k
~
..,
'
,1.1'
I
.
~
~~
\i..
j
I
( !C
~
I
.. h
..:
~":,·
~
"" l> )
..,.
'
y )'
~'
r·,..S
<
(
I
~-~~ ,~
~
.'
~
"~
t. -..
~
lo.:l;\, ~ .)N
BEING AND TIME
SUNY Series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy Dennis J. Schmidt, editor
~ --------
BEING AND TIME A Translation of Sein und Zeit
-
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
Translated by
Joan Stambaugh
STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK PRESS
\
l
-t
Originally published by Max Niemeyer Verlag, Tiibingen, © 1953. Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 1996 State University of New York
All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, address State University of New York Press, State University Plaza, Albany, N.Y., 12246 Production by Marilyn P. Semerad Marketing by Nancy Farrell Typesetting by Baker Typesetting Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Heidegger, Martin, 1889-1976. [Sein und Zeit. English] Being and time I Martin Heidegger ; translated by Joan Stambaugh. p. em. - (SUNY series in contemporary continental philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-7914-2677-7 (hardcover).- ISBN 0-7914-2678-5 (pbk.) 1. Ontology. 2. Space and time. I. Stambaugh, joan, 193211. Title. III. Series. B3279.H48S43 1996 111-dc20 96-476 CIP
Dedicated to EDMUND HUSSERL
in friendship and admiration Todtnauberg in Baden, Black Forest 8April1926
CONTENTS
Translator's Preface
xiii
Author's Preface to the Seventh German Edition
xvii
[Exergue]
xix
INTRODUCTION The Exposition of the Question of the Meaning of Being
I. The Necessity, Structure, and Priority of the Question of Being
1. The Necessity of an Explicit Retrieve of the Question of Being 2. The Formal Structure of the Question of Being 3. The Ontological Priority of the Question of Being 4. The Ontic Priority of the Question of Being
1 1 3 7 9
II. The Double Task in Working Out the Question of Being: The Method of the Investigation and Its Outline
5. The Ontological Analysis of Da-sein as the Exposure of the Horizon for an Interpretation of the Meaning of Being in General 6_ The Task of a Destructuring of the History of Ontology 7. The Phenomenological Method of the Investigation a. The Concept of Phenomenon b. The Concept of Logos c. The Preliminary Concept of Phenomenology 8. The Outline of the Treatise
13
13 17 23 25 28 30 35 vii
viii
Being and Time
PART ONE The Interpretation of Da-sein in Terms of Temporality and the Explication of Time as the Transcendental Horizon of the Question of Being DWISION ONE: The Preparatory Fundamental Analysis of Da-sein
37
I. The Exposition of the Task of a Preparatory Analysis of Da-sein 9. The Theme of the Analytic of Da-sein 10. How the Analytic of Da-sein is to be Distinguished from Anthropology, Psychology, and Biology 11. The Existential Analytic and the Interpretation of Primitive Da-sein: The Difficulties in Securing a "Natural Concept of the World"
39 39 42
47
II. Being-in-the-World in General as the Fundamental Constitution of Da-sein 12. A Preliminary Sketch of Being-in-the World in Terms of the Orientation toward Being-in as Such 13. The Exemplification of Being-in in a Founded Mode: Knowing the World
III. The Worldliness of the World 14. The Idea of the Worldliness of the World in General A. Analysis of Environmentality and Worldliness in General 15. The Being of Beings Encountered in the Surrounding World 16. The Worldly Character of the Surrounding World Making Itself Known in Innerworldly Beings 17. Reference and Signs 18. Relevance and Significance: The Worldliness of the World B. Contrast between Our Analysis of Worldliness and Descartes' Interpretation of the World 19. The Determination of the "World" as Res Extensa 20. The Fundaments of the Ontological Definition of the "World" 21. Hermeneutical Discussion of the Cartesian Ontology of the "Wodd" c. The Aroundness of the Surrounding World and the Spatiality of Da-sein
49 49 56 59 59 62 62 67 71 77 83 84 86 88 94
Contents
22. The Spatiality of Innerworldly Things at Hand 23. The Spatiality of Being-in-the-World 24. The Spatiality of Da-sein and Space
ix
94 97 102
IV. Being·in·the-World as Being-with and Being a Self: The "They" 25. The Approach to the Existential Question of the Who of Da-sein 26. The Mitda-sein of the Others and Everyday Being-with 27. Everyday Being One's Self and the They
V. Being-in as Such 28. The Task of a Thematic Analysis of Being-in A. The Existential Constitution of the There 29. Da-sein as Attunement 30. Fear as a Mode of Attunement 31. Da-sein as Understanding 32. Understanding and Interpretation 33. Statement as a Derivative Mode oflnterpretation 34. Da-sein and Discourse: Language B. The Everyday Being of the There and the Falling Prey of Da-sein 35. Idle Talk 36. Curiosity 37. Ambiguity 38. Falling Prey and Thrownness
VI. Care as the Being of Da-sein 39. The Question of the Primordial Totality of the Structural Whole of Da-sein 40. The Fundamental Attunement of Ang3t as an Eminent Disclosedness of Da-sein 41. The Being of Da-sein as Care 42. Confirmation of the Existential Interpretation ofDa-sein as Care in Terms of the Pre-ontological Self-interpretation of Da-sein 43. Da-sein, Worldliness, and Reality a. Reality as a Problem of Being and the Demonstrability of the "External World" b. Reality as an Ontological Problem c. Reality and Care
107 108 llO 118
123 123 126 126 131 134 139 144 150 156 157 159 162 164 169 169 172 178
183 186 187 193 195
x
Being and Time
44. Da-sein, Disclosedness, and Truth a. The Traditional Concept of Truth and Its Ontological Foundations b. The Primordial Phenomenon of Truth and the Derivative Character of the Traditional Concept of Truth c. The Kind of Being of Truth and the Presupposition of Truth DNISION TWO: Da-sein and Temporality
45. The Result of the Preparatory Fundamental Analysis of Da-sein and the Task of a Primordial, Existential Interpretation of This Being
196 198
201 208 213
213
I. The Possible Being-a·Whole of Da·sein and Being·toward-Death 46. The Seeming Impossibility of Ontologically Grasping and Determining Da-sein as a Whole 47. The Possibility of Experiencing the Death of Others and the Possibility of Grasping Da-sein as a Whole 48. What is Outstanding, End, and Totality 49. How the Existential Analysis of Death Differs from Other Possible Interpretations of This Phenomenon 50. A Preliminary Sketch of the Existential and Ontological Structure of Death 51. Being-toward-Death and the Everydayness of Da-sein 52. Everyday Being-toward-Death and the Complete Existential Concept of Death 53. Existential Project of an Authentic Being-toward-Death
219 219 221 224 229 231 233 236 240
II. The Attestation of Da-sein of an Authentic Potentiality-ofBeing, and Resoluteness 54. The Problem of the Attestation of an Authentic Existentiell Possibility 55. The Existential and Ontological Foundations of Conscience 56. The Character of Conscience as a Call 57. Conscience as the Call of Care 58. Understanding the Summons, and Guilt 59. The Existential Interpretation of Conscience and the Vulgar Interpretation of Conscience
247 247 250 251 253 258 266
Contents
60. The Existential Structure of the Authentic Potentiality-of-Being Attested in Conscience
xi
272
III. The Authentic Potentialityfor-Being-a-Whole of Da-sein, and Temporality as the Ontological Meaning of Care 61. Preliminary Sketch of the Methodical Step from Outlining the Authentic Being-a-Whole of Da-sein to the Phenomenal Exposition of Temporality 62. The Existentielly Authentic Potentiality-for-Being-a-Whole of Da-sein as Anticipatory Resoluteness 63. The Hermeneutical Situation at Which We Have Arrived for Interpreting the Meaning of Being of Care, and the Methodical Character of the Existential Analytic in General 64. Care and Selfhood 65. Temporality as the Ontological Meaning of Care 66. The Temporality of Da-sein and the Tasks Arising from It of a More Primordial Retrieve of the Existential Analysis
IV. Temporality and Everydayness 67. The Basic Content of the Existential Constitution of Da-sein, and the Preliminary Sketch of Its Temporal Interpretation 68. The Temporality of Disclosedness in General a. The Temporality of Understanding b. The Temporality of Attunement c. The Temporality of Falling Prey d. The Temporality of Discourse 69. The Temporality of Being-in-the-World and the Problem of the Transcendence of the World a. The Temporality of Circumspect Taking Care b. The Temporal Meaning of the Way in which Circumspect Taking Care Becomes Modified into the Theoretical Discovery of Things Objectively Present in the World c. The Temporal Problem of the Transcendence of the World 70. The Temporality of the Spatiality Characteristic of Da-sein 71. The Temporal Meaning of the Everydayness of Da-sein
279
279
282
287 292 297
304 307
307 308 309 312 317 320 321 322
326 333 335 338
Being and Time
xii
V. Temporality and Historicity
VI.
341
72. Existential and Ontological Exposition of the Problem of History 73. The Vulgar Understanding of History and the Occurrence of Da-sein 74. The Essential Constitution of Historicity 75. The Historicity of Da-sein and World History 76. The Existential Origin of Historiography from the Historicity of Da-sein 77. The Connection of the Foregoing Exposition of the Problem of Historicity with the Investigations ofDilthey and the Ideas of Count Yorck
363
Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin ofthe Vulgar Concept of Time
371
78. The Incompleteness of the Foregoing Temporal Analysis of Da-sein 79. The Temporality ofDa-sein and Taking Care ofTime 80. Time Taken Care of and Within-Timeness 81. Within-Timeness and the Genesis of the Vulgar Concept of Time 82. The Contrast of the Existential and Ontological Connection ofTemporality, Da-sein, and World Time with Hegel's Interpretation of the Relation between Time and Spirit a. Hegel's Concept of Time b. Hegel's Interpretation of the Connection between Time and Spirit 83. The Existential and Temporal Analytic of Da-sein and the Question of Fundamental Ontology as to the Meaning of Being in General
341 346 350 354 358
371 373 378 385
391 392 394
397
Notes
399
Lexicon
419
TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE
There are many reasons that Being and Time poses special problems for its translator and for the readers of an English language translation. Three aspects of the text are especially noteworthy and so need to be commented upon here. First, one needs to bear in mind that, in Being and Time, Heidegger has introduced a large number of German neologisms. Words such as Befindlichkeit, which are readily intelligible to a German reader since it has a clear relation to an everyday German phrase (wie befinden Sie sich?-"How are you doing?"), appear here as Heidegger's own coinage and so pose a challenge even to a German reader. Typically, Heidegger's neologisms have strong connections to everyday phrases or words, and so exhibit a curious mix of strangeness and familiarity. Second, Heidegger frequently employs quite common vocabulary in uncommon ways. Here the most visible example is his use of the word Dasein which, besides having a long history as a philosophic term (it is, for example, one of the categories in Hegel's Science of Logic), is a word that belongs to everyday conversation. One ofHeidegger's intentions in Being and Time is to re-appropriate that word and give it new meaning without completely repudiating its everyday sense. Again, a German reader might find a sort of alchemy of familiarity and strangeness in Heidegger's use of such words. Third, naturally one finds Heidegger using quite traditional philosophical vocabulary in Being and Time, but he goes to great lengths to move such words into new and rather untraditional senses. Words such as Wahrheit ("truth") and Sein ("being") are only the most obvious examples of the problem a translator and reader face. Such are some of the sorts of translation problems that are especially amplified by the nature of this text. There remain of course the
xiv
Being and Time
usual problems that belong to the project of translating German into English. But these problems, while demanding a certain vigilance on the part of both the translator and the reader, are not insurmountable. Some three decades ago Macquarrie and Robinson published a translation of Being and Time and in so doing were at the forefront of bringing Heidegger's work into English. That translation itself came to shape the way in which Heidegger's work was discussed in English. After three decades of translations of Heidegger's other works by a variety of some of the decisions that were made in that early translation of Being and Time might now need to be reconsidered. The present translation attempts to take into account the insights of the past thirty years of Heidegger scholarship in English. This translation was begun some time ago and has undergone changes over the years as colleagues have offered suggestions. Some individual translations will no doubt still provoke controversy and, because Heidegger's language is so rich and multivalent, would likely do so no matter how they were translated. But it is hoped that this translation will remedy some of the infelicities and errors of the previous translation, and open a productive debate about some of the more original and still puzzling language of this text. To that end, a few very brief remarks about some of the terminology decisions may be in order to help orient the reader to some of the choices made here and to some of the alternative translations that might well be borne in mind by the reader. However, in the end, the translation will need to justify itself in the reading. It was Heidegger's express wish that in future translations the word Da-sein should be hyphenated throughout Being and Time, a practice he himself instigated, for example, in chapter 5 of Division One. Thus the reader will be less prone to assume he or she understands it to refer to "existence" (which is the orthodox translation of Dasein) and with that translation surreptitiously bring along all sorts of psychological connotations. It was Heidegger's insight that human being is uncanny: we do not know who, or what, that is, although, or perhaps precisely because, we are it. As is the case with German nouns in general, the terms Da-sein and Ang.st, which remain untranslated, retain capitalization: no other English expressions are capitalized, including the term "being." Capitalizing "being," although it has the dubious merit of treating "being" as something unique, risks implying that it is some kind of Super Thing or transcendent being. But Heidegger's use of the word "being" in no sense refers the word to something like a being, especially not a transcendent Being. Heidegger does not want to substantivize this word, yet capitalizing the word in English does tend to imply just that. The later words for being, Ereignis, ("appropriation," "belonging-together") and Das Geviert
Translator's Preface
xv
("the Fowfold") express relations that ftrst constitute any possible relata or things, and thus confirm this nonsubstantializing intention. Another peculiarly problematic word is Veifallen which does not literally mean "falling," but speaks rather of a "falling prey" to something (the world). In other words, it is a kind of "motion" that is unable to go anywhere. While one might render the substantive (das Veifallen /die Verfallenheit) as "ensnarement," I choose to translate it as "entanglement" to avoid the connotation of a trap. The word Beftndlichkeit, which I have translated as "attunement," needs some qualification and special comment. Another legitimate translation for this word is "disposition" (here one could refer to the French translation which uses disposition). But despite quite compelling reasons to use "disposition," I decided that "attunement" was the better choice if only because it seems better able to avoid suggesting that there are psychological connotations carried in Heidegger's analysis of Beftndlichkeit. The translation of the word Bewandtnis here as "relevance" also needs a comment. While one might opt for a different translation, namely "situation," it seems that such a choice leaves the meaning of the word too broad and vague, and that it fails to capture the distinction Heidegger makes between Bewandtnis, which has primarily to do with things, and Situation, which is more applicable to people. The crucial trio of words Sorge, Besorgen, and Filrsorge was rendered as "care," "taking care," and "concern," respectively. A shift from the previous translation of Being and Time needs to be noted here. Macquarrie and Robinson had used "concern" as a translation for besorgen; however, I have chosen to use the word "concern" as a translation for Filrsorge, which involves human issues. I have translated besorgen as "taking care" {as opposed to the Macquarrie and Robinson translation of "solicitude") because it refers more to errands and matters that one takes care of or settles. Heidegger sometimes uses the word Andere with an article (die Andere), but for the most part the word appears without an article. I have followed him in this and so use "others" rather than "the others." The emphasis on the other(s), so strongly expressed in Sartre as a threat to subjectivity, is lacking in Heidegger. Mter all, we belong to others; we are others too. Vorlaufen. Anticipation is perhaps too weak. Macquarrie and Robinson's "running forward in thought" seemed a bit awkward. But it may be the better choice. Niihe was consistently rendered as "nearness," whereas in earlier versions I often used "closeness" as well. The word Wiederholung, which I have translated as "retrieval," could also be translated as "recapitulation" since that word is used in
xvi
Being and Time
music to refer to what Heidegger seems to intend by Wiederholung. In music (specifically in the sonata form) recapitulation refers to the return of the initial theme after the whole development section. Because of its new place in the piece, that same theme is now heard differently. One final word, which is a departure from the previous translation, needs to be noted. Augenblick, which I have translated as "moment" (as opposed to Macquarrie and Robinson's "moment of vision"), should help pick up the temporal connotations of the word and also shed some of the almost mystical sense of the previous translation. Here the reader might do well to associate the word with the English expression "in the twinkling of an eye" or the French coup d'oeil. The nonnumerical notes at the bottom of the pages are Heidegger's own notes made in the margin on the occasion of subsequent rereadings. I wish to thank Dennis Schmidt for his valuable and helpful suggestions. I also wish to thank the Alexander von Humboldt-Stiftung for its generous support enabling me to complete this translation.
AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO THE SEVENTH GERMAN EDITION
The text of Being and Time first appeared in the spring of 1927 in the Jahrbuchfilr Phiinomenologie und phiinomenologische Forschung, Vol. VIII, and it was published simultaneously as a separate volume. The present reprint, which is the seventh edition, is unchanged with respect to the text, but has been newly revised with regard to quotations and punctuation. The page numbers of this reprint agree with those of the earlier editions except for minor deviations. The designation "First Half," which previous editions bore, has been deleted. Mter a quarter century, the second half could no longer be added without the first being presented anew. Nonetheless, its path still remains a necessary one even today, if the question of being is to move our Da-sein. For the elucidation of that question the reader may refer to my Einfilhrung in die Metaphysik which is being published by the same press as this text. That work presents the text of a lecture course delivered in the summer semester of 1935.
... liij).ov rap a)~ V)lel~ )lEV -raii'ra (Ti 1rOTE {JovA.Ea9e a7J)lUlVElV otrchav ov ;oerr'Tia9e) trd).a[ YlYVaJUI("E'fE, r7JJe"i~ liE: trpo -roii JJEV qioJJe9a, viiv li • T,troprimJJev . ..
[Plato, Sophist 244a]
"V
.l'or manifestly you have long been aware of what you mean when you use the expression 'being.' We, however, who used to think we understood it, have now become perplexed. n Do we in our time have an answer to the question of what we really mean by the word 'being'? Not at all. So it is fitting that we should raise anew the question of the meaning of being. But are we nowadays even perplexed at our inability to understand the expression 'being'? Not at all. So first of all we must reawaken an understanding for the meaning of this question. Our aim in the following treatise is to work out the question of the meaning of being and to do so concretely. Our provisional aim is the interpretation of time as the possible horizon for any understanding whatsoever of being. But the reasons for making this our aim, the investigations which such a purpose requires, and the path to its achievement, call for some introductory remarks.
INTRODUCTION
The Exposition of the Question of the Meaning of Being
I The Necessity, Structure, and Priority of the Question of Being
1. The Necessity of an Explicit Retrieve of the Question of Being This question has today been forgotten-although our time considers itself progressive in again affirming "metaphysics." All the same we believe that we are spared the exertion of rekindling a gigantomachia peri t'es ousias ["a Battle of Giants concerning Being," Plato, Sophist 245e6-246el]. But the question touched upon here is hardly an arbitrary one. It sustained the avid research of Plato and Aristotle but from then on ceased to be heard as a thematic question of actual investigation. What these two thinkers achieved has been preserved in various distorted and "camouflaged" forms down to Hegel's Logic. And what then was wrested from phenomena by the highest exertion of thought, albeit in fragments and first beginnings, has long since been trivialized. Not only that. On the foundation of the Greek point of departure for the interpretation of being a dogma has taken shape which not only declares that the question of the meaning of being is superfluous but sanctions its neglect. It is said that "being" is the most universal and the emptiest concept. As such it resists every attempt at definition. Nor does this most universal and thus indefinable concept need any definition. Everybody uses it constantly and also already understands what is meant by it. Thus what troubled ancient philosophizing and kept it so by virtue of its obscurity has become obvious, clear as day, such that whoever persists in asking about it is accused of an error of method.
2
3
4
Being and Time
Int.
1
At the beginning of this inquiry the prejudices that constantly instill and repeatedly promote the idea that a questioning of being is not needed cannot be discussed in detail. They are rooted in ancient ontology itself. That ontology can in tum only be interpreted adequately under the guidance of the question of being which has been clarified and answered beforehand. One must proceed with regard to the soil from which the fundamental ontological concepts grew and with reference to the suitable demonstration of the categories and their completeness. We therefore wish to discuss these prejudices only to the extent that the necessity of a retrieve of the question of the meaning of being becomes evident. There are three such prejudices. 1. "Being"* is the most "universal" concept: to on esti katholou malista panton. 1 Illud quod primo cadit sub apprehensione est ens, cuiu.s intellectu.s includitur in omnibu.s, quaecumque quis apprehendit. "An understanding of being is always already contained in everything we apprehend in beings." 2 But the "universality" of "being" is not that of genu.s. "Being" does not delimit the highest region of beings so far as they are conceptually articulated according to genus and species: oute to on genos ["Being is not a genus"].~ The "universality" of being "surpasses" the universality of genus. According to the designation of medieval ontology, "being" is a transcendens. Aristotle himself understood the unity of this transcendental "universal," as opposed to the manifold of the highest generic concepts with material content, as the unity of analoffY. Despite his dependence upon Plato's ontological position, Aristotle placed the problem of being on a fundamentally new basis with this discovery. To be sure, he too did not clarify the obscurity of these categorial connections. Medieval ontology discussed this problem in many ways, above all in the Thomist and Scotist schools, without gaining fundamental clarity. And when Hegel fmally defines "being" as the "indeterminate immediate," and makes this definition the foundation of all the further categorial explications of his Logic, he remains within the perspective of ancient ontology-except that he does give up the problem, raised early on by Aristotle, of the unity of being in contrast to the manifold of "categories" with material content. If one says accordingly that "Being" is the most universal concept, that cannot mean that it is the clearest and that it needs no further discussion. The concept of "being" is rather the most obscure of all. 2. The concept of "being" is indefinable. This conclusion was drawn from its highest universality. 4 And correctly so-if definitio fit per genu.s proximum et differentiam specificam [if "definition is achieved through the proximate genus and the specific difference"]. Indeed, "being" cannot be understood as a being. Enti non additur aliqua natura: "Being" *the being [das Seiende], beingness
Int.
Being and Time
I
3
cannot be defined by attributing beings to it. Being cannot be derived from higher concepts by way of definition and cannot be represented by lower ones. But does it follow from this that "being" can no longer constitute a problem? Not at all. We can conclude only that "being" is not something like a being.* Thus the manner of definition of beings which has its justification within limits-the "definition" of traditional logic which is itself rooted in ancient ontology-cannot be applied to being. The indefinability of being does not dispense with the question of its meaning but forces it upon us. 3. "Being" is the self-evident concept. "Being" is used in all knowing and predicating, in every relation to beings and in every relation to oneself, and the expression is understandable "without further ado." Everybody understands, "The sky is blue," "I am happy," and similar statements. But this average comprehensibility only demonstrates the incomprehensibility. It shows that an enigma lies a priori in every relation and being toward beings as beings. The fact that we live already in an understanding of being and that the meaning of being is at the same time shrouded in darkness proves the fundamental necessity of repeating the question of the meaning of "being." If what is "self-evident" and this alone-"the covert judgments of common reason" (Kant)-is to become and remain the explicit theme of our analysis (as "the business of philosophers"), then the appeal to selfevidence in the realm of basic philosophical concepts, and indeed with regard to the concept "being," is a dubious procedure. But consideration of the prejudices has made it clear at the same time that not only is the answer to the question of being lacking but even the question itself is obscure and without direction. Thus to retrieve the question of being means first of all to work out adequately the formulation of the question. 2. The Formal Structure of the Question of Being
The question of the meaning of being must be formulated. If it is a-or even the-fundamental question, such questioning needs the suitable transparency. Thus we must briefly discuss what belongs to a question in general in order to be able to make clear that the question of being is an eminent one. Every questioning is a seeking. Every seeking takes its direction beforehand from what is sought. Questioning is a knowing search for beings in their thatness and whatness. The knowing search can become an *no! rather: no decision about being [Seyn] can be made with the help of such conceptuality
5
4
6
Being and Time
Int.
I
"investigation," as the revealing determination of what the question aims at. As questioning about ... questioning has what it asks about. All asking about ... is in some way an inquiring of .... Besides what is asked, what is interrogated also belongs to questioning. What is questioned is to be defmed and conceptualized in the investigating, that is, the specifically theoretical, question. As what is really intended, what is to be ascertained lies in what is questioned; here questioning arrives at its goal. As an attitude adopted by a being, the questioner, questioning has its own character of being. Questioning can come about as ·~ust asking around" or as an explicitly formulated question. What is peculiar to the latter is the fact that questioning first becomes lucid in advance with regard to all the abovenamed constitutive characteristics of the question. The question to be formulated is about the meaning of being. Thus we are confronted with the necessity of explicating the question of being with regard to the structural moments cited. As a seeking, questioning needs prior guidance from what it seeks. The meaning of being must therefore already be available to us in a certain way. We intimated that we are always already involved in an understanding of being. From this grows the explicit question of the meaning of being and the tendency toward its concept. We do not know what "being" means. But already when we ask, "What is being'?" we stand in an understanding of the "is" without being able to determine conceptually what the "is" means. We do not even know the horizon upon which we are supposed to grasp and pin down the meaning. This average and vague understanding of being is a fact. No matter how much this understanding of being wavers and fades and borders on mere verbal knowledge, this indefiniteness of the understanding of being that is always already available is itself a positive phenomenon which needs elucidation. However, an investigation of the meaning of being will not wish to provide this at the outset. The interpretation of the average understanding of being attains its necessary guideline only with the developed concept of being. From the clarity of that concept and the appropriate manner of its explicit understanding we shall be able to discern what the obscure or not yet elucidated understanding of being means, what kinds of obfuscation or hindrance of an explicit elucidation of the meaning of being are possible and necessary. Furthermore, the average, vague understanding of being can be permeated by traditional theories and opinions about being in such a way that these theories, as the sources of the prevailing understanding, remain hidden. What is sought in the question of being is not completely unfamiliar, although it is at first totally ungraspable. What is asked about in the question to be elaborated is being, that which determines beings as beings, that in terms of which beings have
Int.
1
Being and Time
5
always been understood no matter how they are discussed. The being of beings "is" itself not a being. The first philosophical step in understanding the problem of being consists in avoiding the mython tina diegeisthai, 5 in not "telling a story," that is, not determining beings as beings by tracing them back in their origins to another being-as if being had the character of a possible being. As what is asked about, being thus requires its own kind of demonstration which is essentially different from the discovery of beings. Hence what is to be ascertained, the meaning of being, will require its own conceptualization, which again is essentially distinct from the concepts in which beings receive their determination of meaning. Insofar as being constitutes what is asked about, and insofar as being means the being of beings, beings themselves tum out to be what is interrogated in the question of being. Beings are, so to speak, interrogated with regard to their being. But if they are to exhibit the characteristics of their being without falsification they must for their part have become accessible in advance as they are in themselves. The question of being demands that the right access to beings be gained and secured in advance with regard to what it interrogates. But we call many things "existent" [seier.d], and in different senses. Everything we talk about, mean, and are related to is in being in one way or another. What and how we ourselves are is also in being. Being is found in thatness and whatness, reality, the objective presence of things [Vorhandenheit], subsistence, validity, existence [Da-sein],* and in the "there is" [es gibt]. In which being is the meaning of being to be found; t from which being is the disclosure of being to get its start? Is the starting point arbitrary, or does a certain being have priority in the elaboration of the question of being? Which is this exempl;uf being and in what sense does it have priority? If the question of being is to be explicitly formulated and brought to complete clarity concerning itself, then the elaboration of this question requires, in accord with what has been elucidated up to now, explication of the ways of regarding being and of understanding and conceptually grasping its meaning, preparation of the possibility of the right choice of the exemplary being, and elaboration of the genuine mode of access to this being. Regarding, understanding and grasping, choosing, and gaining access to, are constitutive attitudes of inquiry and are thus *neither the usual concept nor any other t two different questions are aligned here; misleading, above all in relation to the
role of Da-sein. t Misleading. Da-sein is exemplary because it is the co-player (das Bei-spiel) that in its essence as Da-sein (perduring the truth of being) plays to and with beingbrings it into the play of resonance.
7
6
8
Being and Time
Int.
I
themselves modes of being of a particular being, of the being we inquirers ourselves in each case are. Thus to work out the question of being means to make a being-he who questions-transparent in its being. Asking this question, as a mode of being of a being, is itself essentially determined by what is asked about in it-being.* This being which we ourselves in each case are and which includes inquiry among the possibilities of its being we formulate terminologically as Da-sein. The explicit and lucid formulation of the question of the meaning of being requires a prior suitable explication of a being (Da-sein) with regard to its being.t But does not such an enterprise fall into an obvious circle? To have to determine beings in their being beforehand and then on this foundation first pose the question of being-what else is that but going around in circles? In working out the question do we not presuppose something that only the answer can provide? Formal objections such as the argument of "circular reasoning," an argument that is always easily raised in the area of investigation of principles, are always sterile when one is weighing concrete ways of investigating. They do not offer anything to the understanding of the issue and they hinder penetration into the field of investigation. But in fact there is no circle at all in the formulation of our question. Beings can be determined in their being without the explicit concept of the meaning of being having to be already available. If this were not so there could not have been as yet any ontological knowledge. And probably no one would deny the factual existence of such knowledge. It is true that "being" is "presupposed" in all previous ontology, but not as an available concept-not as the sort of thing we are seeking. "Presupposing" being has the character of taking a preliminary look at being in such a way that on the basis of this look beings that are already given are tentatively articulated in their being. This guiding look at being grows out of the average understanding of being in which we are always already involved and which ultimatelyt belongs to the essential constitution of Da-sein itself. Such "presupposing" has nothing to do with positing a principle from which a series of propositions is deduced. A "circle in reasoning" cannot possibly lie in the formulation of the question of the meaning of being, because in answering this question it is not a matter of grounding by deduction but rather of laying bare and exhibiting the ground. "Circular reasoning" does not occur in the question of the meaning of being. Rather, there is a notable "relatedness backward or forward" of what is asked about (being) to asking as a mode of being of a
* Da-sein: being held out into the nothingness of being, held as relation. t t
But the meaning of being is not drawn from this being. i.e., from the beginning
Int.
I
Being and Time
7
being. The way what is questioned essentially engages our questioning belongs to the innermost meaning of the question of being. But this only means that the being that has the character of Da-sein has a relation to the question of being itself, perhaps even a distinctive one. But have we not thereby demonstrated that a particular being has a priority with respect to being and that the exemplary being that is to function as what is primarily interrogated is pregiven?* In what we have discussed up to now neither has the priority of Da-sein been demonstrated nor has anything been decided about its possible or even necessary function as the primary being to be interrogated. But certainly something like a priority of Da-sein has announced itself.
3. The Ontological Priority of the QJJ.estion of Being The characterization of the question of being, under the guideline of the formal structure of the question as such, has made it clear that this question is a unique one, such that its elaboration and even its solution require a series of fundamental reflections. However, what is distinctive about the question of being will fully come to light only when that question is sufficiently delineated with regard to its function, intention, and motives. Up to now the necessity of a retrieve of the question was motivated partly by its venerable origin but above all by the lack of a definite answer, even by the lack of any adequate formulation. But one can demand to know what purpose this question should serve. Does it remain solely, or is it at all, only a matter of free-floating speculation about the most general generalities-or is it the most basic and at the same time most concrete question, Being is always the being of a being. The totality of beings can, with respect to its various domains, become the field where particular areas of knowledge are exposed and delimited. These areas-for example, history, nature, space, life, human being, language, and so on-can in their tum become thematized as objects of scientific investigations. Scientific research demarcates and first establishes these areas of knowledge in a rough and ready fashion. The elaboration of the area in its fundamental structures is in a way already accomplished by prescientific experience and interpretation of the domain of being to which the area of knowledge is itself confined. The resulting "fundamental concepts" comprise the guidelines for the first concrete disclc:>sure of the area. *Again as above, an essential simplification and yet correctly thought. Da-sein is not an instance of being for the representational abstraction of being; rather, it is the site of the understanding of being.
9
8
10
Being and Time
Int.
1
Whether or not the importance of the research always lies in such establishment of concepts, its true progress comes about not so much in collecting results and storing them in "handbooks" as in being forced to ask questions about the basic constitution of each area, these questions being chiefly a reaction to increasing knowledge in each area. The real "movement" of the sciences takes place in the revision of these basic concepts, a revision which is more or less radical and lucid with regard to itsdf. A science's level of development is determined by the extent to which it is capable of a crisis in its basic concepts. In these immanent crises of the sciences the relation of positive questioning to the matter in question becomes unstable. Today tendencies to place research on new foundations have cropped up on all sides in the various disciplines. The discipline which is seemingly the strictest and most securely structured, mathematics, has experienced a "crisis in its foundations." The controversy between formalism and intuitionism centers on obtaining and securing primary access to what should be the proper object of this science. Relativity theory in physics grew out of the tendency to expose nature's own coherence as it is "in itself." As a theory of the conditions of access to nature itself it attempts to preserve the immutability of the laws of motion by defining all relativities; it is thus confronted by the question of the structure of its pre-given area of knowledge, that is, by the problem of matter. In biology the tendency has awakened to get behind the definitions mechanism and vitalism have given to "organism" and "life" and to define anew the kind of being of living beings as such. In the historical and humanistic disciplines the drive toward historical actuality itself has been strengthened by the transmission and portrayal of tradition: the history of literature is to become the history of critical problems. Theology is searching for a more original interpretation of human being's being toward God, prescribed by the meaning of faith itsdf and remaining within it. Theology is slowly beginning to understand again Luther's insight that its system of dogma rests on a "foundation" that does not stem from a questioning in which faith is primary and whose conceptual apparatus is not only insufficient for the range of problems in theology but rather covers them up and distorts them. Fundamental concepts are determinations in which the area of knowledge underlying all the thematic objects of a science attain an understanding that precedes and guides all positive investigation. Accordingly these concepts first receive their genuine evidence and "grounding" only in a correspondingly preliminary research into the area of knowledge itself. But since each of these areas arises from the domain of beings themsdves, this preliminary research that creates the fundamental concepts amounts to nothing dse than interpreting these beings in terms of
Int. 1
Being and Time
9
the basic constitution of their being. This kind of investigation must precede the positive sciences-and it can do so. The work of Plato and Aristotle is proof of this. Laying the foundations of the sciences in this way is different in principle from "logic" limping along behind, investigating here and there the status of a science in terms of its "method." Such laying of foundations is productive logic in the sense that it leaps ahead, so to speak, into a particular realm of being, discloses it for the first time in its constitutive being, and makes the acquired structures available to the positive sciences as lucid directives for inquiry. Thus, for example, what is philosophically primary is not a theory of concept-formation in historiology, nor the theory of historical knowledge, nor even the theory of history as the object of historiology; what is primary is rather the interpretation of genuinely historical beings with regard to their historicality. Similarly, the positive result of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason consists in its approach to working out what belongs to any nature whatsoever, and not in a "theory" of knowledge. His transcendental logic is an a priori logic of the realm of being called nature. But such inquiry-ontology taken in its broadest sense without reference to specific ontological directions and tendencies-itself still needs a guideline. It is true that ontological inquiry is more original than the ontic inquiry of the positive sciences. But it remains naive and opaque if its investigations into the being of beings leave the meaning of being in general undiscussed. And precisely the ontological task of a genealogy of the different possible ways of being (a genealogy which is not to be construed deductively) requires a preliminary understanding of "what we really mean by this expression 'being.'" The question of being thus aims at an a priori condition of the possibility not only of the sciences which investigate beings of such and such a type-and are thereby already involved in an understanding of being; but it aims also at the condition of the possibility of the ontologies which precede the ontic sciences and found them. AU ontology, no matter how rich and tightly knit a system of categories it has at its disposa~ remains fundamentally blind and peruens its innermost intent if it has not previously clarifaed the mean· ing of being sufficiently and grasped this clarification as its fundamental task. Ontological research itself, correctly understood, gives the question of being its ontological priority over and above merely resuming an honored tradition and making progress on a problem until now opaque. But this scholarly, scientific priority is not the only one.
4. The Ontic Priority of the QJJ,estion of Being Science in general can be defined as the totality of fundamentally coherent true propositions. This definition is not complete, nor does it get at
11
10
12
Being and Time
Int.
1
the meaning of science. As ways in which human beings behave, sciences have this being's (the human being's) kind of being. We are defining this being terminologically as Da-sein. Scientific research is neither the sole nor the most immediate kind of being of this being that is possible. Moreover, Da-sein itself is distinctly different from other beings. We must make this distinct difference visible in a preliminary way. Here the discussion must anticipate subsequent analyses which only later will become truly demonstrative. Da-sein is a being that does not simply occur among other beings. Rather it is ontically distinguished by the fact that in its being this being is concerned about its very being. Thus it is constitutive of the being of Da-sein to have, in its very being, a relation of being to this being. And this in tum means that Da-sein understands itself in its being in some way and with some explicitness. It is proper to this being that it be disclosed to itself with and through its being. Understanding of being is itself a determination of being of Da-sein. * The ontic distinction of Da-sein lies in the fact that it is ontological. To be ontological does not yet mean to develop ontology. Thus if we reserve the term ontology for the explicit, theoretical question of the meaning of beings, the intended ontological character of Da-sein is to be designated as pre-ontological. That does not signify being simply on tical, but rather being in the manner of an understanding of being. We shall call thet very being to whicht Da-sein can relate in one way or another, and somehow always does relate, existence [Existenz]. And because the essential definition of this being cannot be accomplished by ascribing to it a "what" that specifies its material content, because its essence lies rather in the fact that it in each instance has to be its being as its own, the term Dasein, as a pure expression of being, has been chosen to designate this being. Da-sein always understands itself in terms of its existence, in terms of its possibility to be itself or not to be itself. Da-sein has either chosen these possibilities itself, stumbled upon them, or in each instance already grown up in them. Existence is decided only by each Da-sein itself in the manner of seizing upon or neglecting such possibilities. We come to terms with the question of existence always only through existence itself. We shall call this kind of understanding of itself existentiell understanding. The question of existence is an antic "affair" of Da-sein. For this the theoretical transparency of the ontological structure of existence is not
* But in this case being not only as the being of human being (Existenz). That becomes clear from the following. Being-in-the-world includes in itself the relation of existence to being in the whole: the understanding of being. tthat tas its own
Int.
I
Being and Time
11
necessary. The question of structure aims at the analysis of what constitutes existence.* We shall call the coherence of these structures existentiality. Its analysis does not have the character of an existentiell understanding but rather an existential one. The task of an existential analysis of Da-sein is prescribed with regard to its possibility and necessity in the on tic constitution of Da-sein. But since existence defines Da-sein, the ontological analysis of this being always requires a previous glimpse of existentiality. However, we understand existentiality as the constitution of being of the being that exists. But the idea of being already lies in the idea of such a constitution of being. And thus the possibility of carrying out the analysis of Da-sein depends upon the prior elaboration of the question of the meaning of being in general. Sciences and disciplines are ways of being of Da-sein in which Dasein also relates to beings that it need not itself be. But being in a world belongs essentially to Da-sein. Thus the understanding of being that belongs to Da-sein just as originally implies the understanding of something like "world" and the understanding of the being of beings accessible within the world. Ontologies which have beings unlike Da-sein as their theme are accordingly founded and motivated in the antic structure of Da-sein itself. This structure includes in itself the determination of a pre-ontological understanding of being. Thus fundamental ontology, from which alone all other ontologies can originate, must be sought in the existential analysis of Da-sein. Da-sein accordingly takes priority in several ways over all other beings. The first priority is an ontic one: this being is defined in its being by existence. The second priority is an ontological one: on the basis of its determination as existence Da-sein is in itself "ontological." But just as originally Da-sein possesses-in a manner constitutive of its understanding of existence-an understanding of the being of all beings unlike itself. Da-sein therefore has its third priority as the antic-ontological condition of the possibility of all ontologies. Da-sein has proven to be what, before all other beings, is ontologically the primary being to be interrogated. However, the roots of the existential analysis, for their part, are ultimately existentiell-they are ontic. Only when philosophical research and inquiry themselves are grasped in an existentiell way-as a possibility of being of each existing Da-sein-does it become possible at all to disclose the existentiality of existence and therewith to get hold of a sufficiently grounded set of ontological problems. But with this the antic priority of the question of being has also become clear. *Thus not a philosophy of existence [Existenzphilosophie].
13
14
12
15
Being and Time
Int. 1
The ontic-ontological priority of Da-sein was already seen early on, without Da-sein itself being grasped in its genuine ontological structure or even becoming a problem with such an aim. Aristotle says, he psyche ta onta pas estin.6 The soul (of the human being) is in a certain way beings. The "soul" which constitutes the being of human being discovers in its ways to be-aisthesis and noesis-all beings with regard to their thatness and whatness, that is to say, always also in their being. Thomas Aquinas discussed this statement-which refers back to Parmenides' ontological thesis-in a manner characteristic of him. Thomas is engaged in the task of deriving the "transcendentals," the characteristics of being that lie beyond every possible generic determination of a being in its material content, every modus specialis entis, and that are necessary attributes of every "something," whatever it might be. For him the verum too is to be demonstrated as being such a transcendens. This is to be accomplished by appealing to a being which in conformity with its kind of being is suited to "come together" with any being whatsoever. This distinctive being, the ens quod natum est convenire cum omni ente ["the being whose nature it is to meet with all other beings"], is the soul (anima). 7 The priority of Da-sein over and above all other beings which emerges here without being ontologically clarified obviously has nothing in common with a vapid subjectivizing of the totality of beings. The demonstration of the ontic-ontological distinctiveness of the question of being is grounded in the preliminary indication of the onticontological priority of Da-sein. But the analysis of the structure of the question of being as such (section 2) came up against the distinctive function of this being within the formulation of that very question. Dasein revealed itself to be that being which must first be elaborated in a sufficiently ontological manner if the inquiry is to become a lucid one. But now it has become evident that the ontological analysis of Da-sein in general constitutes fundamental ontology, that Da-sein consequently functions as the being that is to be interrogated fundamentally in advance with respect to its being. If the interpretation of the meaning of being is to become a task, Da-sein is not only the primary being to be interrogated; in addition to this it is the being that always already in its being is related to what is sought in this question. But then the question of being is nothing else than the radicalization of an essential tendency of being that belongs to Da-sein itself, namely, of the pre-ontological understanding of being.
II The Double Task in Working Out the Question of Being: The Method of the Investigation and Its Outline
5. The Ontological Analysis of Da-sein as the Exposure of the Horizon for an Interpretation of the Meaning of Being in General In designating the tasks involved in "formulating" the question of being,
we showed that not only must we pinpoint the particular being that is to function as the primary being to be interrogated but also that an explicit appropriation and securing of correct access to this being is required. We discussed which being it is that takes over the major role within the question of being. But how should this being, Da-sein, become accessible and, so to speak, be envisaged in a perceptive interpretation? The on tic-ontological priority that has been demonstrated for Dasein could lead to the mistaken opinion that this being would have to be what is primarily given also ontically-ontologically, not only in the sense that such a being could be grasped "immediately" but also that the prior giveness of its manner of being would be just as "immediate." True, Da-sein is ontically not only what is near or even nearest-we ourselves are it, each of us. Nevertheless, or precisely for this reason, it is ontologically what is farthest removed. True, it belongs to its most proper being to have an understanding of this being and to sustain a certain
13
14
16
Being and Time
Int.
II
interpretation of it. But this does not at all mean that the most readily available pre-ontological interpretation of its own being could be adopted as an adequate guideline, as though this understanding of being had to arise from a thematically ontological reflection on the most proper constitution of its being. Rather, in accordance with the kind of being belonging to it, Da-sein tends to understand its own being in terms of that being to which it is essentially, continually, and most closely related-the "world."* In Da-sein itself and therewith in its own understanding of being, as we shall show, the way the world is understood is ontologically reflected back upon the interpretation of Da-sein. The ontic-ontological priority of Da-sein is therefore the reason why the specific constitution of the being of Da-sein-understood in the sense of the "categorial" structure that belongs to it-remains hidden from it. Da-sein is ontically "nearest" to itself, ontologically farthest away; but pre-ontologically certainly not foreign to itself. We have merely precursorily indicated that an interpretation of this being is confronted with peculiar difficulties rooted in the mode of being of the thematic object and the way it is thematized. They do not result from some shortcoming of our powers of knowledge or lack of a suitable way of conceiving-a lack seemingly easy to remedy. Not only does an understanding of being belong to Da-sein, but this understanding also develops or decays according to the actual manner of being of Da-sein at any given time; for this reason it has a wealth of interpretations at its disposal. Philosophical psychology, anthropology, ethics, "politics," poetry, biography, and historiography pursue in different ways and to varying extents the behavior, faculties, powers, possibilities, and destinies of Da-sein. But the question remains whether these interpretations were carried out in as original an existential manner as their existentiell originality perhaps merited. The two do not necessarily go together, but they also do not exclude one another. Existentiell interpretation can require existential analysis, provided philosophical knowledge is understood in its possibility and necessity. Only when the fundamental structures of Da-sein are adequately worked out with explicit orientation toward the problem of being will the previous results of the interpretation of Da-sein receive their existential justification. Hence the first concern in the question of being must be an analysis of Da-sein. But then the problem of gaining and securing the kind of access that leads to Da-sein truly becomes crucial. Expressed negatively, no arbitrary idea of being and reality, no matter how "self-evident" it is, may be brought to bear on this being in a dogmatically constructed *i.e., here in terms of what is objectively present.
Int.
11
Being and Time
15
way; no "categories" prescribed by such ideas may be forced upon Dasein without ontological deliberation. The manner of access and interpretation must instead be chosen in such a way that this being can show itself to itself on its own terms. And furthermore, this manner should show that being as it is initially and for the most part-in its average everydayness. Not arbitrary and accidental structures but essential ones are to be demonstrated in this everydayness, structures that remain determinative in every mode of being of factual Da-sein. By looking at the fundamental constitution of the everydayness of Da-sein we shall bring out in a preparatory way the being of this being. The analytic of Da-sein thus understood is wholly oriented toward the guiding task of working out the question of being. Its limits are thereby determined. It cannot hope to provide a complete ontology of Da-sein, which of course must be supplied if something like a "philosophical" anthropology is to rest on a philosophically adequate basis. With a view to a possible anthropology or its ontological foundation, the following interpretation will provide only a few "parts," although not inessential ones. However, the analysis of Da-sein is not only incomplete but at first also preliminary. It only brings out the being of this being without interpreting its meaning. Its aim is rather to expose the horizon for the most primordial interpretation of being. Once we have reached that horizon the preparatory analytic of Da-sein requires repetition on a higher, genuinely ontological basis. The meaning of the being of that being we call Da-sein proves to be temporality [Zeitlichkeit]. In order to demonstrate this we must repeat our interpretation of those structures of Da-sein that shall have been indicated in a preliminary way-this time as modes of temporality. While it is true that with this interpretation of Da-sein as temporality the answer to the guiding question about the meaning of being in general is not already given,* the soil from which we may reap it will nevertheless be prepared. We intimated that a pre-ontological being belongs to Da-sein as its antic constitution. Da-sein is in such a way that, by being, it understands something like being. Remembering this connection, we must show that time is that from which Da-sein tacitly understands and interprets something like being at all. Time must be brought to light and genuinely grasped as the horizon of every understanding and interpretation of being. For this to become clear we need an original explication of time as the horizon of the understanding of being, in terms of temporality as the being of Da-sein which understands being. This task as a whole requires that the concept of time thus gained be distinguished from the common under-
* Katholou, kath' auto.
17
16
18
19
Being and Time
Int.
II
standing of it. The latter has become explicit in an interpretation of time which reflects the traditional concept that has persisted since Aristotle and beyond Bergson. We must thereby make clear that and in what way this concept of time and the common understanding of time in general originate from temporality. In this way the common concept of time receives again its rightful autonomy-contrary to Bergson's thesis that time understood in the common way is really space. "Time" has long served as the ontological-or rather antic-criterion for naively distinguishing the different regions of beings. "Temporal" beings (natural processes and historical events) are separated from "atemporal" beings (spatial and numerical relationships). We are accustomed to distinguishing the "timeless" meaning of propositions from the "temporal" course of propositional statements. Further, a "gap" between "temporal" being and "supratemporal" eternal being is found, and the attempt made to bridge the gap. "Temporal" here means as much as being "in time," an obscure enough definition to be sure. The fact remains that time in the sense of "being in time" serves as a criterion for separating the regions of being. How time comes to have this distinctive ontological function, and even with what right precisely something like time serves as such a criterion, and most of all whether in this naive ontological application of time its genuinely possible ontological relevance is expressed, has neither been asked nor investigated up to now. "Time," especially on the horizon of the common understanding of it, has chanced to acquire this "obvious" ontological function "ofitself," as it were, and has held onto it until today. In contrast we must show, on the basis of the question of the meaning of being which shall have been worked out, that-and in what way-the central range ofproblems of all ontology is rooted in the phenomenon of time correctly viewed and correctly explained. If being is to be conceived in terms of time and if the various modes and derivatives of being, in their modifications and derivations, and in fact to become intelligible through consideration of time, then being itself-and not only beings that are "in time"-is made visible in its "temporal" ["zeitlich"] character. But then "temporal" can no longer mean only "being in time." The "atemporal" and the "supratemporal" are also "temporal" with respect to their being; this not only by way of privation when compared to "temporal" beings which are "in time," but in a positive way which, of course, must first be clarified. Because the expression "temporal" belongs to both prephilosophical and philosophical usage, and because that expression will be used in a different sense in the following investigations, we shall call the original determination of the meaning of being and its characters and modes which devolve from time its temporal [temporale] determination. The funda-
Int.
II
Being and Time
17
mental ontological task of the interpretation of being as such thus includes the elaboration of the temporality of being [Temporalitiit des Seins]. In the exposition of the problem of temporality the concrete answer to the question of the meaning of being is first given. Because being is in each instance comprehensible only in regard to time, the answer to the question of being cannot lie in an isolated and blind proposition. The answer is not grasped by repeating what is stated propositionally, especially when it is transmitted as a free-floating result, so that we merely take notice of a "standpoint" which perhaps deviates from the way the matter has been previously treated. Whether the answer is "novel" is of no importance and remains extrinsic. What is positive about the answer must lie in the fact that it is old enough to enable us to learn to comprehend the possibilities prepared by the "ancients." In conformity to its most proper sense, the answer provides a directive for concrete ontological research, that is, a directive to begin its investigative inquiry within the horizon exhibited-and that is all it provides. If the answer to the question of being thus becomes the guiding directive for research, then it is sufficiently given only if the specific mode ofbeing of previous ontology-the vicissitudes of its questioning, its findings, and its failures-becomes visible as necessary to the very character of Da-sein. 6. The Task of a Destructuring of the History of Ontology
All research-especially when it moves in the sphere of the central question of being-is an antic possibility of Da-sein. The being of Da-sein finds its meaning in temporality. But temporality is at the same time the condition of the possibility of historicity as a temporal mode of being of Da-sein itself, regardless of whether and how it is a being "in time." As a determination historicity is prior to what is called history (world-historical occurrences). Historicity means the constitution of being of the "occurrence" of Da-sein as such; it is the ground for the fact that something like the discipline of "world history" is at all possible and historically belongs to world history. In its factual being Da-sein always is as and "what" it already was. Whether explicitly or not, it is its past. It is its own past not only in such a way that its past, as it were, pushes itself along "behind" it, and that it possesses what is past as a property that is still objectively present and at times has an effect on it. Da-sein "is" its past in the manner of its being which, roughly expressed, on each occasion "occurs" out of its future. In its manner of existing at any given time, and accordingly also with the understanding of being that belongs to it, Da-sein grows into a customary interpretation of itself and grows up in that interpretation. It understands itself in terms of this interpre-
20
18
21
Being and Time
Int.
II
tation at first, and within a certain range, constantly. This understanding discloses the possibilities of its being and regulates them. Its own pastand that always means that of its "generation"-does not follow after Dasein but rather always already goes ahead of it. This elemental historicity of Da-sein can remain concealed from it. But it can also be discovered in a certain way and be properly cultivated. Da-sein can discover, preserve, and explicitly pursue tradition. The discovery of tradition and the disclosure of what it "transmits," and how it does this, can be undertaken as a task in its own right. Da-sein thus assumes the mode of being that involves historical inquiry and research. But the discipline of history-more precisely, the historicality underlying it-is possible only as the kind of being belonging to inquiring Da-sein, because Da-sein is determined by historicity in the ground of its being. If historicity remains concealed from Da-sein, and so long as it does so, the possibility of historical inquiry and discovery of history is denied it. If the discipline of history is lacking, that is no evidence against the historicity of Da-sein; rather it is evidence for this constitution of being in a deficient mode. Only because it is "historic" in the first place can an age lack the discipline of history. On the other hand, if Da-sein has seized upon its inherent possibility not only of making its existence transparent but also of inquiring into the meaning of existentiality itself, that is to say, of provisionally inquiring into the meaning of being in general; and if insight into the essential historicity of Da-sein has opened up in such inquiry, then it is inevitable that inquiry into being, which was designated with regard to its ontic-ontological necessity, is itself characterized by historicity. The elaboration of the question of being must therefore receive its directive to inquire into its own history from the most proper ontological sense of the inquiry itself, as a historical one; that means to become historical in a disciplined way in order to come to the positive appropriation of the past, to come into full possession of its most proper possibilities of inquiry. The question of the meaning of being is led to understand itself as historical in accordance with its own way of proceeding, that is, as the provisional explication of Da-sein in its temporality and historicity. The preparatory interpretation of the fundamental structures of Da-sein with regard to its usual and average way of being-in which it is also first of all historical-will make the following clear: Da-sein not only has the inclination to be entangled in the world in which it is and to interpret itself in terms of that world by its reflected light; at the same time Da-sein is also entangled in a tradition which it more or less explicitly grasps. This tradition deprives Da-sein of its own leadership in questioning and choosing. This is especially true of that understanding (and
Int.
II
Being and Time
19
its possible development) which is rooted in the most proper being of Da-sein-the ontological understanding. The tradition that hereby gains dominance makes what it "transmits" so little accessible that initially and for the most part it covers it over instead. What has been handed down it hands over to obviousness; it bars access to those original "wellsprings" out of which the traditional categories and concepts were in part genuinely drawn. The tradition even makes us forget such a provenance altogether. Indeed, it makes us wholly incapable of even understanding that such a return is necessary. The tradition uproots the historicity of Da-sein to such a degree that it only takes an interest in the manifold forms of possible types, directions, and standpoints of philosophizing in the most remote and strangest cultures, and with this interest tries to veil its own groundlessness. Consequently, in spite of all historical interest and zeal for a philologically "objective" interpretation, Da-sein no longer understands the most elementary conditions which alone make a positive return to the past possible-in the sense of its productive appropriation. At the outset (section 1) we showed that the question of the meaning of being was not only unresolved, not only inadequately formulated, but in spite of all interest in "metaphysics" has even been forgotten. Greek ontology and its history, which through many twists and turns still define the conceptual character of philosophy today, are proof of the fact that Da-sein understands itself and being in general in terms of the "world." The ontology that thus arises is ensnared by the tradition, which allows it to sink to the level of the obvious and become mere material for reworking (as it was for Hegel). Greek ontology thus uprooted becomes a fixed body of doctrine in the Middle Ages. But its systematics is not at all a mere joining together of traditional elements into a single structure. Within the limits of its dogmatic adoption of the fundamental Greek conceptions of being, this systematics contains a great deal of unpretentious work which does make advances. In its scholastic mold, Greek ontology makes the essential transition via the disputationes metapkysicae of Suarez into the "metaphysics" and transcendental philosophy of the modem period; it still determines the foundations and goals of Hegel's Logic. Insofar as certain distinctive domains of being become visible in the course of this history and henceforth chiefly dominate the range of problems (Descartes' ego cogito, subject, the "I," reason, spirit, person), the beings just cited remain unquestioned with respect to the being and structure of their being, which indicates the thorough neglect of the question of being. But the categorial content of traditional ontology is transferred to these beings with corresponding formalizations and purely negative restrictions, or else dialectic is called upon to help with an ontological interpretation of the substantiality of the subject.
22
20
23
Being and Time
Int.
11
If the question of being is to achieve clarity regarding its own history, a loosening of the sclerotic tradition and a dissolving of the concealments produced by it is necessary. We understand this task as the destructuring of the traditional content of ancient ontology which is to be carried out along the guidelines of the question of being. This destructuring is based upon the original experiences in which the first and subsequently guiding determinations of being were gained. This demonstration of the provenance of the fundamental ontological concepts, as the investigation which displays their "birth certificate," has nothing to do with a pernicious relativizing of ontological standpoints. The destructuring has just as little the negative sense of disburdenmg ourselves of the ontological tradition. On the contrary, it should stake out the positive possibilities of the tradition, and that always means to fix its boundaries. These are factually given with the specific formulation of the question and the prescribed demarcation of the possible field of investigation. Negatively, the destructuring is not even related to the past: its criticism concerns "today" and the dominant way we treat the history of ontology, whether it be conceived as the history of opinions, ideas, or problems. However, the destructuring does not wish to bury the past in nullity; it has a positive intent. Its negative function remains tacit and indirect. The destructuring of the history of ontology essentially belongs to the formulation of the question of being and is possible solely within such a formulation. Within the scope of this treatise, which has as its goal a fundamental elaboration of the question of being, the destructuring can be carried out only with regard to the fundamentally decisive stages of this history. In accord with the positive tendency of the destructuring the question must first be asked whether and to what extent in the course of the history of ontology in general the interpretation of being has been thematically connected with the phenomenon of time. We must also ask whether the range of problems concerning temporality which necessarily belongs here was fundamentally worked out or could have been. Kant is the first and only one who traversed a stretch of the path toward investigating the dimension of temporality-or allowed himself to be driven there by the compelling force of the phenomena themselves. Only when the problem of temporality is pinned down can we succeed in casting light on the obscurity of his doctrine of the schematism. Furthermore, in this way we can also show why this area had to remain closed to Kant in its real dimensions and in its central ontological function. Kant himself knew that he was venturing forth into an obscure area: "This schematism of our understanding as regards appearances and their mere form is an art hidden in the depths of the human soul,
Int.
11
Being and Time
21
the true devices of which are hardly ever to be divined from Nature and laid uncovered before our eyes. " 1 What it is that Kant shrinks back from here, as it were, must be brought to light thematically and in principle if the expression "being" is to have a demonstrable meaning. Ultimately the phenomena to be explicated in the following analysis under the rubric of "temporality" are precisely those that determine the most covert judgments of "common reason," analysis of which Kant calls the "business of philosophers." In pursuing the task of destructuring on the guideline of the problem of temporality the following treatise will attempt to interpret the chapter on the schematism and the Kantian doctrine of time developed there. At the same time we must show why Kant could never gain insight into the problem of temporality. Two things prevented this insight. On the one hand, the neglect of the question of being in general, and in connection with this, the lack of a thematic ontology of Da-sein-in Kantian terms, the lack of a preliminary ontological analytic of the subjectivity of the subject. Instead, Kant dogmatically adopted Descartes' position-notwithstanding all his essential advances. Despite his taking this phenomenon back into the subject, however, his analysis of time remains oriented toward the traditional, common understanding of it. It is this that finally prevented Kant from working out the phenomenon of a "transcendental determination of time" in its own structure and function. As a consequence of this double effect of the tradition, the decisive connection between time and the "I think" remained shrouded in complete obscurity. It did not even become a problem. By taking over Descartes' ontological position Kant neglects something essential: an ontology of Da-sein. In terms of Descartes' innermost tendency this omission is a decisive one. With the cogito sum Descartes claims to prepare a new and secure foundation for philosophy. But what he leaves undetermined in this "radical" beginning is the manner of being of the res cogitans, more precisely, the meaning of being of the "sum." Working out the tacit ontological foundations of the cogito sum will constitute the second stage of the destructuring of, and the path back into, the history of ontology. The interpretation will demonstrate not only that Descartes had to neglect the question of being altogether but also why he held the opinion that the absolute "certainty" of the cogito exempted him from the question of the meaning of the being of this being. However, with Descartes it is not just a matter of neglect and thus of a complete ontological indeterminateness of the res cogitans sive mens sive animus ["the thinking thing, whether it be mind or spirit"]. Descartes carries out the fundamental reflections of his Meditations by applying medieval ontology to this being which he posits as the fundamentum incon-
24
22
25
26
Being and Time
Int.
II
cussum ["unshakable foundation"]. The res cogitans is ontologically determined as ens, and for medieval ontology the meaning of the being of the ens is established in the understanding of it as ens creatum. As the ens infinitum God is the ens increatum. But createdness, in the broadest sense of something having been produced, is an essential structural moment of the ancient concept of being. The ostensibly new beginning of philosophizing betrays the imposition of a fatal prejudice. On the basis of this prejudice later times neglect a thematic ontological analysis of "the mind" ["Gemilt"] which would be guided by the question of being; likewise they neglect a critical confrontation with the inherited ancient ontology. Everyone familiar with the medieval period sees that Descartes is "dependent" upon medieval scholasticism and uses its terminology. But with this "discovery" nothing is gained philosophically as long as it remains obscure to what a profound extent medieval ontology influences the way posterity determines or fails to determine the res cogitans ontologically. The full extent of this influence cannot be estimated until the meaning and limits of ancient ontology have been shown by our orientation toward the question of being. In other words, the destructuring sees itself assigned the task of interpreting the foundation of ancient ontology in light of the problem of temporality. Here it becomes evident that the ancient interpretation of the being of beings is oriented toward the "world" or "nature" in the broadest sense and that it indeed gains its understanding of being from "time." The outward evidence of this-but of course only outward-is the determination of the meaning of being as parousia or ousia, which ontologically and temporally means "presence" ["Anwesenheit"]. Beings are grasped in their being as "presence"; that is to say, they are understood with regard to a definite mode of time, the present. The problem of Greek ontology must, like that of any ontology, take its guideline from Da-sein itself. In the ordinary and also the philosophical "definition," Da-sein, that is, the being of human being, is delineated as zoon logon echon, that creature whose being is essentially determined by its ability to speak. Legein (cf. section 7, b) is the guideline for arriving at the structures of being of the beings we encounter in speech and discussion. That is why the ancient ontology developed by Plato becomes "dialectic." The possibility of a more radical conception of the problem of being grows with the continuing development of the ontological guideline itself, that is, with the "hermeneutics" of the logos. "Dialectic," which was a genuine philosophic embarrassment, becomes superfluous. Aristotle "no longer has any understanding" of it for this reason, that he places it on a more radical foundation and transcends it. Legein itself, or noein-the simple apprehension of something objectively present in its pure objective presence [Vorhandenheit], which Parmenides already used as a guide for interpreting being-has the temporal struc-
Int.
II
Being and Time
23
ture of a pure "making present" of something. Beings, which show themselves in and for this making present and which are understood as genuine beings, are accordingly interpreted with regard to the present; that is to say, they are conceived as presence (ousia). However, this Greek interpretation of being comes about without any explicit knowledge of the guideline functioning in it, without taking cognizance of or understanding the fundamental ontological function of time, without insight into the ground of the possibility of this function. On the contrary, time itself is taken to be one being among others. The attempt is made to grasp time itself in the structure of its being on the horizon of an understanding of being which is oriented toward time in an inexplicit and naive way. Within the framework of the following fundamental elaboration of the question of being we cannot offer a detailed temporal interpretation of the foundations of ancient ontology-especially of its scientifically highest and purest stage, that is, in Aristotle. Instead, we offer an interpretation of Aristotle's treatise on time/ which can be taken as a way of discerning the basis and limits of the ancient science of being. Aristotle's treatise on time is the first detailed interpretation of this phenomenon that has come down to us. It essentially determined all the following interpretations, including that of Bergson. From our analysis of Aristotle's concept of time it becomes retrospectively clear that the Kantian interpretation moves within the structures developed by Aristotle. This means that Kant's fundamental ontological orientationdespite all the differences implicit in a new inquiry-remains Greek. The question of being attains true concreteness only when we carry out the destructuring of the ontological tradition. By so doing we can thoroughly demonstrate the inescapability of the question of the meaning of being and so demonstrate the meaning of our talk about a "retrieve" of this question. In this field where "the matter itself is deeply veiled,"~ any investigation will avoid overestimating its results. For such inquiry is constantly forced to face the possibility of disclosing a still more original and more universal horizon from which it could draw the answer to the question "What does 'being' mean?" We can discuss such possibilities seriously and with a positive result only if the question of being has been reawakened and we have reached the point where we can come to terms with it in a controlled fashion.
7. The Phenomenological Method of the Investigation With the preliminary characterization of the thematic object of the investigation (the being of beings, or the meaning of being in general) its
27
24
28
Being and Time
Int.
11
method would appear to be already prescribed. The task of ontology is to set in relief the being of beings and to explicate being itself. And the method of ontology remains questionable in the highest degree as long as we wish merely to consult historically transmitted ontologies or similar efforts. Since the term "ontology" is used in a formally broad sense for this investigation, the approach of clarifying its method by tracing the history of that method is automatically precluded. In using the term "ontology" we do not specify any particular philosophical discipline standing in relation to others. It should not at all be our task to satisfy the demands of any established discipline. On the contrary, such a discipline can be developed only from the objective necessity of particular questions and procedures demanded by the "things themselves." With the guiding question of the meaning of being the investigation arrives at the fundamental question of philosophy in general. The treatment of this question is phenomenological. With this term the treatise dictates for itself neither a "standpoint" nor a "direction," because phenomenology is neither of these and can never be as long as it understands itself. The expression "phenomenology" signifies primarily a concept of method. It does not characterize the "what" of the objects of philosophical research in terms of their content but the "how" of such research. The more genuinely effective a concept of method is and the more comprehensively it determines the fundamental conduct of a science, the more originally is it rooted in confrontation with the things themselves and the farther away it moves from what we call a technical device-of which there are many in the theoretical disciplines. The term "phenomenology" expresses a maxim that can be formulated: "To the things themselves!" It is opposed to all free-floating constructions and accidental findings; it is also opposed to taking over concepts only seemingly demonstrated; and likewise to pseudo-questions which often are spread abroad as "problems" for generations. But one might object that this maxim is, after all, abundantly self-evident and, moreover, an expression of the principle of all scientific knowledge. It is not clear why this commonplace should be explicitly put in the tide of our research. In fact, we are dealing with "something self-evident" which we want to get closer to, insofar as that is important for the clarification of procedure in our treatise. We shall explicate only the preliminary concept of phenomenology. The expression has two components, phenomenon and logos. Both go back to the Greek terms phainomenon and logos. Viewed extrinsically, the word "phenomenology" is formed like the terms theology, biology, sociology, translated as the science of God, of life, of the community. Accordingly, phenomenology would be the science of phenom-
Int. II
Being and Time
25
ena. The preliminary concept of phenomenology is to be exhibited by characterizing what is meant by the two components, phenomenon and logos, and by establishing the meaning of the combined word. The history of the word itself, which originated presumably with the Wolffian school, is not important here.
(a) The Concept of Phenomenon. The Greek expression phairwmenon, from which the term "phenomenon" derives, comes from the verb phainesthai, meaning "to show itself." Thus phainomenon means what shows itself, the self-showing, the manifest. Phainesthai itself is a "middle voice" construction of phaino, to bring into daylight, to place in brightness. Phaino belongs to the root pha-, like pkOs, light or brightness, that is, that within which something can become manifest, visible in itself. Thus the meaning of the expression "phenomenon" is established as what shows itself in itself, what is manifesL The phainomena, "phenomena," are thus the totality of what lies in the light of day or can be brought to light. Sometimes the Greeks simply identified this with ta onta (beings). Beings can show themselves from themselves in various ways, depending on the mode of access to them. The possibility even exists that they can show themselves as they are not in themselves. In this self-showing beings "look like ...." Such self-showing we call seeming [Scheinen]. And so the expression phainomenon, phenomenon, means in Greek: what looks like something, what "seems," "semblance." Phainomenon agathon means a good that looks like-but "in reality" is not what it gives itself out to be. It is extremely important for a further understanding of the concept of phenomenon to see how what is named in both meanings of phainomenon ("phenomenon" as self-showing and "phenomenon" as semblance) are structurally connected. Only because something claims to show itself in accordance with its meaning at all, that is, claims to be a phenomenon, can it show itself as something it is not, or can it "only look like .... " The original meaning (phenomenon, what is manifest) already contains and is the basis of phainomenon ("semblance"). We attribute to the term "phenomenon" the positive and original meaning of phainomenon terminologically, and separate the phenomenon of semblance from it as a privative modification. But what both terms express has at first nothing at all to do with what is called "appearance" or even "mere appearance." One speaks of "appearances or symptoms of illness." What is meant by this are occurrences in the body that show themselves and in this self-showing as such "indicate" something that does not show itself. When such occurrences emerge, their self-showing coincides with the objective presence [Vorhandensein] of disturbances that do not show themselves. Appearance, as the appearance "of something," thus pre-
29
26
30
Being and Time
Int.
II
cisely does not mean that something shows itself; rather, it means that something makes itself known which does not show itself. It makes itself known through something that does show itself. Appearing is* a not showing itself But this "not" must by no means be confused with the privative not which determines the structure of semblance. What does not show itself, in the manner of what appears, can also never seem. All indications, presentations, symptoms, and symbols have this fundamental formal structure of appearing, although they do differ among themselves. Although "appearing" is never a self-showing in the sense of phenomenon, appearing is possible only on the basis of a self-showing of something. But this, the self-showing that makes appearing possible, is not appearing itself. Appearing is a making itself known through something that shows itself. If we then say that with the word "appearance" we are pointing to something in which something appears without itself being an appearance, then the concept of phenomenon is not thereby delimited but presupposed. However, this presupposition remains hidden because the expression "to appear" in this definition of "appearance" is used in two senses. That in which something "appears" means that in which something makes itself known, that is, does not show itself; in the expression "without itself being an 'appearance'" appearance means the self-showing. But this self-showing essentially belongs to the "wherein" in which something makes itself known. Accordingly, phenomena are never appearances, but every appearance is dependent upon phenomena. If we define phenomenon with the help of a concept of "appearance" that is still unclear, then everything is turned upside down, and a "critique" of phenomenology on this basis is surely a remarkable enterprise. The expression "appearance" itself in turn can have a double meaning. First, appearing in the sense of making itself known as something that does not show itself and, second, in the sense of what does the making itself known-what in its self-showing indicates something that does not show itself. Finally, one can use appearing as the term for the genuine meaning of phenomenon as self-showing. If one designates these three different states of affairs as "appearance" confusion is inevitable. However, this confusion is considerably increased by the fact that "appearance" can take on still another meaning. If one understands what does the making itself known-what in its self-showing indicates the nonmanifest-as what comes to the fore in the nonmanifest itself, and radiates from it in such a way that what is nonmanifest is thought of as *in this case
Int.
II
Being and Time
27
what is essentially never manifest-if this is so, then appearance is tantamount to production [Hervorbringung] or to what is produced [Her· vorgebrachter]. However, this does not constitute the real being of the producing or productive [Hervorbringende], but is rather appearance in the sense of "mere appearance." What does the making itself known and is brought forward indeed shows itself in such a way that, as the emanation of what it makes known, it precisely and continually veils what it is in itself. But then again this not-showing which veils is not semblance. Kant uses the term "appearance" in this twofold way. On the one hand, appearances are for him the "objects of empirical intuition," what shows itself in intuition. This self-showing (phenomenon in the genuine, original sense) is, on the other hand, "appearance" as the emanation of something that makes itself known but conceals itself in the appearance. Since a phenomenon is constitutive for "appearance" in the sense of making itself known through a self-showing, and since this phenomenon can tum into semblance in a privative way, appearance can also tum into mere semblance. Under a certain kind of light someone can look as if he were flushed. The redness that shows itself can be taken as making known the objective presence of fever; this in tum would indicate a disturbance in the organism. Phenomenon-the self-showing in itself-means a distinctive way something can be encountered. On the other hand, appearance means a referential relation in beings themselves such that what does the referring (the making known) can fulfill its possible function only if it shows itself in itself-only if it is a "phenomenon." Both appearance and semblance are themselves founded in the phenomenon, albeit in different ways. The confusing multiplicity of "phenomena" designated by the terms phenomenon, semblance, appearance, mere appearance, can be unraveled only if the concept of phenomenon is understood from the very beginning as the self-showing in itself. But if in the way we grasp the concept of phenomenon we leave undetermined which beings are to be addressed as phenomena, and if we leave altogether open whether the self-showing is actually a particular being or a characteristic of the being of beings, then we are dealing solely with the formal concept of phenomenon. If by the self-showing we understand those beings that are accessible, for example, in Kant's sense of empirical intuition, the formal concept of phenomenon can be used legitimately. In this usage phenomenon has the meaning of the common concept of phenomenon. But this common one is not the phenomenological concept of phenomenon. In the horizon of the Kantian problem what is understood phenomenologically by the term phenomenon (disregarding other differences) can be illustrated when we say that what already shows itself in appearances prior to and always accompanying
31
28
Being and Time
Int.
II
what we commonly understand as phenomena, though unthematically, can be brought thematically to self-showing. What thus shows itself in itself ("the forms of intuition") are the phenomena of phenomenology. For, clearly, space and time must be able to show themselves in this way. They must be able to become phenomena if Kant claims to make a valid transcendental statement when he says that space is the a priori "wherein" of an order. Now if the phenomenological concept of phenomenon is to be understood at all (regardless of how the self-showing may be more closely determined), we must inevitably presuppose insight into the sense of the formal concept of phenomenon and the legitimate use of phenomenon in its ordinary meaning. However, before getting hold of the preliminary concept of phenomenology we must delimit the meaning of logos, in order to make clear in which sense phenomenology can be "a science of" phenomena. 32
(b) The Concept of Logos. The concept of logos has many meanings in Plato and Aristotle, indeed in such a way that these meanings diverge without a basic meaning positively taking the lead. This is in fact only an illusion which lasts so long as an interpretation is not able to grasp adequately the basic meaning in its primary content. If we say that the basic meaning of logos is speech, this literal translation becomes valid only when we define what speech itself means. The later history of the word logos, and especially the manifold and arbitrary interpretations of subsequent philosophy, conceal constantly the real meaning of speechwhich is manifest enough. Logos is "translated," and that always means interpreted, as reason, judgment, concept, definition, ground, relation. But how can "speech" be so susceptible of modification that logos means all the things mentioned, and indeed in scholarly usage? Even if logos is understood in the sense of a statement, and statement as '1udgment," this apparently correct translation can still miss the fundamental meaning-especially if judgment is understood in the sense of some contemporary "theory of judgment." Logos does not mean judgment, in any case not primarily, if by judgment we understand "connecting two things" or "taking a position" either by endorsing or rejecting. Rather, logos as speech really means deloun, to make manifest "what is being talked about" in speech. Aristotle explicates this function of speech more precisely as apophainesthai. 4 Logos lets som~thing be seen (phainesthai), namely what is being talked about, and indeed for the speaker (who serves as the medium) or for those who speak with each other. Speech "lets us see," from itself, apo ... , what is being talked about. In speech (apophansis), insofar as it is genuine, what is said should be derived from what is being talked about. In this way spoken commu-
Int. n
Being and Time
29
nication, in what it says, makes manifest what it is talking about and thus makes it accessible to another. Such is the structure of logos as apophansis. Not every "speech" suits this mode of making manifest, in the sense of letting something be seen by indicating it. For example, requesting (euche) also makes something manifest, but in a different way. When fully concrete, speech (letting something be seen) has the character of speaking or vocalization in words. Logos is phone, indeed phone meta phantasias-vocalization in which something always is sighted. Only because the function of logos as ap()jlhansis lies in letting something be seen by indicating it can logos have the structure of synthesis. Here synthesis does not mean to connect and conjoin representations, to manipulate psychical occurrences, which then gives rise to the "problem" of how these connections, as internal, correspond to what is external and physical. The syn [of synthesis] here has a purely apophantical meaning: to let something be seen in its togetherness with something, to let something be seen as something. Furthermore, because logos lets something be seen, it can therefore be true or false. But everything depends on staying clear of any concept of truth construed in the sense of "correspondence" or "accordance" [Ubereinstimmung]. This idea is by no means the primary one in the concept of aletheia. The "being true" of logos as aletheuein means: to take beings that are being talked about in legein as apophainesthai out of their concealment; to let them be seen as something unconcealed (alethes); to discover them. Similarly "being false," pseudesthai, is tantamount to deceiving in the sense of covering up: putting something in front of something else (by way of letting it be seen) and thereby passing it off as something it is not. But because "truth" has this meaning, and because logos is a specific mode of letting something be seen, logos simply may not be acclaimed as the primary "place" of truth. If one defines truth as what "genuinely" pertains to judgment, which is quite customary today, and if one invokes Aristotle in support of this thesis, such a procedure is without justification and the Greek concept of truth thoroughly misunderstood. In the Greek sense what is "true"-indeed more originally true than the logos we have been discussing-is aisthesis, the simple sense perception of something. To the extent that an aisthesis aims at its idia [what is its own]-the beings genuinely accessible only through it and for it, for example, looking at colors-perception is always true. This means that looking always discovers colors, hearing always discovers tones. What is in the purest and most original sense "true"-that is, what only discovers in such a way that it can never cover up anything-is pure noein, straightforwardly observant apprehension of the simplest determinations of the being of beings as such. This noein can never cover
33
30
34
35
Being and Time
Int.
II
up, can never be false; at worst it can be a nonapprehending, agnoein, not sufficing for straightforward, appropriate access. What no longer takes the form of a pure letting be seen, but rather in its indicating always has recourse to something else and so always lets something be seen as something, acquires with this structure of synthesis the possibility of covering up. However, "truth of judgment" is only the opposite of this covering up; it is a multiplyfounded phenomenon of truth. Realism and idealism alike thoroughly miss the meaning of the Greek concept of truth from which alone the possibility of something like a "theory of Ideas" can be understood as philosophical knowledge. And because the function of logos lies in letting something be seen straightforwardly, in letting beings be apprehended, logos can mean reason. Moreover, because logos is used in the sense not only of legein but also of legomenon-what is pointed to as such; and because the latter is nothing other than the hypokeimenon-what always already lies present at the basis of all relevant speech and discussion; for these reasons logos qua legomenon means ground, ratio. Finally, because logos as legomenon can also mean what is addressed, as something that has become visible in its relation to something else, in its "relatedness," logos acquires the meaning of relation and relationship. This interpretation of "apophantic speech" may suffice to clarify the primary function of logos.
(c) The Preliminary Concept of Phenomenology. When we bring to mind concretely what has been exhibited in the interpretation of "phenomenon" and "logos" we are struck by an inner relation between what is meant by these terms. The expression "phenomenology" can be formulated in Greek as legein ta phainomena. But legein means apophainesthai. Hence phenomenology means: apophainesthai ta phainomena-to let what shows itself be seen from itself, just as it shows itself from itself. That is the formal meaning of the type of research that calls itself "phenomenology." But this expresses nothing other than the maxim formulated above: "To the things themselves!" Accordingly, the term "phenomenology" differs in meaning from such expressions as "theology" and the like. Such titles designate the objects of the respective disciplines in terms of their content. "Phenomenology" neither designates the object of its researches nor is it a title that describes their content. The word only tells us something about the how of the demonstration and treatment of what this discipline considers. Science "of' the phenomena means that it grasps its objects in such a way that everything about them to be discussed must be directly indicated and directly demonstrated. The basically tautological expression "descriptive phenomenology" has the same sense. Here descrip-
Int.
11
Being and Time
31
tion does not mean a procedure like that of, say, botanical morphology. The term rather has the sense of a prohibition, insisting that we avoid all nondemonstrative determinations. The character of description itself, the specific sense of the logos, can be established only from the "material content" ["Sachheit"] ofwhat is "described," that is, of what is to be brought to scientific determinateness in the way phenomena are encountered. The meaning of the formal and common concepts of the phenomenon formally justifies our calling every way of indicating beings as they show themselves in themselves "phenomenology." Now what must be taken into account if the formal concept of phenomenon is to be deformalized to the phenomenological one, and how does this differ from the common concept? What is it that phenomenology is to "let be seen"? What is it that is to be called "phenomenon" in a distinctive sense? What is it that by its very essence becomes the necessary theme when we indicate something explicitly? Manifestly it is something that does not show itself initially and for the most part, something that is concealed, in contrast to what initially and for the most part does show itself. But at the same time it is something that essentially belongs to what initially and for the most part shows itself, indeed in such a way that it constitutes its meaning and ground.* But what remains concealed in an exceptional sense, or what falls back and is covered up again, or shows itself only in a distorted way, is not this or that being but rather, as we have shown in our foregoing observations, the being of beings. It can be covered up to such a degree that it is forgotten and the question about it and its meaning altogether omitted. Thus what demands to become a phenomenon in a distinctive sense, in terms of its most proper content, phenomenology has taken into its "grasp" thematically as its object. Phenomenology is the way of access to, and the demonstrative manner of determination of, what is to become the theme of ontology. Ontology is possible only as phenomenology. The phenomenological concept of phenomenon, as self-showing, means the being of beings-its meaning, modifications, and derivatives. This self-showing is nothing arbitrary, nor is it something like an appearing. The being of beings can least of all be something "behind which" something else stands, something that "does not appear." Essentially, nothing else stands "behind" the phenomena of phenomenology. Nevertheless, what is to become a phenomenon can be concealed. And precisely because phenomena are initially and for the most part not given phenomenology is needed. Being covered up is the counterconcept to "phenomenon." *Truth of being.
36
32
37
Being and Time
Int.
11
There are various ways phenomena can be covered up. In the first place, a phenomenon can be covered up in the sense that it is still completely undiscovered. There is neither knowledge nor lack of knowledge about it. In the second place, a phenomenon can be buried over. This means it was once discovered but then got covered up again. This covering up can be total, but more commonly, what was once discovered may still be visible, though only as semblance. However, where there is semblance there is "being." This kind of covering up, "distortion," is the most frequent and the most dangerous kind because here the possibilities of being deceived and misled are especially pertinacious. Within a "system" the structures and concepts of being that are available but concealed with respect to their autochthony may perhaps claim their rights. On the basis of their integrated structure in a system they present themselves as something "dear" which is in no need of further justification and which therefore can serve as a point of departure for a process of deduction. The covering up itself, whether it be understood in the sense of concealment, being buried over, or distortion, has in turn a twofold possibility. There are accidental coverings and necessary ones, the latter grounded in the enduring nature of the di.scovered. It is possible for every phenomenological concept and proposition drawn from genuine origins to degenerate when communicated as a statement. It gets circulated in a vacuous fashion, loses its autochthony, and becomes a freefloating thesis. Even in the concrete work of phenomenology lurks possible inflexibility and the inability to grasp what was originally "grasped." And the difficulty of this research consists precisely in making it self-critical in a positive sense. The way of encountering being and the structures of being in the mode of phenomenon must first be wrested from the objects of phenomenology. Thus the point of departure of the analysis, the access to the phenomenon, and passage through the prevalent coverings must secure their own method. The idea of an "originary" and "intuitive" grasp and explication of phenomena must be opposed to the naivete of an accidental, "immediate," and unreflective "beholding." On the basis of the preliminary concept of phenomenology just delimited, the terms "phenomenal" and "phenomenological" can now be given fixed meanings. What is given and is explicable in the way we encounter the phenomenon is called "phenomenal." In this sense we speak of phenomenal structures. Everything that belongs to the manner of indication and explication, and constitutes the conceptual tools this research requires, is called "phenomenological." Because phenomenon in the phenomenological understanding is always just what constitutes being, and furthermore because being is
Int.
II
Being and Time
33
always the being of beings, we must first of all bring beings themselves forward in the right way if we are to have any prospect of exposing being. These beings must likewise show themselves in the way of access that genuinely belong to them. Thus the common concept of phenomenon becomes phenomenologically relevant. The preliminary task of a "phenomenological" securing of that being which is to serve as our example, as the point of departure for the analysis proper, is always already prescribed by the goal of this analysis. As far as content goes, phenomenology is the science of the being of beings-ontology. In our elucidation of the tasks of ontology the necessity arose for a fundamental ontology which would have as its theme that being which is ontologically and ontically distinctive, namely, Da-sein. This must be done in such a way that our ontology confronts the cardinal problem, the question of the meaning of being in general.* From the investigation itself we shall see that the methodological meaning of phenomenological description is interpretation. The logos of the phenomenology of Da-sein has the character of hermeneuein, through which the proper meaning of being and the basic structures of the very being of Da-sein are made known to the understanding of being that belongs to Da-sein itself. Phenomenology of Da-sein is hermeneutics in the original signification of that word, which designates the work of interpretation. But since discovery of the meaning of being and of the basic structures of Da-sein in general exhibits the horizon for every further ontological research into beings unlike Da-sein, the present hermeneutic is at the same time "hermeneutics" in the sense that it works out the conditions of the possibility of every ontological investigation. Finally, since Da-sein has ontological priority over all other beings-as a being in the possibility of existence [Existenz]-hermeneutics, as the interpretation of the being of Da-sein, receives a specific third and, philosophically understood, primary meaning of an analysis of the existentiality of existence. To the extent that this hermeneutic elaborates the historicity of Da-sein ontologically as the ontic condition of the possibility of the discipline of history, it contains the roots of what can be called "hermeneutics" only in a derivative sense: the methodology of the historical humanistic disciplines. As the fundamental theme of philosophy being is not a genus of beings; yet it pertains to every being. Its "universality" must be sought in a higher sphere. Being and its structure transcend every being and every possible existent determination of a being. Being is the transcendens pure *being-not a genus, not being for beings generally; the "in general"=katholou•as the whole of: being of beings; meaning of difference.
38
34
39
Being and Time
Int.
11
and simple.* The transcendence of the being of Da-sein is a distinctive one since in it lies the possibility and necessity of the most radical indi· viduation. Every disclosure of being as the trarucendens is trarucendental knowledge. Phenomenological truth (disclosedness of being) is veritas transcendentalis. Ontology and phenomenology are not two different disciplines which among others belong to philosophy. Both terms characterize philosophy itself, its object and procedure. Philosophy is universal phenomenological ontology, taking its departure from the hermeneutic of Da-sein, which, as an analysis of existence,t has fastened the end of the guideline of all philosophical inquiry at the point from which it arises and to which it returns. The following investigations would not have been possible without the foundation laid by Edmund Husserl; with his Logical Investigatioru phenomenology achieved a breakthrough. Our elucidations of the preliminary concept of phenomenology show that its essential character does not consist in its actuality as a philosophical "movement."t Higher than actuality stands possibility. We can understand phenomenology solely by seizing upon it as a possibility.5 With regard to the awkwardness and "inelegance" of expression in the following analyses, we may remark that it is one thing to report narratively about beings and another to grasp beings in their being. For the latter task not only most of the words are lacking but above all the "grammar." If we may allude to earlier and in their own right altogether incomparable researches on the analysis of being, then we should compare the ontological sections in Plato's Parmenides or the fourth chapter of the seventh book of Aristotle's Metaphysics with a narrative passage from Thucydides. Then we can see the stunning character of the formulations with which their philosophers challenged the Greeks. Since our powers are essentially inferior, and also since the area of being to be disclosed ontologically is far more difficult than that presented to the Greeks, the complexity of our concept-formation and the severity of our expression will increase. *of course not transcendens-despite every metaphysical resonance-scholastic and greek-platonic koinon, rather transcendence as the ecstatic-temporal [Zeitlichkeit]-temporality [Temporalitat]; but "horizon"! Being has "thought beyond" ["uberdacht"] beings. However, transcendence from the truth of being: the event [das Ereignis]. t "Existence"-fundamental ontologically, i.e., itself related to the truth of being, and only in this way! 1 i.e., not in the transcendental-philosophic direction of Kantian critical idealism.
Int.
Being and Time
II
35
8. The Outline of the Treatise The question of the meaning of being is the most universal and the emptiest. But at the same time the possibility inheres of its most acute individualization in each particular Da-sein. * If we are to gain the fundamental concept of "being" and the prescription of the ontologically requisite conceptuality in all its necessary variations, we need a concrete guideline. The "special character" of the investigation does not belie the universality of the concept of being. For we may advance to being by way of a special interpretation of a particular being, Da-sein, in which the horizon for an understanding and a possible interpretation of being is to be won. But his being is in itself "historic," so that its most proper ontological illumination necessarily becomes a "historical" interpretation. The elaboration of the question of being is a two-pronged task; our treatise therefore has two divisions. Part One: The interpretation of Da-sein on the basis of temporality and the explication of time as the transcendental horizon of the question of being. Part Two: Basic features of a phenomenological destructuring of the history of ontology on the guideline of the problem of temporality. The first part consists of three divisions: 1. The preparatory fundamental analysis of Da-sein. 2. Da-sein and temporality. 3. Time and being. t The second part likewise has three divisions:
1. Kant's doctrine of the schematism and of time, as preliminary stage of a problem of temporality. 2. The ontological foundation of Descartes' cogito sum and the incorporation of medieval ontology in the problem of the res cogitans. 3. Aristotle's treatise on time as a way of discerning the phenomenal basis and the limits of ancient ontology. *authentic: bringing about standing-within the there [Irutandigkeit]. The difference bound to transcendence [traruzendenzhafte Differenz.]. The overcorning of the horizon as such. The return into the source [Herkunft]. The presencing out of this source.
40
PART ONE
The Interpretation of Da-sein in Terms of Temporality* and the Explication of Time as the Transcendental Horizon of the Question of Beingt DIVISION ONE
The Preparatory Fundamental Analysis of Da-sein
What is primarily interrogated in the question of the meaning of being is that being which has the character of Da-sein. In keeping with its uniqu~ ness, the preparatory existential analytic of Da-sein itself needs a prefigurative exposition and delimitation from investigations which seem to run parallel (chapter 1). Bearing in mind the point of departure of the investigation, we must analyze a fundamental structure of Da-sein: beingin-th~world (chapter II). This "a primi" of the interpretation of Da-sein is not a structure which is pieced together, but rather a structure which is primordially and constantly whole. It grants various perspectives on the factors which constitute it. These factors are to be kept constantly in view, bearing in mind the preceding whole of this structure. Thus, we have as the object of our analysis: the world in its worldliness (chapter III), being-in-the-world as being a self and being with others (chapter IV), being-in as such (chapter V). On the foundation of the analysis of this fundamental structure, a preliminary demonstration of the being of Dasein is possible. Its existential meaning is Care (chapter VI).
* Only this in the part published. t
Cf. the Marburg lecture, SS 1927 (Die Grundprobleme der Phiinomenologie).
37
41
I The Exposition of the Task of a Preparatory Analysis of Da-sein
9. The Theme of the Analytic of Da-sein The being whose analysis our task is, is always we* ourselves. The being of this being is always mine. In the being of this being it is related to its being.t As the being of this being, it is entrusted to its own being. It is beingt about which this being is concerned. From this characteristic of Da-sein two things follow: I. The "essence" of this being lies in its to be.§ The whatness (essen· tia) of this being must be understood in terms of its being (existentia) insofar as one can speak of it at all. Here the ontological task is precisely to show that when we choose the word existence for the being of this being, this term does not and cannot have the ontological meaning of the traditional expression of existentia. Ontologically, existentia means objective presence [Vorhandenheit], a kind of being which is essentially inappropriate to characterize the being which has the character of Da-sein. We can avoid confusion by always using the interpretive expression objective presence [Vorhandenheit] for the term existentia, and by attributing existence as a determination of being only to Da-sein. *always "I" But this is historical being-in-the-world. t Which one? To be the There and thus to perdure being as such. § that it "has" to be; definition. t
39
42
40
43
Being and Time
1.1
The "essence" of Da-sein lies in its existence. The characteristics to be found in this being are thus not objectively present "attributes" of an objectively present being which has such and such an "outward appearance," but rather possible ways for it to be, and only this. The thatness of this being is primarily being. Thus the term "Da-sein" which we use to designate this being does not express its what, as in the case of table, house, tree, but being.* 2. The being which this being is concerned about in its being is always my own. Thus, Da-sein is never to be understood ontologically as a case and instance of a genus of beings as objectively present. To something objectively present its being is a matter of "indifference," more precisely, it "is" in such a way that its being can neither be indifferent nor non-indifferent to it. In accordance with the character of always-being-myown-being (femeinigkeit], when we speak of Da-sein, we must always use the personal pronoun along with whatever we say: "I am," "You are."t Da-sein is my own, to be always in this or that way. It has somehow always already decided in which way Da-sein is always my own. The being which is concerned in its being about its being is related to its being as its truest possibility. Da-sein is always its possibility. It does not "have" that possibility only as a mere attribute of something objectively present. And because Da-sein is always essentially its possibility, it can "choose" itself in its being, it can win itself, it can lose itself, or it can never and only "apparently" win itself. It can only have lost itself and it can only have not yet gained itself because it is essentially possible as authentic, that is, it belongs to itself. The two kinds of being of authenticity and inauthenticity-these expressions are terminologically chosen in the strictest sense of the word-are based on the fact that Da-sein is in general determined by always being-mine. But the inauthenticity of Dasein does not signify a "lesser" being or a "lower" degree of being. Rather, inauthenticity can determine Da-sein even in its fullest concretion, when it is busy, excited, interested, and capable of pleasure. The two characteristics of Da-sein sketched out-on the one hand, the priority of "existentia" over essentia, and then, always-being-minealready show that an analytic of this being is confronted with a unique phenomenal region. This being does not and never has the kind of being of what is merely objectively present within the world. Thus, it is also not to be thematically found in the manner of coming across something objectively present. The correct presentation of it is so little a matter of course that its determination itself constitutes an essential part of the ontological analytic of this being. The possibility of under-
* The Being "of' the There, "of': genitivus objectivus. t
That is, in each case my own means being appropriated.
1.1
Being and Time
41
standing the being of this being stands and falls with the secure accomplishment of the correct presentation of this being. No matter how provisional the analysis may be, it always demands the securing of the correct beginning. As a being, Da-sein always defines itself in terms of a possibility which it is and somehow understands in its being. That is the formal meaning of the constitution of the existence of Da-sein. But for the ontological interpretation of this being, this means that the problematic of its being* is to be developed out of the existentiality of its existence. However, this cannot mean that Da-sein is to be construed in terms of a concrete possible idea of existence. At the beginning of the analysis, Da-sein is precisely not to be interpreted in the differentiation of a particular existence; rather, to be uncovered in the indifferent way in which it is initially and for the most part. This indifference of the everydayness of Da-sein is not nothing; but rather, a positive phenomenal characteristic. All existing is how it is out of this kind of being, and back into it. We call this everyday indifference of Da-sein averageness. And because average everydayness constitutes the ontic immediacy of this being, it was and will be passed over again and again in the explication of Da-sein. What is ontically nearest and familiar is ontologically the farthest, unrecognized and constantly overlooked in its ontological significance. Augustine asks: "Quid autem propinquius meipso mihi'f' ("But what is closer to me than myself?") And must answer: "Ego certe laboro hie et laboro in meipso: Jactus sum mihi terra difficultatis et sudoris nimii." (Assuredly I labor here and I labor within myself: I have become to myself a land of trouble and inordinate sweat"}} This holds true not only for the ontic and preontological opacity of Da-sein, but to a still higher degree for the ontological task of not only not failing to see this being in its phenomenally nearest kind of being, but of making it accessible in its positive characteristics. But the average everydayness of Da-sein must not be understood as a mere "aspect." In it, too, and even in the mode of inauthenticity, the structure of existentiality lies a priori. In it, too, Da-sein is concerned with a particular mode of its being to which it is related in the way of average everydayness, if only in the way of fleeing .from it and of forgetting it. The explication of Da-sein in its average everydayness, however, does not just give average structures in the sense of a vague indeterminacy. What is ontically in the way of being average can very well be understood ontologically in terms of pregnant structures which are not structurally different
* better: of its understanding of being
42
45
Being and Time
1.1
from the ontological detenninations of an authentic being of Da-sein. All explications arising from an analytic of Da-sein are gained with a view toward its structure of existence. Because these explications are defined in terms of existentiality, we shall call the characteristics of being of Da-sein existentials. They are to be sharply delimited from the determinations of being of those beings unlike Da-sein which we call categories. This expression is taken and retained in its primary ontological signification. As the exemplary basis of its interpretation of being, ancient ontology takes the beings which we encounter within the world. Noein or logos was regarded as the manner of access to those beings. It is there that beings are encountered. The being of these beings, however, must become comprehensible in a distinctive kgein (a letting be seen), so that this being is comprehensible from the very beginning as what it is and already is in every being. In the discussion (logos) of beings, we have always previously addressed ourselves to being; this addressing is kategoreisthai. That means, first of all: to accuse publicly, to say something to someone directly and in front of everyone. Used ontologically, the term means: to say something to a being, so to speak, right in the face, to say what it always already is as a being; that is, to let it be seen for everyone in its being. What is caught sight of in such seeing and what becomes visible are the kategoriai. They include the a priori detenninations of the beings which can be addressed and spoken about in the logos in different ways. Existentil'ls and categories are the two fundamental possibilities of the charactet ;sties of being. The being which corresponds to them requires different ways of primary interrogation. Beings are a who (existence) or else a what (objective presence in the broadest sense). It is only in terms of the clarified horizon of the question of being that we can treat the connection between the two modes of characteristics of being. We intimated in the introduction that a task is furthered in the existential analytic of Da-sein, a task whose urgency is hardly less than that of the question of being itself: the exposition of the a priori which must be visible if the question "What is human being?" is to be discussed philosophically. The existential analytic ofDa-sein is prior to any psychology, anthropology, and especially biology. By being delimited from these possible investigations of Da-sein, the theme of the analytic can become still more sharply defined. Its necessity can thus at the same time be demonstrated more incisively.
10. How the Analytic of Da-sein is to be Distinguished from Anthropology, Psychology, and Biology After a theme for investigation has been initially outlined in positive terms, it is always important to show what is to be ruled out, although it
I.J
Being and Time
43
can easily become unfruitful to discuss what is not going to happen. We must show that all previous questions and investigations* which aim at Da-sein fail to see the real philosophical problem, regardless of their factual productivity. Thus, as long as they persist in this attitude, they may not claim to be able to accomplish what they are fundamentally striving for at all. In distinguishing existential analytic from anthropology, psychology, and biology, we shall confine ourselves to what is in principle the fundamental ontological question. Thus, our distinctions will be of necessity inadequate for a "theory of science" simply because the scientific structure of the above-mentioned disciplines (not the "scientific attitude" of those who are working to further them) has today become completely questionable and needs new impulses which must arise from the ontological problematic. Historiographically, the intention of the existential analytic can be clarified by considering Descartes, to whom one attributes the discovery of the cogito sum as the point of departure for all modern philosophical questioning. He investigates the cogitare of the ego-within certain limits. But the sum he leaves completely undiscussed, even though it is just as primordial as the cogito. Our analytic raises the ontological question of the being of the sum. Only when the sum is defined does the manner of the cogitationes become comprehensible. At the same time, it is of course misleading to exemplify the intention of the analytic historiographically in this way. One of our first tasks will be to show that the point of departure from an initially given ego and subject totally fails to see the phenomenal content of Da-sein. Every idea of a "subject"-unless refined by a previous ontological determination of its basic character-still posits the subjectum (hupokeimenon) ontologically along with it, no matter how energetic one's ontic protestations against the "substantial soul" or the "reification of consciousness." Thingliness itself needs to be demonstrated in terms of its ontological source in order that we can ask what is now to be understood positively by the nonreified being of the subject, the soul, consciousness, the spirit, the person. All these terms name definite areas of phenomena which can be "developed." But they are never used without a remarkable failure to see the need for inquiring about the being of the beings so designated. Thus we are not being terminologically idiosyncratic when we avoid these terms as well as the expressions "life" and "human being" in designating the beings that we ourselves are. On the other hand, if we understand it correctly, in any serious and scientifically minded "philosophy of life" (this expression says about
* They did not aim at Da-sein at all.
46
44
47
48
Being and Time
1.1
as much as the "botany of plants") there lies an inexplicit tendency toward understanding the being of Da-sein. * What strikes us first of all in such a philosophy (and this is its fundamentallack)t is that "life" itself as a kind of being does not become a problem ontologically. W. Dilthey's investigations are motivated and sustained by the perennial question of "life." Starting from "life" itself as a whole, he attempts to understand its "experiences" in their structural and developmental interconnections. What is philosophically relevant about his "humanistic psychology" is not to be found in the fact that it is no longer oriented toward psychic elements and atoms and no longer tries to piece together the life of the soul, but rather aims at the "whole of life" and "gestalt." Rather, it is to be found in the fact that in the midst of all this he was, above all, on the way to the question of "life." It is true that we can see here very plainly the limits of his problematic and of the set of concepts with which it had to be expressed. But along with Dilthey and Bergson, all the directions of "personalism" and all tendencies toward a philosophical anthropology influenced by them share these limits. The phenomenological interpretation of personality is in principle more radical and transparent; but it does not reach the dimension of the question of being in Da-sein, either. Despite all their differences in questioning, development, and orientation of their worldviews, the interpretations of personality found in Husserl2 and Scheler agree in what is negative. They no longer ask the question about the "being of the person." We choose Scheler's interpretation as an example, not only because it is accessible in print,' but because he explicitly emphasizes the being of the person as such, and attempts to define it by defining the specific being of acts as opposed to everything "psychical." According to Scheler, the person can never be thought as a thing or a substance. Rather it is "the immediately co-experienced unity of ex-periencing-not just a thing merely thought behind and outside of what is immediately experienced. "4 The person is not a thinglike substantial being. Furthermore, the being of the person cannot consist in being a subject of rational acts that have a certain lawfulness. The person is not a thing, not a substance, not an object. Here Scheler emphasizes the same thing which HusserP is getting at when he requires for the unity of the person a constitution essentially different from that of things of nature. What Scheler says of the person, he applies to acts as well. "An act is never also an object, for it is the nature of the being of acts only to be experienced in the process itself and given in reflection. "6 Acts are nonpsychical. Essentially the person exists *no! Not only that, but the question of truth is totally and essentially inadequate.
t
I.I
Being and Time
45
only in carrying out intentional acts, and is thus essentially not an object. Every psychical objectification, and thus every comprehension of acts as something psychical, is identical with depersonalization. In any case, the person is given as the agent of intentional acts which are connected by the unity of a meaning. Thus psychical being has nothing to do with being a person. Acts are carried out, the person carries them out. But what is the ontological meaning of "carrying out," how is the kind of being of the person to be defined in an ontologically positive way? But the critical question cannot stop at this. The question is about the being of the whole human being, whom one is accustomed to understand as a bodily-soul-like-spiritual unity. Body, soul, spirit might designate areas of phenomena which are thematically separable for the sake of determinate investigations; within certain limits their ontological indeterminancy might not be so important. But in the question of the being of human being, this cannot be summarily calculated in terms of the kinds of being of body, soul, and spirit which have yet first to be defined. And even for an ontological attempt which is to proceed in this way, some idea of the being of the whole would have to be presupposed. But what obstructs or misleads the basic question of the being of Da-sein is the orientation thoroughly colored by the anthropology of Christianity and the ancient world, whose inadequate ontological foundations personalism and the philosophy of life also ignore. Traditional anthropology contains the following: 1. The definition of human being: zoon logon echon in the interpretation: animal rationale, rational life. The kind of being of the zoon, however, is understood here in the sense of occurring and being objectively present. The logos is a higher endowment whose kind of being remains just as obscure as that of the being so pieced together. 2. The other guideline for the determination of the being and essence of human being is a theological one: kai eipen ho theos. Po~amen anthri)jJon kat' eikona hemeteran kai kath' homoiasin; faciamu.s hominem ad imaginem nostram et similitudinem nostram. 7 From this, Christian theological anthropology, taking over the ancient definition, gets an interpretation of the being we call human being. But just as the being of God is ontologically interpreted by means of ancient ontology, so is the being of the ens ftnitum, to an even greater extent. The Christian definition was de-theologized in the course of the modem period. But the idea of "transcendence" -that human being is something that goes beyond itself-has its roots in Christian dogma, which can hardly be said to have ever made an ontological problem of the being of human being. This idea of transcendence, according to which the human being is more than a rational being, has elaborated itself in
49
46
Being and Time
I. I
various transformations. We can illustrate its origin with the following quotations: "His praeclaris dotibus excelluit prima hominis conditio, ut ratio, intelligentia, prudentia, iudicium, non modo ad terrenae vitae gubernationem suppeterent, sed quibus transcenderet usque ad Deum et aeternam Jelititatem." 8 "For the fact that human being looks toward God and His word clearly shows that according to his nature he is born closer to God, is more similar to God, is somehow drawn toward God, that without doubt everything flows from the fact that he is created in the image of God." 9
50
The sources which are relevant for traditional anthropologythe Greek definition and the theological guideline-indicate that, over and above the attempt to determine the essence of "human being" as a being, the question of its being has remained forgotten; rather, this being is understood as something "self-evident" in the sense of the objective presence of other created things. These two guidelines intertwine in modern anthropology, where the res cogitans, consciousness, and the context of experience, serve as the methodical point of departure. But since these cogitationes are also ontologically undetermined, or are again inexplicitly and "self-evidently" taken as something "given" whose "being" is not a matter of question, the anthropological problematic remains undetermined in its decisive ontological foundation. This is no less true of "psychology," whose anthropological tendencies are unmistakable today. Nor can the missing ontological foundations be replaced by building anthropology and psychology into a general biology. In the order of possible understanding and interpretation, biology as the "science of life" is rooted in the ontology of Da-sein, although not exclusively in it. Life has its own kind of being, but it is essentially accessible only in Da-sein. The ontology of life takes place by way of a privative interpretation. It determines what must be the case if there can be anything like just-being-alive. Life is neither pure objective presence, nor is it Da-sein. On the other hand, Da-sein should never be defined ontologically by regarding it as life-( ontologically undetermined) and then as something else on top of that. In suggesting that anthropology, psychology, and biology all fail to give an unequivocal and ontologically adequate answer to the question of the kind of being of this being that we ourselves are, no judgment is being made about the positive work of these disciplines. But, on the other hand, we must continually be conscious of the fact that these ontological foundations can never be disclosed by subsequent hypotheses derived from empirical material. Rather, they are always already "there" even when that empirical material is only collected. The fact that
I. I
Being and Time
47
positivistic investigation does not see these foundations and considers them to be self-evident is no proof of the fact that they do not lie at the basis and are problematic in a more radical sense than any thesis of positivistic science can ever be. 10
11. The Existential Analytic and the Interpretation of Primitive Da-sein: The Difficulties in Securing a "Natural Concept of the World" The interpretation of Da-sein in its everydayness, however, is not identical with describing a primitive stage of Da-sein, with which we can become acquainted empirically through the medium of anthropology. Everydayness is not the same thing as primitiveness. Rather, everydayness is also and precisely a kind of being of Da-sein, even when Da-sein moves in a highly developed and differentiated culture. On the other hand, primitive Da-sein also has its possibility of noneveryday being, and it has its own specific everydayness. To orient the analysis of Da-sein toward "the life of primitive peoples" can have a positive methodical significance in that "primitive phenomena" are often less hidden and complicated by extensive self-interpretation on the part of the Da-sein in question. Primitive Da-sein often speaks out of a more primordial absorption in "phenomena" (in the pre-phenomenological sense). The conceptuality which appears to be clumsy and crude to us can be of use positively for a genuine elaboration of the ontological structures of phenomena. But up until now our information about primitive peoples has been provided by ethnology. And ethnology already moves in certain preliminary concepts and interpretations of human being in general, beginning with the initial "collection" of its materials, its findings and elaborations. We do not know whether commonplace psychology or even scientific psychology and sociology, which the ethnologist beings with him, offer any scientific guarantee for an adequate possibility of access, interpretation, and mediation of the phenomena to be investigated. The situation here is the same as with the disciplines mentioned before. Ethnology itself already presupposes an adequate analytic of Da-sein as its guideline. But since the positivistic sciences neither "can" nor should wait for the ontological work of philosophy, the continuation of research will not be accomplished as "progress"; but, rather, as the repetition and the ontologically more transparent purification of what has been ontically discovered. 11 Although the formal differentiation of the ontological problematic as opposed to antic investigation may seem easy, the development and above all the beginning of an existential analytic of Da-sein is not without
51
52
48
Being and Time
1.1
difficulties. A need is contained in this task which has made philosophy uneasy* for a long time, but philosophy fails again and again in fulfilling the task: the development of the idea of a "natural concept of the world. " The wealth of knowledge of the most exotic and manifold cultures and forms of existence available today seems favorable to taking up this task in a fruitful way. But that is only an illusion. Fundamentally, this plethora of information seduces us into failing to see the real problem. The syncretistic comparison and classification of everything does not of itself give us genuine essential knowledge. Subjecting the manifold to tabulation does not guarantee a real understanding of what has been ordered. The genuine principle of order has its own content which is never found by ordering, but is rather already presupposed in ordering. Thus the explicit idea of world as such is a prerequisite for the order of world images. And if "world" itself is constitutive of Da-sein, the conceptual development of the phenomenon of world requires an insight into the fundamental structures of Da-sein. The positive characteristics and negative considerations of this chapter aimed at directing the understanding of the tendency and question of the following interpretation to the right path. Ontology can only contribute indirectly to the furtherance of existing positivistic disciplines. It has a goal of its own, provided that the question of being is the spur for all scientific search over and above the acquisition of information about beings. *Not at all! The concept of world is not understood at all.
II Being-in-the-World in General as the Fundamental Constitution of Da-sein
12. A Preliminary Sketch of Being-in-the-World in Terms of the Orientation toward Being-in as Such In the preparatory discussions (section 9) we already proflled characteristics of being which are to provide us with a steady light for our further investigation, but which at the same time receive their structural concretion in this investigation. Da-sein is a being which is related understandingly in its being toward that being. In saying this we are calling attention to the formal concept of existence. Da-sein exists. Furthermore, Da-sein is the being which I myself always am. Mineness belongs to existing Da-sein as the condition of the possibility of authenticity and inauthenticity. Da-sein exists always in one of these modes, or else in the modal indifference to them. These determinations of being of Da-sein, however, must now be seen and understood a priori as grounded upon that constitution of being which we call being-in-the-world. The correct point of departure of the analytic of Da-sein consists in the interpretation of this constitution. The compound expression "being-in-the-world" indicates, in the very way we have coined it, that it stands for a unifzed phenomenon. This primary datum must be seen as a whole. But while being-in-theworld cannot be broken up into components that may be pieced together, this does not prevent it from having several constitutive structural factors. The phenomenal fact indicated by this expression actu-
49
53
50
Being and Time
1.11
ally gives us a threefold perspective. If we pursue it while keeping the whole phenomenon in mind from the outset we have the following: 1. "In-the-world": In relation to this factor, we have the task of questioning the ontological structure of "world" and of defining the idea of worldliness as such (cf. chapter 3 of this division). 2. The being which always is in the way of being-in-the-world. In it we are looking for what we are questioning when we ask about the "who?". In our phenomenological demonstration we should be able to determine who is in the mode of average everydayness of Da-sein (cf. chapter 4 of this division). 3. Being in as such: The ontological constitution of in-ness itself is to be analyzed (cf. chapter 5 of this division). Any analysis of one of these constitutive factors involves the analysis of the others; that is, each time seeing the whole phenomenon. It is true that being-in-the-world is an a priori necessary constitution of Da-sein, but it is not at all sufficient to fully determine Da-sein's being. Before we thematically analyze the three phenomena indicated individually, we shall attempt to orient ourselves toward a characteristic of the third of these constitutive factors.
54
What does being-in mean? Initially, we supplement the expression being-in with the phrase "in the world," and are inclined to understand this being-in as "being-in something." With this term, the kind of being of a being is named which is "in" something else, as water is "in" the glass, the dress is "in" the closet. By this "in" we mean the relation of being that two beings extended "in" space have to each other with regard to their location in that space. Water and glass, dress and closet, are both "in" space "at" a location in the same way. This relation of being can be expanded; that is, the bench in the lecture hall, the lecture hall in the university, the university in the city, and so on until: the bench in "world space." These beings whose being "in" one another can be determined in this way all have the same kind of being-that of being objectively present-as things occurring "within" the world. The objective presence "in" something objectively present, the being objectively present together with something having the same kind of being in the sense of a definite location relationship are ontological characteristics which we call categorial. They belong to beings whose kind of being is unlike Da-sein. In contrast, being-in designates a constitution of being of Dasein, and is an existential. But we cannot understand by this the objective presence of a material thing (the human body) "in" a being objectively present. Nor does the term being-in designate a spatial "in one another"
1.11
Being and Time
51
of two things objectively present, any more than the word "in" primordially means a spatial relation of this kind. 1 "In" stems from innan-, to live, habitare, to dwell. "An" means I am used to, familiar with, I take care of something. It has the meaning of colo in the sense of habito and diligo. We characterized this being to whom being-in belongs in this meaning as the being which I myself always am. The expression "bin" is connected with "bei." "Ich bin" (I am) means I dwell, I stay near ... the world as something familiar in such and such a way. Being* as the infinitive of "I am": that is, understood as an existential, means to dwell near ... , to be familiar with .... Being-in is thus the formal existential expression of the being of Da-seint which has the essential constitution of being-in theworld. "Being together with" the world, in the sense of being absorbed in the world, which must be further interpreted, is an existential which is grounded in being-in. Because we are concerned in these analyses with seeing a primordial structure of being of Da-sein in accordance with whose phenomenal content the concepts of being must be articulated, and because this structure is fundamentally incomprehensible in terms of the traditional ontological categories, this "being together with" must also be examined more closely. We shall again choose the method of contrasting it with something essentially ontologically different-that is, a categorical relation of being which we express linguistically with the same means. Fundamental ontological distinctions are easily obliterated; and if they are to be envisaged phenomenally in this way, this must be done explicitly, even at the risk of discussing something "obvious." The status of the ontological analytic, however, shows that we do not at all have these "obvious" matters adequately "in our grasp," still less have we interpreted them in the meaning of their being; and we are even farther from possessing the proper structural concepts in a secure form. As an existential, "being with" the world never means anything like the being-objectively-present-together of things that occur. There is no such thing as the "being next to each other" of a being called "Dasein" with another being called "world." It is true that, at times, we are accustomed to express linguistically the being together of two objectively present things in such a manner: "The table stands 'next to' the door," "The chair 'touches' the wall." Strictly speaking, we can never talk about "touching," not because in the last analysis we can always find a space between the chair and the wall by examining it more closely, but because in principle the chair can never touch the wall, even if the
* "To be" is also the infinitive of the "is": a being is. t
But not of being in general and not at all of being itself-absolutely.
55
52
56
Being and Time
I.n
space between them amounted to nothing. The presupposition for this would be that the wall could be encountered "by" the chair. A being can only touch an objectively present being within the world if it fundamentally has the kind of being of being-in-only if with its Da-sein something like world is already discovered in terms of which beings can reveal themselves through touch and thus become accessible in their objective presence. Two beings which are objectively present within the world and are, moreover, worldless in themselves, can never "touch" each other, neither can "be" "together with" the other. The supplement "which are moreover worldless" must not be left out, because those beings which are not worldless, for example Da-sein itself, are objectively present "in" the world, too. More precisely, they can be understood within certain limits and with a certain justification as something merely objectively present. To do this, one must completely disregard or just not see the existential constitution of being-in. But with this possible understanding of "Da-sein" as something objectively present, and only objectively present, we may not attribute to Da-sein its own kind of "objective presence." This objective presence does not become accessible by disregarding the specific structures of Da-sein, but only in a previous understanding of them. Da-sein understands its ownmost being in the sense of a certain "factual objective presence. "2 And yet the "factuality" of the fact of one's own Da-sein is ontologically totally different from the factual occurrence of a kind of stone. The factuality of the fact Da-sein, as the way in which every Da-sein actually is, we call its facticity. The complicated structure of this determination of being is itself comprehensible as a problem only in the light of the existential fundamental constitutions of Da-sein which we have already worked out. The concept of facticity implies that an "innetworldly" being has being-in-the-world in such a way that it can understand itself as bound up in its "destiny" with the being of those beings which it encounters within its own world. Initially it is only a matter of seeing the ontological distinction between being-in as an existential and the category of the "insideness" that things objectively present can have with regard to one another. If we define being-in in this way, we are not denying to Da-sein every kind of "spatiality." On the contrary. Da-sein itself has its own "being-in-space," which in its tum is possible only on the basis of being-in-the-world in general. Thus, being-in cannot be clarified ontologically by an ontic characteristic, by saying for example: being-in in a world is a spiritual quality and the "spatiality" of human being is an attribute of its bodiliness which is always at the same time "based on" corporeality. Then we again have to do with a being-objectively-present-together of a spiritual thing thus constituted with a corporeal thing, and the being of the beings thus compounded is more obscure than ever. The understanding of being-in-the-world as an
1.11
Being and Time
53
essential structure of Da-sein first makes possible the insight into its existential spatiality. This insight will keep us from failing to see this structure or from previously cancelling it out, a procedure motivated not ontologically, but "metaphysically" in the naive opinion that human being is initially a spiritual thing which is then subsequently placed "in" a space. With its facticity, the being-in-the-world of Da-sein is already dispersed in definite ways of being-in, perhaps even split up. The multiplicity of these kinds of being-in can be indicated by the following examples: to have to do with something, to produce, order and take care of something, to use something, to give something up and let it get lost, to undertake, to accomplish, to find out, to ask about, to observe, to speak about, to determine .... These ways of being-in have the kind of being of taking care of which we shall characterize in greater detail. The deficient modes of omitting, neglecting, renouncing, resting, are also ways of taking care of something, in which the possibilities of taking care are kept to a "bare minimum." The term "taking care" has initially its prescientific meaning and can imply: carrying something out, settling something, "to straighten it out." The expression could also mean to take care of something in the sense of "getting it for oneself." Furthermore, we use the expression also in a characteristic tum of phrase: I will see to it or take care that the enterprise fails. Here "to take care" amounts to apprehensiveness. In contrast to these prescientific ontic meanings, the expression "taking care" is used in this inquiry as an ontological term (an existential) to designate the being of a possible being-in-the-world. We do not choose this term because Da-sein is initially economical and "practical" to a large extent, but because the being of Da-sein itself is to be made visible as care. Again, this expression is to be understood as an ontological structure concept (compare chapter 6 of this division). The expression has nothing to do with "distress," "melancholy," or "the cares of life" which can be found ontically in every Da-sein. These-like their opposites, "carefreeness" and "gaiety"-are ontically possible only because Dasein, ontologically understood, is care. Because being-in-theworld belongs essentially to Da-sein, its being toward the world is essentially taking care.* According to what we have said, being-in is not a "quality" which Da-sein sometimes has and sometimes does not have, without which it could be just as well as it could with it. It is not the case that human being "is," and then on top of that has a relation of being to the "world" which it sometimes takes upon itself. Da-sein is never "initially" a sort of
*Human being [Mensch-sein] here equated with Da-sein.
57
54
58
Being and Time
1.11
a being which is free from being-in, but which at times is in the mood to take up a "relation" to the world. This taking up of relations to the world is possible only because, as being-in-the-world, Da-sein is as it is. This constitution of being is not first derived from the fact that besides the being which has the character of Da-sein there are other beings which are objectively present and meet up with it. These other beings can only "meet up" "with" Da-sein because they are able to show themselves of their own accord within a world. The saying used so often today "Human beings have their environment" does not say anything ontologically as long as this "having" is undetermined. In its very possibility this "having" has its foundation in the existential constitution of being-in. As a being essentially existing in this way, Da-sein can explicitly discover beings which it encounters in the environment, can know about them, can avail itself of them, can have "world." The ontically trivial talk about "having an environment" is ontologically a problem. To solve it requires nothing less than defining the being of Da-sein beforehand in an ontologically adequate way. If in biology use has been made of this constitution of being-especially since K. E. von Baer-one must not conclude that its philosophical use implies "biologism." For as a positive science, biology, too, can never find and determine this structure, it must presuppose it and continually make use of it.* This structure itself, however, can be explicated philosophically as the a priori condition for the thematic objects of biology only if it is understood beforehand as a structure of Da-sein. Only in terms of an orientation toward the ontological structure thus understood, can "life" as a constitution of being be defined a priori in a privative way. Ontically, as well as ontologically, being-in-the-world has priority as taking care. This structure gets its fundamental interpretation in the analytic of Da-sein. But does not this determination of the constitution of being discussed up to now move exclusively in negative statements? Though this being-in is supposedly so fundamental, we always keep hearing what it is not. Indeed. But the prevalence of negative characteristics is no accident. Rather it makes known what is peculiar to this phenomenon, and is thus positive in a genuine sense-a sense appropriate to the phenomenon itself. The phenomenological demonstration of being-in-theworld has the character of rejecting distortions and obfuscations because this phenomenon is always already "seen" in every Da-sein in a certain way. And that is true because it makes up a fundamental constitution of Da-sein, in that it is always already disclosed, along with its being, for the understanding of being in Da-sein. But the phenomenon has mostly
* Is one justified in speaking of "world" here at all? Only surroundings ( Umge· bung). "Having" corresponds to this "giving." Da-sein never "has" world.
1.11
Being and Time
55
been basically misinterpreted, or interpreted in an ontologically inadequate way.* However, this "seeing in a certain way and yet mostly misinterpreting" is itself based on nothing other than this constitution of being of Da-sein itself. In accordance with that constitution, Da-sein understands itself-and that means also its being-in-the-world-ontologically in terms of those beings and their being which it itself is not, but which it encounters "within" its world.t Both in Da-sein and for it, this constitution of being is always already somehow familiar. If it is now to be recognized, the explicit cognition that this task implies takes itself(as a knowing of the world) as the exemplary relation of the "soul" to the world. The cognition of world (noein)-or addressing oneself to the "world" and discussing it (logos)-thus functions as the primary mode of being-in-the-world even though being-in-the-world is not understood as such. But because this structure of being remains ontologically inaccessible, yet is ontically experienced as the "relation" between one being (world) and another (soul), and because being is initially understood by taking being as innerworldly beings for one's ontological support, one tries to conceive the relation between world and soul as grounded in these two beings and in the sense of their being; that is, as objective presence. Although it is experienced and known prephenomenologically, beingin-the-world is invisible if one interprets it in a way that is ontologically inadequate. One is just barely acquainted with this constitution of Dasein only in the form given by an inadequate interpretation-and indeed, as something obvious. In this way it then becomes the "evident" point of departure for the problems of epistemology or a "metaphysics of knowledge." For what is more obvious than the fact that a "subject" is related to an "object" and the other way around? This "subject-object-relation" must be presupposed. But that is a presupposition which, although it is inviolate in its own facticity, is truly fatal, perhaps for that very reason, if its ontological necessity and especially its ontological meaning are left in obscurity. Thus the phenomenon of being-in has for the most part been represented exclusively by a single exemplar-knowing the world. This has not only been the case in epistemology; for even practical behavior has been understood as behavior which is not theoretical and "atheoretical." Because knowing has been given this priority, our understanding of its ownmost kind of being is led astray, and thus being-in-the-world must be delineated more precisely with reference to knowing the world, and must itself be made visible as an existential "modality" of being-in.
* Yes. As far as being goes, it is not at all. t
A subsequent interpretation.
59
56
Being and Time
1.11
13. The Exemplification of Being-in in a Founded Mode: Knowing the World
60
If being-in-the-world is a fundamental constitution of Da-sein, and one in which it moves not only in general but especially in the mode of everydayness, it must always already have been experienced ontically. It would be incomprehensible if it were totally veiled, especially since Da-sein has an understanding of its own being at its disposal, no matter how indeterminately that understanding functions. However, no sooner was the "phenomenon of knowing the world" understood than it was interpreted in an "external" formal way. The evidence for this is the interpretation of knowledge, still prevalent today, as a "relation between subject and object" which contains about as much "truth" as it does vacuity. But subject and object are not the same as Da-sein and world.* Even if it were feasible to give an ontological definition of being-in primarily in terms of being-in-the-world that knows, the first task required would still be the phenomenal characterization of knowing as a being in and toward the world. But if one thinks about this relation of being, one first has a being, called nature, as that which is known. Knowing itself is not ~o be found in this being. If knowing "is" at all, it belongs solely to those beings which know. But even in those beings, the things called human beings, knowing is not objectively present. In any case, it can not be ascertained externally like corporeal qualities. In that knowing belongs to these beings and is not an external characteristic, it must be "inside." The more unequivocally we bear in mind that knowing is initially and really "inside," and indeed has by no means the kind of being of physical and psychic beings, the more we believe that we are proceeding without presuppositions in the question of the essence of knowledge and of the clarification of the relation between subject and object. For only then can the problem arise of how this knowing subject comes out of its inner "sphere" into one that is "other and external," of how knowing can have an object at all, and of how the object itself is to be thought so that eventually the subject knows it without having to venture a leap into another sphere. But in this approach, which has many variations, the question of the kind of being of this knowing subject is completely omitted, though its way of being was always included tacidy in the theme when we spoke of its knowing. Of course, we are sometimes assured that the subject's inside and its "inner sphere" is certainly not to be thought as a kind of a "box" or "cabinet." But what the positive meaning is of the "inside" of immanence in which knowing is initially
* Certainly not. So little that even rejecting this by putting them together is already fatal.
1.11
Being and Time
57
enclosed, and how the character of being of this "being inside" of knowing is founded in the kind of being of the subject, about this there is silence. However this inner sphere might be interpreted, if one asks how knowing gets "out" of it and achieves a "transcendence," it becomes evident that the knowing which presents such enigmas remains problematical unless one has first clarified how it is and what it is. With this kind of approach one is blind to what was already implicitly implied in the preliminary thematization of the phenomenon of knowing. Knowing is a mode of being of Da-sein as being-in-the-world, and has its ontic foundation in this constitution of being. But if, as we suggest, we thus find phenomenally that knowing is a kind of being of being-in-the-world, one might object that with such an interpretation of knowing, the problem of knowledge is annihilated. What is there left to ask about if one presupposes that knowing is already together with its world which it is, after all, flt'St supposed to reach in the transcending of the subject? Apart from the fact that in the question just formulated, the "standpoint"-which is again not demonstrated phenomenally but is rather constructivist-makes its appearance, what criterion then decides whether and in which sense there is to be a problem of knowledge other than that of the phenomenon of knowing itself and the kind of being of the knower? If we now ask what shows itself in the phenomenal findings of knowing, we must remember that knowing itself is grounded beforehand in already-being-in-the-world which essentially constitutes the being ofDa-sein. Initially, this already-being-with is not solely a rigid staring at something merely objectively present. Being-in-the-world, as taking care of things, is taken in by the world which it takes care of. In order for knowing to be possible as determining by observation what is objectively present, there must first be a deficiency of having to do with the world and taking care of it. In refraining from all production, manipulation, and so on, taking care of things places itself in the only mode of being-in which is left over, in the mode of simply lingering with.... On the basis of this kind of being toward the world which lets us encounter beings within the world solely in their mere outward appearance (eidos), and as a mode of this kind of being, looking explicitly at something thus encountered is possible.* This looking at is always a way of assuming a definite direction toward something, a glimpse of what is objectively present. It takes over a "perspective" from the beings thus encountered from the very beginning. This looking itself becomes a mode of
* Looking at does not occur merely by looking away. Looking at has its own origin and has looking away as its necessary consequence. Looking has its own primordiality. Looking at the eidos requires something different.
61
58
62
Being and Time
l.n
independent dwelling together with beings in the world. In this "dwelling"-as the refusal of every manipulation and use-the perception of what is objectively present takes place. Perception takes place as addressing and discussing something as something. On the foundation of this interpretation in the broadest sense, perception becomes definition. What is perceived and defined can be expressed in propositions and as thus expressed can be maintained and preserved. This perceptive retention of a proposition about ... is itself a way of being-in-the-world, and must not be interpreted as a "procedure" by which a subject gathers representations about something for itself which then remain stored up "inside" as thus appropriated, and in reference to which the question can arise at times of how they "correspond" with reality. In directing itself toward ... and in grasping something, Da-sein does not first go outside of the inner sphere in which it is initially encapsulated, but, rather, in its primary kind of being, it is always already "outside" together with some being encountered in the world already discovered. Nor is any inner sphere abandoned when Da-sein dwells together with a being to be known and determines its character. Rather, even in this "being outside" together with its object, Da-sein is "inside," correctly understood; that is, it itself exists as the being-in-the-world which knows. Again, the perception of what is known does not take place as a return with one's booty to the "cabinet" of consciousness after one has gone out and grasped it. Rather, in perceiving, preserving, and retaining, the Da-sein that knows remains outside as Da-sein. In "mere" knowledge about a context of the being of beings, in "only" representing it, in "solely" "thinking" about it, I am no less outside in the world together with beings than I am when I originally grasp them. Even forgetting something, when every relation of being to what was previously known seems to be extinguished, must be understood as a modifuation of primordial being-in, and this holds true for every deception and every error. The foundational context shown for the mode of being-in-theworld constitutive for the knowledge of the world makes the following clear: in knowing, Da-sein gains a new perspective of being toward the world always already discovered in Da-sein. This new possibility of being can be independently developed. It can become a task, and as scientific knowledge can take over the guidance for being-in-the-world. But knowing neither first creates a "commercium" of the subject with the world, nor does this commercium originate from an effect of the world on a subject. Knowing is a mode of Da-sein which is founded in being-in-theworld. Thus, being-in-the-world, as a fundamental constitution, requires a prior interpretation.
III
63
The Worldliness of the World
14. The Idea of the Worldliness of the World in General
First of all, being-in-the-world is to be made visible with regard to the structural factor "world." The accomplishment of this task appears to be easy and so trivial that we still believe we may avoid it. What can it mean, to describe "the world" as a phenomenon? It means letting what shows itself in the "beings" within the world be seen. Thus, the first step is to enumerate the things which are "in" the world: houses, trees, people, mountains, stars. We can describe the "outward appearance" of these beings and tell of the events occurring with them. But that is obviously a pre-phenomenological "business" which cannot be phenomenologically relevant at all. The description gets stuck in beings. It is ontic. But we are, after all, seeking being. We formally defined "phenomenon" in the phenomenological sense as that which shows itself as being and the structure of being. Thus, to describe the "world" phenomenologically means to show and determine the being of beings objectively present in the world conceptually and categorially. Beings within the world are things, natural things and "valuable" things. Their thingliness becomes a problem. And since the thingliness of the latter is based upon natural thingliness, the being of natural things, nature as such, is the primary theme. The character of being of natural things, of substances, which is the basis of everything, is substantiality. What constitutes its ontological meaning? Now we have given our investigation an unequivocal direction. But are we asking ontologically about the "world"? The problematic characterized is undoubtably ontological. But even if it succeeds in
59
60
64
Being and Time
l.m
the purest explication of the being of nature, in comparison with the fundamental statements made by the mathematical natural sciences about this being, this ontology never gets at the phenomenon of the "world." Nature is itself a being which is encountered within the world and is discoverable on various paths and stages. Should we accordingly keep to the beings with which Da-sein initially and for the most part dwells, to "valuable" things? Do not these things "really" show the world in which we live? Perhaps they do in fact show something like "world" more penetratingly. But these things are, after all, also beings "within" the world. Neither the ontic description of innenvorldly beings nor the ontological interpretation of the being of these beings gets as such at the phenomenon of "world." In both kinds of access to "objective being," "world" is already "presupposed" in various ways. Can "world" ultimately not be addressed as a determination of the beings mentioned at all? But, after all, we do say that these beings are innerworldly. Is "world" indeed a character of being of Da-sein? And then does every Da-sein "initially" have its own world? Doesn't "world" thus become something "subjective"? Then how is a "common" world still possible "in" which we, after all, are? If we pose the question of"world," which world is meant? Neither this nor that world, but rather the worldliness of world in general. How can we encounter this phenomenon? "Worldliness" is an ontological concept and designates the structure of a constitutive factor of being-in-the-world. But we have come to know being-in-the-world as an existential determination of Da-sein. Accordingly, worldliness is itself an existential. When we inquire ontologically about the "world," we by no means abandon the thematic field of the analytic of Da-sein. "World" is ontologically not a determination of those beings which Da-sein essentially is not, but rather a characteristic of Da-sein itself. This does not preclude the fact that the path of the investigation of the phenomenon of "world" must be taken by way of innerworldly beings and their being. The task of a phenomenological "description" of the world is so far from obvious that its adequate determination already requires essential ontological clarification. The multiplicity of meanings of the word "world" is striking now that we have discussed it and made frequent application of it. Unraveling this multiplicity can point toward the phenomena intended in their various meanings and their connection. 1. World is used as an ontic concept and signifies the totality of beings which can be objectively present within the world. 2. World functions as an ontological term and signifies the being of those beings named in 1. Indeed, "world" can name the region which
I.m
Being and Time
61
embraces a multiplicity of beings. For example, when we speak of the "world" of the mathematician, we mean the region of all possible mathematical objects. 3. Again, world can be understood in an ontic sense, but not as beings essentially unlike Da-sein that can be encountered within the world; but, rather, as that "in which" a factical Da-sein "lives." Here world has a pre-ontological, existentiell meaning. There are various possibilities here: world can mean the "public" world of the we or one's "own" and nearest (in the home) surrounding world. 4. Finally, world designates the ontological and existential concept of worldliness. Worldliness itself can be modified into the respective structural totality of particular "worlds," and contains the a priori of worldliness in general. We shall reserve the expression world as a tenn for the meaning established in 3. If we use it at times in the first meaning, we shall put it in quotation marks. Thus, tenninologically "worldly" means a kind of being of Da-sein, never a kind of being of something objectively present "in" the world. We shall call the latter something belonging* to the world, or innerworldly. One look at traditional ontology shows us that one skips over the phenomenon of worldliness when one fails to see the constitution of Dasein of being-in-the-world. Instead, one tries to interpret the world in tenns of the being of the being which is objectively present within the world but has not, however, even been initially discovered-in terms of nature. t Ontologically and categorially understood, nature is a boundary case of the being of possible innerworldly beings. Da-sein can discover beings as nature only in a definite mode of its being-in-the-world. This kind of knowledge has the character of a certain "de-worlding" of the world. As the categorial content of structures of being of a definite being encountered in the world, "nature" can never render worldliness intelligible.! But even the phenomenon "nature," for instance in the sense of the Romantic concept of nature, is ontologically comprehensible only in tenns of the concept of world; that is, in terms of an analytic ofDa-sein. With regard to the problem of an ontological analysis of the worldliness of the world, traditional ontology is at a dead-end-if it sees the problem at all. On the other hand, an interpretation of the worldliness of Da-sein and its possibilities and ways of becoming worldly, must show
* It is just Da-sein that obeys and listens to the world (welthiirig). "Nature" in the Kantian concept in the sense of modem physics. t Rather, the other way around!
t
65
62
66
Being and Time
I.JJJ
why Da-sein skips over the phenomenon of worldliness ontically and ontologically in its way of knowing the world. But at the same time this fact of skipping over the phenomenon of worldliness indicates that special measures are necessary in order to gain the correct phenomenal point of departure for access to that phenomenon, a point of departure which does not permit any skipping over. The methodological directive for this has already been given. Being-in-the-world and thus the world as well must be the subject of our analytic in the horizon of average everydayness as the nearest kind of being ofDa-sein. We shall pursue everyday being-in-the-world. With it as a phenomenal support, something like world must come into view. The nearest world of everyday Da-sein is the surrounding world. Our investigation will follow the path from this existential character of average being-in-the-world to the idea of worldliness as such. We shall seek the worldliness of the surrounding world (environmentality) by way of an ontological interpretation of those beings initially encountered within the surroundings. The expression surrounding world contains a reference to spatiality in its component "around." The quality of "around" which is constitutive for the surrounding world does not, however, have a primarily "spatial" meaning. Rather, the spatial character which uncontestably belongs to a surrounding world can be clarified only on the basis of the structure of worldliness. Here the spatiality of Da-sein mentioned in section 12 becomes phenomenally visible. But ontology has tried precisely to interpret the being of the "world" as res extensa on the basis of spatiality. The most extreme tendency toward such an ontology of the "world," oriented in opposition to the res cogitans which is neither ontically nor ontologically identical with Da-sein, is to be found in Descartes. The analysis of worldliness attempted here becomes clearer if we show how it differs from such an ontological tendency. It has three stages: (A) An analysis of environmentality and worldliness in general. (B) An illustrative contrast between our analysis of worldliness and Descartes' ontology of the "world." (C) The aroundness of the surrounding world and the "spatiality" of Da-sein.
A.
ANALYSIS OF ENVIRONMENTALITY AND WORLDLINESS IN GENERAL
15. The Being of Beings Encountered in the Surrounding World
67
The phenomenological exhibition of the being of beings encountered nearest to us can be accomplished under the guidance of the everyday being-in-the-world, which we also call association in the world with innerworldly beings. Associations are already dispersed in manifold ways of
1.111
Being and Time
63
taking care of things. However, as we showed, the nearest kind of association is not mere perceptual cognition, but, rather, a handling, using, and taking care of things which has its own kind of "knowledge." Our phenomenological question is initially concerned with the being of those beings encountered when taking care of something. A methodical remark is necessary to secure the kind of seeing required here. In the disclosure and explication of being, beings are always our preliminary and accompanying theme. The real theme is being. What shows itself in taking care of things in the surrounding world constitutes the pre-thematic being in the domain of our analysis. This being is not the object of a theoretical "world"-cognition; it is what is used, produced, and so on. As a being thus encountered, it comes pre-thematically into view for a "knowing" which, as a phenomenological knowing, primarily looks toward being and on the basis of this thematization of being thematizes actual beings as well. Thus, this phenomenological interpretation is not a cognition of existent qualities of beings; but, rather, a determination of the structure of their being. But as an investigation of being it independently and explicitly brings about the understanding of being which always already belongs to Da-sein and is "alive" in every association with beings. Phenomenologically pre-thematic beings, what is used and produced, become accessible when we put ourselves in the place of taking care of things in the world. Strictly speaking, to talk of putting ourselves in the place of taking care is misleading. We do not first need to put ourselves in the place of this way of being in associating with and taking care of things. Everyday Da-sein always already is in this way; for example, in opening the door, I use the doorknob. Gaining phenomenological access to the beings thus encountered consists rather in rejecting the interpretational tendencies crowding and accompanying us which cover over the phenomenon of "taking care" of things in general, and thus even more so beings as they are encountered of their own accord in taking care. These insidious mistakes become clear when we ask: Which beings are to be our preliminary theme and established as a pre-phenomenal basis? We answer: things. But perhaps we have already missed the prephenomenal basis we are looking for with this self-evident answer. For an unexpressed anticipatory ontological characterization is contained in addressing beings as "things" (res). An analysis which starts with such beings and goes on to inquire about being comes up with thingliness and reality. Ontological explication thus finds, as it proceeds, characteristics of being such as substantiality, materiality, extendedness, side-bysideness. . . . But the beings encountered and taken care of are also pre-ontologically hidden at first in this being. When one designates things as the beings that are "initially given" one goes astray ontologi-
68
64
69
Being and Time
1.111
cally, although one means something else ontically. What one really means remains indefinite. Or else one characterizes these "things" as "valuable." What does value mean ontologically? How is this "having" value and being involved with value to be understood categorially? Apart from the obscurity of this structure of having value, is the phenomenal character of being of what is encountered and taken care of in association thus attained? The Greeks had an appropriate term for "things": pragmata, that is, that with which one has to do in taking care of things in association (praxis). But the specifically "pragmatic" character of the pragmata is just what was left in obscurity and "initially" determined as "mere things."* We shall call the beings encountered in taking care useful things. In association we find things for writing, things for sewing, things for working, driving, measuring. We must elucidate the kind of being of useful things. This can be done following the guideline of the previous definition of what makes useful thing a useful thing: usable material. Strictly speaking, there "is" no such thing as a useful thing. There always belongs to the being of a useful thing a totality of useful things in which this useful thing can be what it is. A useful thing is essentially "something in order to ...". The different kinds of "in order to" such as serviceability, helpfulness, usability, handiness, constitute a totality of useful things. The structure of "in order to" contains a reference of something to something. Only in the following analyses can the phenomenon indicated by this word be made visible in its ontological genesis. At this time, our task is to bring a multiplicity of references phenomenally into view. In accordance with their character of being usable material, useful things always are in terms of their belonging to other useful things: writing materials, pen, ink, paper, desk blotter, table, lamp, furniture, windows, doors, room. These "things" never show themselves initially by themselves, in order then to fill out a room as a sum of real things. What we encounter as nearest to us, although we do not grasp it thematically, is the room, not as what is "between the four walls" in a geometrical, spatial sense, but rather as material for living. On the basis of the latter we find "accommodations," and in accommodations the actual "individual" useful thing. A totality of useful things is always already discovered before the individual useful thing. Association geared to useful things which show themselves genuinely only in this association, that is, hammering with the hammer, neither grasps these beings thematically as occurring things nor does it even know of using or the structure of useful things as such. Hammering
* Why? eidos-m01phe-hyle, after all, come from techne, thus from an "artistic" interpretation ! if morphe is not interpreted as eidos, idea.
1.111
Being and Time
65
does not just have a knowledge of the useful character of the hammer; rather, it has appropriated this useful thing in the most adequate way possible. When we take care of things, we are subordinate to the inorder-to constitutive for the actual useful thing in our association with it. The less we just stare at the thing called hammer, the more actively we use it, the more original our relation to it becomes and the more undisguisedly it is encountered as what it is, as a useful thing. The act of hammering itself discovers the specific "handiness" of the hammer. We shall call the useful thing's kind of being in which it reveals itself by itself handiness. It is only because useful things have this "being-in-themselves," and do not merely occur, that they are handy in the broadest sense and are at our disposal. No matter how keenly we just look at the "outward appearance" of things constituted in one way or another, we cannot discover handiness. When we just look at things "theoretically," we lack an understanding of handiness. But association which makes use of things is not blind, it has its own way of seeing which guides our operations and gives them their specific thingly quality. Our association with useful things is subordinate to the manifold of references of the "in-order-to." The kind of seeing of this accommodation to things is called circumspection. "Practical" behavior is not "atheoretical" in the sense of a lack of seeing, and the difference between it and theoretical behavior lies not only in the fact that on the one hand we observe and on the other we act, and that action must apply theoretical cognition if it is not to remain blind. Rather, observation is a kind of taking care just as primordially as action has its own kind of seeing. Theoretical behavior is just looking, noncircumspectly. Because it is noncircumspect, looking is not without rules; its canon takes shape in method. Handiness is not grasped theoretically at all, nor is it itself initially a theme for circumspection. What is peculiar to what is initially at hand is that it withdraws, so to speak, in its character of handiness in order to be really handy. What everyday association is initially busy with is not tools themselves, but the work. What is to be produced in each case is what is primarily taken care of and is thus also what is at hand. The work bears the totality of references in which useful things are encountered. As the whatfor of the hammer, plane, and needle, the work to be produced has in its tum the kind of being of a useful thing. The shoe to be produced is for wearing (footgear), the clock is made for telling time. The work which we primarily encounter when we deal with things and take care of them-what we are at work with-always already lets us encounter the what-for of its usability in the usability which essentially belongs to it. The work that has been ordered exists in its tum only on the
70
66
71
Being and Time
I.m
basis of its use and the referential context of beings discovered in that use. But the work to be produced is not just useful for ... ; production itself is always a using of something for something. A reference to "materials" is contained in the work at the same time. The work is dependent upon leather, thread, nails, and similar things. Leather in its tum is produced from hides. These hides are taken from animals which were bred and raised by others. We also find animals in the world which were not bred and raised and even when they have been raised these beings produce themselves in a certain sense. Thus beings are accessible in the surrounding world which in themselves do not need to be produced and are always already at hand. Hammer, tongs, nails in themselves refer to-they consist of-steel, iron, metal, stone, wood. "Nature" is also discovered in the use of useful things, "nature" in the light of products of nature. But nature must not be understood here as what is merely objectively present, nor as the power of nature. The forest is a forest of timber, the mountain a quarry of rock, the river is water power, the wind is wind "in the sails." As the "surrounding world" is discovered, "nature" thus discovered is encountered along with it. We can abstract from nature's kind of being as handiness; we can discover and define it in its pure objective presence. But in this kind of discovery of nature, nature as what "stirs and strives," what overcomes us, entrances us as landscape, remains hidden. The botanist's plants are not the flowers of the hedgerow, the river's "source" ascertained by the geographer is not the "source in the ground." The work produced refers not only to the what-for of its usability and the whereof of which it consists. The simple conditions of craft contain a reference to the wearer and user at the same time. The work is cut to his figure; he "is" there as the work emerges. This constitutive reference is by no means lacking when wares are produced by the dozen; it is only undefined, pointing to the random and the average. Thus not only beings which are at hand are encountered in the work but also beings with the kind of being of Da-sein for whom what is produced becomes handy in its taking care. Here the world is encountered in which wearers and users live, a world which is at the same time our world. The work taken care of in each case is not only at hand in the domestic world of the workshop, but rather in the public world. Along with the public world, the surrounding world of nature is discovered and accessible to everyone. In taking care of things, nature is discovered as having some definite direction on paths, streets, bridges, and buildings. A covered railroad platform takes bad weather into account, public lighting systems take darkness into account, the specific change of the presence and absence of daylight, the "position of the sun." Clocks take into account a specific con-
Being and Time
1.111
67
stellation in the world system. When we look at the clock, we tacitly use the "position of the sun" according to which the official astronomical regulation of time is carried out. The surrounding world of nature is also at hand in the usage of clock equipment which is at first inconspicuously at hand. Our absorption in taking care of things in the work world nearest to us has the function of discovering; depending upon the way we are absorbed, innerworldly beings that are brought along together with their constitutive references are discoverable in varying degrees of explicitness and with a varying attentive penetration. The kind of being of these beings is "handiness" (Zuhandenheit). But it must not be understood as a mere characteristic of interpretation,* as if such "aspects" were discursively forced upon "beings" which we initially encounter, as if an initially objectively present world-stuff were "subjectively colored" in this way. Such an interpretation overlooks the fact that in that case beings would have to be understood beforehand and discovered as purely objectively present, and would thus have priority and take the lead in the order of discovering and appropriating association with the "world." But this already goes against the ontological meaning of the cognition which we showed to be a founded mode of being-in-the-world. To expose what is merely objectively present, cognition must first penetrate beyond things at hand being taken care of. Handiness is the ontological categorial definition of beings as they are "in themselves. " But "there are" handy things, after all, only on the basis of what is objectively present. Admitting this thesis, does it then follow that handiness is ontologically founded in objective presence? But if, in our continuing ontological interpretation, handiness proves to be the kind of being of beings first discovered within the world, if its primordiality can ever be demonstrated over and against pure objective presence, does what we have explained up to now contribute in the least to an ontological understanding of the phenomenon of world? We have, after all, always "presupposed" world in our interpretation of these innerworldly beings. Joining these beings together does not result as a sum in something like "world." Is there then any path at all leading from the being of these beings to showing the phenomenon of world? 1
16. The Worldly Character of the Surrounding World Making Itself Known in InnernJorldly Beings World itself is not an innerworldly being, and yet it determines innerworldly beings to such an extent that they can only be encountered and
* But only as a characteristic of being encountered.
72
68
73
Being and Time
1.111
discovered and show themselves in their being because "there is" world. But how "is there" world? If Da-sein is ontically constituted by being-inthe-world and if an understanding of the being of its self belongs just as essentially to it, even if that understanding is quite indeterminate, does it not then have an understanding of world, a pre-ontological understanding which lacks and can dispense with explicit ontological insights? Does not something like world show itself to being-in-the-world taking care of the beings encountered within the world, that is, their innerworldliness? Does not this phenomenon come to a pre-phenomenological view; is it not always in view without requiring a thematically ontological interpretation? In the scope of its heedful absorption in useful things at hand, does not Da-sein have a possibility of being in which, together with the innerworldly beings taken care of, their worldliness becomes apparent to it in a ·certain way? If such possibilities of being of Da-sein can be shown in its heedful associations, a path is opened to pursue the phenomenon thus illuminated and to attempt, so to speak, to "place" it and interrogate the structures evident in it. Modes of taking care belong to the everydayness of being-in-theworld, modes which let the beings taken care of be encountered in such a way that the worldly quality of innerworldly beings appears. Beings nearest at hand can be met up with in taking care of things as unusable, as improperly adapted for their specific use. Tools tum out to be damaged, their material unsuitable. In any case, a weful thing of some sort is at hand here. But we discover the unusability not by looking and ascertaining properties, but rather by paying attention to the associations in which we use it. When we discover its unusability, the thing becomes conspicuous. Conspicuousness presents the thing at hand in a certain unhandiness. But this implies that what is unusable just lies there, it shows itself as a thing of use which has this or that appearance and which is always also objectively present with this or that outward appearance in its handiness. Pure objective presence makes itself known in the useful thing only to withdraw again into the handiness of what is taken care of, that is, of what is being put back into repair. This objective presence of what is unusable still does not lack all handiness whatsoever; the useful thing thw objectively present is still not a thing which just occurs somewhere. The damage to the useful thing is still not a mere change in the thing, a change of qualities simply occurring in something objectively present. But heedful association does not just come up against unusable things within what is already at hand. It also finds things which are missing, which are not only not "handy," but not "at hand" at all. When we come upon something unhandy, our missing it in this way again discovers what is at hand in a certain kind of mere objective presence.
1.111
Being and Time
69
When we notice its unhandiness, what is at hand enters the mode of obtrusiveness. The more urgently we need what is missing and the more truly it is encountered in its unhandiness, all the more obtrusive does what is at hand become, such that it seems to lose the character of handiness. It reveals itself as something merely objectively present, which cannot be budged without the missing element. As a deficient mode of taking care of things, the helpless way in which we stand before it discovers the mere objective presence of what is at hand. In associating with the world taken care of, what is unhandy can be encountered not only in the sense of something unusable or completely missing, but as something unhandy which is not missing at all and not unusable, but "gets in the way" of taking care of things. That to which taking care of things cannot tum, for which it has "no time," is something unhandy in the way of not belonging there, of not being complete. Unhandy things are disturbing and make evident the obstinacy of what is initially to be taken care of before anything else. With this obstinacy the objective presence of what is at hand makes itself known in a new way as the being of what is still present and calls for completion. The modes of conspicuousness, obtrusiveness, and obstinacy have the function of bringing to the fore the character of objective presence in what is at hand. What is at hand is not thereby observed and stared at simply as something objectively present. The character of objective presence making itself known is still bound to the handiness of useful things. These still do not disguise themselves as mere things. Useful things become "things" in the sense of what one would like to throw away. But in this tendency to throw things away, what is at hand is still shown as being at hand in its unyielding objective presence. But what does this reference to the modified way of encountering what is at hand, a way in which its objective presence is revealed, mean for the clarification of the phenomenon of worltP. In the analysis of this modification, too, we are still involved with the being of innerworldly beings. We have not yet come any closer to the phenomenon of world. We have not yet grasped that phenomenon, but we now have the possibility of catching sight of it. In its conspicuousness, obtrusiveness, and obstinacy, what is at hand loses its character of handiness in a certain sense. But this handiness is itself understood, although not thematically, in associating with what is at hand. It does not just disappear, but bids farewell, so to speak, in the conspicuousness of what is unusable. Handiness shows itself once again, and precisely in doing so the worldly character of what is at hand also shows itself, too. The structure of being of what is at hand as useful things is determined by references. The peculiar and self-evident "in itself' of the
74
70
75
Being and Time
1.111
nearest "things" is encountered when we take care of things, using them but not paying specific attention to them, while bumping into things that are unusable. Something is unusable. This means that the constitutive reference of the in-order-to to a what-for has been disturbed. The references themselves are not observed, rather they are "there" in our heedful adjustment to them. But in a disturbance of reference-in being unusable for ... -the reference becomes explicit. It does not yet become explicit as an ontological structure, but ontically for our circumspection which gets annoyed by the damaged tool. This circumspect noticing of the reference to the particular what-for makes the what-for visible and with it the context of the work, the whole "workshop" as that in which taking care of things has always already been dwelling. The context of useful things appears not as a totality never seen before, but as a totality that has continually been seen beforehand in our circumspection. But with this totality world makes itself known. Similarly, when something at hand is missing whose everyday presence was so much a matter of course that we never even paid attention to it, this constitutes a breach in the context of references discovered in our circumspection. Circumspection comes up with emptiness and now sees for the first time what the missing thing was at hand for and at hand with. Again, the surrounding world makes itself known. What appears in this way is not itself one thing at hand among others and certainly not something objectively present which lies at the basis of the useful thing at hand. It is "there" before anyone has observed or ascertained it. It is itself inaccessible to circumspection insofar as circumspection concentrates on beings, but it is always already disclosed for that circumspection. "To disclose" and "disclosedness" are used as technical terms in what follows and mean "to unlock"-"to be open." Thus "to disclose" never means anything like "obtaining something indirectly by inference." That the world does not "consist" of what is at hand can be seen from the fact (among others) that when the world appears in the modes of taking care which we have just interpreted, what is at hand becomes deprived of its worldliness so that it appears as something merely objectively present. In order for useful things at hand to be encountered in their character of "being-in-itself' in our everyday taking care of the "surrounding world," the references and referential contexts in which circumspection is "absorbed" must remain nonthematic for that circumspection and all the more so for a noncircumspect, "thematic" abstract comprehension. When the world does not make itself known, that is the condition for the possibility of what is at hand not emerging from its inconspicuousness. And this is the constitution of the phenomenal structure of the being-in-itself of these beings.
Being and Time
1.111
71
Privative expressions such as inconspicuousness, unobtrusiveness, and nonobstinacy tell of a positive phenomenal character of the being of what is initially at hand. These negative prefixes express the character of keeping to itself of what is at hand. That is what we have in mind with being-in-itself which, however, we "initially" typically ascribe to things objectively present, as that which can be thematically ascertained. When we are primarily and exclusively oriented toward that which is objectively present, the "in itself" cannot be ontologically explained at all. However, we must demand an interpretation if the talk about "in-itself" is to have any ontological importance. Mostly one appeals ontically and emphatically to this in-itself of being, and with phenomenal justification. But this ontic appeal does not already fulfill the claim of the ontological statement presumably given in such an appeal. The foregoing analysis already makes it clear that the being-in-itself of innerworldly beings is ontologically comprehensible only on the basis of the phenomenon of world. If, however, world can appear in a certain way, it must be disclosed in general. World is always already predisclosed for circumspect heedfulness together with the accessibility of innerworldly beings at hand. Thus, it is something "in which" Da-sein as a being always already was, that to which it can always only come back whenever it explicitly moves toward something in some way. According to our foregoing interpretation, being-in-the-world signifies the unthematic, circumspect absorption in the references constitutive for the handiness of the totality of useful things. Taking care of things always already occurs on the basis of a familiarity with the world. In this familiarity Da-sein can lose itself in what it encounters within the world and be numbed by it. With what is Da-sein familiar? Why can the worldly character of innerworldly beings appear? How is the referential totality in which circumspection "moves" to be understood more precisely? When this totality is broken, 2 the objective presence of beings is thrust to the fore. In order to answer these questions which aim at working out the phenomenon and problem of worldliness, a concrete analysis of the structures is necessary in whose context our questions are being asked. 17. Reference and Signs
In our preliminary interpretation of the structure of being of things at hand ("useful things"), the phenomenon of reference became visible, but in such a sketchy fashion that we at the same time emphasized the necessity of uncovering the phenomenon merely indicated with regard to its ontological origin. Moreover, it became clear that reference and the
76
72
77
78
Being and Time
I.m
referential totality were in some sense constitutive of worldliness itself. Until now we saw the world appear only in and for particular ways of taking care of what is at hand in the surrounding world, together with its handiness. Thus the further we penetrate into the understanding of the being of innerworldly beings, the more broad and certain the phenomenal basis for the freeing the phenomenon of world becomes. We shall again take our point of departure with the being of what is at hand with the intention of grasping the phenomenon of reference more precisely. For this purpose we shall attempt an ontological analysis of the kind of useful thing in terms of which "references" can be found in a manifold sense. Such a "useful thing" can be found in signs. This word names many things. It names not only different kinds of signs, but being-a-sign-for something can itself be formalized to a universal kind of relation so that the sign structure itself yields an ontological guideline for "characterizing" any being whatsoever. But signs are themselves initially useful things whose specific character as useful things copsists in indicating. Such signs are signposts, boundary-stones, the mariner's storm-cone, signals, flags, signs of mourning, and the like. Indicating can be defined as a "kind" of referring. Taken in an extremely formal sense, to refer means to relate. But relation does not function as the genus for "species" of reference which are differentiated as sign, symbol, expression, and signification. Relation is a formal definition which can be directly read off by way of "formalization" from every kind of context, whatever its subject matter or way of being.' Every reference is a relation, but not every relation is a reference. Every "indicating" is a reference, but not every reference is an indicating. This means that every "indicating" is a relation, but not every relation is an indicating. Thus the formal, universal character of relation becomes apparent. If we investigate such phenomena as reference, sign, or even signification, nothing is to be gained* by characterizing them as relations. Finally, we must even show that "relation" itself has its ontological origin in reference because of its formal, universal character. If this analysis is limited to an interpretation of the sign as distinct from the phenomenon of reference, even within this limitation, the full multiplicity of possible signs cannot be adequately investigated. Among signs there are symptoms, signs pointing backward as well as forward, marks, hallmarks whose way of indicating is different regardless of what it is that serves as a sign. We should differentiate these signs from the following: traces, residues, monuments, documents, certificates,
* This is fundamental for demonstrating the possibility for the claim of logistics.
1.111
Being and Time
73
symbols, expressions, appearances, significations. These phenomena can easily be formalized on the basis of their formal relational character. We are especially inclined today to subject all beings to an "interpretation" following the guideline of such a "relation," an interpretation which is always "correct" because it basically says nothing, no more than the facile scheme of form and content. As an example of a sign, we choose one which we shall see again in a later analysis, though in a different regard. Motor cars are equipped with an adjustable red arrow whose position indicates which direction the car will take, for example, at an intersection. The position of the arrow is regulated by the driver of the car. This sign is a useful thing which is at hand not only for the heedfulness (steering) of the driver. Those who are not in the car-and they especially-make use of this useful thing in that they yield accordingly or remain standing. This sign is handy within the world in the totality of the context of useful things belonging to vehicles and traffic regulations. As a useful thing, this pointer is constituted by reference. It has the character of in-order-to, its specific serviceability, it is there in order to indicate. The indicating of this sign can be taken as a kind of "referring." But here we must note that this "referring" as indicating is not the ontological structure of the sign as a useful thing. As indicating, "referring" is rather grounded in the structure of being of useful things, in serviceability for. The latter does not automatically make something a sign. The useful thing "hammer" is also characterized by serviceability, but it does not thus become a sign. The "referral" of indicating is the ontic concretion of the what-for of serviceability, and determines a useful thing for that what-for. The referral "serviceability for," on the other hand, is an ontological, categorical determination of the useful thing as useful thing. The fact that the whatfor of serviceability gets its concretion in indicating is accidental to the constitution of the useful thing as such. The distinction between referral as serviceability and referral as indicating became roughly apparent in the example of the sign. The two coincide so litde that their unity first makes possible a particular kind of useful thing. But just as surely as indieating is fundamentally different from referral as the constitution of a useful thing, it is just as incontestable that signs have a peculiar and even distinctive relation to the kind of being of the totality of useful things present in the surrounding world and their worldly character. Useful things which indicate have an eminent use in heedful association. However, it cannot suffice ontologically simply to ascertain this fact. The ground and meaning of this pre-eminence must be clarified. What does the indicating of a sign mean? We can only answer this by defining the appropriate way of associating with things that indicate.
79
74
80
Being and Time
l.m
In doing this we must also make their handiness genuinely comprehensible. What is the appropriate way of dealing with signs? Taking our orientation toward the above example (the arrow), we must say that the corresponding behavior (being) toward the sign encountered is "yielding" or "remaining still" with reference to the approaching car which has the arrow. As a way of taking a direction, yielding belongs essentially to the being-in-the-world of Da-sein. Da-sein is always somehow directed and underway. Standing and remaining are only boundary instances of this directed being "underway." Signs address themselves to a specifically "spatial" being-in-the-world. A sign is not really "comprehended" when we stare at it and ascertain that it is an indicating thing that occurs. Even if we follow the direction which the arrow indicates and look at something which is objectively present in the region thus indicated, even then the sign is not really encountered. The sign applies to the circumspection of heedful association in such a way that the circumspection following its direction brings the actual aroundness of the surrounding world into an explicit "overview" in that compliance. Circumspect overseeing does not comprehend what is at hand. Instead, it acquires an orientation within the surrounding world. Another possibility of experiencing useful things lies in encountering the arrow as a useful thing belonging to the car. Here the arrow's specific character of being a useful thing need not be discovered. What and how it is to indicate can remain completely undetermined, and yet what is encountered is not a mere thing. As opposed to the nearest finding of a multiply undetermined manifold of useful things, the experience of a thing requires its own definiteness. Signs such as we have described let what is at hand be encountered, more precisely, let their context become accessible in such a way that heedful association gets and secures an orientation. Signs are not things which stand in an indicating relationship to another thing but are useful things which explicitly bring a totality of useful things to circumspection so that the worldly character of what is at hand makes itself known at the same time. In symptoms and preliminary indications "what is coming" "shows itself," but not in the sense of something merely occurring which is added to what is already objectively present. "What is coming" is something which we expect or "didn't expect" insofar as we were busy with other things. What has happened and occurred becomes accessible to our circumspection through signs after it has already happened. Signs indicate what is actually "going on." Signs always indicate primarily "wherein" we live, what our heedfulness is concerned with, what the relevance is. The peculiar character of useful things as signs becomes especially clear in "establishing a sign." This happens in and through a circumspect
I.m
Being and Time
75
anticipation which needs the possibility at hand of letting the actual surrounding world make itself known for circumspection through something at hand at any time. But the character of not emerging and keeping to itself which we described belongs to the being of innerworldly beings at hand nearest to us. Thus circumspect association in the surrounding world needs a useful thing at hand which in its character of being a useful thing takes over the "work" of letting things at hand become conspicuous. Accordingly, production of such useful things (signs) must take their conspicuousness into consideration. But even as conspicuous things, they are not taken as objectively present arbitrarily, but are "set up" in a definite way with a view toward easy accessibility. But establishing signs does not necessarily have to come about in such a way that a useful thing at hand which was not yet present at all is produced. Signs also originate when something already at hand is taken as a sign. In this mode establishing a sign reveals a still more primordial meaning. Indicating not only creates the circumspectly oriented availability of a totality of useful things and the surrounding world in general, establishing a sign can even discover something for the first time. What is taken as a sign first becomes accessible through its handiness. For example, when the south wind is "accepted" by the farmer as a sign of rain, this "acceptance" or the "value attached" to this being is not a kind of bonus attached to something already objectively present, that is, the movement of the wind and a certain geographical direction. As this mere occurrence which is meteorologically accessible, the south wind is never initially objectively present which sometimes takes on the function of omen. Rather, the farmer's circumspection first discovers the south wind in its being by taking the lay of the land into account. But, one will protest, what is taken as a sign must, after all, first have become accessible in itself and grasped before establishing the sign. To be sure, it must already be there in some way or another. The question simply remains how beings are discovered in this preliminary encounter, whether as something merely occurring and not rather as an uncomprehended kind of useful thing, a thing at hand which one did not know "what to do with" up to now, which accordingly veiled itself to circumspection. Here again, one must also not interpret the character of use· ful things at hand which have not been discovered by circumspection as mere thingliness presented for the comprehension of something merely objectively present.
The handy presence of signs in everyday associations and the conspicuousness which belongs to signs and can be produced with varying intentions and in different ways not only document the inconspicuousness constitutive for what is at hand nearest to us, the sign itself takes its conspicuousness from the inconspicuousness of the totality of useful
81
76
82
&ing and Time
1.111
things at hand in everydayness as a "matter of course," for example, the well-known "string on one's finger" as a reminder. What it is supposed to indicate is always something to be taken care of within the purview of everydayness. This sign can indicate many things of the most diverse sort. The narrowness of intelligibility and use corresponds to the breadth of what can be indicated in such signs. Not only is it mostly at hand as a sign only for the person who "establishes" it, it can become inaccessible to him so that a second sign is necessary for the possible circumspect applicability of the first one. The knot which cannot be used as a sign does not thus lose its sign character, but rather acquires the disturbing obtrusiveness of something near at hand. One could be tempted to illustrate the distinctive role of signs in everyday heedfulness for the understanding of the world itself by citing the extensive use of "signs," such as fetishism and magic, in primitive Dasein. Certainly the establishment of signs that underlies such use of signs does not come about with theoretical intent and by way of theoretical speculation. The use of signs remains completely within an "immediate" being-in-the-world. But when one looks more closely, it becomes clear that the interpretation of fetishism and magic under the guideline of the idea of signs is not sufficient at all to comprehend the kind of "handiness" of beings encountered in the world of primitives. With regard to the phenomenon of signs, we might give the following interpretation that for primitive people the sign coincides with what it indicates. The sign itself can represent what it indicates not only in the sense of replacing it, but in such a way that the sign itself always is what is indicated. This remarkable coincidence of the sign with what is indicated does not, however, mean that the sign-thing has already undergone a certain "objectification," has been experienced as a pure thing and been transposed together with what is signified to the same region of being of objective presence. The "coincidence" is not an identification of hitherto isolated things, but rather the sign has not yet become free from that for which it is a sign. This kind of use of signs is still completely absorbed in the being of what is indicated so that a sign as such cannot be detached at all. The coincidence is not based on a first objectification, but rather upon the complete lack of such an objectification. But this means that signs are not at all discovered as useful things, that ultimately what is "at hand" in the world does not have the kind of being of useful things at all. Perhaps this ontological guideline (handiness and useful things), too, can provide nothing for an interpretation of the primitive world, and certainly for an ontology of thingliness. But if an understanding of being is constitutive for primitive Da-sein and the primitive world in general, it is all the more urgent to develop the "formal" idea of worldliness; namely, of a phenomenon which can be mod-
Being and Time
I.Ill
77
ified in such a way that all ontological statements which assert that in a given phenomenal context something is not yet or no longer such and such may acquire a positive phenomenal meaning in terms of what it is not. The foregoing interpretation of signs should simply offer phenomenal support for our characterization of reference. The relation between sign and reference is threefold: (I) As a possible concretion of the what-for of serviceability, the indicating is based upon the structure of useful things in general, upon the in-order-to (reference). (2) As the character of useful things at hand, the indicating of signs belongs to a totality of useful things, to a referential context. (3) Signs are notjust at hand along with other useful things but rather in their handiness the surrounding world becomes explicitly accessible to circumspection. Signs are something ontically at hand which as this definite useful thingfunctioru at the same time as something which indicates the ontological structure of handiness, referential totality, and worldliness. The distinctive characteristic of these things at hand within the surrounding world circumspectly taken care of is rooted here. Thus reference cannot itself be comprehended as a sign if it is ontologically to be the foundation for signs. Reference is not the ontic specification of something at hand since it, after all, constitutes handiness itself. In what sense is reference the ontological "presupposition" of what is at hand, and as this ontological foundation, to what extent is it at the same time constitutive of worldliness in general?
18. Relevance and Significance: The Worldliness of the World Things at hand are encountered within the world. The being of these beings, handiness, is thus ontologically related to the world and to worldliness. The world is always already "there" in all things at hand. World is already discovered* beforehand together with everything encountered, although not thematically. However, it can also appear in certain ways of associating with the surrounding world. World is that in terms of which things a,t hand are at hand for us. How can world let things at hand be encountered? Our analysis showed that what is encountered within the world is freed in its being for heedful circumspection, for taking matters into account. What does this prior freeing mean and how is it to be understood as the ontological distinction of the world? What problems does the question of the worldliness of the world confront? The constitution of useful things as things at hand has been described as reference. How can world free beings of this kind with regard to their being, why are these beings encountered first? We men-
* cleared (gelichtet)
83
78
84
Being and Time
1.111
tioned serviceability for, impairment, usability, and so forth, as specific kinds of reference. The what-for of serviceability and the wherefore of usability prefigure the possible concretion of reference. The "indicating" of signs, the "hammering" of the hammer, however, are not qualities of beings. They are not qualities at all if this term is supposed to designate the ontological structure of a possible determination of things. In any case, things at hand are suited and unsuited for things, and their "qualities" are, so to speak, still bound up with that suitability or unsuitability,just as objective presence, as a possible kind of being of things at hand, is still bound up with handiness. But as the constitution of useful things, serviceability (reference) is also not the suitability of beings, but the condition of the possibility of being for their being able to be determined by suitability. But then what does reference mean? The fact that the being of things at hand has the structure of reference means that they have in themselves the character of being referred. Beings are discovered with regard to the fact that they are referred, as those beings which they are, to something. They are relevant together with something else. The character of being of things at hand is relevance. To be relevant means to let something be together with something else. The relation of "together ... with ... "is to be indicated by the term reference. Relevance is the being of innerworldly beings, for which they are always already initially freed. Beings are in each case relevant. Being is the ontological determination of the being of these beings, not an on tic statement about beings. What the relevance is about is the what-for of serviceability, the wherefore of usability. The what-for of serviceability can in turn be relevant. For example, the thing at hand which we call a hammer has to do with hammering, the hammering has to do with fastening something, fastening something has to do with protection against bad weather. This protection "is" for the sake of providing shelter for Da-sein, that is, for the sake of a possibility of its being. Which relevance things at hand have is prefigured in terms of the total relevance. The total relevance which, for example, constitutes the things at hand in a workshop in their handiness is "earlier" than any single useful thing, as is the farmstead with all its utensils and neighboring lands. The total relevance itself, however, ultimately leads back to a what-for which no longer has relevance, which itself is not a being of the kind of being of things at hand within a world, but is a being whose being is defined as being-inthe-world, to whose constitution of being worldliness itself belongs. This primary what-for is not just another for-that as a possible factor in relevance. The primary "what-for" is a for-the-sake-of-which. But the forthe-sake-of-which always concerns the being of Da-sein which is essentially concerned about this being itself in its being. For the moment we shall
1.111
Being and Time
79
not pursue any further the connection indicated which leads from the structure of relevance to the being of Da-sein itself as the real and unique for-the-sake-of-which. "Letting something be relevant" first of all requires a clarification which goes far enough to bring the phenomenon of worldliness to the kind of definiteness needed in order to be able to ask questions about it in general. Ontically, to let something be relevant means to let things at hand be* in such and such a way in factical taking care of things, to let them be as they are and in order that they be such. We grasp the ontic meaning of this "letting be" in a fundamentally ontological way. Thus we interpret the meaning of the previous freeing of innerworldly beings initially at hand. Previously letting "be" does not mean first to bring something to its being and produce it, but rather to discover something that is already a "being" in its handiness and thus let it be encountered as the being of this being. t Tills "a priori" letting something be relevant is the condition of the possibility that things at hand be encountered so that Da-sein in its ontic association with the beings thus encountered can let them be relevant in an ontic sense. On the other hand, letting something be relevant, understood in an ontological sense, concerns the freeing of every thing at hand as a thing at hand, whether it is relevant in the ontic sense or whether it is such a being which is precisely not relevant ontically-which is initially and for the most part what is taken care of, which we do not let "be" as the discovered being it is, but work over it, improve it, destroy it. To have always already let something be freed for relevance is an a priori perfectt characterizing the kind of being of Da-sein itself. Understood ontologically, letting something be relevant is the previous freeing of beings for their innerworldly handiness. The with-what of relevance is freed in terms of the together-with-what of relevance. It is encountered by heedfulness as this thing at hand. When a being shows itself in general
* Letting-be (Seyn-la.ssen). Cf. "On the Essence of Truth," where letting-be is related in principle and very broadly to every kind of being. t Thus to let it presence in its truth. t In the same paragraph we speak of "previous freeing" -namely (generally speaking) of being for the possible manifestness of beings: "Previously" in this ontological sense means in Latin a priori, in Greek proteron te physei (Aristotle, Physics, A 1). More clearly in Metaphysics E 1025b29-to ti en einai, "what already was-being," "what always already presences in advance," what has-been, the perfect. The Greek verb einai has no perfect tense; it is named here in en einai. It is not something ontically past, but rather what is always earlier, what we are referred back to in the question of beings as such. Instead of a priori perfect we could also say ontological or transcendental perfect (cf. Kant's doctrine of the schematism).
85
80
86
Being and Time
l.m
to heedfulness, that is, when a being is discovered in its being, it is always already a thing at hand in the surrounding world and precisely not "initially" merely objectively present "world-stuff." As the being of things at hand, relevance itself is always discovered only on the basis of a relevant totality previously discovered, that is, in the things at hand encountered; what we called the worldly character of things at hand thus lies prediscovered. This totality of relevance previously discovered contains an ontological relation to the world. Letting beings be relevant and thus freeing them for a totality of relevance must have already somehow disclosed that for which it is freeing. That for which things at hand in the surrounding world are freed (in such a way that the things at hand first become accessible as innerworldly beings) cannot itself be understood as a being of the kind ofbeing thus discovered. It is essentially not discoverable if we restrict discoveredness as the term for a possibility of being of all beings unlike Da-sein. But now what does that mean, to say that for which innerworldly beings are initially freed must previously be disclosed? An understanding of being belongs to the being of Da-sein. Understanding has its being in an act of understanding. If the kind of being of being-in-the-world essentially belongs to Da-sein, then the understanding of being-in-the-world belongs to the essential content of its understanding of being. The previous disclosure of that for which the freeing of things encountered in the world ensues is none other than the understanding of world to which Da-sein as a being is always already related. Previous letting something be relevant to ... with ... is grounded in an understanding of something like letting things be relevant, and such things as the in-which and with-which of relevance. These things and what underlies them, such as the what-for to which relevance is related, the for-the-sake-of-which from which every what-for is ultimately derived, all of these must be previously disclosed in a certain intelligibility. And what is that in which Da-sein understands itself pre-ontologically as being-in-the-world? In understanding a context of relations, Dasein has been referred to an in-order-to in terms of an explicitly or inexplicitly grasped potentiality-of-its-being for the sake of which it is, which can be authentic or inauthentic. This prefigures a what-for as the possible letting something be relevant which structurally allows for relevance to something else. Da-sein is always in each case already referred in terms of a for-the-sake-of-which to the with-what of relevance. This means that, insofar as it is, it always already lets beings be encountered as things at hand. That within which Da-sein understands itself beforehand in the mode of self-reference is that for which it lets beings be encountered beforehand. As that for which one lets beings be encountered in the kind of being of relevance, the wherein of self-referential understanding is the
1.111
Being and Time
81
phenomenon of world. And the structure of that to which Da-sein is referred is what constitutes the worldliness of the world. Da-sein is primordially familiar with that within which it understands itself in this way. This familiarity with the world does not necessarily require a theoretical transparency of the relations constituting the world as world. But it is probable that the possibility of an explicit ontological and existential interpretation of these relations is grounded in the familiarity with the world constitutive for Da-sein. This familiarity, in its tum, helps to constitute Da-sein's understanding of being. This possibility can be explicitly appropriated when Da-sein has set as its task a primordial interpretation of its being and the possibilities of that being or, for that matter, of the meaning of being in general. But as yet our analyses have only first laid bare the horizon within which something akin to world and worldliness is to be sought. For our further reflection, we must first make clear how the context of the selfreferral of Da-sein is to be understood ontologically. Understanding, which will be analyzed with proper penetration in what follows (see section 31), holds the indicated relations in a preliminary disclosure. In its familiar being-in-relevance, understanding holds itself before that disclosure as that within which its reference moves. Understanding can itself be referred in and by these relations. We shall call the relational character of these referential relations signifying. In its familiarity with these relations, Da-sein "signifies" to itself. It primordially gives itself to understand its being and potentiality-of-being with regard to its being-in-the-world. The for-the-sake-ofwhich signifies an in-order-to, the in-order-to signifies a what-for, the what-for signifies a what-in of letting something be relevant, and the latter a what-with of relevance. These relations are interlocked among themselves as a primordial totality. They are what they are as this signifying in which Da-sein gives itself to understand its being-in-theworld beforehand. We shall call this relational totality of signification significance. It is what constitutes the structure of the world, of that in which Da-sein* as such always already is. In its familiarity with significance Da-sein is the antic condition of the possibility of the disclosure of beings encountered in the mode of being of relevance (handiness) in a world that can thus make themselves known in their in-itself. As such, Da-sein always means that a context of things at hand is already essentially discovered with its being. In that it is, Da-sein has always already referred itselft to an encounter with a "world." This dependency of being referred belongs essentially to its being.
* The Da-sein in which human being presences. t
But not as the egoistic deed of a subject, rather: Da-sein and being.
87
82
88
Being and Time
1.111
But the significance itself with which Da-sein is always already familiar contains the ontological condition of the possibility that Dasein, understanding and interpreting, can disclose something akin to "significations" which in tum found the possible being of words and language.* As the existential constitution of Da-sein, its being-in-the-world, disclosed significance is the ontic condition of the possibility for discovering a totality of relevance. If we thus define the being of what is at hand (relevance) and even worldliness itself as a referential context, are we not volatizing the "substantial being" of innerworldly beings into a system of relations, and, since relations are always "something thought," are we not dissolving the being of innerworldly beings into "pure thought"? Within the present field of investigation the repeatedly designated differences of the structures and dimensions of the ontological problematic are to be fundamentally distinguished: 1. The being of the innerworldly beings initially encountered (handiness); 2. The being ofbeings (objective presence) that is found and determined by discovering them in their own right in going through beings initially encountered; 3. The being of the ontic condition of the possibility of discovering innerworldly beings in general, the worldlinesst of the world. This third kind of being is an existential determination of being-in-theworld, that is, of Da-sein. The other two concepts of being are categories and concern beings unlike Da-sein. The referential context that constitutes worldliness as significance can be formally understood in the sense of a system of relations. But we must realize that such formalizations level down the phenomena to the extent that the true phenomenal content gets lost, especially in the case of such "simple" relations as are contained in significance. These "relations" and "relata" of the in-orderto, for-the-sake-of, the with-what of relevance resist any kind of mathematical functionalization in accordance with their phenomenal content. Nor are they something thought, something first posited in "thinking," but rather relations in which heedful circumspection as such already dwells. As constitutive of worldliness, this "system of relations" does not volatize the being of innerworldly beings at all. On the contrary,
* Untrue.
Language is not imposed, but is the primordial essence of truth as there (Da). t Better: the holding sway (Wallen} of the world.
I. III
Being and Time
83
these beings are discoverable in their "substantial" "in itself' only on the basis of the worldliness of the world. And only when innerworldly beings can be encountered at all does the possibility exist of making what is merely objectively present accessible in the field of these beings. On the basis of their merely objective presence these beings can be determined mathematically in "functional concepts" with regard to their "properties." Functional concepts of this kind are ontologically possible only in relation to beings whose being has the character of pure substantiality. Functional concepts are always possible only as formalized substantial concepts. In order to delineate the specific ontological problematic of worldliness still more clearly, the interpretation of worldliness is to be clarified in terms of an extreme counter-example before preceding with our analysis.
B. CONTRAST BETWEEN OUR ANALYSIS OF WORLDLINESS AND DESCARTES' INTERPRETATION OF THE WORLD
Our investigation can secure the concept of worldliness and the structures contained in this phenomenon only step by step. Since the interpretation of the world initially starts with an innerworldly being and then never gains sight of the phenomenon of world again, we shall attempt to clarify this point of departure ontologically in what is perhaps its most extreme development. We shall not only give a short presentation of the fundamental features of Descartes' ontology of the "world," but also ask about its presuppositions and try to characterize those presuppositions in the light of what has been clarified up to now. This discussion should tell us on what fundamentally undiscussed ontological "foundations" the interpretations of the world after Descartes, and especially those preceding him, are based. Descartes sees the fundamental ontological determination of the world as extensio. Since extension is a component of spatiality, for Descartes in fact identical with it, and since spatiality is in some sense constitutive of the world, our discussion of the Cartesian ontology of the "world" at the same time offers a negative support for the positive explication of the spatiality of the surrounding world and of Da-sein itself. With regard to Descartes' ontology we shall discuss three things: I. The determination of the "world" as res extensa (19). 2. The foundations of this ontological determination (20). 3. The hermeneutical discussion of the Cartesian ontology of the "world" (21).
89
84
Being and Time
1.111
The following reflections can be grounded in more detail only by the phenomenological de-structuring of the cogito sum (cf. part 2, division 2). *
19. The Determination of the "World" as Res Extensa
90
Descartes distinguishes the ego cogito as res cogitans from the res corporea. From then on this distinction ontologically defines the distinction of "spirit" and "nature." Although this opposition between nature and spirit is formulated ontically in many variations of content, the unclarity of its ontological fundaments and even of the poles of this opposition itself have their proximate roots in Descartes' distinction. In what kind of understanding of being did he determine the being of these beings? The term for the being of beings in themselves is substantia. This expression sometimes means the being of beings as substance, substantiality, sometimes beings themselves, particular substances. This ambiguity of substantia, already inherent in the ancient concept of ousia,t is not accidental. The ontological determination of the res corporea requires the explication of substance, that is, of the substantiality of these beings as particular substances. What constitutes the true being-in-itself of the res corporea? How is a substance as such, that is, its substantiality to be understood? Et quidem ex quolibet attributo substantia cognoscitur; sed una tamen est cuis que substantiae praecipua proprietas, quae ipsius naturam essentiamque constituit, et ad quam aliae omnes referuntur. 4 Substances are accessible through their "attributes," and every substance has an eminent property in terms of which the essence of the substantiality of a definite substance can be determined. What is this property with regard to the res corporea? Nempe extensio in longum, latum, et profundum, substantiae coporeae naturam constituit. 5 Extension in terms of length, breadth, and depth constitutes the real being of the corporeal substance that we call "world." What gives the extensio this distinction? Nam omne aliud quod corpori tribui potest, extensionem praesupponit. 6 Extension is the constitution of being of the beings under discussion, a constitution which must already "be" before other determinations of being in order for the latter to be able to "be" what they are. Extension must primarily be "attributed" to the corporeal thing. Accordingly, the proof for the extension and the substantiality of the "world" characterized by that extension is accomplished by showing how all other properties of this substance, above all divisio, figura, motus can only be conceived as modes of extensio and the extensio, conversely, is intelligible sine figura vel motu.
* Never published. t
And especially the on; to on: (1) being (beingness), (2) beings.
l.lll
Being and Time
85
Thus a corporeal being can maintain its total extension and yet change the distribution of the extension in many ways and in various dimensions and still present itself as one and the same thing in manifold shapes. Atque unum et idem corpus, retinendo suam eandem quantitatem, pluribus diversis modis potest extendi: nunc scilicet magis secundum longitudinem, minusque secundum latitudinem vel projunditatem, ac paulo post e contra magis secundum latitudinem et minus secundum longitudinem. 7 Gestalt is a mode of extensio, and motion as well. For motus is comprehended only si de nullo nisi locali cogitemus, ac de vi a qua excitatur non inquiramus. 8 If motion is an existent property of the res corporea, it must be understood in terms of the being of this being itself, in terms of extensio, that is, as mere change of location in order to be experienced in its being. Something like "force" adds nothing to the determination of the being of this being. Properties such as durities (hardness), pondus (weight), color, can be removed from matter, yet matter remains what it is. These properties do not constitute its true being. Insofar as they are, they turn out to be modes of extensio. Descartes attempts to show this in detail with regard to "hardness": Nam, quantum ad duritiem, nihil aliud de ilia sensus nobis indicat, quam partes durorum corporum resistere motui manuum nostrarum, cum in illas incurrunt. Si enim, quotiescunque manus nostrae versus aliquam partem moventur, corpora omnia ibi existentia recederent eadem celeritate qua illae accedunt, nullam unquam duritiem sentiremus. Nee ullo modo potest intelligi. corpora quae sic recederent, idcirco naturam corporis esse amissura; nee proinde ipsa in duritie consistit. 9 Hardness is experienced by touch. What does the sense of touch "tell" us about hardness? The parts of the hard thing "resist" the motion of the hands, for instance in wanting to push something away. But if the hard bodies, those that do not give way, changed their location with the same speed as the hand "approaching" the bodies, nothing would ever be touched. Hardness would not be experienced and thus would never be. But it is in no way comprehen!lible that bodies that give way with such velocity should thus forfeit any of their corporeal being. If they were to retain this even under a change of velocity which makes it impossible for anything like "hardness" to be, then hardness does not belong to the being of these beings either. Eademque ratione ostendi potest, et pondus, et colorem, et alias omnes eiusmodi qualitates, quae in materia corporea sentiuntur, ex ea tolli posse, ipsa integra remanente: unde sequitur, a nulla ex illis eius (sc. extensionis) naturam dependere. 10 Thus, what constitutes the being of the res corporea is extensio, the omnimodo divisibile, Jip;urabile et mobile, what can change in every kind of divisibility, gestalt, and motion, the capax mutationum, what persists throughout all these changes, remanet. In a corporeal being what is capable of such a remaining constant is its true being, in such a way that it characterizes the substantiality of this substance.
91
92
86
Being and Time
l.m
20. The Fundaments of the Ontological Definition of the "World"
93
The idea of being from which the ontological characteristics of the res extensa are derived is substantiality. Per substantiam nihil aliud intelligere possumus, quam rem quae ita existi4 ut nulla alia re indigeat ad existendum. By substance we can understand nothing other than a being which is in such a way that it needs no other being in order to be. 11 The being of a "substance" is characterized by not needing anything. Whatever in its being absolutely needs no other being, satisfies the idea of substance in the true sense. This being is the ens perfectissimum. Substantia quae nulla plane re indigeat, unica tantum potest intelligi, nempe Deus. 12 Here, "God" is a purely ontological term when He is understood as ens perfectissimum. At the same time, the "self-evident" connotation of the concept of God makes possible an ontological interpretation of the constitutive factor of substantiality, that of not needing anything. Alias vero omnes (res), non nisi ope concursus Dei existere posse percipimus. 1 ~ All beings other than God need to be produced in the broadest sense and to be sustained. The production of what is objectively present and the lack of need for production constitute the horizon within which "being" is understood. Every being other than God is ens creatum. The being which belongs to one of these entities is "infinitely" different from that which belongs to the other; yet we still consider what is created and the creator alike as beings. We thus use being in such a broad sense that its meaning encompasses an "infmite" distinction. Thus we can also call created beings substances with a certain justification. It is true that these beings need to be produced and sustained, relative to God, but within the region of created beings, of the "world" in the sense of the ens creatum, there are beings which are "in need of no other being" relative to creaturely production and sustenance for instance, human beings. There are two such substances: res cogitans and res extensa. The being of that substance whose eminent proprietas is extensio is thus definable in principle ontologically when the meaning of being "common" to the three substances, the one infinite and the two finite ones, is clarified. But nomen substantiae non convenit Deo et illis univoce, ut dici solet in Scholis, hoc est . . . quae Deo et creaturis sit communis. 14 Here Descartes touches upon a problem which occupied medieval ontology in many ways, the question in what way the meaning of being signifies the being under consideration. In statements such as "God is" and "the world is" we predicate being. But this word "is" cannot signify the being in question in the same sense (suniinumiis, univoce)* when, after all, there is an infinite distinction of being between the two beings. If the significance of "is" were univocal, the creature would be understood as the
* in a consistent sense
1.111
Being and Time
87
uncreated or else the uncreated would be degraded to being a creature. But "being" does not simply function as the same name; rather, in both cases "being" is understood. Scholasticism understands the positive sense of the significance of "being" as an "analogous" meaning in contradistinction to the univocal or merely homonymous one. Following Aristotle in whom the problem is prefigured, as it is in the point of departure of Greek ontology in general, various kinds of analogy were established according to which the "schools" differ in their interpretation of the functional significance of being. With regard to the ontological development of the problem, Descartes is far behind the scholastics;15 he actually evades the question. Nulla eius (substantiae) nominis signijicatio potest distincte intelligi, quae Deo et creaturis sit communis. 16 This evasion means that Descartes leaves the meaning of being contained in the idea of substantiality and the character of "universality" of this meaning unexplained. Medieval ontology left the question of what being itself means just as unquestioned as did ancient ontology. Thus it is not surprising if a question such as that of the kinds of significations of being gets nowhere as long as it is to be discussed on the foundation of an unclarified meaning of being which the signification "expresses." The meaning was unclarified because it was held to be "self-evident."* Descartes not only completely evades the ontological question of substantiality, he emphasizes explicitly that substance as such, that is, its substantiality, is in and for itself inaccessible from the very beginning. Verumtamen non potest substantia primum animadverti ex hoc solo, quod sit res existens, quia hoc solum per se nos non afficit. 17 "Being" itself does not "affect" us, therefore it cannot be perceived. "Being is not a real predicate"t according to Kant who is only repeating Descartes' statement. Thus the possibility of a pure problematic of being is renounced in principle and a way out is sought for arriving at the definitions of substances designated above. Because "being" is in fact not accessible as a being, it is expressed by existing definite qualities of the beings in question, by attributes. Not, however, by arbitrary qualities, but by those that most purely satisfying the meaning of being and substantiality tacitly presupposed. Extensio is the primarily necessary "attribute" in the substantia finita as res corporea. Q!lin et Jacilius intelligimus substantiam extensam, vel substantiam cogitantem, quam substantiam solam, omisso eo quod cogitet vel sit extensa; 18 for substantiality is ratione tantum, it is not detachable realiter, t nor is it to be found like substantial beings themselves.
* and was content with intelligibility. "Real" belonging to thinghood (Sachheit}, to what alone can concern us in this or that way. t The content of the what (wasgehaltlich}. t
94
88
95
Being and Time
I.m
Thus the ontological foundations for the definition of "world" as res exten.sa have become clear: the idea of substantiality which is not only unexplained in the meaning of its being, but also declared to be inexplicable, and is presented by way of a detour around the most distinctive substantial attribute of the substance in question. In the definition of substance in terms of a substantial being one also sees the reason why the term substance is ambiguous. What is intended is substantiality and it is understood in terms of an existent quality of substance. Because something ontic is made to underlie the ontological, the expression substantia functions sometimes in an ontological, sometimes in an ontic meaning, but mostly in a meaning which shifts about in a hazy mixture of the two. But behind this slight difference of meaning lies hidden the failure to master the fundamental problem of being.* Its development requires "tracking down" the equivocations in the right way. Whoever tries this sort of thing is not "occupied" with "mere verbal meanings," but must venture forth to the most primordial problematic of the "things themselves" to get such "nuances" straightened out.
21. Hermeneutical Discussion of the Cartesian Ontology of the "World" The critical question now arises: Does this ontology of the "world" see the phenomenon of world at all, and if not, does it at least define innerworldly beings to the extent that their worldly character can be made visible? To both questions we must answer "No". The being which Descartes is trying to grasp ontologically and in principle with the extensio is rather of such a nature that can be initially discovered only through an innerworldly being initially at hand. But if this and even if the ontological characteristic of this particular innerworldly being (nature)-the idea of substantiality as well as the meaning of existit and ad existendum contained in its definition-leads to obscurity, the possibility nonetheless still exists that through an ontology grounded in the radical separation of God, ego, "world," the ontological problem of the world is in some sense raised and further advanced. But even if this possibility does not exist, we must show explicitly that Descartes not only goes amiss ontologically in his definition of the world, but that his interpretation and its foundations led him to pass over the phenomenon of world as well as the being of innerworldly beings initially at hand. In our exposition of the problem of worldliness (section 14) we referred to the importance of gaining proper access to this phenomenon. Thus in our critical discussion of the Cartesian point of departure we must ask which kind of being of Da-sein we should fix
* Ontological difference.
l.lll
Being and Time
89
upon as the appropriate kind of access to that being with whose being as extensio Descartes equates the being of the "world." The sole, genuine access to this being is knowing, intellectio, in the sense of the kind of knowledge we get in mathematics and physics. Mathematical knowledge is regarded as the one way of apprehending beings which can always be certain of the secure possession of the being of the beings which it apprehends. Whatever has the kind of being adequate to the being accessible in mathematical knowledge is in the true sense. Tiris being is what always is what it is. Thus what can be shown to have the character of constantly remaining, as remanens capax mutationem, constitutes the true being of beings which can be experienced in the world. What enduringly remains truly is. Tiris is the sort of thing that mathematics knows. What mathematics makes accessible in beings constitutes their being. Thus the being of the "world" is, so to speak, dictated to it in terms of a definite idea of being which is embedded in the concept of substantiality and in terms of an idea of knowledge which cognizes beings in this way. Descartes does not allow the kind of being of innerworldly beings to present itself, but rather prescribes to the world, so to speak, its "true" being on the basis of an idea of being (being = constant objective presence) the source of which has not been revealed and the justification of which has not been demonstrated. Thus it is not primarily his dependence upon a science, mathematics, which just happens to be especially esteemed, that detennines his ontology of the world, rather his ontology is determined by a basic ontological orientation toward being as constant objective presence, which mathematical knowledge is exceptionally well suited to grasp.* In this way Descartes explicitly switches over philosophically from the development of traditional ontology to modem mathematical physics and its transcendental foundations. Descartes does not need to raise the problem of the appropriate access to innerworldly beings. Under the unbroken dominance of traditional ontology, the way to get a grasp of what truly is has been decided in advance. That way lies in noein, "intuition" (Ansckauung) in the broadest sense, of which dianoein, "thinking," is just a derivative form. It is in terms of this basic ontological orientation that Descartes gives his "critique" of the possible intuitive-perceptive access to beings, of sensatio (aistkesis) as opposed to intellectio. Descartes knows very well that beings do not initially show themselves in their true being. What is given "initially" is this waxen thing which is colored, flavored, hard, cold, and resonant in a definite way. But this is not important ontologically, nor, in general, is anything which
* but orientation to the mathematical as such, mathema and on.
96
90
Being and Time
I.m
is given through the senses. Satis erit, si advertamw sensuum perceptiones non referri, nisi ad istam corporis humani cum mente coniunctionem, et nobis quidem ordinarie exhibere, quid ad illam externa corpora prodesse possint aut nocere. 19 The senses do not enable us to know any being in its being; 97
they merely make known the usefulness and harmfulness of "external" innerworldly things for human beings encumbered with bodies. Nos non docent, qualia (corpora) in seipsw existant; 20 they tell us nothing at all about beings in their being. Quod agentes, percipiemw naturam materiae, sive corporis in universum spectat~ non consistere in eo quod sit res dura vel ponderosa vel colorata, vel alio aliquo modo senses afficiens: sed tantum in eo, quod sit res extensa in longum, latum et profundum. 21
98
If we subject Descartes' interpretation of the experience of hardness and resistance to a critical analysis, it will be plain how unable he is to let what shows itself in sensation present itself in its own kind of being, let alone determine its character. (Cf. section 19.) Hardness is understood as resistance. But neither hardness nor resistance is understood in a phenomenal sense, as something experienced in itself and determinable in such experience. For Descartes, resistance amounts to no more than not yielding place, that is, not undergoing any change of location. A thing's resistance means that it stays in a definite place, relative to another thing changing its place, or else that it changes its own location with a velocity that permits the thing to "catch up" with it. But when the experience of hardness is interpreted in this way, the kind of being that belongs to sensory perception is obliterated, and with it the possibility of grasping the being of those beings encountered in such perception. Descartes translates the kind of being of the perception of something into the only kind of being that he knows: the perception of something becomes a definite objective presence of two objectively present res extensa next to each other; the relation of their movements is itself a mode of extensio that primarily characterizes the objective presence of the corporeal thing. It is true that the possible "fulfillment" of the act of touching requires a distinctive "nearness" of what is touchable. But that does not mean that touching and the hardness made known in touching consist, ontologically understood, in different velocities of two corporeal things. Hardness and resistance do not show themselves at all unless there is a being which has the kind of being of Da-sein, or at least of a living being. Thus Descartes' discussion of the possible kinds of access to innerworldly beings is dominated by an idea of being which is patterned after a particular region of these beings themselves. The idea of being as constant objective presence not only motivates an extreme definition of the being of innerworldly beings and their identification with the world as such. At the same time, it blocks the
1.111
Being and Time
91
possibility of bringing to view attitudes of Da-sein in a way which is ontologically appropriate. But thus the road is completely blocked to seeing the founded character of all sensuous and intellective apprehension, and to understanding them as a possibility of being-in-the-world. But Descartes understands the being of "Da-sein," to whose basic constitution being-in-the-world belongs, in the same way as the being of res extensa, as substance. But with these criticisms have we not foisted upon Descartes a task altogether beyond his horizon, and then "demonstrated" that he failed to solve it? How could Descartes identify a definite innerworldly being and its being with the world if he does not know the phenomenon of world at all and thus something akin to innerworldliness? In the realm of controversy over principles, one must not only attach oneself to theses which can be grasped doxographically, rather one must take the objective tendency of the problematic as an orientation, even if it does not go beyond a rather common version of that problematic. The fact that Descartes not only wanted to raise the question of "self and world" with his doctrine of res cogitans and res extensa, but claimed to give a radical solution, becomes clear in his Meditations (cf. especially I and IV) . The preceding discussion should have demonstrated that the basic ontological orientation toward the tradition, devoid of any positive criticism, made it impossible for him to clear the way for a primordial ontological problematic of Da-sein, and necessarily distorted his view of the phenomenon of the world and forced the ontology of the "world" into the ontology of a particular innerworldly being. One might object, however, that even if the problem of the world and also the being of beings encountered in the surrounding world indeed remain obscured, Descartes nonetheless laid the foundation for the ontological characteristic of that innerworldly being which in its being is the basis for every other being, material nature.* The other strata of innerworldly reality are based upon it, the fundamental stratum. The definite properties which do show themselves as qualities, but which are "basically" quantitative modifications of the modes of extensio itself, initially have their basis in the extended thing as such. Specific qualities such as beautiful, not beautiful, fitting, unfitting, usable, unusable then find a footing in these qualities which are themselves further reducible. Those specific qualities must be understood in a primary orientation to thingliness as nonquantifiable value predicates through which the thing, initially merely material, gets stamped as something good. But with this stratification we come, after all, to the being that we characterized onto-
* Critique of Husserl's development of ontologies! just as the whole critique of Descartes is inserted here with this intention!
99
92
100
Being and Time
l.lll
logically as the useful thing at hand. Thus the Cartesian analysis of the "world" first makes possible a secure erection of the structure of what is initially at hand. It only needs to round out the natural thing to a complete thing of use, a task easily accomplished. But apart from the specific problem of the world, is the being of what we initially encounter in the world ontologically attainable in this way? When we speak of material thingliness, do we not tacitly posit a kind of being-the constant objective presence of a thing-which is so far from being rounded out ontologically by subsequently outfitting beings with value predicates that these value characters themselves rather remain mere ontic qualities of a being which has the kind of being of a thing? The addition of value predicates is not in the least able to tell us anything new about the being of goods, but rather only again presupposes for them the kind of being of pure objective presence. Values are objectively present determinations of a thing. In the end, values have their ontological origin solely in the previous point of departure of the reality of the thing as the fundamental stratum. But pre-phenomenological experience already shows something about the being supposed to be a thing which is not fully intelligible through thingliness. Thus thinglike being needs a supplement. What, then, does the being of values or their "validity," which Lotze understood as a mode of "affirmation," mean ontologically? What does this "inherence" of values in things mean ontologically? As long as these matters remain obscure, the reconstruction of a thing of use in terms of a thing of nature is an ontologically questionable undertaking, not to speak of the fundamental distortion of the problematic. And does not this reconstruction of the initially "stripped" thing of use always need the previous, positive view of the phenomenon whose totality is to be reestablished in the reconstruction? But if its ownmost constitution of being of the phenomenon is not adequately explicated, are we not building the reconstruction without a plan? In that this reconstruction and "rounding out" of the traditional ontology of the "world" results in our reaching the same being from which the above analysis of the handiness of useful things and totality of relevance took its point of departure, it seems as if the being of that being were indeed clarified or had at least become a problem. Just as Descartes cannot grasp the being of substance with extensio as proprietas, the flight to "valuable" qualities cannot even catch sight of being as handiness, let alone make it ontologically thematic. Descartes narrowed down the question of the world to that of the thingliness of nature as that innerworldly being which is initially accessible. He strengthened the opinion that the supposedly strictest antic knowledge of a being is also the possible access to the primary being of the being discovered in such knowledge. But we must at the same time
1.111
Being and Time
93
realize that the "roundings-out" of an ontology of things are fundamentally on the same dogmatic basis as that of Descartes. We have already intimated (section 14) that passing over the world and those beings initially encountered is not a matter of chance, not an oversight which we could simply make up for, but rather is grounded in the essential kind of being of Da-sein itself. When our analytic of Da-sein has made the most important basic structures of Da-sein transparent in the scope of this problematic, when we have assigned to being in general the horizon of its possible intelligibility,* thus first making handiness and objective presence ontologically and primordially intelligible, too, only then can the critique of the Cartesian ontology of the world, basically still customary today, claim its philosophical justification. To do this, we must show several things (cf. Part I, Division 3): 1. Why was the phenomenon of world passed over at the beginning of the ontological tradition decisive for us, explicitly in Parmenides; where does the constant recurrence of this passing over come from? 2. Why do innerworldly beings take the place of the phenomenon thus passed over as the ontological theme? 3. Why are these beings initially found in "nature"? 4. Why does the rounding out of such an ontology of the world, experienced as necessary, take place with the help of the phenomenon of value? In the answers to these questions a positive understanding of the problematic of the world will be reached, for the first time the source of our failure to recognize it will be demonstrated and the justification for rejecting the traditional ontology of the world will have been demonstrated. The world and Da-sein and innerworldly beings are the ontologically constitutive states nearest to us; but we have no guarantee that we achieve the basis for encountering them phenomenally by the seemingly obvious procedure of starting with the things of the world, still less by taking our orientation from what is supposedly the most rigorous knowledge of beings. Our remarks about Descartes should have brought us this insight. But if we recall that spatiality also manifestly constitutes innerworldly beings, it is, after all, possible to "salvage" the Cartesian analysis of the "world" in the long run. With his radical exposition of extensio as the praesuppositum for every quality of the res corporea, Descartes pre-
* Sic! Of course, "intelligibility" is based on understanding as project, project as ecstatic temporality.
101
94
Being and Time
I. III
pared the way for the understanding of an a priori whose content Kant then made precise with greater penetration. Within certain limits, the analysis of extensio remains independent of his neglecting to provide an explicit interpretation of the being of extended beings. Taking extensio as the basic determination of the "world" has its phenomenal justification, although in recourse to it neither the spatiality of the world nor the spatiality initially discovered of beings encountered in the surrounding world, nor even the spatiality of Da-sein itself, can be conceived ontologically.
C.
102
THE AROUNDNESS OF THE SURROUNDING WORLD AND THE SPATIALITY OF DA-SEIN
In connection with our first preliminary sketch of being-in (cf. section 12), Da-sein had to be contrasted with a way of being in space which we call insideness. This means that a being which is itself extended is surrounded by the extended boundaries of something extended. The being which is inside and what surrounds it are both objectively present in space. Our rejection of such an insideness of Da-sein in a spatial container should not, however, basically exclude all spatiality of Da-sein, but only keep the way dear for seeing the kind of spatiality which is constitutive for Da-sein. This must now be set forth. But since innerworldly beings are also in space, their spatiality has an ontological connection with the world.* Thus we must determine in what sense space is constitutive for the world which in tum was characterized as a structural factor of being-in-the-world. We must especially show how the aroundness of the surrounding world, the specific spatiality of the beings encountered in the surrounding world is grounded in the worldliness of the world, and not the other way around, that is, we cannot say that the world in its tum is objectively present in space. Our study of the spatiality of Da-sein and the spatial definiteness of the world takes its point of departure from an analysis of the innerworldly things at hand in space. We shall consider three stages: ( 1) The spatiality of innerworldly things at hand (section 22). (2) The spatiality of being-in-the-world (section 23). (3) The spatiality ofDa-sein and space (section 24).
22. The Spatiality of Innerworldly Things at Hand If space constitutes the world in a sense which we have yet to determine, it cannot be surprising that in our foregoing ontological charac-
* Thus world is also spatial.
1.111
Being and Time
95
terization of the being of what is within the world we already had to have that being in view as something in space, too. This spatiality of things at hand has not yet been grasped phenomenally in an explicit way and its interconnection with the structures of being of what is at hand has not yet been demonstrated. That is now the task. To what extent have we already bumped up against this spatiality in our characterization of what is at hand? We spoke of what is initially at hand. This means not only beings which we encounter first before others, but means at the same time beings that are "near by." The things at hand of everyday association have the character of nearness. To be exact, this nearness of useful things is already hinted at in the term which expresses their being, in "handiness." Beings "at hand" have their various proximities which are not ascertained by measuring distances. Their nearness is determined by the handling and use that circumspectly "calculate." The circumspection of taking care of things at the same time establishes what is thus near with respect to the direction in which useful things are always accessible. The structured nearness of useful things means that they do not simply have a place in space, objectively present somewhere, but as useful things are essentially installed, put in their place, set up, and put in order. Useful things have their place, or else they "lie around," which is fundamentally different from merely occurring in a random spatial position. The actual place is defined as the place of this useful thing for ... in terms of a totality of the interconnected places of the context of useful things at hand in the surrounding world. Place and the multiplicity of places must not be interpreted as the where of a random objective presence of things. Place is always the definite "over there" and the "there" of a useful thing belonging there. Actual belonging there corresponds to the useful character of what is at hand, that is, to its relevant belonging to a totality of useful things. But a whereto in general, in which the positional totality is referred to a context of useful things, underlies the positional belonging somewhere of a totality of useful things as the condition of their possibility. We call this whereto of the possible belonging somewhere of useful things, circumspectly held in view in advance, and heedful association, the region. "In the region of" means not only "in the direction of," but also in the orbit of something that lies in that direction. The kind of place which is constituted by direction and remoteness-nearness is only a mode of the latter-is already oriented toward a region and within that region. Something akin to a region must already be discovered if there is to be any possibility of referring and finding the places of a totality of useful things available to circumspection. This regional orientation of the multiplicity of places of what is at hand constitutes the aroundness,
103
96
104
Being and Time
I.m
the being around us of beings encountered initially in the surrounding world. There is never a three-dimensional multiplicity of possible positions initially given which is then filled out with objectively present things. This dimensionality of space is still veiled in the spatiality of what is at hand. The "above" is what is "on the ceiling," the "below" is what is "on the floor," the "behind" is what is "at the door." All these wheres are discovered and circumspectly interpreted on the paths and ways of everyday associations, they are not ascertained and catalogued by the observational measurement of space. Regions are not first formed by things objectively present together, but are always already at hand in individual places. The places themselves are assigned to what is at hand in the circumspection of taking care of things, or else we come across them. Thus things constantly at hand, with which circumspect being-in-the-world reckons from the outset, have their place. The where of their handiness is taken account of in taking care of things and is oriented toward other handy things. Thus the sun whose light and warmth we make use of every day has its circumspectly discovered, eminent places in terms of the changing usability of what it gives us: sunrise, noon, sunset, midnight. The places of these things, which are constantly at hand in various ways and yet uniformly, become accentuated "indicators" of the regions contained in them. These regions of the sky which do not yet need to have any geographical meaning at all, give beforehand the whereto for every particular development of regions which can be occupied by places. The house has its sunny side and its shady side. This provides the orientation for dividing up the "rooms" and "arranging" them according to their useful character. Churches and graves, for example, are laid out according to the rising and setting of the sun-the regions of life and death which determine Da-sein itself with regard to its ownmost possibilities of being in the world. In taking care of things Da-sein which is in its very being concerned about that being, discovers beforehand the regions which are each in a decisive relevance. The discovery of regions beforehand is determined by the totality of relevance for which what is at hand is set free as something encountered. The handiness which belongs to each region beforehand has as the being of what is at hand the character of inconspicuous familiarity in a more primordial sense. The familiarity itself becomes visible in a conspicuous manner only when what is at hand is discovered circumspectly in the deficient mode of taking care of things. When we do not find something in its place, the region of that place often becomes explicitly accessible as such for the first time. Space, which is discovered in circumspect being-in-the-world as the spatiality of a totality of useful things, belongs to beings themselves as their place. Bare space is still veiled.
Being and Time
I. III
97
Space is split up into places.* But this spatiality has its own unity by virtue of the worldlike totality of relevance of what is spatially at hand. The "surrounding world" does not arrange itself in a previously given space, but rather its specific worldliness articulates in its significance the relevant context of an actual totality of places circumspectly referred to each other. The actual world discovers the spatiality of space belonging to it. The fact that what is at hand can be encountered in its space of the surrounding world is ontically possible only because Da-sein itself is "spatial" with regard to its being-in-the-world.
23. The Spatiality of Being-in-the-World When we attribute spatiality to Da-sein, this "being in space" must evidently be understood in tenns of the kind of being of this being. The spatiality of Da-sein, which is essentially not objective presence, can mean neither something like being found in a position in "world space" nor being at hand in a place. Both of these are kinds of being belonging to beings encountered in the world. But Da-sein is "in" the world in the sense of a familiar and heedful association with the beings encountered within the world. Thus when spatiality is attributed to it in some way, this is possible only on the basis of this being-in. But the spatiality of being-in shows the character of de-distancing and directionality. By de-distancing as a kind of being of Da-sein with regard to its being-in-the-world, we do not understand anything like remoteness (nearness) or even being at a distance. We use the expression de-distancing in an active and transitive sense. It means a constitution of being of Da-sein of which de-distancing something, putting it away, is only a definite, factical mode. De-distancing means making distance disappear,t making the being at a distance of something disappear, bringing it near. Da-sein is essentially de-distancing. As the being that it is, it lets beings be encountered in nearness. De-distancing discovers remoteness. Remoteness, like distance, is a categorial determination of beings unlike Da-sein. De-distancing, on the other hand, must be kept in mind as an existential. Only because beings in general are discovered by Da-sein in their remoteness, do "distances" and intervals among innerworldly beings become accessible in relation to other things. Two points are as little remote from each other as two things in general because neither of these beings can de-distance in accordance with its kind of being. They
* No, rather a peculiar unity of places that are not split up. t
l
Where does the distance come from that is de-distanced? Nearness and presence (AnW&renheit), not the extent of the distance, is essential.
105
98
106
Being and Time
1.111
merely have a measurable distance between them which is encountered in de-distancing.* Initially and for the most part, de-distancing is a circumspect approaching, a bringing near as supplying, preparing, having at hand. But particular kinds of the purely cognitive discovery ofbeings also have the character of bringing near. An essential tendency toward nearness lies in Da· sein. t All kinds of increasing speed which we are more or less compelled to go along with today push for overcoming distance. With the "radio," for example, Da-sein is bringing about today de-distancing of the "world" which is unforeseeable in its meaning for Da-sein, by way of expanding and destroying the everyday surrounding world. De-distancing does not necessarily imply an explicit estimation of the farness of things at hand in relation to Da-sein. Above all, remoteness is never understood as measurable distance. If farness is estimated, this is done relative to the de-distancing in which everyday Da-sein is involved. In the calculative sense these estimations may be imprecise and variable, but they have their own thoroughly intelligible definiteness in the everydayness of Da-sein. We say that to go over there is a good walk, a stone's throw, as long it takes to smoke a pipe. These measures express the fact that they not only do not intend to "measure," but that the estimated remoteness belongs to a being which one approaches in a circumspect, heedful way. But even when we use more exact measures and say "it takes half an hour to get to the house," this measure must be understood as an estimation. "Half an hour" is not thirty minutes, but a duration which does not have any "length" in the sense of a quantitative stretch. Tills duration is always interpreted in terms of familiar, everyday "activities." Even where "officially" calculated measurements are familiar, remoteness is initially estimated circumspectly. Because what is de-distanced is at hand in such estimates, it retains its specifically innerworldly character. This even implies that the paths we take in our associations to remote beings are of different lengths every day. What is at hand in the surrounding world is, after all, not objectively present for an eternal spectator exempt from Da-sein, but is encountered in the circumspect, heedful everydayness of Da-sein. On these paths Da-sein does not traverse, like an objectively present corporeal thing, a stretch of space, it does not "eat up kilometers"; nearing and de-distancing are always a heedful being toward what is approached and de-distanced. An "objectively" long path can be shorter than an "objectively" much shorter path which is perhaps an "onerous one" and strikes one as infinitely long.
* De-distancing is more precise [schiiifer] than nearing. t
To what extent and why? Being qua constant presence [bestiindige Anwesen·
heit] has priority, making present.
1.111
Being and Time
99
When it "strikes" one thus, however, the actual world is first truly at hand. The objective distances of objectively present things do not coincide with the remoteness and nearness of what is at hand within the world. The former may be exactly known, but this knowledge is blind. It does not have the function of the circumspectly discovering approach to the surrounding world. One uses such knowledge only in and for a heedful being which does not measure stretches and which is related to the world which "concerns" us. When there is a prior orientation toward "nature" and the "objectively" measured distances of things, one is inclined to consider such interpretations and estimates of remoteness "subjective." However, that is a "subjectivity" which perhaps discovers what is most real about the "reality" of the world, which has nothing to do with "subjective" arbitrariness and the subjectivistic "conceptions" of beings which are "in themselves" otherwise. The circumspect de-distancing of everyday Da-sein discovers the being-in-itself of the "true" world, of beings with which Da-sein as existing is always already together. The primary and even exclusive orientation toward remoteness as measured distances, obscures the primordial spatiality of being-in. What is supposedly "nearest" is by no means that which has the smallest distance "from us." What is "near" lies in that which is in the circle of an average reach, grasp, and look. Since Da-sein is essentially spatial in the manner of de-distancing, its associations always take place in a "surrounding world" which is remote from it in a certain leeway. Thus we initially always overlook and fail to hear what is measurably "nearest" to us. Seeing and hearing are senses of distance not because of their scope, but because Da-sein, de-distancing, predominantly lives in them. For someone who, for example, wears spectacles which are distantially so near to him that they are "sitting on his nose," this useful thing is further away in the surrounding world than the picture on the wall across the room. This useful thing has so little nearness that it is often not even to be found at all initially. Useful things for seeing, and those for hearing, for example, the telephone receiver, have the inconspicuousness of what is initially at hand which we characterized. That is also true, for example, of the street, the useful thing for walking. When we walk, we feel it with every step and it seems to be what is nearest and most real about what is generally at hand, it slides itself, so to speak, along certain parts of our body-the soles of one's feet. And yet it is further remote than the acquaintance one meets while walking at the "remoteness" twenty steps away "on the street." Circumspect heedfulness decides about the nearness and farness of what is initially at hand in the surrounding world. Whatever this heedfulness dwells in from the beginning is what is nearest, and regulates our de-distancing.
107
100
108
Being and Time
1.111
When Da-sein in taking care brings something near, this does not mean that it flxes upon something at a position in space which has the least measurable distance from a point of its body. To be near means to be in the range of what is initially at hand for circumspection. Bringing near is not oriented toward the I-thing encumbered with a body, but rather toward heedful being-in-the-world, that is, what that being-in-theworld initially encounters. Neither is the spatiality of Da-sein determined by citing the position where a corporeal thing is objectively present. It is true that we also say of Da-sein that it occupies a place. But this "occupying" is to be fundamentally differentiated from being at hand at a place in terms of a region. Occupying a place must be understood as dedistancing what is at hand in the surrounding world in a region previously discovered circumspectly beforehand. Da-sein understands its here in terms of the over there of the surrounding world. The here does not mean the where of something objectively present, but the where of dedistancing being with ... together with this de-distancing. In accordance with its spatiality, Da-sein is initially never here, but over there. From this over there it comes back to its here, and it does this only by interpreting its heedful being toward something in terms of what is at hand over there. This becomes quite clear from a phenomenal peculiarity of being-in which has the structure of de-distancing. As being-in-the-world, Da-sein essentially dwells in de-distancing. This de-distancing, the farness from itself of what is at hand, is something that Da-sein can never cross over. It is true that Da-sein can take the remoteness of something at hand to be distance if that remoteness is determined in relation to a thing which is thought of as being objectively present at a place which Da-sein has already occupied. Da-sein can subsequently traverse the "between" of this distance, but only in such a way that the distance itself becomes de-distanced. So little has Da-sein crossed over its de-distancing that it rather has taken it along and continues to do so because it is essentially de-distancing, that is, it is spatial. Dasein cannot wander around in the current range of its de-distancings, it can only change them. Da-sein is spatial by way of circumspectly discovering space so that it is related to .beings thus spatially encountered by constantly de-distancing. As being-in which de-distances, Da-sein has at the same time the character of directionality. Every bringing near has always taken a direction in a region beforehand from which what is de-distanced approaches so that it can be discovered with regard to its place. Circumspect heedfulness is a directional de-distancing. In this heedfulness, that is, in the being-in-the-world of Da-sein itself, the need for "signs" is already present. As useful things, signs take over the giving of directions in a way which is explicit and easily handled. They explicitly keep the circum-
1.111
Being and Time
101
spectly used regions open, the actual whereto of belonging, going, bringing, fetching. If Da-sein is, it always already has directing and de-distancing, its discovered region. As modes of being of being-in-the-world, directing and de-distancing are guided beforehand by the circumspection of heedfulness. The firm directions of right and left originate out of this directionality. Da-sein continually takes these directions along together with its de-distancing. The spatialization ofDa-sein in its "corporeality," which contains a problematic of its own not to be discussed here, is also marked out in accordance with these directions. Thus things at hand and in use for the body, such as gloves, for example, that must go along with the hands' movement, must be oriented in terms of right and left. Tools, however, which are held in the hand and moved with it, do not go along with the specifically "handlike" movement of the hand Thus there are no right- and left-handed hammers, even though they are held with the hand as gloves are. But we must observe the fact that the directionality that belongs to de-distancing is grounded in being-in-the-world. Left and right are not something "subjective" for which the subject has a feeling, but they are directions of orientation in a world which is always already at hand. I could never find my way around in a world "by the mere feeling of a difference between my two sides. "22 The subject with the "mere feeling" of this difference is a construct posited without regard to the true constitution of the subject, namely that whenever Da-sein has this "mere feeling" it is always already in a world and must be in order to be able to orient itself at all. This becomes clear in the example with which Kant tries to clarify the phenomenon of orientation. Let us assume that I enter a familiar but dark room which has been rearranged during my absence in such a way that everything which was on the right-hand side is now on the left-hand side. If I am to get oriented, the "mere feeling of the difference" between my two sides does not help at all as long as I do not apprehend some particular object "whose position," as Kant casually remarks, "I have in mind." But what else does this mean except that I necessarily orient myself in and from already being in a "familiar"* world. The context of useful things in a world must already be given to Da-sein. The fact that I am always already in a world is no less constitutive for the possibility of orientation than the feeling for right and left. That this constitution of being of Da-sein is obvious does not justify suppressing it in its ontologically constitutive role. Kant does not suppress it either, any more than any other inter-
* From a familiar belongingness that I hold before myself and vary accordingly.
109
102
110
Being and Time
1.111
pretation of Da-sein. Continual use of this constitution does not, however, exempt us from giving an adequate ontological explication, but rather requires it. The psychological interpretation that the ego has something "in mind" fundamentally refers to the existential constitution of being-in-the-world. Because Kant did not see this structure, he failed to understand the full context of the constitution of a possible orientation. Directedness toward the right or the left is grounded in the essential directionality of Da-sein in general, which in turn is essentially determined by being-in-the-world. However, Kant is not interested in a thematic interpretation of orientation, either. He only wishes to show that all orientation needs a "subjective principle." But "subjective" means here a priori. The a priori of directionality in terms of right and left, however, is grounded in the "subjective" a priori of being-in-the-world, which has nothing to do with a determinate character restricted beforehand to a worldless subject. As constitutive characteristics of being-in, de-distancing and directionality determine the spatiality of Da-sein, for its being heedfully and circumspectly in discovered innerworldly space. Our previous explication of the spatiality of innerworldly things at hand and the spatiality of being-in-the-world first give the presuppositions for working out the phenomenon of the spatiality of the world and for asking about the ontological problem of space.
24. The Spatiality of Da-sein and Space As being-in-the-world, Da-sein has always already discovered a "world." We characterized this discovering which is founded in the worldliness of the world as the freeing of beings for a totality of relevance. Freeing something and letting it be relevant occur by way of circumspect selfreference which is grounded in a previous understanding of signification. We have now shown that circumspect being-in-the-world is spatial. And only because Da-sein is spatial by way of de-distancing and directionality can things at hand in the surrounding world be encountered in their spatiality. The freeing of a totality of relevance is equiprimordially a letting something be relevant in a region which de-distances and gives direction. It is a freeing of the spatial belongingness of things at hand. The essential disclosure of space lies in the significance with which Dasein as heedful being-in is familiar. Space that is disclosed with the worldliness of the world does not yet have the characteristic of a pure manifold of three dimensions. In this nearest disclosedness, space is still hidden as the pure wherein in which points are ordered by measurement and the positions of things are determined. With the phenomenon of the region we have already indi-
I.m
Being and Time
103
cated that for which space is discovered beforehand in Da-sein. We understand the region as that to which the context of useful things at hand possibly belongs, a context which can be encountered as something directional, that is, containing places and as de-distanced. The belongingness is determined by the significance constitutive for the world and articulates the here and there within the possible whereto. The whereto in general is prefigured by the referential totality established in a for-the-sake-of-which of heedfulness. Freeing and letting something be relevant is referred within this totality. With what is encountered as things at hand, there is always relevance in a region. A regional spatial relevance belongs to the totality of relevance which constitutes the being of things at hand in the surrounding world. On the basis of this relevance, things at hand can be found and determined according to form and direction. In accordance with the possible transparency of heedful circumspection, innerworldly things at hand are dedistanced and oriented with the factical being of Da-sein. Letting innerworldly beings be encountered, which is constitutive for being-in-the-world, is "giving space." This "giving space," which we call making room, frees things at hand for their spatiality. As a way of discovering and presenting a possible totality of places relevantly determined, making room makes actual factical orientation possible. As circumspect taking care of things in the world, Da-sein can change things around, remove them or "make room" for them only because making room-understood as an existential-belongs to its being-in-the-world. But neither the previously discovered region nor the actual spatiality in general are explicitly in view. In itself, it is present in the inconspicuousness of things at hand being taken care of by a circumspection absorbed in them for that circumspection. Space is initially discovered in this spatiality with being-in-the-world. On the basis of the spatiality thus discovered, space itself becomes accessible to cognition. Space is neither in the subject nor is the world in space. Rather, space is "in" the world since the being-in-the-world constitutive for Da-sein has disclosed space. Space is not in the subject, nor does that subject observe the world "as if' it were in space. Rather, the "subject," correctly understood ontologically, Da-sein, is spatial in a primordial sense. And because Da-sein is spatial in the way described, space shows itself as a priori. This term does not mean something like belonging beforehand to an initially worldless subject which spins a space out of itself. Here, apriority means the previousness of encountering space (as region) in the actual encountering of things at hand in the surrounding world. The spatiality of what is initially circumspectly encountered can itself become thematic and the task of calculation and measurement for circumspection, for example, in building a house and surveying
Ill
112
104
113
Being and Time
l.m
land. With this predominantly circumspect thematization of the spatiality of the surrounding world, space in itself already comes to view in a way. The space which thus shows itself can be studied by purely looking at it if the former sole possibility of access to space, circumspect calculation, is given up. The " formal intuition" of space discovers pure possibilities of spatial relations. Here there is a series of stages laying bare pure homogeneous space, going from the pure morphology of spatial shapes to analysis situs and finally to the purely metrical science of space. In this present study we shall not consider how these are all interconnected. 23 In our problematic we wish solely to establish ontologically the phenomenal basis for the thematic discovery and working out of pure space. Where space is discovered non-circumspectly by just looking at it, the regions of the surrounding world get neutralized to pure dimensions. The places and the totality of places of useful things at hand, which are circumspectly oriented, are reduced to a multiplicity of positions for random things. The spatiality of innerworldly things at hand thus loses its character of relevance. The world loses its specific character of aroundness, the surrounding world becomes the natural world. "The world" as a totality of useful things at hand is spatialized to become a connection of extended things which are merely objectively present. The homogeneous space of nature shows itself only when the beings we encounter are discovered in such a way that the worldly character of what is at hand gets specifically deprived of its worldliness. In accordance with its being-in-the-world, Da-sein has always already been pre-given its discovered space, even if unthematically. On the other hand, space in itself is initially still obscured with regard to the mere possibilities of the pure spatial being of something contained in it. The fact that space essentially shows itself in a world does not tell us anything about its kind of being. It need not have the kind of being of something itself at hand in space or objectively present. Nor does the being of space have the kind of being of Da-sein. From the fact that the being of space itself cannot be conceived as the kind of being of res extensa, it follows neither that it must be ontologically determined as "phenomenon" of this res-it would not be distinguished from that res in its being-nor that the being of space can be equated with that of the res cogitans and be conceived as something merely "subjective," quite apart from the questionability of the being of this subject. The perplexity still present today with regard to the interpretation of the being of space is grounded not so much in an inadequate knowledge of the factual constitution of space itself as in the lack of a fundamental transparency of the possibilities of being in general and of their ontologically conceived interpretation. What is decisive for the
1.111
Being and Time
105
understanding of the ontological problem of space lies in freeing the question of the being of space from the narrowness of the accidentally available and, moreover, undifferentiated concepts of being, and, with respect to the phenomenon itself, in moving the problematic of the being of space and the various phenomenal spatialities in the direction of clarifying the possibilities of being in general. The primary ontological character of the being of innerworldly beings is not found in the phenomenon of space, either as unique or as one among others. Still less does space constitute the phenomenon of world. Space can only be understood by going back to the world. Space does not become accessible only by depriving the surrounding world of its worldliness. Spatiality can be discovered in general only on the basis of world in such a way that space, after all, also constitutes the world in accordance with the essential spatiality of Da-sein itself with regard to its fundamental constitution of being-in-the-world.
IV Being-in-the-World as Being-with and Being a Self: The "They"
The analysis of the worldliness of the world continually brought the whole phenomenon of being-in-the-world into view without thereby delimiting all of its constitutive factors with the same phenomenal clarity as the phenomenon of world itself. The ontological interpretation of the world which discussed innerworldly things at hand came first not only because Da-sein in its everydayness is in a world in general and remains a constant theme with regard to that world, but because it relates itself to the world in a predominant mode of being. Initially and for the most part, Da-sein is taken in by its world. This mode of being, being absorbed in the world, and thus being-in which underlies it, essentially determine the phenomenon which we shall now pursue with the question: Who is it who is in the everydayness of Da-sein? All of the structures of being of Da-sein, thus also the phenomenon that answers to this question of who, are modes of its being. Their ontological characteristic is an existential one. Thus, we need to pose the question correctly and outline the procedure for bringing to view a broader phenomenal domain of the everydayness of Da-sein. By investigating in the direction of the phenomenon which allows us to answer the question of the who, we are led to structures of Da-sein which are equiprimordial with being-in-the-world: being-with and Mitda-sein. In this kind of being, the mode of everyday being a self is grounded whose explication makes visible what we might call the "subject" of everydayness, the they. This chapter on the "who" of average Da-sein thus has the following structure:
107
114
108
Being and Time
I. IV
( 1) The approach to the existential question of the who of Da-sein (section 25 ). (2) The Mitda-sein of the others and everyday being-with (section 26). (3) Everyday being a self and the they (section 27). 25. The Approach to the Existential Q}lestion of the Who of Da-sein
115
The answer to the question of who this being actually is (Da-sein) seems to have already been given with the formal indication of the basic characteristics of Da-sein (cf. section 9). Da-sein is a being which I myself am, its being is in each case mine. This determination indicates an ontological constitution, but no more than that. At the same time, it contains an ontic indication, albeit an undifferentiated one, that an I is always this being, and not others. The who is answered in terms of the I itself, the "subject," the "self." The who is what maintains itself in the changes throughout its modes of behavior and experiences as something identical and is, thus, related to this multiplicity. Ontologically, we understand it as what is always already and constantly objectively present in a closed region and for that region, as that which lies at its basis in an eminent sense, as the subjectum. As something self-same in manifold otherness, this subject has the character of the self. Even if one rejects a substantial soul, the thingliness of consciousness and the objectivity of the person, ontologically one still posits something whose being retains the meaning of objective presence, whether explicitly or not. Substantiality is the ontological clue for the determination of beings in terms ofwhom the question of the who is answered. Da-sein is tacitly conceived in advance as objective presence. In any case, the indeterminacy of its being always implies this meaning of being. However, objective presence is the mode of being of beings unlike Da-sein. The ontic obviousness of the statement that it is I who is in each case Da-sein must not mislead us into supposing that the way for an ontological interpretation of what is thus "given" has been unmistakably prescribed. It is even questionable whether the ontic content of the above statement reaches the phenomenal content of everyday Dasein. It could be the case that the who of everyday Da-sein is precisely not I myself. Even when we manage to gain ontic and ontological statements, if the phenomenal demonstration in terms of the mode of being of beings is to retain priority over the most obvious and usual answers and the problems arising from these, the phenomenological interpretation of Da-sein must be protected from a distortion of the problematic with regard to the question to be raised now. But does it not go against the rules of a sound method when the approach to a problematic does not stick to the evident data of the the-
I.IV
Being and Time
109
matic realm? And what is less dubious than the givenness of the I? And (for the purpose of working this givenness out in a primordial way) does it not direct us to abstract from everything else that is "given," not only from an existing "world," but also from the being of the other "l"'s? Perhaps what gives this kind of giving, this simple, formal, reflective perception of the I, is indeed evident. This insight even opens access to an independent phenomenological problematic which has its fundamental significance in the framework known as "formal phenomenology of consciousness." In the present context of an existential analytic of factical Da-sein, the question arises whether the way of the giving of the I which we mentioned discloses Da-sein in its everydayness, if it discloses it at all. Is it then a priori self-evident that the access to Da-sein must be simple perceiving reflection of the I of acts? What if this kind of "self-giving" of Dasein were to lead our existential analytic astray and do so in a way grounded in the being of Da-sein itself? Perhaps when Da-sein addresses itself in the way which is nearest to itself, it always says it is I, and finally says this most loudly when it is "not" this being. What if the fact that Dasein is so constituted that it is in each case mine, were the reason for the fact that Da-sein is, initially and for the most part, not itselfl What if, with the approach mentioned above, the existential analytic fell into the trap, so to speak, of starting with the givenness of the I for Da-sein itself and its obvious self-interpretation? What if it should turn out that the ontological horizon for the determination of what is accessible in simple giving should remain fundamentally undetermined? We can probably always correctly say ontically of this being that "I" am it. However, the ontological analytic which makes use of such statements must have fundamental reservations about them. The "I" must be understood only in the sense of a noncommittal formal indication of something which perhaps reveals itself in the actual phenomenal context of being as that being's "opposite." Then "not I" by no means signifies something like a being which is essentially lacking "1-hood," but means a definite mode of being of the "I" itself; for example, having lost itself.* But even the positive interpretation of Da-sein that has been given up to now already forbids a point of departure from the formal givenness of the I if the intention is to find a phenomenally adequate answer to the question of value. The clarification of being-in-the-world showed that a mere subject without a world "is" not initially and is also never given. And, thus, an isolated I without the others is in the end just as far from being given initially! But if the "others" are always already there with
* Or else genuine selfhood as opposed to miserable egotism.
116
110
Being and Time
I.Iv
us in being-in-the-world, ascertaining this phenomenally, too, must not mislead us into thinking that the ontological structure of what is thus
117
"given" is self-evident and not in need of an investigation. The task is to make this Mitda-sein of the nearest everydayness phenomenally visible and to interpret it in an ontologically adequate way. Just as the antic, self-evident character of being-in-itself of innerworldly beings misleads us to the conviction of the ontological self-evident character of the meaning of this being and makes us overlook the phenomenon of world, the antic, self-evident character that Da-sein is always my own also harbors the possibility that the ontological problematic indigenous to it might be led astray. Initially the who of Da-sein is not only a problem ontologically, it also remains concealed ontically. But, then, is the existential analytical answer to the question of the who without any dues at all? By no means. To be sure, of the formal indications of the constitution of being of Da-sein given above (sections 9 and 12), it is not so much the one which we discussed which is functional, but rather, the one according to which the "essence" of Da-sein is grounded in its existence. If the "I" is an essential determination of Da-sein, it must be interpreted existentially. The question of the who can then be answered only by a phenomenal demonstration of a definite kind of being of Da-sein. If Da-sein is always only its self in existing, the constancy of the self as well as its possible "inconstancy" require an existential-ontological kind of questioning as the only adequate access to the problematic. But if the self is conceived "only" as a way of the being of this being, then that seems tantamount to volatizing the true "core" of Dasein. But such fears are nourished by the incorrect preconception that the being in question really has, after all, the kind of being of something objectively present, even if one avoids attributing to it the massive element of a corporeal thing. However, the "substance" of human being is not the spirit as the synthesis of body and soul, but existence. 26. The Mitda-sein of the Others and Everyday Being-with
The answer to the question of the who of everyday Da-sein is to be won through the analysis of the kind of being in which Da-sein, initially and for the most part, lives. Our investigation takes its orientation from being-in-the-world. This fundamental constitution of Da-sein determines every mode of its being. If we justifiably stated that all other structural factors of being-in-the-world already came into view by means of the previous explication of the world, the answer to the question of the who must also be prepared by that explication. The "description" of the surrounding world nearest to us, for example, the work-world of the handworker, showed that together with the
I.JV
Being and Time
111
useful things found in work, others are "also encountered" for whom the "work" is to be done. In the kind of being of these things at hand, that is, in their relevance, there lies an essential reference to possible wearers for whom they should be "cut to the figure." Similarly, the producer or "supplier" is encountered in the material used as one who "serves" well or badly. The field, for example, along which we walk "outside" shows itself as belonging to such and such a person who keeps it in good order, the book which we use is bought at such and such a place, given by such and such a person, and so on. The boat anchored at the shore refers in its being-in-itself to an acquaintance who undertakes his voyages with it, but as a "boat strange to us," it also points to others. The others who are "encountered" in the context of useful things in the surrounding world at hand are not somehow added on in thought to an initially merely objectively present thing, but these "things" are encountered from the world in which they are at hand for the others. This world is always already from the outset my own. In our previous analysis, the scope of what is encountered in the world was initially narrowed down to useful things at hand, or nature objectively present, thus to beings of a character unlike Da-sein. This restriction was not only necessary for the purpose of simplifying the explication; but, above all, because the kind of being of the existence of the others encountered within the surrounding world is distinct from handiness and objective presence. The world of Da-sein thus frees beings which are not only completely different from tools and things, but which themselves in accordance with their kind of being as Da-sein are themselves "in" the world as being-in-the-world in which they are at the same time encountered. These beings are neither objectively present nor at hand, but they are like the very Da-sein which frees them-they are there, too, and there with it. So, if one wanted to identify the world in general with innerworldly beings, one would have to say the "world" is also Da-sein. But the characteristic of encountering the others is, after all, oriented toward one's own Da-sein. Does not it, too, start with the distinction and isolation of the "I," so that a transition from this isolated subject to the others must then be sought? In order to avoid this misunderstanding, we must observe in what sense we are talking about "the others." "The others" does not mean everybody else but me-those from whom the I distinguishes itself. They are, rather, those from whom one mostly does not distinguish oneself, those among whom one is, too. This being-there-too with them does not have the ontological character of being objectively present "with" them within a world. The "with" is of the character of Da-sein, the "also" means the sameness of being as circumspect, heedful being-in-the-world. "With" and "also" are to be understood existentially, not categorially. On the basis of this like·with being-inthe-world, the world is always already the one that I share with the
118
112
119
120
Being and Time
I. IV
others. The world of Da-sein is a with-world. Being-in is being-with others. The innerworldly being-in-itself of others is Mitda-sein. The others are not encountered by grasping and previously discriminating one's own subject, initially objectively present, from other subjects also present. They are not encountered by first looking at oneself and then ascertaining the opposite pole of a distinction. They are encountered from the world in which Da-sein, heedful and circumspect, essentially dwells. As opposed to the theoretically concocted "explanations" of the objective presence of others which easily urge themselves upon us, we must hold fast to the phenomenal fact which we have indicated of their being encountered in the surrounding world. This nearest and elemental way of Da-sein of being encountered in the world goes so far that even one's own Da-sein initially becomes "discoverable" by looking away from its "experiences" and the "center of its actions" or by not yet "seeing" them all. Da-sein initially finds "itself' in what it does, needs, expects, has charge of, in the things at hand which it initially takes care of in the surrounding world. And even when Da-sein explicitly addresses itself as "I here," the locative personal designation must be understood in terms of the existential spatiality of Da-sein. When we interpreted this (section 23), we already intimated that this I-here does not mean an eminent point of an I-thing, but as being-in is to be understood in terms of the over there of the world at hand where Da-sein dwells in taking care. W. V. Humboldt2 has alluded to certain languages which express the "I" by "here," the "thou" by "there," and the "he" by "over there," thus rendering the personal pronouns by locative adverbs, to put it grammatically. It is controversial whether the primordial meaning of locative expressions is adverbial or pronominal. This dispute loses its basis if one notes that locative adverbs have a relation to the I qua Dasein. The "here," "over there," and "there" are not primarily pure locative designati~ns of innerworldly beings objectively present at positions in space, but, rather, characteristics of the primordial spatiality of Dasein. The supposedly locative adverbs are determinations of Da-sein; they have primarily an existential, not a categorial, meaning. But they are not pronouns, either. Their significance is prior to the distinction of locative adverbs and personal pronouns. The true spatial meaning of these expressions for Da-sein, however, documents the fact that the theoretically undistorted interpretation of Da-sein sees the latter immediately in its spatial "being-together-with" the world taken care of, spatial in the sense of de-distancing and directionality. In the "here" Da-sein, absorbed in its world, does not address itself, but speaks away from itself, in circumspection, to the "over there" of something at hand and means, however, itself in its existential spatiality.
I.IV
Being and Time
113
Da-sein understands itself, initially and for the most part, in terms of its world, and the Mitda-sein of others is frequently encountered from innerworldly things at hand. But when the others become, so to speak, thematic in their Da-sein, they are not encountered as objectively present thing-persons, but we meet them "at work," that is, primarily in their being-in-the-world. Even when we see the other "just standing around," he is never understood as a human-thing objectively present. "Standing around" is an existential mode of being, the lingering with everything and nothing which lacks heedfulness and circumspection. The other is encountered in his Mitda-sein in the world. But, after all, the expression "Da-sein" clearly shows that this being is "initially" unrelated to others, that it can, of course, also be "with" others subsequently. But we must not overlook the fact that we are also using the tenn Mitda-sein as a designation of the being to which the existing others are freed within the world. The Mitda-sein of others is disclosed only within the world for a Da-sein and thus also for those who are Mitda-sein, because Da-sein in itself is essentially being-with. The phenomenological statement that Da-sein is essentially being-with has an existential-ontological meaning. It does not intend to ascertain ontically that I am factically not objectively present alone, rather that others of my kind also are. If the statement that the being-in-the-world of Da-sein is essentially constituted by being-with meant something like this, being-with would not be an existential attribute that belongs to Da-sein of itself on the basis of its kind of being, but something which occurs at times on the basis of the existence of others. Being-with existentially determines Da-sein even when an other is not factically present and perceived. The being-alone of Da-sein, too, is being-with in the world. The other can be lacking only in and for a beingwith. Being-alone is a deficient mode of being-with, its possibility is a proof for the latter. On the other hand, factical being alone is not changed by the fact that a second copy of a human being is "next to" me, or perhaps ten human beings. Even when these and still more are objectively present, Da-sein can be alone. Thus, being-with and the facti city of beingwith-one-another are not based on the fact that several "subjects" are physically there together. Being alone "among" many, however, does not mean with respect to the being of others that they are simply objectively present. Even in being "among them," they are there with. Their Mitda-sein is encountered in the mode of indifference and being alien. Lacking and "being away" are modes of Mitda-sein and are possible only because Dasein as being-with lets the Da-sein of others be encountered in its world. Being-with is an attribute of one's own Da-sein. Mitda-sein characterizes the Da-sein of others in that it is freed for a being-with by the world of that being-with. Only because it has the essential structure of being-with, is one's own Da-sein Mitda-sein as encounterable by others.
121
114
122
Being and Time
I. IV
If Mitda-sein remains existentially constitutive for being-in-theworld, it must be interpreted, as must also circumspect association with the innerworldly things at hand which we characterized by way of anticipation as taking care of things, in terms of the phenomenon of care which we used to designate the being ofDa-sein in general. (Cf. chapter 6 of this division.) Taking care of things is a character of being which being-with cannot have as its own, although this kind of being is a being toward beings encountered in the world, as is taking care of things. The being to which Da-sein is related as being-with does not, however, have the kind of being of useful things at hand; it is itself Da-sein. This being is not taken care of, but is a matter of concern. Even "taking care" of food and clothing, the nursing of the sick body is concern. But we understand this expression in a way which corresponds to our use of taking care of things as a term for an existential. For example, "welfare work," as a factic(\1 social institution, is based on the constitution of being of Da-sein as being-with. Its factical urgency is motivated by the fact that Da-sein initially and, for the most part, lives in the deficient modes of concern. Being for-, against-, and without-oneanother, passing-one-another-by, not-mattering-to-one-another, are possible ways of concern. And precisely the last named modes of deficiency and indifference characterize the everyday and average being-with-oneanother. These modes of being show the characteristics of inconspicuousness and obviousness which belong to everyday innerworldly Mitdasein of others, as well as to the handiness of useful things taken care of daily. These indifferent modes of being-with-one-another tend to mislead the ontological interpretation into initially interpreting this being as the pure objective presence of several subjects. It seems as if only negligible variations of the same kind of being lie before us, and yet ontologically there is an essential distinction between the "indifferent" being together of arbitrary things and the not-mattering-to-one-another of beings who are with one another. With regard to its positive modes, concern has two extreme possibilities. It can, so to speak, take the other's "care" away from him and put itself in his place in taking care, it can leap in for him. Concern takes over what is to be taken care of for the other. The other is thus displaced, he steps back so that afterwards, when the matter has been attended to, he can take it over as something finished and available or disburden himself of it completely. In this concern, the other can become one who is dependent and dominated even if this domination is a tacit one and remains hidden from him. This kind of concern which does the job and takes away "care" is, to a large extent, determinative for being with one another and pertains, for the most part, to our taking care of things at hand.
I.IV
Being and Time
115
In contrast to this, there is the possibility of a concern which does not so much leap in for the other as leap ahead of him, not in order to take "care" away from him, but to first to give it back to him as such. This concern which essentially pertains to authentic care; that is, the existence of the other, and not to a what which it takes care of, helps the other to become transparent to himself in his care and free for it. Concern proves to be constitutive of the being of Da-sein which, in accordance with its different possibilities, is bound up with its being toward the world taken care of and also with its authentic being toward itself. Being-with-one-another is based initially and often exclusively on what is taken care of together in such being. A being-with-one-another which arises from one's doing the same thing as someone else not only keeps for the most part within outer limits but enters the mode of distance and reserve. The being-with-one-another of those who are employed for the same thing often thrives only on mistrust. On the other hand, when they devote themselves to the same thing in common, their doing so is determined by their Da-sein, which has been stirred. This authentic alliance first makes possible the proper kind of objectivity which frees the other for himself in his freedom. Between the two extremes of positive concern-the one which does someone's job for him and dominates him, and the one which is in advance of him and frees him-everyday being-with-one-another maintains itself and shows many mixed forms whose description and classification lie outside of the limits of this investigation. Just as circumspection belongs to taking care of things as a way of discovering things at hand, concern is guided by considerateness and tol· erance. With concern, both can go through the deficient and indifferent modes up to the point of inconsiderateness and the tolerance which is guided by indifference. The world not only frees things at hand as beings encountered within the world, but also Da-sein, the others in their Mitda-sein. But in accordance with its own meaning of being, this being which is freed in the surrounding world is being-in in the same world in which, as encounterable for others, it is there with them. Worldliness was interpreted (section 18) as the referential totality of significance. In being familiar with this significance and previously understanding it, Da-sein lets things at hand be encountered as things discovered in their relevance. The referential context of significance is anchored in the being of Da-sein toward its ownmost being-a being which cannot be in a relation of relevance, but which is rather the being for the sake of which Da-sein itself is as it is. But, according to the analysis which we have now completed, being-with-others belongs to the being of Da-sein, with which it is con-
123
116
124
Being and Time
I. IV
cemed in its very being. As being-with, Da-sein "is" essentially for the sake of others. 1bis must be understood as an existential statement as to its essence. But when actual, factical Da-sein does not tum to others and thinks that it does not need them, or misses them, it is in the mode of being-with. In being-with as the existential for-the-sake-of-others, these others are already disclosed in their Da-sein. 1bis previously constituted disclosedness of others together with being-with thus helps to constitute significance, that is, worldliness. As this worldliness, disclosedness is anchored in the existential for-the-sake-of-which. Hence the worldliness of the world thus constituted in which Da-sein always already essentially is, lets things at hand be encountered in the surrounding world in such a way that the Mitda-sein of others is encountered at the same time with them as circumspectly taken care of. The structure of the worldliness of the world is such that others are not initially objectively present as unattached subjects along with other things, but show themselves in their heedful being in the surrounding world in terms of the things at hand in that world. The disclosedness of the Mitda-sein of others which belongs to being-with means that the understanding of others already lies in the understanding of being of Da-sein because its being is being-with. This understanding, like all understanding, is not a knowledge derived from cognition, but a primordially existential kind of being which first makes knowledge and cognition possible. Knowing oneself is grounded in primordially understanding being-with. It operates initially in accordance with the nearest kind of being of being-together-in-the-world in the understanding knowledge of what Da-sein circumspectly finds and takes care of with the others. Concemful taking care of things is understood in terms of what is taken care of and with an understanding of them. Thus the other is initially disclosed in the taking care of concern. But because concern, initially and for the most part, dwells in the deficient or at least indifferent modes-in the indifference of passingone-another-by-a nearest and essential knowing oneself is in need of a getting-to-know-oneself. And when even knowing oneself loses itself in aloofness, concealing oneself and misrepresenting oneself, being-withone-another requires special ways in order to come near to the others or to "see through them." But just as opening oneself up or closing oneself off are grounded in the actual mode of being of being-with-one-another, in fact is nothing besides this mode itself, even the explicit disclosure of the other in concern grows only out of one's primarily being-with him. Such a disclosure of the other which is indeed thematic, but not in the mode of theoretical psychology, easily becomes the phenomenon that first comes to view for the theoretical problematic of understanding the "psychical life of oth-
I.IV
Being and Time
117
ers." What "initially" presents phenomenally a way of being-with-oneanother that understands-is at the same time, however, taken to mean that which "originally" and primordially makes possible and constitutes being toward others. This phenomenon, which is none too happily designated as "empathy," is then supposed, as it were, to provide the first ontological bridge from one's own subject, initially given by itself, to the other subject, which is initially quite inaccessible. To be sure, being-toward-others is ontologically different from being toward objectively present things. The "other" being itself has the kind of being of Da-sein. Thus, in being with and toward others, there is a relation of being from Da-sein to Da-sein. But, one would like to say, this relation is, after all, already constitutive for one's own Da-sein, which has an understanding of its own being and is thus related to Dasein. The relation of being to others then becomes a projection of one's own being toward oneself"into an other." The other is a double of the self. But it is easy to see that this seemingly obvious deliberation has little ground to stand on. The presupposition which this argument makes use of-that the being of Da-sein toward itself is a being toward anotheris incorrect. As long as the presupposition has not been demonstrated clearly in its legitimacy, it remains puzzling how the relation of Da-sein to itself is to disclose the other as other. Being toward others is not only an autonomous irreducible relation of being, as being-with it already exists with the being ofDa-sein. Of course, it is indisputable that a lively mutual acquaintanceship on the basis of being-with often depends on how far one's own Da-sein has actually understood itself, but this means that it depends only upon how far one's essential being with others has made it transparent and not disguised itself. This is possible only if Da-sein as being-in-the-world is always already with others. "Empathy" does not first constitute beingwith, but is first possible on its basis, and is motivated by the prevailing modes of being-with in their inevitability. But the fact that "empathy" is not an original existential phenomenon, any more than is knowing in general, does not mean that there is no problem here. Its special hermeneutic will have to show how the various possibilities of being of Da-sein themselves mislead and obstruct being-with-one-another and its self-knowledge, so that a genuine "understanding" is suppressed and Da-sein takes refuge in surrogates; this positive existential condition presupposes a correct understanding of the stranger for its possibility. Our analysis has shown that being-with is an existential constituent of being-in-the-world. Mitda-sein has proved to be a manner of being which beings encountered within the world have as their own. In that Da-sein is at all, it has the kind of being of
125
118
Being and Time
I. IV
being-with-one-another. Being-with-one-another cannot be understood as a summative result of the occurrence of several "subjects." Encountering a number of "subjects" itself is possible only by treating the others encountered in their Mitda-sein merely as "numerals." This number is discovered only by a definite being with and toward one another. "Inconsiderate" being-with "reckons" with others without seriously "counting on them" or even wishing "to have anything to do" with them. One's own Da-sein, like the Mitda-sein of others, is encountered, initially and for the most part, in terms of the world-together in the surrounding world taken care of. In being absorbed in the world of taking care of things, that is, at the same time in being-with toward others, Dasein is not itself. Who is it, then, who has taken over being as everyday being-with-one-another?
126
27. Everyday Being One's Self and the They The ontologically relevant result of the foregoing analysis of being-with is the insight that the "subject character" of one's own Da-sein and of the others is to be defined existentially, that is, in terms of certain ways to be. In what is taken care of in the surrounding world, the others are encountered as what they are; they are what they do. In taking care of the things which one has taken hold of, for, and against others, there is constant care as to the way one differs from them, whether this difference is to be equalized, whether one's own Dasein has lagged behind others and wants to catch up in relation to them, whether Da-sein in its priority over others is intent on suppressing them. Being-with-one-another is, unknown to itself, disquieted by the care about this distance. Existentially expressed, being-with-one-another has the character of distantiality. The more inconspicuous this kind of being is to everyday Da-sein itself, all the more stubbornly and primordially does it work itself out. But this distantiality which belongs to being-with is such that, as everyday being-with-one-another, Da-sein stands in subservience to the others. It itself is not; the others have taken its being away from it. The everyday possibilities of being of Da-sein are at the disposal of the whims of the others. These others are not definite others. On the contrary, any other can represent them. What is decisive is only the inconspicuous domination by others that Da-sein as being-with has already taken over unawares. One belongs to the others oneself, and entrenches their power. "The others," whom one designates as such in order to cover over one's own essential belonging to them, are those who are there initially and for the most part in everyday being-with-one-another. The who is not this one and not that one, not oneself and not some and
I.IV
Being and Time
119
not the sum of them all. The "who" is the neuter, the they. We have shown earlier how the public "surrounding world" is always already at hand and taken care of in the surrounding world nearest to us. In utilizing public transportation, in the use of information services such as the newspaper, every other is like the next. This beingwith-one-another dissolves one's own Da-sein completely into the kind of being of "the others" in such a way that the others, as distinguishable and explicit, disappear more and more. In this inconspicuousness and unascertainability, the they unfolds its true dictatorship. We enjoy ourselves and have fun the way they enjoy themselves. We read, see, and judge literature and art the way they see and judge. But we also withdraw from the "great mass" the way they withdraw, we find "shocking" what they find shocking. The they, which is nothing definite and which all are, though not as a sum, prescribes the kind of being of everydayness. The they has its own ways to be. The tendency of being-with which we called distantiality is based on the fact that being-with-one-another as such create\_averagemu:Jit is an existential character of the they. In its being, the they is essentially concerned with averageness. Thus, the they maintains itself factically in the averageness of what is proper, what is allowed, and what is not. Of what is granted success and what is not. This averageness, which prescribes what can and may be ventured, watches over every exception which thrusts itself to the fore. Every priority is noiselessly squashed. Overnight, everything primordial is flattened down as something long since known. Everything gained by a struggle becomes something to be manipulated. Every mystery loses its power. The care of averageness reveals, in turn, an essential tendency of Da-sein, which we call the levelling down of all possibilities of being. Distantiality, averageness, and levelling down, as ways of being of the they, constitute what we know as "publicness." Publicness initially controls every way in which the world and Da-sein are interpreted, and it is always right, not because of an eminent and primary relation of being to "things," not because it has an explicitly appropriate transparency of Da-sein at its disposal, but because it does not get to "the heart of the matter," because it is insensitive to every difference of level and genuineness. Publicness obscures everything, and then claims that what has been thus covered over is what is familiar and accessible to everybody. The they is everywhere, but in such a way that it has always already stolen away when Da-sein presses for a decision. However, because the they presents every judgment and decision as its own, it takes the responsibility of Da-sein away from it. The they can, as it were, manage to have "them" constantly invoking it. It can most easily be responsible for everything because no one has to vouch for anything. The they always "did it,"
127
120
128
129
Being and Time
I.IV
and yet it can be said that "no one" did it. In the everydayness of Da-sein, most things happen in such a way that we must say "no one did it." Thus, the they disburdens Da-sein in its everydayness. Not only that; by disburdening it of its being, the they accommodates Da-sein in its tendency to take things easily and make them easy. And since the they constantly accommodates Da-sein, it retains and entrenches its stubborn dominance. Everyone is the other, and no one is himself. The they, which supplies the answer to the who of everyday Da-sein, is the nobody to whom every Da-sein has always already surrendered itself, in its being-amongone-another. In these characteristics of being which we have discussed-everyday being-among-one-another, distantiality, averageness, levelling down, publicness, disburdening of one's being, and accommodation-lies the initial "constancy" of Da-sein. This constancy pertains not to the enduring objective presence of something, but to the kind of being of Da-sein as being-with. Existing in the modes we have mentioned, the self of one's own Da-sein and the self of the other have neither found nor lost themselves. One is in the manner of dependency and inauthenticity. This way of being does not signify a lessening of the facti city of Da-sein, just as the they as the nobody is not nothing. On the contrary, in this kind of being Da-sein is an ens realissimum, if by "reality" we understand a being that is like Da-sein. Of course, the they is as little objectively present as Da-sein itself. The more openly the they behaves, the more slippery and hidden it is, but the less is it nothing at all. To the unprejudiced ontic-ontological "eye," it reveals itself as the "most real subject" of everydayness. And if it is not accessible like an objectively present stone, that is not in the least decisive about its kind of being. One may neither decree prematurely that this they is "really" nothing, nor profess the opinion that the phenomenon has been interpreted ontologically if one "explains" it as the result of the objective presence of several subjects which one has put together in hindsight. On the contrary, the elaboration of the concepts of being must be guided by these indubitable phenomena. Nor is the they something like a "universal subject" which hovers over a plurality of subjects. One could understand it this way only if the being of "subjects" is understood as something unlike Da-sein, and if these are regarded as factually objectively present cases of an existing genus. With this approach, the only possibility ontologically is to understand everything which is not a case of this sort in the sense of genus and species . The they is not the genus of an individual Da-sein, nor can it be found in this being as an abiding characteristic. That traditional logic also fails in the face of these phenomena, cannot surprise us if we con-
I. IV
Being and Time
121
sider that it has its foundation in an ontology of objective presence-an ontology which is still rough at that. Thus, it fundamentally cannot be made more flexible no matter how many improvements and expansions might be made. These reforms of logic, oriented toward the "humanistic sciences," only increase the ontological confusion. The they is an existential and belongs as a primordial phenomenon to the positive constitution of Da-sein. It itself has, in tum, various possibilities of concretion in accordance with Da-sein. The extent to which its dominance becomes penetrating and explicit may change historically. The self of everyday Da-sein is the they-self which we distinguish from the authentic self, the self which has explicitly grasped itself. As the they-self, Da-sein is dispersed in the they and must first fmd itself. This dispersion characterizes the "subject" of the kind of being which we know as heedful absorption in the world nearest encountered. If Da-sein is familiar with itself as the they-self, this also means that the they prescribes the nearest interpretation of the world and of being-in-the-world. The they itself, for the sake of which Da-sein is every day, articulates the referential context of significance. The world of Da-sein frees the beings encountered for a totality of relevance which is familiar to the they in the limits which are established with the averageness of the they. Initially, factical Da-sein is in the with-world, discovered in an average way. Initially, "I" "am" not in the sense of my own self, but I am the others in the mode of the they. In terms of the they, and as the they, I am initially "given" to "myself." Initially, Da-sein is the they and for the most part it remains so. If Da-sein explicitly discovers the world and brings it near, if it discloses its authentic being to itself, this discovering of "world" and disclosing of Da-sein always comes about by clearing away coverings and obscurities, by breaking up the disguises with which Da-sein cuts itself off from itself. With this interpretation of being-with and being one's self in the they, the question of the who in the everydayness of being-with-oneanother is answered. These considerations have at the same time given us a concrete understanding of the basic constitution of Da-sein. Beingin-the-world became visible in its everydayness and averageness. Everyday Da-sein derives the pre-ontological interpretation of its being from the nearest kind of being of the they. The ontological interpretation initially follows this tendency of interpretation, it understands Da-sein in terms of the world and rinds it there as an innerworldly being. Not only this; the "nearest" ontology of Da-sein takes the meaning of being on the basis of which these existing "subjects" are understood also in terms of the "world." But since the phenomenon of world itself is passed over in this absorption in the world, it is replaced by objective presence in the world, by things. The being of beings, which is there,
130
122
Being and Time
I. tv
too, is understood as objective presence. Thus, by showing the positive phenomenon of nearest, everyday being-in-the-world, we have made possible an insight into the root of missing the ontological interpretation of this constitution of being. It itself, in its everyday kind of being, is what initially misses itself and covers itself over. If the being of everyday being-with-one-another, which seems ontologically to approach pure objective presence, is really fundamentally dif. ferent from that kind of presence, still less can the being of the authentic self be understood as objective presence. Authentic being one:S self is not based on an exceptional state of the subject, a state detached from the they, but is an existentiell modification of the they as an essential existential. But, then, the sameness of the authentically existing self is separated ontologically by a gap from the identity of the I maintaining itself in the multiplicity of its "experiences."
v Being-in as Such
28. The Task of a Thematic Analysis of Being-in In the preparatory stage of the existential analytic of Da-sein we have for our leading theme this being's basic constitution, being-in-the-world. Our first aim is to bring into relief phenomenally the unitary primordial structure of the being of Da-sein by which its possibilities and ways "to be" are ontologically determined. Until now, the phenomenal characterization of being-in-the-world has been directed toward the structural moment of the world and has attempted to provide an answer to the question of the who of this being in its everydayness. But in first sketching out the tasks of a preparatory fundamental analysis of Da-sein we already provided an orientation to being-in as such' and demonstrated it by the concrete mode of knowing the world. 2 We anticipated this sustaining structural moment with the intention of relating the analysis of individual moments, from the outset, with a steady view to the structural whole, and with the intention of preventing any disruption and fragmentation of the unitary phenomenon. Now, keeping in mind what has been achieved in the concrete analysis of world and who, we must turn our interpretation back to the phenomenon of being-in. By considering this more penetratingly, however, we shall not only get a new and more certain phenomenological view of the structural totality of being-in-the-world, but shall also pave the way to grasping the primordial being of Da-sein itself, care. But what more is there to point out in being-in-the-world, beyond the essential relations of being together with the world (taking care of
123
131
124
132
Being and Time
l.v
things}, being-with (concern}, and being one's self (who)? There is still the possibility of broadening the analysis by comparing the variations of taking care and its circumspection, of concern and its considerateness, and of distinguishing Da-sein from all beings unlike Da-sein by a more precise explication of the being of all possible innerworldly beings. Without question, there are unfinished tasks in this direction. What we have set forth so far needs to be supplemented in many ways with respect to a full elaboration of the existential a priori of philosophical anthropology. But this is not the aim of our investigation. Its aim is that ofJunda· mental ontolog;y. If we thus inquire into being-in thematically, we cannot be willing to nullify the primordiality of the phenomenon by deriving it from others, that is, by an inappropriate analysis in the sense of dissolving it. But the fact that we cannot derive something primordial does not exclude a multiplicity of characteristics of being constitutive for it. If these characteristics show themselves, they are existentially equiprimordial. The phenomenon of the equiprimordiality of constitutive factors has often been disregarded in ontology on account of a methodically unrestrained tendency to derive everything and anything from a simple "primordial ground." In which direction must we look for the phenomenal characteristics of being-in as such? We get the answer to this question by recalling what we were charged with keeping in view phenomenologically when we pointed out this phenomenon: being-in in contradistinction to the objectively present insideness of something objectively present "in" an other; being-in not as an attribute of an objectively present subject effected or even initiated by the objective presence of the "world"; rather, being-in essentially as the kind of being of this being itself. But then what else presents itself with this phenomenon other than the objectively present commercium between an objectively present subject and an objectively present object? This interpretation would come closer to the phenomenal content if it stated that Da-sein is the being of this "between." Nonetheless, the orientation toward the "between" would still be misleading. It colludes unawares with the ontologically indefinite approach that there are beings between which this between as such "is." The between is already understood as the result of the convenientia of two objectively present things. But this kind of approach always already splits the phenomenon beforehand, and there is no prospect of ever again putting it back together from the fragments. Not only do we lack the "cement," even the "schema" according to which this joining together is to be accomplished has been split apart, or never as yet unveiled. What is ontologically decisive is to avoid splitting the phenomenon beforehand, that is, to secure its positive phenomenal content. The fact that extensive and complicated preparations are necessary for
I.v
Being and Time
125
this, only shows that something ontically self-evident in the traditional treatment of the "problem of knowledge" was ontologically distorted in many ways to the point of becoming invisible. The being which is essentially constituted by being-in-the-world is itself always its "there." According to the familiar meaning of the word, "there" points to "here" and "over there." The "here" of an "!-here" is always understood in terms of an "over there" at hand in the sense of being toward it which de-distances, is directional, and takes care. The existential spatiality of Da-sein which determines its "place" for it in this way is itself based upon being-in-the-world. The over there is the determinateness of something encountered within the world. "Here" and "over there" are possible only in a "there," that is, when there is a being which has disclosed spatiality as the being of the there." This being bears in its ownmost being the character of not being closed. The expression "there" means this essential disclosedness. Through disclosedness this being (Da-sein) is "there" for itself together with the Dasein of the world. When we talk in an ontically figurative way about the lumen naturale in human being, we mean nothing other than the existential-ontological structure of this being, the fact that it is in the mode of being its there. To say that it is "illuminated" means that it is cleared* in itself as being-in-the-world, not by another being, but in such a way that it is itself the clearing. t Only for a being thus existentially do objectively present things become accessible in the light or concealed in darkness. By its very nature, Da-sein brings its there along with it. If it lacks its there, it is not only factically not of this nature, but not at all a being. Da-sein is its disclosure.t We must set forth the constitution of this being. But since the nature of this being is existence, the existential statement that "Da-sein is its disclosure" means at the same time that the being about which these beings are concerned in their being is to be their "there." In addition to characterizing the primary constitution of the being of disclosure, we must, in accordance with the character of our analysis, interpret the kind of being in which this being is its there in an everyday way. This chapter, which undertakes the explication of being-in as such, that is, of the being of the there, has two parts: (A) The existential constitution of the there. (B) The everyday being of the there and the entanglement' of Da-sein.
* Aletheia-openness-dearing, light, shining. But not produced. Da-sein exists, and it alone. Thus existence is standing out and perduring the openness of the there: Ek-sistence.
t
t
133
126
134
Being and Time
I.v
We see the two equiprimordially constitutive ways to be the there in attunement and understanding. For their analysis the necessary phenomenal confirmation can be gained by an interpretation of a concrete mode which is important for the following problematic. Attunement and understanding are equiprimordially determined by discourse. Under part A (the existential constitution of the there) we shall treat Da-sein as attunement (section 29), fear as a mode of attunement (section 30), Da-sein as understanding (section 31), understanding and interpretation (section 32}, statement as a derivative mode of interpretation (section 33), Da-sein, discourse, and language (section 34). The analysis of the characteristics of the being of Da-sein is an existential one. This means that the characteristics are not properties of something objectively present, but essentially existential ways to be. Thus, their kind of being in everydayness must be brought out. Under part B (the everyday being of the there and the entanglement of Da-sein}, we shall analyze idle talk (section 35), curiosity (section 36), and ambiguity (section 37) as existential modes of the everyday being of the there: we shall analyze them as corresponding to the constitutive phenomenon of discourse, the vision which lies in understanding, and the interpretation (meaning) belonging to that understanding. In these phenomena a fundamental kind of the being of the there becomes visible which we interpret as entanglement. This "entangling" shows a way of being moved which is existentially its own (section 38).
A.
THE EXISTENTIAL CONSTITUTION OF THE THERE
29. Da-sein as Attunement
What we indicate ontologically with the term attunement is ontically what is most familiar and an everyday kind of thing: mood, being in a mood. Prior to all psychology of moods, a field which, moreover, still lies fallow, we must see this phenomenon as a fundamental existential and outline its structure. Both the undisturbed equanimity and the inhibited discontent of everyday heedfulness, the way we slide over from one to another or slip into bad moods, are by no means nothing ontologically although these phenomena remain unnoticed as what is supposedly the most indifferent and fleeting in Da-sein. The fact that moods can be spoiled and change only means that Da-sein is always already in a mood. The often persistent, smooth, and pallid lack of mood, which must not be confused with a bad mood, is far from being nothing. Rather, in this Da-sein
I.v
Being and Time
127
becomes tired of itself. Being has become manifest as a burden [Last].* One does not know why. And Da-sein cannot know why because the possibilities of disclosure belonging to cognition fall far short of the primordial disclosure of moods in which Da-sein is brought before its being as the there. Furthermore, an elevated mood can alleviate the manifest burden of being. This possibility of mood, too, discloses the burdensome character of Da-sein even when it alleviates that burden. Mood makes manifest "how one is and is coming along." In this "how one is" being in a mood brings being to its "there." In being in a mood, Da-sein is always already disclosed in accordance with its mood as that being to which Da-sein was delivered over in its being as the being which it, existing, has to be. Disclosed does not, as such, mean to be known. Just in the most indifferent and harmless everydayness the being of Da-se~n can burst forth as the naked "that it is and has to be." The pure "that it is" shows itself, the whence and whither remain obscure. The fact that Da-sein normally does not "give in" to such everyday moods, that is, does not pursue what they disclose and does not allow itself to confront what has been disclosed, is no evidence against the phenomenal fact of the moodlike disclosure of the being of the there in its that, but is rather evidence for it. For the most part Dasein evades the being that is disclosed in moods ip. an ontic and existentiell way. Ontologically and existentially this means that in that to which such a mood pays no attention Da-sein is unveiled in its being delivered over to the there. In the evasion itself the there is something disclosed. We shall call this character of being of Da-sein which is veiled in its whence and whither, but in itself all the more openly disclosed, this "that it is," the thrownness of this being into its there; it is thrown in such a way that it is the there as being-in-the-world. The expression thrownness is meant to suggest the facticity of its being delivered over. The "that it is and has to be" disclosed in the attunement of Da-sein is not the "that" which expresses ontologically and categorially the factuality belonging to objective presence; The latter is accessible only when we ascertain it by looking at it. Rather, the that disclosed in attunement must be understood as an existential attribute of that being which is in the mode of being-in-the-world. Facticity is not the factuality ofthe factum brutum of something objectively present, but is a characteristic of the being of Da-sein taken on in existence, although initially thrust aside. The that of facticity is never to be found by looking. Beings of the character of Da-sein are their there in such a way that they find themselves in their thrownness, whether explicitly or not. *"Burden": what bears [das Zu-tragentk]; hwnan being is delivered over to Da~ein, appropriated by it. To bear: to take over something in belonging to being itself.
135
128
136
Being and Time
I.v
In attunement, Da-sein is always already brought before itself, it has always already found itself, not as perceiving oneself to be there, but as one fmds one's self in attunement. As a being which is delivered over to its being, it is also delivered over to the fact that it must always already have found itself, found itself in a finding which comes not from a direct seeking, but from a fleeing. Mood does not disclose in the mode of looking at thrownness, but as turning toward and away from it For the most part, mood does not tum toward the burdensome character of Da-sein revealed in it, least of all as the alleviation of this burden in an elevated mood. This turning away is always what it is in the mode of attunement. Phenomenally, what mood discloses and how it discloses would be completely misunderstood if what has been disclosed were conflated with that which attuned Da-sein "at the same time" is acquainted with, knows, and believes. Even when Da-sein is "sure" of its "whither" in faith or thinks it knows about its whence in rational enlightenment, all of this makes no difference in the face of the phenomenal fact that moods bring Da-sein before the that of its there, which stares at it with the inexorability of an enigma. Existentially and ontologically there is not the slightest justification for minimizing the "evidence" of attunement by measuring it against the apodictic certainty of the theoretical cognition of something merely objectively present. But the falsification of the phenomena, which banishes them to the sanctuary of the irrational, is no better. Irrationalism, as the counterpart of rationalism, talks about the things to which rationalism is blind, but only with a squint. That a Da-sein factically can, should, and must master its mood with knowledge and will may signify a priority of willing and cognition in certain possibilities of existing. But that must not mislead us into ontologically denying mood as a primordial kind of being of Da-sein in which it is disclosed to itself before all cognition and willing and beyond their scope of disclosure. Moreover, we never master a mood by being free of ·a mood, but always through a counter mood. The first essential ontological characteristic of attunement is: Attunement discloses Da-sein in its thrownness, initially and for the most part in the mode of an evasive turning away. From this we can already see that attunement is far removed from anything like finding a psychical condition. Far from having the character of an apprehension which first turns itself around and then turns back, all immanent reflection can find "experiences" only because the there is already disclosed in attunement. "Mere mood" discloses the there more primordially, but it also closes it off more stubbornly than any not-perceiving. Bad moods show this. In bad moods, Da-sein becomes blind to itself, the surrounding world of heedfulness is veiled, the circumspection
I.v
Being and Time
129
of taking care is led astray. Attunement is so far from being reflected upon that it precisely assails Da-sein in the unreflected falling prey to the "world" of its heedfulness. Mood assails. It comes neither from "without" nor from "within," but rises from being-in-the-world itself as a mode of that being. But thus by negatively contrasting attunement with the reflective apprehension of the "inner," we arrive at a positive insight into its character of disclosure. Mood has always already disclosed being-in-the-world as a whole and first makes possible directing oneself toward something. Being attuned is not initially related to something psychical, it is itself not an inner condition which then in some mysterious way reaches out and leaves its mark on things and persons. This is the second essential characteristic of attunement. It is a fundamental existential mode of being of the equiprimordial disclosedness of world, being-there-with, and existence because this disclosure itself is essentially being-in-the-world. Besides these two essential determinations of attunement just explicated, the disclosure of thrownness and the actual disclosure of the whole of being-in-the-world, we must notice a third which above all contributes to a more penetrating understanding of the worldliness of the world. We said earlier• that the world already disclosed lets innerworldly things be encountered. This prior disclosedness of the world which belongs to being-in is also constituted by attunement. Letting something be encountered is primarily curcumspective, not just a sensation or staring out at something. Letting things be encountered in a circumspect heedful way has-we can see this now more precisely in terms of attunement-the character of being affected or moved. But being affected by the unserviceable, resistant, and threatening character of things at hand is ontologically possible only because being-in as such is existentially determined beforehand in such a way that what it encounters in the world can matter to it in this way. This mattering to it is grounded in attunement, and as attunement it has disclosed the world, for example, as something by which it can be threatened. Only something which is the attunement of fearing, or fearlessness, can discover things at hand in the surrounding world as being threatening. The moodedness of attunement constitutes existentially the openness to world of Da-sein. And only because the "senses" belong ontologically to a being which has the kind of being attuned to being-in-the-world, can they be "touched" and "have a sense" for something so that what touches them shows itself in an affect. Something like an affect would never come about under the strongest pressure and resistance, resistance would be essentially undiscovered, if attuned being-in-the-world were not already related to having things in the world matter to it in a way prefigured by moods. In attunement lies existentially a disclosive submission to world out of
137
130
138
139
Being and Time
I.v
which things that matter to us can be encountered. Indeed, we must ontologically in principle leave the primary discovery of the world to "mere mood." Pure beholding, even if it penetrated into the innermost core of the being of something objectively present, would never be able to discover anything like what is threatening. The fact that everyday circumspection goes wrong on account of attunement, which is primarily disclosive and is vastly subject to deception, is, gauged by the idea of an absolute "world"
Being and Time
I.v
131
contrary, the affects and feelings fall thematically under the psychic phenomena, functioning as a third class of these, mostly along with representational thinking and willing. They sink to the level of accompanying phenomena. It is the merit of phenomenological investigation that it has again created the freer view of these phenomena. Not only that: Scheler, adopting the suggestions of Augustine and Pascal,6 steered the problematic toward the foundational context between "representing" and "interested" acts. Of course, here too, the existential-ontological foundations of the phenomenon of act generally remain in the dark. Attunement discloses Da-sein not only in its thrownness and dependence on the world already disclosed with its being, it is itself the existential kind of being in which it is continually surrendered to the "world" and lets itself be concerned by it in such a way that it somehow evades its very self. The existential constitution of this evasion becomes clear in the phenomenon of entanglement. Attunement is an existential, fundamental way in which Da-sein is its there. It not only characterizes Da-sein ontologically, but is at the same time of fundamental methodical significance for the existential analytic because of its disclosure. like every ontological interpretation in general, the analytic can only listen in, so to speak, on beings already previously disclosed with regard to their being. And it will keep to the eminent disclosive possibilities of Da-sein of the widest scope in order to gain from them information about this being. The phenomenological interpretation must give to Da-sein itself the possibility of primordial disclosure and let it, so to speak, interpret itself. It goes along with this disclosure only in order to raise the phenomenal content of disclosure existentially to a conceptual level. With regard to the later interpretation of such an existential-ontologically significant basic attunement ofDa-sein, Angst (cf. section 40), the phenomenon of attunement will be demonstrated more concretely in the definite mode of fear.
30. Fear as a Mode of Attunement' The phenomenon of fear can be considered in three aspects. We shall analyze what we are afraid of, fearing, and why we are afraid. These possible aspects of fear are not accidental; they belong together. With them, the structure of attunement as such comes to the fore. We shall complete our analysis by alluding to the possible modifications of fear each of which concerns its various structural factors. That before which we are afraid, the "fearsome," is always something encountered within the world, either with the kind of being of
140
132
Being and Time
l.v
something at hand or something objectively present or Mitda-sein. We do not intend to report ontically about beings which often and for the most part can be "fearsome," but to determine phenomenally what is fearsome in its fearsome character. What is it that belongs to the fearsome as such which is encountered in fearing? What is feared has the character of being threatening. Here several points must be considered.
141
1. What is encountered has the relevant nature of harmfulness. It shows itself in a context of relevance. 2. Thus harmfulness aims at a definite range of what can be affected by it. So determined, it comes from a definite region. 3. The region itself and what comes from it is known as something which is "uncanny." 4. As something threatening, what is harmful is not yet near enough to be dealt with, but it is coming near. As it approaches, harmfulness radiates and thus has the character of threatening. 5. This approaching occurs within nearness. Something may be harmful in the highest degree and may even be constantly coming nearer but if it is still far off it remains veiled in its fearsome nature. As something approaching in nearness, however, what is harmful is threatening, it can get us, and yet perhaps not. In approaching, this "it can and yet in the end it may not" gets worse. It is fearsome, we say. 6. This means that what is harmful, approaching near, bears the revealed possibility of not happening and passing us by. This does not lessen or extinguish fearing, but enhances it.
Fearing itself frees what we have characterized as threatening in a way which lets us be concerned with it. It is not that we initially ascertain a future evil (malum futurum) and then are afraid of it. But neither does fearing first confirm something approaching us, but rather discovers it beforehand in its fearsomeness. And then fear, in being afraid, can "clarify" what is fearsome by explicitly looking at it. Circumspection sees what is fearsome because it is in the attunement of fear. As a dormant possibility of attuned being-in-the-world, fearing, "fearfulness" has already disclosed the world with regard to the fact that something like a fearful thing can draw near to us from this fearfulness. The ability to draw near is itself freed by the essential, existential spatiality of being-inthe-world. The about which fear is afraid is the fearful being itself, Da-sein. Only a being which is concerned in its being about that being can be afraid. Fearing discloses this being in its jeopardization, in its being left to itself. Although in varying degrees of explicitness, fear always reveals Da-sein in the being of its there. When we are afraid for house and
I.V
Being and Time
133
home, this is not a counter-example for the above determination of what it is we are fearful about. For as being-in-the-world, Da-sein is always a heedful being-with. Initially and for the most part, Da-sein is in terms of what it takes care of. The jeopardization of that is a threat to being with. Fear predominantly discloses Da-sein in a privative way. It bewilders us and makes us "lose our heads." At the same time, fear closes off our jeopardized being in by letting us see it so that when fear has subsided Da-sein has to first find its way about again. Fear about as being afraid of always equiprimordially discloses, whether privatively or positively, innerworldly beings in their possibility of being threatening and being-in with regard to its being threatened. Fear is a mode of attunement. But fearing about can also involve others, and we then speak of fearing for them. This fearing for ... does not take away the other's fear from him. That is out of the question because the other for whom we are afraid does not even have to be afraid on his part. We are afraid for the other most of all precisely when he is not afraid and blunders recklessly into what is threatening. Fearing for ... is a mode of co-attunement with others, but it is not necessarily being afraid with them or even being afraid together. One can be afraid for ... without being afraid oneself. But viewed precisely, fearing for ... is, after all, being afraid oneself. What is "feared" here is the being-with the other who could be snatched away from us. What is fearsome is not aimed directly at the one who is fearing with. Fearing for ... knows in a way that it is unaffected and yet is affected in the involvement of Mitda-sein for whom it is afraid. Thus fearing for is not a weaker form of being afraid. It is not a matter here of degrees of "feeling tones," but of existential modes. Fearing for ... does not lose its specific genuineness when it is "really" not afraid. The factors constitutive for the full phenomenon of fear can vary. Thus various possibilities of fear result. Approaching nearby belongs to the structure of encountering what is threatening. When something threatening itself suddenly bursts into heedful being-in-the-world in its character of "not right now, but at any moment," fear becomes alarm. We must distinguish in what is threatening: the nearest approach of what threatens and the way of encountering this approach itself, suddenness. What we are alarmed about is initially something known and familiar. But when what threatens has the character of something completely unfamiliar, fear becomes horror. And when something threatening is encountered in the aspect of the horrible, and at the same time is encountered as something alarming, suddenness, fear becomes terror. We are familiar with further variations of fear, such as timidity, shyness, anxiety, misgiving. All modifications of fear as possibilities of attunement point to the fact that Da-sein as being-in-the-world is "fear-
142
134
Being and Time
l.v
ful." This "fearfulness" must not be understood in the ontic sense of a facti cal, "isolated" tendency, but rather as the existential possibility of the essential attunement of Da-sein in general, which is, of course, not the only one. 31. Da-sein as Understanding
143
Attunement is one of the existential structures in which the being of the "there" dwells. Equiprimordially with it, understanding constitutes this being. Attunement always has its understanding, even if only by suppressing it. Understanding is always attuned. If we interpret understanding as a fundamental existential,* we see that this phenomenon is conceived as a fundamental mode of the being of Da-sein. In contrast, "understanding" in the sense of one possible kind of cognition among others, let us say distinguished from "explanation," must be interpreted along with that as an existential derivative of the primary understanding which constitutes the being of the there in general. Our previous inquiry already encountered this primordial understanding, but without explicitly taking it up in the theme under consideration. The statement that Da-sein, existing, is its there means: World is "there"; its Da-sein is being-in. Being-in is "there" as that for the sake of which Da-sein is. Existing being-in-the-world as such is disclosed in the for-the-sake-of-which, and we called this disclosedness understanding. 8 In understanding the for-the-sake-of-which, the significance grounded therein is also disclosed. The disclosure of understanding, as that of the for-the-sake-of-which and of significance, is equiprimordially concerned with complete being-in-the-world. Significance is that for which world as such is disclosed. The statement that the for-the-sake-of-which and significance are disclosed in Da-sein means that Da-sein is a being which, as being-in-the-world, is concerned about itself. Speaking ontically, we sometimes use the expression "to understand something" to mean "being able to handle a thing," "being up to it," "being able to do something." In understanding as an existential, the thing we are able to do is not a what, but being as existing. The mode of being of Da-sein as a potentiality of being lies existentially in understanding. Da-sein is not something objectively present which then has as an addition the ability to do something, but is rather primarily being-possible. Da-sein is always what it can be and how it is its possibility. The essential possibility of Da-sein concerns the ways of taking care of the "world" which we characterized, of concern for others and, always already present in all of this, the potentiality of being itself, for its own sake.
* Fundamentally and ontologically, that is, from the relation of the truth of being.
I.v
Being and Time
135
The being-possible, which Da-sein always is existentially, is also distinguished from empty, logical possibility and from the contingency of something objectively present, where this or that can "happen" to it. As a modal category of objective presence, possibility means what is not yet real and not always necessary. It characterizes what is only possible. Ontologically, it is less than reality and necessity. In contrast, possibility as an existential is the most primordial and the ultimate positive ontological determination of Da-sein; as is the case with existentiality, it can initially be prepared for solely as a problem. Understanding as a potentiality of being disclosive offers the phenomenal ground to see it at all. As an existential, possibility does not refer to a free-floating potentiality of being in the sense of the "liberty of indifference" (libertas indif ferentiae). As essentially attuned, Da-sein has always already got itself into definite possibilities. As a potentiality for being which it is, it has let some go by; it constantly adopts the possibilities of its being, grasps them, and goes astray. But this means that Da-sein is a being-possible entrusted to itself, thrown possibility throughout. Da-sein is the possibility of being free for its ownmost potentiality of being. Being-possible is transparent for it in various possible ways and degrees. Understanding is the being of such a potentiality of being which is never still outstanding as something not yet objectively present, but as something essentially never objectively present, is together with the being of Da-sein in the sense of existence. Da-sein is in the way that it actually understands or has not understood to be in this or that way. As this understanding, it "knows" what is going on, that is, what its potentiality of being is. This "knowing" does not first come from an immanent self-perception, but belongs to the being of the there which is essentially understanding. And only because Da-sein, in understanding is its there, can it go astray and fail to recognize itself. And since understanding is attuned and attunement is existentially surrendered to thrownness, Da-sein has always already gone astray and failed to recognize itself. In its potentiality of being, it is thus delivered over to the possibility of first finding itself again in its possibilities. Understanding is the existential being of the ownmost potentiality of being of Da-sein in such a way that this being discloses in itself what its very being is about. The structure of this existential must be grasped more precisely. As disclosing, understanding always concerns the whole fundamental constitution of being-in-the-world. As a potentiality of being, being-in is always a potentiality of being-in-the-world. Not only is the world, qua world, disclosed in its possible significance, but innerworldly beings themselves are freed, these beings are freed for their own possibilities. What is at hand is discovered as such in its serviceability, usability, detrimentality. The totality of relevance reveals itself as the categorial
144
136
145
Being and Time
I.v
whole of a possibility of the connection of things at hand. But the "unity," too, of manifold objective presence, nature, is discoverable only on the basis of the disclosedness of one of its possibilities. Is it a matter of chance that the question of the being of nature aims at the "conditions of its possibility?" On what is this questioning based? It cannot omit the question: Why are beings unlike Da-sein understood in their being if they are disclosed in terms of the conditions of their possibility? Kant presupposed something like this, perhaps correctly so. But this presupposition itself cannot be left without demonstrating how it is justified. Why does understanding always penetrate into possibilities according to all the essential dimensions of what can be disclosed to it? Because understanding in itself has the existential structure which we call project. It projects the being ofDa-sein upon its for-the-sake-of-which just as primordially as upon significance as the worldliness of its actual world. The project character of understanding constitutes being-in-the-world with regard to the disclosedness of its there as the there of a potentiality of being. Project is the existential constitution of being in the realm of factical potentiality of being. And, as thrown, Da-sein is thrown into the mode of being of projecting. Projecting has nothing to do with being related to a plan thought out, according to which Da-sein arranges its being, but, as Da-sein, it has always already projected itself and is, as long as it is, projecting. As long as it is, Da-sein always has understood itself and will understand itself in terms of possibilities. Furthermore, the project character of understanding means that understanding does not thematically grasp that upon which it projects, the possibilities themselves. Such a grasp precisely takes its character of possibility away from what is projected, it degrades it to the level of a given, intended content, whereas in projecting project throws possibility before itself as possibility, and as such lets it be. As projecting, understanding is the mode of being of Da-sein in which it is its possibilities as possibilities. Because of the kind of being which is constituted by the existential of projecting, Da-sein is constantly "more" than it actually is, if one wanted to and if one could register it as something objectively present in its content of being. But it is nevermore than it factically is because its potentiality of being belongs essentially to its facticity. But, as beingpossible, Da-sein is also never less. It is existentially that which it is not yet in its potentiality of being. And only because the being of the there gets its constitution through understanding and its character of project, only because it is what it becomes or does not become, can it say understandingly to itself: "become what you are!"*
*But who are "you"? The one who lets go-and becomes.
I.v
Being and Time
137
Project always concerns the complete disclosedness of being-inthe-world. As a potentiality of being, understanding itself has possibilities which are prefigured by the scope of what can be essentially disclosed to it. Understanding can turn primarily to the disclosedness of the world, that is, Da-sein can understand itself initially and for the most part in terms of the world. Or else understanding throws itself primarily into the for-the-sake-of-which, which means Da-sein exists as itself.* Understanding is either authentic, originating from its own self as such, or else inauthentic. The "in" does not mean that Da-sein cuts itself off from itself and understands "only" the world. World belongs to its being a self as being-in-the-world. Again, authentic as well as inauthentic understanding can be either genuine or not genuine. As a potentiality of being understanding is altogether permeated with possibility. Turning to one of these fundamental possibilities of understanding, however, does not dispense with the other. Rather, because understanding always has to do with the complete disclosedness of Da-sein as being-in-the-world, the involvement of understanding is an existential modification ofproject as a whole_ In understanding the world, being-in is always also understood. Understanding of existence as such is always an understanding of world. As factical, Da-sein has always already transferred its potentiality of being into a possibility of understanding. In its character of project, understanding constitutes existentially what we call the sight of Da-sein. In accordance with the fundamental modes of its being which we characterized as the circumspection of taking care of things, the considerateness of concern, as the sight geared toward being as such for the sake of which Da-sein is as it is, Da-sein is equiprimordially the sight existentially existing together with the disclosedness of the there. We shall call the sight which is primarily and as a whole related to existence transparency. We choose this term to designate correctly understood "self-knowledge" in order to indicate that it is not a matter here of perceptually finding and gazing at a point which is the self, but of grasping and understanding the full disclosedness of being-in-the-world throughout all its essential constitutive factors. Existent beings glimpse "themselves" only when they have become transparent to themselves equiprimordially in their being with the world, in being together with others as the constitutive factors of their existence. Conversely, the opacity of Da-sein is not solely and primarily rooted in "egocentric" self-deception, but also in lack of knowledge about the world.
* But not qua subject and individual or qua person.
146
138
147
148
Being and Time
I.v
We must, of course, guard against a misunderstanding of the expression "sight." It corresponds to the clearedness characterizing the disclosedness of the there. "Seeing" not only does not mean perceiving with the bodily eyes, neither does it mean the pure, nonsensory perception of something objectively present in its objective presence. The only peculiarity of seeing which we claim for the existential meaning of sight is the fact that it lets the beings accessible to it be encountered in themselves without being concealed. Of course, every "sense" does this within its genuine realm of discovery. But the tradition of philosophy has been primarily oriented from the very beginning toward " seeing" as the mode of access to beings and to being. To preserve the connection, one can formalize sight and seeing to the point of gaining a universal term which characterizes every access as access whatsoever to beings and to being. By showing how all sight is primarily based on understandingthe circumspection of taking care of things is understanding as common sense [Vtmtiindigkeit]-we have taken away from pure intuition its priority which noetically corresponds to the traditional ontological priority of objective presence. "Intuition" and "thought"* are both already remote derivatives of understanding. Even the phenomenological "intuition of essences" is based on existential understanding. We can decide about this kind of seeing only when we have gained the explicit concepts of being and the structure of being, which only phenomena in the phenomenological sense can become. The disclosedness of the there in understanding is itself a mode of the potentiality-of-being of Da-sein. In the projectedness of its being upon the for-the-sake-of-which together with that upon significance (world) lies the disclosedness of being in general.t An understanding of being is already anticipated in the projecting upon possibilities. Being is understood! in the project, but not ontologically grasped. Beings which have the kind of being of the essential project of being-in-the-world have as the constituent of their being the understanding of being. What we asserted earlier9 dogmatically is now demonstrated in terms of the constitution of the being in which Da-sein, as understanding, is its there. In accordance with the limits of this whole inquiry, a satisfactory clarification of the existential meaning of this understanding of being can only be attained on the basis of the temporal interpretation of being. As existentials, attunement and understanding characterize the primordial disclosedness of being-in-the-world. In the mode of "being attuned" Da-sein "sees" possibilities in terms of which it is. In the pro-
* To understand this as the "understanding" [Verstand], dianoia, but not the act of understanding [Verstehen] from the understanding [Verstand]. t How does it "lie" there and what does being [Seyn] mean? I This does not mean that being "is" by the grace of the project.
Being and Time
I.V
139
jective disclosure of such possibilities, it is always already attuned. The project of its ownmost potentiality of being is delivered over to the fact of thrownness into the there. With the explication of the existential constitution of the being of the there in the sense of thrown project does not the being ofDa-sein become still more mysterious? Indeed. We must first let the full mysteriousness of this being emerge, if only to be able to get stranded in a genuine way in its "solution" and to raise the question anew of the being of thrown-projecting being-in-the-world. In order to sufficiently bring even only the everyday mode of being of attuned understanding phenomenally to view, a concrete development of these existentials is necessary.
32. Understanding and Interpretation As understanding, Da-sein projects its being upon possibilities. This being
toward possibilities that understands is itself a potentiality for being because of the way these disclosed possibilities come back to Da-sein. The project of understanding has its own possibility of development. We shall call the development of understanding interpretation. In interpretation understanding appropriates what it has understood in an understanding way. In interpretation understanding does not become something different, but rather itself. Interpretation is existentially based in understanding, and not the other way around. Interpretation is not the acknowledgment of what has been understood, but rather the development of possibilities projected in understanding. In accordance with the train of these preparatory analyses of everyday Da-sein, we shall pursue the phenomenon of interpretation in the understanding of the world, that is, in inauthentic understanding in the mode of its genuineness. In terms of the significance of what is disclosed in understanding the world, the being of taking care of what is at hand learns to understand what the relevance can be with what is actually encountered. Circumspection discovers, that is, the world which has already been understood is interpreted. What is at hand comes explicitly before sight that understands. All preparing, arranging, setting right, improving, rounding out, occur in such a way that things at hand for circumspection are interpreted in their in-order-to and are taken care of according to the interpretedness which has become visible. What has been circumspectly interpreted with regard to its in-order-to as such, what has been explicitly understood, has the structure of something as something. The circumspectly interpretive answer to the circwnspect question of what this particular thing at hand is runs: it is for .... Saying what it is for is not simply naming something, but what is named is understood as that as which what is in question is to be taken. What is disclosed in understanding, what is understood is always already accessible in such a way that in it its "as what" can be explicitly delin-
149
140
150
Being and Time
l.v
eated. The "as" constitutes the structure of the explicitness of what is understood; it constitutes the interpretation. The circumspect, interpretive association with what is at hand in the surrounding world which "sees" this as a table, a door, a car, a bridge does not necessarily already have to analyze what is circwnspectly interpreted in a particular statement. Any simple prepredicative seeing of what is at hand is in itself already understanding and interpretative. But does not the lack of this "as" constitute the simplicity of a pure perception of something? The seeing of this sight is always already understanding and interpreting. It contains the explicitness of referential relation (of the in-order-to) which belong to the totality of relevance in terms of which what is simply encountered is understood. The articulation of what is understood in the interpreting approach to beings guided by the "something as something" lies before a thematic statement about it. The "as" does not first show up in the statement, but is only first stated, which is possible only because it is there as something to be stated. The fact that the explicitness of a statement can be lacking in simple looking, does not justify us in denying every articulate interpretation, and thus the as-structure, to this simple seeing. The simple seeing of things nearest to us in our having to do with ... contains the structure of interpretation so primordially that a grasping of something which is, so to speak, free of the as requires a kind of reorientation. When we just stare at something, our just-having-it-before-us lies before us as a failure to u'ntkrstand it any more. This grasping which is free of the as is a privation of simple seeing, which understands; it is not more primordial than the latter, but derived from it. The ontic inexplicitness of the "as" must not mislead us into overlooking it as the a primi existential constitution of understanding. But if any perception of useful things at hand always understands and interprets them, letting them be circumspectly encountered as something, does this not then mean that initially something merely objectively present is experienced which then is understood as a door, as a house? That would be a misunderstanding of the specific disclosive function of interpretation. Interpretation does not, so to speak, throw a "significance" over what is nakedly objectively present and does not stick a value on it, but what is encountered in the world is always already in a relevance which is disclosed in the understanding of world, a relevance which is made explicit by interpretation. Things at hand are always already understood in terms of a totality of relevance. This totality need not be explicitly grasped by a thematic interpretation. Even if it has undergone such an interpretation, it recedes again into an undifferentiated understanding. This is the very mode in which it is the essential foundation of everyday, circumspect interpretation. This is always based on a fore-having. As the appropriation of understanding in being that understands, the interpretation operates in being toward a totality of relevance which has already been understood. When
J.v
Being and Tim.
141
something is understood but still veiled, it becomes unveiled by an act of appropriation and this is always done under the guidance of a perspective which fixes that with regard to which what has been understood is to be interpreted. The interpretation is grounded in a foresight that "approaches" what has been taken in fore-having with a definite interpretation in view. What is held in the fore-having and understood in a "fore-seeing" view becomes comprehensible through the interpretation. The interpretation can draw the conceptuality belonging to the beings to be interpreted from these themselves or else force them into concepts to which beings are opposed in accordance with their kind of being. The interpretation has always already decided, finally or provisionally, upon a definite conceptuality; it is grounded in afore-conception. The interpretation of something as something is essentially grounded in fore-having, fore-sight, and fore-conception. Interpretation is never a presuppositionless grasping of something previously given. When the particular concretion of the interpretation in the sense of exact text interpretation likes to appeal to what "is there," what is initially "there" is nothing else than the self-evident, undisputed prejudice of the interpreter, which is necessarily there in each point of departure of the interpretation as what is already "posited" with interpretation as such, that is, pre-given with fore-having, fore-sight, fore-conception. How are we to conceive the character of this "fore"? Have we done this when we formally say "a priori"? Why is this structure appropriate to understanding which we have characterized as a fundamental existential of Da-sein? How is the structure of the "as" which belongs to what is interpreted as such related to the fore-structure? This phenomenon is obviously not to be dissolved "into pieces." But is a primordial analytic to be ruled out? Should we accept such phenomena as "finalities"? Then the question would remain, why? Or do the fore-structure of understanding and the as-structure of interpretation show an existential-ontological connection with the phenomenon of project? And does this phenomenon refer back to a primordial constitution of being of Da-sein? Before answering these questions for which the preparation up to this point is not at all sufficient, we must inquire whether what is visible as the fore-structure of understanding and qua the as-structure of interpretation does not itself already represent a unitary phenomenon which is used copiously in philosophical problematics, though what is used so universally falls short of the primordiality of ontological explication. In the projecting of understanding, beings are disclosed in their possibility. The character of possibility always corresponds to the kind of being of the beings understood. Innerworldly beings in general are projected toward the world, that is, toward a totality of significance in whose referential relations taking care, as being-in-the-world, has rooted itself from the beginning. When with the being of Da-sein innerworldly beings
151
142
152
Being and Time
I.v
are discovered, that is, have come to be understood, we say that they have meaning. But strictly speaking, what is understood is not the meaning, but beings, or being. Meaning is that wherein the intelligibility of something maintains itself. What can be articulated in disclosure that understands we call meaning. The concept of meaning includes the formal framework of what necessarily belongs to what interpretation that understands articulates. Meaning, structured by fore-having, fore-sight, and fore· conception, is the upon which of the project in terms of which something becomes intelligible as something. Since understanding and interpretation constitute the existential constitution of the being of the there, meaning must be understood as the formal, existential framework of the disclosedness belonging to understanding. Meaning is an existential of Da-sein, not a property which is attached to beings, which lies "behind" them or floats somewhere as a "realm between." Only Da-sein "has" meaning in that the disclosedness of being-in-the-world can be "fulfilled" through the beings discoverable in it. Thus only Da-sein can be meaningful or meaning· less. This means that its own being and the beings disclosed with that being can be appropriated in understanding or they can be confined to incomprehensibility. If we adhere to this interpretation of the concept of "meaning," that is in principle ontological-existential, all beings whose mode of being is unlike Da-sein must be understood as unmeaningful, as essentially bare of meaning as such. "Unmeaningful" does not mean here a value judgment, but expresses an ontological determination. And only what is unmeaningful can be absurd. Objectively present things encountered in Da-sein can, so to speak, run against its being, for example, events of nature which break in on us and destroy us. And when we ask about the meaning of being, our inquiry does not become profound and does not brood on anything which stands behind being, but questions being itself in so far as it stands within the intelligibility of Da-sein. The meaning of being can never be contrasted with beings or with being as the supporting "ground" of beings because "ground" is only accessible as meaning, even if that meaning itself is an abyss of meaninglessness. As the disclosedness of the there, understanding always concerns the whole of being-in-the-world. In every understanding of world, existence is also understood, and vice versa. Furthermore, every interpretation operates within the fore-structure which we characterized. Every interpretation which is to contribute some understanding must already have understood what is to be interpreted. This fact has always already been noticed, if only in the realm of derivative ways of understanding and interpretation, in philological interpretation. The latter belongs to the scope of scientific cognition. Such cognition demands the rigor of
I.V
Being and Time
143
demonstration giving reasons. Scientific proof must not already presuppose what its task is to found. But if interpretation always already has to operate within what is understood and nurture itself from this, how should it then produce scientific results without going in a circle, especially when the presupposed understanding still operates in the common knowledge of human being and world? But according to the most elementary rules of logic, the circle is a circulus vitios'lis. But the business of historical interpretation is thus banned a priori from the realm of exact knowledge. If the fact of the circle in understanding is not removed, historiography must be content with less strict possibilities of knowledge. It is permitted more or less to replace this lack with the "spiritual significance" of its "objects." It would be more ideal, of course, moreover according to the opinion of the historiographers themselves, if the circle could be avoided and if there were the hope for once of creating a historiography which is· as independent of the standpoint of the observer as the knowledge of nature is supposed to be. But to see a vitiosum in this circle and to look for ways to avoid i~ even to "feel" that is an inevitable impeifection, is to misunderstand understanding from the ground up. It is not a matter of assimilating understanding and interpretation to a particular ideal of knowledge which is itself only a degeneration of understanding which has strayed into the legitimate grasping what is objectively present in its essential unintelligibility. The fulfillment of the fundamental conditions of possible interpretation rather lies in not mistaking interpretation beforehand with regard to the essential conditions of its being done. What is decisive is not to get out of the circle, but to get in it in the right way. This circle of understanding is not a circle in which any random kind of knowledge operates, but it is rather the expression of the existential fore-structure of Da-sein itself. The circle must not be degraded to a vitiosum, not even to a tolerated one. A positive possibility of the most primordial knowledge is hidden in it which, however, is only grasped in a genuine way when interpretation has understood that its first, constant, and last task is not to let fore-having, fore-sight, and fore-conception be given to it by chance ideas and popular conceptions, but to guarantee the scientific theme by developing these in terms of the things themselves. Because in accordance with its existential meaning, understanding is the potentiality for being of Da-sein itself, the ontological presuppositions of historiographical knowledge transcend in principle the idea of rigor of the most exact sciences. Mathematics is not more exact than historiographical, but only narrower with regard to the scope of the existential foundations relevant to it. The "circle" in understanding belongs to the structure of meaning, and this phenomenon is rooted in the existential constitution of Dasein, in interpretive understanding. Beings which, as being-in-the-world,
153
144
Being and Time
I.v
are concerned about their being itself* have an ontological structure of the circle. However, if we note that the "circle" belongs ontologically to a kind of being of objective presence (subsistence), we shall in general have to avoid characterizing something like Da-sein ontologically with this phenomenon.
33. Statement as a Derivative Mode of Interpretation
154
All interpretation is grounded in understanding. What is articulated as such in interpretation and is prefigured as articulable in understanding in general is meaning. Since the statement (the "judgment") is based on understanding and represents a derivative form of interpretation, it also "has" a meaning. Meaning, however, cannot be defined as what occurs "in" a judgment along with the act of judgment. The explicit analysis of the statement has several goals in our context. On the one hand, we can demonstrate in the statement in what way the structure of the "as," which is constitutive for understanding and interpretation, can be modified. Understanding and interpretation thus come into sharper focus. Then, the analysis of the statement has a distinctive place in the fundamental-ontological problematic because in the decisive beginnings of ancient ontology the logos functioned as the sole guide for the access to true beings and for the determination of the being of beings. Finally, the statement has been regarded from ancient times as the primary and true "locus" of truth. This phenomenon is so intimately connected with the problem of being that our inquiry necessarily runs into the problem of truth as it proceeds; it already lies within the dimension of that problem, although not explicitly. The analysis of the statement is to make way for this problematic. In what follows we shall assign to the term statement three significations which are drawn from the phenomenon thus characterized. They are interconnected and delineate in their unity the full structure of the statement I. Primarily, statement means pointing out. With this we adhere to the primordial meaning of logos as apophansis: to let beings be seen from themselves. In the statement "the hammer is too heavy," what is discovered for sight is not a "meaning," but a being in the mode of its being at hand. Even when this being is not near enough to be grasped and "seen," pointing out designates the being itself, not a mere representa-
* But this "its being itself" is intrinsically determined by the understanding of being, that is, by standing within the dearing of presence, where neither the dearing as such nor presence as such becomes thematic for representational thinking.
I.v
Being and Time
145
tion of it, neither something "merely represented" nor even a psychical condition of the speaker, his representing of this being. 2. Statement is tantamount to predication. A "predicate" is "stated" about a "subject," the latter is determined by the fanner. What is stated in this signification of statement is not the predicate, but the "hammer itself." What does the stating, that is, the determining, on the other hand, lies in the "too heavy." What is stated in the second signification of statement, what is determined as such, has been narrowed down in its content as opposed to what is stated in the first signification of this tenn. Every predication is what it is only as a pointing out. The second signification of statement has its foundation in the first. The elements which are articulated in predication, subject-predicate, originate within the pointing out. Determining does not first discover, but as a mode of pointing out initially limits seeing precisely to what shows itself-hammer-as such, in order to manifest explicitly what is manifest in its determinacy through, the explicit limitation of looking. When confronted with what is already manifest, with the hammer which is too heavy, determining must first take a step back. "Positing the subject" dims beings down to focus on "the hammer there" in order to let what is manifest be seen in its determinable definite character through this dimming down. Positing the subject, positing the predicate, and positing them together are thoroughly "apophantic" in the strict sense of the word. 3. Statement means communication, speaking forth. As such it has a direct relation to statement in the first and second meanings. It is letting someone see with us what has been pointed out in its definite character. Letting someone see with us shares with the others the beings pointed out in their defmiteness. What is "shared" is the being toward what is pointed out which has a way of seeing common to all. We must keep in mind that this being-toward is being-in-the-world, namely, in the world from which what is pointed out is encountered. Any statement, as a communication understood existentially, must have been expressed. As something communicated, what is spoken can be "shared" by the others with the speaker even when they themselves do not have the beings pointed out and defmed in a palpable and visible range. What is spoken can be "passed along" in further retelling. The scope of communication which sees is broadened. But at the same time what is pointed out can become veiled again in this further retelling, although the knowledge and cognition growing in such hearsay always means beings themselves and does not "affinn" a "valid meaning" passed around. Even hearsay is a being-in-the-world and a being toward what is heard. The theory of "judgment" prevalent today that is oriented toward the phenomenon of "validity" shall not be discussed at any length here. It is sufficient to refer to the very questionable character of this phe-
155
146
156
157
Being and Time
I.v
nomenon of "validity" which, ever since Lotze, people have been fond of passing off as a "primal phenomenon" not to be traced further back. It owes this role only to its ontological lack of clarity. The "problematic" which has entrenched itself around this idolatry of the word is just as opaque. On the one hand, validity means the "form" of the reality which belongs to the content of the judgment since it has an unchangeable existence as opposed to the changeable "psychic" act of judgment. In the light of the position of the question of being in general characterized in the introduction to this inquiry, we can hardly expect that "validity" as "ideal being" is going to be distinguished by any special ontological clarity. Then, at the same time, validity means the validity of the meaning of the judgment which is valid for the "object" it has in view and thus receives the significance of "objective validity" and objectivity in general. The meaning thus "valid" for beings, and which is valid "timelessly" in itself, is said to be "valid" also in the sense of being valid for every person who judges rationally. Now validity means bindingness, "universal validity." If one then advocates a "critical" epistemological theory, according to which the subject does not "truly" "come out" to the object, then this valid character, as the validity of an object, objectivity, is based on the valid content of true(!) meaning. The three meanings of "validity" set forth, the way of being of the ideal, as objectivity and as bindingness, are not only in themselves opaque, but constantly get confused with one another. Methodological caution requires we do not choose such unstable concepts as the guide for our interpretation. We make no advance restriction on the concept of meaning which would confine it to a signification of a "content of judgment," but we understand it as the existential phenomenon characterized in which the formal framework of what can be disclosed in understanding and articulated in interpretation becomes visible as such. When we collect the three meanings of "statement" analyzed here in a unitary view of the complete phenomenon, the definition reads: Statement is a pointing out which communicates and defines. Now we must ask: what right do we have at all to conceive the statement as a mode of interpretation? If it is something of this sort, the essential structures of interpretation must be repeated in it. The statement's pointing out is accomplished on the basis of what is already disclosed in understanding, or what is circumspectly discovered. The statement is not an unattached kind of behavior which could of itself primarily disclose beings in general, but always already maintains itself on the basis of being-in-theworld. When we showed earlier10 with regard to world cognition is just as true of the statement. It needs a fore-having of something disclosed in general which it points out in the mode of determining. Furthermore, when one begins to determine something, one has a directed viewpoint
I.v
Being and Time
147
of what is to be stated. The function of determining takes over the direction in which beings that have been presented are envisaged in the act of determining. The statement needs a fore-sight in which the predicate which is to be delineated and attributed is itselfloosened, so to speak, in its inexplicit enclosure in beings themselves. A significant articulation of what is pointed out always belongs to the statement as communication that defmes, it operates within a defmite set of concepts. The hammer is heavy, heaviness belongs to the hammer, the hammer has the property of heaviness. The fore-conception always also contained in the statement remains mostly inconspicuous because language always already contains a developed set of concepts. Like interpretation in general, the statement necessarily has its existential foundations in fore-having, fore-sight, and fore-conception. But how does the statement become a derivative mode of interpretation? What has been modified in it? We can point out the modification by sticking with limiting cases of statements which function in logic as normal cases and examples of the most "simple" phenomena of statement. What logic makes thematic with the categorical statement, for example, "the hammer is heavy," it has always already understood "logically" before any analysis. As the "meaning" of the sentence, it has already presupposed without noticing it the following: this thing, the hammer, has the property of heaviness. "Initially" there are no such statements in heedful circumspection. But it does have its specific ways of interpretation which can read as follows as compared with the "theoretical judgment" just mentioned and may take some such form as "the hammer is too heavy" or, even better, "too heavy, the other hammer!" The primordial act of interpretation lies not in a theoretical sentence, but in circumspectly and heedfully putting away or changing the inappropriate tool "without wasting words." From the fact that words are absent, we may not conclude that the interpretation is absent. On the other hand, the circumspectly spoken interpretation is not already necessarily a statement in the sense defined. Through what existential ontological modifu;ations does the statement originate from circumspect interpretation?* The being held in fore-having, for example the hammer, is initially at hand as a useful thing. If this being is the "object" of a statement, as soon as we begin the statement, a transformation in the fore-having is already brought about beforehand . Something at hand with which we have to do or perform something, turns into something "about which" the statement that points it out is made. Fore-sight aims at something
* In what way can the statement be made by changing the interpretation?
158
148
159
Being and TifTU!
l.v
objectively present in what is at hand. Both by and for the way oflooking, what is at hand is veiled as something at hand. Within this discovering of objective presence which covers over handiness, what is encountered as objectively present is detennined in its being objectively present in such and such a way. Now the access is first available for something like qual· ities. That as which the statement detennines what is objectively present is drawn from what is objectively present as such. The as-structure of interpretation has undergone a modification. The "as" no longer reaches out into a totality of relevance in its function of appropriating what is understood. It is cut off with regard to its possibilities of the articulation of referential relations of significance which constitute the character of the surrounding world. The "as" is forced back to the uniform level of what is merely objectively present. It dwindles to the structure ofjust letting what is objectively present be seen by way of determination. This levelling down of the primordial "as" of circumspect interpretation to the as of the detennination of objective presence is the speciality of the statement. Only in this way does it gain the possibility of a pointing something out in a way that we sheerly look at it. Thus the statement cannot deny its ontological provenance from an interpretation that understands. We call primordial the "as" of circumspect interpretation that understands (hermeneia}, the existentialhermeneutical "as" in distinction from the apophantical "as" of the statement. There are many interim stages between interpretation which is quite enveloped in heedful understanding and the extreme opposite case of a theoretical statement about objectively present things: statements about events in the surrounding world, descriptions of what is at hand, "reports on situations," noting and ascertaining a "factual situation," describing a state of affairs, telling about what has happened. These "sentences" cannot be reduced to theoretical propositional statements without essentially distorting their meaning. Like the latter, they have their "origin" in circumspect interpretation. With the progress of knowledge about the structure of the logos, it was inevitable that this phenomenon of the apophantical "as" carne to view in some form. The way in which it was initially seen is not a matter of chance, nor did it fail to have its influence on the history of logic to come. When considered philosophically, the logos is itself a being and, in accordance with the orientation of ancient ontology, something objectively present. What is initially objectively present, that is, what can be found like things, are words and the succession of words in which the logos is spoken. When we first seek for the structure of the logos thus objectively present, we find an objective presence together of several words.
I.v
Being and Time
149
What constitutes the unity of this together? As Plato knew, it consists in the fact that the logos is always logos tinos. With regard to the beings manifest in the logos, the words are combined to form one totality of words. Aristotle had a more radical view; every logos is synthesis and diairesis at the same time, not either the one-say, as a "positive judgment"-or the other-as a "negative judgment." Rather, every statement, whether affirmative or negative, whether false or true, is equiprimordially synthesis and diairesis. Pointing out is putting together and taking apart. However, Aristotle did not pursue this analytical question further to a problem: what phenomenon is it then within the structure of the logos that allows and requires us to characterize every statement as synthesis and diairesis? What is to be got at phenomenally with the formal structures of "binding" and "separating," more precisely, with the unity of the two, is the phenomenon of "something as something." In accordance with this structure, something is understood with regard to something else, it is taken together with it, so that this confrontation that understands, interprets, and articulates, at the same time takes apart what has been put together. If the phenomenon of the "as" is covered over and above all veiled in its existential origin from the hermeneutical "as," Aristotle's phenomenological point of departure disintegrates to the analysis of logos in an external "theory of judgment," according to which judgment is a binding or separating of representations and concepts. Thus binding and separating can be further formalized to mean a "relating." Logistically, the judgment is dissolved into a system of "coordinations," it becomes the object of "calculation," but not a theme of ontological interpretation. The possibility and impossibility of the analytical understanding of synthesis and diairesis, of "relation" in the judgment in general, is closely bound up with the actual state of the fundamental ontological problematic. To what extent this problematic has an effect on the interpretation of the logos and, on the other hand, to what extent the concept of "judgment" has, by a remarkable counter-movement, an effect on the ontological problematic, is shown by the phenomenon of the copula. It becomes evident in this "bond" that the structure of synthesis is initially posited as a matter of course and that it has also maintained the decisive interpretative function. But if the formal characteristics of "relation" and "binding" cannot contribute anything phenomenally to the factual structural analysis of the logos, the phenomenon intended with the term copula finally has nothing to do with bond and binding. Whether expressed explicitly in language or indicated in the verbal ending, the "is" and its interpretation are moved into the context of problems of the existential analytic if statements and an understanding of being are exis-
160
150
Being and Time
I.v
tential possibilities of being of Da-sein itself. The development of the question of being (cf. division I, section 3) will then encounter again this peculiar phenomenon of being within the logos. For the time being, we wanted to clarify with this demonstration of the derivation of the statement from interpretation and understanding the fact that the "logic" of logos is rooted in the existential analytic of Dasein. Recognizing the ontologically insufficient interpretation of the logos at the same time sharpens our insight into the lack of primordiality of the methodical basis on which ancient ontology developed. The logos is experienced as something objectively present and interpreted as such, and the beings which it points out have the meaning "of objective presence as well. lbis meaning being itself is left undifferentiated and uncontrasted with other possibilities of being so that being in the sense of a formal being-something is at the same time fused with it and we are unable to obtain a clear-cut division between these two realms.*
34. Da-sein and Discourse: Language
161
The fundamental existentials which constitute the being of the there, the disclosedness of being-in-the-world, are attunement and understanding. Understanding harbors in itself the possibility of interpretation, that is, the appropriation of what is understood. To the extent that attunement is equiprimordial with understanding, it maintains itself in a certain understanding. A certain possibility of interpretation also belongs to it. An extreme derivative of interpretation was made visible with the statement. The clarification of the third meaning of statement as communication (speaking forth) led us to the concept of saying and speaking, to which we purposely paid no attention up to now. The fact that language only now becomes thematic should indicate that this phenomenon has its roots in the existential constitution of the disclosedness of Da-sein. The existential-ontological foundation of language is discourse. In our previous interpretation of attunement, understanding, interpretation, and statement we have constantly made use of this phenomenon, but have, so to speak, suppressed it in the thematic analysis. Discourse is existentially equiprimordial with attunement and understanding. Intelligibility is also always already articulated before its appropriative interpretation. Discourse is the articulation of intelligibility. Thus it already lies at the basis of interpretation and statement. We called what can be articulated in interpretation, and thus more primordially in speech, meaning. What is articulated in discoursing articulation as such, we call the totality of significations. lbis totality can be dissolved into significations.
* Husserl.
I.V
Being and Time
151
As what is articulated of what can be articulated, significations are always bound up with meaning. If discourse, the articulation of the intelligibility of the there, is the primordial existential of disclosedness and if disclosedness is primarily constituted by being-in-the-world, discourse must also essentially have a specifically worldly mode of being. The attuned intelligibility of being-in-the-world is expressed as discourse. The totality of significations of intelligibility is put into words. Words accrue to significations. But word-things are not provided with significations. The way in which discourse gets expressed is language. This totality of words in which discourse has its own "worldly" being can thus be found as an innerworldly being, like something at hand. Language can be broken up into word-things objectively present. Discourse is existential language because the beings whose disclosedness it significantly articulates have the kind of being of being-in-the-world which is thrown and reliant upon the "world."* As the existential constitution of the disclosedness ofDa-sein, discourse is constitutive for the existence of Da-sein. Hearing and keeping silent are possibilities belonging to discoursing speech. The constitutive function of discourse for the existentiality of existence first becomes completely clear in these phenomena. First of all, we must develop the structure of discourse as such. Discoursing is the "significant" articulation of the intelligibility of being-in-the-world, to which belongs being-with, and which maintains itself in a particular way of heedful being-with-one-another. Being-withone-another talks in assenting, refusing, inviting, warning, as talking things through, as getting back to someone, interceding, furthermore as "making statements" and as talking in "giving a talk." Discourse is discourse about .... That which discourse is about does not necessarily have the character of the theme of a definite statement; in fact, mostly it does not have it. Even command is given about something; a wish is about something. And so is intercession. Discourse necessarily has this structural factor because it also constitutes the disclosedness of being-inthe-world and is prestructured in its own structure by this fundamental constitution of Da-sein. What is talked about in discourse is always "addressed" in a particular view and within certain limits. In all discourse there is what is spoken as such, what is said as such when one actually wishes, asks, talks things over about .... In this "something said," discourse communicates. As the analysis has already indicated, the phenomenon of communication must be understood in an ontologically broad sense. "Commu-
* Tirrownness is essential to language.
162
152
163
Being and Time
I.v
nication" in which one makes statements, for example, giving information, is a special case of the communication that is grasped in principle existentially. Here the articulation of being-with-one-another understandingly is constituted. It brings about the "sharing" of being attuned together and of the understanding of being-with. Communication is never anything like a conveying of experiences, for example, opinions and wishes, from the inside of one subject to the inside of another. Mitda·sein is essentially already manifest in attunement-with and understanding-with. Being-with is "explicitly" shared in discourse, that is, it already is, only unshared as something not grasped and appropriated. All discourse about ... which communicates in what it says has at the same time the character of expressing itself In talking, Da-sein expresses itself not because it has been initially cut off as "something internal" from something outside, but because as being-in-the-world it is already "outside" when it understands. What is expressed is precisely this being outside,* that is, the actual mode of attunement (of mood) which we showed to pertain to the full disclosedness of being-in. Being-in and its attunement are made known in discourse and indicated in language by intonation, modulation, in the tempo of talk, "in the way of speaking." The communication of the existential possibilities of attunement, that is, the disclosing of existence, can become the true aim of "poetic" speech. Discourse is the articulation in accordance with significance of the attuned intelligibility of being-in-the-world. Its constitutive factors are: what discourse is about (what is discussed}, what is said as such, communication, and making known. These are not properties which can be just empirically snatched from language, but are existential characteristics rooted in the constitution of being of Da-sein which first make something like language ontologically possible. Some of these factors can be lacking or remain unnoticed in the facticallinguistic form of a particular discourse. The fact that they often are not "verbally" expressed is only an indication of a particular kind of discourse which, insofar as it is discourse, must always lie within the totality of these structures. Attempts to grasp the "essence of language" have always taken their orientation toward a single one of these factors and have understood language guided by the idea of"expression," "symbolical forms," communication as "statement," "making known" experiences or the "form" of life. But nothing would be gained for a completely sufficient definition of language if we were to put these different fragmentary definitions together in a syncretistic way. What is decisive is to develop
* The there; being exposed as an open place.
I.V
Being and Time
153
the ontological-existential totality of the structure of discourse beforehand on the basis of the analytic of Da-sein. The connection of discourse with understanding and intelligibility becomes clear through an existential possibility which belongs to discourse itself, hearing. It is not a matter of chance that we say, when we have not heard "rightly," that we have not "understood." Hearing is constitutive for discourse. And just as linguistic utterance is based on discourse, acoustic perception is based on hearing. listening to ... is the existential being-open of Da-sein as being-with for the other. Hearing even constitutes the primary and authentic openness of Da-sein for its ownmost possibility of being, as in hearing the voice of the friend whom every Da-sein carries with it. Da-sein hears because it understands. As being-in-the-world that understands, with the others, it "listens to" itself and to Mitda-sein, and in this listening belongs to these. listening to each other, in which being-with is developed, has the possible ways of following, going along with, and the privative modes of not hearing, opposition, defying, turning away. On the basis of this existentially primary potentiality for hearing, something like hearkening becomes possible. Hearkening is itself phenomenally more primordial than what the psychologist "initially" defines as hearing, the sensing of tones and the perception of sounds. Hearkening, too, has the mode of being of a hearing that understands. "Initially" we never hear noises and complexes of sound, but the creaking wagon, the motorcycle. We hear the column on the march, the north wind, the woodpecker tapping, the crackling fire. It requires a very artificial and complicated attitude in order to "hear" a "pure noise." The fact that we initially hear motorcycles and wagons is, however, the phenomenal proof that Da-sein, as being-in-theworld, always already maintains itself together with innerworldly things at hand and initially not at all with "sensations" whose chaos would first have to be formed to provide the springboard from which the subject jumps off finally to land in a "world." Essentially understanding, Dasein is initially together with what is understood. In the explicit hearing of the discourse of the other, too, we initially understand what is said: more precisely, we are already together with the other beforehand, with the being which the discourse is about. We do not, on the contrary, first hear what is expressed in the utterance. Even when speaking is unclear or the language is foreign, we initially hear unintelligible words, and not a multiplicity of tone data. When what the discourse is about is heard "naturally," however, we can at the same time hear the way in which it is said, the "diction," but this, too, only by previously understanding what is spoken. Only thus is there a possibility of estimating whether the way in which it is said is
164
154
165
Being and Time
l.v
appropriate to what the discourse is about thematically. Similarly, speaking in turn as an answer initially arises directly from understanding what the discourse is about, which is already "shared" in being-with. Only when the existential possibility of discourse and hearing are given, can someone hearken. He who "cannot hear" and "must feel" can perhaps hearken very well precisely for this reason. Just listening around is a privation of the hearing that understands. Discourse and hearing are grounded in understanding. Understanding comes neither from a lot of talking nor from busy listening around. Only he who already understands is able to listen. Another essential possibility of discourse has the same existential foundation, keeping silent. In talking with one another the person who is silent can "let something be understood," that is, he can develop an understanding more authentically than the person who never runs out of words. Speaking a lot about something does not in the least guarantee that understanding is thus furthered. On the contrary, talking at great length about something covers things over and gives a false impression of clarity to what is understood, that is, the unintelligibility of the trivial. But to keep silent does not mean to be dumb. On the contrary, if a person is dumb, he still has the tendency to "speak." Such a person has not only not proved that he can keep silent, he even lacks the possibility of proving this. And the person who is by nature accustomed to speak little is no better able to show that he can be silent and keep silent. He who never says anything is also unable to keep silent at a given moment. Authentic silence is possible only in genuine discourse. In order to be silent, Da-sein must have something to say,* that is, must be in command of an authentic and rich disclosedness of itself. Then reticence makes manifest and puts down "idle talk." As a mode of discourse, reticence articulates the intelligibility of Da-sein so primordially that it gives rise to a genuine potentiality for hearing and to a being-with-one-another that is transparent. Since discourse is constitutive for the being of the there, that is, attunement and understanding, and since Da-sein means being-in-theworld, Da-sein as discoursing being-in has already expressed itself. Dasein has language. Is it a matter of chance that the Greeks, whose everyday existence lay predominantly in speaking with one another and who at the same time "had eyes" to see, determined the essence of human being as zoon logon echont in the pre-philosophical as well in as the philo*and what calls for saying [das Zu-sagende]? (being) [Seyn]Human being as the "gatherer," gathering toward being [Seyn ]-presencing in the openness [Offenheit] of beings (but with the latter in the background.
t
I.v
Being and Time
155
sophical interpretation of Da-sein? The later interpretation of this definition of human being in the sense of the animal rationale, "rational living being," is not "false," but it covers over the phenomenal basis from which this definition of Da-sein is taken. The human being shows himself as a being who speaks. This does not mean that the possibility of vocal utterance belongs to him, but that this being is in the mode of discovering world and Da-sein itself. The Greeks do not have a word for language, they "initially" understood this phenomenon as discourse. However, since the logos came into their philosophical view predominantly as statement, the development of the fundamental structures of the forms and constituents of discourse was carried out following the guideline of this logos. Grammar searched for its foundation in the "logic" of this logos. But this logic is based on the ontology of objective presence. The basic stock of "categories of significance" which were passed over in subsequent linguistics and are fundamentally still accepted as the criterion today is oriented toward discourse as statement. If, however, we take this phenomenon in principle to have the fundamental primordiality and scope of an existential, the necessity arises of reestablishing the linguistics on an ontologically more primordial foundation. The task of freeing grammar from logic requires in advance a positive understanding of the a priori fundamental structure of discourse in general as an existential and cannot be carried out subsequently by improving and supplementing the tradition. Bearing this in mind, we must inquire into the basic forms in which it is possible to articulate what is intellible in general, not only of the innerworldly beings that can be known in theoretical observation and expressed in propositions. A doctrine of significance will not emerge automatically from a comprehensive comparison of as many languages as possible and those that are most exotic. Nor is it sufficient to adopt the philosophical horizon within which W. von Humboldt took language as a problem. The doctrine of significance is rooted in the ontology of Da-sein. Whether it prospers or decays depends upon the fate of this ontology. 11 In the end, philosophical research must for once decide to ask what mode of being belongs to language in general. Is it an innerworldly useful thing at hand or does it have the mode of being of Da-sein or neither of the two? What kind of being does language have if there can be a "dead" language? What does it mean ontologically that a language grows or declines? We possess a linguistics, and the being of beings which it has as its theme is obscure; even the horizon for any investigative question about it is veiled. Is it a matter of chance that initially and for the most part significations are "worldly," prefigured beforehand by the significance of the world, that they are indeed often predominantly "spatial"? Or is this "fact" existentially and ontologically necessary
166
156
Being and Time
I.v
and why? Philosophical research will have to give up the "linguistics" if it is to ask about the "things themselves" and attain the status of a problematic that has been clarified conceptually. The foregoing interpretation of language has the sole function of pointing out the ontological "place" for this phenomenon in the constitution of being of Da-sein and above all of preparing the way for the following analysis, in which, taking as our guideline a fundamental kind of being belonging to discourse, in connection with other phenomena, we shall try to bring the everydayness of Da-sein into view in a way that is ontologically more primordial. B. THE EVERYDAY BEING OF THE THERE AND THE FALLING PREY OF DA-SEIN
167
In returning to the existential structures of the disclosedness of being-inthe-world, our interpretation has in a way lost sight of the everydayness of Da-sein. The analysis must again regain this phenomenal horizon that was our thematic point of departure. Now the question arises: What are the existential characteristics of the disclosedness of being-in-theworld, to the extent that the latter, as something everyday, maintains itself in the mode of being of the they? Is a specific attunement, a special understanding, discourse, and interpretation appropriate to the they? The answer to this question becomes all the more urgent when we remember that Da-sein initially and for the most part is immersed in the they and mastered by it. Is not Da-sein, as thrown being-in-the-world, initially thrown into the publicness of the they? And what else does this publicness mean than the specific disclosedness of the they? If understanding must be conceived primarily as the potentiality-forbeing of Da-sein, we shall be able to gather from an analysis of the understanding and interpretation belonging to the they which possibilities of its being Da-sein as the they has disclosed and appropriated to itself. These possibilities themselves, however, reveal an essential tendency of being of everydayness. And everydayness must finally, when explicated in an ontologically sufficient way, unveil a primordial mode of being of Da-sein in such a way that from it the phenomenon of thrownness which we have pointed out can be exhibited in its existential concreteness. What is initially required is to make visible the disclosedness of the they, that is, the everyday mode of being of discourse, sight, and interpretation, in specific phenomena. With regard to these, the remark may not be superfluous that our interpretation has a purely ontological intention and is far removed from any moralizing critique of everyday Da-sein and from the aspirations of a "philosophy of culture."
I.v
Being and Time
157
35. Idle Talk
The expression "idle talk" is not be used here in a disparaging sense. Terminologically, it means a positive phenomenon which constitutes the mode of being of the understanding and interpretation of everyday Da-sein. For the most part, discourse expresses itself and has always already expressed itself. It is language. But then understanding and interpretation are always already contained in what is expressed. As expression, language harbors in itself an interpretedness of the understanding of Da-sein. This interpretedness is no more merely objectively present than language is, but rather its being is itself of the character of Da-sein. Da-sein is initially and in certain limits constantly entrusted to this interpretedness that directs and apportions the possibilities of the average understanding and the attunement belonging to it. In the totality of its articulated contexts of signification, expression preserves an understanding of the disclosed world and thus equiprimordially an understanding of the Mitda-sein of the others and of one's own being-in. The understanding already deposited in expression concerns the discoveredness of beings actually reached and handed down, as well as the actual understanding of being and the possibilities and horizons available to fresh interpretation and conceptual articulation. But above and beyond a mere reference to the fact of this interpretedness of Da-sein, we must now ask about the existential mode of being of the discourse which is expressed and expressing itself. If it cannot be conceived as something objectively present, what is its being, and what does this being say in principle about the everyday mode of being of Da-sein? Discourse expressing itself is communication. Its tendency of being aims at bringing the hearer to participate in disclosed being toward what is talked about in discourse. In the language that is spoken when one expresses oneself, there already lies an average intelligibility; and in accordance with this intelligibility, the discourse communicated can be understood to a large extent without the listener coming to a being toward what is talked about in di!rcourse so as to have a primordial understanding of it. One understands not so much the beings talked about, but one does listen to what is spoken about as such. This is understood, what is talked about is understood, only approximately and superficially. One means the same thing because it is in the same averageness that we have a common understanding of what is said. Hearing and understanding have attached themselves beforehand to what is spoken about as such. Communication does not "impart" the primary relation of being to the being spoken about, but being-withone-another takes place in talking with one another and in heeding
168
158
169
Being and Time
T.v
what is spoken about. What is important to it is that one speaks. The being-said, the dictum, the pronouncement provide a guarantee for the genuineness and appropriateness of the discourse and the understanding belonging to it. And since this discoursing has lost the primary relation of being to the being talked about, or else never achieved it, it does not communicate in the mode of a primordial appropriation of this being, but communicates by gossiping and passing the word along. What is spoken about as such spreads in wider circles and takes on a authoritative character. Things are so because one says so. Idle talk is constituted in this gossiping and passing the word along, a process by which its initial lack of grounds to stand on increases to complete groundlessness. And this is not limited to vocal gossip, but spreads to what is written, as "scribbling." In this latter case, gossiping is based not so much on hearsay. It feeds on sporadic superficial reading: The average understanding of the reader will never be able to decide what has been drawn from primordial sources with a struggle, and how much is just gossip. Moreover, the average understanding will not even want such a distinction, will not have need of it, since, after all, it understands everything. The groundlessness of idle talk is no obstacle to its being public, but encourages it. Idle talk is the possibility of understanding everything without any previous appropriation of the matter. Idle talk already guards against the danger of getting stranded in such an appropriation. Idle talk, which everyone can snatch up, not only divests us of the task of genuine understanding, but develops an indifferent intelligibility for which nothing is closed off any longer. Discourse, which belongs to the essential constitution of being ofDasein, and also constitutes its disclosedness, has the possibility of becoming idle talk, and as such of not really keeping being-in-the-world open in an articulated understanding, but of closing it off and covering over innerworldly beings. To do this, one need not aim to deceive. Idle talk does not have the kind of being of consciously passing off something as something else. The fact that one has said something groundlessly and then passes it along is in further retelling sufficient to tum disclosing around into a closing off. For what is said is initially always understood as "saying," that is, as discovering. Thus, by its very nature, idle talk is a closing off since it omits going back to the foundation of what is being talked about. This closing off is aggravated anew by the fact that idle talk, in which an understanding of what is being talked about is supposedly reached, holds any new questioning and discussion at a distance because it presumes it has understood and in a peculiar way it suppresses them and holds them back. This interpretedness of idle talk has always already settled itself down in Da-sein. We get to know many things initially in this way, and
I.v
Being and Time
159
some things never get beyond such an average understanding. Da-sein can never escape the everyday way of being interpreted into which Dasein has grown initially. All genuine understanding, interpreting and communication, rediscovery and new appropriation come about in it and out of it and against it. It is not the case that a Da-sein, untouched and unseduced by this way of interpreting, was ever confronted by the free land of a "world," merely to look at what it encounters. The domination of the public way in which things have been interpreted has already decided upon even the possibilities of being attuned, that is, about the basic way in which Da-sein lets itself be affected by the world. The they prescribes that attunement, it determines what and how one "sees." Idle talk, which closes off in the way we described, is the mode of being of the uprooted understanding of Da-sein. However, it does not occur as the objectively present condition of something objectively present, but it is existentially uprooted, and this uprooting is constant. Ontologically, this means that when Da-sein maintains itself in idle talk, it is-as being-in-the-world-cut off from the primary and primordially genuine relations of being toward the world, toward Mitda-sein, toward being-in itself. It keeps itself in suspension and yet in doing so it is still always together with the "world," with the others, and toward itself. Only those beings whose disclosedness is constituted by attuned and understanding discourse, that is, who are in this ontological constitution their there, who are "in-the-world," have the possibility of being of such uprooting which, far from constituting a nonbeing of Da-sein, rather constitutes its most everyday and stubborn "reality." However, it is in the nature of the obviousness and self-assurance of the average way of being interpreted that under its protection, the uncanniness of the suspension in which Da-sein can drift toward an increasing groundlessness remains concealed to actual Da-sein itself.
36. Curiosity In the analysis of understanding and the disclosedness of the there in general, we referred to the lumen naturale and called the disclosedness of being-in the clearing of Da-sein in which something like sight first becomes possible. Sight was conceived with regard to the basic kind of disclosing characteristic of Da-sein, understanding in the sense of the genuine appropriation of beings to which Da-sein can be related in accordance with its essential possibilities of being. The basic constitution of being of sight shows itself in a peculiar tendency of being which belongs to everydayness-the tendency toward "seeing." We designate it with the term curiosity which is characteristically
170
160
171
172
Being and Time
I.v
not limited to seeing and expresses the tendency toward a peculiar way of letting the world be encountered in perception. Our aim in interpreting this phenomenon is in principle existential and ontological. We do not restrict ourselves to an orientation toward cognition. Even in the early stages of Greek philosophy, and not by accident, cognition was conceived in terms of the "desire to see." The treatise which stands first in the collection of Aristotle's treatises on ontology begins with the sentence: pantes anthropoi tou eidenai oregontai phusei. 12 The care for seeing is essential to the being of human being. Thus an inquiry is introduced which attempts to discover the origin of all scientific investigation of beings and their being by deriving it from the kind of being of Da-sein which we mentioned. This Greek interpretation of the existential genesis of science is not a matter of chance. It brings to an explicit understanding what was prefigured in the statement of Parmenides: to gar auto noein estin te kai einai. Being is what shows itself in pure, intuitive perception, and only this seeing discovers being. Primordial and genuine truth lies in pure intuition. This thesis henceforth remains the foundation of Western philosophy. The Hegelian dialectic has its motivation in it, and only on its basis is that dialectic possible. Above all, it was Augustine who noted the remarkable priority of "seeing" in conjunction with his interpretation of concupiscentia. 1! Ad oculos enim videre proprie pertinet, seeing truly belongs to the eyes. Utimur autem hoc verbo etiam in ceteris sensibus cum eos ad cognoscendum intendimus. But we use this word "to see" for the other senses, too, when we use them in order to know. Neque enim dicimus: audi quid rutilet; aut, olefac quam niteat; auc, gusta quam splendeat; aut, palpa quam fulgeat: videri enim dicunter haec omnia. For we do not say: hear how that glistens, or smell how that shines, or taste how that glows, or feel how that gleams; but we say of each: see, we say that all these things are seen. Dicimus autem non solum, vide quid luceat, quod soli oculi sentire possunt, nor do we just say: see how that glows when only the eyes can perceive it, sed etiam, vide quid sonet; vide quid oleat, vide quid sapiat, vide quid durum sit. We also say: see how that sounds, see how it smells, see how it tastes, see how hard that is. ldeoque generalis experientia sensuum concupiscentia sicut dictum est oculorum vacatur, quia videndi officium in quo primatum oculi tenent, etiam ceteri sensus sibi de similitudine usurpant, cum aliquid cognitionis explorant. Thus because of experience of the senses in general is called "the pleasure of the eyes" because the other senses, by a certain resemblance, take to themselves the function of seeing when it is a knowing something, a function in which the eyes have priority. What is it with this tendency to just-perceive? Which existential constitution of Da-sein becomes intelligible in the phenomenon of curiosity'
I.v
Being and Time
161
Being-in-the-world is initially absorbed in the world taken care of. Taking care of things is guided by circumspection which discovers things at hand and preserves them in their discoveredness. Circumspection gives to all our teaching and performing its route of procedure, the means of doing something, the right opportunity, the proper moment. Taking care of things can rest in the sense of one's interrupting the performance and taking a rest, or of one's finishing something. Taking care of things does not disappear in rest, but circumspection becomes free, it is no longer bound to the work-world. When it rests, care turns into circumspection which has become free. The circumspect discovery of the work-world has the character of being of de-distancing. Circumspection which has become free no longer has anything at hand which it has to bring near. Essentially de-distancing, it provides new possibilities of de-distancing for itself, that is, it tends to leave the things nearest at hand for a distant and strange world. Care turns into taking care of possibilities, resting and staying to see the "world" only its outward appearance. Da-sein seeks distance solely to bring it near in its outward appearance. Da-sein lets itself be intrigued just by the outward appearance of the world, a kind of being in which it makes sure that it gets rid of itself as being-in-the-world, get rid of being with the nearest everyday things at hand. When curiosity has become free, it takes care to see not in order to understand what it sees, that is, to come to a being toward it, but only in order to see. It seeks novelty only to leap from it again to another novelty. The care of seeing is not concerned with comprehending and knowingly being in the truth, but with possibilities of abandoning itself to the world. Thus curiosity is characterized by a specific not-staying with what is nearest. Consequently, it also does not seek the leisure of reflective staying, but rather restlessness and excitement from continual novelty and changing encounters. In not-staying, curiosity makes sure of the constant possibility of distraction. Curiosity has nothing to do with the contemplation that wonders at being, thaumazein, it has no interest in wondering to the point of not understanding. Rather, it makes sure of knowing, but just in order to have known. The two factors constitutive for curiosity, not-staying in the surrounding world taken care of and distraction by new. possibilities, are the basis of the third essential characteristic of this phenomenon, which we call never dwelling anywhere. Curiosity is everywhere and nowhere. This mode of being-in-the-world reveals a new kind of being of everyday Da-sein, one in which it constantly uproots itself. Idle talk also controls the ways in which one may be curious. It says what one is to have read and seen. The being everywhere and nowhere of curiosity is entrusted to idle talk. These two everyday modes of being
173
162
Being and Time
I.v
of discourse and sight are not only objectively present side by side in their uprooting tendency, but one way of being drags the other with it. Curiosity, for which nothing is closed off, and idle talk, for which there is nothing that is not understood, provide themselves (that is, the Da-sein existing in this way) with the guarantee of a supposedly genuine "lively life." But with this supposition a third phenomenon shows itself as characterizing the disclosedness of everyday Da-sein. 37. Ambiguity
174
When in everyday being with one another, we encounter things that are accessible to everybody and about which everybody can say everything, we can soon no longer decide what is disclosed in genuine understanding and what is not. This ambiguity extends not only to the world, but likewise to being-with-one-another as such, even to the being of Dasein toward itself. Everything looks as if it were genuinely understood, grasped, and spoken whereas basically it is not, or it does not look that way, yet basically is. Ambiguity not only affects the way we avail ourselves of what is accessible for use and enjoyment, and the way we manage it, but it has already established itself in understanding as a potentiality for being, and in the way Da-sein projects itself and presents itself with possibilities. Not only does everyone know and talk about what is the case and what occurs, but everyone also already knows how to talk about what has to happen first, which is not yet the case, but "really" should be done. Everybody has always already guessed and felt beforehand what others also guess and feel. This being-on-the-track is based upon hearsay-whoever is "on the track" of something in a genuine way does not talk about it-and this is the most entangling way in which ambiguity presents po~ sibilities of Da-sein so that they will already be stifled in their power. Even supposing that what they guessed and felt should one day be actually translated into deeds, ambiguity has already seen to it that the interest for what has been realized will immediately die away. This interest persists only, after all, in a kind of curiosity and idle talk, only as long as there is the possibility of a noncommittal just-guessing-withsomeone. When one is on the track, and as long as one is on it, being "in on it" with someone precludes one's allegiance when what was guessed at is carried out. For then Da-sein is actually forced back upon itself. Idle talk and curiosity lose their power. And they do take their revenge. In the light of the actualization of what they also guessed, idle talk is quick to ascertain that they could have done that, too, for, after all, they had guessed it, too. In the end, idle talk is indignant that what it guessed and constantly demanded now actually happens. Mter all, the
I.v
Being and Time
163
opportunity to keep guessing is thus snatched away from it. Since, however, the time span when Da-sein becomes involved in the reticence of carrying something out, and even of genuinely getting stranded, is different from that of idle talk which "lives at a quicker pace," so that viewed publicly it is essentially slower, idle talk will have long since gone on to something else, to what is currently the very newest. That which had been surmised earlier, and has now been carried out, has come too late with regard to what is the very newest. In their ambiguity, curiosity and idle talk make sure that what is done in a genuine and new way is outdated as soon as it emerges before the public. Only then can it become free in its positive possibilities, when the idle talk covering it over has become ineffectual and the "common" interest has died out. The ambiguity of the way things have been interpreted publicly passes off talking about things ahead of time and curious guessing as what is really happening, and stamps carrying things out and taking action as something subsequent and of no importance. The understanding of Da-sein in the they thus constantly goes astray in its projects with regard to the genuine possibilities of being. Da-sein is always ambiguously "there," that is, in the public disclosedness of being-withone-another where the loudest idle talk and the most inventive curiosity keep the "business" going, where everything happens in an everyday way, and basically nothing happens at all. Ambiguity is always tossing to curiosity what it seeks, and it gives to idle talk the illusion of having everything decided in it. This kind of being of disclosedness of being-in-the-world, however, also dominates being-with-one-another as such. The other is initially "there" in terms of what they have heard about him, what they say and know about him. Idle talk initially intrudes itself into the midst of primordial being-with-one-another. Everyone keeps track of the other, initially and first of all, watching how he will behave, what he will say to something. Being-with-one-another in the they is not at all a self-contained, indifferent side-by-sideness, but a tense, ambiguous keeping track of each other, a secretive, reciprocal listening-in. Under the mask of the for-one-another, the against-one-another is at play. Here we must note that ambiguity does not first originate out of an explicit intention to deceive and distort, that it is not called forth by the individual Da-sein. It is already implied in being-with-one-another, as thrown being-with-one-another in a world. But publicly it is precisely concealed, and they will always protest the possibility that this interpretation of the kind of being of interpreting the they could be correct. It would be a misunderstanding if the explication of these phenomena were to seek to be confirmed by the approval of the they.
175
164
Being and Time
I.v
The phenomena of idle talk, curiosity, and ambiguity were set forth in such a way as to indicate that they are already interconnected in their being. The kind of being of this connection must now be grasped existentially and ontologically. The basic kind of being of everydayness is to be understood in the horizon of the structures of the being of Da-sein hitherto obtained.
38. Falling Prey and Thrownness
176
Idle talk, curiosity, and ambiguity characterize the way in which Da-sein is its "there," the disclosedness of being-in-the-world, in an everyday way. As existential determinations, these characteristics are -not objectively present in Da-sein; they constitute its being. In them and in the connectedness of their being, a basic kind of the being of everydayness reveals itself, which we call the entanglement of Da-sein. This term, which does not express any negative value judgment, means that Da-sein is initially and for the most part together with the "world" that it takes care of. This absorption in ... mostly has the character of being lost in the publicness of the they. As an authentic potentiality for being a self, Da-sein has initially always already fallen away from itself and fallen prey to the "world." Falling prey to the "world" means being absorbed in being-with-one-another as it is guided by idle talk, curiosity, and ambiguity. What we called the inauthenticity of Dasein 14 may now be defined more precisely through the interpretation of falling prey. But inauthentic and unauthentic by no means signify "not really," as if Da-sein utterly lost its being in this kind of being. Inauthenticity does not mean anything like no-longer-being-in-the-world, but rather it constitutes precisely a distinctive kind of being-in-the-world which is completely taken in by the world and the Mitda-sein of the others in the they. Not-being-its-self functions as a positive possibility of beings which are absorbed in a world, essentially taking care of that world. This nonbeing must be conceived as the kind of being of Da-sein nearest to it and in which it mostly maintains itself. Thus neither must the entanglement of Da-sein be interpreted as a "fall" from a purer and higher "primordial condition." Not only do we not have any experience of this ontically, but also no possibilities and guidelines of interpretation ontologically. As factical being-in-the-world, Da-sein, falling prey, has already fallen away from itself; and it has not fallen prey to some being which it first runs into in the course of its being, or perhaps does not, but it has fallen prey to the world which itself belongs to its being. Falling prey is an existential determination of Da-sein itself, and says nothing about Dasein as something objectively present, or about objectively present rela-
I.v
Being and Time
165
tions to beings from which it is "derived" or to beings with which it has subsequently gotten into a commercium. The ontological-existential structure of falling prey would also be misunderstood if we wanted to attribute to it the meaning of a bad and deplorable ontic quality which could perhaps be removed in the advanced stages of human culture. Neither in our first reference to being-in-the-world as the fundamental constitution of Da-sein nor in our characterization of its constitutive structural factors, did we go beyond an analysis of the constitution of this kind of being, and note its character as a phenomenon. It is true that the possible basic kinds of being-in, taking care and concern, were described. But we did not discuss the question of the everyday kind of being of these ways of being. It also became evident that being-in is quite different from a confrontation which merely observes and acts, that is, the concurrent objective presence of a subject and an object. Still, it must have seemed that being-in-the-world functions as a rigid framework within which the possible relations of Da-sein to its world occur, without the "framework" itself being touched upon in its kind of being. But this supposed "framework" itself belong to the kind of being of Da-sein. An existential mode of being-in-the-world is documented in the phenomenon of falling prey. Idle talk discloses to Da-sein a being toward its world, to others and to itself-a being in which these are understood, but in a mode of groundless floating. Curiosity discloses each and every thing, but in such a way that being-in is everywhere and nowhere. Ambiguity conceals nothing from the understanding of Da-sein, but only in order to suppress being-in-the-world in this uprooted everywhere and nowhere. With the ontological clarification of the kind of being of everyday being-in-the-world discernible in these phenomena, we first gain an existentially adequate determination of the fundamental constitution of Dasein. What structure does the "movement" of falling prey show? Idle talk and the public interpretedness contained in it are constituted in being-with-one-another. Idle talk is not objectively present for itself within the world, as a product detached from being-with-oneanother. Nor can it be volatilized to mean something "universal" which, since it essentially belongs to no one, "really" is nothing and "actually" only occurs in individual Da-sein that speaks. Idle talk is the kind of being of being-with-one-another itself, and does not first originate through certain conditions which influence Da-sein "from the outside." But when Da-sein itself presents itself with the possibility in idle talk and public interpretedness oflosing itself in the they, offalling prey to groundlessness, that means that Da-sein prepares for itself the constant temptation of falling prey. Being-in-the-world is in itself tempting.
177
166
178
Being and Time
l.v
Having already become a temptation for itself in this way, the way in which things have been publicly interpreted holds fast to Da-sein in its falling prey. Idle talk and ambiguity, having-seen-everything and having-understood-everything, develop the supposition that the disclosedness of Da-sein thus available and prevalent could guarantee to Da-sein the certainty, genuineness, and fullness of all the possibilities of its being. In the self-certainty and decisiveness of the they, it gets spread abroad increasingly that there is no need of authentic, attuned understanding. The supposition of the they that one is leading and sustaining a full and genuine "life" brings a tranquillization to Da-sein, for which everything is in "the best order" and for whom all doors are open. Entangled being-in-the-world, tempting itself, is at the same time tranquillizing. This tranquillization in inauthentic being, however, does not seduce one into stagnation and inactivity, but drives one to uninhibited "busyness." Being entangled in the "world" does not somehow come to rest. Tempting tranquillization aggravates entanglement. With special regard to the interpretation of Da-sein, the opinion may now arise that understanding the most foreign cultures and "synthesizing" them with our own may lead to the thorough and first genuine enlightenment of Da-sein about itself. Versatile curiosity and restlessly knowing it all masquerade as a universal understanding of Da-sein. But fundamentally it remains undetermined and unasked what is then really to be understood; nor has it been understood that understanding itself is a potentiality for being which must become free solely in one's ownmost Dasein. When Da-sein, tranquillized and "understanding" everything, thus compares itself with everything, it drifts toward an alienation in which its ownmost potentiality for being-in-the-world is concealed. Entangled being-in-the-world is not only tempting and tranquillizing, it is at the same time alienating. However, alienation cannot mean that Da-sein is factically torn away from itself. On the contrary, this alienation drives Da-sein into a kind of being intent upon the most exaggerated "self-dissection" which tries out all kinds of possibilities of interpretation, with the result that the "characterologies" and "typologies" which it points out are themselves too numerous to grasp. Yet this alienation, which closes off to Da-sein its authenticity and possibility, even if only that of genuinely getting stranded, still does not surrender it to beings which it itself is not, but forces it into its inauthenticity, into a possible kind of being of itself. The tempting and tranquillizing alienation of falling prey has its own kind of movement with the consequence that Da-sein gets entangled in itself. The phenomena pointed out of temptation, tranquillizing, alienation, and self-entangling (entanglement) characterize the specific kind
I.v
Being and Time
167
of being of falling prey. We call this kind of "movement" of Da-sein in its own being the plunge. Da-sein plunges out of itself into itself, into the groundlessness and nothingness of inauthentic everydayness. But this plunge remains concealed from it by the way things have been publicly interpreted so that it is interpreted as "getting ahead" and "living concretely." The kind of movement of plunging into and within the groundlessness of inauthentic being in the they constantly tears understanding away from projecting authentic possibilities, and into the tranquillized supposition of possessing or attaining everything. Since the understanding is thus constantly torn away from authenticity and into the they (although always with a sham of authenticity), the movement of falling prey is characterized by eddying. Not only does falling prey determine being-in-the-world existentially; at the same time the eddy reveals the character of throwing and movement of thrownness which can force itself upon Da-sein in its attunement. Not only is thrownness not a "finished fact," it is also not a self-contained fact. The facticity of Da-sein is such that Da-sein, as long as it is what it is, remains in the throw and is sucked into the eddy of the they's inauthenticity. Thrownness, in which facticity can be seen phenomenally, belongs to Da-sein, which is concerned in its being about that being. Da-sein exists factically. But now that falling prey has been exhibited, have we not set forth a phenomenon which directly speaks against the definition in which the formal idea of existence was indicated? Can Da-sein be conceived as a being whose being is concerned with potentiality for being if this being has lost itself precisely in its everydayness and "lives" away from itself in falling prey? Falling prey to the world is, however, phenomenal "evidence" against the existentiality of Da-sein only if Da-sein is posited as an isolated !-subject, as a self-point from which it moves away. Then the world is an object. Falling prey to the world is then reinterpreted ontologically as objective presence in the manner of innerworldly beings. However, ifwe hold on to the being ofDa-sein in the constitution indicated of being-in-the-world, it becomes evident that falling prey as the kind of being of this being-in rather represents the most elemental proof for the existentiality of Da-sein. In falling prey, nothing other than our potentiality for being-in-the-world is the issue, even if in the mode of inauthenticity. Da-sein can fall prey only because it is concerned with understanding, attuned being-in-the-world. On the other hand, authentic existence is nothing which hovers over entangled everydayness, but is existentially only a modified grasp of everydayness. Nor does the phenomenon of falling prey give something like a "night view" of Da-sein, a property occurring ontically which might serve
179
168
180
Being and Time
I.v
to round out the harmless aspect of this being. Falling prey reveals an essential, ontological structure of Da-sein itself. Far from determining its nocturnal side, it constitutes all of its days in their everydayness. Our existential, ontological interpretation thus does not make any ontic statement about the "corruption of human nature," not because the necessary evidence is lacking but because its problematic is prior to any statement about corruption or incorruption. Falling prey is an ontological concept of motion. Ontically, we have not decided whether human being is "drowned in sin," in the status corru.ptionis, or whether he walks in the status integritatis or finds himself in an interim stage, the status gratiae. But faith and "worldview," when they state such and such a thing and when they speak about Da-sein as being-in-the-world, must come back to the existential structures set forth, provided that their statements at the same time claim to be conceptually comprehensible. The leading question of this chapter pursued the being of the there. Its theme was the ontological constitution of the disclosedness essentially belonging to Da-sein. The being of disclosedness is constituted in attunement, understanding, and discourse. Its everyday mode of being is characterized by idle talk, curiosity, and ambiguity. These show the kind of movement of falling prey with the essential characteristics of temptation, tranquillization, alienation, and entanglement. But with this analysis the totality of the existential constitution of Da-sein has been laid bare in its main features and the phenomenal basis has been obtained for a "comprehensive" interpretation of the being of Da-sein as care.
VI Care as the Being of Da-sein
39. The QJJ.estion of the Primordial Totality of the Structural Whole of Da-sein Being-in-the-world is a structure that is primordial and constantly whole. In the previous chapters (division I, chapters 11-V) this structure was clarified phenomenally as a whole and, always on this basis, in its constitutive moments. The preview given at the beginning1 of the whole of the phenomenon has now lost the emptiness of its first general prefiguration. However, the phenomenal manifoldness of the constitution of the structural whole and its everyday kind of being can now easily distort the unified phenomenological view of the whole as such. But this view must be held in readiness more freely and more securely when we now ask the question toward which the preparatory fundamental analysis of Da-sein was striving in general: How is the totality of the structural whole that we pointed out to be determined existentially and ontologically? Da-sein exists factically. We are asking about the ontological unity of existentiality and facticity, namely, whether facticity belongs essentially to existentiality. On the basis of the attunement essentially belonging to it, Da-sein has a mode of being in which it is brought before itself and it is disclosed to itself in its throwness. But throwness is the mode of being of a being which always is itself its possibilities in such a way that it understands itself in them and from them (projects itself upon them). Being-in-the-world, to which being together with things at hand belongs just as primordially as being-with others, is always for the sake of itself. But the self is initially and for the most part inauthentic, the they-self.
169
181
170
182
Being and Time
I. VI
Being-in-the-world is always already entangled. The average everydayness of Da-sein can thus be determined as entangled-disclosed, thrown-projecting being-in-the-world which is concerned with its ownmost potentiality in its being together with the "world" and in being-with with the others. Can we succeed in grasping this structural whole of the everydayness of Da-sein in its totality? Can the being of Da-sein be delineated in a unified way so that in terms of it the essential equiprimordiality of the structures pointed out becomes intelligible, together with the existential possibilities of modification which belong to it? Is there a way to attain this being phenomenally on the basis of the present point of departure of the existential analytic? To put it negatively, it is beyond question that the totality of the structural whole is not to be reached phenomenally by means of cobbling together elements. This would require a blueprint. The being of Da-sein, which ontologically supports the structural whole as such, becomes accessible by completely looking through this whole at a primordially unified phenomenon which already lies in the whole in such a way that it is the ontological basis for every structural moment in its structural possibility. Thus a "comprehensive" interpretation cannot consist of a process of piecing together what we have hitherto gained. The question of Da-sein's existential character is essentially different from the question of the being of something objectively present. Everyday experience of the surrounding world, which is directed ontically and ontologically to innerworldly beings, cannot present Da-sein ontically and primordially for the ontological analysis. Similarly, our immanent perception of experiences is lacking an ontologically sufficient guideline. On the other hand, the being of Da-sein is not to be deduced from an idea of human being. Can we gather from our previous interpretation of Da-sein what antic-ontological access to itself it requires, from itself, as the sole appropriate one? An understanding of being belongs to the ontological structure of Da-sein. In existing, it is disclosed to itself in its being. Attunement and understanding constitute the kind of being of this disclosedness. Is there an understanding attunement in Da-sein in which it is disclosed to itself in a distinctive way? If the existential analytic of Da-sein is to keep a fundamental clarity as to its basic ontological function, it must search for one of the most farreaching and most primordial possibilities of disclosure which lie in Da-sein itself for mastering its preliminary task, that of setting forth the being of Da-sein. The kind of disclosure in which Da-sein brings itself before itself must be such that in it Da-sein becomes accessible to itself, so to speak, in a simplified way. Together with what has been disclosed to it, the structural whole of the being we seek must then come to light in an elemental way.
Being and Time
171
As a kind of attunement adequate for such methodical requirements, we shall take the phenomenon of Angst as the basis of analysis. The elaboration of this fundamental kind of attunement and the ontological characteristics of what is disclosed in it as such take their point of departure from the phenomenon of entanglement, and distinguish Angst from the related phenomenon of fear analyzed earlier. As a possibility of being of Da-sein, together with the Da-sein itself disclosed in it, Angst provides the phenomenal basis for explicitly grasping the primordial totality of being of Da-sein. Its being reveals itself as care. The ontological development of this fundamental existential phenomenon demands that we differentiate it from phenomena which at first might seem to be identified with care. Such phenomena are will, wish, predilection, and urge. Care cannot be derived from them because they are themselves founded upon it. Uke any ontological analysis, the ontological interpretation of Dasein as care, with whatever can be gained from the interpretation, is far removed from what is accessible to the pre-ontological understanding of being or even to our ontic acquaintance with beings. That the common understanding estranges what is known ontologically by referring it to that with which it is solely ontically acquainted, is not surprising. Nonetheless, even the ontic approach with which we have tried to interpret Da-sein ontologically as care might appear to be contrived in a farfetched and theoretical way; not to speak of the act of violence which one might discern in the exclusion of the traditional and cherished definition of human being. Thus we need a pre-ontological confirmation of the existential interpretation of Da-sein as care. It lies in demonstrating that as soon as Da-sein expressed anything about itself, it has already interpreted itself as care (cura), although only pre-ontologically. The analytic of Da-sein which penetrates to the phenomenon of care is to prepare the way for the fundamental, ontological problematic, the question of the meaning of being in general. In order to direct our view explicitly to this in the light of what we have gained, and go beyond the special task of an existential, a priori anthropology, the phenomena which are most intimately connected with the leading question of being must be grasped more precisely in hindsight. They are the modes of being explained hitherto: handiness and objective presence which determine innerworldly beings unlike Da-sein. Because the ontological problematic has hitherto understood being primarily in the sense of objective presence ("reality," "world"-actuality), while the being of Da-sein remained ontologically undetermined, we need to discuss the ontological connection of care, worldliness, handiness, and objective presence (reality). That leads to a more exact determination of the concept of reality in the context of a discussion of the epistemological questions oriented
183
172
184
Being and Time
I.VI
toward this idea which have been raised by realism and idealism. Beings are independently of the experience, cognition, and comprehension through which they are disclosed, discovered, and determined. But being "is" only in the understanding* of that being to whose being something like an understanding of being belongs. Thus being can be unconceptualized, but it is never completely uncomprehended. In ontological problematics, being and truth have been brought together since ancient times, if not even identified. This documents the necessary connection of being and understanding,t although perhaps concealed in its primordial grounds. Thus for an adequate preparation of the question of being, we need an ontological clarification of the phenomenon of truth. This will be accomplished initially on the basis of that which our interpretation hitherto has gained with the phenomena of disclosedness and discoveredness, interpretation and statement. The conclusion of the preparatory fundamental analysis of Dasein thus has as its theme the fundamental attunement of Angst as a distinctive disclosedness of Da-sein (section 40), the being of Da-sein as care (section 41 ), the confirmation of the existential interpretation of Dasein as care in terms of the pre-ontological self-interpretation of Dasein (section 42), Da-sein, worldliness, and reality (section 43), Da-sein, disclosedness, and truth (section 44). 40. The Fundamental Attunement of Angst as an Eminent Disclosedness of Da-sein
One possibility ofbeing ofDa-sein is to give ontic "information" about itself as a being. Such information is possible only in the disclosedness belonging to Da-sein which is based on attunement and understanding. To what extent is Angst a distinctive attunement? How is Da-sein brought before itself in it through its own being so that phenomenologically the being disclosed in Angst is defined as such in its being, or adequate preparations can be made for doing so? With the intention of penetrating to the being of the totality of the structural whole, we shall take our point of departure from the concrete analysis of entanglement carried out in the last chapter. The absorption of Da-sein in the they and in the "world" taken care of reveals something like a flight of Da-sein from itself as an authentic potentiality for being itself. This phenomenon of the flight of Da-sein from itself and
* But this understanding as hearing. But this never means that "being" is only "subjective," but being (qua the being of beings) qua difference "in" Da-sein as what is thrown by the (throw). t Thus: being and Da-sein.
I.VI
Being and Time
173
its authenticity seems, however, to be least appropriate to serve as a phenomenal foundation for the following inquiry. In this flight, Da-sein precisely does not bring itself before itself. In accordance with its ownmost trait of entanglement, this turning away leads away from Da-sein. But in investigating such phenomena, our inquiry must guard against conflating ontic-existentiell characteristics with ontological-existential interpretation, and must not overlook the positive, phenomenal foundations provided for this interpretation by such a characterization. It is true that existentielly the authenticity of being a self is closed off and repressed in entanglement, but this closing off is only the privation of a disclosedness which reveals itself phenomenally in the fact that the flight ofDa-sein is a flight from itself. That from which Da-sein flees is precisely what Da-sein comes up "behind." Only because Da-sein is ontologically and essentially brought before itself by the disclosedness belonging to it, can it flee from that from which it flees. Of course, in this entangled turning away, that from which it flees is not grasped, nor is it experienced in a turning toward it. But in turning away from it, it is "there," disclosed. On account of its character of being disclosed, this existentielly-ontic turning away makes it phenomenally possible to grasp existentially and ontologically what the flight is from. Within the ontic "away from" which lies in turning away, that from which Da-sein flees can be understood and conceptualized by "turning toward" in a way which is phenomenologically interpretive. Thus the orientation of our analysis toward the phenomenon of entanglement is not condemned in principle to be without any prospect of ontologically experiencing something about the Da-sein disclosed in that phenomenon. On the contrary, it is just here that our interpretation is the least likely to be surrendered to an artificial self-conception of Da-sein. It only carries the explication of what Da-sein itself discloses ontically. The possibility of penetrating to the being ofDa-sein by going along with it and pursuing it interpretatively in an attuned understanding increases, the more primordially that phenomenon is which functions methodologically as disclosive attunement. To say that Angst accomplishes something like this is only an assertion for now. We are not completely unprepared for the analysis of Ang-st. It is true that we are still in the dark as to how it is ontologically connected with fear. Obviously they are kindred phenomena. What tells us this is the fact that both phenomena remain mostly undifferentiated, and we designate as Ang-st what is really fear and call fear what has the character of Angst. We shall attempt to penetrate to the phenomenon of Ang-st step by step. The falling prey of Da-sein to the they and the "world" taken care of, we called a "flight" from itself. But not every shrinking back from ... ,
185
174
186
Being and Time
I. VI
not every turning away from ... is necessarily flight. Shrinking back from what fear discloses, from what is threatening, is founded upon fear and has the character of flight. Our interpretation of fear as attunement showed that what we fear is always a detrimental innerworldy being, approaching nearby from a definite region, which may remain absent. In falling prey, Da-sein turns away from itself. What it shrinks back from must have a threatening character; yet this being has the same kind of being as the one which shrinks back from it-it is Da-sein itself. What it shrinks back from cannot be grasped as something "fearsome"; because anything fearsome is always encountered as an innerworldly being. The only threat which can be "fearsome" and which is discovered in fear always comes from innerworldly beings. The turning away of falling prey is thus not a flight which is based on a fear of innerworldly beings. Any flight based on that kind of fear belongs still less to turning away, as turning away precisely turns toward innerworldly beings while absorbing itself in them. The turning away of falling prey is rather based on Angst which in turn first makes fear possible. In order to understand this talk about the entangled flight of Dasein from itself, we must recall that being-in-the-world is the basic constitution of Da-sein. That about which one has Angst is being-in-the-world as such. How is what An~t is anxious about phenomenally differentiated from what fear is afraid of? What An~t is about is not an innerworldly being. Thus it essentially cannot be relevant. The threat does not have the character of a definite detrimentality which concerns what is threatened with a definite regard to a particular factical potentiality for being. What Angst is about is completely indefinite. This indefiniteness not only leaves factically undecided which innerworldly being is threatening us, but also means that innerworldly beings in general are not "relevant." Nothing of that which is at hand and objectively present within the world, functions as what Angst is anxious about. The totality of relevance discovered within the world of things at hand and objectively present is completely without importance. It collapses. The world has the character of complete insignificance. In An~t we do not encounter this or that thing which, as threatening, could be relevant Thus neither does An~t "see" a definite "there" and "over here" from which what is threatening approaches. The fact that what is threatening is nowhere characterizes what Angst is about. An~t "does not know" what it is about which it is anxious. But "nowhere" does not mean nothing; rather, region in general lies therein, and disclosedness of the world in general for essentially spatial being-in. Therefore, what is threatening cannot approach from a definite direction within nearness, it is already "there"-and yet nowhere. It is so near that it is oppressive and stifles one's breath-and yet it is nowhere.
I. VI
Being and Time
175
In what Angst is about, the "it is nothing and nowhere" becomes manifest. The recalcitrance of the innerworldly nothing and nowhere means phenomenally that what Angst is about is the world as such. The utter insignificance which makes itself known in the nothing and nowhere does not signify the absence of world, but means that innerworldly beings in themselves are so completely unimportant that, on the basis of this insignificance of what is innerworldly, the world is all that obtrudes itself in its worldliness. What oppresses us is not this or that, nor is it everything objectively present together as a sum, but the possibility of things at hand in general, that is, the world itself. When Angst has quieted down, in our everyday way of talking we are accustomed to say "it was really nothing." This way of talking, indeed, gets at what it was ontically. Everyday discourse aims at taking care of things at hand and talking about them. That about which Angst is anxious is none of the innerworldly things at hand. But this "none of the things at hand," which is all that everyday, circumspect discourse understands, is not a total nothing. The nothing of handiness is based on the primordial "something,"* on the world. The world, however, ontologically belongs essentially to the being of Da-sein as being-in-the-world. So if what Angst is about exposes nothing, that is, the world as such, this means that that about which Angst is anxious is being-in-the-world itself.t Being anxious discloses, primordially and directly, the world as world. It is not the case that initially we deliberately look away from innerworldly beings and think only of the world about which Angst arises, but Angst as a mode of attunement first discloses the world as world. However, that does not mean that the worldliness of the world is conceptualized in Angst. Angst is not only Angst about ... , but is at the same time, as attunement, Angst for .... That for which Angst is anxious is not a definite kind of being and possibility of Da-sein. The threat itself is, after all, indefinite and thus cannot penetrate threateningly to this or that factically concrete potentiality of being. What Angst is anxious for is being-in-the-world itself. In Angst, the things at hand in the surrounding world sink away, and so do innerworldly beings in general. The "world" can offer nothing more, nor can the Mitda-sein of others. Thus Angst takes away from Dasein the possibility of understanding itself, falling prey, in terms of the "world" and the public way of being interpreted. It throws Da-sein back upon that for which it is anxious, its authentic potentiality-for-being-in-
* Thus nothing to do with "nihilism." Determining being as such; what is absolutely unhoped for and not to be perdured-what estranges. t
187
176
188
189
Being and Time
I.v1
the-world. Angst individuates Da-sein to its ownmost being-in-the-world which, as understanding, projects itself essentially upon possibilities. Thus along with that for which it is anxious, Angst discloses Da-sein as being-possible, and indeed as what can be individualized in individuation of its own accord. Angst reveals in Da-sein its being toward its ownmost potentiality of being, that is, being free for the freedom of choosing and grasping itself. Angst brings Da-sein before its being free for ... (propensio in), the authenticity of its being as possibility which it always already is. But at the same time, it is this being to which Da-sein as being-in-the-world is entrusted. That about which Angst is anxious reveals itself as that for which it is anxious: being-in-the-world. The identity of that about which and that for which one has Angst extends even to anxiousness itself. For as attunement, anxiousness is a fundamental mode of being-in-the-world. The existential identity of disclosing and what is disclosed so that in what is disclosed the world is disclosed as world, as being-in, individualized, pure, thrown potentiality for being, makes it clear that with the phenomenon of Angst a distinctive kind of attunement has become the theme of our interpretation. Angst individualizes and thus discloses Da-sein as "solus ipse." This existential "solipsism," however, is so far from transposing an isolated subject-thing into the harmless vacuum of a worldless occurrence that it brings Da-sein in an extreme sense precisely before its world as world, and thus itself before itself as being-in-the-world. Again, everyday discourse and the everyday interpretation of Dasein furnish the most unbiased evidence that Angst as a basic attunementis disclosive in this way. We said earlier that attunement reveals "how one is." In Angst one has an "uncanny" feeling. Here the peculiar indefiniteness of that which Da-sein finds itself involved in with Angst initially finds expression: the nothing and nowhere. But uncanniness means at the same time not-being-at-home. In our first phenomenal indication of the fundamental constitution of Da-sein and the clarification of the existential meaning of being-in in contradistinction to the categorial signification of "insideness," being-in was defined as dwelling with ... , being familiar with .... 2 This characteristic of being-in was then made more concretely visible through the everyday publicness of the they which brings tranquillized self-assurance, "being-at-home" with all its obviousness, into the average everydayness of Da-sein.' Angst, on the other hand, fetches Da-sein back out of its entangled absorption in the "world." Everyday familiarity collapses. Da-sein is individuated, but as being-in-the-world. Being-in enters the existential "mode" of not-being-athome. The talk about "uncanniness" means nothing other than this. Now, however, what falling prey, as flight, is fleeing from becomes phenomenally visible. It is not a flight from innerworldly beings, but
I. VI
Being and Time
177
precisely toward them as the beings among which taking care of things, lost in the they, can linger in tranquillized familiarity. Entangled flight into the being-at-home of publicness is flight from not-being-at-home, that is, from the uncanniness which lies in Da-sein as thrown, as being-inthe-world entrusted to itself in its being. This uncanniness constantly pursues Da-sein and threatens its everyday lostness in the they, although not explicitly. This threat can factically go along with complete security and self-sufficiency of the everyday way of taking care of things. An83t can arise in the most harmless situations. Nor does it have any need for darkness, in which things usually become uncanny to us more easily. In the dark there is emphatically "nothing" to see, although the world is still "there" more obt1USively. If we interpret the uncanniness of Da-sein existentially and ontologically as a threat which concerns Da-sein itself and which comes from Da-sein itself, we are not asserting that uncanniness has always already been understood in factical An83t in this sense. The everyday way in which Da-sein understands uncanniness is the entangled turning away which "phases out" not-being-at-home. The everydayness of this fleeing, however, shows phenomenally that Angst as a fundamental kind of attunement belongs to the essential constitution of Da-sein of being-inthe-world which, as an existential one, is never objectively present, but is itself always in the mode of factical Da-sein, that is, in the mode of an attunement. Tranquillized, familiar being-in-the-world is a mode of the uncanniness of Da-sein, not the other way around. Not-being-at-home* must be conceived existentially and ontologically as the more primordial phenomenon. And only because Angst always already latently detennines being-inthe-world, can being-in-the-world, as being together with the "world" taking care of things and attuned, be afraid. Fear is Angst which has fallen prey to the "world." It is inauthentic and concealed from itself as such. Factically, the mood of uncanniness remains for the most part existentielly uncomprehended. Moreover, with the dominance of falling prey and publicness, "real" An83t is rare. Often, Angst is "physiologically" conditioned. This fact is an ontological problem in its facticity, not only with regard to its antic causes and course of development. The physiological triggering of Angst is possible only because Da-sein is anxious in the very ground of its being. Still more rare than the existentiell fact of real Angst are the attempts to interpret this phenomenon in its fundamental, existential-
* (Ex-propriation).
190
178
191
Being and Time
I. VI
ontological constitution and function. The reasons for this lie partly in the general neglect of the existential analytic of Da-sein, particularly in the failure to recognize the phenomenon of attunement. 4 The factical rarity of the phenomenon of Ang.5t, however, cannot deprive it of its suitability for taking over a methodical function in principle for the existential analytic. On the contrary, the rarity of the phenomenon is an indication of the fact that Da-sein, which mostly remains concealed from itself in its authenticity on account of the public way of being interpreted of the they, can be disclosed in a primordial sense in its fundamental attunement. It is true that it is the nature of every kind of attunement to disclose complete being-in-the-world in all its constitutive factors (world, being-in, self). However, in Ang.5t there lies the possibility of a distinctive disclosure, since Angst individualizes. lbis individualizing fetches Da-sein back from its falling prey and reveals to it authenticity and inauthenticity as possibilities of its being. The fundamental possibilities of Da-sein, which is always my own,* show themselves in Ang.5t as they are, undistorted by innerworldly beings to which Da-sein, initially and for the most part, clings. To what extent has this existential interpretation of Ang.5t, gained a phenomenal basis for the answering the leading question of the being of the totality of the structural whole of Da-sein?
41. The Being of Da-sein as Care With the intention of grasping the totality of the structural whole ontologically, we must first ask whether the phenomenon of Ang.5t and what is disclosed in it are able to give the whole of Da-sein in a way that is phenomenally equiprimordial, so that our search for totality can be fulfilled in this givenness. The total content of what lies in it can be enumerated: As attunement, being anxious is a way of being-in-the-world; that about which we have Ang.5t is thrown being-in-the-world; that for which we have Ang.5t is our potentiality-for-being-in-the-world. The complete phenomenon of Ang.5t thus shows Da-sein as factical, existing beingin-the-world. The fundamental, ontological characteristics of this being are existentiality, facticity, and falling prey. These existential determinations are not pieces belonging to something composite, one of which might sometimes be missing, but a primordial content is woven in them which constitutes the totality of the structural whole that we are seeking. In the unity of the determinations of being of Da-sein that we have mentioned, this being becomes ontologically comprehensible as such. How is this unity itself to be characterized?
* Not egotistical, but to be taken over in thrownness.
I.VI
Being and Time
179
Da-sein is a being which is concerned in its being about that being. The "is concerned about ... " has become clearer in the constitution of being of understanding as self-projective being toward its ownmost potentiality-for-being. This potentiality is that for the sake of which any Da-sein is as it is. Da-sein has always already compared itself, in its being, with a possibility of itself. Being free for its ownmost potentiality-forbeing, and thus for the possibility of authenticity and inauthenticity, shows itself in a primordial, elemental concretion in Ang.5t. But ontologically, being toward one's ownmost potentiality-for-being means that Da-sein is always already ahead of itself in its being. Da-sein is always already "beyond itself," not as a way of behaving toward beings which it is not, but as being toward the potentiality-for-being which it itself is. This structure of being of the essential "being concerned about" we formulate as the being-ahead-ofitself of Da-sein. But this structure concerns the whole of the constitution of Da-sein. Being-ahead-of-itself does not mean anything like an isolated tendency in a worldless "subject," but characterizes being-in-the-world. But to being-in-theworld belongs the fact that it is entrusted to itself, that it is always already thrown into a world. The fact that Da-sein is entrusted to itself shows itself primordially and concretely in Anglt. More completely formulated, beingahead-ot:itself means being-ahead-()fU.selfin-already-being-in-a-world. As soon as this essentially unitary structure is seen phenomenally, what we worked out earlier in the analysis of worldliness also becomes clearer. There we found that the referential totality of significance (which is constitutive for worldliness) is "anchored" in a for-the-sake-ot:which. The fact that this referential totality, of the manifold relations of the in-order-to, is bound up with that which Da-sein is concerned about, does not signify that an objectively present "world" of objects is welded together with a subject. Rather, it is the phenomenal expression of the fact that the constitution of Da-sein, whose wholeness is now delineated explicitly as being-ahead-of-itself-in-alreadybeing-in ... is primordially a whole. Expressed differently: existing is always factical. Existentiality is essentially detennined by facticity. Furthermore, the factical existing of Da-sein is not only in general and indifferently a thrown potentiality-for-being-in-the-world, but is always already also absorbed in the world taken care of. In this entangled being-together-with, fleeing from uncanniness (which mostly remains covered over by latent Ang.5t because the publicness of the they suppresses everything unfamiliar) announces itself, whether it does so explicitly or not, and whether it is understood or not. In being-ahead-ofoneself-already-being-in-the-world, entangled being-together-with innerworldly things at hand taken care of lies essentially included. The formal existential totality of the ontological structural whole of Da-sein must thus be formulated in the following structure: The being of
192
180
193
Being and Time
I.VI
Da-sein means being-ahead-of-oneself-already-in (the world) as beingtogether-with (innerworldly beings encountered). This being fills in the significance of the term care, which is used in a purely ontological and existential way. Any ontically intended tendency of being, such as worry or carefreeness, is ruled out. Since being-in-the-world is essentially care, being-together-with things at hand could be taken in our previous analyses as taking care of them, being with the Mitda-sein of others encountered within the world as concern. Being-together-with is taking care of things, because as a mode of being-in it is determined by its fundamental structure, care. Care not only characterizes existentiality, abstracted from facticity and falling prey, but encompasses the unity of these determinations of being. Nor does care mean primarily and exclusively an isolated attitude of the ego toward itself. The expression "care for oneself," following the analogy of taking care and concern, would be a tautology. Care cannot mean a special attitude toward the self, because the self is already characterized ontologically as being-ahead-of-itself; but in this determination the other two structural moments of care, already-being-in ... and being-together-with, are also posited. In being-ahead-of-oneself as the being toward one's ownmost potentiality-of-being lies the existential and ontological condition of the possibility of being free for authentic existentiell possibilities. It is the potentiality-for-being for the sake of which Da-sein always is as it factically is. But since this being toward the potentiality-for-being is itself determined by freedom, Da-sein can also be related to its possibilities unwillingly, it can be inauthentic, and it is so factically initially and for the most part. The authentic for-the-sake-of-which remains ungrasped, the project of one's potentiality-of-being is left to the disposal of the they. Thus in being-ahead-of-itself, the "self' actually means the self in the sense of the they-self. Even in inauthenticity, Da-sein remains essentially ahead-of-itself, just as the entangled fleeing of Da-sein from itself still shows the constitution of being of a being that is concerned about its being. As a primordial structural totality, care lies "before" every factical "attitude" and "position" of Da-sein, that is, it is always already in them as an existential a priori. Thus this phenomenon by no means expresses a priority of "practical" over theoretical behavior. When we determine something objectively present by merely looking at it, this has the character of care just as much as a "political action," or resting and having a good time. "Theory" and "praxis" are possibilities of being for a being whose being must be defined as care. The phenomenon of care in its totality is essentially something that cannot be split up; thus any attempts to derive it from special acts or
I. VI
Being and Time
181
drives such as willing and wishing or urge and predilection, or of constructing it out of them, will be unsuccessful. Willing and wishing are necessarily rooted ontologically in Da-sein as care, and are not simply ontologically undifferentiated experiences which occur in a "stream" that is completely indeterminate as to the meaning of its being. This is no less true for predilection and urge. They, too, are based upon care insofar as they are purely demonstrable in Da-sein in general. This does not exclude the fact that urge and predilection are ontologically constitutive even for beings which are only "alive." The basic ontological constitution of "living," however, is a problem in its own right and can be developed only reductively and privatively in terms of the ontology of Da-sein Care is ontologically "prior" to the phenomena we mentioned, which can, of course, always be adequately "described" within certain limits without the complete ontological horizon needing to be visible or even known as such. For the present fundamental ontological study, which neither aspires to a thematically complete ontology of Da-sein nor even to a concrete anthropology, it must suffice to suggest how these phenomena are existentially based in care. The potentiality-for-being for the sake of which Da-sein is, has itself the mode of being of being-in-the-world. Accordingly, the relation to innerworldly beings lies in it ontologically. Even if only privatively, care is always taking care of things and concern. In willing, a being that is understood, that is, projected upon its possibility, is grasped as something to be taken care of or to be brought to its being through concern. For this reason, something willed always belongs to willing, something which has already been determined in terms of a for the-sake-of-which. If willing is to be possible ontologically, the following factors are constitutive for it: the previous disclosedness of the for-the-sake-of-which in general {beingahead-of-oneself), the disclosedness of what can be taken care of (world as the wherein of already-being), and the understanding self-projection of Da-sein upon a potentiality-for-being toward a possibility of the being "willed." The underlying totality of care shows through in the phenomenon of willing. As something factical, the understanding self-projection of Da-sein is always already together with a discovered world. From this world it takes its possibilities, initially in accordance with the interpretedness of the they. This interpretation has from the outset restricted the possible options of choice to the scope of what is familiar, attainable, feasible, to what is correct and proper. The levelling down of the possibilities of Dasein to what is initially available in an everyday way at the same time results in a phasing out of the possible as such. The average everydayness of taking care of things becomes blind to possibility and gets tranquil-
194
195
182
196
Being and Time
I. VI
lized with what is merely "real." This tranquillization not only does not rule out a high degree of busyness in taking care of things, it arouses it. It is not the case that positive, new possibilities are then willed, but what is available is "tactically" changed in such a way that there is an illusion of something happening. All the same, under the leadership of the they, this tranquillized "willing" does not signify that being toward one's potentiality-for-being has been extinguished, but only that it has been modified. Being toward possibilities then shows itself for the most part as mere wishing. In the wish, Da-sein projects its being toward possibilities which not only remain ungrasped in taking care of things, but whose fulfillment is not even thought about and expected. On the contrary, the predominance of being-ahead-of-itself in the mode of mere wishing brings with it a lack of understanding of factical possibilities. Being-in-the-world whose world is primarily projected as a wish-world has lost itself utterly in what is available, but in such a way that in the light of what is wished for, what is available (all the things at hand) is never enough. Wishing is an existential modification of understanding self-projection which, having fallen prey to thrownness, solely hankers after possibilities. This hankering after closes off possibilities; what is "there" in such wishful hankering becomes the "real world." Ontologically, wishing presupposes care. In hankering, being-in-the-world-already-among ... has priority. Being-ahead-of-itself-in-already-being-in is modified accordingly. Entangled hankering reveals the predilection of Da-sein to be "lived" by the world in which it actually is. Predilection shows the character of being out for something. Being-ahead-of-itself has gotten lost in a just-alwaysalready-among. The "toward" of predilection lets itself be attracted by what predilection hankers after. When Da-sein, so to speak, sinks down into predilection, a predilection is not just objectively present, but the complete structure of care is modified. Blinded, it puts all possibilities in the services of the predilection. On the other hand, the urge "to live" is a "toward" which brings its own drive along with it. It is "toward at any cost." Urge seeks to crowd out other possibilities. Here, too, being-ahead-of-oneself is inauthentic if one is invaded by an urge coming from the very thing that is urging one on. The urge can outrun one's actual attunement and understanding. But then Da-sein is not-and never is-a "mere urge" to which other relations of dominating and leading are sometimes added, but as a modification of complete being-in-the-world, it is always already care. In pure urge, care has not yet become free, although it first makes it ontologically possible for Da-sein to be urged on by itself. On the other hand, in predilection care is always already bound. Predilection and urge are possibilities rooted in the thrownness of Da-sein. The urge
I. VI
Being and Timl!
183
"to live" is not to be destroyed; the predilection to be "lived" by the world is not to be eradicated. But because and only because they are ontologically based in care, both are to be modified ontically and existentielly by care as something authentic. The expression "care" means an existential and basic ontological phenomenon which is yet is not simple in its structure. This ontologically elemental totality of the care structure cannot be reduced to an ontic "primal element," just as being certainly cannot be "explained" in terms of beings. Finally, we shall see that the idea of being in general is no more "simple" than the being of Da-sein. The characterization of care as "being-ahead-of-itself-in-already-being-in"-as being-together-with-makes it clear that this phenomenon, too, is yet structurally articulated in itself. But is that not a phenomenal indication that the ontological question must be pursued still further until we can set forth a still more primordial phenomenon which ontologically supports the unity and totality of the structural manifold of care? Before we follow up this question, we need to appropriate in hindsight and more precisely what has been interpreted up to now with the intention of seeing the fundamental ontological question of the meaning of being in general. But first we must show that what is ontologically "new" in this interpretation is ontically rather old. The explication of the being of Da-sein as care does not force Da-sein under a contrived idea, but brings us existentially nearer to the concept of what has already been disclosed ontically and existentielly.
42. Confirmation of the Existential Interpretation of Da-sein as Care in Terms of the Pre-ontological Self-interpretation of Da-sein In the foregoing interpretations, which finally led to exposing care as the being of Da-sein, the most important thing was to arrive at the appropriate ontological foundations of the being which we ourselves actually are and which we call "human being." For this purpose, it was necessary from the outset to change the direction of our analysis from the approach presented by the traditional defmition of human being, which is an approach ontologically unclarified and fundamentally questionable. In comparison with this definition, the existential and ontological interpretation might seem strange, especially if "care" is understood just ontically as "worry" and "troubles." Accordingly, we shall cite a document that is pre-ontological in character, even though its demonstrative power is "only historical." Let us bear in mind, however, that in this document Da-sein expresses itself about itself "primordially," unaffected by any theoretical interpretation and without aiming to propose any. Furthermore, let us observe that the being of Da-sein is characterized by historicality, though
197
184
Being and Time
I. VI
this must first be demonstrated ontologically . .lfDa-sein is "historical" in the basis of its being, a statement that comes from its history and goes back to it and that, moreover, is prior to any scientific knowledge takes on a special importance which, however, is never purely ontological. The understanding of being which lies in Da-sein itself expresses itself pre-ontologically. What is cited in the following document is to make clear the fact that our existential interpretation is not a mere fabrication, but as an ontological "construction" it is well grounded and has been sketched out beforehand in elemental ways. The following self-interpretation ofDa-sein as "care" is preserved in an old fable: 5
198
Cura cum fluvium transiret, videt cretosum lutum sustulitque cogitabunda atque coepit fingere. dum deliberat quid iam fecisset. Jovis interventi. rogat eum Cura ut det spiritum, et facile impetrat. cui cum vellet Cura nomen ex sese ipsa imponere, Jovis prohibuit suumque nomen ei dandum esse dictitat. dum Cura etjovis disceptant, Tellus surrexit simul suumque nomen esse volt cui corpus praebuerit suum. sumpserunt Saturnum iudicem, is sic aecus iudicat; "tu Jovis quia spiritum dedisti, in morte spiritum, tuque Tellus, quia dedisti corpus, corpus recipito, Cura enim quia prima finxit, teneat quamdiu vixerit. sed quae nunc de nomine eius vobis controversia est, homo vocetur, quia videtur esse factus ex humo." Once when "care" was crossing a river, she saw some clay; she thoughtfully took a piece and began to shape it. While she was thinking about what she had made, jupiter came by. "Care" asked him to give it spirit, and this he gladly granted. But when she wanted her name to be bestowed upon it, jupiter forbade this and demanded that it be given his name instead. While "Care" and Jupiter were arguing, Earth (Tellus) arose, and desired that her name be conferred upon the creature, since she had offered it part of her body. They asked Saturn to be the judge. And Saturn gave them the following decision, which seemed to be just: "Since you, Jupiter, have given its spirit, you should receive that spirit at death; and since you, Earth, have given its body, you shall receive its body. But since 'Care' first shaped this creature, she shall possess it as long as it lives. And because there is a dispute among you as to its name, let it be called 'homo,' for it is made out of humus (earth)." This pre-ontological document becomes especially significant not only in that "care" is here seen as that to which human Da-sein belongs
I.VI
Being and Time
185
"for its lifetime," but also because this priority of "care" emerges in connection with the familiar interpretation of human being as a compound of body (earth) and spirit. Cura primafinxit. This being has the "origin" of its being in care. Cura teneat, quamdiu vixerit: this being is not released from its origin, but retained, dominated by it as long as this being "is in the world." "Being-in-the-world" has the character of being of "care." It does not gets its name (homo) with regard to its being, but in relation to that of which it consists (humus). The decision as to wherein the "primordial, being of this creature is to be seen is left to Saturn, "time."6 The pre-ontological characterization of the essence of human being expressed in this fable thus has envisaged from the very beginning the mode of being which rules its temporal sojourn in the world. The history of the signification of the ontic concept of "cura" permits us to see still further fundamental structures of Da-sein. Burdach7 calls our attention to an ambiguity of the term "cura," according to which it means not only "anxious effort," but also "carefulness," "dedication." Thus Seneca writes in his last letter (Ep. 124): "Of the four existing natures (tree, animal, human being, God), the last two, which alone are endowed with reason, are distinguished in that God is immortal, human being mortal. The good of the One, namely of God, is fulfilled by its nature; but that of the other, human being, is fulfilled by care (cura): uniu.s bonum natura perjicit, dei sciliet, alteriu.s cura, hominis." The peifectio of human being-becoming what one can be in being free for one's ownmost possibilities (project)-is an "accomplishment" of "care." But, equiprimordially, care determines the fundamental mode of this being according to which it is delivered over ( thrownness) to the world taken care of. The "ambiguity" of "care" means a single basic constitution in its essentially twofold structure of thrown project. As compared with the ontic interpretation, the existential and ontological interpretation is not only a theoretical and antic generalization. That would only signify that ontically all the human being's behavior is "full of care" and guided by his "dedication" to something. The "generalization" is an a priori-ontological one. It does not mean ontic qualities that constantly keep emerging, but a constitution of being which always already underlies. This constitution first makes it ontologically possible that this being can be addressed ontically as cura. The existential condition of the possibility of "the cares of life" and "dedication" must be conceived in a primordial, that is, ontological sense as care. The transcendental "universality" of the phenomenon of care and all fundamental existentials has, on the other hand, that broad scope through which the basis is given on which every antic interpretation of Da-sein with a worldview moves, whether it understands Da-sein as "the cares of life" and need, or in an opposite manner.
199
200
186
Being and Time
I. VI
The "emptiness" and "generality" of the existential structures which obtrude themselves ontically have their own ontological definiteness and fullness. The whole of the constitution of Da-sein itself is not simple in its unity, but shows a structural articulation which is expressed in the existential concept of care. Our ontological interpretation of Da-sein has brought the preontological self-interpretation of this being as "care" to the existential concept of care. The analytic of Da-sein does not aim, however, at an ontological basis for anthropology; it has a fundamental, ontological goal. This is the purpose that has inexplicitly determined the course of our considerations, our choice of phenomena, and the limits to which our analysis may penetrate. With regard to our leading question of the meaning of being and its development, our inquiry must now, however, explicitly secure what has been gained so far. But something like this cannot be attained by an external synopsis of what has been discussed. Rather, what could only be roughly indicated at the beginning of the existential analytic must be sharpened to a more penetrating understanding of the problem with the help ofwhat we have gained. 43. Da-sein, Worldliness, and Reality
201
The question of the meaning of being is possible at all only if something like an understanding of being is. An understanding of being belongs to the kind of being of the being which we call Da-sein. The more appropriately and primordially we have succeeded in explicating this being, the surer we are to attain our goal in the further course of working out the problem of fundamental ontology. While following the tasks of a preparatory existential analytic of Da-sein, we developed an interpretation of understanding, meaning, and interpretation. Our analysis of the disclosedness of Da-sein showed furthermore that, with that disclosedness, Da-sein is revealed equiprimordially in accordance with its fundamental constitution of being-inthe-world with regard to the world, being-in, and the self. Furthermore, in the factical disclosedness of world, innerworldly beings are also discovered. This means that the being of these beings is always already understood in a certain way, although not appropriately conceived ontologically. The pre-ontological understanding of being comprehends all beings which are essentially disclosed in Da-sein, but the understanding of being itself has not yet gotten articulated according to the various modes of being. At the same time, our interpretation of understanding showed that, in accordance with its entangled kind of being, it has initially and for the most part transposed itself into an understanding of "world."
I.VI
Being and Time
187
Even when it is not only a matter of ontic experience, but of ontological understanding, the interpretation of being initially orients itself toward the being of innerworldly beings.* Here the being of things initially at hand is passed over and beings are first conceived as a context of things (res) objectively present. Being acquires the meaning of reality. 8 Substantiality becomes the basic characteristic of being. Corresponding to this diversion in the understanding of being, even the ontological understanding of Da-sein moves into the horizon of this concept of being. Like other beings, Da-sein is also objectively present as real. Thus being in general acquires the meaning of reality.t Accordingly, the concept of reality has a peculiar priority in the ontological problematic. This priority diverts the path to a genuine existential analytic of Da-sein, it also diverts our view of the being of innerworldly things initially at hand. Finally, it forces the problematic of being in general into a direction which lies off course. The other modes of being are defined negatively and privatively with regard to reality. Therefore, not only the analytic of Da-sein, but the development of the question of the meaning of being in general must be wrested from a one-sided orientation toward being in the sense of reality. We must demonstrate that reality is not only one kind of being among others, but stands ontologically in a definite foundational context with Da-sein, world, and handiness. To demonstrate this, we must discuss in principle the problem of reality, its conditions and limitations. Under the heading "the problem of reality" various questions are clustered: (1) whether the beings which are supposedly "transcendent to consciousness" are at all; (2) whether this reality of the "external world" can be sufficiently proved; (3) to what extent this being, if it is real, is to be known in its being-in-itself; (4) what the meaning of this being, reality, signifies in general. The following discussion of the problem of reality treats three things with regard to the question of fundamental ontology: (a) reality as a problem of being and the demonstrability of the "external world," (b) reality as an ontological problem, (c) reality and care.
(a) Reality as a Problem of Being and the Demonstrability of the "External World." Of these questions enumerated about reality, the one which comes first is the ontological question of what reality signifies in general. However, as long as a pure ontological problematic and methodology was lacking, this question (if it was asked explicitly at all) was necessarily
* To differientiate: physis, idea, ousia, substantia, res, objectivity, objective presence. t Reality as actuality and realitas as factuality [Sachheit]. The middle position of Kant's concept of "objective reality."
202
188
203
Being and Time
l.vt
confounded with a discussion of the "problem of the external world"; for the analysis of reality is possible only on the basis of an appropriate access to what is real. But intuitive cognition has always been viewed as the way to grasp what is real. Intuitive cognition "is" as a kind of behavior of the soul, of consciousness. Since the character of the in-itself and independence belongs to reality, the question of the possible independence "from consciousness" of what is real, or of the real possible transcendence of consciousness in the "sphere" of what is real, is coupled with the question of the meaning of reality. The possibility of an adequate ontological analysis of reality depends on how far that .from which there is independence, what is to be transcended, is itself clarified with regard to its being. Only in this way can the kind of being that belongs to transcendence be ontologically grasped. And, finally, the primary kind of access to what is real must be secured by deciding the question whether cognition can take over this function at all. These inquiries which take precedence over any possible ontological question about reality have been carried out in the foregoing existential analytic. Accordingly, cognition is a founded mode of access to what is real. The real is essentially accessible only as innerworldly beings. Every access to such beings is ontologically based on the fundamental constitution of Da-sein, on being-in-the-world. This has the primordial constitution of being of care (being-ahead-of-itself-already-being-in-a-world-as being together with innerworldly beings). The question of whether there is a world at all and whether its being can be demonstrated, makes no sense at all if it is raised by Da-sein as being-in-the-world-and who else should ask it? Moreover, it is encumbered with an ambiguity. World as the wherein of being-in, and "world" as innerworldly beings, that in which one is absorbed in taking care of things, are confused or else not distinguished at all. But world is essentially disclosed with the being of Da-sein; "world" is always already discovered with the disclosedness of world, too. Of course, innerworldly beings in the sense of what is real, as merely objectively present, can still remain covered over. However, what is real, too, is discoverable only on the basis of a world already disclosed. And only on this basis can what is real still remain concealed. One asks the question about the "reality" of the "external world" without previously clarifying the phenomenon of world as such. Factically, the problem of the external world is constantly oriented toward innerworldly beings (things and objects). Thus these discussions drift into a problematic which ontologically can hardly be disentangled. The entanglement of these questions and the confusion of what one would like to demonstrate with what is demonstrated and with what guides the demonstration, is shown in Kant's "Refutation of Idealism. "9
I. VI
Being and Time
189
Kant calls it "a scandal of philosophy and human reason in general" 10 that there is still no cogent proof for "the existence of things outside us" which will do away with any skepticism. He himself proposes such a proof as the foundation of his "theorem" that "the mere consciousness of my own existence which, however, is empirically determined, proves the existence of objects outside of me in space." 11 First we must explicitly note that Kant uses the term "existence" [Dasein] to designate the kind of being which we have called "objective presence" in our present inquiry. "Consciousness of my existence" means for Kant consciousness of my objective presence in the sense of Descartes. The term "existence" means both the objective presence of consciousness and the objective presence of things. The proof for the "existence of things outside of me" is supported by the fact that change and persistence belong equiprimordially to the nature of time. My objective presence, that is, the objective presence given in the inner sense of a manifold of representations, is change objectively present. But the definiteness of time presupposes something objectively present which persists. This, however, cannot be "in us," "because precisely my existence in time can first be determined by this persisting thing." 12 With the objectively present change "in me" which is posited empirically, an objectively present thing which persists "outside of me" is also posited. This persisting thing is the condition of the possibility of the objective presence of change "in me." The experience of the being-in-time of representations equiprimordially posits changing things "in me" and persisting things "outside of me." Of course, this proof is not a causal inference and, accordingly, not burdened with the prejudices of such proof. Kant gives, so to speak, an "ontological proof' in terms of the idea of temporal beings. At first, it appears as if Kant has abandoned the Cartesian position of a prediscovered isolated subject. But that is only illusion. The fact that Kant requires any proof at all for the "existence of things outside of me" already shows that he takes the subject, the "in me," as the starting point for this problematic. The proof itself is then carried out by departing from the empirically given change "in me." For only "in me" is "time" experienced, and time carries the burden of the proof. It provides the foundation for leaping into the "outside of me" in the course of the proof. Moreover, Kant emphasizes the fact that "the problematic kind of [Idealism] which ... only alleges our inability to prove an existence outside of our own by immediate experience is reasonable and in accordance with a fundamental, philosophical way of thinking; namely, before a sufficient proof has been found, never to permit a decisive judgment." 13 But even if the on tic priority of the isolated subject and of inner experience were given up, ontologically the position of Descartes would,
204
190
205
Being and Time
I.VJ
after all, be retained. What Kant proves-if we admit that his proof and its basis are correct at all-is that beings that are changing and beings that are permanent are necessarily present together. But ordering two objectively present things on the same level does not as yet mean that subject and object are objectively present together. And even if this were proved, what is ontologically decisive would still remain covered over: the fundamental constitution of the "subject," of Da-sein, as beingin-the-world. The objective presence together of the physical and the psychical is ontically and ontologically completely different from the phenomenon of being-inthe-world. Kant presupposes the difference and the connection of the "in me" and "outside of me" factically with justification, but in the sense of the tendency of his proof without justification. It has not been proved that whatever is decided about the objective presence together of what changes and what persists when one takes time as a guideline also applies to the connection between the "in me" and the "outside of me." But if the whole of the difference and connection of the "inside" and "outside" presupposed in the proof were seen, if what is presupposed with this presupposition were ontologically understood, the possibility for believing that a proof of the "existence of things outside of me" was still lacking and necessary would collapse. The "scandal of philosophy" does not consist in the fact that this proof is still lacking up to now, but in the fact that such prooft are expected and attempted again and again. Such expectations, intentions, and demands grow out of an ontologically insufficient way of positing what it is from which, independently and "outside" of which, a "world" is to be proven as objectively present. It is not that the proofs are insufficient, but the kind of being of the being that does the proving and requests proofs is not definite enough. For this reason the illusion can arise that with this demonstration of the necessary objective presence together of two objectively present things something is proved or even demonstrable about Da-sein as being-in-the-world. Correctly understood, Dasein defies such proofs, because it always already is in its being what the later proofs first deem necessary to demonstrate for it. If one wanted to conclude from the impossibility of the proofs for the objective presence of things outside of us that this is thus "merely to be accepted on faith," 14 the distortion of the problem would not be overcome. The preconceived opinion would persist that basically and ideally a proof must be possible. The inappropriate way of approaching the problem is still endorsed when one confmes oneself to a "faith in the reality of the external world," even if this faith is explicitly "acknowledged." Although one is not offering a stringent proof, one is still in principle demanding a proof and trying to satisfy that demand. 15
I. VI
Being and Time
191
Even if one wanted to fall back on the fact that the subject must presuppose, and indeed always already does unconsciously presuppose, the fact that the "external world" is objectively present, one would still be starting with the construct of an isolated subject. The phenomenon of being-in-the-world would no more be met with than it would be by demonstrating that the physical and the psychical are objectively present together. With such presuppositions, Da-sein always already comes "too late," because, in that it carries out this presupposition as a being (and otherwise this would not be possible); as a being, it is always already in a world. "Earlier" than any presupposition that Da-sein makes, or any of its ways of behavior, there is the "a priori" of its constitution of being in the mode of being of care. Faith in the reality of the "external world," whether justified or not, proves this reality for it, whether sufficiently or insufficiently, it presupposes it, whether explicitly or not, such attempts that have not mastered their own ground with complete transparency, presuppose a subject which is initially worldless, or not certain of its world, and which basically must first make certain of a world. Here being-in-the-world is from the very beginning geared to interpreting, opining, being certain, and having faith, a kind of behavior which is in itself always already a founded mode of being-in-the-world. The "problem of reality" in the sense of the question of whether an external world is objectively present or demonstrable, turns out to be an impossible one, not because its consequences led to inextricable impasses, but because the very being which serves as its theme repudiates such a line of questioning, so to speak. It is not a matter of proving that and how an "external world" is objectively present, but of demonstrating why Da-sein as being-in-the-world has the tendency of "initially" burying the "external world" in nullity "epistemologically" in order first to prove it. The reason for this lies in the falling prey of Da-sein and in the diversion motivated therein of the primary understanding of being to the being of objective presence. If the line of questioning in this ontological orientation is "critical," it fmds a mere "inner thing" as what is objectively present and alone certain. After the primordial phenomenon of being-in-the-world has been shattered, the isolated subject is all that remains, and becomes the basis for being joined together with a "world." The multiplicity of attempts at a solution of the "problem of reality" developed through the various kinds of realism and idealism, and in the positions which mediate between them, cannot be discussed in this inquiry at any great length. Just as certainly as a core of genuine understanding is to be found in all of them, it would be just as wrong if one wanted to achieve a tenable solution of the problem
206
207
192
208
Being and Time
I.VJ
by calculating what is actually correct. Rather, what is needed is the basic insight that the various epistemological directions do not so much go off the track epistemologically, but, that, because they neglect the existential analytic of Da-sein in general, they do not even attain the basis for a phenomenally secured problematic. Nor is this basis to be attained by subsequent phenomenological improvements of the concept of the subject and consciousness.* Such a procedure would not guarantee that the inappropriate line of questioning would not, after all, remain. With Da-sein as being-in-the-world, innerworldly beings have already been disclosed. This existential and ontological statement seems to agree with the thesis of realism that the external world is objectively present in a real way. Since the objective presence of innerworldly beings is not denied in this existential statement, it agrees in its result, so to speak, doxographically, with the thesis of realism. But it is distinguished in principle from all realism in that realism believes that the reality of the "world" needs proof, and at the same time is capable of proof. Both views are directly negated in the existential statement. But what completely separates it from realism is the lack of ontological comprehension in realism. Mter all, it tries to explain reality ontically by real connections of interaction between real things. As opposed to realism, idealism, no matter how contraryt and untenable it might be, has a fundamental priority, if it does not misunderstand itself as "psychological" idealism. If idealism emphasizes the fact that being and reality are only "in consciousness," this expresses the understanding that being cannot be explained by beings. But to the extent that it remains unclarified that understanding of being occurs here and what this understanding of being means ontologically, how it is possible, and that it belongs to the constitution of being of Da-sein, t idealism constructs the interpretation of reality in a vacuum. The fact that being cannot be explained by beings, and reality is only possible in the understanding of being, does not absolve us from asking about the being of consciousness, of . the res cogitans itself. If the idealist thesis is to be followed consistently, the ontological analysis of consciousness is prescribed as an inevitable prior task. Only because being is "in consciousness," that is, intelligible in Da-sein, can Da-sein also understand and conceptualize characteristics of being such as independence, "in itself," reality in general. Only for that reason are "independent" beings accessible to circumspection as encountered in the world.
* Leap into Da-sein. t
Namely, to existential and ontological experience.
t And Da-sein belongs to the essence of being as such.
I. VI
Being and Time
193
If the term idealism amounts to an understanding of the fact that being is never explicable* by beings, but is always already the "transcendental" for every being, then the sole correct possibility of a philosophical problematic lies in idealism. Then Aristotle was no less of an idealist than Kant. If idealism means the reduction of all beings to a subject or a consciousness which are only distinguished by the fact that they remain undetermined in their being and are characterized at best negatively as "unthinglike," then this idealism is methodologically no less naive than the grossest realism. It is still possible that one may give the problematic of reality priority over any orientation in terms of "standpoints" by maintaining the thesis that every subject is what it is only for an object and vice versa. But with this formal position the terms of the correlation and the correlation itself remain undetermined ontologically. But at bottom the whole correlation is necessarily thought as "somehow" existent, thus thought with regard to a definite idea of being. Of course, if the existential and ontological basis is secured beforehand with the evidence of being-in-theworld, this correlation can be known subsequently as a formalized, ontologically indifferent relation. Our discussion of the unexpressed presuppositions of efforts to solve the problem of reality in ways which are merely "epistemological," shows that this problem must be taken back into the existential analytic of Da-sein as an ontological problem. 16 (b) Reality as an Ontological Problem. If the term realityt refers to the being ofinnerworldly beings (res) objectively present (and nothing else is understood by this), that means for the analysis of this mode of being that innerworldly beings are ontologically to be comprehended only when the phenomenon of innerworldliness has been clarified. But innerworldliness is based on the phenomenon of world, which in tum belongs to the fundamental constitution of Da-sein as an essential structural factor of beingin-the-world. Again, being-in-the-world is ontologically bound up with the structural totality of the being of Da-sein which we characterized as care. But thus we have characterized the foundations and the horizons that must be clarified if an analysis of reality is to be possible. In this connection the character of the in-itself first becomes ontologically intelligible. By taking our orientation toward this context of problems, we have interpreted the being of innerworldly beings in our earlier analyses. 16 To be sure, within certain limits a phenomenological characterization of the reality of what is real can already be given without an
* Ontological difference. t
Not reality as factuality [Sachheit).
209
194
210
Being and Time
I. VI
explicit existential and ontological basis. Dilthey tried this in the treatise which we mentioned above. What is real is experienced in impulse and will. Reality is resistance, more exactly the character of resistance. The analytic elaboration of the phenomenon of resistance is what is positive in Dilthey's treatise, and is the best concrete substantiation of his idea of a "descriptive and analytic psychology." But he is kept from correctly working out the analysis of the phenomenon of resistance by the epistemological problematic of reality. The "principle of phenomenality" does not let Dilthey get to an ontological interpretation of the being of consciousness. "The will and its inhibition emerge within the same consciousness. "18 What kind of being belongs to "emerging"? What is the meaning of the being of the "within"? What relation ofbeing does consciousness bear to what is real itself? All this needs an ontological determination. That this was not done can be fmally explained by that fact that Dilthey left "life" standing in such a way that it is ontologically undifferentiated, and one cannot go back "behind" life. However, an ontological interpretation of Da-sein does not mean an antic return to some other being. The fact that Dilthey was epistemologically refuted cannot prevent us from making fruitful use of what is positive in his analyses, which is precisely what has not been understood in these refutations. Thus recently Scheler took up Dilthey's interpretation of reality. 19 He champions a "voluntative theory of Da-sein." Here Da-sein is understood in the Kantian sense as objective presence. The "being of objects is given immediately only in relation to drive and will." Scheler, like Dilthey, not only emphasizes the fact that reality is never primarily given in thinking and grasping, above all he also refers to the fact that knowledge itself is, again, not judgment and that knowing is a "relation of being." Fundamentally, what we have already said about the ontological indefiniteness of Dilthey's foundations is valid for this theory too. Nor can the fundamental ontological analysis of "life" be inserted afterwards as a support. It bears and conditions the analysis of reality, the full explication of resistance and its phenomenal presuppositions. We encounter resistance in not-getting-through, as an obstacle to wanting-to-getthrough. But with this willing, something must already have been disclosed, something which drive and will are out to get. The antic indefiniteness of what they are out to get must not, however, be overlooked ontologically or, for that matter, be understood as if it were nothing. Being out to get ... , which comes up against resistance and must "come up against it," is itself already together with a totality of relevance. But the discoveredness of that totality is grounded in the disclosedness of the referential totality of significance. The experience of resistance, that is, the dis-
I.VI
Being and Time
195
covery of resistance in striving, is ontologically possible only on the basis of the disclosedness of world. Resistance characterizes the being of innerworldly beings. Experiences of resistance factically determine only the extent and direction in which beings encountered within the world are discovered. Their sum does not first introduce the disclosure of world, but presupposes it. The "against" and the "counter to" are supported in their ontological possibility by disclosed being-in-the-world. Nor is resistance experienced in a drive or a will "emerging" in its own right. These tum out to be modifications of care. Only beings with this kind of being are able to run up against something resistant in the world. Thus, if reality is defined by resistance, we must consider two things. On the one hand, we have only gotten at one characteristic of reality among others, and on the other hand the already disclosed world is necessarily presupposed for resistance. Resistance characterizes the "external world" in the sense of innerworldly beings, but never in the sense of world. "Consciousness of reality" is itself a way of being-in-the-world. Every "problematic of the external world" necessarily goes back to this basic existential phenomenon. If the "cogito sum" is to serve as the point of departure for the existential analytic, we need not only to tum it around, but we need a new ontological and phenomenal confirmation of its content. Then the first statement is "sum," in the sense of l-am-in-a-world. As such a being, "I am" in the possibility of being toward various modes of behavior (cogitationes) as ways of being together with innerworldly beings. In contrast, Descartes says that cogitationes are indeed objectively present and an ego is also objectively present as a worldless res cogitans. (c) Reality and Care. As an ontological term, reality is related to innerworldly beings. If it serves to designate this kind of being in general, then handiness and objective presence function as modes of reality. But if one lets this word keep its traditional* meaning, it means being in the sense of the pure, objective presence of things. But not all objective presence is the objective presence of things. "Nature," which "surrounds" us, is indeed an innerworldly being, but it shows neither the kind of being of handiness nor of objective presence as "natural things." However one interprets this being of "nature," all modes of being of innerworldly beings are ontologically founded in the worldliness of the world, and thus in the phenomenon of being-in-the-world. From this there arises the insight that neither does reality have priority within the modes of being of innerworldly beings nor can this mode of being even characterize something like world and Da-sein in an ontologically adequate way. *Prevalent today.
211
196
212
Being and Time
I.VI
Reality is referred back to the phenomenon of care in the order of ontological foundational contexts and possible categorial and existential demonstration. The fact that reality is ontologically grounded in the being of Da-sein cannot mean that something real can only be what it is in itself when and as long as Da-sein exists. However, only as long as Da-sein is, that is, as long as there is the on tic possibility of an understanding of being, "is there" [gibt es] being. If Da-sein does not exist, then there "is" no "independence" either, nor "is" there an "in itself." Such matters are then neither comprehensible nor incomprehensible. Innerworldly beings, too, can neither be discovered, nor can they lie in concealment. Then it can neither be said that beings are, nor that they are not. Now, as long as there is an understanding of being and thus an understanding of objective presence, we can say that then beings will still continue to be. As we have noted, being (not beings) is dependent upon the understanding of being, that is, reality (not the real) is dependent upon care. This dependency protects our further analytic of Da-sein from an uncritical interpretation of Da-sein constantly obtruding itself-an interpretation that follows the guideline of the idea of reality. Only the orientation toward existentiality as interpreted in an ontologically positive way guarantees that in the factical course of the analysis of "consciousness," of "life," some meaning of reality is not made basic, even if it is one that has not been further differentiated. The fact that beings having the kind of being of Da-sein cannot be comprehended in terms of reality and substantiality has been expressed by the thesis that the substance of human being is existence. Interpreting existentiality as care and distinguishing it from reality do not, however, signal the end of the existential analytic, but only lets the maze of problems in the question of being and its possible modes, and the meaning of such modifications, emerge more sharply. Only if an understanding of being is, are beings accessible as beings; only if beings of the kind of being of Da-sein are, is an understanding of being possible as beings [Seinsverstiindnis als Seiendes]. 44. Da-sein, Disclosedness, and Truth
213
From time immemorial, philosophy has associated* truth with being. The first discovery of the being of beings by Parmenides "identifies" being with the perceptive understanding of being: to gar auto noein estin te kai einai. 20 Aristotle emphasizes in his sketch of the history of the discovery of archai 21 the fact that the philosophers before him were led
* Physis is intrinsic.ally aletheia, since kryptesthai philei.
I. VI
Being and Time
197
by "the things themselves" to question further: auto to pragma hiidopoiesen autois kai sunenagka.se zetein. 22 He also characterizes the same fact with the words: anagkazomenos d'akolouthein tois phainomenois/~ he (Pannenides) was compelled to follow what showed itself in itself. In another passage he says: hup' autes tes aletheia.s anagkazomenoi, 24 compelled by "truth" itself, they inquired. Aristotle designates this inquiry as philosophein peri tes aletheia.s,25 philosophizing" about the "truth" or even as apophainesthia peri tes aletheia.s, 26 as demonstrating something and letting it be seen with regard to the "truth" and in the scope of "truth." Philosophy itself is defined as episteme tis tes aletheia.s/7 the science of "truth." But at the same time it is characterized as an episteme, he theiJrei to on he on/8 as the science that considers beings as beings, that is, with regard to their being. What does "inquiring into 'truth'" mean here, the science of "truth"? Is "truth" made thematic in this inquiry in the sense of a theory of knowledge or of judgment? Obviously not, for "truth" means the same thing as "matter" ["Sache"], "what shows itself." But then what does the expression "truth" mean if it can be used as a tenn for "beings" and "being"? But if truth rightfully has a primordial connection with being, the phenomenon of truth moves into the scope* of the problematic of fundamental ontology. But must not this phenomenon have been encountered already within our preparatory fundamental analysis, the analytic of Da-sein? What antic-ontological connection does "truth" have with Dasein and with its antic characteristic which we call the understanding of being? Can the reason why being necessarily goes together with truth and vice versa be pointed out in tenns of this understanding? These questions cannot be avoided. Because being actually "goes together" with truth, the phenomenon of truth has already been one of the themes of our earlier analysis, although not explicitly under this name. Now we must explicitly delimit the phenomenon of truth giving precision to the problem of being and fixing the problems contained therein. In doing this, we shall not simply summarize what we have said previously. The investigation takes a new point of departure.t Our analysis starts from (a) the traditional concept of truth and attempts to lay bare its ontological foundations. In tenns of these foundations the primordial phenomenon of truth becomes visible. On the basis of this, (b) the derivativeness of the traditional concept of truth can be indicated. Our investigation makes clear that the question of the kind of being of truth also necessarily belongs to the question of the *Not only here, but into the middle. This is the real place to begin the leap into Da-sein.
t
214
198
Being and Time
I.VI
"essence" of truth. Together with this we must (c) clarify the ontological meaning of saying that "there is truth," and also clarify the kind of necessity with which "we must presuppose" that there "is" ["gibt"] truth.
(a) The Traditional Concept of Truth and Its Ontological Foundations. Three theses characterize the traditional interpretation of the essence of truth and the way it is supposed to have been first defined: 1. The "locus" of truth is the proposition (judgment). 2. The essence of truth lies in the "agreement" of the judgment with its object. 3. Aristotle, the father of logic, attributed truth to judgment as its primordial locus, he also started the definition of truth as "agreement."
215
A history of the concept of truth, which could only be presented on the basis of a history of ontology, is not intended here. A few characteristic references to familiar matters may serve to introduce our analytical discussions. Aristotle says: pathemata tes psyches ton pragmaton homoiomata/9 the "experiences" of the soul, the noemata ("representations"}, are correspondences [Angleichungen] to things. This assertion, which is by no means presented as an explicit essential definition of truth, also became the occasion for the development of the later formulation of the essence of truth as adaequatio intellectus et rei. Thomas Aquinas, 30 who refers this definition to Avicenna (who adopted it, in turn, from Isaak Israeli's Book of Definitions [tenth century]}, also uses the terms correspondentia (correspondence) and convenentia (coming together) for adaequatio (agreement). The neo-Kantian epistemology of the nineteenth century frequently characterized this definition of truth as an expression of a methodologically retarded naive realism, and declared it to be incommensurable with any line of questioning which had gone through Kant's "Copernican revolution." But Kant, too, retained this concept of truth, so much so that he did not even start to discuss it. This has been overlooked, though Brentano had already called our attention to it. "The old and celebrated question with which it was supposed that one might drive the logicians into a corner is this: 'what is truth?' The explanation of the name of truth-namely, that it is the agreement of knowledge with its object-will be here granted and presupposed. "! 1 "If truth consists in the agreement of knowledge with its object, then this object must be distinguished from others; for knowledge is false if it does not agree with the object to which it is related, even if it should contain something which might well be valid for other objects." 32
I. VI
Being and Time
199
And in the introduction to the transcendental dialectic Kant says: "Truth and illusion are not in the object so far as it is intuited, but in the judgment about it so far as it is thought."" Of course the characterization of truth as "agreement," adaqua· tio, homoiosis, is very general and empty. But it will still have some justification if it can hold its own without prejudice to any of the most varied interpretations this distinctive predicate "knowledge" will support. We now ask about the foundations of this "relation." What is tacitly co-posited in the relational totality-adequatio intellectus et rei? What ontological character does what is co-posited itself have? What does the term "agreement" mean in general? The agreement of something with something has the formal character of the relation of something to something. Every agreement, and thus "truth" as well, is a relation. But not every relation is an agreement. A sign points to what is shown. Showing is a relation, but not an agreement between the sign and what is shown. But obviously every agreement does not mean something like the convenentia laid down in the definition of truth. The number 6 agrees with 16 minus 10. These numbers agree; they are equal with regard to the question of how much. Equality is one kind of agreement. Structurally, something like a "with regard to" belongs to it. What is that with regard to which what is related in the adequatio agrees? In clarifying the "truth relation" we must notice also what is peculiar to the terms of this relation. With regard to what do intellectus and res agree? In their kind of being and essential content do they supply anything at all with regard to which they can agree? If it is impossible for intellectus and res to be equal because they are not of the same species, are they then perhaps similar? But knowledge is supposed to "give" the matter just as it is. "Agreement has the relational character of ·~ust-as." In what way is this relation possible, as a relation between intellectus and res? From these questions it becomes clear that it is not sufficient for the clarification of the structure of truth simply to presuppose this relational totality, but we must rather ask about the context of being which supports this totality as such. Do we need for this purpose to unfold the "epistemological" problematic with regard to the subject-object relation, or can our analysis be limited to an interpretation of the "immanent consciousness of truth," thus remaining "within the sphere" of the subject? According to general opinion, what is true is knowledge. But knowledge is judging. In judging, one must distinguish between judging as a real psychical procedure and what is judged as an ideal content. It is of the latter that we say it is "true." In contrast, the real psychical procedure is either objectively present or not. Accordingly, the ideal content of judgment stands in a relation of agreement. Thus this relation pertains to a connection between an
216
200
217
Being and Time
I. VI
ideal content of judgment and the real thing as that about which one judges. Is agreement real or ideal in its kind of being, or neither of the two? Haw is the relation between an ideal being and a real thing objectively present to be grasped ontologicaUy? It does, after all, subsist and it: subsists in facti cal judging not only between the content of judgment and the real object, but rather at the same time between the ideal content and the real act ofjudgment, and here obviously even more "intimately"? Or are we not allowed to ask about the ontological meaning of the relation between the real and the ideal (methexis) ? The relation is supposed to subsist. What does subsistence mean ontologically? Why should this not be a legitimate question? Is it a matter of chance that this problem has not made any headway for more than two thousand years? Does the distortion of the question already lie in the beginning, in the ontologically unclarified separation of the real and the ideal? And is it not the separation of the real act and the ideal content thoroughly illegitimate with regard to the "actual" judging of what is judged? Is not the reality of knowing and judging sundered into two kinds of being, two "levels" that can never be pieced together so as to get at the kind of being of knowing? Is not psychologism correct in rejecting this separation even if it neither clarifies ontologically the kind of being that belongs to the thinking of what is thought, nor is even familiar with it as a problem? If we go back to the separation between the act ofjudgment and its content, we shall not further our discussion of the kind of being that belongs to the adequatio, but only make plain the indispensability of clarifying the kind of being of knowing itself. The analysis necessary for this must attempt to bring to view the phenomenon of the truth that characterizes knowledge. When does truth become phenomenally explicit in knowing itself? When knowing proves to be true. By demonstrating itself, it is assured of its truth. Thus the relation of agreement must become visible in the phenomenal connection of demonstration. Let someone make the true statement with his back to the wall: "The picture on the wall is hanging crookedly." This statement demonstrates itself when the speaker turns around and perceives the picture hanging crookedly on the wall. What is proved in this demonstration? What is the meaning of confirming this statement? Do we perhaps ascertain an agreement between "knowledge" or "what is known" with the thing on the wall? Yes and no, depending on whether our interpretation of the expression "what is known" is phenomenally adequate. To what is the speaker related when he judges without perceiving the picture, but "only representing" it? Possibly to "representations"? Certainly not, if representation is supposed to mean here representing as a psychical event. Nor is he related to representations in the sense of what is
I. VI
Being and Time
201
represented, if we mean by that a "picture" of the real thing on the wall. Rather, the statement that is "only representing" is in accordance with its owrunost meaning related to the real picture on the wall. What one has in mind is the real picture, and nothing else. Any interpretation that inserts something else here as what one has in mind in a statement that merely represents falsifies the phenomenal state of affairs about which a statement is made. Making statements is a being toward the existing thing itself. And what is demonstrated by perception? Nothing other than the fact that it is this very being that one has in mind in one's statement. This is further confirmed by the fact that this is pointed out by the being in which the statement is made-which is being toward what is put forward in the statement. What is to be confirmed is that it discovers the being toward which it is. What is demonstrated is the discovering being of the assertion. Here knowing remains related solely to the being itself in the act of demonstration. It is in this being, so to speak, that the confirmation takes place. The being that one has in mind shows itself os it is in itself, that is, it shows that it, in its selfsameness, is just as it is discovered or pointed out in the assertion. Representations are not compared, neither among themselves nor in relation to the real thing. What is to be demonstrated is not an agreement of knowing with its object, still less something psychical with something physical, but neither is it an agreement between the "contents of consciousness" among themselves. What is to be demonstrated is solely the being-discovered of the being itself, that being in the how of its being discovered. 'Ibis is confirmed by the fact that what is stated (that is, the being itself) shows itself os the very same thing. Confirmation means the being's showing itself in its selfsameness. 54 Confirmation is accomplished on the basis of the being's showing itself. That is possible only in that the knowing that asserts and is confirmed is itself a discovering being toward real beings in its ontological meaning. To say that a statement is true means that it discovers the beings in themselves. It asserts, it shows, it lets beings "be seen" (apophansis) in their discoveredness. The being true (truth) of the statement must be understood as discovering. Thus, truth by no means has the structure of an agreement between knowing and the object in the sense of a correspondence of one being (subject) to another (object). Being-true as discovering is in tum ontologically possible only on the basis of being-in-the-world. This phenomenon, in which we recognized a basic constitution of Da-sein, is the foundation of the primordial phenomenon of truth. This is now to be followed up in a more penetrating manner.
(b) The Primordial Phenomenon of Truth and the Derivative Character of the Traditional Concept of Truth. Being-true (truth) means to-be-discovering.
218
219
202
220
Being and Time
I. VI
But is that not a highly arbitrary definition of truth? With such drastic definitions of the concept we might succeed in eliminating the idea of agreement from the concept of truth. Must we not pay for this dubious gain by letting the "good" old tradition fall into nothingness? However, this seemingly arbitrary definition contains only the necessary interpretation of what the oldest tradition of ancient philosophy primordially surmised and even understood in a pre-phenomenological way. The beingtrue of the logos as apophansis is aletheuein in the manner of apophainesthai: to let beings be seen in their unconcealment (discoveredness ), taking them out of their concealment. The aletheia which is equated by Aristotle with pragma and phainomena in the passages cited above signifies the "things themselves," that which shows itself, beings in the how of their discoveredness. And is it a coincidence that in one of the fragments of Heraclitusg5-the oldest fragments of philosophical doctrine which explicitly treat the logos-the phenomenon of truth in the sense of discoveredness (unconcealment), as we have set it forth, shows through? Those who do not understand are contrasted with the logos and with him that speaks the logos and understands it. The logos is phrazfm hokOs echei, it tells how beings behave. In contrast, to those who do not understand, what they do remains in concealment, lanthanei; they forget (epilanthanontai), that is, for them it sinks back into concealment. Thus unconcealment, aletheia, belongs to the logos. To translate this word as "truth," and especially to define this expression conceptually in theoretical ways, is to cover over the meaning of what the Greeks posited at the basis-as "self-evident" and as pre-philosophical-of the tenninological use of aletheia. In citing such evidence we must guard against uninhibited wordmysticism. Still, in the end it is the business of philosophy to protect the power of the most elemental words in which Da-sein expresses itself from being flattened by the common understanding to the point of unintelligibility, which in its turn functions as a source for illusory problems. What we presented earlier,~ so to speak in a dogmatic interpretation, about logos and aletheia has now gained its phenomenal demonstration. The "definition" of truth presented does not shake off the tradition, but is rather its primordial appropriation; and this will be even more the case if we succeed in demonstrating whether and how the theory had to arrive at the idea of agreement on the basis of the primordial phenomenon of truth. Nor is the "definition" of truth as disclosedness and disclosing a mere explanation of words, but grows out of the analysis of the relations of Da-sein which we are initially accustomed to call "true." Being true as discovering is a manner of being of Da-sein. What makes this discovering itself possible must necessarily be called "true" in
I.VI
Being and Time
203
a still more primordial sense; The existential and ontological foundations of discovering itselffirst show the most primordial phenomenon of truth. Discovering is a way of being of being-in-the-world. Taking care of things, whether in circumspection or in looking in a leisurely way, discovers innerworldly beings. The latter become what is discovered. They are "true" in a secondary sense. Primarily "true," that is, discovering, is Da-sein. Truth in the secondary sense does not mean to be discovering (discovery), but to be discovered (discoveredness). But we showed in our earlier analysis of the worldliness of the world and innerworldly beings that the discoveredness of innerworldly beings is grounded in the disclosedness of the world. However, disclosedness is the basic character of Da-sein in accordance with which it is its there. Disclosedness is constituted by attunement, understanding, and discourse, and pertains equiprimordially to the world, being-in, and the self. The structure of care as being-ahead-tif-itself-already-being-in-aworld-as being together with innerworldly beings contains the disclosedness of Da-sein. With and through it is discoveredness; thus only with the disclosedness of Da-sein is the most primordial phenomenon of truth attained. What was shown earlier with regard to the existential constitution of the there'7 and in relation to the everyday being of the there'8 pertains to nothing other than the most primordial phenomenon of truth. In that Da-sein essentially is its disclosedness, and, as disclosed, discloses and discovers, it is essentially "true." Da-sein is "in the truth." This statement has an ontological meaning. It does not mean that Dasein is ontically always or at times introduced to "all truth," but that the disclosedness of its owmnost being belongs to its existential constitution. By considering what we have gained so far, the full existential meaning of the statement "Da-sein is in the truth" can be summarized by the following considerations: 1. Disclosedness in general belongs essentially to the constitution of being of Da-sein. It comprehends the totality of the structure of being that has become explicit through the phenomenon of care. To care belongs not only being-in-the-world, but being together with innerworldly beings. The being of Da-sein and its disclosedness belong equiprimordially to the discoveredness of innerworldly beings. 2. Thrownness belongs to the constitution of being of Da-sein as a constituent of its disclosedness. In thrownness the fact is revealed that Da-sein, as my Da-sein and this Da-sein, is always already in a definite world and together with a definite range of definite innerworldly beings. Disclosedness is essentially factical. 3. Project belongs to the constitution of being of Da-sein: disclosive being toward its own potentiality-of-being. Da-sein can, as an understanding being, understand itself in terms of the "world" and the others, or
221
204
222
Being and Time
I. VI
else in terms of its ownmost potentiality-of-being. This possibility means that Da-sein discloses itself to itself in and as its ownmost potentiality-ofbeing. This authentic disclosedness shows the phenomenon of the most primordial truth in the mode of authenticity. The most primordial and authentic disclosedness in which Da-sein can be as a potentiality-of-being is the truth of existence. Only in the context of an analysis of the authenticity of Da-sein does it receive its existential, ontological definiteness. 4. Falling prey belongs to the constitution of being of Da-sein. Initially and ·for the most part, Da-sein is lost in its "world." As a project upon possibilities of being, understanding has diverted itself there. Absorbing oneself in the they signifies that it is dominated by public interpretedness. What is discovered and disclosed stands in the mode in which it has been disguised and closed off by idle talk, curiosity, and ambiguity. Being toward beings has not been extinguished but uprooted. Beings are not completely concealed, but precisely discovered, and at the same time distorted. They show themselves, but in the mode of illusion. Similarly, what was previously discovered sinks back again into disguise and concealment. Becawe it essentially falls prey to the world, Dasein is in "untruth" in accordance with its constitution of being. This term is used here ontologically, as is the expression "falling prey." Any ontically negative "value judgment" is to be avoided in its existential and analytical use. Being closed off and covered over belong to the facticity of Da-sein. The full existential and ontological meaning of the statement "Da-sein is in the truth" also says equiprimordially that "Da-sein is in untruth." But only insofar as Da-sein is disclosed, is it also closed off, and insofar as innerworldly beings are always already discovered with Dasein, are such beings covered over (hidden) or disguised as possible innerworldly beings to be encountered. Thus, Da-sein must explicitly and essentially appropriate what has also already been discovered, defend it against illusion and distortion, and ensure itself of its discoveredness again and again. All new discovery takes place not on the basis of complete concealment, but takes its point of departure from discoveredness in the mode of illusion. Beings look like ... , that is, they are in a way already discovered, and yet they are still distorted. Truth, (discoveredness) must always first be wrested from beings. Beings are tom from concealment. The actual factical discoveredness is, so to speak, always a kind of robbery. Is it a matter of chance that the Greeks express themselves about the essence of truth with a privative expression (a-litheia)? Does not a primordial understanding of its own being make itself known in such an expression-the understanding (even if it is only pre-ontological) that being-in-untruth constitutes an essential determination of being-in-the-world?
I. VI
Being and Time
205
The fact that the goddess of truth who leads Parmenides places him before two paths, that of discovering and that of concealment, signifies nothing other than the fact that Da-sein is always already both in the truth and the untruth. The path of discovering is gained only in krinein logo, in distinguishing between them understandingly and in deciding for the one rather than the other.~ 9 The existential and ontological condition for the fact that being-inthe-world is determined by "truth" and "untruth" lies in the constitution of being of Da-sein* which we characterized as throum project. It is a constituent of the structure of care. The existential and ontological interpretation of the phenomenon of truth has shown: (1) Truth in the most primordial sense is the disclosedness of Da-sein to which belongs the discoveredness of innerworldly beings. (2) Da-sein is equiprimordially in truth and untruth. Within the horizon of the traditional interpretation of the phenomenon of truth our insight into these statements will not be completet until it can be shown: (1) Understood as agreement, truth has its origin in disclosedness by way of a definite modification. (2) The kind of being of disclosedness itself leads to the fact that initially its derivative modification comes into view and guides the theoretical explication of the structure of truth. Statement and its structure, the apophantical "as," are based on interpretation and its structure, the hermeneutical "as," and furthermore on understanding, on the disclosedness of Da-sein. But here truth is regarded as an eminent determination of statements thus derived. Accordingly, the roots of the truth of statement reach back to the disclosedness of understanding.4° But now the phenomenon of agreement must be shown explicitly in its derivation above and beyond this indication of the origin of the truth of statements. Being together with innerworldly beings, and taking care of them, discovers. But to the disclosedness of Da-sein discourse essentially belongs. 41 Da-sein expresses itself; itself-as a being toward beings that discovers. And it expresses itself as such about beings that have been discovered in statements. Statements communicate beings in the how of their discoveredness. Da-sein, perceiving the communication, brings itself to a discovering being toward the beings discussed. The statements made are made about something, and in what they are about they contain the discoveredness of beings. This discoveredness is preserved in what is expressed. What is expressed becomes, so to speak, an inner-
* Of Da-sein and thus of standing·in [Irutandigkeit]. t
It will never be complete.
223
224
206
225
Being and Time
LVI
worldly thing at hand that can be taken up and spoken about further. Because the discoveredness has been presenred, what is expressed (what is thus at hand) has in itself a relation to any beings about which it is a statement. Discoveredness is always a discoveredness of .... Even when Da-sein repeats what has been said, it comes into a being toward the very beings that have been discussed. But it is and believes itself exempt from a primordial repetition of the act of discovering. Da-sein does not need to bring itself to beings in " original" experience, but it nevertheless remains in a being toward these beings. Discoveredness is appropriated to a large extent not by one's own discovering, but by hearsay of what has been said. Absorption in what has been said belongs to the kind of being of the they. What is expressed as such takes over the being toward these beings discovered in the statement. But if they are to be explicitly appropriated with regard to their discoveredness, this means that the statement is to be demonstrated as one that discovers. But the statement expressed is something at hand, in such a way that, preserving discoveredness, it has in itself a relation to the beings discovered. To demonstrate that it is something that discovers, means to demonstrate how the statement that presetves discoveredness is related to these beings. The statement is something at hand. The beings to which it has a discovering relation are innerworldly things at hand or objectively present. Thus the relation presents itself as something objectively present. But this relation lies in the fact that the discoveredness presenred in the statement is always a discoveredness of .... The judgment "contains something valid for the objects" (Kant). But the relation itself now acquires the character of objective presence by getting switched over to a relation between objectively present things. Discoveredness of ... becomes the objectively present conformity of something objectively present, of the statement expressed, to something objectively present, the being spoken about. And if this conformity is then viewed only as the relation between objectively present things, that is, if the kind of being of the terms of the relation is understood without differentiation as merely objectively present things, then the relation shows itself as the objectively present conformity of two objectively present things. When the statement has been expressed, the discoveredness of beings moves into the kind of being of inneroJorldly things at hand. But to the extent that in this discoveredness, as a discoveredness of ... , a relation to things objectively present persists, discoveredness (truth) in its turn becomes an objectively present relation between objectively present things (intellectus et res). The existential phenomenon of discoveredness based on the disclosedness of Da-sein becomes an objectively present property that still contains the character of relation and, as such, is split up into an objec-
I. VI
Being and Time
207
tively present relation. Truth as disclosedness and as a being toward discovered beings-a being that itself discovers-has become truth as the agreement between innerworldly things objectively present. Thus we have shown the ontological derivation of the traditional concept of truth. However, what comes last in the order of the existential and ontological foundational context is regarded ontically and factically as what is first and nearest. But the necessity of this fact is again based in the kind of being of Da-sein itself. Absorbed in taking care of things, Da-sein understands itself in terms of what it encounters within the world. The discoveredness belonging to discovering is initially found within the world in what has been expressed. But not only is truth encountered as something objectively present, but the understanding of being in general initially understands all beings as something objectively present. If the "truth" that we encounter initially in an antic way is understood ontologically in the way nearest to us, the logos (statement) gets understood as logos tinos (statement about ... , discoveredness of ... ), but the phenomenon gets interpreted as something objectively present with regard to its possible objective presence. But because objective presence is equated with the meaning of being in general, the question whether this kind of being of truth, and its initially encountered structure, are primordial or not can not arise at all. The understanding of being of Da-sein which was initially dominant, and has still not been overcome today in a fundamental and explicit way, itself covers over the primordial phenomenon of truth. At the same time, we must not overlook the fact that for the Greeks, who were the first to develop this initial understanding of being as a branch of knowledge and to bring it to dominance, this primordial understanding of truth was also alive, even if pre-ontologically, and it even held its own against the concealment implicit in their ontology-at least in Aristotle. 42 Aristode never defended the thesis that the primordial "place" of truth is the judgment. Rather, he says that the logos is the kind of being of Da-sein which can either discover or cover over. This double possibility is what is distinctive about the truth of the logos; it is the attitude which can also cover over. And since Aristode never asserted this thesis, he was never in the position of "expanding" the concept of truth of logos to pure noein. The "truth" of aesthesis and of the seeing of the "Ideas," is the primordial discovering. And only because noesis primarily discovers, can the logos, too, have the function of discovering as dianoein. The thesis that the genuine "locus" of truth is the judgment not only invokes Aristotle unjustly, it also fails with regard to its content to recognize the structure of truth. The statement is not the primary
226
208
Being and Time
I.VJ
"locus" of truth, but the other way around, the statement as a mode of appropriation of discoveredness and as a way of being-in-the-world is based in discovering, or in the disclosedness of Da-sein. The most primordial "truth" is the "locus" of the statement and the ontological condition of the possibility that statements can be true or false (discovering or covering over). Understood in its most primordial sense, truth belongs to the fundamental constitution of Da-sein. The term signifies an existential. But thus we have already sketched out our answer to the question of the kind of being of truth and the meaning of the necessity of the presupposition that "there is truth."
227
(c) The Kind of Being of Truth and the Presupposition of Truth. Constituted by disclosedness, Da-sein is essentially in the truth. Disclosedness is an essential kind of being of Da-sein. "There is" ["gibt es"] truth only insofar as Da-sein is and as long as it is. Beings are discovered only when Da-sein is, and only as long as Da-sein is are they disclosed. Newton's laws, the law of contradiction, and any truth whatsoever, are true only as long as Da-sein is. Before there was any Da-sein, there was no truth; nor will there be any after Da-sein is no more. For in such a case truth as disclosedness, discovering, and discoveredness cannot be. Before Newton's laws were discovered, they were not "true." From this it does not follow that they were false or even that they would become false if ontically no discoveredness were possible any longer. Just as little does this "restriction" imply a diminution of the being true of "truths." The fact that before Newton his laws were neither true nor false cannot mean that the beings which they point out in a discovering way did not previously exist. The laws became true through Newton, through them beings in themselves became accessible for Da-sein. With the discoveredness of beings, they show themselves precisely as the beings that previously were. To discover in this way is the kind of being of "truth." The fact that there are "eternal truths" will not be adequately proven until it is successfully demonstrated that Da-sein has been and will be for all eternity. As long as this proof is lacking, the statement remains a fantasical assertion which does not gain in legitimacy by being generally "believed" by the philosophers. In accordance with the essential kind of being appropriate to Da-sein, all truth is relative to the being ofDa-sein. Is this relativity tantamount to saying that all truth is "subjective"? If one interprets "subjective" to mean "left to the arbitrariness of the subject, " then certainly not. For in accordance with its very meaning, discovering exempts statements from the province of "subjective" arbitrariness and brings discovering Da-sein before beings themselves. And only because "truth," as discovering, is a
I.VI
Being and Time
209
kind of being of Da-sein, can it be removed from the arbitrariness of Dasein. The "universal validity" of truth, too, is rooted solely in the fact that Da-sein can discover and free beings in themselves. Only thus can this being in itself be binding for every possible statement, that is, for every possible way of pointing them out. If truth has been correctly understood, is it not in the least jeopardized by the fact that it is ontically possible only in the "subject," and stands or falls with the being of that "subject"? The meaning of the presupposition of truth, too, becomes intelligible in terms of the existentially conceived kind of being of truth. Why must we presuppose that there is truth? What does "presuppose" mean? What do "must" and "we" mean? What does it mean "there is truth"? "We" presupposes truth because, "we," existing in the kind of being of Da-sein, are "in the truth." We do not presuppose it as something "outside" and "above" us to which we are related along with other "values" too. We do not presuppose truth, but* truth makes it ontologically possible that we can be in such a way that we "presuppose" something. Truth first makes possible something like presupposition. What does "presupposing" mean? To understand something as the ground of the being of another being. Such understanding of a being in its context of being is possible only on the basis of disdosedness, that is, the discovering ofDa-sein. To presuppose "truth" then means to understand it as something for the sake of which Da-sein is. But Da-sein is always already ahead of itself; that lies in its constitution of being as care. It is a being that is concerned in its being about its ownmost potentialityof-being. Disdosedness and discovering belong essentially to the being and potentiality-for-being of Da-sein as being-in-the-world. Da-sein is concerned with its potentiality-for-being-in-the-world, and this includes circumspectly discovering and taking care of innerworldly beings. In the constitution of being of Da-sein as care, in being ahead of itself, lies the most primordial "presupposing." Because this presupposing itself belongs to the being of Da-sein, "we" have to also presuppose "ourselves" as determined by disclosedness. This "presupposing" that lies in the being of Da-sein is not related to beings unlike Da-sein, which are there in addition, but solely to itself. The truth which is presupposed, or which "is there," by which its being is to be defined, has the kind of being, or meaning of being, of Dasein itself. We have to "make" the presupposition of truth because it is already "made" with the being of the "we." We must presuppose truth, it must be as the disdosedness of Dasein, just as Da-sein itself must always be as my own and this particular
* but the essence of truth places us in the "prior" of what is spoken to us.
228
210
229
Being and Time
I. VI
Da-sein. This belongs to the essential thrownness of Da-sein into the world. Has Da-sein as itself ever freely decided and will it euer be able to decide whether it wants to come into "Da·sein" or not? "In itself' we cannot see why beings should be discovered, why truth and Da-sein must be. The usual refutation of scepticism, that denies either the being or the knowability of "truth," gets stuck halfway. What it shows in formal argumentation is simply the fact that when someone judges, truth has been presupposed: this suggests that "truth" belongs to statements, that pointing out is a discovering according to its meaning. Why that must be never gets clarified, it has never been clarified wherein the ontological ground for this necessary connection of being of statement and truth lies. Similarly, the kind of being of truth and the meaning of presupposing and its ontological foundation in Da-sein itself remain completely obscure. Moreover, one fails to recognize the fact that truth is already presupposed even when no one is judging, insofar as Da-sein is at all. A skeptic can no more be refuted than the being of truth can ever be "proved." If the skeptic, who denies the truth, factically is, he does not even need to be refuted. Insofar as he is and has understood himself in this being, he has obliterated Da-sein, and thus truth, in the despair of suicide. The necessity of truth cannot be proven because Da-sein cannot first be subjected to prooffor its own part. It has no more been demonstrated that there has ever "been" a "real" skeptic (although that is what has at bottom been believed in the refutations of skepticism, in spite of what these undertake to do) than it has been demonstrated that there are any "eternal truths." Perhaps such skeptics have been more frequent than one would innocently like to believe when one tries to overturn "skepticism" by formal dialectics. Thus with the question of the being of truth and the necessity of its presupposition as well as that of the essence of knowledge, an "ideal subject" has generally been posited. The explicit or inexplicit motive for this lies in the requirement that philosophy should have the "a prion'" as its theme, rather than "empirical facts" as such. There is some justification for this requirement, though it still needs to be grounded ontologically. But is this requirement satisfied by positing an "ideal subject"? Is it not a fantastically idealized subject? Is not precisely the a priori character of the merely "factual" subject, of Da-sein, missed with the concept of such a subject? Is it not an attribute of the a priori character of the factical subject (that is, of the facticity of Da-sein) that it is equiprimordially in truth and untruth? The ideas of a "pure ego" and a "consciousness in general" are so far from including the a priori character of "real" subjectivity that they pass over the ontological character of facticity of Da-sein and its constitution of being, or do not see it at all. Rejection of a "consciousness in general" does not mean the negation of the a priori, any more than the
I.VI
Being and Time
211
positing of an idealized subject guarantees a factually based a priori character of Da-sein. The contention that there are "eternal truths," as well as the confusion of the phenomenally based "ideality" of Da-sein with an idealized absolute subject, belong to the remnants of Christian theology within the philosophical problematic that have not yet been radically eliminated. The being of truth stands in a primordial connection with Da-sein. And only because Da-sein exists as constituted by disclosedness (that is, by understanding) can something like being be understood, only so is an understanding of being possible at all. "There is"[.& gibt] being-not beings-only insofar as truth is. And truth is only because and as long as Da-sein is. Being and truth "are" equiprimordially. What does it mean that being "is," where being is, after all, supposed to be distinguished from all beings?* One can inquire into this only when the meaning of being and the scope of the understanding of being in general have been clarified. Only then can one also analyze primordially what belongs to the concept of a science of being as such, its possibilities and transformations. And in the definition of this inquiry and its truth, the inquiry will have to be ontologically defined as the discovery of beings and their truth. The answer to the question of the meaning of being is still lacking. What has the fundamental analysis of Da-sein so far accomplished for the development of that question? By freeing the phenomenon of care, we clarified the constitution of being of that being to whose being something like an understanding of being belongs. The being of Da-sein was thus at the same time distinguished from the modes of being (handiness, objective presence, reality) that characterize beings unlike Da-sein. We clarified understanding itself, whereby at the same time the methodical transparency of the procedure of interpreting being by understanding and interpreting it has been guaranteed. If the primordial constitution of being of Da-sein is to be gained through care, then on this basis the understanding of being contained in care must also be grasped, that is, it must be possible to delineate the meaning of being. But is the most primordial, existential, and ontological constitution of Da-sein disclosed with the phenomenon of care? Does the structural manifoldness in the phenomenon of care give the most primordial totality of the being of factical Da-sein? Has the inquiry up to now gotten Da-sein as a whole in view at all?
* Ontological difference.
230
DIVISION TWO
231
Da-sein and Temporality
45. The Result of the Preparatory Fundamental Analysis of Da-sein and the Task of a Primordia~ Existential Interpretation of This Being What was gained by our preparatory analysis of Da-sein, and what are we looking for? We have found the fundamental constitution of the being in question, being-in-the-world, whose essential structures are centered in disclosedness. The totality of this structural whole revealed itself as care. The being of Da-sein is contained in care. The analysis of this being took as its guideline existence, 1 which was defined by way of anticipation as the essence of Da-sein. The term existence formally indicates that Dasein is as an understanding potentiality-of-being which is concerned in its being about its being. Thus existing, I myself am that being. The development of the phenomenon of care provided an insight into the concrete constitution of existence, that is, into its equiprimordial connection with facticity and with the falling prey of Da-sein. We are looking for the answer to the question of the meaning of being in general, and above all the possibility of radically developing this basic question* of all ontology. But freeing the horizon in which something like being in general becomes intelligible amounts to clarifying the possibility of the understanding of being in general, an understanding which itself belongs to the constitution of that being which we *By which, however, "onto-logic" is transformed at the same time (cf. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, section IV).
213
214
232
Being and Time
II
call Da-sein. 2 The understanding of being, however, cannot be radically clarified as an essential factor in the being of Da-sein, unless the being to whose being it belongs has been primordially interpreted in itself with regard to its being. Are we entitled to the claim that in characterizing Da-sein ontologically as care we have given a primordial interpretation of this being? By what standard is the existential analytic of Da-sein to be measured with regard to its primordiality or nonprimordiality? What then do we mean by the primordiality of an ontological interpretation? Ontological inquiry is a possible way of interpretation which we characterized as a development and appropriation of an understanding.' Every interpretation has its fore-having, its fore-sight, and its foreconception. If such an interpretation becomes an explicit task of an inquiry, the totality of these "presuppositions" (which we call the hermeneutical situation) needs to be clarified and made secure beforehand both in a fundamental experience of the "object" to be disclosed, and in terms of that experience. In ontological interpretation beings are freed with regard to their own constitution of being. Such an interpretation obliges us first to give a phenomenal characterization of the being we have taken as our theme and thus bring it into the scope of our fore-having with which all the subsequent steps of our analysis are to conform. But at the same time these steps need to be guided by the possible fore-sight of the kind of being of the being in question. Forehaving and fore-sight then prefigure at the same time the conceptuality (fore-conception) to which all the structures of being are to be brought. But a primordial, ontological interpretation requires not only in general that the hermeneutical situation be secured in conformity with the phenomena, but also the explicit assurance that the totality of the beings taken as its theme have been brought to a fore-having. Similarly, it is not sufficient just to make a first sketch of the being of these beings, even if it is phenomenally based. If we are to have a fore-sight of being, we must see it with respect to the unity of the possible structural factors belonging to it. Only then can the question of the meaning of the unity that belongs to the totality of being of all beings be asked and answered with phenomenal certainty. Did the existential analysis of Da-sein which we made, arise from such a hermeneutical situation as will guarantee the primordiality that fundamental ontology requires? Can we proceed from the results attained-that the being of Da-sein is care-to the question of the primordial unity of this structural totality? What is the status of the fore-sight which has been guiding our ontological procedure up to now? We defined the idea of existence as a potentiality of being, a potentiality that understands and is concerned
II
Being and Time
215
about its own being. But this potentiality-ofbeing that is always mine is free for authenticity or inauthenticity, or for a mode in which neither of these has been differentiated.• Our previous interpretation was limited to an analysis of indifferent or inauthentic existence, starting out with average everydayness. Of course, it was possible and necessary to reach a concrete definition of the existentiality of existence in this way. Still, our ontological characterization of the constitution of existence was flawed by an essential lack. Existence means potentiality-of-being, but also authentic potentiality-of-being. As long as the existential structure of authentic potentiality-of-being is not incorporated in the idea of existence, the fore-sight guiding an existential interpretation lacks primordiality. And what is the situation with the fore-having of the hermeneutical situation up to now? When and how did our existential analytic make sure that by starting with everydayness it forced all ofDa-sein-this being from its "beginning" to its "end"-into the phenomenological view giving us our theme? We did assert that care is the totality of the structural whole of the constitution of being of Da-sein.5 But have we not at the very beginning of our interpretation renounced the possibility of bringing Da-sein as a whole to view? Everydayness is, after all, precisely the being "between" birth and death. And if existence determines the being of Da-sein and if its essence is also constituted* by potentiality-of-being, then, as long as Da-sein exists, it must always, as such a potentiality, not yet be something? A being whose essence is made up of existence essentially resists the possibility of being comprehended as a total being. Not only has the hermeneutical situation given us no assurance of "having" the whole being up to now; it is even questionable whether the whole being is attainable at all, and whether a primordial, ontological interpretation of Da-sein must not get stranded-on the kind of being of the thematic being itself. One thing has become unmistakable. Our existential analytic of Dasein up to now cannot lay claim to primordiality. Its fore-having never included more than the inauthentic being of Da-sein, of Da-sein as fragmentary. If the interpretation of the being of Da-sein is to become primordial as a foundation for the development of the fundamental question of ontology, it will have to bring the being of Da-sein in its possible authenticity and totality existentially to light beforehand. Thus the task arises of placing Da-sein as a whole in our fore-having. However; that means that we must first unpack the question of this being's potentiality-for-being-a-whole. As long as Da-sein is, something is
* at the same time: already-being.
233
216
234
235
Being and Time
II
always still outstanding, what it can and will be. But the "end" itself belongs to what is outstanding. The "end" of being-in-the-world is death. This end, belonging to the potentiality-of-being, that is, to existence, limits and defines the possible totality of Da-sein. The being-at-an-end* of Da-sein in death, and thus its being a whole, can, however, be included in our discussion of the possible being whole in a phenomenally appropriate way only if an ontologically adequate, that is, an existential concept of death has been attained. But as far as Da-seint goes, death is only in an existentiell being toward death. t The existential structure of this being turns out to be the ontological constitution of the potentialityfor-being-a-whole of Da-sein. Thus, the whole existing Da-sein can be brought into our existential fore-having. But can Da-sein also exist as a whole authentically? How is the authenticity of existence to be defined at all if not with reference to authentic existing? Where do we get our criterion for this? Obviously Da-sein itself in its being must present the possibility and way of its authentic existence, if such existence is neither imposed upon it ontically, nor ontologically fabricated. But an authentic potentiality-of-being is attested by conscience. Like death, this phenomenon of Da-sein requires a genuinely existential interpretation. It leads to the insight that an authentic potentiality-of-being of Da-sein lies in wanting-to-have-a-conscience. This existentiell possibility, however, tends, from the meaning of its being, to be made definite in an existentiell way by being toward death. With the demonstration of an authentic potentialityfor-being-a-whole of Da-sein our existential analytic has secured the constitution of the primordial being of Da-sein. But the authentic potentialityfor-being-a-whole becomes visible as a mode of care. With this the phenomenally adequate basis for a primordial interpretation of the meaning of being of Da-sein is also secured. The primordial ontological ground of the existentiality of Da-sein, however, is temporality. The articulated structural totality of the being of Da-sein as care first becomes existentially intelligible in terms of temporality. The interpretation of the meaning of being of Da-sein cannot stop with this fact. The existential-temporal analysis of this being needs concrete confirmation. We must go back and free the ontological structures of Da-sein already gained with regard to their temporal meaning. Everydayness reveals itself as a mode of temporality. But by thus repeating our preparatory fundamental analysis of Da-sein, the phenomenon of temporality itself will at the same time become more transparent. In
* "being"-toward-the-end. t
Thought in accordance with the essence of Da-sein. of nonbeing.
1 being
II
Being and Time
217
tenns of temporality, it becomes intelligible why Da-sein is and can be historical in the ground of its being and, being historical, it can develop historiography. If temporality constitutes the primordial meaning of being of Dasein, and if this being is concerned about its being in its very being, then care must need "time" and thus reckon with "time." The temporality of Da-sein develops a "time calculation." The "time" experienced in such calculation is the nearest phenomenal aspect of temporality. From it originates the everyday, vulgar understanding of time. And that develops into the traditional concept of time. The clarification of the origin of the "time" "in which" innerworldly beings are encountered, of time as within-timeness, reveals an essential possibility of the temporalization of temporality. Now the understanding is being prepared for a still more primordial temporalization of temporality. In it is based the understanding of being that is constitutive for the being of Da-sein. The project of a meaning of being in general can be accomplished in the horizon of time.* Thus the inquiry comprised in this division will traverse the following stages: The possible being whole of Da-sein and being toward death (chapter I); the attestation of Da-sein of an authentic potentialityof-being and resolution (chapter II); the authentic potentiality-for-beinga-whole of Da-sein and temporality as the ontological meaning of care (chapter III); temporality and everydayness (chapter IV); temporality and historicity (chapter V); temporality and within-timeness as the origin of the vulgar concept of time (chapter VI). 6
* Presencing [An-wesenheit] (Arrival and Appropriation).
I The Possible Being-a-Whole of Da-sein and Being-toward-Death
46. The Seeming Impossibility of Ontologically Grasping and Determining Da-sein as a Whole The inadequacy of the hermeneutical situation from which the foregoing analysis originated must be overcome. With regard to the fore-having, which must necessarily be obtained, of the whole of Da-sein, we must ask whether this being, as something existing, can become accessible at all in its being. There seem to be important reasons that speak against the possibility of our required task, reasons that lie in the constitution of Da-sein itself. Care, which forms the totality of the structural whole of Da-sein, obviously contradicts a possible being whole of this being according to its ontological sense. The primary factor of care, "being ahead of itself," however, means that Da-sein always exists for the sake of itself. "As long as it is," up until its end, it is related to its potentiality-of-being. Even when it, still existing, has nothing further "ahead of it," and has "settled its accounts," its being is still influenced by "being ahead of itself." Hopelessness, for example, does not tear Da-sein away from its possibilities, but is only an independent mode of being toward these possibilities. Even when one is without illusions and "is ready for anything," the "ahead of itself' is there. This structural factor of care tells us unambiguously that something is always still outstanding in Da-sein which has not yet become "real" as a potentiality-of-its-being. A constant unfinished quality thus lies in
219
236
220
237
Being and Time
11.1
the essence of the constitution of Da-sein. 1bis lack of totality means that there is still something outstanding in one's potentiality-for-being. However, if Da-sein "exists" in such a way that there is absolutely nothing more outstanding for it, it has also already thus become nolonger-being-there. Eliminating what is outstanding in its being is equivalent to annihilating its being. As long as Da-sein if as a being, it has never attained its "wholeness." But if it does, this gain becomes the absolute loss of being-in-the-world. It is then never again to be experienced as a being. The reason for the impossibility of experiencing Da-sein ontically as an existing whole and thus of defining it ontologically in its wholeness does not lie in any imperfection of our cognitive faculties. The hindrance lies on the side of the being of this being. What cannot even be in such a way that an experience of Da-sein could pretend to grasp it, fundamentally eludes being experienced. But is it not then a hopeless undertaking to try to discern the ontological wholeness of being of Da-sein? As an essential structural factor of care, "being ahead of itself' cannot be eliminated. But is what we concluded from this tenable? Did we not conclude in a merely formal argumentation that it is impossible to grasp the whole of Da-sein? Or did we not at bottom inadvertently posit Da-sein as something objectively present ahead of which something not yet objectively present constantly moves along? Did our argumentation grasp not-yet-being and the "ahead-of-itself' in a genuinely existential sense? Did we speak about "end' and "totality" in a way phenomenally appropriate to Da-sein? Did the expression "death" have a biological significance or one that is existential and ontological, or indeed was it sufficiently and securely defined at all? And have we actually exhausted all the possibilities of making Da-sein accessible in its totality? We have to answer these questions before the problem of the wholeness of Da-sein can be dismissed as nothing. The question of the wholeness of Da-sein, both the existentiell question about a possible potentiality-for-being-a-whole, as well as the existential question about the constitution of being of "end" and "wholeness," contain the task of a positive analysis of the phenomena of existence set aside up to now. In the center of these considerations we have the task of characterizing ontologically the being-toward-the-end of Da-sein and of achieving an existential concept of death. Our inquiry related to these topics is structured in the following way: The possibility of experiencing the death of others, and the possibility of grasping the whole of Da-sein (section 4 7); what is outstanding, end and wholeness (section 48); how the existential analysis of death is distinguished from other possible interpretations of this phenomenon (section 49); preliminary sketch of the existential and
11.1
Being and Time
221
ontological structure of death (section 50); being toward death and the everydayness ofDa-sein (section 51); everyday being toward death and the complete existential concept of death (section 52); the existential project of an authentic being toward death (section 53).
4 7. The Possibility of Experiencing the Death of Others and the Possibility of Grasping Da-sein as a Whole When Da-sein reaches its wholeness in death, it simultaneously loses the being of the there. The transition to no-longer-being-there lifts Dasein right out of the possibility of experiencing this transition and of understanding it as something experienced. This kind of thing is denied to actual Da-sein in relation to itself. The death of others, then, is all the more penetrating. In this way, an end of Da-sein becomes "objectively" accessible. Da-sein can gain an experience of death, all the more because it is essentially being-with with others. This "objective" givenness of death must then make possible an ontological analysis of the totality of Da-sein. Thus from the kind of being that Da-sein possesses as being-withone-another, we might glean the fairly obvious information that when the Da-sein of others has come to an end, it might be chosen as a substitute theme for our analysis of the totality of Da-sein. But does this lead us to our intended goal? Even the Da-sein of others, when it has reached its wholeness in death, is a no-longer-being-there in the sense of no-longer-being-in-theworld. Does not dying mean going-out-of-the-world and losing beingin-the-world? Yet, the no-longer-being-in-the-world of the deceased (understood in an extreme sense) is still a being* in the sense of the mere objective presence of a corporeal thing encountered. In the dying of others that remarkable phenomenon of being can be experienced that can be defmed as the transition of a being from the kind of being of Da-sein (or of life) to no-longer-being-there. The end of the being qua Dasein is the beginning of this being qua something objectively present. This interpretation of the transition from Da-sein to something merely objectively present, however, misses the phenomenal content in that the being still remaining does not represent a mere corporeal thing. Even the objectively present corpse is, viewed theoretically, still a possible object for pathological anatomy whose understanding is oriented toward the idea of life. Merely-being-objectively-present is "more" than a lifeless, material thing. In it we encounter something unliving which has lost its life.
* ein Sein-TR.
238
222
239
Being and Time
II.I
But even this way of characterizing what still remains does not exhaust the complete phenomenal findings with regard to Da-sein. The "deceased," as distinct from the dead body, has been torn away from "those remaining behind," and is the object of "being taken care of" in funeral rites, the burial, and the cult of graves. And that is so because he is "still more" in his kind of being than an innerworldly thing at hand to be taken care of. In lingering together with him in mourning and commemorating, those remaining behind are with him, in a mode of concern which honors him. Thus the relation of being to the dead must not be grasped as a being together with something at hand which takes care of it. In such being-with with the dead, the deceased himself is no longer factically "there." However, being-with always means being-with-oneanother in the same world. The deceased has abandoned our "world" and left it behind. It is in terms of this world that those remaining can still be with him. The more appropriately the no-longer-being-there of the deceased is grasped phenomenally, the more clearly it can be seen that in such being-with with the dead, the real having-come-to-an-end of the deceased is precisely not experienced. Death does reveal itself as a loss, but as a loss experienced by those remaining behind. However, in suffering the loss, the loss of being as such which the dying person "suffers" does not become accessible. We do not experience the dying of others in a genuine sense; we are at best always just "there" too. And even if it were possible and feasible to clarify "psychologically" the dying of others, this would by no means let us grasp the way of being we have in mind, namely, coming-to-an-end. We are asking about the ontological meaning of the dying of the person who dies, as a potentiality-of-being of his being, and not about the way of being-with and the still-being-there of the deceased with those left behind. If death as experienced in others is to be the theme of our analysis of the end of Da-sein and its totality, this cannot give us what it presumes to give, either ontically or ontologically. After all, taking the dying of others as a substitute theme for the ontological analysis of the finished character of Da-sein and its totality rests on an assumption that demonstrably fails altogether to recognize the kind of being of Da-sein. That is what one presupposes when one is of the opinion that any Da-sein could arbitrarily be replaced by another, so that what cannot be experienced in one's own Da-sein is accessible in another Da-sein. But is this assumption really so groundless? Indubitably, the fact that one Da-sein can be represented by another belongs to the possibilities-of-being of being-with-one-another in the world. In the everydayness of taking care of things, constant use of such
11.1
Being and Time
223
representability is made in many ways. Any going to ... , any fetching of ... , is representable in the scope of the "surrounding world" initially taken care of. The broad multiplicity of ways of being-in-the-world in which one person can be represented by another extends not only to the used-up modes of public being with one another, but concerns as well the possibilities of taking care of things limited to definite circles, tailored to professions, social classes, and stages of life. But the very meaning of such representation is such that it is always a representation "in" and "together with" something, that is, in taking care of something. Everyday Da-sein understands itself initially and for the most part, however, in terms of what it is accustomed to take care of. "One is" what one does. With regard to this being (the everyday being-absorbed-with-oneanother in the "world" taken care of), representability is not only possible in general, but is even constitutive for being-with-one-another. Here one Da-sein can and must, within certain limits, "be" another Da-sein. However, this possibility of representation gets completely stranded when it is a matter of representing the possibility of being that constitutes the coming-to-an-end of Da-sein and gives it its totality as such. No one can take the other's dying awayfrom him. Someone can go "to his death for an other." However, that always means to sacrifice oneself for the other "in a definite matter." Such dying for ... can never, however, mean that the other has thus had his death in the least taken away. Every Da-sein must itself actually take dying upon itself. Insofar as it "is," death is always essentially my own. And it indeed signifies a peculiar possibility of being in which it is absolutely a matter of the being of my own Da-sein. In dying, it becomes evident that death* is ontologically constituted by mineness and existence! Dying is not an event, but a phenomenon to be understood existentially in an eminent sense still to be delineated more closely. But if "ending," as dying, constitutes the totality of Da-sein, the being of the totality itself must be conceived as an existential phenomenon of my own Da-sein. In "ending," and in the totality thus constituted of Da-sein, there is essentially no representation. The way out suggested fails to recognize this existential fact when it proposes the dying of others as a substitute theme for the analysis of totality. Thus the attempt to make the totality of Da-sein phenomenally accessible in an appropriate way gets stranded again. But the result of these considerations is not just negative. They were oriented toward the phenomena, even if rather crudely. We have indicated that death is an existential phenomenon. Our inquiry is thus forced into a purely
* The relation of Da-sein to death; death itself-its arrival-entrance, dying.
240
224
241
Being and Time
II. I
existential orientation toward my own Da-sein. For the analysis of death as dying, there remains only the possibility of bringing this phenomenon either to a purely existential concept or, on the other hand, of renouncing any ontological understanding of it. Furthermore, it was evident in our characterization of the transition from Da-sein to no-longer-being-there as no-longer-being-in-theworld that the going-out-of-the-world of Da-sein in the sense of dying must be distinguished from a going-out-of-the-world of what is only alive. The ending of what is only alive we formulate terminologically as perishing. The distinction can become visible only by distinguishing the ending characteristic of Da-sein from the ending of a living thing.2 Dying can, of course, also be conceived physiologically and biologically. But the medical concept of"exitus" does not coincide with that of perishing. From the previous discussion of the ontological possibility of conceiving of death, it becomes clear at the same time that substructures of beings of a different kind of being (objective presence or life) thrust themselves to the fore unnoticeably and threaten to confuse the interpretation of the phenomenon, even the first appropriate presentation of it. We can cope with this problem only by looking for an ontologically adequate way of defining constitutive phenomena for our further analysis, such as end and totality.
48. What is Outstanding, End, and Totality Our ontological characterization of end and totality can only be preliminary in the scope of this inquiry. To perform this task adequately we must not only set forth the formal structure of end in general and totality in general. At ~e same time, we must disentangle the structural variations possible for them in different realms, that is, deformalized variations which are related to definite beings with content and structurally determined in terms of their being. This task again presupposes a sufficiently unequivocal and positive interpretation of the kinds of being that require a regional separation of the whole of beings. The understanding of these ways of being, however, requires a clarified idea of being in general. The task of adequately carrying out the ontological analysis of end and totality gets stranded not only because the theme is so far-reaching, but because there is a difficulty in principle: in order to master this task, we must presuppose that precisely what we are seeking in this inquiry (the meaning of being in general) is something that we have found already and with which we are quite familiar. In the following considerations, the "variations" in which we are chiefly interested are those of end and totality; these are ontological determinations of Da-sein which are to lead to a primordial interpreta-
11.1
Being and Time
225
tion of this being. With constant reference to the existential constitution of Da-sein already developed, we must initially try to decide how ontologically inappropriate to Da-sein are the concepts of end and totality initially forcing themselves upon us, no matter how indefinite they are categorially. The rejection of such concepts must be further developed to a positive directive to their specific realms. Thus our understanding of end and totality in their variant forms as existentials will be strengthened, and this guarantees the possibility of an ontological interpretation of death. But if the analysis of the end and totality of Da-sein takes an orientation of such broad scope, this nevertheless cannot mean that the existential concepts of end and totality are to be gained by way of a deduction. On the contrary, it is a matter of taking the existential meaning of the coming-to-an-end of Da-sein from Da-sein itself and of showing how this "ending" can constitute a being whole of that being that exists. What has been discussed up to now about death can be formulated in three theses:
1. As long as Da-sein is, a not-yet belongs to it, which it will be-what is constantly outstanding. 2. The coming-to-its-end of what is not-yet-at-an-end (in which what is outstanding is liquidated with regard to its being) has the character of no-longer-being-there. 3. Coming-to-an-end implies a mode of being in which the actual Da-sein absolutely cannot be represented by someone else. In Da-sein there is inevitably a constant "fragmentariness" which finds its end in death. But may we interpret the phenomenal fact that this not-yet "belongs" to Da-sein as long as it is to mean that it is something outstanding? With regard to what kind of beings do we speak of something outstanding? The expression means indeed what "belongs" to a being, but is still lacking. Outstanding, as lacking, is based on a belongingness. For example, the remainder of a debt still to be paid is outstanding. What is outstanding is not yet available. Liquidating the "debt" as paying off what is outstanding means that the money "comes in," that is, the remainder is paid in sequence, whereby the not-yet is, so to speak, filled out until the sum owed is "all together." Thus, to be outstanding means that what belongs together is not yet together. Ontologically, this implies the unhandiness of portions to be brought in which have the same kind of being of those already at hand. The latter in their turn do not have their kind of being modified by having the remainder come in. The existing untogethemess is liquidated by a cumulative placing together. The beingfor which something is outstanding has the
242
226
243
244
Being and Time
II. I
kind of being of something at hand. We characterize the together, or the untogether based on it, as a sum. The untogether belonging to such a mode of the together, lacking as something outstanding, can, however, by no means ontologically define the not-yet that belongs to Da-sein as its possible death. Da-sein does not have the kind of being of a thing at hand in the world at all. The together of the being that Da-sein is "in running its course" until it ha8 completed "its course" is not constituted by a "progressive" piecingon of beings that, somehow and somewhere, are already at hand in their own right. That Da-sein should be together only when its not-yet has been filled out is so far from being the case that precisely then it no longer is. Da-sein always already exists in such a way that its not-yet belongs to it. But are there not beings which are as they are and to which a not-yet can belong, without these beings necessarily having the kind of being of Da-sein? For example, one can say that the last quarter of the moon is outstanding until it is full. The not-yet decreases with the disappearance of the shadow covering it. And yet the moon is, after all, always already objectively present as a whole. Apart from the fact that the moon is never wholly to be grasped even when it is full, the not-yet by no means signifies a not-yet-being-together of parts belonging together, but rather pertains only to the way we grasp it perceptually. The not-yet that belongs to Da-sein, however, not only remains preliminarily and at times inaccessible to one's own or to others' experience, it "is" not yet "real" at all. The problem does not pertain to the grasp of the not-yet of the character of Da-sein, but rather its possible being or nonbeing. Dasein, as itself, has to become, that is, be, what it is not yet. In order to thus be able, by comparison, to define the being of the not-yet of the character of Da-sein, we must reflect on beings to whose kind of being becoming belongs. For example, the unripe fruit moves toward its ripeness. In ripening, what it not yet is is by no means pieced together as something notyet-objectively-present. The fruit ripens itself, and this ripening characterizes its being as fruit. Nothing we can think of which could be added on could remove the unripeness of the fruit, if this being did not ripen of itself The not-yet of unripeness does not mean something other which is outstanding that could be objectively present in and with it in a way indifferent to the fruit. It means the fruit itself in its specific kind of being. The sum that is not yet complete is, as something at hand, "indifferent" to the unhandy remainder that is lacking. Strictly speaking, it can be neither indifferent to it nor not indifferent. The ripening fruit, however, is not only not indifferent to its unripeness as an other to itself, but, ripening, it is the unripeness. The not-yet is already included in its
11.1
Being and Time
227
own being, by no means as an arbitrary determination, but as a constituent. Correspondingly, Da-sein, too, is always already its not-yef as long as it is. What constitutes the "unwholeness" in Da-sein, the constant beingahead-of-itself, is neither a summative together which is outstanding, nor even a not-yet-having-become-accessible, but rather a not-yet that any Da-sein always has to be, given the being that it is. Still, the comparison with the unripeness of the fruit does show essential differences despite some similarities. To reflect on these differences means that we shall recognize how indefinite our previous discussion of end and ending has hitherto been. Ripening is the specific being of the fruit. It is also a kind of being of the not-yet (unripeness}, and is formally analogous to Da-sein in that the latter, as well as the former, always already is its not-yet in a sense yet to be defined. But even then, this does not mean that ripeness as "end" and death as "end" coincide with regard to the their ontological structure as ends. With ripeness, the fruit fulfills itself. But is the death at which Da-sein arrives a fulfillment in this sense? It is true that Da-sein has "completed its course" with its death. Has it thus necessarily exhausted its specific possibilities? Rather, are these not precisely what gets taken from it? Even "unfulfilled" Da-sein ends. On the other hand, Da-sein so little needs to ripen only with its death that it can already have gone beyond that ripeness before the end. For the most part, it ends in unfulfillment, or else disintegrated and used up. Ending does not necessarily mean fulfilling oneself. It thus becomes more urgent to ask in what sense, if any, death must be grasped as the ending of Da-sein. Initially, ending means stopping, and it means this in senses that are ontologically different. The rain stops. It is no longer objectively present. The road stops. This ending does not cause the road to disappear, but this stopping rather determines the road as this objectively present one. Hence ending, as stopping, can mean either to change into the absence of objective presence or, however, to be objectively present only when the end comes. The latter kind of ending can again be determinative for an unfinished thing objectively present, as a road under construction breaks off, or it may rather constitute the "finishedness" of something objectively present-the painting is finished with the last stroke of the brush. But ending as getting finished does not include fulfillment. On the other hand, whatever has got to be fulfilled must reach its possible finishedness. Fulfillment is the mode of "finishedness," and is founded upon it. Finishedness is itself possible only as a determination of something objectively present or at hand.
245
228
246
Being and Time
II.I
Even ending in the sense of disappearing can still be modified according to the kind of being of the being. The rain is at an end, that is, it has disappeared. The bread is at an end, that is, used up, no longer available as something at hand. None of these modes of ending are able to characterize death appropriately as the end of Da-sein. If dying were understood as being-at-an-end in the sense of an ending of the kind discussed, Da-sein would be posited as something objectively present or at hand. In death, Da-sein is neither fulfilled nor does it simply disappear; it has not become finished or completely available as something at hand. Rather, just as Da-sein constantly already is its not-yet as long as it is, it also always already is its end. The ending that we have in view when we speak of death, does not signify a being-at-an-end of Da-sein, but* rather a being toward the end of this being. Death is a way to be that Dasein takes over as soon as it is. "As soon as a human being is born, he is old enough to die right away. "4 Ending, as being toward the end, must be clarified ontologically in terms of the kind of being of Da-sein. And supposedly the possibility of an existing being of the not-yet that lies "before" the "end" will become intelligible only if the character of ending has been determined existentially. The existential clarification of being toward the end first provides the adequate basis for defming the possible meaning of our discussion of a totality ofDa-sein, if indeed this totality is to be constituted by death as an "end." The attempt to reach an understanding of the totality of Da-sein by starting with a clarification of the not-yet and proceeding to a characterization of ending has not yet attained its goal. It showed only negatively that the not-yet which Da-sein always is resists an interpretation as something outstanding. The end toward which Da-sein is, as existing, remains inappropriately defined by being-at-an-end. At the same time, however, our reflections should make it clear that their course must be reversed. A positive characterization of the phenomena in question (notyet-being, ending, totality) can be successful only when it is unequivocally oriented toward the constitution of being of Da-sein. This unequivocal character, however, is protected in a negative way from being sidetracked when we have an insight into the regional belonging together of the structures of end and totality which belong to Da-sein ontologically. The positive, existential, and ontological interpretation of death and its character of end are to be developed following the guideline of the fundamental constitution of Da-sein, attained up to now-the phenomenon of care.
* death as dying.
Being and Time
11.1
229
49. How the Existential Analysis of Death Differs from Other Possible Interpretations of This Phenomenon The unequivocal character of the ontological interpretation* of death should be made more secure by explicitly bringing to mind what this interpretation can not ask about and where it would be useless to expect information and instructions. In the broadest sense, death is a phenomenon of life. t life must be understood as a kind of being to which belongs a being-in-the-world. It can only be defined in a privative orientation to Da-sein. Da-sein, too, can be considered as pure life. For the biological and physiological line of questioning, it then moves into the sphere of being which we know as the world of animals and plants. In this field, dates and statistics about the life-span of plants, animals, and human beings can be ontically ascertained. Connections between the life-span, reproduction, and growth can be known. The "kinds" of death, the causes, "arrangements," and ways of its occurrence can be investigated.5 An ontological problematic underlies this biological and ontic investigation of death. We must still ask how the essence of death is defined in terms of the essence of life. The ontic inquiry into death has always already decided about this. More or less clarified preconceptions of life and death are operative in it. These preliminary concepts need to be sketched out in the ontology of Da-sein. Within the ontology of Dasein, which has priority over an ontology oflife, the existential analytic of death is subordinate to the fundamental constitution of Da-sein. We called the ending of what is alive perishing. Da-sein, too, "has" its physiological death of the kind appropriate to anything that lives and has it not ontically in isolation, but as also determined by its primordial kind of being. Da-sein, too, can end without authentically dying, though on the other hand, qua Da-sein, it does not simply perish. We call this intermediate phenomenon its demise. Let the term dying stand for the way of being in which Da-sein is toward its death. Thus we can say that Da-sein never perishes. Da-sein can only demise as long as it dies. The medical and biological inquiry into demising can attain results which can also become significant ontologically if the fundamental orientation is ensured for an existential interpretation of death. Or must sickness and death in general-even from a medical point of view-be conceived primarily as existential phenomena? The existential interpretation of death is prior to any biology and ontology of life. But it also is the foundation for any biographico-his-
* That is, the interpretation of fundamental ontology. t If we
are talking about human life, otherwise not-"world."
24 7
230
248
Being and Time
11.1
torical or ethnologico-psychological inquiry into death. A "typology" of "dying" characterizing the states and ways in which a demise is "experienced," already presupposes the concept of death. Moreover, a psychology of "dying" rather gives information about the "life" of the "dying person" than about dying itself. That is only a reflection of the fact that when Da-sein dies-and even when it dies authentically-it does not have to do so with an experience of its factical demise, or in such an experience. Similarly, the interpretations of death in primitive peoples, of their behavior toward death in magic and cult, throw light primarily on the understanding of Da-sein; but the interpretation of this understanding already requires an existential analytic and a corresponding concept of death. The ontological analysis of being-toward-the-end, on the other hand, does not anticipate any existentiell stance toward death. If death is defined as the "end" of Da-sein, that is, of being-in-the-world, no ontic decision has been made as to whether "after death" another being is still possible, either higher or lower, whether Da-sein " lives on" or even, "outliving itself," is "immortal." Nor is anything decided ontically about the "otherworldly" and its possibility any more than about the "thisworldly"; as if norms and rules for behavior toward death should be proposed for "edification." But our analysis of death remains purely "this-worldly" in that it interprets the phenomenon solely with respect to the question of how it enters into actual Da-sein as its possibility-of-being. We cannot even ask with any methodological assurance about what "is after death" until death is understood in its full ontological essence. Whether such a question presents a possible theoretical question at all is not to be decided here. The this-worldly, ontological interpretation of death comes before any ontic, other-worldly speculation. Finally, an existential analysis of death lies outside the scope of what might be discussed under the rubric of a "metaphysics of death." The questions of how and when death "came into the world," what "meaning" it can and should have as an evil and suffering in the whole of beings-these are questions that necessarily presuppose an understanding not only of the character of being of death, but the ontology of the whole of beings as a whole and the ontological clarification of evil and negativity in particular. The existential analysis is methodically prior to the questions of a biology, psychology theodicy, and theology of death. Taken ontically, the results of the analysis show the peculiar formality and emptiness of any ontological characterization. However, that must not make us blind to the rich and complex structure of the phenomenon. Since Da-sein never becomes accessible at all as something objectively present, because being possible belongs in its own way to its kind of being, even less may we
Being and Time
11.1
231
expect to simply read off the ontological structure of death, if indeed death is an eminent possibility of Da-sein. On the other hand, our analysis cannot be supported by an idea of death that has been devised arbitrarily and at random. We can restrain this arbitrariness only by giving beforehand an ontological characterization of the kind of being in which the "end" enters into the average everydayness of Da-sein. For this we need to envisage fully the structures of everydayness worked out earlier. The fact that existentiell possibilities of being toward death have their resonance in an existential analysis of death, is implied by the essence of any ontological inquiry. All the more explicitly, then, must an existentiell neutrality go together with the existential conceptual definition, especially with regard to death, where the character of possibility of Da-sein can be revealed most clearly of all. The existential problematic aims solely at developing the ontological structure of the being-toward-the-end of Da-sein.6
249
50. A Preliminary Sketch of the Existential and Ontological Structure of Death From our considerations of something outstanding, end, and totality there has resulted the necessity of interpreting the phenomenon of death as being-toward-the-end in terms of the fundamental constitution of Da-sein. Only in this way can it become clear how a wholeness constituted by being-toward-the-end is possible in Da-seiil itself, in accordance with its structure of being. We have seen that care is the fundamental constitution of Da-sein. The ontological significance of this expression was expressed in the "definition": being-ahead-of-itselfalready-being-in (the world) as being-together-with beings encountered (within the world). 7 Thus the fundamental characteristics of the being of Da-sein are expressed: in being-ahead-of-itself, existence, in alreadybeing-in ... , facticity, in being-together-with ... , falling prey. Provided that death belongs to the being of Da-sein in an eminent sense, it (or being-toward-the-end) must be able to be defined in terms of these characteristics. We must, in the first instance, make it clear in a preliminary sketch how the existence, facticity, and falling prey of Da-sein are revealed in the phenomenon of death. The interpretation of the not-yet, and thus also of the most extreme not-yet, of the end of Da-sein in the sense of something outstanding was rejected as inappropriate. For it included the ontological distortion of Dasein as something objectively present. Being-at-an-end means existentially being-toward-the-end. The most extreme not-yet has the character of something to which Da-sein relates. The end is imminent for Da-sein. Death
250
232
251
Being and Time
11.1
is not something not yet objectively present, nor the last outstanding element reduced to a minimum, but rather an imminence. However, many things can be imminent for Da-sein as being-in-theworld. The character of imminence is not in itself distinctive for death. On the contrary, this interpretation could even make us suspect that death would have to be understood in the sense of an imminent event to be encountered in the surrounding world. For example, a thunderstorm can be imminent, remodeling a house, the arrival of a friend, accordingly, being which are objectively present, at hand or Da-sein-with. Imminent death does not have this kind of being. But a journey, for example, can also be imminent for Da-sein, or a discussion with others, or a renouncing something which Da-sein itself can be-its own possibilities-of-being which are founded in being-with others. Death is a possibility of being that Da-sein always has to take upon itself. With death, Da-sein stands before itself in its ownmost potentialityof-being. In this possibility, Da-sein is concerned about its being-in-theworld absolutely. Its death is the possibility of no-longer-being-able-to-bethere. When Da-sein is imminent to itself as this possibility, it is completely thrown back upon its ownmost potentiality-of-being. Thus imminent to itself, all relations to other Da-sein are dissolved in it. This nonrelational ownmost possibility is at the same time the most extreme one. As a potentiality of being, Da-sein is unable to bypass the possibility of death. Death is the possibility of the absolute impossibility of Da-sein. Thus death reveals itself as the uwnmost nonrelational possibility not to be bypassed. As such, it is an eminent imminence. Its existential possibility is grounded in the fact that Da-sein is essentially disclosed to itself, in the way of being-ahead-of-itself. This structural factor of care has its most primordial concretion in being-toward-death. Being-toward-the-end becomes phenomenally clearer as being toward the eminent possibility of Dasein which we have characterized. The ownmost nonrelational possibility not to be bypassed is not created by Da-sein subsequently and occasionally in the course of its being. Rather, when Da-sein exists, it is already thrown into this possibility. Initially and for the most part, Da-sein does not have any explicit or even theoretical knowledge of the fact that it is delivered over to its death, and that death thus belongs to being-in-the-world. Thrownness into death reveals itself to it more primordially and penetratingly in the attunement of Ang.s-t. 8 Ang.s-t in the face of death is Ang.s-t "in the face of' the ownmost nonrelational potentiality-of-being not to be bypassed. What Ang.s-t is about is being-in-the-world itself. What Ang.s-t is about is the potentiality-of-being of Da-sein absolutely. Ang.s-t about death must not be confused with a fear of one's demise. It is not an arbitrary and chance "weak" mood of the individual, but, as a fundamental attunement of
11.1
Being and Time
233
Da-sein, the disclosedness of the fact that Da-sein exists as thrown beingThus the existential concept of dying is clarified as thrown being toward the ownmost nonrelational potentiality-of-being not to be bypassed. Precision is gained by distinguishing this from pure disappearance, and also from merely perishing, and finally from the "experience" of a demise. Being-toward-the-end does not first arise through some attitude which occasionally turns up, rather it belongs essentially to the thrownness of Da-sein which reveals itself in attunement (mood) in various ways. The factical "knowledge" or "lack of knowledge" prevalent in Dasein as to its ownmost being-toward-the-end is only the expression of the existentiell possibility of maintaining itself in this being in different ways. The fact that factically many people initially and for the most part do not know about death must not be used to prove that being-towarddeath does not "generally" belong to Da-sein, but only proves that Dasein, fleeingfrom it, initially and for the most part covers over its ownmost being-toward-death. Da-sein dies factically as long as it exists, but initially and for the most part in the mode of falling prey. For factical existing is not only generally and without further differentiation a thrown potentiality-for-being-in-the-world, but it is always already absorbed in the "world" taken care of. In this entangled being together with ... , the flight from uncanniness makes itself known, that is, the flight from its ownmost being-toward-death. Existence, facticity, falling prey characterize being-toward-the-end, and are accordingly constitutive for the existential concept of death. With regard to its ontological possibility, dying is grounded in care. * But if being toward death belongs primordially and essentially to the being of Da-sein, it must also be demonstrated in everydayness, although initially in an inauthentic way. And if being-toward-the-end is even supposed to offer the existential possibility for an existentiell wholeness of Da-sein, this would give the phenomenal confirmation for the thesis that care is the ontological term for the wholeness of the structural totality ofDa-sein. However, for the complete phenomenal justification of this statement, a preliminary sketch of the connection between beingtoward-death and care is not sufficient. Above all, we must be able to see this connection in the concretion nearest to Da-sein, its everydayness . toward-i~nd.
.51. Being-toward-Death and the Everydayness of Da-sein The exposition of everyday, average being-toward-death was oriented toward the structures of everydayness developed earlier. In being-
* But care presences out of the truth of being.
252
234
253
Being and Time
II.J
toward-death, Da-sein is related to itself as an eminent potentiality-ofbeing. But the self of everydayness is the they9 which is constituted in public interpretedness which expresses itself in idle talk. Thus, idle talk must make manifest in what way everyday Da-sein interprets its beingtoward-death. Understanding, which is also always attuned, that is, mooded, always forms the basis of this interpretation. Thus we must ask how the attuned understanding lying in the idle talk of the they has disclosed being-toward-death. How is the they related in an understanding way to its ownmost nonrelational possibility not-to-be-bypassed of Da-sein? What attunement discloses to the they that it has been delivered over to death, and in what way? The publicness of everyday being-with-one-another "knows" death as a constantly occurring event, as a "case of death." Someone or another "dies," be it a neighbor or a stranger. People unknown to us "die" daily and hourly. "Death" is encountered as a familiar event occurring within the world. As such, it remains in the inconspicuousness 10 characteristic of everyday encounters. The they has also already secured an interpretation for this event. The "fleeting" talk about this which is either expressed or else mostly kept back says: One also dies at the end, but for now one is not involved. The analysis of"one dies" reveals unambiguously the kind ofbeing of everyday being toward death. In such talk, death is understood as an indeterminate something which first has to show up from somewhere, but which right now is not yet objectively present for oneself, and is thus no threat. "One dies" spreads the opinion that death, so to speak, strikes the they. The public interpretation ofDa-sein says that "one dies" because in this way everybody can convince him/herself that in no case is it I myself, for this one is no one. "Dying" is levelled down to an event which does concern Da-sein, but which belongs to no one in particular. If idle talk is always ambiguous, so is this way of talking about death. Dying, which is essentially and irreplaceably mine, is distorted into a publicly occurring event which the they encounters. Characteristic talk speaks about death as a constantly occurring "case." It treats it as something always already "real," and veils its character of possibility and concomitantly the two factors belonging to it, that it is nonrelational and cannot-be-bypassed. With such ambiguity, Da-sein puts itself in the position of losing itself in the they with regard to an eminent potentiality-ofbeing that belongs to its own self. The they justifies and aggravates the temptation of covering over11 for itself its ownmost being-toward-death. The evasion of death which covers over, dominates everydayness so stubbornly that, in being-with-one-another, the "neighbors" often try to convince the "dying person" that he will escape death and soon return again to the tranquillized everydayness of his world taken care of. This
11.1
Being and Time
235
"concern" has the intention of thus "comforting" the "dying person." It wants to bring him back to Da-sein by helping him to veil completely his ownmost nonrelational possibility. Thus, the they makes sure of a constant tranquillization about death. But, basically, this tranquillization is not only for the "dying person," but just as much for "those who are comforting him." And even in the case of a demise, publicness is still not to be disturbed and made uneasy by the event in the carefreeness it has made sure of. Indeed, the dying of others is seen often as a social inconvenience, if not a downright tactlessness, from which publicness should be spared. 12 But along with this tranquillization, which keeps Da-sein away from its death, the they at the same time justifies itself and makes itself respectable by silently ordering the way in which one is supposed to behave toward death in general. Even "thinking about death" is regarded publicly as cowardly fear, a sigh of insecurity on the part of Da-sein and a dark flight from the world. The they does not permit the courage to have Angst about death. The dominance of the public interpretedness of the they has already decided what attunement is to determine our stance toward death. In Angst about death, Da-sein is brought before itself as delivered over to its possibility not-to-be-bypassed. The they is careful to distort this Angst into the fear of a future event. Angst, made ambiguous as fear, is, moreover, taken as a weakness which no self-assured Da-sein is permitted to know. What is "proper" according to the silent decree of the they is the indifferent calm as to the "fact" that one dies. The cultivation of such a "superior" indifference estranges Da-sein from its ownmost nonrelational potentiality-of-being. Temptation, tranquillization, and estrangement, however, characterize the kind of being offalling prey. Entangled, everyday being-towarddeath is a constant flight from death. Being toward the end has the mode of evading that end-reinterpreting it, understanding it inauthentically, and veiling it. Factically one's own Da-sein is always already dying, that is, it is in a being-toward-its-end. And it conceals this fact from itself by reinterpreting death as a case of death occurring every day with others, a case which always assures us still more clearly that "one oneself' is still "alive." But in the entangled flight from death, the everydayness of Dasein bears witness to the fact that the they itself is always already determined as being toward death, even when it is not explicitly engaged in "thinking about death." Even in average everydayness, Da-sein is constantly concerned with its ownmost nonrelational potentiality-ofbeing not-to-be-l:lypassed, if only in the mode of taking care of things in a mode of untroubled indifference toward the most extreme possibility of its existence. The exposition of everyday being-toward-death, however, gives us at the same time a directive to attempt to secure a complete existential
254
255
236
Being and Time
11.1
concept of being-toward-the-end, by a more penetrating interpretation in which entangled being-toward-death is taken as an evasion of death. That from which one flees has been made visible in a phenomenally adequate way. We should now be able to project phenomenologically how evasive Da-sein itself understands its death. 1s
52. Everyday Being-toward-Death and the Complete Existential Concept of Death
256
Being-toward-the-end was determined in a preliminary existential sketch as being toward one's ownmost nonrelational potentiality-of-being notto-be-bypassed. Existing being toward this possibility, brings itself before the absolute impossibility of existence. Beyond this seemingly empty characteristic of being-toward-death, the concretion of this being revealed itself in the mode of everydayness. In accordance with the tendency toward falling prey essential to everydayness, being-toward-death proved to be an evasion of it, an evasion that covers over. Whereas previously our inquiry made the transition from the formal preliminary sketch of the ontological structure of death to the concrete analysis of everyday being-toward-the-end, we now wish to reverse the direction and attain the complete existential concept of death with a supplementary interpretation of everyday being-toward-the-end. The explication of everyday being-toward-death stayed with the idle talk of the they: one also dies sometime, but for the time being not yet. Up to now we solely interpreted the "one dies" as such. In the "also sometime, but for the time being not yet," everydayness acknowledges something like a certainty of death. Nobody doubts that one dies. But this "not doubting" need not already imply that kind of being-certain that corresponds to the way death-in the sense of the eminent possibility characterized above-enters into Da-sein. Everydayness gets stuck in this ambiguous acknowledgment of the "certainty" of death-in order to weaken the certainty by covering dying over still more and alleviating its own thrownness into death. By its very meaning, this evasive covering over of death can not be authentically "certain" of death, and yet it is. How does it stand with this "certainty of death"? To be certain of a being means to hold it for true as something true. But truth means discoveredness of beings. All discoveredness, however, is ontologically based in the most primordial truth, in the disclosedness of Da-sein. 14 As a being that is disclosed and disclosing, and one that discovers, Da-sein is essentially "in the truth." But certainty is based in truth or belongs to it equiprimordially. The expression "certainty," like the expression "truth," has a double meaning. Primordially, truth
II. I
Being and Time
237
means the same as being-disclosive as a mode of behavior of Da-sein. From this comes the derivative meaning: disclosedness of beings. Accordingly, certainty is primordially tantamount to being-certain as a kind of being of Da-sein. However, in a derivative significance, any being of which Da-sein can be certain is also called "certain." One mode of certainty is conviction. In conviction, Da-sein lets the testimony of the thing itself that has been discovered (the true thing itself) be the sole determinant for its being toward that thing understandingly. Holding-something-for-true is adequate as a way of keeping oneself in the truth, if it is based on the discovered beings themselves, and as a being toward the beings thus discovered, has become transparent to itself with regard to its appropriateness to them. Something like this is lacking in any arbitrary invention or in the mere "opinion" about a being. The adequacy of holding-for-true is measured by the truth claim to which it belongs. This claim gets its justification from the kind of being of the beings to be disclosed, and from the direction of the disclosure. The kind of truth and, along with it, the certainty, changes with the various kinds of beings, and accords with the leading tendency and scope of the disclosure. Our present considerations are limited to an analysis of being-certain with regard to death; and this being-certain will, in the end, present us with an eminent certainty of Da-sein. For the most part, everyday Da-sein covers over its ownmost nonrelational possibility of being not-to-be-bypassed. This factical tendency to cover over confirms our thesis that Da-sein, as factical, is in "untruth." 15 Thus the certainty which belongs to such a covering over of being-toward-death must be an inappropriate way of holding-for-true, and not an uncertainty in the sense of doubting. Inappropriate certainty keeps that of which it is certain covered over. If "one" understands death as an event encountered in the surrounding world, the certainty related to this does not get at being-toward-the-end. They say that it is certain that "death" comes. They say it and overlook the fact that, in order to be able to be certain of death, Da-sein itself must always be certain of its ownmost nonrelational potentiality-of-being not-to-be-bypassed. They say that death is certain, and thus entrench in Da-sein the illusion that it is itself certain of its own death. And what is the ground of everyday being-certain? Evidently it is not just mutual persuasion. Yet one experiences daily the "dying" of others. Death is an undeniable "fact of experience." The way in which everyday being-toward-death understands the certainty thus grounded, betrays itself when it tries to "think" about death, even when it does so with critical foresight-that is to say, in an appropriate way. So far as one knows, all human beings "die." Death is
257
238
258
Being and Time
11.1
probable to the highest degree for every human being, yet it is not "unconditionally" certain. Strictly speaking, "only" an empirical certainty may be attributed to death. Such certainty falls short of the highest certainty, the apodictical one, which we attain in certain areas of theoretical knowledge. In this "critical" determination of the certainty of death and its imminence, what is manifested in the first instance is, once again, the failure to recognize the kind of being of Da-sein and the being-towarddeath belonging to it, a failure characteristic of everydayness. The fact that demise, as an event that occurs, is "only" empirically certain, in no way decides about the certainty of death. Cases of death may be the factical occasion for the fact that Da-sein initially notices death at all. But, remaining within the empirical certainty which we characterized, Dasein cannot become certain at all of death as it "is." Although in the publicness of the they Da-sein seemingly "talks" only of this "empirical" certainty of death, basically it does not keep exclusively and primarily to those cases of death that merely occur. Evading its death, everyday beingtoward-the-end is indeed certain of death in another way than it itself would like to realize in purely theoretical considerations. For the most part, everydayness veils this from itself "in another way." It does not dare to become transparent to itself in this way. We have already characterized the everyday attunement that consists in an air of superiority with regard to the certain "fact" of death-a superiority that is "anxiously" concerned while seemingly free of Angst. In this attunement, everydayness acknowledges a "higher" certainty than the merely empirical one. One knows about the certainty of death, and yet "is" not really certain about it. The entangled everydayness of Da-sein knows about the certainty of death, and yet avoids being-certain. But in the light of what it evades, this evasion bears witness phenomenally to the fact that death must be grasped as the ownmost nonrelational, certain possibility not-to-be-bypassed. One says that death certainly comes, but not right away. With this "but ... , the they denies that death is certain. "Not right away" is not a purely negative statement, but a self-interpretation of the they with which it refers itself to what is initially accessible to Da-sein to take care of. Everydayness penetrates to the urgency of taking care of things, and divests itself of the fetters of a weary, "inactive thinking about death." Death is postponed to "sometime later," by relying on the socalled "general opinion." Thus the they covers over what is peculiar to the certainty of death, that it is possible in every moment. Together with the certainty of death goes the indefiniteness of its when. Everyday beingtoward-death evades this indefiniteness by making it something definite. But this procedure cannot mean calculating when the demise is due
11.1
Being and Time
239
to arrive. Da-sein rather flees from such definiteness. Everyday taking care of things makes definite for itself the indefiniteness of certain death by interposing before it those manageable urgencies and possibilities of the everyday matters nearest to us. But covering over this indefiniteness also covers over certainty. Thus the ownmost character of the possibility of death gets covered over: a possibility that is certain, and yet indefinite, that is, possible at any moment. Now that we have completed our interpretation of the everyday talk of the they about death and the way death enters Da-sein, we have been led to the characteristics of certainty and indefiniteness. The full existential and ontological concept of death can now be defined as follows: As the end of Da-sein, death is the uum:most nonrelationa~ certain, and, as such, indefinite and not to be bypassed possibility of Da-sein. As the end of Dasein, death is in the being of this being-toward-its-end. The delineation of the existential structure of being-toward-theend helps us to develop a kind of being of Da-sein in which it can be wholly as Da-sein. The fact that even everyday Da-sein is always already toward its end, that is, is constantly coming to grips with its own death, even though "fleetingly," shows that this end, which concludes and defines being-whole, is not something which Da-sein ultimately arrives at only in its demise. In Da-sein, existing toward its death, its most extreme not-yet which everything else precedes is always already included. So if one has given an ontologically inappropriate interpretation of the not-yet of Da-sein as something outstanding, any formal inference from this to the lack of totality of Da-sein will be incorrect. The phenomenon of the not1et has been taken from the ahead-ofitself; no more than the structure of care in genera~ can it seroe as a higher court that would rule against a possible, existent wholeness; indeed, this ahead-ofitself first makes possible such a beingtoward-the-end. The problem of the possible wholeness of the being which we ourselves actually are exists justifiably if care, as the fundamental constitution of Da-sein, "is connected" with death as the most extreme possibility of this being. Yet it remains questionable whether this problem has been as yet adequately developed. Being-toward-death is grounded in care. As thrown being-in-the-world, Da-sein is always already delivered over to its death. Being toward its death, it dies factically and constantly as long as it has not reached its demise. That Da-sein dies factically means at the same time that it has always already decided in this or that way in its being-toward-death. Everyday, entangled evasion of death is an inauthentic being toward it. Inauthenticity has possible authenticity as its basis. 16 Inauthenticity characterizes the kind of being in which Da-sein diverts itself and for the most part has always diverted itself, too, but it
259
240
260
Being and Time
II.I
does not have to do this necessarily and constantly. Because Da-sein exists, it determines itself as the kind of being it is, and it does so always in terms of a possibility which it itself is and understands. Can Da-sein authentically understand its ownmost, nonrelational, certain possibility not-to-be-bypassed that is, as such, indefinite? That is, can it maintain itself in an authentic being-toward-its-end? As long as this authentic being-toward-death has not been set forth and ontologically determined, there is something essentially lacking in our existential interpretation of being-toward-the-end. Authentic being-toward-death signifies an existentiell possibility of Da-sein. This ontic potentiality-of-being must in its tum be ontologically possible. What are the existential conditions of this possibility? How are they themselves to become accessible?
53. Existential Project of an Authentic Being-toward-Death Factically, Da-sein maintains itself initially and for the most part in an inauthentic being-toward-death. How is the ontological possibility of an authentic being-toward-death to be characterized "objectively," if, in the end, Da-sein is never authentically related to its end, or if this authentic being must remain concealed from others in accordance with its meaning? Is not the project of the existential possibility of such a questionable existentiell potentiality-of-being a fantastical undertaking? What is needed for such a project to get beyond a merely poetizing, arbitrary construction? Does Da-sein itself provide directives for this project? Can the grounds for its phenomenal justification be taken from Da-sein itself? Can our analysis of Da-sein up to now give us any prescriptions for the ontological task we have now formulated, so that what we have before us can be kept on a secure path? The existential concept of death has been established, and thus we have also established that to which an authentic being-toward-the-end should be able to relate itself. Furthermore, we have also characterized inauthentic being-toward-death and thus we have prescribed how authentic being-toward-death cannot be in a negative way. The existential structure of an authentic being-toward-death must let itself be projected with these positive and prohibitive instructions. Da-sein is constituted by disclosedness, that is, by attuned understanding. Authentic being-toward-death cannot evade its ownmost nonrelational possibility or cover it over in this flight and reinterpret it for the common sense of the they. The existential project of an authentic beingtoward-death must thus set forth the factors of such a being which are constitutive for it as an understanding of death-in the sense of being toward this possibility without fleeing it or covering it over.
II. I
Being and Time
241
First of all, we must characterize being-toward-death as a being toward a possibility, toward an eminent possibility of Da-sein itself. Being toward a possibility, that is, toward something possible, can mean to be out for something possible, as in taking care of its actualization. In the field of things at hand and objectively present, we constantly encounter such possibilities: what is attainable, manageable, viable, and so forth. Being out for something possible and taking care of it has the tendency of annihilating the possibility of the possible by making it available. The actualization of useful things at hand in taking care of them (producing them, getting them ready, readjusting them, etc.), is, however, always merely relative, in that what has been actualized still has the character of being relevant. Even when actualized, as something actual it remains possible for ... , it is characterized by an in-order-to. Our present analysis should simply make clear how being out for something and taking care of it, is related to the possible. It does so not in a thematic and theoretical reflection on the possible as possible, or even with regard to its possibility as such, but rather in such a way that it circumspectly looks away from the possible to what it is possible for. Evidently being-toward-death, which is now in question, cannot have the character of being out for something and taking care of it with a view toward its actualization. For one thing, death as something possible is not a possible thing at hand or objectively present, but a possibility-of-being of Da-sein. Then, however, taking care of the actualization of what is thus possible would have to mean bringing about one's own demise. Thus Da-sein would precisely deprive itself of the very ground for an existing being-toward-death. Thus if being-toward-death is not meant as an "actualization" of death, neither can it mean to dwell near the end in its possibility. This kind of behavior would amount to "thinking about death," thinking about this possibility, how and when it might be actualized. Brooding over death does not completely take away from it its character of possibility. It is always brooded over as something coming, but we weaken it by calculating how to have it at our disposal. As something possible, death is supposed to show as little as possible of its possibility. On the contrary, if being-toward-death has to disclose understandingly the possibility which we have characterized as such, then in such being-towarddeath this possibility must not be weakened, it must be understood as possibility, cultivated as possibility, and endured as possibility in our relation to it. However, Da-sein relates to something possible in its possibility, by expecting it. Anyone who is intent on something possible, may encounter it unimpeded and undiminished in its "whether it comes or not, or whether it comes after all." But with this phenomenon of expecting has
261
262
242
263
Being and Time
II. I
our analysis not reached the same kind of being toward the possible which we already characterized as being out for something and taking care of it? To expect something possible is always to understand and "have" it with regard to whether and when and how it will really be objectively present. Expecting is not only an occasional looking away from the possible to its possible actualization, but essentially a waitingfor that actualization. Even in expecting, one leaps away from the possible and gets a footing in the real. It is for its reality that what is expected is expected. By the very nature of expecting, the possible is drawn into the real, arising from it and returning to it. But being toward this possibility, as being-toward-death, should relate itself to that death so that it reveals itself, in this being and for it, as possibility. Terminologically, we shall formulate this being toward possibility as anticipation of this possibility. But does not this mode of behavior contain an approach to the possible, and does not its actualization emerge with its nearness? In this kind of coming near, however, one does not tend toward making something real available and taking care of it, but as one comes nearer understandingly, the possibility of the possible only becomes "greater." The nearest nearness of being-toward-death as possibility is as far removed as possible from anything real. The more clearly this possibility is understood, the more purely does understanding penetrate to it as the possibility of the impossibility of existence in general. As possibility, death gives Da-sein nothing to "be actualized" and nothing which it itself could be as something real. It is the possibility of the impossibility of every mode of behavior toward ... , of every way of existing. In running ahead to this possibility, it becomes "greater and greater," that is, it reveals itself as something which knows no measure at all, no more or less, but means the possibility of the measureless impossibility of existence. Essentially, this possibility offers no support for becoming intent on something, for "spelling out" the real thing that is possible and so forgetting its possibility. As anticipation of possibility, being-toward-death first makes this possibility possible and sets it free as possibility. Being-toward-death is the anticipation of a potentiality-of-being of that being whose kind of being is anticipation itself. In the anticipatory revealing of this potentiality-of-being, Da-sein discloses itself to itself with regard to its most extreme possibility. But to project oneself upon one's ownmost potentiality of being means to be able to understand oneself in the being of the being thus revealed: to exist. Anticipation shows itself as the possibility of understanding one's ownmost and extreme potentiality-of-being, that is, as the possibility of authentic existen.ce. Its ontological constitution must be made visible by setting forth the concrete structure of anticipation of death. How is the phenomenal
11.1
Being and Time
243
definition of this structure to be accomplished? Evidently by defining the characteristics of anticipatory disclosure which must belong to it so that it can become the pure understanding of the owiunost nonrelational possibility not-to-be-bypassed which is certain and, as such, indefinite. We must remember that understanding does not primarily mean staring at a meaning, but understanding oneself in the potentiality-of-being that reveals itself in the project. 17 Death is the ownmost possibility of Da-sein. Being toward it discloses to Da-sein its ownmost potentiality-of-being in which it is concerned about the being of Da-sein absolutely. Here the fact can become evident to Da-sein that in the eminent possibility of itself it is torn away from the they, that is, anticipation can always already have torn itself away from the they. The understanding of this "ability," however, first reveals its facticallostness in the everydayness of the they-self. The ownmost possibility is nonrelational. Anticipation lets Da-sein understand that it has to take over solely from itself the potentiality-ofbeing in which it is concerned absolutely about its ownmost being. Death does not just "belong" in an undifferentiated way to one's own Da-sein, but it lays claim on it as something individual. The nonrelational character of death understood in anticipation individualizes Dasein down to itself. This individualizing is a way in which the "there" is disclosed for existence. It reveals the fact that any being-together-with what is taken care of and any being-with the others fails when one's ownmost potentiality-of-being is at stake. Da-sein can authentically be itself only when it makes that possible of its own accord. But if taking care of things and being concerned fail us, this does not, however, mean at all that these modes of Da-sein have been cut off from its authentic being a self. As essential structures of the constitution of Da-sein they also belong to the condition of the possibility of existence in general. Dasein is authentically itself only if it projects itself, as being-together with things taken care of and concernful being-with ... , primarily upon its ownmost potentiality-of-being, rather than upon the possibility of the they-self. Anticipation of its nonrelational possibility forces the being that anticipates into the possibility of taking over its ownmost being of its own accord. The ownmost nonrelational possibility is not to be bypassed. Being toward this possibility lets Da-sein understand that the most extreme possibility of existence is imminent, that of giving itself up. But anticipation does not evade the impossibility of bypassing death, as does inauthentic being-toward-death, but frees itselffor it. Becoming free for one's own death in anticipation frees one from one's lostness in chance possibilities urging themselves upon us, so that the factical possibilities lying before the possibility not-to-be-bypassed can first be authentically under-
264
244
265
Being and Time
11.1
stood and chosen. Anticipation discloses to existence that its extreme inmost possibility lies in giving itself up and thus shatters all one's clinging to whatever existence one has reached. In anticipation, Da-sein guards itself against falling back behind itself, or behind the potentialityfor-being that it has understood. It guards against "becoming too old for its victories" (Nietzsche). Free for its ownmost possibilities, that are determined by the end, and so understood as finite, Da-sein prevents the danger that it may, by its own finite understanding of existence, fail to recognize that it is getting overtaken by the existence-possibilities of others, or that it may misinterpret these possibilities, thus divesting itself of its owrunost factical existence. As the nonrelational possibility, death individualizes, but only, as the possibility not-to-be-bypassed, in order to make Da-sein as being-with understand the potentialities-ofbeing of the others. Because anticipation of the possibility not-to-bebypassed also disclosed all the possibilities lying before it, this anticipation includes the possibility of taking the whole of Da-sein in advance in an existentiell way, that is, the possibility of existing as a whole potentiality-ofbeing. The ownmost nonrelational possibility not-to-be-bypassed is certain. The mode of being certain of it is determined by the truth (disclosedness) corresponding to it. But Da-sein discloses the certain possibility of death as possibility only by making this possibility as its owrunost potentiality-of-being possible in anticipating it. The disclosedness of this possibility is grounded in a making possible that anticipates. Holding oneself in this truth, that is, being certain of what has been disclosed, lays claim all the more upon anticipation. The certainty of death cannot be calculated in terms of ascertaining cases of death encountered. This certainty by no means holds itself in the truth of something objectively present. When something objectively present has been discovered, it is encountered most purely by just looking at it and letting it be encountered in itself. Da-sein must first have lost itself in the factual circumstances (this can be one of care's own tasks and possibilities) if it is to gain the pure objectivity, that is, the indifference of apodictic evidence. If being-certain in relation to death does not have this character, that does not mean it is of a lower grade, but that it does not belong at all to the order of degrees of evidence about things objectively present. Holding death for true (death is always just one's own) shows a different kind of certainty, and is more primordial than any certainty related to beings encountered in the world or to formal objects, for it is certain of being-in-the-world. As such, it claims not only one definite kind of behavior of Da-sein, but claims Da-sein in the complete authenticity of its existence. 18 In anticipation, Da-sein can first make certain of its ownmost being in its totality not-to-be-bypassed. Thus, the evidence of
II. I
Being and Time
245
the immediate givenness of experiences, of the ego or of consciousness, necessarily has to lag behind the certainty contained in anticipation. And yet this is not because the kind of apprehension belonging to it is not sUict enough, but because at bottom it cannot hold for true (disclosed) something that it basically insists upon "having there" as true: namely, the Da-sein which I myself am and can be as potentiality-ofbeing authentically only in anticipation. The ownmost nonrelational possibility not-to-be-bypassed is indefinite with regard to its certainty. How does anticipation disclose this character of the eminent possibility of Da-sein? How does understanding, anticipating, project itself upon a definite potentiality-of-being which is constantly possible in such a way that the when in which the absolute impossibility of existence becomes possible remains constantly indefinite? In anticipating the indefinite certainty of death, Da-sein opens itself to a constant threat arising from its own there. Being-toward-the-end must hold itself in this very threat, and can so little phase it out that it rather has to cultivate the indefiniteness of the certainty. How is the genuine disclosing of this constant threat existentially possible? All understanding is attuned. Mood brings Da-sein before the thrownness of its "that-it-is-there." 19 But the attunement which is able to hold open the constant and absolute threat to itself arising from the ownmost individualized being of Dasein is Angst. 20 In Angst, Da-sein fmds itselffaced with the nothingness of the possible impossibility of its existence. Angst is anxious about the potentiality-of-being of the being thus determined, and thus discloses the most extreme possibility. Because the anticipation of Da-sein absolutely individualizes and lets it, in this individualizing of itself, become certain of the wholeness of its potentiality-of-being, the fundamental attunement of Angst belongs to this self-understanding of Da-sein in terms of its ground. Being-toward-death is essentially Angst.* This is attested unmistakably, although "only" indirectly, by being-toward-death as we characterized it, when it distorts Angst into cowardly fear and, in overcoming that fear, only makes known its own cowardliness in the face of Angst. What is characteristic about authentic, existentially projected beingtoward-death can be summarized as follows: Anticipation reveals to Da-sein its lostness in the they-self, and brings it face to face with the possibility to be itself, primarily unsupported by concern taking care of things, but to be itself in passionate anxious freedom toward death which is free of the illusions of the they, factica~ and certain of itself. All relations, belonging to being-toward-death, to the complete content of the most extreme possibility of Da-sein, constitute an antici-
* I.e., but not only Angs-t and certainly not Angs-t as a mere emotion.
266
246
267
Being and Time
11.1
pation that they combine in revealing, unfolding, and holding fast, as that which makes this possibility possible. The existential project in which anticipation has been delimited, has made visible the ontological possibility of an existentiell, authentic being-toward-death. But with this, the possibility then appears of an authentic potentiality-for-being-awhole-but only as an ontological possibility. Of course, our existential project of anticipation stayed with those structures of Da-sein gained earlier and let Da-sein itself, so to speak, project itself upon this possibility, without proffering to Da-sein the "content" of an ideal of existence forced upon it "from the outside." And yet this existentially "possible" being-toward-death remains, after all, existentielly a fantastical demand. The ontological possibility of an authentic potentiality-for-being-a-whole of Da-sein means nothing as long as the corresponding ontic potentialityof-being has not been shown in terms of Da-sein itself. Does Da-sein ever project itself factically into such a being-toward-death? Does it even demand, on the basis of its ownmost being, an authentic potentiality of being which is determined by anticipation? Before answering these questions, we must investigate to what extent at all and in what way Da-sein bears witness to a possible authenticity of its existence from its ownmost potentiality-of-being, in such a way that it not only makes this known as existentielly possible, but demands it of itself. The question hovering over us of an authentic wholeness of Dasein and its existential constitution can be placed on a viable, phenomenal basis only if that question can hold fast to a possible authenticity of its being attested by Da-sein itself. If we succeed in discovering phenomenologically such an attestation and what is attested to in it, the problem arises again of whether the anticipation of death projected up to now only in its ontological possibility has an essential connection with that authentic potentiality-ofbeing attested to.
II The Attestation of Da-sein of an Authentic Potentiality-ofBeing, and Resoluteness
54. The Problem of the Attestation of an Authentic Existentiell Possibility We are looking for an authentic potentiality-of-being of Da-sein that is attested by Da-sein itself in its existentiell possibility. First of all, we have to find this attestation itself.* If it is to "give Da-sein to understand" itself in its possible authentic existence, it will have its roots in the being of Da-sein. The phenomenal demonstration of such an attestation thus contains the evidence of its origin from the constitution of being of Dasein. The attestation is to give us to understand an authentic potentialityof-being-ones-self. With the expression "self," we answered the question of the who of Da-sein. 1 The selfhood of Da-sein was defmed formally as a way of existing, that is, not as a being objectively present. I myself am not for the most part the who of Da-sein, but the they-self is. Authentic being-aself shows itself to be an existentiell modification of the they which is to be defined existentially. 2 What does this modification imply, and what are the ontological conditions of its possibility? With the lostness in the they, the nearest, factical potentiality-ofbeing of Da-sein has always already been decided upon-tasks, rules,
* (1) What attests as such. (2) What is attested by it. 247
268
248
269
Being and Time
11.11
standards, the urgency and scope of being-in-the-world, concerned and taking care of things. The they has always already taken the apprehension of these possibilities-of-being away from Da-sein. The they even conceals the way it has silently disburdened Da-sein of the explicit choice of these possibilities. It remains indefinite who is "really" choosing. So Da-sein is taken along by the no one, without choice, and thus gets caught up in inauthenticity. This process can be reversed only in such a way that Da-sein explicitly brings itself back to itself from its lostness in the they. But this bringing-back must have the kind of being by the neglect of which Da-sein has lost itself in inauthenticity. When Da-sein thus brings itself back from the they, the they-self is modified in an existentiell manner so that it becomes authentic being-one's-self. This must be accomplished by making up for not choosing. But making up for not choosing signifies choosing to make this choice-deciding for a potentiality-of-being, and making this decision from one's own self. In choosing to make this choice, Da-sein makes possible, first and foremost, its authentic potentiality-of-being.* But because Da-sein is lost in the "they," it must first find itself. In order to find itself at all, it must be "shown" to itself in its possible authenticity. In terms of its possibility, Da-sein is already a potentiality-forbeing-its-self, but it needs to have this potentiality attested. In the following interpretation, we shall claim that this potentiality is attested by that which, in the everyday interpretation of itself, Dasein is familiar to us as the "voice of conscience. "3 That the very "fact" of conscience has been disputed, that its function as a higher court for Da-sein's existence has been variously assessed, and that "what conscience says" has been interpreted in manifold ways-all this might only mislead us into dismissing this phenomenon if the very "doubtfulness" of this fact-or of the way in which it has been interpreted-did not precisely prove that here a primordial phenomenon of Da-sein lies before us. In the following analysis, conscience will be taken as something which we have in advance thematically, and it will be investigatedt in a purely existential manner, with fundamental ontology as our aim. We shall first trace conscience back to its existential foundations and structures and make it visible as a phenomenon of Da-sein, holding fast to what we have hitherto arrived at as that being's constitution of being. The ontological analysis of conscience started in this way is prior to any psychological description and classification of experiences of conscience, just as it lies outside any biological "explanation," that is, dissolution of this phenomenon. But it is no less distant from a theological *a taking place of being-philosophy, freedom. More radically now in terms of the essence of philosophizing.
t
11.11
Being and Time
249
exegesis of conscience or any employment of this phenomenon for proofs of God's existence or an "immediate" consciousness of God. Still, in our restricted inquiry into conscience, we must neither exaggerate its importance nor make distorted claims about it and lessen its worth. As a phenomenon of Da-sein, conscience is not a fact that occurs and is occasionally objectively present. It "is" only in the kind of being of Da-sein and makes itself known as a fact only in factical existence. The demand for an "inductive, empirical proof' for the "factuality" of conscience and for the legitimacy of its "voice" is based on an ontological distortion of the phenomenon. But this distortion is also shared by every superior critique of conscience as something that occurs only at times rather than as a "universally established and ascertainable fact." The fact of conscience cannot be coupled with such proofs and counter-proofs at all. That is not a lack, but only the sign of its ontological character that is different from objectively present things in the surrounding world. Conscience gives us "something" to understand, it discloses. From this formal characteristic arises the directive to take this phenomenon back into the disclosedness of Da-sein. This fundamental constitution of the being that we ourselves actually are is constituted by attunement, understanding, falling prey, and discourse. A more penetrating analysis of conscience reveals it as a call. Calling is a mode of discourse. The call of conscience has the character of summoning Da-sein to its ownmost potentiality-of-being-aself, by summoning it to its ownmost quality of being a lack.4 But this existential interpretation is necessarily a far cry from everyday, ontic common sense, although it sets forth the ontological foundations of what the vulgar interpretation of conscience has always understood in certain limits and has conceptualized as a "theory" of conscience. Thus our existential interpretation needs to be confirmed by a critique of the vulgar interpretation of conscience. When this phenomenon has been exhibited, we can bring out to what extent it bears witness to an authentic potentiality-of-being ofDa-sein. To the call of conscience there corresponds a possible hearing. Understanding the summons reveals itself as wanting to have a conscience. But in this phenomenon lies that existentiell choosing of the choice of being-a-self which we are looking for and which we call r~soluteness5 in accordance with its existential structure. Thus we have the divisions of the analyses of this chapter: the existential and ontological foundations of conscience (section 55); the character of conscience as a call (section 56); conscience as the call of care (section 57); understanding the summons and being a lack (section 58); the existential interpretation of conscience and the vulgar interpretation of conscience (section 59); the existential structure of the authentic potentiality-of-being attested to in conscience (section 60).
270
250
Being and Time
11.11
55. The Existential and Ontological Foundations* of Conscience
271
The analysist of conscience will start out with an undifferentiated fact about this phenomenon, the fact that it somehow gives one to understand something. Conscience discloses, and thus belongs to the scope of the existential phenomena which constitute the being of the there as disclosedness.6 We have analyzed the most general structures of attunement, understanding, discourse, and falling prey. If we put conscience in this phenomenal context, this is not a matter of a schematic application of the structures gained there to a particular "case" of the disclosure of Da-sein. Rather, our interpretation of conscience will not only continue the earlier analysis of the disclosedness of the there, but will grasp it more primordially with regard to the authentic being of Da-sein. Through disclosedness, the being that we call Da-sein is in the possibility of being its there. It is there for itself, together with its world, initially and for the most part in such a way that it has disclosed its potentiality-ofbeing in terms of the "world" taken care of. The potentiality-of-being as which Da-sein exists has always already given itself over to definite possibilities. And this is the case because it is a thrown being, and its thrownness is disclosed more or less clearly and penetratingly by being attuned. Understanding belongs equiprimordially to attunement (mood). In this way Da-sein "knows"t where it stands, since it has projected itself upon possibilities of itself, or, absorbed in the they, has let itselfbe given such possibilities as are prescribed by its public interpretedness. But this prescription is existentially possible through the fact that Da-sein as understanding being-with can listen§ to others. Losing itself in the publicness of the they and its idle talk, it fails to hear its own self in listening to the theyself. If Da-sein is to be brought back from this lostness of failing to hear itself, and if this is to be done through itself, it must first be able to find itself, to find itself as something that has failed to hear itself and continues to do so in listening to the they. This listening must be stopped, that is, the possibility of another kind of hearing that interrupts that listening must be given by Da-sein itself. The possibility of such a breach lies in being summoned immediately. Da-sein fails to hear itself, and listens to the they, and this listening gets broken by the call if
*Horizon. Many things are involved here: ( 1) The call of what we call conscience. (2) Being called. (3) The experience of being. (4) The usual, traditional interpretation. (5) The way of coming to terms with it. t Or thinks it knows. § Where does this listening and being able to listen come from? Sensuous listening with the ears is a thrown mode of being affected. t
Being and Time
II. II
251
that call, in accordance with its character as call, arouses another kind of hearing which, in relation to the hearing that is lost, has a character in every way opposite. If this lost hearing is numbed by the "noise" of the manifold ambiguity of everyday "new" idle talk, the call must call silendy, unambiguously, with no foothold for curiosity. What this gives us to understand in calling is conscience. We take calling as a mode of discourse. Discourse articulates intelligibility. What is characteristic about conscience as a call is by no means only an "image," like the Kantian representation of conscience as a court of justice. We must only not overlook the fact that vocal utterance is not essential to discourse, and thus not for the call either. Every speaking and "calling out" already presupposes discourse.' If the everyday interpretation knows about a "voice" of conscience, it is thinking not so much about an utterance, which can factically never be found,* but "voice" is understood as giving-to-understand. In the tendency toward disclosure of the call lies the factor of a jolt, of an abrupt arousal. t The call calls from afar to afar. It reaches him who wants to be brought back.t But with this characterization of conscience, only the phenomenal horizon for the analysis of its existential structure has been oudined. We are not comparing this phenomenon with a call, but we are understanding it as discourse, in terms of the disclosedness constitutive for Dasein. Our reflection avoids from the very beginning the path which initially offers itself for an interpretation of conscience: one traces conscience back to a faculty of the soul, understanding, will, or feeling, or explains it as the product of a mixture of these. In view of a ph~ nomenon such as conscience,§ what is ontologically and anthropologically inadequate about an unattached framework of classified facult!~s of the soul or personal acts becomes painfully obvious.8
56. The Character of Conscience as a Call To discourse belongs what is talked about in it. Discourse gives information about something in a certain respect. It draws from what is thus talked about what it actually says as this discourse, what is said as such. In discourse as communication, this becomes accessible to the Mitda-sein of others, mosdy by way of utterance in language.
* We don't "hear" it with the senses. But it stops us, too. Who has distanced himself from his own self. § Namely, in view of its origin in being-a-self, but is this not just an assertion so far?
t
~
272
252
273
Being and Time
11.11
What is what is talked about in the call of conscience, what is summoned? Evidently Da-sein itself. This answer is just as incontestable as it is indefinite. If the call had such a vague goal, it would still be an occasion for Da-sein to pay heed to itself. But to Da-sein essentially belongs the fact that it is disclosed to itself with the disclosedness of its world, so that it always already understands itself. The call reaches Da-sein in this always-already-understanding-itself in everyday, average taking care of things. The call reaches the they-self of heedful being-with with others. And to what is one summonded? To one's oum self. Not to what Dasein is, can do, and takes care of in everyday being-with-one-another, not even to what has moved it, what it has pledged itself to, what it has let itself be involved with. Understood in a worldly way for others and for itself, Da-sein is passed over in this call. The call to the self does not take the slightest notice of all this. Because only the self of the they-self is summoned and made to hear, the they collapses. The fact that the call passes over both the they and the public interpretedness of Da-sein by no means signifies that it has also not been reached. Precisely in passing over the they, the call pushed it (adamant as it is about public recognition) into insignificance. But, robbed of its refuge and this subterfuge by the summons, the self is brought to itself by the call. The they-self is summoned to the self. However, this is not the self that can become an "object" for itself on which to pass judgment, not the self that unrestrainedly dissects its "inner life" with excited curiosity, and not the self that stares "analytically" at states of the soul and their backgrounds. The summons of the self in the they-self does not force it inwards upon itself so that it can close itself off from the "external world." The call passes over all this and disperses it, so as to summon solely the self which is in no other way than being-in-the-world. But how are we to define what is spoken in this discourse? What does conscience call to the one summoned? Strictly speaking-nothing. The call does not say anything, does not give any information about events of the world, has nothing to tell. Least of all does it strive to open a "conversation with itself' in the self which has been summoned. "Nothing" is called to the self which is summoned, but it is summoned to itself, that is, to its ownmost potentiality-of-being. In accordance with its tendency as call, the call does not mandate a "trial" for the self which has been summoned, but as a summons to the ownmost potentiali~f-being a-self, it calls Da-sein forth (ahead-of-itself) to its most unique possibilities. The call is lacking any kind of utterance. It does not even come to words, and yet it is not at all obscure and indefinite. Conscience speaks solely and constantly in the mode ofsilence. Thus it not only loses none of its
Being and Time
11.11
253
perceptibility, but forces Da-sein thus summoned and called upon to the reticence of itself. The fact that what is called in the call is lacking a formulation in words does not shunt this phenomenon into the indefiniteness of a mysterious voice, but only indicates that the understanding of "what is called" may not cling to the expectation of a communication or any such thing. What the call discloses is nevertheless unequivocal, even if it gets interpreted in different ways in individual Da-sein in accordance with its possibilities of being understood. Whereas the content of the call is seemingly indefinite, the direction it takes is a sure one and is not to be overlooked. The call does not need to search gropingly for someone to be summoned, nor does it need a sign showing whether it is he who is meant or not. "Deceptions" occur in conscience not by an oversight of the call (a mis-calling) but only because the call is heard in such a way that, instead of being understood authentically, it is drawn by the theyself into a manipulative conversation with one's self and is distorted in its character of disclosure. We must remember that when we designate conscience as a call, this call is a summons to the they-self in its self. As this summons, it is the summons of the self to its potentiality-of-being-a-self, and thus calls Dasein forth to its possibilities. But we shall not obtain an ontologically adequate interpretation of conscience until we can clarify not only who is called by the call, but who calls, how the one who is summoned is related to the caller, how this "relation" is to be grasped ontologically as a connection of being.
274
57. Conscience a.s the Call of Care Conscience calls the self of Da-sein forth from its lostness in the they. The self summoned remains indifferent and empty in its what. The call passes over what Da-sein understands itself as initially and for the most part in its interpretation in terms of taking care of things. And yet the self is unequivocally and unmistakably reached. Not only is the call meant for him who is summoned "without regard to his person," the caller, too, remains in a striking indefiniteness. It not only fails to answer questions about name, status, origin, and repute, but also leaves not the slightest possibility of making the call familiar for an understanding of Da-sein with a "worldly" orientation. On the other hand, it by no means disguises itself in the call. The caller of the call-and this belongs to its phenomenal character-absolutely distances any kind of becoming familiar. It goes against its kind of being to be drawn into any consideration and talk. The peculiar indefiniteness and indefinability of the caller are not nothing, but a positive distinction. It lets us know that the
275
254
276
Being and Time
11.11
caller uniquely coincides with summoning to ... , that it wants to be heard only as such, and not be chattered about any further. But is it then not suitable to the phenomenon to leave unasked the question of who the caller is? Yes, for the e:xistentiell way of listening to the factical call of conscience, but not for the existential analysis of the facticity of calling and the e:xistentiality of hearing. But is it at all necessary to keep raising explicitly the question of who is calling? Is this not answered for Da-sein just as unequivocally as the question whom the call summons? Da-sein calls itself in conscience. This understanding of the caller may be more or less awakened in factically hearing the call. However, ontologically it is not enough to answer that Da-sein is the caller and the one summoned at the same time. When Da-sein is summoned, is it not "there" in another way from that in which it does the calling? Is it perhaps the ownmost potentiality-of-being that functions as the caller? The call is precisely something that we ourselves have neither planned nor prepared for nor willfully brought about. "It" calls, against our expectations and even against our will. On the other hand, the call without doubt does not come from someone else who is with me in the world. The calls comes from me, and yet over me. These phenomenal findings are not to be explained away. They were also taken as the point of departure for interpreting the voice of conscience as an alien power entering Da-sein. Continuing in this direction of interpretation, one supplies an owner for the power thus localized, or else one takes that power as person (God) making himself known. Conversely, one tries to reject this interpretation of the caller as the expression of an alien power and at the same time to explain conscience away "biologically." Both interpretations hastily pass over the phenomenal findings. Such procedures are made easier by the unspoken, but ontologically guiding dogmatic thesis that what is (that is, anything so factual as the call) must be objectively present; what cannot be demonstrated as objectively present just is not at all. As opposed to this methodical hastiness, we want not only to hold on to the phenomenal findings in general-the fact that the call, coming from me and over me, reaches me-but also to the implication that this phenomenon is here delineated ontologically as a phenomenon of Da-sein. The existential constitution of this being can offer the sole guideline for the interpretation of the kind of being of the "it" that calls. Does our previous analysis of the constitution of the being of Dasein show a way of making ontologically intelligible the kind of being of the caller, and thus also that of calling? The fact that the call is not explicitly brought about by me, but rather, "it" calls, does not justify
11.11
Being and Time
255
looking for the caller in a being unlike Da-sein. Da-sein, after all, always exists factically. It is not an unattached self-projection, but its character is determined by thrownness as a fact of the being that it is, and so determined, it has always already been delivered over to existence, and remains so constantly. But the facticity of Da-sein is essentially distinguished from the factuality of something objectively present. Existing Dasein does not encounter itself as something objectively present within the world. But neither is thrownness attached to Da-sein as an inaccessible quality that is of no importance to its existence. As thrown, Da-sein has been thrown into existence. It exists as a being that has to be as it is andean be. That it factically is, might be concealed with regard to its why, but the "that-it-is" has itself been disclosed to Da-sein. The thrownness of this being belongs to the disclosedness of the "there," and reveals itself constantly in its actual attunement. Attunement brings Da-sein, more or less explicitly and authentically, before its "that it is, and as the being that it is, has to be as a potentiality-of-being." But for the most part, mood closes off thrownness. Da-sein flees from thrownness to the alleviation that comes with the supposed freedom of the they-self. We characterized this flight as the flight from the uncanniness that fundamentally determines individualized being-in-the-world. Uncanniness reveals itself authentically in the fundamental attunement of An~t, and, as the most elemental disclosedness of thrown Da-sein, it confronts being-in-theworld with the nothingness of the world about which it is anxious in the An~ about its ownmost potentiality-of-being. What if Da-sein, finding itself in the ground of its uncanniness, were the caller of the call of conscience? Nothing speaks against this, but all the phenomena that were set forth up to now in characterizing the caller and its calling speak for it. In its who, the caller is definable by nothing "worldly." It is Da-sein in its uncanniness, primordially thrown being-in-the-world, as not-athome, the naked "that" in the nothingness of the world. The caller is unfamiliar to the everyday they-self, it is something like an alien voice. What could be more alien to the they, lost in the manifold "world" of its heedfulness, than the self individualized to itself in uncanniness thrown into nothingness? "It" calls, and yet gives the heedfully curious ears nothing to hear that could be passed along and publicly spoken about. But what should Da-sein even report from the uncanniness of its thrown being? What else remains for it than its own potentiality-of-being revealed in An~t? How else should it call than by summoning to this potentiality-of-being about which it is solely concerned? The call does not report any facts; it calls without uttering anything. The call speaks in the uncanny mode of silence. And it does this only because in calling the one summoned, it does not call him into
277
256
278
Being and Time
II.u
the public idle chatter of the they, but calls him back from that to the reticence of his existent potentiality-ofbeing. When the caller reaches him who is summoned, it does so with a cold assurance that is uncanny and by no means obvious. Wherein lies the basis for this assurance, if not in the fact that Da-sein, individualized to itself in its uncanniness, is absolutely unmistakable to itself? What is it that takes away from Da-sein so radically the possibility of misunderstanding itself from some other direction and failing to recognize itself, if not the abandonment in being delivered over to itself? Uncanniness is the fundamental kind of being-in-the-world, although it is covered over in everydayness. Da-sein itself calls as conscience from the ground of this being. The "it calls me" is an eminent kind of discourse of Da-sein. The call attuned by Angst first makes possible for Da-sein its project upon its ownmost potentiality-of-being. The call of conscience, existentially understood, first makes known what was simply asserted9 before: uncanniness pursues Da-sein and threatens its self-forgetfullostness. The statement that Da-sein is at the same time the caller and the one summoned has now lost its empty formal character and its obviousness. Conscience reveals itself as the call of care: the caller is Da-sein, anxious in thrownness (in its already-being-in ... ) about its potentialityof-being. The one summoned is also Da-sein, called forth to its ownmost potentiality-of-being (its being-ahead-of-itself ... ). And what is called forth by the summons is Da-sein, out of falling prey to the they (already-being-together-with-the-world-taken-care-of ... ). The call of conscience, that is, conscience itself, has its ontological possibility in the fact that Da-sein is care in the ground of its being. Thus we need not resort to powers unlike Da-sein, especially since recourse to these is so far from explaining the uncanniness of the call that it rather annihilates it. In the end, does not the reason for the farfetched "explanations" of conscience lie in the fact that we have not looked long enough to establish our phenomenal findings as to the call, and have mutely presupposed Da-sein to be in some kind of ontological determination or indetermination, whichever it may chance. Why should we look to alien powers for information before we have made sure that in starting our analysis we have not given too low an assessment of the being of Da-sein, that is, as a harmless subject occurring somewhere, endowed with personal consciousness? And yet if the caller-who is "no one" viewed from the perspective of the world-is interpreted as a power, this seems to be an unprejudiced recognition of something "objectively ascertainable." But rightly considered, this interpretation is only a flight from conscience, a way out for Da-sein along which it slips away from the thin wall that separates the
11.11
Being and Time
257
they, so to speak, from the uncanniness of its being. This interpretation of conscience pretends to recognize the call in the sense of a "universally" binding voice that "does not speak just subjectively." Better yet, this "universal" conscience gets exalted to a "world conscience," which still has the phenomenal character of an "it" and "no one," yet which speaks-there in the individual "subject"-as this indefinite something. But what else is this "public conscience" than the voice of the they? Da-sein can only get the dubious idea of a "world conscience" because at bottom conscience is essentially always mine, not only in the sense that one's ownmost potentiality-of-being is always summoned, but because the call comes from the being that I myself always am. With this interpretation of the caller, which sheerly follows the phenomenal character of calling, the "power" of conscience is not diminished and made "merely subjective." On the contrary, the inexorability and unequivocal quality of the call thus first becomes free. The "objectivity" of the summons thus is first justified when the interpretation leaves it its "subjectivity" which, of course, denies the they-self its dominance. Still, this interpretation of conscience as the call of care will be countered by the question of whether any interpretation of conscience can stand up if it removes itself so far from "natural experience." How is conscience as that which summons us to our ownmost potentiality-ofbeing supposed to function when it, after all, initially and for the most part, reproves and warns? Does conscience speak in so indefinite and empty a way about our ownmost potentiality-of-being? Does it not rather speak definitely and concretely in relation to failures and omissions which have already occurred or which we intended? Does the alleged summons come from a "bad" conscience or a "good" one? Does conscience give us anything positive at all? Does it not function rather only critically? Such second thoughts are incontestably justified. We can demand in any interpretation of conscience that "one" should recognize in it the phenomenon in question, as it is experienced daily. But to do justice to this demand does not mean that the vulgar, ontic understanding of conscience must be recognized as the first court of appeal for an ontological interpretation. But, on the other hand, the second thoughts we are having are premature as long as the analysis of conscience to which they pertain has not reached its goal. Up to now we have tried solely to trace conscience as a phenomenon of Da-sein back to the ontological constitution of this being. This served to prepare the task of making conscience intelligible as an attestation in Da-sein of its ownmost potentialityof-being.
279
258
280
Being and Time
11.11
But what conscience attests becomes completely definite only when we have stated with sufficient clarity what quality the hearing must have that genuinely corresponds to calling. The authentic understanding "following" the call is not an addition annexed to the phenomenon of conscience, a process that can either occur or else be lacking. The complete experience of conscience can only be grasped from understanding the summons together with it. If the caller and he who is summoned are themselves at the same time one's own Da-sein, a definite kind of being of Dasein lies in any failure to hear the call or in a mishearing of oneself. Viewed existentially, an unattached call from which "nothing ensues" is an impossible fiction. "That nothing ensues" means something positive with regard to Da-sein. Thus only an analysis of understanding the summons can lead to an explicit discussion of what the caU gives to understand. But only with our foregoing, general ontological characterization of conscience is the possibility given to comprehend existentially conscience's call of"guilty." All interpretations and experiences of conscience agree that the "voice" of conscience somehow speaks of "guilt."
58. Understanding the Summons, and Guilt In order to grasp phenomenally what is heard in understanding the summons, we shall take up this summons anew. Summoning the theyself means calling forth the authentic self to its potentiality-of-being, as Da-sein, that is, being-in-the-world taking care of things and being-with others. The existential interpretation of that to which the call calls forth, thus cannot define any concrete individual possibility of existence if it understands itself correctly in its methodical possibilities and tasks. What can be established, and what seeks to get established, is not what is called in and to each particular Da-sein from an existentiell standpoint, but what belongs to the existential condition of the possibility of the actual, factical and existentiell potentiality-of-being. When the call is understood with an existentiell kind of hearing, such understanding is the more authentic the more Da-sein hears and understands its own being summoned in a nonrelational way, and the less the meaning of the call gets distorted by what one says is proper and valid. What lies essentially in the authenticity of understanding the summons? What is actually essentially given to understand in the call, although not always factically understood? We have already answered this question in our thesis that the call "says" nothing which could be talked about, it does not give any information about factual occurrences. The call directs Da-sein f01Ward toward its potentiality-of-being, as a call out of uncanniness. The caller is indeed
11.11
Being and Time
259
indefinite, but where it calls from is not indifferent for the calling. Where it comes from-the uncanniness of thrown individuation-is also called in the calling, that is, is also disclosed. Where the call comes from in calling forth to ... is that to which it is called back. The call does not give us to understand an ideal, universal potentiality-of-being; it discloses it as what is actually individualized in that particular Da-sein. The disclosive character of the call has not been completely determined until we understand it as a calling back that calls forth. Only if we are oriented toward the call thus understood, may we ask what it gives to understand. But is the question of what the call says not answered more easily and certainly by the "simple" reference to what we generally hear or fail to hear in any experience of conscience: namely, that the call addresses Da-sein as "guilty" or, as in the warning conscience, refers to a possible "guilt" or as a "good" conscience, confirms that one is "conscious of no guilt"? If only this "guilty" experienced "universally" in experiences and interpretations of conscience were not defined in such completely different ways! And even if the meaning of this "guilty" could be grasped in general agreement, the existential concept of this beingguilty would still be obscure. However, when Da-sein addresses itself as guilty, where should its idea of guilt be drawn from if not from the interpretation of its own being? But the question arises again: who says how we are guilty and what guilt means? The idea of guilt cannot be arbitrarily thought up and forced upon Da-sein. But if an understanding of the essence of guilt is possible at all, this possibility must have been sketched out in Da-sein beforehand. How are we to find that trace that can lead to revealing this phenomenon? All ontological inquiries into phenomena such as guilt, conscience, and death must start from what everyday Da-sein "says" about them. Because its kind of being is entangled, the way Da-sein gets interpreted is for the most part inauthentically "oriented" and does not get at the "essence," since the primordially appropriate ontological kind of line questioning remains alien to it. Whenever we see something wrongly, a directive as to the primordial "idea" of the phenomenon is also revealed. But where do we get our criterion for the primordial, existential meaning of "guilty"? From the fact that this "guilty" turns up as a predicate of the "I am." Does what is understood as "guilt" in inauthentic interpretation possibly lie in the being of Da-sein as such, in such a way that it is also already guilty in that it actually, factically exists. Thus by invoking the "guilty" which everyone agrees that he hears, one has not yet answered the question of the existential meaning of what is called in the call. This must first be defined if we are to make intelligible what the call of "guilty" means, and why and how it gets distorted in its significance by everyday interpretation.
281
260
282
Being and Time
11.11
Everyday common sense initially takes "being guilty" in the sense of"owing something," "having something on account." One is supposed to return something to the other which is due to him. 1bis "being guilty" as "having debts" is a way of being-with with others in the field of taking care of things, as in providing something or bringing it along. Further modes of taking care of things are depriving, borrowing, withholding, taking, robbing, that is, in some way not doing justice to the claims that the others have made as to their possessions. This kind of being guilty is related to things that can be taken care of Then, being guilty has the further significance of "being responsible for," that is, being the cause or author of something or "being the occasion" for something. In the sense of this "being responsible" for something, one can "be guilty" without "owing" anything to someone else or corning to "owe" him. Conversely, one can owe something to another without being responsible for it oneself. Another person can "incur debts" to others "for me." These vulgar significations of being guilty as "having debts with ... " and "being responsible for ... " can go together and determine a kind of behavior which we call "making oneself responsible," that is, by having the responsibility for having a debt, one may break a law and make oneself punishable. However, the requirement that one fails to satisfy need not necessarily be related to possessions, it can regulate public being-with-one-another in general. This definite "making oneself responsible" by breaking a law can also at the same time have the character of "becoming responsible to others." That does not occur by breaking a law as such, but through my having the responsibility for the other's becoming jeopardized in his existence, led astray, or even destroyed. This becoming responsible to others is possible without breaking the "public" law. The formal concept of being responsible in the sense of having become responsible to others can be defined as being the ground for a lack in the Da-sein of another, in such a way that this being-the-ground itself is defined as "lacking" in terms of that for which it is the ground. This kind of lacking is a failure to satisfy some demand placed on one's existing being-with with others. It remains a question how such demands arise and in what way their character of demands and laws is to be conceived on the basis of this origin. In any case, being guilty in this latter sense of breaking a "moral requirement" is a kind of being of Da-sein. Of course, that is also true of being guilty as "making oneself punishable," as "having debts," and of any "having responsibility for ... ". These, too, are modes of behavior ofDa-sein. Very little is said by grasping "burdened with moral guilt" as a "quality" of Da-sein. On the contrary, it only thus becomes evident that this characterization is not sufficient for distinguishing onto-
11.11
Being and Time
261
logically between this kind of "determination of being" of Da-sein and the other ways of behaving just listed. The concept of moral guilt has been so little clarified ontologically that when the idea of deserving punishment, or even having debts to someone, has also been included in this concept, or when these ideas have been employed in the very defining of it, such interpretations of this phenomenon could become prevalent and have remained so. But in this way the "guilty" is again forced aside into the area of taking care of things in the sense of calculating claims and balancing them off. The clarification of the phenomenon of guilt which is not necessarily related to "having debts" and breaking the law, can be successful only if we ask beforehand in principle about the being-guilty of Da-sein, that is, if the idea of "guilty" is conceived in terms of the kind of being of Da-sein. For this purpose, the idea of "guilty" must be formalized to the extent that the vulgar phenomena of guilt related to being-with others in taking care of things are excluded. The idea of guilt must not only be removed from the area of calculating and taking care of things, but must also be separated from relationship to an ought and a law such that by failing to comply with it one burdens himself with guilt. For here, too, guilt is still necessarily defined as a lack, when something which ought to be and can be is missing. But to be missing means not being objectively present. A lack, as the not being objectively present of what ought to be, is a determination of being of objective presence. In this sense nothing can be essentially lacking in existence, not because it is complete, but because its character of being is distinguished from any kind of objective presence. Still, the quality of the not is present in the idea of "guilty." If the "guilty" is to be able to define existence, the ontological problem arises here of clarifying existentially the not-quality of this not. Furthermore, there belongs to the idea of "guilty" what is expressed without differentiation in the concept of guilt as "being responsible for": being-theground for .... Thus we define the formal existential idea of "guilty" as being-the-ground for a being which is determined by a not-that is, beingthe-ground of a nullity. If the idea of the not present in the existentially understood concept of "guilt" excludes relatedness to anyt11ing objectively present which is possible or which ought to be, if thus Da-sein is altogether incommensurable with something objectively present or valid which it itself is not, or which is not in the way Da-sein is, that is, exists, so any possibility that, with regard to being-the-ground for a lack, the being that is itself such a ground might be calculated as "deficient," is a possibility that is excluded. If a lack, such as a failure to fulfill some requirement, has been "caused" in a way characteristic of Da-sein, we cannot
283
284
262
285
Being and Time
11.11
simply calculate back to a deficiency of the "cause." Being the ground for . . . need not have the same character of not as the privativum grounded in it and arising from it. The ground need not acquire a nullity of its own from what is grounded in it. But this means that beingguilty does not result from an indebtedness, but the other way around: indebtedness is possible only "on the basis" of a primordial being guilty. Can we show this in the being of Da-sein, and how is it existentially possible at all? The being ofDa-sein is care. It includes in itselffacticity {thrownness), existence {project) and falling prey. Da-sein exists as thrown, brought into its there not of its own accord. It exists as a potentiality-ofbeing which belongs to itself, and yet has not given itself to itself. Existing, it never gets back behind its thrownness so that it could ever expressly release this "that-it-is-and-has-to-be" from its being a self and lead it into the there. But thrownness does not lie behind it as an event which actually occurred, something that happened to it and was again separated from Da-sein. Rather, as long as it is, Da-sein is constantly its "that" as care. As this being, delivered over to which it can exist uniquely as the being which it is, it is, existing, the ground of its potentiality-ofbeing. Because it has not laid the ground itself, it rests in the weight of it, which mood reveals to it as a burden. And how is Da-sein this thrown ground? Only by projecting itself upon the possibilities into which it is thrown. The self, which as such has to lay the ground of itself, can never gain power over that ground, and yet it has to take over being the ground in existing. Being its own thrown ground is the potentiality-of-being about which care is concerned. Being the ground, that is, existing as thrown, Da-sein constantly lags behind its possibilities. It is never existent before its ground, but only from it and as it. Thus being the ground means never to gain power over one's ownmost being from the ground up. This not belongs to the existential meaning of thrownness. Being the ground, it itself is a nullity of itself. Nullity by no means signifies not being objectively present or not subsisting, but means a not that constitutes this being of Da-sein, its thrownness. The quality of this not as a not is determined existentially. Being a self, Da-sein is the thrown being as self. Not through itself, but released to itself from the ground in order to be as this ground. Da-sein is not itself the ground of its being, because the ground first arises from its own project, but as a self, it is the being of its ground. The ground is always ground only for a being whose being has to take over being-theground_ Existing, Da-sein is its ground, that is, in such a way that it understands itself in terms of possibilities and, thus understanding itself, is thrown being. But this means that, as a potentiality-of-being, it always
II.II
Being and Time
263
stands in one possibility or another; it is constantly not other possibilities and has relinquished them in its existentiell project. As thrown, the project is not only determined by the nullity of being the ground but is itself as project essentially null. Again, this definition by no means signifies the antic property of being "unsuccessful" or "of no value" but an existential constituent of the structure of being of projecting. This nullity belongs to the being-free of Da-sein for its existentiell possibilities. But freedom is only in the choice of the one, that is, in bearing the fact of not having chosen and not being able also to choose the others. In the structure of thrownness as well as in that of the project, essentially lies a nullity. And it is the ground for the possibility of the nullity of inauthentic Da-sein in its falling prey which it always already actually is factically. Care itself is in its essence thoroughly permeated with nullity. Care, the being of Da-sein, thus means, as thrown project: being the (null) ground of a nullity. And that means that Da-sein as such is guilty if our formal existential definition of guilt as being-the-ground of a nullity is valid. Existential nullity by no means has the character of a privation, of a lack as compared with an ideal which is set up but is not attained in Dasein; rather, the being of this being is already null as project before everything that it can project and usually attains. Thus this nullity does not occur occasionally in Da-sein, attached to it as a dark quality that it could get rid of if it made sufficient progress. Still, the ontological meaning of the notness of this existential nullity remains obscure. But that is true also of the ontological essence of the not in general. Of course, ontology and logic have expected much of the not, and thus at times made its possibilities visible without revealing it itself ontologically. Ontology found the not and used it. But is it then so selfevident that every not means a negativum in the sense of a lack? Does its positivity get exhausted by its constituting the "transition"? Why does every dialectic take refuge in negation, without grounding it itself dialectically, without even being able to locate it as a problem? Has anyone ever made the ontological origin of notness a problem at all, or, before that, even looked for the conditions on the basis of which the problem of the not and its notness and the possibility of this notness could be raised? And where else should they be found than in a thematic clarification of the meaning of being in general? The concepts of privation and lack which, moreover, are hardly transparent, are insufficient for the .ontological interpretation of the phenomenon of guilt, though if we take them formally enough, we can put them to considerable use. Least of all, can we get nearer to the existential phenomenon of guilt by taking our orientation toward the idea of evil, the malum as privatio boni. The bonum and the privatio have the
286
264
287
Being and Time
11.11
same ontological provenance in the ontology of objective presence which also characterizes the idea of "value" derived from that. Beings whose being is care can not only burden themselves with factical guilt, but they are guilty in the ground of their being. This being guilty first gives the ontological condition for the fact that Da-sein can become guilty while factically existing. This essential being guilty is, equiprimordially, the existential condition of the possibility of the "morally" good and evil, that is, for morality in general and its possible factical forms. Primordial being guilty cannot be defined by morality because morality already presupposed it for itself. But what experience speaks for this primordial being-guilty of Dasein? Nor may we forget the counter-question: "is" guilt "there" only if a consciousness of guilt is awakened, or does not the most primordial being guilty make itself known in the very fact that guilt "is sleeping"? The fact that this primordial being-guilty initially and for the most part remains undisclosed and is kept closed off by the entangled· being of Dasein only reveals this nullity. Being guilty is more primordial than any knowing about it. And only because Da-sein is guilty in the ground of its being and closes itself off from itself as thrown and fallen prey, is conscience possible, if indeed the call basically gives us to understand this being guilty. The call is the call of care. Being guilty constitutes the being that we call care. Da-sein stands primordially together with itself in uncanniness. Uncanniness brings this being face to face with its undisguised nullity, which belongs to the possibility of its ownmost potentiality-of-being. In that Da-sein as care is concerned about its being, it calls itself as a they that has factically fallen prey, and calls itself from its uncanniness to its potentiality-of-being. The summons calls back by calling forth: forth to the possibility of taking over in existence the thrown being that it is, back to thrownness in order to understand it as the null ground that it has to take up into existence. The calling back in which conscience calls forth gives Da-sein to understand that Da-sein itself-as the null ground of its null project, standing in the possibility of its being-must bring itself back to itself from its lostness in the they, and this means that it is guilty. What Da-sein thus gives itself to understand would then, after all, be a knowledge about itself. And the hearing corresponding to that call would be a taking notice of the fact of being "guilty." But if the call is indeed to have the character of a summons, does not this interpretation of conscience lead to a complete distortion of its function? Summoning to being-guilty, is that not summoning to evil? Even the most violent interpretation would not wish to impose upon conscience such a meaning for the call. But then what is "summoning to being-guilty" supposed to mean?
n.n
Being and Time
265
The meaning of the call becomes clear if our understanding of it keeps to the existential meaning of being-guilty, instead of making basic the derivative concept of guilt in the sense of an indebtedness "arising" from some deed done or left undone. Such a demand is not arbitrary if the call of conscience, coming from Da-sein itself, is directed solely to this being. But then summoning to being-guilty means a calling forth to the potentiality-of-being that I always already am as Da-sein. Da-sein need not first burden itself with "guilt" through failures or omissions; it must only be authentically the "guilty" that it is. Then the correct hearing of the summons is tantamount to understanding oneself in one's ownmost potentiality-of-being, that is, in projecting oneself upon one's ownmost authentic potentiality for becoming guilty. When Da-sein understandingly lets itself be called forth to this possibility, this includes its becoming free for the call: its readiness for the potentiality-of-being summoned. Understanding the call, Da-sein listens to its ownmost possibility of existence. It has chosen itself. With this choice, Da-sein makes possible its ownmost beingguilty, which remains closed off from the they-self. The common sense of the they knows only what is sufficient or insufficient with respect to handy rules and public standards. It calculates infractions of them and tries to balance them off. The they has slunk away from its ownmost being-guilty so as to talk about mistakes all the more vociferously. But in the summons, the they-self is summoned to the ownmost being-guilty of the self. Understanding the call is choosing, but it is not a choosing of conscience, which as such cannot be chosen. What is chosen is having a conscience as being free for one's ownmost being-guilty. Understanding the summons means: wanting to have a conscience. This does not mean wanting to have a "good conscience," nor does it mean willfully cultivating the "call"; it means solely the readiness to be summoned. Wanting to have a conscience is just as far away from searching out one's factical indebtedness as it is from the tendency to liberation from guilt in the sense of the essential "guilty." Wanting to have a conscience is rather the most primordial existentiell presupposition for the possibility of becoming factically guilty. Understanding the call, Da-sein lets its ownmost self take action in itself in terms of its chosen potentiality-of-being. Only in this way can it be responsible. But factically every action is necessarily "without conscience," not only because it does not avoid factical moral indebtedness, but because on the basis of the null ground of its null project it has always already become guilty toward the others in being-with with them. Thus wanting to have a conscience takes over the essential lack of conscience within which alone there is the existentiell possibility of being "good."
288
266
289
Being and Time
11.11
Although the call does not give us any information, it is not merely critical, but positive. It discloses the most primordial potentiality-of-being of Da-sein as being-guilty. Thus, conscience reveals itself as an attestation belonging to the being of Da-sein-an attestation in which conscience calls Da-sein forth to its ownmost potentiality-of-being. Can the authentic potentiality-of-being thus attested be defined existentially in a more concrete way? But now that we have shown a potentiality-of-being that is attested in Da-sein itself, a preliminary question arises: can we claim sufficient evidential weight for the way we have shown this as long as the strange feeling of our interpreting conscience one-sidedly by tracing it back to the constitution of Da-sein while hastily passing over all of the findings familiar to the vulgar interpretation of conscience is one that is still undiminished? Is the phenomenon of conscience still recognizable at all, as it "really" is, in our interpretation? Have we not been all too sure of ourselves in the ingenuousness with which we deduced an idea of conscience from the constitution of being of Da-sein? The last step in our interpretation of conscience is the existential delimitation of the authentic potentiality-of-being that conscience attests. If we are to assure ourselves of a way of access that will make such a step possible even for the vulgar understanding of conscience, we need explicit evidence for the connection between the results of the ontological analysis and the everyday experiences of conscience. 59. The Existential Interpretation of Conscience and the Vulgar Interpretation of Conscience
Conscience is the call of care from the uncanniness of being-in-theworld that summons Da-sein to its ownmost potentiality-for-being-guilty. We showed that wanting-to-have-a-conscience corresponded to understanding the summons. Both of these characterizations are not immediately harmonious with the vulgar interpretation of conscience. Indeed, they seem to be in direct conflict with it. We call this interpretation of conscience vulgar because in characterizing this phenomenon and describing its " function" it keeps to what they know as conscience, how they follow it or fail to follow it; But must the ontological interpretation be in harmony with the vulgar interpretation at all? Should not the latter be, in principle, ontologically suspect? If Da-sein initially and for the most part understands itself in terms of what it takes care of, and if it interprets all its modes of behavior as taking care of things, then will there not be falling prey and covering over in its interpretation of precisely the way of its being that, as a call, seeks to bring it back from its lostness in the cares of the they? Everydayness takes Da-sein as something at hand that is taken care of,
11.11
Being and Time
267
that is, is regulated and calculated. "Ufe" is a "business," whether or not it covers its costs. With regard to the vulgar kind of being of Da-sein itself, there is thus no guarantee that the interpretation of conscience arising from it or the theories of conscience oriented toward it have attained the appropriate ontological horizon for its interpretations. Nevertheless, even the vulgar experience of conscience must somehow get at the phenomenon, pre-ontologically. Two things follow from this. On the one hand, the everyday interpretation of conscience cannot be valid as the ultimate criterion for the "objectivity" of an ontological analysis. On the other hand, such an analysis is not justified in elevating itself over the everyday understanding of conscience and passing over the anthropological, psychological, and theological theories of conscience based on it. If the existential analysis has exposed the phenomenon of conscience in its ontological roots, the vulgar interpretations must be intelligible precisely in terms of that analysis; where they miss the phenomenon and why they cover it over. However, since in the context of problems in this inquiry the analysis of conscience is only subservient to the ontological, fundamental question, the characterization of the connection between the existential interpretation of conscience and the vulgar interpretation of conscience will have to be content with a reference to the essential problems. In this vulgar interpretation of conscience there are four objections to our interpretation of conscience as the summons of care to being-guilty.
1. Conscience has an essentially critical function. 2. Conscience always speaks relative to a definite deed that has been done or wished for. 3. According to experience, the "voice" is never related so radically to the being of Da-sein. 4. Our interpretation pays no attention to the basic forms of the phenomenon, to "evil" and "good" conscience, to what "reproves" and "warns." Let us begin our discussion with the last reservation. In all interpretations of conscience, it is the "evil" or "bad" conscience that has priority. Conscience is primarily "bad"; such a conscience makes known to us that in every experience of conscience something like a "guilty" gets experienced first. But in the idea of bad conscience how is this making itself known of evil understood? The "experience of conscience" turns up after the deed has been done or left undone. The voice follows up the transgression and points back to the event through which
290
268
291
Being and Time
II.n
Da-sein has burdened itself with guilt. If conscience makes known a "being guilty," this cannot occur as a summons to ... , but as a pointing that reminds us of the guilt incurred. But does the "fact" that the voice comes later prevent the call from being basically a calling forth? The fact that the voice is grasped as a stirring of conscience that follows after is not yet evidence for a primordial understanding of the phenomenon of conscience. What if the factical indebtedness were only the occasion for the factical calling of conscience? What if the interpretation we described of "bad" conscience got stuck halfway? That this is true can be seen from the ontological forehaving within whose scope the phenomenon has been brought by this interpretation. The voice is something that turns up, it has its place in the series of objectively present experiences, and it follows after the experience of the deed. But neither the call nor the past deed nor the guilt assumed are events with the character of something objectively present that runs its course. The call has the kind of being of care. In the call, Da-sein "is" ahead of itself in such a way that at the same time it directs itself back to its thrownness. Only by first positing that Da-sein is a serial connection of successive experiences, is it possible to take the voice as something coming afterwards, something later that necessarily refers back. The voice does call back, but it calls back beyond the past deed into thrown being-guilty, which is "earlier" than any indebtedness. But the call back at the same time calls forth a being-guilty, as something to be seized upon in one's own existence, in such a way that authentic, existentiell being-guilty precisely "comes after" the call, and not the other way around. Basically, bad conscience is so far from reproving and pointing back that it rather points forward by calling back into thrownness. The order ofsuccession in which experiences run their course is not valid for the phenomenal structure of existing. If a characterization of "bad" conscience does not get at the primordial phenomenon, still less can this be done by characterizing the good conscience, whether one takes it as an independent form of conscience or as one essentially founded upon "bad" conscience. As the "bad" conscience makes known a "being evil," the good conscience would have to make known the "being good" of Da-sein. One can easily see that conscience that used to be the "effluence of the divine power" now becomes the slave of Pharisaism. It is supposed to let men say of themselves: "I am good." Who else can say this and who would be less willing to affirm it than the good man himself? But from this impossible consequence of the idea of good conscience, the fact only becomes apparent that being-guilty is what conscience calls. To escape this consequence, one has interpreted "good" conscience as a privation of the "bad" one, and defined it as an "experi-
n.n
Being and Time
269
enced lack of bad conscience." 10 Accordingly it would be an experience of the fact that the call does not tum up, that is, that I have nothing to reproach myself with. But how is this "lack" "experienced"? The supposed experience is not the experience of a call at all, but a making certain that a deed attributed to Da-sein was not committed by it and that Da-sein is therefore innocent. Becoming certain of not having done something does not have the character of a phenomenon of conscience at all. On the contrary, it can rather mean a forgetting of conscience, that is, that one is emerging from the possibility of being able to be summoned. This "certainty" contains the tranquillizing suppression of wanting to have a conscience, that is, of understanding one's ownmost and constant beingguilty. "Good" conscience is neither an independent form of conscience nor a founded form of conscience, that is, it is not a phenomenon of conscience at all. Since the talk about a "good" conscience arises from the experience of conscience of everyday Da-sein, the latter only betrays the fact that basically it does not get at the phenomenon, even when it speaks of "bad" conscience. For factically the idea of "bad" conscience is oriented toward that of the "good" conscience. The everyday interpretation keeps to the dimension of calculating and taking care of things and balancing out "guilt" and "innocence." It is in this horizon that the voice of conscience is "experienced." In characterizing the primordiality of the ideas of a "bad" and a "good" conscience, we have also already decided as to the distinction between a conscience that points ahead and warns, and one that points back and reproves. It is true that the idea of the warning conscience comes nearest to the phenomenon of summoning to .... It shares with the latter the character of pointing ahead. But this agreement is only an illusion, after all. The experience of a warning conscience again sees the voice only in orientation toward the willed deed from which it wants to deter us. As the suppression of what is wanted, the warning is thus possible only because the "warning" call aims at the potentiality-of-being of Da-sein, namely, at its understanding of itself in being-guilty in which "what is wished for" first gets shattered. The warning conscience has the function of sporadically governing our staying free from indebtedness. The experience of a "warning" conscience sees the tendency of its call only to the extent that it remains accessible to the common sense of the they. The third reservation appeals to the fact that the everyday experience of conscience is not familiar with anything like a being summoned to be guilty. This we must admit. But does the everyday experience of conscience then guarantee that the complete possible content of the call of the voice of conscience is heard in it? Does it follow from this that the
292
270
293
294
Being and Time
II.n
theories of conscience based on the vulgar experience of conscience have secured for themselves the appropriate ontological horizon for the analysis of the phenomenon? Does not rather an essential kind of being of Da-sein, falling prey, show that this being initially and for the most part understands itself ontically in terms of the horizon of taking care of things, but ontologically defines being in the sense of objective presence? But from this comes a twofold covering over of the phenomenon: the theory sees a series of experiences or "psychic processes" that are for the most part quite indefinite in their kind of being. Experience encounters conscience as a judge and an admonisher with whom Da-sein calculatingly deals. The fact that Kant takes the "idea of a court of justice" as the key idea for the basis of his interpretation of conscience is not a matter of chance, but was suggested by the idea of moral law, although his concept of morality was far removed from utilitarianism and eudaemonism. Even the theory of value, whether it be formally or materially conceived, has a "metaphysics of morals," that is, an ontology of Da-sein and existence as its unspoken ontological presupposition. Da-sein is conceived as a being to be taken care of, and this taking care of has the meaning of "actualizing values" or satisfying norms. The appeal to the scope of what the everyday conscience is familiar with as the sole higher court for the interpretation of conscience, cannot be justified unless it has stopped to consider whether conscience can become authentically accessible at all. Thus the further objection that the existential interpretation overlooks the fact that the call of conscience is always related to a definite "actualized" or willed deed, also loses its force. It cannot be denied that the call is frequently experienced as having such a tendency. It remains questionable only whether this experience of the call lets it "proclaim" itself fully. The commonsense interpretation might believe that it keeps itself to "facts," and yet in the end has restricted the call's scope of disclosure by its very common sense. As little as the "good" conscience can be placed in the service of a "Pharisaism, "just as little may the function of the "bad" conscience be reduced to pointing out indebtednesses that are objectively present or to repressing possible ones. As if Da-sein were a "household" whose indebtedness only needed to be balanced out in an orderly way for the self to be able to stand "next to" these experiential occurrences as an uninvolved spectator. But if what is primary in the call is not a relatedness to factically "objectively present" guilt or culpable deeds that have been factically willed, and if thus the "reproving" and "warning" types of conscience express no primordial functions of the call, then the ground is also taken out from under the feet of the first reservation, that the existential
II.II
Being and Time
271
interpretation fails to recognize the "essentially" critical accomplishment of conscience. This reservation, too, arises from a view of the phenomenon which is genuine within certain limits. For, indeed, in the content of the call, nothing can be shown that the voice "positively" recommends and commands. But how is this positivity that is missing from what conscience does to be understood? Does it follow from this that conscience has a "negative" character? We miss a "positive" content in what is called because we expect to be told something actually useful about assured possibilities of "action" that are available and calculable. This expectation is based on the horizon of interpretation of the commonsense way of taking care of things, which forces the existence of Da-sein to be subsumed under the idea of a governable course of business. Such expectations (which also in part inexplicitly underlie the demands of a material ethics of value as opposed to a "merely" formal one) are, however, disappointed by conscience. Such "practical" directions are not given by the call of conscience for the sole reason that it summons Da-sein to existence, to its ownmost potentialityof-being-a-self. With its unequivocally calculable maxims that one is led to expect, conscience would deny to existence nothing less than the possibility of acting. Because conscience evidently cannot be "positive" in this way, neither does it function in the same way "only negatively." The call discloses nothing that could be positive or negative as something to be taken care of, because it has to do with an ontologically completely different being, namely, existence. On the contrary, the correctly understood call gives the "most positive thing of all" in the existential sense-the ownmost possibility that Da-sein can give itself as a calling back that calls it forth to its factical potentiality-of-being-a-self. To hear the call authentically means to bring oneself to factical action. But only by setting forth the existential structure implied in our understanding of the summons when we hear it authentically, shall we attain a completely adequate interpretation of what is called in the call. We wanted to show how the phenomena that alone are familiar to the vulgar interpretation of conscience, point back to the primordial meaning of the call of conscience when they are understood in an ontologically appropriate way; then, that the vulgar interpr:etation arises from the limitations of the entangled self-interpretation of Da-sein, and, since falling prey belongs to care itself, we must show that this interpretation, even though it is self-evident, is by no means accidental. The ontological critique of the vulgar interpretation of conscience could be subject to the misunderstanding that by showing the lack of existential primordiality of the everyday experience of conscience one wanted to pass judgment upon the existentiell "moral quality" of Da-sein. Just as existence is not necessarily and directly jeopardized by an onto-
295
272
Being and Time
Il.n
logically insufficient understanding of conscience, the existentiell understanding of the call is not guaranteed by an existentially adequate interpretation of conscience either. Seriousness is no less possible in the vulgar experience of conscience than is a lack of seriousness in a more primordial understanding of conscience. Still, the existentially more primordial interpretation also discloses possibilities of a more primordial existentiell understanding, as long as our ontological concepts do not get cut off from ontic experience.
60. The Existential Structure of the Authentic Potentiality-ofBeing Attested in Conscience
296
The existential interpretation of conscience is to set for an existent attestation in Da-sein itself of its ownmost potentiality-of-being. Conscience attests not by making something known in an undifferentiated way, but by a summons that calls forth to being-guilty. What is thus attested to is "grasped" in the hearing which understands the call without distortion in the sense it has itself intended. Understanding the summons, as a mode of being of Da-sein, first gives the phenomenal content of what is attested in the call of conscience. We characterized authentically understanding the call as wanting to have a conscience. Letting one's ownmost self act in itself of its own accord in its being-guilty represents phenomenally the authentic potentiality-of-being attested in Da-sein itself. Its existential structure must now be exposed. Only in this way can we penetrate to the fundamental constitution, disclosed in Da-sein itself, of the authenticity of its existence. As self-understanding in one's ownmost potentiality of being, wanting-to-have-a-conscience is a mode of disclosedness of Da-sein. Disclosedness is constituted by attunement and discourse as well as by understanding. Existentiell understanding means to project oneself upon one's ownmost factical possibility of having the potentiality-for-being-inthe-world. But the potentiality-of-being is understood only by existing in this possibility. What mood corresponds to such understanding? Understanding the call discloses one's own Da-sein in the uncanniness of its individuation. The uncanniness revealed in understanding is genuinely disclosed by the attunement of Angst belonging to it. The fact of the Angst of conscience is a phenomenal confirmation of the fact that in understanding the call Da-sein is brought face to face with its own uncanniness. Wanting to have a conscience becomes a readiness for Ang.5t. The third essential element of disclosedness is discourse. The call itself is a primordial discourse of Da-sein, but there is no corresponding counter-discourse in which, for example, one talks about what con-
11.11
Being and Time
273
science has said and tries to deal with it. In hearing the call understandingly, one denies oneself any counter-discourse, not because one has been overcome by an "obscure power," which suppresses one's hearing, but because this hearing appropriates the content of the call in an uncovered way. The call introduces the fact of constantly being-guilty and thus brings the self back from the loud idle chatter of the they's common sense. Thus the mode of articulative discourse belonging to wanting to have a conscience is reticence. We characterized silence as an essential possibility of discourse. 11 Whoever wants to give something to understand in silence must "have something to say." In the summons, Da-sein gives itself to understand its ownmost potentiality-of-being. Thus this calling is a keeping silent. The discourse of conscience never comes to utterance. Conscience only calls silently, that is, the call comes from the soundlessness of uncanniness and calls Da-sein thus summoned back to the stillness of itself, and calls it to become still. Wanting to have a conscience thus understands this silent discourse appropriately only in reticence. It takes the words away from the commonsense idle chatter of the they. The commonsense interpretation of conscience, which "strictly adheres to facts," takes the silent discourse of conscience as the occasion to pass it off as something not ascertainable at all or objectively present. The fact that they, hearing and understanding only loud idle chatter, cannot "confirm" any call, is attributed to conscience with the excuse that it is "dumb" and evidently not objectively present. With this interpretation, the they only covers over its own failure to hear the call and the fact that its "hearing" does not reach very far. The disclosedness of Da-sein in wanting-to-have-a-conscience is thus constituted by the attunement of Ang.5t, by understanding as projecting oneself upon one's ownmost being-guilty, and by discourse as reticence. We shall call the eminent, authentic disclosedness attested in Da-sein itself by its conscience-the reticent projecting oneself upon ones ownmost being-guilty which is ready for Angst-resoluteness. Resoluteness is an eminent mode of the disclosedness of Da-sein. But in an earlier passage disclosedness was interpreted existentially12 as primordial truth. This is not primarily a quality of '1udgment" or of any particular mode of behavior at all, but an essential constituent of beingin-the-world as such. Truth must be understood as a fundamental existential. Our ontological clarification of the statement that "Da-sein is in the truth" has pointed to the primordial disdosedness of this being as the truth of existence; and for its delineation we have referred to the analysis of the authenticity of Da-sein. 1 ~ Now, in resoluteness the most primordial truth of Da-sein has been reached, because it is authentic. The disclosedness of the there dis-
297
274
298
Being and Time
Il.n
closes equiprimordially the whole of being-in-the-world-the world, being-in, and the self that is this being as "I am." With the disclosedness of world, innerworldly beings have always already been discovered. The discoveredness of things at hand and objectively present is grounded in the discoveredness of the world; 14 for if the actual totality of relevance of things at hand is to be freed, this requires a pre-understanding of significance. In understanding significance, Da-sein, taking care of things, is circumspectly referred to the things at hand encountered. The understanding of significance as the disclosedness of the actual world is again grounded in the understanding of the for-the-sake-of-which, to which discovering of the totality of relevance goes back. In seeking shelter, sustenance, and livelihood, we do so for-the-sake-of the constant possibilities of Da-sein that are near to it; upon these, this being which is concerned about its being has always already projected itself. Thrown into its "there," Da-sein is always factically dependent on a definite "world"-its "world." At the same time those nearest factical projects are guided by the lostness in the they taking care of things. This lostness can be summoned by one's own Da-sein, the summons can be understood in the mode of resoluteness .. But authentic disclosedness then modifies equiprimordially the discoveredness of "world" grounded in it and the disclosedness of being-with with others. The "world" at hand does not become different as far as "content," the circle of the others is not exchanged for a new one, and yet the being toward things at hand which understands and takes care of things, and the concerned being-with with the others is now defined in terms of their ownmost potentiality-ofbeing-a-self. As authentic being a self, resoluteness does not detach Da-sein from its world, nor does it isolate it as free floating ego. How could it, if resoluteness as authentic disclosedness is, after all, nothing other than authentically being-in-the-world? Resoluteness brings the self right into its being together with things at hand, actually taking care of them, and pushes it toward concerned being-with with the others. In the light of the for-the-sake-of-which of the potentiality-of-being which it has chosen, resolute Da-sein frees itself for its world. The resoluteness toward itself first brings Da-sein to the possibility of letting the others who are with it "be" in their ownmost potentiality-of-being, and also discloses that potentiality in concern which leaps ahead and frees. Resolute Da-sein can become the "conscience" of others. It is from the authentic being a self of resoluteness that authentic being-with-oneanother first arises, not from ambiguous and jealous stipulations and talkative fraternizing in the they and in what they wants to undertake. In accordance with its ontological essence, resoluteness always belongs to a factical Da-sein. The essence of this being is its existence.
11.11
Being and Time
275
Resoluteness "exists" only as a resolution that projects itself understandingly. But to what does Da-sein resolve itself in resoluteness? On what is it to resolve? Only the resolution itself can answer this. It would be a complete misunderstanding of the phenomenon of resoluteness if one were to believe that it is simply a matter of receptively taking up possibilities presented and suggested. Resolution is precisely the disclosive projection and determination of the actual factical possibility. The indefiniteness that characterizes every factically projected potentiality-of-being of Dasein belongs necessarily to resoluteness. Resoluteness is certain of itself only in a resolution. But the existentiell indefiniteness of resoluteness never makes itself definite except in a resolution; it nevertheless has its existential definiteness. What one resolves upon in resoluteness is prefigured ontologically in the existentiality of Da-sein in general as a potentiality-of-being in the mode of heedful concern. But, as care, Da-sein is determined by facti city and falling prey. Disclosed in its "there," it stays equiprimordially in truth and in untruth. 15 This "really" is true in particular for resoluteness as authentic truth. Thus resoluteness appropriates untruth authentically. Da-sein is always already in irresoluteness, and perhaps will be soon again. The term irresoluteness merely expresses the phenomenon that was interpreted as being at the mercy of the dominant interpretedness of the they. As the they-self, Da-sein is "lived" by the commonsense ambiguity of publicness in which no one resolves, but which has always already made its decision. Resoluteness means letting oneself be summoned out of one's lostness in the they. The irresoluteness of the they nevertheless remains in dominance, but it cannot attack resolute existence. As the counter-concept to existentially understood resoluteness, irresoluteness does not mean an ontic, psychical quality in the sense of being burdened with inhibitions. Even resolutions are dependent upon the they and its world. Understanding this is one of the things that resolution discloses, in that resoluteness first gives to Dasein its authentic transparency. In resoluteness, Da-sein is concerned with its ownmost potentiality-of-being that, as thrown, can project itself only upon definite, factical possibilities. Resolution does not escape from "reality," but first discovers what is factically possible in such a way that it grasps it as it is possible as one's ownmost potentiality-ofbeing in the they. The existential definiteness of possible resolute Dasein includes the constitutive moments of the existential phenomenon that we call situation and which we have not yet discussed. In the term situation (position-"to be in the position of"), there is an overtone of a spatial significance. We shall not attempt to eliminate it from the existential concept. For such an overtone is also implied in the "there" of Da-sein. Being-in-the-world has a spatiality of its own that
299
276
300
Being and Time
II.n
is characterized by the phenomena of de-distancing and directionality. Da-sein "makes room" in factically existing. 16 But the spatiality ofDa-sein, on the basis of which existence actually determines its "place," is grounded in the constitution of being-in-the-world, for which disclosedness is primarily constitutive. Just as the spatiality of the there is grounded in disclosedness, situation has its basis in resoluteness. Situation is the there disclosed in resoluteness-as which the existing being is there. It is not an objectively present framework in which Da-sein occurs or into which it could even bring itself. Far removed from any objectively present mixture of the circumstances and accidents encountered, situation is only through and in resoluteness. The actual factical relevant character of the circumstances is disclosed to the self only when that relevant character is such that one is resolute for the there which that self, in existing, has to be. What we call accidents in the with-world and the surrounding world can only befall resoluteness. For the they, however, situation is essentially closed off. The they knows only the "general situation," loses itself in the nearest "opportunities," and settles its Da-sein by calculating the "accidents" which it fails to recognize, deems its own achievement and passes off as such. Resoluteness brings the being of the there to the existence of its situation. But resoluteness delineates the existential structure of the authentic potentiality-of-being attested in conscience-wanting to have a conscience. In this potentiality we recognized the appropriate understanding of the summons. This makes it quite clear that the call of conscience does not dangle an empty ideal of existence before us when it summons us to our potentiality-of-being, but calls forth to the situation. This existential positivity of the correctly understood call of conscience at the same time makes us see how in limiting the tendency to the call to actual and planned incidents of indebtednesses we fail to recognize the disclosive character of conscience. It also makes us see how the concrete understanding of the voice of conscience is only seemingly transmitted to us if this restriction is made. The existential interpretation of understanding the summons as resoluteness reveals conscience as the kind of being contained in the ground of Da-sein, in which it makes its factical existence possible for itself, attesting its ownmost potentiality-ofbeing. The phenomenon set forth with the term resoluteness can hardly be confused with an empty "habitus" and an indefinite "velleity." Resoluteness does not first represent and acknowledge a situation to itself, but has already placed itself in it. Resolute, Da-sein is already acting. We are purposely avoiding the term "action." For in the first place, it would have to be so broadly conceived that activity also encompasses the passivity of resistance. In the second place, that term suggests a misinter-
11.11
Being and Time
277
pretation of the ontology of Da-sein as if resoluteness were a special mode of behavior of the practical faculty as opposed to the theoretical one. But, as concern taking care of things, care includes the being of Dasein so primordially and completely that it must be already presupposed as a whole when we distinguish between theoretical and practical behavior; it cannot first be put together from these faculties with the help of a dialectic that is necessarily groundless because it is existentially unfounded. But resoluteness is only the authenticity of care itself, cared for in care and possible as care. To portray the factical existentiell possibilities in their general features and connections, and to interpret them according to their existential structure, belongs to the scope of tasks of thematical existential anthropology. 17 For the purpose of our inquiry as a study of fundamental ontology, it will be sufficient to outline existentially the authentic potentiality-of-being attested in conscience for Da-sein itself in terms of Da-sein itself. Now that resoluteness has been worked out as a self-projection upon one's ownmost being-guilty in which one is reticent and ready for Ang.st, we are prepared to define the ontological meaning of the authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of Da-sein which we have been looking for. The authenticity of Da-sein is neither an empty term nor a fabricated idea. But even so, as an authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole, the authentic being-toward-death which we have deduced existentially remains a purely existential project for which the attestation of Da-sein is lacking. Only when we have found this attestation, will our inquiry suffice to set forth (as its problematic requires) an authentic potentiality-ofbeing-a-whole of Da-sein, existentially confirmed and clarified. For only when this being has become phenomenally accessible in its authenticity and its wholeness will the question of the meaning of the being of this being, to whose existence belongs an understanding of being as such, be based upon something that will stand a test.
301
III The Authentic PotentialityforBeing-a-Whole of Da-sein, and Temporality as the Ontological Meaning of Care
61. Preliminary Sketch of the Methodical Step from Outlining the Authentic Being-a-Whole of Da-sein to the Phenomenal Exposition of Temporality We projected existentially an authentic potentiality-for-being-a-whole of Da-sein. Analyzing this phenomenon revealed authentic being-towarddeath as anticipation. 1 In its existentiell attestation, the authentic patentiality-of-being of Da-sein was shown to be resoluteness, and at the same time was interpreted existentially. How are we to bring these phenomena of anticipation and resoluteness together? Did our ontological project of the authentic potentiality-for-being-a-whole not lead us to a dimension of Da-sein that is far removed from the phenomenon of regular type resoluteness? What is death supposed to have in common with the "concrete situation" of acting? Does not the attempt to bring resoluteness and anticipation forcibly together lead us astray into an intolerable, completely unphenomenological construction which may no longer even claim to have the character of an ontological project that is phenomenally grounded? Externally binding both phenomena together is intrinsically out of the question. There is still one way out, and this is the only possible
279
302
280
303
Being and Time
II.m
method: to start from the phenomenon of resoluteness, attested in its existentiell possibility, and to ask: Does resoluteness, in its ownmost existentiell tendency of being itself, point ahead to anticipatory resoluteness as its ownmost authentic possibility? What if resoluteness, following its own meaning, were brought into its authenticity only when it no longer projects itself upon arbitrary possibilities merely lying near by, but rather upon the most extreme possibility that lies ahead of every factical potentiality of being of Da-sein, and, as such, more or less enters without distortion every potentiality-of-being of Da-sein factically seized upon? What if resoluteness, as the authentic truth of Da-sein, reached the certainty authentically belonging to it only in the anticipation of death? What if all the factical "anticipatoriness" of resolve were authentically understood, that is, existentielly caught up with only in the anticipation of death? As long as our existential interpretation does not forget that the being given it as its theme has the kind of being of Da-sein, and cannot be joined together out of objectively present pieces into something objectively present, its steps must be guided by the idea of existence. For the question of the possible connection between anticipation and resoluteness, this means nothing less than the demand that we should project these existential phenomena upon the existentiell possibilities prefigured in them and "think these possibilities through" in an existential way. Thus the development of anticipatory resoluteness as an existentielly possible authentic potentiality-for-being-a-whole loses the character of an arbitrary construction. It becomes the interpretation that frees Da-sein for its most extreme possibility of existence. With this step, the existential interpretation at the same time makes known its ownmost methodical character. Apart from occasional, necessary remarks, we have until now deferred explicit discussions of method. We wanted first of all to "proceed" to the phenomena. Before exposing the meaning of being of the being revealed in its fundamental phenomenal content, the course of our inquiry needs to pause, not in order to "rest," but in order to gain new momentum. Any genuine method is grounded in the appropriate preview of the fundamental constitution of the "object" or area of objects to be disclosed. Any genuine reflection on method, which is to be distinguished from empty discussions of technology, thus at the same time tells us something about the kind of being of the being in question.* The clarification of methodical possibilities, requirements, and limits of the existential analytic in general can alone secure the transparency that is necessary if we are to take the basic step of revealing the meaning of
* Distinguish between scientific method and the advance of thinking.
11.111
Being and Time
281
being of care. But the interpretation of the ontological meaning ofcare must be done on the basis of a complete and constant phenomenological reconsideration of the existential constitution of Da-sein set forth up to now. Ontologically, Da-sein is in principle different from everything objectively present and real. Its "content" is not founded in the substantiality of a substance, but in the "self-constancy" [Selbstiindigkeit] of the existing self whose being was conceived as care. The phenomenon of the self included in care needs a primordial and authentic existential definition, in contrast to our preparatory demonstration of the inauthentic they-self. Along with this, we must establish what possible ontological questions are to be directed toward the "self," if it is neither substance nor subject. The phenomenon of care thus sufficiently clarified, can then be interrogated as to its ontological meaning. Defining this meaning will lead to the exposition of temporality. In exhibiting this, we are not led into remote, separate areas of Da-sein; we merely get a conception of the total phenomenal content of the existential fundamental constitution of Da-sein in the ultimate foundations of its own ontological intelligibility. Temporality is experienced as a primordial phenomenon in the authentic beinga-whole of Da-sein, in the phenomenon of anticipatory resoluteness. If temporality makes itself known primordially here, the temporality of anticipatory resoluteness is presumably a distinctive mode of that temporality. Temporality can temporalize itself in various possibilities and various ways. The fundamental possibilities of existence, the authenticity and inauthenticity of Da-sein, are ontologically grounded in possible temporalizations of temporality. If the ontological character of its own being is remote from Da-sein because of the dominance of its entangled understanding of being (being as objective presence), the primordial foundations of this being are still more remote. Thus one must not be surprised if at first glance temporality does not correspond to what is accessible to the vulgar understanding as "time." Thus neither the concept of time of the vulgar experience of time nor the problematic arising from it can function uncritically as a criterion for the appropriateness of an interpretation of time. Rather, our inquiry must become familiar with the primordial phenomenon of temporality beforehand, so that in terms of this we may cast light on the necessity, the source, and the reason for the dominance of the vulgar understanding of time. The primordial phenomenon of temporality will be made secure by demonstrating that all the fundamental structures of Da-sein exposed up to now are to be basically conceived "temporally" with regard to their possible totality, unity, and development, and as modes of the temporalizing of temporality. Thus, when temporality has been exposed, the task
304
282
305
Being and Time
II.m
arises for the existential analytic of retrieving the analysis of Da-sein in the sense of interpreting the essential structures with a view to their temporality. Temporality itself sketches out the fundamental directions of the analyses thus required. Thus the chapter has the following divisions: Anticipatory resoluteness as the existentielly authentic potentiality-forbeing-a-whole of Da-sein (section 62); the hermeneutical situation at which we have arrived for interpreting the meaning of being of care and the methodical character of the existential analytic in general (section 63); care and selfhood (section 64); temporality as the ontological meaning of care (section 65); the temporality ofDa-sein and the tasks arising from it of a primordial retrieve of the existential analytic (section 66).
62. The Existentielly Authentic Potentialityfor-Being-a-Whole of Da-sein as Anticipatory Resoluteness How does resoluteness, "thought out" in accordance with its ownmost tendency of being, lead us to authentic being-toward-death? How is the connection between wanting to have a conscience and the existentially projected, authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of Da-sein to be conceived? Does welding the two together result in a new phenomenon? Or are we left with the resoluteness attested in its existentiell possibility in such a way that it can undergo an existentiell modalization through beingtoward-death? But what does it mean "to think out" the phenomenon of resoluteness existentially? Resoluteness was characterized as the reticent self-projecting upon one's ownmost being-guilty, and as demanding Ang:st of oneself. Beingguilty belongs to Da-sein and means: null being the ground of a nullity. The "guilty" that belongs to the being of Da-sein admits neither of increase nor decrease. It lies before all quantification, if the latter has any meaning at all. Being essentially guilty, Da-sein is not just guilty occasionally and other times not. Wanting-to-have-a-conscience resolves itself for this being-guilty. The intrinsic sense of resoluteness is to project upon itself this being-guilty that Da-sein is as long as it is. Taking over this "guilt" existentielly in resoluteness occurs authentically only if resoluteness in its disclosing of Da-sein has become so transparent that it understands being-guilty as something constant. But this understanding is made possible only in such a way that Da-sein discloses to itself its potentialityof-being "up to its end." The being-at-an-end ofDa-sein, however, means existentially being-toward-the-end. Resoluteness becomes authentically what it can be as being-toward-the-end-that-understands, that is, as anticipation of death. Resoluteness does not simply "have" a connection with anticipation as something other than itself. It harbours in itself authentic being-toward-death as the possible existentiell modality of its own authenticity.
n.nl
Being and Time
283
We want now to clarify this "connection" phenomenally. Resoluteness means: letting oneself be called forth to one's ownmost being-guilty. Being-guilty belongs to the being of Da-sein itself, which we defined primarily as potentiality-of-being. The statement that Da-sein "is" constantly guilty can only mean that it always maintains itself in this being either as authentic or inauthentic existence. Beingguilty is not just a lasting quality of something constantly objectively present, but the existentiell possibility of being authentically or inauthentically guilty. "Guilty" is always only in the actual factical potentiality-ofbeing. Thus, being-guilty must be conceived as a potentiality-for-beingguilty, because it belongs to the being of Da-sein. Resoluteness projects itself upon this potentiality-of-being, that is, understands itself in it. Thus, this understanding stays in a primordial possibility of Da-sein. It stays in it authentically when resoluteness is primordially what it tends to be. But we revealed the primordial being of Da-sein toward its potentiality-of-being as being-toward-death, that is, toward the eminent possibility of Da-sein which we characterized. Anticipation disclosed this possibility as possibility. Thus, resoluteness becomes a primordial being toward the ownmost potentiality-of-being of Da-sein only as anticipatory. Resoluteness understands the "can" of its potentiality-for-being-guilty only when it "qualifies" itself as being-toward-death. Resolutely, Da-sein takes over authentically in its existence the fact that it is the null ground of its nullity. We conceived of death existentially as what we characterized as the possibility of the impossibility of existence, that is, as the absolute nothingness of Da-sein. Death is not pieced on to Da-sein as its "end," but, as care, Da-sein is the thrown (that is, null) ground of its death. The nothingness primordially dominant in the being of Da-sein is revealed to it in authentic being-towarddeath. Anticipation makes being-guilty evident only on the basis of the whole being of Da-sein. Care contains death and guilt equiprimordially. Only anticipatory resoluteness understands the potentiality-for-beingguilty authentically and wholly, that is, primordially. 2 Understanding the call of conscience reveals the lostness in the they. Resoluteness brings Da-sein back to its ownmost potentiality-ofbeing-a-self. One's own potentiality-of-being becomes authentic and transparent in the understanding being-toward-death as the ownmost possibility. The call of conscience passes over all "worldly" status and abilities of Da-sein in its summons. Disregarding those, it individualizes Da-sein down to its potentiality-for-being-guilty which it expects it to be authentically. The unwavering trenchancy with which Da-sein is thus essentially individualized down to its ownmost potentiality-of-being discloses anticipation of death as the nonrelational possibility. Anticipatory reso-
306
307
284
308
Being and Time
II.m
luteness lets the potentiality-for-being-guilty, as its ownmost nonrelational possibility, completely strike into its conscience. Wanting-to-have-a-conscience signifies the readiness for the summons to one's ownmost being-guilty that always already determined factical Da-sein before any factical indebtedness and after that indebtedness has been settled. This prior and constant being guilty, which is constantly with us, does not show itself without being covered over in its character as prior until that priority is placed in the possibility which is for Da-sein absolutely not to be bypassed. When resoluteness, anticipating, has caught up with the possibility of death in its potentiality-of-being, the authentic existence of Da-sein can no longer be left behind by anything. With the phenomenon of resoluteness we were led to the primordial truth of existence. Resolute, Da-sein is revealed to itself in its actual factical potentiality-of-being in such a way that it itself is this revealing and being revealed. To any truth, there belongs a corresponding holdingfor-true. The explicit appropriation of what is disclosed or discovered is being-certain. The primordial truth of existence requires an equiprimordial being-certain in which one holds oneself in what resoluteness discloses. It gives itself the actual factical situation and brings itself into that situation. The situation cannot be calculated in advance and pregiven like something objectively present waiting to be grasped. It is disclosed only in a free act of resolve that has not been determined beforehand, but is open to the possibility of such determination. Wha~ then, does the certainty belonging to such resoluteness mean? This certainty must hold itself in what is disclosed in resolution. But this means that it simply cannot become rigid about the situation, but must understand that the resolution must be kept free and open for the actual factical possibility in accordance with its own meaning as a disclosure. The certainty of the resolution means keeping oneselffree for the possibility of taking it back, a possibility that is always factically necessary. This holding-for-true in resoluteness (as the truth of existence), however, by no means lets us fall back into irresoluteness. On the contrary, this holding-for-true, as a resolute holding oneself free for taking back, is the authentic resoluteness to retrieve itself. But thus one's very lostness in irresoluteness is existentielly undermined. The holding-for-true that belongs to resoluteness tends, in accordance with its meaning, toward constantly keeping itself free, that is, to keep itself free for the whole potentiality-of-being ofDa-sein. This constant certainty is guaranteed to resoluteness only in such a way that it relates to that possibility of which it can be absolutely certain. In its death, Da-sein must absolutely "take itself back." Constantly certain of this, that is, anticipating, resoluteness gains its authentic and whole certainty. But Da-sein is equiprimordially in untruth. Anticipatory resoluteness at the same time gives Da-sein the primordial certainty of its being
II.III
Being and Time
285
closed off. In anticipatory resoluteness, Da-sein holds itself open for its constant lostness in the irresoluteness of the they-a lostness which is possible from the very ground of its own being. As a constant possibility of Da-sein, irresoluteness is also certain. Resoluteness, transparent to itself, understands that the indefiniteness of its potentiality-of-being is always determined only in a resolution with regard to the actual situation. It knows about the indefiniteness that prevails in a being that exists. But this knowledge must itself arise from an authentic disclosure if it is to correspond to authentic resoluteness. Although it always becomes certain in resolution, the indefiniteness of one's own potentiality-of-being, however, always reveals itself completely only in being-toward-death. Anticipation brings Da-sein face to face with a possibility that is constantly certain and yet remains indefinite at every moment as to when this possibility becomes impossibility. Anticipation makes evident the fact that this being has been thrown into the indefiniteness of its "borderline situation," when, resolved upon the latter, Da-sein gains its authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole. The indefiniteness of death discloses itself primordially in Angst. But this primordial Angst strives to expect resoluteness of itself. It clears away every covering over of the fact that Dasein is left to itself. The nothingness before which Angst brings us reveals the nullity that determines Da-sein in its ground, which itself is as thrownness into death. Our analysis revealed in order the moments of modalization toward which resoluteness tends of itself and which stern from authentic beingtoward-death as the ownrnost nonrelational possibility not-to-bebypassed, certain and yet indefinite. It is authentically and completely what it can be only as anticipatory resoluteness. But, conversely, our interpretation of the "connection" between resoluteness and anticipation first attained the complete existential understanding of anticipation itself. Until now, it was valid only as an ontological project. Now we see that anticipation is not a fictitious possibility that we have forced upon Da-sein, but rather a mode of a potentiality-of-being existentielly attested in Da-sein which it expects of itself, if indeed it understands itself authentically as resolute. Anticipation "is" not some kind of unattached behavior, but must rather be conceived of as the possibility of the authenticity of that resoluteness existentielly attested to in such resoluteness-a possibility concealed and thus also attested. Authentic "thinking about death" is wanting to have a conscience, which has become existentielly transparent to itself. If authentic resoluteness tends toward the mode defined by anticipation, and if anticipation constitutes the authentic potentiality-of-beinga-whole of Da-sein; then an authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of Da-sein is also attested in resoluteness existentielly attested. The ques-
309
286
Being and Time
11.111
tion of the potentiality-ofbeing-a-whole is a Jactical, existentiell one. It is answered by Da-sein as resolute. The question of the potentiality-of-being-a-
310
whole of Da-sein has now completely cast off the character which we initially3 pointed out when we treated it as if were just a theoretical, methodical question of the analytic of Da-sein, arising from the attempt to have the whole of Da-sein completely "given." The question of the totality of Da-sein, initially discussed only with regard to ontological method, has its justification, but only because the ground for that justification goes back to an on tic possibility of Da-sein. Our clarification of the "connection" between anticipation and resoluteness in the sense of a possible modalization of resoluteness by anticipation, turned into the phenomenal demonstration of an authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of Da-sein. If with this phenomenon a mode of being of Da-sein has been grasped in which it brings itself to and before itself, it must remain ontically and ontologically unintelligible to the everyday, commonsense interpretation of Da-sein by the they. It would be a misunderstanding to put this existentiell possibility aside as being "unproven" or to want to "prove" it theoretically. Nevertheless, the phenomenon must be shielded from the crudest distortions. Anticipatory resoluteness is not a way out fabricated for the purpose of "overcoming" death, but it is rather the understanding that follows the call of conscience and that frees for death the possibility of gaining power over the existence of Da-sein and of basically dispersing every fugitive self
n.m
Being and Time
287
etration both the presuppositions themselves and that for which they are presuppositions. This is the function that the methodical considerations now demanded of us have.
63. The Hermeneutical Situation at Which We Have Arrived for Interpreting the Meaning of Being of Care, and the Methodical Character of the Existential Analytic in General 1n its anticipatory resoluteness, Da-sein has been made phenomenally vis-
ible with regard to its possible authenticity and totality. The hermeneutical situation• which was previously insufficient for the interpretation of the meaning of being of care, now has the required primordiality. Dasein has been placed in our fore-having primordially, that is, with regard to its authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole; the guiding fore-sight, the idea of existence, has attained its definiteness through the clarification of the ownmost potentiality-of-being; with the concretely developed structure of being of Da-sein, its ontological peculiarity, as opposed to everything objectively present, has become so clear that our fore-grasp on the existentiality of Da-sein possesses sufficient articulation to guide securely the conceptual development of the existentials. The path of the analytic of Da-sein which we have traversed so far has led us to a concrete demonstration of the thesis 5 only suggested at the beginning: The being that we ourselves always are is ontologically farthest from us. The reason for this lies in care itself. Entangled beingtogether-with-the-"world" initially taken care of, guided the everyday interpretation of Da-sein, and covered over ontically the authentic being of Da-sein, thus denying the appropriate basis for an ontology oriented toward this being.* Thus the primordial phenomenal fore-giving of this being is not at all self-evident, even if the ontology initially follows the course of the everyday interpretation of Da-sein. Rather, freeing the primordial being of Da-sein must be wrested from Da-sein in opposition to the entangled, ontic, and ontological tendency of interpretation. Not only the demonstration of the most elemental structures of being-in-the-world, the definition of the concept of world, the clarification of the nearest and most average who of this being, of the they-self, the interpretation of the "there," but above all the analyses of care, death, conscience, and guilt show how the commonsense way of taking care of things has taken over the potentiality-of-being of Da-sein and the disclosure of that potentiality, or rather its closing off.
* Wrong! As if ontology could be taken from what is genuinely ontic. For what is the genuinely ontic if it is not genuinely taken from a pre-ontological projectif all of this is to remain in this distinction.
311
288
312
Being and Time
Il.m
Thus the kind of being of Da-sein requires of an ontological interpretation that has set as its goal the primordiality of the phenomenal demonstration that it be in charge of the being of this being in spite of this being's own tendency to cuver things uver. Thus the existential analytic constantly has the character of doing violence, whether for the claims of the everyday interpretation or for its complacency and its tranquillized obviousness. Of course, this character is especially distinctive of the ontology of Da-sein, but it belongs to any interpretation because the understanding that unfolds in interpretation has the structure of a project. But is not anything of this sort guided and regulated in a way of its own? Where are ontological projects to get the evidence that their "findings" are phenomenally appropriate? Ontological interpretation projects the beings given to it upon the being appropriate to them, so as to bring them to a concept with regard to their structure. Where are the guideposts to direct the projection so that being will be reached at all? And what if the being that is thematic for the existential analytic conceals the being which belongs to it and does so in its very way of being? To answer these questions we must initially restrict ourselves to clarifying the analytic of Da-sein, as the questions themselves demand. Self-interpretation belongs to the being of Da-sein. In the circumspect discovery of the "world" taking care of things, taking care of things is sighted, too. Da-sein always already understands itself factically in def.. inite existentiell possibilities, even if its projects arise only from the common sense of the they. Whether explicitly or not, whether appropriately or not, existence is somehow understood too. Every antic understanding "includes" certain things, even if only pre-ontologically, that is, even if they are not grasped theoretically and thematically. Every ontologically explicit question about the being of Da-sein has already had the way prepared for it by the kind of being of Da-sein. Nevertheless, how are we to find out what constitutes the "authentic" existence of Da-sein? Without an existentiell understanding, all analysis of existentiality remains without foundation. Does not an antic conception of existence underlie our interpretation of the authenticity and totality of Da-sein, an antic interpretation that might be possible, but need not be binding for every one. Existential interpretation will never seek to take over a fiat as to those things that, from an existentiell point of view, are possible or binding. But must it not justify itself with regard to those existentiell possibilities that it uses to give the antic base for the ontological interpretation? If the being of Da-sein is essentially potentiality-of-being and being free for its ownmost possibilities, and if it always exists only in freedom or unfreedom for them, can the ontological interpretation take as its basis anything other than ontic possibilities (modes of potentiality-of-being) and project these upon their ontological
u.m
Being and Time
289
possibility? And if Da-sein mostly interprets itself in terms ofits lostness in taking care of the "world," isn't the determination of the ontic and existentiell possibilities and the existential analysis based upon them (in opposition to that lostness) the mode of its disclosure appropriate to this being? Does not then the violence of this project amount to freeing the undisguised phenomenal content of Da-sein? The "violent" presentation of possibilities of existence may be required for our method, but can it escape being merely arbitrary? If our analytic takes anticipatory resoluteness as its basis, as an existentielly authentic potentiality-of-being, and if Da-sein itself summons to this possibility right out of the ground of its existence, is this possibility then an arbitrary one?* Is the mode of being in accordance with which the potentiality-of-being of Da-sein relates to its eminent possibility, death, picked up by chance? Has being-in-the-world a higher instance of its potentiality-of being than its own death? The antic and ontological project of Da-sein upon an authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole may not be arbitrary, but is the existential interpretation of these phenomena then already justified? Where does this interpretation get its guidelines, if not from a "presupposed" idea of existence in general? How are the steps of the analysis of inauthentic everydayness regulated, if not by the concept of existence that we have posited? And if we say that Da-sein "falls prey," and that thus the authenticity of its potentiality-of-being is to be wrested from this tendency of being-from what perspective are we speaking here? Isn't everything illuminated by the light of the "presupposed" idea of existence, even if rather dimly? Where does this idea get its justification? Has our initial project, in which we called attention to it, led us nowhere? By no means. Our formal indication of the idea of existence was guided by the understanding of being in Da-sein itself. Without any ontological transparency, it was, after all, revealed that I myself am always the being which we call Da-sein, as the potentiality-of-being that is concerned to be this being. Da-sein understands itself as being-in-the-world, although without sufficient ontological definiteness. Thus existing, it encounters beings of the kind of being of things at hand and objectively present. No matter how far removed from an ontological concept the distinction between existence and reality may be, even if Da-sein initially understands existence as reality, Da-sein is not just objectively present, but has always already understood itself, however mythical or magical its interpretations may be. For otherwise, Da-sein would not "live" in a myth and would not take heed of its magic in rites and cults. The idea of exis-
* Probably not; but "not arbitrary" does not mean "necessary and binding."
313
290
314
315
Being and Time
II.m
tence which we have posited gives us an outline of the formal structure of the understanding of Da-sein in general, and does so in a way that is not binding from an existentiell point of view. Under the guidance of this idea the preparatory analysis of the everydayness nearest to us has been carried out as far as a first conceptual definition of care. This phenomenon enabled us to get a more precise grasp of existence and its relations to facticity and falling prey. The definition of the structure of care has given us a basis on which to distinguish ontologically between existence and reality for the first time. 6 This led to the thesis that the substance of human being is existence. 7 But even this formal idea of existence, which is not binding in an existentiell way, already contains a definite though unprofiled ontological "content" that "presupposes" an idea of being in general-just like the idea of reality contrasted with it. Only in the horizon of that idea of being can the distinction between existence and reality be made. After all, both mean being. But is not the ontologically clarified idea of being in general first to be attained by developing the understanding of being that belongs to Da-sein? However, that understanding can be grasped primordially only on the basis of a primordial interpretation of Da-sein guided by the idea of existence. Does it not thus finally become evident that this problem of fundamental ontology that we have set forth is moving in a "circle"? We already showed, in the structure of understanding in general, that what is faulted with the inappropriate expression "circle" belongs to the essence and the distinctiveness of understanding itself. 8 Still, our inquiry must now return explicitly to this "circular" argument if the problematic of fundamental ontology is to have its hermeneutical situation clarified. When it is objected that the existential interpretation is "circular," it is said that the idea of existence and of being in general is "presupposed," and that Da-sein gets interpreted "accordingly" so that the idea of being may be obtained from it. But what does "presupposing" mean? In positing the idea of existence, do we also posit some proposition from which we can deduce further propositions about the being of Da-sein, according to the formal rules of consistency? Or does this pre-supposing have the character of an understanding project in such a way that the interpretation developing this understanding lets what is to be interpreted be put in words for the very first time, so that it may decide of its own accord whether, as this being, it will provide the constitution of being for which it has been disclosed in the projection with regard to its formal aspect? Is there any other way that beings can put themselves into words with regard to their being at all? In the existential analytic, a "circle" in the proof cannot be "avoided," because that analytic is not proving any-
n.m
Being and Time
291
thing according to the rules of logic of consistency at all. What common sense wishes to get rid of by avoiding the "circle," thinking that it does justice to the loftiest rigor of scientific investigation, is nothing less than the basic structure of care. Primordially constituted by care, Da-sein is always already ahead of itself. Existing, it has always already projected itself upon definite possibilities of its existence; and in these existentiell projects it has also projected pre-ontologically something like existence and being- But can one deny this projecting of that research essential to Da-sein, which, like all research itself is a kind of being of disclosive Da-sein, that wants to develop and conceptualize the understanding of being belonging to Da-sein? But the "charge of circularity" itself comes from a kind of being of Da-sein. Something like projecting, especially ontological projecting, necessarily remains foreign for the common sense of our heedful absorption in the they because common sense barricades itself against it "in principle." Whether "theoretically" or "practically," common sense only takes care of beings that are in view of its circumspection. What is distinctive about common sense is that it thinks it experiences only "factual" beings in order to be able to rid itself of its understanding of being. It fails to recognize that beings can be "factually" experienced only when being has already been understood, although not conceptualized. Common sense misunderstands understanding. And for this reason it must also necessarily proclaim as "violent" anything lying beyond the scope of its understanding as well as any move in that direction. The talk about the "circle" in understanding expresses the failure to recognize two things: (1) That understanding itself constitutes a basic kind of the being of Da-sein. (2) That this being is constituted as care. To deny the circle, to make a secret of it or even to wish to overcome it means to anchor this misunderstanding once and for all. Rather, our attempt must aim at leaping into this "circle" primordially and completely, so that even at the beginning of our analysis of Da-sein we make sure that we have a complete view of the circular being of Da-sein. Not too much, but too little is "presupposed" for the ontology of Da-sein, if one "starts out with" a worldless I in order then to provide that I with an object and an ontologically baseless relation to that object. Our view is too short-sighted if we make "life" a problem, and then occasionally also take death into account. The thematic objection is artificially and dogmatically cut out if one limits oneself "initially" to a "theoretical subject," and then complements it "on the practical side" with an additional "ethic." This will suffice to clarify the existential meaning of the hermeneutical situation of a primordial analytic of Da-sein. With the exposition of anticipatory resoluteness Da-sein has been brought before us with regard to its authentic totality. The authenticity of the potentiality-of-being-a-self
316
292
Being and Time
II.m
guarantees the fore-sight of primordial existentiality, and this assures us of coining the appropriate existential concepts. At the same time, the analysis of anticipatory resoluteness led us to the phenomenon of primordial and authentic truth. Earlier we showed how the understanding of being that prevails initially and for the most part conceives being in the sense of objective presence and thus covers over9 the primordial phenomenon of truth. But if "there is" [es gibt] being only when truth "is," and if the understanding of being always varies according to the kind of truth, then primordial and authentic truth must guarantee the understanding of the being of Da-sein and of being in general. The ontological "truth" of the existential analysis is developed on the basis of primordial, existentiell truth. Yet the latter does not necessarily need the former. The most primordial and basic existential truth, for which the problematic of fundamental ontology strives in preparing the question of being in general is the disclosure of the meaning of being of care. In order to reveal this meaning, we need to hold in readiness, undiminished, the full structural content of care.
64. Care and Seljhood 317
The unity of the constitutive moments of care, existentiality, * facticity, and falling prey made possible a first ontological definition of the totality of the structural whole of Da-sein. The structure of care was given an existential formula: being-ahead-of-oneself-already-being-in (a world) as being-together-with (innerworldly beings encountered). The totality of the structure of care does not first arise from a coupling together, yet it is articulated. 10 In assessing this ontological result, we have had to estimate how well it satisfies 11 the requirements of a primordial interpretation of Da-sein. We found that neither the whole of Da-sein nor its authentic potentiality-of-being had been made thematic. However, the attempt to grasp phenomenally the whole of Da-sein seemed to get stranded precisely on the structure of care. The ahead-of-itself presented itself as a not-yet. But the ahead-of-itself, characterized in the sense of something outstanding, revealed itself to our genuine existential reflection as being toward the end, someth~ng that in the depths of its being every Da-sein is. We also made it clear that care summons Da-sein to its ownmost potentiality-of-being in the call of conscience. Understanding the summons revealed itself-primordially understood-as anticipatory resoluteness, which includes an authentic potentiality-of-being-whole of Da-sein. The structure of care does not speak against the possibility of being-a-whole,
* Existence: (1) For the whole of being of Da-sein; (2) only for "understanding."
u.au
Being and Time
293
but is the condition of the possibility of such an existentiell potentiality-ofbeing. In the course of these analyses it became clear that the existential phenomena of death, conscience, and guilt are anchored in the phenomenon of care. The articulation of the totality of the structural whole has become still richer, and thus the existential question of the unity of this totality has become more urgent. How are we to grasp this unity? How can Da-sein exist as a unity in the ways and possibilities of its being that we mentioned? Evidently only in such a way that it itself is this being in its essential possibilities, that I am always* this being. The "I" seems to "hold together" the totality of the structural whole. The "I'' and the "self" have been conceived for a long time in the "ontology" of this being as the supporting ground (substance or subject). Even in its preparatory characterization of everydayness, our analytic also already encountered the question of the who of Da-sein. We found that Da-sein is initially and for the most part not itself, but lost in the they-self. t The they-self is an existentiell modification of the authentic self. The question of the ontological constitution of selfhood remained unanswered. It is true that we already established the guidelines for the problem: 12 If the self belongs to the essential qualities of Da-sein whose "essence," however, lies in existence, then 1-hood and selfhood must be conceived existentially. Negatively, we also saw that our ontological characterization of the they ruled out any application of the categories of objective presence (substance). In principle it became clear that care cannot be derived ontologically from reality or be constructed with the categories of reality. 1 ~ Care already contains the phenomenon of self, if indeed the thesis is correct that the expression "care for self' would be tautological 14 if it were proposed in conformity with concern as care for others. But then the problem of the ontological definition of the selfhood of Da-sein gets sharpened to the question of the existential "connection" between care and selfhood. To clarify the existentiality of the self, we take as our "natural" point of departure the everyday self-interpretation of Da-sein that expresses" itself" in saying-!. Utterance is not necessary. With the "I," this being means itself. t The content of this expression is taken to be absolutely simple. It always means only me, and nothing further . As this simple thing, the "I" is not a definition of other things: it is itself not a predicate, but the absolute "subject." What is expressed and addressed in saying-1 is always met with as the same persisting thing. The charac-
* Da-sein itself is this being. The "I" as what is in a sense "nearest," in the foreground, and thus seemingly the self. : Clarify more precisely: saying-/ and being a self.
t
318
294
319
Being and Time
II.m
teristics of "simplicity," "substantiality," and "personality," which Kant, for example, takes as the foundation for his doctrine "On the paralogisms of pure reason" 15 arise from a genuine "pre-phenomenological" experience. The question remains whether what was experienced in such a way ontically may be interpreted ontologically with the aid of the "categories" mentioned. In strict conformity with the phenomenal content given in saying1, Kant did show that the ontic theses about the substance of the soul inferred from these characteristics are without justification. But in so doing, he merely rejects a wrong ontic explanation of the I.* He has by no means attained an ontological interpretation of selfhood, nor has he obtained some assurance of it and made positive preparations for it. Although Kant attempts, more strictly than his predecessors, to hold on to the phenomenal content of saying I, he does, after all, slip back into the same inappropriate ontology of the substantial, whose_ ontic foundations he theoretically rejected for the I. We must show this more precisely, in order to establish what it means ontologically to take saying I as the point of departure for the analysis of selfhood. The Kantian analysis of the "I think" should now be adduced as an illustration, but only to the extent that it is required for the clarification of the problematic in question. 16 The "I" is a bare consciousness that accompanies all concepts. In the I, nothing more is represented than a transcendental subject of thoughts. "Consciousness in itself (is) not a representation ... , but a form of representation in general. " 17 The "I think" is "the form of apperception that adheres to every experience and precedes it. " 18 Kant grasps the phenomenal content of the "I" correctly in the expression "I think" or-if the relation of the "practical person" to "intelligence" is also considered-in the expression "I act." In Kant's sense saying-1 must be conceived as saying I think. Kant attempts to establish the phenomenal content of the I as res cogitans. If he then calls this I a "logical subject," that does not mean that the I in general is a concept gained merely by logical means. Rather, the I is the subject of logical behavior, of binding together. The "I think" means I bind together. All binding together is an "/bind together." In any taking together and relating, the I always already underlies-hupokeimenon. Thus the subject is "consciousness in itself," not a representation,t but rather the "form" of representation. That means that the I think is not something repre*And being intent upon ontic-suprasensuous statements (Metaphysica specialis). Not something re-presented, but what represents as what-places-something-beforeitself in representing-but only in this, and the I "is" only as this before-itself, only as this itseljness. t
n.m
Being and Time
295
sented, but the formal structure of representing as such, and this formal structure alone makes it possible for anything to be represented. The form of representation means neither a framework nor a universal concept, but that which, as eidos, makes everything represented and every representing be what it is. If the I is understood as the form of representation, this amounts to saying that it is the "logical subject." Kant's analysis has two positive aspects: on the one hand, he sees the impossibility of ontically reducing the I to a "substance." On the other hand, he holds fast to the I as "I think." Nevertheless, he conceives this I again as subject, thus in an ontologically inappropriate sense. For the ontological concept of the subject does not characterize the seljhood of the I qua self, but the sameness and constancy of something always already objectively present. To define the I ontologically as a subject means to posit it as something always already objectively present. The being of the I is understood as the reality* of the res cogitans. 19 But what is the reason that while the "I think" gives Kant a genuine phenomenal point of departure, he cannot exploit it ontologically, but is forced to fall back upon the "subject," that is, something substantial? The I is not only an "I think," but an "I think something." However, does not Kant himself emphasize again and again that the I remains related to its representations, and would be nothing without them? But for Kant these representations are the "empirical," which is "accompanied" by the 1-the appearances to which the I is "connected." But nowhere does Kant show the kind of being of this "connection" and "accompanying." At bottom, however, their kind of being is understood as the constant objective presence of the I together with its representations. Kant did avoid cutting off the I from thinking, but without positing the "I think" itself in its full essential content as "I think something," and above all without seeing the ontological "presupposition" for the "I think something" as the fundamental determination of the self. t For even the point of departure of the "I think something" is not definite enough ontologically, because the "something" remains indefinite. If by this something we understand an innerworldly being, it tacitly implies that world has been presupposed; this very phenomenon of the world also determines the constitution of being of the I, if indeed it is to be possible for the I to be something like an "I think something." Saying! means the being that I always am as "l-am-in-a-world." Kant did not see the phenomenon of world and was consistent enough to keep the "representations" at a distance from the a priori content of the "I think." But thus the I again was forced back to an isolated subject that accom-
* "Presence"; constant "accompanying." t
That is, temporality.
320
321
296
322
Being and Time
II.m
panies representations in a way that is ontologically quite indefinite.20 In saying-/, Da-sein expresses itself as being-in-the-world. But does everyday saying-! take itself as being-in-the-world [in-der-Welt-seiend]? Here we must make a distinction. Surely in saying-I Da-sein means the being that it itself always is. But the everyday interpretation of the self has the tendency to understand itself in terms of the "world" taken care of. When Da-sein has itself in view ontically, it fails to see itself in relation to the kind of being of the being that it itself is. And that is particularly true of the fundamental constitution ofDa-sein, being-in-the-world.21 How is this "fleeting" saying-! motivated? By the entanglement of Da-sein, for as falling prey it flees from itself to the they. The "natural" talk about the I takes place in the they-self. What expresses itself in the "I'' is that self that, initially and for the most part, I am not authentically. When one is absorbed in the everyday multiplicity and rapid succession of what is taken care of, the self of the self-forgetful "I take care of' shows itself as what is constantly and identically simple, but indefinite and empty. One is, after all, what one takes care of. The fact that the "natural" ontic way of saying-! overlooks the phenomenal content of Da-sein that one has in view in the I does not give the ontological interpretation of the I the right to go along with this oversight and to force an inappropriate "categorial" horizon upon the problematic of the self. Of course, by refusing to go along with the everyday way in which the I talks, our ontological interpretation of the "I'' has by no means solved the problem; but it has indeed prescribed the direction for further questioning. The I is the being that one is in "being-in-the-world." Already-being in-a-world as being-together-with-innerworldly-things-athand means, however, equiprimordially being-ahead-of-oneself. "I" means the being that is concerned about the being of the being which it is. Care expresses itself with the "I'' initially and for the most part in the "fleeting" talk about the I in taking care of things. The they-self keeps on saying I most loudly and frequently because at bottom it is not authentically itself and evades its authentic potentiality-of-being. If the ontological constitution of the self can neither be reduced to a substantial I nor to a "subject," but if, on the contrary, the everyday, fleeting saying-! must be understood in terms of our authentic potentiality-of-being, the statement still does not follow that the self is the constantly objectively present ground of care. Existentially, selfhood is only to be found in the authentic potentiality-of-being-a-self, that is, in the authenticity of the being of Da-sein as care. In terms of care the constancy [Standigkeit] of the self, as the supposed persistence of the subject, gets its clarification. The phenomenon of this authentic potentiality-of-being, however, also opens our eyes to the constancy of the self in the sense of its having gained a stand. The constancy of the self in the double sense of constancy and steadfastness is the authentic
Being and Time
D.DI
297
counter-possibility to the lack of constancy [Unselbst-stiindigkeit] of irresolute falling prey. Existentially, the constancy of the self [Selbst-stiindigkeit] means nothing other than anticipatory resoluteness. Its ontological structure reveals the existentiality of the selfhood of the self. Da-sein is authentically itselfin the mode of primordial individuation of reticent resoluteness that expects Angst* of itself. In keeping silent, authentic being-one's-self does not keep on saying "1," but rather "is" in reticence the thrown being that it can authentically be. The self that is revealed by the reticence of resolute existence is the primordial phenomenal basis for the question of the being of the "I." Only if we are phenomenally oriented toward the meaning of being of the authenticpotentiality-of-being-a-self are we put in a position to discuss what ontological justification there is for treating substantiality, simplicity, and personality as characteristics of selfhood. The ontological question of the being of the self must be extricated from the forehaving, constantly suggested by the predominant way of saying-I, of a persistently objectively present self-thing. Care does not need a foundation in a self. But existentiality as a constituent of care gives the ontological constitution of the self-constancy of Dasein to which there belongs, corresponding to the complete structural content of care, the factical falling prey to unself-constancy. The structure of care, conceived in full, includes the phenomenon of selfhood. This phenomenon is clarified by interpreting the meaning of care which we defined as the totality of being of Da-sein .
323
65. Temporality as the Ontological Meaning of Care In characterizing the "connection" between care and selfhood, our aim was not only to clarify the special problem of 1-hood but also to help in the fmal preparation for phenomenally grasping the totality of the structural whole of Da-sein. We need the unwavering discipline of the existential line of questioning if, for our ontological viewpoint, the kind of being of Da-sein is not finally to be distorted into a mode of objective presence, even if it is quite undifferentiated. Da-sein becomes "essential" in authentic existence that is constituted as anticipatory resoluteness. This mode of the authenticity of care contains the primordial selfconstancy and totality of Da-sein. We must take an undistracted look at these and understand them existentially if we are to expose the ontological meaning of the being of Da-sein. What are we looking for ontologically with the meaning of care? What does meaning signify? Our inquiry encountered this phenomenon
* That is, the clearing of being as being.
324
298
325
Being and Time
II.m
in the context of the analysis of understanding and interpretation. 22 According to that analysis, meaning is that in which the intelligibility of something keeps itself, without coming into view explicitly and thematically. Meaning signifies that upon which the primary project is projected, that in terms of which something can be conceived in its possibility as what it is. Projecting discloses possibilities, that is, it discloses what makes something possible. To expose that upon which a project is projected, means to disclose what makes what is projected possible. This exposure requires that we methodically pursue the project (usually an inexplicit one) underlying an interpretation in such a way that what is projected in the project is disclosed and conceivable with regard to its upon-which. To set forth the meaning of care, then, means to pursue the project underlying and guiding the primordial existential interpretation of Da-sein in such a way that its upon-which becomes visible in what is projected. What is projected is the being of Da-sein, disclosed in what constitutes it as an authentic potentiality-for-being-a-whole. The upon-which of what is projected, of the disclosed being thus constituted, is what itself makes possible this constitution of being as care. With the question of the meaning of care, we are asking what makes possible the totality of the articulated structural whole of care in the unity of its unfolded articulation? Strictly speaking, meaning signifies the upon-which of the primary project of the understanding of being. Being-in-the-world that is disclosed to itself equiprimordially understands the being of innerworldly beings together with the being of the being that it itself is, although unthematically and not yet differentiated in its primary modes of existence and reality. Every on tic experience of beings, the circumspect calculation of things at hand as well as the positive scientific cognition of things objectively present, are always grounded in the more or less transparent projects of the being of the beings in question. But these projects contain an uponwhich from which, so to speak, the understanding of being is nourished. If we say that beings "have meaning," this signifies that they have become accessible in their being, and this being, projected upon its uponwhich, is what "really" "has meaning" first of all. Beings "have" meaning only because, as being that has been disclosed beforehand, they become intelligible in the project of that being, that is, in terms of the uponwhich of this project. The primary project of the understanding of being "gives" meaning. The question of the meaning of the being of a being takes as its theme the upon-which of the understanding of being that underlies all being of beings. Da-sein is disclosed to itself authentically or inauthentically with regard to its existence. Existing, it understands itself in such a way that this understanding does not just grasp something, but constitutes the exis-
n.ul
Being and Time
299
tentiell being of its factical potentiality-of-being. The being that is disdosed is that of a being that is concerned about its being. The meaning of this being-that is, care-is what makes care possible in its constitution, and it is what primordially makes up the being of this potentiality-of-being. The meaning of being of Da-sein is not something different from it, unattached and "outside" of it, but is self-understanding Da-sein itself. What makes possible the being of Da-sein, and thus its factical existence? What is projected in the primordial existential project of existence revealed itself as anticipatory resoluteness.* What makes possible this authentic being-a-whole of Da-sein with regard to the unity of its articulated structural whole? Expressed formally and existentially, without constantly naming the complete structural content, anticipatory resoluteness is the being tuward one's ownmost, eminent potentiality-of-being. Something like this is possible only in such way that Da-sein can come toward itself at all in its ownmost possibility and perdure the possibility as possibility in this letting-itself-come-toward-itself, that is, that it exists. Letting-come-toward-itself that perdures the eminent possibility is the primordial phenomenon of the future. If authentic or inauthentic beingtuward-death belongs to the being of Da-sein, this is possible only as futural in the sense indicated now and to be more closely defined later. Here "future" does not mean a now that has not yet become "actual" and that sometime will be for the first time, but the coming in which Dasein comes toward itself in its ownmost potentiality-of-being. Anticipation makes Da-sein authentically futural in such a way that anticipation itself is possible only in that Da-sein, as existing, always already comes toward itself, that is, is futural in its being in general. Anticipatory resoluteness understands Da-sein in its essential beingguilty. This understanding means to take over being-guilty while existing, to be the thrown ground of nullity. But to take over thrownness means to authentically be Da-sein in the way that it always already was. Taking over thrownness, however, is possible only in such a way that futural Da-sein can be its ownmost "how it always already was," that is, its "having-been." Only because Da-sein in general is as I am-having-been, can it come futurally toward itself in such a way that it comes-back. Authentically futural, Da-sein is authentically having-been. Anticipation of the most extreme and ownmost possibility comes back understandingly to one's ownmost having-been. Da-sein can be authentically having-been only because it is futural. In a way, having-been arises from the future. Anticipatory resoluteness discloses the actual situation of the there in such a way that existence circumspectly takes care of the factical
* Ambiguous: existentiell project and existential self-engagement projecting itself into that project go together.
326
300
327
Being and Time
II.m
things at hand in the surrounding world in action. Resolute being together with what is at hand in the situation, that is, letting what presences in the surrounding world be encountered in action, is possible only in a making that being present. Only as the present, in the sense of making present, can resoluteness be what it is, namely, the undistorted letting what it grasps in action be encountered. Futurally coming back to itself, resoluteness brings itself to the situation in making it present. Having-been arises from the future in such a way that th<; future that has-been (or better, is in the process of having-been) releases the present from itself. We call the unified phenomenon of the future that makes present in the process of havingbeen temporality. Only because Da-sein is determined as temporality does it make possible for itself the authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of anticipatory resoluteness which we characterized. Temporality reveals itself a.s the meaning of authentic care. The phenomenal content of this meaning, drawn from the constitution of being of anticipatory resoluteness, fulfills the significance of the term temporality. We must now keep the terminological use of this expression at a distance from all of the meanings of "future," "past," and "present" initially urging themselves upon us from the vulgar concept of time. That is also true of the concepts of a "subjective" and an "objective," or an "immanent" and "transcendent" "time." Since Da-sein understands itself initially and for the most part inauthentically, we may suppose that the "time" of the vulgar understanding of time indeed presents a genuine phenomenon, but a derivative one. It arises from inauthentic temporality that has an origin of its own. The concepts of "future," "past," and "present" initially grew out of the inauthentic understanding of time. The terminological definition of the corresponding primordial and authentic phenomena battles with the same difficulty in which all ontological terminology is stuck. In this field of inquiry, forcing things is not an arbitrary matter, but a necessity rooted in facts. However, in order to demonstrate the origin of inauthentic temporality from primordial and authentic temporality without any gap, we first need to work out correctly the primordial phenomenon concretely, which we have thus far only sketched out roughly. If resoluteness constitutes the mode of authentic care, and if it is itself possible only through temporality, the phenomenon at which we arrived by considering resoluteness must itself only present a modality of temporality, which makes care possible in general. The totality of being of Da-sein as care means: Ahead-of-itself-already-being-in (a world) as being-together-with (beings encountered within the world). In first estalr lishing this articulated structure, we referred to the fact that with regard to this articulation the ontological question had to be taken back further
II.III
Being and Time
301
to the exposition of the unity of the totality of the structural manifold. 23 The primordial unity of the structure of care lies in temporality. Being-ahead-of-oneself is grounded in the future. Already-beingin ... makes known having-been. Being-together-with ... is made possible in making present. After what we have said, it is automatically ruled out to conceive the "ahead" in the "ahead-of-itself" and the "already" in terms of the vulgar understanding of time. The "ahead" does not mean the "before" in the sense of a "not-yet-now, but later." Nor does the "already" mean a "no-longer-now, but earlier." If the expressions "ahead of" and "already" had this temporal meaning, which they can also have, then we would be saying about the temporality of care that it is something that is "earlier" and "later," "not yet" and "no longer" at the same time. Then care would be conceived as a being that occurs and elapses "in time." The being of a being of the nature of Dasein would then turn into something objectively present. If this is impossible, the temporal significance of these expressions must be a different one. The "before" and the "ahead of" indicate the future that first makes possible in general the fact that Da-sein can be in such a way that it is concerned about its potentiality-of-being. The self-project grounded in the "for the sake of itself" in the future is an essential quality of existentiality. Its primary meaning is the future. Similarly, the "already" means the existential, temporal meaning of being of the being that, in that it is, is always already something thrown. Only because care is grounded in having-been, can Da-sein exist as the thrown being that it is. "As long as" Da-sein factically exists, it is never past, but is always already having-been in the sense of "l-am-as-havingbeen." And only as long as Da-sein is, can it be as having-been. On the other hand, we call beings past that are no longer objectively present. Thus existing Da-sein can never ascertain itself as an objectively present fact that comes into being and passes away "with time," and is already partially past. It always "finds itself" only as a thrown fact. In attunement Da-sein is invaded by itself as the being that it still is and already was, that is, that it constantly is as having been. The primary existential meaning of facticity lies in having-been. The formulation of the structure of care indicates the temporal meaning of existentiality offacticity with the expressions "before" and "already." On the other hand, such an indication is lacking for the third constitutive factor of care: entangled being-together-with .... That is not supposed to mean that falling prey is not also grounded in temporality; it should instead intimate that making present, as the primary basis for the falling prey to things at hand and objectively present that we take care of, remains included in the future and in having-been in the mode of primordial temporality. Resolute, Da-sein has brought itself back out of
328
302
329
Being and Time
II.m
falling prey in order to be all the more authentically "there" for the disclosed situation in the "Moment" [Augenblick]. Temporality makes possible the unity of existence, facticity, and falling prey and thus constitutes primordially the totality of the structure of care. The factors of care are not pieced together cumulatively, any more than temporality itself has first been put together out of future, past, and present "in the course of time." Temporality "is" not a being at all. It is not, but rather temporalizes itself. Nevertheless, we still cannot avoid saying that "temporality 'is' the meaning of care," "temporality 'is' determined thus and so." The reason for this can be made intelligible only when we have clarified the idea of being and the "is" as such. Temporality temporalizes, and it temporalizes possible ways of itself. These make possible the multiplicity of the modes of being of Da-sein, in particular the fundamental possibility of authentic and inauthentic existence. Future, having-been, and present show the phenomenal characteristics of "toward itself," "back to," "letting something be encountered." The phenomena of toward ... , to ... , together with ... reveal temporality as the ekstatikon par excellence. Temporality is the primordial "outside of itself' in and for itself. Thus we call the phenomena of future, havingbeen, and present, the ecstasies of temporality. Temporality is not, prior to this, a being that first emerges from itself, its essence is temporalizing in the unity of the ecstasies. What is characteristic of the "time" accessible to the vulgar understanding consists, among other things, precisely in the fact that it is a pure succession of nows, without beginning and without end, in which the ecstatic character of primordial temporality is levelled down. But this very levelling down, in accordance with its existential meaning, is grounded in the possibility of a definite kind of temporalizing, in conformity with which temporality temporalizes as inauthentic the kind of "time" we have just mentioned Thus if we demonstrate that the "time" accessible to the common sense of Da-sein is not primordial, but arises rather from authentic temporality, then, according to the principle a potiori fit denominatio, we are justified in calling the temporality now set forth primordial time. In enumerating the ecstasies, we have always mentioned the future first. That should indicate that the future has priority in the ecstatic unity of primordial and authentic temporality, although temporality does not first originate through a cumulative sequence of the ecstasies, but always temporalizes itself in their equiprimordiality. But within this equiprimordiality, the modes of temporalizing are different. And the difference lies in the fact that temporalizing can be primarily determined out of the different ecstasies. Primordial and authentic temporality temporalizes itself out of the authentic future, and indeed in such a way that,
Il.lll
Being and Time
303
euturally having-been, it first arouses the present. The primary phenomenon of primordial and authentic temporality is the future. The priority of the future will itself vary according to the modified temporalizing of inauthentic temporality, but it will still make its appearance in derivative "time." Care is being-toward-death. We defined anticipatory resoluteness as authentic being toward the possibility that we characterized as the absolute impossibility of Da-sein. In this being-toward-the-end, Da-sein exists authentically and totally as the being that it can be when "thrown into death." It does not have an end where it just stops, but it exists finitely. The authentic future, which is temporalized primarily by that temporality which constitutes the meaning of anticipatory resoluteness, thus reveals itself as finite. But, in spite of my no longer being there, "does time not go on?" And can there not be an unlimited number of things that still lie "in the future" and arrive from it? These question are to be answered in the affirmative. Nevertheless, they do not contain any objection to the finitude of primordial temporality because they no longer deal with that at all. The question is not how many things can still occur "in an ongoing time," or about what kind of a "letting-come-toward-oneself" we can encounter "out of this time," but about how the coming-toward-oneself is itself to be primordially detennined as such. Its finitude does not primarily mean a stopping, but is a characteristic of temporalizing itself. The primordial and authentic future is the toward-oneself, toward oneself, existing as the possibility of a nullity not-to-be-bypassed. The ecstatic quality of the primordial future lies precisely in the fact that it closes the potentiality-ofbeing, that is, the future is itself closed and as such makes possible the resolute existentiell understanding of nullity. Primordial and authentic coming-toward-oneself is the meaning of existing in one's ownmost nullity. With the thesis of the primordial finitude of temporality, we are not contesting the fact that "time goes on." We are simply holding fast to the phenomenal quality of primordial temporality that shows itself in what is projected in the primordial existential project of Da-sein. The temptation to overlook the finitude of the primordial and authentic future and thus the finitude of temporality, or to think a priori that finitude is impossible, arises from the constant intrusion of the vulgar understanding of time. If the latter is justifiably familiar with an endless time, and only with that, it has not yet been demonstrated that it also understands this time and its "infinity." What does it mean to say that time "goes on" and "keeps passing away"? What does "in time" mean in general, and "in the future" and "out of the future" in particular? In what sense is "time" endless? These things require clarification if the vulgar objections to the finitude of primordial time are not to
330
304
331
Being and TitlU!
II.m
remain without foundation. But we can clear them up only if we have obtained the appropriate line of questioning with regard to finitude and in finitude. However, this line of questioning arises only if we view the primordial phenomenon of time understandingly. The problem is not how does "derivative," infinite time, "in which" objectively present things come into being and pass away, become primordial, finite temporality, but rather, how does inauthentic temporality, as inauthentic, temporalize an infinite time out of finite time? Only because primordial time is finite can "derivative" time temporalize itself as infinite. In the order in which we grasp things through the understanding, the finitude of time does not become fully visible until we have set forth "endless time" so that these may be contrasted. Let us summarize the analysis of primordial temporality in the following theses: Time is primordial as the temporalizing of temporality, and makes possible the constitution of the structure of care. Temporality is essentially ecstatic. Temporality temporalizes itself primordially out of the future. Primordial time is finite. Yet the interpretation of care as temporality cannot remain restricted to the narrow basis we have so far attained, although it did take the first steps toward the primordial, authentic being-a-whole of Da-sein. The thesis that the meaning of Da-sein is temporality must be confirmed by the concrete content of the fundamental constitution of this being which we have set forth.
66. The Temporality oJDa-sein and the Tasks Arisingfrom It of a More Primordial Retrieve of the Existential Analysis
332
The phenomenon of temporality which we have set forth requires not only a more wide-ranging confirmation of its constitutive power, it itself thus comes to view with regard to the fundamental possibilities of temporalization. We shall briefly call the demonstration of the possibility of the constitution of being of Da-sein on the basis of temporality, the "temporal" interpretation, although this is only a provisional term. Our next task is to go beyond the temporal analysis of the authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of Da-sein and a general characterization of the temporality of care, so that the inauthenticity of Da-sein may be made visible in its specific temporality. Temporality first showed itself in anticipatory resoluteness. That is the authentic mode of disclosedness that for the most part stays within the inauthenticity of the entangled self-interpretation of the they. The nature of the temporality of disclosedness in general leads to the temporal understanding of that heedful being-in-the-world nearest to us, and thus of the average indifference ofDa-sein from which the existential analytic first started.24 We
II.lll
Being and Time
305
called the average kind of being of Da-sein, in which it initially and for the most part stays, everydayness. By retrieving our earlier analysis, everydayness must be revealed in its temporal meaning so that the problematic included in temporality may come to light and the seeming "obviousness" of our preparatory analyses may disappear completely. Indeed, confirmation is to be found for temporality in all the essential strUctures of the fundamental constitution of Da-sein. Yet that does not lead us to repeat our analyses in the same external schema in the order of their presentation. The course of our temporal analysis has a different direction. It is to make the connection of our earlier reflections clearer and to remove their chance character and seeming arbitrariness. However, beyond these necessities of method, there are valid motives in the phenomenon itself that compel us to articulate our analysis in a different way when we retrieve it. The ontological strUcture of the being that I myself always am is centered in the self-constancy of existence. Because the self cannot be conceived either as substance or as subject, but is rather grounded in existence, our analysis of the inauthentic self, the they, was left completely in the train of the preparatory interpretation of Da-sein. 25 Now that selfhood has been explicitly taken back into the structure of care, and thus of temporality, the temporal interpretation of self-constancy and the lack of self-constancy acquires an importance of its own. It requires a special thematic development. But it not only gives us the right protections against the paralogisms and the ontologically inappropriate question about the being of the I in general; at the same time it provides us, in accordance with its central function, with a more primordial insight into the structure of the temporalizing of temporality. Temporality reveals itself as the historicity of Da-sein. The statement that Da-sein is historical is confirmed as an existential and ontological fundamental proposition. It is far removed from merely ontically ascertaining the fact that Dasein occurs in a "world history." The historicity of Da-sein, however, is the ground of a possible historiographical understanding that in its tum harbors the possibility of getting a special grasp of the development of historiography as a science. The temporal interpretation of everydayness and historicity secures the view of primordial time sufficiently to uncover it as the condition of the possibility and necessity of the everyday experience of time. Da-sein expends itself primarily for itself as a being that is concerned about its being, whether explicitly or not. Initially and for the most part, care is circumspect taking care of things. Expending itself for the sake of itself, Da-sein "uses itself up." Using itself up, Da-sein uses itself, that is, its time. Using its time, it reckons with it. Taking care of things which is circumspect and reckoning, initially discovers time and develops a mea-
333
306
Being and Time
II.m
surement of time. Measurement of time is constitutive for being-in-theworld. Measuring its time, the discovering of circumspection which takes care of things lets what it discovers at hand and objectively present be encountered in time. Innerworldly beings thus become accessible as "existing in time." We shall call the temporal quality of innerworldly beings "within-time-ness." The "time" initially found therein ontically becomes the basis for the development of the vulgar and traditional concept of time. But time as within-time-ness arises from an essential kind of temporalization of primordial temporality. This origin means that the time "in which" objectively present things come into being and pass away is a genuine phenomenon of time; it is not an extemalization of a "qualitative time" into space, as Bergson's interpretation of time-which is ontologically completely indeterminate and insufficientwould have it. The elaboration of the temporality of Da-sein as everydayness, historicity, and within-time-ness first gives uncluttered insight into the complexities of a primordial ontology of Da-sein. As being-in-the-world Dasein exists factically together with beings encountered within the world. Thus the being of Da-sein gets its comprehensive ontological transparency only in the horizon of the clarified being of beings unlike Dasein, that is, even of what is not at hand and not objectively present, but only "subsists." But if the variations of being are to be interpreted for everything of which we say that it is, we need beforehand a sufficiently clarified idea of being in general. As long as we have not reached this, the retrieve of the temporal analysis of Da-sein will remain incomplete and marred by lack of clarity, not to speak extensively of the factual difficulties. The existential-temporal analysis of Da-sein requires in its tum a new retrieve in the context of a fundamental discussion of the concept of being.
IV Temporality and Everydayness
334
6 7. The Basic Content of the Existential Constitution of Da-sein, and the Preliminary Sketch of Its Temporal Interpretation Our preparatory analysis 1 has made accessible a multiplicity of phenomena that must not disappear from our phenomenological view, in spite of our concentration on the foundational structural totality of care. Far from excluding such a multiplicity, the primordial totality of the constitution of being of Da-sein as articulated demands it. The primordiality of the constitution of Da-sein does not coincide with the simplicity and uniqueness of an ultimate structural element. The ontological origin of the being of Da-sein is not "less" than that which arises from it, but exceeds it in power from the beginning. Any "arising" in the field of ontology is degeneration. The ontological penetration to the "origin" does not arrive at things which are ontically self-evident for the "common understanding," but rather it is precisely this that opens up the questionability of everything self-evident. In order to bring the phenomena at which we arrived in our preparatory analysis back to a phenomenological view, a reference to the stages we have gone through will suffice. The delineation of care emerged from our analysis of the disclosedness that constitutes the being of the "there." The clarification of this phenomenon signified that a preliminary interpretation of the basic constitution of Da-sein of being-in-the-world was necessary. Our inquiry began with a characterization of being-in-the-world, and then went on to secure from the very beginning an adequate phenomenal horizon as opposed to the inap-
307
308
335
Being and Time
II.IV
propriate ontological predeterminations of Da-sein that are mostly inexplicit. Being-in-the-world was initially characterized with regard to the phenomenon of the world. Indeed, our explication moved from an ontic and ontological characterization of the things at hand and objectively present "in" the surrounding world to a delineation of innerworldliness, thus making the phenomenon of worldliness in general visible in innerworldliness. But the structure of worldliness, significance, turned out to be coupled with that upon which the understanding essentially belonging to disclosedness projects itself, with the potentiality-ofbeing of Da-sein for the sake of which it exists. The temporal interpretation of everyday Da-sein must begin with the structures in which disclosedness constitutes itself. These are: understanding, attunement, entanglement, and discourse. The modes of the temporalizing of temporality to be exposed with regard to these phenomena provide the basis for defining the temporality of being-in-theworld. This leads again to the phenomenon of the world and permits us to delineate the specifically temporal problematic of worldliness. It must be confirmed by characterizing the everyday being-in-the-world nearest to us-by entangled, circumspect taking care of things. The temporality of taking care of things makes it possible for circumspection to be modified into a perceiving that looks at things and the theoretical knowledge based on such perceiving. The temporality of being-in-the-world that thus emerges at the same time turns out to be the foundation of the specific spatiality of Da-sein. The temporal constitution of de-distancing and directionality must be shown. The whole of these analyses reveals a possibility of temporalizing of temporality in which the inauthenticity of Da-sein is ontologically grounded, and leads to the question of how the temporal nature of everydayness-the temporal meaning of the "initially and for the most part," which we have continually been using-is to be understood. Fixing upon this problem makes clear that the clarification of the phenomenon that we have so far attained is not sufficient, and we shall show the extent of this insufficiency. The present chapter thus has the following articulation: the temporality of disclosedness in general (section 68); the temporality of being-in-the-world and the problem of transcendence (section 69); the temporality of the spatiality commensurate with Da-sein (section 70); the temporal meaning of the everydayness commensurate with Da-sein (section 71). 68. The Temporality of Disclosedness in General
Resoluteness, which we characterized with regard to its temporal meaning, represents an authentic disclosedness of Da-sein. Disclosedness con-
II. IV
Being and Time
309
stitutes a being in such a way that, existing, it can be itself its "There." Care was characterized with respect to its temporal meaning only in its basic features. To demonstrate its concrete temporal constitution means to interpret temporally its individual structural moments, that is, understanding, attunement, entanglement, and discourse. Every understanding has its mood. Every attunement understands. Attuned understanding has the characteristic of entanglement. Entangled, attuned understanding articulates itself with regard to its intelligibility in discourse. The actual temporal constitution of these phenomena always leads back to that one temporality that holds within itself the possible structural unity of understanding, attunement, entanglement, and discourse.
(a) The Temporality of Understanding. 2 With the term understanding we mean a fundamental existential; neither a definite kind of cognition, as distinct from explaining and conceiving, nor a cognition in general in the sense of grasping something thematically. Understanding constitutes the being of the There in such a way that, on the basis of such understanding, a Da-sein in existing can develop the various possibilities of sight, of looking around, and of just looking. As the understanding discovery of what is unintelligible, all explanation is rooted in the primary understanding of Da-sein. Formulated primordially and existentially, understanding means: to be projecting toward a potentiality-ofbeingfor the sake of which Da-sein always exists. Understanding discloses one's own potentiality-of-being in such a way that Da-sein always somehow knows understandingly what is going on with itself. This "knowing," however, does not mean that it has discovered some fact, but that it holds itself in an existentiell possibility. The ignorance corresponding to this does not consist in a failure to understand, but must be taken as a deficient mode of the projectedness of one's potentiality-of-being. Existence can be questionable. If it is to be possible for something "to be in question," a disclosedness is necessary. When one understands oneself projectively in an existentiell possibility, the future underlies this understanding, and it does so as a coming-toward-oneself from the actual possibility as which Da-sein always exists. The future makes ontologically possible a being that is in such a way that it exists understandingly in its potentiality-of-being. Projecting, which is fundamentally futural, does not primarily grasp the projected possibility thematically by opening it, but throws itself into it as possibility. Understandingly, Da-sein always is as it can be. Resoluteness turned out to be primordial and authentic existing. Of course, initially for the most part Da-sein remains irresolute, that is, it remains closed off from its ownmost potentiality-of-being to which it always brings itself
336
310
337
Being and Time
ll.IV
only in individuation. This means that temporality does not temporalize itself constantly out of the authentic future. However, this inconstancy does not mean that temporality at times lacks the future, but rather that the temporalizing of the future is changeable. We shall retain the expression anticipation for the terminological characterization of the authentic future. It indicates that Da-sein, authentically existing, lets itself come toward itself as its ownmost potentialityof-being-that the future must first win itself, not from a present, but from the inauthentic future. The formally neutral term for the future lies in the designation of the first structural factor of care, in being-ahead-of itself. Factically, Da-sein is constantly ahead-of-itself, but in its existentiell possibility inconstantly anticipatory. How is the inauthentic future to be contrasted with this? As the authentic future is revealed in resoluteness, the inauthentic future, as an ecstatic mode, can reveal itself only by going back ontologically from the everyday, inauthentic understanding taking care of things to its existential and temporal meaning. As care, Da-sein is essentially ahead-ofitself. Initially and for the most part, the being-in-the-world that takes care understands itself in terms of what it takes care of. Inauthentic understanding projects itself upon what can be taken care of, what can be done, what is urgent or indispensable in the business of everyday activity. But what is taken care of is as it is for the sake of the potentiality-ofbeing that cares. This potentiality lets Da-sein come toward itself in its heedful being together with what is to be taken care of. Da-sein does not come toward itself primarily in its ownmost, nonrelational potentialityof-being, but it awaits this heedfully in terms of that which what is taken care ofproduces or denies. Da-sein comes toward itself in terms of what is taken care of. The inauthentic future has the character of awaiting. The selfunderstanding of the they that takes care in terms of what one is doing, has the "ground" of its possibility in this ecstatic mode of the future. And only because factical Da-sein is thus awaiting its potentiality-for-being in terms of what is taken care of, can it expect and wait for .... Awaiting must always already have disclosed the horizon and scope in terms of which something can be expected. Expecting is a motk of the future fountkd in awaiting that temporalizes itself authentically as anticipation. Thus a more primordial being-toward-death lies in anticipation than in the heedful expecting of it. Existing in the potentiality-of-being, however it may be projected, understanding is primarily futural. But it would not temporalize itself if it were not temporal, that is, equiprimordially determined by havingbeen and the present. The way in which the ecstasy of the present helps constitute inauthentic understanding was already made roughly clear. Everyday taking care of things understands itself in terms of the paten-
II.IV
Being and Time
311
tiality-of-being that confronts it as coming from its possible success or failure with regard to what is actually taken care of. Corresponding to the inauthentic future (awaiting), its own way ofbeing together with what is taken care of. The ecstatic mode of this present reveals itself if we adduce for comparison this very same ecstasy, but in the mode of authentic temporality. To the anticipation ofresoluteness there belongs a present in keeping with which a resolution discloses the situation. In resoluteness, the present is not only brought back from the dispersion in what is taken care of nearest at hand, but is held in the future and having-been. We call the present that is held in authentic temporality, and is thus authentic, the Moment. This term must be understood in the active sense as an ecstasy. It means the resolute raptness of Da-sein, which is yet held in resoluteness, in what is encountered as possibilities and circumstances to be taken care of in the situation. The phenomenon of the Moment can in principle not be clarified in terms of the now. The now is a temporal phenomenon that belongs to time as within-time-ness: the now "in which" something comes into being, passes away, or is objectively present. "In the Moment" nothing can happen, but as an authentic present it lets us encounter for the first time what can be "in a time" as something at hand or objectively present.' In contrast to the Moment as the authentic present, we shall call the inauthentic present making present. Understood formally, every present makes present, but not every present is "in the moment." When we use the expression making present with no additional qualification, we always mean the inauthentic kind, which is irresolute and lacking the Moment. Making present will become clear only in terms of the temporal interpretation of falling prey to the "world" taken care of; this falling prey has its existential meaning in making present. But since inauthentic understanding projects its potentiality-of-being in terms of what can be taken care of, this means that it temporalizes itself in terms of making present. The Moment, on the other hand, temporalizes itself out of the authentic future. Inauthentic understanding temporalizes itself as an awaiting that makes present-an awaiting to whose ecstatic unity a corresponding having-been must belong. The authentic coming-toward-itself of anticipatory resoluteness is at the same time a coming back to the ownmost self thrown into its individuation. This ecstasy makes it possible for Da-sein to be able to take over resolutely the being that it already is. In anticipation, Da-sein brings itself forth again to its ownmost potentiality-ofbeing. We call authentic having-been retrieve. But when one projects oneself inauthentically upon the possibilities drawn from what is taken care of in making it present, this is possible only because Da-sein has forgotten itself in its ownmost thrown potentiality-of-being. This forgetting is not
338
339
312
Being and Time
II.IV
nothing, nor is it just a failure to remember; it is rather a "positive," ecstatic mode of having-been; a mode with a character of its own. The ecstasy (rapture) of forgetting has the character of backing away from one's ownmost having-been in a way that is closed off from oneself. This backing away from ... ecstatically closes off what it is backing away from, and thus closes itself off, too. As inauthentic having-been, forgottenness is thus related to its own thrown being. It is the temporal meaning of the kind of being that I initially and for the most part am as having-been. And only on the basis of this forgetting can the making present that takes care of and awaits retain things, retain beings unlike Da-sein encountered in the surrounding world. To this retention corresponds a nonretention that presents us with a kind of "forgetting" in the derivative sense. Just as expectation is possible only on the basis of awaiting, remem· bering is possible only on the basis of forgetting, and not the other way around. In the mode offorgottenness, having-been primarily "discloses" the horizon in which Da-sein, lost in the "superficiality" of what is taken care of, can remember. Awaiting that forgets and makes present is an ecstatic unity in its own right, in accordance with which inauthentic understanding temporalizes itself with regard to its temporality. The unity of these ecstasies closes off one's authentic potentiality-of-being, and is thus the existential condition of the possibility of irresoluteness. Although inauthentic heedful understanding is determined in the light of making present what is taken care of, the temporalizing of understanding comes about primarily in the future. (b) The Temporality of Attunement. 4 Understanding is never free floating,
340
but always attuned. The there is equiprimordially disclosed by mood, or else closed off. Attunement brings Da-sein before its thrownness in such a way that the latter is not known as such, but is disclosed far more primordially in "how one is." Being thrown means existentially to find oneself in such and such a way. Thus attunement is grounded in thrownness. Mood represents the way in which I am always primarily the being that has been thrown. How can the temporal constitution of attunement become visible? How can we gain insight into the existential connection between attunement and understanding in terms of the ecstatic unity of actual temporality? Mood discloses by turning away from and toward one's own Dasein. Whether authentically revealing or inauthentically concealing, bringing Da-sein before the That of its own throwness is existentially possible only if the being of Da-sein, by its very meaning is as constantly having-been. Having-been does not first bring one face to face with the thrown being that one is oneself, but the ecstasy of having-been first
II. IV
Being and Time
313
makes possible finding oneself in the mode ofhow-I-find-myself. Understanding is primarily grounded in the future; attunement, on the other hand, temporalizes itself primarily in having-been. Mood temporalizes itself, that is, its specific ecstasy belongs to a future and a present, but in such a way that having-been modifies the equiprimordial ecstasies. We emphasized the fact that whereas moods are ontically familiar, they are not cognized in their primordial and existential function. They are taken as fleeting experiences that "color" one's whole "psychical condition." Whatever can be observed as having the nature of a fleeting appearance and disappearance belongs to the primordial constancy of existence. But, nevertheless, what should moods have in common with "time"? It is a trivial established fact that these "experiences" come and go, that they run their course "in time," certainly an ontic and psychological fact. But our task is to demonstrate the ontological structure of attunement in its existential and temporal constitution. And this is initially only a matter of first making the temporality of mood visible. The thesis that "attunement is primarily grounded in having-been" means that the existential fundamental nature of mood is a bringing back to .... This does not first produce having-been, but attunement always reveals a mode of having-been for the existential analysis. Thus the temporal interpretation of attunement cannot have the intention of deducing moods from temporality and dissolving them in the pure phenomena of temporalizing. We solely want to show that moods are not possible in what they "signify" existentielly or how they "signify" it except on the bosis of temporality. Our temporal interpretation will restrict itself to the phenomena of fear and Ang;5t, which were already analyzed in a preparatory way. We shall begin our analysis by exhibiting the temporality ofjear.5 Fear was characterized as inauthentic attunement. Why does the existential meaning that makes such an attunement possible lie in what has been? What mode of this ecstasy characterizes the specific temporality of fear? Fear is a fear of something threatening-of something that is detrimental to the factical potentiality-of-being of Da-sein, and approaches within the scope of the things at hand and objectively present being taken care of in the manner described. Fearing discloses something threatening in the mode of everyday circumspection. A subject that merely looks could never discover anything like this. But is not this disclosing of fear of ... a letting something-come-toward-oneself? Has not fear been justifiably described as the expectation of a coming evil (malum futurum)? Is not the primary temporal meaning of fear the future and not at all having-been? Fearing is incontestably "related" not only to "something futural" in the sense of what first arrives "in time," but this relatedness itself is futural in the primordially temporal sense. Await-
341
314
Being and Time
II.IV
ing obviously also belongs to the existential and temporal constitution of fear. But this initially only means that the temporality of fear is inauthentic. Is the fear of ... merely the expectation of something futurally
342
threatening? The expectation of something futurally threatening need not already be fear, and it is so far from being fear that it lacks the specific mood character of fear. In fear, the awaiting of fear lets what is threatening come back to one's potentiality-of-being factically taking care of things. Only if that to which this comes back is already ecstatically open, can what is threatening be awaited back to the being that I am, and only so can Da-sein be threatened. The character of mood and affect of fear lies in the fact that the awaiting that fears is afraid "for itself," that is, fear of is a fearing about. The existential and temporal meaning of fear is constituted by a self-forgetting: the confused backing away from one's own factical potentiality-of-being, which is threatened being-in-the-world taking care of what is at hand. Aristotle correctly defines fear as lupe tis he tarake, as depression or confusion. 6 Depression forces Da-sein back to its thrownness, but in such a way that its thrownness is precisely closed off. Confusion is based upon forgetting. When one forgets and backs away from a factical, resolute potentiality-of-being, one keeps to those possibilities of self-preservation and evasion that have already been circumspectly discovered beforehand. Taking care of things which fears for itself leaps from one thing to the other, because it forgets itself and thus cannot grasp any definite possibility. All "possible" possibilities offer themselves, and that means impossible ones, too. He who fears for himself stops at none of these-the "surrounding world" does not disappear-but he encounters it in the mode of no longer knowing his way around in it. This confused making present of the nearest best thing belongs to forgetting oneself in fear. That, for example, the inhabitants of a burning house often "save" the most unimportant things nearby is known. When one has forgotten oneself and makes present a jumble of unattached possibilities, one thus makes possible the confusion that constitutes the nature of the mood of fear. The forgottenness of confusion also modifies awaiting, and characterizes it as depressed or confused awaiting that is distinguished from pure expectation. The specific, ecstatic unity that makes fearing for oneself existentially possible, temporalizes itself primarily out of the forgetting we described that, as a mode of having-been, modifies its present and its future in their temporalizing. The temporality of fear is a forgetting that awaits and makes present. In accordance with its orientation toward things encountered within the world, the commonsense interpretation of fear initially seeks to determine the "approaching evil" as what it is afraid of and to define its relation to that evil as expectation. What belongs to the phenomenon beyond that remains a "feeling of pleasure or pain."
II.JV
Being and Time
315
How is the temporality of Ang.5t related to that of fear? We called the phenomenon of Ang.5t a fundamental attunement. 7 It brings Da-sein before its ownmost thrownness and reveals ~e uncanniness of everyday, familiar being-in-the-world.Just like fear, Ang.5t is formally determined by something in the face of which one is anxious and something about which one is anxious. However, our analysis showed that these two phenomena coincide. That is not supposed to mean that their structural characteristics are fused, as if Ang.5t were anxious neither in the face of anything nor about anything. Their coincidence means that the being exhibiting these structures is the same, namely Da-sein. In particular, that in the face of which one has Ang.rt is not encountered as something definite to be taken care of; the threat does not come from something at hand and objectively present, but rather from the fact that everything at hand and objectively present absolutely has nothing more to "say" to us. Beings in the surrounding world are no longer relevant. The world in which I exist has sunk into insignificance, and the world thus disclosed can set free only beings that are not relevant. The nothingness of the world in the face of which Angst is anxious does not mean that an absence of innerworldly things objectively present is experienced in Ang.5t. They must be encountered in just such a way that they are of no releuance at all, but can show themselves in a barren mercilessness. However, this means that our heedful awaiting finds nothing in terms of which it could understand itself, it grasps at the nothingness of the world. But, thrust toward the world, understanding is brought by Ang.5t to being-in-the-world as such. Being-in-the-world is both what Ang.5t is anxious in the face of and what it is anxious about. Being anxious in the face of ... neither has the nature of an expectation nor of an awaiting at all. That in the face of which one has Ang.5t is, after all, already "there"; it is Da-sein itself. Then is not Ang.5t constituted by a future? Certainly, yet not by the inauthentic one of awaiting. The insignificance of the world disclosed in Ang.rt reveals the nullity of what can be taken care of, that is, the impossibility of projecting oneself upon a potentiality-of-being primarily based upon what is taken care of. But the revelation of this impossibility means to let the possibility of an authentic potentiality-of-being shine forth. What is the temporal meaning of this revealing? Ang.5t is anxious about naked Da-sein thrown into uncanniness. It brings one back to the pure That of one's ownmost, individuated thrownness. This bringing back has neither the character of an evasive forgetting, nor that of a remembering. But neither does Ang.5t already imply that one has already taken over one's existence in resolution and is retrieving it. On the contrary, Ang.rt brings one back to thrownness as something to be possibly retrieved. And thus it also reveals the possibility of an authentic potentiality-of-being that must, as
343
316
344
345
Being and Time
II.IV
something futural in retrieving, come back to the thrown There. Bring· ing before the possibility of retrieval is the specifu ecstatic mode of the attunement of the having-been that constitutes Angst The forgetting constitutive for fear confuses Da-sein and lets it stray back and forth between ungrasped "worldly" possibilities. In contrast to this frantic making present, the present of Ang.st is held in bringing oneself back to one's ownmost thrownness. In accordance with its existential meaning, Ang.st cannot lose itself in what can be taken care of. If something like this happens in an attunement similar to it, this is fear, which everyday understanding mixes up with Ang:s-t. Although the present of Ang:s-t is held, it does not as yet have the character of the Moment that temporalizes itself in resolution. Ang:s-t only brings one into the mood for a possible resolution. The present of Angst holds the Moment in readiness [auf dem Sprung], as which it, and only it, is possible. In the peculiar temporality of Ang:s-t, in the fact that it is primordially grounded in having-been, and only out of this do future and present temporalize themselves, the possibility was shown of the powerfulness that distinguishes the mood of Ang:s-t. In it, Da-sein is taken back fully to its naked uncanniness and benumbed by it. But this numbness not only takes Da-sein back from its "worldly" possibilities, but at the same time gives it the possibility of an authentic potentiality-of-being. Yet neither of these moods, fear and Ang:s-t, ever "occurs," just isolated in the "stream of experience," but always attunes an understanding or is attuned by it. Fear is occasioned by beings taken care of in the surrounding world. In contrast, Ang.st arises from Da-sein itself. Fear comes over us from innerworldly beings. Ang:s-t arises from being-in-theworld as thrown being-toward-death. Understood temporally, this "arising" of Angst from Da-sein means that the future and the present of Ang:s-t temporalize themselves out of a primordial having-been in the sense of bringing us back to the possibility of retrieve. But Ang:s-t can arise authentically only in a resolute Da-sein. He who is resolute knows no fear, but understands the possibility of Ang:s-t as the mood that does not hinder and confuse him. Ang:s-t frees him from "null" possibilities and lets him become free for authentic ones. Although both modes of attunement, fear and Ang:s-t, are primarily grounded in having-been, yet their origin is different with regard to the temporalizing belonging to each in the totality of care. Ang:s-t arises from the future of resoluteness, while fear arises from the lost present of which fear is fearfully apprehensive, thus falling prey to it more than ever. But is not the thesis of the temporality of moods perhaps valid only for the phenomena that we selected? How is a temporal meaning to be found in the pallid lack of mood that dominates the "gray everyday"?
II.tV
Being and Time
317
And how about the temporality of moods and affects such as hope, joy, enthusiasm, and gaiety? That not only fear and Ang3t are founded existentially in a having-been, but other moods, too, becomes clear if we just mention such phenomena as boredom [Uberdruss], sadness, melancholy, and despair. However, these must be interpreted on the broader basis of a developed existential analytic of Da-sein. But even such a phenomenon as hope, which seems to be completely founded in the future, must be analyzed in a way similar to fear. In contrast to fear which is related to a malum futurum, hope has been characterized as the expectation of a bonum futurum. But what is decisive for the structure of hope as a phenomenon is not so much the "futural" character of that to which it is related as the existential meaning of hoping itself. Here, too, the mood character lies primarily in hoping as hoping something for oneself. He who hopes takes himself, so to speak, along in the hope and brings himself toward what is hoped for. But that presupposes having-gained-oneself. The fact that hope brings relief from depressing anxiousness only means that even this attunement remains related to a burden in the mode of having-been. Elevated or elevating moods are ontologically possible only in an ecstatic-temporal relation of Da-sein to the thrown ground of itself. The pallid lack of mood of indifference to everything, which clings to nothing and urges to nothing, and which goes along with what the day brings, yet in a way takes everything with it, demonstrates in the most penetrating fashion the power offorgetting in the everyday moods of taking care of what is nearby. just barely living, which "lets everything alone" as it is, is grounded in giving oneself over to thrownness and forgetting. It has the ecstatic meaning of an inauthentic having-been. Indifference, which can go along with busying oneself head over heels, is to be sharply distinguished from equanimity. This mood arises from the resoluteness that, in the Moment, has its view to the possible situations of the potentiality-of-being-a-whole disclosed in the anticipation of death. Only beings that in accordance with the meaning of their being are attuned, that is, existing, have always already been and exist in a constant mode of having-been can be affected. Ontologically, affection presupposes making present in such a way that in it Da-sein can be brought back to itself as having-been. How the stimulation and touching of the senses in beings that are simply alive are to be ontologically defmed, how and where in general the being of animals is constituted, for example, by a "time," remains a problem for itself.
(c) The Temporality ofFalling Prey. 8 The temporal interpretation of understanding and attunement not only came up against a primary ecstasy for each of these phenomena, but at the same time always came up against temporality as a whole. Just as the future primarily makes understanding
346
318
347
Being and Time
II.IV
possible, and having-been makes mood possible, the third constitutive factor of care, falling prey, has its existential meaning in the present. Our preparatory analysis of falling prey began with an interpretation of idle chatter, curiosity, and ambiguity 9 Our temporal analysis of falling prey should follow the same path. We shall restrict our inquiry, however, to a consideration of curiosity because in it the specific temporality of falling prey is most easily seen. However, our analysis of idle chatter and ambiguity already presupposes a clarification of the temporal constitution of discourse and meaning (interpretation). Curiosity is an eminent tendency of being of Da-sein in accordance with which Da-sein takes care of a potentiality of seeing. 10 Like the concept of sight, "seeing" is not limited to perceiving with the "physical eyes." Perceiving in the broader sense lets what is at hand and objectively present be "bodily" encountered with regard to their outward appearance. This letting something be encountered is grounded in a present. This present provides the ecstatic horizon in general within which beings can be bodily present. Curiosity, however, does not make present what is objectively present in order to understand it, staying with it, but it seeks to see only in order to see and have seen. As this making present that gets tangled up in itself, curiosity has an ecstatic unity with a corresponding future and having-been. Greed for the new indeed penetrates to something not yet seen, but in such a way that making present attempts to withdraw from awaiting. Curiosity is altogether inauthentically futural, in such a way that it does not await a possibility but in its greed only desires possibility as something real. Curiosity is constituted by a dispersed making present that, only making present, thus constantly tries to run away from the awaiting in which it is nevertheless "held," although in a dispersed way. The present "arises from" the awaiting that belongs to it in the sense of running away from it that we emphasized. But the making present of curiosity that "arises" is so little interested in the "matter in question" that, as soon as it catches sight of it, it already is looking for the next thing. The making present that "arises" from the awaiting of a definite, grasped possibility makes possible ontologically the not-staying that is distinctive of curiosity. Making present does not "arise" from awaiting in such a way that it, so to speak, disengages itself from awaiting and leaves it to itself, ontically understood. "Arising" is an ecstatic modification of awaiting in such a way that awaiting pursues making present. Awaiting gives itself up, so to speak; it no longer lets inauthentic possibilities of taking care of things come toward it from what is taken care of, unless they serve the purpose of an impatient making present. When awaiting is ecstatically modified by a making present that no longer arises, but pursues, this modification
II.IV
Being and Time
319
is the existential and temporal condition of the possibility of dispersion.
Making present is left more and more to itself as it is modified by the awaiting that pursues. It makes present for the sake of the present. Thus tangled up in itself, the dispersed not-staying turns into the inability to stay at all. This mode of the present is the most extreme opposite phenomenon to the Moment. In this inability Da-sein is everywhere and nowhere. The Moment brings existence to the situation and discloses the authentic "There." The more inauthentic the present is, that is, the more making present comes to "itself," the more it flees from a definite potentiality-ofbeing and closes it off. But then the future can hardly come back at all to the being that has been thrown. In the "arising" of the present, one also forgets increasingly. The fact that curiosity always already keeps to what is nearest by, and has forgotten what went before, is not something resulting.from curiosity, but the ontological condition for curiosity itself. With regard to their temporal meaning, the characteristics of falling prey that we described-temptation, tranquillization, alienation, and self-entanglement-mean that the making present that "arises" seeks to temporalize itself out of itself in accordance with its ecstatic tendency. Da-sein entangles itself, and this determination has an ecstatic meaning. The raptness of existence in making present does not mean that Da-sein is separated from its I and its self. Even in the most extreme making present, it remains temporal, that is, awaiting and forgetting. Even in making present, Da-sein still understands itself, although it is alienated from its ownmost potentiality-of-being that is primarily grounded in the authentic future and having-been. But since making present always offers something "new," it does not let Da-sein come back to itself and constantly tranquillizes it anew. But this tranquillization again enforces the tendency toward arising. Curiosity is "brought about" not by the endless immensity of what has not yet been seen, but rather by the entangled kind of temporalizing of the arising present. Even if one has seen everything, curiosity invents new things. The mode of temporalizing of the "arising" of the present is grounded in the essence of temporality, which is finite. Thrown into being-toward-death, Da-sein initially and for the most part flees from this more or less explicitly revealed thrownness. The present arises from its authentic future and having-been, so that it lets Da-sein come to authentic existence only by taking a detour through that present. The origin of the "arising" of the present, that is, of being entangled in lostness, is the primordial, authentic temporality itself that makes possible thrown being-toward-death. The thrownness before which Da-sein can indeed be brought authentically and in which it can authentically understand itself yet remains
348
320
349
Being and Time
II. IV
dosed off from it with regard to where it comes from and how it comes ontically. But this dosed-off-ness is by no means only a factually existent lack of knowledge, but constitutes the facticity of Da-sein. It also determines the ecstatic nature of existence, left to the null ground of itself. Initially, the throw of being-thrown-into-the-world does not authentically get caught by Da-sein. The "movement" in it does not already come to a "stand" because Da-sein "is there." Da-sein is swept along in thrownness, that is, as something thrown into the world, it loses itself in the "world" in its being factically dependent on what is to be taken care of. The present, which constitutes the existential meaning of being swept along, never acquires another ecstatic horizon of its own accord, unless it is brought back from its lostness by a resolution so that both the actual situation and thus the primordial "boundary situation" of beingtoward-death are disclosed as the held Moment. (d) The Temporality of Discourse. 11 The complete disdosedness of the There constituted by understanding, attunement, and falling prey is articulated by discourse. Thus discourse does not temporalize itself primarily in a definite ecstasy. But since discourse is for the most part spoken in language and initially speaks by addressing the "surrounding world" in taking care of it and talking about it, making present has, of course, a privileged constitutive function. Tenses, like the other temporal phenomena of language-"kinds of action" and "temporal stages"-do not originate from the fact that discourse "also" speaks about "temporal" processes, namely, processes that are encountered "in time." Nor does the reason for this lie in the fact that speaking occurs "in psychical time." Discourse is in itself temporal, since all speaking about ... , of ... , or to ... is grounded in the ecstatic unity of temporality. The kinds of action are rooted in the primordial temporality of taking care of things, whether it is related to things within time or not. With the help of the vulgar and traditional concept of time which linguistics is forced to make use of, the problem of the existential and temporal structure of the kinds of action cannot even be formulated. 12 But because discourse is always talking about beings, although not primarily and predominantly in the sense of theoretical statements, our analysis of the temporal constitution of discourse and the explication of the temporal characteristics of language pattems can be tackled only if the problem of the fundamental connection between being and truth has been unfolded in terms of the problematic of temporality. Then the ontological meaning of the "is" can be defined, which a superficial theory of propositions and judgments has distorted into the "copula." The "origination" of "significance" can be clarified and the possibility of the formulation of concepts can be made ontologically intelligible only
II.IV
Being and Time
321
in terms of the temporality of discourse, that is, of Da-sein in general. Understanding is grounded primarily in the future (anticipation or awaiting). Attunement temporalizes itself primarily in having-been (retrieve or forgottenness). Falling prey is temporally rooted primarily in the present (making present or the Moment). Still, understanding is always a present that "has-been." Still, attunement temporalizes itself as a future that "makes present." Still, the present "arises" from or is held by a future that has-been. From this it becomes evident that temporality temporalizes itself completely in troery ecstasy, that is, in the ecstatic unity of the actua~ complete temporalizing, of temporality is grounded the totality of the structural whole of existence, facticity, and falling prey, that is, the unity of the structure of care. Temporalizing does not mean a "succession" of the ecstasies. The future is not later than the having-been, and the having-been is not earlier than the present. Temporality temporalizes itself as a future that makes present, in the process of having-been. The disclosedness of the There and the fundamental existentiell possibilities of Da-sein, authenticity and inauthenticity, are founded in temporality. But disclosedness always pertains equiprimordially to the whole of being-in-the-world, to being-in as well as the world. In orientation toward the temporal constitution of disclosedness we must thus be able to demonstrate the ontological condition of the possibility that there can be beings that exist as being-in-the-world.
350
69. The Temporality of Being-in-the-World and the Problem ofthe Transcendence of the World The ecstatic unity of temporality-that is, the unity of the "outside-itself' in the raptures of the future, the having-been, and the present-is the condition of the possibility that there can be a being that exists as its "There." The being that bears the name Da-sein is "cleared."1' The light that constitutes this clearedness of Da-sein is not a power or source, objectively present ontically, for a radiant brightness sometimes occurring in this being. What essentially clears this being, that is, makes it "open" as well as "bright" for itself, was defined as care, before any "temporal" interpretation. The full disclosedness of the There is grounded in care. This clearedness first makes possible any illumination or throwing light, any perceiving, "seeing," or having of something. We understand the light of this clearedness only if we do not look for an innate, objectively present power, but rather question the whole constitution of being ofDasein, care, as to the unified ground of its existential possibility. Ecstatic temporality clears the There primordially. It is the primary regulator of the possible unity of all the essential existential structures of Da-sein.
351
322
352
Being and Time
II. IV
Only in terms of the rootedness of Da-sein in temporality, do we gain insight into the existential possibility of the phenomenon that we characterized at the beginning of our analytic of Da-sein as the fundamental constitution of being-in-the-world. At the beginning, it was a matter of securing the inseparable, structural unity of this phenomenon. The question of the ground of the possible unity of this articulated structure remained in the background. With the intention of protecting the phenomenon from the most obvious and thus the most fatal tendencies to divide it up, the everyday mode of being-in-the-world nearest to us-taking care of innerworldly beings at hand-was interpreted more extensively. Now that care itself has been ontologically defined and traced back to temporality as its existential ground, taking care in its turn can be conceived explicitly in terms of care or temporality. Our analysis of the temporality of taking care of things initially kept to the mode of circumspectly having to do with things at hand. Then it followed up the existential and temporal possibility that circumspect taking care may be modified into a discovering of innerworldly beings in the sense of certain possibilities of scientific investigation and discovering them by "merely" looking at them. Our interpretation of the temporality of the being together with innerworldly things at hand and objectively present-being together circumspectly as well as theoretically taking care-shows at the same time how the same temporality is already the advance condition of the possibility of being-in-the-world in which being together with innerworldly beings is grounded as such. The thematic analysis of the temporal constitution of being-in-the-world led to the question: how is something like world possible at all, in what sense is world, what and how does the world transcend, how are "independent" innerworldly beings "connected" with the transcending world? The ontological exposition of these questions does not already entail their answer. On the other hand, they do bring about the clarification, previously necessary, of the structures with reference to which the problem of transcendence is to be interrogated. The existential and temporal interpretation of being-in-the-world will consider three things: (a) the temporality of circumspect taking care; (b) the temporal meaning of the modification of circumspect taking care into theoretical knowledge of innerworldly things objectively present; (c) the temporal problem of the transcendence of the world.
(a) The Temporality of Circumspect Taking Care. How are we to gain the perspective for an analysis of the temporality of taking care? We called heedful being together with the "world" our association in and with the surrounding world. 14 As examples of the phenomena of being together with ... we chose the using, handling, and producing of things at hand
II. IV
Being and Time
323
and their deficient and undifferentiated modes, that is, the being together with things that belong to everyday need. 15 The authentic existence of Da-sein also has to do with such taking care, even when it remains "indifferent" for it. Things at hand taken care of are not the cause of taking care, as if this were to arise only on the basis of the effects of innerworldly beings. Being together with things at hand can neither be explained ontically in terms of those things at hand nor can things at hand be derived from this kind of being. Taking care, as a kind of being of Da-sein, and things taken care of, as innerworldly things at hand, are, however, not simply objectively present together. Nevertheless, there is a "connection" between them. What is associated with, if correctly understood, sheds light on heedful association itself. On the other hand, if we miss the phenomenal structure of what is associated with, we fail to recognize the existential constitution of this kind of behavior. It is indeed already an essential gain for the analysis of the beings encountered nearest to us if their specific handy character is not omitted. But we must understand further that heedful association never has to do with a single useful thing. Using and handling a definite useful thing remains as such oriented toward a context of useful things. If, for example, we look for a "misplaced" useful thing, we do not mean by this simply and primarily only what is looked for in an isolated "act," but the context of the whole of useful things has already been discovered. Any "going to work" and starting out does not meet up with a useful thing given in isolation out of nothing, but in taking hold of a useful thing we come back to the useful thing grasped from the work-world that has always already been disclosed. If in our analysis of having to do with things, we aim at what we have to do with, our existent being together with beings taken care of must be given an orientation not toward an isolated useful thing at hand, but rather toward the totality of useful things. Our reflection upon the eminent character of being of useful things at hand, relevance, 16 also forces us to this conception of what we have to do with. We understand the term relevance ontologically. The phrase "something is in a certain relevance" is not supposed to ontically ascertain a fact, but to indicate the kind of being of things at hand. The relational character of relevance, with its ... together with ... points to the fact that a useful thing is ontologically impossible. Indeed, a single useful thing may be at hand while another is "missing." But here the fact makes itself known that one thing at hand belongs to the other. Heedful association can only let things at hand be encountered circumspectly if it already understands something like a relevance in which things are. The being together with ... that takes care in a way that circumspectly discovers amounts to letting something be in relevance, that is, to projecting rei-
353
324
354
Being and Time
II.IV
evance understandingly. If letting things be relevant constitutes the existential structure of taking care, and if the latter as being together with ... belongs to the essential constitution of care, and if care in its tum is grounded in temporality, then the existential condition of the possibility of letting something be relevant must be sought in a mode of the temporalizing of temporality. Letting something be relevant lies in the simplest handling of a useful thing. Relevance has an intentional character with reference to which the thing is useable or in use. Understanding the intention and context of relevance has the temporal structure of awaiting. Awaiting the intention, taking care can at the same time come back to something like relevance. Awaiting the context and retaining the means of relevance make possible in its ecstatic unity the specifically handy way in which the useful thing is made present. Awaiting the intention is neither a reflection upon the "goal" nor an expectation of the imminent completion of the work to be produced. It does not have the nature of a thematic grasping at all. Nor does retaining what is relevant mean holding fast to it thematically. Handling things is no more related merely to what it handles than to what it uses in relevance. Rather, being relevant constitutes itself in the unity of awaiting and retaining in such a way that the making present arising from this makes the characteristic absorption in taking care in the world of its useful things possible. When one is "really" busy with ... and totally immersed in it, one is neither only together with the work nor with the tools nor with both "together." Being in relevance, which is grounded in temporality, has already founded the unity of the relations in which taking care of things "moves" circumspectly. A specific kind of forgetting is essential for the temporality that constitutes being in relevance. In order to be able to "really" get to work "lost" in the world of tools and to handle them, the self must forget itself. But since an awaiting is always guiding in the unity of the temporalizing of taking care, the ownmost potentiality-of-being of Da-sein, taking care is nevertheless placed in care, as we shall show. The making present that awaits and retains constitutes the familiarity in accordance with which Da-sein "knows its way around" as beingwith-one-another in the public surrounding world. We understand letting things be in relevance existentially as letting-"be." On its basis, things at hand can be encountered by circumspection as the beings that they are. We can thus further clarify the temporality of taking care if we pay attention to the modes of circumspectly letting something be encountered that were characterized before 17 as conspicuousness, obtrusiveness, and obstinacy. The useful thing at hand is precisely not encountered with regard to its "true in-itself' by a thematic perception of things, but is encountered in the inconspicuousness of what is found "obvi-
II.IV
Being and Time
325
ously" and "objectively." But if something is conspicuous in the totality of these beings, herein lies the possibility that the totality of useful things as such also obtrudes itself. How must letting things be in relevance be structured existentially so that it can let something conspicuous be encountered? This question is not aiming at factical occasions that direct attention to something already presented, but at the ontological meaning of this directability as such. Things that cannot be used, for example, a tool that will not work, can be conspicuous only in and for someone using them. Even the most sharp and persistent "perception" and "representation" of things could never discover something like damage to the tool. The using must be able to be hampered so that something unhandy can be encountered. But what does this mean ontologically? The making present that awaits and retains is held up with regard to its absorption in the relevant relations, and it is held up by something which afterwards turns out to be a damage. The making present, which equiprimordially awaits the whatfor, is held fast with the tool used in such as way that the what-for and the in-order-to are now explicitly encountered for the first time. However, making present itself can only meet up with something unsuited for ... because it is already moving in an awaiting retention of what is in relevance. Making present is "held up," that is, in the unity of the awaiting that retains, it shifts more to itself and thus constitutes the "inspection," checking, and removal of the disturbance. If heedful association were simply a succession of "experiences" occurring "in time"· and if these experiences "associated" with each other as intimately as possible, letting a conspicuous, unusable tool be encountered would be ontologically impossible. Whatever we have made accessible in contexts of useful things, letting things be in relevance as such must be grounded in the ecstatic unity of the making present that awaits and retains. And how is it possible to "ascertain" that something is missing, that is, unhandy, and not just at hand in an unhandy way? Unhandy things are not discovered circumspectly in missing something. "Finding out" that something is not objectively present is based upon missing something, and both have their own existential presuppositions. Missing something is by no means a not-making-present, but is a deficient mode of the present in the sense of the not-making-present of something expected or always already available. If circumspect letting things be relevant were not awaiting what is taken care of "from the very beginning," and if awaiting did not temporalize itself in the unity with a making present, Da-sein could never "find out" that something is missing. On the other hand, the possibility of being surprised lies in the fact that the making present that awaits a thing does not await something else that stands in a possible context of relevance with the former. The not
355
326
356
357
Being and Time
II. IV
awaiting of the making present that is lost first discloses the "horizonal" realm in which something surprising can overcome Da-sein. That with which heedful association fails to cope, either by producing or procuring something, or even by turning away, keeping at a distance, protecting oneself from something, is revealed in its insurmountability. Taking care accepts this. But accepting something is a mode peculiar to circumspectly letting something be encountered. On the basis of this discovery, taking care can fmd what is inconvenient, disturbing, hindering, jeopardizing, or in general resistant in some way. The temporal structure of accepting something lies in a nonretention that awaits and makes present. The making present that awaits does not, for example, count "on" something that is unsuitable, but yet available. Not counting on ... is a mode of taking into account what one cannot hold on to. It is not forgotten, but retained so that it remains at hand precisely in its unsuitability. Things at hand like this belong to the everyday content of the factically disclosed surrounding world. Only because things offering resistance are disclosed on the basis of the ecstatic temporality of taking care, can factical Da-sein understand itself in its abandonment to a "world" of which it never becomes master. Even if taking care remains restricted to the urgency of everyday needs, it is never a pure making present, but arises from a retention that awaits; on the basis of such retention, or as such a "basis," Da-sein exists in a world. For this reason factically existing Da-sein in a way always already knows its way around, even in a strange "world." When, in taking care of things, one lets something be in relevance, one's doing so is grounded in temporality and amounts to an altogether pre-ontological and unthematic way of understanding relevance and things at hand. In what follows, we shall show how the understanding of these determinations of being as such is in the end also founded in temporality. We must first demonstrate the temporality of being-in-theworld still more concretely. With this as our aim, we shall trace how the theoretical mode of behavior toward the "world" "arises" out of circumspect taking care of things at hand. The circumspect as well as the theoretical discovery of innerworldly beings is based upon being-in-theworld. The existential and temporal interpretation of these ways of discovering will prepare the temporal characterization of this fundamental constitution of Da-sein.
(b) The Temporal Meaning of the Way in which Circumspect Taking Care Becomes Modified into the Theoretical Discovery of Things Objectively Present in the World. When in the course of our existential and ontological analyses we ask about how theoretical discovery "arises" from circumspect taking care, this means that we are not making a problem out of the ontic his-
n.rv
Being and Time
327
tory and development of science, or of its factical occasions or of its nearest goals. In searching for the ontological genesis of the theoretical mode of behavior, we are asking which of these conditions of possibility in the constitution of being of Da-sein are existentially necessary for Da-sein to be able to exist in the mode of scientific investigation? This question aims at an existential concept of science. This is distinct from the "logical" concept that understands science with regard to its results and defines it as a "context of causal relations of true, that is, valid propositions." The existential concept understands science as a mode of existence and thus as a mode of being-in-the-world which discovers or discloses beings or being. However, a completely adequate existential interpretation of science cannot be carried out until the meaning of being and the "connection" between being and truth 18 have been clarified in terms of the temporality of existence. The following considerations are to prepare the understanding of this central problematic within which the idea of phenomenology can first be developed, as opposed to the pre-conception19 indicated in an introductory fashion. In accordance with the stage of our study attained up to now, a further restriction will be imposed upon our interpretation of the theoretical mode of behavior. We are only inquiring into the way in which circumspect taking care of things at hand changes over into the investigation of things objectively present found in the world, and we shall be guided by the aim of penetrating to the temporal constitution of being-in-the-world in general. In characterizing the change-over from "practically" circumspect handling and using and so on, to "theoretical" investigation, it would be easy to suggest that merely looking at beings is something that emerges when taking care abstains from any kind of use. Then what is decisive about the "origin" of theoretical behavior would lie in the disappearance of praxis. So if one posits "practical" taking care as the primary and predominant kind of being offactical Da-sein, the ontological possibility of "theory" will be due to the absence of praxis, that is, to a privation. But stopping a specific kind of use in heedful association does not simply leave its guiding circumspection behind as a remnant. Rather, taking care then transposes itself explicitly into just-looking-around. But this is by no means the way in which the "theoretical" attitude of science is reached. On the contrary, the staying that stops which comes about when use stops can acquire the quality of a more precise kind of circumspection, such as "inspecting," checking what has been attained, as looking over the "operations" just now "at a standstill." To refrain from the use of tools is so far from "theory" that staying, "reflecting" circumspection remains completely stuck in the tools at hand taken care of. "Practical" dealings have their own way of staying. And just as praxis has its own spe-
358
328
359
Being and Time
II.IV
cific sight ("theory"), theoretical investigation is not without its own praxis. Reading off the measurements that result from an experiment often requires a complicated "technological" set-up for the experimental arrangement. Observing with the microscope is dependent upon the production of "prepared slides." Archeological excavation that precedes any interpretation of the "findings" demands the most massive manual labor. But even the most "abstract" working out of problems and refining what has been gained, uses, for example, writing materials. As "uninteresting" and "obvious" as these components of scientific investigation may be, they are by no means ontologically indifferent. The explicit reference to the fact that scientific behavior as a way of being-in-the-world is not only a "purely intellectual activity" might seem unnecessarily complicated and superfluous. If only it did not become clear from this triviality that it is by no means obvious where the ontological boundary between "theoretical" and "atheoretical" behavior really lies! One will want to assert that all manipulation in the sciences is only in the service of pure observation, of the investigating discovery and disclosure of the "things themselves." Taken in its broadest sense, "seeing" regulates all "procedures" and retains its priority. "To whatever kind of objects one's knowledge may relate itself and by whatever means it may do so, still that through which it relates itself to them immediately, and which all thinking as a means has as its goal [Heidegger's italics] is intuition." 20 The idea of the intuitus has guided all interpretation of knowledge ever since the beginnings of Greek ontology up to today, whether that intuition is actually attainable or not. In accordance with the priority of "seeing," the demonstration of the existential genesis of science will have to start out by characterizing the circumspection that guides "practical" taking care of things. Circumspection moves in the relevant relations of the context of useful things at hand. It itself is again subject to the guidance of a more or less explicit view over the totality of useful things in the actual world of tools and the public surrounding world belonging to it. This overview is not simply one that subsequently scrapes objectively present things together. What is essential in the overview is the primary understanding of the totality of relevance within which factical taking care always starts out. The overview illumines taking care, and gets its "light" from the potentiality-of-being of Da-sein for the sake of which taking care exists as care. The circumspection of taking care that has this "overview" brings things at hand nearer to Da-sein in its actual using and handling in the mode of interpreting what it has seen. We call the specific bringing near of what is taken care of by interpreting it circumspectly deliberation. The schema peculiar to it is "if-then": If this or that is to be produced, put into use, or prevented, for example, then we need these or those
II. IV
Being and Time
329
means, ways, circumstances, or opportunities. Circumspect deliberation throws light on the actual factical position of Da-sein in the surrounding world taken care of. Thus it never simply "confirms" the objective presence of a being or of its qualities. Deliberation can also come about without what is circumspectly approached itself being concretely at hand or present within the nearest range. Bringing the surrounding world near in circumspect deliberation has the existential meaning of making present. For representing is only a mode of making present. In it, deliberation catches sight directly of what is needed, but not at hand. Representing circumspection does not relate itself to "mere ideas." But circumspect making present is a phenomenon with more than one kind of foundation. First of all, it belongs to the full ecstatic unity of temporality. It is grounded in a retention of the context of useful things that Da-sein takes care of in awaiting a possibility. What has already been disclosed in awaiting retention is brought nearer by one's deliberative making present or representing. But if deliberation is to be able to move in the scheme of "if-then," taking care must already understand a context of relevance in an "overview." What is addressed with the "if' must already be understood as this and that. For this, it is not necessary that the understanding of useful things be expressed predicatively. The scheme "something as something" is already prefigured in the structure of pre-predicative understanding. The as-structure is ontologically grounded in the temporality of understanding. Only because Da-sein, awaiting a possibility (that is, here a what-for), has come back to a for-this (that is, retains a thing at hand}, can conversely the making present that belongs to this awaiting retention start with this retention and bring it explicitly nearer in its reference to the what-for. The deliberation that brings near must in the scheme of making present adapt itself to the kind of being of what is to be brought near. The character of relevance of what is at hand is not first discovered by deliberation, but only gets brought near by it in such a way that it circumspectly lets what is in relevance be seen as this. The way the present is rooted in the future and in the having-been is the existential and temporal condition of the possibility that what is projected in circumspect understanding can be brought nearer in a making present in such a way that the present must adapt itself to what is encountered in the horizon of awaiting retention, that is, it must interpret itself in the schema of the as-structure. This gives us the answer to our question whether the as-structure is existentially and ontologically connected21 with the phenomenon of projecting. Like understanding and interpretation in genera~ the "as" is grounded in the ecstatic and horizontal unity of temporality. In our fundamental analysis of being, and indeed in connection with the interpretation of the "is" (which as a copula
360
330
361
Being and Time
II.IV
"expresses" the addressing of something as something), we must again make the as-phenomenon thematic and define the concept of the "schema" existentially. However, what is the temporal characterization of circumspect deliberation and its schemata supposed to contribute to answering our current question of the genesis of the theoretical mode of behavior? Only enough to clarify the situation of Da-sein in which a circumspect taking care changes over into theoretical discovery. We may then try to analyze this change-over itself following the guideline of an elemental statement of circumspect deliberation and its possible modifications. In our circumspect use of tools, we can say that the hammer is too heavy or too light. Even the sentence that the hammer is heavy can express a heedful deliberation, and mean that it is not light-that it requires force to use it or it makes using it difficult. But the statement can also mean that the being before us, with which we are circumspectly familiar as a hammer, has a weight, that is, the "property" of heaviness. It exerts a pressure on what lies beneath it, and when that is removed, it falls. The discourse understood in this way is no longer in the horizon of the awaiting retention of a totality of useful things and its relations of relevance. What is said has been drawn from looking at what is appropriate for a being with "mass." What is now in view is appropriate for the hammer, not as a tool, but as a corporeal thing that is subject to the law of gravity. Circumspect talk about being "too heavy" or "too light" no longer has any "meaning"; that is, the being now encountered of itself provides us with nothing in relation to which it could be "found" too heavy or too light. Why does what we are talking about, the heavy hammer, show itself differently when our way of talking is modified? Not because we are keeping our distance from handling, nor because we are only looking away from the useful character of this being, but because we are looking at the thing at hand encountered in a "new" way, as something objectively present. The understanding of being guiding the heedful association with innerworldly beings has been transformed. But does this already constitute a scientific mode of behavior if we "comprehend" things at hand as something objectively present, instead of circumspectly deliberating about them? Moreover, even things at hand can be made a theme of scientific investigation and determination, for example, in examining someone's surrounding world, his milieu in the context of a historiographical biography. The everyday context of useful things at hand, their historical origination and utilization, their factical role in Da-sein-all these are the objects of the science of economics. Things at hand need not lose their character of being useful things in order to become the "object" of a science. A modification of our understanding
II.IV
Being and Time
331
of being seems not to be necessarily constitutive for the genesis of the theoretical mode of behavior "toward things." Certainly not, if this modification is supposed to mean a change of the kind of being which, in understanding the being in question, we understand it to possess. In our first characterization of the genesis of the theoretical mode of behavior from circumspection, we have made basic a kind of theoretical grasping of innerworldly beings, of physical nature, in which the modification of our understanding of being amounts to a transformation. In the "physical" statement that "the hammer is heavy," we overlook not only the tool-character of the being encountered, but thus also that which belongs to every useful thing at hand: its place. The place becomes indifferent. This does not mean that the objectively present thing loses its "location" altogether. Its place becomes a position in space and time, a "world point," which is in no way distinguished from any other. This means that the multiplicity of places of useful things at hand defined in the surrounding world is not just modified to a sheer multiplicity of positions, but the beings of the surrounding world are released. The totality of what is objectively present becomes thematic. In this case, a releasing of the surrounding world belongs to the modification of the understanding of being. Following the guideline of the understanding of being in the sense of objective presence, this release becomes at the same time a delimitation of the "region" of what is objectively present. The more appropriately the being of the beings to be investigated is understood in the guiding understanding of being and the more the totality of beings is articulated in its fundamental determinations as a possible area of subject-matter for a science, the more assured will be the actual perspective of methodical questioning. The classic example for the historical development of a science, and even for its ontological genesis, is the origin of mathematical physics. What is decisive for its development lies neither in its higher evaluation of the observation of "facts," nor in the "application" of mathematics in determining events of nature, but the mathematical project of nature itself. This project discovers in advance something constantly objectively present (matter) and opens the horizon for the guiding perspective on its quantitatively definable constitutive moments (motion, force, location, and time). Only "in the light of' a nature thus projected can something like a "fact" be found and be taken in as a point of departure for an experiment defined and regulated in terms of this project. The "founding" of "factual science" was possible only because the researchers understood that there are in principle no "bare facts." What is decisive about the mathematical project of nature is again not primarily the mathematical element as such, but the fact that this project discloses a priori. And thus the paradigm of the mathematical natural sci-
362
332
363
364
Being and Time
II.IV
ences does not consist in its specific exactitude and binding character for "everyone," but in the fact that in it the thematic beings are discovered in the only way that beings can be discovered: in the prior project of their constitution of being. When the basic concepts of the understanding of being by which we are guided have been worked out, the methods, the structure of conceptuality, the relevant possibility of truth and certainty, the kind of grounding and proof, the mode of being binding and the kind of communication-all these will be determined. The totality of these moments constitutes the complete existential concept of science. The scientific project of the beings somehow always already encountered lets their kind of being be explicitly understood in such a way that the possible ways of purely discovering innerworldly beings thus become evident. The articulation of the understanding of being, the definition of the subject-matter defined by that understanding, and the prefiguration of the concepts suitable to these beings, all belong to the totality of this projecting that we call thematization. It aims at freeing beings encountered within the world in such a way that they can "project" themselves back upon pure discovery, that is, they can become objects. Thematization objectifies. It does not first "posit" beings, but frees them in such a way that they become "objectively" subject toquestioning and definition. The objectifying being together with innerworldly things objectively present has the character of an eminent making pre· sent. 22 It is above all distinguished from the present of circumspection by the fact that the discovering of the science in question solely awaits the discoveredness of what is objectively present. This awaiting of discoveredness is grounded existentielly in a resoluteness of Da-sein by means of which it projects itself upon its potentiality-of-being-in-the-"truth." This project is possible because being-in-the-truth constitutes a determination of the existence of Da-sein. How science has its origin in authentic existence is not to be pursued here. It is simply a matter of understanding that and how the thematization of innerworldly beings presupposes being-in-the-world as the fundamental constitution of Dasein. If the thematization of what is objectively present-the scientific project of nature-is to become possible, Da-sein must transcend the beings thematized. Transcendence does not consist in objectivation, but is rather presupposed by it. But if the thematization of innerworldly beings objectively present is a change-over from taking care which circumspectly discovers, then a transcendence of Da-sein must already underlie "practical" being together with things at hand. Furthermore, if thematization modifies and articulates the understanding of being, insofar as Da-sein, the being that thematizes, exists, it must already understand something like being. This understanding of
II. IV
Being and Time
333
being can remain neutral. Then handiness and objective presence are not differentiated, still less are they conceived ontologically. But for Dasein to be able to have something to do with a context of useful things, it must understand something like relevance, even if only unthematically. A world must be disclosed to it. The world is disclosed with the factical existence of Da-sein, if indeed Da-sein essentially exists as being-in-theworld. And if the being of Da-sein is completely grounded in temporality, temporality must make possible being-in-the-world and thus the transcendence of Da-sein, which in its tum supports the being together with innerworldly beings that takes care, whether theoretical or practical.
(c) The Temporal Problem of the Transcendence of the World. The understanding of a totality of relevance inherent in circumspect taking care is grounded in a previous understanding of the relations of in-order-to, what-for, for-that, and for-the-sake-of-which. We set forth the connection of these relations as significance. 2~ Their unity constitutes what we call world. Now the question arises of how something like world in its unity with Da-sein is ontologically possible? In what way must world be for Da-sein to be able to exist as being-in-the-world? Da-sein exists for the sake of a potentiality-of-being of itself. Existing, it is thrown, and as thrown, delivered over to beings that it needs in order to be able to be as it is, namely for the sake of itself. Since Da-sein exists factically, it understands itself in this connection of the for-thesake-of-itself with an actual in-order-to. That within which existing Dasein understands itself is "there" together with its factical existence. The wherein of primary self-understanding has the kind of being of Da-sein. Existing, Da-sein is its world. We defined the being ofDa-sein as care. Its ontological meaning is temporality: We showed that and how temporality constitutes the disclosedness of the there. World is also disclosed in the disclosedness of the There. The unity of significance, that is, the ontological constitution of the world, must then also be grounded in temporality. The existential and temporal condition of the possibility of the world lies in the fact that temporality, as an ecstatical unity, has something like a horizon. The ecstasies are not simply raptures toward .... Rather, a "whereto" of raptness belongs to each ecstasy. We call this whereto of the ecstasy the horizonal schema. The ecstatical horizon is different in each of the three ecstasies. The schema in which Da-sein comes back to itselfjuturally, whether authentically or inauthentically, is the for-the-sake-of-itself. We call the schema in which Da-sein is disclosed to itself in attunement as thrown, that in the face of which it has been thrown and that to which it has been delivered over. It characterizes the horizonal structure of the having-been. Existing for the sake of itself in being delivered over to itself as thrown, Da-sein is
365
334
366
Being and Time
ll.IV
at the same time making present as being together with .... The horizonal schema of the present is determined by the in-order-to. The unity of the horizonal schemata of future, having-been, and present is grounded in the ecstatic unity of temporality. The horizon of the whole of temporality determines whereupon the being factically existing is essentially disclosed. With factical Da-sein, a potentiality-of-being is always projected in the horizon of the future, "already being" is disclosed in the horizon of the having-been, and what is taken care of is discovered in the horizon of the present. The horizonal unity of the schemata of the ecstasies makes possible the primordial connection of the relations of the in-order-to with the for-the-sake-of-which. This means that on the basis of the horizonal constitution of the ecstatic unity of temporality, something like a disclosed world belongs to the being that is always its There. Just as the present arises in the unity of the temporalizing of temporality from the future and the having-been, the horizon of a present temporalizes itself equiprimordially with those of the future and the having-been. Insofar as Da-sein temporalizes itself, a world is, too. Temporalizing itself with regard to its being as temporality, Da-sein is essentially "in a world" on the basis of the ecstatic and horizontal constitution of that temporality. The world is neither objectively present nor at hand, but temporalizes itself in temporality. It "is" "there" together with the outside-itself of the ecstasies. If no Da-sein exists, no world is "there" either. The world is already presupposed in one's being together with things at hand heedfully and factically, in one's thematization of what is objectively present, and in one's objectivating discovery of the latter, that is, all these are possible only as modes of being-in-the-world. The world is transcendent, grounded in the horizonal unity of ecstatic temporality. It must already be ecstatically disclosed so that innerworldly beings can be encountered from it. Temporality already holds itself ecstatically in the horizons of its ecstasies and, temporalizing itself, comes back to the beings encountered in the There. With the factical existence of Da-sein, innerworldly beings are also already encountered. That such beings are discovered in the There of its own existence is not under the control of Da-sein. Only what, in which direction, to what extent, and how it actually discovers and discloses is a matter of freedom, although always within the limits of its thrownness. The relations of significance that determine the structure of the world are thus not a network of forms that is imposed upon some material by a worldless subject. Rather, factical Da-sein, ecstatically understanding itself and its world in the unity of the There, comes back from these horizons to the beings encountered in them. Coming back to
II. IV
Being and Time
335
these beings understandingly is the existential meaning ofletting them be encountered in making them present; for this reason they are called innerworld.ly. The world is, so to speak, already "further outside" than any object could ever be. The "problem of transcendence" cannot be reduced to the question of how does a subject get outside to an object, whereby the totality of objects is identified with the idea of the world. We must rather ask what makes it ontologically possible for beings to be encountered within the world and objectified as encountered beings? Going back to the ecstatically and horizonally founding transcendence of the world will give us the answer. If the "subject" is conceived ontologically as existing Da-sein, whose being is grounded in temporality, we must say then that the world is "subjective." But this "subjective" world, as one that is temporally transcendent, is then "more objective" than any possible "object." By tracing being-in-the-world back to the ecstatic and horizonal unity of temporality, we have made the existential and ontological possibility of this fundamental constitution of Da-sein intelligible. At the same time it becomes clear that the concrete development of the structure of world in general and of its possible variations can be attempted only if an ontology of possible innerworld.ly beings is oriented toward a clarified idea of being in general with sufficient assurance. The possible interpretation of this idea requires that we set forth the temporality of Da-sein beforehand; here our characterization of being-in-the-world will be of service.
70. The Temporality of the Spatiality Characteristic of Da-sein Although the expression "temporality" does not mean what the talk about "space and time" understands by time, spatiality seems to constitute another basic attribute of Da-sein corresponding to temporality. The existential and temporal analysis thus appears to reach a limit with the spatiality of Da-sein, so that this being that we call Da-sein must be addressed coordinately as "temporal" "and also" as spatial. Does the existential and temporal analysis of Da-sein come to a halt on account of the phenomenon that we got to know as the spatiality of Da-sein and that we showed to belong to being-in-the-world?24 If in the course of our existential interpretation we were to talk about the "spatio-temporal" determination of Da-sein, we could not mean that this being is objectively present "in space and also in time"; this needs no further discussion. Temporality is the meaning of being of care. The constitution of Da-sein and its modes of being are ontologically possible only on the basis of temporality, regardless whether this being occurs "in time" or not. But then the specific spatiality of Da-sein
367
336
368
Being and Time
II.IV
must be grounded in temporality. On the other hand, the demonstration that this spatiality is existentially possible only through temporality, cannot aim either at deducing space from time or at dissolving it into pure time. If the spatiality of Da-sein is "embraced" by temporality in the sense of an existential foundation, this connection (which is to be clarified in what follows) is also different from the priority of time over space in Kant's sense. That the empirical representations of what is objectively present "in space" occur as psychical events "in time," so that the "physical" also occurs indirectly "in time," is not to give an existential and ontological interpretation of space as a form of sensibility, but rather to ascertain ontically that what is psychically objectively present runs its course "in time." We shall ask existentially and analytically about the temporal conditions of the possibility of the spatiality of Da-sein-the spatiality that in tum founds the discovering of space within the world. Before that we must remember in what way Da-sein is spatial. Da-sein can be spatial only as care, in the sense offactically entangled existing. Negatively this means that Da-sein is never objectively present in space, not even initially. Da-sein does not fill out a piece of space as a real thing or useful thing would do, so that the boundaries dividing it from the surrounding space would themselves just define that space spatially. In the literal sense, Da-sein takes space in. It is by no means merely objectively present in the piece of space that its body fills out. Existing, it has always already made room for a leeway. It determines its own location in such a way that it comes back from the space made room for to a "place" that it has taken over. To be able to say that Da-sein is objectively present at a position in space, we have to grasp this being beforehand in an ontologically inappropriate way. Nor does the difference between the "spatiality" of an extended thing and that of Da-sein lie in the fact that Da-sein knows about space. Making room is so far from identical with the "representation" of something spatial that the latter presupposes the former. Nor may the spatiality ofDa-sein be interpreted as a kind of imperfection that adheres to existence on account of the fatal "connection of the spirit with a body." Rather, because Da-sein is "spiritual," and only because it is spiritual, it can be spatial in a way that essentially remains impossible for an extended corporeal thing. The making room of Da-sein is constituted by directionality and de-distancing. How is something like this existentially possible on the basis of the temporality of Da-sein? The foundational function of temporality for the spatiality of Da-sein is to be indicated briefly only to the extent that it is necessary for later discussions of the ontological meaning of the "coupling" of space and time. The directional discovery of something like a region belongs to the making room of Da-sein. With
II. IV
Being and Time
337
this expression we mean initially the whereto of the possible belonging somewhere of useful things at hand in the surrounding world. Whenever one comes across useful things, handles them, moves them around, or out of the way, a region has already been discovered. Being-in-the-world that takes care of things is directed, directing itself. Belonging-somewhere has an essential relation to relevance. It is always factically determined in terms of the context of relevance of the useful things taken care of. The relevant relations are intelligible only in the horizon of a disclosed world. Their horizonal nature also first makes possible the specific horizon of the whereto of regional belonging. The self-directive discovering of a region is grounded in an ecstatically retentive awaiting of the possible hither and whither. As a directed awaiting of region, making room is equiprimordially a bringing-near (or de-distancing) of things at hand and objectively present. De-distancing, taking care comes back out of the previously discovered region to what is nearest. Bringingnear and the estimating and measurement of distances within what is objectively present within the de-distanced world are grounded in a making-present that belongs to the unity of temporality in which directionality is possible, too. Because Da-sein as temporality is ecstatic and horizonal in its being, it can factically and constantly take along space for which it has made room. With regard to this space ecstatically made room for, the here of its actual facticallocation or situation never signifies a position in space, but the leeway of the range of the totality of useful things taken care of nearby-a leeway that has been opened in directionality and dedistancing. In bringing-dose that makes possible the handling and being occupied that is "absorbed in the matter," the essential structure of carefalling prey-makes itself known. Its existential and temporal constitution is distinguished by the fact that in falling prey, and thus also in the bringing near which is founded in "making present," the forgetting that awaits pursues the present. In the making present that brings something near from its wherefrom, making present loses itself in itself, and forgets the over there. For this reason if the "observation" of innerworldly beings starts in such a making present, the illusion arises that "initially" only a thing is objectively present, here indeed, but indeterminately, in a space in general. Only on the basis of ecstatic and horizonal temporality is it possible for Da· sein to break into space. The world is not objectively present in space; however, only within a world can space be discovered. The ecstatic temporality of the spatiality of Da-sein makes it intelligible that space is independent of time, but on the other hand this same temporality makes intelligible also the "dependency" of Da-sein upon space-a dependence
369
338
Being and Time
II.IV
that makes itself manifest in the familiar phenomenon that both the self-interpretation of Da-sein and the content of significance of language are to a large extent dominated by "spatial representations" in general. This priority of the spatial in the articulation of significations and concepts has its ground, not in some specific power of space, but rather in the kind of being of Da-sein. * Essentially entangled, temporality loses itself in making present, and understands itself not only circumspectly in terms of the things at hand taken care of, but from those spatial relations that making present constantly meets up with in what is at hand as present, it takes its guidelines for articulating what is understood and can be interpreted in understanding in general. 370
71. The Temporal Meaning of the Everydayness of Da-sein The analysis of the temporality of taking care showed that the essential structures of the constitution of being of Da-sein that were interpreted before setting forth temporality, with the intention of arriving at temporality, must themselves be taken back existentially into temporality. At the very beginning of our analysis we did not choose a definite, eminent possibility-of-existence of Da-sein as our theme, but our analytic was oriented toward the inconspicuous, average modes of existing. We called the kind of being in which Da-sein holds itself initially and for the most part everydayness. 25 What this expression signifies basically when ontologically defined remains obscure. At the beginning of our inquiry there was no way available of even making the existential and ontological meaning of everydayness a problem. But now the meaning of being of Da-sein has been illuminated as temporality. Can there still be any doubt with regard to the existential and temporal significance of the term "everydayness"? Yet we are far removed from an ontological concept of this phenomenon. It even remains questionable whether the explication of temporality carried out up to now is adequate to explain the existential meaning of everydayness. Everydayness evidently means the mode of existing in which Dasein holds itself "each day." And yet "each day" does not signify the sum of the "days" that are allotted to Da-sein in its "lifetime." Although "each day" is not to be understood in the sense of the calendar, yet some such temporal determination still echoes in the significance of the "everyday." But the expression "everydayness" primarily signifies a certain How of existence that prevails in Da-sein "as long as it lives." In our earlier analyses we often used the expression "initially and for the
* No opposition; both belong together.
II.IV
Being and Time
339
most part." "Initially" means the way in which Da-sein is "manifest" in the being-with-one-another of publicness, even if it has "basically" precisely "overcome" everydayness existentielly. "For the most part" signifies the way in which Da-sein shows itself for everyone "as a rule," but not always. Everydayness means the How in accordance with which Da-sein "lives its day," whether in all of its modes of behavior or only in certain ways prefigured by being-with-one-another. Furthermore, being comfortable in habit belongs to this How, even if habit forces us to what is burdensome and "repulsive." The tomorrow that everyday taking care waits for is the "eternal yesterday." The monotony of everydayness takes whatever the day happens to bring as a change. Everydayness determines Da-sein even when it has not chosen the they as its "hero." But these manifold qualities of everydayness by no means characterize it as the mere "aspect" that Da-sein proffers when "one" "looks at" the things human beings do. Everydayness is a way to be-to which, of course, public manifestness belongs. But as a way of its own existing, everydayness is more or less familiar to actual "individual" Da-sein, indeed, through the attunement of the pallid lack of mood. Da-sein can "suffer" dully from everydayness, sink into its dullness, and evade it by looking for new ways in which its dispersion in its affairs may be further dispersed. But existence can also master the everyday in the Moment, often only "for the moment," but it can never extinguish it. What is ontically so familiar in the factical interpretedness of Dasein that we don't even pay any attention to it, contains enigma upon enigma existentially and ontologically. The "natural" horizon for starting the existential analytic of Da-sein is only seemingly obvious. But, after our earlier interpretation of temporality, are we in a more fruitful position with regard to the existential delimitation of the structure of everydayness? Or does this confusing phenomenon precisely make evident what is insufficient about our explication of temporality up to now? Have we not been constantly immobilizing Da-sein in certain positions and situations, while "consistently" disregarding the fact that, in living into its days, it stretches itself along "temporally" in the succession of its days? The monotony, the habit, the "like yesterday, so today and tomorrow," and the "for the most part" cannot be grasped without recourse to the "temporal" stretching along of Da-sein. And is it not also a fact of existing Da-sein that, passing its time, it takes "time" daily into account and regulates the "calculation" astronomically and with the calendar? Only if we bring the everyday "occurrence" of Da-sein and the heedful calculation of "time" in this occurrence into the interpretation of the temporality of Da-sein, will our orientation become comprehensive enough to enable us to make the
371
340
372
Being and Time
II.IV
ontological meaning of everydayness as such problematic. However, since basically nothing other is meant by the term everydayness than temporality, and since temporality makes the being of Da-sein possible, an adequate conceptual delineation of everydayness can succeed only in the framework of a fundamental discussion of the meaning of being in general and its possible variations.
v Temporality and Historicity
72. Existential and Ontological Exposition of the Problem of History All our efforts in the existential analytic are geared to the one goal of finding a possibility of answering the question of the meaning of being in general. The development of this question requires that we delineate the phenomenon in which something like being itself becomes accessiblethe phenomenon of the understanding of being. But this phenomenon belongs to the constitution of being of Da-sein. Only when this being has been interpreted beforehand in a sufficiently primordial way, can the understanding of being contained in its constitution of being itself be grasped, and only on that basis can we formulate the question of being understood in this understanding and the question of what such understanding "presupposes." Although many structures of Da-sein still remain in the dark with regard to particulars, yet it seems that we have reached the requisite, primordial interpretation ofDa-sein with the clarification of temporality as the primordial condition of the possibility of care. Temporality was set forth with regard to the authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of Da-sein. The temporal interpretation of care was then confirmed by demonstrating the temporality of heedful being-in-the-world. Our analysis of the authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole revealed that an equiprimordial connection of death, guilt, and conscience is rooted in care. Can Da-sein be understood still more primordially than in the project of its authentic existence? Although up to now we have not seen any possibility of a more radical starting point for our existential analytic, yet with regard to the
341
342
373
Being and Time
II.v
above discussion of the ontological meaning of everydayness, a serious reservation comes to light: Has indeed the whole of Da-sein with respect to its authentic being-a-whole been captured in the fore-having of our existential analysis? It may be that the line of questioning related to the wholeness of Da-sein possesses a genuinely unequivocal character ontologically. The question itself may even have been answered with regard to being-toward-the-end. However, death is, after all, only the "end" of Dasein, and formally speaking, it is just one of the ends that embraces the totality of Da-sein. But the other "end" is the "beginning," "birth." Only the being "between" birth and death presents the whole we are looking for. Then the previous orientation of our analytic would remain "onesided," in spite of all its tendencies toward a consideration of existing being-a-whole and in spite of the genuineness with which authentic and inauthentic being-toward-death have been explicated. Da-sein has been our theme only as to how it exists, so to speak, "forward" and leaves everything that has been "behind." Not only did being-toward-the-beginning remain unnoticed, but, above all, the way Da-sein stretches along between birth and death. Precisely the "connection of life," in which, after all, Da-sein constantly somehow holds itself, was overlooked in our analysis of being-a-whole. Must we not then take back our point of departure of temporality as the meaning of being of the totality of Da-sein, even though what we addressed as the "connection" between birth and death is ontologically completely obscure? Or does temporality, as we set it forth, first give the foundation on which to provide an unequivocal direction for the existential and ontological question of that "connection"? Perhaps it is already a gain in the field of this inquiry if we learn not to take the problems too lightly. What seems "more simple" than the nature of the "connection of life" between birth and death? It consists of a succession of experiences "in time." If we pursue this characterization of the connection in question and above all of the ontological assumption behind it in a more penetrating way, something remarkable happens. In this succession of experiences only the experience that is objectively present "in the actual now" is "really" "real." The experiences past and just coming, on the other hand, are no longer or not yet "real." Da-sein traverses the timespan allotted to it between the two boundaries in such a way that it is "real" only in the now and hops, so to speak, through the succession of nows of its "time." For this reason one says that Da-sein is "temporal." The self maintains itself in a certain sameness throughout this constant change of experiences. Opinions diverge as to how this persistent self is to be defined and how one is to determine what relation it may possibly have to the changing experiences. The being of this persistingly chang-
II.v
Being and Time
343
ing connection of experiences remains undetermined. But basically something objectively present "in time," but of course "unthinglike," has been posited in this characterization of the connection of life, whether one admits it or not. With regard to what was developed as the meaning of being of care under the rubric of temporality, we found that while following the guideline of the vulgar interpretation of Da-sein, within its own limits, is justified and adequate, we could not carry through a genuine ontological analysis of the way Da-sein stretches along between birth and death if we take this interpretation as our guideline, nor could we even establish such an analysis as a problem. Da-sein does not exist as the sum of the momentary realities of experiences that succeed each other and disappear. Nor does this succession gradually fill up a framework. For how should that framework be objectively present, when it is always only the experience that one is having "right now" that is "real," and when the boundaries of the framework-birth that is past and death that is yet to come-are lacking reality. At bottom, even the vulgar interpretation of the "connectedness oflife" does not think of a framework spanned "outside" of Da-sein and embracing it, but correctly looks for it in Da-sein itself. When, however, one tacidy regards this being ontologically as something objectively present "in time," an attempt at any ontological characterization of the being "between" birth and death gets stranded. Da-sein does not first fill up an objectively present path or stretch "of life" through the phases of its momentary realities, but stretches itself along in such a way that its own being is constituted beforehand as this stretching along. The "between" of birth and death already lies in the being of Da-sein. On the other hand, it is by no means the case that Dasein is real in a point of time, and that, in addition, it is then "surrounded" by the nonreality of its birth and its death. Understood existentially, birth is never something past in the sense of what is no longer objectively present, and death is just as far from having the kind of being of something outstanding that is not yet objectively present but will come. Factical Da-sein exists as born, and, born, it is already dying in the sense of being-toward-death. Both "ends" and their "between" are as long as Da-sein factically exists, and they are in the sole way possible on the basis of the being of Da-sein as care. In the unity of thrownness and the fleeting or else anticipatory being-toward-death, birth and death "are connected" in the way appropriate to Da-sein. As care, Da-sein is the "Between." But the constitutional totality of care has the possible ground of its unity in temporality. The ontological clarification of the "connectedness of life," that is, of the specific way of stretching along, movement,
374
344
375
376
Being and Time
II.v
and persistence of Da-sein, must accordingly be approached in the horizon of the temporal constitution of this being. The movement of existence is not the motion of something objectively present. It is determined from the stretching along of Da-sein. The specific movement of the stretched out stretching itself along, we call the occurrence of Da-sein. The question of the "connectedness" of Da-sein is the ontological problem of its occurrence. To expose the structure of occurrence and the existential and temporal conditions of its possibility means to gain an ontological understanding of historicity. With the analysis of the specific movement and persistence appropriate to the occurrence of Da-sein, our inquiry returns to the problem that was touched upon right before the exposition of temporality: to the question of the constancy of the self that we determined as the who of Da-sein. 1 Self-constancy is a mode of being of Da-sein and is thus grounded in a specific temporalizing of temporality. The analysis of occurrence introduces the problems found in a thematic investigation into temporalization as such. If the question of historicity leads back to those "origins," the place of the problem of history has thus already been decided upon. We must not search in historiography as the science ofhistory. Even if the scientific and theoretical kind of treaunent of the problem of "history" does not just aim at an "epistemological" (Simmel) clarification of historiographical comprehension, or at the logic of the concept formation of historiographical presentation (Rickert}, but is rather oriented toward the "objective side," history is accessible in this line of questioning only as the object of a science. The basic phenomenon of history, which is prior to the possibility of making something thematic by historiography and underlies it, is thus irrevocably set aside. How history can become a possible object for historiography, can be gathered only from the kind of being of what is historical, from historicity and its rootedness in temporality. If historicity itself is to be illuminated in terms of temporality, and primordially in terms of authentic temporality, then it is essential to this task that it can only be carried out by way of a phenomenological construction. *2 The existential and ontological constitution of historicity must be mastered in opposition to the vulgar interpretation of the history of Da-sein that covers over. The existential construction of historicity has its definite support in the vulgar understanding of Da-sein and is guided by those existential structures attained so far. We shall first describe the vulgar concept of history, so that we may give our investigation an orientation as to the factors which are generally
*Project.
II.v
Being and Time
345
held to be essential for history. Here it must become clear what is primordially considered as historical. Thus the point of departure for the exposition of the ontological problem of historicity has been designated. Our interpretation of the authentic potentiality-of-being-a-whole of Da-sein and our analysis of care as temporality arising from that interpretation, offer the guideline for the existential construction of historicity. The existential project for the historicity of Da-sein only reveals what already lies enveloped in the temporalizing of temporality. Corresponding to the rootedness of historicity in care, Da-sein always exists as authentically or inauthentically historical. What we had in view under the rubric of everydayness for the existential analytic of Da-sein as the nearest horizon gets clarified as the inauthentic historicity of Da-sein. Disclosure and interpretation belong essentially to the occurrence of Da-sein. From the kind of being of this being that exists historically, there arises the existentiell possibility of an explicit disclosure and grasp of history. Making it thematic, that is, the historiographical disclosure of history, is the presupposition for the possibility of "building up the historical world in the sciences of the humanities." The existential interpretation of historiography as a science aims solely at a demonstration of its ontological provenance from the historicity of Da-sein. Only from here are the boundaries to be staked out within which a theory of science oriented toward the factical business of science may expose itself to the chance elements of its line of questioning. The analysis of the historicity of Da-sein attempted to show that this being is not "tempora~ " because it "is in history, " but because, on the contrary, it exists and can exist historically only because it is temporal in the ground of its being. Nevertheless, Da-sein must also be called "temporal" in the sense of its being "in time." Factical Da-sein needs and uses the calendar and the clock even without a developed historiography. What occurs "with it," it experiences as occurring "in time." In the same way, the processes of nature, whether living or lifeless, are encountered "in time." They are within-time. So while our analysis of how the "time" of within-time-ness has its source in temporality will be deferred until the next chapter,' it would be easy to put this before the discussion of the connection between historicity and temporality. What is historical is ordinarily characterized with the aid of the time of within-time-ness. But if this vulgar characterization is to be stripped of its seeming self-evidence and exclusiveness, historicity is to be "deduced" beforehand purely from the primordial temporality of Da-sein. This is required by the way these are "objectively" connected. But since time as within-time-ness also "stems" from the temporality of Da-sein, historicity and within-time-ness tum out to be equiprimordial. The vulgar interpretation of the temporal character of history is thus justified within its limits.
377
346
Being and Time
Il.v
After this first characterization of the course of the ontological exposition of historicity in terms of temporality, do we still need explicit assurance that the following inquiry does not believe that the problem of history can be solved by a sleight of hand? The paucity of the available "categorial" means and the uncertainty of the primary ontological horizons become all the more obtrusive, the more the problem of history is traced to its primordial rootedness. In the following reflections, we shall content ourselves with indicating the ontological place of the problem of historicity. Basically, the following analysis is solely concerned with furthering the investigations of Dilthey in a preparatory way. Today's present generation has not as yet made them its own. Our exposition of the existential problem of historicity-an exposition, moreover, that is of necessity limited by our fundamental and ontological aim-is divided up as follows: the vulgar understanding of history and the occurrence of Da-sein (section 73); the fundamental constitution of historicity (section 74); the historicity of Da-sein and world history (section 75); the existential origin of historiography from the historicity of Da-sein (section 76); the connection of the previous exposition of the problem of historicity with the investigations of Dilthey and the ideas of Count Yorck (section 77). 378
73. The Vulgar Understanding of History and the Occurrence of Da-sein Our next goal is to find the point of departure for the primordial question of the essence of history, that is, for the existential construction of historicity. This point is designated by what is primarily historical. Thus our reflections begin with a characterization of what is meant by the expressions "history" and "historical" in the vulgar interpretation of Dasein. They are ambiguous. The most obvious ambiguity of the term "history" has often been noted, and it is by no means "approximate." It makes itself known in the fact that it means "historical reality" as well as the possibility of a science of it. For the time being, we shall leave out the signification of "history" in the sense of a science of history (historiography}. Among the meanings of the expression "history" that signify neither the science of history nor the latter as an object, but rather this being itself which has not necessarily been objectified, the one in which this being is understood as something past claims a preferred use. This significance makes itself known in talk such as "this or that already belongs to history." Here "past" means on the one hand "no longer objectively present," or else "indeed still objectively present, but without 'effect' on the 'present'." However, what is historical as what is past also has the opposite significance when we say that one cannot evade history.
II.v
Being and Time
347
Here history means what is past,* but is nevertheless still having an effect. However, what is historical as what is past is understood in a positive or privative effective relation to the "present" in the sense of what is real "now" and "today." "The past" has a remarkable ambiguity here. Here "the past" belongs irrevocably to an earlier time; it belonged to former events and can yet still be objectively present "now"-for example, the remains of a Greek temple. A "bit of the past" is still "present" in it. Thus history does not so much mean the "past" in the sense of what is past, but the derivation from it. Whatever "has a history" is in the context of a becoming. Here the "development" is sometimes a rise, sometimes a fall. Whatever "has a history" in this way can at the same time "make" history. "Epoch making," it "presently" determines a "future." Here history means a "connection" of events and "effects" that moves through the "past," the "present" and the "future." Here the past has no particular priority. Furthermore, history signifies the whole of beings that change "in time," the transformations and destinies of humankind, human institutions and their "cultures," in contradistinction to nature that similarly moves "in time." History means here not so much the kind of being, the occurrence, as the region of beings that one distinguishes from nature with regard to the essential determination of the existence of human being as "spirit" and "culture," although nature, too, belongs in a way to history thus understood. And finally, what has been handed down as such is taken to be "historical," whether it be known historiographically or taken over as being self-evident and concealed in its derivation. If we consider the four meanings together, we find that history is the specific occurrence of existing Da-sein happening in time, in such a way that the occurrence in being-with-one-another that is "past" and at the same time "handed down" and still having its effect is taken to be history in the sense emphasized. The four meanings have a connection in that they are related to human being as the "subject" of events. How is the kind of occurrence of these events to be determined? Is the occurrence a succession of processes, a changing appearance and disappearance of events? In what way does this occurrence of history belong to Da-sein? Is Da-sein factically already "objectively present" beforehand, and then at times gets into "a history"? Does Da-sein first become historical through a concatenation of circumstances and events? Or is the being of Da-sein first constituted by occurrence, so that only because Da-sein is historical in its being
* What preceded beforehand and now still remains.
379
348
380
Being and Time
II.v
are anything like circumstances, events, and destinies ontologically possible? Why does precisely the past have an important function in the "temporal" characterization of Da-sein occurring "in time"? If history belongs to the being of Da-sein, and if this being is grounded in temporality, it seems logical to begin the existential analysis of historicity with the characteristics of what is historical that evidently have a temporal meaning. Thus a more precise characterization of the remarkable priority of the "past" in the concept of history should prepare the exposition of the fundamental constitution ofhistoricity. The "antiquities" preserved in museums (for example, household things) belong to a "time past," and are yet still objectively present in the "present." How are these useful things historical when they are, after all, not yet past? Only because they became an object of historiographical interest, of the cultivation of antiquity and national lore? But such useful things can only, after all, be historiographical objects because they are somehow in themselves historical. We repeat the question: With what justification do we call these beings historical when they are not yet past? Or do these "things" "in themselves" yet have "something past" about them although they are still objectively present today? Are these objectively present things then still what they were? Evidently these "things" have changed. The tools have become fragile and worm-eaten "in the course of time." But yet the specific character of the past that makes them something historical does not lie in this transience that continues even during their objective presence in the museum. But then what is past about the useful thing? What were the "things" that they no longer are today? They are still defmite useful things, but out of use. However, if they were still in use, like many heirlooms in the household, would they then not be historical? Whether in use or out of use, they are no longer what they were. What is "past"? Nothing other than the world within which they were encountered as things at hand belonging to a context of useful things and used by heedful Da-sein existing-in-theworld. That world is no longer. But what was previously innerworldly in that world is still objectively present. As useful things belonging to that world, what is now still objectively present can nevertheless belong to the "past." But what does it mean that the world no-longer-is? World is only in the mode of existing Da-sein, that is,Jactically as being-in-the-world. The historical character of extant antiquities is thus grounded in the "past" of Da-sein to whose world that past belongs. According to this, only "past" Da-sein would be historical, but not "present" Da-sein. However, can Da-sein be past at all, if we define "past" as "now no longer objectively present or at hand"? Evidently Da-sein can never be past, not because it is imperishable, but because it can essentially never be objectively present. Rather, if it is, it exists. But a Da-sein that no longer exists is not past in the
II.v
Being and Time
349
ontologically strict sense; it is rather having-been-there. The antiquities still objectively present have a "past" and a character of history because they belong to useful things and originate from a world that has-been-the world of a Da-sein that has-been-there. Da-sein is what is primarily historical. But does Da-sein first become historical by no longer being there? Or is it historical precisely as factically existing? Is Da-sein something that has-been only in the sense of having-been-there, or has it been as something making present and futura~ that is, in the temporalizing of its temporality? From this preliminary analysis of the useful things belonging to history that are still objectively present and yet somehow "past," it becomes clear that this kind of being is historical only on the basis of its belonging to the world. But the world has a historical kind of being because it constitutes an ontological determination of Da-sein. Furthermore, we can see that when one designates a time as "the past," the meaning of this is not unequivocal, but "the past" is manifestly distinct from the having-been, which we got to know as a constituent of the ecstatic unity of the temporality of Da-sein. But thus the enigma ultimately only becomes more acute; why is that precisely the "past" or, more appropriately, the having-been predominately determines what is historical when, after all, having-been temporalizes itself equiprimordially with present and future. We asserted that Da-sein is what is primarily historical. But secondarily historical is what is encountered within the world, not only useful things at hand in the broadest sense, but also nature in the surrounding world as the "historical ground." We call beings unlike Da-sein that are historical by reason of their belonging to the world that which is worldhistorical. We can show that the vulgar concept of "world history" arises precisely from our orientation toward what is secondarily historical. What is world-historical is not first historical on the basis of a historiographical objectivation, but rather as the being that it is in itself encountered in the world. The analysis of the historical character of a useful thing still objectively present not only led us back to Da-sein as what is primarily historical, but at the same time made it dubious whether the temporal characteristics of what is historical should be primarily oriented toward the being-in-time of something objectively present at all. Beings do not become "more historical" as we go on to a past ever farther away, so that what is most ancient would be the most authentically historical. But the "temporal" distance from now and today again has no primarily constitutive significance for the historicity of authentically historical beings, not because they are not "in time" or are timeless, but rather because they primordially exist temporally in a way that nothing objectively present "in time," whether passing away or coming into being, could ever, by its ontological essence, be temporal in such a way.
381
382
350
Being and Time
II.v
It will be said that these are overly complicated remarks. No one denies that human existence is basically the primary "subject" of history, and the vulgar concept of history cited says this clearly enough. But the thesis that "Da-sein is historical" not only means the ontic fact that human being presents a more or less important "atom" in the business of world history, and remains the plaything of circumstances and events, but poses the problem why and on the basis of what ontological conditions, does historicity belong to the subjectivity of the "historical" subject as its essential constitution?
74. The Essential Constitution of Historicity
383
Factically, Da-sein always has its "history," and it can have something of the sort because the being of this being is constituted by historicity. We want to justify this thesis with the intention of setting forth the ontological problem of history as an existential one. The being of Da-sein was defined as care. Care is grounded in temporality. Within the scope of temporality we must accordingly search for an occurrence that determines existence as historical. Thus the interpretation of the historicity of Da-sein turns out to be basically just a more concrete development of temporality. We revealed temporality initially with regard to the mode of authentic existing that we characterized as anticipatory resolution. Why does this involve an authentic occurrence of Da-sein? We determined resoluteness as self-projection upon one's own being guilty4 that is reticent and ready for Angst. It attains its authenticity as anticipatory resoluteness. 5 In it, Da-sein understands itself with regard to its potentiality-of-being in a way that confronts death in order to take over completely the being that it itself is in its thrownness. Resolutely taking over one's own factical "There" means at the same time the resolve for the situation. In the existential analytic we cannot, on principle, discuss what Da-sein factically resolves upon. Our present inquiry excludes even the existential project of factical possibilities of existence. Nevertheless, we must ask whence in general can the possibilities be drawn upon which Da-sein factically projects itself? Anticipatory self-projection upon the possibility of existence not to-be-bypassed-on death-guarantees only the totality and authenticity of resoluteness. But the factically disclosed possibilities of existence are not to be taken from death. All the less so since anticipation of that possibility is not a speculation about it, but rather precisely signifies coming back to the factical There. Is taking over the thrownness of the self into its world supposed to disclose a horizon from which existence seizes its factical possibilities? Did we not moreover say that Da-sein never gets behind its thrownnessj>fi Before we rashly decide whether Da-sein draws its authentic possibilities of existence from
II.v
Being and Time
351
thrownness or not, we must assure ourselves of the complete concept of this fundamental determination of care. It is true that Da-sein is delivered over to itself and its potentialityof-being, but as being-in-the-world. As thrown, it is dependent upon a "world," and exists factically with others. Initially and for the most part, the self is lost in the they. It understands itself in terms of the possibilities of existence that "circulate" in the actual "average" public interpretedness of Da-sein today. Mostly they are made unrecognizable by ambiguity, but they are still familiar. Authentic existentiell understanding is so far from extricating itself from traditional interpretedness that it always grasps its chosen possibility in resolution from that interpretation and in opposition to it, and yet again for it. The resoluteness in which Da-sein comes back to itself discloses the actual factical possibilities of authentic existing in tenns of the heritage which that resoluteness takes over as thrown. Resolute coming back to thrownness involves handing oneself over to traditional possibilities, although not necessarily as traditional ones. If everything "good" is a matter of heritage and if the character of "goodness" lies in making authentic existence possible, then handing down a heritage is always constituted in resoluteness. The more authentically Da-sein resolves itself, that is, understands itself unambiguously in terms of its ownmost eminent possibility in anticipating death, the more unequivocal and inevitable is the choice in finding the possibility of its existence. Only the anticipation of death drives every chance and "preliminary" possibility out. Only being free for death gives Da-sein its absolute goal and knocks existence into its finitude. The finitude of existence thus seized upon tears one back out of endless multiplicity of possibilities offering themselves nearest by-those of comfort, shirking and taking things easyand brings Da-sein to the simplicity of its fate. This is how we designate the primordial occurrence ofDa-sein that lies in authentic resoluteness in which it hands itself down to itself, free for death, in a possibility that it inherited and yet has chosen. Da-sein can only be reached by the blows of fate because in the basis of its being it is fate in the sense described. Existing fatefully in resoluteness handing itself down, Da-sein is disclosed as being-in-the-world for the "coming" of "fortunate" circumstances and for the cruelty of chance. Fate does not first originate with the collision of circumstances and events. Even an irresolute person is driven by them, more so than someone who has chosen, and yet he can "have" no fate. When Da-sein, anticipating, lets death become powerful in itself, as free for death it understands itself in its own higher power, the power of its finite freedom, and takes over the powerlessness of being abandoned to itself in that freedom, which always only is in having chosen the choice,
384
352
385
386
Being and Time
II.v
and becomes clear about the chance elements in the situation disclosed. But if fateful Da-sein essentially exists as being-in-the-world in beingwith others, its occurrence is an occurrence-with and is determined as destiny. With this term, we designate the occurrence of the community, of a people. Destiny is not composed of individual fates, nor can beingwith-one-another be conceived of as the mutual occurrence of several subjects. 7 These fates are already guided beforehand in being-with-oneanother in the same world and in the resoluteness for definite possibilities. In communication and in battle the power of destiny first becomes free. The fateful destiny of Da-sein in and with its "generation"8 constitutes the complete, authentic occurrence of Da-sein As the powerless higher power preparing itself for adversities, the power of reticent self-projection, ready for Ang.5t, upon one's own beingguilty, fate requires the constitution of being of care as the ontological condition of its possibility, that is, temporality. Only if death, guilt, conscience, freedom, and finitude live together equiprimordially in the being of a being as they do in care, can that being exist in the mode of fate, that is, be historical in the ground of its existence. Only a being that is essentially futural in its being so that it can let itself be throum back upon its factical There, free for its death and shattering itself on it, that is, only a being that, as futura~ is equiprimordially having-been, can hand doum to itself its inherited possibility, take over its own thrownness and be in the Moment for "its time. " Only authentic temporality that is at the same time finite makes something like fate, that is, authentic historicity, possible. It is not necessary that resoluteness explicitly know of the provenance of its possibilities upon which it projects itself. However, in the temporality of Da-sein, and only in it, lies the possibility of fetching the existentiell potentiality-of-being upon which it projects itself explicitly from the traditional understanding of Da-sein. Resoluteness that comes back to itself and hands itself down then becomes the retrieve of a possibility of existence that has been handed down. Retrieve is explicit handing down, that is, going back to the possibilities of the Da-sein that has been there. The authentic retrieve of a possibility of existence that has been-the possibility that Da-sein may choose its heroes-is existentially grounded in anticipatory resoluteness; for in resoluteness the choice is first chosen that makes one free for the struggle to come, and the loyalty to what can be retrieved. The handing down of a possibility that has been in retrieving it, however, does not disclose the Da-sein that has been there in order to actualize it again. The retrieve of what is possible neither brings back "what is past," nor does it bind the "present" back to what is "outdated." Arising from a resolute self-projection, retrieve is not convinced by "something past," in just letting it come back as what was once real. Rather, retrieve responds to the possibility of existence that has-
II.v
Being and Time
353
been-there. But responding to the possibility in a resolution is at the same time, a5 in the Moment, the disavowal of what is working itself out today as the "past." Retrieve neither abandons itself to the past, nor does it aim at progress. In the Moment, authentic existence is indifferent to both of these alternatives. We characterize retrieve as the mode of resolution handing itself down, by which Da-sein exists explicitly as fate. But if fate constitutes the primordial historicity of Da-sein, history has its essential weight neither in what is past nor in the today and its "connection" with what is past, but in the authentic occurrence of existence that arises from the future of Da-sein. As a mode of being of Da-sein, history has its roots so essentially in the future that death, as the possibility of Da-sein we characterized, throws anticipatory existence back upon its factical thrownness and thus first gives to the having-been its unique priority in what is historical. Authentic being-toward-death, that is, the finitude of temporality, is the concealed ground of the historicity of Da-sein. Da-sein does not first become historical in retrieve, but rather because as temporal it is historical, it can take itself over in its history, retrieving itself. Here no historiography is needed as yet. We call the anticipatory handing oneself down to the There of the Moment that lies in resoluteness fate. In it destiny is also grounded, by which we understand the occurrence of Da-sein in being-with-others. Fateful destiny can be explicitly disclosed in retrieve with regard to its being bound up with the heritage handed down to it. Repetition first makes manifest to Da-sein its own history. Retrieve first reveals to Dasein its own history. The occurrence itself and the disclosedness belonging to it, or the appropriation of it, is existentially grounded in the fact that Da-sein is ecstatically open as a temporal being. What we characterized as historicity in conformity with the occurrence lying in anticipatory resoluteness, we shall call the authentic historicity of Da-sein. It became clear in terms of the phenomena of handing down and retrieve, rooted in the future, why the occurrence of authentic history has its weight in having-been. However, it remains all the more enigmatic how this occurrence, as fate, is to constitute the whole "connection" of Da-sein from its birth to its death. What can going back to resoluteness add to this by way of clarification? Is not each resolution just one more single "experience" in the succession of the whole connection of experiences? Is the "connection" of authentic occurrence supposed to consist of an uninterrupted succession of resolutions? Why does the question of the constitution of the "connection of life" not find an adequate and satisfactory answer? Is not our inquiry overhasty? Does it not, in the end, cling too much to the answer, without having tested the question beforehand as to its legitimacy? Nothing
387
354
Being and Time
II.v
became more clear from the course of the existential analytic so far than the fact that the ontology of Da-sein falls prey to the temptations of the vulgar understanding of being again and again. We can cope with this methodically only by pursuing the origin of the question of the constitution of the connection of Da-sein, no matter how "self-evident" this question may be, and by determining in what ontological horizon it moves. If historicity belongs to the being of Da-sein, then even inauthentic existence must be historical. Did the inauthentic historicity of Da-sein determine our line of questioning about a "connection of life" and block the access to authentic historicity and the "connection" peculiar to it? However that may be, if the exposition of the ontological problem of history is supposed to be adequate and complete, we cannot escape considering the inauthentic historicity of Da-sein.
75. The Historicity of Da-sein and World History
388
Initially and for the most part, Da-sein understands itself in terms of what it encounters in the surrounding world and what it circumspectly takes care of. Understanding is not just a bare taking cognizance of itself which simply accompanies all the modes of behavior of Da-sein. Understanding signifies self-projection upon the actual possibility of being-in-the-world, that is, existing as this possibility. Thus understanding, as common sense, also constitutes the inauthentic existence of the they. What everyday taking care of things encounters in public beingwith-one-another is not just useful things and works, but at the same time what "is going on" with them: "affairs," undertakings, incidents, mishaps. The "world" belongs to everyday trade and traffic as the soil from which they grow and the stage where they are displayed. In public being-with-one-another the others are encountered in the activities in which "one" "swims along" with it "oneself." One always knows about it, talks about it, furthers it, fights it, retains it, and forgets it primarily with regard to what is being done and what will "come out of it." We initially calculate the progress, arrest, adjustment, and "output" of individual Da-sein in terms of the course, status, change, and availability of what is taken care of. As trivial as the reference to the understanding of Da-sein of everyday common sense may be, ontologically this understanding is by no means transparent. But then why should the "connectedness" ofDa-sein not be determined in terms of what is taken care of and "experienced"? Do not useful things and works and everything that Da-sein spends time with also belong to "history"? Is the occurrence of history then only the isolated course of "streams of experience" in individual subjects?
Il.v
Being and Time
355
Indeed, history is neither the connectedness of movements in the alteration of objects, nor the free-floating succession of experiences of "subjects." Does the occurrence of history then pertain to the "linking" of subject and object? Even if one assigns occurrence to the subject-object relationship, then we must ask about the kind of being of this linking as such, if it is that which basically "occurs." The thesis of the historicity of Da-sein does not say that the worldless subject is historical, but that what is historical is the being that exists as being-in-the-world. The occurrence of history is the occurrence of being-in-the-world. The historicity of Da-sein is essentially the historicity of the world which, on the basis of its ecstatic and horizonal temporality, belongs to the temporalizing of that temporality. When Da-sein factically exists, it alrea:dy encounters beings discovered within the world. With the existence of historical being-in-the-world, things at hand and objectively present have always already been included in the history of the world. Tools and works, for example books, have their "fates"; buildings and institutions have their history. And even nature is historical. It is not historical when we speak about "natural history," 9 but nature is historical as a countryside, as areas that have been inhabited or exploited, as battlefields and cultic sites. These innerworldly beings as such are historical, and their history does not signify something "external" that simply accompanies the "inner" history of the "soul." We shall call these beings world-historical. Here we must observe that the expression "world history" that we have chosen and that is here understood ontologically, has a double meaning. On the one hand, it signifies the occurrence of world in its essential existent unity with Da-sein. But at the same time it means the innerworldly "occurrence" of what is at hand and objectively present, since innerworldly beings are always discovered with the factically existent world. The historical world is factically only as the world of innerworldly beings. What "occurs" with tools and works as such has its own character of motion, and this character has been completely obscure up to now. For example, a ring that is "presented" and "worn" does not simply undergo a change of location in its being. The movement of occurrence in which "something happens to it" cannot be grasped at all in terms of motion as change of location. That is true of all world-historical "processes" and events, and in a way even of "catastrophes of nature." Quite apart from the fact that we would necessarily go beyond the limits of our theme if we were to pursue the problem of the ontological structure of world-historical occurrence, we cannot do this because the intention of this exposition is to lead us to the ontological enigma of the movement Qf occurrence in general. We only want to delimit that range of phenomena that we also necessarily have in mind ontologically when we speak about the historicity of Da-sein. On the basis of the temporally founded transcen-
389
356
390
Being and Time
Il.v
dence of the world, what is world-historical is always already "objectively" there in the occurrence of existing being-in-the-world, without being grasped historiographically. And since factical Da-sein is absorbed and entangled in what it takes care of, it initially understands its history as world history. And since, furthermore, the vulgar understanding of being understands "being" as objective presence without further differentiation, the being of what is world-historical is experienced and interpreted in the sense of objective presence that comes along, is present, and disappears. And finally since the meaning of being in general is taken to be what is absolutely self-evident, the question of the kind of being of what is world-historical and of the movement of occurrence in general is "after all really" only unfruitful and unnecessarily complicated verbal sophistry. Everyday Da-sein is dispersed in the multiplicity of what "happens" daily. The opportunities and circumstances that taking care keeps "tactically" awaiting in advance, result in "fate." Inauthentically existing Dasein first calculates its history in terms of what it takes care of. In so doing, it is driven about by its "affairs." So if it wants to come to itself, it must first pull itself together from the dispersion and the disconnectedness of what has just "happened," and because of this, it is only then that there at last arises from the horizon of the understanding of inauthentic historicity the question of how one is to establish Da-sein's "connectedness" if one does so in the sense of the experiences of the subject "also" objectively present. The possibility that this horizon for the question should be the dominant one, is grounded in irresoluteness that constitutes the essence of the in-constancy of the self. We have thus pointed out the origin of the question of Da-sein's "connectedness" in the sense of the unity with which experiences are linked together between birth and death. At the same time, the provenance of this question betrays its inappropriateness with regard to a primordial existential interpretation of the totality of occurrence of Dasein. But, on the other hand, with the predominance of this "natural" horizon of questioning, it becomes explicable why precisely the authentic historicity of Da-sein-fate and retrieve-looks as if it, least of all, could provide the phenomenal basis for bringing into the form of an ontologically founded problem what is fundamentally intended with the question of the "connectedness of life." This question can not ask: how does Da-sein acquire such a unity of connection that it can subsequently link together the succession of "experiences" that has ensued and is still ensuing; rather, it asks in which of its own kinds of being does it lose itself in such a way that it must, as it were, pull itself together only subsequently out of its dispersion, and think up for itself a unity in which this together is embraced? Lostness in the they and in
II.V
Being and Time
357
world history, revealed itself earlier as a flight from death. This flight from ... reveals being-toward-death as a fundamental determination of care. Anticipatory resoluteness brings this being-toward-death to authentic existence. But we interpreted the occurrence of this resoluteness that anticipates and hands down and retrieves the heritage of possibilities, as authentic historicity. Does perhaps the primordial stretching along of the whole of existence, which is not lost and does not need a connection, lie in historicity? The resoluteness of the self against the inconstancy of dispersion is in itself a steadiness that has been stretched along-the steadiness in which Da-sein as fate "incorporates" into its existence birth and death and their "between" in such a way that in such constancy it is in the Moment for what is world-historical in its actual situation. In the fateful retrieve of possibilities that have-been, Da-sein brings itself back "immediately," that is, temporally and ecstatically, to what has already been before it. But when its heritage is thus handed down to itself, "birth" is taken into existence in coming back from the possibility of death (the possibility not-to-be-bypassed) so that existence may accept the thrownness of its own There more free from illusion. Resoluteness constitutes the loyalty of existence to its own self. As resoluteness ready for Angst, loyalty is at the same time a possible reverence for the sole authority that a free existence can have, for the possibilities of existence that can be retrieved. Resoluteness would be misunderstood ontologically if one thought that it is real as "experience" only as long as the "act" of resolution "lasts." In resoluteness lies the existentiell constancy which, in keeping with its essence, has already anticipated every possible Moment arising from it. As fate, resoluteness is freedom to give up a definite resolution, as may be required in the situation. Thus the steadiness of existence is not interrupted, but precisely confirmed in the Moment. Constancy is not first formed either through or by "Moments" adjoining each other, but rather the Moments arise from the temporality, already stretched along, of that retrieve which is futurally in the process of having-been. On the other hand, in inauthentic historicity the primordial stretching along of fate is concealed. With the inconstancy of the theyself, Da-sein makes present its "today." Awaiting the next new thing, it has already forgotten what is old. The they evades choice. Blind toward possibilities, it is incapable of retrieving what has been, but only retains what is and receives "real," what has been left over, of the world-historical that has been, the remnants, and the information about them that is objectively present. Lost in the making present of the today, it understands the "past" in terms of the "present." In contrast, the temporality of authentic historicity, as the Moment that anticipates and retrieves, undoes the making present of the today and the habituation to the con-
391
358
392
Being and Time
Il.v
ventionalities of the they. Inauthentic historical existence, on the other hand, is burdened with the legacy of a "past" that has become unrecognizable to it, looks for what is modern. Authentic historicity understands history as the "recurrence" of what is possible and knows that a possibility recurs only when existence is open for it fatefully, in the Moment, in resolute retrieve. The existential interpretation of the historicity of Da-sein constantly gets eclipsed unawares. The obscurities are all the more difficult to dispel when the possible dimensions of appropriate questioning are not disentangled and when everything is haunted by the enigma of being and, as has now become clear, of movement. Nevertheless, we may venture a project of the ontological genesis of historiography as a science in terms of the historicity of Da-sein. It should serve as a preparation for the clarification of the task of a historical destructuring of the history of philosophy 10 to be carried out in what follows.
76. The Existential Origin of Historiography from the Historicity of Da-sein
393
That historiography, like every science as a mode of being of Da-sein, is factically and actually "dependent" upon the "dominant worldview" needs no discussion. However, beyond this fact, we must inquire into the ontological possibility of the origin of the sciences from the constitution of being of Da-sein. This origin is still not very transparent. In the present context our analysis will familiarize us in outline with the existential origin of historiography only to the extent that it will throw more light upon the historicity of Da-sein, and its roots in temporality. If the being of Da-sein is in principle historical, then every factical science evidently remains bound to this occurrence. But historiography presupposes the historicity of Da-sein in its own distinctive way. At first one wants to clarify that by referring to the fact that historiography, as a science of the history of Da-sein, must "presuppose" the being that is primordially historical as its possible "object." But history must not only be in order for a historiographical object to be accessible; and historiographical cognition, as an actual mode of behavior of Dasein, is not only historical. Rather, the historiographical disclosure of history is in itself rooted in the historicity of Da-sein in accordance with its ontological structure, whether it is factically carried out or not. This connection is what the talk about the existential origin of historiography from the historicity of Da-sein means. To throw light on this connection means methodically to project ontologically the idea of historiography in terms of the historicity of Da-sein. On the other hand, it is not a matter of "abstracting" the concept of historiography from some factical proce-
II.V
Being and Time
359
dure of the sciences today nor of assimilating it to that procedure. For what guarantee do we have in principle that this factical procedure indeed represents historiography's primordial and authentic possibilities? And even if that is true (we shall not decide now) then the concept could still be "discovered" in fact only if guided by the idea of historiography that had already been understood. However, on the other hand, the existential idea of historiography is not given a higher justification if the historian's factical mode of behavior confirms it by agreeing with it. Nor does the idea become "false" if he contests any such agreement. The idea of historiography as a science implies that it has grasped the disclosure of historical beings as its own task. Every science is primarily constituted by thematization. What is known prescientifically in Da-sein as disclosed being-in-the-world is projected upon its specific being. The region of beings is limited by this project. The accesses to it contain their methodical "directive," and the conceptual structure of interpretation is outlined. If we may postpone the question of whether a "history of the present" is possible and assign to historiography the task of disclosing the "past," the historiographical thematization of history is possible only if the "past" has always already been disclosed in general. Quite apart from the question of whether sufficient sources are available for a historiographical envisagement of the past, the way to it must be open in general for the historiographical return to it. That something like this is true and how it is possible is by no means obvious. But since the being of Da-sein is historical, that is, since it is open in its character of having-been on the basis of ecstatical and horizonal temporality, the way is in general freed for such thematization of the "past" as can be carried out in existence. And because Da-sein and only Da-sein is primordially historical, what historiographical thematization presents as the possible object of its investigation must have the kind of being of Da-sein that has-been-there. Together with factical Da-sein as being-in-the-world, there is also always world history. If Da-sein is no longer there, then the world, too, is something that has-been-there. This is not in conflict with the fact that what was formerly at hand within the world does not yet pass away, but is available "historiographically" for the present as something that has not passed away and belongs to the world that has-been-there. Remains, monuments, and records that are still objectively present are possible "material" for the concrete disclosure of Da-sein that hasbeen-there. These things can become historiographical material only because they have a world-historical character in accordance with their own kind of being. And they become such material only by being understood from the outset with regard to their innerworldliness. The world
394
360
395
Being and Time
II.v
already projected is determined by way of an interpretation of the worldhistorical material that has been "preserved." The acquisition, sifting, and securing of such material does not first bring about a return to the "past," but rather already presupposes historical being toward the Da-sein that has-been-there, that is, the historicity of the historian's existence. His existence existentially grounds historiography as science, down to the most trivial, "mechanical" procedures. 11 If historiography is rooted in historicity in this way, then we should also be able to determine from there what the object of historiography "really" is. The delimitation of the primordial theme of historiography must be carried out in conformity with authentic historicity and its disclosure of what-has-been-there, of retrieve. Retrieve understands Dasein that has-been-there in its authentic possibility that has-been. The "birth" of historiography from authentic historicity then means that the primary thematization of the object of historiography projects Da-sein that has-been-there upon its ownmost potentiality-of-existence. Does historiography thus have what is possible as its theme? Does not its whole "meaning" lie in "facts," in what has factually been? However, what does it mean that Da-sein "factually" is? If Da-sein is "really" actual only in existence, its "factuality" is, after all, constituted precisely by its resolute self-projection upon a chosen potentiality-ofbeing. What has "factually" really been there, however, is then the existentiell possibility in which fate, destiny, and world history are factically determined. Because existence always is only as factically thrown, historiography will disclose the silent power of the possible with greater penetration the more simply and concretely it understands having-been-inthe-world in terms of its possibility, and "just" presents it. If historiography, which itself arises from authentic historicity, reveals by retrieve the Da-sein that has-been-there in its possibility, it has also already made the "universal" manifest in what is unique. The question of whether historiography only has as its object a series of unique, "individual" events, or whether it also has "laws," is radically mistaken. Neither what only occurs uniquely nor something universal above these is its theme, but rather the possibility that has been factically existent. This possibility is not retrieved as such, that is, authentically understood historiographically, if it is distorted into the pallor of a supratemporal pattern. Only factically authentic historicity, as resolute fate, can disclose the history that has-been-there in such a way that in retrieve the "power" of the possible breaks into factical existence, that is, comes toward it in its futurality. Historiography by no means takes its point of departure from the "present" and what is "real" only today, any more than does the historicity of unhistorical Da-sein, and then grope its way back from there to a past. Rather, even historiographical dis-
II.v
Being and Time
361
closure temporalizes itself out of the future. The "selection" of what is to become a possible object for historiography has already been made in the factical existentiell choice of the historicity of Da-sein, in which historiography first arises and is uniquely. The historiographical disclosure of the "past" is grounded in fateful retrieve and is so far from being "subjective" that it alone guarantees the "objectivity" of historiography. For the objectivity of a science is primarily regulated by the question whether that science can unconcealedly confront understanding with the being belonging to it as its theme in the primordiality of its being. In no science are the "universal validity" of standards and the claims to "universality" that are demanded by the they and its common sense less possible criteria of "truth" than in authentic historiography. Only because the central theme of historiography is always the possibility of existence that has-been-there, and because the latter always factically exists in a world-historical way, can historiography demand of itself a relentless orientation toward "facts." For this reason factical research has many branches and makes the history of useful things, works, culture, spirit, and ideas its object. At the same time history, handing itself down, is in itself always in an interpretedness that belongs to it, and that has a history of its own; so that for the most part it is only through traditional history that historiography penetrates into what hasbeen-there itself. This explains why concrete historiographical research can always keep to its authentic theme in varying degrees of nearness. The historian who from the outset has "projected" upon the "worldview" of an era has not yet proven that he understands his subject-matter authentically and historically and not just "aesthetically." On the other hand, the existence of a historian who "only" edits sources may be determined by an authentic historicity. Thus the dominance of a differentiated historiographical interest, even in the most remote and primitive cultures, is in itself no proof of the authentic historicity of an "age." Ultimately, the rise of the problem of "historicism" is the clearest indication that historiography strives to alienate Da-sein from its authentic historicity. Historicity does not necessarily need historiography. Unhistoriographical ages are as such not also automatically unhistorical. The possibility that historiography in general can be either an "advantage" or a "disadvantage" ... for "life" is based on the fact that life is historical in the roots of its being and has thus, factically existing, always already decided upon authentic or inauthentic historicity. Nietzsche recognized what is essential about "advantage and disadvantage of historiography for life" in the second of his Untimely Meditations ( 1874) and stated it unequivocally and penetratingly. He distinguishes three
396
362
397
Being and Time
II.v
kinds of historiography: the monumental, the antiquarian, and the critical, without demonstrating explicitly the necessity of this triad and the ground of its unity. The threefold character of historiography is prefigured in the historicity of Da-sein. At the same time historicity enables us to understand why authentic historiography must be the factical and concrete unity of these three possibilities. Nietzsche's division is not accidental. The beginning of his Untimely Meditations makes us suspect that he understood more than he made known. As historical, Da-sein is possible only on the basis of temporality. Temporality temporalizes itself in the ecstatic-horizonal unity of its raptures. Da-sein exists as futural authentically in the resolute disclosure of a chosen possibility. Resolutely coming back to itself, it is open in retrieve for the "monumental" possibilities of human existence. The historiography arising from this historicity is "monumental." As havingbeen, Da-sein is delivered over to its thrownness. In appropriating the possible in retrieve, there is prefigured at the same time the possibility of reverently preserving the existence that has-been-there, in which the possibility grasped became manifest. As monumental, authentic historiography is thus "antiquarian." Da-sein temporalizes itself in the unity of future and the having-been as the present. The present, as the Moment, discloses the today authentically. But since the today is interpreted in terms of understanding a possibility of existence grasped-an understanding that futurally retrieves-authentic historiography ceases to make the today present, that is, it suffers itself to become detached from the entangled publicness of the today. As authentic, monumental-antiquarian historiography is necessarily a critique of the "present." Authentic historicity is the foundation of the possible unity of the three kinds of historiography. But the ground on which authentic historiography is founded is temporality as the existential meaning of being of care. The existential and historical origin of historiography may be presented concretely by analyzing the thematization that constitutes this science. Historiographical thematization centers on developing the hermeneutical situation that is opened up-once historically existing Dasein has made its resolution-to the disclosure in retrieve of what hasbeen-there. The possibility and the structure of historiographical truth are to be set forth in terms of the authentic disclosedness ("truth") of historical existence. But since the fundamental concepts of the historiographical sciences-whether they pertain to the objects of these sciences or to the way these are treated-are concepts of existence, the theory of the humanistic sciences presupposes a thematic and existential interpretation of the historicity of Da-sein. Such an interpretation is the constant goal that Dilthey's investigations attempt to approach and that is illuminated more penetratingly by the ideas of Count Yorck von Wartenburg.
n.v
Being and Time
363
77. The Connection of the Foregoing Exposition of the Problem of Historicity with the Investigations of Dilthey and the Ideas of Count Yorck Our analysis of the problem of history grew out of an appropriation of Dilthey's work. It was corroborated, and at the same time strengthened, by Count Yorck's theses that are scattered throughout his letters to Dilthey. 12 The image of Dilthey still prevalent today is that of the "sensitive" interpreter of the history of the spirit, especially the history of literature, who "also" concerned himself with the distinction between the natural and the human sciences, attributing a distinctive role to the history of these sciences and also to "psychology," then letting the whole merge into a relativistic "philosophy of life." For a superficial consideration, this sketch is "correct." But it misses the "substance." It covers over more than it reveals. Dilthey's investigations can be divided schematically into three areas: psychology, in which the "whole fact of man" is presented and differentiated from the natural sciences; investigations on the history of the human sciences, society, and the state; and endeavors toward a psychology in which the "whole fact of being human" is to be presented. Investigations in scientific theory, the history of science, and hermeneutical psychology constantly interpenetrate and overlap each other. When one direction predominates, the others are motives and means. What appears to be disunity and uncertain, chance "attempts," is an elemental restlessness, of which the one goal is to understand "life" philosophically and to secure for this understanding a hermeneutical foundation in terms of "life itself." Everything is centered in the "psychology" that is supposed to understand "life" in the historical context of its development and its effects, as the way in which human being is, as the possible object of the human sciences and especially the root of these sciences. Hermeneutics is the self-clarification of this understanding; it is also the methodology of historiography, though only in a derivative form. In contemporaneous discussions, Dilthey's own investigations for laying the foundations for the humanistic sciences were forced one-sidedly into the field of a theory of science; and it was with a regard for such discussions that his publications were often oriented in this direction. The "logic of the human sciences" was by no means central for him-no more than he was striving in his "psychology" inerely to improve the positivistic science of the psychical. Dilthey's friend, Count Yorck, gives unambiguous expression to Dilthey's ownmost philosophical tendency when he refers to our common interest in understanding historicity (Heidegger's italics). 15 Dilthey's
398
364
399
Being and Time
II.v
investigations are only now becoming accessible in their complete scope, if we are to make them our own we need the constancy and concretion of coming to terms with them in principle. This is not the place 14 for a detailed discussion of the problems that motivated him or how they motivated him. We shall, however, describe in a provisional way some of Count Yorck's central ideas by selecting characteristic passages from the letters. In these communications Yorck's own tendency is brought to life by Dilthey's questions and work, and this tendency can be seen in his stance with regard to the tasks of the fundamental discipline-analytical psychology. About Dilthey's academy treatise, "Ideas on a Descriptive and Analytic Psychology," he writes: It is definitely established that self-reflection is the primary means of knowing, and that the primary procedure of knowing is analysis. From this standpoint principles are formulated that are verified by their own findings. No progress is made toward critically breaking down constructive psychology and its assumptions, explaining it and thus refuting it from within. . .. Your disregard for breaking things down critically (i.e., for demonstrating their provenance psychologically and carrying this out trenchantly in detail) is, in my opinion, connected with your concept of the theory of knowledge and the position you assign to it. (Briefwechsel, p. 177) The explanation of inapplicability-the fact is set up and made dear-is given only by a theory of knowledge. It has to give justifications for the adequacy of scientific methods; it has to provide the grounds for a doctrine of method, instead of having its methods taken from individual areas, at a venture, I must say. (p. 179) At bottom Yorck is demanding a logic preceding the sciences and guiding them as did Platonic and Aristotelian logic, and this demand includes the task of developing, positively and radically, the various categorial structures of the being that is nature and the being that is history (Da-sein). Yorck finds that Dilthey's investigations "too little emphasize the generic difference between the ontic and the historical" (p. 191, Heidegger's italics).
400
In particular, the procedure of comparison is claimed as the method of the human sciences. Here I disagree with you.... Comparison is always aesthetic and is bound to form. Windelband assigns forms to history. Your concept of the type is an entirely
II.v
Being and Time
365
inward one. Here it is a matter of characteristics, not forms. For Windelband, history is a series of pictures, individual forms, aesthetic demands. For the natural scientist, besides science, only aesthetic pleasure remains as a kind of human tranquillizer. Your concept of history is, after all, that of a nexus of forces, unities of force, to which the category of form should be applied only in a symbolic sense. (p. 193) In terms of his certain instinct for the "difference between the ontic and the historical," Yorck knew how strongly traditional historical investigation is geared to "purely ocular determinations" (p. 192) that aim at what has body and form. Ranke is a great ocularist, for whom things that have vanished can never become realities . ... Ranke's whole manner can be explained in terms of his limiting the stuff of history to the political. Only the political is dramatic. (p. 60) The modifications that have come in the course of time seem inessential to me, and here I probably judge differently from you. For example, I think that the so-called historical school is merely a side-current within the same riverbed, and represents only one branch of an old and thorough-going opposition. The name has something deceptive about it. That school was not historical at all [Heidegger's italics], but rather an antiquarian one, construing things aesthetically, whereas the great, dominating movement was one of mechanical construction. Thus what it added methodically to the method of rationality was only a general feeling. (pp. 68f.) The genuine philologian-he conceives of historiography as a cabinet of antiquities. Where nothing is palpable-where only a living psychical transposition guides us-these gentlemen never get there. At heart they are natural scientists, and they become skeptics all the more because there are no experiments. One must keep completely away from the petty details, for example, how often Plato was is Magna Graecia or Syracuse. There is no vitality in that. This superficial affectation that I have seen through critically, finally boils down to a large question mark and is put to shame by the great realities of Plato, Homer, and the New Testament. Everything real becomes a schema when it is considered as a "thing in itself," when it is not experienced. (p. 61) The "scientists" confront the powers of the time in a way similar to the over-refined French society of the revolutionary period. Here
366
401
Being and Time
II.v
as there, formalism, the cult of form, the defining of relationship is the last word of wisdom. Of course, this direction of thought has its own history that, I believe, is not yet written. The groundlessness of this thinking and of the faith in it (and such thinking is, epistemologically considered, a metaphysical attitude) is a historical product. (p. 39) The groundswells evoked by the principle of eccentricity that led to a new time more than four hundred years ago seem to me to have become exceedingly broad and flat; knowledge has progressed to the point of negating itself; man has become so far removed from himself that he has lost sight of himself. "Modem man," i.e., man since the Renaissance, is ready to he buried. (p. 83) In contrast, "all written history that is alive and not just depicting life is critique" (p. 19). "But historical knowledge is, for the best part, knowledge of hidden sources" (p. 109). "With history, what creates a spectacle and catches the eye is not the main thing. The nerves are invisible, as is the essential in general. And as it is said that 'if you were quiet, you would be strong,' the variation of this is also true: If you are quiet, you will perceive, i.e., understand" (p. 26). "And then I enjoy the silent soliloquy and commerce with the spirit of history. This spirit did not appear to Faust in his study, nor to Master Goethe either. They would not have flinched from him in alarm, no matter how serious and compelling the apparition was. For it is brotherly and akin to us in a sense deeper and other than the inhabitants of bush and field. These exertions are like Jacob's wrestling, a sure gain for the wrestler himself. That is what matters first of all" (p. 133). Yorck gets his clear insight into the fundamental character of history as "virtuality" from his knowledge of the characteristics of being of human existence itself, thus precisely not in a theoretical and scientific way oriented to the object of historical observation. That the whole psychophysical datum is not [being is the objective presence of nature-Heidegger's note], but lies in the core of historicity. And if self-reflection is directed not to an abstract ego, but to the fullness of my self, it will find me historically determined, just as physics knows me as cosmically determined. I am history as well as nature" (p. 71). And Yorck, who saw through all false "relational definitions" and "groundless" relativisms, did not hesitate to draw the final conclusion from his insight into the historicity of Da-sein.
402
But, on the other hand, a systematic that is separated from history is methodologically inadequate for the inner historicity of
II.v
Being and Time
367
self-consciousness. Just as physiology cannot be studied in abstraction from physics, neither can philosophy from historicity, especially if it is critical.... Self-relation and historicity are like breathing and atmospheric pressure and, although this sounds rather paradoxical, it seems to me methodologically like a residue of metaphysics not to historicize philosophizing. (p. 69) Since philosophizing is living, there is (don't be alarmed) in my opinion a philosophy of history-but who could write it! Certainly not in the way that it has been interpreted and attempted up to now, and you have declared yourself irrefutably against this. The line of questioning up to now was simply false, even impossible, but it is not the only one. Thus there is no longer any real philosophizing that is not historical. The separation between systematic philosophy and historical presentation is essentially wrong. (p. 251) Being able to become practical is now, of course, the real basis for the justification of any science. But the mathematical praxis is not the only one. The practical aim of our standpoint is the pedagogical one in the broadest and deepest sense of the word. It is the soul of all true philosophy and the truth of Plato and Aristotle. (pp. 42f.} You know what I think about the possibility of ethics as a science. Nevertheless, it can always be improved. Who are such books really for? Registries about registries! The only thing worthy of notice here is the drive from physics to ethics. (p. 73) If one conceives of philosophy as a manifestation of life and not as the expectoration of a groundless thinking (and such thinking appears groundless because the view is turned away from the ground of consciousness}, the task is as complicated and arduous in its gain as it is meagre in its results. Freedom from prejudice is what it presupposes, and that is difficult to obtain. (p. 250) That Yorck set out to grasp the historical categorially, as opposed to the antic (ocular) and to elevate "life" into its appropriate scientific understanding, becomes clear from his reference to the kind of difficulty of such investigations. The aesthetic and mechanistic kind of thinking is more easily expressed verbally than an analysis that goes behind intuition, and this can be explained by the wide extent to which words have their provenance in the ocular.... On the other hand,
368
403
Being and Time
II.v
what penetrates to the ground of vitality eludes an exoteric presentation; hence all its terminology is not intelligible to all, it is symbolic and inevitable. From the special kind of philosophical thinking follows the special character of its linguistic expression. (pp.70f.) But you are familiar with my predilection for paradox, which I justify by the fact that paradox is a mark of truth, that the communis opinio is surely never in the truth, but is like an elemental precipitate of a halfway understanding that makes generalizations; in its relationship to truth it is like the sulphurous fumes that lightning leaves behind. Truth is never an element. To dissolve elemental public opinion and, if possible, to make possible the shaping of individuality in seeing and regarding, would be a pedagogical task for the state. Then instead of a so-called public conscience-instead of this radical externalization-individual conscience, i.e., conscience, would again become powerful. (pp. 249f.) If one has an interest in understanding historicity, one is brought to the task of developing the "generic difference between the ontic and the historical." Thus we have ascertained the fundamental goal of the "philosophy of life." Still, our line of questioning needs a more fundamental radicalization. How else is historicity to be philosophically grasped and "categorially" conceived in its difference from the ontic than by bringing the "ontic" as well as the "historiographical" into a more primordial unity so that they can be compared and distinguished? But that is possible only if we attain the following insights:
1. The question of historicity is an ontological question about the constitution of being of historical beings. 2. The question of the ontic is the ontological question of the constitution of being of beings unlike Da-sein, of what is objectively present in the broadest sense. 3. The ontic is only one area of beings. The idea of being encompasses the "ontic" and the "historiographical." This idea is what must be "generically differentiated." It is not by chance that Yorck calls nonhistorical beings simply the ontic. That just reflects the unbroken dominance of traditional ontology that, coming from the ancient questioning of being, holds fast to the ontological problematic and fundamentally narrows it down. The problem of the difference between the ontic and the historiographical can be worked out as a problem to be investigated only if it has made sure of its
II.V
Being and Time
369
guideline beforehand by clarifying, through fundamental ontology, the
question of the meaning of being in general. 15 Thus it becomes clear in what sense the preparatory existential and temporal analytic of Da-sein is resolved to cultivate the spirit of Count Yorck in the service of Dilthey's work.
404
VI Temporality and Within- Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time
78. The Incompleteness of the Foregoing Temporal Analysis of Da-sein To demonstrate that and how temporality constitutes the being of Dasein, we showed that historicity, as the constitution of being of existence, is "basically" temporality. Our interpretation of the temporal nature of history was carried out without regard to the "fact" that every occurrence runs its course "in time." In the course of the existential and temporal analysis of historicity, there was no room for the everyday understanding of Da-sein that factically knows all history only as an occurrence "within time." If the existential analytic is to make Da-sein ontologically transparent in its very facticity, the factical, "ontic-temporal" interpretation of history must also explicitly be given its due. It is all the more necessary that the time "in which" beings are encountered be given a fundamental analysis, since not only history, but natural processes, too, are determined "by time." However, more elemental than the circumstance that the "time factor" occurs in the sciences of history and nature, is the fact that, before all thematic investigation, Da-sein "reckons with time" and orients itself according to it. And here again the "reckoning" of Da-sein "with its time" remains decisive, the reckoning that precedes any use of instruments that are geared to determining time. The reckoning is prior to such instruments, and first makes possible something like the use of clocks. Factically existing, actual Da-sein either "has" "time" or it "has none." It either "takes time" or "cannot take time." Why does Da-sein
372
405
Being and Time
II. VI
take "time" and why can it "lose" it? From where does it take time? How is this time related to the temporality of Da-sein? Factical Da-sein takes account of time without existentially understanding temporality. The elemental mode of behavior of reckoning with time must be clarified before we turn to the question of what it means that beings are "in time." All the modes of behavior ofDa-sein are to be interpreted in terms of its being, that is, in terms of temporality. We must show how Da-sein as temporality temporalizes a mode of behavior that is related in such a way to time that it takes account of it. Our characterization of temporality up to now is thus not only generally incomplete, since we did not pay heed to all the dimensions of the phenomenon, but it has fundamental gaps in it because something like world time belongs to temporality itself, in the strict sense of the existential and temporal concept of world. We wish to understand how that is possible and why it is necessary. Thus we can throw light on the vulgarly familiar "time" "in which" beings occur, as well as the within-timeness of these beings. Everyday Da-sein taking time initially finds time in things at hand and objectively present encountered within the world. It understands time thus "experienced" in the horizon of the understanding of being that is nearest to it, that is, as something that is itself somehow objectively present. We must clarify how and why the development of the vulgar concept of time comes about in terms of the temporally grounded constitution of being of Da-sein taking care of time. The vulgar concept of time owes its provenance to a levelling down of primordial time. By demonstrating that this is the source of the vulgar concept of time, we shall justify our earlier interpretation of temporality as primordial time. In the development of the vulgar concept of time, there is a remarkable vacillation as to whether a "subjective" or an "objective" character should be attributed to time. When one conceives it as being in itself, it is attributed primarily to the "soul." And when it has the character of "belonging to consciousness," it still functions "objectively." In Hegel's interpretation of time both possibilities are in a way elevated to a higher unity. Hegel attempts to determine the connection between "time" and "spirit" in order to make it intelligible why spirit, as history, "falls into time." In its results, the foregoing interpretation of the temporality of Da-sein and the way world time belongs to it seems to agree with Hegel. But since our analysis of time is already distinguished from the outset in principle from that of Hegel, and since its orientation is precisely the opposite of his in that it aims at fundamental ontology, a short presentation of Hegel's interpretation of the relation between time and spirit can help to clarify indirectly our existential and ontological interpretation
II. VI
Being and Time
373
of the temporality of Da-sein, world time, and the origin of the vulgar concept of time and may conclude our discussion for now. The question as to whether and how time has any "being," why and in what sense we designate it as "being," cannot be answered until we have shown how temporality itself makes possible something like an understanding of being and addressing of beings in the whole of its temporalizing. Our chapter will be diyided as follows: The temporality of Da-sein and taking care of time (section 79); time taken care of and within-timeness (section 80); within-timeness and the genesis of the vulgar concept of time (section 81); a comparison of the existential and ontological connection of temporality, Da-sein, and world time with Hegel's interpretation of the relation of time and spirit (section 82); the existential and temporal analytic of Da-sein and the question offundamental ontology as to the meaning of being as such (section 83).
79. The Temporality of Da-sein and Taking Care of Time Da-sein exists as a being that, in its being, is concerned about that being itself. Essentially ahead of itself, it has projected itself upon its potentiality-of-being before going on to any mere consideration of itself. In its project it is revealed as something thrown. Thrown and abandoned to the world, it falls prey to it in taking care of it. As care, that is, as existing in the unity of the entangled, thrown project, this being is disclosed as a There. Being-together-with others, it keeps itself in an average interpretedness that is articulated in discourse and expressed in language. Being-in-the-world has always already expressed itself, and as being-togetherwith beings encountered within the world, it constantly expresses itself in addressing and talking over what is taken care of. The circumspect taking care of common sense is grounded in temporality, in the mode of making present that awaits and retains. As taking care in calculating, planning, preparing ahead, and preventing, it always already says, whether audibly or not: " then" ... that will happen, "before" ... that will get settled, "now" ... that will be made up for, that "on that former occasion" failed or eluded us. In the "then," taking care expresses itself in awaiting; retaining in the "on that former occasion" and making present in the "now." In the "then"-but for the most part inexplicitly-lies the "now not yet," that is, it is spoken in a making present that awaitingly retains or forgets. The "on that former occasion" contains the "now no longer." With it, retaining expresses itself as a making present that awaits. The "then" and the "on that former occasion" are understood with regard to a "now," that is, making present has a peculiar weight. Indeed, it always temporalizes itself in a unity with awaiting and retaining, even if these are modified
374
408
Being and Time
II.VI
into a forgetting that does not await. In this mode of forgetting, temporality gets caught in the present that primarily says "now-now" in making present. What taking care awaits as what is nearest to it, is addressed in the "right away"; what has been made initially available or lost is addressed in the ·~ust now." The horizon of retaining that expresses itself in the "on that former occasion" is the "earlier," the horizon for the "then" is the "later on" ("in the future"), the horizon for the "now" is the "today." But every "then" is as such a "then, when ... "; every "on that former occasion" is an "on that former occasion when ..."; every "now" is a "now that ...". We shall call this seemingly self-evident relational structure of the "now," "on that former occasion," and "then" datability. We completely leave aside the question whether this datability is factically carried out with regard to a "date" on the calendar. Even without such "dates," the "now" and "then" and "on that former occasion" are more or less dated in a definite way. If the dating is not made more definite, that does not mean that the structure of datability is lacking or is a matter of chance. What is that to which such datability essentially belongs and what is datability based upon? But can a more superfluous question be raised than this one? With the "now that ...", we mean, after all, a "point in time," "as one knows." The "now" is time. Undeniably we understand the "now ... that," "then ... when," "on that former occasion ... when" in a way as also being connected with "time." That all this means "time" itself, how that is possible, and what "time" signifies-these are matters of which we have no conception in our "natural" understanding of the "now" and so on. Is it then self-evident that we "right away understand" and "naturally" express something like "now," "then," and "on that former occasion"? Where do we get this "now ... that ... ?" Did we find something like this among innerworldly beings, among those that are objectively present? Obviously not. Have we found it at all? Have we ever started to look for it and ascertain it? It is "always" available to us without our ever having explicitly taken it over, and we make constant use of it, although not always in verbal expression. Even in the most trivial, offhand kind of everyday talk (for example, "it is cold") we also have in mind a "now that ... ". Why does Da-sein express a "now that ... ", "then when ... ", "on that former occasion when ... " in addressing what it takes care of, although mostly without verbalizing it? First, because in addressing itself to something interpretively, it expresses itself too; that is, it expresses its circumspect and understanding being-together-with things at hand that lets them be discovered and encountered. And secondly because this addressing and discussing that also interprets itself is grounded in a making present, and is possible only as this. 1
II.VI
Being and Time
375
The making present that awaits and retains interprets itself And that is again possible only because, in itself ecstatically open, it is always already disclosed to itself and can be articulated in the interpretation that understands and speaks. Since temporality is ecstatically and horiz.onally constitutive of the clearedness of the There, it is already always interpreted primordially in the There and is thus familiar. The making present that interprets itself, that is, what has been interpreted and addressed in the "now," is what we call "time." What is made known in this is simply that temporality, recognizable as ecstatically open, is initially and for the most part known only in this interpretedness that takes care. But while time is "immediately" intelligible and recognizable, this does not, however, preclude the possibility that primordial temporality as such, as well as the origin temporalizing itself in it of expressed time, may remain unknown and unconceived. The fact that the structure of datability belongs essentially to what is interpreted with the "now," "then," and "on that former occasion," becomes the most elemental proof that what has been interpreted originates from temporality interpreting itself. Saying "now," we always already also understand a "now that ... "without actually saying it. Why? Because the "now" interprets a making present of beings. In that "now that ... " lies the ecstatic nature of the present. The datability of the "now," "then," and "on that former occasion" is the reflex of the ecstatic constitution of temporality, and is thus essential for time itself that has been expressed. The structure of the datability of the "now," "then," and "on that former occasion" is evidence for the fact that they stem from temporality and are themselves time. The interpretive expression of "now," "then," and "on that former occasion" is the most primordial* way of giving the time. In the ecstatic unity of temporality that is understood along with datability, but unthematically and unrecognizable as such, Da-sein has always already been disclosed to itself as being-in-the-world, and innerworldly beings have been discovered along with it; because of this, interpreted time has always already been given a dating in terms of the beings encountered in the disclosedness of the There; now that ... the door slams; now that ... my book is missing, etc. Because they have the same origin from ecstatic temporality, the horizons that belong to the "now," "then," and "on that former occasion" also have the character of datability as "today when ... ,""later on when ... ," and "earlier when ... ".
*nearest.
409
376
410
Being and Time
II.VI
If awaiting, understanding itself in the "then," interprets itself and in so doing, as a making present, understands what it is awaiting in terms of its "now," the "and now not yet" already lies in the "giving" of the "then." The awaiting that makes present understands the "until then." Interpretation articulates this "until then"-namely, "it has its time"-as the in-between that also has a relation of datability. This relation is expressed in the "meanwhile." Taking care can again articulate in awaiting the "during" itself by giving further "thens." The "until then" is subdivided by a number of "from then ... until thens" that, however, have been "embraced" beforeh3Ild in the awaiting project of the primary "then." The "lasting" is articulated in the understanding of the "during" that awaits and makes present. This duration is again the time revealed in the self-interpretation of temporality, a time that is thus actually, but unthematically, understood in taking care as a "span." The making present that awaits and retains interprets a "during" with a "span," only because in so doing it is disclosed to itself as being ecstatically stretched along in historical temporality, even though it does not know itself as this. But here a further peculiarity of the time "given" shows itself. Not only does the "during" have a span, but every "now," "then," and "on that former occasion" is always spanned with the structure of datability, with a changing span: "now" in the intermission, at dinner, in the evening, in summer; "then" at breakfast, while climbing, and so on. The taking care that awaits, retains, and makes present, "allows itself' time in this or that way and gives this time to itself in taking care, even without determining the time by any specific reckoning, and before any such reckoning has been done. Here time dates itself in one's actual mode of allowing oneself time heedfully in terms of what is actually disclosed in what is taken care of in the surrounding world and in attuned understanding, in terms of what one does "all day long." The more Dasein is absorbed in awaiting what is taken care of and, not awaiting itself, forgets itself, the more its time that it "allows" itself is covered over by this mode of "allowing." In the everyday " living along" that takes care, Da-sein never understands itself as running along in a continuously enduring succession of pure "nows." By reason of this covering over, the time that Da-sein allows itself has gaps in it, so to speak. We often cannot bring a "day" together again when we come back to the time that we have "used." Yet the time that has gaps in it does not go to pieces in this lack of togetherness, but is a mode of temporality that is always already disclosed and ecstatically stretched along. The mode in which the time "allowed" "elapses," and the way in which taking care gives that time to itself more or less explicitly, can be phenomenally explicated appropriately only if, on the one hand, we avoid the theoretical "representation" of a continuous stream of nows, and if, on the
II. VI
Being and Time
377
other hand, the possible modes in which Da-sein gives and allows itself time are to be conceived of as primarily determined in terms of how it "has" its time in a manner corresponding to its actual existence. In an earlier passage, authentic and inauthentic existing were characterized with regard to the modes of the temporalizing of temporality upon which such existing is founded. Accordingly, the irresoluteness of inauthentic existence temporalizes itself in the mode of a making present that does not await but forgets. The irresolute person understands himself in terms of the events and accidents nearest by that are encountered in such making present and urge themselves upon him in changing ways. Busily losing himself in what is taken care of, the irresolute person loses his time in them, too. Hence his characteristic way of talking: "I have no time." Just as the person who exists inauthentically constantly loses time and never "has" any, it is the distinction of the temporality of authentic existence that in resoluteness it never loses time and "always has time." For the temporality of resoluteness has, in regard to its present, the nature of the Moment. The Moment's authentic making present of the situation does not itself have the leadership, but is held in the future that has-been. The existence of the Moment temporalizes itself as fatefully whole, stretching along in the sense of the authentic, historical constancy of the self. This kind of temporal existence "constantly" has its time for what the situation requires of it. But resoluteness discloses the There in such a way only as situation. Thus the resolute person can never encounter what is disclosed in such a way that he could lose his time on it in an irresolute way. Factically thrown Da-sein can "take" and lose time for itself only because a "time" is allotted to it as temporality ecstatically stretched along with the disclosedness of the There grounded in that temporality. As disclosed, Da-sein exists factically in the mode of being-with with the others. It keeps itself in a public, average intelligibility. The "now that ...", "then when ..." interpreted and expressed in everyday beingwith-one-another, are understood in principle, although they are unequivocally dated only within limits. In the "nearest" being-with-oneanother, several people can say "now" together, and each can date the "now" in a different way: now that this or that happens. The "now" expressed is spoken by each one in the publicness of being-with-oneanother-in-the-world. The time interpreted and expressed by actual Dasein is thus also always already made public as such on the basis of its ecstatic being-in-the-world. Since everyday taking care understands itself in terms of the "world" taken care of, it knows the "time" that it takes for itself not as its own, but rather heedfully exploits the time that "there is," the time with which the they reckons. But the publicness of "time" is all the more compelling, the more factical Da-sein explicitly takes care of time by expressly taking it into account.
411
378
Being and Time
II.VI
80. Time Taken Care of and Within-Timeness
412
Thus far we have only had to understand how Da-sein, grounded in temporality, takes care of time in existing, and how time makes itself public for being-in-the-world in the taking care that interprets. We did not determine at all in what sense the public time expressed "is," or whether it can be addressed as being at all. Before any decision as to whether public time "is merely subjective" or whether it is "objectively real," or neither of the two, the phenomenal character of public time must first be determined more precisely. Making time public does not occur occasionally and subsequently. Rather, since Da-sein is always already disclosed as ecstatic and temporal and because understanding and interpretation belong to existence, time has also already made itself public in taking care. One orients oneself toward it, so that it must somehow be available for everyone. Although taking care of time can be carried out in the mode of dating that we characterized-namely, in terms of events in the surrounding world-this always occurs basically in the horizon of a taking care of time that we know as astronomical and calendrical time-reckoning. This reckoning is not a matter of chance, but has its existential and ontological necessity in the fundamental constitution of Da-sein as care. Since Da-sein essentially exists entangled as thrown, it interprets its time heedfully by way of a reckoning with time. In this reckoning, the "real" making public of time temporalizes itself so that we must say that the thrownness of Da-sein is the reason why "there is" public time. If we are to demonstrate that public time has its origin in factical temporality and if we are to assure ourselves that this demonstration is as intelligible as possible, we must characterize beforehand the time interpreted in general in the temporality of taking care, if only to make clear that the essence of taking care of time does not lie in the application of numerical procedures in dating. What is existentially and ontologically decisive about reckoning with time must not be seen in the quantification of time, but must be more primordially conceived in terms of the temporality of Da-sein reckoning with time. "Public time" turns out to be the time "in which" innerworldly things at hand and objectively present are encountered. This requires that we call these beings unlike Da-sein beings within-time. The interpretation ofwithin-timeness gives us a more primordial insight into the essence of "public time" and at the same time makes it possible to define its "being." The being of Da-sein is care. This being exists entangled as thrown. Delivered over to the "world" discovered with its factical There and dependent upon it in taking care, Da-sein awaits its potentiality-of-being-
II.VI
Being and Time
379
in-the-world in such a way that it reckons with and on whatever is in eminent relevance for the sake of its potentiality-of-being. Everyday, cir· cumspect being-in-the-world needs the possibility of sight, that is, brightness, if it is to take care of things at hand within what is objectively present. With the factical disclosedness of world, nature has been discovered for Da-sein. In its thrownness Da-sein is subject to the changes of day and night. Day with its brightness gives it the possibility of sight, night takes it away. Awaiting the possibility of sight while circumspectly taking care, Da-sein, understanding itself in terms of its daily work, gives itself its time with the "then when it dawns." The "then" taken care of is dated in terms of what is in the nearest context of relevance of the surrounding world, with getting light, the sunrise. Then, when the sun rises, it is time for .... Thus Da-sein dates the time that it must take for itself in terms of what is encountered within the world and in the horizon of being delivered over to the world as something for which there is an eminent relevance for the circumspect potentiality-of-being-in-the-world. Taking care makes use of the "handiness" of the sun giving forth light and warmth. The sun dates the time interpreted in taking care. From this dating arises the "most natural" measure of time, the day. And since the temporality of Da-sein that must take its time is finite, its days are also already numbered. "While it is day" gives to awaiting that takes care the possibility of determining in a precautionary way the "thens" of what is to be taken care of, that is, of dividing up the day. The dividing up in its tum is carried out with regard to what dates time, the moving sun. like sunrise, sunset and noon are distinctive "places" that this heavenly body occupies. Da-sein, thrown into the world, temporalizing, and giving itself time, takes account of its regular recurring passage. The occurrence of Da-sein is a daily one by reason of interpreting time by dating it-a way that is prefigured in its thrownness into the There. This dating of things in terms of the heavenly body giving forth light and warmth, and in terms of its distinctive "places" in the sky, is a way of giving time which can be done in our being-with-one-another "under the same sky," and which can be done for "everyone" at any time in the same way so that within certain limits everyone is initially agreed upon it. That which dates is available in the surrounding world and yet not restricted to the actual world of useful things taken care of. Rather, in that world, nature in the surrounding world and the public surrounding world are always discovered along with it. 2 At the same time everyone can "count on" this public dating in which everyone gives himself his time. It makes use of a measure that is available to the public. This dating reckons with time in the sense of time measurement that needs something to measure time, that is, a clock. This means that with the tem-
413
380
414
Being and Time
II. VI
porality of Da-sein as thrown, delivered over to the world, and giving itself time, something like a "clock" is also discovered, that is, a handy thing that has become accessible in its regular recurrence in a making present that awaits. Thrown being-together-with things at hand is grounded in temporality. Temporality is the reason for the clock. As the condition of the possibility of the factical necessity of the clock, temporality is at the same time the condition for its discoverability. For while the course of the sun is encountered along with the discoveredness of innerworldly beings, it is only by making it present in awaitingly retaining, and by doing so in a way that interprets itself, that dating in terms of things at hand in the public surrounding world is made possible and is also required. The "natural" clock, which is always already discovered with the factical thrownness of Da-sein grounded in temporality, first motivates and at the same time makes possible the production and use of still more handy clocks. It does this in such a way that these "artificial" clocks must be "adjusted" to the "natural" one if they are to make the time primarily discovered in the natural clock accessible in its tum. Before we characterize the main traits in the development of reckoning with time and the use of clocks in their existential and ontological meaning, we first want to characterize more completely the time taken care of in the measurement of time. If the time we take care of is "really" made public only when it gets measured, then public time is to be accessible in a way that has been phenomenally unveiled. We must have access to it by following up the way that which has been dated shows itself when dated in this "reckoning" way. When the "then" that interprets itself in heedful awaiting gets dated, this dating includes some such statement as: then-when it dawns-it is time for the day's work. The time interpreted in taking care is always already understood as time for .... The actual "now that so and so" is as such either appropriate or inappropriate. The "now"-and thus every mode of interpreted time-is not only a "now that . . ." that is essentially datable, but is at the same time essentially determined by the structure of appropriateness or inappropriateness. Interpreted time has by its very nature the character of "time for ... " or "not the time for . . .". The making present that awaits and retains of taking care understands time in its relation to a what-for, that is in tum ultimately anchored in a for-the-sake-of-which of the potentiality-of-being of Dasein. With this relation of in-order-to, time made public reveals the structure that we got to know earlier' as signifuance. It constitutes the worldliness of the world. As time-for ... , the time that has been made public essentially has the nature of world. Thus we shall call the time making itself public in the temporalizing of temporality world time. And we shall designate it thus not because it is objectively present as an innerworldly
II. VI
Being and Time
381
being (that it can never be), but because it belongs to the world in the sense interpreted existentially and ontologically. How the essential relations of the world structure (for example, the "in-order-to") are connected with public time (for example, the "then-when") on the basis of the ecstatic and horizonal constitution of temporality will be shown in what follows. At any rate, only now can time taken care of be completely characterized as to its structure: It is datable, spanned, and public and, as having this structure, it belongs to the world itself. Every "now," for example, that is expressed in a natural, everyday way, has this structure and is understood as such when Da-sein allows itself time in taking care, although unthematically and preconceptually. The disclosedness of the natural clock belongs to Da-sein that exists as thrown and entangled, and in this disclosedness factical Da-sein has at the same time already brought about an eminent making public of the time taken care of. This making public is enhanced and strengthened as time reckoning is perfected and the use of the clock becomes more refmed. The historical development of time reckoning and the use of the clock is not to be presented here historiographically with all its possible variations. Rather, we want to ask existentially and ontologically what mode of temporalizing of the temporality of Da-sein is made manifest in developing the direction of reckoning with time and the use of the clock. The answer to this question must further a more primordial understanding of the fact that time measurement-that is, at the same time the explicit making public of time taken care of-is grounded in the temporality of Dasein and indeed in a quite definite temporalizing of that temporality. If we compare "primitive" Da-sein, which we used as the basis for the analysis of "natural" time-reckoning, with more "advanced" Da-sein, we find that for more advanced Da-sein day and the presence of sunlight no longer possess an eminent function, because this Da-sein has the "advantage" of even being able to turn the night into day. Similarly, we no longer need to glance explicitly and directly at the sun and its position to ascertain the time. The manufacture and use of one's own measuring instruments permits us to read off the time directly by clocks explicitly produced for this purpose. The what o'clock is it?, is the "what time is it?" Because the clock-in the sense of what makes possible a public reckoning of time-must be regulated by the "natural" clock, even the use of clocks is grounded in the temporality of Da-sein that, with the disclosedness of the There, first makes possible a dating of the time taken care of. This is a fact, even if it is covered over when the time is read off. Our understanding of the natural clock that develops with the progressive discovery of nature directs us to new possibilities for time measurement that are relatively independent of the day and of any explicit observation of the sky.
415
382
416
417
Being and Time
II.VI
But in a way even "primitive" Da-sein makes itself independent of reading off the time directly from the sky, since it does not ascertain the position of the sun in the sky, but measures the shadow cast by some being available at any time. That can happen at first in the most simple form of the ancient "peasant's clock." In the shadow that constantly accompanies everyone, we encounter the sun with respect to its changing presence at different places. The various lengths of the shadow during the day can be paced off "at any time." Even if the lengths of the individual' s body and feet are different, still the relation of the two remain constant within certain limits. Thus, for example, when one takes care of making an appointment, one designates the time publicly by saying: "When the shadow is so many feet long, we will meet each other there." Here in being-with-one-another in the more narrow limits of a surrounding world nearest to us, we tacitly presuppose that the "locations" at which the shadow is paced off are at the same latitude. Dasein does not even need to wear this clock, it is it in a way itself. The public sundial, in which the line of a shadow is counterposed to the course of the sun and moves along a graduated dial needs no further description. But why do we fmd something like time at the position that the shadow occupies on the dial? Neither the shadow nor the graduated dial is time itself, nor is the spatial relation between them. Where, then, is the time that we read off directly not only on the "sundial" but also on every pocketwatch? What does reading off the time signify? "To look at the clock" cannot simply mean to contemplate the tool at hand in its changes and to follow the positions of the pointer. Ascertaining what time it is in using the clock, we say, whether explicitly or not, now it is such an hour and so many minutes, now it is time to ... , or there is still time ... , namely now until .... Looking at the clock is grounded in and guided by a taking-time-for-oneself. What already showed itself in the most elemental reckoning of time becomes more clear here: Looking at the clock and orienting oneself toward time is essentially a now-saying. Here the now is always already understood and interpreted in its complete structural content of datability, spannedness, publicness, and worldliness. This is so "obvious" that we do not take any notice of it at all; still less do we know anything about it explicitly. But now-saying is the discoursing articulation of a making present that temporalizes itself in unity with an awaiting that retains. The dating carried out in the use of the clock tums out to be the eminent making present of something objectively present. Dating does not simply take up a relation with something objectively present, but taking up a relation itself has the character of measuring. Of course, the number of the measurement can be read off directly. However, this means that when a
II. VI
Being and Time
383
length is to be measured, we understand that our standard is contained in it, that is, we determine the frequency of its presence in that length. Measuring is constituted temporally when a present standard is made present in a present length. The idea of a standard implies unchangingness; this means that it must be objectively present in its constancy at every time for everyone. When the time taken care of is dated by measuring, one interprets that time by looking at something objectively present and making it present-something that would not become accessible as a standard or as something measured except by our eminent making present. Since the making present of what is present has special priority in the dating that measures, when one measures and reads off the time by the clock, one also expresses the now with special emphasis. Thus in measuring time, time gets made public in such a way that it is encountered in each case and at each time for everyone as "now and now and now." This time "universally" accessible in clocks is found as an objectively present multiplicity of nows, so to speak, though time measurement is not directed thematically toward time as such. The temporality of factical being-in-the-world is what primordially makes the disclosure of space possible; and spatial Da-sein has always been referred to a here of the character of Da-sein out of an over there that has been discovered. Because of all this, the time taken care of in the temporality of Da-sein is always bound up with some location of Da-sein with regard to its datability. It is not that time is connected to a location, but rather temporality is the condition of the possibility that dating may be bound up with the spatially-local in such a way that the latter is binding for everyone as a measure. Time is not first coupled with space, but the "space" that is supposedly to be coupled with it is encountered only on the basis of temporality taking care of time. Inasmuch as both the clock and time-reckoning are grounded in the temporality of Dasein, which constitutes this being as historical, we can show ontologically how the use of the clock is itself historical and how every clock as such "has a history. "4 The time made public in our measurement of it by no means turns into space because we date it in terms of spatial relations of measurement. Nor is what is existentially and ontologically essential in time mea· surement to be sought in the fact that dated "time" is determined numerically in terms of spatial distances and changes in the location of some spatial thing. Rather, what is ontologically decisive lies in the specific making present that makes measurement possible. Dating in terms of what is objectively present "spatially" is so far from a spatialization of time that this supposed spatialization signifies nothing other than that a being that is objectively present for everyone in every now is made pre-
384
419
Being and Time
II. VI
sent in its own presence. Measuring time is essentially such that it is necessary to say now, but in obtaining the measurement we, as it were, forget what has been measured as such so that nothing is to be found except distance and number. The less time Da-sein has to lose while taking care of time, the more "precious" time becomes and the more handy the dock must be. Not only must time be able to be given "more precisely," but the determination of time itself should require the least time possible, though it must still be in conformity with the time given by the others. Preliminarily, we only wanted to point out the general "connection" of the use of the dock with temporality that takes time for itself. Just as the concrete analysis of the astronomical time-reckoning in its full development belongs to the existential and ontological interpretation of the discovery of nature, the foundations of calendrical and historiographical "chronology" can also be set forth only in the scope of tasks of an existential analysis of historiographical cognition.5 The measurement of time brings about a making public of time, so that only in this way does what we usually call "time" become familiar. In taking care, "its time" is attributed to every thing. It "has" it, and like every innerworldly being, it can "have" it only because it is "in time" in general. The time "in which" innerworldly beings are encountered we know as world time. On the basis of the ecstatic and horizonal constitution of temporality to which it belongs, world time has the same transcendence as the world. With the disdosedness of world, world time is made public, so that every being-together-with innerworldly beings that temporally takes care understands those beings as circumspectly encountered "in time." The time "in which" objectively present things move or are at rest is not "objective," if by this is meant the objective presence in itself of beings encountered in the world. But time is not "subjective" either, if we understand by that the objective presence and occurrence in a "subject." World time is more "objective" than any possible object because, with the disclosedness of the world, it always already becomes ecstatically and horizonally "objectified" as the condition of the possibility ofinnerworldly beings. Thus, contrary to Kant's opinion, world time is found just as directly in what is physical as in what is psychical, and not just by way of a detour over the psychical. Initially "time" shows itself in the sky, that is, precisely where one finds it in the natural orientation toward it, so that "time" is even identified with the sky. But world time is also "more subjective" than any possible subject since it first makes possible the being of the factical existing self, that being which, as is now well understood, is the meaning of care. "Time" is neither objectively present in the "subject" nor in the "object," neither "inside" nor "outside,"
II. VI
Being and Time
385
and it "is" "prior" to every subjectivity and objectivity, because it presents the condition of the very possibility of this "prior." Does it then have any "being" at all? And if not, is it then a phantom or is it "more in being" than any possible being? Any investigation that goes further in the direction of these questions will bump into the same "limit" that already posed itself for our provisional discussion of the connection between truth and being.6 However these questions are to be answered in what follows, or are to be asked primordially, we must first understand that temporality, as ecstatic and horizonal, first temporalizes something like world time that constitutes a within-timeness of things at hand and objectively present. But then these beings can never be called "temporal" in the strict sense. Like every being unlike Da-sein, they are atemporal, whether they occur, arise, and pass away realistically, or subsist "ideally." If world time thus belongs to the temporalizing of temporality, it can neither be volatized "subjectivistically" nor be "reified" in a bad "objectification." These two possibilities can be avoided with clear insight-not just by vacillating insecurely between them-only if we understand how everyday Da-sein theoretically conceives "time" in terms of its nearest understanding of time, and only if we understand how this concept of time and its dominance blocks the possibility of understanding what it means in terms of primordial time, that is, as temporality. Everyday taking care that gives itself time finds "time" in innerworldly beings that are encountered "in time." Thus our illumination of the genesis of the vulgar concept of time must take its point of departure from within-timeness.
420
81. Within-Timeness and the Genesis of the Vulgar Concept of Time How does something like "time" initially show itself for everyday, circumspect taking care? In what mode of taking care and using tools does it become explicitly accessible? If time has been made public with the disclosedness of world, if it has always already been taken care of with the discoveredness of innerworldly beings belonging to the disclosedness of world since Da-sein calculates time reckoning with itself, then the mode of behavior in which "one" orients oneself explicitly toward time lies in the use of the clock. The existential and temporal meaning of the clock turns out to be making present of the moving pointer. By following the positions of the pointer in a way that makes present, one counts them. This making present temporalizes itself in the ecstatic unity of a retaining that awaits. To retain the "on that former occasion" in making present means that in saying-now to be open for the horizon of the earlier, that is, the now-no-longer. To await the "then" in making present means that in saying-now to be open for the horizon of the later, that is, the now-not-
421
386
422
Being and Time
II. VI
yet. What shows itself in this. making present is time. Then how are we to defme the time manifest in the horizon of the use of the clock that is circumspect and takes time for itself in taking care? This time is what is counted, showing itself in following. making present, and counting the moving pointer in such a way that making present temporalizes itself in ecstatic unity with retaining and awaiting horizonally open according to the earlier and later. But that is nothing more than an existential and ontological interpretation of the definition that Aristotle gave of time: touto gar estin ho chronos, arithmos kineseos kata to proteron kai hysteron. "That, namely, is time, what is counted in the motion encountered in the horizon of the earlier and the later."' As strange as this definition may appear at first glance, it is "self-evident" and genuinely drawn if the existential and ontological horizon is defined from which Aristotle took it. The origin of time thus revealed is not a problem for Aristotle. His interpretation of time rather moves in the direction of the "natural" understanding of being. However, since that understanding and the being understood in it have been made a problem in principle in our present inquiry, the Aristotelian analysis of time can be thematically interpreted only after the solution to the question of being, and indeed in such a way that that analysis gains a fundamental significance for a positive appropriation of the critically limited line of questioning of ancient ontology in general.8 All subsequent discussion of the concept of time in principle keeps to the Aristotelian definition, that is, it makes time thematic in the way that it shows itself in circumspect taking care. Time is "what is counted," that is, it is what is expressed and what is meant, although unthematically, in the making present of the moving pointer (or shadow). In making present what is moved in its motion, one says "now here, now here, and so on." What is counted are the nows. And they show themselves "in every now" as "right-away-no-longer-now" and 'just-now-not-yet." The world time "caught sight of' in this way in the use of the clock we shall call now-time. The more "naturally" the taking care of time that gives itself time reckons with time, the less it dwells together with the expressed time as such. Rather, it is lost in the useful things taken care of that always have their time. When taking care determines time and gives it, the more "naturally" it does so-that is, the less it is directed toward treating time as such thematically-all the more does the being-together-with what is taken care of (the being-together making present and falling prey) say unhesitatingly (whether with or without utterance): now, then, on that former occasion. And thus time shows itself for the vulgar understanding as a succession of constantly "objectively present" nows that pass away and arrive at the same time. Time is understood as a sequence, as the "flux" of nows, as the "course of time." What is implied by this interpretation of world time taken care oft
II. VI
Being and Time
387
We can answer this if we go back to the complete essential structure of world time and compare this with that with which the vulgar understanding of time is familiar. We set forth datability as the first essential factor of time taken care of. It is grounded in the ecstatic constitution of temporality. The "now" is essentially a now-that .... The datable now that is understood in taking care, although not grasped as such, is always appropriate or inappropriate. Signifzcance belongs to the now-structure. Thus we called time taken care of world time. In the vulgar interpretation of time as a succession of nows, both datability and significance are lacking. The characterization of time as pure sequence does not let these two structures "appear." The vulgar interpretation of time covers them over. The ecstatic and horizonal constitution of temporality, in which the datability and significance of the now are grounded, is levelled down by this covering over. The nows are cut off from these relations, so to speak, and, as thus cut off, they simply range themselves along after one another so as to constitute the succession. This covering over and levelling down of world time that is carried out by the vulgar understanding of time is no accident. Rather, precisely because the everyday interpretation of time keeps itself solely in the perspective of commonsense taking care, and understands only what "shows" itself in the commonsense horizon, these structures have to escape it. What is counted in the measurement of time taken care of, the now, is also understood in taking care of things at hand and objectively present. Since this taking care of time comes back to the time itself that has also been understood and "contemplates" it, it sees the nows (that are also somehow "there") in the horizon of the understanding of being by which this taking care is itself constantly guided. 9 The nows are thus also in a way objectively present, that is, beings are encountered and also the now. Although it is not explicitly stated that the nows are objectively present like things, still they are "seen" ontologically in the horizon of the idea of objective presence. The nows pass away, and the past ones constitute the past. The nows arrive, and the future ones define the "future." The vulgar interpretation of world time as now-time does not have the horizon available at all by which such things as world, significance, and datability can be made more accessible. These structures remain necessarily covered over, all the more so since the vulgar interpretation of time enforces this covering over by the way in which it conceptually develops its characterization of time. The succession of nows is interpreted as something somehow objectively present; for it itself moves "in time." We say that in every now it is now, in every now it already disappears. The now is now in every now, thus constantly present as the same, even if in every now another may be disappearing as it arrives. Yet it does show at the same time the
423
388
Being and Time
II. VI
constant presence of itself as this changing thing. Thus even Plato, who had this perspective of time as a succession of nows that come into being and pass away, had to call time the image of eternity: eiko d' epenoei kineton tina aionos poiesai, kai diakosmon kama ouranon poiei menontos aianos en heni kat' arithmon iousan aionion eikona, touton hon de kronon onomakamen. 10
424
The succession of nows is uninterrupted and has no gaps. No matter how "far" we penetrate in "dividing" the now, it is still always now. One regards the continuity of time in the horizon of something indissolubly objectively present. Ontologically oriented toward something constantly objectively present, one either looks for the problem of the continuity of time, or one leaves the aporia alone. Here the specific structure of world time must remain covered over, since it is spanned together with ecstatically founded datability. The spannedness of time is not understood in terms of the horizontal being stretched along of the ecstatic unity of temporality that has made itself public in taking care of time. The fact that it is always already now in every now, no matter how momentary, must be conceived in terms of what is still "earlier" and from which every now arises: in terms of the ecstatically being stretched along of the temporality that is foreign to any continuity of something objectively present, but that in tum presents the condition of the possibility of the access to something continuous and objectively present. The main thesis of the vulgar interpretation of time-that time is "infinite"-reveals most penetratingly the levelling down and covering over of world time and thus of temporality in general in this interpretation. Initially, time gives itself as an uninterrupted succession of nows. Every now is already either a just now or a right-away. If the characterization of time keeps primarily and exclusively to this succession, no beginning and no end can be found in principle in it as such. Every last now, as a now, is always already a right-away that is no longer, thus it is time in the sense of the no-longer-now, of the past. Every first now is always a justnow-not-yet, thus it is time in the sense of the not-yet-now, the "future." Time is thus endless "in both directions." This thesis about time is possible only on the basis of an orientation toward an unattached in-itself of a course of nows objectively present, whereby the complete phenomenon of the now is covered over with regard to the datability, worldliness, spannedness, and publicness of Da-sein, so that it has dwindled to an unrecognizable fragment. If "one thinks" the succession of nows "to the end" with the perspective of objective presence or the lack of it, an end can never be found. In this way of thinking time through to the end, one must always think more time; from this one concludes that time is endless. But in what is this levelling down of world time and covering over of temporality grounded? In the being of Da-sein itself that we inter-
II. VI
Being and Time
389
preted as care in a preparatory way. 11 Thrown and entangled, Da-sein is initially and for the most part lost in what it takes care of. But in this lostness, the flight of Da-sein from its authentic existence that we characterized as anticipatory resoluteness makes itself known, and this is a flight that covers over. In such heedful fleeing lies the flight from death, that is, a looking away from the end of being-in-the-world! 2 This looking away from ... is in itself a mode of the ecstatic,JUtural being toward the end. Looking away from finitude, the inauthentic temporality of entangled everyday Da-sein must fail to recognize authentic futurality and thus temporality in general. And if the vulgar understanding of Da-sein is guided by the they, then the self-forgetful "representation" of the "infinitude" of public time can first anchor itself. The they never dies because it is unable to die, since death is always my own and is understood authentically only in anticipatory resoluteness in an existentiell way. The they, which never dies and misunderstands being-toward-theend, nonetheless interprets the flight from death in a characteristic way. Up to the end "it always has more time." Here a way of having time makes itself known in the sense of being able to lose it: "right now this, then that ... ". Here it is not as if the finitude of time were understood, but quite the opposite. Taking care is out to snatch as much as possible from time that is still coming and "goes on." Publically, time is something that everyone can and does take. The levelled-down succession of nows remains completely unrecognizable with regard to its provenance from the temporality of individual Da-sein in everyday being-withone-another. How should that affect "time" in its course even in the least if a human being objectively present "in time" no longer exists? Time goes on as it already "was," after all, when a human being "entered life." One knows only public time that, levelled down, belongs to everyone, and that means to no one. However, just as one who flees death is pursued by it even as one evades it, and just as in turning away from it one has to see it nonetheless, the harmless endless succession of nows that just runs on imposes itself "on" Da-sein in a remarkably enigmatic way. Why do we say that time passes away when we do not emphasize just as much how it comes into being? With regard to the pure succession of nows, both could, after all, be said with equal justification. In talking about time's passing away, Da-sein ultimately understands more about time than it would like to admit, that is, the temporality in which world time temporalizes itself is not completely closed off despite all covering over. Talking about time's passing away gives expression to the "experience" that time cannot be halted. This "experience" is again possible only on the basis of wanting to halt time. Herein lies an inauthentic awaiting of "moments" that already forgets the moments as they slip by. The awaiting of inau-
425
390
426
Being and Time
II. VI
thentic existence that makes present and forgets is the condition of the possibility of the vulgar experience of time's passing away. Since Dasein is futural in being ahead-of-itself, it must, in awaiting, understand the succession of nows as one that slips away and passes away. Da-sein knows fleeting time from the "fleeting" knowledge of i/.5 death. In the kind of talk that emphasizes time's passing away, the finite futurality of the temporality of Da-sein is publicly reflected. And since even in the talk about time's passing away death can remain covered over, time shows itself as a passing away "in itself." But even in this pure succession of nows passing away in itself, primordial time reveals itself in spite of all levelling down and covering over. The vulgar interpretation determines the flux of time as an irreversible succession. Why can time not be reversed? Especially when one looks exclusively at the flux of nows, it is incomprehensible in itself why the sequence of nows should not accommodate itself to the reverse direction. The impossibility of this reversal has its basis in the provenance of public time in temporality, whose temporalizing, primarily futural, "goes" ecstatically toward its end in such a way that it "is" already toward its end. The vulgar characterization of time as an endless, irreversible succession of nows passing away arises from the temporality of entangled Da-sein. The vulgar representation of time has i/.5 natural justification. It belongs to the everyday kind of being of Da-sein and to the understanding of being initially prevalent. Thus even history is initially and for the most part understood publicly as an occurrence within time. This interpretation of time loses its exclusive and distinctive justification only if it claims to convey the "true" concept of time and to be able to sketch out the sole possible horizon for the interpretation of time. Rather, we found that only from the temporality of Da-sein and its temporalizing does it become intelligible why and how world time belongs to it. This interpretation of the complete structure of world time is drawn from temporality and gives us guidelines for "seeing" the covering over contained in the vulgar concept of time and for estimating how far the ecstatic and horizonal constitution of temporality has been levelled down. This orientation toward the temporality of Da-sein, however, at the same time makes it possible to demonstrate the provenance and the factical necessity of this covering over that levels down, and to examine the arguments for the vulgar theses on time. On the other hand, temporality remains inaccessible in the horizon of the vulgar understanding of time. Not only must now-time be oriented primarily toward temporality in the order of possible interpretation, but it temporalizes itself only in the inauthentic temporality of Da-sein; so if we pay attention to the derivation of now-time from tern-
II.VI
Being and Time
391
porality we are justified in addressing temporality as primordial time. Ecstatic and horizonal temporality temporalizes itself primarily from the future. However, the vulgar understanding of time sees the fundamental phenomenon of time in the now, and indeed in the pure now, cut off in its complete structure, that is called the "present." One can gather from this that there is in principle no prospect of explaining or even deriving the ecstatic and horizonal phenomenon of the Moment that belongs to authentic temporality from this now. Thus the ecstatically understood future-the datable, significant "then"-does not coincide with the vulgar concept of the "future" in the sense of the pure nows that have not yet arrived and are only arriving. Nor does the ecstatic having-been, the datable, significant "on that former occasion," coincide with the concept of the past in the sense of the past pure nows. The now is not pregnant with the not-yet-now, but rather the present arises from the future in the primordial, ecstatic unity of the temporalizing of temporality.13 Although, initially and for the most part, the vulgar experience of time knows only "world time," it nonetheless also always accords world time an eminent relation to "soul" and "spirit." And it does this even when an explicit and primary orientation toward philosophical questioning of the "subject" is absent. Two characteristic passages will suffice as evidence for this. Aristotle says: ei de meden allo pephuken arithmein e psyche kai psyches nous, adunaton einai chronon psyches me ouses. 14 And Augustine writes: inde mihi visum est, nihil esse aliud tempus quam distentionem; sed cuius rei nescio; et mirum si non ipsius animi. 15 Thus in principle the interpretation of Da-sein as temporality does not lie beyond the horizon of the vulgar concept of time. And Hegel made an explicit attempt to point out the way in which time, understood in the vulgar sense, is connected with spirit. For Kant, on the other hand, time is indeed "subjective," but stands unconnected "next to" the "I think." 16 The grounds that Hegel explicitly gave for the connection between time and spirit are well suited for clarifying indirectly the foregoing interpretation of Da-sein as temporality and our exhibition of the origin of world time from it.
82. The Contrast of the Existential and Ontological Connection of Temporality, Da-sein, and World Time with Hegel's Interpretation of the Relation between Time and Spirit History, which is essentially the history of spirit, runs its course "in time." Thus "the development of history falls into time." 17 But Hegel is not satisfied with establishing the within-timeness of spirit as a fact, but attempts to understand how it is possible for spirit to fall into time, which
427
428
392
Being and Time
II. VI
is the "completely abstract, the sensuous." 18 Time must be able to receive spirit, as it were. And spirit must in turn be related to time and its essence. Thus we must discuss two things: (1) How does Hegel define the essence of time? (2) What belongs to the essence of spirit that makes it possible for it to "fall into time"? Our answer to these two questions will serve merely to el'l.lCitklte our interpretation of Da-sein as temporality and to do so by way of a comparison. We shall make no claim to give even a relatively complete treatment of the allied problems in Hegel, especially since we have no intention of "criticizing" Hegel. Because Hegel's concept of time presents the most radical way in which the vulgar understanding of time has been given form conceptually, and one that has received too little attention, a comparison of this concept with the idea of temporality that we have expounded is one that especially suggests itself.
429
(a) Hegel's Concept of Time. The "systematic place" in which a phil~ sophical interpretation of time is carried out can serve as a criterion for understanding the basic guideline which leads the fundamental interpretation of time. The first traditional, thematically detailed interpretation of the vulgar understanding of time is to be found in Aristotle's Physics, in the context of an ontology of nature. "Time" is connected with "location" and "motion." True to the tradition, Hegel's analysis of time has its place in the second part of his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences bearing the title: "The Philosophy of Nature." The first division treats mechanics. Its first section is dedicated to a discussion of "space and time." They are the "abstract outside-of-one-another." 19 Although Hegel puts space and time together, this does not amount simply to juxtaposing them externally: space "and also time." "Philosophy battles with this 'also'." The transition from space to time does not mean that they are treated in adjoining paragraphs, but "space itself goes over." Space "is" time, that is, time is the "truth" of space.20 If space is thought dialectically in what it is, this being of space reveals itself as time according to Hegel. How must space be thought? Space is the unmediated indifference of nature's outside-itself.21 That means that space is the abstract multiplicity of the points distinguishable in it. Space is not interrupted by these points, but neither does it first arise from them by way of joining them together. Space remains in its tum undifferentiated, differentiated by the differentiable points that are themselves space. The differentiations themselves have the nature of what they differentiate. But yet the point is a negation of space in that it differentiates something in space, though in such a way that it itself remains in space as this negation (the point is, after all, space). The point does not lift itself out of space as something other than space. Space is the undifferentiated outside-one-another of the multi-
II. VI
Being and Time
393
plicity of points. But space is not a point, but, as Hegel says, "punctuality."22 On this Hegel bases his statement in which he thinks space in its truth, that is, as time. "Negativity, which is related to space as a point and which develops its determinations in it as line and surface, is, however, for itself and its determinations in the sphere of being-outside-itself, though while it is positing as in the sphere of being-outside-itself, it appears indifferent to what is side by side at rest. Thus posited for itself, it is time. "u If space is represented, that is, directly looked at in the indifferent subsistence of its distinctions, the negations are, so to speak, simply given. But this representing does not yet grasp space in its being. That is possible only in thought-as the synthesis that goes through thesis and antithesis and supersedes them. Space is thought and thus grasped in its being only if the negations do not simply subsist in their indifference, but are superseded, that is, themselves negated. In the negation of negation (that is, punctuality) the point posits itself for itself and thus emerges from the indifference of subsistence. Posited for itself, it distinguishes itself from this or that point; it is no longer this one and not yet that one. In positing itself for itself, it posits the succession in which it stands, the sphere of being-outside-of-itself that is now the negated negation. The superseding of punctuality as indifference signifies that it can no longer lie quietly in the "paralyzed stillness of space." The point "rebels" against all the other points. According to Hegel, this negation of negation as punctuality is time. If this discussion has any demonstrable meaning at all, it can mean nothing other than that the positing of itself for itself of each point is a now-here, now-here, and so on. Every point "is" posited for itself as a now-point. "Thus the point has actuality in time." By what means the point can posit itself for itself, always as this point, is always a now. The condition of the possibility of the point's positing itself for itself is the now. This condition of possibility constitutes the being of the point, and being is at the same time being-thought. Thus, since the pure thinking of punctuality, that is, of space, always "thinks" the now and the being-outside-itself of the nows, space "is" time. How is time itself defined? "As the negative unity of being-outside-itself, time is similarly something absolutely abstract and ideal. It is the being that, in being, is not, and, in not being, is: it is intuited becoming. This means that the absolutely momentary distinctions that directly supersede themselves are determined as external, but external to themselves. "24 Time reveals itself for this interpretation as "intuited becoming." According to Hegel, this signifies a transition from being to nothingness,or from nothingness to being. 25 Becoming is coming into being as well as passing away. Being, or nonbeing, "goes over." What does that mean with regard to time? The being of
430
431
394
432
433
Being and Time
II.VI
time is the now. But since every now either "now" is-no-longer, or now isnot-yet, it can also be grasped as nonbeing. Time is "intuited" becoming, that is, the transition that is not thought, but simply presents itself in the succession of nows. If the essence of time is determined as "intuited becoming," this reveals the fact that time is understood primarily in terms of the now, in the way that such a now can be found by pure intuition. We do not need any complicated discussion to make it clear that in Hegel's interpretation of time, he is wholly moving in the direction of the vulgar understanding of time. Hegel's characterization of time in terms of the now presupposes that the now remains covered over and levelled down in its full structure, so that it can be intuited as something objectively present, though objectively present only "ideally." The fact that Hegel interprets time in terms of this primary orientation toward the now that has been levelled down is proved by the following statements: "The now is enormously privileged-it 'is' nothing but the individual now, but this now that is so exclusive in its revolt is dissolved, diffused and pulverized by my expressing it. "26 "Moreover, in nature where time is now, no 'stable' difference between those dimensions (past and future) ever comes about." 27 "In the positive sense of time one can thus say that only the present is, the before and after are not; but the concrete present is the result of the past and pregnant with the future. Thus the true present is eternity."28 If Hegel calls time "intuited becoming," neither coming into being nor passing away has priority in it. Nevertheless, on occasion he characterizes time as the "abstraction of consuming," and thus formulates the vulgar experience and interpretation of time in the most radical way. 29 On the other hand, when Hegel really defines time, he is consistent enough to grant no such priority to consuming and passing away as that to which the everyday experience of time rightly adheres; for Hegel can no more provide dialectical grounds for this priority than for the "circumstance" (that he introduces as self-evident) that precisely when the point posits itself for itself, the now turns up. So even when he characterizes time as becoming, Hegel understands this becoming in an "abstract" sense that goes beyond the representation of the "flux" of time. The most appropriate expression for Hegel's interpretation of time thus lies in the determination of time as the negation of negation (that is, of punctuality). Here the succession of nows is formalized in the most extreme sense and levelled down to an unprecedented degree. 30 It is only in terms of this formal and dialectical concept of time that Hegel can produce a connection between time and spirit.
(b) Hegel's Interpretation of the Connection between Time and Spirit. In what way has spirit itself been understood in its actualization that Hegel can
II. VI
Being and Time
395
say it is in accordance with spirit to fall into time, with time defined as the negation of a negation? The essence of spirit is the concept. By this Hegel understands not the universal that is intuited in a genus as the form of what is thought, but the form of the very thinking that thinks itself: Conceiving itself-as r;rasping the non-I. Since grasping the non-I presents a differentiation, there lies in the pure concept, as the grasping of this differentiation, a differentiation of the difference. Thus Hegel can define the essence of spirit formally and apophantically as the negation of a negation. This "absolute negativity" gives a logically formalized interpretation of Descartes' cogito me cogitare rem wherein he sees the essence of conscientia. Thus the concept is the conceivedness of the self conceiving itself, the way the self is authentically as it can be, that is, free. "The I is the pure concept itself that has come to existence as the concept."" "But the I is this first pure unity relating itself to itself, not directly, but rather, in abstracting from all determinateness and content and going back to the freedom of the limitless identity with itself."'2 Thus the I is "universality," but it is "individuality" just as immediately. This negating of negation is both the "absolute unrest" of spirit and also its self-revelation, which belongs to its essence. The "progression" of spirit actualizing itself in history contains a "principle of exclusion."" However, in this exclusion what is excluded does not get detached from the spirit, it gets surmounted. Making itself free in overcoming, and at the same time supporting, characterizes the freedom of the spirit. Thus "progress" never means a quantitative more, but is essentially qualitative, and indeed has the quality of spirit. "Progression" is known and knowing itself in its goal. In every step of its "progress," spirit has to overcome "itself' as the truly inimical hindrance of its aim.,. The goal of the development of spirit is "to attain its own concept."55 The development of itself is "a hard infinite struggle against itself. "56 Since the restlessness of the development of spirit bringing itself to its concept is the negation of a negation, it is in accordance with its selfactualization to fall "into time" as the immediate negation of a negation. For "time is the concept itself that is there, and represents itself to consciousness as empty intuition. For this reason spirit necessarily appears in time, and it appears in time as long as it has notr;rasped its pure concept, that is, has not annulled time. Time is the pure self that is externally intuited and not r;rasped by the self, the concept merely intuited."" Thus spirit appears in time necessarily in accordance with its essence. "Thus world history in general is the interpretation of spirit in time, just as the idea interprets itself in nature as space."'8 The "excluding" that belongs to the movement of development contains a relation to nonbeing. That is time, understood in terms of the revolt of the now.
434
396
435
436
Being and Time
II. VI
Time is "abstract" negativity. As "intuited becoming," it is the differentiated self-differentiation that is directly to be found, the concept that "is there," that is, objectively present. As something objectively present and thus external to spirit, time has no power over the concept, but the concept is rather "the power of time. "'9 Hegel shows the possibility of the historical actualization of spirit "in time" by going back to the identity of the formal structure of spirit and time as the negation of a negation. The most empty, formal-ontological and formal-apophantical abstraction into which spirit and time are externalized makes possible the production of a kinship of the two. But since at the same time, time is yet conceived in the sense of world time that has been absolutely levelled down, so that its provenance thus remains completely covered over, it simply confronts spirit as something objectively present. For this reason spirit must first fall "into time." It remains obscure what indeed is signified ontologically by this "falling" and the "actualization" of spirit that has power over time and really "exists" outside of it. Just as Hegel throws little light on the origin of time that has been levelled down, he leaves totally unexamined the question of whether the essential constitution of spirit as the negating of negation is possible at all in any other way than on the basis of primordial temporality. Whether Hegel's interpretation of time and spirit and their connection is correct and has an ontologically primordial basis at all cannot be discussed now. However, that the formal and dialectical "construction" of the connection of spirit and time can be ventured at all reveals the primordial kinship of both. Hegel's "construction" was prompted by his arduous struggle to conceive the "concretion" of the spirit. The following statement from the concluding chapter of his Phenomenology of Spirit makes that known: "Thus time appears as the very fate and necessity of spirit when it is not in itself complete-the necessity of its giving self-consciousness a richer share in consciousness, of setting in motion the immediacy of the in-itself(the form in which substance is in consciousness), or conversely, of its realizing and revealing the in-itself taken as what is inward (and this is what is first inward), that is, vindicating it for the certainty of itself. "'8 Our existential analytic of Da-sein, on the other hand, begins with the "concretion" of factically thrown existence, and reveals temporality as what makes such existence primordially possible. "Spirit" does not first fall into time, but exists as the primordial temporalizing of temporality. Temporality temporalizes world time, in whose horizon "history" can "appear" as an occurrence within time. Spirit does not fall into time, but factical existence "falls," in falling prey, out of primordial, authentic temporality. This "falling," however, itself has its existential possibility in a mode of temporalizing that belongs to temporality.
II. VI
Being and Time
397
83. The Existential and Temporal Analytic of Da-sein and the QJ.testion of Fundamental Ontology as to the Meaning of Being in General The task of the foregoing considerations was to interpret the primordial totality of factical Da-sein with regard to its possibilities of authentic and inauthentic existing and to do so existentially and ontologically in terms of its very basis. Temporality revealed itself as this basis and thus as the meaning of being of care. Thus what the preparatory existential analytic of Da-sein contributed prior to setting forth temporality has now been taken back into temporality as the primordial structure of the totality of being of Da-sein. In terms of the possible ways in which primordial time can temporalize itself, we have provided the grounds for those structures that we only "indicated" earlier. Setting forth the constitution of being of Da-sein, however, still remains only one way that we may take. Our goal is to work out the question of being in general. Our thematic analytic of existence needs in its tum the light from a previously clarified idea of being in general. That is especially true if the statement expressed in our introduction is retained as a standard for every philosophical investigation: Philosophy is universal phenomenological ontology, beginning with a hermeneutic of Da-sein which, as an analytic of existence, has made fast the guideline for all philosophical questioning at the point where it arises and to which it returns. *41 Of course, this thesis must not be taken dogmatically, but as a formulation of the fundamental problem still "veiled": Can ontology be grounded ontologically or does it also need for this an ontic foundation, and which being must take over the function of this foundation? The distinction between the being of existing Da-sein and the being of beings unlike Da-sein (for example, reality) may seem to be illuminating, but it is only the point of departure for the ontological problematic; it is nothing with which philosophy can rest and be satisfied. We have long known that ancient ontology deals with "reified concepts" and that the danger exists of "reifying consciousness." But what does reifying mean? Where does it arise from? Why is being "initially" "conceived" in terms of what is objectively present, and not in terms of things at hand that do, after all, lie still nearer to us? Why does this reification come to dominate again and again? How is the being of "consciousness" positively structured so that reification remains inappropriate to it? Is the "distinction" between "consciousness" and "thing" sufficient at all for a primordial unfolding of the ontological problematic? Do the answers to these questions lie along our way? And can the
* Thus not existential philosophy.
437
398
Being and Time
II.VI
answer even be searched for as long as the question of the meaning of being in general remains unasked and unclarified? We can never inquire into the origin and the possibility of the "idea" of being in general with the means of formal and logical "abstraction," that is, not without a secure horizon for questions and answers. We must look for a way* to illuminate the fundamental ontological question and follow it. Whether that way is at all the only one or even the right one can be decided only after we have followed it. The strife in relation to the interpretation of being cannot be settled because it has not yet roen been started. And finally it cannot be '1umped into," but the beginning of the strife already needs preparation. This investigation is solely underway to that. Where does it stand? Something like "being" has been disclosed in the understanding of being that belongs to existing Da-sein as a way in which it understands. The preliminary disclosure of being, although it is unconceptual, makes it possible for Da-sein as existing being-in-the-world to be related to beings, to those it encounters in the world as well as to itself in existing. How is the disclosive understanding of being belonging to Da·sein possible at all? Can the question be answered by going back to the primordial constitution of being of Da-sein that understands being? The existential and ontological constitution of the totality of Da-sein is grounded in temporality. Accordingly, a primordial mode of temporalizing of ecstatic temporality itself must make the ecstatic project of being in general possible. How is this mode of temporalizing of temporality to be interpreted? Is there a way leading from primordial time to the meaning of being? Does time itself reveal itself as the horizon of being?
* Not "the" sole way.
AUTHOR'S NOTES
INTRODUCTION THE ExPOSffiON OF THE QUESTION OF THE MEANING OF BEING
I. The Necessity, Structure, and Priority of the QJ.testion of Being 1. Aristotle, Metaphysics, III.4.1001a21. 2. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae 11.1, qu. 94, a. 2. 3. Aristotle, Metaphysics III.3.998b22. 4. Cf. Pascal, Pensees et Dpuscules, ed. Brunschvicg (Paris, 1912}, p. 169: "One cannot undertake to define being without falling into this absurdity. For one cannot define a word without beginning in this way: 'It is .. .'. This beginning may be expressed or implied. Thus, in order to defme being one must say 'It is .. .' and hence employ the word to be defined in its definition." 5. Plato, Sophist 242c. 6. De anima III.8.431b21; cf. III.5.430a14ff. 7. Quaestiones de veritate, qu. 1, a. 1c; cf. the occasionally stricter exposition, which deviates from what was cited, of a "deduction" of the transcendentals in the brief work de natura generis.
II. The Double Task in Working Out the QJ.testion of Being: The Method of the Investigation and Its Outline 1. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vemunft, B 180-81. 2. Aristotle, Physics IV.10.217b29-14.224a17.
400
Notes for pp. 23-46 (German pp. 26-49) 3. Kant, Kritik derreinen Vemunft, B 121.
4. Cf. De interpretatione, chaps. 1-6. See further, Metaphysics VII.4 and Nichomachean Ethics VII. 5. If the following investigation takes any steps forward in disclosing "the things themselves" the author must above all thank E. Husser!, who by providing his own incisive personal guidance and by very generously turning over his unpublished investigations familiarized the author during his student years in Freiburg with the most diverse areas of phenomenological research.
DIVISION ONE THE PREPARATORY FuNDAMENTAL ANALYSIS OF DA-SEIN
I. The Exposition of the Task of a Preparatory Analysis of Da-sein 1. St. Augustine, Confessions X.16. 2. E. Husserl's investigations on "personality" have not yet been published. The fundamental orientation of the problematic is already evident in the treatise "Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910), p. 319. The investigation is extensively furthered in the second part of ldeen zu einer Philnomenologie und phanomenologischen Pkilosopkie (Husserliana IV), the first part of which (cf. this]ahrbuch, vol. 1, 1913) presents the problematic of "pure consciousness" as the basis for investigating the constitution of every possible reality. The second part gives developmental constitutional analyses and treats in three sections: 1. The constitution of material nature. 2. The constitution of animal nature. 3. The constitution of the spiritual world (the personalistic formula in contrast with the naturalistic one). Husser! begins his presentation with the words: "Dilthey did formulate the problems which present the goal, the direction which the work to be done should take, but he did not arrive at the decisive formulations of the problem and the solutions which are methodically correct." Mter this first attempt, Husser! pursued the problems in a more penetrating way and communicated essential sections of this in his Freiburg lectures. 3. Cf. this]ahrbuch, vols. 1, 2 (1913) and 2 (1916), especially p. 242ff. 4. Ibid., vol. 2, p. 385. 5. Cf. Logos 1, op. cit. 6. Ibid., p. 388. 7. Genesis I.26. ["And God said, 'Let us make man in our image, after our likeness'."] 8. Calvin, lnstitutio I, 15, paragraph 8. 9. Zwingli, Von klarheit und gewii.sse des wortes Gottes (Deutsche Schriften I, 58).
Notes for pp. 47-84 (German pp. 50-90)
401
10. But the discovery of the a priori is not an "a prioristic" construction. Through E. Husserl we have again learned not only to understand the meaning of all genuine philosophical "empiricism," but we have also learned to use the tools necessary for it. "A priorism" is the method of every scientific philosophy which understands itself. Because a priorism has nothing to do with construction, the investigation of the a priori requires the proper preparation of the phenomenal foundation. The nearest horizon which must be prepared for the analytic of Da-sein lies in its average everydayness. 11. Recently E. Cassirer has made mythical Da-sein the theme of a philosophical interpretation. Cf. Philosophie der symbolischen Formen, part 2, "Das mythische Denken," 1925. Through this investigation more comprehensive guidelines are made available to ethnological investigation. Viewed in terms of the philosophical problematic the question remains whether the foundations of the interpretation are sufficiently transparent, whether especially the architectonic of Kant's Kritik der reinen Vemurft and its systematic content are able to offer the possible outline for such a task at all, or whether a new and more primordial beginning is not necessary here. Cassirer himself sees the possibility of such a task as is shown in the footnote on pages 16ff., where Cassirer points out the phenomenological horizon disclosed by Husserl. In a conversation which the author was able to have with Cassirer on the occasion of a lecture in the Hamburg group of the Kantian Society in December 1923, a lecture on "Aufgaben und Wege der phanomenologischen Forschung," an agreement as to the necessity of an existential analytic which was sketched out in the lecture already became apparent.
II. Being-in-the-World in General as the Fundamental Constitution of Da-sein 1. Cf.Jakob Grimm, Kleinere Schriften, vol. 7, p. 247. 2. Compare section 29.
Ill. The Worldliness of the World 1. The author would like to remark that he has repeatedly communicated the analysis of the surrounding world and the "hermeneutic of the facticity of Da-sein in general" in his lecture courses ever since the winter semester of 1919-20. 2. Misprint in the German original. Read Brilche instead of Brilcke.-TR. 3. Cf. E. Husserl, ldeen, vol. 1, sect. I Off, and idem, Logische Untmuchungen, vol. 1, chapter 11. For the analysis of sign and signification, see ibid., vol. 2, first investigation. 4. Principia I, pr. 53. But although any one attribute is sufficient to give us a knowledge of substance, there is always one principal property of substance which constitutes its nature and essence, and on which all the others depend.
402
Notesforpp. 84-89(Germanpp. 90-95)
5. Ibid. This extension in length, breadth, and depth, constitutes the nature of corporeal substance. 6. Ibid For all else that may be attributed to the body presupposes extension. 7. Ibid., pr. 64. And that one body, retaining the same size, may be extended in many different ways, sometimes being greater in length and less in breadth or depth, and sometimes on the contrary greater in breadth and less in length. 8. Ibid. pr. 65. If we inquire only about locomotion, without taking into account the force that produces it. 9. Ibid., 2, pr. 4. For as regards hardness we do not know anything of it by sense, excepting that the portions of the hard bodies resist the motion of our hands when they come in contact with them; but if, whenever we moved our hands in some direction, all the bodies in that part retreated as soon as our hands approached them, we should never feel hardness; and yet we have no reason to believe that the bodies which recede in this way would on this account lose what makes them bodies. It follows from this that the nature of body does not consist in hardness. 10. Ibid. The same reason shows us that weight, color, and all the other qualities of the kind that is perceived in corporeal matter, may be taken from it, it remaining meanwhile entire: it thus follows that the nature of body depends on none of these. 11. Ibid., I, pr. 51. And when we conceive of substance, we merely conceive an existent thing which requires nothing but itself in order to exist. j,
12. Ibid. Nothing but God answers to this description as being that which absolutely self-sustaining.
13. Ibid. For we perceive that there is no other created thing which can exist without being sustained by his power. 14. Ibid. That is why the word substance does not pertain univoce to God and to other things, as the Scholastics say, that is, no common signification for this appellation which will apply equally to God and to them can be distinctly understood. 15. Cf. Dpwcula omnia Thomae de Vio Caietani Cardinalis, Lugduni (1580), III.5, "de nomimum analogia," pp. 211-19. 16. Descartes, Principia 1, pr. 51. No signification of this name (substance) which would be common to God and his creation can be distinctly understood. 17. Ibid., pr. 52. Yet substance cannot be first discovered merely from the fact that it is a thing that exists, for that fact alone is not observed by us. 18. Ibid., pr. 63. It is moreover easier to know a substance that thinks, or an extended substance, than substance alone, without regarding whether it thinks or is extended.
Notesforpp. 90-131 (Germanpp. 96-139)
403
19. Ibid., 2, pr. 3. It will be sufficient for us to observe that the perceptions of the senses are related simply .to the intimate union which exists between body and mind, and that while by their means we are made aware of what in external bodies can profit or hurt this union, they do not present them to us as they are in themselves unless occasionally and accidentally. 20. That the perceptions of the senses do not teach us what is really in things, but merely that whereby they are useful or hurtful to man's composite nature. 21. Ibid., pr. 4. In this way we shall ascertain that the nature of matter or of body in its universal aspect does not consist in its being hard, or heavy, or colored, or one that affects our senses in some other way, but solely in the fact that it is a substance extended in length, breadth, and depth. 22. Immanuel Kant: "Was Heisst: Sich im Denken orienteren?" (1786)
Werke (Akad. Ausgabe), vol. 8, pp. 131-47. 23. Cf. 0. Becker, Beitriige zur phiinorrumologi.schen Begriindung der Geometrie und ihrer physikalischen Anwendungen,Jahrbuch, vol. 6 (1923), pp. 385ff.
IY. Being-in-the-World as Being-with and Being a Self: The "They,. 1. Cf. the phenomenological elucidations of M. Scheler, Zur Phiinomenologie und Theorie der Sympathiegefilhle, 1913, addendum, pp. 118ff. Also, the second edition under the title Wesen und Formen der Sympathie, 1923, pp. 244ff. 2. "Uber die Verwandtschaft der Ortsadverbien mit dem Pronomen in einigen Sprachen" (1829). Gesammelte Schriften, ed. PreuB. Akad. der Wissen, vol. 6, part 1, pp. 304-30.
V. Being-in as Such 1. cr. section 12. 2.
cr. section 13.
3. Veifallen. "Entanglement" and "falling prey" are both used. Veifallen, is, so to speak, a kind of "movement" that does not get anywhere.-TR. 4.
cr. section 18.
5. [Regarding "taking it easy" and "just passing the time") cf. Aristotle,
Metaphysics A, 982b22ff. 6. Cf. Pascal, Pensees: "Et de Ia vient qu'au lieu qu'en parlant de choses humaines on dit qu'il faut les connaitre avant que de les aimer; ce qui a passe en proverbe, les saints au contraire disent en parlant de choses divines qu'il faut les aimer pour les connaitre, et qu'on n'entre dans Ia verite que par Ia charite, dont ils ont fait une de leurs plus utiles sentences." ["And thence it comes about that in the case where we are speaking of human things, it is said to be necessary
404
Notesforpp. 131-178(Germanpp. 139-190)
to know them before we can love them, and this has become a proverb; but the saints, on the contrary, when they speak of divine things, say we must love them before we know them, and that we enter into truth only through charity; they have made of this one of their most useful maxims."]' Cf. Augustine, Opera (Migne, ed., Patrologiae Latinae, vol. 8), Contra Faustum, book 32, chap. 18: non intratur in veritatem, nisi per charitatem ["one does not enter into truth except through charity"]. 7. Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric B 5.1382a20-1383b11. 8. Cf. section 18. 9. Cf. section 4. 10. Cf. section 13. 11. Cf. Husserl's doctrine of signification in Logische Untersuchungen, vol. 2, investigations 1 and 4-6. See also the more radical version of the problematic in ldeen, vol. 1, sect. 123 et sqq. 12. Metaphysics A i, 980a21. 13. Confessions X.35. 14. Cf. section 9.
VL Care as the Being of Da-sein 1. Cf. section 12. 2. Cf. section 12. 3. Cf. section 27. 4. It is not a matter of chance that the phenomena of Angst and fear, which have never been distinguished in a thoroughgoing way, were constitutive for the scope of Christian theology ontically and also ontologically, although in very narrow limits. This always happened when the anthropological problem of the being of human being toward God gained priority, and phenomena such as faith, sin, love, and repentance guided the questions. Cf. Augustine's doctrine of timor castus and servilis, which is often discussed in his exegetical writings and letters. On fear in general, cf. "De diversis quaestionibus octoginta tribus," qu. 33; "De metu," qu. 34; "Utram non aliud amandum sit, quam metu carere," qu. 35; "Quid amandum sit" (Migne, ed., P. L., vol. 7, 23 sqq.). Apart from the traditional context of an interpretation of poenitentia and contritio, Luther treated the problem of fear in his commentary on Genesis, here, of course, least of all conceptually, but all the more penetratingly by way of edification. Cf. Enarrationes in genesin, chap. 3, WW. (Erl. edition), Eugetica opera latina, vol. 1, 177 et sqq.
Notes for pp. 178-193 (German pp. 190-208)
405
S. Kierkegaard got furthest of all in the analysis of the phenomenon of Angst, again in the theological context of a "pyschological" exposition of the problem of original sin. Cf. Der Begriff der Angst, 1844, Ges. Werke (Diedrichs), vol. 5. 5. The author found the following pre-ontological evidence for the existential and ontological interpretation of Da-sein as care in the essay of K. Burdach, "Faust und die Sorge," Deutsche Vierteljahrschrift for Literatu7Wissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte 1 (1923): Iff. Burdach shows that Goethe took the care fable, handed down as no. 220 of the fables of Hyginus, and reworked it for the second part of his Faust. Cf. particularly pp. 40ff. The above text is cited according to F. Bucheler, Rheinisches Museum 41 (1886): 5, translation Burdach, ibid., pp. 41ff. 6. Cf. Herder's poem "Das kind der Sorge," Suphan 29: 75. 7. "Faust und die Sorge," p. 49. Already with the Stoics, merimna was a stable term, and it comes back in the New Testament, in the Vulgate, as sollicitudo. The direction followed in our existential analytic of Da-sein toward "care" occurred to the author in connection with attempts at an interpretation of Augustinian, that is, Greek and Christian, anthropology with regard to the basic foundations attained in the ontology of Aristotle. 8. Cf. above, pp. 89ff. and 99f. 9. Cf. Kritik der reinen Vernunft, B 274ff., and the amended additions in the preface to the second edition, p. xxxix; note, also, "On the Paralogisms of Pure Reason," pp. 399ff., especially p. 412. 10. Ibid., preface, note. 11. Ibid., p. 275. 12. Ibid, p. 275. 13. Ibid. 274/275. 14.1bid., preface, note. 15. Cf. W. Dilthey, "Beitrage zur LOsung der Frage vom Ursprung unseres Glaubens an die Realitiit der Aussenwelt und seinem Recht" (1890}, Ges. Schr. 5, 1, pp. 90ff. Right at the beginning of this treatise, Dilthey says unmistakably: "For if there is to be a universal truth for man, thinking must, following the method first given by Descartes, clear a path from the facts of consciousness toward outer reality," ibid., p. 90. 16. Recently Nicolai Hartmann, following the procedure of Scheler, used the thesis of knowledge as a "relation of being" as the foundation for his ontologically oriented epistemology. Cf. Grundz:ilge einer Metaphy.sik der Erkenntnis, second enlarged edition, 1925. But Scheler and Hartmann both fail in the same way, in spite of all the differences between their phenomenological point of
406
Notesforpp. 193-201 (Germanpp. 208-218)
departure, to recognize that "ontology" fails in its traditional, basic orientation with regard to Da-sein and that precisely the "relation of being" (cf. above, pp. 79ff.) contained in knowledge forces us to its furulmnmtal revision, not just to a critical improvement. Because Hartmann underestimates the inexplicit scope of influence of an ontologically unclarified positing of the relation of being, he is forced into a "critical realism" which is basically completely strange to the level of problematic put forth by him. For Hartmann's interpretation of ontology, cf. "Wie ist kritische Ontologie iiberhaupt moglich?" in the Festschrift for Paul Natorp, 1924, p. 124ff. 17. Cf., above all, section 16 (The worldliness of the surrounding world announcing itself in innerworldly beings); section 18 (Relevance and Significance: The worldliness of the world); section 29 (Da-sein as Attunement). On the being-in-itself of innerworldly beings, cf. pp. 10 lff. 18. Cf. Beitriige, p. 134. 19. Cf. Die Formen des Wisseru und die Bildung,lecture, 1925, notes 24 and 25. Note in the galleys: Scheler has now published his inquiry, long since announced, on "Erkenntnis und Arbeit" in the collection of treatises just published, Die Wisseruformen und die Gesellschaft, 1926. Section VI of this treatise (p. 455) gives a more detailed presentation of the "theory of voluntary Da-sein" in connection with an appreciation and critique of Dilthey. 20. Diels, Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, fragment 3. 21. Metaphysics A. 22. Ibid., 984a18ff. 23. Ibid., 986b31. 24.1bid., 984b10. 25. Ibid., A, 983b2, cf. 988a20. 26.1bid., 993b17. 27. Ibid., 993b20. 28. Ibid., 1003a21. 29. De interpretatione 1.16a6. 30. Cf. Quaest. disp. de veritate, qu. I, art. 1. 31. Kritik derreinm Vernunft, B82. 32. Ibid., p. 83. 33. Ibid., p. 350. 34. For the idea of demonstration as identification, cf. Husserl's Logische Untersuchungen, vol. 2, part 2, investigation 6. On "evidence and truth," see
Notesforpp. 201-217(Germanpp. 218-235)
407
ibid., pp. 36-39. The usual treaunents of the phenomenological theory of truth are limited to what is said in the critical prologornena (vol. l) and note the connection with Bolzano's theory of the proposition. In contrast, the positive phenomenological interpretations which are quite different from Bolzano's theory are left alone. The only person who took up these investigations in a positive sense was E. Lask whose "Logik der Philosophie" (1911) is influenced just as strongly by the sixth investigation ("Ober sinnliche und kategoriale Anschauungen," p. 128ff.) as his "Lehre vorn Urteil" (1912) through the sections cited on evidence and truth. 35. Cf. Diels, Fragmente der Vor.tokratiker, Heraclitus, fragment 1. 36. cr. PP· 32ff. 37. cr. section 29. 38. cr. section 34b. 39. K. Reinhardt fll'St grasped and solved the much mistreated problem of the connection of the two parts of Parrnenides' poem (cf. Parmenides und die Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie, 1916), although he does not explicitly point out the ontological foundation for the connection between aletheia and doxa. 40. Cf. above, section 33. Assertion as a derivative mode of interpretation. 41. Cf. section 34. 42. Cf. Nichomachean Ethics Z, and Metaphysics TH, 10.
DIVISION TWO DA-SEIN AND TEMPORALITY
Section 45 1. Cf. section 9. 2. Cf. sections 6, 21, and 43. 3. Cf. section 32. 4. Cf. section 9. 5. Cf. section 41. 6. In the nineteenth century S. Kierkegaard explicitly grasped and thought through the problem of existence as existentiell in a penetrating way. But the existential* problematic is so foreign to him that in an ontological regard he is completely under the influence of Hegel and his view of ancient philosophy. Thus more is to be learned philosophically from his "edifying" writings than from his theoretical work-with the exception of the treatise on the concept of Angl't. * and, to be sure, the fundamental ontological one, i.e. aiming at the question of being as such in general.
408
Notesforpp. 217-234 (Germanpp. 235-252)
I. The Possible Being-a-Whole of Da-sein and Being-toward-Death I. Cf. section 9.
2. Cf. section 10. 3. The difference between whole and sum, holon and pan, totum and compositum is familiar to us ever since Plato and Aristotle. Of course, the systematics of the categorial transformation already contained in this division is not yet recognized and conceptualized. For the beginning of a detailed analysis, cf. E. Husser!, Logische Untersuchungen, vol. 2, third investigation: "On the Doctrine of Wholes and Parts." 4. Der Ackermann aus Bohmen, ed. A. Bernt and K. Burdach, in Vom Mittelalter zur Reformation: Forschungen zur Geschichte der deutschen Bildung, ed. K. Burdach, vol. 3, part 2 (1917), chap. 20, p. 46. 5. Cf. E. Korschelt' s comprehensive portrayal, Lebensdauer, Altern und Tod, 3rd edition, 1924, especially the rich bibliography, pp. 414ff. 6. The anthropology developed in Christian theology-from Paul to Calvin's meditatio futurae vitae-has always already viewed death together with its interpretation of "life." Dilthey, whose true philosophical tendencies aimed at an ontology of "life," could not fail to recognize its connection with death. "And finally, the relation which most deeply and universally defmes the feeling of our Da-sein-that of life toward death, for the limitation of our existence by death is always decisive for our understanding and our estimation of life." Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung, 5th edition, p. 230. Recently G. Simmel has also explicitly related the phenomenon of death to the definition of "life," however without a clear separation of the biological and ontic from the ontological and existential problematic. Cf. Lebensanschauung: Vier metaphysische Kapitel, 1918, pp. 99-153. For the present inquiry, compare especially K. Jaspers, Psychologie der Weltanschauungen, 3rd edition, 1925, p. 299ff. and especially 259-70. Jaspers understands death by following the guidelines of the phenomenon of the "borderline situation" developed by him, whose fundamental significance lies beyond any typology of "attitudes" and "worldviews." R. Unger took up Dilthey's suggestions in his work Herder, Novalis und Kleist: Studien iiber die Entwicklung des Todesproblems im Denken und Dichten von Sturm und Drang Zur Romantik, 1922. Unger offers a major reflection on Dilthey's questions in the lecture: Literaturegeschichte als Problemgeschichte: Zur Frage geisteshistorischer Synthese, mit besonderer Beziehung auf W. Dilthey (Schriften der Konigsberger Gelehrten Gesellschaft, Geisteswiss. Klass 1.1, 1924). Unger (pp. 17ff.) sees clearly the significance of phenomenological investigation for a more radical foundation of the "problems of life." 7. Cf. section 41. 8. Cf. section 40. 9. Cf. section 27.
Notes for pp. 234-2.51 (German pp. 2.53-272)
409
10. Cf. section 16. 11. Cf. section 38. 12. L. N. Tolstoi in his story "The Death of Ivan llyitch" has portrayed the phenomenon of the disruption and collapse of this "one dies." 13. Cf., with regard to this methodological possibility, what was said about the analysis of Angst, section 40. 14. Cf. Section 44. 15. Cf. section 44, b. 16. Regarding the inauthenticity ofDa-sein, see section 9, section 27, and in particular section 38. 17. Cf. section 31. 18. Cf. section 62. 19. Cf. section 29. 20. Cf. section 40.
IL The Attestation of Da-sein of an Authentic Potentiality-ofBein~ and Resoluteness 1. Cf. section 25. 2. Cf. section 27. 3. These observations and those which follow after were communicated as theses on the occasion of a public lecture on the concept of time, which was given at Marburg in july 1924. 4. Schuldigsein. The basic meaning of Schuld is ontological, lacking something ontologically. Since "being a lack" is often linguistically cumbersome, we retain the terms "guilt" and "guilty," bearing in mind that they are ontological, not "ethical" and certainly not "theological."-TR. 5. Entschlrusenheit. Literally in Heidegger's primary meaning "unlockedness," the emphasis being on freed and open for something.-TR. 6. Cf. section 28 et seq. 7. Cf. section 34. 8. Besides Kant's, Hegel's, Schopenhauer's, and Nietzsche's interpretations of conscience, we should note M. Kahler, Das Gewissen, erster geschichtlicher Teil, 1878, and the article by the same author in the Realenzyklopiidie f prot. Theologie und Kirche. Furthermore, A. Risch!, Uber das Gewissen, 1876, reprinted in Gesammelte Aufsiitze, Neue Folge, 1896, pp. 177ff. Finally, cf.
Notesforpp. 251-283 (German pp. 272-306)
410
the monograph just published of H. G. Stoker, Das Gewissen, in Schriften zur Philosophie und Soziologie, ed. Max Scheler, vol. 2, 1925. This broadly conceived inquiry clarifies a manifold richness of phenomena of conscience, characterizes critically the various possible kinds of treating the phenomenon, and notes further literature which is not complete with regard to the history of and concept of conscience. Stoker's monograph differs from our existential interpretation already in his initial position and thus also in its conclusions in spite of many points of agreement. Stoker underestimates from the beginning the hermeneutical conditions for a "description" of the "objectively real conscience," p. 3. Hand in hand with this goes the muddling of the borderlines between phenomenology and theology-to the detriment of both. With regard to the anthropological foundations of the inquiry which Scheler's personalism takes over, cf. the present inquiry, section 10. Still, Stoker's monograph signifies considerable progress as compared with the traditional interpretations of conscience, but more by the comprehensive treatment of the phenomenon of conscience and its ramifications, than by pointing out the ontological roots of the phenomenon. 9.
cr. section 40.
10. Cf. M. Scheler, Der Formalismu.s in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik, part 2. This]ahrbuch, vol. 2 (1916), p. 334. 11. cr. section 34. 12. Cf. section 44. 13. cr. section 44. 14.
cr. section 18.
15. cr. section 44. 16. Cf. sections 23 and 24. 17. K.Jaspers explicitly conceived and carried out the task of a doctrine of worldviews for the first time in the direction of this problematic. Cf. his Psychologie der Weltanschauungen, 3 ed., 1925. "What man is" is here questioned and determined in terms of what he can essentially be (cf. the preface to the first edition). From this the existential ontological significance of "borderline situations" becomes clear. The philosophical tendency of this work is completely missed if one uses it solely as an encyclopedia of "types of worldviews."
III. The Authentic Potentialityfor-Being-a-Whole of Da-sein, and Temporality as the Ontological Meaning of Care 1. cr. section 53. 2. The being guilty that belongs primordially to the constitution of being of Da-sein is to be distinguished from the status corruptionis as it is understood by theology. Theology can find an ontological condition of its factical possibility in
Notes for pp. 283-295 (German pp. 306-320)
411
being guilty as it is defined existentially. The guilty contained in the idea of this
status is a factical indebtedness of a completely unique kind. It has its own attestation that remains fundamentally closed off to every philosophical experience. The existential analysis of being-guilty does not prove anythingfor or against the possibility of sin. Strictly speaking, one cannot even say that the ontology of Da-sein leaves this possibility open at all of its own accord since, as philosophical questioning, it "knows" nothing about sin in principle. 3. Cf. section 45. 4. Cf. section 45. 5. Cf. section 5. 6. Cf. section 43. 7. Cf. sections 44 and 26. 8. Cf. section 32. 9. Cf. section 44. 10. Cf. section 41. 11. Cf. section 45. 12. Cf. section 25. 13. Cf. section 43, c. 14. Cf. section 41. 15. Cf. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunjt, B399, and especially the treatment in the 1st edition, A348ff. 16. On the analysis of transcendental apperception, cf. M. Heidegger,
Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik, 2nd ed., 1951, Division III. 17. Kritik derreinen Vernunft, B404. 18. Ibid., A354. 19. The fact that Kant in principle conceived the ontological character of the self of the person within the horizon of an inappropriate ontology of things objectively present in the world as "substantial things" becomes clear in the material that H. Heimsoeth worked on in his essays Personlichkeitsbewu.sstsein und Ding an sick in der Kantischen Philosophie, (reprint from Immanuel Kant: Festschrift zur zweiten]ahrhundertsfeier seines Geburtstages, 1924). The tendency of the essay goes beyond a historiographical report and aims at the "categorial" problem of personality. Heimsoeth (pp. 31f.) says: There is still too little consideration of the close working together of theoretical and practical reason as Kant practised and planned it. One does not sufficiently notice how even the categories (in contrast to their natu-
412
Notesjorpp. 295-311 (Germanpp. 320-338) ralistic fulfillment in the "principles") are here to receive explicit validity and find a new application free of natural rationalism with the primacy of practical reason (for example, substance in the "person" and the duration of personal immortality, causality as "causality through freedom," reciprocity in the "community of reasonable beings," etc.). As a means of establishing things in thought, they serve as a new access to the unconditioned without wishing to give rationalizing knowledge of objects.
But, after all, the real ontological problem has been passed over here. The question cannot be omitted whether these "categories" can maintain primordial validity and only need to be applied differently, or whether they do not in principle distorl the ontological problematic of Da-sein. Even if theoretical reason is included in practical reason, the existential and ontological problematic of the self remains not only unsolved, but unasked. On what ontological basis is the "working together" of theoretical and practical reason supposed to occur? Does theoretical behavior determine the kind of being of the person, or is it the practical reason or neither of the two-and which one then? Do not the paralogisms, in spite of their fundamental significance, reveal the lack of ontological foundation of the problematic of the self from Descartes' res cogitans to Hegel's concept of the Spirit? One does not even need to think "naturalistically" or "rationalistically" and can yet be in subservience to an ontology of the "substantial" that is only all the more fatal because it is seemingly self-evident. Cf. as an essential complement to the above-mentioned essay, Heimsoeth, "Die methaphysischen Motive in der Ausbuildung des kritischen Idealismus," Kantstudien 29 (1924): 121ff. For the critique of Kant's concept of the I, cf. also Max Scheler, Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik, part II of this yearbook, vol. 2 (1916), 246ff., "Uber 'Person' und das 'Ich' der transcendentalen Apperception." 20. Cf. our phenomenological critique of Kant's "Refutation of Idealism," section 43a, above. 21. Cf. sections 12 and 13. 22. Cf. section 32. 23. Cf. section 41. 24. Cf. section 9. 25. Cf. sections 25 et seq.
IV. Temporality and Everydayness 1. Cf. Division I, chapters I-VI. 2. Cf. section 31. 3. S. Kierkegaard saw the existentiell phenomenon of the Moment in the most penetrating way, which does not mean that he was also as successful in the existential interpretation of it. He gets stuck in the vulgar concept of time and
Notesjorpp. 311-332 (Germanpp. 338-363)
413
defines the Moment with the help of the now and eternity. When Kierkegaard speaks of "temporality," he means hwnan being's being-in-time. Time as withintime-ness knows only the now, but never a moment. But if the moment is experienced existentielly, a more primordial temporality is presupposed, although existentially inexplicit. In relation to the "Moment," cf. K. Jaspers, Psychologie der Weltanschauungen, and the "Rejerat Kierkegaards. " 4. Cf. section 29. 5. Cf. section 30. 6. Cf. Rhetoric B 5, 1382a21. 7. Cf. section 40. 8. Cf. section 38. 9. Cf. sections 35 et seq. 10. Cf. section 36. 11. Cf. section 34. 12. Cf. J. Wackemagel, Vorl&ungen uber Syntax, vol. 1 (1920), p. 15 and especially pp. 149-210. See also G. Herbig, "Aktionasart und Zeitstufe," Indogermanische Forschung 6 (1896): 167ff. 13. Cf. section 28. 14. Cf. section 15. 15. Cf. section 12. 16. Cf. section 18. 17. Cf. section 16. 18. Cf. section 44. 19. Cf. section 7. 20. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunjt, B33. 21. Cf. section 32. 22. The thesis that all cognition aims at "intuition" has the temporal meaning that all cognition is a making present. Whether every science or even philosophical cognition aims at a making present must remain undecided here. Husserl uses the expression "making present" to characterize sense perception. Cf. Logische Untersuchungen (1901), vol. 2, pp. 588, 620. The intentional analysis of perception and intuition in general had to suggest this "temporal" characterization of the phenomenon. How the intentionality of "consciousness" is grounded in the ecstatic temporality of Da-sein will be shown in the following division.
414
Notesforpp. 332-369 (German pp. 363-404) 23. Cf. section 18. 24. Cf. sections 22-24. 25. Cf. section 9.
V. Temporality and Historicity 1. Cf. section 64. 2. Cf. section 63. 3. Cf. section 80. 4. Cf. section 60. 5. Cf. section 62. 6. Cf. section 58. 7. Cf. section 26. 8. On the concept of "generation," cf. W. Dilthey, "Uber das Studium der Geschichte der Wissenschaften vom Menschen, der Gesellschaft und dem Staat" (1875), Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 5 (1924), pp. 36-41. 9. For the question of ontologically differentiating the "motion of nature" from the movement of history, cf. F. Gottl, Die Grenzen der Geschichte (1904). These reflections have not been appreciated sufficiently at all. 10. Cf. section 6. 11. Concerning the constitution of historiographical understanding, cf. E. Spranger, "Zur Theorie des Verstehens und zur geisteswissenschaftlichen Pyschologie," Festschriftfor]ohannes Volkelt, (1918), pp. 357ff. 12. Cf. Briefwechsel zwischen Wilhelm Dilthey und dem Grafen Paul Yorck von Wartenburg, 1877-1897, (Halle an der Salle, 1923). 13. Correspondence, p. 185. 14. This is not necessary since we have G. Misch to thank for a concrete presentation of Dilthey that aims at the central tendencies that is essential to any discussion of his work. Cf. W. Dilthey, Ges. Schriften, vol. 5 (1924), Vorbericht, pp. vii-cxvii. 15. Cf. sections 5 and 6.
Notesforpp. 369-389 (German pp. 404-424)
415
VI. Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time 1. Cf. section 33. 2. Cf. section 15. 3. Cf. section 18 and 69c. 4. We shall not go into the problem of time measurement in the theory of relativity here. The illumination of the ontological foundations of this measurement already presupposes a clarification of world time and within-timeness in terms of the temporality of Da-sein and the explication of the existential and temporal constitution of the discovery of nature and the temporal meaning of measurement in general as well. An axiomatic of the technique of physical measurement is based on these investigations and can never in its turn explicate the problem of time as such. 5. For a first attempt at the interpretation of chronological time and "historical numeration," cf. the Freiburg habilitation lecture of the author (SS 1915): "Der Zeitbegriff in der Geschichtswissenschaft," published in the Zeitschrift for Philosophie und philosophische Kritik vol. 161 (1916): 173ff. The connections between historical numeration, astronomically calculated world time, and the temporality and historicity of Da-sein need further investigation. Cf. also G. Simmel, "Das Problem der historischen Zeit," in Philos. Vonriige, published by the Kantgesellschaft, no. 12 (1916). The two fundamental works on the development of historiographical chronology are: Josephus Justus Scalinger, De emendatione temporum, 1583, and Dionysus Petavius, SJ., opus de doctrina temporum, 1627. For the ancient time reckoning, cf. G. Bilfinger, Die antiken Stundenangaben (1888); Der bii.rgerliche Tag: Untersuchungen iiber den Beginn des Kalendertages im klassischen Altertum und im christlichen Mittelalter ( 1888); H. Diels, Antike Technik, 2nd ed. (1920}, pp. 155-232, "Die antike Uhr." On newer chronology, see Fr. Riihl, Chronologie des Mittelalters und der Neur.eit (1897). 6. Cf. section 44c. 7. Cf. Physics, IV 11, 219b1 et seq. 8. Cf. section 6. 9. Cf. section 21. 10. Cf. Timaeus 37d: "But he decided to make a kind of moving image of the eternal; and while setting the heavens in order, he made an eternal image, moving according to number-an image of that eternity which abides in oneness. It is to this image that we have given the name of'time'." 11. Cf. section 41. 12. Cf. section 51.
416
Notesforpp. 389-394 (Gennanpp. 424-432)
13. We do not need to discuss in detail the fact that the traditional concept of eternity in the significance of the "standing now" (nunc stans) is drawn from the vulgar understanding of time and defined in orientation toward the idea of "constant" objective presence. If the eternity of God could be philosophically "constructed," it could be understood only as more primordial and "infinite" temporality. Whether or not the via negationis et eminentiae could offer a possible way remains an open question. 14. Physics, 14, 223a25; cf. 11, 218b29-219a1, 219a4-6. "But if nothing other than the soul or the soul's mind were naturally equipped for numbering, then if there were no soul, time would be impossible." 15. Confessions XI.26. "Hence it seemed to me that time is nothing else than an extendedness; but of what sort of thing it is an extendedness I do not know; and it would be surprising if it were not an extendedness of the soul itself." 16. On the other hand, how a more radical understanding of time emerges in Kant than in Hegel will be shown in the first section of the second part of this treatise. 17. Hegel, Die Vemunft in der Geschichte. Einleitung in die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte, ed. G. Lasson (1917), p. 133. 18. Ibid. 19. Cf. Hegel, Encyklopiidie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse, ed. G. Bolland (Leiden, 1906), section 254 et seq. This edition also has the "Zusatze" from Hegel's lectures. 20. Ibid., section 257, Zusatz. 21. Ibid., section 254. 22. Ibid., section 254, Zusatz. 23. Cf. Hegel, Encyklopiidie, critical edition of Hoffmeister (1949), section 257. 24. Ibid., section 258. 25. Cf. Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik, Bk. I, Div. 1, Chap. 1 (ed. G. Lasson, 1923), pp. 66ff. 26. Cf. Encyklopadie, section 258, Zusatz. 27. Ibid., section 259. 28. Ibid., section 259, Zusatz. 29. Ibid., section 258, Zusatz. 30. In terms of the priority of the now levelled down, it becomes dear that Hegel's conceptual determination of time also follows the course of the vulgar
Notesforpp. 394-395 (Germanpp. 432-433)
417
understanding of time, and that means at the same time the traditional concept of time. We can show that Hegel's concept of time is even drawn directly from Aristotle's Physics. In the]enenser Logik (cf. G. Lasson's edition, 1923) that was projected at the time of Hegel's habilitation, the analysis of time of the Enzyklopadie is already developed in all its essential constituents. The section on time (pp. 202fT.) reveals itself to even the roughest examination as a paraphrase of the Aristotelian treatise on time. Already in the Jenenser Logik, Hegel develops his interpretation of time in the scope of the philosophy of nature (p. 186); its first part is entitled "The System of the Sun" (p. 186). Following the conceptual determination of the ether and motion, Hegel discusses the concept of time. The analysis of space is still subordinate here. Although dialectic already breaks through, it does not have the later, rigid, schematic form, but still makes possible a more flexible understanding of the phenomena. On the way from Kant to Hegel's developed system, a decisive impact of Aristotelian ontology and logic comes about once more. As a fact this has been long familiar. But the way, manner, and limits of this influence are just as obscure today. A concrete, comparative, philosophical interpretation of Hegel's Jenenser Logik and Aristotle's Physics and Metaphysics will throw new light on this. A few rough references will suffice for the above reflections. Aristotle sees the essence of time in the nun; Hegel in the now. Aristotle conceives the nun as horos; Hegel interprets the now as "limit." Aristotle understands the nun as stigme; Hegel interprets the now as point. Aristotle characterizes the nun as tode ti; Hegel calls the now the "absolute this." Aristotle connects chronos with sphaira, in accordance with the tradition; Hegel emphasizes the "circular course" of time. Of course, Hegel misses the central tendency of Aristotle's analysis of time of discovering a foundational connection (akolouthein) between the nun, horos, stigme, and tode ti. In spite of all differences in reasoning, Bergson's interpretation agrees with Hegel's thesis that space "is" time. Bergson just turns it around: Time (temps) is space. Bergson's interpretation of time, too, obviously grew out of an interpretation of Aristotle's treatise on time. It is not just a matter of an external literary connection that simultaneously with Bergson's Essai sur les donnees immediates de la conscience, where the problem of temps and duree is expounded, a treatise of Bergson's appeared with the title: Quid Aristoteles de loco senserit. With regard to the Aristotelian definition of time as arithmos kineseas, Bergson analyses number before analyzing time. Time as space (cf. Essai, p. 69) is quantitative succession. Duration is described in a counter-orientation toward this concept of time as qualitative succession. This is not the place for a critical discussion of Bergson's concept of time and other present-day interpretations of time. To the extent that anything essential has been gained at all beyond Aristotle and Kant, the concern is more with grasping time and "time consciousness." By referring to the direct connection of Hegel's concept of time and Aristotle's analysis of time, we do not intend to charge Hegel with being "dependent," but to point out the fundamental ontological scope of this affiliation for Hegel's Logic. On "Aristotle and Hegel," cf. the essay with this title of Nicolai Hartmann in Beitrage zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus, vol. 3 (1923), pp. 1-36.
418
Notes for pp. 394-398 (German pp. 433-437)
31. Cf. Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik, vol. 2 (ed. Lasson, 1923), part 2, p. 220. 32.1bid. 33. Cf. Hegel, Die Vemunft in der Geschichte. Einleitung in die Philosophie, ed. G. Lasson (1917), p. 130. 34. Ibid., p. 132. 35.1bid. 36.1bid. 37. Cf. Phiinomenologie des Geistes, Werke, vol. 2, p. 604. 38. Cf. Die Vemunft in der Geschichte, p. 134.
39. Cf. Encyklopiidie, section 258. 40. Cf. Phiinomenologie des Geistes, p. 605. 41. Cf. section 7.
LEXICON
ON THE COMPOSITION OF THE LEXICON
The following Lexicon has been composed with the help of the following sources, each of which is here gratefully acknowledged as a powerful tool, each in its own way, in the labor of its composition: Hildegard Feick, Index zu Heifkggers 'Sein und Zeit'. Fourth newly revised edition by Susanne Ziegler. Tiibingen: Niemeyer, 1961, 41991. Rainer A Bast/Heinrich P. Delfosse, Handbuch zum Textstudium von Martin Heifkggers 'Sein und Zeit'. Vol. 1: Stellenindiz.es; Philologisch-kritischer Apparat. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog, 1980. John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson, translators of Martin Heidegger, Being and Time. New York/San Francisco: Harper-Collins, 1962. "Index of English Expressions (Latin Expressions; Greek Expressions; Proper Names)," pp. 524-589.
All three sources, including the English index by Macquarrie and Robinson, refer to the pagination of the original German edition of Sein und Zeit (Tiibingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 7 1953, 16 1986), pp. 1-437, which since the 14th edition (1977) also lists Heidegger's later marginal remarks in an appendix, "Randbemerkungen aus dem Handexemplar des Autors," pp. 439-445. Following this convention, the following Lexicon also lists the pagination of the original German edition, which is to be found in the margins of the pages of this translation. Since this translation presents Heidegger's later marginal remarks as footnotes to the appropriate pages within the body of the transla-
419
420
Being and Time
tion itself, these footnotes will be identified in the Lexicon by the designation "fn" preceded by the German page number, "85fn," for example (here citing the longest of the marginal remarks). Heidegger's 157 marginal remarks, ranging from a single word to a lengthy paragraph or a long list, are to be found on 101 pages of the German text of 437 pages. Heidegger's footnotes to the original edition (1927) are now listed at the end of this translation under "Author's Notes" and numbered within each chapter; these endnotes are accordingly identified in the Lexicon by German page number followed by the designation "n." and the number assigned to the note, "190 n. 4," for example. I have, on occasion, italicized particularly important page numbers within the individual entry and, on rarer occasion, parenthesized pivotal page numbers where the entry is clearly being alluded to without actually being named. Subentries are by and large ordered, not alphabetically, but more or less seriatim or "genealogically," in the order in which the idea is initially broached in the sequence of the text. For some of the entries, I have borrowed subentries extensively from the abundant Index by Macquarrie and Robinson. For others, I have relied heavily on the computer-generated list of page numbers presented by Bast/Delfosse, without however trying to be exhaustive with the highestfrequency terms, especially in their combining forms so prolific in the German language. Since this Lexicon is not designed to serve as an index for this work, I have avoided the temptation to cite extensive "exergues" that would serve to define terms in greater depth, as is the case in Feick's "Index" and in Albert Hofstadter's lengthy Lexicon to his translation of Heidegger's The Bo.sic Probkms ofPherwmenology. In lieu of this, I have relied more than usually both on the briefest of subentries and on the "See also" cross-referencing at the end of especially some of the less familiar entries, in order to suggest the relational context from which the terms spring. I have omitted a number of minor entries provided in the English index by Macquarrie and Robinson, amplifying however its focus on ordinary expressions and phrases like "giving to understand" and "having to be," which play crucial albeit often incipient roles in Heidegger's argument, and added and/ or developed some neglected terms which have come to be recognized as important to the developmental infrastructure of the published Divisions of Being and Time. Finally, in a few rare instances, I have made a halting beginning toward illustrating how some common idioms ("in the Light of," "with Regard to") also function in a methodological way for Heidegger in the development of his opus magnum. A shift in emphasis in entries chosen was in part also dictated by the incorporation of Heidegger's later marginal remarks into this
Lexicon
421
English translation. But Feick's index in particular is devoted to relating the terms of Being and Time to those of Heidegger's later works, thereby turning it, as Heidegger himself remarks in praise of Feick's Index, into a "Way-not a Work." In sum, the following important conventions should be noted by users of this Lexicon: Usage of the German pagination of the Niemeyer edition of Sein und Zeit, which is to be found in the margins of the translation n. 1 =reference to Heidegger's original Notes, now listed numerically in the "Author's Notes" at the end of the translation fn =reference to Heidegger's later marginal remarks, now to be found as Footnotes to the appropriate pages within the body of the translation -Theodore Kisiel LEXICON OF ENGLISH EXPRESSIONS Abandonment (Uberlassenheit): to oneself, 141, 192, 277, 308, 347, 365; to one's own null basis, 348; to one's having-been, 365; to having made a choice, 384; to defmite possibilities, 270; to one's thrownness, 345; to the disposal of the they, 193; to the world, 172, 412; to a 'world', 356, 406, 412-413; to the past, 386. See also Angst; Lostness; Thrownness "About which," the (das Worum of Angst and fear; das Woruber of statement, etc.): offear, 140-141; of Angst, 187-188, 191, 251, 266, 342-343; of statement, 158, 218, 224; of discourse or talk, 161-162, 164, 168, 272; ofjudgement, 216. See also As-structure; In the face of which Absorption (Aufgehen ): in the world, 51,54,71-72,75-76,111,113, 120,125,129-130,186,203,225, 322,354-355,369,389,409;in the they, 167,175,184,189,222,
270; through dedication, 354. See also Familiarity; Lostness; Obviousness Abyss (Abgrund): of meaninglessness, 152 Access (Zugang) to being: 28, 94-96, 324; to the original "wellsprings" of categories and concepts, 21; voeiv and Mr~ as, 33, 44, 100, 154; phenomeno-logy as, 35-37; "sight" as "access as such," formally universal term for, 147; through being's understanding, 212, 372. See also Es gibt; Given; Phenomenology; Sight; Understanding of being Access (Zugang) to Da-sein, 13, 16, 115, 117; through Angst, 182. Accident (Zufall): be-falls resoluteness, 300, 384, (152); inauthentic, 410. See also Fate Act (Akt), 115, 119, 272, 352, 391; in Scheler, 47-48, 139. Action, taking action (Handeln, handeln), 69, 174, 176, 288,
422
Being and Time
Action, taking action (continued) 294-295,300,302,310,319,326; "verbal" kinds of action (Aktionsarten, grammatical), 349. See also Practical; Praxis; Resolution; Situation Actual, actuality (Wirklich[keitf), 201fn ("reality" as); and possibility, 38, 143, 195, 236, 243, 254,261-262,299,347,430; 'world', 62, 195; of things, 99; 'external' (Dilthey), 205 n. 13; historical, 10, 378; validity as 'form' of, 156; subjectivity, 229; conscience as 'a.' subsisting (Stoker), 272 n. 8; agreement with, 62; momentary, etc., 373-374. See also Reality; Subsistence Actualization (Verwirklichung) of possibility of: death, 261-262; Dasein in repetition, 385; spirit, 433-435. See also Modification Aesthetic (iiesthetisch), 396, 399-400, 402 Affect, Affection (Affekt, Affektion, affizieren, etc.), 94, 137-139, 142, 341, 345-346. See also Attunement; Mood Be afraid (sich fiirchten), 140-142, 186, 189, 341-342. See also Angst; Fear "Against," the (das Wider): of resistance, 210; one-another, 121, 175 (Gegen-). See also For-oneanother Ahead of itself (sich vorweg), 191-196, 202,220,227-228,236-237,244, 249-251,259,277,291,315,317, 322, 327, 337, 406, 425. See also Care, structure of; Future Alien, strange ifremd): stranger, 121, 125; world, 172, 356; power, 275, 278; voice, 277-278 Alienation (Entfremdung): in falling prey, 178, 180,254,347-348; from authentic historicity, 396. See
also Entanglement; Tranquillization Ambiguity (Zweideutigkeit), 133, 173-175,177,180,222,253-255, 271,298-299,346,378,383.See also Curiosity; Falling prey; Idle talk Analogy (Analogie): of being, 3, 93; of care, 193. See also Being, Concept; Genus Analysis (Analyse), 12, 14, et passim; distinguished from analytic, 131; of Da-sein (Daseinsanalyse), 51, 315; ontological, 65-68, 77, 181-182,207,241,247,269,289, 374; existential, 232-233, 237, 246-248,275,290,305,311-313, 316,331,340,372,378,383,418; existential-temporal, 234, 333, 367, 404; temporal, 332, 346, 404; intentional, 363 n. 23. See also Fundamental analysis Analytic (noun: Analytik): in Kant's sense, 4, 23-25; of existence, 38, 436; of Da-sein, 41-45, 53, 58, 64-66,100,163,183,213,309, 315; primordial, 151, 316. See also Existential analytic Anatomy (Anatomie), 238 Ancient ontology (antike Ontologie), 2-4,19,24-26,40,48-49,154, 159-160,219,235,403,421,437 Ang:st (Ang:st), 140, 182-192, 199, 235 n. 6, 251,254-255,258,265-266, 266fn,276-277, 296-297,301, 305,308,310,322,341-345; readiness for, 297, 301, 382, 385, 391 Animals (Tiere), 70, 199, 246, 346. See also Life Anthropology (Anthropologie), 200, 290; philosophical, 16-17,47, 131; distinguished from analytic of Dasein and fundamental ontology, 45-50, 131, 194; existential a priori, 183, 301; Greek-Christian, 48-49, 190, 199 n. 7, 249 n. 6, 272 n. 8; Jaspers, 301 n. 17
Lexicon Anticipation of death (Vorlaufen zum Tode), 262-267, 301-310, 313, 316-318,322-326,329,331, 336-339,345,350,374,382-386, 390-391,424-425 Antiquarian (antiquari.sch), 396-397, 400. See also Historiography Apophantical (apophantisch), 33-34, 155, 433, 435; "as," 158, 223. See also citrO?avcnq; Statement Appearance (Erscheinen), 23, 29-31, 35-36, 78, 321, 436; outward a. or "look" (Awsehen), 28-30, 42, 61 (eidos), 63, 69, 73, 138, 172, 222, 346. See also Phenomenon; Illusion Apperception (Apperzeption), 319, 319 n. 16 A priori (Apriori, apriori.sch): in Kant's sense, 11, 31, 101, 110-111, 115, 321; categories, 45; of Da-sein, 45, 53, 229; research, 50 n. 10; of "life," 58; of worldliness, 65, as perfect [tense], 85; of space, 111; existential, 131, 149; as forestructure, 150-151; of discourse, 165; -ontological, 199; as "earlier," 206; of mathematical project of nature, 362. See also a priori (Latin); Condition of possibility; Ground; Horizon Archeological (archiiologisch), 358 "Arising" (Entspringen, "springing from") from and between the temporalizing modes of originative temporality, 326 (having-been from future), 333 (within-time-ness from primordial), 344 (Angst from Dasein), 345 (equanimity from resoluteness), 386 (authentic occurrence of existence from future), 391 (Moments from repetition), 426 (vulgar concept of time from entangled Da-sein); present from a future that hasbeen, 350, 365, 427; making
423
present from awaiting-retaining, 347-348, 354, 356; is degeneration from origin, 334; is ecstatic modification, 347; historiography from historicity, 395-396; and returning point of all philosophical questioning, 38, 436; a river's "source" geographically, 70. See also Leaping; Origin; Provenance; Temporalizing; Temporality, primordial Aroundness (das Umhafte), 66, 79, 101, 103, 112. See also Surrounding world Art (Kunst), 23 (deep within the soul), 127 Gudged by the they); "artistic" interpretation of useful things, 68fn. See also Literature; Poetry Articulable (Artikulierbares, Gliederbares): is meaning, 151, 153, 161. See also Discourse; Interpretation Articulation (Artikulation, Gliederung): by worldliness, 104, 111; by theyself, 129; as interpretation of meaning, 151; predicating a. of subject and predicate, 155, 157; of referential relations of significance, 158; of contexts of signification, 161, 168, guided by spatial relations, 369; equiprimordially binding and separating, 159; as discursivity (Rede) of understandability, 161-162,271,335,349(of disclosedness); of being-with-oneanother, 162, 165 (in reticence); conceptual, 168; of structure of care, 196,200,234,311(as enriched fore-grasp), 317, 324-325,327(unifiedin temporality), 351; of understanding of being modally, 201, 363-364; by attuned understanding, 335; of totality of
424
Being and Time
Articulation (continued) beings for science, 362-364; of average interpretedness, 406; of time that makes present 409, 416. See also Discourse; Interpretation As-structure (Als-Stmktur), 149-151, 154, 158-159,223,359-360.See also Explicitness; Interpretation; Schema Association(s) (Umgang, dealings): in having to do with surrounding beings everyday, 66-73, 79-81, 83, 85, 102-104, 107, 121, 149, 352-355,357-358,361,364,412, 420. See also Familiarity; Taking care At home (zuhau.se), 188-189, 276. See also Familiarity; Uncanny Attestation (Bezeugung), 234-235, 254,258,266,267fn,267-270, 279,288,295-296,300-302, 305-306, 309. See also Authenticity; Call of conscience; Potentiality of being Attunement (Befindlichkeit), 133-142, 144, 148, 160-162, 167-170, 177-191,195,209,220,251-254, 258-260,265,269-270,276, 295-296,328,335,339-341, 344-346,349-350,365,371.See also Facticity; Mood; Thrownness; Understanding Attunement (Gestimmtheit, Gestimmtsein), 135, 142, 340; being in a mood, 134; moodedness, 137, 252; attunedness, 138; being attuned, 148, 169, 277, 335. See also Mood Authentic (eigentlich), passim: Ang.st, 190; appropriation of untruth, 299; being of Da-sein, 44, 188, 191, 322; being-come-to-an-end, 239; being-guilty, 291; being-one'sself, 129, 184, 263, 268, 298; being-toward-death, 237, 260-267 (§53), 373; being toward oneself, 122; being-a-whole, 267; care, 122,
301, 323; certainty, 258, 308; coming toward, 330; constancy of the self, 410; disclosedness, 221, 297, 325, 331, 397; dying, 247; encountering of the un-handy, 73; existence: passim; existentiell possibility, 193, 267-270; face to face with thrownness, 348; "forthe-sake-of-which," 193; future, 329-330,336-338,348;grasping of a sign, 79; guilt, 287; hearing the call, 294; historicity, 382, 385-387,390-391,395-396; historiographical, 395; occurrence, 382, 385, 387; history, 386; maintaining oneself in a primordial possibility, 306; making present, 410; possibilities of existence, 383; possibility which has been, 394; potentiality-ofbeing, 233-235, 266, 267-301 (11.111) 322, 339, 343-344; potentiality-of-being-one's-self, 175, 322-323; potentiality-ofbeing-a-whole, 235, 266-267, 301-333 (II.m), 372; present, 338; handiness, 69, 106; repetition, 385; resoluteness, 308, 310, 313, 382; self, 129-130, 433 (Hegel); temporality, 327, 329, 331, 338, 348, 375, 385, 414; "there," 328, 347; time, 329; transparency, 298; truth of Da-sein, 297, 302; understanding, 146, 364, 279-280, 295,302,306,348,383,425 Authenticity (Eigentlichkeit), in its distinction from inauthenticity, 42-43,53,146,178,191,232, 259,268,304,306,325,331,335, 350, 410, 436; condition of possibility of distinction is in mineness, 42-43, 53; "really" versus genuineness, 142, 178; grounded in temporalizing of temporality, 304; are the fundamental existentiell possibilities, 350. See also
Lexicon Genuineness; Inauthentic; Mineness Autochthony (Boderutiindigkeit), 36, 168 (grounds to stand on). See also Dwelling; Rootedness Average, averageness (Durchschnittlich[keit]), 43-44, 127-129, 168-170; everydayness, 16, 50 n. 10, 53, 66, 121, 181, 189, 195,232,248,254,272,332,370; indifference, 43, 121, 232, 331; interpretedness, 170, 383. See also Everydayness; Interpretedness; Publicness Awaiting (gewiirtigen), 337-339, 341-343,347-348,350,353-356, 359-361,363,368-369,371, 390-391,406-410,412-414,416, 420-421, 425. See also Future Beginning and end (Anjang und Entk, said of Da-sein), 233, 238, 373, 424. See also the Between; Birth; Death Behavior, relation (Verhalten, sich verhalten: a middle-voiced verb translated as either "relates itself' or "is related," e.g. p. 52-53: "Da-sein is a being which relates itself understandingly in its being toward that being." In this ontological context, the term usually alludes to the relationship of being to being itself [Sich-zu-sich-selbst-verhalten, p. 4] in self-understanding or "self-evidence."): sich verhalten, 4, 7, 12-13, 15, 22, 41-42,44,52-53,86(to world), 108 (to beings), 113, 121 (to others), 124, 151 (foreto as-structure), 170 (understanding), 175 (behave), 193,219,227-228,236,250, 252-253, 260-262 (to death), 274,308,313,342,353, 404-405,437.
425
Verhalten, Verhaltung, 4-5, 7, 11, 16,59,69,79,97-98, 114,156, 176,192-193,196,199,211, 220,247-248,256,261-262, 265,282,289,297,300,309, 319-320,356-358,360-361, 370,387,392-393,401, 404-405, 420. See also Circle; "It is concerned in its being about ..."; Obviousness; Relation; Understanding of being; Understanding itself; the Upon-which Being, concept of (Beg;riff de.s Seins, Seinsbeg;riJI), 2-8, 4fn, 24, 39, 54 (as infinitive of "I am"), 54fn, 93 (as analogous), 100, 113, 128, 201, 333 Being, expression or word (Ausdruck [Wort] 'Sein '), 1, 4, 11 Being, idea of (Idee de.s Seins, Seinsidee), 13, 16, 96-97, 196, 201, 314,333,366,403,436-437 Being and becoming (Sein und Werden),243,430-434;"Become what you are," 145; ["Become what you can be"], 199, 305 Being and movement (Sein und Bewegung), 392 Being and seeming (Sein und Schein), 36 (semblance), 215 (transcendental illusion), 222 (illusion). See also Illusion Being and time (Sein und Zeit), 1, 17-19,23-26,39-40,235, 371-372,406,430-434,437 Being and truth (Sein und Wahrheit), 154,183,212-213,230,316,349, 357,420 Being as such (Sein als solches), 7fn, 85fn, 146, 187fn,207fn,230 Being in general (Sein ilherhaupt), 11, 13, 15, 17 + fn, 54fn, 183, 196,201,231,235,314-316, 332-333,372,389,403,406, 436-437
426
Being and Time
Being of beings (Sein des Seienden), 6-9, 11,27,37,37fn,201,212, 230, 333; as compartmental relation, 4, 437; difference between them, 38, 230. See also Difference, ontological Being- (with a prepositional or adverbial phrase attached): Being against one another (Widereinandersein), 121 Being alone (Alleinsein), 120-121 Being together with (Sein bei), 54-55, 107, 109, 119-120, 131, 141, 146, 148, 172, 181, 189, 192-193,196,202,211,220, 223,238,249-250,252,263, 298,311,317,322,326-328, 337,351-353,363-365, 406-408,413,419,422 Being already (Schon-sein), 194, 233fn 365 Being-already-together with (Schon-sein-bei), 61, 109, 277 Being-already-in (Schon-sein-in), 192-193,195-196,202,220, 249-250,277,317,327,365 Being-among-one-another (Untereinandersein), 128 Being as it is (Sosein), 5, 7, 14, 42 Being-the-basis (Grundsein), 282-285, 305. See also Guilt; Responsibility Being for one another (Filreinandersein), 121 Being-in (In.Sein, In-sein), 41, 52-59(§ 12), 105, 108, 110, 113, 118-119, 123, 130-180 (I.V), 186, 189-190, 193, 200, 202,220,297,350 Being 'in' one another ("In". einandersein), 54 Being "in on it" with someone (Mit-dabei-sein), 174 "Being in something" (Sein in ... ), 54 Being-in-the-world (In-der-Weltsein), 12fn, 13, 41 + fn
(historical), 52-62 (1.11), 104-110 (§ 23), 113-180 (I.V), 350-366 (§ 69), et passim. See also Being-in; World Being-on-the-scent (Auf-der.Spursein), 173 Being-one's-self, being-its-self (Selbstsein), 41, 113-130 (I.IVesp. 126-130, § 27), 131, 146, 176,184,263,267-268,270, 284-285, 298, 323. See also potentiality-of-being-one's-self Being out for ... (Aussein auf . .. ), 195, 210, 261-262. See also Directing oneself toward Being-something (Etwas.Sein), 160 Being toward (Sein zu): the beginning, 373; the Da-sein that has-been-there, 394; death, 235-267,301-302,305-307, 309-310,329,337,344, 348-349,373-374,386,390;the end, 234fn 245, 247, 249-252, 254, 255-260, 255 df., 265, 305, 317,329, 372-373, 424; being, 4, 121, 218, 222-225; God, 10, 190 n. 4; oneself, 124-125, 173, 177; others, 124-125, 177; possibilities, 148, 236, 261-264, 329; one's own most potentiality-of-Being, 188, 191-193,195,221,255,306, 325; a totality of relevance, 150; ways of comporting oneself, 211; what is brought near, 106; what is de-distanced, 106; what is heard, 155; what is indicated, 82; what is talked about, 168; the world, 57, 61-62, 106, 122, 177. See also Directing itself toward Being-with (Mitsein), 41, 113-130 (I.IV, esp. §§26, 27), 131, 142, 146, 161-164, 181, 193, 237-238,250,263-264, 270-272,280-283,288,298, 384,386,406,410
Lexicon
Belonging (hin-, zu-gehOren, sometimes implying hOren [hearing] and hOrig [obedient listening]), 65, 65fn, 68, 102-103, 109fn, 110-111, 126, 134fn, 163, 242-243,246,288,296,368, 378-381, et passim; regional, 102-103, 110-111, 368; ofworld time to Da-sein, 426. See also Dwelling "Between," the (das Zwischen), (55), 108, 132, 233, 373-374, 390. See also Beginning and End; Birth; Death "Beyond itself' ("ilber sich hinaus"), 192. See also Ahead-of-itself; Transcendence Biography (Biographie), 16, 247, 361 Biology (Biologie), 10, 28, 45, 49-50, 58,237,241,246-249,269,275 Birth (Geburt), 233, 373-374, 387, 390-391, 394; as "being toward the beginning," 373. See also Being toward the end; the Between; Death Body (Korper, generic), 91, 107, 198, 416. See also Corporeal thing Body (Leib, living, human), 29, 54, 60,96, 108,121, 147,346;and soul and spirit, 48, 117, 198, 368; as "figure" to fit, 70. See also Corporeality Botany (Botanik), 35, 46, 70 Brightness (Helle), 28, 350, 412. See also Clearing; Phenomenon Burden (Last), 134-135 (ofbeing), 134fn,284,299,371,345,385; disburden (entlasten), 122, 127-128, 268. See also the They Calculating (berechnen): versus circumspective estimating, 102, 106,111-112,258,261,294,307, 324, 418 n. 5, 420; as "reckoning" (Rechnen) with time, 71, 103, 235-236,333,371,404-405,409, 411-420, 422; logical, 159. See also Estimating
427
Calendar (Kalender), 370, 376, 407, 411, 418; astronomical, 71, 371, 411,418 n. 5 Call of conscience (Gewissensruf, Ruf des Gewissens), 269-280, 270fn, 287-289,293-296,300,307,317; 'It' calls ( 'Es' ruft), 275-278. See also Conscience; Es gibt Care (Sorge), 41, 57, 121-122, 126-127, 131, 171-174, 180-230 (I.VI), 231-236, 246, 249, 251, 252fn,254,259,265,270, 274-280 (§57), 284-289, 298, 300-301,303-306,310-333 (II.III), 334-335, 337, 344, 346, 350-354,359,364,367,369,372, 374,376,382,385,390,397,406, 411-412, 419, 424, 436; structure of, 192-196, 200, 259, 314-317, 323,327-328,331,350-351 (articulated by time); self-, 193, 318. See also Concern; Taking care Category (Kategorie), 3, 11, 16, 21-22, 63, 144, 211, 218 n. 34, 244 n. 3, 318, 320 n. 19, 322, 377; distinguished from existentials, 44-45,54-56,88,105,111, 118-119,188,241-242,399-403 (antic vs. historical); ontological, 65, 71, 78, 135, 143; in statements, 157, 165. See also Concept, fundamental; Existentials; Genus; Transcendental(s); Universal Certainty (Gewissheit): apodicticcognitive, 24, 136, 206, 257, 265, 362, 435 (Hegel); of the they, 177, 291-292; of death, 255-258, 264-266; of resoluteness, 302, 307-308; making certain (sich vergewissem), 265, 291, 293. See also Truth Change (Veriinderun~ Wechsel), problem of, 90-92, 97, 108, 114, 203-204,373-375,388-389,410, 412, 416, 423. See also Being and becoming
428
Being and Time
Change-over ( Umschlag): in moods, 134; hermeneutic to apophantic, 158; Da-sein to coq>se, 238; "practical" to theoretical, 357, 360-361, 364. See also Modification Choice (Wahl), 7, 21, 194, 285, 391; to be or not to be itself, 12, 42, 188, 287-288; of choice to be itself, 264, 268, 270, 383-385; of hero, 371, 385; of historian's possibilities, 394-397. See also Freedom; Resoluteness Christian theology/anthropology, 48, 190 n. 4, 199 n. 7, 229, 249 Chronology (Chronologie), 418-419, 423,427 Circle (Zirkel, Kreis): hermeneutical, 7-8, 152-153, 314-315; of cyclical time, 432 n. 30. See also Forestructure; Movement; Understanding Circumspection, circumspect ( Umsicht, umsichtig): the sight of taking-care, 69, 73-76, 79-83, 88, 102-108, 110-112,351-364,et passim; compared to considerateness, 123, 131; based on understanding's "sight," 146-147, 336, 358, 364, 412; is understanding as common sense, 146; c. interpretation, 148-149, 156-158, 359 (if-then); c. discovery, 172, 220, 228, 342, 353; c. calculation, 111-112, 258, 261, 294, 324, 333, 420; c. talk, 154-157,360-361,407-408.See also Common sense; Inteq>retation; Sight Circumstances (Umstiinde), as regarded by circumspection, 177, 300,338,359,379,382,384,389. See also Leeway; Location; Orientation; Place; Position; Relevance; Situation; Space Clearing (Lichtung, lichten), 133, 133fn, 153fn, 170,322fn, 350-351; cleared by ecstatic
temporality, 351, 408; Clearedness (Gelichtetheit), 147, 350-351, 408; cleared (gelichtet), 83fn, 133, 350-351. See also Disclosedness; Ecstatic unity; There; Understanding of being Clock (Uhr), 70-71, 376,404, 413-418,420-421 Close off (verschliessen), 23, 124, 132, 136, 141, 169-170, 173, 178, 184, 195,222,273,276,286,288,300, 306 n. 2, 308, 311, 339-340, 342, 347-348, 425. See also Cover up Co-attunement (Mitbeftndlichkeit), 116, 120 (attunement-with). See also Being-with; Communication Coming toward (zukommen, Zu-kunft), 325-326,329-330,336-337,341, 343, 347, 365, 395. See also Future Common sense (Verstiindigkeit), 292-294,299,309,329,342,395, 406, 422; related to understanding, 147, 315, 387-388; of the they everyday, 260, 269, 281, 288, 296, 311-312; is not ontologically transparent, 388. See also Circumspection; Heedfulness; Interpretation; Understanding; Taking care Communication (Mit-teilung, "sharing-with," 155, 162, 168), 32, 155-157, 160, 162-163, 168-169, 224,272,274,363,384.Seealso Being-with Come to be and pass away (entstehen und vergehen), 328, 330-331, 333, 338,420,423,425,430-431.See also Being and movement; Change Conceal, hide (verbergen), 2 (obscurity), 6, 20, 23 (Kant's art), 30, 35-36, et passim Concealment (Verborgenheit), 33, 36, 212, 219, 222; ofbeing, 35-36, 222, 260, 312. See accordingly the modes of concealment: Close off (verschliessen) Cover up (verdecken)
Lexicon Distortion, disguise (verstellen) Veil (verhiillen) Concept (Begrijj), 2-6, 4fn, 7fn, 10, 16,21,37-39,47,51,63-64, 150-152, 156-157,201fn,232, 311-316,360-364,etpauim; fundamental, 3-4, 9-10, 22, 39, 362, 397; formation of, 10, 39, 150-152, 157,219,312,349,375; of time, 17-18,26,235,304,326, 333,338,349,404-406,418,420, 426-428, 432. See also Being, concept of; Category; Existentials; Foreconception Concern (Fursorge, solicitude), 121-124,131,143,146,176, 193-194,238,253,263,266,268, 298, 300, 318. See also Being-with Concerned about (es geht um). See "It is concerned in its being about ... " Concrete, concreteness (konkret, Konkretion}, 1, 7, 9, 18-19, 26, 32, 34,36,39,43,52,78-79,82-83, 129, 131, 133, 140, 167, 178, 184, 187-188,191-192,194,209, 229-234,251-252,255,279,300, 302,311,335,366,382,393-396, 398, 399 n. 14, 431, 432 n. 30, 435. See also Totality; Whole Condition of possibility, (Bedingung der Moglichkeit}, 11 (a priori}, 13 (ontic-ontological}, 19, 37 (through hermeneutics}, 38, 53 (mineness as), 75 (unthematized world as}, 83 (reference as}, 85 (relevance as), 87-88, 103, 125, 145 (possibility), 193, 199 (care as), 204 (Kant on), 223 (project as), 226 (primordial truth as), 260, 263, 267, 280, 286 (being-guilty as}, 306 n. 2 (for state of corruption), 317 (care as), (324), 333 (primordial time as), 339, 347, 350-351 (temporal clearing as), 353,357,360,364-365(temporal horizon as), 367, 372, 375, 382,
429
385,413,417,419,424-425,430 (Hegel); Dasein as, 13, 38, 87-88; temporality as, 19, 324, 333, 350-351, 364-365 (of world, transcendence), 372 (of care), 417; ontic, 38, 85, 87-88; existential, 125,193,199,223,260,280,286, 339, 353, 357; ontological, 193, 223, 267, 306 n. 2, 350, 382, 385; existential-temporal, 34 7, 360, 365, 367, 375. See also Clearing; Ground; Horizon; Possibility; Temporality Connection (Zusammenhang): of time and the "I think," 24, 427 (Kant); existential-existentiell c. between anticipation and resoluteness, 267, 302, 305, 309; of care and selfhood, 318; of attunement and understanding in ecstatic unity, 340; between being and truth, 213 (original}, 349, 357, 420; of innerworldly beings with transcending world, 351-352; of in-order-to and for-the-sakeof in horizonal unity, 365; of spirit and body, 368; of life between birth and death, 372-390; of temporality, Dasein, and world time, 428; of time and spirit, 427-435 (Hegel). (Note: (Zusammenhang, a highfrequency word in German philosophy since Dilthey, in combination words is often translated hermeneutically as "context," as in "causal context," "life context" and "referential context.") Conscience (Gewissen), 234, 268-282, 270fn,286,296,298,300-301, 307,310-311,317,372,385,403 (Yorck); bad, 279, 290-293; call of, 269-274 (§56}, 274-280 (§57), 288-289,307,317;e~I,209;good,
430
Being and Time
Conscience (continued) 279, 281, 288, 290-293; public, 278, 403 (Yorck); universal, 278; voice of, 268-269, 271, 275, 278, 280, 290-292, 294, 300; wanting to have a, 234, 270-271, 288-289, 292,295-296,300,305,307, 309-310; world, 278. See also Call; Guilt; Resoluteness Consciousness (Bewusstsein); 49, 62, 115, 218,229,265, 278; of God, 269; of God, 269; of guilt, 281, 286; of reality, 211-212; of truth, 216; intentionality of, 363 n. 23; reification of, 46, 114, 437; transcending of, 201-202; Dilthey on, 205 n. 15, 209; Hegel on, 435, 437; Husser! on 47 n. 2; Kant on, 203, 319; Yorck on, 401-402 Considerateness (Rilcksicht, regard): the sight of concern/solicitude, 123, 125, 131; and other "sights," 146. ["with regard to ... "(mit Rilcksicht auf ... ), 178 (Da-sein's interpretation), 198 (its being), 201 (reality, the question of fundamental ontology), 213 (truth), 236 (fore-having of the whole Da-sein), 283 (being the basis of a lack), 314 (clarifying the hermeneutic situation), 327 (articulation of care's structure), 335 (its temporal sense), 369 (ecstatically arranged space), 374 (temporality), 398 (contemporary discussions), 407 (a calendar date), 413 (dating time), 426 (deriving now-time from temporality), et passim]. See also Light; Sight Conspicuousness (Auffallen), 46, 71, 73-75,80-81,104,107,111,121, 126,157,253,274,354-355,370. See also Modification; Obstinacy; Obtrusiveness; Reference
Constant, constancy (Stiindig[keit], Bestiindigkeit)), 117, 128, 291, 303, 320, 322, 332, 375, 417, 427 n. 13; existent "stand" of, 117, 322; and inconstancy ("dependency") of the self, 117, 128, 322-323, 332, 375, 390, 410; Descartes on the constancy of corporeal things, 92, 96; (objective) presence, 96, 98, 105fn, 320-321, 423, 427 n. 16; handiness, 103; the closest c. of Dasein, 128; the primordial c. of existence, 340; ahead-of-itself, 337; Being-guilty, 305; certainty, 308; resoluteness, 391; inconstancy, 117, 128, 336-337, 390-391. See al.ro Ancient ontology; Presence; Self Constitution (Veifassung, Konstitution), 8, 12, 13, 17, et passim; of being (Seinsverfassung), 10,12-13,15-16,20,53-58, 191-193, et passim; a priori (fundamental) existential, 53-58, 133-134,138-139, 145-149,et passim; temporal, 346: analyses of, 47 n. 2, 48; constitutive factors (moments), 41, 53, 92, 113, 131, 144, 146, 162-163, 172, 180, 190, 193,236,253,260,271,299,309, 316,328,362-363,376.Seealso Construction; Existentials; Structure; Whole Construction(s) (Konstruktion): of non-deductive genealogy, 11; against dogmatic, free-floating, arbitrary, 16, 28, 33, 36, 43, 260, 302-303; standpoint as, 61; isolated subject as, 109, 206; ontological, 197; phenomenological, 50 n. 10 (disclosive vs. aprioristic), 302-303,375-376,376fn(as project), 378 (existential); psychology, 399; mechanical, 400; of God's eternity, 427 n. 13; formal-dialectical, 435 (Hegel); Husserl's c. (Au.foau) of
Lexicon ontologies, 98fn. See also Constitution; Destructuring; Structure; Whole Copula (Copula, Kopula), 159-160, 349,360 Corporeal thing (Korperding), 54, 56, 90-92,97,106-107,117,238,361, 368. See also Matter Corporeality (Leiblichkeit): [an existential] directive of spatiality, 56, 108 Cover up, cover over; conceal, hide (verdecken, Verdecktheit), 10, 16, 21, 22,30,253-258,422-426,a passim; counter-concept to phenomenon, 36; obfuscation (Verdeckung), 58; tendency to, 256, 311 Crisis (Krisis): in fundamental concepts of the sciences, 9-10 Critical (kritisch): Kantian idealism, 38fn; epistemology, 156, 206; realism, 208 n. 16 (Hartmann); function of conscience, 279, 288, 290, 294; historiography, 396-397 (Nietzsche) Criticism, critique (Kritik), 167, 269, 401; of the "today," the "present," 22-23, 397; of phenomenology, 30; hermeneutic c. of Descartes' ontology of the "world," 95-101 (§22), 98fn; phenomenological c. of Kant's "Refutation of Idealism," 202-208 (§ 43a), 321 n. 20; of vulgar interpretation of conscience, 269, 295; conscience functions as, 279, 288, 290, 294; c. of Descartes is also that of Husser!, 98 fn. See also Destructuring; Phenomenology Cult (Kultus), 247, 313, 388, 400 Culture (Kultur), 21,51-52, 176, 178, 379, 395-396; philosophy of, 167 Curiosity (Neugier), 134, 170-173 (§ 36), 174-175,177-178,180,222, 271,273,277,310,346-348.See also "Just looking"; Looking
431
Da-sein (Dasein, being-there): is question of being, 7, 9; formally indicated, 11-16, 41-43, 53, 114, 116-117, 132, 151, 179,231, 313-315; its self-referentiality in the understanding of being (es geht ihm um sein Sein), 12, 14, 41-42, 44,52-53,133,179,191-193,228, 231,236,240,250,252,263,277, 284, 287, 325; its being is to exist [ex-sis, standa out], 12-13,42-43, 117, 126, 133, 143-144, 179, 262-263,276-277,280,284-285, 311,316,328-329,337,384,394; primordial occurrence of, 20, 384-385; word already hyphenated in first German editions (/line numbers 1-40), 55/26,132-134, 132/40(ofthe world), 142/35, 143/11, 160/26, 189/30,347/29,350-351, 365/22; hyphenated in marginal remarks (-fn), 7fn, 57fn, 58fn, 65fn, 87fn, 134fn, 183fn, 207fn, 214fn, 223fn; not hyphenated, 7fn,8fn,45fn,87fn, 134fn, 183fn, 207fn,234fn,240fn,316fn,317fn Datability (Datierbarkeit), 407-418, 422-424,427 Death (Tod), 104, 198, 233-234, 237-241 (§ 47), 240fn (and dying) 242, 245fn (as dying), 246-249 (§ 49), 249-252 (§ 50), 302, 306-308, 311,317,329,345,372-374, 382-387,390, 424-425; being toward, 234-267, 301-302, 305-307,309-310,329,337,344, 348-349,373-374,386,390; freedom toward (for), 266, 2\384-385. See also Anticipation; Being toward the end; Die, dying Deception, delusion (Tiiuschung), 33, 36, 62, 138, 146, 169, 274. See also Cover up; Distortion Dedication (Hingabe) to a matter, 136, 199, 347 (interested in), 354 (immersed in)
432
Being and Time
De-distancing (Entfernung, an existential: when unhyphenated, "removal"; Entferntheit= remoteness), 105-111, 105fn, 120, 132, 172, 27lfn (self-distancing), 299, 335, 361 ("removed"), 368-369. See also Directionality; Making room; Nearness; Remoteness; Spatiality Deduce (deduzieren), 20, 36, 182, 242, 289,301,314,340,367,377 Deficient (defzzient), 61, 121; mode, 20,57,73, 104,120-121,123-125, 336, 352, 355. See also Derivative; Indifferent mode; Privative Deformalize (Entformalisieren), 35, 241 Deliberation (Uberlegung), 187, 359-361. See also Praxis; Thematization; Theory Delivered over, entrusted (ilberantwortet), 21, 42, 134-135, 134fn, 144, 148, 167, 173, 188-189,192,251-252,254,259, 276, 284, 364, 383, 396. See also Abandon; Death; Surrender; Thrownness Demise (Ableben), 247, 251, 254, 257-259, 261. See also Death; End Demonstration (Ausweisun~ demonstrieren), ontological, 3, 4, 10 ("evidence"), 23, 26, 35, 46, 131, 140, 152 (grounding), 154, 211 (categorial and existential), 217 (as phenomenal connecting), 217-218 (of being-discovering of truth of statement), 218 n. 34 (as "identification" in Husserl), 220, 224, 311, 345, 430 (Hegel). See also Description; Exhibition; Interpretation Depersonalization (Entpersonalisierung), 48 De-presentifying (Entgegenwiirtigung), 391, 397: "ceases to make the today present," undoes it. See also Critique (of the present); Des tructuring
Derivative (abkilnftig, abgeleitet, Derivat; Herkunft): character of statement, 133, 153-160 (§ 33); sense of "certainty," 256; conception of guilt, 287; conception of time, 326, 329-331; conception of truth, 214, 219-226 (§ 44b), 256; kinds of understanding, 143, 147, 152, 160; underived character of Being, 4, 8; underived character of care, 182, 318; history as derivation (Herkunft) from the past, 378; et passim. See also Deficient; Privative Description (Beschreibung, Deskription), 35, 37, 63-64, 79-80, 111,117,122.158,194,209,269, 341, 399, 432; descriptive phenomenology, 35-37; as interpretation, 37, 272 n. 8. See also Demonstration; Exhibition; Interpretation; Phenomenology Despair (Verzweiflung): of sceptic's suicide, 229; as mood of havingbeen, 345. See also Angst; Fear Destiny (Geschick), 16, 19 ("vicissitudes"), 56, 379, 384-386, 395; authentic occurrence of a people or "generation," 384-385. See also Fate; Historicity Destructuring (Destruktion), 22-27, 39, 89, 392, (397). See also Critique; Construction; Phenomenology De-theologized (enttheologisiert), 49 Detrimentality, harmfulness (Abtriiglichkeit), 83, 140-141, 144, 185-186, 341. See also References of "in order to" De-worlding (Entweltlichung), depriving s. th. of its worldliness, 65, 75, 112-113.Seealso Modification Diaeresis (Diairesis), 159. See also Discourse; Negating; Statement Dialectic (Dialektik), 22, 286, 301; Platonic, 25; Hegelian, 171,
Lexicon
429-430, 432 + n. 30; transcendental, 215; formal, 229 Die, dying (Sterhen), 238-241, 240fn, 245 + fn, 247-255, 257, 259, 374, 424-425; "one dies," 253-255. See also Death; Being toward the end Difference ( Unterschied, Differem ): ontological, 4, 37fn, 56, 67, 94 + fn, 196, 208fn, 230 + fn; transcendental, 38-39, 208; transcendence-like {time and being), 39fn; being qua, 183fn; generic (Yorck), 399, 403. See also Being of beings; Indifference Directing oneself toward, being directed toward (Sichrichten-auf [nach]: middle-voiced formula for intentionality), 61-62, 128, 137, 181, 287; orienting oneself to time, 404, 411, 416, 419. See also Being out for; Intentionality; Knowledge Directionality (Awrichtung), 79, 102, 105,108-111,120,132,157,299, 335, 368-369; as "orientation," 96fn. See also De-distancing; Nearness; Orientation; Spatiality Disappear (verschwinden), 105, 244-245,251,342,357,375,379, 389. See also Concealment; Cover up Disavowal (Widerruj), 386. See also Repetition Disclosure (Erschlie.ssen), 10, 12-13, 20,26,38-39,50,67,86-87, 124-125, 129, 134-141, 144-146, 148, 151, 156, 162, 169-170, 162, 185,188,191,256,308,341,358, 396, et passim; is understanding, 86-87,142-153,170,263,265, 305. See also Understanding Disclosedness (Erschlossenheit: a "present perfect a priori," 85 + fn), 38, 75, 87, 110, 123, 132-137, 141, 143-149, 150-152, 160-162, 165-170, 173-175, 180-186, § 44 (truth), § 68 (its temporality), et
433
passim; as technical term, 75; Dasein is its, 133, 269; of being-in ("there") is Dasein's "clearing," 133, 170. See also Clearing; Light; There; Truth; Understanding of being Discourse (&de), 25-26, 29-30, 32-34, 37, 55, 57, 58+ fn, 85fn, 133, 143, 160-167 (§ 34), 168-170, 173-174, 180, 186-189, 220,223,269-273,277,295-296, 335,346,349-350,349-350(§ 68d), 406-408, 416,425. See also Call of conscience; Grammar; ,Wy~ Silence Discover(y), uncover(ing) (entdecken, Entdeckung), 3, 6, 14, 20, 25, 33, 36,45,55,58,62-63,65,69-73, 79-88, et passim; of things at hand, 69,73, 104,123,144,172,333, 408; of objectively present, 73, 158, 333, 356-364 {§ 69b); of work-world, 172; of a world, 62, 70-71,129,138,165, 194,413;of a "world," 110, 129, 203, 297, 312, 412; ofNature, 63, 70-71,81, 412-413, 415 n. 4; ofunusability, 73, 354-355; of relevance, 85-87, 297, 360; of with-world, 129; history of, 212; being-discovering {truth of statement), 218-220, 223-225, 228; circumspective, 73, 104-108,123,148,172,220,228, 312, 333, 351, 356, 364; scientific (theoretical), 351, 356-357, 360-364. See also Cover up; Modification Discoveredness (Entdecktheit), 85, 168,172,183,210,218-228,256, 264, 297, 363, 413, 420; truthterm reserved for beings that are not Da-sein, 85. See also Disclosedness; Resoluteness; Truth Dispersion, distraction (Zerstreuung): in a multiplicity of associations, 56, 67, 389-390; in the they, 129,
434
Being and Time
Dispersion, distraction (contintuJd) 273; of curiosity, 172, 347; of fugitive self-concealments by the call, 273, 310; in immediate affairs, 338, 371, 390; its source in inauthentic impatient present, 347. See also Ambiguity; Curiosity; Everydayness Dissecting (zergliedem ): inner self in curiosity, 178, 273; Dilthey's analyzing, 209, 399 Distance (Abstand, a category), 102, 105-108, 105fn, 122,126,269, 361, 369, 381. See also Dedistancing; Estimating; Famess; Nearness Distantiality (Abstiindigkeit, an existential): everyday space of being-with, 126-128. See also Averageness; Levelling down; Publicness Distortion, disguise (ver.stellen, Ver.stelltheit), 35-36, 58, 98, 124 (misrepresenting}, 132, 175, 180, 191, 222, 295, 302, 326; one kind of covering up, 36; disguise, 125, 129, 222, 274; See also Close off; Cover up Doxographical (dosographisch}, 23, 98,207 Drive (Trieb): a modification of care, 194, 210-211, 402. See also its four kinds: Predilection (Hang) Urge (Drang) Willing (Wollen) Wishing (Wilnschen) Dumb, mute (stumm), 164-165,296. See also Silence Duration (Dauer), 106, 409, 432 n. 30 "During," the (das "wiihrend," Wahren), 409. See also the Between Dwelling (Aufenthalt, sick aujhalten), 54, 61-63, 69 ("busy with"), 75, 80,88, 107,119,124,164,173, 188 ("at home"), 189 ("linger"), 261 ("dwell on death"}, 347
("stay"), 388 ("spends time with"), 422; as wohnen, 54, 188. See also At home; Being-in; Familiarity; Surrounding world Economics (Wirtschaft, okonomisch), 57, 361. See also Practical; Praxis Ecstasy (Ekstase), 329, 337-341, 349-350, 365-366. See also Eksistence; Rapture; Temporality Ecstatic (ekstatisch), 38fn (the), 133fn (ek-sistence}, 341 (open), 347 (modification, 348 (tendency, meaning), 366, 368, 369, 386 (open), 391, 408 (open), 409-410 (stretch), 411 (being-in-the-world), 422 (constitution), 423 (stretch}, 426, 437 (project of being in general); temporality, lOOfn, 329, 331,351,356,366,369,388,393, 408, 426, 437; mode of future, 330, 337, 424, 427; mode of present, 337-338; mode ofhavingbeen,339,343,345,427; -temporal, 345, 411; horizon, 346, 348, 365; -horizonal, 360, 365, 366,369,388,393,396,408,414, 419-420,422,426-427. Ecstatic unity (ekstatische Einheit), 329,335,338-340,342,346,349, 350-351,353,355,359,365,381, 408, 420-421, 423; temporalizes equiprimordial ecstasies, 329, 365; connecting attunement and understanding, 340; as unity of care-structure, it constitutes clearing of "there," 350-351, 408; ecstatic-horizonal unity, 360, 365-366, 396. See also Clearing; Horizonal schema; Temporalizing Eddying (Wirbel, hineinwirbeln), 178-179. See also Falling prey; Plunge Ek-sistence (Ek-sistenz), "standing out (Hinaw-stehen) and perduring (Aw-stehen) the openness of the there," 133fn; "being-held-into
Lexicon (Hineingehaltenheit) the nothing of the there," 7fn; standing-in (Instiindigkeit), 39fn, 223fn; standing-within (Innestehen) "the clearing of presence," 153fn. See also Ecstasy; Existence; Existing; Existentials Empathy (Einfilhlung), 124-125. See also Being-with Encounter (Begegnis, mode of: an existential structure), 31, 35-37, 7lfn (of handy), 119 (of of others), 142 (of fear), 252 (event of death). See also Phenomenal; Phenomenon Encountering (Begegnen, act of), 25, 44,55,56,58,61-76,79,81-88, 97,99,101-111,117-126,129, 137-138,140,142,147, 149,et passim; in dating public time, 404-423; letting [beings] be encountered (Begegnenlassen), 86, 104,111,137,170,264,326,328, 346, 354-356, 366. See also Making present End (Ende, endlm), 233-238, 241-246 (§ 48), 249-250, 259, 264, 305, 329, 373-374, 424, 426; being-atan-end, 238-242 Enigma (Riitsel): of the comporting of being toward beings, 4; of immanence and transcendence of knowing, 61; of how the relation of Da-sein to itself is to disclose the other as other, 125; of the that of Da-sein's there, 136, 148; of being and the everyday movement of occurrence, 371, 381, 387, 389, 392; of the imposition of a succession of nows "on" Da-sein, 425. See also Question of being Entangle(ment) (Veifallen: also "falling prey." See translator's note, 133 n. 3), 21, 22 (ensnared), 36 {fell back under cover), 133-134, 139, 175-180 (§ 38), 177 (ensnared), 181-182, 184-186,
435
189, 192-193, 195, 201, 254-255, 258-259,281,286,294,304,311, 322,328,331,335,367,369,389, 397, 406, 411-412, 426. See also Falling prey Entanglement ( Veifiingnis: an essential characteristic of falling prey), 67 (insidious), 173, 178, 180, 346-348 (tangled up). See therefore the related essential characteristics: Alienation; Temptation; Tranquillization Envisage (vergegenwiirtigen), 34 (bring to mind), 55, 248, 303 (reconsideration), 359 (represent), 393. See also Making present Epistemology (Erkenntnistheorie), 10, 59,156,183,206-210,213-216, 375,399,401 Equanimity (Gleichmut), 134, 345 Equiprimordial(ity) (Gleichursprilnglich[keit]), 13, 110, 114,131,133,137,141-3,146 (sights), 159-161, 168, 181, 191, 199,200,203-204,220,221-223, 229-231,256,270,286,297,298, 306-308,322,324,329(of temporality), (334), 337, 339-340, 350,355,365,368,372,377,381, 385. See also Ecstatic Unity Es geht um: See "It is concerned in its being about ... " Es gibt (there is, "it gives"), 7; handy things, 71; world, 72; being, 212, 230, 316; truth, 214, 226-228, 316; meaning, 325, time publicly, 411-412. See also Call of conscience ("It" calls); Give to understand; Givenness; "It is concerned in its being about"; Temporalizing Essence: Essenz, 117,233, 418; Wesen, 12,35,42,48-49,56, 121, 136-137,172,199,214,216,231, 298, 318, 323, et passim; statement of essence, 123; intuition of essence, 14 7
436
Being and Time
Essence (Wesen) as presencing (Anwesen, das Wesende, es west}, in the later marginal remarks (=fn): 7fn (as Da-sein), 39fn (Anwesen}, 85fn (wesen lassen}, 85fn (das Wesende}, 207fn (of being as such}, 234fn (of Dasein}, 235fn (An-wesenheit}, 268fn (of philosophizing); of truth,84fn,87fn, 227fn; ofthe human being, 87fn, 165fn, 252fn (as care}; essential (wesentlich}, 46fn, 105fn, 161fn_ See also presence Estimating (Schii.tun), 105-106, 369, 426- See also Calculating; Circumspection; De-distancing; Directionality; Nearness {bringing near) Eternal, eternity (ewig, Ewigkeit), 18, 106, 227, 229, 238 n_ 3, 381, 423, 437 n_ 13, 431 Ethics (Ethik), 16, 291 n_ 10 (Scheler}, 294, 316, 320-321 n_ 19 (Scheler}, 402 (Yorck). See also Presence, constant Ethnology (Ethnologie}, 51, 51 n. 11, 247 Eudaemonism (Eudaimonismu.s}, 293 Evade (ausweichen}, 93-94, 135-136 (disclosure}, 139, 253-260 (death}, 264, 322 (authentic potentiality) 342-343 (to forget}, 371 (daily dullness}, 391 (choice}, 425 {death). See also Being toward death; the They Event (Ereignis): of nature, 152; daily e. of death, 250, 253-254, 257; world, 273; passing and past world-historical, 284, 290, 378-379, 382, 389; in the later marginal remarks {=fn}, e. of the truth of archaic being, 38fn, 235fn (Appropriation); 189fn (Expropriation). See also Occurrence Everydayness (Alltii.glichkeit}, 16-17, 43-44,50-51, 117-125 (§ 26},
126-130 (§ 27), 166-180 (I.VB}, 181, 233-235, 252-255 (§ 51), 255-260 (§52), 332-335, 370-372 (§ 71), et passim; is temporality, 372 Everyone (Jedermann), 362, 370, 411, 413, 416-417, 425. See also Nobody; Time, public; the they Everywhere and nowhere (i.i.berall und nirgends} of curiosity, 173, 177, 347 ("inability to dwell"}. See also Curiosity Evidence, evident (Evidenz, evident), 59, 115, 125, 136, 218 n. 34 (Husser!), 265 (apodictic}, 288 (of attestation), 312 {of ontological project); of attunement is not apodictically certain, 136. See also Apophantic "as"; Attestation; Attunement; Demonstration; Intuition; Obviousness Evil (Ubel, noun}, 141, 248, 341-342 Evil (biise, adj.}, 286-287, 290-291 Exhibition, demonstration, showing, indicating (Aufweisung}, 6, 8, 12, 16, 72 (of phenomenon of world}, 130, 138, 147, 158-159 {"pointing out"), 179, 208 ("evidence"}, 213 (as apophansis), 223, 234, 272 n. 8 ("pointing out"), 301 ("set forth"}, 303, 311, 327 (of origin of inauthentic temporality}, 335, 341, 350, 358 of existential genesis of science), 428 (of origin of world time); phenomenological, 32-33, 35, 37, 53, 58, 66, 116 n. 1 (Scheler's "elucidation"); phenomenal, 115, 117, 267, 309, 311. See also Demonstration; Description; Interpretation Existence (Existenz}, passim; as formal indication, 12-14, 42-43, 53, 231-233, 313-315; "essence" of Da-sein is its, 42, 231, 298, 318, 323; "the substance of human being," 117, 212; is not substance, objective presence, reality, 12,
Lexicon 200-212 (§ 43), 267, 283, 303, 313-314,318,324,328,340,380, 436; "stand" of ek-sistence versus object's constancy, 117, 128, 133fn, 294, 322, 348, 436 (existing as primordial temporalizing); as understanding relationship to being, 12 + fn, 38fn, 44, 52-53, 123,133,179,193,212,231,284, 306,313-316,316fn,325-330, 336; idea of, 233, 313-314; antic factic ideal of, 266, 300, 310. See also Ek-sistence; Existing; Formal Indication; "It is in its being concerned about ..."; Mineness; Understanding of being Existence, philosophy of (Existenzphilosophie), 12fn, 436fn. See also Angst; Freedom; Self Existential (existenzial, a
437
categories, 44-46, 54-56, 88, 105, 111, 118-119,242;fundamental e.: 134 (attunement), 143 (understanding), 150, 160, 199, 297 (to be in the truth), 336; primordial: 161 (discourse). See also Category; Existence; Existing; Formal indication Existential analytic (existenziale Analytik des Daseins), 45, 50-52, 130, 139, 160, 181-182, 190, 199 n. 7,200-202,207-208,211-212, 231,234,247,303-304,331,345, 371-373,376,387,435;as ontological, 12-15, 43, 115-116, 310-316; as existential-temporal, 404, 406, 436. See also Fundamental ontology Existential-ontological (existenzialeontologisch), 117, 120, 207fn, 437, et passim Existential-temporal (existenzialzeitlich): analysis or interpretation, 234,333,351,356,367,404,406, 436; meaning, 337, 34;1, 370, 420; constitution, 340, 369, 417 n. 4; condition of possibility, 347, 360, 365, 375; structure of verb's types of action, 349; concept of world, 405 Existentiality (Existenzialitiit), 20, 38, 43,144,161,179,233-234, 311-312, 318, 322-323 as coherence of structures of existence, 12; as being in general, 13, 20; its explicata called existentials, 44; structured with facticity, 181, 192, 275, 328 ... and falling prey, 298, 316, 191, 193; versus reality, 212; "its primary meaning is the future," 327. See also Care Existentiell (existenziell), 12-13, 267-270 (§54), 305-310 {§ 62), et passim; distinguished from the existential, 12-16, 325fn. See also Existential; Ontic
438
Being and Time
Existing (Existieren), 12-13, 43, 53 (formal indication), 106, 117, 136, 146,165,212,264,281-287,291, 298 (resolutely), 299, 303, 306, 308,312,325,3280330,333-337, 346,350,353,356,364-365,367, 370-371,373-374,376,379-384, 386-391,395-397,404,406, 410-412,415,419,425,436-437; as difference emerging out of everyday indifference, 43, 53, 192, 232; and con-stancy, 117, 128; as self, 130; as having to be, 134, 276, 300; (way of) being of Da-sein is, 143, 263, 283; as for-the-sake-ofwhich, 143, 146, 236, 334, 336, 359, 364; factically, 179, 181, 191-192, 251-252, 276; as outstanding, 233, 236, 243, 245-246, 329 (finitely); as authentically whole, 234, 242, 373; as being toward death's possibility, 255, 259, 261-262; selfness as a way of, 267; versus objective presence (substance, reality), 267, 283, 303, 324, 328, 380; is its potential-to-be, 270, 295; is primarily futural, 337; is primordial temporalizing. See also Ek-sistence; Existence; Existentiality; For-the-sake-ofwhich; Formal Indication; Indifference Expecting (Erwarten), 119, 156, 195, 205,246,248,261-262,269, 274-275,294,337,339,341-343, 345, 353, 355. See also Future Experience (Erlebnis: lived experience), 46-49, 114, 119, 130, 136,181,194,214,247,251,265, 269,279,291-293,340,344,355, 373-374,387-388,390-391,400; living through the experience (Erleben), 4 7; stream of experience, 194, 344, 388. See also Life Experience (Eifahmng: learning encounter), 22, 59, 82, 91, 97, 99-100, 150, 155, 158, 171, 176,
183,185,201,204,224,234-239, 243,279,286,292-295,304-306, 318-319, 324,425, et passim; fact of, 257; of conscience, 291-292; in the later marginal remarks (=fn), 207fn (existential-ontological), 270fn ("the experiencing of this Being"). See also Encountering Explanation (Erkliimng), 119, 128, 143,196,207-208,215,220,269, 271,278,336,352,390,399-402 (Yorck); versus understanding, 143; as understanding discovery of unintelligible, 336. See also Intelligibility; Understanding Explicitness (Ausdrilcklichkeit), 12, 71, 126, 129, 141; the "as" is structure of, 149. See also Interpretation Expressing (Ausdrilcken, but esp. the verb Aussprechen), 149, 155, 161-165,167-168,222-225,271, 406-411,414,417,421-422,et passim; itself, 162, 168, 222-225. See also Understanding itself Expression, expressedness (Awgesprochenheit): relation between discourse and language, 155, 167-168, 224-225. See also Interpretedness External world (Awsenwelt), 201, 202-208 (§ 43a), 211, 273. See also Proof Extreme: See instead Most extreme Fact (Faktum), 5, 18, 56, 66, 79, 148, 152,168,179,190,225,254, 268-269,276,287,296,310,328, 371,382,387,392-393,428 Fact (Tatsache), 56, 179, 229, 254, 257-258,268-269,290,293,328, 362,394-395,398,404,apassim Factical (faktisch), 145-146, 179, 192, 221,229,251-252,256-257, 259-260,263-264,266,269,276, et passim Facticity (Faktizitiit), 56, 59, 72 n. 1, 120, 128, 135, 145, 179, 181,
Lexicon
190-193,222,229,231,250,252, 275-276,284,298,314,316,328, 348, 350, 404; and existentiality, 181,191-192,221-222,231, 249-250,276,284-285,328,364. See also Attunement; Historicity; Having-been; Thrownness Factual (tatsiichlich), 56, 135, 229, 276, 315, 394, et passim; versus factical, 56, 135, 229 Factuality (Tatsachlichkeit), 56, 135, 269,276,284,315,348,354 Faith (Glaube; glauben=believe), 10, 180, 190 n. 4, 205-206 Falling Prey (Verfallen, also entanglement. See translator's note, 133 n. 3.), 175-180 (§ 38), 185-191,193,195,206,221-222, 231,250-252,254-255,269-270, 277,284-286,293,294,298, 313-314,316,323,328,338,345, 346-349 (§ 68c), 350, 369, 378 (fall), 436; See also Entangle(ment) Familiarity (Vertrautheit), 104, 142, 274; with the world (its significance), 54, 76, 86-87, 110, 123, 188, 342, 354; with itself as the they-self, 129; everyday, 189; ontically nearest as familiar (bekannt), 43, 371, 405, 408. See also Obviousness; Reference; Uncanniness Famess, distance (Feme, a category), 105 + fn, 107-108, 140, 172; conscience calls from and to, 271. See also De-distancing; Distantiality (an existential); Nearest/Farthest; Nearness Fate (Schicksal), 166, 384-392, 394-395, 410, 435. See also Destiny; Historicity Fear, fearing (Furcht,filrchten), 133, 140-142 (§ 30), 182, 185-186, 189, 190 n. 4, 251, 254, 266, 341-345. See also An~t; Attunement
439
Feeling (Gefiihl), 109, 138-139, 142, 249 n. 6, 271, 342, 400 (Yorck); Emotion, 266fn. See also Affect; Mood
Find oneself (sick finden: as related to sich befinden-finding oneself attuned), 119, 128-129, 135, 144, 268, 271, 328, 340. See also Attunement; Thrownness Finiteness, fmitude (Endlichkeit), 93, 264,329-331,348,384-386,413, 424-425. See also Being-towardthe-end; Situation boundary Flight (F1ucht), 44, 134-135, 184-186, 189,192-193,251-255,258-260, 276,278,310,322,340,348,390, 424-425 For-the-sake-of-which, the (das Worumwillen), 84, 86-88, 111, 123, 129, 143, 145-147, 181, 191-194,228,236,297-298,327, 333-334,337,347,359,364-365, 412,414 For-one-another (Fureinander), 121-122, 175. See also Against; Being-for; Being-with; Concern; Liberate Fore-having (Vorhabe), 150-151, 153, 157-158,232-234,236,268,290, 311, 316, 323, 372. See also Circle; Having Fore-sight (Vor-sicht), 80, 150-151, 153,156-158,232-233,257,311, 316. See also Sight Fore-structure (Vor-Struktur), 151-153. See also As-structure; Circle; Interpretation; Understanding Forget (vergessen), 21, 44, 62, 219, 262,277,292,322,339,341-345, 347-348,350,354,369,388,391, 406-407,409-410,424-425,d passim; Forgottenness Vergessenheit), 2, 21, 339, 342, 350 (of having-been versus its repetition). See also Remembering; Retrieve; Retaining
440
Being and Time
Formal (formal), 27, 88, 147, 159, 241, 248, 255, 277, 325, 435, et passim; structure of question, 5-8; concept of phenomenon, 31, 35; sense of phenomenological research, 34; sense of constitution of existence, 43; idea of existence, 53, 179, 314; existential expression, 54; -universal relational character, 77-78, 159-160, 208, 215; idea of worldliness, 82; system of relations, 88; intuition, 112; phenomenology of consciousness, 115; -existential totality, 192; -dialectical argumentation, 228-229,236,314,432-435; structure of end and totality, 241, 373; not-yet, 244; objects, 265; way to exist, 267; existential idea of "guilty," 283, 285-286; ethics of value, 293-294; structure of understanding of Da-sein, 313; structure of representation, 319; indifferent "ahead of itself," 337; "in the face of which" and "about which," 342; -dialectical concept of time and spirit as negation of a negation, 432-435. See also Formal Indication Formal Indication (/ormale Anzeige), (43), 53, 114, 116-7, 132, 179, 231, 313-315; called provisional i. (vorliiufige Anzeige), 14, 16, 41; phenomenal i., 188. See also Demonstration; Description; Exhibition; Interpretation; Phenomenology Formalism (Formalismus), 9, 291, 320, 400 Formality (Formalitiit), 248 Formalizing (/ormalisieren), 22, 77-78, 88,147, 159,208,283,432-433; deformalized, 45, 241 Found (fundieren), 11, 13, 31, 49, 54, 56-57,61-63,71,75,82,87,96, 98, 102, 109-110, 150, 172, 181-182,185-186,202,211,223,
225,242,245,247,291-292,297, 323,334,337,340,343,345,350, 355-356,359,366-369,389,394, 405,410,417,423,436;founding connections,62, 138-139,201, 211, 225, 432; laying the foundations, 249 n. 6; See also Demonstration; Exhibition; Fundamental analysis; Fundamental ontology; Ground Foundations (Fundamente), 4, 9-10, 22,24,26,48-51,83,89,92, 95-96, 129, 139, 150, 153, 155, 157, 160, 164, 165 (in .Wr~). 171, 197,199,209-210,214-215, 219-220,223,228,233,252, 268-272,299,304,319,335,373, 397-398,417-418,435; existential, 153, 157, 268; existential-ontological, 270 + fn (are a horizon). See also Ground; Horizon Free, freedom (/rei, Freiheit): for authenticity or inauthenticity, 188, 268fn, 191, 195,232,344;for Being-guilty, 288; for the call of conscience, 287; for care, 122; for death,264,266,384-385;for freedom of choice, 188; for oneself, 122; for possibilities, 191, 193, 199,264,285,312,344;for one's ownmost potentiality-forBeing, 144, 191; for repetition, 385. See also Liberate Free (/reigeben, verb), 83-86, 85fn, 104, 110-111, 118, 120-123, 129, 141,144,227,264,297-298,310, 313,343,363 Free-floating (jreischwebend), 9, 19, 28, 36,123,144,156,272,276,279, 298,309,325,339,388,424 Fulfillment (Eifilllung) of intentional project of meaning, 31, 52, 76, 97, 151, 153, 191-192, 195, 320 n. 19, 326, 343. See also Directing-itselftoward; Meaning; Significance; the Upon-which
Lexicon Function (Funktion), 80, 106, 157-158,160-161,182,190,202, 289-293,310,332,340,349,368, 379, 415, 436; functional concepts, 88. Fundamental analysis (Fundamentalanalyse): of Dasein, 39,41, 131,181,184,213,230, 231-235; equated with analytic of Dasein, 213; ontological f. a. of "life" (Dilthey), 210; as preparatory, 231; of being, 360. See also Existential analytic Fundamental ontology (Fundamentalontologie), 13-14, 19, 37,38fn, 131, 143fn, 154, 182-183,194,196,200-202,213, 232, 235fn ton. 6, 268, 301, 310, 314,316,377,403,405-406, 436-437; related to genealogy of being, ( 11 ). See also Ontology; Phenomenology Future, futural (Zukunft, zukilnftig), 20,141,325-330,336-348,350, 360,365,378,381,385-387,391, 395-397,410,423-427,431.8ee also Being-ahead-of-itself; Coming toward; For-the-sake-of-which Genealogy (Genealogie) of being, 11 Generation (Generation), 20, 28, 377, 385, 385 n. 8. see also Destiny; Handdown; Heritage; Historicity; Tradition Genesis (Genesis): ontological, 68, 357, 362, 392; existential, 171, 358; of reference, 68; of science, 171 (Aristotle), 358; of theoretical beha~or,357-358,360-362;of
historiography as science out of historicity, 392; of vulgar concept of time, 420. See also Origin; Primordiality; Temporalizing Genuine (echt, genuin), 95-96, 127, 165, 168-169 (understanding), 173-174,177-178,234,237,239, 279, 303, 317 (-existential), 333,
441
372, 374, 421, et passim; versus authentic, 142, 146; inauthentic as, 146, 148, 326. See also Authenticity; Inauthentic Genus (Gattung), 3, 14, 37fn, 38, 42, 77, 128, 433 (Hegel); generic, 399, 403; being is not a, 3, 14, 38; Dasein is not a, 42, 128; relation, as formal, is not a, 77. See also jeweiligkeit; Mineness; Transcendentals; Universal Geographical (geographisch), 70, 80, 103 Geometry (Geometrie), 68, 112 Give to understand (zu verstehen geben), 148, 267, 269-271, 279-280, 287, 296. See also Call of conscience; Givenness Given(ness) (Gegeben[heit]; Gebung), 36,68,115-116,129,191,237, 265,271,279,280,284,309,401, et passim; (self-)gi~ng, 115-116, 216; gi~ng meaning, 324-325; "gi~ng" of surroundings (Gebe der Umgebung), 58fn. See also Call of conscience; Es gibt; Give to understand; Thrownness God (Gott), 10, 24, 28, 48-49, 49 nn. 7, 9; 92f, 95, 190 n. 4, 199, 269, 275, 291, 427 n. 13. See also Theology Grammar (Grammatik), 39, 119, 165, (349, of verb). See also Discourse; Logic; Rhetoric Greeks,25-26,28,33-34,39,68, 165,170-171,219,222,225,358, 378 Ground (grilnden, begriinden, verb: sometimes "found"), 8, 10, 14, 16 ("rooted"), 36, 43, 50, 60-61, 89, 112,203,256,284,286,299,303, 327-329, 362, et passim; in ecstatic unity of temporality, 327-329, 332,335,340,342,344-346, 348-351,353-355,359-360, 363-369,379-380,382,436,et passim; science as grounded
442
Being and Time
Ground (verb) (continued) coherence of true statements, 11, 357, 362. See also Found Ground (Grund, noun), 8, 32,34-36, 152-153,206-207,228,234,236, 257, 278, 332, et passim; laying or exhibiting the, 8, 10; of Da-sein in ecstatic temporality, 300 337, 351, 356 ("basis"), 374, 386, 396 (basis), 397, 436 (basis); being the ground of a not or nullity, 282-285,305,325,348;as horizon, 339, 366, 436 (Note that the common idiom, auf Grund des, on the basis of, is often translated here as "because of, on account of, due to, as a result of."). See also Foundation; Guilt; Horizon; Responsibility Groundless (bodenlos), 21, 168-170 (idle talk), 177-178 {public interpretedness), 312, 320 n. 19, 330, 401-402 (thinking). Guilt, guilty (Schuld, schuldig), 242, 269-270, 279, 280-289 (§ 58), 290-293,295-297,301,305-307, 306 n. 2, 311,317,325,372,382, 385, 400; translator's note, 269 n.4. See also Conscience; Resoluteness Hammer (Hammer), 69-70, 78, 83-84, 109, 154-155, 157, 360-361 Hand down, over (Uberlieferung), 21, 166,379,383-387,390-391,395. See also Fate; Repetition; Tradition; Transmission Handiness (Zuhandenheit), 69, 71-74, 76,79-80,82-85,87-88,100-104, 118,121,154,158,183,187,201, 211, 230, 356, 364; thing at hand (Zuhandenes), 69-88, 102-112, et passim; h. translating Handlichkeit: See also References of "in order to" Have been, having-been (Gewesen[heitf), 85fn, 326-329,
337-346,348,350,360,365,381, 385-387,391,393-397,410,427; have-been-there (da·gewesen ), 380-381,385-386,393-397; having-been-in-the-world, 394; beas-having-been, 326, 350, 385, 391, 396, 410. See also Ecstatic unity; Past; Repetition Have to be (zu sein haben, said of Dasein), 12, 42fn, 134-135, 244, 276, 284-285, 300. See also Facticity; "That I am"; Way to be Have to do (zu tun haben, said in regard to things), 48, 56, 61, 79, 125,149,158,160, 172,351.See also Association(s) Having, possession (Habe(n), translation of ovma), 58fn, 95 (being), 233 (whole being of Dasein), 351 (something); meaning, 151, 154, 324, 361; time, 404, 409-410,418-419,422,425.See also Fore-having "Having" ("Haben" in scare quotes): its environing world, 57-58, 58fn; a history, 378, 382,417 Hearing (Hiiren), 33, 107 (distance sense), 161, 163-165, 168, 271, 277; as understanding, 163-165, 183fn, 287, 296; potentiality for, 163, 165, 271fn; the call of conscience, 269, 273-275, 279-281,287,292,294-296.See also Call of conscience; Discourse; Listening; Reticence; Silence; Understanding Hearsay (Hiirensagen), 155, 169, 173, 224. See also Ambiguity; Curiosity; Idle talk Heedful (Besorgendes, adj.), 352. See also Taking care Heedfulness (Besorgen, also "taking care"), 72-73, 79-81, 83, 85, 88, 103, 106-108, 111, 129, 136, 352-353,355,357,360-361,372, 380, et passim. See also Associations; Circumspection;
Lexicon
Practice; Taking care; Useful things "Here," the (das Hier), 107, 119-120, 132, 186,369,417. See also There Heritage (Erbe), 383-386, 390-391. See also Handing down; Retrieve; Tradition Hermeneutical (hermeneutisch): discussion of Descartes's ontology of the "world," 89, 95 (title of§ 21); -existential "as," 158-1159, 223; situation, 232-233, 235, 304, 310 (title of§ 63), 314-316 (circle of pre-suppositions), 397; conditions for a "description," 272 n. 6; psychology, 398; foundation out of "life itself," 398. See also Asstructure; Circle; Destructuring: Fore-structure; Understanding Hermeneutic(s) (Hermeneutik), 25, 37-38 (in four senses), 72 n. 1 (of facticity), 125 (of empathy), 138 (as rhetoric), 398 (psychological), 436 (in three senses); of the .1!.6roq, 25, 37, (158-160); ofDa-sein, 37-38, 72, 436; as universal phenomenological ontology, 37-38, 436; as analytic of existence, 38, 436; as historicalhumanistic methodology, 38, 398; of the everydayness of being-withone-another (=rhetoric), 125, 138. See also Analytic; Interpretation; Ontology; Phenomenology; Philosophy; Rhetoric Heroes (Helden), 371, 385. See also Ideal, antic; Repetition Historian (Historiker), 152, 393-394, 396, 400-404 (Ranke, Yorck, et al.). See also Historiography; World history Historicality (Historizitiit, said of historiography), 20 Historicism (Historismus), 396 Historicity (Geschichtlichkeit) of history as occurrence of Da-sein, 10,19-22,38,197,234-235,
443
332-333,361-362,375-382, 385-399,401-404,409-410,415, 417 n. 5, 418, 435; inauthentic, 376, 387-391. See also Destiny; Fate; Forgetting; Hand down; Have-been (-there); Occurrence; Repetition; Tradition Historiography (Historie), 10, 20, 38, 152-153,235,332,361 (biography), 375-378, 386, 392-397 (§ 76), 398, 400-402, 415,418 (chronology); of things at hand,361,380-381,388-389; science of, 375, 378, 395, 404; kinds of, 396-397. See also World history History (Geschichte), 9-10, 19-24, 372-382,386,388,391,399,417, 418 n. 5, 426, et passim; of useful things, works, culture, spirit, and ideas, 395; of the human sciences, 398; of literature, 10, 397; of ontology, 19-26 (§ 6), 39; of philosophy, 392; of the present, 393; of problems, 10, 23, 249 n. 6; of the sciences of man, society, and state, 398; of the spirit, 395, 397; of the uncovering of the apzai, 212; of what-has-beenthere, 395; of the word 'cura', 199; of the word .lt6yoq, 32; of the word 'phenomenology', 28; philosophy of history, 402 (Yorck); natural history, 388; world, 19-20, 332, 377,381-382,387-395,428 n. 17, 434 (Hegel); having a history, 378, 382, 417; making history, 378; Hegel on history, 428, 434, 436; Yorck on history, 400. See also Historicity Hope (Hoffnung), 236, 345. See also Anticipation; Future Horizon (Horizont), 19,31 (of Kant's problem), 39fn (as such overcome), 86 (freed by analyses), 98 (beyond Descartes), 209 (foundations
444
Being and Time
Horizon (continued) and), 270fn (instead of "foundations"), 365 (as whereupon of disclosure), 368 (transcendent versus specific), 421 (as "according to which," Ka-ra) Four major ambits of the term "Horizon" (Horizont), ordered roughly according to descending comprehensiveness: A. (Time as the transcendental) Horizon of(any and all) understanding of being, 1 (statement of provisional aim of treatise), 5,17, 26, 38fn (is transcendence as the ecstatic), 39, 41, 92 (of constant presence), 235 (of time), 314 (of idea of being as existence), 423 (that gains access to world, significance, and datability), 437 (time as h. of being); of intelligibility of being, 100, 231 B. 1. Horizon of Temporality (comprehensive): of temporality as ecstatic unity, 365; of whole of temporality determines the whereupon of disclosure, 365; of temporal constitution of Da-sein, 374; offacticity and thrownness, 383; horizons of earlier and later, and the dock-usage that makes present, 408, 421; of time-reckoning, 411-412; to gain access to world, significance, and datability, 423; of world time, 436; ecstatic h., 346, 348,365 B. 2. Horizon of temporality (specific dimensions): of
expectation, 337; of remembering, 339; of awaiting retaining, 360-361, 407; of future, 365, 421 (of now-not-yet); ofhavin~been,365;of
the present, 365; of disclosed world and specific h. of whereto of region, 368 C. Nearest (interpretive) Horizon of Average Everydayness: 50 n. 10, 66, 167, 175 (of structures of the being of Da-sein already obtained), 292-293 (where voice of conscience is "experienced"), 371 ("natural"), 376; of everyday understanding of being: 92 (of constant presence), 201 (of traditional concept of being), 294 (of vulgar understanding and interpretation of time), 427 (of vulgar concept of time) D. Horizon of Research and Investigation progressively indicated in and for this treatise (miscellaneous formulations): 1. interrogative: 26, 37 (for further ontological investigation), 45 (of question ofbeing), 166 (to understand language), 390, 437 (of question and answer) 2. phenomenological: disclosed by Husser!, 51 n. 11 3. ontological: 116, 194, 289 (for interpretation), 293 (appropriate for analysis of conscience), 320 n. 19 (of inappropriate ontology of objective
Lexicon presence), 377, 387, 422 (of idea of objective presence) 4. phenomenal: 167,271, 334 5. of interpretation: 168, 223,289, 6. conceptual: inappropriate "categorial," 322; of a clarified being of the beings unlike Da-sein, 333 See also Foundation; Ground; Light ("in the light of"); Schema; Understanding of being Horizonal (horizontal): leeway, 355; unity, 360, 366, 396; schema(ta), 365; structure of having-been, 365; unity of schemata, 365; constitution of the ecstatic unity, 365,408,414,419,422,426; phenomenon of the Moment, 427 "How," the (das Wie), 27, 34-35, 218-219,224,348,370 "How one is" ("Wie einem ist"), 138, 188, 340. See also Attunement; Facticity; It is concerned in its being about ... ; It "knows" where it itself stands; Thrownness Human sciences, humanistic disciplines (Geisteswissenschaften ), 10,38,46,129,376,397-399 I, the (das lch), 4lfn (in each case "I"), 87fn (egoistic), 109 + fn (egotism}, 114-119,316-323,318fn,319fn, 332, et passim; as subject, 22, 179, 317, 322; as the "who" ofDa-sein, 114-115, 129,267,313,317,322; abstract, 401 (Yorck); isolated, 116, 118, 179, 298; pure, 229; worldless, 316; 1-here, 119, 132; 1hood (/chheit), 116, 318, 323; 1Thing (/chding), 107, 119; the "I am": (das "ich bin"), 24, 54, 129, 211,278,297,317,321, 381; I amas-having-been: ich bin gewesen,
445
326, 328, 339; l-am-in-a-world, 211, 321; I take action, 319; I think, 24, 319-321, 427; the givenness of, 46, 115-116, 129, 265; the not-1, 116, 433; saying "I," 318-319,318fn,321-323; Descartes on, 46, 95, 98; Hegel on, 433-434; Humboldt on, 119; Kant on, 109, 318-321, 320 n. 19; the "I" and the Self, 129-130, 317-23, 348. See also cogito sum; Mineness; Self; Subject Ideal (Ideal, ideal), 153 (scientific strictness), 156 (validity), 216-217 (content of judgment), 229 (subject versus factic "subject," Dasein), 266 (of existence), 280 (potentiality-of-being individualized in this particular Da-sein), 285 (versus lack of nullity); of existence (Existenzideal), 266, 300; factical existentiell ontic ideal [Heidegger's], 266, 300, 310. See also Existentiell, versus existential; Ontic, versus ontological Idealism (/dealismus), 34, 39fn, 183, 203-204, 206-208, 320 n. 20 Idle talk (Gerede), 134-135, 165, 167-170 (§ 35), 173-175, 177, 180,222,252-253,255,271,277, 296, 346. See also Ambiguity; Averageness; Publicness "If-then," the (das "wenn-so"), 359. See also Schema Illusion (Schein, also "semblance"), 52, 174, 195, 204-205 (Kant's proofs), 215, 222, 257, 292, 369; as semblance, 29-32, 36, 176 Immanent (immanent), 9, 60, 136, 144, 181, 216, 326; scientific crises, 9; versus transcendent, 60, 326; reflection, 136; (self)perception, 144, 181; consciousness of truth, 216; time, 326. See also Experience (Erlebnis); Transcendence
446
Being and Time
Imminent (bevorstehend), said of event ofdeath,250-251,257,264,353 Impossibility ( Unmoglichkeit), 250, 255,262,265-266,306,308,329, 342-343; of experiencing Da-sein ontically as an existing whole, 236; death as possibility of i. of Da-sein pure and simple (existence as such), 250, 262, 306, 329; of reversing time, 426. See also Nothingness; Nullity; Possibility In itself (an sich, an ihm selbst), 16, 28, 30-31,69,71,74-76,87-90,94, 106, 112, 116, 118, 169, 191, 201-202, 207, 209, 209 n. 17, 212-213,218,227-228,264,288, 329,354,380-381,400,405,419, 424-426, 435; ecstasy an "in and for itself," 329. See also Outside-ofitself In-order-to, the (das Um-zu), 68-69, 74,78,82,86-88,149,192,261, 355, 364-365, 414. See also Forthe-sake-of-which; Reference( s); Relevance In the face of which, the (das Wovor), 140,142,184-188,191,251,255, 266,339,342-343,365.Seealso the About-which; Angst; Fear Inauthentic (uneigentlich): and genuine, 127, 142, 148, 168, 177-178, 326 (derivative); inauthentic versus ungenuine, 146; and non-authentic, 176; Angst, 189; awaiting, 435; Being of Dasein, 43-44,53, 128, 175-178, 191,193,233,268,285,304,331, 335, 350, 390; Being-ahead-ofoneself, 195; Being-in-the-world, 179; Being-toward-death, 252, 259-260, 264, 373; Being-a-whole, 331; disclosedness, 325, 331; everydayness, 178; existence, 232, 328,376,387,410,425,436; future, 337, 343, 347; having-been, 339, 345; historicality, 376, 387,
390-391, 396; interpretation, 281, 331; possibilities of concern, 347; potentiality-for-Being-a-whole, 331; present, 338, 347; self, 181, 332; temporality, 326, 329, 331, 341, 424; "they," 179, 332; theyself, 181, 303; time, 329; understanding, 146, 148, 254, 326, 337-339. See also Authenticity; Genuineness Indebtedness (Verschuldung), 284, 287-288,290-293,300,306n. 2, 307. See also Guilt Indefiniteness (Unbestimmtheit): of the call of conscience, 273-274, 278-279; of the caller, 274-275, 280; of death and its "when," 253, 258-260,263,265,308;ofthatin the face of which one is anxious, 186-187; of Da-sein's potentialityof-Being, 298, 308; of resoluteness, 298; of the self to which the appeal is made, 274; of the self which takes care of things, 322; of the understanding of being, 5; of what Da-sein finds itself together with in uncanniness, 188; of what one's drive and will are out for, 210 Indeterminate Immediate
(unbestimmtes Unmittelbare), 3 Indicating (Zeigen, said of signs), 77-82, 215. See also Formal indication (Anzeige) Indifference (Gleichgilltigkeit), 42, 121, 123-124, 134, 144, 175, 243-244,254-255,265,280,342, 345,352,358,361,386,429-430; liberty of, 144 Indifference (Indifferenz), 43, 53, 121, 123-124, 160, 169, 192, 194, 208-209,212,232,252,263,270, 283, 295, 323, (324), 331, 337, 352, 389; called averageness, 43, 121, 232, 331. See also Absorption; Averageness; Formal indication; Lostness
Lexicon Indifferent mode: versus deficient mode, 120-121,123-124,232, 352. See also Deficient; Derivative Individualize, individuate (vereinzeln), 39, 142, 146fn, 187-189, 191, 263-266,276-277,280,295,307, 310, 322, 336, 339, 343; principle of individuation (Individuation), 38. See also Angst; Self lnfmite (unendlich), 92-93, 106, 330-331, 424-425, 427 n. 13; inauthentic temporality as infinite, 331. See also Finite; Infinitive (lnfinitiv) of being, 54 + fn. See also Grammar "initially and for the most part," (zuniichst und zumeist), 6 ("at first"), 16, 21, 35 (hide/show), 36, 43, 63, 85, 105, 113, 116, 117, 120, 121, 124-126, 129, 136, 141, 146, 166-167 etpassim; as indifference of average everydayness, 16, 43; temporal meaning of phrase, 335, 370. See also Averageness; Everydayness; Indifference; Nearest/farthest Inner, inward (inner, innerlich), 31, 56,60,62, 101,132,136-137, 188,203-206,216,273,364,389, 401 (Yorck), 435 (Hegel); inner experience (innere Eifahrung), 204; inner life (Innenleben), 273; inner sense (innerer Sinn), 203; inner sphere (Innensphiire, innere Sphiire), 60, 62; Being inside (Innensein), 60. See also Immanent Innerworldly (innerweltlich), 56, 61, 64-66, 72-76 (§ 16), 80, 82-88, 95-98, 100-101, 102-104 (§ 22), 113,118,144,186-187,189,201, 203,209,211,344,351,366,380, 394, et passim; terminologically defined, 65 + fn. See also Handiness; Objective presence Insideness (Inwendigkeit), category juxtaposed to the existential
447
being-in, 56, 101, 132, 188. See also Aroundness; Being-in; Between; Spatiality Insignificance (Unbedeutsamkeit) of the world disclosed in Angst, 186-187,273,343 Intelligibility (Verstiindlichkeit, comprehensibility, understandability), 4, 59, 65 + fn, 81, 86, 93fn, 100 + fn, 105, 151-153,161-165,168-169,209, 220,271,324,335-336,366,368, 369,405,410,412;average, 168; as horizon of being, 100, 231, 234 + 426 (is temporality); unintelligibility, 4, 153, 164, 220, 236; to be, become, or make intelligible, 18, 44, (comprehensible), 65, 90, 99, 172, 181,227,231,234,245,276,279, 281,290,328,349,426.seealso Explanation; Understanding Intend (intendieren), 5, 94, 295, 390. See also Directing itself toward Intentionality, intentional acts (Intentionalitiit, intentionale Akte), 48, 363 n. 21. See also Directing itself toward; Phenomenology Interpretation (Auslegung), 9-10, 15-17,37-39,59-60,68fn (artistic), 130, 132-133, 148-160 (§§ 32-33), 157fn, 167-169, 231-232,292-294,310-313, 407-409, 434, et passim; self-, 51, 116,184,196-197,200,312,318. see also Interpretedness; Understanding itself Interpretation (Interpretation), 1-3, 14-17,21-26,50-52,61-62, 64-66,75-78,129-131,138-140, 159-161, 179-185, 199-201, 231-234,270-272,270fn (Deutung), 278-281, 286-290, 293-295,301-304,309-314, 322-324,331-335,356-358, 426-428,431-433,435-437,u passim. See also Hermeneutics
448
l
Being and Time
lnterpretedness, way of being (having been) interpreted (Awgelegtheit), 15-16, 167-170, 174-175, 177-178,187,190,194,222, 252-254,270-273,299,371,383, 395, 406, 408. See also Averageness; Circumspection; Public Intuition (Anschauung), 30-31, 96, 112, 135, 138, 147, 171, 193,202, 218 n. 34, 341, 358, 363, 402, 431, 434; forms of, 31, 367; objects of, 30, 215, 358; of Reality, 202; of space, 112; as care, 193; limitations of pure beholding, 135, 138, 341; voeiv as beholding, 96, 171; Hegel on, 430-431, 433-434; Husser! on, 363 n. 21; Kant on, 30-31, 215, 358, 367; Yorck on, 402; intuitionism, 9. See also Looking; Sight; Understanding Irrationalism (Irrationalismu.s), 136 Irresoluteness ( Unentschlossenheit), 299,308,322,336,338-339,384, 390,410 Isolate (isolieren), 19, 82, 247, 344, 352-353, 388; isolated "I" or subject, 116, 118, 179, 188, 192-193,204,206,298,321.See also the "I"; Immanent; Individualize; Subject It is concerned in its being about this very being (es geht in seinem Sein um dieses Sein selbst, the formally indicative formula for Seinsverstiindnis usually said of dative Da-sein), 12, 42, 52f, 84, 104, 123, 133-5, 141, 143, 153, 153fn, 179,19J-J93,231L235, 250,257,263 (ownmost being), 287,289,297,313,322,325,406; the being of this concern is in each case my own, 42. See also Mineness; Understanding of being It "knows" where it itself stands (es "weiss," woran es mit ihm selbst ist),
144, 270. See also "How one is"; It is concerned in its being about; Project; Understanding
jeweiligkeit, precursor to Jemeinigkeit = "mineness," thus more like "whileness," "temporal particularity";je ="in each particular case" is typically translated as "always" in its highfrequency usage in the text, thus effacing its distributive and individuating intent, as in jeweils = "on each occasion, at each particular time," jeweilig = "at this particular time, regarding this particular individual," with a tendency of overlapping translations of these terms. Here, we shall index only the latter form, jeweilig, in its most significant instances of usage as adverb ("actually") and adjective ("actual") in reference to particular individual Da-sein: 12, 16,20,39,41fn,56, 110-111, 127-129,170,237,240,242,248, 276,280,294,297-300,306-308, 313, 317fn, 319fn (itself-like), 326, 335-336,340,349-350(temporal particularity), 359, 366, 371, 383, 387,391,404,410-411,414.See also Formal indication; Individualize; mineness Joy (Freude), 310, 345 Judgment (Urteil), 4, 23, 32-34, 127, 153-159,204, 210-217,218 n. 34, 224, 229, 297, 341; and statement, 32, 153,214,224,226;and copula, 159, 349; and binding, 32, 159; and knowing etc., 210 (Scheler), 213, 216-217; and A.Oyo,, 32; and the they, 127; and truth, 33-34, 214, 226; and validity, 155-156; theoretical judgments, 157; acts vs. content of j., 156, 216-217; theory of, 32, 155, 159,
·~
'
Lexicon 213, 218 n. 34, 349; Kant on, 4, 23, 204, 224. See also Psychologism; Statement; Truth "Just looking" (Nur-noch-hinsehen), 69, 172 (perceiving), 336,341,351, 358 (" ... around"). See also Circumspection; Looking; Sight Keeping silent, see Silence Knowing, knowledge (Erkennen, Erkenntnis), 152-153, 217-218, 358, 363, et passim; of the world, 59-62 (§ 13), 65, 57, 131, 138, 156; most primordial, 153; in general, 71, 134, 138, 170-171, 324, et passim; of the real, 202; of the self, 146; of space, Ill; and intuition, 258, 363 n. 22; judgment, and truth, 210, 215-219, 228; and makingpresent, 363 n. 22; and mood, 134, 136; and understanding, 143, 356; historiographical, 392; perceptual, 67; rigorous, 152; scientific, 28, 152, 324; theoretical, 69, 136, 166, 335, 352, 356-364 (§ 69b); Augustine on, 171; Descartes on, 95-96, 100; Kant on, 215, 358; Scheler on, 210 Knowledge (Wissen): of death, 251, 258, 425; of distances, 106; of beings encountered, 58; of space, 368; of what one is capable of, 144, 270, 336; and acquaintance, 155; and curiosity, 172; and mood, 134-136; and the other, 174; Scheler on, 210, 210 n. 19 Knowledge (Kenntnis: familiar knowhow or acquaintance), 36, 59, 123-125, 129, 135-136, 142, 155, 169,178,182,252,300,330,367, 401,404,411,425,427,etpassim. See also Familiarity Lack (Mangel), 233, 260, 269, 282-286,291,336,374.Seealso Nullity
449
Language (Sprache), 9, 19, 32, 42fn (genetivus objectivus), 55, 85fn (present perfect), 87 + fn, 119 (adverbs), 133, 157 + fn (statement), 160-166 (§ 34), 161fn, 167-168, 272, 349 (tenses, their types of action), 369, 406. See also Articulation; Copula; Discourse; Expressedness; Grammar; Hermeneutics; Infinitive; Logic; Rhetoric Law (Gesetz), 10 (of motion), 47, 226-227 (Newton's), 282-283 (moral), 293, 361 (of gravity), 395 (of history); breaking the, 282-283. See also Truth Lay open (aufschliessen), 75, 359. See also Close off. Leeway (Spielraum), 107, 145, 355 (horizonal), 368-369 (not position in space). See also Clearing; making room; Possibility; Region Leaping (Springen): into the circle, 315; "productive logic" leaps ahead (vorspringen) into a realm of being to lay its foundations, 10; leaping in (einspringen) and dominating the other, 122; leaping ahead (voraus-) or forward (vorspringen) and liberating the other 122, 298; leap into (Einsprung ins) Da-sein, 207fn, 214fn; primal leap of an origin (Ur-sprung), 271fn. See also Arising; Being-for; Formal indication; Origin Letting (Lassen): be (sein lassen), 84-85, 84fn, 298 (the others), 345, 354; be seen (sehen lassen), 32-35, 44, 63, 141 (see), 154-155, 158, 213, 218-219; be relevant (Bewendenlassen), 84-87, 110-111, 353-356; be encountered (Begegnenlassen), 85-86, 104, 111, 137,264,326,328,346,354-356, 366, 408; itself be concerned (sichangehen-lassen), 141 (in fearing
450
Being and Time
Letting (continued) itself); it act in itself (In-sichhandeln-lassen), 295 (said of "ownmost self'); itself be summoned (Sich-aufrufen-lassen), 299; come toward itself (AufsichZukommen-lassen), 330, 341; "allowing itself' time (Sick-Zeitlassen), 409, 415; presence, (wesen lassen), 85fn; letting it matter to oneself (sich-angehen-lassen), 141, 170. See also Openness; Possibility; Resoluteness; Resolution Levelling (Nivellientng), 88, 158, 194, 220,253,329,405,422,424-426, 431-432, 432 n. 30, 435; levelling down (Einebnung), 127-128. See also Averageness; Everydayness Liberate (befreien), 113, 122, 165, 264, 288, 298, 303, 344; the other, 122, 298. See also Being-for; Concern; Free Life, living, live (Leben, Ieben), 25, 46-51,57-58,97,104, 163,246fn, 425, et passim; in an understanding of being, 4; world in which we, 63, 65, 71, 80; that which has life, 10, 25,48,50,97, 165,194,240,247, 346, 377; and care, 198 (Hyginus); and death, 104, 238, 240, 245-247, 249 n. 6, 316; and historicity, 401 (Yorck); and historiography, 396 (Nietzsche); and language, 163; and philosophy, 402 (Yorck); and reality, 212; and the they, 177; as a business, 289; the full and genuine, 177; inner (Innenleben), 273; cares of (Lebenssorge), 57; philosophy of, 46, 48, 398, 403; science of (i.e. biology), 9-10, 28, 46, 50; living (in general), 194; living along (dahinleben), 345, 405; 'living' away from oneself, 179; 'living' concretely, 178; living in a myth, 313; living in an understanding of Being, 4; living
on (/OTtleben), 247; living unto the day (in tkn Tag hineinleben), 370-371; living-through (Er-leben), 47 (Scheler); the urge 'to live', 195-196; getting lived by one's world, 195-196; getting lived by the ambiguity of publicness, 299; Dilthey on, 46, 209-210, 249 n. 6, 398; Yorck on, 400-402. See also Experience(Erlebnu) Light (Licht), 28, 133, 133fn (Leuchten as "shining"), 350-351, 359, 362 (and horizon); of day and sun, 103, 412-413; "in the light of ... ": 25 (problem of Temporality), 56 (existentially fundamental constitutions of Da-sein), 70 (nature's products), 313 {formal indication of existence), 362 (mathematically projected Nature), 392-393 (historicity), 436 {idea of being in general). See also Brightness; Clearing; Horizon, interrogative; Openness; Sight, etc. Limit-situation, see Situation (borderline) Linguistics (Sprachwissenschaft), 165-166,349 Listening (Horen auf, z.uhiiren, hiirig sein), 163-164, 168, 271 + fn; related to belonging, 65fn (welthiirig); as openness, 163; listening-in on the they, 139, 175, 271; to ownmost self, 275, 287. See also Belonging; Hearing; Openness; Resoluteness, Reticence; Silence Literature (Literatur), 10, 127, 397; specific authors, 197-198 (Hyginus), 245 n. 4 medieval German), 254 n. 12 (Tolstoi), 400 (Homer). See also Art; Poetry Location, locus, place (OTt): to begin the leap into Da-sein, 214fn; location or place of Da-sein, 132, 299,368, 417; location ofthe
Lexicon objectively present, 54, 361-362; spatial location, 54, 119, 132, 299, 416-418, 428 (Aristotle); change of place, 91, 97, 389; locative adverbs, 119; place of time in a system, 428-429; place of language, 166; place of the problem of history, 375; place of the problem of historicality, 377; locus of truth, 33, 154, 214,226. See al.5o Leeway; Place; Spatiality Logic (Logik), 2-4, 10-11, 38 (Husserl's), 129, 143 (modal), 152, 157-160, 165, 214 (Aristotle), 215, 218 n. 34 (Lask's I. of philosophy), 285,315,319,357,375(of concept formation), 398-399 (of the human sciences), 432 n. 30, 433, 437; Hegel's, 2-3, 22, 431-433; traditional, 4, 10, 129, 315 (of consistency); groundlaying, productive, 10, 399. See al.5o Concept(-formation); Grammar; Hermeneutics; Rhetoric Logistics (Logistik), 77fn, 159 "Look": See Appearance, outward Looking (hinsehen, Hin-sicht): sight of theoretical behavior, 7, 33, 61 + fn, 69,73,79, 112,119, 135; 138,141, 149, 158,220,264,335-336,357; "just" looking, 69,336, 351; away, 119,261-252,347,424;around, 336, 358. ["in view of ..." (in Hinsicht auf, hinsichtlich .. .), 200 (world, being-in, and self), 231-232 (its being primordially interpreted), 304 (their totality, unity, and development), 310-312 (its authenticity and wholeness), 324 (its upon-which), 325 (its existence), 335 (its temporal meaning), et passim]. See al.5o Circumspection; Light; Science; Sight Lose, losing (verlieren): 1. Said of Da-sein: oneself: See instead Lostness below; the
451
being of its there, 237; its being-in-the-world, 236, 238; its life, 238; time, 404, 410, 418, 425. See al.5o Death; Transition; Within-time-ness; Wholeness; World time 2. Said of things at hand: their handiness, 73-74, 361; their sign-character, 81. See al.5o Modification; Obtrusiveness 3. Said of spatiality of innerworldly things at hand; its character of relevance, 112 4. Said of the world: its character of aroundness, 112. See al.5o Circumspection; "Just looking"; Modification; Science 5. Said of something original: its originality, 36, 127 (and its power of mystery). See al.5o Concealment; Cover up; Idle talk Lostness, being-lost (Verlorenheit, Verlorensein) in the everyday "world" and the they, 175, 189, 263-265,268,271,273-274,277, 287,289,297,299-300,307-308, 312,348-349,390,424;istolose oneself, 42, 76, 116, 124, 128, 175-177,179,195,253,265,289, 312,344,348-349,369,390. Being-lost (not in above pages): in the world of useful things, 354, 422; in the making present of the "today," 391. See al.5o Absorption; Everydayness; Falling prey; Inauthenticity; Levelling; Numbing; Publicness Love (Liebe}, 190 n. 4 Loyalty (Treue), 385, 391. See al.5o Fate Magic (Magie, Zauberei), 81, 247, 313 Making present (Gegenwiirtigen), 26, 105fn,326-328,338-339,342, 344,346-350,353-357,359-360, 363, 363 n. 22, 365-366, 369, 381, 391,406-410,413-414,416-418,
452
Being and Time
Making present (continued) 420-422, 425; making-unpresent, 355. See also Present; Temporality, inauthentic Making room (Einriiumen, an existential}, 111, 299, 368-369. See also Freeing; Letting; Spatiality of Da-sein Man, human being (Mensch}, 51, 54, 60,97, 120, 134fn, 176,179,198, 203, 246, 246fn (human life}, 371, 379,382,396,400-401,425; being of, 12fn, 25, 45, 48-49, 57fn, 87fn, 165fn; his being toward God, 10, 190 n. 4; his good, 199; his substance, 117, 212, 314; his transcendence, 49; as rational animal, 48-49, 165, 183, 197; as the being which talks, 165; as unity of body, soul, spirit, 48, 117, 198; as made in God's image, 48-49; as the 'subject' of events, 379; as an 'atom' in world-history, 382; and Da-sein, 25, 46, 87fn, 134fn, 182; and the world, 57, 105, 152; and the surrounding world, 57; and the lumen naturale, 133; Aristotle on, 171; Calvin on, 49; Dilthey on, 398; Hyginus on, 198-199; Seneca on, 199; Zwingli on,49 Manifestness (O.ffenbarkeit}, 85fn (of beings}, 134 (of burden of being}, 371. See also Openness Material (Material), 68 (materiality), 366 (formed), 394 (historical); used in a craft, 70, 73, 117. See also Matter; Reality; Nature; Substance Mathematics (Mathematik), 9, 63, 65, 88,95-96, 153,362,402; mathematical physics, 9-10, 96 + fn ("the mathematical as such"), 362 Matter (Materie), 10, 68, 91, 97, 362; material nature (thing), 47, 98-99, 238. See also Corporeal thing; Extension; Motion; Natural thing; Natural science
"Matters," esp. in "the world matters to us" (angehen, Angiinglichkeit), 94fn, 106, 121-122, 137-139, 141, 170; sich-angehen-lassen, 141 (lets us be concerned), 170 (lets itself be affected). See also Affection; Attunement; Letting Meaning (Sinn), 1, 37fn (of difference), 137, 151-153, 156, 161, 324; meaningful (sinnvoll), 151; meaningless (sinnlos), 151; unmeaning (unsinnig), 152; give meaning (Sinn geben), 324-325; have meaning (Sinn haben), 151, 154, 221, 324, 348, 361. See also Significance; Signification; the Upon-which Meaning of being (Seinssinn, Sinn von Sein}, 1-6, 7fn, 11, 14-15, 17-21, 24,26-27,37,39,55,86,93 (Bedeutung}, 115, 123, 145, 152, 183,194,196,200-201,209, 211-213,226,228,230-231, 234-235,286,303-304,310,314, 316,323-330,332-333,346,357, 370-374,392,397,406,419-420, 435-437. See also Question of being Measurement (Mass, messen}, 68, 262, 358,417 n. 4; of space, 102-103, 105-106, 110-111, 369; of time, 71,404,413-415,417-419,417 n. 4. See also Calculating; Estimating Medical (medizinisch), 241, 247 Medieval ontology, 3, 25, 40, 93-94 Metaphysics (Metaphysik), 2, 21-22, 38fn,39,56,59,85fn,231fn,248, 293, 401-402 (Yorck), 433 n. 30; in the marginal remarks (~fn), 38fn, 318fn Method, methodology (Methode, Methodologie, Methodik}, 2, 10, 27-39 (§ 7}, 49, 66-67, 131, 139, 156,160,182,185,190,202,205 n. 15 (Dilthey), 208, 215, 230, 248, 255 n. 13, 280, 301-305 (§ 61), 303fn, 309, 310-316 (§ 63}, 324,
Lexicon 332, 362, 387, 393, 398 (Dilthey), 399-400 (Yorck), 402 (Yorck). See also UndeiWay; Way Mineness, always-being-mine, "always being my own being" (jemeinigkeit; je meines • "always my own, in each case mine"), 41-43, 4lfn, 53, 109fn, 114-116,118,191,221, 228,232,240,253,278,424-425. See also the I; Individualize; Jeweiligkeit; Self; Thrownness Missing, lacking (Fehlend), 191, 357; thing at hand, 73, 75, 353, 355, 408; Other, 120-121; something outstanding, 242-243; of an ought, 283; datability in vulgar time, 407, 422. See also Obtrusiveness; Wholeness Mitda-sein (co-existence), 114, 116, 117-125 (§ 26), 137, 140, 142, 162-163, 168, 170, 176, 187, 193, 239, 272, 297. See also Being-with Modalization (Modalisierung) of resoluteness through beingtoward-death, 305 (existentiell), 309 Modes (Modi, Seinsmodi), 17, 20, 59-62 (founded), 140-142 (of fear), 436, et passim; of being, 7-8, 17-19,42,50,61,108,120-121, 173,176,201,209,211,230,242, 295, 328, et passim; of temporality and temporalizing, 17, 25 (time), 329,335-348,410,424,436-437, et passim. See also Deficient; Derivative; Indifferent mode; Modification Modifications(s) (Modifikation[en}, Modifizierung): of the being of beings, 18, 35, 212 (and their meaning); semblance a privative m. of phenomenon, 29; of "speech," discourse, 32; of worldliness, 54, 82; of primordial being-in through knowing, 62; of circumspection to "just" looking and theoretical discovery, 73-74 (through breach of references),
453
157-158 (in statements), 335, 351-352,356,360-362; quantitative m. of extension, 98; reciprocal existentiell m. between they-self and authentic self, 130, 179, 196,267-268,297,JJ~of fear, 140, 142; shift in understanding is existential m. of project as a whole, 146; of asstructure, 154, 158, 223; of the being of Da-sein, 181; of care, 195-96, 211; of the understanding of truth, 223; of parts within whole, 242; of ending, 245; mutual m. of and by temporalizing ecstasies, 329, 340, 342,347,404;ofour understanding of being, 361-362, 364. See also Change-over; Deficient; Derivative; Indifferent; Modes Moment (Augenblick): as singular and unique Moment, 328, 338, 338 n. 3,344-345,347,349-350,371, 385-386,391-392,397,410,427; as multiple, 142, 165, 172, 258, 308, 391, 425. See also Temporality, authentic; Withintime-ness Monument (Denkmal), 78, 394; monumental historiography, 396-397 Mood (Stimmung), 134-139, 142, 148, 162,169,190,251-252,265,270, 276-277,284,310,335,339-346, 371; bad, 134, 136; lack of, 134, 345, 371. See also Affect; Attunement; Feeling Moral (moralisch, sittlich), 167, 282, 286,288,293,295 Most extreme {iiusserst), said of possibility of death, 250, 255, 259, 262-264,266,302-303,326.See also Being toward the end Motion (Bewegung), 10, 91, 178, 180, 362, 375 (of objectively present), 389 (as change of place), 421
454
Being and Time
Motion (continued) (Aristotle), 428, 432 n. 30, 435 (Hegel). See also Change Movement (Bewegtheit), 134, 177-180 (of falling prey), 348 (of the throw), 374-375 {of existence), 388 n. 9 {of history), 389 (of occurrence). See also Falling prey; Project; Thrownness Movement (Bewegung), 9 (of sciences), 91, 97, 109 (of hand); enigma of being and, 392. See also Change; Motion Multiplicity (Mannigfaltigkeit), 3, 68-69 (of references), 102-103 (of places), 110 (of positions), 164 (of tone data), 203 (of representations), 362 (of places), 417, 429, et passim; ofthe [equiprimordial] phenomena, 334; Vielerlei of daily occurrences, 389. See also Dispersion; Equiprimordial Museum (Mweum), 380 Myth (Mythos), 51 n. 11, 313 Nature (Natur), 9-11, 18, 25, 47 n. 2, 48, 60, 63, 65 + fn, 70-71, 89, 95, 98-100, 106, 112, 144-145, 152, 165,179,199,211,361-363,377, 379, 388, 388 n. 9, 398-400, 401 (Yorck), 404,412-413,415,417 n. 4, 418, 428 (Aristotle); 429, 431, 4323 n. 30, 434 (Hegel); thing of n., natural thing (Naturding), 48, 63, 99-100, 211; surrounding world of ... (Umweltnatur), 71, 381, 413. See also Intelligibility (unintelligibility) Natural history (Naturgeschichte), 388. See also World history Natural science (Naturwissenschaft), 9-10, 63, 362, 398, 400 (Yorck). See also Crisis; Law; Thematization Nearest/farthest (niichste/fernste): said of being of Da-sein, 15-16, 43, 66, 76,102,105, 107,271,311-312;
the "I" as n., 317fn; n. as most primordial, 408fn. See also Familiarity; Obviousness; Understanding of being Nearness (Nahe, an existential), 97, 102-103 (of useful things), 105-107, 105fn, 140-142 {of what is feared), 154-155, 185-186, 262, 396; bringing near, nearing, approaching (Naherung), 105-108, 105fn, 142, 149, 172, 185-186, 262, 359-360, 368-369. See also Calculating; De-distancing; Distantiality; Estimating; Farness; Nearest/farthest Necessity (Notwendigkeit), 8, 13, 16, 45, 59, 76, 143 (as a modal), 165, 225-229, 249, 313fn (versus nonarbitrary), et passim; of repeating the question of being, xvii, 2-5, 20 (ontic-ontological), 37; of return to original "sources" of tradition, 21; and possibility of the most radical individuation, 38; of the presupposition that "there is truth," 214, 226, 229; of presupposing an ontic-factical ideal of Da-sein for its ontological interpretation, 31 0; of a coverup levelling ecstatic temporality, 304, 326-327, 426; primordial time is the condition of possibility and n. of the everyday experience of time, 332-333; of Nietzsche's triad of historiography, 396; of timereckoning found in care, 411, 413; of time as the fate of spirit (Hegel), 435. See also Accident; Condition of possibility; Possibility; Reality Negating, negation (Negieren, Negation), 22, 159 (statements), 207,229,248,286,429-435 (Hegel). See also the Not; Nothing; Nullity New, the (das Neue), 19 (against the "ancients"), 24-25 (beginning
Lexicon sought by Descartes), 196 (ontologically "new" as ontically old); sought by Neu-gier (curiosity), 24-25,172-174,271,346,348, 391. See also Ancient ontology Nihilism (Nihilismw), 176fn No longer (nicht-mehr-), 373, 430-431 (Hegel), et passim; being-able-to-bethere, 250; no-longer-Being-there, 236; no longer Da-sein, 237-238, 240, 242, 330; no-longer-now (nicht-mehr-jetz.t), 327, 42l, 424; now-no-longer (jetzt nicht mehr), 380,406,421;nolonger objectively present, 374, 378, 380; Being-no-longer-in-the-world, 176, 238,240 Nobody, no one (Niemand), 128, 177, 253,255,268,278,299,425.See also Everyone; the They Nonbeing (Nichtsein) and being, 170, 243, 431, 434 (Hegel); beingtoward-death as being of nonbeing, 234fn. See also Being and becoming; Transition Not, the (das Nicht, Nichtheit), 29, 283-286; ontological origin of, 286 Not-to-be-bypassed (uniiJJerholbar), 250-256,258-259,263-265,307, 309,330,383,386,391.5eealso Being toward death; Being toward the end Not-yet (noch-nicht), 145, 242-246, 250,259,317,325,347,373,380, 393-394, 427,430-431 (Hegel), et passim; the "not-yet-now" (das Noch-nicht-jetzt), 327, 421, 424, 427; the "now-not-yet" (das]etztnoch-nicht), 406, 309, 421; Beingnot-yet (Noch-nicht-sein), 237, 246; not yet objectively present, 144, 237,243,374 Nothing(ness), the (das Nichts), 7fn, 43,128,177,186-188,266,273, 276-277,308,343,352,431; indifference not, 43; no one not,
455
128, 177; and nowhere, 186, 188; of Ang.rt, 186-188, 308; of possible impossibility of one's existence, 266; of the world, 187, 276-277, 343; self thrown into, 7fn, 277; being and, 431 (Hegel) Now (jetzt), 325, 338 n. 3, 373, 378, 406-411,414,416-418, 421-427, 430-432, 432 n. 30; now-here (jetzt-hier), 421, 430; now-point (jetzt-Punkt), 430; now that (jetzt, da ... ), 406-408, 410-411, 414, 422; now-time (jetzt-zeit), 421, 423, 426; just now (soeben), 407, 424; multiplicity of "nows" (jetztmannig[altigkeit), 417; saying "now" (jetzt-sagen), 406, 408, 416, 418, 421; succession of "nows" (jetztfolge), 329, 373, 422-426, 431-432; stream of "nows" (jetztjlws), 410, 436 Nowhere (nirgends), 175, 177, 186-188, 347. see also Curiosity;
Ang.rt Nullity (Nichtigkeit, sometimes "nothingness"), 23, 206, 219; being the ground of a, 283-287, 305-306,308,330,348; "nothingness" of inauthentic everydayness, 178 Numbed, benumbed (benommen), 76, 271 (by everyday ambiguity), 344 (by uncanniness); "taken in" by everyday world, 61, 113, 176. See also Absorption; Falling prey; Flight; Lostness Number(Zahij,215,412,417-418, 432 n. 30 (Bergson). See also Calculating Object (Objekt): and judgment, 156, 216; and subject, 59-60, 156, 176, 179,192,204,208,216,219,366, 388; and world, 60, 179, 203, 366; ofhistoriology, etc., 10, 375-376, 392,397,401
456
Being and Time
Object (Gegenstand): of a statement, 157; of taking care, 238; of historiography, 152, 375, 380, 392-395;ofjudgment,214,224, 273; of knowing, 60, 215 (Kant), 218; of mathematics, 9; of phenomenology, 34-36; of a science, 9-10, 238, 361; to be disclosed, 232, 303 Objectivation (Objektivierung), 48, 82, 363,375-376,378,381,419-420. See also Thematization Objective(ly), objectivity (Objektiv[itiit]), 20lfn, 237, 260, 275, 289, 363, et passim; being, 64; distance, 106; 'there', 389; valid, 156; and subjectivity, 278, 326, 366, 405, 419; of the appeal, 278; of historiology, 395; of a science, 395;oftime,405,419;ofthe world, 366. See also 237, 260, 275, 289,363 Objective, objectivity (Sachlich[keitj), 11, 15fn,21,27,45,98, 122,265, 333, 377. See also "the Things themselves" Objective presence (Vorhandenheit), 42-43,45,49-50,54-56,61, 70-75, 88, 96 (constant), 183, et passim. See also Existence; Handiness; Objectivity; Presence; Reality; Substance Observation (Betrachtung, Beobachtung), 69, 75, 340, 357-358, 362, 415. See also Circumspection, Looking Obstinacy (Aufsiissigkeit), 74-75, 186, 354. See also Conspicuousness; Familiarity; Modification; Obtrusiveness; References Obtrusiveness (Aufdringlichkeit), 73-75, 81, 189, 354, 377. See also Conspicuousness; Familiarity; Modification; Obstinacy; Reference Obviousness, Self-evidence (Selbstverstiindlichkeit), 2, 4, 21-22,
(of what is handed down), 28, 49-50, 55, 59, 74, 92, 93 + fn, 115-116, 121, 132, 150, 170, 188-189,219,277,286,311,320 n. 19,332,334,351,354,358, 371, 387, 407; "matter of course," 75, 81, 160; the "business of philosophers" is the questionability of all, 4, 23, 219-220, 334. See also Absorption; Dwelling; Familiarity; Nearest/farthest; Uncanniness; Understanding of being Occurrence (Geschehen) ofDa-sein as such, 19-20,371,375-379,382, 384-390,392,404,413,426,436; natural, 388 n. 9; world-historical, 389; o. of being (Seinsge5chehnis), 268fn. See also the Between; Connection; Event; Historicity; Resoluteness; Temporalizing Ontic (ontisch), 11-15 (§ 4), 19, 37, 43,63,84-87,85fn,92,94, 114, 116,182,199,201,266,279,293, 312,318fn,324,371,382, 399-400 (Yorck), 402-403, et passim; ontic-existentiell, 135, 184, 196, 312; ontic-factical, 225; onticother worldly, 248; onticpsychical, 299; ontic-psychological, 340; ontic-worldviewlike, 200; ontic-temporal, 404; being (seiend)ontic, 12; a genuine ontic (Ontik), 311fn. On tic-ontological (where joined and/or distinguished), 12-16, 20, 37,43,63-64,74,84-85,85fn 94-95, 115-116, 120, 128, 135, 179-182,184-185,199-200,213, 221,246-248,260,266,295, 310-312,311fn,316,322,334, 340,356-357,382,403,436 Ontological (ontologisch), 8-11 (§ 3), 12-19,27,43,52,77,94, 116, 182,199,201,204,210,301-333 (11.111), 266, 295, 311-312, 403, 436, et passim; o.-categorial, 65, 71,
1. .
I
<~.
Lexicon 78, 135; a.-existential, 65, 86, 152, 163, 176, 184, 249; a.anthropological, 272; a.methodological, 309; o.-ontic, 37; a.-phenomenal, 211; o.-temporal, 25; being-o. 12; o. or transcendental perfect tense, 85fn; o. difference, 94fn, 208fn, 230fn. See also Difference; Existentialontological; Ontic-ontological; Pre-ontological Ontology (Ontologie), 3-4, 8, 11-13, 17-19,21-27,35,37-40,49-50, 52,63,65-66,82,89,93,95-96, 98-100, 129-131, 154, 159-160, 165-166,170,194, 199n. 7,208 n. 16,214,225,231,247-248,249 n.6,285-286,293,311,315,317, 319-320, 320 n. 19, 333, 358, 387, 403, 421, 428, 432 n. 30, 436-437; of Da-sein, (37), 49, 130, 166, 194, 247, 293, 306 n. 2, 311, 315, 333, 387; in the later marginal remarks: 98fn (Husserl's), 231fn (ontology), 311fn (and an Ontik). See also Ancient ontology; Fundamental ontology; Hermeneutics; Medieval ontology; Phenomenology Open(ing) (offen, Offnen): said ofDasein, 162fn (the there), 163, 169, 265 (by being-toward-the-end), 307-308 (by resoluteness), 341, 350-351 (of clearing), 369, 386, 392-393, 396-397 (hermeneutical situation), 408, 421; being-open (listening), 163; ecstatically, 341, 386, 408; horizonally, 421; said of the horizons of this investigation, 72 (way), 115, 334, 362; doors, 67, 177. See also Clearing; Closing off; Covering up; Disclosure Openness (Offenheit), 133fn, 137 (world-), 163 (oflistening), 165fn. See also Clearing; Disclosedness; Discoveredness; Manifestness; Publicness
457
Opportunity (Gelegenheit) of circumspection, 172, 174,300, 359, 389. See also Circumspection; Circumstances Orientation (Orientierung): 1. Existential: within the spatiality of being-in, 79-80 (through signs), 102-103 (to a region), 104 (arrangement of a house), 106-107, 109-111 (through Da-seing's directionality), 118 (in encountering others), 342; from Da-sein encountered within the world and its history, 381 (temporal distance), 395-396. See also Directionality; Distantiality; Spatiality 2. Methodological: a) of existential analytic of Da-sein to the question of being and time, 16-17,24-25,45,52-53, 58, 117, 131, 132 (toward "between"),209,212,240,242, 246 (private life to Da-sein), 280 (to individual Da-sein), 286, 323 (to the being of the 1), 350,371,373,376,381,426; b) prior ontology's o. to constant presence, 96 + fn, 98-99, 101, 159, 163, 170, 185, 201 + fn, 206 (to "reality"), 208, 381, 423-424, 427 n. 13 (to eternity), 431 (to the now). See also Circle; Forestructure; Hermeneutical situation; Presence Origin (Ursprnng, Ur-sprnng, "primalleap": 271fn), 61fn, 77, 96, 99-100,158-159,171,198,205, 235,267,271fn,282,286,304, 326-327,333-334,344,348,363, 377,387,390,392,397,404-405, 408,412,421,428,435,437.See also Arising; Equiprimordiality; Provenance; Source
458
Being and Time
Original, Originality: See instead Primordial, primordiality Originary (originiir), 37, 62, 224 Other(s), the (der Andere), 114-125 (§§ 25-26F), 126, 128-129, 155, 260, 281-282, 383, 418, et passim; being toward, 124-125, 177; coming to owe something to Others, 282; conscience for others, 298; death of others, 237-241 (§ 47), 254, 257; encountering of other, 117, 120, 125; fearing for other, 141-142; potentiality-of-Being of others, 264, 298; understanding Others, 123. See also Being-with; Concern; Mitda-sein; Self; the They Other-worldly, the (dasjenseits), 248. See also Death Outside (ausser, Aussen), 62, 118, 136, 162,177,205,227,243,366,374, 419, 435; being-outside (Draussensein), 62, 162; beingoutside-of-itself (Aussersich-sein), 429-430; the "outside-of-itself' (das Aussersich), 329, 350, 365; the "outside-of-one-another" (das Aussereinander), 429. See also Being-out-for; Ecstases; External world; Rapture Outstanding (Ausstand, ausstehen); 144,227,233-234,236-237, 241-246 (§ 48), 249-250, 259, 317, 374. See also Indebtedness; Guilt Owe (schulden), 242, 281-282. See also Guilt; Indebtedness; Responsible Paralogism (Paralogismus), 318 (Kant), 320 n. 19, 332 Pass away (vergehen), 373, 382, 393-394,422-423,425-427.See also Come to be and pass away Past (Vergangenheit), 20-23, 85fn (ontic), 326, 328, 374, 378-381, 385-386,391,393-395,424,427, 431 (Hegel). See also Having-been
Perceiving: (Vernehmen), 25,33-34,61-62,67,
94,96-98,115,147,163, 170-172,212,224,273,335, 346, 351, 400 (Yorck) (Wahrnehmen), 120, 135-136, 144, 146-147,149,181,217-218, 243, 354, 363 n. 22. See also Intuition; ('~ust") Looking Perish (verenden), 240-241,247, 251. See also Demise; End; Pass away Persistence (Beharrlichkeit), 203-204 (through a manifold of representations: Kant) 322-323 (of subject), 373-375 (of Da-sein). See also Steadfastness; Steadiness; Constancy; Resoluteness; Subsistence Person (Person), 22, 38, 45-50 (§ 10), 119,137, 146fn,274, 278, 318-320; as object, 114; personthing, 120; practical, 319; God as, 275; personal actions, 272; personal being, 4 7-48; personal consciousness, 278; personal immortality, 320 n. 19; personal pronouns, 42, 119; depersonalization, 48; personalism, 47-48, 47 n. 2, 272 n. 8; Heimsoeth on personality, 320 n. 19; Husserl on personality, 47, 47 n. 2; Kant on personality, 318-319, 320 n. 19, 323; Scheler on personality, 47-48, 272 n. 8, 320 n. 19 Phenomenology (Phiinomenologie), 27-39 {§ 7), 39, 47, 51 n. 11, 63-64, 89, 115-116, 116 n. 1, 131, 139-140, 147, 159, 180, 184-185, 207, 208 n. 16, 218 n. 34, 219, 249 n. 6, 267, 272 n. 8, 357, 375, 436. See also Hermeneutics; Husserl; Ontology; Pre-phenomenological Phenomenal {phiinomenal), 37, 60-61, 66,82,101-102,115-117, 128-136, 179-182, 184-189, 191-192,209-210,234-235,
Lexicon 237-238,303-305,318-320, 322-323, et passim Phenomenon (Phanomen), 28-31 (§ 7a), 34-37, 58-68, 131-134, 153-156, 158-162, 179-185, 188-191,248-250,268-271, 289-292,302-305,316-318, 359-360, 433 et passim Philological (philologisch), 21, 152. See also Grammar; Rhetoric Philosophy (Philosophie), 6, 13, 27, 38, 45, 50 n. 10, 208, 213, 229, 310, 436, et passim; "the business of philosophers," 4, 23, 220 (Kant); 'the scandal of philosophy', 203, 205 (Kant); of culture, 167; of history, 402 (Yorck); of language, 166; oflife, 46, 48, 398, 403; of Nature, 432 n. 30 (Hegel); and the occurrence of being, 268fn; essence of philosophizing, 268fn. See also Hermeneutics; Ontology; Phenomenology Physics (Physik), 9, 33, 60, 65fn, 95-96,204,206,218,361-362, 367, 401-402 (Yorck), 417 n. 4, 419, 428, 431 n. 30 Physiology (Physiologie), 190, 241, 246-247, 402 (Yorck) Place (Platz, platzieren), 97, 102-104, 104fn, 107-108, 111-112, 361-362,368,413,416.Seealso Dwelling; Location; Orientation; Position Plunge (Stun:), 178. See also Alienation, Eddying; Falling prey; Temptation; Tranquillization Poetry (Dichtung), 16, 162, 249, 260. See also Art; Literature Point (Punkt), 105, 107, 119, 179, 362,374,407,429-430,432,et passim. See also Now; Place; Space Point out (Aufzeigung): first function of a statement, 154-158, 160, 218, 227-228. See also Apophantic "as"; Statement
459
Political (politisch), 16, 193, 400 (Yorck); occurrence-with, of a community and people, (384). See also Destiny; Heroes; Ideal, ontic; Rhetoric Position: (Stelle): spatial, 102-104, 107, 109-110 (order), 112 (multiplicity), 119, 362, 368-369,420 (of a pointer); et passim. (Stand): of the sun, 71, 415; social class or status (standing), 239, 274; of Da-sein, 253, 322 (self having gained a stand), 388; p. or state of "status" of a science (esp. our present problematic), 10, 55 (ontological analytic), 156 (question of being), 159, 166, 301, 323. (Lage), also translated as location, lay (of things): 110 (lay), 193, 226,249,299-300,359,369, 371. See also Circumstances; Dwelling; Location; Orientation; Place; Situation; Space (and time) Positive (positiv): versus privative, negative, critical, etc., 19, 52, 75, 141,260,279,286,378,etpassim; sciences, etc. 9-11, 50-52, 58, 324, 398, et passim; call of conscience as, 279, 294, 300; forgetting as, 339. See also Deficient; Lack; Negating; Privation Possibility (Moglichkeit): as an existential, it is the most original and positive ontological determination of Da-sein, 143-144; higher than actuality, 38, 262, 299; ofDa-sein, 7, 12-13, 19-20,42-43,50,62,104, 125-126, 144, 148, 170, 173, 177-178, 181, 187-188, 191, 193-195,199,211,236,239-240, 244,250,260,264,266,270,273,
460
Being and Time
Possibility (continued) 284,288,295,325,384,394,396; of impossibility of existence, 250, 262, 265-266, 306; impossibie and possible, 342; death as, 248, 250-266,302-303,307,309,391; being toward, 262; extreme, 122, 182; existentiell, 267-270 (§54), 336-337; factical, 264, 299, 383-384; ontic and ontological, 312; category oflogical, 143; as project of understanding, 145-148,151,194,260,270,274, 284-285,295,302,306,312,324, 336,339,383,387,394,397.See also Condition of possibility; Future; Meaning; Potentiality of being; Project Possible, the (das Mogliche), 143, 261-262, 299; Da-sein as being-, 42-43,143-145,188,248-249, 259; historical repetition of the silent power of the, 385, 394-395. See also Future; Potentiality of being; Power Potentiality of being (Seinkonnen, lit. can-be, potential-to-be), 86-87, 122,143-148,153,173,186-188, 191-195,221,231-236,250-255, 257,262-270,277-280,287-289, 298-302,305-313,334,336-339, 341-344,359,363-365,382-383, 414, et passim; authentic, 233, 235, 267-301 (11.11), 302,313,317,322, 343; chosen, 288, 298, 394; existentiell, 260, 280, 313, 385; factical, 145, 187, 268, 280, 298, 306,325,341-342;ontic,260; ownmost, 163, 181, 188, 191, 221, 228,250-255,259,262-263,265, 267,273,276-279,287-288,296, 299,306-308,317,325,336-337, 339, 348; projected potentialityfor-Being, 336-337, 365; whole potentiality-for-Being, 264, 266, 303, 317; Da-sein as potentialityfor-Being, 143, 145, 191, 231, 250,
252,264-265,277,284,287, 312-313, 337; Da-sein as delivered over to its potentiality-for-Being, 383; as something for the sake of which, 86, 191, 193-194, 334, 336, 359,412, 414; of Others, 264; potentiality-for-Being-guilty, 289, 306-307; potentiality-for-Being-inthe-world, 144, 179, 187, 191-192, 228, 252, 295, 412; in the 'truth', 363; potentiality-for-Being-one' sSelf, 175, 184, 267-269, ~73-275, 294,298,307,316,322-323; Being-a-whole, 233-235, 237, 266, 301-333 (KK, III), 345, 372. See also Future; Meaning; Possibility; Project Power: (Kraft), 91, 127 (of mystery), 220 (of the most elementary words); of the possible, possibilities of Da-sein, 173, 394-395; light of clearedness not an innate ontic, 350-351; as ontic "force," 360, 362. (Macht): of the they's chatter, 126, 174; of the call of conscience, 275,278,291,296,310,403;of forgetting, 345; of time is the Concept (spirit), 435 (Hegel); gaining p. (miichtig werden) over ground, existence, fate, destiny, 284, 310, 384-385 (powerless superpower); Miichtigkeit of temporality, 331 (constitutive), 334 (as ontological origin), 344 (through angst), 369 (and space). See also Clearing; Condition of possibility; Origin; Possibility Practical (praktisch), 57, 59, 69, 294, 193, 300, 315-316, 319, 320 n. 19, 357-358, 364, 402 (Yorck). See also Praxis; Theory Pragmatic (pragmatisch), 68; pragmata ("things"), 68, 214. See also Circumspection
Lexicon Pr~s(Praxu),68,
193,357-358,402 (Yorck). See also Theory Pre-(vor-): pr~ntological, 12-13, 15-17,44,65,68,72,86, 130, 182-184, 196-200 (§ 42), 197 n. 6, 201,222,225,289,312,315,356; pre-phenomenological, 51, 59, 63, 72,99,219,318;pr~
philosophical, 19, 165, 219; prepredicative, 149, 359; pr~ scientific, 9, 393 Predicate, predication (Priidikat[ion]), 94,99,154-155,157,215,281, 318, 359. See also Communicating; Pointing out; Statement Predilection (Hang), 182, 194-196, 345. See also Care; Urge; Willing; Wishing Prefiguration, prescription (Von:eichnung}, 39, 41, 45, 52, 101, 114,127,129,232,237,247, 249-250,252,255,275,301,313, 322,334,363,393,426.Seealso Horizon; Schema Presence (Anwesenheit), 25-26, 71, 415-418, 423 (constant); das Anwesende, 326 ("what presences"}, 417 ("what is present"); being preseng (anwesend sein), 346 ("bodily," leibhaftig), 359, 369,389,417 ("having presence"}, 423 (constantly); in the later marginal remarks (=fn): 105fn (constant}, 153fn, 320fn; also "presencing," 39fn (Anwesen), 235fn (Anwesenheit). See also Objective presence Presencing: 39fn (Anwesen), 85fn (wesen lassen}, 235fn (An-wesenheit); es west, 87fn, 165fn, 252fn. See also Essence as presencing Present (Gegenwart), 25-26, 326, 328-329,337-340,342,344-348, 350,355,360,363,365,369, 378-381,385,391,393-395,397, 407-408, 410, 427, 431; Gegen-
461
wart, "waiting toward," to accentuate its ecstasy, 26, 338 (twice). See also Making present; Moment Preservation (Verwahmng): since wahr= true, its sense in these contexts is "preservation of discoveredness in the truth of statements," 62, 168, 172, 224; perduring(wahrend}, 7fn.Seealso Discoveredness; Objective presence (constant); Truth Presupposition (Voraussetzung}, 7-8, 29,31,55,58-61,124-125,145, 150,152-153,157,205-206, 214-216, 226-230 (§ 44c, p. of truth}, 239, 310-316 (§ 63, on the hermeneutic situation}, 321, 392, 402,416, et passim; presuppositionless, 60, 150. See also Circle; Es gibt; For~structure; Givenness; Hermeneutic situation; Logic Primitive (primitiv), 50-52(§ 11), 81-82,247,396,415 Primordial (urspriinglich), 10-11, 16-17,86,87fn,94, 123-124,127, 130-131,230-235,303-308, 314-317,322-334,435-437,u passim; most p. determination of Da-sein, 143; most p. knowing, 153; truth, 219-226 (§ 44b), et passim; temporality, 323-331 (§ 65), et passim. See also Deficient; Derivative Primordiality ( Urspriinglichkeit), 61fn, 72,131,151,165,231-233,292, 311, 334, 395. See also Equiprimordiality; Origin; Provenance Priority (Vorrang): of the question of being, 2-15 (Introd. I); of the problem of man's being towards God, 190 n. 4; of Da-sein, 7-8, 13-16,37, 126;of~tentwover essentia, 43; of being-in-the-world as care-taking, 58; of care, 198; of
462
Being and Time
Priority (continued) volition and cognition, 136; of Dasein's disclosure of itself, 136; of 'seeing', 171, 358; of pure intuition, 14 7; of the practical attitude, 193; of 'bad' conscience in interpretations of the conscience, 290; of time over space, 367 (Kant); of the future, 111; of the past, 379; of havingbeen, 386; of making-present, 417; of the "now," 432 n. 30; of arising and passing away, 431-432; of the objectively present, 147; of being as constant presence, 105fn; of the concept of reality, 201, 211; of the isolated subject, 204; of idealism over realism, 207; every priority is suppressed by the they, 127 Privation, privative (Privation, privativ), 18, 29, 50, 58, 75, 141, 149,163-164,184,194,201,222, 246,285-286,291,357,378.See also Deficient; Guilt; Lack; Negating Production (Herstellung), 24, 61, 67, 70-71,80,85,92,99, 117,261, 352,355,358-359,414-415,435; essential structural moment of the ancient concept of being, 24; of clocks, 414-415; production of the things at hand, 261, 352; production of signs, 80-91; production of work, 67,69-71, 117, 353; production and creation, 24, 92; production as mode of being-in, 56, 61. See also Making present Project(ing) (Entwurf, entweifen), lOOfn (as ecstatic temporality), 145-151, 147fn, 174, 181, 199, 221-223,235,260,262-263,277, 284-285,295,297,301-302, 31lfn (pre-ontological), 312-315, 324-327, 325fn (existentiell and existential), 330, 336-338, 360,
362-363 (mathematical), 372, 375fn (phenonemenological construction as), 383, 385, 392-394, 437, et pa.ssim; as thrown, 144-145,148,181,223,276,285, 406; of Da-sein, 270, 277, 284, 313,363,385,394, 406; ofDasein's being, 145, 147, 195, 324; of existence, 325, 372; of being-inthe-world, 147; of authentic beingtowards-death, 237, 260-267 (§ 53); of anticipation, 266-267; of resoluteness, 385; of understanding, 148, 151, 174,265, 324; of possibilities, 298, 312, 383, 394; of a potentiality-of-being, 148, 305, 336, 365; of a meaning of being in general, 235; of relevance, 353; of a world, 195, 394; of nature, 362-363; of the primary 'then', 409; of historicality, 376; of the idea of historiography, 393; upon its "upon-which," 151, 324-325; upon possibilities, 145, 147-148, 181,187,194-195,222,263,270, 284,295,297,299,312,315,339, 383,385,387, 394; upon a potentiality-of-being, 194, 262-263,265,277,287,306,313, 334, 343, 385, 406; upon a "forthe-sake-of-oneself," 327; upon significance, 145, 147, 151; upon the world, 151; upon meaning, 151, 324; upon being, 312, 393; upon one's being-guilty, 296-297, 301, 305, 382, 385; upon one's potentiality for becoming guilty, 287, 306; existential, 301, 305, 323, 376, 383; ontological, 302, 309, 312, 393; understanding, 314-315; self, 276, 287, 382-383, 385-386, 387; resolute, 386; thrown, 148, 223, 285; null, 285, 287-288; inauthentic, 339; factical, 297. See also Anticipation; Disclosedness; Meaning;
Lexicon Possibility; Potentiality of being; Understanding Proof (Beweis), 7-8, 20-21, 90, 152, 179, 201, 202-208 (§ 43a), 229, 268-269,310,315,396,408,u passim. See also Logic Property (Eigenschaft), 20, 42, 56-57, 60,73,83,88,90-91,94, 133, 151,157-158,162,179,199,225, 285,306,359,361 Provenance(/lerkun.ft),6,8, 21-22, 39fn (source), 46, 49, 76, 131, 158, 223,274,286,376,378-379,381, 385,390,405,408,425-426,435. See also Arising; Derivative; World history Psychical (psychisch, seelisch ): versus physical, 60, 204, 206, 218, 401, 419; elements and atoms, 46; occurrences, 33, 367; processes, 56,216-217,293;phenomen~
139; time, 349; ontico-psychical, 299; transposition, 400 (Yorck); the 'psychical' vs. acts, 47; being vs. personal being, 48 (Scheler); positive science of the psychical, 398; conditions, 136-137, 273, 340; faculties, 271-272; life (Seelenkben), 46, 124. See also Life; Soul; Psychology Psychologism (Psychologismus), 217. See also Husserl; Phenomenology Psychology (Psychologie), 16, 45-50 (§ 10),51, 109,124,163,190,207, 247-249,269,301,338,398-401; of conscience, 290; of death and dying, 239, 247; of moods and affects, 134, 138, 340; of original sin, 190 n. 4 Public, publicness (Offentlich[keit/) 126-128, 138, 167, 169, 174-177, 187-192,252-254,257,271,273, 277-278,282,299,370-371, 387-388,397,410-416,424-426; of the they, 138, 167, 175, 188, 190, 192, 257, 273; of being with one another, etc. 174, 239, 252,
463
370, 387-388; ambiguity of, 299; idle talk, 277; of the "to-day," 397; intelligibility, 410; interpretation, 169,174,177-178,187,190,220, 252-254,270-271,273,383; surrounding world, 126, 354, 359, 413; world, 65, 71; time, 411-430, 424-426; conscience, 278, 30 (Yorck); law, 282; norms, 288; opinion, 403 (Yorck) Punctuality (Punktualitiit), 429-430, 432 (Hegel). See also Now; Point Question of (the meaning of) being (Seinsfrage, Frage nach dem Sein [Sinn von] Sein), V, 1-19 (§§ 1-5), 7fn (two separate questions), 20-27, 39-40 (§ 8), 45, 85fn (of beings as such, 156, 160, 183, 196, 200, 212 (through the understanding of being), 230-231 (Through the whole of care), 235 n. 6fn, 316, (333, 392), 421, 436-437 (§ 83). See also Being as such, in general; Fundamental ontology; Understanding of being Rapture (Entriickung), 338-399, 348 (raptness, 350, 365, 396. See also Ecstasy Rationalism (Rationalismus), 136, 320 n.19 Read(ing) off (Ablesung), 7 + fn (meaning of being, 77 (sign relations), 90 (essence of the substantiality of particular substances), 97 (an idea of being "patterned after" a particular region), 236 ("discern" ontological wholeness of being), 311fn (ontology "taken" from ontic), 358 (measurements); "telling" time (Zeitablesung), 70, 415-417. See also Interpretation Ready (bereit): for Ang.ft, 296-297, 301,382,385,391;forthe summons, 287-288,307
464
Being and Time
Reality (Realitat), 7, 47 n. 2, 68, 94 (Kant), 106-107, 128, 170, 177, 183-184, 200-212 (§ 43), 216-218,230,303,313-314,318, 329 (Kant), 324, 368, 400 (Yorck), 420, 437; in the later marginal remarks (=fn), 94fn, 20 lfn, 209fn Realism (Realismus), 34 183, 206-208, 208 n. 16, 215 Reason (Vernunft), 4, 22f, 32, 34, 48, 165, 320 n. 19, et passim Reckon (rechnen), 284, 293, 333; reckon on, 356, 412-413; r. up, 207,283,288-289,292,294, 300, 406; r. with: 125, 235, 333, 356,371,404,411-413,420, 422; take into one's reckoning, 71,81,83, 103,290,356,371, 404-405, 411, 413; timereckoning, 235, 333, 411-412, 414-418, 418 n. 5; See also Calculating; Estimating Reference, referential (Verweisung, a category): of"in order to," 68-71; constitutive of handiness, 74-76, 78-79,82-84,86,360;of indicating by signs, 77-79, 82; to self in terms of its for-the-sake-ofwhich, in understanding significance, 86-87, 110-111; to others, 117-118; context (Venueisungszusammenhang), 70, 75,77,82,87-88, ... of significance 123, 129; referential totalicy,70,75-76,82, ... of significance, 111, 123, 151, 192, 210; relation(s), 77 (of indicating), 88, 149, 151, 158 (of significance); relation of appearance, 33; venuiesen to self, with death's imminence, 250, 258 (evasively); back to thrown guilt by conscience, 281, 290-291. See also Relevance; Circumspection; Conspicuousness; Obstinacy; Obtrusiveness
References of "in order to," kinds of: listed, 68, 83, 144 (as abilities) Handiness (Handlichkeit), 68, 69, 73,108-109,127,288,355 (unhandy) Helpfulness (Beitraglichkeit), 68 Detrimentalicy, harmfulness (Ahtraglichkeit), 83, 140-141, 144,185-186,341 Serviceabilcy (Dienlichkeit), 68, 78, 82-84, 137, 144 Usabilicy (Venuendharkeit), 68, 70, 73-74,81,83-84,103,144, 353-355 Reflection (Rejlexion), 48, 60, 115, 136. See also Subject Regard; See instead Considerateness Region (Gegend, a category), 79, 103-104, 107-108, 110-112. 140, 185-186, 368-369. See also dedistancing; Directionalicy; Making room; Nearness (bringing near) Reification (Verdinglichung) 46, 420, 437 Relation (Beziehu~ Bezu~ Verhaltnis): as such, 77-78, 87-88 (Relation); between caller and called, 274; between phenomenon and logos, 54, between intellectus and res, 216; between ideal content and real object, 216; Between ideal content and act of judgment, 216; between knowing and known, 218; between statements and beings uncovered, 224; between sign and reference, 82; between man and the world, 57; between soul and world, 59; between life and death, 249 n. 6 (Dilthey); Da-sein's relationship to itself, 125, 433; Da-sein's relationship to Others, 120, 250; agreement as a, 215-216; binding and separating as, 195; indicating as a, 215; reference as a, 77-78; spatial, 54, 112; of Being, 54-55; 57,60,62, 122. 124-125; 168,
Lexicon
170, 208 n. 16, 209-210, 238; of relevance, 355, 359, 361; 'relation' as a meaning of A.Oroq, 32, 34, 159-160; non-relational (unbeziiglich), 250-260, 263-265, 280, 307, 309, 337; in the later marginal remarks (=fn), (Verhiiltni.s) of being-held-into the nothing of being (Seyn), 7fn; Bezug, 12fn, 38fn, 143fn, 240fn. See also Behavior; Connection; Directing itself toward; Existence; Intentionality; It is in its being concerned about Relativity (Relativitiit), 9, 22, 93, 97, 105,227,261,290,398,401,417 n. 6. See also Historicism; Psychologism Relevance (Bewandtni.s, a category), 80, 83-88 (§ 18), 99-100, 103-104, 110-112, 117, 123, 129, 140,144,148-150,158,186,209, 261,297,300,343,353-357, 359-361, 364, 368, 412; totality of, 84-85,87,100,104,110,129, 144,149-150,158,186,210,297, 359, 364; let things be relevant (Bewendenlassen), 84-87, 110-111, 353-356; context of, 140, 355, 359, 368, 412; relations of, 355, 359, 361, 368; is a character of spatiality, 112. See also Reference; References of "in-order-to"; Significance; Useful thing Remembering (Erinnerung), 290, 339, 343. See also Forgetting; Retaining Remoteness, Remove (Entfemtheit, a category), 103, 105-106, 108. See also De-distancing; Famess; Nearness Representation: 1. ideational (Vorstellung), 33, 62, 139,154,159,203-204,214, 217-218,319,321,354,359 ("ideas"), 367-369, 410, 424, 430; in the later marginal remarks (=fn), 8fn (-al
465
abstraction of being), 153fn (cannot thematize clearing and presence), 319fn (as placingbefore -itself). 2. personal (Vertretung), 59, 82, 126,239-240,242,253 Research (Forschung), 9-11, 19-20 (ontological), 50-52, 166 (philosophical) 213, 230, 404 (thematic); phenomenological, 27-28,34,36-39, 139; hermeneutica1232, 315; scientific, 351, 357-358, 362; historical, 393, 395-396. See also Thematization Resistance (Widerstand), 2, 91, 97-97, 137,209-211,300,356 Resoluteness (Entschlossenheit), 166, 235,267,270,297-301(§§ 60-62),313,316-317,322-323, 325-331,335-339,342-345,349, 363,382-387,390-392,394-397, 404, 410, 424; translator's note, 270 n. 5. See also Conscience; Disclosedness; Ready; Silence Resolution (Entschluss), 298-299, 307-308,338,343-344,382-383, 386-387, 397. See alsojeweiligkeit; Situation Responsible (schuldig, Schuldhaben), being or becoming, 282-283. See also Guilt; Indebtedness; Owe Reticence (Verschwiegenheit), 165, 174, 273,277,296-297,301,305, 322-323, 382, 385 as discourse proper to wanting to have conscience, 296-297. See also Discourse; Resoluteness; Silence Retrieve, repetition (Wiederholung), 2-4, 8, 17, 26, 51, 72 n. 1, 234, 304-305,308,331-333,339,343, 350,380,385-386,390-392, 394-397; of the question ofbeing, 2-4 (§ 1), 8, 26; of the analysis of Da-sein, 17, 234, 304-305, 331-333 (§ 66); of what has been ontically discovered, 51; of possibilities, 343, 385-386,
466
Being and Time
Retrieve, repetition (continued) 390-391,395-396;and anticipation, 391; and destiny, 386; and fate, 386, 390-391, 395; and the future, 386, 397; and having-been, 339, 343-344, 350, 391,394-395,397;and resoluteness, 308, 386, 392, 396. See also Heritage; Historicity; Tradition Reveal (enthilllen}, 14, 25, 73-74, 116, 127-128, 132, 135, 141, 144, 150, 221,262-263,269-270,276-277, 306-309, et passim. See also Disclosure; Veiling Rhetoric (Rhetorik), (125}, 138 341-342. See also Being-with; Discourse; Everydayness; Fear; Hermeneutics; Idle talk; Political Rootedness, roots (Venounelung), 13 (of existential in existentiell), 18, 21,27,83, 153,160,166,194, 227,290,349-351,360,372;of history and historicity in temporality, 38, 375-377, 386, 392. See also Autochthony; Foundation; Ground; Uprooting Saying (sagen): and discourse, 32, 162, 164-165; and keeping silent, 165; and speaking, 160; and understanding, 168-169; 173; without audible or explicit utterance, 406, 408, 416, 422; 'what conscience says', 269, 280; saying "I," 318-319, 321-323; saying "now," etc., 406, 408, 416, 418,421-422 "Scandal of philosophy" (Skandal der Philosophie), 203, 205 (Kant) Scepticism (Skeptizismus), 203, 228-229,400(Yorck) Schema, scheme (Schema), 78 (of form and content), 132 (of "between"), 332 (external to internal), 359-360 (of "if-then," "as," and making-present}, 365
(horizonal); schematic, 270, 332, 432 n. 30. See also Ecstatichorizonal; Ecstatic unity; Temporality Schematism (Schematismus), Kant}, 23, 40, 85fn Schlasticism (Scholastik), 22, 25, 38fn, 93, 139 Science (Wissenschaft), 9-11, 13, 26-28,31,34-35,37,45-47, 49-52,58,62,96,112,138, 152-153,171,197,213,230, 303fn (versus thinking), 315, 324, 332,357-35~ 361-363,375-376, 378,385,392-396,397-402,404, 429, 431, 433; of being, 26, 230; ofhistory, 375-376, 378, 392, 397-398,404;oflanguage, 165-166, 349; oflife, 49; of nature, 404; of phenomena, 31; of the objectively present, 324; of the psychical, 309; of the signs at hand,361;ofthetruth,213;of man, society, and the state, 398; factical, 392-393; factual, 362; theoretical science, 358; existential genesis of, 171, 258; existential conception of, 357; logical conception of, 357; objectivity of science, 395; theory of science, 45, 375-376, 398, 401; ethics as a science, 402 (Yorck); scientific attitude (or behavior), 358, 361; scientific projection, 363. See also Calculating; Human science; Knowing; Measurement; Natural science; Object; Subject; Thematization Seeing (Sehen), 32-35, 39, 44-45, 53-56,58,63,67,101,107, 119-120, 124, 138, 147-149, 153-155, 170-172, 179, 189 (in the dark), 213, 218-219, 226, 345, 351, 358, 403; as a distance-sense, 107; possibilities, 148; desire to, care for, 170-171; and curiosity, 170-17 (§ 36), 346-348; "ideas,"
Lexicon
226; priority of, 358. See also Brightness; Circumspection; Intuition; Letting (be seen); Light; Looking: Phenomenon; Perception: Sight Self, the (das Selbst), 72, 114, 117, 124, 128-130, 146, 181, 190, 193, 200,220,252-253,267-268,271, 273-274,277,280,284,288,293, 295-298,300,303,317-323,332, 339,348,354,373,375,383, 390-391,410,419,433-434;as the "who" of Da-sein, 114, 267; of everyday Da-sein, 129, 193, 252, 273; as authentic or unauthentic, 129-130,181,253,268,271,273, 280, 288, 295, 339; Da-sein's ownmost, 129, 253, 268, 271, 273, 280, 288, 295, 339; as a constitutive moment of being-inthe-world; as subject or substance, 129-130, 317, 320 n. 19, 323, 332; and the "I," 129-130,317-323, 348; as thrown, 277, 284,339, 383; as lost in the they, 271, 274, 383. and the Other, 124, 128; as being-ahead-of-itself, 193; and care, 193, 304, 316-323 (§ 64); and the call of conscience, 273-274,277,280,288,296;and resoluteness, 298, 300, 310, 391; and rapture, 348; Da-sein's understanding of Hegel on, 72; must lay the basis for itself, 284; must forget itself, 354; Hegel on, 433-434;Kanton,318-321,320 n. 19, 323; (Yorck) on, 399, 401. See also Being-one's-self; Potentiality-of-being( -one's-self); the They-self Self- (Selbst}, some important compounds: self-consciousness (Selbstbewusstein}, 401 (Yorck), 435 (Hegel); self-forgetful (selbstvergessen), 277, 322, 342, 354, 424; self-interpretation (Selbstauslegung), 51, 116, 184,
467
196-197, 200, 312, 318; "selfknowledge" (Selbsterkenntnis}, 146; self-point (Selbstpunkt), 146, 179; self-thing (Selbstding), 323; selfsubsistence, autonomy (Selbststiindigkeit}, 291-292, 303, 332; self-constancy (Selbststiindigkeit}, 322-323, 332, 373. See also "It is in its being concerned about ... "; Understanding-itself Selfness (Selbstheit), 267, 304, 316-320,322-323 Selfsameness (Selbigkeit}, 114, 130, 188,218,320,322,373,423,435; of the self, 114, 130,320,373. See also Constancy; Presence, constant; Self; Substantiality Semblance: See instead Being and Seeming; Illusion Sensing (Empjinden), 137, 152-153, 163-164, sensation (Sinnlichkeit}, 97, 271fn (sensuous), 271 fn (senses) Serviceability (Dienlichkeit}, 68, 78, 82-84, 137, 144. See also References of "in order to"; Relevance Showing itself, self-showing (Sichz.eigen), 28-31, 35-36, 57, 63, 67-68, 72-73, 97 137-138, 140, 155,173,213,218-219,222,361, 421, et passim. See also Phenomenon Shrinking back (Zuriickweichen}, 23 (Kant's from the "abyss"), 185 (from angst) Sight (Sicht), 69, 75, 133, 139, 146-149, 154, 167, 170 (curiosity), 173, 294, 336, 346-347, 358-359, 412; of Dasein is the understanding grounding all other sights 146-147, 336; formally taken as any access made possible by clearing of being, 147, 170; not perceiving, intuiting, taking cognizance, or "cognition,"
468
Being and Time
Sight (continued) 147, 336, 387. See also Clearing; Light; Seeing; Understanding; and the other "sights": Circumspection of taking-care Considerateness (regard) of concern/ solicitude "Just looking," of theoretical attitude and curiosity Transparency (perspicuity) of selfcare Sighting (sichten), 33, 45, 75, 146, 312,359,412 Sign (Zeichen), 76-83 (§ 17), 108, 215 Significance (Bedeutsamkeit), 83-83 (§ 18), 104, 110-111, 123, 129, 143-148, 151, 158, 161, 166, 186-187,192,209-210,297,334, 343,364-366,414,422-423,427. See also Understanding; World Signify, signification (bedeuten, Bedeutung: also "significance" and "meaning," the latter usually in reference to terms and expressions), 31, 87 (as worldly), 93 (of being as analogous), 161 (its whole related to meaning), 165 (categories of), 166 (and language) 168 (as context), 369, et passim. See also Discourse; Language;~eaning
Silence, keeping silent (Schweigen), 161,164-165,183,273,277,296, 323; conscience speaks in the mode of 273, 277; as stillness, 296, 398. See also Discourse; Reticence Situation (Situation), 158, 189, 232-233,235,299-300,302,304, 307, 310-316 (§ 63), 326, 328, 338,345,347,349,360,371,382, 384, 391, 397, 410; borderline(Grenzsituation), 249 n. 6, 301 n. 17, 308, 349; hermeneutical (hermeneutische Situation),
(150-153), 232-233, 235, 304, 310-315 (§ 63), 397. See also Resoluteness; Resolution
Solipsism (Solipsismus), 188 Soul (Seele), 14, 23, 46, 48, 59, 114, 117, 202,214,318,402 (Yorck), 405, 427. See also Psychical; Life Source (Quelle), 6, 21 ("wellsprings"), 70, 220, 350; transmitted historical, 6, 21, 393, 396, 410. See also Historian; Historiography; World history Space, spatial (Raum, riiumlich, a category), 9, 18, 31, 54-56,§§ 22-24,66,68,79,89,101-113, 119-120,132,141,166,186,299, 333, 335, 367-369 (§ 70), 416-418, 429-430 (Hegel), 432 n. 30; positions, 102, 107, 119, 368-369; receptacle (Raumgefiiss), 101; spatial significations, 166, 299, 369 + fn; in itself, 112; of nature, (Naturraum), 112; pure, 112; and region, 110-111, 186, 368-369; and time, spatiality and temporality, 18, 31, 333, 335, 367-369 (§ 70), 416-418, 429-430 (Hegel), spatial temporal, 362, 367; giving space (Raum-geben), Ill; taking space in (Raum einnehmen), 368-369; stretch of (Raumstrecke), 106, 428; world space, 54, 204; spatially-local ( riiumlich.{irtlich ), 417; Bergson on, 18, 333, 432 n. 30; Descartes on, 89; Hegel on, 429-430, 432 n. 30; Kant on space, 89 Spatiality (Riiumlichkeit, an existential): of Da-sein, 56, 89, 101-113 (§§ 22-24), 119-120, 132, 141,299,335,367-369(§ 70); of the "there," 132, 299; of being-in-the-world, 79, 101, 104-110 (§ 23}, 141, 299; of being-in, 54, 105-106, 186; of the world, 101 + fn, 110-112, 369; of the 'world', 112; of the surrounding world, 60, 66, 89, 112; of beings encountered in the surrounding world, 10 I; of things
Lexicon at hand, 102-104 (§ 22), 110, 112, 418; of extended things, 112-113, 368; spatializing (verriiumlichen), 108,112,418 Spirit, spiritual (Geist, geistig), 22, 26, 47 n. 2 (Husserl), 48, 56, 89, 117, 152, 198, 320 n. 19 (Hegel), 368, 379, 395, 397, 401, (Yorck) 404, 405-406 (Hegel), 427, 428-436 (§ 82) Stand (Standgewonnenhaben), gained through constancy of resoluteness, 322. See also Constancy; Existence (ek-sistence); Position; Self-constancy Standpoint (Standpunkt), 19, 21-22, 61,208, 402; phenomenology versus, 27, 152 Statement, proposition (Aussage, Satz.): as apophantical discourse,§ 7B; derivative from the hermeneutical "as," §§ 13, 33, 69b; as traditional place of truth, § 44a, b; interim stages between hermeneutical and theoretical, 157fn, 158; transcendental [example], 31, § 82; ontological 76, 82; phenomenological [example], 120; existentialontological [examples], 153, 207, 332; ontic-suprasensuous, 318fn. See also Apophantic "as"; Diairesis; Judgment; Predicate Staying, lingering (Verweilen), 61, 120, 138, 172 (not-staying of curiosity), 222, 238, 346-347, 358. See also Dwelling Steadfastness (Standfestigkeit), 322. See also Constancy; Persistence; Resoluteness; Situation; Stand Steadiness (Stiitigkeit), 390-391, 398. See also Constancy; Persistence; Resoluteness Stream (Strom, Fluss): of experiences, 194, 344, 388; of "nows," 410, 422, 426; of time, 426, 432. See also Succession
469
Stretch (Strecke), 23, 106, 285, 374, 417-418. See also Connection, between birth and death; Span; Stretching along; Succession Stretching along (Erstrecktheit, Erstreckung), 371 (temporal), 373-375 (between birth and death), 390-391 (ecstatic), 409-410,417-418,423.Seealso Being and movement; Steadiness; Persistence; Constancy Structure, Structural (Struktur, struktural): of the question of being, 5-8(§ 2), 14; of existence, 12, 44, et passim; of being-in-theworld, 41, 53, 58, 64, 66, et passim; of experience, 46; of Da-sein, 54, 56, et passim; as-, 149, 151, 154, 158,359-360;ofcare, 196,259, 317,323,328,331-332,346,350; end-structure, 244, 246; forestructure, 151-153; of temporalization-structure, 332; of world, 366, 414; of truth, 216, 223, 226; structural moments, 5, 24,41,53,63, 101,117,130-131, 140,162,176, 181,209,230,232; totality (Strukturganz.heit), 131, 182, 193, 209, 234, 334; whole, (Strukturganz.e), 65, 131, 180-184 (§ 39), 191-192, 231-233, 236, 252,316-317, 323-325,350.See also Constitution; Whole Subject, subjectivity (Subjekt, Subjektivitiit), 14, 22, 24, 46-47, 59-62, 109-111, 113-114, 123-126,128-130,154-156,204, 227,229-230,316-322,366,388, 419, 427, et passim; subject-object relation, 59, 216, 388; versus Dasein, 60, 229; versus self, 303, 322; versus objectivity, 395, 405, 411, 419; isolated, 118, 179, 188, 204, 206, 321; worldless, 110-111, 116, 192, 206, 366; of others, 119, 121, 123, 126, 128, 384; objectively present, 119, 121, 123, 128,
470
Being and Time
Subject, subjectivity (continued) 131-132, 176, 320; 'ideal', 229; absolute, 228, 318; knowing, 47, 69; of everydayness, 114, 128; 'factual' and factical 229; 'theoretical', 316; 'historical', 382; 'logical', 319 (Kant); versus predicate, 154-155, 318-319; the a priori and the, 229, (Cf 110); truth and the, 227, 229; time and, 62, 109-110, 164; subjectivity of the, 24; 'subjectivity' of the world, 65, 366; 'subjectivity' of time, 419, 427; 'subjectivity' of world-time, 419; Kant on the, 24, 109, 204, 319-321 Submission to (Angewiesenheit auf= dependence/reliance on [the world]), 87, 137, 139, 161, 297, 348, 383,412. See also Abandon; Surrender; lbrowness Subsist, subsistence (Bestehen, Bestand), 7, 153, 216, 284, 288, 303, 333, 348, 352, 420, 430; in a marginal remark: the there is to "perdure" (bestehen) being as such, 42fn. See also Constancy; Persistence; Self-subsistence; Steadfastness; Substance Substance, substantiality (Substanz, Substantialitiit), 22, 46-47, 63, 68, 87-90,92-96,98,100,114,117, 201,212,303,314,317-323,320 n. 19, 398, 435; as basic attribute ofbeing, 201; ontology of the, 319,320 n. 19; and subject, 2, 317, 321, 332; and self, 114,303,317, 320 n. 10, 323, 332; and the "I" 317-318,320, 322; and person, 47,320 n. 19; and spirit, 117; and Da-sein's subsistence, 303; soulsubstance, 26, 114, 318; man's substance, 117b, 212, 314; and world, 90, 94, 96; corporeal substance, 90, 92; and the objectively present, 114, 318; and Reality, 212; and function, 88;
Descartes on, 90, 92-96, 98, 100; Kant on, 318-323; Scheler on, etc., 4 7. See also Reality; Subject Succession (Folge, Abfolge): also Nacheinander, 242 (debt paid in sequence),291,350,374,422 (sequence of nows), 426, 430; s. of experiences, 291 (in "serial connection"), 293, 355, 373-374, 387-388, 390; of ecstasies, 350; of days, 371; of processes, 379; of resolutions, 387; of nows, 329, 373,409,422~426,431-432.See
also Connection (of occurrences); Suicide (Selbstmord), 229 Sum (Summe), 125-127, 187, 210, 242-244, 244 n. 3, 370, 374. See also Whole Summons (Anruf, Aufru!, of conscience), 269-275, 277-280, 287-290,292,294-297,299-300, 307,313,317. See also Call of conscience Sun (Sonne), 71, 103, 412-413, 415-416, 432 n. 30 (Hegel). See also Brightness; Light Surrender (sick ausliejem) to, 128 (they), 139 ("world"), 144 (thrownness), 199 (world taken care of), 299 (interpretedness of they), 412 (changes of day and night). See also Abandon; Delivered Over; Thrownness Surrounding world ( Umwelt), 57-58, 58fn ("surroundings"), 65-66, 70-72,75,79-80,82-83,89,101, 104-107, 112-133, 117, 126, 136, 158,172,209,239,300,334,342, 349,352,354,356,359,361-362, 413, 416. See also Public world; With-world; Work-world; World Symbol (Symbol), 29, 77-78, 163. See also Sign Symptom (Anzeichen, Symptom), 29, 78, 80. See also Sign Synthesis (Synthese, Synthesis), 33-34, 117, 159-160, 178,430 (Hegel)
Lexicon System (System), 36, 87-88, 159, 432 n. 30; systematics (Systematik), 10, 22,51, 138,244n.3,402,428 Taking care (Besorgen, also "heedfulness"), 57-58,61,67-76, 78, 103-104, ll1, ll9, 126, 131, 189,351-360,364,369-371, 406-416,419-422,424-425,et passim; distinguished from concern, 121-124; distinguished from care, 193-195. See also Associations; Care; Circumspection; Clocks; Concern; Hammer; Heedfulness; Useful things Tautology {Tautologie), 35, 193, 318. See also Circle Technology, technical (Technik, technisch), 27, 303 + fn, 358, 418 n. 5. See also Method; Practice; Science Temporality (Temporalitiit) of being, 19,23-26,38fn,39-40, 147; Tenses (Tempora) as temporal phenomenon of language, 349; tempo (Tempo) of talk, 162. See also Clearing; Ecstatic unity; Temporality, horizonal Temporal, temporality (zeitlich, Zeitlichkeit) of Da-sein, 17-19, 38fn, 100fn,234-235,303-305, 321fn,326-354,356-357, 359-360,363-377,379,381-382, 385-386,388-389,391-393, 396-397,404-428,435-437; authentic, 304, 327, 329, 331, 338, 348,373,385,410,414; inauthentic, 304, 326, 329, 331, 391, 424; ecstatic, 38fn, 100fn, 329,331,356,366,369,388,393, 408, 426, 437; horizonal, 369, 388, 393, 420, 426; ecstatic-horizonal 426; primordial, 325-331 (§ 65), 349 (of taking care), 436 et passim; enables transcendence, § 69c. See also Clearing; Ecstatic unity;
471
Horizon; Temporalitiit; Temporalizing; Transcendence Temporalizing (Zeitigung, lit. ripening, maturing, bringing to fruition), 22, 122, 152, 178, 235, 304,328-350,342,344,349-350, 352-355,365-366,375-376,381, 388,395-397,405-416,420-421, 425-427, 436-437; modes of, 333, 348, 437; structure of, 332. See also Es gibt; Movement "That it is ... and has to be," the (das "Dass es ist ... und z.u sein hat"), 134-136,276,284,340,343;the fact that it is (Dass-sein), 5, 7, 17; the "that it is there" (das "dass-esda-ist"), 265. See also Abandon; Thrownness Thematization (Thematisierung), 2, 4, 9, 16,23-26,27,31,61,67-69, 74-76,83,111-113,124,145, 149-150,238-239,354,362-365, 375-376,393,397,421-422.See also Knowing; Objectivation; Science; Theory "Then," the (das Dann), 406-414, 421-422,427 Theology (Theologie), 10, 28, 34, 48-49, 139, 190 n. 4, 229, 248, 249 n. 8, 269, 272 n. 8, 290, 306 n 2. See also God Theory (Theorie), 59, 67, 69, 81, 136, 138,157-158,166,193,199,248, 251,257-258,261,300,312, 315-316 320 n. 19, 335, 351-352, 356-364 (§ 69b), et passim. See also "just looking"; Objectivation; Practice; Subject; Thematization There, the (das Da), 75, 102, 119, 132-133, 134-166 (1, V, A). 166-180 (1, V, B), 220-221, 237, 263,265,270,276,284,296-300, 311,326,334-336,339,343, 347-350,364,366,382,385,391, 406,408,410,412-413,415,a passim; in the later marginal remarks (~ fn), 39fn, 42fn, 87fn,
472
Being and Time
There, the (continued) 133fn, 162fn. See also Being-in; Clearing: Disclosedness; Openness "There is": See instead Es gibt They, the (das Man), 114, 126-130, 138, 167, 170, 174-179, 184-185, 188-190,192-195,222,224, 252-255,257-258,260,263, 266-268,270-274,277-278, 287-289,292,296-300,307-309, 312,315,318,322,331-332,371, 383,387,390-391,395,424-425; publicness of 138, 188, 190, 192, 252-253,271,277-278;common sense of, 260, 288, 292, 296, 309, 312, 387, 395; way things have been interpreted by, 190, 252, 258, 273, 309, 331; idle talk of, 174,252-255,277-278,296; ambiguity of, 174; tranquillization by the they, 177, 195, 254; Beingwith-one-another in, 175; everyday Being-one's-self and, 126-130 (§ 27), 252; inauthentic being (or existence) in, 178-179, 367; authentic Being-one's-self as a modification of, 267-268, 277; absorption in, 167, 175, 184, 189, 222, 270, 315; lostness in, 175, 177,189,253,268,271,274,287, 289,297,299,307-308,383,390; listening away to, 271; fleeing into, 322; falling and, 135, 189, 277, 287, 331; as hero, 371; as determining one's attunement, 170, 177, 254; passing over, 273; the they and the call, 296; and resoluteness, 299, 307; and the situation, 300; and retrieve, 391; and death, 252-255, 257, 263, 266,424-425;andtime,411,425 They-self (Man-selbst), 129, 181, 193, 263,266-268,271-274,276-278, 280,288,299,303,311,317,322, 337, 391. See also the I; the Self Thing, thingliness (Ding[lichkeit]), 46-49,54,63-64,67-69,73-74,
79-83,90-91,96-100,114,121, 124, 130, 203-204, 369, et passim. See also Objective presence; Things at hand; Useful things Things at hand (Zuhandene), 69-88, 102-113, 437, et passim. See also Handiness; Useful things Things themselves, [to] the (die Sachen selbst), the phenomenological maxim, 9, 27, 34, 38 n. 5, 95, 153, 166, 213, 219, 256, 358; Sachheit (thinghood, "factuality" ), 94fn, 201fn, 209fn. See also Object; Phenomenology; Phenomenon Think, thinking ([D]enken), 62, 303fn, et passim; "I think," 24, 319-321, 427, thinking as 8tavoeiv, 96; pure, 88; as a derivative from understanding, 147; about death, 254,257-258,261,309;tothe end,305,424 This-worldly, the (das Diesseits), 248; See also Death Thrown, thrownness (Gewoifen{heit]), 122, 135-13~ 139, 144-145, 148, 161 + fn, 167, 175, 179, 181, 183fn (Da-sein as the thrown of the throw), 188-189, 191-192, 19lfn, 195-196,199,221,223,228, 251-252,256,259,265,270, 271fn,276-277,284-287,291, 297,299,306,308,323,325, 328-329,339-340,342-345, 347-348,364-366,374,382-383, 385-386,391,394,396,406, 410-412,415,424,435;into existence, 276; into the there, 135, 148, 265, 284, 297, 413; into a world, 192,228,348,383,406, 413; into uncanniness, 343; into indefmiteness, 298, 308; into the possibility of death, 251; into being-towards-death, 348; into death, 251, 256, 308, 329; into the "nothing," 277; thrown being-inthe-world, 161, 181, 189, 191-192,
Lexicon
259, 383; being-with-one-another, 175; being-toward-the end, 251; being-towards-death, 344, 348; ground,284,287,306,325; individualization, 280, 343; possibility, 144-145; potentiality of being, 188, 339; and facticity, 135,179,221,276,284,328,348, 410, 414, 436; and everydayness, 167; and disclosedness, 221, 276, 215; and falling, 179, 415, 424; and turbulence, 179; and abandonrnent,347,365,406,413; and mood, attunernent, etc., 135-136,139,144,179,181,251, 270, 276, 328, 340, 365; and fear, 342; and angst, 187, 191, 251, 343-344; and predilection and urge, 196; and care, 383, 406, 412; and project, 145, 138, 195, 199, 223,285,336,406;and conscience, 291; and beingtowards-death, 344, 348, 374; and time-reckoning, 412-413; taking over one's, 383, 385; corning back behind one's thrownness, 284, 383; throwing against, (entgegenweifen), 363. See also Abandon; Deliver over; Dependence; Facticity; Submission to; Surrender Time (Zeit): as the horizon for the understanding or interpretation of being, 1, 17, 39, 41,235, 437; the ordinary way to understanding or interpreting time, 18, 235, 304, 326, 328-329, 338 n. 3, 404-437 (II.VI; esp. § 81); traditional conception of, 18, 24, 235, 349, 428, 432 n. 30; everyday experience of, 333, 405, 420; primordial and derivative, 329-332, 405, 426, 436; and care, 235,327,424;andthethey,425; and idle talk, 174; and space, (see entry under 'space}; and history, 379, 404-405; and spirit,
473
405-406, 428-436 (§ 82), 427; allowing time, (Zeit-lassen), 404, 409-410, 414; assigning time, (Zeit angeben, Zeit-angabe),
408-410, 413, 418, 422; counting time, 421-422; dating time, 408-09,412,413,415,417,422; expressing time, (Zeit aussprechen), 406-408, 410-411, 421-422; giving the time, (Zeit geben), 412-413, 420, 422, 432 n. 30; having time, (Zeit haben), 404, 409-410,418-419,422,425; interpreting time, 407-414; levelling down time, 329, 405, 422, 424-426, 431-432, 432 n. 30, 435; losing time, 404, 410, 418, 425; measuring, 71, 413-419,417 n. 4, 422; reading off (Zeit ablesen), (tell time, 70), 415-417; taking time, taking one's time, (sich Zeit nehmen), 404-405,410-413,416,418,421, 424-425; using time (Zeit brauchen), 235, 333, 409; taking care of time, 353, 406-420 (§ 79, 80), 422; time-reckoning, 235, 333, 411-412, 414-418 n. 5; reckoning with time, 235, 333, 371, 404, 411-413, 422; taking time into one's reckoning, 371, 404-405, 411, 413; 'time goes on', 330, 425; 'time passes away', 330, 425-426; time as finite, endless, in-finite, 330-331, 424-426; as continuous, 423; as irreversible, 426; stream of time, 426, 432; course of time, 400, 422, 432 n. 30; point of time, (Zeitpunkt), 374, 407; 'past', 380; 'fugitive', 425; 'qualitative', 333; 'psychical', 349; 'subjective' or 'objective', 326, 405, 411, 419, 427; "immanent" or "transcendent," 326, 419; "time for ... ," 412, 414; in time (in der Zeit) 18-19, 204, 330, 338, 338 n.
474
Being and Time
Time (continued) 3,340-341,349,355,367, 373-374,376,379,381-382, 404-405,412,419-420,425,428, 435; timeless, 18, 156, 382; nowtime, (jet:J-Zeit), 421, 423, 426; world-time (Weltzeit); 405-406, 414,417,417 n. 4, 417 n. 5, 419-423,426-428,428-436(§ 82); Aristotle on, 26, 40, 42, 427, 427 n. 14, 432 n. 30; Augustine on, 427, 427 n. 15; Bergson on, 18, 26, 333, 432 n. 30; Hegel on, 405-406, 427, 428-436 (§ 82), 432 n. 30; Hyginus on, 338 n. 3; Plato on, 423; the being of time, 406, 419, 432. See also Leeway; Space: Temporality; Within-time-ness To-be (Zu-sein), 42 + fn (having to be). See also Formal indication; Having to be; Way to be Today (heute), 371, 378, 381, 386, 391, 397, 407, 409. See also Critique; the Present; Now Tolerance (Nachsicht): one of the regards or "sights" of concerned being-with, 123. See also Considerateness; Sight Tool (Werkzeug), 50, 68-69, 73-74, 157, 354-355, 360-361. See also Useful thing Totality (Ganzhei4 das Ganze [the whole]): of being-in-the-world, 231;ofcare, 193-194,196,317, 324, 374; of Da-sein, 234, 237-240, 241-246 (§ 48), 249, 265,309-310,316,323,373,437; of Da-sein's being, 182, 230 232-233,236,265,323,327,436; of Da-sein's potentiality of being, 266; of Da-sein's structural whole, 180-184 (§ 39), 191-192, 233, 236,253,317, 323-324; ofbeings, 9, 14,64,241,248;ofuseful things, 68-69, 76, 79-82, 103-104, 112,352-354,361,369; of occurrences; 390, of relevance;
84-85,87,100,104,110-111,129, 144,149-150,158,186,210,297, 359, 364; of places, 102-103, 111-112, of resoluteness, 383; of signification, 161; of temporalizing, 406; of words, 161; constitutive totality, 373; referential totality, 70, 75-76, 82, 111, 123, 192, 210; relational totality, 87, 215-216; structural totality, 131, 182, 193, 209, 234, 334; lack of totality, ( Unganz.heit), 236, 242, 244 n.3, 259. See also Constitution; Sum; Structure; Whole Tradition(al) (Tradition(eU), Uberlieferung), 4, 10-11, 18, 20-22, 24,26,42,48-49,96,98-100, 129,138,147,197,214,219-220, 223,225,235,270fn,333,349, 395, 400, 403, 427, 429, 432 n. 30; conception of time, 18, 235, 349, 428, 432 n. 30; conception of truth, 214-226 (§§ 441, b); ontology,22,25-27,54,65,96, 99-100, 147, 403. See also Hand down; Retrieve Tranquillization (Beruhigung), 177-178, 180, 188-189, 195, 253-254,292,311,347-348,400, 437. See also Alienation; Entanglement; Falling prey; Temptation Transcendence (Transzendenz), 38 (of the being of Da-sein), 38fn, 39fn (-like), 49 (idea of), 61 (and immanence of knowing), 202 (of consciousness into reality) 364 (of Da-sein); of the world (as a problem), 335, 350-351, 363-364, 366, 389; world-time has the same t. as the world, 419; as Temporality, 38fn. See also Clearing; Ecstatic unity; Temporality of being; Temporality, horizonal; Time (world-time)
Lexicon
Transcend(ing) ([T]ranszendieren, verbal), 61 (of the subject), 202, 351,363 Transcendent (traruzendent), 326 (objective time vs. immanent subjective time), 366 (world, in the horizonal unity of ecstatic temporality) Transcendental (traruzendental), 3 (universal), 11 (logic), 22 (philosophy), 24, (determination of time: Kant), 31 (statement), 38 (knowledge, truth) 38fn (philosophy), 41 (horizon of time), 85fn (present perfect tense), 96 (foundations) 199 ("universality" of care), 208 (being is the T. for beings), 215 (dialectic of Kant), 319 (subject), 319 n. 16 + 320 n. 19 (apperception); tranS
475
&n. 11,86, 100,113,206,230, 234-235,303,313,324,333, 388, 392, 404. See also Sight; Understanding, circle of Truth (Wahrheit), § 44 (as disclosedness and discoveredness); §§ 60, 62, 64 (as resoluteness); 33, 429, et passim; in the later marginal remarks(~ fn): of being, 7fn, 35fn, 38fn (Seyn), 143fn, 252 (Seyn); question of, 46fn; essence of, 84fn (lecture on), 87fn, 227fn; letting it presence, 85fn; being and 183, 213,227,230,349,357,420; being of, 226-230 (§ 44c); beingtrue, 33, 218-220, 226-227; beingin-the-truth, 24-25, 172, 226-227, 229,256,264,298,363;of assertion, 154, 218, 223, 225, 228; ofjudgment,33-34,225,297;of the M:lro~, 33, 219, 225; of knowledge, 46-47; of pure beholding, 171; ofvOEiv, 33, 171; of sensory perception, 33; of the objectively present, 264; of Newton's laws, 226-227; of existence, 221, 297, 307, 397; as agreement,33, 214-225;as validity, 357; as discovering and Being-discovering, 218-220, 225-227; as discoveredness and being-discovered, 219-220, 222, 224-225, 256; as being-disclosive, 256; as disclosedness, 221, 223, 225,264-265,297,397; phenomenological (veritas trarucendentalis), 38; primordial, 33, 214, 219-226 (§ 44b), 297-298, 307, 316; authentic, 297-299, 302, 316; existential, 316; existentiell, 316; 'eternal', 227, 229; 'subjective', 227; 'universal', 227; presupposing, 226-230 (§ 44c); maintaining oneself in the truth, 256, 264, 298; and certainty, 264, 362; 'There is
4 76
Being and Time
Truth (continued) truth', 226-228, 316; true propositions and science, 11, 357; truth-daims, 256; pre-ontological conception of, 225; traditional conception of, 214-226 (§ 44a, b); Greek conception of: 33-34, 219, 222; Heraclitus on, 219; Parmenides on, 222; Aristotle on, 33, 214, 219, 225-226; Thomas Aquinas on, 214; Kant on, 215; Hegel on, 429, 431; Yorck on, 402-403. See also Disclosedness; Discoveredness; Resoluteness; Unconcealment; Untruth Typology (Typologie), 21, 52, 178, 247, 249 n. 6. See also Alienation; Culture; Curiosity Uncanny (unheimlich), 170, 188-190, 192,252,276-278,280,286-287, 289,295-296,342-344.Seealso Ang.tt; At-home; Familiarity Unconcealment (Unverborgenehit), 33, 219. See also Concealment; Truth Uncovering: See instead Discovery Understanding (Verstehen, act of), 6-7,12-13,85-86, 100fn, 133, 147fn,l42-154, 156,158, 160-165, 167-170, 173-174, 180-184, 183fn (as hearing), 200-201,220-223,262-263, 269-270,279-280,289-293, 295-297,305-315, 316fn, 324-326,334-340,359-361,437, et passim; fundamental existential, 143-144, 148, 336; its most primordial knowing is circle, 152, 314-315. See also Project; Sight Understanding itself (Sichverstehen), 144-146 (Sichverlegen) 266, 287, 292,295,298,336-337,348,364; projecting-itself, 191, 194-195, 276,287,296-297,301,305,327, 339,343,382-383,385-387,394; expressing-itself (Sichaussprechen ), 162, 168, 222, 223-224; self-
referring (Sichverweisen), 86-87, 110. See also Ahead of itself; Finding itself; For-the-sake-ofwhich; "It is in its being concerned about ... "; Selfinterpreting Understanding of Being (Seinsverstiindnis, state or condition), 1, 4-6, 8 + fn (abode of), 11-13, 12fn, 15-17,20,26, 37,43fn,58,60,67,72,86,89, 123-124, 147, 153fn, 150, 182-183,197,200-201,206-207, 212-213,222,225,230-231,235, 301,313-316,325,361-364,372, 387,389,405-406,421-422,426, 437; average vague, 4-6, 8, 168; formally indicated, 12, et passim; pre-ontological, 12. See also Clearing; Intelligibility; "It is in its being concerned about ... "; Sight Underway (unternlegl): Dilthey, toward the question of "life," 46; Da-sein is always, 79; Being and Time itself is, 437. See also Method; Way Unity (Einheit): of analogy, 3; of being-in-the-world, 53, 351; of being-outside-of itself, 430 (Hegel); unity of care, 181, 316, 327-328, 351; of Da-sein's constitution, 200; of Da-sein's existential structure, 351; of experiences, 390; of horizontal schemata, 365; of the I, 433 (Hegel); of living-through, 4 7 (Scheler); of meaning, 48 (Scheler); of nature, 144; of the person, 47-48 (Scheler); of project, 407; of relations, 354; of significance, 365; of spatiality, 104; of the structural whole, 317, 325 of temporality, 339-340, 365-366,369,408,423;of temporalizing, 354, 427; of the there, 366; of things of nature, 48; of the world, 364; ecstatic
Lexicon unity, 328, 338-340, 342, 346, 349-350, 353, 355, 363 n. 22, 365, 381, 408, 421, 423; of future and having-been, 397; of makingpresent and retentive awaiting, 355, 416; of the ontic and the historical, 403; of the reference of serviceability and the reference of indicating, 78; of thrownness and being-towardsdeath, 374; unitary phenomena, 53, 151, 181, 326; unitary structures, 130-131, 192; of places, 104fn. See also Ecstatic Unity; Sum; Whole Universal(ity) (Allgemein[heit], Universal[itiit]), 2-4, 38-39, 156, 177-178,251,278,280,395,417, 434 (Hegel); transcendental u. of being, 3, 14, 38-39, 199-200, 208; validity, 156, 2205 n. 15, 227, 395. See also Concept; Existentials; Genus; Individualization; jeweiligkeit; Transcendentals Untruth ( Unwahrheit), 222-223, 229, 256-257,298-299,308 Upon-which, the (da.s Woraufoin, woraufoin): 1. As noun: 86 (significance), 151 (meaning), 210 (what drive and will are out to get) 324-325 (meaning of care grounded in ecstatic temporality). 2. As preposition: 6 (what is asked about "in terms of which" beings are understood), 85-86 (that for which beings are freed = understanding of world), 110 (that for which space is discovered = region), 143 (that for which world is disclosed= significance), 145 (that upon which understanding projects .. possibility), 157 (direction in which beings have been presented), 273 (to that which
477
one is summoned in call), 298 (to that which Da-sein discloses itself in resoluteness), 365 (whereupon Da-sein is disclosed). See also Circle, hermeneutical; Meaning; Project Uprooting (Entwurzelung), of historicity by transmission, 21-22, 170, 173, 177, 196, 222. See also Ground; Rootedness Urge (Drang), 10, 194-196. See also Care; Predilection; Willing; Wishing Usability: See instead References of "in order to" Use (verwenden), 56,67-70,74, 83-84,99,102-103,144,235,333, 352-353, 357, et passim. See also References of "in order to" Useful thing (Zeug), 68-70, 72-82, 107-110,352-355,380-381, 387-389, 422, et passim; totality of, 68-69, 76, 79-82, 103-104, 112, 352, 358, 361, 369; manifold of, 79; context of, 75, 78, 102-103, 109-110,118,352,355,359,361, 364, 380; world of, 354, 359, 413. See also Innerworldly; Handiness; Things at hand; Within-time-ness; World history Using (Verwenden, Gebrauchen): and handling, 67, 69, 102, 352, 357, 359; clocks, 404, 414-418, 420-421; signs, 79, 81-82; time, 235,333,409;up,244-245,333; unusable, 73-74, 355; thing of use (Gebrauchsding), 99 Utilitarianism (Niltz.lichkeitmoral), 293 Validity (Geltung; Gilltigkeit}, 7, 99, 127,155-156,227,357,395 Value (Werl), 63, 69, 80, 99-100, 150, 152,227,286,293-294 Veil, conceal (verhilllen), 21, 30, 36, 59,74,81,103-104,135-136,140, 155,158-159,166,253-254,258. See also Cover up; Reveal
4 78
Being and Time
Violent (gewaltsam), typically said of phenomenological interpretation, 183,287,311,313,315,327;that is "wrested" (abgerungen) from everyday untruth, 2, 222 (robbery), 311. See also Destructuring Voice (Stimme): alien, 277; mysterious, 274; of conscience, 268-269,271,275,280,290-292, 294, 300; of the friend, 163; ofthe "they," 278; which is universally binding, 278. See also Call of conscience; Discourse; Idle talk; Rhetoric Vulgar (vulgar): conception of Being, 387, 389; conception of Being guilty, 282; conception of conscience, 269-270, 279, 289-295 (§ 59); conception of the 'connectedness of life', 374; conception of Da-sein, 374, 378, 427; conception of historicality, 377; conception of history, 376-377, 378-382 (§ 73); conception of phenomenon, 31, 35, 37; conception of time, 17-18, 24,235,304,326,329-330,333, 338 n. 3, 404-437 (II, VI) Way (Weg) of investigating (in the course of this treatise), V, 1, 7 (circular), 23, 24 (of destructuring return), 27, 39, 50, 51 n. 11, 55, 58 (of privation), 59, 63-64, 72, 98-99, 181, 194 (of reductive privation), 201, 222 (Parmenides'), 228, 232, 242, 271, 276,302,311,319,363,370,375 (of phenomenological construction), 393-394, 402 (Yorck's), 427 n. 13 (via negationis et eminentiae), 432 n. 30 (from Kant to Hegel), 436-437, 437fn (not "the" sole way); 437, Conclusion: "Is there a way from original time to the sense of
being?" See al5o Circle;
Construction; De-struction; Method; Underway Way to be, way of being (Weise zu sein), 14, 42, 126-128 (of the they), 130, 133 (ofattunement and understanding), 176 (everyday being-in, taking-care, concern), 245 (of death), 312 (of concealment) 371 (of everydayness). See also Existentials; Existing; Have to be; To-be We-world (Wir-welt), 65. See also; Public world; With-world; Workworld Whence, the (das Woher), 134-136, 280, 348. See also Origin; Thrownness Whither, the (das Wohin), 103, 108, 110-111,134-136,280,365,368. See also Being-toward-the-end "Who," the (das Wer), 45, 53, 113, 114-117 (§ 25), 126, 128-131, 267,276,311,317,375 Whole, the (das Ganze), esp. 244 n. 3; of Da-sein, 181, 191-192, 200, 230, 232-233, 237-241 (§ 47), 259,264,306,317,329,372-373, 436; of being-in-the-world, 41, 137,152, 180;ofcare,221,300;of life, 46; of discourse, 163; of places, 48; the moon as a, 243; and sum, 244 n. 3; Being-a-whole (Ganzsein), 234, 235-267 (11.1 esp. § 46), 301-305 (§ 61), 317, 325, 331, 372-373; in the later marginal remarks (=fn): of the being of Da-sein, 316fn; being on the whole, 12, 37. See also Potentiality of being (a whole); Sum; Totality Wholeness (Giinze), 236-238, 240. See also Constitution; Sum; Totality Will (Wille, noun), 136, 182, 209-211,271,275 Willing (Wollen, verb), 194-195, 210, 290-293. See al5o Care; Wishing
Lexicon
Wishing (Wunschen), 162, 182, 194-195. See also Care; Predilection; Urge; Willing With (mit): the "with," 118; the withwhich (das Womit), 85-88, 158, 352-353; with one another (miteinander), 120-127, 129-130, 138, 142, 161-162, 164-165, 168, 173-175,177,238-240,252-253, 273,282,298,354,370,379,384, 387-388,410-411,413,416,425; Being without one another (Ohneeinandersein), 121 With-world (Mitwelt), 118, 125, 129, 300 Within-timeness (Innmeitigkeit), 235, 333, 338, 338 n. 3, 349, 377, 404-406,411-412,417,420,426, 428, 436. See also Now-time; Time Word(s) (Wort[e]), 87, 159, 161 (accrue to significations), 164, 219-220 (power of the most elemental), 273,402 (Yorck). See also Discourse; Grammar; Language; Rhetoric; Statement Work (Werk), 69-70, 352-354, 387-389,395,412 Work-world (Werkwelt), 71, 117, 172, 352. See also Surrounding world World (Welt): defmed, 63-65, 72, 75, 364-365,380,414;inthe marginal remarks (=fn): 52fn (concept of), 58fn (Da-sein never "has"), 65fn, 88fn (its sway), 101fn (also spatial), 246fn; abandonment to the, 172, 412; absorption in the, 125,129-130,172, 192;being together with the, 54, 119, 146, 194, 277; being-already-togetherwith-the, 61, 109, 277; being-nolonger-in-the, 176, 238, 240; beingwith-one-another-in-the, 238-239, 384; belonging-to-the, 65, 381; taking care of the, 61, 199, 253, 277, et passim; discovering the, 55, 129,138,165, 195,203; disclosedness of the, 76, 137, 139,
479
141,145-146,186-188,202-203, 210-211,220,272,297,333, 364-365,368,412,419-420; familiarity with the, 76, 86; fascination with the, 61; fleeing the, 254; getting 'lived' by the, 195-196; going-out-of-the, 238, 240; having-been-in-the, 394; interpreting, 129; letting the world 'matter' to one, 170; openness to the, 137; presupposing the, 361, 365; relations to, 57; submitting to the, 137-138, 139; surrendered to the, 199; thrown into the, 192, 199, 221, 228, 348, 413; understanding the, 16, 86, 146, 148, 152, 168, 366;An~tand, 186-188,335,343; Mitda-sein and, 121-123, 137; fear and the, 141; the objectively present and, 57, 130, 369; reality and, 106, 203, 211; the things at hand and, 75-76,83, 106, 119, 122, 137; resoluteness and, 298-299; significance and, 111, 144-145,147,151,166,186,297, 335, 343, 366, 423; spatiality and, 101-113 (§§ 22-24), 369; beingthere of the, 132; occurrence of the, 389; 'natural conception' of, 50-52(§ 11); the "nothing" of the, 187, 189,276,335,343;ontology of, 100; 'subjectivity' of, 36; transcendence of, 350-366 (§ 69, esp. 69c), 419; alien, 172; historical, 376, 381, 388-389; past, 380; primitive, 82; projected, 394; public, 71; spiritual, 47 n. 2; weworld, 65; wish-world, 195; of useful things, 354, 359, 413; of plants and animals, 246; that has been, 381; that has-been-there, 393-394; that is no longer, 380; world-conscience, 278; worldhistory, 19-20, 332, 377, 387-397 (§§ 75, 76), 428 n. 17 (Hegel), 434 (Hegel); world-point, 362; world-
480
Being and Time
World (continued) space, 54, 104; world-structure, 366, 414; world-stuff, 71, 85; world-time (See entry under 'time' above); world-view (Weltanschauung}, 180, 200, 301 n. 17 (Jaspers}, 392, 396; is not an entity within-the-world, 72, 118; Da-sein is its, 364; is there, 144; frees beings, 123, 129; How death 'came into the world', 248; Descartes on, 89-90; Husser) on, 47 n. 2; Kant on, 108, 321. See also Being-in-the-world; Surrounding world; With-world "World" ("Welt"}: defined, 58fn, 63-65, 89, 202, 246fn; abandoning (verlassen) the, 238; abandonment (ilberlassen) to the, 356, 406, 412-413; absorption in the, 184, 189; addressing oneself to the, 59; Being-together-with the, 175,181, 189,311,352; taking care of the 'world', 136, 143,175,184-185,252,270,277, 311, 338, 411; de-distancing the, 105; devotion to the, 136; discovering the, 110, 129, 203,
297, 312; falling into the, 175, 185, 189, 338; fascination with the, 176;ha~ngthe,58;knowing the, 138; letting the 'world' 'matter' to one, 139; losing oneself in the, 221, 348; presupposing the, 64; relationship to the, 57; seeing the, 138; spatializing the, 112; submission to the, 161, 297, 383; surrendering to the, 139; theoretical attitude toward the, 356; understanding the, 148, 201; understanding oneself in terms of the, 15, 22, 221, 411; Angst and the, 187, 189; fear and the, 189; nature and the, 25; reality and the, 183, 207; objective presence of the, 132, 192; alien, 356; as it looks, 172; Descartes on, 99-101. See also External world; Multiplicity; Thingliness Worldliness (Weltlichkeit}, 41, 53, 63-66,72,76,82-84,86-89,95, 101, 104, 110, 113, 123, 211, 220, 334-335,414,416,424 Worldless (weltlos}, 55, 110-111, 188, 192,206,211,316,366,388
SUPPLEMENTAL LEXICON OF THE LATER MARGINAL REMARKS (-fn)
Listed below are some of the German terms in the marginal remarks that could not easily be accommodated into the above Lexicon of the most important terms in the vocabulary of Being and Time ( 1927). These constitute terms proper to the later Heidegger, notably from the period of the Beitriige zur Philosophic (1936-38) and reflecting its major divisions in terms like resonance (Anklang), play (Zuspiel}, and leap (Sprung). See also above, for some of the connective links between the two works, in terms like Belonging; Clearing; Constancy; Ek-sistence; Essence as presencing; Event; Presence; Leaping; Relation; Truth; Understanding of being. Along with the usage in the later marginal remarks, we include here, where relevant, instances of pages of minor usage of the same and related terms in Being and Time itself.
Lexicon Anklang, resonance, 7fn, 38fn, 248 Ankunft, arrival, 235fn, 240fn, 250; Ankommen(des), (on)coming, 79, 254,259,330,341-342,373-374, 382, 389, 422-423, 427. See also Imminence Ausgesetztheit, being exposed, 162fn Bei-spiel, exemplary co-player that plays-with and plays-to (zu-spielt) the play (Spiel) of resonance of being, 7fn; man as Spielball, "plaything" of the circumstances and events (Ereignisse) of world history, 382. See also Leeway (Spielraum) Einsprung, Ur-sprunK'- See instead Leaping Ereignis, appropriation, 38fn, 235fn. See also Event von Gnaden des, by the grace of, 147fn
481
Sammler, Sammlung; gatherer, gathering, 165fn, 266 (of relations in anticipation of death) das Sichliche, the itself-like, 319fn; "itself," 193, 317-318, 321. See alsc "It is concerned in its being about .. .";Jeweiligkeit; Mineness; Understanding itself Tragen, to bear, 134fn; Zu-tragende, what bears (toward), 134fn; das Unaustragbare, what is not to be perdured, 187fn. See also Burden ilbereignetheit, being appropriated, 42fn, 134fn. See also Ereignis; Event Umkehr, return into (reversal), 39fn, 426 (and irreversibility of time) VVahrend,perduring, 7fn;das "wahrend," the "during," 409, 413. See also Preservation das Zu-sagende, what calls for saying,
Hin-nehmen, taking-in (accepting), 147fn, 151, 391 (existence accepting thrownness) Mitte, center (middle), 213fn. See also the Between; Clearing
165fn; das Zugesagte, what is said to us, 227fn; to say directly (auf den Kopfzusagen) to one's face, to "categorize," 44. See also Call of conscience; Gives to understand Zu-spiel: See Bei-spiel
LATIN EXPRESSIONS
a potiori fit denominatio (The name originates from the more potent), 329 a priori (from the former), 4, 11, 41, 44-45,50,n. 10,53,58,65,85, 85fn, 101, 110-111, 115, 131, 149-150, 152, 165, 183, 193, 199, 206,229,321,362 adaequatio intellectus et rei (adequation of intellect and thing), 214-217 anima (soul), 14
animal rationale (rational animal), 48, 165 bonum (good), 286, 345 capax mutationum (capable of changes), 91, 96 circulus vitiosus (vicious circle), 152 cogitare, cogitationes (thinking, thoughts), 46, 49, 211, 433 cogito me ccgitare rem (I think myself thinking the thing), 433
482
Being and Time
cogito sum (I think, I am), 24, 40, 46, 89,211 colo (I cultivate, inhabit), 54 color (color), 91 commercium (commerce, intercourse), 62, 132, 176 communis opinio (common opinion), 403 (Yorck) compositum (composite), 244 n. 3 concupiscentia (concupiscence), 171 conscientia (consciousness), 433 convenientia (agreement), 132, 214-215 contritio (contrition), 190 n. 4 correspondentia (correspondence), 214 cura(care), 183,197-199 dejinitio (defmition), 4 diligo (I take care of, esteem highly, cherish), 54 durities (hardness), 91 ego (1), 43, 46, 211 ego cogito (I think), 22, 89 ens (being), 24; ens creatum (created being), 24, 92; ens finitum (finite being), 49; ens increatum (uncreated being), 24; ens infinitum (infinite being), 24; ens perfectissimum (most perfect being), 92; ens quod natum est convenire cum omni enti (being that is born to come together with all beings), 14; ens realissimum (most real being), 128; modw; specialis entis (special mode of being), 14 essentia (essence), 42-43 existentia (existence), 42-43 existit, ad existendum (it exists, for existing), 95 exitw; (finish, end), 241 extensio (extension), 89-91, 93-95, 97,99-101 factum brutum (brute fact), 135 fundamentum inconcw;sum (unshakable foundation), 24
futurum (future): bonum futurum (good future), 345; malum futurum (bad future), 141, 341, 345; meditatio futurae vitae (meditation on the future life), 249 n. 6 genetivw; objectivw; (objective genitive), 42fn habitare (dwell, inhabit), 54 habitw; (habit), 300 homo (human being), 198 humus (earth), 198 intellectio (intellection), 95-96 intellectus (intellect), 214, 216, 225 intuitw; (intuition), 358 libertas indifferentiae (freedom of indifference), 144 lumen naturale (natural light), 133, 170 malum (evil), 141, 286, 341, 345 meditatio futurae vitae (meditation on the future life), 249 n. 6 modus (mode), 14, 90-91 motw; (motion), 91 nunc stans (standing now), 427 n. 13 peifectio (perfection), 199 poenitentia (penance), 190, n. 4 pondw; (weight), 91 praesuppositum (presupposition), 101 privatio (privation, deprivation), 286 privativum (privative; deficient thing), 284 propensio in (inclination to), 188 proprietas (property), 93, 100 ratio (reason), 34, 94 realiter (in reality, really), 94 remanens capax mutationum (remaining capable of changes), 96 res (thing), 67, 201, 20lfn, 209, 214, 216, 225; res cogitans (thinking thing), 98, 112-113,207,211,
Lexicon 319-320, 320 n. 19; res corporea (corporeal thing), 90-91, 94, 101; res extensa (extended thing), 66, 89-92, 97-98, 112
sensatio (sensation), 96 sollicitudo (solicitude), 199 n. 7 solus ipse (himself/itself alone), 188 status corruptionis (state of corruption), 180, 306 n. 2 status gratiae (state of grace), 180 status integritatis (state of integrity, wholeness), 180 subjectum (subject), 46, 114 substantia (substance), 89-90, 92, 94, 201fn sum (I am), 24, 211
483
totum (whole), 244 n. 3 timor castus et seroilis (pure and servile fear), 190 n. 4 transcendens, transcendentia (a transcendental, transcendentals ), 3, 14, 38 + fn transcendentalis (transcendental, adj.), 38 univoce (univocally), 93 veritas (truth), 38 verum (true), 14 via negationis et eminentiae (way of negation and eminence), 427 n. 13 vitiosus (vicious), 152-153
GREEK EXPRESSIONS
(rya96v, agathon (good), 29 (ryvmiv, agnoein (nonapprehension, ignorance), 33 ai.o9JJcn~, aisthesis (sense perception), 14,33,96,226 airov, airovo~. aianos (the eternal, eternity), 423 aKoA.ou9eiv, akolouthein (to follow, accord with), 213, 432 n. 30 aA.,aec;, aA.it9eta, aA.,aei>etv; alethes, alitheia, alitheuein (true; truth; being-true), 33, 133fn, 212fn, 213, 219-220, 223 n. 39; a-A.it9eta (taken out of hiding), 222 OJla, kama (at the same time, at once), 423 Civ9pom:o~. anthropos (human being, man), 48, 171 a1to, apo (from itself), 32 a1tocpai vea9at, a1t6cpavcnc;, apophainesthai, apophansis (letting be seen from itself [showing]; what allows this display [speech]), 32-34,154,213,218-219 Cipt9Jloc; JCt vitae we;, arithmos kineseos (number [numeration, count] of
motion), 421, 423, 427, 432 n. 30 apxai, archai (beginnings, origins), 212
yevoc;, genos (genus), 3 YtyavtoJla:x;ia 1tEpi tii~ oOOi.a~. gigantomachia peri tes ousias (battle of the giants over being), 2 li11A.ouv, deloun (making manifest), 1, 32 litayOY'fli, diagl!ge (staying, tarrying, "whiling"), 138 otaipecn~, diairesis (division, separation), 159 litavoeiv, dianoein (understanding), 96, 147fn, 226 M~a, doxa (opinion), 223 n. 39 ei.Mvat, eidenai (to know, to see), 171 ellio~, eidos (outward appearance, look), 61, 61fn, 68fn, 319 eiJCci>v, ei.Kova, eikona (image, semblance), 48, 423 elvat, einai (to be, be-ing), 85fn, 171, 212,427
484
Being and Time
EKcrtacn~.
EK<J'tanK6v, ekstasis, ekstatikon (ecstasy; ecstatic), 329 entA.av9
158-160, 165, 219-220, 222, 225-226 A.inrr), lupe (pain, depression), 342
(escape notice, be forgotten), 219 E7tlcml~l1. episteme (knowledge, science), 213 ep~TJVEVElv, epJ.li)vEia, hermeneuein, hermeneia (understanding interpreting; interpretation), 37, 158 EUxi), euchetE (request, petition), 32
111l9l]J.la, mathima (learning, the mathematical), 96fn J.lE9£~1~, methexis (participation),216 J.lEPlJ.lVa, merimna (care, anxiety), 194 n.7 llil ov, me on (nonbeing), 138 J.lOp$i), morphe (form), 68fn J.lU9o~, mythos (story), 6
~<'j)ov
A.Oyov exov, zoon logon echon (living being having speech, rational animal), 25, 48, 165
9a'UJ.l
thaumazein (to wonder),
172 9£6~,
theos (God), 48 9EropEiv, theorein (to behold, consider), 213
iliea, idea (idea), 68fn, 20lfn tlita, idia (its own, unique), 33 Ka9' airt6, kath' auto (according to itself), 17fn Ka96A.ou, katholou (on the whole, in general),3, 17fn,37fn KanJYopcla9at, Ka'tl]yopia, kategoreisthai, kategoria (to accuse publicly, denounce, "categorize"; category), 44-45 Kotv6v, koinon (common, universal), 38fn KpivEtv A.Oyc:p, krinein logo (to distinguish intelligently, "understandingly"), 222-223 Kplnt'tEa9at (cllti..Ei), kryptesthai (philei) ([it loves] to hide), 212fn A.av9
voeiv, v6~a. VOT]m~, noein, noema, noesis (thinking ["intuitive apprehending"]; [re ]presentation; thought), 14, 25-26, 33, 43, 59, 96, 171,212,214,226;vo~,nous (mind, intuition), 427 vuv, nun (now), 432 n. 30 oA.ov, holon (whole), 244 n. 3 OJ.lOlWJ.la, OJ.loirocn~, homoioma, homoiiisis (likeness; correspondence), 48, 214-215 ov, ov'ta, on, onta (being, beings), 1, 3, 14,90fn,96fn, 138,213 opeyoJ.lal, oregomai (I desire, "care"),
171 opo~.
horos (limit), 432 n. 30 ouranos {heaven, sky), 423 ouaia, ousia (being), 2, 25-26, 90, oupavo~.
20lfn nVTJ, rhastone (leisure), 138
Lexicon <myJ.u'l, stigme (point), 432 n. 30 crov, syn (together), 33 a6v9em~, synthesis (a placing together, synthesis), 33-34, 159 crovrovi>J.J.coc;, synonymas (univocally), 93 O"$a'ipa, sphaira (sphere), 432 n. 30
tapax1\, tarachi (confusion), 342 tEXVTI. techni (art), 68fn t6Se n, tode ti (something, "this here"), 432 n. 30 to ti ~v eivat, to ti in einai (that which was to be), 85fn
485
light; to show itself; what shows itself), 28-29, 32, 219 $QvtaO'i.a, phantasia (a making visible; display, sight), 33 $tA€1, philei (it loves), 212fn $tAoao$e'iv, philosophein (to philosophize), 213 $pa~CDV OKcoc; exet, phrazon hokOs echei (telling how it is [holds itself, behaves]), 219 $001<;, physis (nature), 85fn, 171, 201fn, 212fn $rov1\, phOni, (sound, voice), 33 $<0<;, phOs (light), 28
UATI, hyli (matter, material), 68fn lmOlCElJ.lEVOV, hypokeimenon (the underlying, basis), 34, 46, 319
xpovo<;, chronos (time), 421, 423, 427, 432 n. 30
$a-, pha- (bright, shining), 28 $aivro, $aive0'9at, $atVOJ.levov; phaina, phainesthai, phainomenon (bring to
veu&0'9at, pseudesthai (being-false), 33 vux1'1. psychi (soul), 14, 214, 427
PROPER NAMES
Ackermann aus Bohmen, Der, 245 n. 4 Aristotle, 2, 3, 10, 14, 18, 25, 26, 32, 33,39,40,85fn,93, 138-140,159, 171,199,208,212-4,219,225, 226, 244 n. 3, 341, 342, 399, 402, 421, 427, 428, 432, 433; De Anima, 14 and n. 6; De Interpretatione, 32 n. 4, 214 and n. 29; Ethica Nicomachea, 32 n. 4, 225 n. 42; Metaphysica, 3, 32 n. 4, 39, 85fn, 138 n. 5, 171,212, 213,225 n. 42; Physica, 85fn, 421 n. 7, 427, 428, 432 n. 30; Rhetorica, 138, 140 n. 7, 342 n. 6 Augustine of Hippo, Saint, 43, 44, 139, 171, 190 n. 4, 199 n. 7, 427; Confessiones, 43, 44, 171, 427; Confessions, 43, 44, 171, 427; Contra Faustum, 138 n. 5; De diversis quaestionibus octoginta tribus, 190 n. 4 Avicenna, 214
Baer, K. von, 58 Becker, 0., 112 n. 23 Bergson, Henri, 18, 26, 47,333,432 n.30 Bernt, Alois, 245 n. 4 Bittinger, G., 418 n. 5 Bolzano, Bernhard, 218 n. 34 Brentano,Franz,215 Biicheler, Franz, 197 n. 5 Burdach, Konrad, 197 n. 5, 199,245 n.4 Cajetan, Thomas de Vio, 93 n. 15 Calvin, John, 49,249 n. 6 Cassirer, Ernst, 51 n. 11 Descartes, Rene, 22, 24, 25, 40, 45, 46,66, 89-101,98fn,203,204, 205 n. 15, 211, 320 n. 19, 433; Meditations, 24, 98; Principia Philosophiae, 90-4, 96, 97
486
Being and Time
Diels, Hermann, 212 n. 20, 219 n. 35, 418 n. 5 Dilthey, Wilhelm, 46, 47 + n. 2, 205 n. 15, 209, 210 + n. 19, 249 n. 6, 377, 385 n. 8, 397-404 Duns Scotus,Johannes, 3 Earth (Tellus), 198 Faust, 401 Genesis, 48 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, 197 n.5,401 Gottl, F., 388 n. 9 Grimm,Jakob, 54 n. 1
Hartmann, Nicolai, 208 n. 16, 433 n. 30 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 2, 3, 22, 171, 235 n. 6, 272 n. 8, 320 n. 19,405, 406, 427 and n. 16, 428-36; Die Vernunft in d£r Geschichte, 428, 434; Encyklopadie, 429, 432 n. 30; Jena Logik, 432 n. 30; Phiinomenologie des Geistes, 434; Wissenschaft d£r Logik, 431 n. 25, 433 Heidegger, Martin, 38 n. 5, 51 n. 11, 72 n. 1, 199 n. 7, 268 n. 3, 319 n. 16,418 n. 5 Heimsoeth, Heinz, 320 n. 19 Heraclitus, 219 Herbig, Gustav, 349 n. 12 Herder,Johann Gottfried von, 197 n. 5, 198 n. 6 Hermann, Karl Friedrich, 400 Homer, 400 Humboldt, Wilhelm von, 119, 166 Husserl, Edmund, 38 + n. 5, 47 + n. 2, 50 n. 10, 51 n. 11, 77 n. 3, 98fn, 160fn, 166 n. 11, 218 n. 34, 244 n. 3, 363 n. 22; ldeen, 47, 77 n. 3; Logische Untersuchungen, 38, 77 n. 3, 166 n. 11, 218 n. 34, 244 n. 3, 363 n. 2; "Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," 4 7 Hyginus, 197 n. 5
Israeli, Isaac, 214 Jacob, 401 Jaspers, Karl, 249 n. 6, 301 n. 17, 338 n.3 Jupiter, 198 Kahler, Martin, 272 n. 8 Kant, Immanuel: 4, 23, 24, 26, 30, 31, 38fn, 40, 51 n. 11, 94, 101, 109, 110,65fn,85fn,20lfn, 203-6, 208,210,215,229,23lfn,271, 272 n. 8, 293, 318 and n. 15, 319 + n. 16, 320 + n. 19, 321, 358, 367, 419, 427 + n. 16, 432 n. 30; Kritik derreinen Vernunft, 23, 30, 31,51 n. 11,94,203-5,318,319,358; "Was heisst: sich im Denken orientieren?," 109 n. 22 Kierkegaard, S111ren, 190 n. 4, 235 n. 6, 338 n. 3 Korschelt, Eugen, 246 n. 5 Lask, E., 218 n. 34 Lotze, Rudolf Hermann, 99, 155 Luther, Martin, 10, 190 n. 4 Misch, Georg, 399 n. 14 New Testament, 199 n. 7, 400 Newton, Isaac, 226, 227 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 264, 272 n. 8, 396 Parmenides, 14, 25, 26, 100, 171, 212, 213, 222, 223 n. 39 Pascal, Blaise, 139 Paul, Saint, 249 n. 6 Petavius, Dionysius, 418 n. 5 Plato: 1, 2, 3, 6, 25, 32, 39, 159, 244 n. 3, 399, 402, 423; Parmenides, 39; Sophistes, 1, 6; Timaeus, 423 Ranke, Leopold von, 400 Reinhardt, Karl, 223 n. 39 Rickert, Heinrich, 375 Ritschl, Albrecht, 272 n. 8 Riihl, F., 419 n. 5
Lexicon
Saturn, 198 Scaliger,Josephusjustus, 418 n. 5 Scheler, Max, 47, 48, 139, 208 n. 16, 210 + n. 19,272 n. 8, 291 n. 10,320 n. 19 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 272 n. 8 Seneca, 199 Simmel, Georg, 249 n. 6, 375,418 n. 5 Spranger, Eduard, 394 n. II Stoics, I99 n. 8 Stoker, H. G., 272 n. 8 Suarez, Franciscus, 22 Thomas Aquinas, Saint, 3, I4 + n. 7, 2I4+n.30
487
Thucydides, 39 Tolstoy, Leo, 254 n. I2 Unger, Rudolf, 249 n. 6 Wackemagel,Jakob, 349 n. I2 Windelband, Wilhelm, 399 Wolff, Christian, 28 Yorck von Wartenburg, Paul Graf, 377,397-404 Zwingli, Huldreich, 49