"'''"
,i
fr
" q.e.d.
3.
In
this
prc-field real
section
is
again
hilbertian
which
are
prc
extension
(3.1)
but
need
V
a simple method
there real
exist
L
first
be
an
treat
W
each
defined P
Then,
by
the
image
under
6 XK
the
is
point
K
Remark
be
of
for
will which
K
in
an at
, W
L-rational
end
of
Then
a
of
field
k
k
such
section).
every
algebraic
too.
construct
extension, defined
over
. Using
an
absolutely
from
to a
V
[L:K] L
Well's
V
defined
K-rational .
= n
which
. has
descent
irreducible
(K,P)-rational
W
have of
say
6 XL
a simple
point
this
of
a countable
real
the
Q
will
is
arbitrary
variety
has
k
extensions
a finite
a
case
a prc-field.
each
extension
algebraic
a prc-field
a morphism on
that
For
K
algebraic
real
irreducible
over
an
many
case
we
assumption ~
is
§ 1.3)
, and
are
every
show
closed.
K
absolutely
[We],
also
Let
of
extensions
that
(see
THEOREM.
We
(see
prove
. We
(L,Q)~rational
variety for
not
not
extension
Let
prc
field
EXTENSION
Proof:
we
Algebraic
point over
point
L
whose
.
149
Let By
Pi(X)
of
L
the p r i m e = x(i)
over
the p r i m e over and
with
K
into
ideal
L (i)
ideal
of
V
be g e n e r a t e d
I< i < n K•
say
we d e n o t e
Pl = id.
an a b s o l u t e l y
. If we
g~i)
of
take
(i) 6 L ( i ) [x#i)
'
variety
V (I)
base
L
over
. Then
d e t ( s ~ i))
(i)
n z : j=1
(*)
XI
defines
K
a(i) 3
an i n v e r t i b l e
the p r i m e
ideal
an a b s o l u t e l y already
which
determined
over
+'''+
(n) al
+"
where
(X/Y)
that
f
s3
fs
I
each
of
P
assumption• Q's V
(i)
variety i
x...x
V
(i)
X# i) ,...X m ,_(I)
'''"
of the
V (n) . Let
defined
(i)
, say
g~1)
I
generate
gr
'''"
absolutely
Sl,...,an
be
for e a c h
I < 1 <m
. Call
substitution.
J
# O
a
and h e n c e
substitution
results
K
from
this
variety , take
fsj
W
. In o r d e r
as g e n e r a t o r s
which
satisfy
to see
for the
J
thus
that
W
J
defines is
the u n i q u e l y
linear
system
(I) f (I) (X/y) an sn = gs
.+ a
(n) n
the
f
sn
(i) (X/Y) gs
:
substitution
(*)
. Now
that
a simple
it is e a s i l y
seen
. 6 K[Y]
P 6 XK
embeddings Q
"
indicates
It r e m a i n s for
linear
polynomials
a 1) fsl
gl (i) '''" 'gr(i)
then
ideal
embeddings
YIj
irreducible
defined
different
'
the p r i m e
product
gl '''''gr 6 L[XI,...,X m]n
for e a c h
n
irreducible of
Then
. X (i) ] ''"
(n) (n) • "" 'gl '''''gr generate
the
irreducible
new variables
• ''''gr
by
This for
Pi to
some map
. Say has
means each
. Fix which
L V
to s h o w
there
I < i < r
has
P 6 XK L
into
pl,...,pr
a simple
that
W
and w r i t e K
are
K
for
correspond these
(L,Q)-rational is a s i m p l e
. The
(K,P)-rational
remaining
point
embeddings.
for
By
the c o r r e s p o n d i n g
(x~ i) '''''x(i))6m
'non-real'
. The
to the e x t e n s i o n s
'real' point
(K,P)
point
embeddings
in
150
Pr+1,...,pn conjugate simple
map with
(~i)
(Here
x
means point
in
K
Since
The
first
that
the type We
have
to
sequence Hence such
It
is
of
that
W
of of
is
is
preimage
. This
choose
an
and
now
clear
and
has
finishes
the the
are
arbitrary conjugate
to
Pl "
over
that
the
corres-
its
a K-rational under
which
the
is c o n j u g a t e
simple
there
its V
is
in p a i r s
"
coordinates
point
on
W
substitution proof
for
.
(*)
finite
.
for
an
arbitrary
proved
3~
in t h e
of
first
L
order
(4.1)
~ (~,~) that
elements
K(~)
on
a prc-field
point
Theorem
show
V (i)
K).
property
<0 -= V ~
for
over
(4.1),
of
we
conjugation
in t h e
proof
6 K(V-~T)
come
case
P3 '
coordinates
the
axioms
this
if
proof
of T h e o r e m
K
. In
They
V (j)
K
L/K
The
: K
for
an L - r a t i o n a l
show
to
K(/-I)
(y11,...,Ymn)
m
extensions
of
respect
~(i)) '''''m
ponding
form
into
(x I(i) ,. .. 'x m(i))
point
point
L
is ~ (u,v)
next
where these
of
L
by
holds
prc
language
these
is
axioms
. Then
fields. can
be
is
the
above
proof.
in
K(~).
Hence
it
we
also
by
be
Let
use
we will a set
seen
to be
free
a finite
Thus
(4.1)
As w i l l
chosen
<0hold in L.
makes
expressed
a quantifier
K(~)
L/K
In T h e o r e m
can be
of
axioms ~
extension
section.
being
all
prc
algebraic
of
from
the
formula.
~
be
a finite
extension
find
~
holds
in
of
in L
K
K(~) .
q.e.d.
The we
have
Theorem
only
seen
so f a r
(3.1),
( L , Q I , . . . , Q n)
algebraic
van
are den
which
PRC1-extensions
real Dries
are
closures proves
algebraic
of
the
of k
a given In
existence
extensions
of
(real)
[v.d.D] of
field , Ch.
II,
PRC n - models
a countable
k
.
151
hilbertian
field
topologies
on
Modifying theorem
k
THEOREM.
which
Proof:
We
a,b
Dries'
n I
PRC1-extensions
Let
about
6 R
to
construct
orderings
inducing
such
an
L
proof
we
will
of
k
still
which
hilbertian
we
different
is
obtain are
fields
real in
not
the
real
refer
closed. next
closed.
the
reader
field
and
to
K = ~ m ~
Km
that
(see
, we
take
construct
f(a,b)
= 0
Sl .... 'ar km
. We
and let will
(f,h)
= 0
number
of
(R,Q)
elements
a PRC1-subfield
such
(K,P)
of
(R,Q)
occurs
K m c . . .c
{0}
, and
(a,b)
Y
that
there
~
, such
% O
. The
enumeration
often.
We
are
going
of
k
. The
with
R
. Thus field
its
If
either
h
Km+ I D K m % 0 r H j=1
or If
such . To
f
both that
take
Irr(ai,k)
ensure
Km
are
looking
(unique)
constructed
Km+ I = K m
every
we
already
then
in
infinitely
we
g =
h 6 R[X]
chain
[Ro])
h(a)
that
monic ~f ~
and
pair
Km
together
(f,h)
hilbertian
finite
irreducible,
every
K Ic . . . c
that
every exists
pairs
f(a,b)
a countable
Assume
Km
there
all
extensions
pair
k
To
real
Sl,...,ar
with
as w e l l
a countable
k
absolutely
k = K° c
field
be
of
6 R ~
such
finite
k
closure
is
chosen
in
den
enumerate
is
will
van
omits
f £ R[X,Y]
in
n =
information
Sl,...,ar
m-th
for
algebraic
a real
of
admits
.
(3.2)
are
which
. But
slightly
Concerning
[Ro]
k
that
ordering
Km do
has
will
P = K
have
we its
n Q
are
also
of
and no
zero
in
Km
6 Km+ I
the
elements
in
.
the
coefficients
a,b
assume
be
consider
coefficients
there
6 k[Z]
a hilbertian for
. Then
not
have
care
g
is
g Km+ I
has
, we
with
no too.
zero
152
Now and is
the
let
By
section and of
(Km,K m
n Km
S Q)
f 6 Km[X,Y]
Theorem
such
that
Km
is
we
algebraically Let
U
enlarging
proof
and
Function
set
U
its
6 Km[X]
Implicit
a Q-open
(R,Q).
h
if
for
and
that
an
closed
From
there
Km•
F = Km(t) [Y]/(f ~Y))
an
we
may
assume
f(t,Y)
such has
has
Ch.
on
that
there
a zero the
f
in
inter-
II
in [ v . d . D
extension
(Km~ ,P*)
that
a zero
following
know
that
(1.16),
elementary
and
the
we
, f(a,Y)
6 Km* ~ K m
. From
(R,Q)
assumption
6 U
Theorem
is
the
a
t
element in
to
each
necessary,
non-empty.
know
applied
. By
K m (t) in
diagram
]
is
(Km~ , P*) . we
conclude
K*F m
K* m
F
K m (t)
1
K m
(i)
f(t,Y)
is
(ii)
f(t,Y)
has
(iii)
g(Z)
has
(i) and
no
is
follows
from
~m
implied
zero
follows
K ~F m
F/K m
a zero
Km*/Km(t)
(iii)
and
irreducible in
O
K * [Y]/(f(t,Y)). m
the
regular. the
h(t) ~
(Km~ , P~)
in
from
K • , and m
facts (ii)
facts
that
t
follows
is
from
transzendental the
choice
over
of
t
K
m
.
that
--~ K * [ Y ] / ( f ( t , Y ) ) m
is by
over
algebraically the
closed
regularity
of
in
K ~F/F m
Km *F
. This
(cf. (0.2))
last and
assertion
the
is
regularity
of
(cf. ( O . 3 ) ) .
It formula
is
clear
~
in
the
how
to
express
language
of
(i) , (ii) , a n d ordered
fields.
(iii) Hence
by we
an know
elementary that
the
153
sentence means Km
H t ~
that we
, h(a)
z e r o in
can
, and
Km(b)
~
(Km~,P~)
a 6 K
f(a,Y)
and t h u s
such
m
that
has
a zero
Km[Y]/(f(a,Y))
. Now
finally
PRC1-model
in
find
# 0
If w e is a
holds
also
in
f(a,Y) b 6 R
let
This
is i r r e d u c i b l e
such
that
g
over
has
no
K m + I = Km(b)
take
K = ~ K m , it b e c o m e s m6~ that al,...,a r ( K
such
(Km,K m D Q).
clear
that
(K,K D Q)
q.e.d.
Remark:
The
assumption
be henselian
with
prc-extension K
must
respect
.
be real
(4.1)
THEOREM.
Proof:
We will
m > 0
we have
(Hm) : F o r
~~y f
Y
there
fixed
total
and
(1.4)
of p r c - f i e l d s
we prove
K/k
and §8
Let
a real
in
[Pr],
k
algebraic
the
field
is e l e m e n t a r y
just one
of p r c - f i e l d s
that
K
absolutely that
% 0
are
The
class
class
show
theorem.
c a n be a x i o m a t i z e d
irreducible
there
£ K
degree
problem and
are
the
in t h e
f(~,b)
if for
f 6 K[Xl,...,Xm+I,Y]
, and = O
collection
is to e l i m i n a t e
arbitrary
if and o n l y
~ , y 6 (K,P)
P 6 XK
with
to e x p r e s s
only
is a p r c - f i e l d
for e a c h
~,b
It r e m a i n s of f i e l d s .
is e s s e n t i a l :
of f i e l d s .
, such
(~,y)
to s o m e v a l u a t i o n ,
section
The
every
in
to be h i l b e r t i a n
closed.
final
language
k
Then by Proposition
4. T h e
In t h i s
on
with
every and
f(x,y)
, monic = 0
(Hm)
#
O
.
in the
for p o l y n o m i a l s
coefficients
~
and
h 6 K [ X I ,- . . , X m + 1 ] ~ { O } , h(~)
of all
every
the
clause
language f
of
154
"for
each
P 6 XK ~f ~-~
and
By
Elimination
"there this
are
..."
formula
express
in
the
to
qi(~)
field
P6
generate fact
XK
This
is
K every
2 squares
by
Proposition
(1.5).
see
of
that
the
: O
P it
of
this
take
this
to
6 P
"
coefficients. such
by
that
equals as
that
So we all
cannot
a formula,
fact
elementarily
take
suffices
qr(~)
K
3 squares
replace
. If w e
-q] (~) ..... - q r ( ~ )
express
We
on
can
type
integral
ordering
sum
we
involving
we
with
that
formulate
f(x,y)
fields
formula
clause
no
. To
a prc-field
can
with
= 0 v ql (~) £ P v . . . v
in
we
closed
form,
some
that
Now
real
free
means
of
6 (K,P)
"
polynomials there
a preordering
~,y
normal
: p(~)
that
negative.
prc-fields.
O
for
language
are
formalize are
•
a quantifier
p,ql,...,qr
have
(~,y)
conjunctive
each
are
Quantifiers
by
in
"for
where
of
there
we
a sum
the
of
a first
there
use
are
axiom
for
sums
s.
1
N
of
squares,
range
over
not all
all
zero,
possible
such
that
r+1-fold
E i=I
b.s. i 1
products
of
= O
, where
elements
the
b. 1
of
{ I ,-ql (~) ..... - q r (~) } " It prc.
As
remains in
generated, a
that
totally
plane
Assume
that
and
(3x,y)
Q
(2.1)
real
regular
extension
6 XL
here,
the
I
[f(x,y)
f
that ~f
= 0 ^ ~
K
satisfying
have
to
K • of
K
algebraically
absolutely
P~ n K = Q Q K
(x,y)
% O
]
we
do
monic
in
irreducible. . Then
is
into not
easier.
independent
and
(H m)
a finitely
. Since
is m u c h
irreducible
is
embed
all
L = K(Xl,...,Xm+1,y)
situation
are be
(o.3), such
we
extension
Xl,...,Xm+
. By
~
field
Theorem
curves
= 0
every
of
f 6 K[XI,...,Xm+I,Y]
f(x,y)
P~ 6 X K ~
that
elementary
to
let
prove
proof
IKl+-saturated
restrict
and
the
to
the
over Y
K
such
Let validity
of
,
155
carries for
over
real
and
closed
h(~)
* 0
K*
is
h(~)
* 0
since and
from
L
fields.
to
(K~,P-~) b y
By
(Hm) , t h e r e
. In g e n e r a l ,
~,b
IKL+-saturated, we for
algebraically to
(L,Q)
all
the E l i m i n a t i o n are
depend even
over
K ,
6 K*
on the
find
h 6 K[~] ~ {0}
independent
~,b
with
choice
f(a,b)
of
h.
~ , b 6 K* w i t h
. Hence
and
of Q u a n t i f i e r s
thus
However,
f(~,b)
a I ..... am+ I K(a,b)
= 0
is
= O
are
isomorphic
. q.e.d.
It s h o u l d not
necessary
But
it m a k e s
be mentioned
to p r o v e life
easier
interesting
in its
to r e s t r i c t
to p l a n e
being
the
the r e s t r i c t i o n
axiomatizability
in w r i t i n g
own right. curves,
down
of the
such
to h y p e r s u r f a c e s class
axioms,
We do not know whether as w e d i d
in T h e o r e m
is
of p r c - f i e l d s .
and
it is
it is p o s s i b l e
(2.1)
in c a s e
of
X
K
finite.
In a f o r t h c o m i n g elementary In f a c t , ordered
subclass
we will fields.
jectured
by van
Last but many
that
inspiring
of
show The
paper we the
that
its
existence
den Dries
not
class
least,
discussions.
(see
show
there
of p r c - f i e l d s
theory of
that
such
[v.d.D]
we would
is a c e r t a i n
which
is the m o d e l a model , p.
like
is m o d e l
companion
companion
complete. of p r e -
has b e e n
con-
Roquette
for
73).
to t h a n k
Peter
REFERENCES
[Ax]
J. Ax: The e l e m e n t a r y theory of finite Ann. of Math. 88(1968), 239-271
[Ba]
S.A. Basarab: D e f i n i t e functions on algebraic v a r i e t i e s ordered fields. To appear in Revue R o u m a i n e Math. pures appliqu6es.
[ Ch]
G. Cherlin: Model t h e o r e t i c Lecture Notes in Math. 521,
[ Ch-K]
C ± Chang-H.
[v.d.D]
L. van den Dries:
[mr]
G. Frey: P s e u d o a l g e b r a i c a l l y closed fields real valuations. J. Alg. 26(1973), 202-207
[Ja]
N. Jacobson: L e c t u r e s in abstract van Nostrand, New Haven, 1964
[Jr]
M. Jarden: E l e m e n t a r y statements over large Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 164(1972), 67-91
[Ea]
I. Kaplansky: P o l y n o m i a l s in t o p o l o g i c a l Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 54(1948), 909-916
[Ki]
C. Kiefe: Sets d e f i n a b l e over finite fields: their functions. T r a n s . A m e r . M a t h . Soc. 223(1976), 45-59
[La]
S. Lang: I n t r o d u c t i o n to algebraic Interscience, New York, 1958
[M-H]
J. Milnor-D. Husemoller: S y m m e t r i c b i l i n e a r Springer, B e r l i n - H e i d e l b e r g - N e w York, 1973
[Pr]
A. Prestel: L e c t u r e s Matem&ti~ca 22, IMPA,
[Pr-Z]
A. Prestel-M. Ziegler: of t o p o l o g i c a l fields. 318-341
[Ro]
P . Roquette: N o n s t a n d a r d aspects of H i l b e r t ' s i r r e d u c i b i l i t y theorem, in: Model theory and algebra, 231-275, L e c t u r e Notes in Math. 498, Springer, 1975
[Sch]
W. Schmidt: E q u a t i o n s over finite fields. An e l e m e n t a r y approach. Lecture Notes in Math. 536, Springer, 1976
[we]
A. Weil: studies,
[Wh]
W. Wheeler: M o d e l - c o m p l e t e theories of p s e u d o - a l g e b r a i c a l l y closed fields. Ann. Math. Logic 17(1979) , 205-226
Keisler:
Model
Model
fields.
algebra; selected Springer, 1976 theory.
theory
topics.
North-Holland,
of fields.
algebra
over et
Amsterdam,1973
Thesis, with
Utrecht,
1978
non-archimedean
III.
algebraic
fields.
fields.
zeta-
geometry.
forms.
on formally real fields. Rio de Janeiro, 1975
Monografias
de
Model t h e o r e t i c m e t h o d s in the theory J. reine angew. Math. 299/300 (1978),
Adeles and algebraic Princeton, 1961
groups.
Institute
for advanced
Some
Remarks
on the M a t h e m a t i c a l
Incompleteness
of P e a n o ' s
Found
and H a r r i n g t o n
by P a r i s
T. v o n d e r
I.
paper
shall
is to s u p p l e m e n t
assume
2.12
give
a simplified
[I]
and
Paris
on the
For m o s t
these
plicitly.
occur,
Finally,
theoretic
central
rSle
strong
they
e.g.
[2],
of r e c u r s i v e
PA satisfied
by
of
L "
is a
. The
have
segments
[I] M ~
(c)~
of the m a i n
on n o n - f i n i t e than
~
of by
in PA.
ones
illustrate
exthe
playing
a
axiomatizability of PRA,
-
and
independence
to w e l l - k n o w n
[2].
2.6
ideas
provabilities
shall
and
(numbers
Z -indiscernibles o
other
[I]
of P ~
completions
of
of m o d e l s .
and N o t a t i o n
P A is f i r s t - o r d e r 0,1,+,.,<
models
the
of
famous
avoid
of a p p l i c a t i o n s
[I]
and
the
be r e d u c e d
of
nonexistence
Basic Concerts
will
a couple
initial
exposition
can c o m p l e t e l y
papers
relation
including
significance
in
lemmas
partition
elaborate
results, we
and H a r r i n g t o n ' s
combinatorial
and m o r e
and H a r r i n g t o n ,
Whenever
model
- 2.14)
[2].
Paris'
the p u r e l y
2.9,
Zo
Twer
Introduction
This We
Arithmetic
only
Peano's
Z -formulas o bounded
Zn+1-formulas, Hn-fOrmula.
arithmetic,
n £ ~ Dually,
its
(or b o u n d e d
quantifiers,
formulas,
e.g.
, are of the Hn+1-formulas
language
3 x < y,
shape are
the
L containing or
limited Vx
< y
3 Xl... 3 X m ~ VXl...
VXm~
formulas) . 9 ° is
, where with
158
Models
as w e l l
as t h e i r
is the n a t u r a l are
thought
underlying
model
of PA,
of as c o n t a i n i n g
sets
other
are d e n o t e d
models
~ . Th N
(M)
by M,MI,M'
of the o c c u r r i n g
is the Th(M)
D Hn
etc.
theories
" We
often
n write
M F ~(a,b,c,...)
M p ~(x,y,z,...) For
n 6 ~
notation
n
M
L-variables
does
a,b,c,..,
I ~ M
and
of
is an i n i t i a l
M
V a,b 6 M(a
an e n d - e x t e n s i o n means
that
I ~ M
I ~ ~(~) We have
of
iff I
and
M
if
nal
defining
for
only,
recursive
plus
truth-predicate
Xl,...,x m
of v a r i a b l e s 6 ~o'
substitution-functions, n ~ I
we
need
in for
of
M
beiff
substructure
in
I
Z -substructure n
arithmetic) recursive
induction
of t h e e x t e n d e d
recursive
~(Xl,...,Xm),~
of e l e m e n t s
M
I ~e M
, ~
M
x,y,z,..,
segment
by
s
I
is t h e n
. I~in
M
: of
M
.
.
any primitive
equations
parameters)
~
arith-
in g e n e r a l .
initial
be denoted
is a
for
a substructure.
~ -formulas n I
. Our
~e
(primitive
symbols
is a l s o
will
all
M
s
interval
a 6 I). A n
of
~ ~(a,b,c,...).
their meanings
I is an i n i t i a l
which
i.e.
I
E~ o PRA
for
symbols
of m o d e l s ,
the
instead
L
off by using
marked
denote
M
in
being
< b 6 I ~
M ~ ~(~),
between
n
and
these.
I , which
for
or r e l a t i o n s
will
segment
a,b,c,...6
(M,a,b,c...)
term
for e l e m e n t s
[a,b]
, including
and
or of
not distinguish functions
a,b 6 M
a and b
~
constant
, the d i f f e r e n c e and
For tween
is the n a t u r a l
definable
the m o d e l
formulas
[ x / a , y / b , z / c .... ]
widely
metically
for
tr
o
r~
~n-definabl~
function
axioms
for
language.
for
satisfying our
is a r i t h m e t i c and
shall
I -formulas o
suppressing
denoting
the
G~del
truth-predicates
P A ~ trn( ~I , X l , . . . , X m ) e~ ~ ( x I .... ,Xm)
for
all
their
formulas
(with
the p r i m i t i v e
a fixed
sequence
I .... ,Xm) ~
numeralnumber
tr n
additio-
for
use
with
P R A H tro( ~ , x
notation
axioms
the o p e n
We
with
of
and ~
. For
satisfying
~ ( X l , . . . , x m)
6 Zn
159
The Strong
Partition
(Paris-Harrington
For
a,b,c,d,e
partitions)
Relation
with
£ ~
[a,b]
the same
1.1
The Finite
This
use G~del's codes
with
large,
i.e.
which
1.2
leads
The proof 1.1,1.2
[a,b] ~
3b
sequences
for
P
[a,b]
X ~[a,b]
for
if
is
P(~)
6 ~
can be f o r m a l i z e d
PA U T h H I ( ~
Matiyasevic's
the p a r t i t i o n homogeneous one obtains
in the
¥n'
Bn~hierarchy
lenghts
to
also b o u n d e d
the
as set-
arithmetically
and hence be p r o v i d e d of 1.1
relation sets
X
is k n o w n
[a,b] ~
to be
(c)~
by
be r e l a t i v e l y
a relation
[a,b] ~ (c)~
d e Theorem,
H2-sentence,
leads
regard
principle
Ramsey
) by Paris
theorem
, as follows:
and their
that any b o u n d e d
theorem, V 2 ) is the best
whereas
as sets
[a,b] ~ (c)
as a
PA
arithmetically,
H2-formalization
Infinite
of
then build up the i n v o l v e d
combinatorial
the
language
can thus be encoded
< Card(X),
6 ~
in the
Note
Strenghtening
to the v a l i d
Matiyasevic's
set
of
d e
sets,
The r e s u l t i n g
min(X)
of
d-element-subsets
homogeneous
sequences
M ~ PA
of this uses
independent
(c)
to enCode
that the r e q u i r e d
V a,c,d,e
(called
reads:
as usual.
set in an
of PA.
for all functions
is a h o m o g e n e o u s
is called
increasing
notions
the c o n d i t i o n
there
the r e s p e c t i v e
a cardinal.
a theorem
of
Theorem
~-function
the c a r d i n a ~ o f
definable
[[a,b]] d
can be f o r m a l i z e d
of s t r i c t l y
theoretical
X
H b 6 ~
statement
means:
~ 6 [X] d
Ramsey
6 ~
(c) d e
<e
~ c .
for all
V a,c,d,e
~
P from the set
Card(X)
Principle
Formula).
into the set of numbers P
and the C o m b i n a t o r i a l
cf.
[I].
w h i c h was proved
and Harrington. attainable
H2
to be
(or, by
by their m e t h o d s ,
Vl-independences. quantifiers
Like
count.)
(Recall
that
160
It 1.3
V xV
which We
is
again
is
of
Lemma: is
c > d
, we
of be
ing
there
1.1) [a,b]
M ~ A
VX
Vy
steps
partitions lifting
the
Let
us
the
, g:~
~
of
,
[I])
([x,y]
~
(z+1) z z
2.7
- 2.9,
of
Z -Indiscernibles o
~
2.12
lemmas
2.6
a primitive
, so
that
If
M ~
[a,b]
~
which
are
for (c)~
all
in
-
[I].
2.9,
2.12
set
X
recursive
M ~ PA
, then
encodable
a homogeneous
~
- 2.14
single
, d ~ r
~
a d
in
for M
function.
and
all
(cf.
, encoded
are: one,
(i)
is
a,b,c
6 M
,
partitions
the
in
lifting e
which
M
remark , for
followP
,
ugly
X
explicitly
together
superscripts essentially, ~
relative
misprint
in
A
< y)
distinguishes
of
< Card(X)
completely
collecting
subscripts
an
^ g(min(X))
< y ~ g(x)
2.1
properties
mention
2.8
s
by
by
lemmas
in
Amin(X)
> min(X)
additional
and
by
1.2
that
M =
into
2.7
combinatorial
(X E X A y 6 X ^ X
the
Card(X)
is
> c
For
lemmas
denoted
of
that
Existence
~asy
[0,2)
Remark: main
the
r 6 ~
, such
Card(X)
using
expressed
have:
r ~
Xc
the
d E ~
P:[[a,b]]
(by
remark
formalization
(z+1) z z
by
on
the
, henceforth
(z+1) z zomax(x+1,7))
Let
There
replace
equivalent,
Results
can
in P A
~
obtained
meaning [~]
2.1
~
to
(z+1) z
~
, but
provably
Basic
The
1.3
[O,y]
P A i- ([O,y]
2.
[x,y]
equivalent use
V z B y
which
convenient
z 3 y
is
shall
1.4
is
[I]
to in
a fixed d
to
(ii)
in
finite
number
a common
using
from a fixed lemma
proved
~
the to
of
without
condition
obtain
primitive 2.14
one
[I],
the recursive
. There
it
is
g.
161
important
that
ly r e a l i z e d a,b,c
s' d o e s
to hold
may be kept
The main tion leads
[a,b]
to the
homogeneous
~
The
model
next
sharpened, in
[I],
2.2 w i l l
of 2.1
all
if
io < ii
M ~
Vx
Proof: of
<'''<
for
P(u,~,~)
these
X
M ~ Card(X)
in
iff
is the large
[a,b]
observaenough
which i.e.
segments
lemmas
are
sets
of
of
M
it < Jl
[a,b]
(M ~
: there
~
< s
satisfy
M ~ PA
the
,
is a s e q u e n c e
in the
for all
language
of
PA
:
~ ( x , e j I ,. " ' ' e j t )).
2.1
c a n be
t-tuples
is s m a l l e r
(~(x,~) ~ with set for
ei,
2.15
' then
denote
Vx
, so let
~
d
< e i + I , so t h a t
[O,c)
Jt
and
b e the p r i m i t i v e
for
Lemma
of
g
. Then we have
<'''<
(~,~
. Let
r,g
6
2.11
same.
. Let
r~
though
2.10,
= no (2n°s+1)
jl,...,jt
a homogeneous
~ c
simplified,
g(n)
with
~ ( x , Y l , . . . , y t) be
the
, e i 6 [a,b) , e i2
any c o m p o n e n t
= O
initial
of the
, c > d
the a s s u m P t i o n s ,
Zo-formulas So let
by
< e l•o ( ~ ( x , e i l , . . . , e i t )
that
of
but
is n e e d e d .
parameters,
a technically
remaining
given
io,il,...,it,
2t+1-tu~es
means
give
~ ( x , Y l , . . . , y t)
With
with
6 ~ , t > O , r = 2t+I
(eili 6 M, M ~ i < c)
and
of P R A
c,d,e
subsets
to e s t a b l i s h
(c) dd ' a , b , c 6 M
Zo-formulas
with
is i m m e d i a t e -
all p a r a m e t e r s
and H a r r i n g t o n
enough
of w h a t w e n e e d
s,t
function
M ~ [a,b] ~
, since
proof
again.
Let
conditions
this
little
M ~ PA
large
thus
. Now
only
Zo-formulas
i d e a of p r o o f
2.2 L e m m a : recursive
of
e
of P a r i s
in s o m e
and
version
the
finite;
the w o r k
(sets of)
PA
lemma
M ~ PA
(c)~
Z -indiscernibles, o which
arbitrary
standard
existence for
on
for
idea behind
that
not depend
i <~c
~
applied with
than
~(x,~))
u < ~ < ~
any of
according
, be the
~)
, ~ <
defined
by
for a l l
< s) , o t h e r w i s e P
to the p a r t i t i o n
first
P(u,~,~)
to 2.1. c
= I
We have
elements
of
X .
162
By
the
choice
of
2 e i < ei+ I
g
2t+1-tuples
in
faction
Z -formulas o
of
P(u,v,w)
{eili
= O
for
< c}
P
q0,z
(~)
=
sequences
have
(a _>2t+I)
has
a subset
~,w
6 A,
~
hence
for
# ~
, we
are
these
be
least
of
M
Notice , so
possible
The
~
of
the
the
M ~
results
is
~,~
~
2.1
Card(X) a
by
> a
to
. There the
> to ( 2 a ° s + 1 )
< ~
with
, and
result
such
. Now by
choice
of
prin-
(P%0,z(~) l
for ei
all can
.
familiar
with
the
case
of
I -indiscernibles o
the
=
of
deals
on
we
Dirichlet
this
only
.
g
for
the
sequence
,
[X~{a}] t
induction
homogeneity
[X] t
at m o s t
proof
PA
in
are
(Pcp,z(~) J~,z)
, the
. For
, ~
that
the
satis-
that
, so
by
are
on
prove
z < a
and
available
6 A
= O
M
there
~ = min(X)
, M ~
elements
or
the
. Set
in by
2 ~'s
< w
lenght
steps
, and
2t+I
suffice
, z 6 M
~0(z,~)
(which
. Since
that
for
basic
have
P(a,~,~) X
X
= a- ( 2 ~ ° s + I )
distinct
of
Remark:
of
conclude
in
< s
than
principle
at
it w i l l
r~
of m o r e
2t+1-tuples taken
with
: c > g(a)
A
there
s
(Pq0,z(~) I%0,z)
"pigeon-hole" ciple)
to
2t+1-tuples
truth-value
2 a's
c > d >_ r =
. Thus,
below
all
~ ( x , y I .... ,yt ) 6 ~o set
By
existence
with
bounded M =
~
definable will
subsets
remain
can
now
be
so
that:
established:
2.3
Theorem:
(i)
For
all
finite
If
M ~
PA
(eiJi
sets
, M ~
[a,b]
e. 2 l
<
(2)
for
all
ei+1
max(a,c)
of ~
I -formulas o
(c) n
, c > n
a < e 1• < b
< max(a,c)),
(I)
F
'
i+I
< max(a
¥x
, then
is
n 6 IN
there
is
a sequence
, satisfying
'
~0(x,y I . .• . . y t ) 6 M ~
there
c)
'
? , i°
<
ii
<'''<
it
< Jl
<" "'<
Jt <
< e l•o (%0(x,e i I , .... eit) (-~ ~ ( x , e j I ..... e j t ) ) •
163
(ii)
(Paris)
If
sequence
M b PA, M ~ (eili
6 IN)
[a,b]
c (c+1)c,
~
, e i £[a,b)
2 (I) e i
< el+ I, i 6 IN
(2) for
all
c > IN , then
there
is a
satisfying
~ ( x ' Y 1 ' ' ' ' ' Y t ) 6 TO'
i o < ii < ' ' ' <
it'io<
J 1 < ' ' ' < J t inl~:
MI= V x < eio(<0(x,eil,...,eit)~ ~x,ej1,...,ejt)). (3)
Moreover, we h a v e
Remark:
(ii)
proved
there.
need
any of
for I ~
(eili)
e
is s t a t e d Note
2.1
or,
sometimes,
Proof:
(i)
is i m m e d i a t e
(ii) the
Let
T(Y)
G~del
graph have
be
I b PA
[2], w i t h
up to 4.3
none
by
2.2,
modification,
of the r e s u l t s
models
M ~ Th(IN)
a formula of
of PA,
9)
for
all
but
but
not
to f o l l o w
will
only
IN
for
.
taking
into
describing
all the
it < Jl
component
of
i]
.
a slight
arbitrary
for
I = {d 6 MI B i 6 IN d < e
account
the
the p r i m i t i v e
final
remark
. By
<'''<
of
x
n E IN
Jt
in
(insert
(i) , u s i n g
recursive
set of
Z -formulas o
(~(x, (Z)il . . .(z)it~-~ . . . ~(x . . (Z)jl, . .
<'''<
the y ' t h
in
(I),(2),
2.2
numbers
M x <(Z)io io < ii
of
and
for
itself
in the p r o o f
M
that
- 2.3
as in
M ~ p(n),
~ , (X)y
the
lemma
(
z)jt ))
denoting
Zo-arithmetic
2.8
where
in (tr
[I]
~(x,y+1) ,
description
to lift
is the
o
,
of the
superscripts,
truth-predicate
we for
E -formulas) o p(x)
= Hz Vy
<x((¥(y)
The v a r i a b l e M
. Since
for
some
stence give
, ~
d 6 M ~ ~
the p r o o f
(i w i t h
might
M b PA
formula
be as in
z
~ tro(Y,Z))
p(d) of
(3)
even
^ (Z)y2 <(Z)y+1
be b o u n d e d
is not d e f i n a b l e M b p(d) , ((e)ili in
[I]
by
with
. Choose 6 ~ ) will
, which
some
do.
(z) Y < _b)
nonstandard
parameters
e 6 M
is not
^ _a ~
in
satisfying For
to be
element M
, so
the exi-
convenience, altered.
(3), d < e i , ~ a E o - f o r m u l a in the l a n g u a g e o subscript always denoting a natural number):
of
we
Let
of PA.
ei
, I
We h a v e
I ~e M, by
(I),
164
and I b
3 Xl V x 2 ... B x t
iff
3 i 1 > i 0 V i 2 > i 1
. ..
iff
~ ii > i o V i 2 > ii
"'" ~ i t > it-l:
iff
M ~
3 x]
< ei
~ ( d , x ] ,... ,x t)
+1 V x 2
~ i t > it_
< e i
o iff
I
b
3 x I < ei
for
any
effectively
+1 vx 2 < e i
e i , so t h a t (without The
induction known.
I b
without
instead
condition
(2).
The
a system
basic
axioms
guished main
(cf.
[I]
+t
~0(d,~)
formula
,
9(x)
containing
this
by
(2)
there
parameters
the
Strenghened
,
c a n be among
the
I
m
e
M
. Now
into
Finite
sequences
of
full is w e l l -
"smaller"
the h o m o g e n e i t y -
Ramsey_Theorem
Its P r o o f . P A I~ ~ in o u t l i n e the m o d e l s
plus
~ Con(T)
Second
subsequent
3.3
of the p r o o f
and
satisfy contain
as o c c u r the
and b y
P A ~ Con(T) Theorem
Instead,
(theorem
3.2
in
for
~ a
, and
PA
a distin-
technical
a lot of c a r r y i n g
theorem.
the
in 2.3, (ii) . The
Incompleteness
Thus
G~del's
as f o l l o w s :
of w h i c h
(for this
2 is n e e d e d ) ,
counting
runs
E -induction o
can be concluded.
as a c o r o l l a r y
and
by i n s e r t i n g
parameter,
and GSdel's
not
M
E -indiscernibles o
in p a r a g r a p h
in P A is r e q u i r e d , attack
of
is P A I- s
Con(PA) , PA ~ s
in
of the
set of
2.3, (ii),(3))
directly
~0(d,~)
i m p l i e s the same w i t h p a r a m e t e r s , a s
j u s t one
O,1,+,o,<
[1]
exposed
3 x t < e i
it is in
is i n t r o d u c e d
for
in
+t
o
since
[I] f o r
T
infinite
lemma
ground
of
proof
First
...
%' (x)
avoided
Applications
original
< ei o
arbitrary
parameters
Independence
and S o m e
3 xt
(9(x) ~ ~' (x)) . B y t h i s , i n d u c t i o n for I o r e d u c e s to Z o - i n d u c t i o n for I with parameters.
have
elements,
...~(d,~)
V x 2 < el2
V x < ei
is s a t i s f i e d ,
We might
3. T h e
and
< ell
M b 3 xl < eil v x2 < ei2"''
"'"
+2
a bounded
parameters)
latter
~ 9 x]
o
i° 6 ~
found
I
o
o
Thus,
+2
1 :
back~ Con(PA) saying
out proofs
we
[I]) w h i c h then we
can occurs shall
165
obtain
the
independence
3.3 r e l y i n g fied proof which
in
only for
[2]
application proofs the
PA
of
PA.
~ a
As
for
the
the
and
constants
ci,i
(I
the u s u a l
axioms
recursive
definitions
induction
axioms
for
for
all
could
By m e a n s
of 3.1
by
For
6 ~ : If
safely
~
f(a)
Jt ~
replace
condition
we
all
[a,b]
can
in
formal
, contrary
to
T
:
0,1,+,o,<
T includes
theory
and
the
(with p a r a m e t e r s )
in the
in the ~ , the
language
of P A
,
axioms:
~(x'cj1'''''c'3t))"
here
io < ii
state
finite
~
by
x
<'''<
b
a
, we have
= ~b([a,b]
~
in a h a n d y
S ~ T
(d+1) d
~
( ~ , e o , . . . , e k) b S
Since
avoiding
to an
(cf.
it'
the p r o o f
of
2.3,
io < Jl < ' ' ' <
Jt
by
(4).
3.2 L e m m a :
with
down
of them.
well-ordering
~ ( x , Y l , . . . , y t)
it < Jl < ' ' ' <
and the
in
[2]
axioms:
Eo-formulas
< Cio(~(x'ci1'''''cit)
the o n e
boiled
simpli-
+,',
all
Eo-formulas
io < ii < ' ' ' <
a,b
of
in
of
of PA,
(4
(3))
the
this
given
tr °
both
system
system
first-order
for
< ci+ I , i £ ~ ,
We
to g i v e
the
again
the p r o o f
that
is e a s i l y
entails
above-mentioned
for
notice
, thus
still
while
corollary,
to the one
and which
6 ~ . T contains
(3
Remark:
close
M b Th(~)
language
2 ci
(ii),
very
it m a y b e w o r t h
The
. Then we
second way
Definition:
Vx
M = ~
on 2.3,(ii]
we define
language
as an i m m e d i a t e
comes
3.1
(2
s
for
2.3,(ii)
one,
First
2.2
is b a s e d
within
first
on
of
there
, then
, ei
is are
recursive This
is n e e d e d
d £ ~
interpreting
a total
(a+1) a )
there
form what
such
of
that
2.2:
for
all
k 6 ~ , eo,- ..,e k 6 [a,~] ci
function
function
exceeds
f:~
~ ~
given
any p r o v a b l y
166
total
3.3
recursive
Theorem
recursive
Proof:
function
(Paris,
Harrinqton)
function,
Let
g:IN
then
~
IN
, with
that
is
not
provably
d
for
S as
S finite, By
3.2
there
Vn
are ~
a
the
interpreting the
By
compactness,
T'
= T U {c
Take I'
c M', --e
g(y)
M'
= x
3.2,
new
a
constant
IN
6 IN
is
(f(m) let
a provably
(m _> n ~
thus
f(m)
its
~ g(m)) . We
S c
T
(the
so
graph
is
to
show
of
3.1),
< g(a)
that < ci(
c,
> g(m)) .
want
T
, a 6 IN , b = f(a)
total
~ g(c)
e i the
definition
of
ci, the
~ x)
i < k}
i K k, graph
"g(y)
of
g
, ~ x"
.
system
of
~ PA.
is
Now
~
function,
S U {c ~ c o } U { V x
the
~ T')
Vm
> n
a ~ d
arithmetical
M'
I'
dicting
total.
~ c O } U { Vx
a model
IN
B m
PA) :
g:IN
a recursive
6 IN
in
in
If
e o , . . . , e k 6 [a,b]
(IN , a , e ° .... ,e k)
abbreviating
:
B n £
be
Z1-definable g
(provability
< ci(~
this, If w e
M'
then had
~ g(c)
It-formula
g(c)
~ x) ]i 6 IN}
the
c
I' ~ d
by
= g(c) ^ d
and
M' l ~
< c
I ' ~Z
d
M'
consistent.
2.3,(ii),(3) , then
for
1
is
we
some
As
we
determine
had
(contra-
i 6 IN might
an
, since
have
added
o Th(IN ) t o 3.4
T'
, we
Corollary
obtain
(Paris,
Harrington)
: PA
U Th
(IN)
~
~
,
nI noting the
that
recursive
total
proof
there
is
2.3(ii) I ~
just
of
3.4:
M ~
for
, a 6 I < b
had
(Xl-formulas
I ~e
contradicts
M
Let b
£ M
models . If
~
of
were end
the minimality
of
f
(a+1) a
M ~
b'
(a+1) a a
there
is
with
. Hence
remark
any
~
extensions) b
the
IN . S i n c e
[a,b]
6 I
. By exceeds
, a 6 M ~
arithmetic)
to
I ~ Th 1 ( I N ) .
up
that
true
there
going
Th(IN)
so
of
totality
~b[O,b]
too.
PA
which
a ~
the
function,
a smallest (only
states
function
recursive
Second
we
a
I =
to
1.4
provably
N ~
a
. Thus
an
I c
[a,b']
M ~
[a,b']
I ~
~ a
~
, by
e ~
M
,
a (a+1) a,
(a+1) a
, and
by
'
167
Remark:
In
finable iff
Paris
function
there
graph
[2]
of
Y:MxM ~ M
is a n
I c M ~e
Y
a
countable
has M ~ PA
Y(a,b)
, then
indicator
M ~ PA
the
in PA,
and
for a l l
, which
which
sentence
the We
can
just
countable
be proved
MI,M 2 ~ PA
one has
MI ~
M3 ~e M2
. This
of
PA
system
formula
~
initial
segment
account,
in
in
by
of
a turns and D.
3.5 C o r o l l a r y : segments
{X c ~
o u t to b e Jensen
There
a nice
asked
are models
(up to i s o m o r p h i s m )
Let
determined
by
language
Define
M 2'
M I' {c i li 6 ~ of P A
S S y ( M I) = SSy(M2) , h e n c e
if
this
MI
part
of t h e
Note
that
for
any in
[5]
3 b 6 M I a
in t h e d e f i n i t i o n
of an
at all.
are
countable
where
{n 6 ~ MI
the
of G a i f m a n ' s
MI,M 2
SSy(MI) , the
IM ~ ~(n) }
for
is i s o m o r p h i c ~e M2'
models
MI
some
to an
% ~ '
[3]. T a k i n g
this
into
example
for T h e o r e m
2 in
[3] w h i c h
MI,M 2 ~ PA
} , MI,
MI
that
M 3 = {a 6 M 2 1
I c M
is
"only-if"-part
2.3, (ii),
that
if
of 3.3
M2
such
, M I'
initial
~e M 2 and
which
another
to be t h e
~
the
> z
, cf.
of o n e
. Since
Y(x,y)
for:
T' b e as in the p r o o f
countable.
in a n y
satisfies
in M } , t h e n
S S y ( M I) = S S y ( M 2)
an i n d i c a t o r
is an i n d i c a t o r
JX =
M 2 . Furthermore,
if t h e
for unprovability.
shows
>
that
but
by a r e s u l t
[4] t h a t
M I , is
parameters
, then
Ehrenfeucht
the
of
with
MI,M 2 ~ PA
M I'
also
: Y(a,b)
. He shows
, then with
c a n be r e p l a c e d
showed
a,b 6 M
, Thz1 (M I) ~ Th(M2) , S S y ( M I) = S S y ( M 2 ) ,
standard
Proof:
stated
M ~ PA
M I ~ M2,
H. F r i e d m a n
all
requiring
this
P A to be a d e -
V z H y
(c+I) c} c
If
I c M --e
M ~
defines Vx
latter
exploited
easily
for
for
, a 6 I < b
reading:
indicator
that
= max{cl[a,b]~
indicator-property any
such
, I ~ PA
indicator-property.
function
an i n d i c a t o r
Z1-definition
true but unprovable of the
defines
are mutually that
C--e MI' 2
U T'
substructure of
ThzI(MI)
are m u t u a l l y
M
M I ~ a , M 2 ~ ~ s.
~ Th(~)
the r e d u c t s
initial
of
, M I'
M I' , M 2' = ThzI(M2)
initial
to and
segments,
168
and
by
M I' l= T'
As theorem
a second that
PA
i~
~
3.6
Lemma:
provable
The
PA
is n o t
All
sentences
provable,
Let
us
but
for
now
this for
these.
Cf.
one
be
so
Theorem that
a
even
V x3
y[x,y]
(~+I)[
remark the
to
v xV
Ryll-Nardzewski's First
we
n
~
(n+1) n
being
provided
give
to
, n 6
IN , a r e
one
given
in
Wilkie)
, even
axiomatizable.
Remark:
By
using
3.6
is
[2].
fact,
3.7
:
For
S U Th
all
(~)
restricted
the
"from
i~ a
provable,
do
far
is
Ramsey
outside"
on
.
theorem
by
finite
are
Infinite
will
which
by
Paris
and
than
the
simpler
a corollamyof
S ~
PA
there
. In p a r t i c u l a r ,
2.3,(i)
is PA
n 6 is
not
n
truth-predicates,
induction
of
a proof In
El-sentences,
(Z)y
following
~I
finitely
~
induction
here
the
true
.
version
But
proved,
with
1.4
using
topic.
, being
y H z[x,y]
a definable
this
once
S I~ s
n
~
superscripts,
(Paris,
PA with
reprove
axiomatizable.
=
n
n
to:
can
e-incompleteness:
the
needs
for
game-theoretic
3.7
use
fixed [6]
can
an
H y[O,y]
that
2 . 3 , (i) Wilkie
we
.
mention
Theorem
of
sentences
are
s .
finitely
form
PA
~
application,
the
in
Proof:
, M2 b
the to
result
can
E -formulas
easily
for
be
fixed
extended r 6
r
does
not
Proof:
imply
Let
a finite
meters)
S
set
induction
all
be £
axioms in
such
i_~f (M, (ei) i E ~
the
a
n
a finite of
Eo-fOrmulas
contained a way ) b
subset
in
of
PA.
By
the
~(x,Yl,...,y S
(which
may
be
proof
of
t) m a t c h e s
2.3,(ii) with
assumed
without
(where
TF
the para-
that
PA U {c~
< ci+1 Hi 6 ~ }
U TF
is
,(3)
the
.
169
last
group
of
then
the
initial
Set
M b
Th(~
according [a,b]
~
to
% ~
the
. By
Remark:
the
As
Paris
model
models than
~
PA
(the
T
of
Proof: are
for
is
a model
Let
S
(eili
6 ~
of
so
(M,eo,...,ek) ~
the
in
number
in
F )
) models
M
S
for
Theorem:
There
not
even
with
such
are
.
S
, so
that
, hence (~)
nl [a,b']
, but
not
s
, n
~
(n+1) n n
would
means there
that are
whereas
not
3.8
segments
in models
of
initial
will
segments
imply
modelling
that
PA
in
, other
3.9, from
PA
nonexistence
paragraph
M ~ PRA
defined
, so in
model by
of
, as
same
~
ce M
argument
as
recursive
that
arithmetic)
(M' (ei)i encoded
of
an
PRA of
. By
( ~ , e o , . . . , e k)
recursive
a sequence
a set
T
of
2
(primitive
, ei 6 M
subset
S
on
~
has
b T
by
an
initial
seg-
Eo-indiscernibles.
3.2
and
S
. Hence,
. Using for
6 ~
PRA
~
~
b
a
there
for tro(~,x)
2 . 3 , (ii) ,(I) ,(2)
~ ~(x) yields
) as d e s i r e d .
3.9
,
with
, a ~ ei < b
U Th
I b
) contained
that ~
6 ~
TF
3.7
nonstandard
a finite
6 ~
element
S
6 ~
a natural
ei,i
initial
6 ~ )
6 ~
any
(eili
formulas
.
element,
extract
(eili
the
all.
(eili
which
be
6 ~}U
[2],
nonstandard
. Thus
Eo-fOrmulas
b
application
M
eo,...,e k
of
at
of
M ~ PRA,
< Ci+lii
any
we
3.1),
be
are
to
by
smallest
there
It-induction
any
a sequence
n
in g e n e r a l
models,
is
the
,
} satisfies i b' 6 I with
above
there
ment
6 M
~
induction
third
For
determined
in
present
Lemma:
M
restricted
pointSout
, are
the
3.1
< e
of
of
nonstandard
element
d
# ~
For
b
minimality
prefix-restricted which
of
2 P A U {c i
) ~
in
2.3, (i)
existence
contradict
T
, a 6 M ~
2.3, (i),
{d 6 Mi 3 i 6 ~
since
3.8
of
segment
), M
(n+1)~
(M' (ei)i 6 ~ I =
axioms
no
recursive
recursive addition.
nonstandard
models
of
PRA
,
170
Proof:
Let
M b PRA,
(M'((e)i)i I 6 ~
6~
, the
) b
T
proof
of
(*)
H x I Vx2...
Set
A =
of
Using
Hence PRA be
we
an
2.3,(ii)
G~del
take
initial ,(3)
numbers
one
e 6 M
segment
shows
a 6 M
as
the
but
on
n)
of
realizes
containing
induction
get
taken
the
3.8,
H x n ~(Xl,...,x
tr °
p(z) by
. By
so
I
that
that
given
for
any
by
(e) i
open
~
,
in
the
PA
set
formula
# ~
. For
of
language I b
M
iff
9(y)
that
the
A =
formula
{n
6 EO
there
3 x1<(e) I Vx2<(e) with
is
parameter
a primitive
with
M b
e
so
IM b
B y({+..~=
x)
A =
p
(M,e)
available
. Here
, p(n)
.
N ~
.
reeursive
that
formula
n 6 a}
~
}(e)
a primitive
recursive
6 ~
M ~
2...
n
6 x
in can
the
p(n)-times n-th b
prime
6 M
number,
so
that
If
addition
follows:
For
6 x of
in
G~del's of
~
and
+
PA
M
, is
models
M
the
that
in
right of
whether
in
IM ~
recursive
n
on
the
[3].
side
M
its
of
Likewise
, we of
could PA
(*),
then
structure
and
~ 6 a
Theorem
there
is
a
6 b}
language
M ~
Incompleteness
proof
of
for
A c as
~
or
decide
compute
of
M ~
Th(I) the
compute
the
the
as
associated formula
recursiveness
~ 6 b
Th(I) , being
6 ~
uses
an
step
a nonrecursive does
nonexistence
in
which
{n
reduction
3.9
the
P_AA g i v e n
representability
Note
{n 6 ~
help
decide
representable
yielding
the
proposed
. But
by
a complete
extension
undecidable.
The
the
were
on
a nonrecursive
Thus
~ A =
sentence
with
First
Remark:
~
any
Zo-Sentence
a device
not
[3] is
JM p n
is
A hold,
even
6 a}
simpler:
for
which
Th(I) which
recursive
arithmetically
induction from
of
to is
however,
just
definable
some is
it
nonstandard
not
a 6 M
available
((M,e)) is o representable even models
and
. But
Thz
for
starts
of
the
from
thus this
in
PRA
.
decisive, in
M ~
basic
PRA
axioms
.
171
for
0,I,+,.,<,-
cf.
plus
open
induction,
as
Sheperdson's
model
shows,
[7].
4.
Generalizations
a
is
a
of
a
H2-statement
Hn+2-formulas
Applying
independent
independent
of
to of
PA
Higher PA
U Th
Prefixes
U Th
I (~)
, and
(~)
similar
we
to
look
for
to
E n-
a
~n+1 So w e
introduce
substructures
modelling
En-indiscernibles proofs
in
replaced M ~
PA
fixed in
by
tr n.
have
n 6 ~
general
rather
try
PA
instead
paragraph
we
generalizations
an
, instead of
shows,
by
infinite
sequence
to
supply
sequences
initial
substructures
way,
of
a result
an
corresponding
the
sequence
by
just
s
of
of
applying
Z -substructures. o will
Zn-indiscernibles
infinite
, whereas
of
of
Eo-indiscernibles
2 yield (This
an
not
as w e l l ,
that
in
if
any
Knight
([6])
Z -indiscernibles o be
closed
for we
so
under
the
tr 0
Zn-indiscernibles, J.F.
for
is
nonstandard
Z -indiscernibles).
of
do,
Using
do
any not
Thus
we
that
the
should
Z -Skolem-functions. n
4.1
Definition:
formulas ~b(V
with
c < a V d
Let two
n > 0
fixed
~ a
, tr
n
the
variables,
(3 e tr
E -truth-predicate n
gn:
(c,d,e)
~
~
~
g i v e n by (n)
[x,y]
~
(z+1) z
gn(a) be
tr
-
g b
the
with
3 e < b
n
relation
~
t h e n becomes
formula
saying:
gn(a)
(c,d,e)))
Hn-definable. ~
required
gn(min(X)) formula
a
n =
< Card(X)" ~
=
Let plus
Z
homogeneous
Ix,y]
E n
. The
(z+1) z
Z
"the
for
n
[x,y]
sets
X
(instead
of
z
(z+1) z)
can the
be
chosen
special
such
case
gn
that = id
in
the
. Set
(n) VxV
z 3y[x,y]
~
(z+1) z z
i
n
(n) is
then
a
Hn+2-sentence
, [x,y]
have
(z+1) z is z
a
H -formula. n
172
The paragraph
second
proof
3 generalizes
4.2 L e m m a : language
For
each
is an i n i t i a l
then
PA U Th
the
to
an
for
independence . First,
n 6 ~ :
of P A so t h a t
there
for
If
all
~
there
~(x,y,z)
a
given
is n o t h i n g
is a
M b PA:(if
substructure
(~)
of
new
in
En+1-formula
M k ~(a,b,c), I ~ PA,
I ~e M with
in
in the
c > ~ , then
I _ c M, n
a 6 I < b),
V x V z ~ y ~(x,y,z) .
~n+] Remark:
Such
indicator,
a
~
this
has
the m a i n
time for
property
of
~ -substructures n
a definition
which
of an
are m o d e l s
of
PA
.
(n) NOW we
show
that
[x,y]
~
(z+1)zz
indeed
defines
such
a
Z -indicator: n
(n) 4.3 L e m m a :
If
then
is an
there
M ~ PA,
a,b
I ~ PA,
£
M,
c 6 M \ ~
I --eC M,
I ~
, n > O, M ~
M
with
[a,b]
~
a 6 I
[a,b]
< b
~
c
(c+I) e,
.
n
(n) Proof:
[a,b]
sequence
c (c+I) c
~
Xo-indiscernibles
of
in 2.3, (ii).
Since
a homogeneous
set
[a,b] as
M
for
being
any
<eo,...,ei>
infinite
segment
in
of
6 ~ ),
partition g~(ei)
primitive
recursive
by
6 ~)
< b
, as
[[a,b]]
d
function,
condition
ei+1,
the
. By 2.3, (ii)
from
all
than
be
arises
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
for
I
a
described
, the
if w e w i s h .
Let
(eili
" So w e h a v e
sequence
is s m a l l e r
Zo-indiscernibility.
determined
this
on s o m e
< ei+1,
(c+I) c c
a ~ ei
2.3,(ii)
(sequence-number)
by
M
some
yields
dominates
i 6 ~
(eili
b y the p r o o ~
(~)* (c+1)Cc
gn
implies
all
ei
initial only
I ~
M n
remains
to b e p r o v e d .
We
show
I ~
M, m
~ n, b y
induction
on
m
.
~ 6 ~m+1
"
Zm By
I --eC M w e h a v e
already
I ~ Z M.
Let
m
< n,
I ~
O
~ =
H x ~ ( y I ..... Y t , X ) ,
I ~NmM .
So
let
Equivalently replacing
M N M ~
yj
by
<eit+1'
~ 6 Nm
Hx
. Clearly
~(al,...,at,x),
3 x~' ( < a l , . . . , a t > , x ) ,
M, m
I ~ ~(~)
~ M ~ ~(~)
a.3 6 I
, a.3 < e . l j ,
~' b e i n g
obtained
, by
eil<'''< from
ei t
$
in
(y) j. W e h a v e g~(eit+1)
< eit+2'
~'
< eit+1'
~'
£ H m ~ Xn
'
173
thus
M ~
3x
trn(r~'n , < a l , . . . , a t > , x )
hence
M ~ 4' (,b)
M ~ ~(a I , . . . , a t , b ) ,
Finally,
4.4 Lenuna: As
all
to its p r o o f ,
homogeneous difficult
X
4.5 T h e o r e m : of
PA U T h
.
taken
- 4.4 w e
all
(~)
b 6 I , for hypothesis
k a that
f(min(X))
4.2
For
remark
M ~
4.3 u s e f u l ,
~
c a n be
to a c h i e v e
Combining
4.2 a n d
n > 0
we only
sets
some
and b y i n d u c t i o n
to r e n d e r
For
for
entails
3x the
this
<e i + 2 t r n ( . . . ) , t same
b
holds
in
I .
we need
n in the p r o o f
from
of
an i n f i n i t e
< Card(X)
for
any
~
~ s
set,
the
so it is n o t
fixed
function
f:~.
obtain
n > O
an
Moreover,
if
is a t r u e M ~
PA,
Nn+2-sentence
M e
~
,
there
is
independent an
~n+1 I --eC M,
I
N PA,
so
that
I
~
M
and
I
~
~
~
n
n
Remark: case
i-6
For
the f i r s t
M ~ Th(~
Corollary:
For
of i n i t i a l
complete
extensions
stronger
all
Ehrenfeucht result
completions that
for
with
regard
of
n = O
of
4.5,4.3
is o n l y
needed
in the
special
)
infinity
Remark:
part
that PA 4.6
n 6 ~
any nonstandard
Zn-SUbStructures of
PA
and D.
satisfying
of
Th(~)
pairwise
has
an
different
.
Jensen
proved
a nonstandard satisfied
by
immediately
to the r e s u l t
model
model
in
[3] f o r
of P A h a s
n = 0 2
~o
its i n i t i a l
substructures.
generalizes
to m o d e l s
by Gaifman
quoted
in the
of
remark
the distinct Note PA
U Th
following
(~), 3.4.
174
References
[i]
J. Paris,
L. Harrington:
Ar i t h m e t i c ,
A Mathematical
in: H a n d b o o k
Incompleteness
of M a t h e m a t i c a l
Logic,
ed.
in Peano
Jon Barwise,
1133-1142. [2]
J. Paris:
Some
The Journal
[3]
Proc.
1971
of the
Lecture
H. Gaifman: Proc.
Lecture
J. F. Knight: The Journal
[7]
A Note
J.C.
of Number S6r.
Types
Astr.,
Bull.
vol.
43, No.
1976,
Summer
in Math.,
School vol.
vol.
40,
Model
XII,
of A r i t h m e t i c , London
255,
1975,
1970,
128-144.
Models
of A r i t h m e t i c ,
317-320.
Polonaise
No.
2,
Logic,
539-573.
for a Free V a r i a b l e
l'acad&mie vol.
in:
Logic,
in U n c o u n t a b l e vol.
arithmetics,
in M a t h e m a t i c a l
337,
in M a t h e m a t i c s ,
de
in e l e m e n t a r y
and Submodels
Logic,
725-731.
223-245.
in M a t h e m a t i c a l
Phys.,
4, 1978,
of Set Theories,
A Nonstandard
Theory,
Math.,
Models
Omitted
of S y m b o l i c
Sheperdson:
XCII,
on Models
Notes
for Peano A r i t h m e t i c ,
Some p r o b l e m s
Cambridge Notes,
of the C o n f e r e n c e
Sp r i n g e r [6]
Mathematical, Countable
Results
Logic,
D. Jensen:
H. Friedman:
Sp r i n g e r
[5]
of S y m b o l i c
A. E h r e n f e u c h t , Fundamenta
[4]
Independence
1964,
Fragment
des Sciences, 79-86.