113212
Beyond the Pleasure Principle Translated and edited by James Strachey Introduction and notes by Gregory Zilboo...
227 downloads
2166 Views
13MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
113212
Beyond the Pleasure Principle Translated and edited by James Strachey Introduction and notes by Gregory Zilboorg
By
SIGMUND FREUD
AN AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL STUDY BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE CIVILIZATION
AND ITS DISCONTENTS
THE COMPLETE INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS THE EGO AND THE FIVE LECTURES
ID
ON PSYCHOANALYSIS
THE FUTURE OF AN ILLUSION
GROUP PSYCHOLOGY AND THE ANALYSIS OF THE EGO INHIBITIONS,
SYMPTOMS AND ANXIETY
INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS JOKES AND THEIR RELATION TO THE UNCONSCIOUS
LEONARDO DA VINCI AND A MEMORY OF HIS CHILDHOOD
NEW INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS ON DREAMS ON THE HISTORY OF THE PSYCHOANALYTIC MOVEMENT AN OUTLINE OF PSYCHOANALYSIS THE PSYCHOPATHALOGY OF EVERYDAY LIFE
THE QUESTION OF LAY ANALYSIS
TOTEM AND TABOO
THE STANDARD EDITION OF THE COMPLETE PSYCHOLOGICAL WORKS OF SIGMUND FREUD 24 VOLUMES
Beyond
the
Pleasure Principle
SIGMUND FREUD Translated and
Newly Edited
by
JAMES STRAGHEY Introduction by
GREGORY ZILBOORG
W-W-NORTON&COMPANY NEW YORK -LONDON
W. W. Norton
& Company, Inc.,
500 Fifth Avenue, N.Y. 10110 Company Ltd. 37 Great Russell Street,
New York, W. W. Norton
&
London COPYRIGHT
WC1B 3NU
1961 BY JAMES STRACHBY
Reprinted by arrangement with Liveright Publishing Corporation Introduction Copyright
ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Published simultaneously in Canada by Penguin Books Canada Ltd, 2801 John Street, Markham, Ontario L3R 1B4.
&
W. W. Norton Company, Inc. is also the publisher of the works of Erik H. Erikson, Otto Fenichel, Karen Homey, Harry Stack Sullivan, and The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Freud, Sigmund, 1856-1939 Beyond the pleasure principle. Translation of Jenseits des Lust-Prinzips. Reprint of the ed. published by Liveright, New York. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Pleasure. 2.
BF173.F65
Psychoanalysis.
1975
150.19'52
I.
Title.
74-22476
Printed in the United States of America
67890
ISBN 0-3*13-0071^-3
CONTENTS Introduction Editor's
vii
Note
xvii ""
Beyond
the Pleasure Principle
1
List of Abbreviations
59
Bibliography and Author Index
60
General Index
64
INTRODUCTION by Gregory Zilboorg, M.D.
A
QUESTION which seems natural and almost unavoidable What can one say about a book, and a little one at that, which is forty years old, and which is supposedly not one of the most impressive or "spectacular" bits of Freud's many writings? The question presupposes the implied answer that forty years even in our swift-moving world is a long time, that the book in question is therefore more or less superannuated and deserves but a respectful historical glance before we put it back on the shelf to gather more dust. It is obvious that the above is a rhetorical way of saying arises:
that forty years after its appearance and twenty years after Freud's death, Beyond the Pleasure Principle still deserves considerable attention, and that the reader would do well if he reads it with studious curiosity. Of recent years we have become so accustomed to the atmosphere of controversy
which surrounds psychoanalysis and Freud that we have almost lost our capacity to pick up a book on psychoanalysis without wanting to know in advance whether the book is for or against it, or, if it is for it, whether it is for Freud or for Jung, or, if it is Freudian, whether it is orthodox or neoFreudian. If we dared to be frank with ourselves, we would have no difficulty in admitting that our judgment of psychoanalysis is actually fragmentary and not too profound. We could also admit that some sort of partisanship possesses us, and that therefore we are preoccupied with "taking sides"
we
get acquainted with the very first elements of the subject. because of the various prejudices which have incul-
long before
psychoanalysis It is
and the many-sidedness of
cated themselves into psychoanalytical and nonpsychoanalytical circles that it is pertinent to invite both the initiated and the uninitiated reader to suspend his fragmentary judgment vii
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
viii
for a short while and re-read afresh the little book that is here offered, and acquaint or re-acquaint himself with the sound of Freud's written voice, with his way of saying things, and then with the substance of what he has to say. An introduction is not supposed to explain in advance
what
said in the book;
is
still less is it
meant
to interpret
it.
intended to clarify some shadows and point to certain lights which will possibly set the book in a proper Rather,
it is
perspective.
Bearing this in mind, let us first recall that Freud wrote Beyond the Pleasure Principle when he was sixty-four years old a mature age indeed and at a time when psychoanalysis had already achieved considerable popularity, even though it was still possible to assess the degree of its importance by the number of enemies it had. The tone of the book, the mannerisms of
Freud
its
it
style are vigorous, poignant,
seems was
still
almost controversial; combatting his opponents rather than
trying to instruct his proponents. his life,
Freud preserved
this
Almost to the
last
years of
combative vigor of writing, and
in Beyond the Pleasure Principle this aspect of style stands out markedly, particularly when he emphasizes his claim that he is a partisan of no special philosophy and that he is indifferent as to whether what he has to say does or does not fit any
known philosophy.
This claim for independence casts
is
characteristic of Freud's
and of all his writings, but I believe aspersion on his originality or his genius,
personality
it
in
no way
if I
say that this declaratory independence should not be taken too seriously. No one, and particularly no genius, is free of the
really ideological inheritance which he carries within himself as a child of a given generation. He not be
aware of it, of may Freud would have been the last man in the world to equate not being aware of something with its nonexistence. For it was of course Freud himself who discovered and uncourse, but
folded before us the staggering richness and power within us many things of which we are not aware. It is of some interest in this connection to recall that Freud denied ever having been acquainted with the writings of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche before he formulated many of his ideas. It was beyond any doubt an honest denial. Yet it is a matter of record that Hitschmann, one of the earliest ad-
of so
INTRODUCTION
ix
herents of Freud, read a paper in Freud's house as early as 1905 (Freud being present, of course) on the very subject of Nietzsche's ideas as compared with some of Freud's theories.
There
no doubt
whether or not Freud ever read of Morals, his was the temperament and the aspiration of a proud iconoclast who, to paraphrase an old saying of Maxim Gorki's, was born to soar and not to crawl, and for whom soaring accomplishment was not a pleasure in itself but a temporary level from which he is
Nietzsche's
that,
The Genealogy
strove to attain ever-greater heights. If we cast but a glance at the rough sketch of a general psychology which we find in Freud's letters to Fliess, we
cannot help but be struck by the depth, diapason and immense horizons which Freud envisaged as the culmination of his system. And these letters, we must remember, were written before 1900, that is to say, before the first book (The Interpretation of Dreams) which really launched psychoanalysis into the stormy waters of a world which never was able to approach the study of the psychology of man without prejudice and considerable animosity and controversy be it religious, scientific,
or plain pedestrian.
which Freud's mind was
The ambition
with
from the very
outset, and his particular goal of discovering, or uncovering, the real nature of man's mind, predestined him as a thinker and a man to fired
become a storm center
for years to come. was also a daring paradox, giving the semblance of self-contradiction, of inconsistency, and of all-solidity. Freud's apparent readiness to change his mind added a great number of dissenters and detractorsas if the scientist who has the courage to change his mind about some of his own ideas has
He
gained a point against himself. The great majority of people do confuse stubbornness for consistency, and rigidity of scientific ideas for soundness of position. At any rate, Beyond the Pleasure Principle is one of the first great landmarks in Freud's ways of "changing his mind." I put these words in quotes to cast at least a little doubt on the traditional attitude that Freud did change his mind in this instance. He did not. What Freud did here was to add a path or two, a little curve or fork, in the tortuous intellectual road which he followed with dogged faith in his own intellectual independence. The additions or added trends of thought
.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
x
cannot be fully grasped and even less understood unless one always bears in mind the inner psychological atmosphere in which Freud worked in order to express his ideas. His literary style was always terse, straightforward, clear and challengingly frank; but the same thing cannot be said about the emotional climate of his thought. First of all, Freud never gave up his belief I am tempted to say faith that the parallel he drew between Fechner's ideas in physics and his own in human psychology was not really a parallel but an actual proof that his concept of the mental apparatus and its energy was actually the same as Helmholtz' and Fechner's ideas about physical energy. To this faith he clung to the last, expressing the hope that some day the whole complexity of human reactions and relations could be reduced to some as yet undiscovered physico-chemical reactions. In other words, Freud remained an organicist throughout his scientific life. But genius and living paradox that he was, Freud was rejected by the materialists (conservative as well as Marxian) because of his alleged mysticism; and he was rejected by the idealists and religious thinkers because he was thought to be a materialist.
The
contradictions into which
Freud's detractors thus
stumbled remained unnoticed as a rule, but Freud was of course aware of them and saw in them merely a sign of general resistance. Yet it was not only that. To Freud the epithet, "mystic," was an expression of opprobrium, and yet it was Freud who stated that saints were saved from severe neuroses by their sainthood, their faith; he mentioned in this connection St. Francis of Assisi.
He who studies
the lives of the saints
would not a
easily issue to all of them, and without reservation, certificate of psychological health. They were saints because
they were able to stand the pressure of their respective neuroses rather than because they did not suffer from them. The lives of St. Ignatius
Loyola, or San Francisco Xavier, or St. Augustine for that matter, offer ample confirmation of my
viewpoint.
As one studies Freud, one can develop the strong suspicion he was more attracted by many mystics than by physicochemical hypotheses, and that he struggled with all the might that
of his great mind against openly giving in to the attraction of the mystical aspects of human life. In other words, the man
INTRODUCTION
xi
who less than twenty years after he wrote Beyond the Pleasure who Principle wrote his Moses and Monotheism, the man some five years before Beyond the Pleasure Principle wrote the article on Michelangelo's Moses, seems throughout this of span of time to have been preoccupied with the greatness human intuitions and the universality of human strivings not only to solve but to participate in the mysteries of life. And it is perhaps because of this inclination that Freud gave signs of "protesting too much." (Perhaps too this is one of the reasons why his article on Michelangelo's Moses appeared
first
anonymously;
it
was only much
later that
it
was admitted
that Freud, the Editor-in-chief of the Zeitschrift fur Psychoanalyse, was the real author of the article.)
While the complex question of Freud's intellectual strugwith his own ideas is far from solved, there is little doubt
gles
that the aggressive, trenchant, emphatic tone of his writings, full of conviction and devoid of doubt, does
which seem to be
not fully convey Freud's struggle with his own ideas, which at times must have reached heroic dimensions. It is because of Freud's aggressive candor, it seems to me, that his earliest followers seem more to have stood in awe, listening to his pronouncements, than actually to have assimilated his
thought like true disciples, ready to ask friendly
critical
questions in order to deepen and broaden the understanding of their master's thought. The very few of his followers who
were endowed with truly original minds and truly ambitious perspicacity and intuition soon broke with Freud; Jung is one of the few one can cite in this respect. The majority became either surly, hostile enemies rather than scientific opponentsor admiring, enthusiastic followers rather than scientific collaborators. It is therefore of particular interest to note that there was hardly a psychoanalyst outside Freud himself who ever made an original contribution to the theory and practice of psychoanalysis; this is particularly true of the time when Freud wrote his Beyond the Pleasure Principle. The one exception one can cite with certainty was Karl Abraham, who made an inestimable contribution to the clinical understanding of character formation and of depression, a contribution which
was spontaneously and "painlessly" incorporated into the body of psychoanalytic knowledge some five years before the
xii
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
appearance of Beyond the Pleasure Principle. But even in the case of Abraham things were not all clarity and sunshine; many of his colleagues were not very kindly disposed to the
man, and Freud himself, as Jones has written, said that he was suspicious of his "Prussian mind" Abraham being a Berliner.
All of the above amounts to saying that the constant and "true" followers of Freud were not very original minds; they were not mediocrities, but for some reason they would not
or perhaps could not "speak up'* until Freud spoke first. It is partly because of this that Beyond the Pleasure Principle acquired such significance in the history of the development of Freudian psychoanalysis. It acquired the reputation of a landmark in how Freud changed his mind and how daring he was in doing so. As a matter of cold fact, the book is an important contribution, a thrust forward in the growth of Freudian thought; but if one reads it carefully one will easily see that Freud did not change his mind, and that Beyond the Pleasure Principle did not overthrow any old psychoanalytic regime nor did it establish any new one. It was not even a small village revolution; it was and is a landmark of further development and a consolidation of the older pathways. Beyond the Pleasure Principle is what it says; it goes a little further beyond, but it does not abandon whatever preceded it. This writer lays no claim to an understanding of Freud's writing better than anyone's else who approaches Freud with the earnestness he deserves and the tolerance which is imperative, even now some twenty years after Freud's death. I say "even now" for the following reason; at the beginning
Freud had to
suffer from the many whose quick and ever misjudgment of him multiplied by thousands the number of his antagonists in every walk of the world's intellectual life. Today, with the full text of Freud at the disposal of every curious reader of the world, everybody claims Freud as his own, because everybody just as alertly is ready to interpret Freud in his own ivay. Thus a plethora of "schools" has mush-
alert
roomed
in the psychological literature, each claiming
its
philosophical, moral and scientific right to consider Freud its fons et origo, and its own exclusive right to understand Freud in its own exclusively correct way. This splintering of interpreters and misinterpreters of Freud is not unnatural, of
INTRODUCTION
xiii
course; the process will undoubtedly continue for some time before the real Freud will stand out in the history of our intellectual
development
we may look calmly and Since
it is
as a figure at
into
whom
not in anyone's power to slow down or to accelit cannot be the ambition
erate the salutary passage of time, of this writer to attempt to do so.
mate
whom and
objectively.
But
this
much
it is legiti-
him
to essay to do: to point out that the vigor of Freud's thought, stimulating as it has always been and is, is
for
frequently obscured by his at times too hasty terminological innovations. Not that one objects to such innovations, or that
one ought to insist on semantic hair-splitting; but Freud, whose clarity of thought and daring intellectual improvisations were always impressive and enlightening, suffered not infrequently from a certain confusion, at first unnoticeable but at length presenting an impediment to easy or clear understanding. Beyond the Pleasure Principle serves as an excellent example. First, there is the tendency which imperceptibly grew into assertive tradition that, having gone beyond the pleasure principle, he abandoned that principle. This, as I have already said, is not true. The reader, bearing this in mind, cannot fail but see it once the text is perused without prejudice, without the unwitting psychological twist which makes him read Beyond the Pleasure Principle and assume that the pleasure principle was left behind. We might as well state right here that the assiduous and faithful translators of Freud, in bringing before the English-speaking readers Freud's version of the pleasure-pain theory, did not help matters when they coined a neologism, "unpleasure." This awkward term is supposed to render somewhat accurately the German term Unlust. It is not an exactly successful rendition (except
etymologically, perhaps). The feeling of pain, of discomfort, of that disagreeable malaise which Freud has in mind is not
perceived as t/n-pleasure, for what we feel in this malaise we feel positively, and not negatively as a lack of something else. This point need not be labored; it is brought out here merely to illustrate how difficult it is to tell the reader what a given writer wants to say in a language his own, but not yours.
Now
let
allegedly
us ask ourselves what appears to be new and not as old in Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
abandoned
xiv
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
The concept of "compulsive repetition" or "repetition compulsion." Some still quarrel with this concept, some no longer do. The arguments for and against it are of no particular importance here. What is important is that new concepts, newly formulated, require greater clarity of definition. Freud discovered the repetitiveness of certain patterns of human behavior and the inevitability or, if you wish, the inescapable nature of this repetitiveness. And he called this
phenomenon
"repetition compulsion" or "compulsive repe-
tition."
We have become accustomed to the term "compulsion" when we speak of compulsion neuroses in other words, a neurosis which makes the sufferer therefrom aware that he is "compelled by something" to make this or that gesture or this or that turn or else he feels uncomfortable, uneasy, at
hardly necessary to go into more compulsive element of which Freud speaks when he speaks of compulsive repetition is something that the individual is not conscious of, that the compulsive element in this concept is something which is not neurotic at all, or not necessarily, and that it is just as or no more compulsive than breathing or the changing of the seasons. To use the term "compulsive" here connotes something that it is not and implies things which are not necessarily there a rather strange semantic fuzziness on the part of that uniquely clear-minded thinker. Such unclarities are strewn throughout many of Freud's writings and translations, and if they do not always confuse the casual reader or even the student, one would do well in being forewarned and therefore in reading and studying Freud with considerable caution and prudence. One more example: the second major innovation which Freud introduced into psychoanalytic thinking was the concept of the death instinct. Now we have become accustomed, particularly since Freud emphasized the role of instincts in the conscious and unconscious life of man, to consider an instinct a drive, an impulsive or perpetually compelling aspiration to gratify a need. In German, Freud uses the words Trieb and Trie b haft, which mean instinct, instinctual drive, a sense of being driven toward a certain even though not times plainly anxious.
It is
detail to observe that the
always comprehended goal. Under the circumstances, the term "death instinct" ought to mean an aspiration, a drive to
INTRODUCTION
xv
be dead. Perhaps Freud was right, even though neither the biologist nor the theologian would find it possible to agree with him. Let us assume that Freud was right; he certainly did not prove his case, because there is nothing instinctual about dying, even though the end is inevitable. Here again we find a strange semantic or terminological confusion, a tendency to use terms which are familiar to us in the psychoanalytic glossaries, but which in certain contexts become
somewhat confusing
The above
labels.
considerations
may
serve as a
warning that
it is
not easy to understand great minds even when they appear to speak simply, or perhaps especially when their language appears simple and the terminology familiar.
EDITOR'S NOTE JENSEITS DES LUSTPRINZIPS (a)
1920
GERMAN
EDITIONS:
Leipzig,
Vienna and Zurich; Interaationaler Psycho
analytischer Verlag. Pp. 60.
Same publishers. Pp. 64. Same publishers. Pp. 94.
1921
2nd
1923
3rd ed.
1925
G.S., 6, 191-257.
ed.
1931
Theoretische Schriften, 178-247.
1940
G.W., 13,3-69.
(b]
ENGLISH TRANSLATIONS: Beyond
1922
the Pleasure Principle
London and Vienna: Press. Pp. viii
+
International Psycho-Analytical
90. (Tr. G. J.
M. Hubback;
Pref.
Ernest Jones.)
1924 1942
New York: Boni and Liveright London: Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analy(Re-issue of above.) Publishers. Pp. vi 97. (Tr. J. Strachey.) S.K, 18, 3-64. (Modified version of above.) sis.
1950
1955
Same
+
Freud made a number of additions in the second
edition,
but
subsequent alterations were negligible. The present translation is a corrected reprint of the Standard Edition version.
As is shown by his correspondence, Freud had begun working on a first draft of Beyond the Pleasure Principle in March, 1919, and he reported the draft as finished in the following May. During the same month he was completing his paper on 'The Uncanny* (1919A), which includes a paragraph setting out much of the gist of the present work in a few sentences. In this paragraph he refers to the 'compulsion to repeat' as a phenomenon exhibited in the behaviour of children and in psychoanalytic treatment; he suggests that this compulsion is something derived from the most intimate nature of the instincts; and he declares that it is powerful enough to disregard the xvii
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
xviii
no allusion to the 'death pleasure principle. There is, however, He adds that he has already completed a detailed
instincts*.
The paper on 'The Uncanny' consummary was published in the autumn of 1919.
exposition of the subject. taining this
But Freud held back Beyond the Pleasure Principle for another In the early part of 1920 he was once more at work on it, and now, for the first time apparently, there is a reference to the 'death instincts' in a letter to Eitingon of February 20. He was still revising the work in May and June and it was finally completed by the middle ofJuly, 1920. On September 9, he gave an address to the International Psycho-Analytical Congress
year.
The Hague, with the title 'Supplements to the Theory of Dreams' (Ergdnzungen zur Traumlekre), in which he announced the approaching publication of the book; it was issued early in December. An 'author's abstract' of the address appeared in Int. %. PsychoawL, 6 (1920), 397-8. (A translation of this was published in Int. J. Psycho-Anal^ 1, 354.) It does not seem certain that this abstract was in fact by Freud himself, but it may be of interest to reprint it here (in a new translation). at
'Supplements to the Theory of Dreams
9
The speaker dealt in his brief remarks with three points touching upon the theory of dreams. The first two of these were concerned with the thesis that dreams are wish-fulfilments and brought forward some necessary modifications of it. The third point related to material which brought complete confirmation of his rejection of the alleged "prospective" purposes of dreams. 1 "The speaker explained that, alongside the familiar wishful dreams and the anxiety dreams which could easily be included in the theory, there were grounds for recognizing the existence of a third category, to which he gave the name of "punishment dreams". If we took into account the justifiable assumption of the existence of a special self-observing and critical agency in the ego (the ego ideal, the censor, conscience), these punishment dreams, too, should be subsumed under the theory of wish-fulfilment; for they would represent the fulfilment of a wish on the part of this critical agency. Such dreams, he said, had approximately the same relation to ordinary wishful dreams 1
[See The Interpretation of Dreams, 1900
506-7
.]
VI
(I),
Standard Ed., 5,
EDITOR'S NOTE
xix
symptoms of obsessional neurosis, which arise from rehad to those of hysteria. 'Another class of dreams, however, seemed to the speaker to present a more serious exception to the rule that dreams are
as the
action formation,
wish-fulfilments.
These were the so-called "traumatic" dreams.
in patients suffering from accidents, but they also occur during psycho-analyses of neurotics and bring back to them forgotten traumas of childhood. In connection with the
They occur
fitting these dreams into the theory of wish-fulfilment, the speaker referred to a work shortly to be published under the title of Beyond the Pleasure Principle. 'The third point of the speaker's communication related to an investigation that had not yet been published, by Dr. Varendonck of Ghent. This author had succeeded in bringing under his conscious observation the production of unconscious phantasies on an extensive scale in a half-sleeping state a process which he described as "autistic thinking". It appeared from this enquiry that looking ahead at the possibilities of the next
problem of
day, preparing attempts at solutions and adaptations, etc., lay wholly within the range of this preconscious activity, which also created latent dream-thoughts, and, as the speaker had x always maintained, had nothing to do with the dream-work.'
In the
of Freud's metapsychological writings, Beyond may be regarded as introducing the final phase of his views. He had already drawn attention to the 'compulsion to repeat* as a clinical phenomenon, but here he attributes to it the characteristics of an instinct; here too for the first time he brings forward the new Dichotomy between Eros and the death instincts which found its full elaboration in The Ego and the Id (1923). In Beyond the Pleasure Principle, too, we can see signs of the new picture of the anatomical structure of the mind which was to dominate all Freud's later writings. Finally, the problem of destructiveness, which played an ever series
the Pleasure Principle
more prominent part explicit appearance.
in his theoretical works, makes its first derivation of various elements in the
The
present discussion from his earlier metapsychological works Two Principles of Mental Functioning' (191 1),
such as 'The
1 Cf. Freud's own preface to this book of Varendonck's (Freud, 1921 b, Standard Ed., 18, 271).
xx
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
(1914*:) and 'Instincts and their Vicissitudes' will be obvious. But what is particularly remarkable (1915^) is the closeness with which some of the earlier sections of the present work follow the 'Project for a Scientific Psychology* (19500), drafted by Freud twenty-five years earlier, in 1895.
'Narcissism*
Extracts from the earlier (1922) translation of this work were included in Rickman's General Selection from the Works of Sigmund Freud (1937, 162-194). Editorial additions, whether to the text or the footnotes, are
printed in square brackets.
Beyond the Pleasure Principle
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE IN the theory of psycho-analysis we have no hesitation in assuming that the course taken by mental events is automatically regulated by the pleasure principle. We believe, that is to say, that the course of those events
is
unpleasurable tension, and that
invariably set in motion by an it takes a direction such that
outcome coincides with a lowering of that tension that with an avoidance of unpleasure or a production of pleasure. In taking that course into account in our consideration of the mental processes which are the subject of our study, we are introducing an 'economic' point of view into our work; and if, its final is,
in describing those processes, we try to estimate this 'economic' factor in addition to the 'topographical' and 'dynamic* ones,
we
shall, I think,
be giving the most complete description of
them of which we can at present conceive, and one which deserves to be distinguished by the term 'metapsychologicaT. 1 It far,
is
of no concern to us in this connection to enquire how this hypothesis of the pleasure principle, we have
with
approached or adopted any particular,
historically established,
We
have arrived at these speculative philosophical system. assumptions in an attempt to describe and to account for the of daily observation in our field of study. Priority and originality are not among the aims that psycho-analytic work facts
and the impressions that underlie the hypothesis of the pleasure principle are so obvious that they can scarcely be overlooked. On the other hand we would readily express our sets itself;
gratitude to any philosophical or psychological theory which was able to inform us of the meaning of the feelings of pleasure
and unpleasure which act point
we
are, alas, offered
so imperatively upon us. But on this nothing to our purpose. This is the
most obscure and inaccessible region of the mind, and, since avoid contact with it, the least rigid hypothesis, it seems to me, will be the best. We have decided to relate
we cannot 1
[See Section
IV
of 'The Unconscious' (1915*).] 1
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
2
and unpleasure to the quantity of excitation that is * is not in any way 'bound*; and to present in the mind but relate them in such a manner that unpleasure corresponds to an increase in the quantity of excitation and pleasure to a diminution. What we are implying by this is not a simple relation
pleasure
feelings ^f pleasure and unpleasure and the corresponding modifications in the quantity of excitain view of all we have been taught by psychotion; least of all
between the strength of the
physiology are we suggesting any directly proportional ratio: the factor that determines the feeling is probably the amount of increase or diminution in the quantity of excitation in a given
Experiment might possibly play a part here; but not advisable for us analysts to go into the problem further so long as our way is not pointed by quite definite
period of time. it
is
observations.*
We cannot, however, remain indifferent to the discovery that an investigator of such penetration as G. T. Fechner held a view on the subject of pleasure and unpleasure which coincides in all essentials with the one that has been forced upon us by psycho-analytic work. Fechner's statement is to be found contained in a small work, Einige Idem zur Schopfiings- und Entwick1873 (Part XI, Supplement, 94), and reads as follows: 'In so far as conscious impulses always have some relation to pleasure or unpleasure, pleasure and
lungsgeschichte der Organismen,
unpleasure too can be regarded as having a psycho-physical relation to conditions of stability and instability. This provides a
a hypothesis into which I propose to enter in greater According to this hypothesis, every psychophysical motion rising above the threshold of consciousness is attended by pleasure in proportion as, beyond a certain limit, it approximates to complete stability, and as attended by unpleasure in proportion as, beyond a certain limit, it deviates from complete stability; while between the two limits, which may be described as qualitative thresholds of pleasure and
basis for
detail elsewhere.
1 [The concepts of 'quantity* and of 'bound* excitation, which run through the whole of Freud's writings, found what is perhaps their most detailed discussion in the early 'Project* (1950<x [1895]). See in particular the long discussion of the term 'bound* near the end of Section 1 of Part III of that work. See also p. 28 f. below.] 1 [This point is again mentioned below on p. 57 and further developed in 'The Economic Problem of Masochism* (1924s).]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE unpleasure, 1 ence. . . .'
The
facts
there
is
3
a certain margin of aesthetic indiffer-
which have caused us to believe in the dominance
of the pleasure principle in mental life also find expression in the hypothesis that the mental apparatus endeavours to keep the quantity of excitation present in it as low as possible or at keep it constant. This latter hypothesis is only another
least to
of stating the pleasure principle; for if the work of the mental apparatus is directed towards keeping the quantity of excitation low, then anything that is calculated to increase that quantity is bound to be felt as adverse to the functioning of the
way
apparatus, that is as unpleasurable. The pleasure principle from the principle of constancy: actually the latter principle was inferred from the facts which forced us to adopt
follows
the pleasure principle.* Moreover, a more detailed discussion will show that the tendency which we thus attribute to the
mental apparatus is subsumed as a special case under Fechner's principle of the 'tendency towards stability', to which he has brought the feelings of pleasure and unpleasure into relation. It must be pointed out, however, that strictly speaking it is incorrect to talk of the dominance of the pleasure principle over the course of mental processes. If such a dominance existed, the immense majority of our mental processes would have to be accompanied by pleasure or to lead to pleasure, whereas universal experience completely contradicts any such con-
The most that can be said, therefore, is that there exists mind a strong tendency towards the pleasure principle, but that that tendency is opposed by certain other forces or circumstances, so that the final outcome cannot always be in harmony clusion.
in the
1 'Aesthetic* is here used in [Cf. 'Project', end of Section 8 of Part I. the old sense of 'relating to sensation or perception'.] * [The 'principle of constancy' dates back to the very beginning of Freud's psychological studies. The first published discussion of it of any length was by Breuer (in semi-physiological terms) towards the end of Section 2 (A) of his theoretical part of the Studies on Hysteria (Breuer and Freud, 1895). He there defines it as 'the tendency to keep intracerebral excitation constant*. In the same passage he attributes this principle to Freud and there in fact exist one or two earlier very brief references to it by Freud himself, though these were not published until after his
death. (See Freud, 1941* [1892] and Breuer and Freud, 1940 [1892].) subject is also discussed at length at the beginning of Freud's 'Project', under the name of 'neuronic inertia*.]
The
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLB
4
We
with the tendency towards pleasure. may compare what Fechner (1873, 90) remarks on a similar point: 'Since however a tendency towards an aim does not imply that the aim is attained,
and
since in general the
tions.
*
.
aim
is
attainable only
by approxima-
.'
If we turn
now to the question of what circumstances are able
to prevent the pleasure principle from being carried into effect, we find ourselves once more on secure and well-trodden ground
and, in framing our answer, we have at our disposal a rich fund of analytic experience. The first example of the pleasure principle being inhibited in this way is a familiar one which occurs with regularity. We know that the pleasure principle is proper to a primary method of working on the part of the mental apparatus, but that, from the point of view of the self-preservation of the organism among the difficulties of the external world, it is from the very outset inefficient and even highly dangerous. Under the influence of the ego's instincts of self-preservation, the pleasure principle is 1 replaced by the reality principle, This latter principle does not abandon the intention of ultimately obtaining pleasure, but it nevertheless demands and carries into effect the postponement of satisfaction, the abandonment of a number of possibilities of gaining satisfaction and the temporary toleration of unpleasure as a step on the long indirect road to pleasure. The pleasure principle long persists, however, as the method of working employed by the sexual instincts, which are so hard to 'educate*, and, starting from those instincts, or in the ego itself, it often succeeds in overcoming the reality principle, to the detriment of the organism as a whole. There can be no doubt, however, that the replacement of the reality principle can only be made number, and by no means the most intense, of unpleasurable experiences. Another occasion of the release of unpleasure, which occurs with no less regularity, is to be found in the conflicts and dissensions that take place in the mental apparatus while the ego is passing through its develop-
pleasure principle
by the
responsible for a small
ment into more highly composite organizations. Almost all the energy with which the apparatus is filled arises from its innate instinctual impulses. But these are not all allowed to reach 1
[See 'Formulations
Freud 191 U.]
on the
Two
Principles of
Mental Functioning',
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
5
same phases of development. In the course of things it that individual instincts or parts of happens again and again instincts turn out to be incompatible in their aims or demands the
with the remaining ones, which are able to combine into the The former are then split off from this unity by the process of repression, held back at lower levels
inclusive unity of the ego.
of psychical development and cut off, to begin with, from the of satisfaction. If they succeed subsequently, as can possibility so easily happen with repressed sexual instincts, in struggling through, by roundabout paths, to a direct or to a substitutive
which would in other cases have been an is felt by the ego as unpleasure. As a consequence of the old conflict which ended in repression, a
satisfaction, that event,
opportunity for pleasure,
new breach has occurred in the pleasure principle at the very time when certain instincts were endeavouring, in accordance with the principle, to obtain fresh pleasure. The details of the process by which repression turns a possibility of pleasure into a source of unpleasure are not yet clearly understood or cannot be clearly represented; but there is no doubt that all neurotic 1 unpleasure is of that kind pleasure that cannot be felt as such. The two sources of unpleasure which I have just indicated are very far from covering the majority of our unpleasurable But as regards the remainder it can be asserted with
experiences.
some show ofjustification that their presence does not contradict the dominance of the pleasure principle. Most of the unpleasure that we experience is perceptual unpleasure. It may be perception of pressure by unsatisfied instincts; or it may be external perception which is either distressing in itself or which excites un-
pleasurable expectations in the mental apparatus that is, 1 is recognized by it as a 'danger . The reaction to these
which
instinctual
demands and
threats of danger, a reaction
which
constitutes the proper activity of the mental apparatus, can then be directed in a correct manner by the pleasure principle
or the reality principle by which the former is modified. This does not seem to necessitate any far-reaching limitation of the mental pleasure principle. Nevertheless the investigation of the reaction to external danger is precisely in a position to produce new material and raise fresh questions bearing upon our
present problem. i
[Footnote added 1925:]
No
doubt the
and unpleasure, being conscious
essential point is that pleasure attached to the ego.
feelings, are
II
A CONDITION has long been known
and described which occurs
mechanical concussions, railway disasters and other accidents involving a risk to life; it has been given the name of after severe
The terrible war which has just ended gave a great number of illnesses of this kind, but it at least put an end to the temptation to attribute the cause of the disorder to organic lesions of the nervous system brought about by 'traumatic neurosis'.
rise to
mechanical force. 1 The symptomatic picture presented by traumatic neurosis approaches that of hysteria in the wealth of its similar motor symptoms, but surpasses it as a rule in its strongly marked signs of subjective ailment (in which it resembles hypochondria or melancholia) as well as in the evidence it gives of a far more comprehensive general enfeeblement and disturbance of the mental capacities. No complete explanation has yet been reached either of war neuroses or of the traumatic neuroses of peace. In the case of the war neuroses, the fact that the
same symptoms sometimes came about without the
inter-
vention of any gross mechanical force seemed at once enlightening and bewildering. In the case of the ordinary traumatic neuroses two characteristics emerge prominently: first, that the chief weight in their causation seams to rest upon the factor of surprise, of fright; and secondly, that a wound or injury inflicted simultaneously works as a rule against the development 9 of a neurosis. 'Fright , 'fear* and 'anxiety' 2 are improperly used as synonymous expressions; they are in fact of clear dis-
capable
tinction in their relation to danger. 'Anxiety' describes a particular state of expecting the danger or preparing for it, even
may be an unknown one. Tear' requires a definite object of which to be afraid. 'Fright', however, is the name we give to the state a person gets into when he has run into danger
though
it
without being prepared for it; it emphasizes the factor of surprise. I do not believe anxiety can produce a traumatic neuro1 Cf. the discussion on the psycho-analysis of war neuroses by Freud, Fcrenczi, Abraham, Simmel and Jones (1919) [to which Freud provided the introduction (1919
6
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
7
There is something about anxiety that protects its subject shall return against fright and so against fright-neuroses. 1 to this point later [p. 25 f.].
sis.
We
The study of dreams may be considered the most trustworthy method of investigating deep mental processes. Now dreams occurring in traumatic neuroses have the characteristic of repeatedly bringing the patient back into the situation of his accident, a situation from which he wakes up in another fright. This astonishes people far too litde. They think the fact that the traumatic experience is constantly forcing itself upon the patient even in his sleep is a proof of the strength of that experience: the patient is, as one might say, fixated to his traumaFixations to the experience which started the illness have long been familiar to us in hysteria. Breuer and Freud declared in 1893 * that 'hysterics suffer mainly from reminiscences'. In the war neuroses, too, observers like Ferenczi and Simmel have been able to explain certain motor symptoms by fixation to the moment at which the trauma occurred. I am not aware, however, that patients suffering from traumatic neurosis are much occupied in their waking lives \vith
memories of then* accident Perhaps they are more concerned with not thinking of it. Anyone who accepts it as something selfevident that their dreams should put them back at night into
them to fall ill has misunderstood the nature of dreams. It would be more in harmony with their nature if they showed the patient pictures from his healthy past or of the cure for which he hopes. If we are not to be shaken in our belief in the wish-fulfillinfi tenor of dreams by the dreams of traumatic neurotics, we still have one resource open to us: we may argue that the function of dreaming, like so much else, is upset in this condition and diverted from its purposes, or we the situation that caused
1
is very far indeed from always carrying out the distinche makes here. More often than not he uses the word Angst* to denote a state of fear without any reference to the future. It seems not unlikely that in this passage he is beginning to adumbrate the distinction drawn in Inhibitions^ Symptoms and Anxiety (1926^) between anxiety as a reaction to a traumatic situation probably equivalent to what is here called Sckrech and anxiety as a warning signal of the approach of* such an event. See also his use of the phrase 'preparedness for anxiety* on
[Freud
4
tion
p. 25.] *
['On the Psychical Mechanism of Hysterical Phenomena*, end of
Section
I.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
8
be driven to oTthe egoT1
may
reflect
on the mysterious masochistic Jrcnds :
At this point I propose to leave the dark and dismal subject of the traumatic neurosis and pass on to examine the method of working employed by the mental apparatus in one of its earliest normal activities
The
I
mean
in children's play.
have only recently been summarized and discussed from the psycho-analytic point of view by Pfeifer (1919), to whose paper I would refer my readers. These theories attempt to discover the motives which different theories of children's play
lead children to play, but they fail to bring into the foreground the economic motive, the consideration of the yield of pleasure involved. Without wishing to include the whole field covered
by these phenomena, I have been able, through a chance opportunity which presented itself to throw some light upon the first game played by a little boy of one and a half and invented was more than a mere fleeting observation, for I under the same roof as the child and his parents for some weeks, and it was some time before I discovered the meaning of the puzzling activity which he constantly repeated. The child was not at all precocious in his intellectual development. At the age of one and a half he could say only a few comprehensible words; he could also make use of a number of sounds which expressed a meaning intelligible to those around him. He was, however, on good terms with his parents and their one servant-girl, and tributes were paid to his being a 'good boy*. He did not disturb his parents at night, he conscientiously
by
himself. It
lived
obeyed orders not to touch certain things or go into certain rooms, and above all he never cried when his mother left him for a few hours. At the same time, he was greatly attached to
who had not only fed him herself but had also him without any outside help. This good little boy, however, had an occasional disturbing habit of taking any small objects he could get hold of and throwing them away from him into a corner, under the bed, and so on, so that hunting for his toys and picking them up was often quite a business. As he did
his
mother, looked after
he gave vent to a loud, long-drawn-out e o-o-o-o*, accompanied by an expression of interest and satisfaction. His mother this
1
[The last 15 words of this sentence were added in 1921. see The Interpretation of Dreams (IQQQa),. Standard Ed., 5, 550
For ff.]
all this
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
9
and the writer of the present account were agreed in thinking was not a mere interjection but represented the German word 'for? ['gone']. I eventually realized that it was a game and that the only use he made of any of his toys was to with them. One day I made an observation which play 'gone' confirmed my view. The child had a wooden reel with a piece of string tied round it. It never occurred to him to pull it along the floor behind him, for instance, and play at its being a carriage. What he did was to hold the reel by the string and very skilfully throw it over the edge of his curtained cot, so that it disappeared into it, at the same time uttering his expressive o-o-o-o*. He then pulled the reel out of the cot again by the string and hailed its reappearance with a joyful da* ['there*]. that this
(
(
This, then, was the complete game disappearance and return. As a rule one only witnessed its first act, which was repeated
untiringly as a
in itself, though there is no doubt that the was attached to the second act. 1 The interpretation of the game then became obvious. It was related to the child's great cultural achievement the in-
game
greater pleasure
stinctual renunciation (that
is,
the renunciation of instinctual
which he had made in allowing his mother to go away without protesting. He compensated himself for this, as it were, by himself staging the disappearance and return of the
satisfaction)
objects within his reach. It is of course a matter of indifference from the point of view of judging the effective nature of the game whether the child invented it himself or took it over on
suggestion. Our interest is directed to another point. The child cannot possibly have felt his mother's departure as something agreeable or even indifferent. then does his repetition of this distressing experience as a game fit in with the pleasure principle? It may perhaps be said in reply that her
some outside
How
departure had to be enacted as a necessary preliminary to her joyful return, and that it was in the latter that lay the true purpose
*A
further observation subsequently confirmed this interpretation the child's mother had been away for several hours and on her return was met with the words 'Baby o-o-o-ol* which was at first incomprehensible. It soon turned out, however, that during this long period of solitude the child had found a method of making himself disappear. He had discovered his reflection in a full-length mirror which did not quite reach to the ground, so that by crouching down he could make his mirror-image 'gone'. [A further reference to this story will be found in The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Ed., 5, 46 In.] fully.
One day
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
10
of the game. But against
this
must be counted the observed
fact that the first act, that of departure, was staged as a game in itself and far more frequently than the episode in its entirety,
with
its
pleasurable ending. certain decision can be reached
from the analysis of a an unprejudiced view one gets an imsingle case like this. a game from pression that the child turned his experience into
No
On
another motive. At the outset he was in a passive situation he was overpowered by the experience; but, by repeating it, unpleasurable though it was, as a game, he took on an active to an instinct for mastery part. These efforts might be put down that was acting independently of whether the memory was in itself pleasurable or not. But still another interpretation may be attempted. Throwing away the object so that it was 'gone' might satisfy an impulse of the child's, which was suppressed in his actual life, to revenge himself on his mother for going away from him. In that case it would have a defiant meaning: *A11 right, then, go away! I don't need you. I'm sending you away myself.' A year later, the same boy whom I had observed at his first game used to take a toy, if he was angry with it, and throw it on the floor, exclaiming: 'Go to the fwont!' He had heard at that time that his absent father was *at the front', and was far from regretting his absence; on the contrary he made it quite clear that he had no desire to be disturbed in his sole possession of his mother. 1
We know of other children who liked to express
similar hostile impulses by throwing away objects instead of 8 are therefore left in doubt as to whether the persons.
We
impulse to work over in the mind some overpowering experience so as to make oneself master of it can find expression as a primary event, and independently of the pleasure principle. For, in the case we have been discussing, the child may, after all, only have been able to repeat his unpleasant experience in play because the repetition carried along with it a yield of pleasure of another sort but none the less a direct one.
Nor shall we be helped in our hesitation between these two views by further considering children's play. It is clear that in 1
When
Now
was five and three-quarters, his mother died. really 'gone' ('o-o-o'), the little boy showed no signs of grief. It is true that in the interval a second child had been born and had roused him to violent jealousy* that sire
1
Cf.
this child
was
my note on a childhood memory of Goethe's
(1917 b).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
11
their play children repeat everything that has made a great impression on them in real life, and that in doing so they abreact the strength of the impression and, as one might put
make themselves master of the situation. But on the other hand it is obvious that all their play is influenced by a wish that dominates them the whole time the wish to be grown-up and to be able to do what grown-up people do. It can also be observed that the unpleasurable nature of an experience does it,
not always unsuit it for play. If the doctor looks down a child's throat or carries out some small operation on him, we may be quite sure that these frightening experiences will be the subject
we must not in that connection overlook a yield of pleasure from another source. As the child passes over from the passivity of the experience to the activity of the game, he hands on the disagreeable experiof the next game; but the fact that there
is
ence to one of his playmates and in on a substitute.
this
way
revenges himself
Nevertheless, it emerges from this discussion 'that there is no need to assume the existence of a special imitative instinct in order to provide a motive for play. Finally, a reminder may be added that the artistic play and artistic imitation carried out by adults, which, unlike children's, are aimed at an audience, do not spare the spectators (for instance, in tragedy) the most painful experiences and can yet be felt by them as highly enjoyable. 1 This is convincing proof that, even under the dominance of the pleasure principle, there are ways and means enough of making what is in itself unpleasurable into a subject to be recollected and worked over ih the mind. The consideration of these cases and situations, which have a yield of pleasure as their final outcome, should be undertaken by some system of aesthetics with an economic approach to its subject-matter.
They
no use for our purposes, since they presuppose the and dominance of the pleasure principle; they give
are of
existence
no evidence of the operation of tendencies beyond the pleasure more primitive than it and inprinciple, that is, of tendencies dependent of it. * his posthumously [Freud had made a tentative study of this point in on the Stage' (1942a) published paper on 'Psychopathic Characters which was probably written in 1905 or 1906.]
Ill
years of intense work have had as their result that the immediate aims of psycho-analytic technique are quite
TWENTV-HVE
other to-day than they were at the outset. At first the analysing more than discover the unconscious physician could do no material that was concealed from the patient, put it together, and, at the right moment, communicate it to him. Psycho-
was then
analysis
first
and foremost an
art of interpreting.
Since this did not solve the therapeutic problem, a further aim to oblige the patient to confirm the quickly came in view: from his own memory. In that endeavour construction analyst's
upon the patient's resistances: the art in uncovering these as quickly as possible, in out to the patient and in inducing him by human
the chief emphasis lay consisted
now
pointing them
was where suggestion operating as 'transference* to abandon his resistances. But it became ever clearer that the aim which had been set up the aim that what was unconscious should become conis not scious completely attainable by that method. The remember the whole of what is repressed in him, cannot patient and what he cannot remember may be precisely the essential part of it. Thus he acquires no sense of conviction of the correctness of the construction that has been communicated to
influence
played
its
this
part
He is obliged to repeat the repressed material as a contemporary experience instead of, as the physician would prefer 1 to see, remembering it as something belonging to the past. These reproductions, which emerge with such unwished-for exactitude, always have as their subject some portion of infantile
him.
of the Oedipus complex, that is, and its derivatives; life and they are invariably acted cut in the sphere of the trans-
sexual
When
ference, of the patient's relation to the physician. things have reached this stage, it may be said that the earlier neurosis
has 1
now been replaced by a fresh,
'transference neurosis'. It has
paper on 'Recollecting, Repeating and Working Through* (1914). [An early reference will be found in this same paper to the 'compulsion to repeat', which is one of the principle topics discussed in the present work. (See also the Editor's Note above, p. xi.) The term See
my
'transference neurosis' in the special sense in down also appears in that paper.]
lower
12
which
it is
used a few lines
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
13
been the physician's endeavour to keep this transference neurowithin the narrowest limits: to force as much as possible into the channel of memory and to allow as little as possible to emerge as repetition. Th$ ratio between what is remembered and what is reproduced varies from case to case. The physician cannot as a rule spare his patient this phase of the treatment. He must get him to re-experience some portion of his forgotten life, but must see to it, on the other hand, that the patient retains some degree of aloofness, which will enable him, in spite of everything, to recognize that what appears to be reality is in fact only a reflection of a forgotten past. If this can be successfully achieved, the patient's sense of conviction is won, together sis
with the therapeutic success that is dependent on it. In order to make it easier to understand this 'compulsion to repeat', which emerges during the psycho-analytic treatment of neurotics, we must above all get rid of the mistaken notion that what we are dealing with in our struggle against resistances is resistance on the part of the unconscious. The unconscious offers no resistance whatever to that is to say, the 'repressed* the efforts of the treatment. Indeed, it itself has no other endeavour than to break through the pressure weighing down on it and force its way either to consciousness or to a discharge through some real action. Resistance during treatment arises from the same higher strata and systems of the mind which originally carried out repression. But the fact that, as we know from experience, the motives of the resistances, and indeed the resistances themselves, are unconscious at first -during the treatment, is a hint to us that we should correct a shortcoming in our terminology. We shall avoid a lack of clarity if we make our contrast not between the conscious and the unconscious but between the coherent ego l and the repressed. It is certain that much of the ego is itself unconscious, and notably what we may describe as its nucleus; 2 only a small part of it is covered by the
term 'preconscious'. 3 Having replaced a purely descriptive 1
[Cf. a discussion of this in the Editor's Introduction to The Ego and Id (1923ft), Standard Ed., 19, 7-8; I.P.L., 12, xiii-xiv.] [This is corrected in a footnote at the beginning of Chapter III of The Ego and the Id, ibid., 28, and ibid., 16.] 3 [In its present form this sentence dates from 192 1 In the first edition (1920) it ran: 'It may be that much of the ego is itself unconscious; only a part of it, probably, is covered by the term "preconscious'V]
the
*
.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
14
terminology by one which is systematic or dynamic, we can say 1 that the patient's resistance arises from his ego, and we then at once perceive that the compulsion to repeat must be ascribed to the unconscious repressed. It seems probable that the comitself after
pulsion can only express
the
work of treatment has
meet it and has loosened the repression. 2 gone There is no doubt that the resistance of the conscious and unconscious ego operates under the sway of the pleasure prinavoid the unpleasure which would be produced ciple: it seelcs to of the repressed. Our efforts, on the other hand, liberation the by half-way to
are directed towards procuring the toleration of that unpleasure by an appeal to the reality principle. But how is the compulsion to repeat the manifestation of the power of the repressed related to the pleasure principle? It is clear that the greater part of what is re-experienced under the compulsion to repeat must
cause the ego unpleasure, since it brings to light activities of repressed instinctual impulses. That, however, is unpieasure of a kind we have already considered and does not contradict the pleasure principle : unpleasure for one system and simultaneously 3 satisfaction for the other. But we come now to a new and re-
markable fact, namely that the compulsion to repeat also recalls from the past experiences which include no possibility of pleasure, and which can never, even long ago, have brought satisfaction even to instinctual impulses which have since been '
repressed.
The early efflorescence of infantile sexual life is doomed to extinction because its wishes are incompatible with reality and with the inadequate stage of development which the child has comes to an end in the most disand to the accompaniment of the most painful feelings. Loss of love and failure leave behind them a permanent injury to self-regard in the form of a narcissistic scar, which in my opinion, as well as in Marcinowski's (1918), contributes more than anything to the 'sense of inferiority' reached.
That
efflorescence
tressing circumstances
1
[A fuller and somewhat different account of the sources of resistance be found in Chap.
XI
Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety (1926^).] have argued elsewhere [1923<] that what thus comes to the help of the compulsion to repeat is the factor of
\vill
*
of
[Footnote added 1923:] I
"suggestion' in the treatment which has its roots
physician,
that
is,
deep in
*
the patient's submissiveness to the his unconscious parental complex.
[C Freud's allegorical use of the fairy tale of the 'Three Wishes* at the beginning of Lecture of his Introductory Lectures (1916-17).]
XIV
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
15
which is so common in neurotics. The child's sexual researches, on which limits are imposed by his physical development, lead to no satisfactory conclusion; hence such later complaints as *I
can't accomplish anything; I can't succeed in anything*. The of affection, which binds the child as a rule to the parent of
tie
succumbs to disappointment, to a vain exof satisfaction or to jealousy over the birth of a new pectation baby unmistakable proof of the infidelity of the object of the child's affections. His own attempt to make a baby himself, carried out with tragic seriousness, fails shamefully. The lessening amount of affection he receives, the increasing demands the opposite sex,
of education, hard words and an occasional punishment these at last the full extent to which he has been scorned.
show him
These are a few typical and constantly recurring instances of the ways in which the love characteristic of the age of childhood is brought to a conclusion. Patients repeat all of these unwanted situations and painful emotions in the transference and revive them with the greatest ingenuity. They seek to bring about the interruption of the treatment while it is still incomplete; they contrive once more to feel themselves. scorned, to oblige the physician to
them and
speak
them
coldly; they discover approfor their jealousy; instead of the passionately priate objects desired baby of their childhood, they produce a plan or a
severely to
treat
some grand present which turns out as a rule to be promise of less unreal. None of these tilings can have produced pleasure in the past, and it might be supposed that they would cause less unpleasure to-day if they emerged as memories or dreams instead of taking the form of fresh experiences. They are of course the activities of instincts intended to lead to satisfaction; but no lesson has been learnt from the old experience of these 1 activities having led instead only to unpleasure. In spite of that, a of are under compulsion. they pressure repeated, What psycho-analysis reveals in the transference phenomena of neurotics can also be observed in the lives of some normal is of being pursued by a maligpeople. The impression they give nant fate or possessed by some 'daemonic' power; but psychoanalysis has always taken the view that their fate is for the most themselves and determined by early infantile part arranged by influences. The compulsion which is here in evidence differs in 1 [This sentence was added in 192 1.] no
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE no way from the compulsion to repeat which we have found in neurotics, even though the people we are now considering have 16
never shown any signs of dealing with a neurotic conflict by Thus we have come across people all of producing symptoms. whose human relationships have the same outcome: such as the benefactor who is abandoned in anger after a time by each of his protigiS) however much they may otherwise differ from one another, and who thus seems doomed to taste all the bitterness
of ingratitude; or the man whose friendships all end in betrayal by his friend; or the man who time after time in the course of his life raises someone else into a position of great private or certain interval, himself uppublic authority and then, after a sets that authority and replaces him by a new one; or, again, the lover each of whose love affairs with a woman passes
through the same phases and reaches the same conclusion. This 'perpetual recurrence of the same thing* causes us no astonishment when it relates to active behaviour on the part of the person concerned and when we can discern in him an essential character-trait which always remains the same and which is comof the same experiences. pelled to find expression in a repetition
We are much more impressed by cases where the subject appears to have a passive experience, over which he has no influence, but in which he meets with a repetition of the same fatality. There is the case, for instance, of the woman who married three successive husbands each of whom fell ill soon afterwards and had to be nursed by her on their death-beds. 1 The most moving poetic picture of a fate such as this is given by Tasso in his romantic epic Gerusalemme Liberate. Its hero, Tancred, unwittingly frillg his beloved Clorinda in a duel while she is disguised in the armour of an enemy knight. After her burial he
makes
his
way into a army with
strange magic forest which
terror. He slashes with his but blood streams from the cut and the voice of Clorinda, whose soul is imprisoned in the tree, is heard complaining that he has wounded his beloved once again. If we take into account observations such as these, based upon behaviour in the transference and upon the life-histories of men and women, we shall find courage to assume that there really does exist in the mind a compulsion to repeat which overrides the pleasure principle. Now too we shall be inclined to 1 Cf. the apt remarks on this subject by C, G. Jung (1909). strikes
the Crusaders*
sword at a
tall tree;
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
17
compulsion the dreams which occur in traumatic neuroses and the impulse which leads children to play. But it is to be noted that only in rare instances can we observe the pure effects of the compulsion to repeat, unsupported by other motives. In the case of children's play we have already laid stress on the other ways in which the emergence of the compulsion may be interpreted; the compulsion to repeat and relate to this
instinctual satisfaction which is immediately pleasurable seem to converge here into an intimate partnership. The phenomena
of transference are obviously exploited by the resistance which the ego maintains in its pertinacious insistence upon repression; the compulsion to repeat, which the treatment tries to bring into its service is, as it were, drawn over by the ego to its side 1 (clinging as the ego does to the pleasure principle). great deal of what might be described as the compulsion of destiny seems intelligible on a rational basis; so that we are under no necessity to call in a new and mysterious motive force to explain it. The least dubious instance [of such a motive force] is perhaps that of traumatic dreams. But on maturer reflection we shall be forced to admit that even in the other instances the whole ground is not covered by the operation of the familiar motive forces. Enough is left unexplained to justify the hypothesis of a compulsion to repeat something that seems more primitive, more elementary, more instinctual than the pleasure principle which it over-rides. But if a compulsion to repeat does operate in the mind, we should be glad to know something about it, to learn what function it corresponds to, under what conditions
A
it
can emerge and what to which, after all,
its
relation
is
to the pleasure principle
we have hitherto ascribed dominance over
the course of the processes of excitation in mental 1
life.
[Before 1923 the last clause read: 'the compulsion to repeat is as it to its help by the ego, clinging as it does to the pleasure
were called principle.*]
IV
WHAT
follows
speculation, often far-fetched speculation,
is
which the reader will consider or dismiss according to his individual predilection. It is further an attempt to follow out an idea consistently, out of curiosity to see where it will lead. Psycho-analytic speculation takes as its point of departure the impression, derived from examining unconscious processes,
may be, not the most universal attribute of mental processes, but only a particular function of them.
that consciousness
Speaking in metapsychological terms, it asserts that consciousis a function of a particular system which it describes as C$. 1 What consciousness yields consists essentially of percep-
ness
of excitations coming from the external world and of of pleasure and unpleasure which can only arise from within the mental apparatus; it is therefore possible to assign to tions
feelings
the system Pcpt.-Cs.* a position in space. It must lie on the borderline between outside and inside; it must be turned to-
wards the external world and must envelop the other psychical systems. It will be seen that there is nothing daringly new in these assumptions; we have merely adopted the views on localization held
by cerebral anatomy, which
of consciousness in the cerebral cortex
locates the 'seat
1
the outermost, envelop-
ing layer of the central organ. Cerebral anatomy has no need to consider why, speaking anatomically, consciousness should be lodged on the surface of the brain instead of being safely
housed somewhere in
more
its
inmost interior. Perhaps we shall be
successful in accounting for this situation in the case of
our system
Pcpt.-Cs.
Consciousness
is
not the only distinctive character which
we
On
the basis of impresascribe to the processes in that system. sions derived from our psycho-analytic experience, we assume that all excitatory processes that occur in the other systems leave *[See Freud, The Interpretation of Dreams (1900a), Standard Ed., 5, 610 ff., and "The Unconscious* (1915*), Section II.] 1 [The system Pcpt. (the perceptual system) was first described by Freud in The Interpretation of Dream, Standard Ed., 5, 536 ff In a later paper (1917
system Gr.] IB
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
19
permanent traces behind in them which form the foundation of memory. Such memory-traces, then, have nothing to do with the fact of becoming conscious; indeed they are often most powerful and most enduring when the process which left them behind was one which never entered consciousness. We find it hard to believe, however, that permanent traces of excitation such as these are also left in the system Pcpt.-Cs. If they re-
mained constantly conscious, they would very soon
set limits
to the system's aptitude for receiving fresh excitations. 1 If,
on
the other hand, they were unconscious, we should be faced with the problem of explaining the existence of unconscious
whose functioning was otherwise accompanied by the phenomenon of consciousness. We should, so to say, have altered -nothing and gained nothing by our hypothesis relegating the process of becoming conscious to a special system. Though this consideration is not absolutely conclusive, it neverprocesses in a system
theless leads us to suspect that
becoming conscious and leaving
behind a memory-trace are processes incompatible with each other within one and the same system. Thus we should be able to say that the excitatory process becomes conscious in the system Cs. but leaves no permanent trace behind there; but
that the excitation is transmitted to the systems lying next within and that it is in them that its traces are left. I followed these same lines in the schematic picture which I included in the speculative section of my Interpretation of Dreams. 2 It must
be borne in mind that little enough is known from other sources of the origin of consciousness; when, therefore, we lay down the proposition that consciousness arises instead of a memory-trace^ the assertion deserves consideration, at all events on the ground of
being framed in fairly precise terms. is so, then, the system Cs. is characterized by the peculiarity that in it (in contrast to what happens in the other
its
If this
psychical systems) excitatory processes do not leave behind any permanent change in its elements but expire, as it were, in the phenomenon of becoming conscious. An exception of this sort * What follows is based throughout on Breuer's views in [the second section of his theoretical contribution to] Studies on Hysteria (Breuer and Freud, 1895). [Freud himself discussed the subject in The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Ed. t 5, 538 and it had previously been fully considered in his 'Project' of 1895 (19500), Part I, Section 3. He returned to 1 the topic later in his paper on the 'Mystic Writing-Pad (1925a).] a \Standard Ed.. 5. 538.1
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
20
to the general ride requires to be explained by some factor that Such a factor, which is applies exclusively to that one system.
absent in the other systems, might well be the exposed situation of the system Cs., immediately abutting as it does on the external world. Let us picture a living organism in its most simplified possible form as an undifferentiated vesicle of a substance that is susceptible to stimulation. Then the surface turned towards the its very situation be differentiated and an organ for receiving stimulL Indeed embryology
external world will from will serve as
s
capacity as a recapitulation of developmental history, actually shows us that the central nervous system originates in
its
from the ectoderm; the grey matter of the cortex remains a derivative of the primitive superficial layer of the organism and may have inherited some of its essential properties. It would be easy to suppose, then, that as a result of the ceaseless impact of external stimuli on the surface of the vesicle, its substance to a certain depth may have become permanently modified, so that excitatory processes run a different course in it from what they run in the deeper layers. A crust would thus be formed which would at last have been so thoroughly 'baked through' by stimulation that it would present the most favourable possible conditions for the reception of stimuli and become incapable of any further modification. In terms of the system Cy., this would mean that its elements could undergo no further permanent modification from the passage of excitation, because they had already been modified in the respect in question to the greatest possible extent: now, however, they would have become capable of giving rise to consciousness. Various ideas may be formed which cannot at present be verified as to the nature of this modification of the substance and of the excitatory process. It may be supposed that, in passing from one element to another, an excitation has to overcome a resistance, and that the diminution of resistance thus effected is what lays down a permanent trace of the excitation, that is, a facilitation. In the system Cs. 9 then, resistance of this kind to passage from one
element to another would no longer exist. 1 This picture can be brought into relation with Breuer's distinction between quiescent (or bound) and mobile cathectic energy in the elements 1 [This passage is foreshadowed in the later half of Section 3 of Part I of the 'Project'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE of the psychical systems; carry no
1
21
the elements of the system Cs. would
bound energy but only energy capable of
free dis-
charge. It seems best, however, to express oneself as cautiously as possible on these points. None the less, this speculation will have enabled us to bring the origin of consciousness into some sort of connection with the situation of the system Cs. and with the peculiarities that must be ascribed to the excitatory processes taking place in it.
But we have more to say of the living vesicle with its receptive This little fragment of living substance is susmiddle of an external world charged with the most powerful energies; and it would be killed by the stimulation emanating from these if it were not provided with a cortical layer. pended in the
protective shield against stimuli. It acquires the shield in this way: its outermost surface ceases to have the structure proper to living matter, becomes to some degree inorganic and thence-
forward functions as a special envelope or membrane resistant to stimuli. In consequence, the energies of the external world are able to pass into the next underlying layers, which have remained living, with only a fragment of their original intensity; and these layers can devote themselves, behind the protective shield, to the reception of the amounts of stimulus which have been allowed through it. By its death, the outer layer has saved all the deeper ones from a similar fate unless, that is to say, stimuli reach it which are so strong that they break through the protective shield. Protection against stimuli is an almost more important function for the living organism than reception
of stimuli.
store of energy
The
protective shield
and must above
is
supplied with
its
own
endeavour to preserve the special modes of transformation of energy operating in it against the effects threatened by the enormous energies at work in the external world effects which tend towards a levelling out of them and hence towards destruction. The main purpose of the reception of stimuli is to discover the direction and nature of the all
external stimuli; and for that it is enough to take small specimens of the external world, to sample it in small quantities. In highly developed organisms the receptive cortical layer of the former vesicle has long been withdrawn into the depths of 1
Breuer and Freud, 1895. [See Section 2 of Brevier's theoretical con-
tribution, and in particular the footnote at the beginning of that section. Cf. also footnote 1 on p. 2 above.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
22
the interior of the body, though portions of it have been left behind on the surface immediately beneath the general shield against stimuli. These are the sense organs, which consist
of apparatus for the reception of certain specific but which also include special arrangements for further protection against excessive amounts of stimulation and for excluding unsuitable kinds of stimuli. 1 It is characteristic of them that they deal only with very small quantities of external stimulation and only take in samples of the external world. They may perhaps be compared with feelers which are all the time making tentative advances towards the external world and then drawing back from it. At this point I shall venture to touch for a moment upon a subject which would merit the most exhaustive treatment. As a result of certain psycho-analytic discoveries, we are to-day in a position to embark on a discussion of the Kantian theorem that time and space are 'necessary forms of thought*. We have learnt that unconscious mental processes are in themselves 'timeless*. 2 This means in the first place that they are not ordered temporally, that time does not change them in any way and that the idea of time cannot be applied to them. These are negative characteristics which can only be clearly understood if a comparison is made with conscious mental processes. On the other hand, our abstract idea of time seems to be wholly derived from the method of working of the system Pcpt.-Cs. and to correspond to a perception on its own part of that method of working. This mode of functioning may perhaps constitute another way of providing a shield against stimuli. I know that these remarks must sound very obscure, but I must limit myself to these hints. 8 We have pointed out how the living vesicle is provided with a shield against stimuli from the external world; and we had previously shown that the cortical layer next to that shield must be differentiated as an organ for receiving stimuli from without. This sensitive cortex, however, which is later to become the essentially
effects of stimulation,
system Cs., also receives excitations from within. The situation of the system between the outside and the inside and the differ* 1
[Cf. 'Project*, Part I, Sections 5
[See Section
8
V of
and
9.]
"The Unconscious' (1915*).] [Freud recurs to the origin of the idea of time at the
on "The Mystic Writing-Pad
1
end of his paper
(1925s). The same paper -contains a further discussion of the 'shield against stimuli'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
23
encc between the conditions governing the reception of excitations in the two cases have a decisive effect on the functioning of the system and of the whole mental apparatus. Towards the outside it is shielded against stimuli, and the amounts of excitation impinging on it have only a reduced effect. Towards the inside there can be no such shield; 1 the excitations in the deeper layers extend into the system directly and in undiminished amount, in so far as certain of their characteristics give rise to feelings
in
the
pleasure-unpleasure
coming from within
series.
The
excitations
however, in their intensity and in in their amplitude, perhaps more other, qualitative, respects commensurate with the system's method of working than the stimuli which stream in from the external world. 2 This state of things produces two definite results. First, the feelings of pleasure and unpleasure (which are an index to what is happening in the interior of the apparatus) predominate over all external stimuli. And secondly, a particular way is adopted of dealing with any internal excitations which produce too great an increase of unpleasure: there is a tendency to treat them as though they were acting, not from the inside, but from the outside, so that it may be possible to bring the shield against stimuli into operation as a means of defence against them. This is the origin of projection, which is destined to play such a large part in the causation of pathological processes. I have an impression that these last considerations have brought us to a better understanding of the dominance of the pleasure principle; but no light has yet been thrown on the cases that contradict that dominance. Let us therefore go a step further. We describe as 'traumatic* any excitations from outside which are powerful enough to break through the protective shield. It seems to me that the concept of trauma necessarily implies a connection of this kind with a breach in an otherwise are,
efficacious barrier against stimuli.
Such an event
as
an
ex-
to provoke a disturbance on a large scale in the functioning of the organism's energy and to^ set in motion every possible defensive measure. At the same time, the is pleasure principle is for the moment put out of action. There ternal
trauma
is
bound
possibility of preventing the mental apparatus from being flooded with large amounts of stimulus, and another
no longer any i
[Cf. 'Project', beginning of Section 10 of Part I.] Part I.] [Cf. 'Project*, later part of Section 4 of
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
24
problem arises instead the problem of mastering the amounts of stimulus which have broken in and of binding them, in the psychical sense, so that they can then be disposed of. The specific unpleasure of physical pain is probably the result of the protective shield having been broken through in a limited area. There is then a continuous stream of excitations
from the part of the periphery concerned to the central apparatus of the mind, such as could normally arise only from within the apparatus. And how shall we expect the mind to react to this invasion? Gathectic energy is summoned from all sides to provide sufficiently high cathexes of energy in the 1
environs of the breach.
An
'anticathexis'
on a grand
scale
is
set
up, for whose benefit all the other psychical systems are impoverished,, so that the remaining psychical functions are extenmust endeavour to draw a sively paralysed or reduced.
We
and use them as a basis for our metapsychological speculations. From the present case, then, we infer that a system which is itself highly cathected is capable of taking up an additional stream of fresh inflowing energy and of converting it into quiescent cathexis., that is of binding it psychically. The higher the system's own quiescent cathexis, the greater seems to be its binding force; conversely, therefore, the lower its cathexis, the less capacity will it have for s taking up inflowing energy and the more violent must be the consequences of such a breach in the protective shield against stimuli. To this view it cannot be justly objected that the increase of cathexis round the breach can be explained far more simply as the direct result of the inflowing masses of excitation. If that were so, the mental apparatus would merely receive an increase in its cathexes of energy, and the paralysing character of pain and the impoverishment of all the other systems would remain unexplained. Nor do the very violent phenomena of discharge to which pain gives rise affect our explanation, for they occur in a reflex manner that is, they follow without the intervention of the mental apparatus. The indefiniteness of all our discussions on what we describe as metapsychology is of course due to the fact that we know nothing of the nature of the excitatory process that takes place in the elements of the lesson
1
from examples such
Cf. 'Instincts
Inhibitions , *
and
as this
their Vicissitudes' (1915*:) [and-
Addendum C
of
Symptoms and Anxiety (1926^)].
[Cf. the 'principle of the insusceptibility to excitation of uncathected systems* in a footnote near the end of Freud, 1917'd.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
25
psychical systems, and that we do not feel justified in framing any hypothesis on the subject. We are consequently operating all the time with a large unknown factor, which we are
obliged to carry over into every new formula. It may be reasonably supposed that this excitatory process can be carried out with energies that vary quantitatively, it may also seem probable
has more than one quality (in the nature of amplitude, As a new factor we have taken into consideration Breuer's hypothesis that charges of energy occur in two forms [see pp. 20-1]; so that we have to distinguish between two kinds that
it
for instance).
of cathexis of the psychical systems or their elements a freely flowing cathexis that presses on towards discharge and a quiescent cathexis. We may perhaps suspect that the binding of the energy that streams into the mental apparatus consists in its change from a freely flowing into a quiescent state.
We may, I think, tentatively venture to regard the common traumatic neurosis as a consequence of an extensive breach being made in the protective 'shield against stimuli. This would seem to reinstate the old, naive theory of shock, in apparent contrast to the later and psychologically more ambitious theory which attributes aetiological importance not to the effects of mechanical violence but to fright and the threat to life. These opposing views are not, however, irreconcilable; nor is the psycho-analytic view of the traumatic neurosis identical with the shock theory in its crudest form. The latter regards the essence of the shock as being the direct damage to the molecular structure or even to the histological structure of the elements of the nervous system; whereas what we seek to understand are the effects produced on the organ of the mind by the breach in the shield against stimuli and by the problems that follow in its And we still attribute importance to the element of fright.
train.
It is caused by lack of any preparedness for anxiety, * including lack of hypercathexis of the systems that would be the first to receive the stimulus. Owing to their low cathexis those
systems are not in a good position for binding the inflowing amounts of excitation and the consequences of the breach in the protective shield follow all the more easily. It will be seen, then, that preparedness for anxiety and the hypercathexis of the receptive systems constitute the last line of defence of the shield against stimuli. In the case of quite a number of traumas, the 1
[Cf. footnote
1
on
p. 7 above.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
26
between systems that are unprepared and systems that are well prepared through being hypercathected may be a decisive factor in determining the outcome; though where the strength of a trauma exceeds a certain limit this factor will no difference
doubt cease to carry weight. The fulfilment of wishes is, as we know, brought about in a hallucinatory manner by dreams, and under the dominance of the pleasure principle this has become their function. But it is not in the service of that principle that the dreams of patients suffering from traumatic neuroses lead them back with such regularity to the situation in which the trauma occurred. We may assume, rather, that dreams are here helping to carry out another task, which must be accomplished before the dominance of the pleasure principle can even begin. These dreams are endeavouring to master the stimulus retrospectively, by developing the anxiety whose omission was the cause of the traumatic neurosis. They thus afford us a view of a function of the mental apparatus which, though it does not contradict the pleasure principle, is nevertheless independent of it and seems to be more primitive than the purpose of gaining
and avoiding unpleasure. This would seem to be the place, then, at which to admit for the first time an exception to the proposition that dreams are fulfilments of wishes. Anxiety dreams, as I have shown repeatedly and in detail, offer no such exception. Nor do 'punishment dreams', for they merely replace the forbidden pleasure
wish-fulfilment
by the appropriate punishment for
it;
that
is
to
say, they fulfil the wish of the sense of guilt which is the reaction to the repudiated impulse. 1 But it is impossible to classify as
wish-fulfilments the
dreams we have been discussing which
occur in traumatic neuroses, or the dreams during psychoanalyses which bring to memory the psychical traumas of childhood. They arise, rather, in obedience to the compulsion to repeat, though
it is
true that in analysis that compulsion
is
a supported by the wish (which is encouraged by 'suggestion') to conjure up what has been forgotten and repressed. Thus it would seem that the function of dreams, which consists in i [Sec The Interpretation of Dreams (1900a), Standard Ed., 5, 557, and Section 9 of Freud's 'Remarks on the Theory and Practice of Dream-
Interpretation* (1923*:).] 8 [The clause in brackets is
was substituted in 1923 for the words 'which not unconscious* which appeared in the earlier editions.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
27
any motives that might interrupt sleep, by fulfilling the wishes of the disturbing impulses, is not their original function. It would not be possible for them to perform that
setting aside
function until the whole of mental
life had accepted the dominance of the pleasure principle. If there is a 'beyond the pleasure principle', it is only consistent to grant that there was also a time before the purpose of dreams was the fulfilment of wishes. This would imply no denial of their later function. But if once this general rule has been broken, a further question arises. May not dreams which, with a view to the psychical binding of traumatic impressions, obey the compulsion to repeat may not such dreams occur outside analysis as well? And the reply can only be a decided affirmative. I have argued elsewhere * that 'war neuroses' (in so far as that term implies something more than a reference to the circumstances of the illness's onset) may very well be traumatic neuroses which have been facilitated by a conflict in the ego. The fact to which I have referred on page 6, that a gross physical injury caused simultaneously by the trauma diminishes the chances that a neurosis will develop, becomes intelligible if one bears in mind two facts which have been stressed by psycho-analytic research: firstly, that mechanical agitation must be recognized as one of the sources of sexual excitation, 3 and secondly, that painful and feverish illnesses exercise a powerful effect, so long as they last, on the distribution of libido. Thus, on the one hand, the mechanical violence of the trauma would liberate a quantity of sexual excitation which, owing to the lack of preparation for anxiety, would have a traumatic effect; but, on the other hand, the simultaneous physical injury, by calling for a narcissistic hypercathexis of the injured organ, 3 would bind the excess of excitation. It is also well known, though the libido theory has not yet made sufficient use of the fact, that such severe disorders in the distribution of libido as melancholia are temporarily brought to an end by intercurrent organic illness, and indeed that even a fully developed condition of dementia praecox is capable of a temporary remission in these
same circumstances. 1
See
2
Cf.
my introduction (I9l9d) to Psycho-Analysis and the War Neuroses. my remarks elsewhere (Three Essays [Standard Ed., 7, 201-2; on the effect of swinging and railway-travel. paper on narcissism (19 14*:) [Beginning of Section II].
I.P.L., 57, 67-8]) 3
See
my
V THE fact that the cortical layer which receives stimuli is without any protective as
its
shield against excitations
from within must have of stimulus have a
result that these latter transmissions
preponderance in economic importance and often occasion economic disturbances comparable with traumatic neuroses. The most abundant sources of this internal excitation are what are described as the organism's 'instincts*
the representatives
of all the forces originating in the interior of the body and transmitted to the mental apparatus at once the most important and the most obscure element of psychological research. It will perhaps not be thought too rash to suppose that the impulses arising from the instincts do not belong to the type of bound nervous processes but of freely mobile processes which
The best part of what we know of these derived from our study of the dream- work. there discovered that the processes in the unconscious systems were press towards discharge.
processes
We
is
fundamentally different from those in the preconscious (or conscious) systems. In the unconscious, cathexes can easily be completely transferred, displaced and condensed. Such treatment, however, could produce onfy invalid results if it were applied to preconscious material; and this accounts for the familiar peculiarities exhibited by manifest dreams after the preconscious residues of the preceding day have been worked over in accordance with the laws operating in the unconscious.
of process found in the unconscious as the 'primary' psychical process, in contradistinction to the 'secondary' process which is the one obtaining in our normal I described the type
waking
impulses have the unconscious systems as their point of impact, it is hardly an innovation to say that they obey the primary process. Again, it is easy to
life.
Since
the
primary psychical process with Breuer's
all instinctual
identify
cathexis
freely mobile in his bound or
and the secondary process with changes it would be the task of the higher
tonic cathexis. 1 If so,
strata of
the mental apparatus to bind the instinctual excitation reaching 1
Cf.
Cf. also
my Interpretation of Dreams,
Chapter VII [Standard Ed., 5, 588 ff. Breuer and Freud, 1895 (Section 2 of Breuer's theoretical con-
tribution)].
28
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
29
A
failure to effect this binding would the primary process. provoke a disturbance analogous to a traumatic neurosis; and only after the binding has been accomplished would it be
dominance of the pleasure principle (and of its modification, the reality principle) to proceed unhindered. Till then the other task of the mental apparatus, the task of mastering or binding excitations, would have precedence not, indeed, possible for the
in opposition to the pleasure principle, but independently of and to some extent in disregard of it.
it
The manifestations of a compulsion to repeat (which we have described as occurring in the early activities of infantile mental life as well as among the events of psycho-analytic treatment) exhibit to a high degree an instinctual 1 character and, when they act in opposition to the pleasure principle, give the appear-
ance of some 'daemonic' force at work. In the case of children's play we seemed to see that children repeat unpleasurable experiences for the additional reason that they can master a powerful impression far more thoroughly by being active than they could by merely experiencing it passively. Each fresh repetition seems to strengthen the mastery they are in search of. Nor can children have their pleasurable experiences repeated often enough, and they are inexorable in their insistence that the repetition shall be an identical one. This character trait disappears later on. If a joke is heard for a second time it produces almost no effect; a theatrical production never creates so great an impression the second time as the first; indeed, it is hardly possible to persuade an adult who has very much enjoyed reading a book to re-read it immediately. Novelty is always the condition of enjoyment. But children will never tire of asking an adult to repeat a game that he has shown them or played with them, till he is too exhausted to go on. And if a child has been told a nice story, he will insist on hearing it over and over again rather than a new one; and he will remorselessly stipulate that the repetition shall be an identical one and will correct any alterations ofwhich the narrator may be guilty though they may 8 actually have been made in the hope of gaining fresh approval. 1
['Triebhaf? here
word
*
Trieb* bears
the next paragraph. The of a feeling of urgency than the English
and at the beginning of
much more
'instinct*.] * [Cf. some remarks on this towards the end of the Chapter VII of Freud's book on jokes (1905).]
sixth section of
5U
tfiiYUJND
THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
None of
this contradicts the pleasure principle; repetition, the re-experiencing of something identical, is clearly in itself a source of pleasure. In the case of a person in analysis, on the contrary, the compulsion to repeat the events of his childhood in the transference evidently disregards the pleasure
principle in ev^ry way. The patient behaves in a purely infantile fashion and thus shows us that the repressed memory-traces of his primaeval experiences are not present in him in a bound
and are indeed in a sense incapable of obeying the secondary process. It is to this fact of not being bound, moreover, that they owe their capacity for forming, in conjunction with the residues of the previous day, a wishful phantasy that emerges in a dream. This same compulsion to repeat frequently meets us as an obstacle to our treatment when at the end of an analysis we try to induce the patient to detach himself completely from his physician. It may be presumed, too, that when people una dread of rousing familiar with analysis feel an obscure fear state
something that, so they feel, is better left sleeping what they are afraid of at bottom is the emergence of this compulsion with its hint of possession by some 'daemonic* power. But how is the predicate of being 'instinctual' 1 related to the compulsion to repeat? At this point we cannot escape a suspicion that we may have come upon the track of a universal attribute of instincts and perhaps of organic life in general which has not hitherto been clearly recognized or at least not explicitly stressed. 2 It seems, then, that an instinct is an urge inherent in organic
an earlier state of things which the living entity has been obliged to abandon under the pressure of external disturbing forces; that is, it is a kind of organic elasticity, or, to put it another way, the expression of the inertia inherent in life to restore
3
organic life. This view of instincts strikes us as strange because we have become used to see in them a factor impelling towards change
and development, whereas we are now asked to recognize in them the precise contrary an expression of the conservative nature of living substance. On the other hand we soon call to mind examples from animal life which seem to confirm the 1
[See the last footnote but one.] [The last six words were added in 1921.] * I have no doubt that similar notions as to the nature of have already been put fonvard repeatedly. *
'instincts*
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
31
view that instincts are historically determined. Certain fishes, for instance, undertake laborious migrations at spawning-time in order to deposit their spawn in particular waters far removed
from their customary haunts. In the opinion of many biologists what they are doing is merely to seek out the localities in which their species formerly resided but which in the course of time they have exchanged for others. The same explanation is believed to apply to the migratory flights of birds of passage but we are quickly relieved of the necessity for seeking for further examples by the reflection that the most impressive proofs of there being an organic compulsion to repeat lie in the
phenomena of heredity and the how the germ of a living animal
facts is
of embryology.
We
see
obliged in the course of its
if only in a transient and abbreviated fashion) the structures of all the forms from which it is sprung, instead of proceeding quickly by the shortest path to its final shape. This behaviour is only to a very slight degree attributable to mechanical causes, and the historical explanation cannot accordingly be neglected. So too the power of regenerating a lost organ by growing afresh a precisely similar one extends far up into the animal kingdom. We shall be met by the plausible objection that it may very well be that, in addition to the conservative instincts which impel
development to recapitulate (even
towards repetition, there may be others which push forward towards progress and the production of new forms. This argument must certainly not be overlooked, and it will be taken into account at a later stage. 1 But for the moment it is tempting to pursue to its logical conclusion the hypothesis that all instincts tend towards the restoration of an earlier state of things. The outcome may give an impression of mysticism or of sham profundity; but we can feel quite innocent of having had any such purpose in view. We seek only for the sober results of research or of reflection based on it; and we have no wish to find in those 3 results any quality other than certainty. Let us suppose, then, that all the organic instincts are conservative, are acquired historically and tend towards the half of this sentence was added in 1921.] The reader should not overlook the fact that what follows is the development of an extreme line of thought. Later on, when account is taken of the sexual instincts, it will be found that the necessary limitations and corrections are applied to it. i
[The
3
[Footnote added 1925:]
last
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
32
restoration of an earlier state of things. It follows that the pheno niena of organic development must be attributed to externa
and diverting influences. The elementary living would from its very beginning have had no wish tc change; if conditions remained the same, it would do no mor< than constantly repeat the same course of life. In the last resort what has left its mark on the development of organisms must be the history of the earth we live in and of its relation to the sun. Every modification which is thus imposed upon the course oi disturbing entity
the organism's life is accepted by the conservative organic and stored up for further repetition. Those instincts are therefore bound to give a deceptive appearance of being forces instincts
tending towards change and progress, whilst in fact they are merely seeking to reach an ancient goal by paths alike old and new. Moreover it is possible to specify this final goal of all organic striving. It would be in contradiction to the conservative nature of the instincts if the goal of life were a state of things which had never yet been attained. On the contrary, it must be an old state of things, an initial state from which the living entity has at one time or other departed and to which it is
striving to return by the circuitous paths along leads. If we are to take it as a truth that
development
which its knows no
exception that everything living dies for internal reasons then we shall be compelled to say that 'the aim of all life is death and, looking backwards, that
becomes inorganic once again
9
9
'inanimate things existed before living ones . The attributes of life were at some time
evoked in inanimate matter by the action of a force of whose nature we can form no conception. It may perhaps have been a process similar in type to that which later caused the development of consciousness in a particular stratum of living matter. The tension which then arose in what had hitherto been an inanimate substance endeavoured to cancel itself out. In this way the first instinct came into being: the instinct to return to the inanimate state. It was still an easy matter at that time for a living substance to die; the course of its life was probably only a brief one, whose direction was determined by the chemical structure of the young life. For a long time, perhaps, living substance was thus being constantly created afresh and easily dying, till decisive external influences altered in such a way as to oblige the still surviving substance to diverge ever more widely from its original course
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
33
life and to make ever more complicated detours before reaching its aim of death. These circuitous paths to death, faithfully kept to by the conservative instincts, would thus present us to-day with the picture of the phenomena of life. If we firmly maintain the exclusively conservative nature of instincts, we cannot arrive at any other notions as to the origin and aim
of
of life.
The
implications in regard to the great groups of instincts we believe, lie behind the phenomena of life in
which, as
organisms must appear no
less
bewildering.
such as
The
hypothesis of
we
attribute to all living opposition to the idea that instinctual
self-preservative instincts,
beings, stands in marked as a whole serves to bring about death. Seen in this light, the theoretical importance of the instincts of self-preservation,
life
of self-assertion and of mastery greatly diminishes. They are
component
instincts
whose function
it
is
to assure that the
organism shall follow its own path to death, and to ward off any possible ways of returning to inorganic existence other than those which are immanent in the organism itself. We have no longer to reckon with the organism's puzzling determination (so hard to fit into any context) to maintain its own existence in the face of every obstacle. What we are left with is the fact that the
organism wishes to die only in its own fashion. Thus these guardians of life, too, were originally the myrmidons of death.
Hence
the paradoxical situation that the living organism most energetically against events (dangers, in fact) which might help it to attain its life's aim rapidly by a kind of short-circuit. Such behaviour is, however, precisely what chararises
struggles
acterizes
purely instinctual
as
contrasted
with intelligent
efforts. 1
But
The
let
us pause for a
moment and
reflect. It
cannot be
so.
sexual instincts, to which the theory of the neuroses gives
a quite special place, appear under a very different aspect. The external pressure which provokes a constantly increasing extent of development has not imposed itself upon every organism. Many have succeeded in remaining up to the present time at their lowly level. Many, though not all, such creatures, which must resemble the earliest stages of the higher animals 1
[In the editions before 1925 the following footnote appeared at this 'A correction of this extreme view of the self-preservative instincts
point.
follows.*]
34
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
and plants, are, indeed, living to-day. In the same way, the whole path of development to natural death is not trodden by all the elementary entities which compose the complicated body of one of the higher organisms. Some of them, the germ-cells, probably retain the original structure of living matter and, after a certain time, with their full complement of inherited and freshly acquired instinctual dispositions, separate themselves from the organism as a whole. These two characteristics may be precisely what enables them to have an independent existence. Under favourable conditions, they begin to develop that is, to repeat the performance to which they owe their existence; and in the end once again one portion of their substance pursues its development to a finish, while another portion harks back once
again as a fresh residual germ to the beginning of the process of development. These germ-cells, therefore, work against the death of the living substance and succeed in winning for it
what we can only regard as potential immortality, though that may mean no more than a lengthening of the road to death. We must regard as in the highest degree significant the fact that this function of the germ-cell possible, if it coalesces with
differing from it. The instincts which
is
another
reinforced, or only
made
cell similar to itself and
yet
watch over the destinies of these elemen-
tary organisms that survive the whole individual, which provide them with a safe shelter while they are defenceless against the stimuli of the external world, with other germ-cells, and so
which bring about their meeting on these constitute the group of
They are conservative in the same sense other instincts in that they bring back earlier states of living substance; but they are conservative to a higher degree in that they are peculiarly resistant to external influences; and they are conservative too in another sense in that they preserve the sexual instincts. as the
life itself
for a comparatively long period. 1
They are the true They operate against the purpose of the other instincts, which leads, by reason of their function, to death; and this fact indicates that there is an opposition between them and
life instincts.
the other instincts, an opposition whose importance was long ago recognized by the theory of the neuroses. It is as though the 1 [Footnote added 1923:] Yet it is to them alone that we can attribute an internal impulse towards 'progress' and towards higher development! (See below [pp. 42-3].)
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
35
of the organism moved with a vacillating rhythm. One group of instincts rushes forward so as to reach the final aim of life as swiftly as possible; but when a particular stage in the advance has been reached, the other group jerks back to a certain point to make a fresh start and so prolong the journey. And even though it is certain that sexuality and the distinction between the sexes did not exist when life began, the possibility remains that the instincts which were later to be described as sexual may have been in operation from the very first, and it may not be true that it was only at a later time that they started life
upon their work of opposing the Let us now hark back for a whether there is any basis at
activities
moment
of the 'ego-instincts'. 1 and consider
ourselves
all for these speculations. Is it really the case that, apart from the sexual instincts there are no instincts that do not seek to restore an earlier state of things?
f
none that aim at a state of things which has never yet been attained? I know of no certain example from the organic world that would contradict the characterization I have thus proposed. There is unquestionably no universal instinct that there are
towards higher development observable in the animal or plant world, even though it is undeniable that development does in fact occur in that direction. But on the one hand it is often merely a matter of opinion when we declare that one stage of development is higher than another, and on the other hand biology teaches us that higher development in one respect is very frequently balanced or outweighed by involution in another. Moreover there are plenty of animal forms from whose early stages we can infer that their development has, on the contrary, assumed a retrograde character. Both higher development and involution might well be the consequences of adapta-
tion to the pressure of external forces; and in both cases the part played by instincts might be limited to the retention (in the form of an internal source of pleasure) of an obligatory
modification. 3 1 [Footnote added 1925:] It should be understood from the context that the term *ego-instincts* is used here as a provisional description and derives from the earliest psycho-analytical terminology. [See below,
pp. 44-5 and 55.] 1 [These five words were italicized from 1921 onwards.] 8 Ferenczi (1913, 137) has reached the same conclusion along different lines: *If this thought is pursued to its logical conclusion, one must make oneself familiar with the idea of a tendency to perseveration or
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
36 It
may
be
difficult, too, for
many of us,
to
abandon the
belief
an instinct towards perfection at work in human beings, which has brought them to their present high level of intellectual achievement and ethical sublimation and which may be expected to watch over their development into supermen. I have no faith, however, in the existence of any such internal instinct and I cannot see how this benevolent illusion is to be preserved. The present development of human beings requires, as it seems to me, no different explanation from that of that there
animals.
is
What
appears in a minority of
human
individuals as
an untiring impulsion towards further perfection can
easily be understood as a result of the instinctual repression upon which is based all that is most precious in human civilization. The repressed instinct never ceases to strive for complete satisfaction, which would consist in the repetition of a primary experience of satisfaction. No substitutive or reactive formations and no
sublimations will suffice to remove the repressed instinct's persisting tension; and it is the difference in amount between the pleasure of satisfaction which is demanded and that which is actually achieved that provides the driving factor which will permit of no halting at any position attained, but, in the poet's
words, 'ungebandigt immer vorwdrts
1
dringt'.
The backward path
that leads to complete satisfaction is as a rule obstructed by the resistances which maintain the repressions. So there is no alternative but to advance in the direction in which growth is free though with no prospect of bringing the process to a conclusion or of being able to reach the goal. The processes involved in the formation of a neurotic phobia, which is nothing still
else
than an attempt at
from the satisfaction of an instinct, manner of origin of this suptowards perfection' an instinct which canflight
present us with a model of the posititious 'instinct
not possibly be attributed to conditions for
its
every
human
being.
The
dynamic
are, indeed, universally present; only in rare cases that the economic situation appears
development
but it is to favour the production of the phenomenon. I will add only a word to suggest that the efforts of Eros to
regression dominating organic life as well, while the tendency to further development, to adaptation, etc., would become active only as a result
of external stimuli.' 1 [Tresses ever forward unsubdued,'] Mephistopheles in Faust, Part [Scene 4].
I
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE combine organic substances into ever larger
unities
37
probably
provide a substitute for this 'instinct towards perfection' whose existence we cannot admit. The phenomena that are attributed to it seem capable of explanation by these efforts of Eros taken in conjunction with the results of repression. 1 1 [This paragraph, which was added in 1923, anticipates the account of Eros that is to follow in the next chapter, p. 44 fF.]
VI
THE
upshot of our enquiry so far has been the drawing of 2 sharp distinction between the 'ego-instincts' and the sexual instincts, and the view that the former exercise pressure toward* death and the latter towards a prolongation of life. But thii conclusion is bound to be unsatisfactory in many respects ever to ourselves. Moreover, it is actually only of the former group oi instincts that we can predicate a conservative, or rather retrograde, character corresponding to a compulsion to repeat. Foi
on our hypothesis the
ego-instincts arise from the coming tc of inanimate matter and seek to restore the inanimate state; whereas as regards the sexual instincts, though it is true that life
they reproduce primitive states of the organism, what the^ are clearly aiming at by every possible means is the coalescence of two germ-cells which are differentiated in a particular way, If this union is not effected, the germ-cell dies along with all the other elements of the multicellular organism. It is only on this condition that the sexual function can prolong the cell's life and lend it the appearance of immortality. But what is the important event in the development of living substance which is being repeated in sexual reproduction, or in its fore-runner, the conl jugation of two protista? We cannot say; and we should con-
sequently feel relieved if the whole structure of our argument turned out to be mistaken. The opposition between the ego or death instincts s and the sexual or Hfe instincts would then cease to hold and the compulsion to repeat would no longer possess the importance we have ascribed to it. Let us turn back, then, to one of the assumptions that we have already made, with the expectation that we shall be able
We
to give it a categorical denial. have drawn far-reaching conclusions from the hypothesis that all living substance is bound to die from internal causes. made this assumption thus carelessly because it does not seem to us to be an
We
tion. 1
We
assump-
are accustomed to think that such
[In what follows Freud appears
to use the
is
the fact, and
terms 'protista* and 'pro-
tozoa* indifferently to signify unicellular organisms. follows the original.] 1
[The
first
published appearance of the term.]
38
we
The
translation
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
39
are strengthened in our thought by the writings of our poets. Perhaps we have adopted the belief because there is some com-
we are to die ourselves, and first to lose in death are dearest to us, it is easier to submit to a remorselaw of nature, to the sublime 'Avdyxrj [Necessity], than to
fort in
those less
it.
If
who
a chance which might perhaps have been escaped. It may be, however, that this belief in the internal necessity of dying is only another of those illusions which we have created 'urn die Schwere des Daseins zu belief.
The notion of
1
ertragen'.'
It
is
'natural death'
certainly not a primaeval is
quite foreign to primi-
they attribute every death that occurs among them to the influence of an enemy or of an evil spirit. We must therefore turn to biology in order to test the validity of the tive races;
belief.
If we do so, we may be astonished to find how little agreethere is among biologists on the subject of natural death and in fact that the whole concept of death melts away under their hands. The fact that there is a fixed average duration of
ment
at least among the higher animals naturally argues in favour of there being such a thing as death from natural causes. But this impression is countered when we consider that certain large animals and certain gigantic arboreal growths reach a very life
advanced age and one which cannot at present be computed. According to the large conception of Wilhelm Fliess [1906], all the phenomena of life exhibited by organism and also, no doubt, their death
are linked with the completion of fixed
which express the dependence of two kinds of living substance (one male and the other female) upon the solar year. When we see, however, how easily and how extensively the periods,
influence of external forces
is able to modify the date of the appearance of vital phenomena (especially in the plant world) to precipitate them or hold them back doubts must be cast upon the rigidity of Fliess's formulas or at least upon whether
the laws laid
down by him
are the sole determining factors.
The
greatest interest attaches from our point of view to the treatment given to the subject of the duration of life and the death of organisms in the writings of Weismann (1882, 1884,
1892, etc.) It was he who introduced the division of living substance into mortal and immortal parts. The mortal part is 1
['To bear the burden of existence.' (Schiller, Die Braut von Messina,
1,8.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
40 the
body in the narrower
sense
the 'soma'
which alone
is
subject to natural death. The germ-cells, on the other hand, are potentially immortal, in so far as they are able, under certain
favourable conditions, to develop into a new individual, or, in other words, to surround themselves with a new soma. (Weis-
mann,
1884,)
What strikes us in this is the unexpected analogy with our own view, which was arrived at along such a different path. Weismann, regarding living substance morphologically, sees in one portion which is destined to die the soma, the body apart from the substance concerned with sex and inheritance and an immortal portion the germ-plasm, which is concerned with the survival of the species, with reproduction. We, on the
it
other hand, dealing not with the living substance but with the it, have been led to distinguish two kinds of
forces operating in
which seek to lead what is living to death, and which are perpetually attempting and achieving a renewal of life. This sounds like a dynamic corollary to Weismann's morphological theory. But the appearance of a significant correspondence is dissipated as soon as we discover Weismann's views on the problem of death. For he only relates the distinction between the mortal soma and the immortal germ-plasm to multicellular organisms; in unicellular organisms the individual and the reproductive cell are still one and the same (Weismann, 1882, 38). Thus he considers that unicellular organisms are potentially immortal, and that death only makes its appearance with the multicellular
instincts: those
others, the sexual instincts,
metazoa. It is true that this death of the higher organisms is a natural one, a death from internal causes; but it is not founded on any primal characteristic of living substance (Weismann, 1884, 84) and cannot be regarded as an absolute necessity with basis in the very nature of life (Weismann, 1882, 33). Death is rather a matter of expediency, a manifestation of adaptation to the external conditions of life; for, when once the cells of the its
soma and germ-plasm, an unwould become a quite pointless luxury. When this differentiation had been made in the multicellular organisms, death became possible and expedient. Since then, the soma of the higher organisms has died at fixed
body have been divided
into
limited duration of individual
life
periods for internal reasons, while the protista have remained immortal. It is not the case, on the other hand, that reproduc-
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
41
On
tion was only introduced at the same time as death. the contrary, it is a primal characteristic of living matter, like
growth (from which it originated), and life has been continuous from its first beginning upon earth. (Weismann, 1884, 84 f.) It will be seen at once that to concede in this way that higher organisms have a natural death is of very little help to us. For if death is a late acquisition of organisms, then there can be no question of there having been death instincts from the very beginning of life on this earth. Multicellular organisms may die for internal reasons, owing to defective differentiation or to imperfections in their metabolism, but the matter is of no
from the point of view of our problem. An account of the origin of death such as this is moreover far less at variance with our habitual modes of thought than the strange assumption
interest
of *death
The
instincts'.
led, so far as I
Some
which followed upon Weismann's suggestions can see, to no conclusive results in any direction. 1
discussion
who reHartmann
writers returned to the views of Goette (1883),
garded death as a direct
result of reproduction.
a (1906, 29) does not regard the appearance of a *dead body* as the criterion of death, living substance
dead portion of the
but defines death as 'the termination of individual development*. In this sense protozoa too are mortal; in their case death always coincides with reproduction, but is to some extent obscured by it, since the whole substance of the parent animal may be transmitted directly into the young offspring. Soon afterwards research was directed to the experimental
on unicellular organisms of the alleged immortality of living substance. An American biologist, Woodruff, experimenting with a ciliate infusorian, the *slipper-animalcule ,
testing
s
which reproduces by fission into two individuals, persisted until the 3029th generation (at which point he broke off the experiment), isolating one of the part-products on each occasion and placing it in fresh water. This remote descendent of the first slipper-animalcule was just as lively as its ancestor and showed no signs of ageing or degeneration. Thus, in so far as figures of this kind prove anything, the immortality of the protista seemed to be experimentally demonstrable. 2 Other experimenters arrived at different results. Maupas, i
Cf.
For
Hartmann (1906), Lipschiitz (1914) and Doflein (1919). this and what follows see Lipschiitz (1914, 26 and 52 fF.).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
42
Calkins and others, in contrast to Woodruff, found that after a
number of divisions these infusoria become weaker, diminish in size, suffer the loss of some part of their organization and eventually die, unless certain recuperative measures are certain
applied to them. If this is so, protozoa would appear to die after a phase of senescence exactly like the higher animals thus completely contradicting Weismann's assertion that death is a
of living organisms. the aggregate of these experiments two facts emerge which seem to offer us a firm footing. First: If two of the animalculae, at the moment before they show signs of senescence, are able to coalesce with each other,
late acquisition
From
(soon after which they once more 'conjugate' from growing old and become *reare saved they separate), juvenated*. Conjugation is no doubt the fore-runner of the sexual reproduction of higher creatures; it is as yet unconnected with propagation, and is limited to the mixing of the substances of the two individuals. (Weismann's 'amphimixis'.) The recuperative effects of conjugation can, however, be replaced by that
is
to
certain stimulating agents, by alterations in the composition of the fluid which provides their nourishment, by raising their
temperature or by shaking them. We are reminded of the celebrated experiment made by J. Loeb, in which, by means of certain chemical stimuli, he induced segmentation in sea-urchins' eggs a process which can normally occur only after fertilization. Secondly: It is probable nevertheless that infusoria die a natural death as a result of their own vital processes. For the
and the others is due having provided each generation with fresh nutrient fluid. If he omitted to do so, he observed the same signs of senescence as the other experimenters. He concluded that the animalculae were injured by the products of metabolism which they extruded into the surrounding fluid. He was then able to prove conclusively that it was only the products of its own metabolism which had fatal results for the particular kind of animalcule. For the same animalculae which inevitably perished if they were
contradiction between Woodruff's findings to his
crowded together in their own nutrient fluid flourished in a solution which was over-saturated with the waste products of a distantly related species. An infusorian, therefore, if it is left to itself, dies a natural death owing to its incomplete voidance of
the products of its
own metabolism.
(It
may
be that the same
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE incapacity
is
the ultimate cause of the death of
43 all
higher
animals as well.)
At this point the question may well arise in our minds whether any object whatever is served by trying to solve the problem of natural death from a study of the protozoa. The primitive organization of these creatures may conceal from our eyes important conditions which, though in fact present in them too, only become visible in higher animals where they are able to find morphological expression.
And if we abandon the morpho-
of view and adopt the dynamic one, it becomes a matter of complete indifference to us whether natural death can be shown to occur in protozoa or not. The substance which is later recognized as being immortal has not yet become separated in them from the mortal one. The instinctual forces which seek to conduct life into death may also be operating in protozoa from the first, and yet their effects may be so completely concealed by the life-preserving forces that it may be very hard to find any direct evidence of their presence. We have logical point
made by biologists allow us to assume that internal processes of this kind leading to death do occur also in protista. But even if protista turned out to be seen, moreover, that the observations
immortal in Weismann's sense, his assertion that death is a late acquisition would apply only to its manifest phenomena and would not make impossible the assumption of processes tending towards it. Thus our expectation that biology would flatly contradict the recognition of death instincts has not been fulfilled. We are at liberty to continue concerning ourselves with their possibility,
we have other reasons for doing so. The striking similarity between Weismann*s distinction of soma and germ-plasm and our separation of the death instincts from the life instincts persists and retains its significance. We may pause for a moment over this pre-eminently dualistic view of instinctual life. According to E. Hering's theory, two kinds of processes are constantly at work in living substance, operating in contrary directions, one constructive or assimilatory and the other destructive or dissimilatory. May we venture to recognize in these two directions taken by the vital processes the activity of our two instinctual impulses, the life instincts and the death instincts? There is something else, at any rate, that we cannot remain blind to. We have unwittingly if
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
44
steered our course into the
sophy. For him death
is
harbour of Schopenhauer's philo-
the 'true result
and
to that extent the
1 instinct is the embodiment of purpose of life', while the sexual the will to live. [Cf. the Appendix to Freud, 19250.] Let us make a bold attempt at another step forward. It is that the union of a number of cells into generally considered a vital association the multicellular character of organismshas become a means of prolonging their life. One cell helps to preserve the life of another, and the community of cells can survive even if individual cells have to die. We have already heard that conjugation, too, the temporary coalescence of two unicellular organisms, has a life-preserving and rejuvenating effect on both of them. Accordingly, we might attempt to apply the libido theory which has been arrived at in psycho-analysis to the mutual relationship of cells. We might suppose that the life instincts or sexual instincts which are active in each cell take the other cells as their object, that they partly, neutralize the death
is, the processes set up by them) in those cells and thus preserve their life; while the other cells do the same for them, and still others sacrifice themselves in the performance of this libidinal function. The germ-cells themselves would behave to use the phrase that we in a completely 'narcissistic* fashion
instincts (that
are accustomed to use in the theory of the neuroses to describe a whole individual who retains his libido in his ego and pays
none of it out in object-cathexes. The germ-cells require
their
libido, the activity of their life instincts, for themselves, as a reserve against their later momentous constructive activity.
(The cells of the malignant neoplasms which destroy the organism should also perhaps be described as narcissistic in this same sense: pathology is prepared to regard their germs as innate and to ascribe embryonic attributes to them.) 2 In this way the libido of our sexual instincts would coincide with the Eros of the poets and philosophers which holds all living things together. Here then is an opportunity for looking back over the slow development of our libido theory. In the first instance the analysis of the transference neuroses forced upon our notice the opposition between the 'sexual instincts', which are directed towards an object, and certain other instincts, with which we were very insufficiently acquainted and which we described 1 2
Schopenhauer (1851; Samtliche Werke, ed. Hubscher, 1938, 5, 236). [This sentence was added in 1921.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE 1
45
A
foremost place among provisionally as the 'ego-instincts'. these was necessarily given to the instincts serving the selfwhat preservation of the individual. It was impossible to say
other distinctions were to be
drawn among them. No knowledge would have been more valuable as a foundation for true psychological science than an approximate grasp of the common characteristics and possible distinctive features of the instincts. But in no region of psychology were we groping more in the dark. Everyone assumed the existence of as many instincts or 'basic instincts' as he chose, and juggled with them like the ancient Greek natural philosophers with their four elements and water. Psycho-analysis, which could not
earth, air, fire
escape making some assumption about the instincts, kept at first to the popular division of instincts typified in the phrase 'hunger arid love'. At least there was nothing arbitrary in this; and by its help the analysis of the psychoneuroses was carried forward 1 quite a distance. The concept of 'sexuality , and at the same time of the sexual instinct, had, it is true, to be extended so as to cover many things which could not be classed under the
reproductive function; and this caused no little hubbub in an austere, respectable or merely hypocritical world.
The
next step was taken
when
psycho-analysis
closer towards the psychological ego, which it know only as a repressive, censoring agency,
had
felt its first
way come to
capable of erecting
protective structures
seeing minds had,
and
reactive formations. Critical
and
far-
true, long since objected to the concept of libido being restricted to the energy of the sexual instincts directed towards an object. But they failed to explain how they it is
had arrived at their better knowledge or to derive from it anything of which analysis could make use. Advancing more cautiously, psycho-analysis observed the regularity with which libido is withdrawn from the object and directed on to the ego (the process of introversion); and, by studying the libidinal development of children in its earliest phases, came to the conclusion that the ego is the true and Original reservoir of libido, 8 x [So, for instance, in the account of this opposition given in Freud's paper on psychogenic disturbances of vision (1910i).] * [This idea was fully stated by Freud in his paper on narcissism (1914*), Section I. See, however, his later footnote, near the beginning of Chapter III of The Ego and the Id (1923), in which he corrects this
statement and describes the id as 'the great reservoir of libido'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
46
and that
it is
to objects.
only from that reservoir that libido
The ego now found
its
is
extended on
among sexual place among them.
position
and was at once given the foremost Libido which was in this way lodged in the ego was described as Narcissistic*. 1 This narcissistic libido was of course also a manifestation of the force of the sexual instinct in the analytical sense of those words, and it had necessarily to be identified with objects
the 'self-preservative instincts' whose existence had been recogfirst. Thus the original opposition between the ego-instincts and the sexual instincts proved to be
nized from the
inadequate. portion of the ego-instincts was seen to be libidinal; sexual instincts probably alongside others operated in the ego. Nevertheless we are justified in saying that the old formula
A
which lays it down that psychoneuroses are based on a conflict between ego-instincts and sexual instincts contains nothing that we need reject to-day. It is merely that the distinction between the two kinds of instinct, which was originally regarded as in some sort of way qualitative) must now be characterized differently namely as being topographical. And in particular it is still true that the transference neuroses, the essential subject of psycho-analytic study, are the result of a conflict between the ego and the libidinal cathexis of objects.
But it is all the more necessary for us to lay stress upon the libidinal character of the self-preservative instincts now that we are venturing
upon
the further step of recognizing the sexual
instinct as Eros, the preserver of all things, and of deriving the narcissistic libido of the ego from the stores of libido means
of which the
we now
by
of the
soma
are attached to one another. But find ourselves suddenly faced by another question. If cells
the self-preservative instincts too are of a libidinal nature, are there perhaps no other instincts whatever but the libidinal ones? At all events there are none other visible. But in that case we shall after all
be driven to agree with the
from the first that psycho-analysis explains
critics
who
suspected
everything by sexuality,
or with innovators like Jung who, making a hasty judgement, have used the word 'libido' to mean instinctual force in general. Must not this be so? It was not our intention at all events to produce such a result. Our argument had as its point of departure a sharp distinction between ego-instincts, which we equated with death instincts, i See my paper on narcissism (1914
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE and sexual
instincts,
which we equated with
47
life instincts.
(We
were prepared at one stage [p. 33] to include the so-called selfinstincts of the ego among the death instincts; but preservative
we subsequently
[p. 46] corrected ourselves
on
this
point and
withdrew it.) Our views have from the very first been dualistict and to-day they are even more definitely dualistic than before now that we describe the opposition as being, not between egoinstincts and sexual instincts but between life instincts and death instincts. Jung's libido theory
is
on the contrary
monistic;
the fact that he has called his one instinctual force *libido* bound to cause confusion, but need not affect us otherwise. 1
is
We
suspect that instincts other than those of self-preservation operate in the ego, and it ought to be possible for us to point to them.
Unfortunately, however, the analysis of the ego has made so little
headway that
it is
very
difficult for us to
do
so. It is possible, in-
deed, that the libidinal instincts in the ego may be linked in a 2 peculiar manner with these other ego-instincts which are still strange to us. Even before we had any clear understanding of narcissism, psycho-analysts had a suspicion that the 'ego-instincts' had libidinal components attached to them. But these are very uncertain possibilities, to which our opponents will pay very attention. The difficulty remains that psycho-analysis has not enabled us hitherto to point to any [ego-] instincts other than the libidinal ones. That, however, is no reason for our falling in with the conclusion that no others in fact exist. In the obscurity that reigns at present in the theory of the instincts, it would be unwise to reject any idea that promises to started out from the great opposition throw light on it. between the life and death instincts. Now object-love itself presents us with a second example of a similar polarity that between love (or affection) and hate (or aggressiveness). If only we could succeed in relating these two polarities to each other and in deriving one from the other! From the very first we recognized the presence of a sadistic component in the sexual little
We
As we know, it can make itself independent and can, form of a perversion, dominate an individual's entire
instinct. 3
in the 1
were added in 1921.] [The two preceding sentences * by instinctual "confluence", to tiorrow [In the first edition only: a term used by Adler [1908] '.] * This was already so in the first edition of Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality in 1905 [Standard Ed., 7, 157 ff.; I.P.I., 57, 23 ff.]. *
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
48
sexual activity. It also emerges as a predominant component instinct in one of the 'pregenital organizations', as I have named them. But how can the sadistic instinct, whose aim it is the object, be derived from Eros, the preserver of life? to injure
not plausible to suppose that this sadism is in fact a death under the influence of the narcissistic libido, has been forced away from the ego and has consequently only emerged in relation to the object? It now enters the service of the sexual function. During the oral stage of organization of the libido, the act of obtaining erotic mastery over an object coincides with that object's destruction; later, the sadistic instinct separates off, and finally, at the stage of genital primacy, it takes on, for the purposes of reproduction, the function of overpowerIs
it
instinct which,
ing the sexual object to the extent necessary for carrying out the sexual act. It might indeed be said that the sadism which has been forced out of the ego has pointed the way for the libidinal components of the sexual instinct, and that these follow after it to the object. Wherever the original sadism has undergone no mitigation or intermixture, we find the familiar ambivalence of
and hate in erotic life. 1 an assumption as this
love
If such
demand
the
that
is permissible, then we have met we should produce an example of a death
though, it is true, a displaced one. But this way of looking at things is very far from being easy to grasp and creates a positively mystical impression. It looks suspiciously as though we were trying to find a way out of a highly embarrassing situation at any price. may recall, however, that there is nothing instinct
We
an assumption of this kind. We put one forward on an earlier occasion, before there was any question of an embarrass-
new
in
ing situation. Clinical observations led us at that time to the view that masochism, the component instinct which is complementary to sadism, must be regarded as sadism that has been turned round upon the subject's own ego. 2 But there is no difference in principle between an instinct turning from an object to the ego and its turning from the ego to an object which is the new point now under discussion. Masochism, the turning round of the instinct upon the subject's own ego, would 1
[This foreshadows Freud's discussion
Chap. IV of The Ego and 2
and
See
my
the
of instinctual 'fusion* in
Id (19236).]
Three Essays (1905
'Instincts
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
49
be a return to an earlier phase of the instinct's The account that was formerly given of masochism requires emendation as being too sweeping in one be such a thing as primary masochism respect: there might in that case
history, a regression.
a possibility which I had contested at that time. 1 Let us, however, return to the self-preservative sexual instincts. The experiments upon protista have already shown us that conjugation that is, the coalescence of two individuals
which separate soon afterwards without any subsequent cellhas a strengthening and rejuvenating effect 3 upon both of them. In later generations they show no signs of degenerating and seem able to put up a longer resistance to the injurious effects of their own metabolism. This single observation may, I think, be taken as typical of the effect produced by sexual union as well. But how is it that the coalescence of two only slightly different cells can bring about this renewal of life? The experiment which replaces the conjugation of protozoa by the application of chemical or even of mechanical stimuli (cf. Lipschtitz, 1914) enables us to give what is no doubt a conclusive reply to this question. The result is brought about by the influx of fresh amounts of stimulus. This tallies well with the hypothesis that the life process of the individual leads for internal reasons to an abolition of chemical tensions, that is to say, to death, whereas union with the living substance of a division occurring
different individual increases those tensions, introducing what may be described as fresh 'vital differences* which must then
be lived off. As regards this dissimilarity there must of course be one or more optima. The dominating tendency of mental life, and perhaps of nervous life in general, is the effort to reduce, to keep constant or to remove internal tension due to 1 A considerable portion of these speculations have been anticipated by Sabina Spielrein (1912) in an instructive and interesting paper which, however, is unfortunately not entirely clear to me. She there describes the sadistic components of the sexual instinct as 'destructive'. A. Starke (1914), again, has attempted to identify the concept of libido itself with the biological concept (assumed on theoretical grounds) of an impetus towards death. See also Rank (1907). All these discussions, like that in the text, give evidence of the demand for a clarification of the [A later theory of the instincts such as has not yet been achieved. discussion of the destructive instinct by Freud himself occupies Chapter VI of Civilization and its Discontents (1930a).] * See the account quoted above, pp. 41-2, from Lipschxitz (1914).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
50
stimuli (the 'Nirvana principle', to
Low
borrow a term from Barbara
a tendency which finds expression in the * pleasure principle; and our recognition of that fact is one of our strongest reasons for believing in the existence of death [1920, 73])
instincts.
But we
still feel
our
line
of thought appreciably hampered by
we cannot
ascribe to the sexual instinct the characteristic of a compulsion to repeat which first put us on the
the fact that
track of the death instincts. The sphere of embryonic developmental processes is no doubt extremely rich in such phenomena of repetition; the two germ-cells that are involved in sexual
reproduction and their life history are themselves only repetitions of the beginnings of organic life. But the essence of the processes to which sexual life is directed is the coalescence of two cell-bodies. That alone is what guarantees the immortality of the living substance in the higher organisms. In other words, we need more information on the origin of sexual reproduction and of the sexual instincts in general. This
a problem which is calculated to daunt an outsider and which the specialists themselves have not yet been able to solve. We shall therefore give only the briefest summary of whatever seems relevant to our line of thought from among the many discordant assertions and opinions. One of these views deprives the problem of reproduction of its mysterious fascination by representing it as a part manifestais
tion of growth.
(Cf. multiplication
by
fission,
sprouting or
gemmation.) The origin of reproduction by sexually differentiated germ-cells might be pictured along sober Darwinian lines by supposing that the advantage of amphimixis, arrived at on some occasion by the chance conjugation of two protista, was
and further exploited in later development.* On this would not be anything very ancient; and the extraordinarily violent instincts whose aim it is to bring about retained
view
*sex
s
1 [Cf. p. 1 ff. The whole topic is further considered in 'The Economic Problem of Masochism* (1924<:).] * Though Weismann (1892) denies this advantage as well: 'In no case
does fertilization correspond to a rejuvenescence or renewal of life, nor occurrence necessary in order tha* life may endure: it is merely an arrangement which renders possible the intermingling of two different
is its
hereditary tendencies.' [English translation, 1893, 231.] He nevertheless believes that an intermingling of this kind leads to an increase in the variability of the organism concerned.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE sexual union
51
would be repeating something that had once and had since become established as
occurred by chance being advantageous.
The question arises here, as in the case of death [p. 43], whether we do right in ascribing to protista those characteristics alone which they actually exhibit, and whether it is correct to assume that forces and processes which become visible only in the for the first higher organisms originated in those organisms time. The view of sexuality we have just mentioned is of little be raised against it help for our purposes. The objection may that it postulates the existence of life instincts already operating in the simplest organisms; for otherwise conjugation, which works counter to the course of life and makes the task of ceasing to live more difficult, would not be retained and elaborated but would be avoided. If, therefore, we are not to abandon the them to be hypothesis of death instincts, we must suppose associated from the very first with life instincts. But it must be admitted that in that case we shall be working upon an equation with two unknown quantities. Apart from this, science has so little to tell us about the to a darkorigin of sexuality that we can liken the problem ness into which not so much as a ray of a hypothesis has penetrated. In quite a different region, it is true, we do meet with such a hypothesis; but it is of so fantastic a kind a myth rather than a scientific explanation that I should not venture to produce it here, were it not that it fulfils precisely the one condition whose fulfilment we desire. For it traces 5
the origin of
an
instinct to a need
to restore
an
earlier state
of
things.
What put
I
have in mind
into the
is,
of course, the theory which Plato
mouth of Aristophanes in the Symposium, and which
deals not only with the origin of the sexual instinct but also with the most important of its variations in relation to its object. 'The original human nature was not like the present, but different. In the first place, the sexes were originally three in number, not two as they are now; there was man;, woman, and the union of the two. . .* Everything about these primaeval .
double: they had four hands and four feet, two faces, two privy parts, and so on. Eventually Zeus decided to cut these men in two, 'like a sorb-apple which is halved for pickAfter the division had been made, 'the two parts of man,
men was
ling'.
52
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
each desiring his other half, came together, and threw their arms about one another eager to grow into one'. 1 Shall we follow the hint given us by the poet-philosopher, and venture upon the hypothesis that living substance at the time of its coming to life was torn apart into small particles, which have ever since endeavoured to reunite through the sexual instincts? that these instincts, in which the chemical affinity of inanimate matter persisted, gradually succeeded, as they developed through the kingdom of the protista, in overcoming the difficulties put in the way of that endeavour by an environment
charged with dangerous stimuli stimuli which compelled them to form a protective cortical layer? that these splintered fragments of living substance in this way attained a multicellular condition and finally transferred the instinct for reuniting, in the most highly concentrated form, to the germ-cells? But here, I think, the moment has come for breaking off. 1 Qowett's translation. Footnote added 1921 :] I have to thank Professor Hcinrich Gomperz, of Vienna, for the following discussion on the origin of the Platonic myth, which I give partly in his own words. It is to be
remarked that what is essentially the same theory is already to be found in the Upanishads. For we find the following passage in the Brihaddranyoka-upanishad, 1, 4, 3 [Max-Mullcr's translation, 2, 85 f.], where the origin of the world from the Atman (the Self or Ego) is described: *But he felt no delight. Therefore a man who is lonely feels no delight. He wished for a second. He was so large as man and wife together. He then made this his Self to fall in two, and then arose husband and wife. Therefore Yagflavalkya .said:''" We two are thus (each of us) like half a shell.*' Therefore the void which was there, is filled by the wife.* The Brihaddranyaka-upanishadis, the most ancient of all the Upanishads, and no competent authority dates it later than about the year 800 B.C. In contradiction to the prevailing opinion, I should hesitate to give an unqualified denial to the possibility of Plato's myth being derived, even if it were only indirectly, from the Indian source, since a similar possibility cannot be excluded in the case of the doctrine of transmigration. But even if a derivation of this kind (through the Pythagoreans in the first instance) were established, the significance of the coincidence between the two trains of thought would scarcely be diminished. For Plato would not have adopted a story of this kind which had somehow reached him through some oriental tradition to say nothing of giving it so important a place unless it had struck him as containing an element of truth. In a paper devoted to a systematic examination of this line of thought before the time of Plato, Ziegler (1913) traces it back to Babylonian origins.
[Freud had already alluded to Plato's Standard Ed., 7, 136; I.P.L., 57, 2.]
myth
in his Three Essays,
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
53
Not, however, without the addition of a few words of critical
may be asked whether and how far I am myself convinced of the truth of the hypotheses that have been set out answer would be that I am not convinced in these pages. myself and that I do not seek to persuade other people to believe in them. Or, more precisely, that I do not know how far I believe in them. There is no reason, as it seems to me, why the emotional factor of conviction should enter into this question reflection. It
My
at all. It is surely possible to throw oneself into a line of thought and to follow it wherever it leads out of simple scientific curiosity, or, if the reader prefers, as an advocatus diaboli, who is not on that account himself sold to the devil. I do not dispute the fact that the third step in the theory of the instincts, which I have taken here, cannot lay claim to the same degree of certainty as the two earlier ones the extension of the concept of sexuality and the hypothesis of narcissism. These two innovations were a direct translation of observation into theory and were no more open to sources of error than is inevitable in all such cases. It is
assertion of the regressive character of instincts namely on the facts of the
true that
my
also rests
upon observed material
may be, however, that I have overestimated their significance. And in any case it is impossible to pursue an idea of this kind except by repeatedly combining factual material with what is purely speculative and thus diverging widely from empirical observation. The more frequently this is done in the course of constructing a theory, the more compulsion to repeat. It
untrustworthy, as we know, must be the final result. But the degree of uncertainty is not assignable. One may have made a lucky hit or one may have gone shamefully astray. I do not think a large part is played by what is called 'intuition* in work of this kind. From what I have seen of intuition, it seems to
me
to
be the product of a kind of
intellectual impartiality.
Unfortunately, however, people are seldom impartial where ultimate things, the great problems of science and life, are concerned. Each of us is governed in such cases by deep -rooted internal prejudices, into whose hands our speculation unwittingly plays. Since we have such good grounds for being distrustour attitude towards the results of our own deliberations cannot well be other than one of cool benevolence. I hasten to
ful,
add, however, that self-criticism such as this is far from binding to any special tolerance towards dissentient opinions. It is
one
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
54
perfectly legitimate to reject remorselessly theories which are contradicted by the very first steps in the analysis of observed
while yet being aware at the same time that the validity of one's own theory is only a provisional one. We need not feel greatly disturbed in judging our speculation upon the life and death instincts by the fact that so many bewildering and obscure processes occur in it such as one instinct being driven out by another or an instinct turning from the ego to an object, and so on. This is merely due to our being obliged to operate with the scientific terms, that is to say with facts,
the figurative language, peculiar to psychology (or, more precisely, to depth psychology). We could not otherwise describe the processes in question at all, and indeed we could not have become aware of them. The deficiencies in our description would probably vanish if we were already in a position to replace the psychological terms by physiological or chemical ones. It is true that they too are only part of a figurative language; but it is one with which we have long been familiar
and which
perhaps a simpler one as well. it should be made quite clear that the uncertainty of our speculation has been greatly increased by the necessity for borrowing from the science of biology. Biology is truly a land of unlimited possibilities. We may expect it to give us the most surprising information and we cannot guess what answers it will return in a few dozen years to the questions we have put to it. They may be of a kind which will blow away the whole of our artificial structure of hypotheses. If so, it may be asked why I have embarked upon such a line of thought as the present one, and in particular why I have decided to make I cannot deny that some of the analogies, it public. Well
On
is
the other hand
and connections which deserve consideration. 1
correlations
it
contains seemed to
me to
1 1 will add a few words to clarify our terminology, which has undergone some development in the course of the present work. We came to know what the 'sexual instincts' were from their relation to the sexes
and
to the reproductive function.
We retained
this
name
after
we had
been obliged by the findings of psycho-analysis to connect them less closely with reproduction. With the hypothesis of narcissistic libido and the extension of the concept of libido to the individual cells, the sexual was transformed for us into Eros, which seeks to force together and hold together the portions of living substance. What are commonly called the sexual instincts are looked upon by us as the part of Eros instinct
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
55
directed towards objects. Our speculations have suggested that Eros operates from the beginning of life and appears as a *Jife instinct* in opposition to the *death instinct* which was brought into being by the coming to life of inorganic substance. These speculations seek to solve the riddle of life by supposing that these two instincts were struggling with each other from the very first. [Added 1921 :] It is not so easy, perhaps, to follow the transformations through which the concept of the *ego-instincts* has passed. To begin with we applied that name to all the instinctual trends (of which we had no closer knowledge) which could be distinguished from the sexual instincts directed towards an object; and we opposed the ego-instincts to the sexual instincts of which the libido is the manifestation. Subsequently we came to closer grips with the analysis of the ego and recognized that a portion of the 'ego1 instincts is also of a Hbidinal character and has taken the subject's own ego as its object. These narcissistic self^preservative instincts had thenceforward to be counted among the iibidinal sexual instincts. The opposition between the ego-instincts and the sexual instincts was transformed into one between the ego-instincts and the object-instincts, both of a Iibidinal nature. But in its place a fresh opposition appeared between the
which
is
Iibidinal (ego- and object-) instincts and others, which must be presumed to be present in the ego and which may perhaps actually be observed in the destructive instincts. speculations have transformed this opposition into one between the life instincts (Eros) and the death
Our
instincts. [
For a general account of the development of Freud's views on the the Editor's Note to 'Instinc'ts and their Vicissitudes"
instincts, see ),
Standard Ed. t 14, 111.]
VII really the case that seeking to restore an earlier state of such a universal characteristic of instincts, we need not things be surprised that so many processes take place in mental life
IF
it is
is
independently of the pleasure principle. This characteristic would be shared by all the component instincts and in their
would aim at returning once more to a particular stage in the course of development. These are matters over which the pleasure principle has as yet no control; but it does not follow
case
that any of them are necessarily opposed to it, and we have still to solve the problem of the relation of the instinctual processes of repetition to the dominance of the pleasure principle.
We
have found that one of the
earliest
and most important
functions of the mental apparatus is to bind the instinctual impulses which impinge on it, to replace the primary process prevailing in them by the secondary process and convert their freely mobile cathectic energy into a mainly quiescent (tonic) cathexis. While this transformation is taking place no
can be paid to the development of unpleasure; but does not imply the suspension of the pleasure principle. the contrary, the transformation occurs on behalf of the
attention this
On
pleasure principle; the binding is a preparatory act which introduces and assures the dominance of the pleasure principle.
Let us make a sharper distinction than we have hitherto made between function and tendency. The pleasure principle, then, is a tendency operating in the service of a function whose business it is to free the mental apparatus entirely from excitation or to keep the amount of excitation in it constant or to cannot yet decide with certainty keep it as low as possible.
We
in favour of any of these ways of putting it; but it is clear that the function thus described would be concerned with the most universal endeavour of
all living substance to the quiescence of the inorganic world. enced how the greatest pleasure attainable
namely to return have all experi-
We
sexual act,
is
by us, that of the momentary extinction of a highly The binding of an instinctual impulse
associated with a
intensified excitation.
would be a preliminary function designed to prepare the excitation for
its final
elimination in the pleasure of discharge. 56
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
57
of whether feelings of pleasure and This can be produced equally from bound and from unpleasure unbound excitatory processes. And there seems to be no doubt whatever that the unbound or primary processes give rise to far more intense feelings in both directions than the bound or secondary ones. Moreover the primary processes are the earlier in time; at the beginning of mental life there are no others, and raises the question
we may infer that if the pleasure principle had not already been operative in them it could never have been established for the thus reach what is at bottom no later ones.
We
very simple
conclusion, namely that at the beginning of mental life the struggle for pleasure was far more intense than later but not so unrestricted: it had to submit to frequent interruptions. In later
dominance of the pleasure principle is very much it itself has no more escaped the process of taming than the other instincts in general. In any case, whatever it is that causes the appearance of feelings of pleasure and unpleasure in processes of excitation must be present in the times the
more
secure, but
secondary process just as it is in the primary one. Here might be the starting-point for fresh investigations.
Our
consciousness communicates to us feelings from within not only of pleasure and unpleasure but also of a peculiar tension which in its turn can be either pleasurable or unpleasurable. Should the difference between these feelings enable us to distinguish between bound and "unbound processes of energy? or is the feeling of tension to be related to the absolute magnitude, or
perhaps to the level, of the cathexis, while the pleasure and unpleasure series indicates a change in the magnitude of the cathexis within a given unit of time? * Another striking fact is that the life instincts have so much more contact with our internal perception emerging as breakers of the peace and constantly
producing tensions whose release is felt as pleasure while the death instincts seem to do their work unobtrusively. The pleasure principle seems actually to serve the death instincts. It is true that it keeps watch upon stimuli from without, which are regarded as dangers by both kinds of instincts; but it is more especially on guard against increases of stimulation from
within, which would make the task of living more difficult. This in turn raises a host of other questions to which we can at 1 [Cf. above, p. 2. These questions had already been touched on by Freud in his 'Project', e.g. in Part I, Section 8 and Part III, Section L]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
58
no answer. We must be patient and await fresh methods and occasions of research. We must be ready, too, to abandon a path that we have followed for a time, if it seems to be leading to no good end. Only believers, who demand that science shall be a substitute for the catechism they have given up, will blame an investigator for developing or even transforming his views. We may take comfort, too, for the slow advances of our scientific knowledge in the words of the poet: present find
Was man Die
nicht erfliegen kann,
Schrift sagt, es
ist
muss
man
erhinken.
keine Siinde zu hinken. 1
1 The ['What we cannot reach flying we must reach limping. Book tells us U is no sin to limp.' The last lines of 'Die beiden Gulden', a version by Riickert of one of the Maqdmdt of al-Hariri. Freud also .
.
.
quoted these lines in a letter to FUess of Oct. 20, 1895 (Freud 1950a Letter 32).]
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS = Freud, Gesammclte Schriften (12 vols.), Vienna, 1924-34. = Freud, Gesarnmdtc W&rke (18 vols), London, from 1940.
G
QW. '
--
P
^" ,
j
TJ\
Standard Ed.) /.
PX.
Freud,
Collected Papers (5 vols.),
London, 1924-50.
= Freud, Standard Edition (24 vols.), London, from 1953. = International Psycho-Analytical Library, Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analysis,
Theoretische SehrifUn
= Freud,
London, from 1921.
Theoretischt Schriften (79/7-^5),
1931,
59
Vienna,
BIBLIOGRAPHY AND AUTHOR INDEX books and periodicals are in italics; tides of papers are in commas. Abbreviations are in accordance with the World List
[Titles of
inverted
of Scientific Periodicals (London, 1952). Further abbreviations used in this volume \vill be found in the List on page 59. Numerals in thick type refer to volumes; ordinary numerals refer to pages. The figures in round brackets at the end of each entry indicate the page or pages of this volume on which the work in question is mentioned. In the case of the Freud entries, the letters attached to the dates of publication are in accordance with the corresponding entries in the complete bibliography of Freud's writings to be included in the last volume of the Standard Edition.
For non-technical authors, and for technical authors where no work is mentioned, see the General Index.]
specific
ABLER, A.
'Der Aggressionsbetrieb im Leben und in der Neurose', Mid., No. 19, (47)
(1 908)
Forisckr.
J., and FREUD, S. (1893) See FREUD, S. (1893
BREUER,
(1940) See FREUD, S.(1940<0 DOFLEIN, F. (1919) Das Problem des Todes und der Unsterblichkeit bd dm Pflanzen und Tieren, Jena. (41) FECHNER, G. T. (1873) Einige Ideen zur Schopfungs- und Entwicktungsgeschichte der Organismen, Leipzig. (2, 4) J
FERENCZI,S. (1913) 'EntwicklungssUifendesWirklichkeitssinnes ,/n^<;. 1, 124. (35)
PsychoanaL,
[Trans.: 'Stages in the
Development of the Sense of Reality', London, 1952, Chap. VIII.]
First Contributions to Psycho-Analysis,
FUESS,
W.
FREUD,
S. (1893a)
(1906) DerAblaufdesLebens, Vienna. (39)
With BREUER, J.,'t)ber den psychischcn Mechanismus Phanomene: Vorlaufige Mittcilung', G.S., 1, 7;
hysterischer
.W., 1,81. (7) [Trans.: 'On the Psychical Mechanism of Hysterical Phenomena: Preliminary Communication', C.P., 1, 24: Standard Ed.,
2,3.] (1895rf)
G.W.,
With BREUER, 1, 75.
J.,
Stodun uber Hysterie, Vienna, G.S.,
Omitting Breuer's contributions.
(3, 19,
1;
21, 28)
[Trans.: Studies on Hysteria, Standard Ed., 2; I.P.L., 50. Including
Breuer*s contributions.]
(1900a) Die Traumdtutung, Vienna,
O, 2-3; G.W., 2-3.
(x,
8-9,
18-19, 26, 28) [Trans.:
The
Interpretation
5; Standard Ed.,
of Dreams, London and
-S.]
60
New
York,
BIBLIOGRAPHY FREUD,
61
S. (cont.)
Der Witz and seine Beziehung zum Unbewussten, Vienna. G.S., G. W., 6. (29) [Trans.: Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious, London, 1960;
(1905c) 9, 5;
Standard Ed., 8.] (1905
Vienna. G.S.,
5, 3;
G. W.,
47-8, 52)
[Trans.: Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality, London, 1949; Standard Ed., 7, 125; I.P.L., 57.] (1910:) 'Die psychogene Sehstorung in psychoanalytischer Auffassung', G.S., 5, 301; G.W., 8, 94. (45) [Trans.: 'The Psycho-Analytic View of Psychogenic Disturbance of Vision', C.P., 2, 105; Standard Ed., 11, 211.] (19116) 'Formulierungen iiber die zwei Prinzipien des psychischen Geschehens', G.S., 5, 409; G.W., 8, 230. (xi, 4) [Trans.: *Formulations on the Two Principles of Mental Functioning', C.P., 4, 13; Standard Ed., 12, 215.] (1914c) 'Zur Einfuhrung des Narzissmus', G.S., 6, 155; G.W., 10, 138. (xii, 27, 45-6) [Trans.: 'On Narcissism: Ed., 14, 69.]
an
Introduction', C.P., 4, 30; Standard
(1914^) *Weitere Ratschlage zur Technik der Psychoanalyse: II Erinnern, Wiederholen und Durcharbeiten', G.S. t 6, 109; G. W., 10, 126. (12) [Trans.:
(Further
Repeating and Working Through Recommendations on the Technique of Psycho-
'Recollecting,
Analysis, II)', C.P., 2, 366; Standard Ed., 12, 147.] (1915c) 'Triebe und Triebschicksale', G.S., 5, 443; G.W., 10, 210. (xii, 24, 48, 55) [Trans.: Instincts and their Vicissitudes', C.P., 4, 60; Standard Ed., 14, 111.] (1915*) 'Das Unbewusste', G.S.> 5, 480; G.W., 10, 264. (1, 18, 22) [Trans.: 'The Unconscious', C.P 4, 98; Standard Ed., 14, 161.] in die Psychoanalyse, Vienna. 11. (14) [Trans.: Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis, revised ed., Lon-, York, don, 1929 (A General Introduction to Psychoanalysis,
(1916-17) Vorlesungen zur Einfuhrung G.S.,
7;G.W.,
New
1935); Standard Ed., 15-16.] (19176) *Eine Kindheitserinnerung aus Dichtung und Wahrheif, G.S., 10, 357; G.W., 12, 15. (10) [Trans.: 'A Childhood Recollection from Dichtung und Wahrhdt\ C.P., 4, 357; Standard Ed., 17, 147.]
5 (1917^) 'Metapsychologische Erganzung zur Traumlehre*, G.S., t 520;.W., 10, 412. (18, 24) 'A Metapsychological Supplement to the Theory of [Trans.:
Dreams', OP., 4, 137; Standard Ed., 15, 219.] der Kriegsneurosm, Vienna. (1919 12, 321. (6, 27)
BIBLIOGRAPHY
62
FREUD,
S. (cont.)
and the War Neuroses, [Trans.: Introduction to Psycho-Analysis London and York, 1921. C.P., 5, 83; Standard Ed., 17, 207.] G.S. y 10, 369; G.W., 12, 229. (ix-x) (19194) 'Das Unheimliche', Standard Ed., 17, 219.] [Trans.: 'The Uncanny*, C.P., 4, 368;
New
of Congress (1920/) 'Erganzungen zur Traumlehre' (Abstract Address), Int. %. Psychoan., 6, 397. of Dreams', Standard Ed., [Trans.: 'Supplements to the Theory 18, 4; I.P.L., 4, x.]
(1920^) Jenseitsdes Lustprinzips, Vienna. G.S., 6, 191; G.W., 13, 3. Standard Ed., 18, 7; [Trans.: Beyond the Pleasure Principle, I.P.L., 4.]
(1921) Introduction in English to J. Varendonck's The Psycho271. (xi) logy of Day-Dreams, London; Standard Ed., 18, [German Text (part only): G.S., 11, 264; G.W., 13, 439.] (1923) Das Ich und das Es, Vienna. G.S., 6, 353; G.W., 13, 237. 13,45,43) Ego and the Id, Standard Ed,, 19, 3; I.P.L., 12.] (1923c [1922]) 'Bemerkungcn zur Theorie und Praxis der Traumdeutung', G.S., 3, 305; G.W., 13, 301. (14, 26) [Trans.: 'Remarks on the Theory and Practice of DreamInterpretation*, C?., 5, 136; Standard Ed., 19, 109.] (1924c) 'Das okonomische Problem des Masochismus', G.S., 5, 374; G.W., 13, 371. (2, 50) [Trans.: 'The Economic Problem of Masochism', C.P., 2, 255; (xi,
[Trans.: The
Standard Ed,, 19, 157.]
(1925a [1924]) 'Notiz uber den "Wunderblock" *, G.S., 6, 415; G.W., 14,3. (19,22) [Trans.: 'A Note upon the "Mystic Writing-Pad" ', C.P., 5, 175; Standard Ed., 19,227.] (1925* [1924]) 'Die Widerstande gegen die Psychoanalyse', GJS., 11, 224; G.W., 14, 99. (44) [Trans.: *The^ ^Resistance to Psycho-Analysis', C.P., 5, 163; Standard Ed., 19,213.] (1926rf) Hemmung, Symptom und Angst, Vienna. G.S. t 11, 23; G.W.,
14,113.
(7,
14,24)
[Trans.: Inhibitions^ Symptoms and Anxiety, Standard Ed., 20, 77; I.P.L., 28.] (1930a) Das Unbehagen in der Kuttur, Vienna. G.S., 12, 29; G.W., 14, 421. (49)
[Trans.: Civilization and its Discontents, 1930; Standard Ed., 21, 59.]
--
London and New York,
(1940<0 With BREUER, J., 'Zur Theorie des hysterischen Anfalls',
G.W., 17,
9. (3)
'On the Theory of
Hysterical Attacks', C.P., 5, 27; Standard Ed., 1.] (1941s) Brief an Josef Breuer, G.W., 17, 5. (3) Letter to Josef Breuer, OP., 5, 25; Standard Ed., 1.] [Trans.: (1942
A
BIBLIOGRAPHY
63
S. (cont.)
FREUD,
305. Translation of 'Psychopathische Personen auf der Buhne', which has not been published in German. (11)
Aus den Anfangen der Psychoanalyse, London. [Includes 'Entwurf einer Psychologic' (1895).] (xii, 2-3, 19-20, 22-4,
(19500)
57-8) [Trans.: The Origins of Psycho-Analysis, 1954. (Partly, including 'A Project for
in Standard Ed., 1.)] (1955c) 'Gutachten iiber die elektrische [Trans.:
a
Scientific Psychology',
Behandlung der Kriegs-
German
text unpublished. (6) Memorandum on the Electrical
neurotiker'; *
London and New York,
Treatment of
War
Neuroses', Standard Ed., 17, 211.]
FREUD,
S.,
FERENCZI,
S.,
and
others* (1919)
%ur Psychoanalyse
der Krieg$~
neurosm, Vienna. (6) [Trans.: Psycho-Analysis
and
the
War
Neuroses,
London and New
York, 1921.] GOETTE, A. (1883) Uber den Ursprung des Todes, Hamburg. (41) HARTMANN, M. (1906) Tod und Fortpflanzung, Munich. (41) JUNG, C. G. (1909) 'Die Bedeutung des Vaters fur das Schicksal dcs Einzelnen', Jb. psychoanal. psychopath. Forsch., 1, 155. (16) [Trans.: "The Significance of the Father in the Destiny of the Individual', Collected Papers on Analytical Psychology, London, 1916, 156.]
Warum wir sterben, Stuttgart. (41, 49) Low, B. (1920) Psycho-Analysis, London. (50) MARCINOWSKI, J. (1918) 'Die erotischen Quellen der Minderwertig. Sexualwiss., 4, 313. (14) keitsgefuhle', LIPSCHUTZ, A. (1914)
1
PFEIFER, S. (1919) 'Ausserungen infantil-erotischer Triebe im Spiele , Imago, 5, 243. (8) RANK, O. (1907) Der Kunstler, Vienna. (49) RICKMAN, J. (ed.) (1937) A General Selection from the Works of Sigmund Freud, London, (xii) SCHOPENHAUER, A. (1851)
't^ber die anscheinende Absichtlichkeit
im
Schicksale des Einzelnen', Parerga und Paralipomena, 1 (Sdmtliche Werke, ed. Hubscher, Leipzig, 1938, 5, 213). (44) SPIELREIN, S. (1912) 'Die Destruktion als Ursache des Werdens', Jb. psychoanaL psychopath. Forsch., 4, 465. (49) STARCKE, A. (1914) Introduction to Dutch translation of Freud's '
"Civilized"
Sexual Morality and Modern Nervous
Illness',
Leyden. (49) Psychology of Day-Dreams, London, (xi) (1882) Uber die Dauer des Lebens, Jena. (39) (1884) DberLeben und Tod, Jena. (39-41) (1892) Das fCeimplasma, Jena. (39HM), 50) [Trans.: The Germ-Plasm, London, 1893.] klass. ZIEGLER, K. (1913) 'Menschen- und Weltenwerden', Neue Jb.
VARENDONCK, J. (1921) The
WEBMANN, A.
Altert.,
31, 529. (52)
GENERAL INDEX This index includes the names of non-technical authors. It also includes the names of technical authors where no reference is made in the text to specific works. For references to specific technical works, the Bibliography should be consulted. Abraham, K., 6 n. I Abreaction, 11 Active and passive in children's play,
Child, desire to have,
KM 1,29
compulsion to repeat 8-11, 17,29-30 play of, 8-11, 17,29
Ambivalence and the opposition between the life and death instincts, 47-8 Amphimixis, 42, 50
sexual researches
47-9, 56 Compulsion to repeat as an attribute of organic 30-2, 34, 38, 50-3, 56
ality,51-2
life,
12during psycho-analysis, 17, 29-30 in children, ix, xi, 8-1 1, 1 7, 29-30 in dreams during traumatic neuroses, 7, 17, 26-7 in normal people, 15-16
conservative nature of instinct in,
ix, xi,
29-34, 36 death of, 39-43 duration of life in, 39-44 Anticathexis, 24
Fear;
15
Component instincts,
Animals
also
of,
in, ix, xi,
Ctorinda (in Gerusalenane Liberata), 16
Analogy, Plato's myth of bisexu-
(set
15
ality)
Aggressiveness, 47
Anxiety
by father,
Childhood, traumas of, xi, 26 Children (sec also Infantile sexu-
Fright;
instinctual character of, ix, xi, 14-
defined,
6-7
15,17,29-31,50-3,56 Condensation, 28 Confluence of instincts, 47
preparedness for, 7 n. 1, 25-7 Anxiety dreams, x, 7, 26 Aristophanes, 51-2 Art, 11
Atman
(in the Upanishads), 1 'Autistic thinking , xi
52
.
1
Biological
concept of death, 39-43, 49 n.
Cs. (see
Conscious system)
51-2 1
'Daemonic force , 15, 29-30 Danger, perception of, 5-6, 33, 52 Darwin, Charles, 50 Day's residues, 28, 30
'Bound*
energy (see psychical Energy, psychical, bound and
unbound) Brain, anatomy of the, 18 Braut mm Messina, Die,- 39 Breutr, 7. (see also Bibliography),
Death aim oflife is, 32-4, 3&-9, 49
20-1, 25, 28
biological
49 Calkins,
also
m 2,
56
1
54
Bisexuality,
2
Constancy, principle of (see Excitatory processes), 3, 3
Beiden Gulden, Die, 58
factors,
n.
Conscience, x Conscious system, 18-22, 28 Consciousness admissibility to, 12-13, 19 origin of, 19-21
. JV.,
Cathexis
(set
42
concept
of,
39-43,
n. 1
internal necessity of, 32, 38-41, 43 'natural', 34, 39-43
Excitatory processes)
Wtismanrfs views on, 39-43
Censorship, x, 45
64
GENERAL INDEX Death instinct (seealso Ego-instincts),
54 ix, 32-5, 38, 40-1, 43-51, equated with ego-instinct, 38, 46,
54.
in opposition to life instinct, xi, 34-5, 38, 43, 47, 54 n.
Dementia praecox, 27 Destiny, compulsion of, 15-17 Destructiveness, xi, 49 n. 1 Displacement in dreams, 28 Dream-content, manifest, 28
65
External world, 18, 20-2
Fairy tales, 14 Father
3
daughter's desire for a child by, 15 jealousy of, 10 Faust (Goethe), 36
Fear
also (see Anxiety; Fright; Phobia), 6, 7 . Fechnert G. T. (see also Bibliography), 2 4 >.
Dreams and sleep, 26-7
Ferencziy S.
6
n. 1,
(see also
26-7,
39,
58
Bibliography),
7
Fliess, Wilhelm
26
anxiety-, x, 7, as wish-fulfilments, x~xi, 7,
B.
(see also
Bibliography),
n.
censorship of, x, 45
Forgetting, 26 Fright (see also Anxiety; Fear), 6-7,
displacement in, 28 during psycho-analysis, 15, 26 hallucinatory character of, 26 'prospective* function of, x
Genital primacy, 48 Gervsalemme Liberata (Tasso), 16
punishment-, x, 26
Goethe, 10 n. 2,
30
traumatic, xi,
7, 17,
26
Dream-thoughts, latent, xi
Dream-work,
xi,
25
36
Gompcrz, H., 52 n. Guilt, sense of, 26
1
28 Hague, The, x Hallucinatory character of dreams,
Ego and
pleasure principle, 14, 17 as reservoir of libido, 44-6, 48 masochistic trends of, 7-8, 48-9 nucleus of, 13 repressive forces of, 13-14, 17 unconscious part of, 13-14 unification of, 4-5, 13, 27
Ego
ideal,
x
Ego-instincts (see also Death instinct; Self-preservation, instinct of),
38,4^7 equated with death 46,
54
instinct, 38,
n.
26 Hereditary factors, 31 Hering, E. t 43
Hunger, 45 Hypochondria, 6 Hysteria, x, 6-7 Id, the, 45 . 2 Inertia, neuronic, principle of, 3 Infantile sexuality, 1 2, 14-15, 45 Inferiority, sense of, 14-15 Instincts
also
(see
stincts;
Death
Component
.
in-
Ego-
instinct;
in opposition to sexual instinct, 35, 38, 44-9, 54 n. Eitingon, Dr. Af., ix
instincts; Life instinct; Self-preservation, instinct of; Sexual
Embryology, 20, 31, 50
45-7, 49
Energy, psychical, bound and unbound, 1-2, 20-5, 27-30, 56-7 Eros (see also Libido; Life instinct; Sexual instinct), xi, 36-7, 44, 46, 48, Excitations
54
external, 20-6, 34, 35 n. 3, 49-50,
instinct),
4-5, n. 1,
14-15,
28-38,
53-7
'conservatism' of, 30-5, 38 Instinctual character of the compulsion to repeat, ix, xi, 14-15, 17, 29-31, 50-3, 56 International Psycho-Analytical Congress, x
Introversion,
45
52,57 internal, 22-3, 28, 57 Excitatory processes, 1, 3, 17, 30,
56-7
Jealousy of father, 10 of younger child, 10
B. 1,
15
GENERAL INDEX
66 Jokes, 29
Jones, E.,6n. I Jowctt, B., 52 n. I Jung, C. G. (see also Bibliography),
46-7
Oedipus complex, 12, 14-15 Oral phase, 48 Organic injury, and neurosis, 6, 27 life, and the compulsion to repeat, 30-2, 34, 38, 53, 56
Kant,
/.,
22
Libido
48
as reservoir of, 44-6,
ego Jung's view
46-7
of,
54 n. Libido theory, 27, 44-8, 49 n. Narcissistic, 46, 48,
54 n.
1 ,
Life
aim of,
death, 32, 34, 38-9, 49 duration of, 39-44 origin of, 32-3, 35, 50 Life instinct (see also Eros; Sexual is
instinct), 34-5, 38, 43-8, 51, 54,
57 loeb,
Pain, physical, 24 Pan-sexualism, 46 Parental complex, 14m 2 Parents and children, relation between (see also Father; Mother;
Oedipus complex), 14-15 Ptpt. (see Perceptual system) PCS. (see Preconscious system)
Perceptual system, 18-19,22 Periodicity (Fliess's theory of), 39 Perversion, 47-8
Phantasies
unconscious, xi
3; 42
wishful,
Maqdmdt of al-Hariri, 58
n.
Masochism, 7-8, 48-9 Maupas, E., 41-2 Melancholia, 6, 27
Memory- traces,
18-19, 30
Mental apparatus, 3-5,
8, 18,
23-6,
28-9, 56
30
Anxiety), 36 Physical injury and neurosis, 6, 27 pain, 24 Plants, 33-4, 39 Plato, 51-2, 52 n. 1 Play of children, 8-1 1, 1 7, 29 Pleasure principle
Phobias
(see also
Mephistopheles (in Faust}, 36 Migration of birds and fishes, 3 1 Mother, child's fear of losing, 8-10
dominance of, 1-4, 11, 14, 23-9, 49-50, 56-7 over-ridden by compulsion to re-
Myths, 51, 52
peat, ix, 8-1 1, 14-18, 36-40, 56 relation to principle of constancy,
n. 1
3 Preconscious system, xi, 13, 28 Primary process (see also Energy,
Narcissism, 14, 46-8, 53^ and physical injury, 27 'of germ-cells',
Neuroses
44
(see also
rosis;
Obsessional neu-
Transference-neuroses;
Traumatic neuroses;
War
neu-
roses)
sexual aetiology of, 33-*, 45 theory of, 33-4, 44-5 Neurotics
compared
to
normal persons, 15
16 psycho-analysis
of, ix, xi,
29-30 'Nirvana principle*, 50 Object-choice, 44-9, 54 Object-instincts, 54 n. Obsessional neurosis, x
13-16,
psychical, bound and unbound), 4, 28-9, 56-7 Primitive peoples, superstitious beliefs of,
39
Principle constancy,
3
n. 2,
insusceptibility
of 2
3,
systems, 24
n.
neuronic inertia, 3 'Nirvana*, 50
n.
uncathected 2
pleasure (see Pleasure principle) reality, 4-5, 14, 29 stability (Fechner),
n.
56
2-3
Projection, 23 'Prospective* function of dreams, x Protective shield against stimuli,
21-6
GENERAL INDEX Protista,
12-15
Psycho-analytic technique, 1 Psycho-analytic theory, 46 'pan-sexualism' of, Psycho-analytic treatment of neurotics, ix, xi, 13-16, 29-
30 termination
of,
of,
1,7
Superstitious belieis, 39
sion to repeat)
Repression
and compulsion to repeat, 12-14, 26,30 and pleasure principle, 5, 14 13-14, 17, 45
36-7
Resistance
and
n.
Symposium, The, 51-2
Reaction-formation, 45 Reality-principle, 4-5, 14, 29 Regression, masochism as, 49 Repeat, compulsion to (see Compul-
of,
origin of, 50-2 Sexual intercourse, 56 Shock and traumatic neurosis, 25
Suggestion as a factor in psychoanalysis, 14n. 2, 26
Quality, 2-3, 23, 25 Quantity, 2, 2 n. 1, 25
instinctual, 5, 14,
ego, 14
of, in psycho-analytic treatment, 12-14 transference exploited by, 17
overcoming
Ruckert F., 58 n.
Tancred (in Gerusalemme Liberaia), 16 Tasso, 16 Three Wishes, The, 14 n. 3 Time, sense of, related to Pcpt.-Cs.,
22 Tragedy,
11
Transference, 12, 15-17, 30 exploited by resistance, 17 Transference neuroses (see also HysObsessional Neurosis), teria; 12-13, 44, 46 Transmigration, 52 n. 1
Trauma,
6-8, 23-7
infantile, xi,
26
Traumatic dreams,
26 17,25-9
x, xi, 7, 1 7,
neurosis, 6-8,
Sadism, 47-8, 49 39 Schopenhauer, A.
instinct, 34-5,
Sleep and dreams, 26-7 Stability, principle of (Feehner), 2-3 Stimuli, 20-6, 34, 35 n. 3, 49-50, 52, 57
12-13
Psychoneuroses (see Neuroses) Punishment-dreams, x, 26 n. I Pythagoras, 52
ego as agent
life
38, 40, 44, 47, 54 n. in opposition to ego-instincts, 35, 38, 44-7, 54 .
Simmel, E., 6
30
therapeutic aspect
67
equated with
38-44, 49-52
n. 1
Uncathected
Schiller, F.,
also
Biblio-
(see also
Energy,
(see
graphy), 44
Secondary process
psychical, bound 28, 30, 56-7
and unbound)
Self-preservation, instinct of (see also Ego-instincts), 4, 33, 45-7, 49,
54 n. Sexual aetiology of the neuroses, 33-
4,45 Sexual curiosity of children, 15 Sexual excitement and mechanical agitation, 27 Sexual instinct (see also Eros; Libido;
systems,
insuscepti-
bility to excitation of,
Unconscious ego, 13-14 mental processes, 12-13, systems, 28 Unconscious, the, 28 relation to Cs., 19, 22, tixnelessness of,
24 n. 2
18,
22
28
22
Unpleasure, 1-5, 10-11, 14-15, 18, 23-4, 32, 56-7 Fechner's
view
of,
2-4
neurotic, 'pleasure that cannot felt as such', 5 Upanishads, 52 n.
be
1
Life instinct)
and component instincts, 47-8, 49 n. 1,53 and pleasure principle, 4-5
Varendonck,J. (see also Bibliography),
GENERAL INDEX
68
Waking
life,
relation of
dreams
to,
28
War of 1914-18, War neuroses, 6 Weismann, A.
39-43
6
(see also
Wsh-nilfilment in dreams, x-xl, 26-7, 30 Woodruff, L. L. 9 41-2
Bibliography),
Zeus, 51
7.
Norton Paperbacks
PSYCHIATRY AND PSYCHOLOGY Adams James L ,
Adler, Alfred
.
).
and Social Interest.
Superiority
The Authoritarian Personality (Abr. Ed. ).
et al.
Alexander, Franz.
Psychosomatic Medicine.
Bernheim, Kay la
and
Ed
Cooperation Between the Sexes.
.
Adorno, T. W.
Conceptual Blockbusting (2d
.
Adler, Alfred.
and Richard R.J. Lewine.
F.
Schizophrenia: Symptoms, Causes,
Treatments.
Bowers, Kenneth
Hypnosis: For the Seriously Curious.
S_.
Bruner, Jerome S,
Bruner, Jerome S.
Beyond the Information Given. The Relevance of Education.
Burgess Linda Cannon ,
Cannon, Walter B. Cannon, Walter B.
Damon, William
.
The A rt of Adoption.
.
The Way of an Investigator. The Wisdom of the Body. Social
and Personality
Development: Essays on the
Growth of the Child. Damon William. Social and Personality Development: ,
Infancy Through
Adolescence.
Daniels, Pamela and Kathy Parenthood
Donaldson, Margaret.
Children's Minds.
Erikson, Erik
H.
Erikson Erik
H
Erikson, Erik
H.
Dimensions of a
H. Erik H.
Gandhi's Truth.
,
.
Erikson, Erik Erikson,
Erikson Erik
H
Erikson, Erik
H. H.
,
Erikson, Erik Fancher,
Fancher,
Sooner or Later: The Timing of
Wemgarten.
m Adult Lives.
.
Raymond Raymond
Adulthood.
Childhood and Society.
Identity: Youth
New Identity. and Crisis.
and the Life Cycle. Insight and Responsibility. Identity
Young
Man Luther.
E.
Pioneers of Psychology.
E.
Psychoanalytic Psychology: The Development of
Freud's Thought.
Finch, Stuart
Freud, Anna.
M.
Fundamentals of Child Psychiatry.
Psychoanalysis for Teachers
and Parents.
Freud, Sigmund.
An Autobiographical Study.
Freud Sigmund
Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
,
.
and its
Freud, Sigmund.
Civilization
Freud Sigmund
The Ego and the
,
.
Freud, Sigmund.
Discontents.
Id.
Five Lectures on Psycho- Analysis.
Freud, Sigmund.
The Future of an
Freud, Sigmund.
Group Psychology and the Analysis
Illusion.
of the Ego.
Symptoms and Anxiety.
Freud, Sigmund.
Inhibitions,
Freud, Sigmund.
Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis.
and Their Relation
to the
Unconscious.
Freud, Sigmund.
Jokes
Freud, Sigmund.
Leonardo da Vinci
and a Memory of His
Freud, Sigmund.
New Introductory
Lectures on Psychoanalysis.
Freud, Sigmund. Freud, Sigmund.
On Dreams. On the History
Freud, Sigmund.
An
Freud, Sigmund.
The Psychopathology of Everyday The Question of Lay Analysis.
Freud, Sigmund.
Childhood.
of the Psycho-Analytic Movement.
Outline of Psycho- Analysis (Rev. Ed.). Life.
Totem and Taboo, H. Jacquelynne E. Parsons, Paula B. Johnson, Diane N. Ruble and Gail L. Zellmann. Women and Sex Roles: A Social Psychological Perspective.
Freud, Sigmund. Frieze, Irene
,
Uncommon Therapy: The
Haley, Jay. Erickson,
Psychiatric Techniques of Milton B.
M.D.
Hendin, David.
Death as a Fact of Life.
Suicide in America. Hendin, Herbert. Are You Considering Psychoanalysts? Horney, Karen (Ed.).
Homey, Karen.
Feminine Psychology.
Horney, Karen. Horney, Karen.
Neurosis
Horney, Karen. Horney, Karen. Horney, Karen.
New
and Human Growth.
The Neurotic Personality of Our Time.
Ways in Psychoanalysis. Our Inner Conflicts. Self-Analysis.
Inhelder, Barbel,
James, William.
and Jean Piagec. Talks
Hamlet and Oedipus
Jones, Ernest.
The Early Growth ofLogic
m the Child.
to Teachers. .
The Growth of the Child: Reflections on Human Development. Twelve to Sixteen. Early Adolescence. Kagan, Jerome, and Robet Coles (Eds.). Katchadourian Herant Human Sexuality: Sense and Nonsense.
Kagan, Jerome.
.
,
George A. A Theory of Personality. Klein, Melanie, and Joan Riviere. Love, Hate and Reparation. Kelly,
Komarovsky, Mirra.
A Study of College Youth, Ghosts in the Mind's Machine: How We Create
Dilemmas of Masculinity :
Kosslyn, Stephen Michael. Pictures in our Brains.
Lacan, Jacques.
Ecrits.
Lacan Jacques
The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psycho-Analysis
,
.
.
William J. Creating a Good Relationship. Maternal Overprotection. Levy, David M. Lifton, Robert Jay. Thought Reform and the Lederer,
Psychology ofTotalism.
Light, Donald.
Lunde, Donald
Becoming Psychiatrists: The Professional Transformation of Self. T.
Murder and Madness
.
Mind and Body: Psychology of Emotion and Stress. Psychology and the Human Dilemma,
Mandler, George.
May, Rollo. Meehl Paul E ,
.
Psychodiagnosis: Selected Papers.
Piaget, Jean.
The Child's Conception of Number.
Piaget Jean
Genetic Eptstemology.
,
.
Piaget, Jean.
Dreams and Imitation
Play,
Piaget, Jean,
and Barbel Inhelder.
Piaget, Jean,
and Barbel Inhelder.
in Childhood.
The Child's Conception of Space. The Origin of the Idea of Chance in Children.
and Alina Szeminska.
Piaget, Jean, Barbel Inhelder,
The Child's Conception of
Geometry.
and Milton B. Singer.
Piers, Gerhart,
Piers ,
Maria
W. (Ed
.
Play
Truth
Will Therapy. Rank, Otto. Ruesch J urgen and Gregory Bateson ,
Shame and GUI It.
and Development.
Ann James Premack. and Reality.
Premack, David and
Rank, Otto.
).
,
.
The
Mind of an Ape.
Communication: The Social Matrix
of Psychiatry.
Schwartz, Barry (Ed Schwartz, Barry and
.
).
Psychology of Learning: Readings in Behavior Theory.
Hugh
Lacey,
Behaviorism, Science,
and Human Nature: An
Introduction to Conditioning.
Sullivan,
Sullivan,
Harry Stack. Harry Stack.
Sullivan, Harry Stack. Sullivan, Harry Stack. Sullivan,
Harry Stack.
van den Berg Walter,
W.
,
J.
H
.
Grey.
Watson, John B.
Clinical Studies in Psychiatry. Conceptions of Modem Psychiatry.
The Interpersonal Theory of Psychiatry. The Psychiatric Interview. Schizophrenia as
a Human
Process.
The Changing Nature of Man. The Living Brain. Behaviorism.
Wheelis, Allen.
The Quest for
Williams, Juanita
H
Identity.
Psychology of Women: Behavior in a Biosocial Context
.
(2d Ed.).
Williams, Juanita H. (Ed. ). Zilboorg, Gregory.
A
Psychology of Women: Selected Readings.
History of Medical Psychology.
Selected Liveright Paperbacks
PSYCHIATRY AND PSYCHOLOGY Jones, Ernest.
On the Nightmare.
Kohler, Wolfgang.
Dynamics in
Kohler, Wolfgang.
Gestalt Psychology.
Kohler, Wolfgang
The Mentality of Apes. The Place of Value in a World of Fact.
.
Kohler, Wolfgang. Kohler, Wolfgang. Luria, Alexander R.
Stekel ,
Wilhelm
Stekel,
Wilhelm.
Relation to Sex.
.
Psychology.
The Selected Papers of Wolfgang Kohler. The Nature of Human Conflicts. Impotence in the Male.
Sexual Aberrations: The Phenomena of Fetishism in
SlOMl'NO
FREUD
Beyond the Pleasure Principle Translated and edited by James Strachey Introduction and notes by Gregory Zilboorg
PUBLIC LIBRARY
HH^
m^-w ocnrpr
T tw***^
Tfwr 132 F89be
Freud, Signwnd, 1856-1939. en Beyond the pleasure
principle
/
Beyond the Pleasure Principle
By
SIGMUND FREUD
AN AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL STUDY
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE CIVILIZATION
AND
ITS
DISCONTENTS
THE COMPLETE INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS THE EGO AND THE FIVE LECTURES
ID
ON PSYCHOANALYSIS
THE FUTURE OF AN ILLUSION GROUP PSYCHOLOGY AND THE ANALYSIS OF THE EGO INHIBITIONS,
SYMPTOMS AND ANXIETY
INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS JOKES AND THEIR RELATION TO THE UNCONSCIOUS
LEONARDO DA VINCI AND A MEMORY OF HIS CHILDHOOD
NEW INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS ON DREAMS
ON THE HISTORY OF THE PSYCHOANALYTIC MOVEMENT AN OUTLINE OF PSYCHOANALYSIS
THE PSYCHOPATHALOGY OF EVERYDAY LIFE
THE QUESTION OF LAY ANALYSIS
TOTEM AND TABOO
THE STANDARD EDITION OF THE COMPLETE PSYCHOLOGICAL WORKS OF SIGMUND FREUD 24 VOLUMES
Beyond Pleasure
the
Principle
SIGMUND FREUD
by
JAMES STRACHEY
Introduction by
GREGORY ZILBOORG
W.W-NORTON&COMPANY NEW YORK -LONDON
W
W. Norton
& Company, Inc.,
500 Fifth Avenue,
New York,
W
W. Norton &
N.Y. 10110 Company Ltd. 37 Great Russell
London
Street,
WC1B3NU
1961 BY JAMES STRACHBY
COPYRIGHT
Reprinted by arrangement with Liveright Publishing Corporation
1959 by Bantam Books. of the publisher. Reprinted by permission
Introduction Copyright
ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Published simultaneously in Canada by
Penguin Books Canada Ltd, 2801 John Street, Markham, Ontario L3R 1B4.
W. W. Norton
& Company,
Inc.
is
also the publisher
of the
works of Erik H. Erikson, Otto Fenichel, Karen Homey, Harry Stack Sullivan,
and The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Works of Sigmund Freud, Data library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Freud, Sigmund, 1856-1939
Beyond the pleasure
principle.
Translation of Jenseits des Lust-Prinzips.
Reprint of the ed. published by Liveright,
New York.
Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Pleasure. 2. Psychoanalysis.
BF173.F65
1975
150.19'52
I.
Title.
74-22476
Printed in the United States of America
67890 ISBN 0-313-007t1-3
CONTENTS Introduction
Editor's
Note
Beyond the Pleasure Principle
vu xvii
1
List of Abbreviations
59
Bibliography and Author Index
60
General Index
64
INTRODUCTION by Gregory Zilboorg, M.D.
A
QUESTION which seems natural and almost unavoidable What can one say about a book, and a little one at
arises:
which is forty years old, and which is supposedly not one of the most impressive or "spectacular" bits of Freud's many writings? The question presupposes the implied answer that that,
even in our swift-moving world is a long time, that the book in question is therefore more or less superannuated and deserves but a respectful historical glance before we put forty years
it
back on the shelf to gather more dust. It is obvious that the above is a rhetorical way of saying
that forty years after
its
appearance and twenty years after
Beyond the Pleasure Principle still deserves considerable attention, and that the reader would do well if he reads it with studious curiosity. Of recent years we have Freud's death,
become so accustomed
to the atmosphere of controversy which surrounds psychoanalysis and Freud that we have almost lost our capacity to pick up a book on psychoanalysis
without wanting to know in advance whether the book is for or against it, or, if it is for it, whether it is for Freud or for Jung, or, Freudian.
if it is
If
Freudian, whether
we dared
have no
difficulty in
analysis
is
it is
orthodox or neo-
to be frank with ourselves,
we would
admitting that our judgment of psychoactually fragmentary and not too profound. We
could also admit that some sort of partisanship possesses us, and that therefore we are preoccupied with "taking sides" long before
we
psychoanalysis
get acquainted with the very first elements of the subject.
and the many-sidedness of
It is because of the various prejudices which have inculcated themselves into psychoanalytical and nonpsychoanalytical circles that it is pertinent to invite both the initiated and
the uninitiated reader to suspend his fragmentary judgment
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
viii
and re-read afresh the
for a short while
little
book
that
is
here offered, and acquaint or re-acquaint himself with the sound of Freud's written voice, with his way of saying things, and then with the substance of what he has to say.
An
introduction
what
is
not supposed to explain in advance
said in the book;
is
Rather,
it is
meant
still less is it
to interpret
it.
intended to clarify some shadows and point to which will possibly set the book in a
certain lights
proper
perspective.
Bearing
this in
mind,
let us first recall that
Freud wrote
Beyond the Pleasure Principle when he was sixty-four years old a mature age indeed-and at a time when psychoanalysis had already achieved considerable popularity, even though was
still
possible to assess the degree of
number of enemies isms of
Freud
its
it
it
importance by the had. The tone of the book, the manner-
still
combatting his opponents rather than
trying to instruct his proponents. his life,
in
almost controversial;
style are vigorous, poignant,
seems was
it
its
Freud preserved
this
Almost
to the last years of
combative vigor of writing, and
Beyond the Pleasure Principle
this
aspect of style stands
out markedly, particularly when he emphasizes his claim that he is a partisan of no special philosophy and that he is indifferent as to whether
what he has
to say does or does
not
fit
any
known philosophy. This claim for independence personality casts
this
and of
aspersion
on
all his
is
writings,
characteristic of Freud's
but
I
believe
it
in
no way
his originality or his genius, if I say that
declaratory independence should not be taken too
ously.
No one, and particularly no genius,
is
seri-
really free of the
ideological inheritance which he carries within himself as a child of a given generation. He may not be aware of it, of
but Freud would have been the last man in the world equate not being aware of something with its nonexistence. For it was of course Freud himself who discovered and uncourse, to
folded before us the staggering richness and many things of which we are not aware.
power within us
of so
It is of some interest in this connection to recall that Freud denied ever having been acquainted with the writings of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche before he formulated of
many
his ideas. It was beyond any doubt an honest denial Yet it is a matter of record that Hitschmann, one of the earliest ad-
INTRODUCTION
ix
herents of Freud, read a paper in Freud's house as early as 1905 (Freud being present, of course) on the very subject of Nietzsche's ideas as
There
is
no doubt
compared with some of Freud's theories. that, whether or not Freud ever read
The Genealogy
Nietzsche's
of Morals, his was the tempera-
ment and the aspiration of a proud iconoclast who, to paraphrase an old saying of Maxim Gorki's, was born to soar and not to crawl, and for whom soaring accomplishment was not a pleasure in itself but a temporary level strove to attain ever-greater heights.
from which he
If we cast but a glance at the rough sketch of a general psychology which we find in Freud's letters to Fliess, we cannot help but be struck by the depth, diapason and im-
mense horizons which Freud envisaged
as the
culmination
of his system. And these letters, we must remember, written before 1900, that is to say, before the first book
were
(The
Interpretation of Dreams] which really launched psychoanalysis into the stormy waters of a world which never was
able to approach the study of the psychology of man without prejudice and considerable animosity and controversy be it religious, scientific, or plain pedestrian. The ambition with
which Freud's mind was
fired
from the very
outset,
and
his
particular goal of discovering, or uncovering, the real nature of man's mind, predestined him as a thinker and a man to
become a storm center
He
was
for years to come.
also a daring paradox, giving the
self-contradiction, of inconsistency,
semblance of
and of all-solidity. Freud's
apparent readiness to change his mind added a great number of dissenters
and detractors
as
if
the scientist
who
has the
courage to change his mind about some of his own ideas has gained a point against himself. The great majority of people do confuse stubbornness for consistency, and rigidity of scientific ideas for
soundness of position.
At any 'rate, Beyond the Pleasure Principle is one of the first great landmarks in Freud's ways of "changing his mind." put these words in quotes to cast at least a little doubt on the traditional attitude that Freud did change his mind in I
this instance.
He
did not.
What Freud
did here was to add a
path or two, a little curve or fork, in the tortuous intellectual road which he followed with dogged faith in his own intellectual independence.
The
additions or added trends of thought
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
x
cannot be fully grasped and even less understood unless one the inner psychological atmosphere in always bears in mind
which Freud worked
in order to express his ideas.
was always terse, straightforward, clear and challengingly frank; but the same thing cannot be said about the emotional climate of his thought. First of all, His literary
style
Freud never gave up his belief-I am tempted to say faiththat the parallel he drew between Fechner's ideas in physics his own in human psychology was not really a parallel but an actual proof that his concept of the mental apparatus and its energy was actually the same as Helmholtz' and
and
Fechner's ideas about physical energy. To this faith he clung to the last, expressing the hope that some day the whole comof human reactions and relations could be reduced plexity
some as yet undiscovered physico-chemical reactions. In other words, Freud remained an organidst throughout his scientific life. But genius and living paradox that he was, to
Freud was rejected by the materialists (conservative
as well
Marxian) because of his alleged mysticism; and he was rejected by the idealists and religious thinkers because he was as
thought to be a materialist.
The
contradictions into
which Freud's detractors thus
stumbled remained unnoticed as a rule, but Freud was of course aware of them and saw in eral resistance,
Yet
it
was not only
them merely that.
To
"mystic," was an expression of opprobrium,
Freud who stated that by
saints
epithet,
and yet
was
it
were saved from severe neuroses
their sainthood, their faith;
tion St. Francis of Assisi.
a sign of gen-
Freud the
he mentioned in
He who studies
this
connec-
the lives of the saints
would not
easily issue to all of them, and without reservation, a certificate of psychological health. They were saints because neuthey were able to stand the pressure of their
respective
roses rather than because they did not suffer lives
of
St.
from them.
The
Ignatius Loyola, or San Francisco Xavier, or St.
Augustine for that matter, offer ample confirmation of
my
viewpoint.
As one studies Freud, one can develop the strong suspicion he was more attracted by many mystics than by physicochemical hypotheses, and that he struggled with all the might that
of his great
of the
mind
against openly giving in to the attraction
mystical aspects of
human
life.
In other words, the
man
INTRODUCTION
xi
than twenty years after he wrote Beyond the Pleasure the man who Principle wrote his Moses and Monotheism,
who
less
five years before Beyond the Pleasure Principle wrote the article on Michelangelo's Moses, seems throughout this
some
with the greatness of span of time to have been preoccupied human intuitions and the universality of human strivings not of life. And only to solve but to participate in the mysteries it is perhaps because of this inclination that Freud gave signs of "protesting too much." (Perhaps too this is one of the reasons first
why
his article
anonymously;
it
on Michelangelo's Moses appeared
was only much
later that
it
was admitted
that Freud, the Editor-in-chief of the Zeitschrift fur Psycho-
analyse, was the real author of the article.)
While the complex question of Freud's intellectual strugwith his own ideas is far from solved, there is little doubt
gles
that the aggressive, trenchant, emphatic tone of his writings,
which seem
to be full of conviction
and devoid of doubt, does
not fully convey Freud's struggle with his own ideas, which at times must have reached heroic dimensions. It is because of Freud's aggressive candor, it seems to me, that his earliest followers seem more to have stood in awe, listening to his pronouncements, than actually to have assimilated his
thought like true disciples, ready to ask friendly critical questions in order to deepen and broaden the understanding of their master's thought.
The
very few of his followers
who
were endowed with truly original minds and truly ambitious soon broke with Freud; Jung is perspicacity and intuition one of the few one can cite in this respect. The majority be-
came
either surly, hostile enemies
ponentsor admiring,
rather than scientific opfollowers rather than
enthusiastic
scientific collaborators. It is
therefore of particular interest to note that there was
hardly a psychoanalyst outside Freud himself who ever made an original contribution to the theory and practice of psychothis is particularly true of the time when Freud analysis-f
wrote his Beyond the Pleasure Principle. The one exception one can cite with certainty was Karl Abraham, who made an inestimable contribution to the clinical understanding of and of depression, a contribution which
character formation
was spontaneously and "painlessly" incorporated into the
body of psychoanalytic knowledge some
five years
before the
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
xii
the Pleasure Principle. But even in appearance of Beyond the case of Abraham things were not all clarity and sunshine;
many
of his colleagues were not very kindly disposed to the as Jones has written, said that he
man, and Freud himself, was suspicious of
his
"Prussian
mind"-Abraham being
a
Berliner.
All of the above amounts to saying that the constant and "true" followers of Freud were not very original minds; they
were not mediocrities, but for some reason they would not or perhaps could not "speak up" until Freud spoke first. It because of this that Beyond the Pleasure Principle partly in the history of the development acquired such significance of Freudian psychoanalysis. It acquired the reputation of a is
landmark in how Freud changed his mind and how daring he was in doing so. As a matter of cold fact, the book is an important contribution, a thrust forward in the growth of Freudian thought; but if one reads it carefully one will easily see that
Freud did not change
his
mind, and that Beyond the
Pleasure Principle did not overthrow any old psychoanalytic regime nor did it establish any new one. It was not even a small village revolution;
it
was and
is
a landmark of further
development and a consolidation of the older pathways. Beyond the Pleasure Principle is what it says; it goes a little further beyond, but
This writer
lays
it
does not abandon whatever preceded it. to an understanding of Freud's
no claim
writing better than anyone's else who approaches Freud with the earnestness he deserves and the tolerance which is imperative,
even
say "even
now some twenty
now"
years after Freud's death. I
for the
following reason; at the beginning Freud had to suffer from the many whose quick and ever
misjudgment of him multiplied by thousands the number of his antagonists in every walk of the world's intellectual life. of Today, with the full text of Freud at the
alert
disposal every curious reader of the world, everybody claims Freud as his own, because everybody just as alertly is ready to interpret Freud in his own way. Thus a plethora of "schools" has mush-
roomed
in the psychological literature, each claiming
philosophical, moral and scientific right to consider forts et origo,
in
its
own
preters
and
its
own
Freud
its its
exclusive right to understand Freud
exclusively correct way. This splintering of interand misinterpreters of Freud is not unnatural, of
INTRODUCTION
xiii
course; the process will undoubtedly continue for some time before the real Freud will stand out in the history of our intellectual
development
we may look calmly and Since
it is
him
for
into
whom
not in anyone's power to slow down or to accelit cannot be the ambition
erate the salutary passage of time, of this writer to attempt to do so.
mate
whom and
as a figure at
objectively.
But
this
much
it is
legiti-
to essay to do: to point out that the vigor of
Freud's thought, stimulating as it has always been and is, is frequently obscured by his at times too hasty terminological innovations. Not that one objects to such innovations, or that
one ought to insist on semantic hair-splitting; but Freud, whose clarity of thought and daring intellectual improvisawere always impressive and enlightening, suffered not infrequently from a certain confusion, at first unnoticeable tions
at length presenting an impediment to easy or clear understanding. Beyond the Pleasure Principle serves as an
but
excellent example. First, there is the tendency which imperceptibly grew into assertive tradition that, having gone beyond the pleasure principle,
he abandoned that principle. This, as
I
have
al-
ready said, is not true. The reader, bearing this in mind, cannot fail but see it once the text is perused without prejudice,
without the unwitting psychological twist which makes him read Beyond the Pleasure Principle and assume that the
We
might as well state pleasure principle was left behind. right here that the assiduous and faithful translators of Freud, in bringing before the English-speaking readers Freud's ver-
sion of the pleasure-pain theory, did not help matters
when
they coined a neologism, "unpleasure." This awkward term is supposed to render somewhat accurately the German term Unlust. It is not an exactly successful rendition (except etymoiogically, perhaps). The feeling of pain, of discomfort, of that disagreeable malaise which Freud has in mind is not
perceived as un-pleasure, for what
we
feel in this
malaise
we
and not negatively as a lack of something else. This point need not be labored; it is brought out here merely to illustrate how difficult it is to tell the reader what a given feel positively,
writer wants to say in a language his own, but not yours.
Now
let
allegedly
us ask ourselves what appears to be new and not as old in Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
abandoned
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
xiv
The
concept of "compulsive repetition" or "repetition compulsion." Some still quarrel with this concept, some no
The arguments for and against it are of no parimportance here. What is important is that new con-
longer do. ticular
newly formulated, require greater clarity of definition. Freud discovered the repetitiveness of certain patterns of human behavior and the inevitability or, if you wish, the
cepts,
inescapable nature of this repetitiveness.
phenomenon
And
he called
this
"repetition compulsion" or "compulsive repe-
tition."
We
have become accustomed to the term "compulsion" of compulsion neuroses in other words, a
when we speak
neurosis which makes the sufferer therefrom aware that he is
"compelled by something" to make this or that gesture or or that turn or else he feels uncomfortable, at
this
times plainly anxious. It detail to observe that the
uneasy, hardly necessary to go into more compulsive element of which Freud is
speaks when he speaks of compulsive repetition is something that the individual is not conscious of, that the
element in at
all,
this
concept
is
or not necessarily,
compulsive something which is not neurotic and that it is just as or no more
compulsive than breathing or the changing of the seasons. To use the term "compulsive" here connotes something that it is not and implies things which are not necessarily there~a rather strange semantic fuzziness on the part of that uniquely clear-minded thinker. Such unclarities are strewn throughout of Freud's writings and translations, and if they do not always confuse the casual reader or even the student, one
many
would do well in being forewarned and therefore in reading and studying Freud with considerable caution and prudence. One more example: the second major innovation which Freud introduced into psychoanalytic thinking was the concept of the death instinct. Now we have become accustomed,
Freud emphasized the role of instincts in life of man, to consider an a drive, an impulsive or perpetually compelling asto piration gratify a need. In German, Freud uses the words Trieb and Triebhaft, which mean instinct, instinctual drive,
particularly since
the conscious and unconscious instinct
a sense of being driven toward a certain even though not always comprehended goal. Under the circumstances, the term "death instinct" ought to mean an a drive to aspiration,
INTRODUCTION
xv
be dead. Perhaps Freud was right, even though neither the nor the theologian would find it possible to agree biologist with him. Let us assume that Freud was right; he certainly did not prove his case, because there is nothing instinctual
about dying, even though the end is inevitable. Here again we find a strange semantic or terminological confusion, a tendency to use terms which are familiar to us in the psychoanalytic glossaries,
somewhat confusing
The above
but which
in certain contexts
become
labels.
considerations
may
serve as a warning that
it is
not easy to understand great minds even when they appear to speak simply, or perhaps especially when their language familiar. appears simple and the terminology
EDITOR'S NOTE JENSEITS DES LUSTPRINZIPS (a)
GERMAN
1920
EDITIONS:
Leipzig,
Vienna and Zurich: Interaationaler Psycho-
analytischer Verlag. Pp. 60.
1921
2nd
1923
3rd ed.
1925
(?.,
1
93 1
Same publishers. Pp. 64. Same publishers. Pp. 94.
6, 191-257.
Theoretische Schriften,
1940
(b]
ed.
1
78-247.
G.W., 13,3-69.
ENGLISH TRANSLATIONS: Beyond
1922
the Pleasure
Principle
London and Vienna: Press. Pp. viii
-f-
International Psycho-Analytical 90. (Tr. C. J. M. Hubback; Pref.
Ernest Jones.)
1924 1942
New York: Boni and Liveright. London: Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analy(Re-issue of above.) Publishers. Pp. vi 97. (Tr. J. Strachey.) S.R, 18, 3-64. (Modified version of above.) sis.
1950 1955
+
Same
Freud made a number of additions in the second edition, but subsequent alterations were negligible. The present translation is a corrected reprint of the Standard Edition version.
As is shown by his correspondence, Freud had begun working on a first draft of Beyond the Pleasure Principle in March, 1919, and he reported the draft as finished in the following May. During the same month he was completing his paper on 'The Uncanny* (1919A), which includes a paragraph setting out much of the gist of the present work in a few sentences. In this paragraph he refers to the 'compulsion to repeat' as a pheno-
menon
exhibited in the behaviour of children
and in psychohe suggests that this compulsion is something derived from the most intimate nature of the instincts; analytic treatment;
and he
declares that
it is
powerful enough to disregard the xvii
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
xviii
There is, however, no allusion to the 'death pleasure principle. He adds that he has already completed a detailed
instincts'.
The paper on 'The Uncanny' consummary was published in the autumn of 1919.
the subject. exposition of taining this
But Freud held back Beyond the Pleasure Principle for another In the early part of 1920 he was once more at work on it,
year.
and now, for the
first
time apparently, there
a reference to
is
the 'death instincts' in a letter to Eitingon of February 20.
He
May and June and it was finally completed by the middle ofJuly, 920. On September 9, he gave was
still
revising the
work in
1
an address at
to the International
The Hague, with
the
title
Psycho-Analytical Congress 'Supplements to the Theory of
Dreams' (Ergsnzungen zur Traumkhre), in which he announced the approaching publication of the book; it was issued early in December. An 'author's abstract' of the address appeared in
of this was pub%. PyckoanaL, 6 (1920), 397-8. (A translation
Int.
lished in Int. J. Psycho- Anal^ 1, 354.) It does not
that this abstract
was in
interest to reprint
it
fact
by Freud
here (in a
'Supplements
to the
new
seem
himself, but
it
certain
may
be of
translation).
Theory of Dreams'
remarks with three points touching upon the theory of dreams. The first two of these were concerned with the thesis that dreams are wish-fulfilments and
The speaker dealt in
his brief
brought forward some necessary modifications of it.
The
third
point related to material which brought complete confirmation of his rejection of the alleged "prospective" purposes of dreams, 1
"The speaker explained
that, alongside the familiar wishful
dreams and the anxiety dreams which could easily be included in the theory, there were grounds for recognizing the existence of a third category, to which he gave the name of "punishment dreams". If we took into account the justifiable assumption of the existence of a special self-observing and critical agency in the ego (the ego ideal, the censor, conscience), these punish-
ment dreams,
too, should
be subsumed under the theory of
would represent the fulfilment of a critical agency. Such dreams, he said,
wish-fulfilment; for they
wish on the part of this
had approximately the same relation to ordinary wishful dreams 1
[See The Interpretation of Dreams, 1900a,
506-7
n.]
VI
(I),
Standard Ed., 5,
EDITOR'S NOTE aft action formation,
had
to those
of hysteria.
'Another class of dreams, however, seemed to the speaker to more serious exception to the rule that dreams are present a wish-fulfilments.
These were the so-called "traumatic" dreams.
in patients suffering from accidents, but they also occur during psycho-analyses of neurotics and bring back to
They occur
them forgotten traumas of childhood. In connection with the problem of fitting these dreams into the theory of wish-fulfilment, the speaker referred to a work shortly to be published title of Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
under the
'The third point of the speaker's communication related to
an investigation that had not yet been published, by Dr. Varendonck of Ghent. This author had succeeded in bringing under his conscious observation the tasies
on an extensive
production of unconscious phana half-sleeping state a process
scale in
which he described as
"autistic thinking". It
enquiry that looking ahead at the
this
day, preparing attempts at solutions
wholly within the range of
appeared from of the next
possibilities
and adaptations,
etc.,
this preconscious activity,
lay
which
dream-thoughts, and, as the speaker had x always maintained, had nothing to do with the dream-work.'
also created latent
In the
series
of Freud's metapsychological writings, Beyond may be regarded as introducing the final
the Pleasure Principle
He had already drawn attention to the 'compulsion to repeat* as a clinical phenomenon, but here he attributes to it the characteristics of an instinct; here too for the phase of his views.
first
time he brings forward the
and the death
instincts
new
which found
Dichotomy its fiill
between Eros
elaboration in The
Ego and the Id (1923i). In Beyond the Pleasure Principle, too, we can see signs of the new picture of the anatomical structure of the mind which was to dominate all Freud's later writings. Finally, the
problem of destructiveness, which played an ever in his theoretical works, makes its first
more prominent part
The
explicit appearance.
derivation of various elements in the
present discussion from his earfier metapsychological
such as 'The 1
Two
Cf. Freud's
own
IWlb, Standard Ed.,
Principles of
works-
Mental Functioning' (19116),
preface to this book of Varendonck's (Freud,
U
t
271).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
xx 'Narcissism'
(19150) is
(191-k)
and
will be obvious.
'Instincts
But what
the closeness with which
present
work follow the
(19500), drafted
is
and
their
Vicissitudes'
particularly remarkable
some of the
earlier sections of the
a Scientific 'Project for Psychology'
by Freud twenty-five years
earlier, in 1895.
Extracts from the earlier (1922) translation of this
included in Rickman's General
#af (1937,
Selection from the
work were
Works ofSigmnd
162-194).
Editorial additions, whether to the text or the footnotes, are
printed in square brackets.
Beyond the Pleasure Principle
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
IN the theory of psycho-analysis we have no hesitation in assuming that the course taken by mental events is automatically regulated by the pleasure principle. We believe, that is to say,
that the course of those events
unpleasurable tension,
is
and that
invariably set in motion by an it takes a direction such that
outcome coincides with a lowering of that tension that with an avoidance of unpleasure or a production of pleasure, In taking that course into account in our consideration of the
its final is,
mental processes which are the subject of our study, we are introducing an 'economic' point of view into our work; and if, in describing those processes, we try to estimate this 'economic' factor in addition to the
we
'topographical* and 'dynamic' ones,
be giving the most complete description of them of which we can at present conceive, and one which shall, I think,
deserves to be distinguished It far,
1
by the term 'metapsychologicaT. of no concern to us in this connection to enquire how with this hypothesis of the pleasure principle, we have is
approached or adopted any particular, historically established, We have arrived at these speculative
philosophical system. assumptions in an
attempt to describe and to account for the of daily observation in our field of study. Priority and work originality are not among the aims that facts
psycho-analytic and the impressions that underlie the hypothesis of the pleasure principle are so obvious that they can scarcely be overlooked. On the other hand we would our sets itself;
readily express gratitude to any philosophical or psychological theory which was able to inform us of the meaning of the feelings of pleasure and unpleasure which act so imperatively upon us. But on this
point
we
are, alas, offered
nothing to our purpose. This
is
the
most obscure and inaccessible region of the mind, and, since we cannot avoid contact with it, the least rigid hypothesis, it seems to me, 1
will
be the
[See Section
IV
best.
We
have decided to relate
of 'The Unconscious' (191&).] 1
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
2
and unpleasure pleasure in the mind but present
to the quantity of excitation that is
not in any
way
'bound';
1
and
is
to
manner that unpleasure corresponds to the quantity of excitation and pleasure to a diminution. What we are implying by this is not a simple relation relate
an
them
in such a
iaartast in
between the strength of the feelings -of pleasure and unpleasure and the corresponding modifications in the quantity of excitain view of all we have been taught by psychotion; least of all
physiologyare we suggesting any
directly proportional ratio:
the factor that determines the feeling
is
probably the amount of
increase or diminution in the quantity of excitation in a given
Experiment might possibly play a part here; but not advisable for us analysts to go into the problem further so long as our way is not pointed by quite definite
time. period of it
is
observations.*
We cannot, however, remain indifferent to the discovery that an investigator of such penetration as G. T. Fechner held a view on the subject of pleasure and unpleasure which coincides in all essentials
with the one that has been forced upon us by is to be found con-
psycho-analytic work. Fechner's statement
lungsgesckichti
and reads
der
Organimen, 1873 (Part XI, Supplement, 94),
as follows: 'In so far as conscious impulses
always have some relation to pleasure or unpleasure, pleasure and can be too a as regarded unpleasure having psycho-physical relation to conditions of stability basis for
a hypothesis
into
and instability. This provides a
which
I
propose to enter in greater
detail elsewhere.
According to this hypothesis, every psychophysical motion rising above the threshold of consciousness is attended by pleasure in proportion as, beyond a certain limit, stability, and is attended by unas, beyond a certain limit, it deviates from complete stability; while between the two limits, which may be described as qualitative thresholds of pleasure and
it
approximates to complete
pleasure in proportion
1
[The concepts of
'quantity*
and of *bound'
excitation,
which rua
through the whole of Freud's writings, found what is perhaps their most detailed discussion in the early 'Project' (1950a [1895]). See in particular the long discussion of the term 'bound* near the cad of Section 1 of Part III of that work. See also p. 28
f. below.] again mentioned below on p. 57 and further de1 veloped in "The Economic Problem of Masochism (1924*).]
1
[This point
is
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE there
unpleasure, ence.
3
a certain margin of aesthetic
is
indiffer-
* .
The
.'
.
facts
which have caused us
to believe in the
dominance
of the pleasure principle in mental life also find expression in that the mental apparatus endeavours to keep the
hypothesis the quantity of excitation present in it as low as possible or at keep it constant. This latter hypothesis is only another
least to
way of
for if the stating the pleasure principle;
work of the
mental apparatus is directed towards keeping the quantity of excitation lowj then anything that is calculated to increase that quantity
is
apparatus,
bound that
to
is
be
felt as
adverse to the functioning of the
as unpleasurable.
The
pleasure principle
follows from the principle of constancy: actually the latter
from the
which forced us
was adopt principle the pleasure principle.* Moreover, a more detailed discussion will show that the tendency which we thus attribute to the inferred
facts
to
mental apparatus is subsumed as a special case under Fechner's of the 'tendency towards stability', to which he has principle brought the feelings of pleasure and unpleasure into relation, It must be pointed out, however, that strictly speaking it is incorrect to talk of the dominance of the pleasure principle over the course of mental processes. If such
the
immense majority of our mental
a dominance
processes
existed,
would have
to
be
accompanied by pleasure or to lead to pleasure, whereas universal experience completely contradicts any such conclusion.
in the
The most that can be
mind a strong
that that tendency
is
stances, so that the final
i
[Cf. 'Project',
saidj therefore, is that there exists
towards the pleasure principle, but opposed by certain other forces or circum-
tendency
outcome cannot always be in harmony
end of Section 8 of Part
I
'Aesthetic*
is
here used in
the old sense of 'relating to sensation or perception'.] 1 [The 'principle 'of constancy' dates back to the very beginning of Freud's psychological studies. The first published discussion of it of any
of length was by Breuer (in semi-physiological terms) towards the end Section 2 (A) of his theoretical part of the Studies on Hysteria (Breuer and Freud, 1895). He there defines it as 'the tendency to keep intracerebral excitation constant'. In the
same passage he
attributes this principle to
Freud and there in fact exist one or two earlier very brief references to it by Freud himself, though these were not published until after bis death. (See Freud, 1941a [1892] and Breuer and Freud, 1940 [1892].)
The
subject
'Project',
is
also discussed at length at the beginning of Freud's
under the name of 'neuronic
inertia'.]
'
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
4
with the tendency towards pleasure, We may compare what Fechner (1873, 90) remarks on a similar point: 'Since however a
tendency towards an aim does not imply that the aim
and
since in general the
tions.
.
.
aim
is
attainable only
is
attained,
by approxima-
.*
now to the
If we turn
question of what circumstances are able from being carried into effect,
to prevent the pleasure principle
we find
ourselves once
more on secure and well-trodden ground
and, in framing our answer, of analytic experience.
The in this
first
we have
at
our disposal a rich fund
example of the pleasure principle being inhibited familiar one which occurs with regularity. We
way is a
know
that the pleasure principle is proper to a primary method of working on the part of the mental apparatus, but that, from the point of view of the self-preservation of the organism among
the difficulties of the external world, inefficient
it is
from the very outset
and even highly dangerous. Under the influence of
the ego's instincts of self-preservation, the pleasure principle is 1 replaced by the reality principle, This latter principle does not
abandon the nevertheless
intention of ultimately obtaining pleasure, but
demands and
of satisfaction,
it
carries into effect the
postponement the abandonment of a number of possibilities of
gaining satisfaction and the temporary toleration of unpleasure as a step on the long indirect road to pleasure. The pleasure principle long persists, however, as the method of working em-
ployed by the sexual
which are so hard to 'educate',
instincts,
and, starting from those instincts, or in the ego itself, it often succeeds in overcoming the reality principle, to the detriment of
There can be no doubt, however, that the replacement of the by the reality principle can only be made
pleasure principle
responsible for a small
number, and by no means the most Another occasion of the
intense, of unpleasurable experiences.
release of unpleasure, to
be found in the
which occurs with no
conflicts
and
less regularity, is
dissensions that take place in the
ment into more highly composite organizations. Almost all the energy with which the apparatus is filled arises from its innate instinctual impulses. But these are not all allowed to reach 1
[See 'Formulations
Freud 191 16.]
on
the
Two
Principles of Mental Functioning
5 ,
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
5
same phases of development. In the course of things it and again that individual instincts or parts of happens again the
instincts turn
out to be incompatible in their aims or demands
with the remaining ones, which are able to combine into the inclusive unity of the ego. The former are then split off from
back at lower levels unity by the process of repression, held of psychical development and cut off, to begin with, from the of satisfaction. If they succeed subsequently, as can possibility this
happen with repressed sexual instincts, in struggling to a direct or to a substitutive through, by roundabout paths, satisfaction, that event, which would in other cases have been an so easily
for pleasure, is felt by the ego as unpleasure. As opportunity a consequence of the old conflict which ended in repression, a
new breach has occurred in the pleasure principle at the very time when certain instincts were endeavouring, in accordance with the principle, to obtain fresh pleasure, The details of the turns a possibility of pleasure into a process by which repression source of unpleasure are not yet clearly understood or cannot
be clearly represented; but there is no doubt that all neurotic as such. 1 unpleasure is of that kind pleasure that cannot be felt
The two
sources of unpleasure which I have just indicated
are very far from covering the majority of our unpleasurable experiences.
But
as regards the
remainder it can be asserted with
some show ofjustification that their presence does not contradict the
dominance of the pleasure
that
principle.
of pressure by unsatisfied instincts; or it tion
Most of the unpleasure
we experience is perceptual unpleasure, which
is
It may be perception may be external percep-
either distressing in itself or
which
excites
un-
that is, pleasurable expectations in the mental apparatus which is recognized by it as a 'danger', The reaction to these instinctual demands and threats of danger, a reaction which constitutes the proper activity of the mental apparatus,
can
then be directed in a correct manner by the pleasure principle or the reality principle by which the former is modified. This does not seem to necessitate any far-reaching limitation of the the investigation of the mental pleasure principle. Nevertheless reaction to external danger is precisely in a position to pro-
duce new material and raise fresh questions bearing upon our present problem. i the essential point is [Footnote added 1925:] No doubt and unpleasure, being conscious feelings, are attached to
that pleasure the ego.
II
A
CONDITION has long been known and described which occurs mechanical concussions, railway disasters and other
after severe
life; it has been given the name of The terrible war which has just ended gave a great number of illnesses of this kind, but it at least put
accidents involving a risk to
'traumatic neurosis'. rise to
to the
an end
temptation to attribute the cause of the disorder
to organic lesions of the nervous system
mechanical
force.
1
The symptomatic
brought about by
picture presented
by
traumatic neurosis approaches that of hysteria in the wealth of its similar motor symptoms, but surpasses it as a rule in its
marked
strongly
signs of subjective ailment (in
which
it re-
sembles hypochondria or melancholia) as well as in the evidence it gives of a far more comprehensive general enfeeblement and disturbance of the mental capacities. No complete explanation has yet been reached either of war neuroses or of the traumatic neuroses of peace. In the case of the war neuroses, the fact that the same
symptoms sometimes came about without the
inter-
vention of any gross mechanical force seemed at once enlightening and bewildering. In the case of the ordinary traumatic neuroses two characteristics emerge prominently: the chief weight in their causation seams to rest factor of surprise, of fright; inflicted simultaneously
of a neurosis. 'Fright*, as
synonymous
first,
that
upon the
and secondly, that a wound or injury
works as a rule
'fear'
and
against, *
'anxiety'
the development
are improperly used
expressions; they are in fact capable of clear dis-
tinction in their relation to danger. 'Anxiety' describes a particular state of expecting the danger or preparing for it, even
be an unknown
one. Tear' requires a definite may object of which to be afraid. 'Fright', however, is the name we the to a state give person gets into when he has run into danger
though
it
without being prepared for it; it emphasizes the factor of surprise. I do not believe anxiety can produce a traumatic neuro1
a.
the discussion
on the psycho-analysis of war neuroses by Freud,
Abraham, Simmcl and Jones (1919) [to which Freud provided the introduction (1915W). See also his posthumously published on the Electrical Treatment of War Neuroses' 'Report (1955* [1920]).]
Fercnczi,
[In
German,
'&W, 'Fackf and 'Angst.] 6
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE There
sis.
is
7
something about anxiety that protects
against fright
and
so against fright-neuroses.
to this point later [p.
25
We
its
subject
shall return
1
f.].
The study of dreams may be considered
the most
trustworthy
method of investigating deep mental processes. Now dreams occurring in traumatic neuroses have the characteristic of the patient back into the situation of his repeatedly bringing accident, a situation from which he wakes up in another fright.
This astonishes people far too Me. They think the fact that the traumatic experience is constantly forcing itself upon the a proof of the strength of that experione might say, fixated to his trauma. Fixations to the experience which started the illness have long in his sleep patient even ence: the patient is, as
is
been familiar to us in hysteria. Breuer and Freud declared in z 1893 that 'hysterics suffer mainly from reminiscences'. In the
war
neuroses, too, observers like Ferenczi
and Simmel have
been able to explain certain motor symptoms by fixation to the moment at which the trauma occurred. I am not aware, however, that patients suffering from traumatic neurosis are much occupied in their waking lives with memories of their accident Perhaps they are more concerned not thinking of it. Anyone who accepts it as something sel evident that their dreams should put them back at night into the situation that caused them to fall ill has misunderstood the
with
nature of dreams. It would be more in harmony with their nature if they showed the patient pictures from his healthy past or of the cure for which he hopes. If we arc not to be shaken in tenor of dreams by the dreams
our beliefjn the
wish-fulfilling
of traumatic neurotics, we still have one resource open to us: we may argue that the function of dreaming, like so much else, is upset in this condition and diverted from its purposes, or we 1
is very far indeed from always carrying out the distinche makes here. More often than not he uses the word *4ngst' to a denote state of fear without any reference to the future. It seems not
[Freud
tion
unlikely that in this passage he is beginning to adumbrate the distinction drawn in Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety (1926V) between anxiety as a
reaction to a traumatic situation called Schrtck
an
and anxiety
as
probably equivalent
to
what
is
here
a warning signal of the approach of such
event. See also his use of the phrase 'preparedness for anxiety
on
p. 25.] *
['On the Psychical Section I.]
Mechanism of Hysterical Phenomena', end of
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE y be driven
to reflect
*
on the mysterious masochistic Jiends ;
'
At this point I propose to leave the dark and dismal subject of the traumatic neurosis and pass on to examine the method of working employed by the mental apparatus in one of earliest normal activities
The
I
mean
its
in children's play.
different theories of children's play
have only recently
been summarized and discussed from the psycho-analytic point of view by Pfeifer (1919), to whose paper I would refer
my
These theories attempt to discover the motives which
readers,
lead children to play, but they fail to bring into the foreground the economic motive, the consideration of the yield of pleasure involved. Without wishing to include the whole field covered
have been
a
chance opable, through by these phenomena, portunity which presented itself, to throw some light upon the first game played by a little boy of one and a half and invented I
by
himself. It
was more than a mere
fleeting observation, for I
under the same roof as the child and
lived
weeks, and
it
was some time before
his parents for
I discovered the
some
meaning
of the puzzling activity which he constantly repeated. The child was not at all precocious in his intellectual de-
velopment. At the age of one and a half he could say only a few comprehensible words; he could also make use of a number of sounds which expressed a meaning intelligible to those around him. He was, however, on good terms with his parents and their
one
servant-girl,
boy'.
and
tributes
were paid to
He did not disturb his parents
at night,
his
being a 'good
he conscientiously
obeyed orders not to touch certain things or go into certain rooms, and above all he never cried when his mother left him for a
few hours. At the same time, he was greatly attached to
mother, who had not only fed him herself but had also looked after him without any outside help. This good little boy, however, had an occasional disturbing habit of taking any small his
objects
a
he could get hold of and throwing them away from him
corner, under the bed,
and so on, so that hunting for his and picking them up was often quite a business. As he did this he gave vent to a loud, long-drawn-out 'o-o-o-o', accompanied by an expression of interest and satisfaction. His mother
into
toys
1
[The
last 15
words of this sentence were added in 192 1 For
see The Intirpretation of Dreams (1900a), Standard Ed., 5,
.
550
ff.]
all this
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
9
and the writer of the present account were agreed in thinking that this was not a mere interjection but represented the Ger-
man word game and
I eventually realized that it was a 'faf ['gone']. made of any of his toys was to
that the only use he
with them,
play 'gone'
confirmed
One day
my view. The
of string tied round
it,
It
child
I
What he
riage.
throw
observation which reel with
never occurred to him to pull
the floor behind him, for instance,
skilfully
made an
had a wooden and play
at
its
a piece it
along being a car-
did was to hold the reel by the string and very over the edge of his curtained cot, so that it
it
at the same time uttering his expressive disappeared into it, Vo-o-o'. He then pulled the reel out of the cot again by the
and hailed
string
This, then,
its
W
reappearance with a joyful
was the complete game
['there'].
disappearance and return.
As a rule one only witnessed its first act, which was repeated untiringly as a game in itself, though there is no doubt that the greater pleasure
The
was attached to the second
interpretation of the
was related
act.
1
game then became
stinctual renunciation (that
is,
away without
protesting.
He compensated
his
is
mother to go
himself for
by himself staging the disappearance and
objects within his reach. It
the in-
the renunciation of instinctual
which he had made in allowing
satisfaction)
were,
obvious. It
to the child's great cultural achievement-
this, as it
return of the
of course a matter of indifference
from the point of view of judging the effective nature of the game whether the child invented it himself or took it over on
some outside point.
The
suggestion.
Our
interest
child cannot possibly have
is
directed to another
felt his
mother's departHow then does
ure as something agreeable or even indifferent. his repetition
of this distressing experience as a game fit in with may perhaps be said in reply that her
the pleasure principle? It
departure had to be enacted as a necessary preliminary to her joyful return, and that it was in the latter that lay the true purpose 1
A
fully.
further observation subsequently confirmed this interpretation the child's mother had been away for several hours and
One day
on her return was met with the words 'Baby o-o-o-o!' which was at first incomprehensible. It soon turned out, however, that during this long period of solitude the child had found a method of making himself disappear, He had discovered his reflection in a full-length mirror which did not quite reach to the ground, so that by crouching
make
down he could
mirror-image 'gone'. [A further reference to this story will be found in The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Ed., 5, 461n.j his
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
10
of the game, But against
must be counted the observed
this
of departure, was staged as a game in itself and far more frequently than the episode in its entirety, fact that the first act, that
with
its
No
pleasurable ending. certain decision can be reached
this. single case like
On
from the
analysis of a
an unprejudiced view one
gets
an im-
turned his experience into a game from pression that the child another motive. At the outset he was in & passive situation he
was overpowered by the experience; but, by repeating it, as a game, he took on an active unpleasurable though it was, be put down to an instinct for mastery part. These efforts might that was acting independently of whether the memory was in itself pleasurable or
not But
still
another interpretation
may
be attempted, Throwing away the object so that it was 'gone' might satisfy an impulse of the child's, which was suppressed in his actual
life,
to revenge himself on his
from him. In that case right, then,
myself.' first it
go away!
I
mother
for going
away
would have a defiant meaning: 'All don't need you. I'ta sending you away it
A year later, the same boy whom I had observed at his if he was angry with it, and throw 'Go to the fwont!' He had heard at
game used to take a toy,
on the
floor, exclaiming:
e
that time that his absent father
was at the
front',
and was
far
from regretting his absence; on the contrary he made it quite clear that he had no desire to be disturbed in his sole possession of his mother. 1
We know of other children who liked to
similar hostile impulses 8
persons.
We
by throwing away
are therefore
left
express
objects instead of
in doubt as to whether the
impulse to work over in the mind some overpowering experience so as to make oneself master of it can find expression as a
primary event, and independently of the pleasure principle. For, in the case we have been discussing, the child may, after only have been able to repeat his unpleasant experience in play because the repetition carried -along with it a yield of pleasure of another sort but none the less a direct one. all,
Nor shall we be helped in our hesitation between these two views by further considering children's play. It is clear that in 1
When
that she
this child
was
five
and
three-quarters, his
mother died.
was
Now
really 'gone' ('o-o-o'), the little boy showed no signs of grief. It is true that in the interval a second child had been born and had
roused him to violent jealousy. 1 Cf. my note on a childhood
memory of Goethe's
(19173).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE their play children repeat everything that has
made a
11
great
in real life, and that in doing so they impression on them abreact the strength of the impression and, as one might put it,
make themselves master of
hand
it is
that dominates
them
the situation. But
on the other
play is influenced by a wish the whole time the wish to be grown-up
obvious that
all their
be able to do what grown-up people do. It can also be observed that the unpleasurable nature of an experience does
and
to
not always unsuit it for play. If the doctor looks down a child's throat or carries out some small operation on him, we may be these frightening experiences will be the subject quite sure that
of the next game; but we must not in that connection overlook the fact that there is a yield of pleasure from another source. child passes over from the passivity of the experience to the activity of the game, he hands on the disagreeable experience to one of his playmates and in this way revenges himself
As the
on a
substitute.
it emerges from this discussion 'that there is no need to assume the existence of a special imitative instinct in
Nevertheless,
order to provide a motive for play. Finally, a reminder may be added that the artistic play and artistic imitation carried out
by adults, which, unlike children's, are aimed at an audience, do not spare the spectators (for instance, in tragedy) the most
and can yet be felt by them as highly enjoyconvincing proof that, even under the dominance are ways and means enough of principle, there
painful experiences 1 able. This
is
of the pleasure
making what is in itself unpleasurable into a subject to be recollected and worked over in the mind. The consideration of these cases
and
situations,
which have a
yield of pleasure as
outcome, should be undertaken by some system of aesthetics with an economic approach to its subject-matter.
their final
They
are of no use for our purposes, since they presuppose the and dominance of the pleasure principle; they give
existence
no evidence of the operation of tendencies beyond the pleasure that is, of tendencies more primitive than it and inprinciple, dependent of it. * this point in his posthumously [Freud had made a tentative study of Characters on the Stage' (1942a) published paper on 'Psychopathic which was probably written in 1905 or 1906.]
Ill
TWENTY-FIVE years of intense work have had as their result that the immediate aims of psycho-analytic technique are quite other today than they were at the outset. At first the analysing do no more than discover the unconscious physician could material that was concealed from the patient, put it together, and, at the right moment, communicate it to him. Psychothen first and foremost an art of interpreting. analysis was Since this did not solve the therapeutic problem, a further aim came in view: to oblige the patient to confirm the quickly construction from his own memory. In that endeavour analyst's
the chief emphasis lay upon the patient's resistances: the art now in uncovering these as quickly as possible, in
consisted
and in inducing him by human was where suggestion operating as 'transference' to abandon his resistances. played its part But it became ever clearer that the aim which had been set
the patient pointing them out to this
influence
aim
the
up
scious
that
what was unconscious should become con-
not completely attainable by that method.
is
patient cannot
remember
the whole of what
and what he cannot remember
Thus he acquires no
part of it.
may be
The
repressed in him,
precisely the essential
sense of conviction of the cor-
rectness of the construction that has
He
is
been communicated to
obliged to repeat the repressed material as a contemporary experience instead of, as the physician would prefer to see, remembering it as something belonging to the past. 1 These
him.
is
reproductions, which emerge with such unwished-for exacti-
have as their subject some portion of infantile of the Oedipus complex, that is, and its derivatives; and they are invariably acted cut in the sphere of the transference, of the patient's relation to the physician. When things have reached this stage, it may be said that the earlier neurosis tude, always
sexual
has 1
life
now been replaced by a fresh, on
'transference neurosis'. It has
Repeating and Working Through' (1914g). [An early reference will be found in this same paper to the 'compulsion to repeat', which is one of the principle topics discussed in See
my paper
'Recollecting,
the present work. (See also the Editor's Note above, The term p. xi.) 'transference neurosis' in the special sense in which it is used a few lines
lower
down
also appears in that paper.] 12
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
13
been the physician's endeavour to keep this transference neurosis within the narrowest limits: to force as much as possible into the channel of
memory and
to allow as little as possible to
emerge as repetition. The ratio between what is remembered and what is reproduced varies from case to case. The physician cannot as a rule spare his patient
He must get him
to re-experience
but must see to
life,
it,
this
phase of the treatment.
some portion of his forgotten
on the other hand,
that the patient
some degree of aloofness, which will enable him, in spite of everything, to recognize that what appears to be reality is in
retains
fact only
a reflection of a forgotten past. If this can be successof conviction is won, together
the patient's sense fully achieved,
with the therapeutic success that is dependent on it. In order to make it easier to understand this 'compulsion to repeat',
which emerges during the psycho-analytic treatment we must above all get rid of the mistaken notion
of neurotics, that
what we are dealing with in our struggle against resistances on the part of the unconscious. The unconscious
resistance
is
that
to say, the 'repressed*
is
no
offers
the efforts of the treatment. Indeed,
resistance
it itself
whatever to
has no other en-
deavour than to break through the pressure weighing down on and force its way either to consciousness or to a discharge
it
through some real action. Resistance during treatment arises from the same higher strata and systems of the mind which originally carried out repression.
But the
from experience, the motives of the
fact that, as
resistances,
we know
and indeed the
resistances themselves, are unconscious at first -during the treatis a hint to us that we should correct a shortcoming in our terminology. We shall avoid a lack of clarity if we make our contrast not between the conscious and the unconscious but
ment,
between the coherent
much
of the ego
l
ego
and the
is itself unconscious,
repressed. It is
certain that
and notably what we may
2
its nucleus; only a small part of it is covered by the term 'preconscious'. 3 Having replaced a purely descriptive
describe as
1
[Cf.
a discussion of
this in
the Editor's Introduction to The Ego and
Id (19236), Standard Ed., 19, 7-8; IJPJL, 12, xiii-xiv.j [This is corrected in a footnote at the beginning of Chapter III of The Ego and the Id, ibid., 28, and ibid., 16.] 3 first edition [In its present form this sentence dates from 192 1 In the
the
s
.
(1920)
it
ran:
'It
may be
a part of it, probably,
is
that much of the ego is itself unconscious; only covered by the term "preconscious'V]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
14
terminology by one which
is
systematic or dynamic,
we
can say
1
that the patient's resistance arises from his ego, and we then at once perceive that the compulsion to repeat must be ascribed to the unconscious repressed. It seems probable that the comitself after the pulsion can only express
work of treatment has
2 to meet it and has loosened the repression. gone half-way There is no doubt that the resistance of the conscious and unconscious ego operates under the sway of the pleasure prin-
ciple:
it
which would be produced Our efforts, on the other hand,
seeks to avoid the unpleasure
liberation of the repressed.
by the
are directed towards procuring the toleration of that unpleasure to the reality principle. But how is the compulsion an
by
appeal
the manifestation of the
to repeat
power of the repressed
related to the pleasure principle? It is clear that the greater part of what is re-experienced under the compulsion to repeat must
cause the ego unpleasure, since
it
brings to light activities of
repressed instinctual impulses. That, however,
is
unpleasure of
a kind we have already considered and does not contradict the unpleasure for one system and simultaneously pleasure principle
:
3 satisfaction for the other.
But we come
now
to a
new and
re-
markable fact, namely that the compulsion to repeat also recalls from the past experiences which include no possibility of
and which can
pleasure,
satisfaction
never, even long ago, have brought even to instinctual impulses which have since been
"
repressed.
The
is doomed to early efflorescence of infantile sexual life its wishes are incompatible with reality and
extinction because
with the inadequate stage of development which the child has reached. That efflorescence comes to an end in the most distressing circumstances
and to the accompaniment of the most
Loss of love and failure leave behind them a painful feelings. permanent injury to self-regard in the form of a narcissisticscar,
which in
contributes
my opinion,
as well as in Marcinowski's (1918),
more than anything
to the 'sense of inferiority'
1
[A fuller and somewhat different account of the sources of resistance will be found in Chap. XI of Inhibitions^ Symptoms and Anxiety (1926rf).] [Footnote added 1923:] I have argued elsewhere [1923;] that what thus comes to the help of the compulsion to repeat is the factor of that the patient's subraissiveness to the 'suggestion' in the treatment Js,
physician, 3
which has
[a. Freud's
its
roots
deep in his unconscious parental complex. of the fairy tale of the "Three Wishes'
allegorical use
at the beginning of Lecture
XIV of his
Introductory Lectures (1916-17).]
*
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
15
which is so common in neurotics. The child's sexual researches, on which limits are imposed by his physical development, lead hence such later complaints as to no satisfactory conclusion;
can't accomplish anything; I can't succeed in anything*. The of affection, which binds the child as a rule to the parent of
tie
succumbs to disappointment, to a vain exof satisfaction or to jealousy over the birth of a new unmistakable proof of the infidelity of the object of the
the opposite sex,
pectation
baby
child's affections.
His
own
attempt to make a baby himself,
carried out with tragic seriousness,
fails
shamefully.
The
les-
amount of affection he receives, the increasing demands of education, hard words and an occasional punishment these sening
show him
at last the full extent to
which he has been scorned.
These are a few typical and constantly recurring instances of the ways in which the love characteristic of the age of child-
hood
brought to a conclusion.
is
Patients repeat all of these
unwanted
and painful
situations
emotions in the transference and revive them with the greatest seek to bring about the interruption of the ingenuity. They treatment while
it is still
incomplete; they contrive once more
to feel themselves. scorned, to oblige the physician to
severely to
them and
treat
them
speak
coldly; they discover appro-
for their jealousy; instead of the passionately priate objects desired baby of their childhood, they produce a plan or a
promise
no less
of some grand present which turns out as a rule to be None of these things can have produced pleasure
unreal.
and it might be supposed that they would cause less unpleasure to-day if they emerged as memories or dreams instead of taking the form of fresh experiences. They are of in the past,
course the activities of instincts intended to lead to satisfaction;
but no lesson has been learnt from the old experience of these 1 activities having led instead only to unpleasure. In spite of that, they are repeated, under pressure of a compulsion.
What psycho-analysis reveals in the
transference
of neurotics can also be observed in the people,
nant
lives
phenomena
of some normal
The impression they give is of being pursued by a maligby some 'daemonic' power; but psycho-
fate or possessed
analysis has always taken the
part arranged influences.
view that their fate
by themselves and determined by
The compulsion which 1
is
is
for the
most
early infantile here in evidence differs in
[This sentence was added in 1921.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
16
to repeat which we have found in though the people we are now considering have
no way from the compulsion neurotics, even
never shown any signs of dealing with a neurotic conflict by Thus we have come across people all of producing symptoms. whose human relationships have the same outcome: such as the
who
is abandoned in anger after a time by each of however much they may otherwise differ from one another, and who thus seems doomed to taste all the bitterness of ingratitude; or the man whose friendships all end in betrayal
benefactor
\os,pTotigkt
by
man who
his friend; or the
time after time in the course of
a position of great private or public authority and then, after a certain interval, himself upsets that authority and replaces him by a new one; or, again, his life raises
someone
else into
the lover each of whose love affairs with a
woman
passes
through the same phases and reaches the same conclusion. This 'perpetual recurrence of the same thing* causes us no astonishment when it relates to active behaviour on the part of the person concerned and when we can discern in him an essential char-
which always remains the same and which is coma repetition of the same experiences,
acter-trait
pelled to find expression in
We are much more impressed by cases where the subject appears to have a passive experience, over which he has no influence, but in which he meets with a repetition of the same fatality.
There
is
the case, for instance, of the
married three successive husbands each of afterwards and
had
woman who
whom
fell ill
soon
be nursed by her on their death-beds. 1 The most moving poetic picture of a fate such as this is given to
by
Tasso in his romantic epic Gerusalmm Liberate. Its hero, Tancred, unwittingly kills his beloved Clorinda in a duel while she
armour of an enemy knight. After her way into a strange magic forest which Crusaders' army with terror. He slashes with his
disguised in the
is
burial he
makes
strikes the
sword at a
his
tall tree;
but blood streams from the cut and the
voice of Glorinda, whose soul
is imprisoned in the tree, is heard complaining that he has wounded his beloved once again.
If
we
take into account observations such as these, based
upon behaviour in the transference and upon the life-histories of men and women, we shall find to assume that there courage
rides the 1
pleasure principle.
Cf. the apt
remark on
Now
too
this subject
we
shall
be inclined to
by CL G. Jung
(1909).
BEYOND THE PDEASURE PRINCIPLE
17
compulsion the dreams which occur in traumatic
relate to this
and the impulse which leads children to play. But it is to be noted that only in rare instances can we observe
neuroses
the pure effects of the compulsion to repeat, unsupported by other motives. In the case of children's play we have already laid stress
hi which the emergence of the be interpreted; the compulsion to repeat and
on the other ways
may
compulsion
instinctual satisfaction
which
is
immediately pleasurable seem
an intimate partnership. The phenomena of transference are obviously exploited by the resistance which to converge here into
the ego maintains in
its pertinacious insistence upon repression; the compulsion to repeat, which the treatment tries to bring into its service is, as it were, drawn over by the ego to its side
A
1 as the ego does to the pleasure principle). great deal (clinging of what might be described as the compulsion of destiny seems a rational basis; so that we are under no necesintelligible on
a new and mysterious motive force to explain it, dubious instance [of such a motive force] is perhaps
in sity to call
The
least
that of traumatic dreams.
be forced is
ground forces.
to
But on maturer
shall
not covered by the operation of the familiar motive is left unexplained to justify the hypothesis of a
something that seems more primitive,
more elementary, more instinctual than which it over-rides. But if a compulsion in the mind, to learn
we should be
what function
it
can emerge and what to which, after aU,
relation
to repeat does operate
know something about
glad to
corresponds its
the pleasure principle
to,
is
to the pleasure principle
we have hitherto ascribed dominance over
principle.']
to
its
life.
read: 'the compulsion to repeat is as it help by the ego, clinging as it does to the pleasure
[Before 1923 the
were called
it,
under what conditions
the course of the processes of excitation in mental 1
we
Enough
compulsion to repeat
it
reflection
admit that even in the other instances the whole
last clause
IV
WHAT
follows
is
which the reader
speculation,
often far-fetched
will consider or dismiss
vidual predilection. It
is
further
speculation,
according to his indi-
an attempt
to follow out
idea consistently, out of curiosity to see where
it
an
will lead.
Psycho-analytic speculation takes as its point of departure the impression, derived from examining unconscious processes, that consciousness may be, not the most universal attribute of
mental processes, but only a particular function of them. Speaking in metapsychological terms, it asserts that consciousis a function of a particular system which it describes as
ness Cs.
1
What
consciousness yields consists essentially of percep-
tions of excitations
coming from the external world and of
of pleasure and unpleasure which can only arise from within the mental apparatus; it is therefore possible to assign to
feelings
the system Pcpt,-Cs.* a position in space. It must He on the borderline between outside and inside; it must be turned to-
wards the external world and must envelop the other psychical systems. It will be seen that there these
localization held
is
nothing daringly new in the views on
we have merely adopted
assumptions;
by cerebral anatomy, which locates the
of consciousness in the cerebral cortex
ing layer of the central organ. Cerebral to consider
'seat'
the outermost, envelop-
anatomy has no need
why, speaking anatomically, consciousness should
be lodged on the surface of the brain instead of being safely housed somewhere in its inmost interior. Perhaps shall be
w
more
successful in accounting for this situation in the case of
our system
Pcpt.-Cs.
Consciousness
is
not the only distinctive character which
ascribe to the processes in that system. sions derived
that
1
610
all
On
we
the basis of impres-
from our psycho-analytic experience, we assume
excitatory processes that occur in the other systems leave
[See Freud, The Interpretation of Drems (19QQa), Standard Ed., 5, ft, and "The Unconscious' (1915*), Section II.]
1
[The system Pcpt. (the perceptual system) was first described by Freud in The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Ed,, 5, 536 ff. In a later paper (19174) he argued that the system jystemCj.] 18
Pcpt.
coincided with the
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
19
behind in them which form the foundation of permanent traces memory. Such memory-traces, then, have nothing to do with the fact of
becoming conscious; indeed they are often most
powerful and most enduring when the process which left them behind was one which never entered consciousness. We find it
hard to believe, however, that permanent traces of excitation such as these are also left in the system Pcpt.-Cs. If they re-
mained constantly conscious, they would very soon
set limits
to the system's aptitude for receiving fresh excitations. 1 If,
the other hand, they were unconscious,
we
on
should be faced
with the problem of explaining the existence of unconscious in a system whose processes functioning was otherwise accompanied by the phenomenon of consciousness. We should, so to
have altered nothing and gained nothing by our hypothesis a special system.
say,
relegating the process of becoming conscious to
Though
this consideration is
not absolutely conclusive,
theless leads us to suspect that
it
never-
becoming conscious and leaving
behind a memory-trace are processes incompatible with each same system. Thus we should be able
other within one and the
to say that the excitatory process becomes conscious in the system Cs. but leaves no permanent trace behind there; but
that the excitation
within and that these
same
lines in
transmitted to the systems lying next its traces are left. I followed
is
it is
in them that
the schematic picture which
the speculative section of
be borne in mind that
I
included in
of Dream? It must known from other sources
my Interpretation
little
enough
is
we lay down the proposition that consciousness arises instead of a memory-trace, the assertion deserves consideration, at all events on the ground of of the origin of consciousness; when, therefore,
being framed in fairly precise terms. is so, then, the system Cs. is characterized by the peculiarity that in it (in contrast to what happens in the other its
If this
psychical systems) excitatory processes do not leave behind any permanent change in its elements but expire, as it were, in the
phenomenon of becoming conscious. An exception of this sort 1 What follows is based throughout on Breuer's views in [the second section of his theoretical contribution to] Studies on Hysteria (Breuer and Freud, 1895). [Freud himself discussed the subject in The Interpretation
of Dreams, Standard Ed., 5, 538 and it had previously been fully considered in his 'Project' of 1895 (I950a), Part I, Section 3, He returned to the topic later in his paper [Standard Ed., 5,538.]
on the 'Mystic Writing-Pad
1
(1925a).]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
20
to the general rule requires to
be explained by some factor that
to that one system. Such a factor, which is applies exclusively absent in the other systems, might well be the exposed situation
of the system Cs. external world,
}
immediately abutting as
Let us picture a living organism in
form
as
an undifferentiated
susceptible to stimulation.
external world will from will serve as
Then
its
its
vesicle
it
does on the
most simplified possible of a substance that
is
the surface turned towards the
very situation be differentiated and
an organ for receiving stimuli Indeed embryology,
of developmental history, its capacity as a recapitulation that the central nervous system originates actually shows us from the ectoderm; the grey matter of the cortex remains a in
derivative of the primitive superficial layer of the organism
may have
inherited
some of its
essential properties. It
and
would be
easy to suppose, then, that as a result of the ceaseless impact of external stimuli on the surface of the vesicle, its substance to a certain depth
may have become permanently
modified, so that
excitatory processes run a different course in it from what they crust would thus be formed which run in the deeper layers.
A
would
have been so thoroughly 'baked through' by stimulation that it would present the most favourable possible at last
conditions for the reception of stimuli
and become incapable of
any further modification. In terms of the system &., this would mean that its elements could undergo no further permanent modification from the passage of excitation, because they had already been modified in the respect in question to the greatest possible extent:
now, however, they would have become capmay be
able of giving rise to consciousness. Various ideas
formed which cannot at present be verified as to the nature of this modification of the substance and of the excitatory process.
may be supposed that, in passing from one element to another, an excitation has to overcome a resistance, and that
It
the diminution of resistance thus effected
permanent trace of the
is
what a
lays
down
a
facilitation.
In
the system &., then, resistance of this kind to passage from
one
excitation, that
is,
element to another would no longer exist. 1 This picture can be brought into relation with Breuer's distinction between quiescent (orbound) and mobile cathectic energy in the elements i
[This passage is foreshadowed in the later half of Section 3 of 1 Part I of the 'Project .]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE of the psychical systems;
1
21
the elements of the system Cs. would
only energy capable of free discarry no bound energy charge. It seems best, however, to express oneself as cautiously as possible on these points. None the less, this speculation will have enabled us to bring the origin of consciousness into some
but
sort of connection
with the situation of the system Cs. and with must be ascribed to the excitatory processes
the peculiarities that taking place in it.
But we have more to say of the living vesicle with its receptive This little fragment of living substance is sus-
cortical layer.
pended in the middle of an external world charged with the most powerful energies; and it would be killed by the stimulation
emanating from these
protective
way:
if it
were not provided with a
shield against stimuli. It acquires the shield in this
outermost surface ceases to have the structure proper to
its
becomes to some degree inorganic and thenceforward functions as a special envelope or membrane resistant to stimuli. In consequence, the energies of the external world living matter,
are able to pass into the next underlying layers, which have
remained
with only a fragment of their original in-
living,
and these layers can devote themselves, behind the protective shield, to the reception of the amounts of stimulus which have been allowed through it. By its death, the outer tensity;
layer has saved all the deeper ones from a similar fate unless, that is to say, stimuli reach it which are so strong that they break through the protective shield. Protection against stimuli is
an almost more important function for the living organism than reception (^stimuli.
store of energy
special
The protective shield
and must above
all
is
supplied with
its
own
endeavour to preserve the
modes of transformation of energy operating in it against
the effects threatened
by the enormous energies at work in the which tend towards a levelling out of them and hence towards destruction. The main purpose of the external world
reception
effects
of stimuli
external stimuli;
is
to discover the direction
and
for that
it is
enough
and nature of the
to take small speci-
mens of the external world,
to sample it in small quantities. In highly developed organisms the receptive cortical layer of the former vesicle has long been withdrawn into the depths of 1
Breuer and Freud, 1895. [See Section 2 of Breuer's theoretical con-
tribution,
and in particular the footnote at the beginning of 1 on p. 2 above.]
Cf. also footnote
that section.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
22
the interior of the body, though portions of it have been left behind on the surface immediately beneath the general shield
These are the sense organs, which consist against stimuli. the reception of certain specific essentially of apparatus for but which also include special arrange-
effects of stimulation,
ments for further protection against excessive amounts of stimu1 lation and for excluding unsuitable kinds of stimuli, It is characteristic of them that they deal only with very small quantities of external stimulation and only take in samples of the external
world,
They may perhaps be compared with
the time
all
making
feelers
which are
tentative advances towards the external
world and then drawing back from it. At this point I shall venture to touch for a subject
a
result
moment upon a which would merit the most exhaustive treatment. As
of certain psycho-analytic discoveries, we are to-day in a embark on a discussion of the Kantian theorem that
position to
time and space are 'necessary forms of thought'. We have learnt 1 that unconscious mental processes are in themselves 'timeless 2 .
This means in the
place that they are not ordered temporally, that time does not change them in any way and that the first
idea of time cannot be applied to them. These are negative characteristics is
which can only be
made with conscious mental
clearly understood if a processes.
comparison
On the other hand, our
abstract idea of time seems to be wholly derived from -the method of working of the system Pcpt.-Cs. and to correspond to its own part of that method of working. This mode of functioning may perhaps constitute another way of providing a shield against stimuli. I know that these remarks
a perception on
must sound very obscure, but I must limit myself to these We have pointed out how the living vesicle is
hints. 3
provided with
a shield against stimuli from the external world; and we had shown that the cortical layer next to that shield must
previously
be differentiated as an organ for receiving stimuli from without. This sensitive cortex, however, which is later to become the system Cs., also receives excitations from within. The situation of the system between the outside and the inside and the differi 1
1
[a
Troject', Part I, Sections 5 and 9.] of 'The Unconscious' [See Section (1915).]
V
[Freud recurs to the origin of the idea of time at the end of his paper
on "The Mystic Writing-Pad'
(1925a). The same paper -contains a further discussion of the 'shield against stimuli'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
23
ence between the conditions governing the reception of excitations in the two cases have a decisive effect on the functioning of
and of the whole mental apparatus. Towards the shielded against stimuli, and the amounts of excitation impinging on it have only a reduced effect. Towards the in-
the system outside
it is
side there
can be no such
1
shield;
the excitations in the deeper and in undiminished
layers extend into the system directly
amount, in so far as certain of
their characteristics give rise to
pleasure-unpleasure series. The excitations coming from within are, however, in their intensity and in in their amplitude, perhaps more other, qualitative, respects in
feelings
the
commensurate with the system's method of working than the 2 stimuli which stream in from the external world. This state of things produces
two definite results. First, the feelings of pleasure
and unpleasure (which are an index to what is happening in the interior of the apparatus)
predominate over all external
stimuli.
And
secondly, a particular way is adopted of dealing with any internal excitations which produce too great an increase of unpleasure: there is a tendency to treat them as though they
were it
acting, not
from the
inside,
but from the outside, so that
may be possible to bring the shield against stimuli into opera-
tion as a projection,
I
means of defence against them. This is the origin of which is destined to play such a large part in the
have an impression that these
last considerations
have
brought us to a better understanding of the dominance of the pleasure principle; but no light has yet been thrown on the cases that contradict that dominance. Let us therefore go a step describe as 'traumatic' any excitations from outside further.
We
which are powerful enough to break through the protective shield. It seems to me that the concept of trauma necessarily implies a connection of this kind with a breach in an otherwise efficacious barrier against stimuli. Such an event as an external
trauma
is
bound
to provoke
a disturbance on a large and te-set in
scale in the functioning of the organism's energy
motion every possible defensive measure. At the same time, the out of action. There is principle is for the moment put pleasure
no longer any
possibility
of preventing the mental apparatus
from being flooded with large amounts of stimulus, and another i
5
of Section 10 of Part
[Cf. 'Project , beginning of Section [Cf. 'Project', later part
4
of Part
I.]
I.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
24
the problem of mastering the amounts problem of stimulus which have broken in and of binding them, in the so that they can then be disposed of. psychical sense, arises instead
The
specific
unpleasure of physical pain
is probably the having been broken through in a then a continuous stream of excitations
result of the protective shield
limited area. There
is
from the part of the periphery concerned
to
the central
apparatus of the mind, such as could normally arise only from 1 within the apparatus. And how shall we expect the mind to react to this invasion? Gathectic energy
is
summoned from
sides to provide sufficiently high cathexes of
environs of the breach.
An
'anticathexis'
all
energy in the
on a grand
scale
is
set
all the other psychical systems are imup, for whose benefit so that the remaining psychical functions are extenpoverished, must endeavour to draw a sively paralysed or reduced.
We
lesson
from examples such
as this
and use them
our metapsychological speculations.
From
as a basis for
the present case,
which is itself highly cathected is we capable of taking up an additional stream of fresh inflowing energy and of converting it into quiescent cathexis, that is of infer that a system
then,
binding
it
psychically.
The
higher the system's
cathexis, the greater seems to
therefore, the lower
its
be
own
quiescent
its
binding force; conversely, cathexis, the less capacity will it have for
2 taking up inflowing energy and the more violent must be the consequences of such a breach in the protective shield against
stimuli.
To
this
view
increase of cathexis
it
cannot be justly objected that the
round the breach can be explained
far
more
simply as the direct result of the inflowing masses of excitation. If that were so, the mental apparatus
would merely receive an
cathexes of energy, and the paralysing character of pain and the impoverishment of all the other systems would increase in
its
remain unexplained. Nor do the very violent phenomena of discharge to which pain gives rise affect our explanation, for they occur in a reflex manner that is, they follow without the intervention of the mental apparatus. The indefiniteness of all
our discussions on what we describe as metapsychology is of course due to the fact that we know nothing of the nature of the excitatory process that takes place in the elements of the :
f r!
Cf. 'Instincts
and
their Vicissitudes' (1915s)
[and
Addendum C
Symptoms and Anxiety (192&Q]. [Cf. the 'principle of the insusceptibility to excitation of systems' in a footnote near the end of
of
Inhibitions, 1
Freud, I917i]
uncathected
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE and that we do not
psychical systems,
any hypothesis on the all
subject.
We
feel
25
justified in
framing
are consequently operating
unknown factor, which we are every new formula. It may be reason-
the time with a large
obliged to carry over into ably supposed that this excitatory process can be carried out with energies that vary quantitatively] it may also seem
probable
that
it
has
more than one
for instance).
As a new
quality (in
factor
the nature of amplitude, taken into consideration
we have
Breuer's hypothesis that charges of energy occur in two forms that we have to distinguish between two kinds [see pp. 20-1] so ;
of cathexis of the psychical systems or their elements flowing cathexis
that presses
quiescent cathexis.
a freely
on towards discharge and a
We may
perhaps suspect that the binding of the energy that streams into the mental apparatus consists in its change from a freely flowing into a quiescent state. We may, I think, tentatively venture to regard the common traumatic neurosis as a consequence of an extensive breach being
made
in the protective shield against stimuli. This
would
seem
to reinstate the old, naive theory of shock, in apparent contrast to the later and psychologically more ambitious
theory which attributes aetiological importance not to the effects of mechanical violence but to fright and the threat to life.
These opposing views are not, however, irreconcilable; nor
is
the psycho-analytic view of the traumatic neurosis identical with the shock theory in its crudest form. The latter regards the essence of the shock as being the direct damage to the molecular structure or even to the histological structure of the elements of
the nervous system; whereas
what we seek to understand are the
produced on the organ of the mind by the breach in the shield against stimuli and by the problems that follow in its effects
And we still attribute importance to the element of fright. caused by lack of any preparedness for anxiety, : including lack of hypercathexis of the systems that would be the first train. It is
to receive the stimulus.
Owing
to their
low cathexis those
systems are not in a good position for binding the inflowing amounts of excitation and the consequences of the breach in the protective shield follow all the more easily. It will be seen, then, that preparedness for anxiety
and the hypercathexis of the
receptive systems constitute the last line of defence of the shield against stimuli. In the case of quite a 1
[Cf. footnote
1
on
number of traumas, the
p. 7 above.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
26
between systems that are unprepared and systems that are well prepared through being hypercathected may be a difference
outcome; though where the trauma exceeds a certain limit this factor will no
decisive factor in determining the
a strength of
doubt cease to carry weight. The fulfilment of wishes is, as we know, brought about in a hallucinatory manner by dreams, and under the dominance of the pleasure principle this has become But it is not in the sendee of that principle that
their function.
the dreams of patients suffering from traumatic neuroses lead regularity to the situation in which the
them back with such trauma occurred.
We may
assume, rather, that dreams are
here helping to carry out another task, which must be accombefore the dominance of the pleasure principle can even plished begin. These
dreams are endeavouring to master the stimulus by developing the anxiety whose omission was
retrospectively,
the cause of the traumatic neurosis,
They
thus afford us a view
of a function of the mental apparatus which, though contradict the pleasure principle, it
and seems
to
is
it
does not
nevertheless independent of
be more primitive than the purpose of gaining
and avoiding unpleasure. This would seem to be the place, then,
pleasure
at
which
to
admit for
time an exception to the proposition that dreams are fulfilments of wishes. Anxiety dreams, as I have shown the
first
repeatedly and in detail, offer no such exception.
Nor do
'punishment dreams', for they merely replace the forbidden wish-fulfilment
by the appropriate punishment for it; that is to of guilt which is the reaction
say, they fulfil the wish of the sense to the
1
repudiated impulse.
But
it is
impossible to classify as
dreams we have been discussing which occur in traumatic neuroses, or the dreams during psychowish-fulfilments the
analyses which bring to
hood. They repeat,
memory the psychical traumas of child-
arise, rather,
though
it is
in obedience to the compulsion to
true that in analysis that compulsion
is
* supported by the wish (which is encouraged by 'suggestion') to conjure up what has been forgotten and repressed. Thus it
would seem that the function of dreams, which i
consists in
[Sec The
Interpretation of Dreams (1900a), Standard Ed., 5, 557, and Section 9 of Freud's 'Remarks on the Theory and Practice of Dream-
Interpretation* (1923
was substituted
in 1923 for the
words 'which
not unconscious' which appeared in the earlier editions.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE setting aside
the wishes of the disturbing impulses, function. It
27
any motives that might interrupt sleep, by fulfilling
would not be
possible for
function until the whole of mental
life
is
not their original
them
to perform that
had accepted the domin-
is a 'beyond the pleasure only consistent to grant that there was also a time before the purpose of dreams was the fulfilment of wishes.
ance of the pleasure principle. If there principle',
it is
This would imply no denial of their later function. But if once this general rule has been broken, a further question arises.
May not dreams which, with a view to the psychical binding of traumatic impressions, obey the compulsion to repeat may not such dreams occur outside analysis as well? And the reply can only be a decided affirmative. I
have argued elsewhere 1 that 'war neuroses' (in so far term implies something more than a reference to the
as that
illness's onset) may very well be traumatic neuroses which have been facilitated by a conflict in the ego. The fact to which I have referred on page 6, that a gross
circumstances of the
physical injury caused simultaneously by the trauma diminishes the chances that a neurosis will develop, becomes intelligible if
one bears in mind two
facts
which have been
stressed
by
psycho-analytic research: firstly, that mechanical agitation must be recognized as one of the sources of sexual excitation, 3 and secondly, that painful effect, so
long as they
and
last,
feverish illnesses exercise a powerful
on the
distribution of libido. Thus,
on
the one hand, the mechanical violence of the trauma would liberate a quantity of sexual excitation which, owing to the lack
of preparation for anxiety, would have a traumatic effect; but, on the other hand, the simultaneous physical injury, by calling 3 for a narcissistic hypercathexis of the injured organ,
bind the excess of excitation. libido theory has not yet
It
made
is
also well
would
known, though the
sufficient use
of the
fact, that
such severe disorders in the distribution of libido as melancholia are temporarily brought to an end by intercurrent organic illness, and indeed that even a fully developed condition of
dementia praecox
is
capable of a temporary remission in these
same circumstances. 1 2
Sec
my introduction
(I919t/) to Psycho- Analysis and the
War
Neuroses,
remarks elsewhere (Three Essays [Standard Ed., 7, 201-2; /,?.!., 57, 67-5]) on the effect of swinging and railway-travel. 1 See my paper on narcissism (191
THE fact that the cortical layer which receives stimuli is without any protective as
its
shield against excitations
from within must have
result that these latter transmissions
of stimulus have a
preponderance in economic importance and often occasion economic disturbances comparable with traumatic neuroses. The most abundant sources of this internal excitation are what are described as the organism's 'instincts'
the representatives
of all the forces originating in the interior of the body and transmitted to the mental apparatusat once the most important and the most obscure element of psychological research. perhaps not be thought too rash to suppose that the
It will
impulses arising from the instincts do not belong to the type of bound nervous processes but of freely mobile processes which
The best part of what we know of these derived from our study of the dream- work. there
press towards discharge.
processes
is
We
discovered that the processes in the unconscious systems were fundamentally different from those in the preconscious (or conscious) systems. In the unconscious, cathexes can easily be
completely transferred, displaced and condensed. Such treatment, however, could produce only invalid results if it were applied to preconscious material;
and
this
accounts for the
familiar peculiarities exhibited
by manifest dreams after the of the preceding day have been worked
preconscious residues over in accordance with the laws operating in the unconscious. I described the type of process found in the unconscious as the 1
'primary psychical process, in contradistinction to the 'secondary* process which life.
Since
is
the one obtaining in our normal waking impulses have the unconscious systems
all instinctual
of impact, it is hardly an innovation to say that they obey the primary process. Again, it is easy to identify as their point
the
primary psychical process with Breuer's freely mobile and the secondary process with changes in his bound or tonic cathexis. 1 If so, it would be the task of the higher strata of cathexis
the mental apparatus to bind the instinctual excitation reaching 1
a. my Interpretation
Cf. also
of Dreams, Chapter VII [Standard Ed., 5, 588 ff. Breuer and Freud, 1895 (Section 2 of Breuer's theoretical con-
tribution)].
28
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
A
the primary process.
29
binding would a traumatic neurosis; and
failure to effect this
provoke a disturbance analogous to only after the binding has been accomplished would possible
for the
dominance of the pleasure
it
be
principle (and of its
modification, the reality principle) to proceed unhindered. Till then the other task of the mental apparatus, the task of master-
ing or binding excitations, would have precedence not, indeed, in opposition to the pleasure principle, but independently of it
some extent in disregard of it. manifestations of a compulsion to repeat (which we have described as occurring in the early activities of infantile mental and
to
The
life
as well as
among
the events of psycho-analytic treatment)
* exhibit to a high degree an instinctual character and, when they act in opposition to the pleasure principle, give the appear-
ance of some 'daemonic' force at work. In the case of children's
we seemed to see that children repeat unpleasurable the additional reason that they can master a experiences for play
active than powerful impression far more thoroughly by being they could by merely experiencing it passively. Each fresh to strengthen the mastery they are in search of. repetition seems
Nor can
children have their pleasurable experiences repeated and they are inexorable in their insistence that
often enough,
the repetition shall be an identical one, This character trait for a second time it disappears later on. If a joke is heard
produces almost no
effect;
a theatrical production never creates
an impression the second time as the first; indeed, it is has very much enjoyed hardly possible to persuade an adult who
so great
reading a book to re-read it immediately. Novelty is always the condition of enjoyment. But children will never tire of asking
an adult
to repeat a
with them,
till
he
is
game
that he has
shown them or played
too exhausted to go on.
And
if
a child has
on hearing it over and over he will remorselessly stipulate again rather than a new one; and that the repetition shall be an identical one and will correct any
been told a nice
story,
he will
insist
alterations ofwhich the narrator maybe guilty
actually have been
though they may
made in the hope of gaining fresh approval*
> and at the beginning of the next paragraph. The ['Triebkaft' here word 'TritV bears much more of a feeling of urgency than the English
'instinct'.] * towards the end of the [Cf. some remarks on this Chapter VII of Freud's book on jokes (1905*).]
sixth section of
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
30
None of
the pleasure principle; repetition, the re-experiencing of something identical, is clearly in itself a source of pleasure. In the case of a person in analysis, this contradicts
on the contrary, the compulsion to repeat the events of his childhood in the transference evidently disregards the pleasure principle in ev^ry way. The patient behaves in a purely infantile fashion and thus shows us that the repressed memory-traces of
primaeval experiences are not present in him in a bound and are indeed in a sense incapable of obeying the secondary process. It is to this fact of not being bound, moreover, that his
state
they
owe
their capacity for forming, in conjunction with the
residues of the previous day, a wishful phantasy that emerges
in a dream. This
same compulsion
we
meets us
to repeat frequently
an obstacle to our treatment when
as
at the
end of an
analysis
try to induce the patient to detach himself completely
from
may be presumed, too, that when people una dread of rousing familiar with analysis feel an obscure fear his physician. It
something that, so they feel, is better left sleeping what they are afraid of at bottom is the emergence of this compulsion with its hint of possession by some 'daemonic' power.
But how is the predicate of being 'instinctual' related to the compulsion to repeat? At this point we cannot escape a suspicion that we may have come upon the track of a universal attribute l
instincts and perhaps of organic life in general which has not hitherto been clearly recognized or at least not explicitly 2 stressed. It seems, then t that an instinct is an urge inherent in
of
organic
to restore
life
an
earlier state
of things which the living entity has
been obliged to abandon under the pressure of external disturbing forces; that is, it is a kind of organic elasticity, or, to it
put
another way, the expression of the inertia inherent in
organic
life.
3
This view of instincts
become used and
to see in
strikes us as
strange because
we have
them a
factor impelling towards change development, whereas we are now asked to recognize in
them the
an expression of the conservative precise contrary nature of living substance. On the other hand we soon call to
mind examples from animal 1
life
which seem to confirm the
[Sec the last footnote but one.]
*
[The last six words were added in 1921.] have no doubt that similar notions as to the nature of have already been put fonvard repeatedly. *
I
'instincts'
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
31
view that instincts are historically determined. Certain fishes, for instance, undertake laborious migrations at spawning-time in order to deposit their spawn in particular waters far removed
from their customary haunts. In the opinion of many biologists what they are doing is merely to seek out the localities in which their species formerly resided
but which in the course of time
they have exchanged for others.
The same explanation is believed to apply to the migratory flights of birds of passagebut we are quickly relieved of the necessity for seeking for further examples by the reflection that the most impressive proofs of there being
an organic compulsion
phenomena of heredity and the how the germ of a living animal
to repeat lie in the of embryology. We see obliged in the course of its
facts is
development to recapitulate (even
if only in a transient and abbreviated fashion) the structures of all the forms from which it is sprung, instead of proceeding quickly by the shortest
to
its
final shape.
This behaviour
is
attributable to mechanical causes,
path only to a very slight degree
and the
historical explana-
tion cannot accordingly
be neglected. So too the power of regenerating a lost organ by growing afresh a precisely similar one extends far up into the animal kingdom.
We
shall be met by the plausible objection that it may very well be that, in addition to the conservative instincts which impel
towards repetition, there may be others which push forward towards progress and the production of new forms. This argument must certainly not be overlooked, and it will be taken into account at a later stage. 1 But for the moment it is tempting to pursue to its logical conclusion the hypothesis that all instincts tend towards the restoration of an earlier state of things. The
outcome may give an impression of mysticism or of sham profundity; but we can feel quite innocent of having had any such purpose in view. We seek only for the sober results of research or of reflection based on it; and we have no wish to find in those results
any quality other than
3
certainty.
Let us suppose, then, that
all
the organic instincts are
conservative, are acquired historically
and tend towards the
half of this sentence was added in 1921,] [The a [Footnote added 1925:] The reader should not overlook the fact that what follows is the development of an extreme line of thought. last
Later on,
when account
is
taken of the sexual
that the necessary limitations
instincts, it will
and corrections are applied
to
be found
it.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
32
restoration of an earlier state of things. It follows that the pheno-
mena
of organic development must be attributed to external
influences. The elementary living very beginning have had no wish to remained the same, it would do no more change; if conditions than constantly repeat the same course of life. In the last resort,
disturbing entity
and diverting
would from
what has
left its
its
mark on
the history of the earth
the development of organisms must be live in and of its relation to the sun.
we
Every modification which
is
thus imposed
upon the course of
the organism's life is accepted by the conservative organic instincts and stored up for further repetition. Those instincts are
bound to give a deceptive appearance of being forces and progress, whilst in fact they are tending towards change merely seeking to reach an ancient goal by paths alike old and therefore
this final goal of all it is possible to specify be in contradiction to the conservaorganic striving. It would tive nature of the instincts if the goal of life were a state of
new. Moreover
things
which had never yet been attained. On the contrary, it old state of things, an initial state from which the
must be an
living entity has at it is
one time or other departed and to which by the circuitous paths along which its
striving to return
development leads. If we are to take
it
as
a truth that knows no
exception that everything living dies for internal reasonsbecomes inorganic once again then we shall be compelled to say that
'the
aim of all
life
is death.'
and, looking backwards, that
'inanimate things existed before living ones'.
The
attributes of life
were at some time evoked in inanimate
matter by the action of a force of whose nature we can form no conception. It may perhaps have been a process similar in type to that
which later caused the development of consciousness in a The tension which then
particular stratum of living matter.
arose in
what had hitherto been an inanimate substance endeav-
oured to cancel
itself out.
In
this
way the first instinct came into
being: the instinct to return to the inanimate state. It
was
still
an easy matter at that time for a living substance to die; the course of its life was probably only a brief one, whose direction was determined by the chemical structure of the young life. For a long time, perhaps, living substance was thus being constantly created afresh and easily dying, till decisive external influences altered in such a
way
as to oblige the
substance to diverge ever more widely from
its
still
surviving
original course
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE of
and
life
reaching
its
make ever more complicated
to
33
before
detours
aim of death. These circuitous paths to death,
fully kept to
by the conservative
us to-day with the picture of the
faith-
would thus present
instincts,
phenomena of
life.
If
we
firmly maintain the exclusively conservative nature of instincts,
we cannot
arrive at
any other notions
as to the origin
and aim
of life.
The
implications in regard to the great groups of instincts
we
which, as
believe, lie
behind the phenomena of
organisms must appear no
less
self-preservative instincts,
such as
beings, stands in
bewildering,
we
marked opposition
The
life
in
hypothesis of
attribute to all living
to the idea that instinctual
as a whole serves to bring about death. Seen in this light, the theoretical importance of the instincts of self-preservation, of self-assertion and of mastery greatly diminishes. They are life
component
instincts
whose function
it
is
to assure that the
organism shall follow its own path to death, and to ward off any possible ways of returning to inorganic existence other than those which are
immanent
in the organism
itself.
We
have no
longer to reckon with the organism's puzzling determination (so hard to fit into any context) to maintain its own existence in the face of every obstacle.
What we
are
left
with
is
the fact that the
organism wishes to die only in its own fashion. Thus these guardians of life, too, were originally the myrmidons of death.
Hence
the paradoxical situation that the living organism most energetically against events (dangers, in fact) which might help it to attain its life's aim rapidly by a kind of arises
struggles
short-circuit.
acterizes efforts.
But
The
Such behaviour
purely instinctual
is,
as
however, precisely what charcontrasted with intelligent
1
let us
pause for a
moment and
reflect It
cannot be
so.
sexual instincts, to which the theory of the neuroses gives
a quite special place, appear under a very different aspect The external pressure which provokes a constantly increasing extent
of development has not imposed
itself
upon
every
organism. Many have succeeded in remaining up to the present time at their lowly level. Many, though not allj such creatures,
which must resemble the
earliest stages
of the higher animals
at this [In the editions before 1925 the following footnote appeared the self-preservative instincts point. 'A correction of this extreme view of
Mows.']
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
34
and
In the same way, the whole
plants, are, indeed, living to-day.
path of development to natural death
is
not trodden by
all
the
elementary entities which compose the complicated body of one of the higher organisms. Some of them, the germ-cells, probably retain the original structure of living matter and, after
a certain
complement of inherited and freshly dispositions, separate themselves from the
time, with their full
acquired instinctual organism as a whole. These two characteristics may be precisely what enables them to have an independent existence. Under
favourable conditions, they begin to develop that is, to repeat the performance to which they owe their existence; and in the
end once again one portion of their substance pursues its development to a finish, while another portion harks back once again as a fresh residual germ to the beginning of the process of development. These germ-cells, therefore, work against the death of the living substance and succeed in winning for it
what we can only regard as potential immortality, though that may mean no more than a lengthening of the road to death.
We
must regard
as in the highest
that this function of the germ-cell possible, if it coalesces with
differing
The
from
degree significant the fact is
another
reinforced, or only
cell similar to itself
it.
instincts
which watch over the
destinies of these
tary organisms that survive the whole individual,
them with a
made
and yet
safe shelter while
stimuli of the external world,
elemen-
which provide
they are defenceless against the
which bring about their meeting on these constitute the group of
with other germ-cells, and so the sexual instincts. They are conservative in the
same
sense
as the
other instincts in that they bring back earlier states of living substance; but they are conservative to a higher degree in that they are peculiarly resistant to external influences; and
they are conservative too in another sense in that they preserve 1 for a comparatively long period. They are the true
life itself
life instincts.
They operate against the purpose of the other leads, by reason of their function, to death; and this fact indicates that there is an opposition between them and the other instincts, an opposition whose importance was long instincts,
which
ago recognized by the theory of the neuroses. i
It
is
as
though the
them alone that we can attribute an internal impulse towards 'progress' and towards higher development! [Footnote added 1923:]
(See below [pp. 42-3].)
Yet
it is
to
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
35
of the organism moved with a vacillating rhythm. One group of instincts rushes forward so as to reach the final aim
life
of life as swiftly as possible; but when a particular stage in the advance has been reached, the other group jerks back to a certain point to
make a
And even though
it is
fresh start
and so prolong the journey. and the distinction
certain that sexuality
sexes did not exist when life began, the possibility remains that the instincts which were later to be described as
between the
may have been in operation from the very first, and it may not be true that it was only at a later time that they started
sexual
upon their work of opposing the Let us
now hark back
whether there
is
any
for
a
activities
moment
of the 'ego-instincts'. 1 and consider
ourselves
basis at all for these speculations. Is
really the case that, apart from the sexual instincts,* there are instincts that
do not seek to
that there are
none that aim at a
restore
an
earlier state
state of things
it
no
of things?
which has never
yet been attained? I know of no certain example from the organic world that would contradict the characterization I have thus proposed. There is unquestionably no universal instinct towards higher development observable in the animal or plant world, even though it is undeniable that development does in fact occur in that direction.
But on the one hand
it is
often
merely a matter of opinion when we declare that one stage of development is higher than another, and on the other hand biology teaches us that higher development in one respect is very frequently balanced or outweighed by involution in another. Moreover there are plenty of animal forms from whose early stages we can infer that their development has, on the contrary, assumed a retrograde character. Both higher develop-
ment and
involution might well be the consequences of adapta-
tion to the pressure of external forces; and in both cases the part played by instincts might be limited to the retention {in
the form of an internal source of pleasure) of an obligatory modification, 8 1
[Footnote added 1925:] It should be understood from the context that the term 'ego-instincts' is used here as a provisional description and derives from the earliest psycho-analytical terminology. [See below,
pp. 44-5 and 55.] 1
*
[These five words were italicized from 1921 onwards.] Ferenczi (1913, 137) has reached the same conclusion along differ-
ent lines: 'If this thought is pursued to its logical conclusion, one must make oneself familiar with the idea of a tendency to perseveration or
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
36 It
may be
that there beings,
difficult, too, for
an
is
instinct
many of us,
to
abandon the
towards perfection at work in
belief
human
which has brought them to their present high level of achievement and ethical sublimation and which
intellectual
may be men.
I
expected to watch over their development into superfaith, however, in the existence of any such
have no
and
internal instinct is
to be preserved.
I
cannot see
The
how
this
benevolent illusion
present development of
human
beings
seems to me, no different explanation from that of animals. What appears in a minority of human individuals as
requires, as
it
an untiring impulsion towards further perfection can easily be understood as a result of the instinctual repression upon which is
based
all
that
is
most precious in
human
civilization.
The
repressed instinct never ceases to strive for complete satisfaction, which would consist in the repetition of a primary
experience
of satisfaction.
No
substitutive or reactive formations
and no
sublimations will suffice to remove the repressed instinct's is the difference in amount between persisting tension; and it the pleasure of satisfaction which is demanded and that which is actually achieved that provides the driving factor which will
permit of no halting at any position attained, but, in the poet's 1 words, 'ungebandigt immer vorwarts dringt'. The backward path that leads to complete satisfaction is as a rule obstructed by the resistances which maintain the repressions. So there is no alternative but to advance in the direction in which growth is
freethough with no prospect of bringing the process to a conclusion or of being able to reach the goal. The processes involved in the formation of a neurotic phobia, which is still
nothing than an attempt at flight from the satisfaction of an instinct, a with model of the manner of origin of this suppresent us else
posititious 'instinct
towards perfection'
not possibly be attributed to every conditions for
but
its
development
an
human
instinct
being.
which can-
The
dynamic
are, indeed, universally present;
only in rare cases that the economic situation appears production of the phenomenon.
it is
to favour the I will
add only a word
to suggest that the efforts of Eros to
regression dominating organic life as well, while the tendency to further as a result development, to adaptation, etc., would become active
only
of external stimuli.
1
!,'|
l !
J
[Tresses ever forward unsubdued.'] Mephistopheles in Faust, Part
[Scene 4].
I
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE combine organic substances into ever larger
unities
37
probably
provide a substitute for this 'instinct towards perfection' whose we cannot admit. The phenomena that are attributed
existence to
it
seem capable of explanation by
these efforts of Eros taken
in conjunction with the results of repression. 1 1 [This paragraph, which was added in 1923, anticipates the account of Eros that is to follow in the next chapter, p. 44 ff.]
VI
THE upshot of our enquiry so far has been the drawing of a sharp distinction between the 'ego-instincts' and the sexual instincts, and the view that the former exercise pressure towards death and the latter towards a prolongation of life. But this conclusion is bound to be unsatisfactory in many respects even to ourselves.
Moreover, it is actually only of the former group of we can predicate a conservative, or rather retro-
instincts that
grade, character corresponding to a compulsion to repeat. For on our hypothesis the ego-instincts arise from the coming to life of inanimate matter and seek to restore the inanimate state;
whereas as regards the sexual
though
instincts,
it is
true that
they reproduce primitive states of the organism, what they are clearly aiming at by every possible means is the coalescence of two germ-cells which are differentiated in a particular way. If this union is not effected, the germ-cell dies along with all the
other elements of the multicellular organism. It is only on this condition that the sexual function can prolong the cell's life and
lend
it the appearance of immortality. But what is the important event in the development of living substance which is being repeated in sexual reproduction, or in its fore-runner, the con-
jugation of two protista?
1
We cannot say;
and we should con-
sequently feel relieved if the whole structure of our argument turned out to be mistaken. The opposition between the ego or
death
* and the sexual or life instincts would then cease and the compulsion to repeat would no longer possess
instincts
to hold
the importance we have ascribed to it. Let us turn back, then, to one of the
assumptions that
we
have already made, with the expectation that we shall be able to give it a categorical denial. We have drawn
far-reaching conclusions from the hypothesis that all living substance is bound to die from internal causes. made this
We
tion. 1
We
assumption
are accustomed to think that such
pn what follows Freud appears
to use the
is
the fact, and
tozoa' indifferently to signify unicellular organisms. follows the original,]
*
(The
first
we
terms 'protista' and 'pro-
published appearance of the term.]
The
translation
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
39
are strengthened in our thought by the writings of our poets. Perhaps we have adopted the belief because there is some comfort in
those
it.
who
If
we
are to die ourselves, and
are dearest to us,
it is
to lose in death
first
easier to submit to a remorse-
less law of nature, to the sublime 'Avdyxrj [Necessity], than to a chance which might perhaps have been escaped. It may be,
however, that this belief in the internal necessity of dying is only another of those illusions which we have created 'urn die Schwere des Dasdns QL ertmgen'. 1 It
The notion of
belief.
is
'natural death'
certainly not a primaeval is
quite foreign to primi-
they attribute every death that occurs among them to the influence of an enemy or of an evil spirit. We must tive races;
therefore turn to biology in order to test the validity of the belief.
we may be astonished to find how little agreeamong biologists on the subject of natural death and in fact that the whole concept of death melts away under their hands. The fact that there is a fixed average duration of If we do so,
ment
there
is
at least among the higher animals naturally argues in favour of there being such a thing as death from natural causes. But this impression is countered when we consider that certain large life
animals and certain gigantic arboreal growths reach a very advanced age and one which cannot at present be computed.
According to the large conception of Wilhelm the
phenomena of
life
exhibited
Fliess [1906], all
and
by organism
also,
no
doubt, their death
are linked with the completion of fixed periods, which express the dependence of two kinds of living substance (one male and the other female) upon the solar year.
When we
see,
however,
how
influence of external forces
easily
and how
extensively the
able to modify the date of the appearance of vital phenomena (especially in the plant world) to precipitate
upon
is
them or hold them back
doubts must be cast
the rigidity of Fliess's formulas or at least
the laws laid
The
upon whether
down by him
are the sole determining factors. greatest interest attaches from our point of view to the
treatment given to the subject of the duration of life and the death of organisms in the writings of Weismann (1882, 1884, 1892, etc.) It was he
who
introduced the division of living The mortal part is
substance into mortal and immortal parts. i
[To
1,8.]
bear the burden of existence.'
(Schiller,
Die Braut von Messina,
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
40 the
body
in the
narrower sense
the 'soma'
which alone
is
death. The germ-cells, on the other hand, are subject to natural in so far as they are able, under certain potentially immortal, favourable conditions, to develop into a new individual, or, in
other words, to surround themselves with a
mann,
new soma.
(Weis-
1884.)
What strikes us in this is the unexpected analogy with our own view, which was arrived at along such a different path. Weismann, regarding one portion which
it
living substance morphologically, sees in is
the soma, the body
destined to die
apart from the substance concerned with sex and inheritance and an immortal portion the germ-plasm, which is concerned
with the survival of the species, with reproduction. We, on the other hand, dealing not with the living substance but with the forces operating in it, have been led to distinguish two kinds of instincts: those
which seek
to lead
others, the sexual instincts,
what
is
living to death,
and
which are perpetually attempting
and achieving a renewal of life. This sounds like a dynamic Weismann's morphological theory.
corollary to
But the appearance of a sipated as soon as
significant correspondence
is dis-
we discover Weismann's views on the problem
of death. For he only relates the distinction between the mortal
soma and the immortal germ-plasm to
multicellular
organisms; in
and the reproductive cell one and the same (Weismann, 1882, 38). Thus he con-
unicellular organisms the individual
are
still
siders that unicellular
organisms are potentially immortal, and its appearance with the multicellular
that death only makes
metazoa.
It is true that this death of the higher organisms is a natural one, a death from internal causes; but it is not founded
on any primal characteristic of living substance (Weismann, 1884, 84) and cannot be regarded as an absolute necessity with basis in the very nature of life (Weismann, 1882, 33). Death rather a matter of expediency, a manifestation of adaptation to the external conditions of life; for, when once the cells of the
its
is
body have been divided
into
limited duration of individual less
luxury.
When
this differentiation
had been made in the
became
possible and expedient, soma of the higher organisms has died at fixed
multicellular organisms, death
Since then, the
soma and germ-plasm, an unwould become a quite point-
life
periods for internal reasons, while the protista have remained immortal. It is not the case, on the other hand, that
reproduc-
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE tion
was only introduced
contrary,
it
is
at the
same time
41
as death.
On
a primal characteristic of living matter,
the like
growth (from which it originated) and life has been continuous from its first beginning upon earth. (Weismann, 1884, 84 f.) 3
It will be seen at once that to concede in this way that higher organisms have a natural death is of very little help to us, For if death is a late acquisition of organisms, then there can be no question of there having been death instincts from the very die beginning of life on this earth. Multicellular organisms
may
for internal reasons,
owing to
defective differentiation or to
imperfections in their metabolism, but the matter
is of no from the point of view of our problem. An account of of as is death such this the origin moreover far less at variance
interest
with our habitual modes of thought than the strange assumption of 'death instincts'.
The
discussion
led, so far as I
Some
which followed upon Weismann's suggestions
can
see, to
no
conclusive results in any direction. 1
who reHartmann
writers returned to the views of Goette (1883),
garded death as a direct
result of reproduction,
(1906, 29) does not regard the appearance of a 'dead
dead portion of the
living substance
bod/
a
as the criterion of death,
death as
'the termination of individual but defines development'. In this sense protozoa too are mortal; in their case death always coincides with reproduction, but is to some extent
obscured by it, since the whole substance of the parent animal may be transmitted directly into the young offspring.
Soon afterwards research was directed
to the experimental
on
unicellular organisms of the alleged immortality of living substance. An American biologist, Woodruff, experi-
testing
menting with a ciliate infusorian, the 'slipper-animalcule', which reproduces by fission into two individuals, persisted until the 3029th generation (at which point he broke off the experiment), isolating one of the part-products on each occasion and placing it in fresh water. This remote descendent of the first slipper-animalcule was just as lively as its ancestor and showed no signs of ageing or degeneration. Thus, in so far as figures of this kind prove anything, the immortality of the protista seemed to be experimentally demonstrable. 2
Other experimenters arrived i i
at different results.
Maupas,
Hartmann (1906), Lipschutz (1914) and Doflein (1919). For this and what follows see Lipschutz (1914, 26 and 52 ff.).
Of.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
42
Calkins and others, in contrast to Woodruff, found that after a certain
number of
divisions these infusoria
and eventually
die,
become weaker,
of some part of their organization unless certain recuperative measures are
diminish in size, suffer the
loss
applied to them. If this is so, protozoa would appear to die after a phase of senescence exactly like the higher animalsthus
completely contradicting Weismann's assertion that death late acquisition of living organisms.
From
is
a
the aggregate of these experiments two facts emerge offer us a firm footing.
which seem to First:
If two of the animalculae, at the
moment
before they
show
are able to coalesce with each other, signs of senescence,
that
is
to 'conjugate'
(soon after which they once more
separate), they are saved
juvenated'. Conjugation
from growing old and become 'reno doubt the fore-runner of the
is
sexual reproduction of higher creatures;
it is
as yet unconnected
with propagation and is Hmited to the mixing of the substances of the two individuals. (Weismann's 'amphimixis'.) The recuperative effects of conjugation can, however, be replaced by
by alterations in the composition of the fluid which provides their nourishment, by raising their are reminded of the temperature or by shaking them.
certain stimulating agents,
We
celebrated experiment made by J. Loeb, in which, by means of certain chemicalstimuli, he induced segmentation in sea-urchins'
a process which can normally occur only after fertilization. Secondly: It is probable nevertheless that infusoria die a natural death as a result of their own vital processes. For the
eggs
contradiction between
Woodruffs findings and the others is due
having provided each generation with fresh nutrient fluid. If he omitted to do so, he observed the same signs of senescence as the other experimenters. He concluded that the animalculae to his
were injured by the products of metabolism which they extruded into the surrounding fluid. He was then able to prove conclusively that it was only the products of its own metabolism
which had
fatal results for the particular
kind of animalcule.
For the same animalculae which inevitably perished if they were
crowded together in their own nutrient fluid flourished in a solution which was over-saturated with the waste products of a distantly related species.
An infusorian,
therefore, if it
is left
to
a natural death owing to its incomplete voidance of the products of its own metabolism. (It may be that the same
itself dies
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE is
incapacity
43
the ultimate cause of the death of all higher
animals as well.)
At
this
point the question
may
well arise in our
minds
whether any object whatever is served by trying to solve the death from a study of the protozoa. The problem of natural of these creatures may conceal from our primitive organization
though in fact present in them
conditions which, eyes important too,
only become
visible in, higher
animals where they are able to
And if we abandon the morpho-
find morphological expression.
of view and adopt the dynamic one, it becomes a matter of complete indifference to us whether natural death logical point
can be shown to occur in protozoa or not. The substance which later recognized as being immortal has not yet become
is
separated in them from the mortal one. The instinctual forces which seek to conduct life into death may also be operating in protozoa from the first, and yet their effects may be so completely concealed
by the
life-preserving forces that
may be
it
very hard to find any direct evidence of their presence. seen, moreover, that the observations made by
We have
biologists allow
us to assume that internal processes of this kind leading to death do occur also in protista. But even if protista turned out to be
immortal in Weismann's sense,
would apply only
acquisition
his assertion that
to
its
manifest
death
is
a late
phenomena and
would not make impossible the assumption of processes
tending
towards it
Thus our expectation that biology would flatly contradict the recognition of death instincts has not been fulfilled. We are at liberty to continue concerning ourselves with their possibility,
we have other reasons for doing so. The striking similarity between Weismann's distinction of soma and germ-plasm and if
our separation of the death persists
and
instincts
from the
life
instincts
retains its significance.
We may pause for a moment over this pre-eminently dualistic view of instinctual life. According to E. Bering's theory, two kinds of processes are constantly at work in living substance, operating in contrary directions, one constructive or assimilatory
and the other
destructive or dissimilatory.
May we
venture to recognize in these two directions taken by the vital processes the activity of our two instinctual impulses, the life instincts and the death instincts? There is something else, at any rate, that
we cannot remain
blind to.
We
have unwittingly
-
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
44
harbour of Schopenhauer's philo-
steered our course into the
him death is the 'true result and to that extent the sophy. For 1 while the sexual instinct is the embodiment of purpose of life', live. [Cf. the Appendix to Freud, 1925*.] Let us make a bold attempt at another step forward. It is considered that the union of a number of cells into generally
the will to
a
the multicellular character of
vital association
has become a means of prolonging their preserve
the
of another, and the
life
life.
One
organismscell
community of
survive even if individual cells have to die.
helps to cells
can
We
have already heard that conjugation, too, the temporary coalescence of two unicellular organisms, has a life-preserving and rejuvenating
on both of them. Accordingly, we might attempt to apply the libido theory which has been arrived at in psycho-analysis to the mutual relationship of cells. might suppose that the life
effect
We
instincts or sexual instincts
other
cell
take the
that they partly neutralize the death the processes set up by them) in those cells their life; while the other cells do the same for
cells as their object,
instincts (that
is,
and thus preserve them, and still others
sacrifice
a completely
themselves in the performance of
germ-cells themselves would behave to use the phrase that we 'narcissistic' fashion
this libidinal function.
in
which are active in each
The
are accustomed to use in the theory of the neuroses to describe his libido in his ego and pays none of it out in object-cathexes. The germ-cells require their
a whole individual who retains
libido, the activity
of their
reserve against their later
life instincts,
momentous
for themselves, as a
constructive activity.
(The cells of the malignant neoplasms which destroy the organism should also perhaps be described as narcissistic in this
same
sense: pathology
innate
and
is
prepared to regard their germs as 2 In this way
to ascribe embryonic attributes to them.)
the libido of our sexual instincts the poets
would coincide with the Eros
and philosophers which holds
Here then
is
an opportunity
of
all living things together.
for looking
back over the slow
development of our libido theory. In the analysis of the transference neuroses forced
first
instance the
upon our
notice the
opposition between the 'sexual instincts', which are directed
towards an object, and certain other instincts, with which we were very insufficiently acquainted and which we described i
a
Schopenhauer (1851; SariBdu Werke, ed, Hiibscher, 1938, 5, 236). [This sentence was added in 1921.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE 1
45
A
as the 'ego-instincts'. foremost place among provisionally these was necessarily given to the instincts serving the self-
of the individual. It was impossible to say what preservation other distinctions were to be drawn among them. No know-
more valuable as a foundation for ledge would have been true psychological science than an approximate grasp of the
common
characteristics
and
possible distinctive features of the
But in no region of psychology were we groping more in the dark. Everyone assumed the existence of as many instincts
instincts.
or 'basic instincts' as he chose, and juggled with them like the ancient Greek natural philosophers with their four elements earth, air, fire
and water. Psycho-analysis, which could not
the instincts, kept at first escape making some assumption about to the popular division of instincts typified in the phrase 'hunger arid love'. At least there was nothing arbitrary in this; and by its
help the analysis of the psychoneuroses was carried forward
of 'sexuality', and at the same quite a distance. The concept time of the sexual instinct, had, it is true, to be extended so as
many things which could not be classed under the reproductive function; and this caused no little hubbub in an austere, respectable or merely hypocritical world. to cover
The
next step was taken
when
psycho-analysis felt
closer towards die psychological ego,
know only as
which
it
had
first
its way come to
a repressive, censoring agency, capable of erecting
protective structures
seeing minds had,
and
it is
reactive formations. Critical
true, long since objected to the
and
far-
concept
of libido being restricted to the energy of the sexual instincts directed towards an object. But they failed to explain how they
had arrived
at their better knowledge or to derive
from
it
anything of which analysis could make use. Advancing more cautiously, psycho-analysis observed the regularity with which libido
is
withdrawn from the object and directed on
to the ego
the libidinal (the process of introversion); and, by studying of children in its earliest phases, came to the con-
development
clusion that the ego 1
is
the true and original reservoir of libido,*
[So, for instance, in the
account of this opposition given in Freud's
paper on psychogenic disturbances of vision (I910t).] narcissism [This idea was fully stated by Freud in his paper on near the beginning (1914s), Section I. See, however, his later footnote, of Chapter III of The Ego and the Id (1923*), in which he corrects this statement and describes the id as 'the great reservoir of libido'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
46
and that to
it is
objects.
that libido only from that reservoir
The ego now found
its
is
extended on
among sexual place among them.
position
and was at once given the foremost Libido which was in this way lodged in the ego was described 1 as 'narcissistic'. This narcissistic libido was of course also a
objects
manifestation of the force of the sexual instinct in the analytical
and
sense of those words,
it
had
necessarily to be identified with
the 'self-preservative instincts' whose existence had been recognized from the first. Thus the original opposition between the
and the sexual instincts proved to be inadequate. of the ego-instincts was seen to be libidinal; sexual probably alongside others operated in the ego.
ego-instincts
A portion instincts
Nevertheless
we
which
down
it
lays
are justified in saying that the old formula that psychoneuroses are based
and sexual
between
ego-instincts
we need
reject to-day. It
is
on a
conflict
instincts contains
nothing that merely that the distinction between
the two kinds of instinct, which
was originally regarded
as in
way qualitative^ must now be characterized differentlynamely as being topographical. And in particular it is still
some
sort of
true that the transference neuroses, the essential subject of
are the result of a conflict between the psycho-analytic study, ego and the libidinal cathexis of objects.
But
it is all
the
more necessary
for us to lay stress
libidinal character of the self-prese'rvative instincts
are venturing
upon the
upon
the
now that we
further step of recognizing the sexual
instinct a? Eros, the preserver of all things,
and of deriving the
ego from the stores of libido by means of the soma are attached to one another. But
narcissistic libido of the
of which the
we now
cells
by another question. If the self-preservative instincts too are of a libidinal nature, are there perhaps no other instincts whatever but the libidinal ones?
At
all
find ourselves suddenly faced
events there are none other visible. But in that case
shall after all
be driven to agree with the
critics
who
we
suspected
from the first that psycho-analysis explains everything by sexuality, or with innovators like Jung who, making a hasty judgement, have used the word 'libido' to mean instinctual force in general.
Must not It
this
be so?
was not our
intention at all
Our argument had
events to produce such a result,
point of departure a sharp distinction between ego-instincts, which we equated with death instincts, 1
Sec
as
its
my paper on
narcissism (1914c) [Section I].
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE and sexual
were prepared at preservative
instincts of the
we subsequently withdrew
47
which we equated with life instincts. (We one stage [p. 33] to include the so-called self-
instincts,
it,)
ego
among the death
[p, 46] corrected ourselves
Our
views have from the very
on
instincts;
this point
first
been
but
and
dualistict
and to-day they are even more definitely dualistic than before now that we describe the opposition as being, not between egoinstincts
and sexual
but between
instincts
life
instincts
and
death instincts. Jung's libido theory is on the contrary mnistic; the fact that he has called his one instinctual force 'libido' is
bound to cause confusion, but need not
affect us otherwise. 1
We
than those of self-preservation opersuspect that instincts other ate in the ego, and it ought to be possible for us to point to them. Unfortunately, however, the analysis of the ego has made so little
headway that
very difficult for us to do
it is
so. It is possible, in-
deed, that the libidinal instincts in the ego may be linked in a 2 these other ego-instincts which are still peculiar manner with
Even before we had any deaf understanding of had a suspicion that the 'ego-in-
strange to us.
narcissism, psycho-analysts stincts'
had libidinal components attached to them. But these are to which our opponents will possibilities, pay very
very uncertain
attention. The difficulty remains that psycho-analysis has not enabled us hitherto to point to any [ego-] instincts other than the libidinal ones. That, however, is no reason for our falling in little
with the conclusion that no others in fact
exist.
In the obscurity that reigns at present in the theory of the instincts, it would be unwise to reject any idea that promises to
throw
light
between the
on
it.
We
started out
and death
life
from the great opposition
instincts.
Now
object-love itself
presents us with a second
between love (or
example of a similar polarity that affection) and hate (or aggressiveness). If only
we could succeed
in relating these
two
polarities to
each other
one from the other! From the very first we recognized the presence of a sadistic component in the sexual 3 instinct. As we know, it can make itself independent and can,
and
in deriving
in the
form of a perversion, dominate an individual's entire
1
[The two preceding sentences were added in 1921.] ' [In the first edition only: by instinctual "confluence", to borrow a term used by Adler [1908]-'.] 1
*
This was already so in the
first
of Sexuality in 1905 [Standard Ed.,
edition of Three Essays on the Theory
7,
157
ff.;
I.P.L, 57, 23 ft].
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
48
sexual activizy. It also emerges as a predominant component instinct in one of the 'pregenital organizations', as I have
named them. But how can
the sadistic instinct,
whose aim
it is
from Eros, the preserver of life? Is it not plausible to suppose that this sadism is in fact a death instinct which, under the influence of the narcissistic libido, has
to injure the object, be derived
been forced away from the ego and has consequently only
emerged in
relation to the object? It
now
enters the service of
the sexual function. During the oral stage of organization of the over an object coinlibido, the act of obtaining erotic mastery cides with that object's destruction; later, the sadistic instinct
at the stage of genital primacy, it takes separates off, and finally, of overpoweron, for the purposes of reproduction, the function
the extent necessary for carrying out the ing the sexual object to sexual act. It might indeed be said that the sadism which has
been forced out of the ego has pointed the way for the libidinal components of the sexual instinct, and that these follow after it
Wherever the original sadism has undergone no the familiar ambivalence of mitigation or intermixture, we find 1 love and hate in erotic life.
to the object.
If such
instinct
as this is permissible, then we have met we should produce an example of a death
an assumption
demand
the
that
true, a displaced one. But this way of very far from being easy to grasp and creates
it is
though,
looking at things
is
a positively mystical impression. It looks suspiciously as though we were trying to find a way out of a highly embarrassing situation at
new
in
any price. We may recall, however, that there is nothing an assumption of this kind. We put one forward on an
was any question of an embarrassing situation. Clinical observations led us at that time to the view that masochism, the component instinct which is compleearlier occasion, before there
mentary to sadism, must be regarded as sadism that has been turned round upon the subject's own ego. 2 But there is no an instinct turning from an turning from the ego to an object which is the new point now under discussion. Masochism, the turning round of the instinct upon the subject's own ego, would difference in principle between
object to the ego
1
and
[This foreshadows Freud's discussion of instinctual
Chap. IV of The Ego and 2
and
its
See
my
Three Essays
'Instincts
and
the
'fusion*
in
Id (19233).]
(190M) [Standard Ed,,
their Vicissitudes' (1915c).
7,
158;
LP.L,
57, 24j;
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
49
be a return to an earlier phase of the instinct's a regression. The account that was formerly given of
in that case history,
masochism requires emendation as being too sweeping in one there might be such a thing as primary masochism
respect:
a possibility which I had contested at that time. 1 Let us, however, return to the self-preservative sexual in-
The experiments upon
stincts.
that conjugation
that
is,
protista have already shown us the coalescence of two individuals
which separate soon afterwards without any subsequent cellhas a strengthening and rejuvenating effect division occurring 3
upon both of them. In later generations they show no signs of degenerating and seem able to put up a longer resistance to the injurious effects of their own metabolism. This single observation may, I think, be taken as typical of the effect produced by sexual union as well. But how is it that the coalescence
of two only slightly different of life? tozoa
cells
The experiment which
can bring about
this
renewal
replaces the conjugation of pro-
by the application of chemical or even of mechanical enables us to give what is no doubt (cf. LipschutZj 1914}
stimuli
a conclusive reply to this question. The result is brought about by the influx of fresh amounts of stimulus. This tallies well with the hypothesis that the internal reasons to say, to death,
an
life
process of the individual leads for
abolition of chemical tensions, that
whereas union with the
may be
described as fresh
is
to
living substance of a
different individual increases those tensions, introducing 'vital differences'
what
which must then
off. As regards this dissimilarity there must of course be one or more optima. The dominating tendency of mental life, and perhaps of nervous life in general, is the effort to
be lived
reduce, to keep constant or to remove internal tension due to 1
A considerable portion of these speculations have
been anticipated
by Sabina Spielrein (1912) in an instructive and interesting paper which, however, is unfortunately not entirely clear to me. She there describes the sadistic
components of the sexual
instinct as 'destructive'.
A, Starke (1914), again, has attempted to identify the concept of libido itself with the biological concept (assumed on theoretical grounds) of an
impetus towards death. See also Rank (1907). All these discussions, like that in the text, give evidence of the demand for a clarification of the
[A later theory of the instincts such as has not yet been achieved, by Freud himself occupies Chapter
discussion of the destructive instinct
VI
of
GriRzatm and
its
Discontents (1930a).]
See the account quoted above, pp. 41-2, from Lipschiitz (1914),
'
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
50
stimuli (the 'Nirvana principle', to
Low
borrow a term from Barbara
a tendency which finds expression in the l pleasure principle; and our recognition of that fact is one of our strongest reasons for believing in the existence of death [1920, 73])
instincts.
But we
still feel
our line of thought appreciably hampered by
we cannot
the fact that
ascribe to the sexual instinct the char-
of a compulsion to repeat which first put us on the track of the death instincts. The sphere of embryonic developacteristic
mental processes is no doubt extremely rich in such phenomena of repetition; the two germ-cells that are involved in sexual reproduction and their life history are themselves only repetitions of the beginnings of organic
processes to
two
which sexual
cell-bodies.
life is
That alone
is
life.
But the essence of the
directed
is
the coalescence of
what guarantees the immortality
of the living substance in the higher organisms. In other words, we need more information on the origin of sexual reproduction and of the sexual instincts in general. This
a problem which is calculated to daunt an outsider and which the specialists themselves have not yet been able to solve. is
We
shall therefore give only the briefest summary of whatever seems relevant to our line of thought from among the many
discordant assertions and opinions. One of these views deprives the problem of reproduction of its
mysterious fascination by representing
tion of growth.
(Cf.
multiplication
by
it
as a part manifesta-
fission,
sprouting or
gemmation.) The origin of reproduction by sexually differentiated germ-cells might be pictured along sober Darwinian lines
by supposing that the advantage of amphimixis, arrived at on some occasion by the chance conjugation of two protista, was retained
view
and
further exploited in later development.*
On
this
would not be anything very ancient; and the extraordinarily violent instincts whose aim it is to bring about 'sex'
1 [Cf. p. 1 ff. The whole topic is further considered in "The Economic Problem of Masochism' (1924c).] *
Though Weismann (1892) denies this advantage as well: 'In no case does fertilization correspond to a rejuvenescence or renewal of life, nor occurrence necessary in order that life may endure: it is an
is its
merely
which
renders possible the intermingling of two different arrangement hereditary tendencies.' [English translation, 1893, 231.] He nevertheless believes that an rntenningling of this kind leads to an increase in the variability of the organism concerned.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
51
would be repeating something that had once occurred by chance and had since become established as sexual union
being advantageous.
The question arises here, as in the case of death [p. 43] whether we do right in ascribing to protista those characteristics alone which they actually exhibit, and whether it is correct to assume that forces and processes which become visible only in the ,
in those organisms for the higher organisms originated
time.
help
The view of sexuality we have just mentioned for our purposes. The objection may be raised
is
first
of little
against
it
of life instincts already operating postulates the existence in the simplest organisms; for otherwise conjugation, which works counter to the course of life and makes the task of ceasing that
it
to live
more
difficult,
would not be retained and elaborated but
would be avoided. If, therefore, we are not to abandon the we must suppose them to be hypothesis of death instincts, associated from the very first with life instincts. But it must be admitted that in that case with two
unknown
Apart from
this,
we shall be working upon an equation
quantities.
science has so
little
to tell us
about the
that we can liken the problem to a darkorigin of sexuality ness into which not so much as a ray of a hypothesis has penetrated.
In quite a different region,
it
is
true,
we
do
meet
with such a hypothesis; but it is of so fantastic a kind a myth rather than a scientific explanation that I should not it here, were it not that it fulfils precisely venture to
produce
the one condition whose' fulfilment
the origin of an instinct to a need
we
desire.
to restore
an
For
it
traces
earlier state
of
things.
What I have in mind is, of course, the theory which Plato the Symposium, and which put into the mouth of Aristophanes in deals not only with the origin of the sexual instinct but also with its variations in relation to its object "The original human nature was not like the present, but different In the first place, the sexes were originally three in and number, not two as they are now; there was man, woman,
the most important of
.' Everything about these primaeval double: they had four hands and four feet, two faces, two privy parts, and so on. Eventually Zeus decided to cut these men in two, 'like a sorb-apple which is halved for pickAfter the division had been made, 'the two parts of man,
the union of the two.
men was
ling'.
.
.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
52
each desiring his other half, came together, and threw their arms about one another eager to grow into one'. 1 Shall we follow the hint given us by the poet-philosopher, and venture upon the hypothesis that living substance at the time of its coming to We was torn apart into small particles, which have ever since endeavoured to reunite through the sexual instincts? that these instincts, in
which the chemical
affinity of
inanimate matter persisted, gradually succeeded, as they developed through the kingdom of the protista, in overcoming the put in the way of that endeavour by an environment charged with dangerous stimuli stimuli which compelled them to form a protective cortical layer? that these splintered frag-
difficulties
ments of living substance in
this
way
attained a multicellular
condition and finally transferred the instinct for reuniting, in the most highly concentrated form, to the germ-cells? But here, I think, the
moment has come for breaking off.
i
Qowett's translation. Footnote added 1921 :] I have to thank Professor Heinrich Gomperz, of Vienna, for the following discussion on the origin of the Platonic myth, which I give partly in his own words. It is to be remarked that what is essentially the same theory is already to be found in the Upanishads. For we find the following passage in the Brihaddrmyoka-uparushadt 1, 4, 3 [Max-Muller's translation, 2, 85 f.], where the origin of the world from the Atman (the Self or Ego) is described: 'But
he
felt
no
made
a man who is lonely feels no delight. He He was so large as man and wife together. He then
delight. Therefore
wished for a second.
two, and then arose husband and wife. Therefore Yagflavalkya-.said^'We two are thus (each of us) like half a shell" Therefore the void which was there, is filled by the wife.' this his Self to fall in
The Brihaddratyaka-upanish&dis the most ancient of all the Upanishads, and no competent authority dates
it later than about the year 800 B.C. In contradiction to the prevailing opinion, I should hesitate to give an unqualified denial to the possibility of Plato's myth being derived, even
if it
were only indirectly, from the Indian source, since a similar possicannot be excluded in the case of the doctrine of transmigration.
bility
But even first
if
a derivation of this kind (through the Pythagoreans in the were established, the significance of the coincidence be-
instance)
tween the two
trains of thought would scarcely be diminished. For Plato would not have adopted a story of this kind which had somehow reached him through some oriental tradition to say nothing of givingitso impor-
unless it had struck him as containing an element of truth. In a paper devoted to a systematic examination of this line of thought before the time of Plato, Ziegler (1913) traces it back to Babylonian
tant a place
origins.
[Freud had already alluded to Plato's myth in his Three Essays, Standard Ed., 7, 136; I.P.L, 57, 2.J
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
53
Not, however, without the addition of a few words of critical
may be asked whether and how far I am myself convinced of the truth of the hypotheses that have been set out answer would be that I am not convinced in these pages. reflection. It
My
that I do not seek to persuade other people to believe myself and in them. Or, more precisely, that I do not know how far I believe in them.
There
is
no
reason, as
it
seems to me,
why
the
emotional factor of conviction should enter into this question at all. It is surely possible to throw oneself into a line of thought
Mow
it wherever it leads out of simple scientific curiosity, reader prefers, as an advocatus diaboli, who is not on that account himself sold to the devil. I do not dispute the fact
and to
or, if the
that the third step in the theory of the instincts,
which
I
have
taken here, cannot lay claim to the same degree of certainty as the two earlier ones the extension of the concept of sexuality
and the hypothesis of narcissism. These two innovations were a of observation into theory and were no more
direct translation
open
to sources of error
ihan
is
inevitable in all such cases. It
is
assertion of the regressive character of instincts
true that
my
also rests
upon observed material
namely on the
facts
of the
may be, however, that I have overtheir significance. And in any case it is impossible to
compulsion to repeat. It estimated
pursue an idea of this kind except by repeatedly combining factual material with what is purely speculative and thus diverging widely from empirical observation. The more frequently this is done in the course of constructing a theory, the more
untrustworthy, as we know, must be the final result. But the degree of uncertainty is not assignable. One may have made a lucky hit or one may have gone shamefully astray. I do not think a large partis played by what is called 'intuition' in work
of
this
me
to
kind.
From what
I
have seen of
be the product of a kind of
intuition, it
seems to
intellectual impartiality.
Unfortunately, however, people are seldom impartial where ultimate things, the great problems of science and life, are concerned.
Each of us
is
governed in such cases by deep-rooted whose hands our speculation unwit-
internal prejudices, into tingly plays. Since ful,
we have such good grounds for being distrustresults of our own deliberations
our attitude towards the
cannot well be other than one of cool benevolence. I hasten to add, however, that self-criticism such as this is far from binding one to any special tolerance towards dissentient opinions. It is
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
54
to reject remorselessly theories which are perfectly legitimate contradicted by the very first steps in the analysis of observed facts,
while yet being aware at the same time that the validity own theory is only a provisional one.
of one's
We need not feel greatly disturbed in judging our speculation upon the
life
and death
by the
instincts
fact that so
many
bewildering and obscure processes occur in it such as one instinct being driven out by another or an instinct turning from the ego to an object, and so on. This is merely due to our being obliged to operate with the scientific terms, that is to say with the figurative language, peculiar to psychology (or, more precisely, to depth psychology). We could not otherwise describe the processes in question at
all,
become aware of them. The
and indeed we could not have deficiencies in
our description
we were
already hi a position to replace the psychological terms by physiological or chemical ones. It is true that they too are only part of a figurative
would probably vanish
if
it is one with which we have long been familiar perhaps a simpler one as well. the other hand it should be made quite clear that the
language; but
and which
On
is
uncertainty of our speculation has been greatly increased by the necessity for borrowing from the science of biology. Biology is
truly a land of unlimited possibilities.
give us the most surprising information
We may
expect
it
to
and we cannot guess
what answers it will return in a few dozen years to the questions we have put to it. They may be of a kind which will blow away the whole of our
be asked
artificial structure
of hypotheses. If so,
it
may
have embarked upon such a line of thought as the present one, and in particular why I have decided to make it public. Well I cannot deny that some of the analogies,
why I
correlations
and connections which
it
contains seemed to
me to
deserve consideration. 1 1 1 will add a few words to clarify our terminology, which has undergone some development in the course of the present work. We came to know what the 'sexual instincts' were from their relation to the sexes
and
to the reproductive function.
We retained
this
name
after
we had
been obliged by the findings of psycho-analysis to connect them less closely with reproduction. With the hypothesis of narcissistic libido and the extension of the concept of libido to the individual cells, the sexual was transformed for us into Eros, which seeks to force together the portions of living substance. What are commonly
instinct
and hold together
called the sexual instincts are looked
upon by us
as the part of Eros
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
55
directed towards objects. Our speculations have suggested that Eros operates from the beginning of life and appears as a 'life instinct' in opposition to the 'death instinct' which was brought into being by the coming to life of inorganic substance. These speculations seek to
which
is
by supposing that these two instincts were strugfrom the very first. [Added 1 92 1 :] It is not so easy, gling with each other to follow the transformations through which the concept of the solve the riddle of life
perhaps,
'ego-instincts'
has passed.
the instinctual trends (of
To
begin with
we
which we had no
applied that closer
name
to all
knowledge) which
could be distinguished from the sexual instincts directed towards an the ego-instincts to the sexual instincts of which object; and we opposed the libido is the manifestation. Subsequently we came to closer grips with the analysis of the ego and recognized that a portion of the 'egoinstincts is also of a libidinal character and has taken the subject's own 1
ego as its object. These narcissistic self-preservative instincts had thenceforward to be counted among the libidinal sexual instincts. The opposition between the ego-instincts and the sexual instincts was transformed into
one between the ego-instincts and the object-instincts, both of a But in its place a fresh opposition appeared between the
libidinal nature. libidinal (ego-
to
and object-)
instincts and others,
be present in the ego and which
in the destructive instincts.
Our
opposition into one between the
which must be presumed
perhaps actually be observed speculations have transformed this
may
life instincts
(Eros)
and the death
instincts.
For a general account of the development of Freud's views on the [ instincts, see the Editor's Note to 'Instincts and their Vicissitudes' (\9lty, Standard Ed., U,ll\.]
VII
IF
it is
really the case that seeking to restore is
things
an
earlier state of
such a universal characteristic of instincts,
we need
not
be surprised that so many processes take place in mental life independently of the pleasure principle. This characteristic
would be shared by all the component instincts and in their case would aim at returning once more to a particular stage in the course of development. These are matters over which the no control; but it does not follow pleasure principle has as yet that any of them are necessarily opposed to it, and we have still to solve the problem of the relation of the instinctual processes of repetition to the dominance of the pleasure principle.
We
have found that one of the
earliest
and most important
functions of the mental apparatus is to bind the instinctual impulses which impinge on it, to replace the primary process prevailing in
them by the secondary process and convert
their freely mobile cathectic energy into (tonic) cathexis.
While
this
a mainly quiescent is taking place no
transformation
can be paid to the development of unpleasure; but does not imply the suspension of the pleasure principle. the contrary, the transformation occurs on behalf of the
attention this
On
pleasure principle; the binding is a preparatory act which introduces and assures the dominance of the pleasure principle.
Let us make a sharper distinction than we have hitherto made between function and tendency. The pleasure principle, then,
is
business
a tendency operating in the service of a function whose it is to free the mental apparatus entirely from excita-
tion or to keep the amount of excitation in it constant or to cannot yet decide with certainty keep it as low as possible. in favour of any of these ways of putting it; but it is clear that
We
the function thus described would be concerned with the most universal endeavour of
all
living substance
to the quiescence of the inorganic world.
enced
how
sexual act,
namely to return have all experi-
We
the greatest pleasure attainable by us, that of the associated with a momentary extinction of a highly
is
The binding of an instinctual impulse would be a preliminary function designed to prepare the excitaintensified excitation.
tion for
its final
elimination in the pleasure of olischarge. 56
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
57
This raises the question of whether feelings of pleasure and unpleasure can be produced equally from bound and from
unbound excitatory
processes.
And
there seems to be
no doubt
whatever that the unbound or primary processes give rise to far more intense feelings in both directions than the bound or secondary ones. Moreover the primary processes are the earlier
beginning of mental life there are no others, and we may infer that if the pleasure principle had not already been in time; at the
operative in them it could never have been established for the thus reach what is at bottom no later ones.
We
conclusion, struggle for
very simple
namely that at the beginning of mental life the pleasure was far more intense than later but not so
it had to submit to frequent interruptions. In later dominance of the pleasure principle is very much more secure, but it itself has no more escaped the process of taming than the other instincts in general. In any case, whatever it is that causes the appearance of feelings of pleasure and unpleasure in processes of excitation must be present in the
unrestricted:
times the
secondary process just as
it is in the primary one. Here might be the starting-point for fresh investigations. Our
of pleasure and unpleasure but also of a peculiar tension which its turn can be either pleasurable or unpleasurable. Should the difference between these feelings enable us to distinguish in
between bound and 'unbound processes of energy? or is the of tension to be related to the absolute magnitude, or
feeling
perhaps to the
level,
of the cathexis, while the pleasure and
unpleasure series indicates a change in the magnitude of the 1 cathexis within & given unit of time? Another striking fact is that the life instincts have so much more contact with our internal
emerging as breakers of the peace and constantly producing tensions whose release is felt as pleasure while the death instincts seem to do their work unobtrusively. The
perception
pleasure principle seems actually to serve the death instincts. It is true that it keeps watch upon stimuli from without, which are regarded as by both kinds of instincts; but it is
dangers
more
on guard against increases of stimulation from within, which would make the task of living more difficult. This in turn raises a host of other questions to which we can at especially
1
[Cf. above, p. 2.
Freud
These questions had already been touched on by Part I, Section 8 and Part III, Section L]
in his 'Project', e.g. in
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
58
present
find
no answer.
We
must be patient and await
fresh
methods and occasions of research. We must be ready, too, abandon a path that we have followed for a time, if it seems
to to
be leading to no good end. Only believers, who demand that science shall be a substitute for the catechism they have given for developing or even transup, will blame an investigator forming his views. We may take comfort, too, for the slow advances of our scientific knowledge in the words of the poet:
Was man Die
nicht erfliegen kann,
muss
Schrift sagt, es ist keine Siinde
man erhinken.
zu hinken. 1
1 The ['What we cannot reach flying we must reach limping. Book tells us it is no sin to limp,' The last lines of 'Die beiden Gulden', a version by Riickert of one of the Maq&m&t of al-Hariri. Freud also .
quoted these Letter 32).]
lines in
a
letter to Fliess
.
.
of Oct. 20, 1895 (Freud I950a,
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS = Freud, Gesammelie Schnflen (12 Vienna, 1924-34. = Freud, Gisammtlte Werke (18 vols), London, from 1940. = Freud, Collected Papers (5 London, 1924-50. -,\ = Freud, Standard Edition (24 vols.), London, from 1953. = International Psycho-Analytical Library, Hogarth Press and vols.),
G.W. C.P.
S.E.
I.P.L
vols.),
Institute of Psycho-Analysis, Theorttische Schriftm
= Freud,
London, from 1921. Vienna,
Theoretische Schnfttn (1911-23),
1931.
59
BIBLIOGRAPHY AND AUTHOR INDEX books and periodicals are sn italics; titles of papers are in commas. Abbreviations are in accordance with the World List
[Titles of
inverted
of Scientific Periodicals (London, 1952), Further abbreviations used in this volume \vill be found in the List on page 59. Numerals in thick type numerals refer to pages. The figures in round brackets at the end of each entry indicate the page or pages of this refer to volumes; ordinary
volume on which the work in question is mentioned. In the case of the Freud entries, the letters attached to the dates of publication are in accordance with the corresponding entries in the complete bibliography of Freud's writings to be included in the last volume of the Standard
For non-technical authors, and for technical authors where no work is mentioned, see the General Index.]
specific
ADLER, A.
(1
908) 'Der Aggressionsbetrieb
Fortschr.
BREUER,
Med. No. t
and FREUD,
J.,
im Lebcn und in der Neurose'
19, (47)
S.
(1893) See FREUD,
S. (1893a)
(1895) See FREUD, S. (18954)
(1940) See FREUD, S. (19404) DOFUEIN, F. (1919) Das Problem des Todes tmd Pflanzen und Tieren, Jena. (41)
FECHNER, G. T. (1873) Eintgg
der Unsterblichkeit bet den
Ideen zur Sckdpfungs- tmd Entwtcklungs-
geschichte der Organismm, Leipzig. (2, 4) FERENCZI, S. (1913) 'EntwipklungsscufendesWirklichkeitssinnes',/^7. 1, 124. (35) [Trans.: 'Stages in the
PychaaaaL,
Development of the Sense of Reality', London, 1952, Chap. VIII.j
First Contributions to Psycho-Analysis,
W.
FUESS,
FREUD,
(1906) DerAblaufdisLebens, Vienna. (39)
S. (1893a)
With BREUER, J.,'t)ber den psychischen Mechanismus Phanomene: Vorlaufige Mitteilung'. GS., 1. 7-
hysterischer
G.W.,1,81. (7) [Trans.: 'On the Psychical Mechanism of Hysterical Phenomena: Preliminary Communication', C.P.. 1, 24; Standard Ed., 2,3.]
(18954)
G.W.,
With BREUER, 1, 75.
J., Stefan uber Hystme, Vienna, G.S., Omitting Breuer's contributions. (3, 19, 21, 28)
[Trans.; Studies on Hysteria, Standard Ed\, 2;
LP.L,
1;
50. Including
Breuer's contributions.]
(1900s) Die Traumdeutung, Vienna,
, 2-3; G.W., 2-3. (x, 8-9. 18-19,26,28) The Interpretation of Dream, London and New York,
[Trans.:
1955; Standard Ed., 4-5.]
60
BIBLIOGRAPHY FREUD,
61
S. (conl.)
Der Witz and setae Beziehmg
(1905c)
G.W.,
9, 5;
6.
zm
Unbeuwsten, Vienna. G.S.,
(29)
Mr
Relation to the Unconscious, London, 1960; [Trans.: Jokes and Standard Ed., 8.] Drei Abhandlwgen zttr Sexualtheorie, Vienna. G.S., 5, 3; G.W.,
(1905tf)
5, 29. (27,
47-8, 52)
on the Theory of Sexuality, [Trans.: Three Essays
Standard Ed., 7, 125;
LP.L,
London, 1949;
57.]
(1910J) 'Die psychogcne Sehstorung in psychoanalytischer Auffassung', G.S., 5, 301; G.W., 8, 94. (45) [Trans.:
'The Psycho-Analytic View of Psychogenic Disturbance
of Vision', C.P., 2, 105; Standard Ed., 11.211] tiber die zwei Prinzipien des psychischen (191 li) 'Formulierungen Geschehens', G.S., 5, 409; G.W., 8, 230. (xi, 4)
'Formulations on the
[Trans.:
Two
Principles of
Mental Func-
tioning', C.P., 4, 13; Standard Ed., 12, 215.] (1914c) 'Zur Einfuhrung des Narzissmus', G.S., 6, 155; G.W., 10, 138, (xii, 27, 45-6)
'On Narcissism: an
[Trans.:
Introduction', CJ>., 4, 30; Standard
zur Technik der Psychoanalyse: II ) 'Weitere Ratschlage Erinnern, Wiederholen und Durcharbeiten', G.S., 6, 109; G.W., 10, 126. (12)
Repeating and Working Through Recommendations on the Technique of Psycho-
'Recollecting,
[Trans.:
(Further
Analysis, II)', C.P., 2, 366; Standard Ed., 12, 147.]
(1915c) 'Triebc
und
Triebschicksale', G.S., 5, 443; G.W., 10, 210.
24, 48, 55)
(xii,
[Trans.: Instincts
and
their Vicissitudes', C.P., 4, 60; Standard
Ed., 14, 111.]
(1915) 'Das Unbewusste',
G&>
5, 480;
G.W., 10, 264.
(1,
18,
22) [Trans.:
"The Unconscious',
(1916-17) Vorlesungen G.S., 7;
G.W., H.
yx
C.P., 4, 98; Standard Ed., 14, 161.]
Einfuhnmg
in die Psychoanalyse,
Vienna.
(14)
on Psycho-Analysis, revised ed., Lon-, [Trans.: Introductory Lectures
don, 1929 (4 General Introduction
to
Psychoanalysis,
New
York,
mS}', Standard f., 15-16.] aus Dichttmg md Wahrhetf, (19176) 'Eine Kbdheitserinnerung G.S., 10, 357; G.W., 12, 15. (10) Recollection from Dicktung md Wahrkeit', 'A Childhood [Trans.: C.P., 4, 357; Standard Ed., 17, 147.] (19174) 'Metapsychologische Erganzung zur Traumlehre', GS., 5, 520; G. W., 10, 412. (18,24) 'A Supplement to the Theory of
Metapsychological 4, 137; Standard Ed., 15, 219.] zu %ir Psychoanalyse der Kriegsneurosen, Vienna. Einleitung (1919J) 11, 252; G.W., 12, 321. (6, 27) [Trans.:
Dreams', CP.,
G,
BIBLIOGRAPHY
62
FREUD,
S. (cant,)
to Psycho-Analysis and the War Neuroses, [Trans.: Introduction 1921. C.P., 5, 83; Standard Ed., 17, 207.]
London and New York,
G.W. t 12, 229. (ix-x) (1919A) 'Das Unheimliche', (?., 10, 369; 'The Uncanny*, C.P., 4, 368; Standard Ed., 17, 219.] [Trans.: 'Erganzungen zur Traumlehre' (Abstract of Congress
(1920/)
Address),
Int.
%. Psyckoan., 6, 397.
to the [Trans.: 'Supplements 18, 4;
IPX.,
Theory of Dreams', Standard
Ed.,
4, x.]
(1920^) Jenseitsdes Lustprimips, Vienna, G.S., 6, 191; G.W., 13, 3. [Tram.: Beyond tks Pleasure Principle, Standard Ed., 18, 7;
1.P.L, 4.] to J. Varendonck's The Psycho(1921*) Introduction in English 271. (xi) logy of Day-Dreams, London; Standard Ed., 18,
[German Text (part only): G.S., 11, 264; G.W., 13, 439.] 237. (1923*) Das Ich und das Es, Vienna. G.S., 6, 353; G.W., 13, (xi, 13,
45, 48)
[Trans.: The
Ego and
the Id,
Standard
&.,
19, 3; I.P.L, 12.]
der (1923c [1922]) 'Bemerkungcn zur Theorie und Praxis 1 3, 305; G.W., 13, 301. (14, 26) deutung ,
Traum-
G,
[Trans.:
'Remarks on the Theory and Practice of Dream-
Interpretation', C.P., 5, 136; Standard Ed., 19, 109.] des Masochismus', G.5., 5, 374; (1924c) 'Das okonomische Problem G.W., 13, 371. (2, 50)
of Masochism', C.P., 2, 255; [Trans.: 'The Economic Problem Standard Ed., 19, 157.] (1925d [1924]) 'Notiz iiber den "Wunderblodc"
',
G.W.,14,3. (19,22) [Trans.: 'A Note upon the "Mystic Writing-Pad"
G.S., 6, 415;
',
C.P., 5, 175;
Standard Ed., 19,227.] (1925* [1924]) 'Die Widerstande gegen die Psychoanalyse', ., 11, 224;
[Trans.:
G.W., 14, 99. (44) "The- J&esistance to Psycho-Analysis',
C.P., B, 163;
Standard Ed., 19,213.]
Symptom und Angst, Vienna. G3., 11, 23; G.W.,
(1926rf) Hemmng, 14, 113. (7, 14,24)
[Trans.: Inhibition^ Symptoms and Anxiety, Standard Ed., 20, 77;
IPX.,
28.]
(1930a) Das Unbehagm 14, 421. (49) [Trans.: Civilization
in der Kultur,
and
its
Vienna. G.S., 12, 29; G.W.,
Discontents,
London and New York,
1930; Standard Ed,, 21,59.] (I940if )
G.W.,
With BREUER,
{
J.,
Zur Theorie des hysterischen AnfaLY,
17, 9. (3)
[Trans.: 'On the Standard Ed., I]
(I94la) Brief
Theory of Hysterical
an Josef Breuer, G.W.,
Attacks', C.P., 5, 27;
17, 5. (3)
A Letter to Josef Breuer, CJ
5
[Trans.:
(I942a) 'Psychopathic Characters
.,
on the
5,
25; Standard Ed.,
1.]
Stage', Standard Ed., 7,
BIBLIOGRAPHY FRBUD,
63
S.
(ami) 1 305. Translation of 'Psychopathische Personal auf der Buhne , which has not been published in German. (11)
(
1950s)
Atis
den
Anfdngen der Psychoanalyse, London.
'Entwurf einer Psychologic' (1895).]
(xii,
[Includes
2-3, 19-20, 22-4,
57-8)
The Origins of Psycho-Analysis, London and New York, 1954. (Partly, including 'A Project for a Scientific Psychology',
[Trans,;
in Standard Ed., 1.)] (1955ff)
'Gutachten iiber die
elektriscfae
Behandlung der Kriegs-
German text unpublished. (6) 'Memorandum on the Electrical Treatment of War
neurotiker'; [Trans.:
Neuroses', Standard Ed., 17, 211.]
FREUD,
S.,
FERENCZI, S., and others. (1919) Vienna. (6)
w Psychoanalyse der Kriegs-
neurosen,
and the War Neuroses, London and [Trans.: Psycho-Analysis York, 1921.] GOETTE, A. (1883) (far den Urspnaig des Todes, Hamburg. (41)
HARTMANN, M.
(1906)
Tod und
Fortpfonzung,
Munich.
JUNG, C. G. (1909) 'Die Bedeutung des Vaters Einzelnen', Jb.
pychoauL
fiir
New
(41)
das Schicksal des
psychopath. Forsch., 1, 155. (16)
of the Father in the Destiny of the [Trans.: "The Significance Individual', Collected Papers on Analytical Psychology, London, 1916, 156.]
Warm
wir sterbcn, Stuttgart (41, 49) Low, B. (1920) Psycho-Analysis, London. (50) MARONOWSKI, J. (1918) 'Die erotischen Quellen der MinderwertigSexwlwiss., 4, 313. (14) keitsgefuhle',
LIPSCHUTZ, A. (1914)
PFEIFER, S. (1919) 'Ausserungen infantil-erotischer Triebe Imago, 5, 243. (8)
RANK, 0. (1907) DerKunstler, Vienna. (49) RICKMAN, J. (ed.) (1937) A General Seltctmfrm Freud, London, (xii) SCHOPENHAUER, A. (1851) 'tJber
the
im
Spiele',
Works ofSigmwid
die anscheinende Absichtlichkeit
im
Schicksale des Einzelnen', Parerga und Paralipomena, 1 (Samtfahe Wtrke, ed. Hubscher, Leipzig, 1938, 5, 213). (44)
SPIELREIN, S. (1912) 'Die Destruktion als Ursache des Werdens', }k, psychoanal psychopath. Forsch., 4, 465. (49)
STARCKE, A. (1914) Introduction to Dutch translation of Freud's ' "Gvilized" Sexual Morality and Modern Nervous Illness', Leyden. (49) Psychology of Day-Dreams, London, (n) des Lebens, Jena. (39) (1882) Uber die Jena. (39-41) (1884) VberLeben und
VARENDONCK,J. (1921) The
WEBMANN, A.
MDam
(1892) Das Keimplasma, Jena. (3940, 50) [Trans.: The Germ-Plasm, London, 1893.] New Jb. ZEEGLER, K. (1913) 'Menschen- und Weltenwerden',
klass.
GENERAL INDEX This index includes the names of non-technical authors. It also includes the names of technical authors where no reference is made in the text to specific works. For references to specific technical works, the Biblioffraohv * y should be consulted. Abraham, K., 6
n. I
Child, desire to have,
Abreaction, II Active and passive in children's play.
KM 1,29
by father,
15
Childhood, traumas of, xi, 26 Children (m also Infantile sexuality)
Aggressiveness, 47
compulsion to repeat
Ambivalence and the opposition between the life and death instincts, 47-8 Amphimixis, 42, 50
play of, 8-1 1,17,29 sexual researches of, 15
in, ix. xi,
8-11,17,29-30
Analogy, Plato's myth of bisexu-
Clorinda (in Gerusalemme Liberate), 16
Component
Animals 29-34, 36 death of, 39-43 duration of life in, 39-44
during psycho-analysis, 17, 29-30
(see
Fear;
Fright;
Phobias)
in
26-7 normal people, 15-16
15, 17, 29-31, 50-3, 56 Condensation, 28 Confluence of instincts 47 , 2
51-2
Art, 11
Conscious system, 18-22, 28
(in the Upamshads), 52
n. 1
'Autistic thinking', xi
Gulden, Die,
admissibility to, 12-13, 19 origin of, 19-21
58
Constancy,
Biological
factors,
of
(see
also .
2,
n. 1
54
Bisexuality,
Cs. (see
Conscious system)
51-2
'Bound'
psychical energy (see Energy, psychical, bound and
unbound) Brain, anatomy of the, 18 Braut mm Messina, Die,* 39 J.
principle
Excitatory processes), 3, 3
concept of death, 39-43, 49
Bretur,
12-
instinctual character of, ix, xi, 14-
preparedness for, 7 n. 1, 25-7 Anxiety dreams, x, 7, 26
Baden
life,
roses, 7, 17,
also
defined, 6-7
Aristophanes,
ix, xi,
in children, ix, xi, 8-1 1 , 1 7, 29-30 in dreams during traumatic neu-
Anticathexis, 24
Ataum
attribute of organic
30-2,34,38,50-3,56
conservative nature of instinct in,
Anxiety
an
as
ality,51-2
56
instincts, 47-9,
Compulsion to repeat
(see
also
'Daemonic force
1
,
15,
Danger, perception Darmi, Charles, 50
29-30
of,
5-6, 33, 52
Day's residues, 28, 30
Death
aim of life is,
Bibliography),
20-1,25,28
biological
49
n.
32-4, 38-9, 49
concept
of,
39-43,
1
internal necessity of, 32, 38-41, 43
Cathexis
(see Excitatory processes) Censorship, x, 45
'natural', 34,
39-43
Weumamts views 64
on, 39-43
GENERAL INDEX Death instinct ix,
(seealso Ego-instincts),
equated with ego-instinct, 38, 46,
54
External world, 18, 20-2
32-5, 38, 40-1, 43-51, 54
rt.
Jn opposition to
life instinct, xi,
34-5, 38, 43, 47, 54 Dementia praecox, 27 Destiny, compulsion Destnictiveness, xi, 49
n.
3
n.
daughter's desire for a child by, 15 jealousy of, 10 Faust (Goethe), 36
Fear
15-17
of,
Fairy tales, 14 Father
n.
also
(see
Anxietyj
Phobia), 6, 7
1
Fright;
n.
in dreams, 28 Displacement Dream-content, manifest, 28
Fechner, G. T. (see also Bibliography),
Dreams and sleep, 26-7
Ferenczi, S.
anxiety-, x, 7,
2,4 6
26
n. 1,
(see also
Bibliography),
7
Fliess,Wtihelm (see also Bibliography),
as wish-fulfilments, x-xi, 7, 26-7,
39,58. Forgetting, 26
30 45 displacement in, 28 during psycho-analysis, censorship
Fright
of, x,
15,
hallucinatory character of, 1 function of, x 'prospective
punishment-, x, traumatic, xi,
26 26
Genital primacy, 48 Genualcmme Uberata (Tassd), 16
26
Goethe,
7, 17,
26
xi,
10.2,36 1
Gomperz,H.,52n. Guilt, sense of, 26
Dream-thoughts, latent, xi
Dream-work,
dso Anxiety; Fear), 6-7,
(see
28 Hague, The, x Hallucinatory character of dreams,
26
and pleasure principle, 14, 17 as reservoir of libido, 44-6, 48 masochistic trends
nucleus
of,
7-8,
of,
Hereditary
48-9
repressive forces of, 13-14, 17
unconscious part
13-14 27
of,
Hering,
factors,
31
43
K,
Hunger, 45 Hypochondria, 6 6-7 Hysteria, x,
13
unification of, 4-5, 13,
Ego
ideal,
x
Id, the,
Ego-instincts (see also
Death instinct; instinct
Self-preservation,
of),
38,44-7 equated with death instinct, 38,
46,54s, 35, 38, 44-9,
M.,
54
n.
2
B.
Infantile sexuality, 1 2, 14-15, Inferiority, sense of, 14-15 Instincts
also
Component instinct;
45-7, 49
bound and un-
Energy, psychical, bound, 1-2, 20-5, 27-30, 56-7 Eros (see also Libido; Life instinct;
Sexual instinct),
xi,
36-7, 44,
Sexual
B.
28-38,
1,53-7
'conservatism' of, 30-5, 38 Instinctual character of the compul-
sion to repeat, ix,xi, 14-15, 17,
29-31, 50-3, 56 International
46, 48, 54
of;
14-15,
instinct
4-5,
instinct),
Embryology, 20, 31, 50
Psycho-Analytical
_
Excitations external, 20-6, 34, 35
45
n. 3,
49-50,
Introversion,
3,
17, 30,
Jealousy of father, 10
52,57 internal, 22-3, 28, 57
Excitatory processes,
56-7
1,
in-
Ego-
instincts; Life instinct; Self-pre-
servation,
ix
.
45
Death
(see
stincts}
in opposition to sexual instinct, Eitingon, Dr.
45
Inertia, neuronic, principle of, 3
of younger child, 10
B.
1,15
GENERAL INDEX
66 Jokes, 29
Oedipus complex, Oral phase, 48
J,
E., 6 n. 1 n. Jowett, 5., 52
Jwg,
C. G.
46-7
12,
14-15
1
(set also
Bibliography),
and neurosis, 6, 27 and the compulsion to repeat.
injury, life,
30-2,34,38,53,56 Kant,
/.,
22
GENERAL INDEX 12-15 Psycho-analytic technique, 1 Psycho-analytic theory, 'pan-sexualism'
Psycho-analytic of neurotics,
of,
46
xi,
ix,
of,
Psychoneuroses
[ste
52
n.
x,
Stimuli, 20-$, 34, 35 n. 3, 49-50, 52,
26
57
1
Suggestion as a factor in psychoanalysis, 14n. 2, 26
25 Quality, 2-3, 23, Quantity, 2, 2
7
n. 1,
Sleep and dreams, 26-7 Stability, principle of (Fechner), 2-3
12-13
Neuroses)
Punishment-dreams, Pythagoras,
54 n.
Sexual intercourse, 56 Shock and traumatic neurosis, 25 Simmel, E,, 6
of,
instinct, 34-5,
38, 40, 44, 47, 54 n. in opposition to ego-instincts, 35, 38, 44-7,
13-16, 29-
30
therapeutic aspect
life
origin of, 50-2
treatment
30 termination
67
equated with
49-52
Protista, 38-44,
Superstitious belieis, 39
25
n. I,
Symposium, Thi, 51-2
Reaction-formation, 45 Tancrcd (in Genisaltmme Liberaia), 16 Tasso, 16
Reality-principle, 4-5, 14,29
Regression,
masochism
to Repeat, compulsion
as,
49
(see
Compul-
22
and compulsion to repeat, 12-14, 26,30 and pleasure principle, 5, 14 ego as agent
13-14, 17, 45
of,
instinctual, 5, 14,
36-7
11
Transference, 12, 15-17, 30 exploited by resistance, 17
Transference neuroses
in psycho-analytic
treatment, 12-14
n. 1
Trauma, 6-8, 23-7 infantile, xi,
transference exploited by, 17
Hys-
Neurosis),
46
Transmigration, 52 of,
(see also
Obsessional
12-13, 44,
ego, 14
overcoming
Tragedy,
teria;
Resistance
and
Three Wishes, The, 14 n. 3 of, related to Pept.-Cs.,
Time, sense
sion to repeat)
Repression
26
Traumatic dreams, x,xi,
7,
17,26 25-9
neurosis, 6-8, 17,
Sadism, 47-8, 49 Sdulkr, P., 39 Schopenhauer,
n. 1
A.
Uncathected (see
also
Biblio-
graphy), 44
Secondary process psychical,
(see
also
Energy,
bound and unbound)
28, 30, 56-7 Self-preservation, instinct of (see also
systems,
mental processes, 12-13, 18,22 systems, 28 relation to Of., 19, 22,
54 n.
timelessness of, 22
4,45
28
Unpleasure, 1-5, 10-11, 14-15, 18, 23-4, 32, 56-7
Sexual curiosity of children, 15 Sexual excitement and mechanical agitation, 27 Sexual instinct
24 n. 2
Unconscious, the, 28
Ego-instincts), 4, 33, 45-7, 49,
Sexual aetiology of the neuroses, 33-
insuscepti-
bility to excitation of,
Unconscious ego, 13-14
(ste also
Eros; Libido;
Fechner's
view
of,
2-4
neurotic, 'pleasure that cannot 1 felt as such , 5 Upanishads, 52 n.
be
1
Life instinct)
and component instincts, 47-8, 49 1,53 and pleasure principle, 4-5 .
VarendonckJ.
(ste also
Bibliography),
GENERAL INDEX
68
Waking
life,
relation of
dreams
to,
28
War of 1914-18, War neuroses, 6 Weimaoi, A. 39-43
6
(see also
Wish-fulfilment in dreams, x-xi, 7 26-7, 30 Woodruff,
Bibliography),
Zeus, 51
L L, 41-2
PSYCHIATRY AND PSYCHOLOGY Adams James L.
Conceptual Blockbusting (2d
,
Adler, Alfred.
Cooperation Between the Sexes.
Adler, Alfred
Superiority and Social Interest
.
Adorno, T.W. etal.
The Authoritarian
Alexander, Franz.
.
)
Personality
(Abr Ed.)
Psychosomatic Medicine.
and Richard R.J. Lewme.
Bernheim, Kayla
F.
Bowers, Kenneth
S.
Bruner, Jerome S. flruner,
Ed
Jerome S
Hypnosis: For the Seriously Curious
Symptom, Causes,
.
Beyond the Information Given. The Relevance of Education
Burgess, Linda Cannon.
Cannon Walter B.
The Art of Adoption.
The Way of an Investigator
,
Cannon Walter B.
The Wisdom of the Body.
,
Damon, William.
Schizophrenia
Social
and Personality
Development: Essays on the
and Personality
Development: Infancy Through
Growth of the Child.
Damon, William.
Social
Daniels, Pamela and Kathy
Sooner or later- The Timing
Wemgarten.
Parenthood in Adult Lives.
Donaldson, Margaret.
Enkson, Erik H. Enkson, Erik H.
H Erik H
Enkson Erik ,
Erikson,
Minds.
Children's
Adulthood Childhood and Society.
New Identity.
.
Dimensions of a
.
Gandhi's Truth.
Enkson, Erik H.
Identity: Youth
Erikson, Erik
H.
Identity
Erikson, Erik
H.
Insight
Enkson, Erik H.
Young
and Crisis.
and the Life Cycle
and Responsibility.
Man Luther.
Fancher,
Raymond
E.
Pioneers of Psychology.
Fancher,
Raymond
E,
Psychoanalytic Psychology: The Development of
Freud's Thought.
Finch, Scuart
Freud, Anna.
M.
Fundamentals of Child Psychiatry.
Psychoanalysis for Teachers
and Parents.
Freud, Sigmund.
An Autobiographical Study.
Freud,
Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
Sigmund
Freud Sigmund ,
.
Freud, Sigmund, Freud, ,
and its Discontents
The Ego and the
.
Id.
Five Lectures on Psycho- Analysts.
Sigmund
Freud Sigmund
Civilization
.
Freud, Sigmund.
The Future of an
Illusion.
Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego
/
S
Freud, Sigrnund.
Inhibitions,
Freud, Sigmund.
Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysts,
Freud,
Sigmund
Freud,
Sigmund
Freud,
Sigmund
Jokes
and Their
Relation to the Unconscious,
Leonardo da Vinci
.
New Introductory
and a Memory of His
Childhood,
Lectures on Psychoanalysis.
Freud, Sigmund.
On Dreams.
Freud,
Sigmund
On
the History of the Psycho-Analytic Movement.
Freud,
Sigmund
An
Outline of'Psycho-Analysts
Freud,
Sigmund
The Question of Lay Analysis
Freud,
Sigmund
Totem
Frieze, Irene
and
Taboo,
,
Women and Sex Roles.
Uncommon Therapy The
Haley, Jay
M
N
Ruble
A Social Psychological Perspective.
Psychiatric Techniques of Milton B.
D.
Hendin, David
Death as a Fact of Life.
Hendin, Herbert
Suicide in America.
Horney, Karen (Ed
Are You Considering Psychoanalysts?
)
Horney, Karen
Feminine Psychology.
Horney, Karen.
Neurosis
Horney, Karen
The Neurotic Personality of Our Time.
and Human Growth.
Horney, Karen.
New Ways in Psychoanalysis.
Horney, Karen,
Our Inner Conflicts
Horney, Karen.
Self-Analysis.
Inhelder, Barbel , and Jean Piaget
James, William.
Talks
to
The Early Growth of Logic in the Child.
Teachers
Hamlet and Oedipus.
Jones, Ernest.
The Growth of the Child-
Kagan, Jerome
Kagan, Jerome, and Robet Coles (Eds. ),
Karchadounan Herant George
A
A
Reflections on
Human
Development.
Twelve to Sixteen. Early Adolescence.
Human Sexuality.
,
Kelly,
Ed)
H. Jacquelynne E Parsons, Paula B Johnson, Diane
and Gail L Zellmann
Ertckson,
(Rev
The Psychopathology of Everyday Life
Freud, Sigmund.
Sense
and Nonsense
Theory of Personality.
Klein, Melanie, and Joan Riviere.
Komarovsky, Mirra.
Love,
Hate and Reparation.
Dilemmas of Masculinity
Kosslyn, Stephen Michael.
A Study of College
Ghosts in the Mind's Machine
Youth.
How We Create
Pictures in our Brains.
Lacan, Jacques
Ecnts.
Lacan, Jacques
The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psycho-Analysis
Lederer,
William J.
Levy, David
M.
Lifton, Robert Jay
Light, Donald
Lunde, Donald
May, Rollo.
Good Relationship.
Thought Reform and the Psychology ofTotalism
Becoming Psychiatrists: The Professional Transformation of Self. T.
Mandler, George
Meehl, Paul E
Creating a
Maternal Qverprotection
Murder and Madness.
Mind and Body:
Psychology
Psychology of Emotion
and the Human Dilemma.
and Stress.
The Child's Conception of Number. Genetic Eptstemology.
Piaget , Jean Piaget Jean
.
Dreams and Imitation
Play,
,
Piaget, Jean and Barbel Inhelder. ,
P
1
agec, Jean,
and Barbel Inhelder
m Childhood.
The Child's Conception if Space.
The Origin of the Idea of Chance tn Children.
Piaget, Jean, Barbel Inhelder, and
Alma Szemmska
The Child's Conception of
Geometry.
and Milton B. Singer
Piers, Gerhart, Piers,
Maria
W
(Ed
Play
)
Shame sndGitilt.
and Development
Premack David and Ann James Premack.
The
,
Mind of an Ape.
and Reality.
Rank, Otto
Truth
Rank, Otto.
Will Therapy.
Ruesch , J urgen and Gregory Bateson.
Communication The Social Matrix
,
of Psychiatry.
Schwartz, Barry (Ed
).
Schwartz, Barry and
Hugh
Psychology of Learning Readings in Behavior Theory.
lacey
Behaviorism, Sconce,
andHuman Nature: An
introduction to Conditioning.
Sullivan,
Harry Stack
Clinical Studies in Psychiatry.
Sullivan,
Harry Stack.
Conceptions of Modern Psychiatry.
Sullivan,
Harry Stack.
The Interpersonal Theory of Psychiatry.
Sullivan,
Harry Stack
The Psychiatric
Sullivan,
Harry Stack.
Schizophrenia as a
W ,
Process.
The Living Brain.
Grey.
Watson John B
Human
The Changing Nature of Man
van den Berg, J H. Walter,
Interview.
Behaviorism
.
The Quest for
Wheelis, Allen.
Williams, Juanita H.
Identity.
Psychology of Women: Behavior tn a Biosocial Context
(2dEd.)-
Williams, Juanita
H
(Ed.)
A
Zilboorg, Gregory.
History of Medical Psychology,
Selected Liveright Paperbacks
PSYCHIATRY AND PSYCHOLOGY Jones, Ernest.
On the Nightmare.
Kohler, Wolfgang.
Dynamics in
Kohler, Wolfgang.
Gestalt Psychology.
Kohler, Wolfgang.
The Mentality of Apes
KShler, Wolfgang
The Place of Value tn a World of Fact.
The Selected Papers of Wolfgang Kohler.
Kohler, Wolfgang.
R
Luria, Alexander
Stekei,
Wilhelm.
Stekel
Wilhelm
,
Relation
to
Sex.
.
Psychology.
.
The Nature of Human Impotence in ihe Male.
Conflicts.
h Ja
Jc Ki
Ks
Ke Ki,
Ko
Ko I
Lac Lac,
Led
Lun<
Man.
May,
113212
Beyond the Pleasure Principle Translated and edited by James Strachey Introduction and notes by Gregory Zilboorg
By
SIGMUND FREUD
AN AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL STUDY BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE CIVILIZATION
AND ITS DISCONTENTS
THE COMPLETE INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS THE EGO AND THE FIVE LECTURES
ID
ON PSYCHOANALYSIS
THE FUTURE OF AN ILLUSION
GROUP PSYCHOLOGY AND THE ANALYSIS OF THE EGO INHIBITIONS,
SYMPTOMS AND ANXIETY
INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS JOKES AND THEIR RELATION TO THE UNCONSCIOUS
LEONARDO DA VINCI AND A MEMORY OF HIS CHILDHOOD
NEW INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON PSYCHOANALYSIS ON DREAMS ON THE HISTORY OF THE PSYCHOANALYTIC MOVEMENT AN OUTLINE OF PSYCHOANALYSIS THE PSYCHOPATHALOGY OF EVERYDAY LIFE
THE QUESTION OF LAY ANALYSIS
TOTEM AND TABOO
THE STANDARD EDITION OF THE COMPLETE PSYCHOLOGICAL WORKS OF SIGMUND FREUD 24 VOLUMES
Beyond
the
Pleasure Principle
SIGMUND FREUD Translated and
Newly Edited
by
JAMES STRAGHEY Introduction by
GREGORY ZILBOORG
W-W-NORTON&COMPANY NEW YORK -LONDON
W. W. Norton
& Company, Inc.,
500 Fifth Avenue, N.Y. 10110 Company Ltd. 37 Great Russell Street,
New York, W. W. Norton
&
London COPYRIGHT
WC1B 3NU
1961 BY JAMES STRACHBY
Reprinted by arrangement with Liveright Publishing Corporation Introduction Copyright
ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Published simultaneously in Canada by Penguin Books Canada Ltd, 2801 John Street, Markham, Ontario L3R 1B4.
&
W. W. Norton Company, Inc. is also the publisher of the works of Erik H. Erikson, Otto Fenichel, Karen Homey, Harry Stack Sullivan, and The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Freud, Sigmund, 1856-1939 Beyond the pleasure principle. Translation of Jenseits des Lust-Prinzips. Reprint of the ed. published by Liveright, New York. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Pleasure. 2.
BF173.F65
Psychoanalysis.
1975
150.19'52
I.
Title.
74-22476
Printed in the United States of America
67890
ISBN 0-3*13-0071^-3
CONTENTS Introduction Editor's
vii
Note
xvii ""
Beyond
the Pleasure Principle
1
List of Abbreviations
59
Bibliography and Author Index
60
General Index
64
INTRODUCTION by Gregory Zilboorg, M.D.
A
QUESTION which seems natural and almost unavoidable What can one say about a book, and a little one at that, which is forty years old, and which is supposedly not one of the most impressive or "spectacular" bits of Freud's many writings? The question presupposes the implied answer that forty years even in our swift-moving world is a long time, that the book in question is therefore more or less superannuated and deserves but a respectful historical glance before we put it back on the shelf to gather more dust. It is obvious that the above is a rhetorical way of saying arises:
that forty years after its appearance and twenty years after Freud's death, Beyond the Pleasure Principle still deserves considerable attention, and that the reader would do well if he reads it with studious curiosity. Of recent years we have become so accustomed to the atmosphere of controversy
which surrounds psychoanalysis and Freud that we have almost lost our capacity to pick up a book on psychoanalysis without wanting to know in advance whether the book is for or against it, or, if it is for it, whether it is for Freud or for Jung, or, if it is Freudian, whether it is orthodox or neoFreudian. If we dared to be frank with ourselves, we would have no difficulty in admitting that our judgment of psychoanalysis is actually fragmentary and not too profound. We could also admit that some sort of partisanship possesses us, and that therefore we are preoccupied with "taking sides"
we
get acquainted with the very first elements of the subject. because of the various prejudices which have incul-
long before
psychoanalysis It is
and the many-sidedness of
cated themselves into psychoanalytical and nonpsychoanalytical circles that it is pertinent to invite both the initiated and the uninitiated reader to suspend his fragmentary judgment vii
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
viii
for a short while and re-read afresh the little book that is here offered, and acquaint or re-acquaint himself with the sound of Freud's written voice, with his way of saying things, and then with the substance of what he has to say. An introduction is not supposed to explain in advance
what
said in the book;
is
still less is it
meant
to interpret
it.
intended to clarify some shadows and point to certain lights which will possibly set the book in a proper Rather,
it is
perspective.
Bearing this in mind, let us first recall that Freud wrote Beyond the Pleasure Principle when he was sixty-four years old a mature age indeed and at a time when psychoanalysis had already achieved considerable popularity, even though it was still possible to assess the degree of its importance by the number of enemies it had. The tone of the book, the mannerisms of
Freud
its
it
style are vigorous, poignant,
seems was
still
almost controversial; combatting his opponents rather than
trying to instruct his proponents. his life,
Freud preserved
this
Almost to the
last
years of
combative vigor of writing, and
in Beyond the Pleasure Principle this aspect of style stands out markedly, particularly when he emphasizes his claim that he is a partisan of no special philosophy and that he is indifferent as to whether what he has to say does or does not fit any
known philosophy.
This claim for independence casts
is
characteristic of Freud's
and of all his writings, but I believe aspersion on his originality or his genius,
personality
it
in
no way
if I
say that this declaratory independence should not be taken too seriously. No one, and particularly no genius, is free of the
really ideological inheritance which he carries within himself as a child of a given generation. He not be
aware of it, of may Freud would have been the last man in the world to equate not being aware of something with its nonexistence. For it was of course Freud himself who discovered and uncourse, but
folded before us the staggering richness and power within us many things of which we are not aware. It is of some interest in this connection to recall that Freud denied ever having been acquainted with the writings of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche before he formulated many of his ideas. It was beyond any doubt an honest denial. Yet it is a matter of record that Hitschmann, one of the earliest ad-
of so
INTRODUCTION
ix
herents of Freud, read a paper in Freud's house as early as 1905 (Freud being present, of course) on the very subject of Nietzsche's ideas as compared with some of Freud's theories.
There
no doubt
whether or not Freud ever read of Morals, his was the temperament and the aspiration of a proud iconoclast who, to paraphrase an old saying of Maxim Gorki's, was born to soar and not to crawl, and for whom soaring accomplishment was not a pleasure in itself but a temporary level from which he is
Nietzsche's
that,
The Genealogy
strove to attain ever-greater heights. If we cast but a glance at the rough sketch of a general psychology which we find in Freud's letters to Fliess, we
cannot help but be struck by the depth, diapason and immense horizons which Freud envisaged as the culmination of his system. And these letters, we must remember, were written before 1900, that is to say, before the first book (The Interpretation of Dreams) which really launched psychoanalysis into the stormy waters of a world which never was able to approach the study of the psychology of man without prejudice and considerable animosity and controversy be it religious, scientific,
or plain pedestrian.
which Freud's mind was
The ambition
with
from the very
outset, and his particular goal of discovering, or uncovering, the real nature of man's mind, predestined him as a thinker and a man to fired
become a storm center
for years to come. was also a daring paradox, giving the semblance of self-contradiction, of inconsistency, and of all-solidity. Freud's apparent readiness to change his mind added a great number of dissenters and detractorsas if the scientist who has the courage to change his mind about some of his own ideas has
He
gained a point against himself. The great majority of people do confuse stubbornness for consistency, and rigidity of scientific ideas for soundness of position. At any rate, Beyond the Pleasure Principle is one of the first great landmarks in Freud's ways of "changing his mind." I put these words in quotes to cast at least a little doubt on the traditional attitude that Freud did change his mind in this instance. He did not. What Freud did here was to add a path or two, a little curve or fork, in the tortuous intellectual road which he followed with dogged faith in his own intellectual independence. The additions or added trends of thought
.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
x
cannot be fully grasped and even less understood unless one always bears in mind the inner psychological atmosphere in which Freud worked in order to express his ideas. His literary style was always terse, straightforward, clear and challengingly frank; but the same thing cannot be said about the emotional climate of his thought. First of all, Freud never gave up his belief I am tempted to say faith that the parallel he drew between Fechner's ideas in physics and his own in human psychology was not really a parallel but an actual proof that his concept of the mental apparatus and its energy was actually the same as Helmholtz' and Fechner's ideas about physical energy. To this faith he clung to the last, expressing the hope that some day the whole complexity of human reactions and relations could be reduced to some as yet undiscovered physico-chemical reactions. In other words, Freud remained an organicist throughout his scientific life. But genius and living paradox that he was, Freud was rejected by the materialists (conservative as well as Marxian) because of his alleged mysticism; and he was rejected by the idealists and religious thinkers because he was thought to be a materialist.
The
contradictions into which
Freud's detractors thus
stumbled remained unnoticed as a rule, but Freud was of course aware of them and saw in them merely a sign of general resistance. Yet it was not only that. To Freud the epithet, "mystic," was an expression of opprobrium, and yet it was Freud who stated that saints were saved from severe neuroses by their sainthood, their faith; he mentioned in this connection St. Francis of Assisi.
He who studies
the lives of the saints
would not a
easily issue to all of them, and without reservation, certificate of psychological health. They were saints because
they were able to stand the pressure of their respective neuroses rather than because they did not suffer from them. The lives of St. Ignatius
Loyola, or San Francisco Xavier, or St. Augustine for that matter, offer ample confirmation of my
viewpoint.
As one studies Freud, one can develop the strong suspicion he was more attracted by many mystics than by physicochemical hypotheses, and that he struggled with all the might that
of his great mind against openly giving in to the attraction of the mystical aspects of human life. In other words, the man
INTRODUCTION
xi
who less than twenty years after he wrote Beyond the Pleasure who Principle wrote his Moses and Monotheism, the man some five years before Beyond the Pleasure Principle wrote the article on Michelangelo's Moses, seems throughout this of span of time to have been preoccupied with the greatness human intuitions and the universality of human strivings not only to solve but to participate in the mysteries of life. And it is perhaps because of this inclination that Freud gave signs of "protesting too much." (Perhaps too this is one of the reasons why his article on Michelangelo's Moses appeared
first
anonymously;
it
was only much
later that
it
was admitted
that Freud, the Editor-in-chief of the Zeitschrift fur Psychoanalyse, was the real author of the article.)
While the complex question of Freud's intellectual strugwith his own ideas is far from solved, there is little doubt
gles
that the aggressive, trenchant, emphatic tone of his writings, full of conviction and devoid of doubt, does
which seem to be
not fully convey Freud's struggle with his own ideas, which at times must have reached heroic dimensions. It is because of Freud's aggressive candor, it seems to me, that his earliest followers seem more to have stood in awe, listening to his pronouncements, than actually to have assimilated his
thought like true disciples, ready to ask friendly
critical
questions in order to deepen and broaden the understanding of their master's thought. The very few of his followers who
were endowed with truly original minds and truly ambitious perspicacity and intuition soon broke with Freud; Jung is one of the few one can cite in this respect. The majority became either surly, hostile enemies rather than scientific opponentsor admiring, enthusiastic followers rather than scientific collaborators. It is therefore of particular interest to note that there was hardly a psychoanalyst outside Freud himself who ever made an original contribution to the theory and practice of psychoanalysis; this is particularly true of the time when Freud wrote his Beyond the Pleasure Principle. The one exception one can cite with certainty was Karl Abraham, who made an inestimable contribution to the clinical understanding of character formation and of depression, a contribution which
was spontaneously and "painlessly" incorporated into the body of psychoanalytic knowledge some five years before the
xii
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
appearance of Beyond the Pleasure Principle. But even in the case of Abraham things were not all clarity and sunshine; many of his colleagues were not very kindly disposed to the
man, and Freud himself, as Jones has written, said that he was suspicious of his "Prussian mind" Abraham being a Berliner.
All of the above amounts to saying that the constant and "true" followers of Freud were not very original minds; they were not mediocrities, but for some reason they would not
or perhaps could not "speak up'* until Freud spoke first. It is partly because of this that Beyond the Pleasure Principle acquired such significance in the history of the development of Freudian psychoanalysis. It acquired the reputation of a landmark in how Freud changed his mind and how daring he was in doing so. As a matter of cold fact, the book is an important contribution, a thrust forward in the growth of Freudian thought; but if one reads it carefully one will easily see that Freud did not change his mind, and that Beyond the Pleasure Principle did not overthrow any old psychoanalytic regime nor did it establish any new one. It was not even a small village revolution; it was and is a landmark of further development and a consolidation of the older pathways. Beyond the Pleasure Principle is what it says; it goes a little further beyond, but it does not abandon whatever preceded it. This writer lays no claim to an understanding of Freud's writing better than anyone's else who approaches Freud with the earnestness he deserves and the tolerance which is imperative, even now some twenty years after Freud's death. I say "even now" for the following reason; at the beginning
Freud had to
suffer from the many whose quick and ever misjudgment of him multiplied by thousands the number of his antagonists in every walk of the world's intellectual life. Today, with the full text of Freud at the disposal of every curious reader of the world, everybody claims Freud as his own, because everybody just as alertly is ready to interpret Freud in his own ivay. Thus a plethora of "schools" has mush-
alert
roomed
in the psychological literature, each claiming
its
philosophical, moral and scientific right to consider Freud its fons et origo, and its own exclusive right to understand Freud in its own exclusively correct way. This splintering of interpreters and misinterpreters of Freud is not unnatural, of
INTRODUCTION
xiii
course; the process will undoubtedly continue for some time before the real Freud will stand out in the history of our intellectual
development
we may look calmly and Since
it is
as a figure at
into
whom
not in anyone's power to slow down or to accelit cannot be the ambition
erate the salutary passage of time, of this writer to attempt to do so.
mate
whom and
objectively.
But
this
much
it is legiti-
him
to essay to do: to point out that the vigor of Freud's thought, stimulating as it has always been and is, is
for
frequently obscured by his at times too hasty terminological innovations. Not that one objects to such innovations, or that
one ought to insist on semantic hair-splitting; but Freud, whose clarity of thought and daring intellectual improvisations were always impressive and enlightening, suffered not infrequently from a certain confusion, at first unnoticeable but at length presenting an impediment to easy or clear understanding. Beyond the Pleasure Principle serves as an excellent example. First, there is the tendency which imperceptibly grew into assertive tradition that, having gone beyond the pleasure principle, he abandoned that principle. This, as I have already said, is not true. The reader, bearing this in mind, cannot fail but see it once the text is perused without prejudice, without the unwitting psychological twist which makes him read Beyond the Pleasure Principle and assume that the pleasure principle was left behind. We might as well state right here that the assiduous and faithful translators of Freud, in bringing before the English-speaking readers Freud's version of the pleasure-pain theory, did not help matters when they coined a neologism, "unpleasure." This awkward term is supposed to render somewhat accurately the German term Unlust. It is not an exactly successful rendition (except
etymologically, perhaps). The feeling of pain, of discomfort, of that disagreeable malaise which Freud has in mind is not
perceived as t/n-pleasure, for what we feel in this malaise we feel positively, and not negatively as a lack of something else. This point need not be labored; it is brought out here merely to illustrate how difficult it is to tell the reader what a given writer wants to say in a language his own, but not yours.
Now
let
allegedly
us ask ourselves what appears to be new and not as old in Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
abandoned
xiv
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
The concept of "compulsive repetition" or "repetition compulsion." Some still quarrel with this concept, some no longer do. The arguments for and against it are of no particular importance here. What is important is that new concepts, newly formulated, require greater clarity of definition. Freud discovered the repetitiveness of certain patterns of human behavior and the inevitability or, if you wish, the inescapable nature of this repetitiveness. And he called this
phenomenon
"repetition compulsion" or "compulsive repe-
tition."
We have become accustomed to the term "compulsion" when we speak of compulsion neuroses in other words, a neurosis which makes the sufferer therefrom aware that he is "compelled by something" to make this or that gesture or this or that turn or else he feels uncomfortable, uneasy, at
hardly necessary to go into more compulsive element of which Freud speaks when he speaks of compulsive repetition is something that the individual is not conscious of, that the compulsive element in this concept is something which is not neurotic at all, or not necessarily, and that it is just as or no more compulsive than breathing or the changing of the seasons. To use the term "compulsive" here connotes something that it is not and implies things which are not necessarily there a rather strange semantic fuzziness on the part of that uniquely clear-minded thinker. Such unclarities are strewn throughout many of Freud's writings and translations, and if they do not always confuse the casual reader or even the student, one would do well in being forewarned and therefore in reading and studying Freud with considerable caution and prudence. One more example: the second major innovation which Freud introduced into psychoanalytic thinking was the concept of the death instinct. Now we have become accustomed, particularly since Freud emphasized the role of instincts in the conscious and unconscious life of man, to consider an instinct a drive, an impulsive or perpetually compelling aspiration to gratify a need. In German, Freud uses the words Trieb and Trie b haft, which mean instinct, instinctual drive, a sense of being driven toward a certain even though not times plainly anxious.
It is
detail to observe that the
always comprehended goal. Under the circumstances, the term "death instinct" ought to mean an aspiration, a drive to
INTRODUCTION
xv
be dead. Perhaps Freud was right, even though neither the biologist nor the theologian would find it possible to agree with him. Let us assume that Freud was right; he certainly did not prove his case, because there is nothing instinctual about dying, even though the end is inevitable. Here again we find a strange semantic or terminological confusion, a tendency to use terms which are familiar to us in the psychoanalytic glossaries, but which in certain contexts become
somewhat confusing
The above
labels.
considerations
may
serve as a
warning that
it is
not easy to understand great minds even when they appear to speak simply, or perhaps especially when their language appears simple and the terminology familiar.
EDITOR'S NOTE JENSEITS DES LUSTPRINZIPS (a)
1920
GERMAN
EDITIONS:
Leipzig,
Vienna and Zurich; Interaationaler Psycho
analytischer Verlag. Pp. 60.
Same publishers. Pp. 64. Same publishers. Pp. 94.
1921
2nd
1923
3rd ed.
1925
G.S., 6, 191-257.
ed.
1931
Theoretische Schriften, 178-247.
1940
G.W., 13,3-69.
(b]
ENGLISH TRANSLATIONS: Beyond
1922
the Pleasure Principle
London and Vienna: Press. Pp. viii
+
International Psycho-Analytical
90. (Tr. G. J.
M. Hubback;
Pref.
Ernest Jones.)
1924 1942
New York: Boni and Liveright London: Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analy(Re-issue of above.) Publishers. Pp. vi 97. (Tr. J. Strachey.) S.K, 18, 3-64. (Modified version of above.) sis.
1950
1955
Same
+
Freud made a number of additions in the second
edition,
but
subsequent alterations were negligible. The present translation is a corrected reprint of the Standard Edition version.
As is shown by his correspondence, Freud had begun working on a first draft of Beyond the Pleasure Principle in March, 1919, and he reported the draft as finished in the following May. During the same month he was completing his paper on 'The Uncanny* (1919A), which includes a paragraph setting out much of the gist of the present work in a few sentences. In this paragraph he refers to the 'compulsion to repeat' as a phenomenon exhibited in the behaviour of children and in psychoanalytic treatment; he suggests that this compulsion is something derived from the most intimate nature of the instincts; and he declares that it is powerful enough to disregard the xvii
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
xviii
no allusion to the 'death pleasure principle. There is, however, He adds that he has already completed a detailed
instincts*.
The paper on 'The Uncanny' consummary was published in the autumn of 1919.
exposition of the subject. taining this
But Freud held back Beyond the Pleasure Principle for another In the early part of 1920 he was once more at work on it, and now, for the first time apparently, there is a reference to the 'death instincts' in a letter to Eitingon of February 20. He was still revising the work in May and June and it was finally completed by the middle ofJuly, 1920. On September 9, he gave an address to the International Psycho-Analytical Congress
year.
The Hague, with the title 'Supplements to the Theory of Dreams' (Ergdnzungen zur Traumlekre), in which he announced the approaching publication of the book; it was issued early in December. An 'author's abstract' of the address appeared in Int. %. PsychoawL, 6 (1920), 397-8. (A translation of this was published in Int. J. Psycho-Anal^ 1, 354.) It does not seem certain that this abstract was in fact by Freud himself, but it may be of interest to reprint it here (in a new translation). at
'Supplements to the Theory of Dreams
9
The speaker dealt in his brief remarks with three points touching upon the theory of dreams. The first two of these were concerned with the thesis that dreams are wish-fulfilments and brought forward some necessary modifications of it. The third point related to material which brought complete confirmation of his rejection of the alleged "prospective" purposes of dreams. 1 "The speaker explained that, alongside the familiar wishful dreams and the anxiety dreams which could easily be included in the theory, there were grounds for recognizing the existence of a third category, to which he gave the name of "punishment dreams". If we took into account the justifiable assumption of the existence of a special self-observing and critical agency in the ego (the ego ideal, the censor, conscience), these punishment dreams, too, should be subsumed under the theory of wish-fulfilment; for they would represent the fulfilment of a wish on the part of this critical agency. Such dreams, he said, had approximately the same relation to ordinary wishful dreams 1
[See The Interpretation of Dreams, 1900
506-7
.]
VI
(I),
Standard Ed., 5,
EDITOR'S NOTE
xix
symptoms of obsessional neurosis, which arise from rehad to those of hysteria. 'Another class of dreams, however, seemed to the speaker to present a more serious exception to the rule that dreams are
as the
action formation,
wish-fulfilments.
These were the so-called "traumatic" dreams.
in patients suffering from accidents, but they also occur during psycho-analyses of neurotics and bring back to them forgotten traumas of childhood. In connection with the
They occur
fitting these dreams into the theory of wish-fulfilment, the speaker referred to a work shortly to be published under the title of Beyond the Pleasure Principle. 'The third point of the speaker's communication related to an investigation that had not yet been published, by Dr. Varendonck of Ghent. This author had succeeded in bringing under his conscious observation the production of unconscious phantasies on an extensive scale in a half-sleeping state a process which he described as "autistic thinking". It appeared from this enquiry that looking ahead at the possibilities of the next
problem of
day, preparing attempts at solutions and adaptations, etc., lay wholly within the range of this preconscious activity, which also created latent dream-thoughts, and, as the speaker had x always maintained, had nothing to do with the dream-work.'
In the
of Freud's metapsychological writings, Beyond may be regarded as introducing the final phase of his views. He had already drawn attention to the 'compulsion to repeat* as a clinical phenomenon, but here he attributes to it the characteristics of an instinct; here too for the first time he brings forward the new Dichotomy between Eros and the death instincts which found its full elaboration in The Ego and the Id (1923). In Beyond the Pleasure Principle, too, we can see signs of the new picture of the anatomical structure of the mind which was to dominate all Freud's later writings. Finally, the problem of destructiveness, which played an ever series
the Pleasure Principle
more prominent part explicit appearance.
in his theoretical works, makes its first derivation of various elements in the
The
present discussion from his earlier metapsychological works Two Principles of Mental Functioning' (191 1),
such as 'The
1 Cf. Freud's own preface to this book of Varendonck's (Freud, 1921 b, Standard Ed., 18, 271).
xx
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
(1914*:) and 'Instincts and their Vicissitudes' will be obvious. But what is particularly remarkable (1915^) is the closeness with which some of the earlier sections of the present work follow the 'Project for a Scientific Psychology* (19500), drafted by Freud twenty-five years earlier, in 1895.
'Narcissism*
Extracts from the earlier (1922) translation of this work were included in Rickman's General Selection from the Works of Sigmund Freud (1937, 162-194). Editorial additions, whether to the text or the footnotes, are
printed in square brackets.
Beyond the Pleasure Principle
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE IN the theory of psycho-analysis we have no hesitation in assuming that the course taken by mental events is automatically regulated by the pleasure principle. We believe, that is to say, that the course of those events
is
unpleasurable tension, and that
invariably set in motion by an it takes a direction such that
outcome coincides with a lowering of that tension that with an avoidance of unpleasure or a production of pleasure. In taking that course into account in our consideration of the mental processes which are the subject of our study, we are introducing an 'economic' point of view into our work; and if, its final is,
in describing those processes, we try to estimate this 'economic' factor in addition to the 'topographical' and 'dynamic* ones,
we
shall, I think,
be giving the most complete description of
them of which we can at present conceive, and one which deserves to be distinguished by the term 'metapsychologicaT. 1 It far,
is
of no concern to us in this connection to enquire how this hypothesis of the pleasure principle, we have
with
approached or adopted any particular,
historically established,
We
have arrived at these speculative philosophical system. assumptions in an attempt to describe and to account for the of daily observation in our field of study. Priority and originality are not among the aims that psycho-analytic work facts
and the impressions that underlie the hypothesis of the pleasure principle are so obvious that they can scarcely be overlooked. On the other hand we would readily express our sets itself;
gratitude to any philosophical or psychological theory which was able to inform us of the meaning of the feelings of pleasure
and unpleasure which act point
we
are, alas, offered
so imperatively upon us. But on this nothing to our purpose. This is the
most obscure and inaccessible region of the mind, and, since avoid contact with it, the least rigid hypothesis, it seems to me, will be the best. We have decided to relate
we cannot 1
[See Section
IV
of 'The Unconscious' (1915*).] 1
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
2
and unpleasure to the quantity of excitation that is * is not in any way 'bound*; and to present in the mind but relate them in such a manner that unpleasure corresponds to an increase in the quantity of excitation and pleasure to a diminution. What we are implying by this is not a simple relation
pleasure
feelings ^f pleasure and unpleasure and the corresponding modifications in the quantity of excitain view of all we have been taught by psychotion; least of all
between the strength of the
physiology are we suggesting any directly proportional ratio: the factor that determines the feeling is probably the amount of increase or diminution in the quantity of excitation in a given
Experiment might possibly play a part here; but not advisable for us analysts to go into the problem further so long as our way is not pointed by quite definite
period of time. it
is
observations.*
We cannot, however, remain indifferent to the discovery that an investigator of such penetration as G. T. Fechner held a view on the subject of pleasure and unpleasure which coincides in all essentials with the one that has been forced upon us by psycho-analytic work. Fechner's statement is to be found contained in a small work, Einige Idem zur Schopfiings- und Entwick1873 (Part XI, Supplement, 94), and reads as follows: 'In so far as conscious impulses always have some relation to pleasure or unpleasure, pleasure and
lungsgeschichte der Organismen,
unpleasure too can be regarded as having a psycho-physical relation to conditions of stability and instability. This provides a
a hypothesis into which I propose to enter in greater According to this hypothesis, every psychophysical motion rising above the threshold of consciousness is attended by pleasure in proportion as, beyond a certain limit, it approximates to complete stability, and as attended by unpleasure in proportion as, beyond a certain limit, it deviates from complete stability; while between the two limits, which may be described as qualitative thresholds of pleasure and
basis for
detail elsewhere.
1 [The concepts of 'quantity* and of 'bound* excitation, which run through the whole of Freud's writings, found what is perhaps their most detailed discussion in the early 'Project* (1950<x [1895]). See in particular the long discussion of the term 'bound* near the end of Section 1 of Part III of that work. See also p. 28 f. below.] 1 [This point is again mentioned below on p. 57 and further developed in 'The Economic Problem of Masochism* (1924s).]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE unpleasure, 1 ence. . . .'
The
facts
there
is
3
a certain margin of aesthetic indiffer-
which have caused us to believe in the dominance
of the pleasure principle in mental life also find expression in the hypothesis that the mental apparatus endeavours to keep the quantity of excitation present in it as low as possible or at keep it constant. This latter hypothesis is only another
least to
of stating the pleasure principle; for if the work of the mental apparatus is directed towards keeping the quantity of excitation low, then anything that is calculated to increase that quantity is bound to be felt as adverse to the functioning of the
way
apparatus, that is as unpleasurable. The pleasure principle from the principle of constancy: actually the latter principle was inferred from the facts which forced us to adopt
follows
the pleasure principle.* Moreover, a more detailed discussion will show that the tendency which we thus attribute to the
mental apparatus is subsumed as a special case under Fechner's principle of the 'tendency towards stability', to which he has brought the feelings of pleasure and unpleasure into relation. It must be pointed out, however, that strictly speaking it is incorrect to talk of the dominance of the pleasure principle over the course of mental processes. If such a dominance existed, the immense majority of our mental processes would have to be accompanied by pleasure or to lead to pleasure, whereas universal experience completely contradicts any such con-
The most that can be said, therefore, is that there exists mind a strong tendency towards the pleasure principle, but that that tendency is opposed by certain other forces or circumstances, so that the final outcome cannot always be in harmony clusion.
in the
1 'Aesthetic* is here used in [Cf. 'Project', end of Section 8 of Part I. the old sense of 'relating to sensation or perception'.] * [The 'principle of constancy' dates back to the very beginning of Freud's psychological studies. The first published discussion of it of any length was by Breuer (in semi-physiological terms) towards the end of Section 2 (A) of his theoretical part of the Studies on Hysteria (Breuer and Freud, 1895). He there defines it as 'the tendency to keep intracerebral excitation constant*. In the same passage he attributes this principle to Freud and there in fact exist one or two earlier very brief references to it by Freud himself, though these were not published until after his
death. (See Freud, 1941* [1892] and Breuer and Freud, 1940 [1892].) subject is also discussed at length at the beginning of Freud's 'Project', under the name of 'neuronic inertia*.]
The
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLB
4
We
with the tendency towards pleasure. may compare what Fechner (1873, 90) remarks on a similar point: 'Since however a tendency towards an aim does not imply that the aim is attained,
and
since in general the
tions.
*
.
aim
is
attainable only
by approxima-
.'
If we turn
now to the question of what circumstances are able
to prevent the pleasure principle from being carried into effect, we find ourselves once more on secure and well-trodden ground
and, in framing our answer, we have at our disposal a rich fund of analytic experience. The first example of the pleasure principle being inhibited in this way is a familiar one which occurs with regularity. We know that the pleasure principle is proper to a primary method of working on the part of the mental apparatus, but that, from the point of view of the self-preservation of the organism among the difficulties of the external world, it is from the very outset inefficient and even highly dangerous. Under the influence of the ego's instincts of self-preservation, the pleasure principle is 1 replaced by the reality principle, This latter principle does not abandon the intention of ultimately obtaining pleasure, but it nevertheless demands and carries into effect the postponement of satisfaction, the abandonment of a number of possibilities of gaining satisfaction and the temporary toleration of unpleasure as a step on the long indirect road to pleasure. The pleasure principle long persists, however, as the method of working employed by the sexual instincts, which are so hard to 'educate*, and, starting from those instincts, or in the ego itself, it often succeeds in overcoming the reality principle, to the detriment of the organism as a whole. There can be no doubt, however, that the replacement of the reality principle can only be made number, and by no means the most intense, of unpleasurable experiences. Another occasion of the release of unpleasure, which occurs with no less regularity, is to be found in the conflicts and dissensions that take place in the mental apparatus while the ego is passing through its develop-
pleasure principle
by the
responsible for a small
ment into more highly composite organizations. Almost all the energy with which the apparatus is filled arises from its innate instinctual impulses. But these are not all allowed to reach 1
[See 'Formulations
Freud 191 U.]
on the
Two
Principles of
Mental Functioning',
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
5
same phases of development. In the course of things it that individual instincts or parts of happens again and again instincts turn out to be incompatible in their aims or demands the
with the remaining ones, which are able to combine into the The former are then split off from this unity by the process of repression, held back at lower levels
inclusive unity of the ego.
of psychical development and cut off, to begin with, from the of satisfaction. If they succeed subsequently, as can possibility so easily happen with repressed sexual instincts, in struggling through, by roundabout paths, to a direct or to a substitutive
which would in other cases have been an is felt by the ego as unpleasure. As a consequence of the old conflict which ended in repression, a
satisfaction, that event,
opportunity for pleasure,
new breach has occurred in the pleasure principle at the very time when certain instincts were endeavouring, in accordance with the principle, to obtain fresh pleasure. The details of the process by which repression turns a possibility of pleasure into a source of unpleasure are not yet clearly understood or cannot be clearly represented; but there is no doubt that all neurotic 1 unpleasure is of that kind pleasure that cannot be felt as such. The two sources of unpleasure which I have just indicated are very far from covering the majority of our unpleasurable But as regards the remainder it can be asserted with
experiences.
some show ofjustification that their presence does not contradict the dominance of the pleasure principle. Most of the unpleasure that we experience is perceptual unpleasure. It may be perception of pressure by unsatisfied instincts; or it may be external perception which is either distressing in itself or which excites un-
pleasurable expectations in the mental apparatus that is, 1 is recognized by it as a 'danger . The reaction to these
which
instinctual
demands and
threats of danger, a reaction
which
constitutes the proper activity of the mental apparatus, can then be directed in a correct manner by the pleasure principle
or the reality principle by which the former is modified. This does not seem to necessitate any far-reaching limitation of the mental pleasure principle. Nevertheless the investigation of the reaction to external danger is precisely in a position to produce new material and raise fresh questions bearing upon our
present problem. i
[Footnote added 1925:]
No
doubt the
and unpleasure, being conscious
essential point is that pleasure attached to the ego.
feelings, are
II
A CONDITION has long been known
and described which occurs
mechanical concussions, railway disasters and other accidents involving a risk to life; it has been given the name of after severe
The terrible war which has just ended gave a great number of illnesses of this kind, but it at least put an end to the temptation to attribute the cause of the disorder to organic lesions of the nervous system brought about by 'traumatic neurosis'.
rise to
mechanical force. 1 The symptomatic picture presented by traumatic neurosis approaches that of hysteria in the wealth of its similar motor symptoms, but surpasses it as a rule in its strongly marked signs of subjective ailment (in which it resembles hypochondria or melancholia) as well as in the evidence it gives of a far more comprehensive general enfeeblement and disturbance of the mental capacities. No complete explanation has yet been reached either of war neuroses or of the traumatic neuroses of peace. In the case of the war neuroses, the fact that the
same symptoms sometimes came about without the
inter-
vention of any gross mechanical force seemed at once enlightening and bewildering. In the case of the ordinary traumatic neuroses two characteristics emerge prominently: first, that the chief weight in their causation seams to rest upon the factor of surprise, of fright; and secondly, that a wound or injury inflicted simultaneously works as a rule against the development 9 of a neurosis. 'Fright , 'fear* and 'anxiety' 2 are improperly used as synonymous expressions; they are in fact of clear dis-
capable
tinction in their relation to danger. 'Anxiety' describes a particular state of expecting the danger or preparing for it, even
may be an unknown one. Tear' requires a definite object of which to be afraid. 'Fright', however, is the name we give to the state a person gets into when he has run into danger
though
it
without being prepared for it; it emphasizes the factor of surprise. I do not believe anxiety can produce a traumatic neuro1 Cf. the discussion on the psycho-analysis of war neuroses by Freud, Fcrenczi, Abraham, Simmel and Jones (1919) [to which Freud provided the introduction (1919
6
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
7
There is something about anxiety that protects its subject shall return against fright and so against fright-neuroses. 1 to this point later [p. 25 f.].
sis.
We
The study of dreams may be considered the most trustworthy method of investigating deep mental processes. Now dreams occurring in traumatic neuroses have the characteristic of repeatedly bringing the patient back into the situation of his accident, a situation from which he wakes up in another fright. This astonishes people far too litde. They think the fact that the traumatic experience is constantly forcing itself upon the patient even in his sleep is a proof of the strength of that experience: the patient is, as one might say, fixated to his traumaFixations to the experience which started the illness have long been familiar to us in hysteria. Breuer and Freud declared in 1893 * that 'hysterics suffer mainly from reminiscences'. In the war neuroses, too, observers like Ferenczi and Simmel have been able to explain certain motor symptoms by fixation to the moment at which the trauma occurred. I am not aware, however, that patients suffering from traumatic neurosis are much occupied in their waking lives \vith
memories of then* accident Perhaps they are more concerned with not thinking of it. Anyone who accepts it as something selfevident that their dreams should put them back at night into
them to fall ill has misunderstood the nature of dreams. It would be more in harmony with their nature if they showed the patient pictures from his healthy past or of the cure for which he hopes. If we are not to be shaken in our belief in the wish-fulfillinfi tenor of dreams by the dreams of traumatic neurotics, we still have one resource open to us: we may argue that the function of dreaming, like so much else, is upset in this condition and diverted from its purposes, or we the situation that caused
1
is very far indeed from always carrying out the distinche makes here. More often than not he uses the word Angst* to denote a state of fear without any reference to the future. It seems not unlikely that in this passage he is beginning to adumbrate the distinction drawn in Inhibitions^ Symptoms and Anxiety (1926^) between anxiety as a reaction to a traumatic situation probably equivalent to what is here called Sckrech and anxiety as a warning signal of the approach of* such an event. See also his use of the phrase 'preparedness for anxiety* on
[Freud
4
tion
p. 25.] *
['On the Psychical Mechanism of Hysterical Phenomena*, end of
Section
I.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
8
be driven to oTthe egoT1
may
reflect
on the mysterious masochistic Jrcnds :
At this point I propose to leave the dark and dismal subject of the traumatic neurosis and pass on to examine the method of working employed by the mental apparatus in one of its earliest normal activities
The
I
mean
in children's play.
have only recently been summarized and discussed from the psycho-analytic point of view by Pfeifer (1919), to whose paper I would refer my readers. These theories attempt to discover the motives which different theories of children's play
lead children to play, but they fail to bring into the foreground the economic motive, the consideration of the yield of pleasure involved. Without wishing to include the whole field covered
by these phenomena, I have been able, through a chance opportunity which presented itself to throw some light upon the first game played by a little boy of one and a half and invented was more than a mere fleeting observation, for I under the same roof as the child and his parents for some weeks, and it was some time before I discovered the meaning of the puzzling activity which he constantly repeated. The child was not at all precocious in his intellectual development. At the age of one and a half he could say only a few comprehensible words; he could also make use of a number of sounds which expressed a meaning intelligible to those around him. He was, however, on good terms with his parents and their one servant-girl, and tributes were paid to his being a 'good boy*. He did not disturb his parents at night, he conscientiously
by
himself. It
lived
obeyed orders not to touch certain things or go into certain rooms, and above all he never cried when his mother left him for a few hours. At the same time, he was greatly attached to
who had not only fed him herself but had also him without any outside help. This good little boy, however, had an occasional disturbing habit of taking any small objects he could get hold of and throwing them away from him into a corner, under the bed, and so on, so that hunting for his toys and picking them up was often quite a business. As he did
his
mother, looked after
he gave vent to a loud, long-drawn-out e o-o-o-o*, accompanied by an expression of interest and satisfaction. His mother this
1
[The last 15 words of this sentence were added in 1921. see The Interpretation of Dreams (IQQQa),. Standard Ed., 5, 550
For ff.]
all this
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
9
and the writer of the present account were agreed in thinking was not a mere interjection but represented the German word 'for? ['gone']. I eventually realized that it was a game and that the only use he made of any of his toys was to with them. One day I made an observation which play 'gone' confirmed my view. The child had a wooden reel with a piece of string tied round it. It never occurred to him to pull it along the floor behind him, for instance, and play at its being a carriage. What he did was to hold the reel by the string and very skilfully throw it over the edge of his curtained cot, so that it disappeared into it, at the same time uttering his expressive o-o-o-o*. He then pulled the reel out of the cot again by the string and hailed its reappearance with a joyful da* ['there*]. that this
(
(
This, then, was the complete game disappearance and return. As a rule one only witnessed its first act, which was repeated
untiringly as a
in itself, though there is no doubt that the was attached to the second act. 1 The interpretation of the game then became obvious. It was related to the child's great cultural achievement the in-
game
greater pleasure
stinctual renunciation (that
is,
the renunciation of instinctual
which he had made in allowing his mother to go away without protesting. He compensated himself for this, as it were, by himself staging the disappearance and return of the
satisfaction)
objects within his reach. It is of course a matter of indifference from the point of view of judging the effective nature of the game whether the child invented it himself or took it over on
suggestion. Our interest is directed to another point. The child cannot possibly have felt his mother's departure as something agreeable or even indifferent. then does his repetition of this distressing experience as a game fit in with the pleasure principle? It may perhaps be said in reply that her
some outside
How
departure had to be enacted as a necessary preliminary to her joyful return, and that it was in the latter that lay the true purpose
*A
further observation subsequently confirmed this interpretation the child's mother had been away for several hours and on her return was met with the words 'Baby o-o-o-ol* which was at first incomprehensible. It soon turned out, however, that during this long period of solitude the child had found a method of making himself disappear. He had discovered his reflection in a full-length mirror which did not quite reach to the ground, so that by crouching down he could make his mirror-image 'gone'. [A further reference to this story will be found in The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Ed., 5, 46 In.] fully.
One day
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
10
of the game. But against
this
must be counted the observed
fact that the first act, that of departure, was staged as a game in itself and far more frequently than the episode in its entirety,
with
its
pleasurable ending. certain decision can be reached
from the analysis of a an unprejudiced view one gets an imsingle case like this. a game from pression that the child turned his experience into
No
On
another motive. At the outset he was in a passive situation he was overpowered by the experience; but, by repeating it, unpleasurable though it was, as a game, he took on an active to an instinct for mastery part. These efforts might be put down that was acting independently of whether the memory was in itself pleasurable or not. But still another interpretation may be attempted. Throwing away the object so that it was 'gone' might satisfy an impulse of the child's, which was suppressed in his actual life, to revenge himself on his mother for going away from him. In that case it would have a defiant meaning: *A11 right, then, go away! I don't need you. I'm sending you away myself.' A year later, the same boy whom I had observed at his first game used to take a toy, if he was angry with it, and throw it on the floor, exclaiming: 'Go to the fwont!' He had heard at that time that his absent father was *at the front', and was far from regretting his absence; on the contrary he made it quite clear that he had no desire to be disturbed in his sole possession of his mother. 1
We know of other children who liked to express
similar hostile impulses by throwing away objects instead of 8 are therefore left in doubt as to whether the persons.
We
impulse to work over in the mind some overpowering experience so as to make oneself master of it can find expression as a primary event, and independently of the pleasure principle. For, in the case we have been discussing, the child may, after all, only have been able to repeat his unpleasant experience in play because the repetition carried along with it a yield of pleasure of another sort but none the less a direct one.
Nor shall we be helped in our hesitation between these two views by further considering children's play. It is clear that in 1
When
Now
was five and three-quarters, his mother died. really 'gone' ('o-o-o'), the little boy showed no signs of grief. It is true that in the interval a second child had been born and had roused him to violent jealousy* that sire
1
Cf.
this child
was
my note on a childhood memory of Goethe's
(1917 b).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
11
their play children repeat everything that has made a great impression on them in real life, and that in doing so they abreact the strength of the impression and, as one might put
make themselves master of the situation. But on the other hand it is obvious that all their play is influenced by a wish that dominates them the whole time the wish to be grown-up and to be able to do what grown-up people do. It can also be observed that the unpleasurable nature of an experience does it,
not always unsuit it for play. If the doctor looks down a child's throat or carries out some small operation on him, we may be quite sure that these frightening experiences will be the subject
we must not in that connection overlook a yield of pleasure from another source. As the child passes over from the passivity of the experience to the activity of the game, he hands on the disagreeable experiof the next game; but the fact that there
is
ence to one of his playmates and in on a substitute.
this
way
revenges himself
Nevertheless, it emerges from this discussion 'that there is no need to assume the existence of a special imitative instinct in order to provide a motive for play. Finally, a reminder may be added that the artistic play and artistic imitation carried out by adults, which, unlike children's, are aimed at an audience, do not spare the spectators (for instance, in tragedy) the most painful experiences and can yet be felt by them as highly enjoyable. 1 This is convincing proof that, even under the dominance of the pleasure principle, there are ways and means enough of making what is in itself unpleasurable into a subject to be recollected and worked over ih the mind. The consideration of these cases and situations, which have a yield of pleasure as their final outcome, should be undertaken by some system of aesthetics with an economic approach to its subject-matter.
They
no use for our purposes, since they presuppose the and dominance of the pleasure principle; they give
are of
existence
no evidence of the operation of tendencies beyond the pleasure more primitive than it and inprinciple, that is, of tendencies dependent of it. * his posthumously [Freud had made a tentative study of this point in on the Stage' (1942a) published paper on 'Psychopathic Characters which was probably written in 1905 or 1906.]
Ill
years of intense work have had as their result that the immediate aims of psycho-analytic technique are quite
TWENTV-HVE
other to-day than they were at the outset. At first the analysing more than discover the unconscious physician could do no material that was concealed from the patient, put it together, and, at the right moment, communicate it to him. Psycho-
was then
analysis
first
and foremost an
art of interpreting.
Since this did not solve the therapeutic problem, a further aim to oblige the patient to confirm the quickly came in view: from his own memory. In that endeavour construction analyst's
upon the patient's resistances: the art in uncovering these as quickly as possible, in out to the patient and in inducing him by human
the chief emphasis lay consisted
now
pointing them
was where suggestion operating as 'transference* to abandon his resistances. But it became ever clearer that the aim which had been set up the aim that what was unconscious should become conis not scious completely attainable by that method. The remember the whole of what is repressed in him, cannot patient and what he cannot remember may be precisely the essential part of it. Thus he acquires no sense of conviction of the correctness of the construction that has been communicated to
influence
played
its
this
part
He is obliged to repeat the repressed material as a contemporary experience instead of, as the physician would prefer 1 to see, remembering it as something belonging to the past. These reproductions, which emerge with such unwished-for exactitude, always have as their subject some portion of infantile
him.
of the Oedipus complex, that is, and its derivatives; life and they are invariably acted cut in the sphere of the trans-
sexual
When
ference, of the patient's relation to the physician. things have reached this stage, it may be said that the earlier neurosis
has 1
now been replaced by a fresh,
'transference neurosis'. It has
paper on 'Recollecting, Repeating and Working Through* (1914). [An early reference will be found in this same paper to the 'compulsion to repeat', which is one of the principle topics discussed in the present work. (See also the Editor's Note above, p. xi.) The term See
my
'transference neurosis' in the special sense in down also appears in that paper.]
lower
12
which
it is
used a few lines
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
13
been the physician's endeavour to keep this transference neurowithin the narrowest limits: to force as much as possible into the channel of memory and to allow as little as possible to emerge as repetition. Th$ ratio between what is remembered and what is reproduced varies from case to case. The physician cannot as a rule spare his patient this phase of the treatment. He must get him to re-experience some portion of his forgotten life, but must see to it, on the other hand, that the patient retains some degree of aloofness, which will enable him, in spite of everything, to recognize that what appears to be reality is in fact only a reflection of a forgotten past. If this can be successfully achieved, the patient's sense of conviction is won, together sis
with the therapeutic success that is dependent on it. In order to make it easier to understand this 'compulsion to repeat', which emerges during the psycho-analytic treatment of neurotics, we must above all get rid of the mistaken notion that what we are dealing with in our struggle against resistances is resistance on the part of the unconscious. The unconscious offers no resistance whatever to that is to say, the 'repressed* the efforts of the treatment. Indeed, it itself has no other endeavour than to break through the pressure weighing down on it and force its way either to consciousness or to a discharge through some real action. Resistance during treatment arises from the same higher strata and systems of the mind which originally carried out repression. But the fact that, as we know from experience, the motives of the resistances, and indeed the resistances themselves, are unconscious at first -during the treatment, is a hint to us that we should correct a shortcoming in our terminology. We shall avoid a lack of clarity if we make our contrast not between the conscious and the unconscious but between the coherent ego l and the repressed. It is certain that much of the ego is itself unconscious, and notably what we may describe as its nucleus; 2 only a small part of it is covered by the
term 'preconscious'. 3 Having replaced a purely descriptive 1
[Cf. a discussion of this in the Editor's Introduction to The Ego and Id (1923ft), Standard Ed., 19, 7-8; I.P.L., 12, xiii-xiv.] [This is corrected in a footnote at the beginning of Chapter III of The Ego and the Id, ibid., 28, and ibid., 16.] 3 [In its present form this sentence dates from 192 1 In the first edition (1920) it ran: 'It may be that much of the ego is itself unconscious; only a part of it, probably, is covered by the term "preconscious'V]
the
*
.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
14
terminology by one which is systematic or dynamic, we can say 1 that the patient's resistance arises from his ego, and we then at once perceive that the compulsion to repeat must be ascribed to the unconscious repressed. It seems probable that the comitself after
pulsion can only express
the
work of treatment has
meet it and has loosened the repression. 2 gone There is no doubt that the resistance of the conscious and unconscious ego operates under the sway of the pleasure prinavoid the unpleasure which would be produced ciple: it seelcs to of the repressed. Our efforts, on the other hand, liberation the by half-way to
are directed towards procuring the toleration of that unpleasure by an appeal to the reality principle. But how is the compulsion to repeat the manifestation of the power of the repressed related to the pleasure principle? It is clear that the greater part of what is re-experienced under the compulsion to repeat must
cause the ego unpleasure, since it brings to light activities of repressed instinctual impulses. That, however, is unpieasure of a kind we have already considered and does not contradict the pleasure principle : unpleasure for one system and simultaneously 3 satisfaction for the other. But we come now to a new and re-
markable fact, namely that the compulsion to repeat also recalls from the past experiences which include no possibility of pleasure, and which can never, even long ago, have brought satisfaction even to instinctual impulses which have since been '
repressed.
The early efflorescence of infantile sexual life is doomed to extinction because its wishes are incompatible with reality and with the inadequate stage of development which the child has comes to an end in the most disand to the accompaniment of the most painful feelings. Loss of love and failure leave behind them a permanent injury to self-regard in the form of a narcissistic scar, which in my opinion, as well as in Marcinowski's (1918), contributes more than anything to the 'sense of inferiority' reached.
That
efflorescence
tressing circumstances
1
[A fuller and somewhat different account of the sources of resistance be found in Chap.
XI
Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety (1926^).] have argued elsewhere [1923<] that what thus comes to the help of the compulsion to repeat is the factor of
\vill
*
of
[Footnote added 1923:] I
"suggestion' in the treatment which has its roots
physician,
that
is,
deep in
*
the patient's submissiveness to the his unconscious parental complex.
[C Freud's allegorical use of the fairy tale of the 'Three Wishes* at the beginning of Lecture of his Introductory Lectures (1916-17).]
XIV
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
15
which is so common in neurotics. The child's sexual researches, on which limits are imposed by his physical development, lead to no satisfactory conclusion; hence such later complaints as *I
can't accomplish anything; I can't succeed in anything*. The of affection, which binds the child as a rule to the parent of
tie
succumbs to disappointment, to a vain exof satisfaction or to jealousy over the birth of a new pectation baby unmistakable proof of the infidelity of the object of the child's affections. His own attempt to make a baby himself, carried out with tragic seriousness, fails shamefully. The lessening amount of affection he receives, the increasing demands the opposite sex,
of education, hard words and an occasional punishment these at last the full extent to which he has been scorned.
show him
These are a few typical and constantly recurring instances of the ways in which the love characteristic of the age of childhood is brought to a conclusion. Patients repeat all of these unwanted situations and painful emotions in the transference and revive them with the greatest ingenuity. They seek to bring about the interruption of the treatment while it is still incomplete; they contrive once more to feel themselves. scorned, to oblige the physician to
them and
speak
them
coldly; they discover approfor their jealousy; instead of the passionately priate objects desired baby of their childhood, they produce a plan or a
severely to
treat
some grand present which turns out as a rule to be promise of less unreal. None of these tilings can have produced pleasure in the past, and it might be supposed that they would cause less unpleasure to-day if they emerged as memories or dreams instead of taking the form of fresh experiences. They are of course the activities of instincts intended to lead to satisfaction; but no lesson has been learnt from the old experience of these 1 activities having led instead only to unpleasure. In spite of that, a of are under compulsion. they pressure repeated, What psycho-analysis reveals in the transference phenomena of neurotics can also be observed in the lives of some normal is of being pursued by a maligpeople. The impression they give nant fate or possessed by some 'daemonic' power; but psychoanalysis has always taken the view that their fate is for the most themselves and determined by early infantile part arranged by influences. The compulsion which is here in evidence differs in 1 [This sentence was added in 192 1.] no
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE no way from the compulsion to repeat which we have found in neurotics, even though the people we are now considering have 16
never shown any signs of dealing with a neurotic conflict by Thus we have come across people all of producing symptoms. whose human relationships have the same outcome: such as the benefactor who is abandoned in anger after a time by each of his protigiS) however much they may otherwise differ from one another, and who thus seems doomed to taste all the bitterness
of ingratitude; or the man whose friendships all end in betrayal by his friend; or the man who time after time in the course of his life raises someone else into a position of great private or certain interval, himself uppublic authority and then, after a sets that authority and replaces him by a new one; or, again, the lover each of whose love affairs with a woman passes
through the same phases and reaches the same conclusion. This 'perpetual recurrence of the same thing* causes us no astonishment when it relates to active behaviour on the part of the person concerned and when we can discern in him an essential character-trait which always remains the same and which is comof the same experiences. pelled to find expression in a repetition
We are much more impressed by cases where the subject appears to have a passive experience, over which he has no influence, but in which he meets with a repetition of the same fatality. There is the case, for instance, of the woman who married three successive husbands each of whom fell ill soon afterwards and had to be nursed by her on their death-beds. 1 The most moving poetic picture of a fate such as this is given by Tasso in his romantic epic Gerusalemme Liberate. Its hero, Tancred, unwittingly frillg his beloved Clorinda in a duel while she is disguised in the armour of an enemy knight. After her burial he
makes
his
way into a army with
strange magic forest which
terror. He slashes with his but blood streams from the cut and the voice of Clorinda, whose soul is imprisoned in the tree, is heard complaining that he has wounded his beloved once again. If we take into account observations such as these, based upon behaviour in the transference and upon the life-histories of men and women, we shall find courage to assume that there really does exist in the mind a compulsion to repeat which overrides the pleasure principle. Now too we shall be inclined to 1 Cf. the apt remarks on this subject by C, G. Jung (1909). strikes
the Crusaders*
sword at a
tall tree;
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
17
compulsion the dreams which occur in traumatic neuroses and the impulse which leads children to play. But it is to be noted that only in rare instances can we observe the pure effects of the compulsion to repeat, unsupported by other motives. In the case of children's play we have already laid stress on the other ways in which the emergence of the compulsion may be interpreted; the compulsion to repeat and relate to this
instinctual satisfaction which is immediately pleasurable seem to converge here into an intimate partnership. The phenomena
of transference are obviously exploited by the resistance which the ego maintains in its pertinacious insistence upon repression; the compulsion to repeat, which the treatment tries to bring into its service is, as it were, drawn over by the ego to its side 1 (clinging as the ego does to the pleasure principle). great deal of what might be described as the compulsion of destiny seems intelligible on a rational basis; so that we are under no necessity to call in a new and mysterious motive force to explain it. The least dubious instance [of such a motive force] is perhaps that of traumatic dreams. But on maturer reflection we shall be forced to admit that even in the other instances the whole ground is not covered by the operation of the familiar motive forces. Enough is left unexplained to justify the hypothesis of a compulsion to repeat something that seems more primitive, more elementary, more instinctual than the pleasure principle which it over-rides. But if a compulsion to repeat does operate in the mind, we should be glad to know something about it, to learn what function it corresponds to, under what conditions
A
it
can emerge and what to which, after all,
its
relation
is
to the pleasure principle
we have hitherto ascribed dominance over
the course of the processes of excitation in mental 1
life.
[Before 1923 the last clause read: 'the compulsion to repeat is as it to its help by the ego, clinging as it does to the pleasure
were called principle.*]
IV
WHAT
follows
speculation, often far-fetched speculation,
is
which the reader will consider or dismiss according to his individual predilection. It is further an attempt to follow out an idea consistently, out of curiosity to see where it will lead. Psycho-analytic speculation takes as its point of departure the impression, derived from examining unconscious processes,
may be, not the most universal attribute of mental processes, but only a particular function of them.
that consciousness
Speaking in metapsychological terms, it asserts that consciousis a function of a particular system which it describes as C$. 1 What consciousness yields consists essentially of percep-
ness
of excitations coming from the external world and of of pleasure and unpleasure which can only arise from within the mental apparatus; it is therefore possible to assign to tions
feelings
the system Pcpt.-Cs.* a position in space. It must lie on the borderline between outside and inside; it must be turned to-
wards the external world and must envelop the other psychical systems. It will be seen that there is nothing daringly new in these assumptions; we have merely adopted the views on localization held
by cerebral anatomy, which
of consciousness in the cerebral cortex
locates the 'seat
1
the outermost, envelop-
ing layer of the central organ. Cerebral anatomy has no need to consider why, speaking anatomically, consciousness should be lodged on the surface of the brain instead of being safely
housed somewhere in
more
its
inmost interior. Perhaps we shall be
successful in accounting for this situation in the case of
our system
Pcpt.-Cs.
Consciousness
is
not the only distinctive character which
we
On
the basis of impresascribe to the processes in that system. sions derived from our psycho-analytic experience, we assume that all excitatory processes that occur in the other systems leave *[See Freud, The Interpretation of Dreams (1900a), Standard Ed., 5, 610 ff., and "The Unconscious* (1915*), Section II.] 1 [The system Pcpt. (the perceptual system) was first described by Freud in The Interpretation of Dream, Standard Ed., 5, 536 ff In a later paper (1917
system Gr.] IB
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
19
permanent traces behind in them which form the foundation of memory. Such memory-traces, then, have nothing to do with the fact of becoming conscious; indeed they are often most powerful and most enduring when the process which left them behind was one which never entered consciousness. We find it hard to believe, however, that permanent traces of excitation such as these are also left in the system Pcpt.-Cs. If they re-
mained constantly conscious, they would very soon
set limits
to the system's aptitude for receiving fresh excitations. 1 If,
on
the other hand, they were unconscious, we should be faced with the problem of explaining the existence of unconscious
whose functioning was otherwise accompanied by the phenomenon of consciousness. We should, so to say, have altered -nothing and gained nothing by our hypothesis relegating the process of becoming conscious to a special system. Though this consideration is not absolutely conclusive, it neverprocesses in a system
theless leads us to suspect that
becoming conscious and leaving
behind a memory-trace are processes incompatible with each other within one and the same system. Thus we should be able to say that the excitatory process becomes conscious in the system Cs. but leaves no permanent trace behind there; but
that the excitation is transmitted to the systems lying next within and that it is in them that its traces are left. I followed these same lines in the schematic picture which I included in the speculative section of my Interpretation of Dreams. 2 It must
be borne in mind that little enough is known from other sources of the origin of consciousness; when, therefore, we lay down the proposition that consciousness arises instead of a memory-trace^ the assertion deserves consideration, at all events on the ground of
being framed in fairly precise terms. is so, then, the system Cs. is characterized by the peculiarity that in it (in contrast to what happens in the other
its
If this
psychical systems) excitatory processes do not leave behind any permanent change in its elements but expire, as it were, in the phenomenon of becoming conscious. An exception of this sort * What follows is based throughout on Breuer's views in [the second section of his theoretical contribution to] Studies on Hysteria (Breuer and Freud, 1895). [Freud himself discussed the subject in The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Ed. t 5, 538 and it had previously been fully considered in his 'Project' of 1895 (19500), Part I, Section 3. He returned to 1 the topic later in his paper on the 'Mystic Writing-Pad (1925a).] a \Standard Ed.. 5. 538.1
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
20
to the general ride requires to be explained by some factor that Such a factor, which is applies exclusively to that one system.
absent in the other systems, might well be the exposed situation of the system Cs., immediately abutting as it does on the external world. Let us picture a living organism in its most simplified possible form as an undifferentiated vesicle of a substance that is susceptible to stimulation. Then the surface turned towards the its very situation be differentiated and an organ for receiving stimulL Indeed embryology
external world will from will serve as
s
capacity as a recapitulation of developmental history, actually shows us that the central nervous system originates in
its
from the ectoderm; the grey matter of the cortex remains a derivative of the primitive superficial layer of the organism and may have inherited some of its essential properties. It would be easy to suppose, then, that as a result of the ceaseless impact of external stimuli on the surface of the vesicle, its substance to a certain depth may have become permanently modified, so that excitatory processes run a different course in it from what they run in the deeper layers. A crust would thus be formed which would at last have been so thoroughly 'baked through' by stimulation that it would present the most favourable possible conditions for the reception of stimuli and become incapable of any further modification. In terms of the system Cy., this would mean that its elements could undergo no further permanent modification from the passage of excitation, because they had already been modified in the respect in question to the greatest possible extent: now, however, they would have become capable of giving rise to consciousness. Various ideas may be formed which cannot at present be verified as to the nature of this modification of the substance and of the excitatory process. It may be supposed that, in passing from one element to another, an excitation has to overcome a resistance, and that the diminution of resistance thus effected is what lays down a permanent trace of the excitation, that is, a facilitation. In the system Cs. 9 then, resistance of this kind to passage from one
element to another would no longer exist. 1 This picture can be brought into relation with Breuer's distinction between quiescent (or bound) and mobile cathectic energy in the elements 1 [This passage is foreshadowed in the later half of Section 3 of Part I of the 'Project'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE of the psychical systems; carry no
1
21
the elements of the system Cs. would
bound energy but only energy capable of
free dis-
charge. It seems best, however, to express oneself as cautiously as possible on these points. None the less, this speculation will have enabled us to bring the origin of consciousness into some sort of connection with the situation of the system Cs. and with the peculiarities that must be ascribed to the excitatory processes taking place in it.
But we have more to say of the living vesicle with its receptive This little fragment of living substance is susmiddle of an external world charged with the most powerful energies; and it would be killed by the stimulation emanating from these if it were not provided with a cortical layer. pended in the
protective shield against stimuli. It acquires the shield in this way: its outermost surface ceases to have the structure proper to living matter, becomes to some degree inorganic and thence-
forward functions as a special envelope or membrane resistant to stimuli. In consequence, the energies of the external world are able to pass into the next underlying layers, which have remained living, with only a fragment of their original intensity; and these layers can devote themselves, behind the protective shield, to the reception of the amounts of stimulus which have been allowed through it. By its death, the outer layer has saved all the deeper ones from a similar fate unless, that is to say, stimuli reach it which are so strong that they break through the protective shield. Protection against stimuli is an almost more important function for the living organism than reception
of stimuli.
store of energy
The
protective shield
and must above
is
supplied with
its
own
endeavour to preserve the special modes of transformation of energy operating in it against the effects threatened by the enormous energies at work in the external world effects which tend towards a levelling out of them and hence towards destruction. The main purpose of the reception of stimuli is to discover the direction and nature of the all
external stimuli; and for that it is enough to take small specimens of the external world, to sample it in small quantities. In highly developed organisms the receptive cortical layer of the former vesicle has long been withdrawn into the depths of 1
Breuer and Freud, 1895. [See Section 2 of Brevier's theoretical con-
tribution, and in particular the footnote at the beginning of that section. Cf. also footnote 1 on p. 2 above.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
22
the interior of the body, though portions of it have been left behind on the surface immediately beneath the general shield against stimuli. These are the sense organs, which consist
of apparatus for the reception of certain specific but which also include special arrangements for further protection against excessive amounts of stimulation and for excluding unsuitable kinds of stimuli. 1 It is characteristic of them that they deal only with very small quantities of external stimulation and only take in samples of the external world. They may perhaps be compared with feelers which are all the time making tentative advances towards the external world and then drawing back from it. At this point I shall venture to touch for a moment upon a subject which would merit the most exhaustive treatment. As a result of certain psycho-analytic discoveries, we are to-day in a position to embark on a discussion of the Kantian theorem that time and space are 'necessary forms of thought*. We have learnt that unconscious mental processes are in themselves 'timeless*. 2 This means in the first place that they are not ordered temporally, that time does not change them in any way and that the idea of time cannot be applied to them. These are negative characteristics which can only be clearly understood if a comparison is made with conscious mental processes. On the other hand, our abstract idea of time seems to be wholly derived from the method of working of the system Pcpt.-Cs. and to correspond to a perception on its own part of that method of working. This mode of functioning may perhaps constitute another way of providing a shield against stimuli. I know that these remarks must sound very obscure, but I must limit myself to these hints. 8 We have pointed out how the living vesicle is provided with a shield against stimuli from the external world; and we had previously shown that the cortical layer next to that shield must be differentiated as an organ for receiving stimuli from without. This sensitive cortex, however, which is later to become the essentially
effects of stimulation,
system Cs., also receives excitations from within. The situation of the system between the outside and the inside and the differ* 1
[Cf. 'Project*, Part I, Sections 5
[See Section
8
V of
and
9.]
"The Unconscious' (1915*).] [Freud recurs to the origin of the idea of time at the
on "The Mystic Writing-Pad
1
end of his paper
(1925s). The same paper -contains a further discussion of the 'shield against stimuli'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
23
encc between the conditions governing the reception of excitations in the two cases have a decisive effect on the functioning of the system and of the whole mental apparatus. Towards the outside it is shielded against stimuli, and the amounts of excitation impinging on it have only a reduced effect. Towards the inside there can be no such shield; 1 the excitations in the deeper layers extend into the system directly and in undiminished amount, in so far as certain of their characteristics give rise to feelings
in
the
pleasure-unpleasure
coming from within
series.
The
excitations
however, in their intensity and in in their amplitude, perhaps more other, qualitative, respects commensurate with the system's method of working than the stimuli which stream in from the external world. 2 This state of things produces two definite results. First, the feelings of pleasure and unpleasure (which are an index to what is happening in the interior of the apparatus) predominate over all external stimuli. And secondly, a particular way is adopted of dealing with any internal excitations which produce too great an increase of unpleasure: there is a tendency to treat them as though they were acting, not from the inside, but from the outside, so that it may be possible to bring the shield against stimuli into operation as a means of defence against them. This is the origin of projection, which is destined to play such a large part in the causation of pathological processes. I have an impression that these last considerations have brought us to a better understanding of the dominance of the pleasure principle; but no light has yet been thrown on the cases that contradict that dominance. Let us therefore go a step further. We describe as 'traumatic* any excitations from outside which are powerful enough to break through the protective shield. It seems to me that the concept of trauma necessarily implies a connection of this kind with a breach in an otherwise are,
efficacious barrier against stimuli.
Such an event
as
an
ex-
to provoke a disturbance on a large scale in the functioning of the organism's energy and to^ set in motion every possible defensive measure. At the same time, the is pleasure principle is for the moment put out of action. There ternal
trauma
is
bound
possibility of preventing the mental apparatus from being flooded with large amounts of stimulus, and another
no longer any i
[Cf. 'Project', beginning of Section 10 of Part I.] Part I.] [Cf. 'Project*, later part of Section 4 of
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
24
problem arises instead the problem of mastering the amounts of stimulus which have broken in and of binding them, in the psychical sense, so that they can then be disposed of. The specific unpleasure of physical pain is probably the result of the protective shield having been broken through in a limited area. There is then a continuous stream of excitations
from the part of the periphery concerned to the central apparatus of the mind, such as could normally arise only from within the apparatus. And how shall we expect the mind to react to this invasion? Gathectic energy is summoned from all sides to provide sufficiently high cathexes of energy in the 1
environs of the breach.
An
'anticathexis'
on a grand
scale
is
set
up, for whose benefit all the other psychical systems are impoverished,, so that the remaining psychical functions are extenmust endeavour to draw a sively paralysed or reduced.
We
and use them as a basis for our metapsychological speculations. From the present case, then, we infer that a system which is itself highly cathected is capable of taking up an additional stream of fresh inflowing energy and of converting it into quiescent cathexis., that is of binding it psychically. The higher the system's own quiescent cathexis, the greater seems to be its binding force; conversely, therefore, the lower its cathexis, the less capacity will it have for s taking up inflowing energy and the more violent must be the consequences of such a breach in the protective shield against stimuli. To this view it cannot be justly objected that the increase of cathexis round the breach can be explained far more simply as the direct result of the inflowing masses of excitation. If that were so, the mental apparatus would merely receive an increase in its cathexes of energy, and the paralysing character of pain and the impoverishment of all the other systems would remain unexplained. Nor do the very violent phenomena of discharge to which pain gives rise affect our explanation, for they occur in a reflex manner that is, they follow without the intervention of the mental apparatus. The indefiniteness of all our discussions on what we describe as metapsychology is of course due to the fact that we know nothing of the nature of the excitatory process that takes place in the elements of the lesson
1
from examples such
Cf. 'Instincts
Inhibitions , *
and
as this
their Vicissitudes' (1915*:) [and-
Addendum C
of
Symptoms and Anxiety (1926^)].
[Cf. the 'principle of the insusceptibility to excitation of uncathected systems* in a footnote near the end of Freud, 1917'd.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
25
psychical systems, and that we do not feel justified in framing any hypothesis on the subject. We are consequently operating all the time with a large unknown factor, which we are
obliged to carry over into every new formula. It may be reasonably supposed that this excitatory process can be carried out with energies that vary quantitatively, it may also seem probable
has more than one quality (in the nature of amplitude, As a new factor we have taken into consideration Breuer's hypothesis that charges of energy occur in two forms [see pp. 20-1]; so that we have to distinguish between two kinds that
it
for instance).
of cathexis of the psychical systems or their elements a freely flowing cathexis that presses on towards discharge and a quiescent cathexis. We may perhaps suspect that the binding of the energy that streams into the mental apparatus consists in its change from a freely flowing into a quiescent state.
We may, I think, tentatively venture to regard the common traumatic neurosis as a consequence of an extensive breach being made in the protective 'shield against stimuli. This would seem to reinstate the old, naive theory of shock, in apparent contrast to the later and psychologically more ambitious theory which attributes aetiological importance not to the effects of mechanical violence but to fright and the threat to life. These opposing views are not, however, irreconcilable; nor is the psycho-analytic view of the traumatic neurosis identical with the shock theory in its crudest form. The latter regards the essence of the shock as being the direct damage to the molecular structure or even to the histological structure of the elements of the nervous system; whereas what we seek to understand are the effects produced on the organ of the mind by the breach in the shield against stimuli and by the problems that follow in its And we still attribute importance to the element of fright.
train.
It is caused by lack of any preparedness for anxiety, * including lack of hypercathexis of the systems that would be the first to receive the stimulus. Owing to their low cathexis those
systems are not in a good position for binding the inflowing amounts of excitation and the consequences of the breach in the protective shield follow all the more easily. It will be seen, then, that preparedness for anxiety and the hypercathexis of the receptive systems constitute the last line of defence of the shield against stimuli. In the case of quite a number of traumas, the 1
[Cf. footnote
1
on
p. 7 above.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
26
between systems that are unprepared and systems that are well prepared through being hypercathected may be a decisive factor in determining the outcome; though where the strength of a trauma exceeds a certain limit this factor will no difference
doubt cease to carry weight. The fulfilment of wishes is, as we know, brought about in a hallucinatory manner by dreams, and under the dominance of the pleasure principle this has become their function. But it is not in the service of that principle that the dreams of patients suffering from traumatic neuroses lead them back with such regularity to the situation in which the trauma occurred. We may assume, rather, that dreams are here helping to carry out another task, which must be accomplished before the dominance of the pleasure principle can even begin. These dreams are endeavouring to master the stimulus retrospectively, by developing the anxiety whose omission was the cause of the traumatic neurosis. They thus afford us a view of a function of the mental apparatus which, though it does not contradict the pleasure principle, is nevertheless independent of it and seems to be more primitive than the purpose of gaining
and avoiding unpleasure. This would seem to be the place, then, at which to admit for the first time an exception to the proposition that dreams are fulfilments of wishes. Anxiety dreams, as I have shown repeatedly and in detail, offer no such exception. Nor do 'punishment dreams', for they merely replace the forbidden pleasure
wish-fulfilment
by the appropriate punishment for
it;
that
is
to
say, they fulfil the wish of the sense of guilt which is the reaction to the repudiated impulse. 1 But it is impossible to classify as
wish-fulfilments the
dreams we have been discussing which
occur in traumatic neuroses, or the dreams during psychoanalyses which bring to memory the psychical traumas of childhood. They arise, rather, in obedience to the compulsion to repeat, though
it is
true that in analysis that compulsion
is
a supported by the wish (which is encouraged by 'suggestion') to conjure up what has been forgotten and repressed. Thus it would seem that the function of dreams, which consists in i [Sec The Interpretation of Dreams (1900a), Standard Ed., 5, 557, and Section 9 of Freud's 'Remarks on the Theory and Practice of Dream-
Interpretation* (1923*:).] 8 [The clause in brackets is
was substituted in 1923 for the words 'which not unconscious* which appeared in the earlier editions.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
27
any motives that might interrupt sleep, by fulfilling the wishes of the disturbing impulses, is not their original function. It would not be possible for them to perform that
setting aside
function until the whole of mental
life had accepted the dominance of the pleasure principle. If there is a 'beyond the pleasure principle', it is only consistent to grant that there was also a time before the purpose of dreams was the fulfilment of wishes. This would imply no denial of their later function. But if once this general rule has been broken, a further question arises. May not dreams which, with a view to the psychical binding of traumatic impressions, obey the compulsion to repeat may not such dreams occur outside analysis as well? And the reply can only be a decided affirmative. I have argued elsewhere * that 'war neuroses' (in so far as that term implies something more than a reference to the circumstances of the illness's onset) may very well be traumatic neuroses which have been facilitated by a conflict in the ego. The fact to which I have referred on page 6, that a gross physical injury caused simultaneously by the trauma diminishes the chances that a neurosis will develop, becomes intelligible if one bears in mind two facts which have been stressed by psycho-analytic research: firstly, that mechanical agitation must be recognized as one of the sources of sexual excitation, 3 and secondly, that painful and feverish illnesses exercise a powerful effect, so long as they last, on the distribution of libido. Thus, on the one hand, the mechanical violence of the trauma would liberate a quantity of sexual excitation which, owing to the lack of preparation for anxiety, would have a traumatic effect; but, on the other hand, the simultaneous physical injury, by calling for a narcissistic hypercathexis of the injured organ, 3 would bind the excess of excitation. It is also well known, though the libido theory has not yet made sufficient use of the fact, that such severe disorders in the distribution of libido as melancholia are temporarily brought to an end by intercurrent organic illness, and indeed that even a fully developed condition of dementia praecox is capable of a temporary remission in these
same circumstances. 1
See
2
Cf.
my introduction (I9l9d) to Psycho-Analysis and the War Neuroses. my remarks elsewhere (Three Essays [Standard Ed., 7, 201-2; on the effect of swinging and railway-travel. paper on narcissism (19 14*:) [Beginning of Section II].
I.P.L., 57, 67-8]) 3
See
my
V THE fact that the cortical layer which receives stimuli is without any protective as
its
shield against excitations
from within must have of stimulus have a
result that these latter transmissions
preponderance in economic importance and often occasion economic disturbances comparable with traumatic neuroses. The most abundant sources of this internal excitation are what are described as the organism's 'instincts*
the representatives
of all the forces originating in the interior of the body and transmitted to the mental apparatus at once the most important and the most obscure element of psychological research. It will perhaps not be thought too rash to suppose that the impulses arising from the instincts do not belong to the type of bound nervous processes but of freely mobile processes which
The best part of what we know of these derived from our study of the dream- work. there discovered that the processes in the unconscious systems were press towards discharge.
processes
We
is
fundamentally different from those in the preconscious (or conscious) systems. In the unconscious, cathexes can easily be completely transferred, displaced and condensed. Such treatment, however, could produce onfy invalid results if it were applied to preconscious material; and this accounts for the familiar peculiarities exhibited by manifest dreams after the preconscious residues of the preceding day have been worked over in accordance with the laws operating in the unconscious.
of process found in the unconscious as the 'primary' psychical process, in contradistinction to the 'secondary' process which is the one obtaining in our normal I described the type
waking
impulses have the unconscious systems as their point of impact, it is hardly an innovation to say that they obey the primary process. Again, it is easy to
life.
Since
the
primary psychical process with Breuer's
all instinctual
identify
cathexis
freely mobile in his bound or
and the secondary process with changes it would be the task of the higher
tonic cathexis. 1 If so,
strata of
the mental apparatus to bind the instinctual excitation reaching 1
Cf.
Cf. also
my Interpretation of Dreams,
Chapter VII [Standard Ed., 5, 588 ff. Breuer and Freud, 1895 (Section 2 of Breuer's theoretical con-
tribution)].
28
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
29
A
failure to effect this binding would the primary process. provoke a disturbance analogous to a traumatic neurosis; and only after the binding has been accomplished would it be
dominance of the pleasure principle (and of its modification, the reality principle) to proceed unhindered. Till then the other task of the mental apparatus, the task of mastering or binding excitations, would have precedence not, indeed, possible for the
in opposition to the pleasure principle, but independently of and to some extent in disregard of it.
it
The manifestations of a compulsion to repeat (which we have described as occurring in the early activities of infantile mental life as well as among the events of psycho-analytic treatment) exhibit to a high degree an instinctual 1 character and, when they act in opposition to the pleasure principle, give the appear-
ance of some 'daemonic' force at work. In the case of children's play we seemed to see that children repeat unpleasurable experiences for the additional reason that they can master a powerful impression far more thoroughly by being active than they could by merely experiencing it passively. Each fresh repetition seems to strengthen the mastery they are in search of. Nor can children have their pleasurable experiences repeated often enough, and they are inexorable in their insistence that the repetition shall be an identical one. This character trait disappears later on. If a joke is heard for a second time it produces almost no effect; a theatrical production never creates so great an impression the second time as the first; indeed, it is hardly possible to persuade an adult who has very much enjoyed reading a book to re-read it immediately. Novelty is always the condition of enjoyment. But children will never tire of asking an adult to repeat a game that he has shown them or played with them, till he is too exhausted to go on. And if a child has been told a nice story, he will insist on hearing it over and over again rather than a new one; and he will remorselessly stipulate that the repetition shall be an identical one and will correct any alterations ofwhich the narrator may be guilty though they may 8 actually have been made in the hope of gaining fresh approval. 1
['Triebhaf? here
word
*
Trieb* bears
the next paragraph. The of a feeling of urgency than the English
and at the beginning of
much more
'instinct*.] * [Cf. some remarks on this towards the end of the Chapter VII of Freud's book on jokes (1905).]
sixth section of
5U
tfiiYUJND
THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
None of
this contradicts the pleasure principle; repetition, the re-experiencing of something identical, is clearly in itself a source of pleasure. In the case of a person in analysis, on the contrary, the compulsion to repeat the events of his childhood in the transference evidently disregards the pleasure
principle in ev^ry way. The patient behaves in a purely infantile fashion and thus shows us that the repressed memory-traces of his primaeval experiences are not present in him in a bound
and are indeed in a sense incapable of obeying the secondary process. It is to this fact of not being bound, moreover, that they owe their capacity for forming, in conjunction with the residues of the previous day, a wishful phantasy that emerges in a dream. This same compulsion to repeat frequently meets us as an obstacle to our treatment when at the end of an analysis we try to induce the patient to detach himself completely from his physician. It may be presumed, too, that when people una dread of rousing familiar with analysis feel an obscure fear state
something that, so they feel, is better left sleeping what they are afraid of at bottom is the emergence of this compulsion with its hint of possession by some 'daemonic* power. But how is the predicate of being 'instinctual' 1 related to the compulsion to repeat? At this point we cannot escape a suspicion that we may have come upon the track of a universal attribute of instincts and perhaps of organic life in general which has not hitherto been clearly recognized or at least not explicitly stressed. 2 It seems, then, that an instinct is an urge inherent in organic
an earlier state of things which the living entity has been obliged to abandon under the pressure of external disturbing forces; that is, it is a kind of organic elasticity, or, to put it another way, the expression of the inertia inherent in life to restore
3
organic life. This view of instincts strikes us as strange because we have become used to see in them a factor impelling towards change
and development, whereas we are now asked to recognize in them the precise contrary an expression of the conservative nature of living substance. On the other hand we soon call to mind examples from animal life which seem to confirm the 1
[See the last footnote but one.] [The last six words were added in 1921.] * I have no doubt that similar notions as to the nature of have already been put fonvard repeatedly. *
'instincts*
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
31
view that instincts are historically determined. Certain fishes, for instance, undertake laborious migrations at spawning-time in order to deposit their spawn in particular waters far removed
from their customary haunts. In the opinion of many biologists what they are doing is merely to seek out the localities in which their species formerly resided but which in the course of time they have exchanged for others. The same explanation is believed to apply to the migratory flights of birds of passage but we are quickly relieved of the necessity for seeking for further examples by the reflection that the most impressive proofs of there being an organic compulsion to repeat lie in the
phenomena of heredity and the how the germ of a living animal
facts is
of embryology.
We
see
obliged in the course of its
if only in a transient and abbreviated fashion) the structures of all the forms from which it is sprung, instead of proceeding quickly by the shortest path to its final shape. This behaviour is only to a very slight degree attributable to mechanical causes, and the historical explanation cannot accordingly be neglected. So too the power of regenerating a lost organ by growing afresh a precisely similar one extends far up into the animal kingdom. We shall be met by the plausible objection that it may very well be that, in addition to the conservative instincts which impel
development to recapitulate (even
towards repetition, there may be others which push forward towards progress and the production of new forms. This argument must certainly not be overlooked, and it will be taken into account at a later stage. 1 But for the moment it is tempting to pursue to its logical conclusion the hypothesis that all instincts tend towards the restoration of an earlier state of things. The outcome may give an impression of mysticism or of sham profundity; but we can feel quite innocent of having had any such purpose in view. We seek only for the sober results of research or of reflection based on it; and we have no wish to find in those 3 results any quality other than certainty. Let us suppose, then, that all the organic instincts are conservative, are acquired historically and tend towards the half of this sentence was added in 1921.] The reader should not overlook the fact that what follows is the development of an extreme line of thought. Later on, when account is taken of the sexual instincts, it will be found that the necessary limitations and corrections are applied to it. i
[The
3
[Footnote added 1925:]
last
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
32
restoration of an earlier state of things. It follows that the pheno niena of organic development must be attributed to externa
and diverting influences. The elementary living would from its very beginning have had no wish tc change; if conditions remained the same, it would do no mor< than constantly repeat the same course of life. In the last resort what has left its mark on the development of organisms must be the history of the earth we live in and of its relation to the sun. Every modification which is thus imposed upon the course oi disturbing entity
the organism's life is accepted by the conservative organic and stored up for further repetition. Those instincts are therefore bound to give a deceptive appearance of being forces instincts
tending towards change and progress, whilst in fact they are merely seeking to reach an ancient goal by paths alike old and new. Moreover it is possible to specify this final goal of all organic striving. It would be in contradiction to the conservative nature of the instincts if the goal of life were a state of things which had never yet been attained. On the contrary, it must be an old state of things, an initial state from which the living entity has at one time or other departed and to which it is
striving to return by the circuitous paths along leads. If we are to take it as a truth that
development
which its knows no
exception that everything living dies for internal reasons then we shall be compelled to say that 'the aim of all life is death and, looking backwards, that
becomes inorganic once again
9
9
'inanimate things existed before living ones . The attributes of life were at some time
evoked in inanimate matter by the action of a force of whose nature we can form no conception. It may perhaps have been a process similar in type to that which later caused the development of consciousness in a particular stratum of living matter. The tension which then arose in what had hitherto been an inanimate substance endeavoured to cancel itself out. In this way the first instinct came into being: the instinct to return to the inanimate state. It was still an easy matter at that time for a living substance to die; the course of its life was probably only a brief one, whose direction was determined by the chemical structure of the young life. For a long time, perhaps, living substance was thus being constantly created afresh and easily dying, till decisive external influences altered in such a way as to oblige the still surviving substance to diverge ever more widely from its original course
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
33
life and to make ever more complicated detours before reaching its aim of death. These circuitous paths to death, faithfully kept to by the conservative instincts, would thus present us to-day with the picture of the phenomena of life. If we firmly maintain the exclusively conservative nature of instincts, we cannot arrive at any other notions as to the origin and aim
of
of life.
The
implications in regard to the great groups of instincts we believe, lie behind the phenomena of life in
which, as
organisms must appear no
less
bewildering.
such as
The
hypothesis of
we
attribute to all living opposition to the idea that instinctual
self-preservative instincts,
beings, stands in marked as a whole serves to bring about death. Seen in this light, the theoretical importance of the instincts of self-preservation,
life
of self-assertion and of mastery greatly diminishes. They are
component
instincts
whose function
it
is
to assure that the
organism shall follow its own path to death, and to ward off any possible ways of returning to inorganic existence other than those which are immanent in the organism itself. We have no longer to reckon with the organism's puzzling determination (so hard to fit into any context) to maintain its own existence in the face of every obstacle. What we are left with is the fact that the
organism wishes to die only in its own fashion. Thus these guardians of life, too, were originally the myrmidons of death.
Hence
the paradoxical situation that the living organism most energetically against events (dangers, in fact) which might help it to attain its life's aim rapidly by a kind of short-circuit. Such behaviour is, however, precisely what chararises
struggles
acterizes
purely instinctual
as
contrasted
with intelligent
efforts. 1
But
The
let
us pause for a
moment and
reflect. It
cannot be
so.
sexual instincts, to which the theory of the neuroses gives
a quite special place, appear under a very different aspect. The external pressure which provokes a constantly increasing extent of development has not imposed itself upon every organism. Many have succeeded in remaining up to the present time at their lowly level. Many, though not all, such creatures, which must resemble the earliest stages of the higher animals 1
[In the editions before 1925 the following footnote appeared at this 'A correction of this extreme view of the self-preservative instincts
point.
follows.*]
34
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
and plants, are, indeed, living to-day. In the same way, the whole path of development to natural death is not trodden by all the elementary entities which compose the complicated body of one of the higher organisms. Some of them, the germ-cells, probably retain the original structure of living matter and, after a certain time, with their full complement of inherited and freshly acquired instinctual dispositions, separate themselves from the organism as a whole. These two characteristics may be precisely what enables them to have an independent existence. Under favourable conditions, they begin to develop that is, to repeat the performance to which they owe their existence; and in the end once again one portion of their substance pursues its development to a finish, while another portion harks back once
again as a fresh residual germ to the beginning of the process of development. These germ-cells, therefore, work against the death of the living substance and succeed in winning for it
what we can only regard as potential immortality, though that may mean no more than a lengthening of the road to death. We must regard as in the highest degree significant the fact that this function of the germ-cell possible, if it coalesces with
differing from it. The instincts which
is
another
reinforced, or only
made
cell similar to itself and
yet
watch over the destinies of these elemen-
tary organisms that survive the whole individual, which provide them with a safe shelter while they are defenceless against the stimuli of the external world, with other germ-cells, and so
which bring about their meeting on these constitute the group of
They are conservative in the same sense other instincts in that they bring back earlier states of living substance; but they are conservative to a higher degree in that they are peculiarly resistant to external influences; and they are conservative too in another sense in that they preserve the sexual instincts. as the
life itself
for a comparatively long period. 1
They are the true They operate against the purpose of the other instincts, which leads, by reason of their function, to death; and this fact indicates that there is an opposition between them and
life instincts.
the other instincts, an opposition whose importance was long ago recognized by the theory of the neuroses. It is as though the 1 [Footnote added 1923:] Yet it is to them alone that we can attribute an internal impulse towards 'progress' and towards higher development! (See below [pp. 42-3].)
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
35
of the organism moved with a vacillating rhythm. One group of instincts rushes forward so as to reach the final aim of life as swiftly as possible; but when a particular stage in the advance has been reached, the other group jerks back to a certain point to make a fresh start and so prolong the journey. And even though it is certain that sexuality and the distinction between the sexes did not exist when life began, the possibility remains that the instincts which were later to be described as sexual may have been in operation from the very first, and it may not be true that it was only at a later time that they started life
upon their work of opposing the Let us now hark back for a whether there is any basis at
activities
moment
of the 'ego-instincts'. 1 and consider
ourselves
all for these speculations. Is it really the case that, apart from the sexual instincts there are no instincts that do not seek to restore an earlier state of things?
f
none that aim at a state of things which has never yet been attained? I know of no certain example from the organic world that would contradict the characterization I have thus proposed. There is unquestionably no universal instinct that there are
towards higher development observable in the animal or plant world, even though it is undeniable that development does in fact occur in that direction. But on the one hand it is often merely a matter of opinion when we declare that one stage of development is higher than another, and on the other hand biology teaches us that higher development in one respect is very frequently balanced or outweighed by involution in another. Moreover there are plenty of animal forms from whose early stages we can infer that their development has, on the contrary, assumed a retrograde character. Both higher development and involution might well be the consequences of adapta-
tion to the pressure of external forces; and in both cases the part played by instincts might be limited to the retention (in the form of an internal source of pleasure) of an obligatory
modification. 3 1 [Footnote added 1925:] It should be understood from the context that the term *ego-instincts* is used here as a provisional description and derives from the earliest psycho-analytical terminology. [See below,
pp. 44-5 and 55.] 1 [These five words were italicized from 1921 onwards.] 8 Ferenczi (1913, 137) has reached the same conclusion along different lines: *If this thought is pursued to its logical conclusion, one must make oneself familiar with the idea of a tendency to perseveration or
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
36 It
may
be
difficult, too, for
many of us,
to
abandon the
belief
an instinct towards perfection at work in human beings, which has brought them to their present high level of intellectual achievement and ethical sublimation and which may be expected to watch over their development into supermen. I have no faith, however, in the existence of any such internal instinct and I cannot see how this benevolent illusion is to be preserved. The present development of human beings requires, as it seems to me, no different explanation from that of that there
animals.
is
What
appears in a minority of
human
individuals as
an untiring impulsion towards further perfection can
easily be understood as a result of the instinctual repression upon which is based all that is most precious in human civilization. The repressed instinct never ceases to strive for complete satisfaction, which would consist in the repetition of a primary experience of satisfaction. No substitutive or reactive formations and no
sublimations will suffice to remove the repressed instinct's persisting tension; and it is the difference in amount between the pleasure of satisfaction which is demanded and that which is actually achieved that provides the driving factor which will permit of no halting at any position attained, but, in the poet's
words, 'ungebandigt immer vorwdrts
1
dringt'.
The backward path
that leads to complete satisfaction is as a rule obstructed by the resistances which maintain the repressions. So there is no alternative but to advance in the direction in which growth is free though with no prospect of bringing the process to a conclusion or of being able to reach the goal. The processes involved in the formation of a neurotic phobia, which is nothing still
else
than an attempt at
from the satisfaction of an instinct, manner of origin of this suptowards perfection' an instinct which canflight
present us with a model of the posititious 'instinct
not possibly be attributed to conditions for
its
every
human
being.
The
dynamic
are, indeed, universally present; only in rare cases that the economic situation appears
development
but it is to favour the production of the phenomenon. I will add only a word to suggest that the efforts of Eros to
regression dominating organic life as well, while the tendency to further development, to adaptation, etc., would become active only as a result
of external stimuli.' 1 [Tresses ever forward unsubdued,'] Mephistopheles in Faust, Part [Scene 4].
I
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE combine organic substances into ever larger
unities
37
probably
provide a substitute for this 'instinct towards perfection' whose existence we cannot admit. The phenomena that are attributed to it seem capable of explanation by these efforts of Eros taken in conjunction with the results of repression. 1 1 [This paragraph, which was added in 1923, anticipates the account of Eros that is to follow in the next chapter, p. 44 fF.]
VI
THE
upshot of our enquiry so far has been the drawing of 2 sharp distinction between the 'ego-instincts' and the sexual instincts, and the view that the former exercise pressure toward* death and the latter towards a prolongation of life. But thii conclusion is bound to be unsatisfactory in many respects ever to ourselves. Moreover, it is actually only of the former group oi instincts that we can predicate a conservative, or rather retrograde, character corresponding to a compulsion to repeat. Foi
on our hypothesis the
ego-instincts arise from the coming tc of inanimate matter and seek to restore the inanimate state; whereas as regards the sexual instincts, though it is true that life
they reproduce primitive states of the organism, what the^ are clearly aiming at by every possible means is the coalescence of two germ-cells which are differentiated in a particular way, If this union is not effected, the germ-cell dies along with all the other elements of the multicellular organism. It is only on this condition that the sexual function can prolong the cell's life and lend it the appearance of immortality. But what is the important event in the development of living substance which is being repeated in sexual reproduction, or in its fore-runner, the conl jugation of two protista? We cannot say; and we should con-
sequently feel relieved if the whole structure of our argument turned out to be mistaken. The opposition between the ego or death instincts s and the sexual or Hfe instincts would then cease to hold and the compulsion to repeat would no longer possess the importance we have ascribed to it. Let us turn back, then, to one of the assumptions that we have already made, with the expectation that we shall be able
We
to give it a categorical denial. have drawn far-reaching conclusions from the hypothesis that all living substance is bound to die from internal causes. made this assumption thus carelessly because it does not seem to us to be an
We
tion. 1
We
assump-
are accustomed to think that such
[In what follows Freud appears
to use the
is
the fact, and
terms 'protista* and 'pro-
tozoa* indifferently to signify unicellular organisms. follows the original.] 1
[The
first
published appearance of the term.]
38
we
The
translation
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
39
are strengthened in our thought by the writings of our poets. Perhaps we have adopted the belief because there is some com-
we are to die ourselves, and first to lose in death are dearest to us, it is easier to submit to a remorselaw of nature, to the sublime 'Avdyxrj [Necessity], than to
fort in
those less
it.
If
who
a chance which might perhaps have been escaped. It may be, however, that this belief in the internal necessity of dying is only another of those illusions which we have created 'urn die Schwere des Daseins zu belief.
The notion of
1
ertragen'.'
It
is
'natural death'
certainly not a primaeval is
quite foreign to primi-
they attribute every death that occurs among them to the influence of an enemy or of an evil spirit. We must therefore turn to biology in order to test the validity of the tive races;
belief.
If we do so, we may be astonished to find how little agreethere is among biologists on the subject of natural death and in fact that the whole concept of death melts away under their hands. The fact that there is a fixed average duration of
ment
at least among the higher animals naturally argues in favour of there being such a thing as death from natural causes. But this impression is countered when we consider that certain large animals and certain gigantic arboreal growths reach a very life
advanced age and one which cannot at present be computed. According to the large conception of Wilhelm Fliess [1906], all the phenomena of life exhibited by organism and also, no doubt, their death
are linked with the completion of fixed
which express the dependence of two kinds of living substance (one male and the other female) upon the solar year. When we see, however, how easily and how extensively the periods,
influence of external forces
is able to modify the date of the appearance of vital phenomena (especially in the plant world) to precipitate them or hold them back doubts must be cast upon the rigidity of Fliess's formulas or at least upon whether
the laws laid
down by him
are the sole determining factors.
The
greatest interest attaches from our point of view to the treatment given to the subject of the duration of life and the death of organisms in the writings of Weismann (1882, 1884,
1892, etc.) It was he who introduced the division of living substance into mortal and immortal parts. The mortal part is 1
['To bear the burden of existence.' (Schiller, Die Braut von Messina,
1,8.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
40 the
body in the narrower
sense
the 'soma'
which alone
is
subject to natural death. The germ-cells, on the other hand, are potentially immortal, in so far as they are able, under certain
favourable conditions, to develop into a new individual, or, in other words, to surround themselves with a new soma. (Weis-
mann,
1884,)
What strikes us in this is the unexpected analogy with our own view, which was arrived at along such a different path. Weismann, regarding living substance morphologically, sees in one portion which is destined to die the soma, the body apart from the substance concerned with sex and inheritance and an immortal portion the germ-plasm, which is concerned with the survival of the species, with reproduction. We, on the
it
other hand, dealing not with the living substance but with the it, have been led to distinguish two kinds of
forces operating in
which seek to lead what is living to death, and which are perpetually attempting and achieving a renewal of life. This sounds like a dynamic corollary to Weismann's morphological theory. But the appearance of a significant correspondence is dissipated as soon as we discover Weismann's views on the problem of death. For he only relates the distinction between the mortal soma and the immortal germ-plasm to multicellular organisms; in unicellular organisms the individual and the reproductive cell are still one and the same (Weismann, 1882, 38). Thus he considers that unicellular organisms are potentially immortal, and that death only makes its appearance with the multicellular
instincts: those
others, the sexual instincts,
metazoa. It is true that this death of the higher organisms is a natural one, a death from internal causes; but it is not founded on any primal characteristic of living substance (Weismann, 1884, 84) and cannot be regarded as an absolute necessity with basis in the very nature of life (Weismann, 1882, 33). Death is rather a matter of expediency, a manifestation of adaptation to the external conditions of life; for, when once the cells of the its
soma and germ-plasm, an unwould become a quite pointless luxury. When this differentiation had been made in the multicellular organisms, death became possible and expedient. Since then, the soma of the higher organisms has died at fixed
body have been divided
into
limited duration of individual
life
periods for internal reasons, while the protista have remained immortal. It is not the case, on the other hand, that reproduc-
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
41
On
tion was only introduced at the same time as death. the contrary, it is a primal characteristic of living matter, like
growth (from which it originated), and life has been continuous from its first beginning upon earth. (Weismann, 1884, 84 f.) It will be seen at once that to concede in this way that higher organisms have a natural death is of very little help to us. For if death is a late acquisition of organisms, then there can be no question of there having been death instincts from the very beginning of life on this earth. Multicellular organisms may die for internal reasons, owing to defective differentiation or to imperfections in their metabolism, but the matter is of no
from the point of view of our problem. An account of the origin of death such as this is moreover far less at variance with our habitual modes of thought than the strange assumption
interest
of *death
The
instincts'.
led, so far as I
Some
which followed upon Weismann's suggestions can see, to no conclusive results in any direction. 1
discussion
who reHartmann
writers returned to the views of Goette (1883),
garded death as a direct
result of reproduction.
a (1906, 29) does not regard the appearance of a *dead body* as the criterion of death, living substance
dead portion of the
but defines death as 'the termination of individual development*. In this sense protozoa too are mortal; in their case death always coincides with reproduction, but is to some extent obscured by it, since the whole substance of the parent animal may be transmitted directly into the young offspring. Soon afterwards research was directed to the experimental
on unicellular organisms of the alleged immortality of living substance. An American biologist, Woodruff, experimenting with a ciliate infusorian, the *slipper-animalcule ,
testing
s
which reproduces by fission into two individuals, persisted until the 3029th generation (at which point he broke off the experiment), isolating one of the part-products on each occasion and placing it in fresh water. This remote descendent of the first slipper-animalcule was just as lively as its ancestor and showed no signs of ageing or degeneration. Thus, in so far as figures of this kind prove anything, the immortality of the protista seemed to be experimentally demonstrable. 2 Other experimenters arrived at different results. Maupas, i
Cf.
For
Hartmann (1906), Lipschiitz (1914) and Doflein (1919). this and what follows see Lipschiitz (1914, 26 and 52 fF.).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
42
Calkins and others, in contrast to Woodruff, found that after a
number of divisions these infusoria become weaker, diminish in size, suffer the loss of some part of their organization and eventually die, unless certain recuperative measures are certain
applied to them. If this is so, protozoa would appear to die after a phase of senescence exactly like the higher animals thus completely contradicting Weismann's assertion that death is a
of living organisms. the aggregate of these experiments two facts emerge which seem to offer us a firm footing. First: If two of the animalculae, at the moment before they show signs of senescence, are able to coalesce with each other,
late acquisition
From
(soon after which they once more 'conjugate' from growing old and become *reare saved they separate), juvenated*. Conjugation is no doubt the fore-runner of the sexual reproduction of higher creatures; it is as yet unconnected with propagation, and is limited to the mixing of the substances of the two individuals. (Weismann's 'amphimixis'.) The recuperative effects of conjugation can, however, be replaced by that
is
to
certain stimulating agents, by alterations in the composition of the fluid which provides their nourishment, by raising their
temperature or by shaking them. We are reminded of the celebrated experiment made by J. Loeb, in which, by means of certain chemical stimuli, he induced segmentation in sea-urchins' eggs a process which can normally occur only after fertilization. Secondly: It is probable nevertheless that infusoria die a natural death as a result of their own vital processes. For the
and the others is due having provided each generation with fresh nutrient fluid. If he omitted to do so, he observed the same signs of senescence as the other experimenters. He concluded that the animalculae were injured by the products of metabolism which they extruded into the surrounding fluid. He was then able to prove conclusively that it was only the products of its own metabolism which had fatal results for the particular kind of animalcule. For the same animalculae which inevitably perished if they were
contradiction between Woodruff's findings to his
crowded together in their own nutrient fluid flourished in a solution which was over-saturated with the waste products of a distantly related species. An infusorian, therefore, if it is left to itself, dies a natural death owing to its incomplete voidance of
the products of its
own metabolism.
(It
may
be that the same
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE incapacity
is
the ultimate cause of the death of
43 all
higher
animals as well.)
At this point the question may well arise in our minds whether any object whatever is served by trying to solve the problem of natural death from a study of the protozoa. The primitive organization of these creatures may conceal from our eyes important conditions which, though in fact present in them too, only become visible in higher animals where they are able to find morphological expression.
And if we abandon the morpho-
of view and adopt the dynamic one, it becomes a matter of complete indifference to us whether natural death can be shown to occur in protozoa or not. The substance which is later recognized as being immortal has not yet become separated in them from the mortal one. The instinctual forces which seek to conduct life into death may also be operating in protozoa from the first, and yet their effects may be so completely concealed by the life-preserving forces that it may be very hard to find any direct evidence of their presence. We have logical point
made by biologists allow us to assume that internal processes of this kind leading to death do occur also in protista. But even if protista turned out to be seen, moreover, that the observations
immortal in Weismann's sense, his assertion that death is a late acquisition would apply only to its manifest phenomena and would not make impossible the assumption of processes tending towards it. Thus our expectation that biology would flatly contradict the recognition of death instincts has not been fulfilled. We are at liberty to continue concerning ourselves with their possibility,
we have other reasons for doing so. The striking similarity between Weismann*s distinction of soma and germ-plasm and our separation of the death instincts from the life instincts persists and retains its significance. We may pause for a moment over this pre-eminently dualistic view of instinctual life. According to E. Hering's theory, two kinds of processes are constantly at work in living substance, operating in contrary directions, one constructive or assimilatory and the other destructive or dissimilatory. May we venture to recognize in these two directions taken by the vital processes the activity of our two instinctual impulses, the life instincts and the death instincts? There is something else, at any rate, that we cannot remain blind to. We have unwittingly if
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
44
steered our course into the
sophy. For him death
is
harbour of Schopenhauer's philo-
the 'true result
and
to that extent the
1 instinct is the embodiment of purpose of life', while the sexual the will to live. [Cf. the Appendix to Freud, 19250.] Let us make a bold attempt at another step forward. It is that the union of a number of cells into generally considered a vital association the multicellular character of organismshas become a means of prolonging their life. One cell helps to preserve the life of another, and the community of cells can survive even if individual cells have to die. We have already heard that conjugation, too, the temporary coalescence of two unicellular organisms, has a life-preserving and rejuvenating effect on both of them. Accordingly, we might attempt to apply the libido theory which has been arrived at in psycho-analysis to the mutual relationship of cells. We might suppose that the life instincts or sexual instincts which are active in each cell take the other cells as their object, that they partly, neutralize the death
is, the processes set up by them) in those cells and thus preserve their life; while the other cells do the same for them, and still others sacrifice themselves in the performance of this libidinal function. The germ-cells themselves would behave to use the phrase that we in a completely 'narcissistic* fashion
instincts (that
are accustomed to use in the theory of the neuroses to describe a whole individual who retains his libido in his ego and pays
none of it out in object-cathexes. The germ-cells require
their
libido, the activity of their life instincts, for themselves, as a reserve against their later momentous constructive activity.
(The cells of the malignant neoplasms which destroy the organism should also perhaps be described as narcissistic in this same sense: pathology is prepared to regard their germs as innate and to ascribe embryonic attributes to them.) 2 In this way the libido of our sexual instincts would coincide with the Eros of the poets and philosophers which holds all living things together. Here then is an opportunity for looking back over the slow development of our libido theory. In the first instance the analysis of the transference neuroses forced upon our notice the opposition between the 'sexual instincts', which are directed towards an object, and certain other instincts, with which we were very insufficiently acquainted and which we described 1 2
Schopenhauer (1851; Samtliche Werke, ed. Hubscher, 1938, 5, 236). [This sentence was added in 1921.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE 1
45
A
foremost place among provisionally as the 'ego-instincts'. these was necessarily given to the instincts serving the selfwhat preservation of the individual. It was impossible to say
other distinctions were to be
drawn among them. No knowledge would have been more valuable as a foundation for true psychological science than an approximate grasp of the common characteristics and possible distinctive features of the instincts. But in no region of psychology were we groping more in the dark. Everyone assumed the existence of as many instincts or 'basic instincts' as he chose, and juggled with them like the ancient Greek natural philosophers with their four elements and water. Psycho-analysis, which could not
earth, air, fire
escape making some assumption about the instincts, kept at first to the popular division of instincts typified in the phrase 'hunger arid love'. At least there was nothing arbitrary in this; and by its help the analysis of the psychoneuroses was carried forward 1 quite a distance. The concept of 'sexuality , and at the same time of the sexual instinct, had, it is true, to be extended so as to cover many things which could not be classed under the
reproductive function; and this caused no little hubbub in an austere, respectable or merely hypocritical world.
The
next step was taken
when
psycho-analysis
closer towards the psychological ego, which it know only as a repressive, censoring agency,
had
felt its first
way come to
capable of erecting
protective structures
seeing minds had,
and
reactive formations. Critical
and
far-
true, long since objected to the concept of libido being restricted to the energy of the sexual instincts directed towards an object. But they failed to explain how they it is
had arrived at their better knowledge or to derive from it anything of which analysis could make use. Advancing more cautiously, psycho-analysis observed the regularity with which libido is withdrawn from the object and directed on to the ego (the process of introversion); and, by studying the libidinal development of children in its earliest phases, came to the conclusion that the ego is the true and Original reservoir of libido, 8 x [So, for instance, in the account of this opposition given in Freud's paper on psychogenic disturbances of vision (1910i).] * [This idea was fully stated by Freud in his paper on narcissism (1914*), Section I. See, however, his later footnote, near the beginning of Chapter III of The Ego and the Id (1923), in which he corrects this
statement and describes the id as 'the great reservoir of libido'.]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
46
and that
it is
to objects.
only from that reservoir that libido
The ego now found
its
is
extended on
among sexual place among them.
position
and was at once given the foremost Libido which was in this way lodged in the ego was described as Narcissistic*. 1 This narcissistic libido was of course also a manifestation of the force of the sexual instinct in the analytical sense of those words, and it had necessarily to be identified with objects
the 'self-preservative instincts' whose existence had been recogfirst. Thus the original opposition between the ego-instincts and the sexual instincts proved to be
nized from the
inadequate. portion of the ego-instincts was seen to be libidinal; sexual instincts probably alongside others operated in the ego. Nevertheless we are justified in saying that the old formula
A
which lays it down that psychoneuroses are based on a conflict between ego-instincts and sexual instincts contains nothing that we need reject to-day. It is merely that the distinction between the two kinds of instinct, which was originally regarded as in some sort of way qualitative) must now be characterized differently namely as being topographical. And in particular it is still true that the transference neuroses, the essential subject of psycho-analytic study, are the result of a conflict between the ego and the libidinal cathexis of objects.
But it is all the more necessary for us to lay stress upon the libidinal character of the self-preservative instincts now that we are venturing
upon
the further step of recognizing the sexual
instinct as Eros, the preserver of all things, and of deriving the narcissistic libido of the ego from the stores of libido means
of which the
we now
by
of the
soma
are attached to one another. But find ourselves suddenly faced by another question. If cells
the self-preservative instincts too are of a libidinal nature, are there perhaps no other instincts whatever but the libidinal ones? At all events there are none other visible. But in that case we shall after all
be driven to agree with the
from the first that psycho-analysis explains
critics
who
suspected
everything by sexuality,
or with innovators like Jung who, making a hasty judgement, have used the word 'libido' to mean instinctual force in general. Must not this be so? It was not our intention at all events to produce such a result. Our argument had as its point of departure a sharp distinction between ego-instincts, which we equated with death instincts, i See my paper on narcissism (1914
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE and sexual
instincts,
which we equated with
47
life instincts.
(We
were prepared at one stage [p. 33] to include the so-called selfinstincts of the ego among the death instincts; but preservative
we subsequently
[p. 46] corrected ourselves
on
this
point and
withdrew it.) Our views have from the very first been dualistict and to-day they are even more definitely dualistic than before now that we describe the opposition as being, not between egoinstincts and sexual instincts but between life instincts and death instincts. Jung's libido theory
is
on the contrary
monistic;
the fact that he has called his one instinctual force *libido* bound to cause confusion, but need not affect us otherwise. 1
is
We
suspect that instincts other than those of self-preservation operate in the ego, and it ought to be possible for us to point to them.
Unfortunately, however, the analysis of the ego has made so little
headway that
it is
very
difficult for us to
do
so. It is possible, in-
deed, that the libidinal instincts in the ego may be linked in a 2 peculiar manner with these other ego-instincts which are still strange to us. Even before we had any clear understanding of narcissism, psycho-analysts had a suspicion that the 'ego-instincts' had libidinal components attached to them. But these are very uncertain possibilities, to which our opponents will pay very attention. The difficulty remains that psycho-analysis has not enabled us hitherto to point to any [ego-] instincts other than the libidinal ones. That, however, is no reason for our falling in with the conclusion that no others in fact exist. In the obscurity that reigns at present in the theory of the instincts, it would be unwise to reject any idea that promises to started out from the great opposition throw light on it. between the life and death instincts. Now object-love itself presents us with a second example of a similar polarity that between love (or affection) and hate (or aggressiveness). If only we could succeed in relating these two polarities to each other and in deriving one from the other! From the very first we recognized the presence of a sadistic component in the sexual little
We
As we know, it can make itself independent and can, form of a perversion, dominate an individual's entire
instinct. 3
in the 1
were added in 1921.] [The two preceding sentences * by instinctual "confluence", to tiorrow [In the first edition only: a term used by Adler [1908] '.] * This was already so in the first edition of Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality in 1905 [Standard Ed., 7, 157 ff.; I.P.I., 57, 23 ff.]. *
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
48
sexual activity. It also emerges as a predominant component instinct in one of the 'pregenital organizations', as I have named them. But how can the sadistic instinct, whose aim it is the object, be derived from Eros, the preserver of life? to injure
not plausible to suppose that this sadism is in fact a death under the influence of the narcissistic libido, has been forced away from the ego and has consequently only emerged in relation to the object? It now enters the service of the sexual function. During the oral stage of organization of the libido, the act of obtaining erotic mastery over an object coincides with that object's destruction; later, the sadistic instinct separates off, and finally, at the stage of genital primacy, it takes on, for the purposes of reproduction, the function of overpowerIs
it
instinct which,
ing the sexual object to the extent necessary for carrying out the sexual act. It might indeed be said that the sadism which has been forced out of the ego has pointed the way for the libidinal components of the sexual instinct, and that these follow after it to the object. Wherever the original sadism has undergone no mitigation or intermixture, we find the familiar ambivalence of
and hate in erotic life. 1 an assumption as this
love
If such
demand
the
that
is permissible, then we have met we should produce an example of a death
though, it is true, a displaced one. But this way of looking at things is very far from being easy to grasp and creates a positively mystical impression. It looks suspiciously as though we were trying to find a way out of a highly embarrassing situation at any price. may recall, however, that there is nothing instinct
We
an assumption of this kind. We put one forward on an earlier occasion, before there was any question of an embarrass-
new
in
ing situation. Clinical observations led us at that time to the view that masochism, the component instinct which is complementary to sadism, must be regarded as sadism that has been turned round upon the subject's own ego. 2 But there is no difference in principle between an instinct turning from an object to the ego and its turning from the ego to an object which is the new point now under discussion. Masochism, the turning round of the instinct upon the subject's own ego, would 1
[This foreshadows Freud's discussion
Chap. IV of The Ego and 2
and
See
my
the
of instinctual 'fusion* in
Id (19236).]
Three Essays (1905
'Instincts
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
49
be a return to an earlier phase of the instinct's The account that was formerly given of masochism requires emendation as being too sweeping in one be such a thing as primary masochism respect: there might in that case
history, a regression.
a possibility which I had contested at that time. 1 Let us, however, return to the self-preservative sexual instincts. The experiments upon protista have already shown us that conjugation that is, the coalescence of two individuals
which separate soon afterwards without any subsequent cellhas a strengthening and rejuvenating effect 3 upon both of them. In later generations they show no signs of degenerating and seem able to put up a longer resistance to the injurious effects of their own metabolism. This single observation may, I think, be taken as typical of the effect produced by sexual union as well. But how is it that the coalescence of two only slightly different cells can bring about this renewal of life? The experiment which replaces the conjugation of protozoa by the application of chemical or even of mechanical stimuli (cf. Lipschtitz, 1914) enables us to give what is no doubt a conclusive reply to this question. The result is brought about by the influx of fresh amounts of stimulus. This tallies well with the hypothesis that the life process of the individual leads for internal reasons to an abolition of chemical tensions, that is to say, to death, whereas union with the living substance of a division occurring
different individual increases those tensions, introducing what may be described as fresh 'vital differences* which must then
be lived off. As regards this dissimilarity there must of course be one or more optima. The dominating tendency of mental life, and perhaps of nervous life in general, is the effort to reduce, to keep constant or to remove internal tension due to 1 A considerable portion of these speculations have been anticipated by Sabina Spielrein (1912) in an instructive and interesting paper which, however, is unfortunately not entirely clear to me. She there describes the sadistic components of the sexual instinct as 'destructive'. A. Starke (1914), again, has attempted to identify the concept of libido itself with the biological concept (assumed on theoretical grounds) of an impetus towards death. See also Rank (1907). All these discussions, like that in the text, give evidence of the demand for a clarification of the [A later theory of the instincts such as has not yet been achieved. discussion of the destructive instinct by Freud himself occupies Chapter VI of Civilization and its Discontents (1930a).] * See the account quoted above, pp. 41-2, from Lipschxitz (1914).
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
50
stimuli (the 'Nirvana principle', to
Low
borrow a term from Barbara
a tendency which finds expression in the * pleasure principle; and our recognition of that fact is one of our strongest reasons for believing in the existence of death [1920, 73])
instincts.
But we
still feel
our
line
of thought appreciably hampered by
we cannot
ascribe to the sexual instinct the characteristic of a compulsion to repeat which first put us on the
the fact that
track of the death instincts. The sphere of embryonic developmental processes is no doubt extremely rich in such phenomena of repetition; the two germ-cells that are involved in sexual
reproduction and their life history are themselves only repetitions of the beginnings of organic life. But the essence of the processes to which sexual life is directed is the coalescence of two cell-bodies. That alone is what guarantees the immortality of the living substance in the higher organisms. In other words, we need more information on the origin of sexual reproduction and of the sexual instincts in general. This
a problem which is calculated to daunt an outsider and which the specialists themselves have not yet been able to solve. We shall therefore give only the briefest summary of whatever seems relevant to our line of thought from among the many discordant assertions and opinions. One of these views deprives the problem of reproduction of its mysterious fascination by representing it as a part manifestais
tion of growth.
(Cf. multiplication
by
fission,
sprouting or
gemmation.) The origin of reproduction by sexually differentiated germ-cells might be pictured along sober Darwinian lines by supposing that the advantage of amphimixis, arrived at on some occasion by the chance conjugation of two protista, was
and further exploited in later development.* On this would not be anything very ancient; and the extraordinarily violent instincts whose aim it is to bring about retained
view
*sex
s
1 [Cf. p. 1 ff. The whole topic is further considered in 'The Economic Problem of Masochism* (1924<:).] * Though Weismann (1892) denies this advantage as well: 'In no case
does fertilization correspond to a rejuvenescence or renewal of life, nor occurrence necessary in order tha* life may endure: it is merely an arrangement which renders possible the intermingling of two different
is its
hereditary tendencies.' [English translation, 1893, 231.] He nevertheless believes that an intermingling of this kind leads to an increase in the variability of the organism concerned.
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE sexual union
51
would be repeating something that had once and had since become established as
occurred by chance being advantageous.
The question arises here, as in the case of death [p. 43], whether we do right in ascribing to protista those characteristics alone which they actually exhibit, and whether it is correct to assume that forces and processes which become visible only in the for the first higher organisms originated in those organisms time. The view of sexuality we have just mentioned is of little be raised against it help for our purposes. The objection may that it postulates the existence of life instincts already operating in the simplest organisms; for otherwise conjugation, which works counter to the course of life and makes the task of ceasing to live more difficult, would not be retained and elaborated but would be avoided. If, therefore, we are not to abandon the them to be hypothesis of death instincts, we must suppose associated from the very first with life instincts. But it must be admitted that in that case we shall be working upon an equation with two unknown quantities. Apart from this, science has so little to tell us about the to a darkorigin of sexuality that we can liken the problem ness into which not so much as a ray of a hypothesis has penetrated. In quite a different region, it is true, we do meet with such a hypothesis; but it is of so fantastic a kind a myth rather than a scientific explanation that I should not venture to produce it here, were it not that it fulfils precisely the one condition whose fulfilment we desire. For it traces 5
the origin of
an
instinct to a need
to restore
an
earlier state
of
things.
What put
I
have in mind
into the
is,
of course, the theory which Plato
mouth of Aristophanes in the Symposium, and which
deals not only with the origin of the sexual instinct but also with the most important of its variations in relation to its object. 'The original human nature was not like the present, but different. In the first place, the sexes were originally three in number, not two as they are now; there was man;, woman, and the union of the two. . .* Everything about these primaeval .
double: they had four hands and four feet, two faces, two privy parts, and so on. Eventually Zeus decided to cut these men in two, 'like a sorb-apple which is halved for pickAfter the division had been made, 'the two parts of man,
men was
ling'.
52
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
each desiring his other half, came together, and threw their arms about one another eager to grow into one'. 1 Shall we follow the hint given us by the poet-philosopher, and venture upon the hypothesis that living substance at the time of its coming to life was torn apart into small particles, which have ever since endeavoured to reunite through the sexual instincts? that these instincts, in which the chemical affinity of inanimate matter persisted, gradually succeeded, as they developed through the kingdom of the protista, in overcoming the difficulties put in the way of that endeavour by an environment
charged with dangerous stimuli stimuli which compelled them to form a protective cortical layer? that these splintered fragments of living substance in this way attained a multicellular condition and finally transferred the instinct for reuniting, in the most highly concentrated form, to the germ-cells? But here, I think, the moment has come for breaking off. 1 Qowett's translation. Footnote added 1921 :] I have to thank Professor Hcinrich Gomperz, of Vienna, for the following discussion on the origin of the Platonic myth, which I give partly in his own words. It is to be
remarked that what is essentially the same theory is already to be found in the Upanishads. For we find the following passage in the Brihaddranyoka-upanishad, 1, 4, 3 [Max-Mullcr's translation, 2, 85 f.], where the origin of the world from the Atman (the Self or Ego) is described: *But he felt no delight. Therefore a man who is lonely feels no delight. He wished for a second. He was so large as man and wife together. He then made this his Self to fall in two, and then arose husband and wife. Therefore Yagflavalkya .said:''" We two are thus (each of us) like half a shell.*' Therefore the void which was there, is filled by the wife.* The Brihaddranyaka-upanishadis, the most ancient of all the Upanishads, and no competent authority dates it later than about the year 800 B.C. In contradiction to the prevailing opinion, I should hesitate to give an unqualified denial to the possibility of Plato's myth being derived, even if it were only indirectly, from the Indian source, since a similar possibility cannot be excluded in the case of the doctrine of transmigration. But even if a derivation of this kind (through the Pythagoreans in the first instance) were established, the significance of the coincidence between the two trains of thought would scarcely be diminished. For Plato would not have adopted a story of this kind which had somehow reached him through some oriental tradition to say nothing of giving it so important a place unless it had struck him as containing an element of truth. In a paper devoted to a systematic examination of this line of thought before the time of Plato, Ziegler (1913) traces it back to Babylonian origins.
[Freud had already alluded to Plato's Standard Ed., 7, 136; I.P.L., 57, 2.]
myth
in his Three Essays,
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
53
Not, however, without the addition of a few words of critical
may be asked whether and how far I am myself convinced of the truth of the hypotheses that have been set out answer would be that I am not convinced in these pages. myself and that I do not seek to persuade other people to believe in them. Or, more precisely, that I do not know how far I believe in them. There is no reason, as it seems to me, why the emotional factor of conviction should enter into this question reflection. It
My
at all. It is surely possible to throw oneself into a line of thought and to follow it wherever it leads out of simple scientific curiosity, or, if the reader prefers, as an advocatus diaboli, who is not on that account himself sold to the devil. I do not dispute the fact that the third step in the theory of the instincts, which I have taken here, cannot lay claim to the same degree of certainty as the two earlier ones the extension of the concept of sexuality and the hypothesis of narcissism. These two innovations were a direct translation of observation into theory and were no more open to sources of error than is inevitable in all such cases. It is
assertion of the regressive character of instincts namely on the facts of the
true that
my
also rests
upon observed material
may be, however, that I have overestimated their significance. And in any case it is impossible to pursue an idea of this kind except by repeatedly combining factual material with what is purely speculative and thus diverging widely from empirical observation. The more frequently this is done in the course of constructing a theory, the more compulsion to repeat. It
untrustworthy, as we know, must be the final result. But the degree of uncertainty is not assignable. One may have made a lucky hit or one may have gone shamefully astray. I do not think a large part is played by what is called 'intuition* in work of this kind. From what I have seen of intuition, it seems to
me
to
be the product of a kind of
intellectual impartiality.
Unfortunately, however, people are seldom impartial where ultimate things, the great problems of science and life, are concerned. Each of us is governed in such cases by deep -rooted internal prejudices, into whose hands our speculation unwittingly plays. Since we have such good grounds for being distrustour attitude towards the results of our own deliberations cannot well be other than one of cool benevolence. I hasten to
ful,
add, however, that self-criticism such as this is far from binding to any special tolerance towards dissentient opinions. It is
one
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
54
perfectly legitimate to reject remorselessly theories which are contradicted by the very first steps in the analysis of observed
while yet being aware at the same time that the validity of one's own theory is only a provisional one. We need not feel greatly disturbed in judging our speculation upon the life and death instincts by the fact that so many bewildering and obscure processes occur in it such as one instinct being driven out by another or an instinct turning from the ego to an object, and so on. This is merely due to our being obliged to operate with the scientific terms, that is to say with facts,
the figurative language, peculiar to psychology (or, more precisely, to depth psychology). We could not otherwise describe the processes in question at all, and indeed we could not have become aware of them. The deficiencies in our description would probably vanish if we were already in a position to replace the psychological terms by physiological or chemical ones. It is true that they too are only part of a figurative language; but it is one with which we have long been familiar
and which
perhaps a simpler one as well. it should be made quite clear that the uncertainty of our speculation has been greatly increased by the necessity for borrowing from the science of biology. Biology is truly a land of unlimited possibilities. We may expect it to give us the most surprising information and we cannot guess what answers it will return in a few dozen years to the questions we have put to it. They may be of a kind which will blow away the whole of our artificial structure of hypotheses. If so, it may be asked why I have embarked upon such a line of thought as the present one, and in particular why I have decided to make I cannot deny that some of the analogies, it public. Well
On
is
the other hand
and connections which deserve consideration. 1
correlations
it
contains seemed to
me to
1 1 will add a few words to clarify our terminology, which has undergone some development in the course of the present work. We came to know what the 'sexual instincts' were from their relation to the sexes
and
to the reproductive function.
We retained
this
name
after
we had
been obliged by the findings of psycho-analysis to connect them less closely with reproduction. With the hypothesis of narcissistic libido and the extension of the concept of libido to the individual cells, the sexual was transformed for us into Eros, which seeks to force together and hold together the portions of living substance. What are commonly called the sexual instincts are looked upon by us as the part of Eros instinct
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
55
directed towards objects. Our speculations have suggested that Eros operates from the beginning of life and appears as a *Jife instinct* in opposition to the *death instinct* which was brought into being by the coming to life of inorganic substance. These speculations seek to solve the riddle of life by supposing that these two instincts were struggling with each other from the very first. [Added 1921 :] It is not so easy, perhaps, to follow the transformations through which the concept of the *ego-instincts* has passed. To begin with we applied that name to all the instinctual trends (of which we had no closer knowledge) which could be distinguished from the sexual instincts directed towards an object; and we opposed the ego-instincts to the sexual instincts of which the libido is the manifestation. Subsequently we came to closer grips with the analysis of the ego and recognized that a portion of the 'ego1 instincts is also of a Hbidinal character and has taken the subject's own ego as its object. These narcissistic self^preservative instincts had thenceforward to be counted among the iibidinal sexual instincts. The opposition between the ego-instincts and the sexual instincts was transformed into one between the ego-instincts and the object-instincts, both of a Iibidinal nature. But in its place a fresh opposition appeared between the
which
is
Iibidinal (ego- and object-) instincts and others, which must be presumed to be present in the ego and which may perhaps actually be observed in the destructive instincts. speculations have transformed this opposition into one between the life instincts (Eros) and the death
Our
instincts. [
For a general account of the development of Freud's views on the the Editor's Note to 'Instinc'ts and their Vicissitudes"
instincts, see ),
Standard Ed. t 14, 111.]
VII really the case that seeking to restore an earlier state of such a universal characteristic of instincts, we need not things be surprised that so many processes take place in mental life
IF
it is
is
independently of the pleasure principle. This characteristic would be shared by all the component instincts and in their
would aim at returning once more to a particular stage in the course of development. These are matters over which the pleasure principle has as yet no control; but it does not follow
case
that any of them are necessarily opposed to it, and we have still to solve the problem of the relation of the instinctual processes of repetition to the dominance of the pleasure principle.
We
have found that one of the
earliest
and most important
functions of the mental apparatus is to bind the instinctual impulses which impinge on it, to replace the primary process prevailing in them by the secondary process and convert their freely mobile cathectic energy into a mainly quiescent (tonic) cathexis. While this transformation is taking place no
can be paid to the development of unpleasure; but does not imply the suspension of the pleasure principle. the contrary, the transformation occurs on behalf of the
attention this
On
pleasure principle; the binding is a preparatory act which introduces and assures the dominance of the pleasure principle.
Let us make a sharper distinction than we have hitherto made between function and tendency. The pleasure principle, then, is a tendency operating in the service of a function whose business it is to free the mental apparatus entirely from excitation or to keep the amount of excitation in it constant or to cannot yet decide with certainty keep it as low as possible.
We
in favour of any of these ways of putting it; but it is clear that the function thus described would be concerned with the most universal endeavour of
all living substance to the quiescence of the inorganic world. enced how the greatest pleasure attainable
namely to return have all experi-
We
sexual act,
is
by us, that of the momentary extinction of a highly The binding of an instinctual impulse
associated with a
intensified excitation.
would be a preliminary function designed to prepare the excitation for
its final
elimination in the pleasure of discharge. 56
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
57
of whether feelings of pleasure and This can be produced equally from bound and from unpleasure unbound excitatory processes. And there seems to be no doubt whatever that the unbound or primary processes give rise to far more intense feelings in both directions than the bound or secondary ones. Moreover the primary processes are the earlier in time; at the beginning of mental life there are no others, and raises the question
we may infer that if the pleasure principle had not already been operative in them it could never have been established for the thus reach what is at bottom no later ones.
We
very simple
conclusion, namely that at the beginning of mental life the struggle for pleasure was far more intense than later but not so unrestricted: it had to submit to frequent interruptions. In later
dominance of the pleasure principle is very much it itself has no more escaped the process of taming than the other instincts in general. In any case, whatever it is that causes the appearance of feelings of pleasure and unpleasure in processes of excitation must be present in the times the
more
secure, but
secondary process just as it is in the primary one. Here might be the starting-point for fresh investigations.
Our
consciousness communicates to us feelings from within not only of pleasure and unpleasure but also of a peculiar tension which in its turn can be either pleasurable or unpleasurable. Should the difference between these feelings enable us to distinguish between bound and "unbound processes of energy? or is the feeling of tension to be related to the absolute magnitude, or
perhaps to the level, of the cathexis, while the pleasure and unpleasure series indicates a change in the magnitude of the cathexis within a given unit of time? * Another striking fact is that the life instincts have so much more contact with our internal perception emerging as breakers of the peace and constantly
producing tensions whose release is felt as pleasure while the death instincts seem to do their work unobtrusively. The pleasure principle seems actually to serve the death instincts. It is true that it keeps watch upon stimuli from without, which are regarded as dangers by both kinds of instincts; but it is more especially on guard against increases of stimulation from
within, which would make the task of living more difficult. This in turn raises a host of other questions to which we can at 1 [Cf. above, p. 2. These questions had already been touched on by Freud in his 'Project', e.g. in Part I, Section 8 and Part III, Section L]
BEYOND THE PLEASURE PRINCIPLE
58
no answer. We must be patient and await fresh methods and occasions of research. We must be ready, too, to abandon a path that we have followed for a time, if it seems to be leading to no good end. Only believers, who demand that science shall be a substitute for the catechism they have given up, will blame an investigator for developing or even transforming his views. We may take comfort, too, for the slow advances of our scientific knowledge in the words of the poet: present find
Was man Die
nicht erfliegen kann,
Schrift sagt, es
ist
muss
man
erhinken.
keine Siinde zu hinken. 1
1 The ['What we cannot reach flying we must reach limping. Book tells us U is no sin to limp.' The last lines of 'Die beiden Gulden', a version by Riickert of one of the Maqdmdt of al-Hariri. Freud also .
.
.
quoted these lines in a letter to FUess of Oct. 20, 1895 (Freud 1950a Letter 32).]
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS = Freud, Gesammclte Schriften (12 vols.), Vienna, 1924-34. = Freud, Gesarnmdtc W&rke (18 vols), London, from 1940.
G
QW. '
--
P
^" ,
j
TJ\
Standard Ed.) /.
PX.
Freud,
Collected Papers (5 vols.),
London, 1924-50.
= Freud, Standard Edition (24 vols.), London, from 1953. = International Psycho-Analytical Library, Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analysis,
Theoretische SehrifUn
= Freud,
London, from 1921.
Theoretischt Schriften (79/7-^5),
1931,
59
Vienna,
BIBLIOGRAPHY AND AUTHOR INDEX books and periodicals are in italics; tides of papers are in commas. Abbreviations are in accordance with the World List
[Titles of
inverted
of Scientific Periodicals (London, 1952). Further abbreviations used in this volume \vill be found in the List on page 59. Numerals in thick type refer to volumes; ordinary numerals refer to pages. The figures in round brackets at the end of each entry indicate the page or pages of this volume on which the work in question is mentioned. In the case of the Freud entries, the letters attached to the dates of publication are in accordance with the corresponding entries in the complete bibliography of Freud's writings to be included in the last volume of the Standard Edition.
For non-technical authors, and for technical authors where no work is mentioned, see the General Index.]
specific
ABLER, A.
'Der Aggressionsbetrieb im Leben und in der Neurose', Mid., No. 19, (47)
(1 908)
Forisckr.
J., and FREUD, S. (1893) See FREUD, S. (1893
BREUER,
(1940) See FREUD, S.(1940<0 DOFLEIN, F. (1919) Das Problem des Todes und der Unsterblichkeit bd dm Pflanzen und Tieren, Jena. (41) FECHNER, G. T. (1873) Einige Ideen zur Schopfungs- und Entwicktungsgeschichte der Organismen, Leipzig. (2, 4) J
FERENCZI,S. (1913) 'EntwicklungssUifendesWirklichkeitssinnes ,/n^<;. 1, 124. (35)
PsychoanaL,
[Trans.: 'Stages in the
Development of the Sense of Reality', London, 1952, Chap. VIII.]
First Contributions to Psycho-Analysis,
FUESS,
W.
FREUD,
S. (1893a)
(1906) DerAblaufdesLebens, Vienna. (39)
With BREUER, J.,'t)ber den psychischcn Mechanismus Phanomene: Vorlaufige Mittcilung', G.S., 1, 7;
hysterischer
.W., 1,81. (7) [Trans.: 'On the Psychical Mechanism of Hysterical Phenomena: Preliminary Communication', C.P., 1, 24: Standard Ed.,
2,3.] (1895rf)
G.W.,
With BREUER, 1, 75.
J.,
Stodun uber Hysterie, Vienna, G.S.,
Omitting Breuer's contributions.
(3, 19,
1;
21, 28)
[Trans.: Studies on Hysteria, Standard Ed., 2; I.P.L., 50. Including
Breuer*s contributions.]
(1900a) Die Traumdtutung, Vienna,
O, 2-3; G.W., 2-3.
(x,
8-9,
18-19, 26, 28) [Trans.:
The
Interpretation
5; Standard Ed.,
of Dreams, London and
-S.]
60
New
York,
BIBLIOGRAPHY FREUD,
61
S. (cont.)
Der Witz and seine Beziehung zum Unbewussten, Vienna. G.S., G. W., 6. (29) [Trans.: Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious, London, 1960;
(1905c) 9, 5;
Standard Ed., 8.] (1905
Vienna. G.S.,
5, 3;
G. W.,
47-8, 52)
[Trans.: Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality, London, 1949; Standard Ed., 7, 125; I.P.L., 57.] (1910:) 'Die psychogene Sehstorung in psychoanalytischer Auffassung', G.S., 5, 301; G.W., 8, 94. (45) [Trans.: 'The Psycho-Analytic View of Psychogenic Disturbance of Vision', C.P., 2, 105; Standard Ed., 11, 211.] (19116) 'Formulierungen iiber die zwei Prinzipien des psychischen Geschehens', G.S., 5, 409; G.W., 8, 230. (xi, 4) [Trans.: *Formulations on the Two Principles of Mental Functioning', C.P., 4, 13; Standard Ed., 12, 215.] (1914c) 'Zur Einfuhrung des Narzissmus', G.S., 6, 155; G.W., 10, 138. (xii, 27, 45-6) [Trans.: 'On Narcissism: Ed., 14, 69.]
an
Introduction', C.P., 4, 30; Standard
(1914^) *Weitere Ratschlage zur Technik der Psychoanalyse: II Erinnern, Wiederholen und Durcharbeiten', G.S. t 6, 109; G. W., 10, 126. (12) [Trans.:
(Further
Repeating and Working Through Recommendations on the Technique of Psycho-
'Recollecting,
Analysis, II)', C.P., 2, 366; Standard Ed., 12, 147.] (1915c) 'Triebe und Triebschicksale', G.S., 5, 443; G.W., 10, 210. (xii, 24, 48, 55) [Trans.: Instincts and their Vicissitudes', C.P., 4, 60; Standard Ed., 14, 111.] (1915*) 'Das Unbewusste', G.S.> 5, 480; G.W., 10, 264. (1, 18, 22) [Trans.: 'The Unconscious', C.P 4, 98; Standard Ed., 14, 161.] in die Psychoanalyse, Vienna. 11. (14) [Trans.: Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis, revised ed., Lon-, York, don, 1929 (A General Introduction to Psychoanalysis,
(1916-17) Vorlesungen zur Einfuhrung G.S.,
7;G.W.,
New
1935); Standard Ed., 15-16.] (19176) *Eine Kindheitserinnerung aus Dichtung und Wahrheif, G.S., 10, 357; G.W., 12, 15. (10) [Trans.: 'A Childhood Recollection from Dichtung und Wahrhdt\ C.P., 4, 357; Standard Ed., 17, 147.]
5 (1917^) 'Metapsychologische Erganzung zur Traumlehre*, G.S., t 520;.W., 10, 412. (18, 24) 'A Metapsychological Supplement to the Theory of [Trans.:
Dreams', OP., 4, 137; Standard Ed., 15, 219.] der Kriegsneurosm, Vienna. (1919 12, 321. (6, 27)
BIBLIOGRAPHY
62
FREUD,
S. (cont.)
and the War Neuroses, [Trans.: Introduction to Psycho-Analysis London and York, 1921. C.P., 5, 83; Standard Ed., 17, 207.] G.S. y 10, 369; G.W., 12, 229. (ix-x) (19194) 'Das Unheimliche', Standard Ed., 17, 219.] [Trans.: 'The Uncanny*, C.P., 4, 368;
New
of Congress (1920/) 'Erganzungen zur Traumlehre' (Abstract Address), Int. %. Psychoan., 6, 397. of Dreams', Standard Ed., [Trans.: 'Supplements to the Theory 18, 4; I.P.L., 4, x.]
(1920^) Jenseitsdes Lustprinzips, Vienna. G.S., 6, 191; G.W., 13, 3. Standard Ed., 18, 7; [Trans.: Beyond the Pleasure Principle, I.P.L., 4.]
(1921) Introduction in English to J. Varendonck's The Psycho271. (xi) logy of Day-Dreams, London; Standard Ed., 18, [German Text (part only): G.S., 11, 264; G.W., 13, 439.] (1923) Das Ich und das Es, Vienna. G.S., 6, 353; G.W., 13, 237. 13,45,43) Ego and the Id, Standard Ed,, 19, 3; I.P.L., 12.] (1923c [1922]) 'Bemerkungcn zur Theorie und Praxis der Traumdeutung', G.S., 3, 305; G.W., 13, 301. (14, 26) [Trans.: 'Remarks on the Theory and Practice of DreamInterpretation*, C?., 5, 136; Standard Ed., 19, 109.] (1924c) 'Das okonomische Problem des Masochismus', G.S., 5, 374; G.W., 13, 371. (2, 50) [Trans.: 'The Economic Problem of Masochism', C.P., 2, 255; (xi,
[Trans.: The
Standard Ed,, 19, 157.]
(1925a [1924]) 'Notiz uber den "Wunderblock" *, G.S., 6, 415; G.W., 14,3. (19,22) [Trans.: 'A Note upon the "Mystic Writing-Pad" ', C.P., 5, 175; Standard Ed., 19,227.] (1925* [1924]) 'Die Widerstande gegen die Psychoanalyse', GJS., 11, 224; G.W., 14, 99. (44) [Trans.: *The^ ^Resistance to Psycho-Analysis', C.P., 5, 163; Standard Ed., 19,213.] (1926rf) Hemmung, Symptom und Angst, Vienna. G.S. t 11, 23; G.W.,
14,113.
(7,
14,24)
[Trans.: Inhibitions^ Symptoms and Anxiety, Standard Ed., 20, 77; I.P.L., 28.] (1930a) Das Unbehagen in der Kuttur, Vienna. G.S., 12, 29; G.W., 14, 421. (49)
[Trans.: Civilization and its Discontents, 1930; Standard Ed., 21, 59.]
--
London and New York,
(1940<0 With BREUER, J., 'Zur Theorie des hysterischen Anfalls',
G.W., 17,
9. (3)
'On the Theory of
Hysterical Attacks', C.P., 5, 27; Standard Ed., 1.] (1941s) Brief an Josef Breuer, G.W., 17, 5. (3) Letter to Josef Breuer, OP., 5, 25; Standard Ed., 1.] [Trans.: (1942
A
BIBLIOGRAPHY
63
S. (cont.)
FREUD,
305. Translation of 'Psychopathische Personen auf der Buhne', which has not been published in German. (11)
Aus den Anfangen der Psychoanalyse, London. [Includes 'Entwurf einer Psychologic' (1895).] (xii, 2-3, 19-20, 22-4,
(19500)
57-8) [Trans.: The Origins of Psycho-Analysis, 1954. (Partly, including 'A Project for
in Standard Ed., 1.)] (1955c) 'Gutachten iiber die elektrische [Trans.:
a
Scientific Psychology',
Behandlung der Kriegs-
German
text unpublished. (6) Memorandum on the Electrical
neurotiker'; *
London and New York,
Treatment of
War
Neuroses', Standard Ed., 17, 211.]
FREUD,
S.,
FERENCZI,
S.,
and
others* (1919)
%ur Psychoanalyse
der Krieg$~
neurosm, Vienna. (6) [Trans.: Psycho-Analysis
and
the
War
Neuroses,
London and New
York, 1921.] GOETTE, A. (1883) Uber den Ursprung des Todes, Hamburg. (41) HARTMANN, M. (1906) Tod und Fortpflanzung, Munich. (41) JUNG, C. G. (1909) 'Die Bedeutung des Vaters fur das Schicksal dcs Einzelnen', Jb. psychoanal. psychopath. Forsch., 1, 155. (16) [Trans.: "The Significance of the Father in the Destiny of the Individual', Collected Papers on Analytical Psychology, London, 1916, 156.]
Warum wir sterben, Stuttgart. (41, 49) Low, B. (1920) Psycho-Analysis, London. (50) MARCINOWSKI, J. (1918) 'Die erotischen Quellen der Minderwertig. Sexualwiss., 4, 313. (14) keitsgefuhle', LIPSCHUTZ, A. (1914)
1
PFEIFER, S. (1919) 'Ausserungen infantil-erotischer Triebe im Spiele , Imago, 5, 243. (8) RANK, O. (1907) Der Kunstler, Vienna. (49) RICKMAN, J. (ed.) (1937) A General Selection from the Works of Sigmund Freud, London, (xii) SCHOPENHAUER, A. (1851)
't^ber die anscheinende Absichtlichkeit
im
Schicksale des Einzelnen', Parerga und Paralipomena, 1 (Sdmtliche Werke, ed. Hubscher, Leipzig, 1938, 5, 213). (44) SPIELREIN, S. (1912) 'Die Destruktion als Ursache des Werdens', Jb. psychoanaL psychopath. Forsch., 4, 465. (49) STARCKE, A. (1914) Introduction to Dutch translation of Freud's '
"Civilized"
Sexual Morality and Modern Nervous
Illness',
Leyden. (49) Psychology of Day-Dreams, London, (xi) (1882) Uber die Dauer des Lebens, Jena. (39) (1884) DberLeben und Tod, Jena. (39-41) (1892) Das fCeimplasma, Jena. (39HM), 50) [Trans.: The Germ-Plasm, London, 1893.] klass. ZIEGLER, K. (1913) 'Menschen- und Weltenwerden', Neue Jb.
VARENDONCK, J. (1921) The
WEBMANN, A.
Altert.,
31, 529. (52)
GENERAL INDEX This index includes the names of non-technical authors. It also includes the names of technical authors where no reference is made in the text to specific works. For references to specific technical works, the Bibliography should be consulted. Abraham, K., 6 n. I Abreaction, 11 Active and passive in children's play,
Child, desire to have,
KM 1,29
compulsion to repeat 8-11, 17,29-30 play of, 8-11, 17,29
Ambivalence and the opposition between the life and death instincts, 47-8 Amphimixis, 42, 50
sexual researches
47-9, 56 Compulsion to repeat as an attribute of organic 30-2, 34, 38, 50-3, 56
ality,51-2
life,
12during psycho-analysis, 17, 29-30 in children, ix, xi, 8-1 1, 1 7, 29-30 in dreams during traumatic neuroses, 7, 17, 26-7 in normal people, 15-16
conservative nature of instinct in,
ix, xi,
29-34, 36 death of, 39-43 duration of life in, 39-44 Anticathexis, 24
Fear;
15
Component instincts,
Animals
also
of,
in, ix, xi,
Ctorinda (in Gerusalenane Liberata), 16
Analogy, Plato's myth of bisexu-
(set
15
ality)
Aggressiveness, 47
Anxiety
by father,
Childhood, traumas of, xi, 26 Children (sec also Infantile sexu-
Fright;
instinctual character of, ix, xi, 14-
defined,
6-7
15,17,29-31,50-3,56 Condensation, 28 Confluence of instincts, 47
preparedness for, 7 n. 1, 25-7 Anxiety dreams, x, 7, 26 Aristophanes, 51-2 Art, 11
Atman
(in the Upanishads), 1 'Autistic thinking , xi
52
.
1
Biological
concept of death, 39-43, 49 n.
Cs. (see
Conscious system)
51-2 1
'Daemonic force , 15, 29-30 Danger, perception of, 5-6, 33, 52 Darwin, Charles, 50 Day's residues, 28, 30
'Bound*
energy (see psychical Energy, psychical, bound and
unbound) Brain, anatomy of the, 18 Braut mm Messina, Die,- 39 Breutr, 7. (see also Bibliography),
Death aim oflife is, 32-4, 3&-9, 49
20-1, 25, 28
biological
49 Calkins,
also
m 2,
56
1
54
Bisexuality,
2
Constancy, principle of (see Excitatory processes), 3, 3
Beiden Gulden, Die, 58
factors,
n.
Conscience, x Conscious system, 18-22, 28 Consciousness admissibility to, 12-13, 19 origin of, 19-21
. JV.,
Cathexis
(set
42
concept
of,
39-43,
n. 1
internal necessity of, 32, 38-41, 43 'natural', 34, 39-43
Excitatory processes)
Wtismanrfs views on, 39-43
Censorship, x, 45
64
GENERAL INDEX Death instinct (seealso Ego-instincts),
54 ix, 32-5, 38, 40-1, 43-51, equated with ego-instinct, 38, 46,
54.
in opposition to life instinct, xi, 34-5, 38, 43, 47, 54 n.
Dementia praecox, 27 Destiny, compulsion of, 15-17 Destructiveness, xi, 49 n. 1 Displacement in dreams, 28 Dream-content, manifest, 28
65
External world, 18, 20-2
Fairy tales, 14 Father
3
daughter's desire for a child by, 15 jealousy of, 10 Faust (Goethe), 36
Fear
also (see Anxiety; Fright; Phobia), 6, 7 . Fechnert G. T. (see also Bibliography), 2 4 >.
Dreams and sleep, 26-7
Ferencziy S.
6
n. 1,
(see also
26-7,
39,
58
Bibliography),
7
Fliess, Wilhelm
26
anxiety-, x, 7, as wish-fulfilments, x~xi, 7,
B.
(see also
Bibliography),
n.
censorship of, x, 45
Forgetting, 26 Fright (see also Anxiety; Fear), 6-7,
displacement in, 28 during psycho-analysis, 15, 26 hallucinatory character of, 26 'prospective* function of, x
Genital primacy, 48 Gervsalemme Liberata (Tasso), 16
punishment-, x, 26
Goethe, 10 n. 2,
30
traumatic, xi,
7, 17,
26
Dream-thoughts, latent, xi
Dream-work,
xi,
25
36
Gompcrz, H., 52 n. Guilt, sense of, 26
1
28 Hague, The, x Hallucinatory character of dreams,
Ego and
pleasure principle, 14, 17 as reservoir of libido, 44-6, 48 masochistic trends of, 7-8, 48-9 nucleus of, 13 repressive forces of, 13-14, 17 unconscious part of, 13-14 unification of, 4-5, 13, 27
Ego
ideal,
x
Ego-instincts (see also Death instinct; Self-preservation, instinct of),
38,4^7 equated with death 46,
54
instinct, 38,
n.
26 Hereditary factors, 31 Hering, E. t 43
Hunger, 45 Hypochondria, 6 Hysteria, x, 6-7 Id, the, 45 . 2 Inertia, neuronic, principle of, 3 Infantile sexuality, 1 2, 14-15, 45 Inferiority, sense of, 14-15 Instincts
also
(see
stincts;
Death
Component
.
in-
Ego-
instinct;
in opposition to sexual instinct, 35, 38, 44-9, 54 n. Eitingon, Dr. Af., ix
instincts; Life instinct; Self-preservation, instinct of; Sexual
Embryology, 20, 31, 50
45-7, 49
Energy, psychical, bound and unbound, 1-2, 20-5, 27-30, 56-7 Eros (see also Libido; Life instinct; Sexual instinct), xi, 36-7, 44, 46, 48, Excitations
54
external, 20-6, 34, 35 n. 3, 49-50,
instinct),
4-5, n. 1,
14-15,
28-38,
53-7
'conservatism' of, 30-5, 38 Instinctual character of the compulsion to repeat, ix, xi, 14-15, 17, 29-31, 50-3, 56 International Psycho-Analytical Congress, x
Introversion,
45
52,57 internal, 22-3, 28, 57 Excitatory processes, 1, 3, 17, 30,
56-7
Jealousy of father, 10 of younger child, 10
B. 1,
15
GENERAL INDEX
66 Jokes, 29
Jones, E.,6n. I Jowctt, B., 52 n. I Jung, C. G. (see also Bibliography),
46-7
Oedipus complex, 12, 14-15 Oral phase, 48 Organic injury, and neurosis, 6, 27 life, and the compulsion to repeat, 30-2, 34, 38, 53, 56
Kant,
/.,
22
Libido
48
as reservoir of, 44-6,
ego Jung's view
46-7
of,
54 n. Libido theory, 27, 44-8, 49 n. Narcissistic, 46, 48,
54 n.
1 ,
Life
aim of,
death, 32, 34, 38-9, 49 duration of, 39-44 origin of, 32-3, 35, 50 Life instinct (see also Eros; Sexual is
instinct), 34-5, 38, 43-8, 51, 54,
57 loeb,
Pain, physical, 24 Pan-sexualism, 46 Parental complex, 14m 2 Parents and children, relation between (see also Father; Mother;
Oedipus complex), 14-15 Ptpt. (see Perceptual system) PCS. (see Preconscious system)
Perceptual system, 18-19,22 Periodicity (Fliess's theory of), 39 Perversion, 47-8
Phantasies
unconscious, xi
3; 42
wishful,
Maqdmdt of al-Hariri, 58
n.
Masochism, 7-8, 48-9 Maupas, E., 41-2 Melancholia, 6, 27
Memory- traces,
18-19, 30
Mental apparatus, 3-5,
8, 18,
23-6,
28-9, 56
30
Anxiety), 36 Physical injury and neurosis, 6, 27 pain, 24 Plants, 33-4, 39 Plato, 51-2, 52 n. 1 Play of children, 8-1 1, 1 7, 29 Pleasure principle
Phobias
(see also
Mephistopheles (in Faust}, 36 Migration of birds and fishes, 3 1 Mother, child's fear of losing, 8-10
dominance of, 1-4, 11, 14, 23-9, 49-50, 56-7 over-ridden by compulsion to re-
Myths, 51, 52
peat, ix, 8-1 1, 14-18, 36-40, 56 relation to principle of constancy,
n. 1
3 Preconscious system, xi, 13, 28 Primary process (see also Energy,
Narcissism, 14, 46-8, 53^ and physical injury, 27 'of germ-cells',
Neuroses
44
(see also
rosis;
Obsessional neu-
Transference-neuroses;
Traumatic neuroses;
War
neu-
roses)
sexual aetiology of, 33-*, 45 theory of, 33-4, 44-5 Neurotics
compared
to
normal persons, 15
16 psycho-analysis
of, ix, xi,
29-30 'Nirvana principle*, 50 Object-choice, 44-9, 54 Object-instincts, 54 n. Obsessional neurosis, x
13-16,
psychical, bound and unbound), 4, 28-9, 56-7 Primitive peoples, superstitious beliefs of,
39
Principle constancy,
3
n. 2,
insusceptibility
of 2
3,
systems, 24
n.
neuronic inertia, 3 'Nirvana*, 50
n.
uncathected 2
pleasure (see Pleasure principle) reality, 4-5, 14, 29 stability (Fechner),
n.
56
2-3
Projection, 23 'Prospective* function of dreams, x Protective shield against stimuli,
21-6
GENERAL INDEX Protista,
12-15
Psycho-analytic technique, 1 Psycho-analytic theory, 46 'pan-sexualism' of, Psycho-analytic treatment of neurotics, ix, xi, 13-16, 29-
30 termination
of,
of,
1,7
Superstitious belieis, 39
sion to repeat)
Repression
and compulsion to repeat, 12-14, 26,30 and pleasure principle, 5, 14 13-14, 17, 45
36-7
Resistance
and
n.
Symposium, The, 51-2
Reaction-formation, 45 Reality-principle, 4-5, 14, 29 Regression, masochism as, 49 Repeat, compulsion to (see Compul-
of,
origin of, 50-2 Sexual intercourse, 56 Shock and traumatic neurosis, 25
Suggestion as a factor in psychoanalysis, 14n. 2, 26
Quality, 2-3, 23, 25 Quantity, 2, 2 n. 1, 25
instinctual, 5, 14,
ego, 14
of, in psycho-analytic treatment, 12-14 transference exploited by, 17
overcoming
Ruckert F., 58 n.
Tancred (in Gerusalemme Liberaia), 16 Tasso, 16 Three Wishes, The, 14 n. 3 Time, sense of, related to Pcpt.-Cs.,
22 Tragedy,
11
Transference, 12, 15-17, 30 exploited by resistance, 17 Transference neuroses (see also HysObsessional Neurosis), teria; 12-13, 44, 46 Transmigration, 52 n. 1
Trauma,
6-8, 23-7
infantile, xi,
26
Traumatic dreams,
26 17,25-9
x, xi, 7, 1 7,
neurosis, 6-8,
Sadism, 47-8, 49 39 Schopenhauer, A.
instinct, 34-5,
Sleep and dreams, 26-7 Stability, principle of (Feehner), 2-3 Stimuli, 20-6, 34, 35 n. 3, 49-50, 52, 57
12-13
Psychoneuroses (see Neuroses) Punishment-dreams, x, 26 n. I Pythagoras, 52
ego as agent
life
38, 40, 44, 47, 54 n. in opposition to ego-instincts, 35, 38, 44-7, 54 .
Simmel, E., 6
30
therapeutic aspect
67
equated with
38-44, 49-52
n. 1
Uncathected
Schiller, F.,
also
Biblio-
(see also
Energy,
(see
graphy), 44
Secondary process
psychical, bound 28, 30, 56-7
and unbound)
Self-preservation, instinct of (see also Ego-instincts), 4, 33, 45-7, 49,
54 n. Sexual aetiology of the neuroses, 33-
4,45 Sexual curiosity of children, 15 Sexual excitement and mechanical agitation, 27 Sexual instinct (see also Eros; Libido;
systems,
insuscepti-
bility to excitation of,
Unconscious ego, 13-14 mental processes, 12-13, systems, 28 Unconscious, the, 28 relation to Cs., 19, 22, tixnelessness of,
24 n. 2
18,
22
28
22
Unpleasure, 1-5, 10-11, 14-15, 18, 23-4, 32, 56-7 Fechner's
view
of,
2-4
neurotic, 'pleasure that cannot felt as such', 5 Upanishads, 52 n.
be
1
Life instinct)
and component instincts, 47-8, 49 n. 1,53 and pleasure principle, 4-5
Varendonck,J. (see also Bibliography),
GENERAL INDEX
68
Waking
life,
relation of
dreams
to,
28
War of 1914-18, War neuroses, 6 Weismann, A.
39-43
6
(see also
Wsh-nilfilment in dreams, x-xl, 26-7, 30 Woodruff, L. L. 9 41-2
Bibliography),
Zeus, 51
7.
Norton Paperbacks
PSYCHIATRY AND PSYCHOLOGY Adams James L ,
Adler, Alfred
.
).
and Social Interest.
Superiority
The Authoritarian Personality (Abr. Ed. ).
et al.
Alexander, Franz.
Psychosomatic Medicine.
Bernheim, Kay la
and
Ed
Cooperation Between the Sexes.
.
Adorno, T. W.
Conceptual Blockbusting (2d
.
Adler, Alfred.
and Richard R.J. Lewine.
F.
Schizophrenia: Symptoms, Causes,
Treatments.
Bowers, Kenneth
Hypnosis: For the Seriously Curious.
S_.
Bruner, Jerome S,
Bruner, Jerome S.
Beyond the Information Given. The Relevance of Education.
Burgess Linda Cannon ,
Cannon, Walter B. Cannon, Walter B.
Damon, William
.
The A rt of Adoption.
.
The Way of an Investigator. The Wisdom of the Body. Social
and Personality
Development: Essays on the
Growth of the Child. Damon William. Social and Personality Development: ,
Infancy Through
Adolescence.
Daniels, Pamela and Kathy Parenthood
Donaldson, Margaret.
Children's Minds.
Erikson, Erik
H.
Erikson Erik
H
Erikson, Erik
H.
Dimensions of a
H. Erik H.
Gandhi's Truth.
,
.
Erikson, Erik Erikson,
Erikson Erik
H
Erikson, Erik
H. H.
,
Erikson, Erik Fancher,
Fancher,
Sooner or Later: The Timing of
Wemgarten.
m Adult Lives.
.
Raymond Raymond
Adulthood.
Childhood and Society.
Identity: Youth
New Identity. and Crisis.
and the Life Cycle. Insight and Responsibility. Identity
Young
Man Luther.
E.
Pioneers of Psychology.
E.
Psychoanalytic Psychology: The Development of
Freud's Thought.
Finch, Stuart
Freud, Anna.
M.
Fundamentals of Child Psychiatry.
Psychoanalysis for Teachers
and Parents.
Freud, Sigmund.
An Autobiographical Study.
Freud Sigmund
Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
,
.
and its
Freud, Sigmund.
Civilization
Freud Sigmund
The Ego and the
,
.
Freud, Sigmund.
Discontents.
Id.
Five Lectures on Psycho- Analysis.
Freud, Sigmund.
The Future of an
Freud, Sigmund.
Group Psychology and the Analysis
Illusion.
of the Ego.
Symptoms and Anxiety.
Freud, Sigmund.
Inhibitions,
Freud, Sigmund.
Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis.
and Their Relation
to the
Unconscious.
Freud, Sigmund.
Jokes
Freud, Sigmund.
Leonardo da Vinci
and a Memory of His
Freud, Sigmund.
New Introductory
Lectures on Psychoanalysis.
Freud, Sigmund. Freud, Sigmund.
On Dreams. On the History
Freud, Sigmund.
An
Freud, Sigmund.
The Psychopathology of Everyday The Question of Lay Analysis.
Freud, Sigmund.
Childhood.
of the Psycho-Analytic Movement.
Outline of Psycho- Analysis (Rev. Ed.). Life.
Totem and Taboo, H. Jacquelynne E. Parsons, Paula B. Johnson, Diane N. Ruble and Gail L. Zellmann. Women and Sex Roles: A Social Psychological Perspective.
Freud, Sigmund. Frieze, Irene
,
Uncommon Therapy: The
Haley, Jay. Erickson,
Psychiatric Techniques of Milton B.
M.D.
Hendin, David.
Death as a Fact of Life.
Suicide in America. Hendin, Herbert. Are You Considering Psychoanalysts? Horney, Karen (Ed.).
Homey, Karen.
Feminine Psychology.
Horney, Karen. Horney, Karen.
Neurosis
Horney, Karen. Horney, Karen. Horney, Karen.
New
and Human Growth.
The Neurotic Personality of Our Time.
Ways in Psychoanalysis. Our Inner Conflicts. Self-Analysis.
Inhelder, Barbel,
James, William.
and Jean Piagec. Talks
Hamlet and Oedipus
Jones, Ernest.
The Early Growth ofLogic
m the Child.
to Teachers. .
The Growth of the Child: Reflections on Human Development. Twelve to Sixteen. Early Adolescence. Kagan, Jerome, and Robet Coles (Eds.). Katchadourian Herant Human Sexuality: Sense and Nonsense.
Kagan, Jerome.
.
,
George A. A Theory of Personality. Klein, Melanie, and Joan Riviere. Love, Hate and Reparation. Kelly,
Komarovsky, Mirra.
A Study of College Youth, Ghosts in the Mind's Machine: How We Create
Dilemmas of Masculinity :
Kosslyn, Stephen Michael. Pictures in our Brains.
Lacan, Jacques.
Ecrits.
Lacan Jacques
The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psycho-Analysis
,
.
.
William J. Creating a Good Relationship. Maternal Overprotection. Levy, David M. Lifton, Robert Jay. Thought Reform and the Lederer,
Psychology ofTotalism.
Light, Donald.
Lunde, Donald
Becoming Psychiatrists: The Professional Transformation of Self. T.
Murder and Madness
.
Mind and Body: Psychology of Emotion and Stress. Psychology and the Human Dilemma,
Mandler, George.
May, Rollo. Meehl Paul E ,
.
Psychodiagnosis: Selected Papers.
Piaget, Jean.
The Child's Conception of Number.
Piaget Jean
Genetic Eptstemology.
,
.
Piaget, Jean.
Dreams and Imitation
Play,
Piaget, Jean,
and Barbel Inhelder.
Piaget, Jean,
and Barbel Inhelder.
in Childhood.
The Child's Conception of Space. The Origin of the Idea of Chance in Children.
and Alina Szeminska.
Piaget, Jean, Barbel Inhelder,
The Child's Conception of
Geometry.
and Milton B. Singer.
Piers, Gerhart,
Piers ,
Maria
W. (Ed
.
Play
Truth
Will Therapy. Rank, Otto. Ruesch J urgen and Gregory Bateson ,
Shame and GUI It.
and Development.
Ann James Premack. and Reality.
Premack, David and
Rank, Otto.
).
,
.
The
Mind of an Ape.
Communication: The Social Matrix
of Psychiatry.
Schwartz, Barry (Ed Schwartz, Barry and
.
).
Psychology of Learning: Readings in Behavior Theory.
Hugh
Lacey,
Behaviorism, Science,
and Human Nature: An
Introduction to Conditioning.
Sullivan,
Sullivan,
Harry Stack. Harry Stack.
Sullivan, Harry Stack. Sullivan, Harry Stack. Sullivan,
Harry Stack.
van den Berg Walter,
W.
,
J.
H
.
Grey.
Watson, John B.
Clinical Studies in Psychiatry. Conceptions of Modem Psychiatry.
The Interpersonal Theory of Psychiatry. The Psychiatric Interview. Schizophrenia as
a Human
Process.
The Changing Nature of Man. The Living Brain. Behaviorism.
Wheelis, Allen.
The Quest for
Williams, Juanita
H
Identity.
Psychology of Women: Behavior in a Biosocial Context
.
(2d Ed.).
Williams, Juanita H. (Ed. ). Zilboorg, Gregory.
A
Psychology of Women: Selected Readings.
History of Medical Psychology.
Selected Liveright Paperbacks
PSYCHIATRY AND PSYCHOLOGY Jones, Ernest.
On the Nightmare.
Kohler, Wolfgang.
Dynamics in
Kohler, Wolfgang.
Gestalt Psychology.
Kohler, Wolfgang
The Mentality of Apes. The Place of Value in a World of Fact.
.
Kohler, Wolfgang. Kohler, Wolfgang. Luria, Alexander R.
Stekel ,
Wilhelm
Stekel,
Wilhelm.
Relation to Sex.
.
Psychology.
The Selected Papers of Wolfgang Kohler. The Nature of Human Conflicts. Impotence in the Male.
Sexual Aberrations: The Phenomena of Fetishism in